Skip to main content

Full text of "Character and social structure: the psychology of social institutions"

See other formats


<6-n 

;3  /^ 


CHARACTER 


AND  SOCIAL 


STRUCTURE 


n 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  SOCIAL  INSTITUTIONS 


Hans   Crertll       university  of  Wisconsin 

C.    Wright    Mills     COLUMBIA    university 


HARCOURT,  BRACE  AND  COMPANY,  NEW  YORK 


ACKNOWLEDGMENTS 


Since  this  volume  is  in  every  way  a  shared 
endeavor,  we  have  placed  our  names  on  its 
title  page  in  alphabetical  order.  We  are  equally 
responsible  for  whatever  merits  or  shortcom- 
ings it  may  contain. 

We  wish  to  thank  the  Social  Science  Research 
Council  of  Columbia  University  for  generous 
financial  support;  our  publishers,  Harcourt, 
Brace  and  Company,  for  their  extraordinary 
patience;  and  Robert  Merton  for  a  careful  and 
helpful  reading  of  the  manuscript. 


COPYRIGHT,    1953,    BY 
HARCOURT,   BRACE   AND  COMPANY,   INC. 


All  rights  reserved.  No  part  of  this  book  may  be  re- 
produced in  any  form,  by  mimeograph  or  any  other 
means,  without  permission  in  writing  from  the  publisher. 


PRINTED      IN     THE     UNITED     STATES     OF     AMERICA 


.a-8-53 


C  O  ]^  T  E  ]\  T  S 

Foreword  vii 

Preface  xi 

Pfl/t  One     Introductory 

I.  PERSPECTIVES  3 

1.  The  Biological  Model  4 

2.  The  Sociological  Model—  10 

II.  CHARACTER  AND  SOCIAL  STRUCTURE  19 

1.  Components  of  Character  Structure  19 

2.  Components  of  Social  Structure  —  22 

3.  The  Tasks  of  Social  Psychology  32 

Fart  Two     Character  Structure 

III.  ORGANISM  AND  PSYCHIC  STRUCTURE  37 

1.  The  Social  Relevance  of  the  Organism   -  37 

2.  Impulse  and  Purpose  44 

3.  Feeling  and  Emotion  48 

4.  Impression  and  Perception  64 

5.  The  Interrelations  of  the  Psychic  Structure  68 

6.  The  Social  Unity  of  the  Psychic  Structure  72 

IV.  THE  PERSON  80 

1.  Language,  Role,  Person  ,  81 

2.  Images  of  Self  84 

3.  Unities  of  Self  91 


iv  CONTENTS 

4.  Generalized  Others  95 

5.  The  Social  Relativity  of  the  Generalized  Other  98 

6.  Types  of  Persons  106 

^fy^THE  SOCIOLOGY  OF  MOTIVATION  112 

1.  The  Sociological  Approach  112 

2.  Vocabularies  of  Motive  114 

3.  The  "Real"  Motives  119 

4.  Awareness  of  Motives  125 

VI.  BIOGRAPHY  AND  TYPES  OF  CHILDHOOD  130 

1.  The  Organism  131 

,'A        2.  The  Psychic  Structure  133 

3.  Learning  135 

4.  Language  and  Person  137 

5.  Four  Theories  of  Biography  139 

6.  The  Theory  of  Adolescent  Upheaval  142 

7.  The  Relevance  of  Childhood  147 

8.  The  Social  Relativity  of  Childhood  Influences  157 

Part  Three     Social  Structure 

VII.  INSTITUTIONS  AND  PERSONS  165 

1.  The  Institutional  Selection  of  Persons  165 

2.  The  Institutional  Formation  of  Persons  173 

3.  The  Theory  of  Premiums  and  Traits  of  Character  176 

4.  Anxiety  and  Social  Structure  183 

VIII.  INSTITUTIONAL  ORDERS  AND  SOCIAL  ^ 

J              CONTROLS,  I  192 

1.  The  Political  Order                             ,  192 

2.  Nation  and  State  197 

3.  Democracies  and  Dictatorships  206 


CONTENTS  V 

4.  Economic  Institutions  213 

5.  Types  of  Capitalism  215 

6.  The  Military  Order  223 

7.  Characteristics  of  Six  Types  of  Armies  227 

IX.  INSTITUTIONAL  ORDERS  AND  SOCIAL 

CONTROLS,  II  230 

1.  Religious  Institutions  230 

2.  Characteristics  of  World  Religions  241 

3.  The  Kinship  Order  245 

4.  The  Educational  Sphere  251 

5.  Types  of  Social  Control  256 

6.  Orientation  to  Social  Controls  266 

(S^YMBOL  SPHERES  274 

1.  Symbol  Spheres^  in  Six  Contexts  278 

2.  Monopoly  and  Competition  of  Symbols  287 

3.  Communication                        ^-^.^^^^  294 

4.  The  Autonomy  of  Symbol  Spheres  298 

XI.  STRATIFICATION  &  INSTITUTIONAL  ORDERS  -       306 

1.  Occupations  3°^ 

2.  Class  Structure  310 

3.  The  Status  Sphere  315 

4.  Class  and  Status  322 

5.  The  Status  Sphere  and  Personality  Types  325 

6.  Power  328 

7.  Stratification  and  Institutional  Dominance  330 

8.  Stratification  and  Political  Mentality  339 

XII.  THE  UNITY  OF  SOCIAL  STRUCTURES  ^  342 

1.  The  Unity  of  Sparta  344 

2.  Units  and  Their  Relationships  349 


Vi  CONTENTS 

3.  Modes  of  Integration  354 

4.  Why  Rome  Fell  366 

Part  Four     Dynamics-r 

XIII.  SOCIAL-HISTORICAL  CHANGE  375 

1,  Six  Questions  377 

2.  The  Range  of  Theory  380 
-    3.  The  Technological  Sphere  388 

4.  Social-historical  Change  —  398 

XIV.  THE  SOCIOLOGY  OF  LEADERSHIP  405 

1.  The  Leader  as  a  Man:  His  Traits  and  Motives  406 

2.  Images  of  the  Leader  and  Motives  of  the  Led  408 

3.  Three  Functions  of  Authoritative  Roles  413 

4.  Contexts  and  Roles  416 

5.  Role  Dynamics  and  Leadership  419 

XV.  COLLECTIVE  BEHAVIOR  427 

1.  The  Structural  Contexts  of  Collective  Behavior  428 

2.  Aggregates,  Crowds,  and  Publics  432 

3.  Movements,  Parties,  and  Pressure  Groups  438 

4.  Revolution  and  Counterrevolution  441 

5.  Anticapitalistic  Movements  and  Parties  450 

XVI.  MASTER  TRENDS  456 

1.  The  Co-ordination  of  Political,  Economic,  and 

Military  Orders  457 

2.  Psychological  Aspects  of  Bureaucracy  460 

3.  The  Decline  of  Liberalism  464 

4.  Character  Structure  in  a  Polarized  World  472 

Bibliographical  Note  481 

Index  4^6 


Foreword 


NEW  findings  and  new  ideas  in  a  field  of  knowledge,  especially 
when  they  come  rapidly,  generally  produce  numerous  efforts  to  work 
out  new  theoretical  formulations.  Various  perspectives  develop,  each 
differing  in  its  view  of  the  central  problems  of  the  field  and  the  major 
conceptions  that  illuminate  these  problems.  This  is  plainly  the  dy- 
namic and  hopeful  condition  of  social  psychology  today. 

Among  this  varied  array  of  perspectives  on  social  psychology, 
there  is  one  which,  while  acknowledged  to  be  important,  has  been 
greatly  neglected  in  systematic  expositions.  This  approach  considers 
not  only  the  psychological  nature  of  social  interaction  but  also,  and 
primarily,  the  psychological  nature  of  the  major  social  institutions 
that  constitute  the  historically  significant  forms  of  such  interaction. 
It  is  the  chief  objective  of  this  book  to  present  a  systematic  statement 
of  just  this  approach,  one  in  which  political,  economic,  military,  re- 
ligious, and  kinship  institutions,  and  their  historical  transformations, 
are  connected  with  the  character  and  personality,  with  the  private 
as  well  as  the  public  lives,  of  those  living  in  the  society.  This  book 
might  therefore  be  described  as  an  historically  oriented  psychology 
of  social  institutions. 

Of  late  general  works  of  social  psychology  have  paid  scant  atten- 
tion to  the  historical  changes  of  social  institutions.  This  has  hap- 
pened, it  seems,  not  so  much  by  design  as  by  inadvertence:  the 
emphasis— quite  understandably— has  been  upon  experiment,  direct 
observation,  and  statistically  controlled  comparisons  of  behavior. 
This  book  should  help  restore  the  balance.  Whether  use  of  the  book 
precedes,  accompanies,  or  follows  intensive  study  of  the  short-run 
present  in  the  laboratory,  field,  and  clinic,  it  should  broaden  the 
horizon  of  the  student  who  generally  comes  into  social  psychology 


Viii  FOREWORD 

either  through  the  gateway  of  psychology  or  of  sociology.  It  should 
help  him  cultivate  his  powers  of  observation  and  analysis  to  under- 
stand the  behavior  of  men,  not  merely  in  small  groups  literally  be- 
fore his  eyes,  but  also  in  relation  to  the  larger  institutional  structure, 
with  all  its  complexity  and  historical  meaning.  And  the  wide  range 
of  comparative  materials  included  in  this  book  should  do  much  to 
curb  any  tendency  on  the  part  of  the  student  toward  the  provin- 
cialism of  thinking  in  terms  only  of  his  own  society  or  his  own  time. 

For  all  their  emphasis  on  the  shaping  of  character  by  the  social 
structure,  the  authors  avoid  dogmatism.  They  refuse  to  be  drawn 
into  the  position,  rapidly  grown  archaic,  of  maintaining  that  every- 
thing about  human  conduct  must  be  explained  by  the  organization 
of  social  institutions,  or  of  assuming  that  even  differences  in  the 
native  endowment  of  men  must  be  denied  as  a  fact  in  order  to  lend 
seeming  support  to  the  sociological  approach  as  an  idea.  On  occa- 
sion, the  authors  do  examine,  compactly  and  fairly,  some  of  the 
theoretical  controversies  which  have  raged  in  the  field— for  example, 
the  long-lived  debate  over  the  use  of  instinct  as  an  explanatory  con- 
cept. In  this  way  a  new  generation  of  students  becomes  acquainted 
with  these  early  victories  of  the  mind  and  is  kept  from  unwittingly 
resurrecting  some  of  these  controversies  in  the  mistaken  belief  that 
they  have  come  upon  a  genuine  intellectual  problem.  As  the  authors 
remind  us,  such  spurious  problems  are  usually  solved  by  being  out- 
grown. 

Any  book  with  a  theoretical  focus  must  select  its  materials  and 
problems  in  terms  of  that  focus,  and  selection  of  course  involves 
omissions  as  well  as  inclusions.  Omissions,  therefore,  do  not  neces- 
sarily constitute  defects.  The  important  thing  is  to  inquire  whether 
an  omission  is  the  result  of  careless  and  faulty  thinking  or  of  a  con- 
sidered judgment  that  the  material  is  not  directly  germane  to  the 
logical  structure  of  the  book.  The  omissions  in  this  book  are  of  the 
second  kind.  On  some  matters,  treated  at  length  in  other  books  of 
social  psychology,  the  authors  maintain  deliberate  silence;  on  some 
matters,  found  not  at  all  in  other  books,  they  expound  at  length. 
Thus,  if  they  make  only  passing  reference  to  the  experiments  on 
social  factors  in  perception,  to  learning  theory,  or  to  recent  studies 
of  voting  behavior,  they  pay  close  and  systematic  attention  to  the 
comparative  psychology  of  political  and  military  life,  of  religious 
institutions,  social  stratification,  and  business  enterprise.  And  they 
make  use  of  every  species  of  social  psychological  data. 


FOREWORD  IX 

The  authors  lay  no  claim  to  having  achieved  a  fully  rounded 
synthesis  which  incorporates  all  the  major  conceptions  of  psychology 
and  sociology  that  bear  upon  the  formation  of  character  and  per- 
sonality in  the  context  of  social  structure.  Such  a  goal,  they  make  it 
clear,  is  still  a  distant  objective  rather  than  a  currently  possible 
achievement.  Nevertheless,  they  have  systematized  a  substantial 
part  of  the  field  and  have  provided  perspectives  from  which  to  ex- 
amine much  of  the  rest. 

But  perhaps  above  all  else  this  book  has  the  merit  of  giving  the 
reader  a  sense  of  the  intellectual  excitement  that  comes  from  using 
the  trained  imagination  to  study  the  psychological  meaning  of  social 
structures.  In  the  world  of  social  psychology  as  we  know  it,  this  is 
no  small  accomplishment. 

ROBERT  K.    MERTON 

Columbia  University 
July  30,  ig53 


Preface 


I 

THE  shock  of  world  events  has  hit  the  social  sciences  harder  than 
many  social  scientists  recognize.  In  most  areas  of  the  world,  historic 
changes  have  been  apparent  to  anyone  who  wished  to  look  at  them; 
if  they  have  been  attended  to  more  by  journalists  than  by  social 
scientists,  that  has  been  to  the  loss  of  the  social  sciences.  During 
the  last  half  century  there  have  been  two  world  wars,  and  in 
Europe  several  political  revolutions.  The  social  structures  of  Russia 
and  of  eastern  Europe  have  been  thoroughly  revolutionized;  great 
changes  continue  to  shake  Asia,  Africa,  and  South  America.  If 
the  people  of  the  United  States  have  not  known  the  tang  and  feel 
of  revolution,  it  may  be  due  to  the  fact  that  elections  have  con- 
tinued to  take  place  here  within  a  political  order  that  is  over  one 
hundred  and  fifty  years  old.  In  the  meantime,  the  United  States  has 
become  the  creditor  country  for  half  the  world  and  the  naval  and 
military  protector  of  all  her  debtor  states.  It  would,  accordingly, 
be  provincial  of  Americans  not  to  think  about  the  diverse  possi- 
bilities latent  in  all  modern  social  structures.  For  war  has  widened 
our  view,  and  now  the  whole  world  lies  before  us,  polarized  be- 
tween the  U.S.S.R.  and  the  U.S.A.  Before  such  world  events  as  we 
have  known,  it  is  not  surprising  that  there  is  an  uneasiness  con- 
cerning the  adequacy  of  the  viewpoint  and  the  equipment  of  the 
social  scientist. 

World  War  II  and  its  aftermath  compelled  thinkers  in  the 
United  States  toward  a  larger  \'iew  of  the  range  and  conditions 
of  mankind.  For  better  or  for  worse,  the  mind  has  followed  the 
army  and  navy.  Members  of  academic  institutions  who,  till  now, 
had  never  considered  Europe  and  Asia  in  connection  with  their 


Xii  PREFACE 

respective  social  studies  have  found  themselves  teaching  courses 
about  the  peoples  and  resources  of  these  areas.  Social  scientists 
have  been  asked  questions  which  they  cannot  answer,  and  some 
of  them,  even  as  all  thoughtful  men,  have  asked  themselves  such 
questions. 

Along  with  the  historical  transformations  of  whole  societies, 
what  mvist  be  described  as  a  vacuum  of  loyalties,  as  a  deep-seated 
malaise,  has  come  about  in  the  public  life  of  the  Western  democ- 
racies.^ Whatever  its  social-historical  foundations  may  be,  this 
malaise  is  of  course  experienced  on  the  psychological  plane.  So- 
cialism's theoretical  crises,  for  example,  are  held  by  many  to  rest 
upon  psychological  misjudgments  rather  than  upon  misjudgments 
of  the  course  of  economic  affairs.  The  radical  and  the  liberal  in 
America  today  are  often  more  interested  in  psychological  than  in 
material  exploitation,  more  interested  in  problems  of  soap  opera 
than  of  child  labor. 

Due  in  part  to  the  rise  of  totalitarian  societies,  we  have  become 
acutely  aware  of  patterns  of  external  constraint  which  are  in  ten- 
sion with  the  impulses  of  man  as  a  willful  animal.  Various  schools 
of  sociology  have  viewed  man  as  a  mechanism  adjusting,  or  trying 
to  adjust,  to  all  sorts  of  overpowering  "environments"  and  "condi- 
tions"; whereas  positivist  -  psychologists  have  increasingly  tended  to 
lose  sight  of  the  individual  man  as  an  actor  in  the  larger  social  and 
historical  scene.  Those  schools  of  psychology,  especially  Gestalt 
and  Psychoanalysis,  which  do  try  to  bring  man  as  an  understand- 
able actor  into  focus  are  not  primarily  interested  in  sociological 
problems.  They  are,  however,  greatly  suggestive  to  the  social  sci- 
entist who  while  looking  at  social  constraints  is  thinking  about 
human  freedoms. 

1  For  an  elaboration  of  this  theme,  see  C.  Wright  Mills,  White  Collar:  the 
American  Middle  Classes  (New  York:  Oxford,  1951);  Leo  Lowenthal  and 
Norbert  Guterman,  Prophets  of  Deceit:  A  Study  of  the  Techniques  of  the 
American  Agitator  (New  York:  Harper,  1949),  esp.  pp.  n-20;  and  Karl 
Mannheim,  Man  and  Society  in  an  Age  of  Reconstruction,  Edward  Shils,  tr. 
(New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1940). 

-  For  one  meaning  of  "positivist,"  we  refer  the  reader  to  the  jingle  allegedly 
written  by  the  distinguished  T.   H.   Huxley: 

"There  was   an   ape   in   days   which   were  earlier; 
Centuries  passed  and  its  hair  it  grew  curlier; 
Centuries  more  and  its  thumb  gave  a  twist, 
And  he  was  a  man,  and  a  Positivist." 


PREFACE  Xlll 

Problems  of  the  natvire  of  human  nature  are  raised  most  urgently 
when  the  life-routines  of  a  society  are  disturbed,  when  men  are 
alienated  from  their  social  roles  in  such  a  way  as  to  open  them- 
selves up  for  new  insight.  When  social  affairs  proceed  smoothly, 
"human  nature"  seems  to  fit  so  neatly  into  traditional  routines  that 
no  general  problem  is  presented;  men  know  what  to  expect  from 
one  another;  their  vocabularies  for  various  emotions  and  their 
stereotyped  motives  are  taken  for  granted  and  seem  common  to 
all.  But  when  society  is  in  deep-going  transformation  and  men  are 
pivots  of  historic  change,  they  challenge  one  another's  explanations 
of  conduct,  and  human  nature  itself  becomes  problematic. 

Several  twentieth-century  schools  of  psychology  originated  in 
conHict-ridden  Central  Europe,  centering  on  notions  of  Gestalt  or 
the  Unconscious,  or  in  types  of  body  builds  or  in  the  projective 
tests  of  specialists  like  Rorschach.  And  there  is  the  philosophical 
legacy  of  Kierkegaard  and  Nietzsche  which  lives  on  in  the  psy- 
chiatric work  of  Karl  Jaspers  and  Ludwig  Binswanger.  Nietzsche 
—in  one  sense  a  precursor  of  Freud— felt  himself  to  be  in  intel- 
lectual kinship  with  the  psychological  essayism  of  such  French 
thinkers  as  Montaigne  and  La  Bruyere,  La  Rochefoucauld  and 
Pascal,  who  had  observed  men  and  their  ways  in  comparably 
profound  periods  of  transition.  And  we  should  not  forget  that  the 
social  psychology  of  such  a  man  as  Le  Bon  concerned  the  revo- 
lutionary action  of  man  in  crowds  and  mobs. 

II 

In  our  historical  situation  the  hybrid,  "social  psychology,"  has 
come  increasingly  to  appeal  to  those  who  are  eager  to  understand 
social  structures  in  such  a  way  as^  to  see  how  they"  "have  shaped 
the  character  of  individual  men  and  women. 

Back  of  the  interest  in  social  psychology  is  the  desire  to  answer 
simple  yet  momentous  questions:  What  do  given  societies  mean 
for  men?  What  sort  of  creature  is  man  in  this  or  that  political  and 
economic  condition?  Are  there  limits  to  his  manipulatability? 
Many  of  the  new  strivings  and  demands  of  social  science  seem  to 
us  to  come  to  fruition  in  a  psychology  that  is  relevant  to  the  proc- 
esses of  history  and  to  varying  types  of  social  structures. 

The  challenge  of  social  psychology,  and  its  great  appeal  to  mod- 
ern scholars,  is  that  in  a  time  of  intellectual  specialization  and  of 
social  and  political  disintegration,  it  promises  a  view  of  man  as  an 


XIV  PREFACE 

actor  in  historic  crises,  and  of  man  as  a  whole  entity.  These  prom- 
ises and  challenges  become  all  the  more  compelling  as  social  life 
becomes  a  set  of  abstracted  specialities,  which  various  authorities 
would  motivate  for  the  disciplined  mass  conduct  of  war  and  peace. 
In  such  a  context,  it  is  one  of  the  special  obligations  of  the  social 
psychologist  again  and  again  to  bridge  the  departmentalized  gap 
which  unfortunately  separates  the  sociological  and  psychological 
approaches. 

Our  general  purpose  Js  to  study  the  personalities  of  men  in  con- 
nection with  types  of  social-historical  structure.  We  wish  to  analyze 
conduct  and  character  by  understanding  the  motivations  of  men 
who  occupy  different  positions  within  various  social  structures. 
And  we  wish  to  understand  how  creeds  and  symbols  contribute  to 
the  motivations  required  for  the  enactment  of  given  roles  by  per- 
sons within  institutional  structures. 

Ill 

No  matter  how  we  approach  the  field  of  social  psychology,  we 
cannot  escape  the  idea  that  all  current  work  that  comes  to  much, 
fits  into  one  or  the  other  of  two  basic  traditions:  Freud,  on  the 
side  of  character  structure,  and  Marx,  including  the  early  Marx 
of  the  1840's,  on  the  side  of  social  structure.  Of  course,  we  use 
both  "freud"  and  "marx"  as  uncapitalized  adjectives:  they  refer  to 
great  perspectives  and  great  bodies  of  work  rather  than  solely  to 
the  books  of  Freud  and  Marx.  We  have  no  objection,  if  the  reader 
prefers,  to  use  the  names  George  H.  Mead  and  Max  Weber,  al- 
though of  course  they  differ  from  Freud  and  Marx  in  many  impor- 
tant ways.^ 

The  reason  we  are  drawn,  again  and  again,  to  Sigmund  Freud 
and  George  Mead,  is  that  they  try,  more  effectively  than  others, 
to  show  us  man  as  a  whole  actor— instead  of  man  as  a  set  of  traits, 
as  a  bundle  of  reflexes.  It  was  Freud's  contribution  to  raise  the 
question  of  the  nature  of  human  nature  in  its  larger  framework. 
That  is  also  the  reason,  from  the  sociological  side,  that  we  are 
drawn,  again  and  again,  to  such  men  as  Marx  and  Weber,  who 
would  do  no  less  than  articulate  a  society  as  a  whole  inside  an  his- 
torical epoch. 

Both  the  structural  sociologist  and  the  depth  psychologist  prom- 

^  The  relevant  books  of  these  four  thinkers  will  be  found  in  the  Bibliograi^hi- 
cal  Note,  pp.  481-85. 


PREFACE  XV 

ise  to  help  us  locate  modern  men— and  ourselves— as  historical 
actors.  This  promise  motivates  modern  social  psychologists,  whose 
present  theoretical  task  is  set  by  the  availability  of  two  such  per- 
spectives—of character  and  of  social  structure— and  by  their  own 
desire  to  see  man  intimately,  yet  as  an  historical  actor.  If  their 
theoretical  task  is  to  roimd  out  and  to  bring  these  two  perspectives 
together,  then  the  theoretical  significance  of  recent  work  in  this 
field  must  be  judged  accordingly:  detailed  research  must  be  viewed 
as  contributing  to  one  or  the  other  of  these  two  conceptions,  and 
at  the  growing  edge,  contributing  to  the  linking  of  them  into  a 
working  model  of  man  and  society. 

IV 

On  the  psychological  side,  the  explanations  that  have  been  ad- 
vanced in  the  brief  history  of  our  discipline  fall  into  two  main 
types:  on  the  one  hand,  there  has  been  the  attempt  to  reduce  social 
regularities  to  universal  constants,  rooted  somehow  in  man_as 
man;  and  on  fhe^otHerTthe  alteiiTpt  to  conrrecrmarTs  conduct  and 
nature  with  the  social  roles  which  he  enacts.'^ 

THe  idea  of  some  constant,  lying  back  of  conduct  and  in  man's 
universal  human  nature,*  has  been  the  most  frequent  and  persistent 
error  of  psychology,  including  that  of  Freud.  It  is  as  if  this  quest 
for  some  constant  elemeiit  has  served  as  a  compensation  for  the 
enormous  relativity  of  human  nature  which  anthropology  and 
world  history  make  so  evident.  It  runs  through  the  older  eight- 
eenth- and  nineteenth-century  rationalist  psychologies,  to  reach  its 
climax  in  the  instinct  school.  Half  of  the  American  life  of  our 
young  discipline  has  been  spent  debating  the  notion  of  instinct  in 
all  its  various  guises. 

Nowadays,  however,  the  idea  of  immutable  biological  elements 
recedes  and  is  no  longer  a  problem  engaging  all  our  energies.  We 
did  not  solve  the  problem;  'we  outgrew  it.  At  best,  all  we  learn  , 
when  we  study  man  as  a  mere  animal  are  his  limitations  when 
stripped  of  all  technologies.  If  we  are  imaginative,  we  learn  also 
that  his  "dispositions"  are  open-ended  and  capable  of  develop- 
ment. We  learn  that  his  "human  natiue"  is  not  given  to  him  once  A 
and  for  all,  but  as  a  continual  series  of  tasks.  The  establishment 

*  See  Chapter  I:  Perspectives,  Section  i:  The  Biological  Model. 


XVI  PREFACE 

ol  the  reality  of  the  social  and  plastic  nature  of  man  is  a  major 
accomplishment  of  U.S.  social  psychology."^ 

The  function  of  American  behaviorism  in  the  history  of  our 
discipline  is  found  precisely  here:  it  opened  up  the  problems  of 
human  nature,  by  allowing  us  to  see  the  great  modifiability  of 
man;  it  opened  up  our  minds  for  explanations  that  are  not  tauto- 
logical blind  alleys.  But  the  behaviorist's  image  of  man  "adjusting" 
to  all  sorts  of  overpowering  circumstances  is  also  in  line  with  the 
modern  temper  of  those  who  would  manipulate  without  under- 
standing closely.  Behaviorism,  as  advanced  by  John  Watson,  elim- 
inated instincts,  but  in  the  process  social  psychology  was  often 
made  shallow.  For  as  an  explanatory  model,  behaviorism  lowered 
our  chance  to  understand  motivations.  Behaviorism's  most  fruitful 
outcome  was  George  Mead's  work,  especially  his  daring  effort  to 
anchor  personal  consciousness  itself  in  the  social  process. 

Mead's  concept  of  the  generalized  other,  and  Freud's  super- 
ego—their closest  point  of  contact  '"'—enable  us  to  link  the  private 
and  the  public,  the  innermost  acts  of  the  individual  with  the  widest 
kinds  of  social-historical  phenomena.  From  a  logical  and  unhis- 
torical  point  of  view,  Freud's  work  at  this  point  may  be  seen  as 
a  specification  of  the  social  and  biographical  locus  of  the  gener- 
alized other.  For  he  indicates  how,  in  the  early  phase  of  develop- 
ment, the  family  is  important  for  the  social  anchorage  of  con- 
science, and  thus  makes  his  central  hookup  of  love  and  authority. 

Various  philosophical  assumptions  that  had  crept  into  Freud's 
work  have  been  torn  out  with  little  or  no  damage  to  what  remains 
as  usable  heritage.  More  importantly,  the  conceptions  of  Freud 
have  been  made  socially  relative  by  the  work  of  such  writers  as 
Bronislaw  Malinowski,"  Abram  Kardiner,®  Karen  Horney,^  and 
Erich  Fromm.^"  Instincts  have  been  formalized  into  "energy,"  in 

5  See  Fay  B.  Karpf,  American  Social  Psychology  (New  York:  McGraw-Hill, 
1932),  for  a  detailed  account. 

6  See  Chapter  IV:  The  Person,  Section  4:  Generalized  Others  and  Section 
5:  The  Social  Relativity  of  the  Generalized  Other. 

■^  Cf.  The  Father  in  Primitive  Psychology  (New  York:  Norton,  1927)  and 
Sex  and  Repression  in  Savage  Society  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1927). 

8  Cf .  The  Individual  and  His  Society  (New  York:  Columbia  University 
Press,  1939)- 

'*  Cf.  The  Neurotic  Personality  of  Our  Time  (New  York:  Norton,  1937) 
and  New  Ways  in  Psychoanalysis  (New  York:  Norton,  1939). 

^°  Escape  from  Freedom  (New  York:  Farrar  &  Rinehart,  1941). 


PREFACE  XVU 

order  that  we  can  better  understand  how  various  goals  of  conduct 
are  socially  fixed  and  socially  changed.  Indeed,  that  is  why  we 
believe  Kardiner's  and  Fromm's  work,  as  well  as  Harry  Stack 
Sullivan's  "  on  the  significant  and  the  authoritative  other,  is  so 
much  in  the  central  stream  of  what  is  most  promising  in  recent  so- 
cial psychology.  In  fact,  work  on  the  superego  or  generalized  other 
is  now  at  the  growing  edge  of  our  studies,  for  such  conceptions 
enable  us  to  link  traits  deep  in  the  individual  with  facts  that  lie  in 
a  widespread  sociological  perspective. 

George  Mead  had  no  adequate  notion  of  emotions  and  motives, 
no  dynamic  theory  of  the  affective  life  of  man;  Freud's  notion  of 
the  personality  certainly  tends  to  be  socially  inflexible.  And  neither 
Freud  nor  Mead  presents  a  conception  of  social  structure  that 
makes  it  inherently,  directly,  and  intimately  relevant  to  psycho- 
logical problems. 

But  from  the  side  of  depth  psychology  and  of  the  mechanisms 
of  personality  formation  and  change,  enormous  advances  have 
been  made.  Freud  and  George  Mead,  when  appropriately  in- 
tegrated and  systematized,  provide  a  well-articulated  model  of 
character  structure,  and  one  of  the  most  fruitful  sets  of  ideas  avail- 
able in  modern  social  science.  It  is  our  aim,  especially  in  Parts  I 
and  II  of  this  book,  to  construct  a  model  of  character  structure 
that  enables  us  to  systematize  some  of  these  ideas  and  make  them 
available  for  more  sociologically  relevant  use. 


From  the  other  side,  that  of  structural,  comparative,  and  his- 
torical sociology— although  there  are  notable  exceptions— less  has 
been  recently  accomplished.  The  tradition  of  Marx  and  Sombart 
and  Weber,  as  well  as  of  the  late  Karl  Mannheim,  who  met  so 
many  of  these  problems  with  such  great  insight,  has  not  advanced 
as  we  might  wish.  Yet,  the  urge  to  compare  large  social  entities 
in  their  historical  epochs  with  one  another  is  one  of  the  bequests 
of  the  founders  of  modern  sociology,  of  August  Comte  and  Her- 
bert Spencer,^^  no  less  than  of  Marx  and  Weber.  Quite  apart  from 
the  problem  of  how  much  and  what  portions  of  their  work  are  of 

11  See  Conceptions  of  Modern  Psychiatry  (Washington:  W.  A.  White 
Psychiatric  Foundation,  1947). 

1-  See  especially  the  great,  much  neglected  work  of  Spencer,  Principles  of 
Sociology  (New  York:  D.  Appleton,  1896). 


\ 


\ 


XViii  PREFACE 

merely  historical  interest,  the  impetus  and  the  breadth  of  focus  of 
such  men  should  not  be  lost  in  otherwise  legitimate  and  necessary 
criticisms  of  their  work.  In  our  endeavor  to  share  the  reawakened 
interest  in  studying  world  societies  comparatively,  we  look  to  the 
outstanding  work  of  such  contemporaries  as  Arnold  Toynbee,^"* 
A.  L.  Kroeber,^*  and  P.  A.  Sorokin.^^ 

If  it  seems  to  be  a  shortcoming  of  many  eminent  Europeans  to 
be  absolutist  in  certain  phases  of  their  work,  it  is  a  distinct  con- 
tribution of  American  pragmatists  to  purge  sociological  thinking  of 
such  rigidities  and  to  open  our  minds  to  the  exploration  of  reality. 
As  Karl  Mannheim  has  written,  "There  were  hardly  ever  two  dif- 
ferent styles  of  study  as  fit  to  supplement  each  other's  shortcomings 
as  are  the  German  and  American  types  of  sociology."  ^*^ 

We  think  a  signal  danger  to  further  advance  in  much  good  work 
now  going  on  in  social  psychology  is  the  use  of  inadequate  notions 
of  "society."  In  place  of  social  structure,  many  students  would  use 
the  concept,  "culture"— one  of  the  spongiest  words  in  social  sci- 
ence, although,  perhaps  for  that  reason,  in  the  hands  of  an  expert, 
enormously  useful.  The  concept,  "culture,"  is  often  more  a  loose 
reference  to  social  milieu  than  an  adequate  idea  of  social  struc- 
ture.^^  Nevertheless,  unhindered,  as  they  have  been,  by  aware- 


13  Cf.  A  Study  of  History,  6  vols.  (London:  Oxford  Univ.  Press,  1946). 
1*  See  his  Configurations  of  Cultural  Growth  (Berkeley:  Univ.  of  California 
Press,  1944). 

15  See,  for  an  introduction  to  the  sociology  of  history,  the  good  summary 
of  doctrines  in  Sorokin's  Social  Philosophies  of  an  Age  of  Crisis  (Boston: 
Beacon  Press,   1950). 

16  Cf.  Karl  Mannheim's  review  in  the  American  Journal  of  Sociology,  Sep- 
tember 1932,  p.  281. 

i'^  We  do  not  wish  to  dispute  the  various  conceptual  distinctions  in\'olving 
"society,"  "culture,"  and  "civilization,"  as  severally  paired  with  "personality." 
To  us,  the  term  "culture"  and  its  derivations  refer  to  "nature  worked  over 
by  man,"  which  of  course  includes  man's  own  nature.  A  gymnastically  de- 
veloped body  and  an  intellectually  trained  mind  are  "cultural"  attainments; 
so  are  various  forms  of  interpersonal  relationshif)s,  social  institutions  and 
organizations  of  all  sorts.  Indeed,  all  the  "works"  that  man  builds  in  his 
exchange  relations  with  nature  as  well  as  in  his  endeavor  to  expand  the 
meaning  of  his  world,  are  part  of  "culture."  And  in  all  this  work,  man  is 
himself  shaped.  For  man's  nature  is  not  given;  it  is  a  task  and  a  challenge. 
During  recent  decades,  scholars  in  all  the  social  studies  have  by  their  work 
brought  out  the  social-historical  determination  of  man's  ideas  and  works,  as 
well  as  of  man  himself. 

It  is   one   thing   to   accept,   as   we   do,   this   very   general  perspective;   it   is 


PREFACE  XIX 

ness  of  "complexity"  and  of  "methodological"  difficulties,  cultural 
anthropologists  have  sought  to  grasp  the  interdependence  of  pre- 
literate  cultural  wholes. 

!  What  is  needed  to  make  such  work  more  usable  is  a  conception 
of  social  structure  as  an  articulation  of  various  institutional  orders 
and  functions;  we  must  study  each  segment  of  a  social  structure 
psychologically,  as  Freud  studied  the  kinship  institutions  of  the 
upper  classes  in  certain  Western  societies.  We  need  to  study  men 
enacting  roles  in  political,  economic,  and  religious  institutions  in 
various  societies;  we  need  to  form  theories  of  how,  on  the  one 
hand,  types  of  personalities  are  variously  anchored  in  each  of  these 
institutional  orders;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  how  the  institutional 
orders  themselves  are  variously  combined,  to  form  historical  types 
of  social  structures.  In  the  course  of  this  book  we  shall  set  forth  a 
general  model  of  social  structure  which  will  help  us  carry  out 
these  aims. 

VI 

Intellectually,  social  psychology  has  become  the  main  area  of 
contact  between  the  decisive  intellectual  traditions  of  our  time; 
politically,  this  field  is  crucial,  because  now,  when  profound  crises 
shake  mankind,  our  urgent  interest  in  the  larger  problems  of  man 
and  society  requires  that  we  understand  man  as  an  historical  actor. 

The  structural  and  historical  features  of  modern  society  must 
be  connected  with  the  most  intimate  features  of  man's  self.  That 
is  what  social  psychology  is  all  about.  And  that,  we  think,  cannot 
be  done  by  dealing  only  in  microscopic  observations.  If  ever  there 
was  a  field  needing  above  all  else  imaginative  theory,  that  field  is 
American  social  psychology  today.  Only  by  such  work,  rather  than 
by  delving  into  unrelated  specialities,  can  we  at  once  avail  our- 
selves of  our  intellectual  opportunities  and  avoid  slivering  our 
image  of  man. 

Our  book  is  intended  to  offer  some  ways  into  the  central  issues 
of  social  psychology.  We  deliberately  omit  any  discussion  of  nu- 
merous  sidelines,   and  we   do   not   attempt   to   offer  encyclopedic 

quite  another  to  try  to  use  the  term  "culture,"  which  we  do  not,  for  more 
technically  precise  constructions.  For  an  unduly  depreciative  assessment  of 
recent  literature,  see  Alfred  R.  Lindesmith  and  Anselm  L.  Strauss,  "A  Critique 
of  Culture-Personality  Writings,"  American  Sociological  Review,  October  1950, 
PP-  587-600. 


XX  P  R  E  F  A  C  E 

information,  which  no  single  volume  can  embrace— not  even  a  one- 
volume  encyclopedia.  We  wish  to  teach,  not  to  engage  in  com- 
mentaries, polemical  or  complementary,  on  what  others  have  writ- 
ten or  left  unwritten.  And  we  do  not  offer  a  history  of  ideas  and 
concepts;  accordingly,  we  have  not  burdened  our  pages  with  his- 
torical references  to  theoretical  literature,  which  professionals  al- 
ready know  and  laymen  often  do  not  need.  With  all  diffidence,  we 
hope  not  to  swallow  up,  but  to  contribute  to  an  on-going  work. 

In  our  work,  we  do  not  make  any  formal  distinctions  among  the 
several  social  sciences  or  their  varying  national  manifestations. 
Indeed,  we  have  constantly  felt  the  need  to  think  through  various 
problems  with  the  aid  of  all  viewpoints  which  seem  available, 
regardless  of  their  departmental  or  national  source.  This  does  not 
mean  that  our  explicit  aim  is  to  show  how  the  concepts  of  the  vari- 
ous human  disciplines  may  be  theoretically  related,  or  how  their 
"fields"  might  be  integrated.  Social  scientists,  although  perhaps 
not  deans,  have  got  beyond  the  need  of  such  formal  discussions, 
or  at  least  have  come  to  believe  that  such  discussions  are  no  longer 
adequate.  What  we  are  trying  to  do  is  actually  think  about  con- 
crete problems  of  social  structure  and  personality,  with  a  set  of 
perspectives  drawn  from  the  work  of  the  various  social  sciences. 
For  such  thinking  is  necessary  if  we  are  to  face  up  to  the  type  of 
questions  which  confront  us. 

The  range  of  data  with  which  we  attempt  to  answer  these  ques- 
tions is  thus  wider  than  Western  society  and  the  world  fringe  of 
preliterate  groupings.  In  time,  it  includes  examples  from  ancient 
China  and  modern  Russia;  in  location,  it  extends  to  Japan  and 
Latin  America,  the  United  States,  and  the  several  European  coun- 
tries. Our  central  aim  is  to  build  a  working  model  in  terms  of 
which  we  can  use  the  data  of  world  history  and  the  perspectives 
of  the  social  sciences  and  psychologies  in  an  effort  to  understand 
the  types  of  human  beings  that  have  risen  in  varying  kinds  of  social 
structure. 

Our  book  is  arranged  in  four  parts,  in  the  first  of  which  we 
introduce  our  general  manner  of  explanation  and  lay  out  in  a 
preliminary  way  the  major  components  of  our  working  models  of 
character  and  of  social  structure. 

In  Part  Two  we  analyze  the  conception  of  character  structure, 
breaking  it  down  into  its  elements,  discussing  each  of  them,  and 


PREFACE  XXI 

indicating  how  they  are  variously  related  to  one  another.  In  this 
connection,  we  pay  particular  attention  to  problems  of  motivation 
as  well  as  to  the  development  of  character  structure  as  a  whole. 

In  Part  Three,  we  turn  to  social  structure,  taking  up,  first,  the 
general  mechanisms  by  which  persons  and  institutions  are  related 
and  then  examining,  in  turn,  the  range  of  institutions  in  the  politi- 
cal, the  economic,  the  military,  the  religious,  the  kinship,  and  the 
educational  areas  of  a  society.  After  relating  these  institutions  to 
systems  of  social  stratification,  we  suggest  and  illustrate  various 
ways  in  which  institutions  may  be  integrated  to  form  going  social 
structures. 

In  Part  Four  we  deal  with  social-historical  change,  explaining 
how  our  idea  of  social  structure  leads  us  to  construct  a  model  of 
social  change,  and  how  within  this  model  we  are  able  to  locate  such 
dynamic  forces  as  leadership  and  the  various  forms  of  collective 
behavior,  including  crowds,  publics,  movements,  and  parties.  We 
end  by  a  general  consideration  of  the  world  trends  that  now  seem 
most  importantly  to  shape  the  types  of  character  that  prevail  in 
modern  social  structures. 


P  A  K  T    ONE 


INTRODUCTORY 


CHAPTER 

I 

Perspectives 


THE  social  psychologist  attempts  to  describe  and  explain  the 
conduct  and  the  motivations  of  men  and  women  in  various  types 
of  societies.  He  asks  how  the  external  conduct  and  inner  life  of  one 
individual  interplay  with  those  of  others.  He  seeks  to  describe  the 
types  of  persons  usually  found  in  different  types  of  societies,  and 
then  to  explain  them  by  tracing  their  interrelations  with  their 
societies. 

The  explanations  generally  offered  by  social  psychologists  have 
proceeded  either  from  the  side  of  biology  or  from  the  side  of 
sociology. 

The  biologist,  as  George  Mead  said  of  Watson,  writes  with  the 
animal  before  him,  viewing  the  individual  primarily  as  an  organ- 
ism, a  live  creature  of  bones,  muscles,  and  nerves,  each  of  which 
fulfills  certain  animal  functions.  To  the  biologist,  the  organism  is  a 
more  or  less  unitary  system,  and  so  in  explaining  its  behavior,  he 
pays  attention  to  what  goes  on  inside  that  organism— to  its  biologi- 
cal and  physiological  mechanisms.  The  guiding  thread  of  his  work 
is  the  physiological  process,  the  biological  conditions  of  behavior. 

The  sociologist,  on  the  other  hand,  tries  to  "locate"  the  human 
being  and  his  conduct  in  various  institutions,  never  isolating  the  in- 
dividual or  the  workings  of  his  mind  from  his  social  and  historical 
setting.  He  explains  character  and  conduct  in  terms  of  these  insti- 
tutions, and  of  the  total  social  structure  which  they  form.  He 
draws  upon  the  experience  of  people  as  social  persons  rather  than 
upon  the  physical  and  organic  facts  about  people  as  animal  organ- 
isms. Since  he  is  interested  in  the  social  setting  and  motivations 
of  conduct,  rather  than  its  physical  conditions  and  organic  mecha- 
nisms, he  does  not  attempt  to  explain  conduct  as  if  it  were  the 
realization  of  some  fundamental  condition  within  the  individual. 


4,  INTRODUCTORY 

The  sociologist  tries  to  explain  character  and  conduct  as  a  ful- 
fillment of  social  function  within  an  already  established,  although 
usually  open-ended,  network  of  social  relations. 

These  two  viewpoints— within  which  the  explanations  of  the 
social  psychologist  are  developed— are  not  mutually  exclusive;  nor 
do  we  believe  it  wise  or  fruitful  to  understand  them  as  competing 
schools  of  thought.  In  the  end,  we  can— in  fact  we  must— use  both 
viewpoints;  but  in  the  beginning  we  must  think  in  oversimplified 
ways,  in  order  the  better  to  see  just  how  to  complicate  our  view- 
point most  profitably.  We  must,  therefore,  examine  the  biological 
and  the  sociological  models  of  conduct,  each  in  its  turn. 

1.  The  Biological  Model 

The  biologist  is  interested  in  what  goes  on  in  man's  animal  or- 
ganism when  it  acts  in  certain  ways  or  reacts  to  certain  experi- 
ences; he  reconstructs  certain  elements  and  sequences  of  internal  . 
events    which   are    then  >used    to    explain    the    external    behavior 
observed. 

One  of  the  simplest  explanations  from  this  general  point  of  view 
proceeds  in  terms  of  the  "conditioning"  of  reflexes.  Here  is  an  or- 
ganism equipped  with  certain  reflexes;  there  are  certain  changes 
in  the  environment  which  stimulate  these  reflexes  to  action.  If  a 
bright  light  is  flashed  into  a  human  eye,  the  pupil  of  the  eye  will 
mechanically  contract;  if  a  blow  is  struck  just  below  the  kneecap, 
the  lower  limb  will  spring  out;  if  an  edible  object  is  presented  to 
a  dog  with  an  empty  stomach,  the  dog  will  salivate;  or  if  a  small 
object  is  shoved  into  or  near  an  infant's  mouth,  the  infant  will 
start  sucking.  Such  automatic  reactions,  or  reflexes,  occur  because 
the  organism  is  a  mechanical  structure  of  muscles,  chemistry,  and 
nerves.  Difterent  animal  species  have  different  sets  of  such  reflexes. 
They  are  simply  built  that  way. 

Now,  if  a  light  is  flashed  into  the  human  eye  and  at  the  same  time 
a  little  puff  of  air  is  shot  at  it,  eventually  the  puff  of  air  by  itself 
will  evoke  the  pupillary  reflex.  The  puff  of  air  replaces,  so  to  speak, 
the  light  as  the  stimulus  that  makes  the  pupil  contract.  Such  re- 
placement of  a  biologically  adequate  stimulus  by  an  artificial  one 
is  known  as  conditioning. 

One  may  generalize  this  idea  of  conditioning— these  mechanical 


PERSPECTIVES  5 

changes  in  the  reactions  of  the  organism— and  attempt  to  explain 
all  of  man's  behavior  in  terms  of  various  series  of  conditioned  re- 
sponses. Even  such  complex  actions  as  getting  married  or  planting 
corn  are  then  broken  down  into  intricate  sets  of  conditioned 
responses.  According  to  such  explanations,  man  is  a  complex 
mechanism:  when  a  given  button  is  pressed  a  given  action  follows. 

Since  man  is  an  animal  organism,  we  may  well  believe  that  all 
changes  in  conduct  and  experience  are  accompanied  by  neuro- 
logical changes.  From  the  biological  viewpoint,  at  any  rate,  it  is 
assumed  that  mental  processes  are  based  on  physiological  processes 
—though  much  of  the  physiology  is  actually  unknown.  This  does 
not,  however,  mean  that  the  conditioning  of  reflexes  is  necessarily 
the  most  important,  much  less  the  only,  mechanism  by  which 
changes  in  behavior  take  place.  Many  experiences  of  the  human 
being  are  not  readily  explained  or  understood  in  such  terms. 

As  a  matter  of  fact,  actual  work  on  conditioning  has,  in  the 
main,  been  limited  to  attempts  to  explain  smalj.  "involuntary  ac- 
tions," like  the  eye  blink,  or  of  certain  animal  behaviors  and  the 
activities  of  small  children  who  have  not  yet  acquired  speech.  A 
generalization  of  "conditioning"  into  an  over-all  explanation  of 
human  behavior— which  overreaches  the  delimited  conditions  and 
actions  on  which  it  is  observationally  based— confuses  the  biologi- 
cally necessary  conditions  of  animal  behavior  with  the  sufficient 
conditions  of  specifically  human  conduct.  By  "explaining"  the  dif- 
fering activities  and  experiences  of  Panamanian  politicians  and 
Chinese  children,  Spanish  generals  and  French  peasants  as  due 
to  the  "difterent  conditioning"  of  their  originally  similar  reflexes, 
we  are  really  explaining  away  the  specific  problems  which  each  of 
these  types  of  persons  present  to  us.  Qonditiouing  as  a  masterO^ 
explanation  of. human  conduct  is  so  general  that  it  accomplishes 
little  Tiiore  than  to  inform  us  that  all  animals,  the  human  as  well 
as  the  ape  and  the  rat,  have  neural  biographies,  that  all  men  are 
neuromujscular  structures,  and  that  these  change  as  men  are  con- 
fronted with  different  physical  environments. 

But  the  mechanical  changes  in  neuromuscular  behavior  which 
conditioning  explains  are  not  all  there  is  to  man.  The  idea  of 
man  as  a  mechanism  is  useful  in  understanding  the  how  of  his 
physical  activity,  but  for  the  why  of  his  conduct,  and  for  the  why 
of  the  mechanism  itself,  we  must  look  further.  In  this  search  we 
can  learn  one  point  from  the  view  of  man  as  "nothing  but"  an  ani- 


b  INTRODUCTORY 

mal  organism.  If  man  is  a  neuromuscular  structure,  all  his  con- 
duct is  controlled,  in  the  sense  of  being  limited,  by  the  mechanical 
structure  of  his  skeleton,  muscles,  and  nerves.  Without  mechanical 
aids,  man  cannot  fly;  he  cannot  sit  down  upon  his  own  stomach. 
The  range  of  his  possible  actions  and  the  co-ordinations  of  his 
body  are  limited  by  the  kind  of  animal  structure  that  he  happens 
to  be.  Different  species  of  animals  are  variously  limited.  The 
grasshopper,  unlike  most  men,  is  not  equipped  to  distinguish  red 
from  yellow  objects;  his  world  is  probably  all  gray.  But  the  grass- 
hopper can  hear  sounds  that  men  (without  mechanical  aids)  can- 
not, for  his  ears  are  differently  made.  Later  we  shall  see  that  all 

"•men  do  not  realize  the  structurally  possible  range  of  perception 
to  the  same  degree  or  in  the  same  way— that  the  possibility,  for 
example,  of  color  discrimination  is  variously  realized  according  to 
such  social  conditions  as  the  vocabularies  we  learn.  But  to  explain 
such  varying  sensitivities,  we  must  avail  ourselves  of  sociological 
as  well  as  biological  explanations. 

In  their  common  biological  limitations,  then,  men  differ  from 
members  of  other  animal  species;  yet  man's  own  structural  range 
is  quite  broad.  Within  the  limits  of  man's  animal  form  lie  the  rich 
diversities  of  conduct  that  make  up  history  and  differentiate  men 
from  one  another  in  different  societies  all  over  the  world.  Insofar 
as  such  constitutional  differences,  inherited  by  men  in  specific  or- 
ganic structures,  may  be  used  in  general  explanations  of  behavior 
and  personality,^  we  must  rest  content  with  the  view  rather  widely 
held  among  clinical  psychiatrists:  "It  is  with  mixed  feelings  of  dis- 
trust and  uneasiness  that  psychiatrists  introduce  factors  of  consti- 
tution into  a  case  study.  If,  after  what  is  believed  to  be  a  'dynamic 
approach'  has  been  exhausted  and  found  wanting,  'constitution' 
becomes  an  insecure  refuge."  -  What  is  here  referred  to  as  a  "dy- 
namic approach"  definitely  involves  a  sociological  model  of  expla- 
nation. 

'-->  Within  the  strictly  biological  viewpoint,  then,  we  see  that  man 
as  an  animal  species  is  structurally  limited.  The  species  limits  the 
motor  behaviors  which  its  members   are  capable   of  performing 

1  We  shall  discuss  such  organic  or  constitutional  differences  as  they  affect 
differing  character  structures  in  Chapter  III:  Organism  and  Psychic  Structure. 

~  Fritz  Kant,  M.D.,  "Integration  of  Constitution  and  Environment  in 
Psychiatry  and  Psychotherapy,"  Diseases  of  the  Nervous  System,  Vol.  IV, 
No.  9   (September  1943). 


PERSPECTIVES  7 

and  the  range  of  sensory  perception  to  which  they  are  open.  Fur-/ 
thermore,  these  structural  limitations  vary  from  one  individual  or- 
ganism to  another  within  the  species,  according  to  individual  con- 
stitutional differences. 

When  we  say  that  man  is  an  organism,  we  imply  that  he  is  some- 
thing more  than  a  mechanical  structure  with  differing  limitations. 
Seeing  the  infant  wiggle  and  twitch  about,  we  impute  impulses  or 
will  to  it;  and  as  its  wigglings  and  twitchings  become  more  definite 
and  co-ordinated,  we  tend  to  ascribe  various  urges,  instincts,  or 
drives  as  lying  within  the  organism  and  impelling  it  to  action.  The 
fact  that  the  organism  sets  itself  in  motion  is  then  explained  by 
one  or  the  other  of  these  driving  forces  which  we  have  imputed  to 
be  naturally  within  the  organism.  Such  an  explanation,  as  Gordon 
Allport  has  put  it,  is  intended  to  answer  the  question:  "What  is 
it  that  sets  the  stream  of  activity  into  motion?"  ^  It  is  the  problem 
of  motivation  taken  in  general,  usually  put  on  the  level  of  biological 
factors.  It  is,  as  John  Dewey  has  said,  "absurd  to  ask  what  induces 
a  man  to  activity  generally  speaking.  He  is  an  active  being  and  that 
is  all  there  is  to  say  on  that  score."  *  The  very  asking  of  the  question 
in  such  a  general  way  assumes  that  the  organism  is  naturally  in  a 
state  of  rest,  and  hence,  like  a  machine,  requires  an  "external"  force 
to  move  it,  to  push  "it"  into  action. 

But  man  is  not  an  inert  machine:  organism  implies  movement; 
our  characterization  of  it  as  possessing  impulse  or  will  is  an  essen- 
tial inference. 

This  spontaneous  movement  characterizes  not  only  the  organism 
but  also  each  of  the  various  organs  that  make  it  up.  Even  in  sleep 
man  seldom  rests  like  a  log,  and  when  he  is  awake  his  perceiving 
eye  is  naturally  in  motion.  By  altering  the  direction  in  which  he 
looks,  and  by  changing  his  focus  to  cover  near  or  distant  objects, 
he  scans  his  world.  He  must  learn  to  fix  and  manage  his  gaze,  like 
the  lens  of  a  camera.  The  school  child  does  not  naturally  hold  his 
eyes  on  the  teacher  nor  keep  his  hands  at  rest.  To  sit  still  is  an 
accomplished  effort  for  which  he  must  be  disciplined. 

The  explanation  of  conduct  by  "instinct"  carries  us  beyond  the 
general  inference  that  the  organism  is  impulsive.  If  we  observe 

^Personality:  A  Psychological  Interpretation  (New  York:  Holt,  1937), 
p.  110. 

'^  Human  Nature  and  Conduct   (New  York:   Holt,   1922),  p.    119. 


8  INTRODUCTORY 

the  organism  engaging  in  sexual  behavior  or  the  ingestion  of  food, 
we  may  say  that  these  specific  activities  are  caused  by  instincts: 
biologically  fixed  ways  of  behaving  which  are  innate  within  the 
organism.  The  term  instinct  thus  includes  more  meanings  than 
any  one  term  properly  should:  it  is  used  to  refer  to  (i)  the  cause 
of  an  activity;  (2)  the  goal  of  the  activity;  and  (3)  the  rigid 
activity  itself.^ 

The  theory  oi  instincts,  v^^hen  logically  assessed,  does  not  possess 
any  explanatory  value.  First,  one  observes  men  engaging  in  a  cer- 
tain activity.  From  this  observation  one  infers  the  existence  of  an 
instinct.  Then,  this  inferred  element  is  separated  from  the  observed 
activity  and  posited  in  the  organism  as  a  force  or  cause  of  its  activ- 
ity. By  this  procedure  one  treats  an  alternative  name  for  some 
activity  as  an  explanation  of  it.  Thus,  if  we  say  that  men  eat  because 
of  the  "instinct  to  eat,"  or  build  houses  because  of  the  "instinct  to 
build  houses,"  we  are  merely  giving  another  name  to  the  observed 
activities  of  eating  and  building.  Such  "explanations"  are  tautolog- 
ical. Instincts,  once  supposed  to  be  biological  entities,  are  actually 
hypothetical  inferences  from  observed  activities.  As  such,  they 
cannot  be  taken  as  logical  explanations,  nor  held  to  be  "causes" 
of  behavior.*^ 

The  notion  of  instinct  encompasses  awareness  of  the  goal  of 
activity.  Thus,  since  instincts  are  held  to  be  biologically  innate, 
goals  must  be  biologically  innate."  And  this  cannot  be  the  case. 
For  while  normal  men  are  everywhere  quite  similar  physiologically, 
the  conduct  patterns  which  make  up  the  behavior  of  men  are 
everywhere  quite  different.  The  biological  structure  and  capacities 
of  man  seem  not  to  have  changed  conspicuously  for  some  thousands 
of  years,  yet  man's  behavior  and  feelings  have  varied  widely.  One 

5  Abram  Kardiner,  The  Individual  and  His  Society  (New  York:  Columbia 
Univ.  Press,  1939). 

^  This  statement  draws  upon  A.  F.  Bentley,  who  in  1908  saw  clearly  the 
logical  deficiencies  of  explanation  by  instinct.  See  his  The  Process  of  Govern- 
ment (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1908),  Section  1.  A  brief  but  acute 
resume  of  the  argument  against  the  conception  was  written  in  1921  by  Ells- 
worth Faris,  "Are  Instincts  Data  or  Hypotheses?",  reprinted  in  his  book,  The 
Nature  of  Human  Nature   (New  York:   McGraw-Hill,   1937). 

"  Thus,  VVilHam  James  defined  the  term  as  follows:  "Instinct  is  usually 
defined  as  the  faculty  of  acting  in  such  a  way  as  to  produce  certain  ends, 
without  foresight  of  the  ends,  and  without  previous  education  in  the 
performance." 


PERSPECTIVES  9 

returns  from  a  survey  of  ethnography  and  history  with  a  fuller 
realization  of  the  relativity  of  men's  acts  and  experiences.  "Homo 
sapiens  of  the  modern  type,"  Morris  Opler  puts  it,  "has  changed 
physically  hardly  at  all  in  the  30,000  years  or  more  of  his  existence," 
yet,  especially  in  the  last  6,000  years  of  this  period,  men's  behavior 
and  character,  his  technical  accomplishments  and  social  techniques 
have  changed  in  deep-going  and  rapid  ways.  The  cultural  may 
not  be  reduced  to,  and  hence  explained  by,  the  organic."* 

The  enormous  variety  of  specific  activities  which  make  up  the 
histories  of  biologically  similar  men  forces  us  to  acknowledge  that 
the  objects  and  goals  of  behavior  are  not  biologically  given,  but 
are  derived  from  the  environment  in  which  men  act.  Both  ends 
and  means  of  conduct  are  diverse  and  changeable.  Neither  man's 
values  and  purposes,  nor  his  ways  and  means  of  achieving  them 
are  common  to  all  men,  nor  stable  in  the  sequence  of  generations. 
Indeed,  such  regularities  of  behavior  as  we  may  observe  in  men 
are  best  described  in  terms  of  their  goals  or  end-situations  rather 
than  in  terms  of  any  constant  set  of  "urges"  somehow  "lying  in" 
the  organism  and  "back  of"  their  conduct  regularities.  What  we 
are  aware  of  through  our  bodily  senses  is  limited  by  the  specific 
societies  in  which  the  human  animal  is  born  and  how  and  what 
this  society  trains  him  to  see  and  hear  and  act  toward.  To  act  one 
must  have  the  proper  apparatus;  but  this  apparatvis  only  limits  and 
facilitates;  it  does  not  determine  man's  actions. 

There  is  usually  a  direct  correlation  between  an  act  and  its  ob- 
ject: we  act  towards  something  when  it  is  a  goal,  away  from  it 
when  it  is  not.  As  we  have  seen,  the  range  of  objects  to  which 
an  organism  is  sensitive  varies  from  species  to  species  and  varies 
further  within  given  species.  These  objects  involve,  as  George 
Mead  has  said,  a  "content  toward  which  the  individual  is  sus- 
ceptible as  a  stimulus."  ^  It  is  these  objects,  toward  which  man 
learns  to  be  sensitive,  that  are  important  in  explaining  the  diver- 
sities and  regularities  of  the  specific  conduct  of  man.  No  inventory 
of  conveniently  catalogued  biological  elements  in  man's  organism 

*  See  Morris  Opler,  "Cultural  and  Organic  Conceptions  in  Contemporary 
World  History,"  American  Anthropologist,  Vol.  46,  No.  4,  October-December, 
1944,  which  contains  an  excellent  discussion  of  A.  L.  Kroeber's  classic  1917 
essay,  "The  Super-Organic." 

9  "Social  Psychology  as  Counterpart  to  Physiological  Science,"  Psychological 
Bulletin,  Vol.  VI,  pp.  401-08. 


lO  INTRODUCTORY 

will  enable  us  to  predict  or  account  for  the  varied  and  changing 
activities  in  which  men  in  different  societies  engage.  The  diversity 

y.  of  conduct  cannot  be  adequately  explained  by  a  study  of  men 
I  merely  as  individual  organisms.  At  an  early  age,  infants  lose  the 
ability  to  discriminate  between  poison  and  edible  food.  Possibly 
man— like  domesticated  animals— has  lost  the  complex  instincts  of 
his  "natural"  orientation.  At  any  rate,  domestic  animals  differ  from 
their  "wild"  counterparts  essentially  in  that  domestication  has 
disintegrated  the  instincts  which  linked  them  to  their  natural 
habitats. 

From  the  biological  point  of  view,  then,  man  as  a  species  and 
men  as  individuals  are  seen  as  organisms  ( i )  whose  action  is 
structurally  limited,  who  are   equipped  with  certain  mechanical 

^  responses,  and  (2)  who  possess  undefined  impulses,  which  may  be 
defined  and  specified  by  a  wide  range  of  social  objects.  What 
these  objects  may  be  is  not  determined  by  man  as  an  organism. 

2.  The  Sociological  Model 

If  we  shift  our  view  from  the  external  behavior  of  individual 
organisms  and  from  explanations  of  such  behavior  in  terms  of 
physiological  elements  and  mechanisms,  and  view  man  as  a  person 
who  acts  with  and  against  other  persons,  we  may  then  ( 1 )  examine 
the  patterns  of  conduct  which  men  enact  together,  and  (2)  avail 
ourselves  of  the  direct  experiences  which  persons  have  of  one  an- 
other and  of  themselves.  At  its  minimum,  social  conduct  consists 
of  the  actions  of  one  person  oriented  to  another,  and  most  of  the 
actions  of  men  are  of  this  sort.  Manjjs  agtion  \s_  inj£fpersonal.  It 
is  often  informed  by  awareness  of  other  actors  and  directly  oriented 
to  their  expectations  and  to  anticipations  of  their  behavior. 

Out  of  the  metaphors  of  poets  and  philosophers,  who  have 
likened  man's  conduct  to  that  of  the  stage  actor,  sociologists  have 
fashioned  analytical  tools.  Long-used  phrases  readily  come  to  mind: 
"playing  a  role"  in  the  "great  theater  of  public  life,"  to  move  "in 
the  limelight,"  the  "theater  of  War,"  the  "stage  is  all  set."  More 
technically,  the  concept  "role"  refers  to  ( 1 )  units  of  conduct  which 
by  their  recurrence  stand  out  as  regularities  and  (2)  which  are 
oriented  to  the  conduct  of  other  actors.  These  recurrent  interactions 
form  patterns  of  mutually  oriented  conduct. 
^  By  definition,  roles  are  interpersonal,  that  is,  oriented  to   the 


PERSPECTIVES  11 

conduct  and  expectatiorLS_  of  _others.  These  others,  who  expect  things 
of  us,  are  also  playing  roles:  we  expect  them  to  do  things  in  cer- 
tain ways  and  to  refrain  from  doing  and  feeling  things  in  other  ways. 
Interpersonal  situations  are  thus^bui]t^ujg^and_  sets  of  roles  held  in 
line  by  mutual  expectationjapprQbdtiQnja:nd  disfavor. 

Much  of  our  social  conduct,  as  we  know  from  direct  experience, 
is  enacted  in  order  to  meet  the  expectations  of  others.  In  this  sense, 
our  enemies  often  control  us  as  much  as  our  friends.  The  father 
of  a  patriarchal  family  is  expected  by  his  wife  and  children  to 
act  in  certain  ways  when  confronted  with  given  situations,  and  he 
in  turn  expects  them  to  act  in  certain  regular  ways.  Being  ac- 
quainted with  these  simple  facts  about  patriarchal  families  we 
expect  regularities  of  conduct  from  each  of  their  members,  and 
having  experienced  family  situations,  we  expect,  with  some  degree 
of  probability,  that  each  of  these  members  will  experience  his 
place  and  his  self  in  a  certain  way. 

Man  as  a  person  is_an  historical  creation,  and  can  most  readily  v, 
be  understood  in  terms  of  the  roles  which  he  enacts  and  incorpp-  n 
rates.  These  roles  are  limited  by  the  kind  of  social  institutions  in 
which  he  happens  to  be  bom  and  in  which  he  matures  into  an 
adult.  His  memory,  his  sense  of  time  and  space,  his  perception,  his 
motives,  his  conception  of  his  self  ...  his  psychological  functions 
are  shaped  and  steered  by  the  specific  configuration  of  roles  which 
he  incorporates  from  his  society^ 

Perhaps  the  most  important  of  tbese  features  of  man  is  his  image 
of  his  self,  his  idea  of  what  kind  of  person  he  is.  This  experience 
of  self  is  a  crucially  interpersonal  one.  Its  basic  organization  is 
reflected  from  surrounding  persons  to  whose  approbation  and  criti- 
cism one  pays   attention. 

What  we  think  of  ourselves  is  decisively  influenced  by  what 
others  think  of  us.  Their  attitudes  of  approval  and  of  disapproval 
guide  us  in  learning  to  play  the  roles  we  are  assigned  or  which 
we  assume.'lBy  internalizing  these  attitudes  of  others  toward  us  and 
our  conduct  we  not  only  gain  new  roles,  but  in  time  an  image  of 
our  selves.  Of  course,  man's  "looking-glass  self"  may  be  a  true  or 
a  distorted  reflection  of  his  actual  self.  Yet  those  from  whom  a 
man  continually  seeks  approval  are  important  determinants  of 
what  kind  of  man  he  is  becoming.  If  a  young  lawyer  begins  to 
feel  satisfaction  from  the  approval  of  the  boss  of  the  local  political 
machine,  if  the  labels  which  this  boss  uses  to  describe  his  behavior 


12  INTRODUCTORY 

matter  a  lot  to  the  lawyer,  he  is  being  steered  into  new  roles  and 
into  a  new  image  of  his  self  by  the  party  machine  and  its  boss. 
Their  values  may  in  time  become  his  own  and  he  will  apply  them 
not  only  to  other  men  but  to  his  own  actions  as  well.^"  Xhe_self, 
—^  Harry  Stack  Sullivan  onga  said,  is  made  up  of  the  reflected  ap- 
pK^isalsjiE-etfe^w:^ 

^  The  concept  of  role  does  not  of  course  imply  a  one  person-one 
role  equation.  One  person  may  play  many  different  roles,  and  each 
of  these  roles  may  be  a  segment  of  the  different  institutions  and 
interpersonal  situations  in  which  the  person  moves.  A  corporation 
executive  acts  differently  in  his  office  than  in  his  child's  nursery. 
An  adolescent  girl  enacts  a  different  role  when  she  is  at  a  party 
composed  of  members  of  her  own  clique  than  when  she  is  at  her 
family's  breakfast  table.  Moreover,  the  luxury  of  a  certain  image 
of  self  implied  in  the  party  role  is  not  often  possible  in  her  family 
circle.  In  the  family  circle  the  party  role  might  be  amusing,  as  a 
charming  attempt  at  sophistication  "beyond  her  age  and  experi- 
ence," but  at  the  party  it  might  bring  prestige  and  even  the  adula- 
tion of  young  males.  She  cannot,  usually,  act  out  the  self-conception 
of  a  long-suffering  lover  before  her  grandfather,  but  she  can  when 
she  is  alone  with  her  young  man. 

The  chance  to  display  emotional  gestures,  and  even  to  feel  them, 
varies  with  one's  status  and  class  position.  For  emotional  gestures, 
expected  by  others  and  by  one's  self,  form  important  features  of 
many  social  roles.  The  Victorian  lady  could  dramatize  certain  emo- 
tions in  a  way  that  today  would  be  considered  silly,  if  not  hysterical. 
Yet  the  working  girl  who  was  her  contemporary  was  not  as  likely 

— *^  (i  lo^The  mechanism  by  which  persons  thus  intemahze  roles  and  the  attitudes 
of  others  is  language.  Language  is  composed  of  gestures,  normally  verbal, 
which  call  forth  similar  responses  in  two  individuals.  Without  such  gestures 
man  could  not  incorporate  the  attitudes  of  others,  and  could  not  so  easily 
make  these  attitudes  a  condition  of  his  own  leiiming  and  enactment  of  roles 
of  his   own   image   of  self. 

These  conceptions  will  be  discussed  in  greater  detail  in  Chapters  III: 
Organism  and  Psychic  Structure  and  IV:  The  Person.  Here  we  are  only 
concerned  with  setting  forth  in  the  most  general  way  the  sociological  model 
of  explanation. 

11  "Conceptions  of  Modern  Psychiatry,"  Fstjchiatnj,  Vol.  Ill,  No.  i  ( Febru- 
ary 1949),  pp.  10-11.  Compare  also  C.  H.  Cooley's  Human  Nature  and  the 
Social  Order  (rev.  ed.;  New  York:  Scribner's,  1922).  The  tradition  is  well 
documented  by  Fay  B.  Karpf,  American  Social  Psychology  (New  York: 
McGraw-HiU,   1932). 


PERSPECTIVES  1^ 

to  faint  as  was  the  lady;  there  would  probably  not  have  been  any- 
one to  catch  the  working  girl.  During  the  nineties  in  America  it 
was  expected  that  women  who  were  also  ladies,  that  is,  members 
of  an  upper  status  group,  would  faint  upon  very  exciting  occasions. 
The  role  of  the  delicate  and  fainting  lady  was  involved  in  the 
very  being  of  a  lady.^-  But  the  "same"  occasions  would  not  elicit 
fainting  on  the  part  of  the  ladies'  maid,  who  did  not  conceive  of 
her  "place,"  and  of  her  self,  as  a  fainting  lady;  fainting  requires  a 
certain  amount  of  leisure  and  gentlemanly  attention,  and  accord- 
ingly offers  opportunities  to  the  gentleman  to  demonstrate  that 
chivalry  is  not  dead. 

The   roles   allowed   and   expected,   the   self-images   which  they  ") 
entail,   and   the   consequences   of  these   roles   and   images   on   the  ^ 
persons  we  are  with  are  firmly  embedded  in  a  social  context.  Inner    I 
psychological  changes  and  the  institutional  controls  of  a  society  are    / 
thus  interlinked. 

(_An  institution  is  an  organization  of  roles,  which  means  that  the 
roles  carry  different  degrees  of  authority,  so  that  one  of  the  roles— 
we  may  call  it  the  "head"  role— is  understood  and  accepted  by  the 
members  of  the  other  roles  as  guaranteeing  the  relative  permanence 
of  the  total  conduct  pattern.  An  institution  is  thus  ( i )  an  organiza- 
tion of  roles,  (2)  one  or  more  of  which  is  understood  to  serve  the^  ^ 
maintenance  nf  thfi_Jotal  set  of  jroles. 

The  "head  role"  of  an  institution  is  very  important  in  the  psychic 
life  of  the  other  members  of  the  institution.  What  "the  head"  thinks 
of  them  in  their  respective  roles,  or  what  they  conceive  him  to 
think,  is  internalized,  that  is,  taken  over,  by  them.  In  a  strictly 
patriarchal  family,  the  head,  the  father,  is  looked  up  to;  his  is  that 
most  important  attitude  toward  the  child  that  may  determine  the 
child's  attitude  toward  his,  the  child's,  own  conduct  and  perhaps 
toward  his  self:  in  taking  over  this  attitude  the  child  builds  up  an 
"other"  within  his  self,  and  the  attitude  he  conceives  this  other  to 
have  toward  him  is  a  condition  for  his  attitude  toward  his  own  self. 
Other  persons  in  other  roles  also  have  attitudes  toward  him  and 
each  of  these  may  be  internalized,  and  eventually  form  segments  of 
his  self-conception.  But  the  attitude  of  the  head  of  the  major  insti- 
tution jn  which  we  play  a  role  is  a  decisive  one  in  our  own  matura- 
tion. If  "he  says  it  is  all  right,"  we  feel  secure  in  what  we  are  doing 

1- Cf.  Ralph  Linton,  The  Study  of  Man  (New  York:  Appleton-Century, 
1936). 


14  INTRODUCTORY 

and  how  we  are  conceiving  our  self.  When  his  attitudes  are  taken 
over  into  the  self,  this  head  constitutes  in  a  concrete  form,  a  "par- 
ticular other."  But  he  is  not  seen  merely  as  a  particular  person;  he 
is  the  symbol  and  the  "mouth  piece"  of  the  entire  institution.  In 
him  is  focused  the  "final"  attitudes  toward  our  major  roles  and 
our  self  within  this  institution;  he  sums  them  up,  and  when  we 
take  over  these  attitudes  and  expectations  we  control  our  institu- 
tional conduct  in  terms  of  them.  It  is  by  means  of  such  internalized 
others  that  our  conduct,  our  playing  of  roles  within  institutions, 
is  "self-controlled." 
JU  By  choosing  the  social  role  as  a  major  concept  we  are  able  to 
reconstruct  thejnner  experience  of  the  person  as  well  as  the  insti- 
tutions which  make  up  an  historical  social  structure.  For  man  as 
a  person  (from  the  Latin  persona,  meaning  "mask" )  js  composed 
of  the  specifiin^jT)^|es-which- h<»-ftRac^t.s  and  of  the  effects  of  enacting 
these  roles  upon  his  self.  And  society  as  a.^ocial  structure  is  com- 
posedL_Df_CQljes-as  segments  variously  eomhiiie.d  in  its  total  circle 
of  institutions.  The  organization  of  roles  is  important  in  building 
up  a  particuTar  social  structure;  it  also  has  psychological  implica- 
tions for  the  persons  who  act  out  the  social  structure. 
/  Most  of  the  various  interpersonal  situations  in  which  we  are 
involved  exist  within  institutions,  which  make  up  a  social  structure; 
and  changes  of  social  structure  make  up  the  main  course  of  human 
history.  In  order  to  understand  men's  conduct^aod  experience  we 
must  recnnstrnnt  the  historical  social  stiaictLires  in  which  they  play 
roles  and  acquire  selyejS..EQr  such  regularity  of  conduct,  and  of  the 
motives  for  this  conduct,  as  we  may  find  will  rest  upon  the  his- 
torical regularities  of  these  social  structures,  rather  than  upon  any 
suprahistorical,  biological  elements  assumed  to  be  innate  and  con- 
stant within  the  organism.  From  the  sociological  point  of  view,  man 
as  a  person  is  a  social-historical  creationTTf  his  view  of  his  self 
and  of  his  motives  is  intimately  connectecFwith  the  roles  which  are 
available  to  him  and  which  he  incorporates,  then  we  may  not  ex- 
pect to  learn  much  that  is  very  concrete  about  individual  men 
unless  we  investigate  a  number  of  his  specific  roles  in  a  number 
of  varied  social-historical  settingsT^ 

Rather  than  constant  elements  within  a  physiological  organism, 
the  sociologist  rests  his  primary  model  of  explanation  upon  the 
interpersonal  situations,  and  in  the  last  analysis,  the  social  struc- 
tures within  which  persons  live  out  their  lives. 


PERSPECTIVES  1$ 

If,  due  to  changes  in  the  organization  of  institutions  in  a  society, 
the  patriarchal  family  should  decline  in  importance,  the  weight 
of  the  father  as  a  social  control  in  the  inner  life  of  family  members 
would  decline.  Thus,  the  institutional  center  of  social  control  within 
ourselves  may  shift.  This  is  what  happens  as  a  child  matures, 
grows  up.  For,  sociologically,  "growing  up"  means  the  relinquishing 
of  some  roles  and  the  incorporating  of  others.  With  this  objective 
shift  in  the  institutional  roles  we  play,  there  is  an  accompanying 
shift  in  the  institutional  center  of  social  control  within  the  person. 
The  child  may  no  longer  look  only  to  his  parents,  but  also  to  the 
leader  of  a  gang  or  to  a  star  of  sports  or  movies  to  sanction  his 
new  roles  and  the  conception  of  his  self  which  goes  with  them. 

The  inner  feelings,  the  entire  psychology  and  outlook,  of  mem- 
bers of  a  stratum  of  small  entrepreneurs  may  vary  enormously  ac- 
cording to  the  historical  positions  and  changes  of  such  strata.  In 
the  growing  cities  of  the  American  Middle  West,  in  the  middle  of 
the  nineteenth  century,  the  hopeful  outlook  and  expansive  view 
which  small  enterprisers  possessed  were  functions  of  what  was 
occurring  in  the  social,  and  especially  the  economic,  structure  of 
which  they  were  a  segment.  The  twentieth-century  members  of 
such  strata  may  experience  anxiety  and  depressive  fear  of  being 
engulfed  and  pushed  down  in  the  social  scale  by  the  increasing 
power  and  scope  of  large  corporations  and  big  government.  To 
grasp  these  different  inner  feelings— self-confidence  or  deep  anxiety 
— reqiirres  a  reconstruction  of  the  historical  shift  from  one  phase  of 
capitalist  economy  to  another.  For  it  is  this  shift  that  carries  with 
it  changes  in  the  psychological  process:es~  of  -members  of  various 
strata/'T^rsir^as  economists  often  trace  the  shiftings  of  tax  loads 
among  various  income  groups  in  the  processes  of  economic  change, 
so,  in  a  similar  way,  the  social  psychologist  may  trace  the  shiftings 
of  psychic  strains  and  stresses  which  are  deposited  in  various 
groups  within  a  society  by  the  structural  changes  which  it  under- 
goes. V^.^A.»^^' -  A-'— ■' 

The  difference  between  the  primary  interests  of  the  social  psy- 
chologist and  the  physiologist  becomes  obvious  if  we  consider,  as 
an  example,  their  respective  approaches  to  the  matter  of  hunger. 
To  the  physiologist,  hunger  is  always  hunger;  his  task  is  to  trace 
the  possible  connections  bet\veen  the  cravings  of  hunger  as  stated 
by  the  subject  and  the  physiological  processes  apparently  going 


l6  INTRODUCTORY 

on  in  the  organism.  And  he  does  this  quite  irrespective  of  the 
institutional  context  and  social  evaluation  of  "hunger"  by  the  per- 
son. "Hunger"  involves  a  relation  betv^een  the  tremblings  of  the 
stomach  wall  and  the  feelings  of  its  pangs,  but  such  hunger  proc- 
esses are  relevant  to  the  social  psychologist  primarily  in  specific 
varieties  of  social  contexts.  For  whatever  the  physiological  proc- 
esses of  hunger  may  be,  the  social  psychologist  is  interested  in  the 
meaning  of  hunger  to  the  persons  involved.  The  use  of  hunger 
strikes  by  suffragettes  in  prison  or  by  political  criminals  as  a 
weapon  against  instituted  authority,  the  famine  imposed  on  inmates 
of  concentration  camps,  the  organized  and  periodic  fasting  of 
monks  and  nuns  in  occidental  religious  orders,  the  old-fashioned 
hunger  of  the  poor  and  destitute,  the  commercial  records  of  forty 
days  and  forty  nights  of  hunger  piled  up  by  competing  hunger 
artists,  the  feasts  of  a  northwest  Indian  potlatch  or  of  a  Southern 
political  barbecue,  or  a  medieval  European  coronation  meal— all 
of  these  types  of  feasting  and  fasting  involve  a  wide  range  of 
meanings  and  hence  of  motivations,  irrespective  of  the  similarity 
of  the  gastric  juices  involved. 

In  similar  manner,  the  anatomy  and  physiology  involved  in  sex 
become  of  interest  to  the  social  psychologist  only  as  the  prerequisite 
for  behavior.  They  must  be  mediated  through  love,  eroticism,  types 
of  passion,  or  other  institutionally  elaborated  patterns  of  conduct 
or  feeling.  In  the  perspective  of  physiological  psychology,  legiti- 
mate and  illicit  love  involve  identical  processes,  whereas  to  the 
social  psychologist  these  two  kinds  of  situations  involve  conven- 
tional and  legal  definitions  which  make  for  significantly  distinct 
motivation  and  conduct. 

Aging  is  a  physiological  process,  as  is  hunger.  But  age  is  im- 
portant to  the  social  psychologist  not  as  a  chemical  and  biological 
process,  but  as  the  object  of  insurance  tables  or  as  relevant  to  the 
chances  of  being  employed  in  given  occupations.  Old  age,  in  short, 
is  sociologically  interesting  for  what  people  make  of  it,  whether 
they  honor  the  grand  old  man,  or  despise  the  mean  old  fogey. 

Certain  biological  capacities  and  traits,  of  course,  often  become 
particularly  relevant  to  the  demands  set  up  by  new  roles.  Thus,  if 
a  society  needs  aviators  in  order  to  fight  an  air  war,  those  individ- 
uals who  have  good  biological  capacities  for  "balance"  have  in- 
creased chances  to  assume  these  roles.  The  sense  of  balance  is 
located  in  the  biology  of  the  ear.  Swiftly  changing  atmospheric 


PERSPECTIVES  1/ 

pressures  also  aflFect  in  rather  different  ways  different  types  of 
luiman  organisms.  In  societies  witli  such  teclmologically  deter- 
mined social  roles,  such  organic  differences  become  relevant  pre- 
requisites, whereas  in  preindustrial  societies  the  same  individual 
differences  would  be  irrelevant.  What  specific  aspects  of  man's 
biological  nature  become  prerequisites  for  role-taking  are  socially 
and  technologically  determined,  and  accordingly,  those  aspects 
which  become  relevant  to  our  explanations  of  conduct,  are  thus 
determined. 

In  a  somewhat  similar  way  the  biological  differences  between 
men  and  women  are  taken  into  account  by  the  social  psychologist 
only  insofar  as  they  become  relevant  to  conduct  by  virtue  of  their 
evaluations  in  different  societies.  A  woman  is  not  only  a  woman: 
she  is  a  wife,  a  nun,  a  railway  conductor,  or  a  parachutist  with  a 
bright  new  deadly  weapon.  She  may  drive  a  four-ton  truck  or  nag 
an  unsuccessful  husband.  There  are  greatly  differing  roles  for  men, 
too,  ranging  from  those  which  gain  a  living,  and  which  the  Jap- 
anese honor  with  a  two-handed  sword,  to  the  eighteenth-century 
fop  with  his  effete  gestures  and  niceties  of  taste.  No  doubt  there 
are  roles  which  women  cannot  fulfill  and  others  which  men  are 
incapable  of  enacting.  Although  a  man  may  be  the  sociological 
mother  of  a  child,  catering  to  its  needs,  he  cannot  actually  give 
birth  to  one— although  he  may,  in  practicing  the  couvade,  hysteri- 
cally experience  birth  pangs.  Most  women  cannot  stand  physical 
exertions  of  bodily  work  as  long  or  as  intensively  as  can  most  men. 
Yet  many  statements  about  psychological  traits  believed  to  be  due  to 
sexual  differences  appear  on  second  thought  to  be  ideologies  which 
identify  or  at  least  confuse  social  traits  with  biological  differences.^^. 
For  apart  from  the  reproductive  functions  and  extremely  heavy 
work,  the  range  of  conduct  patterns  which  are  interchangeable  be- 
tween the  sexes  is  very  broad,  and  it  may  become  broader  as  social 
history  unrolls. 

The  differences  between  biological  and  sociological  types  of  ex- 
ploration may  be  further  revealed  in  the  matter  of  authority  and 
leadership.  In  an  external,  behaviorist  manner,  the  term  authority 
describes  a  situation  in  which  one  or  several  organisms  will  obey 

'3  See  Viola  Klein,  The  Feminine  Character  (New  York:  International  Uni\s. 
Press,   1949)- 


l8  INTRODUCTORY 

another  one.  Thus,  groups  may  jump  to  rigidity  when  one  man 
shouts  "atten-tion."  This  is  a  purely  objective  definition.  It  grasps 
what  is  observed  in  the  behavior  of  two  or  more  individuals.  This 
might  be  further  explored  biologically:  We  might  try  to  correlate 
the  size  of  the  organism  who  is  obeyed  with  the  probability  that 
he  will  be  obeyed;  the  larger  he  is,  the  higher  the  probability  is 
that  he  will  be  obeyed;  or  we  might  try  to  compare  some  measure 
of  the  vitality  of  the  leader's  constitution  with  the  hypothetically 
lesser  vitality  of  the  bodies  of  the  followers.  Such  external  observa- 
tions and  physiological  hypotheses  are  about  all  that  we  can  do 
with  animals  and  with  prelingual  children. 

We  have,  however,  another  source  of  information  when  we  deal 
with  persons  who  possess  language,  and  we  would  be  foolish  not 
to  avail  ourselves  of  it.  It  is  simply  the  direct  experience  such  per- 
sons have  of  the  authority  situation  by  those  who  enact  it.  Why 
do  they  obey?  What  feelings  do  they  experience  when  they  do  so? 
Do  they  feel  compelled  to  obey,  do  they  experience  fear?  And,  if 
they  do  not  obey,  are  they  full  of  enthusiasm  or  anxiety,  remorse 
or  elation?  Such  questions  as  these  cannot  be  answered  merely 
by  observing  the  external  behavior  of  the  organisms,  nor  by  probing 
their  physiology  .(We  must  study  the  inner  experiences  and  feelings 
of  the  persons  who  play  various  roles  in  the  interpersonal  situa- 
tions of  authority.  And  to  do  this  adequately  we  must  reconstruct 
the  roles  of  followers  and  leaders  in  different  societies,  and  the 
symbols  they  use  and  believe  in. 

The  view  that  the  biological  or  constitutional  aspects  of  man  are 
irrelevant  and  that  everything  depends  upon  social  acquisitions  and 
training  may  be  just  as  dogmatic— however  fashionable— as  the  view 
that  such  biological  features  are  the  major  determinants  of  man's 
character.  The  conflict  of  these  two  viewpoints  is  not  resolved 
merely  by  the  slogan  that  personality  is,  "after  all,"  an  integra- 
tion of  biological  constitution  and  sociological  environment. 
"Though  proportion  is  the  final  secret,"  E.  M.  Forster  has  remarked, 
"to  espouse  it  at  the  outset  is  to  insure  sterility."  What  we  want 
to  know  is  precisely  how  one  or  the  other  of  these  two  general 
forces  influences  the  total  individual. 


CHAPTER 
I   1 


Character  and  Social  Structure 


BIOLOGICAL  explanations  of  human  nature  and  conduct  cen- 
ter upon  the  notion  of  the  organism;  sociological  explanation  upon 
that  of  the  person.  In  connection  with  the  organism,  we  have  dis- 
cussed  conditioning  and  instinct  as  explanatory  mechanisms;  in 
definin^and  elaborating  the  notion  of  the  person  we  have  discussed 
roles  and  institutions.  Now,  both  organism  and  person— or  other 
terms  standing  for  similar  viewpoints— must  be  understood  and 
used  in  any  adequate  conception  of  the  human  individual.  But  each 
of  them  must  be  broken  down  and  linked  with  other  terms,  and 
each  must  be  more  precisely  linked  with  the  other.  If  we  did  not 
so  elaborate  and  refine  them,  we  would  find  that  our  vocabulary 
was  too  gross  for  the  sort  of  work  we  want  to  undertake.  In  this 
chapter,  which  completes  our  introduction,  we  shall  lay  out,  in  an 
over-all  and  hence  a  rather  general  way,  other  features  of  character 
and  of  social  structure,  which  will  enable  us  to  complete  our  first 
view  of  these  conceptions. 

1.  Components  of  Character  Structure 

To  try  to  understand  the  individual  only  as  organism  and  as 
person  is  to  leave  out  an  area  of  experience  and  observation  that 
is  very  much  a  part  of  any  adequate  portrayal:  the  direct  world 
of  emotion  and  will  and  perception,  of  rage  and  determination  and 
anger,  of  sight,  sound,  and  fury.  Physiologists,^  of  course,  do  study 
such  phenomena,  but  psychiatrists  and  psychoanalysts  have  been 
most  directly  concerned  with  man  as  an  emotional  and  willful  crea- 
ture, in  short,  as  a  "psychic  structure." 

1  See  Chapter  III:  Organism  and  Psychic  Structure,  Section  3:  Feeling  and 
Emotion. 


20  INTRODUCTORY 

X  We  shall  use  this  term,  psychic  structure,  to  refer  to  man  con- 
ceived as  ^n  integratiQn  of  perception,  emotion,  and  impulse.  Of 
course  there  are  other  psychic  functions,  memory  and  imagination, 
for  example;  but  we  shall  limit  our  term  at  this  point.  For  our  pur- 
pose, "psychic  structure"  will  refer  to  when,  how,  and  why  man 
feels,  perceives,  and  wills. 

If  the  human  organism  did  not  possess  a  chromatic  eye,  it  could 
not  distinguish  colors;  if  it  were  not  equipped  with  a  certain 
glandular  and  nervous  apparatus,  it  probably  could  not  experience 
rage  and  hate;  without  undefined  impulses,  what  is  experienced 
as  purpose  or  willfulness  could  not  occur.  Clearly,  sensation,  im- 
pulse, and  feeling  are  in  some  way  rooted  in  the  animal  organism 
and  in  its  specialized  organs;  it  may  not  be  so  apparent  that  they 
are  also  linked  to  man  as  a  person,  where  they  are  revealed  to 
u&^as  perception,  purpose,  and  emotion. 

\Jp  In  order  for  inner  feelings  to  become  emotions,  these  feelings 
must  be  linked  with  socially  recognizable  gestures,  and  the  person 
must  become  aware  of  them  as  related  to  his  self.  The  same  physical 
environment  and  the  same  physiology,  for  all  we  know,  may  be 
present,  but  in  one  case  these  conditions  may  lead  to  fear  and 
flight,  and  in  another,  to  rage  and  attack.  The  difference  be- 
tween the  two  experiences  and  behaviors  cannot  be  adequately 
explained  physically  or  organically.  [The  social  definition  of  the 
occasion,  the  meaning  it  comes  to  have  for  certain  types  of  per- 
sons, provides  the  clue  to  which  emotion  and  which  conduct  will 
arise.j 

JI.  For  sensation  (the  physical  and  organic  event,  for  example, 
of  light  waves  impinging  in  a  certain  way  upon  a  certain  kind  of 
eye)  to  become  perception  (the  seeing  of  the  object  as  a  red  light) 
certain  meanings  must  be  added.  The  sensation  must  come  "to 
stand  for"  or  to  represent  something:  stop  the  car— a  rather  com- 
plex sequence  of  near-automatic  behavior  which  as  an  aspect  of 
a  social  role  must  be  learned  by  the  person  as  a  driver.  Sensations 
are  organized  into  perceptions,  and  this  organization  goes  on  in 
close  unity  with  the  social  organization  of  the  person  as  an  actor  of 
roles. 

\III.J For  impulse  (the  undefined  and  generalized  urge  to  move- 
ment) to  become  ^purpose  (the  more  or  less  controlled  striving 
toward  a  specific  object)  the  objects  so  specified  and  defined  must 
be  learned.   Impulses  are  specified  and  directed  in  terms  of  the 


CHARACTER     AND     SOCIAL     STRUCTURE  21 

expectations  of  others;  they  are  socially  defined,  linked  with  socially  4r 
available  goals  and  thus  sustain  the  person  in  enactment  of  his 
roles,    and   in   turn,    the   institutions   of   which   these   roles   are   a 
going  part. 

The  way  in  which  each  of  these  three  elements  of  the  psychic 
structure  is  joined  to  the  other  elements  in  some  sort  of  unity; 
the  way  each  is  linked  to  activity;  and  the  way  each  element,  and 
thus  the  psychic  structure  as  a  whole,  is  socialized  in  man  as  a 
social  actor— these  linkages  must  be  examined  if  we  are  to  under- 
stand the  integration  of  the  organically  based  psychic  structure 
with  the  person  and  his  social  experiences. 

With  the  acquisition  of  language,  we  learn  to  experience  our 
conduct  and  ourselves  in  relation  to  the  expectations  of  others.  We 
learn  to  distinguish  ourselves  from  objects  and  from  other  persons 
by  referring  to  ourselves  by  the  personal  pronoun,  "I."  With  these 
distinctions,  we  acquire  a  self-awareness  which  henceforth  accom- 
panies many  of  our  psychic  acts;  in  fact,  if  our  perceptions  and 
impulses  are  experienced  as  alien,  automatic,  or  compulsive— as 
not  emerging  from  our  self— we  speak  of  the  pathological  phenom- 
enon of  "depersonalization."  A  sense  of  our  own  unity,  of  our  iden- 
tity, in  time,  and  of  our  contrast  to  the  world  outside  us,  is  char- 
acteristic of  our  very  awareness  of  self.  The  person,  accordingly^  )j^ 
should  be  understood  to  involve  two  things:  toward  the  outside 
world  and  in  relation  to  others,  we  act  out  roles  which,  by  virtue 
of  our  own  feelings  and  consciousness,  we  ascribe  to  ourself.  At 
the  same  time,  we  "enrich"  our  self  by  accepting  the  challenges  of 
external  tasks  and  by  taking  over  into  our  selves  the  expectations  of 
others. 

In  our  attempt  to  understand  the  human  individual,  we  shall 
find  four  key  conceptions  useful.  Each  of  these  conceptions  stands 
for  one  aspect  of  man;  no  one  of  them  exhausts  our  interest; 
together  they  may  be  adequate  to  form  understandable  models. 
In  discussing  the  ways  in  which  they  may  be  integrated,  we  will 
also  be  assessing  more  precisely  the  relative  weights  of  biological 
and  sociological  elements  making  up  different  types  of  human 
beings.  The  four  key  terms  are  organism,  psychic  structure,  person, 
and,  finally,  character  structure  itself. 

I.  The  human  organism  refers  to  man  as  a  biological  entity.  The 
term  invites  attention  to  structural  mechanisms  and  undefined  im- 
pulses. 


22  INTRODUCTORY 

II.  Psychic  structures  refers  to  the  integration  of  feeling,  sensa- 
tion, andTlmpulse.  These  elements  are  anchored  in  the  organism, 
but  their  specific  integrations  into  emotions,  perceptions,  and  pur- 
poses must  be  understood  with  reference  to  man  as  a  person. 

III.  Person  refers  to  man  as  a  player  of  roles.  Under  it  we  view 
man  as  a  social  actor  and  try  to  grasp  the  results  of  this  social  act- 
ing and  experience  upon  him.  By  liis  experience  in  enacting  various 
xoles,  the  person  incorporates  certain  objectives  and  values  which 
steer  and  direct  his  conduct,  as  well  as  the  elements  of  his  psychic 
structure.  Viewing  man  as  a  person  we  try  to  understand  his  con- 
duct in  terms  of  motives  rather  than  to  explain  his  behavior,  in 
terms  of  stimuli  and  responses,  or  as  an  expression  of  physiological 
constants  in  the  organism. 

"/  IV.  Character  structure,  in  our  vocabulary,  is  the  most  inclusive 
term  for  the  individual  as  a  whole  entity.  It  refers  to  the  relatively 
\  ,  i  stabilized  integration  of  the  organism's  psychic  structure  linked 
'  with  the  social  roles  of  the  person.  On  the  one  hand,  a  character 
structure  is  anchored  in  the  organism  and  its  specialized  organs 
through  the  psychic  structure:  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  formed  by 
the  particular  combination  of  social  roles  which  the  person  has 
incorporated  from  out  of  the  total  roles  available  to  him  in  his 
society.  The  uniqueness  of  a  certain  individual,  or  of  a  type  of 
individual,  can  only  be  grasped  by  proper  attention  to  the  organi- 
zation of  these  component  elements  of  the  character  structure. 

Each  of  these  four  terms  represents  an  abstracted  dimension  of 
man,  a  manner  of  looking  at  him,  a  suggestion  of  what  to  look 
for.  Such  differences  as  are  found  among  men  may  be  attributable 
to  the  constitution  of  their  organisms,  to  the  specific  role-con- 
figurations incorporated  in  their  persons,  or  to  the  peculiar  integra- 
tion of  their  perception,  feelings,  and  will  within  a  psychic  struc- 
ture. An  adequate  portrayal  will  direct  our  attention  to  all  three 
as  they  come  together  to  form  a  character  structure  within  the 
limits  of  a  given  organism  and  the  institutional  confines  of  a 
specific  social  structure. 

2.  Components  of  Social  Structure 

~^  The  concept  of  role,  the-Jf^  term  in  our  definition  of  the  person, 
is  also  the  key  term  in  our  definition  of  institution.  It  is,  therefore, 


CHARACTER     AND     SOCIAL     STRUCTURE  2;^ 

in  our  definitional_model,  the  major  link  of  character  and  social  ^ 
striicture;_We  have  already  examined  the   formal  components  of 
"cTTaracter  structure;  we  must  now  elaborate  and  classify  the  organi- 
zation of  roles  into  institutions. 

We  speak  of  roles  as  orRgnized  or  instituted  when  they  are 
guaranteed  by  authority.^  Thus,  the  cluster  of  roles  enacted  by 
the  members  of  a  hotrsehold  is  guaranteed  by  "parental  authority": 
the  "head"  of  the  household  may  use  sanctions  against  infractions 
of  the  role  pattern.  Thus,  employees  are  subject  to  the  control  of 
owners  and  managers;  soldiers  are  subject  to  the  authority  of  the 
commanding  officer;  parishioners  stand  under  the  jurisdiction  of  > 
church  authorities.  Whatever  ends  the  organized  and  interacting 
partiiers^nay_pursue  and  whatever  means  they  may  employ,  "au- 
thority" exists:  and  whenever  a  role  configuration  is  so  guaranteed 
or^tabilized  by  a  "head"  who  wields  authority  over  the  "members" 
who  enact  the  roles,  the  configuration  may  be  called  an  institution. 

The  head  of  the_  institution,  the  king  of  a  political  order,  or  the 
father  of  a  patriarchal  kinship  system  is  the  most  significant  "other,"     \  / 
of   the   pcTsons   following   the  institutional  patterns.   The  kind  of      / 
external  sanction  this   head  may  take  against  those  who  do  not       1 
meet  their  expected  roles  in  expected  manners  may  range  from       * 
disapproval  to  expulsion  or  death.  His  expectations  are  treated  as 
most  important  by  persons  so  long  as  they  are  really  involved  in 
the  institution  as  a  going  concern.  In  this  way,  then,  as  well  as  in 
others  which  in  due  course  we  shall  take  up,  institutions  are  deeply 
relevant  to  our  understanding  of  the  person,  and  in  turn  to  the 
entire  character  structure. 

Just  as  role  is  the  unit  with  which  we  build  our  conception  of  T" 
institutions,  so  institution  is  the  unit  with  which  we  build  the 
conception  of  social  structure.  There  is  more  to  a  social  structure 
than  the  interrelations  of  its  institutions,  but  these  institutions,  in 
our  view,  do  make  up  its  basic  framework.  Our  immediate  aim, 
then,  is  to  classify  institutions  in  such  a  way  as  to  enable  us  to 
construct  types  of  social  structure. 

There  are  many  possible  classifications  of  institutions;   in  fact, 
the  main  concern  of  sociologists  has  often  seemed  to  be  the  making 

-  The  conception  of  authority  will  be  explained  more  fully  in  Chapter  VII: 
Institutions  and  Persons;  it  will  be  elaborated  in  Chapters  VIII  and  IX. 


24  INTRODUCTORY 

^  of  such  classifications.  Many  of  these  classifications  are  descriptively 
useful;  they  help  us  sort  out  many  items  of  social  conduct  and 
experience  and  thus  to  handle  them  more  neatly.  But  we  need 
more  than  this;  we  need  a  classification  that  will  be  relevant  and, 
we  should  hope,  fundamental  to  our  general  concern  in  understand- 
ing character  structure  on  the  one  hand  and  social  structure  on 
the  other. 

First  we  shall  briefly  examine  two  very  simple  classifications  of 
institutions:  a  classification  by  size  and  a  classification  by  recruit- 
ment of  members. 

I.  If  we  classify  institutions  according  to  size  we  end,  for  example, 
with  large  families  ( households  comprising  three  generations  under 
one  roof— as  among  the  Chinese),  small  families  (comprising  two 
generations— parents  and  children ) ,  and  incomplete  families  ( of  one 
generation  only— the  childless  couple).  Even  such  a  simple  classifi- 
cation as  this  may  be  relevant  to  the  types  of  social  structures  as  a 
whole,  as  well  as  to  the  milieu  in  which  persons  grow  up  and  live. 

Classifications  of  institutions  by  size,  in  fact,  are  sometimes  used 
as  a  basis  for  far-going  descriptions,  for  example,  the  shift  from 
business  institutions  of  very  small  size  to  those  of  great  proportions. 
The  difference  between  the  classic  laissez-faire  capitalist  and  the 
monopoly  capitalist  eras  rests  upon  this  simple  numerical  fact.  It 
is  also  clear  that  the  types  of  entrepreneurial  roles  typical  of  small 
business  institutions  differ  from  those  of  the  giant  firm;  and  hence 
the  personalities  of  men,  selected  and  trained  for  their  roles,  vary. 

Classifications  by  size,  then,  can  be  very  important:  a  sense  of 
numerical  proportion  is  always  indispensable  for  the  understand- 
ing of  social  structure  and  character.  But  size  by  itself  does  not 
seem  to  us  useful  enough  to  be  a  fundamental  classifying  device. 
The  size  of  institutions  is  more  often  a  subsidiary  than  a  funda- 
mental distinction. 

II.  Institutions  may  be  classified  according  to  the  way  in  which 
their  members  are  recruited.  Compulsory  institutions— those  which 
enroll  members  without  the  members'  choice— include  churches 
which  recruit  their  members  essentially  through  infant  baptism  and 
modern  states,  in  whose  territory  we  are  "born"  as  citizens  subject 
to  state  authority.  Where  "compulsory  education"  exists  we  become 


CHARACTER     AND     SOCIAL     STRUCTURE  2^ 

members  of  a  "public  school,"  from  which  we  can  steer  clear  only 
under  special  regulations. 

Voluntary  institutions— those  which  one  may  join  or  not,  accord- 
ing to  one's  will— include  the  modern  childless  family,  as  well  as 
most  American  civic  societies  and  clubs.  Indeed,  most  of  the  insti- 
tutional drift  of  postmedieval  society  has  been  in  the  direction  of 
an  enlarged  area  of  voluntary  associations  in  social  life  as  a  whole. 
The  United  States  is  distinguished  by  the  wide  range  and  number 
of  such  voluntary  institutions;  it  is  with  reference  to  them  that 
Americans  are  known  as  joiners. 

It  is  obvious  that  personality  development  in  a  society  based 
primarily  on  voluntary  associations  differs  from  that  in  a  society 
based  primarily  on  compulsory  institutions.  In  the  former,  one 
has  to  make  many  decisions  on  his  own,  for  better  or  for  worse; 
in  the  latter,  one  has  no  opportunity  to  make  such  decisions  and 
hence  is  not  burdened  with  the  personal  responsibilities  which  they 
may  entail. 

There  are  other  ways  of  classifying  institutions  that  are  descrip- 
tively useful.  For  instance,  the  roles  composing  institutions  may 
be  permanently  or  only  temporarily  played  by  given  individuals; 
they  may  be  provisional  or  at  once  secure.  But  there  is  no  need 
to  parade  additional  classifications.  Although  we  shall  introduce 
and  use  them  for  various  purposes  as  we  need  them,  we  do  not 
believe  they  are  adequate  for  our  general  purpose. 

III.  The  classification  of  institutions  that  we  shall  take  as  funda- 
mental to  our  model  of  social  structure  is  a  simple  classification  ^ 
according  to  objecti\e  function,  that  is,  to  the  ends  which  institu-    /^ 
tions  serve.  . 

An  institutional  order,  as  we  shall  use  the  phrase,  consists  of 
all  those  institutions  within  a  social  structure  which  have  similar 
consequences  and  ends  or  which  serve  similar  objective  functions.  1 
However  institutions  may  vary  in  size,  recruitment,  and  composi-  ' 
tion  of  membership,  in  forms  of  control  or  proportions  of  per- 
manent and  transitory  roles,  as  we  examine  the  advanced  societies 
of  the  modern  Western  world  we  can  distinguish  some  five  major 
institutional  orders. 

At  least  at  first  glance,  we  may  classify  most  of  the  institutions 
as  having  to  do  with  such  ends  as  power,  goods  and  services, 
violence,  deities,  and  procreation.  All  those  institutions  which  deal 


26  INTRODUCTORY 

with  the  recurrent  and  collective  worship  of  God  or  deities,  for 
instance,  we  may  call  religious  institutions;  together  they  make 
up  the  religious  order.  Similarly,  we  may  call  those  institutions  that 
have  to  do  with  power,  the  political;  with  violence,  the  military; 
with  procreation,  the  kinship;  and  with  goods  and  services,  the 
economic  order.  By  delineating  these  institutional  orders,  which 
form  the  skeleton  structure  of  the  total  society,  we  may  conven- 
iently analyze  and  compare  different  social  structures.  Any  social 
structure,  according  to  our  conception,  is  made  up  of  a  certain 
combination  or  pattern  of  such  institutional  orders. 

In  the  course  of  Part  Three  of  this  book,  we  shall  concern  our- 
selves with  the  social  psychology  of  each  of  these  orders  in  topical 
detail.  In  the  present  introductory  statement  we  shall  only  present 
some  of  the  mechanisms  that  hold  generally  for  institutional  con- 
duct and  some  of  the  linkages  of  institutions  with  character  struc- 
ture. 

( 1 )  The  political  order  consists  of  those  institutions  within 
which  men  acquire,  wield,  or  influence  the  distribution  of  power 
and  authority  within  social  structures.^ 

(2)  The  economic  order  is  made  up  of  those  establishments  by 
which  men  organize  labor,  resources,  and  technical  implements  in 
order  to  produce  and  distribute  goods  and  services.* 

(3)  The  military  order  is  composed  of  institutions  in  which  men 
organize  legitimate  violence  and  supervise  its  use.*^ 

(4)  The  kinship  order  is  made  up  of  institutions  which  regulate 
and  facilitate  legitimate  sexual  intercourse,  procreation,  and  the 
early  rearing  of  children." 

(5)  The  religious  order  is  composed  of  those  institutions  in 
which  men  organize  and  supervise  the  collective  worship  of  God 
or  deities,  usually  at  regular  occasions  and  at  fixed  places.^ 

2  See  Chapter  VIII:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  I,  Section  i: 
The  Political  Order;  Section  2:  Nation  and  State;  and  Section  3:  Democracies 
and  Dictatorships. 

4  See  Chapter  VIII,  Section  4:  Economic  Institutions;  and  Section  5:  Types 
of  Capitalism. 

^  See  Chapter  VIII,  Section  6:  The  Military  Order;  and  Section  7:  Char- 
acteristics of  Six  Types  of  Armies. 

^  See  Chapter  IX:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  II,  Section  3: 
The  Kinship  Order. 

^  See  Chapter  IX,  Section  i:  Religious  Institutions;  and  Section  2:  Charac- 
teristics of  the  World   Religions. 


CHARACTER     AND     SOCIAL     STRUCTURE  2/ 

Some  four  qualifications  or  cautions  about  this  way  of  classifying 
institutions  must  be  kept  in  mind  at  all  times,  and  although  they 
will  become  clearer  as  we  proceed  with  our  work,  we  must  state 
them  at  once: 

i  I.  The  conception  of  social  structures  in  terms  of  such  functional 
institutional  orders  is,  of  course,  suggested  by  modern  society  in 
which  various  institutional  orders  have  reached  a  high  degree  of 
autonomy  and  in  which  the  relative  differentiation  of  ends  has 
gone  very  far;  so  far  in  fact,  that  business  men  often  engage  in 
the  pursuit  of  profits  without  consideration  for  the  effects  of  busi- 
ness institutions  upon  other  institutional  orders;  that  is,  they  pos- 
ture as  purely  economic  man.  Yet  few,  if  any,  modern  claims  for 
the  pure  autonomy  of  an  institutional  order  have  been  realized. 
If  they  were,  it  would  mean  that  one  order  was  wholly  segregated 
from  all  others;  no  social  structure  is  so  mechanically  composed. 
Moreover,  during  the  last  half  century,  modern  social  structures 
have  definitely  tended  to  become  more  tightly  integrated,  and 
their  various  orders  interlinked  under  more  total  control. 

There  are  social  structures  in  which  the  specialization  of  ends 
and  institutions  has  not  been  pushed  as  far  as  in  modern  society. 
Business  and  private  life,  or  the  economic  and  kinship  orders,  are 
not  segregated  in  peasant  society.  Farms  provide  members  of 
peasant  families  with  a  household  way  of  life  in  which  economic 
production  and  family  living  are  not  only  interrelated  but  in  many 
respects  identical.  We  may  isolate  one  aspect  of  a  society  from 
another  for  the  sake  of  analysis,  but  we  have  to  realize  that  often, 
as  in  the  peasant  village  and  the  garrison  state,  this  analytical  isola- 
tion is  not  experienced;  life  is  an  inseparable  fusion.  For  example, 
the  fact  that  ancient  Israel  had  no  distinct  term  for  "religion"  did 
not  mean  that  there  were  no  religious  functions;  on  the  contrary, 
there  was  little  in  this  society  that  was  not  at  least  indirectly  related 
to  Yahweh  and  his  commandments. 

Therefore,  our  first  caution  is:  In  "less  developed"  societies  than 
the  mid-nineteenth-century  West,  as  well  as  in  more  developed 
societies,  any  one_of  th.e_fimctioiis  we  have  isolated  may  not  have 
autonomous  institutions  serving  it.  Just  what  institutional  orders 
exist  in  a  more  or  less  autonomous  way  is  a  matter  to  be  investi- 
gated in  any  given  society.  In  some  societies  the  institutions  of 
the  kinship  order  may  perform  functions  which,  in  more  segmented 
societies,  are  performed  by  specifically  political  institutions.  Any 


28  INTRODUCTORY 

classification  of  institutional  orders  in  terms  of  function  should  be 
seen  as  an  abstraction  which  sensitizes  us  to  the  possibilities  and 
enables  us  to  construct  and  to  understand  the  concrete  segments 
and  specific  functions  of  any  given  social  structure. 

II.  The  classification  of  institutional  orders  according  to  the 
dominant  ends  of  the  institutions  composing  them  should  not  bltiiH 
us  to  the  fact  that  the  activities  and  and  functions  of  an  institution 
are  not  exhaustively  characterized  by  its  primary  end.  A  religious 
institution,  such  as  the  Catholic  Church,  employs  numerous  special- 
ized functionaries  who  devote  themselves  to  the  financial  and 
property  affairs  of  the  institution;  a  monastery  may  specialize  in 
the  production  and  sale  of  "Chartreuse,"  an  exquisite  French 
liqueur;  or  it  may  engage  in  the  brewing  of  beer,  the  printing  of 
books,  and  so  on.  Yet,  we  shall  not  call  such  institutions  "economic 
institutions";  for  it  is  hardly  satisfactory  to  account  for  the  exist- 
ence and  shape  of  a  "monk  order"  in  terms  of  its  economic  pur- 
suits, no  matter  how  relevant  economic  activities  may  be  for  the 
religious  organization.  Monks  who  brew  beer  do  not  thereby  con- 
stitute a  brewery  which  just  happens  to  recruit  tonsured  and  celi- 
bate men  as  employees.  The  financial  transactions  of  the  Vatican 
do  not  make  it  a  bank.  That  an  army  or  a  factory  may  employ 
religious  leaders  for  morale-building  purposes  does  not  mean  that 
the  army  or  the  factory  becomes  a  religious  institution,  but  rather 
that  the  military  order  is  able  to  use  religious  personnel  for  its 
own  ends.  That  the  dispute  concerning  the  dogma  of  the  Trinity 
was  settled  at  Nicaea  in  a.d.  325  by  monks  armed  with  clubs  does 
not  make  "military  institutions"  out  of  monasteries.  Neither  is  the 
employment  of  practitioners  of  violence  by  business  corporations 
or  trade  unions  sufficient  to  turn  such  institutions  into  elements  of 
the  "military"  order.  An  institution  may  enroll  numerous  agents 
and  may  comprise  many  specialized  roles  for  the  implementation 
of  its  dominant  goal. 

Many  and  varied  activities  are  required  to  operate  large  insti- 
tutions, and  these  activities  often  overlap  with  those  of  other  or- 
ders; accordingly,  the  ends  of  one  order  often  serve  as  the  means 
'-^  of  another.  Nevertheless,  we  must  first  set  up  a  scheme  in  which  we 
attempt  to  define  and  classify  institutions  by  their  dominant  func- 
tions before  we  can  consider  such  problems  of  "overlap"  and  in- 
tegration in  a  fruitful  and  systematic  way. 


CHARACTER     AND     SOCIAL     STRUCTURE  2g 

III.  Our  classification  of  institutions  into  orders  is  in  terms  of 

their  objective,  social  functions,  not  subjective,  personal  meanings 
of  their  members  or  leaders.  jConcretely,  this  means  that  whether 
or  not  the  persons  who  enact  roles  making  up  the  institutions 
within  an  order  are  aware  of  the  order's  ends,  nevertheless,  their 
conduct  is  so  oriented.  A  Catholic  cardinal,  for  example  Richelieu, 
may  have  been  personally  motivated  to  win  political  power,  and 
may  even  have  spent  most  of  his  life  in  political  rather  than  reli- 
gious activities;  but  this  does  not  make  the  churches  under  his 
authority  part  of  the  political  order.  Nor  does  it  necessarily  mean 
that  the  more  political  bishops  are  less  eflective  in  their  religious 
roles  than  "more  religious"  bishops.  The  motives  that  are  typical 
of  persons  playing  roles  in  a  given  order  are  matters  to  be  investi- 
gated in  every  case;  they  are  not  in  any  way  settled  by  any  ob- 
jective definition  of  the  dominant  functions  of  institutional  orders. 

IV.  Not  all  social  experience  and  conduct  are  included  in  this 
scheme  of  institutional  orders.  The  "dating"  of  young  lovers  and 
the  behavior  of  "the  man  in  the  street"  are  not  institutional  con- 
duct—although, of  course,  they  are  aftected  by  several  institutional 
orders.  Yet,  if  we  aim  to  grasp  total  societies,  it  is  convenient  to 
focus  first  on  institutions  and  their  settings  rather  than  on  the  more 
amorphous  and  ephemeral  modes  of  social  interaction,  however 
crucial  these  may  at  times  be.® 

There  are  several  aspects  of  social  conduct  which  characterize 
all  institutional  orders,  the  most  important  being:  technology,  sym- 
bols, status,  and  education.  All  orders  may  be  characterized  by 
technolog'  7al  implements,  by  the  modes  of  speech  and  symbols 
peculiar  to  them,  by  the  distribution  of  prestige  enjoyed  by  their 
members,  and  by  the  transmission  of  skills  and  values.  We  shall 
arbitrarily  call  these  "spheres,"  in  contradistinction  to  "orders,"  be- 
cause they  are,  in  our  view,  rarely  or  never  autonomous  as  to  the 
endsJdiey  serve  and  because  any  of  them  may  be  used  within  any 
one  of  our  five  orders. 

( 1 )  "Symbols"  may  be  visual  or  acoustic;  they  may  be  signs,  sig- 
nals, emblems,  ceremonial,  language,  music,  or  other  arts.  Without 
such  symbols  we  could  not  understand  the  conduct  of  human 
actors,  and  normally,  their  belief  in  and  use  of  these  symbols  oper- 
ate to  uphold  or  justify  the  institutional  order.  The  religious  order 

®  See  Chapter  XV:  Collective  Behavior. 


^O  INTRODUCTORY 

has  its  sphere  of  theology,  the  elaboration,  attenuation,  and  justifi- 
cation of  God  or  deities;  the  military  order  has  its  startle  com- 
mands; and  the  political  order  has  its  political  formulae  and 
rhetoric,  in  the  name  of  which  its  agents  exercise  authority.'' 

(2)  "Technology"  refers  to  the  implementation  of  conduct  with 
tools,  apparatus,  machines,  instruments,  and  physical  devices  of  all 
sorts.  In  addition  to  such  instrumentalities,  the  technological  sphere 
refers  to  the  skill,  dexterity,  or  expertness  with  which  persons  meet 
their  role  demands.  In  this  sense,  "technique"  is  used  by  the  violin- 
ist as  well  as  by  the  skilled  soldier;  it  is  revealed  by  the  surgeon's 
use  of  his  tools,  as  well  as  by  priest  handling  such  paraphernalia 
of  worship  as  the  chalice  or  the  prayer  wheel.  Whenever  we  con- 
centrate on  the  degree,  or  the  absence,  of  skill  with  which  roles  are 
enacted,  we  may  speak  of  the  technological  sphere,  regardless  of 
what  the  institutional  context  may  be.  Technology  is  never  auton- 
omous: it  is  always  instituted  in  some  specific  order  or  orders.  In 
modern  industrial  society,  it  is  centered  primarily  in  the  economic 
and  military  orders,  which  not  only  stimulate  it  and  "supervise" 
its  production  and  distribution  to  other  institutions,  but  are  the 
orders  in  which  it  is  most  often  used.^° 

(3)  The  "Status"  sphere  consists  of  agencies  and  means  of  dis- 
tributing prestige,  deference,  or  honor  among  the  members  of  the 
social  structure.  Any  role  in  any  institutional  order  may  be  the  basis 
for  status  claims,  and  the  status  sphere  as  a  whole  may  be  anchored 
primarily  in  any  one  order  or  in  many  specific  combinations  of 
institLitional  orders.^^ 

(4)  The  "Educational"  sphere  consists  of  those  institutions  and 
activities  concerned  with  the  transmission  of  skills  and  values  to 
those  persons  who  have  not  yet  acquired  them.^- 

A  social  structure  is  composed  of  institutional  orders  and  spheres. 
The  precise  weight  which  each  institutional  order  and  sphere  has 
with  reference  to  every  other  order  and  sphere,  and  the  ways  in 

9  For  the  public  role  of  symbol  spheres,  see  Chapter  X:  Symbol  Spheres; 
for  the  private  role  of  symbols,  see  Chapter  V:  The  Sociology  of  Motivation. 

10  See  Chapter  XIII:  Social-historical  Change,  Section  3:  The  Technological 
Sphere. 

11  See  Chapter  XI:  Stratification  and  Institutional  Orders,  Section  3:  The 
Status  Sphere;   and   Section   4:    Class   and  Status. 

12  See  Chapter  IX:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  II. 


CHARACTER     AND     SOCIAL     STRUCTURE  ^^ 

which  they  are  related  with  one  another— these  determine  the  unity 
andthe  composition  of  a  social  structure. ^^ 

The  analysis  of  social  structure  into  orders,  as  we  have  said, 
does  not  decide  what  "orders"  exist;  only  concrete  investigation  of 
different  societies  can  do  that.  We  shall  not  be  surprised,  of  course, 
when  we  have  to  elaborate  or  simplify  the  classification  of  insti- 
tutional orders  sketched  here.  SgciaL-strufctures  aie^ i}i>t_ijpzen,Jthey 
may^  be  static  or  dynamic,  they  have  beginnings,  duration,  varying 
degrees  of  unity,  an3l:hev  may  disintegrate. 

These  problemsof  the  interrelations  or  institutional  orders  and 
of  social  change  will  be  dealt  with  in  due  course.  Here  it  is  per- 
haps enough  to  remark  that  the  warp  of  one  institutional  order  may 
be  the  woof  of  another.  Military  men,  for  instance,  becoming  con- 
scious of  a  scarcity  of  manpower,  may  be  concerned  about  the 
declining  health  of  the  working  classes  because  they  anticipate  an 
increasing  percentage  of  men  unfit  for  military  service— a  thought 
that  may  not  enter  the  mind  of  the  businessman,  still  thinking 
of  the  abundance  of  labor  force.  Similarly,  businessmen,  interested 
in  educated  labor  for  clerical  jobs,  may  become  much  concerned 
with  tax-supported  high  schools. 

In  their  ramifications,  then,  institutional  orders  have  definite 
bearings  upon  each  other;  tensions  and  conflicts  arise,  and  practices 
lead  to  results  which  the  practitioners  neither  intend  nor  foresee. 

It  is  often  convenient  to  examine  these  interrelations  of  institu- 
tional orders  in  terms  of  ends  and  means;  often  the  activities  which 
fulfill  one  institutional  order's  ends  serve  as  means  to  the  dominant 
ends  of  another  order.  When  we  focus  upon  such  subsidiary 
aspects  of  institutions,  we  may  see  the  ramifications  of  another 
order.  What  dominates  in  one  order  may,  in  a  different  order, 
merely  implement.  The  political  activities  of  businessmen  and 
corporations  may  thus  be  understood  as  "political  ramifications  of 
the  economic  order."  The  religious  order  or  the  educational  order 
may  also  have  political  ramifications:  the  political  activities  of 
religious  and  educational  institutions  and  personnel.  Similarly, 
we  may  speak  of  the  educational  and  religious  ramifications  of  the 
political  order  when  focusing  upon  educational  activities  of  politi- 
cians in  party  schools  or  the  role  of  prayer  and  other  religious 

13  See   Chapter   XII:    The    Unih'    of   Social    Structures. 


32  INTRODUCTORY 

activities  in  politics.  Any  given  order  may  thus  become  the  ramifi- 
cation of  any  other  order.  "Ramifications"  may  thus  be  defined  as 
those  activities  which  are  ends  in  one  order  but  which  are  used 
as  the  means  of  another  institutional  order.  In  total  war,  for  ex- 
ample, all  orders  become  ramifications  of  the  military  state,  for  the 
military  impinges  upon  all  other  orders  which  thus  become  pre- 
requisites for  realizing  or  for  limiting  military  ends. 

3.  The  Tasks  of  Social  Psychology 

Throughout  this  book  we  shall  be  engaged  in  elaborating  and 
refining  the  various  elements  noted  in  our  general  model  of  char- 
acter and  social  structure,  and  in  tracing  the  possible  linkages  con- 
necting one  element  with  another.  The  various  components  of 
character  and  social  structure  are  diagrammed  in  the  following 
chart: 


ORGANISM 


character        psychic 
Structure       structure 


PERSON 


ROLE 


INSTITUTIONS 


KINSHIP 
ORDER 


Social  Structure 


RELIGIOUS 
ORDER     - 


SPHERES 

SYMBOLS 

TECHNOLOGY 

STATUS 

EDUCATION 


POLITICAL 
ORDER 


MILITARY 
ORDER 


ECONOMIC  ORDER 


CHARACTER     AND     SOCIAL     STRUCTURE  ;^;^ 

With  this  model  in  mind  we  wish  to  construct  features  of  various 
institutional  orders  and  their  interrelations,  in  connection  with  the 
psychology  of  the  individual.  Now  that  we  have  presented  the  gen- 
eral features  of  our  model,  we  are  in  a  position  to  set  forth,  in  a 
preliminary  way,  the  tasks  which  it  allows  and  invites. 

I.  The  numerous  roles  organized  into  various  institutional  orders 
must  be  analyzed.  Obviously,  our  goal  cannot  be  the  examination 
of  all  the  roles,  past  and  contemporary,  which  men  have  enacted. 
This  would  involve  a  complete  rewriting  of  the  universal  history 
of  mankind!  Nor  would  a  formal  dictionary  of  possible  roles  be 
tied  closely  enough  to  institutional  orders  and  social  structures  to 
be  revealing  and  realistic.  We  shall  have  to  use  two  general  criteria 
for  our  selection  of  roles,  and  of  persons  formed  and  selected  by 
them,  which  we  shall  analyze: 

First,  we  shall  selecL_thQse  roles  which  are  ^  pivotal  signifi- 
cance _iii_jJie-nwixxtenance_aad^.transformation  of  given  types  of 
institutional  orders.  Of  course,  what  order  or  orders  we  think  most 
important  in  historical  transformations  will  influence  our  selection 
of  roles.  Va^^l     ^i«A^■^^X>J^-'^a,Q- 

Second,  the  roles  we  select  for  analysis  will  represent  the  polar 
or  extreme  types  within  given  institutional  orders,  thus  affording  us 
a  chance  to  see  the.3d.destj:aftge-ef  possible  conduct.^^jyv/iMUA;"'*^-"  i 

II.  We  wish  to  focus  upon  the  type  of  person  selected  and^- 
formed  by  the  enactment  and  internalization  of  the  roles  which  we 
analyze.  Since  a  person  participates  in  the  roles  of  various  institu- 
tional orders,  and  the  dominant  roles  of  given  types  of  persons  may 
be  role-segments  of  one  type  of  institution  within  a  given  institu- 
tional order,  we  shall  pay  attention  to  the  various  effects  on  the 
persons  so  formed  and  selected  by  institutions. 

Our  expectation  of  finding  regularities  in  human  conduct,  experi- 
ence, and  motives  is  keyed  to  the  role  configurations  forming  insti-  ■'\ 
tutions.  We  seek  (a)  to  analyze  roles  as  segments  of  institutions; 
(b)  to  discern  the  typical  motivations  which  are  required  by  indi- 
viduals as  necessary  and  sufficient  for  the  enactment  of  these  roles; 
and  (c)  to  show  how  the  central  ideas  and  beliefs  of  a  society,  its 
communications  and  symbols,  contribute  to  the  formation,  main- 
tenance, and  effectiveness  of  these  motivations. 

III.  With  reference  to  each  institutional  order,  we  need  more 
adequately  to  characterize  the  primary  and  secondary  functions 
which  it  may  fulfill  in  the  full  range  of  social  structures.  In  order 


34  INTRODUCTORY 

to  do  this  in  an  historically  adequate  way,  we  must  lay  out  the  range 
of  institutional  types  which  are  available  in  each  order.  We  shall 
then  find  it  convenient  to  select  polar  extremes  and  analyze  them 
in  some  detail.  In  this  way  we  hope  to  grasp  the  possible  scope 
of  the  character  and  functions  of  political  and  military,  kinship 
and  economic,  educational  and  religious  institutions.^* 

IV.  We  need  also  to  gain  a  view  of  the  major  ways  in  which 
various  institutional  orders  are  related  to  one  another  in  different 
types  of  social  structures,^"  and  changes  in  these  relations. ^"^  For 
types  of  social  structure  may  be  constructed  and  compared  by 
examining  the  specific  combinations  of  institutional  orders  which 
make  them  up,  the  varying  importance  each  of  these  orders  has, 
and  the  definite  ways  they  are  interrelated.  In  a  parallel  way, 
working  models  of  various  kinds  of  historical  change  can  be  devel- 
oped by  viewing  types  of  social  structure  in  terms  of  their  dynamic 
movements  and  shifts  rather  than  in  static  cross  section.  For  history 
is  of  course  only  the  changes  of  social  structures  and  their  com- 
ponent parts. 

■^Our  general  aim,  then,  is  to  display,  analyze,  and  understand 
types  of  persons  in  terms  of  their  roles  within  institutions  in  given 
orders  and  social  structures  within  various  historical  eras;  and  we 
want  to  do  this  for  each  institutional  order.  We  cannot,  for  example, 
rest  content  with  the  assumption  that  the  kinship  order,  with  its 
tensions  of  early  love  and  authority,  is  necessarily  the  basic  and 
lasting  factor  in  the  formation  of  personality;  and  that  other  orders 
of  society  are  projective  systems  from  this  until  we  have  studied 
the  selection  and  continued  formation  of  personality  in  the  eco- 
nomic and  religious  and  political  institutions  of  various  social 
structures.  The  father  may  not  be  the  primary  authority,  but  rather 
the  replica  of  the  power  relations  of  society,  and  of  course,  the 
unwitting  transmitter  of  larger  authorities  to  his  spouse  and  chil- 
dren. We  must  set  forth  institutional  orders  in  a  systematic  way, 
relate  them  to  one  another  within  a  social  structure,  and  trace  their 
impact  upon  persons  and  psychic  structures. 

1*  See   especially   Chapter   VIII:    Institutional   Orders   and    Social   Controls, 
I;  and  Chapter  IX:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  II. 
15  See   Chapter  XII:    The   Unity  of  Social   Structures. 
10  See  Chapter  XIII:   Social-historical  Change. 


P  A  U  T    T  W  » 


CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 


CHAPTER 
III 


Organism  and  Psychic  Structure 


TO  understand  the  psychic  structure  we  must  understand  how 
it  is  both  rooted  in  the  organism  and  hnked  with  the  person.  For 
there  is  nothing  within  the  psychic  structure  itself  which  enables  us 
to  understand  how  impulses  are  transformed  into  purposes,  im- 
pressions into  perceptions,  feelings  into  emotions.  These  psychic 
elements  are  linked  with  one  another,  and  each  of  them,  as  well 
as  the  unity  they  form,  is  socialized  in  such  a  way  as  to  sustain 
or  to  restrict  the  social  roles  that  the  person  enacts. 

1.  The  Social  Relevance  of  the  Organism 

Human  organisms  are  different  in  size,  shape,  and  color.  People 
who  are  lean  and  tall,  with  flat,  narrow  chests,  who  seem  to  be 
thinly  made  with  bonelike  arms  and  legs,  have  been  called  lepto- 
somes.  Others,  whose  organic  constitutions  appear  to  center  around 
their  abdomen,  who  have  plump  bodies,  rather  short  limbs,  deep- 
vaulted  chests  and  magnificent  paunches,  have  been  called  pyknic. 
And  then  there  are  the  athletic  men,  tall  and  broad  of  shoulder, 
thick-skinned  and  coarse-boned,  with  big  hands  and  feet.  In  sum, 
different  individuals  may  be  classified  according  to  such  body 
types.  But  can  we  go  further?  Can  we  state  that  these  constitu- 
tional types  are  correlated  with  types  of  character,  temperament, 
or  with  specific  traits  of  personality?  Is  the  appearance  of  the  indi- 
vidual "expressive"  of  different  psychic  traits  and  qualities? 

The  physical  signs  of  aging  appear  to  us  as  signs  of  physical 
change,  just  as  the  trembling,  sweating,  swollen  features  of  an 
alcoholic  indicate  somatic  processes,  and  no  more.  But  other  bodily 
features  and  processes  are  often  "read"  as  indicative  of  spiteful 
resentment,  happy  disposition,  or  other  character  traits.  We  ex- 


28  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

perience  our  body  externally  by  touch  and  sight,  and  internally  by 
feeling  tone;  our  psychic  and  our  somatic  life  are  thus  intimately 
fused.  But  since,  once  we  have  grown  up,  our  physical  structure 
changes  very  little,  this  structure  serves  as  a  reference  point  in 
physiognomic  observations  of  psychic  life,  in  a  twofold  manner: 

I.  In  observing  the  general  appearance,  the  gestures,  deport- 
ment, and  conduct  of  the  individual,  one  can  assume  that  they 
are  documentary  evidence  for  an  essential  unit:  The  "nature"  of 
this  or  that  man,  comprising  his  organic,  psychic,  social,  moral, 
and  other  qualities.  This  current  of  romantic  thinking  has  been 
elaborated  in  a  broad  literature.  Yet  however  plausible  and  attrac- 
tive the  morphological  types  constructed  may  seem,  one  has  to 
allow  for  so  many  exceptions  and  so  many  contradictions  that  the 
endeavor  always  seems  to  break  down. 

II.  In  the  morphological  approach  one  tries  to  intuit  the  essen- 
tial nature  of  a  type  of  individual  as  a  unit.  In  a  second  approach, 
one  measures  certain  traits,  which  one  then  correlates  with  one 
another.  These  elements  and  their  correlations  do  not  always  pos- 
sess the  plausibility  of  the  unitary  whole  or  Gestalt.  For  in  the 
process  of  such  detailed  research  the  idea  of  providing  materials 
for  physiognomic  documentation  loses  its  symbolic  overtones. 

Now,  physiognomic  propositions  usually  follow  one  or  more  of 
three  principles:  (i)  Individual  traits,  being  read  as  "signs,"  are 
understood  as  "symptoms"  of  character.  Karl  Jaspers,^  whom  we 
follow  in  this  matter,  points  out  the  absurdity  of  this  approach, 
which  is  perhaps  best  revealed  in  Lombroso's  work,  to  be  dis- 
cussed presently.  (2)  By  intuitive  understanding,  the  observer  tries 
to  grasp  the  totality  of  the  body,  which  at  the  same  time  is  held 
to  indicate  a  certain  psychic  type.  The  bodily  form,  the  head  and 
the  hands,  are  artistically  composed  into  a  configuration  that  is 
"seen"  as  a  whole  of  psychological  quality.  (3)  The  body  build 
provides  the  observer,  not  with  any  psychological  meanings,  but 
with  a  form  which  the  artist  may  take  up  and  use  in  shaping  his 
image  of  man.  The  human  form— the  thick  and  the  thin,  the  angu- 
lar and  the  round,  the  tall  and  the  short,  the  straight  and  the  lop- 
sided—is thus  put  to  essentially  artistic  rather  than  psychological 
use. 

Much  physiognomic  literature— going  back  to  ancient  India  and 

1  Allgemeine  Psychopathologie  ( Berlin  and  Heidelberg,  1946 ) . 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  39 

Mediterranean  antiquity— has  since  the  eighteenth  century  been 
subject  to  intellectual  fashions.  In  the  recent  past,  two  such  works 
stand  out:  the  "degeneration"  literature  connected  with  Lom- 
broso's  name,  and  the  psychological  elaborations  of  "bodily  types" 
of  Kretschmer. 

In  Lombroso's  conception,-  bodily  deviations— such  as  inordi- 
nately long  legs  in  comparison  with  the  length  of  the  entire  body, 
strange  skull  shapes,  absence  of  a  proper  chin,  excessive  hairiness 
or  the  absence  of  bodily  hair,  ingrown  earflaps  or  big,  protruding 
ears— are  considered  as  signs  of  the  "degeneration"  of  the  psychic 
structure,  and  are  alleged  to  stand  for  the  degenerate  nature  of  the 
respective  individuals,  of  their  dispositions  to  neurosis  and  mental 
disease  and  especially  to  criminal  behavior.  This  sort  of  approach 
brings  physiognomic  intuition  into  spuriously  scientific  form,  the 
"symbolism"  of  old  assumes  the  form  of  "symptomatology,"  and 
medically  nothing  can  be  proven. 

Kretschmer's  attempt  is  comparable.^  Its  content  differs,  of 
course,  but  the  method  of  relating  body  build  and  psychic  traits 
allows  us  to  place  him  near  Lombroso,  although  he  happened  to 
be  more  concerned  with  geniuses  than  criminals.  He  distinguished 
three  types— the  leptosomic,  the  athletic,  and  the  pyknic— and  as- 
signed the  few  unclassifiable  individuals  to  the  residual  category 
of  dysplastic  men. 

One  of  the  most  recent  large-scale  and  careful  studies  designed 
to  answer  physiognomic  type  problems— the  study  of  Sheldon  and 
Stevens  *— concludes  with  this  comment:  "If  anything  is  demon- 
strated conclusively  by  the  study  as  a  whole,  it  is  this:  that  neither 
the  somatotype  [type  of  organic  constitution]  alone,  nor  any  other 
single  factor,  will  suffice  to  'explain'  a  personality.  Persons  of  the 
same  somatotype  frequently  develop  into  singularly  different  kinds 
of  people.  .  .  Furthermore,  although  the  correlation  between 
somatotype  and  temperament  [of  two  hundred  young  American 
men],  taken  at  large,  is  [moderately  high]  ...  so  many  [appar- 
ently secondary]  variables  are  at  work  that  the  specific  manifesta- 

2  Cesare  Lombroso,  Crime,  Its  Causes  and  Remedies,  H.  P.  Horton,  tr. 
(Boston:   Little,  Brown,   1911). 

3  E.  Kretschmer,  Physique  and  Character:  An  Investigation  of  the  Theory 
of  Temperament   (New  York:    Harcourt,   Brace,   1926). 

*  W.  W.  Sheldon  and  S.  S.  Stevens,  The  Varieties  of  Temperament:  A 
Psycliology  of  Constitutional  Differences  (New  York:   Harjjer,  1942). 


40  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

tions  of  temperament  can  be  predicted  from  the  somatotype  [only] 
within  very  wide  hmits  ,  .  ." 

Such  studies,  we  beHeve,  do  not  result  in  more  definitive  find- 
ings because  ( i )  they  do  not  succeed  in  isolating,  or  in  making 
fine  enough  distinctions  among,  the  various  elements  of  the  total 
character  structure.  Usually  working  with  such  "constitutional 
traits,"  as  size  and  proportions  of  abdomen  and  legs,  on  the  one 
hand,  and  with  "temperamental"  items  such  as  "love  of  comfort" 
or  "desire  for  action"  on  the  other,  it  is  not  odd  that  the  results  are 
gross  and  generally  unrevealing. 

(2)  The  total  character  structure,  in  which  such  "tempera- 
mental" factors  are  included,  involves  more  than  the  organism. 
If  attention  were  paid  to  the  specific  social  constellation  in  which 
"love  of  comfort"  was  attributable  to  given  individuals,  it  would 
be  realized  that  the  person  as  well  as  the  organism  must  be  studied 
if  we  are  to  grasp  the  integration  of  types  of  character  structure, 
or  even  of  "temperament." 

(3)  We  might  say  that  the  tall  constitution  is  organically  cor- 
related with  "traits"  or  "abilities"  of  leadership  (Abraham  Lin- 
coln) and  that  the  short  physique  is  accompanied  by  a  lack  of 
these  social  or  psychic  traits  (Corporal  Napoleon!).  We  would 
then  search  for  something  about  the  organism  that  makes  for 
aggressive  leadership  or  for  its  absence.  So  far,  those  who  believe 
in  such  organic  correlations  of  constitution  with  psychic  traits 
have  not  isolated  its  mechanisms.  And  no  statistical  correlations 
have  been  found  to  be  adequate  as  long  as  the  organic  mechanisms 
of  the  imputed  influence  were  not  set  forth,  for  there  are  other 
ways  to  explain  any  correlations  which  might  exist  between  types 
of  constitutions  and  temperamental  or  personal  traits. 

Insofar  as  "leadership"  is  an  accompaniment  of  big  or  of  little 
physiques,  for  example,  the  connection  may  be  in  terms  of  others' 
reactions  to  such  men,  rather  than  through  the  organisms  of  the 
individual  leaders.  Biological  capacities  and  deficiencies,  as  me- 
diated through  the  reactions  of  others  to  them,  influence  the 
child's  reactions  to  others  and,  in  turn,  his  attitude  toward  himself. 
In  given  societies,  the  "social  burden"  of  some  organic  deficiency 
may  lead  to  the  development  of  certain  character  traits.  The  per- 
son with  a  deficiency  of  some  organ  may  be  more  preoccupied 
with  himself  than  are  organically  normal  persons.  In  compensa- 
tion,  he   may   increase   his   striving   for   superiority   and   supreme 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  4I 

recognition.^  On  the  other  hand,  defects,  such  as  those  of  vision 
may  be  the  basis,  not  of  compensatory  striving  for  superiority,  but 
of  ahbis  and  justifications  for  feehngs  of  inferiority."  How  organic 
conditions  are  related  to  the  development  of  personality  traits  and 
conduct  patterns  depends  on  how  the  whole  structure  of  the  char- 
acter is  socially  estimated. 

For  the  social  psychologist,  those  features  of  the  organism 
which  are  to  be  studied  must  be  relevant  to  the  social  situation  of 
the  actor  and  to  the  actor  himself.  For  that  seems  to  be  the  way 
in  which  the  type  of  body  and  other  "constitutionally  determined 
characteristics  need  to  be  taken  into  account  in  any  successful 
effort  to  interpret  a  personality. "  The  same  principle  of  interpreta- 
tion holds  for  races. 

Race  refers  to  a  statistical  type  of  constitution  which  a  group  of 
organisms  approximate.  The  members  of  a  race  vary  as  individ- 
uals, but  they  vary  around  a  norm  or  type:  they  are  characterized, 
in  E.  A.  Hooton's  words,"  by  a  "certain  combination  of  morphologi- 
cal and  metrical  features,  principally  nonadaptive,  which  have  been 
derived  from  their  common  descent."  The  anatomical  features 
chosen  as  the  bases  of  classification  are  biologically  useless  ("non- 
adaptive");  they  usually  include  the  shape  of  the  head  as  meas- 
ured in  various  ways,  the  type  of  hair,  the  proportions  of  the 
nose.  Skin  color  is  no  longer  generally  used  by  biologists  and 
anthropologists  as  a  primary  classification  trait. 

Given  the  type  of  organic  traits  seized  upon  for  racial  classifi- 
cation, it  would  indeed  be  fortuitous  if  organic  correlations  be- 
tween these  types  of  anatomies  and  any  character  or  psychic  traits 
were  discovered.  So  far,  they  have  not  been:  there  is  no  conclusive 
evidence  of  difference  in  "native"  intelligence  or  in  types  of  per- 
sonality between  biologically  defined  racial  types.* 

The  social  and  psychological  irrelevance  of  the  biological  traits 
used  by  anthropologists  in  classifying  races  does  not,  however, 
abolish  the  "reality  of  race"  or  the  "psychology"  of  races.  It  does 

^  Cf.  Alfred  Adler,  Understanding  Human  Nature  (London:  Faber,  1927), 
pp.  69  fF. 

•^  See  I.  E.  Bender,  et  al..  Motivation  and  Visual  Factors  (Hanover,  New 
Hampshire:  Dartmouth  College  Publications,  1942). 

■^  Up  From  the  Ape  (rev.  ed.;  New  York:   Macmillan,  1946). 

8  Cf .  for  e.xample,  Otto  Klineberg,  Race  Differences  (New  York:  Harper, 
1935)- 


42  CHARACTERSTRUCTURE  jj 

change  the  bases  on  which  these  matters  are  open  to  fruitful  study. 
For  if  we  use  as  racial  criteria  those  anatomical  traits  characteriz- 
ing a  people,  or  even  a  portion  of  them,  to  which  others  pay  social 
attention,  we  do  find  types  of  "racial  personality."  The  personality 
traits  which  may  become  typical  of  members  of  races  are  then 
sociological  in  origin  and  operation.  They  will  be  traits  which  are 
socially  visible  and  socially  used  as  "badges"  by  other  persons  and 
by  members  of  the  race  itself  in  social  relations.  In  the  United 
States,  for  example,  color  is  obviously  a  primary  criterion. 

"Racial  psychology"  is  most  fruitfully  understood  as  a  social 
psychology  of  racial  relations.*^ 

Our  emphasis  on  the  causal  irrelevance  of  the  organism,  indi- 
vidual or  racial,  to  character  traits  and  conduct  patterns  should 
not  blind  us  to  the  direct  intrabody  effects  of  constitutional  dif- 
ferences which  do  exist.  We  have  said  that  the  emotions,  purposes, 
and  perceptions  which  make  up  the  psychic  structure  are  "rooted 
in  the  organism";  this  means  that  constitutional  differences  and 
changes  in  the  organism  may  directly  affect  the  elements  of  the 
psychic  structure: 

I.  Feelings  and  gestures,  the  alertness  and  clarity  of  perception 
or  the  strength  of  impulse,  may  be  changed  by  modification  of 
physiological  processes.  Thus,  physical  exhaustion  and  fatigue  may 
limit  the  control  of  one's  speech  in  a  court  hearing  or  a  police- 
directed  interview.  The  organism  may  be  so  exhausted,  due  to 
prolonged  worry  and  sleeplessness,  as  to  be  incapable  of  resisting 
suggestion.  The  speed  with  which  one  thi'ows  up  his  guard  and 
collects  his  wits  may  thus  be  reduced.  In  this  way  one's  physiologi- 
cal condition  may  be  modified  in  order  to  open  one  up  for  ease  of 
psychic  manipulation. 

II.  Toxics  may  be  used  so  to  modify  the  physiological  process 
and  guarantee  certain  predictable  psychic  states.  A  candidate  for 
an  examination  may  use  unusually  strong  coffee  in  an  effort  to 
heighten  his  alertness  and  forestall  the  slackening  effects  of  fatigue 
and  overlong  concentration.  Resources  are  thus  mobilized  for  a 
supreme  effort.  The  lowering  of  conventional  inhibitions  against 
aggressive  impulses  by  the  use  of  alcohol  is  another  case  in  point. 

9  These  matters  will  be  examined  in  Chapter  XI:  Stratification  and  Institu- 
tional Orders,  Section  3:  The  Status  Sphere;  and  Section  5:  The  Status 
Sphere  and  Personality  Types. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  43 

It  should  be  noted  that  the  economic  position  of  persons  may 
affect  their  type  of  diet,  and  deficiency  in  diet  may  lower  the  alert- 
ness of  their  perception,  the  intensity  of  their  emotions,  or  the 
persistence  of  their  will. 

III.  In  certain  role  contexts,  the  physiological  foundations  of  the 
psychic  structure  become  especially  relevant.  The  opera  singer 
thus  abstains  from  smoking,  which  is  detrimental  to  the  voice,  and 
athletes  who  are  in  training  are  exhorted  not  to  spend  their  "energy" 
with  women.  The  history  of  religion  is  rich  in  examples  of  ascetic 
practices  which  lead  to  psychic  states  which  are  appraised  as  holy. 
There  is  the  cultic  chastity  of  the  priest,  and  the  abstentions  from 
food,  sleep,  and  sex  of  a  variety  of  monks  and  holy  men.  And 
there  are  the  practices  of  Buddhists  which  are  productive  of  ex- 
traordinary psychosomatic  states,  which,  in  turn,  are  subject  to 
elaborate  interpretations. 

IV.  The  general  organic  changes  involved  in  maturation,  pu- 
berty, and  aging  determine  changes  in  performance  in  emotional 
state  or  perceptual  clarity.  But  what  is  "childish"  in  the  life-cycle 
and  what  is  "mature"  and  "senile"  vary  widely  in  different  so- 
cieties. ^°  Yet  this  variation  is  limited,  and  in  part  may  be  consti- 
tuted, by  biologically  fixed  and  directed  processes  of  maturation 
and  aging.  The  link  of  physiological  changes  and  psychic  sequences 
is  not  set  by  external  or  chemical  manipulations  of  the  physiologi- 
cal state  of  the  organism,  but  is  rather  a  result  and  an  aspect  of  the 
natural  conditions  and  changes  of  man's  body  in  the  cycle  of  its 
life-span. 

CHARACTER    STRUCTURE 


Organism 


Person 


PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE 


structural 
limitations 


impulse  .  .  . 
impression 
feeling  .    .  . 


purpose 

perception 

emotion 


roles, 

meanings, 

gestures 


10  See  Chapter  VI:  Biography  and  Types  of  Childhood,  Section  7:  The 
Relevance  of  Childhood;  and  Section  8:  The  Social  Relativity  of  Childhood 
Influences. 


44  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

The  physiological  foundations  of  the  psychic  structure,  then,  have 
intrabody  effects;  and  within  certain  social-historical  conditions 
they  also  have  social  effects.  The  way  people  feel,  perceive,  and 
will  is  rooted  in  the  animal  organism,  and  is  influenced  directly 
by  its  changing  physiological  conditions.  The  psychic  structure  is 
also  linked  to  the  person,  most  crucially  by  the  way  in  which  social 
expectations  play  upon  the  person  to  steer  and  control  his  im- 
pulses, emotions,  and  perceptions.  The  psychic  structure  (how, 
what,  and  when  we  feel,  perceive,  and  will)  is  determined  by  the 
total  character  structure,  but  the  "executive"  of  the  character  struc- 
ture, the  person,  is  a  result  of  social  experience  and  training. 

2.  Impulse  and  Purpose 

Man  is  not  merely  a  machine  reacting  to  physical  stimuli;  he 
does  not  rest  inert  until  he  is  jerked  and  pushed  by  outside  forces. 
The  use  of  such  terms  as  "will,"  "volition,"  or  "impulse"  signifies 
the  self-movement  of  the  organism:  the  infant  organism  moves  and 
wriggles  and,  in  due  course,  gains  a  purposive  control  over  the 
directions  and  objectives  of  its  conduct. 

From  the  rather  abstract  "standpoint  of  society,"  the  question  of 
impulse  is:  How  can  a  person  be  produced  who  wants,  or  "wills," 
what  is  socially  approved,  demanded,  or  premivimed?  How  can 
impulse  be  trained  to  fit  in  with  role-demands?  The  problem  of 
social  control  is  not  merely  one  of  coercing  persons  to  act  against 
their  own  wills,  but  rather  to  offer  socially  approved  goals  which 
will  be  incorporated  as  objectives  of  the  will. 

When  the  impulses  of  a  psychic  structure  are  directed  toward 
socially  approved  objectives,  they  support  and  sustain  the  person 
in  his  roles.  Then  he  wants  to  do  what  is  expected  of  him.  These 
roles  of  the  person,  many  of  which  are  segments  of  institutions, 
are  then  supported  by  the  trained  impulses  of  the  person. 

There  is  a  cycle  involving  undefined  impulses  and  socially  avail- 
able goals;  and,  by  repetition  and  suggestion,  punishment  and  re- 
ward, impulses  are  integrated  with  goals.  Persons  incorporate  the 
goals  and  link  them  with  impulses,  which  then  sustain  the  con- 
tinued operation  of  the  conduct  patterns  that  form  various  institu- 
tions. It  is  of  course  also  true  that  persons  may  invent  goals  in  order 
to  deal  with  challenges  which  frustrate  their  impulses,  and  these 
may  become  social  objectives. 


ORGANMSM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  45 

The  internal  stimulation  of  hunger,  thirst,  or  pain  may  excite 
the  infant  organism  to  general  action  and  sensitize  its  perceptions 
toward  certain  classes  of  objects.  This  activity  is  impulsive  and 
blind;  when  it  is  defined  by  external  objects,  when  animal  restless- 
ness fuses  with  social  objects,  it  is  socialized.  And  in  due  course,  if 
it  becomes  deliberate,  it  may  be  purposive. 

At  feeding  time  the  baby  raises  its  head,  waves  its  arms,  opens 
its  toothless  mouth.  Its  mother  says  that  it  is  hungry,  inferring 
"hunger"  from  the  activity  she  observes.  The  correctness  of  her 
imputation  is  shown  b\'  the  eagerness  with  which  the  baby  grasps 
the  nipple,  firmly  holds  it,  frantically  sucks.  By  the  choice  and 
control  of  the  food  that  is  offered,  the  baby's  food  preferences 
are  patterned.  It  learns  what  is  "good"  to  eat  and  what  is  "bad," 
that  food  is  good  and  feces  are  disgusting;  and  in  due  course,  it 
will  want  the  one  and  reject  the  other.  Impulses  for  food  are  thus 
disciplined  by  sensations  of  sight  and  touch,  of  taste  and  odor,  and 
more  importantly,  by  the  norms  of  others  expressed  in  the  child's 
presence:  the  social  definitions  of  appetites  and  thresholds  of  dis- 
gust. Through  her  expressions  of  disgust  and  her  gestures  of  ap- 
proval, the  mother  patterns  the  baby's  "taste."  Organic  disposition 
—the  baby's  "need"  for  food— its  dependence  upon  whatever  is  pro- 
vided, and  the  experience  of  gestured  approval  and  disgust  by 
those  who  care  for  it  merge  into  the  formation  of  the  appetite  and 
tastes  of  the  social  novice. 

If^several  activities  are  possible  and  the  individual  chooses  one 
and  refuses  the  others,  we  ascribe  will,  purpose,  or  volition  to  him. 
Such  a  mastery  of  one's  movement,  a  use  of  it  as  a  means  of  ac- 
quiring what  is  wanted,  involves  the  awareness  and  the  anticipa- 
tion of  goals.  Purpose,  desire,  or  intention,  as  one  stage  in  the 
development  of  impulse,  exists  when  impulses  have  found  objects. 

Such  anticipation  of  goals,  as  distinct  from  the  "pushes"  of  bare 
impulses  and  needs,  plays  a  decisive  role  in  man's  conduct.  The 
anticipation  of  goals  which  will  realize  our  impulses  is  often  in 
terms  of  symbols.  So  purpose  or  intention  may  be  termed  "sym- 
bolized impulse."  Wishes  or  desires  are  for  something.  Impulses 
which  are  not  so  attached  to  an  object  which  would  satisfy  them 
may  be  said  to  be  irrational  and/or  undefined.  We  cannot  fruit- 
fully treat  "desires"  as  standing  in  contrast  with  what  is  desired. 
In  desire,  content  and  impulse  form  an  intrinsic  unity.  When  the 
impulsive  features  of  a  psychic  structure  are  not  so  linked  and 


^6  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

integrated  with  objects,  they  may  burst  asunder  in  wild  and  ran- 
dom action  or  become  attached  to  objects  which  are  not  socially 
approved. 

•  The  definition  of  impulses  accompanies  the  definition  of  social 
situations.  Organic  impulse  and  social  situations  become  linked  so 
that  impulse  seeks  the  situation  as  an  outlet,  and  the  situation  fur- 
nishes the.. cue  and  sets  the  type  of  conduct  that  will  satisfy  the 
impulse.  Such  social  transformations  of  impulses  into  conduct  pat- 
terns are  important  aspects  of  the  social  integration  of  a  psychic 
structure.  The  internalization  of  social  values  and  objectives  gives 
direction  to  impulses  and,  to  some  extent,  even  sets  the  intensity 
of  these  impulses.  When  impulses  are  not  disciplined  into  com- 
municable purposes,  conduct  is  irrational:  it  cannot  readily  be  un- 
derstood in  terms  of  a  rational  calculation  to  attain  some  end, 
although  it  may  of  course  be  predictable  to  the  psychiatrist  in  ac- 
cordance with  his  scheme  of  diseases.  In  fact,  only  certain  areas  of 
social  life,  for  example,  the  rational  calculation  of  men  bargaining 
in  a  market,  typically  lend  themselves  to  strict  interpretation  in 
terms  of  the  rational  choice  of  expedient  means  for  explicit  ends. 

Because  undefined  impulses  become  desires  only  by  the  impor- 
tation of"sdctal  values,  we  cannot  take  "desires"  at  large,  nor  lists 
of  speuific  desires,  as  explanations  for  specific  conduct.  The  con- 
ditions of  concrete  desires  and  impulses  must  themselves  be  ex- 
plained, and  this  explanation  requires  us  to  pay  attention  to  inter- 
personal situations  which  train  and  which  steer  impulses. 

When  the  adult  observes  the  baby's  overt  activity  and  then  says 
that  it  "manifests"  desires,  he  is  treating  this  activity  as  a  symptom 
or  a  sign  of  desire.  For  the  baby,  no  connection  between  the  activ- 
ity and  the  goal  may  at  first  exist,  and  unless  it  does  we  cannot  say 
that  the  baby  is  acting  "out  of  desire."  Eventually,  activity  and 
goal  will  be  linked:  the  child  will  learn  to  elicit  an  activity  on  our 
part  which  completes  his  impulsive  activity.  He  will  then  be  acting 
"in  order  to"  experience  the  satisfaction  accruing  as  a  consequence 
of  his  action.  He  will  be  acting  purposively.  When  his  stomach  is 
empty  the  baby  squalls  impulsively.  Later,  he  will  link  this  squall 
to  the  touch  of  the  mother's  breast  and  later  to  the  visual  percep- 
tion of  the  mother.  When  the  tactual  and  visual  consequences  of 
the  squalling  are  linked  with  the  impulsive  spasm  of  squalling, 
the  baby  will  have  learned  to  cry  purposively.  He  will  experience 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  4/ 

his  cry  as  a  sign,  just  as  the  mother  had  previously  interpreted  it. 

We  learn  to  desire  by  having  our  impulses  frustrated;  purposes 
arise  our'df~deprivations;  they  involve  a  duality;  we  strive  against 
something;  to  have  will,  as  C.  S.  Pierce  put  it,  we  must  encounter 
resistance./^  But  before  the  physiological  deprivation  of  an  impulse 
can  become  a  desire,  experience  must  enter  to  connect  the  depri- 
vation to  a  meaningful  object  that  will  satisfy  it.  The  object  of  our 
desires  and  purposes  will  obviously  be  selected  from  among  the 
objects  that  are  socially  available  or  offered  to  us,  however  oddly 
they  may  be  combined  in  fantasies  which  arise  from  lengthy 
deprivations.  Qui"  desires  for  particular  things  are  ofteTi  placed  in 
us  by  the  fact  that  others  desire  them.  "EHiulutimi,  \\rot('  Spinoza, 
"is  the  desire  of  anything  which  is  engendered  in  us  from  the  fact 
that  we  imagine  others  to  desire  it  also."  ^- 

Objects  which  are  offered  to,  or  withdrawn  from,  the  infant,  be- 
come the  objectives  of  his  impulses.  Not  having  an  adequate  no- 
tion of  space  and  the  limits  and  burdens  which  it  places  upon 
man,  the  child  will  literally  reach  for  the  moon.  A  glaring  dispro- 
portion between  the  child's  impulsive  movements  toward  objects 
that  would  hurt  him  and  his  insufficient  fear  of  these  objects 
Ferenczi  has  called  "the  magical  hallucination  of  omnipotence." 
For  the  sake  of  the  physical  security  of  the  child,  his  guardians 
train  him  to  avoid  dangers  and  to  acquire  adequate  fears.  In  his 
interaction  with  others  and  with  things,  the  child  thus  acquires 
purposes  which  determine  the  direction  of  his  conduct  and  per- 
ception. Impulses  are  thus  socially  linked  to  perceptions  of  antici- 
pated goals  and  are  turned  away  from  harmful  traps. 

The  ascription  of  purposes  to  others  on  the  basis  of  our  own  pur- 
poses may  be  quite  complicated,  but  in  terms  of  our  awareness 
of  our  own  purposes  and  our  ascription  of  these  purposes  to  our- 
selves or  to  others,  there  are  four  types  of  situation.  (I)  We  may, 
in  rational  self-clarification,  know  our  own  purposes  and  ascribe 
them  to  ourselves  as  ours.  ( II )  Our  purposes  may  be  unknown  to  us, 
although  we  ascribe  them  to  ourselves,  as  in  undefined  states  of 
"longing"  or  "cravings"  or  "free-floating  anxieties."  (Ill)  We  may 

^^  Collected  Papers  (Cambridge,  Mass.:  Harvard  Univ.  Press,  1934),  Vol.  I, 
Book  3. 

1-  Beiiedictus  de  Spinoza,  Origin  and  Nature  of  the  Emotions,  Boyle's 
translation  (Everyman's  Library,  New  York,  1934). 


48  C^IARACTER     STRUCTURE 

know  our  purposes  and  yet  deliberately  ascribe  them  to  others,  as 
imperialist  statesmen  in  modern  propaganda  have  been  known  to 
do  just  before  they  launch  their  attacks.  (IV)  We  may  not  know 
our  purposes  and  at  the  same  time  unconsciously  ascribe  them  to 
others.  In  this  case,  we  speak  of  "projection,"  as  when  the  anti- 
Semite  believes  himself  to  be  persecuted  by  a  world  conspiracy  of 
Jews,  against  which  he  then  "defends"  himself:  he  projects  his  ag- 
gressiveness to  Jewry,  in  order  to  be  "free"  or  to  be  justified  in 
releasing  his  own  aggressiveness. 

The  straightforward  understanding  of  the  purposes  of  others  on 
the  basis  of  our  own  purposes  is  more  likely  to  be  accurate  in  so- 
cially standardized  situations.  For  if  two  persons  are  similarly 
trained,  the  purposes  which  the  one  finds  in  himself  are  likely  to  be 
similar  to  those  in  the  other.  But  in  a  society  composed  of  widely 
variegated  situations,  ascriptions  of  purpose  are  more  often  mis- 
taken. 

Men  may  treat  anything  which  proves  beneficent  as  motivated 
by  benevolent  purposes,  and  anything  which  hurts  them  as  mali- 
ciously motivated.  This  may  also  occur  with  reference  to  physical 
objects,  as  when  we  curse  a  chair  over  which  we  have  stumbled 
in  the  dark,  or  with  reference  to  impersonally  caused  social  up- 
heavals, as  when  men  curse  the  revolution  or  the  reaction  coming 
after  a  war. 

3.  Feeling  and  Emotion 

All  understanding  of  laughter  and  gaiety,  of  fear  and  trembling, 
and  other  expressive  phenomena  is  often  said  to  be  based  upon 
logical  inferences  from  one's  own  psychic  life  to  that  of  another. 
Actually,  however,  we  seem  to  understand  such  expressive  acts 
directly,  we  seem  to  understand  even  as  we  observe  the  activity. 

In  fact,  before  they  have  acquired  language,  infants— as  well 
as  some  domesticated  animals— seem  to  "understand"  the  facial 
expressions    of    adults.    Rene    Spitz,    in    exemplary    experiments,^^ 

1=^  Rene  A.  Spitz  with  the  assistance  of  K.  M.  Wolf,  "The  Smiling  Re- 
sponse: A  Contribution  to  the  Ontogenesis  of  Social  Relations,"  Genetic  Psy- 
chology Monographs,  Vol.  34,  1946,  pp.  57-125.  Cf.  also,  Weston  LaBarre, 
"The  Cultural  Basis  of  Emotions  and  Gestures,"  Journal  of  Personality,  Vol. 
16,  pp.  49-68,  reprinted  in  Personal  Character  and  Cultural  Milieu,  Douglas 
G.  Haring,  ed.  (rev.  ed.;  Syracuse:  Syracuse  Univ.  Press,  1949),  pp.  487-506. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  4Q 

has  shown  that  the  smihng  response  can  be  elicited  between  the 
second  and  sixth  month  by  the  direct  presentation  of  "another  hu- 
man being,"  or  what  the  baby  takes  to  be  another,  regardless  of  the 
facial  "expressions"  tliat  are  presented.  After  the  second  month, 
the  smile  is  "integrated  into  the  nascent  pattern  of  the  child's  emo- 
tional needs  on  the  social  level.  In  the  course  of  this  integration 
the  purely  motor  pattern  of  the  smile  is  endowed  with  the  psycho- 
logical meaning  inherent  in  the  child's  emotional  relations  with 
its  human  partners."  In  view  of  this,  Dr.  Spitz  feels  justified  in 
calling  the  smile  a  semantic  pattern,  a  genuine  communication. 

Dr.  Spitz,  dealing  with  the  exceptions  to  the  normal  smiling 
response,  holds  them  to  be  indicative  of  emotionally  disturbed 
child-mother  relation,  which  seems  to  indicate  that  this  gestural 
pattern— the  smile— is  an  acquired  aptitude  rather  than  the  un- 
folding of  an  "innate  disposition."  At  any  rate,  after  the  sixth 
month,  the  indiscriminate  smiling  response  becomes  more  discrim- 
inate. The  baby  distinguishes  friendly  and  unfriendly  faces. 

Not  all  bodily  movements  accompanying  emotions  are  expressive 
phenomena.  And  we  have  no  clear  knowledge  of  which  movements 
are  and  which  are  not  understandable  expressions.  We  do  not 
necessarily  and  directly  "understand"  the  dilated  pupil  as  a  phe- 
nomenon of  fear,  but  if  we  know  this  meaning  and  have  frequently 
observed  it,  then  we  seem  to  understand  the  enlarged  pupil  di- 
rectly as  fear. 

Let  us  carefully  sort  out  the  various  elements  involved  in  the 
whole  phenomena  of  feelings  and  emotions: 

I.  In  observing  the  conduct  and  appearance  of  other  persons, 
we  notice  on  certain  occasions  that  the  postures  of  their  bodies 
change,  their  voices  are  modulated  or  hysterical,  offensive  or  invit- 
ing. Sometimes  we  see  sweat  break  out  on  their  faces.  At  others, 
the  face  before  us  suddenly  goes  white,  or  the  play  of  its  features 
is  distorted.  People  look  at  us  with  aggressive  eyes  as  if  they 
wanted  to  destroy  us.  These  types  of  behavior  are  called  gestures. 

II.  Such  conduct  obviously  in\'olves  physiological  changes  in  the 
organism.  When  someone  "blushes  with  shame,"  the  distribution 
of  blood  within  his  body  has  concentrated  in  his  face.  When  he 
feels  strong  in  rage,  his  adrenalin  glands  have  brought  about  an 
increased  sugar  content  in  his  blood,  thus  strengthening  his  muscle 


$0  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

power.  In  times  of  stress  and  danger  the  organism  secretes  adrena- 
lin which,  in  co-operation  with  the  sympathetic  nervous  system, 
ehcits  sugar  from  the  hver  and  floods  the  blood  with  it;  this  sugar, 
in  turn,  eliminates  fatigue  in  the  muscles  and  strengthens  the  action 
systems  of  the  organism.  Within  ten  seconds  the  heart  beats  faster; 
within  three  minutes  after  an  "emotional  experience"  there  is  20  to 
30  per  cent  more  sugar  in  the  blood.  These  processes  increase  mus- 
cular efficiency;  physiologically,  the  body  prepares  for  exertion  in 
anticipation  of  action.^* 

III.  From  certain  gestures  and  expressive  movements  we  seem 
to  know  that  those  who  make  them  are  experiencing  certain  feel- 
ings, and  looking  within  ourselves  we  experience  the  fact  that  our 
own  gestures  often  involve  feeling  states.  These  feelings  of  pleas- 
ure, pain,  or  satisfaction  seem  to  belong  to  the  feeler  alone.  Our 
feelings  can  only  be  ascribed  to  us  by  others  on  the  basis  of  our 
gestures  and  appearance.  We  do  not  read  these  signs  unerringly 
and  thus  know  the  feelings  of  others;  sometimes,  even  often,  we  do 
not  know  directly,  nor  can  we  name,  what  we  ourselves  feel. 

Simple  feeling  states,  or  moods,  or  "affects,"  may  be  diffused:  we 
feel  tiredness  or  buoyancy  all  over;  or,  these  feelings  may  be  local- 
ized in  the  organism:  we  have  an  acute  toothache.  When  feelings 
are  localized,  we  can  sometimes  deflect  attention  away  from  them, 
and  thus  diminish  the  intensity  of  our  awareness.  Normally,  feel- 
ings of  hunger  and  thirst  are  localized  signals  of  general  bodily 
needs,  but  as  hunger  becomes  starvation  our  whole  psychic  life  is 
affected,  and  all  our  declining  energies  are  marshaled  to  serve  our 
craving  for  food.  And  as  we  sink  into  a  state  of  general  drowsiness, 
food  becomes  the  all-absorbing  concern  of  our  phantasy  life  and 
thought,  of  our  feelings  and  consciousness.  Feelings  of  sexual  at- 
traction are  usually  diffused,  but  in  severe  tension  they  may  be 
heavily  localized  in  specific  erotic  zones. 

Both  localized  and  diffused  feeling  states  may  be  classified  in 
terms  of  their  respective  intensities  of  pain  or  pleasure.  Thus: 
There  is  the  intense,  localized  feeling  of  a  broken  bone;  the  intense, 
general  feeling  of  starvation;  the  mild  yet  localized  pain  of  a  small 

^*  A  good  account  of  the  physiological  changes  involved  in  emotions  is 
available  in  Walter  B.  Cannon,  Bodily  Changes  in  Pain,  Hunger,  Fear,  and 
Rage  (2d  ed.;  New  York:  Appleton,  1929),  pp.  194,  196,  220,  225,  343.  For 
a  comprehensive  examination  of  the  literature,  see  H.  F.  Dunbar,  Emotions 
and  Bodily  Changes  (New  York:   Columbia  Univ.  Press,   1935). 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  ^1 

cut;  the  mild,  general  feeling  of  tiredness;  the  intense,  localized 
pleasure  of  the  loving  kiss;  the  intense,  general  feeling  of  bliss  or 
euphoria;  the  mild,  localized  feeling  of  a  pleasant  taste  in  our 
mouth;  and  there  is  the  mild,  general  awareness  that  we  just  feel 
good.  Of  course  there  are  thresholds  of  intensity:  climactic  pain 
may  become  so  unbearable  that  we  faint  to  save  ourselves  from 
further  awareness.  And  with  palliatives,  drugs,  and  ethers,  modern 
medicine  has  made  the  intensities  of  pains  and  our  awareness  of 
them  more  manageable.  ^° 

It  is  possible  to  approach  "emotions"  in  terms  of  einotioiml  ges- 
tures, in  terms  of  physiological  conditions  in  the  organism,  or  in 
terms  of  our  awareness  of  feelings  in  the  psychic  structure.  To 
understand  emotions,  we  must  avail  ourselves  of  each  of  these  levels 
of  description.  We  must  see  how  they  are  each  experienced,  how 
social  factors  are  involved  in  the  experience  of  their  operations, 
and  precisely  how  the  various  levels  may  be  linked. 

One  statement  of  the  occasion  and  nature  of  emotions  runs  as 
follows:  If  an  organism  acts  immediately  and  adequately  in  the 
presence  of  some  stimulating  occasion,  no  emotion  is  engendered. 
The  action  proceeds  smoothly  and  no  gestures,  no  feelings,  and 
no  physiological  changes  need  occur.  If,  however,  the  response  is 
in  some  way  blocked  or  the  impulse  behind  it  is  frustrated,  emotion 
occurs;  then  gestures  and  feelings  will  make  their  appearance.  The 
urgency  of  the  feelings  may  be  reduced  by  the  expression  of  emo- 
tional gestures.  Emotions  occur,  the  statement  runs,  when  the  or- 
ganism is  disorganized;  when  it  has  no  ready  response.  When  be- 
havior is  running  smoothly  no  emotional  outbursts  occur. 

Such  a  formal  physiological  scheme  does  not  tell  us  how  we  are 
to  distinguish  between  different  emotions,  nor  does  it  inform  us 

15  There  is  another  type  of  feehng  which  invoKes  an  awareness  of  our 
self  as  well  as  of  our  body.  We  feel  ashamed  or  guilty  or  generally  insecure. 
These  experiences  may  be  called  self-related  feelings:  we  shall  call  them  emo- 
tions. They  involve  the  psychic  structure,  just  as  simple  feelings  of  pleasure 
do,  but  they  also  involve  the  person.  Our  image  of  our  self,  which  is  reflected 
from  the  social  experiences  which  form  the  person,  is  in^'olved  in  them. 
(See  Chapter  IV:  The  Person.)  The  emotions  which  are  related  to  this  self- 
image  are  linked  with  situations  and  social  occasions  in  which  emotional  states 
are  experienced.  They  are  related  to  the  position  of  the  self  within  the 
social  circle  of  others.  Such  self-related  feelings,  or  emotions,  may  react 
upon  and  elicit  more  simple  awareness  of  general  feelings. 


52  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

of  the  social  occasions  which  for  different  types  of  persons  en- 
gender the  feehngs,  gestures,  and  physiology  of  emotions.  Emo- 
tions, especially  if  they  are  intense,  cannot  be  classified  in  terms 
of  differing  physiological  conditions,  nor  in  terms  of  different  ges- 
tures. Both  fear  and  rage  may  involve  similar  glandular  secretions, 
similar  facial  contortions,  and  even  awareness  of  similar  feelings. 
Different  emotions  are  identified  in  terms  of  the  situations  in  which 
gestures  are  expressed.  The  vocabularies  which  are  used  as  a  re- 
sponse of  others  to  our  gestures  define  and  give  meaning  to  our 
emotion. 

As  "different  emotions "  become  more  intense,  their  gestural  and 
feeling  aspects  become  more  similar.  Psychic  elements  seem  to 
take  over  the  whole  character  structure.  The  control  of  emotions 
by  the  person  is  minimized,  or  even  shattered.  We  cannot  time  and 
shape  the  gestural  expressions  nor  the  feelings  according  to  de- 
fined occasions;  we  are  overwhelmed.  If  the  occasions  which  so 
upset  us  recur,  we  may  develop  ways  of  meeting  them.  If  we  can 
organize  appropriate  roles  or  rituals,  and  thus  integrate  and  socially 
steer  our  emotions,  our  psychic  structures  will  be  less  likely  to  take 
over  the  character  structure  as  a  whole  and  thus  dominate  our 
conduct. 

To  understand  what  "emotional  experiences"  involve,  and  what 
specific  direction  increased  bodily  power  may  take  during  such 
experiences,  we  must  consider  not  only  the  physiological  organism 
and  the  psychic  structure,  but  also  the  person.  In  the  face  of  "dan- 
ger," flight  is  possible,  but  so  is  struggle  and  attack;  fear,  as  well 
as  rage  or  hate,  may  be  felt.  Adrenalin  does  not  decide  which  of 
these  emotions  will  be  experienced  and  enacted.  There  do  not,  for 
example,  seem  to  be  noteworthy  differences  in  the  visceral  accom- 
paniments of  fear  and  anger.  In  anger  and  in  rage,  in  fear  and  in 
fury,  there  is  adrenalin.  The  organism  allows  us,  indeed  helps  us, 
to  become  truly  fearful  or  full  of  powerful  rage.  But  there  does 
not  seem  to  be  any  one  stimulating  condition  in  the  physical  en- 
vironment of  the  organism  that  automatically  produces  awareness 
of  any  given  emotional  feeling  or  the  expression  of  certain  emo- 
tional gestures.  We  must  go  beyond  the  organism  and  the  physical 
environment  to  account  for  human  emotions.  Physiological  psy- 
chology has  not  reached  a  point  at  which  it  can  claim  to  have 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  $2 

established  the  identity  or  parallehsm  of  physiological  processes 
and  specific  emotional  sequences  and  feelings. 

