Skip to main content

Full text of "Christian ethics"

See other formats


UCSB   LIBRARY 


CHRISTIAN    ETHICS. 


BY  DE.  ADOLF  WUTTKE, 

LATE  PROFESSOR  OP  THEOLOGT  AT  HALLE. 


WITH  AN  INTRODUCTION 
BY      DR.     W.     F.     WARREN. 

OP  THE  BOSTON  TJNIVEE8ITT. 


TRANSLATED  BY 

JOHN    P.    LACROIX. 


VOLUME    II.-PURE    ETHICS. 


EDINBURGH : 
T.   &   T.   CLARK,    GEORGE    STREET. 

'    •        MDCCCLXXIII.  . 


Entered  according  to  Act  of  Congress,  in  the  year  1873,  by 

NELSON  &   PHILLIPS, 
In  the  Office  of  the  Librarian  of  Congress  at  Washington. 


NOTE  OF  TRANSLATOR 


THIS  second  volume  contains  the  first  of  the  three 
forms  under  which  Dr.  Wuttke  treats  of  the  subject- 
matter  of  Christian  Ethics.  It  embraces  and  occu 
pies  the  entire  ethical  field.  Its  aim  is  to  treat  each 
phase  and  bearing  of  the  moral  life  from  a  normal 
or  ideal  stand-point ;  in  other  words,  to  present  the 
moral  life  as  God  originally  willed,  and  yet  wills, 

that  it  should  be.     It  involves  in  its  scope,  therefore, 

» 

all  the  essential  principles  of  the  system  of  the  author, 
and  constitutes  a  whole  in  and  of  itself. 

As  to  the  scientific  character  of  the  work,  and  as 
to  whether  it  answers  wants  which  are  but  v.ery  im 
perfectly  met  by  any  of  our  present  English  treatises ; 
in  a  word,  as  to  whether  the  work  of  Dr.  Wuttke 
finds  before  it,  in  the  English-reading  world,  a  com 
paratively  unoccupied  and  yet  very  important  field, 
I  beg  leave  to  refer  the  reader  chiefly  and  ultimately 
to  the  work  itself,  but  also,  preliminarily,  to  the  special 


iv  NOTE   OF  TEANSLATOE. 

introduction  to  this  volume,  for  which  I  am  thank 
fully  indebted  to  Dr.  W.  F.  Warren,  of  the  Boston 
University.  Frank  and  earnest  words  like  these  from 
this  distinguished  scholar  and  theologian  will,  I  am 
sure,  not  fail  to  arrest  the  attention  of  whoever 
thirsts  after  clear  and  truly  Christian  views  on  the 
great  problems  of  human  life.  J.  P.  L. 


INTKODUCTION. 


No  literature  is  richer  in  native  productions  in 
the  field  of  Ethics  than  the  English.  It  probably  pre 
sents  more  original,  representative  systems  of  moral 
philosophy  than  any  other.  This  at  least  would  seem, 
to  be  the  verdict  of  a  distinguished  French  philoso 
pher,  and  French  philosophers  are  not  often  afflicted 
with  "  anglomania "  in  any  amiable  sense.  In  the 
nineteenth  Lecture  of  his  Introduction  to  Ethics, 
Jouffroy  pays  this  high  tribute  to  his  neighbors  across 
the  channel :  "  How  has  it  happened,  you  may  ask, 
that  all  these  moral  systems,  which  we  have  been 
considering,  were  of  English  origin  ?  The  explana 
tion  of  the  fact  is  this  very  simple  one,  that  moral 
philosophy,  properly  so  called,  has  been  infinitely 
more  cultivated  in  England  during  the  seventeenth 
and  eighteenth  centuries  than  in  any  other  part  of 
Europe.  In  France,  for  example,  the  Cartesian  era 
produced  only  one  eminent  moralist,  Malebranche ; 
and  Malebranche  belonged  neither  to  the  class  of 
selfish  philosophers,  nor  to  that  of  the  sentimental 
philosophers.  Cartesianism  was  followed  in  France, 
in  the  middle  of  the  eighteenth  century,  by  a  new 
philosophy,  but  this  was  the  system  of  materialism 


yi  INTKODUCTKXN. 

in  metaphysics  and  of  selfishness  in  morals ;  and 
called  to  choose  between  Helvetius  and  Hobbes,  I 
could  not  b,ut  prefer  Hobbes.  Much  the  same  might 
be  said  of  the  philosophy  of  Germany,  which  has 
always  been  more  metaphysical  than  moral,  and  has 
never  exhibited  any  forms  of  the  selfish  or  instinctive 
systems,  which  have  obtained  such  a  European  celeb 
rity  as  those  of  Hobbes,  of  Smith,  and  of  Hume." 
That  fhis  fertility  of  Anglo-Saxon  mind  in  the  de 
partment  of  ethical  speculation  was  not  limited  to 
the  centuries  named,  is  clear  from  the  bulk  of  our 
more  recent  ethical  literature.  Its  full  stream  has 
never  subsided,  and  is  to-day  pouring  on  past  Bain 
and  Barratt,  in  England,  past  Hickok  and  Hopkins 
in  America. 

But  while  this  department  of  our  literature  is  al 
most  immeasurable,  and  certainly  invaluable,  it  is 
sadly  deficient  in  works  written  from  a  distinctively 
Christian  stand-point.  One  large  portion  of  our  trea 
tises  are  purely  philosophical.  Another,  perhaps  still 
larger,  wretchedly  confuse  and  mix  up  the  ethics  of 
philosophy  with  the  ethics  of  revelation.  Scarce  one 
author  has  attempted  to  present  in  an  independent 
scientific  form  the  whole  ethical  system  of  Chris 
tianity.  It  is  much  as  if  we  had  innumerable  treatises 
on  what  is  called  natural  theology,  but  as  yet  not  one 
on  the  doctrines  of  the  Christian  Revelation.  Di 
dactic  theologians  have  occasionally  included  in  their 
Bodies  of  Divinity  a  brief  account  of  the  "  Morals  of 


INTRODUCTION.  yii 

Christianity,"  but  thus  far  no  one  has  yet  done  for 
Christian  Ethics  in  our  literature,  what  Danseus  and 
Calixtus  did  for  it  in  the  Keformed  and  Lutheran 
Churches  of  continental  Europe.  The  Science  of 
Christian  Ethics  is  with  us  almo'st  unknown.  Too 
many  of  our  least  suspected  manuals,  written  by 
honored  arid  able  evangelical  divines,  presuppose 
and  continually  imply  a  Socinian  anthropology  ^  and 
a  worse  than  Romish  soteriology.*  * 

Whatever  may  be  the  true  explanation  of  this  grave 
deficiency,  it  certainly  is  not  due  to  an  oversight  of 
the  essential  difference  between  philosophical  and 
Christian  Ethics.  Not  a  few  of  our  evangelical  writ 
ers  have  pointed  out  the  incompleteness  and  com 
paratively  imperfect  basis  of  the  former;  but,  with 
the  exception  of  Wardlaw,  scarce  one  has  done 
any  thing  to  supplant  or  to  supplement  it.  John 
Foster,  in  the  Fourth  of  his  "Essays,"  has  some 
excellent  thoughts  on  the  impossibility  of  ignoring 
such  revealed  facts  as  Human  Depravity,  Redemption, 
the  Mission  of  the  Spirit,  Immortality,  and  Future 
Judgment,  in  any  comprehensive  and  thorough 
presentation  of  the  system  of  Human  Duty.  Richard 
Watson  enumerates  five  grave  mischiefs,  which  result 

*  Twenty  years  ago,  when  a  mere  college  lad,  the  present  writer 
addressed  a  letter  to  Dr.  Wayland,  respectfully  and  earnestly  inquir 
ing  in  what  way  certain  statements  in  his  "  Moral  Science  "  could  be 
harmonized  with  evangelical  views  of  human  depravity.  His  answer 
was  a  curiosity.  I  would  give  not  a  little  to  be  able  to  present  it 
here. 


Viii  INTRODUCTION. 

from  the  attempt  "  to  teach  morals  independently  of 
Christianity."  The,  writer  of  the  essay  on  the  Science 
of  Christian  Ethics  in  the  work,  "  Science  and  the 
Gospel,"  (London,  1870,)  a  writer  who  acknowledges 
his  great  obligation  to  "the  lucid  and  admirable 
WUTTKE,"  calling  him  "  one  of  the  most  deservedly 
distinguished  ethicists  of  modern  times,"  "  a  Chris 
tian  ethicist  of  superlative  merit,"  expresses  this 
sentiment:  "The  propriety  of  discussing  moral 
questions  apart  from  their  natural  and  immediate 
implication  with  Christian  Truth,  admits  of  the  gravest 
doubts."  Wardlaw  goes  even  further  and  asserts 

D  » 

that,  "The  science  of  morals  has  no  province  at  all 
independently  of  theology,  and  it  cannot  be  philo 
sophically  discussed  except  upon  theological  princi 
ples."  "Watson's  final  definition  of  the  relation  of  the 
two  systems  or  methods  is  less  extreme  than  this, 
and  accords  very  nearly  with  that  given  by  WUTTKE 
in  section  fourth  of  his  Introduction.* 

But  whatever  may  be  thought  of  philosophical 
ethics,  or  of  the  exact  relation  of  the  two  branches  to 
each  other,  no  believer  in  Christian  Revelation  can 
for  a  moment  call  in  question  the  legitimacy  of  specifi 
cally  Christian  Ethics.  No  Christian  believer  can 
possibly  speak  his  whole  mind  respecting  man,  the 
ethical  subject,  or  God,  the  author  of  our  ethical 
relations,  or  our  destiny,  the  result  of  our  ethical  action, 
without  stating  or  implying  all  the  fundamental  doc- 
*  See  "Institutes,"  Vol.  II,  bottom  of  p.  474. 


INTRODUCTION.  ix 

trines  of  Christianity.  Indeed,  no  man  can  elaborate 
any  ethical  system  of  any  considerable  completeness 
without  definite  and  most  important  theological  im- 
plicajions.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  most  of  our  accepted 
text-books  are  thoroughly  Deistic.  They  give  us  not 
the  Morals  of  Christianity,  or  of  Judaism,  or  of 
heathenism,  but  simply  the  ethical  system  of  Lord 
Herbert,  or  Theodore  Parker.  We  are  glad  to 
possess  them,  glad  to  see  just  what  ethical  consequence 
Deism  carries  with  it ;  nevertheless  we  must  repudiate 
their  claims  to  an  exclusive  occupancy  of  the  field, 
and  especially  their  claims  to  represent  the  ethics  of 
Revelation.  Their  use  in  Christian  schools  is  at  least 
of  very  doubtful  expediency.  Let  every  theological 
system,  even  those  of  the  heathen,  develop  its  sup 
plementary  ethical  system,  only  let  it  not  attempt  to 
palm  off  its  own  ethical  implication  for  those  of  wholly 
different  systems. 

The  value  of  any  elaborate  system  of  ethics  is 
largely  in  proportion  to  its  fidelity  to  the  theological 
views  and  principles  of  its  author.  If  we  study  an 
atheistic  system,  we  desire  to  ascertain  precisely  what 
the  logical  results  of  atheism  are  in  the  field  of 
morals.  This  is  the  only  special  benefit  we  can  hope 
to  gain  from  the  study.  So  a  modern  Jewish,  Mo 
hammedan,  or  ethnic  system  is  valuable  in  proportion 
as  it  gives  us  the  true  ethical  results  of  the  particular 
religion  from  which  it  springs.  Thorough  ethical 
treatises  are,  therefore,  to  be  welcomed  from  what- 


X  INTRODUCTION. 

ever  theological  stand-point  they  may  be  written.  If 
thorough,  they  will  serve  the  cause  of  truth.  In  the 
way  of  reductio  ad  dbsurdum  they  will  often  evince 
the  untenableness  of  the  theological  principles  upon 
which  they  rest.  So  for  as  they  spring  from  correct 
theological  conceptions,  they  will  mutually  comple 
ment  "and  confirm  each  other. 

The  same  thing  may  be  said  of  systems  of  Christian 
ethics  written  from  different  confessional  stand-points. 
Their  value,  too,  is  usually  in  proportion  to  their 
logical  consistency.  One  of  their  most  important 
uses  is  to  throw  light  upon  the  necessary  ethical  con 
sequences  of  their  respective  types  of  doctrine.  In 
this  respect  the  most  strictly  confessional  are  the 
most  useful.  In  the  interest  of  universal"  Christian 
theology,  therefore,  we  greatly  desiderate  a  thorough 
and  active  confessional  cultivation  of  this  field.  The 
more  clearly  and  constantly  conscious  of  his  distinc 
tive  doctrinal  stand-point,  the  better  service  the 
author  will  render.  Nothing  is  gained,  much  lost, 
by  mixing  up  essentially  Romish  and  essentially 
Protestant  definitions.  In  like  manner  Augustinian 
ethics  are  as  eternally  distinct  from  Pelagian  as  are 
the  theological  systems  so  named.  If  Methodist 
theology  be  true,  no  consistent  Calvin ist  can  ever 
write  a  system  of  ethics  acceptable  to  a  Methodist, 
and  vice  versa.  Romanism,  Calvinism,  Lutheranism 
and  Methodism  as  much  need  distinctive  treatises 
upon  ethics  as  upon  Christian  doctrine.  Each  has 


INTRODUCTION.  XI 

the  same  right  to  the  one  as  to  the  other.  Nor  will 
they  thus  aggravate  and  prolong  the  dissensions  and 
divisions  of  the  universal  Church ;  they  will  rather 
accelerate  the  coining  of  the  day  when  each  great 
branch  of  Christendom  will  have  matured  its  distinct 
ive  thought  and  perfected  its  distinctive  life,  prepar 
atory  to  a  higher  and  grander  synthesis.  Even  before 
that  day  comes,  each  type  of  ethical  inculcation  will 
ha^ye  its  essential  and  characteristic  excellences,  and 
so  effectively  supplement  all  other  types. 

Especially  welcome  to  the  English  reader  must  be 
a  thorough  scientific  presentation  of  Christian  ethics 
from  the  Lutheran  stand-point.  Hitherto  none  has 
been  accessible.  The  whole  theological  literature  of 
Lutheranism  in  the  English  language  is  deplorably 
meager.  Considering  the  historic  interest  and  pres 
ent  relations  of  this  great  Church  of  the  Reformation, 
the  deficiency  is  almost  inexplicable.  In  this  country 
the  actual  numerical  proportions  of  the  communion, 
its  rapid  growth  from  immigration,  the  close  affinities 
of  its  best  theology  and  best  life  with  the  dominant 
theology  and  life  of  the  country,  conspire  to  render  its 
teachings  and  spirit  a  study  of  great  interest  to  every 
intelligent  American  believer.  Nor  can  the  unedify- 
ing  controversies  and  schisms  which  have  hitherto  -so 
excessively  characterized  the  body,  or  even  the  high- 
churchly  self-complacency  of  such  representatives  as 
the  author  of  "  The  Conservative  Reformation  and 


Xii  INTRODUCTION. 

its  Theology."  effectually  prevent  the  Christians  of 
neighboring  folds  from  cherishing  a  growing  interest 
in  their  ecclesiastical  life,  and  in  that  of  their  confes 
sional  and  ethnological  kindred  in  the  Fatherland. 

An  English  translation  of  WUTTKE'S  great  work  on 
"  Christian  Ethics ' '  ought,  therefore,  to  be  warmly 
welcomed  on  many  accounts.  First,  for  all  the  excel 
lent  reasons  suggested  by  Dr.  Biehm,  at  the  close  of 
his  special  preface  to  Volume  I  of  this  translation. 

Second,  because  as  a  work  on  Christian  Ethics  it 
will  contribute  to  the  supply  of  what  is  perhaps  the 
gravest  and  most  unaccountable  lack  in  the  whole 
range  of  English  theological  literature. 

Third,  because  it  will  have  a  tendency  to  stimulate 
American  and  English  moralists  to  a  cultivation  of 
their  science  from  evangelical,  and  possibly  from 
strictly  confessional,  stand-points. 

Fourth,  because  by  means  of  it  the  English  student 
will  now,  for  the  first  time,  have  an  opportunity  to  see 
in  full  scientific  form  the  ethical  implications  and  in 
culcations  of  modern  evangelical  Lutherauism. 

For  all  these  reasons,  it  affords  the  writer  unfeigned 
pleasure  to  bid  the  new-clad  work  God-speed,  and  to 
commend  it  to  the  faithful  study  of  all  lovers  of  Chris 
tian  truth  and  holiness.  WM.  F.  WARREN. 

BOSTON  UNIVERSITY,  SCHOOL  OF  THEOLOGY,  October,  1872. 


CONTENTS. 


PAGE 
§  50.  CLASSIFICATION  OF  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS 1 

PAKT  FIRST. 

PURE  ETHICS;  OE,  THE  MORAL  PER  SE  IRRESPECTIVELY 

OF  SIN. 
INTRODUCTORY  OBSERVATIONS. 

I.  NOTION  AND  ESSENCK  OF  THE  MORAL,  §  51 5 

§  51.  THE  GOOD 5 

§§  52-54.  THE  MORAL 8-14 

II.  RELATION  OF  MORALITY  TO  RELIGION,  §,55 15 

III.  SCIENTIFIC  CLASSIFICATION  OF  ETHICS,  §§  56-57 23-29 

CHAPTER  I. 

THE  MORAL   SUBJECT,  §  58. 

I.  THE  INDIVIDUAL  MORAL  SUBJECT,  MAN,  §  59 36 

A.  MAN  AS  A  SPIRIT,  §  59 36 

§  60.  (1)  THE  COGNIZINO  SPIRIT 41 

§  61.  (2)  THE  VOLITIONATING  SPIRIT,  FREEDOM  OF  WILL.  . .  45 

§  62.  (3)  THE  FEELING  SPIRIT 49 

§  63.  (4)  THE  IMMORTAL  SPIRIT 51 

B.  MAN  AS  TO  HIS  SENSUOUSLY- CORPOREAL  LIFE,  §§  64-66.  .59-64 
O.  THE  UNITY  OF  SPIRIT  AND  BODY,  §  67 67 

§  67.  (1)  THE  STAGES  OF  LIFE 67 

§  68.  (2)  TEMPERAMENTS  AND  NATIONAL  PECULIARITIES 71 

§  69.  (3)  THE  SEXES 74 

II.  THE  COMMUNITY-LIFE  AS  MORAL  SUBJECT,  §70 76 

CHAPTER  H. 

GOD  AS  THE  GROUND  AND  PROTOTYPE  OP  THE  MORAL  LIFE  AND 
AS  THE  AUTHOR  OP  THE  LAW. 

§  72.  (1)  GOD  AS  HOLY  WILL 82 

§  73.  (2)  GOD  AS  PROTOTYPE  OF  THE  MORAL 85 


xiv  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

§  74.  (3)  GOD  AS  UPHOLDER  OF  THE  MORAL  WORLD-GOVERN 
MENT  87 

•  §  75.  (4)  GOD  AS  HOLY  LAW-GIVER 90 

I.  THE  REVELATION  OF  THE  DIVINE  WILL  TO  MAN,  §  76 92 

(a)  THE   EXTRAORDINARY,  POSITIVE,    SUPERNATURAL  REVE 
LATION 92 

§§  77-78.  (b)  THE    INNER    REVELATION    AND    THE     COX- 
SCIENCE  96-99 

II.  THE  ESSENCE  OF  THE  MORAL  LAW  AS  THE  DIVINE  WILL,  §  79.  107 

§  79.  (a)  THE  FORM  OF  THE  LAW  (COMMAND,  PROHIBITION, 

"OUGHT") ' 107 

§  80.  (b)  SCOPE  OF  THE  LAW  (REQUIREMENT,  COUNSELS).  ...   112 
§  81.  (c)  RELATION  OF  THE  LAW  TO  THE  PERSONAL  PECUL 
IARITY  118 

§  82.  THE  ALLOWED 122 

§  83.  MORAL  PRINCIPLES  OR  LIFE-RULES 133 

§  84.  DUTY 136 

§  85.  RIGHT   139 

CHAPTER  III. 

THE   OBJECT   OP   THE   MOKAL   ACTIVITY. 

I.  GOD,  §  86 145 

II.  THE  CREATED,  §  87 149 

§  87.   (1)  THE  MORAL  PERSON  HIMSELF 149 

§  88.  (2)  THE  EXTERNAL  WORLD.  . .    151 

§  89.  EXTERNAL  NATURE 156 

CHAPTER  IV. 
THE  MORAX  MOTIVE. 

§  90.  PLEASURE  AND  DISPLEASURE 159 

§  91.  LOVE  AND  HATRED 161 

§92.  ANTE-MORAL  LOVE 1G3 

§  93.  MORAL  LOVE 168 

§  94.  LOVE  TO  GOD 169 

§  95.  GOD-FEARING .   171 

§  96.  GOD-TRUSTING  AND  ENTHUSIASM 173 

§  97.  HAPPINESS    175 

CHAPTER  V. 

THTC   MORAL   ACTIVITY,    §  89. 
SUBDIVISION  FIRST:    THE  MORAL  ACTIVITY  per  se  IN  ITS  INNER 

DIFFERENCES,  §  99 180 

I.  MORAL  SPARING,  §  100 .  182 


CONTENTS.  xv 

PAGE 

II.  MORAL  APPROPRIATING,  §  1 01 186 

(a)  IN  RESPECT  TO  WHAT  ELEMENT  OF  THE  OBJECT  is  APPRO 

PRIATED,  §  101 }S6 

§  102.  (1)  NATURAL  APPROPRIATING 187 

§  103.  (2)  SPIRITUAL  APPROPRIATING 190 

(b)  IN  RESPECT  TO  HOW  THE  OBJECT  is  APPROPRIATED,  §  104. .  191 

(1)  GENERAL  (UNIVERSAL)  APPROPRIATING,  COGNIZING,  §  104.  192 

(2)  PARTICULAR    (INDIVIDUAL)  APPROPRIATING,    ENJOYING, 

§  105 194 

III.  MORAL  FORMING,  §  106 1 98 

(a)  IN  RESPECT  TO  WHAT  ELEMENT  OF  THE  OBJECT  is  FORMED, 

§  107 200 

§  107.  (1)  NATURAL  FORMING .*. 200 

§  108.  (2)  SPIRITUAL  FORMING 201 

(b)  IN  RESPECT  TO  HOW  THE  OBJECT  is  FORMED,  §  109 203 

§  109.  (1)  PARTICULAR  FORMING 203 

§  110.  (2)  GENERAL  FORMING,  ARTISTIC  ACTIVITY 205 

§§  111,  112.  APPROPRIATING   AND  FORMING  AS  MORALLY 

RELATED  TO  EACH  OTHER 210-212 

SUBDIVISION  SECOND  :  THK  MORAL  ACTIVITY  IN  RELATION  TO  if  s 

DIFFERENCES  AS  RELATING  TO  ITS  DIFFERENT  OBJECTS  : 
L  IN  RELATION  TO  GOD,  §  113 214 

(a)  THE  MORAL  APPROPRIATING  OF  GOD,  FAITH  AND  KNOWL 

EDGE,  §  113 214 

§§  114-117.  PRAYER  AND  SACRIFICE 218-221 

(b)  THE  MORAL  SPARING  OF  THE  DIVINE,  §  118 232 

II.  IN  RELATION  TO  THE  MORAL  PERSON  HIMSELF,  §  119 236 

(a)  MORAL  SPARING,  §  119 236 

(b)  MORAL  APPROPRIATING  AND  FORMING,  §  120 237 

§§  120.  121.  (1)  OF  THE  BODY  BY  THE  SPIRIT 238-242 

§  122.  (2)  OF  THE  SPIRIT  ITSELF 247 

III.  IN  RELATION  TO  OTHER  PERSONS,  §  123 252 

(a)  MORAL  SPARING,  §  123 252 

(b)  MORAL  APPROPRIATING  AND  FORMING,  §§  124-126 254-262 

IV.  IN  RELATION  TO  OBJECTIVE  NATURE,  §  127 264 

(a)  MORAL  SPARING,  §  127 264 

(b)  MORAL  APPROPRIATING. 

§  128.  (1)  'SPIRITUAL 266 

§  129.  (2)  ACTUAL 267 

(c)  MORAL  FORMING,  §  130. 271 


xvi  CONTENTS. 

CHAPTER  VI. 

THE  FRUIT   OF   THE  MORAL   LIFE   AS  MOEAL  END. 

iPiQB 

§  131.  GOOD : 274 

§  132.  THE  HIGHEST  GOOD 275 

I.  THE  PERSONAL  PERFECTION  OP  THE  INDIVIDUAL,  §  133 277 

(a)  OUTWARD  POSSESSIONS,  §  134 270 

(6)  INNER  POSSESSIONS,  §  135 280 

§  135.   (1)  WISDOM- 280 

§  136.   (2)  BLISS 283 

§  137.  (3)  HOLY  CHARACTER 284 

(c)  THE  GOOD  AS«POWER,  §  138 289 

§  138.  VIRTUE 289 

§  139.  THE  VIRTUES 291 

§  140.  THE  PIETY- VIRTUES 297 

II.  MORAL  COMMUNION  AS  A  FRUIT  OF  THE  MORAL  LIFE,  §  141 . .  302 

(a)  THE  FAMILY,  §  142 304 

§  142.  SEXUAL  COMMUNION 304 

§§  143.  144.  MARRIAGE 304-306 

§  145.  PARENTS  AND  CHILDREN >. 313 

§  146.  BROTHERS  AND  SISTERS,  AND  FRIENDS 318 

§  147.  BLOOD-EELATIONSHIP  AS  BEARING  ON  MARRIAGE 319 

§  148.  FAMILY  PROPERTY  AND  FAMILY  HONOR 323 

(b)  MORAL  SOCIETY,  §  149 324 

§  150.  HONOR,  THE  MORAL  HOME 330 

(c)  THE  MORAL  ORGANIZATION  OF  SOCIETY,  §  151 332 

§  151.  RIGHT  AND  LAW 332 

§  152.  CHURCH  AND  STATE,  THEOCRACY 334 


SECTION  L. 

THEOLOGICAL  Christian  ethics,  as  distinguished  from 
philosophical  ethics,  has  an  historical  presupposition — 
the  redemption  accomplished  in  Christ.  But  re 
demption  presupposes  sin,  from  the  power  of  which 
it  delivers  man ;  and  sin  presupposes  the  moral  idea 
per  se,  of  which  it  is  the  actual  negation.  Hence 
the  knowledge  of  Christian  ethics,  as  resting  on  the 
accomplished  redemption,  presupposes  a  knowledge 
of  the  moral  state  of  man  while  as  yet  unredeemed, 
as  in  turn  this  knowledge  presupposes  a  knowledge 
of  that  ideal  state  of  being  from  which  man  turned 
aside  in  sin.  Christian  ethics  has  therefore  a  three 
fold  state  of  things  to  present : 

(1)  The  ethical  or  moral  per  se  irrespectively  of 
sin, — the  moral  in  its  ideal  form,  the  proto-ethical, 
that  which  God,  as  holy,  wills. 

(2)  The  fall  from  the  truly  moral,  namely,  sin,  or 
the  guilty  perversion  of  the  moral  idea  in  the  actual 
world, — that  which  man,  as  unholy,  wills. 

(3)  The  moral  in  its  restoration  by  redemption, 
that  is,  the  regeneration  of  moral  truth  out  of  sinful 
corruption, — that  which  is  willed  by  God  as  gracious, 
and  by  man  as  repentant. 

VOL.  II— 2 


2  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  50. 

These  three  forms  of  the  moral  or  ethical  stand,  in 
relation  to  humanity,  not  beside  but  before  and  after 
each  other, — constitute  a  moral  history  of  humanity  : 
the  first  stage  is  j>r0-historical ;  the  second  is  th'e  sub 
stance  of  the  history  of  humanity  up  to  Christ ;  the 
third  is  the  substance  of  that  stream  of  history  which 
proceeds  from  Christ  and  is  embodied  in,  and  carried 
forward  by,  those  who  belong  to  Christ. 

As  in  Christianity  all  religious  and  moral  life  stands  in  re 
lation  to  the  redemption  accomplished  in  Christ,  that  is,  to  an 
historical  factt  hence  Christian  ethics  must  also,  under  one 
of  its  phases,  bear  an  historical  character.  Man  is  Christianly- 
moral  only  in  so  far  as  he  is  conscious  of  being  redeemed  by 
Christ ;  hence  in  this  Christianly-moral  consciousness  the 
abqve-stated  three  thoughts  are  directly  involved.  Only  that 
one  can  know  himself  as  redeemed  who  knows  himself  as 
sinful  without  redemption ;  and  only  he  can  know  himself  as 
sinful  who  has  a  consciousness  of  the  moral  ideal.  The 
classification  of  ethics  here  presented  is  based  therefore  in 
the  essence  of  Christian  morality  itself.  The  first  division 
presents  ideal  morality  as  unaffected  as  yet  by  the  reality  of 
sin, — morality  in  the  state  of  innocence ;  the  second  presents 
the  actual  morality  of  man  as  natural  and  spiritually-fallen, — 
morality  in  the  state  of  sin;  the  third  presents  the  Christian 
morality  of  man  as  rescued  from  sin  by  regeneration,  and 
reconciled  to  and  united  with  God, — morality  in  the  state  of 
grace.  The  first  part  is  predominantly  a  steadily-progressive 
unfolding  of  the  moral  idea  per  se  ;  the  second  belongs  pre 
dominantly  to  historical  experience;  while  the  third,  as  a 
reconciling  of  reality  with  the  ideal,  belongs  at  the  same 
time  to  both  fields.  The  historical  person  of  Christ  is,  for  all 
three  spheres  of  the  moral,  a  revelation  of  the  truth  that  is  to 
be  embraced ;  in  relation  to  ideal  morality  Christ  is  the  pure 
moral  prototype  per  se — the  historical  realization  of  the  moral 
idea;  in  relation  to  the  moral  state  in  the  second  sphere,  he 
manifests  the  antagonism  of  sin  to  moral  truth,  in  the  hatred 
of  which  he  is  the  object ;  in  relation  to  the  third  sphere,  he 


§  50.]  PURE    ETHICS.  3 

is  the  essentially  founding  and  co-working  power,  and  mani 
fests  the  antagonism  of  holiness  to  sin. 

To  present  distinctively-Christian  morality  alone  would  be 
scientifically  defective,  as,  without  the  two  antecedent  forms 
of  the  moral,  it  cannot  be  properly  understood.  To  present 
ideal  morality  alone  is  the  task  of  .purely  philosophical  ethics, 
— usually,  however,  instead  of  the  proposed  pretendedly  ideal 
ethics,  the  result  is  simply  an  artfully  disguised  justifica 
tion  of  the  natural  sinful  nature  of  unredeemed  man.  The 
ideal  morality  of  our  first  division  is  in  itself  fully  sufficient 
only  for  such  as  do  not  admit  an  antagonism  between  the 
actual  state  of  humanity  and  the  requirements  of  the  moral 
idea,  or  who  explain  it  into  a  mere  remaining-behind  the  sub 
sequently  to-be-attained  perfection,  instead  of  conceiving  of 
it  as  an  essentially  perverted  state.  The  fundamental  thought 
of  Christian  morality  is  this,  namely,  that  the  natural  man  is 
not  simply  normally  imperfect,  but  that  he  is,  guiltily,  in  an 
essential  antagonism  to  the  truly  good,  and  that  he  is  in  need 
of  a  thorough  spiritual  renewing  or  regeneration.  That  this 
is  the  case  is  not  to  be  proved  a  priori,  not  to  be  developed 
scientifically,  but  to  be  recognized  as  a  fact.  With -the  reality 
of  sin  the  moral  life  becomes  essentially  changed,  and  an 
ethical  treatise  which  should  make  reference  to  sin  only  as  a 
mere  possibility,  as  is  the  case  with  purely  philosophical  ethics, 
would,  for  this  reason,  be  insufficient  for  the  actual  state  of 
humanity.  The  history  of  humanity  has  become  in  all  re 
spects  other  than  it  would  have  been  without  sin,  and  hence  a 
complete  system  of  ethics  cannot  have  merely  a  purely  phil 
osophical,  but  must  have  also  an  historical  character, — must 
grapple  with  the  entire  and  dread  earnestness  of  real  sin.  If 
it  ended  at  this  stage,  however,  it  would  present  but  a  dismal 
panorama  of  woe,  utterly  unrelieved  by  a  gleam  of  comfort. 
But  divine  love  has  interrupted  the  history  of  sin  by  an  his 
torical  redemption-act,  and  founded  a  history  of  salvation 
inside  of  humanity, — has  given  to  man  the  possibility  and  the 
power  to  overcome  sin  in  himself,  and  to  rise  up  from  his 
God-estrangement  toward  the  moral  goal.  This  is  the  third 
sphere,  that  of  distinctively  Christian  morality,  which,  while 
it  has  indeed  its  prototype  in  the  ideal  ante-sinful  form  of 
morality,  is  nevertheless  not  identical  therewith,  inasmuch  as 


4  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  50. 

its  actual  presuppositions  and  conditions  are  entirely  differ 
ent,— namely,  no  longer  a  per  se  pure,  and  spiritually  and 
morally  vigorous,  subject,  and  no  longer  a  per  se  good,  and, 
for  all  moral  influences,  open  and  receptive,  objective  world, 
but,  on  the  contrary,  in  both  cases  an  obstinate  resistance ;  it 
is  in  both  respects  therefore  a  morality  of  incessant  struggle, 
while  that  of  our  first  division  is  rather  the  morality  of  a 
simple  detelopment ; — it  is  also  not  a  mere  pressing  forward 
out  of  an,  as  yet,  incomplete  and  in  so  far,  imperfect  state, 
but  a  real  overcoming  of  actual  immoral  powers;  and  the 
earnestness  of  the  morality,  as  well  as  of  the  ethical  system, 
rises  in  proportion  as  we  more  deeply  comprehend  the  inner 
and  essential  ditference  between  the  above-given  three  divis 
ions  of  the  subject-matter  of  ethics,  as  well  as  at  the  same 
time  their  inner  and  historical  connection. 

This  our  distribution  of  the  subject-matter  of  ethics,  though 
manifestly  very  accordant  with  the  Christian  consciousness, 
has  been  assailed  on  many  sides ;  and  especially  have  some 
writers  manifested  great  concern  as  to  whence  in  fact  we 
could  have  any  knowledge  of  this  ideal  and  strictly-speaking 
non-realized  morality.  Such  an  objection  ought  at  least  not 
to  be  urged  by  those  who  think  themselves  able  to  construct 
a  system,  even  of  Christian  ethics,  upon  the  mere  facts  of  the 
consciousness,  or  indeed  upon  a  basis  purely  speculative. 
But  certainly  all  who  conceive  of  sin  as  a  something  abso 
lutely  necessary,  will  of  course  have  to  regard  our  first  divis 
ion  as  a  pure  product  of  a  dreamy  imagination ;  we  contest, 
however,  to  writers  holding  such  an  opinion,  the  right  to  deny 
to  a  system  of  Christian  ethics — which  is  throughout  inspired 
with  the  thought  that  sin  is  the  ruin  of  men  [Prov.  xiv,  34] 
and  an  abomination  to  the  Lord  [xv,  9]— the  privilege  of 
treating  upon  and  discussing  that  which  God,  as  holy,  requires 
of  his  good-created  children.  As  to  whether  for  such  dis 
cussion  we  have  also  a  source  of  knowledge,  will  appear  as 
we  proceed. 


PART    FIRST. 

THE  MORAL  PER  SE  IRRESPECTIVELY  OF   SIN. 


(Dbsertwtiona. 


I.  NOTION  AND  ESSENCE  OF  THE  MORAL. 
SECTION  LI. 

THE  moral  idea  rests  upon  that  of  purpose  or  end. 
An  end  is  an  idea  to  be  realized  by  a  life-movement. 
Whatever  answers  to  an  idea  is  good  relatively  to  that 
idea.  Whatever  answers  to,  and  perfectly  realizes,  a 
rational,  and  hence  also  a  divine,  idea,  is  good  abso 
lutely.  All  divine  life  and  activity  has  a  divine  pur 
pose  ;  whatever  God  brings  to  realization  is  therefore 
absolutely  good, — is  in  perfect  harmony  with  the 
divine  will. — A  nature-object  is  good  per  se  and  di 
rectly,  in  virtue  of  the  creative  act  itself;  and  what 
ever  is  implied  in  it,  as  an  end  to  be  attained  to  by 
development,  is  actually  realized  in  fact  by  an  inner 
divinely-willed  necessity.  The  essence  of  a  rational 
creature  is  per  se  likewise  good  ;  but  its  full  realiza 
tion  as  that  of  a  truly  rational  being,  that  is,  its 
rational  end,  is  not  directly  forced  upon  it  by  natural 
necessity,  but  is  proposed  to  it  as  to  be  realized  by  its 
own  rational,  and  hence  free,  activity.  The  good 
ness  of  a  merely  natural  being  lies  in  the  necessarily 
self-fulfilling  purpose  of  God  in  the  creature ;  that 
of  a  rational  creature  lies  in  the  free,  self-fulfilling, 


6  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS  §  51. 

through  it,  of  the  will  of  God  to  the  creature.  The 
divine  will  is,  in  the  latter  case,  not  merely  an  end 
for  God,  it  is  also  a  conscious  end  for  the  rational 
creature.  The  good  in  general,  in  so  far  as  it  is  a 
conscious  end  for  a  rational  creature,  is  a  (concrete) 
good.  In  as  far  as  this  good  is  unitary  and  perfect, 
and  hence  perfectly  answering  to  the  divine  will  as 
to  the  creature,  it  is  the  highest  good, — which  conse 
quently  must  also  be  absolutely  one  and,  for  all 
rational  creatures,  essentially  the  same,  namely,  their 
fully  attained  rational  perfection.  Hence  all  rational 
development  of  a  rational  creature  aims  at  the  reali 
zation  of  the  highest  good. 

As  far  back  as  in  ancient  Greece,  philosophers  have  engaged 
in  the  discussion  of  the  notion  of  the  good,  and  of  the  highest 
good,  and  have  proposed  various  definitions  thereof, — those 
of  Aristotle  being  in  the  main  correct.  In  and  of  itself  the 
question  is  quite  simple ;  it  becomes  difficult  only  when  we 
look  upon  the  actual  condition  of  man  without  fully  taking 
into  account  the  antagonism  of  his  reality  with  his  ideal,  and 
are  for  that  reason  unable  clearly  to  distinguish  in  human 
aspirations  the  abnormal  from  the  normal.  As  to  the  notion 
of  the  relatively  good,  there  is  no  dispute;  it  is  always  the 
agreement  of  a  reality  with  an  idea  or  with  another  reality, 
and  hence  is  based  on  the  thought  of  a  mutual  congruity  of 
the  manifold. — The  simple  and  true  notion  of  the  good  is  in 
dicated  in  Gen.  i,  3,  4,  31 ;  [comp.  1  Tim.  iv,  4].  God  speaks 
and  it  comes  to  pass;  the  reality  is  the  perfect  expression  of 
the  divine  thought  and  will,  and  hence,  of  its  own  ideal. 
We  have  here  the  notion,  not  merely  of  the  relatively  good, 
but  of  the  absolutely  good ;  relatively  good  is  every  har 
monizing  or  congruence  of  the  different;  absolutely  good  is 
a  harmonizing  with  God.  Hence,  first  of  all,  God  himself  is 
good  and  the  prototype  of  all  good  [Psa.  xxv,  8;  Ixxxvi,  5; 
Matt,  xix,  17], — good  relatively  to  himself,  as  being  in  per 
fect  harmony  with  himself, — good  relatively  to  his  creatures, 
in  that  He  sustains  them  in  the  form  of  life  which  He  gave 


§51.]  PURE  ETHICS.  7 

them,  that  is,  in  their  true  peculiarities  and  autonomy,  and 
constantly  manifests  himself  to  them  as  their  loving  God  and 
Father  [Psa.  xxxiv,  9].  A  creature  is  good  in  so  far  as  it  is 
an  image  of  God, — namely,  such  a  revelation  of  the  divine  as 
is  conditioned  by  the  normal  peculiarity  of  the  creature, — 
and,  from  another  point  of  view,  in  so  far  as  its  actual  state 
is  in  harmony  with  its  essence,  its  ideal,  and  hence  also  (since 
all  creatures  are  created  for  each  other)  with  the  totality  of 
creation.  Every  thing  that  God  created  was  "very  good" 
also  in  this  respect,  namely,  that  the  different  creatures  con 
stituted  among  themselves  a  perfectly  concordant  and  har 
monious  whole;  "it  was  not  good  that  the  man  should  be 
alone,"  seeing  that  a  finite  creature  is,  in  its  very  essence, 
not  a  mere  isolated  individual,  but  should  constitute  a  mem 
ber  of  a  community.  Hence  the  expression  lit3  has  also  the 
signification  of  KeiAof,  gratus,  jucundus,  suavis ;  we  attribute 
this  quality  to  an  object  as  bearing  upon  ourselves  in  so  far 
as  it  harmonizes  with  and  reflects  our  own  peculiarities, — in 
so  far  as  we  feel  an  affinity  for  it  and  are  enriched  and  fur 
thered  by  it  in  our  life-sphere  and  activity.  Hence,  that  is 
truly  good  for  man  which  contributes  to  the  attainment  of 
his  true,  divinely-intended  perfection,  and  hence,  in  the  last 
instance,  this  perfection  itself.  Now,  a  mere  nature-object 
possesses  the  good  within  itself  as  a  necessary  law,  and  can 
not  but  realize  it ;  but  a  rational  creature  has  it  within  itself 
as  a  rational  consciousness,  as  a  free  law,  as  a  command,  and 
it  may  decline  to  realize  it.  In  a  nature-object  the  end  ful 
fills  itself ;  in  a  rational  creature  it  is  fulfilled  only  by  the  free 
will  of  the  same.  Nature-objects  are,  in  and  of  themselves, 
an  image  of  God  ;  but  man  was  created  not  only  in  accordance 
with  the  image  of  God,  but  also  unto  it, — has  this  image  before 
him  as  a  goal  to  be  attained  to  by  free  action,  as  a  rational 
task. 

Whatever  is  good  is  good  for  some  object,  and  is  for  the 
same,  in  so  far  as  actually  appropriated  by  it,  a  good,.  That 
only  can  be  a  true  good  which  is  good  absolutely,  that  is, 
divine;  all  true  goods  are  from  God  [James  i,  17],  and  lead 
to  God.  The  idea  of  the  highest  good  we  propose  here  to  de 
termine,  preliminarily,  not  as  to  its  contents,  but  simply  as 
to  its  form.  It  cannot  belong  exclusively  to  any  one  phase 


8  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§52. 

of  man's  being,  but  must  consist  in  the  symmetrical  comple 
tion  of  his  life  as  a  whole;  hence  it  cannot  be  simply  the  per 
fection  of  his  isolated  individuality  as  such,  but  only  as  a 
li\ing  member  of  the  living  whole.  Nor  is  the  highest  good 
a  merely  relatively  higher  among  many  other  less  high  goods, 
otherwise  the  sum  total  of  the  former  together  with  these 
latter  would  amount  to  something  higher  still ;  on  the  con 
trary  all  goods  collectively,  as  far  as  they  are  really  such, 
must  be  single  elements  of  the  highest  good  ;  and  the  simple 
fact  that  a  particular  object  which  I  desire,  and  which  hence 
seems  to  me  as  a  good,  is  adapted  to  be  a  manifestation  or  an 
element  of  the  highest  good,  is  clear  proof  that  it  is  a  real, 
and  not  a  merely  seeming,  good.  Whatever  a  man  aims  after 
appears  to  him  as  a  good ;  whatever  he  shuns,  as  an  evil ;  and 
rationality  consists  in  the  fact  that  he  aim  not  at  the  seem 
ingly,  but  at  the  really,  good,  and,  in  each  single  good,  at 
the  highest  good  ;  and  this  aiming  is  itself  good.  The  highest 
good  is,  consequently,  the  highest  perfection  of  the  rational 
personality,  or  the  perfect  development  of  God-likeness,  or, 
in  other  words,  the  perfect  agreement  of  the  actual  state  of 
man's  entire  being  and  life  with  his  ideal,  that  is,  with  the 
will  of  God, — which  all  are,  in  fact,  only  so  many  different 
expressions  for  the  same  thing.  Whatever  contributes  to 
this  highest  end  is  good ;  whatever  leads  from  it  is  evil. 

SECTION  LII. 

In  so  far  as  a  rational  creature  realizes  the  good 
rationally,  that  is,  with  a  consciousness  of  the  good 
end,  and  with  a  free  will,  it  is  moral.  The  moral  is 
the  good  in  so  far  as  it  is  realized  by  the  free  will  of 
a  rational  creature;  and.  in  this  manifestation  of  ra 
tional  life,  both  the  will,  and  also  the  action  and  the 
(Mid,  are  moral ;  and  true  morality  consists  in  the  com 
plete  harmony  of  these  three  elements.  Morality  is 
therefore  the  life  of  a  rational  being  who  accom 
plishes  the  good  with  conscious  freedom,  arid,  hence, 
works  the  harmony  of  existence, — as  well  the  harmony 


§  52.]  PURE   ETHICS.  9 

of  its  own  being  with  God  as  also  (and  in  fact  there 
by)  the  harmony  of  the  being  in  and  with  itself  and 
with  all  other  beings,  in  so  far  as  they  themselves  are 
in  harmony  with  God.  Morality,  therefore,  embraces 
within  itself  two  phases  of  rational  life :  on  the  one 
hand,  it  preserves  and  develops  the  normal  autonomy 
and  peculiarity  of  the  moral  subject, — does  not  let  it 
vanish  into,  or  be  absorbed  by,  God  or  the  All, — for 
there  is  harmony  only  where  there  is  a  distinctness 
and  individuality  of  the  objects  compared  ;  on  the 
other  hand,  it  does  not  permit  this  difference  to  be 
come  an  antagonism  or  contradiction,  but  preserves 
it  in  unity, — shapes  it  into  rational  harmony.  The 
moral  is  therefore  the  beautiful  in  the  sphere  of  ra 
tional  freedom. — is  rationally  self-manifesting  free 
dom  itself.  To  be  rational  and  to  be  moral  is,  in  the 
sphere  of  freedom,  one  and  the  same  thing. 

Moralness  bears  the  same  relation  to  the  goodness  of  mere 
nature-objects,  as  conscious  freedom  to  unconscious  necessity. 
The  goodness  of  creatures  is  not  their  rriere  being,  but  their 
life,  for  God  whose  image  they  are,  is  life ;  God  is  not  a  God 
of  the  dead  but  of  the  living.  Hence  the  goodness  of  rational 
creatures  is  essentially  life  also,  and  in  this  life  morality  real 
izes  the  good.  With  this  view  of  morality  we  may  properly 
enough  speak  also  of  a  morality  of  God  ;  the  fact  that  human 
morality  is  really  a  progressive  development  of  the  image  of 
God,  even  presupposes  this;  moreover  the  Scriptures  posi 
tively  express  this  thought,  and  there  is  no  good  ground  for 
explaining  it  away.  God  is  good  [nio]  and  upright;  [fif-i; 
Deut.  xxxii,  4;  Psa.  xxv,  8];  hence  our  German  hymn:  "O 
God,  thou  upright  God ! "  is  strictly  Biblical.  God,  as  the 
absolutely  holy  will,  is  perfect  morality  itself,  inasmuch  as 
his  entire  being  and  activity  are  in  perfect  accord  with  his 
will  and  essence,  and  inasmuch  as  his  infinite  justice  and  love 
establish  and  uphold  the  harmony  of  life  in  the  created  uni 
verse.  God's  morality  is  his  holiness.  For  this  reason  God 


10  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [g  53. 

is  also  the  perfect  prototype  and  pattern  of  all  morality ;  "  ye 
shall  therefore  be  holyf  for  I  am  holy "  [Lev.  xi,  45] ;  also 
virtue,  aperi?,  in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word,  is  attributed  to 
God  [1  Pet.  ii,  9;  2  Pet.  i,  3].  Hence,  man  is  moral  not 
merely  in  general,  in  that  he  makes  God's  will  the  law  of  his 
life,  but  more  specifically,  in  that  he  makes  God's  morality 
his  pattern.  In  God  all  good  is  also  moral  or  holy ;  in  the 
creature,  all  that  is  moral  is  also  good,  but  all  that  is  good  is 
not  also  moral. 

Rothe  objects  to  the  more  common  notion  of  the  moral, 
because  it  embraces  only  the  idea  of  the  morally-good,  but  not 
that  of  the  moral  in  its  secondary  sense ;  in  his  view  a  defini 
tion  of  the  moral  should  include  also  the  morally-evil.  It  is 
evidently  proper,  however,  to  confine  a  notion  primarily  to 
the  normal  manifestation  of  its  contents,  and  to  treat  the  con 
trary  manifestation  as  an  abnormal  perversion.  Surely,  for 
example,  it  would  be  too  much  to  ask  that  the  notion  of  the 
rational  be  so  conceived  as  to  embrace  also  the  irrational, — 
that  of  organism,  so  as  to  include  also  disease.  In  fact  the 
'objection  of  Rothe  has  weight  with  him,  chiefly  for  the  rea 
son  that,  in  his  system,  evil  is  viewed  not  as  a  merely  morbid 
phenomenon,  but  on  the  contrary  as  a  necessary  transition- 
state  of  development ;  ia  which  case,  of  course,  a  definition 
of  the  moral  would  have  to  include  also  evil. 


SECTION  LIII. 

Though  morality,  as  the  free  realizing  of  the  good, 
appears  essentially  in  the  sphere  of  the  will,  yet  as 
this  will  is  a  rational  one, — the  expression  of  a  con 
sciousness  and  of  a  love  to  the  object  of  that  con 
sciousness,— hence,  morality  embraces  the  whole  life 
and  being  of  the  spirit  in  all  its  forms  of  manifesta 
tion,  as  knowing,  feeling,  and  willing.  Moral  know 
ing  \*  faith,  not  only  religions,  but  also  rational  faith 
in  general;  moral  feeling  is  pleasure  in  the  good,  and 
love  of  it,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  displeasure  in  the 


§  53.]  PURE   ETHICS.  11 

non-good  ;  moral  willing  is  a  striving  after  the  reali 
zation  of  the  good.  Morality  itself,  however,  is  not 
one  of  these  three,  but  always  and  necessarily  the 
union  of  all  three  of  these  phases  of  the  spirit-life. 

These  three  phases  of  the  spirit-life  are  severally  and  col 
lectively  an  expression  of  the  union  of  the  subject  with 
objective  being,  with  the  All  in  general, — in  the  final  in 
stance  with  God.  The  subject  itself  becomes  also  to  itself 
an  object,  and  only  thereby  attains  to  its  truth.  The  mere 
isolatedness  of  a  being  is  per  se  evil,  is  the  opposite  of  true 
existence  and  life,  the  ruin  of  life,  that  is,  death, — is  a  disso 
lution  of  the  unitary  collective  life  into  indifferent  ultimate 
atoms.  The  individual  exists  in  its  truth  only  in  so  far  as  it 
comes  into  union  with  the  All ;  this  union  is  not  its  annihila 
tion  but  its  preservation,  its  recognition  in  the  All  as  an 
organic  member  of  the  same ;  it  is  a  mutual,  vital  relation,  a 
unity  in  diversity;  and  this  is  in  fact  the  essence  of  life, 
namely,  that  both  the  individual  being  and  the  collective 
whole,  in  all  its  parts,  stand  in  relation  to  each  other,  and 
that,  in  this  relation,  the  individual  is,  on  the  one  hand,  as 
a  member,  quite  as  fully  at  one  with  the  whole,  as,  on  the 
other,  it  is  an  integral  being  of  itself. 

In  actively  knowing,  man  brings  the  object  into  relation 
to  himself, — takes  it  up,  in  its  idea,  spiritually  into  himself; 
in  feeling,  the  subject  brings  himself  in  this  spiritual  appro 
priation  into  relation  to  himself, — embraces  the  appropriated 
object  as  in  harmony  or  as  in  disharmony  with  his  own  be 
ing  and  character,  that  is,  as  pleasing  or  displeasing ;  in 
willing,  the  subject  assumes  an  active  determining  relation 
toward  the  approvingly  or  disapprovingly  received  object; 
hence,  the  will  rests  on  feeling,  as  in  turn,  feeling  on  knowl 
edge,  though  the  latter  may  be  obscure  and  only  half-con 
scious.  In  each  of  these  three  respects  the  spirit  may  be 
more  or  less  free  or  unfree ;  in  so  far  so  it  is  free,  it  is  also 
moral.  It  is  true,  knowing  and  feeling  are  primarily  un 
free, — they  press  themselves  directly  upon  the  essentially 
passive  subject  without  his  voluntary  co-operation,  and  in 
so  far  as  this  is  the  case  they  are  as  yet  extra-moral ;  but  the 


12  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  53. 

moment  they  appear  as  freely  willed  they  enter  into  the 
moral  sphere,  and  this  is  their  higher,  rational  form.  Know 
ing  is  moral  when  we  will  to  know  rationally,  that  is,  when 
we  embrace  isolated  being,  whether  that  of  objective  nature 
or  of  ourselves,  as  not  existing  for  itself  in  its  isolation,  but 
on  the  contrary,  when,  passing  beyond  its  isolatedness,  we 
conceive  it  as  having  ultimately  a  divine  ground, — in  other 
words,  when  we  associate  all  individual  being  with  the  in 
finite  being  and  life  of  God,  and  thus  conceive  all  existence 
as  unitary  and  as  established  by  God.  Now,  this  passing 
beyond  the  individual  object  is  not  an  unfree  process ;  the 
object  does  not  force  us  to  do  so,  much  rather  it  arrests  us  at 
its  own  immediate  reality ;  but  it  is  bur  rational  nature  that 
induces  us  to  will  to  pass  beyond.  Knowing  becomes  moral 
when  it  becomes  a  pious  consciousness, — assumes  a  religious 
character;  and  this  pious  associating  of  the  finite  with  the 
infinite  \s  faith,  which  is  in  its  very  essence  religious.  Faith 
can  never  be  compelled  by  a  presentation  of  arguments ;  in 
all  its  forms  it  is  a  voluntary  matter ;  and  from  the  simple 
fact  that  faith  is  a  moral  knowing,  and  hence  includes  within 
itself  willingness  and  love,  it  is  consequently  not  a  mere 
knowing,  not  a  mere  holding-for-true ;  hence  it  may  be,  and 
is,  a  moral  requirement.  Without  this  willingness  to  find  and 
acknowledge  the  divine  in  infinite  objects,  there  is  no 
knowledge  of  God,  and  hence  no  real  rationality  of  knowl 
edge.  Though  faith  is  essentially  religious,  nevertheless, 
springing  forth  from  this  source,  it  overflows  and  fructifies 
with  its  moral  potency  the  entire  field  of  rational  knowledge. 
By  virtue  of  this  faith  we  have  confidence  in  the  truthfulness 
of  the  universe,— confidence  that  truth  is  discoverable,  that 
the  laws  of  our  mind  and  the  impressions  made  upon  us  by 
the  external  world  are  not  untrue  and  defective,  that  divine 
order  and  conformity  to  law,  and  hence  conformity  to  reason, 
pervade  the  universe,  so  that,  consequently,  we  may  rely  on 
this  order  and  this  conformity  to  law.  Without  such  a  faith, 
without  such  a  confidence  independently  of  all  presentation 
of  evidence,  there  could  be  no  knowledge — no  possibility  of 
a  spiritual  life  in  general.  Without  this  confidence  we 
would  be  unable  to  avoid  suspecting  poison  in  every  cup  of 
water,  in  every  morsel  of  bread, — we  would  tremble  lest,  at 


§  53.]  PURE   ETHICS.  18 

every  step,  the  ground  might  give  way  beneath  our  feet. 
Fondness  of  doubting  presupposes  depravity;  skepticism 
proper,  like  the  arts  of  sophistry,  is  an  immoral  dissolution 
of  rational  knowledge ;  under  the  skeptic's  eye,  both  the 
spiritual  world  and  the  realm  of  nature  fall  apart  into  lifeless 
ultimate  atoms. 

In  so  far  as  feeling  is  simply  a  direct  consciousness  of  such 
an  impressed  state  of  the  subject,  it  is  as  yet  extra-moral, 
because  unfree ;  it  becomes  rational  and  moral  through  free 
dom  on  the  basis  of  the  religious  consciousness, — namely, 
when  I  do  not  permit  myself  to  be  determined  by  finite 
things  in  an  absolutely  passive  manner,  but,  on  the  contrary, 
when  I  subordinate  all  my  states  of  feeling  to  the  power  of 
faith  or  of  the  religious  consciousness, — in  a  word,  when  I 
rise  so  far  into  the  sphere  of  freedom  as  to  have  pleasure  only 
in  that  which  is  God-pleasing,  and  displeasure  only  in  the 
ungodly, — when  my  love  to  finite  things  is  only  a  phase  of 
my  love  to  God. 

The  will,  the  more  immediate  sphere  of  the  moral,  is  in 
itself  likewise  not  as  yet  moral,  but  must  first  become  so. 
Free  will,  as  distinguished  from  the  unfree  impulse  of  the 
brute,  is  primarily  as  yet  devoid  of  positive  contents, — is 
only  the  possibility,  but  not  the  actuality,  of  the  moral.  It 
becomes  a  really  free  and,  hence,  a  moral  will  only  by  com 
ing  into  relation  to  faith,  namely,  in  that  it  ceases  to  be  a 
merely  individual  will  determined  solely  by  the  isolated  per 
sonality  of  the  subject, — for,  as  such,  it  is  as  yet  simply 
irrational  and  animal, — and  furthermore  in  that  it  imbues 
itself  with  a  positive  faith, — determines  itself  by  its  God- 
consciousness  and  by  its  love  to  God, — so  that  thus,  passing 
beyond  mere  finite  being,  it  bases  its  outgoings  on  a  rational 
faith  in  the  infinite.  This  is  so  wide-reaching  a  condition 
of  the  moral  will,  that  even  an  evil  will  (which  also  lies 
within  the  sphere  of  the  moral)  is  determined  by  a  certain 
faith-consciousness,  seeing  that  such  a  will  is  a  rebelling 
against  its  God-consciousness ;  "  devils  also  believe  "  in  God's 
existence  "  and  tremble  "  [James  ii,  19] ;  the  degree  of  guilt 
is  strictly  determined  by  the  degree  in  which  God  is  known. 
Hence  the  will  is  morally  good  when  it  rests  on  faith, — when 
it  strives  to  realize  the  God-pleasing  1  ecause  of  its  God-con- 


14  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  54. 

sciousness  and  of  its  love  to  God ;  and  it  is  morally  evil  when, 
despite  its  God-consciousness,  it  aims  at  the  ungodly, — seeks 
to  divorce  finite  beings,  and  especially  its  own,  from  its 
union  with  God.  Hence  in  general  terms,  though  morality 
has  its  essential  sphere  in  the  will,  yet  it  also  embraces,  as 
intimately  involved  therein,  the  spheres  of  knowledge  and  of 
feeling. 

SECTION  LIV. 

As  the  life  of  a  rational  spirit  is  continuous,  name 
ly,  a  continuous  free  activity,  hence  it  bears  contin 
uously  a  moral  character.  Morality  is  not  simply  a 
succession  of  single  moral  points,  it  is  an  uninter 
rupted  life,  and  every  moment  of  the  same  is  either 
in  harmony  or  in  antagonism  with  the  moral  end, — 
is  either  good  or  evil.  In  the  entire  life  of  man 
there  is  not  a  single  morally  indifferent -moment  or 
state. 

Man  is  God's  image  only  in  so  far  as  he  lives  this  God-like 
ness,  for  God  is  life,  and  all  life  is  continuous ;  a  real  inter 
ruption  of  the  same  is  its  destruction, — is  death.  Sleep  is  only 
a  change  in  the  manifestation  of  life,  arising  from  the  union 
of  the  spirit  with  material  nature,  but  not  a  real  interruption 
of  the  same.  Spirit  sleeps  not;  also  the  slumbering  spirit  is 
moral, — may  be  pure  or  impure ;  the  soul  of  the  saint  cannot 
have  unholy  dreams;  dreams  are  often  unwelcome  mirrorings 
forth  of  impure  hearts;  when  Jacob  rebuked  nis  son  Joseph 
for  his  supposed  ambitious  dream  [Gen.  xxxvii,  10],  his  moral 
judgment  was  quite  correct, — simply  his  hypothesis  was  erro 
neous.  Any  assumption  that  there  are  morally  indifferent 
moments  in  life  is  anti-moral.  And  that  there  are,  in  fact,  in 
the  natural  life  of  man  middle  states  between  life  and  death, — 
for  example,  swoons,— is  of  itself  a  fruit  of  depravity,  and  in 
the  same  sense  that  death  is  such.  Morality  is  the  health  of 
the  rational  spirit;  and  every  interruption  of  health  is  disease. 
God's  will  is  incessantly  binding;  there  is  absolutely  nothing 
conceivable  which  would  not  either  harmonize  with,  or  antag- 
ouize,  it. 


§  55.]  PURE   ETHICS.  15 

II.    RELATION  OF  MORALITY  TO  RELIGION. 

SECTION   LV. 

The  religious  consciousness, — which  expresses  the 
couditionment  of  our  being  and  life  by  God,  and  which, 
as  a  state  of  heart,  is  piety, — is  necessarily  and  inti 
mately  connected  with  morality,  so  that  neither  is 
possible  without  the  other;  yet  they  are  not  identi 
cal.  Religion  and  morality,  both,  bring  man  into 
relation  to  God.  In  religion,  however,  his  relation 
is  rather  of  a  receptive  character, — he  permits  the 
divine  to  rule  in  him ;  in  morality  he  is  more  self- 
active,  he  reflects  forth  the  God-pleasing  from  within 
himself.  In  religion  he  exalts  himself  to  communion 
with  God;  in  morality  he  evidences  this  communion 
by  developing  the  divine  image  both  in  himself  and 
in  the  external  world.  In  religion  he  turns  himself 
away  from  finite  individuality  and  multiplicity,  and 
toward  the  unitary  central-point  of  all  life ;  in  mo 
rality  he  turns  himself  from  this  divine  life-center  as 
a  basis,  toward  the  periphery  of  created  being, — 
from  unity  toward  multiplicity, — in  order  to  manifest 
the  former  in  the  latter.  The  two  movements  cor 
respond  to  the  double  life-stream  in  every  natural 
organism,  and  hence  they  are  simply  two  inseparably 
united  phases  of  one  and  the  same  spiritual  life ;  and 
the  very  commencement  of  spiritual  life  involves  the 
union  of  them  both.  In  religion  and  in  morality 
God  glorifies  himself  no  less  than  in  creation, — in 
religion  for  and  in  man,  in  morality  through  man  ; 
and  the  moral  man,  in  that  he  fulfills  God's  will  in 
and  for  the  world,  actually  accomplishes  the  divine 


16  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§55. 

purpose  in  creation. — the  free  moral  activity  of  man 
being,  in  fact,  the  divinely-willed  continuation  and 
completion  of  the  work  of  creation. 

The  consciousness  that  we,  as  separate  individuals,  have 
no  absolutely  self-sufficient  and  independent  existence  and 
rights,  as  also  that  we  are  not  simply  dependent  on  other 
finite  powers,  but,  on  the  contrary,  on  an  infinite  divine  first 
cause,  is  of  a  religious  character ;  and  the  spiritual  life  that 
develops  itself  on  the  basis  of  this  consciousness  is  the  relig 
ious  life.  In  so  far,  however,  as  it  is  a  disposition  or  state  of 
heart,  that  is,  in  so  far  as  it  expresses  itself  in  the  feeling  of 
love  to  God  and  in  the  thence-arising  habit  of  will,  it  is  piety, 
— in  which  form  it  assumes  directly  also  the  character  of 
morality.  A  pious  life  is  per  se  also  a  moral  one ;  and  morality 
is  the  practical  outgoing  of  piety.  Religion  and  morality  are 
therefore  most  closely  and  inseparably  associated ;  as  morality 
rests  on  the  recognition  that  the  good  is  either  the  actual  state 
or  the  final  destination  of  all  existence,  and  as  this  recogni 
tion,  even  in  its  rudest  forms,  is  of  a  religious  character  (since 
the  "good"  can  have  no  meaning  save  as  the  divine  ultimate 
destination  of  creation),  hence  morality  without  religion  is 
impossible,  and  its  character  rises  and  falls  with  the  clear 
ness  and  correctness  of  the  religious  consciousness.  He 
who  despises  religion  is  also  immoral ;  and  the  immoral 
man  is  also  correspondingly  irreligious ;  all  immorality  is  a 
despising  of  God,  since  it  is  a  despising  of  the  good  as  the 
God-like.  As  now,  on  the  other  hand,  religion  is  a  believ 
ing,  and  hence  a  free,  loving  recognition  of  the  divine,  and 
as  it  places  man  in  a  living  relation  with  God,  hence  all 
religion  is  per  se  also  moral,  and  religion  without  morality  is 
inconceivable. 

Thus,  whatever  is  moral  is  religious,  and  whatever  is  re 
ligious  is  moral;  and  yet  these  two  are  not  identical;  every 
religious  life  includes  in  itself  a  moral  will,  and  every  moral 
action  contains  a  religious  element, — implies  religious  faith ; 
"without  faith  it  is  impossible  to  please  God"  [Heb.  xi,  6J. 
This  looks  like  a  contradiction  utterly  irreconcilable  save  by 
making  religion  and  morality  absolutely  one  and  the  same 
thing.  Things,  however,  that  are  indissolubly  associated,  as, 


§  55.]  PURE   ETHICS.  17 

for  example,  heat  and  light  in  the  rays  of  the  sun,  need  not 
for  that  reason  be  identical.  In  the  .religiously-moral  life 
two  things  are  always  united :  our  individual  personality  as  a 
relatively  self-dependent  legitimate  entity,  and  the  recogni 
tion  of  God  as  the  unconditioned  ground  of  our  entire  being 
and  life, — that  is  to  say,  an  affirming  and  also  a  relative 
negating  of  our  separate  individuality,  an  active  and  a  pas 
sive  element.  Both  are  equally  true  and  important ;  the  one 
calls  for  the  other,  and  either,  taken  separately  for  itself, 
would  be  untrue ;  the  two  must  exist  in  harmony  and  unity. 
The  passive  phase — the  emphasizing  of  the  being  of  God  in 
the  presence  of  which  individual  being  retires  into  the  back 
ground  and  appears  only  as  conditioned  and  dependent — is 
the  religious  phase  of  the  spiritual  life;  the  active  phase — 
that  is,  the  emphasizing  of  the  personal  element  by  virtue  of 
which  man  appears,  as  an  initiative  actor  with  the  mission,  as 
a  free  personality,  of  carrying  farther  forward  in  the  spiritual 
sphere  the  creative  work  of  God — is  the  moral  phase.  The 
religious  life  is,  so  to  speak,  centripetal ;  moral  life,  as  radi 
ating  out  from  the ,  middle-point,  is  centrifugal ;  the  former 
corresponds,  in  the  spiritual  life,  to  the  functions  of  the 
veins  of  the  body ;  the  latter  is  more  like  the  arteries,  which, 
receiving  from  the  lungs,  through  the  heart,  the  vitalized 
out-gushing  blood,  distribute  it  nourishingly  and  produc 
tively  through  the  body,  and  ramify  themselves  out  toward 
the  periphery,  whereas  the  veins  conduct  it  back  from  the 
outermost  ramifications  toward  the  center.  In  correspond 
ence  to  this  figure,  the  separate  outgoings  of  the  moral  life 
are  more  manifold  than  are  the  center-seeking  manifestations 
of  the  religious  life.  Hence  piety,  by  its  very  nature,  tends  to 
a  communion  of  pious  life-expression,  to  the  social  worship  of 
God ;  but  in  morality  the  person  comes  into  prominence  more 
in  his  self-dependent  individuality :  in  the  sphere  of  morality, 
moral  communion  rests  more  on  the  moral  individuals ;  in  that 
of  piety,  the  pious  personality  rests  more  upon  pious  com 
munion  and  upon  the  spirit  which  inspires  this  communion. 
In  the  moral  sphere,  Christ  says  to  the  individual:  "  Go  thou 
and  do  likewise; "  in  that  of  religion  he  says:  "Where  two 
or  three  are  gathered  together  in  my  name,  there  am  I  in  the 
midst  of  them./'  Secret  prayer  does  not  conflict  with  this, 
VOL.  II— 3 


18  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  55. 

for  it  is  only  one  phase  of  piety ;  the  piety  of  the  recluse  is 
simply  morbid. 

Religious  life  is  only  then  genuine  when  it  is  at  the  same 
time  also  moral, — Avhen  it  does  not  in  Pantheistico-mysticai 
wise  dissolve  and  merge  the  individual  into  God ;  the  one- 
sidedly  religious  life  which  lightly  esteems  outward  morality 
entangles  itself  inevitably  in  this  quietistic  renunciation  of 
personality.  Moral  life  is  healthy  only  when  it  is  at  the  same 
time  also  religious, — when  the  person  does  not  assume  to  live 
and  act  as  an  isolated  being  from  an  unconditioned  autonomy 
of  its  own  independently  of  God ;  it  is,  however,  as  dis 
tinguished  from  the  religious  life,  essentially  a  virtualizing 
of  liberty.  The  one-sidedly  moral  life,  that  is,  the  attempt 
to  virtualize  personal  freedom  without  religion,  leads  to  the 
reverse  of  the  morally-religious  life — to  haughtiness  of  per 
sonality  as  of  an  absolutely  independent  power,  to  an  athe 
istic  idolizing  of  the  creature,  and,  in  practice,  to  a  throwing 
off  of  all  obligation  that  conflicts  with  "personal  enjoyment. 
The  moral  life  is  therefore  true  and  good  only  when  the 
virtualization  of  the  freedom  and  independence  of  the  per 
son  is  rational,  that  is,  essentially  religious ;  and  it  becomes 
morally  evil  so  soon  as  it  asserts  its  freedom  as  unconditioned 
and  apart  from  God. 

Piety  and  morality  consequently  mutually  condition  each 
other, — develop  themselves  in  no  other  way  than  in  union 
with  each  other.  It  is  true,  the  first  beginning  of  the  relig 
iously-moral  life  is,  in  so  far,  the  religious  phase,  as  all  re 
ligion  rests  upon  a  revelation  of  God  to  man,  that  is,  upon  a 
receiving,  and  not  upon  a  personal  doing;  but  this  revelation 
is  only  then  our  own,  the  contents  of  our  religious  spirit, 
when  we  embrace  it  in  faith,  and  this  embracing  is  a  free,  a 
moral  activity.  Hence  even  the  first  incipiency  of  the  ra 
tional,  the  morally-religious  life  includes  in  immediate  and 
necessary  union  both  phases  of  the  same,  so  that,  though  in 
logic  we  may  speak  of  the  one  as  being  antecedent  to  the 
other,  yet  in  point  of  reality  we  cannot  so  speak.  Should 
this  seem  enigmatical  to  the  understanding,  still  it  is  no  more 
enigmatical  than  is  the  nature  of  all  and  every  life-beginning; 
and  just  as  little  as  Mre  can  deny  the  reality  of  the  beginning 
of  man's  natural  life,  for  the  reason  that  it  is  absolutely  hid- 


PUKE   ETHICS.  19 

den  and  mysterious — so  that  we  can  neither  say  that  the 
material  being  of  the  same  is  antecedent  to  its  spiritual  power 
nor  the  converse, — even  so  little  can  we  hope  to  solve  the 
mystery  of  the  beginning  of  the  religiously-moral  life,  by  as 
suming  the  one  or  the  other  of  its  phases  as  the  first  and 
fundamental  one.  The  plant,  in  developing  itself  out  of  its 
embryo,  grows  upward  and  downward  almost  simultaneously ; 
if  it  is  insufficiently  rooted  it  fades ;  if  it  cannot  grow  upward 
it  decays ;  the  sending  out  of  roots  corresponds  to  religion ; 
the  development  into  foliage  and  fruit,  to  morality.  Also  in 
the  further  development  of  the  rational  life  these  two  phases 
are  constantly  associated,  and  in  their  associated  unity  and 
harmony  consists  the  spiritual  health  of  man.  We  are  relig 
ious  in  so  far  as  we  recognize  that  God  is  the  unconditioned 
ground  of  our  being  and  moral  life ;  moral,  in  so  far  as  by  our 
free  life  we  confess  in  acts  that  God  is  fer  us  the  absolute  rule 
of  action, — that  we  are  free  accomplishes  of  the  divine  will. 
In  religion,  God  is  for  us ;  in  morality,  we  are  for  God ;  in 
the  former  God  is  manifested  to  us ;  in  the  latter  God  is  mani 
fested  in  and  through  us.  "I  live,  yet  not  I,  but  Christ 
liveth  in  me "  [Gal.  ii,  20] ;  this  is  the  essence  of  Christian 
morality.  "As  many  as  are  led  by  the  Spirit  of  God,  they 
are  the  sons  of  God  "  [Rom.  viii,  14] ;  that  is,  religion  is  the 
vitality  of  morality,  and  morality  the  factive  life-manifesta 
tion  of  religion,  and  consequently  of  divine  sonship.  "  Fear 
God  and  keep  his  commandments,  for  this  is  the  whole  duty 
of  man"  [Eccl.  xii,  13;  comp.  Deut.  x,  12];  hence  the  fear 
of  God  is  the  ground  and  beginning  of  moral  wisdom;  "this 
is  the  fear  of  God,  that  we  keep  his  commandments  "  [1  John 
v,  3],  According  to  the  uniform  tenor  of  Scripture,  religion 
and  morality  go  always  hand  in  hand  ;  this  is  aptly  expressed 
by  Luther  in  his  Catechism :  "  We  should  fear  and  love  God, 
in  order  that,"  etc. ;  the  fear  of  God  necessarily  involves  the 
keeping  of  the  commandments,  and  this  fear  is  itself  of  moral 
character,  as  is  implied  by  the  very  word  "should"  ;  "if 
thou  doest  not  well,  sin  lieth  at  the  door"  [Gen.  iv,  7]. 
Hence  the  usual  Scripture  expression  for  morality  is :  "to 
walk  before  God  "  [Gen.  xvii,  1 ;  xxiv,  40],  that  is,  to  act  out 
of  a  full  consciousness  of  the  holy  and  almighty  One,  in  full 
trust  and  love  to  Him ;  or :  "to  walk  with  God  "  [Gen.  v, 


20  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  55. 

22,  24;  vi,  9],  to  "keep  the  way  of  the  Lord"  and  "do 
justice  and  judgment"  [Gen.  xviii,  19],  "to  walk  in  God's 
ways,"  "to  serve  the  Lord"  and  "to  keep  his  command 
ments  and  statutes  "  [Deut.  x,  12] ;  and  God's  exhortation  to 
the  progenitor  of  the  Israelites  is:  "I  am  the  Almighty 
God,  [therefore]  walk  before  me  and  be  thou  perfect "  [Gen. 
xvii,  1]. 

-The  glorifying  of  God  in  religion  and  morality  is  the  com 
pleting  of  his  glorification  in  nature.  In  religion,  God  per 
mits  the  man  who  comes  into  living  communion  with  Him, 
to  behold  his  glory ;  in  morality  God  permits  men  to  show 
forth  his  glory — to  let  their  light  shine  before  others  that 
they  also  may  praise  the  Father  in  heaven.  The  will  of  God 
in  creation  was  not  as  yet  fulfilled  at  the  conclusion  of  the 
creative  act.  "  Let  us  make  man  in  our  image,  after  our  like 
ness," — but  this  image  is  God-like,  not  in  its  mere  being,  but 
only  in  its  rational,  moral  life.  God  created  the  world  for 
rational  creatures,  in  order  that  for  them  and  through  them 
his  image  might  be  manifested  in  creation, — that  is  to  say,  in 
the  interest  of  moral  development.  Hence  sin  is  treachery 
against  God,  an  infringement  on  his  honor.  Morality  looks 
to  the  honor,  not  of  man,  but  of  God ;  it  is  per  se  a  serving 
of  God,  and  all  divine  service  or  worship  is  a  moral  act. 

The  relation  of  religion  to  morality  is  often  stated  quite  dif 
ferently  from  the  view  here  presented.  The  more  important 
of  these  views  are  the  following  four : 

(1)  Religion  and  morality  are  totally  identical.     In  develop 
ing  this  view,  the   one  is  necessarily  reduced  to   the  other, 
(a)  Morality  is  entirely  merged  into  religion — the  view  of  all 
consistent  mysticism ;  man  has  nothing  to  do  but  to  give  him 
self  entirely  over  to  God ;  and  wisdom  consists  not  in  acting, 
but,  on  the  contrary,  in  renouncing  all  practical  activity  (Eck- 
nrt,   Tauler,    Molinos).     (b)  Religion  is  entirely  merged  into 
morality.     Morality  is  directly  in  and  of  itself  true  religion; 
to  be  moral  is  identical  with  being  pious ;    outside  of  virtue 
there  is  no  piety  which  is  not  only  not  simply  associated  with 
virtue,  but  which  is  not,  in  fact,  itself  virtue ; — the  view  of  the 
worldly-minded  in  general,  and,  particularly,  of  the  "illumin- 
ism  "  of  the  eighteenth  century. 

(2)  Religion  and  morality  are  in  their  entire  nature  radically 


§  55.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  21 

different,  and  hence  entirely  independent  of  each  other;  the 
one  may  exist  without  the  other.  This  is  the  view  of  all  the 
naturalistic  systems  of  recent  date.  It  is  at  once  refuted  by 
the  simple  fact  that  the  different  religions  have  given  rise  to 
correspondingly  different  systems  of  morality. — In  approxima 
tion  to  this  view,  Rothe  affirms  (Ethik,  I,  Seite,  191,  sqq.)  at 
least  a  predominant  non-dependence  of  the  two  spheres  on  each 
other. 

His  position  is  as  follows : — Morality  and  piety,  while 
not  entirely  different,  are  yet  relatively  independent  and  self- 
based.  Each  has  indeed  a  certain  relation  to  the  other,  and 
there  is  no  morality  which  is  not,  in  some  degree,  also  piety ; 
both  have  the  same  root,  namely,  the  personality ;  but  the  two 
form,  nevertheless,  independent  branches  strictly  coetaneous. 
The  consciousness  of  this  relative  independence  of  morality 
belongs  among  the  inalienable  conquests  of  recent  culture, — 
namely,  the  consciousness  that  an  individual  human  life  may 
be  relatively  determined  by  the  idea  of  the  moral,  nay,  even  by 
the  idea  of  the  morally  good,  or,  more  definitely,  by  the  idea 
of  human  dignity  and  of  humanity,  without  at  the  same  time 
being  determined  by  the  idea  of  God, — and  indeed  in  such  a 
manner  that  it  shall  possess  this  idea  of  the  moral  as  not  de 
rived  to  it  from  the  idea  of  God.  The  Christian  moralist  can 
not  refuse  to  recognize  this  consciousness.  The  misconception, 
that  morality  can  rest  on  no  other  basis  than  the  religious 
relation,  would  at  once  vanish,  could  moralists  determine  to 
keep  distinct  the  moral  sensu  medio,  from  the  morally-good. 
For,  that  there  can  be  moral  evil  on  a  basis  other  than  a  re 
ligious  one,  will  of  course  be  questioned  by  none.  It  is  true, 
when  strictly  understood  or  comprehended,  the  idea  of  the  moral 
cannot  arise  apart  from  the  idea  of  God.^-These  last  two  state 
ments  of  Rothe  undermine  his  entire  position ;  for  the  ques 
tion  here  is  not  at  all  as  to  evil,  but  exclusively  as  to  the 
morally-good ;  and  it  is  hardly  possible  that  any  one  would 
argue  thus :  Because  evil  can  exist  without  religion,  therefore 
also  the  good  can  exist  without  religion.  Moreover,  in  admit 
ting  that  without  religion  man  can  be  morally-good  only  rela 
tively,  but  not  truly,  Rothe  implicitly  admits  also  that  morality 
is  in  fact  not  a  something  existing  alongside  of  religion  and 
in  real  independency  of  it;  consequently  the  above-assumed 


22  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§55. 

morality  that  is  independent  of  religion,  is  but  mere  appear 
ance. 

(3)  Religion  is  the  first,  the  lasis,  also  in  point  of  time ; 
while  morality  is  the  second,  the  sequence.     This  is  the  most 
usual,  also  ecclesiastical,  view ;  and  as  applied  to   Christian 
morality  it  is  also  undoubtedly  correct,  since  here  the  ques 
tion  is  as  to  being  redeemed  from  a  presupposed  immoral 
state;   in  which  case,  of  course,  the  religious  back-ground 
forms  the   basis  of  the  renewal,  from  which,  as  a  starting- 
point,  the  moral  will,  in  general,  must  rise  to  freedom.    Where, 
however,  the  moral  life  does  not  presuppose  a  spiritual  re 
generation,  there  no   moment  of  the   religious  life  is  con 
ceivable  in  which  it  does  not  also  contain  in  itself  the  moral 
element, — thus   absolutely  precluding  the  idea  of   a  prece 
dency  of  one  to  the  other;   moreover,  even  in  the  spiritual 
regeneration  of  the  sinner,  the  process  of  being  morally  laid 
hold  upon  by  the  sanctifying  Spirit  of   God,  issues  directly 
into  a  willing,  and  hence  moral,  laying  hold  upon  the  ottered 
grace  of  God. 

(4)  Morality  is  the  first,  the  basis,  while   religion  is  the 
second,  the  sequence,  also  in  point  of  time;  the  moral  con 
sciousness  of  the  practical  reason  is  the  ground  upon  which 
the  God-consciousness  springs  up ; — so  taught  the  school  of 
Kant,  and  in  part,  also,  Rationalism.     This  view,  in  its  practi 
cal  application,  coincides  largely  with  that  one  which  merges 
the  religious  into  the  moral.     It  is  true,  appeal  is  made  to 
the  passage  in  John  vii,  7:   "If  any  one  will  do  his  will," 
etc. ;   here,  however,  the  question  is  not  as  to  the  religious 
consciousness  in  general,  but  as  to  the  recognition  of  Christ 
as  the  Messenger  of  God.     But  whoever  purposes  to  do  the 
will  of  God,  must  have  a  consciousness  of  God  already. 

From  the  intimate  unity  of  religion  and  morality,  which 
we  have  insisted  upon,  results  readily  the  solution  of  the 
question,  as  to  how  and  whence  we  can  have  a  knowledge 
of  the  moral  condition  of  humanity  as  pure  and  unfalleu. 
The  sources  of  a  knowledge  of  religion  are  at  the  same  time, 
also,  the  sources  of  an  acquaintance  with  morality ;  and  re 
ligion  throws  light  not  only  upon  what  has  transpired  and 
now  is,  since  the  fall,  but  also  upon  what  preceded  all  sin. 
Thus  we  have  for  morality  in  general,  as  well  as  for  the  con- 


§  56.J  PURE   ETHICS.  23 

sideration  of  tnorality  irrespectively  of  sin,  the  following 
sources  of  information: — 1.  The  rational,  morally-religious 
human  consciousness,  both  as  it  is  yet  extant  even  in  the 
natural  man,  and  also,  as  it  is  enlightened  by  divine,  grace  in 
the  redeemed. — 2.  The  historical  revelation  of  God  in  the 
Old  and  New  Testaments.  Although  as  bearing  upon  the 
moral  sphere  Revelation  relates  predominantly  to  the  actual 
sinful  condition  of  humanity,  yet  it  contains  also,  at  the  same 
time,  the  holy  will  of  God  to  man  per  se.  The  moral  law  of 
Christ,  "Thou  shalt  love  thy  God,"  etc.,  is  in  fact  absolutely 
valid,  not  only  for  such  as  are  as  yet  implicated  in  sin,  but 
also  for  man  per  se,  and  irrespectively  of  sin ;  moreover,  it  is 
not  difficult  for  the  Christian  who  has  become  acquainted 
with  the  divine  economy  of  grace  to  distinguish,  in  the  di 
vine  precepts,  that  which  is  intended  for  the  chastening  and 
discipline  of  the  sinner,  from  that  which  is  morally  binding 
per  se. — 3.  From  the  personal  example  of  Him  who  knew  no 
sin,  from  the  holy  humanity  of  the  Redeemer. — So  much  here 
merely  preliminarily. 


HI.    SCIENTIFIC  CLASSIFICATION  OF  ETHICS. 
SECTION  LVI. 

The  usual  distribution  of  the  subject-matter  of 
ethics  into  the  doctrine  of  goods,  of  virtues,  and  of 
duties,  does  not  answer  the  nature  of  this  science,  as 
these  are  not  different  parts  of  the  whole,  but  only 
different  modes  of  contemplating  one  and  the  same 
thing, — modes  which  are  so  intimately  involved  in 
each  other,  that  such  a  classification  inevitably  in 
volves,  on  the  one  hand,  an  unnatural  severing  of 
the  subject-matter,  and,  on  the  other,  manifold  rep 
etitions  of  the  same  thought.  All  the  various  articu 
lations  of  this  science  into  the  mere  discussion  of 
virtues,  duties,  and  goods,  according  to  the  different 
classes  and  subdivisions  of  particular  virtues,  duties, 


24  CHRISTIAN   ETUICS.  [§  56. 

and  goods,  come  short  of  exhausting  the  subject- 
matter,  and  must  therefore  involve  the  throwing  of 
other  important  ethical  considerations  into  an  intro 
duction  or  some  other  subordinate  position. 

Among  the  various  classifications  of  the  matter  of  ethics,  the 
above-mentioned  is  in  recent  times  the  more  usual ;  it  is 
adopted  by  Schleiermacher,  though  only  in  his  Philosophical 
Ethics,  and  it  is  applied  by  Rothe  to  Theological  Ethics  also. 
In  both  of  these  writers,  the  importance  of  such  a  classifica 
tion  lies  in  the  thought  of  the  working  of  reason  upon  nature, 
in  which  morality  is  by  them  made  to  consist.  The  goal  of 
this  working,  namely,  the  positive  harmony  of  nature  and  rea 
son,  is  the  good;  the  power  of  reason  which  works  this  good, 
is  virtue;  the  mode  of  procedure  for  working  the  good,  the 
directing  of  the  activity  toward  it,  is  duty.*  This  view,  ir 
respectively  of  the  so-strongly  emphasized  thought  of  Rothe, 
of  the  good  as  a  harmony  of  (material)  nature  and  reason, — 
which  is  utterly  inapplicable  to  Christian  morality, — is  in  fact 
valid  also  for  Christian  ethics  (Schwarz).  In  Christ's  words: 
"  Seek  ye  first  the  kingdom  of  God  and  his  righteousness,  and 
all  these  things  [temporal  goods]  shall  be  added  unto  you" 
[Matt,  vi,  33],  are  comprehended  both  the  highest  good  and 
the  single  goods,  duty  and  virtue, — the  latter  being  embraced 
in  "righteousness,"  though  righteousness  is  indeed  more  than 
virtue.  There  is  a  difference  between  the  goal  to  be  reached, 
the  way  or  movement  toward  it,  and  the  power  of  the  subject 
which  conditions  this  movement ;  still  it  does  not  follow  from 
this  that  the  entire  subject-matter  of  ethics  can  be  organically 
and  exclusively  distributed  on  this  basis.  The  antithesis  of 
duties  and  goods  could  be  most  easily  carried  out,  since  the 
producing  activity  and  the  produced  result  are  clearly  dis 
tinguishable.  But  even  here  the  difficulty  arises,  that  true 
good,  and  hence,  of  course,  also  happiness  (as  Aristotle  very 
justly  remarks),  is  not  an  inert  result  but  an  activity ;  but 
every  activity,  if  it  is  rational,  must  be  the  expression  of  a  moral 
idea,  the  realizing  of  a  duty ;  so  that  we  are  brought  to  the  at 

*Schl*irm.  Syst.,  p.  71  tqq. ;  Grundlinien,  1803,  p.  175  sqq;  ifb.  d. 
Legriffdtt  hocfotcn  Gutea,  Werke  III,  2,  447  sqq.  Conip.  §.  48. 


§56.]  PURE   ETHICS.  25 

first  strange-seeming  conclusion,  that  dutiful  acting  is  itself  a 
part  of  the  being  and  essence  of  the  good, — is  in  one  respect 
itself  a  good.      The  family,  the   church,  the   state,   etc.,  are 
goods ;  but  these  all  are  conditioned  not  merely  on  dutiful  act 
ing, — they  themselves  are  a  purely  moral  life, — consist,  strictly 
speaking,  in  a  collectivity  of  moral  actions,  although  not  solely 
therein.      If  we   once   abstract  these  actions,   there   remains 
neither  family  nor  state  nor  church ;  these  are  not  mere  empty 
spaces  in  which  moral  acting  takes  place,  but  they  are  them 
selves  incessantly  generated  by   this  acting,    and  without  it 
would  not  exist, — just  as  the  fiery  ring  of  a  revolved  torch  is 
not  an  entity  per  se,   but  exists  alone  by  virtue  of  the  motion. 
Hence  the  visible  embarrassment  of  the  ethical  writers  in  ques 
tion  as  to  where  they  shall  treat,  for  example,  of  family  and 
political  duties,  whether  under  the  head  of  duties  proper  or 
of  goods. — Still  more  embarrassing  is  it  in  the  discussion  of 
the  virtues.     That  virtue  is  per  se  a  good,  being  an  end  to  be 
acquired  by  moral  effort,  is  perfectly  evident,  and  is  so  ad 
mitted  by  Schleiermacher  (Werke,  III,   2,  459)  ;     also  in  the 
above-cited  utterance  of  Christ,  righteousness   appears  as   a 
goal  of  effort,  as  an  element  of  the  essence  of  the  kingdom  of 
God  [comp.  Phil,  iv,  8J ;   we  a-nn  at  virtue,  and  we  possess  vir 
tues;    but  every  possession  is  a  good.     Now  as  goods  are  of 
course  not  merely  objective, — as  indeed  the  highest  good  of 
Christians,  the  possession  of  the  kingdom  of  God,  comes  not 
with    outward   observation  but  is  of  a  strictly  inward  char 
acter  [Luke  xvii,   20,  21],— hence  it  is  plain  that   virtue   is 
also  a  good;   as  indeed   the   kingdom  of  God  consists  "in 
power  "  [1  Cor.  iv,  20],  and  hence  by  its  very  nature  includes 
in  itself  virtue.     Hence  the  doctrine  of  goods  cannot  be  dis 
cussed  without  treating  also  of  virtue.     On  the  other  hand,  a 
merely  dormant  power  is  in  reality  nothing  at  all;   the  reality 
of  a  power  is  its  outgoing, — the  reality  of  virtue  is  moral 
action,  that  is,  the  fulfilling  of  duty.     It  is  not  possible,  there 
fore,  to  discuss  the  virtues  without  at  the  same  time  treating 
of  all  the  duties,  and  vice  versa,     Hence  the   distribution  of 
ethics   above-mentioned  can  be  adhered  to  only  so  long  as 
the   discussion  lingers  in   generalities    and   avoids    the  par 
ticular. 

Schleiermacher  and  Rothe,  in  fact,  admit  that  the  three 


26  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  56. 

divisions,  goods,  virtues,  and  duties,  are  not,  in  reality,  dif 
ferent  parts  of,  but  only  a  three-fold  manner  of  viewing,  the 
same  object, — yet  in  such  a  manner  that  in  each  of  the  three 
the  other  two  are  included,  if  not  expressly,  at  least  sub 
stantially.  The  doctrine  of  goods,  of  virtues  or  of  duties, 
embraces,  either  of  them,  according  to  Schleiermacher,  when 
fully  developed,  the  whole  of  ethics  (Syst.,  p.  76  sqq.).  The 
classification  in  question  can  therefore  be  carried  out  only  by 
arbitrarily  leaving  some  of  the  divisions  imperfectly  discussed. 
Particular  goods,  says  Rothe,  do  not  spring  from  the  working 
of  a  particular  virtue  and  through  the  fulfilling  of  a  particu 
lar  duty,  but  on  the  contrary  no  single  one  is  realized  other 
wise  than  through  the  co-working  of  all  the  virtues  and 
through  the  fulfilling  of  all  the  duties,  and  each  single  virtue 
contributes  to  the  realization  of  all  the  goods,  and  is  condi 
tioned  on  the  fulfilling  of  all  the  duties,  and  each  particular 
virtue  contributes  in  turn  to  every  dutiful  manner  of  action 
(i,  202).  Irrespectively  of  the  fact  that  the  latter  declara 
tions  are  too  sweeping, — seeing  that,  for  example,  the  family 
may  often  exist  as  a  good  without  the  virtue  of  courage,  of 
industry,  etc.,  and  that  courage  may  exist  apart  from  the  ful 
fillment  of  the  family  duties,  etc., — still  it  is  quite  evident 
that  if  either  of  the  three  divisions  in  question  were  really 
and  completely,  and  not  merely  in  general,  carried  out,  there 
would  remain  nothing  for  the  other  divisions  save  a  few  gen 
eral  observations.  The  family,  for  example,  is  a  good  only 
in  so  far  as  it  has  domestic  love  for  its  basis,  and,  in  point 
of  fact,  Ilothe  treats  of  domestic  love  among  the  goods ;  but 
what  remains  then  to  be  said  of  it  in  treating  of  the  virtues 
and  duties?  The  remarkable  scantiness  of  Schleiermacher's 
discussion  of  duties  is  itself  evidence  of  an  erroneous  classi 
fication.  And  Rothe  obtains  for  his  discussion  of  duties  (in 
fact  confessedly  finds  any  occasion  whatever  therefor)  simply 
because,  as  he  says,  reference  is  there  to  be  had  to  si/i,  so  that 
the  discussion  of  duties  becomes  essentially  the  portrayal  of 
struggle.  But  this  admission  destroys  the  very  basis  of  the 
classification; — were  it  not  for  sin,  a  discussion  of  duties 
would  not  be  possible,  whereas  the  basis  of  this  classification 
has  not  the  least  reference  to  sin.  If  Schleiermacher,  after 
speaking,  in  his  first  part,  of  chastity  and  unchastity,  had 


§  56.]  PURE   ETHICS.  27 

then  in  his  second  part  spoken  of  chastity  as  among  the  vir 
tues, — which  his  plan  required  of  him,  but  which  he  does  not 
do — and  in  his  third  part  fully  discussed  the  duties  of  chastity, 
then  in  order  to  carry  out  his  classification  he  would  have 
had  to  reiterate  the  same  matter  three  times. — Rothe  speaks 
in  very  strong  expressions  against  those  who  do  not  adopt 
this  classification,  affirming  that  all  previous  ethical  teaching 
and  phraseology  have  been  erroneous,  and  have  ignored  the 
fact  that  even  every-day  parlance  makes  a  difference  between 
being  virtuous  and  acting  dutifully; — as  if  common  usage  does 
not,  just  as  frequently  and  just  as  correctly,  speak  also  of 
acting  virtuously  and  being  true  to  duty!  Oddly  enough  it 
seems,  in  the  face  of  this  so-deemed  "imperishable  desert "  of 
Schleiermacher  in  regard  to  this  classification,  that  Schleier- 
macher  himself — clearer-sighted  here  than  Rothe — does  not 
apply  it  to  his  own  Christian  Ethics ;  and  not  only  that,  but 
he  even  declares  it  inadmissable  here, — seeing  that  a  descrip 
tion  of  virtue  and  a  description  of  the  kingdom  of  God  as  the 
highest  good,  cannot  possibly  be  kept  separate,  inasmuch  as 
virtue  is  simply  a  "habitus"  generated  by  the  Holy  Spirit 
as  indwelling  in  the  kingdom  of  God ;  nor  can  Christian 
ethics,  in  his  opinion,  be  treated  under  the  head  of  duties, 
seeing  that  no  one  duty  can  be  discussed  save  in  and  with 
the  totality  of  all  the  duties,  and  hence  in  connection  with 
the  idea  of  the  kingdom  of  God  (Chr.  Sitte.,  p.  77  »qq.}.  And 
the  same  might  also  be  said  against  the  application  of  this 
classification  to  Philosophical  Ethics. 

If  this  classification  of  general  ethics  into  the  doctrines  of 
goods,  of  virtues  and  of  duties,  is  practically  untenable,  much 
more  is  it  inapplicable  to  Christian  Ethics,  since  it  lacks  one 
essential  Christian  thought,  that  of  the  divine  law.  Schleier 
macher  presented  no  discussion  of  the  law,  as  he  wrote  wholly 
irrespectively  of  the  idea  of  God ;  and  for  this  reason  alone 
his  classification  Avould  be  inapplicable  to  Christian  Ethics. 
For  duty  is  not  identical  with  the  law.  The  law  is  objective, 
duty  subjective ;  the  law  is  the  moral  idea  per  se  in  its  definite 
form,  as  thought,  as  universally  valid — the  will  of  God  in 
general ;  duty  is  the  subjective  realization  of  the  law  for  a 
particular  individual  under  particular  circumstances, — relates 
per  se  always  to  the  strictly  particular,  the  actual.  The  law 


28  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  56. 

is  valid  always,  and  under  all  circumstances;  duty  varies 
largely  according  to  time  and  circumstances ;  the  very  same 
mode  of  action  which  is  to-day  my  duty,  may  be  to-morrow, 
contrary  to  my  duty ; — to-day  my  duty  is  silence,  to-morrow 
I  must  speak.  The  law  is  categorical,  duty  is  usually  hypo 
thetical  ;  the  former  is  the  expression  of  divine  morality,  the 
latter  of  human.  So  also  is  the  relation  of  goods  to  virtue; 
the  former  are  more  the  general,  objective  phase ;  the  latter 
is  more  the  particular,  personal,  subjective  phase ;  virtue  is 
the  subjective  possession  of  a  moral  power  the  product  of 
which  is  objective  good.  In  the  Old  Testament  the  moral 
life-movement  went  over  from  the  divine  objective  will, 
namely,  the  law,  to  the  human  subject  in  order  to  bring  the 
latter  into  possession  of  the  highest  good ;  in  the  Christian 
world  the  moral  life-movement  goes  out  from  the  subject  as 
being  already  in  union  with  God,  and  already  in  possession 
of  the  everlasting  good,  and  directs  itself  to  the  objective 
realization  of  God-like  being, — from  the  inward  possession  of 
the  kingdom  of  God  to  the  objective  manifestation  and  realiz 
ation  of  the  same. 

Of  other  scientific  classifications,  we  will  say  but  little. 
The  older  popular  division  of  the  subject-matter  of  ethics 
according  to  the  Ten,  Commandments,  was  a  form  very  wrell 
adapted  for  popular  Christian  instruction,  and,  indeed,  by 
giving  a  large  construction  to  the  more  immediate  scope 
of  these  commandments,  it  admits  of  the  treatment  of 
all  evangelically-ethical  thoughts:  it  does  not,  however, 
suffice  for  a  scientific  development  of  Christian  ethics,  seeing 
that  this  series  of  commands  was  constructed  primarily  for 
merely  practical  purposes ;  very  essential  points,  such  as  the 
moral  essence  of  man  and  of  the  good,  and  (as  parts  of  the 
latter)  of  the  state  and  the  church,  would  have  to  be  thrown 
into  introductory  or  collateral  remarks. — The  classification 
according  to  our  duties  to  God,  to  our  neighbor,  and  to  our 
selves,  while  in  fact  embracing  the  whole  circle  of  duties, 
yet  requires  likewise  too  much  of  the  essential  matter  to  be 
thrown  into  an  introduction. — Harless  makes  the  divisions, 
the  good  itself,  the  possession  of  the  good,  and  the  preserva 
tion  of  the  good;  but  by  "good"  he  understands  rather  the 
antecedent  condition  than  the  goal  of  the  moral  life;  by 


§57.]  PURE   ETHICS.  29 

"  possession,"  more  the  obtaining  and  preserving  of  the  pos 
session;  and  by  "preservation,"  rather  its  actual  manifesta 
tion.  This,  as  well  as  Schleiermacher's  theological  classifi 
cation,  relates  only  to  distinctively  Christian  ethics. — A  very 
common  classification  is,  into  general  and  special  ethics, — 
the  latter  treating  of  the  special  circumstances  and  relations 
of  the  moral  life ;  but  such  a  system  can  be  carried  out  with 
out  violence  only  when  the  first  division  is  reduced  to  a  mere 
general  introduction. 

SECTION  LVH. 

Morality  is  life,  and  hence,  activity  or  movement, 
and  more  definitely,  rationally-free  movement. 
Herein  lie  three  things :  the  subject  that  moves,  the 
end  toward  which  the  movement  goes  out,  and  the 
movement-activity  itself.  The  subject  goes  out  from 
its  immediate  condition  of  being  per  se,  through  move 
ment,  over  into  another  condition  which  lies  before 
it  as  an  end.  But  the  moral  subject  is  not  a  mere 
isolated  individual ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  the  freely 
self-developing  image  of  God  as  the  primitive  ground 
and  prototype  of  all  morality,  and  it  lives  only  in 
virtue  of  constant  inner-communion  with  God.  The 
holily-ruling  God  becomes,  as  distinguished  from  man, 
the  eternal,  holy  proto-subject  of  the  moral  life ;  and 
there  is  no  moment  of  the  moral  life  in  which  the 
human  subject,  strictly  per  se  and  without  God's  co 
operation,  works  the  good. — The  goal  toward  which 
the  moral  movement  directs  itself  is  also  of  a  twofold 
character.  Man  finds  himself  already  in  the  presence 
of  an  objective  world  different  from  himself;  and  even 
where  he  makes  himself  his  own  object,  this,  his 
reality,  is,  primarily,  a  gift  conferred  upon  him  with 
out  any  moral  action  on  his  own  part ;  this  conferred 
existence  (world  and  self)  is  the  working-sphere  of  his 


30  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  57. 

moral  activity — the  most  immediate  object  and  end 
of  the  same.  But  man  is  not,  in  his  activity,  to 
throw  himself  away  upon  this  objective  world — to 
merge  himself  into  it — but  he  is  to  shape  it  by  his 
own  power,  and  in  harmony  with  the  moral  idea, — 
to  make  the  possibility  of  the  good  into  real  good, 
to  realize  a  spiritual  end  in  and  through  the  object 
ive  world.  Hence  the  goal  of  the  moral  activity  is 
to  be  considered  under  two  phases :  (a)  As  a  pure 
object  untouched  as  yet  by  the  moral  activity, — as  a 
mere  platform,  as  material  given  for  the  moral 
activity  in  order  to  be  spiritually  dominated  by 
this  activity  so  as  to  become  a  spiritually  and  morally 
formed  real  good.  (J)  This  object  itself,  as  morally 
fashioned,  as  having  become  a  good, — existing  prima 
rily  only  as  an  idea,  a  rational  purpose,  but  afterward 
as  a  result  of  moral  activity,  as  a  fruit  realized, — that 
is  the  ideal  goal  proper,  or  the  end  of  the  moral 
activity.  In  the  first  case,  the  object  is,  for  the 
moral  activity,  a  directly-given  reality,  but  it  is  not 
to  remain  as  such  ;  in  the  second  case  it  is  primarily 
not  real,  but  exists  only  in  thought,  but  it  is  ulti 
mately  to  become  a  reality  expressive  of  the  thought. 
—The  third  phase  of  the  moral  movement,  namely, 
the  moral  activity  itself,  is,  as  spiritually  free,  like 
wise  of  a  twofold  character ;  on  the  one  hand,  it  is  to 
be  considered  from  its  subjective  side,  that  is,  in 
respect  to  how  it  is  rooted  in  the  subject  himself, 
and  from  him  issues  forth, — the  subjective  motive 
of  the  moral  activity,  the  source  of  the  stream  ;  on 
the  other  hand,  it  is  to  be  considered  as  a  life- 
stream^  sent  forth  from  the  subject  and  directed 
upon  the  object, — that  is,  the  activity  proper  itself 
as  having  become  real  and  objective  in  its  pro- 


§51]  PURE   ETHICS.  SI 

gressive   development   toward  the  attained  goal  in 
which  it  ends. 

The  subject-matter  of  ethics  falls,  therefore,  into 
the  following  subdivisions  : 

1.  The  moral  subject,  purely  in  and  of  itself  con 
sidered. 

2.  God  as  the  objective  ground  of  the  moral  life 
and  of  the  moral  law,  and  also  as  the  prototype  of  the 
moral  idea,  and  as  co- working  in  the  moral  life. 

3.  The  given  objective  existence  upon   which,   as 
material  to  be  fashioned,  the  moral  activity  exerts 
itself. 

4.  The  subjective  ground  of  the  moral  activity,  the 
personal  motive  to  morality. 

5.  The  moral  working  or  acting  itself,  the  moral 
life-movement  toward  the  moral  goal. 

6.  The  conceived  object  of  the  moral  activity,  its 
goal  or  end. — the  good  as  an  object  to  be  realized. 

While  Dogmatics  sets  out  most  naturally  from  the  thought 
of  God,  Ethics  takes  its  start  from  man,  the  moral  subject, 
inasmuch  as  morality  in  its  totality  is  simply  the  rational  life- 
development  of  man, — God  coming  into  consideration  here 
not  so  much  in  his  character  as  Creator  as  rather  in  that  of  a 
Lawgiver  and  righteously-ruling  Governor.  Should  we,  how 
ever,  divorce  Ethics  entirely  from  Dogmatics,  we  would,  of 
course,  have  to  preface  the  moral  discussion  of  man  by  a 
presentation  of  the  doctrine  of  God. 

The  idea  of  the  moral  subject,  of  the  rational  personality, 
is  the  foundation- thought  of  ethics, — the  root  out  of  which 
all  the  other  branches  spring.  But  man  is  a  morally  rational 
person  only  in  so  far  as  he  conceives  of  himself,  not  as  an 
isolated  individual,  but  as  conditioned  by  the  divine  reason 
and  the  divine  holiness.  Hence  the  idea  of  the  moral  per 
sonality  leads  out  beyond  itself  to  the  thought  of  God,  as  the 
eternal  fountain  and  the  measure  of  morality,  as  the  holy  and 
just  Lawgiver;  the  prototypal  relation  of  God  to  the  moral 


32  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  57 

has  its  personally-historical  manifestation  in  Christ,  the  Son 
of  God  ;  the  moral  idea  becomes  in  Christ  an  actually-realized 
ideal.  The  doctrine  of  the  moral  law  belongs  not  in  the 
sphere  of  the  human  subject,  but  in  that  of  the  divine,  for 
the  law  is  not  man's  but  God's  will. 

In  the  notion  of  the  moral  subject  considered  as  an  indi 
vidual  being,  there  lies  implicitly  also  the  notion  of  an  ob 
jective  world  different  from  the  same.  Morality,  as  active 
life,  has  this  world  before  it  as  its  theater  of  effort;  the 
activity  in  its  outgoing  comes  into  contact  with  a  reality  in 
dependent  of  itself,  which,  though  because  of  the  unity  of 
creation  it  is  not  antagonistic  to  the  subject,  is  nevertheless 
primarily  foreign  to  the  same,  and  not  in  any  wise  imbued 
with  or  dominated  by  it.  But  to  be  a  spirit,  implies  in  itself 
the  dominating  of  the  unspiritual,  the  entering  into  harmony 
with  all  that  is  spiritual.  It  is  the  task  of  the  moral  subject 
to  bring  about  this  domination  and  this  harmony.  Moreover, 
in  so  far  as  man  finds  himself  in  a  simply  given,  and  not  as 
yet  spiritually-dominated  and  cultivated  condition,  he  be 
comes  to  himself  his  own  object,  his  moral  activity  being 
directed  upon  himself. 

The  modifying  activity  as  exerted  upon  this  given  exist 
ence  is  not,  however,  of  a  purposeless  character,  but  it  has 
before  it,  in  the  rational  end,  an  ideal  object  the  realizing  of 
which  is  to  be  effected  by  the  activity  as  moral.  In  an  ethical 
discussion  which  follows  the  actual  order  of  the  moral  life, 
this  moral  activity  will  have  to  be  considered  first,  although 
with  constant  reference  to  the  moral  end.  This  activity,  as 
a  spiritual  outgoing  from  the  subject,  has,  on  the  one  hand, 
its  fountain  in  the  moral  subject,  on  the  other,  it  has  also  a 
development-course  as  a  stream.  Each  is  to  be  considered 
separately,  so  that  we  have  here  again  two  subdivisions. 
The  consideration  of  the  subjective  origin  or  ground  of  the 
moral  activity — its  motive, — has  to  do  with  the  why.  The 
existence  of  the  law  and  the  encountering  of  an  external 
world  by  the  subject,  do  not  suffice  to  explain  why  man 
should  enter  upon  a  course  of  moral  activity ;  there  must  be 
found,  as  distinguished  from  these,  a  motive  in  the  subject 
himself  that  prompts  directly  to  moral  activity, — that  sets 
the  subject  into  movement.  The  mere  "should"  is  not 


§  57.]  PURE   ETHICS.  33 

enough  to  move  us ;  we  may  remain  indifferent  and  emotion 
less  in  the  presence  of  every  "categorical  imperative"  and 
of  every,  however  well-grounded,  command ;  if  there  is  not 
some  impulse  to  activity  within  us,  all  and  every  command 
will  fall  back  powerless  from  us ;  and  this  impulse  must  be  of 
a  rationally-free,  a  moral  character. 

The  moral  activity  itself,  which  is  occasioned  by  this  inner 
motive,  is  to  be  considered  primarily  only  in  its  essence  and 
in  its  general  forms' of  manifestation,  and  it  involves  only  the 
general,  but  not  the  special,  discussion  of  the  doctrine  of 
duties.  By  far  the  largest  scope  of  special  activity  comes 
under  the  last  division  of  our  classification;  for  the  true 
essence  and  real  worth  of  moral  good  lies  in  the  fact  that  it  is 
not  a  dormant  possession,  but  that,  on  the  contrary,  it  unfolds 
continuously  new  and  richer  life, — just  as  a  natural  fruit  is 
not  simply  a  product  in  which  the  life  of  the  plant  ends,  but 
is  also  the  germ  of  a  new  life ; — with  this  difference,  however, 
that  the  fruit  of  the  moral  activity  is  not  merely  the  germ  of 
a  new  life  that  simply  repeats  its  former  self,  but  rather  of 
an  enriched,  spiritually-heightened  life.  In  the  attained 
moral  good  the  moral  life-movement  rises  to  a  new,  higher 
circulation ;  the  person  in  possession  of  this  good  has  become 
richer, — is  a  spiritually  higher-developed  personality;  the 
previously  existing  moral-subject  has  become  more  exalted 
and  spiritualized, — is,  in  fact,  the  already  attained  moral 
good  itself;  and  the  moral  activity  gains  thereby  ampler  and 
more  ennobled  contents ;  with  the  acquired  good  springs  up 
new  duty. 

In  elucidation  of  the  classification  we  have  given,  compare 
the  passages  Deut.  x,  12  sqq. ;  xi,  1  sqq. ;  xii,  1  sqq.  Here  we 
may  consider  as  the  moral  subject  the  people  of  Israel, — the 
moral  mission  and  activity  of  whom  cannot  possibly  be  un 
derstood  save  in  the  light  of  their  historically-moral  peculi 
arity.  Jehovah  is  the  sovereign,  requiring  moral  obedience 
to  his  will;  the  people's  sinful  hearts  [x,  16],  the  heathen 
country  and  inhabitants  [x,  19;  xi,  10  sqq. ;  xii,  2  sqq.],  and 
the  national  life  of  the  Israelites,  form  the  sphere,  the  theater, 
of  the  moral  activity ;  thankful  love  to  the  merciful,  long- 
suffering  God  is  the  moral  motive  [x,  15,  21  sqq.] ;  willing 
obedience,  the  walking  in  the  ways  of  God,  is  the  moral 
VOL.  II— 4 


34  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  57. 

activity ;  and  the  approbation  of  God  and  his  blessings  are 
the  moral  end  [x,  13-15;  xi,  8  sqq.  ;  xii,  7  sqq.]. 

In  consideration  of  the  thought  that  there  lies  at  the  basis 
of  all  moral  activity  an  end  to  which  the  activity  directs  it 
self,  it  might  seem  more  correct  to  consider  this  end,  namely, 
the  good,  before  discussing  the  moral  activity  itself;  however, 
on  the  other  hand,  as  the  realization  of  the  good  presupposes 
the  moral  activity,  and  as  we  are  to  consider  the  good  not  as 
simply  conceived,  but  as  realized,  and,  inasmuch  as  out  of 
the  realization  of  one  good  a  new  field  of  moral  activity  arises 
in  turn  before  us,  hence  it  is  clearly  more  natural,  in  fact,  to 
place  the  discussion  of  the  end  or  the  good  (as  being  actually 
the  last  in  the  order  of  the  moral  development)  in  the  last 
place ;  for,  it  is  in  fact  quite  evident,  that  we  cannot  speak 
of  the  family,  the  church,  and  the  state,  without  having  first 
examined  the  moral  activity  per  se.  To  begin  with  the 
discussion  of  the  good  would  be  the  so-called  "analytical 
method,"  whereas  ours,  on  the  contrary,  is  the  "synthetic;" 
— the  course  of  the  former  is,  so  to  speak,  retrogressive  -,  while 
the  latter  proceeds  forward,  more  in  the  actual  course  of  the 
moral  development,  and  hence  is  the  more  natural. 

The  first  three  subdivisions  of  our  classification  embrace,  it 
is  true,  only  the  antecedent  conditions  of  the  moral  activity 
itself;  but  it  does  not  follow  from  this  that  their  subject-mat 
ter  is  to  be  thrown  into  an  introduction.  Free  rational  life, 
as  an  object  of  ethics,  cannot  be  treated  as  a  mere  activity 
without  taking  into  consideration  also  the  active  subject,  as 
well  as  the  law  by  which  the  subject  is  governed,  and  the 
field  upon  which  it  acts ;  he  who  describes  vegetable  life, 
must  surely  speak  also  of  the  organs  of  plants.  In  any  case, 
a  controversy  as  to  whether  this  consideration  forms  only  an 
introduction  to  the  subject-matter,  or  is  a  part  of  the  subject  •• 
matter  itself,  would  be  very  unprofitable. 


§58.]  PUKE   ETHICS. 


CHAPTER  I. 

THE     MORAL     SUBJECT. 
SECTION   LVIII. 

THE  moral  subject  is  the  personal  spirit,  in  a  stricter 
sense,  the  created  spirit.  Between  the  different 
grades  of  spiritual  beings,  there  is,  in  respect  to  the 
moral  life-task,  no  essential  difference ;  and,  hence, 
for  the  individual  spirit,  the  life-task  never  comes  to 
a  definitive  close.  The  basis  of  the  moral  life  is  the 
individual  moral  person  ;  but  in  so  tar  as  a  plurality 
of  persons  constitute  themselves  into  a  spiritual  life- 
whole,  such  a  collective  totality  becomes  also  itself  a 
moral  subject  with  a  peculiar  moral  task. 

In  the  widest  sense  of  the  moral  thought,  even  God  him 
self,  as  the  holy  One,  is  a  moral  subject.  But  in  so  far  as 
ethics  has  regard  not  to  an  absolutely  infinite,  eternal  Being 
and  life,  but  to  a  task  accomplishing  itself  in  time,  it  con 
siders  only  the  created  spirit  as  a  subject  of  morality.  But 
all  created  personal  spirits  without  exception  are  moral  sub 
jects,  and  that  too  with  an  individual  task  that  never  comes  to 
a  close ;  the  blessed  spirits,  angels  included,  have  not  only, 
like  earthly  men,  constantly  to  accomplish  morality,  but  so 
soon  as  we  leave  sin  out  of  view  as  an  abnormal  reality,  their 
moral  task  is  essentially  the  same  as  that  of  man ;  and  Schleier- 
macher  is  wrong  in  limiting  moral  acting,  and  hence  also 
ethics,  to  the,  as  yet,  militant  life,  and  in  excluding  them 
from  the  perfected  life  of  the  blessed  (Syst.,  p.  51,  61).  Un 
less  we  are  to  conceive  the  blessed  as  spiritually  dead,  then 
they  must  have  a  life-activity  answering  to  the  divine  will, — 
that  is,  a  moral  one.  Were  this  not  the  case,  then  Christ's 


36  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  59. 

holy  life  would  be  moral  only  so  long  as  he  had  to  do  with 
an  opposing  world  ;  and  only  the  earthly,  but  not  the  glorifled, 
Christ,  as  also  not  the  saints  in  heaven,  could  be  looked  upon 
as  moral  examples  for  us.  It  is  true,  the  manifestation-form 
of  the  morality  of  a  blessed  spirit  will  be  different  from  that 
of  the  yet  militant;  nevertheless  the  essence  remains  the 
same. 

The  distinguishing  of  the  moral  collective  subject  from  the 
individual  subject  is  a  point  of  essential  importance ;  for,  the 
moral  activity  of  the  two  is  by  no  means  the  same.  For  the 
member  of  a  moral  community,  there  arise  special  moral  duties 
that  fall  to  him,  not  as  a  moral  individual  but  as  an  organic 
member  of  a  whole,  and  which  he  is  to  fulfill  not  in  his  own 
name  but  in  that  of  the  totality.  The  action  of  the  individual 
is,  of  course,  the  first,  the  presupposition  of  the  other;  the 
moral  community  is  always  the  fruit  of  a  precedent  moral 
activity  of  the  individuals, — is  itself  a  realized-good,  which, 
however,  at  once  becomes  in  turn  itself  a  morally-active  sub 
ject,  unless  indeed  it  is  to  cease  to  be. 


I.  THE  INDIVIDUAL  MORAL  SUBJECT,  MAN. 

SECTION  LIX. 

Man  as  created  after  God's  image  is,  as  spiritual 
ized  nature,  both  spirit  and  nature,  and  also  the  real 
unity  of  the  two. 

A.  As  a  spirit  he  is  a  rationally-free,  self-determin 
ing  being,  attaining  to  his  fall,  peculiar  reality 
through  free  activity.  The  basis  and  essence  of  this 
spirituality  is  personal  self -consciousness.  Only  in 
so  far  as  man  is  self-conscious  can  he  be  moral,  and 
by  virtue  of  this  self-consciousr,ess  he  is  answerable 
for  his  life, — his  life  becomes  to  him  a  moral  one, 
and  is  counted  to  him.  But  he  is  conscious  of  him 
self  as  &  personal  individual,  that  is,  he  distinguishes 
himself  from  others  not  merely  by  his  being,  but  by 


§59.]  PURE   ETHICS.  37 

a  to  him  exclusively-peculiar,  determined  being, — by 
his  peculiar  personality,  which  in  this  peculiarity 
does  not  belong  to  him  directly  from  nature,  but  is 
acquired  only  by  personal,  moral  activity,  and  hence 
constitutes  character  -  peculiarity.  The  individual 
being  of  man  is  distinguished  from  that  of  nature- 
objects  by  the  fact  that  it  has  inherent  in  itself,  as 
an  inner  rational  power,  the  destination  not  to  re 
main  a  mere  individual  unit,  but  to  become  a  per 
sonality, — in  a  word,  man  is  from  the  very  beginning 
not  a  mere  specimen  of  his  species,  but  is  called  to 
become  a  peculiarly-determined  being. 

The  Christian  idea  of  man  is  summed  up  in  the  thought  of 
the  image  of  God,  and  hence  presupposes  dogmatically  the 
development  of  the  idea  of  God.  The  great  emphasis  which 
is  laid  in  Scripture  on  this  idea  of  God-likeness  [Gen.  i,  26,  27 ; 
ix,  6 ;  1  Cor.  xi,  7 ;  James  iii,  9 ;  Col.  iii,  10 ;  Acts  xvii,  28,  29] 
shows  of  itself  that  we  have  not  to  do  here  with  a  mere  poetic 
figure.  All  that  is  created  is  good, — is  an  expression  of  the 
divine  will,  and  hence  is  an  image  of  the  divine  thought ;  but 
the  rational  creature,  as  the  crown  of  creation,  is  the  most 
complete  expression  of  this  goodness, — is  the  image  of  God, 
bears  upon  itself  the  most  perfect  impress  of  the  Creator. 
Now  as  God  is  essentially  a  spirit,  hence,  man  is  God's  image 
more  immediately  only  as  a  rational  spirit,  whereas  the  body 
merely  bears  on  itself,  like  other  nature-objects,  the  trace  of 
the  Creator,  but  not  his  perfect  impress,  and  it  becomes  an 
image  of  God  only,  mediately, — namely,  in  so  far  as  it  is  pro 
gressively  transfigured  by  the  spirit  into  its  own  perfect  ex 
pression.  In  the  Scriptures  Christ  is  called  by  pre-eminence, 
the  true  image  of  God ;  but  man  is  called  to  become  like  this 
image  [Rom.  viii,  29].  Christ  is  this  image  not  merely  as  the 
eternal  Son  of  God,  but  also  and  especially  as  the  true  Son  of 
Man,  who  historically  and  visibly  reveals  the  divine  [Col. 
i,  15] ;  and  as  such  he  is  the  "first-born  among  many  brethren." 

The  rational  spirit  stands  in  contrast  to  mere  nature-exist 
ence.  A  nature-entity  determines  not  itself,  but  is  determined 


38  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  59. 

by  a  nature-force  not  lying  within  its  own  consciousness, — 
is  even  in  its  activity  predominantly  unfree,  whereas  that 
which  constitutes  the  essence  of  spirit  is,  to  be  free,  to  deter 
mine  itself  in  its  peculiarity,  to  be  active  toward  conscious 
ends.  The  brute  has  not  purposes,  but  only  impulses.  There 
is  indeed  reason  in  the  brute ;  the  brute  does  not,  however, 
have  the  reason,  but  the  reason  has  the  brute.  The  reason 
that  is  in  nature  is  only  objective  rationality ;  whereas  spirit 
is  a  subject  possessing  reason  as  a  consciousness.  This  con 
sciousness  is  rational,  however,  only  as  self-consciousness, 
wherein  man  becomes  to  himself  a  real  object, — comes  into 
spiritual  self-possession,  and  in  this  self-possession  distin 
guishes  himself  from  all  other  objective  beings.  By  virtue  of 
self-consciousness  man  remains  ever  in  the  presence  of  Mmself, 
and  at  one  with  himself ;  and  only  in  virtue  of  this  continuous 
sameness  of  the  personal  spirit,  is  it  morally  responsible. 

But  a  spirit  is  more  than  a  mere  numerical  individual ; 
nature-creatures  differ  from  others  of  their  species,  not  by 
essential  peculiarities  but  by  their  mere  separate  being  and 
by  outward  fortuitous  determinations, — are  mere  esseutially- 
similar  specimens  of  the  same  kind,  mere  repetitions  of  the 
same  existence.  But  each  individual  personal  spirit  has,  as 
distinguished  from  other  personal  spirits,  a  determined  pecul 
iarity  of  its  own,  which  raises  it  from  a  mere  numerical  ex 
istence  into  a  determined  personality.  In  self-consciousness 
man  knows  himself  not  merely  as  a  man,  but  as  this  particu 
larly-determined  man.  He  bears,  therefore,  a  personal  name, 
the  significance  of  which  is,  that  it  is  his  destination  to  be 
something  different  from  others, — to  possess  in  his  being 
something  which  others  neither  have  nor  can  have  in  the 
same  manner.  The  name  is,  with  man  as  well  as  with  God, 
an  expression  of  personal  peculiarity — of  that  which  inwardly 
distinguishes  one  determined  personality  from  others  [Exod. 
xxxiii,  12,  17;  Isa.  xliii,  1;  xlv,  3,  4;  Ivi,  5;  John  x,  3;  Rev. 
iii,  5] ;  this  personal  peculiarity  the  spirit  docs  not  have  from 
nature,  nor  yet  is  it  generated  by  merely  natural  develop 
ment;  but  the  child  has  from  the  very  beginning  the  capacity 
for,  and  hence  the  destination  unto,  such  a  personality-con 
stituting  peculiarity;  nor  is  this  capacity  a  merely  conceived 
possibility,  on  the  contrary  it  is  a  real  germ ;  but  this  germ 


§  59.]  ,         PURE  ETHICS.  39 

can  come  to  development  only  by  moral  activity.  This  germ 
of  personality  which  lies  in  the  very  essence  of  the  rational 
spirit  does  not  contain  within  itself  the  determined  pecul 
iarity;  it  simply  requires  development,  but  as  to  how,  and 
unto  what  peculiarity  it  becomes  developed,  that  depends 
on  the  free  moral  activity  of  the  person  himself.  That  this 
personal  peculiarity  does  not  come  from  nature,  but  belongs 
to  the  life  of  the  free  spirit,  is  clearly  implied  in  the  custom, 
prevalent  among  almost  all  nations  and  tribes,  of  name-giving. 
Nature  gives  to  man  at  birth  his  individual  existence ;  the 
spiritually  and  historically  formed  society,  or  family,  gives 
to  him  his  personal  name, — designating  thereby  either  the 
goal  of  this  personality  or  its  already  acquired  peculiarity 
[Gen.  iii,  20;  iv,  25;  v,  29;  xxi,  3;  xli,  51,  52;  Matt,  i,  25; 
Luke  i,  60,  etc.]. 

This  thought  of  the  moral  quality  of  the  personality  is  not 
so  uncontested  as  might  be  supposed.  Schleiermacher,  in 
his  Philosophical  Ethics,*  holds  that  moral  individualities 
differ  primitively,  before  all  moral  activity,  and  hence  do  not 
merely  become  different.  While  preceding  moral  systems, 
and  especially  that  of  Kant,  either  overlooked  the  special 
peculiarity  of  the  person,  or  even  ignored  it  as  something  il 
legitimate,  Schleiermacher  emphasizes  justly  enough  the  moral 
significancy  of  this  peculiarity,  but  he  also  rushes  to  the 
opposite  one-sidedness,.  and  magnifies  the  difference  into  a 
primitive,  determined,  ante-moral  one, — a  sort  of  moral 
atomistics,  which,  in  order  to  escape  the  difficulty  of  the 
notion  of  free  self-determination,  assumes  a  much  greater  in 
comprehensibility.  In  a  system,  sprung  up  from  essentially 
Pantheistic  soil,  this  view  is  not  inconsequential,  inasmuch 
as  here  the  notion  of  a  really  free  self-determination  is  out  of 
the  question ;  but  at  the  same  time  also  the  notion  of  moral 
personality  is  precluded,  and  ethics  is  reduced  to  a  presenta 
tion,  not  of  how  man  as  a  free  individual  should  conform  him 
self  to  a  moral  idea,  but  of  how  he  must  develop  himself  in 
his  strictly  naturally-determined  idiosyncrasy.  But  a  spirit 
that  is  absolutely  determined  by  the  All  (conceived  here  as 

*  System,  p.  93  sqq.,  157, 172;  comp.  CJiristl.  Sitte,  p.  58  sqq.,  and 
Grundlin.  einer  Kritik,  etc.,  p.  79  tqg.  (2  ed.,  p.  57) ;  Monologen,  4  Ausg., 
p..  24  sqq. ;  Reden,  2.  ed.,  129. 


40  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  59. 

strictly  impersonal)  could  not  essentially  differ  from  a  mere 
nature-creature ;  even  brutes  have  unfree  spirituality.  We 
admit  that  men,  even  had  they  not  sinned,  would  not  have 
manifested  perfect  similarity,  but  would  have  been  in  some 
respects  differently  attuned  from  nature  itself, — as,  for  ex 
ample,  in  the  peculiarities  of  sex,  of  temperament  and  of  na 
tionality,  (see  §  67,)  but  these  natural  differences  affect  not 
the  personal  essence  itself, — do  not  make  of  the  individual  a 
being  strictly  personatty-diSerent  from  all  others,  but  are  only 
different  traits  of  entire  clans  or  groups, — are  not  so  much 
differences  of  individuals  as  of  races.  The  fact  that  in  ;he 
present  condition  of  mankind,  each  individual  has  inborn 
within  him  the  germ  of  determined  moral  peculiarities,  of 
particular  vices  and  the  like,  is  simply  a  result  of  his  illegiti 
mate  abnormal  state,  and  is  very  far  from  justifying  us  in 
merely  cultivating  and  developing  our  inborn  peculiarities. 
But  Schleiermacher  is  very  erroneous  when  he  regards  this 
original  difference,  even  in  spiritual  and  moral  respects,  as 
something  necessary  and  contributive  to  the  aesthetic  beauty 
of  the  All, — as,  for  example,  when  he  says:  "Some  [of  the 
phases  of  humanity]  are  the  most  sublime  and  striking  ex 
pression  of  the  beautiful  and  the  divine ;  others  are  grotesque 
products  of  the  most  original  and  fleeting  whim  of  a  master- 
hand  ;  .  .  .  why  should  we  despise  that  which  throws  into 
relief  the  chief  groups,  and  gives  life  and  fullness  to  the 
whole?  Is  it  not  befitting  that  the  single  heavenly  forms 
should  be  glorified  by  the  fact  that  thousands  of  others  bow 
themselves  before  them?  Undying  humanity  is  unweariedly 
busy  in  reproducing  itself  and  in  manifesting  itself  under  the 
greatest  variety  of  manner  in  the  transitory  phenomena  of 
finite  life.  Such  is  the  harmony  of  the  universe,  such  the 
great  and  wonderful  simplicity  in  its  eternal  art-work.  What 
indeed  were  the  monotonous  reiteration  of  a  lean  ideal  in 
which,  after  all,  the  individuals  would  be  (time  and  circum 
stances  substracted)  strictly  like  each  other — the  same  formula 
with  the  coefficients  varied? — what  were  such  a  monotony  in 
comparison  with  this  infinite  variety  of  human  peculiarities? 
.  .  .  This  individual  appears  as  the  rude  animal  part  of  hu 
manity,  affected  only  by  the  first  infantile  instincts  of  the 
race;  that  other  one,  as  the  finest  sublimated  spirit,  free 


§60.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  41 

from  all  that  is  common  and  unworthy,  and  with  light  wing 
rising  above  the  earth ; — but  all  are  there  in  order  to  show, 
by  their  existence,  how  the  various  forces  of  human  nature 
operate  separately  and  in  detail."  (Reden,  2ed.,p.  \3Qsqq.). 
Such  language  outdoes  even  the  Greek  distinction  of  man 
into  barbarous  and  free-men,  and  is,  as  a  consistent  expres 
sion  of  a  purely  naturalistic  view  of  the  world,  in  most  direct 
antagonism  to  the  Christian  thought  of  a  moral  world-order 
upheld  by  a  holy  God. — Rothe  (EtJtik  i,  §  120  sqq.~)  adopts 
the  view  of  Schleiermacher  in  a  somewhat  different,  though 
less  consistent  form. 

SECTION  LX. 

The  self-conscious  personality  unfolds  its  life  under 
a  variety  of  forms. — (1)  Man  is  a  knowing,  a  cog- 
noscitive,  spirit, — he  takes  objects  spiritually,  that  is, 
according  to  their  idea,  into  himself,  and  thus  makes 
them  his  enduring  possession.  The  object  of  knowl 
edge  is  truth,  and  the  knowing  spirit  is  capable  of 
attaining  thereto.  Knowledge  is  in  itself  true  and 
does  not  deceive,  for  God's  created  universe  is  good, 
and  hence  true  and  in  perfect  harmony  with  itself. 
As  a  rational  spirit,  man  knows  not  only  the  created 
world  but  also  its  divine  source, — in  fact  the  essence 
of  rationality  consists  in  the  knowledge  of  God  in  his 
existence,  his  nature,  his  government,  and  his  will. 
This  God-consciousness,  resting  upon  a  self-revelation 
of  God  to  man,  is  indeed,  as  finite  knowledge,  not 
capable  of  thoroughly  comprehending  the  infinite 
essence  of  God,  yet,  with  a  full  consciousness  of  its 
own  limits,  it  is  nevertheless  a  true,  real,  and  well- 
grounded  knowledge  of  the  divine,  and  as  such  it  is 
the  presupposition  of  moral ity. 

The  human  spirit  is  an  image  of  the  eternal  divine  life, 
though  in  the  form  of  a  temporal  life.  God,  in  his  eternal 
life,  is  eternally  self-begetting,  self-knowing,  and  self-loving, 


42  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  60. 

— absolutely  his  own  object ;  and  the  finite  spirit,  reflectively 
manifesting  the  life-development  of  God,  has  a  threefold  ob 
ject  upon  which  its  life-movement  is  directed,  namely,  itself, 
the  external  world  and  God.  Man  is  God's  image  in  this 
threefold  relation, — in  willing,  in  knowing,  and  in  feeling; 
but  as,  primarily,  his  reality  is  given  to  him,  as  already  ex 
isting  without  his  co-operation,  hence  these  three  activities 
appear  in  another  and  chronologically  different  order  of  suc 
cession,  as  knowing,  feeling,  and  willing.  Thus  the  finite 
spirit  knows  (takes  cognizance  of),  feels  (loves)  and  wills 
both  itself,  the  objective  world  and  God ;  and,  as  the  life  of 
a  created  being  is  a  progressive  development  whose  spiritual 
significance  lies  before  it  as  a  goal  or  purpose, — as  something 
not  as  yet  fully  real,  but  rather  as  to  be  won  by  effort,  —hence 
the  threefold  life  of  the  spirit  has  also  a  threefold  end, 
namely,  truth,  happiness,  and  the  good ;  and  it  is  only  in  the 
perfect  attaining  of  this  threefold  end  that  the  image  of  God 
in  man  perfects  itself, — that  the  highest  good  is  realized. 
But  as  the  perfection  of  created  things  consists-  in  the  fact 
that  they  perfectly  correspond  to  the  divine  creative  idea,  so 
the  perfection  of  knowledge,  feeling,  and  willing,  and  con 
sequently  of  truth,  of  happiness,  and  of  the  good,  consists  in 
their  so  relating  to  God  that  all  finite  objects  are  known, 
willed,  and  loved  only  in  God  and  as  relating  to  him.  God 
himself  is  the  truth,  the  good  and  love,  and  whatever  falls 
under  this  threefold  notion,  does  so  only  in  so  far  as  it  is 
rooted  in  and  in  harmony  with  God. 

Man,  as  created  good  by  God,  must  have  the  capacity  per 
fectly  to  attain  to  this  good  state  which  is  divinely  proposed 
to  him  as  his  life-goal.  Hence  his  knowledge  cannot  be  de 
ceptive,  but  must  have  the  truth  as  its  contents.  The  world 
would  not  be  good,  would  not  be  in  harmony,  if  the  intellect 
ual  images  of  objects  in  the  knowing  spirit  were  not  true  to 
the  originals, — if  the  thought  as  objectively  real  were  essen 
tially  other  than  the  subjective  one.  "What  Christ  promises 
to  his  followers:  "Ye  shall  know  the  truth"  [John  viii,  32], 
must  also  be  fully  applicable  to  man  per  se ;  redemption  is  in 
fact  essentially  a  restoration  of  the  lost  perfection;  God  wills 
that  all  men  should  "  come  unto  the  knowledge  of  the  truth  " 
1 1  Tim.  ii,  4J.  The  destination  of  man  to  know  the  truth  is 


§  60.]  PURE   ETHICS.  43 

expressed  in  Gen.  ii,  19,  20.  God  brought  the  beasts  to 
Adam  in  order  "to  see  what  he  would  call  them,"  that  is, 
how  he  would  distinguish  them  from  himself  and  from  other 
objects, — form  of  them  a  definite,  generically-characterizing 
notion ;  the  name  is  an  expression  of  the  obtained  notion ; — 
and  whatsoever  he  severally  called  them,  "that  was  the  name 
thereof; " — this  is  not  a  mere  experiment  on  the  part  of  God, 
but,  on  the  contrary,  a  divine  guaranty  for  the.  truthfulness 
of  human  knowledge,  and  at  the  same  time  for  the  freedom 
of  the  same.  God  himself  brings  before  man  the  outer 
world ;  thereby  he  guarantees  to  him  that  his  knowledge  is 
legitimate,  true,  and  reliable ;  and  it  is  not  God  who  gives 
names  to  the  objects;  man  himself  does  it,  and  freely;  the 
knowing  (taking  cognizance)  of  the  truth  is  a  free,  and  hence 
a  moral  activity ;  and  this  calling  by  name,  this  definite,  dis 
tinguishing  knowing,  is  sealed  by  God  as  truthful,  —  "that 
was  the  name  thereof ; "  man's  free  knowing  is  not  to  be 
mere  empty  play,  but  to  have  a  reality  as  its  contents ;  and 
the  spiritual  significance  of  things  is  to  find  its  goal  only  in 
its  being  spiritually  appropriated  by  man.  Our  knowledge 
of  the  objective  world  is  not  to  remain  a  mere  sensuous  be 
holding,  as  with  the  brute,  but  is  to  rise  beyond  that  stage 
into  the  sphere  of  ideas ;  this  is  for  us  a  moral  duty,  and  one 
which  has  a  divine  promise.  Thus  the  first  man  takes  cog 
nizance  of,  and  names,  also  the  woman,  his  created  helpmeet 
[Gen.  ii,  23] ;  and  Eve,  as  well  as  Adam,  recognizes  the  di 
vine  will  and  distinguishes  it  from  her  own  as  owing  obedi- " 
ence  to  the  former  [Gen.  iii,  2,  3] ;  in  the  one  case  as  well  as 
in  the  other,  there  is  manifested  at  the  same  time  a  definite 
self-consciousness  as  different  from  the  objective  conscious 
ness. 

The  relation  of  our  knowledge  to  God  is  of  course  quite 
different  from  its  relation  to  the  world.  While  all  worldly 
being  may,  as  created,  be  also  ultimately  fully  known  and 
comprehended  by  man,  on  the  contrary  the  infinite  and  eternal 
being  and  essence  of  God  is,  for  the  essentially  limited  human 
spirit,  a  thought  never  fully  to  be  grasped ;  and  the  incompre 
hensibility  of  God  [Psa.  cxlvii,  5;  Isa.  xl,  28;  Iv,  8,  9;  Job 
xi,  8;  Rom.  xi,  33]  is  a  Christian  doctrine  by  no  means  to  be 
rejected.  But  this  incomprehensibility  does  not  preclude  a 


4-4  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  60. 

very  essential  and  true  knowledge,  otherwise  were  all  God- 
likeness  in  man  a  mere  empty  rhetorical  phrase.  Even  as  the 
eye  is  unable  to  take  in  the  entire  ocean,  and  nevertheless 
has  a  very  definite  intuition  of  its  existence  and  peculiarities, 
so  likewise  is  the  finite  spirit  unable  to  take  in  the  infinite, 
to  fathom  it  in  it?  bottomless  depths,  and  yet  it  is  able  with 
constantly  increasing  clearness  to  attain  to  a  true  knowledge 
not  only  of  the  existence  but  also  of  the  nature  of  God, — not, 
however,  by  means  of  the  understanding,  which  relates  to  and 
is  exclusively  occupied  with  the  finite,  but  by  means  of  the 
reason,  which  relates  essentially  to  the  infinite.  As  all  created 
being  is  a  reflection  of  God,  and  as  man  is  his  image,  hence 
the  type  leads  directly  to  an  (imperfect  it  may  be,  but  yet) 
true  knowledge  of  the  prototype  [Rom.  i,  19,  20;  Col.  iii,  10]. 
The  assumption  that  man  can  know  of  God  only  that  he  is, 
and  what  he  is  not,  but  not  what  he  is,  is  self-contradictory 
and  unbiblical ;  a  merely  negative  knowledge  is  no  knowledge 
at  all,  and  of  that  of  whose-  nature  I  know  nothing  I  cannot 
affirm  even,  that  it  is.  The  Evangelical  Church  very  strongly 
emphasizes  primitive  man's  capability  of  attaining  to  a  knowl 
edge  of  the  truth,  even  in  relation  to  the  divine  nature ;  the 
Apologia  (i,  §  17,  18)  ascribes  to  him  sapientia  et  notitia  del 
certior,  "  a  correct  and  clear  knowledge  of  God."  Skepticism 
may  readily  find  excuse  for  itself  outside  of  Christianity,  but 
what  holds  good  of  man  as  estranged  from  God,  does  not 
hold  equally  of  him  who  is  in  communion  with  that  God  who 
is  himself  the  truth ;  and  hence  within  the  Christian  world, 
skepticism  has  no  longer  any  reason  of  existence.  Also  the 
assertion  of  Kant,  that  the  object  per  se  remains  hidden  from 
human  knowledge,  and  that  all  knowledge  of  reality  has,  in 
the  sphere  of  pure  reason,  only  a  formal  and  subjective  valid 
ity,  is  in  direct  contradiction  to  the  Christian  world-view, 
which  expresses  a  much  greater  confidence  in  the  harmony  of 
the  universe.  The  perfect  man  and  the  Christian  can  do  more 
than  "conjecture  and  presume;"  for,  "the  spirit  of  man  is 
the  candle  of  the  Lord"  [Prov.  xx,  27]. — That  man's  first 
God-consciousness  should  rest  on  an  objective  self-revelation 
of  God,  was  a  necessary  condition  to  his  spiritual  education 
toward  finding  the  truth  for  himself. 


§  61-1  PURE  ETHICS.  45 

SECTION  LXI. 

(2)  Man  is  a  ivilling,  a  volition ating,  spirit ;  the 
goal  of  his  life-movement  is  for  him  a  conscious  end. 
He  is  not  impelled  unconsciously  and  by  extraneous 
force  toward  that  to  which  he  is  to  attain,  but  he 
knows  the  end,  and  himself  directs  himself  toward 
it, — he  chooses  the  known  goal  by  virtue  of  a  personal 
will-determination, — that  is,  in  his  willing  he  is  free. 
The  end  of  rational  willing  is  the  good,  and,  in  so  far 
as  this  is  to  be  realized  by  freedom,  the  morally-good. 
That  which  in  nature-objects  takes  place  by  necessity, 
becomes,  in  the  sphere  of  the  moral  will,  a  "should  ;" 
that  which  in  the  former  case  is  natural  law,  becomes 
here  a  moral  precept;  that  which  is  there  natural  de 
velopment,  becomes  here  moral  life.  But  the  will 
of  the  created  spirit  differs  from  the  prototypal  will 
of  God  by  the  fact  that  its  development  in  time  is 
not  unconditioned,  but  is  always  conditioned  on  free 
self-determination,  so  that  consequently  there  exists 
the  possibility  of  another  self-determination  than  that 
toward  the  true  end, — that  is,  in  a  word,  by  the  fact 
that  man's  freedom  of  will,  as  distinguished  from  the 
divine  (which  is,  at  the  same  time,  eternal  necessity), 
is  freedom  of  choice — liberum  arbilrium.  The  finite 
spirit  can,  and  should,  attain  to  the  good  as  the  pur 
pose  of  its  life,  but  it  can  also — what  it  should  not 
do — turn  away  from  this  good ;  and  it  attains  to  the 
good  only  when  it  freely  wills  to  attain  to  it.  Man, 
as  created  good,  has  this  freedom  in  the  highest  de 
gree,  so  that  it  is  not  limited  or  trammeled  by  any 
tendency  to  evil  inherent  in  his  natural  non-perfec 
tion,  as,  for  example,  by  his  sensuousness.  It  is  in 
cumbent  upon  ethics  to  describe  and  explain  the 


46  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  61- 

development  of  the  natural  freedom  of  the,  as  yet, 
undetermined  will,  into  the  moral  freedom  of  the 
holy  will. 

The  moral  freedom  of  the  will  is  distinctly  presupposed  in 
the  Biblical  account  of  primitive  man.  "And  the  Lord  God 
commanded  the  man,  saying,  Of  every  tree  of  the  garden 
thou  mayest  freely  eat ;  but  of  the  tree  of  the  knowledge  of 
good  and  evil,  thou  slialt  not  eat  of  it "  [Gen.  ii,  16,  17].  God's 
injunction  addresses  itself  to  the  free  will  of  man,  and  requires 
of  him  moral  obedience.  When,  now,  man  nevertheless  actu 
ally  did  that  which  was  forbidden,  he  simply  did  the  opposite 
of  what  God's  holy  will  was ;  and  he  thereby  demonstrated  in 
fact,  though  to  his  ruin,  the  reality  of  human  freedom  of 
choice.  Scripture  knows  absolutely  nothing  of  any  other 
view  of  the  true  nature  of  man  than  that  he  was  capable 
of  freely  choosing  good  or  evil.  For  this  idea  of  freedom  of 
choice,  however,  Scripture  has  no  specific  expression;  for 
thevdepof,  i^Evdepla,  originally  used  in  a  legal  sense,  designate 
the  condition  of  man  as  emancipated  by  Christ ;  the  idea  of 
man's  freedom  of  choice  is  expressed  rather  as  a  "  choosing 
between  good  and  evil;"  for  example,  in  Isa.  vii,  15,  16, 
where  the  time  of  the  spiritual  maturity  of  a  man  is  called 
the,  time  when  he  "  shall  know  to  refuse  the  evil  and  choose 
the  good"  [comp.  Dent,  xi,  26  sqq.],  or  when  he  can  do  "  ac 
cording  to  his  pleasure"  [Esth.  i,  8],  or  that  which  is  "good 
in  his  own  eyes"  [Gen.  xvi,  6;  xix,  8].  The  view  of  freedom 
of  choice  as  presented  in  the  book  of  Sirach  xv,  14,  holds 
good  in  its  full  sense  evidently  only  of  man  as  free  from 
the  bondage  of  sin.  In  the  New  Testament,  man's  freedom  of 
choice  is  implied  by  Oefotv  (for  example,  in  Matt,  xxiii,  37 ; 
whereas  the  "power  over  one's  own  will "  mentioned  in  1  Cor. 
vii,  37  refers  more  to  our  moral  discretion). 

In  the  Christian  church  the  full  moral  freedom  of  choice  of 
man  before  the  fall,  has  been  uniformly  admitted ;  and  the 
notion  that  human  actions  are  necessarily  determined,  just  as 
uniformly  rejected  [comp.  Apol.  i,  p.  52,  53 ;  Form.  Cone,  ii, 
p.  580,  677].  The  "  supralapsarian "  predestinarianism  of 
Calvin  has  never  been  ecclesiastically  sanctioned,  nor  in  fact 
does  even  it  deny  freedom  of  choice  as  a  principle,  and  ex- 


§  61.]  PURE   ETHICS.  47 

pressly,  but  only  actually.  Entirely  different  from  this  teach 
ing  of  Calvin  is  the  fundamental  denial  of  freedom  of  will  in 
all  Pantheistic  systems  since  Spinoza.  In  Pantheism  there  is 
no  place  for  freedom,  and  what  appears  there  under  this 
name  is  something  entirely  different  from  that  which  the 
consciousness  of  all  nations  understands  thereby.  'Where 
conscious  spirit  is  not  the  ground,  but  simply  a  product  of 
the  collective  development  of  the  All,  there  the  individual 
spirit  is  in  its  entire  existence,  essence,  and  life,  absolutely 
determined ;  and  its  single  life-manifestations  are  quite  as 
absolutely  determined  as  is  its  being  itself ; — in  which  case 
the  rational  spirit  can  never  have  a  consciousness  of  freedom, 
but  only  a  "sense  of  absolute  dependence,"  and  hence  there 
can  be  no  room  for  any  moral  responsibility.  The  seemingly 
moral  life  is  as  immediate  and  necessary  a  manifestation  of 
the  "all-life"  as  is  the  growth  of  plants,  and  it  differs  from 
the  nature-life  only  in  the  fact,  that  man  has  a  consciousness 
of  that  which  he  does  necessarily,  in  fact,  but  which  he 
fancies  he  does  freely.  The  will  differs  from  unconscious 
nature-impulse  only  by  the  consciousness  which  attends  it, 
but  it  is,- in  fact,  quite  as  absolutely  determined  and  unfree 
as  is  the  latter.  This  view  is  expressed  most  clearly,  simply, 
and  consequentially,  by  Spinoza  ;  and  it  is  neither  in  the  in 
terest  of  clearness  nor  of  scientific  honesty,  when  more^  re 
cent  systems,  based  on  him,  make  free  use  of  fair-sounding 
words  about  human  'freedom.  In  essential  agreement  with 
Spinoza,  Schleiermacher,  in  his  "Discourses  on  Religion," 
rejects  the  freedom  of  the  will.  The  essence  of  religion  is  a 
sense  of  the  absolute  unity  of  the  universe  and  the  individual 
existence, — a  consciousness  that  our  whole  being  and  activity 
are  the  being  and  activity  of  the  universe  itself,  and  are  de 
termined  thereby. — Schelling,  who  subsequently  attributed 
to  the  idea  of  the  personal  will  a  very  high  significancy,  held 
as  yet  in  his  "Lectures  on  Academic  Study"  (1803)  to  the 
unconditional  necessity  of  all  apparently  free  phenomena. 
History  is  quite  as  fully  an  immediate  and  necessary  mani 
festation  of  the  absolute,  as  is  nature ;  men  are  but  instru 
ments  for  carrying  out  that  which  is  per  se  necessary,  and 
they  are,  in  their  reality  and  peculiarities,  quite  as  fatally- 
determined  as  the  actions  themselves.  Actions  appear  as  free 


48  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  61. 

or  arbitrary  only  in  so  far  as  man  makes  a  necessarily-deter 
mined  action  specifically  his  own,  but  this  action  itself,  as 
well  as  its  result  in  good  or  evil,  and  hence  also  man  in  all 
his  life-manifestations,  is  but  the  passive  instrument  of  abso 
lute  necessity ;  all  that  which  is  apparently  free  is  but  a 
neceseary  expression  of  the  eternal  order  of  things.  Subse 
quently  (1809),  Schelling  sought  to  rise  above  Pantheism, 
and,  in  some  manner,  to  comprehend  the  freedom  of  the  will, 
but  he  did  not  rise  beyond  wide-reaching  contradictions. 
The  assumption  of  an  ante-mundane  fall  into  sin  was  in 
tended  to  reconcile  freedom  with  necessity  (Phil.  Schr.,  1809, 
i,  438  sqq.,  463  sqq.).  On  this  we  remark  here  simply,  that 
from  an  ethical  stand-point  it  makes  no  moral  difference 
whether  free  self-determination  is  precluded,  for  our  whole 
mundane  life,  by  an  absolute  natural  necessity,  or  by  a  pre 
tended  ante-mundane  free  determination  of  man  himself,  but 
of  which  he  has  not  the  least  consciousness.  Where  there  is 
no  continuity  of  the  consciousness,  there  there  is  also  no  unity 
of  the  person ;  and  a  pretended  free  act  which  /  am  supposed 
to  have  done,  but  of  which  /know  absolutely  nothing,  is  not 
my  act  but  is  absolutely  foreign  to  me ;  and  a  fettering  of  my 
freedom  by  a,  to  me  entirely  unknown,  timeless  act  cannot 
be  regarded  from  a  moral  point  of  view  as  other  than  a  sim 
ple  being-determined  by  unconditional  necessity. — Hegel  has 
left  the  idea  of  freedom,  in  many  respects,  in  great  uncer 
tainty  ;  he  is  very  fond  of  talking  of  freedom ;  but  his  system 
itself  is  compatible  only  with  a  universal  all-determining 
necessity ;  freedom  is  nothing  more  than  "  the  not  being  de 
pendent  on  another,  the  sustaining  relations  to  one's  self ; " 
in  its  full  sense,  however,  this  is  true  only  of  the  spirit  as 
absolute ;  individual  spirits  are  only  transient  manifestations 
of  the  collective-  life,  and  are  determined  by  the  same. — 
More  recent  philosophy,  wherever  it  deviates  from  strict 
Pantheism,  uniformly  attempts  to  bring  personal  freedom  of 
will  more  clearly  before  the  consciousness.  There  is  here  no 
possibility  of  a  middle-ground,  and  ambiguous  rhetoric  can 
no  longer  deceive.  Where  God  is  not  the  infinite  eternal 
Spirit,  but  comes  to  self-consciousness  only  in  man,  there  the 
thought  of  a  real  freedom  of  will  is  impossible.  The  infinite 
domination  of  the  All  leaves  no  place  for  the  free  movement 


§  62.]  PURE   ETHICS.  49 

of  the  individual  spirit;  the  misused  freedom  of  a  single 
creature  would  throw  the  collective  universe  into  disorder, 
for  the  unfree  All  affords  no  possibility  of  preserving  moral 
order  as  against  the  free  actions  of  individuals.  On  this 
ground  there  remains  a  freedom  only  for  thoughtless  con 
templation  ;  and  this  would  then,  of  necessity,  lead  to  the 
ethics  of  an  unlimited  self-love  which  can  seek  and  find  in 
the  bedlam  of  individual  wills  nothing  higher  than  itself. 
Freedom  is  possible  only  where  a  free  Spirit  rules  in  and 
over  the  All.  The  personal  God  is  able,  in  almighty  love,  to 
create  free  spirits,  and  to  guarantee  them  in  their  freedom, 
namely,  in  that  he  lovingly  withdraws  his  direct  activity 
from  the  sphere  of  will-freedom,  and  thus  preserves  the 
created  spirit  in  its  spiritual  essence  which  is  freedom  itself ; 
and  such  a  God  is  able  in  the  midst  of  the  diversity  and  mul 
tiplicity  of  free  actions,  and  even  of  ungodly  ones,  to  preserve 
the  moral  order  of  the  universe. 

(The  question  of  freedom  of  will  has  of  late  been  much 
discussed,  mostly  from  the  stand-point  of  recent  philosophy 
and  in  relation  thereto.  Daub:  Statement  and  Criticism  of 
Hypotheses  Relating  to  Free  -  Will,  1834 ;  Romang :  On  Free  -  Will 
and  Determinism,  1835  [starting  out  from  Schleiermacher's 
stand-point,  he  attains  only  to  a  semblance  of  freedom] ; 
Matthias:  The  Idea  of  Freedom,  1834;  [since  Hegel]  Herbart: 
On  the  Doctrine  of  the  Freedom  of  the  Human  Will,  1836  [critic 
al,  rather  than  furnishing  new  matter] ;  Vatke ;  Passavant : 
On  the  Freedom  of  the  Will,  1835;  K.  Ph.  Fischer,  in  Fichte's 
Zeitschrift,  iii,  101;  ix,  79;  Zeller,  in  the  Theologische  Jahr- 
lucher,  1846  ;  and  others). 

SECTION  LXII. 

(3)  Man  is  a  feeling,  a  sensitive,  spirit, — becomes 
conscious  of  himself  as  standing;  in  harmony  with,  or 
in  antagonism  to,  other  being;  and,  inasmuch  as  in 
the  primitive  unperverted  creation,  goodness,  and 
hence  harmony,  is  an  essential  quality,  and  a  real 
disharmony  therein  inconceivable,  hence  while  man 
— as  self-developing,  that  is,  as  seeking  after  an,  as 

VOL.  II-5 


50  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  f§  62- 

yet,  unrealized  goal — has  a  consciousness  of  some 
thing  yet  lacking  to  his  ultimate  perfection,  still  he 
knows  nothing  of  any  real  antagonism  of  existence, 
and  hence  he  has  no  feeling  of  pain,  but  only  of  joy 
in  existence,  arising  from  his  consciousness  of  an  un 
disturbed  harmony  of  universal  existence  with  his 
own  personality, — that  is,  in  a  word,  the  feeling  of 
happiness.  In  so  far  as  this  feeling  expresses  at  the 
same  time  the  recognition  of  this  existence  in  its 
peculiar  reality,  it  is  love.  Bliss  and  love  to  God  and 
to  his  works  are  not  two  different  things,  but  only 
two  different  phases  of  the  same  spiritual  life-mani 
festation, — the  former  being  rather  the  subjective, 
the  latter  the  objective  phase, — inasmuch  as  in  bliss 
and  love  man  is,  in  fact,  perfectly  at  one  with  the 
objective  universe. 

Feeling  is  not  peculiar  to  the  rational  spirit ;  it  becomes 
rational  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  an  expression  of  self-conscious 
ness;  and  as  self-consciousness  is  rational  only  in  being  a  con 
sciousness  not  of  mere  individual  being  but  also  of  a  God- 
likeness  in  the  peculiarity  of  the  person,  so  also  is  rational 
feeling  not  of  a  merely  individual  nature,  but  it  is  excited  by 
the  traces  of  God  which  shine  forth  from  all  created  exist 
ence,  and  hence  it  is,  at  bottom,  always  a  love  of  God.  The 
goodness  of  created  existence  is  embraced  by  rational  feeling 
not  as  being  good  merely  for  the  feeling  individual,  but  as  a 
being-good  perse;  the  rational  spirit  feels  not  merely  that 
this  or  that  entity  stands  in  harmony  with  itself,  but  it  feels 
itself  as  standing  in  harmony  with  the  totality  of  existence, — 
feels  the  harmony  of  God's  world  as  such.  In  the  same  de 
gree  that  spirituality  rises,  rises  also  the  vividness  and  com 
pass  of  feeling.  The  unconscious  nature-object  is  affected 
only  by  the  very  few  things  that  come  into  immediate  contact 
with  it ;  the  brute  shows  so  much  the  more  extended  and 
more  lively  a  sympathy  with  external  existence  the  higher 
and  nobler  its  rank.  Emotionlessness,  blunt  indifference  to- 


§  63.]  PURE   ETHICS.  51 

ward  external  objects,  is  always,  save  where  it  is  artificially 
superinduced  by  false  teachings,  a  sign  of  deep  moral  degra 
dation.  The  Biblical  account  of  the  primitive  condition  of 
man  uniformly  represents  the  destination  of  nature  to  be,  to 
procure  to  the  rational  spirit  the  feeling  of  joy,  of  happiness. 
Man  is  placed  in  the  garden  of  Eden,  and  thereby  brought 
into  the  immediate  presence  of  the  full  harmony  of  the  created 
world ;  in  it  God  causes  to  grow  "every  tree  that  is  pleasant 
to  the  sight  and  good  for  food ; "  and  the  full  feeling  of  hap 
piness,  as  springing  from  his  love  to  that  which  harmonizes 
with  him,  is  procured  to  man  (to  whom  it  is  not  "  good  "  to 
be  alone)  by  the  creation  of  woman, — in  whom  he  at  once 
recognizes  that  she  is  bone  of  his  bone  and  flesh  of  his  flesh, 
— a  being  other  than,  and  yet  of,  himself. 

Feeling  is  the  presupposition  of  all  activity,  and  hence  also 
of  the  moral ;  and  the  most  real  feeling  of  all — that  which 
relates  to  the  moral — is  not  an  un-pleasure  feeling,  as  is  often 
assumed  in  antagonism  to  the  Biblical  world-view,  but  in  fact 
a  happiness-feeling.  It  would  not  imply  a  "good "  creation, 
nor  indeed  any  God-likeness  in  man,  were  it  a  fact  that  man 
were  incited  to  activity  only  by  un-pleasure,  that  is,  by  pain, 
while  yet  happiness  were  the  end  of  the  active  life.  Even 
as  God  is  not  prompted  to  activity  by  any  feeling  of  want, 
but  rather  in  virtue  of  his  eternal  and  absolutely  perfect  bliss, 
so  also  can  the  true  moral  feeling  of  man,  who  is  God's  image, 
be  no  other  than  the  feeling  of  happiness  and  love ;  but  the 
consciousness  of  a  yet  to  be  won  good  is  per  se  by  no  means 
a  feeling  of  unhappiness,  on  the  contrary  it  in  fact  awakens 
a  direct  pleasure  in  seeking. 

SECTION  LXIII. 

(4)  Man,  as  a  rationally  self-conscious  spirit,  is 
personally  immortal;  only  as  such  is  he  a  truly 
moral  being, — has  a  moral  life-task  transcending  his 
own  immediate  individuality.  Faith  in  immortality 
is  the  presupposition  of  true  morality ;  for  the  moral 
life-task  is  one  that  is  incessantly  progressive,  ever 
self-renewing,  and  at  no  moment  perfectly  brought 


52  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§63. 

to  a  close;  and,  as  the  perfect  realization  of  God- 
likeness,  it  can  only  be  accomplished  through  an 
uninterruptedly-continuing  personal  life. 

We  have  to  do  here,  not  with  the  scientific  demonstration 
of  the  doctrine  of  personal  immortality,  but  only  with  its 
moral  significance.  In  recent  times,  especially  since  Kant, 
the  notion  has  frequently  been  maintained,  that  morality  is 
entirely  independent  of  a  belief  in  immortality,  nay,  that  it 
evinces  its  purity  and  genuineness  by  the  very  fact  of  entirely 
leaving  out  of  view  this  belief,  and  that  a  man  is  not  truly 
moral  so  long  as  he  allows  himself  to  be  determined  in  his 
moral  activity  by  this  belief.  It  is  true,  Kant  deduces  from 
the  idea  of  the  moral,  the  idea  of  personal  immortality  as  a 
rational  postulate ;  the  moral  idea  itself,  however,  is  with 
him  independent  of  this  postulate, — calls  for  its  fulfillment 
absolutely  and  unconditionally.  There  is  in  this  some  de 
gree  of  self-contradiction ;  if  the  "categorical  imperative  "  de 
mands  morality  unconditionally,  and  utterly  irrespectively  of 
immortality,  then  this  immortality  cannot  be  embraced  in  it 
as  a  postulate,  but  must  be  merely  associated  thereto  from 
without.  In  the  endlessness  of  the  life-task,  however,  as  it 
is  presented  by  Kant,  there  actually  lies,  in  fact,  the  thought 
of  immortality  as  included  in  the  moral  idea  itself, — so  that 
his  express  dissociating  of  the  two  ideas  is  illegitimate  and 
unnatural.  Schleiermacher  goes  further;  and,  even  in  his 
Dogmatics,  he  is  unable  entirely  to  rise  above  his  previous 
express  denial  of  immortality.  In  his  Discourses  on  Re 
ligion  he  places  the  religiously-moral  life-task  proper  in  an 
actual  disregarding  of  the  idea  of  this  immortality.  "  Strive 
even  in  this  life  to  annihilate  your  personality,  and  to  live  in 
the  One  and  All;  strive  to  be  more  than  yourselves,  in  order 
that  you  may  lose  but  little  when  you  lose  yourselves;"  the 
immortality  to  be  aimed  at  is  not  that  of  the  personality,  not 
above  and  beyond  the  earthly  existence,  but  it  is  an  ideal  im 
mortality  in  each  and  every  moment;  men  should  not  desire 
to  hold  fast  t'  their  personality,  rather  "  should  they  embrace 
the  single  opportunity  presented  to  them  by  death  for  escaping 
beyond  it."*  Even  in  his  Dogmatics  Sehleiermacher  holds, 
*  Reden  ub  die  Itel.,  p.  174  sjj.,  2  Auj, 


§  63.]  PURE  ETHICS.  53 

that  the  purest  morality  perfectly  consists  with  a  "renuncia 
tion  of  the  perpetuity  of  the  personality, — that,  in  fact,  an 
interestedness  in  a  recompense  is  impious.  In  the  Hegelian 
philosophy  morality  is  absolutely  independent  of  immortality ; 
this  idea  in  fact  can  nowhere  find  footing  in  the  system ;  the 
religion  of  the  ' '  this-side  "  which  sprang  from  this  philoso 
phy,  affects  to  give  point  to  its  rhetorical  flourishes  on  mo 
rality  by  its  seemingly  magnanimous  renunciation  of  all 
expectation  of  eternal  life. 

The  pretended  disinterestedness  of  moral  actions  performed 
without  reference  to  immortality,  is  mere  appearance.  All 
moral  activity  looks  to  an  end,  and  this  end  is  a  good ;  and 
personal  perfection  is  for  each  individual  an  essential  part  of 
the  highest  good,  or,  in  fact,  this  good  itself;  hence  not  to 
wish  to  obtain  any  thing  for  one's  self  by  one's  moral  activity 
is  simply  absurd ;  the  first  and  most  necessary  of  all  goods, 
and  the  one  which  is  the  presupposition  of  all  morality,  is  in 
fact  existence ;  to  desire  to  renounce  personal  existence,  or  to 
regard  it  as  indifferent,  is  equivalent  to  renouncing  moral 
life,  and  is  consequently  not  unselfish,  but  it  is  immoral.  It 
is  true  we  cannot  claim  for  the  so-called  ideological  proof  of 
the  immortality  of  the  soul,  full  demonstrative  power;  this 
much,  however,  it  does  prove,  namely,  that  the  highest  moral 
perfection  would  be  impossible  without  immortality ;  for,  as 
man  can  never  arrive  at  such,  a  perfection  of  the  moral  life  as 
that  he  can  advance  no  further,  so  that  consequently  his 
farther  existence  would  be  purposeless,  but  in  fact,  on  the 
contrary,  every  fulfillment  of  one  moral  duty  gives  in  turn 
birth  to  new  ones,  and  there  is  absolutely  no  point  to  be 
found  where  the  moral  spirit  might  say,  "  thus  far  and  no 
farther,  there  remains  nothing  more  for  me  to  do," — hence 
also  moral  perfection  cannot  be  realized  save  in  an  unbroken 
perpetuity  of  personal  life.  To  say  now,  that  the  moral  life- 
task  does  not  consist  in  obtaining  entire  moral  perfection,  but 
only  a  limited  degree  thereof,  would  be  per  se  immoral.  And 
in  fact  should  we  for  a  moment  concede  some  such  limited 
degree  of  the  moral,  then  there  would  be  no  conceivable  rule 
for  fixing  this  degree,  and  each  would  be  at  liberty  to  narrow 
the  limits  of  his  morality  at  pleasure,  without  that  any  one 
would  be  justified  in  blaming,  or  less  esteeming  him  therefor. 


54  CHRISTIAN"   ETHICS.  [§  63. 

In  all  moral  systems,  even  those  of  heathen  nations,  mo 
rality  is  more  precious  than  temporal  life,  and  that  person  is 
regarded  as  ignoble  and  contemptible,  even  by  pagans,  who 
clings  to  his  life  at  any  price,  for  example,  at  that  of  failing 
in  his  duty  to  his  country,  to  his  family,  or  to  his  own  honor. 
This  moral  sentiment  of  honor  we  have  no  wish  to  weaken. 
It  is  conceivable,  on  the  assumption  of  the  prevalence  of  sin, 
that  one's  moral  duty,  as,  for  example,  that  of  speaking  or 
confessing  the  truth,  or  of  fidelity  in  love  or  obedience,  can 
not  in  some  conjunctures  be  fulfilled  save  at  the  sacrifice  of 
temporal  life.  Now,  to  one's  existence  in  general  one  has  an 
unlimited  right ;  it  is  his  first  and  most  natural  right.  In 
the  atj&ence  of  immortality,  however,  the  sacrifice  of  one's  life 
for  a  moral  duty  would  not  only  not  be  a  moral  requirement, 
but  it  would  be  downright  folly  and  sin ;  for  morality  can  never 
require  the  giving  up  of  the  first  condition  of  all  moral  activity, 
namely,  personal  existence.  The  first,  the  most  immediate 
and  absolutely  unconditional  duty,  is  self-preservation,  and 
other  duties  are  binding  only  in  so  far  as  they  do  not  radically 
interfere  with  this  one.  As  it  would  not  be  a  moral  action, 
but  on  the  contrary  a  proof  of  insanity  if  one  man  should  really 
choose*  eternal  damnation  for  the  sake  of  another,  just  as 
little  is  any  being  whatever  at  liberty  to  purchase  for  others 
any  temporal  good,  however  great,  at  the  cost  of  personal 
existence ;  and  in  the  absence  of  immortality  there  can  be 
none  other  than  temporal  goods.  Man  may  sacrifice  any  one 
good  only  for  the  sake  of  a  higher  good  ;  but  in  renouncing 
existence  he  obtains  no  good  whatever.  The  sound  and  un 
sophisticated  judgment  will  find,  on  the  denial  of  immor 
tality,  no  other  rule  of  life-wisdom  than  simply  to  take  ad 
vantage  of  the  short  span  of  life  here  allotted  to  us  for 
enjoying  the  greatest  possible  happiness.  Happiness  is  in 
fact  an  absolutely  necessary  phase  of  human  perfection,  and 
an  essential  expression  of  the  highest  good :  to  strive  after  it 
is  not  only  not  selfishness,  on  the  contrary,  it  is  a  require 
ment  of  reason  and  of  moral  duty;  and  it  is  not  possible  that 
in  a  world  of  rational  order  morality  should  work  any  thing 
else  than  happiness.  Were  it  otherwise  it  would  be  a  plain 

*  It  is  only  seemingly  so  that  Paul  expresses  such  a  willingness  in 
Bom.  ix,  3. 


§  63.]  PURE   ETHICS.  55 

proof  of  the  non-existence  of  a  rational,  moral  world-order, 
and  in  that  case  it  would  be  totally  absurd  to  speak  further 
of  moral  duty  at  all,  for  duty  is  itself  a  part  of  a  moral  world- 
order.  If  there  is,  now,  no  eternal  blessedness  as  a  highest 
good,  then  it  can  be  only  after  temporal,  earthly  happiness, 
that  man  has  to  seek,  and  by  which  consequently  he  is  to 
measure  the  morality  of  his  acts.  If  it  is  true  that  all  mo 
rality  necessarily  renders  happy,  then  on  the  above  hypoth 
esis  only  that  can  be  moral  which  procures  for  us  earthly 
comfort,  temporal  enjoyment ;  the  teachings  of  the  Epicureans 
would  then  be  the  only  rational  theory,  and  no  valid  objec 
tion  could  be  made  to  the  moral  rule :  ' l  Let  us  eat  and  drink, 
for  to-morrow  we  die  "  [1  Cor.  xv,  32].  Foolish  then  would 
he  be  who  did  not  recklessly  seek  as  much  enjoyment  in  his 
earthly  life  as  in  any  way  he  possibly  could.  It  is,  of  course, 
not  necessary  that  this  system  should  lead  simply  to  groveling 
sensual  enjoyment ;  the  ancient  Epicureans  knew  well  enough 
that  riotous  intemperate  indulgence  works  much  suffering, 
and  the  modern  ones  also  know  equally  well,  that  by  unre 
strained  wantonness  they  bring  themselves  into  shame  and 
contempt  in  the  eyes  of  the  morally-taught  masses;  this, 
however,  does  not  in  any  degree  ameliorate  the  essence  of 
this  morality  of  the  "this  side."  The  outwardly-respectable 
life  of  many  a  denier  of  immortality  rests  in  reality  on  the 
power  of  public  opinion,  and  on  custom  as  grown  up  from 
Christian  ground.  But  the  case  is  quite  otherwise  where  un 
belief  becomes  fashionable  in  wider  circles  of  society.  Let 
vouch  for  this,  the  utter  immorality  and  depravity  that  pre 
vailed  in  the  circles  of  the  French  and  of  the  Gallicized 
German  free-thinkers  of  the  last  century.  In  the  lower  walks 
of  society  where  a  simpler  logic  prevails,  and  where  respect 
for  position  and  for  public  opinion  has  a  less  controlling 
power,  the  practical  inferences  from  a  naturalistic  philosophy 
are  more  speedily  and  consistently  drawn;  and  the  ring 
leaders  in  depravity  among  the  lower  classes  of  the  present 
day  are,  for  the  most  part,  deeply  imbued  with  the  con 
quests  of  ''free  thought,"  and  are  able  thereby  admirably  to 
justify  their  wantonness;  and  there  is  scarcely  conceivable 
a  more  absurd  role  than  that  assumed  by  the  "respectable" 
among  the  free-thinkers,  who  presume  to  preach  morality 


56  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  63. 

to  their  more- free-thinking  and  more  logically  reasoning 
brethren. 

He  who  is  without  belief  in  immortality  cannot  act  from 
an  unconditional  moral  idea,  but  only  from  empirical  external 
fitness,  from  circumstantial  need ;  he  cannot  make  moral  duty 
his  life-task,  and  his  moral  life  sinks  to  a  merely  higher- 
cultured  animal  life.  The  question  as  to  whether  Christian 
morality  is  possible  without  a  belief  in  immortality  would 
have  to  be  rejected  as  trivial, — seeing  that  a  belief  in  Christ's 
and  God's  express  word  is  certainly  included  in  Christian 
morality, — had  it  not  been  expressly  affirmed  by  some.  The 
word  of  Christ,  however,  is  a  sufficient  answer.  "He  that 
loseth  his  life  for  my  sake  shall  find  it,"  and  "He  that  loveth 
his  life  shall  lose  it,  and  he  that  hateth  his  life  in  this  world 
shall  keep  it  unto  life  eternal "  [Matt,  x,  39 ;  Luke  ix,  24 ; 
xvii,  33;  John  xii,  25;  x,  17;  comp.  1  Cor.  ix,  25;  Phil,  i,  81]. 
We  emphasize  in  these  passages,  not  the  expressly  pro 
nounced  affirmation  of  a  life  after  death,  but  simply  the  ex 
press  requirement  to  sacrifice  one's  life  in  the  interest  of  a 
moral  duty.  But  a  world-government  in  which  the  realiza 
tion  of  the  good  is  possible  only  by  the  destruction  of  him 
who  has  for  his  life-task  to  realize  the  good,  would  be  per  se 
in  a  state  of  utter  anarchy,  and  would  have  no  right  to  im 
pose  moral  duties.  The  simple  undeniable  fact  is  this,  that 
the  Christian  heroes  who  literally  fulfilled  the  above  word  of 
Christ,  had  joy  in  so  doing  only  because  of  that  living  faith 
that  enabled  them  to  pray  amid  the  tortures  of  death:  "Lord 
Jesus,  receive  my  spirit "  [Acts  vii,  59].  But  between  the 
Christian  martyr's  joy  in  death  and  an  unbeliever's  defiant 
contempt  of  death,  there  is  a  world-wide  difference.  Cases 
are  not  unfrequently  seen  of  hardened  criminals  and  atheists 
meeting  death  with  undaunted  courage  and  great  CQolness ; 
this  is,,  however,  but  another  form  of  the  cold  defiance  with 
which  other  persons  blow  out  their  own  brains ;  and  whoever 
has  the  assurance  to  compare  such  blind  hardness,  even  in  the 
remotest  degree,  with  the  joyousness  and  peace  of  soul  of  the 
Christian,  surely  shows  himself  utterly  incapable  of  appre 
ciating  the  true  nature  of  morality. 

When  Schleiermachcr  and  others,  after  him,  declare  it  as 
unpious  to  be  interested  in  a  recompense, — understanding  by 


§  63.]  PURE   ETHICS.  57 

this  assertion  that  there  is  wanting  a  pure  and  immediate 
seeking  for  piety  and  morality  themselves,  and  that  both  are 
desired  merely  as  means  for  attaining  to  perfect  happiness  in 
a  future  life, — there  is  indeed  some  ground  for  their  position, 
but  only  in  so  far  as  the  subject  should  regard  morality 
merely  as  a  means  to  happiness,  and  that  too  as  a  meritorious 
means  even  in  our  present  state  of  sinfulness,  while  the  hap 
piness  should  be  considered  as  a  justly  claimable  reward. 
But  so  soon  as  the  objectors  presume  to  reprehend  the  seek 
ing  after  happiness  as  an  essential  and  necessary  phase  of  the 
high  st  good,  and  to  brand  as  unpious  the  striving  after  the 
same  as  an  actual  life-purpose  in  general,  we  must  reject  their 
position  as  one-sided  and  untrue.  Every  good  and  hence 
every  moral  end  produces  happiness ;  and  it  would  be  a 
strange  requirement,  to  permit  the  seeking  after  the  good 
but  not  the  seeking  after  the  happiness  therein  contained. 
When  Christ  and  the  Apostles  hesitated  not  to  base  all  moral 
sacrifice  on  the  promise  and  confident  hope  of  eternal  life,  it 
does  not  seem  very  becoming  in  a  Christian  to  stigmatize 
this  as  immoral  self-seeking.  When  appeal  is  made  to  the 
Reformed  divine  Danaeus,  who  (in  his  Ethica  Christ,  i,  c.  17) 
represents  the  honor  of  God  as  the  sole  motive,  and  that  for 
the  sake  of  which  we  should  be  in  duty  bound  to  take  upon 
ourselves  eternal  death,  were  it  required  of  us,  and  who  stig 
matizes  it  as  mercenary  to  act  morally  for  the  sake  of  eternal 
happiness, — we  may  reply,  on  the  one  hand,  that  it  could 
never  occur  to  one  who  is  a  Christian  and  conscious  of  re 
demption  by  grace  to  regard  eternal  blessedness,  as  a  reward 
due  for  his  virtue-merit, — which,  in  fact,  is  the  sole  view 
that  Danseus  rejects  [fol.  78,  ed.  3], — and,  on  the  other 
hand,  that  this  somewhat  rash  and  readily  misunderstood 
declaration  has  quite  a  different  sense  in  the  mouth  of 
DanaBus,  who  held  fast  to  personal  immortality,  and  in  the 
mouth  of  those  who  see  in  the  thought  of  immortality  only  a 
"dogma"  without  significance  for  the  religious  life,  and 
which  it  is  well  to  vail  as  much  as  possible  in  ambiguous 
phraseology.  And  in  fact  it  doubtless  forms  a  part  of  the 
moral  honoring  of  God,  that  we  believe  in  his  promises,  and 
love  and  thank  him  for  them,  and  also  act  piously  from  this 
loving  thankfulness.  For  the  moral  life  is  genuine  only 


58  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  63. 

when  it  is  a  full  and  true  -expression  of  the  filial  relation  of 
man  to  God ;  and  it  is  not  only  illegitimate,  but  also  a  sinful 
disregarding  of  God,  to  require  that  we  should  keep  only  one 
phase  of  this  relation  in  view,  and  violently  throw  aside  and 
forget  the  other, — that  we  should  see  in  God  only  the  Sover 
eign  and  not  also  the  lovingly  promising  Father.  If  God  has 
gifted  man  with  immortality,  if  he  has  promised  to  the 
Christian  eternal  life,  then  neither  can  nor  should  man,  as 
moral,  have  any  other  moral  goal  than  that  which  answers  to 
this  promise ;  if  man,  in  his  moral  life,  ignores  that  this  life 
is  the  way  to  eternal  life, — that  God  has  placed  before  him 
an  everlasting  goal, — such  conduct  is  an  immoral  rejecting 
of  God's  love.  "Whoever  does  not  act  from  love  acts  immor 
ally  ;  now,  for  the  promise  of  eternal  life  we  owe  God  thank 
ful  love;  hence  there  is  no  true  morality  which  has  not  this 
loving  thankfulness  for  its  motive. 

Against  this  view, — which  is  surely  in  perfect  harmony  with 
the  general  Christian  consciousness, — indignant  warning  lias 
been  made,*  as  if  it  were  an  ignoring  of  the  inalienable  "con 
quests  of  recent  science,"  and  even  appeal  has  been  made 
to  the  Old  Testament,  in  which,  as  an  actual  fact,  it  is  as 
serted,  the  doctrine  of  immortality  is  not  presented  as  a 
moral  motive.  Now,  if  the  conquests  of  modern  science  are 
to  consist  in  going  back  to  the  Old  Testament  stand-point, 
for  which,  on  other  occasions,  the  objectors  are  not  in  the 
habit  of  showing  any  very  high,  esteem,  we  may  well  allow 
ourselves  to  deem  it  a  progress  beyond  said  conquests,  to  come 
back  to  the  stand-point  of  Christ  and  the  Apostles.  What  the 
wise  educative  purpose  of  the  said  Old  Testament  peculiarity 
was,  we  have  elsewhere  inquired,  and  we  do  not  hesitate  .in 
the  least  to  claim  that  Christian  morality  stands  higher  than 
that  of  the  Old  Testament,  and  that  also  in  moral  respects 
"he  that  is  least  in  the  kingdom  of  heaven  is  greater"  than 
the  greatest  of  the  Old  Testament  saints  [Matt,  xi,  11], 
though  indeed  the  latter  also  had,  in  their  faith  in  the  divine 
promise,  in  their  hope  of  a  future  glorious  goal  for  all  the 
children  of  God,  a  powerful  moral  motive  that  was  in  no 
wise  opposed  to  a  belief  in  immortality,  but  on  the  contrary 

*  So  especially  Alex.  Schweitzer  in  the  Protest.  Kirchem^  1862,  Nr.  If 
Fr.  Nitzscb  in  the  Stud.  u.  Krit.,  1863,  II,  875. 


§  64.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  59 

implicitly  contained  it.  .Whether  those  who  in  recent  times 
decline,  with  such  professed  disinterestedness,  the  applica 
tion  of  faith  in  immortality  as  a  moral  motive,  seek  their 
moral  glory  in  quite  as  unconditional  a  submission  to  God's 
revealed  Word  and  guidance  as  did  the  saints  of  the  Old 
Testament,  seems  to  us,  after  all,  quite  questionable.  We  do 
not  doubt  but  that  there  may  be  some  sort  of  morality  with 
out  said  faith ;  but  the  question  is  as  to  true  morality — that 
which  embraces  the  whole  man,  appropriates  to  itself  all 
truth,  and  is  of  the  truth.  The  pains  which  some  persons 
give  themselves  to  prove  that  there  may  be  a  moral  life  with 
out  faith  in  immortality,  reminds  us  very  much  of  the  re 
cently  made  experiment  of  a  naturalist: — he  scooped  out 
with  a  spoon  the  brain  of  a  living  dove,  and  the  poor  bird 
actually  continued  to  live  for  six  several  weeks,  and  even  par 
took  of  food  in  the  mean  time !  Very  interesting  experiments 
may  be  had  by  performing  similar  amputations  on  the  living 
body  of  the  Christian  faith, — and  some  of  our  theologians 
are  quite  busy  at  the  work, — but  whether  the  patient  prospers 
very  well  under  the  operation  is  another  question. 


B.— MAN  AS  TO  HIS  SENSUOUSLY-CORPOREAL  LIFE. 

i 
SECTION  LXIV. 

The  natural  body,  as  the  physical  basis  on  which 
the  spirit  develops  itself  to  its  full  reality,  has  not  a 
purpose  in  and  of  itself,  but  only  for  the  spirit, 
namely,  to  be  the  perfectly-answering  and  absolutely- 
subserving  organ  of  the  spirit's  relations  to  nature. 
This  embraces  three  points : — 1.  The  sensuous  cor 
poreality  is,  despite  its  seemingly  trammeling  power 
over  the  freedom  of  the  spirit,  per  se  absolutely  good, 
and  there  is  neither  any  thing  evil  in  it  nor  is  it  the 
cause  of  any  evil  whatsoever;  and  as  the  body  must, 
in  so  far  as  it  is  normal,  be  in  harmony  with  the 
spirit  and  with  nature,  hence  there  is  in  it  no  sort 


60  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§64. 

of  ground  for  any  trammeling  of  the  spiritual  life — 
for  any  pain. 

The  moral  significance  of  the  sensuous  nature,  the  cor 
poreality,  of  man  is  a  very  important  point  in  the  Christian 
world-theory,  and  can  ill  no  wise  be  regarded  as  non-essential. 
It  is,  in  fact,  one  among  the  living  questions  of  the  day, — 
questions  which  are  being  warmly  agitated  even  outside  of 
the  church,  and  in  relation  to  which  the  bearing  of  the  Chris 
tian  consciousness  is,  in  many  respects,  entirely  misunder 
stood.  As  early  as  the  fourth  century  there  'infected  the 
Christian  church  (partly  under  the  prompting,  or  at  least  the 
countenance  of  non-Christian  influences)  a  spiritualistic  view 
of  the  naturally-sensuous, — a  practical  disesteeming  of  the 
same  in  comparison  with  the  spiritual ;  and  the  Middle  Ages 
followed  in  general  the  same  tendency ;  the  Reformation  re 
turned  to  the  primitive  Christian  and  biblical  view.  The 
recent  rationalistic  philosophy  of  the  understanding  de 
veloped,  in  contrast  to  the  Middle  Ages,  the  theoretical  rather 
than  the  practical  phase  of  spiritualism,  and  conceived  the 
sensuously-corporeal  life,  not  merely  as  the  cause  of  sin,  but 
asperse  and  originally  a  trammeling  of  the  spiritual  life, — 
as  the  real  source  and  seat  of  sin,  and  hence  as  a  mere  transi 
tory  and  soon  entirely-to-be-thrown-off  evil, — and  interpreted, 
utterly  erroneously,  the  New  Testament  term,  adp%,  referring 
it  to  the  natural  corporeality.  Death,  which  had  previously 
been  viewed  as  the  wages  of  sin,  was  now  regarded  as  the 
emancipator  from  the  seductive  and  spirit-burdening  cor 
poreal  life, — as  the  divinely  appointed  normal  beginning  of 
the  untrammcled  life  of  the  spirit.  Sensuousness  is  here  the 
not  inherited,  but  innate,  and  not  guilty,  but  guilt-generating 
molum  originis — an  evil,  the  origin  of  which  was  not  free  re 
sponsibly-sinning  man,  but  the  divine  creative  will  itself;  in 
getting  rid  of  corporeality  therefore  man  gets  rid  at  the  same 
time  also  of  his  (so-regarded)  scarcely-imputable  sinfulness. 
Sin  consists  essentially  in  the  predominating  of  the  sense-life 
over  the  spirit ;  the  spirit  per  xc  would  have  little  or  no  occa 
sion  for  sin.  The  doctrine  of  a  resurrection  of  a  glorified 
body  is  rejected  as  belonging  to  a  crude,  unspiritual  world- 
view  ;  it  is  only  the  pure  disembodied  spirit  that  is  free  and 


§  64.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  61 

perfect.  In  opposition  to  this  view,  the  more  recent  and  now 
spreading  irreligious  Materialism  has  exalted  the  sensuously- 
corporeal  nature  above  the  spirit,  and  conceived  of  the  spirit 
as  merely  a  transient  force-manifestation  of  organized  matter. 

The  evangelically-Christian  view  is  neither  the  above  spirit 
ualistic  nor  this  materialistic  one.  Christianity,  though  so 
often  charged  by  worldlings  with  a  one-sided  spiritualism, 
places  in  fact  a  much  higher  moral  worth  on  the  corporeal 
nature  than  was  ever  done  by  heathenism.  The  body  is 
destined,  it  is  true,  to  absolute  subserviency  to  the  spirit; 
but  it  has  precisely  in  this,  its  perfect  service,  also  a  share  in 
the  high  moral  significancy  of  the  spirit, — it  is  not  only  not 
to  be  discarded  as  a  trammeling  of  the  spirit,  but  is  a  very 
essential  part  of  the  moral  person.  As  the  eye  cannot  say  to 
the  hand:  "I  have  no  need  of  thee"  [1  Cor.  xii,  21],  neither 
also  may  the  spirit  thus  speak  to  the  body.  As  the  nature- 
side  of  man,  corporeality  mediates  the  action  of  the  spirit 
upon  nature,  so  that  nature  becomes  thrown  open  to  the 
spirit  as  an  object  both  of  knowledge  and  of  action.  The 
spirit  stands  in  living  relation  not  only  to  spirit,  but  essen 
tially  also  to  nature,  and  virtualizes  also  therein  its  God- 
likeness. 

The  normal  relation  of  the  body  ta  the  spirit  cannot  be 
directly  inferred  from  the  present  actual  state  of  humanity ; 
for  if  we  assume,  even  preliminarily,  the  possibility  that  the 
moral  spirit  of  the  race  has  fallen  away  from  its  harmony 
with  God,  we  yet  thereby  render  it  unsafe  to  infer  that  rela 
tion  from  the  present  state  of  things,  since  from  the  dis 
turbed  harmony  of  man  with  God  follows  also  the  disturb 
ance  of  his  harmony  with  himself,  and  especially  of  that  be 
tween  spirit  and  body.  The  true  original  relation  can  be 
educed  only,  on  the  one  hand,  from  Scriptural  declarations 
and  from  the  living  example  of  Christ,  and,  on  the  other, 
from  the  Christian  idea  of  creation.  The  simple  fact  that 
all  that  God  creates  is  good,  is  itself  proof  that  the  corporeality 
created  for  the  spirit  can  neither  be  a  trammeling  nor  a  nat 
ural  source  of  suffering  for  the  same.  Suffering  and  pain  are 
indeed  means  of  educative  chastening  for  man  as  sinful,  but 
for  the  unsinful  their  presence  would  be  the  reversing  of  all 
moral  order.  In  God's  good-created  world,  men,  were  they 


62  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  64. 

unfallen,  would  receive  their  moral  training  through  mani 
festations  of  love,  without  the  intervention  of  suffering  and 
pain ;  to  deny  this  would  be  to  deny  either  God's  love  or  his 
power. 

The  sensuous  corporeality  in  its  uncorrupted  primitiveness 
can  disturb  neither  the  moral  life  by  really  immoral  appe 
tites,  nor  the  feeling  of  happiness  by  pains  and  sickness, — 
the  aequale  temperamentum  qualitatum  corporis  (equipoise  of 
the  qualities  of  the  body)  of  the  Apologia  (i,  17) ; — in  that 
which  was  created  good  there  can  be  no  antagonism  between 
the  life  of  the  spirit  and  that  of  the  body,  nor  between  the 
body  and  nature ;  but  every  suffering,  every  pain,  is  evidence 
of  an  antagonism,  of  an  evil  in  its  subject.  In  the  Scriptures 
all  bodily  sufferings  are  expressly  traced  back  to  sin  [Gen. 
iii,  16,  19;  Rom.  v,  12-21];  this  is  the  only  possible  "theod 
icy"  in  regard  to  human  suffering.  The  body  of  the  rational 
spirit  is  under  the  dominion  of  that  spirit,  and  not  under 
that  of  unspiritual  nature ;  and  the  spirit  is  under  the  power 
of  itself,  and  not  under  that  of  a  nature-bound  body ;  and  it 
is  only  such  a  spirit  as  is  free  in  every  respect, — one  that  is 
not  rendered  unfree  by  a  hampering  corporeality, — that  is  in 
a  condition  to  fulfill  the  whole  of  moral  duty.  In  proportion 
as  the  now  actually  spirit-hampering  sensuous  corporeality  is 
held  to  be  the  normal  condition,  and  to  answer  to  the  divine 
creative  idea,  in  the  same  proportion  must  the  moral  life-task 
also  be  lowered.  And  when  Rationalism  finds  the  true  free 
dom  and  moral  emancipation  of  the  spirit  only  in  the  freeing 
of  the  same  from  the  body,  there  is  at  least  this  much  of 
truth  in  the  position,  namely,  that  it  is  an  admission  that  the 
present  bondage  of  the  spirit  under  the  manifoldly-hampering 
power  of  the  body  is  not  in  harmony  with  the  true  life  of  the 
moral  spirit.  But  whereas  the  evangelically-Christian  con 
sciousness  refers  this  antagonism  in  God's  world  to  the  guilt 
of  man,  Rationalism  casts  the  responsibility  for  this  condition 
(which  itself  admits  to  be  in  contradiction  to  the  moral  idea) 
upon  Qod,  and  thereby,  in  fact,  undermines  the  Christian  idea 
of  God,  and  hence  also  the  unconditional  obligatoriness  of 
moral  .duty.  Ultra  posse  nemo  obligatur  (Obligation  does  not 
transcend  ability) ;  this  is  an  ancient  truth  valid  not  only  in 
the  sphere  of  jurisprudence  but  also  in  that  of  morality. 


§  65.]  PURE   ETHICS.  63 

SECTION  LXV. 

2.  The  body  mediates  the  relation  of  the  objective 
world  to  the  personal  spirit,  through  the  senses ;  and 
this  mediation,  as  being  established  by  the  divine 
creative  will,  is  a  truthful  one.  On  the  other  hand, 
the  body  mediates  the  active  relation  of  the  spirit  to 
the  objective  world,  and,  in  subserving  the  spirit,  it 
thereby  mediates  the  morally-essential  dominion  of 
the  spirit  over  nature,  and  is,  hence,  the  necessary 
and  adequate  organ  of  the  moral  spirit  in  its  relation 
to  the  external  world, — and  not  that  of  nature  for  its 
dominion  over  the  spirit. 

If  the  created  spirit  has  surety  of  ability  for  knowing  the 
truth,  this  of  itself  implies  that  the  knowledge  mediated  by 
the  senses  must  be  real  and  true, — that  sense-impressions 
per  se  do  not  deceive  us.  ' '  The  hearing  ear  and  the  seeing 
eye,  the  Lord  hath  made  even  both  of  them"  [Prov.  xx,  12] ; 
but  God  is  a  God  of  truth;  and  the  solemn  exhortation: 
"Lift  up  your  eyes  on  high,  and  behold  who  hath  created 
these  things ! "  [Isa.  xl,  26],  is  at  the  same  time  a  guarantee 
of  the  reliableness  of  the  senses.  If  the  senses  deceive  us, 
then  God  deceives  us.  Just  as  without  faith  in  God  there  is 
no  morality,  so  also,  without  confidence  in  the  truthfulness 
of  the  divinely  established  world-order — which  of  course  in 
cludes  the  vital  relations  of  creatures  to  each  other — a  com 
plete  morality  is  impossible.  Man  cannot  be  under  obliga 
tion  to  be  truthful,  if  creation  is  not  so.  The  matter  is 
therefore  not  so  morally  indifferent  as  at  first  glance  it  might 
seem.  If  God  is  to  be  seen  in  his  works  [Rom.  i,  20]  then 
must  these  works  speak  truthfully  to  us.  If  sense-impres 
sions  have  only  subjective  truth,  then  they  have  none  at  all, 
and  hence  no  worth  whatever, — then  we  sustain  no  moral  re 
lation  to  the  objective  world,  inasmuch  as  under  such  cir 
cumstances  it  would  have  for  us  no  existence.  There  could 
then  be  no  further  question  save  of  a  moral  duty  of  man  to 
himself  or  to  God.  Skepticism  on  this  point  is  therefore  no 


6i  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§66. 

less  anti-moral  than  impious.  Deceptions  growing  out  of 
false  judgments  as  to  per  se  true  sense-impressions,  must  of 
course  not  be  confounded  with  the  deception  of  sense-im 
pressions  themselves ;  it  is  not  the  eye  that  sees  the  sky  touch 
the  earth  at  the  horizon,  it  is  only  a  premature  judgment 
£hat  leads  .to  this  deception.  Real  sense-deceptions  spring 
of  disease,  but  disease  does  not  exist  in  a  state  of  moral 
purity. 

The  spirit  is  ,to  dominate  over  nature,  not  directly,  how 
ever,  by  a  mere  magic-working  will,  but  by  the  instrumen 
tality  of  its  own  dominated  body.  The  destination  to  this 
domination  is  expressed  even  in  the  build  of  the  human 
body :  erect,  with  upturned  look,  with  hands  planned  for  the 
most  manifold  activity,  the  human  body  bears  upon  it  the 
impress  as  well  as  the  reality  of  dominating  power.  While 
Materialism  subordinates  spirit  to  nature,  the  Christian  world- 
view  subordinates  nature  to  spirit;  and  as  the  spirit  is  entirely 
master  over  its  body,  so  is  it  likewise  master  over  nature  by 
means  of  the  body.  A  childish,  morally-unripe  spirit  cannot, 
it  is  true,  dominate  nature  at  the  will  of  its  irrational  whims, 
— but  we  speak  here  only  of  the  rational  spirit,  and  in  this 
sphere  the  words,  "the  spirit  is  willing,  but  the  flesh  is  weak, " 
have  no  application;  in  normal  man  the  flesh  is  also  willing 
and  strong.  Even  as  through  the  senses  nature  is  open  and 
unlocked  for  the  cognizing  spirit,  so  is  it  also  through  the 
bodily  organs  for  the  volitionating  spirit.  If  the  facts  seem 
otherwise  in  the  present  reality  of  things,  if  the  body  is  no 
longer  an  absolutely  obedient  medium  for  the  dominion  of  the 
spirit  over  nature,  but  on  the  contrary  is  much  ofteuer  a  mere 
instrument  of  nature  for  her  dominating  over  the  spirit,  this 
is  simply  because  the  right  and  primitive  relation  has  been 
disturbed,  and  has  given  place  to  the  enfeebling  influence  of 
sin. 

SECTION  LXVI. 

3.  The  incipient  limitation  of  the  freedom  of  the 
normally  self-developing  spirit  by  the  body  in  conse 
quence  of  the  dependent  condition  of  the  latter  on 
external  nature,  is  only  the  corresponding  normal 
expression  of  the  btill  existing  unfreedorn  of  the,  as 


§  66.]  PURE   ETHICS.  65 

yet,  unmatured  spirit,  and  is  therefore  also  the  pro 
tection  of  the  same  against  its  own  immaturity,— a 
divinely-intended  means  of  discipline  for  the  same. 
But  this  primarily  limiting  relation  of  the  body  to 
the  spirit  is  only  transient,  and  is  not  a  real  tram 
meling.  The  body,  while  following  in  its  own  de 
velopment  the  growth  of  the  spirit  in  rationality  and 
freedom,  passes  gradually  over  from  its  at  first  pre 
dominantly  determining  and  conditioning  character 
to  that  of  being  predominantly  determined  and  con 
ditioned  by  the  spirit ;  and  in  its  ultimate  perfection, 
— as  corresponding  to  the  full  moral  maturity  of  the 
spirit, — it  becomes  perfectly  spirit-imbued  and  spirit- 
appropriated, — the  absolutely  subservient  organ  of  the 
emancipated  spirit, — becomes  a  perfectly  spiritualized 
and  transfigured  body,  which  latter,  as  being  de 
veloped  by  a  regular  growth  out  of  the  original  un- 
free  nature-body,  is  conditioned  neither  on  a  violent 
death  of  the  nature-body  nor  is  subject  itself  to  death, 
seeing  that  it  is  simply  the  necessary  and  normal 
organ  of  the  immortal  spirit. 

It  would  be  an  injustice  in  the  Creator,  and  a  God-repug 
nant  defect  in  creation,  were  the  essentially  free  and  morally 
matured  spirit  bound  in  unfreedom  by  a  per  se  irrational  na 
ture;  and  the  anti-scriptural  notion,  that  the  rational  spirit 
has  been  banished  into  a  body,  as  into  a  prison,  in  punish 
ment  for  the  sins  of  a  previous  life,  would  then  be  the  sole 
possible  justification  of  the  Creator.  But  the  conditional  un 
freedom  of  the  spirit  such  as  we  must  admit  also  for  the 
unfallen  state,  namely,  that  it  is  limited  by  the  natural  al 
ternation  of  sleeping  and  waking  [comp.  Gen.  ii,  21]  by  the 
natural  wants  of  food,  etc.,  [comp.  Gen.  i,  29,  30],  is  not 
against  but  for  the  spirit.  It  reminds  the  personal  spirit  of 
its  belonging  to  the  per  se  unitary  and  law-governed  All,  its 
regulated  connection  with  nature ;  it  protects  the,  as  yet,  inex- 

VOL.  II— 6 


66  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  66. 

perienced  spirit  from  unwise  presumption,  from  arbitrary  irra 
tional  meddling  with  the  divinely-established  order  of  the 
world, — teaches  it  to  submit  itself  to  the  divinely- willed  and 
ordered  laws  of  existence,  teaches  it  humility,  and  brings  to 
its  consciousness  its  dependence  on  God's  power,  thereby  im 
pressing  upon  it  the  lesson  that  it  can  attain  to  true  freedom 
only  by  a  free  and  cheerful  self-denial  in  relation  to  the  will 
of  God.  Hunger,  e.  g.,  is  the  most  powerful  stimulus  to 
activity,  and  hence  to  the  development  of  the  spirit,  and  ever 
since  the  entrance  of  sin  into  the  race  there  has  been  no  other 
so  sure  and  effectual  a  means  of  stirring  up  the  spirit  out  of 
its  slothful  indolence  [Prov.  xvi,  26,  in  the  original].  In  the 
present  state  of  man  hunger  is  not  only  of  significance  for  the 
individual,  it  is  a  world-historical  power,  the  first  and  most 
persistent  stimulus  to  civilization.  Unf alien  humanity,  it  is- 
true,  knows  nothing  of  any  hunger-stress,  but  it  knows  it  as  a 
want  requiring  satisfaction ;  and  it  is  not  a  feature  of  the  suffer 
ing  but  of  the  true  humanity  of  Christ,  that  he  also  felt  hunger. 
That  which  was  a  disciplining  beginning,  however,  is  not  to 
be  permanent ;  but  it  is  not  the  body,  but  only  the  limiting 
power  of  the  same  that  is  to  pass  away.  The  view  that  the 
body  is  not  a  permanent  condition  of  the  spirit,  but  only  a 
prison-house  destined  to  destruction, — a  merely  useless  bur 
dening  incident  of  the  spirit, — is  a  very  favorite  one,  it  is 
true,  but  it  is  a  very  un-Christian  one.  What  God  does  is 
done  well,  and  he  has  given  the  body  to  the  spirit  for  perfect 
service,  and  not  for  a  burden  and  a  clog.  Of  the  notion  that 
the  original  body  is  only  a  worthless  case  or  husk,  to  be  cast 
off  like  the  chrysalis  of  the  butterfly,  the  Scriptures  know 
nothing; — the  dissolving  of  the  earthly  house  [2  Cor.  v,  1]  ap 
plies  only  to  the  body  of  sin  and  death  [Gen.  iii,  19] ; — the  body 
is  originally,  on  the  contrary,  the  divinely-established  perma 
nent  condition  of  true  life,  though  indeed  not  an  absolutely 
necessary  condition  of  the  life  of  the  spirit  in  general.  Christ, 
the  perfect  man,  shows  in  his  own  person  what  the  human 
body  signifies  and  is ;  Christ's  resurrection  is  a  stone  of  stum 
bling  for  all  one-sided  spiritualism.  Christ  lives  on,  not  as  a 
mere  bodiless  spirit,  but  in  his  now  glorified  body,  and  he  will 
transfigure  our  sin-ruined  body  that  it  may  be  like  unto  his 
glorious  body  [Phil,  iii,  21].  This  transfiguration,  though 


§  66.]  PURE   ETHICS.  67 

without  death — not  a  being  unclothed,  but  a  being  clothed 
upon  [2  Cor.  v,  4] — is  the  original  purpose  of  the  body  given 
to  the  immortal  spirit  as  its  subservient  organ.  The  spirit's 
body  is  in  fact,  as  such,  no  longer  a  mere  nature-object,  but, 
as  the  exclusive  possession  of  an  immortal  subject,  it  is  also 
itself  raised  above  the  perishableness  incident  to  all  mere 
nature-objects. — Death  is  in  the  Scriptures  uniformly  referred 
back  to  sin;  and  the  great  emphasis  which  the  New  Testa 
ment  lays  upon  the  resurrection  of  the  body  indicates  what 
the  original  body  was  to  have  been.  If  it  is  the  moral  des 
tination  of  the  spirit  to  be  free,  to  dominate  by  reason  over 
the  merely  natural,  then  death,  as  a  violent  interruption  of 
life,  comes  into  direct  antagonism  with  this  destination;  it 
indicates  a  complete  ascendency  of  unconscious  nature  over 
spirit,  the  impotency  of  the  spirit  in  the  face  of  nature — a 
condition  of  the  real  bondage  of  spirit  to  nature.  Were  this 
wide-reaching  antagonism  between  the  actual  state  and  the 
moral  nature  of  the  spirit  the  original  condition,  and  were  it 
included  in  the  nature  of  things  or  in  the  creative  will  itself, 
then  the  nerve  of  all  morality  would  be  paralyzed,  and  all 
moral  courage  broken.  To  struggle  against  too  great  odds  is 
folly;  if  irrational  nature  is  more  powerful  than  the  moral 
spirit,  then  the  latter  can  rationally  take  no  better  course 
than  to  yield  to  superior  force,  and  to  place  its  own  sensuous 
nature  higher  than  its  spiritual. 

C.— THE  UNITY  OF  THE  SPIRIT  AND  THE  BODY. 
SECTION  LXYII. 

In  virtue  of  the  union  of  spirit  and  body  into  one 
personality,  the  spirit  is  manifoldly  determined  also 
in  its  moral  life,  and  it  appears  in  consequence  under 
different  phases  of  existence,  which  occasion  also 
correspondingly  different  manifestations  of  morality. 

1.  The  stages  of  life.  The  spirit  is  dependent  in 
its  development  on  that  of  the  body,  not  absolutely, 
however,  but  only  relatively ;  the  development-stages 
of  the  moral  spirit — which  do  not  entirely  coincide 


68  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  67. 

with  those  of  the  body,  but  only  in  general  and 
partially  run  parallel  therewith — are  the  following  : — 
(a)  The  stage  of  moral  minority,  childhood.  Here 
the  body  is  as  yet  master  over  the  spirit ;  the  spirit 
is  as  yet  in  most  things  essentially  unfree — dependent 
on  outer,  sensuous,  and  spiritual  influences, — is  more 
guided  than  self-guiding. — (J)  The  stage  of  transition 
to  majority, — still  wavering  between  freedom  and 
unfreedom ;  morality  appears  essentially  under  the 
form  of  free  obedience  toward  educators. — (c)  The 
stage  of  moral  majority.  The  person  has  come  into 
possession  of  himself, — is  actually  master  over  him 
self  as  regards  moral  self-determination,  is  able  by 
his  moral  consciousness  to  guide  himself  independ 
ently;  hence  he  is  fully  morally  responsible,  and  is 
in  process  of  developing  an  independent  character. — 
A  relapsing  of  the  morally  matured  into  a  state  of 
moral  irresponsibility,  a  becoming  childish,  is  not 
conceivable  in  a  normal  condition  of  humanity, 
though  here  there  would  doubtless,  indeed,  be  a 
greater  turning  away  from  merely  earthly  things, 
and  a  growing  preoccupation  with  the  supernatural, 
— in  tlie  stage  of  moral  old  age. 

The  development  of  a  spirit  as  united  with  a  body,  consists 
in  one  of  its  phases  in  the  fact  that  it  more  and  more  throws 
off  its  primarily  normal  greater  dependence  on  the  corporeal 
life, — that  it  becomes  freer,  ripens  toward  maturity.  Al 
though  we  cannot  conceive  of  the  first  created  human  beings 
as  beginning  life  in  a  state  of  unconscious  childhood,  still  the 
above-mentioned  stages  of  life,  seeing  that  they  are  implied 
in  the  very  nature  of  self-development,  must  hold  good,  at 
least,  of  all  succeeding  generations ;  and  even  the  first  man 
could  not  appear  at  once  as  a  perfectly  mature,  morally-ripened 
spirit,  but  had  to  pass  through  similar  stages  of  development. 
According  to  the  naturalistic  view,  the  spiritual  development 


§  67.]  PURE   ETHICS.  69 

is  exclusively  and  absolutely  conditioned  on  that  of  the  body 
— is  only  the  bloom  and  vigor  of  the  same.  This  assertion,  as 
well  as  the  theory  on  which  it  is  based,  is  refuted  by  the  sim 
ple  matter  of  fact  that  spiritual  development  often  far  outruns 
that  of  the  body,  and  in  fact  in  a  normal  development  must 
do  so,  and  also  that  in  persons  of  precisely  equal  bodily  de 
velopment,  the  spiritual  ripeness  may  be  very  widely  different. 
In  an  as  yet  unmatured  body  there  may  be  a  mature  spirit,  in  a 
weak  and  ailing  body,  a  strong  spirit ;  this  would  be  incon 
ceivable  on  the  naturalistic  hypothesis.  But  especially  the 
moral  development  may  come  to  ripeness  of  character  much 
earlier  than  the  corporeal  life ;  growth  in  knowledge  is  much 
more  dependent  on  the  development  of  the  body ;  the  under 
standing  does  not  outrun  the  years,  and  children  that  are 
early  ripe  intellectually,  are  usually  morbid  phenomena;  but 
a  very  youthful  soul  may  acquire  a  real  and  firm  moral  char 
acter.  The  proverb,  "Youth  is  without  virtue,"  in  so  far 
as  it  is  meant  to  be  an  excuse,  is  absolutely  immoral  and 
perverse. 