"Emotional  experiences"  give  the  cue  for  physiological  prepara- 
tion; and  after  these  experiences  are  under  way  the  physical  exer- 
tion produces  further  bodily  changes.  Socially  induced  worry,  ex- 
citement, or  anxiety,  for  example,  may  distm-b  the  digestive  proc- 
esses, or  cause  peptic  ulcers  in  the  walls  of  the  stomach.  The 
mechanisms  seem  to  include  increased  acidity  as  well  as  move- 
ments of  contraction  in  the  stomach. 

The  brain  does  not  have  any  direct  control  over  the  viscera.^'' 
The  autonomic  nervous  system  and  the  system  of  our  glands,  ac- 
cording to  modern  medicine,  are  the  links  of  physiology  and  the 
study  of  conduct  and  experience:  they  make  up  the  sphere  of 
the  psychosomatic.^^ 

The  chief  access  we  have  to  the  autonomic  nervous  system  is  the 
experience  of  moods.  These  feeling-states,  as  Ives  Hendrick  has 
said,  are  thought  to  be  an  awareness  of  "changes  in  the  muscle  tone 
and  blood  supply  of  our  internal  organs  produced  by  autonomic 
nervous  stimulation  .  .  ."  ^*  At  times  we  cannot  control  such  feel- 
ings. Physiologically  this  means  that  the  central  nervous  system  is 
"immobilized"  so  that  we  cannot  control  the  "panicky  feeling,"  or 
sometimes  the  excretory  functions  of  the  organism. 

Whatever  our  theoretical  assumptions  concerning  the  complex 
relations  between  physiological  organism  and  psychic  structure,  we 
know  that  externally  produced  physiological  changes,  for  instance 
the  consumption  of  stimulants  or  drugs  like  coffee,  alcohol,  mari- 
juana, or  aspirin,  often  becomes  relevant.  A  society  may  avail  itself, 
at  conventionally  and  legally  defined  occasions,  of  these  toxics;  it 
may  manage  to  suppress,  or  indeed,  to  impose  them.  In  colonial 
societies,  alcohol  has  been  distributed  to  natives  as  a  technique  of 
"domestication."  And  as  we  have  already  remarked,  suitable  meas- 
ures of  alcohol  have  also,  on  occasion,  been  used  to  reduce  con- 
ventional inhibitions,  as  between  the  sexes.  Legal  as  well  as  con- 
ventional norms  may  define  the  range  and  direction  of  permitted 
consumption.  In  Western  societies  the  habitual  and  medically  un- 
authorized use  of  cocaine  is  prosecuted,  and  accordingly,  trade  in 

^^  Cannon,  op.  cit.,  p.  264. 

i'^  Ives  Hendrick,  Facts  and  Theories  of  Psyclwanahjsis  (2d  ed.;  New  York: 
Knopf,    1944),   pp.   290-91. 
IS  Ibid.,  p.  289. 


54  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

such  stimulants  is  specifically  licensed.  Such  norms  have,  of  course, 
been  violated,  as  when  the  British  under  the  slogan  of  free  trade  im- 
posed opium  upon  defenseless  populations  in  China,  as  did  the  Japa- 
nese at  a  later  date.  When  coffee  was  introduced  into  seventeenth- 
century  England,  there  were  attempts  to  suppress  its  use.  The  au- 
thorities feared  the  politically  suspect  sociability  of  literati  and 
businessmen  in  the  coffee  houses;  the  women  wanted  their  men 
to  stay  at  home  and  away  from  the  morally  suspect  female  em- 
ployees of  such  establishments. 

The  meaning  of  a  situation  to  a  person  sets  the  experience  and 
the  nature  of  emotion.  These  meanings  vary  according  to  the  per- 
son's past  experiences;  these  experiences,  in  turn,  must  be  explained 
in  terms  of  the  person's  position  and  career  within  given  kinds  of 
social  structure.  Now,  recurring  situations  become  stereotyped  in 
their  meaning  for  emotion.^"  In  some,  it  is  "proper "  to  become  fear- 
ful and  run;  in  others  it  is  cowardly  so  to  feel  and  act.  The  Ameri- 
can father  is  conventionally  expected  to  gush  joyfully  at  sight  of  a 
newborn  baby;  the  Roman  father  could  inspect  it  critically,  de- 
ciding to  accept  or  reject  it.  Persons  internalize  these  social  ex- 
pectations of  emotional  display,  which  thus,  at  the  proper  occasion, 
are  exemplified  by  the  psychic  structure.  Even  if  we  feel  joy  on 
some  occasions,  we  may  suppress  the  gestures  of  joy,  should  the 
occasion  and  our  associates  conventionally  expect  a  display  of  sor- 
row. 

19  Gestures  and  mimic  movements  are  of  course  socially  and  historically 
determined;  they  have,  as  it  were,  a  grammar  of  their  own,  although  the 
expressively  gesturing  person  may  know  of  this  grammar  as  little  as  M.  Jourdain 
knew  of  the  fact  that  he  had  been  speaking  prose  all  his  life.  D.  Efron  has 
compared  the  gestural  habits  of  East  European  Jews  with  that  of  first-genera- 
tion Italian  immigrants.  He  found  that  in  Jewish  arm  gestures,  the  upper 
arm  and  elbow  are  held  close  to  the  body,  that  the  lower  arm  and  the 
hand  are  used  at  a  close  distance  to  the  conversational  partner;  there  is  a 
sort  of  turtle  movement  of  the  head,  a  poking  with  the  finger,  or  across  the 
table  with  the  fork;  there  are  down  strokes  with  the  hand  or  chin  and  beard. 
By  contrast,  Italian  gestures  seek  the  greatest  possible  amplitude  for  horizontal 
movements  of  the  outstretched  arms  and  hands,  to  the  right  and  left  of  the 
bodily  axis.  Efron  attributes  these  differences  to  the  ghetto,  with  its  physical 
narrowness,  in  contrast  to  the  Italian  plaza,  as  delimiting  and  facilitating  scenes 
of  expressive  behavior.  Subsequent  generations  of  immigrant  Italians  and 
Jews  of  course  lose  these  gestural  peculiarities  as  they  take  on  the  general 
Amrican  pattern  of  expressive  behavior.  See  D.  Efron,  Gesture  and  Environ- 
ment (New  York:   Columbia  Univ.   Press,   1941). 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  ^^ 

Gestures  of  sorrow— stylized  according  to  expectation— may  be- 
come the  basis  lor  feelings  of  sorrow.  Thus  the  person  regulates 
the  psychic  structure,  although  of  course  psychic  elements  may 
burst  out  in  uncontrollable  ways.  By  our  facial,  bodily,  and  verbal 
gestures  we  make  evident  to  others  our  psychic  reactions.  But 
when  our  feelings  are  vague  and  inchoate,  the  reactions  of  others 
to  our  gestures  may  help  define  what  we  really  come  to  feel.  For 
example,  if  a  girl  has  been  jilted  at  the  altar  and  is  generally  upset 
about  it,  the  responses  of  her  mother  may  define  the  girl's  feelings 
of  sadness  and  great  grief,  or  of  indignation  and  anger.  In  such 
cases,  our  gestures  do  not  necessarily  "express"  our  prior  feelings. 
They  make  available  to  others  a  sign.  But  what  it  is  a  sign  of 
may  be  influenced  by  their  reactions  to  it.  We,  in  turn,  may  inter- 
nalize their  imputation  and  thus  define  our  inchoate  feeling.  The 
social  interaction  of  gestures  may  thus  not  only  express  our  feel- 
ings but  define  them  as  well. 

Moreover,  our  gestures  may  elicit  or  impose  feelings  which  at 
first  were  not  present.  For  example,  a  child  may  playfully  heave  a 
brickbat  at  another  innocent  youngster.  The  second  youngster  may 
not  take  the  act  as  a  playful  gesture  but  treat  it  as  an  indication 
of  meanness  and  aggression.  This  definition  of  the  affective  intent 
by  another  on  the  basis  of  the  gesture  or  act  may  lead  to  a  fight 
in  which  the  first  child  acquires  a  feeling  more  socially  appropriate 
to  his  own  gestures.-"  The  child  thus  links  certain  gestures  and 
acts  with  their  conventionally  ascribed  feelings.  Children,  or  adults 
for  that  matter,  may  begin  to  feel  angry  while  they  are  scuffling  or 
fighting.  "Hostility,"  as  Bovet  has  made  clear,  cannot  be  abstracted 
and  treated  as  a  cause  of  fighting;  it  may  just  as  well  be  an  effect 
of  fighting  acts  and  fighting  gestures. 

We  know  our  own  emotioi^  by  observations  of  our  gestures  and 
actions,  and  more  importantly  perhaps,  by  what  other  people  ob- 
serve and  report  to  us,  directly  or  indirectly  by  their  responses  and 
gestures  to  the  gestures  we  have  made.  Even  if  the  external  ges- 
tures from  which  persons  normally  infer  the  emotions  felt  by  others 
are  not  available,  as  to  the  deaf  or  blind,  the  emotional  agitations 
of  others  may  be  detected  by  feeling  the  tensions  in  the  muscles 
of  their  arms  and  hands. -^ 

-"See  Pierre  Bo\et,  TJie  Fi^Jitinf^  Instinct,  J.  Y.  T.  Greig,  tr.  (New  York: 
Dodd  Mead,  1923),  pp.  23-27. 

-1  Helen  Keller,  Stunj  of  My  Life  (New  York:  Doubleday,  1903),  p.  353  ff. 


^6  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

Normally,  a  certain  skill  of  emotional  expression  is  socially  de- 
manded. Because  of  traumatic  shocks  or  slights,  a  person  may  at 
an  early  time  seek  spurious  emotional  security  by  what  seems  to 
him  riskless  withdrawal  behavior.  Accordingly,  he  may  not  learn 
how  to  "deal"  with  people.  But  this  does  not  necessarily  mean  that 
he  is  insensitive,  or  has  no  feelings.  On  the  contrary,  he  may  be 
hypersensitixe,  and  out  of  overwhelming  fear  of  contact,  prefer 
withdrawal  and  isolation. 

Out  of  the  social  interplay  of  gestures  a  vocabulary  of  emotions 
emerges:  the  terms  for  the  emotions  and  feelings  which  are  sup- 
posed to  accompany  certain  gestures  bring  out  the  meaning  of 
those  gestures  for  other  persons.  The  vocabulary  of  emotions  the 
person  acquires  is  usually  limited  to  the  more  common  emotions 
experienced  by  all  members  of  a  language  group  in  a  similar 
enough  manner  to  have  been  given  common  names.  It  is  no  acci- 
dent that  such  phrases  as  "that  leaves  me  speechless"  exist  in  several 
different  languages.  At  times,  under  severe  emotional  shocks,  per- 
sons actually  do  lose  their  power  of  speech  and  may  even  become 
mute  for  life. 

Skill  groups,  such  as  poets  and  novelists,  specialize  in  fashioning 
and  developing  vocabularies  for  emotional  states  and  gestures;  they 
specialize  in  telling  us  how  we  feel,  as  well  as  how  we  should  or 
might  feel,  in  various  situations.  Many  terms  for  our  emotions  be- 
come useless  as  they  become  banal  or  trivial  through  too  frequent 
use.  Stale  words  may  not  serve  to  designate  fresh  feelings.  Thus, 
we  find  fashions  in  the  vocabularies  of  emotion.  We  smile  today 
at  the  direct  way  in  which  books  given  to  young  Anglo-Saxon  ladies 
in  the  1830's  verbalized  the  sentiments  of  friendship  and  love,  or 
at  how  Dickens  described  his  heroines'  feelings  about  their  mates. 
We  now  shy  at  using  words  thus  "Icmded"  with  the  gush  of  emo- 
tion of  sentiment.  Many  twentieth-century  European  and  American 
expressions  were  taboo  in  the  Puritan  past.  Certain  terms  may  be 
transferred  from  one  sphere  of  emotion  to  another  sphere  in  which 
they  lose  their  appropriateness:  by  the  incongruity  of  such  shifts 
the  terms  are  banalized  and  made  "hollow."  For  example,  political 
slogans  meant  to  engage  public  sentiment  and  to  implement  na- 
tional efforts  have  often  been  exploited  for  private  commercial 
ends.  Advertisements  for  eyeglasses  have  tried  to  exploit  the  emo- 
tions of  a  war,  the  eyeglass  manufacturer  implying  that  those  who 
do  not  buy  are  saboteurs  of  the  war  effort. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  ^J 

Much  contemporary  literature  and  music  deals  with  such  "emo- 
tional masks,"  by  means  of  caricatures;  "Yankee  Doodle,"  for 
instance,  may  be  musically  caricatured,  distorting  the  harmonious 
features  of  the  tune  or  chords  or  substituting  words  to  deliberately 
produce  incongruities.  Prokofiev  and  e.  e.  cummings,  Stravinsky 
and  Bert  Brecht  are  masters  of  such  effects,  as,  for  that  matter,  is 
Charlie  Chaplin,  in  the  incongruous  opening  of  his  Modern  Times. 
Daumier's  sketches  may  be  said  to  have  "dethroned"  the  Olympian 
figures  before  continental  Europe.  Karl  Marx  theorized  about  such 
matters  when  he  stated  that  the  end  of  an  epoch  repeats  in 
comical  form  what  at  the  beginning  is  enacted  as  heroic  tragedy, 
fie  assigned  a  psychological  function  to  this  by  stating  that  man- 
kind could  thus  bid  farewell  to  outlived  forms,  not  with  nostalgia, 
but  with  gaiety,  and  he  viewed  in  this  sense  Napoleon  III  as  the 
comical  repetition  of  Napoleon  the  Great.  If  Beethoven's  work 
belongs  in  the  Napoleonic  age,  Offenbach's,  for  good  reasons,  be- 
longs in  the  age  of  Napoleon  III  and  the  Empress  Eugenie. 

There  are  vocabularies  for  gestures  and  other  vocabularies  for 
feelings,  but  usually  the  two  are  combined.  "Sadness"  may  thus 
refer  to  both  the  feeling-state  and  the  drawn-down  mouth  and 
tearful  eye.  This  double  reference  combined  in  a  single  term  may 
be  one  cause  of  the  social  coincidence  of  gesture  and  feeling.  For 
it  symbolizes  the  expectation  that  the  displayed  feeling  is  genuine, 
an  expectation  based  upon  observation  of  the  person's  gesture. 

But  often  emotional  gestures  may  be  "put  on"  without  any  "cor- 
responding" affective  feelings  being  present.  Ranging  from  the 
expert  professional  actress  to  the  insincere  lover  with  the  tender 
look,  the  stylization  of  emotional  gestures  may  proceed  without 
any  development  of  corresponding  feelings.  We  characterize  as 
"spurious"  those  emotions  which  are  not  felt  but  which  consist 
merely  of  gestural  "expressions."  Those  gestures  which  do,  in  fact, 
reveal  feelings  appropriate  to  them  we  call  "genuine."  It  should  be 
remembered  that  the  distinction  is  nice,  and  in  many  cases  the 
inference  from  gesture  to  feeling  is  very  difficult  to  make.  Further- 
more, in  observing  the  gestures  of  others  we  often  come  to  a  point 
where  our  externally  responsive  gesturings  invoke  their  feelings 
within  us.  Thus,  we  experience  borrowed  emotions,  which,  like 
our  original  gestures,  may  at  first  be  spurious  displays,  put  on 
for  the   purpose  of  dissimulation,   but   later   be   internalized   and 


^8  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

thus  become  quite  genuine.   The  diffusion  of  the  Nazi  salute  in 
Germany  may  be  cited. 

Emotional  vocabularies  of  patriotism  may  be  imposed  upon 
populations  who  are  thus  denied  the  public  "expression"  of  their 
own  sentiments.  Nationalist  prospects  may  be  sentimentalized  as 
"Missions,"  and  nationalist  history  becomes  the  hallowed  memories 
of  heroes  and  martyrs.  In  such  cases,  some  persons  may  experience 
the  imposed  sentiments  as  spurious,  although  they  may  make  the 
conventional  gestures  that  express  no  emotion;  others  may  with- 
draw even  from  the  gestures,  and  some  may  even  actively  criticize 
and  resist  both  the  inner  meaning  and  the  outer  expression. 

For  the  degree  to  which  persons  can  play  roles  involving  emo- 
tional gestures  without  feeling  the  emotions  conventionally  appro- 
priate to  them  varies  widely,  in  terms  of  types  of  individuals  and 
in  terms  of  the  frame  of  conventions.  In  the  course  of  Western 
civilization,  the  rising  lower  classes  have  attributed  greater  truth 
and  honesty  in  such  matters  to  themselves  than  to  the  "sophisti- 
cated" upper  classes.  The  rising  plebeian  almost  always  places  a 
premium  on  "uprightness"  and  "candor"  and  "righteous  indigna- 
tion." Exclusive  and  high  status  groups,  on  the  other  hand,  are 
apt  to  feel  that  if  they  owe  truthfulness  and  candor  to  anyone, 
it  is  to  their  peers,  but  never  to  those  "not  on  their  level."  Polite 
speech  generally  seems  more  important  to  them  than  honest  speech. 
The  language  of  righteous  indignation  is  discounted  as  "rude"  or 
"tactless,"  and  in  any  case,  "beneath  them."  And  yet,  the  sense 
of  responsibility  of  high  decision-making  circles  in  crisis  situations 
makes  them  inclined  to  ascribe  to  themselves  an  extraordinary 
capacity  to  "face  the  facts,"  which  they  feel  might  unnerve  the 
contemporary  Little  Man  or  the  Common  Man. 

Autobiographical  statements  of  actors  and  actresses  -2— experts 
in  gesturing— indicate  that  the  artistic  enactment  of  prescribed  roles 
may  lead  to  an  intense  emotional  identification  of  person  and 
psychic  structure  with  role  and  hence  to  deep  feelings  appropriate 

--  On  the  following  autobiographical  statements  of  actors,  we  quote  from 
the  following,  in  the  order  given:  K.  E.  Behnke,  Speech  and  Movement  on 
the  Stage  (New  York:  Oxford,  1930),  p.  166;  John  Barrymore,  Confessions  of 
an  Actor  (Indianapolis:  Bobbs-Merrill,  1926),  no  pagination;  Morton  Eustis, 
Players  At  Work    (New  York:   Theatre  Arts,   1937),  pp.   26  and  45. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  59 

to  the  role  and  the  character  played.-^  On  the  other  hand,  there 
are  actors  who  interpret  the  gestures  with  which  they  act  out  a 
role  in  a  detached  and  calculating  manner;  they  do  not  feel  that 
their  own  personality  and  psychic  structure  is  fused  with  the 
enacted  character,  and  they  do  not,  therefore,  experience  the 
emotions  which  their  gestures  spuriously  display.-' 

The  fact  that  professional  actors  and  actresses  have  different 
attitudes  concerning  the  emotional  feelings  appropriate  to  the 
gestures  of  the  roles  they  present  has  led  to  a  variety  of  esthetic 
norms,  held  by  professional  critics  and  laymen.  The  social  psy- 
chologist records  the  range  and  types  of  experiences  and  notes 
that  no  doctrine  or  rule  of  the  psijchic  structure  covers  the  mat- 
ter. To  understand  the  extent  to  which  gestures  correspond  with 
feelings,  one  must  know  something  of  the  persons  involved  and 
the  conventions  of  the  situation  in  which  the  gesture  and  emotion 
are  presumably  linked. 

Emotional  masks  may  be  said  to  have  a  "tighter"  or  a  "looser" 
fit  for  the  social  actor.  Theatrical  styles,  as  we  have  just  seen,  vary 
in  this  respect.  Nowadays  it  would  seem  that  critics  and  audiences 
prefer  a  "loose"  fit  and  derive  special  enjoyment  from  realizing  the 
self-conscious  distance  of  the  person  of  the  actor  from  his  presented 
mask.  Bert  Brecht  has  raised  this  attitude  to  a  principle  of  mod- 
ern staging,  and  has  scored  singular  success  with  his  performances 
in  postwar  Europe.  A  specific  ethos  informs  this  stand,  basically 
holding  that  stage  acting  is  after  all  "play,"  and  that  the  art 
consists  in  being  quite  serious  about  the  playfulness  of  the  play, 
lest  the  presumption  of  sincerity  become  ridiculous.  This  whole 

23  Ristori,  the  great  Italian  tragedienne,  claims:  "I  throw  my  whole  pas- 
sionate soul  into  my  emotional  scenes,  because  I  know  that  my  technique  will 
ne\er  desert  me."  John  Barrymore,  playing  Galsworthy's  Justice:  "On  the 
opening  night  when  I  pounded  with  frenzy  on  my  cell  door,  I  broke  right 
through  the  wood  grating  which  was  painted  black  as  an  understudy  for 
iron." 

-*  Helen  Hayes  believes  that  she  follows  this  pattern:  "At  some  time  or 
other  I  must  feel  the  role,  but  never  in  actual  performance.  There  is  usually 
one  rehearsal  in  which  I  go  through  the  part  with  real  feeling.  Thereafter,  I 
simulate  what  I  haxe  felt."  Such  players  as  Alia  Nazimova,  Katliarine  Cornell, 
and  Maurice  Exans  agree  with  Burgess  Meredith  who  says:  "You  are  conscious 
of  the  effect  that  emotion  should  produce,  but  you  don't  let  it  affect  you." 
Ina  Claire  goes  further:  "The  moment  tlie  actor  lets  himself  feel  the  emo- 
tions, he  begins  to  wallow  in  a  role,  he  becomes  a  ham." 


6o  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

tendency  has  undoubtedly  been  influenced  by  the  development  of 
motion  picture  acting,  which  is  best  where  the  actor  "acts"  least, 
and  which  has  trained  the  movie  audience  to  new  levels  of  critical 
appreciation,  to  the  quick  grasping  of  meaningful  sights  and 
sounds,  of  the  weight  and  significance  of  gestures  and  words.  So 
a  slip  of  the  tongue,  which  fifty  years  ago  went  unnoticed  by  all 
but  psychiatrists,  nowadays  is  understood  by  millions,  when  pre- 
sented close-up  and  on  a  magnified  sound-track. 

Certain  occasions  conventionally  require  certain  gestures.  A  per- 
son may  cry  and  otherwise  express  grief,  not  because  his  relative 
has  died,  but  because  he  is  at  a  funeral.  Crying  may  be  a  ritual 
of  conduct,  as  is  the  wearing  of  black  clothing.  Gestures  without 
feehngs  may  also  be  simulated  for  the  purposes  of  rational  bar- 
gaining, as  when  sororities  on  college  campuses  send  their  very 
best  "pleader"  to  a  professor  to  inveigle  better  grades  for  a  failing 
pledge  who  is  not  so  adept  at  crying. 

The  gestures  supposedly  accompanying  various  emotions  may  be 
stylized  without  affecting  any  change  of  feelings.  But  this  styliza- 
tion  of  gesture  may  in  time  influence  and  stylize  the  effect.  When 
you  begin  the  ritual  gestures  of  a  funeral  you  may  not  feel  grief, 
but  in  time  the  atmosphere  of  the  funeral  throng  with  its  incanta- 
tions of  grief,  its  evocations  of  sorrow,  may  affect  you  quite 
genuinely. 

When  we  ascribe  feelings  to  others  in  terms  of  what  we  our- 
selves feel,  the  basis  of  our  analogy  is  social.  The  correctness  or 
falseness  of  such  imputations  does  not  have  to  depend  upon  any 
general  biological  similarity  of  human  organisms.  We  can  some- 
times interpret  correctly  the  behavior  and  gestures  of  others  by 
ascribing  to  them  sentiments,  emotions,  or  purposes  similar  to  our 
own  because:  (i)  our  interpretation  of  their  external  gestures,  or 
of  the  situation  they  are  in,  influences  and  helps  to  define  for 
them  what  they  feel,  and  (2)  because  of  the  standardized  expecta- 
tion of  certain  gestures,  and  eventually  of  inner  feeling-states,  mo- 
tives, and  emotions,  which  are  set  up  in  recurring  social  situations 
within  given  societies.  The  measure  to  which  we  are  correct  in 
ascribing  our  feelings  to  others  in  any  given  case  depends  upon 
the  extent  to  which  these  two  conditions  hold  true. 

Today,  under  conditions  of  mass  movie-attendance,  the  styliza- 
tions  of  such  emotions  as  tenderness,  or  various  models  of  erotic 
allurement  or  approach,  tend  to  be  standardized  and  fashioned 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  6l 

after  the  movie  stars  who  speciahze  in  such  matters.  And  there 
are  gestural  fads  which  are  related  to  fashions  of  clothing  and 
make-up;  the  bent  head  with  the  eyes  looking  slyly  out  from  under 
the  brows  goes  with  big  brimmed  hats  or  heavy  bangs.  Various 
gestures  have  differing  prestige  values  attached  to  them,  and  insofar 
as  inner  feelings  may  develop  from  the  repeated  use  of  gestiu'es 
in  recurring  roles,  the  emotions  as  well  as  the  gestures  of  members 
of  various  status  groups  may  be  stereotyped. 

On  the  other  hand,  gestures  may  be  conventionalized  precisely 
to  hide  inner  feelings  of  one  sort  or  another.  In  old  Japan  a  code 
of  deportment  was  elaborated  in  which  it  was  a  "mark  of  disrespect 
to  betray,  by  look  or  gesture,  any  feeling  of  grief  or  pain  in  the 
presence  of  a  superior."  The  code  exacted  very  much  more  than 
impassiveness.  It  required  not  only  that  any  sense  of  anger  or  pain 
should  be  denied  all  outward  expression,  but  that  the  sufferer's 
face  and  manner  should  indicate  the  contrary  feeling.  Sullen  sub- 
mission was  an  offense;  mere  impassive  obedience  inadequate;  the 
proper  degree  of  submission  should  manifest  itself  by  a  pleasant 
smile,  and  by  a  soft  and  happy  tone  of  voice.  The  smile,  however, 
was  also  regulated.  One  had  to  be  careful  about  the  quality  of  the 
smile.  It  was  a  mortal  offense,  for  example,  in  addressing  a  superior, 
to  smile  in  such  a  way  that  the  back  teeth  could  be  seen.  In  the 
military  class  especially  this  code  was  ruthlessly  enforced.  The 
women  of  the  Samurai,  like  the  women  of  Sparta,  were  required  to 
show  signs  of  joy  on  hearing  that  their  husbands  or  sons  had  fallen 
in  battle;  to  betray  any  other  feeling  was  a  grave  breach  of 
decorum.-'"' 

A  person  whose  conception  of  his  own  welfare  is  deeply  in- 
volved in  the  sacredness  of  religious  objects  will  experience  awe 
in  their  presence.  He  will  become  enraged  at  their  desecration  or 
destruction.  A  person  who  has  not  incorporated  these  objects  as 
sacred,  however,  may  be  not  at  all  awed,  but,  although  externally 
respectful,  amused  at  people  who  go  mewling  to  the  mosque.  To 
the  person  whose  security  of  self  is  deeply  involved  in  the  approval 
of  a  political  party  whose  program  includes  atheism,  the  destruc- 
tion of  the  sacred  objects  and  the  personnel  who  service  them 

-5  Cf.  Lafcadio  Ht-arn,  Japan:  An  Attempt  at  Interpretation  (New  York: 
Macmillan,   1924),   pp.    191  fF. 


62  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

may  produce  the  feelings,  gestures,  and  the  physiological  changes 
which  accompany  great  triumph  and  exalted  joy. 

A  soldier  genuinely  imbued  with  a  belief  in  the  honor  and 
correctness  of  his  nation's  cause  and  of  the  evil  character  of  the 
enemy  may  experience  hysteric  joy  or  elation  in  "killing";  whereas 
two  years  before  the  "same  man"  as  a  clerk  may  have  been  revolted 
at  even  the  thought  of  "killing."  There  are  all  types  of  killing. 
"You  men  are  learning  ranger  fighting,"  said  the  lieutenant,  accord- 
ing to  a  New  York  Times  report.-**  "There  are  no  rules  of  clean 
fighting  that  apply  here.  The  dirtier  you  are  the  better  we  like 
it.  A  stab  in  the  back  is  one  of  the  finest  principles  we  know  of. 
Every  time  you  think  of  a  Jap,  say  to  yourself,  'We  must  be  more 
silent,  cruel,  and  vicious  than  these  little  sons  of  b— ' "  A  general 
".  .  .  watching  with  approval  whispered:  'And  that  lieutenant  used 
to  be  a  clerk  in  Wall  Street.' "  The  military  training  of  the  clerk  for 
the  situation  of  killing  in  war  has  given  the  thought  and  the  act 
a  difi^erent  meaning  to  him.  His  immediate  associates,  and  the 
patriots  of  his  nation,  have  placed  an  honorable  premium  upon 
efficient  killing. 

Only  rarely  ia  history,  have  spontaneous  individual  emotions  and 
their  expression  been  socially  approved.  When  this  does  occur  it 
is  likely  to  be  during  great  Social'  trans^f©r«iations,  such  as  the 
waning  of  the  Middle  Ages,  the  revolutionary  turns  of  Italian  city 
republics  during  the  Renaissance,  the  upthrusts  of  the  middle 
classes  in -Holland  or  in  Cromwellian  England,  the  peasant  wars 
of  central  Europe  during  Luther's  time,  the  American  Revolu- 
tion, and  the  French  revolutionary  and  Napoleonic  epochs.  In 
such  periods,  the  barriers  of  convention  and  status  do  not  stand  in 
the  way  of  enthusiastic  solidarity,  but  are  broken  down  by  the 
emancipated  who  spontaneously  join  with  one  another  in  the  name 
of  friendship  or  patriotism.  There  is  much  weeping,  both  spurious 
and  genuine,  and  when  such  solidarity  is  religiously  tinged,  there 
is  a  renewed  affirmation  of  the  brotherhood  of  man.  Thus  during 
the  1820's  mass  revivals  swept  through  the  Western  world,  young 
lovers  learned  to  trust  their  own  hearts,  and  love  became  the 
prerequisite  to  marriage. 

Such  periods,  however,  soon  give  way  to  the  re-establishment 
of  convention,  often  to  the  point  of  rigid  etiquette  as  we  know  it 

~"  June   16,   1943. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  6,3 

from  Victorianism  or  the  court  societies  of  the  anciens  regimes  of 
prerevolutionary  France  and  Tsarist  Russia.  Then  elegant  pro- 
prieties, rigidly  prescribed  forms  of  etiquette  with  "perfectionist" 
habituation  of  gesture  and  their  ritual  elaborations  of  spurious  senti- 
ments bespoke  the  underlying  anxiety— in  Western  societies  no 
less  than  in  Confucian  China. 

The  roles  men  play  affect  their  physiology;  the  meanings  of  situa- 
tions may  be  pointed  up  by  ritual  and  ceremony.  Football  games  in 
the  United  States  are  preceded  by  rituals  which  focus  the  players' 
and  their  followers'  emotions  on  the  game.  Incentives  of  acclaim 
and  censure  are  vividly  presented  to  the  players.  An  eminent  Har- 
vard physiologist  has  reported  that  such  social  keying-up  of  the 
players  may  result  in  their  feeling  such  an  "excess  of  strength"  as 
to  be  able  to  crouch  and  then  go  breaking  down  a  closed  door. 
The  physiologist  is  interested  in  discovering  that  such  experiences 
increase  the  percentage  of  sugar  in  the  player's  urine;  the  social 
psychologist  is  attracted  by  the  feelings,  verbalizations,  and  conse- 
quences of  such  social  interaction. 

Many  mass  audience  situations,  with  their  "vicarious"  enjoy- 
ments, serve  psychologically  the  unintended  function  of  channeling 
and  releasing  otherwise  unplacable  emotions.  Thus,  great  volumes 
of  aggression  are  "cathartically"  released  by  crowds  of  spectators 
cheering  their  favorite  stars  of  sport— and  jeering  the  umpire.  And 
in  tear-jerking  motion  pictures,  in  the  dark,  the  release  of  other- 
wise unwept  tears  is  facilitated. 

Eccentrist  dances  may  have  the  same  efiFects  as  football  rallies  and 
motion  pictures.  Religious  manias  and  the  jumpings  and  jerkings  of 
the  old  Methodists  may  be  more  violent  than  "hysterical  or  epileptic 
fits."  And  dervishes  can  sometimes  dance  for  days.  In  many  displays 
of  astonishing  bodily  strength,  it  has  been  noted  that  "crowds  of 
witnesses"  facilitate  the  exertion  "beyond  consideration  of  personal 
prudence."  Music,  especially  martial  band  music  and  choral  sing- 
ing, may  stimulate  the  physiology  of  emotion  and  bodily  strength.-" 
The  meanings  which  the  person  incorporates  from  his  expected 
roles  are  thus  linked  to  his  gestures,  produce  changes  in  his  body, 
and  influence  the  feelings  of  which  he  is  aware. 

-''  Cf.  Cannon,  op.  cit.,  p.  233. 


64  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

4.  Impression  and  Perception 

The  senses  are  those  speciaHzed  parts  or  areas  of  the  organism 
that  are  particularly  sensitive  to  changes  in  the  environment.  The 
human  organism,  equipped  with  special  kinds  of  sense  organs, 
along  with  the  intensity,  duration,  size,  and  movement  of  various 
stimuli,  makes  up  the  physical  and  organic  conditions  of  perception. 

We  cannot  see  out  of  the  back  of  our  heads,  although  if  we  hear 
a  very  slight  sound  and  whirl  swiftly  we  may  imagine  we  can. 
The  body,  insofar  as  it  puts  our  senses  in  a  position  to  record  stimuli 
(the  cocked  ear,  the  peering  eye)  is  involved  in  the  act  of  atten- 
tion. We  bend  down  to  smell  a  rose;  we  turn  our  heads  in  order 
to  see  to  the  side.  These  bodily  postures  put  our  sense  organs  into 
"contact"  with  the  sights,  sounds,  and  smells  to  which  our  sense 
organs  are  sensitive. 

The  pupil  of  the  eye  expands  or  contracts  according  to  the 
amount  of  light  reaching  it;  the  eardrum  vibrates  with  condensa- 
tions and  rarefactions  of  the  air,  and  transmits  these  vibrations, 
tones,  and  noises,  via  three  small  bones,  to  the  inner  ear  where 
different  little  hair  cells  are  stimulated  by  high  and  low  frequencies. 
The  skin  with  which  the  organism  is  covered  may  be  considered 
an  organ  of  touch,  but  scattered  through  it  are  spots  more  sensitive 
than  others  to  tactile  pressure,  pain,  cold,  or  heat.  When  we  move 
our  arms,  legs,  or  trunk,  we  are  aware  of  these  movements  and  of 
their  extent,  speed,  and  direction.  The  tastes  of  various  substances 
in  our  mouths  are  received  by  virtue  of  our  sensitive  tongues.  Smells 
come  to  us  through  our  noses  to  stimulate  olfactory  areas.  And  by 
means  of  the  nervous  system  these  various  perceptions  are  con- 
nected with  the  mechanisms  of  response  and  action,  the  muscles 
of  which  are  hung  and  stretched  over  our  skeleton. 

What  become  stimuli  to  us  are  limited  by  the  sensitivity  of  our 
sense  organs.  If  sound  waves  are  below  or  above  a  certain  number 
of  vibrations  per  minute,  they  do  not  stimulate  our  ears.  We  thus 
have  physiological  thresholds.  The  anatomy  and  physiology  of  the 
eye  and  ear  and  finger  are  part  of  the  structure  of  the  organism; 
how  these  organs  are  constructed  limits  and  selects  what  we  can 
see,  hear,  and  touch.  Thus,  the  eye  is  not  merely  a  photographic 
lens  which  mirrors  the  world  for  the  organism.  Out  of  the  total 
world  of  external  objects,  the  nature  of  the  eye  cuts  those  which 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  6^ 

are  visible  to  a  particular  organism.  If  the  retina  is  not  appropriately 
equipped  for  the  job,  colors  cannot  be  distinguished.  What  is  per- 
ceived is  limited  by  the  object  itself  and  by  the  structure  of  the 
organism  doing  the  perceiving. 

The  sudden  and  intense  nature  of  some  changes  in  the  physical 
environment  may  completely  dominate  the  organism  so  that  the 
reaction  is  quite  uncontrolled  by  the  person.  A  noise  of  this  sort, 
like  a  gunshot,  will  in  most  cases  produce  a  definite  pattern  of 
startle.-**  Yet  professional  hunters  or  men  very  long  in  battle  may 
have  gained  some  control  over  such  stimuli  and  over  their  organ- 
isms: they  won't  startle  so  easily.  Within  the  limits  of  the  organism, 
our  sense  organs  may  become  habituated  to  paying  attention  to 
certain  stimuli  and  to  overlooking  others.  The  crashing  noises,  fast- 
moving  sights,  and  "queer"  odors  of  a  metropolitan  area  are  differ- 
ent to  men  brought  up  there  than  to  someone  just  arrived  from 
the  country.  The  soldier  dozing  off  under  ceaseless  cannon  fire, 
may  be  instantly  alert  to  the  faint  signal  of  his  field  telephone; 
the  young  mother  wakes  from  deep  slumber  at  her  baby's  slightest 
whimper.  What  we  are  trained  to  pay  attention  to  is  related  to  our 
patterns  of  conduct  and  to  the  furthering  of  our  purposes.  Through 
repeated  use  of  certain  sense  organs  in  connection  with  certain 
activities,  the  different  organs  and  the  different  impressions  derived 
from  them  become  linked  together  or  fused  into  a  unit  of  social 
activity  and  perception. 

The  sense  of  smell,  for  example,  must  be  understood  in  varying 
social  contexts.  There  are,  for  instance,  two  ways  of  handling  body 
scent.  Conventions  may  encourage  the  covering  up  of  body  odor 
by  artificially  produced  scents.  This  has  been  the  historic  way  in 
Latin  countries,  notably  France  and  Italy.  Ladies  may  then  choose 
a  personalized  perfume  so  as  to  have,  as  Georg  Simmel  has  noted, 
a  subjectively  characteristic  "scent"  in  ballrooms  and  in  opera 
foyers.  Or,  in  the  second  place,  washing  with  soap  may  be  the 
conventional  way.  Since  the  eighteenth  century  in  Great  Britain 
frequent  use  of  the  bathtub  has  been  standard  for  certain  classes 
in  Anglo-Saxon  and  British-influenced  societies. 

Our  sense  organs  are  specialized,  but  they  are  also  closely  re- 
lated to  one  another.  Our  taste  and  our  smell  of  a  peach,  for  ex- 

28  See  C.  Landis  and  W.  Hunt,  The  Startle  Pattern  (New  York:  Farrar  & 
Rinehart,   1939). 


66  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

ample,  form  a  close  blend  of  perceptions;  the  odors  we  inhale 
stimulate  the  olfactory  regions,  but  they  also  stimulate  the  gustatory 
areas  in  back  of  our  mouths.  Other  evidence  of  the  interrelations  of 
our  senses  is  shown  when,  one  sense  organ  being  defective,  the 
others,  being  used  more,  seem  more  keen.  If  a  person  is  blind  and 
deaf,  the  sense  of  smell  may  become  more  discriminating  and 
hence  more  useful  in  the  orientation  of  the  individual.  Such  a  per- 
son may  learn,  as  Laura  Bridgram  did,  to  select  by  smell  her  own 
clothing  from  the  clothing  of  a  hundred  other  persons,  or  to 
detect  the  differences  between  the  recently  washed  socks  of  boys 
and  of  girls. -^ 

In  normal  adults,  "intersensory  resemblances,"  as  Charles  Harts- 
home  has  shown, ^°  seem  more  typical  than  do  isolated  impressions 
from  any  one  sense  organ.  We  have  already  noted  that  the  taste 
and  the  smell  of  a  fresh  peach  may  be  closely  blended.  But  that 
experience  was  organically  based;  the  matter  goes  further.  Our 
vocabularies  themselves  reveal  two  explanations  of  intersensory 
resemblances: 

I.  When  we  speak  of  "high"  or  "low"  pitched  sounds,  or  of  the 
soaring,  thin  notes  of  the  flute,  we  are  translating  perceptions  of 
sound  into  vocabularies  of  anatomical  and  tactual  experiences. 
When  we  speak  of  the  "brightness"  of  high-pitched  sounds,  we 
refer  to  an  intersensory  analogy  of  the  eye  and  the  ear.  When  we 
speak  of  the  "loudness"  of  certain  colors  or  color  combinations  we 
are  transferring  the  negative  prestige  value  of  talking  in  a  loud 
voice  in  a  "refined"  atmosphere  to  visual  perceptions  that  are  "un- 
refined" or  in  "bad  taste."  By  calling  it  "loud"  one  means  that  it  is 
inappropriate.  "Bad  taste,"  used  in  this  context,  is  itself  an  inter- 
sensory analogy  of  vision  and  taste.  The  eye  and  the  tongue,  vision 
and  taste,  are  related  when  we  speak  of  the  darkness  of  bitter  or 
of  the  brightness  of  salty.  The  tactual  sense  is  related  to  the  audi- 
tory in  "the  softness"  or  the  "smoothness"  of  music.  Poets  and 
novelists  are  expert  at  describing  colors  and  smells  in  terms  of 
sounds,  and  sounds  in  terms  of  color,  odor,  or  touch.  But  the  matter 

2"  See  M.  S.  Lamson,  T/ie  Life  and  Education  of  Laura  Dewey  Bridgram 
(New  York:   Houghton  Mifflin,   1881). 

30  See  his  The  Phihsop]iy  and  Psychology  of  Sensation  (Chicago:  Univ.  of 
Chicago  Press,  1934),  pp.  54  and  74.  Our  account  is  influenced  by  this 
excellent  monograph,  although  it  should  be  noted  diat  the  position  taken 
does   not  at  all  points  coincide  with  his. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  6j 

is  not  reserved  to  them.  Anyone  can  look  at  something,  and  with- 
out smelling  it  say,  "It  stinks." 

II.  But  there  is  another  view  of  such  intersensory  resemblances. 
Some  psychologists  hold  that  when  we  experience  sweet  music  or 
sugary  words,  a  sweet  girl  or  a  sour  face,  we  are  experiencing 
synesthetically  the  qualities  of  sweetness  and  sourness  in  manifold 
contexts.  Thus,  when  we  speak  of  a  "cutting"  remark,  we  do  not, 
according  to  this  view,  transfer  inferentially  or  by  analogy  the 
quality  of  cutting  or  sharpness  from  a  knife  to  another  context; 
nor  do  we  transfer  by  analogy  from  taste  to  ear  when  speaking 
of  a  "bitter"  tone  or  inflection  of  voice.  Rather,  the  qualities  of 
sharpness  or  of  bitterness  are  directly  available  to  us  in  diverse 
fields  of  experience.  High  life  and  "high-mindedness,"  "low  think- 
ing" and  "base"  feelings  are  in  their  contexts  perceived  qualities, 
just  as  is  the  "high"  soprano  voice  or  the  "low"  basso. 

For  the  purposes  of  the  social  psychologist,  it  does  not  seem 
urgent  that  we  commit  ourselves  to  either  of  these  views.  Both, 
especially  the  second,  have  been  elaborated  on  in  a  rich  series  of 
monographic  work  in  technical  psychology  ^^  and  none  of  the 
inferences  or  constructions  we  wish  to  make  rest  upon  explanations 
which  go  beyond  these  alternatives. 

At  any  rate,  the  movement  of  the  human  organism  differs  from 
the  physical  movements  of  bodies  in  time  and  space.  For,  due  to 
our  body  build,  the  forward  position  of  our  eyes  and  of  our  gait, 
as  well  as  our  upright  postme,  we  experience  our  spatial  world  in 
terms  of  forward  and  backward,  of  high  and  low,  of  left  and 
right.  These  dimensions  have  qualitative  properties  which  differ 
from  the  purely  quantitative  dimensions  of  the  physico-mathemat- 
ical  space.^- 

31  \\p  refer  to  the  work  of  Wertheimer,  Kohler,  KofFka,  and  Lewin.  See 
W.  D.  Ellis,  Source  Book  in  Gestalt  Psychology  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace, 
1938). 

3-  Cf.  Jerome  S.  Bruner  and  Cecile  C.  Goodman,  "Value  and  Need  as 
Organizing  Factors  in  Perception,"  in  Readings  in  Social  Psychology,  Newcomb, 
Hartley,  et  ah,  eds.  (New  York:  Holt,  1947),  pp.  99-108;  M.  Sherif,  "A 
Study  of  Some  Social  Factors  in  Perception,"  Arch.  Psychol.,  No.  187,  1935; 
J.  Piaget,  Language  and  Thought  of  the  Child  (London:  Routledge,  1948); 
L.  Postman  and  J.  S.  Bruner,  "The  Reliability  of  Constant  Errors  in  Psycho- 
physical Measurement,"  Journal  of  Psychology,  1946,  XXI,  pp.  293-299;  A.  I. 
Hallowell,  "Cultural  Factors  in  the  Structuralization  of  Perception,"  in  Social 
Psychology  at  the  Crossroads,  John  H.  Rohrer  and  Muzafer  Sherif,  eds.  (New 
York:  Harper,  1951),  pp.  164-95;  and  Robert  R.  Blake  and  Glen  V.  Ramsey, 
Perception:  An  Approach  to  Personality  (New  York:  Ronald  Press,  1951). 


68  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

Each  of  our  sense  organs  contributes  in  its  own  way  to  our 
articulation  of  our  own  organism  in  space  and  time.  As  we  know 
from  studies  of  the  bHnd  and  the  deaf,  the  experience  of  space  that 
is  mediated  through  our  eyes  differs  from  that  mediated  exclusively 
through  our  ears.  "The  normal"  way  of  locating  our  organisms  in 
space  and  time  is  a  complex  integrative  process  of  diverse  sense 
experiences.  Blind  persons  who  learn  to  see  have  to  reconstruct  the 
experience  of  their  own  bodies,  because  the  visual  experience  added 
to  their  previous  tactile  and  acoustic  orientations  demands  a  new 
and  more  complex  integration  of  perceptions.  Similarly,  unless  we 
deliberately  control  our  selves,  we  will  not  "naturally"  walk  in  a 
straight  but  rather  in  a  slightly  curved  line;  our  "rhythmic"  experi- 
ences and  activities  (our  gait,  for  example)  will  have  more  to  do 
with  the  nonmetric  regularities  of  the  heartbeat  and  the  blood 
pulsation,  than  with  the  chronometric  exactitude  of  the  pendulum 
stroke.  The  rhythm  of  language  and  of  music  is  not  identical  with 
the  metronomic  "beat." 

5.  The  Interrelations  of  the  Psychic  Structure 

To  understand  how  impressions  are  organized  into  perceptions 
we  have  to  understand  the  interrelations  of  all  elements  of  the 
psychic  structure,  for  perception  and  feeling  and  impulse  may  be 
so  closely  linked  that  in  the  active  experiences  of  each  of  them 
there  is  an  element  of  the  others. 

By  an  act  of  attention,  we  connect  our  perceptions  with  our 
impulses.  What  we  see  is  connected  with  what  we  want  to  see, 
and  we  tend  to  overlook  what  we  dislike  to  see,  or  what  is  irrelevant 
for  us.  If  we  are  beset  by  an  impulsive  need,  we  often  dream 
the  image  of  the  object  required  for  its  fulfillment.  We  may  see  it 
in  everything,  as  a  man  dying  of  thirst  sees  water  everywhere  ini 
the  desert.  "All  things  look  yellow  to  the  jaundiced  eye."  Suchi 
mirages  or  hallucinations  induced  by  our  bodily  deprivations  are 
a  subtle  part  of  our  waking  lives.  In  a  child  the  impulse  of  the 
moment  will  determine  his  action,  his  feeling,  and  even  his  per- 
ception of  various  objects.  With  a  sudden  change  of  impulse  and  I 
feeling  he  will  react  quite  differently  to  the  same  objects.  His 
focus  of  perception  will  shift  and  race  about  as  his  impulse  activities 
change.  Feeling  tone  will  lead  us  to  see  or  hear  the  "brighter"  or 
the  "-darker"  side  of  things.  The  unpremeditated  emotional  effects 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  6q 

that  are  socially  trained  into  a  person  will  determine  his  gestures 
and  other  conduct  when  he  perceives  a  combination  ot  colors  in  a 
flag  or  hears  a  national  anthem. 

Perceptions  often  have  affective  significance.  The  feeling  tones 
of  colors,  sounds,  and  odors  are  imputed  to  them  by  virtue  of  the 
feelings  which  we  typically  have  when  we  perceive  them."*^  Thus 
we  speak  of  the  gaiety  of  yellow,  the  aggressiveness  of  red,  the 
coolness  of  green,  the  distance  of  blue— or  blue  moods,  hot  scarlet, 
warm  orange,  and  the  melancholy  of  deep  purple. 

In  live  experiences  not  only  visions  but  sounds  seem  to  embody 
feeling  tones:  "There  is  the  stillness  of  a  city  street  at  three  a.m., 
the  stillness  of  a  Sunday,  the  startling  quietness  of  the  country 
after  alighting  from  a  train,  or  the  muffling  of  sounds  with  a  fall 
of  snow.  In  each  of  these  the  stimulus  is  the  same,  a  contrast,  a 
lack  of  noise."  ^"^  Yet  each  of  these  lack-of-sounds  feels  differently: 
we  have  linked  different  feelings  and  activities  to  each  of  them, 
and  our  psychic  structure  responds  in  a  unity  with  the  perceptions. 

The  interrelations  of  feelings,  impulses,  and  impressions  in  the 
psychic  structure  form  dynamic  trends.  The  linkages  of  feelings 
with  perceptions  are  parts  of  trends  which  involve  expressive  and 
purposive  action  within  social  relations.  Impressions  received  from 
the  various  senses  are  fused  with  other  features  of  the  psychic 
structure— and  they  are  linked  with  the  social  purposes  of  the  per- 
son. 

Just  as  our  bodily  postiu'es  are  trained  so  that  we  can  better  see, 
hear,  or  smell  different  things,  so  are  our  senses  trained  by  social 
directives  and  personal  expectations.  Since  perception  is  linked  to 
the  values  and  norms  incorporated  by  the  person,  the  commands 
which  literally  direct  a  person's  focus  of  attention  tell  him  what 
to  look  for  in  a  given  field  of  perception.  He  will  single  this  out 
and  organize  the  field  around  it;  the  social  trainings  of  his  pur- 
poses and  interests  sensitize  his  view  of  the  world.  A  carpenter  per- 
ceives a  different  house  than  does  its  prospective  owner;  he  looks 

33  On  the  affective  significance  of  perceptions,  see  Charles  Hartshome,  op. 
cit.,  where  he  discusses  these  experiences  under  the  term  "affective  continuum." 
The  primary  connection  of  sensing  and  feeling  was  suggested  by  C.  S.  Pierce 
who  pointed  out  that  both  may  in\'oh'e  relatixely  simple  unit  qualities;  pur- 
pose, in  contrast,  is  dual:  we  strive  against  something.  See  C.  S.  Pierce,  Col- 
lected Papers,  Vol.  I,  Book  3. 

3^  J.  T.  MacCurdy,  The  Psychology  of  Emotion  (New  York:  Harcourt, 
Brace,   1925),  p.  52. 


JO  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

for  those  features  of  the  house  which  will  guide  his  construction 
work,  while  the  owner  sees  an  image  of  his  finished  house  born 
of  liis  desires  and  expectations. 

What  we  see  and  hear  and  smell  today,  determined  in  small  or 
larger  part  as  it  l§~by  our  social  context  and  personal  expectations, 
helps  determine  what  we  see  and  hear  and  smell  in  the  future. 
The  world  we  experience  is  in  no  small  degree  determined  by  our 
past  experiences  and  future  expectations,  which  form  a  "frame  of 
reference"  or  "apperceptive  mass,"  as  it  has  been  called.^^  Because 
of  this,  man  cannot  be  said  to  receive  passively  the  world  of  sensa- 
tions; he  is  an  active  determiner  of  what  he  perceives  and  experi- 
ences. For  not  only  his  sense  organs  but  his  apperceptive  mass,  with 
its  social  organization  of  feelings  and  impulses,  is  part  of  his  per- 
ception. In  this  sense,  man  as  a  person  constructs  the  world  that 
he  perceives,   and  this  construction   is   a  social   act. 

Although  they  all  have  the  same  kind  of  sense  organs  biologi- 
cally, people  in  different  societies  perceive  things  differently.  Those 
who  live  on  great  plains  develop  visual  capacities  which  inhabitants 
of  Paris  may  not  possess.  Writes  de  Poncins:  "I  strained  and, 
strained  and  saw  nothing  until  one  of  the  Eskimos  pointed  with  his 
whip  and  rather  against  my  will  I  agreed  that  I  saw  what  he  saw'. 
Soon  what  he  saw  became  for  me  something  as  big  as  a  pin-head; 
in  a  quarter  hour  the  pin-heads  were  fly-specks;  and  in  the  end  I 
could  see  that  the  fly-specks  were  in  truth  a  camp."  '^^ 

Expertness  at  fulfilling  some  role  often  involves  psychic  training; 
it  involves  learning  what  to  look  for  as  well  as  the  meaning  of 
what  is  seen.  To  one  unaccustomed  to  an  Eskimo  trail,  it  seems 
that  "nothing  happens,"  yet  for  those  who  have  long  been  on  the 
trail,  there  is  always  work  to  be  done.  Every  perception  suggests 
something  to  do:  "Watch  the  dog!  She  is  getting  ready  to  squat 
and  stop,  and  if  she  does,  give  her  the  whip  as  the  sled  passes  her 
(for  her  lead  is  long  enough  to  allow  the  passage  of  the  sled). 
Mind  that  stone!  If  the  runner  strikes  it,  the  coating  of  ice  may 
break  .  .  ."  ^'^ 

Moral  and  social  taboos,  as  well  as  interests  and  skills,  patterni 

^^  Grace  De  Laguna,  Speech:  Its  Function  and  Development  (New  Haven: 
Yale  Univ.  Press,   1927). 

•*^  Gontran  de  Poncins  and  Levi'is  Galantiere,  Kahloona  (New  York:  Reynali 
and  Hitchcock,  1941),  pp.  297-98. 

^■' Ibid.,  p.  55. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  /I 

our  perceptions.  If  the  members  of  a  group  believe  that  children 
should  not  resemble  certain  relatives,  it  is  unlikely  that  within 
the  group  any  such  resemblances  will  ever  be  remarked.  The 
Trobriander,  Malinowski  has  indicated,  will  not  see  resemblances 
between  female  parent  and  children,  nor  between  two  brothers. 
These  resemblances  are  taboo  and  it  is  an  insult  to  say  that  .they 
exist."''  These  social  norms  may,  in  time,  be  internalized  and 
actually  block  out  the  perception  of  resemblances.  Proud  mothers 
in  American  society  will  "see  resemblances "  between  their  offspring 
and  themselves  where  the  uninterested  onlooker  will  merely  see 
another  infant.  What- we  expect  to  sec  and  what  we  should  not 
see  are  selected  and  patterned  1)\  the  yarioits  social  norms  that 
we  liave  intt'niali/x'd. 

Of  all  our  social  acquisitions,  perhaps  our  vocabulary  is  most  di- 
rectly geared  to  our  perceptions.  Our  perception  is  organized  in 
terms  of  symbols,  and  our  vocabularies  influence  the  perceptions 
to  which  we  are  sensitive.  The  classifications  we  learn  for  colors, 
for  example,  enable  us  to  distinguish  between  them,  to  pick  out 
red  from  pink,  lavender  from  gray.  The  Eskimo  has  so  elaborated 
distinctions  in  his  language  that  he  is  able  to  discriminate  between 
types  of  "snow"  which  to  the  English  or  the  Chinese  seem  to  be 
the  same.^**  Socially  equipped  with  a  color  classification  different 
from  that  of  the  West,  natives  of  New  Guinea,  Margaret  Mead 
asserts,  "see  yellow,  olive-green,  blue-green,  grey,  and  lavender 
as  variations  of  one  color."  ^°  And  a  metropolitan  woman,  intensely 
interested  in  clothing  fashions,  can  detect  that  slight  difference  in 
shade  of  blue  which  marks  the  difference  between  last  season's  and 
this  season's  style. 

"In  acquiring  the  vocabulary  of  his  day,"  Grace  De  Laguna  has 
written,  "each  adolescent  youth  is  being  fitted  with  a  set  of  vari- 
ously colored  spectacles  through  which  he  is  to  look  at  the  world 
about  him,  and  with  whose  tints  it  must  inevitably  be  colored  .  .  . 
The  lenses  we  acquire  with  language  are  not  merely  colored,  but 

38  Bronislaw  Malinowski,  The  Father  in  Primitive  Psychohgy  (New  York: 
Norton,  1927),  pp.  87  fF.;  and  Sex  and  Repression  in  Savage  Society  (New 
York:    Harcourt,   Brace,    1927). 

•^3  See  Franz  Boas,  The  Mind  of  Primitive  Man  (New  York:  Macmillan, 
1927),  p.  119  ff. 

^"  "The  Primitive  Child,"  Handbook  of  Child  Psychology,  Carl  Murchison, 
ed.   (2d  ed.,  rev.;  Worcester:   Clark  Univ.  Press,   1933),  p.  638. 


J  2  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

blocked  out  in  more  or  less  regular  designs,  so  that  the  world  we 
see  through  them  is  patternized  to  our  earliest  view."  ^^ 

6.  The  Social  Unity  of  the  Psychic  Structure 

We  have  not  been  able  to  confine  our  analysis  of  emotion,  pur- 
pose, and  perception  to  the  organism  and  the  psychic  structure. 
We  ha\e  had  also  to  examine  the  person  and  the  roles  and 
vocabularies  he  has  acquired,  and  accordingly,  we  have  had  to 
discuss  many  relations  between  the  different  features  of  the  char- 
acter structure.*" 

At  this  point  it  is  convenient  to  examine  the  psychic  structure 
as  a  whole  with  a  minimum  of  attention  to  the  person.  Points  of 
view  from  which  we  may  hope  to  observe  the  operations  of  the 
psychic  structure  in  a  relatively  autonomous  condition  include: 
I.  the  child;  II.  severe  organic  deprivation;  III.  social  crises,  when 

"  Op.  cit.,  pp.  287,  288-89. 

■*-  We  are  able  now  to  make  more  precise  a  rather  \ague  term— tempera- 
ment—often  used  to  refer  to  individuals.  We  speak  of  phlegmatic,  melancholic, 
sanguine,  or  choleric  temperaments.  Such  characterizations  seem  to  in\olve 
two  general  facts  about  "the  psychic  structure":  (a)  the  degree  and  manner 
in  which  it  is  socialized,  and  (b)  the  constitutional  strength  of  the  organism 
in  so  far  as  this  affects  the  level,  speed,  and  persistence  of  psychic  reaction. 
The  common  denominator  of  all  types  of  temperament  and  of  temperamental 
actions  seems  to  be  the  level  of  psychic  reactivity.  If  it  is  generally  high, 
emotional  and  impulsive  reactions  are  quick  and  spontaneous.  To  slower  paced 
individuals,  the  degree  of  emotionality  experienced  and  expressed  seems  to 
be  disproportionate  to  the  occasion.  In  contrast  to  elation,  when  he  is  de- 
pressed, the  individual  loses  this  capacity  for  spontaneous  feeling  and  impulse. 
The  level,  speed,  and  persistence  of  psychic  reactivity,  in  relation  to  standard- 
ized situations,  is  the  basis  upon  which  we  gauge  and  characterize  types  of 
temperament.  Although  these  degrees  of  reactivity  are  limited  in  their  speed, 
and  certainly  in  their  persistence,  by  the  constitutional  strength  of  the  organ- 
ism, they  are  also  set  by  the  degree  to  which  and  the  manner  in  which  the 
psychic  structure  is  socialized.  For  it  is  only  in  terms  of  socially  expected 
reactions  to  given  situations  that  we  can  gauge  temperament.  Thus,  if  an 
emotional  reaction  to  a  given  situation  is  disproportionate  to  the  occasion's 
conventionally  expected  reaction,  we  speak  of  excitable  or  of  flighty  tempera- 
ments. If  emotion  or  feeling  is  less  intense  than  is  expected,  we  speak  of  mild 
or  of  phlegmatic  temperaments.  Thus,  although  temperament  involves  the 
constitution  of  the  organism,  it  is  by  no  means  an  innate  or  wholly  organic 
feature  of  the  character  structure.  It  is  closely  related  to  both  organism  and 
person. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  y;^ 

instituted  routines  collapse;  and  IV.  certain  unsocialized  aspects  of 
particular  individuals. 

I.  The  psychic  structure  of  the  prelingual  child  has  not  yet  been 
integrated  with  the  person.  And  since  its  elements  are  not  firmly 
integrated  with  one  another,  it  is  highly  plastic.  The  unification  of 
these  elements  is  not  a  ready-made  affair,  but  involves  a  long  proc- 
ess; both  the  unification  and  the  socialization  of  the  psychic  struc- 
ture are  major  processes  of  human  maturation.^  ■ 

The  psychic  structure  of  the  infant  is  more  quickly  translatable 
into  activity  than  that  of  the  normal  adult.  The  infant  has  more 
immediate  impulses  which  may  be  more  immediately  satisfied.  If 
he  is  drowsy  and  you  wake  him  up,  he  may  begin  to  scjuall;  but 
if  you  adjust  his  thumb  back  in  his  mouth  he  may  quickly  go  to 
sleep  again.  His  impulses  have  a  limited  range  of  objects  and  these 
objects  easily  satisfy.  The  pushes  of  impulse  result  in  random 
moxements  and  convulsive  grasping  at  anything  placed  before  him; 
if  impulse  and  satisfaction  are  not  tightly  and  quickly  joined,  he 
is  upset.  There  is  little  or  no  poise  in  the  gratification  of  his  im- 
pulses, for  they  are  not  yet  purposive. 

Plis  perceptions  are  not  focused  clearly  upon  definite  objects,  so 
he  is  easily  distracted.  The  slightest  sound  may  engage  his  attention 
in  another  direction.  Since  definite  perceptions  are  not  linked  to 
impulses,  his  activities  are  not  only  random  but  they  do  not  carry 
through.  Stray  impressions  of  sound  or  sight  easily  entice  him,  and 
his  impressions  of  one  thing  are  not  linked  to  his  impressions  of 
another;  impressions  are  not  patterned  into  meaningful  perceptions. 
He  cannot  see  what  is  coming  up.  Perceptions  of  taste,  for  in- 
stance, may  dominate  the  entire  animal  infant.  A  stick  of  candy 
will  be  slobbered  over  and  bitten  at  with  eager  impulsive  motions 
and  gestures.  When  you  take  it  from  him,  he  will  squall,  with 
his  mouth  open  and  drooling,  eager  to  engulf  it  again  in  an  infant 
frenzy. 

The  reactivity  of  the  infant's  psychic  structure  is  high,  random, 
and  very  responsive.  Since  its  various  elements  are  not  integrated 
into  unities,  its  feelings,  impressions,  and  impulses  are  not  linked 
firmly   with   one   another.    It   is,   in   short,    not   yet   internally   co- 

*3  See  Chapter  VI:  Biography  and  Types  of  Childhood,  Section  2:  The 
Psychic   Structure. 


74  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

ordinated,  nor  linked  with  activities,  and  much  less  with  the  per- 
son. 

Bodily  discomfort  is  not  yet  a  sign  for  the  motor  apparatus  to 
move  into  another  position.  All  the  baby  can  do  is  cry  and  maybe 
wriggle  at  random  a  little.  That  is  what  we  mean  when  we  say  he 
is  "so  helpless." 

The  unification  of  impulse,  feeling,  and  impression  into  a  psychic 
structure  occurs  before  the  child  has  acquired  language,  by  means 
of  the  interrelations  of  the  various  senses.  An  infant,  or  an  adult 
for  that  matter,  cannot  visually  perceive  all  the  parts  of  his  body. 
Usually  he  cannot  hear  his  own  heartbeat  nor,  without  mirrors, 
see  the  middle  of  his  back.  Nor  can  he  hear  the  beat  of  his  own 
pulse.  But  what  is  not  available  through  one  sense  organ  may  be 
experienced  through  another:  not  being  able  to  see  his  rearward 
portions  the  individual  can  touch  them  with  his  hands  and  thus 
finding  them  to  be  round  can  see  the  image.  Out  of  the  feeling- 
awareness  an  image  of  the  body  develops. 

Of  many  feelings  and  parts  of  his  body  the  individual  has  access 
in  two  or  more  ways:  he  can  feel  his  toe  wiggle  and  he  can  see 
it  wiggle.  Just  as  he  learns  his  motor  capacity— what  he  can  do  with 
his  arms  and  legs  and  trunk,  through  feeling  them  in  action— so 
he  can  learn  by  vision,  by  seeing  distances  between  what  he  grasps 
for  and  what  he  actually  grasps.  By  the  consequences  of  various 
bodily  movements  upon  his  feelings,  he  learns  and  his  movements 
are  integrated.  The  sight  of  his  toes  wriggling  may  become  a  sign 
to  him  for  the  bodily  feeling  which  usually  accompanies  this  sight. 
Thus  a  network  of  intersensory  signs  is  set  up. 

The  feeling-states  which  are  consequences  of  various  action  also 
operate  as  signs.  Through  the  systems  of  such  signs  the  infant  in- 
dividual's psychic  structure  becomes  unified.  Impulses  are  linked 
with  positive  and  negative  feeling-states  in  the  early  history  of  the 
organism.  The  range  of  the  infant's  feeling-states,  which  follow 
from  acting  out  various  impulses,  is  probably  set  by  and  limited 
to  the  motor  experiments  which  he  has  made. 

Just  as  impulses  are  steered  and  limited  by  the  circle  of  the 
baby's  feeling-states,  so  is  the  horizon  of  his  perceptions.  Bright 
colors  may  feel  gay  to  the  baby,  dark  shades  feel  threatening.  The 
positive  and  negative  feeling-states  accompanying  acts  of  percep- 
tion are  circumscribed  by  the  ranges  of  the  stimuli,  especially  by 
the  thresholds  of  sense  perceptions  and  the  "saturation  points"  of 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  "/^ 

the  organism;  after  a  certain  point  what  was  "sweet"  becomes 
"gaga."  The  increased  sphere  of  a  child's  perception  is  steered  by 
the  hmitations  which  the  accompanying  feehngs  set  up. 

Gradually,  habituated  feelings  channel  impulses  and  impressions 
into  aversions  and  likings;  the  world  is  learned  and  divided  into 
things  for  which  to  grasp  and  things  from  which  to  draw  away.  If 
impression,  feeling,  impulse,  and  motor  behavior  are  linked  and 
habituated  into  a  positive  unit,  a  channel  of  action  is  set  up  and 
we  may  expect  a  willful  repetition  of  the  unit.  As  it  is  repeated, 
sometimes  over  and  over  again,  the  psychic  structure  of  the  baby 
is  being  set  into  a  "dynamic  trend."  Such  repetitions,  often  rhythmic 
in  the  child,  form  patterns  of  impulse,  impression,  and  feeling  as  a 
unit  and  as  a  part  of  a  locomotion:  they  are  often  experienced  as 
pleasure.  And  they  are,  in  fact,  the  beginnings  of  play;  for  play 
begins  when  the  baby  beats  his  hands  together  regularly,  or  when 
he  utters  rhythmic  noises. 

Learning  is  anchored  in  the  feelings  and  impressions  which  are 
both  prerequisites  and  consequences  of  actions.  We  learn  to  ex- 
perience our  self  as  an  organized  and  mobile  unit  in  opposition  to 
inviting  and  challenging  features  of  the  environment.  The  realities 
of  the  world  and  the  capacities  of  our  own  bodies  are  learned 
together;  both  come  to  us  in  terms  of  resistance  and  mastery,  limi- 
tation and  capacity.  We  get  an  image  of  what  can  be  done  with 
our  organic  equipment  by  learning  what  can't  be  done  and  some- 
times suffering  from  the  consequences  of  trying. 

II.  In  severe  organic  deprivation  the  impulse  that  is  deprived  of 
an  object  of  gratification  may  temporarily  dominate  and  shape  the 
entire  psychic  structure.  It  may  even  operate  autonomously,  casting 
off  the  social  inhibitions,  patterning,  and  pose  of  the  person.  Thus, 
feelings  of  hunger,  as  we  have  seen,  are  intrabody  signals  that  the 
stomach  is  contracted  for  ingestion.  When  we  eat,  gastric  juices 
begin  to  flow  and  the  feelings  disappear.  Eventually,  if  we  fail  to 
eat,  this  state  of  deprivation  may  dominate  not  only  our  bodily 
feelings  but  the  entire  field  of  our  external  perception.  We  will 
see  and  smell  food  everywhere  as  we  walk  about  the  city;  all 
people  may  begin  to  look  plump  to  us.  We  see  objects  that  would 
satisfy  the  deprived  impulse.  Eventually,  we  may  invent  sights  and 
sounds  and  smells;  in  sleeping,  if  we  can,  we  may  dream  of  suc- 
culent foods  or  even  scraps  of  edible  objects.  Our  experience,  in  all 


y6  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

its  phases,  night  and  day,  is  dominated  by  the  deprivation.  In 
many  ways,  we  are  Hke  the  child,  who  does  not  have  a  unified 
psychic  structure  under  the  control  of  the  person. 

The  norms  which  have  been  internalized  and  which  have  con- 
trolled the  psychic  impulses  and  regulated  their  operation  may 
no  longer  be  eflFective.  Our  pride,  our  sensitivities  to  what  others 
will  think,  are  drastically  minimized  or  eliminated;  we  may  simply 
go  "all  out"  to  satisfy  our  want.  We  will  snatch  food,  eat  garbage, 
go  on  the  dole.  The  one  deprived  element  of  the  psycliic  struc- 
ture controls  our  conduct. 

To  what  degree  the  person  may  lose  control  is  shown  by  various 
accounts  of  cannibalism  due  to  starvation.  In  California  in  the 
winter  of  1846-47  a  party  of  pioneers  were  trapped  and  isolated 
in  the  Sierra  mountains.  They  were  starving.  Cannibalism  oc- 
curred, even  between  members  of  the  same  family.  When  the  sur- 
vivors were  rescued,  one  man,  having  lost  the  social  prohibitions 
of  the  person,  was  so  dominated  by  the  bare  psychic  structure 
that  he  had  apparently  come  to  prefer  the  flesh  of  infants  to  that 
of  mules,  leaving  the  latter  until  he  had  consumed  his  supply  of 
the  former.** 

On  the  other  hand,  there  is  ample  evidence  that  concentration 
camp  survivors  facing  extreme  situations  of  mass  starvation  and 
death  may  regularly  share  what  is  to  be  had  and  "take  it"  together. 
They  have  been  known  to  develop  intense  group  solidarity  and 
friendship,  and  to  invent  new  codes  of  conduct  to  meet  the  chal- 
lenge of  traumatizing  events,  such  as  transportation  to  the  camp 
and  induction  into  its  routine.  Held  together  by  religious  faith  or 
political  conviction,  the  members  of  such  groups  jointly  resist  all 
attempts  to  strip  them  of  man's  natiire  as  a  "political  animal,"  and 
reduce  them  by  twentieth-century  techniques  to  Hobbesian  wolves. 
The  available  evidence  of  survivors  strongly  suggests  that  the 
chances  for  survival  in  the  extreme  situations  of  the  concentration 
camp  universe  were  greater  for  the  socially  attached  person  than 
the  competitive  lone  wolf. 

During  prolonged  sexual  deprivation,  a  domination  of  the  emo- 
tions, perceptions,  and  social  incorporations  of  the  person  may 

4*  For  documentation  on  the  Donner  party,  see  C.  F.  McGlashan,  History 
of  the  Donner  Party  (San  Francisco:  Bancroft,  1881)  (Stanford:  Stanford 
Univ.  Press,  1940),  especially  pp.  88,  106,  129,  211 ;  see  also  Quinn  Thronton, 
Oregon  and  California  in  1848  (New  York,  1848),  Vol.  II. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  // 

occur.  The  whole  environment  and  most  bodily  feehngs  become 
sexuahzed.  All  the  members  of  the  opposite  sex,  regardless  of  their 
condition,  look  attractive,  for  their  attractiveness  is  linked  with 
deprivation.  Conventional  ways  of  winning  the  erotical  partner 
may  give  way  to  bold  aggression  and  physical  coercion.  In  such 
deprived  states,  the  sexual  object  to  which  the  sexual  aim  is  socially 
directed  may  be  replaced  by  another,  which  may  be  a  member  of 
his  own  sex,  or  it  may  be  himself.  Every  touch  of  his  hand  upon 
his  own  body  may  excite  him  sexually.  In  the  prolonged  absence 
of  the  socialized  object  the  impulse  of  sex  thus  shifts  its  aim  and 
tries  to  achieve  another  target.  On  the  other  hand,  religiously  mo- 
tivated asceticism  may  condition  celibate  life  to  the  point  where 
sexual  stimuli,  objects,  and  impulses  shrink  and  wither  away. 

III.  In  crises  of  institutional  orders,  as  during  a  peasant  revolu- 
tion, when  suppressed  feelings  of  anger  and  aggressive  impulses 
toward  the  landlord  flame  into  cruel  action,  the  social  steering  and 
traditional  controls  of  the  person  may  become  ineffective,  indeed, 
quite  swept  away.  Peasants  seem  more  likely  to  revolt  when  the 
lord  is  not  present  in  person,  that  is,  under  conditions  of  absentee 
landlordism.  The  atmosphere  of  prestige  and  power  which  sur- 
rounds the  lord  is  probably  too  strong  an  anchor  of  dutiful  conduct 
for  the  repressed  anger  and  aggression  to  be  released  directly 
upon  him.  His  presence  enforces  the  social  roles  which  the  peasant 
must  enact;  but  in  his  absence,  inhibitions  collapse  and  repressions 
are  removed. 

During  the  enthusiastic  phase  of  mass  movements  there  may 
occur  a  mass  transformation  of  character  structures.  Hitherto  un- 
socialized  and  repressed  psychic  impulses  may  emerge  on  the  field 
of  social  conduct.  New  norms  are  incorporated  as  new  obligations, 
as  features  of  a  new  duty  and  conscience,  thus  forming  a  stabiliza- 
tion and  integration  of  character  in  terms  of  the  new  conduct  pat- 
terns. Changes  in  the  objective  social  structure  are  paralleled  by 
changes  in  what  psychic  elements  are  accentuated  in  the  character 
structures  of  man.*^ 

IV.  It  should  not  jje  supposed  that  all  the  elements  of  the  "nor- 
mal" adult's  psychic  structure  are  socialized  in  terms  of  approved 

•15  See  Chapter  XV:  Collecti\e  Beha\ior,  Section  2:  Aggregates,  Crowds  and 
Publics;  and  Section  4:   Rexolution  and  Counterrex  olution. 


j8  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

social  roles.  Various  impulses  and  feelings  which  have  been  set 
into  a  psychic  structure,  perhaps  before  the  emergence  of  the  per- 
son, may  not  have  become  institutionalized,  and  cannot  be  socially 
placed  in  the  roles  available  to  the  person.  The  steering  process 
provided  by  role  incorporations  and  social  conditioning  may  not 
take  care  of  all  that  there  is  in  man;  that  is,  the  person's  roles  may 
not  include  all  that  is  involved  in  his  psychic  structure.  Through 
its  specific  systems  of  premiums  and  taboos,  approbations  and  dis- 
approvals, the  social  context  may  rule  out  the  display  of  some  fea- 
tures of  the  psychic  structures  of  some  persons. 

Due  weight  must  be  given  to  that  in  man  which  institutions  do 
not  "place."  To  the  conservative  such  impulses  and  darker  emo- 
tions usually  appear  as  destructive  of  organized  social  conduct. 
But  they  may  also  be  viewed  as  the  conditions  of  new  beginnings 
in  social  organization  and  in  man  himself.  These  elements,  upon 
which  society  places  no  premium,  or  places  a  negative  premium, 
form  the  psychic  stuff  covered  by  the  term  "repression." 

Now  impulses,  when  they  are  socially  disapproved,  may  not 
have  become  linked  with  social  objects  and  roles.  The  emotion 
which  wells  up  within  us  and  for  which  we  have  no  vocabulary 
nor  outlet  in  conduct  may  form  an  extraconscious  or  an  uncon- 
scious part  of  our  character.*^  Nevertheless,  such  forces  may  influ- 
ence our  conduct.  Blocked  at  one  outlet,  psychic  elements  may  be 
directed  through  another;  hatred  and  aggression  toward  economic 
and  social  superiors  may  enter  into  a  man's  cruel  conduct  toward 
his  wife  and  children. 

An  easy  socialization  of  impulses  requires  that  their  outlet  be 
ordered  in  time  and  with  reference  to  certain  occasions.  Thus, 
among  their  institutions  most  societies  provide  special  occasions 
for  the  release  of  psychic  elements  not  otherwise  placed.  Mass 
sports  may  thus  be  seen  as  a  vicarious  discharge  of  latent  aggres- 
sion, as  well  as  a  feeder  of  it.  In  other  contexts,  such  aggression 
may  come  out  in  mass  political  rallies.  But  whether  in  sports  or  in 
politics,  the  expression  of  the  latent  aggression  is  socially  chan- 
neled. By  being  released  in  these  special  ways,  the  psychic  struc- 
ture, experiencing  catharsis,  is  relieved  of  otherwise  unplaced  im- 
pulses. The  deflection  of  such  mass  emotions  through  the  scape- 

^'^  For  problems  of  the  "unconscious,"  see  Chapter  V:  The  Sociology  of 
Motivation,  Section  4:   Awareness  of  Motives. 


ORGANISM     AND     PSYCHIC     STRUCTURE  yg 

goat  mechanism  or  through  warfare  waged  by  tottering  regimes 
has  frequently  been  noted. 

In  discussing  how  the  various  elements  of  the  psychic  struc- 
ture are  rooted  in  the  organism,  we  have  found  it  necessary  also 
to  discuss  the  person  and  the  society  in  which  he  lives.  The  organic 
features  of  men— individual  or  racial— do  not  in  themselves  enable 
us  to  explain  man's  psychic  traits;  in  fact,  we  cannot  adequately 
define  psychic  traits  without  reference  to  the  social  milieus  and 
trainings  of  the  person.  This  is  not,  of  course,  to  say  that  the  or- 
ganism is  not  relevant  to  the  development  of  psychic  traits  as  well 
as  of  the  person;  it  is  to  say  that  the  organism  is  relevant  only 
within  the  meanings  assigned  it  in  the  roles  men  play. 

Our  undefined  impulses  are  defined  by  goals  that  are  socially 
acquired.  Our  perception  is  decisively  conditioned  by  the  social 
organization  of  our  organic  sensations  in  accordance  with  accepted 
symbols  and  vocabularies.  And  our  feelings  are  socially  transformed 
into  the  emotions  of  the  developing  child.  We  recognize  such  emo- 
tions by  the  gestures  that  are  socially  associated  with  them.  Dif- 
ferent societies  and  different  social  units  have  their  verbal  and  ges- 
tural vocabularies  of  emotions  which  define  approved  feeling 
states:  the  emotions  that  individuals  feel  on  given  occasions  are 
often  socially  stereotyped. 

The  development  of  the  psychic  structure— of  impulse,  percep- 
tion, and  emotion— thus  involves  the  social  roles  that  the  person 
acquires  and  enacts.  But  in  order  to  view  the  organization  of  the 
psychic  structure  with  a  minimum  of  social  complication,  we  have 
examined  it  in  the  child,  in  severe  organic  deprivation,  in  social 
crisis,  and  in  certain  unsocialized  areas  of  individual  development. 
And,  among  other  things,  we  have  found  out  that  nothing  we  can 
learn  of  the  naked  psychic  structure  necessarily  enables  us  to  un- 
derstand the  conduct  of  the  person;  that,  in  fact,  we  must  interpret 
the  psychic  structure  within  the  larger  frame  provided  by  the  char- 
acter structure  as  a  whole. 


CHAPTER 

I  V 

The  Person 


IN  discussing  the  psychic  integration  of  emotion,  impulse,  and 

perception,  we  found  it  necessary  to  consider  man  as  a  person  as 

well  as  man  as  an  animal  organism.  The  conception  of  the  psychic 

structure  is  closely  linked  to  that  of  the  person,  and  the  person  as 

such,  in  turn,  is  predominantly  a  creature  of  interpersonal  situa- 

.tions.  Indeed,  this  integration  of  person  with  others— that  is  to  say, 

/the  roles  that  persons  play— is  the  key  to  the  understanding  of  the 

'  I  concept  ^- the  jgerson  is  composed  of  the  combination  of  roles  that 

\he  enacts.. 

Awareness,  or  consciousness,  is  a  reference  to  the  field  of  our 
experiences  at  any  given  waking  moment;  it  is  what  we  are  aware 
of.  Thus  we  may  experience  a  crowd  of  people,  or  a  forest  of  trees; 
or  we  may  experience  a  certain  body  tone,  a  diffuse  feeling  of 
tiredness,  the  localized  pangs  of  hunger,  or  a  knife  cutting  our  left 
hand.  To  be  conscious  of  external  events  in  just  the  way  that  we 
are,  requires  an  organism  with  certain  kinds  of  sense  organs;  the 
anatomy  and  physiology  of  these  organs  are  as  necessary  for  our 
consciousness  of  a  brown  dog  as  is  the  dog  as  a  brovvTi  physical 
thing.  Anyone  who  is  equipped  with  the  appropriate  kind  of  eyes 
can  be  aware  of  the  dog.  But  awareness  of  our  toothache,  hunger 
pangs,  or  body  tone  of  buoyancy  is  restricted  to  each  of  us  individ- 
ually. Yet,  our  awareness  of  external  and  of  internal  events,  is  pri- 
marily rooted  in  the  organism  and  the  psychic  structure. 

In  seZ/-consciousness,  or  *e//-awareness,  however,  the  person  is 
also  involved.  Although  our  bodily  feelings  and  our  awareness  of 
our  toes,  hands,  and  noses  are  involved  in  our  image  of  self,  or  at 
least  often  color  it  with  feelings  and  sensitivities,  our  total  self- 
4  image  involves  our  relations  to  other  persons  and  their  appraisals 
of  us. 


THEPERSON  8l 

1.  Language,  Role,  Person 

-*^he  use  of  language  is  the  most  important  mechanism  of  inter- 
personal conduct,  and  the  major  source  of  knowledge  of  our  selves. - 

The  speech  apparatus  of  the  organism  is  a  necessary  condition 
for  the  acquisition  and  use  of  language.  As  an  organism,  man  can 
make  a  wider  variety  of  articulate  noises  than  any  other  animal. 
Moreover,  he  can  control  his  noises,  varying  them  according  to 
tone,  pitch,  percussion,  inflection,  and  intervening  silences;  he  can 
gurgle,  goo,  squeak,  and  grunt  in  a  wonderfully  flexible  manner. 
From  this  wide  variety  of  sounds,  certain  patterns  of  articulate 
sounds  are  selected  and  socially  fixed  as  units  with  definite  mean- 
ings. Strictly  speaking,  there  are  no  "organs  of  speech";  rather,  as 
Edward  Sapir  put  it,  there  are  "organs  that  are  incidentally  useful 
in  the  production  of  speech  sounds."  ^  The  controlled  sounds  of 
speech  require  delicate  co-ordinations  of  an  elaborate  muscle  and 
nervous  structure;  they  involve  the  teeth,  tongue  and  lips,  the 
larynx  and  the  lungs,  as  well  as  the  auditory  senses. 

Yet  these  organic  conditions  are  not  sufficient  for  human  speech. 
The  human  organism  isolated  from  all  other  human  beings  probably 
would  not  develop  intelligible  speech,  even  though  it  had  all  the 
organically  required  equipment. 

All  men  are  biologically  similar  in  their  speech  equipment,  yet 
they  learn  variously  to  speak  Chinese,  Portuguese,  Brooklynese,  or 
English,  according  to  which  is  spoken  in  the  community  in  which 
they  grow  up.  No  doubt  the  larynx  of  a  North  Chinese  peasant  is 
not  very  different  from  the  larynx  of  an  East  End  Londoner,  but 
the  language  they  come  to  understand  and  use  is  quite  diflFerent. 
When  we  say  that  the  Londoners  and  the  Chinese  cannot  "under- 
stand" the  different  articulate  noises  they  have  respectively  learned 
to  make,  we  refer  to  the  fact  that  the  sounds  which  one  makes  do 
not  "mean"  the  same  thing  to  the  other.  Now,  what  is  meant  by 
"mean  the  same  thing"? 

When  a  sound  which  one  person  utters  calls  out  similar  responses 
in  those  who  hear  it  as  in  those  who  utter  it,  then  the  sound  has  a 
common  meaning.  It  is  then,  as  George  Mead  terms  it,  a  significant 
symbol.  When  a  given  symbol  means  similar  things  to  a  group  of 
persons,  we  may  say  that  these  persons  make  up  a  community  of 

^Language  (New  York:   1939),  pp.  7-9. 


82  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

discourse.  In  general,  symbols  will  mean  similar  things  to  this 
community  in  so  far  as  they  are  used  by  persons  acting  in  co-ordi- 
nation.rif  one  person  interprets  a  symbol  differently  than  another, 
the  common  behavior  in  which  they  are  involved  may  become  unco- 
ordinated. This  mixup  of  conduct,  arising  from  the  symbol's  failure 
to  co-ordinate  the  actions  of  two  or  more  persons,  will  check  the 
wrong  interpretation— that  is,  the  one  which  is  not  usual  and  com- 
mon to  most  of  the  participants.  In  this  way,  the  meaning  of  a 
symbol,  the  response  which  it  typically  calls  out  in  various  persons, 
is  kept  common. 

'^n^  community  of  discourse  thus  normally  coincides  with  a  com- 
inlmity  of  co-ordinated  activities.  For  tUe  prime  function  of  lan- 

^guage  is  to  co-ordinate  social  conduct.  J^^ery  little  truly  human 
conduct  could  be  successfully  performea  if  for  even  a  single  day 
we  could  not  speak  or  understand  the  speech  of  others. 

Traditional  theorists  of  language  have  held  that  the  primary 
function  of  language  is  the  "expression"  of  some  "idea,"  or  some 
feeling  already  within  the  individual.  Although  it  is  true  that  lan- 
guage enables  the  mature  person  to  express  ideas  and  feelings, 
modern  theorists  no  longer  agree  that  the  prime  function  of  lan- 
guage is  expressive.  It  has  been  found  more  fruitful  to  approach 
linguistic  behavior,  not  by  referring  it  to  prior  states  or  elements 
in  the  psychic  structure  or  even  in  the  person,  but  by  observing  its 
objective  function  of  co-ordinating  social  behavior.- 
—  Language  is  primarily  a  system  of  signs  which  are  responded  to 

2  The  shift  in  the  general  approach  to  language  has  been  summarized  by 
Edwin  Esper  in  "Language,"  Handbook  of  Social  Psychology,  Carl  Murchison, 
ed.  (2d  ed.,  rev.;  Worcester:  Clark  Univ.  Press,  1935).  The  shift  is  part 
of  the  larger  drift  to  a  sociological  psychology,  a  connection  traced  by  John 
F.  Markey,  The  Symbolic  Process  and  Its  Integration  in  Children  (New  York: 
Harcourt,  Brace,  1928).  From  a  philosophical  viewpoint,  the  neatest  and 
most  useful  analytic  scheme  for  the  study  of  language  is  probably  C.  W. 
Morris,  Foundations  of  the  Theory  of  Signs,  International  Encyclopedia  of 
Unified  Science,  Volume  1,  No.  2  (Chicago:  1938).  Among  the  many  scholars 
responsible  for  the  newer  viewpoint  toward  language,  see:  Grace  De  Laguna, 
Speech:  Its  Function  and  Development  (New  Haven:  Yale  Univ.  Press, 
1927);  Bronislaw  Malinowski,  Appendix  in  Ogden  and  Richards's,  The 
Meaning  of  Meaning  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1927)  and  Coral  Gardens 
and  Their  Magic  (New  York:  American  Book  Co.,  1935),  Vol.  H;  George  H. 
Mead,  Mind,  Self  and  Society  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1934);  and 
John  Dewey,  Experience  and  Nature  (Chicago:  Open  Court,  1925),  Chapter  4. 


y 


THEPERSON  H^ 

!  by  other  persons  as  indicators  of  the  future  actions  of  the  person 
i  speakingrA  given  symbol  can  thrs  mediate  conduct  only  if  it  calls 
out  a  similar  response  in  the  one  as  in  another,  that  is,  if  it  has  a 
common  meaning.  This  point  of  view  toward  the  function  of  lan- 
guage invites  us  to  pay  attention  to  the  social  context  of  language 
behavior,  for  the  same  sound  may  have  different  meanings  when 
uttered  in  different  contexts. 
I      Words  take  on  meanings  from  the  other  words  with  which  they 
/  are  associated.  The  United  States  Senate  has  been  known  to  argue 
for  several  days  over  the  insertion  of  the  word  "an"  in  a  formal 
document. 

But  the  context  which  lends  meaning  to  words  is  social  and     ^ 
behavioral,  as  well  as  linguistic.  This  is  indicated  by  the  meaning- 
lessness  of  words  which  we  hear  without  being  aware  of  the  context 
in  which  they  are  uttered  or  written.   Most  language  situations 
carry  unseen  and  unspoken  references  which  must  be  known   if 
the  utterances  are  to  be  meaningful.  In  the  case  of  the  Senate  de- 
bate, the  full  meaning  of  the  inclusion  or  omission  of  "an"  may 
require  an  understanding  of  the  connections  of  various  senators 
with  their  respective  state  organizations,  and  of  pronouncements 
previously  made  by  Republican  and  Democratic  party  officials. 
""A  person  is  composed  of  an  internalization  of  organized  social 
roles;  language  is  the  mechanism  by  which  these  internalizations 
occur.'  It  is  the  medium  in  which  these  roles  are  organized.  Now, 
we  have 'defined  role  as  a  conduct  pattern  of  a  person  which  is       j 
typically  expected  by  other  persons.- It  is  an  expected  pattern  of 
conduct,   Xhe   roles   a   person   plays   thus   integrate   one   segment       / 
of  his  total  coiiduct  with  a  segment  of  the  conduct  of  others.  And     / 
this  integration  of  persons,  and  of  the  roles  they  expect  of  one  an-    / 
other^  occurs  by  means  of  language.  For  it  is  largely  by  a  language 
of  vocal  gestures  that  we  know  what  is  expected  of  us.  We  meet 
the  expectations  of  others  by  calling  out  in  ourselves  a  response 
similar  to  the  response  which  the  other  person  has  called  out  in/ 
himself  .  .  .  that  is,  both  respond  similarly  to  the  same  vocal  ges- 
ture. 

When  we  are  learning  a  new  role  and  do  not  know  what  is  ex- 
pected of  us,  our  correct  and  incorrect  moves  are  indicated  to  us 
by  the  approval  and  disapproval  of  others.  By  their  vocal  expecta- 
tions they  guide  us  into  the  conduct  pattern.  Various  nonvocal  ges- 


84  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

tures  may  also  guide  our  performance:  The  frown  and  the  smile 
deter  or  encourage  us.  But  the  vocal  gesture  is  more  explicit,  for 
the  gesturer  himself  is  more  readily  affected  by  speech  than  by 
any  other  kind  of  gesture  he  can  make.  We  can  hear  ourselves  talk 
more   easily  than  we   can  feel   our  eyes   blink  or  our   foreheads 
wrinkle.  This  means  that  we  can  manage  the  performance  of  our 
'"    own  roles  by  our  own  vocal  gestures. 
/   '  When  we  have  internalized  the  vocal  gestures^  of  others,  we 
/  have  internalized,  so  to  speak,  certain  key  features  of  an  inter- 
personal situation.  We  have  taken  over  into  our  own  person  the 
I   gestures  which  indicate^to  us  what  others  expect  and  require.  And 
vthenTwe^^n  make  certain  expectations  of  ourselves.  The  expecta- 
/tions  of  others  have  thus  become  the  self-expectations  of  a  self- 
/  steering  person.  The  social  control  and  guidance  which  the  gestures 
/  !  of  others  provide  have  thus  become  the  basis  for  self-control— and 
VjFor  the  self-image  of  the  person.] 

2.  Images  of  Self 

The  self-image  develops  and  changes  as  the  person,  through  his 
;  social  experiences,  becomes  aware  of  the  expectations  and  ap- 
[  praisals  of  others.  He  acts  one  way,  and  others  reward  him  with 
food,  warmth,  and  attention;  he  acts  in  another  way  and  they  pun- 
ish him  with  inattention;  when  he  fails  to  meet  their  durable  ex- 
pectations, they  deny  him  satisfaction  and  give  him  their  disap- 
proval. "The  approbation  of  the  important  person  is  very  valuable," 
Harry  Stack  Sullivan  has  written,  "since  disapprobation  denies  satis- 
faction [psychic  structure]  and  gives  anxiety  [person],  the  self 
becomes  extremely  important."  ^ 

If,  as  a  child,  the  person  does  not  meet  the  roles  expected  of 
him,  he  may  be  faced  with  two  results:  (1)  Such  impulses  as  impel 
him  will  not  be  satisfied,  for  other  persons  will  not  cater  to  his 
needs  unless  he  meets  the  requirements  they  exact.  He  is  de- 
pendent upon  these  others  for  nutrition  and  warmth  and  other 
bodily  requirements.  (2)  He  may  also,  in  the  course  of  his  experi- 
f  ence,  know  anxiety  or  insecurity,  for  he  is  dependent  upon  others 
for  approval  of  himself  as  a  person, 

^Conceptions  of  Modern  Psychiatry  (Washington:  W.  A.  White  Psychiatric 
Foundation,  1947). 


THEPERSON  8^ 

As  he  matures,  the  person's  image  of  self  is  taken  over  from  the 
images  of  him  which  others  present  to  him,  by  their  gestures  of 
approval  and  of  disapprobation.  This  general  statement,  however, 
must  be  qualified  in  two  ways: 

I.  For  the  adult,  it  is  more  accurate  to  say  that  the  attitudes 
and  expectations  of  others  facilitate  or  restrain  the  self-image.  For 
by  the  time  the  person  is  adult,  the  image  of  self,  although  depend- 
ent in  varying  degrees  upon  the  current  appraisals  of  others,  is  nor- 
mally strong  enough  to  exist  autonomously.  This  is  possible  because 
the  person  has  already  built  his  self-image  on  the  basis  of  a  long 
sequence  of  previous  appraisals  and  expectations  which  others 
have  presented  to  him. 

The  person  learns  to  follow  models  of  conduct  which  are  sug- 
gested to  him  by  others;  in  addition,  as  he  comes  to  read,  he 
chooses  such  models  from  the  store  of  socially  organized  memory. 
These  latter  models,  as  well  as  those  he  imagines  for  himself,  may 
be  at  variance  with  those  whom  others  immediately  around  him 
appraise  favorably.  His  own  expectations  and  appraisals  of  self 
thus  acquired  may  enable  him  to  accept,  refract,  ignore,  or  reject 
the  expectations  and  appraisals  of  the  current  others.  Indeed,  if 
this  is  not  the  case,  if  there  is  not  some  autonomy  of  self-image  and 
the  adult  person  is  completely  and  immediately  dependent  for  his 
own  self-image  upon  what  others  may  currently  think  of  him, 
he  is  considered  an  inadequate  person.*  The  self-image  which  we 
have  at  any  given  time  is  a  reflection  of  the  appraisals  of  others 
as  modified  by  our  previously  developed  self. 

*  Erich  Fronim  has  aptly  called  such  a  person  "the  automaton":  being  com-' 
pletely    dependent    upon    tlie    appraisals    of    others    the    person    conforms    to  \ 
their   expectations   in   a   compulsive   manner;   he   does   not  have   "a   center  in  I 
himself."  Both  Fromm  and  Karen  Homey  attempt  to  resolve  the  problem  by  I 
invoking   components   of  the   psychic   structure   as   "tlie   real   self."   This   does  j 
not  seem  to  us  an  adequate  solution:  The  psychic  structure,  if  it  is  to  operate 
in  a  manner  harmonious  to  a  social  order,  must  itself  be  quite  socialized  inv 
specific  directions,  even  stereotyped  in  some.  The  answer  to  the  "fagade  self"  \ 
and    the    "real    self"    dichotomy    is    found    not   by   trying    to    jump    past   the  / 
socialized  portions  of  the  personality  and  finding  something  more  "genuine"/ 
in  the  psychic  or  organic  "foundations,"  but  by  viewing  tlie  social  process  om 
the  self  in  a  longitudinal  way,  and  "finding"  a  "genuine  self'  that  is  buriedj 
by  later  socializations.  See  Erich  Fromm,  Escape  from  Freedom  (New  York: 
Farrar  &  Rinehart,  1941). 


86  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

II.  The  social  idea  of  the  self  must  be  qualified  in  a  second 
(   way:   by  consideration  of  who  the  "others"  to  whom  we  respond 
\  are.   Only  the   appraisals   of  those   others   who   are   in   some  way 
Significant  to  the  person  count  for  much  in  the  building  and  main- 
tenance   of   his    self-image.    In    some    societies    and   families   "the 
mother"  is  the  most  significant  other  to  the  infant  and  r'hild,  since 
she  caters  most  directly  to  the  bodily  needs  and  by  her  actions 
completes   the   impulsive   beginnings   of  the   child's   activities.    In 
such  cases,  the  image  which  the  child  has  of  himself  is  perhaps  at 
first  the  image  which  his  mother  has  of  him.  But  as  the  person 
grows  up,  a  variety  of  significant  others  begins  to  operate.  If  we 
y    know  who  has  been  and  who  is  thus  significant  to  the  person's 
image  of  self,  we  know  a  very  great  deal  about  that  person. 

Three    general   principles    seem    important   in    determining   this 
selection  of  significant  others: 

( 1 )  Cumulative  Confirmations.  The  image  of  self  which  a  person 
already  possesses  and  which  he  prizes  leads  him  to  select  and  pay 
/Attention  to  those  others  who  confirm  this  self-image,  or  who 
[  offer  him  a  self-conception  which  is  even  more  favorable  and  at- 
\  tractive  than  the  one  he  possesses.  This  principle  leads  the  person 
to  ignore,  if  he  can,  others  who  do  not  appreciate  his  prized  or 
aspired-to  self-image,  or  who  debunk  his  image  or  restrain  the 
development  of  it.  A  circle  of  friends  is  typically  made  up  of  those 
who  further,  or  who  at  least  allow  the  -ether  persons  to  retain, 
their  respective-  self-images.  .As  the  ancients  put  it,  "The  friend 
is  my  other  self."  One  avoids  as  best  he  can  the  enemies  of  the 
self-images  one  prizes.  The  cumulative  selection  of  those  persons  I 
who  are  significant  for  the  self  is  thus  in  the  direction  of  confirming  ; 
persons,  and  the  more  he  succeeds  in  limiting  his  significant  others  \ 
to  those  who  thus  confirm  his  prized  self-image,  the  more  strongly 
he  will  seek  such  persons  as  significant  in  the  future.  So  there  is  a 
tendency  in  the  biography  of  the  person  for  a  sequence  of  con- 
firming persons  to  accumulate. 

Now  if  this  were  the  only  principle  involved  in  the  selection  of 
significant  others,  life  might  perhaps  be  a  happy  and  spontaneous 
affair;  but  other  considerations  do  interfere  with  its  single  action: 
^  a  person  cannot  choose  all  his  relationships.  The  child,  for  example, 
is  less  selective  than  the  adult  of  the  others  to  whom  he  pays  at- 
tention—which is  one  reason  that  children  are  so  easily  "hurt." 
^Trusting  children  frequently  experience  disappointments,  rebuffs, 


THEPERSON  8y 

and  slights,  until  they  learn  to  stem  their  confident  approach  with  ^ 
some  degree  of  "shyness^'j  If  the  balance  tips  in  the  direction  of    I 
withdrawal,  a  scale  of  orientations  and  traits  are  observable,  from    / 
reserve    through    suspicion    toward    the    friendliest    guest;    anyone   ' 
and  anything  that  is  new  may  become  fearsome,  until  the  child  is 
frequently   misunderstood   as   "insensitive."   In   fact,   he   may   not 
have  learned  how  to  deal  with  the  new,  and  hence  be  relying  upon 
total  avoidance  of  all  new  challenges. 

The  image  of  self  built  up  during  childhood  may  thus  contain 
negative  elements  so  firmly  integrated  that  they  are  never  gotten 
rid  of.  During  adolescence  in  Western  societies,  the  child  is  "catch- 
ing on"  to  the  selection  of  confirming  others  as  significant,  and 
this  involves  the  development  of  sensitivities  to  little  cues  which 
other  persons  present  and  which  warn  the  person  whether  or  not 
someone  is  likely  to  confirm  or  to  threaten  prized  self-images. 
Between  the  polar  opposites  of  the  fear  of  always  being  "left  out" 
and  of  "never  being  left  alone,"  the  maturing  person  seeks  to  win 
and  move  in  his  own  "elbow  room."  The  adult  often  sees  a  man 
and  immediately  "takes  a  dislike  to  him."  Other  persons  he  imme- 
diately likes;  they  are  felt  to  be  "considerate,"  which  means  that 
they  defer  to  him  in  the  direction  of  his  desired  self-image.  They 
treat  him  as  he  would  like  to  be  treated:  they  are  confirming 
others.  But  the  child  may  not  be  so  aware  of  those  often  unspoken 
cues  which  aid  the  strategic  adult  in  his  selection  of  significant 
others  according  to  the  principle  of  the  confirmation  of  his  desired 
self-image, 

(2)  Selection  by  Position  and  Career.  In  the  construction  and 
maintenance  of  a  prized  self-image,  the  selection  of  significant 
others  is  limited  by  the  institutional  position  of  the  person  and 
by  the  course  of  his  career  from  one  institutional  position  to  an- 
other. This  selection  is  not,  of  course,  a  simple  mechanical  process; 
in  most  positions  there  are  various  possibilities.  The  position  of  a 
nobleman  within  the  status  levels  of  a  feudal  society  in  revolt,  and 
of  a  factory  worker  within  the  occupational  hierarchy  of  modem 
capitalism  may  each  be  examined  in  this  connection: 

A  nobleman  may  be  (a)  insulated  against  the  harsh  and  nega- 
tive appraisals  of  serfs  or  peasants  by  childhood  segregation  in 
which  a  strong  and  exalted  self-image  was  built— an  image  which 
later  enables  him  to  deem  the  peasants'  approval  and  disapproval 
as  equally  irrelevant.  Only  the  judgments  oQiis  status_peersjcount^__^^ 


88  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

(b)  The  noble  may  interpret  the  peasants'  negative  appraisals  in 
a  wholly  different  way  than  they  are  intended.  He  may  have  be- 
come aware  of  the  peasants'  attitudes  only  from  other  nobles,  and 
thus  his  self  may  refract  and  modify  the  appraisals  before  they 
are  incorporated  into  his  self-image.  He  may,  indeed,  force  the 
obedience  of  the  peasants  to  him,  and  then  interpret  their  obedient 
gestures  as  confirming  and  facilitating  his  honorable  image  of  self. 

(c)  Under  certain  conditions,  the  noble  may  not  be  able  to  stand 
the  real  or  imaginary  disapprovals  of  the  peasants.  He  may  then 
change  his  own  self-image,  and  the  conduct  which  it  involves,  so 
as  to  permit  kindness  to  the  peasants,  which  liis  previous  self- 
image  permitted  only  to  other  nobles.  ,  He  thus  seeks  to  modify 
their  negative  appraisals  and  in  the  process  of  doing  so,  he  gets 
from  their  appraisals  another  image  of  himself.  In  turn,  he  will 

y  now  strive  "to  live  up  to  it":  the  line  of  his  confirming  other  has 
shifted,  and  the  strategies  employed  by  him  to  win  such  confirma- 
tion from  persons  who  become  significant  have  shifted.  So  did 
certain  Russian  noblemen  in  the  nineteenth  century  "humble  them- 
selves," go  among  the  peasants,  and,  on  humanitarian  grounds, 
seek  to  co-operate  with  them  politically. 
(The  class  and  status  positions  of  a  person  may  thus  be  restric- 
'^  tions  upon  his  selection  of  significant  others,  as  well  as  determi- 
nants of  the  degree  and  kind  of  significance  and  of  the  angles  of 
refraction  which  other  persons  of  differing  status  may  possess  for 
the  person  of  a  given  status  position. 

If  a  factory  worker  rejects,  on  ideological  or  other  grounds,  the 
appraisals  of  members  of  the  employing  class,  his  image  of  self 
may  not  directly  reflect  their  appraisals  of  him.  If  working-class 
parents  proudly  tell  their  children  tales  of  how  they,  and  their  par- 
ents before  them,  were  imprisoned  for  heroic  violence  "against  the 
capitalists  and  their  state  apparatus,"  then  upper-class  appraisals 
are  less  likely  to  be  positively  significant  to  the  construction  and 
retention  of  a  self-image  of  the  child  of  the  workers.  Under  such 
conditions  we  may  speak  of  "class  consciousness."  Such  class  tradi- 
tion and  consciousness  may  be  said  to  have  considerable  weight 
when  it  restricts  to  one's  own  economic  class  the  community  of 
others  who  are  significant  for  the  self-image. 

On  the  other  hand,  if  the  upper  classes  monopolize  the  means  of 
communication  and  fill  the  several  mass  media  with  the  idea  that 
all  those  at  the  bottom  are  there  because  they  are  lazy,  unintelli- 


THEPERSON  89 

gent,  and  in  general  inferior,  then  these  appraisals  may  be  taken 
over  by  the  poor  and  used  in  the  building  of  an  image  of  their 
selves.  The  appraisal  of  the  wealthy,  privileged  children  may  then 
be  internalized  by  underprivileged  children  and  facilitate  negative 
self-images.  Such  images,  if  impressed  early  enough  and  continually 
enough  by  all  persons  who  are  significant  to  these  children  may 
cripple  their  chances  to  better  their  social  position  and  thus  ob- 
tain economic  and  social  bases  for  more  favorable  self-images.  An 
outstanding  example  of  such  restriction  in  the  selection  of  signifi- 
cant others  as  determined  by  class  and  ethnic  position  is  found  in 
the  self-images  of  many  American  Negroes.^  If,  on  the  other  hand, 
the  Negro  child  is  able  to  exclude  the  appraisals  of  various  public 
others,  he  may  build  up  a  more  favorable  self-image  on  the  social 
basis  of  the  more  intimate  others  of  his  ingroup  of  fellow  Negroes. 

It  is  worth  noting  that  there  are  several  ways  in  which  self- 
respect  and  social  respect  may  be  related: 

Self-valuation  and  valuation  by  others  may  be  in  positive  agree- 
ment. For  example,  a  proud  group  of  rulers  may  also  be  admired 
by  others— the  feudal  lords  of  the  Middle  Ages  or  the  Roman 
emperors  come  to  mind. 

The  self  and  the  other  may  be  in  agreement— but  negatively; 
an  inferior  group  may  accept  the  negative  images  imposed  on  it  by 
their  status  superiors.  All  ruling  groups  seek  to  impose  such  senti- 
ments upon  subject  groups.  Stereotyped  images  and  unwarranted 
generalizations  from  the  worst  case,  which  make  him  "represent- 
fitive"  for  all,  are  among  the  means  used  to  breed  inferiority  feel- 
ings. Exacted  deference  is  another.  Thus,  the  despised  serf  comes 
to  think  lowly  of  himself  and  of  his  fellows.  The  slave  is  despised 
as  chattel  and,  being  powerless,  seeks  to  hold  his  own  by  fraud, 
which  is  despicable  to  those  who  esteem  only  violence. 
I  Self-respect  may  be  high,  but  the  social  esteem  of  others  may 
be  low.  Thus,  the  posturing  of  the  "misunderstood"  or  "unknown" 
genius  and  the  dictum  that  the  prophet  is  not  known  in  his  own 
home  town.  In  such  cases,  an  invented  or  imaginary  other  may 
be  used  to  compensate  for  the  denial  of  respect  by  a  public  and 
thus  high  self-valuation  be  maintained.  The  misunderstood  genius 
assures  himself  that  "posterity,"  if  not  his  present  colleagues,  will 

5  See  Chapter  XI:  Stratification  and  Institutional  Orders,  Section  5:  The 
Status  Sphere  and  Personality  Types. 


go  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

surely  come  to  honor  and  respect  him  and  his  work.  Behind  such 
a  secularized  theology  of  martyrdom  there  is  often  religious  imag- 
ery of  various  sorts.  Such  sentiment  may  be  entirely  adequate  to  the 
situation— as  it  was  for  Schopenhauer,  who  published  in  1819,  but 
gained  esteem  only  after  1848;  or  for  Arnold  Schonberg  whose 
works  for  long  years  were  not  fully  appreciated.  On  the  other 
hand,  a  mere  megalomanic,  and  hence  groundless  and  spurious, 
attitude  is  also  possible. 

Finally  there  are  situations  in  which,  despite  the  great  esteem 
of  others,  a  man  deprecates  his  own  worth,  and,  in  the  eyes  of  his 
God  he  may— as  did  young  Luther— go  to  extraordinary  length  in 
his  sense  of  humility  and  his  moods  of  penance. 

(3)  The  Confirming  Use  of  the  Intimate  Other.  Thwarted  in  his 
public  search  for  a  confirming  other,  the  person  may  restrict  his 
search  for  confirming  others  to  a  few  intimate  others.  Perhaps  this 
is  especially  true  of  persons  who  occupy  inferior  institutional  posi- 
tions, who  thus  try  to  build  durable,  intimate  relations  with  which 
to  counteract  public  depreciation.  The  number  of  intimate  others 
may  even  become  drastically  restricted  and  at  times  become  a  sole  / 
significant  other.  The  person  may  then  attempt  to  derive  the  image 
of  his  or  her  self  entirely  from  the  appraisals  of  this  one  particular  "^ 
/  other.  These  two  withdraw  socially:  as  far  as  other  people  are 
concerned,  they  are  "in  a  daze."  They  integrate  themselves  in  a 
situation  of  intimacy,  and  together  face  the  broad  and  alien  world 
which  "does  not  understand."  Fed  by  the  warmth  and  security  of 
such  intimate  closure,  they  have  this  larger  world  at  their  mercy 
and  can  discuss,  debunk,  and  ignore  it.  This  strategy  may  be 
temporarily  successful— and  in  fact,  expected— during  certain  phases 
of  adolescence,  when  many  others  crowd  in  upon  the  person  with 
new  and  less  favorable  appraisals  than  his  family  and  school  have 
offered. 

Such  a  condition  cannot  usually  last  forever.  Nevertheless,  in 
the  modern  industrial  metropolis  in  which  private  and  public  roles 
are  rigorously  segregated,  a  certain  degree  of  such  exclusion  and 
refraction  of  public  appraisals  by  intimate  circles,  and  a  more  or 
less  exclusive  acceptance  of  the  desired  approval  of  intimate  others, 
may  be  integrated  into  a  rather  enduring  basis  for  personal  images 
of  self. 
^  r  These  three  principles  involved  in  the  selection  of  significant 
^  \Qthers  may  be  linked  in  this  way:  the  social  position  and  career 


THEPERSON  9^"^ 

of  the  person  set  limits,  more  or  less  broad,  for  the  selection  of 
significant  others.  Within  these  limits,  the  selection  will  proceed 
in  the  direction  of  those  others  who  are  believed  to  confirm  the 
prized  or  aspired-to  image  of  self.  If  the  institutional  position  and 
career  prohibits  the  selection  of  such  others  from  public  life,  the 
quest  for  such  confirmation  of  self-image  by  significant  others  may  • 
be  narrowed  down  to  a  sequence  of  intimate  others. 

These  principles  do  not,  of  course,  exhaust  the  determinants 
of  the  process  of  selection.  We  shall  encounter  others,  and  further 
examples  of  these,  in  their  proper  institutional  contexts.'''  For  it  is, 
in  some  major  part,  through  the  line-up  of  significant  others  that 
institutions  form  personalities  in  often  intricate  ways. 

3.  Unities  of  Self 

"It  has  been  said,"  writes  Frank  Jones  in  commenting  on  the 
contemporary  painter,  Marshall  Glasier,  "that  everyone  is  three 
persons:  what  he  thinks  he  is,  what  others  think  he  is,  and  what  he 
thinks  others  think  he  is.  The  fourth— what  he  really  is— is  un- 
known; perhaps  it  doesn't  exist."  '  ^^  a 

If  a  man  is  what  he  thinks  he  is,  his  image  of  himself  has  a  ' 
controlling  function:  he  shapes  himself  in  terms  of  his  own  self-  . 
image.  But  others  may  hold  diverse  images  of  a  man,  according 
to  their  own  perspectives  and  roles.  Both  hatred  and  love  may  lead 
to  exaggerated  emphasis  upon  despicable  or  upon  lovable  features. 
The  fighting  caricaturist  and  the  build-up  specialist,  like  the  dis- 
illusioned lover  and  the  adoring  lover,  know  this  well.  There  are 
as  many  images  of  us  in  circulation  as  there  are  people  who  take 
note  of  our  past,  our  present,  or_our  potential  relevance  for  their 
own  actions_and  expectations.  Some  of  these  images  may  be  of 
no  concern  to  us— we  may  not  even  know  of  them;  others  we  may 
"overlook"  as  irrelevant.  Or  a  series  of  images  may  be  known  to  us, 
and  may  matter  to  us  in  quite  varying  extents.  Our  awareness  of 
the  fact  that  others  hold  views  about  us,  and  our  eagerness  to  be 
well  thought  of  by  those  who  matter  to  us  most,  naturally  influences 

6  See  Chapter  VII:  Institutions  and  Persons,  Section  i:  The  Institutional 
Selection  of  Persons;  Section  2:  The  Institutional  Formation  of  Persons;  and 
Section  3:  The  Theory  of  Premiums  and  Traits  of  Character. 

^  Reed  College  Brochure,   1952. 


Q2  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

J   our  behavior;  and  that  is  why  to  quite  some  extent  we  are  what 
"others  think  of  us." 

But  we  are  also  to  some  extent  what  we  think  others  think  of 

'  L,  us.  For  often  there  is  a  difference  between  what  we  think  others 
/  think  of  us  and  what  they  actually  do  think.  The  entire  machinery 
of  "conventional  lies"  and  "tactful  proprieties"— along  with  the  fact 
that  most  people  do  not  feel  any  particular  incentive  to  "tell  the 
truth"  to  others— allows  for  a  considerable,   and  often   a  typical, 
disparity  between  what  people  actually  tliink  of  us  and  what  they 
allow  us  to  know  of  their  true  opinion.  "Flattery,"  as  we  all  know, 
is  widespread  in  a  society  where  people  crave  to  be  "popular.^  , , 
Consider  some  of  the  ways  by  which  other  persons  may  have 
gotten  the  image  of  us  which  they  hold :    ( i )   Other  people  may 
get  an  image  of  us  in  terms  of  the  role  we  play  in  a  given  stratum 
or  group.  Thus,  no  matter  what  other  roles  he  may  have  played 
or  may  currently  be  playing,  an  American  Negro  is  often  viewed 
as  a  Negro.  The  image  held  of  the  person's  self  is  based  on  experi- 
ence with  him  only  as  a  member  of  some  social  category,  and  no 
other  aspect  of  the  self  which  may  exist  outside  this  segmental 
role  is  considered.  (2)  Another  person  may  "make  allowances"  or 
modify  his  image  of  us  in  terms  of  the  manner  in  which  we  play 
some  role.  Variation  in  our  enactment  of  even  the  most  stereotyped 
role  often  results  in  another's  calling  us  a  "very  intelligent  Negro," 
or  in  our  having  some  personal  characteristics  which  lifts  us  out 
of  the  segmental  role  of  the  Negro.  (3)  Others  may  experience  us 
in  an  intimate  situation  and  build  their  image  of  us  as  we  present 
it  in  this  situation.  We  sometimes  tend  to  believe  that  those  with 
whom  we  are  intimate  accept  our  self-image,  but  this  may  be  very 
far  from  the  case!   The  concept  of  intimacy  has  to  be  handled 
with  care.  Mere  intimacy  does  not  guarantee  that  we  know  an- 
other's image  of  his  or  her  self:  There  are  many  ways  in  which 
we  can  let  our  hair  down,  and  we  may  appear  differently  in  each. 
Two  persons  can  integrate  their  selves  in  a  most  intimate— and 
quite    false— manner;    indeed,    quick    and    mutual    acceptance    of 

^     presented  or  stylized  selves,   or  of  aspired-to   selves,  may  be   a 

\_  requirement  for  certain  kinds  of  intimacy. 

We  can  have  an  adequate  image  of  ourselves  and  it  can  be 
shared  by  our  friends;  but  we  can  also  share  with  them  a  false 
image  of  ourselves  and  tlius  be  self-deceived  hypocrites.  Then 
again,  we  can  have  a  true  image  of  ourselves  which  is  rejected  by 


THE     P  E  R  S  OTSI — ■  g3 

our  friends— and  thus  be  the  misunderstood  woman,  the  unknown 
genius  or  prophet.  Finally,  we  can  have  a  false  image  of  ourselves 
which  is^  rejected  by  our  friends:  we  deceive  ourselves  but  not 
other^ 

At  any  rate,  the  scale  of  impersonal,  personal,  and  intimate  does 
not  seem  to  provide  us  with  an  adequate  basis  for  predicting  the 
chances  of  one  person  to  know  the  self-image  of  another., The  self- 
image  we  hold  and  the  image  we  present  to  others  are  complicated 
by  the  appraisals  of  significant  others  with  whom  we  are  currently 
integrated,  and  by  such  appraisals  as  have  carried  over  from  our 
previous  integration.  A  total  view  of  even  the  presented  images 
to  current  others  would  require  us  to  tag  along  with  a  person  and 
observe  the  selves  he  presents  in  all  the  situations  in  which  he  is 
integrated  with  other  persons.  But  even  if  we  had  access  to  every 
image  the  person  presented  in  every  one  of  his  relations,  we  would 
still  have  to  choose  which  of  these  segmental  roles  in  which  the 
self  is  presented  is  the  one  most  likely  to  coincide  with  "the  genuine 
self-image,"  if  any,  held  by  the  person  himself. 

The  question  of  what  really  lies  beyond  all  the  imagery  of  self 
and  of  others,  of  what  the  individual  really  is— clearly  that  is  one 
of  the  great  puzzles  of  man.  So  the  Buddhist  pronounces  his  tat 
tvam  asi,  "Man  become  who  you  are";  so  Socrates  finds  it  a  hard 
task  for  man  "to  know  himself";  and  so  Nietzsche  proclaims  "Man 
is  most  remote  from  himself." 

At  any  rate,  we  do  know  that  in  some  situations  the  image  a 
person  holds  of  himself  is  more  or  less  integrated  with  the  images 
which  significant  others  hold  of  him.  The  image  of  self  which  he 
presents  to  others  and  which  he  is  trying  to  have  them  accept  or 
confirm  is  identical  with  the  image  to  which  he  aspires.  In  other 
situations,  there  may  be  great  differences  between  self-image,  pre- 
sented image,  and  aspired-to  image. 

Such  difi'erences  and  similarities,  though  they  often  arise  in  the 
direct  experience  of  the  person,  are  determined  by  sociological  con- 
ditions. We  may  attempt  to  systematize  those  varied  conditions 
under  which  the  difi^erent  images  coincide;  and  those  under  which 
they  may  collide. 

To  know  another's  self-image  we  have  to  study  the  others  who  ^ 
are  significant  to  him.   It  is  convenient  to  refer  to  the  circle  of 
current  significant  others  as  "the  position"  of  the  person,  and  to     L^ 
refer  to  the  sequence  of  previous  significant  others  as  "theyareer" 


g^  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

of  the  person.*  These  terms  enable  us  to  simplify  our  terminology. 
With  them— "position"  and  "career"— we  knit  interpersonal  situa- 
tions into  social  structures.  For  these  concepts  help  us  to  locate 
types  of  persons  within  social  structures. 

Unity  of  self,  occurring  when   all  the   images   of  self  held  by_ 
the  person  and  by  others  coincide,  will  most  likely  occur  when 
the  position  and  the  career  of  the  person  is  composed  of  significant 
others  who  are  harmonious  in  their  appraisals  and  expectations. 

In  a  society  where  roles  are  stereotyped  and  each  man  "knows 
his  place,"  as  do  others,  there  is  not  much  chance  for  differences 
to  arise  between  self-images  and  the  images  others  hold  of  hirnT] 
The  techniques  of  self-presentation,  the  problem  of  what  others 
really  think  of  us,  and  the  possible  differences  between  what  they 
say  to  others  about  us  and  what  they  say  to  us,  all  compared  with 
what  they  really  think  of  us,  do  not  arise.  In  such  a  society,  the 
changing  self-images  which  occur  along  the  career  are  fairly  well 
set,^and  hence  calculable.  The  roles  which  different  age  groups  are 
\  '.  (expected  to  play  are  well  known  by  all  significant  others  and  are 
0  adhered  to  traditionally.  So  previous  self-images  do  not  conflict 
\^  but  blend  with  later  self-images,  just  as  the  expectations  and 
appraisals  of  others  smoothly  shift  as  the  person  passes  through 
stereotyped  stages  of  his  career.  Aspiration  is  also  traditionally 
stereotyped,  publicized,  and  accepted  by  everyone  as  appropriate; 
indeed,  there  is  no  alternative  available.  Both  the  self  and  all 
significant  others  know  what  the  person  would  like  to  be  at  the 
next  juncture,  and  what,  under  optimum  conditions,  he  probably 
will  be. 

The  type  of  society  in  which  we  may  imagine  various  images 
of  self  to  conflict  is  characterized  by  the  fact  that  both  the  position 
and  the  career  of  the  person  involves  conflicting  expectations  and 
appraisals  by  persons  who  are  significant  to  him. 

In  such  a  society,  according  to  the  principle  of  the  confirming 
other,  persons  will  present  themselves  in  one  way  to  one  set  of 
persons  and  in  another  way  to  another  set.  The  ways  in  which  the 
person  presents  his  self  will  vary  according  to  what  he  believes 
these  various  others  think  of  him.  In  general,  his  style  of  self- 
presentation  will  be  a  bridge  from  the  image  of  self  which  he 

s  See  Chapter  VI:   Biography  and  Types  of  Childhood. 


THEPERSON  95 

believes  others  hold  of  him  and  the  self-image  he  would  like  to 
have  them  confirm. 

If  he  has  the  power,  like  the  nobleman  discussed  above,  the 
person  may  force  others  to  defer  to  the  image  of  his  self  which 
he  desires,  and  then  interpret  their  deference  as  a  confirmation  of 
this  image.  If  he  does  not  have  the  power  and  is  not  certain  that 
someone  accepts  the  image  he  wishes  to  publicize,  he  may  run 
little  tests,  or  have  third  persons  spy  for  him  in  order  to  find  out 
if  his  presented  self  has  been  accepted. 

Hypocrisy  and  posing— the  stylization  of  self-presentations— are 
the  results  of  the  status-ridden  man's  frantic  attempt  to  get  others 
to  confirm  his  self-image  in  a  society  in  which  there  is  no  common 
career  pattern,  no  harmony  in  the  shifting  expectations  and  ap- 
praisals by  others.  Diversity  of  ascent  and  aspiration  is  thus  pos-  ' 
sible;  there  is  freedom  to  choose  occupational  roles  and  intimate 
others;  there  are  many  and  often  conflicting  alternatives.  People 
learn  to  feel  that  certain  others  would  never  accept  the  stylization 
of  self  to  which  they  aspire,  and  so  they  refrain  from  presenting, 
it,  lest  laughter  hurt  the  image.  In  short,  pri\ate  persons  go  in 
for  "public  relations."^  " 

4.  Generalized  Others 

The  attitudes  of  significant  others  toward  the  person  leave  their 
mark  upon  his  self-image;  they  form  a  residue  from  social  experi- 
ence which  he  may  re-experience  and  use  in  evaluating  his  own 
self-image;  when  thus  internalized,  they  form  his  "generalized 
other." 

The    experience    of    this    generalized    other— the    experience    of 
"conscience"— is  not  the  experience  of  a  self-image;  it  is  the  experi- 
ence of  the  appraisals  of  others  who  are  not  immediately  present, 
but  who,  nevertheless,  restrain  or  facilitate  our  own  appraisals  and    J 
images  of  our  self. 

Significant  others,  as  we  have  remarked,  are  those  to  whom  the 
person  pays  attention  and  whose  appraisals  are  reflected  in  his 
self-appraisals;  authoritative  others  are  significant  others  ^hose^ 
appraisals  sanction  actions  and  desires.  The  generalized  other  is 
composed  of  an  integration  of  the  appraisals  and  values  of  the 
significant,  and  especially  the  authoritative,  others  of  the  person. 


96  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

The  generalized  other  of  any  given  person  does  not  necessarily 
represent  the  "entire  community"  or  "the  society,"  but  only  .those 
who  have  been  or  who  are  significant  to  him."  And  some  of  those 
who  have  been  significant  others  may  not  operate  in  the  gen- 
eralized other,  but  may  have  been  excluded  from  awareness— a 
fact  that  is  in  line  with  the  principle  of  selecting  as  significant  those 
others  who  confirm  the  desired  image  of  self. 

The  content  of  a  person's  generalized  other  generally  depends 
upon  the  normative  attitudes  of  "the  society"  only  as  these  attitudes^ 
have  be^n  selected  anr)  ref ranted  _by  those  who  have  been  and.  who 
are  authoritatively  significant  to  the  person.  Accordingly,  persons 
who  have  moved  along  different  career  lines  will  accordingly  feel 
quite  diff^erent  "pangs  of  conscience"  in  regard  to  given  actions. 
And,  on  the  other  hand,  persons  who  have  occupied  similar  insti- 
tutional positions  will  have  similar  generalized  others. ^° 

Both  Sigmund  Freud  and  Max  Weber  have  attempted  to  ex- 
plain the  rise  of  conscience.  Freud  believed  that  the  primordial 
parricide  by  the  "brother  horde"  was  the  fateful  event  leading  to 
religion  and  morality,  to  law  and  guilt  feelings.  Despite  the  in- 

9  This  term,  generalized  other,  is  an  invention  of  the  late  G.  H.  Mead. 
Our  use  of  the  term  differs  from  Mead's  in  one  crucial  respect:  we  do  not 
believe  that  the  generalized  other  necessarily  incorporates  "the  whole  society." 
It  may  stand  for  selected  societal  segments.  See  George  Herbert  Mead,  op. 
cit.,  pp.  154  ff.  For  a  preliminary  statement  of  our  use  of  the  term  see 
Mills,  "Language,  Logic,  and  Culture,"  American  Sociological  Review,  Vol. 
IV,  No.  5  (October  1939),  p.  672,  footnote  12.  Abram  Kardiner,  working  with 
a  modified  version  of  Freud's  concept  of  the  superego,  has  made  several 
very  provocative  remarks  concerning  the  relativity  of  what  we  here  call 
the  generalized  other  to  certain  social  relations  bearing  on  the  child;  see 
his  The  Individual  and  His  Society  (New  York:  Columbia  Univ.  Press,  1939), 
pp.  74,  124,  130,  134. 

1°  We  may  express  the  jjosition  of  some  Freudians  by  saying  that  they 
restrict  the  significant  others  who  by  their  appraisals  deposit  a  generahzed 
other  (or  "superego")  to  one  or  two  persons,  and  locate  these  influences  in 
the  childhood  phase  of  the  career  of  the  person.  The  generalized  other  is 
thus  believed  to  be  composed  of  the  forbidding  or  authoritarian  parent.  See 
Chapters  IV  and  V  on  the  temijoral  autonomy  of  motives,  self-images,  and 
generalized  other.  Freud's  own  position  excluded  such  bases  of  the  superego 
as  we  are  considering.  Only  when  social  influences  remain  "properly  within 
its  assigned  realm  .  .  .  [and]  follows  the  path  sketched  for  it  by  the  organic 
determinant"  are  they  to  be  considered.  See  Freud,  "Three  Contributions  to 
the  Theory  of  Sex,"  in  The  Basic  Writings  of  Sigmund  Freud,  A.  A.  Brill,  tr. 
and  ed.  (New  York:  Modern  Library,  1938). 


THEPERSON  9/ 

formed  criticisms  of  anthropologists  and  historians,  Freud  did  not 
modify  this  view. 

Max  Weber  sought  to  trace  the  rise  of  conscience  in  the  history 
of  ancient  Judaism  and  in  the  Judeo-Christian  tradition.  He  exam- 
ined the  ethical  and  religious  compromises  of  this  tradition,  its 
reformations  and  revivals,  and  its  sequence  of  martyrs,  saints,  and 
priests.  In  his  work,  Weber  highlighted  the  Torah  teachers  (the 
Levites)  and  the  great  scriptural  prophets  of  Jewish  antiquity,  as 
well  as  the  Puritans  who,  because  of  their  "activist"  concerns,  in- 
fluenced mass  behavior  in  everyday  life.^^  To  this  Western  se- 
quence, Weber  juxtaposed  that  of  the  East.  There  religious  elites, 
as  aristocratic  intellectuals  in  despotically  ruled  societies,  withdrew 
to  practice  apathetic  contemplation.  These  elites  failed  to  shatter 
the  massive  growth  of  popular  magic  and  to  displace  it  by  religious 
and  ethical  systems  of  action.  In  other  words,  for  most  people  in 
such  societies,  the  generalized  other  remained  narrowly  circum- 
scribed by  the  particular  groups— castes  or  ancestral  families— to 
which  the  individual  referred  himself. 

In  the  generalized  other,  the  appraisals  of  many  particular  others 
are  organized  into  a  pattern.  The  contributions  of  any  particular 
other  are  fused  with  the  contributions  of  these  various  others,  and 
thus  form  the  generalized  other.  Accordingly,  when  the  person 
performs  an  act  that  is  out  of  line  with  expected  norms  he  may 
experience  a  general  disapproval  of  his  self,  which  means  that  the 
generality  of  his  significant  and  authoritative  others  expected  an 
alternative  act.  He  may  not  be  able  to  locate  and  specify  just  which 
other  forbids  this  act,  for  this  particular  other  has  become  part  of 
his  generalized  other. 

If  the  others  who  have  been  most  significant  to  a  person  have 
been  very  forbidding,  the  person  may  be  burdened  by  feelings 
of  unbearable  guilt.  In  a  restricting  parental  situation  he  may  have 
incorporated  a  generalized  other  that  is  too  narrow  for  the  require- 
ments of  the  larger  institutional  world  of  business  and  pleasure, 
and  he  may  not  have  been  able  to  integrate  the  appraisals  and 
expectations  of  later  others  which  are  more  appropriate  to  his  adult 
roles.  With  psychiatric  aid  the  person  may  be  able  critically  to 
review  his  internal  behavior  and  escape  his  generalized  feelings  of 

11  See  Chapter  IX:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  II,  Section  i: 
Religious  Institutions. 


g8  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

guilt  by  specifying  and  recomposing  the  significance  of  particular 
others  within  his  generalized  other.  He  may  be  able  to  add  (or 
evenTto  substitute)  the  authority  of  the  psychiatrist  to  his  general- 
ized other  in  such  a  way  as  to  gain  genuine  independence  for  ra- 
tional determination  of  self. 

As  new  appraisals  are  added  to  older  ones,  and  older  ones  are 
dropped  or  excluded  from  awareness,  the  generalized  other  nor- 
mally changes.  Such  changes  in  the  composition  of  the  generalized 
other  may  occur  as  an  aspect  of  the  person's  growing  up  or  matur- 
ing, which  we  shall  discuss  in  a  later  chapter;  '-  or  the  generalized 
other  typical  of  an  entire  stratum  or  of  an  entire  society  of  persons 
may  change.  If,  for  example,  the  norms  of  a  society  are  smashed, 
new  significant  and  authoritative  others  may  emerge  who  define 
new  values  and  loyalties,  and  there  is  a  crisis  in  every  person's 
conscience  as  his  authoritarian  others  change.  The  person  is  re- 
appraised, and  he  reappraises  himself  as  well  as  the  selves  of  others. 
Such  "crises  of  conscience "  ^'^  have  occurred  several  times  in  the 
course  of  Western  history,  for  example,  in  cases  of  political  revolu- 
tions and  religious  revivals  and  conversions.  In  fact,  crises  of  this 
sort  are  quite  widespread  in  contemporary  society,  in  connection 
with  totalitarian  parties.  Such  a  recomposing  of  the  content  of 
generalized  others  may  conceivably  be  initiated  in  any  area  of 
society.  In  political  and  economic  revolutions,  the  authoritarian 
other  of  public  figures  and  leaders  may  begin  the  process  of  re- 
appraisals which  gradually  spread  into  other  segments  of  the  so- 
ciety so  that  parents  and  teachers  will  imbibe  them  and  present 
them  to  the  social  novice.  Or,  changes  of  interpersonal  conditions 
may  force  such  reappraisals,  which  will  then  be  transmitted  to 
public  figures  and  political  leaders,  so  that  a  revolution  in  these 
institutions  may  be  forced.^* 

5.  The  Social  Relativity  of  the  Generalized  Other  ' 

V  Since  the  generalized  other  is  relative  to  those  others  who  have 
been  and  who  are  significant  to  a  person,  any  area  of  the  person's 

1-  See  Chapter  VI:   Biography  and  Types  of  Childhood. 

1'*  This  phrase  is  used  by  H.  D.  Lasswell  in  a  lecture  reprinted  in  Public 
Opinion  and  World  Politics  (Chicago,  1933). 

1*  We  shall  examine  these  processes  in  Chapter  XV:  Collective  Behavior, 
Section  4:   Revolution  and  Counterrevolution. 


THEPERSON  gg 

life  may  contribute  to  its  content.  This  is  so  whether  or  not  their 
appraisals  have  been  presented  in  a  sequence  of  interpersonal 
situations,  or  in  various  secondary  symbols,  in  movie,  play,  or  book. 
""The  content  of  the  generalized  other  changes  with  shifts  in  the 
person's  career  and  with  changes  in  the  norms  of  those  institutions 
which  the  person  enacts. - 

We  may  imagine  certain  sequences  of  roles  in  which  no  gen- 
eralized other  would  be  deposited,  and,  quite  apart  from  such 
constructions,  there  are  historical  societies  in  which  the  generalized 
other  is  so  minimized  that  its  effects  seem  negligible.  By  inquiring 
into  the  types  of  condition  which  bear  upon  the  chances  for  a  strong 
and  for  a  weak  generalized  other  to  develop,  we  are  able  to  under- 
stand the  concept  in  a  more  adequately  sociological  manner:  1 

I.  The  most  important  of  the  conditions  which  favor  the  chances 
for  an  effective  generalized  other  to  emerge  are  found  in  the 
childhood  and  adolescent  phases  of  the  life  history.  To  consider 
the  mechanisms  involved  we  must  consider  both  the  career  of 
the  person  and  the  maturation  of  the  psychic  structure.  For  the 
infant  and  the  child  is  typically  helpless  in  both  zones  of  his  devel- 
oping character  structure. 

The  disciplining  of  the  child's  impulses  by  the  appraisals  of  au- 
thoritative others  may  be  internalized  as  expectations  by  which  the 
child  will  come  to  control  his  own  impulses.  Although  normally  the 
psychic  structure  is  socially  integrated,  its  socialization  may  not 
direct  all  the  impulses  which  are  available,  and  accordingly  some 
are  excluded  from  the  child's  awareness.  In  this  case,  there  might, 
in  time,  be  no  tension  between  the  psychic  structure  and  person. 
But  if  it  is  not  the  case,  and  authoritative  others  continue  to  forbid 
the  realization  of  the  impulse,  the  tension  between  the  child's  per- 
son and  his  psychic  structure  may  in  time  lead  to  the  experience 
of  a  repressive  generalized  other. 

/  In  terms  of  this  view,  we  may  say:  look  for  a  society  in  which 
the  impulses  of  the  child  are  typically  allowed  free  sway,  or  even 
allowed  to  govern  the  conduct  of  others  toward  him— in  such  situ- 
ations, the  chances  of  a  generalized  other  to  develop  are  minimized, 
and  the  operations  of  the  generalized  other  that  may  be  deposited 
are,  in  turn,  minimized.  Or,  to  put  it  another  way,  which  carries 
us  beyond  childhood:  when  the  proportion  of  authoritative  others  ' 


100  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

to  the  total  of  significant  others  is  high,  the  chances  are  increased 
for  a  maximum  generahzed  other  to  develop. 
lIL^A  generalized  other  arises  only  with  g.eat  difficulty  when 
many  contradictory  expectations  are  exacted  of  the  person--for 
under  such  conditions  a  given  performance  will  be  appraised  by 
one  significant  or  authoritative  person  quite  diflFerently  than  by 
another.  When  expectations  and  appraisals  thus  conflict,  the  person 
may  choose  between  alternatives— or  he  may  reject  both.  In  the 
latter  case,  he  may  project  a  new  generalized  other  in  the  name 
of  new  and  wider  groups,  real  or  imaginary;  or  he  may  withdraw 
from  the  larger  society  into  "criminal"  behavior;  or,  in  case  of 
extreme  tensions  and  value  conflicts,  into  a  privatized  world  of 
behavior  disorders  defined  as  pathological. 

[III.  On  the  other  hand,  a  conscience  does  involve  a  degree  of 
individuation,  which  in  turn  requires  a  detachment  from  roles,  a 
distance  from  the  expectations  others  exact  when  we  play  these 
roles.  Such  detachment  and  individuation  come  about  when  there 
are  conflicting  expectations  exacted,  along  the  sequence  of  our 
careers  and  currently  among  our  circles  of  significant  others.  Indi- 
viduation of  the  self  results  from  the  variety  and  scope  of  voluntary 
actions  which  we  undertake.  It  involves  the  reality  of  individual 
decision  and  being  held  responsible  for  personal  choices.     ~ 

Personal  or  joint  "responsibility"  exists  socially  when  the  indi- 
vidual, as  an  individual  or  as  a  member  of  a  group,  is  held  account- 
able for  his  activities,  in  short,  when  his  acts  are  ascribed  to  his 
self  or  his  group.  In  a  society  where  roles  are  quite  stereotyped, 
this  reality  of  alternatives,  and  such  conceptions  as  personal  respon- 
sibility, may  not  exist.  Only  if  they  do  may  a  person  come  to 
address  himself  in  an  attempt  to  secure  "consistency"  and  unity 
of  self-image  on  the  basis  of  self -expectations;  There  must  be  an 
area  of  voluntary  action,  which  normally  involves  the  perception 
of  open  alternatives  or  of  conflicting  expectations.  The  chances  for 
an  individual  to  emerge  and  to  control  himself  by  a  generalized 
other  are  decreased  as  the  variety  of  \oluntary  choices  and  de- 
cisions which  confront  persons  diminish. 

In  a  society  in  which  the  roles  certain  persons  may  play  are 
consistent,  and  in  which  few  choices  exist,  the  problem  of  the 
consistency  of  the  self  is  socially  solved.  For  then  no  one  person 
may  take  it  upon  himself  to  achieve  an  individual  integration  of 
self.   But  in  a  society  where  there  are  inconsistent  expectations 


THE     PERSON  101 

exacted  of  the  person,  and  hence  alternatives  oflFered,  each  person 
will  have  to  achieve  such  consistency  and  unity  of  self  as  he  can. 
In  this  process,  man  is  individuated,  and  this  individuation  in- 
volves the  building  of  a  generalized  other  from  the  conflicting 
expectations  of  significant  others/' 

IV.  One  person  may  be  integrated  with  another  because  they 
both  feel  themselves  to  belong  together.  -This  kind  of  relationship 
may  be  called  "communal."  But  they  may  be  integrated  because 
both  think  that  their  special  interests  are  facilitated  by  collabora- 
tion—the individual  purposes  of  each  are  thought  to  be  furthered 
by  the  other,  and  each  thus  uses  the  other.  This  kind  of  relationship 
may  be  called  "societal."  Nations  and  families,  religious  orders, 
and  intimate  playgroups  are  generally  communal.  Business  corpo- 

15  The  accountability  of  the  indi\  idual  refers  to  the  ways  in  which  societies 
ascribe  responsibility  to  their  members.  They  may  do  so  ( i )  by  ascribing  the 
acts  of  the  individual  to  a  subcommunity,  and  holding  all  of  its  members 
responsible  for  what  any  single  member  does.  In  such  cases,  we  speak  of 
"joint  responsibility."  Thus,  an  army  officer  may  punish  a  whole  company  for 
the  misconduct  of  one  GI,  a  school  teacher  may  punish  her  school  class  for 
the  misdeeds  of  one  child,  family  clans  in  old  Kentucky  still  engage  in  tlie 
blood  feud,  that  is,  punish  the  family  for  the  behavior  of  one  of  its  members. 
Ancient  Jewry  felt  jointly  responsible  to  angry  and  jealous  Yahweh.  It  has  taken 
Western  civilization  centuries  to  emancipate  the  individual  from  such  joint 
responsibility.  Among  the  forces  involved  have  been  Roman  jurisprudence, 
canonical  law,  revolutionary  movements  of  urban  middle  classes,  the  cumula- 
tive work  of  professional  jurists,  academicians  and  free  intellectuals,  as  weU 
as  all  the  individualizing  social,  intellectual,  and  economic  forces.  All  these 
stand  behind  (2)  a  situation  in  which  no  son  should  be  punished  for  the 
trespasses  of  his  father,  no  parent  for  those  of  their  children,  no  wife  for 
those  of  her  husband.  Indeed,  not  persons  but  specific  acts  of  persons  should 
be  prosecuted  under  due  process  of  law  and  punished  with  pedagogical  or 
preventive  intent  rather  than  in  vengeance  or  annihilative  interest. 

Much  of  the  history  of  legal  technology  in  the  West  is  associated  with  this 
interest  in  ascribing  responsibility  strictly  to  the  individual,  only  to  acts  proven 
to  be  his  by  due  process  of  law.  In  many  other  ways  the  "crisis"  of  our 
times  also  means  a  recession  from  individual  responsibility  in  favor  of  joint 
responsibility.  Peace  treaties  and  their  punitive  stipulations  hold  an  entire 
nation  responsible  for  war.  Thus,  the  Nazis  punish  families  for  the  political 
acts  or  thoughts  of  one  of  its  members.  During  the  late  war,  American-bom 
citizens  of  Japanese  descent  were  placed  behind  barbed  wire.  Thus  citizens 
have  to  prove  their  loyalty  to  authorities,  who  may  discriminate  administra- 
tively against  them  as  a  group,  without  bothering  to  prove  individual  guilt, 
and  without  giving  the  individual  information  about,  nor  occasion  for  defend- 
ing himself  against,  his  civic  disability. 


102  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

rations  and  special  interest  organizations  are  generally  societal. 
There  may,  of  course,  be  elements  of  each  type  present  in  cases 
which  are  placed  under  the  other/ '^ 

Now,  if  a  society  is  predominantly  composed  of  communal  rela- 
tionships, so  that  interpersonal  integrations  throughout  the  person's 
career  are  communal,  there  is  less  chance  of  experiencing  a  gen- 
eralized other  than  if  the  careerline  contains  first  communal  and, 
at  a  later  juncture,  societal  integrations.  The  mechanisms  at  work 
in  this  latter  type  of  biographical  sequence  are  as  follows: 

The  career  of  the  person  will  at  first  be  composed  of  significant 
others  with  whom  he  is  integrated  communally.  Their  harmonious 
expectations  will  coincide  with  his  roles,  and  each  person  will  be 
his  own  end  and  his  own  means.  The  center  of  the  self  will  thus 
coincide  with  the  center  of  social  expectations.  But  at  a  later  stage 
of  his  career,  the  person  will  have  to  integrate  the  self  so  built 
with  societal  others,  and  in  these  societal  integrations  he  will  have 
to  use  these  others— to  be  sure,  under  enforceable  rules— for  his  own 
purposes;  and  he,  in  turn,  will  also  be  used  by  others  for  their 
purposes.  Accordingly,  there  are  more  chances  for  conflicts  be- 
tween others'  expectations  and  the  purposes  of  the  self.  Out  of 
the  calculations  involved  in  successfully  meeting  these  conflicts,  and 
out  of  the  differences  between  the  societal  integrations  and  the 
previously  integrated  communal  roles,  a  generalized  other  may 
emerge. 

V.  All  the  interpersonal  conditions  which  lower  or  raise  the 
chances  for  a  generalized  other  to  develop  are  themselves  facili- 
tated or  restrained  by  broader  conditions  of  social  structure.  When, 
for  example,  the  rate  of  social  change  is  so  low  that  during  their 
careers  the  members  of  one  generation  are  not  aware  of  significant 
changes,  the  career  patterns  of  persons  will  not  significantly  change. 
Hence,  no  conflicting  expectations  arising  from  changing  careers 
are  experienced.  In  such  stable  societies  communal  relations  are 
also  more  likely  to  prevail. 

It  is  also  true  that  where  all  persons  are  on  very  similar  eco- 

!'•  Community  ( Gemeinschaft )  and  society  ( Gesellschaft )  were  invented 
as  technical  terms  by  F.  Tonnies.  See  his  Fundamental  Concepts  of  Sociology, 
C.  P.  Loomis,  tr.  (New  York:  American  Book  Co.,  1940).  See  also  the  twist 
given  these  concepts  by  Max  Weber,  The  Theory  of  Social  and  Economic 
Organization,  A.  M.  Henderson  and  Talcott  Parsons,  trs.  (New  York:  Oxford, 
1947),  P-  136  ff. 


THE     PERSON  10^ 

nomic,  political,  and  social  levels,  the  individual  cannot  easily 
experience  the  drastic  inflation  and  deflation  of  self-image  involved 
in  dramatic  social  ascent  and  descent.  Since  all  positions  involve 
similar  deference,  competition  for  status  position  does  not  exist. 
On  the  other  hand,  somewhat  similar  personal  consequences,  in 
terms  of  our  problem,  may  occur  where  there  is  very  rigid  stratifica- 
tion. For  if  positions  are  fairly  equal  (no  sigiuficant  stratification) 
or  hereditarily  closed  and  endogamous  (rigid  stratification),  the 
careers  of  all  persons  are  likely  to  be  settled  and  known.  In  neither 
case  is  there  competition  for  positions,  or  status  alternatives  be- 
tween different  careerlines.  As  soon  as  the  person  is  old  enough 
to  realize,  he  knows  rather  precisely  what  his  future  will  be,  and 
so  does  everyone  else.  Hence,  the  expectations  exacted  of  him  by 
various  others  are  homogeneous  and  coincide  with  the  person's 
image  of  self,  realized  and  aspired  to. 

But  where  stratification  is  steep  and  open  enough  to  permit 
ascent  and  descent,  the  chances  for  the  development  of  a  gen- 
eralized other  are  increased.  For  then  there  are  likely  alternatives 
between  the  conflicting  expectations  of  various  significant  others, 
along  the  different  careers  open  to  the  person,  and  confronting  him 
in  the  choice  of  positions  for  which  he  may  strive.  It  becomes 
necessary  to  control  the  strivings  for  success  and  to  train  the 
failure  to  "be  a  good  loser." 

When  the  total  society  is  stable,  social  change  being  so  slow 
that  the  members  of  no  one  generation  are  aware  of  it;  and  when 
there  are  no  strata  in  society  or  the  strata  are  absolutely  rigid  and 
fixed  by  level  of  birth— then  the  norms  of  conduct  are  likely  to  be 
positive,  and  the  approved  virtues  to  be  specialized.  This  occurs 
in  Indian  Hindu  society,  hereditary  castes,  or  in  some  periods  of 
feudal  Europe  with  its  legally  privileged  status  groups— its  Chris- 
tian saints  and  kings,  its  lords  and  gentlemen,  its  Christian  burghers 
and  peasants  down  to  its  honorable  prostitutes  and  Christian  hang- 
men. There  is,  thus,  little  opportimity  for  any  given  person  to  face 
the  stri\'ings  of  ascent,  the  discomforts  of  descent,  or  the  insecur- 
ities either  may  involve.  The  image  of  aspiration  coincides  with 
the  image  achieved,  and  in  fact,  there  is  little  awareness  of  such 
a  distinction.  Auguste  Comte  of  nineteenth-century  France  ad- 
mired Indian  caste  society  for  its  excellent  integration,  cohesion, 
and  wondrous  stability. 


104  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

In  summary:  A  strong  conscience  is  likely  to  emerge  when  group 
controls  are  continuous,  rather  than  sporadic,  and  when  they  ex- 
tend over  the  entire  way  of  life,  rather  than  to  only  segments  of 
it.  This  is  most  likely  to  be  the  case  when  the  group's  members 
are  "up  close"  to  one  another  in  everyday  life  and  hence,  as  in  a 
small  community,  know  one  another  well.  It  is  also  likely  to  be 
the  case  when  to  belong  to  the  group  is  prestigeful  or  otherwise 
worthwhile  for  the  member,  as  it  is,  for  example,  for  the  husband 
to  be  a  good  provider,  or  for  the  businessman  to  have  a  good 
credit  rating.  To  be  "a  member  in  good  standing"  must  be  seen 
as  a  competitive  task  for  the  person.  For  example,  he  may  be 
admitted  only  after  investigation  of  his  character  and  his  record, 
threatened  to  be  excluded  for  failure  to  abide  by  the  code.  More- 
over, he  must  gain  the  respect  of  the  group's  members  by  follow- 
ing the  code  in  all  his  roles;  that  is,  the  code  must  be  total.  In  addi- 
tion, all  his  merits  and  demerits,  gained  in  various  roles,  should 
be  ascribed  by  other  group  members  to  the  role  of  the  member 
in  this  group;  it  is  his  master  role  which,  as  it  were,  co-ordinates 
his  motives  for  and  his  enactment  of  roles  in  other  social  areas. 
The  collective  aspirations  of  this  co-ordinate  group,  which  forms 
the  frame  of  reference  for  the  member's  strong  generalized  other, 
should  be  to  subject  the  rest  of  the  world  to  its  standards.  Thus, 
although  it  is  "exclusive,"  it  must  be  actively  exhortative  or  at 
least  exemplary,  seeking  to  extend  its  jurisdiction  or  to  withdraw 
in  exemplary  perfectionism. 

We  may  thus  speculate  about  typological  conditions  for  the  gen- 
eralized other,  but  we  do  not  have  available  the  kind  of  sensitive 
field  and  clinical  observations  necessary  to  discuss  the  matter  in 
full  detail  for  any  given  society.  We  can,  of  course,  apply  general 
conditions  and  mechanisms  to  various  societies  in  an  effort  to  see 
how  they  may  approximate  the  typical  conditions. 

Certain  of  the  conditions  for  the  "particularization  of  conscience" 
seem  to  be  present  in  the  old  Chinese  peasant  village.  We  do  not 
hold  that  the  Chinese  peasant  villager  did  not  have  a  generalized 
other,  but  we  do  suspect  that  his  chances  to  develop  one  beyond 
the  enlarged  kinship  group  were  drastically  minimized  by  the 
roles  which  his  society  laid  down  for  him,  and  that  if  developed,  his 
generalized  other  was  not  a  leading  feature  of  the  person. 

The  peasant  of  classical  China  was  so  bound  to  his  roles,  so 


THE     PERSON  lOg 

closely  tied  to  rigidly  conventionalized  situations  that  the  question 
of  a  center  of  self-expectations  which  would  form  the  basis  of  an 
individuated  self  did  not  typically  arise.  So  the  Chinese  never 
experienced  a  prophetic  salvation  religion  which  might  lead  him 
to  self-repentance  or  train  him  for  feelings  of  personal  guilt.  He 
never  felt  the  need  to  "redeem  the  times  because  the  days  were 
evil."  The  growth  of  an  individualized  conscience  in  the  Occident 
has  been,  to  a  very  large  degree,  the  result  of  Christian  endeavor. 

The  Chinese  peasant  of  course  experienced  occupational,  social, 
and  residential  mobility,  but  he  did  not  experience  any  prophecy 
of  salvation— either  salvation  of  the  individual  soul  or  of  a  suffering 
people.  Therefore  no  ethical  code  shattered  magic  practices  and 
ancestor  worship.  He  was  forever  bound  to  his  extended  family, 
wherever  and  however  high  he  managed  to  climb.  His  successes 
and  failures,  no  matter  how  competitively  won,  were  not  "counted 
to  his  righteousness"  but  to  the  honor  or  blame  of  his  family  name. 
The  multiplicity  of  functional  deities  and  the  ritualistic  magical 
techniques  which  were  professionally  offered  in  the  market  for  pay 
provided  no  central   and  unified  anchorage   for  an  ethical  code. 

It  is  also  significant  for  our  problem— the  conditions  under  which 
the  generalized  other  is  minimized— that  the  significant  others  of 
the  peasant's  childhood  phase,  his  extended  kinship  group,  re- 
mained predominant  among  his  significant  others  until  he  died. 
This  continuity  of  homogeneous  expectations  throughout  his  life 
was  extended  by  the  cult  of  ancestor  worship.  Elaborate  polite- 
ness and  the  "conventional  lie"  were  socially  secured  and  enforced 
patterns;  they  reinforced  the  stability  and  harmony  of  the  expecta- 
tions exacted  of  him.  They  enabled  persons  to  avoid  shaming  one 
another,  that  is,  from  presenting  an  image  of  self  to  the  person 
which  would  conflict  with  his  self-image.  The  conduct  of  the  per- 
son could  thus  be  controlled  by  prudence  and  fear,  but  not  by 
the  internalized  expectations  of  self  which  we  know  as  the  gen- 
eralized other. 

A  man  would  accept  another  as  significant  only  if  this  other  was 
a  member  of  his  sib  and  local  in-group.  People  from  outside  these 
circles,  such  as  an  imperial  tax  collector,  had  to  perform  their  work 
without  benefit  of  tax  morality  on  the  part  of  the  peasant:  tax 
collecting  involved  raids  and  flogging. 

Were  we  to  develop  our  point  in  detail  we  would  have  to  con- 
sider the  different  sequences  of  roles  played  by  men  as  compared 


106  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

with  women,  and  of  both  men  and  women  reared  in  households 
owning  different  quantities  of  land,  and  so  on.  The  order  of  birth 
of  the  siblings  and  their  sex  would  also  claim  our  attention. 

We  should  seek  interpersonal  conditions  typical  of  Chinese  so- 
ciety which  would  favor  or  disfavor  the  development  and  opera- 
tions of  a  generalized  other.  For  instance,  when  a  woman  was 
married  she  went  to  live  in  the  husband's  family  abode  and  took 
the  role  of  a  daughter  to  his  parents.  The  man  stayed  at  home 
after  his  marriage  and,  although  the  wife  became  one  of  his  others, 
her  significance  was  precisely  conventionalized,  just  as  were  the 
expectations  she  exacted  of  the  husband.  The  woman,  however, 
changed  households  and  thus  came  into  a  new  circle  of  significant 
others.  If  the  expectations  exacted  of  her  were  drastically  shifted 
at  this  juncture,  we  might  expect  her  to  become  aware  of  these 
conflicts  and  out  of  them  to  strengthen  her  generalized  other. 
Operating  against  this  was  the  fact  that  the  pattern  of  her  parental 
family  was  probably  very  similar  to  that  of  her  husband's.  Because 
of  the  conventional  similarity  of  family  integrations,  the  expecta- 
tions along  her  careerline  were  harmonious,  and  thus  permitted  a 
ready  transfer,  or  substitution,  of  one  circle  of  significant  others  for 
a  previous  circle. 

6.  Types  of  Persons 

When  we  speak  of  types  of  persons  we  do  not  mean  types  of 
character  structure.  Of  course,  any  conduct  regularly  perfomied 
by  the  person  doubtless  involves  the  integration  df  his  roles  with 
components  of  his  psychic  structure;  nevertheless,  by  types  of  per- 
son we  mean  only  the  variations  of  roles  which  compose  the  per- 
son, and  the  person's  way  of  reacting  to  these  roles.  Here  are 
three  dimensions  in  terms  of  which  types  of  persons  may  be  con- 
structed: 

I.  If  in  all  his  social  relations,  a  person  is  subordinate— a  sub- 
ordinate bureaucrat,  a  henpecked  husband,  a  docile  newspaper 
reader,  a  willing  soldier,  a  gullible  consumer,  or  an  avaricious 
absorber  of  advertisements— we  may  say  that  from  a  formal  point 
of  view  this  type  of  person  is  unified.  This  means  that  we  can 
state  a  principle— submissiveness— which  seems  to  underlie  all  of 
his  reactions  to  the  roles  expected  of  him.  Other  persons,  who  react 


THE     PERSON  lO"/ 

differently  to  their  own  roles,  might  consider  such  a  man  a  dupe 
or  a  "sucker";  by  still  others  this  term  of  opprobrium  might  be 
sophisticated  into  the  term  "conformity  neurotic,"  while  for  still 
others,  and  perhaps  for  the  man  himself,  this  type  might  be  sup- 
posed to  represent  "Christian  humility,"  as  the  man  willingly  shoul- 
ders all  the  crosses  which  others  and  he  himself  place  upon  his 
back.  / 

If  in  all  his  social  relations  a  person  is  domineering— self-assertive 
on  his  job,  a  tyrant  of  his  family,  a  critical  newspaper  reader,  a 
scoffer  at  advertisements-^we  may  also  say  that  he  is  unified.  The 
principle  of  his  unity  is  that  of  domination,  which  all  his  conduct 
and  feeling  seem  to  follow.  He  is  a  imified  person,  and  if  he  is 
not  a  unified  character  structure  he  may  become  such  should  he 
continue  to  enact  roles  according  to  the  unifying  principle  of  his 
person. 

L  There  are,  on  the  other  hand,  types  of  persons  who  have  ex- 
tremely diverse  reactions  to  various  roles.  A  man  who  is  a  self- 
assertive  authority  on  the  astronomical  movements  of  the  universe 
may,  in  the  smaller  orbit  of  his  family  circle,  be  a  mere  satellite 
of  his  wife.  The  subordinated  and  ingratiating  peddler  who  has 
doors  slammed  in  his  smiling  face  all  day  may  himself  slam  doors 
all  the  more  viciously  as  his  family  trembles  in  fear.  These  types 
of  persons  seem  to  make  up  in  one  context  what  they  give  up  in 
another.  By  exploiting  their  chances  at  self-assertion  in  one  role, 
they  "compensate"  for  the  frustrations  inflicted  upon  them  in  an- 
other. The  organization  which  connects  their  reaction  to  one  role 
with  that  to  another  is  a  network  of  compensations,  and  with  this 
principle  they  achieve  a  sort  of  balance. "^ 

II.  The  reactions  of  a  person  to  the  requirements  of  a  role  may 
be  classified  in  terms  of  the  role's  powers  to  make  him  feel  re- 
stricted, or,  on  the  other  hand,  anxious  that  he  cannot  meet  the 
expectations  upon  him. 

A  man  may  feel  restricted  in  playing  certain  roles;  he  may  not 
be  able  "to  place"  all  his  energies,  push,  and  drive  within  the  con- 
ventionalized expectations  fiis  roles  require.  The  image  of  self 
reflected  from  other  roles  (currently  and  previously  enacted)  may 
conflict  with  the  image  reflected  from  enactment  of  the  restricting 
role.  Hence,  the  person  cannot  "put  his  all"  into  their  enactment,  ^ 
for  by  doing  so  he  would  be  damaging  his  own  image  of  self.  Or 


lo8  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

some  component  of  his  psychic  structure,  whkh  had  been  socially 
channeled,  may  now  be  blocked  by  this  role. /Hence,  as  the  person 
strives  to  perform  it,  this  role  restricts  his  accustomed  impulses 
and  emotions.  Or,  his  feeling  of  restriction  may  be  due  to  am- 
bition: the  referral  of  his  self  to  larger  tasks  ahead  by  anticipation. 
"^On  the  other  hand,  the  person  may  feel  that  in  performing* a 
certain  role  he  must  do  his  very  utmost  in  order  to  satisfy  its 
requirements.  This  reaction  may  arise  from  the  fact  that  others 
involved  in  the  role  are  very  significant,  yet  their  expectations  are, 
from  the  person's  standpoint,  very  hard  to  meet.  Enactment  of  the 
role  may,  for  instance,  require  energies  and  habits  which  his  or- 
ganism is  not  capable  of  developing,  or  it  may  require  a  type  of 
temperament  which  his  psychic  integration  does  not  enable  him  to 
develop,  or  again,  it  may  be  that  he  does  not  have  the  education 
or  intelligence  to  meet  the  demands.  Yet,  since  they  are  very 
significant  to  him,  he  continues  to  try,  and  hence  he  continually 
feels  the  strain.  It  is  also  possible  that  he  is  a  "perfectionist"  and 
thus  holds  an  exaggerated  view  of  the  role  demands  exacted  of 
him,  even  if  others  encourage  him  to  "take  it  easy." 
(jHEither  incongruity— the  restricting  or  the  straining  role— may  lead 
to  personal  dissatisfaction; -in  either  case,  frustration  and  anxiety 
may  result.  These  mechanisms  may,  of  course,  operate  in  any 
role  context— in  the  home  no  less  than  in  the  diplomatic  confer- 
ence. 

(^III.  However  similar  different  men's  external  reactions  to  the 
requirements  of  their  roles  may  seem,  they  may,  in  truth,  have 
internalized  different  roles  in  quite  varying  degrees.  The  image 
of  self  reflected  from  one  significant  circle  may  be  so  satisfactory 
that  men  do  not  accept  the  significance  conventionally  assigned  to 
appraisals  by  other  circles. 

A  professional  man,  for  example,  may  be  so  absorbed  in  his 
work,  and  be  so  satisfied  with  the  self-image  reflected  by  his  col- 
leagues that  his  love  life  may  remain  quite  undeveloped,  his  reac- 
tions to  it  remaining  quite  stereotyped.  Such  men  are  among  those 
who  at  the  age  of  sixty  speak  to  their  wives  in  the  same  flowery 
vocabulary  of  romance  that  was  current  in  their  high  school  days. 
On  the  other  hand,  a  man  may  dedicate  his  life  to  his  intimate 
other,  whom  he  has  "chosen  from  all  the  world,"  and  she  may  be 
the  center  of  his  life  and  of  his  person.  His  occupation  may  thus 


THE     PERSON  lOQ 

be  a  mere  means  of  economic  support  for  her,  and  for  himself.  It 
may  be  that  when  one  has  no  such  intimate  other,  he  will  be  all 
the  more  sensitive  to  the  appraisals  of  his  professional  role,  since 
it  is  the  deepest  internalized;]  then  those  who  are  significant  to 
him  in  this  role  will  form  the  social  basis  for  his  central  self- 
expectations.  But  if  we  were  to  take  any  one  type  of  role,  say  the 
occupational,  and  attempt  to  classify  persons  solely  in  terms  of 
that  one  type,  we  should  fail  to  grasp  what  is  essential  to  the  kind 
of  man  whose  job  is  merely  a  means  of  support  and  not  significant 
to  his  self-image  and  personal  integration. 

Roles,  we  know,  may  be  segments  of  various  institutions  and  at 
the  same  time  components  of  persons. --The  relationship  between 
different  roles  may  be  construed  as  a  scheme  of  means  and  ends.j 
Certain  political  roles  or  family  roles,  for  example,  may  be  enacted 
in  order  to  achieve  or  facilitate  ends  which  lie  in  other  institutional 
orders.  [Now,  the  integration  of  the  roles  which  compose  a  given 
person  may  also  be  grasped  in  terms  of  such  a  means-end  scheme. 
If,  for  example,  political  ends  are  all  that  matter  to  a  man,  he 
may  act  the  role  of  the  clerk  only  in  order  to  make  money  in  order 
to  have  pamphlets  printed  in  behalf  of  a  political  movement.  His 
personality  is  integrated  around  his  political  role,  and  the  other  j 
roles  he  has  incorporated  facilitate  this  political  role.  The  signifi-  ^ 
cances  of  family  and  of  occupational  others  are  instrumental,  and     i 
his  image  of  self  and  his  conscience  are  primarily  reflections  of  his     \ 
political  others., 

Suppose,  on  the  other  hand,  a  professional  career  is  the  most 
significant  basis  for  a  man's  self-image;  then  he  may  be  willing  to 
play  the  role  of  the  husband  in  order  to  secure  a  typist.  Or  a 
woman  may  be  willing  to  play  the  role  of  a  wife  because  this 
role  guarantees  her  membership  in  the  household  of  a  man  who 
is  a  good  provider  and  whose  position  enables  her  to  borrow 
prestige. 

TjOf  course,  the  person— as  built  of  roles  and  of  his  reactions  to 
them— is  not  the  complete  character  structure.  The  psychic  struc- 
ture, as  we  have  seen,  is  linked  with  the  person,  and  the  two,  along 
with  the  organism,  form  the  dynamic  whole  of  character.  As  we 
have  just  seen,  one  type  of  person  may  be  more  or  less  dominated 
by  a  key  role,  which  is  thus  the  hub  of  his  character.  But  there  is 
also  the  contrasting  type  of  person  in  which  no  one  role  predomi- 
nates^^In  all  post-Renaissance   societies,   for  example,   the  upper 


110  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

classes  have  produced  certain  models  of  representative  men.  The 
British  gentleman,  the  Italian  cortegiano,  the  French  cavalier— 
these  are  images  of  men  who  are  7iot  dominated  by  any  one  role, 
but  rather  maintain  a  certain  distance  from  all  roles,  even  while 
playing  them  all  with  proficiency.  Such  excellent  performances 
would  seem  possible  only  when  the  demand  for  special  skills  is 
not  too  rigorous.  Whether  they  involve  generalship  or  erotical  con- 
quest, statesmanship  or  economic  bargaining,  their  contexts  must 
be  sufficiently  personalized  to  permit  what  nowadays  would  seem 
amateurish.  The  images  of  such  representative  men,  including  as 
they  do  psychic  elements  as  well  as  external  demeanor,  transcend 
any  one  role,  and  yet  enable  men  to  play  all  the  roles  required 
by  their  social  position. 

There  is  also  what  may  be  called  the  experimental  man,  who 
like  Saint-Simon,  takes  up,  one  after  the  other,  many  roles,  and 
puts  the  whole  force  of  his  character  into  each  of  them  in  turn. 
Such  a  man  does  not  try  to  integrate  himself  in  terms  of  all  these 
roles,  but  rather  to  conquer  all  of  them  and  to  be  above  any  one 
of  them.  Thus  Bismarck  asked:  "Why  should  I  be  a  harmonious 
personality?"  ^^ 

In  the  analysis  of  institutional  orders  and  social  structures,  one 
encounters  many  types  of  persons,  integrated  with  roles  in  various 
degrees  and  in  various  ways.  The  discernment  of  such  types,  in 
fact,  is  a  major  part  of  the  social  psychology  of  institutions.  For 
the  perscinjs_related— to  society  by  the  roles  he  acquires.  These 
ToTes,  in  turn,  are  related  to  his  psychic  structure,  primarily  by  the 
language  of  his  group.  The  acquisition  of  language  requires  a  cer- 
tain kind  of  organic  equipment,  but  the  function  of  language  is 
to  co-ordinate  the  social  activities  and  roles  which  the  person 
enacts,  for  it  is  primarily  by  means  of  language  that  we  learn 
what  is  expected  of  us  in  all  the  varied  roles  we  play. 

©ur  images  of  our  self  are  facilitated  and  restrained  by  the  ex- 
pectations of  others;  we  are  sensitive  to  the  expectations  of  those 
who  are  most  significant  to  us.  But  oiir  selection  of  significant 
others  is  limited  by  our  positions  in  the  varied  institutions  of  which 

!''■  Alfred  von  Martin,  Sociology  of  the  Renaissance  (New  York:  Oxford, 
1944),  P-  95- 


THE     PERSON  111 

we  are  members.  Within  these  institutional  Hmits,  however,  we 
will  generally  turn  towards  those  whom  we  believe  will  confirm 
the  desired  image  we  would  have  of  our  self.  And,  if  others'  ex- 
pectations and  images  of  us  are  contrary  to  our  desired  image,  we 
will  try  to  reject  them,  and  seek  only  confirmation  among  more 
congenial  others. 

Our  unity  of  self— the  secure  feeling  of  what  we  really  are— 
ideally  occurs  when  the  various  images  of  our  self— held  by  us 
and  by  others— are  in  some  way  reconcilable.  In  some  societies, 
all  the  roles  we  play  are  stereotyped,  so  that  it  is  easy  for  us 
to  experience  unity  of  self.  In  other  societies,  there  is  no  set  pat- 
tern, and  we  spend  much  of  our  life  trying  to  get  the  images  we 
hold  of  our  self  confirmed  by  others. 

Our  conscience— the  generalized  other  or  superego— is  the  prod- 
uct of  all  expectations  of  significant  others  in  our  life  history.  Many 
of  these  expectations  are  internalized  during  our  childhood,  and    . 
are  below  the  level  of  our  awareness;  hence,  in  later  life,  as  we 4^ 
become   sensitive   to   new   significant   others,   we   often   encounter 
conflicts  of  conscience.  Social  conflicts  among  the  expectations  and  I 
demands  of  various  significant  others  thus  become  conflicts  within 
the  person.  The  consciences  of  men  can  only  be  similar  in  so  far 
as  they  have  experienced  similar  types  of  significant  others.  And, 
as  we  have  shown,  not  all  human  beings  have  a  strong  conscience. 

Types  of  persons  can  be  deduced  from  the  various  roles  that 
different  persons  play  and  the  various  ways  they  react  to  those 
roles.  They  may  make  up  for  restriction  in  one  role  by  aggressive 
activity  in  another;  they  may  expend  more  energy  in  some  roles 
than  in  others;  and,  even  though  one  person  may  seem  to  play 
a  role  in  a  similar  way  to  another,  he  may  have  internalized  this 
role  in  his  psychic  structure  very  differently.  Accordingly,  the 
similar  objective  social  role  may  carry  very  different  meaning  in 
his  character  structure.  In  order  to  understand  types  of  persons, 
we  must  know  something  of  the  motivations  which  prompt  the 
acquisition  and  the  enactment  of  various  roles.  ^' 


CHAPTER 

V 


The  Sociology  of  Motivation 


OUR  threefold  division  of  character  structure  enables  us  to  set 
forth  three  theories  of  motivation.  We  can  locate  the  center  of 
motivation  primarily  in  the  organism,  in  the  psychic  structure,  or 
in  the  person. 

On  the  level  of  the  organism,  we  might  assume  that  "all  organic 
processes  are  initiated  by  the  need  to  restore  a  physio-chemical 
equilibrium  which  is  experienced  as  health." 

In  terms  of  the  psychic  structure  we  might  assume  that  "psycho- 
logical processes  are  initiated  by  the  need  to  restore  an  emotional 
equilibrium  which  is   experienced  as  pleasure."  ^ 

In  terms  of  the  person,  we  might  assume  that  conduct  is  mo- 
tivated by  the  expectations  of  others,  which  are  internalized  from 
the  roles  which  persons  enact,  and  that  important  aspects  of  such 
motivation  are  the  vocabularies  of  motive  which  are  learned  and 
used  by  persons  in  various  roles.  Motivation  thus  has  to  do  with 
the  balance  of  self-image  with  the  appraisals  of  others. 

1.  The  Sociological  Approach 

When  motivation  is  viewed  on  the  level  of  the  organism,  the 
processes  and  elements  of  the  psychic  structure  are  likely  to  be 
seen  as  mere  epiphenomena,  or  at  best,  means  to  the  attainment 
of  some  physiological  condition.  On  the  other  hand,  many  who, 

1  These  two  quotations  paraphrase  the  positions  of  the  physiologist,  W.  B. 
Cannon,  and  of  the  psychologist,  Sigmund  Freud,  respectively.  They  are 
from  Ives  Hendrick,  Facts  and  Theories  of  Psychoanalysis  (2d  ed.;  New  York: 
Knopf,  1944),  pp.  206  ff.  See  W.  B.  Cannon,  The  Wisdom  of  the  Human 
Body  (New  York:  Norton,  1932),  pp.  306  ff.  The  formal  similarity  of  the 
two  writers  is  the  more  striking  when  we  realize  that  they  worked  inde- 
pendently of  each  other  and  used  very  different  methods. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  II3 

like  Freud,  consider  the  psychic  structure  as  a  fairly  autonomous 
and  somewhat  closed  system,  ascribe  what  they  cannot  otherwise 
explain  to  "the  constitution"  of  the  organism.  "Organism"  is  thus 
used  as  a  residual  category  to  "explain"  what  cannot  otherwise  be 
explained.  Operating  on  either  of  these  two  levels,  the  impact  of 
the  social  roles  of  the  person  upon  the  psychic  structure  and 
organism  is  minimized  or  omitted. 

For  Freud,  the  psychic  structure;-^ "drives")  may  be  socially 
canalized,  but  is  not  itself  subject  to  basic  social  modifications. 
The  concept  of  "sublimation,"  for  instance,  implies  that  role-con- 
ditioned forms  of  psychic  drives  are  epiphenomena  of  "the  basic 
drives."  These  "real  drives"  are  assumed  somehow  to  lie  in  the 
psychic  structure  or  in  the  constitution  of  the  organism.  The  split 
between  man's  primordial  biological  nature  and  man's  cultured 
personality  is  thus  retained  and  a  metaphysical  accent  is  placed 
upon  the  biological  or  the  psychic  level.  Emotions,  urges,  or  vari- 
ous physiological  processes  are  "the  real"  motivating  factors  of 
conduct;  the  rest  is  sham,  or  at  any  rate  distorted  and  ungenuine 
expressions  of  the  real  motives  of  the  'tear' individual.^ 


If  we  drop  this''metaphysical  *accent  on  the  biological  and  the 
psychic  and  treat  the  person  as  just  as  "real"  as,  and  in  many  ways 
more  important  than,  the  organism  and  the  psychic  structure,  we 
are  able  to  enlarge  our  conception  of  motivation.  Although  we 
shall  give  due  weight  to  organic  and  psychic  factors  of  motivation, 
we  shall  approach  the  topic  primarily  in  terms  of  the  person: 

It  should  be  clear  from  previous  chapters  that  by  "the  prob- 
lem of  motivation"  we  mean  the  understanding  and  explaining  of 
why  and  how  human  conduct  takes  a  specific  direction.  It  is  a 
problem  of  steered  conduct  rather  than  a  problem  of  motive  power. 
And  we  stand  a  better  chance  of  solving  this  problem  in  terms 
of  the  person  than  in  terms  of  the  unsocialized  organism  or  psychic 
structure. 