In  consequence  of  the  normal  super-ordination  of  the  spirit 
to  the  body,  the  spiritual  development-stages  do  not  coincide, 
in  point  of  time,  with  the  corresponding  bodily  stages,  but 
precede  them  somewhat.  The  first  stage  is  that  of  childlike 
innocence,  where  the  child  as  yet  knows  not  how  to  distin 
guish  between  good  and  evil  [Isa.  vii,  16],  where,  as  yet,  the 
moral  consciousness  slumbers,  and  the  life-activity  does  not 
spring  from  a  will  conscious  of  a  moral  purpose,  but,  on  the 
contrary,  from  unconscious  feelings  which  are  directly  excited 
by  external  or  sensuous  influences;  hence  an  accountability 
proper  cannot  as  yet  be  presumed.  The  child  has  indeed 
propensions  and  aversions,  love  and  anger,  and  other  states 
of  feeling,  but  it  does  not  have  them  intelligently, — is  not 
as  yet  in  spiritual  self-possession.  Obedience  is,  as  yet,  a 
mere  scarcely-conscious  following,  taking  its  rise  simply  from 
natural  feelings  and  from  the  instinct  of  imitation,  and  which 
is  indeed  a  germ  of  morality,  though  not,  as  yet,  actual 
morality,  but  is,  in  fact,  also  found  to  some  extent  among 
domesticated  animals.  The  typical  character  of  children  as 
presented  by  Christ  [Matt,  xviii,  3]  does  not  relate  to  any 
moral  perfection  in  them,  but  only  to  their  receptiveness  for 


70  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  67. 

moral  impressions,  to  their  innocence,  to  their  consciousness 
of  need,  and  their  readiness  to  believe. 

The  stage  of  transition,  or  youth,  is  the  time  when  the  per 
son  can  distinguish  between  good  and  evil,  and  where,  conse 
quently,  there  exists  a  real  moral  consciousness,  though  not 
one  that  is  thoroughly  formed  and  in  every  case  self -determin 
ing,  but  only  primarily  a  consciousness  of  good  and  evil  in 
general,  and  the  particular  application  of  which  in  single 
cases  is,  for  the  most  part,  not  left  to  personal  free  self-deter 
mination,  but  to  the  guidance  of  educators.  The  boy  has  the 
definite  law,  as  yet,  only  in  an  objective  manner,  in  the  will 
of  his  parents ;  his  moral  consciousness  sketches  only  general 
outlines, — for  the  more  definite  traits  and  shades  it  is  as  yet 
dependent  on  some  other,  to  him  objective,  consciousness. 
Hence  the  most  characteristic  form  of  the  morality  of  this 
period  is  obedience ;  and  the  greatest  danger  to  morality,  so 
long  as  this  partial  uncertainty  yet  remains,  is  the  tendency, 
readily  resulting  from  the  incipient  consciousness  of  moral 
self-determination,  to  wish  to  determine  one's  conduct  in  par 
ticular  cases  directly  and  immediately  from  the,  as  yet,  only 
general  and  indefinite  moral  consciousness,— that  is,  the  tend 
ency  to  premature  freedom,  the  pleasure  in  an  unregulated 
enjoyment  of  freedom,  in  arbitrary  self-determination.  This 
in  fact  was  the  danger  to  which  our  first  parents  fell  a  prey. 

The  stage  of  moral  maturity,  in  a  normal  development,  far 
more  than  overtakes  that  of  bodily  ripeness.  While  civil  law 
fixes  the  civil  majority,  that  is,  the  time  of  ripe  understand 
ing,  at  the  period  of  full  bodily  maturity,  the  moral  com 
munity,  the  Church,  declares  man  as  morally  mature  much 
earlier  (confirmation) ;  also  the  state  fixes  full  moral  respon 
sibility  much  earlier  than  the  civil  majority.  These  dis 
tinctions  rest  on  well-grounded  experience.  The  young  man 
knows  not  merely  moral  duty  in  general,  but  he  is  also  capa 
ble  of  conforming  his  life  thereto  in  particular.  Obedience  to 
parents  or  gunrdians  assumes  now  the  form  of  obedience  to 
the  moral  law,  which  latter  indeed  includes  the  former,  but 
no  longer  as  an  essentially  unconditional  obedience,  but  sim 
ply  as  one  that  is  to  be  subordinated  to  the  moral  law.  But  a 
morally  mature  person  can  come  into  an  actual  conjuncture 
where  it  is  necessary  to  refuse  obedience  to  parents,  only  on 


§67.]  PURE   ETHICS.  71 

the  presupposition  of  a  morally  disordered  state  of  humanity ; 
and  also  civil  law  finds  in  such  obedience,  after  years  of  moral 
majority,  no  excuse  for  criminal  acts. 

The  becoming-childish  of  the  aged  would  be  a  very  weighty 
reason  for  doubting  of  personal  immortality,  were  it  a  normal 
phenomenon  of  old  age.  When,  however,  we  consider  that 
even  in  the  present  sin-disordered  condition  of  the  race,  this 
becoming-childish  is  by  no  means  a  necessary  and  universal 
phenomenon,  but  that,  on  the  contrary,  the  fruit  of  a  morally- 
pious  life — even  in  far  advanced  age,  and  despite  the  other 
wise  slumber-like  obscuration  of  the  intellectual  faculties — is  a 
heightening  of  the  religious  and  moral  consciousness,  and  that 
even  the  better  forms  of  heathenism  consider  reverence  for  the 
moral  wisdom  of  the  aged  as  a  high  virtue, — we  can  readily, 
then,  infer  from  this,  how  little  room  there  would  be  for  a  real 
becoming-childish  in  any  respect  whatever  in  an  unfallen  state 
of  humanity.  Precisely  what  would  have  been  the  character 
istics  of  normal  old  age  in  a  sinless  state,  we  know  not ;  this 
much,  however,  we  do  know,  that  the  life  of  an  immortal 
spirit,  as  being  destined  to  a  higher  ennoblement  or  trans 
figuration,  and  as  not  subject  to  a  positive  violent  death, 
could  not  be  liable  to  a  return  to  a  state  of  moral  minority, — 
at  the  farthest  it  would  only  have  prepared  itself  for  this 
freely  self-accomplishing  ennobling,  by  a  greater  turning 
away  from  earthly  things.  All  senility  of  age  we  can  regard 
only  as  an  absolutely  abnormal  sin-born  phenomenon,  seeing 
that  it  stands  in  manifest  antagonism  to  the  nature  and  des 
tination  of  the  personal  spirit. 

SECTION  LXVIH. 

2.  Differences  of  temperament — the  different  tem 
pers  of  the  spirit  in  its  bearing  toward  the  outer 
world,  as  determined  by  differences  of  bodily  pecul 
iarity.  These  differences  are — as  an  expression  of 
that  manifoldness  of  being  which  is  necessary  to  the 
perfection  of  the  whole — per  se  good,  and  give  rise 
to  a  vital  reciprocalness  of  relation  among  the  mem 
bers  of  society.  As  mere  natural  determinations  of 


72  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  68. 

the  spirit  they  have  primarily  no  moral  significance  ; 
they  receive  such,  however,  as  conditions  of  the 
moral  life.  They  do  not  constitute  moral  character ; 
on  the  contrary,  they  are,  in  their  disproportionate- 
ness,  to  be  controlled  by  the  character,  and  trained 
into  virtue. — Related  to  the  temperaments  are  the 
normal  differences  in  the  natural  peculiarities  of 
nations. 

From  a  naturalistic  stand-point  great  importance  is  attrib 
uted  to  temperaments,  as  if  they  were  original  moral  deter 
minations.  But  that  which  is  original  and  merely  natural  is 
not  as  yet  moral ;  it  is  only  the  antecedent  condition  of  the 
moral.  Moral  character  is  not  determined  by  nature,  but  only 
by  the  free  action  of  man  himself;  in  proportion  as  we  con 
sider  the  moral  as  determined  by  nature,  we  destroy  its  very 
essence.  While  the  ancients  considered  the  temperaments 
rather  in  their  purely  corporeal  significance,  in  recent  times 
emphasis  is  often  given  rather  to  their  spiritually-moral  signif 
icance,  to  the  detriment  of  morality.  On  this  point  there 
has  been  much  fallacious  speculation,  and  the  inclination  is  in 
many  respects  manifest,  to  attempt  to  comprehend  man  in  his 
moral  peculiarity  from  mere  nature-circumstances,  rather  than 
honestly  to  look  into  his  moral  nature — to  search  his  heart ; 
and  men  are  very  ready  to  excuse  their  moral  foibles  and 
vices  on  the  score  of  temperament ;  this  course  is  naturalistic, 
and,  in  fact,  materialistic.  Temperament  is,  essentially,  sim 
ply  the  normal  basis  on  which  morality  is  to  develop  itself ; 
it  does  not,  however,  itself  determine  the  moral  life-task,  but 
only  has  influence  in  throwing  it  into  its  peculiar  form;  he 
whose  character  is  shaped  only  by  his  temperament  has  no 
character.  The  moral  character  stands  above  all  temperament ; 
and  where  there  are  different  and  opposed  temperaments  like 
moral  characters  may  be  formed,  and  the  converse.  Temper 
aments  are  not  per  se  a  peculiarity  of  the  spirit,  but  are  based 
in  that  of  the  corporeal  life,  and  pass  over  upon  the  spirit 
only  by  virtue  of  a  kind  of  communicatio  idiomatum.  It  is 
usual  to  distinguish  four  temperaments, — according  to  the 
susceptibility  for  external  influences,  and  to  the  active  bearing 


§68.]  PURE   ETHICS.  73 

toward  the  outer  world :  (1)  that  which  is  very  open  for  out 
ward  impressions,  and  is  at  the  same  time  more  acted  upon 
from  without,  than  self-active — the  light,  sanguine  tempera 
ment  ; — (2)  that  which  is  very  open  for  outward  impressions, 
but  is  at  the  same  time  rather  self-active,  initiatively  working, 
and  influencing  the  outer  world — the  warm,  choleric  tempera 
ment; — (3)  that  which  is  less  receptive  for  outward  impres 
sions,  and  at  the  same  time  rather  inactive,  indifferent — the 
cool,  phlegmatic  temperament ; — (4)  that  which,  while  equally 
feebly-receptive  for  outward  impressions,  is  yet  more  active, 
storing  up  in  itself  what  it  receives — the  heavy  melancholic 
temperament. — The  types  of  temperament,  however,  do  not 
usually  appear  under  these  pure  forms;  generally  they  are 
commingled  and  toned  down.  Nor  does  a  temperament  al 
ways  remain  the  same,  but  it  changes  with  the  outward  rela 
tions  and  age  of  the  person. 

As  the  moral  person  is  not  to  permit  himself  to  be  deter 
mined  by  the  irrational,  but  should  himself  freely  determine 
himself  on  the  basis  of  the  moral  consciousness,  hence  he  is 
all  the  more  moral  the  more  he  subordinates  his  temperament 
to  his  moral  will, — not  cultivating  simply  those  virtues  which 
are  more  congenial  to  his  temperament,  as,  for  example,  friend 
liness  in  the  sanguine,  patience  in  the  phlegmatic,  courage 
in  the  choleric,  etc.  Morality  consists  rather,  on  the  con 
trary,  in  the  inner  harmony  of  all  the  different  moral  phases, 
and  must  consequently  counteract  the  one-sidedness  of  any 
particular  temperament.  The  light  temperament  tends  to 
frivolity,  the  warm  to  passionateness  and  revenge,  the  cool  to 
indifference  and  indolence,  the  heavy  to  selfishness  and  nar 
rowness.  He  who  leaves  his  temperament  unbridled,  culti 
vates  not  its  virtue  but  its  defect ;  for  virtue  is  never  a  mere 
nature-proclivity.  As  a  peculiar  endowment,  temperament, 
like  every  other  endowment,  must  be  morally  shaped,  and 
hence  brought  into  proper  harmony  with  the  moral  whole  of 
the  life.  No  sin  finds  a  moral  justification  in  temperament ; 
and,  on  the  other  hand,  only  that  course  of  action  is  morally 
good  which  springs  not  merely  from  temperament,  but  from 
the  moral  consciousness. 

The  differences  of  natural  national  peculiarities  are  related 
to  the  difference  of  temperament.  Also  in  a  sinless  state,  a 


74  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§69. 

diversity  among  nations,  a  difference  of  taste,  etc.,  arising 
primarily  from  differences  of  country,  would  be  perfectly  nor 
mal  and  necessary  [Acts  xvii,  26].  As  the  mountaineer  is 
different  in  his  entire  bodily  and  spiritual  temper  from  the 
dweller  in  the  plain,  the  inhabitant  of  the  North  from  him  of 
the  Tropics,  etc.,  so  there  arises  therefrom  a  diversity  of  forms 
of  the  moral  lif^-work, — which,  however,  cannot  come  into 
hostile  antagonism  with  each  other,  but  in  fact  constitute  a 
stimulating  diversity,  from  which  arises  an  all  the  greater  and 
more  vital  harmony  of  the  whole.  Labor  and  enjoyment,  the 
family-life  and  the  life  of  society,  will  necessarily  assume  dif 
ferent  forms ;  and  the  proper  development  and  preservation 
of  the  normal  peculiarities  of  nations  form  an  essential  feat 
ure  of  general  moral  perfection.  It  is  not  as  a  progress  of 
spiritual  and  moral  culture,  but  to  some  extent  as  a  perver 
sion  thereof,  that  we  must  regard  the  tendency  manifested  in 
recent  times  to  sweep  away,  to  a  large  extent,  the  peculiarities 
of  nations,  and  to  bring  about  the  greatest  possible  uniformity. 
Manifoldness  of  language  and  spirit  is  not  confusion,  and  it 
has,  as  opposed  to  a  bald,  lifeless  monotony,  its  legitimate 
moral  right.  The  sons  of  Jacob,  as  differing  in  character, 
imparted  also  a  normal  difference  to  the  tribes  in  Israel ; 
nevertheless  one  spirit  could  and  should  have  pervaded  them 
all. 

SECTION  LXIX. 

3.  The  difference  of  sex  conditions  a  correspond 
ingly  different  peculiarity  of  the  moral  life-work. 
Man  represents  the  out  ward- working,  productive 
phase  of  humanity,  woman  the  receptive  and  forma 
tive, — he  more  the  spirit-phase,  she  more  the  nature- 
phase  ;  in  him  preponderate  thought  and  will ;  in 
her  rather  the  feelings,  the  heart;  to  man  it  is 
more  peculiar  to  act  initiatively, — to  woman  rather, 
morally  to  associate  herself.  The  moral  life-work  of 
each  is  different  in  the  details,  but  in  both  it  is  of 
like  dignity;  it  is  sinrply  two  different  mutually- 
complementing  phases  of  the  %anie  morality.  The 


§69.]  PUEE   ETHICS.  75 

morality  of  both  sexes  consists,  in  fact,  in  especially 
developing  that  phase  of  the  moral  life  that  is 
peculiar  to  each, — not  as  strictly  the  same  as,  but  as 
in  harmony  with,  the  peculiarity  of  the  other. 

The  antithesis  of  the  two  sexes  is  the  highest  spiritualized 
manifestation  of  that  primitive  antithesis  of  the  operative  and 
the  reposing,  the  active  and  the,  passive,  that  conditions  all 
earthly  life, — that  assumes  an  endless  variety  of  forms,  and 
appears  in  .each  single  phenomenon  of  the  world  under  some 
of  its  many  forms  of  combination.  Nowhere  do  we  find  mere 
force,  nowhere  mere  matter,  but  every-where  in  nature  both 
are  united ;  and  yet  they  are  not  the  same.  "What  this 
primitive  antithesis  is  in  nature, — what  the  greater  antitheses 
of  the  light  and  the  heavy,  repulsion  and  attraction,  motion 
and  rest,  sun  and  planet,  animal  and  plant,  arteries  and  veins, 
etc.,  are, — this  is,  in  highest  refinement  and  perfection,  the  an 
tithesis  of  man  and  woman  in  humanity.  That  the  nature- 
phase  is  somewhat  more  prominent  in  woman  than  in  man  is. 
evidenced  also  by  the  earlier  physical  development  and 
maturity  of  the  female  sex,  and  by  the  greater  dependence  on 
nature  and  on  the  changes  of  the  seasons  in  the  entire  female 
sex-life.  The  higher  intellectual  power  is  undoubtedly  with 
man,  and  the  moral  subordination  of  woman  to  man  in  wed 
lock  and  in  society  is  an  unmistakable  law  of  universal  order. 
The  difference  of  the  two  sexes  is  not  to  be  toned  down,  but 
to  be  developed  into  moral  harmony.  As  an  effeminate  man 
or  masculine  woman  is  offensive  to  the  esthetic  sense,  and  a 
hermaphrodite  repugnant  to  uncorrupted  feelings,  and  a  sex 
less  form  expressionless  and  unnatural,  so  also,  in  moral  re 
spects,  it  is  the  duty  of  man  to  cultivate  his  manliness,  and  of 
woman  to  cultivate  her  womanliness ;  and  any  assumption  by 
one  party  of  the  peculiarities  of  the  opposite  sex,  is  not  only 
unnatural  but  also  immoral. 


76  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  70. 

H.    THE  COMMUNITY-LIFE  AS  A  MORAL  SUBJECT. 

SECTION  LXX. 

Man  is  not  simply  an  individual  being,  but,  by 
virtue  of  his  moral  rationality,  which  seeks  every 
where  to  reduce  the  manifold  to  unity,  he  effects  also 
a  moral  community-life,  a  community  of  persons,  to 
which  the  individual  is  related  as  a  serving  member, 
and  which  has  in  turn  itself  a  definite  moral  life- 
purpose,  to  the  fulfilling  of  which  the  individual 
members  are  indeed  called,  though  this  moral  life- 
purpose,  that  is  to  be  carried  out  by  the  individual, 
is  not  identical  with  the  life-work  which  he,  as  a 
personal  individual,  has  to  fulfill  for  himself.  A 
plurality  of  persons  constitutes  a  moral  community- 
life  only  when,  in  virtue  of  a  real  common-conscious 
ness,  and  a  common  moral  life-purpose,  they  are 
molded  into  a  life-unity,  so  that  the  individual 
members  bring  not  only  the  whole  into  active  rela 
tion  to  themselves,  but  also  and  essentially  themselves 
into  active  relation  to  the  whole;  and  the  moral  life 
of  the  individual  is  the  more  perfect  the  more  it 
develops  itself  into  a  life  of  the  whole ;  and  the  ulti 
mate  goal  of  moral  development  is,  that  all  humanity 
become  a  unitary  moral  community.  The  true 
morality  of  the  individual  assumes  therefore  always 
a  twofold  form :  one  that  is  personally-individual,  and1 
one  that  is  an  expression  of  the  moral  life-purpose  of 
the  community-life,  and  in  the  name  of  which  it  ful 
fills  that  purpose ;  neither  is  subordinate  to  the 
other,  but  they  stand  in  vital  reciprocity  of  relation. 

The  notion  of  the  community-life  as  a  moral  subject  is  of 
very  great  significance  for  ethics.  Heathenism  attained  to  it 
but  very  imperfectly,  inasmuch  as  the  thought  of  the  unity  of 


§  70.]  PURE  ETHICS.  77 

mankind  was  entirely  wanting,  and  as  where  the  community- 
life  was  most  prominent — in  China — there  only  a  naturalistic, 
mechanical  world-theory  prevailed,  and  as,  on  the  contrary, 
where  the  personal  spirit  came  into  prominence — in  the  Occi 
dent — there  it  did  so  only  in  the  form  of  the  strong  individual 
will, — that  is,  the  will  did  not  appear  as  general  but  as  indi 
vidual  and  arbitrary,  so  that  the  community-life  itself  bore 
the  impress  of  the  individual  will.  In  the  Israelitic  theocracy 
we  find,  in  virtue  of  the  divine  disciplinary  purpose,  only 
the  embryonic  beginnings  of  the  community-life ;  as  yet, 
the  morality  of  the  individual  prevails  over  the  collective 
morality.  But  to  the  idea  of  the  latter  itself  there  is  very 
clear  allusion.  The  words,  "I  will  make  of  thee  a  great 
nation;  ...  in  thee  shall  all  families  of  the  earth  be 
blessed"  [Gen.  xii,  2,  3],  are  not  a  mere  blessing,  but  they 
imply  also  for  Abraham  ^i  moral  duty,  namely,  that  he  live 
not  for  himself,  but  also  for  his  people,  and  through  them  for 
the  whole  race, — that  he  work  and  act  not  merely  as  Abram 
but  as  Abraham,  as  the  father  of  nations  [Gen.  xvii,  5]. 
Christianity  brought  the  great  idea  to  realization ;  the  truth 
that  makes  man  truly  free  rendered  again  possible  the  found 
ing  of  a  true  moral  community, — primarily  as  the  Church,  but 
then  also  as  the  Christian  state.  The  idea  of  moral  com 
munion  becomes  here  at  once  a  fundamental  one.  Personal 
communion  with  the  personal  Son  of  God  and  of  Man  as  chief, 
creates  the  true,  vital  moral  community-life;  the  individual 
lives  for  the  community  and  the  community  for  the  individual, 
and  both  through  Christ  and  for  Christ.  This  circumstance 
is  very  suggestive  as  to  the  moral  destination  of  humanity  as 
sinless. 

The  moral  activity  of  the  individual  person  as  such  is 
clearly  to  be  distinguished  from  the  moral  activity  of  the 
same  as  an  embodiment  of  the  public  morality.  The  mere 
circumstance,  that  in  a  state  of  sinfulness  these  two  forms  of 
morality  may  appear  in  antithesis  and  contradiction— that  a 
man  may  perform  his  duty  as  a  citizen  to  a  certain  degree  of 
serviceableness,  while  his  personal  morality  stands  very  low — 
shows  that  in  the  thing  itself  there  is  a  real  difference.  What 
I  do  as  a  vital  member  of  the  moral  community — as  it  were 
out  of  the  spirit  of  the  same,  and  to  some  extent,  in  the  name 


78  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  TO. 

of  and  as  representing  the  same,  that  is,  what  I  do,  not  because 
I  am  a  moral  individual,  but  because  I  belong,  as  a  part,  to  a 
moral  community, — that  must  of  course,  under  circumstances 
of  moral  maturity,  be  in  entire  harmony  with  my  personal 
moral  disposition ;  but  harmony  is  not  identity.  As  repre 
senting  the  moral  community-life  and  the  common  conscious 
ness,  my  personal  individual  will  retires  essentially  into  the 
back-ground,  and  the  public  spirit  possesses  me  and  guides 
me, — rules  sovereignly  in  me,  and  thrusts  aside  even  my 
otherwise  legitimate  individual  weal.  The  warrior,  in  fight 
ing  for  his  country,  acts  not  from  his  personal  individual  will ; 
he  seeks,  in  case  he  enters  into  it  morally,  nothing  for  him 
self,  but  every  thing  solely  for  his  country ;  he  sacrifices  his 
personal  right  to  domestic  happiness,  to  quiet  labor,  to  legiti 
mate  enjoyments,  and  even  his  life  itself,  for  the  community, 
— not  as  a  personal  individual,  btft  as  a  vital  member  of  the 
nation.  The  morality  of  the  individual  bears  more  a  mas 
culine,  that  of  the  community  more  a  feminine  character,  in 
asmuch  as  in  the  latter  case  there  is  a  predominancy  of  yield 
ing  to  influence,  of  self-associating,  of  devotion  even  to 
sacrifice.  The  moral  honor  of  a  community  is  other  than  that 
of  the  individual ;  when  the  soldier  defends  the  flag  of  his 
regiment,  it  is  not,  or  should  not  be,  his  own  honor,  but  that 
of  the  entire  body,  that  prompts  him;  and  where  there  is 
honor,  there  there  is  also  morality. 

The  distinction  of  this  twofold  morality  presents  itself, 
under  one  of  the  special  forms  of  the  second  phase,  namely, 
official  morality,  as  recognizable  also  outwardly.  What  the 
clergyman,  the  soldier,  the  judge  does  officially,  is  also 
morality,  but  it  is  not  by  any  means  identical  with  his  personal 
morality,  as  is  shown  even  by  the  fact  of  the  different  degrees 
of  censure  incurred  for  violations  of  duty  in  the  two  spheres.* 
An  untruth,  a  deception,  perpetrated  in  official  activity,  is 
much  more  severely  punished,  and  deserves  also  severer  moral 
rebuke,  than  a  like  act  done  in  non-official  life.  He  who  is 
acting  in  a  public  capacity  is  not  at  liberty  to  overlook  an 
offered  indignity,  while  his  very  first  duty  when  insulted  in  a 
private  capacity,  is,  to  manifest  a  readiness  for  reconciliation. 
The  moral  community  often  expresses  this  difference  in  the 
fact  that  those  who  act  principally  and  professionally  in  its 


§70.]  PURE  ETHICS.  79 

name,  wear  a  special  official  garb,  so  that  the  entire  external 
appearance  and  bearing  of  such  public  persons  are  not  gov 
erned  merely  by  their  personally  free  self-determination,  but 
bear  the  impress  of  that  which  transcends  the  individual  will, 
namely,  the  community-life ;  personal  character,  while  realiz 
ing  public  morality,  falls  back  behind  the  character  of  the 
community-life.  Nevertheless  it  is  true  that  the  whole  moral 
activity  and  life  of  the  individual  contributes  essentially  to 
the  honor  or  shame  of  the  family  and  of  the  community  to 
which  he  belongs  [Lev.  xxi,  9],  so  that  consequently  this  dis 
tinction  of  a  twofold  moral  sphere  of  activity  does  not  amount 
to  a  real  separation. 


80  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  Tl. 


CHAPTER  II. 

GOD  AS  THE  GROUND  AND  PROTOTYPE  OF  THE  MORAL 
LIFE  AND  AS  THE  AUTHOR  OF  THE  LAW. 

SECTION  LXXI. 

As  morality  is  connected  with  religion  in  an  indis- 
solubly  vital  unity,  hence  the  God-consciousness  is 
the  necessary  presupposition  and  condition  of  mo 
rality,  and  the  character  and  degree  of  the  morality 
is  consequently  also  conditioned  on  the  character  and 
degree  of  the  God-consciousness,  although  a  higher 
degree  of  the  latter  does  not  necessarily  work  also  a 
higher  degree  of  morality.  Hence  true  morality  is 
only  there  possible  where  there  is  a  true  God- 
consciousness,  that  is,  where  God  is  not  conceived 
of  as  in  some  manner  limited,  but  as  the  infinite 
Spirit  in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  word.  Only  where 
the  moral  idea  has  its  absolutely  perfect  reality,  in 
the  personal  holy  God,  has  morality  a  firm  basis,  true 
contents,  and  an  unconditional  goal. 

If  morality  is  in  any  manner  conditioned  by  religion,  then 
is  also  the  quality  of  this  morality  different  in  different  re 
ligions.  We  have  already  shown  that  morality  is  not  condi 
tioned  by  the  mere  God-consciousness,  but  only  by  it  as 
having  grown  into  religion,  for  a  God-consciousness  which 
does  not  become  a  religious  one,  but  remains  mere  knowl 
edge,  cannot  become  a  moral  power ;  and  this  is  the  simple 
explanation  of  the  fact,  that  while  a  feebler  God-consciousness 
cannot  produce  a  higher  degree  of  morality,  yet  a  higher 
God-consciousness  does  not  necessarily  create  also  a  higher 
degree  of  morality, — namely,  when  it  does  not  develop  itself 


§71.]  PURE  ETHICS.  81 

into  a  religious  life-power.  When  it  does  so  develop  itself, 
however,  then  it  is  unconditionally  true  that  the  degree  of 
morality  perfectly  corresponds  to  the  degree  of  God-con 
sciousness; — otherwise  we  would  be  forced  to  modify  our 
previously  assumed  position,  that  religion  and  morality  are 
two  indissolubly  united  and  mutually  absolutely  conditioning 
phases  of  one  and  the  same  spiritual  life.  Where  God  is 
conceived  of  as  merely  an  unspiritual  nature-force,  as  in 
China  and  India,  there  morality  cannot  rest  on  the  free  moral 
personality  of  man,  but,  on  the  contrary,  it  must  throw  the 
personality  into  the  back-ground  as  illegitimate ;  where  the 
divine  is  conceived  of  only  in  the  form  of  an  antagonism  of 
mutually  hostile  divinities,  as  with  the  Persians,  there  the 
moral  idea  lacks  its  unconditional  obligatoriness,  and  in  fact 
the  contra-moral  has  its  relative  justification;  and  where  the 
divine  is  conceived  of  as  a  plurality  of  limited  individual 
personalities,  there  the  sphere  of  morality  is  invaded  by  the 
pretensions  of  the  arbitrarily  self-determining  subject,  and 
moral  action  lacks  a  solid  basis.  It  is  only  where  there  is  a 
consciousness  of  the  infinite  personal  Spirit  that  both  the 
moral  personality  is  free,  and  the  moral  idea  absolutely  un 
conditional  and  sure.  The  heathen  do  not  really  have  the 
divine  law;  they  have  only,  lying  in  the  very  nature  of  the 
rational  spirit,  an  unconscious  presentiment  of  the  same 
[Rom.  ii,  14,  15]. — Though  Polytheism  is  with  us  no  longer 
in  fashion,  still  we  are  all  the  more  infested  with  Pantheism, 
or  such  a  form  of  Deism  as  differs  therefrom  only  by  an 
unscientific  arbitrary  inconsequence, — not,  however,  by  any 
means  with  that  vigorous  and  comparatively  respectable 
Pantheism  of  India  which  drew,  with  moral  earnestness,  the 
full  practical  consequence  of  its  world-theory,  and  presented 
in  an  actually-carried-out  renunciation  of  the  world  the  very 
contrary  of  our  natural  and  legitimate  claim  to  happiness, — 
but,  on  the  contrary,  with  a  Pantheism  that  is  in  every 
respect  morbid  and  characterless,  and  which,  greedy  of  en 
joyment,  delights  itself  in  a  world  robbed  of  God.  Pan 
theism  lacks  the  antecedent  condition  of  all  morality,  namely, 
personal  freedom ;  with  the  universal  prevalence  of  uncondi 
tional  necessity  there  is  no  place  for  choice  and  self-deter 
mination  ;  it  also  lacks  a  moral  purpose,  seeing  that  it  knows 
VOL.  II— 7 


82  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  72. 

no  ideal,  reality-transcending  goal  of  morality,  but,  on  the 
contrary,  must  acknowledge  the  real  as  per  se  the  fulfillment 
.  of  the  ideal,  that  is,  as  good, — and  for  the  reason  that  that 
which  appears  as  a  goal  of  life-development,  is,  in  fact, 
realized  from  necessity ;  it  lacks  also  a  moral  motive,  for  the 
sole  causative  ground  of  the  absolutely  necessary  life-develop 
ment  is,  as  unfree  and  as  unfreely-acting,  non-moral, — is  only 
a  conscious  nature-impulse.  On  the  assumption  that  the 
entire  being  and  activity  of  the  individual  is  simply  a  neces 
sary  expression  of  the  existence  and  life  which  God  generates 
for  himself  in  the  world,  it  follows  that  each  and  every  being 
is  fully  and  perfectly  justified  in  whatever  nature  and  activity 
he  may  chance  to  appear,  and  no  one  can  reproach  another 
because  of  any  seeming  moral  depravity.  The  moral  ten 
dencies  of  Pantheism,  and  of  the  therewith  essentially  iden 
tical  Naturalism,  must  not  be  judged  of  from  individual  in 
stances  of  men  who  are  still  unconsciously  imbued  with  the 
moral  spirit  of  the  community,  but  lather  from  the  effects 
that  result  where  this  world-theory  has  taken  hold  on  the 
mousey,  — as  at  the  time  of  the  Ileign  of  Terror  in  France,  and 
in  the  bearing  and  aspirations  of  our  more  recent  demagogues 
of  reform,  nearly  all  of  whom  are  imbued  with  Pantheistic 
views. 

SECTION  LXXII. 

The  personal  God  is  the  basis  of  the  moral,  (1)  in 
that  He,  as  holy  will,  is  the  eternal  fountain  and  em 
bodiment  of  the  moral  idea.  The  good  is  not  a  mere 
object  of  a  possible  willing,  not  merely  ought  to  be 
willed,  but  is  eternally  willed  by  an  eternal  will,  and 
is  nothing  other  than  the  contents  of  this  will  itself; 
God  is  the  absolutely  moral  spirit,  the  holy  spirit — 
perfectly  at  one  with  himself  in  his  free  personality, 
and  eternally  self-consistent, — and  who  as  such 
guarantees  to  the  moral  life-task  of  his  free  creatures, 
full  truth,  unconditional  and  permanent  validity  as 
God's  requirement,  and  unshaken  certainty,  and 
perfect,  constant  unity  and  consistency. 


§72.]  PURE   ETHICS.  83 

Outside  of  the  Christian  God-consciousness  the  moral  idea 
lacks  all  certainty  and  strength.  It  is  easy  to  say,  that  we 
should  do  the  good  for  its  own  sake,  that  the  moral  law  pre 
sents  itself  as  a  "categorical  imperative,"  but  in  the  reality  of 
life  such  generalities  will  not  avail.  For  a  mere  idea  without 
any  sort  of  reality,  no  human  heart  can  grow  actively  warm ; 
here  there  is  at  best  only  an  intellectual  interest,  but  not  a 
morally-practical  one.  The  validity  of  the  moral  idea  must 
have  a  deeper  basis  than  a  mere  intellectual  process.  Before 
I  can  do  the  good  for  its  own  sake,  I  must  love  it ;  before  I 
love  it,  I  must  with  full  certainty  know  it.  So  long  as  I  am  in 
doubt  as  to  what  is  good,  or  as  to  whether  there  is  any  good, 
I  have  no  object  of  love.  The  essence  of  the  good,  however, 
implies  that  the  same  is  not  my  merely  subjective  opinion, 
but  that  it  is  universally  valid — good  per  se.  Now,  should  I 
leave  the  God-consciousness  out  of  sight,  then  there  would 
remain  for  me,  in  order  to  determine  the  unconditional 
validity  of  a  supposed  moral  precept,  and  to  avoid  the  possi 
bility  of  a  mere  arbitrary  judgment,  no  other  resort  than  the 
impracticable  test  of  Kant.*  Suppose,  however,  that,  apart 
from  religious  faith,  there  were  in  fact  a  scientific  source  for 
a  certain  knowledge  of  the  moral  law,  still  this  would  not  yet 
answer  the  purpose ; — not  every  one  can  be  a  philosopher,  but 
all  are  required  to  be  moral.  Hence  the  moral  consciousness 
cannot  be  based  on  mere  scientific  demonstrations,  but  must 
have  a  basis  available  for  all  rational  men;  now  just  such  a 
resource  is  the  God-consciousness.  So  soon  as  I  know  that  a 
mode  of  action  is  God's  will,  then  am  I  perfectly  certain  that 
it  is  good,  that  it  has  universal  and  unconditional  validity ; — 
I  have  not  to  infer  that  because  it  is  universally  valid,  there 
fore  it  is  God's  will,  but  the  converse.  Without  certainty  of 
moral  consciousness  there  can  be  no  moral  confidence ;  in  this 
connection  all  doubt  works  ruin.  The  question  is  as  to  cer 
tainty  of  moral  consciousness,  and  hence  essentially  as  to 
God's  will's  becoming  known  to  me. 

So  soon  as  there  exists  a  consciousness  of  God,  all  good 
must  be  referred  absolutely  to  God's  will;  whatever  God 
wills  is  good,  and  whatever  is  good  is  God's  will.  The 

*  Namely:  "Act  so  that  the  maxim  of  thy  conduct  shall  be 
adapted  to  become  a  universal  law  for  all  men." 


84  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  72. 

divine  order  of  the  world  assumes,  in  the  sphere  of  the  free 
will  of  creatures,  the  form  of  a  moral  command ;  the  "must  " 
becomes  a  "should;"  this  is  not  a  lowering,  but  an  exalting 
of  the  law,  for  freely  realized  good  is  higher  than  the  un- 
freely  realized,  seeing  that  God  himself  is  freedom.  If  a 
moral  duty  is  God's  will,  then  I  am  also  further  certain  that 
it  cannot  be  in  real  conflict  with  other  moral  duties.  This  is 
the  high  moral  significancy  of  faith  in  the  living  God,  namely, 
that  it  alone  can  give  a  full  unity  and  certainty  to  the  moral 
consciousness ;  with  every  limitation  of  the  idea  of  God  the 
moral  consciousness  also  becomes  uncertain  and  doubtful. 
Hence  the  Scriptures,  even  in  the  Old  Testament,  attribute 
such  high  significancy  to  the  unity  and  unchangeableness  of 
the  holy  and  almighty  God  as  moral  law-giver,  and  base 
thereon,  in  contrast  to  heathenism,  all  morality, — as,  for  ex 
ample,  in  Gen.  xvii,  1 ;  Deut.  vi,  4  sqq.  ;  x,  14,  17.  In  the 
first  passage  God's  omnipotence  is  emphasized  in  order  to 
awaken  in  man  a  consciousness  of  his  dependence ;  inasmuch 
as  all  existence  is  absolutely  in  God's  hand,  therefore  should 
also  man's  free  activity  subordinate  itself  to  Him, — therefore 
also  is  the  sinful  effort  to  be  independent  of  God,  that  is,  to 
be  equal  to  God,  unmitigated  folly.  Hence  also  he,  who 
walks  before  the  Almighty,  has  the  assurance  that  he  will 
attain  to  his  goal ;  thou  canst,  for  the  reason  that  tliou 
shouldst,  for  it  is  God  who  places  upon  thee  the  "  should." 

But  the  certainty  of  the  moral  idea  is  only  one  of  its 
phases,  the  other  is  its  actuating  power.  It  is  true,  the  idea 
itself  of  the  good  should  move  the  will;  but  its  power  is  im 
measurably  greater  when  it  is  itself  the  expression  of  a  holy 
will  than  when  it  merely  speaks  to  the  human  will.  It  is  the 
sacred  awe  of  the  Holy  One  that  lends  it  this  power.  In  a 
mere  idea  I  can  have  pleasure,  but  it  cannot  inspire  me  with 
awe.  The  command  that  emanates  from  the  Living  One, 
gives  life;  a  mere  idea pre-supposes  life  as  a  condition  of  its 
efficacy.  The  moral  idea  becomes  truly  influential  on  the 
personal  spirit  only  by  its  being  the  actual  will  of  a  personal 
God.  "The  statutes  of  the  Lord  are  right,  rejoicing  the 
heart;  the  commandment  of  the  Lord  is  pure,  enlightening 
the  eyes"  [Psa.  xix,  8J. 

The  question :  is  a  thing  good  because  God  wills  it,  or  does 


§  73.]  PURE  ETHICS.  85 

God  will  it  because  it  is  good  ?  contains  for  us  no  contra 
diction.  It  would  do  so,  however,  if  the  first  clause  meant, 
that  it  is  accidental  and  arbitrary  that  God  declares  this  or 
that  to  be  good,  and  that  He  might  also  just  as  well  have 
declared  good  the  very  opposite  (Duns  Scotus,  Occam,  Des 
cartes,  Pufendorf).  God  cannot  will  anything  else  than 
what  is  God-like — corresponding  to  his  nature ;  this  ' '  can 
not  "  is  a  limitation  only  in  the  form  of  expression,  in  reality 
it  is  the  highest  perfection.  A  being  that  can  come  into  con 
tradiction  and  antagonism  with  itself,  is  not  perfect.  If  the 
good  is  that  which  corresponds  to  the  divine  nature,  and  if 
God's  will  is  necessarily  an  expression  of  his  nature,  then, 
whatever  is  good  is  good  because  God  wills  it,  and  God  wills 
it  because  it  is  good.  God's  declaration :  "I  am  that  I  am" 
[Exod.  iii,  14]  is  valid  also  for  his  holy  volitions.  The  idea  of 
the  good  is  not  something  existing  without  and  apart  from 
God,  it  is  a  direct  beam  from  his  inner  nature. 

SECTION  LXX1II. 

God  is  the  basis  of  the  moral,  (2),  in  that  He  re 
veals  himself  in  his  universe  as  the  Holy  One, — dis 
covers  himself  to  man  as  the  prototype  of  the  moral, 
as  the  personally  holy  pattern  after  which  man  should 
form  himself.  In  this  consciousness  of  God  as  pro 
totype  of  the  moral,  man  conceives  morality  as  God- 
likeness,  and  himself,  in  his  true  moral  dignity,  as 
God's  image  and  as  a  child  of  God. 

The  idea  of  a  moral  self-revelation  of  God  is  of  wide- 
reaching  moral  significancy.  Heathenism  knows  nothing  of 
such  a  self-revelation ;  it  is  true,  in  the  higher  heathen  relig 
ions,  moral  laws  are  referred  to  a  divine  origin,  but  this  sig 
nifies  simply  either  a  revelation  of  the  general  laws  of  world- 
order,  or,  at  best,  a  revelation  of  the  divine  will  in  regard  to 
men,  but  not  of  the  real  moral  nature  of  God.  According  to 
the  Christian  world- view,  the  good  is  not  merely  to  ~be  realized, 
but  it  exists  already  in  full  reality  from  eternity ;  morality  is 
not  to  create  something  absolutely  new,  but  only  to  shape  the 


86  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  73. 

created  after  the  model  of  its  divine  Creator;  the  free  creature 
is  to  become  like  the  holy  God, — to  come  into  free  harmony, 
not  simply  with  a  naked  idea  but  with  an  eternal  reality. 
As  a  consequence  of  this,  morality  has  an  incomparably  higher 
certainty  and  vitality  than  if  the  moral  law  appeared  merely 
under  the  form  of  an  idea.  There  can  be  no  more  convincing 
logic  than  the  word :  "Ye  shall  be  holy,  for- 1  the  Lord  your 
God  am  holy "  [Lev.  xix,  2 ;  xi,  44,  45 ;  xx,  7 ;  comp.  Deut. 
x,  17  sqq.  ;  I  Pet.  i,  15,  16;  Eph.  v,  1];  and  Christ  himself 
repeatedly  presents  the  moral  essence  of  God  as  the  true  pat 
tern  for  man,  both  in  general  and  in  particular  [Matt,  v,  48 ; 
Luke  vi,  36].  Even  as  in  education  there  is  no  better  moral 
instruction  than  that  by  personal  example,  so  is  there  also  in 
the  moral  education  of  humanity  no  more  deeply  influential 
moral  revelation  than  that  of  the  holy  personality  of  God ;  and 
as  the  child  naturally  seeks  not  so  much  to  realize  a  lifeless 
law  as  to  become  like  a  beloved  and  revered  personal  example, 
so  is  it  likewise  the  case  in  the  moral  development  of  humanity 
in  general ;  and  this  is  not  childlike  immaturity,  but  rational 
truth ;  and  herein  also  is  the  child  a  proper  example.  In  real 
izing  morality  man  does  not  present  himself  in  the  All  as  a 
solitarily-shining  star,  but  as  a  God-loved  and  God-loving 
image  of  the  invisible  God, — as  a  human  resplendence  of  His 
holiness. 

A  much  deeper  impression  than  that  made  by  the  revelation 
of  the  holy  personality  of  God  through  speech,  is  made  by 
the  revelation  of  the  same  by  actual  reality  in  the  person  of 
Christ.  We  cannot  answer  here  the  oft  proposed  question  as 
to  whether  the  Son  of  God  would  have  become  man  even  had 
not  sin  entered  into  the  world ;  the  Scriptures  give  us  on  this 
point  no  decision;  and  even  those  who  affirm  it  do  not  place 
the  advent  of  the  perfect  man  at  the  beginning  of  the  race. 
Hence,  even  in  this  view,  the  coining  of  Christ  is  not  held  as 
a  necessary  condition  of  the  moral  life.  But  as  Christ  is  in 
fact  not  merely  the  Redeemer  suffering  for  and  through  sin, 
but  also  the  true  personal  manifestation  of  the  perfect  image 
of  God — the  absolutely  perfect  prototype  of  human  morality, — 
hence,  far  «s,  who  are  no  longer  in  the  condition  of  original 
sinlcssness,  the  knowledge  of  pure  morality  is  essentially  con 
ditioned  on  a  knowledge  of  Christ.  The  first  sin-free  human 


§-74.j  PURE  ETHICS.  87 

beings  needed  not  this  historically-personal  example  in  order 
to  have  a  truthful  moral  consciousness,  and  to  be  able  to 
realize  morality ;  but  we  need  it — we  who  have  had  to  be  re 
deemed  from  the  curse  and  power  of  sin ;  we  need,  also  as  a 
help  to  a  knowledge  of  the  morality  of  unfallen  man,  this 
example  that  did  not  rise  out  of  sin  but  stood  above  it.  In  a 
much  higher  degree,  in  fact,  than  Christ  is  the  example  for  the 
redeemed,  is  he  the  true  criterion  for  a  knowledge  of  unfallen 
human  nature;  for  there  is  much  in  the  moral  life  of  the 
Christian  for  which  Christ's  own  life  cannot  be  a  direct  ex 
ample  ;  for  instance,  the  continuous  struggle  against  the  still- 
remaining  sin  in  the  human  heart, — in  Christ  there  was  no 
such  struggle ;  to  him  every  tiling  that  was  sinful  was  foreign 
and  external,  but  never  inward  and  personal.  On  the  con 
trary,  there  could  be  nothing  in  the  moral  life  of  unfallen 
man  which  could  not  be  directly  connected  with  the  person  of 
Christ,  though  indeed,  not  all  the  special  phases  of  human 
morality  could  have  their  particular  expression  in  the  life  of 
Christ.  Thus  we  have  occasion  here  to  make  at  least  allu 
sion  to  Christ. 

SECTION  LXXIV. 

God  is  the  basis  of  the  moral,  (3),  in  that,  omni- 
presently  ruling  and  judging  in  his  universe,  He 
wisely,  lovingly,  arid  justly  guides  and  furthers 
toward  its  eternal  goal  the  moral  life  of  his  creatures, 
without,  however,  interfering  with  their  moral  free 
dom.  This  consciousness  gives  to  the  moral  life  full 
confidence  and  joy  in  the  fulfillment  of  the  divine 
will,  and  the  proper  fear  of  all  that  is  ungodly. 

The  thought  of  a  merely  impersonal  moral  world-ordei  may 
seem  in  itself  simple  and  attractive ;  for  real  life,  however,  it 
is  of  no  efficiency.  Even  the  proud  equanimity  of  the  Stoic 
is  unable  definitively  to  find  any  better  remedy  for  the  antag 
onism  of  the  reality  of  existence  with  his  self-conceived 
ideals,  than  suicide ;  and  those  who,  in  recent  times,  assum 
ing  that  the  Christian  world-view  is  gloomy  and  unhumani- 
tarian,  prefer  to  it  the  domination  of  eternal  impersonal 


88  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  74. 

necessity,  and  explain  away  all  evil  and  anarchy  as  mere 
appearance,  gain  after  all  from  this  pretended  self-explaining 
and  all-reconciling  view,  little  other  profit  than  a  complacent 
satisfaction  with  themselves  and  with  their  own  system.  So 
long  as  man  cannot  rid  himself  of  his  consciousness  of  free 
dom  and  of  the  possibility  of 'its  misuse,  as  well  as  of  his 
consciousness  of  the  reality  of  evil  in  the  world,  just  so  long- 
will  the  notion  of  a  world-order  unembodied  in  a  personal 
God  prove  to  be  powerless.  The  Greek  had  a  much  higher 
world-theory  than  that  of  ordinary  Pantheism,  and  yet  he 
could  not  explain  away  the  antagonism  that  exists  between 
the  moral  life  and  non-moral  fate,  or  the  excess  of  real  evil ; 
and  he  gave  utterance,  in  his  noblest  intellectual  productions, 
either  to  a  melancholy  lament  over  the  mysterious  tragedy  of 
life,  or  to  a  blank  hopelessness  as  to  the  triumph  of  the  good. 
Greek  tragedy  is,  by  far,  more  moral  than  the  anti- Christian 
Pantheism  of  recent  date.  To  feel  and  bewail  the  antago 
nism  of  existence  even  with  out-spoken  hopelessness,  approx 
imates  more  nearly  the  truth  than  to  explain  it  away  with 
delusive  sophistry.  In  a  world  where  the  misuse  of  moral 
freedom  may  create  evil  and  disturb  the  harmony  of  exist 
ence,  there  can  be  hopefulness  and  confidence  in  moral  effort 
only  in  virtue  of  a  firm  faith  in  the  personally-ruling  almighty 
and  holy  God ;  without  this  there  is  for  {he  rational  spirit  no 
possibility  of  an  unshaken  conviction  that  a  truly  moral  con 
duct  will,  in  fact,  bring  real  fruit,  and  not  prove  to  be  a  use 
less  vain  undertaking,  an  empty  play  of  a  restless  activity- 
instinct. — We  are  here  as  yet  not  dealing  with  a  world  actually 
disordered  by  sin ;  but  also  for  the  unfallen  state  all  moral 
effort  becomes  impossible,  becomes  even  idle  folly,  so  soon  as 
we  assume  even  the  possibility  of  a  disturbance  of  the  har 
mony  of  the  world, — unless  there  exists  at  tiie  same  time  the 
consciousness  of  a  holy  God  freely  ruling  Move  all  creature- 
life,  and  conducting  the  moral  order  of  the  universe.  But 
the  possibility  of  sucli  a  disturbance  through  the  misuse  of 
freedom,  is  directly  implied  in  the  idea  of  freedom.  Hence 
the  notion  of  a  merely  general  world-order  without  a  per 
sonally-ruling  God  does  not  suffice,  even  for  the  unfallen 
state,  to  give  to  moral  effort  the  necessary  confidence.  The 
question  is  here  as  to  a  certainty  not  merely  that  the  moral 


§  74.]  •         PURE  ETHICS.  89 

efforts  of  the  individual  will  bear  the  expected  fruit  for  him 
self. — though  we  must  consider  this  also  as  a  perfectly  legiti 
mate  claim, — but  also,  in  general,  that  his  moral  efforts  will 
not  be  in  vain  for  the  furtherance  of  the  perfection  of  the 
whole, — will  not  be  counteracted  by  the  possibly  interfering 
power  of  evil.  Without  the  confidence  that  by  virtue  of  the 
all-potent  wisdom  of  the  personal  God,  all  truly  moral  effort 
will  bear  legitimate  fruit,  and  that  evil  can  never  prevent  him 
who  continues  faithful,  from  reaching  the  last  and  highest 
goal  of  the  moral,  and  that  consequently  the  anarchy  that 
evil  brings  into  the  world  will  fall  only  on  the  heads  of  the 
evil-doers,  while  even  the  ' '  prince  of  this  world  "  can  effect 
nothing  against  the  just  [John  xiv,  30], — without  this  confi 
dence,  the  courage  and  vitality  of  all  morality  are  paralyzed. 
Also  in  the  unfallen  state  human  knowledge  must  still  be 
limited, — must  be  unable  to  see  into  the  ultimate  depths  and 
ends  of  existence,  and  least  of  all  into  the  future.  Hence, 
without  confidence  there  is  no  means  of  rising  above  doubt  as 
to  the  success  of  moral  effort,  and  consequently  also  of  a 
degree  of  discouragement  in  the  same.  The  true  moral  cour 
age  is  not  a  blind  defiance  of  fate,  but  a  rejoicing  in  the  con 
sciousness  that  all  tilings  work  to  the  good  of  those  who  love 
God  [Rom.  vii,  28],  and  that  "in  Him  we  live  and  move  and 
have  our  being"  [Acts  xvii,  28], — that  God,  the  ground  and 
source  of  all  morality,  is  not  far  from  any  one  of  us,  but 
works  in  and  with  us  for  the  accomplishment  of  his  holy  will. 
— And  as  effort  for  the  good  can  be  potent  only  through  con 
fidence  in  God,  so  also  is  the  moral  dread  of  evil  effectual  only 
through  the  fear  of  God.  Not  as  if  a  mere  fear  of  punishment 
were  to  restrain  man  from  evil,  but  rather  a  holy  awe  of  the 
holy  and  all-knowing  God.  This  is  also  fear, — not,  however, 
slavish,  selfish  fear,  but  moral  reverence,  befitting  shame  in 
the  presence  of  the  pure  and  holy  One.  To  say  that  man 
should  shun  evil  even  irrespectively  of  God,  is  empty  talk; 
if  he  believes  in  God,  then  he  cannot  leave  Him  out  of  thought 
at  the  sight  of  evil ;  and  if  he  believes  not  in  God,  then  he 
believes  also  not  in  the  holiness  of  the  moral  command,  and 
he  will  in  fact  not  shun  the  evil, — he  will  simply  deny  it,  as 
modern  observation  proves.  The  fear  of  the  Lord  is  the 
beginning  of  wisdom,  and  also  of  morality  [Psa.  cxi,  10] ; 


90  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.      *  §75.] 

"fear  the  Lord  and  keep  his  commandments,"  says  the 
Preacher  [Eccles.  xii,  13] ;  this  is  the  fundamental  idea  of  mo 
rality  in  the  Old  Testament  [comp.  Dent,  x,  12,  13].  There  is 
one  Lawgiver  and  Judge  who  is  able  to  save  and  destroy 
[James  iv,  12]  ^  in  the  unity  of  the  lawgiver  and  judge  lies 
the  guarantee  and  holy  potency  of  morality.  Whoever  be 
lieves,  not  merely  in  an  All,  but  in  the  living  God,  and  knows 
that  all  that  is  hidden  from  human  eyes  is  known  to  the  all- 
knowing  One,  and  that  all  secret  sins  rest  under  the  curse  of 
Him  who  can  kill  and  make  alive,  who  can  wound  and  heal, 
and  out  of  whose  hand  there  is  none  that  can  deliver  [Deut. 
xxvii,  15  sqq.  ;  xxxii,  39], — such  a  one  will  evidently  have  a 
very  different  dread  of  evil  from  that  of  him  who  regards 
it  as  a  mere  world-inherent  necessary  transition-stage  to 
perfection. 

SECTION  LXXV. 

God  is  the  basis  of  the  moral,  (4),  in  that  as  holy 
Lawgiver  he  reveals  his  eternal,  holy  will  in  time. 
The  totality  of  created  being  is,  in  the  design  of 
the  creative  will,  to  be  in  harmony  with  God  and 
with  itself.  The  idea  of  this  harmony,  as  active  in 
God  under  the  form  of  will,  is  God's  law.  Unfree 
creatures  have  it  as  an  inner  necessity,  and  must 
fulfill  it ;  free  creatures  have  it  as  a  moral  command, 
and  should  fulfill  it ;  for  the  former  it  exists  as  an 
unconscious  instinct  or  impulse,  for  the  latter  it  is 
revealed ;  as  God's  law,  it  is  made  known  to  rational 
creatures  by  revelation.  The  moral  law  is  therefore 
the  revealed  will  of  God  as  to  the  rational  creature, 
—namely,  that  the  same  should  bring  its  entire  life, 
consciously  and  with  free  will,  into  harmony  with 
God's  purpose. 

A  law  which  cannot  be  derived  from  God's  will  is  not  a 
moral  law,  but  at  best  a  civil  one.  That  the  moral  law  is 
based  in  the  inner  essence  of  the  human  reason  is  not  contro 
verted  by  the  proposition,  that  it  is  God's  will,  but  it  is  in 


§  75.]  PURE  ETH^S.  91 

fact  confirmed.  Human  reason  is  conditioned  by  the  same 
divine  will  which  wills  the  good;  and  as,  among  the  goods 
which  God  himself  created,  the  highest  is  reason,  hence  the 
inner  essence  of  the  reason  must  involve  also  the  moral, — not, 
however,  as  something  conditioned  independently  of  God, 
but  in  fact  as  God's  will  revealed  to  the  reason,  in  so  far  as 
the  latter  has  kept  itself  unclouded.  However,  this  moral 
law,  as  immanent  in  the  reason,  is  not  to  be  conceived  as  im 
plying  that  the  rational  will  gives  law  unto  itself;  it  is  the 
part  of  the  will  to  submit  itself  to  the  law,  but  not  to  give  it ; 
the  moral  law  is  above  the  will,  above  human  reason  in  general ; 
and  the  latter,  in  its  consciousness  of  the  same,  recognizes  it 
in  fact  as  divine,  and  consequently  as  absolutely  valid  and 
beyond  the  scope  of  human  determination.  As  little  as  man 
can  give  to  himself  reason  and  its  dialectical  laws,  so  little 
ca.n  he  give  to  himself  moral  law.  Freedom  of  will  has  to  do 
only  with  the  fulfilling,  but  not  with  the  conditioning  of  the 
law.  The  morally  cognizing  reason  simply  finds  revealed 
within  itself  the  divine  law,  but  does  not  make  it.  The 
Scriptures  uniformly  present  the  moral  law  as  being  essen 
tially  the  will  of  God,  without,  however,  thereby  interfering 
with  the  idea  that  the  same  is  the  expression  of  the  inner 
purpose  of  being  itself.  "Be  ye  transformed,"  says  Paul, 
[Rom.  xii,  2],  "by  the  renewing  of  your  mind,  that  ye  may 
prove  what  is  that  good  and  acceptable  and  perfect  will  of 
God ; "  the  "  will "  of  God  is  here  the  fundamental ;  any  thing 
is  "good"  only  because  it  expresses  the  will  of  God  which  is 
itself  good  per  se ;  the  "acceptable"  is  that  which  is  good 
relatively  to  the  spirit  that  is  contemplating  it, — that  excites 
approbation  in  the  rational  spirit,  and  is  in  harmony  there 
with, — in  a  word,  that  is  in  harmony  with  God  and  his 
thoughts,  and  with  God-related  spirit  in  general;  and  the 
"perfect,"  the  goal-attaining,  is  whatever  is  the  realization 
of  the  divine  and  good  end.  Thus  the  apostle  expresses  the 
essence  of  the  good  under  all  its  phases;  the  good  is  good 
both  as  to  its  origin,  as  to  the  cognizing  spirit,  and  as  to  its 
end. 


92  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  16 

SECTION   LXXVI. 

In  treating  of  the  moral  law  as  tlie  expression  of 
the  divine  will,  we  have  two  points  to  consider,  first, 
the  communication  of  this  law  by  God  to  man,  and 
then  its  inner  essence. 

I.  THE  REVELATION  OF  THE  DIVINE  WILL  TO  MAN. 

This  revelation  reveals  to  us  not  only  the  contents 
•of  the  divine  law,  but  must  also  reveal  it  as  the 
divine  will.  This  manifestation  of  the  holy  will  of 
God  is  of  a  twofold  character.  In  reason,  which  is 
the  more  especial  embodiment  of  the  divine  image, 
and  which  is  consequently  the  God-ward  phase  of 
man,  man  has  the  power  of  recognizing  the  divine 
will  in  regard  to  reason, — the  rational  life-purpose 
of  the  rational  spirit.  Hence,  by  virtue  of  his  ration 
ality,  man  has  the  divine  law  in  himself  as  a  per 
sonal  knowledge  attained  to  through  free  self-de 
velopment.  The  divine  will-revelation  is  therefore 
primarily  an  inner  revelation  within  the  rational 
spirit  conditioned  by  the  creative  will  itself.  As, 
however,  this  knowledge  cannot  be  a  directly-given 
one,  but  must  be  first  attained  to  by  morally-spiritual 
activity,  hence  it  cannot  be  for  morality  the  sufficient 
antecedent  condition.  There  is  a  necessity  therefore, 
in  order  to  the  commencement  of  the  morally-rational 
life  of  humanity,  of  a  special  training  of  the  same  by 
God  unto  moral  knowledge, — of  a  direct  extraordi 
nary  objective  revelation  by  means  of  which  man  may 
have  from  the  very  beginning  a  definite  conscious 
ness  as  to  the  divine  will,  and  a  firm  guarantee  of 
the  truth. 

(a)  The  extraordinary,  positive  and  supernatural 


§  76.]  PURE   ETHICS.  93 

revelation  of  the  divine  will,  in  the  educative  guid 
ance  of  man  by  God,  precedes  indeed  his  own  reason- 
knowledge  as  arising  from  the  inner,  general,  natural 
revelation,  but  in  a  normal  development  of  man  it 
then  gradually  retires  into  the  back-ground  in  pro 
portion  as  his  spiritual  ripening  advances.  Its  pur 
pose  is  to  awaken  rational  knowledge,  and  to  conduct 
the  awakened  spirit  to  its  spiritual  majority ;  and 
hence  it  involves  the  virtualizing  of  the  moral  free 
dom  and  of  the  independent  personality  of  the  ra 
tional  spirit. 

The  seeming  contradiction  that  lies  in  the  facts,  that 
rational  knowledge  cannot  be  given  in  an  immediate  and 
ready  form,  but  must  be  first  attained  to  through  moral  effort, 
and  that,  on  the  other  hand,,  all  moral  activity  presupposes 
already  the  consciousness  of  the  moral,  is  reconciled  solely 
and  simply  by  the  fact  that  the  creating  God  is  also  an  edu 
cating  one, — that  He  reveals  to  man  Himself  and  his  will, — 
even  as  also  the  child  does  not  ripen  to  reason  and  maturity 
by  being  abandoned  to  itself,  but  by  being  educated  by  reason 
and  to  reason, — by  having  the  moral  consciousness  which  as 
yet  slumbers  in  it  awakened,  by  instruction,  and,  when  once 
awakened,  then  strengthened  by  actual  moral  example. 
Without  instruction  and  training  the  child  never  becomes 
a  truly  rational  person ;  and  when,  in  harmony  with  the 
Christian  system,  we  affirm  the  same  thing  of  the  first  man, 
we  do  not  thereby  state  anything  inconsistent  with  the  nature 
of  man,  but  in  fact  simply  that  which  is  implied  in  the  very 
nature  of  rational  spirit-development.  If  for  a  moment  we 
should,  with  Rousseau,  conceive  of  the  first  generations  of 
man  as  in  a  condition  of  animal  unculture,  creeping  on  all 
fours,  and  without  speech,  then  we  are  utterly  unable  to  learn 
from  any  of  the  champions  of  this  theory  in  what  manner 
these  human-like  animals  could  ever  attain  to  reason  and  to  a 
moral  consciousness.  We  have  in  fact,  in  the  case  of  the  un 
civilized  tribes  of  the  race — who,  low  as  they  are,  are  yet  not 
so  low  as  the  above-supposed  semi-men,  — positive  proof  that 


94  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  76. 

man  when  once  sunk  into  the  condition  of  a  savage  never 
again  rises  to  a  higher  culture, of  his  own  strength. 

Without  a  consciousness  of  God  and  of  his  will,  man  is  as 
yet,  on  the  whole,  not  rational ;  but  man  was  created  by  God 
after  his  own  image,  and  hence  unto  reason  and  unto  morality. 
This  implies  of  itself  that  this  consciousness  was  necessarily 
shared  in  even  by  the  first  man.  Now  as  man  knows  nothing 
of  nature  save  as  nature  communicates  herself  to  him  through 
sensuous  impressions,  so  also  can  man  know  nothing  of  God 
unless  God  reveals  himself  to  him;  and  in  fact  a  God  who 
should  not  reveal  himself  is  utterly  unconceivable.  If  now  a 
consciousness  of  the  moral,  that  is  of  God's  will,  is  the  neces 
sary  antecedent  condition  of  all  moral  activity,  and  if,  at  the 
same  time,  all  real  rational  knowledge  springs  from  a  moral 
using  of  such  knowledge,  then  is  it  perfectly  self-evident  that 
the  beginning  of  this  knowledge  must  have  been  directly 
prompted  by  God  himself.  The  fact  that  this  first  revelation 
is  termed,  in  distinction  from  the  self-wrought-out  knowledge, 
an  extraordinary  and  supernatural  one,  does  not  imply  that  it 
stands  in  contradiction  or  antagonism  to  the  inner  revelation 
in  the  self-developing  spirit.  On  the  contrary  it  is  for  the 
development  of  humanity  in  general  both  very  natural  and  in 
harmony  with  general  order;  for,  all  life  of  individual 
objects,  both  in  the  spiritual  and  in  the  natural  world,  re 
quires  a  first  stimulation,  an  awakening  influence  from  other 
already  developed  objects  and  beings ;  and  this  stimulating 
rises  toward  educative  training  in  proportion  as  the  perfection 
of  the  species  rises;  man  has  therefore,  by  virtue  of  his 
rational  nature,  a  claim  upon  an  educative  influence  from  the 
rational  spirit;  and  this  is  in  fact  the  historical  revelation. 
Man  is  not  by  his  birth  or  creation  already  really  a  morally- 
rational  spirit,  he  becomes  so  only  by  an  educative  influence 
from  the  rational  spirit,  and  hence,  in  the  case  of  the  first 
man,  from  a  primarily  objective  revelation  from  God.  This 
revelation,  however,  does  not  remain,  in  this  objective  charac 
ter,  but,  in  stimulating  man  to  a  moral  consciousness  and  to 
moral  activity,  it  brings  him  to  the  inner  revelation  in  the 
rational  nature  of  man  himself— to  a  consciousness  of  his  own 
God-likeness,  and  hence  also  to  a  consciousness  of  the  divine 
prototype.  The  first  man  sustained  to  God  an  absolutely 


§  76.]  PURE   ETHICS.  95 

child-like  relation,  as  to  an  educating  father;  and  such  is 
precisely  the  Biblical  account  of  the  primitive  state.  If  we  do 
not  presuppose  such  an  educative  primitive  revelation  of  the 
moral,  then,  either  the  moral  law  would  have  to  exist,  (as  in 
irrational  nature-creatures,  so  also  in  man)  as  a  direct  in 
stinctive  impulse, — in  which  case  man  would  not  be  a  moral 
being,  but  only  a  peculiar  species  of  animal;  or,  a  rational 
knowledge  of  the  moral  would  have  to  be  already  created  in 
him, — which  would  be  contrary  to  all  our  notions  of  man's 
spiritual  development,  and  surely  a  much  greater  miracle 
than  the  one  which  it  was  designed  to  dispense  with.  That 
which  has  no  need  of  training  is  either  not  a  rational  being, 
or  it  is  God  himself.  The  educative  revelation  presupposes 
indeed  a  corresponding  moral  endowment  in  man;  but  this 
moral  endowment,  the  unconscious  germ  of  the  moralT  has 
need,  in  order  to  its  developing  itself  into  reality,  of  a  spiritual 
training.  This  training  does  not  create  the  moral  conscious 
ness,  but  only  awakens  it — gives  to  it  primarily  definite  con 
tents,  which  the  thus  stimulated  morally  rational  conscious 
ness  then  perceives  as  not  in  antagonism  but  as  in  harmony 
with  itself,  and  for  that  very  reason  appropriates  to  itself. 

In  order  to  man's  being  really  moral  he  must  be  conscious 
that  in  his  free  acting  he  freely  subordinates  himself  to  the 
will  of  God ;  but  he  can  do  this  only  when  he  recognizes  the 
moral,  not  merely  as  such,  but  also  as  being  of  divine  origin, 
and  this  he  can  do  only  when  he  distinguishes  the  divine  will 
from  his  own ;  this  distinguishing,  however,  is  possible,  for 
the  first  man,  only  when  the  divine  will  presents  itself  to  him 
as  other  than  his  own,  as  objective  to  him, — when  God  ex 
pressly  reveals  himself  to  him.  On  this  definite  distinguishing 
of  one's  own  personal,  from  the  divine  will,  depends  all 
morality ;  a  merely  unconscious  following  of  propension  is 
not  moral,  but  immoral.  Man  must  become  conscious  that  he 
does  this  or  that  act  not  simply  because  it  pleases  him,  but 
that  it  pleases  him  because  it  pleases  God.  In  this  conscious, 
discriminating,  free  choosing  of  the  divine  will  as  distin 
guished  from  the  merely  natural  individual  will,  man  is  ex 
pected  to  discover  his  essential  difference  from  nature,  his 
belonging  to  the  kingdom  of  God ;  he  is  to  learn  to  distin 
guish  between  "can"  and  "should,"  between  his  ability 


96  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  77. 

and  his  obligation,  and  thus  to  become  conscious  of  his 
moral  destination  to  freedom.  Were  the  moral  consciousness 
or  the  moral  impulse  inborn  in  man,  then  he  could  not  come 
to  a  consciousness  of  his  freedom — of  his  ability  morally  to 
rise  above  his  merely  individual  being,  and  freely  to  choose 
the  divine.  Herein  lies  the  high  moral  significancy  of  the 
notion  of  an  historical  divine  revelation.  In  the  interest  of 
freedom,  in  the  interest  of  the  training  of  man  into  a  moral 
personality,  we  would  have  been  forced  philosophically,  to 
presuppose  such  a  revelation,  did  we  not  already  know  of  it 
from  Biblical  teaching. 

SECTION  LXXVII. 

(b)  The  inner  revelation  of  the  holy  will  of  God 
in  the  rational  consciousness  of  man  is  not  a  mere 
instinctive  impulse,  as  this  is  the  characteristic  of 
irrational  nature-creatures,  nor  is  it  a  mere  feeling, 
inasmuch  as  this,  so  far  as  relating  to  spiritual 
things,  always  presupposes  a  knowledge,  a  conscious 
ness,  but  it  is  a  real  consciousness,  which,  however,  is 
at  first  only  obscure  and  indefinite,  and  receives 
more  definite  contents  only  through  educative  reve 
lation,  whereby  it  is  developed  into  full  clearness. 
The  inner  and  the  objective  revelations,  though 
differing  from  each  other  as  to  the  order  of  their 
taking-place  and  as  to  their  form,  do  not  differ  in 
their  essential  contents,  nor  indeed  as  to  their  cer 
tainty  ;  and  the  objective  revelation  is  no  more  ren 
dered  superfluous  by  the  inner  one,  than  is  the  latter 
by  the  former ;  each  mutually  calls  for  the  other. 

Just  as  the  educative  influencing  of  the  child  does  not 
render  superfluous  its  o^vn  active  moral  self-development,  but 
in  fact  calls  for  the  same  as  its  end,  and  as  the  latter  without 
the  former  is  not  possible,  so  is  it  also  with  the  twofold  rev 
elation.  If  the  historical  revelation  did  not  lead  to  a  knowl 
edge  of  the  moral  law  as  immanent  in  this  reason  itself,  man 


§  77.1  PURE  ETHICS.  97 

would  remain  in  perpetual  nonage, — would  not  come  to  a  con 
sciousness  of  his  rationality;  in  fact  this  revelation  has  its 
own  withdrawal  into  the  back-ground  as  its  ultimate  end, — 
as  indeed  since  the  accomplishment  of  redemption  it  has  act 
ually,  in  a  large  degree,  so  withdrawn. — By  inner  revelation, 
here,  is  not  to  be  understood  a  real  inspiration  as  in  the  case 
of  the  prophets,  for  this  would  in  fact  be  supernatural-  and 
extraordinary ;  it  is  simply  the  gradual  coming  forward  of  the 
divine  image  in  man, — the  rational  spirit's  becoming-conscious 
of  itself  as  such  image.  This  becoming-conscious  on  the 
part  of  one's  own  rational  nature  is  properly  called  a  revelation, 
for  the  reason  that  this  God-likeness  is  not  conditioned  by 
man  himself  but  is  created  by  God  in  the  state  of  a  germ, 
and  is  by  the  free  activity  of  man,  simply  developed.  The 
positive  revelation  is  the  light  whereby  this  divine  image, 
hidden  in  man's  inner  nature,  becomes  visible  to  his  under 
standing,  or  more  properly,  it  is  the  warming  sunlight  under 
whose  influence  the  germ  of  rationality  unfolds  itself  out  of 
secrecy  into  day.  The  inner  revelation  is  neither  in  antago 
nism  to,  nor  is  it  identical  with,  the  objective ;  it  is  no  more 
in  antagonism  therewith  than  is  man's  own  active  self-develop 
ment  to  moral  maturity  in  antagonism  with  his  training 
received  from  others ;  nor  is  it  so  nearly  identical  therewith 
as  to  amount  to  a  repetition  of  the  same  thing.  Their 
respective  difference  of  origin  continues  to  hold  good  also 
for  the  morally  mature ;  even  for  the  regenerated  Christian, 
though  he  possesses  the  law  of  the  Spirit  as  a  living  power 
within  him,  the  historical  revelation  continues  to  serve  as  a 
permanent  unvarying  basis  for  the  development  of  his  moral 
consciousness,  and  as  a  sure  criterion  for  testing  the  truth  of 
the  light  within  him ;  Christ  came  not  to  destroy  the  law. — 
As  in  their  origin,  so  also  in  their  form,  they  are  different; 
the  positive  revelation  bears  a  thoroughly  historical  character; 
the  inner,  a  psychological.  The  former  assumes  the  form  of 
positive  laws  given  at  particular  times,  and  through  particular 
personal  instrumentalities ;  the  latter  is  continuous  in  every 
individual  throughout  his  life. 

On  this  inner  revelation  through  the  God-likeness  of  the 
rational  spirit  the  Scriptures  lay  some  stress,  notwithstanding 
that  they  speak  of  it  simply  in  connection  with  man  as  per- 

VOL.  II— 8 


^ 
98  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§77. 

verted  by  sin,  in  whom  the  natural  consciousness  of  God  and 
of  his  will  is  seriously  obscured  and  in  need  of  special  illumi 
nation, — for  which  reason  the  natural  inner,  and  the  super 
natural  inner,  revelations  are  not  strictly  and  formally 
distinguished.  In  allusion  to  moral  wisdom,  it  is  said :  "  It 
is  the  spirit  in  man,  the  breath  of  the  Most  High,  that  gives 
him  understanding"  [Job  xxxii,  8;  comp.  Prov.  xx,  27];  and 
it  is  prophesied  of  the  new  Covenant:  "  I  will  put  my  law  in 
their  inward  parts,  and  write  it  in  their  hearts"  [Jer.  xxxi,  33], 
— as  in  contrast  to  the  Old  Covenant  under  which  the  law 
was  predominantly  objective  and  in  sharp  antagonism  to  the 
sin-blinded  heart.  But  what  is  true  of  the  New  Covenant  is 
likewise  true  of  the  unfallen  state.  This  prophecy  refers,  it 
is  true,  to  the  working  of  the  Holy  Spirit,  but  unfallen  man 
was  per  se  already  filled  with  this  Spirit.  Paul  speaks  of  a 
natural  consciousness  of  God  and  of  the  moral,  even  in  the 
heathen  [Rom.  i,  19  oqq.]',  by  how  much  more  must  this  be 
true  of  man  as  unfallen.  This  natural  God-consciousness  is 
the  general  manifestation  of  that  "life"  which  was  the  light 
of  men  [John  i,  4]. 

It  is  a  favorite  manner  with  some  to  speak  of  a  moral 
"feeling,"  and  even  of  a  moral  instinctive  "impulse,"  as 
the  primitive  germ  which  subsequently  develops  itself  into  a 
moral  consciousness.  If  by  such  feeling  or  impulse  so  much 
is  meant  as  a  knowledge  as  yet  indistinct — a  presentiment 
rather  than  a  comprehension, — we  can  readily  admit  it, 
though  in  any  case  the  expressions  are  very  inappropriate, 
and  serve  only  to  confusion.  Understood  in  their  proper 
sense,  we  must  emphatically  reject  them  ;  for  feeling  is  simply 
an  immediate  becoming-conscious  of  a  state  occasioned  in 
the  subject  by  an  impression,  and  is  hence  always  of  a  merely 
subjective  and  strictly  individual  nature,  whereas  the  moral 
law  is  per  se  necessarily  objective  and  universal — an  idea ;  an 
idea  cannot  be  felt,  but  must  be  known,  though  indeed  this 
knowledge  may  be  primarily  as  yet  indistinct.  A  direct  feel 
ing  can  be  occasioned  only  by  a  sensuous  impression  ;  of  spirit 
ual  things  I  can  have  a  feeling  properly  so-called,  only  after 
they  have  become  an  object  of  my  cognizing  consciousness ; 
every  feeling  presupposes  either  a  sensuous  impression  or  an 
idea,  a  conception.  To  consider  feeling,  Ih  the  sphere  of  the 


§  78.]  PURE   ETHICS.  99 

religiously-moral,  as  the  fundamental  antecedent  condition 
tie/ore  all  knowledge,  is  simply  to  confound  an,  as  yet  indis 
tinct,  anticipatory  consciousness  with  feeling  proper,  and 
poorly  serves  to  the  attainment  of  scientific  clearness.  Still 
less  can  we  speak  of  a  moral  impulse,  in  the  strict  sense  of 
the  word,  as  the  primitive  antecedent ;  an  impulse  that  does 
not  rest  on  a  moral  consciousness  belongs  not  to  the  sphere  of 
the  moral  but  to  that  of  the  merely  natural,  and  in  the  exact 
proportion  that  we  attribute  power  to  some  such  pretended 
impulse,  we  violate  the  freedom  of  the  will.  If  an  uncon 
scious  impulse  toward  the  good  is  the  primitive  antecedent  in 
man,  then  is  a  choice  of  the  evil  utterly  impossible.  If,  how 
ever,  we  should  assume,  as  the  primitive  condition,  that  there 
were  in  man  contradictory  impulses,  the  one  toward  the  good, 
the  other  toward  the  evil,  still  we  would  not,  by  this  anarch 
ical  duality,  safeguard  the  freedom  of  the  will,  if  we  did  n^t 
assume  as  above  these  mutually  conflicting  impulses,  also  a 
higher  moral  consciousness, — whereby  in  fact  the  hypothesis 
itself  would  be  destroyed. 

SECTION  LXXVIII. 

The  revelation  of  the  divine  will  to  the  moral  sub 
ject,  as  given  in  the  rational  self-consciousness,  is 
the  conscience.  This  is  not  an  originally  ready  power, 
but,  as  given  at  first  only  in  germ,  it  must  be  devel 
oped, — stands  in  need  of  culture,  primarily  by  God 
himself,  and,  in  all  after  the  first  generation,  by  the 
already  morally-matured  spirit  of  men ;  and  with  its 
further  moral  development  it  constantly  becomes 
more  definite,  more  clear  and  more  rich  in  contents. 
Now,  as  sin  separates  man  from  God  and  from  the 
knowledge  of  flim,  and  also  damagingly  affects  the 
moral  training  received  from  others,  it  is  clear  that 
the  conscience  has  its  full  purity  and  power  only  in  a 
sinless  state. — As  relating  to  the  moral  life-manifes 
tations,  the  conscience  appears  as  a  morally-judging 
power,  and  as  sifch  it  is  either  in  harmony  with  the 


100  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  78. 

particular  manner  of  action — in  which  case  it  awak 
ens  a  joyous  feeling  of  approval, — or  it  is  in  antag 
onism  therewith,  and  in  this  case  it  awakens  a  painful 
feeling  of  disapproval ;  and  either  feeling  prompts 
to  a  corresponding  course  of  action.  As  the  con 
science  is  a  revelation  of  the  moral  law  as  the  divine 
will,  hence  it  never  exists  without  a  God-consciousness, 
— it  is  itself,  in  fact,  one  of  the  phases  of  this  con 
sciousness,  and  is  per  se  of  a  religious  character,  and 
is  inexplicable  from  the  mere  world-consciousness. 
In  its  germ  it  is  a  primitive  and  not  a  derived  power, 
and  in  this  sense  it  is  already  presupposed  on  the 
entrance  of  the  positive  divine  revelation.  The 
ffbtual  acceptance  of  this  revelation  is  of  itself  already 
a  moral  act  which  presupposes  the  conscience ;  but 
the  latter  is  excited  to  activity  and  to  full  develop 
ment  only  by  the  positive  revelation.  Conscience  is 
essentially  an  integral  part  of  man's  God-likeness, — 
is,  like  rationality  in  general,  a  divine  life-power 
imparted  to  the  creature. 

The  conscience  is  in  its  essence,  not  different  from  the  God- 
consciousness,  but  is  only  the  bearing  of  the  God-conscious 
ness  upon  the  moral ;  as  relating  to  the  good,  it  relates  also 
to  God,  for  none  is  good  but  God  alone  [Matt,  xix,  17] ;  and 
God  is  the  criterion  of  all  good,  for  the  good  is  the  God- 
answering  ;  a  conscience  which  is  not  a  God-consciousness  is 
a  perverted,  an  unanchored  one.  As  the  conscience  is  an 
inner  revelation  of  God  to  man,  we  place  its  discussion  in  this 
section,  although  it  is  an  essential  element  of  the  moral  sub 
ject. — The  manners  of  conceiving  of  the  conscience  differ 
very  widely ;  it  is,  in  turn,  regarded  either  as  a  cognizing  con 
sciousness,  or  as  a  feeling,  or  as  an  instinctive  impulse ;  and 
consequently  it  is  sought  for  in  all  the  different  spheres  of  the 
soul-life;  it  is  indeed  true  that  the  conscience  cannot  be  real 
without  embracing  in  itself  all  three  of  these  spheres;  and 
hence  the  word  may  be  used  in  all  three  significations.  In 


§  78.]  PURE  ETHICS.  101 

the  expression:  "Conscience  says  to  me,"  or  "it  approves 
this  and  rejects  that,"  it  is  conceived  of  as  a  cognizing,  .judg 
ing  consciousness;  but  we  also  speak  of  a  joyous,  or  a  chas 
tising  conscience;  and  again  we  say:  "conscience  compels 
me  to  this  act  or  deters  me  from  it."  The  question, however, 
is:  which  of  the  three  phases  is  the  primitive,  the  funda 
mental  one  ?  which  constitutes  the  essence  of  the  conscience  ? 
According  to  what  we  have  previously  said  as  to  the  relation  of 
feeling  and  willing  to  the  cognizing  consciousness,  it  follows 
very  plainly  that  the  essence  of  the  conscience  is  to  be  found 
in  that  which  its  name  directly  expresses  in  various  languages, 
namely,  a  being-certain,  hence  a  certain  knowing,  a  cognizing 
consciousness ;  in  -the  New  Testament  the  term  aweidrjaif — 
(from  avvotda,  conscious  sum,  strictly:  "I  am  afellow-knower," 
and  in  a  higher  sense:  "I  know  with  God,"  in  whom  all 
knowledge  centers), — an  associate  knowing  with  God,  in  virtue 
of  his  indwelling  in  rational  creatures,  is  used  of  the  co'n- 
science,  both  in  so  far  as  it  leads  to  the  good  (ayadrj  aweidrjaif, 
or  KaMi  or  /caftzpd),  and  in  so  far  as,  by  reproving,  it  punishes 
evil  [John  viii,  9] ;  and  the  same  word  is  used  also  directly 
in  the  sense  of  religious  consciousness,  presenting  the  con 
science  as  a  consciousness  of  the  divine  will  [1  Peter  ii,  19; 
Rom.  xiii,  5;  Heb.  ix,  9].  The  conscience,  as  differing  from 
the  enlightening  influence  of  the  Holy  Spirit  [Rom.  ix,  1],  is 
a  power  inherent  in  the  essence  of  man  per  se,  see  Rom.  ii, 
14,  15 ;  in  this  passage  the  hoytafioi  are  not  the  conscience, 
but  the  reflections  that  spring  from  the  conscience,  which 
itself  is  the  "work  of  the  law  written  in  the  hearts,"  that  is, 
the  consciousness  of  the  contents,  of  the  requirements  of  the 
moral  law ;  Paul  is  not  speaking  here  of  the  true  and  perfect 
conscience,  but  of  the  natural  conscience  of  sinful  man ;  the 
essential  features  of  the  true  conscience,  however,  still  lurk 
in  the  disordered  one ;  and  this  essential  character  appears 
here  evidently  as  a  consciousness  of  the  moral.  In  the  Old 
Testament  the  conscience  is  designated  by  the  word  heart, 
Mlb  [Job  xxvii,  6]. 

The  conscience  is  not  a  mere  simple  knowing,  it  is  an  utter 
ance  of  the  practical  reason,  a  direct  judging  of  moral  thoughts 
and  actions,  an  approving  or  condemning  witness  as  to  the  moral 
conductof  man  [2  Cor.  i,  12 ;  v,  11 ;  Rom.  xiv,  22 ;  Acts  xxiii,  1 ; 


102  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  78. 

xxiv,  16;  2  Tim.  i,  3;  1  Peter  iii,  16;  Heb.  xiii,  18].  Such  a 
judging  presupposes  the  consciousness  of  amoral  law,  accord 
ing  to  which  the  decisions  are  made ;  and  this  consciousness 
is  the  inner  essence  of  conscience  itself.  The  conscience  is  a 
judging  power,  for  the  reason  that  it  is  per  se  a  consciousness 
of  the  law  as  the  divine  will;  it  utters  itself  discriminating 
and  deciding  (npivuv)  because  it  is  mindful  of  the  eternal 
ground  of  the  holy, — because  it  is  the  inner  essence  of  the 
divine  image  as  coming  to  self-consciousness ;  this  latter  is 
the  essence  of  the  conscience,  the  judging  is  its  active  mani 
festation. — The  conscience  can  be  awakened,  cultivated,  and 
refined  by  human  instruction,  but  not  generated ;  it  is  a  per 
petual  witnessing  of  God  as  to  himself  and  his  holy  will  in 
the  rational  spirit  of  man,  and  for  this  simple  reason  it  is  not 
within  the  control  of  man,  but  is  a  power  above  him ;  it  may 
be  silenced  temporarily,  and  led  astray  in  its  particular  utter 
ance  as  a  discriminating  power,  but  it  can  never  be  eradicated 
nor  definitively  perverted.  It  is  not  the  person,  strictly  speak 
ing,  who  has  the  conscience,  but  it  is  the  conscience  that  has 
the  person ;  it  dwells  indeed  in  the  individual  personality,  but 
it  is  not  itself  of  subjective  character,  since  it  is  of  divine 
quality;  it  does  not  express  my  personal  peculiarity,  but  the 
holy  will  of  God  in  regard  to  me.  Conscience  is  the  fact  of 
the  divine  morality  in  man  antecedent  to  all  human  morality ; 
it  is  the  germ  proper  of  man's  God-likeness, — the  God-like 
ness  itself  as  bearing  relation  to  free  conduct,  in  so  far  as  this 
consciousness  constitutes  a  part  of  the  essence  of  rationality. 
Without  this  divine  germ  of  the  moral  in  man,  morality 
would  be  impossible — as  impossible  as  is  seeing  without  eye 
sight,  no  matter  how  much  light  there  might  be,  or  instruction 
without  previously  existing  rationality  as  a  basis.  A  convict 
ing  by  argumentation  is  possible  only  when  there  is  antece 
dently  existing  in  the  subject  some  certain  knowledge  where 
with  the  new  truth  shall  agree.  What  axioms  are  in  mathe 
matics,  that  is  the  conscience  in  the  moral  sphere.  He  who 
does  not  recognize  the  axioms,  and  hence  has,  as  it  were,  no 
mathematical  conscience,  is  beyond  the  reach  of  instruction. 
He  alone  can  become  rational  and  moral,  and  live  so,  who 
is  so  already  in  the  original  structure  of  his  being;  and  this 
deepest  ground  of  moral  rationality  is  in  fact  the  conscience. 


§  78.]  PURE   ETHICS.  103 

He  in  whom  the  witness  of  the  holy  God  does  not  witness  for 
the  holy,  cannot  be  moral ;  but  such  an  abandoned  one  there 
cannot  be  in  the  entire  creation  of  God,  for  to  none  has  he 
"left  himself  without  witness."  A  man  may  become  un 
godly,  may  be  unconscieutious,  and  yet  not  be  free  from  the 
power  of  conscience ;  he  may  deprive  himself  of  his  eyes,  but 
not  of  his  reason,  and  consequently  not  of  his  conscience. 
For  this  simple  reason,  every  sin  is  a  fall  of  man  from  his  own 
proper  nature,  an  unfaithfulness  toward  himself.  Conscience 
rests  on  the  discrimination  of  the  personal  creature  and  its 
will  from  the  personal  God  and  his  will ;  it  finds  its  universal 
expression  in  the  words  of  the  Lord:  "Not  my  will  but  thine 
be  done."  Whoever  supposes  himself  to  act  from  necessity, 
or  merely  according  to  his  own  individual  will,  for  him  the 
idea  of  the  conscience  is  obscured ;  the  irreligious  are  neces 
sarily  unconscientious.  It  is  for  the  simple  reason  that  it  is 
not  the  individual  ego,  but  the  divine,  that  speaks  in  the  con 
science,  that  there  can  be  a  reproving,  an  evil,  conscience,  in 
which  the  difference  of  this  twofold  ego  appears  in  an  irreduci 
ble  antithesis.  But  this  voice  of  the  divine  ego  does  not 
first  come  to  the  consciousness  of  the  individual  ego,  from 
•  without;  rather  does  every  external  revelation  presuppose 
already  this  inner  one ;  there  must  echo  out  from  within  man 
something  kindred  to  the  outer  revelation,  in  order  to  its  be 
ing  recognized  and  accepted  as  divine.  Even  as  Adam  at  the 
first  sight  of  the  woman  recognized  at  once  that  she  was 
flesh  of  his  flesh,  so  recognizes  man  immediately  on  the  utter 
ance  of  the  divine  will  by  special  revelation  that  this  is  spirit 
of  that  spirit  which  dwells  and  speaks  within  him,— not,  how 
ever,  as  his  individual  ego,  but  as  distinct  from  it,  and  as 
having  uncontested  right  to  rule  over  it. 

The  first  manifestation  of  conscience  in  the  Scriptures 
appears  in  the  words  wherein  Eve  opposes  the  temptation: 
"We  may  eat  of  the  fruit  of  the  trees  of  the  garden;  but  of 
the  fruit  of  the  tree  which  is  in  the  midst  of  the  garden,  God 
hath  said:  ye  shall  not  eat  of  it."  Here  Eve  distinguishes  the 
command,  as  the  divine  will,  from  her  own  will ;  which 
latter,  however,  she  afterward  carries  out;  but  this  adversely 
judging  conscience  presupposes  a  previous  first  activity  of  the 
same,  namely,  the  recognition  of  the  divine  command  as 


10-4  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  78. 

obligating.  The  command  itself  spoke  in  fact,  primarily, 
only  to  the  understanding;  the  recognition  of  it  as  divine,  as 
a  legitimate  determining  authority  for  the  individual  will,  the 
receiving  of  it  into  the  heart,  and  the  willingness  to  conform 
the  individual  volitions  to  it, — all  this  is  not  a  matter  of  the 
cognizing  understanding,  nor  in  general  of  the  individual 
spirit  as  such,  but  of  that  divine  element  in  man  which  re 
sponds  to  the  divine  command — the  conscience;  and  in  the 
very  first  utterance  of  this  power,  it  shows  itself  primarily, 
indeed  as  a  consciousness,  but  then  straightway  also  as  a 
feeling  of  love  as  toward  the  congenial,  the  right,  and  as  a 
willingness  arising  from  this  consciousness  and  this  love. 

The  cognizing  activity  of  the  conscience  relates  primarily 
and  directly  only  to  the  God-pleasing,  and  not  also  to  the  God- 
repugnant  ;  for  the  former  is  real,  but  not  the  latter,  and  all 
true  and  real  cognition  relates  to  something  real.  Hence  the 
second  phase  of  conscience,  that  where  men's  "eyes  are 
opened"  and  they  "know  the  good  and  the  evil,"  does  not 
belong  to  the  primative  and  pure  conscience,  but  is  a  mani 
festation  of  the  conscience  as  already  in  antagonism  to  the 
moral  actuality  of  man.  As  primarily  relating  to  the  God 
like,  and  hence  as  attended  by  a  feeling  of  approbation,  the 
conscience  has  originally  nothing  to  do  with  fear  of  punish 
ment,  but  is  on  the  contrary  an  expression  of  peace  with  God; 
fear  presupposes  already  a  disturbed  harmony  and  a  knowl 
edge  of  good  and  evil ;  hence  in  the  Scriptures  we  find  con 
science  expressly  distinguished  from  fear.  [Rom.  xiii,  5.] 

According  to  Rothe,  conscience  is  the  divine  activity  in  its 
passive  forth,  that  is,  it  is  the  soul's  self-activity  as  being  de 
termined  by  the  body,  or,  in  general,  by  material  nature, 
and,  in  the  final  instance,  by  the  divine  self-activity,  or,  in 
general,  by  God  himself, — that  is,  it  is  instinctive  impulse  as 
religious.  In  Ids  opinion  conscience  lies  not  on  the  side  of 
the  self-consciousness,  but  on  that  of  the  self-activity,  and 
relates  not  to  conceptions  and  to  the  understanding,  but  to 
volitions  and  to  actions.  Conscience  has  essentially  an  indi 
vidual  character, — is  of  subjective,  not  of  objective,  nature; 
hence  it  is  not  correct  to  speak  of  a  tribunal  of  conscience. 
"The  conscience  of  another  has  not  the  least  binding  force 
for  me,  but  only  my  own ;  when  an  appeal  is  made  to  con- 


§  78.]  PUEE   ETHICS.  105 

science,  there  all  further  discussion  is  cut  off,  there  all  object 
ive  arguments  become  powerless ;  whatever  is  a  matter  of 
conscience  to  me  is  to  me  a  sanctum  sanctorum  which  none 
dare  violate  " — not  even  for  objective  reasons ;  nor  does  my 
conscience  bind  any  one  else.  Conscience  is  essentially  a 
religious  instinct-impulse ;  and  as  being  an  activity  of  God  in 
man  under  the  form  of  an  instinctive  impulse,  and  hence  also 
a  sensuously  perceptible  one,  it  is  attended  by  sensuously- 
somatic  phases  of  feeling.  Now  every  instinct-impulse  is 
either  positive  or  negative,  hence  conscience  is  either  appro- 
bative  or  disapprobative ;  as  disapprobative  it  is  religious 
aversion, — an  instinctive  impulse  toward  the  counterworking 
of  the  sin  (hence  stings  of  conscience)  ;  as  approbative  it  is  the 
religious  appetite.  Rothe  takes  occasion  here  to  complain 
seriously  of  the  hitherto  prevalent  confusion  of  phraseology 
on  this  subject, — namely,  in  view  of  the  fact  that  conscience 
is  treated  of,  sometimes  as  a  propension,  sometimes  as  a  moral 
feeling,  sometimes  as  a  religious  feeling,  sometimes  as  such 
and  such  an  instinct-impulse,  or  as  such  and  such  a  sense ;  in 
this,  however,  he  is  manifestly  unjustifiable ;  it  is  to  no  good 
purpose  to  quarrel  with  language  which  is,  in  fact,  often 
profounder  and  truer  than  the  boldest  theoretical  systems. 
No  one  has  a  right  arbitrarily  to  define  ideas  contrarily  to  the 
general  consciousness,  and  then  to  find  fault  with  language 
because  it  does  not  harmonize  with  the  definitions.  In  the 
present  case  we  find  language  perfectly  justifiable  in  making 
so  wide  a  use  of  the  term  conscience,  inasmuch  as  all  the 
above  phases  are  in  fact  embraced  in  it,  though  indeed  not  in 
equal  degrees.  The  strange  notion  that  conscience  rests  on  a 
determination  of  the  personal  soul  by  the  material  body,  so 
that  by  implication  a  rational  spirit  without  a  material  body 
would  not  have  any  conscience,  we  pass  over  in  silence,  and 
make  only  the  following  observations.  Should  we  admit 
that  conscience  relates  to  volition  and  action,  it  does  not 
follow  from, this  that  it  is  not  per  se,  and  primarily,  a  con 
sciousness  ;  thought  in  fact  may  influence  volition ;  and  the 
necessary  presupposition  of  every  volition  is  a  thought ;  but 
an  unconscious  instinct-impulse  is  neither  religious  nor  moral, 
but  irrational.  The  fact  is,  conscience  lies  most  strictly  on 
the  side  of  the  self-consciousness;  otherwise  an  evil  con- 


106  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  78. 

science  could  not  contain  a  self-accusation.  That  the  con 
science  is  of  sulrjective  nature  is  only  in  so  far  correct  as  it 
constitutes  an  integral  element  of  rational  personality ;  but  it 
is  entirely  incorrect  in  Rothe  to  reduce  it  to  a  mere  individ 
ually-subjective  phenomenon,  and  entirely  to  deprive  it  of 
objective  character.  If  conscience  is  to  be  at  all  of  a  rational 
character,  it  must  have  a  general,  and  hence  also  an  objective 
significancy.  That  which  is  merely  subjective  lias  not  the 
least  moral  significancy,  rather  is  it  the  opposite  of  the 
moral ;  what  is  holy  for  me  must  be  also  holy  per  se  and 
before  God,  and  what  is  holy  before  God  must  be  holy  for  all 
moral  creatures.  My  conscience  is  true  only  in  so  far  as  it  is 
an  expression  of  the  moral  idea;  but  the  moral  idea  is  not  of 
a  merely  subjective  nature.  For  every  Christian,  it  is  a 
matter  of  Conscience  to  follow  Christ;  this  holds  good  in 
general  as  well  as  in  particular,  and  not  simply  for  me  as  such 
and  such  a  particular  person.  The  more  the  conscience  bears 
a  merely  subjective  character,  the  more  detective  it  is;  in  a 
normal  condition  of  humanity  all  moral  consciences  would 
necessarily  be  essentially  concordant,  inasmuch  as  there  is 
only  one  God  and  only  one  divine  will,  and  inasmuch  as  con 
science  is  the  expression  of  this  will.  Rothe  comes  himself 
into  violent  contradiction  with  his  assertions,  in  that  he  makes 
conscience  to  be  determined  by  a  divine  activity ;  for  this 
divine  activity  must  be  objective  to  the  subject ;  and,  as  of  a 
holy  character,  it  certainly  does  not  determine  each  individual 
to  a  different  decision:  and  a  little  farther  on  Rothe  himself 
takes  this  position:  that  the  conscience  as  an  activity  of  God 
in  man,  has  a  direct  and  unconditional  authority,  and  from 
which  man  cannot  in  any  manner  escape ;  that  arguments 
avail  nothing  as  against  conscience, — that  perfectly  convinc 
ing  arguments  may  be  urged  and  yet  the  conscience  remain 
unmoved  ;  that  consequently  conscience  is  also  infallible,  that 
it  never  deceives  and  is  incapable  of  being  bribed  ;  and  that 
though  we  may  blind  ourselves  as  to  its  decision,  yet  it  is 
itself  not  to  be  deceived.  These  positions,  so  utterly  ex 
treme  and  so  contrary  to  all  experience,  are  manifestly 
irreconcilable  with  his  previous  position,  namely,  that  con 
science,  being  entirely  devoid  of  objective  character,  is  a 
mere  subjective  phenomenon ;  for  in  the  notion  of  an  authority 


§  79.]  PURE   ETHICS.    '  107 

in  conscience,  and  especially  of  an  unconditional  one,  it  is 
manifestly  implied  that  the  subject  is  subordinate  thereto.* — 
According  to  Schenkel  (Dogmatik,  1858,  I,  135  sqq.)  the  con 
science  is  a  special  faculty  of  the  human  soul,  or  rather  that 
one  of  its  organs  which  has  to  do  with  religious  functions, 
whereas  the  reason  and  the  will  do  not  relate  directly  to  God 
biit  to  the  world;  this  conscience,  in  which  the  God-con 
sciousness  is  primarily  and  immediately  given,  is  at  the  same 
time  also  the  ethical  central-organ.  What  is  to  be  gained  by 
this  freak  of  fancy  it  is  difficult  to  determine.  When  men 
thus  arbitrarily,  and  contrary  to  prevalent  usage,  limit  the 
notion  of  the  reason  and  the  will,  it  is  of  course  an  easy 
matter  to  discover  new  faculties  of  the  soul  and  new  organs 
of  the  same;  but  whether  anything  important  is  gained  there 
by,  and  whether  the  supposed  epoch-making  ne^f  discovery 
will  meet  with  much  favor,  we  may  seriously  doubt. — Tren- 
delenburg  shows  much  more  circumspection  and  acumen  in 
considering  conscience  as  the  reaction  and  pro-action  of  the 
total  God-centered  man  against  the  man  as  partial,  especially 
against  the  self-seeking  part  of  himself  (Naturrecht,  1860,  §  39). 


II.— THE  ESSENCE  OF  THE  MOEAL  LAW  AS  THE 
DIVINE  WILL. 

SECTION  LXXIX. 

The  essence  of  the  moral  law  as  the  divine  will 
cannot  be  deduced  from  the  nature  of  man  alone,  but 
essentially  only  from  the  idea  of  God  as  ruling  right 
eously  in  his  creation. — (a)  As  morality  rests  on 
freedom,  and  as  freedom  consists  in  the  fact  that  a 
man  chooses,  by  a  personal  independent  volition,  a 

*  Kothe  appears  to  have  become  dissatisfied  with  this  exposition  of 
the  conscience.  In  his  revised  edition  (Theol.  Ethik,  2  Auf.,  1867, 
§  177,  Anm.  3)  he  carries  his  dissatisfaction  with  the  term  conscience 
so  far  as  entirely  to  exclude  it  from  his  work.  He  declares  the  word  as 
"scientifically  inadmissible,"  inasmuch  as  it  is  devoid  of  " accurately 
determined  logical  contents ;  " — it  is  but  a  popular  expression  for  the 
collective  moral  nature  of  man. — TRANSLATOR. 


108  ,     CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  79 

particular  mode  of  action  among;  several  possible 
ones,  hence  every  moral  action  is  at  the  same  time 
the  leaving  undone  of  a  possible  contrary  action. 
The  moral  law  is  therefore  per  «6 -always  twofold;  it 
is  command  and  prohibition  at  the  same  time,  and 
consequently  there  is  in  fact  no  essential  difference 
whether  the  law  appears  in  the  one  or  in  the  other 
form;  and  as  the  moral  life  of  man  is  a  continuous 
one,  hence  he  must  at  every  moment  of  time  be  ful 
filling  a  divine  law ;  a  mere  non-doing  would  be  a 
negation  of  the  moral.  It  is  in  consequence  of  the 
freedom  of  choice,  and  not  in  consequence  of  sin- 
fulness,  that  the  divine  law  bears  the  form  of  a 
"  should." 

Every  presentation  of  the  moral  law  from  the  stand-point  of 
man  alone,  that  is,  purely  from  the  nature  of  man,  without 
deriving  it  from  God,  is  anti-religious,  and  can  never  include 
the  whole  truth  of  the  moral  idea.  And  in  precise  proportion 
as  we  conceive  more  highly  of  the  moral  nature  of  man  from  that 
stand-point,  we  render  unavoidable  his  Pantheistic  exaltation 
into  the  highest  realization  of  God  himself — the  putting  of 
man  in  the  place  of  the  personal  God.  We  cannot  possibly 
understand  the  moral  law  save  as  the  divine  purpose  in  regard 
to  free  creatures,  and  we  can  base  it  on  the  nature  of  man 
only  in  so  far  as  we  recognize  in  and  through  this  nature  the 
divine  creative  will,  the  fulfillment  of  which  lies  in  the  real 
ized  moral  perfection  of  man. 

The  fact  that  any  particular  action  is  morally  good,  neces 
sarily  implies  as  possible  a  contrary,  or  non-good  one ;  and 
the  commanding  of  the  fonner  is  per  se  a  prohibiting  of  the 
latter;  every  command  directly  implies  the  prohibition  of  the 
contrary  form  of  action.  Now  it  might  seem  as  if  the  con 
verse  did  not  hold  good,  namely,  that  a  prohibition  does  not 
imply  at  the  same  time  also  a  command;  the  laws:  thou  shalt 
not  kill,  thou  shalt  not  commit  adultery,  seems  to  require 
simply  a  non-doing.  This,  however,  would  be  possible 
only  on  condition  that  a  mere  non-doing  were  in  general  a 


§  79.]  PURE   ETHICS.  109 

moral  possibility.  But  as  life  is  strictly  continuous  in  all  of 
its  stages,  and  as  even  a  momentary  real  cessation  of  life  is 
death,  hence  least  of  all  can  the  highest  form  of  life,  the  moral 
life,  be  a  non-living,  a  simple  non-doing,  without  thereby  turn 
ing  into  the  contrary,  namely,  into  spiritual  and  moral  death. 
As  the  human  spirit,  even  in  the  deepest  sleep  as  conditioned 
by  the  weariness  of  the  body,  is  never  idle,  but  keeps  up  an 
activity  in  remembered  or  unremembered  dreaming,  so  also 
the  highest  form  of  spirit  life,  the  moral  life,  is  never  inter 
rupted  by  a  pure  inactivity.  Hence  a  prohibition  that  should 
include  in  itself  no  contents  of  a  positive  character,  no  com 
mand,  could  not  be  of  a  moral  nature.  The  moral  non-doing 
of  a  morally  prohibited  action  is  in  and  of  itself  necessarily 
the  doing  of  the  contrary.  Hence,  Luther,  in  his  elucidation 
of  the  Commandments,  is  strictly  right  in  never  leaving  them 
in  the  form  of  a  simple  "thou  shalt  not,"  but  in  uniformly 
deducing  from  them  a  very  positive  "thou  shalt."  The  law: 
"thou  shalt  not  kill,"  though  in  form  a  simple  prohibition, 
nevertheless  directly  implies  the  enjoining  of  all  that  man,  in 
his  intercourse  with  others,  ought  to  do  as  contrasting  with 
the  disposition  that  leads  to  murder ;  we  should  not  only  not 
kill  our  neighbor,  but  we  should  help  and  succor  him  in  all 
his  bodily  perils ; — a  mere  non-doing  in  the  face  of  such 
perils  would  be  a  direct  violation  of  the  law.  If  man  is  not 
to  commit  adultery,  then  must  he,  in  the  conjugal  relation, 
not  only  not  do  any  thing  that  stimulates  and  nurtures  an 
adulterous  disposition,  but  he  must  do  the  contrary  thereof; 
that  is,  he  must  live  purely  and  chastely  in  words  and  acts, 
and  love  and  honor  his  own  consort. 

Nevertheless  it  is  not  indifferent  as  to  which  of  the  two 
forms  the  moral  law  .assumes ;  the  difference,  however,  lies 
not  in  the  essence,  but  in  the  practical  educative  adaptation. 
As  the  essence,  the  end,  of  the  moral  life  is  not  negative  but 
has  positive  contents,  the  true  and  perfect  form  of  the  law  is 
in  fact  that  of  the  express  command;  "thou  shalt"  is  higher 
than  "thou  shalt  not."  But  for  man  while  as  yet  undevel 
oped  to  moral  maturity,  the  form  of  prohibition  is  the  more 
obvious  and  simple,  since,  on  the  one  hand,  it  brings  his 
moral  liberty  of  choice  more  clearly  to  his  consciousness,  and, 
with  the  exclusion  of  the  immoral,  opens  to  him  the  whole 


110  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  79. 

field  of  the  discretionary,  and  since,  on  the  other,  it  estab 
lishes  protecting  limits  for  the  field  within  which  he  is  to 
train  himself  up  to  moral  maturity,  to  a  consciousness  of  the 
good.  With  the  child,  education  always  begins  in  the  pro 
hibiting  of  what  conflicts  with  its  well-being;  God's  first  law 
to  man  was  a  free  throwing-open  of  the  field  of  the  discre 
tionary  in  connection  with  a  limiting  prohibition  [Gen.  ii,  16, 
17],  whereas  the  real  command  appears  primarily  only  in  the 
general  form  of  a  Messing,  as  expressive  of  the  goal  of  moral 
effort,  the  good  [Gen.  i,  28].  While  the  Mosaic  Command 
ments  bear  predominately  the  character  of  prohibition,  Christ 
sums  up  the  moral  contents  of  the  divine  law  in  the  form  of 
a  positive  command:  "Thou  shalt  love  the  Lord  thy  God 
with  all  thy  heart,  and  thy  neighbor  as  thyself;"  and  at  the 
same  time  Christ  declares  that  this  command  embraces  the 
whole  ancient  law.  Hence,  while  the  essence  of  the  divine 
law  continues  ever  the  same,  the  revelation  of  it  gradually 
advances  from  the  predominantly  prohibitory  form  to  that  of 
the  positive  command. 

As  both  forms  of  the  divine  law  present  a  duty  to  the  free 
will  of  man,  they  both  bear  the  expression  of  a  command,  a 
"  should."  This  is  the  form  assumed  by  nearly  all  laws,  from 
the  first  one  given  to  Adam  to  the  perfect  laws  of  Christ. 
Since  the  time  of  Schleiermacher,  however,  many  take  offense 
at  this  "should,"  and  strive  to  banish  it,  at  least,  from  the 
pure  moral  law.  In  Schleiermacher's  Philosophical  Ethics, 
this  rejection  of  the  "should"  is  entirely  consequential;  for 
here  the  moral  is  quite  as  necessarily-determined  a  phe 
nomenon  of  the  universe  as  is  the  natural,  and  for  freedom 
of  will  there  is  no  place  whatever;  consequently  ethics  has 
no  other  task  than  simply  to  describe  that  which  takes  place 
from  necessity,  but  not  to  present  laws  under  the  form  of  re 
quirements,  of  duty.  Rothe  follows  this  .view  only  up  to  a 
certain  point;  he  rejects  the  form  of  the  "should"  only  for 
sinless  man,  as  indeed  also  one  cannot  apply  the  idea  of 
"should"  to  God;  only  for  sinful  man  can  the  moral  appear 
as  a  duty  (Eth.  I,  Anf.,  §  817).  As  relating  to  God  this  is 
doubtless  correct,  inasmuch  as  God's  freedom  is  not  human 
liberty  of  choice,  and  as  it  absolutely  excludes  the  possibility 
of  sinning,  and  since  God  is  absolutely  his  own  law.  But  as 


§79.]  PURE   ETHICS.  Ill 

relating  to  free  creatures,  even  though  they  be  as  yet  perfectly 
sinless,  it  is  erroneous, — at  least  unless  we  are  to  regard  the 
moral  perfection  of  the  same  as  a  cessation  of  all  freedom  of 
choice  and  likewise  of  all  moral  duty.  As  long  as  man  does 
not  cease  to  propose  to  himself  moral  ends,  and  freely  to  aim 
to  reach  them,  so  long  will  duty  as  yet  continue.  This  form 
of  the  law  would  be  unsuitable  for  perfect  man  only  wlien 
it  should  be  conceived  of  as  something  uncongenial  to  man, 
as  some  sort  of  oppressive  yoke,  which,  however,  is  by  no 
means  the  case.  The  as  yet  unrealized  state  of  a  freely-to-be- 
attained  goal  always  implies  a  "should."  It  is  only  from 
some  such  misconception  as  if  the  ' '  should  "  implied  some 
thing  foreign  and  burdensome  to  man,  that  we  can  explain 
why  even  Harless  limits  the  application  of  this  word  to  the 
fallen  state  (Christl.Eih'ik,  6  Auf.,  p.  80  sqq.).  There  is,  how 
ever,  no  shadow  of  censure  in  the  form  "thou  shouldst;  "  in 
fact,  there  is  for  the  free  will  no  other  form  of  law  conceiv 
able  than  that  of  the  "should."  Without  a  distinguishing 
of  the  divine  will  from  that  of  the  subject,  no  real  conscious 
morality  is  possible ;  and  simply  this  distinguishing  and 
nothing  more — not  an  antagonism  of  estrangement — is  con 
tained  in  the  idea  of  the  "should."  It  is  in  this  idea  in  fact 
that  morality  and  piety  find  their  unity,  the  moral  being  con 
ceived  as  the  divine  will  [Deut.  x,  12;  Micah  vi,  8].  The 
child  that  does  the  good  for  the  reason  that  it  knows  that  it 
is  the  will  of  its  parents  that  it  should  do  so,  stands  morally 
higher  than  the  one  that  does  it  without  a  consciousness  of 
its  duty;  the  former,  but  not  the  latter,  is  able  to  offer  resist 
ance  to  temptation;  for  temptation  is  overcome  only  by  the 
thought  of  the  divine  will,  or  of  duty.  A  command  does  not 
presuppose  a  contrary  inclination,  but  only  the  possibility  of 
sin,  that  is,  it  presupposes  freedom  of  will.  In  denying  to 
man  while  as  yet  in  a  sinless  state  all  consciousness  of  the 
divine  law,  and  supposing  him  to  act  simply  from  a  direct 
impulse  of  love,  we  not  only  contradict  the  express  declara 
tion  of  the  Scriptures  as  to  a  revelation  of  the  divine  will 
to  primitive  man,  but  we  also  render  the  fall  into  sin  an 
impossibility. 


112  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  80. 

SECTION  LXXX. 

(5)  Whatever  is  morally  good  is  God's  will,  and  is 
hence  also  moral  law;  and  this  law  has,  as  God's 
will,  an  unconditional  claim,— presents  itself  always 
as  a  requirement  from  which  there  is  no  escape,  and 
cannot  possibly  be  construed  into  a  mere  counsel  the 
non  fulfillment  of  which  would  not  be  a  sin,  and  the 
voluntary  fulfillment  of  which  would  constitute  a 
supererogatory  merit.  The  moral  goal  of  every  human 
being  is  moral  perfection,  and  all  that  conducts 
thereto  is  for  every  such  being  an  absolute  duty,  that 
is,  it  is  God's  will  and  law  concerning  him.  JSTo  one 
can  do  more  good  than  is  required  of  him ;  for  the 
human  will  cannot  be  better  than  the  divine,  and 
God's  law  is  not  less  good  than  God's  will.  That 
which  in  the  Scriptures  has  the  appearance  of  real 
moral  counsel  is  simply  a  conditional  law,  the  fulfill 
ment  of  which  becomes  a  duty  to  the  individual  onl}7 
under  certain,  not  universally-existing,  circumstances; 
but  wherever  it  does  become  a  duty,  there  it  is  so 
absolutely,  and  hence  its  non-fulfillment  is  a  violation 
of  duty ;  and  wherever  it  does  not  become  a  duty 
there  its  fulfillment  has  no  merit. 

Here,  for  the  first  time,  we  meet  an  antagonism  of  moral 
views  between  the  different  Christian  churches;  and  it  is  a 
far-reaching  one ;  and  from  this  point  on,  in  our  attempt  to 
construct  a  system  of  Christian  ethics,  and  not  simply  of  the 
ethical  views  of  this  or  that  church,  we  must  seek  for  the 
essence  of  Christianity,  not  merely  in  those  generalities  which 
are  common  to  all  particular  churches,  but,  wherever  two 
views  are  in  irreconcilable  antagonism,  we  must  necessarily 
decide  for  that  one  which  is  of  a  really  Christian  character, 
and  cannot  regard  both  as  equally  legitimate.  And  although 
the  question  in  this  connection  is  nearly  always,  as  to  coun- 


§80.]  PURE   ETHICS.  113 

sels  to  redeemed  Christiana,  still  it  properly  belongs  in  this 
place,  since  in  fact  unfallen  man  would  be,  even  much  more 
than  the  redeemed,  in  a  condition  to  obtain  a  higher  merit 
than  is  strictly  required. 

On  a  superficial  examination  it  might  seem  that  by  the 
dogma  as  to  the  evangelical  counsels  (consilia  as  distinguished 
from  praecepta)  the  moral  requirements  were  advanced  higher 
than  the  generally-sufficient  degrees  of  morality;  the  fact  is, 
however,  the  very  opposite.  The  notion  that  there  is  some  good 
which  is  not  also  a  duty,  can  only  be  obtained  by  lowering 
the  moral  requirement  from  that  of  the  highest  possible 
moral  perfection  to  an  inferior  requirement ;  and  a  supereroga 
tory  merit  becomes  possible  only  where  the  idea  of  the  good 
embraces  more  than  the  moral  requirement.  The  Protestant 
church,  however,  holds  fast  ,the  view  that  all  real  good  is 
absolutely  a  duty,  and  hence  that  man  is  obligated  to  do  all  the 
good  within  his  power, — that  he  should  unconditionally  strive 
for  the  highest  possible  perfection.  The  Protestant  view  as 
to  the  moral  requirement  stands  therefore  higher  than  the 
opposing  view.  The  Protestant  church  rejects  the  notion 
of  moral  counsels,  and  of  the  meritoriousuess  of  their  fulfill 
ment,  for  the  reason  that  it  regards  their  contents  as  not 
absolutely  good,  as  not  per  se  moral,  but  as  only  good  under  cer 
tain  not  universally-existing  circumstances,  but  as  absolutely 
commanded  when  those  circumstances  do  exist.  That  which 
is  good  in  a  particular  conjuncture  is,  when  that  case  arises, 
an  absolute  duty,  and  not  a  mere  discretionary  and  non-obli 
gating  counsel.  The  saying  of  Christ  [Luke  xvii,  10] :  "When 
ye  shall  have  done  all  those  things  which  are  commanded 
you,  say:  we  are  unprofitable  servants," — which  is  not  designed 
to  disparage  the  worth  of  true  morality,  but  simply  to  lead 
man  to  humility  by  reminding  him  of  his  sinful  state,  and 
of  his  redemption  by  grace  alone, — is,  however,  applied  by 
the  theologians  of  the  Romish  church  to  the  doctrine  of  the 
evangelical  counsels,  in  that  they  say  that  man  should  in  fact 
not  remain  a  mere  unprofitable  servant,  but  should  be  a  child 
of  God,  as  indeed  also  Christ  was  not  an  unprofitable  servant ; 
and  even  some  Protestant  exegetes  try  to  escape  this  inference 
simply  by  referring  the  works  here  in  question  not  to  Chris 
tian  morality,  but  merely  to  the  Mosaic  law.  We  regard  both 

Vol.  II— 9 


CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§80. 

the  inference,  and  this  mode  of  escaping  it  as  inadmissible. 
It  is  indeed  true,  man  should  not  be  simply  an  unprofitable 
servant  but  a  child  of  God ;  but  from  this  very  fact  it  follows 
that  that  which  morally  conditions  this  filial  relation  to  God, 
must  also  be  a  positive  moral  requirement  and  duty,  and  not 
a  mere  counsel,  which  we  may  leave  unfulfilled  and  yet  not 
fail  in  doing  all  that  is  actually  required  of  us;  man  is  in 
fact  absolutely  bound  to  become  a  child  of  God.  Now  as  a 
limitation  of  these  words  of  Christ  to  the  Mosaic  law  is  not 
justified  by  the  context,  seeing  that  just  previously  (verses 
5,  6)  the  question  had  been  as  to  the  power  of  faith,  hence 
their  true  scope  is,  we  think,  as  follows:  man,  even  though 
redeemed  but  not  yet  free  from  sin,  is  unable  by  his  dutiful 
works  to  acquire  merit  before  God  in  such  a  sense  as  that  he 
could  claim  of  God  the  blessedness  of  the  children  of  God 
as  a  reward  due,  and  which  God  would  be  required  by  his 
justice  to  grant,  but  on  the  contrary  he  can  regard  this  bless 
edness  only  as  a  gracious  gift  conferred  upon  him  in  virtue  of 
his  faitli  in  the  compassionate  love  of  God  in  Christ.  To  the 
works  owed,  it  is  not  other  non-owed  and  hence  supererogatory 
works  that  are  compared,  but  faith,  which,  though  indeed 
also  a  moral  requirement,  yet  differs  essentially  from  works 
properly  so  called  (comp.  verse  19;  "thy  faith  hath  made 
the  whole").  Christ's  utterance,  therefore,  teaches  clearly 
the  very  opposite  of  sanctification  by  works  as  prevailing  in 
the  Romish  church. 

The  Romish  church  finds  further  support  for  its  supereroga 
tory  good  works, — which  consist  essentially  in  intensified  self- 
denial,  that  is,  in  voluntary  celibacy,  poverty,  obedience  to  man- 
devised  rules,  solitary  life,  etc., — in  those  texts  of  the  New 
Testament  which  seem  to  present  celibacy  and  voluntary  pov 
erty  as-a  higher  morality  not  to  be  expected  of  all  Christians. 
To  the  rich  young  man,  who,  as  he  himself  affirmed,  had  kept 
all  the  commandments,  Christ  says  [Matt,  xix,  21]:  "If  them 
wilt  be  perfect,  go  and  sell  that  thou  hast,  and  give  to  the. 
poor,  and  then  thou  shalt  have  treasure  in  heaven ;  and  come 
and  follow  me."  Now,  it  is  argued,  the  moral  law  does  not 
in  fact  require  of  all  men  the  giving  up  of  their  possessions, 
and  yet  this  young  man  had  fulfilled  all  the  commands  which 
Christ  mentions  to  him;  hence  this  giving-up  was  over  and 


§80.]  PUEE   ETHICS.  115 

above  these  commands.  This  is  a  very  unfortunate  inference, 
for  surely  a  morality  which  does  not  lead  to  the  perfection  of 
man,  can  hardly  be  pure  and  required  by  God ;  and  in  the  case 
of  this  young  man  the  giving-up  of  his  riches  was  the  condition 
of  his  perfection,  and  hence,  as  we  hold,  an  unconditional 
requirement,  in  case  he  really  desired  to  attain  to  the  highest 
good.  The  young  man  in  declining  the  requirement  failed, 
as  Christ  says,  to  have  part  in  the  kingdom  of  heaven ;  all 
his  presumed  fulfillment  of  the  law  was  insufficient.  Now 
this  is  in  plain  antagonism  to  the  Romish  doctrine,  according 
to  which  the  fulfillment  of  the  law,  even  without  obedience 
to  the  counsels,  is  amply  sufficient  to  a  participation  in  the 
kingdom  of  heaven,  whereas  the  supererogatory  works  simply 
serve  to  a  more  speedy  attainment  thereof,  or  to  a  higher  de 
gree  of  blessedness.  Hence  those  who  refuse  to  admit  that 
certain  particular  actions  become  a  duty  only  under  particu 
lar  and  not  universally-existing  relations,  but  that  when  these 
do  exist,  then  they  become  in  fact  a  positive  requirement, 
would  have  no  other  alternative  left,  than  to  regard  the 
requirement  made  of  the  rich  young  man  as  a  general  duty 
for  all  Christians.  "We  can  distinguish  universally- valid 
commands  from  conditional  ones,  not,  however,  moral  com 
mands  from  mere  counsels.  Also  the  conditional  commands 
are,  when  the  particular  conjuncture  arrives,  of  absolute  ob 
ligation,  and  not  to  fulfill  them  is  disobedience  to  God's  com 
mand  ;  whereas,  in  the  Romish  view,  the  non-fulfillment  of 
the  counsels  does  not  incur  the  least  moral  blame. — When 
Paul  says  of  himself  [1  Cor.  ix,  12-18]  that  he  has  denied 
himself  many  things  to  which  he  had  a  right,  that  he  has 
labored  without  charge,  etc.,  the  Romanists  here  find  a  super 
erogatory  work  to  which  the  Apostle  was  not  obligated.  Paul, 
however,  declares  expressly  that  he  so  acted  in  order  "not  to 
abuse  his  power  [liberty]  in  the  Gospel."  Now  if  the  taking 
advantage  of  his  discretionary  power,  under  these  particular 
circumstances,  would  have  been  a  misuse  of  his  liberty,  then 
the  course  of  action  adopted  by  the  apostle  was  evidently 
simply  his  duty,  and  by  no  means  a  supererogatory  work. — But 
the  greatest  emphasis  is  placed  on  the  utterances  of  Christ 
and  of  St.  Paul  as  to  abstaining  from  marriage :  "  All  cannot  re 
ceive  this  saying,  but  they  to  whom  it  is  given  "  [Matt,  xix,  11], 


116  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  f§  80. 

Now,  that  those  who  do  not  receive  the  saying  can  be 
believing  Christians  who  attain  to .  the  kingdom  of  God, 
although  not  to  that  higher  stage  of  salvation  which  is  con 
ditioned  on  supererogatory  works  as  Romanists  understand  it, 
is  not  only  not  said,  but,  to  the  contrary,  it  is  said  that  the 
self-chastening  in  question  is  done  ' '  for  the  kingdom  of 
heaven's  sake,"  and  hence  plainly  in  the  sense  that  the  same 
is  a  condition  of  attaining  to  the  kingdom  of  heaven.  But 
the  opera  super erogationis  of  which  one  is  found  here,  are  not 
regarded  as  a  condition  to  participation  in  the  kingdom  of 
heaven.  Wh<en  Paul  [1  Cor.  vii]  commends  to  Christians  to 
abstain  from  marriage,  this  is  certainly  not  offered  as  a  univer 
sally-applying  command,  but  manifestly  as  a  mere  counsel 
(comp.  Averse  12),  not,  however,  in  such  a  sense  as  that  indi 
viduals  may  disregard  it  at  perfect  pleasure  and  without 
moral  detriment.  On  the  contrary,  the  apostle  expressly  gives 
the  ground  of  his"  ad  vice:  "I  suppose  that  this  is  good  («aAw) 
for  the  present  distress ;  "  "  such  (as  marry)  shall  have  trouble 
in  the  flesh;  but  I  spare  you."  From  this  it  follows  that 
where  such  a  "present  distress  "  does  not  exist,  or  where  there 
is  full  moral  power  and  readiness  to  endure  the  worldly  trials, 
there  the  advisableness  of  celibacy  no  longer  applies.  In 
general  the  principle  is  valid:  "If  thou  marry  thou  hast  not 
sinned  "  (verse  28) ;  but  in  every  definite  case  the  duty  becomes 
definite  also.  Where  there  is  such  a  pressure  of  "distress," 
and  where  higher  duties  are  to  be  fulfilled,  and  there  is  not 
sufficient  power  to  bear  the  worldly  trials  without  danger  to 
faithfulness,  there  to  marry  is  not  only  not  a  mere  non-sinning, 
and  abstaining  from  marriage  a  good  counsel,  but  the  former 
is  a  positive  sin,  and  the  latter  a  duty.  And  wherever  any 
one,  in  view  of  these  particular  circumstances  does  remain 
unmarried,  he  does  not  thereby  acquire  a  higher,  a  supereroga 
tory  desert,  but  he  simply  fulfills  his  duty.  Such  a  supereroga 
tory  desert  is  moreover  directly  excluded  by  the  fact  that  the 
apostle  proposed  by  freedom  from  marriage  to  preserve  the 
Christians,  in  that  time  of  distress,  from  temporal  "trouble;" 
now  he  who  renounces  an  otherwise  legitimate  privilege  in 
order  to  be  spared  from  worldly  trouble,  cannot  possible  lay 
claim  to  a  special  higher  desert  and  to  a  special  recompense 
for  the  same.  In  fact,  we  can  readily  conceive  of  cases  to  the 


§  80.]  PURE  ETHICS.  117 

contrary,  where  the  greater  desert  would  consist  precisely 
in  the  assumption  of  these  trials  by  marrying,  and  where 
therefore  to  marry  would  be  a  duty. 

According  to  the  Romish  doctrine  there  is  a  difference  be 
tween  God's  holy  will  and  his  moral  law ;  the  former  has  not 
an  unconditional  validity,  but  is,  in  relation  to  man  in  the 
sphere  of  higher  moral  perfection,  simply  a  wish  the  fulfill 
ment  of  which  would  indeed  be  pleasing  to  God,  but  with 
the  non-fulfillment  of  which  He  will  nevertheless  be  satisfied. 
Bellarmin  says,  apropos  to  Matt,  xxii,  36:  "He  who  loves 
God  with  his  whole  heart,  is  not  bound  to  do  all  that  God 
counsels,  but  only  what  He  commands," — an  assertion  that 
must  appear  to  an  evangelical  conscience  as  a  reversal  of  the 
moral  consciousness.  Hirscher,  in  his  earlier  writings,  de 
fended  this  doctrine  thus:  "Love  is  a  command  given  to  all 
without  exception,  whereas  a  specific  degree  of  love  is  not 
commanded ;  rather  is  love,  when  once  really  existing,  left  to 
its  own  nature ;  it  jn  fact  presses  forward  of  its  own  prompt 
ing,  and  it  is  inconsistent  with  its  inner  nature  that  the  rude 
hand  of  a  command  should  impose  upon  it  that  which  it  will 
always  freely  bring  forth  from  its  own  heart ;  hence  love  is  in 
general  an  absolute  duty,  not,  however,  a  specific  higher  degree 
of  love ;  the  absence  of  the  higher  degree  does  not  involve 
also  an  absence  of  righteousness  in  general,  but  only  a  certain 
higher  range  of  the  moral  affections;  so  was  it  with  the  rich 
young  man  in  the  Gospel."  Now,  all  this  is  manifest  soph 
istry.  •  It  is  true  the  degree  of  love  cannot,  for  every  particu 
lar  case,  be  stated  in  a  particular  legal  formula,  still,  however, 
this  degree  is  an  absolute  duty ;  it  simply  depends  on  the 
spiritual  and  moral  culture  of  the  individual,  but  is  in  no 
case  left  to  individual  caprice.  Whoever  loves  God  or  Christ, 
or  father,  mother,  or  consort  less  than  his  moral  culture  en 
ables  him  to  do,  simply  commits  sin ;  and  he  who  loves  with 
all  the  capacity  of  his  soul  does  not  do  any  thing  supereroga 
tory,  but  simply  his  bounden  duty ;  and  it  is  nearer  the  truth 
to  say  that  all  will  have  to  accuse  themselves  of  loving  too 
little,  than  that  any  single  soul  may  boast  of  loving  God  more 
than  with  the  "  whole  heart  and  soul  and  strength."  (In  the 
fifth  edition  of  his  Moral,  II,  p.  328  sqq. ,  Hirscher  so  tones 
down  the  above  teaching  that  only  a  mere  shadow  of  it  remains. ) 


118  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§81. 

The  Romish  doctrine,  in  making  perfection  dependent  on  the 
fulfillment  of  the  counsels,  implies  thereby  that  God's  will, 
as  expressed  in  the  moral  law,  is  not  that  man  should  be  per 
fect,  but  it  is  on  the  contrary  rather  an  individual  courage 
transcending  the  mere  will  of  God,  that  leads  him  out  beyond 
the  moral  goal  set  for  him  by  God  himself.* 

SECTION  LXXXI. 

(<?)  While,  on  the  one  hand,  there  is  no  form  of 
action  which  could  be  to  the  subject,  in  any  given 
moment,  morally  indifferent,  that  is.  neither  in  har 
mony  nor  in  disharmony  with  the  divine  will,  neither 
good  nor  evil,  still,  on  the  other  hand,  no  detinitely- 
frarned  form  of  law  embraces  within  itself  the  total 
contents  of  the  moral  life-sphere;  for  as  every  law 
has  only  contents  of  a  general  character,  while*  the 
moral  activity  itself  is  always  of  an  individual  char 
acter,  so  that  the  moral  actions  of  different  men  that 
fall  under  the  same  moral  law  offer  a  great  diversity, 
hence  the  moral  law  does  not  sustain  to  the  actions 
that  answer  to  it  precisely  the  same  relation  as  an 
idea  to  its  direct  realization  and  manifestation  ;  the 
particular  moral  action  is  not  the  simple,  pure 
expression  and  copy  -of  the  moral  law  itself,  "but  it 
always  contains  something  whicli  does  not  arise  from 
the  law,  but  from  the  individual  peculiarity.  The 
law  as  appropriated  by  the  person  is  fulfilled  only  in 
such  a  manner  as  expresses  also  the  peculiarity  of  the 
person.  Every  moral  action  contains  therefore  two 
elements :  a  general  ideal  one,  the  moral  law,  and  a 
particular  and  more  real  one,  the  personal  element, — 

*  See,  for  the  Komish  view,  Thorn,  Aqu.,  Su?n/na,  II,  I,  qu.  108,  4 ; 
.Bellarmini,  De  Oontrov.  Fid.  II.  2,  De  Monachis,  c.  7  &qq. — For  the  op 
posite  view:  Joh.  Gerhard,  Loci  Tk.,  Loo.  17  (De  Evany.)  o.  15;  M. 
ChemnitiuS)  Loci,  De  Diser.  Piaecept.  et  Cons. 


§  81.]  PURE   ETHICS.  119 

which  latter,  as  the  expression  of  the  personally 
peculiar  character,  has  also  its  perfect  legitimacy. 
God's  moral  will  is  not  that  men  should  be  mere  im 
personal,  absolutely  similar  expressions  of  the  moral 
law,  but  that  the  latter  should  come  to  its  realization 
only  as  appropriated  by  the  particular  personality. 
This  personally- peculiar  element  that  inheres  in  every 
actual  moral  action  cannot  be  embraced  in  any  gen 
eral  legal  formula,  inasmuch  as  in  its  nature  it  is  in 
fact  not  general,  but  a  pure  expression  of  individual 
personality.  Every  real  moral  activity  is  therefore 
the  product  of  a  twofold  freedom  :  of  that  which  sub 
ordinates  the  individual  personality  to  the  law,  and  of 
that  which  does  not  merge  the  personality  into  a  mere 
abstract  idea,  but  preserves  it  in  its  legitimate  peculiar 
ity,  and  which  is  to  a  certain  extent  a  law  unto  itself. 

By  this  notion  of  the  right  of  personality  Christian  Ethics 
differs  from  all  non-Christian  systems,  not  excepting  those  of 
the  Greeks,  notwithstanding  that  the  latter  lay  such  great 
stress  on  the  freedom  of  the  person ;  and  this  feature  is  of 
wide-reaching  significance.  The  decided  rejection  of  the 
notion  that  there  may  be  morally-indifferent  actions  and  condi- 
tions,^ind  the  emphasizing  the  rights  of  personal  individual 
ity,  are  very  essential  to  a  true  understanding  of  the  moral. 
By  insisting  disproportionately  on  the  former,  we  leave  too 
little  room, for  the  peculiarity  of  the  moral  personality,  and 
make  it  necessary  that  for  every  particular  action  there  should 
be  also  a  special  law ;  this  leads  inevitably  to  a  legal  bondage 
hostile  alike  to  all  vital  individuality,  and  to  the  essence  of 
personal  freedom.  This  is  the  stand-point  of  Chinese  and  of 
Talmudic  ethics,  and  to  a  certain  extent,  of  the  casuistics  of 
some  Romish  moralists.  On  the  other  hand,  if  we  insist  too 
exclusively  on  the  peculiarity  of  the  person,  we  incur  the 
danger  of  trespassing  on  the  unconditional  validity  of  the 
law,  to  the  profit  of  the  fortuitous  caprice  of  the  subject, — 
somewhat  as  recently  in  the  period  of  the  sp-called  "gen- 


120  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  81. 

iuses  "  and  of  the  genius-less  freethinkers  who  followed  them, 
all  morality  was  made  to  consist  in  the  uncurbed  develop 
ment  of  the  fortuitous  peculiarity  of  the  individual,  to  which 
peculiarity  every  thing  was  freely  allowed  provided  only  that 
it  was  "genial."  The  only  true  course  is,  in  harmony  with 
the  general  Christian  consciousness,  to  hold  fast  to  both  of 
these  elements. 

At  each  and  every  particular  point  of  time,  the  moral  activity 
and  the  moral  state  are  either  good  or  evil,  either  in  harmony 
with  the  moral  idea  or  not  so.  Although  in  the  same  action 
there  may  be  different  phases  which  have  morally  different 
characters,  and  which  place  good  and  evil  in  close  proximity, 
still  these  contrary  elements  never  coalesce  into  a  moral 
neutrum,  into  a  morally-indefinite  fluctuating  between  good  and 
evil — a  moral  indifference.  An  individual  may"  indeed  be 
morally  undecided,  neither  cold  nor  warm;  this  indecision, 
however,  is  not  of  a  morally-indifferent  character,  but  is  itself 
evil.  There  may  be  different  degrees  of  good  or  evil,  but  not 
an  action  that  is  neither  good  nor  evil.  This  will  become 
self-evident  if  we  fix  our  mind  on  the  fundamental  idea  of 
good  and  evil  as  that  which  answers  to,  or  does  not  answer 
to,  the  divine  will ;  between  these  two  a  third  is  absolutely 
inconceivable,  just  as  in  mathematics  there  is  no  medium  be 
tween  a  correct  and  a  false  result,  or  in  a  clearly  presented 
legal  case  no  medium  between  yes  and  no.  The  bride  who 
cannot  answer  "yes"  to  the  question  as  to- her  willingness  to 
the  marriage,  says  thereby,  in  fact,  "no;"  and  whoev<^%  does 
not  at  any  given  moment  say  "yes"  to  God's  never  neutral 
will,  simply  rejects  it.  The  essentially  self-contradictory  as 
sumption  of  a  morally-indifferent  middle-sphere  between  good 
and  evil,  is  in  itself  anti-moral ;  and  every  immoral  person  is 
only  too  ready  to  transfer  all  his  immorality,  in  so  far  as  he 
cannot  explain  it  into  good,  into  this  pretended  sphere  of  the 
morally  indifferent. 

And  yet  this  so  widely  prevalent  tendency  to  assume  that 
there  is  a  morally-indifferent  sphere  of  action,  is  based  on  an 
actual,  though  falsely  interpreted,  presentiment  of  the  true 
relations  in  the  case.  The  fact  is,  every  feature  in  correct 
moral  action  is  not  directly  and  specifically  determined  by  the 
moral  law,  but  a  very  essential  phase  of  such  action,  has  an- 


§  81.]  PURE   ETHICS.  121 

other  source  than  the  general  law ;  nor  is  the  truly  moral  man 
simply  a  mere  expression  of  the  moral  law,  but,  as  differing 
from  other  equally  moral  men,  he  is  entitled  as  a  person  to 
have  and  retain  his  special  peculiarity.  This  phase  of  the 
moral  life  appears  at  once,  and  very  clearly,  in  that  which 
lies  at  the  basis  of  all  moral  society — wedlock-love.  Love, 
and,  more  specifically,  conjugal  love,  is  a  moral  command ; 
but  the  fact  that  this  love  fixes  itself  exclusively  and  continu 
ously  upon  precisely  this  particular  person,  is  a  personally- 
peculiar  shaping  of  the  moral  law ;  no  law  can  prescribe  what 
particular  person  shall  be  the  object  of  my  conjugal  love ;  and 
the  personal  element  is  here  so  manifestly  legitimate  that  the 
eliminating  of  it — the  indulging  in  love,  not  to  a  particular 
personally-chosen  person,  but  to  the  other  sex  in  general — re 
sults  in  "free"  love,  the  very  quintessence  of  immorality  and 
vulgarity.  Wherever  moral  theories  ignore  the  rights  of  per 
sonality,  there  the  tendency  is  very  strong  to  base  marriage, 
not  on  personal  choice,  but  on  the  choice  of  the  State,  as  in 
ancient  Peru.  Now,  what  is  true  of  conjugal  love  is  true 
also,  though  not  always  in  such  striking  consequences,  of  all 
moral  activity.  When  two  equally  moral  persons  do  the  same 
thing,  fulfill  the  same  law,  it  is,  after  all,  not  the  same  action ; 
nor  indeed  should  it  be ;  what  is  right  and  good  in  one  person 
may,  in  that  particular  form,  be  even  wrong  in  another,  not 
withstanding  that  the  moral  law  is  the  same  for  all.  Paul  em 
ploys  his  moral  activity  in  a  different  manner  from  that  of 
Peter  jnd  James ;  in  fact,  in  the  living  communion  of  Chris 
tians  there  is  presented  not  only  a  great  diversity  of  spiritual 
"gifts,"  but  also  of  personally-moral  idiosyncrasies;  even  in 
the  purely  spiritual  sphere  there  are  manifold  gifts,  but  only 
one  Lord.  The  normal  difference  of  moral  life-tendency  as 
seen  in  the  sous  of  Adam,  and  which  must  have  occasioned 
as  great  a  difference  in  the  fulfilling  of  the  moral  commands 
as  it  did  in  the  manner  of  offering  worship,  presents  a  type 
of  the  manifold  moral  diversities  into  which  the  moral  law  is 
shaped  by  peculiarities  of  personality. 

The  visualization  of  the  personal  element  is  not  to  be  un 
derstood  as  a  something  conflicting  witli  the  divine  law ;  on 
the  contrary,  it  is  in  fact  the  divine  will  that  the  peculiarity 
of  the  personality  be  preserved.  If,  at  first  thought,  it  should 


122  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  82. 

seem  questionable  to  place  along-side  of  the  universally-valid 
law  another  essentially  variable  element,  lest  thereby  the  un 
conditional  validity  of  the  law  be  infringed  upon  and  nega 
tived,  let  it  be  observed,  in  the  first  place,  that  the  personal 
peculiarity  finds  in  the  moral  law  both  its  limits  and  its  moral 
criterion,  so  that  consequently  it  can  never  come  into  antago 
nism  with  the  same,  but  that,  nevertheless,  there  is,  within  the 
scope  of  the  personal  spiritual  life,  a  field  into  which  the  law, 
because  of  its  general  character,  does  not  dictatingly  enter. 
So  long  as  the  moral  consciousness  is  not  yet  truly  mature, 
there  is,  indeed,  in  the  personal  element  of  the  moral,  a  peril 
for  the  moral  life,  inasmuch  as  the  law  cannot  give  specific 
directions  for  every  special  case.  Hence  in  the  Old  Testament 
God  complemented  his  earlier  legislation  by  special  revelations 
of  his  will  through  priestly  and  prophetic  inspiration ;  now, 
however,  since  the  Spirit  of  God  is  poured  out  upon  all  men, 
there  is  no  longer  any  need  of  this  extraordinary  revelation 
of  the  divine  will  in  individual  cases,  for  now  the  human  per 
sonality,  having  come  into  possession  of  the  truth,  has  also 
become  "free  indeed," — is  so  imbued  with  the  divine  law 
that,  in  loving  and  acting  as  prompted  by  its  divinely  purified 
heart,  it  fulfills  the  divine  law  in  the  very  fact  of  developing 
its  personality;  and,  in  fulfilling  the  law,  it  preserves  also  at 
the  same  time  its  personal  peculiarity, — as,  for  example,  in  a 
happy  marriage  there  is  no  longer  any  antagonism  between 
the  fulfilling  of  the  will  of  the  one  party  by  the  other,  and 
the  acting-out  by  each  of  his  own  personal  peculiarity,  but, 
on  the  contrary,  in  each  of  the  two  elements  the  other  is  al 
ready  implied.  And  the  moral  unripeness  of  individual  per 
sons,  that  necessarily  still  exists  even  in  a  normal  condition  of 
humanity,  is  complemented  to  full  moral  safety  by  the  spirit 
of  the  moral  community, — as  in  fact  this  thought  is  vitally 
embodied  in  every  true  Christian  church-communion. 

.   SECTION  LXXXII. 

The  sphere  of  the  personally-peculiar  element  is 
that  of  the  discretionary  or  the  allowed.  That  par- 
tieular  action  which  is  neither  commanded  nor  for 
bidden  in  general  by  any  moral  law  is  an  allowed 


§82.]  PURE   ETHICS.  123 

action  ;  this  circumstance  does  not,  however,  by  any 
means  make  it  of  a  morally-indifferent  character ;  on 
the  contrary,  the  morally-allowed  belongs  per  se  to 
the  morally-gwe?  in  so  far  as  the  development  of  per 
sonal  individuality  is  per  se  legitimate  and  good. 
The  idea  of  the  allowed  relates  therefore  less  to  the 
moral  activity  per  se  and  in  general,  than  rather  to 
the  peculiar  manner  in  which  an  end  that  is  per  se 
good,  that  is,  correspondent  to  the  moral  law,  is 
realized  in  particular,  by  virtue  of  the  personal  pecul 
iarity  of  the  actor ;  and  the  same  moral  law  may  be 
fulfilled  in  many  ways,  the  moral  quality  of  which, 
however,  is  conditioned  in  each  particular  case  by  the 
said  peculiarity.  There  is  nothing  that  is  allowed 
under  all  circumstances  ;  and  all  that  is  allowed,  and 
all  so-called  indifferents  (adiaphord)  are  in  each  par 
ticular  case  either  good  or  evil,  but  never  morally 
neutral,  notwithstanding  that  such  actions  may  be 
per  se,  that  is,  generally  considered,  morally  unde 
termined,  and  neither  commanded  nor  forbidden.  The 
moral  quality  lies  not  so  much  in  the  action  objec 
tively  considered,  as  in  the  disposition  from  which  it 
springs  and  by  which  it  is  attended. — The  sphere  of 
the  allowed  is  different  for  every  stage  of  the  moral 
development  and  for  each  particular  circle  of  life. 
The  farther  the  moral  development  of  the  person  has 
progressed,  that  is,  the  more  the  moral  law  has  be 
come  identified  with  his  personality,  so  much  the 
higher  will  also  be  the  rights  of  his  personal  individu 
ality,  so  much  the  higher  the  morally-personal  free 
dom,  and  consequently  so  much  the  wider  also  the 
sphere  of  the  allowed  ;  to  the  pure  all  things  are  pure. 
Free  movement  within  the  sphere  of  the  alloweckis 
therefore  essential  to  a  truly  moral  life,  and  condi- 


124  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  82. 

tions  the  all-sided  development  thereof;  this  move 
ment  is  per  se  good,  and  it  is  in  itself  a  good,  the 
significance  and  compass  of  which  increase  with  the 
moral  development  of  the  subject.  Herein  lies  the 
contrast  of  the  Christian  freedom  of  the  Gospel  to 
the  bondage  of  the  law. 

This  is  one  of  the  most  important  and,  at  the  same  time, 
most  difficult  points  in  ethical  science,  and  both  for  the  same 
reason,  namely,  from  the  necessity  of  giving  play  to  personal 
freedom,  and  of  doing  this  without  infringing  on  the  uncon 
ditionally-valid  moral  law ;  and  in  exact  proportion  as  a 
system  of  ethics  embraces  the  idea  of  personal  freedom,  will 
it  also  be  able  to  embrace  the  idea  of  the  allowed.  As  in  ex 
press  laws — commands  and  prohibitions — God  manifests  him 
self  as  holy,  so  in  the  concession  of  the  allowed  he  shows  him 
self  as  loving.  As  in  the  fulfilling  of  the  command  and  in  the 
observing  of  the  prohibition,  man  becomes  conscious  of  his 
moral  freedom,  so,  within  the  sphere  of  the  allowed,  this 
freedom  becomes  to  him  an  enjoyment.  Now,  as  freedom  of 
will  is  not  a  mere  antecedent  condition  of  all  morality,  but  also 
itself  a  moral  good,  and  as  every  good  is  per  se  an  enjoyment, 
hence  free-created  beings  have  also  a  moral  claim  upon  the 
legitimate  enjoyment  of  freedom, — not  simply  of  freedom  as 
subject  to  definite  commands,  but  also  of  freedom  as  entitled 
to  free  choice  in  various  directions, — that  is,  they  have  dis 
cretionary  power  to  free  activity;  this  constitutes  in  fact 
the  divinely  conceded  sphere  of  the  allowed,  wherein  mainly 
the  personally-peculiar  element  of  the  moral  comes  to 
virtualization. 

The  very  first  moral  direction,  or  rather  blessing,  that  was 
given  to  man,  contains  implicitly  the  notion  of  the  allowed  or 
discretionary :  ' '  Replenish  the  earth  and  subdue  it  and  have 
dominion  over  the  fish  of  the  sea,"  etc.  This  is  really  not  so 
much  a  command  as  a  blessing, — it  proposes  a  moral  goal,  a 
good.  But  in  this  good  that  is  to  be  sought  after,  namely, 
dominion  over  nature,  there  is  at  the  same  time  implied  a 
command  to  realize  this  supremacy  of  the  rational  spirit 
through  moral  activity.  But  within  this  command  there  lies 
also  a  discretionary  field.  The  particular  manner  Tiotc  man  is 


§^2.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  125 

to  realize  this  dominion,  is  not  expressed  in  the  command, 
but  is  left  to  his  free  personal  self-determination — in  so  far  as 
he  does  not  thereby  come  into  collision  with  other  moral  com 
mands.  Thus,  man  may  use  animals  for  his  own  purposes, 
may  domesticate  them,  train  them,  force  them  to  help  him. 
and  use  them  for  his  nourishment ;  but  as  to  what  choice  of 
them  he  shall  make,  and  as  to  what  kind  of  service  he  shall 
exact  of  them,  this  is  left  to  his  discretion, — here  he  may 
act  freely,  here  he  has  the  full  enjoyment  of  his  freedom. 
For  unfallen  man  there  was  no  need  of  narrower  limits ;  but 
when  depravity  gained  the  upper  hand  these  limits  were 
drawn  closer,  and  the  Mosaic  lajv  gives  very  specific  and 
narrower  bounds  within  which  man,  as  no  longer  morally 
stable,  was  to  exercise  his  freedom  upon  nature. — The  first 
definite  command  of  God  presents  at  once,  along-side  of  the 
expressed  command,  also  the  allowed:  "Of  every  tree  of  the 
garden  thou  mayest  freely  eat ;  but  of  the  tree  of  the  knowl 
edge  of  good  and  evil  thou  shalt  not  eat ; "  whatever  he  may 
choose  of  the  other  trees  is  per  se  good ;  the  choice  he  shall 
make  is  not  prescribed;  simply  a  boundary  is  set,  beyond 
which  begins  evil.  -Now,  we  cannot  say  that  this  choosing 
within  the  given  limits  is  of  a  morally- indifferent  character ; 
rather  is  such  choice,  as  the  realization  of  a  good,  itself 
morally  good;  and  this  goodness  consists  in  the  simple  fact 
that  every  choice  is  good,  and  that  the  choice  of  the  one  is 
not  better  and  not  worse  than  the  choice  of  the  other.  To 
infer  from  this  that  the  single  objects  of  the  choice  are 
morally  indifferent,  would  be  to  overlook  the  fact  that  the 
moral  element  does  not  lie  in  the  object,  but  in  the  choosing 
person,  and  that  the  latter  exercises  his  morality  precisely  in 
the  fact  of  freely  choosing  in  accordance  with  the  peculiarity 
of  his  personality ;  not  to  choose  at  all  would  be  to  despise  the 
divine  gift,  and  hence  immoral. 

In  the  state  of  innocence  the  sphere  of  the  allowed  was, 
notwithstanding  the  indispensable  educative  limitation, 
wider  than  it  was  subsequently  in  the  state  of  sin,  not,  how 
ever,  because  men  were  then  morally  more  contracted,  but 
because  they  were  morally  purer.  In  consequence  of  redemp 
tion  from  the  power  of  sin,  the  now  sanctified  personality 
becomes  also  freer,  and  the  sphere  of  the  allowed  is  enlarged ; 


126  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  82. 

herein  lies  one  of  the  most  essential  differences  between  Old 
Testament  and  New  Testament  ethics.  The  moral  itself  re 
ceives,  in  contrast  to  the  specifically  and  particularizingly 
prescribing  ancient  law,  a  more  general  form,  and  the  whole 
law  and  the  prophets  are  summed  up  in  one  short  command : 
"Thou  shalt  love  the  Lord  thy  God  with  all  thy  heart,  and 
thy  neighbor  as  thyself."  The  sanctified  personality  acts 
within  the  limits  of  the  law  Avith  more  freedom ;  the  bound 
aries  of  the  allowed,  as  established  for  the  state  of  sin,  are 
thrown  more  into  the  back-ground ;  the  laws  as  to  the  Sabbath 
and  as  to  meats  and  other  similar  prescriptions,  are  thrown  into 
a  freer  form  by  the  personality  as  made  free  in  Christ.  In 
stead  of  the  limiting  laws  regulating  the  use  of  "  meats,"  and 
other  material  objects  in  general,  and  which  were  framed 
with  reference  to  the  sinful  impurity  of  man,  Christ  gives  the 
broad  principle :  ' '  Not  that  which  goeth  into  the  mouth  cle- 
fileth  a  man,  but  that  which  cometh  out  of  the  mouth,  this 
detileth  a  man"  [Matt,  xv,  11];  and  Paul  expresses  this  in  a 
still  more  general  form:  "Every  creature  of  God  is  good,  and 
nothing  to  be  refused,  if  it  be  received  with  thanksgiving  " 
[1  Tim.  iv,  4] ;  and  elsewhere  [Titus  i,  15]  he  states  the 
thought  in  its  highest  exaltation:  "Unto  the  pure  all  things 
are  pure ; "  that  is,  the  higher  the  morality  rises,  so  much  the 
wider  becomes  also  the  sphere  of  the  allowed,  and  hence  of 
freedom;  and  upon  him  who  is  morally  perfect,  who  is  in 
wardly  fully  identified  with  the  divine  will,  there  is  no  longer 
imposed  any  degree  whatever  of  outwardly-legal  limitation  to 
the  employment  of  his  freedom ;  for  whatever  he  can  love, 
that  God  loves  also,  and  his  sanctified  personality  cannot 
choose  any  thing  that  would  be  offensive  to  God, — and  such  a 
person  is  again  invested  with  his  original  full  right  of  do 
minion  over  nature,  with  his  full  right  of  free  choice ;  and 
whatever  he  does  of  free  choice,  that  he  does  to  the  glory  of 
God  [1  Cor.  x,  31]. 

The  words  of  Paul  [1  Cor.  vii,  28]  may  serve  as  a  further 
illustration  of  the  notion  of  the  allowed :  ' '  If  thou  marry,  thou 
hast  not  sinned ; "  whereas  on  this  very  occasion  the  apostle 
dissuaded  from  marriage.  The  Christian  lias  a  right  to  mar 
riage  ;  whether,  however,  under  circumstances  that  would 
otherwise  morally  admit  of  it,  he  put  into  execution  this 


§82.J  PURE   ETHICS.  127 

right,  does  not  depend  on  any  particular  legal  prescription, 
but  on  his  own  untrammeled  personal  choice.  Paul  had  dis 
cretionary  ' '  power  to  lead  about  a  sister,  a  wife,  as  well  as 
other  apostles "  [1  Cor.  ix,  5] ;  but  he  did  not  do  so ;  all  have 
the  "power  to  eat  and  to  drink "  [verse  4],  but  our  choice  is, 
within  particular  limits,  left  free.  Ananias  was  at  liberty 
to  keep  his  field  or  not  [Acts  v,  4] ;  what  he  did  was  of  his 
own  election ;  it  was  not  a  moral  law,  but  solely  his  personal 
choice  that  determined  his  conduct.  [Comp.  1  Cor.  vi,  12 ; 
x,  23;  Rom.  xiv,  1  sqq.  ;  xv,  1  sqq.  ;  Matt,  xii,  3,  4.] 

The  sphere  of  the  allowed  is  the  more  special  theater  of 
personal  freedom,  as  distinguished  from  mere  moral  freedom. 
In  obedience  to  the  commanding  law  I  am  indeed  free,  but  this 
freedom  is  nevertheless  a  controlled  one ;  it  is  true,  I  can  will 
and  act  otherwise  than  the  law  wills,  but  I  dare  not ;  and  if  I 
in  fact  do  so,  then  I  violate  the  law,  then  I  am  an  enemy  of 
God;  I  have  the  liberty  but  not  the  right  so  to  act.  Com 
manded  duty  has  consequently,  notwithstanding  the  liberty 
on  which  it  rests,  always  still  a  certain  constraint  in  it ;  and 
though  in  the  mere  literal  fulfillment  of  the  law,  man  becomes 
conscious  of  his  freedom,  yet  he  does  not  come  to  a  proper 
and  full  enjoyment  thereof.  If  God's  law  actually  entered, 
prescribing  and  prohibiting,  into  all  the  details  of  individ 
ual  action,  without,  by  some  concessions,  allowing  play 
ground  for  discretionary  action,  then,  though  man  would  in 
deed  have  the  privilege  of  freely  obeying  or  disobeying  at 
each  particular  moment,  nevertheless  he  would  feel  the  law  as 
a  burden  upon  him ;  and  Paul  was  very  apt  in  expression 
when  he  spoke  of  the  preparatory  law  of  the  Old  Covenant 
as  a  chastening-master.  For  the  simple  reason  that  the  es 
sence  of  man  is  freedom  or  self-determination,  it  is  natural 
for  him  to  aspire  to  become  also  fully  conscious  of  this  free 
dom,  — to  put  it  into  exercise  in  so  far  as  consistent  with  his 
moral  obedience, — and  hence  he  needs  a  free  field  wherein  he 
may  act  with  real  freedom,  without  having  his  actions  in  every 
respect  prescribed  to  him,  without  being  strictly  bound  by 
the  law, — where,  in  a  word,  he  may  say:  I  may  choose  this, 
but  I  do  not  need  to  choose  it ;  and  whether  I  choose  this  or 
that  depends  entirely  on  my  personal  self-determination,  and 
that  too  without  detriment  to  my  moral  duty. 


128  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  82. 

The  sphere  of  the  allowed  stands  in  the  same  relation  to 
that  of  the  express  law  as  pl<iy  to  earnest  activity.  Play 
also  is  an  element  essential  to  the  full  development  of  youth 
ful  moral  life.  With  the  child,  play  is  of  high  moral  signifi- 
cancy,  as  it  is  thereby  that  it  learns  to  comprehend,  to  exer 
cise,  and  to  enjoy  its  full  personal  freedom.  In  learning  and 
working  the  child  is  also  free ;  but  however  good  and  zealous 
of  work  it  may  be,  it  is  nevertheless  conscious  at  the  same 
time  of  being  controlled  by  an  objective  law  to  which  it  must 
adapt  itself;  the  other  and  equally  legitimate  phase  of  its  life, 
that  of  personal  freedom  and  self-determination,  is  revealed 
to  it  in  its  purest  form  only  in  play ;  and  the  child,  even  the 
morally-good  one,  finds  so  great  a  delight  in  play,  for  the 
simple  reason  that  it  thereby  comes  to  the  enjoyment  of  its 
personal  freedom ;  and  the  essence  of  its  enjoyment  lies  in  the 
simple  fact  that  in  its  playful  activity  and  feats  it  is  free  lord 
of  its  own  volitions  and  movements ;  and  those  children  be 
come  spiritually  dull  whose  plays  are  strictly  watched  over  by 
tutorial  intermeddling.  Playing  is  freedom,  however,  only 
in  form,  and  is  without  definite  contents ;  hence  it  is  essen 
tially  only  a  transition-occupation  appropriate  to  the  age  of 
childhood.  The  sphere  of  the  allowed  in  general,  is  the 
wider  and  positive-grown  extension  of  that  play.  Here  be 
longs  recreation  after  labor,  as  in  contrast  to  the  positive 
fulfilling  of  the  law ;  recreation  is  per  se  morally  good  and  its 
essence  consists  in  freedom ;  that  I  select  precisely  this  path 
for  a  promenade,  or  busy  myself  thus  or  thus,  is  neither  pre 
scribed  to  me  by  any  law,  nor  is  that  which  I  do  not  select 
forbidden.  It  is  entirely  erroneous  to  say  that  man  must  be 
totally  swallowed  up  in  his  calling,  that  he  has  a  definite  duty 
to  fulfill  at  every  moment;  this  would  be  a  moral  slavery. 
The  sphere  of  personal  liberty  has  also  its  own  good  right, 
and  for  the  plain  reason  that  man  is  not  merely  an  obligated 
member  of  the  whole,  but  also  a  free  individuality.  Recrea 
tion  per  se  is  therefore  by  no  means  of  a  morally  indifferent 
character,  but  the  particular  mode  of  its  realization  is  discre 
tionary,  and  the  moral  law  is  not,  at  this  point,  of  a  detailed 
particularizing  character,  but  it  simply  hovers  protectingly 
on  the  outskirts,  and  wards  against  abuses, — even  as  a  prudent 
educator  simply  exercises  a  protecting  oversight  over  the 


§  82.]  PURE   ETHICS.  129 

child's  play,  but  does  not  prescribe  the  details.  Man  is  indeed 
moral  at  every  moment  of  his  existence,  and  should  at  each 
moment  be  and  act  morally  right,  but  every  thing  that  he 
does  is  nevertheless  not  a  direct  expression  of  some  moral 
formula,  on  the  contrary  there  is  a  share  therein  that  belongs, 
and  rightly  too,  to  personal  free  choice, — just  as,  in  regard  to 
his  clothing,  a  sensible  man,  though  in  the  main  following 
the  prevalent  mode,  will  nevertheless  reserve  the  privilege  of 
deviating  therefrom  whenever  it  better  suits  his  personal  indi 
viduality. — Even  as  a  fish  in  the  water,  though  indeed  swim 
ming  according  to  the  natural  laws  of  gravitation  and  motion, 
yet,  within  the  scope  of  these  laws,  disports  itself  at  pleas 
ure,  and  exhibits  precisely  in  this  free  motion  the  traits  which 
distinguish  it  from  the  unfree  plant,  so  also  does  man,  within 
the  limits  and  conditions  of  the  moral  law,  comport  himself 
freely  on  the  field  of  the  allowed,  and  in  so  doing  manifests 
the  characteristics  of  the  free  child  of  God  as  in  contrast 
to  servitude  under  a  chastening  law. 

Schleiermacher  (WerJcelTL,  2,  418  sqq.)  denies  the  admissi- 
bility  of  the  notion  of  actions  that  are  merely  allowed.  We 
have,  in  his  opinion,  no  time  for  that  which  claims  to  be,  not 
duty,  but  simply  allowed,  not  morally  necessary,  but  only 
morally  possible  ;  every  performance  of  such  an  action  implies 
a  definite  willingness  to  act  otherwise  than  from  moral  mo 
tives, — which  is  immoral ;  the  idea  of  the  allowed  belongs 
not  to  ethics  but  to  civil  law.  This  we  concede  in  so  far  as 
Schleiermacher  speaks  of  such  actions  as  are  held  to  be  neither 
in  conformity  nor  in  disconformity  to  duty,  that  is  morally 
indifferent,  but  this  is  by  no  means  the  true  idea  of  the  al 
lowed.  However,  we  do  not  admit  the  existence  of  such  a 
class  of  actions ;  but  in  rnorally-gw^  actions  there  is  a  phase 
which  is  not  determined  by  the  law  itself,  and  which  consti 
tutes  the  allowed. — Eothe  (Ethik,  i  Auf.  §  819)  finds  the 
idea  of  the  allowed  in  the  fact  that  particular  forms  of  ac 
tion  cannot  be  referred  with  certainty  to  a  particular  legal 
formula,  so  that  consequently  their  moral  worth  cannot  be 
estimated  thereby  beyond  a  doubt.  The  reason  of  this  may 
lie  in  the  incompleteness  of  the  law;  hence  the  allowed  has  a 
larger  scope  in  the  minority-period  and  with  children ;  but  as 
the  law  becomes  more  definite  and  perfect,  the  sphere  of  the 
VOL.  11—10 


130  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§82. 

allowed  grows  narrower ;  the  more  fully  man  is  as  yet  without 
positive  law,  so  much  the  more  numerous  are  the  actions  that 
are  allowed  to  him ;  but  there  arrives  a  turning-point  in  the 
development  where  the  relation  again  changes,  and  for  the 
reason  that,  then,  the  law  begins  to  retire  into  the  back 
ground  and  to  become  progressively  simpler,  so  that  the 
sphere  of  the  allowed  becomes  again  more  extensive.  With 
this  view  of  Rotlie  we  cannot  coincide.  According  to  it  the 
sphere  of  the  allowed  rests  only  on  a  lack  of  the  law,  and  it 
would  be  more  properly  termed  the  sphere  of  the  morally 
doubtful.  Adam,  however,  to  whom  the  allowed  was  at  once 
presented  in  connection  with  the  commanded  and  the  prohib 
ited,  could  not  possibly  be  in  doubt  as  to  what  would  be 
moral  for  him;  and  the  divine  word  placed  before  him  with 
perfect  definiteness  the  sphere  within  which  he  was  allowed 
entire  freedom  of  action.  And  it  is  utterly  erroneous  to  say 
that  in  childhood  the  sphere  of  the  allowed  is  wider  than  in 
maturer  years.  The  fact  that  many  a  thing  is  allowed  to  the 
.child  which  does  not  become  it  in  later  years,  is  not  a  proof 
that  it  has  a  wider  liberty,  but  only  that  at  this  period  the 
allowed  lies  in  a  different  circle,  and  one  that  answers  to  the 
childish  understanding ;  on  the  contrary,  the  fact  undoubtedly 
is,  that  to  the  child  more  things  by  far  are  not  allowed  which 
are  allowed  to  the  man,  than  conversely ;  and  every  wider 
stage  of  development  brings  to  the  youth  a  consciousness  of 
an  increased  freedom  of  self-determination,  although,  on  the 
other  hand,  it  is  true  that  the  more  earnest  demands  that  are 
made  by  the  growing  positiveness  of  the  life-work,  exclude 
much  of  the  earlier  childish  liberty.  But  that  there  comes 
again  afterward  a  turning-point  when  a  contrary  relation 
begins,  cannot  be  substantiated,  and  moreover  it  conflicts 
directly  with  the  idea  .of  a  constantly  progressive  develop 
ment  toward  moral  maturity. — With  a  similar  tendency,  Stahl 
(Iiechts-philos.  II,  1,  112)  transfers  the  allowed  beyond  the 
sphere  of  the  ethical  proper,  as  being  in  its  fulfillment  morally 
indifferent,  and  into  the  sphere  of  satisfaction,  that  is,  of 
earthly  enjoyment;  hence  he  infers  consistently  enough,  that 
the  sphere  of  the  merely  allowed  must  constantly  decrease  as 
morality  advances,  and  that  satisfaction  is  ultimately  to  be 
sought  only  in  that  which  is  at  the  same  time  a  fulfilling  of 


§82.]  PUEE   ETHICS.  131 

the  moral  law, — as,  for  example,  in  the  exercise  of  benevo 
lence,  etc.  Christian  Friedrich  Schmid  arrives  at  the  same 
conclusion  (Sittenl.,  p.  450  sqq.).  According  to  this  view  the 
sphere  of  the  allowed  would  amount  in  Tact  but  to  a  sphere 
of  the  non-allowed,  and  would  be  simply  a  temporary  con 
cession  to  moral  immaturity  and  weakness.  This  seems  to  us 
incorrect.  For  a  truly  rational  man,  there  can  be  no  other 
satisfaction  than  a  moral  one ;  whatever  he  does  and  receives, 
he  does  and  receives  in  faith  and  love  and  with  thanksgiving, 
and  in  virtue  of  this  thankfulness  every  truly  allowable  enjoy 
ment  becomes  invested  with  a  moral  character.  Stahl  appeals 
to  the  fact  that,  with  the  progress  of  moral  development, 
many  a  thing  that  is  otherwise  allowed  must  be  renounced ; 
but  this  is  only  in  appearance  a  greater  limitation;  for  though 
it  is  true  that  mature  man'  no  longer  allows  himself  many  of 
the  pleasures  of  his  unripe  youth,  yet  he  has  in  their  stead 
other  and  wider  fields  of  ^the  allowed  which  are  denied  to 
youth.  The  greater  freedom  of  the  Christian  as  compared 
with  the  law-observer  of  the  Old  Testament,  is  perfectly  evi 
dent.  It  is  true,  many  things  were  allowed  to  the  Jew,  which, 
because  of  the  higher  morality  introduced,  are  no  longer  al 
lowed  to  the  -Christian,  such  as  the  putting  away  of  wives, 
and  retaliation  [Matt,  v,  Slsqq.],  so  that  it  might  seem  as  if 
the  sphere  of  the  allowed,  and  hence  of  personal  freedo'm, 
were  really  more  narrowly  limited  in  Christianity  than  in 
Judaism.  However,  when  we  reflect  upon  the  above-cited 
declarations  of  Paul*as  to  the  contrast  of  Christian  freedom 
to  the  yoke  of  the  law,  the  matter  will  doubtless  appear  in 
reality  very  differently.  Many  things  were  not  indeed  morally 
allowed  to  the  Jews,  but  only  tolerated  in  them,  because  of 
their  hardness  of  heart;  the  whole  significancy  of  the  moral 
law  was  not  yet  exacted  of  them,  just  as  in  children  many  a 
thing  is  tolerated  and  overlooked  because  of  their  more  lim 
ited  moral  knowledge,  which  in  riper  persons  would  be 
regarded  as  improper  and  blameworthy,  without  implying, 
however,  that  that  which  is  tolerated  is  actually  admitted  as 
allowable.  The  fact  is,  that  as  the  moral  consciousness  grows 
in  clearness,  the  compass  of  duties  grows  wider  also,  so  that 
many  a  thing  that  was  not  previously  a  moral  requirement  now 
becomes  really  such.  This  does  not,  however,  render  the 


132  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  82. 

sphere  of  the  allowed  narrower,  but  in  fact  wider,  inasmuch 
as  every  duty  admits  also  of  a  variety  of  ways  of  fulfillment, 
and  consequently  also  a  diversity  of  ways  of  virtualizing 
our  personal  peculiarities.  Thus,  the  fact  that  consorts  may 
no  longer  discard  each  other,  though  at  first  sight  a  seeming 
limitation  of  the  sphere  of  the  allowed,  yet  really  greatly 
exalts  the  moral  personality  of  both  parties ;  they  have  by  far 
a  higher  right  in  each  other, — may  require  more  of  each 
other,  may  more  strongly  emphasize  the  right  of  their  moral 
personality,  may  each  allow  to  the  other,  and  to  himself  to 
ward  the  other,  more  than  would  be  proper  were  marriage 
merely  an  easily-dissolved  contract, — even  as  the  son  of  the 
house  is  freer  and  may  allow  himself  more  liberty  than  the 
servant,  and  for  the  simple  reason  that  the  former  is  more 
indissolubly  united  with  the  house  than  the  latter; — the 
closer  and  firmer  the  bond,  so  much  the  greater  mutual 
trust  and  confidence,  so  much  wider  also  the  sphere  of  the 
allowed. 

Writers  often  admit  two  different  species  of  the  allowed : 
the  one  is  allowed   because  of  the  meagerness  of  the  moral 
knowledge,  as  with  the  child ;  the  other,  conversely,  because 
of  the  advanced  state  of  the  moral  maturity.     This  difference, 
however,  is  by  no  means  a  real  one ;  and,  when  expressed  in 
this  form,  the  idea  of  the  allowed  has  no  longer  any  unity, 
but  involves  a  direct  antagonism.     Rather  do  both  of  these 
forms  of  the  allowed  fall  under  the  one  notion  of  the  rights  of 
the  personal  peculiarity.     Many  things>are,  for  the  peculiar 
nature  of  the  child,  morally  good,  which  are  not  so  for  a  riper 
person,  and  for  the  simple  reason  that  the  unsuspecting  child, 
in  doing  that  which  would  be  improper  in  those   of   riper 
years,   "thinketh  no  evil,"  and  because  the  sentiment  holds 
good  also  of  unconscious  innocence,   that   ' '  to  the  pure  all 
things  are  pure."     And  the  case  is  essentially  the  same  with 
him  who  is  morally  matured;  simply  the  form  is  different. 
When  man  has  come,  through  moral  growth,  into  a  state  of 
conscious  innocence,  then  also  to  him,  as  being  pure,  many  a 
tiling  is  pure  which  would  be  impure  to  the  sinful. 


§  83.]  PURE   ETHICS.  133 

SECTION  LXXXIII. 

In  so  far  as  the  moral  law  is  made  into  a  moral 
possession  of  the  person,  that  is,  a  constituent  element 
of  his  personally-moral  nature,  it  becomes  to  him  a 
moral  principle,  a  life-rule  or  maxim  •  without  moral 
principles  there  is  no  real  morality.  As  in  this  union 
with  the  personal  peculiarity  the  moral  law  itself 
enters  into  this  peculiarity,  hence  though  it  is  in 
fact  the  same  always  and  for  all  men,  still  the  life- 
rules  that  grow  out  of  this  law,  among  different  per 
sons  and  nations  and  under  different  conditions  in 
life,  must  evidently  also  be  relatively  different. 
The  correct  shaping  of  the  moral  law  into  life-rules 
correspondent  to  the  peculiarity  of  persons  and  cir 
cumstances,  constitutes  the  principal  work  of  practi 
cal  wisdom. — A  disregarding  of  the  rights  of  the 
personal  peculiarity  in  the  moral  life,  and  the  ex 
clusive  application  of  general  and  definitely-expressed 
laws  as  direct  rules  of  life,  result  in  a  servitude  to  a 
legal  yoke  (rigorism)  which  is  incapable  of  producing 
any  truly  personal  morality,  and  has  no  justification 
save  as  a  temporary  disciplinary  process  in  a  state  of 
depravity. 

The  law  is  not  of  man,  but  solely  of  God ;  life-rules  each 
person  makes  for  himself,  not,  however,  independently  of  the 
law,  but  as  based  on  it,  though  peculiarly  modified  by  his 
moral  personality.  The  life-rule  or  maxim  is  the  law  as  in 
carnated,  as  having  become  subjective ;  in  it  man  has  appro 
priated  the  law  as  a  personal  possession, — has  merged  it  into 
his  flesh  and  blood.  My  life-rule,  even  in  so  far  as  it  is  per 
fectly  correct,  is  valid  in  this  definite  form  only  for  me,  and 
it  may  legitimately  enough  be  widely  different  at  different 
life -stages  and  under  different  circumstances.  The  manifold- 
ness  of  life-rules  contributes  to  the  esthetic  richness  of  the 


134:  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  83. 

collective  life  of  the  race ;  in  them  the  moral  idea,  though 
essentially  one,  yet  shapes  itself  into  a  variegated  diversity, 
just  as  the  light  of  day,  though  in  itself  essentially  colorless, 
is  reflected  back  from  flowers  in  a  thousand  varying  tints.  It 
is  true,  the  giving  scope  here  for  freedom  of  will  involves 
also  a  possibility  of  immoral  self-determination ;  and  it  is  also 
true  that  sin,  in  consequence  of  its  essential  deceptiveness, 
seeks  almost  always  to  hide  itself  under  the  cloak  of  pretend- 
edly  legitimate  life-rules,  and  thereby  attains  to  its  seductive 
power,  and  that  the  free  personal  shaping  of  the  moral  law 
into  life-rules  is  possible  without  danger,  only  as  proceeding 
from  pure  and  sanctified  human  nature,  so  that  consequently 
the  severe  discipline  of  the  tutorial  law  appears  as  peculiarly 
appropriate  for  the  divine  training  of  mankind  before  the  full 
realization  of  redemption ;  but  wherever  morality  is  to  become 
perfect,  that  is,  free,  there  the  law  itself  must  become  an 
inner  freely-appropriated  one, — must  be  received  into  the 
personality  as  its  essential  possession,  and  not  as  a  foreign 
element,  but  as  one  that  has  coalesced  with  its  essence;  and 
this  essence  is  a  personally-peculiar  one.  Even  as  natural 
nutriment  does  not  nourish  in  its  natural  crudeness,  but  only 
in  so  far  as  it  is  received  and  really  appropriated  into  the 
natural  organism  and  into  its  peculiarity,  so  is  it  also  with 
the  moral  law.  From  the  possible  danger  of  subordinating 
the  unconditional  validity  of  the  divine  law  to  individual 
caprice,  there  does  not  follow  a  condemnation  of  the  person 
ally-peculiar  molding  of  the  law,  but  only  the  requirement 
that  morality  be  based  not  on  merely  unconscious  or  obscure 
feelings  or  impulses,  but  upon  a  positive  clear  consciousness 
of  God's  will  and  of  one's  own  moral  condition.  The  non- 
governing  of  one's  self,  the  yielding  of  one's  self  to  immediate 
natural  impulses,  the  giving  rein  to  the  spiritual  and  sensuous 
proclivities  that  already  exist  irrespective  of  a  knowledge  of 
the  divine  will,  is  per  se,  even  where  sin  does  not  yet  exist  as 
a  power  of  evil,  immoral.  Moral  life-wisdom  is  not  an  acqui 
sition  attained  to  in  unserious  play ;  and  slavish  submission 
to  an  all-specifying,  rigorous  law  is  easier  than  the  free, 
moral  developing  of  life-rules  on  the  basis  of  the  more  general 
moral  law.  The  less  ripe  the  moral  personality,  so  much  the 
more  dictating  must  be  the  objective  character  of  the  law,  so 


§  83.]  PURE   ETHICS.  135 

much  the  more  severe  must  be  its  discipline  [Gal.  iii,  24] ;  and 
the  riper  the  moral  nature  of  the  person  becomes,  so  much 
the  more  freely  and  independently  may  and  should  he  shape 
the  law  into  life-rules  for  himself. 

It  creates  confusion  to  confound  the  moral  law  with  personal 
life-rules ;  it  inevitably  leads  either  to  legal  bondage  or  to 
moral  laxity.  The  Scriptures  contain  not  only  moral  laws, 
but  also  life-rules  for  particular,  not  generally  existing  life- 
relations,  and  the  regarding  these  latter  as  general  moral  com 
mands  or  counsels  has  sometimes  led  Christian  ethics  into 
error.  When  the  apostle  recommends  celibacy  because  of  the 
"present  distress  "  [1  Cor.  vii,]  he  gives  simply  a  life-rule  for 
particular,  expressly-stated  circumstances;  and,  in  order  to 
prevent  all  misunderstanding,  he  says,  in  relation  to  the  un 
married:  "I  have  no  commandment  of  the  Lord"  [verse  25]. 
By  this,  Paul  does  not  mean  that  he  establishes  on  his  own 
authority  a  new  command  without  reference  to  any  divine  law, 
but  only  that  this  specific  life-rule  is  not  itself  a  divine  law, 
but  rather  simply  a  rule  of  conduct  applying  the  divine  law  to 
particular  circumstances.  The  law  on  which  it  is  based,  how 
ever,  is  no.t:  "Thou  shaltnot  marry,"  but:  Care  for  the  things 
that  belong  to  tRe  Lord,  and  not  for  the  things  that  belong  to 
the  world  [see  verses  32,  34].  Monasticism  made  of  this  life- 
rule  an  objective  law  or  counsel.  The  instructions  of  Christ 
to  the  apostles,  when  sent  out  to  prepare  the  way  for  himself 
[Matt,  x,  9  sqq.]:  "Provide  neither  gold  nor  silver  nor  brass 
in  your  purses,"  etc.,  are  not  given  as  a  moral  rule  to  the 
moral  man  in  general,  but  to  the  apostles  for  this  specific  mis 
sion.  But  the  mendicant  orders  made  of  this  also  an  objective 
law.  When  Christ  required  of  the  rich  young  man  to  sell  all 
that  he  had  and  give  it  to  the  poor,  it  is  perfectly  evident  that 
this  was  simply  a  specific  injunction  for  this  particular  person, 
seeing  that  neither  Christ  nor  the  apostles  required  in  all 
cases,  or  in  any  manner,  the  giving  up  of  possessions,  not 
withstanding  their  strong  emphasizing  of  the  duty  of  charity 
[Acts  v,  4;  1  Tim.  vi,  17  sqq.;  2  Cor.  viii,  1  sqq.].  The  mo 
nastic  vow  of  poverty  is  a  perverted  application  of  this  in 
junction.  To  the  same  category  belong  the  rules  of  propriety 
for  women,  as  given  in  1  Cor.  xi,  5,  10  sqq.,  and  in  part  evi 
dently  also  the  resolution  of  the  Apostolic  Council  [Acts  xv, 


136  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  84. 

20,  29].  In  all  such  rules  either  the  assigned  or  the  directly 
implied  reference  to  particular,  but  not  generally  existing  and 
permanent  relations  and  circumstances,  distinguishes  them 
very  readily  from  general  moral  laws,  the  characteristic  of 
which  is  to  be  valid  absolutely  and  always. 

SECTION  LXXXIV. 

The  moral  law  as  (by  virtue  of  the  particular  form 
into  which  it  is  thrown  by  the  peculiarity  of  the 
moral  person)  requiring  its  realization  in  a  particular 
case,  is  moral  duty;  duty  is,  therefore,  the  law  as 
coming  to  actual  application  in  moral  action  through 
the  moral  life-rules  into  which  it  has  been  shaped  by 
appropriation  into  the  moral  person, — that  is,  it  is 
the  law  as  realizing  itself  under  the  form  of  life-rules, 
in  other  words,  it  is  the  law  as  shaping  itself  in  and 
for  a  particular  person  under  particular  circum 
stances,  and  as  becoming  in  him  a  determining  and 
actuating  power.  I  fulfill  the  law  in,  that  I  do  my 
duty.  The  duties  that  spring  from  the  same  law  are 
different  for  diiferent  men  and  for  different  circum 
stances. — As,  therefore,  duty  is  the  product  of  two 
elements,  the  moral  law  and  the  peculiarity  of  the 
person,  and  as  the  moral  laws  collectively,  though 
existing  under  the  form  of  a  plurality,  must  yet  of 
necessity  constitute  a  concordant  whole,  hence,  if  we 
leave  out  of  view  the  actuality  of  sin,  a  conflict  of 
different  duties  with  each  other  (collision  of  duties)  is 
utterly  impossible.  The  distinction  of  conditional 
and  unconditional  duties  is  not  correct,  and  rests  on  a 
confounding  of  the  notions  of  law  and  duty. 

The  moral  person  does  not  directly  and  strictly  fulfill  the 
law,  but  simply  his  duty.  Even  ordinary  speech  indicates 
the  difference;  we  do  not  say,  "my  law,"  but  always,  "my 
duty."  The  law  per  se  is  general  and  above  man;  duty  is  al- 


§  84.]  PURE  ETHICS.  137 

ways  special  and  personal.  No  one  person  can  do  the  duty  of 
another ;  and  what  is  duty  for  me,  may  be  a  violation  of  duty 
for  another.  The  law  alone  is  directly  prescribed ;  to  what 
particular  form  of  action  this  law,  as  appropriated  into  my 
personality,  determines  or  obligates  me,  is  not  directly  ex 
pressed  in  the  law,  but  is  the  result  of  a  moral  judgment  in 
view  of  my  special  moral  peculiarity  and  circumstances.  We 
cannot,  therefore,  with  propriety  institute  a  contrast  between 
conditional  and  unconditional  duties.  The  condition  is  al 
ready  implied  in  the  relation  of  the  fulfillment  of  the  law  to 
the  fulfillment  of  duty ;  what  I  may  not  or  cannot  now  do,  is 
simply  not  my  duty ;  at  another  time,  however,  this  same  form 
of  action  may  become  my  duty.  Any  and  every  duty  may, 
with  as  much  propriety,  be  called  conditional  as  uncondi 
tional  ;  in  its  becoming  a  duty  it  is  always  conditional ;  when 
ever,  however,  it  actually  presents  itself,  there  there  can  no 
longer  be  any  question  of  conditionality.  Whoever  is  in  a 
condition  to  rescue  a  person  from  imminent  life-peril,  has  the 
unconditional  duty  of  doing  so ;  whoever  cannot  do  so,  has 
no  duty  whatever  in  the  matter ;  between  these  two  positions 
there  is  no  third  one  possible.  With  like  propriety  we  may 
say  also  that  the  law  is  at  the  same  time  conditional  and  un 
conditional,  but  in  a  converse  relation;  in  its  essence  it  is 
unconditional,  in  the  manner  of  its  fulfillment  it  is  always 
conditional.  The  law,  "Thou  shalt  love  thy -neighbor  as 
thyself,"  is  in  its  moral  contents  unconditional;  every  human 
being  is  an  object  of  this  love,  but  how  this  love  is  to  be  exer 
cised,  in  what  manner  it  is  actually  to  manifest  itself  in  actions, 
that  is,  to  what  definite  duties  it  shall  lead,  this  depends  on 
manifold  conditions  not  contained  in  the  law  itself ;  to  one's 
husband  or  wife,  or  to  parents,  one  owes  a  very  different  love 
from  that  due  to  friends,  and  the  very  same  sacrificing  love 
will  manifest  itself  very  differently  toward  the  moral  and 
toward  the  immoral. 

When  the  law  is  presented  in  the  general  form  of  command 
or  prohibition,  the  manners  in  which  the  manifold  relations 
of  life  make  it  the  duty  of  different  persons  to  fulfill  it  are  so 
different,  that  there  may  even  arise  an  appearance  of  contra 
diction.  The  fact  is,  however,  that  for  a  real  conflict  (collision) 
pf  duties  (a  subject  which  has  from  of  old  been  a  favorite  and 


138  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  84- 

much  discussed  one  among  moralists)  there  is  in  a  normal  state 
of  humanity  no  possible  place.  Moral  laws  cannot  come  into 
conflict  with  each  other,  otherwise  the  idea  of  the  moral,  and 
the  moral  order  of  the  universe  itself,  would  be  undermined ; 
and  there  is  just  as  little  ground  for  a  conflict  between  duties, 
seeing  that  their  conditionment  is  in  fact  based  in  part  on  the 
personal  peculiarity  and  special  circumstances  of  the  subjects. 
The  personal  peculiarity  of  a  sinful  man  may  indeed  come 
into  conflict  with  the  moral  law ;  but  in  so  far  as  this  is  the 
case  it  forms  no  legitimate  element  in  the  construction  of  the 
notion  of  duty ;  rather  will  it  become  our  duty  in  many  re 
spects  to  counteract  this  element.  But  all  legitimate  personal 
peculiarity  is  itself  formed  in  harmony  with  the  uioral  idea, 
and  hence  cannot  come  into  conflict  therewith.  For  an  irre 
concilable  collision  of  duties  there  is,  therefore,  nowhere  any 
manner  of  possibility. 

The  idea  of  duty  is  often  otherwise  understood  than  as  here 
presented.  Duty  is  frequently  declared  to  be  the  divine  law 
itself.  Now  if  by  this  is  meant,  that  which  God  requires  of 
us  in  each  particular  case,  and  that  too  of  each  individual  in 
particular,  then  it  would  be  correct, — this,  however,  is  not 
expressed  by  the  term  "law ; "  but  if  it  means,  that  duty  and 
the  divine  law  are  identical,  then  it  is  incorrect.  More  definite 
is  the  statement,  that  duty  is  the  manner  of  action  which  con 
forms  to  01  harmonizes  with  the  law.  The  Kantian  school 
explains  ducy  as  that  which,  according  to  the  law,  should 
take  place,  or  which,  by  virtue  of  a  law,  is  practically  neces 
sary,  or  which  answers  to  an  obligation, — obligation  being 
understood  as  the  necessity  of  an  action  in  consequence  of  a 
moral  law.  All  these  statements  are  inadequate,  inasmuch  as 
the  personal  peculiarity  is  left  out  of  the  account,  so  that  con 
sequently  no  difference  whatever  is  made  between  duty  and 
law;  and  as  to  how  obligation  differs  from  duty  we  are  ut 
terly  unable  to  see.  Schleiermacher  in  his  System  (§  112  sqq.~) 
defines  duty  as  "the  form  of  conduct  in  which  the  activity 
of  the  reason  is  at  the  same  time  special,  as  directed  upon  the 
particular,  and  also  general,  as  directed  upon  the  totality," 
or,  the  law  of  the  free  self-determination  of  the  individual  in 
relation  to  the  common  moral  life-task  of  the  race,  or,  the 
,  formula  for  the  guidance  of  rationality  in  single  actions  in 


§  85.]  PURE  ETHICS.  139 

the  realizing  of  the  highest  good.  That  these,  in  the  main, 
correct  statements,  are  still  too  indefinite,  is  shown  even  by 
their  numerousness.  Similarly,  but  more  definitely,  Rothe  ex 
plains  duty  as  that  definite  form  of  action  which  is  required 
by  the  moral  law  as  under  the  form  impressed  upon  it  by  the 
individual  instance. 

SECTION  LXXXV. 

To  duty  on  the  part  of  the  moral  subject,  corre 
sponds  right  on  the  part  of  the  law.  My  duty  is  to 
fulfill  the  right  of  the  moral  law,  that  is,  the  right  of 
God  to,  or  his  claim  upon,  me.  The  substance  of 
dutiful  action  is  therefore  justice  or  right,  and  the 
product  of  this  action  is  the  right,  i.  e.,  the  realized 
claim.  Hence  dutiful  action  is  per  se  right-doing. 
Duty  and  .right  call  for  each  other, — are  but  two 
phases  of  the  same  thing;  to  every  right  there  cor 
responds  a  duty,  and  conversely, — simply  the  subjects 
are  different ;  every  duty  is  the  expression  of  a  right ; 
another's  right  in  regard  to  me  is  for  me  a  duty,  and 
to  the  fulfillment  of  another's  duty  in  regard  to  me  I 
have  a  right ;  the  two  ideas  are  absolutely  correlative 
and  co-extensive.  In  virtue  of  duty  I  accomplish  the 
moral,  for  the  law  has  a  right,  a  claim,  upon  me; 
in  virtue  of  right  the  moral  is  accomplished  upon 
me  ;  in  the  fulfilling  of  duty  /keep  the  law;  in  my 
accomplishing  of  the  right  the  law  keeps  me.  The 
fulfilling  of  my  duty  obtains  for  me  a  right  to,  or 
claim  upon,  the  moral  law  in  so  far  as  this  law  is  an 
element  of  universal  order,  namely,  the  right  to  be  a 
real,  living,  and  hence  free,  member  of  the  moral 
whole, — in  other  words,  a  moral  claim  on  the  just 
recompense  of  God.  There  is,  morally,  no  other 
right  of  an  individual  than  such  as  is  conditioned  by 
a  corresponding  fulfillment  of  duty  on  his  part; 


140  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§85. 

rights  without  duties  would  be  a  reversing  of  moral 
world-order.  God  has  an  absolutely  unlimited  right 
because  he  is  absolutely  holy,  and  man,  as  related  to 
God,  is  under  absolute  obligations.  All  right  has 
therefore  its  basis  in  God's  right  and  in  God's  love. 
Hence  in  the  Scriptures  the  notion  of  duty  is  nearly 
always  presented  as  an  indebtedness , — as  the  right  of 
God  to  man,  as  what  man  owes  to  God.  God's  right 
eousness  has  a  right  to  righteousness  in  man,  and 
hence  righteousness  is  man's  duty  ;  those  who  fulfill 
their  duty  are  therefore  the  righteous. 

As  duty  is  not  merely  of  a  subjective  character,  a  mere 
utterance  of  the  individual  consciousness,  but  the  law  as 
appropriated  by  the  person,  so  also,  and  equally  emphatically, 
is  right  also  not  a  mere  subjective  something  with  no  better 
basis  than  a  merely  fortuitous  power  of  the  individual.  Every 
right  of  the  individual  is  a  special  expression  of  the  right  of 
the  whole,  and  is  valid  only  in  so  far  as  this  individual  is  in 
moral  harmony  with  the  whole.  Whoever  by  undutif  ul  conduct 
dissolves  his  union  with  the  moral  whole,  loses  thereby,  in 
like  measure,  his  right  to  or  claim  upon  the  whole.  Duty  and 
right  are  both  an  expression  of  the  moral ;  the  former  is  the 
moral  as  subjective  obligation,  the  latter  is  the  moral  as  ob 
jective  requirement ;  both  manifest  the  essence  of  the  moral 
as  an  essential  law  of  collective  being.  The  individual  has 
duties  and  rights  only  as  in  vital  union  with  the  whole.  I 
have  duties  and  rights,  not  in  virtue  of  being  a  mere  indi 
vidual,  but  in  virtue  of  the  fact  that  the  totality  of  being 
bears  a  moral  character.  From  this  it  follows  at  once,  that 
there  can  be  true  duties  and  rights  only  where  the  morality  of 
the  whole  is  based,  not  merely  on  the  morality  of  the  indi 
vidual  persons, — which  would  be  a  mere  arguing  in  a  circle, — 
but  where  it  is  based  on  t»he  holiness  of  the  personality  of 
God.  I  can  keep  and  fulfill  the  law  only  when  the  law  keeps 
and  fulfills  me;  I  can  do  my  duty  only  when  I  therein  recog 
nize  a  right  or  claim  of  the  moral  whole,  and  hence  of  the  holy 
God,  upon  me.  An  impersonal  whole  has  no  right  to,  nor 


§  85.]  PURE   ETHICS.  141 

claim  upon,  the  personal  spirit;  from  such  a  servitude  Chris 
tianity  has  definitively  emancipated  human  thought ;  nor  has 
one  man,  as  upon  his  fellow,  any  other  right  or  claim  than 
such  as  he  derives  from  God ;  that  is,  he  has  it  only  by  the 
grace  of  God ;  that  man  has  per  se  a  right  upon  his  fellow, 
irrespective  of  God,  is  an  un-Christian  view;  "Be  not  ye  the 
servants  of  men  "  [1  Cor.  vii,  23] ;  this  is  Christian  right  and 
Christian  freedom. 

In  such  a  moral  world-order  where  duty  and  right  are  ab 
solutely  correlative,  where  right  extends  as  far  as  duty,  and 
duty  as  far  as  right,  every  one  receives  strictly  his  own  light 
— his  due.  The  dutiful  man  has  a  right  upon  the  moral 
whole, — a  right  to  have  his  personality  respected, — and  it  is 
thus  that  the  moral  law,  the  moral  world-order,  realizes  itself 
on  man ;  it  upholds  in  a  just  and  honorable  position  him  who 
has  upheld  it.  He  who  gives  honor  to  God,  to  him  God  gives 
also  his  honor.  Also  he  who  violates  duty  receives  his  right ; 
every  punishment  is  the  fulfilling  of  the  right  of  God  and  of 
the  collective  universe  upon  the  individual ;  the  criminal  has  a 
right  to  the  punishment ;  when  the  criminal  comes  to  his  right 
mind  he  demands  himself  his  own  punishment,  and  a  child 
that  is  not  totally  perverted  finds  a  moral  tranquillization  in 
suffering  the  punishment  it  deserves, — it  even  calls  for  it. 

The  notion  that  the  fulfillment  of  moral  duty  acquires  for 
man  a  claim  upon  the  moral  order  of  the  world,  and  hence 
upon  God,  is  emphatically  rejected  by  Schwarz  (Eth.  I," 
p.  199),  who  even  declares  such  a  view  as  blasphemous ;  God 
alone,  he  holds,  is  the  absolutely-entitled  One;  man  has,  as 
toward  God,  simply  duties,  but  no  rights;. God  only  can  have 
claims  upon  us,  not  we  upon  God.  And  he  appeals  for  sup 
port  to  Rom.  ix,  20;  xi,  35  sqq.;  Job  ix,  12;  Luke  xvii,  10. 
The  first  two  passages,  however,  relate  to  the  impossibility  of 
fathoming  the  eternal  divine  counsel,  and  declare  any  doubt 
as  to  God's  holiness  and  righteousness  as  unjustifiable ;  more 
over  all  of  them  relate  exclusively  to  the  condition  of  sinful- 
ness,  in  which  we  of  course  concede,  in  harmony  with  Script 
ure,  that  all  salvation  rests  exclusively  on  the  undeserved  and 
compassionate  mercy  of  God.  We  are  now  speaking,  however, 
of  man  as  not  yet  under  sin,  of  the  moral  life  in  its  unclouded 
purity,  and  here  the  matter  stands  very  differently.  If  God's 


142  -  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  35. 

righteousness  is  not  a  mere  empty  figure  of  speech,  it  must 
form  the  basis  of  a  moral  right ;  we  cannot  doubt  that  God 
rewards  each  according  to  his  moral  conduct;  and  when  a 
truly  moral  creature  receives  from  God  a  just  reward  [Rom.  ii, 
6,  7,  13],  this  is  not  a  mere  compassionating  gift,  but  it  is 
justice,  and  the  creature  has,  in  virtue  of  his  righteousness,  a 
claim  upon  such  a  reward.  It  is  indeed  a  gracious  gift  of  the 
Creator,  that  he  has  made  the  creature  thus  noble,  that  it  is 
permitted  to  bear  in  itself  God's  own  image ;  but  that  God 
regards  and  treats  the  creature  that  has  become  positively 
holy,  in  view  of  and  in  reference  to  that  fact,  is  simply  justice. 
As  the  sinner  receives  but  his  right  when  the  divine  punish 
ment  falls  upon  him,  so  also  the  sinless  creature  receives  but 
his  right  when  he  is  an  object  of  the  divine  pleasure.  To 
think  otherwise  on  this  point  would  be  to  overthrow  our 
notion  of  a  holy  and  just  God.  The  Scriptures  express  very 
distinctly  this  thought  of  the  right  of  the  moral  person  upon 
God,  even  in  circumstances  where,  because  of  sin,  there  can 
no  longer  be  any  question  of  a  right  strictly  speaking, — so  that, 
then,  it  is  in  fact  a  pure  grace  that  God,  notwithstanding 
this,  yet  concedes  to  man  such  rights.  Of  the  justifying  faith 
of  Abraham,  Paul  says,  ' '  To  him  that  worketh  is  the  reward 
not  reckoned  of  grace,  but  of  debt "  [Rom.  iv,  4] ;  if  therefore 
man  should  really  and  truly  fulfill  the  law  of  God,  then  his 
reward  would  fall  to  him  in  due  course  of  justice.  The  infer 
ence  of  the  apostle,  as  to  the  worth  of  faith  for  sinful  man, 
would  not  have  tho  least  basis  should  we  presume  to  regard 
this  declaration  of  his  as  per  se  meaningless  and  impossible ; 
and  this  holds  good  in  the  fullest  sense  of  man  as  untouched 
by  sin,  as  also  it  is  true  of  the  Son  of  man.  The  true  and  real 
fulfilling  of  the  law  has  in  fac't  eternal  life  as  its  just  reward 
[Matt,  xix,  17] ;  the  only  question  is,  as  to  whether  in  fact  any 
person  perfectly  fulfills  the  law  as  Christ  did.  The  doctrine 
-of  grace  for  the  redeemed  is  not  interfered  with  by  that  of  a 
claim  of  the  moral  man  upon  God,  but  receives  in  fact  thereby 
its  proper  foundation.  In  the  idea  of  the  Covenant  which  God 
made  with  the  Patriarchs,  and  as  to  which  li^e  himself  says : 
' '  I  have  made  a  covenant  with  my  chosen,  I  have  sworn  to 
David  my  servant:  Thy  seed  will  I  establish  forever,"  etc., 
there  is  contained  also  the  idea  of  a  right  upon  God  as  gra- 


§  85.]  PURE  ETHICS.  143 

ciously  conceded  even  to  sinful  man,  provided  he  should  obey 
the  voice  of  God  and  keep  his  commandments  [Psa.  Ixxxix,  4 ; 
Exod.  ii,  24;  xix,  5;  Deut.  vii,  8,  9,  12;  ix,  5].  That  God 
should  make  such  a  covenant,  is  pure  grace ;  but  now  that 
He,  the  truthful  One,  has  made  it,  it  follows  that  those  who 
keep  it  acquire  thereby  a  right  to  its  fulfillment  on  the  part 
of  God;  and  hence  the  pious  of  the  Old  Covenant  make 
appeal  in  their  petitions  to  the  promises  of  God  [Gen.  xxxii, 
12;  Exod.  xxxii,  13;  Deut.  ix,  26  sqq.].  The  great  emphasis 
which  the  Scriptures  place  upon  the  thought  of  the  covenant 
of  God  with  man,  which  is,  in  fact,  more  than  a  promise,  im 
plies  very  clearly  that  here  the  moral  character  of  God,  as  well 
as  that  of  man,  is  essentially  involved.  We  need  only  sepa 
rate  from  the  idea  of  a  right  all  that  the  sinful  heart  has 
associated  therewith,  all  that  is  presumptuous  and  self-seek 
ing,  and  it  will  no  longer  have  the  least  feature  that  could 
give  offense  to  the  most  reverential  mind.  The  Scriptures 
present  the  thought  of  duty  as  intimately  connected  with  the 
idea  of  right ;  and  this  involves,  in  fact,  the  profoundest  con 
ception  of  the  moral.  Here,  all  dutiful  living,  on  the  part  of 
man,  is  a  right  of  God  upon  him  (DWMp),  a  paying  of  his  debt 
to  God, — it  is  60«A#, — and  man  is  debtor  to  God  and  to  the 
brethren  [Rom.  i,  14;  viii,  12;  Luke  xvii,  10;  comp.  1  Cor. 
vii,  22] ;  and  God's  laws  are  an  expression  of  the  rights  of 
God  [Lev.  xviii,  4,  5 ;  xix,  37 ;  xxv,  18 ;  Deut.  vii,  12 ;  xxxiii, 
10;  Psa.  xix,  10;  1,  16;  cv,  45;  cxix,  5  sqq.;  Isa.  xxvi,  9;  and 
others].  By  virtue  of  his  moral  nature,  of  the  likeness  of  God 
that  was  impressed  upon  him,  man  becomes  in  turn  a  debtor, 
— is  under  obligation  to  bring  this  nature  into  realization,  to 
fulfill  the  claim  or  right  of  God  upon  him ;  and  he  who  ful 
fills  this  right  is  consequently  just  or  righteous:  "He  hath 
showed  thee,  O  man,  what  is  good  (the  moral  law) ;  and  what 
doth  the  Lord  require  of  thee  (as  duty)  but  to  do  justly  (the 
right)  and  to  love  mercy  ? "  [Micah  vi,  8 ;  comp.  Deut.  x, 
12,  13].  Thus,  as  it  appears,  the  Scriptures  present  rather  the 
objective  phase  of  the  moral,  the  right  of  God  and  of  the 
divine  law  upon  man ;  whereas  the  moralists  of  recent  times, 
especially  since  Kant,  devote  their  attention  rather  to  its  sub 
jective  phase,  as  duty. 
In  the  manner  of  viewing  the  relations  between  right  and 


144  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§85. 

duty  there  often  prevails  some  confusion ;  right  is  often  con 
founded  with  discretionary  power,  whereas,  in  fact,  the 
former  is  more  than  the  latter,  and  contains  an  actual  require 
ment  ;  or,  right  is  regarded  as  the  mere  possibility  or  liberty 
to  act.  Furthermore  a  great  difference  is  frequently  made 
between  right  and  the  right,  the  two  being  taken  as  capable 
of  excluding  each  other,  so  that  I  may  have  a  right  and  yet 
its  execution  be  not  right.  This,  in  so  far  as  the  question  is 
as  to  moral  right,  is  manifestly  absurd.  It  is  true,  according 
to  civil  law,  I  may  have  a  so-called  right  in  the  exercising  of 
which  I  shall  do  wrong ;  but  of  such  civil  right  we  are  not 
here  speaking;  in  the  sphere  of  morality  I  can  never  have  a 
right  to  what  is  wrong,  and  I  can  never  exercise  a  right  with 
out  doing  the  right.  I  have  a  right  only  in  so  far  as  the 
moral  law  takes  me  under  the  protection  of  the  moral  order 
of  the  universe ;  I  have  a  right  upon  another  in  so  far  as  he 
has  a  moral  duty  to  fulfill  toward  me ;  I  have  right  conduct 
in  so  far  as  I  myself  realize  the  moral  law ;  and  this  I  do  in 
fact  when  I  do  not  throw  away  my  own  moral  right,  but. 
maintain  it  intact.  Whenever  I  have  a  moral  right,  then  is  it 
also  right  to  realize  it. 


§  86.]  PURE   ETHICS.  145 


CHAPTER  III. 

THE   OBJECT  OF  THE   MORAL  ACTIVITY. 

SECTION  LXXXVL 

As  the  moral  is  the  free  realizing  of  the  good,  and 
as  the  good  itself  is  the  inner  law  and  nature  of  the 
divinely-created  All,  hence,  in  every  moral  activity, 
man  comes  into  relation  to  this  All,  and  this  All — as 
well  as  also  God  himself — becomes  in  its  entire  exist 
ence,  so  far  as  within  the  scope  of  man,  an  object  of 
.the  moral  activity,  namely,  either  in  that  as  a  good 
it  is  brought  into  unity  with  the  moral  person,  or 
appropriated  by  the  same, — or  in  that,  as  material 
capable  of  being  modified,  it  is  formed  by  the  moral 
activity. 

I.  The  moral  life  relates  primarily  always  to  God. 
God  can  be  an  object  of  the  morally-pious  activity 
only  in  so  far  as  he  is  conceived  of  as  a  personal 
spirit ;  to  an  impersonal  God  there  can  be  no  moral 
relation.  This  moral  activity  is  not  a  mere  receiv 
ing,  but  it  is  a  real  acting,  namely,  in  that  man 
not  only  turns  himself  toward  God,  but  in  that  he 
also  turns  God  toward  himself;  the  good  that  is  real 
ized  by  this  activity  becomes  actual,  however,  not  in 
God,  but  in  us,  in  that  it  brings  us  into  communion 
with  God,  so  that  consequently  all  pious  activity  is 
at  the  same  time  a  moral  producing  for  ourselves. — 
As  God  upholds,  and  rules  in,  all  creatures,  hence 
all  moral  activity  without  exception  stands  in  relation 

VOL.  II— 11 


146  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  86. 

to  God,  arid  all  realizing  of  the  good  works  com 
munion  with  God.  All  that  is  moral  is  also  pious, 
and  all  that  is  pious  is  also  moral.  Hence  all  duties 
are  also  duties  to  God,  and  religious  duties  do  not 
stand  along-side  of  other  duties,  but  they  include 
them  in  themselves. 

Every  view  is  defective  which  excludes  from  the  moral  life 
any  thing  whatever  that  comes  into  the  life-sphere  of  man. 
This  is  precisely  that  which  distinguishes  rational  creatures 
from  the  irrational,  namely,  that  the  latter  have  always  sim 
ply  a  quite  definite  and  restricted  scope  for  their  life-mani 
festation,  while  every  thing  else  is  indifferent  to  them,  and  as 
good  as  not  existing,  whereas  rational  creatures  have  an  in 
terest  in  all  that  exists,  and  bring  it  into  some  manner  of 
relation  to  themselves.  Perfect  indifference  to  the  world  is 
Indian,  but  not  Christian,  wisdom ;  God  is  indifferent  to 
nothing,  and  for  this  reason  moral  man,  the  image  of  God,  is 
so  also.  The  collective  All  and  God  himself  constitute  the 
life-sphere  of  the  moral.  Because  of  the  inner  unity  of  all 
things,  every  moral  act  not  only  reverberates  in  the  whole 
universe,  and  there  is  joy  among  the  angels  in  heaven  over 
one  sinner  that  repents,  but  this  act  itself  acts  upon  the  All, 
for  all  that  is  good  and  all  that  is  capable  of  good  belong 
together  in  one  great  unity.  The  declaration :  "  Whether  life, 
or  death,  or  things  present  or  things  to  conic — all  are  yours  " 
[1  Cor.  iii,  22],  holds  good  in  its  fullest  sense  of  the  moral 
life,  although  indeed  our  moral  bearing  toward  the  different 
forms  of  existence  is  correspondingly  different;  to  nature  the 
moral  spirit  is  related  as  dominating,  to  God  as  obeying. 