Moreover,  only  on  the  level  of  the  person  can  we  expect  to  deal 
with  understandable  motives.  The  restoral  of  the  organic  equilib- 
rium of  health  or  the  impulsive  squirmings  of  emotional  balance 
experienced  as  pleasure  are  not  understandable  in  terms  of  the 

2  The  new  psychoanalysis  of  Karen  Homey  and  Erich  Fromm,  e.g.,  has  not 
succeeded  in  entirely  o\ercoming  Freud's  biological  metaphysic.  See  below, 
this  section. 


iij^  character    structure 

organism  or  the  psychic  structure  as  such.  Motives  may  be  ex- 
plained in  part  in  terms  of  these  levels,  but  they  cannot  be  under- 
stood.-It  is  clear  that  when  we  speak  of  understandable  motives 
or  intentions,  we  must  pay  attention  to  the  social  function  of 
language  in  interpersonal  conduct;  we  can  speak  of  understanding 
something  only  if  it  is  meaningful,  and  language,  a  social  acquisi- 
tion and  a  personal  performance,  is  the  prime  carrier  of  meaning. 
Even  dreams  have  to  be  deciphered  or  interpreted  as  a  language 
of  "unconscious  impulses." 

We  have  also  seen  that  the  organism  is  relevant  to  our  under- 
standing of  conduct  and  character  only  when  its  effects  are  me- 
diated by  the  social  evaluations  of  other  persons;  and  that  the 
impulses,  emotions,  and  perceptions  of  the  psychic  structure  are 
patterned  and  channeled  by  the  social  organization  of  the  person. 
"^Therefore,  insofar  as  the  organism  and  psychic  structure  enter  into 
understandable  motivations,  they  may  be  most  readily  and  signifi- 
cantly grasped  in  terms  of  the  person,  for  it  is  in  such  terms  that 
emotional  or  organic  equilibria  are  organized  and  attained.— 

The  person  acting  out  his  roles  in  various  situations  is  the 
most  immediately  observable  aspect  of  character  structure.  Al- 
though, like  the  psychic  structure  and  the  organism,  the  person  is 
an  abstraction  with  which  we  conceive  one  aspect  of  the  total 
reality  of  man,  it  is  that  aspect  which  is  typically  what-is-to-be- 
explained-and-understood.  In  ordinary  life  situations  we  do  not 
deal  directly  with  the  psychic  structure  or  with  the  organism.  We 
deal  with  these  indirectly,  often  without  being  aware  of  doing  so; 
we  deal  with  them  as  they  manifest  themselves  in  man  as  he  pre- 
sents himself  to  us,  and  he  presents  himself  as  a  social  person. 

Our  "final"  theory  should  be  a  model  within  which  we  can  locate 
M:he  other  theories,  which  is  adequate  to  everyday  experience  and 
to  known  data,  and  which  allows  and  even  suggests  lines  of  reflec- 
tion that  are  open  to  research  test. 

2.  Vocabularies  of  Motive 

Motives  are  generally  thought  of  as  subjective  "springs"  of  ac- 
tion lying  in  the  psychic  structure  or  organism  of  the  individual. 
But  there  is  another  way  to  think  of  them.  Since  persons  do 
ascribe  motives  to  themselves  and  to  other  persons,— ^ve  may  con- 
sider motives  as  the  terms  which  persons  typically  use  in  their 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  11^ 

interpersonal  relations^To  explain  some  line  of  conduct  by  re- 
ferring it  to  an  inferred  and  abstracted  motive  or  to  some  psychic 
element  is  one  thing;  to  observe  the  function  of  motive  imputation 
and  avowal  in  certain  types  of  social  situations  is  quite  another.^ 

We  have  already  seen  that  we  cannot  treat  "desires"  at  large  as 
motives,  and  yet,  since  persons  do  talk  about  their  own  and  others' 
desires  in  this  way,  we  cannot  afford  to  ignore  them.  These  avowals 
and  ascriptions  of  motives— the  differing  reasons  men  give  for  their 
actions— are  not  themselves  without  bases.  Rather  than  throw 
these  reasons  aside  as  "mere  rationalizations, "  we  may  use  them  in 
understanding  why  men  act  as  they  do. 

^Avowals  and  imputations  of  motives  seem  to  arise  in  interper- 
sonal situations  in  which  "purposes"  are  vocalized  and  carried  out 
with  close  reference  to  the  speech  and  actions  of  others;  in  situa- 
tions in  which  one's  conduct  or  intentions  are  questioned  by  other 
men  or  by  one's  selfr-We  tend  to  ask  questions  in  situations  which 
in\'ol\e  alternative  or  unexpected  purposes  or  conduct.  Sometimes 
we  refer  to  such  situations  as  crises,  however  minor  they  may  be. 
Men  live  in  immediate  acts  of  experience  and  their  attention  is 
directed  outside  themselves— until  their  conduct  is  in  some  way 
frustrated  or  fails  to  receive  an  expected  response  from  others. 
Then  there  is  awareness,  questioning  by  others,  self-questioning, 
and  justifications  to  others  and  to  self.  And  it  is  then  that  state- 
ments of  motive  perform  their  important  function. 

Conversations  may  be  about  the  facts  of  a  situation  as  they  are 
seen  by  the  participants,  or  they  may  be  attempts  on  the  part  of 
various  persons  to  co-ordinate  social  conduct.^  By  means  of  con- 
versation, different  roles  are  geared  to  patterns  of  expectations, 
but  when  a  person  does  not  respond  to  the  expectations  of  signifi- 
cant others,  he  will  typically  begin  to  explain  or  justify  his  own 
conduct.*JSJow  it  is  in  such  conversations  that  statements  of  motive 
are  often  brought  into  operation.  The  function  of  such  statements 

•'■  For  a  preliminary  statement  of  the  point  of  \iew  expressed  here,  see 
C.  Wright  Mills,  "Situated  Actions  and  Vocabularies  of  Motive,"  American 
Sociological  Review  (October  1940).  Cf.  K.  Burke,  Permanence  and  Cliange 
(New  York:  The  New  Republic,  1935). 

^  On  the  "question"  and  on  "con\  ersation,"  see  Grace  De  Laguna,  Speech: 
If.s  Fnnction  and  Development  (New  Haven:  Yale  Univ.  Press,  1927), 
p.  37.  For  motives  in  "Crises,"  see  J.  M.  WiUiams,  The  Foundations  of  Social 
Science   (New  York;  Knopf,   1920),  pp.  435  ft. 


Il6  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

is  to  persuade  others  to  accept  our  act,  to  urge  them  to  respond 
to  it  as  we  expect  them  to,  and  to  make  them  beHeve  that  our  act 
sprang  from  "good  intentions." 

Sociologicallyr  as  Max  Weber  put  it,  a  motive  is  a  term  in  a 
vocabulary  which  appears  to  the  actor  himself  and/or  to  the  ob- 
server to  be  an  adequate  reason  for  his  conduct-.^ This  conception 
grasps  the  intrinsically  social  character  of  motivation:  a  satisfac- 
tory or  adequate  motive  is  one  that  satisfies  those  who  question 
some  act  or  program,  whether  the  actor  questions  his  own  or  an- 
other's conduct.  The  words  which  may  fulfill  this  function  are 
limited  to  the  vocabulary  of  motives  acceptable  for  given  situa- 
tions by  given  social  circles. 

Conceived  in  this  wayr-«iotives  are  acceptable  justifications  for 
present,  future,  or  past  programs  of  conduct,— But  to  call  them 
^■'  "justification"  is  not  to  deny  their  efficacy;  it  is  merely  to  indicate 
L  their  function  in  conduct.  Only  by  narrowing  our  view  to  the  point 
where  we  see  the  isolated  individual  as  a  closed  system,  can  we 
treat  verbalized  motives  as  "mere  justifications."  By  examining  the 
social  function  of  motives,  we  are  able  to  grasp  just  what  role  mo- 
tives may  perform  in  the  social  conduct  of  individuals.  We  know 
that  even  in  purely  rational  calculations  acceptable  justifications 
may  play  a  rather  large  role.  Thus,  we  may  reason,  "If  I  did  this, 
what  could  I  say?  And  what  would  they  then  say  or  do?"  Deci- 
sions to  perform  or  not  to  perform  a  given  act  may  be  wholly  or  in 
part  set  by  the  socially  available  answers  to  such  queries. 

But  the  problem  of  the  social  function  of  motives  goes  deeper. 
A  man  may  begin  an  act  for  one  motive;  in  the  course  of  this  act 
he  may  adopt  an  auxiliary  motive  which  he  will  use  to  explain  his 
act  to  others  who  question  it,  or  whom  he  feels  may  question  it  in 
the  future.  The  use  of  this  second  motive  as  an  apology  does  not 
make  it  inefficacious  as  a  factor  in  his  conduct.-4n  such  after-the- 
event  explanations  we  often  appeal  to  an  acceptable  vocabulary  of 
motives,  associated  with  expectations  with  which  the  members  of 
the  situation  are  in  agreement^-Accordingly,  our  statement  of  mo- 
tive serves  to  integrate  social  conduct,  in  that  the  reasons  we  give 
for  an  act  are  among  the  conditions  for  its  continued  performance. 
By  winning  allies  for  our  activities  the  motives  we  verbalize  may 

•"'  The  Theory  of  Social  and  Economic  Organization,  A.  M.  Henderson  and 
Talcott  Parsons,  trs.  (New  York:  Oxford,  1947),  Chapter  1. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  llj 

even  be  controlling  conditions  for  the  activity's  successful  perform- 
ance. And  by  winning  social  acceptance,  such  motives  often 
strengthen  our  own  will  to  act.  For  the  performance  of  many  roles 
requires  the  agreement  of  others,  and  if  no  reason  can  be  ad- 
\  anced  which  is  acceptable  to  these  others,  such  acts  may  be  aban- 
doned. Diplomacy  in  the  choice  of  motives  thus  controls  the  con- 
duct of  the  diplomatic  actor.  Strategic  choice  of  motive  is  part  of 
the  attempt  to  motivate  the  act  for  the  other  persons  involved  in 
our  conduct.  Carefully  chosen  and  publicized  motives  often  re- 
solve social  conflicts,  potential  and  real,  and  thus  effectively  in- 
tegrate and  release  social  patterns  of  conduct. 

""-When  a  person  confesses  or  imputes  motives,  he  is  not  usually 
trying  to  describe  his  social  conduct,  he  is  not  merely  stating  rea- 
sons for  it-r^Iore  usually  he  is  trying  to  influence  others,  to  find 
new  reasons  which  will  mediate  the  enactment  of  his  role— and  in 
so  trying  to  influence  others,  he  may  often  influence  himself.  The 
verbalization  of  motives  for  an  act  is  itself  a  new  act;  it  is  a  phase 
of  role  playing  which  lines  up  the  role  with  or  against  the  expec- 
tations of  others.  In  such  cases,  accordingly,  it  is  not  necessarily 
wise  to  seize  upon  the  differences  between  the  conduct  and  the 
verbalization  as  a  discrepancy  between  action  and  speech.  There 
is  simply  a  difference  between  two  kinds  of  action,  one  verbal,  one 
motor. 

In  terms  of  motives,  cqnceiyed^s  acceptable  groimds.^ 
action^  persons  will  alter,  deter,  or  reinforce  their  individual  con- 
duct. To  speak,  for  instance,  of  someone  as  having  "scruples"  is 
of  course  to  indicate  a  complex  type  of  internal  behavior,  but  one 
index  to  it  is  that  a  moral  vocabulary  of  moti\  es  is  effective  in 
controlling  their  conduct. 

In  the  course  of  our  biography,  our  motives  are  imputed  to  us 
by  others  before  they  are  avowed  by  ourselves.^Such  vocabularies 
of  motive  then  become  components  of  our  generalized  other;  they 
are  internalized  by  the  person  and  operate  as  mechanisms  of  so- 
cial control. -^hus  the  mother  controls  her  child  by  imputing  mo- 
tives to  him;  by  having  certain  actions  called  "greedy"  and  others 
"good,"  the  child  learns  what  conduct  he  may  perform  with  ap- 
proval; and  he  learns  what  he  cannot  get  away  with  socially.  He 
is  also  given  standardized  motives  which  sanction  and  promote 
some  acts  by  placing  a  public  premium  on  them,  and  which  dis- 


Il8  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

suade  or  prohibit  him  from  other  acts  by  pubhcly  disapproving 
them. 

Along  with  the  conduct  patterns  appropriate  for  various  occa- 
sions, we  learn  their  appropriate  motives,  and  these  are  the  mo- 
tives we  will  use  in  dealing  with  others  and  with  ourselves.  The 
motives  we  use  to  justify  or  to  criticize  an  act  thus  link  our  con- 
duct with  that  of  significant  others,  and  line  up  our  conduct  with 
the  standardized  expectations,  often  backed  up  by  sanctions,  that 
we  call  norms.  Such  words  may  function  as  directives  and  incen- 
tives: they  are  the  judgments  of  others  as  anticipated  by  the  actor. 

Accordingly,  when  new  roles  are  taken  on,  old  motives  may  need 
to  be  modified  or  new  motives  learned.  For  new  motives  may  be 
conditions  for  the  enactment  of  new  roles.  Wejcoatrol  another  man   .' 
by  manipulating  the  premiums  which  the  other  accepts;  we  influ-  L 
ence  a  man  by  naming  his  act  in  terms  of  some  motive  which  we    ; 
ascribe  to  him.  /  _ 

Vocabularies  of  motives  have  histories,  as  their  various  institu- 
tional contexts  undergo  historical  change.  The  motives  accom- 
panying the  institutional  conduct  of  war  are  not  "the  causes  of 
war,"  but  they  do  promote  continued  participation  in  warfare, 
and  they  do  vary  from  one  war  to  the  next.  For  vocabularies  of 
motive  are  modified,  as  the  institutions  in  which  they  are  anchored 
undergo  change. 

Examine  the  shift  from  the  laissez-faire  to  the  monopolistic  phase 
of  modern  capitalism.  The  profit  motive  of  individual  gain  may  be 
widely  espoused  and  accepted  by  businessmen  during  a  relatively 
prosperous  and  free  economic  era,  but  such  commercial  vocabu- 
laries of  motive  may  undergo  severe  modifications  during  monopo- 
listic phases  of  the  economy.  For  then,  a  vocabulary  of  public 
service  and  efficiency  may  be  added  to  the  public  motives  of  busi- 
nessmen. Now,  if  a  man  finds  himself  unable  to  engage  in  business 
conduct  without  joining  a  "liberal"  business  organization  and 
proclaiming  its  public-spirited  vocabulary,  it  follows  that  this 
particular  vocabulary  of  motives  is  an  important  reinforcing  fea- 
ture of  his  social  conduct. 

The  choice  of  a  motive  which  is  ascribed  to  some  conduct  pat- 
tern reflects  the  institutional  position  of  the  actor  and^pf  those 
who  ascribe  motives  to  him.  For  example,  the  vocabulary  of  mo- 
tives used  by  privileged  groups  for  the  conduct  of  persons  in  minor- 
ity groups  is  different  from  the  motives  used  for  members  of  high 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  lig 

prestige  groups.  "Aggressiveness"  on  the  part  of  a  Jewish  child  may 
be  "impertinence"  or  "pushing"  to  anti-Semites,  who  may  entitle 
the  same  conduct,  when  it  is  displayed  by  a  Gentile  child,  "inde- 
pendence" and  "initiative."— By  thus  ascribing  different  motives  to 
similar  acts,  status  lines  are  upheld. - 

The  "success"  or  the  power  of  an  actor  may  drastically  influence 
the  vocabulary  used  in  describing  his  character  and  motives.  Lord 
Byron  put  the  fact  of  these  dual  vocabularies  of  motive  for  identi- 
cal conduct  neatly  in  speaking  of 

"Firmness  in  heroes,  kings  and  seamen, 
That  is,  when  they  succeed;  but  greatly  blamed 
As  obstinacy,  both  in  men  and  women. 
Whenever  their  triumph  pales  or  star  is  tamed  .  .  ."  "^ 

"Events"  may  decide  between  which  of  two  vocabularies  of  mo- 
tive are  used.  Only  great  men  can  leave  their  reasons  to  the  crea- 
tive hands  of  their  apologists,  and  some  are  famous  because  they 
have  found  apologists."  Yet,  there  may  be  a  way  to  go  behind 
the  event  and,  by  using  the  acceptable  vocabularies  of  motive, 
understand  successful-men-with-apologists  as  well  as  those  who 
failing  descend  into  the  limbo  of  anonymity. 

3.  The  "Real"  Motives 

Thus  far  we  have  been  examining  motivation  on  the  level  of 
the  explanations  people  use  and  accept  to  account  for  their  ac- 
tions. But  now  we  must  ask  whether  such  explanations  are  "the 
real  motives"  of  the  persons  using  them. 

• — -We  have  first  to  abandon  the  notion  that  merely  because  vocabu- 
laries of  motives  are  acceptable  they  are  necessarily  deceptive 
shams.^he  very  fact  that  many  "sophisticated"  persons  doubt  the 
validity  of  such  motives  is  itself  an  historical  phenomenon  which 
must  be  explained.  The  Freudian  theory  of  motives,  for  example, 
has  been  summarily  stated  by  Ralph  Barton  Perry  as  the  view  "that 
the  real  motives  of  conduct  are  those  which  we  are  ashamed  to 
admit  either  to  ourselves  or  to  others."  *  We  can  admit  the  truth 

^  Don  Juan,  Canto  XIV,  pp.  89  fF. 
^  See  Chapter  XIV:   The  Sociology  of  Leadership. 

^  General  Theory  of  Value  (  New  York:  Longmans,  Green,  1936),  pp.  292-93. 
For  another  criticism  of  Freud  on  this  point,  see  Karen  Homey,  New  Ways  in 


120  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

in  this  statement  in  a  more  fruitful  manner:  the  vocabularies 
which  persons  choose  for  their  statements  of  motive  tend  to  be 
those  which  are  accepted  by  others.  But  whether  this  means  ( i ) 
that  these  acceptable  motives,  stated  to  others  and  to  self,  are 
inefficacious  in  social  conduct,  or  (2)  that  they  are  not  to  be  con- 
sidered "the  real  motives"  of  the  person  using  them  are  further 
questions,  the  answers  to  which  cannot  be  inferred  from  the  prin- 
ciple governing  the  social  choice  of  vocabularies  of  motive. 

We  have  already  indicated  thal^-acceptable  vocabularies  of  mo- 
tives may  be  controlling  factors  of  social  conduct,  but  under  what 
conditions  may  they  be  considered  "the  real  motives"2^We  may 
assume  that  the  more  deeply  internalized  in  the  person,  and  the 
more  closely  integrated  with  the  psychic  structure,  a  vocabulary 
of  motives  is,  the  greater  is  the  chance  that  it  contains  "the  real 
motives;^LJn  fact,  that  is  what  "real  motives"  may  be  assumed  to 
mean.  We  must,  in  order  to  "test"  motives,  therefore,  attempt  to 
find  out  on  what  level  of  character  structure  a  given  vocabulary 
of  motives  is  integrated. 

But  how  can  we  find  this  out?*^hat  are  the  optimum  conditions 
for  the  fuller  integration  of  a  vocabulary  of  motives  with  the 
psychic  structure?^ 
"Those  vocabularies  of  motive  which  are  consistently  used  by 
the  person  when  in  public,  when  in  private,  and  when  alone 
have  the  highest  chance— other  things  being  equal— to  become 
fully  integrated  with  the  psychic  structurer^f  difl:ering  vocabu- 
laries are  used  by  the  person  when  with  his  wife  than  when  with 
his  coworkers,  and  still  another  vocabulary  is  used  when  he  is  by 
himself,  we  do  not  know  what  his  motive  may  be. 

Moreover,  in  terms  of  his  life  history,  to  the  extent  that  the 
vocabularies  of  motive  now  used  by  the  person  are  the  same  as 
those  which  were  used  in  the  socialization  of  his  psychic  struc- 
ture, the  chances  are  higher  that  they  are  integrated  on  deeper 
psychic  levels  of  his  character. 

In  other  words:  to  probe  for  motives  requires  us  to  observe  the 
function  and  the  context  of  vocabularies  of  motive.  It  is  from  such 
observations   that  we   may  infer  how  deeply   given   motives   are 

Psychoanalysis  (New  York:  Norton,  1939).  The  present  discussion  is  not,  of 
course,  intended  as  a  comprehensive  statement  or  criticism  of  Freud's  theory  of 
motivation. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  121 

integrated  with  the  character  structure,  and  thus  how  "real"  they 
may  be. 

Now,  whether  the  same  vocabulary  of  motives  for  given  types 
of  activity  is  used  frequently  in  the  life  history  and  widely  in  con- 
temporary contexts  depends  not  only  upon  the  internal  condition 
of  the  individual  but  also  upon  the  typical  social-historical  situa- 
tion that  prevails.  Accordingly,  we  can  imagine  sociological  con- 
diticms  which  favor  or  which  work  against  the  psychic  integration 
of  vocabularies  of  motive;  we  can  in  fact  construct  two  contrasting 
types  of  society— (I)  in  one  of  which  conditions  maximize  the 
chances,  and  in  the  other  ( II )  minimize  the  chances  that  a  vocabu- 
lary of  motives  coincides  with  "real"  motives.  We  know  that  so- 
cieties, as  well  as  institutions  within  societies,  differ  in  the  extent 
to  which  the  roles  of  their  members  may  be  classified  into  different 
sectors  of  the  private  and  public.  At  one  extreme,  we  may  think 
in  a  simplified  way,  of  a  small  preindustrial  village;  at  the  other, 
of  a  modern  industrialized  metropolis. 

I.  In  the  village  the  various  situations  in  which  men  play  roles 
are  not  so  widely  different  from  one  another  and  are  transparent  to 
all.  Even  in  his  family  group  a  person's  talk  and  actions  may  not 
be  very  different  from  his  talk  and  actions  while  working  with 
other  family  heads.  The  variety  of  roles  which  any  given  person 
plays  is  not  very  wide,  and  each  is  translatable  into  the  others. 
In  such  a  society  a  single  vocabulary  of  moti\  es  may  be  used  by  a 
person  for  all  his  roles,  or  at  least  he  will  use  the  same  motives  in 
speaking  of  some  conduct  pattern  to  his  wife  and  to  his  neighbor, 
to  his  working  mates  and  to  the  village  head.  His  children  will 
learn  these  same  homogeneous  vocabularies  of  motive.  And  these 
vocabularies  of  motive  are  not  likely  to  be  questioned,  for  they  are 
used  in  public,  in  private,  and  when  alone,  and  their  chances  of 
being  integrated  firmly  and  smoothly  with  the  psychic  structure 
of  the  character  will  be  high. 

In  such  a  society,  if  a  variety  of  motives  is  used,  each  set  of 
motives  is  likely  to  remain  associated  in  a  stable  way  with  its 
respective  roles.  The  motives  used  to  explain  why  one  works  will 
be  the  same  before  one's  wife  and  friend  as  before  one's  working 
mate  and  village  chief.  So,  different  vocabularies  for  different  situa- 
tions are  easily  understood  and  relatively  unquestioned  by  the  dif- 
ferent members  of  each  situation. 


122  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

The  motives  of  a  person  are  thus  compartmentahzed  and  or- 
dered without  conflict  to  their  respective  institutional  compartment. 
So  motives  stabihze  and  guide  conduct;  the  expectations  of  the 
several  others  with  which  the  person  is  confronted  are  not  in  con- 
flict when  he  uses  the  vocabulary  of  motives  appropriate  to  a  given 
occasion.  Being  typically  unquestioned  and  being  intertranslatable 
—and  hence  usable  before  everyone— the  chance  is  great  that  stable 
and  acceptable  vocabularies  of  motive  will  be  used  when  alone  and 
that  they  will  be  linked  with  impulse  and  emotion  during  the 
socialization  of  the  psychic  structure.  Appearance  and  reality  are 
one;  or  if  such  be  the  case,  the  cant  is  completely  shared  and 
socially  effective. 

II.  In  an  industrialized  metropolis,  the  person  is  confronted  with 
a  variety  of  roles  and  situations.  Not  only  is  there  a  typical  split 
between  his  more  intimate  roles  and  his  more  public  appearances, 
but  the  differences  between  any  two  intimate  roles  or  between 
any  two  public  roles  may  be  very  wide.  Different  motives  may  be 
employed  for  roles  involving  one's  wife  and  for  those  involving 
one's  acquaintance  on  the  commuter  train. 

This  segmentalization  of  conduct  means  that  the  person  will 
internalize  many  vocabularies  of  motive  which  may  very  well  be 
in  conflict.  Then  the  individual  must  keep  one  set  of  motives  secret 
from  the  others,  for  they  may  appear  "silly"  to  some,  even  though 
"beautiful"  to  others.  He  compartmentalizes  not  only  his  conduct 
but  also  his  reasons  for  it,  and  insofar  as  he  cannot  do  so,  his 
motives  may  be  in  conflict.  He  may  have  difficulties  deciding 
whether  he  does  this  or  that  for  love  or  for  duty,  for  "selfish" 
economic  gain  or  for  civic  betterment;  perhaps  he  will  not  be  sure 
whether  he  is  marrying  this  woman  because  he  loves  her  and  she 
has  such  a  pleasant  voice,  or  because  she  is  so  wealthy. 

No  one  vocabulary  of  motives  is  accepted  by  everyone,  so  the 
alert  individual  must  use  one  or  the  other  tentatively,  until  he 
finds  the  way  to  integrate  his  conduct  with  others,  to  win  them  as 
allies  of  his  act.  Different  motives  may  integrate  roles  and  release 
conduct  in  the  same  situation,  and  similar  motives  may  integrate 
roles  and  justify  conduct  in  very  different  situations.  Then  others 
and  the  person  himself  may  be  confused  and  not  know  just  what 
motive  does  prevail. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  12^ 

Vocabularies  of  motive  which  are  historically  associated  with 
one  type  of  institutional  conduct  may  spread  to  other  institutions. 
The  motives  which  are  acceptable  for  economic  enterprise  may 
gain  partial  or  entire  acceptance  in  other  institutions.  And  such 
spreading  motives  may  become  universally  accepted  as  the  com- 
prehensive motives  of  man.  The  intricate  motives  of  business  con- 
duct in  America  have  spread  in  this  way  to  other  types  of  con- 
duct. They  have  encroached  upon  the  Victorian  vocabulary  of  the 
virtuous  relations  of  men  and  women:  love,  duty,  kindness.  Among 
certain  strata,  the  romantic  and  virtuous  vocabularies  of  motive 
have  been  "confused"  with  the  pecuniary.  To  ask  whether  a  woman 
or  man  is  marrying  "for  love  or  for  money"  is  to  point  to  this  over- 
lap. The  decline  of  the  family  relative  to  other  institutions  in- 
voh'es  a  questioning  of  the  vocabularies  of  motive  which  accom- 
panied the  more  stable  family  patterns.  And  Max  Weber  has  re- 
marked that  what  formerly  was  thought  of  morally  is  in  our  time 
thought  of  esthetically  or  psychiatrically.  Whereas  formerly  maidens 
and  ladies  spoke  of  "wicked"  men  and  of  "good"  and  "bad"  con- 
duct, today  they  speak  of  "decent"  and  "indecent"  conduct,  or  of 
"neurotic"  and  "stable"  persons. 

— Due  to  the  great  weight  which  the  economic  order  has  in  the 
American  social  structure,  pecuniary  motives  tend  to  form  a  sort 
of  common  denominator  of  many  other  roles  and  motives.  Other 
vocabularies  are  treated  as  shams,  fa9ades,  and  "rationalization," 
and  "ihe  wise  guy"  knows  that  the  real  motive  is  the  desire  for 
money  which,  as  is  commonly  said,  may  not  be  everything  but  is 
almost  everything.— 

--Back  of  the  motive-mongering  and  the  self-doubts  of  persons  as 
to  their  own  motives  is  the  fact  that  in  modern  life  there  is  often 
no  stable  or  unquestioned  vocabulary  of  motives  available.  And 
back  of  this  is  the  fact  that  the  institutional  arrangements  of  roles 
demand  that  we  rapidly  give  up  and  take  on  roles  and  along  with 
them,  their  socially  appropriate  motives.  -  Back  of  these  "mixed 
motives"  and  "motivational  conflicts"  there  is  going  on  a  competi- 
tion of  varying  institutional  patterns  and  of  their  respective  vocabu- 
laries of  motives.  Shifting  and  borderline  situations,  having  no 
stable  vocabularies  of  motive,  may  contain  several  alternative  sets 
of  moti\  es  originally  belonging  to  different  systems  of  roles. 

Such  institutional  conflicts  are  internalized  and,  accordingly,  are 
revealed  in  the  confusion  and  self-doubt  of  institvitionally  marginal 


124  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

persons.^Institutional  conflict,  in  short,  threatens  the  sense  of  unity 
and  even  the  identity  of  the  modern  self^~The  rival  demands  of 
conflicting  roles,  brought  to  self-awareness,  call  forth  the  com- 
plex internal  behavior  called  "conscience,"  a  term  literally  mean- 
ing "shared  knowledge."  If  this  "conscience,"  that  is  our  general 
other,  passes  in  review  all  the  particular  role  enactments,  there  is, 
as  it  were,  an  internal  court  which  will  let  "the  left  hand  know 
what  the  right  is  doing."  Compartmentalization  of  roles  and  of  role 
demands  will  work  so  long  as  the  generalized  other  is  not  con- 
cerned, that  is,  so  long  as  no  ethical  universals  are  involved.  The 
Sunday  Christian  who  professes  to  be  an  honest  dealer  may  no 
longer  be  able  to  jab  his  business  partner,  without  discarding  or 
trying  to  cheat  his  own  conscience.  The  same  goes  for  the  "high 
minded  citizen"  who  may  vote  for  higher  taxes— for  others,  but 
not  for  him,  to  pay.  If  he  has  internalized  the  professed  values  of 
his  Christian  community  or  of  his  nation,  his  generalized  other 
is  bound  to  saddle  him  with  guilt  for  whatever  acts  fall  short  of  the 
professed  demand  level. 

What  is  expedient  for  the  purpose  at  hand  is  not  necessarily 
high-minded,  law  abiding,  or  moral,  however  successful  we  may 
be  in  deceiving  ourselves  and  others,  and  however  intense  and 
widespread  the  tacit  consensus  of  a  group.  Uncertainty  continues 
to  exist  so  long  as  there  are  critical  out-groups  that  are  ready  and 
capable  of  pointing  to  disparities  between  expedient  practice  and 
ethical  professions.  Victorian  cant  is  painfully  transparent  to  every- 
one—in retrospect;  for  Karl  Marx,  for  example,  it  was  plainly  ob- 
vious at  the  time.  When  what  is  done  cannot  be  undone,  self- 
expurgating  behavior  is  a  ritual;  the  motto  "now  it  can  be  told" 
usually  prefaces  such  retrospective  and  harmless  exercise.  It  is  the 
sequel  to  twentieth-century  cant  which  H.  Nicholson  has  defined 
as  the  tribute  vice  pays  to  virtue.  t 

The  speed  with  which  decision  makers,  in  their  sixties  today, 
have  repeatedly  written  off  presumably  universal  principles  pro- 
duces mass  skepticism  and  cynicism  and  the  increasing  realization 
that'Wirs  is  indeed  a  secular  age  in  which  the  exjDloitation  of  moral 
values  for  expedient  interests  is  quite  standardf^he  motto,  wrought 
on  the  gate  of  the  Dachau  concentration  camp— "Labor  Means 
Liberty"— dramatically  highlights  the  condition  of  "moral  man" 
who  in  malaise,  drifts  in  "immoral  society." 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  I25 

4.  Awareness  of  Motives 

Two  experiences  lead  us  to  beliexe  that  there  are  motives  which 
operate  but  of  which  the  individual  himself  is  not  aware: 

I.  We  may  arrange  a  special  type  of  interview  with  another  per- 
son and  decide  about  real  and  sham  motivations  on  the  basis  of 
this  interview.  This  interview  may  be  a  variant  of  a  highly  per- 
sonal or  intimate  situation;  but  in  addition  to  privacy  it  may  con- 
tain the  authority  of  both  scientist  and  physician— the  psychiatrist. 
By  systematic  and  skillful  questioning,  the  psychiatrist  may  so 
arrange  and  conduct  the  interview  that  the  person  will  confess 
motives  which  he  comes  to  believe  are  his  real  motives  yet  of  which 
he  was  previously  unaware.  In  the  interview  he  loosens  up  the  set 
vocabularies  which  he  has  typically  used  and  which  he  had  come 
to  ascribe  to  others.  He  may  now  use  this  new  vocabulary  in  the 
presence  of  self;  he  may  also  publicize  it  to  chosen  others,  or  to  a 
wider  public. 

The  new  motives  thus  emerging  from  the  psychiatric  interview 
may  come  to  approximate  more  closely  the  true  state  of  the  psychic 
structure,  and  they  may,  in  time,  be  used  in  resocializing  this 
psychic  structure.  Such  interviews  do  not  occur  only  in  psychiatric 
work.  Rather  sudden  shifts  in  motivations  may  occur  in  intimate 
life  situations,  as  well  as  in  the  police  interview,  where  regular 
techniques  have  been  worked  out  to  detect  the  lie  or  sham.  Of  a 
Gestapo  agent,  Anna  Seghers  has  written:  "He  arranged  the  slips 
of  paper,  looked  over  his  notes,  sorted  them,  underscored  words, 
and  connected  various  items  by  a  certain  system  of  lines.  .  .  .  His 
notes  for  an  examination  were  comparable  only  to  intricate  musi- 
cal scores."  ^ 

n.  The  phenomenon  of  motives  which  operate,  yet  of  which  the 
person  is  not  aware,  appears  even  more  convincingly  in  hypnotic 
situations.  If  several  persons  are  hypnotized  and  while  in  this  state 
it  is  suggested  to  them  that  they  breathe  faster  while  reading  every 
other  page  of  a  book,  they  will  do  so  in  the  posthypnotic  period, 
without  being  aware  of  doing  so  or  of  the  planted  motives  which 
impel  them.^° 

9  The  Seventh  Cross,  J.  A.  Galston,  tr.  (Boston:  Little,  Brown,  1942),  p.  156. 

1"  See  E.  R.  Kellogg,  "The  Duration  and  EflFects  of  Posthypnotic  Suggestion," 

Journal  of  Experimental  Psychology  (1929),  Vol.  XII,  pp.  502-514.  Compare 


126  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

On  the  basis  of  the  psychiatric  interview  and  the  hypnotic  ex- 
perience, one  must  suppose  that  many  motives  operating  in  social 
Hfe  are  outside  the  awareness  of  persons.  AVe  may  approach  this 
fact  by  asking:  What  conditions  favor  the  operation  of  motives 
of  which  the  person  is  unaware,  even  when  he  is  alone? 
fli  an  act  can  be  typically  construed  by  the  actor  in  such  a  way 
as  to  have  others  and  himself  ascribe  it  to  an  acceptable  motive, 
then  a  premium  has  been  placed  upon  the  act.  Other  feelings  and 
actions  are  typically  tabooed  by  virtue  of  the  motives  to  which  they 
are  usually  ascribed.  Tabooed  actions  and  the  impulses  and  emo- 
tions associated  with  them  may  be  restricted  to  private  occasions 
by  the  actor,  or  he  may  seek  to  represent  them  in  terms  of  some 
more  favorable  vocabulary  of  motives.  But  there  is  another  way  in 
which  such  motives  may  be  handled:  the  conduct,  feeling,  and 
discussion  of  them  in  a  tabooed  vocabulary  of  motives  may  be 
repressed,  which  simply  means  that  they  cannot  be  recalled  by  a 
simple  act  of  attention. 

There  are  topics  and  feelings  for  which  vocabularies  exist  and 
are  used  in  all  public  situations,  just  as  there  are  feelings  and  im- 
pulses, which  can  be  discussed  openly  in  most  conversations.  Other 
topics  and  feelings  are  restricted  to  intimate  occasions,  and  still 
others  which  may  be  available  only  to  the  person  when  alone. 
Finally,  there  are  topics  and  feelings  which  the  person  will  not 
discuss  even  with  himself.  These  situations,  in  brief,  range  from 
those  in  which  a  vocabulary  of  motives  is  quite  socialized  to  those 
in  which  given  topics  or  feelings  are  not  verbalized  even  by  the 
person  when  alone. 

As  we  descend  this  scale  of  conventionally  premiumed  to  per- 
missible topics  and  to  those  which  are  conventionally  tabooed, 
we  also  descend  into  those  spheres  which  are  most  likely  to  be 
"unconscious."  For  the  prime  meaning  of  "unconscious"  is  that 
which  is  unverbalized,  or  sometimes  even,  unverbalizable.  j 

/Just  as  a  man  who  is  writing  a  note  for  his  own  future  reference 
may  abbreviate  it  so  that  only  he  can  understand  its  meaning,  so 
our  internal  speech  follows  a  grammar  of  its  own,  in  which  symbol 
condensations  and  images  may  call  forth  whole  streams  of  thought. 
I  This  inner  speech  may  be  very  important  in  the  person's  self- 
Erich  Fromm's  discussion  of  motives  planted  during  hypnosis:  Escape  from 
Freedom   (New  York:   Farrar  &  Rinehart,   1941). 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  12J 

understanding.  To  communicate  our  inner  speech  to  others  we  have 
to  translate  it  into  discursive,  outer  speech,  and  it  is  this  explain- 
ing to  others  which  gives  rise  to  "objectivity."  The  terms  which 
the  person  uses  to  refer  to  his  own  feelings  are  socially  confirmed 
by  their  use  by  other  persons. -Self-knowledge  that  is  not  socially 
confirmed,  not  yet  disciplined  by  interaction  with  others,  is  not 
secine  knowledge. ^^ 

'If  we  do  not  publicize  the  vocabularies  we  use  for  our  motives 
and  feelings,  we  may  develop  little  areas  of  private  speech  which 
we  use  only  with  very  intimate  friends  or  perhaps  only  in  intro- 
spection and  soliloquy.  Sometimes  two  persons  who  are  very  inti- 
mate will  share  such  patterns,  although  no  one  else  can  under- 
stand the  meanings  which  these  two  use  privately.  In  this  way, 
the  unconscious  may  be  made  articulate  and  partially  shared 
with  a  few  selected  others  "who  understand."  For  sometimes  in 
these  intimate  conversations,  using  very  private  cues  and  innuen- 
dos  of  motive,  a  person  will  suddenly  become  aware  of  motives 
which  he  did  not  know  as  his  own.  Then  what  was  unconscious  is 
no  longer  unconscious  but  privately  conscious.  / 

The  becoming  aware  of  previously  unconscious  feelings  and 
impulses  proceeds  by  just  such  socialization.  But  the  social  area  in 
which  th^se  elements  of  the  psychic  structure  are  socialized  may 
still  be  restricted.  From  the  standpoint  of  the  urbane  character 
structure,  only  the  yokel  or  the  fool  will  give  away  his  "private" 
motives  in  "public."  Urbane  "maturity"  involves  a  specialization  of 
displayed  motives  in  varying  degrees  and  according  to  private  and 
public  appearances. 

t"  Those  topics  which  are  excluded  from  public  conversation  with 
others  will  more  likely  be  part  of  the  private  world  of  the  indi- 
vidual, and  if  the  taboos  are  strong  and  morally  enforced  by 
significant  others,  they  will  tend  to  become  unconscious.  ^Then 
the  person  will  not  discuss  them  even  with  intimate  others,  and 
he  will  not  be  able  to  discuss  them  with  himself.  •■ — 

That  which  the  person  is  unaware  of  is  related  to  that  which  is 


11  George  H.  Mead  has  done  much  witli  the  cjiiestion  of  the  social  character 
of  objectivity  in  his  Mind,  Self  and  Society  (Chicago:  Uni\'.  of  Chicago  Press, 
1934).  See  also  C.  S.  Pierce,  "How  to  Fix  Belief,"  Vol.  V,  of  Collected  Papers 
(Cambridge,  Mass.:  Harvard  Univ.  Press,  1934).  Vigotsky  has  systematized  this 
matter  and  has  introduced  the  distinction  between  inner  and  outer  speech.  See 
his  essay  "Language,"  Psycliiatry,  1940-41. 


120  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

tabooed  in  his  society.  The  approved  motives  which  are  typically 
ascribed  to  conduct  are  sanctions  which  reinforce  that  conduct. 
Disapproved  motives  are  sanctions  which  discourage  the  conduct 
to  which  they  are  typically  applied.  Vocabularies  of  motives  are 
thus  a  special  class  of  premium  or  taboo. ^- 

When  we  are  motivated  by  impulses  that  are  disapproved,  we^' 
sometimes  cannot  stand  the  image  of  ourselves,  and  so  we  Iceep 
these  motives  out  of  our  awareness.  \"arious  impulses  which  we 
thus  "repress"  pop  up  in  our  daydreams,  or  in  our  dreams  at  night. 
But  we  do  not  face  them  when  we  are  alert;  the  mechanisms  of 
awareness  exclude  them  in  the  interests  of  self-security;  they  catch 
us  only  when  we  are  alone  and  our  level  of  consciousness  is  lowered. 

The  subjective  is  what  the  person  presents  only  to  himself.  When 
he  communicates  it  to  another  it  is  no  longer  subjective,  but  ob- 
jective, no  longer  private  but  socializedv-We  may  communicate  such 
private  feelings,  moods,  and  motives  in  intimate  relations,  or  even 
sometimes  among  perfect  strangers.  And  as  we  do  so  we  are  learn- 
ing about  ourselves.  As  we  tell  our  motives  to  others,  we  become 
aware  of  new  aspects  of  ourselves.  For  by  telling  them  even  to  one 
significant  other,  we  may  justify  our  having  them  or  seek  relief 
from  them.  We  are  developing  or  using  a  vocabulary  of  motives 
with  this  particular  other,  and  on  the  basis  of  this  vocabulary  we 
understand  our  own  motives  in  a  more  socially  acceptable  way. 

We  can  integrate  these  motives  and  moods  into  our  own  self  by 
socializing  them  to  others,  even  to  a  few  others,  who  understand. 
Thus  making  others  understand  us,  we  can  understand  ourselves 
and  reconstruct  our  image  of  self.  If  we  faced  our  motives  alone, 
our  sense  of  unity  and  identity  of  self  might  be  tlireatened.  Just 
as  we  repress  a  motive,  an  act,  a  mood,  a  feeling  from  public 
display,  we  may  also  repress  it  to  the  point  where  we  ourselves 
are  not  aware  of  it.  It  may  be  that  we  cannot  by  an  act  of  atten- 
tion recall  some  motive  or  some  feeling  until  it  is  put  into  a  vocabu- 
lary of  motives  which  we  might  use  before  some  others  without 
loss  of  self-esteem  and  security.  The  vocabulary  in  terms  of  which 
our  motives  are  thus  phrased  may  not  be  approved  by  many  others, 
indeed  it  may  be  a  vocabulary  which  we  can  accept  only  because 
of  the  authority  of  the  one  psychiatrist  who  gives  us  the  words, 
tells  us  that  it  is  all  right  since  at  times  "others"  feel  the  same  way. 

^2  See  Chapter  VII:  Institutions  and  Persons,  Section  3:  The  Theory  of 
Premiums  and  Traits  of  Cliaracter. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     MOTIVATION  12g 

Motivation  may  be  discussed  in  terms  of  the  organism,  the  psy- 
chic structure  and  the  person.  Although  we  have  paid  attention 
to  each  of  these,  we  have  approached  the  problem  primarily  from 
the  standpoint  of  the  person.  So  approached,  motives  are  viewed 
as  social  justifications  for  one's  own  conduct,  and  as  means  of  per- 
suading others  to  accept  and  to  further  one's  conduct.  Such  state- 
ments of  motive  arise  when  we  are  faced  with  alternatives,  with 
unexpected  choices,  or  when  there  is  opposition  to  one's  role,  for 
in  routine  conduct  our  motives  are  often  not  questioned. 

When  there  are  many  vocabularies  of  motives,  it  becomes  diffi- 
cult to  know  the  "real  motives "  of  persons.  The  more  closely  in- 
tegrated our  vocabulary  of  motives  with  our  person  and  our  psychic 
structure,  the  greater  the  chance  that  it  contains  our  real  motives. 
Such  integration  is  most  often  present  when  we  use  the  same  mo-  ; 
tives  in  public,  in  private  and  when  alone.  In  some  societies  this  is  ' 
generally  the  case;  in  others  it  is  not.  And  when  it  is  not,  when 
various  institutions  and  roles  compete  with  each  other,  there  is  a 
confusion  of  motives,  as  we  have  shown  by  contrasting  the  problem 
of  motivation  in  a  preindustrial  village  and  an  industrialized 
metropolis.    , 

All  this  does  not  mean  that  there  are  not  motives  which  affect 
conduct  but  of  which  the  person  involved  is  not  aware.  We  have 
suggested,  with  due  regard  to  individual  comiplications,  that  these 
unconscious  motives  may  be  explained  primarily  in  terms  of  unver- 
balized  areas  of  feeling  and  conduct. 


CHAPTER 

V  I 

Biography  and  Types 
of  Childhood 


SOMATIC  development  refers  to  the  growth  of  the  organism; 
maturation,  as  we  shall  use  the  term,  to  changes  of  the  psychic 
structure;  biographical  development,  to  the  development  of  the 
person,  to  changes  in  the  roles  that  are  taken  up  and  cast  off  in  the 
passage  from  one  age  group  to  another. 

These  three  lines  of  somatic,  psychic,  and  biographical  develop- 
ment proceed  together  and  each  is  involved  in  the  course  of  the 
others.  Yet,  in  their  interplay  there  is  no  universal  pattern  or  se- 
quence. Changes  in  the  vegetative  system  and  the  use  of  the  motor 
mechanisms  of  the  body  require  an  appropriate  integration  of 
sensory  organs  and  psychic  components.  The  person  cannot  per- 
form certain  roles  without  properly  developed  psychic  and  organic 
functions  and  prerequisite  dispositions.  The  emotions  of  the  psychic 
structure  are  timed  and  shaped  in  their  expressions  according  to 
the  roles  required  of  the  person. 

Thus  one  sequence  of  these  three  lines  of  development  limits 
arid  facilitates  another,  but  no  one  of  them  determines  what  oc- 
curs in  the  other  two. 

Development  of  any  sort  involves  differentiation  and  integration. 
The  unco-ordinated  and  "mass  activity"  of  the  infant  becomes  dif- 
ferentiated into  specialized  verbal  responses  and  motor  skills,  and 
these  specializations— of  organism,  psychic  structure,  and  person- 
are  integrated  with  various  kinds  of  human  character  and  conduct. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        i;^l 

1.  The  Organism 

Everyone  begins  life  as  part  of  another;  birth  is  a  biological 
separation:  the  infant  is  ejected  and  cut  off  from  the  mother.  Then 
it  begins  its  slow  movement  through  infancy,  childhood,  preado- 
lescence,  adolescence,  and  adulthood.  Soon  after  adulthood,  the 
organism  begins  to  decline,  it  passes  through  middle  age  and  be- 
gins its  senescence,  until  finally,  it  dies.  If  birth  is  a  biological  sepa- 
ration, death  is  a  social  separation.  After  we  are  biologically  dead 
we  "live"  only  in  the  memory  or  ancestor  worship  or  imagination, 
or— if  we  were  important  enough— in  the  legends  of  others. 

The  history  of  the  human  organism  is  one  of  very  rapid  growth 
during  the  first  year  of  life,  of  more  gradual  growth  up  to  ma- 
turity, and  then  a  gradual  decline  in  vigor,  alertness,  and  capacity. 
From  conception  imtil  birth  the  weight  of  the  organism  increases 
about  a  billionfold;  during  the  rest  of  the  entire  lifetime  it  increases 
only  about  twerityfold,  a  great  deal  of  it  during  the  first  three  years 
after  birth. ^ 

Regardless  of  race  or  creed,  the  biological  history  of  every  man 
is  limited  by  his  animal  ancestry.  During  the  first  year  after  birth, 
it  is  scarcely  proper  to  distinguish  organic  from  psychic  matura- 
tion, and  it  is  unknowledgeable  to  speak  of  personal  development, 
although  other  persons  and  their  activities  do,  of  course,  influence 
the  maturation  of  the  organism  and  the  psychic  structure.  Ex'en 
while  it  is  in  the  uterus,  the  organism  does  not  unfold  according 
to  an  unalterable  pattern.  It  interacts  with  the  uterine  environ- 
ment which  thus  facilitates  or  retards  its  growth.  Moreover,  the 
economic  environment,  as  registered  in  the  family's  class  position, 
vitally  influences  the  fetus  and  the  birth  of  the  child,  with  or 
without  professional  service.  In  typical  United  States  cities,  in  the 
1930's,  the  infant's  chances  to  stay  alive  immediately  after  birth 
were  three  times  as  great  if  its  family  earned  $1,250  a  year  than 
if  they  earned  under  $450  a  year.-  Thus,  even  though  there  is  as 
yet  no  person,  social-historical  influences  bear  vitally  upon  even 
the  prenatal  organism. 

1  B.  T.  Baldwin,  The  PJujsical  Growth  of  Children  from  Birth  to  Maturity 
(Iowa  City:    The  University,    1921). 

-  Robert  Woodbury,  "Infant  Mortality  in  the  United  States,"  Annals  of  the 
American  Academy  of  Political  and  Social  Science  (November,  1936). 


1^2  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

Some  eight  weeks  after  conception,  the  unborn  child  responds 
to  external  stimulation;  the  skin  around  the  areas  that  will  become 
its  nose  and  mouth  being  sensitive  to  tactile  stimulation.  Later, 
definite  reflexes  appear  and  other  skin  areas  become  sensitive.  By 
six  or  seven  months,  all  the  reflexes  needed  for  postnatal  life  have 
appeared.^  The  birth  of  the  infant  may  occur  as  early  as  twenty- 
four  weeks  and  as  late  as  forty-eight  weeks,  and  a  variation  of 
some  three  lunar  months  is  quite  frequent.  Yet  the  pattern  of 
organic  maturation  proceeds  irrespective  of  such  irregularities  of 
birth.* 

As  a  little  animal,  the  child  is  equipped  with  certain  invariable 
responses  which  occur  when  given  stimulations  are  presented. 
These  reflexes,  as  we  have  already  seen,  may  be  transferred  in  such 
a  way  that  they  will  occur  as  reaction  to  stimulations  other  than 
the  ones  which  at  first  evoke  them.  Such  conditioning  is  perhaps 
the  bottom  level  of  what  may  be  called  development  in  the  infant. 
Habits,  once  learned,  may  become  quasi-automatic.  The  stereo- 
typing and  restereotyping  of  reflexes  and  of  habits  enable  the  in- 
fant to  meet  situations  which  recur;  they  do  not  enable  him  to 
meet  new  situations.  Conditioning,  and  the  learning  of  habits,  are 
subject  to  conscious  modification  by  others,  and,  in  time,  even  by 
the  child's  own  will. 

The  infant  does  not  at  first  distinguish  persons  from  inanimate 
objects,  and  even  for  children,  physical  things  often  seem  to  be 
animated— as  the  content  of  fairy  tales,  nursery  stories,  and  movie 
cartoons  witness.  But  by  continually  doing  things  to  him,  other 
persons  stimulate  the  infant  more  and  more;  they  elicit  more  re- 
sponses and  more  changes  of  bodily  feelings  than  do  the  objects 
of  the  inanimate  environment.^   Soon  they  become  identified  as 

3  Based  on  D.  Hooker,  "Reflex  Activities  in  the  Human  Fetus,"  Chapter  -2 
of  Child  Behavior  and  Development,  R.  G.  Barker,  J.  S.  Kounin,  and  H.  F. 
Wright,  eds.   (New  York:   McGraw-Hill,   1943). 

4  Arnold  Gesell,  "Maturation  and  Infant  Behavior  Pattern,"  Psychological 
Review    (1929),   36,   pp.   308-19. 

■''  See  the  precise  studies  of  Orvis  C.  Irwin,  "Tlie  Amount  and  Nature  of 
Activities  of  New  Born  Infants  Under  Constant  External  Stimulating  Condi- 
tions During  the  First  Ten  Days  of  Life,"  Genetic  Psychology  Monograph 
No.  1,  1930,  pp. 1-92.  See  also  M.  A.  Ribble,  "Clinical  Studies  of  Instinctive 
Reactions  in  New  Born  Babies,"  American  Journal  of  Psychiatry  (1938),  95, 
p.  149;  and  F.  Peterson,  "The  Beginnings  of  Mind  in  the  New  Born,"  Bulletin 
of  the  Lying  In  Hospital  of  the  City  of  New  York  ( 1910),  7,  p.  99. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        1^;^ 

sources  of  food  and  warmth,  the  first  image  of  the  mother  prob- 
ably centering  about  the  feel  of  the  breast.  The  fact  tiiat  persons 
are  a  source  of  vital  stimulations,  and  the  fact  that  persons  are 
active  and  move  by  themselves,  form  the  basis  of  their  being  dis- 
tinguished from  mere  things, 

2.  The  Psychic  Structure 

As  the  child  matures  he  engages  in  a  greater  variety  of  be- 
havior, of  motor  skills,  of  displayed  feelings  and  interests,  of  psychic 
abilities.  As  the  "mass  activity"  of  the  infant  develops  into  seg- 
mental activities  and  functionally  segregated  acts,  his  psychic  ele- 
ments are  linked  with  them.  So  perception,  touch,  and  grasp  come 
to  form  the  child's  total  image  of  given  objects;  he  links  the  sight 
with  the  taste  with  the  feel  of  these  objects.  The  normal  adult  can 
wiggle  his  big  toe  without  waving  his  entire  foot;  the  infant  is  not 
so  able;  he  has  les^  poise,  less  "distance"  from  internal  stimulation 
as  well  as  from  environmental  influences.  An  impulse  is  directly 
and  quickly  translated  into  activity;  a  simple  frustration  is  likely 
to  affect  the  whole  inner  condition  and  external  activity  of  the 
infant. 

The  feelings  of  the  newborn  infant  seem  to  be  undifferentiated. 
At  first,  they  may  be  described  simply  as  "excitability,"  but  gradu- 
ally this  capacity  becomes  differentiated  and,  as  it  is  linked  to 
bodily  movements,  two  "emotions"  may  be  socially  distinguished: 
distress  and  delight— terms  which  may  describe  slight  visceral  dif- 
ferences in  the  infant,  but,  more  importantly,  indicate  differences  in 
the  provoking  situations  and  in  observable  behavior  and  gesture. 
Whether  they  indicate  a  distinct  awareness  of  feeling  on  the  part 
of  the  infant  is  an  open  question.  As  differentiation  continues, 
what  may  later  become  fear  and  anger  arise  from  a  sort  of  general- 
ized distress:  fear  at  sudden  shock,  anger  at  interference.  Delight, 
in  due  course,  becomes  joy  and  affection." 

Any  "marked  interference"  with  the  normal  functioning  of  the 
infant's  organism  seems  to  lead  to  "impleasant  emotions"  which 
appear  to  be  a  reaction  to  the  restraining  of  the  child's  free  action 
—as  John  Watson  observed— of  infantile  rage. 

During  early  phases  of  development,  the  clinging  and  sucking 

s  For  this  \'ocabulary  of  infant  emotion,  see  K.  M.  B.  Bridges,  "A  Genetic 
Theory  of  Emotions,"  Journal  of  Genetic  Psychology  ( 1930),  37,  pp.  514-26. 


i;^^  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

reflexes  of  the  infant  are  linked;  later  the  act  of  clinging  becomes 
more  purposive,  more  deliberately  aimed  at  support.  In  fact,  cling- 
ing for  support  occurs  when  the  child  experiences  his  own  bodily 
weight  as  a  challenge  and,  as  Paul  Schilder  puts  it,  "strives  to 
make  himself  independent  of  others  in  preserving  his  equilibrium."  ' 

The  motor  actions  of  the  child  move  him  toward  the  world  of 
objects  around  him,  which  is  full  of  danger  and  the  possibility  of 
physical  trouble.  His  fear  of  danger  is  a  response  to  what  happens 
to  him  when  he  reaches  and  falls.  He  may  also  fear  loss  of  food, 
or  of  bodily  support,  or  even  of  the  stroking  of  his  skin  by  another. 

Parents  may,  of  course,  play  upon  these  fears  in  a  great  variety 
of  ways.  "The  Kaffirs  terrorize  their  children  with  tales  of  horrid 
monsters.  The  Manus  try  to  evoke  evil  bush  demons,  but  the  chil- 
dren, trained  to  self-reliance,  physical  bravery,  and  the  experi- 
mentation necessary  for  effective  physical  adjustment  to  their  pile- 
dwelling  life,  take  very  little  stock  in  these  bogey-men.  As  adults, 
they  are  the  only  Oceanic  people  I  know  of  who  are  not  afraid  of 
the  dark."  * 

The  contents  of  fear,  as  well  as  of  other  emotions,  undergo 
change  as  the  psychic  structure  matures.  The  infant  exhibits  what 
may  be  taken  to  be  fear  in  response  to  intense  or  sudden  stimuli, 
to  unexpected  or  unfamiliar  events.  During  their  first  year  after 
birth,  one  group  of  children  belonging  to  urban,  upper-income 
American  families  experienced  fear  in  response  to  noises  and  events 
associated  with  noises,  to  falling  or  sudden,  unexpected  move- 
ments, and  to  persons  or  objects  associated  with  pain.  From  be- 
tween two  to  six  years  of  age,  the  fear  of  noise,  of  falling,  and  of 
strange  persons  tends  to  decline. 

As  their  spheres  of  social  activity  are  enlarged,  the  fears  of 
children  involve  more  complex  and  wider  circumstances.  They  no 
longer  fear  some  of  the  things  they  previously  feared,  but  they 
become  afraid  at  signs  of  danger,  and  they  experience  imagined 
fears.  Signs  of  fear  seem  to  appear  when  the  child  knows  enough 
to  recognize  possible  danger,  but  cannot  understand  nor  control 
it.  The  proportion  of  their  fears  in  response  to  being  left  alone— 
especially   in   the   dark— of   imaginary   creatures,   and   dreamed   of 

"  "The  Relation  Between  Clinging  and  Equilibrium,"  International  Journal 
of  Psijchoanalysis,  Vol.  20  (1939),  p.  62. 

'^  Margaret  Mead,  "The  Primitive  Child,"  Handbook  of  Child  PsijcJiology, 
Carl  Murchison,  ed.  (2d  ed;  rev.;  Worcester:  Clark  Univ.  Press,  1933),  p.  682. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        I.35 

events  tend  to  increase.  With  his  enrollment  in  school,  the  Ameri- 
can child  meets  competitive  situations  and  is  subject  to  many 
achievement  ratings.  At  about  this  age,  he  also  experiences  fear 
relating  to  personal  prestige  and  achievement,  as  shown  by  his 
tear  of  social  exclusion  and  personal  inadequacy.  And  as  he  grows 
older,  the  proportion  of  such  fears  increases. 

The  immature  psychic  structure  does  not  yet  have  organized  and 
effective  outlets.  A  temper  tantrum— in  which  the  child  bursts  into 
disorganized  mass  behavior,  kicking  the  floor  and  screaming— may 
be  the  only  way  in  which  he  can  let  out  his  anger  or  aggression 
against  adults.  Later,  as  the  psychic  structure  is  more  integrated 
and  disciplined  by  foresight  of  consequences,  the  style  of  rage  and 
of  aggression  usually  becomes  more  pointed  and  effective.  In  this 
respect,  there  are  differences  in  children's  psychic  development 
according  to  the  class  position  of  their  parents.  In  New  York  City, 
as  L.  B.  Murphy  has  shown,  the  chance  for  children  to  display 
and  express  such  traits  as  affection  and  helpfulness  is  apparently 
freer  and  greater  in  lower  economic  groups  than  in  children  from 
professional  families  with  higher  incomes.^ 

3.  Learning 

The  development  of  habits  requires  a  chance  to  practice  them. 
Boys  who  grow  up  on  a  flat  desert  do  not  develop  so  readily  as 
mountain  boys  the  network  of  habits,  the  postural  swing  and  the 
leg  work,  required  in  skiing.  And  what  is  true  of  motor  skills  is 
also  true  of  psychic  traits  and  social  conduct.  Many  traits  which 
are  often  thought  of  as  "inborn"  may  be  traced  back  to  the  simple 
fact  of  ample  and  early  opportunity  for  practice. 

We  may  thus  ask  of  the  total  situation  of  a  child— his  home  and 
school  and  the  play  space  provided— what  opportunities  are  given 
for  the  practice  of  this  or  that  skill  or  trait?  Opportunity  for  prac- 
tice is  a  very  important  feature  of  the  child's  development.  The 
more  the  child  can  practice  some  skill  or  trait,  the  more  will  op- 
portunities for  further  practice  be  given  him.  Whereas  children 
who  have  had  less  practice  and  so  less  skill  will  often  be  afforded 
still  less  practice.  The  structures  which  we  build  up  facilitate  and 
limit  the  functions  we  can  later  learn  to  perform.   Other  people 

^Social  BeJuwior  and  Child  Personality  (New  York:  Columbia  Univ.  Press, 
1937)- 


1S6  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

often  let  us  put  our  best  foot  forward;  that  is  why  the  worst  foot 
often  fails  to  develop. 

"The  Samoan  child  is  taught  to  sit  cross-legged  almost  as  soon 
as  it  can  sit  at  all.  .  .  .  The  baby's  hands  are  clapped  to  the  dance 
rhythm  while  it  is  an  infant  in  arms,  and  as  soon  as  it  can  stand 
it  is  taught  to  dance.  Ten-year-old  Samoan  children  are  so  set  in 
their  postural  and  rhythmic  patterns  of  their  conventions  that  I 
found  it  impossible  to  teach  them  so  simple  an  activity  as  skipping, 
and  sitting  upon  a  chair  for  any  length  of  time  is  torture  to  them. 
Manus  children,  however,  taught  physical  skill  and  agility  rather 
than  any  formal  set  of  postures,  could  adapt  themselves  to  new 
physical  activities  with  ease."  ^° 

In  modern  Western  societies  there  is  not  so  heavy  a  weighting 
of  early  successes  and  failures.  Premiums  and  taboos  are  often  re- 
laxed in  recognition  of  the  child's  immaturity.  Yet  premiums  and 
taboos  are  used  to  facilitate  and  retard  certain  lines  of  develop- 
ment. If  crying  and  whining  are  "rewarded"  by  social  attention 
and  fondling,  crying  and  whining  will  become  more  and  more  used 
as  infantile  tools.  But  if  whining  goes  unrewarded  it  will  not  be  as 
likely  to  develop  into  a  stable  bid  for  attention. 

Such  techniques  and  traits  as  are  successful  in  the  cradle  and 
home  may  become  firmly  integrated  and  used  in  the  school.  When 
some  such  pattern  as  whining  is  established  and  linked  with  satis- 
faction, this  habit  may  prove  an  obstacle  to  further  and  more  inde- 
pendent learning.  We  do  not  readily  undo  patterns  of  behavior 
which  achieve  satisfactions.  Habituation  enables  the  child  effec- 
tively to  meet  certain  situations,  but  it  narrows  the  versatility  of 
response  to  these  situations.  Training  may  thus  incapacitate  one 
for  further  learning,  as  well  as  provide  a  basis  for  it. 

The  repeated  performance  of  identical  tasks  leads  to  routine 
practice.  With  the  security  which  habits  lend  the  individual  in 
these  situations,  the  attention  and  feelings  at  first  involved  are  now 
minimized;  they  become  available  for  an  expanding  area  of  new, 
not  yet  routinized,  experiences.  The  novice  at  handball  is  painfully 
aware  of  the  way  he  holds  his  hands  and  body;  the  expert  can  keep 
his  eye  on  the  ball. 

The  young  child  finds  few  fields  for  early  triumphs  of  learning 
in  the  mastery  of  self-chosen  tasks.  But  as  his  attention  and  feelings 

1"  See  Margaret  Mead,  op.  cit. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        l^J 

are  freed  by  the  automatic  service  of  habit,  he  can  then  strive 
further  to  "stand  on  his  own  feet."  Development  is  more  an  achieve- 
ment than  an  unfolding,  but  the  general  direction  of  conscious 
learning  shifts  as  the  integration  and  organization  of  automatic 
activities  proceed. 

4.  Language  and  Person 

The  first  vocal  sounds  of  the  baby  are  aspects  of  a  more  gener- 
alized "mass  activity"  involving  almost  all  portions  of  the  organism. 
This  mass  activity  and  crying  modifies  the  baby's  social  environ- 
ment: persons  are  stimulated  to  do  things  for  and  to  the  infant. 
At  first,  the  infant's  movements  are  "an  amorphous  mass  of  activ- 
ity"; later,  specific  or  segmental  activities  are  articulated,  which 
involve  only  local  parts  of  the  organism.  Although  both  generalized 
and  segmental  movements  may  be  consequences  of  internal  phys- 
iological stimulation,  from  an  early  period  the  responses  of  other 
persons  are  likely  to  be  differentiated  according  to  the  infant's 
movements.  These  different  responses  of  others  help  the  infant 
to  articulate  segmental  movements;  in  time,  he  learns  to  use  his 
movements  and  cries  as  instruments  for  the  control  of  others. 

The  growth  of  language  in  the  child  is  undoubtedly  the  most 
important  single  feature  of  his  development  as  a  person. ^^  Lan- 
guage becomes  his  most  important  tool  in  dealing  with  others  and 
with  himself.  The  infant's  cries,  signaling  others  to  attend  to  it, 
are  components  of  mass  actions  in  response  to  internal  or  environ- 
mental discomforts;  later  the  child  babbles,  thus  engaging  in  seg- 
mental action— the  use  of  the  voice.  Sometimes  babbling  seems 
like  an  outlet  of  exuberant  energies,  at  other  times  like  a  response 
to  irritations,  and  at  all  times  it  is  rhythmic.  Thus  babies  play  with 
their  voices,  if  we  may  call  babbling  vocal  play. 

The  first  spontaneous  cries  of  the  infant  and  child  are  not  socially 
meaningful,   but  others   respond   to   certain   of  these   noises,   thus 

^1  On  the  language  de\'el()pment  of  the  child,  see  Frank  Lorimer,  TJie 
Growth  of  Reason  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1929);  G.  H.  Mead,  Mind, 
Self,  and  Society  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1934);  J.  Markey,  The 
Symbolic  Process  and  Its  Integration  in  Cliildren  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace, 
1928);  Jean  Piaget,  The  Language  and  Thought  of  the  Child  (New  York: 
Harcourt,  Brace,  1926);  and  especially  D.  McCarthy,  Language  Development 
■of  the  Freschool  Child,  Institute  of  Child  Welfare,  Monograph  series,  No.  4 
(Minneapolis:  Univ.  of  Minnesota,  1930). 


138  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

socially  confirming  them.  In  time,  the  sounds  become  fixed  units 
calling  forth  adult  actions  which  bring  the  child  bodily  comfort 
and  social  attention.  The  baby  who  cries  ends  up  with  a  com- 
fortable diaper. 

The  babblings  of  the  child  become  socialized  speech  when  he 
addresses  his  hearers  in  an  expressive  efi^ort  to  influence  them,  when 
he  becomes  aware  that  a  given  sound  which  he  makes  is  going 
to  call  forth  a  certain  response  in  another.  As  the  talking  experience 
of  the  child  increases,  his  speech  becomes  more  socialized  and 
comprehensible  to  others.  The  early  incomprehensible  babbling 
is  split  into  "internal  speech"  and  comprehensible  "outer  speech." 
The  vocal  sounds  of  American  children  of  both  sexes  at  one  and 
one-half  years  are  only  about  one-fourth  comprehensible;  but  com- 
prehensibility  increases  until  at  four  years  practically  all  that  the 
child  says  is  understandable.  What  begins  as  a  component  of  mass 
activity  in  response  to  organic  discomforts  becomes,  after  three 
or  four  years,  a  chief  feature  of  a  little  person,  who  has  several 
hundred  words  with  which  to  ask  naively  simple  and  penetratingly 
disarming  questions  about  himself  and  the  world. 

There  are,  of  course,  differences  in  the  rate  and  type  of  chil- 
dren's linguistic  developments,  and  these  differences  often  corre- 
spond to  the  social  and  economic  position  of  their  families.  Thus 
an  early  study  asserts  that  "the  child  of  the  rich  understands  more 
words  and  less  actions,  and  the  child  of  the  poor  less  words  and 
more  actions."  More  recent  studies  have  indicated  that  the  "ex- 
pansion of  a  child's  environment  ,  .  .  tends  to  increase  nouns  rela- 
tively to  other  parts  of  speech.  Conversely,  with  a  constant  or 
relatively  constant  environment,  the  other  parts  of  speech  will 
increase  relatively  to  the  nouns."  Upper-class  children  tend  to  do 
better  than  lower-class  children  on  tests  which  involve  linguistic 
ability,  the  differences  between  the  educated  and  the  working 
class  sometimes  being  the  equivalent  of  about  eight  months  in 
linguistic  development.  These  differences  in  linguistic  development, 
corresponding  to  economic  and  educational  level  of  family,  are 
not  to  be  attributed  to  differences  in  "intelligence."  ^- 

1-  Summary  of  results  obtained  by  Cliamberlain,  Drever,  and  Descoeudres, 
Stern  and  Markey,  Handbook  of  Child  Psychology,  D.  McCarthy,  pp.  303-04. 
Cf.  also  Frank  J.  Kobler,  "Cultural  Differences  in  Intelligence,"  The  Journal 
of  Social  Psychology   (1943),  Vol.   18,  pp.  279-303- 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        l^g 

Some  time,  usually  rather  late  in  childhood,  the  child  appears 
to  need  persons  who  are  on  his  level,  who  have  similar  attitudes 
and  feelings  toward  the  adult  world.  He  is  no  longer  content  to 
live  with  more  or  less  authoritarian  adults,  and  more  or  less  com- 
plaisant toys  and  pets.  He  requires  an  environment  of  persons 
significantly  like  himself,  and  with  these  equals  he  learns  to  com- 
pete, co-operate,  and  compromise. 

As  the  child  becomes  a  person— acquires  language  and  begins 
to  enact  roles— these  social  acquisitions  interact  with  the  maturing 
features  of  the  organism  and  the  psychic  structure.  Emotion,  per- 
ception, and  impulse  are  caught  up  in  the  integration  of  his  childish 
roles,  and  these  roles  pattern  his  impressions  into  focused  percep- 
tions, elicit  and  style  his  gestures  and  feelings,  discipline  his  im- 
pulses into  purposes. 

The  manner  in  which  perception  is  socially  stereotyped  ranges 
from  admonitions  in  specific  situations  ("look  this  way,"  "pay  atten- 
tion to  this")  to  a  more  subtle  building  up  of  sensitivities  by  means 
of  vocabularies  for  color  or  social  relations.  The  perceptions  thus 
socially  directed  are  accompanied  by  feeling  tones  of  pleasure  or 
displeasure  with  which  they  are  integrated. 

The  impulses  of  the  psychic  structure  tend  to  be  disciplined 
into  those  activities  which  are  socially  held  to  be  "proper"  conduct. 
By  assuming  roles  under  the  guidance  of  others,  we  form  and  re- 
form the  elements  of  our  psychic  structures:  some  are  shaped  by 
our  sensitivity  to  what  others  think,  as  well  as  by  the  tribulations 
caused  by  our  own  impulses.  "When  a  young  man,"  E.  M.  Forster 
once  remarked,  "is  untroubled  by  passions  and  sincerely  indiffer- 
ent to  public  opinion  his  outlook  is  necessarily  limited."  ^^  It  is  nec- 
essary, although  sometimes  difficult,  to  link  our  passions  with  the 
opinions  of  others,  and  during  early  adolescence  the  stress  and 
strain  of  the  attempt  may  become  quite  acute. 

5.  Four  Theories  of  Biography 

There  are  at  least  four  general  conceptions  of  "the  crucial  stage" 
of  the  human  biography.  They  include:  I,  the  cross-sectional  view 
of  functional  autonomy;  and  the  polar  opposite:  H,  the  genetic 
view,  which  emphasizes  infanthood.   Between  these  two  are  HI, 

^^  Howard's  End  (New  York:   Knopf,   1921),  p.  24. 


1^0  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

the  autonomous  hierarchal  view  and  IV,  the  theory  of  the  adoles- 
cent upheaval. 

I.  According  to  the  strictly  cross-section  view,  the  motives  and 
traits  of  the  adult  character  structure  are  "self-sustaining."  To  un- 
derstand them  we  have  only  to  examine  the  contemporary  posi- 
tion of  the  person,  and  the  function  of  traits  and  motives  within 
his  total  character.  For  although  these  traits  and  motives  may  have 
"grown  out  of  antecedent  systems,"  they  are  at  any  given  moment 
viewed  as  "functionally  independent  of  them."  The  tie  between 
earlier  experiences  and  the  present  character  is  thus  seen  as  strictly 
"historical,  not  functional."  Although  contemporary  features  of 
character  are  continuous  with  earlier  experiences,  they  do  not  in 
any  sense  depend  upon  them.  To  understand  a  given  character 
and  its  traits,  we  must  study  its  present  structure  and  position.^* 

II.  At  the  other  extreme,  the  adult  character  structure  is  viewed 
longitudinally  or  genetically.  Everything,  no  doubt,  has  a  history, 
and  it  may  be  thought  that  everything  about  a  character  structure 
is  present  in  seed-form  at  birth.  Maturation  is  then  conceived  as 
a  more  or  less  mechanical  unfolding  of  what  was  already  there. 
To  understand  a  character  structure  and  its  traits,  according  to 
this  view,  we  must  grasp  it  in  its  beginnings.  This  view  tends  to 
place  great  weight  upon  biological  factors,  and  it  conceives  of 
the  experiences  of  infancy  and  childhood  as  the  most  important 
features  of  the  biography  of  a  character  structure.^^ 

III.  Between  the  attempt  to  understand  all  features  of  a  char- 
acter in  terms  of  its  contemporary  structure  and  situation,  and  the 
attempt  to  know  all  contemporary  features  in  terms  of  its  genetic 
development,  there  is  the  position  that  at  each  of  several  age 
levels  of  experience  a  system  of  traits,  feelings,  and  experiences 
develop.  The  experiences  belonging  to  adult  life  are  then  under- 
stood as  occupying  a  position  higher  than  those  assumed  by  the 

1*  This  position  has  been  taken  by  Gordon  W.  Allport  with  reference  to 
motives;  he  terms  it  the  theory  of  "functional  autonomy"  in  his  Personality:  A 
Psychological  Interpretation  (New  York:  Holt,  1937),  pp.  190-212,  especially 

P-   194- 

15  This  position,  of  course,  owes  much  to  the  work  of  Freud;  although  it 
is  a  position  which  many  nonfreudians  share  with  Freud.  See  below,  this 
section. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        I4I 

experiences  of  youth,  and  these,  in  turn,  stand  above  the  experi- 
ences of  childhood.  The  more  recently  acquired  experiences  are 
assumed  to  control  the  experiences  of  earlier  phases  of  the  biog- 
raphy. Each  such  level  is  thus  a  "storehouse"  of  the  experiences 
of  each  phase  of  the  biography,  and  each  of  these  levels  "preserves 
in  its  mode  of  action  the  characteristics  of  the  mentality  in  which 
it  had  its  origin."  When  we  dream  of  infantile  experiences  or  feel- 
ings, the  later  levels  have  temporarily  lost  their  controlling  function 
and  we  regress  to  re-experience  the  earlier  formations.  Just  as  we 
may  lose  control  of  our  motor  habits  as  when  the  skilled  craftsman 
ruins  his  carving  by  a  clumsy  slip  of  the  chisel,  so  may  we  let 
infantile  or  adolescent  feelings  or  self-appraisals  slip  into  aware- 
ness when  the  control  of  a  later  level  of  experience  and  integration 
of  the  psychic  structure  or  person  lapses.  What  is  normally  con- 
trolled becomes  for  an  instant  controlling.^'^ 

IV.  Another  theory  of  development  holds  that  the  leading  char- 
acteristics of  the  adult  character  structure  arise  and  are  set  at  the 
adolescent  juncture  of  the  biography.  Adolescence  is  viewed  as  a 
new  birth,  or,  in  G.  Stanley  Hall's  words,  as  "the  infancy  of  man's 
higher  nature."  ^^  Although  the  child  may  be  father  to  the  man, 
in  adolescence  a  new  child  is  created.  The  individual,  Hall  con- 
tinues, is  "reduced  back  to  a  state  of  nature,  so  far  as  some  of 
the  highest  faculties  are  concerned,  again  helpless  .  .  .  The  flood- 
gates of  heredity  are  thrown  open  again  somewhat  as  in  infancy." 
Childhood  unity  and  integrations  are  "broken  up"  and  "powers  and 
faculties,  essentially  nonexistent  before,  are  now  born."  Some  older 
impulses  are  reinforced  and  greatly  developed;  others  are  subor- 
dinated and  lost.  The  self  finds  a  new  center.  "Love,"  according  to 
Hall,  "is  born  with  all  its  attendant  passions— jealousy,  rivalry  .  .  ." 
The  "old  level"  of  childhood  is  "left  forever."  Like  milk  teeth  juve- 
nile interests  fade  away,  and  the  "well  matured  .  .  .  [have]  utterly 
lost  all  traces  and  perturbations  of  the  storm  and  stress  period,  be- 
cause they  are  so  contradictory  and  mutually  destructive,  and 
because  feelings  themselves  cannot  be  well  remembered." 

16  This  position  has  been  set  forth  by  W.  H.  R.  Rivers  in  "Freud's  Concept 
of  the  Censorship,"  reprinted  in  Psychology  and  Ethnology  (New  York:  Har- 
court.  Brace,  1926),  pp.  21-35. 

1"  The  view  summarized  in  tliis  paragraph  is  tliat  of  G.  Stanley  Hall.  See 
his  Adolescence  (New  York,  D.  Appleton,  1904),  Vol.  2,  especially  pp.  70-73. 


1^2  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

The  strictly  cross-sectional  view  treats  experience  and  character 
as  functionally  autonomous  at  any  given  moment  of  the  biography. 
The  relations  of  past  experience  to  present  character  are  simply 
historical,  and  not  connected  in  any  functional  way. 

The  extreme  genetic  view  treats  the  present  traits  of  character 
as  simply  unfolded  features  of  what  was  given  at  birth  in  seed-form, 
or  alternatively,  as  experiences  which  in  later  life  operate  as  prec- 
edents or  models  structuring  new  experiences  in  their  terms. 

The  third  view  which  we  may  call  the  theory  of  biography  as  an 
autonomous  hierarchy  accepts  the  genetic  emphasis  upon  child- 
hood and  the  identity  between  early  experiences  and  later  regres- 
sive traits,  but  also  accepts  the  cross-sectional  view  of  each  age 
level  of  experience  as  autonomous  in  its  respective  action.  To  these 
acceptances,  it  adds  the  autonomy  and  retention  of  earlier  systems 
of  experience  and  the  view  that  these  earlier  ssytems  may  be  re- 
experienced  when  the  controlling  function  of  later  systems  relaxes, 
as  in  dreams  and  various  phenomena  of  the  unconscious. 

In  the  fourth  view— the  theory  of  adolescent  origins— we  see  the 
adult  orientation  and  the  leading  features  of  a  character  structure 
as  arising  from  an  adolescent  upheaval.  We  take  this  period  in  the 
life  history  as  the  most  important  for  the  formation  of  adult  char- 
acter.^^ 

What  shall  we  make  of  these  theories?  How  can  we  best  realize 
the  truth,  if  any,  in  each  of  them? 

6.  The  Theorij  of  Adolescent  Upheaval 

The  theory  that  adult  character  is  "born"  in  adolescent  upheaval 
is  open  to  two  major  criticisms,  one  of  principle  and  one  of  ade- 
quate fact. 

I.  The  principle  is  that  of  selective  and  cumulative  development. 
Although  it  is  not  feasible  to  telescope  all  contemporary  trends  and 
traits  of  a  character  structure  into  its  past,  it  is  necessary  to  see 
past  organizations  of  conduct,  feeling,  and  attitude  as  setting  a 
limit  within  which  later  developments  may  occur.  In  this  sense, 
our  past  does  limit  and  select  our  present,  and  in  turn  these  selec- 

1^  Our  brief  statement  of  these  four  views  is  an  intentional  simplification  of 
Allport,  Freud,  Rivers,  and  Hall,  respectively.  We  are  not  writing  a  history  or 
a  systematic  account  of  positions  held  by  various  scholars.  Hence,  we  select 
and  stress  basic  ideas  without  quahfications  in  order  to  set  forth  sharp  contrasts. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        14^ 

tions  become  part  of  the  total  selective  structure.  Development 
is  thus  cumulative.  To  be  sure,  there  are  rapid  accelerations  and 
sudden  conversions  and  traumatic  reverses,  but  these,  too,  are 
explainable  in  terms  of  diverse,  often  inadequate,  integrations  and 
selectivities  in  the  line  of  biographical  development. 

II.  The  most  telling  criticism  of  the  theory  of  adolescent  up- 
heaval, however,  has  to  do  with  fact.  The  theory  assumes  that 
adolescence  is  always  an  upheaval,  and  of  course  this  is  not  the 
case.  It  takes  as  universal  the  rather  extreme  experience  of  adoles- 
cence in  the  modern  West,  and  more  specifically  the  middle-class 
experience  with  its  prolonged  gap  between  organic  capacity  for 
and  actual  assumption  of  the  adult  roles  of  marriage  and  of  the 
job.  From  the  standpoint  of  an  adequate  comparative  sociology, 
we  see  at  once  that  ours  is  merely  one  possible  way  in  which  a 
society  may  handle  the  changes  of  puberty.  Some  societies  are  so 
organized  that  these  organic  changes  are  passed  through  with 
no  upheaval  at  all. 

Biologically,  adolescence  extends  from  puberty  to  physiological 
maturity.  Chronologically,  it  may  begin  as  early  as  eight  years 
and  last  until  as  late  as  twenty-five.  The  individual's  growth  is 
accelerated  and,  sometimes  to  a  lesser  degree,  his  co-ordination 
improved.  Some  organs,  such  as  the  heart  and  the  organs  of 
reproduction,  grow  in  size  very  rapidly,  while  others,  such  as  the 
brain,  do  not  perceptibly  increase.  During  puberty  the  voice  tends 
to  fluctuate,  "changing"  before  it  settles  down. 

Since  "the  further  one  moves  from  birth,"  as  Sullivan  has  written, 
"the  less  relevant  an  absolute  physiological  chronology  becomes, 
the  epoch  of  adolescence  is  the  least  fixed  in  terms  of  bodily 
changes.  Adolescence  varies  from  culture  to  culture,  and  its  actual 
time  of  appearance  in  young  people  among  us  is  very  widely 
varied."  Interactions  with  significant  others  "are  the  predominating 
factors  in  bringing  about  delays  .  .  .  and  accelerations  ...  in 
the  later  stages  of  personality  development."  ^" 

The  "quiet  miracle  of  preadolescence"  in  American  society  usu- 
ally occurs  between  the  ages  of  nine  to  twelve.  It  is  not  a  sudden 
happening  but  the  continuation  of  a  trend  toward  a  fuller  social 
integration.    Early   adolescence    is   marked   by   the   fact   that  "the 

19  Harry  Stack  Sulli\an,  "Conceptions  of  Modern  Psycliiatr\ ,"  rsychiatry 
(February  1949),  Vol.  Ill,  No.  1. 


144  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

satisfactions  and  the  security  which  are  being  experienced  by  some- 
one else,  some  particular  other,  begin  to  be  as  significant  to  the 
person  as  are  his  own  satisfactions  and  security."  Indeed,  one's 
own  satisfactions  and  security  are  facilitated  by  the  satisfactions 
and  securities  of  the  loved  one.  Perhaps  at  this  point  the  approval 
of  a  significant  other  takes  on  its  sharpest  significance.  This  fact 
goes  far  to  explain  the  usual  and  much  discussed  social  behavior 
of  adolescence  in  American  society.  The  social  upheaval  of  adoles- 
cence—especially typical  of  the  middle-class  young  man  or  woman 
—results  in  large  part  from  this  intensified  need  and  awareness  of 
the  approval  of  others. 

But  why  this  awareness  and  this  need?  The  roles  played  by  the 
American  adolescent  approximate  adult  roles,  yet  the  adolescent 
seems  only  to  play  them.  In  two  key  roles  in  particular,  the  boy 
is  not  yet  fully  adult:  he  is  not  integrated  with  a  durable  mate 
by  marriage,  and  he  does  not  fulfill  a  regular  occupational  role. 
Economically  and  emotionally  he  is  still  a  dependent,  and  because 
of  this  he  often  strives  all  the  harder  to  be  accepted  as  an  adult. 
He  shaves  the  downy  cheek,  and  plays  the  man  with  girls,  older 
girls  if  possible,  to  the  fullest  extent  of  his  abilities  and  opportuni- 
ties, and  for  want  of  sexual  gratification  he  masturbates. 

In  American  society,  adolescence  is  a  juncture  at  which  childhood 
roles  are  abandoned  and  adult  ones  not  yet  fully  available  or 
internalized.  Adolescence  is  a  major  point  of  social  reorientation 
and  since  the  person  is  in  this  transition,  previous  integrations  of 
person  and  psychic  structure  are  likely  to  be  loosened.  Often  these 
integrations  undergo  such  extreme  modification  that  it  is  no  wonder 
some  students  view  it  as  a  social  rebirth. 

Among  the  typical  features  of  adolescence  in  modern  Western 
societies,  especially  among  middle-class  children,  are  an  increase  of 
inner  absorptions  and  reverie,  of  self-criticism  and  sometimes  a 
drastic  tightening  up  of  scruples;  there  is  frequently  an  extreme 
assertion  of  individuality,  a  susceptibility  to  poses,  mannerisms, 
affectations;  there  are  all-absorbing  friendships. 

These  general  characteristics  may  be  summed  up  by  the  state- 
ment that  imitation  ^°  and  identification  -^  as  processes  of  develop- 

-0  Imitation  is  the  conscious  patterning  of  behavior  upon  a  model  afforded 
by  otlicr  persons.  It  is  learning  by  example. 

-1  Identification  is  the  unconscious  taking  on  of  traits  which  another  dis- 
plays. It  refers  to  a  development,  without  awareness,  in  the  direction  of  an- 
other person. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        14^ 

ment  and  learning  are  often  at  their  height  during  adolescence, 
or  at  least  they  are  more  open  to  our  observation. 

Conceivably,  one  could  coast  through  childhood  under  guard 
and  guidance  without  ever  being  absorbed  in  one's  self.  But  at 
adolescence  one  must  make  decisions  on  one's  own,  and  face  many 
models  which  would  guide  one  in  these  self-scrutinies  of  develop- 
ment. The  rest  of  one's  life  as  a  person  will  consist  largely  of  getting 
in  and  being  accepted  and  getting  out  of  voluntary  associations, 
and  such  decisions  must  now  be  faced  in  some  earnest.  The  middle- 
class  adolescent,  in  deciding  the  general  directions  that  this  cumu- 
latively selective  process  of  his  social  career  will  take,  wants  to 
find  out  what  kind  of  man  he  seems  really  to  be.  And  so  he  will 
usually  experiment  with  the  models  and  self-stylizations  available 
to  him. 

In  ancient  Sparta  and  in  many  preliterate  societies  definite  tests 
of  fitness  for  adult  roles  were  specified  and  known  to  adolescents. 
In  the  modern  West  the  very  standards  of  adulthood  are  often 
contradictory,  various,  and  not  readily  accessible  to  youth.  During 
the  teen  age,  the  requirements  for  adult  roles  are  often  temporarily 
lowered.  This  allows  the  psychic  structure  an  increased  opportu- 
nity: One  can  be  inebriated  without  the  use  of  intoxicants,  as 
sensitivities  and  emotionalisms  expand  and  hot  and  cold  feelings 
may  alternately  flood  the  adolescent.  So  he  is  the  more  easily 
carried  away  by  total  euphoria  or  equally  total  despair. 

It  is  characteristic  of  modern  Western  societies  not  to  have  a 
generally  understood  and  clearly  demarcated  "threshold"  between 
childhood  and  adulthood.  Religious  rites  such  as  "confirmation" 
remain  segmental,  as  they  do  not  coincide  with  the  transition  from 
school  years  to  employment  and  marriage.  As  we  have  noted,  two 
major  choices  are  expected  of  the  individual,  the  choice  of  occupa- 
tion—more and  more  closely  connected  with  problems  of  educa- 
tion—and the  choice  of  a  mate.  Having  the  "freedom"  to  make 
these  choices  for  himself,  the  individual  also  takes  on  the  respon- 
sibility for  his  choices,  that  is,  "he  has  no  one  to  blame  but  him- 
self." During  times  of  mass  unemployment  it  is  difficult  to  say  who 
feels  more  at  a  loss  for  advice,  the  parents  or  their  grown-up  chil- 
dren. 

The  pressure  on  adolescents  to  commit  themselves  to  vocational 
choices  varies  according  to  the  social  and  economic  status  of  the 
parents;   the  higher  the   class   position   of  the   youth's  home,   the 


146  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

longer  time  he  has  to  make  up  his  mind.  The  social  elevator  of 
higher  education  carries  the  youngster  past  entire  fields  of  inferior 
occupational  choices,  up  to  vantage  points  from  which  he  may 
assess  opportunities  which  otherwise  would  not  be  concretely  vis- 
ible, much  less  available.  Thus,  the  well  provided  student  "can 
wait."  Similar  differences  in  the  time  of  waiting  have  been  shown 
to  differentiate  lower-  and  upper-class  youth  with  regard  to  sexual 
conduct.  Whereas  the  lower-class  youth  comes  to  consummate  nor- 
mal sexual  activity  at  the  biologically  adequate  age,  middle-class 
youth  waits  until  presumably  the  attainment  of  the  coveted  social 
and  occupational  status  position  permit  things  "which  can  come 
later."  In  the  meantime,  there  are  the  widespread  substitute  grati- 
fications of  adolescence— masturbation  and  necking— and  the  accom- 
panying frustrations  incited  further  by  the  imageries  of  eroticism 
that  are  ubiquitous  in  advertising,  the  pulps,  and  slick  celluloid. 
One  result  of  all  this  is  often  an  inarticulate  giggle  pattern  among 
middle-class  youngsters,  especially  the  girls. -- 

~-  Cf.  Alfred  C.  Kinsey,  Wardell  B.  Pomeroy,  and  Clyde  E.  Martin,  Sexual 
Behavior  in  the  Human  Male  (Philadelphia  and  London:  Saunders,  1948), 
which  contains  data  on  the  sexual  behavior  of  5,300  white  American  men, 
who  co-operated  in  interviews.  Regardless  of  allowances  that  may  have  to  be 
made  with  regard  to  precise  details  and  small  differences  in  proportions,  Dr. 
Kinsey 's  major  findings  concerning  the  differences  between  lower-  and  higher- 
class  members  are  so  great  that  we  do  not  believe  more  precise  and  rigorously 
controlled  studies  are  likely  to  change  their  direction  and  therewith  their 
significance.   The  following  facts  are  from   "The  Kinsey  Report": 

The  working  class  adolescent  engages  in  sexual  intercourse  earlier,  although 
frequently  more  promiscuously  than  the  middle-  and  upper-class  youth,  who 
more  frequently  seek  substitute  gratifications  through  masturbation,  homo- 
sexual activities,  petting,  or  involuntary  although  experienced  nocturnal  emis- 
sions. Youths  between  sixteen  and  twenty  years  of  age  with  grade  school 
educations  find  less  than  30  per  cent  of  dieir  "sexual  outlet"  in  masturbation 
and  57  per  cent  in  intercourse;  college  men,  however,  find  66  per  cent  of 
their  outlet  in  masturbation,  and  10  per  cent  in  intercourse.  High  school  boys 
of  the  same  age  stand  midway  between  the  two  groups.  Among  college  men 
up  to  twenty-five  years  of  age,  petting  to  a  climax  accounts  for  nearly  half 
as  much  of  the  total  outlet  as  does  intercourse.  Such  petting  is  the  compromise 
which  allows  the  college  girl  to  preserve  technical  chastity  and  at  the  same 
time  to  be  helpful  in  granting  her  lover  substitute  gratification.  College  men 
rank  lowest  in  homosexuality,  with  2.4  per  cent  of  their  sexual  outlet  in 
this  form;  grade  school  and  high  school  boys  find  6.9  and  10.8  per  cent  of 
their  total  outlet  in  homosexual  activities. 

Such  figures  indicate  that  different  values  and  attitudes  prevail  among 
lower   and   higher   classes   in   matters   of   sex   which   in   turn   reflect   broader 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        14-/ 

Biological  adolescence  is  over  with  the  completion  of  puberty. 
Social  adolescence  is  over  when  the  person  is  regularly  expected  to 
enact,  and  does  enact  with  greater  or  lesser  conformity,  the  roles 
which  adults  of  his  social  position  typically  perform.  But  when  is 
"psychological"  adolescence  over  and  full  adulthood  established? 
The  psychiatrist  Stack  Sullivan  held  that  the  adult  is  one  who  has 
established  "durable  situations  of  intimacy  such  that  all  the  major 
integrating  tendencies  are  freely  manifested  within  awareness  in 
the  series  of  one's  interpersonal  relations."  -' '  This  is  an  adequate 
definition  of  adulthood.  It  is  also  an  expression  of  a  philosophy  of 
life  for  free  men  and  women  living  in  modem  society. 

7.  The  Relevance  of  Childhood 

We  must  reject  the  philosophical  assumption  of  the  extreme 
genetic  theory  that  a  biography  is  simply,  or  even  primarily,  a 
mechanical  unrolling  of  traits  already  present  at  birth  in  seed-form. 
This  mechanical  theory  of  growth  must  be  rejected  even  for  the 
organic  features  of  character;  and  we  have  already  seen  that  both 
the  person  and  the  psychic  structure  are  formed,  developed,  and 
integrated  very  largely  through  the  mediation  of  other  persons. 
The  maturation  of  character  structure  is  not  determined  by  inner 
features  of  development,  just  as  it  is  not  shaped  altogether  by  the 

characterological  differences.  Eli  Ginzberg  has  stressed  that  "these  essential 
differences  between  the  two  classes"  re\'ol\e  around  the  fact  that  the  entire 
environment  of  the  poor  boy  operates  to  place  a  premium  on  current  gratifica- 
tion, for  the  future  is  not  propitious,  at  least  no  more  so  than  the  present. 
There  is  little  or  no  rational  basis  for  his  "delaying  gratification."  But  the 
college  boy's  "entire  existence  is  in  the  nature  of  a  postponement.  He  is 
using  up  parental  capital  rather  than  adding  to  it;  he  is  studying  today  in 
order  to  profit  tomorrow.  He  has  been  trained  to  accept  postponement  in 
gratification  and  he  has  also  been  encouraged  to  seek  gratification  from  other 
experiences— his  studies,  his  sports,  his  extracurricular  acti\ities.  By  recourse- 
to  masturbation  and  petting,  he  manages  to  reach  a  tolerable,  if  not  a  de- 
sirable, equilibrium.  He  can  wait:  for  him  the  future  is  propitious."  See  Elir 
Ginzberg,  "Sex  and  Class  Behaxior"  in  About  the  Kinsey  Report,  Observations 
by  11  Experts  on  "Sexual  Behavior  in  the  Human  Male"  Donald  Porter 
Geddes  and  Enid  Curie,  eds.  (New  York:  Signet  Special,  1948),  p.  136;  cf. 
also:  Morris  L.  Ernst  and  David  Loth,  American  Sexual  Behavior  and  the 
Kinsey  Report  (New  York:  Bantam,  1948).  The  detailed  tabulations  are  taken 
from  the  Kinsey  Report,  pp.  374-83,  417-48,  488-93. 
-■^  "Conceptions  of  Modern  Psychiatr>',"  op.  cit. 


148  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

external  forces  of  the  environment.  The  human  biography  results 
from  the  interplay  of  inner  features  of  character  previously  given 
and  acquired,  w^ith  the  external  world  of  man  and  nature,  and 
with  hopes  and  fears,  demands  and  expectations  of  the  future.  We 
caU  this  interplay  "experience,"  and  we  know  that  it  continues, 
although  at  different  pace  and  with  differing  intensity,  throughout 
the  individual's  biography. 

In  our  attempt  to  answer  the  question  of  how  much  weight 
we  should  assign  infant  and  childhood  experiences  in  the  adult 
character,  we  must  pay  attention  to  two  questions: 

I.  What  types  of  infant  and  childhood  experiences  are  most  likely 
to  be  important  in  influencing  the  formation  of  an  adult  character 
structure? 

II.  How  do  these  experiences  "influence"  adult  character?  Or, 
what  are  the  mechanisms  that  connect  earlier  experiences  with 
later  traits  of  the  character  formation? 

I.  Two  general  and  interrelated  types  of  infant  and  childhood 
experience  may  be  especially  important  in  forming  the  structure 
of  childhood  character:  (a)  The  impact  of  the  social  constellations 
of  the  family  and  the  child's  reactions  to  them;  and,  (b)  the  sanc- 
tions and  regulations  of  such  organic  functions  as  feeding,  excre- 
tion, and  the  sensations  of  sex.^* 

All  experiences  of  the  infant  and  of  child  are  socially  limited,  or 
even  determined,  by  the  kinship  structure,  for  it  is  the  personnel 
of  this  structure  who  administer  to  the  organic  needs  of  the  young 
member,  and  it  is  their  relations  to  one  another  and  to  the  child 
that  are  his  first  social  contacts.  The  infant  must  be  covered  and 
warmed  and  cooled,  lest  he  die  from  inappropriate  temperatures; 
he  must  breathe  air  through  his  own  mouth  and  nose;  others  must 
feed  him.  Biologically,  the  child  is  helplessly  dependent  upon 
others,  and  particularly  upon  those  who  have  most  to  do  with  his 
creature  comforts,  as  well  as  his  privations  and  discomforts. 

The  infant-mother  relationship  is  often  intimate  to  the  point  of 

24  For  an  excellent  summary  and  critique  of  the  literature  on  "infant  care 
and  personality"  see  Harold  Orlansky's  article  of  that  title,  Psychological  Bul- 
letin, Vol.  46,  No.  1,  pp.  1-48.  His  conclusion  is  generally  negative.  See  also 
W.  H.  Sewell,  "Infant  Training  and  the  Personality  of  the  Child,"  Amer.  Journ. 
of  Sociology,  Vol.  LVHI,  No.  2,  September  1952,  pp.  150-59. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        I49 

forming  an  emotional  communion.  If  the  mother  did  not  want  the 
child,  or  is  frightened  or  disturbed  about  something,  there  are 
often  endless  feeding  difficulties.  And  if  the  child  is  breast-fed,  the 
slightest  indigestion  on  the  part  of  the  mother  will  be  "chemically 
communicated"  to  the  infant.  Long  before  any  explicit  understand- 
ing between  mother  and  child  could  emerge,  Sullivan  has  noted, 
there  seems  to  be  an  emotional  contagion  between  them.-^ 

The  very  biological  dependency  of  the  infant  and  child  upon 
some  adult  is  of  great  aid  to  the  infant's  becoming  a  full-fledged 
human  being.  He  becomes  a  person  because  others  are  indispen- 
able  to  him  as  an  organism;  his  helplessness  qualifies  him  for  great 
modifications  and  vast  learning.  His  helplessness  is  due  to  the 
fact  that  the  human  animal  is  singularly  devoid  of  rigid,  innate, 
instinctive  patterns  of  behavior.  "Instinct,"  wrote  Paul  Schilder, 
"is  a  diminishing,  if  not  a  disappearing  category  in  higher  animal 
forms,  especially  in  the  human."  -® 

The  mother  is  a  social  instrument  of  the  infant's  organic  satis- 
factions: she  is  also  a  source  of  insecurities  and  anxieties.  The 
satisfactions  of  such  privations  as  hunger  depend  upon  significant 
adults,  who  usually  want  the  child  to  develop  those  traits  they 
think  well  of  and  to  avoid  those  patterns  which  they  taboo.  If  he 
does  not  meet  their  expectations,  the  adults  may  deprive  him  of 
organic  satisfactions  as  well  as  social  attention.  Since  the  child, 
according  to  L.  L.  Bernard,  "does  not  think  that  deprivation  may 
occur  in  the  natural  course  of  events,  but  is  rather  the  result  of 
ill-will,"  deprivation  seems  "equivalent  to  aggression  and  vio- 
lence" and  often  the  child  will  react  with  counteraggressions.^^ 

Child  clinicians,  psychiatrists,  and  nursery  students  have  taught 
the  social  psychologist  the  important  role  childhood  experiences 
may  play  in  the  early  formations  of  emotional  life.  In  this  connec- 
tion, of  course,  one  overlooks  the  contributions  of  Freud  only  at  the 
risk  of  serious  omission.  Whereas  pre-Freudian  psychologists  saw 
early  childhood  as  a  psychological  state  of  paradisaical  Innocence, 
Freud  taught  us  to  view  this  stage  as  problematic  and  crucial  for 
the  formation  of  character.  What  Freud  did,  in  brief,  was  to  con- 

25  Cf.  Harry  Stack  Sullivan,  op.  cit.,  pp.  7,  8. 

26  See  Paul  Schilder,  Goals  and  Desires  of  Man  (New  York:  Columbia  Univ. 
Press,  1942),  p.  79- 

-~  Instinct   (New  York:    Holt,   1924),  p.   509. 


1^0  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

nect  the  formation  of  character  with  the  structure  of  authority  in 
the  family. 

Within  the  kinship  structure,  there  is  an  interplay  between  depri- 
vations and  satisfactions,  between  the  organic  needs  of  the  child 
and  the  authoritative  agency  of  socialization  which  provides  for 
these  needs.  The  family  upon  which  the  child  is  dependent  is  thus 
the  early  context  of  his  insecurities  and  of  his  gratifications.  The 
child's  experience  of  the  organs  of  his  body  and  his  recognition  of 
what  he  can  and  what  he  should  not  do  with  them  is  guided  by 
adults,  who  try  to  regulate  the  rhythm  of  such  functions  as  excre- 
tion and  sexual  sensations  as  well  as  his  attitude  toward  them. 

The  regulations  of  organic  functions  and  the  social  impact  of 
family  roles  upon  the  child  are  closely  related  experiences.  For 
what  Freud  called  the  Oedipus  and  Electra  complexes— attraction 
for  the  parent  of  the  opposite  sex  and  jealousy  toward  the  other- 
is,  as  Karen  Horney  notes,  simply  "engendered  by  the  parent's  care 
of  the  physical  needs  of  the  child,"  -®  and  by  the  child's  dependency 
upon  the  parent  for  this  care. 

The  decisive  childhood  drama  of  man's  psychic  life  was  schema- 
tized by  Freud  in  terms  of  the  identification  of  the  male  child 
with  the  father  of  the  family  who  establishes  for  his  boys  his  model 
of  primary  aspiration.  As  the  father  loves  the  mother  so  does  the 
son,  who  thus  becomes,  as  did  Oedipus,  the  father's  competitor  for 
the  exclusive  love  of  the  mother.  For  the  female  child  a  similar 
early  triangle  is  supposed  to  be  repeated,  which  Freud  called 
the  Electra  complex.  These  complexes  may  originate  from  the  end 
of  the  first  year  up  to  the  age  of  four  or  five:  however,  the  critical 
age,  according  to  most  psychoanalysts,  is  between  three  and  five. 

Schemes  of  this  sort  have  the  great  merit  of  showing  early  char- 
acter formations  in  the  social  context  of  the  family.  By  knitting 
together  such  strong  motives  and  mechanisms  as  love,  identifica- 
tion, and  authority,  they  provide  useful  explanatory  models.  It  is, 
however,  a  model  that  is  open  to  much  abuse— even  in  the  hands 
of  its  originator. 

One  of  Freud's  greatest  shortcomings  is  that  he  understood  this 
process  as  at  least  quasi-biologically  set,  and  hence  a  universal 
occurrence;  but  this  is  a  universalization  of  a  partial  observation, 
for  it  overgeneralizes  the  psychic  impact  of  a  particular  type  of 

^^  New  Ways  in  Psychoanalysis  (New  York:   Norton,   1939),  p.  791. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        1$1 

kinship  organization— that  of  the  occidental,  patriarchal  family. 
Freud,  as  a  sociological  thinker,  was  thus  handicapped  by  Freud, 
as  a  medical  man.  His  formulation  pointed  toward  an  important 
sociological  phenomenon,  but  it  was  not  itself  sociologically  in- 
formed. Yet  the  internalization  of  a  family  constellation  by  the 
character  structure  of  its  youngest  member  was  an  important  point 
to  observe. 

Preliterate  as  well  as  historical  societies  show  a  great  variety 
of  kinship  structures,  of  which  the  patriarchal  organization  repre- 
sents only  one.  In  the  absence  of  the  patriarchal  family  one  cannot 
very  readily  expect  the  Oedipus  complex  to  develop  in  the  child's 
character,  much  less  exert  an  influence  upon  the  later  adult.  And 
even  within  patriarchal  families,  this  complex  is  probably  not  uni- 
versal. "Restrictive  discipline  and  companionship,"  Meyer  Nimkoff 
has  shown,  "are  two  .  .  .  factors  of  importance  in  determining  the 
child's  relations  to  his  parents.  In  general  .  .  .  that  parent  will  be 
preferred  who  offers  more  in  the  way  of  companionship  and  exacts 
less  in  the  way  of  discipline."  ^^  The  preference  for  the  mother  may 
thus  be  connected  with  that  type  of  patriarchal  family  in  which 
the  mother  is  a  source  of  maternal  tenderness  and  care  and  the 
father  is  the  more  severe  disciplinarian.  The  development  of  an 
equalitarian  family  in  which  the  parents  are  equally  responsible 
for  discipline  and  for  companionship  leads  to  the  child's  equal 
preference  for,  or  equal  independence  from,  both  parents.  The 
connection  of  types  of  child  preference  and  identification  with 
types  of  family  structure  is  not,  of  course,  completely  uniform. 

The  Hopi  child  shows  no  marked  preference  for  either  parent, 
having  agreeable  relations  with  both.  The  Samoan  child,  who  like 
the  upper-class  English  child  does  not  typically  reside  with  his 
parents,  has  a  minimum  relation  with,  and  is  usually  emotionally 
independent  of,  them.  Marquesan  children  of  both  sexes  prefer 
their  fathers,  who  are  their  adult  companions;  their  mothers,  be- 
ing specialized  as  courtesans  to  the  limited  number  of  males, 
neglect  or  even  abuse  them.  In  the  Marquesan  situation  there  are 

29  "The  Child's  Preference  for  Father  or  Mother,"  American  Sociological 
Review,  August  1942,  pp.  517-25.  Several  of  the  cases  which  are  given 
below  in  the  te.xt  are  taken  from  citations  in  this  excellent  summary  article. 
Others  are  from  Margaret  Mead's  article,  op.  cit.,  and  her  Coming  of  Age  in 
Samoa  (New  York:  Morrow,  1928);  and  from  Wayne  Dennis,  The  Hopi  Child 
(New  York:   D.  Appleton-Century,   1940). 


152  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

more  males  than  females,  a  definite  maternal  neglect,  few  restric- 
tive regulations  on  the  sex  life  of  the  child,  and  no  punishments. 
There  does  not  occur  in  this  society  any  Oedipus  complex,  and 
females  are  usually  represented  in  a  hostile  manner  rather  than  as 
inflated  images  of  maternal  tenderness.^*' 

In  Freud's  formulation,  the  father  is  the  child's  sexual  rival  and 
has  the  most  potent  authority.  Yet  these  functions  are,  after  all, 
determined  by  a  particular  kinship  structure. 

The  peasant  father  often  exploits  his  sons  in  work,  whereas  the 
prosperous  middle-class  fathers  may  treat  theirs  as  sources  of 
pleasure  and  display.  In  some  societies,  family  relations  locate 
family  jealousies  between  brothers,  rather  than  between  father  and 
son;  in  other  societies  in  which  there  are  strong  brother-sister 
taboos,  jealousies  are  likely  to  occur  between  brothers  over  their 
sisters,  rather  than  over  their  mother. 

Authority  certainly  does  not  stop  with  the  father;  the  authori- 
tarian regulation  of  impulse  and  of  conduct  may  begin  in  the  fam- 
ily and  with  the  father,  but  they  are  continued  in  later  epochs  of 
the  biography  by  sanctions  of  the  school,  church,  and  job,  and  ulti- 
mately by  the  state. 

Bronislaw  Malinowski  has  compared  the  Oedipus  complex  of 
European  patriarchal  society  with  the  situation  among  the  Tro- 
briand  Islanders.  In  the  latter  case,  the  husband  of  the  mother 
is  not  the  authoritative  male  in  the  life  of  the  child.  The  mother's 
brother,  or  the  child's  maternal  uncle,  is  the  authoritative  male, 
while  the  child's  father  is  merely  a  kindly  counselor,  a  helper  and 
companion.  The  Trobriand  father  does  not  support  his  wife  and 
child,  but  rather  his  sister  and  her  children.  The  wife,  therefore, 
is  economically  dependent  upon  her  own  brother,  who,  as  a  ma- 
ternal uncle,  is  the  arbiter  and  disciplinarian  of  the  child.^^ 

In  United  States  society,  the  child's  dependence  upon  the  mother 
is  used  by  her  to  enforce  certain  regulations  upon  the  child.  Among 
the  Marquesans,  such  dependence  is  frustrated  by  the  absence  of 
the  mother's  care,  but  no  restrictive  regulations  of  organic  and  so- 
cial activity  are  imposed.  Children  are  more  independent  at  an 

•*°  Abram  Kardiner,  The  Individual  and  His  Society  (New  York:  Columbia 
Univ.  Press,   1939),  p.  248. 

31  See  Sex  and  Repression  in  Savage  Society  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace, 
1927)  and  H.  D.  Lasswell's  critique  of  Malinowski's  work  in  Methods  in 
Social  Science,   S.   H.   Rice,   ed.    (Chicago,    1931),   pp.   480  ff. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        l^^ 

earlier  age  than  in  the  United  States  and  acquire  a  self-confidence 
which  contrasts  sharply  with  the  lack  of  confidence  in  similar  age 
groups  in  Western  societies. 

The  Oedipus  constellation,  with  its  close  blend  of  dependence 
upon  and  craving  for  the  mother,  occurs  most  frequently,  accord- 
ing to  A.  Kardiner,  "in  societies  where  the  sexual  goal  is  interfered 
with  in  childhood.  In  societies  where  Oedipus  attachment  does 
occur,  it  should  be  viewed  as  the  result  of  kinship  organization  and 
restrictive  regulations  on  childhood  sexual  tendencies  which  tend  V^ 
to  prolong  and  complicate  the  dependency  of  the  child."  ^^ 

Tha  imprint  of  family  roles  upon  the  child's  character  thus  varies 
with  the  kinship  arrangement.  The  social  conditions  which  the 
child  experiences  and  his  psychic  reactions  to  them  must  be  care- 
fully reconstructed  if  we  are  to  understand  his  early  character 
formation. 

II.  To  the  individual  himself,  the  most  obvious  manner  in  which 
any  earlier  phase  of  his  biography  may  influence  later  phases 
is  memory.  Memory  seems  to  be  an  inner  connection  between 
events  and  experiences  along  the  biographical  line.  It  also  seems 
to  be  closely  connected  with  language.  Memory  is  past  experience 
regained  by  an  act  of  attention. 

The  young  child  lives  in  the  immediate  present,  and  probably 
does  not  have  much  conception  of  the  past  or  of  the  future.  His 
impulses  demand  immediate  gratification  and  he  cannot  delay  and 
wait  upon  the  future  to  satisfy  them.  He  cries.  For  the  adult, 
experience  is  a  conjunction  of  past  memories,  present  situations, 
and  anticipations  of  the  future.  To  recapture  the  past  by  memory, 
surmount  the  immediate  present,  and  anticipate  the  future  by 
imagination,  requires  the  guidance  and  use  of  signs.  "In  studying 
infantile  situations  and  infantile  experiences,"  Paul  Schilder  has 
written,  "we  should  not  forget  that  it  is  difficult  to  come  to  clear 
conclusions  transcending  the  mere  observational,  since  language— 
the  most  reliable  sign  system— is  either  absent  or  not  developed  in 
the  child."  33 

•^'-  Op.   cit.,  pp.  481-82. 

^^  Goals  and  Desires  of  Man  (New  York,  1942),  p.  129.  For  a  wonderfully 
sensitive  account  of  memory— which  unfortunately  we  came  upon  only  after 
this  book  was  in  press— see  Ernest  G.  Schachtel,  "On  Memory  and  Childhood 
Amnesia,"  reprinted  in  A  Study  of  Interpersonal  Relations,  P.  Mullahy,  ed. 
(New  York:  Hermitage  Press,  1949). 


1^4  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

Language  gives  us  the  pegs  upon  which  memories  as  well  as 
future  anticipations  may  be  fixed.  Stenographic  reports  of  the 
two-  to  three-year-old  child  indicate  this  connection  of  memory 
with  symbols  and  verbal  processes.  Once  linked  to  organic  habits, 
psychic  feelings,  or  segments  of  experience,  symbols  may  be  con- 
stantly reorganized  in  memory  and  imagination. 

We  remember  others  from  whom  we  have  been  separated  ac- 
cording to  our  desires  and  fantasies,  and  the  same  is  true  of  our 
memories  of  our  own  past  selves.  The  photographs  and  the  stories 
'^old  us  by  others  limit  this  work  of  reconstructive  fantasy,  but 
not  altogether,  for  the  act  of  perception  is  also  a  construction  that 
-is  often  influenced  by  our  fantasies  and  anticipations,  and  the 
stories  our  mother  and  other  relatives  tell  us,  to  which  we  listen, 
■md  which  we  remember,  are  not  usually  the  whole  story.  Mothers 
are  not  notable  as  scientific  observers  of  their  children. 

Although  patterns  formed  by  the  impressionable  experiences  of 
the  childhood  epoch  may  be  difficult  to  dissolve  by  subsequent 
experiences,  their  influences  upon  the  adult  do  not  seem  to  be 
primarily  transmitted  by  explicit  memory.  Those  experiences,  actual 
or  imaginary,  which  were  not  explicitly  nor  adequately  symbolized 
are  more  likely  to  be  the  bearers  of  our  past  which  influences  our 
present  and  future.  But  just  how  do  these  early  formations  influ- 
ence later  formations  of  character? 

The  conditioning  of  reflexes  and  the  development  of  habits  dur- 
ing the  childhood  phase  of  the  organism  may  carry  over  into  later 
life.  It  is  doubtful  that  they  persist  in  identical  form,  though  they 
may  persist  in  newer  integrations  and  they  do  limit  the  later  habits 
that  can  be  acquired.  There  is  continuity  and  development,  not 
mere  repetition;  there  is  a  cumulative  selection  exerted  by  previ- 
ously organized  habits.  Habits,  developed  in  one  phase  of  the  biog- 
raphy, are  thus  often  unconscious  determinants  of  later  habits. 
We  may  be  quite  unaware  of  them,  until  they  get  us  into  trouble 
or  limit  our  learning  of  new  ways.  Habits  are  among  the  persistent 
heritages  from  the  training  and  history  of  our  bodies. 

It  is  the  psychic  structure  that  is  perhaps  most  crucial  in  this 
question  of  the  adult  burden  of  childhood  experiences.  Given 
societies,  for  example,  do  not  conventionally  symbolize  many  phases 
of  emotional  experiences.  Sexual  interests  and  sensations  may  thus 
remain  outside  the  verbalized  areas  of  the  character,  and  yet  de- 
termine conscious  conduct  and  psychic  life.  For  the  childhood  feel- 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        1^^ 

ings  and  imagination  that  are  not  socialized  and  anchored  by  ver- 
bahzation  may  nevertheless  exert  an  influence  upon  later  psychic 
life.  In  fact,  the  influence  of  such  unconscious  elements  and  linkages 
may  be  all  the  more  controlling  because  they  are  not  normally 
remembered  and  brought  to  awareness.  No  symbolic  organization 
is  socially  provided  for  them.  And,  like  the  mass  activities  of  the 
infant,  such  elements  may  avalanche  upon  the  person  during 
severe  crises  or  strains.^* 

Fears  which  the  child  experiences  with  reference  to  sex  may  be 
tabooed  in  conversation  and  hence  remain  unverbalized,  unana- 
lyzed,  and  subject  to  the  constructions  and  modifications  of  imagi- 
nation. Because  of  the  conventional  taboos  and  inadequate  vocabu- 
laries on  the  part  of  the  parents,  a  verbal  lag— as  far  as  the  psychic 
structure  is  concerned— is  typical  in  Western  societies.  It  has  been 
noted,  by  Norman  Cameron, ^"^  that  among  some  strata  in  Western 
civilization  "sexual  attitudes  enter  relatively  seldom  into  social 
communication.  The  ratio  of  sexual  attitudes  functioning  in  private 
to  those  freely  and  genuinely  shared  with  the  community  is  dis- 
proportionately high  when  compared  with  most  other  commonly 
held  attitudes."  That  is  why  the  imagery,  motives,  the  day  and 
night  dreams,  and  uncontrolled  ve/balization  in  the  authoritatively 
controlled  yet  intimate  interview,  are  likely  to  reveal  a  large  per- 
centage of  sexual  content.  And  yet,  as  we  have  already  noted,  the 
ready  availability  of  sexual  imagery  and  themes  in  public  life— 
in  magazines  and  movies,  as  well  as  in  "unwritten  literature,"  in 
highly  informal  channels— naturally  attracts  the  child's  attention 
and  concern.  It  is  fair  to  assume  that  most  children  of  any  given  age 
are  more  "knowing"  than  most  parents  (and  teachers)  think  they 
are. 

The  verbal  lag  is  facilitated  by  conventional  suppression  and 
lack  of  a  happy  rapport  with  parents  during  later  epochs  of  the 
biography.  The  experience  and  the  imagination  of  the  child  and 
later  of  the  adolescent  continue  to  interplay  with,  reinforce,  or 
repress  these  emotional  cravings  and  impulsive  squirmings  of  the 
psychic  structure,  which  show  up  in  the  giggles  of  girls  and  the 

3*  See  A.  Kardiner,  The  Traumatic  Neuroses  of  War  (London:  Hoeber, 
1941).  See  also  the  acute  remarks  on  \erbal  organization  in  Lorimer,  op.  cit., 

pp.  185  fr. 

'■^•'  See  "The  Paranoid  Pseudo-Community,"  American  Journal  of  Sociologtj, 
July   1943,  p.  36. 


1^6  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

whistles  of  boys.  They  may  therefore  be  unintegrated  aspects  of 
the  adult  character,  and  may  be  repeated  in  the  adult  character  in 
a  form  identical  with  their  childhood  shape.  More  typically,  how- 
ever, they  are  modified  and  fulfill  some  contemporary  function 
within  the  adult's  integration.  Yet  they  may  not  be  adequately 
integrated,  and  hence  may  be  in  conflict.  In  trying  fully  to  under- 
stand the  adult  character,  as  Karen  Homey  has  held,  we  must 
grasp  these  so-called  infantile  elements  as  they  function  contem- 
poraneously. 

To  think  of  infantile  trends  of  the  psychic  structure  as  being 
repeated  in  identical  form  in  the  adult  is  to  assume  that  they  re- 
mained "isolated  and  unaltered "  by  subsequent  developments.  Ob- 
servations—such as  the  child's  tendency  to  repeat  previous  experi- 
ences, the  re-experience  of  traumatic  incidents  in  similar  or  iden- 
tical detail,  the  practice  recall  of  past  experiences  under  condi- 
tions of  the  psychoanalytic  interview— these  observations  can  be 
adequately  explained  on  grounds  other  than  that  of  a  supposed 
persistence  in  the  adult  of  childhood  experiences.^*^  Moreover,  the 
undue  genetic  emphasis  is  open  to  the  criticism  that  it  does  not 
explain  why  the  childhood  trends  and  traits  persist.  Normally,  the 
person  "grows  out  of  them,"  or  at  least  they  do  not  seem  to  oper- 
ate within  the  adult  character.  But  why  do  they  persist  in  certain 
cases?  ^^y  V:gQ^c\si^^^ 

To  answer  this  we  have  to  examine  the  whole  adult  psychic  and 
character  structure  and  find  out  what  role  they  perform  in  their 
dontemporary  setting.  In  the  adult  character  supposedly  childish 
emotions  and  techniques  of  conduct  may  have  a  meaning  and  ful- 
fill a  function  quite  different  than  in  the  child.  A  woman  may  cry 
like  a  child,  but  her  crying  after  all  may  not  be  very  childish. 

The  influence  of  children's  ex-perience  upon  their  adult  char- 
acters may  leave  a  residue  which  can  be  directly  discerned.  Thus, 
we  "spontaneously"  like  or  dislike  a  person  because  this  person  is 
linked  with  early  memories  of  people  whom  as  a  child  we  experi- 
enced pleasantly  or  unsatisfactorily.  More  importantly,  the  influ- 
ence of  the  childhood  experience  may  be  due  to  the  simple  fact 
that  the  adult  character  structure  develops  from  the  one  formed 
in  childhood.  It  is  in  childhood  that  the  character  is  first  formed 

■'"  This  position  is  taken  by  Karen  Homey,  see  op.  cit..  Chapters  4,  8,  and 
9,  especially  pp.  136-38  and  158. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD         I57 

and  the  adult  one  is  thereby  started.  Although  one  may  not  often 
draw  a  straight  and  isolated  line  from  an  adult  trait  back  to  a  spe- 
cific childhood  experience,  one  can  see  that  the  experiences  which 
formed  the  adult  character  include  the  childhood  structures  and 
developed  from  them.  If  early  traits  fit  in  with,  and  reinforce  pres- 
ent trends  of  character,  they  are  all  the  more  likely  to  exert  an 
influence  upon  the  adult's  conduct  and  experience. 

The  general  direction  and  the  degree  of  this  development  de- 
pend upon  the  adult  functions  which  traits  acquired  in  childhood 
may  come  to  have.  And  as  we  shall  now  see,  the  answer  to  this 
psychological  question  also  depends  upon  distinctively  sociological 
factors. 

8.  The  Social  Relutivitij  of  Childhood  Influences 

To  answer  the  questions  of  how  much  weight  we  should  assign 
to  the  childhood  phase  of  the  biography,  and  what  adult  features 
of  character  are  most  likely  to  be  infantile  in  origin,  we  have  to 
know  something  about  the  full  biography  and  something  about 
the  society  in  which  it  is  lived  out.  We  have  to  consider  entire 
biographical  patterns,  not  only  as  they  are  lived  out  but  as  they 
are  laid  down  in  different  social  structures.  Let  us  first  discuss 
several  types  of  societies  which  permit  very  different  answers  to 
our  general  question. 

If  the  pace  of  social  change  is  rapid,  then  the  world  of  youth  is 
more  likely  to  be  different  from  the  adult  world.  Historical  tempo 
is  not  of  course  the  only  condition  leading  to  such  differences 
between  child  and  adult.  Even  if  the  rate  of  social  change  is  slow, 
the  age  stratification  of  the  society  may  be  very  rigid  and  the 
things  expected  of  the  child  very  different  from  those  expected  of 
the  adult.  Still  another  factor  favoring  differences  in  roles  played 
by  the  youthful  and  by  the  mature  is  the  extent  of  the  societies' 
complexity.  For  this  means  that  there  may  be  complicated  roles 
which  take  time  to  learn  to  enact  in  an  acceptable  and  mature 
manner. 

Yet  this  need  not  be  the  case,  for  a  complex  society  may  be 
specialized  in  such  a  way  that  any  one  person  need  only  learn  his 
specialty:  the  child  may  have  to  develop  beyond  the  youthful  roles 
only  in  one  or  two  respects— such  as  the  job;  the  remainder  of  his 
roles  may  not  be  so  very  different  from  those  he  learned  in  child- 


1^8  CHARACTER     STRUCTURE 

hood;  these  roles  may  continue  to  work  quite  well  throughout  the 
person's  biography. 

An  extreme  division  of  labor  and  specialization  may  block  the 
development  by  practice  of  features  other  than  those  held  suitable 
to  childhood.  Only  in  the  skills  required  for  the  specialty  will  de- 
velopment occur.  Thus  the  theoretical  expert  may  be  relatively 
undeveloped  in  manual  skills,  not  knowing  how  to  use  a  snow 
shovel  or  lathe,  or  he  may  be  "deficient"  in  the  capacity  for  mature 
love  and  affection,  experiencing  throughout  his  life  an  adolescent 
embarrassment  in  front  of  all  women. 

If  in  a  society  there  are  many  large  differences  between  the  roles 
expected  of  the  child  and  the  roles  of  the  adult  world,  then  pat- 
terns acquired  during  childhood  are  less  likely  to  be  successful  if 
they  persist  in  the  adult.  Accordingly  we  may  ask  of  any  given 
society,  how  many  psychic  or  character  traits  which  "worked,"  in 
childhood  continue  to  secure  satisfactions  and  security  in  adult 
life? 

A  narrow  gap  between  the  child  and  the  adult  world  may  be 
due  to  a  lack  of  complexity,  the  intrinsic  difficulties  and  diversities 
of  the  roles  in  the  adult  society,  or  to  the  fact  that  the  expectations 
for  adults  are  from  a  very  early  period  focused  upon  the  child. 

Societies  differ  greatly  in  the  degrees  to  which  childhood  roles 
approximate  those  of  adults.  Thus,  among  the  Chuckchees,  child- 
hood seems  "largely  an  imitation  of  the  life  of  elders."  ^^  "The 
plains  Indians  constructed  for  their  children  miniature  camps, 
encouraged  them  to  enact  the  scenes  of  adult  life;  the  Samoans 
banish  children  from  even  imitating  adult  conditions  and  give 
them  small  tasks  graded  to  their  skill;  the  Kaffirs  give  their  chil- 
dren unpleasant  jobs  and  lie  about  the  facts  of  life,  and  the  chil- 
dren retaliate  by  developing  a  small  outlaw  state  with  a  secret 
language  and  spy  system  of  its  owai.  The  Manus  use  play  only  to 
develop  physical  proficiency,  no  attempt  to  instill  the  cultural  con- 
ventions or  the  industrial  techniques  is  made."  ^^ 

To  view  anxiety  in  an  adult  as  an  infantile  attitude  is  "to  con- 
fuse two  different  things,  to  mistake  for  an  infantile  attitude  an  atti- 
tude merely  generated  in  childhood.  With  at  least  as  much  justifi- 
cation as  calling  anxiety  an  infantile  reaction  one  might  call  it  a 

3^  See  Abram  Kardiner,  op.  cit.,  p.   121. 

38  See  Margaret  Mead,  "The  Primitive  Child,"  Handbook  ...  p.  680. 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        l$g 

precocious  attitude  in  a  child."  •^'•'  It  is,  in  large  part,  a  question  of 
the  size  of  the  social  gap  between  child  and  adult  with  reference 
to  specific  traits  and  roles. 

Infant  or  childhood  patterns  which  are  successful  in  satisfying 
the  infant  or  child  are  less  likely  to  be  modified  or  dropped.  If 
many  childhood  patterns  are  not  agreeable  to  an  adolescent's  peers, 
he  will  cling  to  them  only  at  the  risk  of  losing  prestige.  In  America 
the  modifications  and  rejections  of  childhood  patterns  are  accom- 
panied by  a  good  deal  of  the  pose  of  toughness  and  the  mannerisms 
taken  to  be  the  adult  swagger.  A  society  that  not  only  contains  a 
large  gap  between  the  expectations  on  various  age  groups  but 
which  is  also  very  rapidly  changing,  thus  accentuating  this  gap, 
will  typically  require  many  changes  of  trait  and  mannerism  in  the 
course  of  the  biography. 

If  the  early  adolescent  cannot  find  new  alternative  patterns 
which  can  replace  the  gratifications  of  the  older  patterns  he  is  more 
likely  to  cling  to  childhood  ones.  If  the  sequence  of  life  experi- 
ences permits  gratifications  to  accrue  from  these  early  patterns, 
repeated  in  adolescent  and  adult  worlds  without  much  modifica- 
tion, we  may  speak,  not  of  repetition,  but  of  social  lines  of  facili- 
tation. 

These  lines  are  just  as  important  in  understanding  the  persist- 
ence of  childhood  or  adolescent  traits  as  are  the  original  experi- 
ences of  childhood  or  adolescence  during  which  the  traits  were 
acquired.  Indeed  they  may  be  more  important,  and  they  are  cer- 
tainly more  immediately  relevant  to  the  understanding  of  the  func- 
tion of  the  trait  within  the  adult  character  structure. 

The  conception  of  social  lines  of  facilitation  permits  us  to  indi- 
vidualize our  discussion  of  the  differing  bearings  of  such  social 
factors  as  age  stratification  upon  the  adult  persistence  of  traits 
acquired  during  childhood.  Of  any  given  person  and  his  society 
we  may  ask:  Has  this  person  found  adult  roles  which  permit  or 
even  encourage  the  continued  use  of  traits  acquired  during  child- 
hood? 

There  are  certain  types  of  marriage,  for  instance,  the  success  of 
which  rests  upon  tacit  agreement  to  allow  the  husband  or  the 
wife,  or  both,  to  play  the  child  or  adolescent  in  certain  roles  and 
aspects  of  personality.  Housewives  may  thus  successfully  employ 

39  K.  Homey,  The  Neurotic  Personalitij  of  Our  Time  (New  York:  Norton, 
1937),  P-  78. 


l6o  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

the  infantile  tear,  or  the  temper-tantrum,  or  the  form  of  hysteria 
known  as  the  crying-jag,  in  order  to  achieve  their  ends.  In  popular 
songs,  phrases  like  "sugar  daddy"— social  expressions  and  facilita- 
tions of  infantilism— are  explicitly  revealed:  "O!  Daddy!"  one  such 
"incest  song"  runs,  "You  ought  to  get  the  best  for  me!"  And  an- 
other: "While  knocking  off,  a  game  of  golf,  I  may  make  a  play 
for  the  caddy;  but  when  I  do,  I  don't  follow  through,  'cause  my 
heart  belongs  to  daddy." 

The  weight  of  childhood  in  adult  character  is  conditioned  by 
regression  under  traumatic  experience,  the  adult  function  of  traits 
within  the  adult  character,  the  spread  of  the  age-structure  of  a 
society,  and  by  the  availability  and  use  of  social  lines  of  facilita- 
tion for  given  character  traits  and  formations. 

Character  structure,  as  we  have  seen  throughout  Part  Two,  refers 
to  the  unique  individual.  It  stands  for  the  individual  variations 
of  the  types  of  persons  usual  in  given  societies  or  strata  within 
given  societies.  These  variations  arise  because  of  different  constitu- 
tions and  because  of  the  different  ways  in  which  the  psychic  struc- 
ture is  integrated  with  the  person.  The  uniqueness  of  the  indi- 
vidual—the particular  composition  and  unity  which  he  achieves— 
arises  from  his  differing  experiences  and  from  his  cumulative  or- 
dering of  these  experiences.  Although  the  roles  which  two  persons 
play  and  have  played  may  seem  identical,  the  way  in  which  they 
have  each  played  them  and  the  different  sequence  in  their  respec- 
tive biographies  means  that  very  different  character  structures  are 
formed. 

Yet  all  of  the  uniqueness  and  unity  of  a  character  structure  may 
not  be  telescoped  into  the  past.  Experience  and  its  effects  involve 
an  interplay  of  past,  present,  and  future.  Unique  traits  may  arise 
from  differences  in  life  goals  and  anticipations,  as  well  as  from 
past  experience  and  present  situation.  The  future  as  well  as  the 
past  and  the  present  need  to  be  taken  into  account  in  explaining 
a  given  character  structure. 

We  do  not  simply  remember  isolated  events  in  our  past.  We 
remember  events  fitted  into  a  framework.  This  framework  is  given 
us  By  our  society,  and  that  which  fits  into  it  and  fills  it  out  may 
be  remembered  better  than  what  we  cannot  thus  locate.  It  is  re- 
ported by  Bartlett  that  after  several  members  of  a  Zulu  tribe 
visited   London   the   one   thing   which  stood  out  vividly  in   their 


BIOGRAPHY     AND     TYPES     OF     CHILDHOOD        l6l 

memories  was  the  image  of  an  English  pohceman  standing  in  traffic 
with  uplifted  arm.  This  gesture  happens  to  be  the  sign  of  greeting 
among  members  of  their  tribes;  it  was  one  of  the  few  images  that 
fitted  immediately  into  the  social  framework  of  their  memories  and 
was  retained.^" 

In  similar  manner,  the  life  plan  of  the  individual,  his  philosophy 
of  life,  and  his  expectations  and  specific  goals,  normally  fit  into  a 
large  social  framework,  which  is  typical  of  members  of  his  social 
position,  and  which  limits  the  scope  of  his  construction  of  a  pos- 
sible future.  To  limit,  however,  is  not  to  determine.  The  structure 
of  a  man's  future  as  he  sees  it  is  subject  to  marked  individual 
modification  from  the  life  plan  suggested  by  his  social  position  in  a 
particular  society  at  a  given  time. 

Problems  occur  and  decisions  must  be  formulated  which  involve 
anticipations  of  the  future  as  well  as  habits  of  the  past.  Conflicting 
expectations  exacted  of  us  by  others  do  not  necessarily  end  in  a 
deadlock  or  in  mere  drifting,  but  often  in  a  redirecting  of  our 
conduct  and  sometimes  of  our  life  plan.  Some  major  goal  of  our 
life  plan  may  be  the  rallying  point  of  present  conduct.  This  selec- 
tion of  goal  and  the  arrangement  of  present  activities  as  means  to 
its  realizations  are,  of  course,  a  distinctive  form  of  the  conscious 
and  intelligent  character.  In  varying  degrees  we  control  our  pres- 
ent conduct  by  the  future  which  we  anticipate  and  desire,  and 
just  as  we  respond  to  the  cut  of  the  knife  before  we  are  cut  by  it, 
so  we  take  roles  in  anticipation  of  the  reactions  of  others,  in  order 
to  avoid  anxieties  or  to  gain  ends  wanted. 

By  anticipation,  the  future  operates  in  the  present;  we  act  now 
in  terms  of  that  future.  These  anticipations  are  the  conditions  of 
our  present  conduct  and  stylizations  of  self.  All  experience  prob- 
ably has  such  elements  of  the  anticipated  future  in  it,  for  we  re- 
spond to  the  present  signs  of  future  objects:  we  run  when  there  is 
smoke,  although  we  have  not  seen  fire.  And  when  we  are  frustrated, 
we  seek  out  such  signs,  items  available  in  the  present  which  indi- 
cate the  future.  By  selecting  these  signs  and  changing  our  be- 
havior in  terms  of  them,  we  use  future  consequences  as  guides  for 
present  conduct. 

Were  we  fully  to  trace  out  the  biographies  typical  of  a  society's 

*oF.  C.  Bartlett,  Remembering  (Cambridge:  Cambridge  Univ.  Press,  1932), 
p.  248. 


l62  CHARACTER  STRUCTURE 

members,  from  before  birth  until  after  death,  we  would  also  have 
to  study  a  great  deal  about  the  roles  and  institutions  of  the  society. 
For  the  biography  of  a  person  consists  of  the  transformations  in 
character  which  result  from  abandoning  roles  and  taking  on  new 
ones. 


P  A  K  T    T  II  It  E  E 


SOCIAL  STRUCTURE 


CHAPTER 

VII 

Institutions  and  Persons 


IN  the  present  chapter,  we  shall  elaborate  some  of  the  ways  in 
which  persons  and  institutions  may  be  related,  thus  attempting 
to  make  clear  the  psychology  of  institutions  and  the  sociology  of 
persons.  For  we  believe  that  the  psychological  results  of  social 
relations  often  provide  the  necessary  and  sufficient  motivations  for 
personal  conduct,  and  since  social  relations  occur  within  societies, 
if  we  are  to  understand  the  single  human  being,  we  must  develop 
a  general  view  of  institutions  and  of  social  structures.  In  terms  of 
our  model  of  man  and  society,  then,  what  are  the  more  or  less 
direct  ways  in  which  character  and  social  structure  are  related? 

1.  The  Institutional  Selection  of  Persons 

"  Institutions  select  and  eject  their  members  in  accordance' with 
a  wide  variety  of  formal  rules  and  informal  codes:  Formal  pre- 
requisites for  assuming  and  relinquishing  roles  may  be  specific 
criteria  of  age,  sex,  health  (as  in  recruitment  for  the  United  States 
armed  forces ) ;  they  may  involve  elaborate  examinations  of  special- 
ized skills  or  aptitudes  or  tests  of  "personality  traits"  (as  in  the 
civil  service  or  in  many  larger  corporations).  Churches  may  recruit 
their  members  hereditarily,  by  infant  baptism,  or  they  may  demand 
self-conscious  choice  and  personal  commitment,  indicated  by  "con- 
version experiences,"  as  necessary  qualifications  for  adult  baptism. 
Such  formal  rules  may  be  supplemented  by  informal  codes  of  en- 
trance; in  fact,  it  is  quite  usual  for  both  formal  and  informal  types 
of  qualifications  to  operate  in  the  institutional  selection  of  persons. 

Birth  is  ^necessar}^  but  not  always  a  sufficient,  condition  for  the 
assumption  of  institutional  roles^The  ancient  Greeks  and  Romans, 


l66  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

for  example,  practiced  infanticide.  The  Spartan  magistrate  sur- 
veyed the  newly  born  and  selected  those  fit  to  survive;  infants 
which  this  eugenic-minded  military  man  thought  unfit  were  con- 
demned to  death  by  exposure.  The  Roman  paterfamilias  considered 
the  newly  born  "his  child"  only  after  having  ceremoniously  ac- 
knowledged it  to  be  such;  without  this  religious  act  the  unwanted 
progeny  was  subject  to  infanticide.  Thus,  in  pre-Christian  an- 
tiquity, the  child  neither  had  a  "right  to  be  born"  nor  a  "birth 
right"  to  be  reared.  Only  after  religious  induction  by  the  father 
did  it  become  a  "person"  endowed  with  "rights."  Similarly  in  cer- 
tain regions  of  India  there  are  strikingly  imbalanced  ratios  of  male 
and  female  children  because  high  castes  practice  female  infanti- 
cide, leaving  it  to  lower  castes  to  rear  brides  for  their  sons. 

Birth  alone,  then,  does  not  guarantee  that  the  newly  born  will 
be  incorporated  into  a  family,-  and  if  he  is,  he  may  be  only  a  provi- 
sional member  of  the  household.  Should  he  prove  to  be  handi- 
capped, physically  or  mentally,  to  a  degree  unsatisfactory  to  the 
relevant  institutional  orders,  the  authorities  of  these  orders  may 
"institutionalize"  him  in  another  order. 

Birth  also  places  the  Western  infant  in  a  particular  social  stratum 
and  milieu  of  a  national  state,  and,  where  "infant  baptism"  exists, 
into  a  rehgious  institution^  All  of  this,  in  Western  societies,  is  un- 
derstood to  be  part  of  "the  accident  of  birth."  In  the  United  States, 
whether  one  is  "born  with  a  silver  spoon  in  one's  mouth"  or  is  the 
descendant  of  a  Negro  slave  is  considered  to  be  a  matter  of  blind 
fate.  But  in  India,  where  the  child  is  born  into  a  caste  society  and 
there  is  belief  in  the  "transmigration  of  souls,"  no  such  "accident 
of  birth"  exists.  The  highborn  and  the  lowborn  are  believed  to  have 
"merited,"  in  compensation  for  a  previous  life,  their  respective 
fates  at  birth. 

The  more  a  society  gauges  people  in  terms  of  their  "backgrounds," 
the  more  fateful  for  them  as  individuals  will  be  their  descent  or 
"birth  right."  Thus,  the  child  does  not  enter  social  life  as  an  "orig- 
inal man."  The  stage  is  set  for  him;  with  his  birth  cry  he  an- 
nounces merely  his  claim  to  be  admitted  to  a  drama  that  has  long 
been  underway.  During  his  life  cycle  he  learns  to  assume  and  to 
discard  roles,  and  each  phase  of  his  life  offers  role  opportunities  of 
its  own. 

Age  often  determines  what  we  may  and  may  not  do^-What  the 
child  plays  in  earnest,  the  adult  may  play  for  fun;  what  the  adult 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  l6y 

plays  in  earnest  is  beyond  the  child's  ability  and  understanding. 
As  adults  we  become  "too  old"  for  some  roles;  as  children  we  are 
"still  too  young"  for  others. 

The  same  is  true  for  sexual  differences^ In  most  societies  girls 
and  boys,  women  and  men  play  certain  widely  different  roles. 
Among  adults  we  speak  of  the  "sexual  di\'ision  of  labor."  We  speak 
of  the  "housewife"  (but  not  of  the  "househusband"),  and  when  we 
speak  of  the  "provider"  we  are  usually  thinking  of  the  male  rather 
than  the  female.  Of  course,  the  interchanging  of  role  does  occur, 
as  during  the  depression  of  the  thirties.  Then  quite  a  few  women 
learned  to  earn  money  after  their  husbands  had  given  up  any  hope 
of  finding  gainful  employment.  Again,  in  the  forties,  many  a  young 
woman  was  gainfully  employed— she,  "the  provider,"  and  he,  her 
"dependent"— in  order  to  see  her  G.I.  husband  through  college. 

Before  World  War  II,  when  men  spoke  of  "women  in  arms"  they 
thought  of  ancient  Amazons  or  of  goddesses  like  Pallas  Athena 
with  lance  and  shield,  or  of  Diana  with  bow  and  arrow.  So  when 
Russian  women  made  their  appearance  as  tank-riding  soldiers  in 
the  Finnish-Russian  war  of  1939,  the  Western  world  was  taken 
by  surprise.  But  the  incorporation  of  women  into  the  United  States 
armed  forces,  as  Wacs  or  Waves,  may  be  only  the  beginning  of 
"equality  in  arms."  Once  it  was  held  that  women  had  to  be  silent 
in  church,  but  they  fought  for  and  gained  the  right  of  prophesying. 
Once  it  was  held  that  woman's  place  was  in  the  home,  that  she 
had  no  right  to  higher  education  and  professional  employment; 
but  she  "emancipated"  herself  from  such  restrictions  and  gained 
such  rights.  By  the  end  of  World  War  I,  throughout  the  Western 
world  (with  the  exception  of  France)  women  had  gained  the  right 
to  vote,  although  they  still  receive  less  compensation  for  the  same 
work  than  men  receive.  Social  differences  bet^^'een  men  and 
women,  it  is  clear,  are  due  less  to  "natural  differences"  than  to 
differences   in  institutional  opportunities. 

-Man's  weakness  in  childhood,  and  again  in  old  age,  binds  him 
close  to  the  household.  He  begins  by  learning  to  play  his  roles  in 
a  few  "primary  groups,"  in  the  family,  the  play  group,  the  neigh- 
borhood.-When  he  is  enrolled  in  kindergarten  and  grammar  school, 
in  Sunday  school  and  youth  associations,  he  is  introduced  into 
"secondary  groups."  He  learns  to  compete  for  grades,  to  struggle 
for  impersonal  standards  of  achievement,  to  abide  by  the  "rules 
of  the  game,"  to  "take  his  defeat,"  to  be  a  "good  loser,"  and  to  en- 


l68  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

joy  his  triumphs.  He  acquires  physical  and  symbolic  skills;  and  he 
learns  to  identify  with  Our  Classmates,  Our  School,  Our  Town, 
Our  Religion,  Our  Nation. 

To  grow  up,  as  we  have  said,  means  to  discard  specific  child- 
hood roles  and  to  assume  an  expanding  range  of  adult  roles.  These 
roles  make  up  the  social  content  of  our  mature  personalities. 

—Men  assuming  identical  roles  are  variously  esteemed  for  the 
ways  in  which  they  play  them.-*Thus,  we  speak  of  great  presidents 
and  of  weak  ones,  of  eminent  and  of  not-so-eminent  teachers  and 
scholars.  We  rate  persons  who  are  assuming  provisional  roles,  as 
promising  or  not  so  promising,  in  anticipation  of  their  future  con- 
tributions. These  estimates  of  the  ways  men  play  their  roles  should 
be  distinguished  from  our  estimations  of  the  roles  themselves— 
whether  these  roles  are  more  or  less  important,  of  central  or  of 
peripheral  significance;  whether  in  terms  of  social  visibility  they 
allow  the  actor  a  conspicuous  or  an  inconspicuous  position.  When 
focusing  upon  such  aspects  of  the  role  as  such,  we  often  refer  to 
"status  position,"  which  we  shall  later  discuss  in  its  psychological 
aspect.^ 

Individuals  often  experience  the  roles  they  assume  as  a  series 
of  tasks,  according  to  the  demands  and  expectations  which  others 
address  to  them.  -They  may  completely  identify  themselves  with 
certain  roles,  and  so  "put  their  hearts  into"  enacting  them>.This 
is  likely  to  happen  when  they  have  deliberately  chosen  their  roles, 
say  as  lover  and  spouse  of  this  particular  partner,  or  as  militant 
fighter  for  this  cause  and  for  no  other:  "Here  I  stand,  I  can  do  no 
other,  so  help  me  God,"  said  Luther  at  the  end  of  his  speech  before 
the  Reichstag  at  Worms.  Similar  postures  may  occur  when  men  are 
born  into  their  roles,  as  members  of  nations,  churches,  language 
communities— and  so  take  them  for  granted— or  when  they  take 
authoritative  roles  assigned  them  by  superiors,  much  as  children 
in  patriarchal  families  will  "honor"  their  parents  by  accepting  the 
marriage  partner  or  occupation  chosen  by  them. 
—  But  in  a  society  which  expects  its  youthful  members  to  choose 
their  roles  "freely,"  that  is,  at  their  own  risk 'and  accovmtability, 
the  internalization  of  roles  will  vary  greatly  in  depth^-This  is  espe- 
cially so  in  a  dynamic  context  of  competitive  values  and  contro- 
versial ideas,  for  then  some  people  may  become  confused  and  dis- 

1  See   Chapter   XI:    Stratification   and   Institutional   Orders,   Section   3:    The 
ir    Status  Sphere. 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  l6g 

cover  that  they  lack  the  capacity  to  "make  up  their  mindsr^  Others 
may  discover  that  it  does  not  pay  to  identify  themselves  with  their 
roles  too  closely  or  too  intensely^-^nd  that  a  relatively  loose  fitting 
of  the  role— while  on  the  look-out  for  the  next  chance— rather  than 
fixed  attention  to  the  task  at  hand  is  more  rewarding  and  oflEers 
more  "bargaining  power."  *  \   O^^jJU/tP-,-^^'- -  ' 

Where  their  skills  are  scarce  and  in  demand,  persons  may  seek  to 
drive  home  their  "indispensability"  by  constantly  threatening  to 
cease  enacting  the  roles  involved.  Where  many  workers  or  staff 
members  actually  do  come  and  go,  we  speak  of  a  high  turnover 
of  labor  or  of  staff.  At  some  given  point  such  turnover  may  prove 
wasteful,  since  those  who  leave  take  with  them  their  experience 
and  those  who  come  have  to  be  "broken  in  on  the  job."  Thus,  when 
the  distribution  of  skills  is  unmanaged,  labor  shortages  may  exist 
side  by  side  with  unemployment. 

It  is  in  such  contexts  that  men  learn  to  see  themselves  "dis- 
tanced" from  any  particular  occupational  role.  They  face  their 
occupational  life  in  terms  of  a  multiplicity  of  opportunities,  with 
only  segmental  involvement  in  any  one  of  them.  They  are  ready 
to  take  up  different  jobs,  finding  fulfillment  in  all  and  in  none, 
that  is,  allowing  none  to  take  firm  hold  of  their  entire  personalities. 
German  humanists  of  the  Napoleonic  age  protested,  in  the  name  of 
universal  man,  against  vocational  specialization.  And  economically 
secure  nobilities  may  consider  aloofness  from  any  special  occu- 
pational role  their  privilege,  and  so  busy  themselves  only  with 
occasional  political,  administrative,  or  military  tasks,  never  allow- 
ing any  single  pursuit  to  fix  them  into  an  enduring  role. 

On  the  other  hand,  the  old-world  peasant  and  artisan,  as  well 
as  the  modern  professional  career-man— the  teacher,  army  officer, 
artist,  minister,  doctor,  or  lawyer— is  more  likely  to  identify  him- 
self with  his  vocational  role  intensely  and  for  life. 

"Roles  in  voluntary  associations  are  often  stratified  as  perma- 
nent, provisional,  or  transient.  Where  there  is  a  premium  on  "se- 
niority," those  with  permanent  roles  may  successfully  claim  pres- 
tigCr-In  political  parties  such  claims  are  usually  raised  by  the  "old 
vanguard,"  "Fascisti  of  the  first  hour,"  "Old  fighter  of  the  Nazi 
party,"  "Charter  member,"  and  the  like.  In  local  communities,  the 
corresponding  phrases  are:  "old  families,"  the  "pioneers,"  "old  set- 
tlers," or  "old  timers,"  in  contrast  with  "newcomers,"  "new  resi- 
dents," or  "new  members."  Transient  members  of  communities  and 


IJO  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

organizations  are  frequently  called  "footloose"  or  "floaters";  in 
political  parties,  they  are  frequently  called  "fly-by-nights"  or  "drift- 
wood." In  the  family  we  speak  of  "the  newly  married"  and  we 
honor  long  marital  companionship  by  celebrating  a  "silver"  and  a 
"golden"  wedding  anniversary.  In  the  economic  order,  honorific 
distinctions  are  made  in  favor  of  "old  wealth,"  in  contrast  to  re- 
cently acquired  wealth.  In  most  modern  societies,  inherited  wealth 
ranks  higher  than  newly  accumulated  wealth;  the  heir  or  the  heiress 
of  the  economic  royalist  ranks  higher  than  the  "self-made  man" 
who,  at  least  in  some  circles,  is  made  to  feel  a  parvenu  by  those 
having  more  exalted  "backgrounds."  In  this,  as  in  many  other  re- 
spects, the  countries  of  the  New  World  no  longer  differ  from  those 
of  Old  Europe. 

Man's  resignation  from  institutions  is  variously  patterned.- Some 
organizations,  such  as  churches,  monastic  orders,  or  totalitarian 
parties,  acknowledge  death  as  the  sole  legitimate  exit  for  their 
members.  The  formal  act  through  which  an  individual  is  elim- 
inated from  his  role  in  an  economic  institution  usually  takes  the 
form  of  a  "notice"  or  a  "nonrenewal"  of  contract,  or  a  retirement 
from  business  or  assignment  to  the  status  of  the  temporarily  un- 
employed or  permanently  unemployable.  In  the  religious  order, 
loss  of  membership  may  be  voluntary  or  may  occur  against  the 
will  of  the  member.  In  the  latter  case,  in  the  Catholic  church,  we 
speak  of  "excommunication,"  or  in  certain  Protectant  churches  and 
sects,  of  "being  dropped  from  membership."  In  the  political  order, 
especially  the  state  itself,  the  person  may  be  deprived  of  "civic 
rights";  if  naturalized  he  may  be  "denaturalized,"  and  if  an  immi- 
grant, he  may  be  "deported"  to  his  country  of  origin,  or  banned 
as  an  "outlaw." 

In  a  world  of  national  states,  to  be  expelled  from  one  state  for 
political  or  religious  reasons  often  makes  admission  to  the  territory 
of  another  quite  a  problem.  Leon  Trotsky,  after  his  expulsion  from 
the  Soviet  Union,  for  instance,  found  himself  in  "a  world  without 
visa";  many  other  earlier  fugitives  from  Bolshevism  found  them- 
selves "stateless"  and  received  a  special  status  through  the  League 
of  Nations'  "Nansen  Pass."  Since  the  advent  of  Hitlerism,  no  com- 
parable instrument  has  been  created.  Jews  driven  from  Germany 
to  the  East  found  themselves  for  months  in  a  no-man's-land,  for 
Poland  refused  to  admit  them. -The  age-old  right  of  the  political 
fugitive  to  asylum  in  another  country  is  no  longer  honoredv- Nowa- 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  IJl 

days  in  Europe,  eight  years  after  "the  shooting  war,"  there  are 
still  millions  of  "displaced  persons,"  that  is,  "stateless  persons," 
without  civic  rights,  who  have  found  no  country  willing  to  accept 
them  as  "new  citizens." 

In  the  kinship  order  we  speak  of  the  "divorcee"  and  of  the  "lost 
son."  In  the  military  order,  of  the  "veteran"  or  the  "reservist"  who 
has  received"  his  "honorable  discharge,"  or  of  the  man  who  has  been 
tried  by  "court  martial,"  of  the  man  who  absentees  himself  without 
permission  as  "having  gone  AWOL,"  and  finally  of  the  "deserter." 
If  such  men  escape  court  jurisdiction,  we  speak  of  "fugitives  from 
justice."  The  disloyal  party  member  is  called  a  "renegade";  the  dis- 
loyal religious  believer  an  "apostate."  Hitler  was  ruled  out  of  Chris- 
tendom by  President  Roosevelt,  although  the  Pope— an  expert  in 
divine  matters— did  not  declare  him  an  "apostate,"  however  sinful 
a  Christian  he  may  have  been  considered. 
~So,  during  their  active  lives,  do  men  enter,  play,  and  leave  roles.^ 

During  their  declining  years  they  see  their  friends  drop  out  of 
their  lives;  then  opportunities  to  mourn  become  more  frequent 
and  opportunities  to  continue  their  roles  with  their  age  peers 
diminish.  In  time,  they  "retire"  from  vocational  life;  and  as  the 
range  of  their  active  roles  slirinks,  they  become  housebound,  and 
finally  they  die.  For  although  in  industrialized  nations  more  people 
live  longer  than  formerly,  we  shall  all  have  to  die  although  no 
one  knows  when  he  personally  will  have  to  go.  This  knowledge  is 
biographically  acquired,  and  like  all  thoughts  of  "unpleasant  facts" 
it  is  not  always  fully  accepted. 

In  one  of  his  most  ingenious,  although  as  usual  problematical, 
papers,^  Freud  has  interpreted  the  heroic  valor  of  the  soldier  who 
"goes  over  the  top"  as  a  regression  to  an  archaic  psychic  state  in 
which  the  individual  acts  as  if  nothing  could  ever  happen  to  him, 
that  is,  a  state  in  which  he  is  basically  convinced  of  his  own  im- 
mortality. Freud's  "hero"  is  thus  a  soldier  who  has  "forgotten"  that 
he  is  mortal,  risks  his  life  in  combat,  and  so  unwittingly  loses  his 
life.  This  may  well  be  an  oversimplification:  some  soldiers  may 
knowingly  seek  death  in  combat.  For  example,  the  "crusader"  who 
knows  what  he  fights  for  and  fights  for  what  he  knows  may  mini- 
mize his  fear  of  personal  death  to  the  zero  point,  and  accept  his 
death  as  inevitable  and  near.  The  image  of  the  last  stand  of  the 

-  Sigmund  Freud,  "Thoughts  for  the  Times  on  War  and  Death,"  Collected 
Papers,  Vol.  IV   (London,   1946),  especially  pp.  307  fF. 


1/2  SOCIALSTRUCTURE 

Spartan  warriors  at  Thermopylae  also  comes  to  mind,  and  we 
should  remember  that  the  Romans  summed  up  their  military  mo- 
rale by  the  saying:  "It  is  sweet  and  becoming  to  die  for  one's  coun- 
try," which  would  seem  to  characterize  men  who  realize  that  they 
are  mortal  yet  are  willing  to  risk  and,  if  need  be,  lose  their  lives 
in  combat.  And  there  is  the  ideal  image  of  the  Christian  martyr, 
who,  though  he  died  for  a  different  cause,  was  in  general  agree- 
ment with  this  Roman  view.  The  same  holds  for  pioneers  of  modern 
ideas,  such  as  Giordano  Bruno,  who  was  burned  at  the  stake,  or 
for  Communists  such  as  Levine,  court  martialed  at  Munich  in 
1918,  who  referred  to  himself,  in  the  language  of  expressionism,  as 
a  "corpse  on  vacation." 

At  any  rate,  we  do  not  experience  our  death:  it  is  the  end  of  all 
experience.  Yet  whatever  we  experience  just  before  death  can  be 
known  to  us  only  if  the  decline  of  our  life  does  not  end  in  death 
but  in  recovery.  Man's  knowledge  of  death  does  sometimes  add  a 
component  of  fear  to  his  image  of  death,  but  even  after  the  loss 
of  consciousness— since  anesthesia— man  may  "fight  death"  and  re- 
cover. On  the  other  hand,  men  may  reconcile  themselves  to  death 
and  die  as  Abraham  did,  "full  of  days";  and  some  may  even  seek 
death  in  suicide.  Yet  what  testimony  we  have  concerning  the 
alleged  "experience  of  death"  is  the  testimony  of  those  who,  like 
Dostoevski  before  the  firing  squad,  were  "close  to  death"  but  some- 
how continued  to  live.  They  did  not  experience  death  itself,  and  so 
they  report  their  attitude  toward  death,  not  their  experience  of  it. 
.-Though-death  is  man's  final  exit  from  all  worldly  roles^Jiis  corpse 
remains  to  his  relatives,  and  to  a  variety  of  experts.  In  funeral  rites 
and  in  sanitary  services,  funeral  directors,  cemetery  wardens,  grave- 
diggers  or  cremators,  are  in  charge.  The  mummification  of  ancient 
Egyptian  pharaohs  and,  in  our  time,  of  Lenin;  the  royal  tombs  in 
the  form  of  Egytian  pyramids  or  the  mausoleum  in  Moscow's  Red 
Square,  the  Christian  cross  and  its  alleged  remains  in  the  form 
of  relics,  the  organized  care  of  soldiers'  cemeteries,  the  memorial 
rites  for  the  Unknown  Soldier  of  World  War  I  at  the  Cenotaph  in 
London,  the  Arc  de  Triomphe  of  Paris,  and  the  Arlington  Cemetery 
in  Washington— all  these  serve  to  "immemorialize"  the  memories  of 
men  who  are  felt  to  have  cast  long  shadows  through  history.  Re- 
ligious and  filial  piety,  biographical  interest  and  secular  hero  wor- 
ship, thus  monumentalize  the  memory  image  of  the  deceased  after 
men  cease  to  play  any  live  role. 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  IJ^^ 

2.  The  Institutional  Formation  of  Persons 

"^Institutions  not  only  select  persons  and  eject  them;  institutions  _ 
also  form  them.-HEn  our  discussion  of  the  biography,  we  have  indi- 
cated some  of  the  ways  in  which  this  occurs.  Institutions  in  the 
several  orders,  as  we  shall  see,  may  also  have^pecial  educational 
spheres  by  means  of  which  people  are  socially  trained  to  enact  the 
roles  of  the  institution;  ^  and,  of  course,  in  the  informal  context 
of  any  institution,'-«ducation— even  to  the  point  of  a  social  trans- 
formation of  the  person— may  proceed.  Impulse  and  sensitivity  are 
channeled  and  transformed  into  standard  motives  joined  to  stand- 
ard goals  and  gratifications.  Thus,  institutions  imprint  their  stamps 
upon  the  individual,  modifying  his  external  conduct  as  well  as  his 
inner  life.  For— ©ne  aspect  of  learning  a  role  consists  of  acquiring 
motives  which  guarantee  its  performance.4. 

"^  But  the-key  mechanism  by  which  institutions  form  persons  in- 
volves  the_circle  of  significant  others  which  the  institution  estab- 
lishes.4>.This  is  important  because  it  in  due  course  leads,  for  full 
institutional  members,  to  changes  in  the  generalized  other.  By 
internalizing  the  expectations  of  institutional  heads,  as  particular 
others,  the  persons  who  enact  the  institutional  role,  come  to  con- 
trol themselves— to  pattern  and  to  enact  their  roles  in  accordance 
with  the  constraints  thus  built  into  their  characters.  As  they  develop 
as  institutional  members,  these  constraints  are  often  generalized, 
and  are  thus  linked  psychologically  with  particular  institutions. 

There  are  two  general  ways  in  which  persons  may  be  attached 
to  institutions,  and  only  one  of  them  involves  the  generalized  other,  y 
socially   anchored   in  the  institution  and  internalized  by  persons 
who  are  its  members. 

^J)iJnstitutional  heads  may  appeal  to  their  members  in  terms  of  \ 
the  generalized  other,  and  so  make  it  a  religious  or  moral  duty 
for  them  to  develop  sentiments  of  attachment  to  the  institution.  — 
So  Jews  and  Christians  teach  their  children  "Honor  thy  father  and 

3  See  Chapter  IX:    Institutional  Orders  and   Social  Controls,  II,  Section  4: 
The  Educational  Sphere. 

^  See  Chapter  V:   The  Sociology  of  Motivation. 
5  See  Chapter  IV:    The  Person. 


T! 


l-J/^  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

thy  mother:  that  thy  days  may  be  long  upon  the  land  which  the 
Lord  thy  God  giveth  thee."  Christian  parents  are  unlikely  to  teach 
Jesus's  words  "Follow  me;  and  let  the  dead  bury  their  dead,"  or 
"I  am  come  to  set  a  man  at  variance  against  his  father  and  the 
daughter  against  her  mother."  Thus  is  institutional  solidarity  ex- 
plicitly trained  and  upheld.  ( II )  -  Those  in  control  of  an  institution, 
or  acting  within  it,  may  appeal  to  the  sense  of  expediency  of  the 
members.-  Affiliation  with  or  adherence  to  the  institution  is  then 
regarded  as  a  rationally  calculated  advantage. 

In  the  first  case,  where  the  generalized  other  is  trained,  the  indi- 
vidual is  expected  to  maintain  membership  "for  better  or  for  worse"; 
in  the  second,  where  rational  calculation  is  the  rule,  the  mainte- 
nance of  the  individual's  membership  is  dependent  upon  his  advan- 
tage in  the  maintenance  of  the  institution,  or  upon  the  mutual  ad- 
vantage of  the  several  members.  Accordingly,  the  nature  of  solidar- 
ity and  of  its  sentimentalization  differs,  which  is  what  Ferdinand 
Tonnies  had  in  mind  when  he  spoke  of  the  differences  between 
"communal  relations"  with  their  moral  sentiment,  and  "societal  rela- 
tions," with  their  expedient  calculations  of  interest. - 

Different  institutional  orders  seem  typically  to  vary  as  to  which 
type  of  attachment  prevails :  communities  of  actual  or  alleged  com- 
mon descent— such  as  the  family,  clan,  sib,  tribe,  nation— are  char- 
acterized by  solidarity  sentimentsjiiaking  it  a  magical,  sacred,  or 
moral  obligation  of  the  members  to  give  such  sentiments  priority 
over  all  considerations  of  expediency.  Nationalism,  to  be  sure,  is 
a  modern  mass  sentiment  of  great  complexity  and  variation,  but 
the  slogan,  "My  country,  right  or  wrong"  places  the  attachment  to 
one's  nation  "beyond  good  and  evil,"  and  thus  corresponds  to  the 
valuation  of  the  king  as  the  head  of  the  nation  who  "can  do  no 
wrong."  ^ 

The  intensity  of  such  solidarity  is  based  upon  its  foundation  in 
the  superego  of  persons,  combined  with  rationalizations  of  power 

*'  Since  the  end  of  World  War  I  this  evaluation  of  the  heads  of  states  has 
been  widely  renounced.  In  articles  227-30  of  the  Versailles  Peace  Treaty, 
the  allied  powers  placed  Wilhelm  II  under  public  accusation  because  of 
infractions  of  "the  international  moral  law  and  the  sanctity  ot  treaties."  After 
World  War  II  a  new  international  law  was  proclaimed  which  is  based  upon 
"natural  law"  and  introduces  the  principles  of  retroactivity  and  guilt  by 
association.  It  does  not  define  "aggression,"  and  so,  given  the  present  power 
constellation,  one  can  only  conclude  that  among  modern  nations,  "the  victor 
can  do  no  wrong." 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  IJ,^ 

and  prestige  which  enlist  a  variety  of  private  interests— economic, 
mihtary,  and  bureaucratic.  Hitler  summed  it  up  in  the  phrase  "Right 
is  what  benefits  the  German  people,"  which  may  be  said  to  mark 
one  end  of  all  universalist  standards,  whether  religious,  moral,  or 
legal.  The  intensity  of  such  loyalty  sentiments  is  relevant  for  the 
degree  to  which  a  social  structure  is  politically  cohesive;  and  the 
scope  of  the  values  which  institutional  leaders  can  successfully  at- 
tach to  such  loyalty  patterns— by  holding  their  particular  institu- 
tions to  be  the  depository  of  all  possible  values— is  of  course  rele- 
\  ant  for  social  cohesion,  because  the  individual  who  is  confronted 
with  such  claims  may  be  too  weak  to  define  his  own  value  position 
in  the  face  of  such  a  "total  opposition."  Accordingly,  such  loyalties 
are  decisive  for  the  sacrifices  which  individual  members  are  ex- 
pected to  be  ready  to  make  for  the  common  cause. 

Totalitarian  societies  and  regimes  seek  to  build  up  such  total 
loyalties  by  their  programs  of  "cadre  training."  Hitler,  however, 
despite  the  aid  of  his  "German  Christians,"  never  succeeded  in 
breaking  Christian  universalism.  Stalin,  on  the  other  hand,  after 
having  made  his  peace  with  the  Eastern  church,  has  been  more 
successful:  the  juxtaposition  of  a  "dialectical  science  of  nature"  (as 
against,  for  example,  "bourgeois  genetics"),  of  "proletarian  or 
socialist  realism"  in  the  fine  arts  and  in  literature  (as  against 
"bourgeois  formalism"  and  other  deviations),  and  of  "Soviet  Man" 
(against  all  other  types  of  man— feudal,  bourgeois,  cosmopolitan, 
or  petty-bourgeois)  divides  sharply  the  value  preferences  and 
thoughtways  of  the  communist  ingroup  from  all  those  on  the  out- 
side. Universalist  criteria  of  the  true,  the  good,  and  the  beautiful 
are  thus  discarded,  and  in  fact  considered  quite  unavailable. 

One  of  the  features  of  this  new  orthodoxy  is  that  no  institutional 
order  is  permitted  to  develop  prestigeful  roles  on  its  own  ground. 
For  all  loyalties,  and  thus  for  all  prestige  and  for  all  authority, 
there  must  be  one  fountainhead.  Success  in  any  field  may  thus  be 
ascribed  to  the  head  of  the  state,  who  in  turn  distributes  all  honor. 
So  there  are  medals  for  warriors  and  for  workers,  for  artists  and 
for  the  mothers  who  bear  many  children.  All  achievement  is  pre- 
conditioned by  the  correct  course  of  the  totalitarian  leadership, 
and  hence  all  achievement  is  credited  to  its  wise  and  infallible 
course.  Criticism  may  be  made  only  of  its  inadequate  means,  not— 
once  they  are  officially  promulgated— of  its  ends.  And  no  one  can 


iy6  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

deviate  from  whatever  "line"  has  been  defined  for  each  field  of 
endeavor. 

The  modern  totalitarian  leader  thus  resurrects  the  image  of  the 
ancient  patriarch  who  was  supreme  judge,  chief  provider,  military 
leader,  and  head  religious  functionary,  all  in  one.  The  individual 
member  of  his  family  had  no  alternative  orientation,  and  func- 
tionally specialized  motives  met  on  the  common  basis  of  all  obliga- 
tion, defined  in  terms  of  filial  piety.  Such  obligations  included  the 
obligation  to  honor  one's  father  and  mother,  to  provide  for  them 
to  the  end  of  their  days,  to  be  devoted  to  their  memories  and  to 
care  for  their  burial  and  their  grave,  to  obey  their  expressed  wishes 
with  regard  to  the  disposition  of  the  inheritance,  to  take  over  the 
blood  feud  as  a  right  and  an  obligation  of  successorship,  never  to 
depart  from  the  God  of  the  fathers  and  His  ways,  and  to  respect 
one's  wife,  chosen  by  one's  father. 

If  the-private  integration  of  persons  and  the  public  cohesion  of 
institutions  may  be  achieved  by  (a)  personal  leadership,  (b)  by 
eliciting  co-operation  in  common  tasks,  or  ( c )  by  joint  utilization  of 
things— such  as  the  house  and  its  contents— then  we  may  say  that 
the  patriarchal  family  of  old,  as  well  as  the  totalitarian  society  of 
the  Soviet  Union  today,  is  "integrated"  on  all  three  levels.  For  such 
societies  make  all  the  instruments  of  production,  administration, 
and  warfare  a  "common  property,"  develop  a  cult  of  the  leader, 
and  define  common  tasks  for  all  in  terms  of  the  "quota  fulfillments" 
set  forth  in  the  "plans"  promulgated  from  on  high. 

3.  The  Theori/  of  Premiums  and  Traits  of  Character 

The  chief  mechanism  by  which  persons  are  formed  by  institu- 
tions has  to  do  with  the  way  types  of  persons  are  "built"  by  the 
combinations  of  various  roles  which  compose  them,  and  by  their 
cumulative  reactions  to  these  roles.)  In  Chapter  IV,  as  well  as  in 
the  present  chapter,  we  have  discussed  some  of  the  relevant  mech- 
anisms as  they  involve  images  of  the  self  and  the  generalized  other, 
(In  this  section,  we  want  to  display  a  further  way  by  which  indi- 
vidual phenomena— specific  "traits"  of  the  individual's  character- 
may  be  linked  with  institutional  contexts,  j 

-^Traits  of  the  individual  may  usefully  be  classified  according  to 
the  scope  of  the  occasions  on  which  the  trait  appears,  and  the  zone 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  IJJ 

or  zones  of  the  character  structure  in  which  the  trait  is  integrated/-^ 
These  two  points  of  observation  may  be  related.  For  example,  if 
a  tiait  is  a  feature  of  the  organism,  the  scope  of  its  appearance  may 
coincide  with  the  appearance  of  the  individual,  and  it  may  in  one 
way  or  another,  become  integrated  with  all  zones  of  the  character 
structure,  ^hus  the  roles  available  to  a  man  born  with  a  hunched 
back  will  he  restricted,  and  the  way  he  combines  and  reacts  to 
these  roles,  as  well  as  the  self-images  reflected  from  them,  will  be 
modified.  These  facts  about  his  roles  and  his  self  may  in  turn  affect 
the  opportunities  of  given  components  of  the  psychic  structure  to 
be  socialized,  in  which  case  the  organic  trait  of  his  hunchback  may 
be  integrated  with  traits  in  all  zones  of  his  character  structure. 
Such  traits  may  thus  cue  a  pattern  of  other  traits  in  other  zones 
of  character,  restricting  and  shaping  whatever  traits  are  to  become 
part  of  the  total  character.  ) 

There  is  no  general  principle  of  character  structure  in  terms  of 
which  any  one  trait  always  leads  to  the  selection  of  other  traits. 
The  reason  for  this  is  that  character  traits  are  presented  by  and 
through  the  medium  of  interpersonal  relations  and  most  traits  are 
relative  to  the  institutional  and  other  interpersonal  contexts  in 
which  they  are  presented.  The  traits  of  a  person  should  not,  there- 
fore, be  ascribed  merely  to  that  one  person,  as  if  he  were  a  turkey 
into  which  different  traits  were  stuffed.  What  is  "selfishness"  to 
one  circle  of  persons  may  to  another  circle  be  "initiative,"  or  to 
either  circle  the  trait  may  be  selfishness  or  initiative  according  to 
when,  how,  and  where  it  is  revealed. 

"frhere  are  two  considerations  involved:  first,  the  context  of  the 
trait's  occurrence,  and  second,  the  different  way  or  ways  in  which 
it  may  be  evaluated  by  different  personst-Those  traits  which  appear 
in  the  enactment  of  a  limited  number  of  roles  we  may  call  specific  — 
traits;  those  which  are  presented  in  a  wide  variety  of  roles  enacted 
by  the  person  we  may  call  general  traits^i  a  trait  is  evaluated 
positively  by  significant  others,  we  may  say  that  a  preiniiim-^is 
placed  upon  its  development  and  presentation.  If  the  trait  is  evalu- 
ated negatively,  or  if  the  person  is  in  any  way  restrained  from 
presenting  it,  we  may  say  that  the  trait  is  tabooed. 

A  premium  or  a  taboo  may  itself  be  used  generally  or  specifically. 
Thus,  if  selfishness  is  generally  tabooed,  it  means  that  all  its  appear- 
ances are  interpreted  as  selfishness  and  are  tabooed.  If  it  is  specifi- 
cally tabooed,  only  in  certain  roles  will  its  presentation  be  tabooed. 


iy8  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

In  like  manner,  a  trait  may  be  generally  or  specifically  "premi- 
umed,"  that  is,  a  premium  may  be  placed  upon  it  no  matter  when, 
where,  or  by  whom  it  is  displayed,  or,  a  premium  may  be  applied 
only  when  the  trait  is  displayed  by  certain  persons  enacting  certain 
roles  on  certain  occasions. 