The  conceiving  of  God  himself  as  an  object  of  the  moral 
activity  is  a  fundamental  point  in  Christian  ethics.  It  is 
true  the  heathen  also  required  reverence  toward  the  gods,  but 
this  exercise  of  piety  did  not  rise  to  a  dominating  power  over 
the  entire  moral  life.  In  recent  times  it  has  become  a  favorite 
view  to  regard  the  moral  as  not  relating  to  God  at  all,  but 
only  to  man,  or  indeed  also  to  nature ;  it  is  even  said  that 
God  cannot  be  an  object  of  the  moral  activity,  seeing  that 
because  of  his  unapproachable  sublimity  he  must  be  inaccess- 


§  86.]  PURE   ETHICS.  147 

ible  to  all  human  influence.  Evidently,  with  this  view  of  the 
matter,  prayer  is  narrowed  down  to  a  mere  pious  exercise 
without  any  other  possible  efficacy  than  to  benefit  the  person 
so  exercising ;  it  would  be  more  consequential,  however,  for 
those  who  think  thus  to  follow  Kant,  and  discard  prayer  alto 
gether  as  empty  and  meaningless.  It  does  not  come  within 
our  scope  to  answer  here  the  question,  how  the  answering  of 
prayer  is  reconcilable  with  the  eternally-immutable  nature  of 
God,  but  we  simply  accept  from  dogmatics  the  unquestion 
ably  Scriptural  principle,  that  God  actually  does  hear  and 
answer  prayer,  that  prayer  and  its  answering  are  not  a  delu 
sion,  but  that  proper  prayer  really  and  truly  conditions  the 
answering  of  the  petitions,  and  that  consequently  it  has  a 
positive  influence  on  the  bearing  of  God  toward  man.  True 
prayer  is  impossible  so  soon  as  I  entertain  the  opinion  that  it 
has  no  effect,  that  the  gracious  turning  of  God  toward  me  is 
not  in  some  way  conditioned  thereby.  This  does  not  imply 
that  God  comes  into  any  manner  of  dependence  on  man; 
whatever  he  does  is  eternally  self-determined,  but  it  is  deter 
mined  in  view  of  the  moral  bearing  of  man  as  divinely  gifted 
with  rational  freedom.  In  this  sense,  prayer  is  really  a  moral 
activity  in  relation  to  God,  and  God  is  a  real  object  of  the 
same.  Prayer  is  the  beginning  and  the  end  of  all  moral 
activity.  The  sentiment:  "Pray  and  work,"  holds  good  of 
all  and  every  moral  life ;  the  two  do  not  stand  beside  each  other, 
but  consist  only  in  and  with  each  other. 

God,  as  living  and  personal,  cannot  sustain  a  relation  of 
indifference  to  human  conduct.  If  we  can  speak  in  any  prop 
er  sense  of  a  displeasure  of  God  at  sin,  of  a  wrath  of  God 
against  sin,  then  must  also,  conversely,  the  pleasure  of  God 
in  the  moral  conduct  of  man  be  of  a  real  character,  and, 
hence,  in  some  manner,  conditioned  by  said  conduct.  The 
moral  activity  as  relating  to  God  is  per  se  necessarily  pious  ; 
but  to  presume,  for  this  reason,  to  exclude  it  from  the  sphere 
of  the  moral,  would  be  very  inconsistent ;  for  in  fact  it  takes 
place  with  freedom,  and  with  moral  consciousness  and  with 
moral  purpose,  and  it  is  frequently,  in  the  Scriptures,  ex 
pressly  required  as  a  duty ;  and  all  duties  are  moral.  But, 
on  the  other  hand,  all  duties  are  also  pious,  inasmuch, as  mo 
rality  is  always'  in  very  close  association  with  piety  (§  55), 


148  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§86. 

and  no  duty  can  in  fact  be  truly  fulfilled  without  being 
regarded  as  an  expression  of  the  divine  will,  and  hence  with 
out  pious  submission  to  that  will.  We  therefore  must  reject 
the  view  that  there  are  no  moral  duties  toward  God,  and  no 
moral  influencing  of  God ;  if  there  are  sins  against  God,  as, 
for  example,  blasphemy,  then  there  must  also  be  duties  to 
ward  Him, — and  we  must,  further,  reject  the  view  that  the 
duties  toward  God  constitute  a  special  group  entirely  distinct 
from  the  others,  so  that  in  fact  the  duties  toward  man  might 
be  fulfilled  without  at  the  same  time  also  fulfilling  those 
toward  God. 

The  distribution  of  the  subject-matter  of  ethics  into  du 
ties  toward  God,  duties  toward  one's  self  an,d  duties  toward 
other  men,  was  formerly  very  usual ;  it  was,  however,  only 
partially  correct.  God  fills,  in  fact,  heaven  and  earth,  and  the 
statement  of  Christ  that  whatever  ' '  ye  have  done  unto  one 
of  the  least  of  these  my  brethren,  ye  have  done  it  unto  me  " 
[Matt,  xxv,  40],  is  of  course  true  also  in  relation  to  God.  It 
might,  however,  be  said  that,  while  it  is  true  that  all  other 
duties  imply  in  themselves  also  a  fulfillment  of  duty  toward 
God,  yet  that  the  converse  is  not  true,  so  that  consequently 
the  duties  of  piety  might  be  considered  by  themselves,  see 
ing  that  in  fact  in  the  duty  of  worshiping  God  no  other  duty 
is  directly  implied.  This  is,  however,  only  seemingly  so;  for 
in  every  duty  toward  God,  I  fulfill  also  directly  at  the  same 
time  a  duty  toward  myself:  I  cannot  possibly  love  and  honor 
God  without  exalting  myself  into  communion  with  Him ; 
whatever  man  does  to  the  honor  of  God  is  at  the  same  time 
a  self-transfiguration ;  he  cannot  praise  God  as  his  Father 
without  confirming  himself  as  the  child  of  God.  Moreover 
toe  can  do  this  only  in  so  far  as  he,  at  the  same  time,  divests 
himself  of  illegitimate  self-love ;  and  only  that  one  can  be  in 
communion  with  God,  who  likewise  enters  into  communion 
with  the  God-fearing.  The  fulfilling  of  our  moral  duties  to- 
•ward  God  implies  consequently  in  itself,  really  and  directly 
at  the  same  time  also,  the  fulfilling  of  our  duties  toward  those 
who  are  beloved  of  God.  Hence,  the  moral  relation  to  God 
is  the  central  spring  of  all  other  moral  life,  and  our  duties 
toward  God  do  not  stand  co-ordinate  with  and  apart  from 
our  other  duties. 


§  87.]  PURE   ETHICS.  149 

SECTION  LXXXVIL 

II.  The  moral  activity  as  strengthened  by  its  moral 
relation  to  God,  that  is,  by  communion  with  Him, 
comes  now,  and  only  in  consequence  of  this  strength 
ening,  into  a  truly  moral  relation  to  the  created, — com 
prehending  both  the  moral  person  himself  and  also 
the,  to  him,  objective  world. 

(1)  The  moral  person  is  his  own  object.  Man  is 
morally  to  form,  to  cultivate  himself — to  make  his  per 
sonal  peculiar  reality  a  product  of  his  moral  activity. 
Man  is  what  he  is  as  a  person  solely  in  virtue  of  moral 
activity ;  without  this  activity  he  remains  in  spiritual 
unculture,  and  is  essentially  impersonal.  Hence  man 
is,  in  so  far,  an  object  of  his  own  moral  activity,  as 
he  has  not  yet  attained  to  his  ultimate  perfection, — 
in  so  far  as  he  is  a  cultivable  and,  as  yet,  relatively 
incompleted  being,  that  is,  in  so  far  as  there  is  yet  a 
difference  between  his  ideal  and  his  reality.  Man  is 
to  form  himself  into  a  good  entity,  that  is,  into  a  per 
sonal  reality  that  is  in  full  harmony  with  God,  with 
itself  and  with  the  All,  in  so  far  as  this  is  good. 

The  possibility  of  man's  bearing  a  moral  relation  to  him 
self  rests  on  the  nature  of  rational  self-consciousness, 
wherein  man  becomes  in  fact  an  object  to  himself.  If  man 
were  from  the  very  start  absolutely  perfect  and  complete,  hg 
would  still  be,  even  then,  an  object  of  his  own  moral  activ 
ity,  only  however  under  its  conserving,  but  not  under  its  form 
ative,  phase.  Progressive  development  is  implied  in  the  very 
nature  of  the  created  spirit,  and  there  is  no  Stage  of  temporal 
life  conceivable  where  man  would  not  have  a  still  higher  per 
fection  to  attain  to,  and  further  moral  culture  to  work  out. — 
All  self- forming,  unless  kept  in  harmony  with  God,  becomes 
necessarily  anti-moral.  Man  can,  it  is  true,  develop  himself 
in  harmony  with  himself  without  being  in  harmony  with  God, 


150  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§87. 

— this  is,  however,  a  culture  of  self  into  the  diabolical ;  and 
if  he  forms  himself  merely  in  harmony  with  the  world,  he 
becomes  an  immoral  worldling,  and  if  in  this  worldliness  he 
leaves  self-harmony  out  of  the  question,  then  he  becomes 
simply  characterless. 

(a)  The  spirit  is  an  object  of  the  moral  activity  in  virtue 
of  its  being  per  se  merely  the  possibility  of  its  real  develop 
ment  into  a  rational  spirit, — the  germ  of  itself, — and  because 
it  does  not  develop  itself  into  its  full  reality  by  inner  nature- 
necessity,  but  by  freedom.  Man  has,  in  virtue  of  his  very 
constitution,  the  task  of  forming  himself  into  the  full  reality 
and  truth  of  spiritual  being,  namely,  in  respect  both  to  his 
knowing,  to  his  feeling,  and  to  his  willing, — that  is,  into  the 
perfect  image  of  God.  The  soul-life  of  brutes  shapes  itself 
by  inner  nature-necessity ;  brutes  have  no  need  of  education ; 
man,  however,  without  education  and  without  moral  self-cul 
ture  would  sink  below  the  brute,  and  for  the  evident  reason 
that  he  would  thus  fall  into  complete  self-antagonism;  his 
freedom  would  become  unbridled  barbarity.  Spirit  lives  only 
by  continuous  development ;  where  it  is  not  morally  trained, 
it  pines  away  and  degenerates.  What  Christ  says  of  the  re 
ceived  talents  [Matt,  xxv,  14  sqq.]  is  especially  true  also  of 
the  moral  culture  of  the  spirit.  . 

(J)  The  body  is  an  object  of  the  moral  activity  in  so  far  as 
it  is  the  necessary  organ  of  the  spirit  in  its  relation  to  the 
world.  It  is  not  from  the  very  start  an  absolutely  subserving 
and  perfectly  spirit-imbued  organ  (§  65,66),  nor  does  it  become 
such  by  purely  natural  development,  but  it  is  trained  into 
such  only  by  the  rightful  dominating  of  the  rational  spirit 
over  it.  The  merely  natural  development  of  the  spirit  forms 
not  as  yet  a  spirit's-body,  but  only  an  unspiritual  animal  body. 
Even  as  in  the  features  of  the  countenance,  spiritual  uncul- 
ture  and  spiritual  refinement  are  almost  always  visibly  ex 
pressed,  so  is  also  the  body  in  its  entire  being  subject  to  the 
refining  influence  of  the  moral  spirit ;  and  this  influence  ought 
not  to  be  of  a  merely  mediate  and  unintended  character,  as 
resulting  from  the  unconsciously-ruling  potency  of  the  spirit 
ual  life  in  the  body,  but  in  fact  also  of  an  immediate  character. 
The  good  that  inheres  in  the  body  is  to  be  faithfully  pre 
served, — the  germs  of  higher  perfection  to  be  developed. 


§88.]  PURE   ETHICS.  151 

Whatever  is  originally  given  in  the  body,  whether  as  actuality 
or  as  capacity,  is  a  legitimate  possession  of  the  spirit  and 
should  not  be  lightly  esteemed.  To  despise  the  body  is  to 
dishonor  the  Creator.  It  should  not  be  honored,  however,  as 
merely  corporeal,  but  as  subserving  the  spirit  in  its  rational 
life-work, — not  as  an  end  in  itself,  but  as  an  end  for  the  spirit. 
"Glorify  God  in  your  body;"  this  moral  precept, the  apostle 
bases  on  the  fact  that  this  body  is  "a  temple  of  the  Holy 
Ghost  which  is  in  you,  which  ye  have  of  God,  and  ye  are  not 
your  own"  [1  Cor.  vi,  19,  20].  The  body  is  not  a  mere 
nature-object,  but  a  holy  temple  of  a  sanctified  spirit, — bears 
the  consecration  "of  a  sacred  destination ;  man  has  not  discre 
tionary  power  over  it,  as  over  a  mere  nature-object, — not 
merely  as  over  an  unconditional  possession,  but  as  over  a  good 
intrusted  to  him  by  God,  and  belonging  to  God,  and  for 
wrhich  he  must  give  account  to  God. 

SECTION   LXXXVIII. 

(2)  The  external  world  as  an  object  of  the  moral 
activity, — the  widest  and  almost  endlessly  diversified 
field  of  this  activity, — is — (a)  the  world  of  rational 
beings, — primarily  and  chiefly  the  world  of  humanity. 
To  the  moral  person  other  persons  stand,  on  the  one 
hand,  in  the  relation  of  similarity,  in  virtue  of  the 
common  possession  of  a  rational  nature,  and,  on  the 
other,  in  the  relation  of  difference,  in  so  far  as  each 
individual  is  an  independent  moral  person  with  a 
special  peculiarity ;  and  it  is  the  part  of  the  moral 
activity  at  once  to  respect,  to  acknowledge,  to  pre 
serve,  and  to  promote  both  these  features,  and  to 
bring  them  into  reciprocal  harmony.  A  human  be 
ing  never  becomes,  for  the  persoi>  acting  upon  it.  a 
merely  dependent  rightless  object,  but  in  all  cases 
continues  to  be  a  personality  that  is  to  be  respected 
in  its  legitimate  peculiarity,  and  hence  it  should 
never  become  an  uufree  and  as  it  were  impersonal 


152  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  88. 

creation  of  another,  but  it  is  an  object  for  the  moral 
activity  only  so  far  as  it  is  itself  at  the  same  time 
recognized  and  treated  as  a  moral  subject.  The  moral 
bearing  of  man  to  his  fellows  rests  essentially  on  the 
thought  of  the  inner,  and  not  merely  conceived,  but 
also  real,  unity  of  the  human  race,  which  finds  its 
whole  truth  only  in  the  thought  of  the  common 
origin  of  all  men  from  a  first-created  primitive  indi 
vidual. 

Here  also  Christian  morality  comes  into  striking  antagonism 
to  all  non-Christian  morality.  The  thought  of  mankind  as  a 
homogeneous  whole  of  which  each  individual  is  a  legitimate 
rightful  member,  is  peculiar  to  Christianity ;  the  heathen  know 
only  nations  and  compatriots  but  not  humanity  and  man ;  even 
the  free  Greek  and  the  Roman  make  the  distinction  both  in 
fact  and  in  law  between  persons  and  slaves;  the  slave  is  only 
a  thing,  not  a  moral  personality.  All  acting  upon  others 
which  aims  simply  to  exert  an  influence  upon  them  without 
also  receiving  an  influence  from  them,  is  immoral.  Even  the 
immature  child  necessarily  exerts  some  influence  upon  its 
educator;  and  when  Christ  presented  a  child  to  his  disciples 
as  a  moral  pattern  [Matt,  xviii,  3,  4],  this  is  not  to  be  regarded 
as  holding  good  simply  in  a  loose  sense  and  for  the  morally 
immature,  on  the  contrary  it  is  the  moral  essence  of  the  child, 
its  God-likeness,  that  is,  in  fact,  a  true  mirror  of  the  moral 
even  for  the  relatively  mature  educator,  and  that  has  a  right 
to  his  respect.  That  person  is  a  pernicious  educator  who  has 
never  experienced  a  real  moral  influence  upon  himself  from 
the  child, — who  has  never  recognized  in  the  soul  of  the  child 
the  features  of  the  image  of  God,  nor  been  impressed  with  re 
spect  for  G\\\\(\-nalvete  ;  and  it  is  the  acme  of  meanness  not  to 
respect  and  sacredly  to  protect  child-innocence. 

The  moral  conceiving  of  man  as  an  object  of  the  moral 
activity,  presupposes  that  we  have  in  fact  to  do  with  real  true 
men,  men  who  are  not  only  similar  to  us,  but  who  are  bound 
to  us  as  members  of  one  body.  To  creatures  which,  while  be 
longing  to  the  zoological  order  limana,  and  while  differing 
from  the  ape  by  the  formation  of  the  skull  and  of  the  feet  and 


§  88.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  153 

by  an  erect  walk,  yet  should  have  been  from  of  old  distin 
guished,  both  in  their  origin  and  also  in  their  spiritually-in 
ferior  nature,  from  the  so-called  "  nobler"  race  of  the  whites, 
we  could  not  come  into  the  same  moral  relation  as  to  those 
who  are  our  brethren.  The  question  as  to  the  origin  of  the 
different  races  of  men  has  a  deep  moral  significancy,  and  is  of 
fundamental  importance  for  ethics.  The  natural  science  of 
the  present  day,  which  has  become  largely  infected  with  a 
spirit-denying  materialism,  is  well  known  to  have  until  quite 
recently  declared  it  as  a  fully-established  fact  that  the  vari 
ous  physically-differing  races  of  men  are  of  different  origin, 
and  cannot  have  descended  from  a  single  primitive  race ;  and 
there  are  not  a  few  persons,  in  other  respects  favorable  to  the 
Christian  faith,  who  recognize  these  pretended  "results  of 
modern  science  "  as  really  such,  and  regard  them  as  beyond 
question.  It  is  not  here  the  place  to  examine  the  scientific 
worth  of  these  so-esteemed  results ;  we  have  to  do  with  the 
question  here  only  in  its  moral  significancy.  We  merely  re 
mark  in  passing,  that  we  must  absolutely  deny  to  an  experi 
mental  science — and  this  is  the  pretended  source  of  said 
results — the  right  to  decide  upon  matters  that  lie  beyond  all 
experience.  Such  science  can  simply  affirm  what  is,  or  is  not, 
but  it  cannot  decide  what  cannot  possibly  be.  "Empirical" 
natural  science  may  be  justifiable  in  saying,  that  so  far  as 
experience  goes,  a  white  person  is  never  born  of  a  negro,  nor 
a  negro  of  a  white  person,  though  even  this  is  not  uncontested, 
but  it  has  no  scientific  ground  for  inferring,  that,  conse 
quently,  it  can  also  never  have  been  otherwise.  Inferences  of 
this  kind,  illegitimate  even  according  to  the  simplest  rules  of 
logic,  are  overturned  almost  daily  by  the  mere  progress  of 
science.  Moreover,  it  is  not  unworthy  of  remark  that  the 
position:  "as  it  is  in  the  life  of  nature  now,  so  must  it  always 
have  been,"  is  applied  to  the  question  before  us  by  the  very 
same  persons  who  cannot  admit  that  the  human  race  could  have 
otherwise  originated  than  through  some  .extraordinarily  potent 
nature-process — through  human  germs,  forsooth,  that  were 
cast  from  the  sea  upon  the  shore. — and  who  in  reply  to  "the 
question :  why  then  this  interesting  nature-process  has  not  re 
peated  itself  also  in  our  own  day,  or  at  least  during  the  his 
torical  period  in  general?  immediately  exclaim,  that  nature 


154  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§88. 

has  declined  in  her  generative  power.  On  the  whole,  there 
fore,  and  in  view  of  the  fact  that  the  latest  ' '  progress "  of 
this  particular  wing  of  natural  science  takes  ground  in  direct 
antagonism  to  the  above  pretended  unassailable  "results," 
namely,  in  regarding  man  as  an  advanced  development  of  the 
ape  (Darwin),  we  may  without  the  least  anxiety  spare  our 
selves  the  trouble  of  refuting  the  above-mentioned  earlier 
view,  and  abandon  this  "modern"  science  to  its  own  further 
self-dissolution. 

Christianity  has  from  the  beginning  had  a  clear  conscious 
ness  of  the  moral  significancy  of  the  original  unity  of  the 
human  race.  Though  God  had  undoubtedly  the  power  to 
create  thousands  of  men  in  the  different  parts  of  the  earth, 
instead  of  one,  as  he  did  in  fact  do  in  the  case  of  plants  and 
animals,  nevertheless  it  must  be  for  good  reasons  that  in  the 
Scriptures  the  whole  human  race  is  assumed  to  have  sprung 
from  a  single  stock  [Gen.  i,  27,  28 ;  ii,  18 ;  iii,  20].  There  is 
involved  here  an  antagonism  of  the  natural  and  the  spiritual 
stand-points,  and  that  too  in  a  moral  respect.  According  to 
naturalism  the  unity  of  the  world  is  a  merely  conceived  some 
thing, — in  reality  it  is  a  product  of  a  presupposed  multi 
plicity  of  single  existences ;  and  also  the  good,  which  in  its 
nature  is  a  manifestation-form  of  unity,  is  not  an  element 
fundamental  and  presupposed  in  every  single  existence,  but  it 
is  simply  a  consequence — a  product  of  the  active  individual ; 
the  good  is  ever  to  "be  without  ever  and  truly  being.  Accord 
ing  to  the  Christian  system,  however,  the  real  unity  and  the 
real  good  are  every-where  the  first,  the  fundamental,  while 
multiplicity  is  only  of  a  derived  character.  Here  the  moral 
is  simply  and  solely  the  following  of  God  as  the  absolutely 
good  One,  a  free  manifestation  of  a  unity  with  God  which  in 
fact,  however,  originally  existed, — which  had  not  first  to  be 
realized,  but  only  revealed,. witnessed,  and  freely  virtualized. 
Man  is  able  to  be  moral  only  Iwcause,  in  his  nature,  he  is  al 
ready  at  one  with  God.  So  is  it  also  in  his  moral  relation  to 
mankind ;  the  unity  of  the  total  sum  of  individual  men  is  not 
first  to  be  created  out  of  an  original  multiplicity,  and  to  be 
constituted  as  an  entirely  new  something,  but  it'  is  simply 
(and  this  is  the  origin  and  the  reason  of  this  plurality)  to  be 
freely  and  morally  witnessed  and  confirmed.  Humanity  is  to 


§  88.]  PURE   ETHICS.  155 

become  morally  one,  for  the  reason  that  in  their  origin  they 
are  already  one ;  love  to  mankind  is  simply  fidelity  to  the 
nature  of  man  as  existing  from  the  beginning.  This  view  is 
in  diametrical  antagonism  to  naturalistic  ethics ;  and  hence 
Paul  presented  it  very  prominently,  at  Athens,  as  the  pecul 
iarly-Christian  view  in  contrast  to  heathenism  [Acts  xvii,  26 ; 
comp.  Rom.  v,  12,  sqq.] ;  the  latter  estranges  humanity  into  an 
original  diversity ;  the  former  attributes  all  hostile  antagonisms 
to  the  workings  of  sin. 

The  very  natural  and  in  fact  morally  legitimate  feeling,  that 
blood-relatives  stand  to  us  in  a  closer  relation  of  duty  than 
entire  strangers,   contains  a  profound  truth.     It  calls  forth 
really  a  very  different  and  morally  more  potent  feeling,  when 
we  know  that  even  the  degenerated  negro  is  of  our  own  blood, 
our  brother,  sprang  from  one  father,  than  if  we  should  assume 
that  he  is  originally,  and  by  nature,  of  a  spiritually  and  cor 
poreally  inferior  species  [August.,  De  Civ.  Dei.,  xii,  21].     That 
which  forms  no  unessential  part  of  the  world-historical  honor  of 
Christianity,  namely,  that  it  has  made  slavery  morally  impos 
sible,  has  been  again   absolutely  put   into   question  by  the 
teachings  of  naturalism ;    and .  it  is  scientifically  as  well  as 
morally  a  signal  indication  of  inconsideration,  and  especially 
so  on  the  part  of  theologians,  to  declare  the  decision  of  the 
question  as  to  the  original  unity  of  the  human  race  as  a  mere 
non-essential   matter.     By  the   assumption   that   there   were 
originally  different  races,  the  slavery-system  is  not  only  ex 
cused,  but  it  is  directly  justified.     In  fact  man  has  not  only 
not  the  duty,  but  he  has  not  the  right  to  break  down  the 
original  and  naturally-constituted  differences  of  spiritual  ex 
istence.     But  the  moral  influencing  of  the  degenerate  races 
consists  essentially  in  raising  the  actually  lower-standing  in 
dividuals  of  the  colored  races  to  the  height  of  the  whites, — in 
placing  them  both,  in  spiritually-moral  respects,  on  an  equal 
footing,  in  making  of  the  colored  races  our  true  and  proper 
brothers,  in  doing  away,  in  fact,  with  whatever  places  them 
actually  below  the  whites.     But  the  effort  to  do  this  would 
be,   in  the  eyes  of  the  above-mentioned  teaching,   a  simple 
presumption,  a  transgression^  of  the  limits  prescribed  to  us  by 
nature  herself ;  according  to  it,  the  negro  is  destined  by  his 
primitive  and  manifestly  inferior  peculiarity,  to  service  under 


156  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  89. 

the  higher  race,  and  it  would  be  a  criminal  interference  with 
the  ordinances  of  nature  to  wish  to  change  this.  That  which 
has  hitherto  passed  for  the  greatest  stain  upon  a  perverted 
Christian  civilization,  the  re-establishment  of  slavery,  can  find 
no  more  desirable  an  apology  than  these  results  of  a  perverted 
science ;  and  it  is  a  standing  and  entirely  consequential  opin 
ion  among  even  the  most  liberal-thinking  champions  of  this 
tendency,  that  negroes  are  in  fact  but  half-men  and  should 
remain  such. 

SECTION  LXXXIX. 

(&)  External  nature  as  an  object  of  the  moral  activity 
is  such  not  merely  in  its  single  manifestations,  but 
also  in  its  totality.     On  the  one  hand,  nature  exists 
not  for  itself  but  for  the  rational  spirit  for  man ;  on 
the  other,  it  is,  as  a  work  of  divine  creation,  a  good 
thing,    and    hence    has    rights    in    and    of    itself. — 
(1)  Nature  is  by  origin  and  essence  destined  to  be 
dominated  by  the  rational  spirit  as  God's  image, — 
to  be  formed  by  the  spirit  into  its  organ  and  for  its 
service.     As  nature  is  not  per  se  moral,  hence  man's 
moral  relation  to  it  does  not  consist  in  his  receiving 
from  it  a  direct  moral  influence,  though  indeed  he 
does    receive    from    it    a    mediate    moral    influence 
through  the  contemplation  of  the  image  of  God  as 
manifesting  itself  therein,  but  in  his  acting  morally 
upon  it.     For  the  single  individual,  this  action  is  al 
ways  limited  to  a  narrow  theater,  but  for  humanity 
it  extends  to  all  terrestrial  nature.     As  the  body  is 
related  to  the  individual  spirit,  so  is  nature  related 
to  humanity  in  general;  nature's  destination  is  to  be 
perfectly  subservient  to  man  and  to  be  exalted  in  the 
service   of    his    rational    destination. — (2)  But    this 
dominating  of  nature  is  essentially  conditioned  on 
the  truly   moral  and   hence  rational  selfculture  of 
man,  in  virtue  of  which  nature  is  not  to  be  subjected 


§  89.J  PURE   ETHICS.  157 

to  the  whims  of  irrational  caprice;  for,  as  God's 
work,  nature  has  claims  upon  man ;  it  is  legitimately 
an  object  for  human  activity  only  in  so  far  as  man 
subordinates  himself  to  the  divine  will,  whose  pecul 
iarity  it  is  not  to  destroy  but  to  preserve. 

The  relation  of  nature  to  the  rational  spirit  is  neither  that 
of  an  object  absolutely  different  from  and  foreign  to  it,  seeing 
that  both  are  the  work  of  one  creative  spirit,  nor  that  of  a 
power  entitled  to  dominate  over  the  same ;  this  would  be  a  re 
versing  of  the  moral  order  of  the  world ;  for  that  which  is  per 
se  higher  and  rational  should  not  be  enslaved  under  that  which 
is  inferior  and  irrational.  If,  therefore,  nature  and  spirit  exist 
for  each  other,  and  if  they  are  to  constitute  an  intimate  unity, 
then  the  only  relation  possible  is,  that  the  spirit  shall  be  the 
dominating  power  over  nature, — the  power  that  forms  and 
molds  it.  And  if  in  reality  the  relation  is  in  many  respects 
now  actually  otherwise,  still  this  should  not  lead  us  astray  in 
conceiving  of  the  true  relation  between  them  in  a  sinless  state. 
The  rational  consciousness  of  all  nations  has  at  least  some 
presentiment  of  the  proper  relation.  Even  as  in  all  forms  of 
superstition  a  more  or  less  clear  expression  is  given  to  a  pre 
sentiment,  though  indeed  misapplied,  of  a  corresponding 
deeper  truth  that  lies  beyond  the  grasp  of  the  superficial  un 
derstanding,  so  also  has  the  notion  of  magic,  so  widely  prev 
alent  throughout  heathendom,  its  roots  in  a  presentiment  of 
the  true  relation  of  reason  to  nature.*  It  is  but  the  childishly 
perverted  thought,  that  the  spirit  should  not  be  enslaved  under 
un spiritual  nature, — that  its  true  destination  is  to  cause  nature 
to  subserve  it  in  its  own  purposes.  When  Christ,  in  his  char 
acter  of  Son  of  man,  exerts  his  mastery  over  nature,  and  by 
his  miraculous  deeds  counterworks  the  sufferings  that  have 
sprung  from  the  enslavement  of  sinful  humanity  under  nature, 
and  when  he  promises  like  power  also  to  his  disciples  on  con 
dition  of  faith  [Matt,  xvii,  20;  Mark  xvi,  17,  18;  Luke  x,  19; 
xvii,  6 ;  John  xiv,  12],  he  simply  indicates,  though  primarily 
only  in  a  typical  manner,  the  true  goal  of  human  development 

*  See  the  author's  Qesch.  des  Heidentums,  i,  141,  and  his  Deutscher 
Volksaberglaube,  1860. 


158  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  89 

in  its  relation  to  nature.  The  miracle  does  not  play  feats  with 
nature,  it  simply  dominates  it, — subjects  it  not  to  the  irra 
tional  caprice  of  the  individual  will,  but  to  the  rational  will 
of  man  as  in  union  with  God ;  and  it  is  a  rational  demand  of 
the  rational  will,  to  be  free  from  all  fetters  that  lie  outside  of 
the  rational  will, — to  be  untrammeled  in  its  activities  by  suf 
ferings  that  spring  from  bondage  to  spirit-hostile  nature. 

Nevertheless  nature  is  not  to  be  considered  as  mere  material 
for  the  active  spirit,  and  absolutely  without  rights  of  its  own ; 
it  has  a  right  to  be  respected,  because  of  the  rationality  that  is 
impressed  upon  it.  From  the  face  of  nature  the  Spirit  of  the 
Creator  beams  forth  upon  us  with  striking  evidence ;  here  also 
there  is  holy  ground  which  man  should  not  tread  with  un 
washed  feet.  That  is  not  a  moral  bearing  toward  nature 
which  forgets  the  image  of  God  that  is  stamped  upon  it,  and 
which,  in  the  zeal  of  shaping  and  enjoying  it,  perceives  not 
that  also  natural  objects,  even  while  as  yet  untouched  by  the 
plastic  hand  of  man,  proclaim  the  glory  of  God.  The  Hindoo's 
dread-reverencing  of  natural  objects,  though  indeed  oblivious 
of  the  Creator,  has  yet  a  positive  presentiment  of  the  divine 
in  the  works  of  the,  to  him,  unknown  God. 


§  90.]  PURE   ETHICS.  .  159 


CHAPTER  IY. 

THE      MORAL      MOTIVE. 
SECTION  XC. 

EVERY  motive  to  action  is  primarily  a  feeling  /  but 
feeling  springs  from  a  consciousness.  And  feeling  is 
such  motive  under  both  of  its  forms  of  manifestation, 
as  feeling  of  satisfaction  or  of  dissatisfaction,  and 
hence  of  pleasure  or  of  displeasure.  The  feeling  of 
displeasure  is  to  be  assumed  as  existing  to  a  certain 
degree  also  in  a  state  of  strictly  normal  life-develop 
ment,  namely,  in  so  far  as  man,  before  reaching  his 
last  stage  of  perfection,  has  always  a  consciousness, 
that  as  yet  something  is  lacking  to  him  to  which  he 
is  yet  to  attain.  This  is  not  pain,  but  yet  it  is  a  feel 
ing  of  want. 

Any  view  is  contrary  to  the  nature  of  the  soul-life  which 
assumes  any  other  soul  activity,  as,  for  example,  cognition,  as 
the  most  immediate  motive  of  the  moral.  Thought  per  se 
contains  nothing  that  moves  the  will ;  but  thought  is  in  fact 
never  absolutely  alone,  is  never  a  merely  inert  possession,  but 
it  excites  at  once  and  necessarily  a  feeling,  and  then,  through 
this  feeling,  the  will.  I  feel  myself  in  some  way  affected  by 
the  perceived  or  conceived,  more  or  less  agreeably  or  dis 
agreeably,  according  as  it  is  in  harmony  with,  or  in  contradic 
tion  to,  my  present  state.  An  entire  indifference  is  here  im 
possible,  though  indeed  the  shades  of  the  feeling  of  pleasure  or 
displeasure  may  be  very  different, — impossible  for  the  reason 
that  that  which  I  receive  into  myself  sensuously  or  spiritually, 
must  necessarily  come  into  some  sort  of  relation  to  my  present 
corporeal  or  spiritual  reality,  and  for  the  reason  that  this  rela- 


160  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  90. 

tion  must  always  be  either  one  of  harmony  or  disharmony. 
It  is  true  indeed  that  the  different  phases  of  a  received  impres 
sion  may  have  different  bearings,  and  hence  the  feeling  that 
arises  from  them  may  be  of  a  complex  character ;  nevertheless 
in  this  complexity  the  elements  of  the  pleasant  and  the  un 
pleasant  remain  always  distinct, — do  not  coalesce  together 
into  a  feeling  of  total  indifference,  just  as  every  object  that  is 
taken  for  nutriment  is  either  strengthening  or  weakening  to 
the  body,  but  cannot  be  absolutely  indifferent.  Now,  every 
feeling  stirs  up  also  straightway  the  will,  and  hence  activity  in 
general ;  in  case  it  is  a  pleasant  feeling  we  desire  to  possess  its 
object,  either  by  preserving  it  or  by  appropriating  it ;  in  case 
the  feeling  is  unpleasant  we  seek  to  get  rid  of  it.  In  this 
double-movement  all  action  is  embraced,  and  hence  also  all 
that  is  moral ;  and  this  movement  itself  rests  absolutely  on  an 
antecedent  feeling.  Thought,  it  is  true,  is  the  foundation  of 
the  moral,  but  it  is  only  the  feeling  excited  thereby  that  is-the 
motive  proper  of  action.  Only  he  can  will  the  good  who  has 
pleasure  in  the  law  of  the  Lord  [Rom.  vii,  22 ;  Psa.  i,  2 ;  cxii,  1]. 
— When  the  thought  of  something  not  yet  existing,  but  which 
may  be  realized  by  my  action,  awakens  in  me  a  feeling  of 
pleasure,  this  is  in  fact  the  thought  of  a  good,  which,  by  virtue 
of  this  feeling,  becomes  an  intention,  which  differs  from  a 
resolution  in  the  fact  that  the  latter  relates  not  to  the  good  itself 
but  to  the  means  of  realizing  it.  While,  however,  an  inten 
tion  refers  to  a  good,  a  purpose  refers  to  the  good.  I  purpose 
to  become  a  perfect  man ;  I  have  an  intention  of  mastering  a 
science ;  I  form  a  resolution  or  determination  to  study.  But 
a  thought  becomes  to  me  a  purpose  only  by  the  accession 
thereto  of  the  feeling  of  love ;  in  a  resolution  the  will  stands 
forth  a  little  more  actively. 

It  might,  now,  seem  that  while  in  the  condition  of  the  primi 
tive  sinless  goodness  of  human  nature,  there  would  be  place 
for  feelings  of  pleasure,  that  is,  of  happiness,  yet  there  would 
not  be  occasion  for  the  feeling  of  displeasure.  This  would 
be  only  then  correct  when  man's  original  perfection  should  be 
conceived  of,  contrary  to  the  very  idea  of  life  in  general,  as  a 
state  of  completion.  But  all  capability  of  development  im 
plies  a  certain  lack,  though  not  a  fault,  nor  a  non-good ;  and 
every  consciousness  of  a  lack  awakens  the  feeling  of  a  want, 


§  91.]  PURE   ETHICS.  161 

which,  though  it  is  not  a  pain,  and  does  not  destroy  inward 
happiness,  is  yet  also  not  the  pleasurable  feeling  of  complete 
satisfaction.  That  even  he  who  is  perfectly  constituted,  and 
who  remains  in  this  perfection,  should  still  have  bodily  and 
spiritual  wants,  which  are  per  se  necessarily  attended  with  a 
certain,  though  indeed  only  momentary,  feeling  of  displeasure, 
is  implied  in  the  very  nature  of  the  creature  and  of  its  de 
velopment. 

SECTION  XCI. 

Feeling  as  relating  to  the  object  that  excites  it,  is, 
as  a  feeling  of  pleasure,  love,  and,  as  a  feeling  of  dis 
pleasure,  hatred.  Between  these  two  there  is  no 
third,  although  both  may  exist  in  different  degrees 
and  even  in  association  with  each  other.  Hence  love 
is  the  feeling  of  pleasure  which  springs  from  the 
consciousness  of  the  harmony  of  a  real  or  conceived 
object  with  the  actual  state  of  the  subject,  together 
with  a  desire  to  preserve  and  to  perfect  this  harmony, 
and  hence  also  to  preserve  the  being  and  essence  of 
this  object.  Hatred  is  the  feeling  of  displeasure 
which  springs  from  the  consciousness  of  an  irrecon 
cilable  antagonism  between  the  object  and  the  subject, 
together  with  a  desire  to  destroy  this  antagonism  in 
the  object,  even  should  this  involve  the  destruction 
itself  of  that  object.  In  a  normal  moral  condition 
of  things  where  all  that  exists  is  good,  love  alone  has 
a  real  object,  while  hatred  has  only  a  possible  one. — 
Love  is  essentially  of  a  preserving  character,  hatred 
is  essentially  of  a  negating,  destroying  character ;  as, 
however,  all  moral  action  aims  to  create  a  reality  by 
continuous  development,  hence  preserving  love  is 
necessarily  at  the  same  time  also  promotive  of  the 
being  and  nature  of  the  beloved  object,  and  negating 
hatred  is  at  the  same  time  a  confirming  of  the  oppo 
site  of  the  hated  object.  Hence  love  works  in  order 

VOT,  IT— 12 


162  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  91. 

to  be  able  to  love  always  ;  hatred  works  ill  order  to 
destroy  itself;  love  lives  in  order  to  be  eternal; 
hatred  lives  in  order  to  come  to  an  end  ;  only  that 
hatred  can  be  endless  whose  object  is  eternal  —  namely, 
Satanic  hatred.  As  moral  hatred  is  necessarily  an 
effort  to  destroy  the  antagonism  of  existence,  that  is, 
to  re-establish  its  harmony,  hence  it  is  in  essence  the 
same  thing  as  love.  Hatred  is  per  se  as  moral  as 
love,  —  is  but  its  necessary  reverse  phase.  There  is 
no  moral  love  without  hatred,  and  no  moral  hatred 
without  love  ;  pure  hatred  without  love  would  be 
simply  Satanic  hatred.  As  moral  hatred  is  in  its 
essence  love,  hence  the  actual  motive  of  all  moral 
activity  is  love. 


"Love  is  the  fulfilling  of  the  law  "  [nvl^ay/a,  Rom.  xiii,  10]  ; 
in  this  formula  the  Christian  idea  of  the  moral  motive  is  very 
definitely  expressed  ;  love  leads  to  the  fulfillment  of  the  law  ; 
it  is  the  rich  fullness  in  which  all  law  is  included.  Without 
love  there  is  no  morality  ;  and  where  love  is,  there  morality  is 
truly  free,  for  love  develops  itself  into  all  forms  of  the  moral. 
Hence  Christ,  after  the  example  of  the  Old  Testament  [Deut. 
vi,  5  ;  x,  12  ;  xi,  13],  sums  up  the  whole  law  in  the  one  precept  of 
love  to  God  and  to  our  neighbor  [Matt,  xxii,  37  ;  Luke  x,  27]  ; 
"This  is  the  love  of  God,  that  we  keep  his  commandments  " 
[1  John  v,  3]  ;  love  is  not  and  cannot  be  a  mere  inert  feeling, 
but  it  is  by  its  very  nature  active,  it  produces  that  which  its 
subject  loves,  —  brings  about  the  full  and  free  harmony  of  the 
person  and  his  life  with  God.  Whoever  assigns  any  other 
motive  for  morality  than  love,  knows  nothing  of  the  moral. 
But  love  tends  by  its  essential  nature  to  a  unity  of  the  diverse, 
—  seeks  not  its  own  mere  isolated  being.  Mere  self-love  to 
the  exclusion  of  love  to  others  is  not  love  at  all,  but  only  im 
moral  self-seeking;  it  is  indeed  a  motive  to  action,  but  to 
anti-moral  action.  Even  that  which  appears  in  the  animal 
world  us  an  unconscious  symbol  of  moral  virtue,  is  based  on 
love,  and  is  an  expression  thereof.  There  is  no  form  of  moral 
activity  conceivable  which  would  not  be  an  expression  of  love 


§  92.  PURE   ETHICS.  163 

[1  Cor.  xvi,  14]. — The  moral  love  of  the  divine  is,  per  se  and 
necessarily,  also  hatred  against  that  which  is  ungodly.  But  as 
the  ungodly  is  primarily  not  real  but  only  conceivable,  and  as 
this  thought  itself  becomes  really  vital  only  through  the  reality 
of  sin,  it  does  not  come  here  properly  within  our  scope. 

Love  is  taken  here  primarily  as  not  yet  a  virtue  or  a  dispo 
sition,  but  as  a  simple  feeling  occasioned  by  a  consciousness 
of  harmony  or  of  disharmony.  The  love  that  is  required  as 
the  fulfilling  of  the  law  is  more  than  mere  feeling,  though 
indeed  it  has  feeling  as  its  basis  and  essence.  And  yet  the 
love  here  in  question  is  not  a  mere  feeling  of  pleasure,  not  a 
mere  impressed  state  of  the  heart,  but  it  contains  in  itself  at 
the  same  time  a  power  prompting  to  an  active  relation  to  the 
beloved  object.  All  love  has  for  its  object  a  something  that 
is  good,  and  hence,  as  relating  to  the  subject,  a  good  (§  51), 
and  it  evidences  the  existence  of  this  good  by  the  outgoing 
and  recognizing  life-movement  of  the  subject  toward  it, — by 
the  effort  of  the  subject  toward  the  object  in  order  to  pre 
serve  or  intensify  its  unity,  its  harmony  therewith.  Now  as 
all  existences  are  created  for  each  other  and  destined  to  a  self- 
harmonious  life,  hence  love  is  the  primitive  feeling  of  all 
rational  creatures, — the  direct  witness  of  the  goodness  of  ex 
istence,  an  echo  of  that  first  witness  of  the  Creator  as  to  his 
created  work,  and  hence  also  the  innermost  vitality  of  the 
moral  life,  the  purpose  and  essence  of  which  is  in  fact  har 
mony,  or  the  good.  Directed  toward  the  good,  and  hence 
the  divine,  love  has  for  itself  the  pledge  of  eternity ;  whereas 
moral  hatred,  as  directed  against  all  non-good,  that  is,  anti- 
divine,  has,  in  virtue  of  its  negating  nature,  for  its  purpose, 
the  destroying  of  its  object  and  of  itself  with  it.  Peace  is  the 
goal  of  love  and  also  of  hatred, — is  an  essential  phase  of  the 
highest  good  itself. 

SECTION  XCII. 

If  love  is  the  motive  to  all  moral  action,  and  con 
sequently  also  the  necessary  presupposition  thereof, 
hence  there  must  also  be  an  ante-moral  love,  one  that 
\%per  se  not  yet  moral  but  which  simply  leads  to  the 
moral.  In  man's  originally-possessed,  though  not  as 


164  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  '    [§  92. 

yet  developed,  God-likeness,  there  is  in  fact  implied 
an  original  love  antecedent  to  all  moral  volition, — 
an  immediate  love  of  the  created  spirit  for  the  Creator 
as  revealing  himself  to  it,  and  for  the  surrounding 
universe  as  proclaiming  the  Creator's  love.  This 
direct  and  not  morally-acquired  love  is,  however,  not 
an  unfreely-operating,  compelling  instinctive  impulse, 
but  receives  the  character  of  moral  freedom  through 
the  simultaneously  awakening  consciousness  of  per 
sonal  independence  and  of  the  therein-contained  love 
of  the  person  to  himself,  so  that  in  virtue  of  this  two 
fold  primitive  love,  which  offers  the  possibility  of  an 
antagonism  as  well  as  of  a  harmony,  man  is  invited 
to  a  free  self-determination. 

If  the  feeling  of  love  is  a  directly  excited  one,  and,  as  such, 
the  presupposition  of  the  moral  activity  to  which  it  leads,  it 
would  seem  as  if  moral  freedom  were  actually  precluded. 
For  this  feeling  is  as  yet  involuntary  and  unfree ;  aud  love  and 
hatred  produce,  directly,  a  desire  or  a  rejection.  On  the  other 
hand,  we  cannot  possibly  exclude  love  from  the  sphere  of  the 
moral,  and  make  of  it  a  mere  antecedent  condition  of  the 
same ;  for  according  to  the  Christian  consciousness  at  least, 
man  is  morally  responsible  for  his  love  and  his  hatred ;  love  is 
an  object  of  duty,  and  is  required  by  Christ  as  the  essence  of 
all  fulfillment  of  the  law.  This  seems  like  an  irreconcilable 
contradiction. 

In  the  first  place,  it  is  unavoidably  necessary  to  admit  that 
there  is  an  ante-moral  love.  Brutes  even  have  love,  and  are 
thereby  impelled  to  activity;  also  the  child  at  its  mother's 
breast  feels  and  manifests  love.  This  is  not  a  love  springing 
from  free  conscious  volition, — not  a  moral  love, — but  a  purely 
natural  love,  which  forms,  however,  the  necessary  antecedent 
conditi  on  of  all  development  to  morality.  Primitive  man  must 
also  have  had  such  a  love,  inasmuch  as  without  this  a  life  of 
God's  image  is  not  conceivable.  Created  in  harmony  with 
God  and  with  the  All,  he  must  have  had  also  a  direct  feeling 
of  this  harmony,  must  have  felt  happy  in  his  existence  and  in 


§  92.]  PURE   ETHICS.  165 

his  Paradise-world ;  and  in  this  feeling  of  happiness  he  must 
also  have  loved  that  whereby  it  was  produced  in  him ;  there 
met  him  on  every  hand  the  image  of  divine  love,  of  the  har 
mony  of  the  universe,  and  he  must  have  felt  and  loved  it; 
and  when  God  revealed  himself  to  him  as  the  loving  Father, 
then  must  man  have  experienced  also  toward  Him  a  feeling 
of  harmony  and  love.  But  all  this  love  is  as  yet  simply  a 
directly-excited  one, — is  not  freely  produced  by  moral  activity, 
and  is  consequently  not  yet  a  moral  love,  though  it  indeed 
conducts  to  moral  activity  and  thereby  to  a  transformation  of 
itself  into  moral  love.  If  now  this  first  ante-moral  love  of 
man  for  God  and  his  work  were  the  sole  love  really  existing 
in  man,  then  evidently  the  action  answering  to  it,  and  hence 
also  to  the  will  of  God,  would  flow  out  of  it  so  immediately 
and  necessarily  that  the  possibility  of  a  contrary  self-deter 
mination  would  be  scarcely  conceivable,  so  that  though  in 
deed  moral  freedom  in  general  would  not  be  thereby  de- 
*<lftroyed,  yet  liberty  of  choice  would  actually  and  essentially 
be  precluded.  Man  would  not  stand  in  free  self-determina 
tion  between  the  choice  of  the  good  and  the  evil,  but  he 
would  be  overpoweringly  driven  by  an  inner  potent  impulse 
to  a  choice  of  the  good.  Now,  though  this  would  in  fact 
render  conceivable  an  absolutely  sinless  development,  still  it 
would  render  all  the  more  inconceivable  the  possibility  of  a 
determination  to  the  sinful. 

But  the  matter  assumes  a  very  different  aspect  when  we 
take  into  account  the  equally  natural  and  immediate  ante- 
moral  impulse  of  self-love.  This  must,  in  fact,  also  be  re 
garded  as  ante-moral,  for  the  reason  that  it  is  the  involuntary 
natural  expression  of  soul-life  in  general,  and  hence  exists 
also  unconsciously  among  brutes.  The  fact  that  with  man  it 
is  conscious,  and  constitutes  a  phase  of  rational  self-conscious 
ness,  does  not  make  it  per  se  moral,  but  simply  renders  it  capa 
ble  of  being  formed  into  a  moral  quality.  While  now  in  the 
case  of  the  brute  the  unconscious  self-love  can  never  become 
really  evil,  the  self-love  of  man  is,  by  virtue  of  the  higher  in 
dependence  of  the  free  spirit,  only  in  a  possible  harmony  with 
the  love  to  God  and  the  universe,  but  should  come  into  real 
harmony  therewith.  Self-love  is  per  se  good, — is  by  no  means 
the  same  as  self-seeking  or  selfishness ;  Christ  himself  repre- 


166  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§92. 

sents  self-love  as  morally  right,  and  as  the  measure  for  our 
love  to  our  neighbor  [Matt,  xxii,  39 ;  Luke  x,  27 ;  conip.  Rom. 
xiii,  9;  Gal.  v,  14;  James  ii,  8;  Eph.  v,  28,  29,  33;  1  Sam. 
xviii,  I',  3] ;  but  the  goodness  of  this  love  consists  not  in  an 
antecedently-established  harmony  with  the  love  to  God  and 
the  world,  but  simply  in  its  liberty  to  confirm  this  harmony 
spontaneously.  The  love  of  God  and  the  love  of  self  are  both 
equally  primitive,  and  are  per  se  not  in  antagonism  with  each 
other  in  the  least,  but  yet  they  are  different  from  each  other 
and  relatively  independent  of  each  other.  In  this  mutual  inde 
pendence  of  these  two  forms  of  love  there  is  afforded  oppor 
tunity  for  the  freedom  of  human  choice.  Man  is  called  freely 
to  confirm  the  harmony  of  his  self-love  and  his  divine  love, 
and  that  too  not  by  suppressing  the  one  or  the  other,  nor  by 
making  his  love  of  God  dependent  on  his  self-love,  but  in  fact 
by  making  his  self-love  dependent  on  his  love  of  God, — by 
freely  subordinating  it  thereto.  As  soon  as  the  divine  com 
mand  was  given  to  him,  man  was  at  once  conscious  that  there*" 
was  a  difference  between  his  self-love  and  his  love  to  God,  but 
also,  at  the  same  time,  that  it  was  his  duty  to  develop  this 
difference,  not  into  antagonism  but  into  harmony.  The  one 
(logically)  possible  mis-choice,  of  suppressing  the  per  se  legiti 
mate  self-love  by  disproportionate  exaltation  of  the  love  to 
God,  was  impossible  in  fact,  inasmuch  as  the  love  to  God 
necessarily  involves  in  itself  all  possible  good,  and  hence  also 
the  proper  love  of  self,  for  God  preserves  that  which  He  him 
self  ha's  willed;  so  that  consequently  there  remained  possible 
only  the  other  mis-choice  (which  was  therefore  morally  forbid 
den),  namely,  of  subordinating  the  love  of  God  to  self-love, 
instead  of  preserving  the  latter  in  its  true  character  through 
its  proper  subordination  to  the  former.  If  simply  the  love  of 
God  had  been  primitive  in  man,  then  a  choice  of  the  ungodly 
would  have  been  impossible;  if  simply  self-love  had  been 
primitive  in  him,  then  a  choice  of  the  good,  of  submission  to 
the  divine  will,  would  have  been  equally  impossible,  and  man 
would  have  been  in  the  one  case  irresponsible  for  the  good, 
and  in  the  other  for  the  evil — without  desert  and  without 
guilt.  But  by  virtue  of  the  fact  that  the  love  to  God  and  the 
love  of  self  are  alike  primitive,  as  the  ante-moral  germ  of 
the  moral,  it  follows  that  man  is  fully  responsible  for  the  con- 


§  92.]  PURE   ETHICS.  167 

firmation  or  the  disturbance  of  the  harmony  of  this  twofold 
love ;  for  this  determination  was  not  already  involved  in  the 
constitution  of  man,  but  was  proposed  as  a  moral  task  to  his 
free  will.  The  mere  love  to  God  would  have  made  man  good 
but  not  free,  the  mere  self-love  would  have  made  him  seem 
ingly  free  but  not  good ;  the  twofold  love  made  him  free  for 
choosing  the  good,  but  also  free  for  the  possible  choice  of  the 
evil, — which,  under  these  circumstances,  assumed,  in  conse 
quence  of  the  equally  real  original  love  to  God,  the  form  of 
infidelity  to  God,  of  a  punishable  sin.  The  case  is  quite 
similar  with  the  moral  culture  of  the  child.  The  child,  as 
soon  as  self-conscious,  has  love  for  its  mother,  and  also  a  per  se 
strictly  legitimate  love  for  play ;  when  the  will  of  the  mother 
calls  the  child  from  its  play,  it  becomes  conscious  of  the  dif 
ference  of  the  two  forms  of  love ;  it  knows  also  that  it  can 
prefer  its  love  for  play,  and  leave  the  will  of  the  mother  un 
heeded.  It  must  by  a  morally-free  choice,  make  a  decision, — 
must  subordinate  the  one  love  to  the  other ;  if  it  chooses  obe 
dience,  then  in  thus  choosing,  and  thus  only,  it  feels  itself 
truly  free.  If  there  had  been  no  difference  of  a  twofold  love, 
the  child  would  have  had  no  choice;  it  would  have  just  as 
unfreely,  and  without  a  consciousness  of  the  good  or  a  right 
to  praise,  followed  its  mother,  as,  on  the  other  supposition, 
it  would  have  unfreely  and  without  a  consciousness  of  the 
evil  or  a  desert  of  blame,  preferred  its  play.  It  is  only  such 
cases  of  choice,  of  moral  self-determination,  that  bring  the 
child's  morality  to  development  and  to  maturity. — It  would 
be  very  erroneous  to  consider  self-love  as  per  se  evil,  and  as  a 
natural  germ  of  the  evil;  the  fact  is,  it  simply  offers — not 
per  se,  however,  but  in  its  normal  difference  from  the  love  to 
God — the  possibility  of  evil,  but  equally  so  also  the  possibility 
of  moral  good  in  general.  It  is  only  in  the  consciously- wrought 
free  subordination  of  self-love  to  the  divine  love,  that  the  latter 
as  well  as  the  former  becomes  moral.  There  can  be  no  ques 
tion  of  a  "  must "  in  the  determination,  whether  in  the  one 
direction  or  in  the  other,  but  only  of  a  "  should "  and  a 
"should  not." 


168  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  93. 

SECTION  XCIII. 

The  primitive  love  of  man  to  God  and  his  works 
becomes  moral  only,  when,  with  consciousness  and 
free  recognition,  it  is  confirmed  by  the  self-loving 
spirit,  and  when  the  love  to  God  is  made  to  control 
the  love  of  self,  that  is,  when  this  twofold  love  be 
comes  a  striving  of  the  self-love  to  put  itself  into 
harmony  with  all  love,  through  free  self-subordina 
tion  to  the  love  for  God.  Love  as  moral,  and  as 
consciously  striving  toward  its  object,  becomes  dis 
position.  Hence  for  all  further  development  of  the 
moral  life,  a  moral  disposition  is  the  necessary  ante 
cedent  condition  ;  and  it  is  such  in  its  twofold  form, 
as  the  affirming  disposition  of  love,  and,  with  refer 
ence  to  evil,  as  the  negating  disposition  of  hatred. 
It  is  only  as  disposition,  but  not  as  ante-moral  nat 
ural  love,  that  love  is  an  object  of  the  divine  law,  a 
moral  requirement,  whereas  the  ante-moral  love  is 
simply  an  element  of  the  good  that  is  conferred  in 
creation  itself.  Hence,  as  moral  motive,  love  is  also 
the  basis  of  the  moral  in  the  fullest  sense  of  the  word, 
the  life-inspiring  germ  of  all  other  moral  activity. 

By  the  fact  that  love  becomes  a  moral  duty,  it  does  not 
cease  to  be  a  moral  motive.  Man,  as  awakened  to  moral  con 
sciousness,  is  to  have  no  other  motive  of  his  moral  activity 
than  one  which  he  has  himself  morally  constituted, — not  a 
merely  natural  ante-moral  love,  but  love  as  a  disposition. 
Many  are  led  to  deny  that  love  is  at  all  an  object  of  the  divine 
law,  from  the  simple  fact  that  they  reduce  it  to  a  mere  in 
voluntary  feeling.  Also  Rothe  affirms  that  we  cannot  com 
mand  to  love,  but  only  to  learn  to  love.  This  is  very  nearly 
a  distinction  without  a  difference ;  for  if  we  can  command  to 
learn,  and  this  learning  has  a  necessary  result,  then  evidently 
in  commanding  the  learning  we  also  command  the  result. 
The  notion  that  man  is  per  se,  and  irrespective  of  his  moral 


§94.]  PURE   ETHICS.  169 

depravity,  not  master  of  his  own  heart, — that  he  cannot  domi 
nate  his  proclivities,  his  love  or  his  repugnance, — simply  de 
stroys  his  moral  responsibility.  If  man  cannot  control  his  love 
and  his  hatred,  and  bring  about  in  himself  moral  love,  but 
must  allow  himself  to  be  ruled  by  blind  inclinations,  then  is 
he  no  longer  a  moral  creature,  but  simply  a  dangerous  sort  of 
animal.  If  marriages  are  contracted  only  from  "irresistible 
inclination"  and  dissolved  because  of  "irresistible  aversion," 
then  they  lie  outside  of  the  sphere  of  morality.  Christian 
morality  does  not  indeed  require  that  marriages  shall  continue 
to  exist  despite  the  pretended  "irresistible  aversion;"  on  the 
contrary,  it  denies  fundamentally  that  the  notion  of  such  an 
ungovernable  aversion  is  to  be  admitted,  inasmuch  as  it  makes 
man  morally  responsible  for  his  love  and  his  hatred.  It  would 
not  only  be  a  monstrous  but  also  an  absurd  theory  of  morals 
which  should  admit,  on  the  one  hand,  that  we  are  not  at  all 
master  of  our  love  and  our  aversion, — that  love  cannot  be 
commanded  as  a  duty, — and  yet,  on  the  other  hand,  should 
require  that  man  should  not  act  according  to  his  love  or  aver 
sion,  but  according  to  requirements  of  the  moral  law  that  have 
no  connection  therewith ;  he  who  has  not  love  cannot  practice 
love  without  hypocrisy ;  but  that  he  has  it  not  is  his  own  fault. 
Christian  ethics  requires  not  to  proclaim  love  in  our  deeds 
where  there  is  no  love,  for  it  cannot  require  falseness ;  but  it 
requires  us  to  have  love  for  all,  and,  for  that  reason  also  to 
practice  it.  The  Scriptures  declare  unequivocally  that  love, 
the  motive  of  all  moral  action,  is  also  a  duty  commanded  by 
the  moral  law ;  the  law  "  Thou  shalt  love  thy  neighbor  as  thy 
self"  [Lev.  xix,  18;  Matt,  xxii,  39;  Mark  xii,  31]  is  called  a 
"royal  law,"  that  is,  a  law  that  dominates  all  others  [James 
ii,  8;  comp.  Gal.  v,  14;  Col.  iii,  14;  I  Tim.  i,  5;  1  John  iii,  11 
s^.yiv,  1  sqq.]. 

SECTION  XCIV. 

As  morality  is  the  free  fulfilling  of  the  divine  will, 
hence  moral  love  is  primarily  always  love  to  God, 
and  the  love  to  created  things  is  moral  only  in  so  far 
as  it  springs  from  the  love  to  God, — considers  created 
things  as  the  work  of  God,  and  loves  them  in  him. 


170  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§94. 

The  God-consciousness,  as  developed  into  a  moral 
love  of  God,  is  piety  (Kvasftud) ;  hence  all  morality 
rests  on  piety.  All  non-pious  love  is  immoral,  and 
hence  also  all  love  to  the  creature  as  such,  taken  in 
itself  without  connection  and  interpenetration  with 
the  divine  love.  But  all  love  to  God  rests  on  our 
consciousness  of  God's-  love  to  us ;  love  is  produced 
only  by  love ;  all  moral  love  is,  in  its  essence,  recip 
rocal  love;  a  non-loving  creature  can  be  loved  only 
in  so  far  as  God's  love  is  reflected  to  us  from  it ;  and 
for  this  very  reason  moral  love  to  persons  seeks  in 
deed  their  love  in  return,  but  does  not  need  it. 

As  rational  thought  finds  the  unity  of  its  thought-world 
only  in  the  thought  of  God,  so  also  moral  love  finds  its  rest 
and  its  unity  only  in  love  to  God ;  it  is  not  content  with  the 
semblance  thereof  but  only  with  the  truth ;  and  all  things  have 
their  truth  only  in  their  relation  to  God.  As  that  love  is 
higher,  truer,  and  mightier  which  loves,  in  a  person,  not 
merely  the  earthly  but  also  the  soul,  so  is  that  love  higher, 
truer,  and  mightier  which  loves  in  man,  not  merely  the  creat 
ure  but  also  the  image  of  God,  and,  through  it,  God  himself. 
Love  is  the  more  genuine  the  higher  its  object ;  he  who  sees 
in  creatures  the  trace  of  God,  and  loves  God  in  them,  he  alone 
loves  with  the  whole  might  of  love.  The  proper  love  to  the 
creature  rests  on  the  consciousness  that  "the  earth  is  the 
Lord's  and  the  fullness  thereof"  [1  Cor.  x,  26] ;  this  does  not 
lower  the  creature  in  the  eyes  of  the  love,  but  elevates  both 
its  worth  and  the  love  for  it.  Thus  also  Christ  presents  the 
precept  of  love  to  God  as  "the  first  and  great  command 
ment;  "  and  "the  second  is  like  unto  it,"  that  is,  it  is  already 
implied  in  it,  though  it  does  not  absolutely  coincide  with  it, — 
it  is  in  fact  the  reflection  of  our  love  to  God  back  upon  our 
neighbor ;  our  love  for  our  neighbor  is  erroneous,  when  it  does 
not  rest  upon  love  to  God.  Hence  Christ  says :  ' '  He  that 
loveth  father  or  mother  more  than  me,  is  not  worthy  of  me  " 
[Matt,  x,  37 J.  To  the  natural  man  this  sounds  hard  and 
severe ;  but  from  a  Christian  stand-point,  nay,  even  from  a  re- 


§95.]  -PURE   ETHICS.  171 

ligious  stand-point  in  general,  no  other  view  is  possible  than 
in  fact,  that  a  love  for  the  creature  without  the  higher  divine 
love,  or  with  one  that  prevails  over  the  latter,  js  sinful.  By 
this  relation  of  all  love  to  the  love  of  God,  this  love  is  pre 
served  also  from  one-sided  narrowness, — clings  not,  in  irra 
tional  caprice,  to  isolated  objects, — but  extends  itself  to  all 
that  is  created,  though  indeed  different  degrees  of  such  love 
are  possible,  from  the  fact  of  the  differing  peculiarity  of  the 
object  and  of  the  loving  person. 

This  true  mutual  relation  of  our  love  to  the  creature  and  our 
love  to  God,  appears  still  more  striking  when  we  attentively 
consider  the  relation  of  human  love  to  the  divine  love.  As 
human  thinking  is  only  a  reflection  of  the  divine  thought,  so 
also  is  human  love  only  a  reflection  of  the  divine  love.  All 
that  is  true  and  good  in  the  copy  is  enkindled  by  the  true  and 
the  good  of  the  prototype ;  "He  that  loveth  not  knoweth  not 
God,  for  God  is  love"  [1  John  iv,  8].  Man  could  not  love 
G«d,  and  hence  could  not  love  morally  at  all,  were  he  not 
loved  of  God.  God's  love  is  a  love  of  grace ;  man's  love  is  a 
love  of  gratitude, — the  answering  love  of  a  child.  Love 
cannot  love  any  thing  else  but  love  [Psa.  ciii,  1  sqq.;  Col. 
iii,  17;  1  Thess.  v,  18;  1  John  iv,  11,  19].  For  this  reason 
there  is  no  pain  so  great  as  where  love  remains  unrequited. 
But  to  the  pious  heart  it  is  not  unrequited ;  such  a  heart  finds 
the  love  which  it  seeks ;  Christ  says :  whatsoever  ' '  ye  have  done 
unto  one  of  the  least  of  these  my  brethren,  ye  have  done  it 
unto  me;  "  and  where,  against  the  loving  one,  the  heart  of 
man  coldly  closes  itself,  there  the  love  of  God  comes  in  its 
place. 

SECTION  XCV. 

While  our  love  to  created  things  is  either  simply  a 
love  to  the  inferior,  or  to  the  equal,  or  to  the  merely 
relatively  higher,  and  hence  always  meets  its  object 
with  a  consciousness  of  its  own  independent  power 
and  of  an  individual  personal  right,  our  love  to  God 
is,  as  directed  to  One  that  is  absolutely  superior  to 
all  that  is  human,  always  associated  with  a  conscious 
ness  of  our  own  impotency  as  in  contrast  to  the  in- 


172  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  95. 

finite  holy  power  of  the  Beloved,  and  hence  is  a  love 
of  fear.  Love  to  God  is  essentially  God-fearing  • 
there  is,  however,  no  moral  fear  of  God  without  also 
love  to  God.  Mere  fear  alone  is  not  a  moral  motive, 
for  only  love  is  this. 

In  all  love  to  a  created  object  our  moral  action  is  comple- 
mentive  and  promotive  of  the  being  and  life  of  the  same ;  we 
render  to  it  in  our  love  a  real  service,  and  obtain  for  our 
selves  a  claim  upon  its  grateful,  answering  love.  But  God's 
being  and  life  cannot  be  complemented  and  heightened  by 
our  love ;  we  cannot  render  to  him  a  real  service  for  which 
he  would  be  under  obligation  to  us  [Job  xli,  2;  Rom.  xi,  35]. 
Our  love  to  God  consists  only  with  the  consciousness  that  we 
receive  every  thing  from  God,  and  God  nothing  from  us, — 
that  our  entire  being  and  life  stand  absolutely  in  his  power. 
Such  a  consciousness  includes  necessarily  the  feeling  of  fear — 
not  fear  of  a  mere  power  operating  without  reference  to  moral 
action,  but  of  a  righteous  God  who  opposes  all  that  is  unholy ; 
and  in  this  sense  Christ  himself  makes  a  regard  for  the  penal 
judgments  of  God  a  motive  for  moral  action  [Matt,  v,  22,  25 
sqq. ;  xxv,  45,  46].  Fear  of  God  in  the  absence  of  love  is,  in 
fact,  by  no  means  irrational ;  rather  is  it,  wherever  such  love 
is  lacking,  the  natural  expression  of  the  antagonism  between 
the  unholy  nature  of  the  person  and  the  holy  God,  but  such 
fear  is  not  a  moral  motive.  It  presupposes  the  antagonism 
which  the  moral  denies;  and  it  cannot  do  away  with  it,  for  it 
is  love  alone  that  harmonizes.  That  nevertheless  this  slavish 
fear  is  of  moral  significancy  for  the  state  of  sinfulness,  we 
shall  subsequently  see.  For  the  unfallen  state,  mere  fear  lias 
neither  reason  nor  possibility,  for  mere  fear  is,  in  its  essence, 
hatred, — hatred  against  the  more  powerful  being  with  whom 
we  are  not  united  by  love. 

Mere  love,  however,  without  fear,  as  toward  God,  is  not 
truthful,  for  that  would  be  only  a  love  of  familiarity  as  with 
our  equal.  He  who  is  conscious  of  his  moral  freedom,  must 
also  be  conscious,  as  often  as  he  makes  use  of  this  moral  free 
dom,  that  God  opposes  his  holy  power  to  its  misuse.  The 
feeling  which  springs  out  of  such  a  consciousness  is  not  con- 


§96.]  PURE  ETHICS.  173 

trary  to  love,  nor  is  it  yet  love  itself,  but  it  is  genuine  moral 
fear.  Hence  this  moral  awe  of  God,  the  true  reverence  for 
God,  is  the  beginning  of  all  wisdom  and  the  condition  of  all 
morality  [Deut.  v,  29;  vi,  2;  x,  20;  Prov.  i,  7;  viii,  13;  ix,  10; 
xv,  33 ;  xvi,  6 ;  Psa.  cxi,  10 ;  cxii,  7 ;  Job  xxviii,  28 ;  2  Cor. 
vii,  1].  Only  those  who  fear  the  Lord  trust  in  the  Lord 
[Psa.  cxv,  11] ;  for  only  the  holy  God  gives  surety  for  his  love 
and  truthfulness;  not  to  fear  God  involves  being  godless 
[Prov.  i,  29 ;  Horn,  iii,  18],  and  piety  is  synonymous  with  the 
fear  of  God  (0o/3of  6eov)  [Acts  ix,  13 ;  Eph.  v,  21 ;  2  Cor.  vii,  1]. 
The  reference  is  not  to  this  pious  dread  of  the  holy  God,  but 
to  that  mere  servile  fear  which  is  at  bottom  hatred,  when  St. 
John  says:  "There  is  no  fear  in  love,  but  perfect  love  casteth 
out  fear ;  because  fear  hath  torment  (itohaaiv  %«,  is  a  feeling  of 
estrangement  from  God,  of  unblessedness) ;  he  that  feareth  is 
not  made  perfect  in  love  "  [1  John  iv,  18].  The  true  fear  of 
God  is  closely  allied  to  the  love  of  God  [Deut.  x,  12]. 

SECTION  XCVI. 

Where  the  love  to  God  is  true  God-fearing,  there 
it  is  also  a  firm  trusting  in  God.  Trusting  is  the 
reverse  side  of  this  fearing.  Man-fearing  is  devoid 
of  trust ;  God-fearing  is  per  se  also  God-trusting.  In 
relation  to  all  that  is  evil,  I  fear  God,  who  will 
bring  it  to  naught  and  me  with  it ;  in  relation  to  all 
that  is  good,  I  trust  God,  who  will  not  permit  me  to 
come  to  naught,  but  will  gloriously  accomplish  that 
which  I  begin  in  his  name.  God-fearing  love  is  full 
of  confidence  in  the  results  of  its  moral  strivings ;  be 
cause  it  fears  God,  it  has  no  reason  to  fear  any  power 
that  is  hostile  to  God.  Certain  of  its  victory,  and 
certain  that  it  works  in  God  and  for  God,  and  hence 
that  it  accomplishes  divine  and  imperishable  work,  it 
becomes  enthusiasm,  which  is  the  highest  and  truest 
moral  motive,  and  the  only  sufficient  power  where 
there  is  involved  a  moral  working  for  general  in- 


174  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  96. 

terests  that  transcend  all  temporal  individual  in 
terests, — where  the  temporal  happiness  of  the  person 
must  be  sacrificed  to  a  moral  principle, — which,  how 
ever,  is  conceivable  only  where  sin  is  dominant. 

Trusting  in  God  is  faith,  love,  and  hope  at  the  same  time ; 
primarily,  however,  it  is  not  a  result  of  moral  self-culture, 
but  it  is  simply  the  germ  of  that  threefold  life  that  is  ante 
cedent  to  all  actual  moral  life.  As  the  awakening  conscious 
ness  of  the  child  expresses  itself  in  an,  as  yet,  obscure  trust 
to  its  mother,  so  is  it  with  man's  first  life-relation  to  God. 
Man  attains  a  trust  not  simply  through  faith  and  through  love, 
but  faith  and  love  are  per  se,  and  of  necessity,  trust  already ; 
and  hence  trust  is  a  necessary  antecedent  condition  of  all 
moral  life.  Trust  relates  to  the  idea  of  an  end ;  the  mere  de 
sire  of  an  end  is  not  a  sufficient  motive  to  inspire  moral  effort 
toward  it ;  it  may  be  a  hopeless,  and  hence  an  inactive,  desire ; 
doubting  Peter  sinks  in  the  waves;  it  is  only  an  unshaken 
trust  that  confirms  courage  and  awakens  strength  [Psa.  xviii, 
31  sqq.  ;  xxvii,  14;  xxxiv,  9;  xxxvii,  3  sqq.  ;  Ixii,  6  sqq.  ; 
Ixxxiv,  13;  Prov.  xvi,  20,  and  elsewhere]. — There  is  no  en 
thusiasm  for  evil, — at  furthest  only  a  Satanic  pleasure  in  evil, 
but  this  pleasure  is  attended  with  fear  and  malice,  but  not 
enthusiasm.  Man  as  sinful  may  err  as  to  what  is  good  or 
evil,  and  he  may  therefore  have  enthusiasm  for  a  folly,  but 
only  from  the  fact  that  he  takes  it  for  something  good  and 
noble.  Nor  can  the  merely  individual  and  temporal  awaken 
enthusiasm;  nothing  but  the  ideal  can  do  this, — that  which 
is,  or  is  conceived  of  as,  absolutely  valid,  as  eternal  truth, 
and  hence  of  divine  significancy,  in  a  word  that  in  the  victory 
and  permanent  endurance  of  which  the  person  has  entire  con 
fidence.  For  that  which  is  merely  individual  or  useful  I 
may  indeed  have  energy  or  passion,  but  not  enthusiasm. 
Only  the  absolutely  good,  the  divine,  is  free  from  all  doubt. 
Doubt  is  death  to  enthusiasm ;  without  faith  it  is  not  possible 
merally  to  battle  for  the  divine.  Without  enthusiasm  there 
can  be  but  a  cold,  calculating  working  for  temporal  ends,  but 
no  effort  for  the  divine  and  eternal ;'  hence  whatever  is  not  of 
faith  is  sin,  for  it  is  non-moral,  whereas  man  ought  constantly 
to  be  moral.  The  apostles  had  indeed,  during  Christ's  earthly 


§  97.]  PURE  ETHICS.  175 

life,  a  warm  love  for  their  Master,  so  that  they  were  ready 
even  to  die  with  him  [John  xi,  16J,  but  they  had  enthusiasm 
only  after  the  pouring  out  of  the  Holy  Ghost. 

SECTION  XCVH. 

As  love  springs  from  the  consciousness  of  the  har 
mony  of  the  person  with  his  object,  and  as  the  feel 
ing  of  such  a  harmony  is  the  feeling  of  happiness, 
hence  all  love  is  per  se  also  happiness,  and  its  striving 
is  necessarily  a  striving  for  happiness.  As,  however, 
love  does  not  seek  its  own,  but  finds  its  bliss  alone  in 
that  of  the  beloved,  it  is  clear  that  this  striving  for 
happiness,  as  based  on  moral  love,  is  in  nowise  self- 
seeking  and  narrow-hearted,  but,  on  the  contrary,  a 
proper  motive  of  moral  activity, — only,  however,  in 
so  far  as  it  is  in  unison  with  the  right  love,  and  does 
not  appear  as  something  different  from  it, — not  as 
the  first  and  fundamental  element,  but  only  as  a  de 
rived  one ;  but  it  becomes  an  immoral  motive  in  so 
far  as  it  is  an  expression  of  mere  self-love  (Eude- 
monism). — The  tendency  to  the  good,  which  is  pro 
duced  by  moral  activity,  becomes  in  turn  itself  a 
higher  motive  to  the  moral. 

The  question  as  to  the  morality  of  happiness-seeking  as  a 
moral  motive,  cannot  be  answered  without  a  more  definite 
characterization.  The  "  eudemonistic  "  view  proper,  that 
of  the  Epicureans,  is  evidently  immoral,  as  it  rests  on  mere 
self-love.  Heathen  ethics  could  oppose  to  this  self-seeking 
happiness-principle  nothing  other  than  the  notion  that  virtue 
should  be  sought  after  for  its  own  sake.  If  there  was  here  a 
seeming  subordinating  of  the  person  to  a  general  moral  idea, 
still,  because  of  the  inner  untruthf  ulness  of  the  position,  it  could 
not  possibly  be  otherwise  than  that  in  fact,  even  in  the  strictest 
Stoicism,  the  mere  proud  self-consciousness  of  the  individual 
should  be,  after  all,  the  influencing  motive  proper.  The 
thought  of  love  as  the  true  moral  motive  was  entirely  wanting 


176  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  97. 

to  heathen  ethics, — is  peculiar  to  Christianity.  The  Christian 
idea  of  love  harmonizes  the  legitimate  self-love  with  submis 
sion  to  the  moral  law.  In  loving  God,  man  loves  also  himself 
as  a  child  of  God,  and  in  fulfilling  his  duty  he  at  the  same 
time  realizes  his  happiness.  The  love  to  God  and  to  His 
creatures  is,  on  the  pne  hand,  a  feeling  of  happiness,  and,  on 
the  other,  a  motive  to  moral  activity.  The  old  controversy 
about 'the  happiness-principle,  which  has  in  recent  times  been 
revived,  especially  by  the  school  of  Kant,  receives  its  proper 
splution  only  in  the  Christian  view,  namely,  in  that,  while 
Christianity  recognizes  in  the  proper  seeking  for  happiness  a 
strictly  moral  motive,  it  also  exalts  the  character  of  this  seek 
ing  by  the  love  in  which  alone  it  bases  it.  It  is  therefore  a 
very  one-sided  illiberality  in  Rationalists  to  reproach  Old 
Testament  ethic*  with  "Eudemonism."  It  is  true,  the  Old 
Testament  recognizes  the  seeking  after  happiness  as  a  proper 
motive  in  the  fulfilling  of  the  law:  ''That  it  may  go  well  with 
thee  and  with  thy  children  after  thee,  and  that  thou  mayest 
prolong  thy  days  upon  the  earth  [Deut.  iv,  40;  Exod.  xx,  12; 
Deut.  v,  16;  xxix,  33;  Psa.  xxxvii,  37;  cxxii,  6,  etc.];  the 
formula  "Blessed  is  he  that,"  etc.,  [Psa.  i,  1 ;  ii,  12;  xxxiv,  8; 
xl,  4,  etc.]  and  other  similar  ones,  are  very  frequently  given  as 
an  encouragement  to  moral  obedience ;  but  also  Christ  himself 
and  the  apostles  expressly  present  such  a  motive:  "Do  this 
and  thou  shalt  live  "  [Luke  x,  28 ;  comp.  Matt,  xix,  16,  17, 
28,  29 ;  vi,  19,  20 ;  Mark  x,  21 ;  Luke  xii,  33 ;  John  iii,  36 ; 
Eph.  vi,  3;  Rom.  ii,  7;  1  Tim.  iv,  88;  vi,  19];  the  "crown" 
of  life  is  promised  as  a  reward  to  fidelity  [1  Cor.  ix,  25; 
2  Tim.  iv,  8 ;  1  Peter  v,  4 ;  James  i,  12 ;  Rev.  ii,  10] ;  but  nei 
ther  the  Old  nor  the  New  Testament  separate  this  striving 
for  happiness  from  the  love  to  God  and  our  neighbor  in  which, 
in  fact,  both  Covenants  find  the  true  motive  to  moral  action. 
There  is,  in  reality,  no  essential  antagonism  between  love  and 
the  striving  after  happiness;  but  the  latter  is  directly  implied 
in  the  former,  and  is,  in  the  nature  of  the  case,  inseparable 
from  it.  Christianity  knows  no  other  happiness  than  love  to 
God  in  the  consciousness  of  being  loved  by  him. 

All  moral  activity  has  necessarily  a  permanent  result  in  the 
person  himself;  it  makes  the  moral  his  possession  and  property, 
— forms  more  and  more  his  moral  character,  and  hence  creates  a 


§97.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  177 

tendency  to,  and  a  readiness  in,  moral  acting.  1  his  moral  pos 
session,  as  a  result  of  moral  activity — virtue— becomes  in  turn 
itself,  as  an  active  power,  a  motive  force  to  moral  life,  so  that 
by  his  moral  activity  man  constantly  increases  the  actuating 
power  of  the  same.  Of  this  readiness  or  skill  in  moral  acting 
we  will  have  occasion  to  speak  hereafter ;  we  merely  remark 
here,  that  by  virtue  of  acting  morally  the  originally  as  yet 
undetermined  freedom  of  choice  receives  a  determined  char 
acter, — takes  up  into  itself  the  morally  good  as  such.  The 
moral  develops  itself  into  a  constantly  increasing  power, — 
renews  itself  on  a  progressively  larger  scale  in  the  organic 
circulation  of  life.  The  good  becomes  to  the  moral  man,  as 
it  were,  a  second  nature,  which,  in  turn,  works  out  of  itself 
by  virtue  of  its  own  power ;  it  is  no  longer  simply  something 
objective  to  him,  nor  merely  a  natural  quality  conferred  upon 
him,  but  it  is  a  vital  possession,  and  hence  an  actuating  power 
within  him. 
VOL.  11—13 


178  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§98. 


CHAPTER  V. 

THE   MORAL   ACTIVITY. 
SECTION  XCV1II. 

LOVE  works  the  accomplishment  of  the  lovingly- 
willed  end  ;  the  moral  motive  and  the  accomplishing 
of  the  end  belong,  therefore,  morally,  inseparably 
together.  The  moral  element  lies  neither  exclu 
sively  in  the  motive,  nor  exclusively  in  the  action  ; 
neither  exclusively  in  the  intention  or  end,  nor 
exclusively  in  the  means  to  the  end,  but  in  the 
unity  of  both.  A  good  end  does  not  sanctity  the 
means,  nor  do  good  means  sanctify  the  end,  but  a 
good  end  is  accomplished  morally  only  by  good 
means ;  an  end  which  actually  can  be  realized  by 
immoral  means,  is  itself  immoral. 

As  the  moral  is  a  free  realizing  of  a  rational  end,  the  ques 
tion  naturally  rises,  wherein  the  moral  element  properly  lies, 
namely,  whether  in  the  end  and  in  the  motive?  or  in  the  means 
to  the  end,  that  is,  in  the  acts  that  lead  to  the  realization  of 
the  end?  or  whether  in  both  at  the  same  time, — that  is, 
whether  we  are  to  judge  of  an  act  exclusively  from  the  inten 
tion,  or  exclusively  from  the  action  itself,  or  in  fact  from  both 
together?  The  first  of  these  queries  has  been 3  answered 
affirmatively  by  the  Jesuits — though  this  is  not  peculiar  to 
them,  but  is  involved  more  or  less  in  all  perverted  moralizing, 
especially  in  that  of  worldly  society  at  large;  outside  of  the 
sphere  of  Christian  earnestness  there  prevails  every-where  in 
fact  a  tendency  to  distinguish  between  the  morality  of  the  end 
and  that  of  the  means. 


§98.]  PURE   ETHICS.  179 

From  the  very  idea  of  the  moral  it  follows  necessarily  that 
the  conscious  end,  and  hence  the  intention,  occupies  with 
good  right  the  chief  place  in  determining  the  moral  judg 
ment,  and  that  consequently  only  that  action  can  be  good 
which  aims  at  a  good  end — one  in  harmony  with  the  moral 
order  of  the  world.  Whatever  accomplishes  such  an  end  must 
consequently  be  in  harmony  with  the  moral  order  of  the 
world,  and  hence  be  itself  good;  when  therefore  the  axiom: 
"The  end  sanctifies  the  means"  is  understood  to  mean  "that 
the  means  which  answer  to  a  really  good  end  are  necessarily 
also  good,"  then  it  is  entirely  unobjectionable;  it  becomes 
false  only  when  either  the  end  is  only  seemingly  good,  or  the 
means  only  seemingly  appropriate,  or  where  it  is  assumed  that 
the  means,  that  is,  the  actions,  are  per  se  morally  indifferent, 
and  receive  a  moral  character  only  from  the  intention.  As, 
however,  all  free  action  falls  within  the  sphere  of  the  moral 
order  of  the  world,  and  as  the  reality  that  is  produced  by  this 
action  is  either  in  harmony  or  in  disharmony  with  this  order, 
hence  also  the  action,  per  se  and  irrespectively  of  its  end,  is 
either  good  or  bad, — though  indeed,  in  order  to  its  full  moral 
appreciation,  its  end  also  must  be  taken  into  the  account.  He 
who  sets  a  house  on  fire  from  negligence  may  have  had  no 
evil  intention,  but  he  is  punished  nevertheless,  and  justly  so, 
for  his  action  was  per  se  evil,  and  might  have  been  avoided 
by  him.  If  we  suppose  instead  of  an  absolutely  good  end, 
that  is,  such  a  one  as  is  a  part  of  the  highest  good,  simply 
particular  ends,  the  goodness  of  which  consists  only  in  their 
subordination  to  the  order  of  the  whole,  then  the  axiom: 
"The  end  sanctifies  the  means,"  is  false,  in  so  far  as  the  end 
or  means  do  not  consist  with  the  order  of  the  whole.  He 
who  burns  down  a  house  in  order  to  drive  the  rats  out  of  it 
attains  indeed  his  end,  but  at  the  same  time  he  destroys  the 
super-ordinate  end  of  the  house.  The  question  becomes  diffi 
cult  only  when  bearing  upon  moral  action  in  a  sinful  world,  in 
which  evil,  and  hence  the  infliction  of  evils  for  punishment, 
for  discipline  and  defense,  has  a  legitimate  place.  But  of  this 
we  can  only  speak  further  on. 

Moral  action,  as  flowing  from  love,  may  be  considered 
from  two  points  of  view:  first,  in  itself,  according  to  its 
inner  differences,  that  is,  moral  action  as  such;  secondly, 


180  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§99. 

in  relation  to  the  different  moral  objects  in  virtue  of  the 
differences  of  which  the  moral  action  itself  assumes  a  differ 
ent  form. 


SUBDIVISION  FIRST. 

THE  MORAL  ACTIVITY  PER  BE  IN   ITS   INNER 
DIFFERENCES. 

SECTION  XCIX. 

As  moral  action  always  seeks  to  effect  a  harmony 
between  the  acting  person  and  the  moral  object, 
hence  it  stands  in  relation,  on  the  one  hand,  to  the 
former  as  its  starting-point,  and,  on  the  other,  to  the 
latter  as  the  goal  aimed  at  by  the  life-movement. 
This  harmony  can  consequently  be  effected  in  a  two 
fold  manner, — either  in  that  the  object  becomes  for  the 
subject,  or  the  subject  for  the  object,  that  is,  either 
by  appropriation  or  by  formation.  As,  however, 
every  entity,  in  so  far  as  it  is  good,  has  a  right  in  and 
of  itself,  hence  it  has  such  a  right  also  as  bearing 
upon  the  morally  active  person,  so  that  neither  the 
appropriating  nor  the  forming  is  without  some  degree 
of  limitation,  but  both  must  respect  this  right  of  the 
object.  The  two  forms  of  moral  action  have  there 
fore,  as  a  necessary  limit,  a  third  form  of  moral  bear 
ing,  namely,  a  bearing  by  which  the  moral  object  is 
preserved  in  its  rights, — moral  sparing. 

This  third  form  of  the  moral  bearing,  which,  as  an  activity 
of  the  will,  has  of  course  a  moral  character,  has  been  very 
largely  ignored  in  ethics,  or  at  least  left  in  the  back-ground, 
and  it  is  even  severely  criticised  in  its  defenders,  and  yet  it  is 
a  sphere  of  very  essential  duties,  duties  which  can  be  classed 
into  other  spheres  only  by  manifest  violence,  and  which  yet 
consist,  in  fact,  neither  in  appropriation  nor  in  formation. 


§99.]  PURE   ETHICS.  181 

When  I  check  my  foot  in  order  not  wantonly  to  crush  an  ant 
that  is  crossing  my  path,  this  is  in  fact  a  moral  self-limitation, 
but  it  cannot  be  properly  classed  as  moral  forming,  seeing 
that  the  end  of  this  action  is  very  evidently  the  to-be-spared 
animal,  and  not  the  acting  person.  But  every  moral  action 
without  exception  is  also  a  moral  self-forming,  a  self-cultivat 
ing,  without,  however,  that  this  self-culture  should  always 
appear  as  the  end  proper.  Without  the  proper  respecting  of 
the  duty  of  sparing,  appropriation  and  formation  would  be 
come  violence.  But  the  moral  motive  of  all  right  action, 
namely,  love,  implies  in  its  very  nature  also  the  exercising  of 
preservative  sparing ;  man  cannot  love  an  object,  and  yet  not 
seek  to  preserve  it  in  the  beloved  peculiarity  of  its  being. 
Sparing  is  not  of  a  mere  negative  character,  a  mere  limiting  of 
another  action,,  but  it  is  essentially  different  from  all  other 
action ;  it  is  of  a  negative  character  only  in  form  but  not  in 
contents.  When  I  do  not  severely  reproach  a  person  who  is 
inwardly  and  deeply  ashamed  and  humiliated  because  of 
his  sin,  but  tenderly  spare  him,  this  is  not  a  mere  non-doing 
of  that  which  I  might  do,  not  a  mere  limiting  of  my  punitive 
activity,  but  it  is  the  very  opposite  of  this.  There  results 
here  from  the  moral  motive,  that  is,  love,  not  a  positive  act 
ing  upon  the  other,  but  a  restraining  of  such  action ;  and  if  I 
thereby  heap  coals  of  fire  upon  the  head  of  an  enemy,  and 
thus  profit  him  morally,  still  this  is  not  a  real  influential  form 
ing  on  my  part,  but  a  giving  place  for  the  moral  self-forming 
of  the  other;  my  sparing  procedure  here  is  indeed  mediately 
a  forming,  as,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  also  a  self-mastering ; 
per  se  however,  it  is  an  action  different  from  both.  When,  in 
the  sphere  of  the  freedom  of  rational  creatures,  God  restrains 
his  immediate  action  in  order  to  preserve  them  in  their  free- 
dora,  — when  God  spared  Cain,  and,  after  the  flood,  promised 
henceforth  to  spare  living  creatures  *as  a  whole  [Gen.  iv,  15 ; 
viii,  21 ;  ix,  11  sqq.],—  this  is  simply  a  divine  example  of  moral 
sparing.  To  spare  is  often  more  difficult  morally  than  to 
appropriate  or  to  influence,  for  in  the  latter  cases  the  person 
has  a  lively  consciousness  of  self,  and  stands  forth  promi 
nently  with  his  own  rights  and  his  enjoyment  of  activity ; 
but,  in  sparing,  it  is  the  right  of  the  object  that  stands  in  the 
foreground,  and  the  actor  must  recognize  and  respect  this 


182  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§100. 

right,  and  must  morally  overcome  his  personal  will  and  his 
pleasure  in  self-assertion.  Sparing  is  the  preservative,  the 
"conservative,"  phase  of  the  moral  life,  and  its  carrying-out 
presupposes  greater  moral  maturity  than  the  exercise  of  the 
appropriating  or  forming  activities;  for  the  youthful  zeal  of 
the  morally  immature  spirit,  its  practice  is  exceedingly  diffi 
cult  ;  not  to  crush  the  bruised  reed,  nor  to  quench  the  smok 
ing  wick  [Matt,  xii,  20],  is  more  difficult,  and  involves  a 
higher  moral  wisdom,  than  to  destroy  or  to  create  anew. — As 
the  sparing  procedure  is  logically  the  most  immediate  course 
of  conduct,  and  rather  a  withholding  than  an  express  acting, 
hence  it  is  more  appropriate  to  treat  of  it  first. 


I.  MORAL  SPARING. 

SECTION  C. 

Moral  sparing  is  a  self-limiting  of  personal  action 
in  the  interest  of  the  rights  of  the  object  j  the  latter  is 
neither  appropriated  nor  formed  by  the  person, 
but  simply  let  alone  in  its  peculiar  being  and  nature. 
The  duty  of  sparing  rests  upon  the  right  of  every 
natural  or  spiritual  and  historical  entity  to  its  exist 
ence  and  its  peculiarity,  in  so  far  as  these  are  good, 
and  hence  upon  love  to  the  object  as  being  good, — 
consequently,  in  the  tinal  instance,  upon  a  pious 
world  theory,  upon  love  to  God.  The  entity  is 
spared  because  it  bears  in  itself  the  impress  of  the 
Eternal, — is  an  expression  of  the  will  of  God  ;  hence 
sparing  is  moral  only  in  so  far  as  it  relates  to  the 
good  and  the  divine  in  existence,  and  not  to  that 
which  "by  virtue  of  its  ungodly  nature  should  be  an 
object  of  moral  hatred. — The  higher  the  perfection 
of  an  object,  so  much  the  higher  is  also  its  right  to 
moral  sparing;  the  less  the  perfection,  the  more  the 
object  falls  within  the  sphere  of  appropriation  and 


§  100-1  PURE   ETHICS.  183 

formation.  The  highest  object  of  moral  sparing 
among  created  things  is  man,  and  whatever  exists 
through  and  for  him ;  but,  above  all,  his  moral  per 
sonality  itself,  and  hence  alsx>  his  honor.  God  him 
self  cannot  indeed  be  an  object  of  moral  sparing  in 
the  strict  sense  of  the  word,  but  he  is  such,  however, 
in  the  forms  of  his  revelation  in  time,  and  in  all  that 
symbolically  represents  him. 

An  indiscriminate  sparing  would  be  simply  spiritual  and 
moral  sloth  or  indifference,  and  hence  immoral.  The  sparing 
of  the  anti-godly  is  a  sinning  against  God,  is  the  withholding 
of  moral  love.  An  evil  existence  has  indeed  also,  in  so  far  as 
any  good  still  inheres  in  it,  a  right  to  be  spared, — only,  how 
ever,  in  that  which  it  has  of  good.  The  right  to  be  spared  is 
not,  of  course,  in  the  case  of  finite 'existences,  of  an  unlimited 
and  unconditional  character,  and  in  the  case  of  nature-objects 
it  is  much  more  limited  than  with  personal  beings,  though 
indeed  it  never  sinks  entirely  to  zero.  It  is  true,  nature  is 
destined  to  service  under  the  dominion  of  the  rational  spirit, 
and,  in  so  far  as  it  reaches  this  destination,  man  has  in  fact  a 
right  to  pass  beyond  the  limits  of  mere  sparing  restraint,  and 
actively  to  lay  hold  on  the  very  existence  of  nature,  trans* 
forming  and  appropriating  it.  Where  the  right  of  the  per 
sonal  spirit  is  not  recognized,  where  God  is  conceived  of  as  a 
mere  nature-entity,  there  pious  morality  manifests  itself  in  a 
wide-reaching  sparing  of  natural  objects,  far  beyond  the 
measure  of  what  is  required  of  us ;  so  is  it  with  the  Brahmins 
and  the  Buddhists ;  and,  especially  in  the  case  of  the  former, 
this  over-delicate  sparing  of  natural  objects  is  associated  with 
a  cruel  ?m-sparingness  toward  themselves. 

As  the  duty  of  sparing  rests  on  the  right  of  each  particular 
being  to  its  own  peculiarity,  hence  this  duty  as  well  as  this 
right  rise  in  scope  in  proportion  to  the  degree  of  the  indi 
vidual  perfection.  That  which  is  absolutely  perfect  bears 
the  character  of  eternity  and  unchangeableness,  and  though 
it  may  indeed  be  spiritually  appropriated,  yet  it  cannot  in  any 
respect  be  formed  or  changed.  In  the  process  of  education, 
the  dictating  influence  upon  the  child  falls  into  the  back- 


184  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  100. 

ground  in  proportion  as  the  child  grows  toward  moral  ma 
turity.  Lifeless  matter  has  no  claim  to  sparing.  When  the 
Brahmin  does  not  allow  himself  causelessly  to  crush  the  least 
earth-clod,  this  is  simply  because  he  regards  it  as  the  sacred 
body  of  Brahma.  Plants  Imve  a  better  claim  to  be  spared 
than  inorganic  objects,  and  the  more  so  the  higher  their  or 
ganization,  and  especially  as  they  stand  in  a  closer  relation  to 
man ;  to  injure  fruit-trees  and  other  edible  vegetation,  without 
cause,  is  regarded  as  sinful  even  by  uncultured  tribes.  The 
more  an  object  enters  into  the  sphere  of  man's  spiritual  life, 
the  more  it  bears  the  impress  of  the  spirit,  constituting,  as 
it  were,  a  sort  of  larger  corporeality  for  man,  so  much  the 
higher  is  its  claim  upon  sparing.  This  is  especially  the  case 
with  the  human  body  itself,  as  the  organ  of  the  spirit,  as  a 
"  temple  of  the  Holy  Ghost;  "  in  the  next  rank  stand  all  such 
natural  objects  as  hold  a  relation  to  the  spiritual  life,  and 
which  are  mementos  of  important  events  and  of  spiritual 
effort  in  general, — every  thing,  in  fine,  that  has  been  actually 
produced  by  the  human  spirit,  and  the  more  so  in  proportion 
as  it  is  of  a  spiritualized  character, — and  hence,  especially, 
all  products  of  industry  and  art.  But  the  highest  right  to 
sparing  is  possessed  by  the  personal  spirit  itself  in  its  personal 
peculiarity;  to  assail  the  honor  of  another  is  to  wound  his 
moral  being;  the  higher  the  moral  culture  and  maturity  of  a 
person,  the  higher  is  also  his  right  to  moral  sparing ;  by  sin 
this  right  is  necessarily  largely  forfeited. 

While  the  heathen  idol  falls,  of  course,  within  the  sphere  of 
human  sparing,  the  eternal  and  almighty  God  stands  beyond 
the  scope  of  this  activity.  Nevertheless  there  are  sacred 
duties  which  express,  in  a  certain  sense,  a  sparing  of  the  di 
vine  ;  the  name  of  God  and  his  honor  are  to  be  held  sacred ; 
and  whatever  is  a  symbol  of  the  divine,  or  is  a  reminder  of 
God's  presence,  has  an  especial  claim  to  moral  sparing ;  even 
uncultured  tribes  practice  a  reverential  sparing  in  regard  to 
all  that  is  sacred  or  stands  in  relation  to  the  divine  in  contra 
distinction  to  the  worldly  and  the  profane.  From  the  simple 
fact  of  the  sparing  of  whatever  stands  in  real,  or  even  in  sym 
bolical,  relation  to  God,  it  is  very  evident,  of  how  great .signiti- 
cancy  is  piety  for  morality.  The  pious  mind  finds  God's 
being  and  providence  in  all  things  and  in  all  life,  and  what- 


§  100.]  PURE   ETHICS.  185 

ever  is  not  hostile  to  God  is,  for  it,  sacred  and  an  object  of 
pious  sparing.  The  higher  the  piety  of  the  person,  so  much 
the  higher  becomes  the  worth,  and  hence  also  the  right,  of  all 
existence,  in  so  far  as  this  existence  is  good.  He  who  is  im 
pious  has  no  reverence  for  created  things, — no  tenderness 
toward  them.  Not  to  spare  that  which  has  a  right  to  sparing, 
is  moral  rudeness.  The  immoral  and  the  impious  are  uniform 
ly  rude  and  coarse  ;  they  have  indeed  fear  but  no  awe. 

Sparing  is,  as  a  non-doing,  only  then  moral  when  it  is  a 
conscious  and  freely-willed  withholding  of  a  real  out-going 
action,  that  is,  when  it  is  an  inner  activity,  a  moral  self-con 
trolling  out  of  respect  for  another's  right,  and  when  it  is  in 
real  harmony  with  moral  forming  and  appropriating,  so  as  not 
in  any  manner  to  interfere  therewith, — that  is,  when  it  is  the 
virtualizing  of  the  real  rights  of  the  moral  object.  The  form- 
able  or  cultivable  object  has,  however,  just  as  good  a  right  to 
be  formed  as  it  has  to  be  spared.  In  so  far  as  sparing  is  a 
mere  non-influencing  of  the  objective  entity,  it  is  not  yet 
moral,  and  may  even  also  be  evil.  The  spiritually  indolent 
declines  even  this  form  of  activity,  not,  however,  from  love 
to  the  object,  but  from  mere  selfishness.  Only  that  sparing 
is  morally  good  which  rests  on  love  to  the  object,  and  which 
therefore  implies  a  conscious  self-limitation  and  self-controll 
ing,  and  which  is,  consequently,  only  in  outer  form,  but  not 
in  inner  essence,  a  mere  non-doing ;  mere  non-doing  would  be 
per  se  sinful,  inasmuch  as  the  moral  life  must  always  be  active, 
and  it  is  only  the  seeming  non-doing  which,  however,  is  an 
inner-doing,  that  can  be  moral.  True  moral  sparing  is,  in  re 
lation  to  beings  that  are  formable  and  in  need  of  formation, 
uniformly  also  a  formative  influence,  namely,  in  that  it  gives 
proper  play  for  legitimate  self-forming  on  the  part  of  the  ob 
ject.  A  tyrannical  education  that  extends  its  tutorial  dicta 
tion  into  all  the  minute  details,  produces  not  a  moral  char 
acter  but  only  servile-mindedness.  All  right  education  must 
also  practice,  in  the  interest  of  the  training  of  moral  freedom, 
a  wise  sparing, — must  allow  the  child  the  possibility  of  de 
termining  itself  independently,  and  of  thereby  maturing  itself 
toward  moral  freedom.  As  the  sparing  of  a  growing  plant  is 
at  the  same  time  also  a  furthering  of  it,  so  also,  and  even  in  a 
higher  degree,  is  this  true  of  sparing  as  exercised  toward  ra- 


186  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  101. 

tional  beings ;  the  pardoning  of  an  offense  exercises  frequently 
a  very  fruitful  influence  on  the  moral  development  of  him 
who  is  pardoned. 


II.  MORAL  APPROPRIATING. 
SECTION  CI. 

In  the  appropriating  activity  man  effects  his  unity 
with  the  objective  entity,  by  taking  it  up  into  him 
self, — by  uniting  it  with  himself,  by  making  it  an 
element  of  his  own  nature.  This  moral  activity  dif 
fers  both  in  regard  to  what  element  of  the  object  is 
appropriated  by  the  actor,  and  in  regard  to  how  this 
takes  piace. 

(a)  According  to  what  element  of  the  object  is 
appropriated,  the  appropriating  is  either  natural  or 
spiritual;  the  latter  is  the  more  comprehensive,  and 
extends  itself  to  all  objective  existence, — also  to 
God. — Natural  appropriation  relates  as  well  to  the 
existence  and  preservation  of  the  individual  person 
as  tothe  existence  and  preservation  of  the  species,  and 
is  the  necessary  condition  of  both.  In  both  respects, 
therefore,  man  is  bound  to  nature  and  stimulated  by 
natural  instinct,  and  although  in  this  respect  he  is 
freer  than  the  brute,  and  all  the  freer  the  higher  his 
personality  is  developed,  nevertheless  in  respect  to  the 
preservation  of  the  existence  of  the  subject,  this  free 
dom  is  still  always  of  a  limited  character,  and  the 
law  of  nature  is,  in  many  respects,  stronger  than  the 
will,  though,  however,  not  so  potent  as  to  force  the 
will  to  the  immoral. 

All  natural  existence  is  at  the  same  time  also  of  spiritual 
significance, — is  a  realized  thought,  the  expression  of  an  idea. 
But  as,  on  the  other  hand,  not  every  spiritual  entity  is  con- 


§  102.]  PURE   ETHICS.  187 

nected  with  a  natural  one,  hence  spiritual  appropriating  is  of 
greater  compass  and  higher  significancy  than  the  merely  nat 
ural.  The  higher  moral  worth  of  the  former  appears  also 
from  this,  that  it  preserves  the  objective  existence  in  its 
reality,  whereas  natural  appropriation  more  or  less  destroys 
it.  With  the  increase  of  moral  and  spiritual  growth,  natural 
appropriation  constantly  gives  place  more  and  more  to  the 
spiritual;  with  the  child  the  former  predominates;  but  what 
is  normal  in  the  child  becomes  immoral  in  mature  age. 