Taboos  or  premiums  may  be  applied  by  coercion— by  actual  re- 
straint of  the  bodily  movements  which  are  involved  in  presenting 
the  trait;  by  co-operating  socially  with  the  performance  or  failing 
to  do  so;  by  the  use  of  gestures— the  smile,  the  frown,  the  flicker 
of  an  eyelid— to  encourage  or  to  restrain  the  presentation  of  the 
trait;  or  by  using  words  which  designate  the  trait  in  question  in 
a  positive  or  in  a  negative  manner.  Systems  of  premiums  and  taboos 
need  not  be  verbalized,  but  if  they  do  become  fixed  in  the  language, 
this  fact  may  stabilize  the  system  and  facilitate  its  diffusion  from 
specific  to  generalized  application.  An  eulogistic  term  for  some  trait 
may  thus  increase  the  chances  that  people  will  approve  it. 

There  are  no  general  psychological  traits  which  exist  as  universals 
in  the  character  structure,  irrespective  of  specific  contexts.  The 
only  meaning  we  can  usefully  give  "general  trait"  is:  used  in  all 
or  most  contexts.  We  can  then  ask: -What  are  the  sociological  con- 
ditions which  favor  the  development  in  persons  of  general  traits? 
And,  conversely,  what  are  the  conditions  under  which  we  may 
expect  specific  traits  to  be  developed?^ 

We  must  emphasize  this  specialization  of  character  traits,  because 
a  nonsociological  psychology  and  an  idealistic  emphasis  upon  the 
"harmony"  of  the  human  personality  have  caused  some  students  to 
underestimate,  if  not  overlook,  it.  Character  traits  are  not  universals 
within  a  character  structure;  they  must  always  be  seen  and  under- 
stood by  the  social  psychologist  as  tied  to  given  ranges  of  social 
situations. 

The  controversy  as  to  whether  or  not  a  person  has  "general  traits" 
or  only  "particular  traits"  may  be  resolved  with  the  aid  of  the  con- 
cepts we  have  presented. -Generalized  traits  are  likely  to  develop 
if  the  roles  a  person  incorporates  are  all  similar.  And  the  fact 
of  such  similarity  is,  of  course,  dependent  on  the  kind  of  society 
in  which  the  person  lives,  as  well  as  upon  his  choice  of  roles,  from 
all  those  available,  at  any  given  time. 

Where  a  majority  of  the  institutional  roles  making  up  a  society 
follow  a  similar  principle,  the  character  traits  formed  in  one  con- 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  Ijg 

text  have  a  chance  to  operate  in  another.  To  this  extent,  the  oppor- 
tunity for  general  traits  to  develop  in  persons  is  maximized."  In 
many  contexts,  however,  such  a  generalization  of  traits  is  not  so- 
ci'^lly  possible.  Perhaps  it  is  true  that  a  man  who  has  acquired  con- 
trol over  his  body  in  dangerous  sports  is  likely  to  be  more  sure  of 
his  bodily  control  in  dangerous  physical  work  or  in  warfare, 
whereas  a  man  who  lacks  this  readiness  to  risk  his  body  may  the 
more  readily  ascribe  "courage"  to  those  who  do  have  it.  Yet,  the 
"courage"  of  the  artist  to  brave  for  years  the  scorn  of  outraged 
critics  is  different  from  the  "courage"  of  the  soldier.  In  fact,  the 
courageous  man  of  the  typewriter  need  not  at  all  be  the  courageous 
man  of  the  machine  gun— yet  both  may  be  "courageous,"  willing 
to  face  risks. 

^^23^hen  the  roles  composing  a  social  structure  are  specialized  into 
more  or  less  autonomous  institutions,  the  traits  of  men  are  likely 
to  be  segregated  and  specific.  A  man  may  cheat  his  wife  but  not 
his  business  partner,  or  vice  versa.  On  the  field  of  sport  the  foot- 
ball player  may  be  a  ruthless  tackier,  but  on  the  dance  floor  an 
awkward  partner  and  timid  competitor.  The  political  courage  of 
a  local  leader  may  or  may  not  carry  over  to  the  courage  of  a  na- 
tional leader,  the  dimensions  and  requirements  of  the  latter  role 
being  enormously  enlarged.  Lenin  is  a  case  in  point;  Kerensky 
represents  the  reverse.  An  American  may  be  enraged  at  earlier 
British  treatment  of  the  Burmese,  but  not  upset  at  American  treat- 
ment of  Southern  Negroes. 

Because  of  such  facts,  no  general  discussion  of  allegedly  univer- 
sal traits  in  terms  of  the  isolated  person  is  apt  to  be  fruitful.  In 
any  society,  and  with  reference  to  given  types  of  character  struc- 
ture, it  is  a  matter  for  empirical  research  to  determine  how  far 
traits  are  generalized  or  hov/  far  they  are  segregated  according  to 
contexts.  We  may,  however,  contribute  to  the  tools  useful  for 
such  work  by  considering  various  kinds  of  individual  traits  as  they 
are  presented  and  evaluated  by  others: 

I.  A  general  trait  that  is  generally  premiumed  has  a  high  chance 
to  continue  to  be  presented  by  the  person  and  to  be  firmly  organ- 
ized into  his  character.  A  person  predominantly  composed  of  such 

"  The  so-called  "problem  ot  transfer  ot  training"  has  been  gi\ en  relati\ely 
fruitless  answers  by  many  psychologists  because  they  fail  to  consider  the 
sociological  conditions  that  are  involved.  Experimental  studies,  in  U.S.  society 
and  laboratories,  have  usually  indicated  very  little  transfer. 


l8o  SOCIALSTRUCTURE 

traits  in  a  society  of  harmonious  premiums  is  apt  to  be  unified— 
and  static. 

IlrA  specific  trait  that  is  generally  premiumed  will  tend  to 
spread,  to  become  a  general  traiW-A  person  predominantly  com- 
posed of  such  traits  in  a  society  of  high  and  ready  premiums  is  apt 
to  be  an  expanding  person,  although  perhaps  suffering  the  tensions 
of  his  growth.  Suppose  a  general  premium  is  placed  upon  the 
specific  trait  of  kindness;  we  would  then  expect  that  kindness  would 
tend  to  become  general.  Yet  the  general  premium  on  kindness  may 
continue  to  be  restricted  to  kindness  toward  certain  kinds  of  per- 
sons, for  no  premium  is  absolutely  general:  to  be  kind  to  Negroes 
may  continue  to  be  tabooed  in  many  contexts  of  Negro-white  rela- 
tions. General  premiums  of  specific  traits  may  even  be  turned  into 
specific  taboos:  during  a  war,  to  be  kind  to  one  of  the  enemy  may 
be  tabooed,  indeed,  it  may  be  treason. 

Premiums  thus  have  a  life  of  their  own,  a  dynamic  by  which 
they  become  less  general  and  turn  into  specific  premiums,  or  even 
change  into  specific  or  general  taboos.  Skill  at  welding  may  be 
highly  premiumed  by  everyone  when  it  is  done  in  the  shop,  but 
the  welder's  wife  may  taboo  it  in  the  kitchen:  it  is  a  specific  trait 
generally  premiumed  but  it  is  not  likely  to  become  a  general  trait. 

III."  A  general  trait  that  is  specifically  premiumed  will  tend  to 
become  a  specific  trait, -or,  if  kept  general,  to  be  modified  or 
camouflaged  in  all  contexts  except  the  one  in  which  it  is  specifically 
premiumed.  If  a  person  presents  traits  that  are  evaluated  as  selfish 
or  grasping  in  all  his  roles,  the  lack  of  general  premiums  on  these 
traits  may  make  him  restrict  their  presentation  to  one  or  two  roles, 
such  as  occur  in  small  business  conduct,  where  there  is  a  chance 
that  they  will  be  specifically  premiumed. 

A  person  who  is  predominantly  composed  of  general  traits  that 
are  specifically  premiumed  is  like  "a  bull  in  a  china  shop."  He  has 
not  yet  learned  to  segregate  the  display  of  traits  according  to  ap- 
propriate contexts;  he  is  making  too  much  of  what,  in  its  proper 
place,  might  be  a  good  thing. 

IV."  A  specific  trait  that  is  specifically  premiumed  will  tend  to 
be  stabilized^-a  person  predominantly  composed  of  such  traits  will 
be  a  compartmentalized  specialist— 

'-  A  similar  scheme  of  the  social  tendencies  of  personal  traits  is 
possible  in  terms  of  taboos:  I.  The  chances  for  a  general  trait  that 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  l8l 

is  generally  tabooed  to  develop  in  the  person  are  very  lowfbut  if 
developed,  its  chances  to  disappear  are  very  high.  II.  A  specific 
trait  that  is  generally  tabooed  will  tend  to  be  given  up  in  its  specific 
context  and  not  to  spread  to  other  contexts.  III."i\  general  trait  that 
is  specifically  tabooed  will  tend  to  become  less  general  or  even  to 
become  a  specific  trait.— IV.""A  specific  trait  that  is  specifically 
tabooed  will  tend  to  be  repressed  in  the  specifically  tabooed  con- 
text.-^ it  is  firmly  integrated  in  the  person,  he  may  try  to  realize 
it  in  other  contexts. 

So  far,  in  our  discussion  of  the  sociology  of  individual  traits,  we 
have  written  in  terms  of  the  person,  intentionally  omitting  con- 
sideration of  other  zones  of  the  character.  We  have  stated  several 
general  propositions  on  the  assumption  that  "other  things  were 
equal."  We  must  now  probe  behind  these  "other  things,"  for  in 
reality,  economists  not  withstanding,  other  things  are  not  "equal." 

Omitting  traits  that  are  visible  features  of  the  organic  constitu- 
tion, there  seem  to  be  three  general  factors  which  select  and  refract 
traits  in  any  given  character  structure.  To  understand  how  a  given 
trait  comes  to  be  part  of  the  character  structure  requires  that  we 
pay  attention  to  these  factors: 

!*»•  Social  premiums  and  taboos  are  applied  to  traits  by  currently 
significant  others,  who  by  thus  responding  to  them,  determine  their 
meaning,  and,  as  it  were,  socialhj  refract  the  traits.-The  premiums 
and  taboos  that  are  applied  by  these  significant  others  may  be  stable 
or  they  may  be  unstable,  and  they  may  be  in  conflict  or  they  may 
be  in  harmony. 

Where  the  unity  of  a  social  structure  is  disintegrating,  the  grip 
of  institutions  upon  men  relaxes,  which  means  that  no  general, 
harmonious,  and  stable  system  of  premiums  and  taboos  operates. 
The  responses  and  traits  of  men  are  accordingly  less  predictable, 
for  then  a  greater  range  is  open  for  traits  to  develop,  and  experi- 
mental types  of  character  may  arise.  Some  of  these  types  may  later 
set  up  a  new  system  of  premiums  and  taboos  which  will,  in  turn, 
select  and  refract  the  development  and  presentations  of  traits  in 
other  persons. 

II.  The  premiums  and  taboos  applied  by  currently  significant 
others  are  not  the  only  ones  which  must  be  taken  into  account 
in  explaining  the  histories  of  various  traits.  For  societies  have  his- 
tories, and  persons  have  biographies.  We  must  pay  attention  to  the 
specific  premiums  and  taboos  to  which  persons  have  been  exposed 


l82  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

by  previous  others  during  the  course  of  their  biographies.  These 
previously  internahzed  taboos  and  premiums  select  and  refract 
those  which  may  be  currently  effective.  We  point  to  this  fact  by 
terming  it  the'- bio  graphical  refraction  of  traits^Ior  it  introduces  a 
certain  depth  into  our  considerations,  the  depth  of  the  person's 
biography. 

III.  There  is  another  depth  factor,  which  involves  the  matura- 
tion of  the  psychic  structure  and  its  integration  with  the  person. 
In  the  interplay  of  social  career  and  psychic  maturation  certain 
traits  which  have  been  premiumed,  and  others  which  have  been 
tabooed,  form  a  more  or  less  stable  configuration.  ■<The  psychic 
structure  may  also  have  a  certain  dynamic  of  its  own  which  is 
involved  in  the  selection  and  refraction  of  traits.  And  at  any  rate, 
the  premiums  and  taboos  which  have  been  applied  to  a  person 
select  and  accentuate  certain  components  of  his  psychic  structure 
as  well  as  of  his  person.  So  we  must  consider  the  psychic  as  well 
as  the  social  and  the  biographical  refraction  of  traits.  Analyzing  a 
specific  character  structure,  the  social  psychologist  tries  to  under- 
stand its  formation  in  terms  of  the  acquisition  of  various  traits  in 
their  different  institutional  contexts,  and  to  trace  what  happens 
to  these  traits  as  they  are  integrated  in  this  particular  character 
structure. 

If  in  educational  institutions  there  is  a  premium  upon  competitive 
examinations  as  a  means  of  selecting  and  evaluating  students,  then 
competitive  and  individualistic  traits  may  be  developed  in  the 
student.  But  if  group  and  team  work  prevail  and  premiums  are 
placed  upon  such  traits  as  co-operativeness,  the  student  will  be 
encouraged  to  be  helpful  to  his  fellow  students.  Educational  insti- 
tutions may  thus  encourage  individual  competitiveness  or  co-opera- 
tive teamwork.  Such  premiums  and  taboos  need  not  be  verbalized 
as  explicit  rules,  yet  successful  adjustment  to  the  rules  of  the  game 
will  necessitate  traits  of  the  type  required  by  the  objective  insti- 
tutional arrangements  and  its  operating  premiums  and  taboos. 

In  internalizing  the  going  premiums  and  taboos,  a  person  may 
not  be  aware  of  the  impact  they  are  making  upon  his  personal  and 
psychic  structure.  He  may  be  a  very  self-conscious  competitor 
while  not  being  aware  of  how  he  got  that  way  or  indeed  that  he 
is.  Intensified  competition  is  apt  to  call  forth  anxieties  in  the  persons 
exposed  to  it.  Then  premiums  upon  such  traits  as  generosity,  light- 
heartedness,   and   the   ever-ready   smile  may   be   lessened   in  the 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  iS^ 

scope  of  their  application,  and  even  transformed  by  some  anxiety- 
ridden  persons  into  taboos.  Thus  do  premiums  stabiHze  traits  into 
the  person  and  into  the  dynamic  trends  of  his  character. 

In  order  to  understand  what  happens  to  a  socially  available  trait 
during  its  internalization  and  integration  in  the  character  structure, 
we  must  grasp  its  angle  of  refraction,  in  terms  of  the  biography 
of  given  persons  and  in  terms  of  their  psychic  structures,  for  these 
modify  the  traits  that  are  socially  offered.  The  autonomous  dy- 
namics of  both  psychic  structure  and  person  may  thus  select  from 
and  then  organize  what  is  socially  premiumed. 

4.  Anxiety  and  Social  Structure 

We  have  been  discussing  some  general  ways  in  which  institu- 
tions select  and  form  persons  by  means  of  the  roles  persons  enact 
and  the  traits  they  internalize.  Persons  are  linked  with  social  struc- 
tures and  with  particular  institutional  orders  in  another  way  having 
to  do  with  what  we  have  called  the- symbol  spheres— or  more  gen- 
erally, the  communication  processes  as  a  whole. 

We  shall  now  examine  one  type  of  emotion— anxiety  and  fear- 
in  order  to  illustrate  how  psychological  states  involving  the  psychic 
structure  as  well  as  the  person  cannot  be  understood  without  refer- 
ence to  the  institutional  framework  in  which  they  go  on,  and  in 
particular,  the  communicational  processes  which  often  define  them. 

Freud  has  taught  us  to  speak  of  anxiety  rather  than  of  fear 
when  the  fear  is  out  of  proportion  to  the  object  or  occasion  which 
arouses  it.  In  pathologically  extreme  instances,  psychologists  speak 
of  "phobias,"  which  are  classified  by  object  or  occasion.  Thus, 
claustrophobia  refers  to  an  inordinate  fear  of  closed-in  places. 
Where  there  is  no  concrete  object  or  occasion  discernible,  one 
may  speak  of  "free-floating  anxieties." 

Public  communications  can  be  seen  as  psychologically  relevant 
to  anxiety  by  means  of  the  shifting  definitions  of  loyalities  and  of 
definitions  of  social  reality  itself  which  they  provide.  The  level  of 
anxiety  and  of  fear  nowadays  existing  among  American  popula- 
tions, for  example,  due  to  Soviet-United  States  tensions,  is  in  some 
part  due  to  the  great  definitional  shift  in  military  perspectives:  the 
old  categories  of  "land  power"  versus  "sea  power"  have  become 
partially  obsolete— due  to  developments  of  air  power,  atom  bombs, 
and  snorkel  submarines.  Accordingly,  there  is  a  loss  of  firm  defini- 


184  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

tions  of  military  reality,  and  for  many  people  this  is  a  source  of 
anxiety  or  fear. 

So  far  as  persons  are  concerned,  we  may  classify  their  psycho- 
logical state  of  security  in  terms  of  the  institutional  areas  it  involves 
and  the  intervals  during  which  it  occurs.  The  areas  of  a  person's 
life  in  which  he  is  secure  are  wide  if  he  is  secure  in  all  his  roles, 
if  he  "knows  where  he  is  going"  and  what  his  situation  is.  They 
are  narrow  if  he  has  an  adequate  definition  of  his  situation  and  its 
wider  context  only  in  a  few  of  his  roles.  Similarly,  the  interval  of 
security  may  be  longer  or  shorter.  The  person  may  be  secure  all 
the  time,  or  such  security  as  he  experiences  may  be  intermittent. 

If  we  cross-classify  these  areas  and  intervals  of  security,  we  come 
out  with  four  possibilities: 

Fully  secure  people  are  secure  in  all  their  roles  all  the  time, 
or  at  least  for  long  periods  of  time.  At  the  opposite  end  of  the 
scale  are  those  whose  area  of  security  is  narrow  and  even  then, 
intermittent— which,  we  might  suppose,  is  the  psychological  coun- 
terpart of  Hobbes's  state  of  nature,  where  life  is  "nasty,  brutish  and 
short."  There  are  also  persons  whose  security  rests  on  some  nar- 
row range  of  roles  played,  but  within  this  range  their  security 
endures.  ("At  least  I  don't  have  to  worry  about  that.")  And,  in 
the  opposite  situation,  there  are  persons  who  are  secure  in  all  rela- 
tions but  only  for  short  intervals. 

This  simple  classification  of  types  of  security  seems  useful  to 
us,  but  of  course  it  does  not  in  itself  establish  any  links  between 
security  or  anxiety  and  social  structure.  When  we  begin  to  exam- 
ine more  closely  what  we  mean  by  "areas  of  security,"  and  to  dis- 
cuss explicitly  the  emotion  itself,  we  find  that  we  cannot  very  well 
do  so  without  closely  linking  our  discussion  with  given  institutional 
contexts.  Emotions  such  as  fear  cannot  usefully  be  divorced  from 
their  objects— from  what  is  feared;  and  these  objects,  involved  in 
the  shifting  anxieties  of  men,  are  historically  given  and  socially 
learned.  "Man's  fear,"  as  Kurt  Riezler  has  put  it,  "is  fear  of  some- 
thing or  for  something;  of  illness,  loss  of  money,  dishonor;  for 
his  health,  family,  social  status."  ^ 

I.  In  the  kinship  order  there  may  be  fear  of  illegitimate  chil- 
dren, or  of  the  marriage  of  daughters  to  class  and  status  inferiors. 
8  American  Journal  of  Sociology,  May  1944,  p.  489. 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  l8$ 

But  whether  there  is  or  there  is  not  fear  of  illegitimate  pregnancy 
of  course  depends  on  the  institutional  definition  of  pregnancy  as 
illegitimate,  the  severity  of  social  sanctions  against  the  illegitimate 
child  and  its  mother,  or  against  the  memlliance  as  defined  by  a 
more  or  less  rigid  status  code.  The  worries  of  fathers  and  mothers 
thus  depend  on  the  existence  of  a  status  system  and  the  competitive 
craving  for  family  respectability. 

II.  In  the  military  order,  there  may  be  fear  of  death  and  fear 
of  defeat.  But  even  the  fear  of  death  can  be  reduced,  virtually  to 
zero,  by  intensive  cowardice-courage  programs  of  morale  build- 
ing. Since  Napoleon,  courage  has  been  "taken  for  granted"  in  all 
patriots,  but  in  the  twentieth  century  cowardice  and  courage  have 
become  part  of  the  manipulative  technology  of  morale  building. 
Surely  there  are  great  differences  in  the  anxieties  which  surrounded 
mercantilist  warfare,  for  which  Voltaire  depreciated  courage,  and 
those  which  surround  warfare  in  the  hills  of  Korea. 

III.  In  the  economic  order,  the  laissez-faire  entrepreneur  may 
fear  bankruptcy,  and  hence  loss  of  respectability,  as  well  as  loss  of 
money.  The  employee  may  fear  unemployment.  But  in  the  corpo- 
rate economy,  the  risk  of  big  business  is  often  largely  taken  over 
by  the  state.  The  fears  thus  become  political  rather  than  focused 
on  the  laissez-faire  market.  As  the  old  inscrutable  market  and  the 
business  firm  itself  are  rationalized  so  as  to  reduce  entrepreneurial 
anxiety,  new  anxieties  about  whether  the  corporation  has  a  political 
"in"  give  business  fears  a  new  focus  and  shape. 

IV.  In  the  political  order,  the  politician  may  fear  loss  of  office 
in  an  election;  the  citizen  may  fear  the  loss  of  prestige  of  the  state 
with  which  he  is  patriotically  identified,  among  the  prestige  striv- 
ings of  the  great  powers.  But  for  the  politician,  the  party  machine's 
fear  may  be  the  basis  of  his  discipline.  And  "the  citizen"  who  knows 
anxiety  from  national  loss  of  prestige  is  likely  to  be  of  the  upper- 
class  gentry  whose  evaluation  of  self  is  closely  joined  with  the 
prestige  of  the  nation,  which  he  represents  to  representative  men 
of  other  nations. 

V.  Some  sociologists— Herbert  Spencer,  for  example— define  re- 
ligion as  fear  of  the  dead.   Other  thinkers,  Freud  for  example, 


l86  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

have  stressed  fear  of  guilty  conscience  and  of  death  itself.  The 
symbol  spheres  of  some  religions,  however,  seem  to  have  to  do 
with  hope  as  well  as  with  fear,  indeed  the  two  are  frequently 
interrelated  in  religious  symbols  and  institutional  life.  If  religious 
institutions  form  a  dominant  order  in  the  social  structure,  and  if 
the  people  are  devout,  all  their  fears  and  anxieties— no  matter  what 
their  social  source— may  feed  into  the  religious  order  and  its  sym- 
bols. 

Agents  of  a  religious  hierarchy  may  fear  demotion  or  reassign- 
ment to  less  desirable  parishes,  and,  like  any  office  holder,  they 
may  relieve  their  anxieties  by  knowing  the  ropes  and  pulling  the 
strings.  What  religious  laities  fear  varies  with  the  religion  in  which 
they  believe,  and  the  demands  raised  by  the  religious  leaders  in 
the  name  of  its  God.  The  level  of  anxiety— for  example,  conscious- 
ness of  sin— will  vary  with  the  level  of  demand  that  prevails. 

Thus,  typical  fears  and  anxieties  may  be  located  sociologically  in 
each  institutional  order  and  sphere.  Although  some  men  may  feel 
that  we  have  nothing  to  fear  but  fear  itself,  most  men,  in  the  long 
history  of  mankind,  have  had  better  reasons  to  fear.  In  preindus- 
trial  times,  when  nature  was  still  unconquered,  many  fears  were 
primarily  based  upon  the  calamitous  consequences  of  that  fact. 
In  modern  societies,  anxieties  are  more  likely  to  have  their  sources 
in  the  opaque  and  unpredictable  drift  of  the  social  structure  and 
the  similarly  unstable  dynamics  of  interpersonal  relations. 

Fifty  years  ago,  "nervousness"  was  most  frequently  discussed  in 
connection  with  Victorian  problems  of  love,  prudery,  and  hysteria; 
nowadays— after  two  world  wars  and  a  vast  depression— insecurities 
and  anxieties  are  more  likely  to  be  seen  as  connected  with  social, 
economic,  and  military  securities,  or  their  prevailing  absence  from 
the  life  of  men. 

Just  as  sociological  conditions  lead  to  anxieties,  so  do  they  chan- 
nel the  compensations  which  relieve  anxieties.  A  number  of  typical 
mechanisms  for  such  relief,  which  Karen  Homey  has  called  "crav- 
ings," may  be  distinguished:  "  A  person  may  compensate  his  anxi- 
eties by  becoming  a  perfectionist,  eager  to  perform  his  roles  in 
such  a  way  as  never  to  lay  himself  open  to  criticism;  accordingly, 

"  For  an  extended  discussion  of  anxiety,  love,  affection,  and  power  see  Karen 
Homey,  The  Neurotic  Personality  of  Our  Time  (New  York,  1937),  Chapters 
3,  6,  and    10. 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  iS/ 

he  may  develop  the  traits  of  the  exaggerated  punctiho.  Anxiety 
may  also  be  personally  refracted  by  an  increased  craving  for  love 
and  affection  and  the  development  of  the  traits  of  the  overly 
affectionate  person.  In  this  craving,  the  person  may  allow  himself 
to  be  exploited  "for  love's  sake"  and  thereby  actually  damage  his 
self  in  other  roles.  He  may  crave  affectioti  at  all  costs,  in  order  to 
gain  protection,  his  motto  being  "If  you  love  me,  you  will  not 
hurt  me." 

Closely  allied  to  this  type  is  the  person  who  may  be  compulsively 
submissive  and  comply  with  every  wish  of  the  other,  "self-less"  as 
it  were,  lest  he  risk  being  hurt.  The  person  ivithdraws  from  involve- 
ment in  the  roles  of  an  institutional  order,  giving  up  all  psychic 
concomitants.  Again,  the  person  may  crave  power,  lest  he  have  to 
fear  anything  from  anybody.  In  extreme  cases,  we  refer  to  megalo- 
mania, but  ordinary  job  anxiety  may  lead  to  an  inordinate  develop- 
ment of  striving  for  family  power,  and  accompanying  traits  may 
be  developed  and  premiumed  by  the  person. 

These  compensatory  mechanisms  may  of  course  be  combined 
in  various  ways.  For  example,  inordinate  cravings  for  power  and 
the  accompanying  traits,  as  a  way  out  of  anxiety,  may  be  closely 
related  to  inordinate  cravings  for  love:  in  love,  one  lays  himself 
open  to  the  powers  of  another;  in  power,  one  strives  to  dominate 
the  submissive  other.  An  individual  who  oscillates  between  such 
opposite  tendencies,  and  their  accompanying  traits,  is  generally 
called  ambivalent.  What  is  logically  exclusive  need  not  be  psy- 
chologically exclusive.^" 

10  "Genuine  lo\'e"  differs  from  the  raw  impulse  of  sex  in  that  the  loved 
partner  is  incorporated  in  the  devoted  lo\er's  circle  of  significant  others  and 
hence,  self.  The  lover  is  eager  to  "gi\e"  and  to  "surrender"  his  best  to  the  per- 
son he  cherishes,  and  is  far  from  considering  his  loving  partner  an  "object  to  be 
gotten"  for  he  wishes  to  "give."  Lcn^jind  death  are  the  great  equalizers  of 
men^  By  loving  the  weak,  the  strong  learn  to  be  tender  and  to  control  rather 
than  to  exploit  their  strength  lest  they  brutalize  their  weaker  partner.  For 
loxe's  sake,  the  more  intelligent  will  not  use  their  superior  intelligence  to 
show  up  their  beloved  partner,  lest  they  shame  them,  or  are  themselves 
shamed.  The  rich  who  are  in  lo\e  with  poor  partners  will  eagerly  seek  to 
pro\e  that  "money-  does  not  matter."  So  loxe  leaps  over  all  differences  that 
divide  men,  and  if  thfe- work  of  art  has  been  called  "a  promise  of  happiness," 
the  art  of  "making  Io\e^in  the  Western  World  has  served  as  an  intimate 
reminder  oF  the  prophetic  promise  of  a  psychological  state  in  which  the 
lion  shall  rest  beside  the  lamb,  and  swords  shall  be  made  into  plowshares. 


l88  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

In  order  briefly  to  demonstrate  some  of  these  compensatory- 
mechanisms,  and  especially  to  show  how  they  may  be  combined 
in  specific  types  of  character,  we  shall  briefly  discuss,  as  types  of 
men,  the  classic  Puritan,  the  Confucian  mandarin,  and  the  noble- 
man of  France's  ancien  regime. 

I.  As  we  have  already  shown,  the  vocabulary  of  motives  need 
not  coincide  with  the  actual  operation  of  the  psychic  structure.^^ 
The  heroic  Puritan  of  seventeenth-century  England  could  methodi- 
cally pursue  his  quest  for  salvation  by  disciplining  himself  for  hard 
work  and  thriftiness,  and  thus  by  his  success  assure  his  religious 
worth  and  his  salvation  in  the  hereafter.  He  could,  in  short,  relieve 
his  anxieties  by  hard  work,  by  work  for  work's  sake,  and,  under 
the  appropriate  premiums,  take  great  pains  to  develop  a  new  "con- 
tract morality"  in  business  relationships.  Thus  perfectionism  and 
moral  rigor,  punctiliousness,  and  pleasure-denying  work,  along 
with  humility  and  the  craving  for  his  neighbor's  love  all  combined 
to  shape  the  character  structure  of  the  classical  Puritan  who  sought 

,Jxuiuastei:Jthe  jworld  rather  than  adjust-te-it.^^ 

II.  As  an  organization,  the  bureaucracy  of  gentlemanly  literati 
in  ancient  China  was  stable  and  weathered  great  political  crises, 
but  as  an  individual  the  Confucian  mandarin  was  highly  insecure. 
In  his  career,  there  existed  no  socially  transparent  link  between 
skill  and  merit  and  rewards  for  success.  Pull  and  bribery,  the 
arbitrary  favors  and  disfavors  of  superiors,  and  "luck"  dominated 
his  bureaucratic  chmb.  He  was  exposed  to  great  reversals  of  per- 
sonal fate  in  a  highly  competitive  context  where  many  aspirants 
pressed  upon  each  office  holder.  The  individual  official  was  a 
stranger  in  his  administrative  bailiwick,  was  subject  to  reassign- 
ments  to  other  provinces,  and  had  to  rely  upon  an  unofiicial  ad- 
viser who,  in  fact,  made  decisions  for  which  the  mandarin  was 
held  accountable. 

These  conditions,  as  well  as  others,  produced  an  intensive  and 
lasting  sense  of  insecurity  and  anxiety.  And  these  anxieties,  in  turn, 
were  compensated  by  a  great  emphasis  upon  a  rigid  code  of 
etiquette  and  ceremony  of  great  polish  and  finesse.  The  magical 
significance  attributed  to  the  Confucian  code  or  rules  of  propriety 
seems  to  indicate  its  compensatory  function  in  relieving  anxiety 

'1  See  Chapter  V:  The  Sociology  of  Motivation, 

i-For  further  comments  on  the  Puritan,  see  pp.  234-36  fiF.  and  360-638^. 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  l8g 

states.  In  passing,  we  may  mention  that  Confucius  himself  had 
lost  his  office  by  the  arbitrary  act  of  his  prince,  and  that  he  had 
developed  his  teachings  in  a  highly  competitve  context  of  itinerant 
political  intellectuals  striving  for  power  positions  at  the  courts  of 
rival  princes. 

Alongside  perfectionist,  ritualistic  tendencies,  we  observe  the 
intense  power  cravings  of  the  competitive  careerists  who,  after 
all,  were  without  specialized  training  for  administration.  These 
administrators  were  saddled  with  the  responsibility  for  anything 
that  went  wrong  in  their  bailiwicks,  whether  it  was  a  harvest  failure 
due  to  flood  or  drought,  a  tribal  invasion,  or  sheer  administrative 
negligence.  For  Confucian  thought  made  no  distinction  between 
nature  and  society— between  the  "acts  of  God"  and  the  responsibili- 
ties of  men.  And  the  mandarin,  partaking  of  the  supposedly  magical 
power  of  the  "Son  of  Heaven"  was  accountable  for  more  than  what 
men  can  control.  Naturally  this  maximized  his  pompous  sense  of 
megalomaniacal  power  and  his  stylized  conceit— as  well  as  his  un- 
derlying state  of  anxiety.  Given  ancestor  worship  as  part  of  the 
unwritten  constitution  of  Chinese  despotism,  the  disturbances  of 
social  order— cosmic  or  human— were  ascribed  to  the  unrest  of  the 
ancestral  spirits,  for  which  the  mandarin  bureaucrats— ultimately 
the  Son  of  Heaven  himself— were  blamed. 

Thus,  perfectionism  in  rigid  ceremonial  deportment  was  supple- 
mented by  intense  cravings  for  power  which  emerged  in  an  opaque 
context  of  career  striving.  These  two  tendencies  were  further  sup- 
plemented by  compulsive  conformism  with  Confucian  orthodoxy, 
a  system  of  "organized  thought"  based  upon  the  hallowed  classical 
writings  of  ancient  authors.  This  conformism  was  enforced  by  the 
ubiquitous  ideological  agents  of  a  powerful  board  of  censors.  How- 
ever efficient  this  spy  system  may  have  been  in  guaranteeing  the 
disciplined  cohesion  of  the  bureaucracy  as  a  whole,  for  the  indi- 
vidual bureaucrat  it  meant  an  additional  source  of  great  insecurity, 
and  the  resultant  anxiety  was  compensated  for  by  the  discourage- 
ment of  independent  thought,  intellectual  initiative,  and  any  direct 
confrontation  of  the  problems  at  hand.  Whatever  was  thought 
about  or  came  up  for  decision  was  stated  and  elaborated  in  terms 
of  the  sanctioned  body  of  classical  writings. ^'^ 

13  On  the  Chinese  literati,  see  Max  Weber,  The  Religion  of  China,  H.  H. 
Gerth,  tr.  ( Glencoe,  111.:  Free  Press,  1951). 


IQO  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

III.  The  nobleman  of  the  ancien  regime  stood  on  the  shaky 
ground  of  prerexolutionary  France.  Middle-class  intellectuals  had 
debunked  the  justification  of  the  divine  right  of  kings  as  a  mere 
sanction  of  despotism,  and  the  authority  of  the  priesthood  had  not 
gone  unquestioned.  Despotic  coercion  had  forced  the  nobility  to 
become  a  leisured  class,  living  as  absentee  owners  and  rentiers 
divorced  from  all  productive  functions.  The  competition  for  the 
king's  favors— for  offices  and  for  politically  profitable  marriages- 
was  intense  and  led  to  great  anxieties. 

These  anxiety  states  were  heightened  through  the  breakdown 
of  the  dividing  line  between  marriage  and  extramarital  relations 
with  mistresses,  between  legitimate  and  illegitimate  children  of 
kings  and  nobles.  Since  the  king  with  his  Christian  and  royal 
mistress  set  the  tone  and  established  the  model  for  all  courtly  be- 
havior, the  mistress  became  politically  and  socially  indispensable 
for  the  court  noble.  Good  relations  with  mistresses  were  important 
for  getting  the  news  behind  the  news. 

Machiavellian  attitudes  and  practices  permeated  the  ruling  strata. 
EflBciency  in  dueling  and  cautious  self-discipline  at  meals— where 
poison  cup  and  dagger  might  threaten  and  the  lap  dog  as  a  pre- 
tester  of  food  was  not  always  reliable— were  needed.  As  in  Chinese 
mandarin  society,  a  polished  ritualism  of  conventional  behavior 
emerged,  and  froze  into  a  rigid  code  of  court  etiquette. 

The  competition  of  cavaliers  under  the  watchful  eyes  of  hostesses 
blurred  the  lines  between  influence  and  love,  and  made  genuine 
love  a  tool  in  the  quest  for  power  and  influence,  and  influence 
an  opportimity  for  exploitative  love.  Love-making  became  a  tech- 
nology of  psychic  manipulation  and  seduction  a  fine  art.  Men 
could  never  know  whether  love  meant  devotion  or  unwilling  vas- 
salage. The  Liaisons  Dangereiises  by  Laclos  may  be  mentioned 
as  the  great  document  of  the  perversion  of  love  into  power. 

Intense  craving  for  power  and  a  ritualist  etiquette  in  personal 
relations  which  barred  "genuine  love";  the  craving  for  love  and 
popularity  as  means  for  the  furtherance  of  personal  careers;  flattery, 
conformist  attitudes,  and  posturing  to  win  the  favors  of  the  absolute 
and  always  suspicious  despot— all  these  were  so  many  compensa- 
tions for  the  basic  anxieties  of  a  class  whose  spokesmen  on  the  eve 
of  revolution  proclaimed:  "Apres  nous  le  deluge."  ^^ 

'*  See,  for  a  good  acctnint  of  tlie  old  regime,  Frantz  Funek-Brentano,  The 
Old  Regime  in  France,  Herbert  Wilson,  tr.  (London:  E.  Arnold,  1929).  See 


INSTITUTIONS     AND     PERSONS  IQl 

In  a  comparable  context,  the  Tsarist  nobility  was  subject  to  in- 
tense competition  for  the  office  appointments  on  which  the  noble 
rank  of  the  family  in  the  social  hierarchy  depended.  Some  re- 
sponded by  an  attitude  of  withdrawal  which  was  implemented  by 
a  mystic  Eastern  Christianity.  Especially  during  the  nineteenth 
century,  many  Russian  "repentant  noblemen"  went  abroad,  even 
preferring  to  be  expropriated  by  the  government  than  to  return. 
This  attitude  has  found  a  profound  elaboration  in  the  figure  of 
Goncharov's  "Oblomov,"  who  withdraws  from  competition  with 
his  erotical  competitor,  dreams  nostalgically  of  the  patriarchal  rela- 
tions of  old,  and  hence  accomplishes  nothing.  In  Russia,  this  state 
of  apathetic  withdrawal  and  soulful  quietism  ■  has  been  known 
as  "Oblomovism." 

In  this  chapter,  we  have  discussed  some  of  the  major  ways  in 
which  man  and  society— character  and  social  structure— are  linked. 
We  ha\'e  seen  that  institutions  select  persons  by  formal  and  in- 
formal rules  of  recruitment  and  ejection,  and  form  them  by  explicit 
training  and  by  means  of  the  particular  and  generalized  other, 
which  the  person— in  internalizing  instituted  roles— comes  in  time 
to  acquire.  We  have  also  explained  how  the  traits  of  the  person 
may  be  socially  premiumed,  and  thus  reinforced,  or  socially  ta- 
booed, and  thus  weakened,  by  various  institutional  contexts. 

We  have  suggested  that  the  symbol  sphere  of  institutional  orders, 
by  socially  defining  situations  that  the  person  confronts,  is  often  a 
cue  to  his  fears  and  anxiety  as  well  as  other  psychic  elements,  and 
we  have  illustrated  this  by  examples  from  the  kinship  and  military, 
the  economic,  the  political  and  the  religious  order.  Finally,  we 
have  discussed  certain  compensatory  mechanisms  as  revealed  in 
the  Puritan,  the  mandarin  and  the  nobleman.  - — 

also  L.  Ducros,  La  Societe  Frangaise  an  Dix-huitieme  Steele   (Paris:   Haties, 
1933). 


CHAPTER 

VIII 

Institutional  Orders 
and  Social  Controls,  I 


WE  wish,  in  the  present  and  in  the  next  chapter,  to  elaborate 
our  conceptions  of  institutional  orders  and  spheres,  as  well  as  to 
raise  certain  questions  appropriate  to  each  of  these  units  of  our 
model  of  social  structure.^  It  is  certainly  not  our  intention  to  ex- 
haust the  topics  which  we  discuss:  even  an  attempt  to  do  so  would 
require  a  many-volumed  universal  history  of  mankind.  What  we 
do  want  to  do  is  to  define  certain  useful  conceptions;  to  lay  out  the 
range  of  institutions  available  to  sociological  observation;  and  to 
describe  certain  pivotal  types  of  institutions  that  have  at  various 
times  characterized  political  and  economic,  military  and  religious, 
kinship  and  educational  endeavors.  In  doing  so,  we  shall  pay  par- 
ticular attention  to  the  social  controls  that  often  prevail  in  each 
of  these  institutional  orders  or  spheres  and  the  types  of  persons 
that  they  tend  to  select  and  form.- 

1.  The  Political  Order  ^ 

The  political  order,  we  have  said,  consists  of  those  institutions 
within  which  men   acquire,   wield,   or  influence   distributions   of 

^  For  preliminary  definitions  of  these  orders  and  spheres,  see  Chapter  II: 
Character  and  Social  Structure,  Section  2:   Components  of  Social  Structure. 

-  For  further  statement  of  our  guiding  questions  for  such  work,  see  Chap- 
ter II:  Character  and  Social  Structure,  Section  3:  The  Tasks  of  Social 
Psychology. 

3  The  student  will  find  the  following  readings  of  signal  importance:  Max 
Weber,  "Politics  as  a  Vocation,"  From  Max  Weber:  Essatjs  in  Sociology, 
H.  H.  Gertli  and  C.  Wright  Mills,  trs.  and  eds.  (New  York:  Oxford,  1946), 
pp.  77-128;  il.  D.  Lasswell  and  A.  Kaplan,  Power  and  Society  (New  Haven: 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I        \  IQ;^ 

power.  We  ascribe  "power"  to  those  who  can  influence  the  conduct 
of  others  even  against  their  will. 

Where  everyone  is  equal  there  is  no  politics,  for  politics  involves 
subordinates  and  superiors.  All  institutional  conduct,  of  course, 
involves  distributions  of  power,  but  such  distributions  are  the  es- 
sence of  politics.  In  so  far  as  it  has  to  do  with  "the  state,"  the  poli- 
tical order  is  the  "final  authority";  in  it  is  instituted  the  use  of 
final  sanctions,  involving  physical  force,  over  a  given  territorial 
domain.  This  trait  marks  off  political  institutions,  such  as  the  state, 
from  other  institutional  orders. 

Since  power  implies  that  an  actor  can  carry  out  his  will,  power 
involves  obedience.  The  general  problem  of  politics  accordingly 
is  the  explanation  of  varying  distributions  of  power  and  obedi- 
ence, and  one  basic  problem  of  political  psychology  is  why  men 
by  their  obedience  accept  others  as  the  powerful.  Why  do  they 
obey? 

A  straightforward,  although  inadequate,  answer  is  given  by  those 
who  see  men  in  the  large  as  herd  animals  who  must  be  led  by  a 
strong  man  who  stays  out  in  front.  The  explanation  of  power  and 
obedience  in  terms  of  the  strong  man  may  hold  in  some  primitive 
contexts  in  which  only  the  strong  fighter  has  a  chance  to  become  a 
military  and  political  chieftain;  ^  it  may  also  hold  in  the  "gang," 
where  awe  of  the  strongest  holds  the  others  to  obedience,  and  con- 
tests over  power  are  decided  by  fist  fights.  Beyond  such  situations, 
however,  the  problem  of  power  cannot  be  reduced  to  a  problem  of 
simple  physical  might. 

In  Bernard  Shaw's  Saint  Joan,  the  dauphin  dryly  remarks  that 
he  lacked  a  great  deal  in  almost  everything  because  his  ancestors 
had  used  it  all  up.  Yet,  despite  such  personal  weaknesses,  other 
men  looked  up  to  the  dauphin  and  obeyed  him.  Physical  and  men- 
tal weaklings  are  often  found  ruling  proud  and  strong  men.  We 
cannot  therefore  always  explain  authority  and  obedience  in  terms 
of  the  characteristics  of  the  power  holder.  Although  Bismarck  once 
said  that  you  can  do  all  sorts  of  things  with  bayonets  except  sit 
on  them,  obviously  power  and  obedience  involve  more  than  dif- 

Yale  Univ.  Press,  1950);  H.  E.  Barnes,  Sociology  and  Political  Theory  (New 
York:  Knopf,  1924);  G.  Mosca,  The  Ruling  Class,  H.  D.  Kahn,  tr.  (New 
York:   McGraw-Hill,   1939). 

*  "And  when  Saul  stood  among  the  people,  he  was  higher  than  any  of 
the  people  from  his  shoulders  and  upward"  (I  Sam.,  10:23). 


ig4  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

ferences  in  the  biological  means  and  the  physical  implements  of 
violence.^ 

The  incongruity  of  strong  men  willingly  obeying  physical  weak- 
lings leads  us  to  ask:  Why  are  there  stable  power  relations  which 
are  not  based  on  the  direct  and  physical  force  of  the  stronger? 
The  question  has  been  answered  by  political  scientists  and  philos- 
ophers in  terms  of  a  consensus  between  the  subordinates  and  the 
powerful.  This  consensus  has  been  rationally  formulated  in  the- 
ories of  "contract,"  "natural  law,"  or  "public  sentiment."  **  For  the 
social  psychologist,  such  approaches  are  valuable  in  that  they  em- 
phasize the  question  of  voluntary  obedience,  for  from  a  psycho- 
logical point  of  view  the  crux  of  the  problem  of  power  rests  in 
understanding  the  origin,  constitution,  and  maintenance  of  volun- 
tary obedience. 

There  is  an  element  of  truth  in  Laud's  assertation:  "There  can 
be  no  firmness  without  law;  and  no  laws  can  be  binding  if  there  is 
no  conscience  to  obey  them;  penalty  alone  could  never,  can  never 
do  it."  '  In  any  given  political  order,  we  may  expect  to  find  both 
"conscience"  and  "coercion,"  and  it  is  the  element  of  conscience,  of 
voluntary  obedience,  that  engages  our  attention,  even  though  we 
keep  in  mind  the  fact  that  regardless  of  the  type  and  extent  of 
conscience,  all  states  practice  coercion. 

An  adequate  understanding  of  power  relations  thus  involves  a 
knowledge  of  the  grounds  on  which  a  power  holder  claims  obedi- 
ence, and  the  terms  in  which  the  obedient  feels  an  obligation  to 
obey.  The  problem  of  the  grounds  of  obedience  is  not  a  supra- 
historical  question;  we  are  concerned  rather  with  reconstructing 
those  central  ideas  which  in  given  institutional  structures  in  fact 
operate  as  grounds  for  obedience.  Often  such  ideas  are  directly 
stated  and  theoretically  elaborated;  often  they  are  merely  implied, 
left  inarticulate  and  taken  for  granted.  But,  in  either  case,  differ- 
ent reasons  for  obedience  prevail  in  different  political  institutions. 

•''  The  extent  of  \ iolcnce  in  political  orders  \aries.  Thus  thirteen  out  of 
fourteen  nineteenth-century  presidents  of  Bolivia  died  by  \'iolence,  but  only 
four  out  of  thirty-tliree  presidents  of  the  United  States.  Cf.  P.  A.  Sorokin, 
"Monarchs  and   Rulers,"  Social  Forces,  March   1926. 

®  See  Chapter  X:  Symbol  Spheres,  especially  Section  1:  Symbol  Spheres 
in  Six  Contexts. 

^  Cited  by  John  N.  Figgis,  The  Divine  Right  of  Kings  (rev.  ed.;  Cambridge: 
University  Press,  1934),  p.  265. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  J  95 

In  terms  of  the  publicly  recognized  reasons  for  obedience— "legi- 
timations" or  symbols  of  justification  ^— the  core  of  the  problem  of 
politics  consists  in  understanding  "authority."  For  it  is  authority 
that  characterizes  ^nduring_pohtical  orders.  The  power  of  one 
animal  over  another  may  occur  in  terms  of  brute  coercion,  accom- 
panied by  grimts  and  growls,  but  man,  as  Susanne  Langer  has 
written,  can  "control  [his]  inferiors  by  setting  up  symbols  of  [his] 
power,  and  the  mere  idea  that  words  or  images  convey  stands  there 
to  hold  our  fellows  in  subjection  even  when  we  cannot  lay  our  hands 
on  them.  .  .  .  Men  .  .  .  oppress  each  other  by  symbols  of  might."  " 

Power  is  simply  the  probability  that  men  will  act  as  another  man 
wishes.  This  action  may  rest  upon  fear,  rational  calculation  of  ad-  ^ 
vantage,  lack  of  energy  to  do  otherwise,  loyal  devotion,  indiffer--^ 
ence,  or  a  dozen  other  individual  motives.  AiitJioritij,  or  legiti- 
mated power,  involves  \'oluntary  obedience  based  on  some  idea 
which  the  obedient  holds  of  the  powerful  or  of  his  position.  "The 
strongest,"  wrote  Rousseau,  "is  never  strong  enough  to  be  always 
master,  unless  he  transforms  his  strength  into  right,  and  obedience 
into  duty."  ^° 

Most  political  analysts  have  thus  come  to  distinguish  between 
those  acts  of  power  which,  for  various  reasons,  are  considered  to  be 
"legitimate,"  and  those  which  are  not.  We  speak  of  "naked  power" 
as,  for  instance,  during  warfare,  after  which  the  successful  tries  to 
gain  "authority"  over  the  defeated;  and  we  speak  of  "authority" 
in  cases  of  legitimate  acts  of  power,  and  thus,  of  "public  authori- 
ties," or  "ecclesiastic"  or  "court  authority"  and  so  on.  In  order  to 
become  "duly  authorized,"  power  needs  to  clothe  itself  with  at- 
tributes of  "justice,"  "morality,"  "religion,"  and  other  cultural  \'alues 
which  define  acceptable  "ends"  as  well  as  the  "responsibilities"  of 
those  who  wield  power.  Since  power  is  seen  as  a  means,  men  ask: 
"Whose  power  and  for  what  ends?"  And  most  supreme  power 
holders  seek  to  give  some  sort  of  answer,  to  clothe  their  power 
in  terms  of  other  ends  than  power  for  power's  sake. 

Machiavelli,  to  be  sure,  formulated  a  rationale  of  power  for 
its  own  sake,  relegating  all  the  alleged  and  professed  purposes  of 

^  See  Chapter  X:   Symbol  Spheres. 

^  Fortune,  January  1944,  p.  150.  See  also  her  Philosophy  in  a  Sew  Key 
(Cambridge:  Hanard  Uni\'.  Press,  1942),  pp.  286-87. 

^°  J.  J.  Rousseau,  Social  Contract,  rev.  tr.  by  Charles  Frankel  (New  York: 
Hafner,  1947). 


ig6  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

power  to  instrumental  positions/^  He  did  this  in  an  effort  to  ana- 
lyze the  necessary  and  sufficient  means  for  getting  and  for  holding 
power.  His  name  accordingly  became  despised  and  to  this  day 
"Machiavellian"  carries  an  infamous  connotation,  although  it  has 
rightly  been  said  that  perhaps  Machiavelli  was  the  one  honest  man 
of  his  age.  His  debunking  of  the  moral  purposes  of  rulers,  and  his 
principled  distrust  of  "power"  as  such,  is  carried  on  by  the  often 
quoted  dictinn  of  Lord  Acton  that  "Power  corrupts  and  absolute 
power  corrupts  absolutely."  This  statement,  however,  seems  to  us 
quite  one-sided;  we  might  assert  with  equal  justice  that  "Power 
ennobles  and  absolute  power  ennobles  absolutely."  We  need  merely 
substitute  "responsibility"  for  power  to  make  the  point  obvious. 
Persons  in  positions  of  authority  are  expected  to  make  "respon- 
sible decisions,"  and  some  men  do  grow  with  the  tasks  which  they 
take  up.  If  men  choose  tasks,  tasks  make  men;  high  or  exalted 
position  sometimes  provides  more  opportunities  for  a  man  to  be- 
come "high  minded"  and  to  act  accordingly.  As  Ralph  Waldo 
Emerson,  writing  of  the  English  nobility,  put  it, 

"You  cannot  wield  great  agencies  without  lending  yourself  to 
them,  and  when  it  happens  that  the  spirit  of  the  earl  meets  his 
rank  and  duties,  we  have  the  best  examples  of  behavior.  Power 
of  any  kind  readily  appears  in  the  manners;  and  beneficit  le  talent 
de  bien  faire,  gives  a  majesty  which  cannot  be  concealed  or  re- 
sisted." ^^ 

Decision-making  groups  in  our  time— with  increasingly  powerful 
machines  and  far-flung  organizations— necessarily  hold  more  power 
and  more  authority  than  ever  before;  accordingly,  their  corruption 
seems  more  hideous,  and  their  ennoblement  more  grandiose,  than 
in  previous  times. 

In  his  Anthropology  of  1789,  Kant  emphasized  liberty  and  law 
—which  restricts  liberty— as  the  two  pivots  around  which  civil 
legislation  turns.  But  he  added  that  force  has  to  be  included  as  a 
mediating  element  in  order  to  make  effective  legislation  according 
to  the  principles  of  liberty  and  law.  Kant  imagined  several  combi- 

11  Niccolo  Machiavelli,  The  Frince;  and  The  Discourses  (New  York:  Mod- 
ern Library,   1940). 

1-  Etifilish  Traits,  Chapter  One,  cited  in  The  Writings  of  Ralph  Waldo  Emer- 
son (New  York:  Modern  Library,  1940),  p.  622. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  IQJ 

nations  of  force,  liberty,  and  law:  thus,  law  and  liberty  without 
force  would  seem  to  be  anarchy.  Law  and  force  without  liberty  are 
despotism.  Force  without  liberty  or  law  is  simply  barbarism.  Force 
with  freedom  and  law  are  the  bases  of  a  republic.  Only  this  last 
condition,  according  to  Kant,  deserves  the  title  of  a  "true  civil 
constitution,"  although  he  did  not  mean  by  republic  that  form  of 
state  we  call  democratic,  but  any  constitutional  state. ^^ 

2.  Nation  and  State  ^* 

The  term  "state"  first  became  popular  in  sixteenth-century  Italy. 
There  the  Italian  city-states  first  organized  bureaucratic  adminis- 
trations, professional  bodies  of  diplomats,  and  armies  of  citizens 
who  were  ready  if  need  be  to  forego  the  salvation  of  their  souls— 
as  Machiavelli  says  in  honor  of  the  Florentine  citizenry— in  order 
to  preserve  the  liberties  of  their  city. 

A  state  is  a  political  institution  which  successfully  claims  supreme 
power  over  a  defined  territory.  This  claim  can  be  realized  when  the 
state  effectively  monopolizes  the  use  of  legitimate  violence  against 
external  and  internal  enemies,  however  the  state-leaders  may  de- 
fine "enemy." 

A  state  capable  of  conducting  wars  against  competing  states 
and  of  monopolizing  legitimate  violence  within  its  own  territory  is 
sociologically  one  state,  even  though  legally  it  may  be  a  confederacy 
of  substates.  That  the  United  States  of  America  is  one  state,  for 
example,  was  decisively  established  by  the  American  Civil  War. 
And  it  is  the  fact  of  a  monopoly  of  legitimate  violence  that  makes 
the  difference  between  the  United  States  and  such  interstate  crea- 
tions as  the  late  "League  of  Nations,"  or  the  prevailing  "United 
Nations." 

A  nation  is  a  body  of  people  which  by  cultural  traditions  and 
common  historical  memories  is  capable  of  organizing  a  state,  or  at 
least  which  raises  the  claim  for  such  an  autonomous  organization 
with  some  chance  of  success. 

13  Paraphrased  from  Inimanuel  Kant,  Anthropologies  in  pragmatischer 
Hinsicht  (5th  ed.;  Leipzig:  Karl  Vorlander,  1912),  pp.  286  ff. 

^*  The  most  informatixe  xohmie  on  nationahsm  is  probably  Hans  Kohn, 
The  Idea  of  Nationalism  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1951).  See  also  Max  Weber, 
op.  cit.,  pp.  159-79- 


ig8  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

The  symbols  by  which  claims  to  statehood,  to  the  state-organized 
cohesiveness  of  a  nation  are  advanced  and  justified  may  be  called 
nationalism.  After  a  state  is  organized,  these  nationalist  symbols 
may  prevail  as  legitimations.  Nationalism  is  thus  the  justifying 
ideology  of  a  nation-state  or  of  a  nation  aspiring  to  become  a  state. 
Nationalism  expresses  loyalties  and  aspirations,  and  tends  to  in- 
\ol\e  the  feeling  that  the  typical  features  of  one  nation  may  be 
used  as  a  yardstick  of  traits  alleged  to  characterize  other  nations. 

We  have  to  distinguish  between  "patriotism"  and  "nationalism" 
as  complex  sentiments  differently  related  to  the  political  order  of  a 
societ)^  National  sentiment  incorporates  patriotism,  but,  because 
of  its  power  reference  to  the  nation-state,  it  involves  more. 

Patriotism  refers  to  "love  of  one's  country  and  people"  without 
necessarily  involving  emotional  investment  in  the  political  order 
and  its  institutional  peculiarity.  Patriotism  is  a  pride  in  the  culture 
heritage  of  the  nation  devoid  of  aspirations  to  win  "glory"  (the 
prestige  of  power)  in  international  competition.  In  fact,  to  stay 
out  of  international  power  contests,  and  to  be  left  alone  by  others, 
is  the  core  of  this  sentiment,  which  is  often  most  intense  among  the 
smallest  nations,  such  as  Norway  or  Switzerland. 

Nationalism  is  a  specifically  modern  sentiment  which  binds  the 
mass  of  the  citizenry  to  the  political  order  in  a  common  aspiration 
to  hold  their  own  in  power  competition  with  other  nations  by  or- 
ganizing all  institutional  orders  in  the  framework  of  a  sovereign 
state.  Nationalism  claims  the  right  of  the  nation  to  determine  its 
own  fate,  that  is  to  organize  itself  without  intervention  from  the 
outside.  To  the  people,  nationalist  spokesmen  address  specific 
expectations  "in  the  name  of  the  nation,"  and  they  define  conduct 
patterns  and  symbolic  behavior  normatively  as  "national,"  that  is, 
as  conduct  to  be  ascribed  to  the  nation  as  a  whole,  and  against 
what  is  "alien."  Nowadays  such  appeals  are  made  to  diverse  aggre- 
gates and  organized  publics  by  power  holders  in  all  institutional 
orders.  Thus,  commercial  advertising  campaigns  demand  "Buy 
American"  or  "Buy  British."  Purists  may  crusade  against  the  bor- 
rowing of  foreign  words  and  ideas.  Nationalist  Christians  tend  to 
conceive  of  Almighty  God  as  having  distinct  national  preferences, 
especially  during  world  wars.  Protestantism,  particularly,  has  al- 
ways had  an  intimate  relationship  to  nationalism.  Publishers  and 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  199 

literati,  of  course,  promote  "national  literature"  and  "national  art," 
and  historians  write  "national  history." 

As  the  symbols  of  justification  for  the  acts  of  a  state,  nationalism 
promotes  loyalty  and  obedience  to  state  authority.  Nationalist  sym- 
bols, however,  may  be  highly  elaborated.  And  in  intellectual 
circles  they  may  be  thought  of  as  the  very  ground  or  embodiment 
of  the  nation-state,  rather  than  merely  symbols  justifying  state 
power.  Thus  Montesquieu's  "national  genius"  and  Herder's  Volks- 
geist  have  been  used  and  abused  in  state  propaganda  for  increas- 
ing internal  loyalty  and  external  aggression. 

Chauvinism  is  nationalism  carried  to  the  extreme  of  exclusive, 
and  hence  fanatical,  assertion  of  a  nation's  mission,  and  the  studious 
devaluation  of  all  other  nations.  The  term  was  put  into  circulation 
because  of  Napoleon's  political  aide,  M.  Chauvin's,  rather  extrava- 
gant glorifications  of  France, 

Nation  and  state  need  not,  of  course,  be  identical,  either  in  ter- 
ritory or  in  political  domination.  The  belief  that  national  unity 
should  be  the  basis  of  state  unity  is,  of  course,  a  political  choice 
and  not  a  universal  historical  fact.  The  existence  of  cultural  and 
national  minorities  in  many  states,  the  absorption  of  national  com- 
munities by  larger,  imperial  states,  and  the  existence  of  nationals 
outside  the  state's  dominion— these  are  facts  which  run  counter  to 
the  ideology  of  national  self-determination.  Indeed,  the  idea  of 
national  self-determination  is  modern,  involving  liberal  democratic 
conceptions  quite  foreign  to  early  dynastic  states.  During  the 
nineteenth  century,  the  Polish  nation  was  organized  by  three  states: 
partly  by  the  Russian  Tsar,  partly  by  the  German  Reich,  and  partly 
by  the  Austro-Hungarian  monarchy.  The  latter  state,  indeed,  or- 
ganized several  nations  under  one  state.  On  the  other  hand,  pre- 
Bismarckian  Germany  was  one  nation  organized  in  a  plurality  of 
states.  The  principle  of  nationality  (namely,  that  each  nation 
should  correspond  to  an  autonomous  state)  was  propagated  by 
such  men  as  Mazzini  and  Napoleon  III;  it  was  given  grandiose 
influence  by  President  Wilson's  late  "self-determination"  program 
for  Europe,  and  Lenin's  for  the  colonial  peoples. 

In  the  first  half  of  the  nineteenth  century,  nationalism  was  the 
sister  creed  of  liberalism  and  defended  one  liberal  goal:  the  re- 
lease of  peoples  from  the  rule  of  alien  states.  Positively,  nationalists 


200  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

sought  to  establish  constitutions.  But  of  course,  nationaUsm  had  re- 
peatedly passed  from  defense  to  aggression  and  back  again:  rather 
than  the  release  of  aspiring  political  communities  from  alien  state 
rule,  nationalism  came,  in  the  nineteenth  century  especially,  to 
involve  the  attempt  to  subjugate  other  peoples  to  its  rule.  In  many 
places  "National  Unity"  superseded  "The  Consent  of  the  Gov- 
erned." Thus  nineteenth-century  nationalism  closed  with  a  flower- 
ing of  imperialism.^^ 

When  loyalty  to  a  ruling  house  is  replaced  by  loyalty  to  a  na- 
tional state,  national  symbols  are  propagated  by  means  of  public 
educational  systems.  Concentrating  upon  the  masses  of  the  popu- 
lation, magazine  and  novel,  newspaper  and  radio  and  motion  pic- 
ture all  help  to  disseminate  favorable  images  and  stereotypes  of 
the  nation.  Scholarly  writings  are  organized  in  terms  of  national 
histories.  As  the  territory  dominated  by  the  nation  is  typically 
larger  than  that  dominated  by,  say,  the  tribe,  and  as  the  population 
is  not  necessarily  connected  even  distantly  by  blood  or  religion, 
modern  nationalism  has  had  to  rely  more  on  mass  education  and 
propaganda.  The  development  of  compulsory  education,  cheap 
printing,  and  recently  of  radio  and  motion  pictures  may  thus  con- 
veniently be  viewed  in  connection  with  nationalism.^*^  It  is  clear 
that  the  state  of  communication  facilities  affects  the  extent  and 
penetration  of  nationalism  within  the  territory  of  the  state.  When 
communication  facilities  are  not  universal  in  their  coverage,  the 
sensitive  spots  will  be  the  frontier  or  border  zones  and  the  na- 
tional capital,  the  intervening  areas  remaining  less  affected. 

Lack  of  correspondence  between  the  territory  dominated  by  a 
state  and  the  population  composing  a  nation  has  stimulated  the 
search  for  other  possible  bases  of  nationhood.  "Nation"  has  thus 
been  used  to  refer  to  feelings  of  loyalty  among  a  population  hav- 
ing language,  literature,  folk  heroes,  historical  tradition,  culture, 
race,  or  religious  denomination  in  common.  All  of  these  factors,  in 
various  combinations,  may  indeed  be  elements  in  the  situation  of 
a  nation,  which  is  to  say  that  they  may  increase  the  chance  that 
aspirations  for  national  self-determination,  for  the  setting  up  of  an 

!■''•  See  William  A.  Dunnigan,  "Fundamental  Conceptions  of  igtli  Century 
Politics,"  Congress  of  Arts  and  Sciences,  St.  Louis,  IQ04  (New  York,  1906), 
Vol.  VII,  pp.  279-92. 

i<^See  Chapter  IX:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  II,  Section  4: 
The  Educational  Si^here. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  201 

autonomous  state,  will  be  realized.  The  actual  reasons,  however, 
for  belief  in  the  existence  of  a  national  community  vary  enor- 
mously, and  may  change  during  the  course  of  national  history. 

Rather  vague  ideas  of  common  descent  are  often  at  the  bottom 
of  nationality  feelings.  But  such  feeling  need  not  exist  at  all,  and 
frequently  does  not.  Nor  do  "races"  by  any  means  correspond  with 
nations.  The  population  of  modern  Germany,  for  example,  is  com- 
posed of  diverse  ethnic  groups,  and  in  such  nations  as  the  United 
States,  Brazil,  and  the  Soviet  Union  practically  all  the  major  strains 
can  be  found  among  the  citizenry.  "Race,"  used  in  reference  to 
Turks,  Germans,  or  English,  is,  as  Franz  Boas  put  it,  "only  a  dis- 
guise of  the  idea  of  nationality."  ^^ 

Most  nation-states  have  been  ready,  willing,  and  eager  to  de- 
clare themselves  "a  God-fearing  people."  The  denominational  varie- 
ties of  Christianity  have  been  conveniently  accommodated  to  this 
eagerness.  Religious  and  national  differences  and  conflicts  may  be 
very  closely  intermingled,  as  in  the  conflict  of  the  Irish  and  the 
English,  and  national  heroes  may  be  treated  as  saints,  as  among 
the  Serbs  and  other  Greek  orthodox  nations.  That  Joan  of  Arc 
was  canonized  by  the  Catholic  church— after  the  Franco-Prussian 
war  of  1870-71— is  a  fact  relevant  to  French  nationalism.^* 

A  specific  language,  given  its  practical  incompatibility  with  other 
languages,  is  perhaps  the  most  important  common  "social"  feature 
of  a  nation.  Yet  a  national  community  organized  under  a  state 
may  have  several  languages— as  in  the  case  of  modern  Switzerland. 
In  terms  of  feeling,  the  national  identity  means  a  specific  kind  of 
pathos,  which  is  more  likely  to  develop  where  there  is  a  common 
language  and  religion,  conventions  and  style  of  life,  history  and 
destiny. 

All  these  communal  factors,  as  components  of  a  national  situa- 
tion, tend  to  increase  the  idea  of  an  autonomous  power  organiza- 
tion or  state,  which  may  already  exist  or  be  ardently  longed  for. 
The  more  this  power  or  state  aspect  is  emphasized,  the  more  spe- 
cific is  the  nation.  To  understand  differences  between  nations,  one 
must  examine  the  components  of  the  national  situation  for  every 
empirical  case,  yet  two   general   and  closely  related  factors   are 

1^  Franz  Boas,  "Race  and  Nationality,"  Bulletin  of  the  American  Association 
for  International  Conciliation,  January   1915,  p.   8. 

^^^  See  Max  Hildebert  Boehm,  "Nationalism,"  Encyclopaedia  of  the  Social 
Sciences,  Vol.  XI,  p.  236. 


202  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

essential   to   the   social   psychologist  who   would  understand   "na- 
tional differences": 

I.  It  is  important  to  understand  the  institutional  composition 
of  the  national  social  structure,  and  especially  the  relations  of  the 
state  to  the  several  institutional  orders.  We  shall  in  due  course 
specify  the  procedures  which  we  think  most  useful  for  this  task. 

II.  It  is  also  important  to  understand  the  types  of  persons  who 
within  a  given  national  social  structure  are  held  up  as  models  of 
imitation  and  aspiration.  These  national  types— the  Prussian 
Junker,^"  the  Japanese  Samurai,-°  the  British  gentleman,"^  the 
French  honnete  hommc,  the  American  self-made  man,  the  Russian 
Soviet  man— serve  to  unify  national  images  and  may  become  the 
stereotyped  image  of  the  nation  itself.-^ 

The  image  of  the  nation,  and  the  entire  conception  of  national- 
ity, will  vary  from  one  stratum  to  another  within  the  national  so- 
cial structure.  In  the  United  States,  for  example,  such  status  groups 
as  the  D.A.R.  and  "Pilgrim  societies"  may  stress  Anglo-Saxon 
descent,  while  industrial  workers,  liberal  intellectuals,  and  immi- 
grants think  rather  of  the  American  Dream  or  "the  melting  pot." 
Various  images  of  the  nation  may  be  seized  upon  by  vested  inter- 
ests or  movements.  Thus  "Americanism"  and  "the  American  way 
of  life"  may  be  identified  with  laissez-faire  economics  and  a  free 
competition  for  workers  (no  trade  unions)  by  capitalist  groups. 

The  initial  claim  of  a  people  to  nationhood  is  typically  advanced 
by  an  intellectual  vanguard  who  out  of  material  and  ideal  interests 
tend  to  sentimentalize  their  native  language  and  to  develop  it  into 

1 "  See  Max  Weber,  "Capitalism  and  Rural  Society  in  Germany"  and  "Na- 
tional Character  and  the  Junkers,"  op.  cit.,  pp.  363-95;  E.  Kohn-Bramstedt, 
Aristocracy  and  the  Middle  Classes  in  Germany  (London:  King,  1937);  and 
Paul  Kosok,  Modern  Germany  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1933). 

-"  See  G.  B.  Sansom,  Japan-  A  Short  Cultural  History  (rev.  ed.;  New  York: 
Appleton-Century,  1943);  and  Hillis  Lory,  Japan's  Military  Masters  (New 
York:  Viking,  1943).  For  a  sensible  statement  of  difficulties,  see  John  F. 
Embrose,  "Standardized  Error  and  Japanese  Character,"  World  Politics,  Vol. 
II   (1948-50),  pp.  439  ff. 

-1  See  Wilhelm  Dibelius,  England,  M.  A.  Hamilton,  tr.  (New  York:  Harper, 
1930);  G.  J.  Renier,  The  English:  Are  They  Human?  (New  York:  P.  Smith, 
1931);  and  Karl  H.  Abshagen,  King,  Lords  and  Gentlemen,  E.  W.  Dickes,  tr. 
(London:  Heinemann,  1939). 

^-  Walter  Bagehot  has  laid  stress  upon  the  social  selection  and  diffusion  of 
such  types  in  his  penetrating  discussion  of  "Nation-making";  see  Physics  and'. 
Politics  (New  York,  1912),  Chapters  3  and  4. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  20^^ 

a  medium  for  a  national  literary  expression.  In  this  creative  process 
the  pecuHarities  of  the  language  are  discovered,  elaborated,  and 
defended  as  superior  or  at  least  equal  to  any  other.  In  these  na- 
tionalist endeavors  intellectual  prestige  and  the  business  interests 
of  publishers  may  clash  or  fuse  with  the  interests  of  politicians. 
Once  it  becomes  the  official  language  of  educational,  scientific,  and 
jurisdictional  institutions,  the  national  tongue  acquires  additional 
prestige.  A  national  literature  as  an  art  form  is  apt  to  emerge  and 
be  democratized.  As  long  as  this  literature  sentimentalizes  promi- 
nent features  of  the  territory,  prominent  folkways,  and  memories 
of  the  people,  we  may  speak  of  "cultural  patriotism."  From  this  it 
is  but  a  short  step  to  modern  nationalism,  which  embodies  a  spe- 
cific political  pathos  for  the  community  at  large.  Symbols  of  the 
people's  martyrdom— national  heroes  and  founding  fathers— in  the 
face  of  aggression  stand  opposite  symbols  of  forthcoming  libera- 
tion, that  is  to  say,  autonomous  statehood. 

In  the  twentieth  century,  these  processes  of  nation-building  are 
being  repeated  in  dependent  political  areas  in  the  Middle  and 
Far  East,  in  the  Caribbean,  and  in  various  British  Dominions.  Na- 
tionals educated  as  clerks,  lawyers,  journalists,  for  purposes  of 
working  in  the  domination  structure  of  the  Western  powers,  usually 
form  the  vanguard  of  these  movements,  which  are  typically  viewed 
by  the  dominant  country's  leaders  as  "a  handful  of  agitators"  rather 
than  a  revival  or  creation  of  a  national  community.  In  modern 
nations,  the  middle  classes  usually  become  the  most  ardent  fol- 
lowers of  the  nationalist  intelligentsia,  although,  especially  during 
wars,  nationalist  enthusiasm  tends  to  be  universal  among  all  classes 
of  the  political  community.-^ 

Once  a  national  community  is  fully  a  state,  it  monopolizes  the 
use  of  legitimate  violence  within  its  domain,  defends  its  domain 
against  other  states,  and  may  attempt  to  expand  it.  The  combat 
range  of  modern  armed  forces  and  the  range  of  communications 
and  transportation  are  important  factors  in  determining  the  size 
of  the  political  territory  of  a  state.  Although,  as  Butler  remarked, 
the  "sphere  of  action  of  .  .  .  the  greater  part  of  mankind  is  much 

-3  See,  for  example,  Rupert  Emerson,  Lennox  A.  Mills  and  Virginia  Thomp- 
son, Government  and  Nationalism  in  Southeast  Asia  (New  York:  Institute  of 
Pacific  Relations,  1942);  and  D.  H.  Buchanan,  The  Development  of  Capitalist 
Enterprise  in  India  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1934). 


204  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

narrower  than  the  government  they  hve  under,"  -*  the  sphere  of 
action  of  the  great  jjower  state  is  typically  larger  than  its  own 
pacified  domain.  Pride  in  one's  nation,  as  we  have  noted,  often 
involves  an  ethnocentric  affirmation  of  the  nation's  peculiarities. 
This  sense  of  superiority  typically  feeds  on  the  notion  of  the  exem- 
plary significance  of  one's  own  nation-state  for  other  nations,  if 
not  for  "the  rest  of  the  world."  This  sense  may  exist  without  any 
ambition  to  do  more  than  propagate  this  prestigeful  image.  Any 
nationalist  expansion  of  power  may  thus  be  rejected  by  "isolation- 
ist" sentiments  and  policies. 

On  the  other  hand,  nationalism  may  inspire  ambitions  territor- 
ially to  expand  the  political  influence  of  the  nation  so  as  to  make 
its  actual  or  potential  policies  count  heavily  in  international  affairs. 
Usually  various  spokesmen  for  the  nation  attribute  a  specific 
"honor"  to  their  nation,  which  forbids  them  to  tolerate  or  "to  take" 
one  thing  or  another  from  various  other  nations.  Their  policies  of 
expansion  may  take  several  forms: 

I.  When  a  state  holds  out  diplomatic  and,  if  need  be,  military 
or  naval  protection  to  its  businessmen,  religious  missionaries,  and 
so  forth,  who  are  living  or  working  in  a  foreign  territory,  and  when 
the  foreign  political  unit  has  no  means  of  asserting  its  sovereignty 
over  these  foreigners,  we  characterize  the  foreign  territory  as  a 
"sphere  of  influence"  of  the  superior  power. 

II.  When  a  weaker  power  relies  upon  the  military  protection  of 
a  superior  power  against  third  powers,  and  accordingly  is  com- 
pelled or  willing  to  co-ordinate  its  foreign  policies  and  their  internal 
institutional  prerequisites  with  the  demands  of  the  superior  power, 
we  speak  of  a  "protectorate." 

III.  When  a  nation-state  extends  political  protection  to  the  trad- 
ing areas  of  its  businessmen  we  speak  of  "imperialism."  -^  The 
most  explicit  types  of  imperialism  involve  the  acquisition  of  a 
colonial  empire  by  purchase,  or  conquest,  or  both.  There  are  many 
reasons  for  such  expansion,  and  many  techniques  of  accomplishing 

2*  Samuel  Butler,  "Sermons,"  Works  (London,  1874),  II,  p.  154. 

-°  See  J.  A.  Hobson's  classic  work,  Imperialism  (London,  1902);  Nikolai 
Lenin,  Imperialism  (New  York:  International  Publications,  1939);  Rosa  Luxem- 
burg, The  Accumulation  of  Capital,  A.  Schwarzchild,  tr.  (New  Haven:  Yale 
Univ.  Press,  1951);  and  Fritz  Sternberg,  Capitalism  and  Socialism  on  Trial 
(New  York:  Day,  1952);  and  J.  A.  Schumpeter,  Imperialism  and  Social  Classes, 
H.  Narden,  tr.  (New  York:  Kelley,  1951). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  20^ 

it.  A  country  may  seek  colonies  in  order  to  settle  "surplus  popu- 
lations," that  is,  people  who  cannot  readily  be  absorbed  in  various 
institutional  orders.  It  may  seek  colonies  in  order  to  expand  its 
politically  guaranteed  market  area;  or  in  order  to  win  and  establish 
a  politically  guaranteed  monopoly  over  resources,  raw  materials, 
and  labor,  or  it  may  merely  wish  to  deny  access  to  such  resources 
to  other  powers.  Again,  and  this  is  more  modern,  one  power  may 
seek  to  expand  its  military  area  of  control  by  establishing  naval 
and  air  bases  abroad  without  assuming  overt  political  responsibili- 
ties in  the  face  of  foreign  political  bodies.  It  may  prefer  other 
nations  to  adjust  to  whatever  implications  ensue  from  its  establish- 
ment of  such  bases.  These  nations,  in  turn,  find  it  difficult  to 
acquire  those  "rights"  which  colonials  in  the  long  run  have  ac- 
quired, as  the  history  of  the  British  Empire— now  the  British  Com- 
monwealth of  Nations— shows. 

The  political  process  is  thus  a  struggle  for  power  and  prestige, 
for  authoritative  positions  within  each  nation-state  and  among 
various  nation-states.  Since  the  French  Revolution,  this  competi- 
tive system  of  sovereign  states  has  led  to  the  unification  of  Italy 
and  Germany;  and  since  World  War  I,  to  the  dissolution  of  the 
feudal  multinationality  state  of  the  Hapsburg  empire  into  small 
nation-states.  In  the  nineteenth  century,  the  several  major  states 
were  sufficiently  equal  to  block  the  possibility  of  one  of  them  vio- 
lently upsetting  the  entire  balance  of  power  competitors.  In  addi- 
tion, each  of  them  was  interested  in  maintaining  this  balance  of 
power;  they  seemed  "saturated,"  as  Bismarck  remarked  of  the 
Germany  he  unified.  The  "family  of  nations"  was  thus  more  or  less 
self-balancing,  and  the  balance  as  a  whole  was  guaranteed  by  the 
power  competition  between  the  British  and  the  Tsarist  empires. 

With  rapid,  although  uneven  industrialization,  urbanization, 
and  population  growth,  the  differences  between  the  various  Euro- 
pean nations  widened.  The  universal  revival  of  imperialist  tenden- 
cies after  the  1890's  eventuated  in  World  War  I,  which  America 
entered  at  the  side  of  Great  Britain  and  Russia.  But  after  that  war, 
the  United  States  abstained  from  the  League  of  Nations,  while  at 
the  same  time  actively  intervening  in  European  affairs  through 
the  Dawes  and  Young  plan,  thus  combining  active  economic  inter- 
vention with  minimal  political  responsibilities.  All  this,  along  with 
the  peacemakers'  work  at  Versailles  and  the  exclusion  of  the  Soviet 


206  OCIAL     Sxiio/CTURE 

Union  from  the  League  of  Nations  proved  abortive  and  short- 
sighted. The  period  between  the  two  World  Wars  has  aptly  been 
referred  to  as  The  Twenty  Years'  Crisis,  When  There  Was  No 
Peace.'-'^ 

3.  Democracies  and  Dictatorships 

Since  Aristotle,  states  have  been  classified  into  six  types:  Mon- 
archy and  tyranny,  the  good  and  evil  types  of  one-man  rule;  aris- 
tocracy and  oligarchy,  the  good  and  evil  types  of  the-rule-of-the- 
few;  and  polity  and  extreme  democracy,  the  good  and  evil  types 
of  the-rule-of-the-many.  In  order  to  classify  modern  states,  how- 
ever, we  must  take  into  account  the  nature  of  their  territory,  the 
terms  in  which  they  enlist  the  loyalties  of  the  organizations  and 
people  they  would  control,  the  type  of  political  organizations  man- 
aging the  integration  of  society  with  the  power  of  the  state,  and 
the  nature  and  composition  of  their  ruling  groups. 

When  we  examine  the  territorial  base,  we  are  able  to  distinguish 
between  the  great  river-states  of  the  ancient  Middle  and  Far  East, 
the  "coastal  states"  of  the  Mediterranean  polis— such  as  Athens, 
Phoenicia,  or  Carthage— the  states  of  the  plains  like  the  U.S.S.R.  or 
the  U.S.A.,  and  the  "oasis  state"  of  the  Middle  East.  When  we 
examine  the  loyalty  structure,  we  may  address  ourselves  to  politi- 
cal formulae  or  legitimations  such  as  "in  the  name  of  the  King," 
"the  divine  right  of  Kings,"  the  "sovereignty  of  the  people,"  or  "in 
the  name  of  the  law,"  or  the  alleged  charism  of  totalitarian  leader- 
ship states  under  Diice,  Fiihrer,  or  Caudillo.  When  we  examine 
the  integrative  political  organizations  we  may  speak  of  the  totali- 
tarian one-party  state,  or  of  a  multiparty  parliamentary  democ- 
racy. When  we  examine  the  nature  and  composition  of  ruling  groups 
we  may  find  a  capitalist  oligarchy  supreme,  as  in  France  before 
the  storm  of  1848;  or  a  semifeudal  group  of  agrarian  capitalists, 
militarists,  and  high  bureaucrats,  as  in  the  Junkerdom  under  the 
Kaiser;  or  a  nobility,  as  in  Russia  under  the  Tsar,  or  party  bureau- 
crats, as  after  Lenin. 

26  E.  H.  Carr,  The  Twenty  Years'  Crisis  (London:  Macmillan,  1949),  is  well 
worth  reading  as  a  retrospective  debunking  of  the  diplomatic  phraseology  of 
vain,  frightened,  short-sighted,  and  popularity-craving  statesmen.  H.  F.  Arm- 
strong, in  When  There  Is  No  Peace  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1939),  gives  an 
astute  account  of  the  war  preceding  the  latest  "shooting  war." 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  20"] 

The  most  diverse  "social  contents"  may  exist  under  the  same 
"political  form."  The  term  "democracy,"  especially  as  used  in  mod- 
ern propaganda  contests,  has  literally  come  to  mean  all  things  to 
all  men.  The  Soviet  use  of  "People's  Democracy"  is  characteristic 
—literally  it  means  "people's  people's  rule,"  which  would  seem  one 
too  many.  Dictatorships,  as  well  as  democracies,  are  ways  of  or- 
ganizing political  orders.  They  mean  quite  different  things  for  men 
in  different  social  structures  and  in  different  historical  eras.  And 
in  particular,  since  the  middle  of  the  nineteenth  century,  political 
choices  have  become  inextricably  involved  with  various  economic 
alternatives. 

The  civic  sources  of  modern  democracies  are  found,  first,  in  an- 
cient Athens,  where  for  the  qualified  citizens  there  was  direct 
democracy.  The  "town  meeting"  was  possible,  for  no  city  was  larger 
than  perhaps  50,000.  The  affairs  of  the  town  were  run  directly, 
foreign  ambassadors,  for  example,  reporting  directly  to  the  open 
assembly.  And  there  was  no  specialized  staff  of  professionals. 

The  second  source  of  democracy  was  the  indirect  democracy  of 
the  medieval  cities  or  guild  communes.  Decisions  were  made  by 
delegates  from  the  guilds,  in  a  manner  not  unlike  UN  delegates 
today.  These  delegates  had  no  real  leeway  and  the  organizations 
they  represented  were  very  unstable.  Some  guilds  were  much 
wealthier  and  stronger  than  others  and  accordingly  tried  to  become 
the  bases  of  hereditary  offices.  Then  minor  guilds  might  make  ur- 
ban revolutions,  and  as  in  ancient  city  tyrannies,  dictatorships  arise. 
The  history  of  the  Italian  city-states  dramatizes  these  develop- 
ments. 

The  medieval  form  of  indirect  democracy  evolved  finally  into 
modern  constitutional  democracy.  The  parliamentary  deputy,  how- 
ever, unlike  the  medieval  guildsman,  became  a  free  agent,  being 
restricted  only  by  his  fear  of  not  being  re-elected  and  by  the 
"pressures"  that  are  exerted  upon  his  decisions. 

And  as  the  rule  of  law  replaced  the  rule  of  men,  loyalties  were 
attached  to  the  authority  of  the  constitution  as  the  supreme  law 
of  the  land.  Wherever  kingship  survived  the  middle-class  revolu- 
tions of  the  seventeenth  and  eighteenth  centuries,  it  was  reduced 
to  "representation."  The  king  was  a  figurehead,  and  the  "kingdom 
of  prerogative"  was  reduced  to  a  "kingdom  of  influence." 


208  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

Regardless  of  constitutional  forms,  the  modern  state  in  an  indus- 
trial society  is  always  an  essentially  bureaucratic  state.  This  simply 
means  that  its  army,  its  executive  departments,  and  its  judiciary 
consist  of  centralized  offices  that  are  arranged  in  a  hierarchy,  each 
level  having  specified  jurisdictions.  To  understand  such  states  we 
must  understand  how  other  political  bureaucracies,  the  party  ma- 
chines for  example,  are  integrated  with  the  officials  at  the  heads 
of  the  state's  various  civil  and  military  hierarchies.  We  must  exam- 
ine the  party  structure  and  its  linkages  to  pressure  groups  and  the 
major  strata  of  the  social  structure,  and  that  we  pay  particular 
attention  to  the  integration  within  the  political  order  of  parties 
with  state  machine. 

I.  Arthur  Rosenberg  has  taught  us  to  understand  liberal  democ- 
racy as  that  phase  of  Western  parliamentary  government  during 
which  the  propertied  and  the  educated  shared  political  decisions, 
the  franchise  being  restricted  by  census  qualifications  and  effec- 
tively denied  to  the  mass  of  workers  as  well  as  to  women. 

II.  Imperialist  democracy  refers  to  parliamentary  governments 
which  rule  an  empire  consisting  of  such  diverse  units  as  dominions, 
colonies,  dependencies  and  protectorates,  radiating  finally  into 
spheres  of  influence.  "Colonial  democracy"  refers  to  a  territory 
under  a  parliamentary  government  which  is  in  fact  dependent  upon 
the  decisions  of  a  great  power.  Such  democracies  are  often  debtor 
states  dependent  upon  the  good  will  of  the  creditor  country. 

III.  Totalitarian  democracy  refers  to  the  absence  of  a  division 
between  private  and  public  life.  Ancient  Athens  and  the  city-states 
of  the  Italian  Renaissance  exemplify  this  absence  of  division,  as  do 
the  heroic  episodes  of  democracies  establishing  themselves  in  war- 
fare, during  which  there  is  no  private  retreat  for  the  citizen.  Non- 
totalitarianism  means  that  the  political  order  permits  its  members 
to  keep  part  of  their  lives  private,  and  to  practice  politics  only 
intermittently.  A  minority  of  the  United  States  electorate  elect 
the  president,  although  his  legitimation  is  in  terms  of  "majority 
rule."  For  many  people  voting  thus  would  seem  to  make  little  differ- 
ence in  many  decisions  of  national  consequence.-^  Insofar  as  de- 
mocracy exists  in  such  a  situation,  it  is  expressed  mainly  by  com- 

27  See  W.  E.  Binkley,  The  Powers  of  the  President  (Garden  City,  N.  Y.: 
Doubleday,  1937)  and  Harold  Laski,  The  American  Presidency,  An  Interpre- 
tation (New  York:  Harper,  1940). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  20g 

peting  pressure  groups  and  parties.  As  a  type,  totalitarian  democ- 
racy enables  us  to  take  into  account  the  fact  that  in  constitutionally 
democratic  states  there  has  been  a  tendency,  implemented  by  the 
emergencies  of  war  and  peace,  for  controls  to  become  increasingly 
total.-'*  The  United  States  has  been  spared  many  controls,  even 
during  World  War  II,  for  there  was  no  mass  evacuation  of  children, 
no  total  civilian  defense,  and  no  intensive  control  of  the  kitchen. 
IV.  Socialist  democracy  refers  to  a  parliamentary  regime  with 
a  democratic-minded  labor  party  at  the  helm,  engaged  in  socializ- 
ing strategic  industries  and  extending  welfare  services  and  housing 
facilities  to  lower  classes.  Pursuing  a  policy  of  "full  employment," 
socialists  would  displace  capitalism's  "anarchy  of  production"  by  a 
policy  of  public  planning.  Such  a  regime  would  contain  a  strong 
judiciary  with  legal  guarantees,  as  well  as  parties  which  compete 
but  which  are  not  strong  enough  to  overrule  juridical  decisions. 
Democratically  accountable  planners  and  managerial  boards  would, 
according  to  this  view  of  democracy,  debate  what  products  should 
be  made:  there  would  be  production  planning  on  the  basis  of 
consumer  demands,  explicitly  linked  with  mass  organizations.  How 
many  television  sets  or  houses  should  be  made  would  thus  be  a 
public  decision,  and  consumption  and  production  of  the  nation 
would  be  considered  as  in  one  big  household.  Under  such  a  social- 
ized and  planned  economy— which  would  involve  the  confiscation 
of  private  property— co-ops  would  own  some  industries,  and  vari- 
ous public  authorities— local,  regional  and  national— would  own 
others.  These  bodies  would  appoint  managers,  and  hold  them 
accountable.  Inheritance  would  have  nothing  to  do  with  who  was 
in  charge.  Co-ops  and  trade  unions  would  have  voices  in  the 
places  of  decision,  and  at  least  a  veto  right  over  managers.  Unions 
would  also  propose,  as  well  as  veto,  managerial  decisions.  Democ- 
racy would  thus  involve  both  the  political  and  the  economic  order. 

In  distinguishing  various  types  of  despotism,  it  seems  conveni- 
ent to  classify  them,  first,  as  Oriental  or  Western.  The  Oriental 
variety  superseded  feudalism  by  establishing  a  bureaucracy— of 
Confucian  gentlemen,  as  in  China;  or  of  priestly  scribes,  as  in 
ancient  Egypt  and  Mesopotamia.  These  bureaucracies  controlled, 

-8  See  Franz  Neumann,  Behemoth;  The  Structure  and  Practice  of  National 
Socialism  (New  York:  Oxford,  1942);  and  Arthur  Rosenberg,  The  Birth  of 
the  German  Republic,  I.  F.   D.  Morrow,  tr.   (London:   Oxford,   1931). 


210  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

among  other  means  of  life,  the  rivers,  with  which  they  managed 
irrigation  systems.  Two  types  should  be  mentioned: 

I.  The  Caesarism  of  Rome's  empire  was  based  upon  an  imperial 
bureaucracy  of  army  officers  and  tax  farmers.  The  Diocletian  Em- 
pire is  the  clearest  example  of  an  imperial  bureacracy  led  by 
hereditary  dynasties  and  punctuated  by  military  usurpers.  It  was 
a  theocracy  with  Caesar  as  god.  The  military  order  was  impor- 
tant, as  a  chronic  state  of  war  was  necessary  to  provide  slaves  for 
the  economy.  Public  financing  was  shifted  from  taxes  to  services 
in  kind.  A  money  economy  broke  down  as  the  area  of  domination 
spread,  so  the  center  of  gravity  shifted  inland.  The  rich,  who  pro- 
vided the  liturgies,  fled  from  the  cities  and,  going  to  country  es- 
tates, rusticated. 

II.  Sultanism  operates  with  a  harem:  the  despot,  by  prudent 
choice  of  women,  attached  various  sibs  to  his  own  ruling  house- 
hold. Within  the  harem,  however,  sib  rivalry  may  be  implemented, 
as  ambitious  women  join  an  opposition.  The  harem  thus  added 
an  additional  element  of  unmanageability.  The  Chinese  dynasties, 
for  example,  went  through  cycles  which  regularly  ended  in  the 
un-Confucian  rule  of  empress-dowagers  and  eunuchs,  the  so-called 
"petticoat  government."  At  any  rate,  in  the  typical  cycle,  the  de- 
cision-making center  resolves  into  factions,  and  then  a  charismatic 
peasant  builds  up  an  army  and  goes  against  the  court.  In  his  rise 
to  power,  he  gets  training  for  the  despotic  role  that  .he  will  later 
play. 

In  Western  civilization,  the  following  historical  types  of  des- 
potism have  widely  prevailed: 

III.  The  feudal  monarchy  of  the  European  Middle  Ages,  with  its 
permanent  tensions  between  Pope  and  Emperor,  was  a  loose  set  of 
principalities,  castled  and  self-equipped  warriors,  of  fortified  semi- 
autonomous  city  republics,  and  corporate  church  and  monastic 
bodies.  The  emperor  had  no  adequate  administrative  and  techno- 
logical means  of  enforcing  sovereign  rights  from  on  high,  and  ac- 
cordingly had  to  bargain  with  variously  privileged  estates,  which 
however  were  held  together  by  a  common  faith  in  Christianity. 

IV.  The  absolutist  regimes  of  European  kings  and  petty  princes, 
from  the  sixteenth  to  the  eighteenth  centuries,  introduced  bureau- 
cratic administrations  which  co-ordinated  military  and  fiscal  poli- 
cies. Within  this  framework,  territories  have  contested  for  prestige 
and  power  through  warfare  and  dynastic  marriages.  As  the  mer- 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  211 

cenary  army  displaced  the  self-equipped  feudal  knighthood, 
princely  absolutism,  based  upon  the  "Divine  Right  of  Kings," 
undermined  the  various  feudal  estates  having  varying  degrees  of 
political  and  legal  power.  This  absolutism  centralized  the  scat- 
tered prerogatives  of  feudal  Europe,  reduced  the  nobility  to  office 
nobles  and  army  officers;  with  cannon  fire,  it  broke  up  their  strong- 
holds and  castles.  It  reduced  the  status  of  quasi-autonomous  cities, 
and  leveled  men  into  subjects  inhabiting  the  territory  which  it  had 
pacified.  With  the  exception  of  the  priesthood  and  the  privileged 
nobles,  the  subjects  of  princely  absolutism  were  held  to  regular 
taxes,  which  in  the  ancien  regime  of  France,  for  example,  were 
collected  by  30,000  privileged  entrepreneurs,  or,  as  in  Prussia,  by  a 
tax-collecting  machine  of  military  bureaucrats. 

Princely  absolutism  was  a  type  of  police  state  which  sought  to 
establish  totalitarian  control.  It  sought  to  increase  its  population 
by  having  ministers  exhort  the  people  to  "be  fruitful  and  multiply," 
and  by  attracting  privileged  immigrant  groups.  It  sought  to  steer 
the  economy  by  investing  tax-income  in  schemes  for  technological 
and  industrial  improvement.  It  sought  to  hoard  precious  metals 
as  a  war  chest,  and  to  promote  agricultural  settlement  schemes  for 
the  sake  of  increasing  the  tax  yield.  It  sought  also  to  inculcate 
loyalties  to  the  state  and  to  its  prince.  Thus  Colbert  had  his  stand- 
ing army  of  mercenary  soldiers  dig  canals  during  peacetime— an 
early  modern  case  of  public  works  performed  by  "forced  labor." 

Yet  with  all  this,  given  the  level  of  preindustrial  technology  and 
communications,  princely  absolutism  was  overthrown  or  reduced 
by  the  industrial  middle  classes,  who  strove  for  democracy  and 
constitutional  government,  for  a  secure  and  calculable  legal  order 
guaranteeing  "due  process  of  law,"  and  thus  for  the  opportunity  to 
orient  themselves  in  a  predictable  way  to  competitive  markets, 
and  other  matters  of  income  and  property. 

V.  The  middle-class  revolutions  of  England  and  France  brought 
forth  Bonapartism—a.  Cromwell  and  a  Napoleon— to  stabilize  their 
revolutionary  attainments.  Kemal  Atatiirk,  regarded  as  the  creator 
of  modern  Turkey,  might  be  compared  with  Napoleon.  The  mili- 
tary juntas  of  Spanish-American  countries,  or  Pilsudski's  regime 
of  colonels  in  Poland  between  the  wars,  are  different  forms  of  dic- 
tatorship in  largely  agrarian  and  debtor  countries.  "Bonapartism" 
means  a  one-man  rule  on  the  basis  of  acclamation.  Yet  we  should 
remember  that  these  despotisms  are  not  totalitarianism:  they  are 


212  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

not  based  on  one  single  mass  party,  they  do  not  manage  the  com- 
plexities of  a  corporate  capitalist  economy  in  terms  of  a  planned 
economy  set  up  for  a  chronic  state  of  war. 

VI.  None  of  the  pre-twentieth-century  types  of  despotism  has,  in 
fact,  much  in  common  with  the  totalitarian  dictatorship  of  the 
Soviet  Union,  or  the  Fascist  regimes  of  Italy  and  Spain,  or  the 
Nazi  dictatorship.  These  modern  despots  mobilize  industrialized 
countries  for  imperialist  wars  in  an  attempt  to  redivide  the  world. 
Modern  dictators  are  revolutionary  usurpers,  usually  going  against 
a  center  which  is  faction-ridden.  Their  usurpation  is  usually  pre- 
ceded by  a  condition  in  which  there  is  a  plurality  of  pressure 
groups  and  parties,  and  no  chance  to  establish  a  stable  govern- 
ment. The  individual  experiences  fully  his  inability  to  meet  the 
public  crises  which  intensify  his  anxieties.  He  longs  for  a  center 
of  management.  Nobody  seems  to  do  anything,  although  everybody 
is  busy.  Both  the  right  and  the  left  may  unite  against  the  middle, 
but  they  cannot  form  a  stable  government.  So,  the  dictator— the 
conspicuous  man  thrown  up  by  crisis  and  eager  to  assume  emer- 
gency powers  and  responsibility  for  all  public  affairs— arises  on  the 
basis  of  a  party  and  establishes  a  one-party  state. 

The  social  content,  the  ruling  elites,  the  justifying  symbols  and 
ideologies— these  vary  with  the  social  setting  and  the  political  aims 
at  hand.  For  example,  where  Hitler's  regime  sought  to  strengthen 
the  individual  peasant  farm  as  well  as  Junker  landlordism  by 
organizing  agrarian  society  into  a  compulsory  cartel  for  purposes 
of  autarchy,  the  Bolshevists,  after  some  detours,  abolished  indi- 
vidual holdings  and  organized  agriculture  in  a  network  of  tractor 
stations  and  state  farms.  They  thus  reduced  the  peasantry  to  wage 
workers  and  so  guaranteed  greater  efficiency  of  production  and 
a  higher  tax  income  from  the  land  than  would  have  been  available 
under  private  property. 

Totalitarian  states  go  beyond  the  bureaucratization  of  demo- 
cratic states  by  subjecting  all  organized  channels  of  communica- 
tion, including  concert  hall  and  exhibition  of  art  work,  as  well  as 
radio,  print,  and  film  to  their  control.  This  requires  that  various 
skill  groups— journalists,  cameramen,  film  directors,  artists,  radio 
men— be  organized  into  quasi-bureaucracies,  that  is,  transformed 
into  "officials"  who  have  all  the  responsibilities  of  regular  state 
officials  but  not  their  decision-making  functions,  their  rights  of 
tenure,  their  pensions,  or  their  anonymity.  Such  skill  groups  must 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  213 

then  define  and  promulgate  official  images  of  the  world  and  what 
is  happening  in  it,  official  "definitions  of  the  situation." 

Public  opinion,  as  Hans  Speier  puts  it,-'*  involves  the  right  of  the 
citizenry  publicly  to  engage  in  critical  communications  to  and 
about  the  government  and  its  policy  decisions.  Such  public  opinion 
does  not  exist  in  totalitarian  societies.  There  is  only  the  precarious 
role  of  the  small-audience  satirist,  who,  like  the  old  court  jester 
or  official  fool,  may  speak  the  truth— within  limits  and  so  long  as 
no  one  takes  him  seriously. 

4.  Economic  Institutions  ^° 

Economic  orders  are  composed  of  institutions  by  which  men 
organize  labor  for  the  peaceful  production  and  distribution  of 
goods  and  services.  The  dominant  economic  organizations  as  well 
as  their  integration  vary  according  to  the  particular  economic  ends 
sought,  of  which  there  are  generally  two  types:  one  may  produce 
for  one's  own  household  and  thus  belong  to  a  "subsistence  econ- 
omy"; or  one  may  produce  for  profits  to  be  gained  through  indirect 
exchange  in  a  "money  economy."  Accordingly,  we  speak  of  the 
"subsistence  farmer,"  such  as  the  old-time  European  peasant,  and 
of  the  "cash  crop  farmer,"  such  as,  predominantly,  the  American 
farm  operator.  Modern  industrial  economies  may  also  be  classified 
as  composed  of  competing  "private  enterprises";  of  "mixed"  enter- 
prises, in  which  public  authorities  and  private  enterprisers  join 
forces;  or  of  "public  enterprises." 

Georg  Simmel  identified  "rationality"  with  money  exchange  be- 
cause money  is  a  common  denominator  of  qualitatively  different 

29  Paraphrased  from  Hans  Speier,  Social  Order  and  the  Risks  of  War  ( New 
York:   Stewart,  1952),  p.  323. 

30  The  reader  will  find  the  following  to  be  important:  Max  Weber,  General 
Economic  History,  Frank  Knight,  tr.  (Glencoe,  Illinois:  Free  Press,  1950); 
Karl  Marx,  Selected  Wor/cs  in  2  Vols.  ( Prepared  at  the  Marx  Institute,  Moscow, 
by  V.  Adoratsky,  edited  in  EngUsh  by  C.  P.  Dutt,  New  York);  Thorstein 
Veblen,  Tlie  Theory  of  Business  Enterprise  (New  York,  1935);  Georg  Simmel, 
The  Sociology  of  Georg  Simmel,  K.  Wolff,  ed.  and  tr.  (Glencoe,  Illinois: 
Free  Press,  1950);  Werner  Sombart,  "Capitalism,"  Encyclopaedia  of  the 
Social  Sciences,  Vol.  Ill,  pp.  195-208,  and  The  Quintessence  of  Capitalism 
(London,  1915);  J.  A.  Hobson,  The  Evolution  of  Modern  Capitalism  (London, 
1926);  and  J.  A.  Schumpeter,  Capitalism,  Socialism,  and  Democracy  (New 
York:   Harper,  1950). 


214  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

goods.  Money  allows  for  the  quantification  of  all  qualities,  and  this 
quantification,  in  turn,  allows  the  analytic  breaking  down  of  quali- 
ties into  equal  units,  as  well  as  for  the  translatability  of  one  qual- 
ity into  another— and  hence  for  calculation.  For  Simmel,  capitalism 
is  therefore  seen  as  a  diffusion  of  the  exchange  medium,  money, 
and  the  concomitant  mental  attitudes  of  ( i )  rational  calculation, 
and  (2)  the  objectification  of  personal  properties  and  belongings. 

In  prepecuniary  eras,  all  goods  and  artifacts  were  identified  with 
their  owner;  they  extended  the  range  of  his  personality,  they  em- 
bodied his  personality  traits.  But  in  pecuniary  eras  this  intimate 
psychic  linkage  of  persons  with  the  goods  they  own  is  broken,  and 
goods  become  objects  circulating  or  ready  to  circulate  among  dif- 
ferent persons.  Hence  economic  goods  become  abstracted  from 
the  personal  work  invested  in  them.  Simmel  thus  defines  capitalism 
in  terms  of  the  money  economy. 

Werner  Sombart,  in  contrast,  emphasizes  the  rational  calcula- 
tion of  profits,  costs,  and  income  as  the  constitutive  element  of 
modern  capitalism.  Hence,  for  Sombart  the  emergence  of  modem 
capitalism  dates  from  the  invention  of  double  entry  bookkeeping 
by  an  Italian  monk  in  the  Italian  city  economy  of  early  Renaissance 
days. 

For  both  Simmel  and  Sombart  the  sphere  of  distribution— the 
market— is  the  decisive  anchorage  of  capitalism.  The  ramifications 
of  technological  changes  implementing  novel  modes  of  production 
are  not  of  primary  significance  to  them.  Capitalism  is  the  use  of 
the  pecuniary  principle  in  different  fields  of  economic  pursuits; 
this  principle  gradually  engulfs  the  economic  orders  of  whole  na- 
tions and  cultural  areas,  and  in  due  course  perhaps,  permeates  the 
entire  world. 

For  Karl  Marx  and  Max  Weber,  in  contrast  to  both  Simmel  and 
Sombart,  "modern  capitalism"  is  anchored  in  the  sphere  of  pro- 
duction. Accordingly,  the  historical  emergence  of  modern  capi- 
talism is  not  seen  as  a  quantitative  expansion  of  markets,  but  as 
the  emergence  of  the  factory  as  the  productive  unit  or,  in  Weber's 
terms,  of  a  rational  organization  of  formally  free  labor  for  the  con- 
tinuous acquisition  of  profits.  Because  of  his  emphasis  upon  pro- 
duction, Marx  focused  upon  the  labor  supply  and  the  exploitabil- 
ity  of  the  "reserve  army  of  labor."  Weber  was  more  interested  in  the 
origin  and  psychology  of  a  stratum  of  middle-class  entrepreneurs. 

Marx  believed  that  fraud  and  violence  implemented  the  initial 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  215 

phase  of  the  primary  accumulation  required  for  capitalism.  Yeomen, 
small  propertied  groups,  and  artisans  were  brutally  dislocated 
from  their  traditional  pursuits. 

Weber  also  placed  great  emphasis  upon  noneconomic  factors,  but 
his  central  problem  became  a  psychological  one:  how  is  it  pos- 
sible that  strata  of  enterprisers  and  workers  emerge  that  are  will- 
ing to  engage  in  methodically  persistent,  hard  work  and  thereby 
gain  a  competitive  advantage  over  less  principled,  more  tradition- 
alist economic  agents?  These  men  forego  the  traditional  enjoyments 
of  wealth— the  expansion  of  their  consumption,  or  the  investment 
of  wealth  in  ostentatious  ways.  How  is  it,  then,  that  men  arise  who 
work  hard,  despite  the  fact  that  in  the  value  terms  of  their  eco- 
nomic tradition  and  epoch  they  have  no  understandable  motives 
for  doing  so?  Weber's  answer  lies  in  his  reconstruction  of  the 
religiously  motivated  asceticism,  the  inner-worldly  or  this-worldly 
asceticism,  of  the  heroic  puritan.^^ 

In  his  causal  analysis,  Weber  thus  specializes  in  the  problem  of 
modern  capitalism.  For  him  industrial  capitalism  is  not  sufficiently 
defined  by  profit-making,  because  profits  are  made  by  Chinese 
traders  as  well  as  by  Armenian  middlemen.  Nor  is  capitalism  a 
matter  of  acquisitive  instincts,  which  are  revealed  by  all  sorts  and 
conditions  of  men  in  contexts  which  lack  the  specific  character  of 
capitalism— modern  industry.  In  contrast  to  Sombart,  Weber  was 
not  interested  in  how  profits  are  counted,  but  in  the  fact  that  they 
are  made. 

For  both  Marx  and  for  Weber,  modern  capitalism,  therefore, 
does  not  exist  in  the  Italian  Renaissance  cities,  or  in  the  Roman 
empire,  or  the  Tokugawa  epoch  of  Japan.  In  its  modern  sense, 
capitalism  is  a  specifically  Occidental  or  Western  economic  order, 
beginning  primarily  in  England  during  the  sixteenth  and  seven- 
teenth centuries. 

5.  Types  of  Capitalism 

It  is  within  the  realm  of  comparative  economics,  however,  that 
Weber  developed  his  "types  of  capitalism"  which  in  reality  consti- 
tute a  panorama  of  economies  existing  prior  to  distinctively  mod- 

31  See  Chapter  IX:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  II,  Section  i: 
Religious  Institutions. 


2l6  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

ern  capitalism.  These  types  include  pariah,  political,  booty,  and 
colonial  capitalism. ^- 

I.  Pariah  capitalism  is  the  capitalism  of  despised  marginal 
traders  who  are  originally  strangers  among  host  nations  which 
allow  them  to  fulfill  economically  welcome  but  morally  impugned 
functions.  Weber  called  such  despised  trading  groups  "pariahs" 
when  they  were  socially  ostracized:  excluded  from  intermarriage 
and  dinner  table  fellowship  with  members  of  the  politically  domi- 
nant group.  And  he  used  the  term  "pariah  capitalism"  in  order  to 
emphasize  the  marginal  position  which  they  typically  occupy. 
Christian  traders  in  the  midst  of  Mohammedan  Turks,  Chinese 
merchants  in  Southeast  Asia,  the  Parsee  traders  of  India,  and  the 
Greek  middlemen  in  Africa  are  cases  in  point,  as  well  as,  of  course, 
occidental  Jewry  in  the  Middle  Ages.  Such  pariah  capitalists  are 
often  commercial  capitalists,  accumulating  profits  by  the  control  of 
major  trade  routes  for  luxury  commodities,  such  as  spices,  precious 
metals,  and  silks. 

II.  Under  certain  conditions  even  pariah  capitalists  may  be  wel- 
come servants  of  political  or  ecclesiastical  rulers.  As  market  experts, 
they  know  how  to  raise  credits  for  political  and  military  enterprises. 
When  any  capitalist,  pariah  or  not,  undertakes  services  of  this  kind, 
we  may  speak  of  political  capitalism. 

Political  capitalism  tends  to  flower  in  states  of  chronic  warfare 
or  revolution.  Many  of  the  Jews,  as  well  as  Gentiles,  of  the  Euro- 
pean Middle  Ages  were  protected  by  courts  and  participated  in 
such  capitalism.  Thus  the  famous  brothers  Rothschild  established 
themselves  in  Frankfort  on  the  Main,  as  well  as  London,  Paris,  and 
Vienna,  They  helped  finance  the  Napoleonic  wars,  on  all  sides  of 
the  battle  lines,  thus  minimizing  possible  losses  of  the  family  as  a 
financial  community. 

Political  capitalism  has  assumed  a  number  of  different  forms. 
Political  rulers  for  example,  in  a  fiscal  capitalism,  have  often 
"farmed  out"  tax  collection  to  private  entrepreneurs.  Such  entre- 
preneurial gatherers  of  taxes  existed  in  the  late  Roman  empire,  in 
which  they  enriched  themselves  by  exploiting  the  provinces  eco- 
nomically and  using  their  private  fortunes  as  stepping  stones  in 
political  careers  in  Rome.  Thus  did  Caesar  squeeze  Gaul.  A  similar 
stratum  of  "tax  farmers"  became  significantly  unpopular  in  pre- 
revolutionary  France  under  the  absolutism  of  the  ancien  regime. 

22  Cf.  General  Economic  Theory,  op.  dt.,  and  Max  Weber,  op.  cit. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  SI/ 

Rulers  have  frequently  farmed  out  the  royal  mint  itself  to  private 
enterprisers.  The  house  of  Mitsui,  for  example,  floated  the  first 
government  currency  after  the  reformation  in  Japan.  The  house 
of  Fuggers  enjoyed  minting  rights  as  well  as  mining  privileges. 
Such  opportunities  as  tax  gathering  and  money-issuing  are  direct 
state  functions,  which  is  why  Weber  called  this  type  of  capitalism 
fiscal  capitalism— the  term  fiscal  referring  to  the  state  as  an  eco- 
nomic agent. 

Another  kind  of  political  capitalism  involves  the  organization  of 
armed  forces  by  private  entrepreneurs.  The  condottiere  emerges 
when  disciplined  units  of  mercenary  footmen  prove  superior  to  the 
individualistic,  undisciplined  feudal  knight-in-armor.  The  Italian 
condottieri  (Sforza),  as  well  as  the  north  Alpine  organizer  of  mer- 
cenary troops  (Frundsberg  and  Wallenstein),  are  best  known. 
The  later  standing  armies  of  absolutist  European  rulers  were  fi- 
nanced by  a  slowly  emerging  technique  of  regular  tax  collection, 
by  political  loans  and  subsidies  from  the  outside  (e.g.,  British 
subsidies  to  Frederick  II  of  Prussia  during  the  Seven  Years  War). 

In  contrast  to  the  devaluation  of  pariah  capitalists,  fiscal  capital- 
ists have  enjoyed  great  esteem,  which,  in  part,  has  been  due  to 
their  participation  in  royal  functions  and  hence  their  borrowing  of 
status.  Jacob  Fugger  of  Augsburg,  who  financed  the  election  of  an 
emperor  was,  and  felt  like,  a  kingmaker. 

III.  During  the  modern  expansion  of  markets,  overseas  traders 
typically  met  tribal  or  other  political  communities  which  denied 
them  access  to  harbor  and  trading  opportunities.  In  such  situations, 
the  trader,  in  the  absence  of  maritime  and  international  law,  used 
to  go  well  armed,  and  if  necessary  open  the  door  to  trade  at  the 
point  of  a  gun.  Where  persuasion  to  trade  is  implemented  by  the 
actual  use  or  the  threat  of  violence,  one  may  speak  of  booty  capi- 
talism. The  term  is  appropriate:  under  conditions  of  forced  trans- 
actions one  can  hardly  speak  of  an  exchange  of  commodities  by 
peaceful  bargaining.  The  exchange  is,  in  fact,  a  polite  fa9ade  for 
direct  appropriation  by  violence.  Slaves  have  been  one  of  the  most 
favored  commodities  appropriated  in  this  fashion. 

IV.  It  has  been  an  old  tradition  of  occidental  merchants  to  estab- 
lish trading  posts  and  stable  places  abroad.  Thus,  the  Hanseatic 
League  maintained  trading  posts  on  the  Volga  as  well  as  on  the 
Thames.  Trading  companies  have  engaged  in  overseas  trade,  and 
in  due  course  acquired  favorable  sites,  called  "factories."  Thus  the 


2l8  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

British  East  India  Company  established  its  factories  in  India.  From 
such  a  "trading"  post,  resident  stewards  expanded  their  operations, 
and  in  due  course,  acquired  considerable  territorial  domains.  In- 
creased holdings  brought  in  their  train  increased  tensions  and 
dangers,  pohtical,  military  and  economic.  Accordingly,  a  military 
estabhshment  had  to  secure  the  colony.  Westerners  residing  in  the 
trading  posts  and  becoming  acquainted  with  the  problems  of  the 
surrounding  territories  naturally  discovered  occasions  and  oppor- 
tunities for  further  expansion  by  entering  the  politics  of  the  par- 
ticular region  and  exploiting  them  for  their  own  advantage.  In 
short,  booty  capitalist  adventures  have  led  to  colonial  capitalism. 
Colonial  capitalism  has  typically  established  "the  plantation 
system,"  which  thrives  on  an  intensive  cultivation  of  tropical  and 
garden  produce  such  as  tea,  cotton,  tobacco,  sugar,  and  in  the  age 
of  the  automobile,  rubber.  It  is  a  further  characteristic  of  the 
plantation  that  it  utilizes  slave  or  forced  labor.  The  most  significant 
areas  of  such  plantation  systems  have  been  in  the  North  African 
grain  belt,  in  the  Portuguese,  French,  Dutch,  and  British  domains 
in  India,  and  in  the  Southern  states  before  the  Civil  War. 

Modern  capitalist  entrepreneurs  have  struggled  against  all  the 
odds  of  jurisdictional  handicaps,  the  closure  policies  of  guilds  and 
politically  privileged  monopolists,  and  the  mercantilist  police  state. 
Their  slogan,  "laissez-faire,"  was  directed  against  the  feudal  ves- 
tiges of  guild  policies,  as  well  as  against  politically  privileged 
monopolists.  The  autonomy  of  the  pacified  market  appeared  to 
them  as  the  ideal  field  of  operations,  and  the  establishment  of  such 
a  market  as  a  fulfillment  of  freedom.  The  free  market  was  thus  the 
economic  precondition  and  result  of  the  free  enterprise;  this 
market  became  world  wide  and  based  in  gold,  and  free  migra- 
tion of  people  knit  together  the  system  as  a  whole. 

Nineteenth-century  capitalism  approximated  the  goal  of  an  eco- 
nomic order  knit  together  by  markets.  To  be  sure,  vestiges  of 
previous  economic  orders  existed,  especially  in  the  rural  economies 
of  continental  Europe,  and  a  good  many  artisan  establishments 
survived.  But  the  dynamics  of  the  economic  order  did  not  rest  upon 
these  vestiges;  it  was  controlled  by  market-oriented  free  entre- 
preneurs. These  agents  enrolled  a  labor  force  in  their  expanding 
capitalist  enterprises,  which  gradually  came  to  permeate  all 
branches  of  production  and  distribution.  The  right  of  the  owner 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  2ig 

freely  to  dispose  of  exchangeable  goods  came  to  include  such 
previously  immobile  items  as  land,  and  the  initiative  ol  the  enter- 
priser fed  upon  continuously  expanding  business  opportunities. 

Legally  guaranteed  monopolies  in  trade,  handicraft,  and  industry 
were  broken  down.  Legislation  which  confined  itself  to  the  formal 
rules  of  the  game  replaced  municipal  statutes  and  guild  rules  that 
restricted  those  who  could  play  the  game.  Free  mobility  became 
a  recognized  right  of  the  citizen.  Everyone  could  leave  his  place 
of  birth  and  move  where  he  pleased;  emigration  and  immigration 
were  legally  facilitated  through  the  free  handing  out  of  passports 
and  the  relatively  free  admission  of  newcomers  to  all  localities.  All 
national  currencies  had  fairly  stable  relations  to  gold,  and  interna- 
tional trade  in  capital  and  commodities  flourished. 

States  minimized  direct  political  intervention  in  the  economic 
order.  For  the  implied  assumption  that  ran  through  the  laissez-faire 
system  was  that  the  automatic  steering  of  the  whole  process  of 
expansion  would  work  out  in  the  interest  of  all  economic  agents. 
A  harmony  of  interests  between  the  individual  profiting  in  the 
process  of  expansion  and  the  public  weal  was  taken  for  granted 
by  the  advocates  of  the  system.  At  the  dawn  of  the  system,  it  was 
possible  for  theoreticians  like  Adam  Smith— the  fountainhead  of 
the  theory  of  economic  liberalism— to  think  in  terms  of  further  in- 
creasing the  relatively  equal  distribution  of  private  property.  This 
was  the  central  meaning  of  equality  of  opportimity:  that  every  man 
of  initiative  and  talent  could  enter  the  competitive  race  on  equal 
terms  with  his  competitors.  Since  at  the  start  of  the  race,  men  were 
assumed  to  be  more  or  less  equally  endowed,  the  different  degrees 
of  their  success  could  be  ascribed  to  their  personal  merit,  and 
initiative.  ' 

Such  business  depressions  as  occurred  were  declared  to  be  tem- 
porary aberrations  of  particular  branches  of  industries;  such  de- 
pressions in  due  course  would  be  compensated  for  by  a  propor- 
tionate expansion  of  more  profitable  fields.  Public  opinion  was 
optimistic  to  the  point  of  enthusiasm,  and  the  turbulent  social  un- 
rest of  the  Chartist  and  similar  movements  was  soon  forgotten. 
Critics  like  Ruskin,  Marx,  and  Saint-Simon  remained  outside  the 
main  drift.  The  severe  human  and  social  costs  of  this  capitalism 
were  overlooked  in  the  scramble  to  get  rich  quick.  In  such  virgin 
economic  areas  as  the  U.S.A.,  the  unrestricted  right  of  the  private 
property   owner   often   allowed   for   short-sighted   exploitation    of 


220  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

natural  resources,  profitable  to  the  individual  but  costly  to  the 
nation  at  large  and  to  later  generations. 

Under  modern  capitalism,  private  enterprises  are  (i)  passed  on 
as  property  to  heirs  and  heiresses  and  (2)  yield  to  these  owners 
"unearned  income"  beyond  the  entrepreneurial  salaries  paid  to 
managers  and  company  directors,  the  interest  due  to  investors  and 
creditors,  and  the  funds  set  aside  for  replacement  and  renewal  of 
plant.  Such  properties  are  not  the  work-properties  which  Adam 
Smith  had  in  mind  when  he  thought  of  "private  enterprise."  The 
theorems  of  classical  economics  in  fact  have  now  become  "ideolo- 
gies" by  means  of  which  politically  interested  spokesmen  apply  the 
small-shop  thinking  of  laissez-faire  days  to  the  giant  enterprises  of 
absentee  owners  in  an  age  of  monopoly  capitalism. 

The  policies  of  the  leading  United  States  corporations  today 
determine  the  economic  fate  of  most  other  economic  units  in  the 
United  States,  of  many  little  businesses  and  family  farmers,  who 
are  all  dependent  upon  the  price  policies  of  the  corporations  that 
produce  oil,  farm  machinery,  electrical  current,  and  artificial  fer- 
tilizer.^-^ The  employment  opportunities  of  employees— of  wage 
workers  and  of  the  white  collar  people  also— depend  upon  the 
strategic  decisions  of  corporate  managements.  The  structure  of 
these  corporations  is  bureaucratic,  and  the  bureaucracy  of  an  oil 
or  a  steel  trust  may  be  more  powerful  than  that  of  many  political 
states.  Their  decisions  concerning  investment  and  price  policies 
pertain  to  far-flung  production  establishments,  located  in  many 
countries  and  so  having  international  ramifications. 

Under  such  conditions,  the  meaning  of  "private"  as  applied  to 
the  leading  American  corporations  means  merely  that  their  policy- 
makers are  not  publicly  accountable  for  their  decisions— so  long 
as  they  "stay  within  the  law,"  which  is  often  loosely  defined  and 
perhaps  necessarily  vague  about  the  latest  business  practices. 

In  the  big  business  establishment,  all  items  of  production,  raw 
materials,  labor,  interest  charges,  and  so  on,  are  carefully  calculated 
as  "costs"  and  all  income  for  goods  sold  is  balanced  against  costs. 
The  goal  of  production  is  to  maximize  the  total  assets,  which  means 

^3  For  a  good  introduction  to  this  subject,  see  Caroline  F.  Ware  and  Gardiner 
C.  Means,  The  Modern  Economy  in  Action  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace, 
1936);  and  David  Lynch,  The  Concentration  of  Economic  Power  (New 
York:    Columbia   Univ.   Press,    1946). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  221 

the  long-run  profitability  of  the  corporation.  This  does  not  mean 
that  the  entrepreneur  or  the  manager  is  necessarily  motivated  by 
"the  profit  motive."  For  he  may  take  the  profitablility  of  his  opera- 
tion for  granted,  and  be  motivated  by  the  enjoyment  of  economic 
power,  realizing  the  extent  to  which  smaller,  less  strategically 
placed  enterprises  have  to  accommodate  themselves  to  his  price- 
policy  lead  or  technological  and  organizational  advances.  He  may 
enjoy  the  opportunity  of  providing  jobs  to  so  many  employees,  that 
is,  the  dependence  of  thousands  of  families  on  his  skillful  operation 
of  the  business.  He  may  enjoy  his  freedom  to  brave  government 
orders  and  find  himself,  as  did  Sevvell  Avery  of  Montgomery  Ward 
during  World  War  H,  gently  carried  from  his  office  in  the  arms  of 
soldiers.  The  handling  of  colossal  amounts  of  goods,  the  boom  and 
din  of  machinery,  the  impressive  figures  of  output,  may  all  feed 
into  a  joyful  sense  of  power,  of  the  sheer  momentum  of  the  opera- 
tion. Couched  in  moral  terms,  the  powerful  man  of  business  may 
see  the  total  enterprise  as  a  going  concern  "demanding  him,"  and 
so  feel  himself  to  be  "indispensable."  And  in  all  these  worries  and 
gratifications,  the  "profit  motive"  may  be  but  a  by-product,  even 
though,  to  be  sure,  analytically  speaking,  profitability  is  the  in- 
dispensable prerequisite  for  continuous  operation  of  the  big  busi- 
ness unit. 

The  principle  of  technological  efficiency  involves  the  solving  of 
given  technical  tasks  by  the  most  efficient  means  available.  The 
economic  principle  involves  the  attaining  of  optimum  profits  for 
a  given  outlay.  These  two  principles  are  fused  in  the  capitalist 
enterprise,  and  so  capitalism  has  often  been  termed  the  embodi- 
ment of  "rationality."  Many  observers,  however,  have  doubted  the 
"rationality"  of  the  capitalist  system  as  they  have  considered  its 
operations  and  results  over  long  periods: 

They  have  noted  ( i )  the  wastefulness  of  its  operations,  as  dra- 
matically revealed  during  depressions;  (2)  the  systematic  unem- 
ployment of  millions  of  men,  as  in  post-World  War  H  Europe, 

(3)  the  costs  of  wars  and  of  colonies  for  raw  material  monopolies; 

(4)  the  costs  of  economic  nationalism  and  protectionism;  (5)  the 
periodic  breakdowns  which  displace  in  an  unplanned  and  uncon- 
cerned way  the  careers  of  men,  condemning  some  to  permanent 
"unemployment"  at  the  age  of  forty-five  unless  they  change  their 
vocations  and  "write  off"  their  educational  investments;  (6)  the 
distributions  of  both  property  and  income,  without  rational  link- 


2.22,  SOCIALSTRUCTURE 

age  to  merit  or  function;  (7)  the  fairy-tale-like  differences  in  con- 
sumption; (8)  the  expropriation  of  large  masses  of  fixed  income 
earners  through  inflationary  processes  benefiting  the  propertied; 
(9)  the  bombardment  of  low-income  groups  with  a  never-ending 
stream  of  advertised  goods  beyond  their  purchasing  power;  and  so, 
the  inculcation  of  wishes  not  to  be  satisfied;  (10)  the  assertion  of 
free  consumers'  choice  to  low-income  groups  who  "have  no  choice." 
Even  Max  Weber,  who  of  course  accepted  capitalism  as  "economic 
rationalism"  incarnate,  liked  to  cite  Robert  Wagner's  phrase  char- 
acterizing capitalism  as  "this  masterless  slavery." 

The  economic  order  is  obviously  related  to  other  institutional 
orders.  It  is  "costly"  to  build  a  church  or  to  recruit  an  army.  What- 
ever ends  may  be  pursued,  economic  means  limit  or  facilitate  their 
attainment.  When  the  state  nationalizes  or  socializes  the  relevant 
means  of  production— the  big  land  holdings,  factories  and  facilities 
of  distribution— and  manages  these  establishments  just  as  military 
property  is  now  managed  in  the  United  States,  then  economic  and 
political  orders  are  fused.  Even  where  there  is  private  property, 
this  process  goes  on,  as  during  wartime,  for  the  planning  and  tech- 
nology required  by  twentieth-century  warfare  increasingly  pene- 
trates the  economy— even  during  times  of  nominal  peace.  There 
are  raw  material  allocations  and  a  planned  distribution  of  scarce 
labor;  there  are  priorities  and  price  controls  and  the  rationing  of 
consumers'  goods;  and  there  is  possibly  a  control  of  private  profits 
as  well  as  major  production  for  state-defined  needs.  At  such  times 
the  production  secrets  of  individual  enterprises  may  be  publicized 
and  communicated  to  less  efficient  units  in  the  economy  in  order 
to  increase  total  output  in  the  shortest  possible  time.^* 

Wartime  planning  under  private  capitalism,  in  short,  is  a  con- 
siderable departure  from  "business  as  usual."  It  is  when  "all-out 
production"  is  the  order  of  the  day  that  the  irrationalities  of  "busi- 
ness as  usual,"  with  its  unused  capacities  and  idle  men,  become 
most  embarrassingly  obvious.  Rather  than  a  promise  of  a  policy, 
"full  employment"  becomes  a  fact.  When  men  then  consider  such 
mobilization  of  production  for  the  sake  of  more  efficient  destruc- 
tion, when  millions  of  men  are  taken  out  of  production  for  years, 

8*  Key  books  include:  Alfred  Vagts,  The  History  of  Militarism  (New  York: 
Norton,  1937);  Makers  of  Modern  Strategtj,  Edward  M.  Earle  and  others,  eds. 
(Princeton:   Princeton  Univ.  Press,  1943);  and  Speier,  op.  cit.,  pp.  223-323. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  22^ 

and  then  millions  of  man-hours  are  spent  for  years  for  destruction, 
the  irrational  factors  seem  to  loom  larger.  At  any  rate,  since  the 
1890's,  the  periodic  armament  races  of  industrial  societies  have  re- 
duced Spencer's  assumption  of  the  peaceful  nature  of  industrial 
societies  to  the  bad  joke  of  a  "Little  England"  liberal. 

6.  The  Military  Order 

The  military  order  comprises  the  legitimate  and  institutionalized 
practice  of  violence.  In  modern  industrial  societies  this  order  is 
of  course  a  department  of  the  state,  but  the  practice  of  violence 
has  come  to  be  of  such  outstanding  significance  that  it  is  conven- 
ient to  single  out  the  military  order  for  separate  analysis. 

Arnold  Toynbee  has  brilliantly  outlined  the  sequence  of  pre- 
industrial  warfare  in  terms  of  footmen  and  horsemen,  either  of 
which  may  be  lightly  or  heavily  armed.  Accordingly,  one  may 
speak  of  (a)  light  footmen  or  (b)  of  light  horsemen,  and  of  (c) 
heavily  equipped  footsoldiers  or  (d)  of  heavily  armed  horsemen. 
Tribal  horse  nomads  (the  Huns),  for  example,  represent  light 
horsemen  whose  disciplined  and  swift  attacks  struck  terror  to  the 
hearts  of  the  men  in  Christendom;  since  that  time,  the  term, 
"horde "  has  appeared  in  the  vocabulary  of  all  Western  languages. 

Toynbee  sees  in  various  civilizations  a  "David  and  Goliath  pat- 
tern" of  warfare:  the  small,  quick  maneuvering  kind  of  man  beats 
the  massively  armored  giant.  Toynbee's  own  materials,  however, 
seem  to  us  to  show  that  in  due  course,  heavy  armor  is  more  likely 
to  be  beaten  by  heavier  armor— and  heavier  discipline.  The  Spar- 
tan phalanx  won  for  a  while;  then  an  Athenian  swarm  of  David's 
peltasts  beat  the  phalanx,  and  then  an  improved  phalanx,  out  of 
Thebes,  with  a  "formation  in  depth  came  to  the  fore.  Later,  every- 
thing went  down  before  the  Roman  legionnaire,  who  as  a  versatile 
fighting  man  combined  in  his  person  a  co-ordination  of  all  known 
military  skills  and  weapons— the  light  infantry  man  or  the  heavily 
armored  hoplite,  with  throwing  spear,  sword,  and  huge  shield.  He 
was  able  to  combine— and  to  use  as  occasion  demanded— the  ma- 
neuverability of  the  individual  skirmisher  with  the  driving  force 
of  the  drilled  formation. 

Yet  the  legionnaire  fell  before  the  light  horseman  with  bow  and 
arrow  and  the  heavily  armed  horseman  with  lance  and  shield. 
And  this  armored  lancer,  according  to  Toynbee,  "kept  the  saddle 


224  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

for  the  next  twelve  hundred  years  .  .  .  before  he  too,  resting  too 
long  on  his  oars  and  so  becoming  an  armor-plated  travesty  of  his 
own  beginnings,  was  decisively  beaten  by  a  David  on  horseback— 
a  light  horse  archer  of  Nomad  type  and  agility  from  the  13th  cen- 
tury steppes."  ^^ 

The  alteration  between  the  undisciplined  hero— jousting  as  a 
chivalrous  knight— and  the  disciplined  formation  of  footmen  may 
be  repeatedly  observed  in  military  history.  In  ancient  Greece  the 
Homeric  heroes  were  displaced  by  the  hoplite  army;  in  medieval 
Europe  the  feudal  hero  was  displaced  by  armies  of  disciplined 
mercenaries;  in  ancient  China  the  charioteers  of  the  feudal  age 
gave  way  to  the  army  of  footsoldiers;  ^^  in  Great  Britain  the  un- 
disciplined fighting  of  the  feudal  lords  proved  technically  inferior 
to  the  disciplined  cavalry  attack  of  Cromwell's  ironsides.^^ 

Before  the  rise  of  nation-states,  warfare  in  agrarian  societies  was 
the  privilege  of  princes.  But  since  the  American  and  French  revo- 
lutions, the  state  has  made  warfare  the  concern  of  the  nation  as  a 
whole.  Mercenary  armies,  which  were  originally  offered  on  a 
competitive  basis  to  princes  and  to  city  states,  became  attached 
to  the  state  as  standing  armies  of  mercenaries  and  impressed  sol- 
diers. Such  armies,  however,  were  costly,  and  the  individual  sol- 
dier, particularly  after  defeats,  was  not  necessarily  loyal  to  the 
respective  prince  or  state.  Men  at  war  accordingly  minimized  open 
battles  in  favor  of  exhausting  the  adversary  economically,  threaten- 
ing and  shadowboxing  without  readily  risking  all-out  battle.  This 
military  technique  has  been  called  the  "strategy  of  attrition"  a 
strategy  pursued  during  World  Wars  I  and  II  by  naval  powers  who 
blockaded  the  central  and  Axis  powers,  blacklisted  enemy-con- 
trolled firms  in  neutral  countries,  and  purchased  commodities  in 
order  to  deny  the  enemy  access  to  goods  important  for  war. 

Napoleon,  however,  revived  and  developed  to  new  heights  an- 
other type  of  strategy,  the  "strategy  of  annihilation."  Its  precondi- 
tion is  a  patriotic  army  which  today  is  recruited  by  universal  drafts. 
The  aim  of  the  leader  in  annihilation  warfare  is  to  administer  crush- 
ing defeats  to  the  enemy's  armies,  to  occupy  his  economically  im- 
portant areas  and  his  capital  city,  and  then,  after  unconditional 

•■'•'■' A  ^tudy  of  History   (London,  1951),  Vol.  IV,  pp.  431  ff. 
38  See  Max  Weber,  The  Religion  of  China,  H.  H.  Gerth,  tr.  ( Glencoe,  Illi- 
nois: Free  Press,  1951),  pp.  24  ff. 

3^  See  Sir  Charles  Firth,  Cromwell's  Army  (London:  Methuen,  1902). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  22.5 

surrender,  to  impose  the  victor's  will.  As  a  type  of  military  strategy, 
annihilation  has  developed  along  with  the  political  form  of  the 
state  and  with  the  industrialization  of  the  nation.  All  twentieth- 
century  warfare  has  been  concluded  by  "unconditional  surrender." 

The  mobilization  of  the  modern  nation's  resources  for  war  has 
reached  a  total  state— in  scope,  intensity,  and  efficiency.  The  age  at 
which  soldiers  are  recruited  has  been  lowered  to  eighteen  years 
and  raised  to  sixty  or  sixty-five;  women  have  been  drafted  for 
military  or  production  service;  the  difference  between  combatants 
and  noncombatants  has  been  abolished  through  blockade  policies 
and  the  tabula  rasa  policy  of  the  atomic  bomb.  Civilians  behind 
the  lines  of  invading  armies  are  expected  to  wage  guerrilla  warfare 
and  to  practice  sabotage.  The  co-ordination  of  all  institutional 
orders  involved  in  modern  war  leads  to  totalitarian  measures  of 
planning.  All  large-scale  organizations  in  all  institutional  orders  are 
co-ordinated  to  further  the  supreme  end  of  victory.  Art  and  science, 
religion  and  education  are  committed  to  the  cause.  The  media  of 
mass  communications  help  to  concentrate  fears  and  aggressions, 
maximizing  their  intensity  and  directing  them  against  the  enemy 
as  the  "total  threat."  Accordingly,  economic,  psychological,  po- 
litical, and  military  warfare  are  so  many  special  aspects  of  total 
war. 

This  co-ordination  of  a  nation  for  war  leads  to  unease  and  ten- 
sion. For  example,  the  lowering  of  the  draft  age,  which  is  largely 
technologically  determined,  comes  into  conflict  with  the  legal  defi- 
nition of  adult  status  and  the  political  definition  of  voting  age.  The 
Soviet  Union  and  the  states  within  her  orbit  have  adjusted  to  this 
conflict  by  lowering  the  legal  definition  of  adult  status  to  eighteen 
years  in  Eastern  Germany,  to  twelve  years  in  the  Soviet  Union. 
The  privileged  status  of  youth  before  the  courts  has  been  abolished. 
In  Russia  a  teen-ager  in  court  is  punished  like  an  adult,  rather  than 
like  a  "juvenile  delinquent."  In  the  United  States,  such  problems  are 
still  controversial. 

Another  tension  results  from  the  equal  employability  and  com- 
pensation of  men  and  women  in  military  and  other  war  work,  and 
from  the  transferability  of  the  worker  to  the  army  and  of  the 
soldier  to  the  factory.  The  cartoonist  Bill  Mauldin  caricatured  such 
tensions  expertly  during  the  late  war.  As  long  as  differences  in 
income  and  in  risk  accompany  such  transfers,  psychic  compensa- 
tions have  to  fill  the  gap.  The  invention  and  manipulation  of  such 


226  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

compensations  require  special  policies  and  ejfforts,  as  well  as  large- 
scale  measures  of  psychological  warfare,  by  which  leaders  seek  to 
control  tension  levels  and  insecurity  feelings. 

An  increasing  array  of  attitude,  trait,  and  aptitude  tests  are 
used  to  "screen"  masses  of  recruits  in  order  to  assign  men  to  their 
most  suitable  roles.  Moreover,  psychological  warfare  now  involves 
the  study  of  suitable  propaganda  addressed  to  partners  of  the 
hostile  coalition  having  diverse  cultures  and  value  preferences, 
which  is  thus  intended  to  divide  them,  to  maximize  whatever  ten- 
sion state  exists  between  them,  to  foment  disloyalty  to  leaders  and 
causes,  to  promote  states  of  apathy  and  indifference,  and  finally,  to 
produce  "crises  of  conscience"  which  will  weaken  the  will  to  fight 
or  even  induce  a  "change  of  sides." 

The  Russians  were  quite  successful  in  such  policies  during  the 
late  war  against  Hitler,  winning  over  and  organizing  captured  "free 
German  officers,"  and  using  them  in  their  anti-Nazi  propaganda. 
The  Nazis,  on  the  other  hand,  organized  an  army  of  Ukrainians 
under  General  Wlassow,  who  had  deserted  the  Red  army;  al- 
though no  Nazi,  he  made  common  cause  with  them  for  reasons  of 
his  own.  During  the  same  war,  the  United  States  and  her  allies 
were  able  to  persuade  Mussolini's  ace  diplomat,  Dino  Grandi,  to 
abandon  Mussolini  and  his  regime,  as  well  as  the  sinking  Nazi  ship, 
and  to  come  over  to  the  side  of  Victor  Emmanuel  and  his  following. 
With  this,  the  Italian  war  was  to  some  extent  transformed  into  a 
civil  war,  as  well  as  a  war  of  liberation  from  the  occupying  Nazi 
army.  Similarly,  France  was  divided,  the  "Free  French"  under 
General  de  Gaulle,  being  cut  loose  from  the  Petain-Laval  regime, 
attacking  the  Retain  administration  of  Syria  and  Dakar. 

The  distrust  characteristic  of  modern  coalition  partners  is  obvious 
when  we  remember  the  clause  in  President  Roosevelt's  destroyer 
deal  with  Great  Britain  which  obliged  his  Majesty  never  to  sur- 
render the  royal  navy  to  Nazi  Germany.  The  swiftness  of  events, 
the  changes  of  sides  by  leaders  who  thus  write  off  decades  of 
verbalized  sentiments  and  loyalties,  the  value  cleavages  by  virtue 
of  which  Churchill  had  to  order  the  sinking  of  the  French  navy 
"with  a  heavy  heart,"  the  transformation  of  Stalin's  image  from 
"Uncle  Joe"  to  a  scheming  enigma— all  such  policies  and  strategies 
and  images  demand  a  subtlety  of  presentation  to  mass  society  and 
a  short  memory  during  the  numerous  changes  in  line. 

In  our  times,  speed  is  indispensable  to  success  in  total  war,  but 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  22^ 

of  late,  the  mass  training  of  hatred  and  friendship  runs  up  against 
an  ever-greater  propaganda  neurosis,  and  has  had  to  overcome  an 
increasing  psychic  inertia. 

In  present-day  warfare,  machines  seem  more  important  than 
men,  who,  in  fact,  often  seem  appendages  to  machines,  rather  than 
the  manipulators  of  machines  as  fighting  tools.  In  the  United  States 
air  force  during  World  War  II,  differences  in  the  interacting  per- 
sonalities of  the  ten  crew  members  of  a  bomber  were  irrelevant 
to  their  efficiency.  Their  tight-knit  roles,  based  on  the  requirements 
of  the  plane,  and  their  co-ordination  to  one  another,  shape  indi- 
vidual men  into  uniform  role  takers.  A  rigid,  straightforward  pa- 
triotic feeling,  and  the  ambition  to  be  a  proved  hero  are  no  longer, 
in  the  view  of  military  personnel  experts,  unquestionable  assets,  at 
least  not  for  all  fighting  men.  Among  bomber  crews  in  the  Eighth 
Air  Force,  such  feelings  and  ambitions  operated  to  repress  anxi- 
eties, and  so  endangered  performance  as  well  as  expensive  equip- 
ment and  training.  Accordingly,  such  feelings  were,  as  a  policy, 
carefully  discouraged  in  favor  of  a  more  candid  admission  of  anxi- 
eties. Among  parachutists,  however,  the  reverse  held:  strong  super- 
egos, and  so  heroic  postures,  were  encouraged. 

7.  Characteristics  of  Six  Types  of  Armies 

In  order  briefly  to  reveal  the  range  of  phenomena  in  the  military 
order,  we  shall  now  discuss  six  quite  different  types  of  armies,  in 
each  case  setting  forth  the  following  social  and  psychological  char- 
acteristics: their  legitimations  and  motivations  for  fighting,  their 
social  recruitment  and  their  financing  or  provisioning,  the  tech- 
nological implements  they  typically  employed  and  the  form  of  or- 
ganization usually  followed,  and  their  typical  strategy  and  tactical 
maneuvers.  We  believe  that  these  are  among  the  key  typological 
features  required  for  the  sociological  understanding  of  any  army. 

I.  The  tribal  formations  of  Teutonic  warriors  and  of  a  variety  of 
nomads  legitimated  their  wars  for  land  and  booty,  or  their  migra- 
tory expansions  due  to  population  pressure,  in  traditional  and 
charismatic  ways.  They  are  free  men— although  among  their  ranks 
are  also  adopted  prisoners  of  war— self-equipped  with  club  and 
sword,  lance  and  bow,  as  well  as,  in  the  case  of  the  Vikings  and 
Homeric  Greeks,  ships.  Their  strategy  is  the  raid,  or  the  quick 
invasion,    and   their   tactics   include   encirclement   by   swarms    of 


228  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

lightly  armed  camel  or  horse  bowmen,  and  the  wedge  formation 
of  Teutonic  warriors. 

II.  Patrimonial  armies  of  the  Eastern  Roman  Empire  are  re- 
cruited from  among  slaves  and  justified  traditionally.  They  are 
organized  in  rational  formations  of  legions  or  cohorts,  and  are 
equipped  and  provided  for  by  their  master  or  prince.  Their  officers 
are  motivated  by  loyalty  to  the  traditional  head,  and  their  ranks 
are  often  compelled  by  harsh  discipline.  Shoulder  to  shoulder  they 
stand  in  a  disciplined  bloc— with  lance,  sword,  and  siege  machinery, 
as  well  as  road  and  bridge  building  apparatus.  Their  objective  is 
to  annihilate  the  enemy  by  frontal  attack  and  envelopment,  by  a 
variety  of  rationally  elaborated  tactics. 

III.  The  feudal  knight  of  the  Occident  is  a  professional  warrior, 
self-equipped  from  his  fief;  his  violence  is  legitimated  by  personal 
charism  and  Christian  blessings.  He  is  motivated  by  personal 
honor,  his  oath  of  allegiance,  and  a  sense  of  heroic  adventure.  He 
is  also  motivated  by  his  interest  in  conquering  fiefs  which  thus  add 
to  the  domain  and  glory  of  Christian  Knighthood.  Since  his  tactic 
is  to  joust  as  an  individual  in  the  open  fields,  the  organization  for 
battle  is  a  loose  federation  of  individual  fighting  men.  On  horse, 
carrying  lance,  sword,  and  shield,  and  armored  by  metal  and 
leather,  his  tactics  include  the  individual  duel  and  the  taking 
of  prisoners  for  ransom. 

IV.  Oliver  Cromwell's  army,  recruited  from  the  Puritan  gentry, 
is  legitimated  by  a  religious  cause.  In  part  it  is  self-equipped,  like 
the  feudal  knights,  and  in  part,  like  modern  national  armies, 
provisioned  by  parliament.  The  men  of  this  army  are  motivated 
by  a  discipline  based  on  an  absolute  belief  in  their  religious  cause. 
They  are  organized  in  numerically  defined  units,  in  disciplined 
formations  with  stratified  ranks  of  officers.  They  are  a  cavalry 
which,  with  pistol  and  saber,  practice  the  tactics  of  the  lineal 
frontal  assault  as  well  as  the  assault  in  depth  for  the  strategical 
objective  of  annihilation. 

V.  The  condottiere  organizes  soldiers  of  fortune,  held  by  con- 
tractional  obligations  with  a  city-state  or  a  prince  or  any  other 
private  or  public  body.  The  fulfillment  of  these  contracts  serves  as 
his  legitimation.  As  a  private  military  enterpriser,  he  recruits  mer- 
cenaries in  a  great  variety  of  ways,  including  the  shanghaiing  of 
vagabonds.  He  is  both  self-equipped  and  provided  for  by  his  em- 
ployer. The  mercenary  army  is  rationally  disciplined  and  motivated 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     I  229 

by  adventurous  quests  for  profits  and  booty,  including  women; 
ranks  of  such  armies  are  held  together  by  coercion  and  expectation 
of  wages  and  the  general  hatred  of  the  population  for  these  "stran- 
gers in  the  land"  and  disdain  of  the  upper  classes  exploiting  them. 
His  implements  vary  with  technological  level,  from  pike  and  sword, 
musket  and  cannon,  to  frigate  and  aircraft.  His  tactics  accordingly 
vary,  as  does  the  organization  of  the  army,  but  his  strategy  tends 
to  be  that  of  attrition,  especially  the  cutting  off  of  the  enemy  from 
his  base  of  operations  and  the  financial  exhaustion  of  the  enemy. 

VI.  The  violence  of  the  modern  national  army  is  legitimated  by 
the  symbols  and  sentiments  of  the  nation  and  its  cause;  the  men 
of  this  army  are  disciplined  for  obedience  to  a  hierarchy  of  staff 
and  line  officers.  Discipline  rests  upon  acceptance  of  the  nation's 
cause  and  is  guaranteed  by  sanctions— including  loss  of  status  and 
career  chances  and,  in  the  last  analysis,  capital  punishment.  Al- 
though voluntary  enlistments  are  permitted  or  encouraged,  the 
mode  of  recruitment  is  compulsory  service  for  all  citizens  judged 
fit.  The  national  army  is  organized  as  a  national  bureaucracy, 
equipped  by  the  state  or  by  the  lend-lease  of  other  friendly  states. 
Historically,  equipment  has  ranged  from  rifle  and  cannon  to  the 
machines  of  modern  industrial  war.  Tactics  include  every  type  from 
"Indian  war"  with  rifle  and  grenade  in  small  quick  attack,  to  trench 
warfare  of  position  and  maneuver  and  break-through,  as  well  as 
saturation  bombardment  from  above.  The  strategical  objective  is 
to  wear  down,  and  in  the  end,  to  obliterate  the  enemy,  occupy 
his  territory  and  impose  the  victor's  will.  Since  major  wars  are 
global,  the  power  blocs  of  nations  aim  at  division  and  redivision 
of  the  world,  and  in  the  last  analysis  at  world  domination. 


CHAPTER 

I  X 

Institutional  Orders 
and  Social  Controls,  II 


I.  Religious  Institutions 

By  "religious  order,"  as  we  have  already  noted,  we  refer  to  all 
those  institutions  in  which  men  organize  the  collective  worship  of 
God  or  gods  at  regular  occasions  and  at  fixed  places.  In  religious 
conduct  men  use  supernatural  means— prayer  and  sacrifice,  for  ex- 
ample—in an  effort  to  attain  supernatural  ends.  In  various  ways 
religion  has  to  do  with  salvation  from  suffering  or,  as  in  many 
Oriental  religions,  with  mysticism— a  fusion  of  the  person  with  the 
All-One.i 

Magic,  which  is  often  associated  with  religion,  involves  the  use 
of  supernatural  means  in  an  effort  to  control  natural  phenomena. 
The  ends  of  magic  are  thus  naturalistic— for  example,  long  life,  or 
good  health,  or  many  offspring,  or  victory  in  the  hunt  or  in  war,  or 
control  of  the  weather.  But  the  means  or  techniques  of  magic  are 
supernatural.  Magic  is  used  for  occasions  at  hand:  the  chief  is 
sick  and  so  the  medicine  man  is  called  in.  Magic  is  not  usually 
practiced  at  fixed  establishments,  but  wherever  it  seems  needed. 

Today  the  great  world  religions  (Hinduism,  Buddhism,  Judaism, 
Christianity,   Islamism,   Confucianism,   and   Taoism)    have  super- 

1  For  systematic  classifications  of  religions  phenomena,  see  J.  Wach,  Sociol- 
ogy of  Religion  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1944).  William  Howells' 
The  Heathens  (New  York:  Doubleday,  1948)  is  a  good  account.  See  also  E. 
Durkheim,  The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life  (Glencoe,  Illinois: 
Free  Press,   1947),  and  Max  Weber,  From  Max  Weber:  Essays  in  Sociology, 

II.  H.  Gerth  and  C.  Wright  Mills,  trs.  and  eds.   (New  York:   Oxford,   1946), 
Part  III. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  2^1 

seded  and  largely  transformed  magical  practices  and  beliefs.  Ac- 
cordingly, in  our  necessarily  brief  discussion  we  shall  emphasize 
the  world  religions. 

The  scriptural  prophets  of  Judaism,  from  the  ninth  century  B.C., 
were  the  first  "men  of  conscience"  about  whom  we  have  literary 
documents  and  so  historical  knowledge.  They  stand  out,  in  the 
course  of  history,  as  the  first  men  ready  to  obey  God  rather  than 
other  men.  They  were  active  prophets,  who  considered  themselves 
instruments  of  God  and,  as  divinely  compelled  men,  volunteered 
to  bring  forth  their  prophetic  oracles  and  exhortations,  in  the  form 
of  a  divinely  inspired  mission,  to  their  people  and  to  their  kings. - 

It  was  characteristic  of  them  to  withdraw  from  society  into 
solitary  states  of  brooding  ecstasy  or  stolid  trance,  and  then  to 
"return"  to  the  market  place,  to  the  Temple  of  Jerusalem.  There 
they  agitated  as  religiously  motivated  demagogues  for  true  Judaist 
conduct  in  daily  life,  for  religiously  inspired  political  isolationism 
in  the  face  of  Egyptian  and  Assyrian  aggression.  Max  Weber  has 
called  such  men  "emissary"  prophets. 

In  the  canonical  books  of  the  Old  Testament,  Amos  represents 
the  first,  Zechariah  the  last  "prophet,"  the  prophet  who  prophesied 
against  all  prophesying.  Since  then  in  Judaism  only  "false  messiahs" 
and  "false  prophets"  have  made  their  appearance.  For  a  time  a 
temple  priesthood  was  restored  to  power  in  Jerusalem;  but  under 
the  Roman  Emperor  Hadrian,  this  second  temple  was  destroyed, 
and  since  then  the  Diaspora  existence  has  been  decisive  for  the 
course  of  Judaism  as  a  world  religion.  The  rabbi— the  religious 
teacher— became  the  decisive  leader  of  this  religion.  The  establish- 
ment of  the  state  of  Israel  marks  a  new  epoch  for  Judaism. 

Both  Christianity  and  Islamism  were  developed  out  of  Judaism's 
legacy.  The  decisive  event  in  the  development  of  Christianity  from 
a  Jewish  sect  into  a  world  religion  was  Paul's  success,  over  Peter, 
in  defining  "liberty  in  Christ"  as  the  renunciation  of  the  ritualistic 
commandments  of  Judaism.  For  this  eliminated  from  Christianity 
the  self-segregating  features  of  Judaism.  In  the  orbit  of  the  Roman 
Caesars,  Christianity  was  successfully  propagated— in  competition 
with  Judaism,  with  innumerable  ancient  cults,  with  local  and  func- 

~  Cf.  Max  Weber,  Ancient  Judaism,  H.  H.  Gerth  and  D.  Martindale,  trs. 
( Glencoe,  Illinois:  Free  Press,  1952). 


232  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

tional  deities  of  the  Greek  Olympia,  with  the  Egyptian  cult  of  Isis 
and  Osiris,  and  especially  Mithras,  as  well  as  with  the  impersonal 
godhead  of  Plato,  Aristotle  and  the  Roman  Stoics.  The  following 
major  factors  were  decisive  in  Christianity's  victory:  ^ 

I.  Like  the  Old  Testament  prophets,  the  Christian  apostles  made 
it  their  rule  to  live  for  religion  rather  than  to  make  their  living  off 
religion. 

II.  The  ethical  code  of  the  ten  commandments— of  course  also 
taught  by  the  Pharisees  and  the  synagogue— was  readily  taught 
to  children  and  to  uneducated  masses  as  the  divine  imperative 
of  an  invisible,  though  personal  and  majestic,  God. 

III.  And  quite  apart  from  its  simplicity,  the  Christian  message 
proved  attractive  to  the  people  of  later  antiquity.  Jewish  messia- 
nism  was  mixed  with  the  Greek  and  Oriental  mythology  of  a  dying 
and  resurrected  God;  its  family  model  upheld  the  image  of  a 
loving  God  who  was  the  just  and  merciful  Father  of  His  faithful 
children;  and  its  majestic  conception  of  an  omniscient,  omnipotent, 
and  omnipresent  figure  held  out  eternal  salvation  of  the  immortal 
soul  in  a  blissful  beyond  to  the  faithful— that  is  to  the  obedient- 
believer,  and  eternal  damnation  in  hell  to  the  nonbeliever. 

IV.  The  dropping  of  Judaist  ritualistic  prescriptions  of  diet,  the 
Sabbath,  and  circumcision— the  self-segregating  features,  as  we 
have  said— made  joining  the  Christians  much  easier  for  the  pagans. 

V.  Finally,  during  the  centuries  of  persecution,  when  public 
agitation  by  preachers  and  prophetic  figures  was  impossible,  the 
Christians  managed  to  transform  each  administrative  hearing,  and 
each  circus  show  of  the  death  of  Christian  martyrs,  into  an  impres- 
sive public  demonstration  of  faith  in  a  world  without  hope.  The 
processional  burial  which  followed  was  a  highly  visible  testimony 
of  the  inner-directed  man  of  conscience  who  would  obey  God 
rather  than  man,  who  would  reject  this  world  and  not  shy  away 
from  suffering,  who  would  in  fact  seek  suffering  in  imitation  of 
Christ  and  for  the  status  of  sainthood,  in  order  to  gain  eternal  sal- 
vation in  the  hereafter. 

Since  then,  with  the  emergence  of  a  Roman  and  a  Byzantine 
oriented  priesthood,  Christendom  has  been  divided  into  an  Eastern 

3  See  Karl  Holl,  "Early  Christian  Propaganda,"  H.  H.  Gerth,  tr.,  which  will 
shortly  be  published  by  Beacon  Press,  Boston.  See  also  Edward  Gibbon's 
famous  chapters  on  the  rise  of  Christianity  in  The  Decline  and  Fall  of  the 
Roman  Empire  (Modern  Library  Edition  in  3  vols.). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  233 

and  Western  Church.  And  since  Martin  Luther  (14S3-1546), 
Ulrich  Zwingh  (1484-1531),  and  John  Calvin  (1509-1564),  West- 
ern Christianity  has  been  differentiated  into  the  Roman  Catliohc 
Church,  the  Calvinist  and  Lutheran  Churches,  as  well  as  numerous 
Protestant  sects. 

The  religious  monopoly  of  the  Catholic  (Jhurch  was,  in  part, 
broken  because  of  Gutenberg's  invention  of  printing  by  movable 
types,  about  1450.  For  this  soon  made  possible  thousands  of  edi- 
tions and  copies  of  the  Bible.  An  intelligentsia,  which  was  opposed 
to  the  pope  but  found  patrons  in  the  princes,  emerged.  The  crisis 
within  the  church  led  to  reform  movements  of  poor  friars  and 
cardinals,  of  students  and  other  migrant  propagandists.  Two  urban 
strata  arose  which  followed  their  own  courses— smaller  middle-class 
entrepreneurs,  who  developed  toward  inner-worldly  asceticism,' 
and  smaller  artisans,  who  tended  to  mysticism  and  the  perfection  of 
contemplation.  In  Central  Europe  all  during  the  fourteenth  century, 
the  peasantry  was  in  revolt.  The  journeymen  were  in  revolt  against 
the  closing  of  the  guilds,  and  they  as  well  as  the  poor  in  the  guilds 
were  against  usury  and  political  capitalism,  and  thus  took  sides 
with  the  peasantry.  German  princes  protected  the  heterodox  move- 
ments, which  thus  allowed  them  to  emancipate  themselves  from  the 
Holy  Roman  Empire,  under  the  Hapsburgs  and  the  pope. 

Today  in  America  there  are  Mennonites  and  Catholics,  Quakers 
and  Baptists,  Old  Order  Amish  and  Methodists;  the  United  States, 
in  fact,  exceeds  all  other  countries  in  the  number  of  denominations 
it  embraces,  there  being  between  two  and  three  hundred.'^  Since 
the  advance  of  the  Red  army  into  Central  Europe,  Protestantism 
has  been  reduced  to  a  minority  status  on  the  continent;  Catholic- 
ism, although  suffering  grievous  losses  in  Eastern  and  Southeastern 
Europe,  prevails  from  Hesse  to  Spain. 

It  has  been  characteristic  of  Western  religion  that  religious 
leaders— saints  and  founders  of  monk  orders,  reformers,  plebeian 
prophets,  and  evangelizing  artisans— repeatedly  democratize  and 
reactivate  Christianity.  Tendencies  toward  an  aristocratic  intel- 
lectualism  of  the  cultured  have  been  repeatedly  submerged;  ac- 
cordingly, by  numerous  compromises  and  concessions,  Christianity 

*  See  below,  pp.  360-63. 

5  Cf.  R.  H.  Abrams,  ed.,  "Organized  Religion  in  the  United  States,"  The 
Annals  of  the  American  Academy  of  Political  and  Social  Science,  March  1948. 


2^4  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

has  permeated  the  daily  Hfe  of  the  masses  hi  quite  diverse  societies. 
This  is  one  meaning  of  the  "emissary  prophets"  of  Christianity, 
who  as  active  men  seek  to  transform  the  v^^orld. 

In  this  perspective,  Protestantism,  by  renouncing  the  rehgious 
aristocracy  of  the  priesthood,  and  of  rehgious  orders,  has  ehminated 
the  spht  between  professionals  and  laity.  Christian  asceticism  was 
developed  behind  monastic  walls  for  especially  organized  elites;  it 
was  democratized  by  the  code  of  "inner-worldly  asceticism,"  which 
was  especially  effective  in  Puritan  Calvinist  denominations  and 
countries. 

Max  Weber,  in  The  Protestant  Ethic  and  the  Spirit  of  Capital- 
ism,'^ ascribed  world  historical  consequences  to  this  turn  of  events. 
Inaugurating  one  of  the  great  intellectual  debates  of  the  social 
sciences,  he  asserted  that  modern  industrial  capitalism  could  not 
have  emerged  without  the  "inner-worldly  asceticism"  which  con- 
tributed to  the  personality  formation  of  the  entrepreneurial  middle 
classes.  In  these  strata,  systematic  vocational  work  was  religiously 
hallowed;  success  in  one's  work  was  religiously  interpreted  as  in- 
dicative of  one's  place  among  those  predestined  by  the  hidden 
God's  inscrutable  resolve.  Hence,  religiously  motivated  fears  for 
one's  salvation  were  mobilized  for  the  conscientious  self-discipline 
of  the  vocational  man.  This  man  sets  out  to  "master"  this  world, 
which  at  the  same  time  he  rejects,  in  order  to  help  produce  the 
kingdom  to  come.  He  does  not  withdraw  from  the  world  into  con- 
templation, nor  build  a  specialized  monastic  world  withdrawn  from 
the  larger  world;  on  the  contrary,  he  stays  in  this  world  yet  is  not 
of  it;  he  actively  tackles  the  world  by  work  in  order  to  realize  his 
ethically  inspired  quest  for  mastery.  Whether  in  his  workshop,  in 
the  market,  or  on  the  battlefield,  he  aspires  to  be  a  crusader  for 
the  kingdom  to  come;  and  wherever  he  finds  them,  he  fights  the 
devil  and  all  evil. 

Weber's  explanatory  scheme  for  the  emergence  of  capitalism 
among  the  rational  bourgeoisie  may  be  summarized  in  more  detail 
as  follows: 

The  religious  doctrines  of  Luther,  and  especially  of  Calvin,  de- 
fined anew  the  Christian's  relation  to  his  everyday  work.  In  the 
English  and  in  the  German  languages— and  in  them  only  since 

''See  also  R.  H.  Tawney,  Religion  and  the  Rise  of  Capitalism  (New  York: 
Harcourt,  Brace,   1948). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  235 

Protestant  Bible  translations— the  terms,  "calling"  or  Beruf,  refer 
both  to  one's  occupation  and  to  one's  religious  destiny.  According 
to  Calvin's  doctrine  of  predestination  each  man  was  to  be  saved  or 
condemned  by  an  inscrutable  judgment  of  the  stern  Lord.  This 
doctrine  released  in  the  pious  believer  great  anxieties  lest  he  be 
among  the  condemned,  and  these  anxieties  could  not  be  relieved 
by  withdrawal  from  the  world  into  monastery  life  or  into  extraor- 
dinary religious  conduct,  like  the  medieval  saint's.  For  these  ave- 
nues were  blocked  by  the  theory  that  God  had  placed  man  in  the 
world  of  his  creation,  coupled  with  the  doctrine  that  the  Lord 
had  chosen  or  condemned  all  men.  Therefore  pious  works,  like 
donations  to  churches,  extra  prayers  and  pilgrimages,  became  sense- 
less and  frivolous  attempts  to  interfere  with  God's  inscrutable  will. 
There  was  indeed  only  one  way  to  gain  signs  of  one's  state  of  grace 
as  a  portent  of  one's  being  elect;  namely,  the  methodical  adherence 
to  a  God-pleasing  code  of  conduct  in  whatever  position  the  pious 
found  himself. 

This  code  of  conduct,  as  historically  developed  by  puritan  sects, 
Weber  called  "inner-worldly"  or  "this-worldly  asceticism"— an  ab- 
negation of  the  enjoyment  of  worldly  pleasures  in  the  midst  of  the 
world.  The  puritan  thus  undertook  to  live  a  quasi-monastic  life 
without  becoming  a  monk,  to  carry  forth  the  norms  of  this-worldly 
asceticism,  and  so  to  "conquer  the  world"  rather  than  to  withdraw. 
To  follow  through  this  program  required  the  methodical  and 
systematic  observation  of  self  and  an  ever-renewed  self-discipline. 
The  minimization  of  impulses  and  deviations  from  the  religious 
code  served  the  pious  pvuitan  as  an  indication  of  his  selected  status 
in,  the  eyes  of  God.  The  religious  code,  however,  by  denying  in- 
dulgence in  joyful  re\'elry  and  dancing,  in  sexual  gratifications,  and 
even  in  sleeping  (the  ideal  of  the  long  hard  day),  left  the  puritan 
the  concentration  on  work  as  his  major  ascetic  technique.  The 
pious  man  must  always  renew  his  efforts,  because  no  final  guarantee 
or  security  is  held  out  to  him.  In  the  face  of  possible  condemnation, 
any  exertions  and  tribulations  in  this  valley  of  tears  weigh  but 
lightly.  Accordingly,  guilt  spurs  his  intensified  work:  the  vocational 
man  is  nowjtbe  man  who  pleases  God. 

The  Religious  ethic  of  the  puritan  makes  it  impossible  for  him  to 
invest  the  fruits  of  his  work  in  ostentatious  consumption,  like  horses 
and  carriages,  mansions  and  feudal  estates;  on  the  other  hand,  he 
believes  that  he  who  does  not  work  shall  not  eat.  Therefore,  Cath- 


2;^6  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

olic  alms  to  beggars,  vagrants,  and  the  like  are  denied.  For  puritan 
philanthropic  enterprises  organize  uniformed  orphans  and  vagrants, 
beggars  and  the  aged  in  institutions  set  up  for  the  purpose.  There 
is  only  one  way  in  which  the  puritan  may  use  his  private  accumu- 
lations of  wealth:  to  invest  and  reinvest  them  in  productive  enter- 
prises. For  this  allows  for  the  extension  of  salvation  opportunities 
to  so  many  more  beggars.  The  puritan  businessman  thus  saves  their 
souls  by  using  them  as  his  labor  supply,  and  they,  the  labor  supply, 
acquire  a  new  work  discipline  by  becoming  the  employer's  breth- 
ren. For  salvation's  sake,  they  forego  many  popular  and  colorful 
days,  festivities,  mysteries,  and  plays  which  were  holidays  from 
work  for  the  medieval  Catholic  worker.  Thus  the  puritan  becomes 
the  restless  worker  making  sure  of  his  state  of  predestination,  and, 
as  a  particularly  saintly  man,  earning  the  respect  of  his  fellow 
believers  the  more  he  expands  his  establishment. 

Weber's  analysis  reveals  the  impact  of  a  creed  upon  the  forma- 
tion of  a  type  of  character.  Religiously  motivated  insecurity  and  its 
religiously  designated  escape  place  premiums  upon  specific  psychic 
attitudes  and  traits  like  thrift,  hard  work,  control  of  "idle  words," 
humility,  continuous  self-control,  purposiveness.  This  character 
structure,  in  turn,  becomes  economically  relevant  in  that  it  guaran- 
tees competitive  advantage  over  traditionalist  and  less  frugal  eco- 
nomic agents. 

The  necessity  of  the  puritan  to  maintain  himself  in  the  eyes  of 
his  sectariaii  brothers  allows  for  the  emergence  of  the  new  morality 
of  everyday  business.  The  puritan  does  not  higgle  in  the  market, 
and  contracts  are  sacred.  Hence  the  puritan  is  a  safe  credit  risk, 
and  has  the  highest  credit  rating  in  the  business  community.  This, 
in  turn,  fructifies  his  business  advance,  and  the  puritan  sect  thus 
becomes  a  selective,  and  at  the  same  time  a  breeding  agency,  for 
that  personality  type  best  fitted  to  develop  and  propagate  industrial 
capitalism  as  a  system. 

Religious  ideas  became  psychologically  relevant  to  character 
structure;  they  place  a  premium  on  specific  traits,  and  these  traits 
become  incentives  for  a  new  style  of  economic  conduct.  As  religious 
organizations,  the  sects  are  fit  to  stabilize  such  personality  types 
into  an  organized  elite.  Their  conduct  and  religiosity  can  be  prop- 
agated, and  hence  expanded.  The  long-run  result  of  these  changes, 
namely  all  that  goes  with  modern  capitalism's  success,  was  neither 
intended  nor  foreseen  by  its  puritan  pioneers. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  2:^^ 

Religious  developments  seem  to  occur  by  revivals  and  by  secu- 
larizations, which  alternate  with  each  other.  Accordingly,  we  speak 
of  the  "great  revival"  of  Protestantism  in  England  during  the  late 
eighteenth  century,  when  the  Methodist  movement  sprang  up 
and  put  an  end  to  the  "merrie  old  England"  of  the  Restoration 
period.  Catholicism  has  also  had  its  revivals,  the  most  prominent 
being  the  renewal  of  religious  ardor  during  the  Jesuit-led  "covmter- 
reformation,"  which  recovered  Southern  and  Southeastern  Europe 
from  Protestantism,  leaving  only  scattered  islands  of  Calvinist  and 
Lutheran  Protestanism  in  Hungary  and  Romania,  which  were 
/eliminated  by  the  advance  of  the  Red  army  during  World  War  II. 

Catholic  and  Protestant  revival  movements  occurred  at  the  end 
of  the  Napoleonic  epoch.  Romantic  intellectuals  were  converted  to 
Catholicism  under  Metternich;  and  nowadays  we  witness  the  suc- 
cessful endeavors  of  Catholics  to  win  over  such  intellectuals  as 
Jacques  Maritain,  the  late  Heywood  Broun,  the  ex-editor  of  the 
Daily  Worker,  Budenz,  as  well  as  influential  upper-class  persons 
such  as  Clare  Boothe  Luce  and  Henry  Ford  II. 

The  role  of  the  convert  merits  special  attention  for  his  ardor  may 
be  especially  intense.  He  may  be  motivated  more  by  his  resent- 
ment against  what  he  leaves  behind  than  by  positive  and  loving 
identification  with  what  he  has  come  to  embrace,  Tertullian  is 
the  often  quoted  case  of  such  "resentful"  Christianity.  This  con- 
cept of  "resentment,"  as  developed  by  Nietzsche,"  asserts,  in  fact, 
that  all  Christianity  is  nothing  but  the  uprising  of  the  slaves  in 
morality,  which  means  that  since  direct  aggression  is  denied  to  the 
slave,  he  must  "repress"  his  aggression  and  thereby  sublimate  it 
ijito  a  wish  for  delayed  aggression,  or  revenge.  This  desire  for  re- 
\enge,  in  turn,  becomes  conscious  and  is  then  repressed,  but  it  is 
repressed  from  a  new  vantage  point,  from  a  presumably  higher 
\alue  positon  resulting  from  a  "transvaluation  of  values."  Not  the 
strong,  the  high,  or  the  mighty  are  accepted  as  highly  valuable 
types  of  men,  but  the  lowly,  the  suffering,  the  meek,  who  "shall 
inherit  the  earth."  It  is  the  uncomely  and  the  despised  of  this  world 
who  are  the  beloved  of  God. 

According   to   this   theory,   the   righteous   can   condescendingly 

"  For  an  excellent  account  of  Nietzsche's  thought,  see  Walter  A.  Kaufmann, 
Nietzsche  (Princeton:  Princeton  Uniw  Press,  1950),  especially  Chapters  7, 
8   and   10. 


238  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

anticipate  the  dire  fate  of  the  godless  and  unrighteous— a  fate 
which  God  is  preparing  for  them  on  "doomsday"  or  on  "The  Day 
of  Judgment,"  of  which  the  Christians  sing.  Nietzsche,  in  thus  con- 
struing neighborhness  and  Christian  love  as  a  "compensation"  for 
denied  aggression,  takes  up  Hobbes's  assumption  that  human  na- 
ture is  "originally"  evil  and  aggressive,  and  that  profession  of  love 
is  a  compensatory  derivation  of  hatred  and  frustrated  aggression. 

One  may,  to  be  sure,  readily  discern  features  of  resentment,  as 
well  as  resentful  men,  in  the  Jewish  as  well  as  the  Christian  tradi- 
tion. But  to  "explain"  these  religions,  in  all  their  complexities,  in 
terms  of  "resentment"  requires  that  we  reduce  their  specific  value 
preferences  and  their  ethos  to  a  natiu-alistic  bias  concerning  the 
nature  of  love.  Max  Scheler  has  convincingly  juxtaposed  the  con- 
ception of  Christian  love  with  that  of  Greek  antiquity's  "eros." 
The  Greek  philosophers  conceived  of  love  in  terms  of  scarcity  con- 
sciousness: Men  should  allocate  their  scarce  love  to  those  men  and 
to  those  values  that  "merit"  love;  hence  they  should  want  to  prefer 
the  "higher"  value  or  the  higher  type  of  man  to  the  "lower."  The 
Christian  idea  of  a  loving  God,  in  contrast,  is  predicated  on  the 
assumption  that  love  is  "infinite."  The  loving  God  and  the  loving 
Christian  are  not  thought  to  be  striving,  in  a  competitive  context, 
towards  something  higher  and  higher  but  rather  from  the  outset  as 
standing  high  and  holding  out  infinite  love  and  mercy  to  the  crea- 
ture who  is  in  his  failings  and  in  his  weakness  lowly.  It  is  a  con- 
ception foreshadowed  by  Isaiah's  hope  for  a  new  covenant  with  a 
merciful  God,  who  will  consider  "not  the  circumcision  of  the  fore- 
skin but  the  circumcision  of  the  heart."  It  is  foreshadowed  also  in 
Isaiah's  idea  of  the  Servant  of  Yahweh.  "Love "  in  Christianity  is 
thus  conceived,  not  as  a  natinalistically  limited  impulse,  but  as  a 
spiritual  and  psychic  act  of  unlimited  capacity. 

William  James,  in  a  quite  different  context,®  gives  expression  to 
this  idea  of  loving  empathy  as  being  a  prerequisite  of  discern- 
ment rather  than  a  compensation  for  a  frustrated  "will  to  power." 
"Every  Jack,"  he  wrote,  "sees  in  his  own  particular  Jill  charms  and 
perfection  to  the  enchantment  of  which  we  stolid  on-lookers  are 
stone-cold.  And  which  has  the  superior  view  of  the  absolute  truth, 
he  or  we?  Which  has  the  more  vital  insight  into  the  nature  of 
Jill's  existence,  as  a  fact?  Is  he  in  excess,  being  in  this  matter  a 

8  Sec  F.  O.  Matthiessen,  TJie  James  Family  (New  York:  Knopf,  1947), 
p.  404  fF. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  2;^g 

maniac?  or  are  we  in  defect,  being  victims  of  a  pathological  anaes- 
thesia as  regards  Jill's  magical  importance?  Surely  the  latter;  surely 
to  Jack  are  the  profounder  truths  revealed;  surely  poor  Jill's  pal- 
pitating little  life-throbs  are  among  the  wonders  of  creation,  are 
worthy  of  this  sympathetic  interest;  and  it  is  to  our  shame  that 
the  rest  of  us  cannot  feel  like  Jack.  For  Jack  realizes  Jill  con- 
cretely, and  we  do  not.  He  struggles  toward  union  with  her  inner 
life,  divining  her  feelings,  anticipating  her  desires,  understanding 
her  limits  as  manfully  as  he  can,  and  yet  inadequately  too;  for  he  is 
also  afflicted  with  some  blindness,  even  here.  Whilst  we,  dead  clods 
that  we  are,  do  not  e\'en  seek  these  things,  but  are  contented  that 
the  portion  of  eternal  fact  named  Jill  should  be  for  us  as  if  it  were 
not.  Jill,  who  knows  her  inner  life,  knows  that  Jack's  way  of  taking 
it— so  importantly— is  the  true  and  serious  way;  and  she  responds 
to  the  truth  in  him  by  taking  him  truly  and  seriously  too.  May  the 
ancient  blindness  never  warp  its  clouds  about  either  of  them 
again." 