In  natural  appropriation  there  is  manifested  a  real  and 
normal  limitation  of  free  self-determination.  When  hunger 
predominates,  the  spiritual  forces  subside,  and  at  last  it  be 
comes  even  mightier  than  the  free  determinations  of  the  will. 
Nevertheless  this  power  of  nature  over  the  will  is  neither 
unlimited  nor  absolutely  definitive,  but  the  moral  will  is 
capable  of  asserting  its  autonomy  against  it.  It  may  indeed 
enfeeble  the  bodily  force  and  therewith  also  the  spiritual, 
but  it  cannot  absolutely  determine  the  will.  Christ  cried  out 
indeed  on  the  cross:  "I  thirst;"  but  when  hungering  in  the 
desert  he  resisted  the  temptation.  The  fact  that  from  grief  or 
despair  persons  have  starved  themselves  to  death,  proves  at 
least  that  the  will  is  capable  of  being  stronger  than  nature, 
even  under  its  most  overpowering  phases.  He  who  in  the  last 
desperation  of  famine  lays  hold  on  human  life  to  satiate  his 
hunger  [Lev.  xxvi,  29]  commits  a  crime  even  in  the  eyes  of 
human  law,  and  the  violence  of  hunger  forms  no  excuse. 
That  also  in  this  respect  a  great  difference  is  to  be  made  be 
tween  man  as  unfallen  and  man  as  enslaved  to  sin,  we  have 
already  observed. 

SECTION  Oil. 

Natural  appropriating  per  se  is  not  yet  a  moral 
activity,  but  it  is  extra-moral,  and  therefore  when  it 
appears  in  and  of  itself  as  the  substance  and  chief-end 
of  life,  it  is  immoral.  It  becomes  morally  good  only 
when  it  is  the  expression  of  an  under-lying  spiritual 
appropriating,  that  is,  when  it  does  not  rest  on  mere 
sensuous  impulse,  but  on  conscious  love,  not  so  much 
to  the  sensuous  object  per  se  as  rather  to  God  who 


188  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  102. 

lovingly  gives  it  to  us.  This  implies  further  that, 
with  a  moral  person,  the  natural  appropriating  should 
never  predominate  over  the  spiritual, — that  not  the 
attendant  sensuous  enjoyment  per  se  should  be  re 
garded  as  the  essential  and  proper  object  of  effort, 
but  rather  the  rational  God-willed  end  of  the  sensu 
ous,  so  that  consequently  the  sensuous  enjoyment 
should  be  aimed  at  only  in  so  far  as  the  moral  pur 
pose  admits  of  it. 

There  is  per  se  forbidden  to  man,  irrespective  of  his  sinful- 
ness,  no  natural  temperate  sensuous  appropriating;  this  is 
plainly  seen  in  the  account  of  Paradise  and  in  the  example 
and  deed  of  Christ  at  the  wedding  of  Cana.  Thankfulness 
to  God  sanctifies  even  the  sensuous  appropriation  of  his  gifts 
[1  Tim.  iv,  3-5].  The  Christian  custom  of  saying  grace  at 
meals,  after  the  example  of  Christ  [Matt,  xiv,  19;  xv,  36], 
which  prevailed  also  generally  in  the  ancient  church  [Acts 
xxvii,  35;  Tert.  Apol.,  39],  has  a  high  moral  significancy;  it 
rescues  the  natural  enjoyment  from  the  stage  of  mere  sensu- 
ousness, — elevates  it  into  the  sphere  of  the  moral.  As  even 
in  >the  opinion  of  worldly  society  the  significancy  of  social 
repasts  consists  not  in  the  sensuous  enjoyment,  but  in  the  in 
tellectual  entertainment  and  interchange  of  sentiment,  so 
according  to  Christian  morals  the  significancy  of  all  sensuous 
appropriation  consists  in  its  relation  to  God, — in  the  appro 
priating  of  the  divine  in  and  through  the  bread  and  wine  of 
daily  food.  "  Whether  therefore  ye  eat  or  drink,  or  whatso 
ever  ye  do,  do  all  to  the  glory  of  God  "  [1  Cor.  x,  30,  31]. 
But  man  does  not  give  God  the  glory  when  he  forgets  Him 
and  finds  pleasure  merely  in  the  sensuous.  God  neither  for 
bids  nor  begrudges  to  man  the  enjoyment  of  the  sensuous,  but 
he  forbids  a  beastly  merging  of  one's  self  into  it.  He  who 
forgets  the  Giver  in  the  gift  sinks  below  the  sphere  of  the 
moral  and  even  of  the  human.  The  world  at  large  is  not 
fond  of  grace-saying,  and  yet  even  the  heathen  made  his 
libations  to  the  gods  at  his  repasts.  Even  Schleiermacher 
(Ohristl.  Sitte,  Bcil.,  p.  33)  found  in  the  just-cited  words  of 
Paul  simply  an  assumption  of  the  animal  element — food- 


§  102.]  PURE   ETHICS.  189 

taking — "into  the  sphere  of  social  pleasure,"  "in  order  to 
chasten  mere  sensuous  desire,"  and  he  is  unable  to  discover 
any  significancy  in  the  saying  of  grace. 

The  observing  of  moderation  in  natural  appropriation,  the  re 
garding  it  as  a  mere  means  to  the  rational  end  of  preserving 
the  individual  as  well  as  the  species,  is  not  merely  a  moral 
preserving  of  the  person  but  also  of  the  object, — is  a  doing  of 
justice  toward  the  object.  He  who  is  temperate  simply,  e.  g., 
in  order  not  to  injure  his  health,  is  not  yet  moral,  but  only 
self-seeking.  Appropriation  finds  its  measure  in  the  moral 
duty  of  sparing.  All  natural  appropriating  is  more  or  less  a 
destroying  of  the  objective  entity ;  and,  as  the  latter  has  per  se 
a  right  to  sparing,  it  follows  that  the  limit  of  appropriation 
is  not  a  merely  subjective  one.  The  nightingale-tongue  pies 
of  the  Roman  epicures  are  not  mentioned  with  detestation 
simply  because  they  are  a  mere  immoderation,  but  because 
they  involved  an  injustice  against  the  right  of  nature  to  be 
spared.  And  many  modern  table-luxuries  are  not  of  a  much 
more  innocent  character. 

In  sexual  appropriation  the  moral  is  conditioned  not  merely, 
as  in  the  use  of  natural  objects,  on  thankful  love  to  God  as  the 
giver,  but — inasmuch  as  the  object  appropriated  is  itself  a 
moral  personality — also  on  personal  love  to  the  same.  With 
out  this  love  the  person  of  the  object  would  be  treated  as  a 
mere  impersonality,  as  a  mere  nature-object,  and  its  validity 
as  a  personal  moral  spirit  ignored.  Upon  this  moral  recog 
nition  of  the  personality  Scripture  lays  great  emphasis. 
"Adam  knew  Eve,  his  wife;"  the  same  expression  OfT^) 
is  very  frequently  used  of  wedlock  communion,  also  on  the 
part  of  the  woman  [Gen.  xix,  8;  Num.  xxxi,  17].  This  is 
usually  explained  as  a  mere  euphemism,  but  it  is  in  fact  the 
appropriate  expression  to  the  essence  of  the  matter.  The 
persons  mutually  recognize  each  other  as  personalities  bound 
to  each  other  in  full  reciprocal  possession, — recognize,  each, 
himself  in  the  other  and  the  other  in  himself — recognize  the 
complete  belonging  of  each  to  the  other  in  virtue  of  a  mutual 
love  which  precludes  every  thing  that  is  strange  or  disunit 
ing,  so  that  consequently  the  two  constitute  truly  one  soul  and 
one  flesh.  The  expression  to  "know,"  to  recognize,  refers 
therefore  primarily  solely  to  legitimate  wedlock  cohabitation, 


190  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  103- 

and  was  applied  only  subsequently  and  improperly  also  to 
sinful. 

Sexual  appropriation  also  is  in  part  a  destruction,  a  despoil 
ing  of  the  person,  which  finds  a  compensation  only  in  the  fact 
that  the  one  person  belongs  to  the  other  as  an  inalienable  pos 
session — that  both  persons  are  united  to  an  indissoluble  life  in 
common.  Hence  the  commerce  of  the  sexes  without  marriage 
is  self-profanation ;  and  virginity  is  esteemed  among  all,  not 
absolutely  barbarous  nations  as  an  inviolable  treasure  to  which 
only  that  one  has  a  right  who  is  united  in  his  whole  person 
ality  to  the  person  of  the  virgin.  And  even  within  the  limits 
of  marriage  each  party  has  a  right  to  sparing,  and  should  not 
be  degraded  into  a  mere  object  of  sensuous  pleasure ;  also  here 
there  is  a  measure  that  is  conditioned  on  the  end,  and  the 
transgressing  of  which  is  a  dishonoring,  a  degrading,  of  the 
consort. 

SECTION  CIII. 

2. — Spiritual  appropriation  relates  to  all  objective 
existence,  nature  included,  and  takes  up  the  spiritual 
contents  thereof  into  the  being  of  the  self-conscious 
subject, — makes  it  its  personal  possession.  The  moral 
subject  enlarges  thus  its  own  spiritual  being, — re 
ceives  the  universe  as  well  as  God  into  itself, — forms 
for  itself  an  inner  world  which,  as  a  copy  of  the  real 
world,  realizes  under  its  subjective  phase  the  moral 
end,  namely,  the  effecting  of  the  harmony  of  exist 
ence. 

In  spiritual  appropriation,  as  the  far  richer  field  of  this 
activity,  the  appropriated  object  is  in  no  wise  destroyed,  but 
on  the  contrary  preserved,  nay,  brought  to  its  higher  truth, 
namely,  in  that  its  spiritual  contents  not  only  exist  per  se,  but 
also  exist  jfor  the  spirit,  and  have  now  in  the  spirit  a  continued 
existence  even  after  the  object  itself  outwardly  perishes. 
That  which  has  become  a  part  of  history  and  science  has 
thereby  attained  to  imperishableness.  That  which  externally 
perishes,  the  natural  existence,  is  the  inferior,  the  less  essen 
tial  ;  that  which  is  capable  of  becoming  a  possession  of  the 


§104.]  PURE   ETHICS.  191 

immortal  spirit  is,  in  fact,  the  higher, — the  essence,  the  idea, 
the  spiritual  contents  of  existence.  In  virtue  of  their  spirit 
ual  contents  even  natural  objects  receive  a  sort  of  immortality 
by  being  appropriated  by  the  rational  spirit ;  in  a  still  higher 
degree  is  this  true  of  the  facts  of  history.  Spiritual  appro 
priation  is  related  to  natural  appropriation  as  the  spirit  to  the 
body ;  the  latter  must  therefore  always  be  subordinate  to  the 
former, — must  absolutely  serve  it. — As  all  nature  is  created 
not  only  by  spirit  but  also/or  spirit,  and  as  whatever  is  spirit 
ually  created  is  likewise  for  the  spirit,  hence  it  is  but  justice 
to  both  natural  and  historical  existence, — but  a  simple  right 
of  the  same  upon  the  rational  spirit, — that  it  be  appropriated 
by  the  latter,  and  it  is  a  perfectly  moral  requirement  that 
spiritual  appropriating  be  made  an  essential  part  of  the  moral 
activity.  Only  savages  know  nothing  of  history,  of  the  per 
manent  preservation  of  the  transitory.  The  preservation  of 
that  which  belongs  to  the  spirit,  that  which  has  been  ap 
propriated  by  it,  is  the  earliest  evidence  of  the  spiritual,  the 
historical  character  of  a  people, — of  human  culture.  The 
most  ancient  historical  nations  of  heathendom,  the  Chinese 
and  the  Egyptians,  place  their  chief  interest  in  the  preserving 
of  transpired  events;  the  Egyptians  sought  to  rescue  from 
perishing  even  the  bodies  of  men,  as  the  tabernacles  of  the 
spirit, — sought  to  appropriate  them  to  history.  The  art  of 
writing  has  as  its  original  purpose,  not  mutual  personal  inter 
course,  but  history, — was  committed  not  to  perishable  leaves 
but  to  the  rock ;  and  also  the  most  ancient  products  of  archi- 
tectural  skill  were  consecrated,  not  to  purposes  of  dwellings, 
but  to  purposes  of  history. 

SECTION  CIV. 

(i)  The  difference  of  spiritual  appropriation  in  re- 
Bpect  to  how  it  takes  place,  appears,  on  the  one  hand, 
in  this,  that  the  appropriating  person  is  active  as  a 
rational  spirit  in  general, — as  at  one  with  all  other 
rational  spirits,  and  hence  in  such  a  manner  as  that 
the  appropriation  might  be  made  in  like  manner  by 
any  other  spirit, — general  appropriation ;  and,  on  the 
other,  in  this,  that  the  person  is  active  as  a  single 


192  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  104. 

personality  for  "himself, — appropriates  the  object  to 
himself  as  an  individual,  makes  it  his  exclusive  pos 
session, — particular  appropriation..- — (1)  General  (uni 
versal)  appropriation  is  cognizing  or  learning.  The 
object  is  indeed  received  by  the  individual  spirit  and 
into  it,  not,  however,  as  its  exclusive  possession ;  on 
the  contrary,  in  this  receiving,  the  person  divests 
himself  at  the  same  time  of  his  isolated  character, — 
has  the  appropriated  not  as  a  mere  particular  posses 
sion  for  himself,  but  as  a  possession  of  the  rational 
spirit  in  general, — as  universally-valid.  The  so  ap 
propriated  spiritual  possession  is  truth-  now  truth 
has  the  destination  and  tendency  to  become  a  com 
mon  possession.  Learning  or  cognizing  is  therefore 
moral :  (a)  in  that  it  seeks  to  appropriate  to  itself  the 
real  spiritual  contents  of  existence,  that  is,  seeks  after 
truth ;  (b)  in  that  it  makes  of  truth,  not  a  personal 
isolated  enjoyment,  but  strives  to  communicate  it  to 
others. 

All  learning  is  spiritual  appropriating,  but  not  all  spiritual 
appropriating  is  general;  we  here  consider  spiritual  appropri 
ation  under  another  phase  than  in  the  preceding  section. 
Where  the  love  of  sensuous  enjoyment  prevails  to  a  sinful 
extent,  there  the  love  of  truth  declines.  The  desire  of  knowl 
edge  is  a  characteristic  of  the  moral  spirit.  Man,  as  called  to 
dominion  over  nature,  is  also  called  to  the  spiritual  appropri 
ating  of  the  same,  and  of  all  existence.  The  striving  after 
truth  is  a  seal  of  man's  God-likeness.  Even  as  to  God  every 
thing  is  open,  and  all  truth  is  known,  so  also  is  man  only  then 
truly  a  spirit  when  he  strives  after  truth  and  seeks  cognosci- 
tively  to  appropriate  to  himself  all  things.  This  is  a  legitimate 
striving  after  possession, — after  the  possession  of  an  inner 
world,  a  true  copy  of  the  real  one ;  and  it  is  among  the  most 
essential  sources  of  the  bliss  of  the  perfected,  that  they  know 
the  truth  and  constantly  appropriate  to  themselves  cognosci- 
tively  more  of  it.  The  acquiring  of  the  truth  is  a  becoming 


§  104.]  PURE  ETHICS.  193 

free  from  the  limits  of  a  merely  individual  existence, — a  di 
vesting  ourselves  of  the  mere  state  of  nature,  an  assuming  of 
a  more  general  character,  an  entering  into  the  life  and  essence 
of  the  self-concordant  All,  an  appropriating  of  the  objective 
outgoings  of  spirit  in  general.  "Ye  shall  know  the  truth 
and  the  truth  shall  make  you  free,"  says  Christ  to  such  as 
shall  continue  in  his  word  [John  viii,  32].  Even  as  light 
breaks  down  the  isolation  of  individual  being,  and  throws  up 
a  bridge  to  that  which  is  outwardly  separated  from  it,  thus 
causing  all  separate  objects  to  exist  in  some  sort  for  each 
other,  so  the  knowledge  of  truth  frees  man  from  the  bonds  of 
a  merely  isolated  being,  opens  for  him  the  totality  of  exist 
ence  as  his  life-sphere, — throws  a  unifying  bond  around  deity 
and  the  totality  of  his  creatures.  As  no  life  of  the  earth  is 
without  light,  so  also  is  there  no  life  of  the  spirit  without  the 
knowledge  of  truth ;  and  it  is  not  this  or  that  truth  that  makes 
man  free,  rational,  and  blessed,  but  the  truth ;  and  the  Spirit 
of  the  Lord  strives  to  lead  his  disciples  into  all  truth.  Who 
ever  seeks  to  set  limits  to  the  moral  thirst  for  truth,  whoever 
declares  any  truth  as  indifferent  or  unworthy  of  effort,  he  re 
sists  the  outgoings  of  the  spirit  of  truth.  Moreover,  there  is 
no  particular  truth  which  stands  isolated  and  for  itself,  and 
does  not  first  receive  its  validity  from  the  truth  which  springs 
from  the  eternal  Spirit  of  God ;  and  he  who  thinks  to  satisfy 
the  thirst  of  the  soul  for  truth  with  certain  separate  morsels 
of  truths  from  the  sphere  of  the  finite  and  transitory,  knows 
not  the  truth  but  only  falsehood. 

All  true  knowing  is  of  such  a  nature  that  every  other  rational 
spirit  can  and  must  know  in  precisely  the  same  manner,  and 
hence  has  a  significance  beyond  the  possession  of  the  indi 
vidual, — is  general  appropriation.  Hence,  as  moral,  it  is  also 
directly  connected  with  a  tendency  to  make  that  which  is 
appropriated  by  the  individual  person  a  general  possession  of 
all  rational  beings.  The  moral  man  cannot  wish  to  retain  the 
truth  for  himself  alone,  but  the  truth  which  has  become  his 
possession  impels  him,  by  virtue  of  its  general  character,  free 
ly  to  communicate  it  to  others  [Luke  ii,  17;  1  John  i,  1  sqq.~\. 
The  duty  of  secret-keeping  has  a  validity  and  significancy 
only  on  the  supposition  of  predominant  sinfuluess, — is  incon 
ceivable  save  on  the  presupposition  of  sin ;  and  the  weakness 

VOL.  11—14 


19-i  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§105. 

of  being  unable  to  keep  a  secret  springs,  in  some  sort  at  least, 
from  a  correct  feeling  of  that  which  ought  to  be.  Good- 
hearted  persons  are  usually  poor  secret-keepers ;  and  for  inno 
cence  there  is  no  secret.  The  truth,  like  light,  cannot  hide 
itself;  it  is  only  with  designing  effort  that  either  can  be  con 
cealed.  Truth,  morally  considered,  belongs  not  to  the  mere 
understanding  but  to  the  heart ;  and  with  that  of  which  the 
heart  is  full,  the  mouth  overflows  [Luke  vi,  45].  He  to  whom 
the  truth  belongs,  belongs  also  himself  to  the  truth, — must 
also  T)ear  witness  of  the  truth.  ' '  We  cannot  but  speak  the 
things  which  we  have  seen  and  heard,"  said  Peter  and  John 
in  the  presence  of  the  chief  council  [Acts  iv,  20],  and  they 
only  express  the  inner  moral  necessity  of  such  a  witnessing  of 
obtained  truth.  Whoever  feels  nothing  of  such  an  inner  im 
pulsion  to  witnessing  either  possesses  not  the  truth,  or  the 
truth  possesses  not  him.  With  the  witnessing  of  the  truth  it 
is  in  some  sense  as  it  is  with  the  first  ante-moral  love ;  the 
person  may  indeed  resist  the  inner  impulse,  but  if  he  does  not 
do  so  then  his  immediate  love  of  the  truth  will  spontaneously 
induce  him  to  witness  for  it  without  any  need  of  a  special 
effort  of  the  will.  "Ye  also  will  bear  witness  (as  well  as 
the  Holy  Ghost),  because  ye  have  been  with  me  from  the  be 
ginning, "  says  the  Lord  to  his  disciples  [John  xv,  27] ;  this  is 
not  an  injunction  but  a  promise ;  they  will  not  be  able  to  do 
otherwise;  the  truth  is  stronger  than  the  command.  Hence 
he  who  is  of  the  truth  needs  no  longer  the  law;  for  the  truth 
impels  him  to  bear  witness  of  itself  through  his  life. 

SECTION  CV. 

(2).  Particular  (individual)  appropriating  is  enjoy 
ing.  Here  the  object  exists  solely  for  me  in  so  far  as 
I  am  an  individual  being, — becomes  my  special  pos 
session.  In  enjoyment  I  do  not,  as  in  cognizing,  have 
the  object  purely  as  such,  but  I  have  it  as  it  stands  in 
accord  with  my  peculiarity,  as  it  has  become  an  ele 
ment  of  my  own  being.  In  enjoyment  I  have,  there 
fore,  always  also  myself  as  in  some  way  affected  by 
the  object ;  hence  the  sphere  of  enjoyment  is  essen- 


§  105.]  PURE   ETHICS.  195 

tially  feeling,  namely,  the  feeling  of  pleasure.  En 
joyment  is  either  sensuous  or  spiritual ;  the  former 
is  never  moral  per  se,  but  only  with  and  in  the  latter. 
— As  the  personal  spirit  has  an  independent  right  in 
and  of  itself,  and  as  true  enjoyment  rests  on  love  to 
the  object,  and  consequently  is  a  visualization  of 
this  love,  hence  enjoyment  is  also  a  moral  right,  and 
therefore  also  relatively  a  duty.  The  morality  of 
enjoyment  consists  primarily  in  a  conscious  and  com 
plete  subordinating  of  merely  sensuous  enjoyment  to 
spiritual ;  and  furthermore  in  the  fact  that  it  be  al 
ways  a  pure  expression  of  moral  love,  and  hence  also 
of  thankfulness,  and  that  it  rest  on  joy  in  God, — that 
it  stand  in  proper  harmony  with  the  formative  activi 
ty  ;  and  also  in  the  fact  that,  by  virtue  of  the  agree 
able  feeling  manifested  in  it,  it  awake  also  commu 
nicative  love,  namely,  the  tendency  to  extend  the 
enjoyment  to  others. — The  highest  enjoyment  consists 
in  the  consciousness  of  the  filial  relation  to  God,  that 
is,  in  the  perfect  appropriation  of  life-communion  with 
God ;  and  in  fact  to  the  child  of  God,  only  that  is  a 
real  enjoyment,  in  which  also  God  has  pleasure.  In 
association  with  this  enjoyment  of  the  filial  relation 
to  God,  every  other  enjoyment  is  sanctified. 

In  learning,  or  cognizing,  I  throw  into  the  back-ground  rny 
isolated  individuality, — let  the  truth,  as  general,  rule  over 
me ;  my  mere  isolated  being  has  no  validity ;  in  enjoying,  on 
the  contrary,  I  come  with  my  separate  individuality  into  the 
fore-ground ;  the  object  per  se  has  no  validity ;  in  learning  I 
have  myself  only  as  a  member  of  the  whole,  but  in  enjoying. I 
have  myself  as  an  individuality  distinct  from  the  whole. 
Hence  enjoyment,  as  of  such  and  such  a  form,  is  not  com 
municable  ;  de  gustibus  non  est  disputandum.  Whatever  one 
rational  person  cognizes  as  true,  that  must  be  cognized  by  all 
as  true ;  but  that  which  is  an  enjoyment  for  one  is  not  necea- 


196  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  105. 

sarily  such  for  another.  All  enjoyment  is  love,  and  the  highest 
earthly  love  is  conjugal  and  maternal  love ;  but  this  love  which 
is  at  the  same  time  the  highest  earthly  enjoyment,  belongs  to 
this  or  that  particular  person, — is  by  no  means  personally- 
communicable  ;  a  child  can  be  loved  by  no  one  else  as  it  is  by 
its  mother.  As  knowledge  naturally  impels  to  communica 
tion,  so  enjoyment,  on  the  contrary,  impels  rather  to  isolation ; 
the  pleasure-seeker  would  fain  have  every  thing  for  himself; 
if  he  seeks  society,  it  is  only  in  so  far  as  society  becomes  to 
him  an  object  of  enjoyment.  Enjoyment  readily  gives  rise  to 
jealousy,  whereas  knowledge  tends  to  a  liberal  imparting  of 
the  acquired  truth ;  even  maternal  love  knows  jealousy. 

Christian  morality  begrudges  not  enjoyment  to  man,  not 
even  the  sensuous,  for  "the  earth  is  the  Lord's  and  the  full 
ness  thereof"  [1  Cor.  x,  6;  Psa.  xxiv,  1;  cornp.  Gen.  ii,  9]. 
-The  pious  reference  of  all  enjoyment  to  God  as  the  Giver  of 
all  good,  and  thankful  love  to  him,  render  even  sensuous 
enjoyment  rioral,  in  so  far  as  it  is  sought  in  the  divinely-or 
dained  manner, — spiritualize  it,  in  fact,  by  the  heart-disposi 
tion  of  the  subject,  and  place  the  joy  proper  in  the  spiritual 
associations  of  the  sensuous.  So  soon  as  sensuous  enjoyment 
is  sought  purely  for  itself,  apart  from  the  spiritual  and  from 
love  to  God,  it  becomes  at  once  immoral,  seeing  that  it  then 
interrupts  (§  102)  the  spiritual  life,  which  by  its  very  nature 
is  continuous;  of  the  relation  of  enjoyment  to  forming,  we  will 
speak  hereafter. 

The  communication  of  enjoyment, — a  constituent  element 
of  its  morality, — springs  not  from  the  essence  of  the  same, 
but  from  love  to  man  in  general.  It  can  only  take  place  in  so 
far  as  thereby  the  essence  of  the  enjoyment  is  not  affected ; 
the  enjoyment  that  lies  in  the  family-life  can  never  be  made 
a  common  possession ;  and  the  fact  that  in  the  case  of  a  few 
rude  tribes,  hospitality  is  extended  to  a  communicating  even 
of  marital  rights,*  is  evidence  simply  of  a  perversion  of  the 
moral.  Manifestly,  however,  wedlock-happiness  and  that  of 
the  family  in  general  require,  in  order  to  their  being  moral, 
that  they  be  communicated  to  others,  not,  however,  as  a  direct 
enjoyment,  but  through  hospitality, — through  the  throwing 
open  of  the  family  to  friendly  intercourse,  through  the  per- 

•TertulL  :  Apolog.,  c.  39;  Wuttke:  Gesoh.  d.  ITeident.,  i,  p.  177. 


§105.]  PURE   ETHICS.  197 

mitting  of  others  to  share  in  the  inner  peace  of  the  domestic 
life.  Hence  there  is  not  lacking  a  moral  back-ground  for  tho 
custom  of  reserving  the  higher  sensuous  enjoyment  of  repasts 
for  hospitable  occasions,  in  which  the  spiritual  intercourse,  and 
hence  spiritual  enjoyment,  occupies  the  fore-ground,  while 
the  sensuous  enjoyment  appears  only  as  an  attendant  in  the 
back-ground.  The  idea  of  Paradise  is  the  epitome  of  the 
entire  circle  of  true  enjoyments, — it  is  not  a  mere  crude  or 
childish  fancy-creation,  but  the  very  truth  itself.  Christian 
morality  is  not  averse  to  enjoyment;  it  favors  man's  taking 
delight  in  this  world  of  reality.  But  Paradise  exists  only 
where  man  is  in  filial  communion  with  the  divine  Father, — 
where  love  to  God  sanctifies  all  earthly  enjoyment.  "The 
kingdom  of  God  is  not  meat  and  drink,  but  righteousness, 
and  peace,  and  joy,  in  the  Holy  Ghost"  [Kom.  xiv,  17]. 
Christianity  knows  no  other  joy  than  joy  in  the  Lord;  "Re 
joice  in  the  Lord  always,  and  again  I  say,  Rejoice  "  [Phil,  iv,  4]. 
He  who  rejoices  in  the  Lord,  takes  true  delight  in  all  that 
comes  from  the  Lord  [Deut.  xxvi,  11].  To  man  as  sinful 
many  enjoyments  are  forbidden,  because  he  is  able  to  enjoy 
them  only  sinfully  ;  to  the  pure  the  sphere  of  morally-pure 
enjoyment  is  much  wider  and  richer  [Titus  i,  15].  The  child 
of  God  has  enjoyment  in  every  thing,  and  every  thing  is  to  him 
a  moral  enjoyment,  save  alone  the  violation  of  God's  law ;  to 
him  the  world  is  a  paradise,  for  it  is  God's,  as  is  also  himself ; 
and  he  loves  not  the  world  without  God,  but  only  in  God  and 
with  God.  The  blessedness  of  the  children  of  God,  the  un 
speakable  enjoyment  of  true  heart-devotion  in  fervent  prayer, 
in  which  man  knows  himself  at  one  with  his  God,  and  rests 
in  the  peace  of  God,  is  not  a  subject  for  scientific  synthesis 
and  analytical  description ;  it  belongs  to  the  sphere  of  the 
inner  life,  and  needs  to  be  experienced  rather  than  described ; 
the  world  knows  nothing  thereof. 


198  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§106. 

III.  MORAL  FORMING. 
SECTION  CVI. 

Moral  forming  works  the  harmony  of  existence,  in 
that  thereby  man  impresses  upon  objective  existence 
the  peculiarity  of  his  own  spirit, — makes  it  an  ex 
pression  thereof,  that  is,  spiritually  shapes  it.  The 
object  is  destroyed  not  in  its  existence,  but  only  in 
its  isolation  and  peculiarity, — receives  the  peculiarity 
of  the  acting  spirit,  is  imbued  with,  and  thus  bound 
to,  it.  Forming  is  morally  good  not  when  it  is  an 
impressing  of  the  merely  individual  and  as  yet  not 
morally-rational  spirit  upon  the  object  (for  this  would 
be  injustice  to  the  object,  a  non-sparing  of  its  legiti 
mate  being),  but  when  it  is  an  impressing  of  the  spirit 
as  moral,  as  rational  and  as  in  harmony  with  God, 
that  is,  when  the  object  itself  is  formed  toward  a 
complete  harmony  with  the  morally-rational  collect 
ive  spirit.  Moral  forming  must  therefore  always  be 
associated  with  moral  sparing,  and  all  the  more  so 
the  higher  the  spiritual  significance  and  worth  of  the 
object  that  is  to  be  formed.  As  related  to  the  moral 
spirit,  therefore,  all  moral  forming  is  an  educating, 
which  latter  is  never  an  absolutely  all-determining 
forming,  but  a  forming  that  respects  the  rights  of  the 
personality  that  is  to  be  formed. 

The  outward-going  formative  activity  can  neither  be  arbi 
trary  and  purposeless,  nor  a  mere  destroying  of  that  which 
exists,  but  must  have  a  rational  end  and  a  right  of  its  own.  In 
view  of  the  wants  of  the  moral  activity,  therefore,  created  exist 
ence  cannot  be,  primarily,  at  once  and  definitively  completed  and 
perfected,  though  indeed  it  is  good,  but  it  stands  in  the  presence 
of  the  activity  of  the  rational  spirit  as  formable  material  to 
which  man,  as  active,  has  a  right,  and  the  final  completion  of 


§106.]  PURE  ETHICS.  199 

\ 

which  is  an  end  for  human  activity.  It  is  only  through  form 
ing  that  man  makes  the  objective  world  his  own,  namely,  in 
that  he  impresses  upon  it  his  stamp,  and  makes  it  by  moral  ac 
tivity  into  a  likeness  of  himself,  and  therefore  into  his  own 
possession.  ' '  Do  your  own  business  (npdaaeiv  TU  Wia)  and  work 
with  your  own  hands  "  [1  Thess.  iv,  11] ;  man  really  possesses 
nothing  as  his  own  but  that  which  he  has  produced  by  work 
ing  and  forming ;  and  it  is  not  a  curse  but  an  original  moral 
law  of  the  universe,  that  the  true  existence  of  man,  bodily  as 
well  as  spiritually-moral,  is  conditioned  on  formative  work 
ing,  on  labor.  Even  the  first  man  was  not  placed  in  Paradise 
simply  to  enjoy  its  delights,  simply  to  appropriate  to  himself, 
naturally  and  spiritually,  that  which  already  existed,  but  he 
was  to  cultivate  the  garden  [Gen.  ii,  15].  Man  is  called  to 
dominion  over  nature,  to' be  a  creator  of  a  spiritual  world; 
this  is  both  a  wide  and  also  a  privileging  and  obligating  field 
for  the  moral.  The  play  of  the  child  is  a  forming ;  that  of  the 
brute  has  no  objective  significancy;  and  wherever  by  virtue 
of  an  instinct,  the  brute  exercises  a  formative  activity,  there  we 
are  simply  presented  with  a  natural  symbol  of  the  moral,  as 
in  the  case  of  the  bee,  the  ant,  etc. 

Forming,  as  compared  to  sparing  and  appropriating,  ap 
pears  at  once  as  the  higher,  and  generally  more  difficult,  form 
of  activity  ;  sparing  is  a  mere  checking  of  the  outward-going 
activity;  appropriating,  according  to  its  kind,  either  annihi 
lates  the  objective  existence,  or  leaves  its  substance  untouched ; 
but  forming  interferes  positively  with  the  existence  and  pecul 
iarity  of  the  object.  There  is  need  here,  on  the  one  hand,  of 
a  considerate  respecting  of  the  right  of  the  object  to  its  own 
peculiarity,  so  that  the  forming  may  not  become  an  unjust 
perverting  and  destroying,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  of  a  proper 
and  clear  consciousness  of  the  rat  onal  purpose  of  the  trans 
forming.  Appropriating  begins  earlier  in  the  spiritual  de 
velopment  of  man  than  forming;  the  latter  always  presupposes 
some  degree  of  moral  maturity  ;  forming  as  exercised  by  an 
immature  spirit  is  a  destroying.  The  formative  activity  of 
the  child  appears  as  a  rending-asunder  of  whatever  falls  into 
its  hand;  the  historical  activity  of  savage  or  half-civilized 
tribes,  bears  also  this  childish  character.  Unripe  youth  have 
also,  as  relating  to  society  and  the  state  and  to  historical  real- 


200  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  107. 

ity  in  general,  great  pleasure  in  destruction ;  and  the  revo 
lutionary  spirit  of  boisterous  young  men  is  only  a  higher 
degree  of  the  destructive  proclivity  of  the  child;  but  on  the 
supposition  of  the  attainment  of  higher  spiritual  maturity,  that 
which  is  innocent  in  the  child  becomes  a  culpable  lack  of 
judgment.  Moral  forming  must  necessarily  always  have  also 
a  preserving  phase,  inasmuch  as  in  all  that  which  is  to  be 
formed  there  is  also  something  that  has  a  right  to  existence, 
and  hence  a  claim  upon  sparing;  and  an  education  which 
ignores  this  right  in  the  pupil,  is  violent  and  therefore 
immoral. 

SECTION  CVII. 

Moral  forming  differs  likewise  in  two  respects. 
(a)  According  to  that  which  is  formed  in  the  object, 
it  is  either  a  sensuously-natural  or  a  spiritual  form 
ing. — 1.  Natural  forming  is  a  shaping  of  nature- 
material  for  the  human  spirit  by  virtue  of  the  mastery 
of  the  spirit  over  nature,  to  the  end  either  of  practical 
utility  or  of  a  manifesting  of  spirit  in  art-work.  Na 
ture,  as  created,  is  indeed  per  se  good  and  perfect,  but  it 
becomes  a  true  home  for,  a  true  organ  of,  the  spirit 
and  of  history,  only  by  becoming  imbued  with  spirit. 
Natural  forming  is  moral  and  rational  only  in  so  far 
as  it  is  the  sensuous  expressing  of  a  spiritual  forming. 

All  dominating  is  necessarily  a  forming,  inasmuch  as  the 
dominated  is  more  or  less  an  expression  of  the  will  of  the  dom 
inating  power.  A  natural  entity  can  bear  this  expression 
only  in  virtue  of  being  shaped  by  man  and  at  the  same  time 
for  man.  In  natural  forming  the  difference  between  man,  as  a 
moral  creature,  and  the  brute,  becomes  at  once  plainly  visible. 
The  activity  of  the  brute  is  predominantly  a  sensuous  appro 
priating;  that  of  man  is  predominantly  a  forming,  and  indeed 
primarily  a  sensuously-natural  forming.  The  appropriating 
of  nature  is  primarily  permitted  by  God  to  man,  and  is  limited 
by  a  prohibition  only  in  one  respect;  the  forming  of  nature 
is  enjoined  upon  him  [Gen.  i,  28;  ii,  15].  The  mere  letting 


§108.]  PURE   ETHICS.  201 

alone  of  even  a  Paradisaical  nature  in  its  given  condition,  is 
for  man  per  se  immoral ;  he  is  called  to  form  it  into  a  home  for 
himself  by  Ms  personal  activity. — But  man  cannot  morally  ac 
complish  a  natural  forming  save  on  the  condition  that  there 
exists  already  in  him  an  antecedent  moral  forming.  The 
artist  cannot  create  a  work  of  art  unless  it  has  already  been 
spiritually  formed  in  his  soul ;  and  each  and  every  object  that 
is  shaped,  is  to  be,  in  its  entire  purpose,  not  a  mere  solitary 
something  existing  for  itself,  but  rather  one  of  the  stones  of  a 
greater  and  essentially-spiritual  structure, — the  structure  of 
history.  Man  shapes  nature  not  for  its  own  sake  but  for  hu 
manity,  namely,  into  a  home  for  man's  spiritual  life,  into  an 
expression  of  historical  reality, — which  is  essentially  the  prod 
uct  of  spiritual  forming.  Hence  natural  forming  has  always 
the  purpose  simply  of  serving  the  spiritual,  even  as  the  nourish 
ment  and  development  of  the  body  take  place  not  in  the  inter 
est  of  the  body,  but  of  the  spirit. 

SECTION  CVIII. 

Spiritual  forming  relates  to  the  spiritual  essence 
of  the  object,  and  hence  predominantly  to  the  con 
scious  spirit ;  it  is  a  communicating  of  the  spiritual 
possession  of  the  subject  to  the  object,  a  shaping  of  the 
object  according  to  the  rational  idea  of  the  subject, 
a  putting  of  the  former  into  harmony  with  the  moral 
person  of  the  latter.  Each  man  has  the  duty  of 
helping  spiritually  to  form  every  other  one  who 
comes  into  spiritual  relation  with  him,  that  is,  of 
communicating  to  him  his  own  moral  nature,  of  re 
vealing  himself  to  him  ;  this  holds  good  even  of  the 
as  yet  morally  immature  in  relation  to  the  morally 
mature.  All  morally-spiritual  communicating  is  a 
forming,  and  all  spiritual  forming  is  a  communicating. 
Communicating  is,  however,  only  then  a  moral  form 
ing,  when  the  communicating  spirit  itself  stands  in 
harmony  with  God,  is  itself  morally  good,  and  when 
its  motive  is  love. 


202  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§108. 

Also  spiritual  forming  extends  in  a  certain  sense  to  nature- 
objects,  in  so  far  as  these  are  not  a  mere  sensuous  existence, 
but  have  also  spiritual  contents.  The  training  and  enno 
bling  of  domestic  animals  is  not  a  sensuous  but  a  relatively- 
spiritual  forming ,  inasmuch  as  their  inner  nature  is  raised 
to  a  higher  plane.  The  chief  sphere  of  spiritual  forming  is, 
however,  the  personal  spirit.  Man  has  neither  the  right  nor 
the  liberty  to  develop  himself  as  a  mere  isolated  individual, — 
he  cannot  develop  himself  morally  save  when  in  spiritual  life- 
relation  with  the  moral  community;  and  each  stands  with 
every  other  in  such  a  moral  relation.  And  this  relation  is  a 
mutual  forming  and  appropriating,  at  the  same  time.  Man  is 
formed  only  by  appropriating  to  himself  spiritual  elements, 
that  is,  in  that  another  spirit  reveals  itself  to  him.  Forming 
cannot  take  place  morally  by  the  imbuing  of  thoughts  and 
sentiments  that  are  foreign  to  the  subject  himself  into  the 
spirit  that  is  to  be  educated,  for  this  would  be  deception,  and 
would  not  establish  a  spiritual  communion ;  it  can  be  done 
only  by  a  self-revelation  of  the  moral  spirit.  Only  the  morally- 
formed  spirit  can  itself  form ;  the  immoral  spirit  can  only  per 
vert,  and  can  do  this  successfully  only  when  it  affects  morality. 
However,  it  is  not  necessary  that  the  formative  spirit  should 
be  already  mature  ;  also  the  child  exerts  a  formative  influence 
upon  its  elders. — In  the  condition  of  sinlessness  the  formative 
activity  has  no  need  of  art  or  of  a  calculated  plan ;  mere  self- 
manifestation  exercises  a  formative  influence  directly  and  of 
itself.  All  artfully-planned  manners  of  influencing  are  evi 
dence  of  lost  purity,  and  cannot,  however  cunningly  contrived, 
exert  the  power  of  the  moral  reality.  The  moral  spirit  lets  its 
light  shine  before  men  that  they  may  see  its  good  works,  and 
this  light  directly  illumines  and  enlightens  the  spirit  of  others. 
This  self-revelation,  however,  would  be  immoral,  that  is,  hollow 
and  empty,  were  it  to  spring  from  self-complacency  instead  of 
from  love  to  others.  It  is  love  alone  that  divests  this  letting 
one's  light  shine  of  an  appearance  of  parade.  Loving  souls 
hide  themselves  not  from  each  other;  true  love  impels  to  a 
full  and  genuine  self-communication;  and  moral  love  has 
nothing  that  it  would  gladly  or  necessarily  conceal. 


§109.]  PURE   ETHICS.  203 


SECTION  CIX. 

(5)  According  to  the  manner  in  which  the  objective 
entity  is  formatively  influenced,  we  have  to  distinguish 
between  particular  and  general -forming. 

1.  Particular  forming  forms  single  objects  for  the 
service  of  the  earthly  wants  of  single  or  several  per 
sons,  that  is,  for  use  for  temporal  ends.  It  is  there 
fore  labor,  in  the  proper  and  narrower  sense  of  the 
word.  Labor  relates  not  merely  to  natural  matter, 
but  also  to  the  individual  spirit,  in  so  far  as  the  latter 
is  to  be  formed  for  the  temporal  earthly  life,  and 
hence  is  spiritual  as  well  as  natural  forming. 

All  utility  relates  to  the  particular ;  that  which  is  for  the 
common  utility  is  simply  that  which  is  useful  for  many  par 
ticular  persons.  When  the  Rationalistic  school  spoke  of  the 
"common  utility"  of  religion,  it  manifested  simply  very  bad 
taste ;  religion  is  thus  placed  on  a  par,  e.  </.,  with  a  public 
fountain  or  an  advertising  sheet.  Labor  concerns  the  indi 
vidual  ;  works  for  the  common  utility,  such  as  roads  or  canals, 
look  not  to  the  good  of  humanity  as  a  whole,  as  a  unity,  but 
to  the  many  individual  persons  whom  they  are  to  benefit ;  for 
him  who  does  not  use  them,  they  have  no  significancy  and  are 
perhaps  even  offensive.  Their  utility  and  enjoyment  fall  to 
the  individual  as  such,  but  not  in  virtue  of  his  being  a  man, 
a  rational  spirit.  In  a  work  of  art,  however,  one  has  pleas 
ure  precisely  in  his  character  of  rational  spirituality ;  although 
from  another  stand-point  this  work  is  of  no  "use"  to  him 
whatever.  That  which  is  to  exalt  the  Tieart  must  be  more 
than  labor.  Products  of  labor  may  indeed  excite  a  general 
and  rational  interest,  as,  for  example,  a  machine  or  other 
superior  fruits  of  skill;  here,  however,  it  is  not  the  work 
itself  that  is  admired,  but  the  art  to  which  the  handicraft  has 
been  exalted, — the  spiritual  power  of  invention,  that  is,  the 
power  of  spirit, — not  the  utility,  but  the  beauty  or  ingenuity, 
— not  the  merely  individual  element,  but  the  spiritual,  which, 
as  such,  bears  upon  itself  the  stamp  of  general  significancy 


204  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [£  109. 

and  validity.  The  actual  work  on  a  machine  is  performed 
not  by  the  ingenious  inventor,  the  master,  but  by  the  manual 
laborer ;  and  in  that  which  this  laborer  executes  there  is  lit 
tle  else  to  admire  than  the  industry,  but  nothing  of  a  general 
interest.  The  end  of  a  work  of  art  is  not,  to  be  used  by  the 
individual,  but  to  be  enjoyed  and  admired  universally;  and 
it  is  properly  regarded  as  a  sign  of  spiritual  unculture  when 
a  particular  age  takes  delight  only  in  the  merely  useful,  in  mere 
labor,  and  not  also  in  that  which  transcends  labor,  namely, 
in  art, — when  the  age  does  not  also  exalt  labor  into  art.  In 
the  time  of  Rationalistic  illuminisin  many  "useless"  art- 
structures  of  the  Middle  Ages,  magnificent  castles  and 
churches,  were  converted  into  magazines  and  factories. — art 
was  turned  into  a  hand-maid  of  labor;  this  was  certainly  very 
"useful,  "but  it  was  at  the  same  time  also  an  evidence  of 
shameful  unculture.  The  spirit  of  mere  utility  is  but  little 
removed  from  barbarism. 

Labor  is  not  mere  manual  toil.  Common  usage  is  perfectly 
right  when  it  speaks  also,  and  not  merely  in  the  stricter 
sense  of  the  word,  of  spiritual,  intellectual,  labor,  and  of  intel 
lectual  laborers,  in  distinction  from  a  higher  spiritual  and 
intellectual  activity.  The  highest  results  to  which  the  spirit 
can  attain  are  not  effected  by  labor;  the  delicate,  etherial  im 
age  which  delights  our  astonished  gaze  was  not  painfully 
wrought  out  by  the  sweat  of  the  multitude,  but  sprang  forth 
at  once  from  the  brain  of  genius ;  but,  as  distinguished  from 
this  ideal  activity  of  the  spirit,  there  is  another  which  is  en 
titled  to  be  called  work  in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word,  and 
which  consists  in  a  strictly-particular  forming.  All  spiritual 
activity  which  looks  to  the  mere  benefit  of  individuals  is 
labor;  thus,  we  speak  of  the  labor  of  pupils,  of  official  labors, 
etc.  The  pupil  labors  in  order,  by  the  appropriation  of  par 
ticular  scientific  material,  to  form  himself  as  an  individual 
for  a  calling  in  life ;  the  teacher  labors  upon  the  pupil  for  the 
same  end.  All  spiritual  forming  which  looks  to  success  in 
the  world,  to  obtaining  a  position  in  it,  is  labor ;  hence  also 
we  maj  speak  of  a  scientific  industry ;  there  is  an  immense 
difference  between  science  as  manual  labor,  and  science  as  an 
art.  When  the  learner,  however,  elevates  himself  to  a  more 
ideal  activity, — when,  inspired  with  enthusiasm  for  the  true 


§110.]  PURE   ETHICS.  205 

and  the  good,  he  soars  above  the  merely  particular,  or  when 
the  teacher  seeks  to  awaken  an  enthusiasm  of  this  character 
in  him,  then  the  activity  ceases  to  be  labor  and  becomes 
a  higher  kind  of  forming.  It  is  true,  we  sometimes  speak, 
though  in  a  less  strict  sense,  of  a  laboring  in  the  sphere  of 
purely  spiritual  things,  as,  for  example,  in  that  of  religion 
and  of  active  love  [Rom.  xvi,  6,  12;  1  Thess.  i,  3;  Heb.  vi,  10; 
1  Cor.  xv,  58;  2  Cor.  vi,  5;  xi,  27;  Rev.  ii,  2,  3;  xiv,  13]; 
Paul  says,  "I  labored  more  abundantly  than  they  all "  [1  Cor. 
xv,  10  J,  and  the  pastor  and  the  messenger  of  the  Word  may 
speak  of  their  labor  on  souls  [1  Cor.  xvi,  16;  2  Cor.  x,  15 ; 
xi,  23 ;  1  Thess.  iii,  5 ;  v,  12 ;  1  Tim.  v,  17] ;  however,  in  this 
essentially  figuratively-used  expression  [see  John  iv,  38 ; 
1  Cor.  iii,  8]  reference  is  had  not  to  the  activity  per  se,  but  to 
the  trouble  in  overcoming  obstacles  (hence  the  words  KOTTOC 
and  KOTUCIW)  which  lie  not  in  the  matter  itself,  but  in  other  cir 
cumstances,  such  as  the  enmity  of  sinful  men,  the  feebleness 
of  the  actor  himself,  etc. 

SECTION  CX. 

2.  General  forming  forms  the  object  for  a  general, 
that  is,  a  rational  end, — not  merely  for  a  particular 
need,  for  temporal  utility,  but  for  the  rational  and 
moral  spirit  in  general, — forms  it  for  rational  enjoy 
ment,  for  moral  approbation,  i.  e.  into  a  beautiful  and 
good  product, — is  artistic  forming,  in  the  largest  sense 
of  the  word.  It  may  be  a  sensuous  as  well  as  a 
spiritual  forming.  The  natural  entity  receives  a  spirit 
ual  form, — becomes  an  expression,  an  image,  of  the 
rational  spirit,  an  expression  of  harmony  in  general, 
—a  work  of  art.  The  spiritual  entity  is  formed  into 
an  essentially  God-answering,  truly  rational  char 
acter,  into  a  beautiful  soul,  into  a  child  of  God.  Re 
ligious  and  ideal  culture  in  general  differs  essentially 
from  education  for  a  worldly  calling, — aims  not  to 
make  man  into  a  "  useful  "  and  serviceable  being,  but 
into  one  in  whom  both  God  and  men  have  pleasure, 


206  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  110. 

and  who  has  himself  pleasure  in  God  and  in  all  that 
is  divine  and  beautiful, — seeks  not  to  mold  him  into 
a  merely  isolated  being,  a  mere  citizen,  a  mere  pro 
fessional  man,  but  seeks  to  bring  to  development  that 
which  is  purely  and  truly  human  in  him, — seeks  to 
make  the  merely  natural  person  into  an  image  of  the 
moral  spirit,  into  a  true  image  of  God,  into  an  ex 
pression  of  the  truth.  All  that  which  is  created  by 
general  forming  is  art-work  ;  and  when  this  forming, 
as  distinguished  from  professional  working,  creates  a 
science,  then  this  science  becomes  itself  a  work  of  art. 
Hence,  no  general  forming  is  possible  without  moral 
enthusiasm,  that  is,  without  being  imbued  with  and 
prompted  by  a  universal  spirit  which  divests  itself  of 
all  individual  narrowness,  and  of  all  selfishness,  and 
aspires  to  a  universal  divine  ideal  (§  96). — A  special 
phase  of  general  forming  constitutes  the  typical  or 
symbolical  activity,  under  which  falls  also  the  mor 
ally  becoming. 

The  fruit  which  is  aimed  at  in  mere  work  is  only  for  the 
benefit  of  the  individual ;  works  of  art,  and  the  beautiful 
and  good  in  general,  are  for  the  spiritual  enjoyment  of  rational 
man  as  such.  Also  the  angels  must  rejoice  in  heaven,  not 
only  over  a  sinner  who  repents,  but  also  over  all  that  is  truly 
beautiful.  Man  forms  himself  into  a  useful,  a  skillful,  a 
learned  member  of  society  by  labor  and  pains-taking,  but  into 
a  beautiful  soul  only  by  enthusiasm ;  this  is  indeed  not  the 
beautiful  soul  as  improvised  by  sentimental  novelists,  but  the 
soul  that  is  beautiful  in  the  eyes  of  God  un,d  of  all  of  God's 
children, — the  child-soul  of  a  child  of  God,  full  of  love  and 
enthusiasm, — the  soul  of  him  who  is  pure  of  heart,  and  which 
inwardly  beholds  God,  because  God  looks  upon  it  with  pleas 
ure.  Hence  the  Scriptures  look  upon  the  higher  artistic 
endowment  as  a  special  gift  from  God  [Exod.  xxxi,  3,  6; 
xxxvi,  1,  2]. 

Art  in  its  deepest  ground  and  essence  is  religious,  as  in  fact 


§  110.]  PURE   ETHICS.  207 

historically  it  is  a  birth  of  religion ;  this  holds  good  with 
out  exception  of  all  nations.  No  religion  is  without  art, 
without  an  ideal  embodying  of  the  highest  ideas.  Architect 
ure,  plastic  art  and  song,  among  all  nations,  have  sprung 
from  religion,  and  are  the  subservient  attendants  of  religion 
[Exod.  xxxi,  2  sqq.;  xxxv,  1  sqq.] ;  and  it  required  all  the  un- 
genial  one-sidedness  and  bald  reflective  tendency  of  Zwingli 
to  banish  art  from  the  Church, — a  wrong  against  Christian 
humanity  which  has,  at  least  in  some  degree,  been  disavowed 
in  most  of  the  branches  of  the  Reformed  Church.  Even 
worldly  art,  in  so  far  as  it  has  not,  untrue  to  its  essential  na 
ture,  entered  into  the  service  of  sin,  is  closely  related  to 
religion.  It  also  elevates  man  above  the  merely  individual 
and  sensuously-natural;  and,  itself  a  birth  of  enthusiasm,  it 
awakens  also  in  man  enthusiasm  for  the  beautiful  and  the 
noble, — for  that  which  raises  him  out  of  his  isolation  and 
self-seeking,  and  up  to  that  which  finds  response  in  all  moral 
souls.  L(*ve  to  art  banishes  rudeness, — makes  the  heart 
receptive  also  for  the  morally  beautiful  and  divine.  Hence 
the  culture  of  art  is  so  important  an  element  in  education 
and  in  the  life  of  nations.  But  for  this  reason  also  art  be 
comes  such  a  demon-power,  when,  forgetting  its  nobility,  it 
stoops  to  the  role  of  pandering  to  corrupt  pleasure,  and  when, 
instead  of  inspiring  enthusiasm  for  the  truly  beautiful,  it  only 
aims  to  intoxicate  and  seduce  by  lustful  appeals  to  the  senses. 
"Wherever  there  is  a  healthful  religious  life,  there  art  and  re 
ligion  stand  in  intimate  and  mutual  relations.  Where  faith  is 
alive  in  the  heart,  there  it  utters  itself  in  "psalms  and  spirit 
ual  songs,"  there  it  celebrates  the  glory  of  its  God  in  a 
becoming  ornamentation  of  his  altars  and  courts  [Exod.  xxxv, 
21  sqq.],  and  wherever  true  art  prevails  there  it  consecrates 
the  most  beautiful  of  its  products  to  the  honor  of  God.  Re 
ligion  created  for  the  Greeks  poets  and  artists,  and  the  poets 
and  artists  created  for  the  Greeks  their  gods ;  and  however 
much  there  may  have  been  of  heathen  error  in  these  creations, 
still  this  much  at  least  is  here  exemplified,  namely,  that  the 
divine  makes  its  nearest  approaches  to  man  in  the  words,  the 
songs  and  the  works  of  artistic  inspiration.  The  prophets  of 
the  Ancient  Covenant  were  also  unable  to  bring  down  to  the 
plane  of  mere  simple  prose,  the  visions  which  they  had  spirit- 


208  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  110. 

ually  beholden ;  and  also  the  Prophet  of  the  Few  Covenant 
publishes  his  visions  under  the  drapery  of  boldly-constructed 
symbols.  He  who  finds  fault  with  this  knows  neither  art  nor 
religion. 

General  moral  forming  does  not  necessarily  take  place 
directly  and  immediately ;  as  relating  to  the  free  spirit,  it 
consists  essentially  in  the  fact  that,  by  the  moral  activity  of 
the  subjcctj  the  object  is  so  incited  and  inspired  as  to  bring 
about  self-development  through  his  own  spontaneity  and 
strength.  In  this  consists  the  true  art  of  education  and  gov 
erning,  namely,  in  that  the  guiding  power  hides  itself  in  some 
respect  from  the  spirit  that  is  to  be  molded, — does  not  per 
mit  its  influence  upon  it  to  appear  as  a  limiting,  overpowering 
force,  but  rather  simply  gives  scope  for  free  and  independent 
self-development.  This  does  not  take  place,  however,  by  a 
simple  "letting  alone"  of  the  one  who  is  to  be  guided,  but 
by  the  fact  that  the  moral  and  rational  consciousness  is  quick 
ened  and  strengthened  in  him,  — that  he  is  brought  to  feel  and 
know  himself,  not  as  a  mere  non-obligated  individual,  but  as 
a  personality  inspired  by  a  holy  and  moral  spirit, — that  a 
moral  disposition  and  an  ideal  enthusiasm  become  in  him  an 
actuating  power,  which  in  turn  itself  forms  him  to  a  higher 
development  and  perfection. 

There  is  an  important  sphere  of  moral  activity,  namely,  sym 
bolical  forming — to  which  belongs  also  the  practicing  of  the  be 
coming, — which  can  be  understood  only  from  the  stand-point  of 
general  artistic  forming; — a  sphere  of  stumbling  and  oft'ense 
to  all  champions  of  the  merely  prosaically  useful.  The  moral 
ly-good,  is  not  simply  to  become  real,  but  the  real  is  also  to  be 
an  expression,  a  manifestation  of  the  morally-good, — is  to  bear 
witness  in  its  entire  outward  appearance  to  an  inner  ideal 
quality,  and  every  single  good  is  to  show  itself  not  merely  as 
per  se  good,  but  is  also  to  point  to  a  higher  good  beyond 
itself.  Even  as  in  nature,  the  good,  as  a  regulated  means  to 
an  end,  is  associated  with  a  beauty  more  significant  than  the 
mere  fitness  for  an  end, — even  as  the  flower  not  merely  pos 
sesses  the  fructifying  organs  and  the  delicate  tissues  that  pro 
tect  them,  but  also,  in  its  graceful  form,  its  hues  and  its 
fragrance,  delights  man,  and,  as  a  symbol  of  the  eternally 
beautiful,  reminds  him  of  divine  love  and  of  the  glory  of  God, 


§110.]  PURE   ETHICS.  209 

— even  as  the  birds  of  song  not  only  nourish  themselves  and 
propagate  their  race,  but  also  praise  the  goodness  of  the 
Creator  in  strains  that  touch  tho  heart, — even  as  God  not  only 
causes  the  sun  to  shine  and  to  awaken  life,  and  the  clouds  to 
drop  rain,  but  also  paints  on  the  skies  the  color-resplendent 
bow  as  a  pledge  of  his  faithfulness  and  grace, — in  a  word,  as 
God  himself  decks  his  creation  with  such  grandeur  that  the 
heavens  proclaim  his  glory,  and  with  such  beauty  that  the 
understanding  is  incapable  adequately  to  comprehend  it,  but 
only  the  adoring  heart  to  feel  and  love  it, — so  also  man,  as 
God-like,  not  only  forms  that  which  is  useful  for  the  temporal 
life,  but  also  that  which,  as  a  significant  sign,  points  to  a 
higher  good, — forms  reality  into  a  type  of  the  true  and  good, 
— creates  the  poetry  of  reality.  Every  artistic  product  is  such 
a  sign  or  symbol,  but  all  symbolical  forming  is  not  properly 
artistic  in  the  stricter  sense,  though  it  is  indeed  poetical. 
The  clothing  of  man  is  not  simply  for  a  protection  against 
the  weather,  but  also  largely  a  suggestive  expression  of  the 
inner  life  *  all  adornment  as  well  as  cleanliness  has  a  spiritual 
suggestiveness.  For  him  who  knows  not  this  symbolical, 
poetical  phase  of  the  moral,  a  very  important  and  essential 
part  of  morality  remains  incomprehensible.  A  large  portion 
of  the  moral  precepts  of  the  Scriptures  look  not  to  a  direct 
and  simple  realization  of  a  good,  but  to  the  expressive  sug 
gesting  of  a  moral  element  not  directly  contained  in  the  mat 
ter  itself, — have  a  symbolical  character;  and  lightly  to  esteem 
this  phase  of  things  is  an  indication  of  moral  obtuseness. 
Doubtless  it  was  not  very  "useful"  when  Mary,  the  sister  of 
Lazarus,  took  a  pound  of  pure  and  costly  ointment  and 
anointed  the  Lord's  feet ;  and  the  harsh  reproof  of  Judas  was 
perfectly  well-grounded  from  the  stand-point  of  mere  utili 
tarianism,  but  the  Lord  judged  very  differently  from  Judas 
[John  xii,  3  sqq.;  comp.  Mark  xiv,  3  sqq.].  To  this  category 
belong  almost  all  the  precepts  of  the  Old  Testament  in  regard 
to  the  clean  and  the  unclean,  to  food  and  clothing, — in  which 
case  the  object  of  the  forming  is  man  himself, — and  also  in 
regard  to  the  form  of  worship  and  whatever  is  therewith  con 
nected,  such  as  circumcision,  etc.,  as  well  as  in  regard  to  agri 
culture  [Lev.  xix,  19 ;  Deut.  xxii,  9,  10]  and  to  the  treatment 
of  animals  [Exod.  xxi,  28,  29,  32;  xxiii,  19;  Lev.  xx,  15,  16]. 
VOL.  11—15 


210  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§1H- 

The  becoming  is  the  outward,  beautiful  or  symbolical  form 
of  the  moral, — in  a  certain  sense  its  esthetic  phase.  To  cele 
brate  the  Lord's  day  in  the  spiritual-exalting  of  the  heart  to 
God,  is  a  moral  duty;  to  give  expression  to  the  celebration 
by  sacred  art  and  by  a  worthy  outward  appearance,  is  becom 
ing.  The  ungodly  world  is  prone  to  substitute  in  the  place  of 
the  moral  substance  an  outwardly  and  externally  gracious 
form — the  becoming ;  the  suggestion  :  ' '  That  is  not  becom 
ing,"  is  with  the  irreligious  world  of  much  more  weight  than : 
"It  is  sinful."  The  outward  form  may  indeed  be  hypocriti 
cally  assumed  in  the  absence  of  the  substance,  but  he  who 
holds  fast  to  the  moral  substance,  must  observe  also  the  form ; 
he  only  is  morally-cultured  who  not  only  observes  the  sub 
stance  of  the  general  precepts,  but  also  aims  at  the  morally- 
becoming  ;  and  this  is  in  fact  a  general  and  artistic  forming 
on  the  part  of  the  moral  activity.  The  becoming  stands  not 
along-side  of  the  moral  precept,  but  is  essentially  contained 
in  it,  as,  in  fact,  without  it  man  remains  coarse  and  rude. 
Almost  all  of  the  above-mentioned  precepts  of  the  Old  Testa 
ment  are  precepts  of  the  becoming,  and  the  New  Testament 
also  lays  great  stress  on  the  becoming  [1  Cor.  xi,  4  sqq.;  1  Tim. 
ii,  9,  and  others]. 

SECTION   CXI. 

Appropriating  and  forming  are,  in  a  right  moral 
development,  ever  in  association  with  eacli  other,  and 
that  too  all  the  closer  the  higher  their  character. 
No  spiritual  appropriating  is  without  spiritual  self- 
forming,  and  no  forming  of  an  objective  entity  is 
without  a  spiritual  appropriating  of  the  thing  formed  ; 
and  in  fact  the  forming  of  one's  own  spirit  is  per  se 
necessarily  an  appropriating.  The  measure  of  appro 
priating  and  especially  of  enjoying  stands  in  all  right 
development,  always  in  strict  relation  to  the  measure 
of  the  forming ;  and  the  two  modes  of  forming  are 
associated  not  only  with  each  other,  but  also  with  the 
two  modes  of  appropriating,  as  are  in  turn  the  latter 
with  each  other. 


§  111.]  PURE   ETHICS.         •  211 

The  fruit  of  labor  and  still  more  the  work  of  art,  are  the 
property  of  the  laborer  and  the  artist;  they  call  it  their  own; 
they  have  appropriated  it  to  themselves  in  the  very  process 
of  producing  it.  The  outward-directed  activity  turns  thus 
about  and  flows  back  into  the  acting  person.  In  forming  an 
objective  entity,  man  forms  his  own  self ;  he  has  the  work 
not  merely  as  his  own,  as  a  copy  of  his  thought,  but  he  ia 
also  himself  spiritually  and  morally  promoted  both  by  the 
working  and  by  the  work.  All  forming  is  self-forming ;  and 
inasmuch  as  man  stands  to  his  fellows  in  a  spiritual  relation, — • 
reveals  himself  to  them  through  his  culture, — hence  all  self- 
forming  is  directly  also  in  turn  a  forming  of  others. — All  par 
ticular  forming,  all  work,  should  as  moral  include  in  itself 
also  at  the  same  time  an  element  of  general  forming;  without 
this  the  laborer  falls  into  spiritual  and  moral  deterioration. 
When  the  laborer  unites  the  useful  with  the  beautiful, — 
gives  to  his  work  a  graceful  form, — when  song  accompanies 
the  work,  when  the  heart  mounts  up  from  the  work  that 
serves  a  temporal  end,  toward  the  Eternal  One,  and  thus  puts 
into  earnest  practice  the  precept:  "Pray  and  labor,"  then 
the  particular  forming  is  exalted  and  transfigured  by  the 
general.  The  more  isolated,  the  more  limited,  the  work  is,  so 
much  the  more  preponderates  the  merely  useful  phase  of  it ; 
hence  no  work  is  so  dangerous,  nay,  so  detrimental,  to  the 
harmoniously-moral  culture  of  man  as  the  spiritless  mechan 
ism  of  f actory-work ;  and  white  slavery  works  here  often 
much  more  ruinously  than  the  black.  The  uninterrupted 
monotony  of  the  narrow  routine  of  the  work  paralyzes  the 
spirit  and  subverts  morality. 

Furthermore,  all  forming  is  not  only  a  general  appropriat 
ing,  formative  of  the  subject  himself,  in  that  he  recognizes 
the  product  of  his  influence,  but  also  a  particular  appropriat 
ing,  in  that  he  enjoys  it.  The  divine  prototype  of  this  is 
seen  in  the  account  of  creation,  where  we  read  that  God 
looked  upon  all  that  he  had  made,  and  found  that  it  was 
very  good.  All  moral  work,  and  still  more,  all  general  form 
ing,  are,  in  and  of  themselves,  also  enjoyment,  and  that  too  the 
highest  and  purest  enjoyment,  even  as  in  the  above  utterance 
of  the  Creator  his  own  bliss  was  implicitly  expressed  also. 
But  also  the  sensuous  enjoyment  that  is  not  directly  included 


212  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  112. 

in  the  formative  activity  itself,  is  nevertheless,  in  virtue  of  the 
moral  order  of  the  world,  associated  with  it.  Adam  was  first 
to  dress  and  care  for  the  garden,  and  thereafter  to  eat  of  its 
fruits  [Gen.  ii,  15,  16].  "If  any  one  will  not  work,  neither 
should  he  eat "  [2  Thess.  iii,  10] ;  this  is  a  morally  unassailable 
principle ;  and  where  the  practice  is  otherwise,  there  the 
social  relations  are  corrupt;  and  the  grudge  of  the  suffering 
laborer  against  the  luxurious  idler  has  a  very  just  foundation. 
In  proportion  to  the  degree  of  productive  activity,  'rises  or 
falls  the  moral  right  to  enjoyment  in  general,  and  to  personal 
position  in  society.  Hence  the  admonition :  Let  each  labor 
to  produce  with  his  own  hands  something  good  [Eph.  iv,  28 ; 
cornp.  Acts  xx,  34,  35;  1  Thess.  iv,  11 ;  ii,  9]. 

SECTION  CXII. 

Inasmuch  as  man  becomes  perfect  only  through 
the  perfect  all-sided  development  of  all  his  life-phases, 
and  as  any  exclusive  realization  and  culture  of  one, 
or  simply  some,  of  them  works  a  disturbance  of  the 
inner  harmony,  hence  every  person  should,  in  so  far 
as  his  circumstances  admit  of  it,  realize  every  form 
of  moral  appropriation  and  moral  culture.  He  who 
allows  his  life  to  be  devoted  exclusively  to  particular 
forming  and  appropriating, — to  toil  and  enjoyment, 
has  fallen  out  of  moral  harmony,  and  is  consequently 
immoral.  General,  and  hence,  essentially,  religious, 
forming  must  attend  the  work  hand  in  hand  ;  and  the 
ordination  of  the  Sabbath  along-side  of  the  days  of 
labor  has  not  simply  a  religious,  but  essentially  also 
a  moral  significancy.  Moral  resting  from  labor  is  a 
rising  to  ideal  self-culture,  an  exalting  of  the  tempo 
rally-particular  into  the  eternal,  the  holy,  the  general, 
the  divine;  the  celebrating  of  the  Sabbath  is  the 
higher  and  moral  transfiguring  of  the  temporal  pro 
saic  individual  life  by  the  poesy  of  the  ideal  and  the 
infinite. 


§112.]  PURE   ETHICS.  213 

In  particular  forming  man  merges  himself  into  objective  ex 
istence  ;  primarily  he  has  not  the  object  in  his  own  possession, 
but  the  object  possesses  him;  hence  the  danger,  especially  in 
a  state  of  sinfulness,  that  the  person  lose  himself  in  his  la 
bor, — that,  as  in  sensuous  enjoyment,  he  passively  surrender 
himself  to  the  creature  [Eccles.  vi,  7,  in  the  Hebrew  text].  Man 
should,  however,  hold  fast  to  himself  and  to  his  Creator, — 
should  withdraw  himself  from  his  absorption  in  finite  things, 
collect  himself  in  spiritual  repose, — should  obtain  fresh  moral 
strength  for  the  particular  forming  of  industry,  in  the  general 
forming  which  springs  of  enthusiasm.  Even  as  God,  though 
merging  himself  into  the  world  while  creating  it,  yet  did  not 
lose  and  forget  himself  in  it,  but  returned  to  himself  and  to 
his  infinite  self-sufficiency,  and  ever  retains  himself  in  eternal 
unchangeable  majesty  above  all  that  is  created,  so  also  is  it  a 
moral  requirement  that  man,  in  his  creating  of  the  finite  and 
particular,  should  not  forget  himself  as  a  personality  gifted 
with  eternal  destinies ;  it  is  for  man's  sake  that  the  Sabbath 
was  made  [Mark  ii,  27].  It  is  very  suggestive  that  in  the 
Scriptures  the  repose  of  God  after  creation  is  made  the  proto 
type  and  basis  for  the  celebration  of  the  Sabbath  [Gen.  ii,  3 ; 
Exod.  xx,  8  sqq.  ].  It  is  thereby  implied  that  it  is  our  innermost  . 
God-likeness  that  calls  for  the  rest  of  the  Sabbath, — the  truly 
rational,  religiously-moral  essence  of  man,  and  not  the  mere 
natural  need  of  repose  and  enjoyment.  That  which  is  with 
God  only  two  phases  of  his  eternal  life  itself,  and  not  an  alter 
nation  in  time,  namely,  creative  action  and  self-possession,  this 
falls,  in  the  case  of  the  finite  spirit,  at  least  partially,  into  such 
an  alternation, — into  labor  and  Sabbath-rest.  God  blessed 
the  Sabbath  day ;  there  rests  upon  its  observance  an  especial, 
an  extraordinary  benediction,  an  impartation  of  heavenly 
goods,  even  as  the  blessing  upon  labor  is  primarily  only  an  im 
portation  of  temporal  goods.  The  Sabbath  has  not  merely  a 
negative  significancy,  is  not  a  mere  interruption  of  labor,  but 
it  has  a  very  rich  positive  significancy, —it  is  the  giving  free 
scope  to  the  higher,  time-transcending  nature  of  the  rational 
God-like  spirit,  the  re-attaching  of  the  spirit  that  had  been 
immersed  by  labor  into  the  temporal,  to  the  imperishable  and 
to  the  divine.  Where  God  is  conceived  of  as  swallowed  up 
in  nature,  as  with  the  Chinese  and  in  the  unbelief  of  our  own 


214  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  113. 

day,  there  there  exists  no  Sabbath ;  there  there  is  to  be  found 
only  a  discretionary  alternation  of  labor  and  sensuous  enjoy 
ment.  The  celebration  of  the  Sabbath  belongs  to  morality 
per  se,  and  does  not  depend  on  the  fact  of  the  state  of  redemp 
tion  from  sinfulness;  but  where  sin  is  as  yet  a  dominant 
power  there  its  observance  is  necessarily  less  free,  legally 
more  strict,  than  where  the  freedom  of  the  children  of  God 
prevails. 

From  the  fact  that  all  moral  working  is  attended  also  with 
a  general  forming,  it  follows  manifestly  that,  for  him  who  is 
truly  morally  free,  the  antithesis  of  Sabbath-rest  and  labor  is 
not  of  au  absolute  character, — that  every  day  and  all  labor  have 
also  their  Sabbath  consecration,  and  that,  on  the  other  hand, 
also  the  Sabbath  does  not  absolutely  exclude  all  work.  It  is 
perfectly  clear,  however,  that,  in  general,  only  such  works 
consist  with  the  observance  of  the  Sabbath  as  express  a  gen 
eral  formative  activity, — as  bear  an  artistic  character  in  the 
noblest  sense  of  the  word.  In  this  category  belong  those 
healings  of  the  sick  by  which  the  Lord  incurred  the  reproach 
of  Sabbath-breaking.  Such  works  are  not  labor,  but,  as  a 
restoring  of  the  disturbed  order  of  the  universe,  are  of  gen 
eral  and  spiritual  significaney. 


SUBDIVISION  SECOND. 

THE  MORAL  ACTIVITY  IN  ITS  DIFFERENCES  AS 
RELATING  TO  ITS  DIFFERENT   OBJECTS.  — I.  IN 

RELATION  TO   GOD. 

SECTION  CXIII. 

As  God  sustains  to  man  an  essentially  active  and 
creative,  but  not  a  receptive,  relation,  hence  in  the 
strict  sense  of  the  word  he  is  an  object  only  of  moral 
appropriating. 

(a)  The  moral  appropriating  of  God  is  directly  at 
the  same  time  also  the  highest  moral  self-forming  of 
the  moral  person,  and  contains  two  necessarily  asso- 


§113.]  PURE   ETHICS.  215 

ciated  elements :  first,  that  God  becomes  for  us,  and 
secondly,  that  we  become  for  God  ;  that  is,  that,  on 
the  one  hand,  we  take  up  into  our  moral  conscious 
ness  the  ever  present  divine,  and  that,  on  the  other, 
we  elevate  our  moral  consciousness  to  God, — form  it 
into  the  divine  lite;  the  former  is  faith,  the  latter  is 
worship  /  neither  can  exist  without  the  other.  Be 
lieving  is  the  lovingly-willed  and  lovingly-willing, 
that  is,  the  pious  recognizing  of  God  as  lovingly 
revealing  himself  to  us  as  our  Lord  and  our  Father, 
and  to  whom  we  are  obligated  to  unconditional  obe 
dience  and  submissive  love, — it  is  the  self-conscious 
ness  of  man  as  having  come  to  its  rational  truth, 
namely,  in  that  man  regards  himself  no  more  as  a 
mere  isolated  individual,  but  thinks  of  himself  con 
stantly  and  strictly  in  his  relations  to  God. 

As  believing  is  essentially  the  particular  appropri 
ating  of  God,  so  the  knowing,  the  cognizing  of  Him 
is  the  general  appropriating ;  and  hence  the  striving 
for  this  knowledge  is  a  high  moral  duty ;  this  duty  is 
fulfilled  not  without  believing,  but  only  through  and 
in  virtue  of  the  same, — is  a  spiritual  receiving  and  a 
true  appropriating  of  the  divine  revelation  imparted 
to  us  through  the  channel  of  faith,  in  regard  to  the 
nature,  power,  and  will  of  God.  The  correct  knowl 
edge  of  God  is  not  the  antecedent  condition,  but  the 
goal  of  the  moral  striving,  and  hence  without  it  there 
can  be  no  perfection  of  morality. 

God  is  indeed  per  se  already  present  in  every  creature ;  but 
in  order  that  he  shall  be  truly  present  for  man,  that  is,  in  a 
manner  called  for  by  his  rational  nature,  it  is  necessary  that  man 
shall  freely  appropriate  to  himself  this  presence  of  God.  I 
possess  rationally  only  that  which  I  rationally  and  morally 
appropriate.  All  appropriating,  and  hence  all  faith,  pre-sup- 


216  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  113. 

poses  a  difference,  and  at  the  same  time  a  mutual  life-relation 
between  its  subject  and  its  object ;  what  I  already  am,  in  and  of 
myself,  that  I  cannot  appropriate  to  myself.  That  the  appro 
priating  of  God  is  a  moral  act,  arises  from  the  fact  that  man 
may  fully  admit  his  difference  from,  and  yet  not  heartily 
recognize  his  life- relation  to,  God, — may  cling  to  himself  as 
independent  of  God,  may  sinfully  aspire  even  to  become  like 
God.  It  is  a  moral  activity  when  man  raises  his  self-conscious 
ness,  which  is  primarily  merely  individual,  into  a  truly  rational 
one,  and  conceives  of  himself  not  merely  as  an  isolated  being, 
but  as  conditioned  by  God,  that  is,  as  created  by  and  obliga 
ted  to  God ;  it  is  only  this  religious  self-consciousness  that  is 
moral,  and  this  is  in  fact  faith.  Faith  is  not  a  mere  regard 
ing  as  true,  not  a  mere  religious  knowledge,  or  a  mere  object 
ive  consciousness,  but  it  is  a  morally-conditioned  believing,  a 
willing,  and  hence  a  loving,  recognition ;  in  faith  we  icill  to 
have  God  and  a  consciousness  of  him  in  us,  and  we  desire 
this  consciousness  as  divine,  that  is,  as  a  full  and  true  life- 
force,  and  hence  as  operative,  as  realizing  the  divine.  The 
notion  of  faith  combines,  therefore,  loving  and  willing  with 
knowing, — is  not  identical  with  one  of  the  three,  but  is  the 
unity  of  them, — is  not  an  affair  of  the  mere  understanding 
but  of  the  heart  (§  53).  Faith  is  the  thankful  reflection  of  the 
divine  love ;  lie  who  is  loved  by  God,  turns  himself  lovingly 
toward  the  loving  One.  Without  the  love  of  God  to  man 
there  would  be  no  love  of  man  to  God ;  man  believes  because 
he  becomes  conscious  of  the  divine  love ;  he  who  would  only 
recognize  received  love,  but  not  reciprocated  it  with  his  heart, 
is  immoral;  a  mere  recognition  of  God  without  heart-faith  is 
sinful. 

"Faith  is  the  substance  (the  sure  confidence)  of  things 
hoped  for,  the  evidence  of  things  not  seen"  [Hcb.  xi,  1];  it 
is  not  a  confidence  of  that  which  falls  within  the  immediate 
scope  of  experience,  but  of  that  which  lies  beyond  it,  not  of 
that  which  already  exists  in  realization  but  of  that  which  is 
yet,  in  virtue  of  faith,  to  be  realized  into  fact,  though  indeed 
it  already  exists  in  germ.  The  really  complete  life-communion 
with  God,  the  full  appropriating  of  the  divine,  is  at  first  only 
an  object  of  hope, — can  be  really  brought  about  only  through 
faith ;  and  faith  lays  hold,  in  full  confidence  of  success,  upon 


§113.]  PURE   ETHICS.  217 

the  divine  as  lovingly  revealing  itself  to  it.  Faith  stands, 
therefore,  not  by  the  side  of  knowledge,  as  if  not  including 
this  within  itself,  nor  yet  below  it,  as  if  it  were  but  a  lower 
degree  thereof,  and  would  cease  with  the  increase  of  knowl 
edge,  but  in  fact  above  it,  inasmuch  as  it  is  a  loving  knowing, 
a  lovingly-willed  and  lovingly-willing  knowing  of  God,  so 
that  consequently  it  includes  within  itself  both  feeling  and 
•willing  as  essential  constituent  elements.  Believing  leads  to 
knowing,  but  also  precedes  actual  knowing,  and  hence  is  not 
conditioned  thereon. 

As  particular  appropriating,  believing  or  faith  is,  so  to  speak, 
an  enjoying  of  the  divine, — belongs  essentially  to  the  person 
ality  itself,  and  is  therefore  not  communicable,  whereas  know 
ing  may,  on  the  presupposition  of  faith,  be  communicated  by 
instruction.  In  the  entire  sphere  of  the  religious  life,  believ 
ing  precedes  knowing,  for  without  faith  God  would  no  more 
exist  for  us  than  would  sensuous  objects  without  our  senses ; 
believing  includes,  it  is  true,  some  degree  of  knowing,  but  is 
not  per  se  complete  knowing.  And  for  the  simple  reason  that 
believing  includes  knowing  as  an  essential  element,  it  is  a 
moral  requirement  to  bring  our  knowing  to  its  highest  possi 
ble  perfection,  and  thereby  also  to  heighten  and  strengthen 
faith.  The  divine  revelation  as  received  by  faith  becomes 
real  knowledge  by  a  proper  spiritual  merging  of  ourselves 
into  it,  by  a  full  appropriating  of  its  contents  into  our  entire 
spiritually-transformed  being,  so  that  the  knowing  becomes 
thus  a  powerful  moral  motive  to  the  loving  of  God  and  to 
obedience  to  his  will  [Psa.  Ixiii,  7  sqq.  ;  Jer.  xxix,  13,  14;  John 
viii,  32;  Acts  xvii,  27;  Col.  i,  11;  Eph.  i,  17,  18].  The  knowl 
edge  of  God  consists  not  merely  iri  the,  as  yet,  only  imperfectly 
attainable  [1  Cor.  xiii,  9,  10;  2  Cor.  v,  7;  Isa.  Iv,  8,9]  knowl 
edge  of  God's  being  [Rom.  i,  19,  20],  but  also  of  the  divine 
will  as  to  us  [Col.  i,  9,  10 ;  Eph.  v,  15-17]  and  of  the  divine 
providential  activity  in  nature  and  in  human  life,  and  of  the 
holy  purpose  of  his  world-government.  Though  indeed  a  prop 
er  and  ripe  knowledge  of  God  leads  to  a  higher  perfection 
of  the  moral  life,  still  knowledge  is  not,  as  faith,  the  ante 
cedent  condition  of  the  moral  in  general;  for  only  he  can 
know  the  truth  of  God  who  is  pure  of  heart  [Matt,  v,  8]. 


218  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  114. 


SECTION  CXIV. 

The  second  phase  of  the  moral  appropriating  of 
God  is,  that  man  becomes  for  God, — that  he  exalts 
himself  toward  God  by  a  moral  act  in  order  to  unite 
God  actually,  and  riot  simply  in  inner  recognition, 
with  himself, — in  order  to  permit  the  divine  activity 
to  be  influential  upon  him  ;  this  is  in  fact  i\\Qivorship- 
ing  of  God,  which  is  at  once  a  religious  and  a  moral, 
and  hence  a  holy,  activity.  The  worship  of  God  is 
either  purely  spiritual  and  at  the  same  time  affirma 
tive,  namely,  in  that  man  puts  himself  spiritually  into 
direct  relation  with  God, — rises  to  God  in  pious  devo 
tion,  which  is  prayer, — or  it  is  of  a  rather  virtual 
and  at  the  same  time  more  negative  character,  namely, 
a  free  moral  turning  away  from  the  ungodly  and  the 
unholy, — sacrifice.  These  two  phases  of  the  worship 
ing  of  God  belong  inseparably  together ;  there  is  no 
prayer  without  sacrifice,  and  no  sacrifice  without 
prayer. 

Faith  is  the  purely  inward  phase  of  the  moral  appropriat 
ing  of  the  divine, — the  woman-like  self-opening  of  the  soul 
for  the  in-shining  of  the  divine  light ;  in  this  receiving,  the 
person  remains  strictly  in  and  with  himself.  Worshiping  is 
more  objective;  the  person  goes  forth  out  of  himself, — lets 
his  own  light  beam  forth  toward  the  divine  original  light, 
even  as  the  flame  of  the  sacrifice,  when  once  kindled  by  the 
heavenly  fire,  mounts  up  toward  heaven  again.  All  worship 
ing  of  God  presupposes  faith,  though  it  is  itself  more  than 
faith.  When  man  has  by  faith  received  the  divine  into  him 
self,  and  imbued  himself  therewith;  he  still  yet  distinguishes 
himself  as  a  creature  from  God, — puts  himself  into  moral  re 
lation  to  God,  raises  himself  by  a  moral  action  to  God  as  to 
one  different  from  himself ;  and  this  is  the  worshiping  of  God. 
To  the  pure  mystic  all  worship  falls  away,  for  he  loses  sight 
of  the  distinction  between  the  Infinite  and  the  finite. 


§  115.]  PURE   ETHICS.  219 

Worship  is  the  immediate  actual  outgoing  of  faith  •,  it  is  a 
religious  activity  which  aims  at  making  the  already  naturally- 
existing  communion  of  God  Avith  us  into  a  consciously-willed 
communion  of  ourselves  with  God ;  it  is  a  sacred  activity  as 
distinguished  from  the  worldly  or  profane, — from  that  which 
deals  only  with  temporal  things.  In  a  normal  moral  condition 
of  humanity,  all  activity  whatever  would  bear  a  sacred  char 
acter,  and  the  distinction  between  the  sacred  and  the  "pro 
fane  "  could  only  assume  the  form  of  a  conditional  outward 
difference  of  a  temporally-alternating  occupation  with  earthly 
things,  on  the  one  hand,  and  with  eternal  interests  on  the 
other ;  with  labor  and  with  the  Sabbath-rest  of  the  soul  dur 
ing  the  continuance  of  the  earthly  life,  and  that,  too,  only  in  so 
far  as  consistent  with  the  fact  that  all  earthly  occupation  is 
constantly  exalted  and  sanctified  by  a  positive  and  conscious 
relation  to  the  eternal.  Our  sacred  activity  relates  either  im 
mediately  to  God, — is  a  purely  affirmative  uniting  of  the  human 
to  the  divine ;  or  it  relates  only  mediately  to  God,  but  imme 
diately  to  the  ungodly,  namely,  in  that  by  refusing  the  un 
godly,  it  sets  up  a  barrier  against  it, — turns  the  heart  away 
from  the  evil,  and  toward  God.  These  two  features  can  never 
be  separated ;  prayer  without  sacrifice,  without  a  rejecting  of 
the  ungodly  both  within  and  without  us,  is  morally  impossi 
ble  ;  in  exalting  ourselves  to  God  in  prayer  we  at  the  same 
time  distinguish  the  divine  from  the  anti-divine,  and 
withdraw  ourselves  from  the  latter;  we  cannot  truly  pray 
without  at  the  same  time  renouncing  the  worldly, — without 
giving  up,  without  sacrificing,  the  pretentious  emptiness  of 
finite  things. 

SECTION  CXV. 

1.  Prayer,  as  resting  on  faith  in  the  personal  God, 
is  the  free  moral  uniting  of  the  believing  heart  with 
God,  in  such  a  manner  that  the  moral  personality  is 
in  fact  not  lost,  but,  on  the  contrary,  exalted  in  and 
by  God ;  it  is  the  free  and  conscious  recognizing  that 
God  knows  all  our  thoughts,  and  the  joyful  wish  that 
such  be  the  case;  it  exalts  our  natural  communion 
with  God  into  a  spiritual  and  moral  one,  the  being 


220  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§115. 

of  God  in  man  into  a  being  of  man  in  God.  As  it 
is  alone  in  this  being  at  one  with  God  that  the  true 
life  of  the  rational  spirit  consists,  hence  in  the  moral 
man,  at  least  ?t  prayerful  disposition,  if  not  express 
praying  in  words,  must  be  strictly  unceasing.  Prayer 
has  only  then  moral  worth  when  it  really  springs  of 
a  praying  heart,  and  hence,  when  it  is  offered  with 
devotion  •  and  as  it  unites  the  person  with  the  Father 
of  all  men,  hence  it  leads  to  a  communion  of  prayer, 
and  the  higher  form  of  prayer  is  therefore  social 
prayer. 

In  prayer  man  enters  into  personal  communion  with  God, 
and  in  loving  confidence  expressly  communicates  to  him  as  the 
All-knowing  One,  his  pious  thinking,  feeling,  and  willing; 
only  that  which  is  pious  can  be  communicated  to  God ;  a  con 
sciously  unpious  prayer  is  blasphemy.  Prayer  is  absolutely 
conditioned  on  a  believing  recognition  of  the  divine  omnis 
cience  ;  it  is  not,  therefore,  so  much  a  means  of  making  our 
thoughts  known  to  God, — for  God  knows  our  thoughts  from 
afar,  and  of  what  we  have  need  before  we  ask  therefor, — as 
rather  an  expression  of  our  belief  that  God  knows,  and  our 
joyful  willingness  that  he  should  know  thereof.  A  prayer 
that  should  spring  from  the  thought  that  God  himself  needed 
it  in  order  to  know  our  inward  state,  would  be  per  se  impious 
and  in  self-contradiction ;  but  every  thought  and  every  act 
that  we  are  not  willing  that  God  should  know,  and  that  we 
would  hide  from  him,  is  impious,  and  the  degree  of  our  piety 
is  measured  by  the  degree  in  which  we  have  the  desire  that 
all  our  acts  and  thoughts  should  be  known  of  God.  The  in 
termission  of  prayer  docs  not  shut  out  our  inner  life  from  the 
divine  knowledge,  it  simply  shuts  out  the  divine  blessing  from 
us.  Prayer  reveals  not  our  being  to  the  divine  knowledge, 
but  it  reveals  the  divine  all-knowing  presence  to  us, — brings 
not  God  down  to  us,  but  elevates  us  to  God ;  it  is  for  us  the 
means  of  uniting  ourselves  truly  with  God,  inasmuch  as 
thereby  not  only  is  God,  as  the  Omnipresent  One,  with  «s,  but 
also  we,  by  a  religiously-moral  act  of  will,  are  with  God ;  and 


§  115.]  PURE   ETHICS.  221 

only  when  God  is  himself  with  us,  not  merely  naturally  and 
without  our  desire,  but  upon  our  express  prayer  and  seeking 
therefor,  are  we  in  real  saving  life-communion  with  him. 
Without  prayer  there  can  be  only  a  natural,  but  not  a  moral 
and  spiritual  communion  with  God ;  and  this  merely  natural 
communion  is,  on  the  supposition  that  it  rises  no  higher,  in 
antagonism  to  the  essence  of  a  moral  creature,  and  hence  leads 
to  the  casting  off  of  man  by  God.  For  him  who  cannot  pray, 
God's  presence  is  judicial  and  condemnatory.  As  in  prayer 
man  exalts  himself  to  the  highest  object  of  the  moral  activity, 
so  is  prayer  also  the  highest  moral  act ;  and  all  other  moral 
action  receives  its  moral  worth  solely  from  its  relation  to  this, 
— solely  as  morally  consecrated  by  prayer. 

In  prayer,  man  gives  utterance  to  his  highest  moral  privi 
leges  and  to  his  free  personality,  inasmuch  as  thereby,  with 
full  and  joyful  freedom,  he  wills,  recognizes  and  heightens 
that  which  already  existed  without  prayer,  though  indeed 
only  in  an  immediate,  natural  ante-moral  manner,  but  which 
could  not  so  remain  without  turning  into  antagonism  and 
unblessedness,  namely,  the  divine  omnipresent  domination. 
Only  to  those  who  desire  it  is  God's  presence  a  blessing, 
and  only  by  those  who  love  is  the  loving  communion 
of  God  experienced ;  ' '  draw  nigh  to  God,  and  he  will 
draw  nigh  to  you "  [James  iv,  8 ;  comp.  Psa.  cxlv,  18, 
19].  It  is  the  sublime  significancy  of  prayer  that  it  brings 
into  prominence  man's  great  and  high  destination,  that  it 
brings  to  expression  his  free  personal  relation  to  God,  that  it 
heightens  man's  consciousness  of  his  true  moral  nature  in  rela 
tion  to  God  ;  and  as  all  morality  depends  on  our  relation  to 
God,  prayer  is,  in  fact,  the  very  life-blood  of  morality.  The 
true  freedom,  and  hence  also  the  true  morality  of  man,  mani 
fests  itself  not  in  his  arbitrarily  choosing  that  which  is  fleet 
ing  or  baseless,  but  in  the  fact  that  with  conscious  free-will 
and  glad  assent  he  recognizes  and  confirms  that  which  lies 
in  the  holy  constitution  of  the  world  itself.  To  the  limited 
natural  understanding,  prayer  seems  useless  and  therefore  irra 
tional  ;  for  this  understanding  is  not  capable  of  comprehend 
ing  the  spiritual.  It  is  true,  God  causes  his  sun  to  rise  upon 
the  good  and  the  evil,  gives  rain  to  the  just  and  the  unjust, 
furnishes  food  to  man  and  beast, — in  a  word,  He  "gives  to  all 


222  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  115. 

men  their  daily  bread  "  even  without  prayer;  but  the  signifi- 
cancy  of  such  prayer  is  the  fact  of  our  recognizing  Him  as  the 
Giver  of  all,  of  our  receiving  his  gifts  with  thankfulness. 
That  God's  presence  and  gifts  be  not  only  about  us  but  also 
for  us,  that  they  become  a  blessing  to  us,  a  bond  of  love 
between  God  and  us,  a  living  fountain  of  godly-minded- 
ness, — that  they  be  not  foreign  to  us,  not  in  antagonism  to 
us,  but  in  fact  our  own  and  in  harmony  writh  us, — that  God's 
being  in  us  be  also  our  being  in  God, — all  this  is  the  fruit  of 
prayer. 

Prayer  is  so  intimately  connected  with  the  morally-religious 
life  that  it  appears,  under  some  form,  even  among  those  na 
tions  where,  because  of  the  relative  ignoring  of  the  person 
ality  of  God,  it  has  almost  lost  all  shadow  of  meaning,  as,  for 
example,  in  India.  Greek  and  Roman  philosophers  often  in 
troduce  their  disquisitions  with  prayers  (Socrates,  Plato) ;  the 
Romans  prayed  on  occasion  of  all  important  state-events,  on 
the  election  of  magistrates,  the  enactment  of  laws,  etc.  Of 
course  in  heathen  prayer  there  could  never  exist  the  proper 
earnestness,  inasmuch  as  the  idea  of  God  was  always  imper 
fect  ;  no  heathen  could  ever  pray  as  could  a  pious  Israelite. 
The  first  real  opposing  of  prayer,  if  we  except  the  frivolous 
Epicureans,  was  on  the  part  of  Maximus  of  Tyre,  a  Platonist 
of  the  second  century  after  Christ;  it  was  also  opposed  by 
Rousseau,  though  for  very  superficial  reasons  (because  the 
order  of  the  universe  could  not  be  changed  by  individual 
wishes),  and,  with  astonishing  lack  of  insight  by  Kant,  who 
even  finds  in  the  Lord's  Prayer,  as  given  by  Christ,  a  very 
clear  suggestion  to  substitute  in  the  place  of  all  prayer  simply 
a  determination  to  lead  a  good  life  (Rclig.  innerh.,  etc.,  1794, 
p.  302).  In  Pantheism  the  rejection  of  prayer  as  absurd,  is  a 
matter  of  course. — The  Scriptures  present  prayer  as  one  of  the 
most  essential  moral  requirements  [Psa.  cxlv,  18,  19;  Matt, 
vii,  7 ;  Mark  xi,  24 ;  James  i,  5  sgq.  ;  1  Tim.  ii,  1-3 ;  Eph. 
vi,  18].  The  injunction  to  pray  without  ceasing  [Luke  xviii, 
1-7;  1  Thess.  v,  17;  Rom.  xii,  12;  Col.  iv,  2;  1  Tim.  ii,  8; 
comp.  Psa.  Ixiii,  7]  implies  the  constant  aspiring  of  our  heart 
to  God  as  to  Him  whose  will  alone  is  our  law,  and  who  gives 
his  blessing  to  whatever  is  done  in  his  name. — Where  sin  is 
not  yet  dominant,  any  other  than  a  devotional  prayer  is  incon- 


§116.]  PURE   ETHICS.  223 

ceivable.  Devotion  in  prayer  is  not  merely  the  absence  of 
distraction,  but  it  is  the  praying  out  of  a  true,  earnest  and 
upright  heart-disposition.  Devotion  cannot  be  required  as  a 
special  duty,  for  it  is  necessarily  included  in  the  very  idea  of 
prayer;  the  Scriptures  simply  allude  to  the  earnestness  of 
prayer,  and  to  the  liability  of  self-deception  in  well-meant 
prayer  [Isa.  xxix,  13;  Psa.  cxlv,  18;  Matt,  xv,  8;  vi,  5-7; 
James  v,  16]. 

It  is  not  as  a  merely  moral,  but  as  a  religious,  activity  that 
prayer  leads  to  communion,  for  religion  is  essentially  socializing, 
not  directly,  however,  but  in  virtue  of  the  communion  which  it 
establishes  with  God.  Mere  individual  prayer  has  its  proper 
justification  as  bearing  on  the  personal  relation  to  God  ;  it  is 
in  fact  the  primary  and  most  obvious  form  [Matt,  vi,  6] ;  but 
prayer  attains  to  its  highest,  though  never  exclusive,  character 
as  the  single-hearted  prayer  of  the  believing  communion  or 
church-society.  And  this  not  simply  because  such  prayer 
hightens  the  feeling  of  the  unitedness  of  the  faithful,  but  be 
cause,  in  virtue  of  the  throwing  off  of  personal  isolation  and 
of  its  flowing  out  of  the  holy  spirit  which  pervades  the 
society,  it  has  a  guarantee  of  greater  purity,  and  consequently 
the  promise  of  special  blessing  [Matt,  xviii,  20 ;  Acts  ii,  42 ; 
Eph.  v,  19;  Col.  iii,  16]. — Christ  himself  gives  the  moral  pat 
tern  of  prayer ;  he  prayed  out  of  the  full  consciousness  of  life- 
communion  with  God,  and  consequently  with  full  confidence 
of  being  answered  [Heb.  v,  7] ;  he  prayed  often  in  solitude , 
[Matt,  xiv,  23 ;  xxvi,  36, 42 ;  Mark  vi,  32 ;  Luke  vi,  12  ;  ix,  28], 
and  often  in  the  presence  of  others  [Matt,  xxvi,  39;  John 
xi,  41  sqq.],  and  in  communion  with  his  disciples  [John 
xvii,  1  sqq.]. 

SECTION  CXVI. 

All  prayer  is  primarily,  either  expressly  or  in 
virtue  of  its  necessary  presuppositions,  a  confession, 
a  recognition  of  God  as  the  unconditional  Lord,  and 
as  the  all-knowing,  all  powerful  and  all-loving  Father. 
In  as  far  as  in  it  we  are  always  conscious  of  ourselves 
as  loved  by  God,  prayer  is  at  the  same  time  also 
thanksgiving.  In  so  far  as  in  prayer  we  have  respect 


224  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  116. 

not  only  to  the  past  and  present,  but  also  to  the  goal 
of  moral  effort,  the  realization  of  which  we  regard  as 
not  in  our  own  power  independently  of  God,  nor  yet 
in  an  unfree  nature-necessity,  but  in  the  will  of  God 
as  co-operating  with  us,  prayer  becomes  petition — the 
climax  of  the  inner  religiously-moral  life,  wherein 
the  true  filial  relation  of  man  to  God  finds  its  ex 
pression  ;  and  as  the  moral  end  is  of  a  rational,  and 
hence  not  merely  individual,  character,  consequently 
the  petition  is  essentially  also  intercession — the  highest 
religious  expression  of  our  love  to  man.  As  only  the 
all-embracing  wisdom  of  God  is  capable  of  fully  seeing 
the  appropriateness  of  earthly  things  and  relations  to 
the  attainment  of  the  highest  good,  hence  the  petition 
for  earthly  goods,  though  per  se  entirely  legitimate, 
can  never  be  more  than  of  a  humbly  conditional 
character ;  and  there  is  no  petition  other  than  that 
for  the  per  se  unquestionably  eternal  good,  that  has 
no  other  condition  than  the  willing,  believing  tfbe- 
dience  of  the  subject.  The  promise  of  answering  is 
based  on  the  condition  of  believing  and  of  humble 
confidence. 

Prayer  is  per  se  a  recognition  of  God, — it  is  adoration  and 
confession  both  to  God  as  the  all-ruling  One,  and  also  before 
bod  as  the  all-knowing  and  holy  One.  In  this  recognizing 
confession  itself,  there  is  involved  a  thanksgiving,  which 
consequently  is  included,  though  it  may  be  but  implicitly,  in 
every  prayer;  in  the  Lord's  Prayer  it  lies  in  the  very  address. 
All  thanksgiving  [1  Sam.  ii  ;  Psa.  cvi,  1  ;  Rom.  xv,  6 ; 
1  Tim.  iv,  4,  5;  Phil,  iv,  6;  Col.  iii,  17;  iv,  2]  is  at  the  same 
time  a  petition  for  the  bestowal  of  the  good  for  which  it 
is  offered  ;  and  the  petition  is,  in  virtue  of  the  soul-uniting 
filial  relation  to  God,  necessarily  also  intercession  for  others 
and  for  the  whole  kingdom  of  God  [Matt,  vi,  10;  John 
xvii,  9  gyq.;  Eph  i,  16;  vi,  18;  1  Tim.  ii,  1-3;  Col.  i,  9; 


§  116.]  PURE   ETHICS.  225 

iv,  3;  Phil,  i,  4;  James  v,  16;  Heb.  xiii,  18].  So  long  as 
prayer  remains  of  a  merely  individual  character,  it  cornea 
short  of  true  prayer, — rests  not  yet  on  a  consciousness  of  the 
filial  relation  to  God,  for  this  consciousness  is  inconsistent 
with  self-seeking  exclusiveness ;  the  children  of  God  have 
their  home  only  in  the  kingdom  of  God. 