The  relevance  of  the  religious  order  to  other  institutional  orders 
depends  upon  the  organizational  principles  of  the  religion  in- 
volved, and  in  particular,  upon  whether  or  not  the  religion  is 
compulsory  or  voluntary.  American  democratic  society,  for  ex- 
ample, with  its  innumerable  voluntary  organizations,  is  greatly 
indebted  to  Puritanism  and  to  the  multiplicity  of  denominations 
and  sects.  At  the  opposite  extreme,  state  and  church  are  led  by  one 
man  who  combines  the  roles  of  supreme  priest  and  emperor.  This 
is  Caesar-Papism,  as  exemplified  by  the  Japanese  Mikado,  the  Con- 
fucian Emperor  of  ancient  China,  the  Roman  Emperors  after 
Augustus,  the  Russian  Tsars  after  Peter  the  Great,  or  the  German 
Lutheran  princes. 

The  oldest,  and  in  the  West,  the  largest,  ecclesiastical  structure 
—the  Roman  Catholic  Church— is  headed  by  the  Pope  who  is  unani- 
mously elected  by  a  college  of  seventy  cardinals.  The  Pope 
legitimizes  his  claim  to  Catholicity,  that  is,  to  universal  authority, 
by  the  dogma  of  the  apostolic  succession  from  Peter,  the  first  Bishop 
of  Rome.  The  authoritarian  structm-e  of  this  priestly  organization, 
however,  has  accommodated  itself  to  constitutional  democracy.  If 
the  state  shoidd  attack  the  church,  the  church  is  likely  to  enter  the 
political  order  more  explicitly  than  it  has  in  the  United  States  by 
lending  its  support  to  the  organization  of  a  special  Catholic  Party, 


240  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

as  is  to  be  found  in  Germany,  Italy,  Belgium,  and  other  European 
countries.  If  the  state,  in  its  public  schools  and  universities,  should 
not  allow  religious  instruction,  the  church  is  likely  to  organize  a 
parochial  school  system  of  its  own  up  through  the  university  level, 
as  in  the  United  States  where  15  per  cent  of  the  school  population 
is  enrolled  in  such  Catholic  schools.  Celibate  monks  and  nuns  can 
compete  effectively  with  more  expensive  secular  teachers.  Where 
the  legal  order  permits  the  free  accumulation  of  property,  the 
church  can  add  to  its  corporate  wealth. 

In  those  large  cities  in  which  the  Catholic  Church  controls  the 
majority  vote,  the  official  "separation  of  state  and  church"  is,  in 
a  way,  bypassed  on  the  municipal  level.  Direct  and  indirect  subsi- 
dies can  be  allocated  under  diverse  headings.  In  the  United  States, 
Catholicism  was  originally  a  religion  of  plebeian  immigrants— of 
Irish,  German,  Italian,  and  Polish  descent.  During  recent  decades, 
however.  Catholics  have  added  propertied  and  educated  elites  to 
their  ranks,  who  can  and  who  do  exert  significant  influence  in  for- 
eign and  domestic  political  decisions.  The  combination  of  the 
Democratic  Party,  the  Catholic  clergy,  and  the  trade  unions  under 
the  presidency  of  Franklin  Roosevelt  is  a  well-known  political 
coalition."  In  the  face  of  attacks,  the  Catholic  Church  of  course 
claims  democratic  rights  and  liberties  for  itself,  but  where  the 
church  is  established  and  represents  the  great  majority  of  the  peo- 
ple it  is  unlikely  to  grant  Protestant  minorities  the  right  to  prosely- 
tize. The  strife  and  tension  in  Italy,  in  Spain,  and  in  Colombia  are 
recent  cases  in  point.  In  France,  the  Catholic  Church  has  twice 
been  disestablished— during  the  French  Revolution,  and  in  1904-05 
under  the  Millerand  coalition  of  socialists  and  bourgeois  liberals. 
Under  Petain,  the  church  was  re-established,  a  measure  that  has 
been  honored  by  postwar  governments. 

Where  religious  authorities  take  over  the  administration  of  the 
state,  we  may  speak  of  a  "theocracy."  World  famed  examples  in- 
clude the  theocracies  of  ancient  Jerusalem  under  Ezra  and  Nehe- 
miah  and  later  under  the  Pharisees;  Calvin's  rule  at  Geneva;  the 
rule  of  the  Puritan  divines  in  colonial  New  England;  and  the  Jesuit 
state  in  Paraguay  in  the  seventeenth  and  eighteenth  centuries. 

8  For  a  knowledgeable  account  of  sucli  matters,  see  Samuel  Lubell,  The 
Future  of  American  Politics  (New  York:  Harper,  1952);  and  Paul  Blanshard, 
American  Freedom  and  Catholic  Power   (Boston:    Beacon  Press,   1949). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  24I 

It  is  characteristic  of  Western  Christianity  that  at  various  times 
it  has  been  in  tension  with  political  authorities  and  economic 
powers,  with  military,  scientific,  philosophical,  and  artistic  move- 
ments. Christianity  has  held  revolutionary  as  well  as  conservative 
positions— at  different  times  and  in  different  contexts.  Accordingly, 
generalizations  of  the  political  orientations  of  Christianity  are 
hound  to  overlook  or  to  bypass  pertinent  aspects  and  ramifications 
of  its  varied  adaptations  to  Western  social  structures.  As  Hegel  has 
observed: 

"The  Christian  religion  has  sometimes  been  reproved,  sometimes 
praised,  for  its  consistency  with  the  most  varied  manners,  charac- 
ters, and  institutions.  It  was  cradled  in  the  corruption  of  the  Roman 
state;  it  became  dominant  when  that  empire  was  in  the  throes  of 
its  decline,  and  we  cannot  see  how  Christianity  could  have  stayed 
its  downfall.  On  the  contrary,  Rome's  fall  extended  ^he  scope  of 
Christianity's  domain,  and  it  appears  in  the  same  epoch  as  the 
religion  of  the  barbarians,  who  were  totally  ignorant  and  savage 
but  completely  free,  and  also  of  the  Greeks  and  Romans,  who  by 
this  time  were  overcivilized,  servile,  and  plunged  in  a  cesspool  of 
vice.  It  was  the  religion  of  the  Italian  states  in  the  finest  period 
of  their  licentious  freedom  in  the  Middle  Ages;  of  the  grave  and 
free  Swiss  republics;  of  the  more  or  less  moderate  monarchies  of 
modern  Europe;  alike  of  the  most  heavily  oppressed  serfs  and  their 
overlords:  both  attended  one  church.  Headed  by  the  Cross,  the 
Spaniards  murdered  whole  generations  in  America;  over  the  con- 
(juest  of  India  the  English  sang  Christian  thanksgivings.  Christian- 
ity was  the  mother  of  the  finest  blossoms  of  the  plastic  arts;  it  gave 
rise  to  the  tall  edifice  of  the  sciences.  Yet  in  its  honor  all  fine  art 
was  banned,  and  the  development  of  the  sciences  was  reckoned 
an  impiety.  In  all  climates  the  tree  of  the  Cross  has  grown,  taken 
root,  and  fructified.  Every  joy  in  life  has  been  linked  with  this  faith, 
while  the  most  miserable  gloom  has  found  in  it  its  nourishment  and 
its  justification."  ^^ 

2.  Characteristics  of  World  Religions 

We  may  grasp  the  main  features  of  a  religion  if  we  know  the 
following  facts:  its  attitude  toward  the  status  quo,  its  representa- 

■'A  Georg  Williclni  Friedrich  Hegel,  Early  Theological  Writings,  T.  M.  Knox, 
tr.   (Chicago:   Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1948),  pp.  168  fF. 


242.  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

tive  class  or  leadership;  the  sources  of  its  religious  authority;  its 
type  of  religious  assembly  and  organization,  the  chief  end  of  life 
it  holds  out,  its  views  of  the  superhuman  and  of  life  after  death, 
its  sexual  code,  its  magical  features,  if  any,  and  its  attitude  towards 
politics,  work,  and  education.  In  the  following  paragraphs  we 
characterize  each  of  the  great  world  religions  in  these  terms.^° 

I.  Confucianism  accepts  the  present  order  as  good,  for  the  em- 
peror who  reigns  is  the  Son  of  Heaven.  It  is  the  religion  of  cultured 
erudites  who  find  their  source  of  religious  authority  in  the  writings 
of  Confucius  and  the  Confucian  tradition.  It  involves  ancestral 
and  political  festivals,  and  understands  the  major  end  of  life  to 
be  the  preservation  of  the  social  order.  A  multitude  of  spirits  popu- 
lates its  world,  although  Heaven  is  rather  impersonally  imagined. 
Confucianisjjjn  is  not  concerned  with  the  salvation  of  immortal  souls. 
It  scorns  women,  although  it  stresses  the  perpetuation  of  the  fam- 
ily. It  officially  disowns  the  magical  beliefs  and  practices  of  wilgar 
Taoism,  which  are  widespread  among  the  masses.  It  upholds  filial 
piety  as  a  cardinal  virtue,  which  ties  it  to  ancestor  worship.  Dis- 
couraging independent  thinking,  it  glorifies  rote  learning  and  feats 
of  memory  among  its  scholarly  leaders.  Man's  work,  according 
to  this  creed,  is  and  should  be  under  the  control  of  the  tradition- 
minded  family,  or  when  it  is  office  work,  under  the  control  of  the 
Confucian  hierarchy  headed  by  the  emperor  as  the  Son  of  Heaven. 

II.  Hinduism,  both  classical  and  popular,  looks  upon  its  world 
of  castes  as  eternal  and  unchangeable,  for  there  is  no  beginning  and 
no  end  of  the  immortal  soul  of  man.  Accordingly,  it  upholds  and 
at  the  same  time  makes  more  tolerable  the  caste  system.  Classical 
Hinduism  is  represented  by  the  Brahmins— an  hereditary,  intel- 
lectual aristocracy;  popular  Hinduism,  by  the  gurus  (i.e.  mendi- 
cant monks)  and  by  holy  men  of  quite  different  caste  origin.  For 
its  classical  form,  the  Brahmins  interpret  ancient  writings  and  tra- 
dition; for  its  popular  form,  the  gurus  interpret  tradition  and  folk- 
lore. Both  forms  involve  pilgrimages  to  holy  places.  The  Brahmin 
identifies  himself  with  the  cosmic  spirit— that  is  the  chief  religious 

^o  See  E.  J.  Jurji,  ed.,  The  Great  Religions  of  the  Modern  World  (Princeton: 
Princeton  Univ.  Press,  1946);  H.  L.  Friess  and  H.  W.  Schneider,  Religion  in 
Various  Cultures  (New  York:  Holt,  1932),  as  well  as  the  works  of  Max  Weber 
cited  elsewhere  in  this  volume. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  24,3 

end  of  his  life;  the  masses  seek  to  improve  their  status  in  their 
next  rebirth.  For  these  masses,  there  is  a  vast  pantheon  of  nature 
and  functional  gods;  for  the  Brahmin,  a  more  or  less  impersonal 
cosmic  spirit.  But  both,  as  Hindus,  believe  in  the  transmigration 
of  souls,  the  next  incarnation  according  to  the  karman  doctrine 
being  determined  by  one's  adherence  to  one's  "dharma":  the 
ritualistically  sanctioned  code  of  one's  hereditary  caste.  The 
Brahmin  scorns  women,  for  they  interfere  with  contemplation; 
among  the  masses  cults  of  various  sorts  prevail.  Among  both,  magi- 
cal features  are  in  evidence,  although  much  more  so  among  the 
popular  than  the  classical  forms  of  Hinduism.  Education  is  limited 
to  the  aristocratic  class,  with  an  emphasis  upon  classic  writings  in 
Sanskrit.  Work  is  completely  controlled  by  the  hereditary  and 
endogamous  caste  system,  and  all  innovations  are  discouraged.  1 1 

HI.  Buddhism  regards  the  present  world  as  evil  and  unchange- 
able. The  Buddhist  monks— the  representative  class  of  this  religion 
—interpret  ancient  writings  and  tradition,  and  religious  assemblage 
is  limited  to  monasteries  and  to  certain  festivals.  The  chief  end  of 
life  is  conceived  to  be  the  escape  from  suffering,  that  is,  escape 
from  the  wheel  of  life  with  its  rebirths  for  more  of  the  same.  There 
is  a  continual  rebirth  through  desire,  but  if  one  escapes  from  de- 
sire there  is  the  eternal  rest  of  nirvana.  Celibacy  and  the  avoidance 
of  all  desire  is  sought  by  means  of  complex  spiritual  exercises 
and  the  achievement  of  extraordinary  psychosomatic  states.  There 
is  no  image  of  the  superhuman  in  classic  Buddhism,  although 
spiritism  is  rampant  in  popular  forms  of  the  religion.  Magic  is 
forbidden  in  the  former,  but  abounds  in  the  latter.  Accordingly, 
education  is  limited  to  the  monasteries  and  to  those  trained  there. 
As  routine  work  would  distract  from  the  holy  path,  it  is  despised 
by  the  mendicant  monks. 

IV.  Judaism  views  the  present  order  with  resolute  hope  for  the 
future.  Its  religious  cohesion  rests  upon  faith  in  being  chosen  by 
Yahweh  for  a  covenant  fellowship  with  him  as  a  party  to  the  con- 
tract. Its  representati^'e  religious  leaders  are  Levites  and  Torah 
teachers,  charismatic  prophets  and  hereditary  temple  priests.  Of 
special  significance  has  been  the  demilitarized,  pacifist,  peasant, 
shepherd,  and  plebeian  strata  of  cities.  Since  the  destruction  of 
the  temple  and  its  priesthood,  the  law  and  the  prophets  are  its  holy 


244  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

books;  its  sources  of  religious  authority  and  its  religious  assemblage 
is  the  synagogue.  Life  is  a  waiting,  a  tarrying,  for  a  new  and  better 
social  order;  in  ancient  Judaism  there  is  no  idea  of  personal  sur- 
vival after  death.  There  are  relatively  few  magical  features  in 
Judaism  and  its  monotheistic  God  is  personal  and  ethical.  Aside 
from  some  cult  prescriptions  of  chastity,  there  is  no  asceticism; 
priests,  prophets,  and  rabbis  marry— and  the  family  is  sanctified. 
Education  consists  of  general  instruction  in  the  Torah  and  in  his- 
tory. The  orthodox  Jew  views  work  rationally  and  practically,  al- 
though since  the  exile,  work  has  been  hampered  in  various  degrees 
by  ritualistic  separation. 

V.  Originally  Mohammedism  was  a  prophetic  creed  of  a  cru- 
sading order  of  warriors;  now  Islamic  society  largely  accepts  the 
present  order  as  fate.  The  individual  interprets  the  Koran;  there 
are  private  devotions  as  well  as  pilgrimages  and  mass  meetings. 
The  chief  end  of  life  is  to  realize  the  will  of  Allah,  who  is  a  per- 
sonal and  monotheistic  God.  Originally  there  was  a  conception  of  a 
warrior's  paradise,  with  houris  and  carousing.  Nowadays  there  is  a 
crudely  conceived  heaven  and  hell,  and  magical  practices  and  be- 
liefs are  much  in  evidence.  Women  are  isolated,  popular  education 
neglected,  and  the  attitude  towards  work  is  indifferent. 

VI.  Christianity,  in  both  its  Roman  Catholic  and  Puritan  form, 
conceives  of  man  as  in  the  present  world  but  not  really  of  it,  as 
forming  a  super-social  fellowship.  Catholicism  is  inclined  to  sup- 
port each  of  the  varieties  of  status  quo  in  its  vast  domains;  Puri- 
tanism, to  stand  in  defiance  of  the  world  and  attempt  to  remake  it. 
The  representative  Catholic  leaders  are  saints,  celibate  priests, 
monks,  and  nuns;  of  Puritan  sects,  the  "middle  classes."  The  sources 
of  religious  authority  for  Catholics  are  the  Bible  as  interpreted  by 
religious,  priestly  guidance,  and  ex  cathedra  pronouncements  of 
the  pope.  For  Puritans  the  Bible,  as  interpreted  by  the  individual 
who  is  qualified  for  sect  membership  by  his  "inner  light,"  is  the 
source  of  authority.  Catholics  have  a  heaven,  a  hell,  and  a  purga- 
tory; Puritans— in  fact,  all  Protestants— have  only  a  heaven  and  a 
hell.  Both,  however,  entertain  images  of  individual  salvation,  al- 
though the  Catholics'  is  in  a  future  heaven,  the  Puritans'  in  a  king- 
dom to  come.  The  Catholic  assemblage  is  the  mass;  the  Puritan, 
common  worship.  Both  are  Trinitarian  in  their  images  of  the  god- 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  24!^ 

head,  although  the  CathoHcs  also  revere  the  saints  and  the  Virgin 
Mary.  Magic  is  much  in  evidence  in  Catholicism— the  sacrament 
being  thought  to  work  by  virtue  of  the  ritual.  Puritanism  has  fought 
and  eliminated  all  magic  as  devilish.  Sacraments,  for  example,  the 
Lord's  Supper,  is  considered  a  festival  in  memory  of  Christ's  last 
supper;  Catholic  priests  are  professionally  trained;  other  Catholic 
education  varies  in  level  according  to  competitive  or  monopolistic 
situation,  and  is  determined  by  the  interests  of  religious  conform- 
ity. Like  Judaism,  Puritanism  lays  great  stress  on  and  pays  zealous 
attention  to  mass  education  of  the  laity,  and  has  encouraged  ex- 
ploratory thinking  in  science  and  technology,  and  education  for 
businessmen.  In  Catholicism  there  is  celibacy  for  the  holy,  mar- 
riage, though  considered  a  sacrament,  being  a  concession  to  hu- 
man frailty  and  belonging  to  "the  natural  order."  In  Puritanism, 
the  same  ethical  demands  hold  for  clergy  and  laity,  marriage  in- 
volving a  love  of  sobriety.  Work,  for  the  Benedictine  monks  espe- 
cially, represents  the  burdensome  legacy  of  man's  fall.  The  re- 
ligious zeal  of  Puritanism,  as  we  have  noted  in  detail  above,  is 
channeled  into  work  of  this  world. 

-3.  The  Kinship  Order 

The  kinship  order— we  have  noted  above— is  composed  of  insti- 
tutions which  regulate  and  facilitate  legitimate  sexual  intercourse, 
procreation,  and  the  rearing  of  children  as  well  as  the  transmission 
of  private  property.  ^^ 

All  social  structures  institutionalize  sexual  activities  and  thus 
regulate  them,  but  often  such  activities  are  accompanied  by  illegiti- 
mate forms  of  relation  that  are  more  or  less  tolerated.  When  the 
kinship  order  is  taxed  beyond  capacity,  the  load  is  shifted  to  men, 
women,  or  children  not  belonging  to  legitimate,  domestic  groups 
but  offering  erotic  services  to  its  members.  Hetaerae,  mistresses, 
concubines,  prostitutes— male  and  female,  sacred  and  profane— all 
play  such  supplementary  roles.  The  idea  that  only  women  have 
honor  (and  hence  can  lose  it)  reflects  thousands  of  years  of  male 
dominance.  If  the  gigolo  were  revealed  throughout  world  history 

'1  See  W.  Goodsell,  A  History  of  Marriage  and  the  Family  (rev.  ed.;  New 
York:  Macmillan,  1934);  and  A.  W.  Calhoun,  A  Social  History  of  the  Aineri- 
can  Family   (New  York:   Barnes  &  Noble,   1945). 


246  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

as  is  the  female  prostitvite,  then  men  too  could  lose  their  honor, 
and  in  this  connection  be  equal  with  women.  Illicit  erotic  rela- 
tions are  most  likely  to  occur  when  economic  conditions  keep  the 
biological  adult  from  assuming  the  role  of  provider.  The  socially 
unplaced  erotic  overhead  is  thus  transferred  to  erotic  specialists, 
to  the  prostitute,  or  on  higher-class  levels,  to  the  mistress. 

When  we  emphasize  the  economic  aspect  of  the  kinship  order, 
we  speak  of  the  "household";  when  we  stress  the  kinship  aspect 
we  speak  of  the  "family."  "  In  the  remote  past,  and  in  many  con- 
temporary preliterate  societies,  the  economic  and  the  kinship  or- 
ders are  not  differentiated.  In  fact,  all  "economy"  was  once  "do- 
mestic economy." 

Max  Weber  has  noted  that  the  kinship  order  is  generally  com- 
prised of  sexually  enduring  communities  of  father,  mother,  and 
children.  Economic  functions,  although  historically  linked  with 
those  of  kinship,  can  of  course  be  analytically  separated  from 
them.  Conjugal  relations  and  parent-child  relations  are  based  on 
the  kinship  order,  but  purely  sexual  relations  are  highly  unstable 
and  problematic.  In  order  to  be  enduring,  they  must  be  instituted, 
and  they  have  most  frequently  been  instituted  with  reference  to 
economic  conditions.  Thus  the  father  must  provide  for  the  mother; 
and,  until  the  child  is  able  to  provide  for  himself,  the  mother  must 
so  provide.  Relations  between  siblings  are  not  necessarily  impor- 
tant until  they  involve  attachments  to  a  common  source  of  provi- 
sions. But  even  in  societies  where  men  are  bound  together  com- 
munally in  bachelor  quarters  for  military  and  economic  purposes, 
mother  and  children  are  likely  to  remain  in  common  residence. 

Marriage  can  only  be  defined  with  reference  to  larger  organiza- 
tions than  the  family;  accordingly  the  kinship  structure  is  usually 
a  dependent  order.  Marriage,  as  a  legitimate  sexual  relation,  pre- 
supposes larger  groups  which  sanction  the  relation,  against  the  will 

1-  On  tlie  relation  of  economic  functions  and  types  of  families,  see  Max- 
Weber,  The  Theory  of  Social  and  Economic  Organization,  Talcott  Parsons 
and  A.  M.  Henderson,  trs.  (New  York:  Oxford,  1948),  pp.  341-57-  See  also 
the  excellent  articles  by  Alfred  Meusel,  "National  Socialism  and  the  Family," 
The  Sociological  Review  (British),  Vol.  28,  1936,  pp.  166  fF.  and  389  ff.  "From 
an  economic  point  of  view  the  family  is  ( 1 )  an  institution  to  transmit  private 
property,  (2)  a  system  of  productive  relations  directed  by  patriarchal  au- 
thority" (page  167). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  24/ 

if  necessary  of  one  or  both  of  the  partners.  These  larger  groups 
which  thus  sanction  marriage— we  may  call  them  "frame  groups"— 
may  be  sib  or  clan,  or  of  political  or  economic,  religious  or  status 
nature.  Only  those  descendants  who  are  borne  as  full  members  of 
such  association  involved  may  consider  legitimate  marriage.  This 
is  the  sociological  meaning  of  legitimate  or  illegitimate  birth. 
There  must  be  agreement  by  the  frame  groups  and  certain  forms 
must  be  met.  Marriage  thus  takes  its  arrangement  and  content  from 
these  associations,  and  not  from  the  merely  sexual  relations  of  man 
and  woman,  or  the  rearing  of  children. 

Sexual  relations  are  economically  important  because  they  lead 
to  the  common  concerns  of  a  household.  The  household  requires 
a  degree  of  planned  production;  in  fact,  it  does  not  typically  exist 
in  preagricultural  societies.  But  the  household  is  central  in  a  so- 
ciety where  there  are  sedentary  agriculturalists  of  relatively  low 
technological  development.  When  agriculture  is- more  advanced, 
domestic  authority  is  placed  under  the  jurisdiction  of  larger  frame 
groups.  As  members  of  these  groups,  individuals  gain  more  rights 
as  family  members,  or  even  against  domestic  authority.  For  ex- 
ample, when  larger  associations  lend  rights  to  the  mother  of  the 
house  so  as  to  separate  her  property  from  that  of  the  husband, 
patriarchal  power  declines. 

The  household  is  the  most  widespread  economic  community,  and 
at  the  same  time  is  the  bedrock  of  piety  and  authority,  which,  in 
turn,  are  the  substructures  of  many  sentiments  involved  in  other 
institutional  orders.  For  the  cardinal  sentiment  of  the  domestic 
group  under  patriarchal  authority  is  a  strong  sense  of  piety,  which 
holds  it  together.  Patrimonial  duties  for  the  women,  and  filial  piety 
for  children  and  servants  complement  the  tradition-bound  author- 
ity of  the  patriarchal  head,  who  freely  bestows  his  favors  and  chas- 
tisements upon  his  "dependents."  In  extreme  cases— ancient  China 
is  the  great  example— this  filial  piety  is  elaborated  into  the  belief 
in  ancestral  spirits,  and  a  family  temple  implements  the  worship 
of  ancestors.  And  almost  everywhere  the  household  unit  stands 
for  in-group  solidarity,  for  common  residence  is  essential  to  the 
domestic  group  in  its  pure  type,  and  its  locale  is  accordingly  senti- 
mentalized and  the  object  of  nostalgic  and  xenophobic  attitudes. 

On  the  basis  of  piety  and  common  residence,  there  is  in  the 
household  a  communism  of  consumption  of  every  day  goods.  In 
the  economics  of  late  medieval  and  Renaissance  Italy,  business 


248  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

ventures  were  engaged  in  by  several  households,  which  are  thus 
prototypes  of  partnerships  and  joint  liability. 

For  all  their  importance,  we  do  not  consider  kinship  institutions 
as  more  "natural"  than  any  other  institutions.  The  bond  between 
mother  and  child  may  be  "natural,"  yet,  as  we  have  seen,  it  may 
be  up  to  the  father  to  determine  whose  offspring  shall  be  ascribed 
to  his  wife,  whether  her  own  or  her  maid's— witness  the  story  of 
Leah  and  Rachel.  Throughout  antiquity,  the  infanticide  of  un- 
wanted infants  was  accepted  as  "natural."  The  "legitimate  child" 
is  defined  to  be  such  by  the  rules  and  agents  of  the  kinship  orders, 
and  so  there  is  a  gap  between  "biology  and  human  nature"  which 
institutionalizes  the  roles  of  father  and  mother. 

In  industrial  and  urban  societies,  kinship  orders  have  tended 
towards  the  small,  two  generation  family,  consisting  of  parents  and 
children.  In  such  an  institution,  children  do  not  have  much  con- 
tact with  older  people,  and  respect  for  old  age  is  at  a  discount; 
even  the  patriarchal  image  of  Santa  Glaus  may  assume  the  char- 
acter of  just  another  funny  man. 

Today  in  America  more  people  are  married  than  was  previously 
the  case,  and  they  tend  to  marry  earlier.  Although  monogamy  is 
guaranteed  by  legal  and  religious  sanctions,  the  Kinsey  report  ^^ 
reveals  that  actual  conduct  deviates  widely  from  professed  norms 
and  moral  codes.  Even  if  we  make  allowances  for  shortcomings  in 
Kinsey's  technique,  and  even  if  the  figures  are  not  perfect,  the  pro- 
portions of  illicit  relations  are  impressive;  they  fit  too  well  with 
what  is  known  from  less  formal  data  to  be  written  off.  The  evi- 
dence shows  that  premarital  chastity  is  not  strictly  enforced  for 
women,  and  that  men  no  longer  place  decisive  weight  upon  it. 
The  emancipation  of  women,  and  the  dissemination  of  contracep- 
tive information,  has  brought  about  her  sexual  freedom.  For  them- 
selves, men  have  never  honored  the  demand  for  premarital  chas- 
tity; "sowing  one's  wild  oats"  has  been  tolerated  as  a  "natural 
privilege"  of  man.  The  monogamous  family,  in  the  meantime,  is 
psychologically  upheld,  positively  by  love,  negatively  by  the  "jeal- 
ousy" of  the  lover  against  any  threat  by  a  third  party  to  his  or  her 
exclusive  rights  to  the  erotical  services  of  the  partner.  Accordingly, 
where  jealousy  is  discounted  or  depreciated,  "monogamous  love" 
is  indirectly  threatened. 

13  Alfred  C.  Kinsey,  Wardell  B.  Pomeroy  and  Clyde  E.  Martin,  Sexual 
Behavior  in   the  lluinan   Male    (Philadelphia  and   London:    Saunders,    1948). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  24g 

The  combination  of  "love"  and  marriage  is  of  course  a  specifically 
modern  linkage.  We  know  from  Thomas's  and  Znaniecki's  study 
of  the  Polish  Peasant  in  Europe  and  America— and  we  may  gen- 
eralize the  point  for  the  Old  World  peasantry  at  large— that  mar- 
riage is  closely  connected  with  the  property  and  status  considera- 
tions of  the  two  families  who  are  to  be  linked  by  marriage.  The 
couples  themselves  are  not  euphorically  infatuated  with  one  an- 
other; on  the  contrary,  they  maintain  a  stylized  respect  in  which 
they  see  one  another  as  "members"  of  their  respective  families 
rather  than  as  heroized  individuals.  In  this,  the  peasant  family  is 
comparable  to  dynastic  and  noble  houses.  King  Edward  VHI  was 
not  permitted  to  be  king  and  also  to  marry  the  "woman  I  love." 
He  might  of  course  have  had  her  in  a  "lefthanded"  marriage,  or 
—possibly  as  a  royal  mistress— anything,  but  not  for  a  queen.  The 
case  is  interesting— as  Kingsley  Martin  in  The  Magic  of  Monarchy 
has  shown— for  its  revelations  of  the  status  sentiments  of  arrive 
bourgeois  society,  which  in  its  ascent  has  acquired  an  understand- 
ing of  proper  background  and  status  as  being  more  relevant  for 
marriage  than  the  "mere  love"  of  movie  fans  and  pulp  magazine 
readers. 

The  combination  of  modem  marriage  with  love  is  a  contribution 
of  the  rising  middle  classes.  Since  the  Italian  opera  and  the  eight- 
eenth-century British  novel,  this  linkage  has  been  glorified  and 
widely  diffused.  What,  by  the  way,  do  we  mean  by  "love"?  Cer- 
tainly more  than  mere  "sex,"  for  sexual  activity  and  gratification 
is  possible  without  "love."  If  sexual  impulse  is  culturally  stylized; 
if  it  is  spiritualized,  refined,  or  "sublimated,"  we  may  speak  of 
"eroticism."  Coquetry  and  flirtation  are  forms  of  erotic  playfulness. 
To  have  an  "affair,"  however,  still  falls  short  of  "true  love'"  in  that 
it  lacks  the  permanent  commitments  of  the  loving  partners. 

Just  as  we  find  types  of  marriages  without  "love,"  we  also  find 
true  love  relationships  without  marriage.  Ever  since  the  French 
Revolution,  in  fact,  the  institution  of  marriage  has  been  criticized 
in  the  name  of  "true  love,"  as  over  against  the  possibly  mercenary 
motives  leading  to  "marriage  without  love,"  or  the  marriage  a  la 
mode,  or  the  "marriage  of  convenience."  Anticapitalist  movements, 
socialists  and  anarchists  of  all  sorts,  including  Marx  and  Engels,  have 
criticized  marriage  without  love  as  "bad."  Here  is  a  recent  voice: 
"There  are  illicit  and  extramarital  relationships  which  are  in  reality 
more  moral  and  more  decent  than  those  often  found  in  marriage. 


2^^0  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

Love  without  marriage  is  in  its  essence  far  more  moral  than  mar- 
riage without  love."  "  Sometimes  status  inequalities  may  preclude 
marriage,  but  not  love;  occasionally  legal  barriers— for  instance  bar- 
riers against  the  emploxment  of  both  husband  and  wife  in  public 
employment,  or  on  the  same  teaching  staff— may  make  marriage 
"inexpedient"  for  the  lovers. 

We  thus  find  types  of  sexual  relations  consisting  of  ( i )  marriage 
combined  with  love,  (2)  love  without  marriage,  (3)  marriage  with- 
out love,  as  well  as  (4)  relations  outside  of  marriage  and  devoid 
of  love— the  transitory  "purely  sexual"  partnership  available  in 
houses  of  prostitution,  which  all  over  the  world  count  soldiers 
and  sailors,  traveling  salesmen  and  itinerant  artisans,  as  their  fore- 
most clientele. 

The  highest  ideal  of  the  modern  marriage  would  seem  to  in- 
volve the  following  elements:  (a)  the  permanent  and  exclusive 
attachment  of  the  partners  to  one  another,  "for  better  or  for  worse, 
in  sickness  or  in  health,"  the  attachment  implemented  by  a  sense 
of  moral  responsibility  for  one  another;  (b)  erotic  elements  pres- 
ent in  the  degree  to  which  the  partners  "charm"  one  another;  and 
(c)  sexual  gratification.  Where  the  puritan  ideal  of  "sobriety"  and 
the  ascetic  factor  remain  strong,  erotic  elements  are  suppressed 
as  "idolatry,"  or  as  creature  worship.  Women  must  not  "adorn 
themselves,"  must  not  be  proud  of  their  "beauty,"  either  in  appear- 
ance or  in  gestural  behavior;  dancing,  for  example,  is  out.  Vestiges 
of  puritan  society  survive  in  rural  America,  especially  in  small 
sectarian  communities  of  Mennonite  groups,  or  the  Old  Order 
Amish. 

Role-differences  between  men  and  women,  and  their  concomi- 
tant traits,  may  be  ascribed  to  presumably  "natural"  differences  of 
sex:  "Women  are  just  naturally  this  or  that"— "That's  just  the  way 
men  are.  .  .  ."  Philosophers,  from  the  time  of  Aristotle,  have  specu- 
lated on  "masculinity"  and  "femininity,"  in  terms  of  man  being 
rational  and  discreet,  women  being  "emotional"  and  given  to  "talka- 
tiveness." The  ideological  legacies  of  patriarchalism  and  of  male 
dominance  clearly  extend  into  Sigmund  Freud's  psychology,  which 
makes  "penis  envy"  the  hub  of  "feminine  character."  ^' 

1*  A.  L.  Wolbarst,  Generations  of  Adam  (New  York:  Stokes,  1930),  p.  240. 

^^  For  an  astute  analysis  of  the  \arious  ideologies  revealed  in  schools  of 
psychology,  see  Viola  Klein,  TJie  Feminine  Character  (New  York:  Interna- 
tional Univs.  Press,  1949). 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  25I 

4.  The  Educational  Sphere 

In  societies  which  allow  or  encourage  special  institutions  for  tlie 
transmission  of  skills  and  values  to  the  young,  we  may  speak  of  an 
educational  "order."  But  the  educational  sphere,  which  comprises 
schools  of  all  sorts,  is  rarely  autonomous,  which  is  why  we  call  it 
a  "sphere"  rather  than  an  "order."  ^'^ 

There  are  in  the  political  order,  party  schools  and  national  com- 
pulsory public  schools;  in  the  economic  order,  there  are  trade 
schools,  for  in-service  training;  in  the  religious  order,  sectarian 
schools,  as  well  as  official  schools  for  the  priesthood.  The  military 
order  has  its  own  military  academies;  and  the  kinship  order  has, 
for  a  long  time,  had  as  one  of  its  aspects  the  training  of  the  young. 
In  fact,  all  institutions  train  people  for  skills  and  loyalties. 

Nevertheless,  we  may  make  a  distinction  between  apprentice- 
ship—in which  the  novice  enters  a  respective  role  as  a  novice  to  be 
trained  as  well  as  to  work— and  formal  education  which  is  a  vicari- 
ous set  of  roles  available  outside  the  institutional  sphere  in  which 
the  student  will  eventually  play  them.  The  educational  sphere  is  thus 
a  world  of  models.  When  such  a  world  occurs  and  is  autonomously 
instituted,  we  have  an  educational  order.  Key  sociological  ques- 
tions about  education  include  the  following:  (1)  Who  gets  edu- 
cated? (2)  By  whom  are  they  educated?  (3)  How  are  they  edu- 
cated? (4)  For  what  roles  are  they  educated?  (5)  When  are  they 
educated?  (6)  Where  are  they  educated? 

Education  is  a  deliberate  attempt  to  transmit  skills  and  loyalties, 
as  well  as  forms  of  inner  cultivation  and  conventional  deportment 
required  by  status  group  membership.  All  education  aims  at  de- 
veloping loyalty  towards  the  educator  at  the  same  time,  for  he  is 
a  trustee  of  the  group  loyalties  which  he  \\'ould  impart.  In  a  society 
dominated  by  salon  ladies,  girls  go  to  finishing  schools;  public 
schools  in  England  turn  out  gentlemen  with  an  inner  sense  of  bear- 
ing and  dignity. 

16  See  Thorstein  Veblen,  The  Higher  Learning  in  America  (New  York: 
Viking,  1918);  I.  L.  Kandel,  Essays  in  Comparative  Education  (New  York: 
Teachers  College,  1930);  E.  H.  Reisner,  Nationalism  and  Education  Since 
1789  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1922);  and  Walter  M.  Kotschnig,  Unemploy- 
ment in  the  Learned  Professions  (London:   Oxford,   1937). 


2^2  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

In  a  very  general  way,  we  may  speak  with  Max  Weber  of  three 
types  of  education:  first,  the  attempt  to  call  forth  and  to  test 
allegedly  inherent  traits  of  the  individual,  to  allow  them  to  un- 
fold, to  be  realized.^'  This  is  generally  characteristic  of  charismati- 
cally  sanctioned  institutions  and  status  groups.  Second,  by  rote 
learning  and  moral  exhortation,  by  drill  and  imposed  habituation, 
the  attempt  to  stereotype  the  individual  into  line  with  tradi- 
tional routines,  which  is  generally  characteristic  of  traditionalist  so- 
cieties. Third,  the  attempt  rationally  to  transmit  to  the  individual 
certain  traits,  to  train  him  for  specific  skills  by  challenging  him  to 
think  and  act  independently— which  is  generally  characteristic  of 
educational  spheres  of  rational  bureaucratic  organizations. 

/ 

In  the  occidental  Middle  Ages,  traditionalist  educational  insti- 
tutions were  attached  to  the  religious  order,  to  the  upper-class 
household  of  the  warrior  noble,  to  the  middle-class  household,  and 
to  the  workshop  of  the  guild  master.  Nowadays,  rationalist  educa- 
tional spheres  are  attached  to  political  institutions,  as  in  "public 
school  systems,"  as  well  as  to  the  religious  order,  as  in  parochial 
schools.  Modern  totalitarian  regimes  attach  part  of  their  educa- 
tional spheres— charismatically  oriented— by  means  of  youth  or- 
ganizations, to  the  ruling  party.  There  was  thus  the  Hitler  Youth, 
and  there  are  the  Communist  youth  organizations  in  the  Soviet 
Union  and  other  states  of  the  Soviet  bloc.  Special  educational 
spheres  of  varied  sorts  in  different  social  structures  may  thus  be 
attached  to  religious,  military,  economic,  and  other  institutional 
orders. 

Only  under  quite  special  conditions  do  professional  educators 
emancipate  themselves  from  the  control  of  superordinate  institu- 
tional orders.  The  situation  of  "private  universities,"  like  Harvard 
or  Oxford,  Yale  or  Cambridge;  of  independent  artists'  studios;  of 
various  types  of  contemporary  progressive  schools;  of  the  Athenian 
philosophers'  "circle  of  disciples"— these  are  rather  the  exception 
than  the  rule. 

In  the  United  States  in  the  middle  of  the  twentieth  century,  some 
84  per  cent  of  all  schools  are  elementary,  6  per  cent  of  them  being 
"private";  15  per  cent  are  secondary  schools,  4  per  cent  of  them 
being  private;  only  1  per  cent  of  all  schools  are  colleges,  universi- 

1^  See  From  Max  Weber,  op.  cit.,  p.  426. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  2.53 

ties,  or  professional  schools,  but  65  per  cent  of  them  are  "private."  '" 
It  is  characteristic  of  the  United  States  that  elementary  education 
rests  in  the  hands  of  853,967  "schoolma'ams"  who  do  not  always 
make  education  their  permanent  careers,  teaching  in  the  interval 
between  the  family  of  their  descent  and  that  of  procreation.''' 

Because  of  the  steady  increase  of  educational  requirements  for 
an  increasing  range  of  specialized  occupations,  the  opportimities 
to  climb  the  ladder  of  occupational  success  becomes  more  and 
more  dependent  upon  education.  During  the  last  half  century  the 
educational  level  of  the  American  people  has  risen  accordingly; 
enrollment  figures  indicate  that  in  1900  some  94,883  adolescents 
graduated  from  high  schools,  but  by  1940  their  number  had  in- 
creased to  1,221,475.-"  This  impressixe  quest  for  higher  education 
is  not  due  to  any  sudden  outburst  of  intellectual  enthusiasm  but 
may  lai'gely  be  attributed  to  the  function  of  education  as  a  "social 
elevator"  in  an  epoch  of  scarcity-consciousness  and  social  fence- 
building.  Degrees  have  become  indispensable  for  entrance  into 
preferred  occupations.  Yet,  at  the  same  time,  many  people  have 
come  to  realize  that  education  alone  is  not  enough  for  "success." 
The  bitter  phrase— "it's  not  what  you  know  but  whom  you  know" 
—is  indicative.  The  traditional  Jeffersonian  optimism  about  educa- 
tion as  the  answer  has  given  way  to  an  increasing  tendency  to 
view  educational  policies  in  connection  with  social  stratification, 
and  to  assess  educational  goals  statistically  in  terms  of  their  func- 
tion for  later  adult  life. 

Since  the  great  depression,  there  has  been  an  awareness  of  social 
rigidities  and  institutional  strains  in  the  United  States.  This  aware- 
ness has  been  reflected  in  a  vogue  of  inquiries  into  the  function  of 
the  school  in  a  democratic  society,  and  the  worthwhileness  of  edu- 
cation as  an  investment  of  long  years  for  hopes  of  social  ascent. 
Yet  the  gulf  between  the  educated  and  the  uneducated  in  the 
United  States  is  not  felt  so  deeply  as  it  is  in  Europe,  or,  in  fact, 
is  not  felt  to  be  a  gulf  at  all.  To  American  eyes,  a  smooth  broad 
ascent  leads  from  elementary  to  higher  education.  And,  on  the 
whole,  the  smooth  gradation  of  institutions  of  higher  learning— 
from  the  best  to  the  not-so-good;  from  lower  grades  to  higher— 

1^  Computed  from  The  World  Ahuanac,   1951,  P-  580. 
^^Cf.  Frances  Dono\an,  The  Schoolmaam   (New  York:   Stokes,   1938). 
20  Table    154,    Statistical   Abstract   of   the    United   States,    1947,    Washing- 
ton, D.  C. 


254  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

and  the  readiness  of  American  educators  to  teach  new  subjects  as 
well  as  popular  hobbies  and  fads,  have  made  for  a  successful  link- 
age of  higher  education  and  the  population  at  large. 

The  demand  of  the  state  and  of  corporations  for  trained  civil 
servants  and  qualified  experts  of  all  sorts  has  been  decisive  for  the 
modern  development  of  universities.  The  displacement  of  patron- 
age and  spoils  systems  by  the  "merit  system,"  and  the  decline  of 
administration  by  amateurs,  however  high-minded  and  notable, 
has  been  one  result  of  this.  Lorenz  von  Stein  correctly  called  the 
modern  university  "a  school  for  bureaucrats."  Germany  is  a  neat 
case  in  point.^^ 

During  the  late  eighteenth  century,  German  princes  "reformed" 
the  universities,  using  Gottingen  as  the  model.  The  universities  of 
Bonn  and  Berlin  were  founded  during  the  Napoleonic  era,  which 
also  witnessed  the  establishment  of  engineering  colleges  in  Ger- 
many. With  industrialization  and  the  expansion  of  administrative 
functions  of  all  sorts,  universities  were  shaped  to  answer  the  needs 
of  a  more  complex  and  swiftly  urbanized  society.  At  the  same  time, 
they  became  social  elevators  for  the  middle  classes.  Of  course,  wage 
workers  and  small-holding  peasants  were  sidetracked  from  that 
educational  ladder  that  led  to  the  university,  being  given  instead 
vocational  training,  which  was  combined  with  apprenticeship  sys- 
tems, first  in  quasi-guilds  of  craftsmen,  and  later  in  big  industries. 

Under  the  Weimar  Republic— in  fact  through  1935— a  sociologi- 
cally-minded census  was  taken  of  university  students.  This  census 
provides  unique  data  on  the  social  composition  of  the  student 
body  in  the  twenty-five  state  universities  of  a  major  industrial  na- 
tion. In  the  years  between  1928  and  1935,  about  one-third  of  the 
students  came  from  upper-class  homes;  about  60  per  cent  from  a 
middle-class  background;  and  only  between  4  and  8  per  cent  from 
lower-class  families.  Over  half  of  the  students  were  the  sons  of 
officials,  army  officers,  or  professional  men.  The  universities  thus 
served  as  a  means  for  the  hereditary  appropriation  of  bureaucratic 
positions.  Despite  broad  discussions  of  university  reform  in  post- 

■-'  For  details  on  school  enrollments  in  Germany,  see  Deutsche  HochscJnil- 
statistik  and  Die  Deutschen  lloclischulen,  Eine  Uebersicht  ueber  ihren  Besuch 
(Berlin,  1936);  ct.  also  Hans  II.  Gerth,  "Germany  on  the  Eve  of  Occupation," 
Problems  of  the  Postwar  World,  T.  C.  McCormick,  ed.  (New  York:  McGraw- 
Hill,  1945),  pp.  422  ff. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  2,55 

World  War  II  Germany,  as  far  as  the  question  "who  shall  study" 
is  concerned,  nothing  essential  has  been  changed  in  Western 
Germany.  The  enrollment  of  the  University  of  Miinster,  in  West- 
phalia in  1947,  conformed  almost  to  the  decimal  point  to  the  old 
picture. 

In  Eastern  Germany  under  Russian  rule  there  has  been  a  speed- 
up of  education  developments,  in  accordance  with  tlie  model  of 
the  Soviet  Union  itself.  The  over-all  slogan  is  "cadre  training," 
which  in  sociological  translation  means  the  displacement  of  all 
elites  by  loyal  communist  vanguards. 

Eastern  Germany  is  typical  of  all  totalitarian  regimes.  Family 
influence  is  weakened  by  remo\ing  young  children  from  their 
homes  and  placing  them  in  publicly  sponsored  kindergartens.  The 
number  of  kindergarten  schools,  teachers,  and  students  has  greatly 
increased  since  1946.'-  This  development  provides  young  women 
with  semiprofessional  opportunities;  communist  aspirants  from 
lower  classes  can  readily  be  found  and  properly  indoctrinated  in 
the  new  loyalties.  The  kindergarten  development  also  permits  the 
increasing  employment  of  housewives  in  industry. 

Whereas  the  wealthy  formerly  sent  their  children  to  private 
schools,  now  private  schools  have  been  abolished.  Whereas  middle- 
and  upper-class  children  once  were  separated  from  lower-class 
children  after  four  years  of  elementary  education,  they  are  now 
separated  only  after  eight  years  of  public  school  education.  A 
minority  of  fee-paying  students  used  to  attend  high  school  from 
the  time  they  were  ten  until  they  were  eighteen  years  of  age;  they 
then  passed  a  stiff  examination  which  was  a  prerequisite  for  uni- 
versity attendance.  Under  Soviet  occupation,  most  children  now 
leave  school  at  the  age  of  fourteen,  and  those  who  wish  to  be 
apprenticed  as  "skilled  workers"  have  to  attend  a  vocational  school 
once  a  week. 

By  August  1949,  the  top  administrator  of  Eastern  Zone  schools 
stated  that  of  the  65,000  teachers  80  per  cent  were  "new  teachers."  '^ 

--  On  schools  in  Eastern  Germany,  see  Annemarie  Jacobs,  "Der  Kinder- 
garten als  Vorstufe  der  Einheitsschule,"  Die  Deutsche  demokratische  Schule 
im  Aufhau  (Berlin,  1949),  p.  7.  Der  Fiinfjahrplan  zur  Entwicklung  der 
Volkswirtschaft  der  DDR    (1951-1955),  Infonnationsdienst   (Berlin,  n.d.). 

-3  These  facts  and  figures  are  taken  from  various  East  German  pubhcations, 
cited  by  Erich  Hoffman,  Cadre  Training  in  East  Germany  (unpublished  MA 
thesis.  University  of  Wisconsin,   1952). 


2^6  SOCIi^L     STRUCTURE 

All  teachers  must  be  organized  in  various  communist  organiza- 
tions, and  naturally  party  membership,  though  not  compulsory, 
suggests  itself  to  the  ambitious  young  teachers.  The  universities 
offer  compulsory  training  courses  for  teachers  in  Marxism-Lenin- 
ism, and  at  all  schools  have  been  formed  communist  teachers' 
groups  which  are  affiliated  with  the  Communist  Youth.  All  educa- 
tional institutions,  in  fact,  are  a  sphere  of  party-controlled  insti- 
tutions. 

All  university  students  in  Eastern  Germany  receive  a  monthly 
salary,  which  is  graded  by  class  background  and  political  activity 
in  favor  of  the  active  communistic,  working-class  student.  Working- 
class  sons  made  up  40  per  cent  of  the  student  body  by  1949.  The 
total  student  body  has  been  considerably  expanded,  and  although 
standards  of  instruction  and  learning  have  been  considerably  low- 
ered, a  new  plebeian  intelligentsia  is  emerging  which  fills  the  ranks 
and  the  offices  of  the  completely  remodeled  bureaucracies.  The 
impressive  mass  euphoria  of  the  two  and  one  half  million  youths 
who  in  May  1951  were  concentrated  in  Berlin  to  march  behind 
Stalin  posters  may  in  large  part  be  ascribed  to  the  opportunities 
open  to  working-class  youth  under  such  policies.  Thus  may  the 
educational  sphere  be  linked  with  dominant  political  and  eco- 
nomic institutions. 

5.  Types  of  Social  Control 

In  the  institutional  orders  and  spheres  of  various  societies  we 
observe  certain  uniformities  of  social  conduct  which  represent 
conformities  with  expected  patterns,  and  may  thus  be  said  to  be 
"socially  controlled."  The  major  types  and  bases  of  such  social 
controls  may  also  be  classified  according  to  their  subjective  mean- 
ings to  the  individual  actors  involved,  and  according  to  the  types 
of  sanctions,  if  any,  employed  against  people  who  deviate  from 
them.2* 

I.  A  custom,  or  a  folkway,  is  a  pattern  of  conduct  which  rests 
upon  long  familiarity.  If  people  do  not  follow  such  rules  no  exter- 

24  The  essentials  of  the  definitions  gixen  below  are  abstracted  and  para- 
phrased from  various  contexts  of  Max  Weber.  Cf.  also,  Karl  Mannheim,  Man 
and  Society  in  an  Age  of  Reconstruction  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1940), 
pp.  311-66. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  2$-/ 

nal  sanctions  will  be  called  into  play,  although  they  may  be  incon- 
venienced. People  may  not  even  be  conscious  of  these  customs; 
if  they  are,  they  may  merely  feel  that  it  is  more  comfortable  to 
conform  than  not  to  do  so.  Thus,  although  conformity  is  not 
"demanded"  by  anybody,  there  is  a  general  expectation  that  peo- 
ple will  do  the  usual  things,  and  this  in  itself  makes  for  the  stabil- 
ity of  the  custom. 

The  routine  metropolitan  day  involves  the  interlocking  of  many 
activities;  it  is  customary  to  adapt  to  this  routine.  The  times  for 
meals,  the  lunch  hour  for  example,  are  of  consequence  for  the  rush- 
hour  traffic,  and  for  peaks  of  demand  on  restaurants  and  news- 
paper stands.  The  stray  latecomer  may  be  inconvenienced:  this  or 
that  item  on  the  menu  "is  out."  Other  restaurants,  in  turn,  adver- 
tise "meals  served  at  all  hours"  for  the  irregular  patron.  Economi- 
cally determined  routines  of  urban  mass  life  make  for  an  adjust- 
ment of  the  program  structures  of  the  mass  media  to  the  peak 
availability  of  specific  mass  publics  and  audiences.  The  statisti- 
cally calculated  coverage  of  leisure-time  hours  by  mass  media  of 
communication  and  other  machinery  of  amusement— radio's  soap 
opera  for  housewives  weekday  afternoons.  Metropolitan  Opera 
Saturday  afternoons,  NBC  symphony  concerts  Sunday  afternoons 
—contributes  to  rigidly  disciplined,  routinized,  and  therefore  pre- 
dictable patterns  of  customary  mass  behavior. 

In  continental  Europe  the  sharper  differences  in  the  ways  of  life 
of  diverse  classes  and  status  groups— folkways  of  village  peasants 
as  against  urban  factory  workers,  of  academicians  as  against  bo- 
hemian  artists  and  intellectuals,  of  salesladies  and  other  white-collar 
groups  as  against  civil  servants  and  their  wives,  of  rural  nobles 
and  ladies  of  leisure  as  against  artisans  and  craftsmen— these  status 
differences  make  for  greater  diversity  of  routinized  schedules.  The 
parallel  habituations  of  millions  who  adjust  and  accommodate  to 
the  customary  ways  of  doing  things  result  in  regularities  of  be- 
havior which  have  caused  thoughtful  men  such  as  Lord  Bryce  to 
posit  inertia  as  one  of  the  fundamental  traits  of  man.  Social  and 
personality  change  stands  out  in  such  a  perspective  as  the  excep- 
tion demanding  explanation.  Both  the  tradition-bound  folkways  of 
agrarian  societies  and  the  interlocking  matrix  of  time-clocked 
metropolitan  ways  of  life,  in  work  and  in  leisure,  seem  to  result  in 
equally  predictable  stability  of  what  man  takes  for  granted  as  the 
usual  thing,  as  the  realm  of  the  customary. 


2^8  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

II,  Fashion  is  a  usage  which  rests  on  appreciation  of  new 
appearance  vakies  as  indicative  of  status  claims  in  a  dynamic  and 
stratified  societ>'.  Fashions  are  new  enough  to  be  discernibly  dif- 
ferent from  "last  year's  model,"  yet  old  enough  so  as  not  to  affront 
conventions  of  propriety. 

Both  fashion  and  conventions,  which  we  shall  presently  con- 
sider, usually  rest  upon  claims  _  of  prestige;  when  internalized 
they  are  obeyed  because  of  expectations  as  to_what  is  "proper," 
or  what  is  "smart,"  :which  means  what  is  accepted  in  the  style  of  life 
of  given  stafus  groups. 

III.  In  the  case  of  the  customary  you  may  "take  it  or  leave  it"— 
part  your  hair  on  the  right  or  the  left  side,  eat  your  soup  with  or 
without  salt— but  this  is  not  true  of  "conventions"  or,  as  William 
Graham  Sumner  termed  them,  "the  mores."  Conventions  are  more 
exacting  than  customs,  for  they  rest  upon  the  expectation  that 
deviation  from  them  will  result  in  a  general  reaction  of  disap- 
proval. Conventions  are  generally  recognized  as  binding,  or  at  least 
definitely  expected,  and  are  protected  against  violation  by  sanc- 
tions of  disapproval,  including  informal  boycott  and  ostracism. 
Convention  is  the  "respectable  thing  to  do"  at  the  right  time  and 
the  right  place,  as  against  the  things  that  "one  just  doesn't  do." 

The  "enforcement  agency"  for  conventions  is  not  a  specialized 
staff,  but  rather  community  opinion  at  large,  or  at  least  the  opin- 
ions of  one's  status  circle.  The  expectations  of  general  disapproval, 
if  one  breaks  with  convention,  may  be  internalized,  and  then 
form  part  of  the  generalized  other,  which  thus  operates  as  a  fur- 
ther psychological  motive  for  conventional  conformity.  The  motive 
for  adherence  to  convention,  as  to  fashion,  thus  involves  one's 
status  or  prestige,  for  the  violation  of  deeply  internalized  conven- 
tions may  lead  to  loss  of  self-esteem  or  self-respect. 

Different  ways  of  life  are  shot  through  with  conventions  which 
all  sorts  of  groups,  communities,  and  institutions  consider  as  bind- 
ing for  their  members.  Body  hygiene  in  America  is  subject  to  con- 
ventional standards  of  cleanliness  and  propriety— we  use  tooth- 
brushes, mouth  wash,  and  handkerchiefs,  and  we  control  body 
odor  by  use  of  soap  and  perfume.  The  enjoyment  of  meals  is  a 
purely  biological  process  only  in  extreme  situations;  usually,  we 
eat  just  as  much  with  our  eyes  and  ears  as  with  our  mouths.  Hence, 
table  manners  and  codes  of  propriety  and  esthetics  serve  to  facili- 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  259 

tate  our  appetites  and  our  ways  of  "setting  the  table,"  of  using  our 
knife,  fork,  and  spoon  in  the  proper  ways,  of  taking  in  the  proper 
amount  of  the  proper  food  at  the  proper  tempo.  We  learn  to  sup- 
press vulgar  noises  by  chewing  with  our  lips  closed. 

There  are  standards  of  sociabilit>%  controlling,  for  example,  the 
preferable,  permissible,  and  tabooed  subjects  for  light  or  serious 
conversations  and  requiring  us  to  be  sensitive  to  the  personal 
tempo  of  our  partner's  responsiveness  of  thought  and  feeling.  The 
demand  to  be  "tactful"  forms  part  of  the  conventional  code  of 
"polite"  behavior.  Most  of  these  conventions  have  been  elaborated 
by  occidental  court  nobilities.  The  very  words  used  for  courteous 
deportment— "curtsy"  and  "courtship,"  for  example— remind  us  of 
their  social-historical  origin:  to  behave  as  people  do  at  court. 
Where  such  conventions  become  rigid  and  complex  we  speak  of 
"codes  of  etiquette."  In  formal  contexts,  such  as  diplomatic  func- 
tions, or  state  dinners  in  high  society,  there  may  be  a  specialist— 
the  chief  of  protocol— who  devotes  his  professional  skill  to  ques- 
tions of  etiquette,  determining  who  should  be  invited  to  what 
functions,  who  might  take  offense  at  being  "overlooked,"  who 
can  be  left  out  without  harm,  who  shall  sit  where,  and  so  on. 

The  best  sellers  of  Mrs.  Emily  Post  and  Miss  Lillian  Eichler 
during  the  last  thirty  years  indicate  the  spread  of  certain  conven- 
tions of  high  society,  prevailing  about  1900,  to  the  growing  mid- 
dle classes.-^ 

Forms  of  intimacy  are  conventionally  stylized  to  guarantee  what 
we  demand  as  our  "right  to  privacy"  even  from  our  marriage  part- 
ner or  lover.  To  be  sure,  in  the  euphoric  phase  of  courtship  we 
seek  to  minimize  all  social  distance,  taking  offense  and  feeling 
hurt  at  every  distancing  response  of  the  intimate  other. 

The  "conventional  lie"  serves  the  purpose  of  securing  "distance" 
from  the  other.  "Tell  him  I  am  not  at  home"  hurts  less  than  the 
candid  "I  don't  wish  to  see  him."  "Young  man,  you  are  a  genius 
and  I  am  afraid  this  job  does  not  give  the  proper  opportiuiity  to 
your  talents"  hurts  less  than  "You  are  fired,"  although  the  occupa- 
tional results  are  of  course  the  same. 

2t  Lillian  Eichler's  The  Book  of  Etiquette  sold  over  a  million  copies  between 
1921  and  1945,  Emily  Post's  Etiquette  from  1922  to  1945  sold  more  than  two- 
thirds  of  a  million  copies.  Cf.  Arthur  M.  Schlcsinger,  Learning  How  to  Behave 
(New  York:  Macmillan,  1946);  and  Edmund  Wilson,  Classics  and  Commer- 
cials (New  York:  Farrar,  Straus,  1950),  pp.  372-82. 


26o  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

IV.  Law,  as  a  type  of  social  control,  is  distinguished  by  two 
features:  First,  as  a  pattern  of  conduct  it  is  upheld  by  the  fact 
that  deviation  will  probably  be  met  by  sanctions  aimed  at  com- 
pelling conformity  or  by  punishment.  Second,  these  sanctions  are 
applied  by  a  staff  of  agents  who  are  especially  empowered  to  carry 
out  this  function.  It  is  clear  that  in  this  rather  broad  sense,  "law" 
may  exist  in  any  institutional  order;  in  modern  societies,  how- 
ever, the  legal  order  of  the  state  is  the  most  inclusive  in  jurisdiction. 

The  state,  as  the  most  powerful  organization  of  contemporary 
social  structures,  regulates  through  its  legal  apparatus  the  power 
that  may  be  wielded  by  and  in  other  institutions.  Thus  a  husband 
may  use  force  against  his  children  or  against  his  wife  only  to  the 
extent  that  administrative  agents  and  courts  permit  it.  In  some 
parts  of  the  United  States,  divorces  are  granted  for  slight  cases 
of  "mental  cruelty";  in  other  nations,  the  husband  or  the  wife  just 
has  "to  take  it."  A  schoolteacher's  use  of  the  rod  may  be  outlawed 
or  at  least  restricted  by  agents  of  the  state.  The  laws  of  the  state 
mediate  between  the  politically  determined  distribution  of  power 
and  the  economic  order,  for  the  legal  apparatus  defines  disposi- 
tions over  goods  and  services  and  other  "assets"  by  the  "owners" 
of  goods  and  the  employers  of  men.  It  is  one  of  the  main  functions 
of  law  to  guarantee,  define,  and  endorse  rights  over  "property"— 
public,  joint,  and  private. 

Laws  differ  from  conventions  in  that  they  are  enforced  by  a 
staff.  In  the  case  of  deviation  from  conventions  anyone  may  ex- 
press disapproval,  anyone  may  apply  the  sanction  and  thus  publicly 
represent  the  generalized  other.  Institutional  patterns  per  se,  as 
we  have  seen,  are  guaranteed  by  an  authoritative  other,  the  head 
of  the  institution.  Law,  as  one  type  of  institutional  control,  involves 
a  specialized  staff.  Or,  in  other  terms,  orientation  to  conventions, 
as  Emile  Durkheim  and  Max  Weber  have  pointed  out,  is  guaran- 
teed by  socially  diffuse  sanctions,  whereas  orientation  to  legal 
codes  is  guaranteed  by  organized  sanctions.  In  the  case  of  con- 
vention, any  member  of  a  given  group  or  institution  may  volun- 
teer to  "punish"  a  breach  of  conventional  proprieties,  of  standards 
of  hygiene,  of  beauty,  or  truthfulness.  In  the  case  of  law,  it  is  the 
agents  or  agencies  of  law  enforcement  that  may  take  action.  As 
Justice  Holmes  said,  "The  prophecies  of  what  the  courts  will  do  in 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  261 

fact,  and  nothing  more  pretentious,  are  what  I  mean  by  the  law."  ^^^ 
Even  in  BibHcal  days,  we  hear  of  the  elders  and  judges  sitting 
"at  the  gates,"  that  is,  holding  court  on  the  town  squares  behind 
the  city  gates.  One  of  the  great  legacies  of  ancient  Rome  are  the 
■Roman  Digests"  which  inform  the  "canonical  law"  of  the  Roman 
Catholic  Church,  as  well  as  Anglo-Saxon  law,  and  which  stand 
back  of  modern  legal  codes.  Among  these  modern  codes,  the  Code 
Napoleon  has  found  the  widest  diffusion  and  the  greatest  author- 
ity because  of  its  lucidity  and  simplicity.  On  the  European  conti- 
nent legal  education  became  a  university  subject  at  an  early  time. 
In  the  Anglo-Saxon  tradition,  the  bar,  essentially  a  guild  of  the 

-'"^^  Oliver  Wendell  Holmes,  Collected  Legal  Papers  (New  York:  Harcourt, 
Brace,  1921),  p.  167.  Especially  pertinent  for  the  social  scientist  are  the  essays 
of  Roscoe  Pound,  "Interests  of  Personality,"  28  Harv.  L.  Rev.,  pp.  343,  445 
(1915);  "A  Survey  of  Social  Interests,"  57  Harv.  L.  Rev.,  p.  1  (1943);  "A 
Survey  of  Public  Interests,"  58  Harv.  L.  Rev.,  p.  909  (1945);  "The  Lay  Tra- 
dition as  to  the  Lawyer,"  Mich.  L.  Rev.,  Vol.  XII,  No.  8  (June  1914);  "The 
Causes  of  Popular  Dissatisfaction  with  the  Administration  of  Justice,"  Trans- 
actions of  the  American  Bar  Association  (1906);  "Common  Law  and  Legisla- 
tion," Harv.  L.  Rev.,  Vol.  XXI,  p.  383  (  1908).  For  his  survey  of  tlie  "Sociology 
of  Law"  see  Twentieth  Century  Sociology,  ed.  by  Georges  Gurvitch  and  Wil- 
bert  E.  Moore  (New  York:  Philosophical  Library,  1945),  pp.  297-341.  Social 
Control  Through  Law  (New  Haven:  Yale  Univ.  Press,  1942)  presents  a  sum- 
mary statement  of  the  "Dean  of  American  Jurisprudence."  Simpson  and  others 
in  their  three-volume  Cases  and  Readings  on  Law  and  Society  (St.  Paul,  Minn.: 
West,  1948-49)  have  attempted  to  do  what  has  been  so  much  talked  about— 
correlate  law  with  the  social  sciences.  Of  special  value  to  the  social  scientist 
are  the  essays  of  K.  Llewellyn.  See  "Law  and  the  Social  Sciences— Especially 
Sociology,"  Harv.  L.  Rev.,  Vol.  62,  p.  1286  (1949). 

The  best  one-volume  history  of  American  legal  institutions  in  the  perspective 
of  social  history  seems  to  us  to  be  Willard  Hurst's  The  Growth  of  American 
Law  (Boston:  Little,  Brown,  1950).  A  translation  by  Max  Rheinstein  of  Max 
Weber's  monumental  Sociology  of  Law  is  due  to  be  published  soon  by  the 
Hanard  Uni\ersity  Press. 

Gi\  en  the  instability  of  the  American  family  and  the  wide  interest  of  social 
scientists  in  family  and  personality  problems,  we  may  draw  attention  to  the 
recent  symposium  of  the  Conference  on  Divorce,  February  29,  1952,  The  Law 
School  of  the  University  of  Chicago  Conference  Series,  No.  9.  Cf.  especially 
the  brilliant  paper  of  Max  Rheinstein,  "Our  Dual  Law  of  Divorce:  The  Law  in 
Action  \ersus  the  Law  of  the  Books,"  pp.  39-47.  The  linkage  between  the 
psychopathology  of  behaxior  disorders  and  the  law  is  well  presented  in  Man- 
fred S.  Guttmacher  and  Henry  Weihofen's  Fsychiutry  and  the  Law  (New  York: 
Norton,  1952). 


262  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

legal  profession,  has  for  centuries  retained  the  transmission  of 
skills  and  knowledge  in  the  form  of  legal  apprenticeship.  University 
training  has  moved  in  the  direction  of  textbook  systematization; 
apprenticeship  has  retained  close  contact  with  legal  practice. 

Conventions  and  laws  may  be  quite  intricately  related,  but, 
briefly,  here  are  four  broad,  possible  combinations :  ( 1 )  A  con- 
vention may  be  guaranteed  by  law,  as  in  the  case  with  most  ordi- 
nances enforcing  proprieties  of  dress  in  public.  (2)  Both  the  legal 
staff  and  the  public  may  co-operate  in  suppressing  "crimes"  against 
person  and  property.  (3)  A  convention  may  rule  out  a  legal  con- 
duct pattern.  In  Tsarist  Russia,  for  example,  it  was  a  widespread 
popular  convention  to  protect  revolutionary  intellectuals  against 
the  police,  that  is,  "denunciation"  in  accordance  with  the  law  was 
conventionally  tabooed.  It  was  considered  "dishonorable"  to  de- 
nounce a  revolutionary.  Hence,  the  political  fugitive  from  the  law 
could  "vanish  among  the  people."  (4)  A  legal  code  may  conflict 
with  a  convention,  i.e.,  the  lawmaker  may  seek  to  "break  up"  a 
conventional  code  of  conduct.  Thus  the  Volstead  Act  was  an  at- 
tempt to  "outlaw"  drink.  Conventional  behavior  proved  stronger, 
to  the  point  where  the  law  was  repealed.  In  Europe,  laws  against 
dueling  have  by  and  large  proved  effective— although  army  offi- 
cers, nobles,  and  some  student  fraternities,  in  Germany  for  in- 
stance, take  a  chance  and  surreptitiously  tiansgress  the  law. 

If  there  is  general  moral  indignation  about  someone's  breaking 
with  an  institutional  pattern,  we  may  say  that  conventions  buttress 
institutional  controls.  Institutional  roles,  however,  may  or  may  not 
be  thus  upheld  by  conventions.  What  is  essential  to  the  institution 
is  that  the  roles  it  organizes  are  upheld  by  the  power  of  the  head 
over  institutional  members. 

Legal  sanctions  may  be  differently  applied  to  persons  of  differ- 
ent social  standing.  Where  justice  involves  the  "bail"  and  legal 
counsel  is  costly,  for  example,  lower-income  groups  are  automati- 
cally at  a  disadvantage.  The  motives  for  conformity  to  law  range 
from  calculations  and  fear  of  possible  sanctions  to  an  absolute 
belief  in  the  justice  or  other  ethical  qualities  of  the  law.  The  con- 
victed offender  may  feel  deeply  guilty,  or  he  may  feel  himself 
to  be  the  innocent  victim  of  a  "miscarriage  of  justice."  Either  ex- 
treme of  attitude  may  of  course  deviate  widely  from  what  the  facts 
warrant.    Some   people   may  take   into   account   what   courts   are 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  26;^ 

likely  to  enforce  as  a  rationally  calculated  cost  factor;  others  may 
view  the  law  in  all  its  majesty  with  simple  awe. 

Vigilantes,  who  "take  the  law  into  their  own  hands,"  or  the 
hooded  men  of  the  Ku  Klux  Klan,  who  practice  "lynch  justice," 
usurp  the  public  prerogative  of  applying  violent  and  coercive 
sanctions.  Where  public  authorities  do  not  care  to  repress  the  de- 
nial of  justice  to  the  underprivileged,  we  encounter  situations 
where  conventional  violence  is  honored  by  men  who  do  not  trust 
the  law  to  "take  its  course." 

Responsibility  for  a  breach  of  law  or  convention  may  be  ascribed 
informally,  or  by  widely  different  trial  procedures  with  varying 
rules  of  evidence,  to  the  individual  actor  or  to  one  of  his  com- 
munity, family,  sex  group,  age  class,  school  class,  status  group, 
army  unit,  mass  organization,  or  nation.  Accordingly,  we  speak  of 
personal  or  of  joint  responsibility,  of  individual  or  of  collective 
guilt.  In  one  African  tribe,  the  Ila,  all  of  the  male  population  "may 
be  held  responsible  for  any  disparagement  by  the  women  of  the 
group."  -*'  The  rules  of  conduct  are  thus  enforced  by  a  sexual 
group.  Moreover,  the  sanctions  are  not  directed  against  the  indi- 
vidual directly  "responsible"  for  the  breach  but  must  be  borne  by 
the  entire  male  population.  Still  another  case  is  found  in  the  pat- 
terns of  the  old  Japanese  Kumi,  in  which  some  five  family  heads 
were  jointly  responsible  for  public  work  and  tax  quotas.  If  any 
one  of  these  five  ran  away  from  the  village,  the  other  four  had 
to  make  up  his  work.  Similar  conditions  of  joint  liability  existed  in 
the  Mir,  the  village  commune  of  Tsarist  Russia,  as  well  as  in 
ancient  China. 

Max  Weber  has  distinguished  three  main  types  of  legal  adminis- 
trations and  staffs,  which  parallel  his  types  of  political  authority 
and  his  types  of  education:  charismatic,  traditionalist,  and  ration- 
ally bureaucratic. 

A.  The  law  of  the  charismatic  leader  is  the  law  of  the  leader's 
will.  The  justice  of  charismatic  leaders  is  always  "emergency  jus- 
tice"; it  is  by  definition  personal  and  arbitrary— if  one  wishes,  it  is 
"justice  without  law."  It  does  not  follow  precedents,  but  estab- 

-•^  W.  I.  Thomas,  Primitive  Beliwior  (New  York:  McGraw-Hill,  1937), 
p.  78. 


264  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

lishes  them  from  case  to  case,  and  its  legitimation  is  the  followers' 
faith  in  the  presumed  extraordinary  qualities  of  the  leader. 

This  is  the  sort  of  justice  meted  out  by  successful  revolutionaries 
such  as  Robespierre  and  the  Directoire,  who  did  not  feel  bound 
to  traditional  codes,  time-honored  rules,  or  precedents  when  deal- 
ing with  "enemies  of  the  state."  More  recently,  there  was  Hitler's 
usurpation  of  judicial  prerogatives  when,  in  June  1934,  he  arrested 
Rohm,  the  leader  of  the  Storm  Troops,  at  night  in  his  home.  Rohm 
and  other  Storm  Troop  leaders  were  "court  martialed"  by  the 
Leader's  bodyguard  after  ten-minute  hearings.  Other  men,  such 
as  Generals  Bredow  and  Schleicher,  were  murdered  by  Elite 
Guards  in  their  homes,  without  form  and  in  plain  daylight. 

The  justice  of  Ibn-Saud,  King  of  Saudi-Arabia,  is  similar.^'^  Ibn- 
Saud  takes  his  seat  on  the  sun-lit  steps  of  his  palace,  hears  a  case, 
for  instance,  against  a  man  who  stole  a  saddle,  convicts  him  and 
promptly  has  one  of  his  Negro  slaves  cut  off  the  man's  hand  with 
a  sword  and  dip  the  arm  in  a  bucket  of  hot  oil. 

B.  Traditionalist  justice  has  been  called  "cadi  justice,"  for  in  this 
legal  system,  the  judges  consider  the  case,  as  does  the  Moham- 
medan cadi,  with  precise  regard  to  the  person.  Cadi  justice  differs 
from  charismatic  justice  in  that  it  usually  follows  religiously  sanc- 
tioned norms  and  time-honored  precedents.  There  are  no  rational 
rules  of  proof  and  evidence,  and  ordeals  and  duels  may  be  con- 
sidered magically  significant  tests  of  guilt  or  innocence.  This  realm 
of  traditional  norms,  in  the  absence  of  rational  definitions  of  terms 
and  rules  of  evidence,  is  supplemented  by  a  realm  of  personal 
arbitrariness  in  which  judicious  wisdom  and  psychological  astute- 
ness enter  the  procedure  and  the  verdict.  King  Solomon's  justice 
readily  comes  to  mind,  as  does  that  of  Chinese  judges  of  old  and 
the  Biblical  "Elders  at  the  Gate."  Both  charismatic  and  traditional- 
ist justice  bespeak  the  rule  of  men,  not  the  rule  of  law.^^-*^ 

C.  The  rule  of  law,  in  a  rational,  bureaucratic  manner,  is  a  late 
and  specifically  Western  attainment,  built  on  the  legacy  of  Rome. 
There  a  prestigeful  group  of  legal  practitioners— the  jurisconsuls— 

^^  Cf.  H.  C.  Armstrong,  Ibii  Sa'ud,  King  of  Saudi  Arabia  ( Penguin  Edition, 
1938). 

2"A  Said  Elihu  Root  in  his  Presidential  Address  to  the  American  Bar  Asso- 
ciation in  Chicago,  in  1916:  "The  vast  ind  continually  increasing  mass  of 
reported  decisions  which  afford  authorities  on  almost  every  side  of  almost  every 
(luestion  admonish  us  that  by  the  mere  following  of  precedent  we  should  soon 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  26$ 

emerged,  who  offered  professional  advice  to  their  ch'ents.  Roman 
law  demanded  that  the  complainant  file  his  charge  in  legal  terms. 
Court  procedure  allowed  the  court  to  judge  the  case  only  in  terms 
of  the  original  charge,  regardless  of  what  facts  might  be  disclosed 
during  the  court  hearings.  This  necessitated  legal  aid.  Moreover, 
under  the  Caesars,  the  bureaucratization  of  public  authorities,  and 
the  de\elopment  of  administrative  and  other  laws  of  great  subtlety, 
made  it  necessary  for  the  politically  ambitious  man  to  study  law 
as  well  as  forensic  rhetoric.  This  allowed  jurisconsuls  to  establish 
free  schools  of  law  and  rhetoric.  A  practical  bent  of  mind  combined 
with  a  ritualist  traditionalism,  reminiscent  of  peasant  background, 
made  the  Romans  eager  to  state  whatever  new  problems  faced 
them  in  terms  of  old  norms  by  construing  them  with  the  necessary 
interpretive  twist.  The  hairsplitting  finesse  of  legal  definitions,  the 
logically  unambiguous  distinctions,  and  the  deductions  made  are 
all  appraised  by  experts  as  unique  and  unsurpassed  in  legal  his- 
tory. 

V.  "Rational  Uniformity"  involves  the  orientation  of  persons  to 
similar,  ulterior  expectations;  it  is  an  action  by  which  men  strive 
to  exploit  opportunities  in  their  own  self  interest.  Rational  uni- 
formities are  only  expediently  oriented  to  norms,  duties,  or  to  felt 
obligations.  Their  stability  as  patterns  of  conduct  rests  on  the  devi- 
ator's  running  the  risk  of  damaging  his  own  interests.  Although  ra- 
tional uniformities  of  conduct  may  be  a  feature  of  any  institutional 
order,  the  economic  actions  of  agents  in  a  free  market,  who  by  their 
interpersonal  calculation  and  bargaining  determine  the  price  of 
commodities,  are  outstanding  cases  of  rational  patterns  of  conduct. 

\T.  Ethical  rules  are  standards  of  conduct,  or  conventions,  to 
which  men  attribute  intrinsic  value.  Ry  virtue  of  this  attribution, 
they  treat  these  patterns  as  valid  norms  governing  their  decisions 
and  conduct.  Such  rules  may  have  profound  influence  upon  human 
action,  even  in  the  complete  absence  of  external  sanctions.  If  they 
are  really  effective,  abstractly  formulated  ethical  rules  become  part 

ha\e  no  system  of  law  at  all,  but  tJie  rule  of  the  Turkish  cadi  who  is  expected 
to  do  in  each  case  what  seems  to  him  to  be  right;  and  then  the  door  would 
be  thrown  wide  open  for  the  rule  of  men  rather  than  the  rule  of  law,  and  for 
the  exercise  of  personal  injustice  as  well  as  personal  justice.  We  are  approach- 
ing a  ix)int  where  we  shall  riui  into  confusion  unless  we  adopt  the  simple  and 
natural  course  of  avoiding  confusion  by  classification."  [Our  italics.] 


M 


266  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

of  the  conventional  patterns,  being  supported  by  the  danger  of  dis- 
approval and  the  loss  of  prestige.  They  may  even  become  part  of 
law,  and  accordingly  be  enforced  by  special  staffs. 

VII.  Institutional  controls  are  of  course  most  important  for  our 
conception  of  social  structure.  They  are  patterns  upheld  by  the 
heads  of  institutions  or  by  their  agents.  The  roles  played  by  mem- 
bers of  a  household  for  example,  are  guaranteed  by  parental  au- 
thority; employees  are  subject  to  the  control  of  owners  and  man- 
agers; soldiers  are  subject  to  the  authority  of  the  commanding 
officer;  parishioners  stand  under  the  jurisdiction  of  church  authori- 
ties. Whatever  ends  the  organized  and  interacting  partners  may 
pursue,  and  whatever  means  of  "authority"  or  "leadership"  exist, 
sanctions  against  infractions  of  the  "rules  of  the  game"  are  expected 
by  those  who  to  any  extent  deviate.  Institutional  controls  are  thus 
upheld  by  the  expectation  and  the  fact  that  deviation  will  prob- 
ably result  in  the  head  of  the  institution  or  his  authorized  agents 
taking  action  of  some  kind  against  the  person  who  deviates. 
I  In  terms  of  internal  sanctions,  institutions  mean  that  the  gen- 
I  eralized  other  which  operates  in  the  persons  involved  is  likely  to 
'  include  the  head  of  the  institution  as  a  particular  other.  The  king 
of  a  political  order  or  the  father  of  a  patriarchal  kinship  order  are 
particular  others— the  most  significant  others  of  persons  who  are 
psychologically  members  of  the  institution.  The  kinds  of  external 
sanction  which  this  head  will  take  against  offenders  have  a  wide 
range— disapproval,  expulsion,  or  death. 

The  types  of  social  controls  which  we  have  defined  ^nd  illus- 
trated often  seem  to  cluster  around  or  be  limited  by  the  institu- 
tional framework.  They  specify  and  formalize  institutional  control 
—as  with  law,  which  is  of  course  a  specific  formalization  of  institu- 
tional control  in  general;  or  they  diffuse  and  generahze  institutional 
regulation— as  with  convention,  which  involves  reactions  to  more 
than  specific  institutional  heads.  InstitLitional  orders  form,  as  it 
were,  typical  limits  in  accordance  with  which  other  social  controls 
normally  tend  to  operate. 

6.  Orientation  to  Social  Controls 

Whether  a  code  is  sanctioned  by  staff  action,  as  in  law,  or  by 
diffuse  agents,  as  in  ethical  rule  or  convention,  it  may  have  a  wide 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  26y 

range  of  personal  and  social  orientations.  Wherever  there  are  norms 
and  codes,  ideals  and  aspirations,  the  social  psychologist  has 
learned  to  expect  "trespasses"  and  failings,  and  in  the  case  of 
religious  commandments,  "sins."  We  have  accordingly  to  distin- 
guish between  behavior  and  attitudes  with  regard  to  norms: 
broadly  speaking,  four  such  orientations  to  conventional,  moral, 
or  legal  codes  may  be  located  by  means  of  this  simple  chart: 

ATTITUDE    TOWARD   THE    IDEAL    OR    NORM 

+ 
CONDUCT    WITH   REFERENCE  -j-  I  II 

TO    THE    NORM    OR   IDEAL  —  XII  IV 

I.  There  is  the  type  of  man  who  cherishes  or  affirms  a  given 
norm  and  in  his  behavior  abides  by  his  conviction.  If  he  is  given 
to  judge  others,  we  may  call  him  an  ethical  rigorist,  with  reference 
to  moral  issues;  a  saintly  man,  with  reference  to  Christian  de- 
mands; or  a  militant  liberal,  with  reference  to  the  American  creed.-^ 

Such  persons  have  successfully  internalized  the  "codified"  value 
—whether  it  is  a  religious  imperative,  a  standard  of  hygiene,  a 
conception  of  the  beautiful,  the  true,  or  the  good.  Socially,  such 
internalization  leads  to  standards  of  "good  taste"  and  "decorum," 
of  savoir-faire  and  "decency";  psychologically,  it  leads  to  the  actor's 
ascribing  traits  such  as  "politeness,"  "tactfulness,"  or  "uprightness" 
to  others  and  to  himself.  Internally,  the  person  of  type  I  subscribes 
to  the  respective  values,  verbally  affirming  them;  externally,  in  his 
conduct,  he  abides  by  these  standards. 

In  matters  of  food,  appropriate  thresholds  of  disgust  secure  the 
person  against  dropping  below  his  dietary  standards.  So  the  pious, 
orthodox  Jew  will  not  consume  pork,  will  not  enjoy  the  "blood" 
in  rare  roast  beef.  He  will  be  as  "disgusted"  as  was  the  sober 
Roman  with  drunkards,  for  the  Roman  identified  drunkenness  with 
"barbarism,"  just  as  the  Hindu  Brahman  identifies  "beef  eaters" 
with  Barbarians.  Religious  and  ritualistic  taboos,  as  well  as  hygienic 
standards  and  simple  childhood  habituation  to  what  is  "usual,"  con- 
tribute to  the  establishment  of  such  thresholds  of  disgust.  Men 
like  to  eat  what  they  are  used  to  eating. 

-s  Robert  K.  Merton  has  applied  this  scheme  to  ethnic  and  racial  tolerance 
in  his  essay  printed  in  Discrimination  and  National  Welfare  (New  York:  In- 
stitute for  Rehgious  Studies,   1948). 


268  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

Most  peoples  or  groups  sentimentalize  certain  food  habits  and 
are  even  proud  of  them,  and  this  is  all  the  more  so  if  they  conceive 
of  these  habits  as  badges  of  group  distinction.  The  Britisher  enjoys 
being  a  "beef  eater";  the  Frenchmen  conceive  of  the  "Paris  cuisine" 
as  a  contribution  to  world  civilization;  the  Spartan  enjoyed  his 
"blacksoup,"  which  disgusted  the  Athenian  ambassadors;  to  the 
Scotch-Irish,  Woodrow  Wilson  attributed  the  whisky  bottle,  just 
as  the  stereotyped  German  is  assigned  his  "stein  of  beer,"  the  In- 
dian his  "peace  pipe,"  and  the  modern  American  his  "cocktail."  "Na- 
tional beverages"  and  food  preferences,  and  differences  between, 
for  example,  the  tea-sipping  salon  society  and  the  plebeian  "beer 
garden"  folks  come  to  mind,  not  to  mention  the  "potato-eating 
Irish"  of  the  nineteenth  century.  Such  standards  and  preferences, 
with  their  accompanying  images  of  "disgust,"  often  serve  then  to 
implement  group  hatreds.  Thus  the  French  consider  the  Boche 
sauerkraut  eaters;  the  Germans  consider  the  Russians  drunkards; 
and  Erasmus  considered  the  British  "dirty." 

II.  There  is  also  the  spurious  conformist  or  opportunist.  Out- 
wardly he  conforms  to  the  code,  inwardly  he  does  not  subscribe 
to  it.  He  conforms  externally  for  reasons  of  expediency,  or  because 
he  deems  it  "cheaper"  to  do  so.  He  "goes  to  church"  in  a  kind  of 
Sunday  obsequiousness  although  he  does  not  believe  in  the  creed. 
Soren  Kierkegaard  thought  that  with  the  exception  of  himself  all 
Christians  in  his  time  were  spurious  Christians.  The  motivation  of 
this  type  of  person  is  thus  an  attitude  of  expedient  opportunism  and 
a  fear  of  sanctions,  not  a  love  of  the  respective  value. 

Since  the  values  involved  in  the  code  are  not  internalized  in 
moral  contexts  we  may  speak  of  this  type  as  the  pretender.  Thus 
there  is  the  sham  patient,  the  malingering  soldier,  the  disguised 
royalty,  and  many  other  masters  of  pretense,  respectable  and  un- 
respectable.  No  matter  how  outwardly  correct  his  conduct,  the 
pretender's  lack  of  conviction  and  integrity,  the  "mask-like"  nature 
of  his  role  enactment  is  often  discernible,  in  the  "give  away,"  the 
slip,  the  inconsistency— no  matter  whether  the  actor  "deceives  him- 
self" and  others,  or  whether  he  is  self-conscious  about  what  he  is 
doing.  Moral  philosophers  from  Pascal  to  Nietzsche  have  con- 
tributed to  the  discernment  of  such  phenomena. 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  269 

III.  The  person  who  subscribes  verbally  to  a  code  but  deviates 
from  it  in  conduct  represents  a  third  type.  Here  is  the  hypocrite 
whose  verbal  cant  is  the  tribute  vice  pays  to  virtue.  When  such 
a  person  acts  in  good  faith  we  speak,  in  modern  terms,  of  "ra- 
tionalization" whereby  the  actor  substitutes  a  socially  acceptable 
vocabulary  of  motives  for  his  socially  unacceptable  motives.  The 
pejorative  connotation  of  the  term  "cant"  implies  the  demand  and 
expectation  that  the  verbalizer  of  "cant"  potentially  could  and 
actually  should  realize  his  double  standard,  the  incongruity  be- 
tween his  words  and  his  deeds.  Such  disparities  often  emerge  when 
the  horizon  of  the  actor's  awareness  is  restricted,  and  he  does  not 
face  up  to  the  implications  and  ramifications  of  his  conduct.  Thus, 
free  enterprisers  during  a  depression  may  discharge  workers,  deny- 
ing them  job  opportimities.  But  regardless  of  whether  the  workers 
by  habituation  then  become  lazy,  or  whether  they  are  only  too 
eager  to  work,  the  entrepreneur  may  readily  blame  their  unem- 
ployment on  their  laziness.  Or  a  similar  situation  may  occur  when 
'  the  social  structure  does  not  offer  to  dependent  workers  adequate 
incentives,  when  the  experience  of  generations  has  taught  them 
that  additional  efforts  remain  fruitless.  And  it  may,  in  fact,  be  so: 
effort  not  paying  off  because  it  remains  without  compensation, 
because  geographical  factors  offer  no  opportimities  to  improve  one's 
lot,  or  because  an  oppressive  tax  system  deprives  the  subject  of 
the  fruit  of  his  labor.  The  ruling  class,  at  this  point,  may  be  only 
too  eager  to  vilify  the  slave,  peasant,  or  worker,  who  thus  has  no 
other  means  of  retaliation  than  skillfully  withholding  his  efforts. 

Such  a  vocabulary  of  motives— of  laziness  and  general  no-good— 
lends  to  the  status  superior  the  secondary  advantage  of  implement- 
ing his  superiority  of  property  and  power  by  a  sense  of  moral 
superiority;  it  enables  him  to  "rationalize"  social  differences  into 
"moral"  differences,  with  all  the  moral  benefits  accruing  to  himself. 
E\en  the  suffering  patience  of  the  downtrodden  is  held  against 
him  as  "lack  of  agility"  and  "stupidity,"  as  "lack  of  initiative"  and 
as  "docility."  Thus  do  status  snobbery  and  human  pride  often  feed 
on  the  misery  of  the  others. 

Criticism  of  upper  classes  and  of  the  codes  and  motives  they  im- 
pose also  finds  its  point  of  attack.  The  professed  values  are  played 
off  against  those  who  profess  them,  as  the  intellectuals,  acting  as  the 
conscience  of  their  time  and  society,  contrast  professed  values  with 


2-/0  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

actual  conduct,  and  thus  "debunk"  and  "unmask"  the  hypocrite,  the 
"Tartufe,"  the  "Elmer  Gantry." 

IV.  This  type  represents  the  consistent  deviationist,  the  noncon- 
formist of  word  and  deed.  Here  we  find  the  rebel  and  the  revolu- 
tionary who  openly  renounce  the  dominant  norm  and  break  it  in 
their  behavior.  We  also  find  the  criminal,  who  differs  from  the  revo- 
lutionary in  that  he  has  no  counternorms.  Naturally  "criminals"  might 
also  belong  in  Type  III,  being  persons  who  acknowledge  the  law 
in  words  and  often  wish  others  to  abide  by  the  code,  whereas  they 
do  not  feel  bound  by  it:  tax  delinquents  may,  for  example,  readily 
be  found  in  this  category.  It  is  the  difference  between  the  role  of 
the  "citizen"  and  that  of  the  "bourgeois,"  in  Marx's  sense,  that 
we  have,  in  mind  here.  One  wishes  to  be  considered  a  respectable 
citizen— but  such  respectability  must  not  cost  too  much.  Abuses 
of  all  sorts— from  corruption  in  high  office  to  food  adulteration  and 
other  evasions  of  government  regulations— are  due  to  the  fact  that 
profit  interests  get  the  better  of  civic  highmindedness.  Whereas  the 
heroic  citotjen  of  France  criticizes  the  corruption  of  kings  and 
nobles  and  establishes  his  own  rules  after  the  revolutionary  over- 
throw of  the  ancien  regime,  once  he  is  in  the  saddle  and  has  de- 
veloped into  a  plutocrat,  his  "republican  virtues"  may  crumble  and 
disintegrate  in  the  face  of  "tempting"  or  "unique  opportunities." 
On  a  large  scale  we  also  see  repeated  the  cycle  of  many  monastic 
orders,  whose  members  work  hard  for  the  glory  of  God,  then  be- 
coming rich,  succumb  to  the  temptations  that  seem  to  go  with 
wealth.  But,  then,  looking  around  them,  they  find  another  and 
new  movement,  and  begin  the  same  cycle.  Municipal  administra- 
tions also  have  their  cycles  of  "reform"  under  the  slogan  "throw 
the  rascals  out";  then  comes  the  relaxation  of  civic  endeavor  and 
the  return  to  "taking  it  easy." 

In  Type  IV,  we  also  find  principled  opponents  of  the  code,  who 
may  be  complete  cynics,  skeptics  in  the  face  of  the  respective  value. 
These  opponents  may  even  publicly  uphold  emergent  counter- 
values  and  thus  be  revolutionaries  or  precursors  of  revolutions  to 
come.  In  this  case,  such  a  person  would  be  inspired  by  a  rival 
value  to  promote  the  establishment  of  "countermores,"  which  are 
usually  linked  to  an  actual  or  imagined  "reference  group"  whose 
members   may  supposedly  or  actually   sustain  him.   Whether   he 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  2-/! 

actually  is  their  "representative"  or  merely  wishes  to  be,  he  may 
think  on  "their  behalf"  or  "in  their  interests." 

Intellectuals  and  their  activities  deserve  special  attention  in  this 
connection,  for  they  often  play  important  roles  during  periods  of 
transition  from  one  social  structure  to  another.  They  criticize  as 
already  "dead"  what  actually  exists,  and  they  do  so  in  the  name 
of  the  as  yet  unrealized,  and  perhaps  even  unrealizable,  "utopian" 
standards.  Thus,  during  the  decline  of  the  Hebrew  kingdoms, 
solitary  prophets  arose  who,  in  their  religiously  motivated  dema- 
goguery,  developed  grandiose  eschatological  expectations  and 
visions  of  divine  punishments  to  come  on  the  Day  of  Yahweh, 
after  which  a  pious  "remnant"  would  be  saved  and  its  hidden 
glory  brought  to  light.  Such  Biblical  eschatologies,  combined  with 
the  rational  utopian  construction  of  a  "good  society"  for  which 
Plato  provided  the  model  in  his  "Republic"  and  "The  Laws,"  were 
fused  in  the  postmedieval  utopianism  of  Renaissance  political 
thinkers— such  as  Thomas  More  and  Campanella— and  in  the  work 
of  the  Enlightenment  philosophers  of  the  dawn  of  democratic  con- 
stitutionalism, as  well  as  in  the  socialist  critiques  of  capitalist  so- 
ciety, from  Saint-Simon  and  Robert  Owen  to  Marx  and  the  Marx- 
ists. 

The  problems  of  subjective  and  objective  orientation  to  norms 
and  codes  become  more  complex  when  moral  and  legal  codes 
conflict.  Sociologically  speaking,  as  we  have  seen,  such  conflict 
means  that  a  staff-enforced  code  deviates  from  a  group-cherished 
convention  which  is  guaranteed  by  diffuse  or  unorganized  sanc- 
tions. Such  situations  may  occur  where  the  lawmakers  and  their 
staffs  seek  to  break  up  certain  special  mores  of  particular  groups. 

Tliis  simple  fourfold  scheme  may  be  useful  for  any  situation 
containing  norms;  applied  to  marriage  in  Western  societies,  for 
example,  we  would  have  under  I  the  loyal,  monogamous  married 
couple;  under  II  persons  who  conform  to  the  conventional  regula- 
tion of  acceptable  marriage  partners  although  they  do  not  "believe 
in  them";  the  white  girl  who  shrinks  back  from  accepting  the 
marriage  proposal  of  her  Negro  lover,  or  vice  versa.  Under  III 
we  have  the  adulterous  husband  who  "believes  in  monogamy,"  or 
the  adulterous  Christian  minister.  And  under  IV  there  is  the  con- 
firmed Mormon  of  old,  or  Goethe  who  in  his  drama  "Stella"  re- 
solved an  erotic  triangle  by  a  "happy  ending"  in  bigamy.  Goethe, 


2/2  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

who  married  for  the  first  and  for  the  last  time  at  the  age  of  fifty- 
seven,  practiced  the  "freedom"  he  beheved  in,  and  in  his  novel, 
Elective  Affinities,  appraised  monogamous  marriage  as  a  story  of 
tragic  resignation. 

In  this  as  well  as  in  the  preceding  chapter  we  have  discussed 
the  range  of  institutions  in  each  of  the  institutional  orders  which 
comprise  a  social  structure  and  some  of  the  types  of  people  which 
may  best  be  understood  in  terms  of  these  institutions. 

In  discussing  the  political  order,  we  have  paid  particular  atten- 
tion to  various  kinds  of  power— especially  as  power  is  organized 
in  the  state  and  associated  with  the  various  sentiments  of  "national- 
ism." And  we  have  devoted  attention  to  the  major  types  of  states 
of  the  twentieth  century:  democracy  and  dictatorship.  In  regard  to 
the  economic  order,  we  have  studied  the  development  of  capital- 
ism, especially  in  terms  of  rationality,  and  described  in  brief  its 
major  types  and  the  kinds  of  roles  men  play  in  each  of  them.  We 
have  tried  in  a  brief  account  of  the  militarij  order  to  relate  some 
of  the  historical  practices  of  violence  to  types  of  military  men,  and 
we  have  paid  special  attention  to  the  sociological  and  psychological 
characteristics  of  six  contrasting  types  of  armies.  In  discvissing  the 
religious  order,  we  have  pointed  out  selected  aspects  of  the  six 
world  religions,  especially  the  type  of  generalized  other  they  in- 
culcate in  their  adherents,  and  their  typical  relations  to  the  other 
institutions  existing  in  the  social  structures  of  which  they  have 
been  components.  With  respect  to  the  kinship  order,  we  have 
discussed  various  types  of  families  and  the  type  of  generalized 
other  they  tend  to  form,  as  well  as  how  the  kinship  order  has  been 
historically  related  to  the  economic  order  in  the  "household,"  and 
hence  to  role  differences  between  men  and  women.  We  have  also 
indicated  some  of  the  intricate  ways  in  which  marriage  and  love 
may  be  related.  The  educational  sphere  refers  to  those  aspects  of 
any  institution  which  transmit  skills  and  values.  Every  institutional 
order  may  to  a  greater  or  a  lesser  degree  have  an  educational 
sphere,  the  types  of  skills  transmitted  in  each  case  being  relevant 
to  the  ends  of  the  respective  order.  We  have  suggested  that  edu- 
cational institutions  are  rarely  autonomous,  and  illustrated  the 
services  educational  institutions  may  perform  for  the  state  by  refer- 
ence to  the  case  of  modern  Germany. 

In  conjunction  with  these  institutional  orders,  we  have  discussed 


ORDERS     AND     CONTROLS,     II  2-/:^ 

certain  major  types  of  social  controls  and  norms  which  guide  the 
enactment  of  roles  by  persons.  These  controls  include  custom, 
fashion,  convention,  ethical  values,  and  the  several  types  of  law. 
In  connection  with  such  controls,  we  have  pointed  out  that  persons 
may  react— objectively  and  subjectively— to  such  controls  in  a  vari- 
ety of  ways,  and  that  to  understand  these,  as  well  as  the  motiva- 
tions involved,  we  must  observe  both  public  conduct  and  private 
attitude. 

Persons  accept  or  reject  various  roles— and  leaders  make  known 
their  expectations— by  means  of  symbols.  Moreover,  whether  or 
not  persons  accept  the  demands  made  upon  them  is  in  part  de- 
pendent upon  their  positions  in  the  prevailing  system  of  stratifica- 
tion. Accordingly,  before  we  consider  how  institutional  orders  are 
variously  combined  into  total  social  structures,  which  we  shall 
do  in  Chapter  XII,  we  must  elaborate  the  conception  of  symbol 
spheres,  in  Chapter  X,  and  we  must  relate  our  scheme  of  institu- 
tional orders  to  systems  of  stratification,  in  Chapter  XI. 


CHAPTER 

X 

Symbol  Spheres 


LANGUAGE  is  central  to  the  concerns  of  social  psychology 
because  it  has  to  do  with  the  functioning  of  institutions  as  well 
as  with  the  socialization  of  the  individual.  By  considering  the 
social  and  the  personal  functions  of  language  we  can  relate  intimate 
details  about  the  person  and  the  psychic  structure  to  broader 
conceptions  of  institutional  organization.  To  understand  how  any 
given  person  strives,  feels,  and  thinks  we  have  to  pay  attention  to 
the  symbols  he  has  internalized;  but  to  understand  these  symbols 
we  have  to  grasp  the  way  in  which  they  co-ordinate  institutional 
actions.^  Symbols  mediate  entire  institutional  arrangements  as  well 
as  the  conduct  and  roles  of  persons. 

In  the  psychic  structure,  language  articulates  and  patterns  the 
objects  and  noises  which  we  see  and  hear;  we  come  to  know  many 
of  our  feelings  and  wishes  in  terms  of  specific  vocabularies.  By 
singling  out  targets  for  action,  language  helps  turn  impulses  into 
defined  purposes,  inchoate  sensations  into  perceptions,  vague  feel- 
ings into  known  emotions. 

In  the  person,  symbols  lend  motives  to  conduct,  and  signal  the 
expectations  of  others.  Symbols  provide  the  person  with  a  frame 
of  reference  for  his  experience,  and  this  frame  of  reference  is  not 
only  "social"  in  general,  it  may  be  definitely  related  to  the  opera- 
tions of  specific  institutions. 

If  we  examine  the  content  and  functions  of  communication 
within  institutions,  or  within  the  various  institutional  orders  of  a 
social  structure,  we  notice  that  certain  symbols  tend  to  recur 
more  frequently  than  others  in  given  contexts.  This  universe  of 
discourse— the    vocabularies,    pronunciations,    emblems,    formulas, 

1  See  Chapter  IV:  The  Person,  and  Chapter  V:  The  Sociology  of  Motiva- 
tion. 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  2y$ 

and  types  of  conversation  which  are  typical  of  an  institutional 
order— make  up  "the  symbol  sphere"  of  this  order. 

Such  symbols  may  be  acoustic— as  in  music  or  in  speech— or  they 
may  be  visual— as  in  written  and  printed  imagery  and  signs.  The 
distinctions  and  symbols  of  a  symbol  sphere  of  a  given  institutional 
order  are  related  to  the  preoccupations  and  practices  of  persons  in 
that  order.  For  since  language  helps  us  to  co-ordinate  social  ac- 
tivities, it  reflects  the  objects  with  which  persons  of  the  order  deal 
and  the  conduct  patterns  with  which  they  do  so. 

Thus  the  myths  of  religion,  the  incantations  of  magic,  the  tech- 
nical jargon  of  an  occupation,  the  high-brow  pronunciations  and 
slang  of  status  groups,  the  tete-a-tete  of  lovers,  and  the  table-talk 
of  families— all  these  represent  modes  of  speech  which  reflect  dif- 
ferent institutional  contexts.  We  become  more  aware  of  this  when 
we  examine  foreign  languages.  Arabic,  for  example,  "contains  about 
6,000  names  for  'camel,' "  or  derived  from  camel— for  breeding- 
camels  and  running-camels  and  for  female  camels  in  all  the  various 
stages  of  pregnancy.-  The  practices  and  objects  involved  in  a 
society  of  camel  breeders  are  reflected  in  the  content  and  dis- 
tinctions which  make  up  the  symbol  sphere  of  their  society.  The 
Teutonic  languages  have  terms  for  horse,  steed,  mare,  stallion,  all 
of  which  to  the  Greek  were  simply  hippos. 

Religious  institutions  develop  their  own  rhetoric  and  liturgy— 
the  hymn,  the  prayer,  the  sermon,  the  benediction.  Similarly  in  the 
political  and  economic  orders  we  find  genres  of  talk  and  of  writing 
—the  sales  talk,  low-  and  high-pressure;  the  election  speech,  stump 
or  fireside.  And,  of  course,  the  bulk  of  our  modern  fiction  is  a 
symbolic  elaboration  of  love  and  kinship  relations.  Not  all  societies, 
of  course,  develop  identical  symbols  for  the  same  pursuit;  the 
increasingly  precise  notation,  and  hence  the  symbolic  recording, 
of  musical  sound  patterns  is  peculiar  to  occidental  civilization.  In 
like  manner,  not  all  institutions  of  the  same  order  have  identical 
symbols.  Puritanism,  for  example,  suppressed  instrumental  music 
as  well  as  opera  and  the  dance.  Catholicism,  however,  has  made 
rich  use  of  all  the  arts,  with  the  exception  of  dancing,  as  symbolic 
means  of  religious  worship. 

Certain   emblems   and   modes   of   language   not   only   recur   in 

2  See  W.  I.  Thomas,  Primitive  Behavior  (New  York:  McGraw-Hill,  1937), 
p.  68. 


2^6  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

given  social  contexts  but  seem  to  be  more  important  to  the  main- 
tenance of  certain  institutions,  to  their  chains  of  authority  and  to 
the  authoritative  distribution  of  their  roles.  The  contexts  in  which 
these  symbols  appear  may  seem  to  be  "staged";  they  are  dramatic, 
solemn,  weird.  They  carry  more  "weight."  These  symbols  may  be 
repeated  every  day  by  everyone;  or  they  may  be  used  only  on 
extraordinary  occasions  and  by  specifically  authorized  persons. 
As  we  have  seen,  the  symbols  which  thus  justify  a  social  structure 
or  an  institutional  order  are  called  symbols  of  "legitimation,"  or 
"master  symbols,"  or  "symbols  of  justification." 

By  lending  meaning  to  the  enactment  of  given  roles,  these  mas- 
ter symbols  sanction  the  person  in  re-acting  the  roles.  When  in- 
ternalized they  form  unquestioned  categories  which  channel  and 
delimit  new  experiences;  they  promote  and  constrain  activities. 
When  public  justifications  are  privately  internalized,  they  make 
up  the  stuff  of  self -justification,  operating  as  reasons  and  motives 
leading  persons  into  roles  and  sanctioning  their  enactment  of  them. 
Indeed,  no  self-justification  is  likely  to  be  entirely  private;  unless 
it  is  accepted  by  others  it  does  not  secure  the  private  self  in  feel- 
ing that  all  is  well.  If,  for  example,  "individualistic"  institutions 
are  publicly  justified,  then  reference  to  self-interest  may  be  accept- 
able as  justification  for  individual  conduct.  Personal  reasons  are 
thus  related  to  public  legitimations. 

While  the  symbols  typically  found  in  any  order  comprise  the 
symbol  sphere  of  that  order,  those  symbols  that  justify  the  institu- 
tional arrangement  of  the  order  are  its  master  symbols.  To  the 
social  scientist  such  master  symbols  are  of  special  interest  in  that 
they  allow  us  to  understand  the  cohesion  of  role  configurations, 
their  permanence  and  change,  and  their  function  in  the  intrapsychic 
life  of  persons. 

The  more  refined  symbol  elaborations  of  the  philosopher,  theolo- 
gian, publicity  director,  scientist,  or  artist  may  not  be  so  immedi- 
ately important  for  the  understanding  of  a  period  and  society  as 
are  the  doctrines  which  do  not  seem  to  be  "doctrines"  at  all,  but 
rather  facts.  In  the  experience  of  men  enacting  the  roles  of  their 
time,  they  seem  "inevitable  categories  of  the  human  mind.  Men 
do  not  look  on  them  merely  as  correct  opinion,  for  they  have 
become  so  much  a  part  of  the  mind,  and  lie  so  far  back,  that  they 
are  never  really  conscious  of  them  at  all.  They  do  not  see  them, 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  IJ-J 

but  other  things  throug,h  them.  It  is  these  abstract  ideas  at  the 
center,  the  things  which  they  take  for  granted  that  characterize 
a  period."  ^ 

Those  in  authority  within  institutions  and  social  structures  at- 
tempt to  justify  their  rule  by  linking  it,  as  if  it  were  a  necessary 
consequence,  with  moral  symbols,  sacred  emblems,  or  legal  for- 
mulae which  are  widely  believed  and  deeply  internalized.  These 
central  conceptions  may  refer  to  a  god  or  gods,  the  "votes  of  the 
majority,"  the  "will  of  the  people,"  the  "aristocracy  of  talents  or 
wealth,"  to  the  "divine  right  of  kings,"  or  to  the  allegedly  extraor- 
dinary endowment  of  the  person  of  the  ruler  himself. 

Various  thinkers  have  used  different  terms  to  refer  to  this  phe- 
nomenon: Mosca's  "political  formula"  or  "great  superstitions,"* 
Locke's  "principle  of  sovereignty,"  ^  Sorel's  "ruling  myth,"  "^  Thur- 
man  Arnold's  "folklore,"  '  Weber's  "legitimations,"  "*  Durkheim's 
"collective  representations,"  ^  Marx's  "dominant  ideas,"  ^"  Rousseau's 
"general  will,"  ^^  Lasswell's  "symbols  of  authority,"  or  "symbols  of 
justification,"  ^-  Mannheim's  "ideology,"  ^•'  Herbert  Spencer's  "pub- 
lic sentiments"  ^*— all  testify  the  central  place  of  master  symbols 
in  social  analysis. 

3  T.  E.  Hulme,  Speculations  (London:   Routledge,  1936),  p.  50. 

*G.  Mosca,  The  Ruling  Class,  H.  D.  Kahn,  tr.   (New  York:  McGraw-Hill, 

1939),  PP-  70-71- 

5  John  Locke,  Two  Treatises  Concerning  Government  (London,  1924). 

^Georges  Sorel,  Reflections  on  Violence,  T.  E.  Hulme,  tr.  (New  York:  Vik- 
ing, 1914). 

"  Thurman  W.  Arnold,  The  Folklore  of  Capitalism  (New  Haven:  Yale 
Univ.   Press,   1937). 

8  Max  Weber,  The  Theory  of  Social  and  Economic  Organization,  Talcott 
Parsons  and  A.  M.  Henderson,  trs.  (New  York:  Oxford,  1948),  Chapters  I 
and  HL 

9  fimile  Durkheim,  The  Elementary  Forms  of  the  Religious  Life  (New  York: 
Macmillan,  1915). 

!'■  K.  Marx  and  F.  Engels,  The  German  Ideology  (New  York:  International 
Publications,   1939). 

11  Jean- Jacques  Rousseau,  The  Social  Contract  (New  York:  Hafner,  1947). 

12  H.  D.  Lasswell,  World  Politics  and  Personal  Insecurity  (New  York: 
McGraw-Hill,  1935),  and  Politics:  Who  Gets  What,  When,  How.  (New 
York:  McGraw-Hill,  1936).  See  also  Kenneth  Burke,  Attitudes  Towards  His- 
tory  (New  York:   New  Republic,   1937),  Vol.  H,  pp.  232  ft. 

1^  Karl  Mannheim,  Ideology  and  Utopia,  Louis  Wirth  and  Edward  Shils, 
trs.    (New  York:    Harcourt,   Brace,    1936). 

1*  Herbert  Spencer,  Principles  of  Sociology  (London,  1882-1896),  \'ol.  H, 
Book  1,  pp.  319  ff. 


2.jS  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

1.  Symbol  Spheres  in  Six  Contexts 

In  modern  social  structures,  it  is  sometimes  difficult  to  classify 
the  prevailing  symbols  according  to  the  institutional  orders  which 
they  justify  or  according  to  the  roles  to  which  they  lend  meaning. 
The  modern  expansion  of  mass  communications  has  made  for  a 
wide  and  rapid  diffusion  of  symbols  and  vocabularies,  which  may 
arise  in  local  areas  for  special  purposes.  Nevertheless,  if  the  inter- 
relations of  the  different  orders,  in  terms  of  their  symbol  spheres, 
are  to  be  grasped,  one  must  attempt  to  sort  them  out. 

Since  the  roles  of  an  institutional  order  involve  specific  modes 
of  conduct  and  the  social  integration  of  these  modes,  it  is  only 
natural  that  special  vocabularies  should  arise.  These  vocabularies 
are  shorthand  ways  of  referring  to  common  tasks;  they  integrate 
the  behaviors  which  go  on  witliin  the  order  more  readily  and 
precisely  than  could  symbols  from  general  discourse.  Thus,  in 
addition  to  master  symbols  (which  justify  and  sanction  the  au- 
thority of  institutions  and  lend  meaning  and  motivation  to  the 
enactment  of  roles),  symbol  spheres  also  contain  many  generally 
less  important  specifications  and  implications  that  are,  in  fact, 
specialized  ways  of  talk  and  writing. 

In  discussing  some  symbols  which  "belong  to"  the  various  orders 
we  are  able  to  illustrate  some  of  the  general  points  we  have  made 
about  symbol  spheres. 

I.  The  vocabulary  is  a  major  element  in  the  style  of  life  which 
sets  off  different  status  groups.  It  is  one  of  the  first  things  we  notice 
about  a  person.  In  terms  of  his  speech,  his  choice  of  words  and 
pronunciation,  we  place  a  person  in  the  hierarchy  of  the  status 
sphere.  The  words  that  may  with  propriety  be  used  on  given  occa- 
sions are  circumscribed  by  status  conventions,  which  may  be  main- 
tained esthetically  in  terms  of  "good"  and  "bad"  taste,  or  magically, 
in  terms  of  "foul"  language,  or  religiously  by  taboos  being  placed 
upon  certain  modes  of  speech,  for  example,  cursing.  Conformity 
to  the  status  conventions  of  the  symbol  sphere  is  upheld  by  the 
formal  and  informal  educations  of  status  group  members. 

Such  vocabularies  change,  and  may  even  be  subject  to  fads  and 
fashions.  No  matter  how  much  formal  education  persons  are  ex- 
posed to,  they  may  never  be  able  to  learn  the  innuendoes  of  a 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  279 

situation  and  respond  to  it  with  the  proper  symbols  unless  they 
have  imbibed  it,  so  to  speak,  with  their  mother's  milk.  For  there 
are  differences  in  enunciation  and  in  the  scope  of  vocabulary  which 
depend  upon  the  variety  of  contacts  and  travel  and  dinner  com- 
panions over  long  periods  of  time.  The  conventionalization  of 
language^  by  an  upper-status  group  is  usually  conservative.  It  slows 
up  the  drift  of  linguistic  change,  as  does  education,  which  makes 
persons  sensitive  to  "good  form"  and  "usage. "  Changes  in  language 
therefore,  tend  to  drift  upward;  the  "uncontrolled  speech  of  the 
folk"  today  provides  advance  information  about  proper  usage  to- 
morrow.^^ 

Where  stratification  is  rigid,  the  vocabularies  of  the  various  strata 
may  not  diffuse  very  readily.  Social  position  is  thus  "closed"  to 
others  by  the  development  of  an  "exclusive"  conventional  language. 
Then,  by  listening  to  conversations  one  can  identify  the  speaker's 
status  level  (in  Confucian  China,  highly  educated  people  could  do 
so  by  the  calligraphy  of  the  writer).  In  Java,  five  vocabularies  may 
be  used  in  connection  with  the  status  stratification,  and  in  old 
Siam,  as  well  as  in  seventeenth-  and  eighteenth-century  Europe, 
the  court-centered  nobility  spoke  French  rather  than  the  national 
language  or  the  regional  dialect  of  commoners,  just  as  the  old  Rus- 
sian court  spoke  French  and,  before  1914,  English.  In  Polynesia, 
among  the  Tonga,  a  similar  situation  prevails,  there  being  three 
vocabularies.  Prince  Hohenlohe,  German  chancellor  around  1900, 
wrote  to  his  wife  only  in  French;  German  for  him  was  public 
language,  French  was  the  private  language.  Frederick  II  of  Prus- 
sia, a  contemporary  of  Kant,  considered  German  a  boorish  and 
vulgar  idiom,  which  the  king  need  not  master. 

A  speaker  may  "emphasize  the  superiority  of  the  person  ad- 
dressed by  using  the  vocabulary  above  that  of  his  rank,  or  his 
inferiority  by  using  that  of  the  rank  just  lower."  ^®  In  England, 
"gentleman,"  a  term  designating  a  status  type,  has  tended  to  spread 
and  include  certain  abstract  character  traits  rather  than  all  well- 
born persons  who  need  not  engage  in  routine  work  for  livelihood. 
Yet  status  groups  tend  to  close  up  their  ranks  by  means  of  language. 
The  use  of  medieval  Latin  thus  excluded  the  uneducated,  just  as 

15  See  Edward  Sapir,  Language  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1921),  p.  167. 
This   point   may   require   modification   under   mass   communication   conditions. 
^^  W.   I.  Thomas,  op.  cit.,  p.  83. 


28o  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

the  use  of  foreign  languages  by  upper-status  groups  excludes  lower 
classes  and  status  groups. 

Germans  in  Goethe's  time  referred  only  to  noble-born  girls  as 
frdulein;  today  for  Germans  it  is  a  common  form  of  address  for 
unmarried  young  women;  for  many  American  soldiers  it  means 
sexually  available  women.  In  the  United  States  such  terms  as  "sir," 
or  even  "Mr."  reflect  status  stratification.  In  classic  China,  with 
its  ancestor  worship,  there  was  no  word  to  designate  "one  who  is 
old"  in  a  socially  neutral,  chronological  way.  The  Chinese  words 
carried  overtones  of  deference  so  that  in  this  language  it  was 
difficult  to  raise  the  ethical  question  of  whether  one  should  or 
should  not  treat  old  men  with  respect.^^ 

The  prestige  of  national  languages  may  be  implemented  by  the 
prestige  of  works  of  art  integrating  language  and  music.  Thus 
Italians  and  Germans  have  profited  from  the  diffusion  of  Italian 
and  German  operas  sung  in  the  original  language,  especially  Verdi 
and  Wagner,  and  the  lied,  from  Mozart  to  Mahler.  Together  with 
the  works,  star  performers  also  have  migrated:  the  Italian  tenor 
and  the  "Wagnerian  soprano." 

II.  In  the  economic  order,  the  jobs  that  men  do  together  give  rise 
to  specialized  trade  jargons.  Changes  in  the  technology  connected 
with  the  job  give  rise  to  new  terms  connected  with  novel  tools  and 
their  use  (kilowatt.  X-ray,  video,  static).  Such  terms  may  spread 
to  persons  and  to  strata  that  are  not  connected  with  the  new 
technology.  Most  craftsmen  and  engineering  groups  develop  spe- 
cialized workshop  vocabularies  which  may  be  quite  seperate  from 
the  terminology  they  are  formally  taught.  Where  speed  is  at  a 
premium,  as  in  a  news  agency,  "shop  languages"  tend  to  develop 
which  aim  at  a  skeleton  language  that,  for  economic  reasons, 
drastically  reduces  the  number  of  syllables,  using  only  those  that 
are  indispensable  for  comprehension.  In  part,  the  prose  style  of 
Time  magazine  represents  an  overt  cultivation  and  publicizing  of 
such  normally  shop-restricted  language,  thus  giving  readers  the 
illusion  that  they  are  "on  the  inside."  This  is  a  comforting  feeling 
at  a  time  when,  due  to  the  concentration  and  secrecy  of  key  de- 
cisions, so  many  people  feel  "on  the  outside"  and  have  learned  to 

1^  Cf.  I.  A.  PUchards,  Mencius  on  the  Mind  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace, 
1932)- 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  281 

distrust  the  news  organs  to  the  extent  of  a  "propaganda  neurosis." 

A  good  deal  of  American  "common  sense,"  for  example,  deals 
with  the  necessity  of  a  man's  "earning  a  living,"  and  the  "practical" 
is  generally  identified  with  the  "pecuniary"  or  the  profitable.  The 
pecuniary  may  also  inform  moral  vocabularies:  he  is  a  sterling 
character,  worth  his  weight  in  gold.  Some  tombstones,  in  fact,  in- 
form us  that  a  deceased  child  was  "worth  a  million  dollars." 

In  tho^  United  States  many  master  symbols  of  the  social  structure 
are  derived  from  and  primarily  legitimate  the  economic  order. 
"Free  Enterprise"  and  "Private  Property"  are  practically  unques- 
tionable symbols,  even  when  they  are  not  very  skillfully  used. 
The  autonomy  and  power  of  the  laissez-faire  economic  order,  as 
guaranteed  by  formal  law,  has  thus  been  a  major  factor  in  shaping 
all  U.S.  symbol  spheres. 

For  over  a  hundred  years,  lawyers  and  politicians,  journalists 
and  academicians  have  taught,  argued,  and  presented  economic 
issues  in  terms  of  the  "competitive  model"  of  laissez-faire  capital- 
ism essentially  derived  from  Adam  Smith.  The  disturbing  facts  of 
an  economic  life  now  dominated  by  giant  corporations  has  led  to 
a  popular  view  of  them  as  deviant  institutions,  as  "monopolies," 
and  the  word  has  about  it  a  ring  of  righteous  indignation  against 
monopolistic  "abuses"  of  power. 

One  of  the  characteristic  legacies  of  puritan  America  is  the 
moral  conception  of  property  as  stewardship.  In  early  days,  in 
the  face  of  the  "roving  Indian,"  this  concept  sanctioned  the  Ameri- 
can seizure  of  hunting  ground  and  the  placing  of  it  under  the 
God-willed  plow.  In  the  face  of  presumably  "improvident"  and 
propertyless  masses  it  has  made  philanthropy  obligatory,  at  least 
from  the  deathbed  of  the  millionaire.  Symbols  of  stewardship  and 
some  accompanying  practices  ha\'e  thus  blended  with  other  legiti- 
mations of  the  dominant  economic  order. 

III.  Families  may  develop  special  terms  understood  only  by  its 
members.  Such  terms  or  phrases  may  originate  from  some  experi- 
ence which  the  family  feels  to  be  unique  and  wishes  to  recall^  by 
symbols  that  carry  its  overtone  or  mood.  Or,  a  baby's  mispronunci- 
ation may  be  considered  so  cute  that  it  is  thought  worthy  of  being 
preserved. 

Everyone  knows  that  lovers  develop  little  phrases  so  intimate 
and  subtle  that  only  they  could  ever  understand  them.  Some  words. 


282  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

like  cute  and  nice,  are  specifically  feminine.  Others  seem  to  arise 
from  the  conduct  of  women  in  handling  babies:  dydee  for  diaper, 
booties,  goodies,  teeny-weeny.  Others  refer  to  objects  connected 
with  the  tabooed  sphere  of  sex:  "unmentionables,"  or  "lingerie" 
for  underwear. 

An  extreme  instance  of  the  segregation  of  language  by  sexual 
groups  is  provided  by  the  island  Caribs  who  have  "two  distinct 
vocabularies,  one  used  by  men  and  by  women  when  speaking  to 
men,  the  other  used  by  women  when  speaking  to  each  other, 
and  by  men  when  repeating,  in  oratio  obligua,  some  saying  of 
women.  .  .  ."  ^®  The  institutions  of  exogamy  and  of  exclusively 
male  war  councils  appear  to  underlie  such  sexual  divisions  of 
vocabulary. 

Words  referring  to  "young  girls"  are  likely  to  take  on  moral 
connotations:  "In  French,  one  word  after  another  that  has  meant 
a  young  girl  has  dropped  out  of  polite  usage  because  words  signify- 
ing this  sweet  creature  too  easily  take  on  the  meaning  of  what 
some  of  the  weaker  of  the  sweet  creatures  may  become.  Thus 
Bachele,  mescme,  touse,  garce  and  even  fille  have  in  succession 
been  demoted."  In  English  one  has  similar  trouble  with  words 
like  "mistress,  lover,  and  even  woman."  ^^  The  sociological  analysis 
of  such  shifts  in  meaning  reveals  the  interdependence  of  words, 
conduct,  and  conventions  within  given  institutions. 

In  Western  civilization  the  "sanctity  of  the  home"  is  a  legitima- 
tion of  the  privacy  maintained  at  the  family  abode.  The  political 
order  in  the  United  States  guarantees  this  feature  of  the  monoga- 
mous family,  the  fourth  amendment  to  the  Constitution  holding 
that  "The  right  of  the  people  to  be  secure  in  their  persons,  houses, 
papers,  and  effects,  against  unreasonable  searches  and  seizures, 
shall  not  be  violated  .  .  ."  Although  the  practical  expediencies  of 
local  authorities  have  modified  the  interpretation  of  this  amend- 
ment it  still  stands  as  part  of  the  formal  sphere  of  political  symbols 
which  guarantee  privacy. 

Reporters  intent  on  making  headlines  with  "the  human  interest 
story"  caused  the  Lindberghs  to  leave  the  country.  Wire  tapping 
and  the  secret  installation  of  equipment  for  overhearing  and  over- 
ly Cf.  the  passage  from  The  Mystic  Rose.  Reprinted  by  W.  I.  Thomas  in 
his  Source  Book  for  Social  Origins  (Boston:   Badger,   1909),  p.  521. 

1"  Cf.  Isaac  Goldberg,  The  Wonder  of  Words  (New  York:  Appleton-Cen- 
tury,    1938),    p.    269. 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  28^ 

seeing  what  goes  on  in  the  home  of  suspects  under  pohce  surveil- 
lance often  seem  to  make  the  legal  rights  to  privacy  quite  tenuous. 
Some  private  citizens  disdain  the  verbal  invasion  of  their  neigh- 
bor's legitimate  privacy  by  dismissing  it  as  "gossip." 

The  German  equivalent  of  "gossip"  is  Klatsch,  and  it  is  perhaps 
no  less  characteristic  that  one  speaks  of  "Klatschbase"— a  gossipy 
woman— but  not  of  a  man.  Hence  one  may  wonder  whether  they 
were  not  men  who  were  in  the  lead  in  depreciating  "gossip"  in  the 
name  of  a  "broader  horizon"  of  public  concerns  in  the  light  of 
which  women's  housebound  talk  appeared  "trivial."  It  is  no  less 
characteristic  that  philosophers,  like  Aristotle  and  Bacon  would 
preferably  ascribe  "garrulity"  to  women. 

At  any  rate,  the  demand  for  conventional  protection  of  privacy 
emerged  along  with  the  greater  individuation  of  families  and  the 
sharper  definition  of  "private"  and  "public"  segments  of  the  per- 
sonality. When  the  workshop  and  the  home  of  the  guildmaster 
were  still  under  the  same  roof,  when  the  master's  wife  was  an 
important  authority  also  in  the  workshop,  such  segmentalization 
of  "private"  and  "public "  life  could  not  emerge.  It  was  the  differen- 
tiation of  workshop  and  home,  office  and  home,  of  private  fortime 
and  business  capital,  of  "bourgeois "  and  "citizen,"  which  allowed 
for  the  drawing  of  a  line  between  "private"  and  "public"  life. 

For  democratically  elected  leaders  of  the  community  the  line 
between  public  and  private  is  differently  drawn  than  for  persons 
having  lower  "representative  value "  to  the  community.  The  public 
claims  the  right  to  know  more  about  the  leader's  life  than  merely 
the  official  aspect.  Thus  baby  pictures  of  the  President  as  well  as 
photographs  of  his  home  and  hobbies  are  publicized  to  satisfy 
"human  interest."  The  moral  conduct  of  teachers,  ministers,  civil 
servants  outside  the  class  room,  church,  or  office  has  a  bearing  on 
their  positions  of  public  trust,  yet  this  is  not  true  for  a  salesman. 

Another  feature  of  the  symbol  sphere  of  kinship  orders  that  is 
associated  with  the  political  order  is  "the  oath."  Western  civiliza- 
tion generally  has  been  guaranteed  by  religious  and  secular  state 
symbols,  rather  than  by  blood.  Fealty,  loyalty,  and  the  magical 
sanctions  involved  in  the  taking  of  oaths  have  centered  around 
these  two  orders,  whose  symbol  spheres  have  been  used  to  guaran- 
tee the  roles  and  contractual  relations  of  other  orders,  including 
that  of  kinship.  Thus  the  marriage  oath— a  vow  of  constant  and 
exclusive  love— is  taken  in  terms  of  the  state  and  on  the  Bible. 


284  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

IV.  The  symbols  of  the  political  order  may  be  visual  or  auditory, 
like  the  flag  or  the  national  anthem,  or  they  may  be  sentimentalized 
places  like  "the  Capital,"  or  written  documents  as  in  the  constitu- 
tional states  of  modern  democracies.  In  discussing  political  symbols, 
our  chief  concern  is  with  those  which  sanction  political  authority. 

The  party  politician  will,  in  one  way  or  the  other,  use  the  master 
symbols  of  the  political  order,  and  will  also  develop  special  rhet- 
orics: both  the  content  and  the  delivery  of  his  speech  will  become 
stereotyped  around  those  modes  that  are  felt  to  be  efi^ectively 
persuasive  appeals.  He  names  events  and  personalities  in  the 
stereotypes  of  his  viewpoint:  "radical"  or  "progressive,"  "regimenta- 
tion" or  "regulation,"  "dole"  or  "home  relief,"  "alien"  or  "foreign," 
the  "New  Deal"  or  the  "Raw  Deal." 

The  symbols  which  legitimate  a  political  order  may  be  so  deeply 
embedded  in  mass  media  and  popular  mentality  that  counter- 
symbols  are  avoided— even  if  they  stand  for  programs  or  policies 
which  people  actually  want.  Thus  a  majority  of  certain  groups 
may  be  in  favor  of  specific  policies  for  which  "socialism"  stands, 
but  reject  the  "socialist  party"  or  socialist  terminology.  Stereotypes 
of  the  symbol  sphere,  and  not  issues,  may  thus  determine  political 
orientation  and  conduct. -° 

V.  The  symbol  spheres  of  the  military  order  and  of  the  political 
order  are  blended  in  the  modern  national  state.  This  symbolic 
integration  follows  the  integration  of  the  institutions  making  up 
the  two  orders.  The  state  monopolizes  the  instruments  of  violence 
and  permits  only  those  who  are  authorized  to  wear  the  uniform 
of  the  army,  navy,  or  police  to  have  access  to  them,  and  then 
only  when  "under  orders."  The  uniform  is  a  symbol  of  this  au- 
thorized access  and  use. 

In  modern  armies  special  premiums  are  placed  upon  such  char- 
acter traits  as  courage  and  bravery,  and  the  risk  involved  is  not 
compensated   in   money  to   the   same   degree   as   it  would   be   if 

-**  On  the  use  ot  stereotypes  in  political  conduct,  see  the  experimental  study 
of  G.  W.  Ilartmann,  "The  Contradiction  Between  the  Feeling-Tone  of  Po- 
litical Party  Names  and  Public  Responses  to  Their  Platforms,"  Journal  of 
Social  Psychology,  1936,  7,  pp.  336-57;  S.  S.  Sargent,  "Emotional  Stereotypes 
in  The  Chicago  Tribune,"  Sociometry  II,  (1939),  pp.  6qS.;  Thurman  W. 
Arnold,  op.  cit.;  and  The  Symbols  of  Government  (New  Haven:  Yale  Univ. 
Press,  1935). 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  2$$ 

anyone  ran  the  same  risk  in  a  civilian  job.  Therefore,  special  weight 
and  a  heavy  emotional  aura  are  characteristic  of  the  symbol  sphere 
of  the  military  order.  Medals  and  other  tokens  of  honor  become 
important  as  psychic  compensations  and  incentives  which  enable 
and  inspire  men  to  risk  their  lives  in  the  fighting  role  of  the  soldier 
or  sailor. 

In  addition  to  these  honorific  accentuations  of  the  traits  needed 
for  the  soldier,  most  armies  tend  to  develop  specialized  vocabu- 
laries which  reflect  the  feelings,  situation,  and  needs  of  the  sol- 
diery. The  organizational  complexities  of  large-scale  armies  and 
navies  bring  about  special  "command  languages"  which  officer 
candidates  have  to  learn.  It  takes  skill  to  write  out  unambiguous 
"orders"  with  the  utmost  economy  of  words  and  yet  perfectly  lucid 
simplicity.  The  speed  of  transmission  and  the  choice  of  proper 
"channels'  of  staff  and  line  officers  who  have  to  transmit  the 
supreme  command  with  the  appropriately  classified  "military  se- 
crecy" have  helped  to  influence  and  foster  such  developments  in 
the  technology  of  means  of  communication,  codes,  ciphers,  de- 
ciphering. These  developments  in  turn  have  been  transferred  to 
other  institutionalized  orders.  "Radio,"  as  developed  during  World 
War  I,  is  only  one,  though  a  most  telling,  example.  Since  the  age 
of  railroading  and  the  telegraph,  modern  business  needs  and  mod- 
ern military  requirements   have  often  coincided. 

An  army  is  made  up  of  diverse  population  elements;  it  contains 
men  who  are  performing  new  roles,  segregated  from  ordinary 
social  routines;  accordingly  these  men  develop  specialized  view- 
points and  modes  of  protest.  In  the  bureaucratically  disciplined 
army,  there  is  repression  of  spontaneous  impulses  and  individual 
differences.  That  is  why  there  is  so  much  cursing  and  griping  in 
armies.  Since  the  sexes  are  segregated,  a  major  restraint  upon 
profanity  is  removed.  Cursing  in  an  army  is  a  safety  valve  of  men 
in  situations  where  obedience  is  stereotyped.  The  extent  to  which 
such  blowing  oft  of  steam  is  necessary  will  vary  with  the  levels 
of  the  personnel.  The  sergeant  in  all  armies,  for  example,  has  tra- 
ditionally been  a  man  of  violent  language.  That  is  because  he  does 
not  formulate  very  many  of  the  orders  which  he  gives,  yet  he 
must  enforce  them  directly  upon  those  who  execute  them. 

VI.  In  the  religious  order  the  symbol  sphere  is  very  important, 
since  the  contents  with  which  religion  deals  and  the  sanctions  it 


286  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

employs  are  "psychic."  The  basic  symbol  which  legitimates  the 
authority  of  any  of  the  salvation  religions  is  some  image  of  God, 
or  of  gods.  All  roles  within  the  religious  order— of  prophet  and 
of  priest  or  of  believers— are  justified  in  terms  of  some  such  sym- 
bol. Theology  is  the  doctrinal  elaboration  of  the  concepts  of  deity 
to  which  the  religion  is  bound.  Religious  symbols  and  the  image 
of  God  are  manipulated  and  argued  over,  or  silently  accepted,  by 
those  in  pursuit  of  salvation.  The  modern  sermon,  which  has  been 
considerably  shortened,  is  still  delivered  with  such  tonal  quality 
and  gesture  as  to  make  the  sound  of  the  voice  identifiable  as  a 
minister's,  even  without  reference  to  content. 

The  extent  to  which  religious  symbols  may  be  internalized  and 
linked  to  the  psychic  structure  may  be  indicated  by  the  follow- 
ing: ".  .  .  the  very  name  of  Jesus  was  of  so  sweet  a  taste  in  her 
mouth  [the  mouth  of  the  Venerable  Sister  Serafia]  that  on  uttering 
it  she  frequently  swooned  away  and  was  therefore  obliged  to 
deprive  herself  of  this  joy  in  the  presence  of  others  till  she  was 
given  sufficient  robustness  of  spirit  to  repress  these  external  move- 
ments/' ^^ 

Language  produces  "action  at  a  distance":  from  a  distance  it 
"wakens  hope  or  fear  .  .  .  excites  the  dangerous  or  useful  action. 
From  this  comes  the  belief  in  the  fruitfulness  of  invocations,  of  in- 
cantations, of  all  that  is  action  by  speech:  thus  came  into  being 
magico-religious   techniques.  .  .  ."  -^ 

The  symbols  of  magic,  if  verbal,  may  not  be  in  the  grammar  of 
ordinary  language,  and  may  not  refer  to  ordinary  objects  of  the 
tangible  everyday  world, "^  yet  in  the  feelings  and  consciousness 
of  the  believer  they  refer  to  extraordinary  realities  and  weird 
powers.  The  symbols  which  are  thus  used  may  be  verbal— as  in  the 
casting  of  a  spell,  like  abracadabra  or  sesame;  or  they  may  be 
manual  acts— like  the  handling  and  eating  of  the  dead  brave  man's 
heart  in  order  to  garner  bravery  for  oneself;  or  they  may  be  both 
—as  when  the  verbal  incantation  is  accompanied  by  the  ceremonial 

-^  See  Norman  Douglas,  Siren  Land,  quoted  by  Isaac  Goldberg,  op.  cit., 
p.  121.  Cf.  also  J.  VVach,  Sociology  of  Religion  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago 
Press,    1944). 

22  Celestin  Bougie,  The  Evolution  of  Values,  H.  Sellars,  tr.  (New  York: 
Holt,    1926),   p.    154. 

■'^•'' See  B.  Malinowski,  Coral  Gardens  and  Their  Magic  (New  York:  Ameri- 
can Book,  1935),  Vol.  II,  pp.  213-14. 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  28y 

rite.  Such  wishful  analogies  may  occur  in  the  symbol  spheres  of 
almost  any  order,  although  historically  they  have  been  most  closely 
associated  with  religious  orders. 

2.  Monopoly  and  Competition  of  Symbols 

The  degree  to  which  master  symbols  are  publicly  unquestioned 
—and  the  depth  to  which  they  are  internalized  in  persons— varies 
from  one  institutional  order  or  social  structure  to  another.  Two 
contrasting  situations  may  be  constructed. 

I.  Where  master  symbols  are  not  questioned  or  even  invoked  by 
anyone  except  those  authorized  to  do  so,  such  key  terms  monopo- 
lize the  symbol  sphere  and,  other  things  being  equal,  are  likely  to 
be  deeply  internalized.  Then  they  are  so  implicit  in  the  prevailing 
speech,  feeling,  and  thought  that  they  require  no  explicit  justifi- 
cation. Indeed,  they  do  not  require  systematic  articulation,  much 
less  promotion.  This  deep  internalization  is  characteristic  of  tradi- 
tional societies  with  relatively  homogeneous  institutional  composi- 
tion. The  chances  for  master  symbols  to  remain  unquestioned,  and 
hence  internalized,  are  also  increased  by  the  extent  that  tlie  com- 
munication channels  are  monopolized  by  persons  who  secure  and 
justify  authority  by  means  of  particular  symbols. 

When  such  conditions  prevail  there  is  not  much  need  for  taboos 
against  challenging  the  master  symbols,  for  no  one  is  likely  to  do 
so.  The  symbols  are  part  of  the  person's  life,  that  is,  so  tied  in  with 
his  roles  that  he  identifies  himself  with  them  as  he  learns  his  roles. 
Giving  meaning  to  his  motives  for  role-enactments,  they  may  be 
linked  in  turn  to  his  psychic  structure,  so  that  his  very  impulses 
are  mobilized  to  sustain  the  symbols  and  the  roles  which  they 
guarantee.  They  are  the  "existential "  categories  of  which  the  pre- 
vailing philosophers  speak.  If  referred  to  at  all,  they  are  preceded 
by  "of  courses"  and  they  make  up  the  higher  "common  sense"  of  a 
period  and  order.  It  is  difficult  to  examine  them  critically;  as 
alternative  symbols,  much  less  symbols  of  protest,  do  not  exist. 
There  are  no  ideas  available  to  compete  with  the  master  symbols 
and  a  unity  of  style  characterizes  the  symbol  sphere  of  the  whole 
social  structure  and  the  reflective  activities  of  its  more  articulate 
members.  "Happy  indeed,"  Harold  Lasswell  once  remarked,  "is 
that  nation  that  has  no  thought  of  itself;  or  happy  at  least  are  the 


288  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

few    who    procure    the    principal    benefits    of    universal    acquies- 
cence." -* 

II.  If  the  master  symbols  are  questioned  and  articulated  by  some 
persons,  but  not  by  others,  "countersymbols"  may  arise.  These 
countersymbols  may  not  justify  any  actual  institutional  arrange- 
ments, but  in  time  those  who  hold  them  may  project  them  as  part 
of  an  ideal  community  of  the  imagination.  Then  they  may  strive 
to  realize  this  community  in  actuality.  With  such  competition, 
the  master  symbols  will  be  cognitively  elaborated  and  thus  re- 
inforced. It  is  in  controversies  that  symbol  systems  are  tightened 
up.  Theology— the  expert  elaboration  of  the  creed  which  legiti- 
mates a  religious  order— emerges  in  response  to  controversies  over, 
or  attacks  upon,  its  symbols.  The  political  treatise  may  serve  a 
similar  function.  The  modern  conservative  thinking  of  Edmund 
Burke,  De  Maistre,  and  Justus  Moser  crystallized  only  in  answer 
to  the  criticism  of  traditionalism  by  the  philosophers  of  the  "En- 
lightenment." 

The  rise  of  competing  symbols  of  protest  and  their  interplay 
with  symbols  of  justification  may  take  the  following  schematized 
form:  (A)  There  is  doubt  of  the  correctness  of  interpretation  and 
management  of  the  master  symbols.  (B)  This  leads  to  a  more  deep- 
going  doubt,  of  the  master  symbols  themselves,  although  this 
debunking  may  not  yet  be  in  the  name  of  any  set  of  articulated 
countersymbols.  (C)  The  originally  implicit  master  symbols  will, 
to  meet  this  attack,  be  explicitly  reshaped  by  apologists.  Thus,  what 
was  simply  "traditionalist"  becomes  "conservatism":  the  self-reflec- 
tion of  traditionalism.  And  what  was  a  simple  piety  becomes  an 
elaborated  theological  orthodoxy:  a  weapon  against  heterodoxy. 

The  critical  themes  of  the  opponent  will  in  part  be  countered 
directly  and  in  part  they  will  be  "fruitfully  misunderstood"  and 
thus  taken  over  into  the  master  perspective.  Each  major  concept 
will  be  answered  by  a  counterconcept,  each  theme  by  a  counter- 
theme.  Thus,  the  "spirit  of  the  times"  and  the  "awakening  of  the 
people"  was  countered  by  the  conservative  romantic  theme  of  the 
"folk  spirit"  and  the  "slow  and  silent  forces"  of  folk  tradition. 
Blind    spots— that    is,    unanswered    themes— are    of   course    highly 

^•^  Politics  (New  York:   McGraw-Hill,  1936),  p.  30. 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  289 

symptomatic  of  bias.-'^  Thus,  Max  Weber— author  of  the  major 
critique  of  Karl  Marx— was  not  interested  in  the  problem  of  the 
business  cycle  as  crucial  for  capitalist  dynamics,  for  it  did  not  fit 
his  conception  of  capitalism  as  the  apex  of  "rationality."  (D)  All 
these  developments,  in  turn,  may  tend  to  make  what  was  merely  a 
protesting  heterodoxy  into  an  explicit  rival  creed. 

If  the  rival  creed  cannot  be  liquidated  and  is  itself  not  strong 
enough  to  establish  another  monopoly  in  the  symbol  sphere,  a 
"duopoly"  may  arise.  This  is  a  situation  of  accommodation  to  a 
tolerant  though  competitive  co-existence.  Both  of  the  churches  or 
parties  may  unite  against  any  newcomer  and  the  newcomer  may 
make  the  most  of  this  chance  by  playing  off  the  first  "two  big 
ones"  against  each  other.  The  third  camp  may  have  more  chance 
to  use  the  technique  of  general  ridicule  or  cynical  deprecation 
("The  Laughing  Third"). 

In  a  territorially  expanding  society  complete  control  of  new 
groups  may  be  impossible  because  they  have  ample  opportunity 
to  escape  in  a  physical  sense.  The  history  of  religious  tolerance  in 
America,  up  to  the  Mormons,  illustrates  this  tolerance  by  emi- 
gration. 

In  the  course  of  time,  former  conflicts  recede  and  are  forgotten. 
Then  new  mergers  become  possible:  differences  which  make  no 
difference  in  practice  will  in  time  be  forgotten  as  differences  in 
theory.  The  interpretation  of  theological  fine  points  is  neutralized 
—for  the  sake  of  institutional  weight  and  the  advantages  of  big- 
ness. This  is  the  more  likely  to  occur  in  the  face  of  a  common  foe: 
United  States  Protestant  sects,  which  once  competed  with  one 
another,  may  put  up  a  common  front  in  the  face  of  an  expanding 
Catholicism.  The  Southern  and  Northern  Methodists  officially  came 
together  two  generations  after  the  slavery  issue  had  been  settled. 
Thus  out  of  competition  there  occurs  a  move  toward  concentration. 

One  or  several  of  the  competitors  increasingly  wins  out,  and  the 
smaller  units,  eager  to  avail  themselves  of  the  prestige  of  the  big 
winner,  will  jump  on  the  band  wagon.  Symbol  cartels  will  thus  be 
formed.  In  such  situations  there  will  be  a  lowering  of  standards  for 
the  sake  of  more  effective  and  "open"  propaganda.  Another  general 
mode  of  concentration  occurs  by  the  alliance  of  a  few  big  imits 

25  Cf.  Karl  Mannheim,  op.  cit. 


2g0  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

for  the  more  eflFective  suppression  of  a  number  of  small  fry  who 
are  thus  gobbled  up. 

On  the  other  hand,  a  practically  insignificant  unit  may  make  a 
virtue  of  necessity.  Its  very  lack  of  appeal  may  motivate  its  ad- 
herents to  consider  their  alienation  and  their  withdrawn  ways  of 
life  and  thought  as  superior.  Rigid  exclusiveness  for  the  sake  of 
maintaining  standards  of  purity  and  orthodoxy  are  frequently  ob- 
served among  sectarians.  With  the  expansion  of  adherents,  leaders 
may  become  more  "broadminded,"  and  viewpoints  with  previously 
sharp  profiles  may  become  more  diffuse  and  blurred. 

Three  factors  are  important  in  giving  rise  to  competition  among 
symbols  of  legitimacy:  (A)  a  diversity  of  institutional  composition, 
(B)  a  rapid  turnover,  or  dynamic,  of  institutions,  and  (C)  a  rela- 
tively easy  access  of  persons  holding  differing  opinions  to  the  chan- 
nels of  communication.  This  latter  condition  may  come  about  by 
the  rise  of  new  media  and  techniques  of  symbol  diffusion.  Thus 
Luther  was  able  to  capitalize  on  the  invention  of  movable  type 
carried  by  itinerant  printers  and  to  outcompete  the  hand-copying 
monk.  Such  conditions  increase  the  chances  that  no  one  set  of  sym- 
bols will  monopolize  and  unify  the  orders  which  make  up  the 
total  society.  They  lead  to  the  onset  of  the  dialectic  of  competing 
creeds  which  we  have  outlined  above. 

Institutional  diversity  and  conflict  may  exist  (A)  among  the 
institutions  which  make  up  a  single  institutional  order,  as  when 
two  religions  compete  for  adherents,  or  when  two  revolutionary 
parties  agitate  in  and  over  the  political  order.  The  master  symbols 
which  compete  will  then  be  different  symbols  yet  of  the  same 
order.  The  diversity  and  conflict  may,  however,  (B)  be  between 
different  orders  within  a  social  structiu'e,  as  when  religious  institLi- 
tions  conflict  with  those  of  the  political  order.  Then  state  and 
church,  secular  and  religious  parties,  compete  for  loyalties,  and 
specialists,  as  in  totalitarian  dictatorships,  may  seek  to  debunk, 
prevent,  hollow  out,  or  otherwise  take  over  for  their  own  ends 
those  religious  symbols  that  conflict  with  undivided  allegiance 
to  the  charismatic  symbols  of  the  dictator's  claim.  Finally  (C)  the 
disharmony  may  be  between  two  different  social  structures,  as 
when  nations  compete  within  each  of  their  respective  confines 
and/or  across  a  third  country  for  the  adherence  to  their  respective 
symbols  of  national  loyalty. 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  2gi 

When  the  roles  men  enact  change  more  rapidly  than  the  legiti- 
mating symbols  which  lend  meaning  to  them,  individnals  may  be- 
come alienated  from  the  symbols  and  even  abandon  them  for  some 
competing  set.  Dnring  revolntions  role  strnctures  may  be  broken 
up  and  made  meaningless  to  practice.  Men  wake  up,  the  morning 
alter,  believing  firmly  in  master  symbols  they  had  not  thought  of 
during  the  time  of  terror  and  panic.  Then  self-elected  elites  may 
say,  with  Yeats:  "The  best  lack  all  conviction,  while  the  worst 
are  full  of  passionate  intensity."  -° 

If,  through  competition,  the  master  symbols  are  made  articulate, 
symbols  venerated  as  absolutely  true  by  some  may  by  others  be 
treated  or  even  believed  in  as  "mere  opinions."  It  is  in  such  a 
situation,  when  beliefs  are  less  absolutely  held,  that  tolerance  may 
emerge.  Tolerance  and  compromise  as  features  of  a  symbol  sphere 
are  found  where  former  contrasts  of  either-or  have  become  less 
compulsive,  and  indeed,  no  longer  vital  to  the  persons  involved. 

When  one  set  of  religious  institutions  forms  the  only  "religion" 
available,  and  the  religious  order  is  dominant  in  the  social  struc- 
ture, then  its  symbols  will  not  be  questioned:  absolute  adherence 
to  them  is  the  only  road  to  salvation. 

But  in  a  social  structure  where  the  religious  order  is  not  domi- 
nant, and  where  the  symbols  of  religious  institutions  are  diverse 
and  contradictory,  the  tolerant  belief  arises  that  one  set  of  symbols 
may  be  as  true  or  as  wise  as  another,  or  at  any  rate  that  other  per- 
sons who  hold  differing  symbols,  or  even  none  at  all,  may  not  be 
entirely  damned.  Religious  agencies  such  as  "Bible  Institutes"  may 
argue  about  whether  Buddhism  is  worse  or  better  than  Cliiistianity, 
or  a  Lessing  (in  his  "Nathan  the  Wise")  may  expound  tolerance 
and  the  equal  worth  of  the  three  rings.  Christian,  Mohammedan, 
Hebrew.  Many  may  feel  that  all  the  diversities  are  equally  worth 
while,  and  few  will  ostracize  those  who  adhere  to  differing  sym- 
bols. Symbol  experts  fulfilling  official  roles  in  religious  institutions 
—teachers  of  theology,  for  example— may  try  to  solve  the  problems 
of  the  variegated  symbol  sphere  by  talking  from  such  an  abstract 
level  as  to  find  that,  after  all,  they  are  "basically,"  or  in  the  last 
analysis,  the  same. 

And   similar   processes   work   in    the   political   order.    Wilsonian 

-6  W.  B.  Yeats,  "The  Second  Coming,"  The  Collected  Poems  of  W.  B.  Yeats 
(2nd  ed.;  New  York:   Macmillan,   1950),  p.   185. 


2Q2  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

idealism  of  World  War  I  could  not  be  effectively  renovated  during 
World  War  II,  nor  could  it  be  revived  in  connection  with  the 
United  Nations.  The  disillusionment  in  the  wake  of  World  War  I, 
and  the  many  crises  between  the  two  wars  prevented  it.  Political 
tracts  advocating  "faith  for  living"  are  usually  more  indicative  of 
the  will  to  believe  than  of  the  actual  faith. 

If  symbols  are  held  as  absolute,  their  adherents  may  be  intoler- 
ant of  beliefs  different  from  their  own.  Absolute  belief  justifies 
and  motivates  the  actions  of  the  propagandist  who  would  convert 
others  and  thus  spread  his  faith.  On  the  other  hand,  the  decline  of 
"crusading"  democracy  and  the  growth  of  a  conscious  propaganda 
of  democracy  in  the  late  thirties  in  America  may  mean  that  the 
symbols  of  this  kind  of  political  order  are  not  felt  to  be  held  with 
sufficient  surety  in  the  face  of  the  threat  of  war  with  dictatorial 
political  systems. 

The  tolerance  and  compromise  allowed  or  available  in  given 
symbol  spheres  vary  according  to  the  estimation  and  condition  of 
the  orders  in  which  the  symbols  are  anchored.  In  a  typical  Ameri- 
can town,  tolerance  of  economic  and  labor-business  differences 
has  "increased  markedly  in  recent  decades,"  whereas  tolerance  of 
"deviant"  religious  creeds  and  practices  has  diminished."  -^  If 
men  don't  really  care  about  the  issues  at  stake  in  a  given  order, 
they  are  likely  to  be  tolerant  in  that  order.  Thus  by  examining 
what  men  are  intolerant  about  one  finds  out  what  really  matters 
to  them.  In  contrast,  when  men  believe  that  only  their  enemies 
have  the  power  to  be  successful  bigots,  they  see  the  value  of  toler- 
ance. Two  religions,  each  claiming  to  monopolize  the  only  toll 
bridge  to  salvation,  will  tolerate  each  other  if  they  are  persuaded! 
that  they  cannot  destroy  each  other. 

Tolerance  in  the  symbol  sphere  must  of  course  be  distinguished  i 
from  toleration  of  deviant  and  threatening  practices.  Symbol  dif- 
ferences may  be  tolerated  only  by  those  who  do  not  expect  them 
to  be  translated  into  threatening  practices.  This  means  that  those 
who  are  thought  to  be  less  powerful  ("ridiculous"  and  "harm- 
less") may  be  the  more  readily  tolerated.  "Parlor  Socialism"  for 
gentlemen  may  be  permitted,  even  though  labor  unions  for  workers 
are  frowned  upon  or  forbidden.  A  skillful  ruler  acting  for  the  status 

-^  See  Robert  S.  and  Helen  M.  Lynd,  Middletown  in  Transition  (New  York: 
Harcourt,  Brace,  1937). 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  293 

quo  may  absorb  new  threats  by  the  cynical  opportunism  of  kindly 
tolerance  and  adroit  compromise.  In  conversation  the  pohtely 
nodding  head  of  tolerance  may  hide  timid  ignorance  and  that 
genial  hypocrisy  which  is  the  death  of  thought.  The  decisive  ques- 
tion of  tolerance  is  always:  tolerance  in  whose  favor? 

A  strong  ruler  unafraid  of  some  "tangential"  challenge  may 
"tolerate"  it  and  thereby  "take  the  wind  out  of  its  sails."  All  mod- 
ern constitutional  regimes  have  "tolerated"  more  and  more  voters 
to  come  to  the  polls— to  the  extent  to  which  stronger  party  organi- 
zations could  effectively  control  such  voting.  The  strategy  of 
British  Empire  politics  may  also  be  recalled,  as  well  as  the  history 
of  compulsory  education  and  the  expansion  of  newspaper  circula- 
tion. The  original  sponsors  of  "equal  rights  for  women"— socialists 
and  progressive  suffragettes  of  bourgeois  background— found  that 
many  housewives,  following  patriotic  and  religious  appeals  with 
prompt  attention,  vote  more  conservatively  than  do  their  husbands. 
In  this  case,  "tolerance"  was  an  adjustment  of  authority  which  but- 
tressed the  dominating  structiu'e  rather  than  challenged  it. 

Tolerance  may,  however,  work  in  favor  of  the  intolerant;  the 
Weimar  Republic  and  Nazism  is  a  recent  example.  Hitler  and  his 
movement  were  ridiculed  as  "playing  the  soldier,"  and  were  able 
to  profit  by  this  minimization  of  their  stature.  Being  tolerated  they 
could  bide  their  time  and  wait  for  their  opportunity,  which  was 
provided  by  depression.  The  "playing  soldiers"  were  thus  held  in- 
tact and  ready  to  capitalize  on  the  decisive  shift  in  votes.  The 
question  of  tolerance,  therefore,  becomes  a  question  of  what  sort 
of  organization  is  built  up  under  its  protection.  In  England  and 
other  countries  there  has  been  an  intolerant  outlawing  of  "private 
uniforms"  and  political  haberdashery. 

Relative  strength  and  the  espousal  of  tolerance  as  a  value  may 
be  briefly  systematized  in  this  way: 

I.  A  strong  party  can  afford  to  be  tolerant  of  deviation  or  even  of 
opposition— at  least  up  to  a  point.  This  characterizes  a  ruling  stra- 
tum of  multiple  elites  without  over-all  bureaucratic  organization. 
Or,  as  Madame  de  Stael  once  remarked,  "If  a  nation  is  to  have 
the  courage  to  laugh  at  itself,  it  must  be  conscious  of  its  superior 
strength."  -"  II.  A  strong  party  can  also  afford  to  suppress  all  oppo- 
sition and  criticism  by  organizing  ruling  elites  and  functions  and 

-*  Cf.  De  L'Allemagne,  critical  edition  prepared  by  Comtesse  Leon  de 
Prange    (Paris:    Hachette,  to  be  published). 


2g4  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

all  authoritative  positions  into  a  central  machine;  for  example,  the 
totalitarian  party.  III.  A  weak  party  may  plead  for  tolerance,  which 
means  the  freedom  to  continue  in  its  own  ways  of  conduct  and 
thought.  Thus,  during  their  struggle  for  power,  totalitarian  parties 
will  most  jealously  plead  for  "the  democratic  liberties"  which,  once 
in  power,  they  promptly  suppress.  IV.  A  weak  party  may  be  in- 
tolerant of  internal  deviation,  enforcing  strict  discipline  upon  the 
in-group  members,  and  imposing  upon  them  a  pattern  of  "organ- 
ized thought"  in  order  to  increase  their  cohesion  and  striking 
power. 

In  summary,  symbol  spheres  may  be  monopolized  by  one  set  of 
legitimating  symbols  which  are  so  deeply  internalized  they  do  not 
need  to  be  defended.  If  they  are  questioned,  persons  become 
articulate  about  them  and  jump  to  their  defense  as  absolutes.  The 
existence  of  such  symbol  spheres  is  conditioned  by  institutional 
harmony  within  and  between  various  orders,  by  a  slow  rate  of  in- 
stitutional change  and  by  a  monopoly  of  the  channels  of  communi- 
cation and  persuasion.  When  the  reverse  of  these  three  conditions 
exists,  the  chances  for  countersymbols  of  legitimacy  to  emerge  are 
increased.  When  there  is  competition  among  symbols,  some  of 
them  may  be  debunked,  and  various  persons  may  hold  them  merely 
as  "opinions,"  whereas  others  may  be  completely  alienated  from 
them;  indeed,  whole  populations  may  become  alienated  from  one 
set  of  symbols  and  shift  allegiance  to  other  symbols  which  make 
more  sense  in  terms  of  actual  or  expected  practices.  In  certain 
competitive  situations,  tolerance  and  compromise  may  emerge  as 
general  features  of  the  symbol  sphere.  Thus  the  legitimacy  of  pub- 
lic competition  in  ideas  has  been  part  of  the  creed  of  parliamentary 
democracy  of  the  modern  constitutional  state.  Totalitarian  parties 
and  states  have  typically  claimed  "the  freedom  to  propagandize" 
in  the  name  of  "democracy"  in  order  to  overthrow  this  system. 

3.  Communication 

Out  of  the  total  range  of  symbols  socially  available,  each  person 
picks  up  certain  symbols  which  he  passes  on  to  others.  Each  per- 
son who  faces  the  total  volume  of  symbols  transmits  a  selected 
number  and  a  selectively  arranged  portion  of  the  total.  Generally, 
we  speak  of  manipulation  or  management  of  symbols  when  this 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  2g,'^ 

channeling  and  rearranging  of  selected  symbols  is  done  consciously 
and  in  an  organized  way.  Competition  among  symbols  referring 
to  given  objects  or  legitimating  different  institutional  roles  may 
lead  to  the  purposive  manipulation  or  management  of  the  spheres 
of  symbols  by  symbol  experts. 

In  a  stratified  society  is  it  possible  to  debunk  or  to  build  up  a 
given  stratum  by  selecting  the  symbols  which  are  used  to  repre- 
sent it.  To  de\aluate  a  religious,  political,  or  ethnic  group,  one 
selects  the  lowest  representative  of  the  group— of  the  Jewish  com- 
munity, e.g.— and  generalizes  him  as  "the  Jew."  To  build  up  a 
group  or  stratum  one  focuses  upon  the  "best"  representative,  select- 
ing those  traits  that  are  most  approved  of  by  those  to  whom  one 
would  build  up  the  group,  and  generalizes  him  as  "the  Jew."  Such 
images  are  known  as  stereotypes.  They  are  symbols  built  out  of  a 
selection  of  alleged  traits  yet  represented  as  the  whole  truth. 
Stereotypes  which  debunk  or  build  up  a  group  may  not  be  set 
forth  in  their  totality  at  any  one  time.  A  newspaper,  for  instance, 
may  use  the  symbol  "Negro"  every  time  a  Negro  commits  a  petty 
crime,  but  avoid  mentioning  "Negro"  when  a  Negro  performs  some 
meritorious  act.  The  stereotype  of  "Negro"  is  thus  built  from  an 
accumulation  of  incidents  with  which  the  symbol  is  associated. 

When  a  small-town  youngster  goes  to  a  big  city  and  does  well, 
the  town's  newspaper  may  carry  the  story:  Podunk  boy  makes 
good.  But  if  he  gets  lost  in  the  anonymity  of  the  city  and  wanders 
into  crime,  the  local  newspaper  may  not  play  the  fact  up.  By  select- 
ing from  the  totality  of  world,  national,  and  local  affairs,  the  story 
of  the  local  youngster  who  grew  up  to  make  $50,000  a  year,  the 
glory  of  his  success  is  reflected  on  the  symbol,  Podunk.  His  success 
is  shared;  ascribed  in  part  to  the  community.  His  failures  are  ig- 
nored, or  ascribed  to  him  alone.  The  stereotyped  image  of  Podunk 
is  built  up  to  the  accumulation  of  such  stories  and  by  the  omis- 
sion of  other  types  of  fact.  At  the  same  time,  a  generally  optimistic 
tone  of  individual  success  is  maintained  in  the  sphere  of  symbols. 

We  may  distinguish  several  ways  in  which  conduct  is  positively 
or  negatively  stereotyped,  and  ascribed  to  the  individual  alone  or 
to  groups  to  which  he  belongs  by  virtue  of  actual  or  past  member- 
ship: 

I.  Meritorious  conduct  may  be  strictly  ascribed  to  the  individ- 
ual, as  in  the  case  of  Homer's  build-up  of  Achilles,  or  as  in  the 
modern  cult  of  genius.  In  legend,  the  family  of  descent  is  often 


2g6  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

entirely  eradicated  by  means  of  an  ascription  of  divine  origin,  or 
by  "foundling"  sagas.  II.  Liabilities  of  conduct  may  be  ascribed 
strictly  to  the  individual,  as  in  contemporary  democratic  court 
proceedings.  III.  Meritorious  conduct  may  be  ascribed  to  the  in- 
dividual as  a  representative  of  a  group  whose  members  are  eager 
to  share  in  the  prestige  accretion  of  their  outstanding  members. 
This  occurs  in  the  construction  of  self-images  by  groups  and  col- 
lectivities, as  when  Americans  see  themselves  as  in  the  "land  of 
the  free  and  the  brave,"  or  nineteenth-century  Germans  saw  them- 
selves as  a  "nation  of  poets  and  thinkers."  IV.  Conduct  liabilities 
may  be  typically  ascribed  by  dominant  groups  to  the  individual 
as  a  representative  of  despised  lower  or  hostile  out-groups.  In  the 
Soviet  Union  and  its  orbit,  "bourgeois"  descent— for  the  failure- 
is  never  an  "accident,"  just  as  in  Nazi  Germany  "Jewish  descent" 
was  the  reference  point  for  alleged  criminal  dispositions,  despite  all 
statistical  evidence  to  the  contrary. 

In  the  selecting  and  editing  of  symbols  referring  to  nations,  all 
these  processes  may  be  observed.  Nations  compete  for  prestige  with 
other  nations  in  terms  of  symbols  and  events  which  are  associated 
by  symbol  manipulations,  with  stereotyped  images  of  the  whole. 
To  an  inhabitant  of  nineteenth-century  India,  "the  British"  may  be 
an  irate  man  with  battleships,  troops,  and  whipping  canes;  a  beef- 
eating  barbarian  who  consumes  alcohol  on  so  supreme  a  religious 
occasion  as  The  Lord's  Supper.  But  in  the  edited  sphere  of  sym- 
bols, "British"  may  appear  to  Englishmen  as  a  rotund  gentleman 
surrounded  by  "tricky  natives,"  or  a  nation  of  small  shopkeepers 
trying  honestly  to  get  along  in  the  world.  During  wartime,  "Uncle 
Sam"  gets  a  fierce  compelling  look  in  his  cartooned  eyes  as  he 
points  his  finger  at  you.  The  superegos  of  some  members  of  the 
public  may  be  stimulated  by  such  compulsive  figures.  The  guilt 
feelings  thus  engendered  may  increase  the  participation  of  for- 
tune, time,  and  life  in  the  war  effort. 

A  nation  becomes  "one  and  indivisible"  through  a  continual 
process  of  communalization.  This  communalization  is  directed  by 
those  strata  that  successfully  address  their  political  expectations 
to  the  rest  of  the  population  in  the  name  of  the  "nation."  To  the 
extent  to  which  this  process  is  successful,  "a  nation  one  and  in- 
divisible" exists.  The  most  effective  symbols  implementing  the 
process  are  those  of  common  historical  fate,  of  common  triumphs 
of  the  past:   national  history  bespeaking  of  grandeur;  a  national 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  2^J 

mission;  assurance  of  the  nation's  worth  for  mankind.  The  em- 
phases, as  between  the  past  or  the  future,  may  shift.  When  the 
"Americaji  dream"  is  no  longer  stressed,  or  does  not  seem  uni- 
linear and  unambiguous,  the  press  may  demand  greater  emphasis 
on  instruction  in  the  nation's  history  as  beneficent  to  civic  morale 
and  patriotism.  History  teaching  is,  of  course,  subject  to  selective 
emphases  and  stylizations  stemming  from  patriotic  loyalties  rather 
than  scientific  detachment.-^  Much  of  the  national  historiography 
of  the  nineteenth  century  falls  under  the  same  heading:  Germany 
had  her  Treitschke,  Great  Britain  her  Seeley.  The  American  Mahan, 
as  the  philosopher  and  historian  of  "seapower,"  could  hardly  have 
emerged  on  Prussian  soil,  and  neither  could  a  Delbriick,  the  Ger- 
man historian  of  warfare,  arise  in  a  great  maritime  power.  "His- 
tory," it  is  often  said,  is  concerned  with  the  past  that  is  "dead," 
but  as  an  ongoing  enterprise  it  is  of  vital  concern  to  the  living  in  an 
age  of  nations  with  rival  claims  to  disputed  areas,  new  boundaries, 
and  opportunities  seized  and  justified  in  terms  of  "historical  rights." 
In  a  world  where  primary  experience  has  been  replaced  by  sec- 
ondary communications— the  printed  page,  the  radio,  and  the  pic- 
ture screen— the  chances  for  those  in  control  of  these  media  to 
select,  associate,  manipulate,  and  diffuse  symbols  are  increased.  In 
the  twentieth  century,  a  unified  symbol  sphere,  one  monopolized 
by  certain  master  symbols,  is  more  likely  to  be  the  result  of  a 
monopoly  of  the  channels  of  communications,  and  of  a  forceful 
tabooing  of  countersymbols,  than  the  result  of  any  harmonious 
institutional  basis.  It  is  more  likely  to  be  imposed  than  to  grow. 
But  the  symbols  which  are  thus  made  masterful  are  not  likely  to 
be  so  deeply  and  unquestioningly  internalized  as  those  arising  as 
adequate  and  meaningful  expressions  of  a  harmony  of  institution- 
ahzed  roles.  Where  there  are  deep  antagonisms  in  the  institutional 
structure,  men  seeking  to  transform  power  into  authority  may  grasp 
all  the  more  compulsixely  for  the  channels  of  mass  communica- 
tion, but  their  monopolization  of  these  media  does  not  necessarily 
mean  that  the  symbols  they  diffuse  will  be  master  symbols. 

-»  See  B.  Pierce,  Civic  Attitudes  in  American  School  Textbooks  (Chicago: 
Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,   1930). 


2q8  social   structure 

4.  The  Autonomy  of  Symbol  Spheres 

In  the  scholar's  study  or  the  agitator's  den  the  symbols  which 
legitimate  various  kinds  of  political  systems  may  be  rearranged, 
debunked,  or  elaborated.  But  such  logical  manipulations  of  master 
symbols  by  intellectuals  do  not  of  themselves  change  the  legiti- 
mating symbols  to  which  the  great  bulk  of  persons  are  attached. 
For  changes  in  the  legitimating  symbols  to  be  realized,  masses 
of  people  must  shift  their  allegiances. 

Hulme,  from  whom  we  have  quoted  above,  believed  that  the 
master  symbols  are  "the  source  of  all  the  other  more  material 
characteristics  of  a  period";  not  "men"  but  "ideas"  make  history. 
This  is  an  unfortimate  manner  of  statement;  as  a  matter  of  fact,  it 
is  magic.  Unless  symbols  are  tied  to  the  roles  enacted  in  institu- 
tional orders,  unless  they  lend  meaning  and  even  sacredness  to 
these  roles,  they  will  not  even  be  master  symbols.  They  will  merely 
be  little  marks  on  paper  or  breath  going  over  vocal  cords.  Symbols 
can  "make  a  difference "  only  if  they  answer  to  some  feature  of  the 
character  structure  and  the  roles  of  individuals,  and  these  character 
structures  and  roles  are  shaped  in  large  part  by  institutional  ar- 
rangements. To  the  extent  that  the  symbol  sphere  is  truly  autono- 
mous, it  does  not  count  in  the  dynamics  of  the  institutional  struc- 
ture. An  autonomous  dynamics  of  the  symbols  sphere  implies  the 
detachment  of  persons  from  it,  and  detachment  is  a  step  towards 
alienation.  To  say  that  there  is  no  symbol  order,  but  rather  a  sym- 
bol sphere,  or  symbol  spheres,  is  to  deny  this  "idealistic"  theory 
of  history  and  society.  And  only  if  one  set  of  symbols  were  success- 
fully imposed  upon  virtually  all  of  a  population  could  we  speak 
strictly  of  "common  values." 

If  the  character  of  the  master  symbols  sets  the  character  of  a 
social  structure,  then  a  monopolization  of  the  communication  of 
symbols  would  enable  the  monopolizers  to  create  new  institutions 
by  diffusing  certain  kinds  of  would-be  master  symbols.  And  we 
know  that  this  is  not  the  case.  Propagation  of  symbols  is  effective 
only  so  long  as  they  have  some  meaningful  relevance  to  the  roles, 
institutions,  and  feelings  which  characterize  a  people.  Symbols 
cannot  create  these  roles.  It  is  in  terms  of  their  relevance  or  lack 
of  relevance  to  persons  and  institutions  that  the  free  competition 
of  autonomously  developed  symbols  will  be  decided.  Only  in  this 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  299 

sense  may  we  speak  of  the  autonomy  of  symbol  spheres  in  certain 
kinds  of  social  structure.  "Governments"  do  not  necessarily,  as 
Emerson  put  it,  "have  their  origin  in  the  moral  identity  of  men." 
This  is  to  confuse  the  legitimations  of  government  with  its  causes. 
Just  as  often,  or  even  more  so,  the  moral  identities  of  men  have 
their  origins  in  governmental  institutions  which  successfully  im- 
pose their  symbol  spheres. 

One  hundred  years  ago  the  matter  was  fruitfully  discussed  in 
terms*  of  the  assumptions  typically  made  by  many  of  those  who 
believe  that  the  dynamics  of  the  symbol  sphere  is  self-determining 
and  that  it  may  dominate  history:  ""  (A)  The  symbols  which  justify 
some  authority  are  separated  from  the  actual  persons  or  strata  that 
exercise  this  authority.  (B)  The  "ideas"  are  then  thought  to  rule, 
not  the  strata  or  the  persons  using  the  ideas.  (C)  In  order  to  lend 
continuity  to  the  sequence  of  these  symbols,  they  are  presented 
as  connected  in  some  "mystical"  way  with  one  another.  The  sym- 
bols are  thus  seen  as  having  an  autonomous  "self-determination." 
(D)  To  make  more  plausible  the  odd  notion  that  symbols  are 
"self-determining,"  they  are  "personalized"  or  given  "self-conscious- 
ness." They  may  then  be  conceived  as  the  concepts  of  history  or 
as  a  sequence  of  "philosophers"  whose  thinking  determine  insti- 
tutional dynamics. 

Symbols  which  are  often  written  about  as  "values"  are  histori- 
cally and  sociologically  irrelevant  unless  they  are  anchored  in  con- 
duct. They  become  relevant  when  they  justify  institutions,  and/or 
motivate  persons  to  create  or  at  least  to  enact  roles.  There  is  un- 
doubtedly an  interplay  of  justifying  symbols,  institutional  author- 
ity, and  role-enacting  persons.  At  times  we  should  not  hesitate  to 
assign  causal  weight  to  master  symbols— but  not  as  a,  much  less 
the,  theory  of  social  unity.  There  axe  ways  of  constructing  unity 
that  are  more  flexibly  geared  to  a  lower  level  of  generality,  closer 
to  empirically  observable  materials. -^^ 

It  seems  to  us  the  better  procedure  to  build  up  to  such  symbolic 
unity  or  "common  values"  as  a  social  structure  may  display  by 
examining  the  symbol  spheres  of  each  of  its  institutional  orders, 
rather  than  to  begin  by  attempting  first  to  grasp  "common  sym- 

30  Cf.  K.  Marx  and  F.  Engels,  op.  cit.,  pp.  42  fl. 

31  As  we  shall  see  below.  Chapter  XII:  The  Unity  of  Social  Structures. 


200  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

bols"  and  then  in  their  Hght  to  "explain"  the  society's  composi- 
tion and  unity. 

There  is  of  course  a  symboHc  aspect  to  social  integration. (If 
all,  or  nearly  all,  members  of  an  institutional  order  internalize  the 
order's  legitimations}  accept  and  adhere  to  these  symbols, (we  may 
speak  of  "common  values,"  or  in  other  terms,  master  symbols  of 
legitimations^  Such  legitimations  do  involve  an  evaluative  aspect; 
as  the  terms  in  which  obedience  is  claimed,  (master  symbols  are 
used  as  yardsticks  for  the  evaluation  of  the  conduct  of  institutions 
and  actors!)  Such  symbols  ramify  throughout  the  institutional  or- 
der so  as  to  "define  the  situations"  of  various  roles.  Social  struc- 
tures, which  are  thus  integrated  through  universal  adherence  and 
acceptance  of  such  central  symbols,  are  naturally  extreme  and 
"pure"  types. 

(At  the  other  end  of  the  typological  scale,  we  find  societies  in 
which  a  dominant  institution  controls  the  total  social  structure 
and  superimposes  its  values  and  legitimations  by  violence  and  the 
threat  of  violence]  This  need  by  no  means  involve  a  breakdown  of 
the  social  structure;  all  institutions  and  roles  for  technical  reasons 
simply  involve  the  effective  conditioning  of  persons  by  formal  disci- 
pline so  that  unless  they  accept  the  institutional  demands  for 
discipline  the  majority  of  the  actors  do  not  have  any  chance  to 
earn  a  living.  A  skilled  compositor  employed  by  a  reactionary  news- 
paper, for  example,  may  for  the  sake  of  making  a  living  and  holding 
his  job  conform  to  the  demands  of  employer  discipline.  In  his 
heart,  and  outside  the  shop,  he  may  be  a  radical  agitator.  Many 
German  socialists  allowed  themselves  to  become  perfectly  disci- 
plined soldiers  under  the  Kaiser's  flag— despite  the  fact  that  their 
subjective  values  were  those  of  revolutionary  Marxism.  It  is  a  long 
way  from  symbols  to  conduct  and  back  again,  and  not  all  integra- 
tion is  based  on  symbols. 

The  emphasis  on  such  disparities  does  not  of  course  mean  a 
denial  of  "the  force  of  rational  consistencies."  Just  as  discrepancies 
between  words  and  deeds  are  often  characteristic,  so  also  is  the 
striving  for  consistency.  The  question  whether  or  not  discrepancy 
or  consistency  is  socially  effective  and  predominant  can  be  decided 
a  priori  neither  on  the  basis  of  "human  nature"  nor  on  the  "principles 
of  sociology";  it  must  be  decided  in  terms  of  socially  and  histori- 
cally situated  responses.  We  might  well  construe  a  pure  type  in 
terms  of  perfectly  disciplined  social  structure  in  which  all  domi- 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  ^01 

nated  men,  for  a  variety  of  reasons,  cannot  afford  to  quit  their  in- 
stitutionally prescribed  roles,  but  who  nevertheless  share  none  of 
the  dominator's  values,  and  thus  in  no  way  believe  in  the  legiti- 
macy of  the  order.  Such  a  social  structure  would  be  run  like  a 
ship  manned  by  galley  slaves;  due  to  the  disciplined  movement  of 
the  oars,  the  individual  is  reduced  to  a  cog  in  a  machine,  and  the 
violence  of  the  whipmaster  may  only  rarely  be  needed.  The  galley 
slaves  need  not  even  be  aware  of  the  ship's  direction  under  their 
propulsion,  although  any  turn  of  the  bow  might  evoke  the  wrath 
of  the  master  who  sees  ahead  and  steers  the  boat. 

(^Between  these  two  polar  typesj-of  a  "common  value  system" 
and  of  a  superimposed  discipline  incapable  of  being  broken  by 
the  institutionalized  members  of  the  structure-fthere  are  numer- 
ous forms  of  social  integration/  For  example,  it  takes  a  long  time 
for  a  social  structure  to  be  totally  revolutionized.  Most  occidental 
societies  have  been  able  to  incorporate  many  divergent  value 
orientations,  as  long  as  the  legitimacy  of  the  political  order  could 
be  successfully  imposed.  The  origin  of  such  a  dominant  order 
has  been  quite  various,  ranging  from  forceful  imposition  to  the 
instituting  of  an  order  by  a  covenant  of  its  beneficiaries.  In  the 
former,  the  submission  of  the  subjects  to  the  superimposed  order 
may  be  a  result  of  accommodation,  compromise,  or  renunciation 
of  their  own  values;  in  the  latter,  joint  agreement  precedes  the 
order. 

Such  unity,  involving  various  degrees  and  mixtures  of  legitima- 
tion and  coercion,  may  be  found  in  any  order,  not  only  in  the 
political  and  economic.  A  father  may  impose  a  specific  order  over 
all  family  members  by  threatening  to  withhold  inheritance  or  his 
necessary  consent  to  a  minor's  wishes,  or  by  the  use  of  such  force 
as  the  political  order  may  allow  him.  \But,  in  any  case,  "common 
values,"  as  a  unified  symbol  sphere,  are  not  necessary  in  order  to 
secure  integration  and  unity.) 

Fruitful  questions  about  symbol  spheres  are  usually  quite  spe- 
cific: What  kind  of  conduct  or  institution  does  this  or  that  symbol 
motivate  and  guarantee?  In  what  orders  are  given  symbols  to  be 
found  and  what  is  their  precise  function  therein?  Symbols  may 
influence  conduct  if  they  are  relevant  to  the  roles  men  enact;  roles, 
in  turn,  are  components  of  institutions.  And  the  dynamics  of  insti- 


^02  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

tutions,  and  of  their  component  roles,  determine  the  content,  range, 
and  character  of  spheres  of  symbols  more  than  the  symbols  deter- 
mine institutional  history. 

[A  person  may  incorporate,  believe  in,  and  use  a  symbol  which 
motivates  a  role  which  he  does  not  enact,  or  legitimate  an  institu- 
tion to  which  he  does  not  belongjit  is  not  necessary  to  be  a  priest 
in  order  to  repeat  the  formula  about  the  doctrinal  infallibility  of 
the  pope.  Yet  this  formula  is  important  primarily  in  the  college  of 
cardinals,  where  it  insures  against  open  dissent  and  unwanted  dis- 
cussion. Wage  workers  in  modern  capitalist  states  may  repeat  the 
formulae  of  laissez-faire,  although  these  symbols  may  be  against 
the  economists'  imputation  of  the  workers'  rational  interest,  that  is, 
his  interests  as  "adequate"  to  his  economic  and  pohtical  position 
within  the  whole  system  were  he  to  act  "rationally"  as  an  "eco- 
nomic man."  [Such  "mislocated"  adherences  are  increased  by  mod- 
ern techniques  of  mass  communication)  which  are,  on  the  one 
hand,  monopolized  in  favor  of  some  one  type  of  institution,  sys- 
tem, or  authority,  and  on  the  other,  used  to  satisfy  irrational 
fantasies  and  distract  from  both  art  and  reality. 

The  institutional  patterns  of  different  orders  are  not  equally  or 
evenly  implemented  by  means  of  symbols.  The  dominant  symbols 
of  a  whole  social  structure  will  tend  to  be  in  the  symbol  sphere' 
of  its  dominant  institutional  order.  These  symbols  will  legitimate 
the  symbols  and  practices  of  other  orders  as  well  as  those  of  its 
own.  If  the  economic  order  is  the  weightiest  one  within  a  social 
structure,  the  legitimating  symbols  of  the  whole  structure  will 
likely  be  related  to  the  economic  order. 

\Specilic  interests  of  different  institutions  are  defined  in  terms 
of  specialized  symbols  appropriate  to  their  respective  contexts. 
There  are,  however,  symbols  which  with  but  slight  modifications 
may  hold  for  various  institutions  serving  quite  different  ends"^  By 
our  definition,  all  institutions  contain  a  distribution  of  authority. 
The  head  of  the  household,  the  principal  of  the  school,  and  the 
army  officer  have  "authority"  over  the  household,  the  school,  and 
the  army  unit.  The  symbols  implementing  this  distribution  of  au- 
thority may  be  the  same  in  all  these  institutional  contexts:  the 
"democratic"  process  may  be  stressed  in  which  the  head  claims 
no  more  than  the  position  of  the  first  among  equals,  or  an  authori- 
tarian discipline  may  pervade  the  relations  of  institutional  leader 


SYMBOL     S  P  H  E  R  E  S  ^^O^ 

and  subordinates.  The  father  may  be  the  stern  family  despot  to 
his  children,  as  the  officer  may  be  to  his  soldiers  and  the  teacher 
to  his  x'l^'pils.  In  the  latter  case  "orders  are  orders,"  and  there  is  to 
be  "no  back  talk,"  only  harsh  silence. 

The  parallelism  of  such  symbols  in  different  institutional  orders 
may  result  from  the  fact  that  one  institutional  context  is  acknowl- 
edged as  the  model  for  others.  /By  identification  of  teacher  with 
military  officer,  or  of  officer  with  {ather)-by  studious  imitation  of 
the  higher  prestige  bearer's  conduct-ithe  diffusion  of  types  of  au- 
thority and  their  concomitant  symbols  is  effected.  Which  institu- 
tional order  sets  the  model  for  others  and  to  what  extent  depends 
upon  special  historical  and  social  situations.JAt  any  rate,  our  anal- 
ysis, to  be  complete,  must  proceed  as  a  search  for  such  "transmis- 
sion belts  of  authority." 

The  rich  symbols  of  medieval  Europe  were  anchored  as  a  sphere 
of  the  religious  order,  and  the  institutional  structure  of  that  society 
was  in  part  dominated  by  religious  institutions  and  in  part  by 
decentralized  hierarchies  of  knights  bound  by  oaths  to  their  feudal 
superiors  and  their  Christian  emperor.  Out  of  the  religious  order 
and  its  symbols,  the  master  images  and  preconceptions  of  a  whole 
society  were  elaborated.  Symbolic  elaborations  which  were  thought 
irreconcilable  with  those  of  the  religious  order  were  tabooed  or 
repressed.  This  anchorage  of  the  institutions  and  the  master  sym- 
bols of  a  society  in  the  religious  order  has  affected  most  philo- 
sophical work  in  Western  societies,  and  may  still  be  seen  in  the 
attempts  of  various  symbol  experts  to  !'reconcile"  the  symbols 
of  modern  science  and  modern  modes  of  living  and  dying  with 
subtilized  and  attenuated  symbols  and  images  of  the  Christian 
religion.  An  order  thus  seeks  to  extend  its  symbols  and  publicize 
them  as  applicable  to  all  conduct.  In  their  competition  with  other 
agencies  for  the  use  of  increased  leisure  time,  modern  religious 
institutions  have  striven  to  publicize  and  adapt  their  symbols  to 
changing  circumstances.  Books  have  been  written  to  show  how 
Jesus  was  after  all  a  businessman  in  mentality  and  outlook,  thus 
attempting  to  adapt  religious  symbols  to  those  of  the  dominant 
economic  order.  On  the  other  hand,  an  order  may  seek  to  hide 
its  sphere  of  symbols:  a  priesthood  may  hide  its  formulae  and 
doctrines  as  too  esoteric  and  holy  to  be  broadcast,  wliile  at  the 
same  time  developing  an  exoteric  set  of  symbols  for  the  laity. 


;^04  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

We  may  note  in  passing  that  much  of  the  symboHc  materials  of 
the  twentieth  century  are  created  for  the  complex  equipment  of  the 
communication  industries,  for  radio,  phonograph,  television,  and 
movies.  The  movie  actress  does  not  play  before  an  audience,  but 
before  a  small  committee  of  visual  and  acoustic  experts;  the  poet 
reads,  and  the  musician  plays  not  before  an  audience  of  apprecia- 
tive laymen  and  journalists,  but  before  committees  of  recording 
experts. 

The  distributed  product,  whether  it  is  seen  on  the  screen  or 
heard  from  a  disk,  is  a  performance  that  has  been  carefully  se- 
lected from  a  series  of  less  flawless  trials.  The  mass  availability  of 
such  performances  by  star  actors,  orchestras  under  star  conductors, 
and  so  on  require  the  communication  and  amusement  industries 
to  establish  and  market  their  products  as  "brands,"  to  command 
attention  by  the  excellence  of  performance  and  reproduction  stand- 
ards. In  fact,  these  items  often  gain  ascendancy  over  the  content 
or  message  of  the  work  of  art  itself.  Interest  in  mass  marketing  also 
promotes  the  selection  of  what  is  "safe"— the  accepted  and  proved 
work.  The  established  work  of  art— that  is,  the  noncontemporary 
or  the  "classical"— stands  in  the  center,  and  enjoyment  of  art  is  not 
enjoyment  of  the  unheard  of  and  hitherto  unseen,  of  the  experi- 
mental thrust  and  the  eye  opener,  but  of  the  acoustically  stereo- 
typed and  soothing  brand,  in  terms  of  which  the  recognition  of 
the  composer,  opus  number,  and  star  performer  become  conversa- 
tionally prestigeful,  and  accordingly  train  for  regressive  listening. 
The  reduction  of  a  Beethoven  symphony  or  a  Verdi  opera  to  the 
acoustic  dimension  of  a  living  room,  the  photographic  "blow  up" 
or  enlargement  of  a  pictorial  detail,  or  the  photographic  reduction 
of  life  size  to  pocket-book  size,  immerse  twentieth-century  men  in 
a  great  stream  of  mechanically  reproduced  visual  and  acoustic 
images  which  tend  to  treat  the  cultural  legacy  of  the  ages  as  raw 
material  for  industrial  processing.  The  original  work,  torn  from  its 
context  and  aura,  tends  to  be  swept  away  by  the  flood  of  its  varied 
reproductions.  For  this  is  the  age  of  the  mechanical  reproduction 
of  art. 

In  the  face  of  all  this,  the  contemporary  artist  unless  he  turns 
to  "commercial  art"  (which  is  to  say,  the  implementing  of  the 
advertising  interests  of  business  or  the  propaganda  interest  of 
political  groups)  is  pushed  to  the  sidelines.  The  more  his  work 
uncompiomisingly  expresses  the  agony  of  the  sensitive  individual, 


SYMBOL     SPHERES  2'^);^ 

the  more  it  is  felt  to  be  shocking,  perverse,  or  intellectually  man- 
nerist. Business  advertising,  however,  like  totalitarian  propaganda, 
flatters  the  escape-seeking,  untutored  masses  by  endorsing  their 
regressive  nostalgia  under  the  slogan,  "the  customer  is  right." 

Language  is  the  major  key  to  an  understanding  of  many  problems 
of  both  character  and  of  social  structure.  We  have  seen,  par- 
ticularly in  Chapter  V,  that  it  provides  us  with  many  clues  to 
the  motivations  of  the  person.  In  the  present  chapter,  [we  have 
seen  that  language— conceived  as  a  sphere  of  symbols— is  necessary 
to  the  operations  of  institutions.  For  the  symbols  used  in  institu- 
tions co-ordinate  the  roles  that  compose  them,  and  justify  the 
enactment  of  these  roles  by  the  members  of  the  institutionJ  Our 
discussion  has  thus  involved  the  various  ways  in  which  such  master 
symbols  justify  and  sanction  institutional  authority  and  at  the 
same  time  motivate  personal  conduct  in  the  economic  and  kinship, 
the  political  and  military  and  religious  orders. 


CHAPTER 

X  I 

Stratification 
and  Institutional  Orders 


IN  New  York  City  some  people  taxi  home  at  night  from  Madison 
Avenue  offices  to  Sutton  Place  apartments;  others  leave  a  factory 
loft  in  Brooklyn  and  subway  home  to  an  East 'Harlem  tenement. 
In  Detroit  there  is  Grosse  Pointe,  with  environs,  but  there  is  also 
Hamtramck,  without  environs;  and  in  a  thousand  small  towns 
people  live  on  either  side  of  the  railroad  track.  In  Moscow,  lead- 
ing party  members  ride  cautiously  in  black  cars  along  well-policed 
avenues  to  well-policed  suburbs;  other  people  walk  home  from 
factories  to  huddle  in  cramped  apartments.  And  in  the  shadow  of 
swank  Washington,  D.  C,  apartment  houses  there  are  the  dark 
alley  dwellings. 

In  almost  any  community  in  every  nation  there  is  a  high  and 
a  low,  and  in  some  societies,  a  big  in-between. 

If  we  go  behind  what  we  can  thus  casually  observe  and  begin 
to  examine  in  detail  the  twenty-four-hour  cycle  of  behavior  and 
experience,  the  twelve-month  cycle,  the  life-long  biographies  of 
people  in  various  cities  and  nations,  we  will  soon  need  to  classify 
the  people  and  their  behavior.  Otherwise  we  cannot  easily  under- 
stand our  observations.  We  might  well  decide  to  make  our  classi- 
fication in  terms  of  valued  things  and  experiences;  to  find  out  just 
which  people  regularly  expect  to  and  do  receive  how  many  of  the 
available  values,  and  in  each  case,  why.  Such  classifications  are 
the  basis  of  all  work  in  stratification. 

Whatever  the  value  may  be  that  most  jieople  seem  to  want, 
some  people  get  more  of  it  than  others,  and  some  do  not  share 
in  it  at  all.  The  student  of  stratification  is  bent  on  understanding 
the  ranking  of  people  with  respect  to  such  values,  and  in  finding 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  I^Oy 

out  in  what  respects  these  ranks  differ  and  why.  Each  rank  or 
stratum  in  a  society  may  be  viewed  as  a  stratum  by  virtue  of  the 
fact  that  all  of  its  members  have  similar  opportunities  to  get  the 
things  and  experiences  that  are  valued:  things  like  cars,  steady 
and  high  incomes,  toys,  or  houses;  experiences,  like  being  given 
respect,  being  educated  to  certain  levels,  or  being  treated  kindly. 
To  belong  to  one  stratum  or  another  is  to  share  with  the  other 
people  in  this  stratum  similar  advantages. 

If,  again,  we  go  behind  these  strata  of  people  having  similar  life- 
chances,  and  begin  to  analyze  each  stratum  and  the  reasons  for 
its  formation  and  persistence,  sooner  or  later  we  will  come  upon 
at  least  four  important  keys  to  the  whole  phenomenon.  We  call 
these  "dimensions  of  stratification."  Each  provides  a  way  by  which 
we  can  rank  people  in  accordance  with  the  specific  opportunity 
each  has  to  obtain  a  given  value.  And  all  together,  these  dimen- 
sions, if  properly  understood,  enable  us  to  account  for  the  whole 
range  of  these  different  opportunities.  These  four  dimensions  are 
occupation,  class,  status,  and  power: 

By  an  occupation  we  understand  a  set  of  activities  pursued  more 
or  less  regularly  as  a  major  source  of  income. 

Class  situation,  in  its  simplest  objective  sense,  has  to  do  with 
the  amount  and  source  (property  or  work)  of  income  as  these 
affect  the  chances  of  people  to  obtain  other  available  values. 

Status  involves  the  successful  realization  of  claims  to  prestige; 
it  refers  to  the  distribution  of  deference  in  a  society. 

Pawer  refers  to  the  realization  of  one's  will,  even  if  this  involves 
the  resistance  of  others.^ 

Each  of  these  four  "keys"  may  be  related  to  our  conception  of 
institutional  orders  and  spheres,  and  in  turn,  to  social  structure. 
In  fact,  these  dimensions  of  stratification  may  be  understood  as 
ways  of  focusing  upon  certain  features  of  certain  roles  in  quite 
various  institutional  orders. 

1  These  definitions  are  loose  fornuiUitions  of  Max  Weber's  terms.  In  the 
course  of  tlie  present  chapter  we  shall  make  them  more  elaborate  and 
precise.  See  E.  Shils  and  II.  Goldhammer,  "Types  of  Power  and  Status," 
Atnerican  Journal  of  Sociology,  September  1939,  and  C.  Wright  Mills,  White 
Collar:  The  American  Middle  Class  (New  York:  Oxford,  1951),  especially 
Chapters  4,  13  and  15. 


2o8  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

The  conceptual  relations  of  dimensions  and  orders  are  not,  how- 
ever, neatly  "systematic";  class  and  occupation  are,  of  course, 
ways  of  referring  to  selected  aspects  of  certain  roles  in  the  eco- 
nomic order.  But  each  may  be  deeply  and  intricately  involved  in 
the  other  orders. 

As  a  sphere  (not  an  order),  status  may  be  based  on,  expressed 
in  terms  of,  and  cashed  in  or  realized  in  any  order,  and  each  aspect 
of  status  may  involve  different  institutional  orders.  Status  is  not 
necessarily  anchored  in  any  order;  it  is  often  the  shadow  of  them 
all  and  always  the  shadow  of  one  or  the  other.  A  man's  status  may 
be  based  primarily  on  his  military  occupation  but  he  may  express 
his  status  claims  in  the  educational  sphere,  and  cash  in  on  these 
claims  in  the  political  order;  thus  a  general,  on  liis  way  to  the 
Presidency  becomes  a  college  president.  The  top  positions  of 
N-arious  institutional  orders  and  occupational  hierarchies  may  in- 
creasingly be  interchangeable— just  as  are  the  bottom,  unskilled 
roles.  When  social  structures  are  in  fluid  change,  status  has  less  of 
a  chance  to  determine  conduct;  when  society  is,  as  it  were,  frozen, 
status  may  become  a  major  determinant. 

As  with  status,  so  with  power:  all  roles  that  are  instituted,  no 
matter  in  which  order,  involve  authoritative  relations— the  family 
no  less  than  the  political,  military,  economic,  and  religious  orders. 
The  power  of  a  person  thus  depends  on  a  great  variety  of  possible 
roles,  in  any  one  or  more  of  the  available  institutional  orders  and 
spheres. 

The  availability  of  the  two  schemes  (institutional  orders  and 
social  strata)  invites  us  to  elaborate  the  very  intricate  range  of  pos- 
sible relations  that  may  exist  among  these  dimensions  of  stratifica- 
tion, as  well  as  between  them  and  the  institutional  orders  char- 
acterizing any  concrete  society. 

4 

1.  Occupations 

As  a  set  of  activities  which  provides  a  livelihood,  occupations 
are  economic  roles,  part  of  the  economic  order.  Yet  these  economic 
roles  may  at  the  same  time  be  part  of  any  of  the  other  orders.  Any 
role  in  any  other  that  is  "paid  for"  may  be  an  occupation.  Occupa- 
tional roles  may  thus  at  once  be  oriented  to  a  job  market,  providing 
goods  or  services,  and  yet  serve  by  their  enactment  the  functions 
of  other  than  economic  institutions.  The  civil  servant  as  well  as  the 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  3OQ 

political  boss  are  "gainfully  occupied."  The  professional  general  and 
the  draftee  fill  occupations  in  the  military  order.  The  priest  and  the 
minister  pursue  occupational  roles  instituted  in  the  religious  order 
and  paid  for  by  religious  devotees;  and  teaching  is,  of  course,  a 
job  in  the  educational  sphere.  Even  in  the  kinship  order,  the 
household  servant,  the  private  tutor,  and  the  governess  may  be 
included  in  the  domestic  circle.  The  "unpaid  family  labor"  of  chil- 
dren and  wives  is  an  important  borderline  case,  especially  in  many 
small  businesses  and  on  farms. 

From  the  individual's  standpoint,  occupational  activities  refer 
to  skills  that  are  marketable.  These  skills  range  from  arranging 
mathematical  symbols  for  $1,000  a  day  to  arranging  dirt  with  a 
shovel  for  $1,000  a  year. 

From  the  standpoint  of  society,  occupations  as  activities  are 
f mictions:  they  result  in  certain  end  products— various  goods  and 
services— and  are  accordingly  classified  into  industrial  groups  within 
the  economic  order. 

As  specific  activities,  occupations  thus  ( 1 )  entail  various  types 
and  levels  of  skill  with  which  roles  are  performed,  and  (2)  their 
exercise  fulfills  certain  functions  within  a  system  of  functional 
specialization. 

We  speak  of  occupations  only  when  (a)  there  is  a  division  of 
labor  in  which  distinct,  functional  roles  have  been  developed— 
such  as  farmer,  artisan,  scribe,  priest,  warrior;  (b)  when  a  certain 
regularity  exists— an  enduring  linkage  between  the  person  and 
what  he  does  for  a  living,  his  "routine";  and  (c)  when  what  he 
does  is  intended  to  win  for  him  a  regular  income. 

If  an  urban  patrician  of  Rennaissance  times  once  in  a  while  made 
a  profitable  deal,  he  was  not  necessarily  a  "merchant";  if  a  covetous 
man  "wins"  even  large  sums  of  money  at  cards,  he  is  not  necessarily 
a  "professional  gambler."  A  man  who  happens  to  save  a  drowning 
man  for  the  sake  of  winning  a  "reward"  does  not  thereby  become 
a  "lifeguard." 

On  the  other  hand,  a  gentleman  who  likes  to  spend  his  leisure 
working  at  masonry  (like  Churchill)  is  not  thereby  a  "bricklayer," 
nor  is  he  a  professional  artist  because  he  regularly  plays  the  piano, 
or  paints  pictures.  A  hobby  is  not  an  "occupation."  This  distinction 
between  the  two  does  not  reflect  the  "seriousness"  v.  the  "lightness" 
of  the  pursuit,  for  some  men  take  their  \ocations  "lightly"  and  their 
hobbies  "seriously."  Similarly,  play— an  acti\  ity  enjoyed  for  its  own 


'^10  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

sake— may  be  taken  quite  seriously.  Some  men,  in  fact,  may  feel 
a  defeat  in  a  game  of  chess  more  severely  than  defeat  in  their 
work. 

In  industrial  nations  today  the  most  publicly  obvious  strata  con- 
sist of  members  of  similar  occupations.  However  it  has  been  and 
may  now  be  in  other  societies,  in  contemporary  United  States 
occupations  are  the  most  ostensible  and  the  most  available  "way 
into"  an  understanding  of  stratification  as  a  whole.  For  most  peo- 
ple spend  the  most  alert  hours  of  most  of  their  days  in  occupational 
work.  What  kind  of  work  they  do  not  only  monopolizes  their  wake- 
ful hours  of  adult  life  but  sets  what  they  can  afford  to  buy;  most 
people  who  receive  any  direct  income  at  all  do  so  by  virtLie  of 
some  occupation. 

As  sources  of  income,  occupations  are  thus  connected  with  class 
position.  Since  occupations  also  normally  carry  an  expected  quota 
of  prestige,  on  and  off  the  job,  they  are  relevant  to  status  position. 
They  also  involve  certain  degrees  of  power  over  other  people,  di- 
rectly in  terms  of  the  job,  and  indirectly  in  other  social  areas. 
Occupations  are  thus  tied  to  class,  status,  and  power  as  well  as 
to  skill  and  function;  to  understand  the  occupations  composing  any 
social  stratum  we  must  consider  them  in  terms  of  each  of  these 
interrelated  dimensions.  And  we  must  understand  how  they  limit 
or  even  determine  the  noneconomic  roles  and  activities  open  to 
their  occupants. 

The  most  decisive  occupational  shift  in  the  twentieth  century 
has  been  the  decline  of  the  independent  entrepreneur  (the  "old 
middle  class")  and  the  rise  of  the  salaried  employee  (the  "new  mid- 
dle class").  During  the  last  two  American  generations  the  old 
middle  class  has  declined  from  33  to  20  per  cent  of  the  total 
occupied,  the  new  middle  class  has  bounded  from  6  to  25  per  cent, 
while  the  wage  workers  have  leveled  off,  in  fact  declining  from 
61  to  55  per  cent.  In  the  course  of  the  following  remarks  we  will 
pay  brief  attention  by  way  of  illustration  to  these  three  occupational 
levels  in  the  United  States. 

2.  Class  Structure 

Classes  are  anchored,  by  source  and  amount  of  wealth,  to  the 
property  institutions  and  occupational  roles  of  the  economic  order. 
But  the  laws  of  property  are  part  of  the  political  order  of  a  society 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ;^11 

and  the  income  from  work  may  be,  as  we  have  seen,  a  feature  of 
occupational  roles  in  any  order.  Property  classes  could  not  exist 
solely  in  term.s  of  economic  institutions;  they  are  facts  of  a  political 
economy.  The  "bourgeoisie"  and  the  "proletariat"  are  social  cate- 
gories corresponding  with  the  economic  categories  of  "entrepre- 
neur" and  "wage  worker."  Moreover,  as  with  occupations,  belong- 
ing to  one  class  or  to  another  may  be  a  prerequisite  or  a  tacit  con- 
dition for  the  assumption  of  selected  roles  in  other  orders.  The  unit 
of  the  property  class  is  the  family  and  "the  firm"  rather  than  the 
individual;  wealth  and  family  coherence  are  often,  as  in  latter-day 
capitalism,  most  intimately  related. 

Even  the  world  religions,  especially  their  economically  relevant 
ethics,  are  decisively  related,  in  origin  and  development,  to  specific 
strata.  As  Max  Weber  has  pointed  out,-  Confucianism  was  classi- 
cally the  status  ethic  of  the  mandarin  stratum,  of  men  educated  in 
literary  and  secular  rationalism,  although  their  "religion"  pro- 
foundly influenced  the  styles  of  life  of  other  strata.  Early  Hindu- 
ism was  carried  hereditarily  by  a  caste  of  literati,  the  Brahmans, 
who  constituted  the  stable  reference  group  for  all  status  stratifica- 
tion in  their  society;  whereas  Buddhism  was  carried  forth  by 
migratory  begging  monks,  and  Islam,  during  its  earliest  period, 
by  "a  knight  order  of  disciplined  crusaders."  Since  the  exile,  Juda- 
ism has  been  carried  by  marginal  strata  of  urban  plebeians,  and 
led  by  intellectuals  trained  in  literatiue  and  ritual.  Christianity, 
beginning  as  a  doctrine  of  itinerant  journeymen  which  spread  in 
ancient  cities,  only  slowly  invaded  rural  society.  "Paysan,"  "peas- 
ant," and  "villain"  bespeak  of  the  Christian  burgher's  disdain  for 
the  rustic  pagan  and  villager. 

The  specific  combinations  of  strata  which  have  embraced  reli- 
gious creeds  are  by  no  means  accidental,  and  every  change  in  the 
socially  decisive  strata  has  been  of  importance  for  every  religion. 
It  is  well  known  that  in  twentieth-century  America  the  members 
of  various  Christian  denominations  are  recruited  along  class  and 
status  lines:  Episcopalians  and  Presbyterians  tend  to  be  upper  class; 
Unitarians  and  Lutherans  middle  class;  revivalist  sects,  Holy 
Rollers,  Jehovah's  Witnesses,  lower  class.  Churches  characterized 
by  crowd  ecstasy  and  euphoria  seem  typical  of  lower-class  groups; 

-See  Chapter  IX:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  II,  Section  2: 
Characteristics  of  the  World  Religions. 


S12  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

churches  emphasizing  ritual  observances,  of  higher-class  groups. 
Shintoism  is  a  cult  for  a  warrior  nobility.  American  Catholicism 
now  combines  upper  and  lower  classes— the  recruitment  of  high- 
class  persons  to  augment  the  urban  plebeian  Catholics  is  a  recent 
trend  of  note. 

In  the  United  States  today,  as  in  most  advanced  industrial  coun- 
tries, occupation  rather  than  property  is  the  source  of  income 
for  most  of  those  who  receive  any  direct  income.  The  possibilities 
of  selling  their  services  in  various  labor  markets,  rather  than  of 
profitably  buying  and  selling  their  property  and  its  yields,  now  de- 
termine the  life-chances  of  over  four-fifths  of  the  American  people. 
All  the  things  money  can  buy  and  many  that  men  dream  about 
are  theirs  by  virtue  of  occupational  level.  In  these  occupations  men 
work  for  someone  else  on  someone  else's  property.  This  is  the 
clue  to  many  differences  between  the  older,  nineteenth-century 
American  world  of  the  small  propertied  entrepreneur  and  the  occu- 
pational structure  of  the  new  society.  If  the  old  middle  class  of 
free  enterprisers  once  fought  big  properties  in  the  name  of  small 
properties,  the  new  middle  class  of  white-collar  employees,  like 
the  wage  workers  in  latter-day  capitalism,  has  been,  from  the 
beginning,  dependent  upon  large  properties  for  job  security. 

Wage  workers  in  the  factory  and  on  the  farm  are  on  the  property- 
less  bottom  of  the  occupational  structure,  depending  upon  the 
equipment  owned  by  others,  earning  wages  for  the  time  they  spend 
at  work.  In  terms  of  property,  the  white-collar  people  are  not  "in 
between  "capital  and  labor;  they  are  in  exactly  the  same  property- 
class  position  as  the  wage  workers.  They  have  no  direct  financial 
tie  to  the  means  of  work,  much  less  any  legal  claims  upon  the 
proceeds  from  property.  Like  factory  workers— and  day  laborers 
for  that  matter— they  work  for  those  who  do  own  such  means  of 
livelihood,  or  for  public  agencies. 

Yet  if  bookkeepers  and  coal  miners,  insurance  agents  and  farm 
laborers,  doctors  in  a  clinic  and  crane  operators  in  an  open  pit 
have  this  condition  in  common,  certainly  their  class  situations  are 
not  the  same.  To  understand  the  variety  of  modern  class  positions 
we  must  go  beyond  the  common  fact  of  source  of  income  and 
consider  as  well  the  amount  of  income. 

In  terms  of  property,  white-collar  people  in  America  are  in  the 
same  position  as  wage  workers;  in  terms  of  occupational  income 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ;2i:^ 

they  are  "somewhere  in  the  middle."  Once  they  were  considerably 
above  the  wage  workers;  they  have  become  less  so;  in  the  middle 
of  the  century  they  still  have  an  edge,  but,  rather  than  adding 
new  income  distinctions  within  the  new  middle-class  group,  the 
o\er-all  rise  in  incomes  is  making  the  new  middle  a  more  homoge- 
neous income  group.  Characteristically,  the  income  pyramids  of 
white-collar  employees  and  wage  workers  overlap.  Thus,  the  in- 
comes of  skilled  miners  and  die  cutters  considerably  exceed  those 
of  schoolteachers  and  salesladies.-^ 

Distributions  of  property  and  income  are  important  economically 
because,  if  they  are  not  wide  enough,  piuchasing  power  may  not 
be  sufficient  to  take  up  the  production  that  is  possible  or  desirable. 
Such  distributions  are  also  important  because  they  underpin  the 
class  structure  and  thus  the  chances  of  the  various  ranks  of  the 
people  to  obtain  desired  values.  Everything  from  the  chance  to 
stay  alive  during  the  first  year  after  birth  to  the  chance  to  view 
fine  art,  the  chance  to  remain  healthy  and  grow  tall,  and  if  sick  to 
get  well  again  quickly,  the  chance  to  avoid  becoming  a  juvenile 
delinquent— and  very  crucially,  the  chance  to  complete  an  inter- 
mediary or  higher  educational  grade— these  are  the  chances  that 
are  crucially  influenced  by  one's  position  in  the  class  structure  of 
a  modern  society. 

These  chances  are  factual  probabilities  of  the  class  structure.  It 
does  not  follow  from  such  facts  that  people  are  aware  of  them  or 
in  similar  class  situations  will  necessarily  become  conscious  of  them- 
selves as  a  class  or  come  to  feel  that  they  belong  together.  Nor 
does  it  follow  that  they  will  necessarily  become  aware  of  any  like 
interests  that  may  objectively  be  attributed  to  their  condition  as 
rationally  expedient.  Nor  need  they  define  like  interests  as  common 
interests  or  organize  to  pursue  them  in  a  movement  or  in  a  party. 
Nor  does  it  follow  that  they  will  necessarily  become  antagonistic 
to  people  in  other  class  situations  and  struggle  with  them.  All 
these— class  consciousness  and  awareness  of  common  interests,  or- 
ganizations and  class  struggle— have  existed  in  various  times  and 
places  and,  in  various  forms,  do  now  exist  as  mental  and  political 
fact.  But  they  do  not  follow  logically  or  historically  from  the 
objective   fact   of   class   structure.    Additional   factors   have   to   be 

^  On  compensation  by  "honors"  ratlier  than  "wages,"  on  "pecuniary"  t. 
"psychic  income,"  see  Adam  Smith,  The  Wealth  of  Nations,  Book  I,  Chapter  lo. 


^1^^  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

adduced  to  explain  why  people  become  or  do  not  become  class 
conscious,  that  is,  raise  demands  and  share  articulate  hopes  and 
fears  in  response  to  special  class  situations. 

There  are  many  reasons  for  lack  of  class  consciousness.  ( i )  Class 
situations  are  not  always  transparent  to  the  people  in  them.  Lower- 
class  people,  for  example,  may  live  in  a  widely  dispersed  way  and 
thus  lack  the  opportunity  to  come  together  in  any  solidarity.  (2) 
They  may  also  lack  leadership  capable  of  articulating  their  griev- 
ances. (3)  Issues  other  than  those  of  class  may  hold  the  attention 
and  preoccupy  the  minds  of  people.  (4)  We  should  also  remember 
that  what  is  conceptually  available  to  modern  men,  trained  in 
economic  thoughtways,  was  not  so  available  to  people  of  past  ages. 
(5)  Most  people,  in  fact,  tend  to  identify  with  "their  betters": 
lower  groups  see  themselves  as  their  educated  and  wealthy  supe- 
riors see  them,  and  frequently  there  emerges  socially  split  images 
among  groups  which  co-operate  in  functionally  different  positions 
in  feudal  manor,  artisan's  shop,  and  factory.  (6)  Many  people  may 
hold  certain  class  situations  only  in  periods  of  social  and  economic 
expansion,  migrations,  and  vertical  mobility.  Those  who  rise  suc- 
cessfully by  finding  themselves  in  advantageous  positions  (for  in- 
stance, around  1900,  in  the  oil,  the  motion  picture,  and  the  electrical 
industries)  are  apt  to  ascribe  their  success  not  to  "good  luck,"  or 
to  "circumstance"  but  to  their  intelligence,  foresight,  and  personal 
excellence,  with  the  concomitant  implication  that  others  lack  com- 
parable traits.  They  consider  good  fortune  as  compensation  for 
excellence  and,  as  did  the  successful  of  the  ancient  world,  consider 
themselves  as  the  "darlings  of  the  gods."  The  implication  of  this 
view  for  the  disadvantaged  requires  no  elaboration. 

In  any  case,  whether  or  not  class  consciousness  and  class  action 
arise  from  class  situations  is  a  matter  of  empirical  study.  The  de- 
velopment of  interest  organizations  along  class  lines  is  one  of  the 
outstanding  trends  of  twentieth-century  society.  In  all  industrial- 
ized nations  labor  has  developed  trade  union  organizations  and  co- 
operatives, and  under  special  conditions,  labor  parties.  Farmers  are 
organized  in  a  "farm  bloc,"  and  industrialists  are  organized  in 
chambers  of  commerce  and  join  forces  in  trade  associations  and 
the  NAM. 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ;^1$ 

3.  The  Status  Sphere 

Prestige  involves  at  least  two  persons:  one  to  claim  it  and  an- 
other to  honor  the  claim.  The  bases  on  which  various  people  raise 
prestige  claims,  and  the  reasons  others  honor  these  claims,  include 
property  and  descent,  occupation  and  education,  income  and  power 
—in  fact,  almost  anything  that  may  invidiously  distinguish  one  per- 
son from  another.  In  the  status  system  of  a  society  these  claims  are 
organized  as  rules  and  expectations  governing  those  who  success- 
fully claim  prestige,  from  whom,  in  what  ways,  and  on  what  basis. 
The  level  of  self-esteem  enjoyed  by  given  individuals  is  more  or 
less  set  by  this  status  system. 

There  are,  thus,  six  items  to  which  we  must  pay  attention:  From 
the  claimant's  side:  (i)  the  status  claim,  (2)  the  way  in  which 
this  claim  is  raised  or  expressed,  (3)  the  basis  on  which  the  claim 
is  raised.  And  correspondingly  from  the  bestower's  side:  (4)  the 
status  bestowal  or  deference  given,  (5)  the  way  in  which  these 
deferences  are  given,  (6)  the  basis  of  the  bestowal,  which  may 
or  may  not  be  the  same  as  the  basis  on  which  the  claim  is  raised. 
An  extraordinary  range  of  social  phenomena  are  pointed  to  by 
these  terms. 

Claims  for  prestige  are  expressed  in  all  those  mannerisms,  con- 
ventions, and  ways  of  consumption  that  make  up  the  styles  of  life 
characterizing  people  on  various  status  levels.  The  "things  that 
are  done"  and  the  "things  that  just  aren't  done"  are  the  status 
conventions  of  different  strata.  Members  of  higher  status  groups 
may  dress  in  distinct  ways,  follow  "fashions"  in  varying  tempi  and 
regularities,  eat  and  drink  at  special  times  and  exclusive  places 
in  select  society.  In  varying  degrees,  they  \'alue  the  elegant  appear- 
ance and  specific  modes  of  address,  have  dinner  together,  and  are 
glad  to  see  their  sons  and  daughters  intermarry.  From  the  point  of 
\'iew  of  status,  the  funeral,  as  a  ritual  procession,  is  an  indication 
of  prestige,  as  is  the  tombstone,  the  greeting  card,  the  seating 
plan  at  dinner  or  the  opera.  "Society"  in  American  cities,  debutante 
systems,  the  management  of  philanthropic  activities,  the  social 
register  and  the  Almanach  de  Gotha— noble  titles  and  heraldic  em- 
blems—reflect and  often  control  the  status  activities  of  upper  circles, 
where  exclusiveness,  distance,  coldness,  condescending  benevo- 
lence towards  outsiders  often  prevail. 


2l6  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

Head  roles  in  any  institution  may  be  the  basis  of  status  claims, 
and  any  order  may  become  the  social  area  in  which  these  claims 
are  realized.  We  can  conceive  of  a  society  in  which  status  rests 
upon  economic  class  position  and  in  which  the  economic  order  is 
dominant  in  such  a  way  that  status  claims  based  on  economic 
class  are  successfully  raised  in  every  order.  But  we  can  also  imagine 
a  society  in  which  status  is  anchored  in  the  military  order,  so  that 
the  person's  role  in  that  order  determines  his  chance  successfully  to 
realize  status  claims  in  all,  or  at  least  in  most,  of  the  other  orders. 
Thus  the  military  role  may  be  a  prerequisite  to  honorific  status 
in  other  publicly  significant  roles. 

Of  course,  men  usually  enact  roles  in  several  orders  and  hence 
their  general  position  rests  on  the  combinations  of  roles  they  enact. 

Claims  for  prestige  and  the  bestowal  of  prestige  are  often  based 
on  birth  into  given  types  of  kinship  institutions.  The  Negro  child, 
irrespective  of  individual  "achievement,"  will  not  receive  the  de- 
ference which  the  white  child  may  successfully  claim.  The  immi- 
grant, especially  a  member  of  a  recent  mass  immigration,  will  not 
be  as  likely  to  receive  the  deference  given  the  "Old  American," 
immigrant  groups  and  families  being  generally  stratified  according 
to  how  long  they  and  their  forebears  have  been  in  America.  Among 
the  native-born  white  of  native  parentage,  certain  "Old  Families" 
receive  more  deference  than  do  other  families.  In  each  case— race, 
nationality,  and  family— prestige  is  based  on,  or  at  least  limited  by, 
descent,  which  is  perhaps  most  obviously  a  basis  of  prestige  at  the 
top  and  the  bottom  of  the  social  ladder.  European  royalty  and 
rigidly  excluded  racial  minorities  represent  the  zenith  and  nadir 
of  status  by  birth. 

Upper-class  position  typically  carries  great  prestige,  all  the  more 
so  if  the  source  of  money  is  property.  Yet,  even  if  the  possession 
of  wealth  in  modern  industrial  societies  leads  to  increased  prestige, 
rich  men  who  are  fresh  from  lower-class  levels  may  experience 
difficulty  in  "buying  their  way"  into  upper-status  circles.  In  the 
southern  states,  in  fact,  impoverished  descendants  of  once  high- 
level  old  families  receive  more  deference  from  more  people  than 
do  wealthy  men  who  lack  appropriate  grandparents.  The  kinship 
may  thus  overshadow  the  economic  order.  The  facts  of  the  nouveau 
riche  (high  class  without  high  prestige)  and  of  the  broken-down 
aristocrat  (high  prestige  without  high  class)  refute  the  complete 
identification    of    upper-prestige    and    upper-class    position,    even 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  327 

though,  in  the  course  of  time,  the  broken-down  aristocrat  becomes 
simply  broken-down,  and  the  son  of  the  noiiveau  riche  becomes  a 
man  of  "clean,  old  wealth." 

The  possession  of  wealth  also  allows  the  purchase  of  an  environ- 
ment which  in  due  course  will  lead  to  the  development  of  these 
"intrinsic"  qualities  in  individuals  and  in  families  that  are  required 
for  higher  prestige.  When  we  say  that  American  prestige  has  been 
fluid,  one  thing  we  mean  is  that  high  economic-class  position  has 
led  rather  quickly  to  high  prestige,  and  that  kinship  descent  has  not 
been  of  equal  importance  to  economic  position.  A  feudal  aristoc- 
racy, based  on  old  property  and  long  descent,  has  not  existed  here. 
Veblen's -theory  '  was  focused  primarily  upon  the  post-Civil  War 
periQd_Jn_the_Lhiitccl  States  and  the  expressions  of  prestige  claims 
raised  in  lavish  consumption  by  the  noiiveau  riche  of  railroads, 
steel,  and  pork.  In  a  democratic  society  equipped  with  mass  media 
we  are  not  surprised  to  find  that  many  images  of  upper-status 
types  are  diffused.  It  is  also  well  known  that  in  contrast  with  feudal 
elites  the  American  upper  classes  have  not  shied  from  publicity. 
Society  columns  and  obituary  pages  chronicle  the  activities  and 
connections  of  conspicuous  members  of  the  high-status  groups. 

The  prestige  of  the  middle  strata  in  America  is  based  on  many 
other  principles  than  descent  and  property.  The  shift  to  a  society 
of  employees  has  made  occupation  and  the  educational  sphere 
crucially  important.  Insofar  as  occupation  determines  the  level  of 
income,  and  different  styles  of  life  require  different  income  levels, 
occupation  limits  the  style  of  life.  In  a  more  direct  way,  different 
occupations  require  different  levels  and  types  of  education,  and 
education  also  limits  the  style  of  life  and  thus  the  status  success- 
fully claimed. 

Some  occupations  are  reserved  for  members  of  upper-status 
levels,  others  are  "beneath  their  honor."  In  some  societies,  in  fact, 
having  no  work  to  do  brings  the  highest  prestige;  prestige  being 
an  aspect  of  property  class,  the  female  dependents  of  high  class 
husbands  becoming  specialists  in  the  display  of  expensive  idleness. 
But  only  when  those  who  do  not  need  to  work  have  more  income 
than  those  who  must,  is  idleness  likely  to  yield  prestige.  When 
work  is  necessary  but  not  available,  "leisure"  means  unemployment, 

•*  See  Thorstein  Veblen,  The  Theory  of  tlic  Leisure  Class  (New  York:  Viking, 
1924)- 


^l8  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

which  inay-Jbring  disgrace.  And  income  from  property  does  not  al- 
ways entail  more  prestige  than  income  from  work;  the  amount  and 
the  ways  the  income  is  used  may  be  more  important  than  its 
sQurce.  Thus  the  small  rentier  does  not  enjoy  an  esteem  equal 
to  that  of  a  highly-paid  doctor.  Status  attaches  to  the  terms  for 
income,  to  its  source  and  timing  of  payment.  Socially  the  same 
number  of  dollars  may  mean  different  things  when  they  are  re- 
ceived as  "rent"  or  "interest,"  as  "royalties"  or  "fees,"  as  "stipends" 
or  "salaries,"  as  "wages"  or  as  "insurance  benefits."  Men  striving 
for  status  may  prefer  smaller  salaries  to  higher  wages,  meager 
royalties  to  substantial  profits,  an  honorific  stipend  to  a  large  bonus. 

Among  the  employed  those  occupations  which  pay  more,  and 
which  presumably  involve  more  mental  activities  and  entail  power 
to  supervise  others,  seem  to  place  people  on  higher  prestige  levels. 
But  sheer  power  does  not  always  lend  prestige:  the  political  boss 
renounces  public  prestige— except  among  his  machine  members— for 
power;  constitutional  monarchs,  on  the  other  hand,  retain  and  pos- 
sibly gain  public  prestige  but  lose  political  power.  In  offices  and 
factories,  skilled  foremen  and  office  supervisors  expect  and  typically 
receive  an  esteem  which  lifts  them  above  unskilled  workers  and 
typists.  But  the  policeman's  power  to  direct  street  masses  does 
not  bring  prestige,  except  among  badly  frightened  drivers  and 
little  boys. 

The  type  of  education,  as  well  as  the  amount,  is  an  important 
basis  of  prestige;  "finishing"  schools  and  "prep"  schools  turn  out 
ladies  and  gentlemen  fit  to  represent  their  class  by  styles  of  life 
which,  in  some  circles,  guarantee  deference.  In  other  circles  the 
amount  of  intellectual  skill  acquired  through  education  is  a  key 
point  for  estimation.  Yet  skill  alone  is  not  as  uniform  a  basis  for 
prestige  as  is  skill  connected  with  highly  esteemed  occupations. 

All  the  variables  which  underpin  status— descent,  skill  (on  the 
basis  of  education  and/or  experience),  biological  age,  seniority 
(of  residence,  of  membership  in  associations),  sex,  beauty,  wealth, 
and  authority— may  be  quite  variously  combined  and  usually  in 
typical  ways.  These  combinations  may  be  and  often  are  quite 
intricate.  For  example,  the  cross-tabulation  of  descent,  wealth,  and 
skill  alone  logically  yields  the  following  types:  where  wealth  and 
high  birth  is  combined  with  skill  we  may  find,  for  example,  the 
experienced    statesmanship    of    a    Churchill;    but   where    there    is 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  329 

wealth  and  high  birth  but  no  skill,  perhaps  a  publicized  heiress, 
or  an  hereditary  successor  to  throne.  The  self-made  man  of  the 
nineteenth  century  in  the  United  States  had  wealth  and  skill  but 
low  birth;  the  ignorant  Negro  woman  who  suddenly  wins  the 
sweepstakes,  has  wealth,  but  low  birth  and  no  skill. 

Sir  Walter  Scott,  a  heavily  indebted  nobleman  who  tlid  well  as 
a  writer,  had  no  wealth  but  both  high  birth  and  high  skill.  And 
famous  artists,  such  as  Beethoven,  or  famous  scholars  such  as 
Albert  Einstein,  do  not  have  wealth  or  high  birth,  but  excel  in 
-skill.  The  Russian  refugee  nobleman  who  becomes  a  waiter  in  a 
Paris  hotel  lacks  both  wealth  and  skill  although  he  has  high  birth. 
Finally,  the  Jewish  Luftmensch,^  the  hobo,  the  tramp,  or  the  Negro 
farmhand  have  no  wealth,  no  birth  status,  and  no  skill. 

Such  a  panorama  may  serve  to  indicate  the  manner  in  which  one 
raises  questions  and  classifies  observations  about  the  status  sphere 
of  given  social  structures. 

We  cannot  take  for  granted  that  to  claim  prestige  is  automatically 
^to  recei\e  it.  Status  conduct  is  not  so  harmonious.  The  status 
claimant  may  in  the  eyes  of  others  "overstate"  his  "true"  worth, 
may  be  considered  "conceited."  If  he  understates  it,  he  may  be 
considered  "diffident"  or  "humble."  The  conceited  status  claimant 
may  of  course  receive  the  deference  he  claims,  but  it  is  likely  to  be 
"spurious  deference"  for  "spurious  claims."  His  conceit  in  fact,  is 
often  strengthened  by  flattery,  sometimes  to  the  point  of  mega- 
lomania, as  with  despots  in  a  context  of  priestly  or  courtier  byzan- 
tinism  or  organized  mass  adulation. 

In  cases  of  mistaken  judgment  people  may  give  genuine  defer- 
ence on  the  basis  of  spurious  or  pretended  claims;  there  are  the 
false  Messiahs,  the  false  prophets,  the  false  princes,  and  the  profes- 
sional charlatans.*^ 

Spurious  deference  for  misconstrued  claims  may  be  illustrated 
by  referring  to  the  mock  coronation  of  Christ  as  "the  King  of  the 
Jews"  with  the  crown  of  thorns.  Genuine  respect  for  genuine  claims 
needs  no  particular  elaboration. 

5  A  man  without  an  occupation,  fonnerly  found  among  Eastern  European 
Jews. 

•^  On  professional  charlatans,  see  Crete  de  Francesco,  The  Power  of  the 
Charlatan   (New  Haven:   Yale  Univ.   Press,   1939). 


220  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

False  humility  is  often  transparent  as  a  technique  for  eliciting 
deference.  We  call  it  "fishing."  The  bid  for  good  will,  with  which 
speakers  often  open  their  talks,  is  often  no  more  than  thinly  veiled 
flattery  of  the  audience.  Once  upon  a  time  kings  were  flattered; 
today  more  often  "the  people"  are.  To  be  sure,  such  flattery  of 
the  people  goes  hand  in  hand  with  open  disdain  for  the  European 
"masses"  or  the  American  "suckers."  Hitler  proved  highly  success- 
ful in  allocating  to  German  Gentiles  the  rhetorical  certificate  of 
presumably  high  birth  and  ancestral  background  by  calling  them 
each  and  every  one  "Nordics." 

Thus  the  extent  to  which  claims  for  prestige  are  honored,  and 
by  whom  they  are  honored,  varies  widely.  Some  of  those  from 
whom  an  individual  claims  prestige  may  honor  his  claims,  others 
may  not;  some  deferences  that  are  given  may  express  genuine 
feelings  of  esteem;  others  may  be  expedient  strategies  for  ulterior 
ends.  A  society  may,  in  fact,  contain  many  hierarchies  of  prestige, 
each  with  its  own  typical  bases  and  areas  of  bestowal;  or  one 
hierarchy  in  which  e\'eryone  uniformly  "knows  his  place"  and  is 
always  in  it.  It  is  in  the  latter  that  prestige  groups  are  most  likely 
to  be  uniform  and  continuous. 

Imagine  a  society  in  which  everyone's  prestige  is  clearly  set 
and  stable;  every  man's  claims  for  prestige  are  balanced  by  the 
deference  he  receives,  and  both  his  expression  of  claims  and  the 
ways  these  claims  are  honored  by  others  are  set  forth  in  understood 
stereotypes.  Moreover,  the  bases  of  the  claims  coincide  with  the 
reasons  they  are  honored;  those  who  claim  prestige  on  the  specific 
basis  of  property  or  birth  are  honored  because  of  their  property 
or  birth.  So  the  exact  volume  and  types  of  deference  expected  be- 
tween any  two  individuals  are  always  known,  expected,  and  given; 
and  each  individual's  level  and  type  of  self-esteem  are  steady 
features  of  his  inner  life. 

Now  imagine  the  opposite  society,  in  which  prestige  is  highly 
unstable  and  ambivalent:  the  individual's  claims  are  not  usually 
honored  by  others.  The  ways  in  which  claims  are  expressed  are 
not  understood  or  acknowledged  by  those  from  whom  deference 
is  expected,  and  when  others  do  bestow  prestige,  they  do  so  un- 
clearly.  One  man  claims  prestige  on  the  basis  of  his  income,  but 
even  if  he  is  given  prestige  it  is  not  because  of  his  income  but 
rather,  for  example,  because  of  his  education  and  appearance.  All 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ^^1 

the  controlling  devices  by  which  the  volume  and  type  of  deference 
might  be  directed  are  out  of  joint  or  simply  do  not  exist.  So  the 
prestige  system  is  no  system  but  a  maze  of  misunderstanding,  of 
sudden  frustration  and  sudden  indulgence,  and  the  individual,  as 
his  self-esteem  fluctuates,  is  under  strain  and  full  of  anxiety. 

American  society  in  the  middle  of  the  twentieth  century  does 
not  fit  either  of  these  projections  absolutely,  but  it  seems  fairly 
clear  that  it  is  closer  to  the  unstable  and  ambivalent  model.  This 
is  not  to  say  that  there  is  no  prestige  system  in  the  United  States; 
given  occupational  groupings,  even  though  caught  in  status  ambiv- 
alence, do  enjoy  typical  levels  of  prestige.  It  is  to  say,  however, 
that  the  enjoyment  of  prestige  is  often  disturbed  and  uneasy, 
that  the  bases  of  prestige,  the  expressions  of  prestige  claims,  and 
the  ways  these  claims  are  honored  are  now  subject  to  great  strain, 
a  strain  which  often  tlirows  ambitious  men  and  women  into  a 
\  irtvial  status  panic. 

As  with  income,  so  with  prestige:  white-collar  groups  in  the 
United  States  are  differentiated  socially,  perhaps  more  decisively 
than  wage  workers  and  entrepreneurs.  Wage  earners  certainly  do 
form  an  income  pyramid  and  a  prestige  gradation,  as  do  entrepre- 
neurs and  rentiers;  but  the  new  middle  class,  in  terms  of  income 
and  prestige,  is  a  superimposed  pyramid,  reaching  from  almost  tlie 
bottom  of  the  first  to  almost  the  top  of  the  second. 

People  in  white-collar  occupations  claim  higher  prestige  than 
wage  workers,  and,  as  a  general  rule,  can  cash  in  their  claims  with 
wage  workers  as  well  as  with  the  anonymous  public.  This  fact 
has  been  seized  upon,  with  much  justification,  as  the  defining 
characteristic  of  the  white-collar  strata,  and  although  there  are 
definite  indications  in  the  United  States  of  a  decline  in  their  pres- 
tige, still,  on  a  nationwide  basis,  the  majority  of  even  the  lower 
white-collar  employees— office  workers  and  salespeople— enjoy  a 
middle  prestige  place. 

The  historic  bases  of  the  white-collar  employees'  prestige,  apart 
from  superior  income,  have  included  ( i )  the  similarity  of  their 
place  and  t>'pe  of  work  to  those  of  the  old  middle  classes  which 
has  permitted  them  to  borrow  prestige.  (2)  As  their  relations  with 
entrepreneur  and  with  esteemed  customer  have  become  more  im- 
personal, they  have  borrowed  prestige  from  the  management  and 
the   firm    itself,    and   in   exclusive   stores,   from   wealthy   patrons. 


322  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

(3)  The  stylization  of  their  appearance,  in  particular  the  fact 
that  most  white-collar  jobs  have  permitted  the  wearing  of  street 
clothes  on  the  job,  has  also  figured  in  their  prestige  claims,  as  have 

(4)  the  skills  required  in  most  white-collar  jobs,  and  in  many  of 
them  the  variety  of  operations  performed  and  the  degree  of  au- 
tonomy exercised  in  deciding  work  procedures.  Furthermore,  (5) 
the  time  taken  to  learn  these  skills  and  (6)  the  way  in  which  they 
have  been  acquired  by  formal  education  and  by  close  contact  with 
the  higher-ups  in  charge  has  been  important.  (7)  White-collar  em- 
ployees have  "monopolized"  high  school  education— even  in  1940 
they  had  completed  twelve  grades  to  the  eight  grades  for  wage 
workers  and  entrepreneurs.  They  have  also  (8)  enjoyed  statiis 
by  descent:  in  terms  of  race,  Negro  white-collar  employees  exist 
only  in  isolated  instances— and,  more  importantly,  in  terms  of 
nativity,  in  1930  only  about  9  per  cent  of  white-collar  workers,  but 
16  per  cent  of  free  enterprisers  and  21  per  cent  of  wage  workers 
were  foreign  born.  Finally,  as  an  underlying  fact,  the  limited  size 
of  the  white-collar  group,  compared  to  wage  workers,  has  led  to 
successful  claims  to  greater  prestige. 

4.  Class  and  Status 

Statiisrnay  be  said  to  "overlay"  class  structures.  Each  has  its 
peculiarities  and  its  relative  autonomy,  yet  the  first  is  dependent 
upon  the  second  as  a  conditioning  and  limiting  factor.  One  of  the 
great  perspectives  of  social  thinking  has  been  the  formulation  of 
the  transition  from  feudalism  to  capitalism  in  terms  of  the  shift 
from  "status"  to  "contract,"  or  from  "feudal  estates"  to  "class  so- 
ciety." One  of  the  aspects  noted  in  this  formulation  is  that,  since 
the  great  middle-class  revolutions,  legally  privileged  and  under- 
privileged estates  of  feudalism  and  absolutism  have  been  leveled 
down,  for  "equality  before  the  law"  meant  doing  away  with  legal 
status  barriers.  This  of  course  does  not  mean  the  doing  away  with 
status  groups,  nor  with  all  grounds  upon  which  status  distinctions 
rest.  But  it  does  mean  that  status  dimensions  are  more  closely  tied 
to  the  economic  order  and  that  class  dynamics  are  automatically 
transformed  into  status  dynamics. 

The  leading  groups  devoted  to  military,  political,  juridical,  and 
religious  pursuits  stand  out  in  all  societies.  So  among  top  status 
groups  are  found  warriors  and  priests,  kings,  lords,  and  gentlemen. 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ^^2;^ 

To  these  have  been  added  the  "merchant  princes"  and  "oil  kings"  as 
well  as  "lumber  kings,"  "railroad  czars"— in  short,  as  Franklin  D. 
Roosevelt  called  them,  "the  economic  royalists."  A  variety  of  status 
groups  may  emerge  on  the  basis  of  one  class.  Upper-class  youths 
may  thus  be  divided  into  "the  smart  set"  and  "the  steady  con- 
servative set."  The  smart  set  may  "sow  their  wild  oats,"  take  up 
eccentric  faddish  behavior,  and  seemingly  break  with  the  old  ways 
of  their  steady  parents,  who  may  smilingly  remember  their  own 
"crazy  days,"  and  rely  on  their  wellborn  children  to  "find  their 
way"  back.  The  steady  set  may  remain  sober  in  mind  and  body, 
take  early  to  correct  family  routine,  and  play  a  quiet  game  of  cards 
with  a  moderate  drink.  Among  working  classes,  one  set  of  men 
may  devote  themselves  to  labor  union  activities  and  possibly  to 
politics;  they  may  accordingly  feel  different  from  and  superior 
to  workers  who  are  nothing  but  sports  fans  and  movie  addicts. 
When  Jewish  traditions  and  cosmopolitan  milieu  combine,  a  special 
group  as,  for  example,  the  Garment  Workers  Unions  of  the  Eastern 
United  States  may  create  cultural  activities  of  all  sorts  wliich  bring 
special  and  general  public  prestige.  But  regardless  of  status  prolifer- 
ation, any  basic  change  in  class  position  usually  does  exert  its 
restrictixe  or  its  facilitating  influence.  If  mass  unemployment  dur- 
ing a  world  depression  reduces  income  levels,  heightens  feelings  of 
insecurity,  intensifies  competition  for  jobs,  reduces  family  savings 
and  earnings— then  status  differentiation  among  the  lower  classes 
is  minimized,  there  is  no  money  for  educational  pursuits  and  mass 
luxuries,  for  leisure-time  hobbies,  and  membership  in  many  organi- 
zations. 

Industrialization  and  applied  science  have  increased  man's  mas- 
tery of  nature  to  a  previously  undreamt  extent,  but  they  have 
also  made  mankind  interdependent,  and  dependent  upon  the  func- 
tioning of  the  world  economy  as  a  sort  of  "second  nature."  Ac- 
cordingh',  concern  with  economic  life  has  become  public  and  the 
control  of  strategic  economic  institutions  has  gi\'en  rise  to  public 
distinction.  Captains  of  industry  have  thus  attained  high  prestige 
positions.  The  Kaiser  was  behind  the  times  when  he  mocked  at 
Mr.  Lipton  as  a  "tea  merchant"  who  did  not  quite  qualify  for  royal 
friendship.  On  the  other  hand,  he  did  seek  to  "ennoble"  Alfred 
Krupp,  the  cannon  king  of  the  Ruhr,  and  it  was  possibly  a  sign 
of  the  times  that  Krupp  felt  a  noble  title  could  add  nothing  to 
the  prestige  of  his  name,  based  on  his  steel  plant  and  its  output. 


324  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

Power  over  the  political  and  military,  the  economic  and  the 
religious  community  brings  prestige  to  those  who  legitimately 
make  or  pronounce  the  key  decisions,  or  to  those  to  whom  the 
key  decisions  are  ascribed  by  the  community.  Such  power  is  today 
exercised  at  the  tops  of  large-scale,  far-flung,  and  steeply  graded 
organizations  of  government,  army,  church,  and  business.  All  the 
staff  members  of  such  organizations  are  likely  to  enjoy  prestige, 
whatever  prestige  the  world  at  large  gives  to  the  respective  or- 
ganizations. When  the  state  is  highly  sentimentalized— usually  be- 
cause the  church  has  been  closely  allied  to  state  power  and  the 
prince  once  stood  at  the  head  of  the  church— a  religious  halo  is 
bestowed  upon  "the  state"  and  upon  all  who  serve  it.  And  when  the 
ecclesiastic  structure  is  the  one  stable  and  ancient  organization 
in  a  history  of  changing  state  constitutions,  then  ecclesiastic  pres- 
tige may  overshadow  that  of  the  state,  and  a  cardinal  or  "prince  of 
the  church,"  holding  life-long  tenure  of  office,  may  rank  higher 
than  an  ephemeral  president  of  a  republic.  Big  power  carries  in  its 
train  big  prestige.  Powerful  nation-states  in  the  long  run  get 
greater  prestige  for  their  members  than  do  small  states.  Thus  the 
American  passport  secures  to  its  bearer  greater  respect  in  the 
world  than  the  Hungarian  passport. 

And  yet  this  statement  must  be  qualified,  for  prestige  based 
purely  on  power  may  in  fact  rest  on  "fear"  rather  than  on  sympa- 
thetic respect.  Power  as  such  may  be  sought  as  an  end  by  many 
men,  but  most  men  sooner  or  later  will  ask,  power  for  what?  They 
will  not  accept  power  as  an  ultimate  end,  and  whenever  power  is 
"naked"  it  is  likely  to  be  questioned  as  "abusive."  In  order  to  be 
respected,  power  must  be  disguised  as  estimable  ends;  it  must 
be  thought  to  serve  the  alleged  ends  of  justice  and  freedom  and 
other  aspirations.  It  must  be  sanctioned  and  implemented  by  cre- 
denda  and  miranda  in  order  to  be  admired.^  Only  then  will  it 
exercise  its  "spell"  over  man.  Such  a  spell  may  be  elaborated  by 
specialists,  and  when  the  elaborated  values  are  widely  shared  we 
may  speak  of  "cultural  prestige."  Power  and  culture  prestige  com- 
bined fascinate  man  and  secure  the  glory  of  power,  or  "majesty." 

"  See  Chapter  XIV:  The  Sociology  of  Leadership.  Cf.  C.  E.  Merriam,  Folit- 
ical  Power  (Glencoe,  111.:  Free  Press,  1950),  Chapter  IV. 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  325 

5.  The  Status  Sphere  and  Personality  Types 

Of  all  the  dimensions  of  stratification,  status  seems  the  most 
directly  relevant  to  the  psychology  of  the  person.  This  is  not  of 
course  to  say  that  it  is  the  most  important;  in  fact  it  is  so  often 
dependent  upon  other  roles  in  various  orders,  and  upon  other 
dimensions  of  stratification,  that  in  most  causal  sequences  status 
must  be  seen  as  a  dependent  variable.  Nevertheless,  in  its  psycho- 
logical effects  and  meanings  it  is  "close  up"  to  the  person.  For 
the  level  of  self-esteem  is  rather  immediately  a  function  of  status 
position,  and  the  type  of  self-image  as  well  as  styles  of  conduct 
defining  types  of  persons  may  often  be  most  readily  understood 
in  terms  of  the  status  spheres. 

We  shall  illustrate  these  general  points  by  a  typology  of  person- 
alities among  minority  group  members.  We  choose  this  area  be- 
cause racial  and  ethnic  "minorities,"  in  our  scheme,^  are  primarily 
status  phenomena,  and,  moreover,  status  phenomena  of  an  extreme 
enough  character  to  permit  rather  sharp  disclosure  of  the  me- 
chanics of  the  status  sphere  as  they  affect  character  structure. 

A  minority  group,  as  we  shall  use  the  term,  refers  to  a  status 
group  based  on  descent,  whose  members  are  denied  status  equality 
with  nonminority  people,  irrespective  of  individual  achievements. 
In  the  United  States,  the  Negro,  the  Jew,  and  immigrants  of  various 
nationality  extractions  find  themselves  in  this  position.  There  are 
of  course  many  differences  between  these  varied  minorities:  Negro 
status  is  no  mere  matter  of  racial  descent,  but  represents  the  harsh 
legacy  of  slavery;  the  immigrant's,  of  nationality  origin  and  the 
length  of  time  his  kinsliip  group  has  resided  in  this  country;  the 
Jew's  status  as  a  Jew  is  often  of  mixed  basis,  including  religious, 
nationality,  and  ethnic  factors. 

The  major  historical  basis  of  status  differences  between  Jew 
and  Gentile  is  in  the  religious  order.  Insofar  as  civic,  military,  and 
political  functions  required  the  Christian  oath,  Jews  did  not  qual- 
ify; and  in  a  complementary  way,  on  religious  grounds,  since  the 
days  of  the  Babylonian  exile,  the  Jewish  people  have  segregated 
themselves  from  their  social  surroundings  by  rituals  of  food,  cos- 
tume, circumcision,  and  holiday.  In  early  periods,  all  this  meant 
conventional  and  often   legal  definitions  of  Jewish  status  and  of 


^26  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

Jewish  styles  of  life.  In  the  economic  order,  for  example,  Jewry 
has  been  excluded  from  all  esteemed  and  established  occupations, 
which  the  dominant  society  monopolized.  In  twentieth-century 
America,  however,  many  of  these  occupations  are  now  once  more 
open  to  Jews,  and  in  addition,  the  religious  and  especially  the 
ritualist  conduct  of  Jews  has  broken  down.  So,  the  possibilities 
for  many  quite  complicated  marginal  situations  for  Jews  now  exist 
in  the  status  sphere  of  American  society. 

The  status  of  any  minority  is  revealed  by  their  exclusion  from 
specific  occupations,  educational  opportimities,  social  clubs,  pre- 
ferred residential  areas,  as  well  as  by  resistance  to  their  inter- 
marriage with  members  of  the  majority  society.  It  is  in  this  situa- 
tion that  the  minority  child  comes  to  awareness  of  his  status.  In 
time,  he  also  comes  to  experience  its  conflict  with  majority  groups 
as  his  conflict— as  others  significant  to  him  reveal  hostile  stereotypes 
based  on  it.  „  Finally,  he  attempts  to  come  to  terms  with  the 
status  situation  in  which  he  finds  himself;  and  in  the  process  he  is 
organized  into  one  of  several  types  of  personality."Whatever  traits 
he  has  as  a  mature  person  of  minority  status  will  be  a  product  of 
his  status  situation  and  of  his  cumulative  reactions  to  it  and  inter- 
actions with  it. 

The  points  in  terms  of  which  personality  types  may  be  con- 
structed are,  first,  the  groups  in  terms  of  which  the  minority  group 
man  or  woman  seeks  status— his  own  minority  group  or  the  ma- 
jority society;  and  the  status  symbols  by  means  of  which  he  strives 
to  claim  status— again,  those  of  his  minority  group  or  those  of  the 
majority  society.  In  terms  of  these  two  points,  we  can  gain  a  view 
of  four  types: 

The  Symbols  and  The  Groups  in  Which  Status  Is  Sought 

Styles  by  Which  in  his  own         in  the  majority 

Status  Is  Sought  minority  society 

Of  His  Own  Minority  I  II 

Of  the  Majority  Society  III  IV 

Within  each  of  these  four  situations  there  are  many  possible 
varieties  and  types  of  men  and  women.  Perhaps  most  Jews  in  the 
United  States,  for  example,  are  in  none  of  these  situations:  they 
seek  status  among  both  groups  and  with  the  symbols  of  both. 
Still,  they  are  sociologically  differentiated  by  means  of  the  propor- 
tion of  their  relations  and  roles  that  are  based  on  Jewish  or  on 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ;^2J 

Gentile  symbols,  and  which  involve  Jewish  or  Gentile  contexts. 
The  compromises  are  many  and  result  in  a  range  of  types  from 
the  utterly  bewildered,  caught  in  bitter  conflicts  of  self-esteem 
and  guilt,  through  the  embittered  and  disillusioned,  to  those  who 
feel  secure  in  strict  segregation. 

In  situation  I,  in  which  status  is  sought  among  ones  minority 
by  means  of  minority  group  symbols,  we  find  the  ultraorthodox 
Jew,  whose  time  is  spent  in  a  ghetto-like  world,  who  withdraws 
from  and  minimizes  all  contacts  with  the  outside,  and  has  no  sig- 
nificant others  among  Gentiles.  Or,  he  may  be  a  middleman  who 
confines  his  contacts  with  Gentiles  to  strictly  segmental  business 
relations;  unlike  the  ultraorthodox,  he  faces  the  two  worlds  but 
chooses  the  Jewish  as  his  status  area.  Socially  and  psychologically 
he  is  unavailable  to  outgroups. 

In  situation  II  we  find  those  personality  types  that  have  been 
formed  by  identification  with  Jewry  as  a  whole  and  who  seek 
status  from  this  identification,  but  among  Gentiles.  One  finds  here 
resentful,  militant  anti-Gentiles  who  in  extreme  cases  may  accu- 
rately be  called  Jewish  chauvinists.  For  they  ascribe  all  Jewish 
ills  to  the  anti-Semitic  Gentiles.  There  is  also  "the  crusader"  who  is 
understandably  touchy  and  "out  to  see  that  Jewish  toes  are  not 
stepped  on";  and  on  higher  ethical  and  intellectual  planes  there  is 
the  individual  who  seeks  to  build  up  the  culture  of  his  people  and 
their  prestige  by  fruitfully  using  their  cultural  symbols  in  a  Gentile 
world. 

In  situation  III,  we  find  those  "emancipated  Jews"  who  use  the 
status  symbols  of  the  larger  society  in  order  to  gain  status  among 
their  own  minority  group.  In  status  situation  IV  are  those  Jews 
who  successfully  escape  Jewish  status  by  using  Gentile  symbols 
and  styles  among  Gentile  groups.  Here  overreaction  is  not  infre- 
quent; on  the  one  hand,  there  is  "the  social  climber"  who  by  his 
conspicuous  economic  success  and  sometimes  fawning  conduct 
would  buy  the  respect  of  the  majority  community  and,  on  the 
other  hand,  "the  lOo  per  cent  American"  who  is  conspicuously 
attached  in  a  kind  of  superloyalty  to  Gentile  ideals  and  status  sym- 
bols. And  in  the  extreme,  there  is  the  person  who  chooses  not  to 
be  a  Jew,  and  who,  in  completely  successful  cases,  is  not  a  minor- 
ity type  of  personality  at  all;  he  has  left  not  only  minority  status 
but  its  marginality  as  well. 


228  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

6.  Power 

By  definition,  all  roles  that  are  instituted,  no  matter  in  what 
institutional  order,  involve  distributions  of  power.  But  the  power 
dimensions  of  a  social  structure  involve  the  power  relations  of 
roles  in  one  order  with  the  roles  in  another  order.  The  power 
attendant  upon  one's  role  in  the  religious  order  may  not  be  con- 
fined to  the  religious  order.  In  fact,  religious  bodies  frequently 
serve  as  frame  organizations,  at  least  for  the  kinship  relations  of 
their  members.  Where  the  religious  order  is  dominant  among  or-^ 
ders,  and  hence  "theocracy"  exists,  one's  religious  role  will  ramify 
into  all  other  orders,  even  determining  effective  power  level  in 
economic  or  political  or  educational  institutions.  This  matter  of 
the  "dominance"  of  orders  will  be  systematically  discussed  in  the 
following  chapter.® 

The  power  position  of  institutions  and  individuals  typically  de- 
pends upon  factors  of  class,  status,  and  occupation,  often  in  intri- 
cate interrelation. 

Some  occupations  involve  formal  authority  and  de  facto  power 
over  other  people  in  the  actual  course  of  their  work;  and  certain 
occupations  by  virtue  of  their  relations  to  institutions  of  property 
as  well  as  the  typical  income  they  afi^ord,  may  lend  social  power 
even  outside  the  job  area.  Members  of  other  occupations  are  super- 
vised by  other  employees,  many  of  them  contingent  of  a  man- 
agerial cadre.  They  are  the  assistants  of  authority:  the  power  they 
exercise  is  a  derived  power,  but  they  do  exercise  it. 

Entrepreneurial  classes,  through  investment  decisions  and  the 
right  "to  hire  and  fire,"  hold  power  over  job  markets  and  com- 
modity markets,  directly  and  indirectly.  They  may  also  support 
power,  because  of  their  property,  over  the  state,  especially  the 
state  that  is  saddled  with  internal  or  external  debts  and  in  need 
of  good  credit  standing  in  the  business  world.  As  Franz  Neumann 
has  neatly  indicated,  each  of  the  powers  of  property  may  be 
organized  for  execution,  in  employer's  association,  cartel,  trust, 
and  pressure  group.  From  the  underside  of  the  property  situation, 
propertyless  wage  workers  may  have  trade  unions  and  consumers' 
co-ops  which  may  contend  for  "more"  or  for  "co-determination" 

8  See  Chapter  XII:   The   Unity  of  Social  Structures. 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  329 

in  a  struggle  with  the  organized  powers  of  property  on  labor  and 
commodity  markets. 

When  we  speak  of  the  power  of  classes,  occupations,  and  status 
groups,  however,  we  usually  refer  more  or  less  specifically  to 
political  power.  This  means  the  power  of  such  groups  to  influence 
or  to  determine  the  policies  and  activities  of  the  state.  Direct  means 
of  exercising  such  power,  and  signs  of  its  existence,  are  organiza- 
tions that  either  are  composed  of  members  of  certain  strata  or  act 
in  behalf  of  their  interests,  or  both.  During  wartime,  even  more 
directly,  business  executives  fill  positions  in  the  army  and  other 
state  agencies,  from  which  they  decide,  within  the  law,  what  the 
government  shall  buy  from  whom  at  "cost  plus."  The  power  of 
various  strata  often  implies  a  political  willfulness,  a  "class-con- 
sciousness" on  the  part  of  members  of  these  strata.  But  not  always: 
there  can  be,  as  in  the  case  of  "unorganized,  grimibling  workers," 
a  common  mentality  among  those  in  common  strata  without  or- 
ganizations. And  there  can  be,  as  with  some  "pressure  groups,"  an 
organization  defining  and  representing  the  interests  of  those  in 
similar  situations  without  any  single  purpose  or  attitude  being 
shared  by  those  represented. 

The  accumulation  of  political  power  by  any  stratum  is  generally 
dependent  upon  some  four  factors:  will  and  purpose,  objective 
conditions  or  opportunities,  the  state  of  organization,  and  the  poli- 
tical skill  of  leaders.  Opportunity  is  limited  by  the  group's  struc- 
tural positions,  which  is  to  say,  its  functional  position  as  a  stratum 
in  the  institutional  stnicture. 

New  York  harbor  pilots  or  Manhattan  elevator  boys— not  to 
mention  miners,  steel  workers,  and  railroad  workers— hold  in  hand 
more  crucial  links  in  the  multiple  chains  of  interdependent  func- 
tions that  constitute  modern  society  than  do  musicians,  barbers, 
textile  workers,  or  small-scale  farmers.  Obviously,  the  functional 
place  of  workers  is  not  simply  a  question  of  skill:  to  push  the 
button  of  an  elevator  and  count  the  floors  requires  less  skill  than 
to  play  the  violin  or  to  operate  a  barbershop.  The  question  is: 
What  links  in  the  interlocking  chains  of  acti\ity  are  broken  by  the 
group's  withdrawal  of  effort?  Strikes  in  the  mining  or  steel  indus- 
tries are  automatically  national  issues  rather  than  local  events. 
Similarly,  coal  and  steel  prices  are  of  national  concern,  because 
coal  and  steel  "go  into  everything"  and  thus  affect  the  cost  of  a 
wide  range  of  commodities.  It  is  during  critical  strikes  and  cost- 


S30  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

price-profit  decisions  that  fonnally  or  legally  "private"  decisions 
are  revealed  to  the  public  as  substantively  "public"  in  nature  and 
consequence.  Bargaining  strength  and  veto  power  are  wielded  by 
groups  and  leaders  in  such  command  positions.  Often  the  height 
and  significance  of  such  positions  become  transparent  to  those 
who  hold  them— and  to  the  public— only  in  crisis.  Then  men  on 
all  sides  learn  "the  facts  of  life." 

The  best  of  opportunity,  however,  will  be  lost  without  the  will 
and  capacity  to  make  the  most  of  it.  This  is  dependent  upon  the 
group's  sense  of  cohesion,  its  consciousness  and  definition  of  com- 
mon interests  and  objectives,  and  the  practicability  and  skill  of 
realizing  them.  In  these  matters  the  few  have  an  advantage  over 
the  many.  Both  functional  position  and  consciousness  interplay 
with  organization  and  skill;  organization  and  skill,  in  turn, 
strengthen  or  weaken  consciousness  and  are  made  politically  rele- 
vant by  the  functions  they  perform. 

When  social  structures  change  rapidly,  because  of  technological 
or  economic  shifts,  military  conquests,  or  migrations,  then  those 
established  status  positions  which  are  remote  from  the  centers  of 
power  are  displaced  by  those  that  are  closely  anchored  to  the 
sources  of  power.  During  warfare,  for  example,  the  status  of  mili- 
tary pursuits  is  enhanced  and  with  it  that  of  youth:  "In  the  clang 
and  clash  of  arms,  the  muses  are  silent."  When  he  conquered 
Italy,  Napoleon  was  only  twenty-eight  years  of  age.  The  turn- 
over of  generals  during  World  War  II— in  Germany,  the  Soviet 
Union,  and  the  United  States— meant  a  "rejuvenation"  of  military 
leadership,  though  not  as  drastic  as  in  preindustrial  warfare. 

The  roles  geared  to  the  control  of  the  instruments  of  destruction, 
administration,  communication,  and  production  in  stormy  periods 
stand  out  as  centers  of  power,  and  accordingly  of  prestige.  The 
revolutionary  "nation  in  arms"  identified  its  cause  with  that  of 
mankind,  and  developed  a  sense  of  a  universal  mission  which  has 
justified  French  imperialism  ever  since  General  Bonaparte  pro- 
claimed: "Peace  to  the  huts!  War  to  the  palaces!" 

7.  Stratification  and  Institutional  Dominance 

We  have  "abstracted"  the  dimensions  of  stratification  from  more 
concrete   institutional   roles   in   order    ( i )    to   be   able   to   discuss 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ;^:^1 

separately  each  dimension  and  its  relations  with  the  other  dimen- 
sions, and  (2)  to  discuss  how,  in  terms  of  these  dimensions,  insti- 
Hitional  orders  are  related  to  one  another." 

That  institutional  order  which  is  dominant  in  a  social  structure 
(power)  will  usually  be  the  order  in  which  status  is  primarily 
anchored  and  upheld.  High  class  position  and  preferred  occupa- 
tions will  also,  given  sufficient  time,  be  acquired  by  those  who  are 
"heads"  of  the  most  powerful  institutional  order.  This  point  may 
be  illustrated  by  brief  examination  of  the  stratification  systems  of 
the  United  States,  Germany,  and  the  Soviet  Union. 

I.  In  the  United  States,  especially  during  the  nineteenth  cen- 
tury, the  economic  order  was  dominant  in  the  social  structure. 
Capitalist  economy  and  the  inheritance  of  property  by  kinship 
groups  set  the  dominant  class  structure.  High  economic  agents 
successfully  claimed  the  greater  prestige,  and  were  powerful  actors 
behind  the  scenes,  as  well  as  on  the  stage,  of  the  political  and  other 
orders. 

A.  Increasingly  in  the  United  States,  class  and  status  situations 
have  been  removed  from  free  market  economic  forces  and  ha\e 
been  subject  to  more  formal  political  rules.  Over  the  last  twenty- 
five  years  the  political  order  has  gained  increasing  weight  and 
influence  upon  the  economic  bases  of  stratification.  Governmental 
regulation  of  the  economic  processes  has  become  a  major  means 
of  alleviating  inequalities  and  insuring  the  risks  of  those  in  lower- 
income  classes.  Not  so  much  free  labor  markets  as  the  bargaining 
power  of  political  and  interest  groups  now  shape  the  class  posi- 
tions and  privileges  of  various  strata  in  the  United  States.  Hours 
and  wages,  vacations,  income  security  through  periods  of  sickness, 
accidents,  unemployment  and  old  age— these  are  now  subject  to 
many  intentional  political  and  economic  pressures,  and,  along 
with  tax  policies,  internal  and  external  loans,  transfer  payments, 
tariffs,  subsidies,  price  floors  and  ceilings,  and  wage  freezes,  make 
up  the  content  of  "class  fights"  in  the  objective  meaning  of  the 
phrase. 

The  "Welfare  State"  in  the  United  States  now  attempts  to  re- 
lieve   class    tensions    and    build    a   mighty   defense    force   without 

9  This  second  point  will  be  discussed  more  s>  stematically  in  Chapter  XII: 
The  Unity  of  Social  Structures. 


33^  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

modifying  basic  class  structure.  In  its  several  meanings  and  types, 
this  kind  of  state  favors  economic  policies  designed  to  redistribute 
life-risks  and  life-chances  in  favor  of  those  in  the  more  exposed 
class  situations,  who  have  the  power  or  threaten  to  accumulate 
the  power  to  do  something  about  their  case.  Labor  union,  farm 
bloc,  and  trade  association  dominate  the  political  scene  of  the 
Welfare  State,  and  contests  within  and  between  them  increasingly 
determine  the  position  of  various  groups.  The  state,  as  a  frame 
organization,  is  at  the  balanced  intersection  of  such  pressures, 
and  increasingly  the  privileges  and  securities  of  various  occupa- 
tional strata  depend  upon  the  bold  means  of  organized  power. 

Pensions,  for  example,  especially  since  World  War  II,  have  been 
a  major  idea  in  labor  union  bargaining,  and  it  has  been  the  wage 
worker  who  has  had  bargaining  power.  Social  insurance  to  cover 
work  injuries  and  occupational  diseases  has  gradually  been  re- 
placing the  common  law  of  a  century  ago,  which  held  the  em- 
ployee at  personal  fault  for  work  injury  and  the  employer's  lia- 
bility had  to  be  proved  in  court  by  a  damage  suit.  Insofar  as  such 
laws  exist,  they  shape  the  opportunities  of  the  worker.  Both  privi- 
leges and  income  level  have  thus  been  increasingly  subject  to  the 
political  pressures  of  unions  and  government,  and  there  is  every 
reason  to  believe  that  in  the  future  these  pressures  will  be  in- 
creased even  more. 

B.  There  have  been  changes  in  the  interrelation  of  status  with 
educational,  economic,  political,  and  military  institutions. 

The  drift  to  bigness  in  business  and  to  an  enlarged  and  cen- 
tralized government  has  meant  the  rise  of  the  civil  service  state 
and  of  corporate  bureaucracies  in  business.  Accordingly,  the  de- 
mand for  the  expertness  of  the  bureaucratic  careerist  has  been 
met  by  an  enormous  expansion  of  educational  facilities.  The 
college  degree  has  become  the  ticket  of  admission  to  many  pre- 
ferred middle-class  job  opportimities  and  their  status  prerequisites. 

C.  This  trend  has  been  reinforced  by  the  decision  of  the  United 
States  to  translate  her  power  potential  into  diplomatic  bargaining 
strength,  by  underpinning  it  with  "military  force  in  being."  The 
unified  defense  forces  have  made  the  status  rivalry  between  gen- 
erals and  admirals  a  mere  holdover  from  the  past,  and  the  United 
States  is  now  a  permanently  "all-around  military  power."  The 
educational  bonus  for  veterans  has  reinforced  the  weight  and 
the  prestige  of  the  military  service  by  the  translatability  of  military 


crt'- 
corps 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ^33 

credit  into  educational  opportunities  which,  in  turn,  serve  as  a 
neans  of  social  ascent  which  increases  the  prestige  of  the  officer 
"orps  and  veteran  into  other  status  channels.  During  the  Civil 
War,  William  Graham  Sumner  could  deem  himself  too  good  for 
irmy  service  and  could  have  himself  bought  out  of  army  service 
by  a  friend.  But  in  an  age  of  world  wars  the  claim  of  civilians  to 
status  superiority  over  the  military  can  no  longer  be  realized  with 
comparable  success. 

D.  Since  the  end  of  mass  immigration  and  the  relative  closing 
off  of  the  nation  through  a  system  of  quota  immigration  admitting 
only  "token"  numbers  of  qualified  immigrants,  the  fusion  of  na- 
tionality groups  with  the  main  body  of  the  population  has  greatly 
advanced.  These  assimilation  and  acculturation  processes  have 
both  permitted  and  been  facilitated  by  the  emergence  of  mass 
organizations  of  labor  under  the  benevolent  legislation  and  ad- 
ministrative policies  of  the  "New  Deal."  The  congeries  of  craft 
unions,  comprising  only  2^>  million  members  in  1933,  has  been 
numerically  overshadowed  by  the  new  industrial  unions  of  both 
the  AFL  and  the  CIO,  which  have  swelled  the  ranks  of  organized 
labor  beyond  the  15  million  mark. 

With  this,  the  multifarious  "immigrant  neighborhoods,"  with 
their  petty  group  competitions  of  ethnic  organizations,  old  world 
cultural  emblems,  and  patterns  of  status  segregation  have  been 
leveled  and  even  superseded  by  mass  organizations  along  class 
lines.  New  and  attractive  channels  for  power  and  status  ascent 
have  thus  come  to  the  fore.  The  benevolent  support  of  organized 
labor  by  the  largest  integrative  organization  of  immigrant  urban 
labor— the  Catholic  Church— has  helped  in  this.  So,  for  some  sec- 
tions of  the  metropolitan  masses,  it  has  become  more  relevant  to 
status  whether  the  family  head  is  a  "union  man"  than  whether 
he  is  a  "Hungarian"  or  an  "Italian,"  a  "Pole"  or  an  "Irishman." 
Association  with  a  functional  class  organization  has  thus  for  many 
overshadowed  affiliation  with  organizations  along  nationality  lines. - 

E.  Yet  all  this  does  not  mean  that  status  by  descent  is  no  longer 
a  factor  in  American  stratification.  In  a  way,  a  central  group  of 
undisputed  "old  American  stock"  still  finds  itself  surrounded  by 
a  plurality  of  more  recent  Americans  of  immigrant  stock.  These 
peripheral  groups  strive,  by  assimilation,  to  slough  off  behavior 
items  and  symbolic  practices  which  permit  the  central  group  to 
refer  to  them  by  national  descent.  These  ethnic  groups  gain  or  lose 


234  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

status  externally  by  the  friendly  or  hostile  position  of  the  nation 
of  their  descent  with  reference  to  America,  and  their  prestige 
thus  rises  and  falls  in  accordance  with  the  power  constellation  of 
nations.  They  gain  or  lose  status  internally  by  their  position  in  the 
sequence  of  immigrant  generations;  longer  residence  in  America 
makes  for  their  reception  into  the  undisputed  "American"  center. 

Thus  during  the  late  war  Americans  of  Greek  or  Slavic  back- 
ground experienced  prestige  increments,  whereas  Americans  of 
German,  Japanese,  and  Italian  background  experienced  status 
deprivations— for  which  they  sometimes  sought  to  compensate  by 
professions  of  loyalty  and  extraordinary  contributions  to  the  war 
effort.  After  the  war,  when  the  position  of  China  and  Japan,  of 
Germany  and  the  Slavic  countries,  changed,  so  did  the  distribution 
of  prestige:  German,  Italian  or  Japanese  descent  no  longer  was 
such  a  status  burden,  and  Slavic  or  Chinese  descent  no  longer  se- 
cured the  prestige  it  once  did. 

F.  For  upper-  and  middle-class  groups  of  undisputed  "Ameri- 
can" standing,  however,  the  background  of  descent  seems  to  have 
become  a  more  attractive  feature  of  status  imagery  and  self-styli- 
zation.  Bric-a-brac,  family  heirlooms,  and  furniture  rate  with 
pedigree  organizations  of  the  sons  and  daughters  of  this  and  that. 
In  eighteenth-century  England  antiquarianism  underpinned  a  new 
sense  of  historical  continuities  culminating  in  Edmund  Burke's 
work;  in  America  today  the  preference  of  upper  middle  classes 
for  genuine  colonial  homes  and  the  interest  in  "Americana,"  family 
heirlooms,  and  old  American  glass  underlies  the  renewed  interest 
in  the  national  past  rather  than  the  elaboration  of  the  future  as 
"the  American  dream."  "Looking  backward"  no  longer  leads  to  a 
vision  of  a  future  Utopia.  Courses  in  American  history  are  increas- 
ingly considered  obligatory  for  all  university  students.  Members 
of  the  living  generation  come  to  consider  themselves  the  heirs  of 
an  illustrious  tradition  rather  than  newcomers  and  pioneers.  The 
days  when  the  successful  businessman  could  claim  status  as  a 
"self-made  man,"  rather  than  an  "upstart,"  may  be  a  bygone  phase 
of  American  social  history.  For  everywhere  established  and  cul- 
tured status  groups  have  ridiculed  the  parvenu  in  terms  of  Mo- 
liere's  model  of  the  bourgeois  gentilhomme.  And,  in  this  respect, 
American  society  is  being  "Europeanized."  During  the  war,  Henry 
Kaiser  was  hailed  as  a  "dynamic  constructionist"  in  the  face  of 
the  "Big  Five";  after  the  war  he  was  considered  by  many  highly 


bvt 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  335 

placed  men  an  intruding  parvenu.  The  status  heights  are  attained 
by  those  of  estabhshed  wealth  who  combine  military,  diplomatic, 
and/or  top  administrative  roles  with  leading  positions  in  the  big 
business  community,  such  as  Dawes,  Young,  Harriman,  Hoffman, 
and  Wilson. 

II.  Status,  in  due  course,  follows  power.  By  observing  twentieth- 
century  Germany,  for  instance,  we  can  see  how  a  sequence  of 
political  regimes  has  led  to  corresponding  redistributions  of  pres- 
tige. 1° 

A.  In  Imperial  Germany,  the  Hohenzollern  and  other  princely 
dynasties,  the  Prussian  Junker  nobility  of  military  officers,  career 
diplomats,  civil  servants,  and  conservative  party  leaders  of  the 
Prussian  parliament  occupied  top  statTis  positions.  A  system  of 
class  suffrage  guaranteed  their  monopoly  of  political  power  over 
Prussia  and,  through  Prussia's  position,  over  the  confederacy  of 
princely  states  that  was  Imperial  Germany. 

This  group  was  set  off  from  the  rest  of  the  nation  by  member- 
ship in  a  university  duel  corps,  as  displayed  by  facial  scar  and 
colored  ribbon.  Its  members  held  the  status  of  reserve  officers,  and 
their  caste  conventions  of  dueling  and  ceremonial  beer-drinking, 
their  speech,  postures,  and  mannerisms  made  them  the  conspicuous 
target  of  caricatures.  The  conventional  demarcations  of  this  status 
group  cut  through  university  staffs,  the  Protestant  clergy,  the  civil 
service,  liberal  professions,  and  business  communities  of  town  and 
country. 

Yet  the  representative  man  of  this  group  could  not  serve  as  a 
model  to  be  popularly  followed  (like  that  of  the  British  gentle- 
man) in  an  industrial  and  urban  society  engaged  in  world  affairs. 
Important  sections  of  the  business  elite,  Jewish  bankers  and  Han- 
seatic  merchants,  scholars  and  writers,  professional  men,  and  poli- 
ticians developed  status  roles  of  their  own.  As  the  Austrian  court 
nobility  under  the  Hapsburgs  sought  to  enlarge  their  basis  by 
granting  spurious  titles  to  newly  risen  business  elites,  so  the  Ger- 
man upper-status  groups  emphasized  bureaucratic  rank  as  status 
badges.  Formal  modes  of  address,  calling  cards,  mailboxes,  and 
even  tombstones  were  used  to  indicate  titled  ranks.  The  correct 

1"  See  H.  H.  Gerth,  "Germany  on  the  Eve  of  Occnpation,"  Problems  of  the 
Post-War  World,  T.  C.  McCormick,  ed.  (New  York:  McGraw-Hill,  1945). 
p.  422  S. 


336  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

title  mattered  more  than  correct  initials  and  served  to  diffuse  this 
prestige  gradation  through  all  public  institutions,  such  as  state 
hospitals  and  university  clinics,  state  theaters  and  state  opera 
houses,  the  business  community  and  the  liberal  professions.  It 
was  characteristic  of  this  status  system  that  all  roles  were  geared 
to  vocational  specialization,  and  that  the  pride  of  even  the  Junker 
was  attached  both  to  noble  descent  and  to  his  military,  diplomatic, 
or  bureaucratic  rank,  his  academic  degree  or  his  role  as  manager 
of  a  farm.  Prussian  poverty  and  pride  in  vocational  efficiency  never 
allowed  a  representative  stratum  of  "cultured  gentlemen,"  cour- 
tiers, or  bourgeois  patricians  to  emerge  as  a  nationally  represen- 
tative status  group. 

Below  the  top  layer  and  its  bureaucratically  ramified  satellite 
groups  stood  the  broader  middle  classes  of  small  businessmen, 
craftsmen,  and  peasants,  and  finally  class-conscious  labor,  organ- 
ized in  the  largest  political  party,  controlling  one-third  of  the  na- 
tional vote,  rallying  the  largest  trade  unions  and  co-operative 
societies  in  a  Social  Democratic  movement  under  the  leadership 
of  a  socialist  intelligentsia,  a  machine  of  political  professionals  and 
union  organizers. 

B.  After  the  collapse  of  Imperial  Germany,  the  ffight  of  the 
Kaiser  and  his  paladins,  and  the  abdication  of  the  ruling  princes, 
a  trade-union  leader  up  from  the  ranks  became  the  first  president 
of  the  Weimar  Republic.  Labor  found  itself  at  the  top.  But  the 
class  structure  was  but  little  affected  by  the  establishment  of  the 
Weimar  Republic.  The  displacement  of  the  feudal  status  system 
did  not  affect  the  institutional  anchorages  of  class  or  status.  When, 
by  1925,  the  upsurge  of  political  reaction  had  brought  Field 
Marshal  von  Hindenburg— now  in  mufti— to  the  presidency,  and 
the  four  years  of  business  prosperity  brought  corporate  wealth 
and  the  Junker-led  farm  bloc  to  the  fore,  labor  lost  what  prestige 
it  had  held  in  the  immediate  postwar  years. 

But  the  keynote,  so  far  as  prestige  goes,  is  that  in  the  Republic 
no  universally  accepted  status  symbols  firmly  attached  to  this  or 
that  group  really  emerged.  The  status  sphere  was  not  one  uni- 
lateral distribution  but  a  plural  affair  and  internally  competitive. 
In  the  meanwhile,  paralleling,  as  it  were,  this  prestige  fragmenta- 
tion, concentration  of  power  in  the  economic  order  went  forward 
swiftly. 


C. 

with 

plo}i 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ;^27 

C.  With  the  economic  collapse  and  world  depression  of  1929, 
with  mounting  bankruptcies  and  foreclosures,  with  mass  unem- 
ployment and  despair  spreading  through  the  old  and  the  new 
middle  classes,  loyalties  to  the  Weimar  Republic  were  under- 
mined. The  "J^^s  ^"d  ^^^  "Marxists"  were  made  scapegoats  by 
the  plutocratically  financed  Nazi  movement,  which  revived  pan- 
Germanic  ideologies,  raised  anti-Semitism  to  a  frenzy,  and  carried 
the  "unknown"  soldier  of  Austrian  descent  into  the  Reichs  chan- 
cellery of  Bismarck's  creation. 

After  Hindenburg's  death.  Hitler,  as  "Fiihrer  and  chancellor" 
with  his  national  socialist  part\'  and  its  octopus-like  mass  affilia- 
tions, organized  all  institutional  orders  for  total  war  and  aggres- 
sion. Hitler  became  the  number  one  recipient  of  honor  and  the 
fountainhead  of  everyone  else's  honor.  A  quasi-military  status 
model  of  uniformed,  party-disciplined  Nazis  was  imposed  upon  all 
occupational  groups,  through  regimented  mass  organizations  of 
youth,  women,  labor.  All  of  them  were  headed  by  the  ubiquitous 
Nazi  plebeian  and  his  assimilated  types.  With  the  advent  of  war, 
the  dynamics  of  status  operated  in  favor  of  the  practitioners  of 
violence,  the  Gestapo  terrorist  of  the  Elite  Guard  and  the  army. 

D.  Under  the  occupation  regimes,  after  Germany's  defeat,  the 
conquerors  from  West  and  East  naturally  overshadowed  German 
society.  There  were  administrative  and  juridical  purges  of  or- 
ganized Nazism.  In  the  West  the  political  reorganization  has  been 
based  upon  the  bureaucracies  of  the  several  states,  and  rested  on  a 
reconstituted  bourgeois  party  of  middle-class  notables,  financed 
by  reconstructed  big  business.  Veteran  organizations  of  officers 
have  emerged,  and  the  general  restoration  policy  under  such  slo- 
gans as  the  "social  market  economy, '  meaning  essentially  laissez 
faire,  seems  to  be  reproducing  a  status  stratification  not  so  differ- 
ent from  the  system  that  preceded  the  great  depression— but,  of 
course,  on  a  generally  lower  economic  level  and  in  a  truncated 
state  of  47  million  people. 

In  the  East,  Germany  has  undergone  a  social  revolution,  involv- 
ing the  communist-managed  liquidation  of  the  Junker  estates,  the 
socialization  of  strategic  industries,  the  establishment  of  a  quasi- 
totalitarian  one-party  state,  the  displacement  of  the  old  bureaucra- 
cies by  newly  trained  Gommunist  cadres.  The  ruling  party  thus 
proceeds  to  manage  class  and  status  developments  by  totalitarian 
plans— all  in  the  direction  of  the  Soviet  model. 


238  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

III.  In  the  Soviet  Union,  the  economic  order  is  fused  with  the 
pohtical  order,  and  subjected  to  the  planned  management  by  poH- 
tical  agents.  Within  the  dominant  poHtical  order,  in  turn,  power, 
status,  class,  and  occupation  have  come  in  large  part,  directly 
and  indirectly,  to  depend  upon  political  party  membership.  In 
Russia,  membership  in  the  Communist  party,  combined  with  execu- 
tive positions,  "replaces,"  as  it  were,  property  ownership  as  a 
central  basis  for  status  and  class. 

The  Soviet  system  has  abolished  private  property  in  the  means 
of  production  and  with  it  the  hereditary  transmission  of  power 
based  on  property.  Stability  and  the  status  quo  are  maintained 
without  these  by  means  of  politicized,  rather  than  primarily  eco- 
nomically based,  ruling  groups.  As  Karl  Mannheim  has  put  it,  the 
problems  were  "how  to  produce  a  new  ruling  group  ...  to  guar- 
antee a  stable  social  order,  how  to  discover  new  status  defining 
factors  other  than  income  and  property,  and  how  to  provide  new 
work  incentives."  The  general  answer  to  all  three  was  found  by 
shifting  the  dominant  institutional  locus  of  stratification  from  the 
economic  to  the  political  order  and  thus  instituting  "new  power 
and  status"  gradations  in  place  of  the  "old  inequalities  of  wealth 
and  income."  But  income  differentials  were  introduced  and  oppor- 
tunities to  save  by  state  bonds  were  opened  up.  To  these  economic 
incentives  were  added  the  rivalrous  incentives  and  rewards  of 
status,  as  well  as  coercive  punishments. 

There  are  honorific  distinctions  for  the  vanguards  and  stars 
of  various  occupational  groups.  There  are  "heroes  of  labor,"  Stak- 
hanov  and  shock  workers  of  all  sorts,  as  well  as  state-honored 
writers  and  actresses,  composers,  schoolteachers  and  soldiers,  and 
the  mothers  of  many  children.  Each  functionally  significant  group 
serves  as  a  base  for  a  conspicuous  vanguard  of  Stalin-decorated 
"heroes,"  of  this  or  that  routine  pursuit  brought  to  extraordinary 
perfection. 

The  star  performers  serve  as  universally  publicized  pacesetters; 
they  receive  special  emoluments  in  money  and  in  kind,  and  oper- 
ate in  especially  planned  competitive  fields  built  into  the  over-all 
plan  of  the  managed  social  structure.  Thus  a  Stalin-honored 
shock  worker  may  receive  a  considerably  higher  income  and  have 
higher  status  than  an  undistinguished  plant  manager  under  whose 
jurisdiction  he  works.  Individual  competition,  group  competition, 
and  institutional   competition   are  utilized  in   a   planned   way  to 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  339 

maximize  effort  and  efficiency.  Tfie  competitively  selected  winners 
are  received  into  the  ruling  party  by  co-optation— if  they  did  not 
already  belong.  Their  public  prestige  is  thus  partially  ascribed  to 
the  fact  that  they  are  pre-eminent  communists  or  exemplary  "Soviet 
men  and  women."  The  party,  in  the  last  analysis,  sets  the  tasks, 
awards  the  premiums,  and  in  turn  cashes  in  on  individual  perform- 
ances. 

The  party  is  thus  at  once  the  fountainhead  and  the  depository 
of  all  prestige  and  status.  Personal  merit  is  premiumed  through 
the  "star  system,"  which,  with  its  prestige  halo,  seemingly  spells 
out  "equal  opportunities  for  all,"  deflects  attention  from  the  un- 
known (and  in  fact  only  statistically  assessable)  differences  in 
life-chances  of  the  various  groups. 

In  any  case,  differences  in  status  and  power,  mediated  by  the 
one-party  state,  are  definitely  established,  as  well  as  income  in- 
equalities. The  "ruling  class"  is  the  Communist  party  (and  its  mass 
of  affiliations),  a  political  fact;  and  not  high  propertied  classes, 
an  economic  fact.  This  system  of  domination  is  anchored  in  large 
bureaucratic  organizations  of  trade  unions  and  trusts,  in  addition 
to  the  branches  of  a  state  apparatus  usual  in  Western  democracies. 
The  source  of  power  and  its  distribution  thus  has  to  do  with  mass 
organizations  which  monopolize  the  means  of  administration  and 
communication,  production  and  destruction.  "The  totalitarian 
party,"  Mannheim  puts  it,  "is  the  ruling  class  in  a  world  of  total 
syndicalization."  ^^ 

8.  Stratification  and  Political  Mentality 

What  is  at  issue  in  theories  of  stratification  and  political  power  is 
( 1 )  the  objective  position  of  various  strata  with  reference  to  other 
strata  of  modern  society,  and  (2)  the  political  content  and  direc- 
tion of  their  mentalities.  Questions  concerning  either  of  these 
issues  can  be  stated  in  such  a  way  as  to  allow,  and  in  fact  de- 
mand, observational  answers  only  if  adequate  conceptions  of  strati- 
fication and  political  mentality  are  clearly  set  forth. 

Often  the  "mentality"  of  strata  is  allowed  to  take  predominance 
over  the  objective  position.  It  is,  for  example,  frequently  asserted 

11  See  Karl  Mannheim,  Freedom,  Power  and  Democratic  Phinninp.  ( New 
York:  Oxford,  1950),  p.  82  ff.,  from  which  we  have  drawn  in  this  subsection. 


240  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

that  "there  are  no  classes  in  the  United  States"  because  "psychol- 
ogy is  of  the  essence  of  classes"  or,  as  Alfred  Bingham  has  put 
it,  that  "class  groupings  are  always  nebulous,  and  in  the  last  anal- 
ysis only  the  vague  thing  called  class  consciousness  counts."  It 
is  said  that  people  in  the  United  States  are  not  aware  of  them- 
selves as  members  of  classes,  do  not  identify  themselves  with  their 
appropriate  economic  level,  do  not  often  organize  in  terms  of 
these  brackets  or  vote  along  the  lines  they  provide.  America,  in 
this  reasoning,  is  a  sandheap  of  "middle-class  individuals." 

But  this  is  to  confuse  psychological  feelings  with  other  kinds  of 
social  and  economic  reality.  Because  men  are  not  "class  conscious" 
at  all  times  and  in  all  places  does  not  mean  that  "there  are  no 
classes"  or  that  "in  America  everybody  is  middle  class."  The  eco- 
nomic and  social  facts  are  one  thing;  psychological  feelings  may 
or  may  not  be  associated  with  them  in  rationally  expected  ways. 
Both  are  important,  and  if  psychological  feelings  and  political 
outlooks  do  not  correspond  to  economic  or  occupational  class,  we 
must  try  to  find  out  why,  rather  than  throw  out  the  economic  baby 
with  the  psychological  bath  water,  and  so  fail  to  understand  how 
either  fits  into  the  national  tub.  No  matter  what  people  believe, 
class  structure  as  an  economic  arrangement  influences  their  life 
chances  according  to  their  positions  in  it.  If  they  do  not  grasp  the 
causes  of  their  conduct  this  does  not  mean  that  the  social  analyst 
must  ignore  or  deny  them. 

If  political  mentalities  are  not  in  line  with  objectively  defined 
strata  that  lack  of  correspondence  is  a  problem  to  be  explained; 
in  fact,  it  is  the  grand  problem  of  the  psychology  of  social  strata. 
The  general  problem  of  stratification  and  political  mentality  thus 
has  to  do  with  the  extent  to  which  the  members  of  objectively 
defined  strata  are  homogeneous  in  their  political  alertness,  out- 
look, and  allegiances,  and  with  the  degree  to  which  their  political 
mentality  and  actions  are  in  line  with  the  interests  demanded  by 
the  juxtaposition  of  their  objective  position  and  their  accepted 
values. 

To  understand  the  occupation,  class,  and  status  positions  of  a 
set  of  people  is  not  necessarily  to  know  whether  or  not  they  ( i ) 
will  become  class  conscious,  feeling  that  they  belong  together  or 
that  they  can  best  realize  their  rational  interests  by  combining; 
(2)  will  have  "collective  attitudes"  of  any  sort,  including  those 
toward  themselves,  their  common  situation;  (3)  will  organize  them- 


INSTITUTIONAL     ORDERS  ^4^ 

selves,  or  be  open  to  organization  by  others,  into  associations, 
movements,  or  political  parties;  or  (4)  will  become  hostile  toward 
other  strata  and  struggle  against  them.  These  social,  political,  and 
psychological  characteristics  may  or  may  not  occur  on  the  basis 
of  similar  objective  situations.  In  any  given  case,  such  possibilities 
must  be  explored,  and  "subjective"  attributes  must  not  be  used 
as  criteria  for  class  inclusion,  but  rather,  as  Max  Weber  has  made 
clear,  stated  as  probabilities  on  the  basis  of  objectively  defined 
situations. 

Implicit  in  this  way  of  stating  the  issues  of  stratification  lies  a 
model  of  social  movements  and  political  dynamics.  (^The  important 
differences  among  people  are  differences  that  shape  their  biogra- 
phies and  ideas;  jwithin  any  given  stratum  of  course,  individuals 
differ,  but  if  their  stratum  has  been  adequately  understood,  we 
ought  to  be  able  to  expect  certain  psychological  traits  to  recur. 
Our  principles  of  stratification  enable  us  to  do  this.  The  proba- 
bility that  people  will  have  a  similar  mentality  and  ideology,  and 
that  they  will  join  together  for  action,  is  increased  the  more  homo- 
geneous they  are  with  respect  to  class,  occupation,  and  prestige. 
Other  factors  do,  of  course,  affect  the  probability  that  ideology, 
organization,  and  consciousness  will  occur  among  those  in  objec- 
tively similar  strata.  But  psychological  factors  are  likely  to  be 
associated  with  strata,  which  consist  of  people  who  are  character- 
ized by  an  intersection  of  the  several  dimensions  we  have  been 
discussing:  class,  occupation,  status,  and  power.  The  task  is  to 
sort  out  these  dimensions  of  stratification  in  a  systematic  way, 
paying  attention  to  each  separately  and  then  to  its  relation  to  each 
of  the  other  dimensions. 


CHAPTER 

XII 


The  Unity  of  Social  Structures 


EVER  since  men  came  to  suspect  that  Adam  Smith's  "Unseen 
Hand"  was  no  longer  the  hand  of  a  harmony-loving  God,  students 
of  society  have  had  to  recognize  and  examine  the  disunity  as  well 
as  the  unity  of  societies.  In  our  times,  we  can  no  longer  assume 
that  friction  and  strain,  tension  and  stress  are  on  the  automatic 
decline.  In  fact,  their  pressure,  as  we  know  full  well,  may  accumu- 
late to  the  breaking  point:  whole  societies  may  be  disrupted,  masses 
of  men  as  well  as  statesmen  astonished,  and  no  hopes  exist  for 
a  new  harmony  or  "equilibrium." 

On  the  other  hand,  "common  values"  held  in  "harmony"  may 
to  some  men  seem  as  frightful  as  great  disharmony  seems  to  be 
to  others.  For  harmony  as  well  as  common  values  may  of  course 
be  imposed,  not  by  any  unseen  hand,  but  by  the  hubris  of  a  dic- 
tator. There  is  a  price  to  pay  for  harmony,  as  well  as  for  dis- 
harmony. 

In  the  main,  however,  academic  students  of  society  have  tended, 
in  one  way  or  another,  to  place  great  value  on  harmony  and  unity. 
The  unity  of  a  social  structure,  for  example,  has  frequently  been 
conceived  as  in  some  way  a  "manifestation"  or  "expression"  of  an 
underlying  "geist,"  "theme,"  or  "style."  Spengler's  "geist"  is  an 
outstanding  case,^  and  deriving  from  him— and  from  Nietzsche— 
the  late  anthropologist,  Ruth  Benedict,  who  attempted  to  subsume 
and  understand  whole  societies  as  "Dionysian"  or  "Apollonian."  - 
Sorokin's  "logico-meaningful"  imity,  reminiscent  of  Georg  Simmel's 
formal  analogies,  is  a  quite  sophisticated  example  of  this  type  of 
integration.'^ 

1  Oswald  Spengler,  The  Decline  of  the  West,  C.  F.  Atkinson,  tr.  (New  York: 
Knopf,   1926). 

-Patterns  of  Culture    (Boston:    Houghton   Mifflin,    1934). 

3  Sorokin's  unity,  in  fact,  comes  in  four  major  types— spatial  or  mechanical 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  ^43 

There  is  no  doubt  but  that  such  morphological  notions  do  often 
allow  us  to  grasp,  sometimes  in  a  suggestive  way,  the  structural 
features  of  total  societies.  The  interpretation  of  variegated  details 
in  the  light  of  a  general,  pervasive  principle  is  fascinating  and 
suggestive,  and  much  imaginative  work  has  been  done  with  the 
aid  of  such  conceptions.  But  they  do  present  certain  difficulties:  ' 

( 1 )  Because  these  "wholes"  are  often  formally  composed  of 
quite  variegated  materials,  their  construction  tends  to  blur  the 
various  parts  of  the  social  structure,  or  at  least,  does  not  invite 
discriminations  of  variations  among  the  parts.  (2)  In  particular, 
the  interest  in  such  morphological  wholes  often  blunts  attention 
to  all  those  tensions,  conflicts,  and  contradictions  of  interests  and 
values  that  may  exist  in  heterogeneous  institutional  structures.  (3) 
In  these  models,  the  linking  of  one  part  of  a  society  with  another 
is  quite  often  by  analogy,  and  accordingly,  we  are  distracted  from 
the  central  task  of  finding  adequate  and  sufficient  causes  for  the 
various  phenomena  we  observe.  Because  they  allow  us  to  deal, 
in  the  beginning,  with  the  whole  society,  such  schemes  do  not 
encourage  us  to  trace  ramifications  from  one  part  of  the  society 
to  other  parts. 

It  is  possible  to  use  what  is  sound  in  such  conceptions  of  "stylis- 
tic" unity— and  to  control  their  assumptions— by  our  notion  of  sym- 
bol spheres.  In  these  terms,  what  this  mode  of  interpretation 
amounts  to  is  the  assumption  of  the  unity  and  the  autonomy  of 
symbol  spheres  and  of  the  causal  weight  of  master  symbols  in  ex- 
juxtaposition:  a  random  group  of  people  in  the  street;  association  due  to  an 
external  factor:  rain  drives  them  to  shelter;  causal  or  functional  unity:  they 
assemble  for  a  movie;  and  "logico-meaningful"  unity:  their  underlying  com- 
monalities in  conduct  due,  in  modern  society  for  example,  to  the  role  of 
money,   punctuality,   and   mechanical   mo\ement. 

We  may  also  place  in  this  type  of  theory  Morris  E.  Opler's  "themes,"  which 
"denote  a  postulate  .  .  .  declared  or  implied,  and  usually  controlling  beha\  ior 
or  stimulating  activity,  which  is  tacitly  appro\ed  or  openly  promoted  in  a 
society."  American  Journal  of  Sociology,  November  1945,  p.  198. 

*  Most  of  these  drawbacks  also  hold  of  the  popular  "dicliotomy  views."  We 
refer  to  Sir  Henry  Maine's  distinction  of  "status  and  contract,"  which  is 
perhaps  the  father,  even  if  often  quite  far  remoxed,  of  Tonnies'  "community 
and  society,"  Spencer's  "military  and  industrial  societies,"  Durkheim's  "organic 
vs.  mechanical,"  Redfield's  "Folk  and  Urban  Society,"  Becker's  "sacred  and 
'  secular."  Often,  in  fact  usually,  the  dichotomy  is  also  used  as  a  trend  model: 
societies  move  from  status  to  contract,  from  sacred  to  secular,  from  military 
to  industrial. 


244  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

plaining  the  details  of  individual  conduct  and  institutional  struc- 
ture.^ 

In  this  chapter,  in  which  we  attempt  to  grapple  with  the  prob- 
lem of  social  unity,  we  shall  briefly  review  those  aspects  of  our 
model  which  bear  upon  the  statement  and  solution  of  the  general 
problem.  We  shall  present  this  "review"  by  setting  forth  a  recom- 
mended procedure  for  analyzing  total  social  structures,  and,  on  a 
more  general  level,  by  advancing  four  types  in  accordance  with 
which  social  structures  may  be  unified.  In  order,  however,  that 
the  reader  may  have  in  mind  concrete  materials,  we  shall  begin 
with  a  brief  account  of  the  integration  of  Sparta,  and  end  with 
an  account  of  the  disintegration  of  Rome. 

1.  The  Unity  of  Sparta 

Whenever  rigid  and  militarized  societies  have  emerged  in  the 
West,  the  image  of  unified  Sparta,  with  its  common  values  enforced 
by  military  co-ordination,  has  been  resurrected.  Men  such  as  Jean- 
Jacques  Rousseau  implemented  the  revolutionary  upsurge  of  demo- 
cratic enthusiasm  by  raising  up  images  of  the  stern  virtues  of  the 
Roman  Republican  and  disciplined  Spartan  warrior.  Nazi  intel- 
lectuals were  fond  of  trying  to  add  a  somber  glamour  to  their 
ranks  by  providing  flashbacks  to  the  stand  of  the  Spartans  at 
Thermopylae. 

From  the  time  of  the  second  Messinian  War  during  the  eighth 
century  B.C.  ancient  Sparta  was  organized  as  a  totalitarian  democ- 
racy of  warriors  on  a  permanent  war  footing.''  The  original  three 
tribal  subgroups,  or  phtjles,  had  been  superseded  by  five  phijles 
subdivided  into  "dining  clubs,"  each  comprising  fifteen  professional 
warrior  athletes.  These  heavily  armed  men  were  in  constant  train- 
ing or  in  constant  action,  from  the  time  of  their  initiation  into  the 
army  at  the  age  of  twenty  years— which  was  reminiscent  of  the 
bachelor  houses  of  archaic  tribes— to  the  veteran's  retirement  to  his 
household  at  the  age  of  sixty. 

■"'  We  have  already  criticized  these  assumptions  above  in  Chapter  X: 
Symbol  Spheres,  Section  4:  The  Autonomy  of  Symbol  Spheres. 

"  Cf.  Our  account  is  based  upon  Max  Weber,  Wirtschaft  und  Gesellschaft 
( Tubingen,  1921 ),  pp.  567  fF.  and  591  ff.;  and  Arnold  Toynbee,  A  Study  of  His- 
tory   (London,    1951),   especially   Vol.    III. 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  345 

At  the  head  of  the  political  community  there  stood  two  kings, 
hence  two  royal  families,  who  were  accountable  to  five  soldierly 
magistrates,  or  ephors,  elected  to  their  offices  for  annual  terms 
by  the  acclamatory  shouts  of  the  lined-up  army  formations.  The 
kings  were  annually  sworn  in  by  tliese  ephors,  who  may  be  com- 
pared to  the  Roman  tribune  of  the  people,  to  political  commissars 
like  Saint-Just,  who  purged  the  revolutionary  French  army  of 
unreliable  ancien  regime  officers,  or  to  the  commissars  of  the  Red 
Army. 

The  Spartan  army  was  led  in  the  field  by  one  of  the  kings,  who 
was  responsible  to  the  five  ephors,  to  the  point  of  exile  or  death, 
for  the  conduct  of  war.  Apart  from  this  perilous  function,  the 
kings  were  representative  figureheads,  restricted  to  the  perform- 
ance of  rituals. 

This  ruling  class  of  warriors  led  a  rigorous  and  austere  life. 
Military  honor,  eligibility  for  admittance  to  the  crack  fighting  unit 
of  300  elite  guards,  for  the  ephorate  and,  after  retirement,  for  the 
council  of  elders,  formed  the  goals  of  their  aspiration.  To  be  pub- 
licly shamed— and  by  husky  women  at  that— for  having  lost  one's 
shield,  for  having  flinched  in  combat,  for  not  having  stood  to  the 
last  by  one's  comrade-in-arms  and  one's  homosexual  partner  was 
the  object  of  fear.  Disputes  among  these  peers  were  settled  by  all- 
out  wrestling  duels  in  which  anything  went— from  the  gouging  of 
eyeballs,  the  splitting  of  nostrils,  to  the  biting  of  genitals.  An 
ascetic  code  controlled  the  personal  deportment  of  these  war- 
riors. To  say  a  great  deal  in  a  few  words  and  without  fuss  has 
become  famous  as  "laconic"  speech.  Gold  and  silver  were  despised, 
as  were  all  bodily  comforts.  The  famous  one-pot-menu  of  "black 
soup"— probably  made  from  oxblood  mixed  with  buckwheat— was 
not  enjoyed  at  Spartan  state  dinners  by  Athenian  ambassadors. 

The  two  kings,  the  five  ephors  in  charge  of  the  five  phylcs,  a 
council  of  elders,  and  the  assembled  army  thus  constituted  the 
political  and  military  order  of  Sparta,  which  is  known  as  the  Lycur- 
gean  system.  Its  rational  features  seem  to  indicate  a  planful  en- 
actment by  a  series  of  statesmen  rather  than  a  cresci\'e  emer- 
gence. The  fact  that  Homer  has  Ulysses's  son  receive  a  chariot  horse 
as  a  farewell  present  after  his  visit  to  the  Spartan  king,  as  well 
as  the  known  differences  in  dress  between  nobles  and  commoners, 
allow  us  to  infer  that  this  warrior  community  resulted  from  the 


34^  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

democratic  leveling  down  of  an  older  stratum  of  charioteering 
nobles  into  a  homogeneous  army  of  disciplined  footmen,  who  de- 
ployed their  phalanx  in  full  view  of  the  enemy. 

This  political-military  order  was  linked  to  the  economic  order 
through  the  economic  role  of  the  warrior's  wife.  She  had  to  pro- 
vide for  her  economically  expendable  husband  who,  living  in  his 
bachelor  club,  could  not  share  her  table.  The  warrior  needed  a 
land-rent  to  pay  for  his  equipment  and  upkeep  in  the  syssitia,  or 
"officers'  mess."  Upon  initiation  into  the  army  he  received  an  allot- 
ment of  land  and,  being  in  training,  he  could  not  farm  it  and  was 
obliged  to  find  a  spouse  capable  of  managing  his  farm  with  helot 
labor.  The  helots  were  the  bottom  stratum,  the  conquered  popu- 
lation who  had  been  reduced  to  serfdom.  Each  year  the  ephors 
ceremoniously  declared  war  upon  them  in  order  to  keep  them  in 
their  places. 

The  Spartan  bachelor  chose  his  wife  from  among  the  young 
women  engaged  in  athletic  contests,  which  thus  served  as  a  bridal 
show.  Exclusion  from  the  ranks  of  the  spectators  was  a  severe  pun- 
ishment for  the  young  man.  As  the  Greeks  displayed  themselves 
nude  in  the  sports  field— which  is  unique  for  any  upper  class— 
we  may  infer  that  the  physical  strength  and  endurance  of  the 
amazon  rather  than  presumably  superior  sensitivity,  premarital 
chastity,  or  status  badges  of  wealth  determined  "good  looks"  in 
the  warrior's  eyes.  Women  had  no  other  educators  than  men. 
They  were  prepared,  if  need  be,  to  bend  a  helot  to  erotic  service, 
or  to  cut  him  down  if  "uppity."  In  all  this,  the  Spartan  farmwife 
found  aid  and  succor  in  the  activities  of  youthful  bands  of  Spartan 
adolescents,  who  were  economically  and  pederastically  attached 
to  the  warrior  syssitias.  They  were  encouraged  to  rove  the  coun- 
tryside for  food.  Their  generalized  other  was  confined  to  the  war- 
rior community,  and,  in  their  chronic  fighting  relation  to  the  helots, 
force  and  fraud  were  meritorious.  To  have  a  dead  helot  to  his 
credit  gave  prominence  to  the  member  of  a  Spartan  youth  gang. 
What  chance  would  a  helot  have  if  a  Spartan  woman  put  the 
finger  on  him? 

The  life  of  the  Spartan  wife  was  not  easy.  Besides  her  economic 
role  of  extracting  a  sufficient  rent  for  her  absentee  warrior  hus- 
band from  the  land-tilling  helots,  she  was  expected  to  bear  and 
to  rear  many  children,  preferably  all  boys.  (In  passing  we  should 
remark  that  the  father  of  four  boys  was  freed  from  all  obligations 


THE  UNITY  OF  SOCIAL  STRUCTURES    3^/ 

to  the  state.)  As  in  other  ancient  societies,  infanticide  was  cus- 
tomary in  Sparta.  Given  the  interest  of  the  warrior  community  in 
the  quantity  and  quahty  of  population,  pubhc  officials  inspected 
the  newly  born  and  selected  those  fit  for  survival.  Spartan  wi\'es 
offered  themselves  or  helped  themselves  to  the  erotic  services  of 
men  other  than  their  husbands,  if  the  husbands  were  not  up  to 
eugenic  par. 

At  the  age  of  seven,  children  were  removed  from  maternal  care 
in  the  home  and  enrolled  in  gangs,  which  combined  children  of 
different  ages  in  such  a  way  that  the  older  led  the  younger,  up 
to  the  final  hurdle  of  unanimous  co-optation  by  a  syssitia.  As  at 
birth,  so  during  his  educational  career,  selective  elimination  threat- 
ened the  Spartan  youngster.  Life  in  the  successive  boy-gangs  se- 
lected and  reinforced  those  traits  required  by  the  he-man  warrior. 
Birth  and  inheritance  were  not  sufficient  for  admission  into  this 
highly  organized  ruling  class.  Exclusion  and  ostracism  by  one's 
peer  group  threatened  the  boy  who  was  lacking  in  physique,  cour- 
age, or  astuteness  and  skill  in  aggression,  in  self-discipline  or 
obedience  of  the  austere  warrior  code  of  this  garrison  state.  These 
boys  and  their  gangs  were  attached  to  the  men's  "messes,"  and 
formed  "fan"  relationships  with  the  warriors,  which  included 
pederastic  practices. 

With  the  old  nobility,  the  old  priesthood  had  gone.  Unlike  other 
Greek  states,  Sparta  left  no  temples  or  priestly  sponsored  art  to 
posterity.  Priests  and  poets,  artists  and  philosophers  were  singularly 
out  of  place  in  the  midst  of  these  military  professionals,  who  as 
is  usual  for  such  men,  despised  intellectuals  as  at  best  unmanly 
"penpushers,"  and  at  worst  likely  to  import  alien  ideas  and  dis- 
tract men  from  the  proper  business  at  hand.  These  warriors,  who 
accepted  death  in  battle  as  man's  usual  fate,  craved  neither  salva- 
tion for  their  souls  nor  spiritual  comfort  in  suffering,  for  they  were 
proud  to  "take  it"  without  e\en  the  rationale  of  stoic  philosophers. 
Their  motivation  and  control  was  a  conventionally  enforced  code 
of  honor,  and  in  this  they  compare  with  the  Confucian  erudite. 
The  difference  is  that  the  first  was  a  code  for  warriors,  the  second 
a  code  for  pacifist  literary  officials. 

In  brief,  then,  this  is  the  structural  scheme  for  the  miit\-  and 
disunity  of  Spartan  societ}':  in  this  warrior  democracy,  the  military 
and  the  political  orders  are  fused.  The  household  and  economic 
production  are  not  differentiated,  but  form  one  unit.  Formally,  the 


^^8  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

military-political  controls  the  economic  through  kinship  relations. 
For  the  ruHng  Spartans,  the  division  of  labor  thus  coincides  with 
sexual  differences:  women  take  over  the  household  and  farm  man- 
agement; men  fight.  The  wives  therefore  reside  in  the  countryside 
among  the  helot  farm  labor;  the  men  are  concentrated  in  their 
garrisoned  city.  Thus,  when  a  man  enters  military  service  he  must 
at  the  same  time  enter  marriage,  in  order  that  his  wife  may  pro- 
vision him. 

In  the  eighth  century  B.C.,  some  8,000  warriors  were  set  up  in 
this  way. 

But  by  the  fourth  century  B.C.  only  400  warriors  were  fully  quali- 
fied for  action. 

Why?  Why  did  Sparta  decline? 

Although  the  warrior  allotments  were  not  negotiable,  economic 
and  social  differentiations  did  slowly  advance.  A  dowry  system 
seems  to  have  allowed  for  the  accumulation  of  landholdings,  and 
as  the  Spartans  did  not  aim  at  imperialist  expansion  and  territorial 
gain,  they  did  not  compensate  for  this  gradual  shrinkage  of  the 
economic  base  for  warriors  qualified  to  equip  themselves  and  meet 
their  syssitia  obligations  in  kind  or  in  iron  money.  During  the 
fourth  century,  the  concentration  of  holdings  was  reinforced,  ac- 
cording to  Plutarch,  when  legislation  enabled  "the  holder  of  a 
family  property  or  an  allotment  to  give  it  away  during  his  lifetime 
or  to  bequeath  it  by  will,  to  anybody  whom  he  chose."  The  de- 
pendence of  the  warrior  on  his  wife  and  her  role  as  "heiress" 
would  seem  to  account  for  the  high  status  of  women  in  the  end. 
Arnold  Toynbee  has  also  pointed  to  the  demoralization  of  the 
Spartan  warrior  when  he  attempted  to  enact  leadership  roles  in 
wider  contexts  than  those  of  his  native  society. 

In  summary,  then,  the  general  reasons  for  Sparta's  disintegration 
are  found  in  the  concentration  of  land  holdings  to  a  point  where 
not  enough  warriors,  given  their  military  tasks,  were  provisioned. 
Thus,  autonomous  processes  in  the  household  and  the  economy 
ramified  into  the  military  and  political  orders,  and  undermined 
them.  These  processes  of  quantitative  change  ( fewer  but  larger  eco- 
nomic bases  for  warriors)  made  for  a  smaller  army  because  family 
size  (especially  sons)  did  not  increase  in  proportion  to  the  in- 
creased sizes  of  the  holdings. 

We  have  briefly  articulated  the  social  stiucture  of  Sparta  in  order 
—as  we  have  already  remarked— that  the  reader  may  have  in  mind 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  249 

some  concrete  materials.  We  shall  now  "back  off"  from  these  ma- 
terials, and  consider  more  abstractly  and  in  terms  of  procedures, 
the  general  problem  of  social  unity. 

2.  Units  and  Their  Relationships 

It  is  easy  to  believe  that  each  section  of  a  society  is  related  to 
every  other  section,  that  society  is  in  some  manner  a  whole  of 
busily  interacting  parts.  But  this  assumption  does  not  tell  us  very 
much.  As  a  beginning  point  it  is  useful,  but  by  itself  it  is  an  unin- 
formative  truism.  For  what  it  does,  at  best,  is  advise  us  to  be  on 
the  lookout  for  specific  connections  between  specific  parts  and  their 
relations  to  the  whole.  Whatever  models  of  integration  we  end 
up  with,  much  less  whatever  theory,  there  is  a  descriptive  task  at 
hand  for  anyone  who  would  intelligently  describe  social  structures 
as  "wholes."  This  task  will  be  governed  in  the  first  instance  by  the 
units  of  social  structure  that  are  used.  So  our  first  question  is: 

I.  Units:  How  shall  we  articulate  a  society— that  is,  what  unit  or 
units  shall  we  seize  upon  or  abstract  as  "parts"  which  we  would 
relate  to  other  "parts"?  And,  specifically,  for  any  given  society,  how 
articulated  or  autonomous  are  these  units? 

We  cannot  claim,  and  in  this  social  psychology  we  cannot  at- 
tempt, a  detailed  coverage  of  world  history;  we  obviously  seek 
to  transcend  ideographic  details  and  to  use  them  in  search  for  gen- 
eralizations and  regularities;  so  we  give  up  the  simple  canon  of 
"complete  description."  We  must  acknowledge  that  we  have  to 
select,  and  we  must  therefore  become  the  self-conscious  masters  of 
our  canons  of  selection.  What  are  these  canons?  We  must  con- 
sciously select  a  set  of  units  which  will  enable  us  ( i )  to  proceed 
systematically  in  our  descriptions  of  the  internal  compositions  of 
each  society  we  would  examine  and  thus  (2)  give  ourselves  a 
maximum  chance  for  comparisons  between  social  structures.  (3) 
Moreover,  the  unit  chosen  must  not  only  permit  economy  of 
systematic  description,  but  it  must  be  a  description  adequate  for 
causal  imputations.  To  do  this  requires  that  we  find  a  fruitful 
level  of  generality,  which  means  a  level  that  is  flexible,  or  that 
has  a  shuttle  from  high  to  low  built  into  it.  (4)  Our  level  of  gen- 
erality must  be  low  enough  not  only  to  allow  but  to  invite  con- 
crete descriptions,  for  there  is  no  substitute  in  "theory"  for  pains- 


250  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

taking  mastery  of  detail;  it  must  equip  us  to  see  what  we  other- 
wise might  miss.  And  (5)  it  must  be  high  enough  to  allow  com- 
parisons across  all  known  societies.  These,  along  with  (6)  the  re- 
quirement that  the  units  be  open  to  psychological  analysis,  are  the 
criteria  which  we  have  kept  in  mind  in  choosing  our  units  and 
constructing  our  scheme  of  social  structure.  Our  unit,  the  institu- 
tional order  (with  its  subunits  of  specific  institutions  and  finally 
of  role),  along  with  the  idea  of  spheres,  satisfies  in  a  provisional 
way,  we  feel,  these  critieria.^ 

II.  Relations:  The  second  question  we  face  is  of  more  immediate 
concern  to  the  problem  of  integration:  Precisely  how  are  these 
units  interrelated,  that  is,  what  is  the  "dimension,"  or  what  are 
the  dimensions,  in  terms  of  which  we  would  relate  them  with  one 
another?  The  relations  of  our  units  are  conveniently  construed  in 
terms  of  a  means-ends  schema,  which  involves  the  dimension  of 
power.  Thus  we  are  interested  in  finding  to  what  extent,  if  any, 
events  in  one  institutional  order  may  be  considered  preconditions 
of  events  in  other  orders.  We  are  also  interested  in  tracing  the 
ramifications  of  trends  in  one  order  with  other  orders,  and  in  under- 
standing how  such  ramifications  may  facilitate  or  limit  activities 
and  policies  in  other  orders.  In  short,  our  units— institutional  orders 
—may  be  related  with  one  another  causally  in  a  variety  of  ways 
and  degrees.  Given  orders  may  be  functionally  independent  or 
dependent  of  one  another. 

III.  Procedural  Scheme:  Let  us  make  our  answers  to  both  of 
these  questions  more  concrete,  and  thus  begin  to  illustrate  why 
we  feel  that  the  scheme  invites  description  of  prevailing  units  and 
of  the  causal  relations  obtaining  among  them. 

In  examining  a  specific  society  our  first  decision  has  to  do  with 
whether  we  will  use  as  our  prime  units  institutional  orders,  insti- 
tutions, or  roles.  This  decision  should  rest  upon  the  degree  to 
which  the  society  is,  upon  examination,  found  to  contain  autono- 
mously existing  orders  of  institutions.  Now,  our  scheme  of  dis- 
tinguishable institutional  orders  is  obviously  derived  from  observa- 

"  Tlie  reader  may  wish  at  this  point  to  reread  Chapter  II :  Character  and 
Social  Structure,  Section  2:  Components  of  Social  Structure,  and  Chapter  VII: 
Institutions  and  Persons,  Section  i:  The  Institutional  Selection  of  Persons, 
and  Section  2.:  The  Institutional  Formation  of  Persons. 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  35I 

tion  of  modern  Western  society,  and  only  in  a  society  which  has 
a  relatively  autonomous  development  of  these  functions  (or  of 
others)  can  we  best  proceed  with  this  unit. 

We  can  conceive  of  societies  (for  example,  the  nomadic  sib)  in 
which  there  is  only  one  coherent  institution— in  this  case,  the  extant 
kinship  group— which  provides  in  its  organization  all  the  roles 
required  to  fulfill  such  functions  as  are  served  in  the  society.  In 
such  a  case,  we  should  seize  upon  roles  as  our  basic  units  which 
are  to  be  related. 

On  the  next  "level,"  we  might  imagine  a  society  (for  instance  a 
tribal  confederacy  of  nomadic  sibs)  in  which  there  was  more  than 
one  institvition,  but  in  which  these  did  not  differ  from  one  another 
in  terms  of  function.  For  example,  in  this  case  we  ha\e  a  society 
in  which  kinship  units  also  performed  all  other  functions.  Accord- 
ingly, we  should  seize  upon  institutions  as  the  basic  units  to  be 
related. 

We  thus  have  three  levels  of  unit,  as  it  were,  to  choose  among 
as  our  first  level  of  description.  We  say  the  first  level  of  description 
because  obviously  in  cases  where  institutions  are  the  units  we  shall 
also  handle  the  roles,  and  where  institutional  orders  have  been  un- 
folded as  articulate  units,  we  shall  also  handle  the  institutions 
that  prevail  in  each  and  the  kinds  of  roles  that  in  turn  compose 
them. 

Why  do  we  always  choose  the  "higher"  of  these  three  units  that 
exist  for  our  first  description?  Because  the  roles  in  which  we  are 
most  interested  are  part  of  an  institution  and  can  be  understood 
only  with  reference  to  its  institutional  context;  and,  institutions, 
if  they  are  part  of  an  institutional  order,  can  most  readily  be  under- 
stood as  part  of  the  order  in  which  they  occur.  This  contextual 
guide-line  is  important;  for  example,  apparently  identical  institu- 
tions may  be  found  in  different  orders,  but  qualitative  differences 
may  occur  to  what,  in  isolation,  may  appear  to  be  identical.  The 
monopoly  factory  in  Tsarist  Russia  differed  in  origin  as  well  as  in 
its  position  among  the  totality  of  Russian  institutions  from  the  fac- 
tory in  1912  America.  In  Russia  such  a  factory  often  results  from 
political  concessions  to  foreign  capital;  in  America,  as  a  more  indig- 
enous development  of  a  laissez-faire  economy.  The  "same"  insti- 
tution "means"  different  things  with  reference  to  the  order  to 
which  it  belongs  and  with  reference  to  the  relation  of  this  order 
to  others  comprising  the  social  structure  of  which  it  is  a  part. 


S52  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

Because  of  the  usefulness  of  this  simple  contextual  principle,  we 
are  prompted,  wherever  possible,  to  proceed  in  the  first  instance, 
on  the  level  of  institutional  order.  In  fact,  we  sometimes  do  so 
even  when  such  an  articulation  of  institutions  is  a  purely  heuristic 
assumption  rather  than  a  discoverable  fact.  This  means  that  we 
might  so  proceed  even  in  a  society  in  which  no  functional  differen- 
tiation has  produced  identifiable  orders,  or  in  which  they  have 
been  "fused"  so  closely  that  the  actors  do  not  experience  their 
behavior  as  placed  in  different  orders.  In  such  cases,  obviously  the 
conception  of  institutional  order  is  an  "artificial"  imposition.  Yet, 
to  distinguish  for  analytical  purposes  is  not  to  overlook  their  unity. 
Only  if  we  do  proceed  thus  analytically  can  we  understand  such  a 
society  as,  in  fact,  representing  one  type  of  unified  integration.® 

As  is  well  known,  each  of  the  institutional  orders  of  the  sort  we 
have  presented  here  begins  to  form  and  to  become  autonomous 
with  the  Western  Renaissance  and  Reformation.  From  that  time, 
politics  emerges  from  the  all-pervasive  religious  order,  as  the  prince 
emerges  as  a  wielder  of  secular  power.  Then  also,  in  the  symbol 
sphere,  philosophy,  science,  and  art  gradually  cease  to  be  hand- 
maidens of  theology.  Then  Machiavelli  discerns  "pure  power  prob- 
lems" of  the  political  man,  who  treats  all  life  as  means  of  getting, 
holding,  increasing,  and  wielding  power.  With  the  emergence  of 
the  factory,  i.e.,  the  segregation  of  enterprise  from  household  dur- 
ing the  eighteenth  century,  the  economic  order  begins  to  acquire 
autonomy,  the  police  state  increasingly  withdraws  from  the  mer- 
cantilist intervention  in  the  economic  order.  Only  then  could  eco- 
nomic science  conceive  of  the  economic  man— and  his  rationally 
expedient  behavior  in  markets— as  a  suitable  model  for  analyzing 
the  economic  order  in  industrial  society.  The  general  process  of  the 
unfolding  and  autonomy  of  orders  perhaps  reaches  its  extreme 
when  in  the  symbol  and  technological  spheres  (which  thus  made 
pretenses  to  be  autonomous  orders)  men  speak  seriously  of  "sci- 
ence for  science's  sake,"  of  "art  for  art's  sake."  Thus  segregated 
activities  and  ends  are  fetishized. 

The  problem  of  the  unity  of  a  social  structure,  especially  as  it 
bears  upon  the  unit  chosen,  obviously  diff^ers  for  differently  artic- 
ulated societies.  The  first  empirical  task,  in  approaching  any  given 
society,  is  to  discover  the  most  convenient  units  that  prevail,  in 

8  See  below,  this  chapter,  Section  3:  Modes  of  Integration. 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  353 

terms  of  which  the  problem  of  structural  unity  or  integration  may 
best  be  stated. 

Having  due  regard  to  this,  we  will  nevertheless  assume  institu- 
tional orders  as  our  unit,  and  use  that  unit  in  presenting  our 
procedural  scheme,  for  this  enables  us  to  handle,  at  least  formally, 
the  salient  problems  of  unity  encountered  in  societies  that  are 
not  articulated  into  orders.  For  a  society  in  which  all  five  orders 
are  autonomous  enough  to  permit  separate  delineation  and  thus 
relationships,  one  must  "fill  in"  the  following  boxes: 


INSTITUTIONAL  SPHERES 

EDUCATION 
STATUS 


ORDERS 

POLITICAL  1 


SYMBOLS 
TECHNOLOGY 


ECONOMIC  6  2 

MILITARY  7  10  3 

RELIGIOUS  8  11  13  4 

KINSHIP  9  12  14  15  5 

POLITICAL  ECONOMIC  MILITARY     RELIGIOUS     KINSHIP 

First,  the  range  and  the  basic  characteristics  of  the  institutions 
prevailing  in  each  order  are  determined:  1  through  5.  This  first 
task  includes  a  description  of  the  spheres  of  each  of  these  orders: 
education,  status,  symbols,  technology. 

Second,  the  relations  between  each  of  the  orders  with  each  of 
the  others  are  described:  6  through  15.  This  second  task  consists 
of  a  detailed  tracing  of  the  ramifications  and  other  relations  of 
each  order  upon  all  others.  So  much  is  basic:  Only  when  this  is 
done  on  a  purely  descriptive  level  do  we  have  ( 1 )  a  basis  for 
comparing  different  social  structures  and  (2)  a  basis  for  causal 
imputations  in  explanation  of  \  arious  roles,  institutions,  or  the  shape 
of  the  social  structure  as  a  whole. 

"Ramification"  refers  to  the  operation  of  one  order  within  other 
orders:  or,  to  the  use  of  one  order  for  the  ends  of  the  ramifying 
order.  The  "ramifications"  of  any  order  refer  to  its  total  range  of 
such  operations  in  all  other  orders.  The  political  order  may  thus 
ramify  into  kinship  most  closely  and  brutally  when  all  intimate 
relations  and  locales  of  the  kinship  unit  are  used  by  police  agents 


S54  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

who  see  them  as  "a  network  of  living  traps"  for  the  suspect  or 
prisoner  of  the  poHtical  order.  When  poHtical  relations— for  ex- 
ample, international  affairs— are  carried  on  by  competing  dynastic 
families,  women,  as  shrewd  manipulators  of  men  in  the  kinship 
order,  may  exert  considerable  influence  upon  key  political  decisions. 
The  economic  order  may  ramify  into  the  political,  as  in  modern 
capitalist  societies;  for  example,  as  economic  institutions,  corpora- 
tions seek  to  influence  the  content  and  administration  of  laws  in 
order  to  gain  or  to  retain  economic  privileges.  Their  political  actions 
are  thus  means  for  an  economic  end.  Ramifications  has  to  do  with 
the  relative  powers  of  orders,  and  the  use  of  one  as  a  means  for 
the  other's  end. 

From  the  more  or  less  descriptive  level,  executed  as  concretely 
as  time  and  information  allow,  and  with  the  aid  of  typologies  found 
relevant  for  each  institutional  order,  we  move  by  examination  and 
comparison  to  explanations  of  the  integration  of  social  structures 
as  wholes. 

3.  Modes  of  Integration 

From  a  somewhat  formal  standpoint,  we  can  observe  certain 
general  ways  in  which  the  institutional  orders  composing  a  social 
structure  are  integrated.  These  modes  of  integration  are,  for  us, 
analytic  models  which  sensitize  us  to  certain  types  of  linkage  of 
one  order  with  another.  They  may  also,  of  course,  be  viewed  dy- 
namically, as  processes  of  social-historical  change. 

By  a  milieu  we  understand  the  social  setting  of  a  person  that  is 
directly  open  to  his  personal  experience.  It  is  a  surface  of  his  daily 
social  life.  In  his  day-to-day  life,  he  acts  in  a  variety  of  milieus— 
the  home,  the  place  of  work,  the  scene  of  amusement,  the  street. 
In  these  milieus  he  of  course  observes  changes,  but  most  people 
do  not  often  ask  why  these  changes  occur.  When  we  do  reflect 
upon  such  changes  in  milieus— such  as  our  neighborhood  over  a 
thirty-year  period— then  we  must  go  beyond  the  milieu  itself  to 
explain  the  change  observed  in  it.  And  this  means  that  we  come 
upon  the  idea  of  structures. 

By  a  structure,  in  the  present  sense,  we  understand  the  modes 
of  integration  by  which  various  milieus  are  linked  together  to  form 
a  larger  context  and  dynamics  of  social  life.  These  modes  of  Integra- 


THE  UNITY  OF  SOCIAL  STRUCTURES    35,5 

tion  may  be  stated  as  principia  media,  as  middle  principles,  ena- 
bling us  to  link  what  is  observable  in  various  milieus  but  caused 
by  structural  changes  in  institutional  orders.  Thus  the  neighbor- 
hood town  of  1850,  with  its  well-known  milieu,  appears  in  1950 
as  a  scatter  of  milieus,  none  of  which  is  recognizable  as  the  old: 
the  dirt  path  is  now  an  asphalt  strip,  and  the  railroad  connects 
the  daily  work  of  the  inhabitants  with  the  world  market. 

We  have  found  some  four  principles  of  structural  change  useful    f  f 
in  understanding  the  integration  of  a  society: 

I.  By  correspondence  we  mean  that  a  social  structure  is  unified 
by  the  working  out  in  its  several  institutional  orders  of  a  common 
structural  principle,  which  thus  operates  in  a  parallel  way  in  each. 

II.  By  coincidence  we  mean  that  different  structural  principles 
or  developments  in  various  orders  result  in  their  combined  effects 
in  the  same,  often  unforeseen,  outcome  of  unity  for  the  whole 
society. 

III.  By  co-ordination  we  refer  to  the  integration  of  a  society  by 
means  of  one  or  more  institutional  orders  which  become  ascendant 
over  other  orders  and  direct  them;  thus  other  orders  are  regulated 
and  managed  by  the  ascendant  order  or  orders. 

IV.  By  convergence  we  mean  that  two  or  more  institutional 
orders  coincide  to  the  point  of  fusion;  they  become  one  institutional 
setup. 

It  is  quite  difficult  to  isolate  concrete  societies  which  fully  and 
exclusively  exemplify  each  of  these  types  of  integration  because 
reality  is  usually  mixed.  The  integrations  of  some  areas  of  a  society 
can  often  best  be  understood  in  terms  of  one  mode  of  integration, 
while  other  parts  can  best  be  understood  by  application  of  an- 
other mode.  Nevertheless,  to  make  clear  what  is  involved  in  each 
type  of  integration,  we  can,  in  a  brief  way,  sketch  cases  in  which 
each  seems  to  predominate. 

I.  Correspondence.  The  handiest  case  of  correspondence  is  per- 
haps the  model  of  a  classic  liberal  society,  best  exemplified  by  the 
society  prevailing  in  the  first  half  of  the  nineteenth  century  in  the 
United  States.^  The  meaning  of  "laissez-faire"  for  the  economic 

9  Cf.  Charles  and  Mary  Beard,  The  Rise  of  American  Civilization  (rev.  ed.; 
New  York:  Macmillan,  1933);  and  A.  Lowe,  Economics  and  Sociology  (Lon- 
don:  Allen,   1935). 


S56  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

order  is  a  demand  on  the  part  of  economic  agents  for  freedom 
from  political  dominance.  It  is  paralleled  by  the  religious  demand 
for  autonomy  from  political  or  state  control  or  even  sponsorship  of 
any  one  type  of  religious  institution;  moreover,  here  too,  one 
Protestant  man  faced  his  God,  free  of  any  hierarchy  of  inter- 
preters. In  the  political  area,  as  in  the  economic  market,  there 
is  a  free  competition  for  the  individual's  vote.  In  the  kinship  order, 
also,  marriage  is  a  contract  between  the  marriage  partners  into 
which  they  enter  of  their  own  free  will;  marriages  are  not  to  be 
arranged  by  parental  collusion  of  economic  or  status  sort.  Just  as 
free  individuals  compete  economically,  so  do  they  in  the  status 
sphere:  "the  self-made  man"  stands  in  contrast  to  "the  family-made 
man"  of  the  kinship  order's  status  sphere,  just  as  a  much  as  to  the 
man  who  moves  on  his  own  across  the  autonomous  economic 
markets.  So  status  styles  are  often  represented  as  conspicuous  con- 
sumption of  the  self-made  businessman. 

On  the  highest  level  of  abstraction,  in  the  symbol  sphere,  the 
idea  of  human  freedom,  of  the  spontaneity  of  thinking,  acting,  and 
judging,  is  proclaimed  and  elaborated.  In  particular,  the  conception 
of  human  genius,  of  the  prerogative  of  free  creativity,  becomes  cen- 
tral, and  even  sets  an  ideal  model  for  the  nature  of  human  nature. 
So  educators  attempt  "to  make  the  student  think  for  himself." 

The  basic  legitimation  of  instituted  conduct  in  each  of  these 
orders  is  very  much  the  same:  the  free  initiative  of  the  autonomous 
individual  for  rational  and  moral  self-determination.  Thus  the 
symbol  spheres  of  the  various  orders  run  in  parallel  or  correspond- 
ing fashion.  In  each  order  free  individuals  could  institute  new  or- 
ganizations according  to  the  principle— or  at  times  even  the  expecta- 
tion—of voluntary  associations.  Independent  decision-making  and 
organization  thus  unify  what  on  the  surface  might  appear  as  merely 
the  unplanned  complexity  and  enormous  variety  of  nineteenth-cen- 
tury "causes." 

The  correspondence  of  diverse  and  relatively  autonomous  orders 
is  the  outcome  of  processes  in  which  all  significant  orders  develop 
in  the  direction  of  an  integrative  principle  of  competition  or  laissez 
faire.  In  all  orders  competition  means  that  individuals  act  in  a 
field  of  action  which  impersonally  disciplines  them  for  uniform 
strivings  and  motives,  and  in  its  terms  free  men  find  their  places. 
This  principle  also  secured  a  rather  smooth  and  gradual  transferal 


THE  UNITY  OF  SOCIAL  STRUCTURES    ;^$y 

or  shift  in  power  within  and  between  orders.  The  translation  of 
economic  into  pohtical  power  is  particularly  relevant. 

Of  course,  the  model  of  a  liberal  society  does  not  contain  only 
elements  that  correspond  to  the  principle  of  individual  freedom  of 
choice.  In  fact,  definite  compulsions  are  introduced  in  the  political 
order  which,  although  enacted  by  free  men,  nevertheless  are  com- 
pulsions: in  Europe  (since  the  time  of  Napoleon)  there  has  been 
universal  compulsory  military  service.  And  there  has  been  com- 
pulsory taxation  and  universal  compulsory  education  up  to  various 
standards.  In  these  respects,  the  modern  state  has  advanced  beyond 
any  previously  known  political  controls,  for  only  in  modern  times, 
with  modern  technology  and  special  techniques  of  communications 
available,  have  such  large-scale  and  intensive  administrative  accom- 
plishments been  possible.  These,  although  most  important,  have 
been  quite  uneven  in  their  application,  and  in  the  case  of  property, 
given  its  wide  distribution,  have  really  been  a  sort  of  anchor  of 
the  basic  freedom.  Accordingly,  such  compulsions  are  important 
for  the  model  of  classic  liberal  society  as  exceptions  to  the  integra- 
tion of  the  whole  by  autonomously  choosing  individuals. 

Many  other  examples  of  correspondence  come  to  mind:  the  occi- 
dental feudal  principle  of  an  "exchange"  of  personal  allegiance  for 
protection,  as  displayed  in  the  psychology  of  vassalship  in  political, 
economic,  military,  religious,  and  kinship  orders  with  the  "lord," 
in  the  first  four,  and,  in  the  upper  ranks,  with  "the  occidental  lady" 
emerging  in  the  noble  household.  The  psychological  link  of  per- 
sonal loyalty  and  sworn  allegiance  between  lord  and  \assal  allows 
for  the  coherent  although  decentralized  domination  of  rather  large 
territories.  And  this  same  mechanism,  giving  rise  in  the  kinship 
order  to  the  knight  and  the  occidental  lady— the  wife  of  another 
knight,  to  whom  the  knight  must  prove  his  love  and  worth,  in 
vassal-like  manner.  In  the  religious  order,  the  Christian  knight's 
orientation  was  similar:  faith  and  vassalship  to  Christ,  the  Lord 
in  whose  name  he  crusaded  against  heathen  and  barbarian.  Thus, 
the  three  orders— politics,  kinship,  and  religion— correspond  in  the 
psychology  of  vassalship  under  the  code  of  loyalty,  love,  and 
honor.  ^° 

1"  Cf.  J.  Huizinga,  The  Waning  of  the  Middle  Ages  (London:  Arnold, 
1949);  H.  O.  Taylor,  The  Medieval  Mind  (London,  1938),  2  vols.;  and 
Eileen  Power,   Medieval  People   (Boston:    Honghton   Mifflin,    1924). 


35^  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

II.  Coincidence^.  We  are  not  aware  of  any  society  that  is  inte- 
grated solely  in  terms  of  coincidence:  different  structural  and 
psychological  tendencies  in  each  of  the  different  orders  bringing 
about  a  unified  end  product.  But  there  are  many  instances  at  hand 
of  the  partial  operation  of  coincidence  as  a  mode  of  integration, 
which  represents  the  unplanned,  unforeseen,  and  "fortuitous"  result 
of  institutional  dynamics.  Every  coincidence  is  of  course  causally 
determined,  but  insofar  as  causal  ascription  to  material  or  ideal 
interests  has  to  be  made,  such  interests  might  well  be  heteroge- 
neous, and,  being  anchored  in  different  orders,  perhaps  even  ulti- 
mately conflicting. 

The  breakdown  of  feudal  codes  of  privilege  and  the  develop- 
ment of  an  administrative  and  legal  framework  which  facilitated 
the  rise  of  capitalism  is  an  outstanding  example.  When  the  absolut- 
ist prince  breaks  the  power  of  feudal  status  groups  he  sets  up, 
or  at  least  calls  into  being,  modern  bureaucracy.  The  prince  is 
interested  in  using  his  officials  in  any  part  of  his  territory  in  order 
to  cheapen  the  costs  of  his  administration,  and  to  rotate  officials 
so  as  to  promote  uniform  administration  and  to  secure  his  central 
control.  This  interest  of  the  prince,  however,  is  blocked  by  the 
legal  peculiarities  of  different  regions,  cities,  and  provinces  which 
for  the  oflBcial  mean  an  unlearning  of  local  statute  and  a  new  learn- 
ing. 

The  bureaucrat,  on  the  other  hand,  finding  extended  career  op- 
portunities in  the  increase  of  his  usefulness  because  of  his  universal 
transferability,  has  a  material  interest,  which  fuses  with  his  purely 
intellectual  interest  in  a  rationally  consistent  set  of  guiding  prin- 
ciples. The  oflBcial's  interest  is  in  legal  norms  that  are  consistently 
applicable  as  reinforced  by  the  university  teacher's  interest  in 
systematic  organization  of  his  teaching  routine,  course  repetition, 
and  textbook  presentation.  Hence,  for  quite  different  reasons,  the 
interests  of  the  prince,  the  bureaucrat,  and  the  academician  coin- 
cide in  the  direction  of  a  rational  systematization  and  codification 
of  legal  rules. 

In  the  meantime,  there  is  another  causal  series  which  coincides 
with  these  to  support  this  process:  in  the  economic  order,  the  rising 
entrepreneurial  middle  class  promotes  a  rational  legal  order.  Due 
to  the  expansion  of  their  market  operations  the  entrepreneurs  are 
interested  in  a  homogeneous  law,  for  this  would  allow  them  to 
calculate  the  legal  consequences  of  their  economic  actions   and 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  3,59 

the  chances  of  contracts  being  enforced  by  court  action.  This  inter- 
est of  the  economic  agent  in  the  calculabiHty  of  law  ob\iously 
coincides  with  the  interests  of  the  bureaucrat  in  the  rationaHty  and 
standardization  of  legal  rules,  and  the  interest  of  the  prince  in  the 
cheapness  of  administration  and  his  control  over  it.  A  second 
and  allied  motive  of  the  enterpriser  is  an  interest  in  legal  security. 
The  arbitrariness  of  the  enlightened  despot's  "cabinet  justice"  was, 
in  the  eyes  of  the  enterpriser,  an  irrational,  incalculable  risk.  His 
interest  in  security  of  contract  coincided  here  with  the  bureaucrat's 
interest  in  security  of  tenure.  Hence  both  the  bureaucratic  per- 
sonnel and  the  middle  classes  were  interested  in  reducing  the  ele- 
ment of  despotic  arbitrariness  in  favor  of  fixing  and  systematizing 
a  set  of  unambiguous  legal  norms.  This  phase  of  legal  history  and 
the  coincidence  of  different  orders  is  the  unforeseen,  unplarmed, 
and  "blind"  result  of  heterogeneous  interests;  at  a  later  juncture 
of  the  historical  process,  the  constellation  of  these  interests  naturally 
breaks  up. 

A  comparable  point  of  coincidence  between  eighteenth-century 
despotism  and  entrepreneurial  capitalism  in  the  making  may  be 
adduced.  Princely  absolutism  for  politico-military  reasons  sought 
to  increase  the  tax  yield  of  its  subjects  by  all  sorts  of  mercantilist 
policy  schemes,  including  subsidized  enterprises  of  privileged  per- 
sons, technological  and  industrial  training  institutes,  travels  of 
officials  for  espying  teclmical  advances  in  Great  Britain,  in  Berlin 
the  hiring  out  of  soldiers  to  textile  manufacturers,  in  France  under 
Colbert  the  digging  of  canals  by  the  army.  The  subsidized  enter- 
prises mostly  fell  by  the  wayside  (only  fiscal  porcelain  manufactur- 
ing establishments  such  as  Sevres,  Dresden,  Meissen,  and  Berlin 
have  remained).  And  taxes  and  their  princely  investment  de- 
flected otherwise  available  private  capital  into  unprofitable,  hence 
uneconomic,  channels;  these  aspects  of  mercantilism  hence  con- 
flicted with  the  entrepreneurial  interest.  The  promotion  of  tech- 
nological innovation,  however,  i.e.,  the  French  canals,  or  later  the 
improvement  of  the  Rhine  River  and  the  construction  of  militarx' 
roads,  under  Napoleon,  proved  invaluable  to  capitalism,  as  did 
the  general  bearing  down  of  princely  absolutism  on  traditionalist 
petty  routine. 

Within  a  latter-day  liberal  capitalist  society,  such  as  the  United 
States  during  World  War  H,  the  military  order  wants  recruits  in 


26o  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

order  to  build  an  army;  educational  institutions  want  students  in 
order  to  maintain  schools  as  going  concerns.  These  different  pur- 
poses coincide  in  army  and  navy  student  training  programs,  in 
which  the  armed  forces  gets  men  in  uniform  being  trained  for 
special  roles,  and  the  educational  plant  stays  open.  Like  other 
cases  of  coincidence,  the  various  groups  of  people  whose  institu- 
tions have  coincided  may  have  set  forth  legitimations  for  participa- 
tion in  the  same  conduct  pattern:  the  war  officers  believe  that  it 
is  part  of  military  preparation;  the  educators  feel  that,  however 
that  might  be,  it  is  also  good  for  nonmilitary,  general  educational 
ends.  And  again,  as  with  many  coincidences,  the  results  outrun  both 
formal  legitimations.  Such  a  program  may  be  seen  as  part  of  the 
breakdown  of  voluntary  liberal  education  on  higher  levels  and  the 
reaching  of  compulsory  practices  into  these  areas.  In  order  to  sur- 
vive as  going  concerns  the  higher-education  plants  become  in 
many  ways  ramifications  of  the  military  order.  Quite  a  few  phys- 
icists and  atomic  scientists  were  bewildered  after  the  war  when 
executive  departments  for  reasons  of  security  considered  the  pub- 
lication of  "secrets  of  nature"  as  dangerous  and  possibly  disloyal 
disclosures  of  "secrets  of  state." 

The  most  striking  and  detailed  case  of  a  coincidence  of  orders 
is  provided  by  Max  Weber's  work  on  Protestant  religion  and  capi- 
talist economics,  on  the  role  of  Puritanism  in  the  character  forma- 
tion of  the  economic  vanguard  of  modern  capitalism. ^^ 

The  theology  of  Calvinism  emphasizes  the  view  that  man  is  evil 
and  that  due  to  the  inscrutable  will  of  a  stern  and  hidden  God  only 
few  men  are  predestined  for  salvation.  This  interpretation  of  Chris- 
tianity at  once  reinforces  and  resolves  intense  anxieties  in  the  be- 
liever as  to  whether  he  is  or  is  not  among  the  elect.  Out  of  this 
situation  two  possibilities  derive:  fatalism  or  intense  activism. 
Puritanism  interprets  man's  Christian  conduct  in  everyday  life  as 
being  an  indicator  though  not  a  guarantee  of  his  salvation  chances, 
so  a  religious  significance  is  attributed  to  everyday  work.  Whereas 
formerly  only  certain  monastic  orders  had  used  work  as  a  means 
of  religious  asceticism,  now  every  believer  has  to  prove  his  religious 
worth  by  self-denying  work  in  this  world.  He  must  work  not  for 
profits,  not  out  of  enjoyment  of  his  work,  nor  yet  of  its  fruits.  His 

11  We  have  discussed  this  in  other  connections;  see  pp.  188  and  234-36. 


THE  UNITY  OF  SOCIAL  STRUCTURES    ^^1 

work  must  be  an  ascetic  exercise  pursued  methodically  for  the 
sake  of  the  kingdom  to  come.  His  work  becomes  his  "calling,"  and 
only  those  who  have  consistently  proved  themsehes  in  their  callings 
can  claim  to  be  "elected."  Those  who  successfully  claim  to  be 
among  the  elect  associate  themselves  in  sects,  and  admit  new  mem- 
bers, by  adult  baptism,  only  after  a  scrutiny  of  the  applicant's 
total  record  of  conduct.  The  earliest  sects  adopted  anabaptism, 
meaning  the  rebaptism  of  qualified  adults  and  their  reception  into 
an  exclusive,  voluntary  association. 

The  economic  consequence  of  such  motivation  is  the  emergence 
of  a  type  of  person  who,  in  the  economic  order,  will  not  readily 
consume  the  profits  he  makes— as  an  entrepreneur  or  middleman. 
Suspicious  of  ostentatious  wealth  and  luxury,  he  considers  his 
accumulation  of  wealth  as  Cliristian  stewardship.  He  has  only  one 
course  open:  reinvestment  in  his  business  for  extended  production. 
This  in  turn  gives  the  Puritan  enterpriser  the  opportunity  to  employ 
additional  men,  in  religious  terms  to  extend  opportunities  to  an- 
guished souls  who  in  an  age  of  enclosures  and  vagrancy,  crave  to 
prove  themselves  as  God-fearing  Christians.  Thus,  the  entrepreneur 
provides  institutional  opportimities  under  Puritan  control  to  unem- 
ployed and  dependent  groups.  From  his  perspective,  wages  increase 
the  workers'  opportunities  to  prove  themselves  as  frugal  and  sober 
and  hard  working.  High  wages  would  only  constitvite  temptations 
to  wander  from  the  ascetic  path.  The  worker,  in  turn,  knows  that 
what  counts  is  to  prove  himself  in  whatever  workaday  life  God 
has  placed  him. 

Admission  to  the  elect  and  recognition  by  sect  members  gi\'e 
each  member  a  claim  for  brotherly  help  from  economic  distress 
which  is  not  his  own  fault.  This  relevance  of  sect  membership 
for  credit,  based  upon  religiously  trained  character,  facilitates  eco- 
nomic ascent.  For  the  observance  of  new  ethical  standards  in  ex- 
change behavior,  of  honest  dealings,  of  charging  the  same  "fair 
price"  to  all  buyers,  of  avoiding  higgling  as  "idle  words,"  of  reliabil- 
ity in  the  fulfillment  of  contracts— all  this  lent  business  prestige  to 
the  sectarians.  This  prestige,  translated  into  good  credit  standing, 
in  turn,  added  to  the  Puritan  business,  and  at  a  later  time,  allowed 
Benjamin  Franklin  to  state  as  a  rule  of  experience:  "honesty  is  the 
best  policy." 

Thus:  The  psychology  of  the  religious  man  furnishes  motives 
for  his   economic  roles.   This   psychological  coincidence  may  be 


;^62  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

traced  in  the  kinship  order,  where  unpurposive  erotic  play  and 
enjoyment  is  suppressed  by  a  code  of  sobriety,  and  in  the  pohtical 
and  mihtary  orders,  where  the  spontaneous  release  of  agression 
is  inhibited.  The  disciplined  attack  of  Cromwell's  Ironsides  gave 
these  "men  of  conscience,"  who  "fought  for  what  they  knew  and 
knew  for  what  they  fought,"  the  superiority  of  machine  war  over 
the  personalist  combat  of  the  feudal  cavaliers.  Cromwell's  army  was 
held  together  after  victory,  and  pursued  the  routed  enemy  rather 
than  wasting  time  in  carousing  and  plundering. 

The  inner-worldly  asceticism  does  not  withdraw  from  this  world 
but  proves  itself  in  the  midst  of  worldly  affairs  and  temptations. 
It  is  based  upon  a  religiously  motivated  character  structure  inte- 
grating the  pious  man's  conduct  in  all  orders  of  life.  In  extreme 
cases,  it  may  lead  to  complete  withdrawal  from  political  and  mili- 
tary orders,  as  is  shown  by  Quakers,  Hutterites,  and  Mennonites 
who  refuse  to  hold  office,  will  not  take  oaths,  and  remain  "defense- 
less." 

The  importance  of  such  a  psychological  type  for  modern  capital- 
ism is  evidenced  by  the  fact  that  even  after  the  universal  process 
of  secularization  and  the  disappearance  of  the  specific  theological 
symbols— voluntary  associations  and  clubs,  fraternal  societies  and 
the  like— prestige  premiums  are  still  placed  upon  such  character 
traits,  which  they  justify  in  terms  of  convevitional  middle-class 
morality. 

The  ramifications  of  Puritanism,  and  hence  of  a  primarily  reli- 
gious phenomenon,  fed  into  the  great  economic  transition  from 
feudalism  to  modern  industrial  capitalism.  The  decline  of  the 
guild  system  and  of  its  restraints  on  competition,  the  technological 
and  organizational  advances  of  the  workshop,  were  reinforced 
by  the  migration  of  persecuted  Protestant  minorities  who  estab- 
lished themselves  outside  urban  jurisdictions.  The  parceling  up  of 
markets  by  politically  privileged  monopolies  was  successfully 
fought  by  Puritan  businessmen.  Thus  numerous  technological, 
monetary,  and  organizational  changes  in  the  age  of  discoveries, 
and  changes  in  trade  routes  from  the  Mediterranean  to  the  At- 
lantic, found  an  area  of  coinciding  changes  in  religion,  in  personal- 
ity formation,  and  in  new  religiously  motivated  ways  of  playing 
the  crucial  roles  instrumental  in  the  emergence  of  modern  indus- 
trial capitalism. 

But,  in  due  course,  the  Puritan  businessman  experienced  what 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  363 

all  monastic  orders,  in  their  contexts,  have  experienced  in  the  face 
of  the  riches  resulting  from  the  asceticism  of  hard  work  without 
consumption  of  its  fruits.  The  "inner- worldly  asceticism"  suc- 
cumbed to  the  temptations  of  this  world.  And  repeated  vogues 
of  religious  revivalism  have  not  changed  decisively  the  big  trend 
toward  a  phase  in  which  as  Weber  put  it,  "Once  in  the  saddle, 
capitalism  could  dispense  with  religion."  In  short,  it  could  rely 
on  pecuniary  incentives  for  work  and  openly  proclaim  "the  chase 
after  the  dollar,"  or  in  the  words  of  the  "bourgeois  king,"  Louis 
Philippe,  "enrichissez  vous!" 

III.  Co-ordination.  In  co-ordination  unity  is  achieved  by  the 
subordination  of  several  orders  to  the  regulation  or  direct  manage- 
ment of  other  orders.  This  in  twentieth-century  "totalitarian"  so- 
cieties unity  is  guaranteed  by  the  rule  of  the  one-party  state  over 
all  other  institutions  and  associations.  But  these  societies  also 
involve  correspondence  and  coincidence. 

The  general  schema— for  the  integration  of  Nazi  Germany,  for 
example  ^^— runs  like  this:  during  the  1920's  the  economic  and  po- 
litical orders  develop  quite  differently:  within  the  economic  order 
institutions  are  highly  centralized;  a  few  big  units  more  or  less 
control  the  operations  and  the  results  of  the  entire  order;  within 
the  political  order  tliere  is  fragmentation,  many  parties  competing 
to  influence  the  state  but  no  one  of  them  powerful  enough  to  con- 
trol the  results  of  economic  concentration.  So,  there  is  a  political 
movement  which  successfully  exploits  the  mass  despair  of  the  great 
depression  and  brings  the  political,  military,  and  economic  orders 
into  close  correspondence;  one  party  monopolizes  and  revamps 
the  political  order;  it  abolishes  or  amalgamates  all  other  parties 
that  would  compete  for  power.  To  do  this  requires  that  the  Nazi 
party  find  points  of  coincidence  and/or  correspondence  with  mo- 
nopolies in  the  economic  order  and  certain  high  agents  of  the 
military  order.  In  these  three  orders  there  is  a  corresponding  high 
concentration  of  power;  then  each  of  them  coincides  and  co-oper- 
ates in  the  taking  of  power.  The  army  under  President  Hindenburg 
is  not  interested  in  defending  the  Weimar  Republic  by  crushing 
the  marching  columns  of  a  popular  war  party.  Big  business  circles 
help  finance  the  Nazi  party,  which,  among  other  things,  promised 
to  smash  the  labor  movement.  And  the  tliree  types  of  chieftains. 

i-Cf.   Franz   Neumann,   Behemoth    (New   York:    Oxford,    1942). 


264  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

join  in  an  often  uneasy  coalition  to  maintain  power  in  their  respec- 
tive orders  and  to  co-ordinate  the  rest  of  society.  Rival  political 
parties  are  either  suppressed  and  outlawed,  or  they  disband  volun- 
tarily. Kinship  and  religious  institutions,  as  well  as  all  organizations 
within  and  between  all  orders,  are  "politicized,"  infiltrated,  and  co- 
ordinated, or  at  least  neutralized  and  subdued. 

The  immediate  organization  by  means  of  which  certain  high 
agents  in  each  of  the  three  dominant  orders  coincide,  and  by  which 
they  co-ordinate  their  own  and  other  orders  and  institutions,  is 
the  totalitarian  party-state.  It  becomes  the  over-all  frame  organiza- 
tion which  imposes  and  defines  substantive  policy  goals  for  all  in- 
stitutional orders  instead  of  merely  guaranteeing  government  by 
law.  The  totalitarian  party  extends  itself  by  prowling  everywhere 
in  "auxiliaries"  and  "affiliations"  to  other  orders.  It  either  breaks 
up  or  infiltrates,  and  so  controls,  every  organization,  even  down 
to  the  family. 