Prayer  as  petition  is  the  profoundest  enigma  for  the-merely 
wordly  finitely-occupied  understanding  ;  for  the  religious 
heart,  however,  it  is  the  beginning  and  the  center  of  the  spirit 
ual  life.  He  who  cannot  offer  petitions  to  God  i§  not  of  God. 
All  intellectual  doubts  as  to  the  nature  and  efficacy  of  peti 
tioning  prayer,  have  as  their  back-ground  a  doubt  of  the  per 
sonality  of  God,  although  they  may  assume  to  be  a  vindication 
of  the  eternal  order  of  the  world.  A  God  who  cannot  answer 
petitions  is  not  a  personal  spirit,  but  only  an  unconscious 
nature-force.  In  the  believin  r  petition  the  Scriptures  promise 
answers  [Psa.  1,  15  ;  x,  17 ;  xxii,  4,  5 ;  xxxiv,  15  ;  Ixii,  1  sqq.  ; 
Ixv,  2;  xciv,  9;  cii,  17;  cxlv,  18,  19;  Prov.  xv,  8;  Isa.  Ixv, 
24 ;  Matt,  vii,  7  ;  xviii,  19 ;  xxi,  22 ;  John  ix,  31 ;  xvi,  23,  24 ; 
1  John  iii,  22;  v,  14;  James  i,  5 ;  iv,  8;  v,  13-18;  1  Pet. 
iii,  12] ;  to  the  impious  and  foolish  petition  they  refuse  it 
[Job  xxvii,  9 ;  xxxv,  13 ;  Psa.  Ixvi,  18 ;  Prov.  xv,  8,  29 ;  xxviii,  9 ; 
Isa.  i,  15 ;  John  ix,  31 ;  James  iv,  3,  and  others] ;  and  confi 
dent  faith  in  an  answer  is  itself  the  condition  of  the  answer 
[Mark  xi,  24 ;  James  i,  6,  7],  As  the  fuller  development  of  the 
subject  belongs  to  dogmatics,  we  here  subjoin  but  a  few  gen 
eral  observations.  The  answering  of  prayer  is  not  uncondi 
tional  ;  it  is  conditioned,  on  the  one  hand,  on  the  loving 
wisdom  of  God,  which  is  higher  than  that  of  man  [Eph. 
iii,  20],  and,  on  the  other,  on  the  prayer-spirit  of  him  who 
prays.  And  the  answer  is  not  a  merely  seeming  one,  so  that 
prayer  would  be  superfluous,  but  .the  answer  is  given  on  the 
basis  and  in  virtue  of  the  prayer  [Luke  xi,  5-13;  xviii, 
1  sqq., — the  lesson  of  which  is,  that  if  earnest  prayer  is  effect 
ual  even  with  unloving  men,  how  much  more  is  it  so  with  the 
all-loving  One  who  gladly  hears  such  petitions;  Gen.  xviii, 
^  sqq.;  Exod.  xxxii,  9  sqq.;  Num.  xiv,  13  sqq.,  20;  xvi, 
20  sqq.;  Isa.  xxxviii].  Prayer  does  not  change  the  eternal 
counsel  of  God ;  this  counsel  is  itself  not  unconditional,  but  it 
is  determined  by  the  all-knowing  One  in  view  of  the  free  con- 

VOL.  11—16 


226  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  116. 

duct  of  his  .creatures;  and,  consequently,  one  element  of  it  is, 
that  prayer  is  eternally  destined  to  be  answered.  Every  pious 
prayer  is  answered,  although  only  in  the  manner  most  whole 
some  to  him  who  offers  it,  and  hence  not  always  in  the  special 
manner  in  which  the  answer  is  expected  [2  Cor.  xii,  8,  9.  ]  If 
man  deceives  himself  as  to  the  sought  good,  still  he  receives 
the  good, — not,  however,  the  false  one  which  he  had  in  mind, 
but  the  true  one  which  he  had  in  heart.  Hence  no  believing 
prayer,  in  so  far  as  it  relates  to  earthly  goods,  can  be  or 
should  be  m<5re  than  a  conditional  petition,  and  the  manner 
of  the  fulfillment  must  be  submitted  to  the  wisdom  of  God. 
If  even  Christ  prays  in  this  conditional  manner  to  the  Father 
[Matt,  xxvi,  39,  42 ;  Luke  xxii,  42],  by  how  much  more  should 
man  so  pray,  whose  knowledge  is  so  limited ;  true  faith  is  in 
fact  a  confidence  that  God  knows  best  what  serves  for  our 
peace,  and  brings  it  about ;  childlikeness  and  humble  confi 
dence  give  power  and  truth  to  prayer  [Rom.  viii,  15 ;  Gal. 
iv,  6].  Under  this  condition,  prayer  for  particular  earthly 
goods  is  not  only  allowed  to  man,  but  is  also  willed  by  God 
and  with  promise  of  answering  [Matt,  vi,  11 ;  vii,  7  sqq.  ;  Phil, 
iv,  5,  6;  Eph.  vi,  18;  James  v,  14  sqq.};  and  the  confidence 
of  obtaining  the  object  sought,  even  in  such  special  petitions 
rises  to  confident  assurance  wherever  the  prayer  goes  forth 
from  a  complete  life-communion  with  God,  and  in  the  power 
of  the  Holy  Ghost, — wherever  it  is  prayer  "  in  spirit  and  in 
truth  "  [John  iv,  24  ;  Rom.  viii,  26,  27  :  Gal.  iv,  6  ;  Eph.  vi,  18; 
comp.  John  xiv,  13;  xvi,  23J;  for,  the  more  complete  the 
union  of  the  pious  heart  with  God,  so  much  the  more  does  it 
partake  of  the  illuminating  power  of  God,  and  God's  knowl 
edge  of  the  future  begets  in  him  who  partakes  of  God's 
Spirit  a  presentiment  of  the  divine  counsel  in  regard  to  him; 
and  the  presentiment  rises  to  a  prayerful  longing,  an  unshaken 
faith ;  and  the  true  petition  to  a  prophecy.  The  fulfillment  of 
the  petition  is  felt  by  anticipation  in  the  prayer  itself;  he 
who  truly  prays  is  a  rjrophet;  and  God  is  the  fulfiller  of  the 
prophecy,  because  he  is  the  author  of  the  counsel.  Here  also 
Christ  himself  furnishes  the  pattern:  "Father,  I  thank  thee 
that  thou  hast  heard  me,"  etc.  [John  xi,  41];  his  prayer  re 
lated  to  what  he  had  already  prophetically  beholden  and  pre 
dicted  [verses  11,  23],  The  primary  and  most  essential 


§  117.  PURE   ETHICS.  227 

element  of  true  prayer  is,  of  course,  the  petition  for  the  filial 
relation  to  God  and  for  the  coming  of  the  kingdom  of  God 
[Matt,  vi,  10,  12;  John  xvii,  15;  Luke  xi,  13].  Man  should 
beware,  however,  of  sinning  in  prayer  itself;  but  by  self- 
seeking  narrowness  he  does  this ;  to  pray  in  the  spirit  of  God, 
is  to  pray  for  the  kingdom  of  God.  Model  prayers  are  the 
Lord's  Prayer  and  the  high-priestly  prayer  of  Christ. 

As  God's  eternal  decree  to  answer  prayer  is  conditioned  on 
the  actuality  of  the  prayer,  hence  prayer  is  not  simply  moral 
appropriation,  but  also,  though  not  in  a  direct  and  strict 
sense,  moral  forming,  seeing  that,  though  indeed  not  God 
himself,  yet  in  fact  the  particular  temporal  manifestation  of 
his  world-government,  is  conditioned  on  prayer.  God's 
essence  is  indeed  not  subject  to  change ;  his  doing  and  acting 
in  the  world,  however,  are,  in  virtue  of  his  righteous  love 
conditioned  on  the  free  conduct  of  his  rational  creatures,  and 
hence  also  on  prayer.  The  real  forming,  however,  which  is 
directly  connected  with  prayer  relates  to  the  personal  re 
ligiously-moral  being  of  the  subject.  The  blessing  efficacy  of 
prayer  beams  back  from  God  upon  the  offerer,  namely,  in  that 
in  virtue  of  the  prayer  not  only  his  being  in  God  comes  more 
vividly  to  his  consciousness,  and  has  a  more  efficacious  in 
fluence,  but  also  God's  being  in  him  comes  to  a  higher  reality. 
Faith  in  prayer  and  in  the  answering  of  prayer,  heighten  the 
divine  life  of  the  children  of  God. 


SECTION  CXVII. 

2.  The  negating  and  rather  virtual  phase  of  the 
service  of  God,  is  the  actual  or  symbolical  manifesting 
of  the  real  or  conditional  vanity  of  earthly  things  and 
relations,  as  contrasted  with  God  or  with  the  God- 
loving,  pious  state  of  the  heart,  namely,  in  sacrifice, 
the  essence  of  which  is  self-denial  or  renunciation. 
In  the  unfallen  state  of  man  sacrifice  consists  essen 
tially  simply  in  a  free  giving-up  of  that  which  is 
naturally  pleasurable,  out  of  regard  to  the  divine  will 
and  for  the  sake  of  the  higher  good,  the  moral  end ; 


228  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§H7- 

hence  it  consists  in  the  subordinating  and  giving  up 
of  earthly  desire.  The  appropriating  of  the  divine 
requires  the  rejection  of  all  that  is  ungodly,  and 
therein  the  person  accomplishes,  at  the  same  time,  a 
high  moral  culture  of  himself. 

As  contrasted  with  the  highest  good  and  with  God,  every 
thing  finite  appears  as  relatively  empty  and  void ;  the  actual 
manifesting  of  this  nullity,  out  of  love  to  the  divine,  is  sacri 
fice, — a  notion  that  is  fundamental  to  all  religions,  and  that 
constitutes  the  focal  point  of  all  religious  life,  and  which  is 
still  recognizable  even  in  the  most  utter  perversions  of  the 
truth.*  There  is  no  love  without  sacrifice;  the  higher  the 
love,  so  much  the  higher  the  readiness  to  sacrifice  for  the  sake 
of  the  beloved ;  sacrifice  is  the  test  of  love ;  maternal  love 
sacrifices  repose  and  enjoyment  for  the  sake  of  the  child ;  this 
is  not  figurative  language, — the  sacrifice  is  real  and  true.  As 
God's  highest  love  expresses  itself  in  the  giving  up  of  his 
Son,  so  man's  love  to  God  is  manifested  in  the  sacrificing  of 
that  to  the  enjoyment  of  which  man  has  in  general  a  right. 
As,  however,  in  the  sinless  state  of  humanity,  there  would 
exist  no  really  untrue  and  vain  object  from  which  man  would 
have  actually  to  turn  away  in  moral  abhorrence,  but  only  a 
merely  relatively  such,  namely,  the  merely  natural  and  transi 
tory  as  in  contradistinction  to  the  spiritual,  hence  in  this  case 
sacrifice  would  not  consist  in  the  destruction  of  an  entity,  but 
in  the  renunciation  of  an  enjoyment,  an  abstaining  from  the 
merely  worldly.  In  the  interest  of  his  spiritual  freedom,  of 
his  moral  growth,  man  is  not  to  give  himself  over  to  nature, 
but  must  by  obedience  renounce  some  degree  of  the  enjoyment 
of  nature  and  of  his  personal  discretion.  He  is  to  sacrifice 
whatever  tempts  him  from  God,  whatever  binds  him  to  the 
merely  natural  or  to  the  non-divine ;  also  of  unfallen  man  it 
was  required  that  he  should  realize  his  spiritual  freedom  by 
the  free  renunciation  of  a  merely  natural  enjoyment.  Christ's 
fasting  in  the  wilderness  was  not  a  part  of  his  atoning  self- 
sacrifice,  and  yet  it  was  a  sacrifice  on  the  part  of  the  Son  of 

*  See  Wuttke's  Gesch.  des  Heident.  I,  pp.  127  sqq.,  268  sqq.t  311  /  //, 
pp.  64,  343  sqq,  547  sqq. 


§  111.]  PURE  ETHICS.  229 

man,  even  as  was  also  required  of  unfallen  man.  In  yielding 
himself  to  enjoyment  without  moral  discrimination,  man  loses 
hold  on  the  spiritual ;  he  must  renounce  in  order  to  be  free. 
In  the  unfallen  state  sacrifice  has  essentially  an  educative  end 
and  a  symbolical  form.  God  certainly  did  not  forbid  man  to 
eat  of  the  designated  tree  because  it  was  a  bad  tree,  for  to  sin 
less  beings  there  could  be  nothing  evil  in  the  entire  circle  of 
God-made  nature ;  but  in  his  educative  wisdom,  God  required 
of  man  a  sacrifice,  for  the  simple  reason  that  no  moral  life  is 
possible  without  self-restraint,  no  religious  life  without  sacri 
fice.  Man  stands  in  the  presence  of  nature  and  God,  both  are 
good ;  but  nature  is  a  created  object  and  may  not  be  placed 
on  an  equal  footing  with  God.  When  man  enjoys  nature  for 
its  own  sake  and  without  reference  to  God,  he  sins ;  for  he 
ought  to  belong,  not  to  nature,  but  to  God.  Hence  he  should 
recognize,  and  manifest  in  moral  acts,  the  truth  that  nature 
per  se  is  not  the  true  being  and  the  true  goal  of  moral  aspira 
tion,  namely,  the  highest  good,  but  only  a  means  to  this  end. 
Hence  his  moral  relation  to  nature  and  to  the  sensuous,  is,  as 
in  contrast  to  his  relation  to  God,  of  a  negative  character. 
This  "no"  in  regard  to  nature,  man  pronounces  morally 
when  he  subordinates  his  relation  to  nature  to  his  higher  rela 
tion  to  God,  when  he  says  to  sensuous  desire:  "Thou  mayest 
not,  shalt  not  absorb  and  dominate  my  thinking  and  willing ; " 
he  must  freely  hold  in.  check  the  merely  sensuous,  for  the 
sake  of  the  spiritual, — must  restrain  himself  from  the  former 
in  order  that  he  may  possess  and  perfect  himself  as  a  moral 
spirit,  and  that  he  may  rise  to  spiritual-mindedness. 

It  is  the  antagonism  of  the  spirit  to  the  flesh  that  lies  at  the 
basis  of  sacrifice ;  in  the  interest  of  the  spiritual,  the  spirit 
sacrifices  the  fleshly.  Also  man  as  normal  and  not  yet  sinful, 
had  to  crucify  his  flesh  with  the  affections  and  lusts  thereof 
[Gal.  v,  24],  although  this  flesh  and  its  desires  were  not  yet 
immoral ;  but  to  have  sought  the  flesh  as  an  end,  as  a  good, 
would  have  been  sinful ;  and  God  put  upon  him  a  requirement 
of  abnegation  in  order  that  he  might  recognize  and  actually 
learn  this  fact, — that  he  might  break  away  from  the  merely 
sensuous,  and  develop  in  himself  the  image  of  God.  Simple 
obedience  to  this  requirement,  without  a  why  or  wherefore, 
was  the  purest  and  best  of  sacrifices.  This  Paradisaical  gerrn 


230  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  117. 

of  all  sacrifice  is,  therefore,  self-denial  in  obedience  to  God,  a 
renouncing  not  a  destroying,  a  giving  up,  out  of  love  to  the 
spirit,  of  that  which  is  dear  to  the  flesh ;  and  this  idea  per 
vades  all  forms  of  sacrifice,  even  the  emphatic  sin-offering; 
only  that  which'is  dear  to  man  can  be  to  him  a  sacrifice ;  and 
because  of  the  simple  fact  that  the  first  man  would  not  bring 
the  light  sacrifice  required  of  him,  it  became  necessary  for 
him  afterward  to  make  severer  ones;  and  from  the  hour  of  the 
fall  and  thenceforth  the  morally-religious  consciousness  of 
humanity  finds  satisfaction  only  in  a  series  of  progressively 
more  violent  and  more  terrible  sacrifices,  culminating  in 
the  offering  of  human  victims,  and  that  too  not  merely 
among  the  rude,  but  even  among  the  most  civilized  of  gen 
tile  nations. 

In  the  idea  of  sacrifice  it  is  always  implied  that  that  which 
the  person  gives  up  is  per  se  good  and  right,  that  primarily  he 
has  a  right  to  its  enjoyment,  but  that  he  gives  it  up  for  the 
sake  of  a  higher  end ;  to  give  up  that  which  is  per  se  bad,  is 
not  to  sacrifice ;  the  offering  that  was  presented  to  Jehovah 
had  to  be  pure  and  spotless ;  and  the  worth  of  the  sacrifice 
rises  with  the  worth  of  the  object  offered.  Thus,  sensuous 
enjoyment  is  per  se  good,  but  it  must  be  restrained  and  limited, 
and  often  refused,  in  order  that  not  it  but  the  rational  spirit 
may  be  the  master.  But  man  has  also  to  bring,  in  the  inter 
est  of  the  moral,  purely  spiritual  sacrifices.  It  was  not  the 
sensuous  per  se  that  was  the  temptation  to  Eve,  but  the  repre 
sentation  made  to  her  that  the  tree  would  render  her  ' '  wise ; " 
it  was  her  duty,  as  it  is  the  duty  of  man  in  general,  to  re 
nounce  the  desire  of  obtaining  from  the  creature  that  wisdom 
which  only  God  can  impart — which  can  be  learned  only  in 
believing  obedience  to  God. 

The  sacrifice  that  was  required  of  unfallen  man  implied  in 
its  renunciation  at  the  same  time,  a  confession,  namely,  to 
God  as  the  highest  good  and  the  highest  love,  and  this 
again  implied  thankfulness  for  the  love  received  in  com 
munion  with  God.  Inasmuch  as  every  good  gift  is  from 
God  hence  the  thank-offering  of  the  believer  can  only  be 
symbolical,  expressive  of  his  readiness  to  give  up  in  the 
interest  of  the  eternal  even  that  which  is  dearest  of  all  to 
him,  in  the  consciousness  that  in  the  communion  with  God 


§117.]  "PURE   ETHICS.  281 

for  whom  it  is  given  up,  the  real  and  true  life  is  in  fact  pre 
served  ;  in  the  presence  of  God  none  is  to  appear  empty  [Exod. 
xxiii,  15;  xxxiv,  20]. 

Sacrifice  appears  in  the  Old  Testament  in  its  more  definite 
form  as  early  as  in  the  case  of  Cain  and  Abel ;  we  find  no 
indication  of  its  express,  institution  by  God ;  and  we  might 
therefore  regard  it  as  an  immediate  and  natural  expression  of 
the  religious  consciousness ;  however,  a  positive  divine  pre 
scription  is  the  more  pro  cable.  It  is  certainly  not  probable  that 
sacrifice  was  first  made  from  a  consciousness  of  guilt;  the 
offerings  of  Cain  and  Abel,  consisting  of  the  products  of  the 
field  and  of  the  flock,  seem  rather  to  be  thank-offerings  than 
sin-offerings ;  Abel's  bloody  offering  is  expressly  designated 
[Gen.  iv,  4]  by  the  word  minchah  (present,  gift)  by  which  are 
subsequently  designated  the  bloodless  thank-offerings  in  con 
tradistinction  to  the  bloody,  and,  for  the  most  part,  atoning 
offerings,  namely,  the  sebachim;  the  offering  of  Noah  appears 
expressly  as  a  thank-offering  [viii,  20]  The  burning  up  of 
the  material  of  the  sacrifice  signifies  the  renunciation  and  the 
eradication  of  the  earthly  desires  of  him  who  sacrifices ;  the 
pure  heavenward-mounting  sacrificial  flame  symbolizes  the 
exaltation  of  the  heart  from  the  earthly  to  the  heavenly, — 
the  union  with  God.  Thus  sacrifice  becomes  a  symbol  of  the 
alliance  of  man  with  God ;  and  in  the  case  of  Noah  and  the 
patriarchs,  a  sign  of  the  Covenant,  and  hence  also  a  sign  of 
the  union  of  the  Israelites  who  escaped  from  Egypt,  into  one 
people  [Exod.  iii,  12].  And,  therefore,  subsequently  in  the 
fully-developed  sacrificial  service  of  a  sinful  people,  the 
essence  of  the  sacrifice  was  in  fact  not  placed  in  the  out 
ward  rite,  but  in  the  submission  of  the  heart,  in  the  renun 
ciation  of  an  earthly  self-seeking  mind,  in  the  complete  giv 
ing  up  of  all  earthly  love  for  God's  sake  [Gen.  xxii,  16] ; 
obedience  is  better  than  [outward]  sacrifice;  God-pleasing 
sacrifices  are  a  broken  spirit  and  a  contrite  heart,  and  "  to  do 
justice  and  judgment  is  more  acceptable  to  the  Lord  than 
sacrifice"  [1  Sara,  xv,  22;  Psa.  xl,  6;  1,  8-15;  li,  16,  17,  18; 
Hos.  vi,  6;  Eccl.  iv,  17;  Prov.  xxi,  3,  27;  Isa.  i,  11;  Jer.  vi, 
20;  comp.  Matt,  ix,  13;  xii,  7;  Mark  xii,  33].  In  the  case  of 
the  very  first  sacrifices  God  warns  man  against  the  error  of 
supposing  that  the  essence  of  the  sacrifice  lies  in  the  outward 


232  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  118. 

act;  Abel's  offering  He  graciously  accepts,  that  of  Cain  He 
disregards.  Sacrifice  is  an  appropriating  of  the  divine,  inas 
much  as  in  the  turning  away  from  the  non-divine  there  is 
necessarily  implied  a  turning  to  the  divine. 


SECTION  CXVHL 

The,  moral  sparing  of  the  divine,  has  direct  refer 
ence  not  to   God  himself,  but  to  the  forms   under 
which  He  is  revealed.     Every  thing  whereby  God 
becomes  for  us  is  sacred  as  distinguished  from  mere 
ly  created  objects  per  se.   .  In  the  unfallen  state  of 
humanity  all  created  objects  are  at  the  same   time 
also  sacred,  namely,  in  so  far  as  they  are  considered  an 
expression  of  the  divine  will ;  and  whatever  is  sacred 
is  in  the  highest  degree  an  object  of  moral  sparing, — 
should   be  treated  as  sacred.     This  sparing  springs 
from  moral  humility, — is  an  express  respecting  of  the 
sacred   in  virtue  of  a   holy  awe,  springing  from   a 
lively  consciousness,  on  the  one  hand,  of  the  divine 
glory  even  in  the  humbler  forms  of  its  manifestation, 
and,  on  the  other,  of  our  own  existence  as  a  limited 
one   and    as    resting   solely  on    divine  grace.     The 
objects  of  this  sacred  awe.  and  hence  of  moral  spar-, 
ing,  are  both   the  immediate,  full    and    actual   self- 
revelations  of  God,  and   also  all   mediating   instru 
mentalities  of  His  revelation  and  communication,  as 
well  as  also  every  thing  that  relates  to  the  reverencing 
of  God  on  the  part  of  man. 

The  distinction  between  the  sacred  and  the  non-sacred  is, 
for  the  unfallen  state,  of  a  merely  conditional  character ;  it 
is  in  fact,  simply  the  same  thing  considered  under  two 
phases;  in  all  things  we  can  behold  both  the  created  and  the 
Creator.  He  who  is  truly  pious  sees  himself  every-where  sur 
rounded  by  the  sacred, — he  prays  to  God  not  merely  in  the 


§  118.]  PURE   ETHICS.  233 

temple  of  Jerusalem,  or  on  Mount  Gerizirn,  but  every-where  in 
spirit  and  in  truth.  Now,  in  so  far  as  objects  that  are 
imbued  with  the  divine  are  temporal  and  finite,  they  are 
capable  of  being  abused  and  desecrated, — hence  the  moral 
duty  of  sparing.  The  direction  of  God  to  Moses  on  occasion 
of  the  revelation  in  the  burning  bush  [Exod.  iii,  5],  suggests 
the  proper  moral  bearing  of  man;  he  must  put  away  from 
himself  all  that  bears  upon  itself  the  character  of  the  com 
mon,  the  unholy,  the  dross  of  earth.  The  duty  of  sparing,  as 
relating  to  the  sacred,  is  not  a  mere .  non-doing,  but,  like 
every  other  form  of  this  duty,  it  is  a  self-restraining  out  of 
regard  to  the  higher  right  of  the  sacred  object;  a  sparing 
from  mere  indifference  would  be  sinful. 

The  objects  of  this  sparing  are:  (1)  The  immediate  per 
sonal  revelations  of  God  himself.  Here  there  is  no  room  for 
a  mere  passive  bearing ;  here  the  mere  non-doing,  the  mere 
not  respecting  the  divine  presence,  is  an  offending  of  God 
himself ;  and  moral  sparing  passes  over  at  once  into  adoring 
reverence ;  here  the  declaration  of  Christ  holds  good :  ' '  He 
that  is  not  for  me  is  against  me;"  the  not-concerning  our 
selves  about  God  is  a  dishonoring  of  God. — (2)  God's  revelation 
and  self-communication  through  his  Word  should  be  recog 
nized  as  absolutely  sacred,  and  distinguished  in  every  respect 
from  whatever  is  merely  human  and  natural ;  it  is  disesteemed 
and  dishonored  by  doubt,  unbelief,  and  disobedience,  and  by 
trifling  or  irreverent  use,  by  ridicule  or  neglect;  the  divine 
Word  as  sacred  is  to  be  treated  entirely  differently  from  the 
merely  human ;  it  calls  for  unconditional  faith  and  reverent 
submission. — (3)  The  name  of  God  [Exod.  iii,  14]  and  other 
symbolical  designations  of  God  must  be  treated  with  sacred 
awe  and  sparing, — may  not  be  associated  with  the  common 
and  thus  subjected  to  irreverent  use,  may  not  be  misused  in 
sport,  or  frivolity,  or  for  deception  [Exod.  xx,  7;  Lev.  xix, 
12;  xxii,  32;  Matt.  vi.  9].  A  name  is  not  a  mere  empty 
sound;  it  is  the  body  of  a  thought;  and  as  the  human  body 
is  not  an  object  of  indifference  for  the  spirit,  and  as  to  dis 
honor  it  is  to  insult  the  spirit,  so  also  is  a  misusing  of  the 
divine  name  a  dishonoring  of  God  himself.  In  the  awe  of  the 
Jews  as  to  the  pronouncing  of  the  name  of  Jehovah,  there 
lay  a  deep  moral  significancy,  though  indeed  this  peculiarity 


234  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  118. 

rendered  also  possible  an  outward  evasion  of  the  command 
itself.     That  the  precept  to  revere  God's  name  appears  as  one 
of  the  chief  commandments  of  the  Mosaic  law,  evinces  its 
high  moral  importance.     Where  there  exists  reverential  love, 
there   the   name  of  the    beloved  will   not  be  desecrated  by 
trifling-ness   and  frivolous   sport.     And   what    is   true   of  the 
name  is  also  true  of  all  symbols  of  God,  as,  for  example,  in 
the  Ancient  Covenant,  of  the  covering  of  the  ark  of  the  Cov 
enant  (the  mercy-seat),  of  the  pillar  of  fire,  etc.     In  a  more 
general  sense  every  form  of  sin  is  a  dishonoring  of  the  name 
and  image  of  God,    inasmuch  as  man   himself  bears  God's 
name  and  image  in  himself,  and  should  therefore  spare  and 
respect  these  in  his  own  person  [comp.  Rom.  ii,  24] ;  and  all 
morality  may  be  summed    up  in  the  keeping  sacred  of  the 
divine  image  in  ourselves, — as  expressed  by  Jehovah:   "Ye 
shall  sanctify  yourselves  and  be  holy,  for  I  am  holy  "  [Lev. 
xi,  44],  or  in  the  words  of  Peter:   "  Sanctify  the  Lord  God  in 
your  hearts"  [1  Pet.  iii,  15]. — (4)  The  human  organs  of  divine 
revelation,  the  prophets  and  the  called  heralds  of  the  divine 
Word  in  general,  have  a  moral  right  to  reverential  sparing, 
though  this  sparing  refers  essentially  not  to  them  as  men, 
but  to  God  in  whose  name  they  speak.     [Psa.  cv,  15 ;  Matt,  x, 
40,  41;  comp.  xi,  49-51;  1  Thes.  v,  12,  13;  Ileb.  xiii,  17] ;  the 
persecuting  and  killing  of  the  prophets  is  frequent ly  spoken 
of  in  Scripture  as  among  the  most  heinous  of  offenses.     Also 
in  a  sinless  development  of   humanity  all   those  would   be 
regarded    in  .the   light   of    prophets   of    God,    who,    having 
attained  to  higher  spiritual  knowledge,  should  bear  witness 
of  divine  truth;  they  would  stand   not  strictly  on  an  equal 
footing  with  those  whom  they  should  .teach  and  train;  and 
their  recognition  as  divine  messengers  would  beget  a  greater 
willingness  to  give  heed  to  them.     Wherever  there  is  a  really 
moral  communion,  there  the  ministers  of  God  are  honored ; 
not  to  respect  them  is  a  sign  of  deep  moral  declension ;  but  the 
deepest  degradation  of  all  is  where  they  themselves  do  not 
respect  their  calling.     No  prophet  of  God  was  ever  without 
moral   self-denial   and    constant    humiliation   before  God, — 
without  the  deeply  felt  consciousness  of  Moses :  "  Who  am  I 
that  I  should  go  unto  Pharaoh,  and  bring  forth  the  children 


§  118.]  PURE   ETHICS.  235 

of  Israel  out  of  Egypt  ? " — but  also  no  prophet  of  God  was 
ever  without  the  sacred  right  to  be  recognized  and  respected 
as  God's  messenger,  provided  only  that  he  be  found  faithful. 
— (5)  All  that  relates  to  the  worshiping  of  God, — the  holy 
seasons,  places,  and  things,  are,  as  sacred,  to  be  distinguished 
from  the  non-sacred,  and  to  be  honored  accordingly,  and  not 
to  be  placed  on  an  equal  footing  with  that  which  serves  only 
temporal,  individual  ends.  The  Sabbath  is  to  be  treated 
quite  otherwise  than  the  day  of  labor ;  it  has  a  right  to  be 
respected,  for  it  is  God's  day,  set  apart  to  his  special  service. 
Its  celebration  by  actual  divine  worship  is  only  one  of  its 
phases,  the  other  is  its  being  sacredly  spared.  Every  thing  is 
to  be  avoided  on  the  Sabbath  which  disturbs  the  devout 
frame  of  the  soul, — attracts  it  back  to  the  merely  earthly  and 
sensuous,  impresses  upon  it  a  mere  every-day  character.  He 
who  does  not  honor  the  day  of  the  Lord,  honors  also  not  the 
Lord  of  the  day.  Holy  places  and  things,  being  consecrated 
to  heavenly  purposes,  should  not  be  profaned  to  worldly 
entertainment  and  to  merely  temporal  uses.  Though  we  do 
not  recognize  any  mystic  power  in  a  special  consecration,  yet 
we  hold  fast  to  the  principle  that  holy  places  and  things 
belong  exclusively  to  the  service  of  the  Lord.  God  himself 
ordained,  in  the  Old  Testament,  particular  sacred  things  and 
a  special  consecration  of  them  [Exod.  xxv,  sqq.  ;  xxx,  22  sqq.]. 
Even  as  the  "burning  bush"  [Exod.  iii,  5]  and  the  mount  of 
legislation  and  the  holy  of  holies  in  the  temple  were  sepa 
rated  from  all  that  was  not  sacred,  so  also  is  it  with  every 
place  that  is  dedicated  to  the  holy  One  [Lev.  x^x,  30].  The 
significancy  of  this  setting  apart,  and  the  importance  of 
this  respecting  of  the  sacred,  increase  with  the  actuality 
of  sin. 

Note.  God  cannot  of  course  be  an  object  of  moral  forming 
in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word.  Though  prayer  is  in  fact  a 
moral  influencing  of  God,  inasmuch  as  it  finds  hearing,  still 
no  change  is  thereby  wrought  in  God,  and  that  which  is  real 
ized  by  the  efficacy  of  prayer  is  not  so  much  in  God  as  in  us 
and  in  the  world.  But  in  a  remote  sense  we  may  speak  of  a 
forming  of  the  divine,  namely,  in  so  far  as  God  is  expressed 
in  sacred  symbols  and  in  sacred  art,  and  in  so  far  as,  by  our 
witnessings  for  God,  the  knowledge  and  love  of  God  are  im- 


236  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  119. 

planted  in  the  souls  of  men ;  all  this,  however,  is  in  reality 
simply  a  forming  of  the  finite  and  the  human  into  an  image 
of  God,  and  not  a 'forming  of  God  himself. 


II.    THE   MOEAL   ACTIVITY,    IN  RELATION   TO   THE 
MORAL  PERSON  HIMSELF. 

SECTION   CXIX. 

(a)  The  duty  of  moral  sparing  is  here  the  preserv 
ing  of  one's  own  existence  and  of  its  normal  pecul 
iarity  and  development,  as  prompted  by  a  conscious 
ness  of  the  divine  will,  and  hence  also  the  warding 
off  of  all  therewith-conflicting  and  disturbing  or 
destroying  influences  on  the  part  of  nature  or  of  the 
spiritual  world.  To  this  end  it  is  necessary  that  in 
all  things  the  true  relation  of  the  body,  as  a  serving 
power,  to  the  rational  spirit,  as  the  dominating  power, 
be  preserved,  and  that  the  image  of  God,  which 
though  originally  inherent  in  man.  is  yet  in  need  of 
fuller  development,  be  preserved  pure  even  in  its 
corporeally-symbolical  manifestation. 

The  moral  sparing  of  one's  self  is  the  higher  moral  applica 
tion  of  a  law*  that  pervades  the  entire  totality  of  being.  That 
which  is  cohesion  in  a  nature-body,  and  the  law  of  gravita 
tion  in  the  natural  world  in  general,  and  the  instinct  of  self- 
defense  and  of  self-preservation  in  the  animal  world,  becomes 
with  man  a  moral  duty.  When  man  seeks  to  preserve  him 
self,  to  ward  off  injury  and  death,  out  of  mere  natural  instinct, 
his  action  is  not  yet  moral ;  it  becomes  moral  only  when  it 
springs  from  a  consciousness  that  it  is  God's  will, — that  God 
has  pleasure  in  our  existence  as  his  own  creative  work,  that 
He  has  a  purpose  in  us  which  we  are  morally  to  fulfill.  Of  a 
duty  of  self-destruction  there  can  never  be  any  possibility; 
and  for  a  duty  of  entire  self-sacrifice,  of  the  giving  up  of  life 
for  the  sake  of  a  higher  end,  there  is,  in  a  state  of  sm- 


§  120.]  PURE   ETHICS.  237 

lessness,  also  no  possibility ;  otherwise  the  divine  government 
would  be  in  anarchy.  God  who  gave  existence  to  man  wills 
also  its  preservation, — has  willed  it  as  a  moral  end,  and  not 
simply  as  a  means  to  an  end.  Death  is  simply  the  wages  of 
sin,  and  not  a  condition  of  virtue,  save  alone  where  on  ac 
count  of  sin  there  is  need  of  a  sacrifice. 

In  a  sinless  state  the  duty  of  self-sparing  is  of  easy  fulfill 
ment,  partly  for  the  reason  that  it  corresponds  to  a  natural 
law  immanent  in  all  living  creatures,  and  partly  because  dis 
turbing  influences  are  conceivable  only  where  they  are  occa 
sioned  by  the  fault  of  man  himself, — for  example,  when  he 
presumptuously  exposes  himself  to  such  natural  influences  as 
he  is  not  yet  able  to  resist, — which  is  in  fact  possible  seeing 
that,  also  for  the  unf alien  state,  the  complete  mastery  over 
nature  is  presented  as  a  condition  yet  to  be  attained  to  by 
moral  effort.  Also  from  the  influence  of  spiritual  beings  an 
injuring  of  the  moral  person  is  possible,  so  long  as  the  rational 
creature  has  not  as  yet  attained  to  its  ultimate  perfection,  so 
that  here  also  there  is  place  for  the  duty  of  watchfulness,  in 
order  that  the  diverse  personalities  that  are  as  yet  in  process 
of  development  may  not  act  hinderingly  upon  each  other. 
And  this  duty  of  sparing  watchfulness  is  still  more  increased 
when  the  moral  person  stands  no  longer  in  the  presence  of 
simply  sin-free  beings,  but  is  assaulted  by  spiritual  temptation, 
as  in  the  case  of  Adam  and  Eve ;  here  the  duty  of  self-pre 
serving  sparing  assumes  at  once  the  form  of  a  positive  ward 
ing  off. — In  the  Scriptures  the  duty  of  sparing  one's  self,  even 
in  relation  to  the  corporeal  life,  is  presented  as  per  se  strictly 
valid;  "  no  man  ever  yet  hated  his  own  flesh,  but  nourisheth 
and  cherishetlTit,  even  as  the  Lord  the  church"  [Eph.  v,  29]. 
Man  is  also  to  exercise  this  duty  of  sparing  in  view  of  his  own 
possible  sinning ;  in  protecting  his  moral  innocence,  man  pro 
tects  also  the  image  of  God  as  created  in  him. 

SECTION  CXX. 

(J)  Moral  appropriating  is,  as  regards  the  moral 
person  himself,  directly  at  the  same  time  also  a  moral 
/"arming  of  the  person  into  a  progressively  more  per 
fect  expression  of  the  moral  idea, — into  a  personally- 


238  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  120. 

peculiar  realization  of  the  moral  end ;  and  in  pro 
portion  as  the  moral  person  appropriates  to  itself  its 
own  self,  puts  itself  into  possession  of  itself,  it  accom 
plishes  upon  itself  also  a  moral  forming. 

(1)  Not  the  body  is  to  appropriate  to  itself  the 
spirit,  but  the  spirit  is  progressively  more  and  more 
to  appropriate  to  itself  the  body,  and  to  form  it,  and 
thereby  also  to  form  itself;  hence  the  spirit  alone  is 
the  appropriating  factor,  and  the  body  is  simply  to 
be  appropriated  and  formed.  Even  as  nature  stands 
to  God  in  a  twofold  relation,  namely,  in  that,  on  the 
one  hand,  God  accomplishes  his  will  in  it,  makes  it 
good,  and,  on  the  other,  reveals  himself  through  it, 
makes  it  into  his  image,  into  an  object  of  beauty,  so 
also  has  the  body  in  relation  to  the  spirit  the  twofold 
destination  of  being  its  organ  and  its  image  •  the 
former  it  becomes  essentially  by  particular  forming, 
the  latter  by  general  forming  (§§  109,  110). 

(a)  The  body  is  formed  and  appropriated  to  itself 
by  the  spirit  as  its  true  absolutely  subservient  organ, 
in  that  (1)  it  is  strengthened  and  rendered  apt  in 
accomplishing  every  service  for  the  rational  will, 
through  the  mediating  and  carrying  out  of  all  appro 
priating  and  forming  action  of  the  rational  spirit  as 
bearing  upon  the  external  world  ;  (2)  in  that,  in  its 
sensuous  impulses,  it  is  held  under  the  discipline  of 
the  spirit,  and  is  never  allowed  to  have  an  independ 
ent  fight  for  itself;  in  both  these  respects  realizes 
itself  the  complete  domination  of  the  spirit  over  the 
body. 

It  is  characteristic  of  the  true  moral  nature  of  man,  that  he 
is  capable,  not  merely,  as  is  the  case  with  the  brute,  of  appro 
priating  and  forming  external  objects,  but  also  himself.  The 
brute  is  formed  by  nature,  not  by  itself,  and  it  appropriates 


§  120.]  PURE   ETHICS.  239 

to  itself  only  nature,  but  not  itself;  but  man  in  his  first- 
given  condition  does  not  as  yet  really  have  himself,  but  must 
first  learn  to  possess  himself, — must  attain  to  moral  ownership 
of  .himself. 

Man  virtualizes  his  god-likeness  primarily  in  this,  that  he 
glorifies  God  even  in  his  body  as  the  temple  of  ihe  Holy 
Ghost  [1  Cor.  vi,  19,  20],  and  that  he  presents  this  body  to 
God  as  a  living,  holy,  and  well-pleasing  sacrifice  [Rom.  xii,  1.] 
The  preliminary  manifold  dependence  of  the  spirit  on  the 
body,  and  through  the  body  also  on  external  nature,  is  to  be 
overcome  and  changed  into  spiritual  freedom ;  the  spirit  is 
itself  to  make  the  body  truly  its  own  body,  to  appropriate  it  to 
itself  as  a  moral  possession,  to  form  it  into  the  perfect  organ 
of  the  spirit, — in  a  certain  sense,  to  create  it  spiritually.  The 
original  foreignness  of  the  body  to  the  spirit  is  to  be  overcome ; 
its  as  yet  partially-actual  independence  is  to  be  broken ;  the 
body  is  to  be  thoroughly  permeated  by  the  spirit,  and  all  that 
is  merely  objective'  and  unfree  in  it,  to  be  done  away  with. 
The  dominion  of  the  spirit  over  nature,  which  is  set  before  it 
as  a  moral  goal,  is  to  realize  itself  first  on  its  own  nature, 
that  is,  on  the  body.  That  this  is  a  moral  task  is  plainly  in 
dicated  by  nature  itself.  The  brute  is  much  earlier  self- 
supporting  and  mature  than  man,  and  needs  no  training  in 
order  to  attain  to  its  greatest  skill;  all  the  skill  that  man 
attains  to  he  has  to  get  by  learning,  to  acquire  by  moral 
effort ;  and  all  learning  is  an  appropriating  through  conscious 
ness;  man  must  in  some  manner  first  comprehend  his  body, 
before  he  can  really  form  it  and  take  it  under  his  control ;  he 
who  is  spiritually  dull  usually  remains  also  physically  clumsy  ; 
man  as  coming  from  the  hands  of  nature  is  the  most  helpless 
and  most  unskillful  of  creatures ;  all  that  he  ever  becomes  is 
by  the  spirit, — by  free  moral  activity;  that  his  nascent  life  is 
much  more  helpless  than  that  of  any  of  the  animals,  is  simply 
an  incident  of  his  high  moral  dignity.  That  which  he  has  from 
nature  is  indeed  good,  but  if  it  remains  as  mere  unspiritual- 
ized,  undominated  nature,  then  it  becomes  for  him  evil, — be 
comes  something  of  which  he  is  to  be  asTwtmed.  This  render 
ing  the  body  skillful  is  a  personally-particular  forming — a 
working  of  the  spirit  upon  the  body  ;  thereby  the  spirit  forms 
the  body  into  its  own  true  possession ;  it  aspires  to  have  it 


240  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  120. 

for  itself,  to  have  it  entirely  in  its  control.  Herein  consists 
also  the  true  particular  appropriating,  the  enjoying,  of  the 
body ;  man  enjoys  it  when  he  has  it  fully  in  his  power.  This 
is  the  secret  of  the  rich  enjoyment  of  young  persons,  when, 
in  free  corporeal  movement,  in  skillful  playing,  in  skating,  in 
rhythmical  muscular  action,  etc.,  they  feel  themselves  mas 
ters  over  their  bodies ;  it  is  the  consciousness  of  freedom, 
of  acquired  mastery;  for,  all  consciousness  of  mastery  is  a 
feeling  of  happiness,  and  that,  too,  a  per  se  legitimate  one. 

Man  is  to  form  and  appropriate  to  himself  his  body  in  two 
respects ;  for  as  a  spirit  he  stands  to  the  outer  world  in  the 
double  relation  of  receiving  and  of  influencing, — through  the 
senses  and  through  the  organs  of  motion.  The  cultivation 
of  the  senses  is  more  an  appropriating  than  a  real  forming;  the 
senses  must  first  be  brought  under  the  control  of  the  spirit ; 
the  seaman  and  the  huntsman  have  not  always  a  really  sharper 
natural  eye  than  others,  but  their  seeing  is  more  skilled, — 
they  see  many  objects  from  which  others  may  indeed  receive 
exactly  the  same  light-impressions,  but  yet  not  actually  per 
ceive  them,  for  the  reason  that  they  overlook  them;  seeing  is 
an  art,  and  many,  though  with  open  eyes,  see  comparatively 
little.  An  uncultured  person  hears,  in  a  beautiful  piece  of 
music,  little  more  than  confused  sounds,  for  the  reason  that 
he  does  not  know  how  to  hear.  It  is  a  moral  duty  of  man  to 
develop  his  senses  to  perfection,  fully  to  appropriate  them  to 
himself,  for  they  were  given  to  him  by  God  as  channels 
through  which  to  appropriate  to  himself  the  outer  world  ; 
and  it  is  unthankfulness  to  God  for  man  to  be  willing  to  see 
and  hear  little  or  nothing  in  God's  nature, — for  him  to  have 
no  open  eyes  for  the  glory  of  God  as  resplendent  in  crea 
tion,  and  no  ear  for  the  beautiful  harmonies  of  nature  and  art. 
Rudeness  and  unculture  are  sinful  in  every  respect,  and  hence 
also  in  respect  to  the  senses. 

The  appropriating  training  of  the  organs  of  motion  to 
vigorous  skillfulness,  not  merely  as  a  pleasure  but  also  as  a 
duty,  is  brought  about  under  normal  circumstances  not  so 
much  by  calculating  art  as  by  spontaneous  natural  activity ; 
and  it  takes  place  chiefly  during  youth.  While  it  was  an 
error  of  many  former  educators  entirely  to  neglect  the  train 
ing  of  the  body  to  skillfulness  and  grace,  still,  on  the  other 


§  120.]  PURE   ETHICS.  241 

hand,  there  is  danger  of  overestimating  the  worth  of  regu 
lated  gymnastics.  The  unnatural  physical  life  of  our  city 
populations  may  render  necessary  a  systematic  process  of 
corporeal  exercise,  notwithstanding  its  manifold  unesthetic 
and  even  repulsive  joint-wrenchings ;  but  where  the  young 
people  can  have  scope  for  indulging  in  more  natural  and 
frolicksome  muscular  recreation,  regular  gymnastics  are  doubt 
less  quite  superfluous ;  the  learned  cramming  of  overcrowded 
schools  needs  them  indeed  as  a  sanitary  complement,  but  it  is 
dangerous  to  substitute  mere  medicine  for  daily  bread.  It  is 
a  morbid  condition  of  society,  when  that  to  which  nature  it 
self  prompts  us  has  to  be  made  a  school-requirement. 

The  complete  subordinating  of  the  sensuous  impulses  to  the 
discipline  of  the  spirit,  that  is,  the  training  of  the  body  by  the 
spirit  to  temperateness  in  respect  to  all  sensuous  enjoyments, 
and  to  such  activity  as  is  necessary  to  its  being  a  proper  organ 
for  the  spirit,  is  also,  at  the  same  time,  an  appropriating  and  a 
forming ;  the  members  are  to  be  formed  into  ' '  instruments  of 
righteousness  unto  God  "  [Rom.  vi,  12,  13].  Paul  represents  the 
complete  dependence  of  the  body  on  the  moral  spirit  as  a 
dependence,  not  on  the  merely  individual  spirit,  but  on  the 
spirit  as  morally  subordinating  itself  to  God.  Man,  as 
consecrated  to  God,  is  not  to  permit  the  per  se  legitimate 
caring  for  his  body  to  become  a  fostering  of  the  sensuous  de 
sires  [Rom.  xiii,  13,  14],  but  is  strictly  to  subordinate  the 
nurturing  of  the  body  and  the  indulgence  in  sensuous  enjoy 
ments  to  the  rational  purposes  of  the  moral  spirit,  so  that 
they  shall  simply  be  means  for  the  spirit  and  never  ends,  in 
themselves  [Luke  xxi,  34;  Rom.  xiv,  17 ;  Eph.  v,  18;  1  Thess. 
v,  6 ;  1  Tim.  iii,  2 ;  Tit.  ii,  1  sqq. ;  1  Pet.  iv,  7,  8].  Temperate- 
ness,  however,  does  not  imply  the  taking  of  the  least  possible 
quantity  of  food  and  drink,  nor  indeed  indifference  to  the 
sensuous  pleasures  of  the  table ;  this  would  in  fact  be  un- 
thankfulness  toward  the  goodness  of  God  who  has  prepared 
for  us  also  this  pleasure ;  it  does,  however,  require  the  observ 
ance  of  that  measure  which  is  conditioned  on  the  needs  and 
health  of  the  body,  and  on  the  properly  understood  social  re 
lations  of  the  person.  Excessive  indulgence  is  not  only  a 
degradation  of  the  person  himself,  but  also  uucharitablenesa 
toward  the  destitute. 
VOL.  11—17 


242  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  121. 

SECTION  CXXI. 

(J)  The  body  is  to  be  formed  into  an  image  or 
symbol  of  the  rational  spirit, — to  become  a  revelation 
of  the  spirit  in  the  external  world ;  that  is,  it  is  to  be 
shaped  into  an  object  of  beauty,  into  a  spiritualized 
expression  of  the  moral  personality.  This  takes 
place :  (1)  immediately, — in  that  the  body,  without 
the  express  and  conscious  activity  of  the  person,  is 
formed  into  a  true  expression  of  the  morally-cultured 
spirit ;  (2)  mediately, — in  that  the  body,  which  though 
per  se  possessing  the  highest  nature-beauty,  is  yet  not 
to  remain  in  simply  that  state,  is  formed  by  means 
of  a  spiritually-expressive  characterizing  adornment 
into  an  expression  of  artistic  beauty, — into  a  sym 
bolical  expression  not  merely  of  the  spiritual  in  gen 
eral,  but  also  of  the  personally-moral  character  in 
particular, — and  in  that,  with  moral  carefulness,  it 
is  kept  free  from  whatever  would  present  it  in  the 
light  of  an  object  that  is  disesteemed  or  given  over 
to  natural  unfreedom,  and  cast  off  by  the  spirit, — the 
virtue  of  cleanliness.  Adornment,  both  under  its 
positive  and  its  negative  phase,  is  a  moral  duty,  not 
merely  out  of  regard  to  others,  as  the  true  moral  pres 
entation  and  revelation  of  self  to  others,  but  also  out 
of  regard  to  the  moral  person  himself. 

The  natural  perfection  of  the  body  is  not  yet  the  true, — is 
to  be  exalted  from  natural  beauty  to  spiritual.  As  the  spirit 
exists  primarily  only  in  a  germinal  form,  hence  the  body  can 
not,  from  the  very  beginning,  bear  the  full  impress  of  the 
same ;  the  spiritual  expression  of  the  body  is  at  first  not  that . 
of  the  personally-formed,  but  only  of  the  as  yet  impersonal, 
spirit  in  general.  The  expression  of  the  countenance  becomes 
really  spiritual,  truly  beautiful,  only  by  and  through  a  per 
sonal  character-development,  which  is,  in  turn,  reflected  back 


§  121.]  PURE   ETHICS.  243 

from  this  personal  peculiarity.  The  spirit  must  already  have 
behind  it  a  moral  history,  before  it  comes  to  expression  in  the 
features.  A  general  beauty  without  character,  is  meaningless ; 
a  personally-spiritual  beauty  is  winning  and  magnetic.  The 
body  becomes  truly  beautiful  only  through  the  complete  ap 
propriating  of  the  same  by,  and  for,  the  spirit ;  and  the  true 
secret  of  beauty  consists  in  a  genuine  spiritual  and  moral  cul 
ture.  Where  falseness  has  not  yet  gained  firm  foothold,  there 
the  countenance  is  the  mirror  of  the  soul;  and,  for  the  skilled 
look,  even  disguising  falseness  is  transparent.  There  lies  at 
the  basis  of  ' '  physiognomies  "  a  deep  truth ;  but  this  truth  is 
not  expressible  in  definite  words  and  lines.  It  is  not  by  mere 
chance  that  for  certain  historic  personalities,  such  as  those  of 
Christ  and  the  more  prominent  of  the  apostles,  certain  very- 
definite  forms  and  casts  of  countenance  have  found  their  place 
in  Christian  art,  and  by  which  every  one  recognizes  them  at 
first  glance.  The  true  character-expression  of  the  cultured 
body  is,  in  some  sense,  spirit-imbued, — is  sensuous  and  super- 
sensuous  at  the  same  time;  neither  words,  nor  outlines,  nor 
even  the  photographic  pencil  of  nature,  is  capable  of  repro 
ducing  it,  but  only  the  spirit-guided  hand  of  the  artist:  spirit 
is  recognized  and  grasped  only  by  spirit ;  no  photograph  of  a 
spiritual,  character-imbued  face  attains  to  the  fidelity  of  an 
artistic  portrait.  In  a  sinless  state,  the  beauty  of  the  spirit 
would  necessarily  reveal  itself  in  beauty  of  body.  So  also 
must  it  have  been  in  the  case  of  Christ, — and  the  erroneous 
notion  that  for  a  time  prevailed  in  the  early  church,  to  the 
effect  that  in  Christ  there  had  been  no  physical  comeliness, 
was  soon  dissipated  by  the  correct  consciousness  of  Christian 
art.  The  heavenly  soul  of  Christ  must  have  depicted  itself  in 
his  countenance  [comp.  Psa.  xlv,  3] ;  and  the  reason  why  the 
children  approached  Him  with  glad  confidence  and  shouted : 
"  Hosanna  !  "  is  doubtless  because  of  a  direct  impression 
which  Christ's  person  made  upon  them ;  children  have  a  won 
derful  capacity  for  reading  character  in  the  external  appear 
ance.  Female  vanity,  in  laying  such  great  stress  on  corporeal 
beauty,  is  guilty  simply  of  applying  to  sinfully-perverted 
reality,  the  thought,  that  is  correct  for  the  unfallen  state  of 
humanity,  namely,  that  beauty  of  body  is  evidence  of  a  beau 
tiful  soul.  The  moral  task  in  relation  to  this  culture  of  bodily 


244  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§121. 

expression,  is,  happily,  not  an  immediate  intentional  forming 
of  the  body,  but  rather  the  moral  forming  of  the  soul,  which 
then,  in  turn,  of  itself  impresses  itself  on  the  body. 

The  ornamentation  of  the  body,  including  the  exclusion  of 
all  uncleanliness,  is  a  very  important  moral  duty,  and  one  that 
is  very  definitely  emphasized  in  the  Scriptures.  On  the  sub 
ject  of  nudity  and  clothing,  there  has  been,  both  from  the 
moral  and  from  the  artistic  stand-point,  much  disputing. 
Greek  art,  in  its  golden  age,  represented  some  of  the  gods 
nude ;  at  a  later  period,  when  it  had  stooped  to  the  service  of 
worldliness  rather  than  of  religion,  it  expressed  itself  predom 
inantly  in  the  nude.  Still,  however,  only  such  gods  appear 
nude  as  represent  a  certain  degree  of  moral  and  spiritual  un 
ripeness  or  sensuousness ;  Jupiter,  Juno,  Minerva,  appear 
almost  always  draped ;  for  spiritually-developed  and  historical 
characters,  also  among  human  beings,  nudity  was  an  artistic 
impossibility.  This  suggests  the  true  law  in  the  case.  Nu 
dity  represents  merely  the  naturally-beautiful,  not  the  spirit 
ually-beautiful,  merely  the  human  in  general,  not  the  personal 
in  particular, — is  that  which  is  alike  in  all  persons,  not  that  in 
which  they  spiritually  differ.  That  portion  of  the  body  which 
does  not  express  the  merely  general,  that  is,  the  countenance, 
is,  in  fact,  uniformly  left  free  of  clothing.  The  very  sense 
for  the  morally-spiritual  gives  even  a  stronger  expression  to 
the  personal  through  the  medium  itself  of  clothing.  Who 
could  bear  the  thought  of  a  nude  Caesar  or  Homer  !  Christian 
art  rejected  the  nude,  for  the  good  reason  that  it  had  spiritual 
characters  to  represent.  Moreover,  mere  nudity  is  artistically 
beautiful  only  in  the  form  of  lust-repellent,  colorless  sculpture ; 
in  painting  it  becomes  licentious  and,  therefore,  un-beautiful. 
It  is  a  very  false  opinion,  that  clothing  really  conceals  beauty ; 
clothing,  as  an  expression  of  the  spiritual,  as  a  free  artistic 
creation,  is  in  fact  the  higher  beauty.  This  appears  very 
clearly  when  man  is  represented  not  as  an  individual,  but  in 
groups;  a  bathing-place,  swarming  with  nude  figures,  pre 
sents  assuredly  no  beautiful  spectacle,  even  if  they  were  so 
many  Apollos;  precisely  where  man  appears  in  his  higher 
truth,  namely,  in  society,  there  a  beautiful  scene  is  presented 
only  by  the  help  of  diversified,  character-expressive  clothing. 
It  is  true,  clothing  is  beautiful  only  where  it  is  really  express- 


§121.]  PURE   ETHICS.  245 

ive  of  a  character,  whether  of  the  nation  or  of  the  person. 
The  slavish  copying  after  journals  of  fashion,  is  evidence  of  a 
want  of  sense  and  of  character,  and  of  a  lack  of  esthetic 
perception. 

Clothing  did  not  first  become  necessary  because  of  sin.  The 
Biblical  account  implies  only,  that  it  became  necessary  pre 
maturely,  and  for  another  than  its  normal  reason, — namely, 
before  the  development  of  personal  character  had  led  to  its 
invention  as  an  adornment.  The  sin  of  the  first  pair  effected 
only  that  the  hitherto-innocent  consorts  felt,  now,  shame  in 
each  other's  presence,  and  that  clothing,  the  proper  object  of 
which  is  ornamentation,  was  turned  into  a  garb  of  penance. 
Clothing  was  not  the  very  jf?rs£  want  of  persons  living  as  yet 
in  the  most  primitive  simplicity ;  nor  was  yet  its  lack  the  char 
acteristic  trait  of  the  Paradisaical  state ;  clothing  would  have 
become  a  moral  requirement  also  in  the  unfallen  state  so  soon 
as  man  had  grown  into  families,  and  the  riper  character  of 
parents  appeared  in  the  presence  of  children  [comp.  Gen.  ix, 
21  sqq.]  The  nudity  of  savages  is  not  innocence,  but  shame 
less  rudeness. 

Animals  do  not  decorate  themselves,  they  are  decorated 
already ;  man  exalts  himself  above  the  animal  by  ingenious 
decoration.  The  tawdry  ornamentation  of  savages  exemplifies 
this,  under  a  rude  form ;  with  them,  the  mere  changing  of  the 
natural  form  is  regarded  as  a  beautifying ;  the  notion  of  or 
namentation  is  conceived  under  an  essentially  negative  form ; 
the  unnatural  itself  is  regarded  as  beautiful.  There  is  a 
higher  significance  in  the  hunter's  hanging  about  himself  the 
skins  of  the  bear  or  lion ; — this  is  to  him  essentially  a  decora 
tion  of  honor,  a  sign  of  his  courage.  Thus  also,  in  the  simpler 
forms  of  civilized  life,  it  is  an  honor  for  a  woman  personally 
to  weave  and  to  prepare  her  own  clothing  and  that  of  the 
family ;  it  is  natural  for  man  to  display  his  work,  the  fruit  of 
his  skill ;  but  he  also  loves  to  manifest  his  spiritual  idiosyn 
crasy  under  an  esthetic  form  in  the  ornamentation  of  the  body. 
Clothing  and  ornamentation  in  general,  when  of  a  normal 
character,  manifest,  in  part,  the  general  element,  the  natural 
peculiarity,  and,  in  part,  the  personal  peculiarity;  hence  in 
the  style  of  the  clothing  we  can  to  a  certain  extent  recog 
nize  the  personal  character ;  the  distinction  between  male  and 


246  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  121. 

female  clothing  among  all  civilized  nations  has  a  deep  moral 
ground  [comp.  Deut.  xxii,  5] ;  and  just  as,  on  the  one  hand,  it 
is  usually  foolish  and  vain  for  an  individual  to  break  entirely 
with  a  general  national  custom,  so,  on  the  other,  it  is  evidence 
of  spiritual  imbecility  to  make  one's  entire  outward  appear 
ance  a  piece  of  mere  imitation,  without  personal  peculiarity. 

The  Scriptures  attach  some  importance  to  a  befitting 
adornment,  especially  in  its  moral  significancy.  Jehovah 
himself  prescribes  a  worthy  garb  for  those  who  officiate  in 
his  worship  [Exod.  xxviii  and  xxxix;  Num.  xv,  38  sqq.];  a 
holy  adornment  becomes  those  who  offer  worship  to  the 
Lord  [Psa.  xxix,  2;  comp.  Exod.  xix,  10;  Ezek.  xxiv,  17]. 
When  Christ  in  his  parable  [Matt,  xxii,  2  sqq.]  characterizes 
the  not  putting  on  of  the  wedding-garment  as  a  serious  fault,  lie 
manifestly  does  more  than  allude  to  a  mere  worthless  custom 
[comp.  Gen.  xli,  14];  and  the  apostle  does  not  consider  it 
unimportant  to  commend  to  the  societies  a  becoming  adorn 
ment  [1  Tim.  ii,  9,  10]. 

That  cleanliness  of  body  and  of  clothing  is  regarded  not 
only  in  the  Old  Testament  [Exod.  xix,  10 ;  xxix,  4 ;  Lev.  viii, 
66;  Num.  viii,  6  sqq.  ;  xxxi,  21  sqq.  ;  comp.  Prov.  xxxi,  25], 
but  also  in  all  the  higher  heathen  religions  and  in  Islamism, 
as  an  important  moral  and  religious  duty,  so  that  in  fact  a 
large  part  of  the  worship  consists  in  washings,  with  direct 
symbolical  reference  to  moral  purification, — is  a  plain  indica 
tion  of  the  deep  moral  significancy  of  bodily  purity.  The 
sanitary  interest  is  here  merely  incidental";  the  essential  point 
is  the  outward  expressing  of  the  spiritual.  Man  is  to  bear,  in 
his  entire  inner  nature,  as  well  as  in  his  outward  manifesta 
tion,  a  spiritually-moral  impress, — is  to  be,  in  all  respects,  an 
expression  of  free  self-determination,  is"  to  have  upon  himself 
nothing  which  has  attached  itself  to  him  merely  outwardly 
or  fortuitously,  as  something  belonging  not  to  him,  but  to  an 
extraneous  nature-body, — is  to  be  a  purely  spiritual  creation. 
Uncleanliness  is  the  expression  of  unfree  nature, — of  a  depend 
ent,  passive  belonging  to  mere  outward  nature,  an  evidence 
of  self-abandonment,  self-disesteem  and  dishonor,  and  is 
regarded  among  all  cultivated  nations  as  a  symbol  and  actual 
indication  of  sin ;  it  lias  never  been  any  tiling  other  than  isolated 
spiritual  perversions  of  humanity  who  have  foimd  an  especial 


§122.]  PURE  ETHICS.  247 

wisdom  and  greatness  of  soul  in  an  open  display  of  uncleanli- 
ness.  Sensual  pleasure-seeking,  riotousuess  and  moral  degra 
dation  usually  lead  to  corporeal  filthiness;  and  it  is  a  very 
wise  principle  of  education  in  the  case  of  the  morally  aban 
doned,  and  in  missions  among  rude  tribes,  to  place  a  very 
high  value  on  bodily  cleanliness.  The  precepts  as  to  cleans 
ing,  in  the  Old  Testament,  are  based  on  this  ground ;  Chris 
tianity  expressly  declares  carefulness  about  outward  cleanli 
ness  as  a  virtue  intimately  connected  with  religion  [Matt,  vi, 
17;  comp.  John  xiii,  4  sqq.]. 

To  the  gracefulness  and  beauty  of  the  physique,  belongs 
also  that  manner  of  movement  or  bearing  which  answers  to  the 
spiritual  character,  to  beauty  of  soul ;  the  cultivation  of 
skillfulness  of  movement  leads  directly  to  the  culture  of 
esthetical  motion.  The  beauty  of  movement  consists  in  the 
fact  that  it  expresses  the  perfect  mastery  of  the  soul  over  the 
body,  and  thus  presents,  in  the  body,  not  merely  the  organ  of 
the  will,  but  also,  through  the  element  of  the  beautiful,  an 
image  of  the  self -harmonious  spirit, — in  youth  an  expression  of 
heart-gladness,  in  age  that  of  earnest  dignity.  The  dance  is 
esthetic  only  in  youth,  in  the  mature  it  is  repulsive. 

SECTION  CXXII. 

(2)  Moral  appropriating  and  forming,  as  bearing 
upon  the  spirit  itself,  that  is,  the  .moral  striving  of 
the  spirit  to  have  and  to  possess  itself  as  its  own 
moral  product,  takes  place  through  conscious,  free 
activity,  although  indeed  in  the  unconscious  nature 
of  the  personal  spirit  there  exists  an  impulse  in  that 
direction.  In  so  far  as  man  is  a  rational  spirit  he 
has  before  him  his  own  self  as  a  moral  task, — is  to 
form  himself  into  a  moral  personality,  into  a  char 
acter  ;  all  non-advancement  is  here  retrogression. 
This  appropriating  and  forming  relates  to  the  spirit 
both  as  cognizing,  as  feeling,  and  as  willing,  and 
looks  to  the  harmony  of  these  three  phases  of  the 
spirit-life. 

It  is  only  when  the  spirit  makes  itself  into  its  own  posses- 


248  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  122. 

sion, — forms  itself  into  a  truly  rational  spirit,  that  it  is  a 
moral  spirit.  He  who  is  only  a  product  of  other  spirits,  who 
allows  himself  passively  to  be  molded  merely  by  the  spirit 
that  for  the  time  being  prevails  in  society,  is,  even  when  this 
spirit  is  a  good  one,  not  yet  morally  mature,  but  is  in  moral 
nonage ;  he  is  not  yet  a  person,  not  yet  a  character.  What 
Christ  says  [Matt,  xxv,  14  sqq.]  of  putting  to  use  the  talents 
received,  holds  good  also  of  the  moral  endowments  of  man ; 
he  dare  not  leave  them  idle,  but  must  put  them  to  moral  usu 
ry, — must  mold  himself  by  spiritual  appropriation  into  richer 
self-possession.  He  who  "has  not," — who  leaves  idle  his 
received  talent,  who  makes  it  not  into  a  vital  possession, — 
does  not  retain  it  even  as  an  unproductive  power,  but  loses 
what  he  already  has,  and  for  the  simple  reason  that  it  is  a 
general  law  that  a  life-power,  if  unawakened  into  activity, 
dies  away  and  perishes ;  it  is  only  in  virtue  of  a  vital  pro 
gressive  development  that  the  spiritual  can  be  preserved, — 
even  as  water  is  saved  from  stagnation  only  by  motion.  The 
state  of  innocence  cannot  be  preserved  by  mere  non-doing; 
moral  indolence  would  let  even  the  trees  of  life  in  Paradise 
wither  away.  By  the  leaving  idle  of  that  which  is  destined  to 
development,  man  sinks  to  moral  dullness  and  insensibility ; 
the  spiritual  condition  of  savages  is  a  manifestation  of  the 
consequences  of  burying  the  received  talent. 

The  culture  of  self  by  the  appropriation  of  truth,  that  is,  the 
forming  of  self  to  knowledge  and  wisdom,  is  presented  in 
the  Scriptures  as  one  of  the  highest  moral  duties,  and  it  is 
inadmissible  to  limit  this  appropriation  to  merely  religious 
and  moral  truth,  though  of  course  this  is  the  principal  thing 
(§  104).  God  actually  directed  the  first  man  to  the  acquire 
ment  of  knowledge  by  the  fact  of  his  referring  him  to  the 
objective  world  about  him  (§  60),  and  in  the  fact  that  He 
made  known  himself  and  his  will  to  him.  But  the  knowledge 
of  good  and  evil  was  forbidden  to  man,  for  the  reason  that  a 
real  knowledge  of  the  latter  was  possible  only  by  its  reali/a- 
tion ;  he  was  indeed  to  know  what  he  should  not  do,  but  not 
to  know  of  a  real  evil,  and  only  a  real  entity  can  be  truly 
known ;  but  the  woman  sought  after  a  wisdom  [Gen.  iii,  6J  apart 
from  true  wisdom,  and  consequently  fell. 

Feeling  is  primarily  of  an  immediate,  involuntary  character; 


§122.]  PURE   ETHICS.  .249 

but  man  is  not  to  be  under  the  power  of  unfree  feelings ;  he 
is  rational  only  when  he  develops  his  feelings  into  moral 
ones^ — brings  them  under  the  control  of  his  rational  knowledge 
and  of  his  moral  volitions.  There  is  absolutely  no  place  in 
the  human  mind  or  heart  for  any  thing  that  is  not  morally 
willed  or  conditioned.  Hence  it  is  a  moral  duty  to  cultivate 
our  feelings  into  moral  integrity,  so  that  they  may  never  incur 
the  liability  of  being  reproached  by  the  moral  consciousness, — 
never,  even  involuntarily,  entertain  envy,  and  the  like.  In  the 
ante-sinful  state  such  feelings  of  course  do  not  yet  exist ;  but 
non-moral  feelings  become  very  soon  sinful  ones  unless  they 
become  developed.  And  even  the,  as  yet,  uncorrupted  feel 
ings  are  primarily  still  in  a  crude  state  and  in  need  of  culture. 
The  feeling  of  delight,  and  hence  of  happiness,  rises  with  the 
increase  of  culture ;  the  first  human  beings  could  not  be  so 
happy  in  their  first  days  as  they  could  have  been  after  further 
moral  development.  They  too  were  liable  to  have  morally 
false  feelings.  It  is  true  there  was  as  yet  nothing  immoral 
before  their  eyes  which  could  have  become  an  object  of  im 
moral  delight ;  but  they  had,  before  them,  themselves  as  in 
need  of  further  development ;  hence  if  they  had  felt  perfectly 
contented  in  this  state  of  need,  instead  of  thirsting  after  a 
higher  perfection,  this  feeling  would  have  been  immoral.  On 
the  other  hand,  they  were  capable  of  feeling  displeasure  at  the 
divine, — as  in  fact  actually  occurred  in  view  of  the  divine 
prohibition.  And  the  pleasure  which  Eve  felt  in  the  words 
of  the  tempter  was  already  decidedly  immoral,  seeing  that  it 
implied  a  will  not  to  follow  .the  will  of  God,  and  was  essen 
tially  the  fall  itself. 

But  feeling  must  be  formed  not  merely  as  to  its  quality,  but 
also  as  to  its  degree  of  liveliness.  If  only  the  more  prominent 
phases  of  good  and  evil  make  an  impression  upon  us,  while 
the  less  prominent  ones  pass  before  us  unnoticed,  then  our 
moral  feeling  is  obscure  and  obtuse.  The  fact  that  feeling, 
like  the  bodily  senses,  is  affected  at  first  only  by  the  stronger 
impressions,  implies  of  itself  the  duty  of  making  it  sensitive — 
sensitive  even  for  the  most  delicate  features  of  the  godly  or 
the  ungodly.  And  this  can  be  brought  about  only  by  a  con 
stantly  increasing  growth  in  knowledge, — by  an  attending  to 
whatever  tajses  place  within  and  without  us;  we  must  prove 


250  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  122. 

all  things  and  hold  fast  to  the  best,  the  good,  and  that  too  not 
merely  as  knowledge  but  also  as  the  possession  of  our  heart, 
as  our  delight  and  joy. — Our  feelings,  as  moral,  stand  not  out 
side  of,  but  also  under  our  will.  The  notion  that  the  heart 
cannot  be  commanded,  is  absolutely  immoral, — is  an  assertion 
of  man's  irresponsibility.  Natural  feeling  does  indeed  pre 
cede  the  will,  but  moral  feeling  is,  under  one  phase,  deter 
mined  by  the  moral  will  [§  93].  It  is  not  left  to  the  hearts  of 
children  whether  they  will  or  can  love  their  parents,  they  are 
bound  to  love  them ;  and  the  same  is  true  of  wedlock-love,  of 
our  love  to  our  calling,  to  our  rulers,  to  our  country.  The 
first  promptings  of  feeling  are  as  yet  extra-moral,  but  in  that 
by  this  first  excitation  the  will  becomes  free  and  is  set  into 
activity,  it  then  in  turn  directs  its  activity  also  upon  the  feel 
ings  and  the  affections. 

That  willing  is  in  harmony  with  knowing  and  feeling,  is 
primarily  strictly  natural ;  in  man,  however,  as  distinguished 
from  the  much  earlier  self-possessing  animal,  this  agreement 
is  primarily  only  approximative ;  the  will  must  be  exercised  in 
order  to  be  sure  of  itself ;  man  must  first  learn  how  to  use  it. 
There  is  need  of  a  moral  will  in  order  that  the  will  may  be 
come  moral.  This  has  all  the  appearance  of  a  vicious  circle, 
but  it  is  not ;  the  fact  is,  I  must  in  general,  and  as  a  principle, 
have  a  will  always  to  follow  the  truth,  in  order  that,  in  par 
ticular,  I  may  actually  form  my  individual  will  morally,  and 
make  it  subject  to  recognized  truth.  The  spirit  is  willing  but 
the  flesh  is  weak ;  this  is  relatively  true  also  in  a  normal  devel 
opment  of  mankind ;  this  flesh  is,  however,  not  merely  sensu- 
ousness,  but  also  the  spirit  itself,  the  will,  in  so  far  as  it  has 
not  as  yet  become  veritably  free.  The  will  of  the  spirit  must 
become  something  which  it  is  not,  as  yet,  from  the  very 
start, — truly  free;  and  it  is  free  only  when  that  feebleness, 
which  is  primarily  merely  a  sort  of  clumsiness,  is  overcome, — 
when  the  spirit  is  not  only  in  general  willing  to  do  God's  will, 
but  also  shows  in  each  particular  case  the  same  unwavering 
willingness.  That  which,  in  a  state  of  sinfulne?s,  becomes  a 
self-conflicting  double  will  [Rom.  vii,  15  sqq.],  exists  also  in 
the  ante-sinful  state,  at  least  in  so  far  as  to  constitute  a  dif 
ference  between  the  will  as  purely  individual  and  the  will  as 
truly  rational,  God-consecrated,  and  self-denying.  The  for- 


§  122.]  PUKE  ETHICS.  251 

mer  is  not  to  be  done  away  with,  but  to  be  harmoniously  sub 
ordinated  to  the  latter ;  the  will  must  be  so  formed  as  that  we 
can  say  at  every  moment :  I  will,  and  yet  not  I,  but  God  who 
dwells  in  me.  The  will  should  not  be  a  willful  will,  but  must 
be  molded  into  an  obedient  one, — into  obedience  to  the  divine 
will,  which,  in  virtue  of  our  love  to  God,  becomes  at  one  with 
our  own  will.  In  obeying,  man  distinguishes  indeed  his  own 
will  from  God's  will,  but  he  subordinates  his  will,  not  loth- 
fully  but  in  loving  willingness,  to  the  lovingly-appropriated 
divine  will, — transfigures  the  former,  more  and  more,  by  his 
love  of  the  latter,  so  that  finally  there  are  no  longer  two  wills, 
but  only  one, — and  that,  not  in  virtue  of  any  destruction,  but 
simply  in  virtue  of  love,  not  by  violence  but  through  free 
dom, — by  following  the  example  of  Christ  in  the  constant 
practice  of  the  principle:  "Not  my  will,  but  thine  be  done" 
[Luke  xxii,  42;  Matt,  vi,  10;  John  v,  30;  Psa.  xl,  8;  Jer.  vii, 
23;  Matt,  vii,  21;  xii,  50;  1  John  ii,  17;  Heb.  xiii,  21]. 
Every  moral  will  must  say  with  Christ :  ' '  My  meat  is  to  do 
the  will  of  him  that  sent  me  "  [John  iv,  34] ;  obedience  is  the 
food  of  the  soul, — forms  and  strengthens  the  will  to  an  in 
creasingly  freer  and  holier  manner  of  willing.  Only  those  are 
the  children  of  God  who  are  led  by  the  spirit  of  God, — who 
permit  themselves  freely  to  be  guided  by  Him,  who  will  only 
in  and  through  Him  [Rom.  viii,  14]. 

Hence  also  in  the  forming  of  the  will  we  have  to  distin 
guish  between  the  quality  and  the  degree.  A  will  may  in  fact 
be  good  in  quality,  may  aim  at  the  good  and  detest  the  evil, 
and  yet  be  lacking  in  strength  and  in  steadfastness, — may 
shrink  before  difficulties ;  it  may  begin  well  and  yet  not  bring 
to  perfection ;  good  resolutions  do  not  necessarily  imply  a  truly 
good  will ;  in  fact,  the  road  to  hell  is  said  to  be  paved  with 
good  resolutions.  He  who  has  a  good  will  only  at  first,  but 
does  not  really  carry  out  any  thing,  is  as  yet  unfree  in  his 
will, — has  it  not  under  his  control,  and  is  yet  a  moral  minor; 
he  does  not  actually  will  at  every  particular  conjuncture  that 
which  he  wills  in  general.  Hence  it  is  man's  duty  to  place 
Ms  will  entirely  under  the  dominion  of  moral  reason,  to  mold 
it  to  freedom,  in  order  that  in  particular  cases  it  may  not  offer 
resistance  to  good  resolutions  in  general, — in  a  word,  that  a 
will  of  the  flesh  may  not  oppose  itself  to  the  will  of  the  spirit. 


252  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  123. 


III.  THE  MORAL  ACTIVITY  AS  RELATING  TO  OTHER 
PERSONS. 

SECTION  CXXIII. 

(a)  The  moral  sparing  of  others  consists  in  a  real 
recognition  of  their  moral  personality,  and  hence  of 
their  personal  independence,  freedom,  and  honor. 

(a)  Man's  personal  independence  and  freedom, 
which  are  the  expression  of  his  morally  rational 
essence,  may  be  limited  by  others  only  in  the  inter 
est  of  higher  moral  ends,  namely,  either  in  order  to 
train  the  as  yet  morally  and  spiritually  immature 
toward  real  freedom,  or  in  the  moral  interests  of  the 
moral  whole  or  society. — (0)  The  personal  honor  of 
our  fellow-man  is  preserved  when  we  recognize  and 
treat  him  as  a  morally-rational  being  called  to  God- 
likeness  and  God-sonship,  and  hence  as  capable  of, 
and  entitled  to,  moral  communion  with  us, — when 
we  do  nothing  toward  him  which  is  inconsistent 
therewith, — which  would  stigmatize  him  as  non- 
moral,  or,  undeservedly,  as  immoral  and  irrational ; 
this  is  the  duty  of  respecting  our  neighbor,  and  as 
implied  therein  of  respecting  the  personal  dignity  of 
man  in  general, — the  duty  of  sparing  and  protecting 
the  good  name  of  our  neighbor. — (y)  From  these  two 
duties  follows  the  duty  of  a  sparing  respect  for  what 
ever  appertains  to  our  neighbor, — belongs  to  him  as 
a  possession,  is  his  property  in  the  broadest  sense  of 
the  word,  that  is,  whatever  he  has  a  right  to  call  his 
own, — and  hence  a  positive  avoidance  of  all  action 
whereby  it  would  be  damaged  or  alienated  from  our 
neighbor. 


§  123-]  PURE   ETHICS.  253 

Even  as  our  personal  morality  does  not  consist  in  undisci 
plined  arbitrary  discretion,  but  in  the  controlling  our  own 
will  by  the  wiH  of  God,  so  also  there  is  no  moral  influencing 
of  our  fellow-man  without  a  limiting  of  his  individual  will, 
of  his  individual  liberty,  and  that  too  in  the  very  interest  of  his 
higher  personal  freedom.  The  child  qannot  be  educated 
without  that  in  many  respects  limits  be  set  to  its,  as  yet, 
unripe,  unintelligent  will ;  in  the  person  of  the  educator  it  is 
confronted  with  the  principles  of  moral  order  under  which  it 
is  to  bow  its  individual  will ;  it  is  in  fact  an  essential  part  of 
the  duty  of  sparing  the  personality  of  the  child,  that  it  be  not 
allowed  to  grow  up  in  rudeness.  As  the  child  is  related  to 
its  parents,  so  is  the  individual  person  to  the  moral  whole. 
He  whose  calling  it  is  to  govern,  must  confine  the  liberty  of 
the  individual  within  the  order  of  the  whole, — must  in  some 
measure  limit  it  in  order  that  all  may  become  truly  free ;  in 
an  organized  moral  community  it  is  each  member's  duty  to 
co-operate  in  the  realization  of  moral  order,  and  hence  to  hold 
within  bounds  both  his  own  will  and  the  will  of  others. 
Hence  the  moral  sparing  of  others  is  never  of  an  unconditional 
character,  but  finds  a  limit  in  the  duty  of  moral  culture ;  but 
within  this  limit  the  duty  of  sparing  becomes  all  the  more 
imperative.  The  limiting  may  never  be  such  as  to  reduce 
the  object  to  a  mere  will-less  creature  of  arbitrary  discretion ; 
the  right  of  the  object  of  education  or  guidance  to  be  an 
independent  moral  personality  with  a  moral  purpose  of  its 
own,  may  never  be  ignored.  He  who  is  as  yet  morally  a  minor 
may  never  be  treated  as  if  he  were  always  to  remain  such, — 
never  as  a  mere  means  to  an  end, — but  he  must  be  treated  as 
having  an  end  in  himself.  A  slavish  education  is  sinful; 
despotic  government  is  immoral,  whether  exercised  by  a 
single  individual  or  by  a  minority-crushing  majority.  Whatever 
apology  may  be  made  for  slavery  in  a  sinful  world,  in  the 
sphere  of  pure  morality  it  is  absolutely  anti-moral. 

The  sparing  and  respecting  of  the  personal  honor  of  others, 
appears  among  the  chief  commands  in  the  Old  Testament 
[Exod.  xx,  16;  Lev.  xix,  16],  and  is  presented  also  in  the  Gos 
pel  as  one  of  the  most  essential  of  duties  [Matt,  v,  21,  22J. 
My  neighbor  has  upon  me  a  claim  to  respect  for  his  honor,  for 
his  good  name.  Man  is  not  a  mere  isolated  unit,  but  a  vital 


254  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§124. 

member  of  a  moral  whole ;  the  personal  honor,  the  good  name, 
of  each  is  the  moral  bond  which  holds  together  the  commu 
nity  ;  he  who  has  lost  respect  in  society  stands  outside  of  the 
scope  of  its  common-life, — is  a  broken-off  leaf  soon  to  wither 
away. — The  sparing  of  the  po ssessions  of  others  [Exod.  xx,  15, 
17;  Lev.  xix,  35,  36;  Deut.  xxv,  13  sqq.;  xxvii,  17;  1  Thess. 
iv,  6]  is  only  a  special  phase  of  the  sparing  of  the  person  of 
others.  In  his  property  man  creates  for  and  about  himself  a 
little  world  which  as  the  product  of  his  labor,  belongs  to 
him,  which  he  calls  his  earnings,  and  for  which  he  has  conse 
quently  a  moral  right  to  recognition  and  respect  on  the  part 
of  others. 

SECTION  CXXIV. 

(5)  The  moral  appropriaiing  and  the  forming  of 
others  are,  in  virtue  of  the  mutual  moral  relation  of 
men  to  each  other,  always  associated  together  in  a  nor 
mal  state  of  things, — each  being  and  involving  at  the 
same  time  also  the  other ;  and  both  take  place  at  the 
same  time  in  the  moral  act  of  love.  In  active  love 
toward  his  neighbor,  man  brings  about  also  love 
toward  himself,  for  the  beloved  person  becomes 
united  to,  and  appropriated  by,  him  who  loves ;  the 
active  love  of  one's  neighbor  is  therefore  an  appro 
priating  arid  a  forming  at  the  game  time,  both  in 
respect  to  the  neighbor  and  in  respect  to  the  loving 
person  himself.  The  exercise  of  love  breaks  down 
the  antithesis  of  individual  persons,  but  at  the  same 
time  respects  their  moral  rights  and  moral  inde 
pendence. 

It  is  noteworthy  that  in  the  Scriptures  we  never  read  of  the 
love  of  mankind,  but  always  of  the  love  of  neighbor  ;  [Matt,  vi, 
14, 15  is  only  a  seeming  exception  to  this,  as  here  "  men  "  stand  in 
contrast  to  God].  Christ's  love  to  us  is  indeed  called  love  to 
man  or  to  the  brethren,  but  never  love  to  neighbor ;  but  our 
love  to  man  in  general,  and  not  merely  to  our  Christian 


§  124.]  PURE   ETHICS.  255 

brethren,  is  always  called  love  to  neighbor.  In  this  very 
circumstance  the  moral  relation  of  men  to  each  other  is 
directly  indicated.  My  fellow-inan  does  not  stand  before  me 
as  a  mere  isolated  individual,  but  as  one  who,  by  God's  will, 
is  near  to  me, — who  belongs  to  me  for  my  full  love,  belongs 
to  me  so  intimately  that  there  ought  to  be  nothing  strange  or 
uncongenial  between  him  and  me.  In  love,  my  neighbor 
becomes  mine,  and  I  his ;  hence  love  is  a  mutual  appropriat 
ing  ;  and  by  the  fact  that  I  thereby  enlarge  both  my  life- 
sphere  and  his  own,  it  is  at  the  same  time  a  mutual  forming. 
Love  seeks  not  merely  the  welfare  of  the  other,  but  also  his 
love.  In  the  act  of  love  I  form  the  other,  in  that  I  impart 
myself  to  him  as  loving,  and  that  too  in  my  moral  character ; 
I  rejoice  him  and  exalt  his  moral  life,  in  that  I  stimulate  him 
to  reciprocal  love.  At  the  same  time  also  I  exercise  a  form 
ative  influence  on  myself,  in  that  by  this  communion  I  am 
myself  exalted  and  promoted  in  my  spiritually-moral  exist 
ence, — in  that  I  spiritually  appropriate  to  myself  an  other 
spiritual  being. 

The  law  of  love  is  presented  by  Christ  as  the  highest  of  all 
commands,  and  love  of  neighbor  as  the  substance  of  all  moral 
duties  toward  our  fellow-man  [Matt,  xxii,  39,  40 ;  John  xiii, 
34,  35;  xv,  12,  17;  comp.  Rom.  xii,  10;  xiii,  8-10;  Gal. 
v,  14 ;  Eph.  v,  2 ;  1  Thess.  iv,  9 ;  1  Cor.  xiii,  1  sqq. ;  1  Pet.  i, 
22;  iv,  8;  1  John  iii,  11;  James  ii,  8;  Heb.  xiii,  1],  All 
fulfilling  of  duty  toward  our  neighbor  is  an  exercise  of 
love ;  when  not  so  it  is  but  deception ;  that  which  springs  not 
of  love,  is  not  only  morally  worthless,  but  also  immoral, 
because  counterfeit.  Love  'is  the  test  of  true  God-souship 
[1  John  iv,  12,  13],  "for  love  is  of  God,  and  every  one  that 
loveth  is  born  of  God  and  knoweth  God "  [1  John  iv,  7] ; 
human  love  is  thankful  reciprocation  for  that  love  which  first 
loved  us, — is  true  religion  [James  i,  27] ;  and  love  to  God 
must  necessarily  manifest  itself  also  in  love  to  the  beloved  of 
God  [1  John  iv,  20,  21;  v,  1,  2].  The  precept  of  love  to 
neighbor  is  presented  even  in  the  Old  Testament  as  a  chief 
duty  [Lev.  xix,  18],  and  is  expressly  extended  to  non- Israel 
ites  [verse  34;  Deut.  x,  19;  Micah  vi,  8;  Zech.  vii,  9];  what 
a  contrast  this  forms  to  the  boasted  "  humanitarianism "  of 
the  Grepks  to  whom  every  non-Greek  was  a  right-less  barba- 


256  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§124. 

rian!  Thou  shalt  love  thy  neighbor  "  as  thyself; "  this  is  not 
a  mere  comparison  of  two  parallel  forms  of  love, — both  are  at 
bottom  but  one  love ;  a  truly  moral  love  of  one's  self  as  a  moral 
personality,  necessarily  manifests  itself  also  as  love  to  other 
moral  persons  through  whom  in  fact  one's  own  rational  being 
is  heightened ;  true  love  of  neighbor  is  also  at  the  same  time 
true  self-love.  This  holds  good  even  of  the  false  love  of 
neighbor;  every  one  seeks,  in  some  form,  friendship  and 
love,  and  feels  himself  unhappy  in  isolation ;  hence  our  Lord 
says:  ;'If  ye  love  [only]  them  which  love  you,  what  reward 
have  ye  ?  do  not  even  the  Publicans  the  same  ? "  [Matt,  v,  46, 
47;  comp.  Luke  vi,  32].  If  now  even  a  false  love  of  neigh 
bor  is  at  the  same  time  a  love  of  self,  how  much  more  so  is 
the  true  love  of  neighbor! — not  however,  of  course,  in  such  a 
sense  as  that  I  love  my  neighbor  only  for  my  own  sake,  for 
that  would  be  self-seeking,  but  in  the  sense  that  I  love  my 
neighbor  for  God's  sake,  and  in  this  love  of  God  exalt  at  the 
same  time  my  own  moral  life,  and  find  in  the  love  of  neigh 
bor  true  moral  enjoyment. 

The  symbolical  expression  of  mutual  union  in  love  is  bodily 
touching,  especially  the  giving  of  the  hand  [2  Kings  x,  15 ; 
Gal.  ii,  9],  and  in  a  higher  form  the  kiss,  which  evinces  a 
more  intimate  equality  of  love  the  more  it  is  reciprocal ;  the 
kiss  on  the  forehead  or  cheek  is  rather  the  sign  of  a  con 
descending  and  more  distant  love,  the  kissing  of  the  hand 
that  of  a  reverential  love,  the  kissing  of  the  feet  that  of  a 
humbly  submissive  love  [Luke  vii,  38 ;  Isa.  xlix,  23],  the  kiss 
on  the  lips  that  of  a  mutual,  confidential,  intimate  love,  and 
hence  especially  expressive  also  of  sexual  love.  In  the 
Scriptures  the  kiss  appears  as  the  sign  of  love  between  parents 
and  children  [Gen.  xxvii,  26,  27;  xxxi,  28,  55  ;  xlviii,  10; 

I,  1  ;  Exod.    xviii,  7 ;    Ruth  i,   9 ;    1    Kings   xix,  20  ;    Luke 
xv,  20],  between  brothers  and  sisters  and  relatives  [Gen.  xxix, 

II,  13  ;  xxxiii,  4 ;  xlv,  15  ;  Exod.  vi,  27  ;  Ruth  i,  14],  between 
friends  [1  Sam.  xx,  41],  as  an  expression  of  homage  [1  Sam. 
x,  1 ;  Psa.  ii,  12 ;  Luke  vii,  38],  and  as  an  expression  of  love 
in  other  respects  [2  Sam.  xx,  9 ;  Matt,  xxvi,  48  sqq. ;  Luke 
vii,  45  ;  Acts  xx,  37] ;  hence   it  is  also  a   symbol  of  recon 
ciliation  [Gen.  xxxiii,  4 ;  2  Sam.  xiv,  33 :  Luke  xv,  20] ;  and 
the  fraternal  kiss  was,  in  the  early  church,  a  general  custom 


§  125.]  PURE   ETHICS.  257 

[Rom.    xvi,  16;  1   Cor.    xvi,   20;  2  Cor.  xiii,    12;  1  Thess. 
v,  26;  1  Pet.  v,  14.] 

SECTION  CXXV. 

Active  love  is  a  self-impartation  of  the  subject  to 
the  object, — an  imparting  of  what  is  one's  own  to 
another  in  order  to  exalt  his  life.  Hence  it  mani 
fests  itself  in  service-rendering,  in  benefiting ;  all 
moral  community-life  is  a  reciprocal  service  of  love  ; 
every  act  of  love  is  a  sacrifice.  Sympathizing  love 
imparts  every  thing  which  is  dear  to  it : — (a)  It  im 
parts  its  own  spiritual  possessions  in"  order  thereby 
to  promote  the  spiritual  life  and  the  spiritual  posses 
sions  of  the  other,  and  this,  in  virtue  of  an  honest 
and  truthful  self-communication.  To  this  communi 
cation  corresponds,  on  the  part  of  the  object,  the 
answering  and  accepting  love  of  confidence,  that  is,  a 
willingness  to  let  himself  be  formed  by  the  appro 
priation  of  the  spiritually-communicating  love  of  his 
fellow, — a  being  receptive  for  self-revealing  truthful 
ness.  (&)  Love  imparts  also  its  material  possessions, 
and  is  hence  a  devoting  of  our  personal  productive 
forces  to  the  aid  of  the  needy,  in  the  fulfillment  of 
the  duties  of  charity  and  personal  assistance.  In  im 
parting  and  devoting  itself,  love  acquires  a  right  to 
the  reciprocating  love  of  the  other, — to  thankfulness 
in  heart  and  act. 

Love  imparts  lovingly  to  the  beloved  that  which  itself 
loves ;  only  that  in  which  I  myself  have  pleasure,  can  I  lov 
ingly  impart ;  for  this  reason  every  true  act  of  love  is  a  sacri^ 
fice,  and  a  sacrifice  that  is  not  hesitatingly  and  stumblingly 
brought  ;  love  makes  it  easy ;  but  every  sacrifice  must  be 
made  to  God ;  only  he  who  practices  love  for  God's  sake 
brings  a  proper  offering.  To  do  good  and  to  communicate  is 
expressly  declared  in  the  Scriptures  as  a  God-pleasing  sacri 
fice  [Heb.  xiii,  16].  The  mite  of  the  poor,  when  offered  in 
VOL.  11—18 


258  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§125. 

love,  avails  more  than  the  rich  gift  of  the  thoughtless  spend 
thrift  ;  in  fact  he  who  does  not  morally  love  his  legitimately- 
obtained  possessions,  cannot  in  the  nature  of  things  make 
therefrom  a  sacrifice. 

Christ  gives  as  the  determining  rule  for  our  conduct  toward 
our  neighbor  the  general  formula:  "  All  things  whatsoever  ye 
would  that  men  should  do  to  you,  do  ye  even  so  to  them,  for 
this  is  the  law  and  the  prophets  "  [Matt,  vii,  12  j.  Hence 
true  self-love  is  the  pattern  and  measure  of  love  to  neighbor ; 
our  own  rational  striving  shows  us  what  is  the  striving  of 
others,  and  ought  to  put  itself  into  harmony  with  the  latter; 
that  which  I  would  acquire  for  myself  as  a  right  upon  others, 
ought  first  to  be  a  duty  toward  them.  By  this  rule  Christ 
implies,  at  the  same  time,  that  love  begets  answering  love, 
and  hence  reverts  back  upon  him  who  exercises  it.  This  is  a 
practical  life-rule  in  answer  to  the  question :  How  shall  I  exer 
cise  love  in  each  and  every  particular  case  ?  and  it  gives  as 
the  answer :  Just  as  I  should  wish  that  it  should  be  done  to 
myself, — a  very  safe  rule,  provided  always  that  my  own  moral 
consciousness  in  general  is  not  beclouded,  so  that  I  should  no 
longer  know  what  would  really  serve  to  my  peace.  The  pre 
cious  is  purchased  only  by  the  precious, — love  only  by  love. 
All  love  seeks  to  serve;  love  of  neighbor  is  ministering  love. 
"  Whosoever  will  be  great  among  you,  let  him  be  your  min 
ister,  and  whosoever  will  be  chief  among  you,  let  him  be 
your  servant,  even  as  the  Son  of  man  came  not  to  be  min 
istered  unto,  but  to  minister,  and  to  give  his  life  a  ransom  for 
many"  [Matt,  xx,  26  sqq.~\.  Christ's  love,  the  highest  pattern, 
is  itself  the  highest  love-service,  and  has  brought  the  greatest 
sacrifice ;  all  love  to  God  is  a  service  of  God ;  all  neighbor- 
love  is  a  God-serving  in  the  service  of  the  neighbor.  ' '  Let  no 
man  seek  what  is  his  own,  but  every  man  what  is  another's" 
[1  Cor.  x,  24] ;  love  to  self  must  not  become  a  separating  of 
ourselves  from  others,  nor  a  self-seeking  using  of  them  ;  self- 
seeking  must  be  sacrificed  in  order  to  attain  to  true  self-love 
in  the  love  of  neighbor.  ''Remember  the  words  of  the  Lord 
Jesus,  how  he  said,  It  is  more  blessed  to  give  than  to  receive  " 
[Acts  xx,  35] ;  giving  makes  happier  in  the  very  love-act 
itself,  and,  though  a  sacrificing,  is  yet  at  the  same  time  a  re 
ceiving,  an  enkindling  of  reciprocal  love,  an  imitating  of 


§  125.]  PURE  ETHICS.  259 

God  and  of  Christ  who  out  of  love  gave  all ;  it  is  more  blessed 
than  receiving, — not  that  we  are  simply  to  give  acts  of  love, 
and  not  also  thankfully  to  receive  them, — for  he  who  cannot, 
out  of  love,  receive,  is  unable  also  to  give  out  of  love,  and  he 
who,  because  of  pride,  will  not  receive,  gives  in  fact  only  out 
of  pride;  but  that  kind  of  receiving  is  not  blessed  and  does 
not  render  blessed,  which  is  not  willing  also  to  give,  but  only  to 
Tiaee,  and  in  which  the  person  regards  only  the  bestowment  as 
such,  and  not  the  love  which  makes  it, — inclines  only  to  pos 
sess  the  gift,  but  not  to  recognize  the  love  and  to  reciprocate 
it  in  love.  The  moral  person  receives  also  gladly,  out  of  love, 
from  love,  not  however  for  the  sake  of  the  gift  but  for  the 
sake  of  the  giver, — desires  indeed  to  receive  love,  but  only 
for  the  reason  that  he  himself  loves.  The  giving  of  presents 
is  a  universally  recognized  sign  of  love,  even  where  the  moral 
consciousness  appears  under  its  rudest  forms  [Gen.  xii,  16 ; 
xlv,  17  cqq.] ;  there  is  no  love  which  does  not  seek  to  impart 
itself, — which  would  not  gladly  offer  liberally,  for  the  delight 
and  enjoyment  of  the  other,  that  in  which  the  loving  one  him 
self  has  delight  and  enjoyment,  and  thus  prove  itself  genuine 
by  sacrifice  [Gen.  xxiv,  22,  53;  xxxii,  13  sqq.;  xlii,  25;  xliii, 
11;  xlv,  22  sqq.  ;  \  Sam.  ix,  7  sqq. ;  xviii,  4;  Prov.  xviii,  16]. 
Among  certain  rude  tribes  it  is  customary  for  friends  to  inter 
change  names,  as  is,  in  fact,  the  case  with  one  of  the  parties, 
even  now,  in  Christian  marriage ;  this  is  also  a  love-offering. 

Communicating  love  imparts  indeed  all  that  it  has,  but  it 
does  not  give  away  all ;  the  spiritual  possession  grows  in  im 
parting  itself.  The  communicating  of  one's  own  spiritual 
possessions  is  the  exercise  of  truthfulness.  The  rational  spirit 
has,  in  virtue  of  its  own  duty  of  spiritual  appropriating,  an 
absolute  right  to  truthfulness  in  the  self-communications  of 
others,  though  indeed  not  an  unconditional  right  to  the  com 
munication  of  all  that  is  known  by  others.  Love  admits  of  no 
falseness ;  and  though  there  may  be  things  in  the  life,  even  of 
the  righteous,  especially  inner  states,  which  may  not  and 
should  not  be  communicated  indiscriminately  to  every  one, — 
for  example,  to  the  as  yet  morally  immature, — still,  this  si 
lence  is  essentially  different  from  falsifying.  In  the  Scriptures 
truthfulness  is  based  on  love;  "speak  every  man  truth  with 
his  neighbor,  for  we  are  members  one  of  another  "  [Eph.  iv, 


260  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [$  125. 

25],  that  is,  because  we  are  united  as  vital  organs  to  a  single 
moral  body, — belong  to  each  other,  should  be  transparent  to 
each  other.  "To  this  end,"  says  Christ,  "was  I  born,  and 
for  this  cause  came  I  into  the  world,  that  I  should  bear  wit 
ness  unto  the  truth "  [John  xviii,  37] ;  this  is  true  of  Christ 
also  in  his  character  of  Son  of  man,  and  hence  also  of  all 
men ;  now  Christ  came  into  the  world  out  of  love,  and  out  of 
love  he  bore  witness  to  the  truth.  Truth  is  the  good,  the  di 
vine,  as  relating  to  spiritual  communicating.  Whatever  exists 
is  for  the  personal  spirit,  and  each  personal  spirit  exists  for  all 
other  personal  spirits, — must  be  perfectly  transparent  to  them, 
in  so  far  as  sin  throws  into  it  no  shadow,  in  order  that  spirit 
in  general,  the  essential  nature  of  which  is  to  unite  the  sepa 
rated,  may  attain  to  the  truth  [Matt,  v,  37 ;  comp.  Job  xxvii, 
4;  Zech.  viii,  16;  Psa.  xv,  2;  xxxiv,  14;  Rev.  xiv,  5].  Where 
sin  is  not  yet  predominant,  but  love  prevails,  there  truthful 
ness  is  easy  and  natural ;  it  becomes  difficult  only  where  sin 
predominates. 

The  formative  influencing  of  others  through  the  living-out 
of  a  moral  character  is  to  be  regarded  simply  as  a  phase  of 
the  truthfulness  of  loving  self- communication,  and  not  as 
constituting  a  special  duty  of  giving  a  good  example  [Matt,  v, 
14-16;  Rom.  xiv,  19;  xv,  2;  Phil,  ii,  15;  iii,  17;  Titus  ii,  7; 

1  Pet.  ii,  9,  12,  15;  comp.  1  Cor.  iv,   16;  xi,  1;  Phil,  iv,   9; 

2  Thess.  iii,  7].     No  one  may  wish  to  be  moral  in  order  to  ap- 
vear  moral ;  that  would  be  downright  hypocrisy ;  but  also 
no  one  should  desire  to  conceal  that  which  in  his  character  is 
truly  moral ;  this  would  likewise  be  untruth.     But  in  order  to 
the  formative  influencing  of  others  through  moral  self-mani 
festation,  it  is  of  course  not  enough  simply  to  be  inactive, 
simply  as  it  were  to  let  one's  self  be  contemplated,  but  there 
is  requisite,  in  view  of  the  diverse  characters  that  are  to  be 
influenced,  a  selection  of  special  manners  of  self-communica 
tion  ;  as  bearing  upon  children  the  manner  must  be  other  than 
with  the  morally  mature ;  from  this,  however,  it  does  not  fol 
low  that  this  self-impartation  is  to  sink  to  a  mere  self-compla 
cent  display  of  self, — an  intentional  presentation  of  self  as  a 
moral  pattern,  in  any  respect  whatever.     This  would  be,  even 
in  a  saint,  a  violation  of  becoming  humility, — a  tempting  of 
hearts  from  Him  who  alone  is  the  perfect  type  of  holiness. 


§125.]  PURE   ETHICS.  261 

Spiritual  self-communicating,  even  when  perfectly  truthful, 
is  not  per  se  of  a  moral  character,  for,  in  view  of  the  limited- 
ness  of  men  as  individual  persons,  it  is  in  fact  a  direct  neces 
sity  ;  for  this  reason,  perfect  solitude  is  so  great  a  torment ; 
the  recluse  endures  his  freely-chosen  solitude  solely  because 
he  is  engaged  in  a  continuous  spiritual  self-communicating, 
namely,  to  God  in  prayer;  a  non-praying,  unpious  solitary 
would  either  be  suffering  the  severest  punishment  or  would  be 
spiritually  deranged.  Self-impartation  may  even  be  sinful,  as 
in  purposeless,  thoughtless  gossip ;  it  becomes  moral  only 
when  it  is  a  practicing  of  love.  Loving  self-communication 
seeks  not  its  own  but  that  which  is  another's.  Falsehood  is 
hatred,  is  lovelessness ;  where  true  love  is  there  falsehood  is 
impossible ;  hence  the  deep  pain  occasioned  by  falseness  on. 
the  part  of  the  beloved  one. 

From  the  fact  that  truthfulness  is  an  expression  of  love,  it 
is  entitled  to  answering  love  from  the  other  party,  to  a  ready 
welcoming,  to  confidence.  It  is  true,  confidence  in  men  is  gen 
erally  presented  in  the  Scriptures  as  deceiving  [Psa.  cxviii,  8 ; 
Jer.  xvii,  5,  6,  etc.];  here,  however,  the  question  is  only  as 
to  an  unpious  confidence  which  builds  not  upon  God  but  upon 
man,  and  of  the  state  of  sinfulness  in  general.  But  where  sin 
is  not  yet  in  the  mastery,  there  mutual  confidence  is  the  nec 
essary  antecedent  condition  of  all  moral  communion,  and  a 
necessary  out-going  of  love.  Distrust  paralyzes  love.  The 
truthful  have  a  moral  right  to  confidence  in  their  word ;  con 
fidence  is  the  reverse  side  of  truthfulness.  Even  as  Christ 
uniformly  required  faith  and  confidence  in  himself,  because  he 
was  the  Truth,  so  may  every  one  who  is  of  the  Truth  lay  claim 
to  confidence ;  hence  confidence  is  not  a  discretionary  state  of 
the  mind,  but  a  moral  act.  The  little  child  that  was  proposed 
to  the  disciples  as  a  moral  type,  is  such  also  in  respect  to  trust 
and  confidence. 

The  more  outward  form  of  self-imparting  through  service- 
rendering  [Gen.  xxiv,  18  sqq, ;  xxxiii,  12,  15;  Exod.  ii,  17; 
Deut.  xxii,  1  sqq.  ;  Matt,  xxi,  3 ;  John  xii,  2 ;  xiii,  4  sqq. ;  Acts 
xxviii,  2;  Gal.  v,  13;  1  Pet.  iv,  10;  Heb.  vi,  10;  xiii,  16,  etc.] 
which,  on  the  supposition  of  a  state  of  sinfulness,  includes  in 
itself  also  beneficence,  is  not  as  yet  in  the  unfallen  state  a 
showing  of  pity,  for  misery  does  not  exist  save  in  a  state  of 


262  CHEISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§126. 

sin ;  but  there  is  always  need  of  mutual  assistance  so  long  as 
the  last  degree  of  perfection  is  not  yet  reached,  and  hence 
there  is  always  also  the  duty  of  helping,  through  the  impart 
ing  of  our  own  forces  and  means, — of  mutually  complementing 
our  possessions  which  largely  vary  according  to  the  personal 
peculiarity  of  the  possessors. 