The  legal  order  is  reduced  to  an  adjunct  of  the  police  state,  with 
its  terrorist  organizations  of  elite  guards  and  police  forces.  The 
individual  has  no  "constitutional  rights"  which  courts  would  or 
could  enforce  against  arbitrary  acts  of  men  in  high  places.  The 
individual  does  not  count;  the  ruler  abolishes  "the  rule  of  law"  and 
proclaims  "the  rule  of  men."  In  the  military  order,  the  party  leader 
establishes  an  autonomous  bodyguard  subject  only  to  his  personal 
command,  and  the  army  is  duplicated  by  the  elite  guard  of  about 
half  a  million  men  who  are  sufficiently  segregated  in  composition 
and  command  as  to  be  a  party-controlled  army,  existing  alongside 
of  the  mass  army  of  the  nation.  The  kinship  order  and  educational 
institutions  are  controlled  through  a  compulsory  organization  of 
all  youth  in  a  "state  youth,"  which  in  turn  is  controlled  by  a  youth 
auxiliary  of  the  party.  A  voluntary  mass  organization  of  women 
controlled  through  a  party  auxiliary  guarantees  control  of  the 
management  of  the  household,  which  in  turn  steers  the  consump- 
tion of  rationed  ersatz.  The  state  party  acquires  economic  enter- 
prises through  expropriation  (of  Jews  and  politically  disloyal  own- 
ers ) .  Outstanding  examples  are  the  Goring  works,  the  Eher  publish- 
ing house,  the  numerous  party  papers  owned  by  the  party,  and 
numerous  municipal  enterprises  and  public  utilities  which  either 
are  directly  appropriated  by  the  party  or  are  under  the  manage- 
ment of  party  members. 

A  system  of  state  and  hence  party  controlled  "chambers"  is  or- 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  365 

ganized,  membership  in  which  is  compulsory  for  all  entrepreneurs 
and  corporations.  Farming  is  organized  into  a  compulsory  cartel, 
the  Reich's  Food  Estate.  The  labor  market  is  controlled  through 
the  compulsory  organization  of  all  gainfully  employed  persons  in 
the  Labor  Front.  The  free  professions  in  addition  to  their  traditional 
state  control  are  organized  in  party  controlled  chambers  of  culture, 
seven  of  them,  under  the  direction  of  a  propaganda  ministry.  Thus, 
with  the  partial  exception  of  the  churches,  the  symbolic  sphere  of 
all  orders  is  centrally  managed. 

There  is  more  than  one  official  hierarchy,  and  this  fact,  through 
the  resultant  competition  and  overlapping  of  ill-defined  authority, 
allows  for  periodic  purges,  as  well  as  quick  changes  of  the  oflRcial 
line.  This  fact  also  means  that  the  Fiihrer,  and  his  inner  circle, 
are  relatively  independent  of  the  pressure  of  his  own  staffs.  His 
personal  decisions  are  ultimate  and  are  enforceable  by  the  effective 
use  of  his  bodyguard,  which  reaches  into  the  army  and  into  the 
police.  When  most  of  the  institutions  in  an  order  cannot  be  super- 
seded by  an  organizational  monopoly,  the  state  party  tries  to  oc- 
cupy at  least  the  strategic  institutions  or  to  co-ordinate  the  insti- 
tutions under  a  superimposed  party  auxiliary. 

The  symbolic  sphere  of  all  orders,  as  we  have  said,  is  controlled 
by  the  party.  With  the  partial  exception  of  the  religious  order,  no 
rival  claims  to  autonomous  legitimacy  are  permitted.  There  is  of 
course  a  party  monopoly  of  all  formal  communications,  including 
the  educational  sphere;  and  all  symbols  are  recast  to  form  the  basic 
legitimation  of  the  co-ordinated  society:  the  principle  of  absolute 
and  magical  leadership  in  a  strict  and  unilateral  hierarchy  is  widely 
and  increasingly  promulgated. 

IV.  Convergence.  Two  different  orders  may  coincide,  often  in 
completely  unplanned  ways,  to  the  point  of  fusion  or  convergence. 
In  a  rapidly  expanding  society,  for  example,  the  frontier  zones  of 
the  nineteenth-century  United  States,  the  institutional  articulation 
of  different  orders  in  the  East  may  peter  out  on  the  vanguard 
edges.  So,  for  lack  of  functional  specification,  certain  Eastern  insti- 
tutional orders  converge  in  the  West.  The  frontier  farmer  is  thus 
a  military  agent  as  well  as  an  economic  man,  and  the  household 
becomes  a  small  military  outpost  as  well  as  a  familj-  abode.  "Neigh- 
borliness"— or  the  relations  between  contiguous  kinship  units— fills 
in  the  gaps  of  institutions  not  yet  organized.  There  is  no  church. 


S66  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

there  are  no  police,  there  are  no  schools— so,  in  this  kinship-cen- 
tered society,  these  functions  converge  in  and  are  carried  by  the 
family.  The  roles  of  women  as  wife  and  mother  come  also  to  in- 
clude the  nurse,  the  midwife,  and  the  teacher;  the  roles  of  men  as 
husband  and  father,  to  include  the  lay  religious  leader  and,  if 
needed,  of  the  vigilante  and  militiaman. 

It  should,  of  course,  be  understood  that  in  any  concrete  social 
structure,  we  may  well  find  mixtures  of  these  four  types  of  struc- 
tural integration  or  structiiral  change.  The  task  is  to  search  within 
and  between  institutional  orders  for  points  of  correspondence  and 
coincidence,  for  points  of  convergence  and  co-ordination,  and  to 
examine  them  in  detail.  The  presence  of  one  type  does  not  exclude 
the  possibility  of  others.  We  do  not  believe  that  there  is  any  single 
or  general  rule  governing  the  composition  and  unity  of  orders  and 
spheres  which  holds  for  all  societies.  Reality  is  not  often  neat  and 
orderly;  it  is  the  task  of  analysis  to  single  out  what  is  relevant  to 
neat  and  orderly  understanding. 

4.  Whij  Rome  Fell 

Those  historians  who  emphasize  the  military  order  as  decisi\'e 
for  the  fall  of  Rome  have  made  much  of  the  "invasion  of  the  bar- 
barians" and  the  allegedly  declining  military  virtues  of  a  Roman 
mercenary  army.  Others,  especially  schoolteachers  of  the  nine- 
teenth century,  have  found  fault  with  the  morality  of  the  ruling 
stratum  before  the  advent  of  Christendom;  they  have  made  the  most 
of  luxuries,  debauchery,  lack  of  hard  work,  and  so  forth.  Anti- 
Christians,  such  as  Nietzsche,  have  emphasized  the  asceticist  ideal 
of  the  Christians  as  corrosive  of  the  lordly  virtues,  and  even  Gibbon 
attributed  much  of  the  population  decline  to  the  spread  of  mo- 
nastic celibacy  and  hermitage  life.  A  Communist  historian  makes 
the  most  of  the  uprising  of  slaves  in  Sicily  and  Africa,  but  Nietzsche 
has  made  the  most  of  the  uprising  of  the  slave  in  morality.  Whereas 
Toynbee  and  Rostovtsev  make  much  of  the  Roman  proletariat, 
external  or  internal,  Friedrich  Engels  makes  much  of  the  alleged 
inability  of  freemen  to  work  because  of  their  leisure-class  attitude 
and  self-respect  in  the  face  of  degrading  slave  labor.  Obviously, 
as  one  observes  the  total  decline  of  a  civilization  as  complex  as 
Rome,  many  causes  and  aspects  can  be  highlighted.  However,  it  is 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  ^^J 

possible  to  locate  a  number  of  contradictions  which  cut  more  and 
more  widely  through  the  Roman  social  structure  and  which  pro\ed 
insoluble  to  the  Caesars." 

I.  The  plantation  economy  of  Roman  agriculture  was  based  upon 
slave  labor,  which  did  not  reproduce  itself,  as  the  masters  garri- 
soned the  field  slaves  by  sex,  interdicting  reproduction  as  an  un- 
welcome risk  to  their  investment.  As  in  the  American  old  South, 
the  plantation  economy  resulted  in  deforestation  and  soil  erosion, 
in  extensive  cultivation,  and  in  increasingly  barren  land  in  Italy 
and  Sicily.  The  prime  objectixes  of  chronic  Roman  warfare,  in 
fact,  were  the  conquest  of  rent-yielding  land  and  of  slave  labor. 
As  prisoners  of  war  became  slaves,  the  military  campaigns  were 
in  the  nature  of  slave  raids.  Roman  imperialism  was  economically 
necessary;  the  military  and  the  economic  orders  were  functionally 
linked.  As  the  economy  shrank  in  productivity  and  production,  tax 
yields  to  support  the  military  and  political  excursions  also  shrank, 
which  in  turn,  failed  to  provide  new  labor  forces  of  slaves. 

II.  The  displacement  of  the  free  peasantry  by  slaves  on  planta- 
tions (the  htifunda)  brought  with  it  a  decline  of  population,  and 
since  the  defeat  of  the  Gracchi  (who  for  military  reasons  fought 
against  the  extension  of  the  latifunda  into  conquered  lands),  the 
army  had  increasingly  to  rely  upon  paid  soldiers  rather  than  upon 
drafted  freemen.  The  decline  of  agriculture,  however,  as  we  have 
just  seen,  caused  a  decline  in  tax  yields,  since  the  land  tax,  as  in 
all  agrarian  societies,  was  the  major  source  of  public  income.  A 
strain  was  thus  placed  upon  the  state,  due  to  the  increasing  mili- 
tary burdens  accompanying  the  great  expansion  and  pacification 
of  the  empire,  and  the  decline  of  money  taxes.  These  tendencies 
were  reinforced  by  the  technique  of  collecting  taxes  through  tax 
farmers,  who  squeezed  their  respective  provinces  for  private  profit 
with  a  short-run  view,  considering  that  "in  the  long  run  we  are  all 
dead."  These  private  speculative  gains,  even  though  partially  used 
to  defray  the  public  expenses  of  office-holding,  should  the  man 
of  wealth  later  take  office,  could  not  compensate  for  the  diminution 

1'^  Our  account  draws  upon  Weber's  essay  "The  Social  Causes  of  the  Decay 
of  Ancient  Ci\ ihzation,"  Journal  of  General  Education  (Vol.  V,  No.  i,  Oc- 
tober 1950,  Christian  Mackauer,  tr. ).  Cf.  M.  I.  Rostovtzeff,  The  Social  and 
Economic  Histonj  of  the  Hellenistic  World  (London:  Oxford,  1941),  2  \ols.; 
and  Arnold  Toynbee,  A  Study  of  History,  Vols.  5  and  6. 


^68  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

of  the  tax  yields  from  the  provinces.  In  addition,  more  and  more 
of  the  costs  of  a  competitive  poHtical  career  were  unproductive 
expenses  for  ostentatious  pomp  and  luxury,  circuses  and  sumptu- 
ous buildings. 

III.  In  due  course,  the  state  sought  a  solution  to  its  fiscal  prob- 
lems by  paying  officials  in  kind,  and  by  levying  forced  labor  upon 
the  productive  classes  of  artisans  and  middlemen.  Guild  associa- 
tions were  made  compulsory  and  hereditary  for  certain  trades- 
such  as  traders  shipping  grain  to  Rome— and  these  associations  were 
obliged  to  contribute  their  services,  as  a  joint  liability,  to  the  pub- 
lic weal. 

Veterans  who  had  served  with  the  colors  for  a  certain  number 
of  years  received  a  soldier  bonus  in  land  located  along  the  public 
water  mains,  military  highroads,  and— after  the  defeat  of  Varus's 
legions  and  the  stabilization  of  the  frontiers— along  the  line  of  forti- 
fications and  camps  running  along  the  Danube  and  the  right  side  of 
the  Rhine.  These  veterans  received  hereditary  and  non-negotiable 
land  allotments,  which  were  mortgaged  hereditarily  and  forever 
with  the  maintenance  services  or  even  with  obligatory  military  serv- 
ices in  case  of  need. 

All  of  this  bespeaks  of  a  decline  of  the  money  economy  and  of 
the  fiscal  system;  as  the  greater  cohesion  of  the  economic  order  is 
fragmented,  payments  in  kind  replace  soldiers'  wages  and  official 
salaries. 

IV.  The  big  consumer  cities,  especially  the  city  of  Rome  itself, 
also  represented  a  financial  burden  for  the  state.  The  bulk  of  the 
population,  the  so-called  "proletariat,"  i.e.,  "men  rich  in  children," 
went  idle.  They  were  free  Romans  having  the  right  to  vote,  who 
had  been  displaced  from  their  farms,  served  in  the  army,  and  sold 
their  votes  to  the  highest  political  bidder.  Much  of  the  payment 
was  in  bread  and  circuses,  and  Roman  circuses  were  anything  but 
cheap. 

V.  As  all  these  fiscal  strains  mounted,  speculative  middlemen 
and  capitalists  in  the  grain  trade  were  displaced,  the  provision  of 
grain  was  made  a  public  business,  the  imperial  bureaucracy  took 
in  hand  the  overseas  grain  shipments  and  their  allocations  to  cities 
—in  order  to  control  the  price  of  grain  and  to  take  the  private  profit 
out  of  the  grain  trade.  This  was  the  greatest  blow  which  capitalist 
middlemen  received  in  Roman  antiquity,  for  the  rest  of  the  much 
vaunted  commerce  between  ancient  trade  emporiums  actually  con- 


THE     UNITY     OF     SOCIAL     STRUCTURES  369 

sisted  of  luxury  trade  across  the  Mediterranean,  linked  to  the  cara- 
van trade  across  the  Middle  East  which  brought  Chinese  silk  and 
tea,  spices  and  other  specialties  to  the  West,  and  whatever  gold 
the  West  had  to  the  East,  to  India,  where  it  was  wrought  into 
temple  and  princely  treasures.  "International  trade,"  in  short,  repre- 
sented a  thin  and  widely  spun  network  of  consumers'  goods  and  not 
bulky  raw  materials  or  production  resources.  Given  the  small  size 
of  the  ships,  which  were  unable  to  sail  against  the  wind  and  which 
were  mainly  propelled  by  expensive  slave-power,  only  high-priced 
luxury  goods  could  be  profitably  transshipped. 

VI.  In  the  economic  order,  in  summary  then,  we  find  an  in- 
creasing contradiction:  land  rents  diminish  with  the  decreasing 
productivity  of  the  land,  and  the  increasing  price  of  slaves  as  the 
frontiers  are  stabilized  and  no  new  slaves  brought  in.  So  the  costs 
of  production  generally  rise,  the  accumulation  of  great  private 
fortunes  slows  down,  and  tax  burdens  become  onerous.  Given  the 
liturgical  obligations  of  office-holding,  to  be  voted  into  office  is 
like  being  popularly  expropriated,  for  the  elected  office  holder 
had  to  defray  the  costs  of  his  office  out  of  his  private  means. 

A  "flight  from  the  city"  got  underway.  Those  who  had  landed 
wealth  and  could  afford  to  do  so,  retreated  to  their  landed  estates, 
taking  their  treasures  along  and  establishing  themselves  in  the 
countryside  and  thus  escaping  the  coercive  environment  of  prole- 
tarian consumers'  cities.  The  center  of  gravity  of  the  Mediter- 
ranean coastal  civilization  gradually  shifted  to  the  hinterlands; 
upper-class  families  became  rusticated  and  sought  to  live  self- 
sufficiently  by  organizing  all  essential  services  in  their  rural  house- 
hold economy.  The  thin  network  of  tiade  broke  up;  both  pri\ate 
and  public  economy  reverted  increasingly  to  subsistence  economy. 
Slaves,  who  could  always  revolt,  required  costly  supervision  and 
management,  and  were  accordingly  set  up  as  self-moti\'ated  workers 
who  could  work  their  way  to  freedom  by  paying  off  stipulated 
annuities,  i.e.,  the  slaves  were  treated  as  a  source  of  rent  rather 
than  as  implements  of  larger  economic  institutions.  Thus  socially 
low  freemen  and  socially  ascending  slaves  merged  into  a  homo- 
geneous plebeian  stratum— to  which  Christianity  made  its  greatest 
appeal.  The  larger  the  city  and  the  poorer  the  people,  the  greater 
the  number  of  Christian  converts.  Paul  is  credited  with  ha\'ing 
established  the  first  Christian  cells  in  the  provincial  capitals 
of  the   Roman   orbit.   This   new  set  of   values,   coming   from   the 


^yO  SOCIAL     STRUCTURE 

Middle  East,  thus  met  the  great  needs  of  a  society  that  was  drifting 
without  hope  to  its  ending. 

In  brief  summary,  then,  Rome  in  the  course  of  three  centuries 
(from  Augustus  to  Diocletian)  disintegrated  for  these  reasons: 

The  economic  order  was  technologically  static  because  of  the 
undue  investment  risks  entailed  by  a  harshly  controlled  slave  labor 
force.  Slaves  who  were  threshing  grain,  for  example,  were  forced 
to  wear  muzzles  in  order  to  restrain  their  unauthorized  eating. 
The  water  mill,  although  known,  was  never  installed.  Agricultural 
production  declined:  Jatifunda  were  allowed  to  run  down  as  their 
hired  managers  "worked  them  out"  for  short-run  returns. 

Thereafter  there  was  a  search  for  new  land  and  new  labor  power, 
which  was  realized  by  imperial  warfare  and  conquest.  This,  in 
time,  failed  to  meet  the  economic  demands  because,  as  the  con- 
quered territories  became  more  distant  from  Rome,  the  fiscal  bur- 
dens of  administration  and  defense  increased  to  the  point  where 
consolidation  of  the  existing  boundaries  replaced  attempts  at  new 
conquests.  But  such  consolidations,  given  point  i  above,  were  no 
solution,  and  attempts  to  shore  up  the  failing  system  all  proved 
abortive. 

In  Rome's  unity,  the  economic  and  the  military  were  func- 
tionally dependent;  in  Rome's  disunity,  their  developments  failed 
to  correspond.  And  so  in  the  dynamics  of  the  two  orders,  the  scissors 
opened,  until  the  pivot  of  the  two  blades  of  Rome  broke. 

The  institutions  composing  a  social  structure  may  be  unified 
by  correspondence  (the  several  institutional  orders  develop  in  ac- 
cordance with  a  common  principle),  by  coincidence  (various  insti- 
tutional developments  lead  to  the  similar  resultant  ends),  by 
co-ordination  (one  institutional  order  becomes  dominant  over  the 
others  and  manages  them),  and  by  convergence  (in  their  devel- 
X)pment,  one  or  more  institutional  orders  blend). 

In  describing  each  of  these  modes  of  integration  we  have  given 
brief  examples.  But  in  trying  to  make  clear  some  of  the  complex- 
ity and  variety  of  total  social  structures,  we  have  also  discussed 
some  of  the  sociologist's  methods  of  constructing  social  structures, 
and,  in  desperate  brevity,  we  have  attempted  to  illustrate  these 
procedures  by  describing  the  structural  unity  of  ancient  Sparta 
and— the  classic  case  of  disunity— Imperial  Rome. 


THE  UNITY  OF  SOCIAL  STRUCTURES    ^Jl 

Neither  Sparta  nor  Rome  endured.  Regardless  of  how  unified  a 
social  structure  may  seem,  its  unity  is  part  of  history,  and  history 
is  change.  Our  examination  of  the  integrations  and  disintegrations 
of  Sparta  and  Rome  thus  point— like  all  social  psychological  topics 
—to  the  problem  of  socio-historical  change. 


P  A  H  T     F  O  i;  It 


DYNAMICS 


CHAPTER 

X  I  1  1 

Social-historical  Change 


FROM  folklore  as  well  as  philosophic  reflection  and  esthetic 
experience  we  inherit  a  rich  legacy  of  often  paradoxical  axioms 
about  change.  From  an  old  Roman  adage  we  learn  that  "Times 
change  and  we  change  with  them,"  but  from  an  old  French  say- 
ing, that  "The  more  it  changes,  the  more  it  remains  the  same." 
In  our  music  the  mathematically  measurable  "beat,"  the  metrical 
articulation  of  time,  is  distinguished  from  "rhythm,"  the  pulsation 
of  a  melodic  flow  of  energy,  which  has  more  to  do  with  our  heart- 
beat and  the  right-left  swing  of  the  human  gait  than  with  the 
mechanical  exactitude  of  the  metronomic  tick-tock. 

There  is  in  the  Western  mind  the  idea  of  "Chronos"— the  mathe- 
matically divisible  extension  of  time  as  a  pure  quantitative  series 
of  equal  measures;  and  there  is  "Kairos"— the  time  for  fateful  deci- 
sions, the  climactic  moments  which  alternate  with  stretches  of  time 
during  which  nothing  seems  to  happen.  In  the  history  of  social 
thought  we  find  that  thinkers  have  often  been  preoccupied  with 
what  seems  to  them  the  incomparably  unique  moment  at  which 
man  faces  novel  decisions.  These  scholars  have  been  concerned 
with  those  situations  in  which  man  finds  himself  at  vmknown  "forks 
in  the  road,"  where  no  signposts  map  out  future  means  and  ends. 

"History  teaches  that  history  teaches  nothing,"  wrote  Hegel,  the 
philosopher  of  the  Napoleonic  age,  who  believed  that  it  was  im- 
possible to  stand  in  the  present  and  yet  penetrate  the  future.  For 
man's  past,  by  definition,  is  dead;  it  has  fallen  behind  in  the 
inexorable  march  of  the  world  spirit.^  Other  no  less  powerful  minds 
—Nietzsche  and  Freud— have  sought  to  master  the  shock  of  the  new 
by  denying  that  there  is  really  anything  new  under  the  sun.  Ac- 

1  G.  W.  F.  Hegel,  The  Philosophy  of  History  (rew  ed.;  New  York:  Wiley, 
1944)- 


;^y6  DYNAMICS 

cording  to  them,  what  matters  for  man  and  his  Hfe  has  already 
happened  in  the  archaic  and  closed  past  which  still  impregnates 
the  present.  What  lies  ahead  is  always  the  return  of  the  same. 

For  Freud,  the  primeval  crime  is  the  son's  killing  the  primordial 
father  of  the  primitive  horde  in  order  to  possess  the  mother.  This 
crime  is  transmitted  through  time  and  repeatedly  asserts  itself  in 
the  changing  costume  of  surface  appearances.  It  is  the  core  of  man's 
constant  nature.  Lamarckian  assumptions  concerning  the  heredi- 
tary transmission  of  once-acquired  psychic  traits  support  this  no- 
tion of  constant  elements  to  which  change  is  analytically  reduced. 
The  history  of  the  Judeo-Christian  religion,  for  example,  is  to 
Freud  a  text  revealing  the  repeated  drama  of  parricide  and  original 
guilt.  This  fact  is  revealed  in  the  Freudian  process  of  reducing 
changing  behavior  to  constant  instinct,  changing  symbolic  elabo- 
rations to  the  constant  pressure  of  the  guilt  complex. 

Man's  history  is  thus  stripped  by  the  psychoanalyst  of  presumed 
surfaces  and  turned  into  immutable  nature.  For,  as  with  Aristotle, 
change  is  spurious,  and  only  the  constant  is  genuine.  So  the  bur- 
den of  the  past  holds  sway  over  the  future.  As  man's  biography, 
when  correctly  understood,  represents  the  recapitulation  of  the 
initial  childhood  constellation,  so  the  historic  drama  of  mankind 
is  but  the  unfolding  and  reassertion  of  the  initial  archaic  crime 
and  of  its  burden. 

One  wonders  why  parricide  rather  than,  let  us  say,  fratricide 
should  thus  be  posited  as  the  primordial  theme  by  Freud;  why  the 
story  of  Oedipus  Rex  rather  than  that  of  Cain  and  Abel  should 
be  seized  upon  as  the  mythological  axis  of  human  nature.  The 
latter  might  be  as  serviceable  for  a  Hobbesian  construction  of 
basic  human  nature  as  the  former.  At  any  rate,  anthropologists, 
especially  Malinowski,  have  shown  the  limited  bearing  of  Freud's 
discernment  of  the  Oedipus  complex  on  non-Western  societies, 
kinship  structures,  and  personality  formations. 

Nietzsche's  idea  of  the  Will  to  Power,  and  its  basic  implementa- 
tion by  the  psychic  resentment  of  the  socially  weak  against  the 
high  and  mighty,  is  out  of  place  when  we  deal  with  Buddhism, 
and  holds  true  only  partially  for  Jewish  and  Christian  traditions. 
Moreover,  it  requires  an  unwarranted  reduction  of  all  love  to  the 
quest  for  power,  of  all  giving  to  getting,  of  all  unselfishness  to 
selfishness. 

In  a  different  way,  the  construction  of  all  human  history  in  ac- 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  ^JJ 

cordance  with  Marx's  historical  materialism  is  apt  to  block  open- 
minded  inquiry,  for  it  reduces  selected  aspects  and  phases  of  social 
history  to  a  series  of  selected  illustrations  in  proof  of  the  alleged 
sovereignty  of  the  economic  order.  It  has  been  established,  for 
example,  that  the  military  needs  of  Christian  Europe  in  the  face 
of  the  Mohammedan  threat  from  across  the  Pyrenees  made  for 
feudal  landlordism  with  its  economically  expendable,  professional 
horsemen.  And  again,  it  requires  a  metaphysical  affirmation  of  the 
"economic  basis"  as  "the  real"  kernel  of  social  life  to  construct 
recent  economic  changes  of  competitive  war  economics  in  terms 
of  impulses  from  the  economy,  rather  than  from  military  "neces- 
sities" and  their  technological  requirements.  At  the  same  time,  it  is 
of  course  obvious  that  economic  and  technological  conditions  limit 
and  facilitate  what  man  can  do  in  the  roles  and  contexts  of  non- 
economic  institutions. 

Such  great  intellectual  constructions  are  fascinating;  the  inter- 
pretative work  of  the  system  builders  who  would  answer  the  ques- 
tion of  "Whither  Mankind?"  in  terms  of  the  hidden  labor  of  "the 
world  spirit,"  man's  "will  to  power,"  the  "instincts  of  life  and 
death,"  or  the  "productive  forces  and  relations"  are  intriguing. 
But  the  complexity  of  themes  now  available  in  human  knowledge 
has  repeatedly  proved  that  all  such  over-all  constructions  in  their 
bold  emphasis  are  apt  to  close  rather  than  to  open  further  inquiry 
into  the  rich  variety  of  human  thought  and  experience. 

i.  Six  Questions 

Every  model  of  social  structure  implies  a  model  of  social-his- 
torical change;  history  consists  of  the  changes  which  social  struc- 
tures undergo.  When  we  discussed  various  institutional  orders,  and 
especially  their  types  of  integration  in  Part  Three,  we  had  also  to 
analyze  social  changes.  In  the  present  chapter,  we  will  systematize 
and  elaborate  the  implications  of  our  model  of  social  structiuc  for 
the  analysis  and  understanding  of  social-historical  change. 

I.  Our  first  question  is  the  same  as  the  question  posed  by  prob- 
lems of  integration:  What  is  it  that  changes?  What  unit  is  to  be 
observed  in  change?  A  conception  of  social  structure  as  an  articu- 
lation of  institutional  orders  provides,  as  we  shall  see,  a  set  of 
answers  to  this  question. 


3/5  DYNAMICS 

II.  The  second  question  is  how  this  unit  changes,  which  points 
to  psychology  as  well  as  to  the  social  sciences  in  general.  It  points 
to  psychology  for  it  leads  us  to  seek  for  the  mechanisms  which 
allow  the  person  to  redefine  his  situation,  to  perceive  alternatives, 
to  choose  new  goals,  to  raise  new  demands,  to  communicate  new 
hopes  and  fears  in  the  face  of  challenging  tasks  and  obstacles;  in 
short,  to  learn  new  ways  of  doing  things. 

The  question  of  how  changes  occur  points  to  the  social  sciences 
in  general,  for  we  must  ask  for  the  mechanisms  which  allow 
newly  invented  roles  to  establish  themselves  in  institutional  orders 
alongside  previously  existing  roles  and  institutions,  displacing  some, 
forcing  others  to  adjust,  and  so  on.  Borrowing  and  diffusion,  in- 
vention and  imitation,  integration  and  disintegration,  expansion 
and  contraction,  acculturation  and  deculturation,  advance  and 
retrogression,  and  many  other  such  paired  terms  of  social  analysis, 
may  prove  useful  in  this  connection. 

III.  We  may  ask,  what  is  the  direction  of  change?  At  this  point, 
there  is  a  rich  vocabulary  of  value-laden  terms,  centered  around 
"progress"  and  "decadence,"  "integration"  and  "disintegration," 
"rise  and  fall."  What  from  one  perspective,  for  example,  appears 
to  be  the  "decline"  of  Rome,  from  another  point  of  view  appears 
to  be  the  "emergence"  of  feudalism.  From  the  perspective  of  feudal- 
ism, the  fact  that  the  Roman  colonus  is  tied  to  hereditary  land 
mortgaged  to  public  services  in  roadways,  water  mains,  or  military 
fortifications  seems  like  the  emergence  of  serfdom. 

IV.  What  is  the  tempo  of  change?  We  are  able  to  discern  two 
different  situations  in  sequence,  and  the  number  of  discernibly  dif- 
ferent situations  per  time-unit  may  naturally  vary.  In  some  parts  of 
some  societies,  changes  may  occur  in  slow-motion,  the  actors  them- 
selves not  even  being  aware  of  change,  which  overtakes  them  un- 
willing and  unaware.  In  other  parts  of  the  society  one  phase  may 
follow  another  at  baffling  speed.  It  may,  for  example,  be  difficult 
for  many  Europeans  to  revise  their  definitions  of  the  swift  redis- 
tributions of  world  power  after  World  War  II— until  it  is  brought 
suddenly  into  the  open  by  powerful  actions. 

Psychologically,  social  changes  may  thus  range  from  instances 
of   slow-motion   which   go   unnoticed   by  the   participants,   to   the 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  {^"/g 

opposite  extreme  of  historical  situations  in  which  the  participants 
take  universal  change  for  granted  and  are  surprised  at  the  affirma- 
tion of  anything  allegedly  constant  other  than  flux  itself.  The 
simple  alternative  of  static  v.  dynamic  accordingly  gives  way  to  a 
series  ranging  from  the  relatively  constant  (for  nothing  is  "abso- 
lutely" static)  through  gradualist  drift,  deliberately  piecemeal  and 
cumulative  reforms,  through  a  \ariety  of  breaks,  discontinuities, 
and  leaps,  to  total  crises  and  revolutions,  with  their  often  incon- 
gruous rise  and  fall  of  institutions  and  leaders,  symbols  and  prac- 
tices. 

V.  All  of  these  questions  about  social  change,  however,  even  if 
satisfactorily  answered,  would  not  satisfy  our  explanatory  interest. 
About  any  given  historical  epoch  we  do  wish  to  know  what  changes, 
how  it  changes,  in  what  direction,  and  at  what  tempo.  But  we  also 
wish  to  know  why  such  change  is  possible  and  why,  in  fact,  it 
occurred.  Accordingly,  we  must  ask  for  the  necessary  and  sufficient 
causes  of  historical  change. 

VI.  We  must  also  answer  certain  questions  which  have  to  do 
with  how  "objective"  and  "subjective"  factors  in  any  given  historical 
sequence  balance  each  other.  These  may  conveniently  be  broken 
into  two  questions:  (A)  What  is  the  causal  importance  of  the 
individual  in  history?  And  (B)  what  is  the  causal  role  of  ideas  in 
history?  Just  as  a  model  of  social  structure  is  needed  to  under- 
stand "objective  factors,"  so  is  a  model  of  character  structure  and 
its  linkages  to  social  structure  needed  to  understand  "subjective" 
factors. 

Under  European  despotism,  historiography  was  largely  coint 
and  dynastic  historiography;  the  great  decision-makers  appeared 
to  be  "absolutist"  princes  and  their  small  circle  of  generals,  cabinet 
officers  and  counselors,  possibly  mistresses  and  camarillas.  Ilero- 
ized  individuals  thus  appeared  to  observers  as  sovereign  decision- 
makers who  by  "divine  grace"  or  "right"  seemed  to  determine  the 
direction  and  tempo  of  history.  In  his  monumental  essay  on  "cul- 
ture history,"  Voltaire  proposed  to  pay  attention  to  broad  and 
deep  and  epochal  changes  of  societies  and  cultures,  and  with  each 
periodic  upswing  of  democratic  sentiment  for  the  last  two  centuries 
his  emphasis  has  been  reasserted.  It  is  no  accident,  incidentally. 


280  DYNAMICS 

that  whenever  great  crisis  situations  bring  doubt  about  "the  world 
we  live  in"  and  large  scale  and  protracted  warfare  among  large 
political  units  brings  statesmen  and  generals  into  the  center  of 
world-wide  attention,  the  "role  of  the  individual  in  history"  became 
a  topic  for  discussion.  Hegel  during  the  Napoleonic  age,  and 
Mommsen  under  Bismarck,  focused  on  Julius  Caesar  to  illustrate 
their  theories  of  genius.  Sidney  Hook  under  Franklin  D.  Roosevelt 
focused  upon  Lenin  and  Hitler  in  illustration  of  his  ideas  of  event- 
making  and  eventful  men.'- 

These  questions  and  points  of  emphasis  will  be  kept  in  mind  as 
we  briefly  lay  out  the  existing  range  of  theory,  develop  a  general 
explanatory  model  of  social-historical  change,  and  consider  the 
dynamics  arising  from  the  technological  sphere.^  Moreover,  we 
accept  the  requirement  that  a  model  of  social-historical  change 
must  enable  us  not  only  to  understand  the  units  and  mechanics  of 
historical  sequence,  but  to  locate  and  to  explain,  as  well  as  use, 
other  theories  of  social  change.  As  sociology  has  absorbed  much 
of  the  old  concerns  of  philosophy  of  history,  a  brief  reflection  on 
the  available  theories  is  appropriate.  We  can  emancipate  ourselves 
only  from  what  we  know  to  be  a  fetter. 

2.  The  Range  of  Theory 

From  a  somewhat  formal  standpoint,  theories  of  social-historical 
change  may  be  classified  into  two  major  types : 

I.  There  are  principled  7nonistic  theories,  in  which  all  institu- 
tional orders  are  reduced  to  one  institutional  order,  and  accord- 
ingly, a  metaphysical  accent  is  placed  upon  one  kind  of  human 
behavior  and  all  other  institutional  behavior  is  derivative.  Vulgar 
Marxism,  many  varieties  of  racial  and  geographical  theories,  and 
vulgar  Freudianism  illustrate  the  type.* 

-The  Hero  in  History   (New  York:    Day,   1943). 

^  We  shall  consider  the  role  of  "the  great  man"  in  history  and  the  character 
of  movements  and  revolutions  below,  Chapter  XIV:  The  Sociology  of  Leader- 
ship, and  Chapter  XV:   Collective  Beha\ior. 

^  It  is  usually  tlie  fate  of  outstanding  intellectual  work  to  be  banalized  in 
the  process  of  its  mass  diffusion.  Qualifications  are  dropped  in  favor  of  black 
or  white  assertions,  unsolved  intricacies  are  ignored,  open-ended  speculations 
are  closed  and  stereotypes,  uncertainties  become  orthodox  credos.  So,  instead 
of  thinking  as  did  Marx  or  Freud,  epigoni  are  busy  with  quotations  from 
their  works.  All  sucli  banalization,  we  refer  to  here  by  the  adjective  "vulgar." 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  ^^1 

Vulgar  Marxists  thus  reduce  all  phenomena  to  an  economic 
base;  economic  institutions  are  thought  to  be  the  reality  of  which 
everything  else  is  a  mere  expression.  Yet,  the  fact  that  religious 
institutions  in  Rome  draw  pilgrims  and  tourists  to  Italy  and  hence 
affect  the  Italian  currency  situation  does  not  make  the  N'atican  an 
economic  institution.  Noneconomic  institutions  are  thus  'Veduced" 
by  analysis  to  other  orders,  overlooked,  or  their  causal  influence 
understated.  In  all  such  monistic  theories  there  is  an  implied  image 
of  the  nature  of  human  nature;  in  vulgar  Marxism,  for  example, 
man  is  seen  merely  as  someone  who  follows  economic  interests. 

II.  There  is  also  principled  and  dogmatic  pltiralism,  which  is  the 
more  popular  theory  in  current  social  science.  It  aims  at  presumed 
a  priori  exhaustiveness,  and  thus  tries  to  explain  something  as  due 
to  all  possible  causes,  rather  than  by  a  statement  of  adequate 
cause. 

We  of  course  assume  that  social  structures  are  causally  bound. 
Events  and  transformations,  if  they  are  sufficiently  known,  can 
always  be  causally  explained.  The  historical  "accident"  is  not  un- 
caused, but  merely,  as  Sidney  Hook  once  put  it,  "not  deducible 
from  the  data  of  the  original  system.  For  example,  the  breakdown 
of  the  rice  economy  in  Japan  was  determined  by  the  preceding 
social  development;  the  visit  of  Commodore  Perry  by  certain  politi- 
cal considerations.  The  conjunction  of  both  was  relatively  acci- 
dental. One  event  could  not  have  been  deduced  from  the  other 
nor  both  from  a  third."  ^ 

Several  factors  and  mechanisms  of  social  change  may  of  course 
operate  at  the  same  time,  and  moreover,  in  various  directions.  But 
not  all  changes  are  "cumulative,"  in  fact,  some  are  quite  jerky  and 
discontinuous.  And  all  phenomena  do  not  result  from  a  great 
plurality  of  causes:  some  are  due  to  unilateral  jerks  and  jolts. 

Many  thought  models  of  historical  change  may  be  useful  for 
discerning  types  of  change  in  specific  historical  sequences.  Some 
institutional  orders,  and  no  doubt  whole  social  structures,  go 
through  what  may  seem  like  cycles;  other  sequences  seem  linear, 
while  still  others  seem  like  the  fluctuations  of  a  pendulum.  And 
of  course,  which  model  one  discerns  is  in  part  dependent  upon 
the  time-span  one  uses.  We  do  not  believe  that  any  unilateral  form 

5  "Determinism,"  Encyclopaedia  of  the  Social  Sciences,  Vol.  V,  p.  iii.  Cf. 
the  remarks  on  "coincidence,"  above.  Chapter  XII:  Tlie  Unit>-  of  Social 
Structures,   Section  3:    Modes  of  Integration. 


^82  DYNAMICS 

of  change  is  applicable  as  a  guide  to,  much  less  as  formal  ex- 
planation of  "history"— even  of  only  Western  history.  But  even 
though  such  formal  conceptions  do  not  possess  explanatory  value, 
it  is  good  to  know  as  many  of  them  as  possible.  For  the  plethora 
of  history  no  doubt  exhibits  at  some  time  and  in  some  society  all 
of  them. 

Any  one  of  the  institutional  orders  or  spheres,  which  we  have 
segregated  may  be  (and,  in  fact,  each  of  them  has  been)  taken  as 
the  dominant  order  from  which  change  springs. 

I.  There  are  technological  theories  of  history  in  which  machine 
industry,  scientific  enlightenment,  and  efficiency  values  are  the 
prime  movers— and  all  else  lags  behind  or  adjusts.  Naturally,  dur- 
ing the  rise  of  industry  in  the  nineteenth  century,  this  process  was 
a  major,  if  not  the  dominant,  experience  of  Western  societies,  and 
so  an  increasing  accentuation  was  placed  upon  the  technological 
sphere  of  the  economic  order  as  of  crucial  importance.  We  shall 
presently  consider  the  technological  sphere  in  detail." 

II.  To  construct  a  theory  of  history  on  the  basis  of  the  kinship 
order  is  to  make  the  growth  of  population  the  hub  of  historical 
dynamics.  Thus  Malthus  saw  a  difference  between  mankind,  which 
procreated  according  to  the  Biblical  principle  of  abundance  ("Be 
fruitful  and  multiply")  and  the  rest  of  nature,  which  followed  the 
principle  of  scarcity.  Man's  increase  is  geometric;  his  food  supply 
only  algebraic.  Accordingly,  the  need  for  food  lags  behind  the 
growth  of  population,  and  this  disproportion  leads  to  a  growing 
consciousness  of  scarcity  in  the  face  of  niggardly  nature.  Thus, 
according  to  Malthus,  if  man  does  not  act  "responsibly"  by  cur- 
tailing his  procreative  activity  and  turn  away  from  Biblical  fun- 
damentalism to  "adjust"  himself  to  natural  scarcity,  mass  pauper- 
ism, infant  mortality,  and  death  will  effect  the  appropriate  balance 
between  burgeoning  population  and  scanty  resources.^ 

When  population  pressure  is  posited  as  the  prime  historical 
mover,  economists  often  discern  industrial  dynamics  as  one  result. 
The  enormous  population  increase  in  China  since  the  eighteenth 
century,  under  static  technological  and  agricultural  conditions,  may 

8  See  below,   this  chapter,   Section  3:   Tlie  Teclinological  Sphere. 
^  T.  R.  Malthus,  An  Essay  on  the  Principle  of  Population  (6th  ed.,  2  vols.; 
London,   1826). 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  1^8^ 

be  referred  to  as  sufficient  to  disprove  the  universality  claimed  for 
such  "laws." 

III.  Closely  connected  with  technological  and  population  the- 
ories is  Marx's  view,  which  posits  class  antagonism  as  the  prime 
engine  of  historical  change.  Of  course,  Marx's  emphasis  had  its 
"precursors,"  and  since  Marx  a  broad  literature  of  historical  mate- 
rialist interpretations  of  various  periods  has  been  developed.  Thus 
Karl  Kautsky  has  interpreted  early  Christendom;  Eduard  Bern- 
stein, the  Cromwellian  Revolution;  and  George  Lukacs  has  de- 
voted  much   effort   to   analyzing   literature   in    materialist   terms. ** 

Today,  from  East  Germany  to  China,  school  children  learn  his- 
tory from  the  textbooks  of  Russian  authors.  One  of  these  books, 
which  we  have  had  an  opportunity  to  examine,  deals  with  ancient 
societies,  with  China,  Egypt,  the  Middle  East,  Greece,  and  Rome 
under  the  recurrent  heading  of  "slave  states."  Regardless  of  whether 
this  or  that  formulation  can  stand  up,  it  is  characteristic  of  the 
emphasis  that  the  religion  and  literature  of  ancient  China— Con- 
fucianism and  Taoism— receive  three  lines,  and  that  in  a  section  on 
ancient  Palestine  the  Bible  is  mentioned,  as  it  were,  in  passing— 
as  if  ancient  Jewry  would  merit  any  attention  at  all  without  it. 

In  such  a  vulgarized  perspective,  man's  relation  to  nature  is 
reduced  to  instrumental  and  efficiency  values,  social  relations  to 
those  of  master  and  slave;  and  the  legacies  of  ancient  civilizations 
in  art,  religion,  and  literature,  which  astound  sensitive  minds  and 
motivate  intellectual  reassessments  of  their  social-historical  set- 
tings, are  pushed  to  the  side  and  obscured.  The  humanist  horizon, 
which  during  the  last  150  years  the  moral  and  cultural  sciences 
have  extended  to  global  scope  and  prehistoric  depth,  is  reduced, 
and  the  thematic  range  adjusted  to  the  mentality  of  future  pro- 
duction managers.  Recent  history,  which  is  so  important  for  in- 
formed perspectives  on  the  future,  is  of  course  rewritten  with  an 
artistic  freedom  beyond  the  boldest  imagination  of  a  Seeley  or  a 
Treitschke.  Faust's  dictum  against  the  historians  still  holds  against 
such  historians  as  these:  "What  you  call  the  spirit  of  the  times  is 
in  the  last  analysis  your  own  spirit  in  which  the  past  is  mirrored." 

8  See  especially,  George  Lukacs,  Studies  in  European  Realism,  Edith  Bone, 
tr.  (London:  Hillway,  1950);  and  die  two  wonderful  volumes  by  Arnold 
Hauser,  The  Social  History  of  Art  (New  York:  Knopf,  1951  )>  which  pertain 
to  much  more  than  art. 


^84  DYNAMICS 

Max  Weber  has  correctly  pointed  out  that  in  applying  historical 
materialism  many  authors  fail  to  distinguish  between  what  is  eco- 
nomic, what  is  economically  determined,  and  what  is  merely 
economically  relevant.  Modern  social  science  as  a  whole  has  given 
increasing  attention  to  the  economic  determination  of  all  sorts  of 
noneconomic  institutions  and  activities.  Economic  institutions  are 
understood  to  facilitate  and/or  to  limit  religious  and  artistic,  mih- 
tary,  and  educational  activities. 

We  agree  with  Weber's  evaluation  of  Marx's  emphasis  upon  the 
economic  order  in  the  modern  capitalist  era:  ''  It  is  a  heuristic 
choice  which  holds  that  the  economic  order  is  the  most  convenient 
way  to  an  understanding  of  this  specific  social  structure.  So  much 
is  fruitful  in  the  Marxist  perspective  that,  although  it  has  not  been 
accepted,  much  of  it  has  gradually  become  taken  for  granted.^" 

In  Marx's  perspective,  the  economic  order  has  a  unique  methodo- 
logical position  among  the  institutions  in  capitalist  society.  For  it 
is  the  order  in  terms  of  which  the  stratification  of  the  whole  society 
is  instituted.  Accordingly  it  is  the  best  point  of  departure  for  any 
realistic  examination  of  instituted  stratifications.  We  also  accept 
the  principle  of  historical  specificity,  which  today  means  that  the 
problems  we  face  are  set  by  conflicting  elements  in  a  specifically 
capitalist  social  structure.  And  we  should  not  forget  that  Marxist 
( or  Marxist  influenced )  conceptions  of  social  change  have  fruitfully 
corrected  those  views  which  dramatize  political  decision-makers 
and  their  work  but  stop  short  of  asking  about  the  limiting  condi- 
tions of  their  power. 

IV.  E.  A.  Ross  once  remarked  that  the  theory  of  economic  de- 
terminism needs  to  be  rounded  out  by  a  theory  of  military  deter- 
minism. There  is  of  course  a  large  literature  on  militarism  which 

»  See  tlie  introduction  to  From  Max  Weber,  Essays  in  Sociology  by  H.  H. 
Gerth  and  C.  Wright  Mills   (New  York:   Oxford,   1946). 

1"  The  original  work  of  Marx  was  translated  for  U.S.  academic  publics,  for 
example,  by  Thorstcin  Veblen,  who  came  to  the  notion  of  "lag,  leak  and 
friction"  between,  specifically,  business  institutions  and  industrial  techniques 
and  institutions.  William  Ogburn  later  generalized  this  so  as  to  take  Veblen's 
leak  and  friction  out  of  it:  the  specificity  of  the  tension  between  business 
institutions  and  industrial  technology.  He  generalized  it  in  such  a  way  that 
he  leaves  unanswered  the  ciuestion  of  which  elements  lag  culturally,  and 
specifically  why  they  do.  See  W.  F.  Ogburn,  Social  Change  (New  York:  Vik- 
ing, 1922). 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  ^^j^ 

the  social  scientist  ignores  at  the  peril  of  missing  very  crucial  fac- 
tors in  contemporary  change.'^ 

Admiral  Mahan's  essay  on  seapower  opened  new  and  larger 
perspectives  on  the  great  conflict  between  Napoleon  and  Great 
Britain.  In  brief,  the  admiral  showed  that  the  relative  cheapness 
of  sea  transport,  as  compared  with  the  costliness  of  land  move- 
ments of  mass  armies,  the  cheapness  of  the  blockade  plus  the 
acquisition  of  overseas  possessions  by  Great  Britain  in  her  two 
decades  of  struggle  to  down  France,  in  the  end  proved  superior  to 
Napoleonic  landpower,  no  matter  how  brilliant  Napoleon's  gener- 
alship, no  matter  how  high  the  morale  of  revolutionary  armies  who 
fought  under  the  sun  in  Egypt,  in  the  mountains  of  Spain,  or  on 
the  snowy  plains  of  Russia.  In  the  contest  between  a  strategy  of 
annihilation  and  that  of  attrition,  seapower  employing  attrition 
proved  superior  to  land  power  and  annihilation.  Mahans  brilliant 
analyses  thus  brought  the  economic  factor  to  bear  on  the  contest 
between  sea  and  land  power. 

Since  then,  the  world  scene  has  changed,  but  the  general  prob- 
lem has  remained.  Industrialism  has  lent  greater  mobility  to  land 
armies.  In  the  railroad  age,  General  Grant  understood  the  condi- 
tion of  victory  as  he  fought  for  mastery  of  the  railroad  lines.  And 
at  about  the  same  time,  during  the  war  of  Prussia  and  Austria  for 
the  hegemony  of  central  Europe,  Grant's  counterpart  in  Europe, 
Hellmuth  von  Moltke,  replaced  old-fashioned  maps  with  railroad 
maps. 

Since  the  end  of  World  War  I,  a  still  closer  "integration"  be- 
tween industrial  technology  and  the  art  of  warfare  has  come  about. 
Mass  armies  are  motorized,  as  is  military  personnel,  in  the  air  and 
under  the  sea.  Trucks  and  submarines,  tanks  and  airplanes  have 
reopened  the  problems  of  the  Napoleonic  strategy  of  annihilation 
on  the  European  continent.  Yet  sea  power  and  the  blockade  weapon, 
along  with  superior  airpower  based  on  U.S.  industry,  have  proved 
on  a  now  global  scale  that  Mahan's  ideas  are  still  pertinent. 

Meanwhile,  all  single-track  theories  of  war  that  rely  on  "one 
weapon"  as  the  last  word— on  the  infantry  or  artiller\-  (Stalin), 
on  sea  power  (Mahan)  or  "air  power"  (Douhet,  Seversky).  on 
the  "superiority"  of  the  defense   (Liddell  Hart,  Maginot)   or  the 

11  See  Alfred  Vagts,  A  History  of  Militarism  (New  York:  Norton,  1937)  and 
Makers  of  Modern  Strategtj,  E.  M.  Earle  and  others,  eds.  (Princeton:  Princeton 
Univ.  Press,   1943)    and  tlie  references  contained  therein. 


^86  DYNAMICS 

offense  ("the  offensive  is  the  best  defense"),  on  the  wisdom  of 
trading  time  for  space  and  "winning  the  last  battle"— have  been 
proved  to  be  partial,  and  in  some  contexts  to  be  fallacious. 

The  theater  of  world  wars  is  now  the  world,  and  the  deployment 
of  means  and  stratagems  is  total.  Whatever  destructive  and  pro- 
ductive capacities  men  develop  they  seem  likely  to  use  in  war.  No 
fear  or  warning  has  ever  deterred  men  from  hoping  for  the  triumph 
of  their  side  by  use  of  "superior"  force.  Thus  during  the  Middle 
Ages  the  pope  of  Christendom  condemned  the  tactics  of  the  Eng- 
lish yeomen  who  with  crossbows  ambushed  unsuspecting  knights. 
During  World  War  I,  submarine  warfare  appeared  to  the  great 
naval  powers  as  a  criminal  breach  of  all  the  rules  of  international 
law  and  Christian  morality.  But  in  the  middle  of  the  twentieth 
century  the  dropping  of  atomic  bombs  has  caused  no  effective 
moral  upheaval,  and  since  the  distinction  between  combatants  and 
noncombatants  by  all  sorts  of  weapons  of  destruction  has  been 
eliminated,  we  may  safely  expect  that  men  will  use  all  weapons 
at  their  command  in  any  war  to  come. 

V.  There  are  thinkers  who  view  ideas  as  the  ultimate  core  of 
human  will  and  action  and  who,  accordingly,  assume  that  "ideas," 
"public  opinion,"  or  "propaganda"  are  the  prime  movers  in  his- 
tory. Arnold  Toynbee,  for  example,  in  his  monumental  study  of 
twenty-six  civilizations  reaches  the  conclusion  that  Western  civili- 
zation is  doomed  without  a  Christian  revival.  ^- 
,  During  the  eighteenth  century,  intellectuals  experienced  the 
formation  and  rise  of  a  new  mass  public  for  their  works,  which 
were  distributed  by  the  press,  the  novel,  and  pamphlet.  Their  ideas 
aroused  and  inspired  those  middle-class  movements  of  the  Western 
world  that  accompanied  the  industrial  revolution,  and  they  came 
to  feel  that  they  were  supported  by  an  increasingly  broad  and  self- 
conscious  public.  In  turn,  they  legitimated  the  "rights  of  man" 
in  the  name  of  "public  opinion,"  which  accordingly  became  the 
master  formula  for  a  complex  network  of  solidarizations  in  the 
reading  halls  and  coffee  houses,  the  salons  of  philosophers  and 
the  political  clubs  of  factions.  "Public  opinion"  became  a  master 
symbol  for  the  demands  of  the  middle  class,  and  the  intellectuals 

1^  See  A  Study  of  History   (London,   1951),  Vol.  VI,  p.  278. 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  ;^8y 

experienced  their  own  role  in  terms  of  the  historical  force  of  ideas. 
Although  he  broke  with  this  tradition  in  the  early  1840's,  Karl  Marx 
stated,  "Theory,  too,  becomes  a  material  force  as  soon  as  it  takes 
hold  of  the  masses."  ^^ 

Out  of  the  experience  of  modern  liberalism  there  arose  the  con- 
ception that  the  ideas  of  "exceptional  individuals"  are  essential 
in  historical  dynamics;  that  public  opinion  makes  history;  that  his- 
tory is  a  sequence  of  ideas.  The  classic  liberal  statement  of  such 
an  ideological  theory  of  history  or  of  progress  is  given  by  John 
Stuart  Mill,  who  in  this  respect  was  influenced  by  Comte: 

"Now  the  evidence  of  history  and  that  of  human  nature  com- 
bine, by  a  striking  instance  of  consilience,  to  show  that  there  really 
is  one  social  element  which  is  thus  predominant,  and  almost  para- 
mount, among  the  agents  of  the  social  progression.  This  is,  the 
state  of  the  speculative  faculties  of  mankind:  including  the  nature 
of  the  beliefs  which  by  any  means  they  have  arrived  at,  concerning 
themselves  and  the  world  by  which  they  are  surrounded. 

"It  would  be  a  great  error,  and  one  very  little  likely  to  be  com- 
mitted, to  assert  that  speculation,  intellectual  activity,  the  pursuit 
of  truth,  is  among  the  more  powerful  propensities  of  human  na- 
ture, or  holds  a  predominating  place  in  the  lives  of  any,  save  de- 
cidedly exceptional  individuals.  But  notwithstanding  the  relative 
weakness  of  this  principle  among  other  sociological  agents,  its 
influence  is  the  main  determining  cause  of  the  social  progress;  all 
the  other  dispositions  of  our  nature  which  contribute  to  that  prog- 
ress, being  dependent  on  it  for  the  means  of  accomplishing  their 
share  of  the  work  ...  in  order  that  mankind  should  conform  their 
actions  to  any  set  of  opinions,  these  opinions  must  exist,  must  be 
beheved  by  them.  And  thus,  the  state  of  the  speculati\e  faculties, 
the  character  of  the  propositions  assented  to  by  the  intellect, 
essentially  determines  the  moral  and  political  state  of  the  com- 
munity, as  we  have  already  seen  that  it  determines  the  physical. 

"These  conclusions,  deduced  from  the  laws  of  human  nature, 
are  in  entire  accordance  with  the  general  facts  of  history.  Every 
considerable  change  historically  known  to  us  in  the  condition  of 
any  portion  of  mankind,  when  not  brought  about  by  external  force, 

13  See  his  "Criticism  of  the  Hegelian  Philosophy  of  Right"  ( Selected  Essays 
by  Karl  Marx,  H.  T.  Stenning,  tr.  New  York:  International  PuliHsliers,  1926), 
p.  n. 


^88  DYNAMICS 

has  been  preceded  by  a  change,  or  proportional  extent,  in  the  state 
of  their  knowledge,  or  in  their  prevalent  beliefs."  " 

We  have  already  criticized  this  view  in  Chapter  X:  The  Symbol 
Sphere. 

S.  The  Technological  Sphere 

By  the  "technological  sphere"  we  refer  to  tools  and  machines 
as  well  as  to  the  ways  in  which  they  are  used.  In  this  sphere  we 
find  wheelbarrows  and  prayer  wheels,  flint  knives  and  rosaries, 
bulldozers,  carbide  tipped  lathe  chisels,  plywood,  and  atom  bombs. 
But  beyond  these  material  objects,  the  term  also  covers  the  im- 
plementation of  human  conduct  by  such  tools  and  machines,  which 
means  that  it  refers  to  the  various  skills  required  of  those  using 
such  artifacts. 

I.  Technology  and  Institutions.  Many  modern  theories  of  social 
change,  as  we  have  seen,  stress  technological  developments,  and 
many  statements  of  the  major  phases  of  history  are  constructed  as 
levels  of  technology.  Classifications  of  technology  may  be  put  in 
several  ways,  each  no  doubt  useful  for  some  purposes.  In  terms  of 
the  dominant  raw  materials  employed,  we  have  ages  of  stone, 
wood,  copper,  bronze,  iron,  steel.  In  terms  of  the  source  of  power 
that  is  used,  we  have  men  and  beasts,  coal  and  steam,  gasoline 
motors  and  electrical  power,  and  finally,  atomic  energy.  Each  of 
these,  alone  or  in  combinations,  is  a  useful  empirical  classification. 

For  our  purposes,  however,  we  find  a  third  way  of  classifying 
technologies  more  promising:  in  terms  of  the  institutional  con- 
text(s)  in  which  they  are  primarily  anchored  and  the  social  context 
in  which  the  use  and  management  of  a  societies'  technology  appear 
to  center.  All  institutional  orders  have  their  technologies,  the  reli- 
gious no  less  than  the  economic  order  or  the  symbol  sphere.  There 
are  techniques  for  playing  the  piano  just  as  there  are  techniques 
for  handling  a  die-casting  or  a  chalice.  The  ends  to  which  the 
techniques  serve  as  a  means  will  obviously  be  determined  by  the 
order  in  which  the  technique  is  instituted.  Accordingly,  the  devel- 
opment of  the  technical  sphere  in  any  order  is  steered  and  limited 
by  the  ends  of  that  order. 

I'A  System  of  Logic  (7th  cd.;  New  York:  Longmans,  1930),  Vol.  II, 
pp.  523-24- 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  3S9 

If  the  end  is  salvation  and  Buddhist  monks  bcHeve  that  mam 
prayers  serve  better  than  one  prayer,  then  the  technique  of  pray- 
ing may  proceed  by  the  construction  of  prayer  wheels.  Slips  car- 
rying a  short  prayer  are  fastened  to  the  spokes  of  the  wheel  and 
one  full  turn  of  each  prayer-carrying  spoke  is  counted  as  one 
prayer  in  behalf  of  the  salvation  seeker.  One  step  toward  greater 
efficiency  involves  the  addition  of  more  spokes  built  into  the  wheel, 
or  making  it  spin  faster,  and  finally  instead  of  man's  tired  hand, 
wind  and  waterpower  are  harnessed  to  the  prayer  wheel.  This  in- 
creased prayer  output  ramifies  into  a  sort  of  salvation  economy. 
Rivers  and  streams  are  valued  according  to  their  water  flow,  for 
swift  currents  make  for  more  prayers  in  one's  lifetime.  The  owners 
of  fortunately  placed  prayer  wheels  thus  have  an  abundance  of 
prayers  to  their  credit  and  may  come  to  feel  that  they  actually 
have  surplus  prayers,  that  is,  more  than  is  needed  for  their  saha- 
tion.  They  may  then  respond  to  their  less  fortimate  brothers  by 
transferring  surplus  prayers  to  their  credit. 

In  modem  society,  technological  spheres  range  from  simple 
gadgets  to  complex  machines.  Kinship  roles  are  modified  by  the 
level  and  type  of  household  technology  available,  especially  in 
cellar,  bathroom,  and  kitchen.  Military  roles  now  involve  quite 
elaborate  machines  and  techniques:  modern  war  technology  is  not 
imaginable  without  a  fusion  with  industrial  technology.  In  the 
religious  order,  there  are  above  all  great  cathedrals,  with  their 
pulpits  and  altars;  and  in  many  religious  units,  more  elaborate  and 
specialized  implements  of  worship.  In  the  pohtical  order,  in  addi- 
tion to  palaces  and  parliaments,  there  are  flags,  seals,  and  files, 
which  implement  roles  technically  and  symbolically. 

But  it  is  in  the  economic  order's  units  of  production  that  modern 
technology  is  centered  and  anchored.  Indeed,  so  much  is  this  the 
case,  that  most  theories  of  technology  as  the  prime  mover  and 
shaker  of  history  tend  to  shade,  often  imperceptibly,  into  an  eco- 
nomic determinism. 

Now,  however  accurate  the  quasi-identification  of  technology 
and  economy  may  be  for  modern  history,  we  run  the  risk  of  un- 
warranted historical  generalization  when  we  take  it  as  a  unixersal 
fact.  There  has  been  no  steady  onward  push  of  technology  in  the 
course  of  world  history.  It  is  well  known,  or  should  be,  that  be- 
tween the  third  millennium  b.c.  and  the  eleventh  century  a.d.,  no 
basic  technological  dexelopments  occurred  in   the  West.   In  fact. 


SQO  DYNAMICS 

only  the  earliest  river-valley  civilizations  of  neolithic  Egypt,  Su- 
meria,  China,  and  the  West's  modern  era  (especially  the  eleventh 
century  and  then  from  the  sixteenth  to  date)  have  witnessed  strik- 
ing technological  progression. 

In  our  formal  model  of  social-historical  change,  and  the  role  of 
technology  within  it,  we  must  remain  carefully  open-minded  and 
historically  specific.  The  technological  sphere  is  not  self-determin- 
ing; it  is  not  autonomous;  it  does  not  develop  "all  by  itself. "  On  the 
contrary,  to  be  part  of  history,  technology  must  be  instituted— it 
must  involve  men  in  skilled  roles— and  it  may  be  primarily  insti- 
tuted in  orders  other  than  the  economic.  Today  we  observe  in 
leading  industrial  societies  a  shift  in  the  center  of  technological 
initiative  and  guidance  from  the  economic  to  the  military.  In  con- 
trast to  the  nineteenth  century,  nowadays  military,  as  much  as 
economic,  orientations  and  goals  determine  how  technology  pro- 
gresses; which  features  of  the  culmination  of  invention  and  mate- 
rial uses  will  be  pushed  further,  and  which  held  back;  which  roles 
in  which  orders  will  be  implemented  by  technology  and  which 
will  not;  and  thus  what  social  effects  technology  has.  Thus  atomic 
power  is  being  developed  for  propelling  a  submarine,  not  an  ocean 
liner.  In  modern  war,  as  we  have  already  remarked,  all  orders 
and  spheres— including  the  technological— tend  to  become  ramifi- 
cations of  military  and  political  orders. 

Due  to  religious  constraints,  technological  implementation  of 
the  household— from  kitchen  utensils  to  drawing  room  comfort- 
is  not  found  among  the  Old  Order  Amish.  But  the  very  same 
religion,  in  its  inner-worldly  asceticism,  places  a  premium  on  active 
technological  ingenuity  and  inventiveness  in  the  sphere  of  produc- 
tion. Early  in  the  eighteenth  century  the  ancestors  of  the  Amish 
along  the  Rhine  invented  crop  rotation  and  the  winter  feeding  of 
livestock  (clover);  later,  as  the  Pennsylvania  Dutch,  they  aston- 
ished their  neighbors  by  putting  artificial  fertilizers  on  their  fields. 
Today  the  Amish  install  telephones  outside  their  homes  in  the 
yard  or  workshop  for  business  calls,  but  they  will  not  use  them 
for  social  calls;  they  install  electricity  in  their  carpenter  shops,  but 
they  will  not  wire  their  homes;  they  accept  the  internal  combustion 
motor  when  it  is  used  in  a  tractor,  but  not  in  a  private  car.  They 
accept  technology  only  in  production,  not  in  consumption. 

In  the  classical  Oriental  civilization,  priestly  and  quasi-religious 
bureaucracies  have  guided  technological  developments.  In  India 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  39 1 

and  in  Egypt  there  were  colossal  temples  and  pyramidal  tombs; 
and  in  China,  in  addition  to  the  Great  Wall,  there  were  the  Im- 
perial Canal  and  other  irrigation  projects,  instituted  and  governed 
politically,  upon  which  the  economy  depended. 

In  the  Mediterranean  epoch,  technological  advance  was  anchored 
in  and  restricted  to  the  military,  religious,  and  political  orders  and 
the  realm  of  consumption.  But  in  the  production  zones  of  the 
economy,  technological  advance  was  deterred.  Thus  in  ancient 
Rome;,  the  hand  and  stone  mill  was  never  displaced  by  the  water 
mill,  despite  the  fact  that  the  water  mill  had  been  described  by 
Strabo.  The  risks  of  slave  labor  on  the  plantations,  the  constant 
danger  of  rebellious  sabotage,  made  more  complicated  and  costly 
machinery  unprofitable.  The  Romans  never  learned  to  make  effec- 
tive use  of  more  than  two  draft  animals,  for  they  never  learned 
to  hitch  teams  head-to-tail;  hence  large  teams  could  not  be  used 
for  draft  work,  and  the  Quadruga  drawn  by  four  horses  hitched 
shoulder-to-shoulder  was  more  for  show  than  for  efficiency.  On  the 
other  hand,  descriptions  by  Caesar,  as  well  as  by  others,  reveal 
that  the  Roman  legions  were  capable  of  using  fairly  complicated 
siege  machinery  and  of  great  engineering  feats  in  military  highways 
and  bridges.  And  the  Romans  developed  an  extensi\'e  and  colossal 
technology  in  the  sphere  of  consumption:  aqueducts,  complicated 
circus  buildings,  and  hot  water  in  bathrooms. 

Whereas  in  the  case  of  the  Old  Order  Amish  technological  ad- 
vances for  four  centuries  remained  strictly  confined  to  production, 
in  ancient  Rome  technological  advances  were  confined  to  con- 
sumption and  warfare,  and  did  not  influence  the  technique  of  pro- 
duction. Therefore,  it  may  be  said  that  technological  spheres  do 
not  advance  simply  on  the  basis  of  available  knowledge  of  tech- 
nical possibilities,  but  that  institutions  must  raise  eftecti\e  demands 
for  the  incorporation  of  technical  implements. 

There  is  no  automatic  causal  relation  between  the  technological 
sphere  and  any  institutional  order,  and  there  is  no  automatic  har- 
mony among  the  technological  spheres  of  different  orders.  It  has 
been  repeatedly  observed  during  the  last  fifty  years  that  tech- 
nological advances  of  progressive  munitions  makers  ha\'e  been 
blocked  by  the  conservatism  of  military  personnel.  Alfred  Krupp's 
fight  against  the  Prussian  officer  corps  for  the  introduction  of  his 
superior  products  was  successful  only  after  a  German  ship  carrying 
the  older  guns  had  been  sunk  by  a  vessel  making  use  of  Krupp 


S92  DYNAMICS 

guns.  The  biographies  of  Count  von  ZeppeHn  or  Alfred  Nobel 
provide  similar  illustrations,  as  do  those  of  Samuel  Colt  and  Billy 
Mitchell  in  America.  Were  military  chieftains  as  conservative  as 
the  plantation  heads  of  old  Rome,  we  might  conceive  of  a  social 
structure  in  which  disproportionate  technical  advances  worked  in 
favor  of  the  economic,  and  to  the  disfavor  of  the  military.  But  mili- 
tary conservatism  is  not  the  whole  story.  We  meet  just  as  frequently 
with  military  demands  for  technological  advances.  The  develop- 
ment of  the  medieval  gun  foundry,  the  tank,  the  radio,  as  well  as 
the  subsidizing  of  modern  aeronautics  and  the  production  of  under- 
water vessels  and  atomic  energy  plants,  would  probably  have  been 
greatly  delayed  without  the  demands  of  war. 

II.  Skill  Levels  and  Role  Changes.  The  technological  sphere  of 
an  institutional  order  determines  the  levels  and  types  of  skill  re- 
quired for  the  enactment  of  its  various  roles.  As  technology  and 
technical  roles  change,  so  do  the  required  skills.  If  we  take  the 
role  as  our  unit  of  change,  and  focus  upon  its  skill  aspect,  we  are 
able  to  understand,  up  close  as  it  were,  the  social  implications  of 
technological  change. 

A.  Technology  may  force  the  formation  of  new  roles  as  well  as 
the  obsolescence  of  old  ones  within  an  institution;  it  may  also 
prompt  the  instituting  of  educational  spheres  for  training  the 
players  of  these  roles. 

B.  Technology  may  determine  the  adequate  criteria  to  be  used 
for  the  selection  of  persons  to  enact  the  roles  it  has  prompted  or 
reshaped. 

C.  Finally,  technology  may  split  one  role  into  two  or  more 
roles,  or  force  the  convergence  of  many  complex  roles  into  one 
simplified  role.\ These  positive  and  negative  effects  upon  required 
skills  and  upon  the  selection  and  formation  of  persons  to  exercise 
them  may,  of  course,  occur  in  given  institutional  contexts,  and 
accordingly  their  "timing"  will  vary. 

In  a  market  for  skilled  labor,  those  persons  who  are  playing 
skilled  roles  for  pay  and  who  cannot  effectively  claim  scarcity  value 
for  their  skill  may  gain  permanent  roles  only  after  they  have  suc- 
cessfully filled  provisional  ones.  On  the  other  hand,  those  who, 
on  the  basis  of  the  irreplaceability  of  their  skills,  monopolize  key 
positions  may  haggle  and  bargain  for  job  security  as  a  condition 
of  their  employment.  This  is  typically  true  of  eminent  scholars  or 


^  SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  393 

die-casters,  highly  paid  executives  or  professional  soldiers,  diplo- 
mats or  administrative  officials. 

Loss  of  skill  may  result  in  loss  of  the  role  requirinif  it;  such 
loss  of  adequate  skill  may  be  due  to  bodily  injury  or  aginti  or  to 
technological  innovation.  If  institutional  demand  for  certain  skills 
should  decline,  due  to  technological  or  economic  changes,  inten- 
sified competition  for  the  shrinking  opportunities  may  lead  to  loss 
of  skills  by  those  who  have  no  opportunity  to  practice  them.  This 
is  one  of  the  consecjuences  of  mass  unemployment  during  business 
depressions,  or  of  defeat  in  war,  with  the  discharge  of  military 
professionals.  After  some  time,  such  competitively  disadvantaged 
actors  may  lose  their  hopes  ^i  ever  marketing  their  skills  and  so 
of  returning  to  their  former  roles;  if  this  should  happen,  the  objec- 
tive relinquishment  of  the  role  is  subjectively  completed. 

Specialization  of  skills  is  involved  in  specialization  of  roles.  What 
was  formerly  done  by  one  man  may,  in  a  division  of  labor,  be 
divided,  and  two  men  perform  it.  A  new  skill  role  thus  de\elops. 
In  the  mass  production  of  music  for  motion  pictures,  the  role  of 
the  composer  is  split  into  those  who  think  up  tunes,  those  who 
arrange  accompanying  chords,  those  who  make  the  instrumental 
arrangements,  and  so  on.  Institutional  mechanics  may  also  take 
the  opposite  course,  by  setting  up  a  demand  that  one  man  com- 
bine two  skills  in  one  role.  One  man  now  does  what  was  formerly 
done  by  two.  Thus  a  household,  finding  itself  in  economic  difficul- 
ties, may  save  money  by  replacing  its  gardener  and  chauffeur  by 
one  person  who  takes  care  of  the  lawn  and  also  drives  the  car, 
or  the  roles  of  maid  and  cook  may  be  merged. 

Technological  changes  thus  eliminate  and  create  roles;  in  fact, 
entire  institutions,  with  their  varying  roles,  may  be  eliminated  by 
the  introduction  of  new  techniques.  Such  changes  naturally  in\  ol\  e 
hopes  and  fears  which  must  be  understood  in  their  precise  role 
context.  New  roles  which  carry  higher  status  or  income  or  power 
create  and  channel  ambitions  and  hopes.  The  contraction  of  roles 
in  any  institutional  order  tends  to  produce  scarcity  consciousness 
and  insecurity  feelings  on  the  basis  of  which  one  may  observe 
heightened  competition  among  job  holders  who  seek  to  displace 
one  another.  Or,  in  contrast,  the  pressures  may  call  forth  solidarity 
sentiments  in  defense  of  jobs  which  the  threatened  workers  or  mili- 
tary men  have  come  to  consider  as  "theirs"  by  right  of  years  of 
service.  Anxieties  or  frustrations  aroused  in  this  way  may  appear 


S94  DYNAMICS 

in  other  contexts  of  the  person  as  aggressions.  Thus  the  anxieties 
of  small  manufacturers  originating  in  the  technological  sphere  of 
an  economic  order  may  cause  cumulative  hostilities  which  may  be 
"free  floating"  or  which  may  be  expressed  in  the  political  order  or 
in  family  life,  in  mass  spectator  sports  or  in  a  seat  on  the  aisle 
in  the  dark  of  a  movie.  To  the  extent  to  which  the  helpless  person, 
under  the  guidance  of  a  severe  generalized  other  and  lack  of  in- 
sight, suppresses  such  hostilities,  he  may  develop  guilt  feelings 
and  hence  punish  himself.  In  extreme  cases,  such  "masochist"  tend- 
encies to  self-punishment  may  tempt  a  desperate  man  to  suicide, 
or,  by  a  curious  inversion  of  cause  and  effect,  it  may  compel  the 
actor  to  "ask  for  it"  by  committing  a  grime.  The  new  transient  role, 
that  of  the  criminal,  "makes  sense"  to  him.  Technological  changes, 
understood  sociologically,  may  thus  have  many  complicated  conse- 
quences. But  then  no  causal  sequence  in  a  social  structure,  when 
adequately  traced,  is  simple. 

Although  technique  is  not  linked  exclusively  to  economic  insti- 
tutions, since  the  seventeenth  century,  science,  technology,  and  eco- 
nomic institLitions  have  become  firmly  linked.  Since  then,  the  tech- 
nique of  production  has  circumscribed  the  limitations  and  possi- 
bilities of  all  technical  implementation. ^r  Without  the  modern  glass 
industry,  astronomy  could  not  have  its  giant  telescopes;  without 
the  production  of  photographic  equipment,  modern  microscopic 
observation  would  be  impossible.  Without  the  skill  of  the  carpenter, 
the  occidental  violin  would  be  impossible;  crafts  and  skills  are 
thus  necessary  preconditions  for  the  development  of  instrumfental 
music.  Whatever  else  his  music  may  express,  Bach  composed  The 
Well  Tempered  Clavichord  to  prove  the  adequate  range  and  pos- 
sibilities of  the  instrument  when  tuned  in  this  way. 

The  priest  and  the  artist  as  well  as  the  die-maker  must  acquire 
facility  with  routines— routines  which  are  required  for  adequately 
handling  the  instruments  each  uses.  Insofar  as  imagination  is  tech- 
nologically oriented,  it  is  to  be  found  in  all  spheres  of  social  life. 
There  are  musical  "inventions"  just  as  there  are  electrical  inventions. 
There  may  of  course  be  differences  in  tempo  between  the  develop- 
ment of  human  skill  and  the  production  of  instruments.  A  new 
instrument  is  a  challenge  to  old  skills:  it  was  thirty  years  after  the 
perfection  of  the  violin  by  Stradivari  and  Guarnieri  before  Corelli 
invented  and  established  the  role  of  the  violin  virtuoso.  But  the 
reverse  may  also  hold:   human  skills  may  confront  problems  the 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  395 

solutions  to  which  become  possible  only  if  suitable  technological 
inventions  are  available.  Beethoven's  compositions  and  style  of  per- 
formance demanded  that  the  piano  pedal  be  de\  eloped.  He  did 
not  develop  his  technique  of  composition  because  the  concert  grand 
piano  had  been  invented;  the  concert  piano  was  promoted  by 
Beethoven,  who  told  the  instrument  makers  what  he  needed.  Some- 
times skills  lag;  sometimes  technologies  do. 

W.  H.  E.  Lecky  wrote:  ^^  "The  causes  which  most  disturbed  or 
accelerated  the  normal  progress  of  society  in  antiquity  were  the 
appearance  of  great  men,  in  modern  times  they  have  been  the 
appearance  of  great  inventions  .  .  .  The  leading  characteristics  of 
modern  societies  are  in  consequence  marked  out  much  more  by 
the  triumphs  of  inventive  skill  than  by  the  sustained  energy  of 
moral  causes."  This  might  lead  us  to  believe  that  "the  inventor"  as 
a  type  of  man  has  in  modern  times  replaced  "the  great  man"  of 
antiquity.  Such  an  inference  would  be  incorrect.  For  the  inventor— 
as  a  free-lance  man  combining  industrial  ingenuity  and  scientific 
ability— was,  in  fact,  a  short-lived  type,  existing  between  the  era  of 
static  technology,  which  ended  in  the  eighteenth  century,  and  the 
era  of  bureaucratized  science  and  bureaucratized  industry  of  the 
twentieth  century.  The  origins  of  the  inventor  lay  in  the  Renais- 
sance of  Leonardo  and  of  experimental  artisans;  his  end  was  al- 
ready adumbrated  in  the  early  nineteenth  century,  for  example, 
in  Balzac's  image  of  David  Sechard.^*^ 

III.  The  Autonomy  of  Technology.  We  have  remarked  that  tech- 
nology does  not  advance  automatically,  of  its  own  force;  that  before 
technology  can  effect  historical  changes,  institutions  must  raise 
effective  demands  to  incorporate  it;  that  institutional  orders  \ary  in 
this  respect;  and  hence  that  the  technological  spheres  of  different 
societies  are  differently  anchored.  Nevertheless,  does  not  technology 
have  some  causal  autonomy?  Does  it  not  exert  a  long-run  causal 
force,  even  if  unevenly,  upon  human  institutions  everywhere,  at  all 
times?  These  are  the  rhetorical  questions  of  "technological  deter- 
minism," perhaps  nowadays  the  leading  theory  of  social  change, 
and  there  is  something  to  them. 

15  See  his  History  of  European  Morals  (New  York:  Appleton,  1929),  1897, 
Vol.  I,  pp.   126-27. 

16  See  his  Lost  Illusions  (Temple  ed.;  New  York:  Macmillan,  1910),  especi- 
ally Part  II. 


396  DYNAMICS 

One  aspect  of  the  conception  of  technological  development  as 
autonomous  deserves  particular  attention:  many  discoveries  have 
not  been  made  out  of  regard  for  any  usefulness.  Of  course  they 
have  been  adapted  with  great  ingenuity  to  given  demands,  but 
the  discoveries  themselves  were  the  results  of  combinations  play- 
fully made  out  of  the  existing  stock  of  technologies  and  ideas.  It 
is  the  impact  of  one  discovery  or  invention  upon  scientific  workers 
in  other  contexts  of  discovery  that  forms  the  internal  interaction  of 
the  quasi-organized  workmanship  and  idea-ship  of  science  and 
technology.  It  is  this  "immanent  logic"  of  playful  or  systematic 
combinations  that  is  concretely  meant  by  the  "idle  curiosity"  of 
the  scientist,  or  the  pursuit  of  science  for  science's  own  sake. 

Now  the  phrase,  "science  and  technology,"  stands  for  an  in- 
tricately specialized  division  of  labor.  Agents  well  entrenched  in 
the  given  institutions— modern  manufacturers,  for  example— con- 
stantly scan  the  world  scientific  output  for  items  useful  to  their 
own  marketable  product.  Other  agents— those  of  the  military  order 
of  the  victorious  nations  of  World  War  I— rested  on  their  oars  and 
had  to  have  some  technologies  useful  to  their  ends  forced  upon 
them  by  the  new  model  armies  of  the  defeated.  But,  according 
to  the  theory  of  the  autonomous  technological  continuum  and  the 
logic  of  combinations,  neither  manufacturer  or  general  can  go 
further  than  the  continuum  permits.  Of  course,  by  supporting  or 
failing  to  support  the  work,  they  can  slow  it  up  or  speed  it  along. 
Atomic  energy  research,  for  example,  had  quite  different  settings 
in  the  United  States  and  in  Hitler  Germany.  Whereas  President 
Roosevelt  promptly  responded  to  Einstein's  letter  in  1939  and  was 
ready  to  set  aside  substantial  funds  and  facilities.  Hitler  proved 
less  available  to  the  counsel  of  physicists  who  were  of  course  unable 
to  guarantee  results  within  six  months,  as  he  demanded.  Hitler 
operated  in  a  context  of  "autarchy"  and  scarcity;  Roosevelt,  as  far 
as  resources  for  military  requirements  are  concerned,  in  an  economy 
of  comparative  abundance. 

In  and  of  itself,  the  technological  continuum  is  socially,  eco- 
nomically, and  morally  blind;  it  is  no  Messiah;  it  has  no  other  aim 
then  to  allow  man  to  implement  any  given  end  he  may  have, 
with  less  physical  effort  in  a  shorter  time.  "Radio"  can  broadcast 
music  or  it  can  teach  that  the  world  is  flat.  But  institutions  are  not 
blind.  The  institutional  "market"  for  science  takes  up  the  discov- 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  ;^gy 

eries  of  science  at  various  stages  of  the  ongoing  process  of  science, 
and  turns  them  into  commodities,  weapons,  and  tools.  Oil  men 
gave  geologists  a  hearing,  Franklin  Giddings  '"  once  remarked, 
because  geologists  make  money  for  them.  And  there  is  often  a 
great  institutional  gap,  especially  in  mature  capitalist  societies, 
between  scientific  discoveries  and  their  public  use:  legal  and  busi- 
ness institutions  often  hold  back  this  "rational"  and  apparently 
easy  transition.  And  if  we  consider  "technological  unemployment" 
in  the  long  run  as  "irrational,"  surely  we  have  learned  that  what  is 
technically  efficient  and  economically  profitable  is  not  necessarily 
socially  rational.  Science  is  not  automatically  "at  the  service  of 
mankind." 

But  that  does  not  mean  that  profit-making  or  war-making  or 
monopolist  restriction  of  in\ention  and  frozen  patents,  "set  the 
ends"  of  science  and  technology.  There  has  been,  in  modern  times, 
a  complicated  interplay  between  industry  and  technology,  busi- 
ness and  science.  Both  sides  of  the  interplay  reached  their  modern 
scale  and  tempo  together.  New  industries  grew  from  a  complex  of 
inventions,  and  industries  have  subsidized  the  development  of  new 
leaps  forward  in  technical  skills  and  big  gadgets.  Inventors  have 
made  money-makers  possible;  money-makers  have  subsidized  in- 
ventors, and  exploited  their  work. 

Necessity  or  purpose  is  the  mother  of  adaptive  inventions;  but 
invention  is  also  the  mother  of  necessity.  There  is  nothing  in  the 
logic  or  in  the  course  of  science  that  dictates  that  its  results  will 
be  used  for  any  particular  end,  or  indeed  that  it  will  be  used  at 
all.  The  growing  points  of  the  technological  continuum  may  or 
may  not  coincide  with  the  growing  points  of  institutional  demand. 
Both  shift,  pass  one  another,  coincide  for  a  moment,  move  on. 

The  person  may  become  attached  to  the  skill  aspects  of  his 
roles  in  such  a  way  that  his  feelings  transcend  the  orienting  func- 
tion of  the  institution  of  which  his  role  is  a  part.  Such  internalized 
standards  are  involved  in  all  "craftsmanship,"  and  groups,  such  as 
the  guild,  may  have  ethical  and  status  codes  which  keep  standards 
of  skill  high.  Craftsmanship  also  refers  to  the  joyful  experience  of 
mastering  the  resistance  of  the  materials  with  which  one  works,  or 
the  solution  of  self-imposed  tasks— an  experience  that  might  occur 

^'^  Civilization  and  Society  (New  York:  Holt,  1932),  p.  164. 


SgS  DYNAMICS 

irrespective  of  the  opinions  of  other  persons  or  of  any  rule  that 
exists.^* 

The  technological  sphere  has  an  inner  dynamic  just  as  all  spheres 
do,  but  the  chances  that  technological  advances  will  be  instituted 
by  given  institutions  are  not  determined  solely  by  the  state  of 
technology.  They  are  also  determined  by  the  premiums  which  given 
institutions  place  upon  the  incorporation  of  such  advances.  The 
technology  of  any  given  time  is  a  necessary  condition  for  the 
technical  dynamics  of  an  institutional  order,  but  not  a  sufficient 
cause  for  their  explanation.  In  order  to  have  a  steamboat  it  is 
necessary  to  have  a  boat  and  a  steam  engine,  but  to  institute  a 
steamboat  in  the  economic  or  military  orders,  the  boat  must  be 
recognized  as  a  serviceable  means  to  the  ends  of  these  orders. 
Napoleon,  we  recall,  refused  Fulton's  offer. 

4.  Social-historical  Change 

By  social  change  we  refer  to  whatever  may  happen  in  the  course 
of  time  to  the  roles,  the  institutions,  or  the  orders  comprising  a 
social  structure:  their  emergence,  growth,  and  decline.  Our  model 
of  social  structure  thus  provides  us  with  several  interconnected  units, 
each  of  which  may  undergo  quantitative  as  well  as  qualitative, 
microscopic  as  well  as  macroscopic,  change. 

When  we  focus  upon  the  concept  of  role  as  the  unit  of  social 
change,  we  ask  how  many  people  play  a  given  role  and,  at  what 
tempo  is  one  role  displaced  by  another.  The  first  point  of  observa- 
tion may  be  illustrated  by  the  decrease  of  independent  producers 
in  certain  industries.  The  displacement  of  one  role  by  another  may 
be  illustrated  by  the  shift  from  entrepreneurial  to  managerial  roles 
in  the  economic  order. 

The  institution  may  be  taken  as  the  unit;  again  the  number  of 

IS  One  economic  aspect  of  tliis  technical  quality  is  that  only  relatively 
wealthy  patrons  can  pay  for  handicraft;  the  masses  have  to  do  without  them. 
High  standards  of  skill  demand  long  years  of  apprenticeship,  hence  the 
social  exclusiveness  of  the  guilds,  the  worker  insisting  upon  controlling  his  prod- 
uct from  raw  material  to  its  completion.  Thus  we  find  helmet-makers,  sword- 
makers,  shoe-makers,  glove-makers.  Industrial  technology  follows  a  different 
principle  of  specialization.  In  its  coiuse  from  raw  material  to  finished  product, 
the  product  passes,  as  it  were,  through  numerous  plants,  and  one  firm,  such  as 
General  Electric,  may  produce  more  than  30,000  differently  priced  products 
by  incorporating  a  great  variety  of  skill  groups  in  one  enterprise. 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  399 

any  given  type  of  institution— churches  or  sects,  factories  or  farms— 
as  well  as  the  types  of  institutions  that  most  generally  prevail. 
Thus,  individual  enterprises  in  the  economic  order  are  replaced  by 
corporations;  and  there  is  a  decline  of  independent  entrepreneur- 
ships. 

We  may  use  the  institutional  order  as  our  unit  of  change,  and 
thus  speak  of  the  changing  numbers  of  institutions  of  given  t\'pes 
that  exist  in  that  order,  the  types  of  institutions  that  have  become 
dominant  or  secondary  within  an  order,  and  finally,  the  shifting 
relations  of  this  order  to  other  orders.  If  there  are  disproportionate 
changes  of  one  type  of  institution  within  the  order,  as  o\er  against 
another,  we  might  observe  a  shift  from  quantitative  to  qualitative 
kinds  of  changes.  Thus,  when  the  small  independent  enterprise  is 
displaced  by  the  giant  corporation  as  the  dominant  institutional 
type,  the  whole  order,,  as  it  were,  has  undergone  a  basic  change. 

The  social  structure  itself  can  be  "overturned,"  as  in  total  revolu- 
tion or  other  epochal  transitions.  This  means  that  in  each  institu- 
tional order  we  observe  a  shift,  not  only  of  personnel,  but  in  the 
type  of  institution  that  prevails.  It  also  usually  means  that  the 
orders  composing  the  social  structure,  the  way  in  which  they  are 
articulated  and  related,  are  recomposed  so  that  a  new  social  struc- 
ture emerges.  And  most  important,  such  revolutions  mean  that  the 
legitimations  and  their  ideological  elaboration  change. 

Microscopic  and  macroscopic  changes  may  occur  inside  the  social 
structiue  as  a  whole,  inside  given  orders,  or  inside  institutions,  and 
these  changes  may  occur  at  disproportionate  rates,  in  quantitative 
and  in  qualitative  ways.^'^ 

1^  Of  course,  other  units  of  change  may  be  chosen.  For  example,  perhaps 
the  simplest  observable  change  is  the  purely  quantitative  increase  or  de- 
crease of  the  biological  units  composing  a  society.  An  increase  in  the 
average  weight  of  a  newly  bom  infant,  or  of  the  height  of  the  average 
man,  is  not,  of  course,  in  and  of  itself  social  change,  but  neither  is  it  a 
purely  "natural  process."  Such  changes  can  often  be  ascribed  to  changed 
social  conditions,  such  as  standards  of  li\ing  or  effecti\e  diets.  Socially  con- 
ditioned biological  changes  of  this  sort,  in  turn,  become  socially  rele\ant; 
the  size  of  army  vmiforms  must  be  changed,  school  benches  become  cramped 
or  obsolete. 

Only  insofar  as  social  actions  are  oriented  to  biological  data  are  such  data 
of  direct  sociological  account.  In  Germany,  for  example,  kinky  hair  has  not 
been  of  public  concern,  but  under  Nazism,  die  distribution  of  blond  hair 
and  blue  e\es  became  relexant,  spurious  status  premiums  ha\ing  been 
ideologically  placed  upon  Uiem.  With  the  motorization  of  the  modern  army. 


400  DYNAMICS 

Many  changes  in  society  may  be  tabulated  as  changes  in  quan- 
tity. A  jDrice  curve  symbolizes  the  changing  prices  which  at  differ- 
ent times  result  from  price-fights  bet\veen  buyers  and  sellers  com- 
peting in,  or  monopolizing,  specific  markets:  such  curves  present 
in  concise  brevity  the  points  at  which  on-going  interest  conflicts 
were  settled  by  compromise.  Any  occupation  may  increase  or 
decline  in  its  membership;  and  in  like  manner,  the  number  of 
institutions  in  any  order  or  structure  may  wax  or  wane. 

Such  quantitative  changes  often  have  qualitative  aspects.  If  the 
same  number  of  persons  live  in  a  scatter  they  will  behave  differ- 
ently and  feel  differently  than  if  they  live  huddled  together.  In 
the  family  and  in  the  factory,  an  increase  in  the  number  of  actors 
who  are  playing  given  roles  will  affect  all  the  actors.  A  small  nation 
of  1  million  differs  from  a  large  nation  of  loo  million  in  a  quantita- 
tive way,  but  also  in  its  qualitative  position  among  nations:  only 
large  nations  are  "great  powers."  The  same  positional  difference 
may  hold  for  institutions  within  any  order:  The  Roman  Catholic 
Church  is  a  church  of  the  Western  World;  the  Norwegian  Lutheran 
Church  is  confined  to  one  nation. 

The  uneven  growth  of  institutions  in  the  same  order  changes 
the  composition  of  that  order.-"  If  such  a  structural  change  occurs 
with  a  corresponding  change  in  the  composition  of  other  orders, 
we  may  speak  of  proportionate  change;  if  it  occurs  without  such 
correspondence,  we  may  speak  of  disproportionate  changes  be- 
tween these  orders.  There  may  be  disproportions  in  the  growth 
of  roles  within  an  institution;  or  of  different  types  of  institutions 
belonging  to  the  same  order.  Laissez-faire  capitalism  is  based  upon 
a  large  number  of  small  competing  enterprises;  monopoly  capital- 
ism results  from  the  disproportionate  growth  of  certain  enterprises 
which  finally  transform  given  industries  into  a  handful  of  great 
enterprises. 

In  Germany,  during  the  1920's,  the  economic  order  was  in- 
creasingly dominated  by  monopoly  corporations,  but  the  political 
order  disintegrated  into  a  competitive  scatter  of  parties,  which 
were  superseded  during  the  great  depression  by  the  Nazis.  Such 

flat  feet  become  of  less  re]e\ance  than  they  were  for  walking  armies.  See 
Chapter  III:  Organism  and  Psychic  Structure,  Section  1:  The  Social  Relevance 
of  the  Organism. 

'"  See  Karl  Mannheim,  Man  and  Society  in  an  Age  of  Reconstruction 
(New  York:   Ilarcourt,  Brace,  1940). 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  4OI 

quantitative  changes  in  one  order,  without  corresponding  changes 
in  other  orders,  may  provide  the  recomposed  order  the  opportunity 
to  exert  increasing  influence  within  a  social  structure.  If  such  influ- 
ences are  lasting,  and  no  correspondence  takes  place,  the  position 
of  the  order  within  the  social  structure  often  changes  significantly: 
the  social  structure  is  recomposed.-' 

It  is  typical  that  in  the  process  of  institutional  recomposition, 
actors  interested  in  the  advancement  and  expansion  of  their  own 
orders,  will  subjectively  experience  other  orders  as  an  encroach- 
ment upon  their  interests.  The  rise  of  economic  liberalism,  in 
opposition  to  the  prerogatives  of  the  mercantilist  state,  may  again 
serve  as  a  brief  illustration: 

The  mercantilist  prince  used  part  of  his  tax-income  to  benefit 
certain  manufacturers  through  subsidies,  tax  exemptions,  and  char- 
ters, guaranteeing  to  such  establishments  a  production  monopoly 
and/or  a  market.  Such  privileged  enterprises  typically  handled  lux- 
ury products  for  court  society  (chinaware,  tapestries,  silver),  as 
well  as  military  provisions.  In  the  meantime,  middle-class  indus- 
trialists, especially  their  vanguard  of  textile  entrepreneurs,  pro- 
duced for  civilian  mass  consumption.  From  their  point  of  view, 
mercantilist  enterprises  and  state-managed  enterprises  (for  exam- 
ple, spinning  in  prisons)  constituted  unfair  competition,  facilitated 
through  what  seemed  to  them  an  uneconomic  investment  of  the 
taxes  they  helped  pay.  For  such  taxes  raised  their  costs  of  produc- 
tion and  hence  restricted  their  sales.  Insofar  as  taxes  upon  the  rest 
of  the  population  served  state  mercantilist  activities,  they  drained 
off  purchasing  power  which  otherwise,  as  consumers'  demands, 
might  encourage  nonmercantilist  enterprise.  As  production  for 
profit  on  the  basis  of  calculations  of  costs  and  prices  is  identified 
with  rationality,  so  mercantilist  tax  policies  and  other  interferences 
in  the  economic  order  appear  as  an  irrational  encroachment  of 
the  political  order  upon  the  economic.  From  this  irrationality,  the 
bourgeoisie  wished  to  be  freed.  Hence,  "control  of  the  budget" 
became  their  battle  cry  and  the  first  princely  prerogati\e  which, 
by  their  parliamentary  parties,  they  sought  to  curtail. -- 

-1  See  Chapter  XII:  The  Unity  of  Social  Structures,  Section  3:  Modes  of 
Integration. 

--  They  may  succeed  in  these  aspirations  witliout  recourse  to  \  iolence  as 
in  the  case  of  England's  Reform  Bill  of  1832,  or  in  the  face  of  such  aspira- 


402  DYNAMICS 

To  analyze  historical  change,  we  have  said,  requires  that  we 
find  out  what  it  is  precisely  that  changes,  how  it  changes,  in  what 
direction,  at  what  rate  of  speed,  and  why.  These  apparently  simple 
questions,  as  we  have  seen,  involve  many  contentious  theories. 
There  are  no  satisfactory  over-all  answers,  but  there  are  general 
ways  of  questioning  which  we  find  convenient  to  map  out  in  terms 
of  our  working  model  of  social  structure. 

We  cannot  accept  any  universalist  theory  of  history  based  on 
any  one  institutional  order  or  upon  the  type  of  personality  prevalent 
in  it.  At  any  given  historical  time  the  precise  scope  of  each  of  the 
institutional  orders— and  their  relations  to  all  others— must  be  deter- 
mined. These  weights  and  relations  are  empirically  open  questions, 
and  we  should  keep  them  open,  in  such  a  way  as  to  enable  us 
to  construct  any  given  epoch  in  terms  of  its  dominant  mode  of  his- 
torical change. 

There  are  many  examples  of  how  given  institutional  orders  are 
variously  involved  in  historical  change.  The  shift  from  war  to  peace, 
or  from  peace  to  war,  obviously  sets  different  relations  between 
the  military  and  other  institutional  orders. 

The  shift  from  peace  to  war  in  industrial  nations  tends  to  make 
the  military  order  supreme,  and  hence  gives  the  expert  in  military 
administration  and  violence  at  least  veto  power  over  anything  he 
fears  might  impede  the  war  effort.  It  also  alters  status  relations, 
for  prestige  seems  always  to  cluster  around  that  order  which  is 
most  authoritative.  The  supremacy  of  the  military  order  tends 
to  raise  the  prestige  of  the  armed  forces. 

Since  modern  war  requires  mass  armies,  it  entails  the  removal 

tions,  the  political  order  may  prove  to  be  inelastic,  and  agents  of  the  status 
quo  may  threaten  to  maintain  and  enforce  their  prerogatives  violently.  Then 
a  disrupture  of  the  social  structure  becomes  possible,  and  in  such  crises,  the 
middle  classes  may  establish  armed  forces  of  their  own.  Against  the  divine 
right  of  kings,  they  posit  the  "sovereignty  of  the  people"  or  of  the  nation. 
If  the  king  is  successful  in  restoring  his  authority,  disarming  the  insurrectionist 
forces,  expelling,  arresting,  or  otherwise  punishing  the  intellectual,  political 
and  military  leaders,  then  we  speak  of  i^utsch  or  rebellion:  the  European 
"revolutions"  of  1848.  If,  however,  the  insurrectionist  forces  are  successful, 
seize  power  and  establish  a  new  political  constitution  (witli  or  without  the 
old  king)  we  may  speak  of  political  revolution:  The  English  Revolution  of 
1649,  the  American  Revolution  of   1776,  the  French   Revolution  of  1789. 

For  further  remarks  on  revolutions,  see  Chapter  XV:  Collective  Behavior, 
Section  4:  Revolution  and  Counterrevolution. 


SOCIAL-HISTORICAL     CHANGE  40;^ 

of  large  numbers  of  men  from  gainful  employment  (or  from  un- 
employment), and  from  the  kinship  order.  Thus,  there  are  fewer 
husbands  available;  many  families  are  without  fathers,  many 
mothers  without  sons,  many  girls  without  boys.  An  increasing  num- 
ber of  women  assume  employment  roles  formerly  enacted  by  men. 

The  war  effort  provides  the  framework  for  all  orders;  the  expan- 
sion of  any  order  is  encouraged  only  to  the  extent  to  which  such 
expansion  may  contribute  to  victory.  Technological  development 
follows  this  pattern:  uniforms  and  soldier's  diets,  microfilm  cor- 
respondence and  motorized  army  chapels,  barracks  and  bomb 
shelters  undergo  intensive  and  extensive  development.  But  durable 
consumers'  goods— houses  and  motor  cars,  refrigerators  and  tele- 
vision—are out  for  the  duration.  There  are  heavy  jet  fighters,  but 
no  civilian  helicopters. 

The  great  elasticity  of  modern  social  structure  is  indicated  by 
the  rapidity  with  which  institutional  orders  may  be  recomposed 
and  millions,  of  people  accommodated  to  the  recomposition.  The 
disciplinary  aspects  involved  are  important  psychological  features 
of  such  processes.  They  involve  new  rules  and  regulations,  enacted 
and  decreed,  which  are  enforced  by  various  agencies,  and  chan- 
neled through  the  mass  media,  as  well  as  educational,  religious  and 
other  institutions.  Consumption  patterns  are  adjusted  to  rationing 
and  price  control,  priority  and  war  production;  the  free  job  mo- 
bility of  workers  and  of  people  in  "defense  areas"  is  legally  cur- 
tailed; compulsory  labor  service,  civilian  defense  and  national 
youth  organizations  are  successfully  introduced.  Millions  of  people 
are  evacuated  from  metropolitan  areas,  school  children  segregated 
from  their  families.  And  in  so  far  as  men  identify  with  the  "will 
to  win,"  the  executive-enforced  codes  lead  to  new  con\entions 
which  underpin  them. 

When  we  try  to  answer  questions  about  the  transformations  of 
a  total  society,  we  must  realize  that  every  social  area  is  connected, 
directly  or  indirectly,  with  every  other,  in  short  that  institutions 
and  roles  are  interdependent.  But  we  must  also  realize  that  that 
is  not  saying  much:  we  must  find  a  "way  into"  these  many  inter- 
connections. The  easiest  "way  in"  involves  examination  of  those 
institutional  orders  in  which  roles  are  implemented  by  control  over 
things  that  require  joint  acti\ities:  the  means  of  production  and 
communication,  the  means  of  destruction,  the  means  of  administra- 


404  DYNAMICS 

tion,  or  in  other  words,  the  economic,  the  mihtary,  and  the  poHtical 
order. 

The  economic  order  is  the  starting  point  for  the  analysis  of  roles 
connected  with  the  level  of  technology,  the  degree  of  specialization 
of  labor,  and  the  class  structure  of  the  respective  society.  It  offers 
us  an  approach  to  the  big  structural  dimensions  of  a  society. 

The  political  order,  with  its  various  specifications  of  executive 
functions,  offers  us  an  approach  to  distributions  of  power  and  pres- 
tige and,  via  the  staff-enforced  distribution  of  "rights"  among  all 
members  of  the  society,  especially  to  "property  rights"  in  which 
we  find  a  convenient  linkage  between  political  and  economic 
affairs. 

In  interpreting  contemporary  social  change,  we  have  found  our- 
selves more  and  more  interested  in  those  roles  and  technologies 
that  involve  violence  and  which  involve  economic  production.  Like 
many  other  observers  we  believe  that  revolutions  in  these  orders 
are  now  crucial  to  the  course  of  world  history.  Tools  and  arms,  in- 
dustrial machines  and  military  weapons,  factories  and  armies,  skill 
levels  and  practices  of  violence— how  these  interplay  with  each 
other  seem  to  us  most  immediately  relevant  to  the  course  of  twen- 
tieth-century societies. 

When  we  consider  types  of  change  characterizing  an  entire  social 
structure,  we  already  have  at  hand  modes  of  integration.  For 
correspondence,  coincidence,  co-ordination,  and  convergence,  as 
we  have  noted,^^  are  not  only  useful  in  analyzing  integration,  but 
also  sequences  of  historical  change;  in  fact,  these  modes  of  integra- 
tion appear,  in  dynamic  perspective,  as  principles  of  social-histori- 
cal change. 

The  problem  of  a  "theory  of  history"  is  neither  one  of  monistic 
hunches  or  principled  pluralism,  but  rather  a  search  for  the  causes 
of  specific  historical  sequences:  those  causes  which  according  to 
experience  and  the  conventional  standards  of  scientific  evidence 
satisfy  our  curiosity.  In  any  given  historical  epoch,  we  must  dis- 
cern shifts  within  and  between  institutional  orders,  and  then  we 
must  search  for  their  adequate  causes.  The  mode  of  historical 
change  characteristic  of  a  given  epoch  will  thus  be  more  or  less 
an  inference  from  the  types  of  integration  which  prevail  in  the 
social  structure  we  are  examining. 

^•'^  In  Chapter  XII:  The  Unity  of  Social  Structures,  Section  3:  Modes  of 
Integration.  1 

r 


CHAPTER 

XIV 


The  Sociology  of  Leadership 


AN  adequate  model  for  the  analysis  of  leadership  inust  enable 
us  to  understand  Nicolai  Lenin  on  his  way  to  the  Finland  Station, 
as  well  as  the  girl  next  door  who  advises  our  daughter  on  make-up; 
what  happened  to  Rousseau's  ideas  and  how  Tolstoi's  general  com- 
manded; why  a  radio  songstress  influences  the  intonations  of  a 
million  high  school  girls,  as  well  as  what  happened  when  Stalin 
met  Ribbentrop.  It  must  enable  us  to  understand  those  epochal 
turning  points  of  history  in  which  some  individual  seems  to  be 
the  pivot,  as  well  as  the  trivial,  casual,  day-to-day  influences  of 
everyday  life:  the  genius  who  is  worshipped  from  afar  as  a  hero, 
the  opinion  leader  who  lives  next  door. 

Leadership,  most  broadly  conceived,  is  a  relation  between  leader 
and  led  in  which  the  leader  influences  more  than  he  is  influenced: 
because  of  the  leader,  those  who  are  led  act  or  feel  differently  than 
they  otherwise  would.  As  a  power  relation,  leadership  may  be 
known  to  both  leader  and  led,  or  unknown  to  either  or  both;  it 
may  be  close-up  or  long-distance;  it  may  occur  at  a  single  cross- 
road in  the  lives  of  both,  or  only  in  the  life  of  the  follower,  after  the 
leader  is  long  dead;  it  may  affect  only  a  momentary  decision,  or 
it  may  dominate  the  life  of  the  led. 

How  can  we  sort  out  all  these  rather  vague  phenomena  of  leader- 
ship in  order  to  gain  a  view  that  is  at  once  empirically  adequate 
and  analytically  suggestive?  Along  what  dimensions  can  we  sim- 
plify what  is  involved  into  types  which  can  then  be  studied  sys- 
tematically? To  understand  leadership,  we  must  pay  attention  to 
( 1 )  the  traits  and  motives  of  the  leader  as  a  man;  ( 2 )  the  images 
that  selected  publics  hold  of  him,  and  their  motives  for  following 
him;  (3)  the  roles  he  plays  as  a  leader,  their  salient  characteristics, 
and  how  the  leader  reacts  to  them;  and   (4)   the  structural  con- 


406  DYNAMICS 

texts  in  which  his  roles,  as  well  as  those  of  the  led,  are  involved. 
We  must  analyze  each  of  these  aspects  of  leadership  in  order  to 
group  their  possible  ranges;  and  we  must  systematically  relate 
them— in  order  to  understand  their  logically  possible  connections 
in  various  types  of  leadership. 

It  may  not  be  fruitful  to  treat  all  situations  of  power  as  involving 
leadership;  perhaps  we  should  delimit  leadership  to  certain  kinds 
of  authority. 

A  bicyclist  may  adjust  to  the  movements  of  the  motorist,  but 
the  power  of  the  motorist  over  the  bicyclist  does  not  bespeak  of 
"leadership."  It  is  also  true  that  not  all  men  who  are  interested  in 
having  their  way  are  also  interested  in  having  others  follow  them. 
And,  in  turn,  the  weak  man  may  accommodate  to  the  moves  of 
the  strong  lest  he  be  crushed,  but  not  in  order  to  follow  his  lead. 
Coercion  of  the  weak  by  the  strong,  whether  physical  or  economic, 
does  not  constitute  relations  of  leader  and  follower,  although  such 
relations  may  emerge  from  originally  naked  power  situations. 

To  be  called  a  leader  one  must  wish  to  have  his  way  accepted, 
and  the  direction  of  the  follower's  behavior  must  be  in  agreement 
with  the  leader's  own  course.  Where  the  led  accepts  the  leader's 
"right"  to  influence  his  course  of  conduct  we  attribute  not  merely 
power  but  "legitimate  power"  or  "authority"  to  the  leader. 

There  are  of  course  all  sorts  of  constellations  of  authority  and 
power  relationships.  Should  we  call  a  patriarchal  father  the 
"leader"  of  his  family?  Should  we  consider  a  railroad  official  who 
advises  us  about  which  train  to  take  a  "leader"?  Not  every  "supe- 
rior" is  a  leader  in  that  he  "leads  us  on"  to  some  goal,  and  not 
every  ruler  has  a  goal  or  need  have  one,  beyond  maintaining  exist- 
ing routines.  Yet  to  limit  "leadership"  in  some  such  way  would 
mean  to  eliminate  attention  to  traditional  leaders  as  well  as  to 
underlings  who  merely  execute  the  will  and  intention  of  policy- 
makers who  actually  "lead  on." 

1.  The  Leader  as  a  Man:  His  Traits  and  Motives 

It  is  more  fruitful  in  the  beginning  to  study  the  social  roles  of 
leaders  in  various  contexts  than  the  individual  traits  of  leaders  in 
social  isolation.  The  traits  so  far  discerned  by  students  of  leader- 
ship are  either  so  formal  as  to  be  useless  and  unrevealing,  or,  if 
specific,  as  varied  as  the  different  groups  led  by  the  leaders.  Some 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  4OJ 

putative  traits  have  been  supposed  to  be  organic,  so  that  history 
is  reduced  to  nature,  society  to  biology;  others  have  been,  sup- 
posedly, socially  acquired.  We  now  know  that  the  first  is  a  fruitless 
error  of  reduction  and  the  second  inadequate  sociology— unless  the 
search  for  leadership  traits  is  closely  united  with  depictions  of  the 
roles  of  leaders  in  different  groups,  in  particular  with  the  way  these 
roles  select,  reinforce,  and  form  the  traits  of  leaders. 

This  is  not  to  say  that  there  are  not  personality  traits,  and  even 
types  of  personality,  historically  associated  with  different  leadership 
roles.  It  is  to  say  that  these  traits  and  types  can  be  generalized 
out  of  their  contexts  only  when  the  personal  demands  of  one 
leader-role  are  quite  similar  to  those  of  another.  When  this  is  so, 
then  individual  traits  and  capacities  may  have  carry-over  value. 

The  army  sergeant  and  the  industrial  foreman;  the  government 
official  and  the  corporation  executive;  the  labor  leader  of  a  certain 
type  and  the  personnel  manager  of  a  certain  type— men  enacting 
these  roles  may  interchange  roles  the  more  easily  because  of  the 
formal  similarity  of  the  demands  and  recruitment  patterns  involved, 
and  hence,  of  the  types  of  men  recruited  and  formed  by  them.  But 
to  so  relate  individual  traits  and  leader  roles,  we  must  pay  atten- 
tion to  the  institutional  dynamics  affecting  roles:  both  armies  and 
factories  are  hierarchies  requiring  morale  builders  and  human 
whips;  public  administration  no  longer  represents  "pedantocracy" 
or  business  corporations  a  series  of  "ventures";  the  modern  union 
comes  to  perform  many  pacifying,  integrating  functions  similar  to 
the  personnel  department  of  the  company.  As  the  functions  and  re- 
lations of  institutions  shift,  so  do  the  roles  of  their  leaders— making 
individual  character  and  personality  traits  more  or  less,  as  the  case 
may  be,  transferable  from  one  institutional  context  to  another. 

It  is  the  same  with  the  motives  of  leaders  as  with  other  traits: 
motives  vary  by  type  of  role,  indeed,  motixes  are  often  understand- 
able only  as  part  of  the  role  itself.  The  gratifications  that  roles 
provide— prestige,  authority,  income,  or  realization  of  superego 
ideal— become  the  motives  of  men  to  enact  the  role.  Motixes  for 
leadership  are  thus  as  varied,  on  the  one  hand,  as  human  motivation 
itself,  and  on  the  other,  as  the  contexts  of  leader-roles. 

Motives  for  leadership  may  be  given  in  terms  ( 1 )  of  the  sub- 
jectively intended  aims  of  the  leader,  hence  in  terms  of  his  overt 
vocabulary  of  personal  values  and  goals.  These  may,  in  turn,  be 
imputed  to   (2)   covert  psychic  "needs"  or  aspirations  in  terms  of 


408  DYNAMICS 

Freudian  or  Nietzschean  mechanics,  compensation,  displacement, 
and  so  on,  or  to  (3)  objective  social  forces  and  opportunities,  re- 
quirements and  contradictions. 

The  points  we  wish  to  make  in  this  connection  are,  first,  that 
many  motives  of  many  types  of  leaders  may  be  linked  in  the  super- 
ego to  articulated  "causes,"  and  second,  that  these  motives  and 
causes  may  or  may  not  have  to  do  with  denied  expediences,  frus- 
trations, or  deprivations.  Mere  calculations,  disguised  as  "gratifica- 
tions," are  not  all  there  is  to  the  motivation  of  leaders.  The  prophet 
Elijah  shuns  income,  forgoes  existing  opportunities  for  prestige, 
and  plays  out  his  role  even  while  he  hates  its  demands— he  served 
only  "his  God."  And  the  point,  made  by  Sombart,  and  again  by 
Lasswell,  that  if  a  Prussian  university  had  given  Karl  Marx  a  secure 
post  he  might  not  have  been  launched  on  his  revolutionary  career, 
seems  to  us  unfounded.  There  is  no  evidence  to  suppose  that  this 
young  doctor  of  philosophy  wished  to  become  a  professor;  more- 
over, as  his  brother-in-law  was  the  Prussian  minister  of  the  interior, 
he  might  well,  if  he  wished,  have  been  appointed.  The  case  illus- 
trates this  point:  We  can  often  explain  the  motives  of  leaders  as 
due  to  superego  formations,  to  the  embracing  of  a  cause,  with  no 
reference  to  personal  frustrations  and  expediences. 

We  should  study  the  traits  and  motives  of  leaders  in  close  con- 
nection with  their  roles,  appropriately  related  to  their  social-his- 
torical contexts.  An  extremely  important  aspect  of  this  context  is 
the  more  or  less  immediate  followers  of  the  leader  and  the  images 
they  hold  of  him. 

2.  Images  of  the  Leader  and  Motives  of  the  Led 

Since  there  can  be  no  leader  without  the  led,  in  order  to  make 
a  transfer  from  one  context  to  another,  the  leader,  regardless  of 
his  traits  and  motives,  must  be  able  to  engage  the  loyalties  of 
those  in  the  new  context.  The  relations  of  leader  and  led  have 
often  been  put  pragmatically  in  terms  of  the  needs  of  the  led. 
But  we  are  by  no  means  ready  to  accept  such  easy  formulae  as 
"the  leader  satisfies  the  needs  of  the  led"  or  "the  leader  articulates 
what  the  led  want  and  cannot  articulate  or  don't  know  how  to 
get."  All  such  formulas,  as  well  as  Max  Weber's  more  sophisticated 
typology  of  legitimations,  we  may  approach  generally  in  terms  of 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  409 

the  images  which  the  led  hold  of  their  leader.  The  question  of 
leadership,  as  Max  Weber  set  it  up  in  terms  of  authority,  is  the 
question  of  why  the  led  follow.  Weber  answers  the  question  in 
terms  of  three  types  of  legitimation:  ^  charismatic,  traditional,  and 
legal.  These  represent  formal  reasons  for  more  or  less  voluntary 
obedience,  the  first,  charismatic,  because  the  led  impute  to  the 
leader  extraordinary  personal  qualities;  the  second,  traditional, 
because  they  feel  that  the  leader  has  always  been  followed  and 
rightly  so;  and  the  last,  legal,  because  they  feel  that  the  leader 
has  attained  his  position  according  to  legal  rules  which  the  led 
accept.  This  classification  is  quite  useful;  but  as  an  over-all  model 
it  is,  of  necessity,  highly  formal  and  leaves  untouched  many  aspects 
or  dimensions  of  leadership  to  which  we  should  like  to  pay  sys- 
tematic attention. 

Images  of  instituted  leaders,  especially  those  images  that  are 
relevant  to  why  they  are  followed,  vary  by  institutional  order.  In 
fact,  as  part  of  the  symbolic  features  of  institution,  these  images 
justify  the  leader's  roles,  and  often  the  role  of  its  occupant.  If  he 
is  a  legitimate  leader,  he  rules,  as  in  Saudi  Arabia  or  a  modern 
totalitarian  party,  by  virtue  of  the  charismatic  gifts  claimed  by  him 
and  imputed  to  him  as  a  presumably  extraordinary  individual;  as 
in  patriarchal  family  or  peasant  village,  by  virtue  of  wealth,  cus- 
tomary family  repute,  and  the  presumed  or  actual  wisdom  of  "the 
grand  old  man."  Or,  as  in  the  constitutional  state,  by  virtue  of  hav- 
ing met  legally  enacted  qualifications,  including  that  of  being  "duly 
elected  or  appointed."  These  images  uphold  the  leader's  authority 
among  the  institution's  members— they  are  the  formal  motives  for 
their  obeying  him.  They  are  his  formal  claims  to  leadership,  which, 
when  he  has  internalized  them,  are,  with  individual  variations,  his 
motives  as  a  leader. 

Any  institutional  structure  needs  to  regulate  the  generalized  others 
of  its  members.  One  of  the  functions  of  the  leader  is  to  import 
larger  codes  into  the  subgroup  which  he  leads.  The  "leader"  is 
a  mediator  between  the  members  of  his  group  and  the  larger  social 
structure.  As  the  responsible  head  of  his  family  or  of  his  enterprise, 

1  The  Theonj  of  Social  and  Economic  Organization,  Talcott  Parsons  and 
A.  M.  Henderson,  trs.  (New  York:  Oxford,  1948).  Chapter  I.  See  also 
Chapter  VIII:  Institutional  Orders  and  Social  Controls,  I,  Section  1:  The 
Pohtical   Order,   and   Chapter   X:    Symbol   Spheres. 


410  DYNAMICS 

for  example,  he  is  to  some  extent  held  responsible  for  what  goes 
on  in  his  family  or  business;  he  represents  family  members,  em- 
ployees, and  their  conduct  before  out-groups,  especially  before 
larger  and  more  powerful  frame  groups— the  police,  the  church,  the 
state.  The  father  is  thus  responsible  to  the  public  school  teacher  for 
the  behavior  of  his  children. 

Such  a  representative  position  exerts  pressures  upon  the  subgroup 
leader  to  build  into  the  "generalized  other"  of  the  subgroup  mem- 
bers elements  of  the  generalized  other  of  "frame  groups"— of  the 
state,  of  the  church,  and  of  wider  status  group  codes.  Thus  he  is 
made  the  "transmission  belt"  for  the  importation  of  larger  group 
values  and  codes  into  the  little  universe  of  the  subgroup.  The  father, 
for  example,  has  to  install  in  his  family  value  preferences  which 
will  assure  that  his  daughters  will  have  the  properly  delimited 
preferences  for  acceptable  husbands. 

This  position  of  the  leader  toward  the  outside  has  a  further 
aspect:  the  leader  may  be  proud  of  the  attainments  of  his  group 
members.  The  father  of  a  family,  for  example,  is  credited  by  out- 
siders with  the  successes  of  his  children,  receives  congratulations 
for  the  successful  marriage  of  his  daughter  or  the  brilliant  achieve- 
ments of  his  son.  He  is  held  responsible  for  what  goes  on  in  the 
unit  he  leads,  and  he  is  blamed  and  credited  for  the  successes  and 
failures  of  its  members.  Thus,  the  deference  which  leaders  receive 
in  their  roles  as  leaders  is  sometimes  quite  elaborate  (gun  salutes, 
flag  hoistings,  and  other  pompous  ritual)  because  through  them 
their  group  is  honored. 

This  deference  -often  refers  to  the  role  rather  than  to  the  man 
who  plays  it.  The  man  may  not  personally  be  highly  esteemed  for 
his  style  of  acting  out  the  role,  but  nevertheless  the  role  is  ranked 
high  as  being  the  vessel  of  the  cumulative  prestige  of  the  entire 
group  which  he  leads.  We  must  distinguish  between  prestige  at- 
tached to  roles  and  personal  esteem  bestowed  upon  role-taking 
men.  Accordingly,  different  constellations  are  possible:  a  role  with 
high  prestige  may  be  filled  by  a  lowly  esteemed  man  ( Harding ) ;  a 
high-prestige  role  may  be  filled  by  a  highly  esteemed  man  (F.  D.  R., 
Wilson,  Washington);  a  low-prestige  role  may  be  filled  by  a  highly 
esteemed  man  (Al  Capone);  or  a  low-prestige  role  may  be  filled  by 
a  lowly  esteemed  man  (a  "lazy"  ditch-digger). 

Of  course  there  may  be  shifts  in  these  evolutions  of  men  and 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  41I 

roles.  At  the  beginning  of  his  State  and  Revolution  -  Lenin  has  a 
nice  commentary  on  the  changes  in  attitude  towards  the  revolu- 
tionary: "During  the  life  time  of  great  revolutionaries,  the  oppress- 
ing classes  have  visited  relentless  persecution  on  them  and  received 
their  teaching  with  the  most  savage  hostility,  the  most  furious 
hatred,  the  most  ruthless  camp)aign  of  lies  and  slanders.  After  their 
death,  attempts  are  made  to  turn  them  into  harmless  icons,  to 
canonize  them,  and  surround  their  names  with  a  certain  halo  for 
the  consolation  of  the  oppressed  classes  and  with  the  object  of 
duping  them,  while  at  the  same  time  emasculating  and  vulgarizing 
the  real  essence  of  their  revolutionary  theories  and  blunting  their 
revolutionary  edge."  With  appropriate  modification,  Lenin's  state- 
ment may  be  extended  to  the  iconography  of  certain  Tsars  in  the 
Soviet  Union  since  the  1930's.  It  is  well  known  that  Stalin  has 
adopted  Peter  the  Great  as  a  somewhat  distant  "colleague,"  or  pos- 
sibly "precursor."  And  at  Teheran,  when  Churchill  presented  Stalin 
with  the  honorific  gift  of  His  Majesty's  sword,  Stalin,  in  apprecia- 
tion of  the  distinction,  took  it  in  the  style  of  Tsarist  protocol  by 
kissing  the  sword.  One  task  a  leader  performs  for  liis  group  is 
to  provide  "official"  sanction  to  the  definition  of  the  group  situation 
in  social  space  and  historical  time. 

Images  of  leaders  are  not,  of  course,  always  adequately  adjusted 
to  the  objective  significance  of  the  leader.  But,  in  fact,  such  ade- 
quacy of  image  to  man  during  the  man's  lifetime  may  occur:  per- 
haps it  did,  positively,  in  the  case  of  Goethe,  "the  poet-prince"  and, 
negatively,  in  the  case  of  the  late  United  States  Secretary  of  De- 
fense Johnson.  There  are  inflated  images— small  leaders  with  big 
images;  and  deflated  images— big  leaders  with  small  images.  These 
•atter  are  often  known  to  us  by  their  later  ascendancy:  recall 
Mozart,  buried  among  the  paupers;  or  Shakespeare  at  such  low 
ebb  in  the  eighteenth  century. 

There  are  of  course  all  sorts  of  "incongruities"  of  image  and  man; 
for  example,  one  cannot  attribute  all  the  consequences  which  fol- 
lowed Columbus'  "discovery"  of  America— including  the  rise  to 
world  power  of  the  United  States— to  Columbus'  greatness  as  a 
man.  His  relatively  low  intelligence  and  poor  nautical  leadership, 
his  religious  superstition  and  irregular  ways  with  money,  pro\  ided 

2  Nikolai  Lenin,  Collected  Works  (New  York:  International  Pubs.,  1932). 
Vol.  XXI,  p.  153. 


412  DYNAMICS 

more  or  less  good  reasons  for  his  being  jailed  by  his  king.  "Great- 
ness," as  Wilhelm  Lange  has  indicated,^  is  more  often  an  attribute 
of  a  man's  image,  held  by  various  publics  who  "need"  to  worship 
the  majestic  and  fascinating,  the  energetic  and  the  mysterious,  the 
sublime  and  the  overpowering  than  it  is  an  attribute  of  a  man  or 
of  an  objective  assessment  of  the  historical  consequences  of  his  role 
and  deeds.  The  elaboration  of  images  of  Columbus  was  determined 
by  factors  having  little  or  nothing  to  do  with  the  work  Columbus 
did;  in  fact,  they  have  obscured  the  ramifications  of  his  action, 
which,  by  the  way,  Columbus  himself  never  got  quite  straight. 

We  do  not  believe  that  the  uniqueness  and  irreplaceability  of 
great  men  can  either  be  proved  or  disproved.  We  cannot,  for  exam- 
ple, prove  or  disprove  the  argument  that  had  Napoleon  not  arisen 
to  act  as  he  did,  another  man  or  men  would  have  so  met  "the  de- 
mands of  the  hour."  What  has  endured  from  the  Napoleonic  context 
are  the  legal  code  and  centralized  administrative  system,  and 
Napoleonic  strategy  and  tactics  as  military  models— all  borrowed 
in  accordance  with  his  model  by  other  nineteenth-century  societies. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  historical  process  of  Western  society  did 
not,  as  it  were,  require  Napoleon's  enterprise  to  conquer  Russia; 
that,  so  to  speak,  is  part  of  the  "overhead"  of  Napoleon's  deeds. 

The  idea  of  genius,  or  of  the  great  man,  has  to  do  not  only  with 
the  man  and  his  work,  but  also,  and  often  more  importantly  we 
think,  with  his  images,  with  his  fame.  It  is  sometimes  quite  a  prob- 
lem in  particular  cases  to  weigh  the  two,  but  that  is  what  must  be 
done  in  each  case.  We  shall  have  more  to  say  about  this  general 
problem  of  great  men  presently. 

Among  leaders  there  is  self-advertising,  in  which  the  leader's 
self-image  is  advanced  by  his  own  posturing;  and  there  are  fame- 
makers,  others  who  advance  the  leader's  image.  But  regardless  of 
how  they  are  diffused,  self  and  other  images  may  conflict  or  coin- 
cide: 

Napoleon,  as  well  as  Goethe,  held  strong  self-images,  and  so  did 
others  of  them.  But  some  scriptural  prophets  deemed  themselves 
unworthy  and  were  detested  by  contemporaries.  Some  leaders 
whom  others  esteem  highly  esteem  themselves  very  little:  public 
images  are  inflated  in  comparison  with  the  insufficiency  feelings 

•^  The  Problem  of  Genius,  E.  and  C.  Paul,  trs.  (New  York:  Macmillan, 
1932). 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  4!^ 

of  the  leader.  And  there  is  the  opposite:  leaders  whom  others 
esteem  very  little  but  who  esteem  themselves  very  much,  whether 
due  to  quiet  pride  (Kierkegaard)  or  bombastic  vanity  (the  Ger- 
man Kaiser). 

All  these  possible  images  of  the  leaders  are  of  course  relevant  to 
their  motives  and  to  the  motives  of  the  led.  Today  both  images  of 
the  leader  and  motives  of  the  led  are  subject  to  intensive  manipu- 
lative cultivation.  Images  and  reality  are  often  so  closely  joined  as 
to  make  difficult  their  analytic  separation;  in  fact,  they  pass  from 
one  to  another.  But  the  immediate  context  of  leader,  led,  and  image 
can  best  be  set  forth  in  terms  of  the  functional  demands  of  power- 
wielding  roles. 

3.  Three  Functions  of  Authoritative  Roles 

Regardless  of  who  wields  it,  and  of  why  others  follow  it,  author- 
ity seems  to  have  three  major  functions  to  which  we  should  pay 
close  attention.^  (I)  There  are  the  imagery,  the  representations 
of  power,  the  pomp  and  the  circumstance,  the  handling  of  the  flag, 
the  scepter,  the  crown,  the  Presidential  smile,  the  tireless,  glad 
handshake,  and  the  master  formulas,  "in  the  name  of  the  king,"  or 
"in  the  name  of  the  people,"  in  terms  of  which  orders  are  given. 
(II)  There  is  the  legitimation  of  power,  an  ideological  elabora- 
tion and  specification  of  the  representation  or  halo;  the  "miranda" 
is  elaborated  into  "doctrine,"  to  the  simple  piety  for  emblems  is 
added  theology.  (Ill)  There  is  decision-making  and  the  manage- 
ment of  the  instrumentalities  of  power,  of  staffs,  allies,  followers, 
enemies,  and  neutrals,  in  order^to  put  decisions  into  effect. 

Both  representation  and  legitimation  are  at  once  possible  aspects 
of  the  leader's  role  and  important  features  of  the  authority-context 
in  which  he  plays  it.  When  we  say  that  they  are  aspects  of  his  role, 
we  point  up  the  fact  that  he  may  modify  or  even  create  them; 
when  we  say  that  they  are  important  features  of  his  context,  we 
point  up  the  fact  that  they  lie  in  the  context  in  which  he  acts  and 
must  be  carried  by  the  led  and,  in  fact,  form  their  reasons  for  fol- 

*  For  distinctions  of  the  functions  of  authority,  see  C.  E.  Merriam,  Political 
Power  (New  York:  McGraw-Hill,  1934)  and  Systematic  Politics  (Chicago: 
Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1945);  H.  D.  Lasswell  and  others,  The  Language  of 
Politics  (New  York:  Stewart,  1949),  p.  9ff-;  and  H.  D.  Lasswell  and  A.  Kaplan, 
Power  and  Society  (New  Haven:  Yale  Univ.  Press,  1950). 


414  DYNAMICS 

lowing  him.  His  decisions  and  managements  also  have  this  dual 
reference  to  his  own  activities  and  the  context  and  motives  of  the 
led.  It  is  for  these  reasons  that  the  concept  of  role  is  so  important 
in  the  study  of  leadership. 

If  we  cross  classify  the  presence  or  absence  of  these  three  func- 
tional demands  of  power-wielding— representation,  legitimation, 
and  decision-making— we  get  eight  situations: 

REPRESENTATION 


YES 

NO 

LEGITIMATION 

LEGITIMATION 

YES 

NO 

YES                   NO 

YES 

1 

2 

3                        4 

NO 

5 

6 

7               8 

DECISION-MAKING 


( 1 )  Some  leaders  successfully  combine  all  three  functions :  Lenin 
and  Mussolini,  Peter  the  Great,  Shih  Huang  Ti,  the  "First  Emperor" 
of  China.  Napoleon  proclaims  among  his  representations  "the  rule 
of  the  genius,"  gets  the  Pope  himself  to  come  to  Paris  to  anoint 
him,  marries  a  Hapsburg  princess  to  tie  himself  in  with  dynastic 
and  Catholic  legitimations,  sets  up  a  new  army  model,  a  new 
code  of  laws,  new  internal  administrative  and  educational  systems. 
In  terms  of  these  three  functions.  Napoleon  is  a  total  leader. 

(2)  Other  leaders  may  carry  representations  of  power  and 
wield  power,  but  not  be  active  developers  of  legitimations.  Crom- 
well, "The  Lord  Protector,"  for  example,  leaves  the  theoretical  work 
of  legitimating  his  rule  to  others,  among  them,  for  a  while,  John 
Milton. 

(3)  Machiavelli,  as  a  political  secretary  of  the  prince,  manages 
affairs  and  is  an  active  creator  of  legitimations,  but  does  not  em- 
body or  display  the  representation  of  power.  Leaving  that  to  the 
prince,  he  works  out  a  legitimation  for  and  enacts  the  role  of  "the 
political  man"  who  with  rational  efficiency  tries  to  win,  hold,  and 
increase  power  for  power's  sake,  reducing  all  other  values  to  in- 
strumentalities for  that  immediate  end  while,  at  the  same  time,  of 
course,  having  in  mind  the  more  distant  goal  of  the  unification  of 
Italy. 

(4)  The  American  political  boss  neither  represents  nor  legiti- 
mates power,  but  actively  makes  decisions  and  manages  their  en- 
actment. He  gives  up  honor  and  doctrine,  if  necessary,  for  power. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  41^ 

(5)  The  polar  opposite  type  of  leader  who  does  not  manage 
decisions  at  all,  but  legitimates  and  displays  representations  is 
diflBcult  to  illustrate,  but  perhaps  the  Romantic  poets  symbolize  the 
French  Revolution  to  an  English  public  and  elaborate  one  strain  of 
its  doctrinal  legitimations.  Also,  John  Reed  operates  in  America 
with  reference  to  early  Russian  Bolshevism.  And,  in  classical  Rome, 
the  poet  Vergil,  as  a  member  of  the  Roman  ruling  class,  writes  his 
Georgics  and  Aeneid  at  the  request  of  what  moderns  might  now 
call  a  propaganda  industry. 

(6)  The  "ruler"  who  displays  representations  and  nothing  else 
is  more  frequent,  for  example,  all  the  cases  of  charismatic  chil- 
dren: the  child  king  of  Egypt,  the  Dalai  Lama  of  Tibet,  as  well  as 
kings,  queens,  and  rulers  who  are  "mere  figureheads."  Also,  Tol- 
stoi's general  has  as  his  role  "appearing  to  be  in  supreme  control" 
of  the  chaos  of  the  battlefield.  Since  unplanned  events  decide  his 
armies'  dispositions,  he  is  primarily  a  representational  leader. 

(7)  The  pure  case  of  the  ideologist,  who  only  legitimates— as 
did  Rousseau  for  the  French  upheaval,  Marx  for  the  Russian  Re\'0- 
lution,  or  Milton  for  Cromwell's  regime— exists  wherever  a  man's 
thought  is  used  by  power  wielders,  but  who  does  not  himself  dis- 
play power  or  wield  it. 

( 8 )  The  man,  finally,  who  neither  legitimizes,  displays,  or  wields 
power  is,  of  course,  no  leader,  although,  as  in  the  case  of  Edward 
Vni,  who  fell  down  on  all  three  functional  role-demands  and  abdi- 
cated, he  may  have  been  expected  to  enact  at  least  the  represen- 
tational role. 

These  three  functional  demands  of  power  wielding,  and  the 
types  of  power  wielders  they  invite  us  to  examine,  have  primarily 
to  do  with  large-scale  institutional  contexts.  By  itself,  the  eightfold 
typology  is  not  an  adequate  model  of  the  analysis  of  leadership;  it 
is  merely  a  descriptive  range  of  what  leaders  may  do.  We  want  to 
spell  out  in  more  detail  the  possibilities  of  leadership  roles  in  con- 
nection with  a  range  of  types  of  contexts  in  which  they  may  occur. 

So,  rather  than  attempt  to  construct  our  model  purely  in  terms 
of  traits  or  personalities  of  the  leader,  or  in  terms  of  the  motives  or 
reasons  of  the  led,  we  do  so  with  reference  to  the  role-denjands 
on  the  functions  of  leadership,  as  begun  in  this  section;  and  with 
reference  to  institutional  contexts  and  dynamics  back  of  these  roles, 
as  presented  in  the  next  two  sections. 


416  DYNAMICS 

4.  Contexts  and  Roles 

By  definition,  all  institutions  of  any  permanence  involve  leaders; 
for  institutions,  as  we  have  noted,  are  constellations  of  roles  graded 
in  authority  in  such  a  way  that  the  members  look  to  the  occupant 
of  the  head-role  to  guarantee,  externally  and  internally,  the  total 
role  constellation.  Externally,  the  instituted  leader,  or  his  agent, 
applies  sanctions  against  those  who  fail  to  meet  instituted  expec- 
tations, ranging  from  the  lifted  eyebrow  of  the  club  leader  to  the 
death  penalty  imposed  by  the  state.  Internally,  the  members  in- 
corporate the  institutional  head's  expectations  as  a  more  or  less 
crucial  component  of  their  particular  or  generalized  others,  and 
then  punish  themselves  when  they  are  out  of  line.  For  it  is  not 
only  that  the  patriarchal  father,  as  Freud  has  shown,  is  thus  in- 
corporated into  the  "original"  superego;  all  instituted  heads  may 
be  so  incorporated,  and,  in  fact,  incorporated  in  their  own  psycho- 
logical right. 

Types  of  instituted  leaders  are  as  various  as  the  types  of  institu- 
tions they  lead.  The  patriarchal  father  and  the  gerontocratic  elder, 
the  pope  and  the  parish  priest,  the  army  captain  and  the  trade 
union  leader,  the  school  master  and  the  corporation  manager- 
each  plays  a  role  more  or  less  in  accordance  with  the  expectations 
institutionally  exacted  of  him  as  the  head.  The  types  of  men  re- 
cruited for  these  roles  and  the  effects  of  enacting  these  roles  upon 
their  character  structures  also  include  a  wide  range  of  possibilities. 
But  as  men  they  are  selected  and  formed  as  leaders  by  the  insti- 
tutional contexts  in  which  they  play  their  parts. 

This  depiction  of  the  instituted  leader  rests  upon  the  assumption 
that  such  leadership  is  role-determined.  It  is  normally  the  insti- 
tuted context  in  which  he  leads  that  selects  and  forms  him  as  a 
man,  that  more  or  less  sets  the  role  he  plays,  that  provides  images 
of  him  which  justify  his  authority  and  motivate  men  to  follow 
him,  and  him  to  lead.  Some  writers,  for  example,  Richard  Schmidt, 
refuse  to  call  such  institutional  heads  leaders,  but  refer  to  them  as 
"agents  of  authority,"  and  to  their  followers  as  "subordinates." 
We  do  not  see  the  full  justification  of  this,  although  it  does  suggest 
three  important  points:  first,  it  points  us  to  the  crucial  distinction 
between  role-determined  and  role-determining  leadership;  second, 
to  the  fact  that  the  role-determined,  the  instituted  head,  may  be 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  4IJ 

more  or  less  determined;  and,  third,  that  he  is  probably  more  deter- 
mined when  his  institutional  sphere  is  stable,  less  determined  when 
his  sphere  is  breaking  up  or  at  least  changing  rapidly. 

The  institutional  head  as  such  does  not  usually  satisfy  our  image 
of  "the  leader"  because  we  often  think  of  leaders  as  men  who  create 
not  only  their  roles  but  the  institutions  in  which  they  will  play 
them.  This  does  not  mean  that  such  leaders  stand  alone  before 
institutions;  they  also  have  a  context  or  else  they  could  not  be 
leaders.  But  the  prime  context  of  the  role-determining  leader  is  the 
movement  or  the  party,  which  is  at  once  an  instrument  of  leader- 
ship and  an  immediate  context  of  the  roles  which  its  leaders  are  to 
play.^  One  of  the  major  aspects  of  a  leader's  role  in  a  social  move- 
ment is  to  establish  his  role,  as  he  organizes  the  internal  structure 
of  the  movement  and  tries  to  adxance  its  power  relations  with  the 
institutional  structure  and  with  other  contending  movements. 

It  is  probably  not  wise  to  split  "institutions"  from  "collective 
behavior"  and  conceive  of  the  first  as  stable  and  controlling,  and 
the  second  as  dynamic,  and,  as  it  were,  intrusive.  The  bureaucrati- 
zation of  modern  government,  of  corporate  business  life,  the  spread 
of  totalitarian,  one-party  states  may  be  more  dynamic  than  all  the 
riots,  mobs,  and  crowds  of  the  last  fifty  years  put  together  from 
all  over  Western  civilization.  And  in  these  institutional  processes 
new  roles  have  come  about,  as  well  as  role-determining  men  of 
enormous  consequences  for  modern  historic  change. 

The  lead  roles  of  many  institutions  are  prescribed,  hemmed  in 
by  rules  of  recruitment  and  office  conduct;  but  in  many  "insti- 
tuted" contexts,  the  role  of  the  leader  is  less  set,  more  open  to 
variety  of  elaborations  by  different  leaders.  Moreoxer,  in  the  latter 
the  allegiance  to  the  leader  is  less  set,  and  must  often  be  won  and 
held  by  the  leader,  whose  relations  with  the  led  must  thus  be  struc- 
tured by  the  leader  himself. 

The  context  is  less  a  structure  than  a  milieu,  and  as  a  milieu, 
more  open  to  the  leader's  structuring.  When,  in  due  course,  the 
movement  is  more  firmly  instituted,  then  the  leader  may  not  ha\e 
to  remold  in  this  way  the  new  members  who  are  selectively  re- 
cruited; in  addition,  the  deputy  leaders,  staff  members,  the  mo\'e- 
ment's  old  timers  may  do  this  job,  for  there  is  then  hierarchy  and 

^  For  a  discussion  of  mo\ements  and  parties,  see  Chapter  XV:  Collective 
Behavior,  Section  3:  Movements,  Parties,  and  Pressure  Groups. 


4l8  DYNAMICS 

and  specialization  of  roles  for  different  levels  and  types  of  leaders. 
But  leadership  in  this  context  very  often  must  begin  by  the  neces- 
sity of  the  leader's  attracting  and  holding  the  voluntary  loyalties 
of  the  led. 

What  is  needed  is  a  statement  of  the  phases  of  leadership,  as 
it  moves  from  a  small,  informal  circle  around  a  leader,  through 
innumerable  transitions,  to  a  prescheduled  role  in  an  institutional 
order  firmly  set  into  a  social  structure.  No  formal,  universal  scheme 
seems  worthwhile:  the  phases  vary  by  epoch  and  institutional  set- 
ting. As  the  contexts  become  less  formal,  the  nature  of  the  leader's 
role  usually  becomes  more  personal,  but  not  always:  there  is  the 
style  of  playing  highly  formal  roles  in  highly  formal  and  personalist 
manners. 

The  way  movements  and  parties,  as  major  contexts  of  leadership, 
are  related  to  institutional  orders  shapes  the  way  leaders  in  the 
one  context  are  related  to  the  second.  The  party  or  movement,  in 
attempting  to  influence  decision-making,  may  ( i )  put  its  leader  in 
the  lead-role  of  the  institution,  as  in  modern  constitutional  parties 
and  the  state;  (2)  change  the  institutions  and  thus  its  lead-role,  and 
then  put  its  leader  in;  or  (3)  create  a  new  institution  and  install  its 
leaders  at  its  head. 

In  terms  of  leadership,  there  is,  first,  the  conquest  of  leading 
positions,  by  revolutionaries  or  reformers;  second,  the  holding  and 
the  routinization  of  these  positions  in  the  generational  sequence  by 
(a)  customary  rights  and  rules  of  precedence  and  successorship, 
and  by  (b)  enacted  rights  which  supersede  personal  ways  of 
doing  things  and  give  issue  to  impersonal  rules  and  regulations. 
It  seems  rather  clear  that  the  chance  of  role-determining  leadership 
is  maximized  in  the  first  phase,  in  which  men's  traits  are  more 
important;  whereas  in  the  later  phases,  recruitment  patterns  are 
more  important. 

There  are  contexts,  which  deserve  detailed  descriptions,  other 
than  those  of  institutions  and  movements.''  But  these  are  perhaps 
sufficient  to  indicate  this  fact:  in  examining  this  range  of  contexts 
we  do  not  find  a  correlation  with  the  possibilities  of  role-determin- 
ing rather  than  role-determined  leaders.  But  we  do  locate  the  zone 
in   which   role-determining   leadership    seems    to   have    its   major 

"See  Chapter  XV:  Collective  Behavior,  Section  2:  Aggregates,  Crowds,  and 
Publics. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  419 

chances:  it  is  the  zone  of  all  those  types  of  voluntary  associations 
which  are  not  (yet)  firmly  a  part  of  more  established  institutional 
orders  and  spheres. 

5.  Role  Dynamics  and  Leadership 

To  ask  whether  leadership  is  a  function  of  the  traits  of  the  leader 
or  of  the  motives  and  images  of  the  led  is  not  a  fruitful  question. 
The  answer,  of  course,  is  that  it  is  both,  but  that  is  an  answer  that 
does  not  help  much.  It  does  help,  however,  to  conceive,  as  we 
have,  both  the  traits  of  the  leader  and  the  motives  of  the  led  as 
part  of  the  role  which  the  leader  plays.  Then  we  may  restate  the 
question  in  these  terms:  Does  the  leader  determine  the  role  he 
plays  or  does  the  role  determine  the  leader?  This  should,  of  course, 
not  be  taken  as  a  general  question  to  be  answered  in  general,  but 
as  a  question  leading  us  to  precise  examination  of  concrete  cases. 
The  general  answer  is  that  different  leaders  are  quite  differently 
related  to  the  roles  they  play. 

It  is  not  true,  as  Theodore  Newcomb  would  have  it,'  that  "all 
leaders  are  motivated  to  take  whatever  kinds  of  roles  are  called 
for  (or  are  permitted)  by  their  position  in  the  role  system."  It  is 
precisely  their  positions  and  the  demands  upon  their  role  that 
leaders  sometimes  put  into  question.  Nobody  "called  for"  (or  per- 
mitted) General  Napoleon  to  chase  Parliament  home  on  the  iS 
Brumaire,  or  later  to  transform  his  consulate  into  an  emperor- 
ship. Nobody  called  for  or  permitted  Adolf  Hitler  to  proclaim 
himself  "Leader  and  Chancellor"  the  day  President  Hindenburg 
died,  to  abolish  and  usurp  roles  by  merging  the  presidenc\'  and  the 
chancellorship.  Far  from  being  utterly  dependent  upon  a  "role 
system,"  the  leader  may  smash  it  and  set  up  another  in  which  his 
role  is  differently  structured.  In  fact,  such  social  destruction  and 
creation  is  what  is  typically  involved  in  one  major  type  of  "great 
leadership."  This  is  not  to  say  that  it  is  not  socially  determined; 
it  is  to  say  that  there  are  often  temporal  lags  between  the  deter- 
mination and  the  shift  in  leadership. 

This  is  a  complex  question,  which  is  to  say  that  it  is  difficult  to 
identify  the   keys   which  when  properly  ranged  and   interrelated 

■Theodore  M.  Newcomb,  Social  Psychology  ( Xew  York:  Dr>clen,  1950), 
p.  656. 


^20  DYNAMICS 

might  best  lead  us  to  observation  of  the  determining  factors  in  any 
given  case.  But  here  are  three  attempts  to  sort  out  such  keys: 

I.  Flexibility  of  Role  and  Reactions  of  Leader  to  It.  From  the 
side  of  context:  the  roles  of  leaders  may  be  quite  flexible  or  quite 
rigid  in  the  latitude  they  allow  the  leader;  ®  moreover  the  leaders 
recruited  for  these  roles  also  vary  widely  in  the  personal  way  in 
which  they  enact  them.  In  terms  of  these  two  factors— the  flexi- 
bility of  the  role  and  the  reaction  of  the  leader  to  it— there  is  clearly 
a  range.  At  one  end  is  the  role-determined  leader:  the  role  is  rigid 
and  the  recruited  man  fulfills  it  exactly  as  required,  in  the  image 
of  the  punctilious  bureaucrat.  At  the  other  end  is  the  role-deter- 
mining leader:  the  role  is  flexible  and  the  man  enacts  it  in  a  highly 
personal  style,  exceeding  what  is  expected,  making  the  most  of 
his  opportimities. 

The  President  of  the  United  States,  for  example,  has  more  lati- 
tude in  the  way  he  plays  his  role  than  the  bureaucratic  chief  of  a 
unit  in  a  division  of  a  department,  or  the  palace-confined  Mikado 
under  the  Shogunate  before  1868.  The  president  can  take  his  role 
big  or  little  in  all  three  aspects  of  authority.  If  he  takes  it  big,  as 
Franklin  D.  Roosevelt  or  Wilson  did,  he  can  modify  features  of  the 
instituted  role,  as  well  as  create  new  lead-roles  in  the  governing 
structure  as  a  whole,  which  action  in  turn  selects  and  forms  new 
types  of  men  as  leaders  around  him.  He  is  more  than  a  creature  of 
authority:  in  all  three  aspects  of  leadership,  he  is  to  some  extent 
a  role-determining  man.  If  he  takes  it  little,  as  Harding  did,  enact- 
ing it  in  an  understated  way,  he  can  sit  back  and  take  it  easy, 
performing  the  expected  actions  but  not  creating  any  new  ones. 

8  This  scale  of  roles  includes  each  of  the  three  major  functional  demands 
on  leadership:  Representation  functions  may  range  from  the  hierocratic 
rigidity  of  court  ceremonial  under  a  theocratic  emperor,  as  in  Oriental  despot- 
isms and  ancient  Roman  Caesarism,  to  the  studied  informality  of  the  British 
king  at  a  Boy  Scout  jamboree  and  the  personable  horseplay  of  Franklin 
Roosevelt  with  liberal  intellectuals.  Legitimation  functions  may  be  strictly 
orthodox,  as  in  the  case  of  Stalinism's  invention  of  "theoretical  heresies,"  or 
Confucianism's  hatred  of  all  sahation  religions,  to  the  free  market  in  ideas 
where  rival  definitions  of  democracy  itself  are  tolerated  as  legitimate  within 
the  limits  of  national  loyalty.  Decision-making  finally  may  range  from  a 
Leadership)  Principle,  as  with  Hitler,  with  the  "authority  of  every  leader 
downward  and  responsibility  upward,"  to  a  maximum  sharing  of  all  decisions 
and   participation   of  virtually  all  citizens. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  ^21 

He  is,  then,  a  symbol  of  authority  ("guardian  of  the  constitution") 
and  a  role-determined  man. 

Whether  a  man  takes  his  instituted  role  big  or  little  depends 
not  only  upon  what  he  as  the  occupant  brings  to  the  role  but  also 
upon  the  institutional  context  of  the  role.  "Great  leaders"  may 
create  new  roles  or  expand  old  ones;  they  are  likely,  as  Hei!;el 
already  knew,  to  emerge  when  the  societies  they  lead  are  at  points 
of  epochal  structural  transition.  For  then  flexibility  of  role  and 
creative  reactions  to  it  are  most  likely  to  coincide. 

The  possibilities  open  to  the  leader  vary  with  the  flexibility  of 
the  role-demands;  if  they  are  inflexible,  so  long  as  he  stays  within 
the  role  he  must  play  it  as  expected,  although  he  may  fall  short; 
if  the  role  is  flexible,  he  will  have  more  difficulty  meeting  it  exactly, 
less  difficulty  making  the  most  of  it. 

This  scale,  constructed  from  flexibility  of  role  and  reactions  of 
leader,  has  implications  for  the  imagery  of  the  leader:  the  role- 
determining  man,  since  he  modifies  a  received  role  of  decision- 
making, may  be  more  likely,  as  part  of  that  modification,  to  shift 
the  imagery  and  legitimations  of  the  authority  he  wields  than  is 
the  role-determined  man,  who  in  the  extreme  case  finds  an  imagery 
and  legitimations  already  there,  and  merely  continues  to  enact 
their  requirements  along  with  other  features  of  his  receixed  role. 

II.  Modifications  of  Functions  and  Scope  of  Role.  A  social  struc- 
ture is  composed  of  \arious  institutional  orders,  each  objectively 
oriented  to  more  or  less  dominant  ends,  the  political,  economic, 
religious,  kinship,  and  military.  Now,  the  head  of  an  institution 
within  any  order  may  expand  the  scope  of  his  command  by  creat- 
ing new  features  of  his  role  or  creating  viitually  new  roles,  by  ( i ) 
expanding  the  functions  of  the  institution  of  which  he  is  head,  or 
(2)  combining  previously  separate  roles  into  one  head  role,  or  (3) 
by  combining  roles  across  institutional  orders.  The  contrary  is  also 
true :  the  leader  may  shrink  in  scope  and  power  if  ( 1 )  his  insti- 
tution shrinks  in  size  or  leverage  in  the  social  structure,  or  (2)  if 
the  leader's  role  is  split,  or  if  (3)  a  new  institution  arises  to  com- 
pete with  an  old  one. 

Leaders,  then,  who  take  a  role  that  is  instituted  to  ser\e  some 
function  may  modify  the  role,  the  function,  or  both. 

John  L.  Lewis,  as  president  of  the  Committee  on  Industrial 
Organization  within  the  AFL,  increased  the  scope  of  his  role  as 


422.  DYNAMICS 

chairman  and  the  function  of  the  organization,  turning  it  from  a 
Committee  to  a  Congress.  So  did  FrankHn  D.  Roosevelt  as  President 
of  the  United  States:  he  expanded  the  role  of  the  President  as  well 
as  the  function  of  the  executive  branch,  and,  in  fact,  of  the  gov- 
ernment as  a  whole. 

Lenin,  with  his  conception  of  a  party  of  professional  revolution- 
aries, greatly  reduced  mass-oriented  activities,  the  winning  of  mass 
membership  to  the  cause,  in  favor  of  very  strict  standards  for 
smaller  circles  of  full-time  members.  In  this  way,  by  his  party  of 
experts— rather  than  of  experts,  amateurs,  and  sympathizers— he 
centralized  command  in  the  hands  of  professionals,  gained  speed 
in  shifting  strategy  and  tactics,  and  gained  greater  security  for 
conspiratorial  work;   in  short,   greater  revolutionary  efficiency. 

In  the  face  of  an  ever-growing  complexity  of  a  bureaucratic 
state  apparatus  of  experts,  the  absolute  monarch  in  the  early  mod- 
ern period  was  reduced  in  role  to  the  position  of  an  amateur  de- 
pending upon  the  advice  of  his  experts.  The  function  which  he 
served  increased,  but  his  role  was  reduced. 

Finally,  both  function  and  role  may  be  reduced:  the  king  may 
come  to  rule,  but  not  govern;  the  king  of  prerogative  may  be  re- 
duced to  a  king  of  influence,  in  short,  a  figurehead  having  officially 
representative  functions  and,  if  capable,  wielding  unofiicial  influ- 
ence. 

These  expansions  or  contractions  of  function  and  of  roles  may 
come  about  by  the  merging  or  the  splitting  of  existing  roles,  and  in 
either  case,  of  course,  there  may  be  an  increase  or  a  decrease  in 
power: 

If,  for  example,  the  supreme  priest  and  the  emperor  merge  into 
one  role,  as  in  Caesar-papism,  the  new  role  carries  increased  power 
by  the  merger.  So  Peter  the  Great  reorganizes  the  Russian  Church 
and  appoints  the  chairman  of  the  synod;  or  in  modern  coali- 
tion warfare,  a  supreme  command  is  established;  or  the  president 
assumes  war  powers  in  a  "constitutional  dictatorship." 

The  merger  of  roles  may  also  mean  a  decrease  in  power:  in 
wishing  to  do  much,  the  leader  becomes  an  amateur  who  blunders. 
In  different  ways,  both  the  German  Kaiser  as  diplomat  and  Der 
Fiihrer  as  supreme  commander  may  be  examples. 

If  roles  are  split  or  divided  into  specialties,  power  may  increase 
for  one  of  the  roles:  the  most  obvious  case  is  the  creation  of  staff 
roles  and  delegation  to  them  of  various  aspects  of  power  wielding. 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  42,3 

The  role  left  is  that  of  co-ordinating  the  divided  roles.  So  the 
premier,  as  chairman  of  a  cabinet,  presides  over  a  committee  of 
policy  co-ordinating  ministers,  who  in  turn  are  served  by  various 
department  heads.  Specialization  of  functions  in  this  way  is  an 
infinite  variety,  and  forms,  in  fact,  the  major  subject  matter  of  much 
of  descriptive   political   science   and  institutional  sociology. 

Roles  may  also  be  divided  and  their  power  weakened;  for  ex- 
ample, when  empires  are  decentralized  so  that  the  center  is  weak- 
ened—as happened  in  the  rise  of  British  colonies  to  dominions,  or 
Alexander's  governors  to  satraps,  or  repeatedly  in  the  Chinese  em- 
pire in  which  the  original  functionaries  of  the  central  authority 
developed  into  warlords  and  governors  in  their  own  right. 

It  is  worthwhile  to  systematize  such  possibilities  because  to  do 
so  alerts  us  to  the  range  of  role  dynamics  possible  in  any  social- 
historical  situation  we  may  wish  to  analyze.  The  major  point  is 
that  the  leader's  creation  of  roles  can  only  be  understood  in  the 
full  context  of  social-historical  dynamics.  For  the  institutional  con- 
text not  only  provides  an  apparatus  for  leadership,  but  sets  the 
scope  of  the  command  and  modifies  the  reasons  for  men's  alle- 
giance to  it.  The  "great  leader"  has  often  been  a  man  who  has 
managed  such  institutional  dynamics,  and  thus  created  new  roles 
of  leadership. 

The  rise  and  decline  of  institutional  structures  invohe  the  rise 
and  decline  of  leaders.  Thus,  in  the  latter  evolution  of  capitalism, 
the  appointed  manager  of  the  large  corporation  supplants,  in  some 
part,  the  self-made  entrepreneur  of  his  family  enterprise.  And  this 
shift  in  key  economic  institutions,  and  hence  in  their  head  roles, 
ramifies  into  other  institutional  areas— the  political  sphere,  the 
status  hierarchy,  and  even  the  kinship  order,  as  selected  family 
circles  rise  to  the  top. 

When  capitalism  came  to  Japan,  it  came  as  corporate  capitalism, 
without  any  individualistic  epoch;  and  it  found  a  point  of  coinci- 
dence with  already  existing  feudal  kinship  units;  the  leaders  of 
these  top  cousinhoods,  with  their  sib  loyalties,  expanded  their  roles 
to  include  the  management  of  corporate  enterprises. 

In  the  transition  from  peace  to  war,  large  numbers  of  men  are 
transferred  from  economic  and  kinship  institutions  to  the  military 
order.  The  expanding  military  order  tends  to  override  the  demands 
of  other  institutional  orders;  its  symbols  of  legitimation  become 
master  symbols  of  political  decisions,  and  it  borrows  or  appro- 


42.4  DYNAMICS 

priates  the  symbols  of  other  orders,  especially  the  religious  and 
political;  its  leaders  become  more  powerful  in  deciding  the  pace 
and  shape  of  the  total  social  structure.  It  is,  today  especially,  obvi- 
ous that  such  structural  shifts  do  not  guarantee  the  emergence  of 
role-determining  men  adequate  to  the  contextual  demands  and 
opportunities. 

III.  Creation  of  Roles  in  and  out  of  Contexts.  We  may  finally 
consider  whether  or  not  the  leader  creates  the  role  he  plays,  that 
is,  modifies  existing  roles  as  virtually  to  reconstitute  them,  or 
merely  assumes  an  already  existing  role  and  enacts  it  within  the 
generally  expected  limits;  and  whether  the  individual  finds  an 
available  institutional  context  for  his  role,  or  is  limited  in  his 
playing  of  it  to  small  informal  groups,  but  mainly  among  a  pub- 
lic. If  we  combine  these  two,  we  get  three  possible  types  of  leaders: 
A.  the  routine  institutional  head  "the  routineer";  B.  the  creative 
institutional  head  "the  innovator";  and  C.  "the  precursor." 

A.  The  routine  leader  creates  neither  his  role  nor  its  institutional 
context,  but  merely  steps  into  a  pre-existing  setup  containing  the 
lead-role  which  he  plays.  The  role  to  be  played  is  already  avail- 
able and  the  leader  comes  to  it  merely  to  enact  it  within  the  gen- 
erally expected  limits.  Such  leaders  are  usually  formally  or  heredi- 
tarily recruited,  and  need  not  create  loyalties  to  their  leadership, 
for  they  are  already  available  in  the  context  of  the  role  which  is  to 
be  played.  The  leader  may,  of  course,  enact  the  role  rigidly  as  it  is 
set  up.  Or,  he  may,  although  within  the  general  expectations, 
personally  stylize  his  enactment  of  it.  But,  in  general,  the  major 
problem  of  such  leadership  is  the  problem  of  the  recruitment 
pattern. 

B.  The  innovating  leader,  within  an  existing  institutional  con- 
text, creates  a  new  role  and  then  plays  it.  The  leader  here  elabo- 
rates a  role  to  the  point  that  it  no  longer  is  recognizable.  He  may 
expand  it  by  creating  new  features  of  it,  or  by  merging  two  or 
more  existing  roles.  In  either  case,  he  monopolizes  functions  of 
leadership  within  the  existing  context.  He  may  split  an  existing 
role  into  two  and  only  play  one  of  them,  delegating  or  giving  up 
the  other.  Any  number  of  mechanisms  of  creation  are  possible,  and 
any  number  of  reasons  for  their  creation.  He  may  be  figuring  out 
new  ways  to  satisfy  expectations  or  sensed  wants  of  the  group  in 


THE     SOCIOLOGY     OF     LEADERSHIP  42;^ 

context,  or  he  may  create  a  new  role  and  by  so  doing  create  new 
wants  at  the  same  time  as  their  means  of  reahzation.  This  kind 
of  leader  may  be  formally  or  informally  recrnited,  and  he  must 
create  or  transfer  the  loyalties  of  the  led  to  the  new  role  w  hich  he 
has  created  for  himself. 

C.  The  leader  as  precursor  creates  a  role,  but  there  is  no  insti- 
tutional opportunity  for  him  to  play  it.  So  Thomas  Miinzer,  left- 
wing  leader  of  German  Protestantism,  is  to  be  hailed  later  by  Marx 
and  Engels  as  a  visionary  of  communism.  So  Rousseau  remains  a 
leader  only  in  symbolic  context  with  publics,  for  the  time  is  not 
yet  ripe  for  action. 

Such  leaders  are  usually  self-appointed  and  their  performance 
of  their  roles  as  decision-making  leaders  is  imaginary.  They  are 
preparing  themselves,  by  pre-enactment,  for  the  day  when  appro- 
riate  contexts  may  be  available.  By  those  who  "take  readily  to 
existing  roles,"  many  such  men  are  judged  as  crazy,  or  at  least  out 
of  joint  with  their  times.  But  such  internal  preparation  is  often 
part  of  the  leadership  phenomenon  of  the  prophet  type.  If  they 
are  successful  as  leaders,  they  come  in  time  to  represent  to  smaller 
inner  circles  and  later  to  larger  publics  and  then  to  movements  and 
parties,  certain  values  or  models  to  be  imitated  and  with  which 
to  identify.  In  the  meantime,  they  are  abstracted  from  such  con- 
texts and  are  leaders  only  in  their  own  minds,  and  symbolically, 
but  not  in  terms  of  power,  to  publics  who  hold  images  of  the  man 
with  the  new  role  he  cannot  yet  play  as  a  symbol  of  a  context  not 
yet  existing.  Such  leaders  are  of  course  self-recruited  and  must 
create  loyalties  among  those  they  would  lead. 

It  follows  from  this  scheme,  as  well  as  from  our  descriptions  of 
the  several  contexts  of  leadership  that,  if  we  would  understand 
any  given  leadership  phenomenon,  the  following  are  important 
questions  to  raise: 

1.  Context:  In  what  context  does  the  leader  arise?  How  is  it 
structured?  Did  this  particular  man  "create"  it  by  modifications 
of  existing  contexts,  or  did  he  simply  become  a  leader  in  it  as  it 
existed? 

2.  Role:  What  are  the  salient  traits  of  his  role  as  a  leader?  In 
what  social  orders  and  spheres  does  he  lead  others?— only  in  opin- 
ion, or  in  activity  as  well?  Did  he  invent  this  role?  \Miat  modifi- 


426  DYNAMICS 

cations,  if  any,  has  he  made  in  it,  and  how?  Has  he  elaborated  it  as 
he  received  it,  constricted  its  scope,  amalgamated  other  roles  with 
it? 

3.  Man:  How  did  this  man  come  to  be  in  this  role?  How  was  he 
recruited  for  it?  What  character  traits  were  relevant  to  his  assum- 
ing or  inventing  this  role?  What  traits  are  relevant  to  his  continu- 
ing to  enact  this  role? 

4.  Images:  What  images  do  those  he  leads  have  of  him  as  man 
and  as  a  leader?  Why  do  they  obey  him?  What  techniques  does  he 
use  to  diffuse  this  image,  these  legitimations? 


CHAPTER 

X  V 

Collective  Behavior 


NO  ONE  observing  the  awful  turbulence  of  twentieth-century 
history  can  believe  that  all  human  affairs  are  neatly  contained 
within  institutions,  or  that  existing  institutional  orders  necessarily 
endure.  Wars  and  revolutions  have  turned  over  social  structures; 
dictators  have  risen  and  fallen  within  great  nations,  and  even 
within  regions  of  great  nations.  Masses  of  men— as  well  as  small 
conspiratorial  groups,  alienated  from  institutions,  and  living,  for  a 
while,  outside  stable  and  stabilizing  institutional  structures— have 
smashed  whole  societies,  and  promptly  built  vast  new  domains. 
In  various  ways,  in  various  countries,  some  periods  of  history 
have  seemed  to  proceed  by  plots,  others  by  polemics.  And  now  no 
one  can  believe  that  all  social  conduct  is  ordered  within  institu- 
tions, or  that  what  is  now  instituted  has  always  been  or  always 
will  be. 

Within  and  between  institutional  orders  and  their  spheres  is  the 
problem  area  known  loosely  to  sociologists  as  "collecti\'e  behavior," 
which,  in  current  usage,  includes  everything  from  totalitarian  one- 
party  states  to  the  ephemeral  mob  that  hangs  a  colored  man  for 
allegedly  looking  too  closely  at  a  white  woman;  from  quiet  little 
groups  of  neighbors  who  go  bowling  together,  to  religious  sects  and 
to  fads  that  appear  and  disappear  in  Southern  California. 

There  is  no  problem  area  for  which  both  deficits  and  assets  have 
been  so  often  remarked.  If  this  area  contains  "mass  phenomena" 
associated  with  the  breakdown  of  social  order— hysterical  rages  and 
euphoric  ecstasies,  during  which  men  act  as  they  never  did  before 
and  never  will  again— it  also  contains  those  associations  which  are 
acknowledged  to  be  major  seedbeds  of  free  men  of  Western 
nations. 

The  prototype  of  modern  voluntary  associations,  as  Max  Weber 


428  DYNAMICS 

has  shown,  is  the  Protestant  sect,  which  is  "a  union  of  specifically 
qualified  people"  rather  than  an  established  and  compulsory  insti- 
tution. Such  associations,  when  secularized  and  difl^used  in  various 
strata,  form  a  pluralist  field  of  units  within  and  between  which 
the  individual,  for  his  own  self-esteem,  must  "put  himself  over." 
In  the  process  of  doing  so,  he  is  naturally  stamped  by  the  values 
and  models  carried  by  the  associations.  In  such  free  associations, 
moreover,  the  individual  can  obtain  his  anchorage  and  make  his 
stand  against  "majority  domination."  And  in  these  smaller  circles 
there  occurs  a  social  selection  and  training  of  leaders  for  larger 
tasks. 

1.  The  Structural  Contexts  of  Collective  Behavior 

The  range  of  phenomena  in  this  area  may  best  be  stated  in  terms 
of  the  degree  of  explicit  organization:  at  one  end  of  the  scale  there 
are  what  appear  to  be  purely  spontaneous  activities;  at  the  other, 
there  is  a  merging  of  "collective  behavior"  with  institutional  or- 
ganization itself.  Ephemeral  crowds  spontaneously  releasing  a 
pent-up  tension,  as  well  as  tightly  organized  class  and  status  parties 
calculatedly  making  their  way  within  and  between  major  insti- 
tutional blocs;  a  barely  discernible  drift  from  year  to  year  in  the 
shade  of  lipstick  color,  the  shift  in  the  atmosphere  of  street  throngs, 
as  well  as  the  farm  bloc  representative  arguing  and  entertaining- 
all  these  belong  to  the  domain  of  "collective  behavior." 

Some  of  these  phenomena  are  already  institutions  in  the  same 
sense  as  a  family  or  a  church;  others  do  not  display  such  struc- 
tural characteristics  at  all.  But  as  we  examine  such  activities  and 
social  forms  over  longer  spans  of  time,  there  does  seem  to  be  a 
sort  of  drift  exhibited  by  all  collective  behavior,  if  it  endures  be- 
yond the  momentary,  towards  institutionalization.  Furthermore,  all 
forms  of  collective  behavior,  no  matter  how  momentary,  are  related 
to  various  institutional  orders  and  spheres:  they  cannot  be  ex- 
plained without  reference  to  them.  For  institutional  structures  are 
the  precipitants  and  the  foci  of  collective  behavior  of  every  sort; 
they  are  the  larger  frameworks  within  which  such  behavior  arises 
and  through  which  it  runs  its  course. 

But  this  does  not  mean  that  collective  behavior  does  not  modify 
(sometimes,  as  in  revolution,  grievously)  the  institutional  struc- 
.ture.  It  does  mean  that  the  interplay  must  always  be  closely  exam- 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  42Q 

ined,  and  the  specific  contributions  to  history  of  structural  shifts 
as  well  as  of  the  more  fluid,  amorphous  forms  of  social  dynamics 
carefully  weighed.  It  is  not  fruitful,  as  we  have  already  noted,  to 
conceive  of  social  structures  as  somehow  inert  and  static,  and  of 
collective  behavior  as  providing  the  dynamic.  Such  a  conception, 
in  fact,  is  a  triple  misconception:  of  the  nature  of  structural  change, 
of  collective  behavior,  and  of  the  typical  relations  between  the  two. 

It  is  in  epochs  of  transition,  like  that  of  the  waning  Middle  Ages 
or  of  the  French  and  Russian  revolutions  that  the  established 
institutions  of  society  lose  their  hold  over  their  members.  In- 
ternally, pressures  seem  to  pile  up,  and  externally  misgi\  ings  and 
public  criticisms  are  rife.  Codes  and  norms  are  no  longer  accepted 
unreflectively  and  without  dispute,  and  to  an  increasing  number 
of  persons  they  may  pro\  e  to  be  unworkable. 

Every  society  in  such  decline  provides  us  with  the  indexes  of 
its  coming  apart.  When  the  privileged  feudal  nobles  of  Europe 
closed  their  ranks  by  demanding  more  rigid  tests  of  "blue  blood" 
descent;  when  the  guilds  jealously  closed  their  master  positions 
against  the  increasing  pressure  of  journeymen  and  apprentices, 
by  demanding  a  "masterpiece"  and  by  adding  an  obligatory  year 
of  itineracy;  when  there  were  not  sufficient  churches  to  absorb  the 
students  of  theology  who,  as  intellectual  vagrants,  joined  the  itiner- 
ant artisans;  when  the  various  intellectual  groups  organized  by 
"nations"  at  medieval  universities  engaged  in  heightened  group 
competition  for  church  prebends— then  established  institutional  ar- 
rangements were  on  the  decline. 

Although  the  specific  indexes  of  disintegration  vary  by  societies, 
all  such  epochs  of  transition  may  be  formally  characterized  b\-  the 
fact  that  old  institutional  orders,  for  a  variety  of  reasons,  lose  their 
hold  over  their  members.  Conduct  deviates  from  the  sanctioned 
norms,  and  newer  ways  of  doing  things  are  no  longer  felt  to  be 
sinful  or  criminal.  In  fact,  quite  a  few  men  may  accept  the  new  as 
the  only  possible  way  of  getting  things  done.  Uninstitiited  or  loosely 
instituted  men  make  their  appearance  but  find  no  place  in  the  old 
order.  Old  ways  of  conduct  with  their  conventional,  legal,  and 
ideological  elaborations  are  available  to  fewer  people,  and  those 
who  cannot  follow  these  ways  lose  their  stake  in  the  old  order,  and 
with  it  they  lose  their  identifications  and  loyalties,  without,  how- 
ever, promptly  finding  new  ones.  Such  social  transitions  may  be 
long  endured,  or  passed  through  swiftly. 


430  DYNAMICS 

Western  medieval  society  knew  a  partial  breakdown  of  its  insti- 
tuted ways  during  the  pestilence,  and  during  the  threatened  con- 
quest, when  Mongolian  armies  penetrated  to  the  gates  of  Vienna, 
and  disciplined  men  on  swift  horses  struck  terror  to  Christian 
hearts.  Since  these  times  the  word  "horde"  has  remained  in  all 
Western  languages.  It  is  during  such  periods  of  transition— when 
old  institutions  break  down  and  new  ones  are  not  yet  available— 
that  mass  movements  and  collective  forms  of  behavior  are  likely  to 
appear.  In  them  and  in  terms  of  them  new  forms  of  organization, 
of  leadership,  and  of  conduct  are  developed.  So  there  is  the  en- 
lightenment movement  of  the  Renaissance,  the  North  Alpine  Ref- 
ormation, the  emergence  of  the  counterreformation  of  Catholic 
revivalism.  And,  in  this  broad  perspective,  is  not  our  time  of  wars, 
revolutions,  and  slumps  comparable? 

In  such  periods  sensitive  minds  usually  experience  stress  and 
strain,  and  formulate  problems  long  before  broad  masses  of  men 
experience  them  consciously  or  act  collectively  in  response  to  the 
mounting  tensions  accompanying  what  Weber  called  "times  of 
distress"  or  Emile  Durkheim  called  "anomy,"  that  is,  a  state  of 
"normlessness."  Then  occurs  in  intellectual  circles  trial  and  error, 
criticism  and  countercriticism,  self-searching  and  doubt,  skepticism 
and  enlightenment,  desperate  attempts  to  revive  and  to  reaffirm 
what  proves  in  the  end  to  be  outlived  and  hollow.  Words  and  deeds 
fail  to  jibe,  and  boredom  overcomes  many  who  feel  weary  of  vm- 
inspiring  days.  Others  crave  forgetfulness  and  intoxication,  and 
still  others  see  the  day  of  judgment  on  a  sinful  age  which  thus 
comes  to  its  doom. 

The  most  ambitious  effort,  since  Le  Bon,^  to  use  concepts  of  col- 
lective behavior  in  an  explanatory  way  is  that  of  the  late  Emil 
Lederer,  who  sought  to  interpret  nazism  as  "an  attempt  to  melt 
society  down  to  a  crowd."  -  For  him  society  is  organized  into  a 
pluralism  of  interested  groups,  each  of  which  is  more  or  less 
homogeneous  and  thus  partial,  yet  capable,  especially  if  small,  of 
supporting  reasoned  opinions  and  reasonable  actions.  But  the  crowd 
or  mass  is  amorphous,  emotional,  given  to  sudden  outbursts;  it  is 
not  articulated  but  fragmented,  and  it  is  without  goals  of  its  own. 

1  Gustave  Le  Bon,  The  Crowd  (new  ed.;  New  York:  Macmillan,  1925). 
-  The  State  of  the  Masses  (New  York:  Norton,  1940),  see  especially  pp.  28, 
45,  50,  and  66. 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  4^1 

Hence  it  is  ideal  material  for  strong  leaders  and  is,  in  fact,  accord- 
ing to  Lederer,  for  nazism  the  "permanent  basis  of  a  political 
system."  Before  our  times,  up  to  1914,  the  economic  theory  of  his- 
tory, Emil  Lederer  believed,  was  approximately  correct:  political 
orders  corresponded  in  due  course  to  economic  de\elopmcnt,  classes 
were  the  units  of  history-making;  and  groups  rather  than  individ- 
uals entered  the  nineteenth-century  political  order.  The  "present 
crisis,"  however,  "is  not  a  manifestation  of  class  struggle  but  a  sub- 
stitution for  society  of  institutionalized  masses,"  at  the  center  of 
which  is  a  corps  of  violent  gangs  who  turn  all  discussion  groups  into 
demonstrative  political  crowds.  These  crowds,  in  turn,  have  no 
tradition  and  no  connection  with  other  parties;  they  dominate  the 
streets,  and  as  they  mass  the  citizenry  they  dominate  the  politi- 
cal minds  of  men  and  women.  So,  the  real  opposites  today  are 
"states  based  on  stratified  society"  (which  may  be  "progressive" 
or  "reactionary"),  and  "states  based  on  masses."  In  this  view  there 
was  in  nazism  only  amorphous  mass  and  ruling  party,  and  no  other 
structures. 

This  theory,  which  we  believe  mistaken,  confuses  the  deliberate 
breaking  up  of  autonomous  associations  standing  between  the  state 
and  the  various  strata  of  a  society  with  the  dissolution  of  such  a 
society  into  a  mass.  It  overlooks  the  continuing  fact  of  propertied 
classes  in  German  society  and  their  strengthening  by  Nazi  policies. 
It  is  true  that  strata  and  organizations,  especially  those  of  labor, 
were  smashed  and  atomized,  but  this  was  accomplished  by  bu- 
reaucracies which  prowled  out  from  the  top,  intervening  to  co- 
ordinate almost  every  institutional  order  and  sphere,  and  regi- 
menting voluntary  associations  into  compulsory  cartels  and  "Labor 
Fronts."  Each  of  these  sectors  was  controlled  by  reliable  party 
personnel  in  charge  of  a  thoroughly  organized,  propagandized, 
and  terrorized  society.  Whatever  spontaneity  or  "sudden  out- 
breaks" occurred  were  less  a  result  of  spontaneity  than  of  the 
managed  or  manipulated  discharge  of  mass  fears  and  trained 
hatreds  under  the  oppressive  weight  of  the  ruling  structure  which 
thus  consolidated  its  domination  and  ensnared  the  underlying 
population.^ 

Adequate  explanation  of  "collective  behavior"  usually  requires 
that  we  pay  attention  to  three  sorts  of  phenomena:  (A)  the  larger 

^  For  an  excellent  criticism  of  Emil  Lederer,  see  Franz  Neumann,  Behemoth 
(New   York:    Oxford,    1942)^  P-   365  ff- 


43^  DYNAMICS 

framework  of  institutional  structure;  (B)  the  more  or  less  struc- 
tured and  managed  associations,  movements,  or  parties;  and  (C) 
collective  behavior  on  its  own  "spontaneous  level. " 

2.  Aggregates,  Crowds,  and  Publics 

Ever  since  Le  Bon,  the  term  "masses"  has  been  used  to  cover  a 
great  variety  of  processes  and  phenomena,  and  accordingly  its 
meaning  is  not  always  clear.  In  various  forms  and  with  various 
qualifications,  Le  Bon's  ideas  have  been  used  by  Ortega  y  Gasset,* 
Emil  Lederer,  E.  A.  Ross,^  and  Karl  Mannheim,  as  well  as  a  host 
of  less  eminent  writers.  Such  terms  as  "mass  society"  or  "mass 
movement,"  "mass  media"  or  "mass  publics,"  "mass  sales"  or  "mass 
demonstrations,"  "mass  orgies"  or  "mass  spectacles,"  and  so  on, 
are  indicative  of  the  very  wide  range  of  phenomena  covered.  We 
shall  use  the  term  "mass"  simply  to  signify  large  numbers  of  men, 
and  distinguish,  for  convenience,  aggregates,  crowds,  mobs,  and 
publics. 

I.  When  people  exhibit  like  behavior,  when  they  "go  in  various 
directions"  and  do  not  share  any  goal,  we  may  speak  of  an  aggre- 
gate, or  of  an  aggregation.  Aggregates,  as  in  a  street  scene, 
are  simply  people  in  the  same  locality  but  not  in  communication 
or  live  contact  with  one  another;  such  regularities  as  they  display 
are  due  to  common  stimuli,  such  as  stoplights  or  signals  of  police- 
men. 

Among  these  there  is  no  joint  or  common  motivation,  no  lead- 
ership, no  common  focus  of  attention,  no  sense  of  cohesion  bind- 
ing them  together.  Thus  do  automobile  drivers  return  on  Sunday 
evening  to  the  big  city,  or  masses  of  women  go  shopping  during 
the  seasonal  sales  or  holidays,  or  masses  of  employees  go  to  work 
or  leave  for  home  in  the  daily  ebb  and  flow  of  the  metropolis. 
Everybody  acts  for  himself,  competing  for  scarce  parking  space 
and  economic  bargains,  and  all  these  aggregates  of  drivers  and 
shoppers,  commuters  and  transients— by  their  parallel  behavior— 

*  Jose  Ortega  y  Gasset,  Tlie  Revolt  of  the  Masses  (London:   Allen,   1932). 
^  See   his   great   books,   Social  Control   (New   York:    Macniillan,    1904)    and 
Social  Psychology   (New  York:    Maemillan,    1908). 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  4^3 

exhibit  uniformities  of  conduct  to  which  traffic  regulations,  adver- 
tising campaigns,  radio  warnings,  and  so  on,  address  themselves. 

II.  When  such  aggregates,  in  physical  proximity,  find  a  common 
focus  of  attention  they  may  become  a  "crowd"  or  a  "mob."  Thus 
crowds  of  spectators  gather  around  the  scene  of  a  traffic  accident, 
or  form  casual  audiences  around  Sunday  speakers  in  Hyde  Park, 
or  slowly  mill  in  the  streets,  watching  mobs  (which  are  crowds  in 
action)  of  hoodlums  beat  up  Negroes  in  "race  riots,"  or  watching 
stormtroopers  and  Hitler  Youth  details  hunt  down  and  beat  up 
Jews  in  Berlin's  boulevard  cafes.  In  such  situations,  the  focused 
attention  of  the  massed  spectators  readily  lead  to  shared  responses, 
ranging  from  the  encouragement  of  mob  activities,  through  sullen 
silences,  to  hisses  and  boos  of  protest. 

The  people  in  a  crowd  are  in  contact  with  one  another,  but 
usually  in  a  random  way:  they  are  unco-ordinated  and  mill  about. 
Mobs  are  crowds  that  are  actixely  oriented  by  emblems  or  slogans 
to  some  goal.  Crowds  as  such  have  no  shared  ends,  no  leaders; 
mobs  are  crowds  that  are  incited  to  specific  action  by  self-appointed 
leaders  or  "rabble-rousing"  shouters.  Such  spontaneous  collecti\  ities 
seemingly  represent  ephemeral,  transient  outbreaks  of  tension. 
They  provide  outlets  and  targets  for  psychic  forces  not  placed 
socially  in  a  more  usually  legitimated  ways. 

Back  of  the  crowd,  and  especially  of  the  mob,  there  is  the  larger 
social  context,  which  usuallv  generates  conflicts,  hatreds,  fears,  and 
tensions,  to  which  the  mob  now  gives  vent.  Old  expectations  guid- 
ing the  usual  role  conduct  of  the  members  have  temporarily  col- 
lapsed, and  the  mutual,  immediate  expectations  of  the  crowd  are 
focused,  or  even  fixed,  upon  the  leader,  who  thus  takes  o\'er.  This 
is  more  easily  accomplished  if  the  usual  roles  and  expectations  of 
the  more  routine  areas  of  life  become  ambivalent  or  surcharged 
with  psychic  and  emotional  elements. 

Mobs  may  act  before  friendly  or  before  hostile  crowds  of  on- 
lookers. Accordingly,  the  relationships  between  acti\e  mobs  and 
spectator  crowds  vary  greatly.  Mobs  may  emerge  spontaneously 
from  an  excited  and  milling  crowd  when  self-appointed  leaders 
incite  the  crowd  to  action.  Usually  in  such  cases,  mobs  of  youths 
come  to  the  fore  and  in  a  loose  gang  formation  swing  into  action. 
A  broadening  field  of  many  gangs  and  mobs  may  come  to  the 


434  DYNAMICS 

fore,  under  the  eyes  of  wildly  cheering  masses  of  spectator  crowds. 
Again  organized  gangs  like  those  of  the  Russian  Black  Hundred 
or  the  Hitler  Youth  may  terrorize  the  community  by  their  program 
activities,  and  attract  crowds  of  more  or  less  friendly,  more  or 
less  excited,  spectators  who  may  themselves  be  drawn  into  the 
fury  of  sadistic  street  terrorism.^"^ 

There  is  a  fluid  transition  between  the  aggregate  masses  of  men 
in  the  street,  the  spectator  crowds,  and  the  wildly  moving  mobs 
which  may  emerge  spontaneously  or  who  may  follow  the  lead  of 
organized  terrorist  squads  under  central  direction.  In  our  century 
we  are  no  strangers  to  the  mob  directed  from  radio-equipped  staff 
cars  and  motorcyclists  who  provide  disciplined  cohesion  for  active 
knots  of  scattered  people  throughout  metropolitan  areas.  In  such 
cases,  running  battles  with  the  police,  swift  changes  of  the  point  of 
attack,  retreats  and  provocative  feints,  a  devastating,  simultaneous 
sweeping  down  on  carefully  mapped-out  targets  in  selected  cities 
throughout  a  nation— what  all  this  reveals  is  a  virtually  warlike 
discipline.  So  in  the  November  days  of  1938  in  Nazi  Germany 
were  synagogues  burned,  Jewish  businesses  destroyed  and  looted, 
and  Jewish  homes  raided.  The  intermingling  of  collective  behavior 
and  officially  organized  action,  of  cloaking  the  machine-organized 
terrorism  by  alleging  that  irresponsible  mob  activities,  motivated 
by  "righteous  indignation,"  is  the  cause— is  revealed  in  Goebbel's 
contradictory  formula:  "the  organized  spontaneity  of  the  people." 

The  mobilization  of  massed  aggregates  for  less  violent  action 
may  also  be  a  response  to  the  policies  of  specific  institutions.  Thus 
the  shopping  sprees  and  bargain  counter  crushes  of  metropolitan 
housewives  are  responses  to  advertised  sales.  The  rush  hour  traffic 
of  millions  of  employees  are  results  of  the  definition  of  the  working 
day  in  factory  and  office;  the  rush  of  the  voters  to  the  polls  results 
from  the  definition  of  voting  times  and  the  exhortations  of  political 
parties  and  mass  media.  Thus,  the  policies  of  various  institutions 
-religious,  political,  economic-are  likely  to  call  forth  unorganized, 
although  patterned,  mass  behavior  of  predictable  volume  and  regu- 
larity. 

5A  Chicago  Commission  on  Race  Relations,  The  Negro  in  Chicago  ( Chicago, 
1922);  Gerald  Brenan,  The  Spanish  Labyrinth  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1944); 
Franz  Borkeneau,  The  Spanish  Cockpit  (London:  Faber,  1937)- 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  ^35 

III.  Publics  are  composed  of  people  who  are  not  in  face  to  face 
relation  but  who  ne\'ertheless  display  similar  interests,  or  are 
exposed  to  similar,  although  more  or  less  distant,  stimuli.  The 
public  of  a  leader  may  be  the  only  context  of  his  leadership;  he 
offers  himself,  or  at  any  rate  is  available,  as  a  symbolic  model.  The 
best  formal  definition  of  the  political  public  is  that  recently  given 
by  Hans  Speier:  a  public  exists  whenever  people  outside  a  gov- 
ernment have  the  right  to  give  public  advice  and  criticism  to  the 
gONernment.*^ 

This  obviously  ties  the  concept  in  with  the  notion  of  institu- 
tional structure,  specifically  with  the  state.  The  leader  in  such  a 
context  is  one  who  can  mediate,  as  it  were,  between  public  and 
state.  Such  leaders  often  coincide  or  are  closely  related  to  leaders 
of  movements  and  parties. 

But  there  is  a  distinction  between  three  types  of  public  which 
we  must  recognize,  especially  in  view  of  the  rise  of  mass  media  of 
communication  and  the  frequent  impossibility  of  realizing  in  fact 
the   formal  right  stated  in   Speier's   definition: 

( 1 )  In  simpler,  early-modern  times,  the  public  might  be  ade- 
quately imagined  as  a  "primary  public":  circles  of  people  in  dis- 
cussion with  one  another.  This  is  what  the  older  literature  of  pub- 
lic opinion— using  the  term  as  a  legitimation  of  democratic  forms 
of  go\ernment— meant  by  "the  public":  discussion  groups  con- 
fronted by  issues.  And  it  is  further  imagined  that  for  e\ery  li\e 
issue  there  is  a  self-activated  public.  The  leaders  of  such  a  public 
are  informal  "opinion  leaders"  who  guide  opinion  in  their  informal 
spheres,  refract  media  communications  to  others,  and  make  legiti- 
mate the  influences  from  other  sources. 

Speier,  in  his  definition,  has  tried  to  save  this  aspect  of  the 
notion  of  public  at  a  time  when  democratic  institutions  are  exter- 
nally under  attack  and  internally  decaying.  He  does  this  In-  ex- 
plicitly linking  the  notion  of  public  to  the  power  structure,  and 
more  importantly  by  formalizing  the  conception  of  public  in  a 
statement  of  a  right  rather  than  of  a  going  fact.  This  becomes 
clear  when  we  seriously  ask,  \\'ho  can  lead  public  opinion  today? 
What  are  its  leaders  like?  What  are  their  chances  to  fulfill  the  role 
assigned  to  them  by  this  definition? 

(2)  At  other  times,  such  public  as  exists  seems  to  be  adequately 
described  as  a  set  of  "media  markets":  people  reached  more  or  less 

<^  Social  Order  and  the  Riska  of  War  (New  York:  Stewart,  1952),  p.  323. 


43^  DYNAMICS 

regularly  by  a  given  medium  of  communication.  On  such  markets, 
no  informal  leadership  as  in  the  primary  public  seems  possible: 
the  only  "leaders"  who  can  arise  in  this  context  are  those  in  charge 
of  or  with  ready  access  to  the  mass  channels  of  communication. 
(3)  Moreover,  as  we  know  from  totalitarian  societies,  the  older 
primary  publics  may  be  infiltrated  and  regimented  by  organizations. 
From  the  aggregate  activities  of  multitudes  of  migrants  and  spec- 
tators, buyers  and  sellers,  voters  and  readers  and  radio  listeners— 
we  may  distinguish  mass  audiences  and  mass  publics  recruited  by 
the  sale  of  tickets  of  admission.  If  such  mass  organizations  as  trade 
unions,  book  clubs,  educational  institutions,  army  units,  churches, 
parties,  or  civic  organizations  "book  the  show"  or  sponsor  the  pub- 
lication, we  may  speak  of  "organized  publics  and  audiences."  This 
pattern  would  seem  to  be  on  the  ascendancy  in  industrial  nations 
during  the  twentieth  century.  A  whole  technique  of  "audience 
building"  has  emerged.  The  availability  of  masses  at  factories  and 
in  office  buildings  and  public  conveyances  provides  opportunities 
to  co-operate  with  religious  or  political  or  cultural  organizations, 
by  offering  employees  or  passengers  as  "captive  audiences."  In 
totalitarian  regimes  this  availability  of  people  in  masses  is  seized 
upon  by  the  ruling  party  during  propaganda  campaigns  to  regiment 
crowds  to  demonstrations,  to  endorse  government  policies  by  plebis- 
cite and  to  discipline  men  to  follow  th6  party  line.  The  techniques 
Americans  know  as  commercial  advertising  have  been  centralized 
and  co-ordinated  by  the  single-party  state,  which  thus— through  its 
mass  organizations,  publicly  owned  enterprises,  collective  farms, 
public  carriers  and  conveyances,  mass  media,  schools,  and  ubiqui- 
tous "agitators"— reaches  into  every  nook  and  cranny  of  the  social 
structure. 

What  happens  to  men  in  crowds  and  mobs? 

Negatively,  the  norms  and  motives  which  they  have  incorporated 
as  features  of  their  instituted  roles  collapse.  If  this  is  complete,  or 
at  least  extreme,  the  result  is  panic  or  ecstasy.  Internally,  the  gen- 
eralized other  no  longer  works  as  it  did,  and,  in  extreme,  the  person 
is  unavailable.  Out  of  fear  or  out  of  ecstatic  joy,  man  is  "beyond 
himself."  This  is  the  key  psychological  meaning  of  "anomy"— 
the  situation  of  normlessness. 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  ^;^y 

Positively,  behavior  is  then  more  open  to  two  sources:  the  eon- 
tents  of  the  unconscious  become  the  leading  predispositions,'  and 
the  individual  is  sensitized  to  others  immediately  around  him. 
The  established  person— in  short,  the  more  routine  seH-images  and 
conscience— are  minimized;  the  features  of  the  psychic  structure, 
maximized.  Mass  panic  is  thus  the  extreme  opposite  of  institutional 
order.  And  if  we  take  seriously  the  term  "crisis,"  as  applied  to 
institutional  orders,  we  mean  a  collapse  sufficient  to  put  men  into 
panic. 

Now,  movements  may  accomplish  the  same  process  as  crowds, 
but  more  gradually;  it  is,  in  fact,  within  the  context  of  a  continuing 
movement  or  party  that  crowd  phenomena  are  more  likely  to  oc- 
cur, and  when  occurring,  to  have  more  lasting  psychological  ef- 
fects. Many  collective  phenomena  which  appear  "spontaneous"  may 
in  reality  be  adroitly  managed  or  manipulated,  and  all  of  them, 
in  their  causal  explanation,  rest  in  one  way  or  another  upon  going 
institutional  structures. 

Men  in  power,  especially  if  they  obtained  institutional  power 
by  means  of  a  movement  in  which  the  masses  played  a  part,  may 
try  to  keep  them,  as  J.  B.  S.  Hardman  put  it,"  "in  a  state  of  sus- 
pended mobility,  immune  to  the  solicitations  of  the  opposition  and 
yet  potentially"  ready,  when  necessary,  to  support  the  authority. 
Contenders  for  power  and  office  appeal  to  the  aggregate  masses 
(which  as  such  have  no  common  goals  or  loyalties)  in  an  effort  to 
identify  themselves  with  the  interests  and  sentiments  of  the  masses, 
and  at  the  same  time  to  bargain  with  or  threaten  concessions  out 
of  existing  authorities.  Masses  may  be  transformed  from  "a  state 
of  passive,  if  intensely  nervous,  suspension  to  one  of  aggressive 
activism  .  .  .  ,"  into  not  a  mob  but  the  Violent  yet  structured  point 
of  action  for  a  movement  that  has  prepared  for  the  day  and  hour. 

On  the  other  hand,  when  the  structural  framework  is  weak, 
crowd  behavior  may  even  shape  the  policies  of  instituted  leaders. 
Thus,  of  one  of  the  crises  in  the  Middle  East  during  the  early 
fifties,  Anne  O'Hare  McCormick  wrote  that  foreign  policy  is  now 
being  made  in  the  streets. 

^  See    Sigmund    Freud,    Group    PsycJiology    and    tlic    Analysis   of   the    Ego, 
J.  Strachey,  tr.  (London:  Internation  Psycho-analytical  Press,  1922),  p.  9  ff . 
s  "Masses,"  Encyclopaedia  of  the  Social  Sciences,  Vol.  X,  pp.  198  and  200. 


438  DYNAMICS 

3.  Movements,  VaHies,  and  Pressure  Groups 

No  one  has  yet  classified  in  an  adequate  way  all  those  types  of 
voluntary  institutions  or  associations,  which  lie  between  the  family 
on  the  one  hand  and  the  state  and  alliances  of  states  on  the  other. 
But  it  does  seem,  as  we  have  already  indicated,  that  it  is  in  this 
zone  that  leadership  of  the  most  interesting  sort  arises.^  It  arises 
here  because  this  context  permits  the  invention  of  leader  roles  and 
the  expansion  of  the  scope  of  existing  roles  by  leaders.  Here  we 
find  the  attempts  to  co-ordinate,  in  Nazi-like  manner,  by  inter- 
locking memberships  and  the  infiltration  of  leaders  into  key  roles  of 
other  voluntary  institutions.  Here  we  find  parties  that  are  the  or- 
gans of  a  movement  becoming  so  dominating  as  to  eliminate  other 
parties,  and  turn  the  movement  into  an  extension  and  instrument 
of  the  party.  Here  we  find  several  movements  represented  in  one 
party,  as  in  major  political  parties  of  the  United  States;  as  well  as 
several  parties  within  one  movement,  as  in  European  labor  move- 
ments. Obviously  such  intricate  overlapping  provides  opportimi- 
ties  for  modification  of  roles  and  functions  at  the  hands  of  those 
who  would  lead. 

(a  movement  attempts  to  change  institutions,  from  the  outside, 
from  the  inside,  or  from  bothj  Like  institutions,  movements  are  or- 
ganized enough  to  permit  a  turnover  of  members  without  loss  of 
identity  as  movements,  and  their  members  are  more  or  less  aware 
of  themselves  as  having  common  interests  and/or  principles./  It 
recruits  members,  usually  from  selected  class  and  status  levels, 
who  are  more  or  less  ready  to  act  in  certain  ways,  and  it  lends  to 
them  its  orienting  aim:  in  some  way  to  change  some  institutional 
setup.)  Whether  based  on  interest,  on  principle,  or  on  both,  people 
are  united  in  voluntary  associations  in  a  more  or  less  energetic 
struggle  for  power,  which,  so  far  as  the  leadership  is  concerned, 
means  power  of  an  instituted  sort  for  the  leaders. 

There  are  many  variations  and  overlaps  between  movements, 
parties,  and  pressure  groups;  clean-cut  definitions  are  more  likely 
to  be  arbitrary  limitations  than  helpful  descriptions. (Party  pro- 
grams,] Heberle  comments,^"!  are  more  likely  to  consider  several 

'•>  We  have  discussed  this  in  Chapter  XIV:  The  Sociology  of  Leadership,  Sec- 
tion 4:  Contexts  and  Roles. 

1"  Rudolf  Heberle,  Social  Movements  (New  York:  Appleton-Century-Crofts, 
1951)- 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  439 

important  issues;  pressure  groups,  only  limited,  specific  issues) 
(i^arties,)  as  Schattschneider  puts  it,^^  (try  to  mobilize  majorities^ 
^jressure  groups  to  organize  minorities/)  Such  a  distinction  seems 
more  or  less  adequate  for  Anglo-Saxon  countries,  but  not  for  move- 
ments such  as  the  Catholic  center  party  in  Germany,  which  as  a 
principled  "minority  party"  had  no  chance  to  win  a  "majority" 
and  hardly  was  so  optimistic  as  to  feel  that  such  aspirations  made 
sense:  they  never  polled  more  than  20  per  cent  and  generally  hov- 
ered around  15  per  cent  of  the  total  vote. 

There  may  exist  strict  "class  parties"  who  advance  merely  their 
specialized  demands,  attract  only  a  following  of  special  interests 
and  orient  their  platform  only  to  them,  and  without  any  particular 
ideological  generalities  for  a  "cloak";  otherwise  they  are  organized 
like  any  other  party  with  parliamentary  party,  machine,  and  press. 
Schattschneider  in  his  definition  unduly  generalizes  the  United 
States  model,  which  in  many  ways  is  unique.  There  have  been 
special  status  group  parties— in  Hungary,  Austria,  and  Germany— 
of  agrarian  nobles,  who  proudly  called  themselves  small  but  strong. 

Moreover  (if  one  wishes  to  speak  of  "majorities-minorities")  a 
"pressure  group,"  such  as  the  German  Trade  Unions  under  the 
Weimar  Republic,  may  be  an  enormous  affair,  as  opposed  to  the 
state  party  of  bourgeois  liberalism. 

[Pressure  groups  are  associations  which  use  political  means  for 
the  promotion  of  strictly  economic,  usually  class,  interests;  parties 
do  the  reverse;  even  declared  "class  parties"  use  economic  means, 
as  well  as  political,  for  both  economic  and  political  ends.  /'Labor 
parties"  generally  differ  from  bourgeois  "class  parties"  in  that  they 
aim  by  reforms  or  by  revolutions  to  attain  a  new  social  structure, 
hence  not  at  "getting  out  of  capitalism"  what  they  can  get,  but 
transforming  capitalism  in  one  way  or  another. M  The  party  struc- 
ture of  the  United  States,  in  spite  of  the  heterogeneous  composi- 
tion of  each  party,  would  seem  at  least  temporarily  to  drift  toward 
class  alignments:)  "the  vested  interest"  u.  wage  earners,  family 
farmers,  and  new  and  old  middle  classes  in  the  big  city. 

It  should  be  clear  that  all  sorts  of  interrelations,  and  hence 
opportunities  for  leaders  to  elaborate  their  roles  and  expand  the 

11 E.  E.  Schattschneider,  Politics,  Pressures  and  Hie  Tariff  ( Xew  Y(irk: 
Prentice-Hall,    1 935 )  • 

12  Cf.  C.  Wright  Mills,  The  New  Men  of  Power  (Xew  York:  Harcourt,  Brace, 
1948). 


440  DYNAMICS 

scope  of  their  commands,  exist  in  the  context  of  voluntary  asso- 
ciations. 

I  Movements  are  composed  of  people  who  are  attempting  to 
change  their  position  with -reference  to  the  personnel  or  the  struc- 
ture of  institution^;.  The  people  involved  need  not  share  common 
values;  land  they  may  be  quite  variously  motivated  in  such  a  way 
as  to  converge  or  coincide  in  the  movement's  direction.  But 
whether  or  not  the  people  involved  are  conscious  of  common  ends 
or  are  propelled  by  similar  motives  is  not  necessary  to  their  defini- 
tion as  a  movement,  but  must  be  determined  in  any  given  case. 

Thus  the  European  crusade  represented  a  movement  having  quite 
heterogeneous  sources,  motives,  and  objectives:  ^"  there  was  Pope 
Urban  II's  desire  to  integrate  the  Greek  and  Roman  church  with 
himself  as  head;  there  was  the  feudal  lord's  willingness  to  make 
war,  which  was  their  trade,  and  which,  for  all  warriors,  was  a 
supremely  prestigeful  activity;  there  were  the  new  lands  to  con- 
quer and  fiefs  to  be  established  for  noble  scions;  there  was  the 
desire  of  the  trading  classes,  especially  of  the  Italian  cities,  to 
benefit  from  shipping  services  and  the  luxurious  plunder  of  the 
East;  there  was  also  the  spiritual  interest  of  all  Christians  to  con- 
quer the  Holy  Land  from  the  Mohammedans;  and  in  the  asceticist 
atmosphere  of  the  age,  there  was  the  desire  of  men  and  women  to 
do  penance  by  the  long,  dangerous  pilgrimage,  and  thus  to  save 
their  souls. 

I  Movements  may  be  located  in  any  one  or  in  several  of  the  insti- 
tutional orders.)  If  their  orientation  has  primarily  to  do  with  the 
personnel,  structure,  policies,  or  symbols  of  the  religious  order  of 
institutions,  they  may  be  understood  as  religious  movements;  if 
they  seek  to  influence  state  power,  who  wields  it  and  how,  they  are 
political  movements.  If  they  seek  to  change  the  status  system  or 
the  class  structure  we  may  speak  of  status  movements,  such  as 
those  of  youth,  women,  and  the  aged,  or  of  class  movements,  such 
as  those  of  middle  classes,  farmers,  and  labor.  Movements  may 
be  specialized  by  institutional  orders  and  spheres,  or  they  may 
lude  several  or  all  orders  within  a  social  structure. 
The  great  ideological  movements  of  liberalism,  nationalism,  and 
socialism  have  generally  tended  to  operate  in  a  total  way\  their 

^■' See  "Crusades,"  Encyclopaedia  of  the  Social  Sciences,  Vol.  IV,  p.  614  flF. 


inc 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  4^1 

goals  and  policies  have  to  do  with  extensive  modifications  of  the 
structure  of  all  orders  and  spheres— religious  and  political,  kinsliip 
and  economic,  military  and  technological,  status  and  educational. 
In  liberalism,  for  example,  we  speak  of  "economic  liberalism"  when 
referring  to  "Manchesterism"  and  free  trade;  of  "political  liberal- 
ism" when  referring  to  constitutionalism  v.  despotism;  of  "cultural 
liberalism"  when  referring  to  the  symbol  and  educational  spheres, 
to  the  elaboration  of  personality  models  in  the  arts,  and  so  on. 

Movements  may  also  be  classified  in  terms  of  how  far-going 
their  aims  may  be:  if  they  seek  to  modify  existing  arrangements, 
we  speak  of  reform  movements,  if  they  seek  to  change  the  struc- 
ture and  the  ruling  legitimations  of  institutional  orders,  we  speak 
of  revolutionary  movements. 

Therefore,  in  examining  a  social  moxement  one  may  first  locate 
it  at  each  phase  through  which  it  runs,  within  institutional  orders 
and  spheres,  and  within  classes  and  status  levels— in  terms  of  at 
least  three  aspects:  (1)  its  professed  goals  and  policies,  whether 
they  are  reformative  or  revolutionary  and  what  their  specific  con- 
tents are;  (2)  the  recruitment  and  composition  of  its  members  and 
leaders;  and  (3)  its  objective  functions;  that  is,  one  must  ask  cui 
bono?— to  whose  benefit  does  its  existence  and  operation  redound? 

4.  Revolution  and  Counterrevolution  " 

As  the  term  implies,  a  revolution  may  be  generically  defined  as  a 
qualitative  turnover  of  institutional  orders.  Movements  or  parties 
which  aim  to  transform  and  replace  the  legitimations  and  institu- 
tions of  an  order,  or  of  several  orders,  may  be  called  re\olution- 
ary.  With  such  exceptions  as  "industrial  revolution,"  the  temi  is  usu- 
ally used  only  for  relatively  rapid  transformations.  The  scope  of 
such  movements  may  be  delimited  in  terms  of  which  orders  the 

1*  For  good  introductory  accounts,  see  Crane  Brinton,  The  Atuitiutiy  of 
Revolution  (New  York:  Norton,  1938);  L.  P.  Edwards,  TJw  Natural  Hidonj 
of  Revolution  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chiciigo  Press,  1927);  E.  II.  Carr,  Studies 
in  Revolution  (London:  Macmillan,  1950);  Edmund  Wilson,  To  the  Finland 
Station  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1940);  but  above  all,  Leon  Trotsky,  The 
History  of  the  Russian  Revolution,  Ma.v  Eastman,  tr.  (New  York:  Simon  & 
Schuster,  1936);  Franz  Borkenau,  The  Comtnunist  International  (New  York: 
Norton,  1938);  Franz  Neumann,  Behemoth  (New  York:  Oxford  Univ.  Press, 
1942);  Alfred  Meusel,  "Rc\olution  and  Counter-Revolution,"  Encij.  Social 
Sciences  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1937),  Vol.  \'II,  pages  367-76. 


442  DYNAMICS 

movement  is  aimed  at:  it  is  "partial"  if  it  operates  only  in  some 
orders,  it  is  total  if  it  aims  to  transform  all  orders.  It  is  probably 
only  with  the  advent  of  modern,  extensive  techniques  of  communi- 
cation, domination,  and  manipulation  that  total  revolutions  become 
possible.  The  Russian  is  thus  more  "total"  than  the  French  revolu- 
tion. We  may  also  define  the  scope  by  determining  whether  the 
movement  comes  to  operate  in  more  than  one  natural  unit.  We  do 
not  wish  to  include  the  occurrence  of  violence  in  our  definition  of 
revolution,  although  it  is  an  historical  fact  that  most  revolutions, 
both  ancient  and  modern,  have  involved  violence,  on  behalf  of  the 
status  quo  as  well  as  against  it. 

For  full-scale  revolution  there  must  be  more  than  a  change  of 
values;  the  ruling  structure  and  its  legitimations  must  change.  Thus, 
without  revolution,  men  of  various  classes  and  with  definite  aims 
and  policies  may  come  and  go  in  cabinets,  but  a  state  run  by  cabi- 
nets may  endure.  Revolution  involves  a  turnover  in  personnel;  but 
such  a  turnover  is  not  by  itself  a  revolution.  A  circulation  of  elites 
is  not  enough;  there  must  also  be  a  restructuring  of  a  system  of 
domination  and  authority. 

A  revolution,  loosely  conceived,  appears  as  a  profound  change 
in  a  social  structure  occurring  suddenly  and  with  violence.  But  it 
is  sudden  only  in  its  appearance  to  the  unprepared.  And  it  is  not 
always  "with  violence"— even  in  the  political  order;  moreover,  the 
major  violence  involved  is  usually  an  effect  of  the  success  of  the 
revolution,  when  the  new  regime  comes  to  grips  with  counterforces 
who  would  by  violence  defend  or  restore  the  old  structure. 

If  law,  in  practice,  is  what  the  courts  are  likely  to  enforce,  and 
if  the  courts  are  of  the  established  order,  revolutions  are  of  course, 
"illegal"— being  beyond  what  courts  can  enforce.  But  revolutions, 
if  successful,  establish  new  legal  orders.  It  is,  in  fact,  a  definitive 
characteristic  of  revolutionary  transitions  that  they  mark  a  gap  in 
legality:  old  legitimations  and  laws  no  longer  can  be  enforced; 
new  ones  are  as  yet  not  established. 

From  the  point  of  view  of  the  old  regime  a  revolution  is  an  illegal 
or  a  "criminal"  change  in  the  conditions  of  legality.  From  the  point 
of  view  of  the  new  regime  the  agents  who  enforce  or  try  to  en- 
force the  old  legitimations  are  "criminals." 

In  "palace  revolutions,"  usurpers— often  from  within  the  ruling 
stratum— dispkice  the  ruler  (King  Farouk  of  Egypt,  1952),  or  his 
legitimate  successor  (Edward  VIII,  1936),  or  the  entire  dynasty 


COLLECT!  V^E     BEHAVIOR  ^^3 

("The  Glorious  Revolution,"  16SS)— without  changing  the  master 
symbols.  And  by  the  so-called  coup  d'etat  rulers  may  change  the 
political  system  and  the  legitimation  formula,  as  did  Napoleon  III 
in  1851,  or  Hitler  upon  the  death  of  Hindenburg. 

If  in  a  political  order  changes  in  the  legal  order  of  private  prop- 
erty rights,  as  from  one  class  to  another,  are  instigated,  which  in 
turn  lead  to  qualitatively  new  institutions  coming  to  predominance 
in  the  economic  order,  we  may  speak  of  political  and  economic 
revolution.  In  the  status  sphere  of  the  political  order,  revolution 
occurred  when  the  Constitution  of  the  United  States  outlawed  titles 
of  nobility  and  disclaimed  any  citizen  who  accepts  a  title  from 
another  government.  This  blow  against  descent  prestige  cleared 
the  way  for  the  estimation  of  men  on  other  terms:  effort,  personal 
merit,  election  to  office  or  wealth.  The  Jacksonian  era  carried 
through  this  status  revolution,  for  many  of  the  phenomena  asso- 
ciated with  Jackson's  administration  are  more  properly  considered 
matters  of  status  than  of  economics. 

The  experience  of  classic  bourgeois  revolutions  was  theoretically 
formulated  by  Marx,  who  saw  the  connection  between  the  eco- 
nomic and  the  political  order  in  terms  of  class  struggle.  This  strug- 
gle was  anchored  in  the  economic  order,  but  culminated  in  a  strug- 
gle of  the  ascending  middle  classes  for  the  state.  The  political 
revolution  was  thus  explained  in  terms  of  changes  in  the  economic 
order.  Such  economically  anchored  political  revolutions,  guided 
by  class  parties,  bring  about  a  new  correspondence  between  the 
economic  and  the  political  orders.  Previous  disproportions  between 
the  two  orders  are  eliminated  in  favor  of  the  ascendant  class  in 
the  economic  order.  Such  political  revolutions  are  visually  preceded 
and  accompanied  by  ideological  and  status  changes:  the  newly 
established  authorities  claim  status  for  themselves  and  for  their 
supporters.  The  political  symbols  turn  over.  Roundhead  and  sans 
culotte  replace  long  curls,  wigs  and  breeches.  Monuments  of  old 
Tsars  and  generals  are  torn  down,  new  heroes  monumentalized; 
old  street  names  and  old  flags,  old  emblems  and  oaths  give  way 
to  new  ones.  Into  the  bonfires  go  the  cultural  symbols  of  past 
power  as  the  zeal  of  the  iconoclast  has  its  heyday. 

So  during  the  heroic  period  of  Puritanism,  Cromwell's  army 
proclaims  itself  an  army  of  saints.  Inspired  soldiers,  "the  agitators," 
mount  pulpits  without  waiting  for  ordination.  Puritan  bibliocracy 


444  DYNAMICS 

is  thus  established.  Similarly,  in  the  French  revolution,  every 
deputy  of  the  revolutionary  parliament  is  sworn  in  with  his  hand 
upon  Rousseau's  Contrat  sociale.  During  the  climax  of  the  revolu- 
tionary enthusiasm  the  cult  of  the  goddess  of  reason  is  proclaimed 
and  in  majestic  public  demonstrations  a  nude  virgin  on  a  flower- 
bedecked  float  symbolizes  the  new  deity  of  political  enlighten- 
ment. Revolutionary  operas  glorify  the  new  regime,  David  stages 
and  directs  the  festival,  immortalizes  the  revolutionary  hero 
(Marat's  death).  The  new  class  abolishes  old  customs,  creates  new 
forms  of  exuberant  mass  enthusiasm.  The  ceremonious  minuet— the 
show  dance  of  the  elite— is  swept  away  by  the  uproarious  passionate 
whirling  of  waltzing  masses.  Then  this  exuberance  is  tinged  with 
proletariat  vigor  when  in  1830  the  cancan,  with  its  high  kicking 
becomes  publicly  acceptable. 

Broad  masses  expand  and,  under  the  impact  of  enthusiastic 
revolutionary  terrorism,  old  status  groups  go  into  hiding  and  exile, 
maintaining  their  esteemed  self-conceptions  through  snobbish  deri- 
sion of  the  vulgarity  of  the  political  parvenus.  They  compensate 
for  their  loss  of  power  by  strictly  emphasizing  the  symbols  of 
status,  the  good  name  of  the  deserved  ancestors,  the  well-mannered 
and  soft-spoken  conventions  of  the  educated,  the  refined  tastes  of 
the  sophisticated.  Marginal  figures  from  these  upper  groups  who 
shift  political  sides  are  the  most  hated  of  men.  Intellectuals  ( minis- 
ters, artists,  political  secretaries)  who  theoretically  elaborate  the 
nostalgic  hope  for  a  return  of  the  "good  old  days"  are  cordially 
welcome.  Refugees  who  have  found  asylum  at  foreign  courts  call 
for  war  against  the  revolutionized  country  and  hope  for  the  return 
of  the  lost  holdings.  And  to  the  extent  to  which  the  new  order  re- 
laxes in  zeal  and  watchfulness,  conspiratorial  activities  increase 
among  the  deposed. 

New  leaders  of  a  counterrevolution  are  appraised  as  past  experi- 
ence is  rationalized.  New  theories  are  developed  which  dispute 
the  legitimacy  of  the  revolutionary  regime  and  debunk,  psycho- 
logically, theoretically,  and  politically,  its  new  measures  and  styles 
of  life.  So  after  the  first  revolutionary  shocks  have  been  overcome, 
fatalism  and  defeatism  tend  to  wane  and  give  way  to  political 
plotting,  inspired  by  the  observation  of  incipient  cracks  and  points 
of  strain  in  the  new  structure.  Out  of  informal  gatherings  grow 
nuclei  of  political  and  perhaps  eventually  military  organizations. 
Their  leaders  play  on  the  sentiments  of  the  disappointed,  woo 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  4^5 

the  good  will  of  foreign  governments  who  nia\'  hesitate  to  grant 
recognition  to  the  rexolutionary  regime. 

In  brief,  the  forces  of  reaction  organize  for  connterrexohition. 
One  member  or  another  of  the  ranks  who  side  with  the  revolntion, 
feeling  the  pulse  of  impending  crises,  may— as  did  Talleyrand- 
change  horses  and  exploit  his  official  position  in  the  new  order  for 
political  intrigue  in  favor  of  a  "restoration."  By  counterrevolution 
we  mean  the  organized  and  successful  endea\'or  of  previous  rul- 
ing groups  to  re-establish  themsehes  in  power  in  the  name  of  the 
old  or  newly  wrought  legitimations. 

The  defeat  of  such  attempts  constitutes  the  supreme  test  of  the 
new  regime:  it  is  at  this  point  that  we  find  the  organized  use  of 
revolutionary  terror.  Political  enemies,  actual  or  suspect,  are  out- 
lawed, their  property  confiscated,  their  families  executed  or  ex- 
pelled, their  friends  hunted  down.  The  secret  police  operates  in  the 
midst  of  wild  rumors,  harsh  denunciations,  veiled  threats.  If  the 
incipient  counterrevolution  cannot  be  nipped  in  the  bud,  military 
emergencies  and  states  of  siege  are  proclaimed.  If  the  army  is  politi- 
cally suspect,  the  revolutionary  vanguard  organizes  a  new  revolu- 
tionary army  controlled  by  "political  commissars"  ( Saint-Just,  Crom- 
well's agitators,  the  Commissars  of  the  Red  Army).  If  the  counter- 
revolution should  succeed,  a  still  stronger  terrorism  is  organized. 
Revolutionary  leaders  and  fighters  may  be  shot  en  masse  ("The 
ten  thousand"  after  the  French  Commune  of  1S71,  the  White 
Terror  in  Hungary  after  World  War  I). 

In  all  cases  there  is  a  rapid  turnover  of  prison  populations.  The 
release  of  prisoners  may  be  equivalent  to  the  Christian  glorifica- 
tion of  martyrs.  Schiller,  the  court  intellectual  of  Weimar,  argued 
that  "man  is  free,  e\'en  if  born  in  chains,"  which  may  hold  for  the 
inner  spirit  of  the  intellectual;  but  for  political  movements,  man 
is  free  only  when  his  chains  are  broken.  The  storming  of  the  Bas- 
tille on  July  14,  in  itself  a  political  bagatelle,  has  become  the  date 
for  the  annual  celebration  of  the  French  Revolution.  The  chorus 
of  the  liberated  prisoners  in  Beetho\'en's  Fidelio  is  the  re\olntion- 
ary  symbol  of  political  liberation  and  freedom. 

It  is  convenient  to  grasp  the  psychological  and  ideological  aspects 
of  revolutionary  movements  by  focusing  upon  their  definition  of 
historical  time  and  reality  and  upon  their  conception  of  freedom. 


44^  DYNAMICS 

As  Karl  Mannheim  has  demonstrated/^  these  aspects  of  mentaHty 
allow  for  a  convenient  approach  to  some  of  the  underlying  and 
implied  categories  tlirough  which  the  revolutionary  actor's  experi- 
ence is  structured,  but  which  are  themselves  rarely  experienced 
self-consciously. 

I.  Time:  As  the  charismatic  leader  and  his  followers  are  not 
bound  by  communal  traditions  nor  by  a  legal  order,  but  rather  are 
the  initiators  of  radical  beginnings,  they  experience  their  time  as  a 
crisis.  They  feel  detached  from  what  appears  to  them  as  old  and 
dead,  although  they  live  in  the  midst  of  such  death.  An  epoch 
is  coming  to  an  end,  a  time  is  ceasing,  the  old  book  is  closed.  But 
new  gates  are  opening  and  they  feel  themselves  at  the  threshold 
of  a  new  epoch,  and  from  this  their  enthusiasm  springs.  Moses  sees 
but  does  not  enter  the  new  land.  The  transition  from  Pharaonic 
bondage  to  this  new  and  liberated  land  is  on  the  way,  Christ  acts 
"to  fulfill  the  time"  and  his  birth  marks  the  beginning  of  Occidental 
Christendom's  history.  So  the  France  of  1789  and  the  Russia  of  the 
October  revolution  attempt  to  institute  new  calendars,  which  begin 
with  their  deeds.  The  leader  as  well  as  his  followers  thus  experi- 
ence their  time  as  the  beginning  of  all  time.  Karl  Marx's  dismissal 
of  the  last  2,000  years  of  history  as  mere  "prehistory,"  and  Engel's 
expectation  of  the  "leap  into  freedom "  indicate  the  temporal  discon- 
tinuity experienced  by  revolutionaries.  Not  the  gradual  transitions 
of  a  continuum,  but  the  historical  hiatus,  expressed  by  many  and 
various  symbols,  is  typical. 

II.  Reality:  The  charismatic  experience  of  reality  shows  the  same 
abrupt  dichotomy  radically  separating  the  black  from  the  white, 
the  dead  from  the  living,  and  light  from  darkness.  Schiller,  as 
a  revolutionary  enthusiast,  cries  out,  "And  new  life  springs  from 
the  ruins  .  .  .  ,"  an  image  to  be  found  in  many  paintings  of  the 
period:  young  mothers  and  babies  playing  amidst  broken  and  an- 
cient columns,  or,  indeed,  hanging  diapers  on  them.  Traditional 
forms  of  life  and  conventions  appear  as  hollow  and  doomed;  they 
are  as  masks  of  death  itself:  they  are  visualized  as  threats.  Institu- 
tions, however  outwardly  firm,  are  built  on  foundations  of  sand. 
If  the  doomed  aristocrat,  in  a  fleeting  moment  of  self-conscious- 
ness, cynically  shrugs  his  shoulders  and  mutters,  "After  us,  the 

'■"' See  his  Ideology  and  Utopia,  Louis  Wirth  and  Edward  Shils,  trs.  (New 
York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1936). 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  4^7 

deluge,"  the  revolutionary  group  is  full  of  hope  in  feeling  itself 
embarking  upon  a  new  era.  The  heir  to  the  past  feels  that  he  would 
make  the  most  of  what  is  left  of  the  old  time;  the  charismatic  actor 
feels  that  all  can  be  had  if  what  is  left  would  but  fall.  Facing  up  to 
what  blocks  his  way,  he  is  eager  not  to  support  but  to  push  over 
what  is  already  tottering.  "And  what  is  this  class  struggle?  It  is  over- 
throwing the  Czar,  overthrowing  the  capitalist,  destroying  the  capi- 
talist class.  .  .  .  We  subordinate  our  Communist  morality  to  this 
task.  We  say:  'Morality  is  that  which  serves  to  destroy  the  old  ex- 
ploiting society  and  to  unite  all  the  toilers  around  the  proletariat 
which  is  creating  a  new  Communist  society.' "  ^^^ 

A  keen  sense  of  a  new  unheard-of  mission  inspires  the  charis- 
matic leader  and  his  followers.  Feeling  at  one  with  the  rush  of 
time,  his  days  are  not  counted;  he  sees  his  days  to  come.  For  him 
there  is  no  end  in  view;  the  new  reality  appears  to  him  under  the 
aspect  of  infinity.  The  optimistic  image  of  the  new  age  of  har- 
mony, the  golden  age,  the  end  of  darkness,  the  rising  sun,  spring, 
and  the  end  of  winter— these  celestial  allegories  and  symbols  ex- 
press experiences  of  a  discontinuous  reality.  Or,  there  may  be 
organic  symbols:  the  image  of  the  pangs  and  travails  of  birth, 
which  Marx  uses  often,  lends  itself  readily  to  this  experience.  Opti- 
mism, of  a  previously  unheard-of  surge,  lifts  up  the  followers  of  the 
charismatic  leader.  With  eyes  fixed  on  the  distant  yet  foreshortened 
goal,  they  move  ahead  with  the  certainty  of  the  sleepwalker,  often 
immunized  against  the  costs  of  blood,  self-sacrifice  and  terror 
which  the  deliberate  destruction  of  the  old  entails. 

III.  Freedom:  These  experiences  of  time  and  reality  dovetail 
with  those  of  the  freedom  which  is  to  come  through  detachment 
in  action.  Freedom  means  liberation,  and  with  the  increasing  size 
and  power  of  the  charismatic  following,  freedom  is  felt  to  increase. 
For  freedom  is  seen  and  felt  to  be  a  sharing  in  the  expanding 
movement  of  the  leader.  The  enthusiasm  of  the  faithful  follower 
is  experienced  as  essential  to  freedom.  Loyalty  to  the  leader  and 
to  new  actions  increasingly  widen  the  gap  between  what  is  to  the 
follower  the  restraint  of  a  doomed  world  and  a  series  of  obstacles; 
so  the  charismatic  groups  in  active  pursuit  of  their  resolution 
experience  this  resolution  as  providing  a  new  freedom  for  all.  Their 

13A  Nikolai  Lenin,  Collected  Works  (New  York:  International  Pubs.,  1923), 
Vol.  XVIII,  p.  322  ff. 


4^8  DYNAMICS 

enthusiasm  is  aggressive  and  inclusive.  They  wish  to  embrace  and 
incorporate  all  things. 

It  is  this  sense  of  an  expanding  generalized  other  which  inspires 
their  sense  of  "mission."  Hence  this  experience  of  freedom  is  far 
from  a  privatizing  of  the  person.  On  the  contrary,  freedom  as  the 
withdrawal  into  privacy  is  derided  as  indifference,  egoism,  and 
selfishness.  Freedom  for  what?  is  answered  by  the  charismatic  group 
in  charismatic  action.  The  leader  challenges  the  old:  in  Christ's 
phrase,  "it  is  written,  but  /  say  unto  you."  To  the  extent  to  which 
it  binds  followers,  the  leader's  word  also  dissolve  their  bonds  to 
outsiders. 

It  would  be  futile  to  go  beyond  some  such  statements  as  these, 
which  cannot  fail  to  be  relatively  abstract,  as  the  symbolic  context 
of  any  charismatic  revolutionary  group  is  of  course  influenced  by 
the  era  and  the  society  in  which  it  emerges.  Yet  these  somewhat 
general  comments  may  suffice  to  characterize  the  directions  which 
detailed  studies  of  different  types  of  revolutionary  movements  might 
have  to  consider. 

The  proletariat  play  a  part  in  all  the  classic  bourgeois  revolu- 
tions; actual  fighting  forces  are  usually  recruited  from  among 
its  ranks,  but  they  are  not  necessarily  led  by  wage  workers  and 
their  aims  are  often  different. 

We  understand  by  "proletarian  revolutions"  those  which  aim  at 
the  conquest  of  the  state  for  the  declared  purpose  of  abolishing  big 
private  property  in  the  means  of  production,  however  indistinct, 
confused,  hazy,  or  romantic  this  implied  goal  may  be  in  its  varied 
formulations.  The  insurrection  of  the  Paris  proletariat  in  1830  is 
thus  the  first  autonomous  revolt  of  the  proletariat.  Similarly,  the 
revolution  of  1848  and  the  establishment  of  the  short-lived  Paris 
Commune,  the  revolution  of  Germany  of  1918  in  part,  the  October 
revolution  in  Russia  in  1917,  China  in  the  forties  are  outstanding 
examples. 

These  revolutions  are  historically  specific  in  that  they  are 
planned.  Modern  revolutions  involve  specific  problems  of  ideologi- 
cal and  political  organization,  political  strategy  and  tactics  and 
insurrectional  technique.  It  is  with  reference  to  such  questions- 
that  different  proletarian  parties  emerge.  A  staff  of  leaders  is  typi- 
cally recruited  from  outside  the  class  for  which  they  speak  but 
with  which  they  identify;   they  have  included  aristocratic  intel- 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  449 

lectuals  and  officers  (Bakunin,  Chicherin,  L.  Renn),  bourgeois  in- 
tellectuals and  Maecenases  (F.  Engels,  Paul  Singer).  The  party 
fund  which  helped  the  Russian  socialists  to  hold  their  historic  1903 
party  congress  in  London,  at  which  the  Bolshevist  party  under  Lenin 
emerged  as  the  "majority,"  was  financed  by  Lloyd  George.  School- 
teachers and  seminarists  (like  Mao  Tse-tung  and  Joseph  Stalin), 
self-educated  migratory  journeymen  (Wilhelm  Weitling,  Eugene 
Debs),  and  declasse,  plebeian  intelligentsia  (such  as  Lenin),  the 
numerous  party  secretaries,  radical  journalists  (like  Lincoln  Stef- 
fens),  runaway  students  (like  John  Reed)  have  also  entered  revo- 
lutionary parties. 

Those  strivings  which  eventuate  in  revolutions  have  historically 
been  conceived  as  national  in  context  and  origin.  Twentieth-cen- 
tury revolutions,  however,  are  characterized  by  the  fact  that  they 
occur  in  the  wake  of  military  defeat  and  subsequent  military 
interventions.  Lenin  is  the  author  of  a  special  elaboration  of  this 
fact  and,  based  upon  it,  of  a  set  of  tactics  to  "transform  imperialist 
war  into  civil  war"  by  "revolutionary  defeatism,"  and  "the  dictator- 
ship of  the  proletariat,"  which  legitimates  the  establisliment  of  the 
vanguard's  power. 

There  is  one  fact  about  the  course  of  one  of  these  modern  pro- 
letariat revolutions,  and  its  ensuing  counterrevolution,  that  is  so 
psychologically  striking  that  we  must  attempt  to  understand  its 
wider  psychological  meanings.  We  refer  to  the  "confessions"  of  the 
old  Bolshevik  vanguard  during  the  thirties. 

The  brilliant  intellectuals,  primarily  of  middle-class  background, 
who  in  1917  led  the  Bolshevik  revolution  succumbed  to  brutally 
efficient  administrators,  primarily  of  such  background— rising  from 
peasant  milieu  through  party  schools  and  up  the  bureaucratic  lad- 
der—that to  them  the  telephone  was  a  prime  symbol  of  power.  The 
old  polemic  leaders  did  not  last  in  the  era  of  bureaucratic  plots, 
but  the  mediocre,  as  Victor  Serge  has  written,  reconciled  their 
convictions  with  the  situation  in  which  they  found  themselves: 
"long  live  our  beefsteak,  long  live  our  chief,  ice  are  the  re\olu- 
tion  .  .  ," 

Since  1917,  some  twenty-seven  men  have  at  one  time  or  another 
been  members  of  the  Russian  Politburo-the  top  power  unit  of  the 
U.S.S.R.  Lenin  died  of  natural  causes  in  1924,  ending  by  his  death 
the  period  of  the  old  Bolsheviks;  from  then  until  1938,  when  the  last 


^^O  DYNAMICS 

big  purge  trial  ended,  is  a  transition  era.  The  third  era,  from  1938 
to  date,  is  the  era  of  the  entrenched  Stahn  administration.  Nineteen 
of  the  total  of  twenty-seven  are  no  longer  members  of  the  Polit- 
buro: eight  were  executed,  two  murdered,  one  was  a  suicide,  one 
was  just  dropped,  and  seven  died  of  natural  causes. ^'^ 

The  remarkable  psychological  aspect  of  this  shift  has  to  do  with 
the  "confessions"  of  the  old  Bolshevik  vanguard.  They  "confessed" 
to  actions  which  there  is  reason  to  believe  they  did  not  commit. 
Why?  They  had  been  members  of  the  party  for  major  portions  of 
their  lives;  they  had  given  up  all  else  for  party  work.  Their  circle 
of  significant  others,  in  brief,  was  confined  to  party  members,  and 
the  party  formed,  as  it  were,  the  only  social  locus  of  their  general- 
ized others.  So,  it  may  be  that  their  confidence  in  themselves,  in 
their  ability  to  think  and  decide,  was  tied  to  their  faith  in  the 
party,  the  I  and  the  Me  having  no  clear-cut  border-line  in  their 
conscience.  Therefore:  no  thought,  no  feeling,  no  consciousness 
outside  the  party.  In  liberal  terminology,  their  commitment  was  not 
provisional  or  partial;  it  was  permanent  and  absolute.  And  since 
they  had  no  social  anchorage  for  individual  behavior  outside  the 
party,  their  last  individual  act  was  to  sacrifice  themselves  for  the 
party.^'  One  thing  we  have  learned  by  the  Soviet  shift  "from 
Lenin  to  Stalin"  is  that  ideologies  can  blind  as  well  as  guide  think- 
ing, feeling,  seeing,  remembering. 

5.  Anticapitalistic  Movements  and  Parties 

There  have  been  some  four  general  movements  in  the  tsventieth 
century  which  have  so  overshadowed  other  movements  that  in 
Europe  their  struggles  and  victories  and  defeats,  their  reforms  and 
revolutions,  have  made  up  "The  Social  Question."  In  intellectual 
circles,  their  debates  and  issues  have  formed  the  live  content  of 
political  discussion.  In  the  world  scene,  their  rise  and  fall  have 
been  the  keys  to  world  wars  and  international  tensions.  They  have 

^''' These  figures  are  drawn  from  George  K.  Schueller,  Tlie  Politburo  (Stan- 
ford: Stanford  Univ.  Press,  1951).  But  compare  Paul  Scheffer,  "From  Lenin  ta 
Stalin,"  Foreign  Affairs,  April  1938,  pp.  445-53. 

^^  See  Philip  E.  Mosely's  "Freedom  of  Artistic  Expression  and  Scientific  In- 
quiry in  Russia,"  Tlie  Annals  of  the  American  Academy  of  Political  and  Social 
Science,  Vol.  200,  November  1938,  pp.  254-74;  and  especially  F.  Beck  and 
W.  Godin,  Russian  Purge  and  tlie  Extraction  of  Confession  ( New  York:  Viking, 
1951)- 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  45I 

each  striven  to  operate  in  all  institutional  orders,  although  the 
political  and  economic  areas  have  been  their  central  locales,  and 
they  have  each  been  an  opposition  movement,  especially  in  the 
economic  order— for  all  but  one  of  them  have  been  generally  anti- 
capitalist. 

We  can  describe  them  systematically,  as  we  can  describe  any 
movement  or  party,  by  examining  their  (1)  ultimate  goals  and 
(2)  typical  ways  of  attaining  them,  (3)  their  immediate  expecta- 
tions and  (4)  demands,  (5)  their  general  conception  of  history 
and  (6)  the  organizational  levers  they  would  use,  (7)  their  domi- 
nant mode  of  action  and  (8)  the  composition  of  their  predominant 
membership,  ( 9 )  the  types  of  leaders  and  staff  they  have  displayed 
and  (10)  their  objective  political  results. 

I.  Anarchism  and  Syndicalism— as  displayed  by  Spanish  and 
Italian  anarchism,  by  France's  syndicalist  movement  and  in  the 
United  States  by  the  I\VW;  by  Russian  nobles,  like  Bakunin  and 
Kropotkin,  by  nihilism  and  earlier  in  what  is  known  as  Blanquism 
—are  now  largely  insignificant  as  political  movements.  As  mo\e- 
ments,  they  are  now  significant  for  us  only  as  precursors  in  this 
or  that  detail  of  doctrine  or  technique  for  later,  more  successful 
movements.  The  historical  aim  of  these  movements  has  been  a 
stateless  society  or  congeries  of  societies  composed  of  free  brethren, 
which  they  sought  to  attain  by  "propaganda  of  the  deed"  (Baku- 
nin), the  promulgation  of  the  "myth  of  the  general  strike"  (Sorel) 
—by,  in  short,  a  spontaneous  insurrection  of  the  exploited.  They 
have  been  eschatological,  expecting  an  immediate  and  universal 
crisis  in  public  affairs,  and  so  they  have  demanded  action-imme- 
diate and  direct.  For  them  all  history  has  been  full  of  evil  power, 
for  all  power  is  evil,  the  existing  state  being  an  incarnation  of  sin- 
ful exploitation,  and  civilization  a  great  progress  towards  a  hubris 
of  the  powerful.  In  the  course  of  history,  the  state  is  doomed.  The 
organizational  levers  with  which  they  would  cause  its  downfall 
have  been  loose  federations  of  sectarian  type  under  charismatic 
leaders,  as  with  Blanqui's  especially,  small  and  vigorously  disci- 
plined fighting  clubs.  They  wished  to  engage  in  individual  terror- 
ism, in  nihilism,  in  the  propaganda  of  the  deed;  or,  as  in  Barce- 
lonean  syndicalism,  in  strikes  of  spontaneous  masses;  or  in  Blan- 
quistic  coup  d'etat.  They  have  recruited  both  men  and  women, 
especially  people  working  in  small  sweatshops,  as  among  Swiss 


^52  DYNAMICS 

watchmakers  or  French  embroidery  workers,  or  as  in  the  United 
States,  among  various  types  of  migratory  laborers  in  the  western 
states.  Their  leaders  have  been  seen  as  extraordinary  men  and 
women  and  as  both  high-  and  low-brow  intellectuals. 

II.  One  may  define  socialism,  generally,  as  the  demand  for  a 
planned  economic  order,  producing  for  use  rather  than  profit,  and 
subject  to  central  administration  and  budgetary  accounting.  This 
involves  the  fusion  of  economic  and  political  orders  by  the  exten- 
sion of  democratic  practices  to  the  economic  order,  which,  in  turn, 
makes  for  the  elimination  of  property  and  income  class  privileges 
in  favor  of  economic  equality.  As  a  movement,  socialism  must  be 
divided  into  at  least  three  types,  the  first  two  of  which— "social 
democracy"  and  "left-wing  socialism"  we  shall  describe  together. 

Social  Democrats  combined  their  parties  in  the  Second  Inter- 
national; its  outstanding  examples  are  the  German  Social-Demo- 
cratic party  operating  up  to  the  Nazi  era,  and  reconstituted  in 
Western  Germany  since  1945.  Left-wing  socialism  has  been  repre- 
sented by  the  Austrian  Socialists  under  Otto  Bauer  or  by  the  left 
socialists  in  Italy  under  Pietro  Nenni.  Both  types  have  aimed  at  a 
Socialist  economy,  by  which  is  meant  one  in  which  no  private 
property  in  the  basic  means  of  production  exists,  and  in  a  demo- 
cratic political  order;  and  both  would  achieve  these  ends  by  the 
constitutional  means  of  parliamentary  democracy.  They  would  win 
over  the  exploited  classes  by  their  political  program  and  propa- 
ganda, engage  in  election  fights  as  a  duly  constituted  party,  and 
would  maintain  this  organization  continuously  by  linking  party 
with  trade  unions  and  consumer  co-operatives,  as  well  as  other 
affiliated  associations.  With  these  organizations  they  would  come 
to  state  power  and  so  enact  their  program.  Their  immediate  de- 
mands have  varied  according  to  the  going  situation,  to  which  they 
would  rationally  orient  their  tactics.  Originally,  the  demand  of  the 
Social-Democrats  was  the  universal  and  equal  franchise,  for  with 
this  gained,  they  supposed,  their  movement  would  flourish;  later, 
their  demands  were  put  into  detailed  petitions  and  bills  for  attain- 
able legislation  in  favor  of  the  anderprivileged  and  in  defense  of 
democracy.  Left-wing  socialists  have  shared  these  demands,  but 
to  them  have  added  possible  coalition  with  Bolshevik  parties  and 
the  formation  of  semimilitary  party  auxiliaries,  for  left-wing  social- 
ists would  not  shrink  from  th ;  use  of  violence  in  order  to  achieve 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAN'IOR  ^53 

or  to  defend  a  democratic  order.  Thus,  in  the  thirties,  when  central 
European  democratic  constitutions  were  being  smashed,  the  Aus- 
trian sociaHsts'  military  wing  fought  back  with  machine  guns  to 
be  put  down  by  Dollfuss'  howitzers. 

Social  Democrats  have  conceived  of  history  as  a  gradual  pro- 
gression in  the  direction  of  the  enlightenment  of  the  masses,  of 
rising  living  standards,  and,  in  the  international  area,  of  peaceful 
compromises  among  labor  governments.  Left-wing  socialists  have 
foreseen  breaks  in  history  and,  in  xiewing  the  past,  ha\e  glorified 
the  revolutionary  traditions  of  various  proletariats.  Their  organiza- 
tional levers  have  been  pretty  much  confined  to  the  party,  but 
those  of  the  Social  Democrats  have  also  included  varying  constel- 
lations of  parliamentary  factions  involving  party,  trade  imion,  and 
co-op,  with  an  over-all  trend  towards  the  ascendancy  of  trade 
unions  over  parties.  The  Social  Democratic  dominant  mode  of  ac- 
tion has  thus  been  the  building  of  mass  organizations  and  the  mass 
indoctrination  of  party  press,  the  electoral  campaign  and  the  lobby- 
ing for  legislation,  and  has  not  failed  to  include  formation  of  coali- 
tion governments  with  nonsocialist,  or  "bourgeois"  parties.  The 
left-wing  socialist's  activity  has  sti'ongly  emphasized  disciplined 
party  formations  with  total,  or  even  totalitarian,  organization  of 
wage  workers,  and  has  moreover  included  lower  middle-class 
movements.  The  backbone  of  the  Social-Democratic  movement  has 
been  the  unions  of  organized  labor.  Left-wing  socialism  has  en- 
rolled the  same  elements,  as  well  as  descending  middle-class  ele- 
ments. The  types  of  leaders  and  staff  ascendant  in  both  types  ha\e 
included  parliamentary  demagogues,  and  party  and  trade  union 
officials. 

in.  All  socialist  movements  are  anticapinlist,  and  they  have 
aimed  in  their  ultimate  visions  at  a  classless  si  ciety  in  which  power 
and  "politics"  would  be  abolished  in  favor  of  the  technical  and 
rational  planning  of  society.  Bolshevisins  poh  "u-al  and  economic 
results  have,  in  fact,  been  the  rise  to  complete  ^x)wer  of  the  Bol- 
shevist party,  the  abolishment  of  private  property  in  the  means  of 
production,  a  planned  war  economy,  in  a  totalita/an  state,  domi- 
nating the  "Third  International"  and  later  the  Cominform  in  \  ary- 
ing  ways  outside  the  Soviet  Union.  The  means  with  which  it  would 
gain  its  ultimate  end,  which  resulted  in  the  present  Russian  state, 
was  revolution,  and  as   a  moxement   its   immediate  expectations 


454  DYNAMICS 

and  tactics  have  been  oriented  to  the  presumed  presence  or  absence 
of  a  "revolutionary  situation."  It  has  therefore  raised  detailed 
"shock  demands,"  which  are  intended  to  attract  and  unite  under- 
privileged classes  and  groups  of  all  sorts,  and  which  have  often 
been  slanted  and  timed  so  as  to  be  impossible  of  fulfillment  short 
of  revolution.  Its  conception  of  history  has  been  that  of  a  dialectical 
struggle  of  the  world  bourgeoisie  and  the  world  proletariat,  and  its 
organizational  lever  has  been  a  small,  select  party  of  active  and 
disciplined  revolutionaries  led  by  skilled  and  dedicated  profes- 
sionals. Their  leaders  and  staff  have  historically  thus  included 
revolutionary  intellectuals,  both  low-  and  high-brow,  but  they 
have  tended,  outside  of  Russia,  to  be  unstable,  and  in  and  out  of 
Russia  to  be  punctuated  by  purges  from  the  top.  The  modes  of 
Bolshevist  action  have  included  all  those  practiced  by  left-wing 
socialists  and  Social-Democrats,  as  well  as  active  preparation  for 
uprising,  and  various  types  of  illegitimate,  illegal  activities.  The 
membership  recruited  for  the  Bolshevik  movement  has  consisted 
mainly  of  men,  especially  of  highly  skilled  groups  of  the  unem- 
ployed, labor  youths  and  a  radical  intelligentsia.  It  has  consisted 
of  a  hard,  persisting  core  of  veterans,  and  a  larger  membership 
that  has  been  unstable  and  peculiarly  high  in  turnover. 

IV.  Fascism,  as  in  Italy  and  Germany,  has  not  been  an  anti- 
capitalist  movement,  although  its  rhetoric  has  borrowed  heavily 
from  Marxian  vocabularies.  It  has  been,  in  its  composition  and 
aims,  an  antilabor  movement  of  chauvinist  middle  classes,  a  mili- 
tary bohemia  of  officer  veterans,  and  elements  of  the  metropolitan 
dregs.  In  its  results  it  has  been  a  totalitarian  imperialism  of  mo- 
nopoly capitalistic  base  with  modifications  and  extensions  of  big 
business,  jurisdiction  il  areas,  social  controls,  and  personnel.  Fas- 
cism's ultimate  aim  has  been  world  empire;  its  dominant  means, 
world  war;  its  im'  .^diate  expectations,  the  crises  of  parliamentary 
democracy  and  .'isting  capitalistic  economies.  Its  promises  and 
demands  have  I  3en:  power  to  us,  and  then  we'll  detail  the  pro- 
grams—all other  demands  set  forth  by  its  leaders  have  seemed 
to  be  a  conflic' 'ng  but  Machiavellian  hodge-podge  of  incitements. 
Its  conceptioi  of  history  has  been  of  a  process  of  racial  pollution 
and  decadent  of  nations,  which  may  be  saved  by  racially  pure 
elites;  all  hist  ry  is  thus  seen  as  a  circulation  of  elites  and  a  suc- 
cession of  e-  -pires.  The  fascist  lever  of  organization,  the  totali- 


COLLECTIVE     BEHAVIOR  455 

tarian  party  and  its  innumerable  officials,  have  included  semi- 
military  auxiliaries— as  with  Bolshevism.  This  rather  miscellaneous 
party  has  been  led  by  Fiihrer,  Duce,  or  Caudillo— and  in  accord- 
ance with  the  leadership  principle,  merged  with  and  upheld  by 
bureaucratic  machines  under  military  discipline. 

Collective  behavior— a  phrase  that  refers  to  the  revolutionary 
overturn  of  social  structures  as  well  as  the  peaceful  milling  about 
of  casual  street  throngs— is  obviously  a  catchall  for  various  phe- 
nomena that  do  not  readily  fit  into  conceptions  of  institutional 
order.  And  yet,  none  of  these  movements,  parties,  crowds,  aggre- 
gates or  publics  can  be  understood  or  explained  without  sensitive 
reference  to  the  social  structure  that  is  their  context.  For  collective 
behavior,  after  all,  is  the  behavior  of  the  same  people  who  in  their 
more  usual,  everyday  lives  enact  the  routines  of  more  or  less  stable 
institutions.  And  it  is  within  the  master  trends  of  institutional  struc- 
tiu-es  that  such  people,  in  their  collective  behavior,  may  place  their 
imprint  upon  an  epoch  of  history. 


CHAPTER 

XVI 

Master  Trends 


IN  reflecting  upon  the  basic  transformations  of  twentieth-century 
societies,  we  may  first  examine  those  institutional  orders  in  which 
the  distribution  of  power  is  most  visible.  We  do  not  intend  by  this 
approach  to  imply  that  "power"  is  the  highest  value,  for  men  in 
general  or  for  us;  it  is  simply  expedient  to  approach  modern  social 
structures  from  this  point  of  view,  for  it  is  from  this  vantage  point 
that  we  may  best  hope  to  understand  the  ground  swell  of  our  age. 
The  "revolution  of  our  time,"  as  it  is  called  in  contemporary  tracts, 
is  certainly  most  readily  discernible  in  the  military,  political,  and 
economic  orders.  Moreover,  from  the  point  of  view  of  "social  con- 
trol," "staff  controlled"  sanctions  offer  the  easiest  way  to  an  under- 
standing of  the  master  problems  of  a  society  as  a  whole. 

The  development  of  technologies  of  production  and  of  destruc- 
tion—from the  stone  ax  to  the  atom  bomb— has  now  reached  a  new 
threshold  of  efficiency  in  both  the  economic  and  the  military  orders 
of  the  great  powers.  With  these  developments,  the  institutional 
units  which  incorporate  these  technological  developments  are^ enor- 
mously expanded.  In  the  United  States,  for  example,  a  handful  of 
corporations  centralize  decisions  and  responsibilities  that  are  rele- 
vant for  military  and  political  as  well  as  economic  developments 
of  global  significance.  For  nowadays  the  military  and  the  political 
cannot  be  separated  from  economic  considerations  of  power.  We 
now  live  not  in  an  economic  order  and  in  a  political  order,  but  in  a 
political  economy  and  moreover  a  political  economy  that  is  closely 
linked  with  military  institutions  and  decisions.  This  is  obvious  in 
the  repeated  "oil  crises"  of  the  Middle  East,  or  in  the  relevance  of 
Southeast  Asia  and  African  resources  for  the  Western  powers. 
Thus,  an  American  state  governor,  upon  his  return  from  the  Far 
East  in  1951,  spoke  casually  of  "our  tin"  and  "our  rubber"  when 


MASTER     TRENDS  ^57 

speaking  of  French  Indo-China,  British  Malaya,  and  tlie  Indone- 
sian RepnbHc.  In  the  perspective  of  the  naxal  powers,  the  Mechter- 
ranean,  as  well  as  the  North  and  the  Baltic  Seas,  are  but  extensions 
of  the  Atlantic  Ocean.  A  network  of  looser  or  firmer  treaties  now 
extends  throughout  the  "Western  world,"  from  the  eastern  Mediter- 
ranean to  the  borderlands  of  Asia  on  the  Pacific  coast. 

1.  The  Co-ordination  of  Political,  Economic  and 
Military  Orders 

Various  tensions  and  bargains  now  implement  a  world  drift 
whose  direction  in  the  postwar  era  has  been  unmistakably  towards 
an  increasing  integration  of  economic,  military,  and  political  struc- 
tin-es,  on  both  sides  of  the  di\iding  lines  running  through  Central 
Europe  and  Korea.  At  the  same  time,  ideological  and  diplomatic, 
and  economic  and  military  conflict  has  been  increasing.  This  is 
what  is  meant  by  the  cold  war  that  is  characteristic  of  a  world  of 
nations  increasingly  polarized  between  the  United  States  and  the 
Soviet  Union. 

The  enormous  range  and  the  destructive  capacities  of  modern 
weapons  has  by  itself  made  for  a  great  increase  in  the  power 
wielded  by  central  decision-making  units.  This  process  was  al- 
ready forcefully  under  way  during  the  depression  of  the  thirties, 
for  at  that  time  the  various  efforts  of  central  governments  to  plan 
rather  than  drift  were  inaugurated  on  some  scale.  This  enhance- 
ment of  central  executi\e  power  has  occurred,  as  it  were,  blindly, 
and  it  has  been  acti\ely  implemented  by  the  deliberate  centraliza- 
tion policies  of  public  authorities.  The  result  is  an  ever-increasing 
bureaucratization. 

In  each  of  the  two  major  crises  of  modern  capitalist  societies— 
in  world  depression  and  in  world  war— central  planning  and  regu- 
lation and  the  enforcement  of  big  decisions  lead  men  of  power 
to  an  increasing  awareness  of  the  interdependence,  and  accord- 
ingly of  the  need  for  co-ordination,  of  all  major  institutional  orders. 
In  order  to  control  the  ramifications  of  key  decisions  in  one  field— 
for  instance,  the  unixersal  peacetime  draft  for  an  army— the  au- 
thorities have  promptly  to  consider  the  cumulative  effects  in  the 
educational  sphere:  the  decreasing  enrollments  of  institutions  of 
higher  learning,  the  threats  of  bankruptcy  for  small  colleges,  the 
long-run   scarcities   of  trained   professional   personnel   in   strategic 


458  DYNAMICS 

skill-groups,  and  so  on.  Or,  the  ramifications  into  the  economic  or- 
der: How  do  the  armies'  demands  for  equipment  affect  industry? 
the  state's  demands  for  "big  hardware"  and  the  public's  demands 
for  consumer  goods?  How  will  the  draft  affect  the  labor  force,  in 
agriculture,  in  industry?  How  about  the  equality  of  men  and 
women— shall  both  be  drafted?  If  so,  in  what  ratio?  at  what  age? 
for  how  long?  What  of  allies?  What  is  their  economic  and  military 
potential?  What  about  their  internal  cohesion  and  political  relia- 
bility? 

The  tensions  of  policy  alternatives  reverberate  throughout  the 
value  structure  of  modern  societies.  Religious  institutions  are  also 
affected,  as  clergymen  enter  the  discussion  with  teachers  and  other 
professionals  concerned  with  marriage  and  population  policies. 
"Moral  problems"  thus  come  to  the  fore,  and  decision-making 
groups  realize  that  their  decisions  touch  directly  or  indirectly 
upon  all  institutional  orders  of  society.  Accordingly  their  decisions 
must,  it  seems,  be  "total." 

Under  laissez-faire  conditions  of  the  nineteenth  century  the  vari- 
ous institutional  orders  were,  so  to  speak,  left  alone,  and  it  was 
taken  for  granted  that  harmony  would  win  out  in  a  process  of 
dynamic  oscillations,  of  minor  frictions  and  adjustments,  that 
would  end  up  in  a  new  "equilibrium."  Today  such  a  spontaneous 
balancing  can  no  longer  be  assumed,  nor  can  harmony  be  left  to 
chance.  Hence,  the  top  decisions  tend  increasingly  to  be  "co- 
ordinated" decisions  and  to  ramify  throughout  institutional  orders; 
so  decision-makers,  when  speaking  of  "calculated  risks,"  anticipate 
long-range  consequences.  The  decision  to  "go  all  out"  in  an  arma- 
ment race,  for  example,  goes  together  with  purchasing  programs 
for  stockpiling  strategically  significant  raw  materials  in  the  hegem- 
ony area,  and  the  U.S.  demand,  as  the  universal  protector  of  the 
Western  orbit,  to  blockade  the  Soviet  orbit.  These  decisions,  in 
turn,  affect  the  weaker  economies  of  other  nations: 

Raw  material  countries  may  raise  their  price  levels.  Weak  im- 
porting industrial  countries  may  feel  their  export  opportunities 
threatened  under  conditions  of  rising  costs  of  production.  Debtor 
nations  may  see  their  relation  to  creditors  badly  affected,  as  well 
as  fear  for  their  economic,  pohtical,  and  psychological  stability, 
should  mass  unemployment  emerge.  These  national  fears  are  due 
to  cumulative  international  processes  often  beyond  the  control  of 
the  nations  involved. 


MASTER     TRENDS  459 

It  is  because  of  such  specific  consequences  as  these  that  deci- 
sions tend  to  become  total,  and  the  pohtical  decisions  of  parties 
and  cabinets  to  become  key  decisions.  Certain  goals  stand  out  in 
relatively  clear  focus,  as  military  and  economic  targets,  and  the 
time  required  for  their  realization  can  be  predicted  within  rela- 
tively narrow  limits.  Up  to  a  point,  moreover,  their  ramifications 
into  various  institutional  orders  can  be  assessed.  But  beyond  a 
given  point,  chances  have  to  be  taken.  It  is  then  that  trained  and 
imaginative  judgment  seems  scarce,  is  highly  premiumed,  and  leads 
to  plaintive  feelings  among  executives  in  political,  military,  and 
business  life  about  the  shortage  of  qualified  successors.  This  feel- 
ing, in  turn,  leads  to  an  increasing  concern  with  the  training  of 
successors  who  could  take  over  as  older  men  of  power  retire. 

The  repeated  experience  of  "boomerangs"— the  unintended  and 
unstated  consequences  of  key  decisions— leads  to  mass  disillusion- 
ment and  to  the  apathetic  withdrawal  of  groups  whose  willing 
support,  or  at  least  readiness  "to  go  along,"  is  indispensible  for 
implementing  expected  changes.  In  postwar  Germany,  Hitler's 
phrase,  "The  Thousand  Year  Reich"  has  become  a  stock  phrase  for 
deriding  his  twelve-year  rule.  The  disillusionment  of  the  American 
public  with  Wilsonian  idealism  shortly  after  World  War  I,  and  with 
the  starry  objectives  of  the  Atlantic  Charter,  even  during  the  course 
of  as  well  as  after  World  War  II,  also  comes  to  mind.  In  fact, 
one  must  realize  that  the  mass  acceptance  of  false  or  insufficient 
definitions  of  reality— and  subsequent  disappointment— is  now  a 
recurrent  feature  of  the  opinion  processes  and  symbol  spheres  of 
the  great  powers. 

Continent-wide  publics  lack  the  flexibility  of  mind  which  char- 
acterizes the  ruling  few;  besides,  these  masses  are  expected  to  ha\e 
"faith"  in  these  changing  definitions  and  frequent  revisions  of 
images  of  reality.  For  such  publics,  the  rapid  succession  thus  con- 
stitutes a  process  of  profound  disillusionment,  comparable  to 
changes  of  creeds  in  other  times.  And  since,  nowadays,  these 
changes  occur  within  the  living  experience  of  a  single  generation, 
the  demand  for  forgetfulness  and  for  learning  new  definitions  of 
reality  make  many  men  lose  the  capacity  wholeheartedly  to  accept 
publicly  sponsored  or  official  definitions  of  their  situation.  At  the 
same  time,  "the  will  to  believe"  may  increase,  as  the  successful 
mass  propagation  of  demonologies  and  world  conspiracy  myths 
seems  to  indicate.   Thus,  propaganda  neurosis  on  the  one  hand. 


460  DYNAMICS 

and  fanatical  superstition  on  the  other,  tend  to  be  widely  diffused 
and  always  to  threaten  the  "small  still  voice  of  reason." 

The  great  increase  in  the  volume  of  official  secrets,  or  secret 
diplomacy,  of  security  demands,  reduces  the  amount  of  relevant 
information  available  to  the  mass  public.  "News  behind  the  news" 
becomes  a  ubiquitous  advertising  slogan,  aimed  at  the  suspicious 
public;  "newsletters"  are  addressed  to  small  circles  of  decision  mak- 
ers in  business,  political,  and  military  affairs.  The  U.S.  mass  media, 
under  corporate  business  control,  often  fail  to  "represent"  public 
opinion,  as  is  evidenced  by  the  frequent  disparity  between  the 
stand  taken  by  "the  organs  of  public  opinion"  and  the  electorate 
during  presidential  elections  since  1936. 

Instead  of  free  competition  and  unco-ordinated  "adjustments," 
there  are  planned  "relay  systems"  which  ramify  across  entire  insti- 
tutional orders.  Hence  "co-operation"  is  at  a  premium,  and  more- 
over, co-operation  from  a  multiplicity  of  leaders  all  of  whom  cannot 
always  be  informed  of  the  whys  and  the  wherefores  of  key  deci- 
sions. Rivalry  makes  for  secrecy;  it  is,  for  example,  in  the  nature 
of  modern  warfare  to  launch  formless  "surprise  attacks"  and  to 
exploit  old-fashioned  diplomatic  forms  as  mere  means  and  shadow 
boxing.  Accordingly,  there  is  much  competition  for  superior  morale, 
a  competition  open  to  the  eyes  of  world-wide  literate  groups  and 
their  publics,  organized  as  well  as  in  aggregate  condition. 

The  nature  of  key,  national  decisions,  in  summary,  involves  long 
range  perspectives  and  targets,  and  extended  and  complex  means- 
ends  schemes.  These  decisions  are  of  global  scope  and  they  cross 
institutional  orders  into  which  they  ramify  and  which  implement 
them.  There  is  about  such  institutional  mechanics  in  our  time  an 
unheard  of  "momentum,"  and  the  decisions,  accordingly,  are 
weighty  and  grave,  and  often  frightful.  They  affect  no  less  than  the 
future  of  mankind. 

2.  Psychological  Aspects  of  Bureaucracy 

All  these  bureaucratic  developments,  so  central  to  modern  so- 
ciety, may  be  accompanied  by  psychological  phenomena,  which,  in 
brief,  result  from  increased  stresses  upon  the  person  and  from 
problems  he  cannot  solve  by  "individual  adjustment." 

I.  An  increasing  number  of  employed  persons  find  themselves 
in  a  position  which  does  not  give  them  an  opportunity  to  take  stock 


MASTER     TRENDS  461 

of  their  whole  situation.  Their  working  environment  is  a  mere 
fragment  of  a  hierarchal  structure,  on  whose  total  proper  func- 
tioning they  are  dependent,  even  though  the  total  structure  and  its 
movements  are  not  intellectually  accessible  to  them.  Modern  em- 
ployees—the worker,  the  salesmen,  the  clerk— know  that  they  are 
dependent  on  the  decisions  of  others,  and  that  few  persons  have 
opportunities  to  attain  the  key  positions  from  which  day-to-day 
decisions  are  made.  Moreover,  the  specialized  knowledge  necessary 
for  decisions  makes  the  ordinary  individual's  intelligence  just  as 
fragmentary  as  is  his  environment.  He  does  not  choose  the  ends, 
for  they  are  set  for  him;  his  rational  knowledge  is  of  a  predeter- 
mined character  and  has  to  do  with  means.  The  traditionalist 
peasant,  in  contrast,  understands  "his  business, "  knows  many  of 
the  factors  which  affect  him,  and  the  rest  he  leaves  to  God  or  to 
other  supernatural  forces. 

II.  At  the  same  time,  the  bureaucratic  organizations  tend  to 
become  more  and  more  interdependent,  partly  because  the  politi- 
cal community  cannot  allow  for  the  breakdown  of  large-scale  insti- 
tutions under  private  management  and  motives— such  as  the  profit 
considerations  of  the  strongest  competitor.  In  an  expanding  econ- 
omy of  relatively  small  enterprises,  the  free  market  did  not  lead 
to  such  cumulative  repercussions  in  the  entire  social  structure. 
But  in  our  time  breakdowns  of  industrial  corporations  or  big  banks 
and  markets  have  enormous  consequences  for  all  members  of  so- 
ciety. The  government  is  therefore  increasingly  obliged  to  inter- 
vene and  to  support  by  special  political  measures  whole  industries 
and  sectors  of  social  life.  This  interventionism,  in  turn,  tends  fur- 
ther to  centralize  controls  and  to  increase  the  interdependence  of 
the  large  structures. 

III.  Should  crises  disrupt  the  social  process,  as  in  the  world 
crisis  of  the  thirties,  mass  unemployment  and  world-wide  insecurity 
are  among  the  consequences.  Even  a  "recession"  of  the  American 
economy  causes  anxiety  in  Western  Europe.  Given  the  instability 
and  difficulties  of  the  debtor  countries,  the  psychological  and  politi- 
cal consequences  of  a  major  crisis  would  be  unpredictable,  but  in 
any  event  disastrous  for  democratic  regimes  based  on  uneasy  coali- 
tions of  weak,  middle  parties.  As  long  as  unemployment  or  bank- 
ruptcy was  experienced  as  a  selecti\e  process  eliminating  the  in- 
efficient and  strengthening  the  efficient,  the  adversities  of  crises 
were  ascribed  to  personal  shortcomings.  The  underprivileged  per- 


462  DYNAMICS 

son  might  seek  to  extricate  himself,  and  by  and  large  each  strove 
as  best  he  could  to  find  his  way  out  of  the  strain  and  duress. 

But  when  in  such  crises  the  breakdown  is  of  the  scope  of  the 
last  world  slump,  individual  avenues  of  escape  are  insignificant, 
and  the  anxieties  of  underprivileged  persons  become  the  basis  for 
collective  readjustment.  In  due  course,  the  unemployed  person  may 
give  up  the  hope  of  finding  any  job,  his  former  aspirations  break 
down,  and  with  them,  the  hopes  and  policies  of  the  family  of  the 
breadwinner.  In  modern  society  insecurity  tends  to  be  experienced 
not  as  a  personal  mishap  or  misfortune,  nor  as  an  irrevocable  fate 
due  to  supernatural  forces  nor  even  to  natural  forces.  And  men, 
full  of  the  tension  of  insecure  positions  correctly  blame  social  fac- 
tors for  personal  defeat. 

IV.  It  is  under  such  conditions  that  beliefs  in  traditional  social 
and  political  values  may  be  shattered.  "Freedom,"  for  example, 
may  be  derided  as  "freedom  to  starve,"  and  unless  democratic 
leadership  succeeds  in  reconstructing  the  social  order,  or  in  pro- 
viding substitutes  for  former  institutions,  general  despair,  skepti- 
cism, and  a  debunking  type  of  agitation  are  likely  to  spread.  This 
was,  for  example,  the  course  German  society  took  during  the  eco- 
nomic crisis  of  the  early  thirties. 

V.  If  militantly  organized  political  parties  succeed  in  attracting 
general  attention,  if  they  play  successfully  on  the  frustrations  of 
socially  descending  and  disappointed  masses,  if  at  the  same  time 
they  promise  "miracles"  and  "salvation,"  then  fascist-type  move- 
ments find  their  opportunity,  especially  if  they  couple  revolution- 
ary tactics  with  nationalist  propaganda— if  they  succeed  in  using 
frustrations  and  anger  in  such  a  way  that  scapegoats  can  be  offered. 
The  scapegoat  provides  for  tension  release,  makes  for  strong  group 
loyalties,  and  heightens  the  belief  in  the  "reality"  of  the  propa- 
gandist symbols.  It  thus  makes  action,  such  as  terrorist  attacks 
against  Jews  and  working-class  organizations,  psychologically  pos- 
sible and  politically  effective. 

VI.  Such  revolutionary  or  pseudo-revolutionary  activities  give 
the  fighting  individual  new  aspirations  and  new  self-esteem,  now 
built  around  his  identification  with  the  new  organization  and  its 
"leader."  As  the  individual  breaks  away  from  all  formerly  held 
values,  cuts  off  many  former  social  obligations,  he  feels  "free"  al- 
though, in  fact,  he  is  enthusiastically  subjecting  himself  to  a  rigidly 
disciplined  organization,  a  political  demonology,  and  a  sanctioned 


MASTER     TRENDS  46;} 

image  of  reality.  However,  by  virtue  of  the  undemocratic  character 
of  its  organizational  pattern,  this  kind  of  movement  gives  the  indi- 
vidual feelings  of  security.  He  need  neither  make  decisions  nor 
think  for  himself.  He  has  merely  to  have  faith  and  carry  out  the 
plans  and  commands  of  the  party.  These  plans  and  commands, 
embodied  in  "the  party  line"  as  defined  from  on  high,  often  zig 
and  zag  in  incredible  patterns.  For  Communists  all  over  the  world, 
for  example,  the  last  war  was  an  "imperialist  war"— during  the 
Stalin-Hitler  alliance  of  1939  to  1941.  Then  Hitler  was  no  aggressor 
and  the  military  offensive  presented  not  "aggression,"  but  merely 
"the  best  defense,"  as  though  it  were  a  mere  tactical  question.  But 
with  Hitler's  attack  upon  the  Soviet  Union,  the  previously  "im- 
perialist war"  was  quickly  transformed  into  a  "people's  war,"  and 
despite  the  Russian  annexation  of  half  of  Poland,  Romania,  Bess- 
arabia and  what  was  formerly  Czechoslovak  Carpatho-Ukraine,  the 
Baltic  states,  Konigsberg,  Finnish  Karelia— the  Soviet  Union  by 
Communist  definition  never  practiced  but  only  fought  imperialism. 
Since  the  war,  the  retrospective  definition  of  "all  peace-loving  na- 
tions" (never  including  neutral  countries  such  as  Switzerland,  Ire- 
land, and  Sweden)  excludes  the  naval  democracies  of  the  West 
and  includes  all  former  allies  of  Hitler  once  they  are  inside  the 
Soviet  orbit  and  so  reorganized  into  "People's  Democracies."  Such 
are  the  changing  images  of  reality,  defined  from  on  high  and  offi- 
cially sanctioned.  Deviations  from  them  are  conventionally  and 
administratively  punished  as  indicating  disloyalty,  submission  to 
petty  bourgeois  or  to  ultra-rightist  or  ultra-leftist  thoughtways. 

The  totalitarian  party  state  is  not  oriented  to  the  pursuit  of 
personal  happiness;  it  demands  "sacrifice."  Life  is  serious;  "en- 
circlement" is  the  claustrophobic  theme.  The  Fascist  party  is  con- 
cerned with  the  attainment  of  political  power,  with  the  distribution 
of  spoils,  and  the  reorganization  of  society  for  military  conquest. 
With  the  attainment  of  political  power  and  the  organization  of 
social  life  in  a  totalitarian  manner,  the  problems  it  poses  become 
international.  For  as  long  as  the  party  member  feels  that  there  is 
any  power  which  might  possibly  check  his,  he  remains  an  aggres- 
sive person  with  the  one  objective  of  power. 

The  frustrated  party  spreads  its  psychology  of  anxiety  and  its 
compensatory  craving  for  power.  There  is  a  characteristic  emotional 
cycle  observable.  During  the  phase  of  preparatory  surprise  coups 
—Hitler,  for  example,  timed  them  on  week  ends— the  hate  cam- 


464  DYNAMICS 

paigns  are  built  to  a  mounting  crescendo.  At  the  same  time,  in- 
tense secrecy  places  all  official  personnel  and  the  party  machine 
on  guard.  The  irritability  and  nervousness  of  men  of  responsibility 
increases.  The  metropolitan  men-in-the-street  sense  an  ominous 
atmosphere  of  mounting  danger,  without  being  able  to  discern  its 
source.  This  sense  of  ominousness  heightens  mass  anxieties  inside 
and  outside  the  party.  Then  suddenly,  once  the  coup  has  been  suc- 
cessfully completed,  diffuse  awareness  is  replaced  by  maximum 
publicity  and  information;  the  leader  triumphantly  proclaims  his 
deed,  and  the  anxieties  give  way  to  a  public  orgy  of  boisterous 
heils,  jubilation,  and  frenzy.  It  is  then  that  "internal  enemies"  are 
hunted  down,  rounded  up,  and  thrown  into  concentration  camps. 

3.  The  Decline  of  Liberalism 

It  is  in  this  world  context  of  total  integrations  and  bureaucratiza- 
tion that  we  must  understand  the  decline  of  liberalism  as  a  style  of 
thinking  and  the  rise  and  spread  of  totalitarian  slogan  manipula- 
tion and  opinion  management.  For  the  problems  of  mass  insecur- 
ity and  of  anxiety  levels,  of  mental  imbalances  and  unclear  defi- 
nitions of  unstructured  situations  now  form  the  sociological  context 
of  political  and  economic  psychology. 

As  one  of  the  great  thought  systems  of  the  Western  world, 
liberalism  is  rooted  in  the  "enlightenment  movement"  of  the  Occi- 
dental middle  classes  and  their  intellectual  vanguards;  it  incor- 
porates the  legacy  of  Greece  and  of  Rome— a  legacy  which  has  been 
reassimilated  by  various  renaissances  since  the  waning  of  the  Mid- 
dle Ages.^ 

Liberalism  has  made  its  greatest  and  least  questioned  headway 
in  the  United  States.  In  Europe  it  has  met  with  older  and  more 
entrenched  patterns  having  elaborate  defensives  of  their  own. 
Among  these  have  been  Catholic  and  Protestant  orthodoxies,  often 
linked  with  modern  conservative  thinking,  and  anticapitalist  in- 
tellectuals and  parties.  From  the  "right"  and  from  the  "left"  anti- 
capitalist  thinking  has  emerged:  European  liberalism  has  been 
identified  with  "the  middle."  But  no  such  position  and  no  such  iden- 

1  See  L.  T.  Hobhouse,  Liberalism  (New  York:  Holt,  1911);  and  G.  De- 
Ruggiero,  The  History  of  European  Liberalism  ( Collingwood  Tr.,  London, 
1927)- 


MASTER     TRENDS  465 

tification  occurred  in  the  United  States,  where  hberahsm  has  be- 
come, at  least  as  rhetoric,  a  common  denominator. 

This  diflFerence  between  hberahsm  in  Europe  and  America  is 
due  to  many  factors,  but  the  most  important  of  them  is  the  fact 
that  in  Europe  capitahst  societies  developed  from  older  feudal 
structures,  which  were  never  entirely  displaced  but  which,  in  a 
number  of  ways,  were  transformed  and  adapted  to  new  societies. 
The  nobility  moved  from  the  military  camp  to  the  court,  becoming 
an  "office  nobility";  and  to  this  day  nobles  play  a  significant  part 
in  the  high  ranks  of  ecclesiastic  dignitaries  in  the  Roman  Catholic 
Church,  of  royalty  in  Lutheran  Scandinavian  countries,  and  in  the 
established  church  of  England.  Landlordism  in  Italy  and  Spain, 
in  France,  Great  Britain,  and  Germany,  although  affected  by  the 
complex  history  of  capitalism,  has  allowed  strong  feudal  elements 
to  adapt  themselves  and  so  survive  in  complicated  forms. 

The  rise  of  capitalist  society  in  Central  Europe  and  in  large 
areas  of  Eastern  Europe  did  not  involve  the  tiansfer  of  political 
and  military  power  to  the  economically  most  powerful  group— the 
urban  capitalist  middle  class.  Because  of  the  failure  of  the  1848 
revolutions,  and  the  complexities  of  national  formations  in  Italy, 
Germany,  and  Japan  during  the  second  half  of  the  nineteenth  cen- 
tury, princely  power,  although  reduced  in  prerogative,  maintained 
itself  in  the  status  structure  and  retained  its  prestigeful  influence 
among  intellectuals.  The  cultural  patronage  of  petty  courts  and 
nobles  continues  to  exist  in  some  European  societies  right  into 
the  present. 

To  all  this  the  United  States  is  the  great  exception,  for  here  there 
was  no  feudal  age,  and  from  their  beginnings  the  middle  classes 
combined  economic  ascendancy  and  expansion  over  a  continent- 
wide  territory  with  unhampered  dominance  of  economic  wealth 
and  monopoly  of  status  structures.  Their  monopoly  of  status  was 
facilitated  by  their  financing  of  numerous  prestigeful  institutions: 
art  collections  and  museums  bound  intellectual  and  cultural  elites 
to  the  "donors"  and  "philanthropists."  Educational  institutions, 
libraries,  colleges,  universities,  and  research  institutions  were  im- 
pressively endowed,  sponsored,  and  controlled  by  wealthy  "private" 
citizens,  and  the  dependent  personnel  became  indebted  to  them; 
if  they  were  not  sycophantic,  they  were  at  least  grateful. 

Wealth  in  the  United  States  also  asserted  itself  through  politics 
as  the  ascending  middle  class  became  the  upper  class  without  hav- 


466  DYNAMICS 

ing  to  compromise  with  ecclesiastic  or  monarchal  elements  or  with 
wealthy  elites  of  older  standing.  Nor  did  they  need  to  compromise 
in  military,  diplomatic,  and  cultural  areas  with  the  standards  or 
traditions  of  feudal  or  semifeudal  groups  clustering  around  the 
courts  of  landed  princes  and  nobles  or  state  university  chairs.  One 
has  of  course  to  make  allowance  for  the  "slavocracy"  of  the  southern 
plantation  society  as  quasi-feudal,  but  the  Civil  War  and  the  recon- 
struction period  eliminated  it  as  a  setup  not  having  clear-cut  capi- 
talist aspect. 

Political  and  economic  power,  religious  and  educational  institu- 
tions, military  and  judicial  elements  as  well  as  status  dominance- 
all  these  could  be  vested  in  the  hands  of  a  ruling  class  of  bourgeois 
extraction  and  composition.  Accordingly,  the  United  States  became 
the  great  scene  for  an  unadulterated  capitalist  society  and  a  busi- 
ness civilization  built  in  its  image. 

The  unique  situation  of  a  geographical  area  which  allowed 
continental  expansion  until  the  turn  of  the  twentieth  century,  and 
the  growth  of  a  nation  of  5  million  into  one  of  150  million  in  the 
short  span  of  150  years— this  made  liberalism  uniquely  fit  the  reality 
of  American  society.  For  liberalism  is  "generous":  it  requires  and 
assumes  a  friendly  universe  of  equal  and  open  opportunities,  and 
it  assumes  that  men  are  born  "free  and  equal."  Here,  the  coming 
of  the  immigrant  coincided  with  "unlimited  opporti_mities"  and  a 
"consciousness  of  abundance."  Liberalism  thus  found  its  affirma- 
tion in  the  daily  experience  of  millions  of  people  living  in  an  ex- 
panding society. 

Instrumental  and  efficiency  values  could  be  and  were  readily  seen 
as  one  with  moral  values.  Characteristically,  the  obvious  problem 
of  the  double-edged  nature  of  technology— capable  of  working  for 
good  or  for  evil— was  profoundly  and  insistently  impressed  upon  the 
American  public  mind  only  after  the  dropping  of  the  atom  bomb. 

In  America  the  marriage  of  science  and  technology,  and  the  joy- 
ful reliance  upon  the  values  of  efficiency,  did  not  entail  the  destruc- 
tion or  the  displacement  of  cultural  legacies,  which  in  Europe 
aroused  the  esthetic  and  nostalgic  reactions  of  men  in  "romantic 
agony."  Here  there  was  no  sense  of  tragic  loss,  for  on  virgin  territory 
such  romantic  sentiments  could  at  best  be  attached  to  the  lure  of 
distant  horizons  and  the  image  of  the  "noble  savage,"  who,  at  any 
rate,  upon  closer  view  seemed  more  savage  than  noble.  The  supe- 
riority of  the  white  man's  advancing  efficiency  over  the  primitive 


MASTER     TRENDS  467 

ways  of  the  Indian  never  led  to  doubts  about  God-willed  steward- 
ship. Besides,  "these  illiterate  savages"  could  neither  work  steadily 
in  the  fields  nor  read  the  Bible  or  the  catechism;  hence  all  the 
easier  the  slogan,  "the  only  good  Indian  is  a  dead  Indian."  Their 
displacement  led  to  no  more  travail  than  that  of  other  preliterate 
societies  on  the  widening  colonial  frontiers  of  the  "expansion  of 
Europe." 

The  widening  of  economic  opportunities  and  the  extension  of 
the  territorial  setting  of  United  States  society  went  hand  in  hand 
and  reinforced  each  other,  as  did  technical  progress  and  the  rising 
levels  of  skill  and  education.  Entrepreneurial,  propertied  groups, 
in  urban  as  well  as  rural  sectors  of  the  society,  pulled  in  the  same 
direction:  both  have  been  money-minded  groups  which  took  the 
competitive  market  for  granted. 

In  this  setting,  the  social  costs  and  liabilities  of  capitalism  could 
be  overlooked,  in  fact,  many  of  them  could  be  socially  defined  as 
ethnic  peculiarities  of  immigrant  minorities,  and  hence  not  truly 
American.  The  anticapitalist  sentiments  of  protesting  intellectuals 
such  as  John  Ruskin  or  Thomas  Carlyle  could  not  perturb  the 
onrushing  multitude  in  its  "pursuit  of  happiness." 

The  dominance  of  Puritanism,  with  its  conception  of  property  as 
"stewardship,"  cast  a  religious  halo  about  the  successful,  and  the 
secularization  of  Puritanism  could  easily  make  for  the  self-righteous 
identification  of  "success"  in  this  world  with  the  complacent  sense 
of  being  "blessed  by  God."  This  was  all  the  more  possible  as  prop- 
erty was  for  a  long  time  work-property,  and  the  linkage  between 
such  personal  virtues  as  diligence  and  initiative,  persistence  and 
hard  work,  with  property  was  highly  and  widely  visible.  Mass 
literature,  from  juveniles  to  human  interest  stories  and  novels,  suc- 
ceeded in  publicizing  the  lore  of  success  and  the  romance  of  those 
who  had  made  it:  the  titans,  the  tycoons,  the  robber  barons,  the 
founding  fathers,  the  pioneers,  the  technological  heroes.  Such  men, 
standing  at  the  center  of  popular  attention,  have  proxided  popu- 
lar models  of  aspiration.  In  American  society  nothing  has  been  able 
to  rival  such  affirmations  of  the  efficient,  successful  heroes  of 
liberalism. 

In  other  countries,  Germany  for  example,-  the  middle-class  in- 

2  See  Paul  Kosok,  Modern  Germany  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1933); 
Max  Weber,  From  Max  Weber  .  .  .  ,  op.  cit.,  pp.  363-85. 


^68  DYNAMICS 

dustrialists  who  had  economic  power  did  not  thereby  have  status 
and  power  in  pohtical,  educational,  or  religious  orders.  For  princely 
power  continued,  entrenched  in  Bismarck's  constitution  of  1870- 
1918,  that  underpinned  the  position  of  nobles  in  diplomatic  and 
officer  corps,  in  Protestant  church,  and  student  association.  Access 
to  such  positions  was  denied  (he  bourgeoisie,  which  accordingly  was 
forced  to  adapt  feudal  and  bureaucratic  prestige  models,  to  seek 
intermarriage  with  nobles,  to  purchase  titles:  in  short,  to  renounce 
liberalism. 

The  course  of  Japan  is  comparable,  except  in  its  case,  the  lower 
nobility  absorbed  capitalist  business  and,  in  the  absence  of  a 
productive  middle  class  in  the  Western  style,  assimilated  the 
corporate  phase  of  capitalism  to  the  feudal  ways  of  noble  and 
military  clan.^ 

In  Britain,*  repeated  compromises  between  landed  gentry  and 
court  society,  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  political  and  economic 
ascendancy  of  the  new  entrepreneurial  class  on  the  other,  led  to  an 
integrative  process  in  which  rentier  strata  of  feudal  aristocrats  and 
urban  patricians  could  fuse  in  exclusive  clubs  and  hold  their  own 
in  navy  and  army,  in  "society"  and  diplomacy.  In  this  they  were 
aided  by  the  "public  school"  pattern  and  a  widespread  system  of 
scholarships  which  implemented  educational  opportunities  and 
made  for  the  staying  power  of  feudal  elements  as  well  as  for  the 
ascending  bourgeois  elements.  The  liberal  heritage  was  thus  assimi- 
lated to  the  reconstructed  conservative  thinking  of  Edmund  Burke 
and  his  successors. 

In  Russia,  capitalism  was  tied  in  with  foreign  (largely  French) 
political  and  strategic  loans. ^  In  the  short  period  from  the  eman- 
cipation of  the  serfs  in  1861  to  the  revolution  of  1917,  this  capitalism 
did  not  allow  an  economically  independent  and  politically  self- 
reliant  middle  class  to  emerge.  Moreover,  the  agrarian  problems  of 
Tsarist  Russia  coincided  with  the  oppressive  social  evils  of  early 
industrialization.  The  peculiarities  of  the  Russian  agrarian  com- 
mune, and  the  quasi-religious  fervor  of  the  intelligentsia  provided 

3  See  the  excellent  monograph,  E.  Herbert  Norman,  Japan's  Emergence  as 
a  Modern  State   (New  York:    Institute  of  Pacific  Relations,   1946). 

*  See  Wilhelm  Dibelius,  Eng,land:  Its  Character  and  Genius,  M.  A.  Hamilton, 
tr.   (New  York:   Harper,   1930). 

^  See  Leon  Trotsky,  The  History  of  the  Russian  Revolution,  Max  Eastman, 
tr.   (New  York:   Simon  &  Schuster,   1936). 


MASTER     TRENDS  46g 

a  barren  soil  for  the  ideas  of  Western  liberalism.  In  addition  to  the 
illiterate  peasant  masses,  there  was  the  Eastern  Orthodox  Church, 
and  the  oppressive  weight  of  the  Tsarist  office  and  court  nobihty. 
There  was  the  anti-Western  turn  of  writers  such  as  Tolstoi  and 
Dostoevski,  of  the  Slavophiles  and  populists,  whether  repentant 
noblemen,  or  proletarian  writers  such  as  Maxim  Gorki;  and  there 
was  the  anticapitalist  turn  of  the  nihilist,  anarchist,  and  socialist 
intellectuals,  acting  as  the  conscience  of  their  time  and  people. 
Accordingly,  liberalism  as  a  temper  of  mind  or  as  a  political  system 
had  little  ground  in  which  to  take  root. 

Since  World  War  I,  the  international  scene,  as  it  bears  on  the 
fate  of  liberalism,  has  been  greatly  changed:  Nationalist  restriction- 
ism  and  economic  protectionism  has  led  to  increasing  stress  and 
strain.''  The  United  States,  as  well  as  the  dominions  and  colonies 
of  the  British  Empire,  closed  their  doors  to  immigration,  and  so  the 
great  nineteenth-century  mobility  of  populations  ceased.  Currency 
policies  and  protective  tariffs  fenced  off  economic  areas  against 
unwanted  competitors  and  deadlocked  the  market  system.  The  rise 
of  large  corporations  and  monopolistic  practices  made  for  a  new 
scene,  which  no  longer  lent  itself  to  liberal  models  of  social  reflec- 
tion. There  was  a  "scarcity  consciousness"  in  regard  to  educational 
and  to  job  opportunities,  in  regard  to  migratory  opportunities,  and 
e\'en  the  marriage  opportunities  for  women  in  the  war-decimated 
nations  after  the  two  world  wars.  "Free  and  open  competition," 
instead  of  rationing  and  planful  administration  of  market  processes, 
now  becomes— as  in  postwar  Germany— a  mechanism  for  distribut- 
ing what  is  to  be  had,  in  which  the  physically  weak,  the  morally 
scrupulous,  the  politically  unorganized  are  pushed  to  the  side. 
Those  who  in  the  eastern  areas  of  Europe  have  lost  everything  they 
once  had— their  farms,  houses,  businesses,  and  skilled  jobs— were  the 
last  to  find  jobs  for  themselves  and  opportunities  for  their  children 
in  the  west.  As  "new  citizens"  they  are  unwanted  competitors, 
walled  out  by  the  competitive  endeavor  of  the  older  residents  to 
build  fences  where\'er  possible  around  preferred  opportunities. 

Liberalism  under  such  conditions  means  free  competition  for  all 
vested   groups— from   trade   unions   to   businessmen's   associations, 

6  See  E.  H.  Carr,  The  Twenty  Years'  Crisis  (London,  1949)  and  The  New 
Society  (London:  Macniillan,  1951). 


^JO  DYNAMICS 

from  villages  to  metropolitan  communities  and  new  states— to  build 
fences.  The  highminded  endeavors  of  welfare  bureaucracies  might 
soften  and  mitigate  and  channel  the  pressures,  but  they  have  not 
prevented  the  emergence  of  irate,  embittered  mass  movements 
among  the  "disinherited."  Mass  unemployment  and  impoverish- 
ment remains  a  lasting  threat,  despite  the  phoenixlike  upswing 
of  the  Western  German  economy  with  American  aid. 

Such  facts  can  no  longer  be  viewed  as  temporary  or  exceptional; 
in  present-day  contexts  the  incongruity  of  liberal  ideologies  with 
modern  social  facts  are  glaringly  evident.  The  sense  of  an  open 
horizon  of  unlimited  opportunities  is  gone;  competition  as  a  fair 
and  equitable  way  for  mating  merit  and  compensation  is  no  longer 
believed  in.  The  competitive  group  pressures  of  society  appear  to 
many  as  "rackets,"  and  freedom  takes  on  the  attributes  not  of 
rational  and  moral  self-determination  among  neighbors  but  of  a 
Hobbesian  jungle  where  the  "elastic  man,"  the  man  without  con- 
science, fends  for  himself  with  tooth  and  claw,  a  lone  wolf  in  an 
unfriendly  universe. 

Such  sentiments  and  feelings  of  bitter  frustration  are  greatest 
where  "competition  among  unequals"  prevails— in  the  commodity 
market,  where  little  and  big  units,  with  quite  different  capital  assets 
and  capacities  for  risk,  meet  in  "free  and  open  competition";  where 
the  little  man  risks  his  all  and  the  big  corporation  risks  practically 
nothing;  where  economic  heavyweights  are  free  to  knock  out  fly- 
weight competitors. 

In  international  relations,  the  economically  strong  country  trans- 
fers the  burden  of  unemployment  to  weaker  countries  by  maintain- 
ing an  active  balance  of  trade  in  its  favor,  and  by  attracting  what- 
ever capital  takes  to  "flight"  from  the  pressured  nation.  Thus,  in  the 
"family  of  nations"  economic  nationalism  disintegrates.  Interna- 
tional trade  dwindles,  a  common  currency  standard  does  not  exist, 
weaker  nations  are  indebted  to  strong  creditors,  who  refuse  to 
accept  imports  which  alone  can  serve  as  payment.  Hence  debtor 
countries  mortgage  or  sell  their  land  and  other  capital  assets  to 
creditor  nations,  and  are  virtually  reduced  to  colonial  status. 

As  in  trade,  so  in  war  and  diplomacy:  a  weak  state  may  be 
peacefully  carved  up— as  was  Czechoslovakia  at  Munich  by  Hitler 
and  Mussolini  with  the  assistance  of  Chamberlain  and  Daladier. 
Strong  powers  do  not  deem  it  honorable  to  live  up  to  treaty  com- 
mitments unless  it  is  expedient  to  do  so.  In  1914  the  Kaiser's  chan- 


MASTER     TRENDS  4/1 

cellor  still  expressed  guilt  feelings  about  the  invasion  of  Belgium 
and  the  breaking  of  neutrality  treaties,  but  great  powers  now 
project  alleged  acts  of  "aggression"  upon  the  prospective  victim, 
however  helpless  and  weak,  of  their  attack.  In  the  world  of  na- 
tions today  might  makes  right  and  all  is  fair  in  war.  And  when 
the  shooting  pauses,  not  moral  and  legal  norms  but  the  de  facto 
principles  of  action  and  power  in  a  world  at  war  is  the  order  of 
the  age. 

Industrialized  peoples  adjust  to  these  changes  by  building  up 
huge  "pressure  groups"  which  emerge  out  of  the  upward  and  down- 
ward shifts  in  economic  opportunities  for  the  aggregates  of  people 
in  common  class  situations.  These  pressure  groups  seek,  on  various 
levels,  to  translate  their  organized  power  into  policy  decisions.  The 
price  of  bread  thus  becomes  as  much  a  political  price  as  are  the 
rents  of  tenement  houses.  "Bloc  competition"  and  "bloc  bargaining" 
replace  the  competitive  scatter  of  small  units;  strivings  for  security 
replace  the  sense  of  joyful  individual  initiative;  feelings  of  solidarity 
become  more  important  than  self-reliance.  Self-help  becomes  a  joke, 
and  "breaking  out  of  line,"  that  is,  lack  of  loyalty  to  one's  organized 
comrades  or  colleagues  or  the  "business  community"  becomes  just 
short  of  a  crime.  The  term  "self-made  man"  becomes  slightly  em- 
barrassing; inherited  wealth  is  believed  a  prerequisite  for  high 
status;  and  the  glamour  of  "the  heiress"  becomes  equivalent  if  not 
superior  to  the  majesty  of  an  old-world  princess. 

In  the  face  of  all  these  changes,  Liberalism  as  an  ideology  be- 
comes "formalized";  it  becomes  a  political  rhetoric  which  is  in- 
creasingly meaningless  and  banal  to  large  masses.  The  prereq- 
uisites for  the  classic  "freedoms"  espoused  in  its  name  are  often 
simply  not  available,  and  hence  its  classic  tenets  are  easily  per- 
verted.' 

Social  and  psychological  changes  of  a  wide  and  deep  sort  thus 
undermine  the  moorings  of  liberalism.  In  the  face  of  such  changes, 
cynical  upper  classes  may  be  ready  to  discard  the  democratic 
legacy  and  allow  or  support  policies  that  end  in  a  totalitarian  so- 
ciety of  Fascist  or  Nazi  type.  In  industrial  societies,  such  move- 

^  See  John  Hallovvell,  The  Decline  of  Liberalism  as  an  Ideology  ( Berkeley 
and  Los  Angeles:  Univ.  of  California  Press,  1943).  For  countertendencies, 
however,  see  Morton  G.  White,  "The  Revolt  against  Formalism  in  American 
Social  Thought  of  the  Twentieth  Centur>-,"  Journal  of  the  History  of  Ideas, 
Vol.  VIII,  No.  2,  April  1947,  pp.  131-52. 


^^2  DYNAMICS 

ments  have  arisen  at  times  when  the  power  of  labor  was  dechning, 
as  in  Italy  after  the  revolutionary  upsurge  of  the  post-World  War 
I,  and  in  Germany,  as  labor's  strength  was  enervated  by  depression, 
and  unemployment  led  to  mass  agony.  On  both  occasions,  terrorist 
organizations  were  subsidized  and  turned  loose  on  labor,  and  the 
labor  press  suppressed,  as  chauvinist  frenzy  replaced  rational  public 
debate.  Hero  worship  drowned  the  competition  in  rational  ideas 
and  arguments  in  public.  The  policy  of  the  street,  the  assassination 
of  leaders,  the  orgiastic  howling  and  pogroms  against  scapegoated 
minority  groups  implemented  the  transitions.  A  political  landslide 
occurred  among  the  masses,  and  after  some  bargaining  and  com- 
promising, the  old  elites  fused  with  the  ascending  political  move- 
ment, which  established  its  own  brand  of  dictatorship.  Society  was 
put  on  a  war  footing. 

Totalitarianism  is  an  imperialist  response  to  the  impasse  of  cor- 
porate capitalism.  It  is  a  twentieth-century  response,  occurring  in 
a  time  when  scarcity  consciousness  prevails  and  when  to  many 
liberal  ideologies  seem  hollow.  Despite  its  destruction  in  Central 
Europe  by  the  last  war,  neo-Fascist  and  neo-Nazi  tendencies  have 
appeared  in  Western  Germany  and  Italy.  Nobody  could  call  Peron's 
or  Tito's  or  De  Gaulle's  program  liberal  democracy;  and  nobody 
can  call  Franco  Spain  anything  but  a  fascist  dictatorship.  In  France 
and  Italy  close  to  one-third  of  the  electorate  demonstratively  and 
persistently  votes  Communist.  Only  the  complacent  and  the  unin- 
formed can  feel  assured  of  liberal  and  democratic  developments  in 
the  world  today. 

4.  Character  Structure  in  a  Polarized  World 

On  the  one  hand,  there  is  the  U.S.S.R.,  the  world's  greatest  land 
power,  extending  its  sway  across  the  Eurasian  land  mass,  from  the 
Thuringian  mountains  to  the  Pacific  coast  and  including  in  its  orbit 
the  vast  areas  of  China.  On  the  other  hand,  there  is  the  U.S.A.,  the 
world's  greatest  industrial  and  naval  power,  including  in  its  con- 
tinental reach  the  greatest  agricultural  production  basin  on  the 
globe,  and  rallying  the  somewhat  unstable  British  Commonwealth 
of  Nations,  France  and  her  shaky  empire,  Western  Germany,  Italy, 
and  other  Mediterranean  countries.  By  their  existence  and  policies, 


MASTER     TRENDS  4/3 

such  hegemony  powers  as  the  U.S.  and  the  U.S.S.R.  define  new 
"in-group"  and  "out-group"  situations  within  and  between  nations. 

There  are,  to  be  sure,  anxious  endeavors  to  "build  bridges, "  to 
find  "common  ground,"  to  prevent  conflict  from  spreading,  to  win 
peace.  The  British  have  been  eager— and  successful  in  spite  of  the 
United  States'  misgivings— to  maintain  trade  relationships  with  the 
Soviet  Union  and  with  Communist  China.  Yet  "the  war  of  words," 
the  voting  patterns  of  governmental  representatives  in  the  United 
Nations  meetings  and  other  diplomatic  conferences,  have  made  the 
una\ailability  of  "harmonious  co-existence"  obvious.  The  big  powers 
have  shown  a  competitive  eagerness  to  integrate  their  respective 
alignments.  The  minor  powers,  in  their  fear,  have  sought  protection 
under  the  air  umbrellas  of  the  leading  powers,  and  such  "protec- 
tion" is  of  course  secured  only  by  the  "obedience"  of  the  weak. 

All  countries  are  now  interdependent,  but  all  countries  are  also 
now  directly  or  indirectly  dependent  upon  the  dollar  or  the  ruble 
standard,  upon  what  the  United  States  or  the  Soviet  Union  does  or 
fails  to  do.  Each  can  rely  on  a  "voting  discipline"  among  its  minor 
partners,  debtor  states,  satellites,  and  proteges.  The  "United  Na- 
tions" are  disunited  and  engaged  in  "cold  war."  The  Eastern  bloc 
uses  the  legal  veto  and  the  Western  bloc  the  de  facto  veto  by 
majority  vote;  and  some  powers,  great  and  small,  remain  outside 
the  "United  Nations."  There  is  no  undivided  court  of  "world 
opinion,"  and  in  our  time,  long  before  a  shooting  war  begins,  the 
propaganda  and  prestige  battles  are  underway  to  put  the  potential 
enemy  in  the  wrong,  to  win  the  sympathy  of  potential  allies,  to 
secure  at  least  benevolent  neutrality  from  the  rest.  Since  industrial 
nations  have  become  literate,  and  ever  larger  masses  of  people 
have  come  into  the  political  order— regardless  of  constitution— an 
increasing  array  of  values  and  institutions  has  been  used  for  po- 
litical purposes. 

World  War  II  revealed  war  leaders  who  would  state  neither 
their  war  aims  nor  their  peace  aims,  beyond  "victory"  or  "uncondi- 
tional surrender,"  which  meant  the  same  thing.  In  fact,  since  World 
War  I,  statesmen,  for  the  benefit  of  mass  sentiments,  haxe  vilified 
one  another  as  war  criminals  and  threatened  to  hang  one  another. 
Since  \\'orld  War  II  they  Jiacc  hanged  one  another.  To  be  sure, 
the  victors  give  the  vanquished  a  fair  trial  before  they  hang  them, 
but  then,  soon  after  the  trial,  the  judges,  falling  into  disagreement. 


474  DYNAMICS 

may  accuse  one  another  of  being  "war  criminals,"  and  retroactively 
revise  their  wartime  roles. ^ 

Let  us  consider  this  polarized  world  in  its  military  and  in  its 
industrial  aspects  and  as  we  do  so,  let  us  keep  in  mind  that  these 
are  not  far-flung  structures  alien  to  the  human  beings  of  the  twen- 
tieth century,  but  that  they  are  in  fact  crucial  parts  of  the  condi- 
tions that  make  and  are  made  by  men  and  women. 

Since  the  Louisiana  purchase  and  the  definition  of  its  north  and 
south  borders,  the  United  States  has  been  practically  free  of  mili- 
tary neighbors.  Its  growth  into  the  mightiest  sea  power  was  more 
or  less  certain.  World  War  I  ended  with  naval  parity  between  Great 
Britain  and  the  United  States;  World  War  II  led  to  U.S.  industrial 
and  naval  dominance.  Today  global  strategy  for  the  West  is  worked 
out  in  Washington;  Great  Britain  has  become  an  indebted  junior 
partner. 

"The  West"  represents  naval  and  air  power  opposed  to  "the 
East's"  land  power.  The  East  cannot  hope  to  conquer  the  West 
without  sea  power;  the  West  cannot  hope  to  conquer  the  East 
without  land  power. 

The  industrialization  of  Europe,  its  urbanization  and  population 
growth  despite  emigration  losses  during  the  nineteenth  century, 
made  Europe  less  and  less  autarchic,  more  and  more  dependent 
upon  raw  material  areas  overseas.  Hitler  shouted,  "Germany  must 
export  or  die,"  and  in  fact,  this  holds  for  all  the  industrial  countries 
of  Europe.  They  have  to  import  food  and  raw  materials  from  out- 
side Europe. 

It  is  this  fact  that  accounts  for  the  efficiency  of  naval  wars  of 
attrition  against  the  central  powers  during  World  War  I,  and 
against  the  "Axis"  during  World  War  II.  Germany's  conquest  of 
the  larger  part  of  European  Russia,  of  Northern  and  Eastern 
Europe,  could  not  compensate  for  the  blockade.  Naval  blockade, 
combined  with  war  purchases  of  what  was  to  be  had  in  neutral 
countries,  proved  unbeatably  effective  weapons  of  attrition  in  the 

^  Thus,  a  Congressional  committee  of  the  United  States  hears  testimony 
of  a  hooded  Pohsh  immigrant,  of  a  Polish  officer,  of  a  German  general, 
against  Russia  to  prove  Russian  war  crimes  in  the  forests  of  Katyn.  The 
Russians  resume  their  early  war-time  tlieme  of  "imperialist  powers"  being 
guilty  of  aggression  all  along— the  military  offensive  being  but  a  technical 
question.  See  the  New  York  Times,  April  20  and  21,  1952,  and  Milton  R.  Kon- 
vitz,  "Will  Nuremberg  Ser\e  Justice?,"  Commentary,  Vol.  I,  No.  3,  January 
1946,  pp.  9-15. 


MASTER     TRENDS  4/5 

hand  of  the  West.  The  miHtary  coup  de  grace  could  be  adminis- 
tered through  the  invasion  of  Europe  when  a  weakened  mihtary 
structure  was  crumbling  in  the  East,  and  disintegration  was  aided 
by  a  saturation  bombing  of  cities  that  greatly  softened  the  re- 
sources, disrupted  railroad  communication  and  the  industrial  foun- 
dations of  military  strength. 

But:  this  constellation  of  sea  power  versus  land  power,  which 
was  elaborated  theoretically  by  Mahan  and  demonstrated  prac- 
tically to  pre-industrial  Europe  during  the  Napoleonic  age,  differs 
from  the  present  confrontation  of  American  sea  power  and  Rus- 
sian land  power. 

The  Soviet  orbit  is  not  necessarily  economically  dependent  upon 
outside  resources.  It  contains  all  the  vital  raw  materials— food,  fiber, 
metal,  and  oil.  And  it  can— as  the  history  of  Russia's  industrial  de- 
velopment has  shown— develop  its  own  resources.  To  be  sure,  skill 
levels  are  comparatively  low,  but  so  are  the  costs  of  labor  and  the 
levels  of  mass  consumption.  There  has  been  and  will  be  "compul- 
sory savings"  for  the  formation  of  capital,  forced  upon  agrarian 
masses  by  bureaucratically  planned  decisions. 

Military  power  depends  upon  industrial  power,  and  so  the  t\vo 
power  blocs  of  the  world  are  now  engaged  in  an  armament  race 
and  in  an  industrial  race.  The  West  realizes  that  the  nonindus- 
trialized  areas— long  exploited  as  raw-material  areas— are  socially 
unstable,  economically  deteriorating,  politically  shaky,  and  ideolog- 
ically open  to  Soviet  influence.  They  can  be  "Western"  in  orienta- 
tion only  at  the  cost  of  industrialization  under  Western  aegis. 
Africa,  India,  and  the  Middle  East  are  crucial,  and  development 
projects  in  Africa  such  as  the  Point  Four  Program— and  schemes 
to  develop  skills  in  the  Far  East— indicate  the  drift. 

Regardless  of  the  enormity  of  institutional  diversity  and  psycho- 
logical types,  the  trend  with  the  widest  scope  and  the  most  far- 
reaching  ramifications  is  the  industrialization  of  the  world.  The 
key  importance,  in  fact,  of  the  rise  of  the  Soviet  Union  to  great 
international  stature  lies  in  this  simple  fact:  for  the  first  time  in 
the  intricate  history  of  the  industiial  revolution  men  can  now  see 
that  this  industrialization  does  not  require  capitalism  as  an  institu- 
tional framework,  that  it  can  be  accomplished  without  depending 
upon  private  initiati\e,  and  that  when  it  is  carried  out  by  state 
bureaucrats,  industrialization  can  even  be  a  more  rapid  and  orderly 


476  DYNAMICS 

process  than  when  carried  out  by  private  capitaHsts  running  private 
firms  for  private  profits. 

Russia  has  reversed  America's  industrial  sequence:  Whereas  un- 
planned industrialization  under  free,  private  initiative  has  pro- 
ceeded from  "light"  consumer  goods  industries  to  heavy  industries, 
Soviet  planning  has  assigned  priority  to  electric  power,  metallurgy, 
and  other  war-important  industries.  In  Russia,  modern  industrial 
civilization  did  not  emerge  autonomously  as  a  slow-motion  process 
from  medieval  guilds  and  burghers,  with  the  rise  of  a  middle  class. 
Industrialization,  in  its  late  nineteenth-  and  twentieth-century 
phase  of  corporate  or  monopoly  capitalism,  entered  the  "back- 
ward" agrarian  society  of  Tsarist  Russia  in  the  usual  forms  of 
political    capitalism,    governmentally   promoted   and   subsidized. 

Under  Stalin's  leadership,  industrialization  has  been  imposed  in 
the  great  pushes  of  the  "Five-Year  plans."  Soviet  men  and  women 
have  been  rallied  behind  the  party  and  its  plans  by  propaganda 
campaigns  and  excessive  orders.  An  agrarian  revolution  from  above, 
at  the  price  of  a  famine  costing  two  and  a  half  million  lives,  has 
accompanied  this  industrialization.  But  the  industrialization  has 
been  accomplished,  not  in  any  cumulative,  competitive,  and  adap- 
tive way,  but  in  the  form  of  centrally  enacted  and  imposed  changes 
under  the  leadership  of  a  totalitarian  one-party  state,  engaged  in 
successive  campaigns  to  transform  traditionalist  agrarian  societies, 
primordial  tribes,  and  congeries  of  nations  in  varied  stages  of 
cultural  development.  The  last  war  allowed  the  Soviet  Union  to 
emerge  as  the  world's  greatest  land  power,  and  this  power  is  now 
reinforced  by  Bolshevized  Eastern  European  countries  and  revo- 
lutionized China.  For  we  must  remember  that  Russia  lost  a  war 
with  Japan  in  1904-05,  and  again,  with  Germany,  in  1914-17.  The 
triumphant  advance  of  the  Soviet  Union  and  her  "indefinite  occu- 
pation" of  Central  Europe  with  a  boundary  line  only  eighty-five 
miles  from  France  has  made  her  victory  over  Nazi  Germany  a 
victory  over  old  Europe.  The  Nazi  drive  to  the  East  has  resulted 
in  the  Soviet  drive  to  the  West. 

The  United  States,  on  the  other  hand,  consummated  its  indus- 
trialization and  nation-building  in  the  span  of  one  and  a  half  cen- 
turies under  conditions  that  were  ideal  for  the  rise  of  the  entre- 
preneurial middle  class  under  laissez-faire  conditions  sanctioned 
by  liberalism." 

»  Cf.  above,  p.  355  fF. 


MASTER     TRENDS  47/ 

Technologically,  the  United  States  may  be  the  fulfillment  of  the 
Soviet  dream,  but  this  does  not  mean  that  the  United  States  is 
therefore  an  ideal  image  and  model  for  the  Soviet  world.  In  fact, 
the  Soviet  Union  has  many  assets  of  its  own  as  an  industrial  leader 
of  borderland  areas. 

Stalinist  communism,  in  the  phrase  of  G.  F.  Achminow,^"  is 
"substitute  capitalism."  For  many  peoples  of  the  world  the  master 
problem  of  our  time  is  simply  how  to  overcome  "backwardness," 
which  means,  how  to  industrialize  and  make  their  populations 
literate.  This  world  problem  of  rapid  industrialization  becomes 
acute  when  there  is  war,  or  when  there  is  the  loss  of  a  war,  or 
when  war  threatens,  or  when  dependency  upon  more  advanced 
states  becomes  for  any  reason  unbearable. 

The  success  of  communism,  in  those  areas  where  it  has  been 
successful,  may  be  due  to  the  simple  fact  that  capitalism— seated 
primarily  in  Northwestern  Europe  in  the  nineteenth  century,  and 
in  the  United  States,  Europe,  and  Japan  in  the  twentieth— has  not 
been  able  to  put  through  this  rapid  industrialization.  It  has  not 
been  able  to  industrialize  such  areas,  because  it  has  not  put  through 
the  "primary  accumulation"  necessary  for  building  up  a  productive 
apparatus  among  nations  composed  of  the  preindustrial  masses  of 
the  world.  But  communism— as  the  shadow  of  a  capitalism  that 
has  defaulted— is  able  to  do  so  by  virtue  of  its  public  management 
of  investment  policies.  The  communists  thus  flourish  on  the  failure 
of  capitalists  to  solve  this  world  historical  task. 

Everywhere  that  communists  have  come  to  power  we  find  a ' 
condition  in  which,  contrary  to  nineteenth-century  expectations, 
there  is  no  politically  effective  and  economically  strong  bourgeoisie. 
In  Russia  such  a  bourgeoisie  as  existed  was  dependent  upon  the 
political  commissions  of  a  despotic  state  and  on  foreign  loans. 
Wherever  capitalism  has  passed  beyond  such  weakling  beginnings 
and  become  of  sizable  stature  and  deep  political  entrenchment— 
as  in  Britain,  the  United  States,  and  Germany— communism  has 
not,  even  during  severe  depressions,  become  strong. 

The  success  of  communism  has  not  been  due  to  the  senescence 
of  mature  capitalism;  it  has  been  due  to  its  insufficient  develop- 
ment. 

1"  Die  Macht  im  Hintergrund:  Totengrdber  des  Kommunismus  (Spatenveriag 
Greunchen,  Ulm:  1950).  In  the  following  pages,  we  have  drawn  upon  this  in- 
teresting although  contradictory  book  by  a  postwar  Russian  refugee. 


478  DYNAMICS 

After  a  hundred  years  of  railroad  building  in  China,  the  Western 
nations  had  not  built  much  more  mileage  than  exists  in  tiny  Bel- 
gium. India,  enjoying  British  rule  and  guidance  for  over  150  years, 
has  built  few  cities  of  more  than  100,000  population.  Since  profits 
were  taken  out  of  these  countries,  there  was  no  investment  capital 
of  sufficient  size  for  the  task,  and  there  were  not  sufficient  political 
guarantees  nor  will  to  attract  private  investment  in  suitable 
amounts. 

But  the  Communist  Mao  Tse-tung  may  well  accomplish  "primary 
accumulations"  by  transforming  his  army  into  a  labor  force,  under 
military  discipline,  to  do  all  that  is  required  for  the  industrializa- 
tion of  China.  Mao  Tse-tung  takes  up  where  the  old  Confucian 
emperors  left  off:  his  tax  policy  in  labor  contributions,  however, 
does  not  result  in  the  building  of  big  stone  walls  or  imperial  tombs, 
but  in  the  industrialization  of  China.  If  his  policy  is  brutal— and 
it  is— one  must  bear  in  mind  Colbert's  use  of  the  French  army  and 
the  other  methods  used  by  European  civilizations  in  their  time  of 
primary  accumulation. 

There  are  apparent  exceptions  to  the  idea  of  communism  as 
substitute  capitalism.  There  is  the  voting  strength  of  communism 
in  pre-Hitler  Germany,  in  postwar  France,  Czechoslovakia,  and 
Italy.  France,  however,  was  liberated,  after  defeat  in  a  six  weeks' 
war,  only  by  her  allies,  who  made  her  a  victor— and  the  French 
know  it.  Italy,  especially  southern  Italy,  is  still  semifeudal  in  its 
agrarianism,  it  lacks  raw  materials,  and  it  has  had  to  pay  dearly 
for  Mussolini's  dream  of  a  "Third  Rome."  Communism  failed  re- 
peatedly and  disastrously  in  Germany.  Only  when  the  Red  army 
stood  in  the  country  or  close  by,  as  in  Czechoslovakia,  has  com- 
munism come  to  power  in  a  country  with  a  developed  capitalist 
economy. 

When  it  has  taken  over,  communism  has  co-ordinated  all  efforts 
by  dictatorial  imposition;  it  has  destroyed  pluralist  and  open-ended 
economic  and  jDolitical  endeavors.  Fascism  gathered  the  old  rulers 
together,  even  if  they  did  not  like  it,  and  supplemented  them  by 
newer,  gangster  types;  communism  has  replaced  the  old  ruling 
groups  by  new  ones  from  below. 

In  Achminow's  view,  three  conditions  are  necessary  and  sufficient 
for  the  rise  to  power  of  communism  within  a  society: 

( 1 )  The  society  must  be  on  a  level  of  development  in  which 
the  most  urgent  national  task  is  the  overcoming  of  the  backward- 


MASTER     TRENDS  479 

ness  of  rural  society  sweating  under  the  burden  of  feudal  rulers, 
usurious  capitalists,  and  a  national  debt.  Russia  of  1917,  and  China 
of  between  the  last  two  wars  certainly  fulfill  this  condition.  (2) 
The  existing  ruling  stratum  must  be  incapable  of  solving  this  task. 
Either  the  old  ruling  elements  misread  the  signs  of  the  times  and 
offer  desperate  resistance  to  change,  or  they  become  cynically  cor- 
rupt and  so  incapable  of  any  consistent  policy  that  might  solve  the 
tasks  they  confront.  (3)  There  must  be  people  who  are  able  to 
take  over  the  management  of  the  state,  but  who  under  pre-com- 
munist  conditions  have  had  no  chance  to  do  so.  This  means  a 
closure  policy  on  the  part  of  the  old  rulers,  or  simply  the  absence 
of  a  qualified  counterelite. 

Whenever  these  three  conditions  are  met,  there  is  a  chance  for 
communist  upheaval;  the  absence  of  any  one  of  them  precludes 
the  victory  of  communism,  although  for  strategic  reasons,  of  course, 
the  armed  force  of  the  Soviet  Union  could,  and  might,  try  to  impose 
it  from  without. 

In  the  conflict  of  East  and  West— of  the  United  States  and  the 
Soviet  Union— Europe  occupies  an  especially  important  position, 
if  only  because  of  its  cultural,  religious,  and  historical  ties  with  the 
white  populations  of  the  Western  Hemisphere.  It  is  also  important 
because  of  the  250  million  population  that  are  settled  on  this 
peninsula  of  Eurasia,  which  is  militarily  weak  in  the  neighborhood 
of  a  great  land  power  controlling  the  Baltic  Sea  and  producing 
atomic  bombs.  Europe  is  a  major  "prize"  of  the  contest  of  the 
two  great  powers.  Were  Europe  to  drift  or  to  be  shoved  into  the 
Russian  orbit.  Great  Britain  would  be  open  to  atomic  attacks  at 
close  range,  and  the  addition  of  skilled  populations  and  of  the 
Ruhr  industries  to  the  East  might  possibly  be  sizable  enough  to 
make  the  decisive  difference.  Inside  Europe,  rival  nations  and 
states— which  have  been  variously  realigning  themselves  for  cen- 
turies and  which  have  known  climactic  heights  of  prestige  and 
power— must  now  redefine  their  respectixe  positions  as  well  as 
their  hopes  and  expectations  for  the  world's  future. 

In  almost  all  orders  and  spheres,  leading  policy-makers  are  hav- 
ing to  learn  to  share  European  problems  and  to  educate  Europeans 
to  the  appreciation  of  American  decision-making  contexts.  Accord- 
ingly, we  may  say  that  a  great  process  of  social  and  cultural  fusion 
is  underway,  a  fusion  comparable  only  to  the  spread  of  Hellenism 
after  Alexander  in  the  Eastern  Mediterranean,  or  to  the  blending, 


480  DYNAMICS 

in  the  leading  urban  strata  of  late  antiquity,  of  the  legacy  of  Athens 
and  Rome  under  the  Caesars.  Militarily,  economically,  and  polit- 
ically, there  is  going  on  a  struggle  for  the  world,  of  which  there 
is  a  portentous  psychological  meaning:  We  witness  and  participate 
in  an  historic  contest  which  will  decide  what  types  of  men  and 
women  will  flourish  on  the  earth. 

Man  is  a  unique  animal  species  in  that  he  is  also  an  historical 
development.  It  is  in  terms  of  this  development  that  he  must  be 
defined,  and  in  terms  of  it  no  single  formula  will  fit  him.  Neither 
his  anatomy  nor  his  psyche  fix  his  destiny.  He  creates  his  own 
destiny  as  he  responds  to  his  experienced  situation,  and  both  his 
situation  and  his  experiences  of  it  are  the  complicated  products 
of  the  historical  epoch  which  he  enacts.  That  is  why  he  does  not 
create  his  destiny  as  an  individual  but  as  a  member  of  a  society. 
Only  within  the  limits  of  his  place  in  an  historical  epoch  can  man 
as  an  individual  shape  himself,  but  we  do  not  yet  know,  we  can 
never  know,  the  limits  to  which  men  collectively  might  remake 
themselves. 


Bibliographical  Note 


In  this  brief  bibliography  we  Hst  only  books  in  English  which  we  have 
found  profitable  and  enjoyable  in  the  production  of  the  present  volume. 
Although  we  do  not  wish  to  impose  this  list  on  others,  we  cannot  help 
but  feel  that  as  a  selection  it  does  suggest  the  major  legacy  available  to 
the  student  of  man  and  society. 

We  should  note  that  we  are  constant  perusers  of  The  Encyclopaedia 
of  the  Social  Sciences  and  of  the  eleventh  edition  of  The  Encyclopaedia 
Britannica.  Students  who  wish  detail  on  any  of  the  factual  or  historical 
topics  we  have  discussed  should  first  consult  these  wonderful  volumes. 
Those  who  wish  further  listings  of  books  by  historical  topic  or  event  may 
consult  the  Library  of  Congress  file  catalogue,  to  be  found  in  most  uni- 
versity libraries.  In  the  following,  we  cite  the  latest,  or  the  most  con- 
venient, editions  available  to  us. 

Albright,  William  F.,  From  the  Stone  Age  to  Christianity  (2nd  ed.;  Balti- 
more: Johns  Hopkins  Press,  1946). 

Bagehot,  Walter,  Physics  and  Politics  (New  York:  D.  Appleton,  1912). 

Beard,  Charles,  An  Economic  Interpretation  of  the  Constitution  of  the 
U.S.  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1935). 

,  Economic  Origins  of  Jeffersonian  Democracy   (New  York:   Mac- 

jnillan,  1915)- 

"Berle,  A.  A.,  Jr.,  and  Means,  Gardiner  C,  The  Modern  Corporation  and 

Private  Property  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1933). 
Borkenau,  Franz,  World  Communism  (New  York:  Norton,  1939). 
Bovet,  Pierre,   The  Fighting  Instinct,  J.  Y.   T.   Creig,   tr.    (New   York: 

Dodd,  Mead,  1923). 
Bryce,  James,  The  Americat\  Commonwealth,  2  vols.   (New  York:  Mac- 
millan, 1895). 
BiJcher,  Karl,  Industrial  Evolution  (New  York:  Holt,  1901). 
Burckhardt,  Jacob,  The  Civilization  of  the  Renaissance  in  Italy,  S.  G.  C. 

Middlemore,  tr.  (New  York:  Oxford  Univ.  Press,  1945). 
Calhoun,  Arthur  W.,  A  Social  History  of  the  American  Family,  3  vols. 
(New  York:  A.  H.  Clark,  1917-19). 


482  BIBLIOGRAPHICAL     NOTE 

Carr,  E.  H.,  The  Twenty  Years  Crisis,  1919-1939  (New  York:  Macmillan, 
1940). 

Cash,  W.  J.,  The  Mind  of  the  South  (New  York:  Knopf,  1941). 

Commons,  John  R.,  Legal  Foundations  of  Capitalism  (New  York:  Mac- 
millan, 1924). 

Cooley,  C.  H.,  Social  Organization  (New  York:  Scribner's,  1909). 

,  Human  Nature  and  the  Social  Order  (rev.  ed.;  New  York:  Scrib- 
ner's, 1922). 

Dewey,  John,  Human  Nature  and  Conduct  (New  York:  Holt,  1922). 

Dibelius,  Wilhelm,  England,  Mary  A.  Hamilton,  tr.  (New  York:  Harper, 

1930)- 
Dorfmann,   Joseph,    Thor stein   Veblen   and   His   America    (New   York: 

Viking,  1934). 
Durkheim,  Emile,  The  Division  of  Labor  in  Society,  George  Simpson,  tr. 

(Glencoe,  111.:  Free  Press,  1947). 
,  Suicide,  John  A.  Spaulding  and  George  Simpson,  trs.   (Glencoe, 

111.:  Free  Press,  1951). 
Earle,  E.  M.,  and  others,  eds..  Makers  of  Modern  Strategy   (Princeton: 

Princeton  Univ.  Press,  1943). 
Fenichel,   Otto,   The  Psychoanalytic   Theory   of  Neurosis    (New   York: 

Norton,  1945). 
Freud,  Sigmund,  The  Basic  Writings  of  Sigmund  Freud,  A.  A.  Brill,  tr. 

(New  York:  Modern  Library,  1938). 
,  Civilization  and  Its  Discontents,  Joan  Riviere,  tr.  (London:  Anglo- 
books,  1952). 

,  Collected  Papers,  vols,  i-iv  (London:  Hogarth  Press,  1946). 

,  General  Introduction  to  Psychoanalysis,  Joan  Riviere,  tr.  (rev.  ed.; 

Garden  City,  N.  Y.:  Garden  City  Pubhshing  Co.,  1943). 
,  Group  Psychology  and  the  Analysis  of  the  Ego,  James  Strachey, 

tr.  (London:  Hogarth  Press,  1948).  ___^ 

Fromm,  Erich,  Escape  from  Freedom   (New  York:   Farrfjr  &  Rinehart, 

1941)- 
Hauser,  Arnold,  The  Social  History  of  Art,  2  vols.   (New  York:  Knopf, 

1951)- 
Hegel,  G.  W.  F.,  The  Philosophy  of  History  (New  York:  Wiley,  1944). 
Hendrick,  Ives,  Facts  and  Theories  of  Psychoanalysis  (2nd  ed.,  rev.  and 

enl.;  New  York:  Knopf,  1939). 
Hobson,  John  A.,  The  Evolution  of  Modern  Capitalism   (new  and  rev. 

ed.;  New  York:  Scribner's,  1926). 
Homey,   Karen,   The  Neurotic  Personality   of  Our   Time    (New   York: 

Norton,  1937). 
Huizinga,  J.,  The  Waning  of  the  Middle  Ages   (New  York:  Longmans, 

1949)- 


BIBLIOGRAPHICAL     NOTE  48;^ 

Isaacs,  Harold,  Tlie  Tragedy  of  the  Chinese  Revolution  (London:  Secher 

&  Warburg,  1938). 
James,  William,  Psychology:  Briefer  Course  (New  York:  Holt,  1923). 
Kardiner,  A.,  The  Individual  and  His  Society    (New  York:    Columbia 

Univ.  Press,  1939). 
Kohn,  Hans,  The  Idea  of  Nationalism  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1944). 
Korsch,  Karl,  Karl  Marx  (New  York:  Wiley,  1939). 
Kosok,  Paul,  Modern  Germany  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago  Press,  1933). 
Kroeber,  A.  L.,  Anthropology  (new  rev.  ed.;  New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace, 

1948). 
,  Configurations  of  Cultural  Growth  (Berkeley:  Univ.  of  California 

Press,  1944). 
Lasswell,  H.  D.,  World  Politics  and  Personal  Insecurity    (New  York: 

Whittlesey,  1936). 
,  The  Analysis  of  Political  Behaviour    (New  York:    Oxford  Univ. 

Press,  1948) . 
,  and  Kaplan,  A.,  Power  and  Society  (New  Haven:  Yale  Univ.  Press, 

1950). 
LeBon,  C,  The  Crowd  (new  ed.;  New  York:  Macmillan,  1925). 
Lenin,   \.   1.,   State  and  Revolution    (New   York:    International   Pubs., 

1932). 

,  Two  Tactics  (New  York:  International  Pubs.,  1935). 

,  What  Is  to  Be  Done?  (New  York:  International  Pubs.,  1929). 

Lippmann,  Walter,  Public  Opinion   (New  York:  Macmillan,  1927). 
Lukacs,  George,  Studies  in  European  Realism,  Edith  Bone,  tr.  (London: 

Hillway,  1950). 
Luxemburg,  Rosa,  The  Accumulation  of  Capital,  Agnes  Schwarzschild, 

tr.  (New  Haven:  Yale  Univ.  Press,  1951). 
Lynd,   Robert   S.    and   Helen   M.,    Middletown    (New   York:    Harcourt, 

Brace,  1929). 
— —^,^^iddletown  in  Transition  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1937). 
Mannheim,  Karl,  Ideology  and  Utopia,  Louis  Wirth  and  Edward  Shils, 

trs.   (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1936). 
,  Man  and  Society  in  an  Age  of  Reconstruction,  Edward  Shils,  tr. 

(New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1940). 
Marcuse,   Herbert,   Reason   and   Revolution    (New  York:    Oxford   L^niv. 

Press,  1941). 
Marx,  Karl,  Capital,  3  vols.  E.  Untermann,  tr.  (Chicago:  Kerr,  1906-09). 
,  Selected  Works  in  2  Volumes  (New  York:  International  Publishers, 

1933)- 
,  and  Engels,  Friedrich,  The  German  Ideology   (New  York:   Inter- 
national Publishers,  1939). 


484  BIBLIOGRAPHICAL     NOTE 

Mead,  George  H.,  Mind,  Self  and  Society  (Chicago:  Univ.  of  Chicago 
Press,  1934). 

Mead,  Margaret,  Sex  and  Temperament  in  Three  Primitive  Societies 
(New  York:  Morrow,  1935). 

Mencken,  H.  L.,  The  American  Language  (4th  ed.,  rev.  and  enl.;  New 
York:  Knopf,  1936). 

Michels,  Robert,  Political  Parties,  Eden  and  Cedar  Paul,  trs.  (Glencoe, 
111.:  Free  Press,  1949). 

Mills,  C.  Wright,  White  Collar:  The  American  Middle  Class  (New  York: 
Oxford  Univ.  Press,  1951). 

Mosca,  Gaetano,  The  Ruling  Class,  H.  D.  Kahn,  tr.  (New  York:  McGraw- 
Hill,  1939). 

Mumford,  Lewis,  Technics  and  Civilization  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace, 

1934)- 
Myrdal,  Gunnar,  The  American  Dilemma  (9th  ed.;  New  York:  Harper, 

1944)- 
Neumann,  Franz,  Behemoth:   The  Structure  and  Practice  of  National 

Socialism   (New  York:  Oxford  Univ.  Press,  1942). 
Nietzsche,  Friedrich,  The  Complete  Works  (Levy  ed.;  New  York:  Mac- 

millan,   1896-1930). 
Norman,  E.  Herbert,  Japan's  Emergence  as  a  Modern  State  (New  York: 

Inst,  of  Pacific  Relations,  1946). 
Oppenheimer,  Franz,  The  State,  John  M.  GitteiTnan,  tr.   (rev.  ed.;  New 

York:  Viking,  1926). 
Ostrogorskii,  M.,  Democracy  and  the  Organization  of  Political  Parties, 

Frederick  Clarke,  tr.,  2  vols.    (New  York:   Macmillan,   1908). 
Piaget,  Jean,  The  Moral  Judgment  of  the  Child  (New  York:  Harcourt, 

Brace,  1932). 
,  The  Language  and  Thought  of  the  Child  (New  York:  Harcourt, 

Brace,  1926). 
Powdermaker,  Hortense,  After  Freedom  (New  York:  Viking,  1937). 
Power,  Eileen,  Medieval  People  (Boston:  Houghton  Mifflin,  1924). 
Rosenberg,  Arthur,  Democracy  and  Socialism  (New  York:  Knopf,  1939). 
Ross,  E.  A.,  Social  Control  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1904). 
Sa]>ine,  George,  A  History  of  Political  Theory  (New  York:  Holt,  1937). 
Sapir,  Edward,  Language  (New  York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1921). 
Schumpeter,  J.  A.,  Capitalism,  Socialism,  and  Democracy  (3rd  ed.;  New 

York:   Harper,  1950). 
Simmel,  Georg,  The  Sociology  of  Georg  Simmel,  Kurt  Wolff,  ed.  and  tr. 

(Glencoe,  111.:  Free  Press,  1950). 
Sombart,  Werner,  The  Quintessence  of  Capitalism,  M.  Epstein,  tr.  (Lon- 
don, 1915). 


BIBLIOGRAPHICAL     NOTE  48$ 

Sorokin,  Pitirim,  Social  MohiUttj  (New  York:  Harper,  1927). 

,   Social  and  Cultural  Dynamics,   4   vols.    (New  York:    American 

Books,  1937-41). 
Speier,  Hans,  Social  Order  and  the  Risks  of  War  (New  York:  Stewart, 

1952). 
Spencer,  Herbert,  Principles  of  Sociology,  2  vols.  (New  York:  D.  Apple- 
ton,  1896). 
Sullivan,  Harry  Stack,  Conceptions  of  Modern  Psychiatry   (Washington: 

W.  A.  White  Psychiatric  Foundation,  1947). 
Tawney,  R.  H.,  Religion  and  the  Rise  of  Capitalism    (new  ed.;   New 

York:  Harcourt,  Brace,  1947). 

,  Equality  (4th  ed.  rev.;  New  York:  Macmillan,  1952). 

Thomas,  W.  I.,  and  Znaniecki,  F.,  The  Polish  Peasant  in  Europe  and 

America  (New  York:  Knopf,  1927). 
de  Tocqueville,   Alexis,   Democracy   in   America,   2  vols.    (New   York: 

Knopf,  1945). 
Toynbee,  Arnold,  A  Study  of  History,  6  vols.  (New  York:  Oxford  Univ. 

Press,  1951). 
Troeltsch,  E.,  The  Social  Teachings  of  the  Christian  Churches,  2  vols. 

(New  York:  Macmillan,  1949). 
Trotsky,  Leon,  The  History  of  the  Russian  Revolution,  Max  Eastman,  tr. 

(New  York:  Simon  and  Schuster,  1936). 
Vagts,  Alfred,  A  History  of  Militarism  (New  York:  Norton,  1937). 
Veblen,  Thorstein,  Absentee  Ownership   (New  York:  Viking,  1923). 
,  Tlie  Place  of  Science  in  Modern  Civilization  (New  York:  Viking, 

1919)- 
Wallas,  Graham,  The  Great  Society  (New  York:  Macmillan,  1914). 

,  Human  Nature  in  Politics  (3rd  ed.;  New  York:  Knopf,  1921). 

^^eber.  Max,  From  Max  Weber:  Essays  in  Sociology,  H.  H.  Gerth  and 

G.  Wright  Mills,  trs.   (New  York:  Oxford  Univ.  Press,  1946). 
,  General  Economic  History,  Frank  H.  Knight,  tr.   (Glencoe,  111.: 

Free  Press,  1950). 
,  The  Protestant  Ethic  and  the  Spirit  of  Capitalism,  Talcott  Parsons, 

tr.  (New  York:  Scribner's,  1930). 
,  The  Theory  of  Social  and  Economic  Organization,  Talcott  Parsons 

and  A.  M.  Henderson,  trs.  (New  York:  Oxford  Univ.  Press,  1947). 
,  The  Religion  of  China,  H.  H.  Gerth,  tr.  (Glencoe,  111.:  Free  Press, 

1951)- 
,  Atjcient  Judaism,  H.  H.  Gerth  and  D.  Martindale,  trs.   (Glencoe, 

111.:  Free  Press,  1952). 
Wellek,  Rene,  and  Warren,  Austin,  Theory  of  Literature    (New  York: 

Harcourt,  Brace,  1949). 


Inde 


X 


Actor,  58  f .,  304 

Adolescence,  87,  99,  141  ff.,  159 

Advertising,  56,  436,  460 

Age,   16,  157,  159,  166,  248 

Aggression,  63,  78,  149,  394 

Aggregates,  432  ff. 

Alienation,  298 

Anarchism,  451 

Anomy,  430,  436 

Anxiety,    15,    63,   84,    108,    149,    158, 

183  ft.,  227,  360,  462  ff. 
Art,  63,  241,  275,  280,  304,  444 
Asceticism,  43,  215,  233  ff.,  244,  360, 

362,  390 
Athens,  207 
Attention,  65,  68 
Audience,  63,  436 
Authority,  def.,  195;  17,  23,  152,  247, 

266,  276,  297,  302  f.,  406,  413  ff. 

Banalization,  56,  380 

Bible,  233,  244,  383 

Biography,  139  ff.,  182 

Birth,   165  f.,  346  f. 

Boss,  318,  414 

Bureaucracy,    188,    209  fF.,   220,   254, 

332,  358,  417,  420,  457 
Business,  218  ff.,  293,  363,  456 

Capitalism,   118,  218,  236,  289,  359, 

439>    467,    477;    types    of,    214  flf.; 

and  religion,  363;  and  war,  22  f. 
Career,  93  f.,  99,  109 
Caste,  103,  242  f. 
Character   structure,   def.,   22;    19  ff., 

160,  177  f.,  236 
Chastity,  146,  248 
Child,  45,  73  f.,  84,  100,  117,  130  If., 

148;     illegitimate,      1841.,     247  f.; 

tribal,  134,  136,  151,  153,  158 
China,     104  ff.,     188  f.,    247,    279  f., 

382,  390  f.,  478 
City,  90,  368  f. 


Class,  307;  consciousness,  88,  329, 
340;  organization,  333,  439;  strug- 
gle, 331,  383,  431,  439,  443,  447; 
ruling,  339,  345;  middle,  15,  144, 
259,  270,  328,  358  f.,  386,  394, 
402,  454 

Coincidence,  def.,  355;  358  ff.,  361  f., 
404 

Collective  beha\'ior,  427  ff. 

Communism,  183,  205,  221,  337  ff., 
383,  447,  449  f-,  453  f-,  463, 
472  ff.;  of  consumption,  247 

Compensation,   107,  238 

Competition,  123  f.,  182,  290  f.,  303, 
338  f.,  356,  401,  460,  470  f.;  of 
symbols,  294,  298 

Compromise,  292  f.,  400 

Conditioning,  4  ff.,   132 — 

Conflict,  102,  117,  123  f. 

Conscience,  96  ff.,  100,  124,  437 

Conservatism,  288,  392 

Conventions,  62,  65,  258,  260,  278; 
and  law,  262;  conventional  lie,  92, 
105,  259 

Con\'ergence,  def.,  355;  365  ff.,  404 

Conversation,  115,  127,  293 

Co-ordination,  def.,   355;   363  ff.,  404 

Corporations,  15,  220  f.,  456 

Correspondence,  def.,  355;  404,  443 

Coup  d'etat,  443,  451 

Courage,  179 

Craftmanship,  397  f. 

Credit  rating,  Puritan,  236 

Criminal,  270,  394,  473  f. 

Crisis,  219  f.,  293,  437 

Crowd,  428,  431  ff. 

Crying,  156,  160 

Cumulative  selection,  154 

Custom,  def.,  256  f. 

Cynic,  cynicism,  124,  270 

Czechoslovakia,  470 

Death,  171  f. 
Decision-making,  413  ff.,  458 


Democracy,  206  fF. 
Denunciation,  262 
Depersonalization,  21 
Depression,  219  f.,  293 
Depri\ation,  organic,  75  ff. 
Despotism,  209  ff.,  239,  422 
Determinism,  389,  395 
Diet,  43,  267  f. 
Discipline,   151,  294,  300  f. 
Disgust,  267  f. 
Disillusionment,  292,  459 
Di\'orce,  260 
Dogmatic  pluralism,  381 
Donner  party,  76 
Dream,  114,  128,  334 
Durkheim,  E.,  260,  277,  430 

Economic     order,     clef.,     26;     213  ff., 

302,  352,  369,  377,  389,  404 
Education,  251  ff.,  293;  German  com- 
munist, 255  f.;  legal,  26 1;  religious, 
240,  242  fT.;   Spartan,  347 
Elite,  236,  293,  442,  454 
Emotions,  20,  51  f.,  56  ff.,  62  f. 
Ends  and  means,  27,  31,  45,  109 
Enthusiasm,  444,  446  ff . 
Equilibrium,   112  f.,   147,  458 
Expectations,  70,  84,   100,   112 
Experience,  67,  68,  70,  75,  153 

Factory,  351  f. 

Faith,  292,  459,  463 

Family,  123,  148,  150  ff.,  246,  248 

Fashion,  71,  258,  278,  427 

Fear,  133  f.,  184  ff. 

Feeling,  tone,  68  f.;  -states,  50,  74 

Feudalism,  210,  357,  377,  440 

Figurehead,  422 

Flattery,  92 

Fragmentation,  363 

Fratricide,  376 

Freedom,  356,  447  f.,  462,  471 

Freud,  S.,  96,   149  ff.,   171,  183,   185, 

250,  375  f->  380,  408,  416 
Fromm,  E.,  85,  113,  126 

Gangs,  347,  431,  433 

Genetic  development,   142,   147 

Genius,  89,  93,  295,  356,  412 

Gentleman,  110,  251,  279 

Germany,  293,  335  ff .,  383,  400 

Gestures,  12,  20,  49  ff.,  54  f. 

Growth,  143,  147 

Guild,  397,  429 

Guilt,  97,   124,  263,  296,  376 

Habit,  132,  136,  154 

Harmony,  343 

Hegel,  G.  W.,  241,  375,  380,  421 


INDEX  ^Sy 

Hero,  171,  338,  467,  472 

History,  296  f.,  379,  382,  386  f.,  404, 

45 1>  454 
Hobbes,   184,  238,  378,  470 
Honor,   30,    175,   245  f.,   285,    338  f., 

347 
Homey,  K.,  113,  119,  150,  156,  158, 

186  f. 
Household,  246  f.,  266 
Hunger,  15,  75,  149 
Hubris,  342,  451 
Hypnosis,  125  f. 
Hypocrisy,  95,   124,  269  f.,  292 


Idealism,  292,  459 

Ideas,  386  f. 

Identification,  144,   150 

Imagination,   153  f.,   155,  395 

Imitation,   144 

Immigrant,  immigration,  333 

Imperialism,  def.,  204;  200,  330,  367, 

463 
Impulse,  20,  45,  133 
India,  103,  166,  369,  390  f.,  478 
Individual,  100,  379  f.,  387,  409 
Infanticide,  166,  248,  347 
Instinct,  7  f.,   10,   149 
Institution,   def.,    13,   416;    11,   22  ff.; 

controls,  266;  dynamics,  290,  301; 

members,    165,    170,    173  ft.;   types, 

24  f . 
Institutional  order,  def.,  25  ff.,  353  ff.; 

31,     174  f-,    302  f.,    307  f-,    350  ff., 

391,  441,  456  f.;  and  antagonisms, 

77,  297,  443 
Integration,    100  f.,    176,    299  f.,    352, 

354  ff.,  404;  (dis-),  348,  370,  429 
Intellectuals,  54,  256,  269,  271,  298, 

344,    386  f.,    444,    448  f.;    Russian, 

262,  469 
InteUigence,   138,  461 
Intimacy,  92,  147,  259 
In\  ention,  inventor,  394  f.,  397 

James,  W.,  238 

Japan,  61,  381,  423,  468 

Jealousy,  248 

Jewry,  170,  325  ff.,  337,  433  f. 

Joint  liability',  248,  263,  368 

Kardiner,  A.,  96,  152  f.,  155,  158 
Kingship,  207,  249,  442 
Kinship  order,  def.,  26,  245;  152,  184, 
245  ff.,  402 

Labor,  87  f.,  169,  302,  329,  333,  368, 

403,  407,  431,  438,  472 
Lady,  12  f.,  65,  357 
Laissez  faire,  281,  302,  356,  458 


488  INDEX 

Language,  12,  21,  81  ff.,  114,  137  ff., 

155,  274  f.,  278  ff.,  304 
Lassvvell,  H.  D.,   152,  277,  287,  408 
Law,  260  ff.,  263  ff.,  412,  442 
Leadership,  40,  176,  330,  365,  405  ff., 

409,  4^4  S.,  418  ff.,  423  ft.,  435  f-> 

455>  462;   charismatic,   210,   263  f., 

446  f.,  448  f. 
Learning,    75,    83,    117,    132,    135  &•; 

rote,  242,  252 
Leisure,  63,  257,  303 
Lenin,  N.,  411,  422,  449 
Liberalism,     199,     355  f.,     401,     439, 

441;  decline  of,  464  ff.,  468  f. 
Literature,  57,  275,  411,  415 
Love,     141,     146,     187,     190,    238  f., 

248  ff.,  376 
Loyalty,  175,  226,  251 

Machiavelli,  195  ff.,  352,  414 
Magic,  97,  230,  242  ft.,  286 
Malinowski,  B.,  71,  152,  376 
Mannheim,  K.,  277,  338  f.,  432 
Marriage,     159,     246  ff.,     250,     259, 

271  f.,  356 
Martyr,  90,  172 
Marx,  214,  249,  377,  383,  384,  387, 

443,  446  f. 
Mass    media,    212,    257,    278,    284  f., 

294,  297,  302,  304,  436,  460,  467 
Masses,  62,   70,    137,  304,  363,  427, 

431,  434 
Maturation,  73,  127,  130,  147 
Mead,  G.  H.,  3,  9,  81,  96,  127 
Mead,  M.,  71,  134,  151,  158 
Memory,  85,   153  f.,  156,  161 
Milieu,  def.,  354;  417 
Military  order,  def.,  26;   185,  223  ff., 

2S4  f.,  423 
Mill,  J.  S.,  387 
Mission,  sense  of,  447,  448 
Mistress,   190,  245  f.,  249 
Mob,  427,  432  ff. 
Models,  85,  110,  303,  412,  425,  467; 

explanatory,  150;  Soviet,  337 
Money,  123,  213  f.,  368,  397 
Monistic  theories,  380 
Mores,  258,  271 
Motives,  29,  112  ff.,  118  ff.,  125,  262, 

269;   of  leaders,   407  f.;   pecuniary, 

123,  221,  270 
Movements,   77,  249,   341,   386,  417, 

437  ff.,  440  f.,  445  f.,  450  ff. 
Music,  63,  68,  90,  160,  280,  304,  393, 

394  f.,  411,  445 

Nation,  Nationalism,  def.,  197  f.;  200, 
203,  296  f.;  and  language,  201  ff.; 
and  state,  199,  470 


Nazism,  293,  337,  363  ft.,  399,  454 
Negro,  89,  92,  271,  295,  433 
NeighborHness,  365 
Nietzsche,  F.,  237  f.,  342,  375 
Nobility,  87  f.,  190  f.,  259,  279,  335  f., 

465,  468 
Nomadic  sib,  351 

Oath,  283  f.,  362 

Obedience,   193  f.,  300,  473 

Occupation,  def.,  307,  308  ff.;  145  f., 
169 

Oedipus  (and  Electra)  complex, 
150  ft"-,  376 

Old  Order  Amish,  250,  390  f. 

Opportunities,  307,  408 

Organism,  3  f.,  7,  9  f.,  21,  40  ff., 
49  ff.,  64  f.,  112,  130  ff. 

Ostracism,  258,  347 

Other,  authoritative,  97,  260;  confirm- 
ing, 87,  94;  generalized,  95  ff., 
98  If.,  124,  173  f.,  258,  260,  410, 
450;  intimate,  90,  109,  127,  259; 
significant,  86  f.,  143,  173,  181, 
266,  450 

Panic,  436  f . 

Parricide,  376 

Party,  294,  422,  428,  438,  439 

Patriarch,   176,  250;   ( -al  family),   11 

Peasant,  249,  257,  461 

Perceptions,  6,  20,  68  f.,  70  f.,  73,  79, 

139 
Person,  def.,  22;  14,  43,  106  ff.,  112, 

114 
Pierce,  C.  S.,  47,  69,  127 
Piety,  242,  247 
Plantation,  218,  367,  466 
Political  order,  def.,  26;   192  ff.,  207, 

363,  404;  symbols  of,  284 
Population  pressure,  382 
Power,     def.,     195,    307;     192,    308, 

328  ff.,     413  ff.,     456  f.;     economic, 

221,  357,  475;  and  status,  335,  407 
Premiums,  118,  128,  136,  177  ft-,  39^ 
Pressure  groups,  329,  438  ft'.,  471 
Prestige,  30,  159,  25S,  266,  280,  289, 

296,  307,  321,  330,  334  ft-,  410  f-, 

473;  -descent,  318,  333  f.,   443;  i" 

Germany,  335  ff.;  military,  332;  in 

U.S.S.R.,  338  f. 
Pretender,  268 
Prisoners,  445 

Pri\  acy,  259,  282  f.,  362,  448 
Proletariat,  368,  448 
Propaganda,  292,  436,  451,  459,  462, 

473,  476 
Property,    170,  245,  260,  281,  328  f., 

338,  361,  445,  448,  467 


INDEX 


489 


Prophet,  89,  93,  231,  238,  240,  243, 

271,  286,  425 
Prostitute,  prostitution,  244,  250 
Psychic   structure,    clef.,    22;    20,    43, 

69,    72  ff.,    112,    130,    133  ft.,    139, 

154,  182  f.,  286 
Psychic   traits,   79,    140,    176  ii.,    182, 

236,  252,  257,  284,  405,  406  ff. 
Pubhc   opinion,    139,    213,   219,    386, 

435  ff- 
Purge,  365,  450,  454 

Race,  41  f.,  201,  433 

Radio,  285,  304,  396 

Ramification,  def.,  32;  328,  353,  360, 
362,  390,  457,  458 

Rationality,  213,  221,  265,  269,  289, 
401 

Reflex,  4  ff.,   134,  154 

Regression,   160 

Religion,  97,  230  ff.,  239,  241  ff.,  289, 
292,  376;  Buddhist,  243,  291,  415; 
Confucian,  242,  383;  Christianity, 
232,  241,  244  f.,  291,  360,  369; 
Hindu,  242  f.;  Jewish,  231  f.,  243  f., 
(v.  prophet);  Mohammedan,  244; 
Protestant,  168,  188,  198,  228, 
233  f-,  235  ff.,  244  ff.,  250,  275, 
281,  288  ff.,  360  ff.,  428,  467; 
Catholic,  28,  170,  201,  233,  237, 
239  f.,  244  f.,  261,  275,  289,  302, 
333,  363,  386,  414,  427,  430,  440 
(v.  priest) 

Religious  order,  def.,  26;  230  ff.,  285, 

303 
Renaissance,  395,  430 
Repression,  78,  128 
Resentment,  237  f. 
Responsibility,    loo  f.,  263 
Re\i\als,  98,  237,  363,  386,  430 
Re\  olution,  def.,  441  f.;  98,  270,  337, 
386,    399,    404,    422,    429,    442  ff., 
476;  counter-,  444  ff.;  French,  415, 

444  f- 
Rome,  166,  172,  264,  366  ff.,  378,  391 
Ross,  E.  A.,  384,  432 
Routine,   136,  257 

Sanctions,  256,  258,  260,  262  f.,  266, 

416 
Scapegoat,  78,  462 
Secrecy,  460,  464 
Security,    84,    144,    149,    184,    462  f., 

471 
Self,    12,    21,    51,    75,    80,    128,    258, 

296,   394;   -image,   11  f.,   84  ff.,   89, 

91  ff.,  loo,  103,  109,  176,  202,  286, 

411  ff. 
Self-made  man,  334,  356,  444 
.Sensation,  20,  64 


Serfdom,  378 

Sex,   16,  77,   146,   155,  245,  248 

Skill,  251,  309,  388,  ,392  ff. 

Sla\e,  89,  366,  367,  369 

Smiling  response,  49,  84 

Sobriety  and  toxics,  42,  53,  250,  262, 

267,  362 

Social  change,  def.,  398  ff.;  102,  157, 

271,  37.5  ff-,  381,  384,  ,386  f.,  429, 

451;  theories  of,  382,  404,  454 

Social  control,  15,  44,  84,  117,  256  ff. 

Social  mobility,  219,  253,  333  f.,  361, 

403,  443 
Social  role,  def.,  10  ff.;  22  f.,  107  ff., 
122,  i66ff.,  308,  392  f.,  394,  398; 
contexts  of,  416  ff.;  change  of,  291, 
393,  420  ff.;  of  leaders,  405,  407; 
of  staff,  422 
Social     psvchologv,    3,     15  f.,     32  ff., 

41  f.,  378 
Social   structure,   22  ff.,    30  f.,   298  ff., 

330,  342  ff.,  349,  403 
Socialism,  284,  336,  452  f. 
Sparta,   166,  172,  344  ff. 
Specialization,   158,  309,  398,  423 
Speech,   126  f.,   138,  275,   278  f.,  345 
Spheres,    29  f.,    204,    274,    353,    365, 

388  ff. 
State,   def.,    197;   26,    193,    199,   208, 

240,  328  f.,  331  f.,  347,  364 
Status,   def.,  307  f.;    119,   249,  257  f., 
269,   278  f.,  280,  318,  330,  332  ff., 
338  f.,    397,    399,    402,    410,    412, 
439,  443  f-;  V.  honor,  prestige 
Stereotype,  284,  295 
Stratification,    279  f.,    306  ff.,    331  ff., 

.340  f. 
Structure,  def.,  354;  429 
Success,  467 

S>-mbols,   29,   71,   81,   274  ff.,   2S7  ff., 
294  ff.,      302  f.;      of      legitimation, 
276  f.,    281,    287  ff.,    298  ff.;    politi- 
cal, 284,  443;  of  status,  444 
Symbol  sphere,  274  f.,  298  ff. 

Taboo,  70  f.,  126,  128,  136,  149,  155, 

177,   180  f.,  267,  278 
Tax,  270,  367,  401 
Technology,     30,     280,     285,     388  ff., 

396  ff.,   456,  466 
Terror,   76,   124,  365,  434,  444,  445, 

450,  454 
Tolerance,  291,  292  f. 
Totalitarianism,  98,  211  f.,  213,  251  f., 

294,  364,  433  f.,  436,  463,  472 
Trade    union,   332  f.,   336,    338,   421, 

439 

Unemployment,    145,   393,   .397,   461, 
470 


422 

472.  S. 


4gO  INDEX 

U.S.A.,  183,  197,  205,  331  fF.,  465  f 

472  f.,  476 
U.S.  president,  240,  396,  420.    '"" 
U.S.S.R.,  183,  338  f.,  468  f.,  4 

Values,  237,  299,  300  f.,  306  f.,  342, 

440 
Village,   121,  260 
Violence,  223,  263,  300,  442 
Vocabularies,  71,  278  ff.,  282,  407 
Voluntary  associations,  145,  356,  419, 

428,  438 
Voting,  208,  225,  293 


War,  79,  118,  296  f.,  390,  392,  402  f.; 
atomic,  386,  390,  396,  466;  crim- 
inals, 473!.;  economics,  377;  Ro- 
man, 367;  strategy,  384  fF.,  474  f.; 
types  of,  223  f.,  225  ff.,  229,  284  fF.; 
and  youth,  330 

Women,  17,  71,  148  f.,  152,  245  fF., 
250,  283;  emancipation  of,  167, 
248,  293,  366;  and  religion,  242  ff. 

Work,  236,  360,  467 

Youth,  71,  252,  330,  346  F.,  364, 
433  f- 


V 


i 


UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA  LIBRARY 

Los  Alleles 
This  book  is  DUE  on  the  last  date  stamped  below. 


1    ■  -, 

H  19Rf 


l)   \.\J'^^^ 


QeWROg  1990 


jutt?a 


Vft 


nr  JAN21198&  i».JAN23 


lECTD  ID-URU 
JAM  1 1 198B 


0  B  199S  ^9 


act  012004 


315       I     - 


3  1158  00014  5903