Love  is  in  its  very  nature  communion-forming, — calls  for  the 
love  of  the  other.  And  unreciprocated  love  presupposes  sin. 
Love  gives  itself  over,  but  it  does  not  give  itself  away ;  it  de 
sires  to  find  itself  again  in  the  beloved,  even  as  light  never 
shines  without  being  reflected.  The  loving  reflection  of  love, 
namely,  love  as  the  fruit  of  love,  is  thankfulness.  He  to  whom 
thankfulness  or  unthankfulness  is  indifferent,  has  no  love; 
even  the  Lord  himself  wept  aver  Jerusalem  when  it  spurned 
his  love.  The  warmer  the  love,  so  much  the  more  sensitively 
is  felt  the  chill  of  thanklessness ;  only  a  taking  refuge  in  the 
love  of  God  can  assuage  this  pang.  But  only  he  is  entitled  to 
thankfulness  whose  love  is  itself  humble  thanks  to  the  loving 
God ;  without  this  the  pretended  right  is  simply  presumptuous 
self-seeking.  The  moral  worth  of  thankfulness  and  the  des- 
picableness  of  thanklessness  are  recognized  even  among  the 
rudest  tribes,  as  in  fact  even  in  brutes  thankfulness  is  mani 
fested  by  brightened  looks ;  and  hence  Christ  represents  this 
duty  as  valid  even  among  the  heathen, — as  instinctively  com 
mending  itself  to  the  natural  consciousness,  and  as  also  prac 
ticed  by  man  in  his  natural  state  [Matt,  v,  46 ;  Luke  vi,  32, 
33 ;  comp.  Exod.  ii,  20 ;  Josh,  vi,  22  sqq. ;  1  Sam.  xv,  6 ;  2 
Kings  v,  16,  23;  Ruth  ii,  10  sqq.;  Luke  xvii,  16;  Acts  xxiv, 
3].  But  only  love  has  a  right  to  thankfulness ;  a  benefit  which 
does  not  flow  from  love,  which  merely  seeks  thankfulness, 
does  not  deserve  thankfulness,  for  it  is  inwardly  false. 

SECTION  CXXVI. 

At  an  equal  stage  of  spiritually-moral  maturity, 
men  are  related  to  each  other  as  mutually-forming 
and  appropriating  each  other  to  a  like  degree ;  but 
the  more  there  is  a  difference  in  this  maturity,  so 
much  the  more  predominates  on  the  part  of  the 


§  126.]  PURE   ETHICS.  263 

morally  higher-developed  the  formative  influencing, 
and  on  the  part  of  others  the  appropriating.  How 
ever,  the  right  and  duty  of  formative  influencing  on 
the  part  of  the  morally  less-developed  never  sinks  to 
zero  ; — even  the  as  yet  morally  immature  inevitably 
exert  a  measure  of  moral  influence  upon  the  morally 
higher-developed  and  upon  the  totality  of  society. 

A  complete  moral  equalization  of  all  men  as  to  their  moral 
influencing  of  others  would  be  an  irrational  reversing  of  all 
moral  order,  a  dissolving  of  all  historical  life  into  unorganized 
individual  units.  Children  never  sustain  to  their  parents  a 
relation  of  perfect  equality ;  their  relation  to  them  is  always 
rather  appropriating  than  formative ;  the  resistance  of  chil 
dren  to  the  higher  moral  validity  of  the  parents  is  regarded 
among  almost  all  nations  as  a  flagrant  outrage,  and  reverence 
for  age  as  a  high  virtue.  But  society  at  large  is  a  moral 
whole,  and  here  also  the  higher-advanced  have  and  exercise 
naturally  a  guiding  and  an  educative  influencing-activity  over 
and  upon  the  others,  and  the  totality  has  a  higher  validity 
than  the  individual.  The  higher-developed  moral  individual 
sustains  to  the  morally-immature  the  right  and  duty  of  edu 
cative  influencing ;  a  perfectly  holy  man  would  enjoy  per  se  a 
right  to  spiritually-moral  dominion  ;  and  for  this  good  reason, 
and  not  simply  in  virtue  of  his  being  the  Son  of  God,  is 
Christ  our  legitimate  Lord.  Nevertheless  the  right  and  duty 
of  moral  forming  never  sinks,  even  in  case  of  the  most  imma 
ture,  to  absolute  nothing  ;  childish  innocence  has  disarmed 
many  an  evil  intent ;  the  direct  impression  of  guileless  confi 
dence,  of  unsuspicion,  strikes  the  malicious  purpose  with 
shame.  The  pious  simplicity  of  the  faith-word  of  a  child  has 
often  proved  a  heart-stirring  awakening  for  vain  wisdom- 
boasting  unbelief. — Also  toward  the  moral  community,  the 
individual  sustains  the  right  and  the  duty  of  moral  influenc 
ing,  though  in  a  normal  development  of  the  community-life 
this  influencing  would  give  place  very  largely  to  appropriat 
ing  ;  moreover  it  varies  according  to  the  varying  social 
stations  of  the  individual. 


264  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§127. 

IV.  THE  MORAL  ACTIVITY  AS  RELATING  TO 
OBJECTIVE  NATURE. 

SECTION  CXXVII. 

(a)  The  moral  -sparing  to  which  nature,  in  virtue 
of  its  essence  as  God's  perfectly  created  work,  and  as 
an  expression  of  the  divine  love  and  wisdom,  has  a 
right,  requires  that  man,  in  the  exercise  of  the  moral 
dominion  over  nature  to  which  he  is  called,  regard 
this,  its  divine  phase,  with  due  respect, — that  he 
avoid  all  purposeless  and  wanton  changing  or  de 
stroying  of  natural  objects,  and  that,  on  the  contrary, 
he  exercise  toward  nature  a  considerate  love,  espe 
cially  in  its  higher  manifestations,  by  preserving 
them  in  their  peculiarity.  The  duty  of  considerate 
sparing  rises  in  proportion  as  the  nature-creature 
comes  into  actual  relation  to  human  life,  and  enters 
into  the  sphere  of  his  moral  activity  as  a  helping 
factor. 

Moral  love  to  nature  is  thankfulness  to  God  who  gave  it  to 
us  for  moral  enjoyment  and  for  moral  dominion ;  to  man,  as 
pure,  God  gave  not  an  uncongenial  and  fear-awakening  na 
ture,  but  a  Paradisaical  nature.  God  loves  nature  as  lie  made 
it,  and  from  its  bosom  God's  creative  love  beams  out  toward 
us,  and  he  has  even  impressed  manifold  natdral  suggestions 
of  the  moral  upon  it  ;  Christ  himself  requires  respect  for 
nature,  for  the  heavens  are  God's  throne  and  the  earth  is  his 
footstool  [Matt,  v,  34,  35],  and  it  is  in  virtue  of  this  religious 
conceiving  of  nature  that  there  can  be  moral  duties  also 
toward  nature  (as  against  Rothe,  JSthik,  1.  ed.,  iii,  §  866). 
With  the  exception  of  the  Indians,  who  adore  nature  as  the 
revealed  divine  essence  itself,  no  people  has  manifested  so 
high  a  respect  for  nature  as  the  Israelites;  the  legislation  of 
the  Old  Testament  surpasses  all  other  systems  in  a  considerate 
sparing  of  nature.  Domestic  animals  especially  are  placed 
under  the  sparing  protection  and  care  of  the  law  [Prov. 


§  127.]  PURE   ETHICS.  265 

xii,  10] ;  the  mouth  of  the  threshing  ox  is  not  to  be  muzzled 
[Deut.  xxv,  4] ;  on  the  Sabbath  cattle,  also  are  given  rest 
Exod.  xx,  10] ;  and  in  the  Sabbatical  year  both  cattle  and 
beasts  are  to  pasture  on  the  fallow  lands  [Exod.  xxiii,  11 ; 
Lev.  xxv,  6,  7,  in  the  original  text] ;  the  beast  of  another 
that  falls  under  its  burden,  or  loses  its  way,  is  to  be  helped 
[Exod.  xxiii,  5;  Deut.  xxii,  1  sqq.  ;  comp.  Matt,  xii,  11]; 
animals  may  not  be  castrated  or  otherwise  maimed  [Lev. 
xxii,  24 ;  even  the  crossing  of  animals  of  different  kinds  is,  in 
high  moral  recognition  of  the  rights  of  nature-creatures,  for 
bidden  [Lev.  xix,  19].  With  the  greates  tenderness  of  feeling, 
a  merely  symbolical  cruelty  is  not  allowed ;  "  thou  shalt  not 
seethe  a  kid  in  its  mother's  milk  "  [Exod.  xxiii,  19 ;  xxxiv, 
26  ;  Deut.  xiv,  21] ;  it  makes  the  impression  of  cruel  mockery 
when  the  milk  which  is  destined  to  nourish  the  young  is 
used  in  connection  with  its  death.  Under  the  same  category 
falls  the  prohibition  of  killing  the  calf,  the  kid,  and  the 
lamb,  on  the  same  day  with  its  mother  [Lev.  xxii,  28], 
and  of  taking  an  incubating  mother-bird  at  the  same  time 
with  the  nest  [Deut.  xxii,  6,  7].  The  touching  account  of 
the  care  of  God  for  the  animals  at  the  time  of  the  deluge,  is 
an  emphatic  illustration  of  the  moral  sparing  of  animals  as 
it  should  be  exercised  by  man ;  God  includes  also  animals  in 
his  covenant  with  Noah,  and  promises  to  spare  them  [Gen. 
ix,  10,  15].  Christ  himself  illustrates  his  own  relation  to  the 
body  of  believers  in  a  gracious  picture  of  a  shepherd  loving 
his  flock  [John  x;  comp.  Matt,  xviii,  12,  13]. 

The  piety-inspired  careful  sparing  of  whatever  contributes 
to  the  nourishment  of  man,  is  so  natural  an  expression  of  the 
moral  consciousness  that  it  prevails  among  almost  all,  and 
even  barbarous,  nations.  Christ  sanctions  this  significant 
carefulness  [John  vi,  12].  This  sparing  has  essentially  a  sym 
bolical  meaning, — is  an  evidencing  of  thankfulness  for  the 
good  gifts  of  God, — a  thankfulness  which  suffers  not  that 
these  gifts  of  love  be  destroyed  in  wanton  thoughtlessness 
and  in  purposeless  waste,  or  contemptuously  thrown  away. 


266  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§128. 

SECTION  CXXVIII. 

(b)  The  moral  appropriating  of  nature  is  either  of  a 
purely  spiritual,  or  of  an  actual  character. — 1.  Spiritu 
al  appropriating  consists,  in  addition  to  the  legitimate 
striving  after  the  highest  possible  knowledge  of 
nature  considered  as  a  manifestation  of  divine  power, 
love  and  wisdom,  mainly  in  the  reflective  contem 
plating  of  nature  in  its  symbolical  suggestiveness  of 
the  moral, — God  having  implanted  in  it  natural 
symbols  of  the  moral. 

The  thoughtful,  moral  contemplating  of  nature  is  at  once 
of  a  pious  and  of  a  poetical  character  ;*  it  is  not  a  mere  play 
of  the  fancy,  it  is  veritable  reality.  Nature  is  not  moral,  but 
it  is  the  work  of  Him  who  is  himself  perfect  morality. 
•Nature  as  created  by  the  holy  God  must  necessarily  reflect 
this  holiness  as  from  a  mirror ;  it  is  the  high  and  mysterious 
charm  of  nature  that  it  is  not  mere  nature,  but  that  every 
where  the  Spirit  whispers  out  of  its  bosom  and  broods  over 
its  expanse.  Nature  reveals  to  us  not  only  God's  creative 
power,  wisdom  and  glory  [Horn,  i,  20;  Job  xxxvii,  sqq. ;  Psa. 
xcvii;  civ;  cxi,  2;  cxlvii,  8  $qq.]J  the  heavens  not  only 
declare  God's  glory  [Psa.  xix,  1  sqq.],  but  also  God's  love  is 
made  known  to  us  in  nature  [Matt,  vi,  26  sqq. ;  Acts  xiv,  17], 
and  the  bow  on  the  clouds  [Gen.  ix,  12  sqq.]  and  the 
bespangled  vault  of  the  skies  are  symbols  of  the  divine  faith 
fulness  [Gen.  xv,  5].  But  the  moral  consciousness  finds  still 
more  than  this;  the  phases  of  beauty  that  are  perceived  in 
nature  are  suggestions  of  spiritual  beauty.  It  is  not  a 
groundless  fancy  when  the  mind  discovers  moral  ideas  sym 
bolically  suggested  even  in  plants ;  we  feel  at  once  the 
kindredness  of  impression  upon  the  sensibilities  that  is  made 
by  a  delicate  rose  and  by  modest  virginity,  by  a  violet  and  by 
childlike  humility,  by  an  oak  and  by  firmness  of  character.  And 
the  fact  that  animals  so  frequently  directly  remind  us  of  human 
moral  qualities,  is  simply  evidence  that  the  holy  creative 

*  Compare :  Zockler,  Theologia  naturalis,  1859. 

f  Eridgewater  Treatises,  vol.  9 ;  Kostlin,  Gott  in  der  Natur,  1851. 


§  129.]  PURE   ETHICS.  267 

Spirit  rules  in  them  and  discovers  to  us;  in  that  which  is 
merely  natural,  embryonic  premonitions  of  the  moral.  The 
ant,  the  bee,  etc.,  are  natural  emblems  of  the  virtue  of  indus 
try  [Prov.  vi,  6] ;  it  is  God  who  causes  them  busily  to  care  for 
a  common  want, — who  works  in  them  in  order  to  speak  to 
man  an  unmistakable  word  of  exhortation  and  instruction. 
The  care  of  birds  for  their  young,  the  fidelity  of  the  dog  and 
of  the  horse,  are  manifestations  of  a  deeply  suggestive  charac 
ter  in  nature.  The  quiet  gentleness  and  the  patient  sufferance 
of  the  lamb  are  applied  as  types  even  to  Christ  |_Isa.  liii,  7 ; 
John  i,  29,  36;  1  Pet.  i,  19;  Rev.  v,  6,  and  elsewhere];  Christ 
himself  uses  the  dove  as  a  symbol  of  uprightness  of  heart 
[Matt,  x,  16].  The  animal-fable  has  something  of  the  mystical 
in  it  and  contains  deep  truth.  The  attractive  and  convicting 
element  thereof  is  this  inner  mysterious  fact,  that  something 
of  the  divine  rules  in  the  animal,  and  looks  out  upon  us, — a 
moral  element  unconsciously  immanent  in  nature  itself;  and 
that  which  appears  in  the  brute  as  a  type  of  human  sin,  is 
more  than  a  mere  fancied  resemblance, — is  in  fact  the  root  of 
that  which  in  man  actually  becomes  sin,  whereas  in  the  animal 
it  is  simply  a  normal  limitedness. 

SECTION  CXXIX. 

(2)  The  actual  appropriating  of  nature-objects  for 
nourishment,  and  thereby  at  the  same  time  for  sens 
uous  enjoyment,  involving  the  destruction  of  living 
natural  objects, — rests  upon  the  moral  right  of  man 
over  nature ;  and  the  limitations  to  the  enjoyment  of 
the  nature-objects  which  serve  for  food,  lie  less  in  the 
nature-objects  themselves  than  in  the  degree  to 
which  they  are  used  and  in  the  moral  state  of  the 
person,  as  also  in  the  thought  of  the  morally-becom 
ing.  Also  the  flesh  of  animals  is  allowed  to  man  for 
food,  and  hence  also  the  killing  of  the  same  for  such 
purposes,  although  in  connection  therewith  all  cru 
elty  and  all  wanton  levity  is  to  be  avoided.  The 
chase  is  moral  only  in  this  sense,  and  not  for  diver- 


268  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§129. 

sion. — As  drink  man  is  permitted  to  use  not  only 
the  strictly  natural  fluids,  but  also  such  as  are  pre 
pared  by  skill,  including  the  vinous;  it  is  simply 
their  misuse  for  inebriation  that  is  immoral. 

What  things  are  per  se  appropriate  as  means  of  nourishment, 
is  not  a  moral  but  a  physiological  question.  Although  for  the 
state  of  sinfulness,  the  disciplinary  law  of  God  required  man 
also  in  this  sphere  to  distinguish  between  clean  and  unclean, 
and  forbade  to  him  a  number  of  per  se  appropriate  means  of 
nourishment,  still  this  law  of  limiting  discipline  had  no  valid 
ity  for  humanity  while  as  yet  unstained  by  sin.  Here  are 
applicable  the  words  of  Christ:  "Not  that  which  goeth  into 
the  mouth  defileth  a  man"  [Matt,  xv,  11;  comp.  Titus  i,  15; 
Acts  x,  15;  Rom.  xiv,  1  sqq.  20;  1  Cor.  x,  25  sqq.].  It  is  not 
the  object  per  se  that  renders  an  article  of  food  sinful,  but  the 
disposition  of  the  eater,  the  manner  of  enjoying  it, — namely, 
when  one  forgets  God  in  the  sensuous,  forgets  his  own  moral 
dignity  in  the  pleasure,  aims  not  at  the  satisfying  of  the  want, 
but  only  at  the  enjoyment,  and  does  not  observe  the  measure 
prescribed  by  the  purpose  of  nourishment. 

The  admissibility  of  flesh-food,  though  very  clear  from  a 
physiological  stand-point,  has  yet  been  contested  from  a 
moral  point  of  view.  Asceticism  has  in  all  ages  laid  great 
stress  on  abstinence  from  flesh ;  the  Indians  reject  flesh-food 
unconditionally,  inasmuch  as,  in  consequence  of  their  Panthe 
istic  philosophy,  they  regard  the  slaughtering  of  animals, 
otherwise  than  for  sacrifice,  as  a  blasphemous  outrage.*  The 
Manichees  (and  Essenes  ?)  abstained  likewise  from  all  flesh. 
The  rejection  of  flesh-food  in  seasons  of  fasting  has  less  an 
objective  than  an  inner  ground.  According  to  St.  Jerome 
flesh  and  wine  were  originally  not  allowed,  and  were  first  per 
mitted  after  the  deluge,  but  they  are  not  permissible  under 
Christianity.!  Paul  mentions  similar  views  [Rom.  xiv,  2]. 
Jehovah  expressly  conceded  to  man  after  the  deluge  also  ani 
mals  for  food  [Gen.  ix,  3],  whereas  in  the  blessing  after  crea- 

*  See  Wuttke's  Gesch.  des  Heid&nt,  II, p.  466  sqq. 
t  Ep.  T9  ad  Salvin.,  /,  p.  500  /  ed  Vattars. ;  adv.  Jovinian.,  t,  7,  pp. 
267,  842. 


§129.]  PURE   ETHICS.  269 

tion  [Gen.  i,  29]  there  is  mention  only  of  plants  as  food ;  from 
this  circumstance  some  have  inferred  that,  previously,  flesh- 
food  was  not  in  fact  allowed ;  but  we  find  no  trace  of  a  pre 
vious  prohibition,  and  we  can  discover  no  reason  for  a  change ; 
rather  would  there  lie  in  the  progressive  corruption  of  man 
kind  a  reason  for  a  limiting  of  former  rights ;  God's  direction 
to  Noah  has  in  fact  all  the  appearance  of  an  express  confirma 
tion  of  a  former  right ;  and  the  privilege  conferred  at  creation, 
of  ruling  over  the  fish  of  the  sea,  etc.,  would  hardly  have  any 
significance  if  it  did  not  also  include  the  right  to  eat  them.  Abel 
brought  offerings  of  the  firstlings  of  his  flock  and  of  their  fat 
[Gen.  iv,  4] ;  now  as  it  was  uniformly  that  which  was  most 
precious  to  man  that  was  offered  as  a  sacrifice,  hence  it  is 
probable  that  flocks  were  kept  also  for  the  sake  of  flesh-food, 
to  which  in  fact  the  "coats  of  skins"  [Gen.  iii,  21]  seems  to 
allude.  Were  flesh-food  simply  a  concession  to  sinfulness, 
which  in  fact  would  have  no  comprehensible  reason,  it  would 
certainly  not  be  prescribed  in  connection  with  the  Passover 
and  with  sacrifices,  and  above  all  Christ  himself  would  have 
abstained  from  it,  whereas  we  know  that  the  contrary  was  the 
case  [Matt,  xi,  19;  comp.  Mark  ii,  19;  John  ii,  2  sqq. ;  Matt, 
xxvi,  17  sqq.].  Paul  declares  abstinence  from  flesh  as  a  weak 
ness  of  faith  [Rom.  xiv,  2 ;  comp.  21 ;  1  Cor.  x,  25] ;  to  Peter 
animals  are  expressly  offered  in  a  vision  for  food  [Acts  11  sqq.], 
and  animals  are  spoken  of  as  destined  to  be  slaughtered 
[2  Pet.  ii,  12 ;  Deut.  xii,  15,  20].  It  is  true  man  can  live  without 
flesh,  and  he  certainly  has  reason  not  needlessly  and  out  of 
mere  wantonness  to  multiply  the  destruction  of  animals ;  still, 
however,  as  it  is  grounded  in  the  very  constitution  of  nature 
that  animals  serve  for  food  to  each  other,  hence  it  must  be 
allowable  also  for  man  to  take  food  for  himself  out  of  the 
animal  kingdom.  And  should  there  seem  to  lie  in  the  killing 
of  an  animal  something  inconsistent  with  the  original  peace 
between  man  and  nature,  and  with  man's  instinctive  feelings, 
and  should  it  be  inferred  therefrom  that  it  is  only  the  chang 
ing  of  the  original  relation  of  things,  as  alluded  to  in  the 
blessing  upon  Noah,  that  rendered  flesh-food  morally  possible, 
— still  the  force  of  this  difficulty  will  vanish  so  soon  as  we 
reflect  upon  the  very  ancient,  pious,  and  significant  custom, — 
wide-spread  even  among  heathen  nations  and  suggested  in  the 


270  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  f§  129. 

laws  of  Moses  [Lev.  xvii,  3  sqq.], — namely,  of  slaying  the  nobler 
animals  in  general  only  for  purposes  of  sacrifice,  and  of  receiv 
ing  back  the  flesh,  thus  consecrated  to  the  Deity,  only  out  of 
His  own  hand.  In  regard  to  the  primitive  usage  it  is  most 
probable,  therefore,  that  before  the  deluge  the  devout  children 
of  God  partook  indeed  of  flesh-food,  but  only  of  animals 
offered  in  sacrifice,  and  that  too  only  seldom,  as  indeed  pastor 
al  people  in  general  use  but  little  flesh-food.  Noah  might,  in 
view  of  the  sensuality  of  the  perished  world,  have  doubted  the 
propriety  of  flesh-food,  and  hence  God  sanctions  it  expressly. 
It  is  indeed  not  to  be  denied  that  in  the  practice  of  the 
slaying  of  animals  in  general  there  lies  a  moral  danger ;  it 
tends  to  blunt  our  feelings  of  natural  compassion ;  and  it  is 
not  a  mere  morbid  sensibility,  that  makes  it  repugnant  to 
some  persons,  e.  g.,  to  wring  off  the  head  of  a  dove;  moreover 
it  is  a  well-known  fact  that  those  who  are  engaged  for  the 
most  part  in  the  slaughtering  of  animals  are  liable  to  become 
hardened  and  cruel;  it  does  not  follow  from  this,  however, 
that  the  slaughtering  of  animals  for  food  is  per  se  wrong,  but 
only  that  the  manner  of  the  slaughtering  is  not  a  matter  of 
indifference, — that  it  should  be  done  with  the  least  possible 
suffering,  and  that  not  every  animal  is  equally  appropriate 
therefor.  It  is  in  fact  repugnant  to  our  moral  feelings  to 
slaughter  such  domestic  animals  as  by  their  fidelity  to  and 
fondness  for  us,  have  become  in  some  respect  our  home-com 
panions;  it  has  the  look  of  treachery  on  the  part  of  man, — 
of  a  betrayal  of  the  confidence  which  the  animal  had  placed 
in  him,  in  a  word,  of  a  breach  of  faith.  The  iron  necessity 
of  our  evil-fraught  actual  condition  may  excuse  it ;  but  it  is 
surely  not  the  proper  relation  of  things ;  and  the  fact  that  the 
general  feeling  of  almost  all  cultured  nations  has  a  horror  of 
the  butchering  of  dogs  and  horses,  man's  most  faithful  com 
panions,  has  its  foundation  surely  not  in  any  notion  of  the  un- 
wholesoineness  of  their  flesh,  but  in  a  very  legitimate  moral 
feeling, — a  feeling  the  disregarding  of  which  is  no  mark  of  a 
special  refinement  of  culture.  Much  more  natural,  and  less 
questionably  morally,  is  the  killing  of  wild  animals,  and  of 
such  animals  of  the  flock  as  have,  not  as  yet  stood  to  man  in 
a  close  relation  of  confidence.  We  cannot  here  as  yet  discuss 
in  full  the  subjects  of  food  and  drink. 


§130.]  PURE   ETHICS.  271 

SECTION   CXXX. 

(c)  The  formative  working  upon  nature,  the  shaping 
of  it  into  an  organ  for  man,  is  at  the  same  time  also 
an  exalting  of  nature  into  the  service  of  the  moral 
life,  and  hence  a  forming  of  it  into  an  expression  of 
the  human  spirit, — an  educating  of  nature  whereby 
it  is  raised  above  its  immediate  naturalness,  and  is 
made  to  receive  the  impress  of  human  action,  of  spir 
itual  discipline.  Man  ennobles,  spiritualizes,  nature, 
and  makes  it  into  his  spiritual  possession,  into  his 
freely-formed  home, — and  in  forming  nature  he  ap 
propriates  it  at  the  same  time  to  himself. 

If  the  dominating  of  man  over  nature, — to  which  God  ex 
pressly  called  the  first  man  [Gen.  i,  28 ;  Psa.  viii],  and  which 
still  holds  good  in  a  somewhat  modified  manner  even  in  the 
state  of  sinfulness  [Gen.  ix,  2,  3],  and  which  is  promised 
again  in  the  fullest  degree  for  the  yet  to  be  recovered  perfect 
state  [Isa.  xi,  6  sqq.], — is  not  to  be  regarded  as  a  mere  figure 
of  speech,  then  it  must  also  imply  a  forming  of  the  same. 
Man  forms  nature  into  an  obedient  instrument  of  the  spirit, 
and  gives  to  it  a  spiritual,  historical  impress.  Nature,  in  its 
wild  state,  stands  to  man  in  an  unhornelike,  not  to  say  hostile 
relation, — it  is  only  in  its  form  as  shaped  and  disciplined  by 
his  skill  that  he  feels  at  home.  God  gave  nature  to  man  as  a 
theater  for  his  moral  activity,  but  man  is  not  at  liberty  simply 
to  sport  with  it,  simply  to  admire  and  enjoy  it, — he  should 
really  rule  over  it;  but  all  ruling  is  at  the  same  time  an 
appropriating  and  a  forming.  Man  is  to  make  of  nature 
something  which  as  yet  it  is  not, — is  himself  to  form  it  into  a 
spiritually-molded  home  for  himself.  This  forming  of  na 
ture  is  either  a  forming  of  it  into  a  useful  object  for  the  indi 
vidual,  and  hence  in  the  service  of  labor  (§  109),  or  a  forming 
of  it  into  an  image  of  the  spirit,  into  a  thing  of  beauty,  into 
&  work  of  art  (§  110).  A  hill-side  cavern  is  not  a  dwelling- 
place  for  man;  his  home-protection,  he  must  construct  for 
himself.  If  even  the  bird  builds  its  nest  in  a  way  of  its  own, 


272  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  130. 

so  that  itr  bears  an  impress  peculiar  to  the  bird,  how  much 
more  must  man  spiritually  shape  nature  into  a  home  for  him 
self !  Of  course  the  forming  of  nature  does  not  consist  in  an 
abuse  of  it, — e.  <?.,  in  a  forcing  of  trees  to  be  square,  in  crop 
ping  the  tails  of  horses  and  the  ears  of  dogs, — but  in  the 
further  development  of  the  natural  beauty  and  perfection 
already  existing  m  nature.  The  cultivated  rose  is  more 
beautiful  than  the  wild  one;  the  improved  fruit  tree  is  bet 
ter  in  many  respects  than  the  wild-growing  one;  the  domes 
ticated  animals  have  become  in  many  respects  quite  other  and 
mpre  perfect  creatures  than  they  were  in  their  wild  state ; 
they  have  attained  not  only  to  higher  soul-capacities,  but  also 
to  a  nobler  and  stronger  physique ;  the  wild  dog  and  the 
wild  horse  cannot  in  any  respect  bear  favorable  comparison 
with  those  which  have  been  cultivated  by  man.  The  fidelity 
of  these  creatures, — which  indeed  they  show  almost  exclu 
sively  toward  man,  to  whom  they  attach  themselves  much 
more  closely  and  affectionately  than  to  their  own  kind, — is  an 
evidence  of  the  normal  dominion  of  spirit  over  nature,  and  a 
positive  ennobling,  and  is  the  thankfulness  of  the  animal  for 
its  culture. 

The  task  of  overcoming  the  wild  forces  of  nature  that 
stand  in  the  way  of  individual  human  life,  and  of  subjecting 
them  to  the  discipline  of  the  spirit,  is  a  powerful  stimulus  to 
moral  activity;  and  they  are  in  fact,  in  virtue  of  the  divine 
creative  plan,  perfectly  overcomable  by  the  rational  spirit, — 
if  not  always  by  the  individual,  yet  at  least  by  the  collective, 
spirit.  Though  it  is  not  true  that  all  nature-objects  exist 
merely  for  the  outward  use  of  man,  nevertheless  they  are  in 
fact  for  man,  in  a  still  higher  sense, — for  his  moral  delight, 
for  spiritual  enjoyment,  for  the  service  of  the  moral  life. 
The  dominion  and  discipline  which  man  can  and  should 
exercise  over  the  animal  world,  does  not  in  the  original  pur 
pose  imply  that  he  is  to  surround  himself  in  his  domestic  life 
with  animals  of  every  sort,  but  it  does  imply  that  lie  ought 
not  (as,  however,  has  actually  taken  place)  to  acknowledge 
them  as  a  power  over  against  himself,  and  before  which  he  has 
to  tremble,  and  against  which  he  can  secure  himself  only  by 
strategy  and  deadly  violence;  on  the  contrary,  he  should  rise 
to  a  consciousness  of  his  all-sufficient  dominating  power  over 


PURE   ETHICS.  273 

them ;  but  to  destroy  is  not  to  dominate.  That  nature-creat 
ures  should  become  to  man  a  torment,  a  plague,  a  death- 
bringing  danger,  and  that  man  in  the  interest  of  his  self- 
preservation  should  have  to  carry  on  a  war  of  extermination 
against  a  large  portion  of  them, — all  this  is,  according  to  the 
Scripture  view,  a  consequence  of  the  disturbance  of  the  har 
mony  of  creation ;  hence,  as  it  is  a  result  of  sin,  we  cannot 
as  yet,  here,  treat  of  it.  Even  in  the  fallen  state,  however, 
we  can  still  discover  clear  traces  of  the  true  relation  of 
things ;  even  the  lion  and  the  tiger  cannot  bear  the  steady, 
fearless  look  of  man.  and  they  throw  off  their  natural  awe  of 
man  only  after  having  tasted  of  human  blood.  Man  can  and 
may,  however,  actually  realize  his  dominion  over  nature,  only 
when  he  permits  himself  to  be  ruled  over  by  the  holy  Origi 
nator  and  Lord  of  nature. 
VOL.  11—19 


274  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  131 


CHAPTER  VI. 

THE  FRUIT  OF  THE  MORAL  LIFE  AS  MORAL  END. 
SECTION  CXXXI. 

The  end  of  moral  action,  as  willed  by  man  as 
moral,  is  identical  with  the  end  of  God  in  man's 
creation  ;  in  this  action  man  wills  perfectly  to  realize 
in  himself  the  image  of  God, — to  develop  himself  in 
reality  as  a  good  being,  and  thereby  to  realize  the  good 
in  general.  In  so  far  as  the  good  is  a  fruit  of  moral 
action,  it  is  not  a  something  exterior  to  man,  but 
inheres  in  him, — is  his  possession,  which,  as  incor 
porated  into  the  morally-formed  essence  of  man  him 
self,  and  as  thenceforth  inseparable  from  him,  is  a 
property  or  quality  of  his  person.  In  so  far  as  the 
good  is  the  property  of  man,  it  is  his  moral  estate. 
Hence,  as  the  end  of  the  moral  activity  in  general  is 
the  good,  so  is  this  end,  for  the  moral  man  himself, 
the  good  as  having  become  a  moral  estate. 

The  world  is,  with  its  mere  creation,  not  as  yet  complete, 
but  is  charged  with  a  task  which  is  to  be  carried  out  by  moral 
creatures  themselves.  Though  it  is  true  that  all  good  is  from 
God,  still  all  good  is  not  from  Him  immediately ;  but  in 
man's  case  it  arises  through  the  free  developing  of  that  which 
was  directly  created.  Man  is  himself  to  create  good ;  though 
as  a  creature  he  is  good,  yet  he  is  not  good  in  such  a  manner 
as  he  is  to  become  so ;  the  image  of  God  becomes  complete  in 
him  only  through  his  own  moral  activity ;  and  he  makes  into 
a  good  entity  not  only  himself,  but  also  the  world  that  comes 
into  contact  writh  him, — he  creates  a  spiritual  historical  world 
which  is  itself  good.  To  this  good  as  created  by  himself  he 
sustains  quite  other  relations  than  to  that  which  is  directly 
given  to  him  in  his  natural  existence.  To  the  first  man  much 


§132.]  PURE   ETHICS.  275 

good  was  given,  to  which  he  had  a  right,  and  which  he  could 
call  his  own.  This  good,  however,  was  simply  placed  upon 
him, — was  as  yet  external  to  him,  and  not  as  yet  identified 
with  his  spiritual  being ;  he  indeed  possessed  it,  but  it  was  not 
yet  his  property, — was  not  a  quality  of  his.  All  that  I  have  in 
my  power,  upon  which  I  have  an  actual  claim,  is  my  posses 
sion.  But  the  idea  of  property  is  higher ;  only  that  is  my 
property  which  by  moral  action  I  have  appropriated  to  myself, 
and  which  consequently  essentially  belongs  to  my  personal  life- 
sphere,  as  my  free  personal  acquisition.  A  merely  inherited 
property  or  power  is  morally  a  mere  possession,  while  an 
estate  or  power  that  is  acquired  by  labor  or  is  morally  devel 
oped,  is  a  property ;  in  it  1  have  invested  my  labor,  my  soul, 
my  will,— it  inheres  in  me  and  in  my  self-created  life-sphere, 
— is  my  enlarged  personality  itself.  Hence  property  has 
always  a  moral  element  in  it, — is  moral  fruit,  is  an  acquisition. 
In  the  case  of  the  first  human  beings,  the  possession  of  Eden 
would  have  become  a  property,  only  in  virtue  of  their  cultivat 
ing  and  caring  for  it.  A  moral  property  is  inalienable ;  it  may, 
as,  for  example,  in  the  case  of  a  work  of  art,  come  into  the 
possession  of  another,  but  it  remains  the  spiritual  property  of 
its  author.  A  slave  is  the  possession  of  his  master ;  but  con 
sorts  not  only  possess  each  other, — they  appertain  to  each 
other, — each  is  the  property-of  the  other.  Thus  in  so  far  as 
the  good  becomes  and  is  a  property,  it  is  a  good,  a  moral 
estate, — and  hence  it  is  such  only  as  a  fruit  of  moral  action. 
The  good  as  an  outward  possession  may  be  lost;  but  when 
exalted  into  a  moral  property,  it  is  permanent ;  to  this  Christ 
alludes  when  he  says :  "  Lay  not  up  for  yourselves  treasures 
upon  earth,"  etc.  [Matt,  vi,  19,  20]. 

SECTION  CXXXII. 

The  good  to  be  attained  to  by  moral  action  is, 
that  perfection  which  answers  to  the  divine  crea 
tive  intention, — on.  the  one  hand,  the  perfection  ot 
the  individual  person,  and,  on  the  other,  that  of 
the  moral  community ;  that  is,  it  is  in  part  a 
personal,  and  in  part  a  common  good.  The  two 


276  .  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  132. 

forms  mutually  condition  each  other,  and  stand 
with  each  other  in  constant  arid  closest  relation  ;  but 
both  are  further  conditioned  on  the  moral  commun 
ion  with  God  which  is  aimed  at  by  the  moral  activ 
ity,  and  which  is  the  highest  moral  goal  as  well  as 
the  ground  and  essence  of  all  creature-perfection  in 
general ;  for  God  alone  is  the  eternally-perfect  good. 
The  real  moral  life-communion  with  God,  as  dis 
tinguished  from  the  merely  natural,  is  consequently 
the  absolute  good,  and  hence  the  highest  good, — that 
which  is  the  source  and  condition  of  all  other  goods. 
In  so  far  as  individual  man  has  the  highest  good  as 
his  moral  property,  he  is  a  child  of  God  ;  in  so  far 
as  the  moral  community  has  this  good  inherent  in 
itself,  it  is  the  kingdom  of  God,  which  rests  on  the 
God-sonship  of  its  individual  members. 

The  thought  of  a  moral  communion,  and  hence  also  of  a 
moral  common-good,  is  met  with  also  in  the  extra-Christian 
world;  the  Republic  of  Plato  was  meant  to  embody  it.  But 
where  the  common  ground  of  the  personal  good  as  well  as  of 
the  common  good,  namely,  communion  with  God,  is  lacking, 
there  this  thought  is  realizable  only  as  a  sum  total  of  single 
goods,  or  only  by  the  all-dominating  despotism  of  the  com 
munity-organism  over  the  individuals,  as  in  the  system  of 
Plato.  A  vital  union  of  the  two  forms  of  good  is  effected 
only  by  the  Christian  God-consciousness.  Some  form  of  com 
munion  with  God  is  enjoyed  by  every  creature  as  such ;  this, 
however,  is  of  a  merely  natural  character,  and.  needs,  in  the 
case  of  rational  creatures,  to  be  exalted  to  a  moral  character. 
As  coming  from  the  hands  of  nature  man  is  not  the  child  of 
God ;  he  becomes  truly  such  only  by  free  moral  love  to  God. 

The  question  as  to  the  highest  good, — for  the  heathen  diffi 
cult  and  in  fact  not  truly  solvable  at  all, — is,  from  an  evan 
gelically-moral  stand-point,  readily  answerable.  There  is 
absolutely  no  good  realizable  or  actually  realized  without 
standing  in  relation  to  God,  without  springing  from  God  as 
its  source,  and  hence  none  for  man  without  personal  life-corn- 


§133.]  PURE   ETHICS.  277 

munion  with  God  [  John  xvii,  21 ;  1  John  i,  3 ;  ii,  5,  6]  who  is  the 
perfectly  good  One  in  an  absolute  sense  [Matt,  xix,  17] ;  only 
he  has  the  highest  good  who  is  rich  toward  God  [Luke  xii, 
21 ;  Psa.  Ixxiii,  25],  and  who  has  everlasting  treasures  in 
heaven  [Matt,  vi,  20;  1  Tim.  vi,  19].  While  heathen  phi 
losophers  grope  about  in  uncertainty  as  to  the  highest  good, 
Jehovah  reveals  it  in  all  simplicity  and  definiteness  to  the 
patriarch  Abraham  at  a  time  when  he  was  wavering  in  faith 
as  to  the  fulfillment  of  the  prophecies  made  to  him, — reveals  it 
in  these  words:  "I  am  thy  exceeding  great  reward"  [Gen.  xv, 
1], — thou  canst  aim  at  and  attain  to  nothing  higher;  and  the 
highest  blessing  of  the  Old  Testament  is  the  ' '  peace  of  God  " 
[Num.  vi,  26;  Psa.  xxix,  11].  This  highest  good  man  cannot 
have  as  a  merely  outward  possession,  as  a  mere  gift, — he  can 
not  have  it  from  nature,  but  only  as  a  morally-acquired 
property;  even  under  the  economy  of  redemption  from  sin, 
where  not  merit  but  grace  prevails,  faith  which  is  in  fact  a 
moral  work — is  the  necessary  condition.  The  idea  of  a  king 
dom  of  God, — unknown  throughout  heathendom,  but  prepared 
for  and  anticipated  in  the  Old  Testament,  and  realized  in 
Christianity, — presents  the  moral  community  as  in  full  pos 
session  of  the  highest  good,  which  now  becomes,  in  turn,  for 
the  individual  members  (by  whom  it  is  enjoyed  as  God-son- 
ship)  the  source  of  higher  moral  perfection.  In  virtue  of 
life-communion  with  God  the  highest  good  bears  the  stamp  of 
eternity,  in  the  sense  of  endless  duration ;  the  life  of  the 
children  of  God  is  an  everlasting  life  [Matt,  xix,  16,  17,  29 ; 
xxv,  46;  John  xvii,  3;  1  John  ii,  25,  and  other  texts],  and 
the  kingdom  of  God  is  an  everlasting  kingdom. 


I.  THE  PERSONAL  PERFECTION  OF  THE  INDIVIDUAL 
AS  THE  END  OF  THE  MORAL  ACTIVITY. 

SECTION  CXXXIII. 

The  personal  perfection  of  the  individual  person  is 
the  realization  and  visualization  of  God-sonship,  that 
is,  of  the  idea  of  man,  and  of  the  creative  will  of  God 
as  to  man.  The  moral  goal  set  before  man,  namely, 


278  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  134. 

the  all-sided  personal  perfection  of  the  human  life- 
powers  and  of  their  manifestation,  is,  as  a  fruit  of 
the  collective  moral  activity,  never  fully  and  defini 
tively  realized  during  the  temporal  life,  but  is  involved 
in  constant  progress,  though  at  every  stage  of  the 
truly  moral  life  it  is  in  fact  relatively  realized. 

To  be  perfect  is  neither  an  improper  nor  an  impossible 
requirement  upon  man ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  expressly  pre 
sented  by  Christ  and  the  apostles  as  the  moral  goal :  "Be  ye 
therefore  perfect  (r&eioi)  even  as  your  Father  which  is  in 
heaven  is  perfect"  [Matt,  v,  48];  "if  thou  wilt  be  perfect, 
follow  me"  [xix,  21 ;  Luke  vi,  40;  1  Cor.  ii,  G;  xiv,  20;  Eph. 
iv,  13 ;  Col.  i,  28 ;  2  Tim.  iii,  17 ;  Ileb.  v,  14 ;  James  iii,  2] ;  the 
term  refaiof  implies  the  contents  of  TfAof,  that  is,  the  purpose 
and  goal  of  the  moral  life.  This  perfection  of  the  creature  is 
indeed,  as  compared  with  the  divine  perfection,  of  a  limited 
character;  such  as  it  is,  however,  it  really  exists,  in  every  case 
of  normal  development,  from  the  very  first  moment  on,  and  it 
steadily  advances,  keeping  pace  with  every  stage  of  the  life- 
development.  Christ  himself,  even  as  a  child,  is  presented  as 
a  pattern,  while  as  yet  he  was  increasing  in  wisdom  and  in 
favor  with  God  and  man;  that  is,  he  was  even  as  a  child  per 
fect,  though  this  perfection  was  not  yet  that  of  the  full  man's- 
age  of  Christ  [Eph.  iv,  13].  Every  moral  being  should  and 
can  be  relatively  perfect  at  every  moment  of  its  life;  even 
the  child  is  to  be  so  in  the  manner  of  a  child  [1  Cor.  xiii,  11] ; 
and  the  final  and  true  perfection  is  not  a  merely  conceived 
and  never-to-be-realized  goal,  for  such  would  not  be  a  goal  at 
all,  but  it  can  in  fact  and  should  actually  be  realized  by  each 
and  all.  Christ  as  the  son  of  man  really  reached  this  goal, 
and  all  who  belong  to  him  have,  in  virtue  of  their  God-son- 
ship,  both  the  duty  and  the  possibility  of  attaining  to  it  [Phil. 
iii,  12,  15;  1  Cor.  xiii,  10]. 

SECTION  CXXXIV. 

All  moral  attainments,  and  hence  all  the  elements 
and  forms  of  perfection  or  of  the  true  good,  are  a 
moral  possession,  and  hence  a  property.  Every  pos- 


§134]  PURE  ETHICS.  279 

session  is  an  enlargement  of  the  existence,  the  power 
and  the  life-sphere  of  the  moral  person,  in  virtue  of 
moral  appropriation, — is  a  breaking  down  of  the 
limits  of  the  original  individuality,  a  uniting  of  the 
isolated  existence  witli  the  life  of  the  whole.  Cor 
responding  to  the  distinction  between  special  and 
general  appropriating  (§  104),  and,  from  another 
point  of  view,  to  that  between  natural  and  spiritual 
appropriating  (§  101),  the  possession  acquired  by 
moral  appropriating  (which  is  at  the  same  time  nec 
essarily  also  a  forming)  is,  on  the  one  hand,  partly  of  a 
more  external  character, — bearing  upon  the  individ 
ual  as  such  and  widening  his  life-sphere,  and  hence, 
as  relating  to  others,  of  an  exclusive  character, — and, 
on  the  other,  in  part  of  a  more  inward,  spiritual  and, 
in  so  far,  riot  merely  personal,  character,  but,  on  the 
contrary,  promotive  of  communion. 

(a)  The  outward  possession — legal  property,  tem 
poral  means — is,  as  the  fruit  of  moral  labor,  a  real 
and  legitimate  good,  and  hence  also  a  legitimate  end 
of  moral  effort,  though  it  becomes  at  once  sinful 
when  it  is  made  the  end  per  se,  the  highest  good 
itself,  when  it  is  placed  above  the  inward  possession 
and  not  rather  vitally  united  with  it,  when  the  effort 
for  it  aims  merely  at  the  enjoyment  and  not  also  at 
the  moral  culture  and  the  moral  communion  natural 
ly  involved  in  it,— when  it  does  not  become  a  channel 
of  communicative  love. 

If  appropriating  is  per  se  a  moral  activity,  then  is  also  the 
striving  after  temporal  possessions  not  only  a  right  but  also  a 
duty.  Possessions  distinguish  man  from  the  brute,  and  civil 
ized  man  from  the  savage ;  the  Diogenic  form  of  wisdom  is 
by  no  means  very  profound.  Labor  finds  in  possessions  its 
normal  fruit ;  possessions  are  labor  as  having  become  reality ' 


280  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  135. 

The  brute  is  possessionless  because  he  does  not  labor.  In  prop 
erty  man  ceases  to  be  a  mere  isolated  individual  of  his  spe 
cies  ;  he  creates  for  himself  a  world  about  himself  which  he 
can  call  his  own ;  his  property  is  the  outward  manifestation 
of  his  inward  peculiarity.  The  fact  that  he  who  possesses 
much  is  also  much  regarded  and  esteemed  in  the  world,  is, 
indeed,  often  very  hollow  and  baseless,  though  in  reality  it 
springs  from  the  per  se  correct  consciousness  that  possessions 
are  the  fruit  of  labor, — the  result  of  moral  effort.  He  who 
acquires  nothing  for  himself  passes  in  the  world,  not  without 
reason,  for  unrespectable.  Of  a  special  virtue  of  possession- 
despising,  as  with  the  mendicant  monks,  there  can,  in  the 
ante-sinful  state,  be  no  question ;  and  even  after  the  fall,  pos 
sessions  are  presented  as  a  perfectly  legitimate  end  of  moral 
effort,  and  their  being  increased  as  a  special  divine  blessing. 
Cain  and  Abel  possess  already  personal  property ;  and  the 
God-blessed  possessions  of  the  patriarchs  occupy  a  very  large 
place  in  their  morally-religious  life  [Gen.  xii.  5,  16 ;  xiii,  2 ; 
xiv,  14;  xxiv,  22,  35,  53;  xxvi,  13,  14;  xxvii,  28;  xxx,  27, 
30,  43;  xxxi,  42;  xxxii,  5,  10,  13  sqq.;  xxxiii,  11;  xxxix, 
5 ;  xlix,  25  ;  Exod.  xxiii,  25 ;  Lev.  xxv,  21 ;  Deut.  ii,  7 ;  vii,  13 ; 
xv,  14  sqq. ;  xvi,  15,  17 ;  xxviii,  3  sqq.  ;  xxxiii,  13  sqq.  ;  xxiv, 
25;  comp.  1  Kings  iii,  13;  Psa:  cvii,  38;  cxii,  2,  3;  cxxxii,  15]. 
Property  being  the  enlarged  life-sphere  of  the  moral  per 
son, — in  some  sense  his  enlarged  personality  itself, — the  moral 
phase  thereof  lies  not  merely  in  its  antecedent  ground,  name 
ly,  labor,  but  also  in  its  moral  use  and  application.  To  its 
enjoyment  man  lias  a  moral  right,  as  such  enjoyment  is  the 
reward  of  labor;  but  to  the  exclusive  enjoyment  of  it  for 
himself  alone  he  has  no  moral  right,  seeing  that  he  is  bound 
to  other  men  by  love,  and  love  manifests  itself  in  communi 
cative  distribution. 

SECTION   CXXXV. 

(J)  The  inner'  possession,  namely,  the  perfection  of 
the  personality  itself  in  its  essence  and  life, — perfectly 
realized  in  the  person  of  the  Son  of  man  alone, — is, 

(1)  The  perfection  of  knowledge,  namely,  wisdom; 
that  is,  that  all-sided  knowledge  of  God  which  rests 


§  135.]  PURE   ETHICS.  281 

on  a  true  love  of  God,  and  winch  in  virtue  of  moral 
effort  has  become  a  true  property  of  the  person,  and 
which  consequently  also  constitutes  a  life-power  de 
terminative  in  turn  of  the  moral  life  itself, — and 
hence  involving  also  a  knowledge  of  the  being,  es 
sence,  and  end  of  created  reality,  especially  also  of 
one's  own  life  (§§  60,  104).  As  influencing  the  moral 
life,  wisdom  is  necessarily  also  practical ;  and  as 
taking  into  view  the  actual  circumstances  of  exist 
ence  and  their  application  to  the  moral  end,  it  as 
sumes  the  form  of  prudence. 

Wisdom  is  presented  in  the  Scriptures  as  the  first  and  most 
essential  element  of  the  highest  good,  and  in  fact  always  under 
its  two  phases,  as  a  knowledge  of  the  truth,  and  as  power  to 
fulfill  it.  It  is  not  a  mere  knowledge  in  which  man  forgets 
himself  in  the  object,  not  mere  science,  but  a  knowledge 
which  merges  the  person  himself  into  the  life  of  the  truth, — 
which  fills  the  soul  with  vital,  life-creating  truth.  The  object 
of  wisdom  is  not  this  or  that  particular  truth,  but  the  truth, — 
is  the  self-consistent  complete  whole.  Knowledge  is  not  yet 
wisdom ;  with  scantier  knowledge  there  may  be  more  wisdom 
than  with  a  richer  knowledge ;  a  much-knowing  one  may  even 
be  a  great  fool.  "Wisdom  is  essentially  not  world-science  but 
God-science ;  it  is,  as  a  manifestation  of  God-sonship,  never 
without  a  life  in  God, — is  in  its  essence  piety ;  without  God- 
knowledge  and  God-fearing  there  can  be  only  folly  [Psa. 
cxi,  10;  xxv,  14;  Job  xxviii,  28;  Prov.  i,  7;  ix,  10].  Wisdom 
is  more  than  knowledge  and  science,  inasmuch  as  it  always 
aims  at  unity,  at  the  central  point,  at  the  whole, — always 
unites  the  person  himself  with  God  and  with  the  All,  both 
cognoscitively  and  actively ;  it  is  moral  knowing.  Its  essence 
consists  not  in  the  compass  and  in  the  fullness  of  the  knowl 
edge,  but  in  the  harmony,  the  true  foundation,  the  truth  and 
the  moral  potency  of  that  which  is  known.  There  is  no  wis 
dom,  therefore,  without  constant  moral  effort ;  but  also  none 
which  does  not  itself  produce  a  moral  life.  Such  wisdom  is 
presented  as  the  most  essential  element  of  the  highest  good, 


282  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  135. 

and  to  acquire  it,  as  a  high  duty  [Prov.  ii,  2  sqq.  ;  iv,  5  sqq.  ; 
viii,  11 ;  xvi,  16 ;  xxiii,  23 ;  John  viii,  32 ;  xvii,  3 ;  Acts  xvii,  27 ; 
Rom.  xii,  2;  xvi,  19;  1  Cor.  xiv,  20;  Eph.  i,  18;  iii,  18;  iv,  13; 
v,  10,  17 ;  Phil,  i,  9,  10 ;  iii,  8 ;  iv,  8,  9 ;  Col.  i,  9,  11 ;  iii,  10,  16 ; 
1  Tim.  ii,  4;  1  Pet.  iii,  15;  2  Pet.  iii,  18;  James  i,  5],  and  the 
non-recognizing  of  the  divine  as  deep  guilt  [Rom.  i,  20,  21 ; 
iii,  11 ;  1  Cor.  i,  21 ;  2  Tim.  iii,  7;  2  Thess.  i,  8].  Wisdom  as 
sociates  all  knowledge  with  God,  and  uses  it  all  in  moral 
self- revelation, — is  pious  and  moral  at  the  same  time, — goes 
back  always  to  the  primitive  ground,  and  forward  to  the  ulti 
mate  end ;  hence  it  leaves  nothing  in  its  isolation  and  separate- 
ness,  but  brings  all  things,  man  included,  into  relation  to  the 
whole,  and  the  whole  into  relation  to  every  part ;  it  is  know 
ing  in  its  truly  rational  character;  the  fear  of  the  Lord,  it  is 
wisdom. — As  wisdom  makes  knowledge  the  full  property 
of  the  person, — as  it  belongs  not  merely  to  the  understand 
ing  but  also  to  the  heart,  and  is  in  fact  intelligent  love, — 
hence  it  is  necessarily  also  active  life, — begets  love  and  works 
from  love,  awakens  a  striving  to  manifest  the  attained  truth 
in  the  reality  of  life.  A  wisdom  which  does  not  generate  life, 
— which  remains  locked  up  in  the  subject, — is  folly  [Deut. 
iv,  6;  Prov.  viii,  11  sqq. ;  James  iii,  13,  17]. 

Prudence  (typovrjaif,  different  from  aofaa,  Eph.  i,  8)  is  indeed 
in  the  sphere  of  sinful  humanity  not  identical  with  wisdom, 
and  can  even  exist  as  a  merely  worldly  quality  apart  there 
from  ;  but  where  sin  is^not  yet  actual,  this  difference  is  merely 
formal.  Wisdom,  as  essential  rationality  itself,  embraces  truth 
per  se  as  a  harmonious  whole ;  prudence,  on  the  contrary,  takes 
into  account  actual  reality  with  a  view  to  bringing  it  into  re 
lation  to  the  moral  idea  as  embraced  by  reason, — in  order  to 
find  for  the  moral  idea  its  realization  in  each  conjuncture,  and 
the  means  thereto ;  hence  it  is  simply  wisdom  as  relating  to 
specific  real  circumstances.  Hence  true  prudence  can  neither 
exist  without  wisdom,  nor  wisdom  without  prudence,  and 
moral  duty  involves  both  of  them  in  inseparable  unity.  The 
harmonizing  of  prudence  with  open-hearted  simplicity  becomes 
difficult  only  in  a  world  of  sin.  Considerateness  and  circum- 
apectness  are  designations  of  prudence  as  applied  in  cases  diffi 
cult  of  decision  [Luke  xiv,  28,  29],  especially  in  so  far  as  it 
guards  against  the  promptings  of  over-rash  feelings. 


§  136.]  PURE  ETHICS.  283 

SECTION  CXXXVI. 

(2)  The  perfection  of  feeling,  as  a  moral  fruit,  is 
the  feeling  of  pure  pleasure  in  the  divine,  and  of  un 
mitigated  repugnance  to  the  ungodly,  and,  as  based 
on  faith,  the  feeling  of  pure  joy  which  springs  from 
the  consciousness  of  the  morally-wrought  harmony 
of  one's  own  existence  with  God  and  with  the  uni 
verse.  As  relating  to  existence  other  than  that  of  the 
moral  subject,  this  perfection  is  perfect  love  as  a  power 
grown  essential  and  inherent  in  the  personality ;  in 
relation  to  the  moral  subject  himself  it  is  the  perfect 
Hiss  of  the  child  of  God,  the  repose  of  the  soul  in 
God. 

So  long  as  the  feeling  of  self  is  not  yet  reduced  to  full 
harmony  with  the  love  of  God  (§  92),  so  long  also  is  feeling, 
as  relating  to  the  godly  and  the  ungodly,  not  pure  and  not 
decided.  As  the  ear  must  first  be  made  skillful  by  atteut- 
iveness  and  practice  in  order  to  be  able  readily  to  distinguish 
beautiful  from  discordant  notes,  so  also  must  feeling,  first  be 
made  sensitive  by  moral  exercise  in  order  to  be  able,  at  every 
moment,  unhesitatingly  to  love  and  to  hate  at  once  in  the 
right  manner.  Such  decisiveness,  such  purity  of  feeling,  con 
stitutes  an  essential  part  of  the  perfection  of  the  life  in  God, 
that  is,  of  blessedness ;  blessed  are  they  who  are  pure  of  heart ; 
blessed  they  who  find  no  occasion  of  offense  in  Christ  and  in 
the  ways  of  God  [Matt,  xi,  6.]  Mere  joy  is  not  yet  blessed 
ness  ;  the  merely  natural  pleasure  in  existence,  even  were  it  of 
a  Paradisaical  character,  is  not  enough  to  satisfy  the  spiritual 
nature  of  man  ;  only  that  which  is  morally  wrought,  or  at  least 
morally  appropriated,  renders  blessed.  Even  a  normal  child 
rejoices  more  in  its  own  playful  creating  than  in  mere  eating 
and  drinking.  The  nine  Beatitudes  of  Christ  [Matt,  v]  relate, 
all  of  them,  to  the  moral,  and  not  one  of  them  to  a  mere  state 
of  enjoyment.  All  blessedness,  however,  is  love,  and  true 
love  is  blessedness;  but  only  morally  attained  love  is  true 
love ;  even  love  to  God  becomes  truly  blissful  only  when  it  is 
the  expression  of  already-attained  God-Sonship.  The  moral 


284  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  137. 

man  feels  blissful  when  he  views  the  harmony  of  being  not  as 
simply  immediately  existing  and  as  merely  contemplated  by 
himself,  but  as  in  moral  freedom  recognized,  willed,  and  re 
alized  by  himself, — namely,  in  so  far  as,  on  the  one  hand, 
those  features  in  the  objective  world  which  are  originally  as 
yet  exterior  and  uncongenial  to  man  are  overcome,  and  the 
dominion  of  man  over  nature  realized,  and  in  so  far  as,  on  the 
other,  a  spiritually  moral  world  is  brought  into  being  with 
which  the  individual  knows  himself  in  moral  harmony;  but 
the  consciousness  of  this  double  harmony  produces  loving 
blessedness  only  when  it  rests  on  the  consciousness  of  a 
morally  virtualized  filial  relation  to  God.  True  blessedness 
exists  only  in  union  with  God;  peace  of  soul  only  in  the 
eternal. 

That  such  blessedness  is  not  simply  an  inheritance  in  the 
future  but  the  destination  even  of  the  present  life,  is  implied 
in  the  moral  idea  itself,  as  well  as  in  the  thought  of  the 
divine  love.  God  has  not  appointed  us  unto  wrath,  but  to 
obtain  blessedness  [1  Thess.  v,  9];  "but  whoso  looketh  into 
the  perfect  law  of  liberty,  and  continueth  therein,  he  being 
not  a  forgetful  hearer,  but  a  doer  of  the  work,  this  man  shall 
be  blessed  in  his  deed "  [  James  i,  25] ;  though  this  thought 
may  hold  good  on  the  part  of  one  redeemed  by  grace,  only 
under  certain  limitations,  yet  it  is  unconditionally  valid  of 
man  per  se  and  as  unf alien ;  with  him  moral  activity  is  per  se 
blessedness,  and  there  is  no  blessedness  without  moral  activ 
ity.  "Blessed  are  they  that  hear  the  word  of  God  and  keep 
it "  [Luke  xi,  28], — keep  it  not  merely  in  memory  but  in  their 
heart,  in  love  and  in  volition ;  ' '  blessed  are  they  that  do  his 
commandments  "  [Rev.  xxii,  14]. 

SECTION  CXXXVII. 

(3)  The  perfection  of  the  moral  will,  that  is,  the 
full  moral  freedom  of  self-determination  as  effected 
by  wisdom  and  love,  the  perfect  mastery  over  one's 
self,  the  completed  possession  of  one's  self,  consti 
tutes  the  fully  developed  personal  character.  As  dis 
tinguished  from  all  mere  fortuitous  character-forming, 


§137.]  PURE   ETHICS.  285 

the  truly  moral  character  is  the  copy  of  the  divine 
holiness  as  attained  to  through  free  moral  culture, — 
the  moral  law  as  become  the  real  free  property  of 
man,  the  harmony  of  the  human  with  the  divine  will 
as  become  a  dominant  power,  a  moral  nature,  so  that 
consequently  the  willing  and  accomplishing  of  the 
ungodly  becomes  to  man  a  moral  impossibility, — so 
that  the  love  to  God  becomes  perfect  hatred  against 
sin.  The  constantly  advancing  development  of 
the  moral  striving  toward  this  holiness,  constitutes 
the  ever-progressive  sanctification  of  the  soul,  the 
ultimate  fruit  of  which  is  the  perfect  freedom  of  the 
will,  and  as  contained  therein  the  enjoyment  of 
blessedness. 

In  that  the  moral  activity  becomes  fact,  that  is,  becomes  a 
moral  possession  of  the  person,  it  transforms  the  original,  as 
yet,  undetermined  will-freedom  into  a  determined  moral  will- 
quality,  into  moral  character.  Character-formation  illustrates 
clearly  the  nature  of  moral  freedom.  An,  as  yet,  undeter 
mined  character  has  a  much  wider  possibility  of  choice  in 
single  cases  than  a  definitely  shaped  one;  a  characterless 
man  is  unreliable  because  his  freedom  has  no  moral  deter- 
niinedness,  but  is  merely  external  freedom  of  choice.  Char 
acter  is  reliable,  and  upon  the  degree  of  its  firmness  rests  the 
confidence  which  it  inspires ;  we  know  in  advance  with  cer 
tainty  how,  in  a  definite  moral  conjuncture,  such  and  such  a 
character  will  choose.  This  is  now  surely  no  limitation  of 
freedom,  but  rather  its  moral  maturity.  The  freedom  is  all 
the  more  perfect,  true,  and  mature,  the  more  it  is  character- 
firm,  the  more  it  has  moral  determinedness;  and  the  highest 
moral  freedom  is  that  where  the  person  can  no  longer  waver 
in  any  moral  question,  where  it  has  become  for  him  a  moral 
impossibility  to  choose  the  immoral, — and  this  is  the  state  of 
holiness.  Holiness  is  related  to  innocence  as  morally-acquired 
good  to  ante-moral  natural  good — as  moral  property  to  mere 
possession. 


286  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  137. 

Human  holiness  as  a  copy  of  the  divine  holiness  differs 
from  the  latter  in  this,  that  with  God  holiness  constitutes 
his  essence  itself,  and  the  possibility  of  sin  is  not  in  any  sense 
conceivable ;  whereas  human  holiness  is  simply  a  morally- 
acquired  good,  and  presupposes  the  possibility  of  sin,  which 
in  fact  it  has  morally  overcome.  God's  holiness  is  eternal ; 
human  holiness  is,  in  its  true  character,  the  goal  of  develop 
ment, — depends  on  progressive  sanctification,  which  advances 
from  a  mere  non-willing  of  the  sinful  to  hatred  against  it 
and  to  abhorrence  of  it.  The  moral  requirement  of  complete 
heart-purity  and  holiness  may  not  in  any  manner  be  lowered, 
as  if  a  limited  measure  thereof  were  enough,  and  as  if  a  lower 
requirement  were  to  be  made  of  feebly  constituted  man  than, 
e.  g..of  the  angels.  According  to  the  testimony  of  Christ,  men 
are  in  fact  to  become  equal  to  the  angels  [fffuyye/Uu,  Luke  xx, 
36] ;  and  also  in  their  moral  essence  they  should  and  must 
not  remain  below  them.  Man  ought  (and  the  word  ought 
expresses  the  fundamental  condition  of  all  morality  in  gen 
eral)  to  become  morally  perfect,  and  hence  holy.  This  re 
quirement  is  fully  maintained  even  in  the  state  of  sinfulness, 
where  primarily,  that  is,  before  the  completion  of  redemption, 
the  entire  fulfilling  of  the  same  was  not  possible.  The  legis 
lation  from  Sinai  places  this  moral  requirement,  as  the  funda 
mental  idea  of  morality,  in  great  prominence:  "Ye  shall  be 
holy,  for  I  am  holy,  the  Lord  your  God  "  [Lev.  xi,  44,  45 ; 
xix,  2;  xx,  7] ;  and  the  apostles  adopt  the  same  words  as  fully 
valid  also  for  Christians  [1  Pet.  i,  15,  16].  The  utterances  of 
the  Scriptures  elsewhere  fully  harmonize  therewith  [Eph.  i,  4 ; 
iv,  24;  1  Thess.  iii,  13;  comp.  Matt,  v,  48;  Luke  i,  75;  and 
other  passages],  and  the  fact  that  the  faithful  of  God  are  so 
frequently  styled  "saints"  is  clearly  an  expression  of  their 
moral  destination. 

Man  is  originally  innocent,  but  not  yet  holy ;  he  is  not, 
however,  to  remain  merely  innocent,  but  is  to  advance  to  real 
holiness.  Man  is  created  in  innocence  unto  holiness.  The 
mere  unconscious  retaining  of  the  first  innocence  would  be  a 
lingering  in  the  child-consciousness;  and  the  going  beyond 
it, — not  of  course  in  the  direction  of  sin  but  only  in  that  of 
conscious  holiness, — was  the  true  normal  course;  Christ's 
holiness  was  not  mere  innocence.  As  a  morally-acquired 


§137.]  PURE   ETHICS.  287 

property,  holiness  as  distinguished  from  the  mere  possession  of 
innocence,  is  a  permanent  quality,  and  constitutes  the  moral 
character  itself  of  man ;  he  for  whom  there  is  yet  possible  a 
single  sinful  moment,  has  not  yet  attained  to  holiness.  There 
is  not  only  a  .natural  but  also  a  moral  must;  and  when  the 
child  Jesus  says:  "Wist  ye  not  that  I  must  be  about  my 
Father's  business  ? "  [Luke  ii,  49],  this  is  a  direct  reference  to 
this  moral  "  must "  of  a  holy  soul.  Holiness  is  consequently  not 
a  quality  of  single  actions,  but  it  is  character-peculiarity;  not 
the  single  volitional  act,  the  single  frame  of  mind  is  holy,  but 
the  heart  itself.  This  purity  of  heart  is  not  a  merely  negative 
state,  a  mere  non-presence  of  sin,  for  that  would  be  only  inno 
cence,  but  it  is  a  moral  fruit,  a  morally-acquired  power  over 
sin,  and  hence  where  sin  has  once  actually  existed  it  cannot 
be  attained  to  by  a  mere  ceasing  to  sin,  but  only  by  cease 
lessly  militant  santification.  Sanctification  (uyiaa^iof)  is 
consequently  by  no  means  a  merely  negative  bearing,  even 
in  the  ante-sinful  state,  but  is  a  positive  forming  of  the  will 
and  heart  unto  holiness.  The  sanctification  mentioned  in  the 
Scriptures  [1  Cor.  i,  30 ;  2  Cor.  vii,  1 ;  1  John  iii,  3 ;  Heb.  xii,  14, 
and  other  passages]  designates  of  course  only  the  putting  off  of 
existing  sinfulness  as  taking  place  in  virtue  of  redemption ;  but 
when  Christ  says  of  himself:  ' '  For  their  sakes  I  sanctify  myself, 
that  they  also  might  be  sanctified  through  the  truth  "  [John 
xvii,  19],  this  self-sanctification  of  the  holy  One  is  indeed  prim 
arily  to  be  understood  of  his  giving  himself  in  sacrifice,  but 
it  alludes  at  the  same  time  also  to  the  perfecting  of  the  moral 
life-development  of  the  Son  of  Man  unto  the  plenary  posses 
sion  of  morally-acquired  holiness  in  his  character  as  man; 
such  sanctification  is  the  duty  of  man  as  man. 

Through  progressive  sanctifying  culture  of  the  will  man 
becomes  perfectly  master  over  his  heart,  over  his  will, — the 
moral  becomes  easy  to  him,  becomes  his  second  nature,  whereas 
his  first  nature  is  the  as  yet  not  morally  formed  one.  The 
will  of  the  person  is  qpw  no  longer  different  from  the  divine 
will,  but  it  is,  in  full  freedom,  at  one  therewith ;  the  divine 
will  has  fully  become  the  inner  essence  and  the  vital  power 
of  the  disposition  of  the  person,  not  merely  in  general  but 
also  in  particular,  so  that  in  each  special  case  the  will  with 
unfailing  certainty  chooses  the  right, — even  as  a  true  artist 


288  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  137. 

possesses  full  mastery  over  his  hand,  so  that  it  never  introduces 
a  false  tone  or  makes  a  false  stroke.  Practice  leads  to  mas 
tery  ;  and  the  morally-matured  man  is  master  over  his  own 
will. 

It  is  only  in  this  mastery  that  man  is  truly  free,  namely,  in 
that  he  has  then  overcome  every  thing  in  himself  which,  as  a 
morally-to-be-mastered  material,  was  as  yet  different  from  the 
moral  idea  itself.  But  freedom  is  bliss ;  he  who  has  become 
truly  free  in  his  will  is  thereby  necessarily  also  happy.  Master 
over  himself,  he  is  also  at  the  same  time  master  over  all  that 
is  unspiritual,  over  nature;  and  in  having  put  himself  into 
complete  and  free  harmony  with  God,  he  participates  in  the 
lordship  of  the  absolute  Spirit  over  nature.  "The  Father 
that  dwelleth  in  me  he  doeth  the  works,"  says  Christ  in  refer 
ence  to  his  miraculous  works — the  works  of  the  Spirit  upon 
nature;  "verily,  verily,"  says  Christ  to  his  disciples,  "he  that 
believeth  on  me,  the  works  that  I  do  shall  he  do  also ;  and 
greater  than  these  shall  he  do  "  [John  xiv,  JO,  12] ;  for  God 
who  dwells  4n  him,  as  he  in  God,  the  same  does  the  works ; 
having  become  free  in  God,  man  has  nothing  more  either 
within  or  without  himself  which  could  prove  a  hinclerance 
to  the  moral  will  of  the  rational  spirit, — which  would  say, 
No!  to  the  striving  of  the  Holy  Spirit;  as  an  expression  of  true 
and  complete  freedom,  and  not  as  the  caprice  of  the  immature 
and  unsanctified  spirit,  this  promise  of  Christ  holds  good  for 
all  his  faithful  followers.  The  hard  rind  of  unspiritual  nature 
must  be  broken  through,  the  longing  of  the  vanity-bound 
creature  must  be  fulfilled  ;  nature  must  be  "  delivered  from 
the  bondage  of  corruption  unto  the  glorious  liberty  of  the 
children  of  God  "  [Rom.  viii,  19-22] ;  all  that  is  natural  must 
be  spiritualized,  must  be  exalted  into  the  complete  untram- 
meled  service  of  the  free  spirit ;  such  is  the  freedom,  such  the 
blessedness  of  the  children  of  God. 

In  the  possession  of  knowledge,  of  purified  feeling,  and  of 
the  mastery  of  the  will,  as  attained  to  by  moral  appropriating 
and  self-forming,  man  becomes  morally  cultured,  as  distin 
guished  from  the  as  yet  morally  immature  and  crude  man; 
and  in  such  culture  he  is  truly  free.  The  very  first  man  was 
called  unto  perfect  culture,  and  it  is  quite  the  opposite  of  cor 
rect  to  conceive,  with  Rousseau,  the  first  human  beings  as 


§  138.]  PURE   ETHICS.  289 

living  in  a  state  of  happy  barbarism.  As  far  back  as  the  Bibli 
cal  account  reaches  we  find  even  in  the  state  of  sin  no  trace  of 
an  actual  cultureless  barbarism.  The  fact  that  Adam  was  to 
till  his  garden  was  of  itself  an  implication  of  his  destination 
to  culture,  for  barbarians  never  till  the  soil ;  Adam's  sons  ap 
pear,  from  the  very  first,  as  persons  of  culture  with  a  definite 
savagery-excluding  calling;  Cain  was  a  founder  of  villages 
[Gen.  iv,  17] ;  and  among  his  immediate  descendants  appear 
inventors  of  manifold  articles  of  skill  [Gen.  iv,  21,  22] ;  and 
from  that  time  forth  we  find  traces  of  a  progressive  culture. 
The  progenitors  of  the  Israelites  are  by  no  means  half-savage 
nomads ;  their  wandering-about  is  only  a  temporary  state  of 
necessity,  for  they  are  in  search  of  a  home ;  and  their  entire 
form  of  life  gives  evidence  indeed  of  great  simplicity,  but 
yet  also  of  high  spiritual  and  moral  culture.  True  culture 
is  always  a  fruit  of  moral  effort,  and  a  culture  that  aims  at 
mere  temporal  enjoyment  and  profit  is  but  a  deceptive  self- 
defeating  counterfeit. 

SECTION  CXXXVIII. 

(c)  In  that  the  morally-good  becomes  an  acquired 
possession  of  man,  his  real  property,  it  has  become  an 
essential  element  of  his  moral  nature,  and  hence  is 
not  an  inert  state,  but  an  active  power  generative  of 
new  moral  life, — has  become  a  creative,  operative 
disposition,  and  is  consequently  itself  per  se  a  directly 
active  motive  to  moral  action.  The  morally-good 
has  become  virtue.,  which  is  accordingly,  on  the  one 
hand,  a  good  not  innate  and  embraced  in  the  nature 
itself  of  man,  but  a  morally-acquired  possession,  and 
on  the  other  a  power  generative  in  turn  itself  of  the 
good. 

"  All  Scripture,  given  by  inspiration  of  God.  is  also  profitable 
for  doctrine,  for  reproof,  for  correction,  for  instruction  in 
righteousness,  that  the  man  of  God  may  be  perfect,  thoroughly 
furnished  unto  all  good  works  "  [2  Tim.  iii,  16,  17] ;  the  moral 
perfection  attained  to  by  the  sanctifying  activity  is  itself  in  turn 
VOL.  11—20 


290  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  138. 

a  stimulus  to  the  good,  a  capacitation,  a  skilledne"ss  and  power 
for  moral  activity ;  -such  is  the  inner  idea  of  virtue.  Man  as 
come  into  possession  of  virtue  is  no  longer  the  original  man 
possessed  of  merely  naturally-moral  power,  but  he  is  man  as 
armed  with  morally  acquired  and  hence  heightened  power. 
There  are  no  innate  virtues,  but  only  innate  capabilities  of 
virtue.  The  merely  natural  man  has  moral  freedom  as  a  simple 
and  as  yet  undetermined  freedom  of  choice ;  the  virtuous 
man  has  his  freedom  as  exalted  to  a  determinedness  for  the 
good ;  he  has  no  longer  an  equally  balanced  choice  between 
good  and  evil,  but  his  morally  acquired  peculiarity  of  char 
acter  inclines  spontaneously  to  the  good.  Man  can  never 
merely  possess  virtue,  he  must  let  it  be  operative ;  a  dormant 
virtue  is  none  at  all.  Hence,  varying  from  the  usual  view 
which  distinguishes  and  contrasts  goods  and  virtues,  we  con 
sider  virtue  directly  as  a  good.  The  contrasting  of  virtue  as 
a  power  and  of  goods  as  a  possession  is  inaccurate ;  all  power 
is  a  good,  and  every  good  is  a  heightening  of  power;  hence 
men  of  the  world  seek  so  zealously  after  earthly  goods,  as  they 
thereby  enlarge"  their  power.  That  virtue  is  not  a  dormant 
possession,  but  strictly  an  operative  power,  does  not  make  it 
differ  essentially  from  all  other  goods ;  no  real  property  exists 
merely  to  lie  idle,  no  talent  is  to  be  buried ;  but  it  is  to  be 
put  to  usury  and  made  constantly  to  acquire  more.  Money  is 
a  good ;  for  him,  however,  who  does  not  put  it  to  use,  it  does 
not  really  exist ;  it  becomes  a  real  good  only  when  it  becomes 
a  power,  when  it  is  employed  in  heightened  life-activity. 
Virtue,  however,  is  a  much  higher  good  than  that  which  is 
given  us  directly  and  from  nature,  or  as  an  outward  posses 
sion. 

In  the  New  Testament  the  notion  of  virtue  is  variously  ex 
pressed  ;  uperf]  [Phil,  iv,  8 ;  1  Peter  ii,  9 ;  2  Peter  i,  3,  5]  is  not 
strictly  virtue,  but  is  rather  the  notion  of  the  morally  good  in 
general.  Usually  the  notion  of  virtue  is  expressed  by  dinaioavvri, 
in  so  far  as  this  quality  is-  a  personal  possession  [Luke  i,  75 ; 
Rom.  vi,  13;  Eph.  iv,  24;  v,  9,  and  other  passages],  also  by 
iiyiaaiii'Ti  [1  Thess.  iii,  13],  by  uyaOvovvr}  [Rom.  xv,  14;  Eph. 
v,  9],  and  likewise  also  by  evaefStta,  in  so  far  as  the  root  of 
virtue  rather  than  virtue  itself  is  meant;  for  Christian  virtue, 
is  also  used,  as  designating  its  resting  upon  divine 


§  139.]  PURE   ETHICS.  291 

grace.  In  the  Old  Testament  the  notion  proper  of  virtue  is 
wanting  ;  under  the  predominance  of  the  thought  of  the  law 
and  of  right,  the  morally  correct  character  is  designated  as 
"righteousness,"  in  virtue  of  its  answering  to  the  law  and 
claims  of  God  ;  hence  this  is  merely  a  designation  of  the  form. 
Before  the  full  accomplishment  of  redemption,  the  inner  essence 
of  virtue  was  neither  fully  realizable  nor  comprehensible. 

SECTION  CXXXIX. 

Inasmuch  as  all  moral  motive  consists  in  love  (§  91), 
and  inasmuch  as  virtue,  as  a  moral  property,  is  also 
an  actuating  power,  hence  virtue  is  essentially  love 
to  God,  and  is  consequently  per  se  not  multiple  but 
single.  In  so  far,  however,  as  the  relation  of  this 
one-fold  virtue  may  be  different  both  as  to  the  moral 
person  and  as  to  the  object,  it  appears  under  the  form 
of  a  plurality  of  virtues,  which,  however,  as  merely 
different  phases  and  manifestation-forms  of  the  one 
virtue,  are  never  to  be  entirely  separated  from  each 
other,  and  can  never  exist  alone.  These  diverse 
manifestation-forms  of  virtue  may  be  reduced  to  four 
cardinal  virtues: — (1)  Moral  love  preserves  itself  for 
the  object  in  its  proper  relation  to  it,  and  thus  mani 
fests  itself  in  the  virtue  of  fidelity. — (2)  Moral  love 
preserves  the  object  in  its  moral  rights,  and  hence  in 
its  legitimate  peculiarity, — as  the  virtue  of  justness. — 
(3)  Moral  love  preserves  the  moral  subject  himself  in 
his  moral  rights,  and  hence  at  the  same  time  within 
his  moral  limits,  in  that  it  places  upon  the  moral 
activity  of  the  same  a  definite  measure, — the  virtue 
of  temper ateness. — (4)  Moral  love  preserves  at  once 
both  itself,  the  moral  object  and  the  .moral  subject  in 
their  moral  rights,  in  that  it  actively  opposes  all  hin- 
derances  that  stand  in  the  way  of  it  and  of  its  realiza 
tion, — the  virtue  of  courage. 


292  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  139. 

We  do  not  adopt  the  Platonic  classification  of  the  virtues 
which  has  found  its  way  into  a  large  portion  of  works  on 
Christian  ethics,  for  it  is  only  by  violence  that  it  can  be  ac 
commodated 'to  the  Christian  consciousness.  The  cardinal 
virtues  which  we  adopt,  result  logically  and  naturally  from 
the  notion  of  love  as  a  disposition  of  the  soul ;  and  it  is,  by  no 
means,  accidental  that  they  correspond  to  the  four  tempera 
ments.  The  so-called  temperament-virtues  are  simply  the 
natural  germs  of  the  real  virtues.  The  virtue  of  courage  cor 
responds  to  the  warm  or  choleric  temperament ;  that  of  tem- 
perateness  to  the  cold  or  phlegmatic ;  that  of  justness  to  the 
quick  or  sanguine, — for  sanguine  persons  are  very  receptive 
for  whatever  is  objective,  accepting  it  just  as  it  presents  itself, 
yielding  themselves  to  it,  doing  it  no  violence ;  sanguine  per 
sons  are  very  companionable.  The  virtue  of  fidelity  corresponds 
to  the  melancholic  temperament,  which,  directed  inwardly 
and  dwelling  within  itself,  and  largely  closed  to  outward  in 
fluences,  is  not  easily  led  astray. — The  four  virtues  are  so  inti 
mately  connected  with  each  other  that  each  contains  within 
itself  in  some  measure  all  the.  others.  Temperateness  is  just 
ness  in  so  far  as  it  restrains  man  from  that  which  does  not 
become  him ;  it  is  fidelity  in  so  far  as  it  regards  love  to  God 
and  to  God's  will  as  having  the  highest  claims,  and  does  not 
allow  the  individual  self  to  become  too  prominent ;  and  it  is 
courage  in  so  far  as  it  actively  confines  the  unspiritual  and 
the  irrational  within  their  proper  limits.  Justness  is  fidelity 
in  so  far  as  it  preserves  love  for  and  verifies  it  upon  the  object ; 
it  is  temperateness  in  so  far  as  it  respects  every-where  the 
measure  and  the.  limits  of  the  moral  person  and  of  the  object ; 
and  it  is  courage  in  so  far  as  it  carries  out  and  vindicates  the 
just.  Fidelity  is  courage  in  so  far  as  it  asserts  itself  in  the 
active  overcoming  of  all  hinderances ;  it  is  justness  in  so  far  as 
it  manifests  to  the  object  only  the  measure  of  love  which  is 
really  felt  for  it ;  and  for  the  same  reason  it  is  temperateness. 
Temperateness  and  fidelity  correspond  to  each  other  in  so  far 
as  they  both  retain  the  moral  person  in  a  proper  bearing  in  re 
lation  to  the  object ;  justness  and  courage  correspond  to  each 
other  in  so  far  as  they  both  resist  all  influences  that  are  un 
friendly  to  the  moral.  Temperateness  and  courage  are  purely 
human  virtues  in  so  far  as  both  presuppose  a  creature-limit 


§  139.]  PURE   ETHICS.  293 

of  the  moral  personality,  and  hence  they  can  in  no  sense  be 
predicated  of  God ;  fidelity  and  justness  are  also  divine  virtues 
[1  John  i,  9]  because  they  presuppose  only  a  difference  of  the 
personal  subject  from  the  object,  and  a  claim  of  the  moral. 
The  former  two  have  in  their  manifestation  a  negating  char 
acter, — presuppose  an  antagonism  in  which  one  phase  must 
be  made  subordinate ;  the  latter  two  bear  a  more  affirmative 
character, — are  an  express  recognition  and  carrying  out  of  the 
moral  rights  of  the  object.  Of  a  conflicting  of  the  virtues 
with  each  other  there  is  no  possibility. 

Of  the  cardinal  virtues  here  presented,  three  coincide  with 
the  Platonic  virtues ;  but  in  the  place  of  wisdom  our  classifi 
cation  gives  fidelity.  With  the  Greeks  the  making  of  wisdom 
the  fundamental  virtue  was  quite  consequential ;  for  all  the 
other  virtues  were  a  fruit  of  moral  knowledge,  but  not  of  love. 
From  a  Christian  stand-point,  where  the  moral  freedom  of  the 
will  is  conceived  more  highly  and  is  not  placed  in  so  uncon 
ditional  a  relation  of  dependence  upon  knowledge  as  with  the 
Greeks,  and  where,  consequently,  virtue  inheres  essentially  in 
the  love-inspired  will,  wisdom  is  indeed  conceived  as  a  high 
morally-to-be-acquired  good,  as  the  presupposition  and  attend 
ant  of  all  virtue,  and  is  also  in  fact  closely  associated  with  love, 
(§  135),  but  still  it  cannot  be  regarded  as  a  virtue  proper.  The 
first  and  most  essential  manifestation-form  of  virtue  as  love 
is  persistent  love,  namely,  fidelity,  which  consequently  cannot 
be  classified  under  any  one  of  the  other  virtues  as  a  subordi 
nate  manifestation,  but  it  must  be  placed  at  the  head,  as  the 
virtue  dominating  all  the  others. 

(1)  Fidelity  (marie),  thrown  very  much  into  the  back 
ground  in  heathen  ethics,  for  the  reason  that,  there,  the  ab 
solutely  firm  basis  of  all  morality,  faith  in  the  true  God,  was 
lacking,  comes  in  the  Christian  consciousness  into  the  fore 
ground.  Human  virtue,  as  lasting  love,  is  an  image  of  the 
divine  fidelity,  which  is  presented  in  the  Scriptures  as  one  of 
the  most  prominent  of  the  divine  attributes,  and  is  almost  al 
ways  associated  with  love,  grace,  and  mercy  [Gen.  ix,  9  sqq.; 
Exod.  xxxiv,  6  ;  Deut.  vii,  9  ;  ix,  5;  xxxii,  4;  1  Sam.  xii,  22; 
Psa.Jxxxvi1  15;  fCor.  i,  9;  x,  13;  I  Thess.  v,  24;  2  Thess. 
iii,  3;  2  Tim.  ii,  13].  God's  fidelity  is  loving  grace;  the 
fidelity  of  man  is  humble  obedience,  and  is  hence  a  manifesta- 


CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  139. 

t5on  of  piety, — is,  in  ground  and  essence,  fidelity  toward  the 
faithful  God  [Matt,  xxv,  21 ;  1  Cor.  iv,  2] ;  the  holy  walk  of 
the  Christian  is  summed  up  in  the  word:  "Be  thou  faithful 
unto  death"  [Rev.  ii,  10;  comp.  Psa.  Ixxxv,  11,  12;  Matt. 
x,  22;  Luke  xvi,  10-12;  1  Cor.  vii,  25].— True  fidelity  relates 
not  to  a  mere  idea,  to  a  mere  law,  but  to  a  spiritual  reality, 
and  chiefly  to  the  personal  spirit ;  love  loves  only  a  loving 
spirit.  A  merely  conceived  law  cannot  be  loved ;  hence  there 
can  be  no  real  fidelity  to  such,  which  is  not  in  reality  fidelity 
to  the  holy  law-giver.  Fidelity  toward  man  is  morally  with 
out  anchor  unless  it  is  based  on  fidelity  to  God  ;  for  fidelity 
can  be  based  only  on  a  perfectly  firm  foundation.  Fidelity  to 
a  creature  in  the  absence  of  fidelity  to  God,  would  not  be 
a  virtue  but  sin.  Fidelity  is  the  truthfulness  of  love  ;  a  chang 
ing  love  is  mere  inclination,  and  is  not  moral ;  truth  changes 
not,  and  hence  also  moral  love  changes  not. — As  relating  to 
industrial  activity  in  a  temporal  calling,  fidelity  appears  as 
diligence,  which  is  only  then  morally  good,  and  hence  a  virtue, 
when  it  is  a  conscious  persistence  in  our  God-appointed  moral 
task  [Prov.  x,  4;  xii,  27;  1  Thess.  iv,  11]. 

(2)  Justness  or  righteousness  is  the  constant  willingness  to 
the  actual  recognition  of  the  rights  of  every  moral  personali 
ty,  as  well  those  of  God  as  those  of  man ;  it  is  love  in  the 
fulfilling  of  the  command :  "  Render  unto  Cesar  the  things 
which  are  Cesar's,  and  unto  God  the  things  that  are  God's  " 
[Matt,  xxii,  21], — the  imitating  of  the  righteousness  of  God 
which  gives  to  each  that  which  is  his  due.  In  the  Scriptures 
justness  or  righteousness  is  one  of  the  most  important  of  the 
moral  notions,  and  it  appears  even  in  its  widest  sense  as  the 
respecting  of  the  suum  cuique;  it  is  a  manifestation  of  love, 
and  a  never  fully  to  be  absolved  debt  [Rom.  xiii,  8] ;  and  in 
so  far  as  it  is  a  manifestation  of  reciprocal  love  it  is  thankful 
ness  (§  125).  It  is  for  the  reason  that  justness  lovingly  fulfills  the 
claims  of  God  that  it  can  lay  claim  to  the  essence  of  virtue  in 
general ;  it  is  virtue  in  so  far  as  virtue  is  a  disposition  of  soul 
recognizing  the  claims  of  God  upon  us.  Christ  sums  up  all  our 
moral  relations  to  our  fellows  under  the  one  head,  justness, 
and  makes  of  this,  in  its  fuller  sense,  the  fundamental  idea  of 
morality:  "All  things  whatsoever  ye  would  that  men  should 
do  to  you,  do  ye  even  so  to  them,  for  this  is  the  law  and 


§  139.]  .  PUKE   ETHICS.  295 

the  prophets  "  [Matt,  vii,  12] ;  this  is  not  merely  ordinary  civil 
justice,  but  the  higher, — that  which  is  an  expression  of  love. 
But  all  love  seeks  to  maintain  the  harmony  of  existence,  and 
hence  the  divine  order  of  the  world,  that  is,  the  rights 
of  whatever  truly  is;  and  all  human  justness  is  a  copy  of  the 
divine  [Deut.  x,  17,  18.] 

Justness  adapts  itself  to  the  differences  of  existence  and  of 
rights ;  God  has  different  rights  from  those  of  man,  and 
among  men  there  exist,  even  in  an  unfallen  state,  different 
rights,  according  to  their  differing  conditions  and  relations ; 
parents  have  different  rights  from  those  of  the  children,  gov 
ernors  from  those  of  the  governed ;  justness  gives  not  to  each 
the  same,  but  to  eacli  -  that  which  is  his  due  [Rom.  xiii, 
7-9],  and  thus  realizes  the  harmony  of  existence.  Even 
toward  nature  there  is  a  justness,  inasmuch  as  nature,  in  vir 
tue  of  its  being  good,  has  a  claim  upon  the  moral  spirit  (§  127;. 
Real  justness  therefore  presupposes  wisdom;  its  practice 
becomes  difficult,  however,  only  where  the  harmony  of  exist 
ence  is  already  disturbed  by  sin.  The  Scriptures  describe 
justness  manifoldly  in  its  single  manifestations  [e.  g.  Lev. 
xix;  Job  xxxi;  Psa.  xv;  ci;  Ezek.  xviii,  6-9;  Isa.  i,  17;  Jer. 
xxii,  3  ;  Zech.  vii,  9,  10;  viii,  16, 17;  Luke  vi,  38] ;  the  Deca 
logue  itself  is  but  a  description  thereof.  That  Christian 
justness  or  righteousness  is  not  a  merely  human  virtue  but 
essentially  a  gift  of  grace,  need  here  only  to  be  mentioned  in 
passing.  As  virtue  simply  and  purely,  it  appears  only  in  the 
person  of  Christ  [1  John  ii,  1,  29 ;  Acts  iii,  14 ;  1  Pet.  iii,  18]. 

(3)  Temperateness,  the  self-discipline  of  the  heart,  the 
aucj>poavv7j  of  the  Greeks,  is  presented  in  the  New  Testament 
in  the  narrower  sense  of  e}'/cpur«a,  while  au^poavvrj  has,  here 
also,  only  the  more  specific  sense  of  modesty  andirreproacha- 
bleness  of  behavior  [1  Tim.  ii,  9 ;  perhaps  only  in  verse  15  in 
a  somewhat  wider  sense],  but  the  adjective  autypuv  is  used  in 
a  more  general  sense  [1  Tim.  iii,  2;  Tit.  i,  8;  ii,  5].  Tem- 
perateness  in  the  wider  and  full  sense  is  the  self-restraining 
of  the  subject  within  his  normal  moral  limits,  a  subordinating 
of  all  self-seeking  desires  to  unconditional  obedience  to  the 
moral  law,  and  hence,  on  the  one  hand,  as  relating  to  sensu- 
ousness,  a  controlling  of  the  sensuous  desires  by  the  moral 
reason,  and,  on  the  other,  as  relating  to  the  spiritual,  a  con- 


296  CHETSTIAN   ETHICS.  [§139. 

trolling  of  self-love  by  love  to  God  and  to  our  neighbor, — a 
maintaining  of  the  rights  of  the  rational  spirit  in  its  true 
essence.  That  temperateness  is  at  once  also  justness  is  self- 
evident;  it  is  but  another  phase  of  the  same  virtue.  Even  as 
relating  to  the  sensuous  desires  it  is  also  justness,  in  so  far 
as  these  are  restrained  within  their  moral  limits  out  of  regard 
to  the  higher  rights  of  the  spirit.  Modesty,  patience,  and 
obed lateness  are  special  phases  of  this  virtue;  so  also  are 
shame,  pudicity  and  chastity,  as  a  keeping  of  sexual  sensu- 
ousness  within  bounds,  a  subordinating  of  it  to  its  higher 
moral  conditions ;  shame  and  pudicity  are  rather  the  inner  ele 
ments,  the  state  of  the  heart,  and  chastity  rather  the  outward 
manifestation ;  they  are  an  expression  of  the  fact  that  this 
sensuous  instinct  has  absolutely  no  right  per  se,  but  only 
in  the  service  of  wedlock-love. — Temperateness  presup 
poses  indeed  a  difference  and  a  possible  antagonism  between 
selfish  desires  (especially  the  sensuous  ones)  and  the  mor 
ally-rational  consciousness,  though  not  an  actually-existing 
antagonism  and  opposition.  In  its  manifestation  it  is  more  a 
negating  virtue  than  justness,  and  yet  its  essence  is  very 
affirmative. — This  virtue  becomes  most  difficult  where  the 
individual  energy  stands  forth  most  strongly  over  against  gen 
eral,  rational  right,  and  hence  in  the  period  of  youthful  vigor 
when  the  consciousness  of  personal  strength  and  of  self-will 
delights  to  cope  with  objective  barriers,  and  seeks  to  cast 
them  off  as  trameling  fetters, — when  the  strongly  self-conscious 
individuality  delights  to  enjoy  this  consciousness,  whether  in 
the  enjoyment  of  sensuous  pleasure,  or  in  that  of  unbounded 
freedom,  or  in  that  of  will-assertion.  Fidelity,  justness,  and 
courage  are,  for  vigorous  youth,  much  more  easily  attained  to 
and  preserved  than  the  virtue  of  temperateness;  but  as  all 
the  virtues  are  only  different  phases  of  virtue  in  general,  and 
as  they  are  all  connected  with  each  other  in  a  vital  unit}', 
hence  the  violation  of  one  of  them  is  necessarily  also  a  viola 
tion  of  the  others ;  intemperateness  is,  in  every  respect,  per  so 
also  an  infidelity,  an  un justness  and  a  cowardliness,  and  it 
leads  directly  to  a  further  development  of  these  vices. 

(4)  Courage,  the  moral  readiness  to  combat  against  what 
ever  opposes  the  moral  end, — expressed  by  the  Greeks  by  the 
more  limited  uvSptia,  and  in  the  Scriptures  by  the  higher  and 


§  140.]  PURE   ETHICS.  297 

more  inward  notion  of  nafifaaia  [Eph.  iii,  12;  1  Tim.  iii,  JO, 
etc.], — is  the  being  joyous  and  confident  in  the  carrying  out 
of  the  moral  idea  on  the  basis  of  hopeful  faith  [Matt..v,  12; 
Acts  ii,  29;  iv,  13,  29,  31;  ix,  27,  28;  xiii,  46;  xiv,  3;  xviii, 
26;  xix,  8;  xxvi,  26;  xxviii,  31;  Rom.  viii,  31  sqq. ;  2  Cor. 
iii,  12 ;  v,  6,  8 ;  xii,  10 ;  Eph.  iii,  12 ;  vi,  19,  20 ;  Phil,  i,  20 ; 
1  Thess.  ii,  2 ;  Heb.  xii,  3 ;  Psa.  cxviii,  5  sqq.].  The  moral  life 
of  the  Christian  is  a  constant  struggle  [Luke  xiii,  24 ;  1  Tim. 
vi,  12]  as  well  against  the  outward  hinderances  of  the  moral 
life  as  also  against  the  inner  opposing  desires  and  against 
carnal  sloth  and  fear.  Though  both  these  forms  of  hin- 
derance  do  not  hold  good  in  a  strict  sense  for  the  unfallen 
state,  still  we  must  doubtless  admit  that  there  were  relatively 
corresponding  relations  of  a  normal  kind.  During  the 
development  of  man  toward  his  ultimate  perfection  there 
constantly  exists  an,  as  yet,  extra  moral  reality,  namely, 
nature  within  and  without  him,  which  is  to  be  brought  with 
in  the  dominion  of  moral  reason,  and  which  is,  as  extra- 
moral,  also  per  se  a  barrier  that  is  to  be  overcome  by  moral 
effort ;  however,  it  is  not  an  active  antagonism,  and  the  effort 
does  not  involve  suffering.  Self-love,  in  itself  perfectly  legiti 
mate,  needs  also  to  be  brought  into  perfect  subordination  to  the 
love  of  God,  and  the  mastering  of  it  requires  conflict  and 
courage.  This  "parrhsesia"  is  not  mere  feeling,  not  mere 
inward  peace,  but  it  is  essentially  a  combat-courting  courage, 
a  persistence  in  the  moral  struggle  in  virtue  of  joyous  trust  in 
God.  Absolutely  sure  of  victory,  it  fears  nothing  and  un 
dauntedly  carries  out  what  it  undertakes. 

SECTION  CXL. 

In  so  far  as  God  himself  is  the  object  of  love,  and 
in  so  far  as,  in  the  creature,  the  divine  phase,  the  image 
of  God,  is  brought  into  prominence,  the  above  four 
virtues  appear  under  a  special  form  expressive  of  the 
essence  of  piety,  as  piety -virtues,  which,  however,  do 
not  stand  along-side  of  the  other  virtues,  but  are  in 
fact  the  highest  and  God-directed  phase  of  the  same. 
Fidelity  as  relating  to  God  appears  as  moral  faith  ; 


298  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  f§  140. 

justness  as  moral  devotedness  or  pious  obedience  ;  tem- 
perateness  as  filially-pious  humility,  as  child-minded- 
ness  ;  and  courage  as  hope  or  confidence. 

The  piety-virtues,  only  partially  corresponding  to  the  so- 
called  theological  virtues,  are  the  essence  proper,  the  ground, 
the  kernel  and  the  crown  of  the  virtues  in  general, — are  neither 
super-ordinate  nor  co-ordinate  to  the  four  cardinal  virtues,  but 
are  their  essential  substance  and  spirit  itself. 

1.  Faith,   designated  in  Scripture  by  the  same  expression 
with  fidelity,  is  the  loving  response  to  God's  fidelity  to  us,  and, 
as  an  expression  of  our  fidelity  toward  the  faithful  God,  is  a 
high  moral  requirement, — is  a  loving  confiding  of   our  own 
being  and  life  to  the  faithful  love  and  truthfulness  of  God, 
a  holding-fast  of  love  to  God.     Were  faith  a  mere  holding  for 
true,  then  it  would  not  be  a  moral  requirement,  and  hence 
the  possession  of  it  not  a  virtue ;  as  fidelity,  however,  it  is  a 
virtue    (§   113).     Faith  is  reckoned  to  man   for  justness  or 

.righteousness  [Rom.  iv,  3;  Gal.  iii,  6],  for  the  reason  that, 
as  fidelity,  it  is  itself  justness  toward  God,  and  the  root  and 
essence  of  all  righteousness. 

2.  Obedience  toward  God,   moral  decotedness,   vTraKof?,  is  the 
inclination  and  willingness  that  God's  claim  upon  us  should 
be  perfectly  realized  in  our  moral  conduct,  and  hence  that  we 
should  do  that  which,  as  God's  creditors,  we  owe  to  Him 
[Rom.  viii,  12] ;  we  meet  God's  claim  upon  us  only  by  perfect, 
voluntary  and  joyous  submission  to  his  will  [Exod.  xix,  8; 
xxiv,  3,  7;  Deut.  iv;  xi,   1;  xii,   1,   32;  xiii,  4,   18;,  Jer.  vii, 
23;  Luke  i,  38;  James  iv,  7 ;  1  Pet.   i,  2,  14,  22;  comp.  Gen. 
vi,  22;  vii,  5;  xii,  4;  xxi,  13  sqq. ;  xxii,  1  sqq.]  ;  the  obedient 
are  by  that  very  fact  the  just  [Hos.  xiv,  9;  Mai.  iii,  18;  Matt^ 
xxv,  37;  1  John  iii,  7];  obedience  is  the  fruit  of  faith  [Pleb. 
xi,  8],  the  expression  of  the  child-mindedness  of  believers 
toward  the  Father.     The  Son  of  man  is  the  holy  pattern  of 
obedience   [Rom.  v,  19;  Gal.   iv,  4;  Phil,  ii,  8;   Heb.  v,   8; 
Isa.  liii]. 

3.  Humility,  Ta-rri-ivofytoavvr),  the  moral  and  reverential  con 
fining  of  ourselves  within  the  limits  fixed  by  God  for  us  as 
creatures  and  for  each  of  us  in  his  special  moral  calling,  is  an 
absolute  duty  even  of  sinless  man,  inasmuch  as  the  moral  crea- 


§  140.]  PURE   ETHICS.  299 

ture,  as  related  to  God,  is  and  lias  nothing  which  is  not  to  be 
recognized  as  depending  upon  God's  support ;  hence  it  holds 
good  also  of  the  angels  [Col.  ii,  18],  and  of  Christ  as  the  Son 
of  man  in  his  subordination  to  God  [Matt,  xi,  29 ;  comp.  xx, 
28;  Phil,  ii,  6-8;  Heb.  xii,  2;  John  xiii,  4  sqq.].  All  moral 
humility  is  at  bottom  humility  before  God  [James  iv,  10 ; 
comp.  Gen.  xxxii,  10;  Luke  xviii,  14],  even  as  the  first  sin 
consisted  in  a  lack  of  humility;  when  humility  before  men 
does  not  rest  on  this  ground,  it  sinks  to  abjectness  and  serv- 
ile-mindedness ;  it  is  only  in  humility  before  God  that  man 
learns  to  harmonize  humility  before  men  with  a  proper  respect 
for  his  own  moral  dignity.  All  humility  rests  on  faith  and  is 
also  obedience ;  its  essence,  however,  is  a  keeping  Avithin 
bounds,  a  self-retention  within  our  divinely-appointed  posi 
tion  [Matt,  v,  3;  xxiii,  11;  Luke  xxii,  24  sqq. ;  Acts  xx,  19; 
Rom.  xii,  3,  16;  Eph.  iv,  1,  2;  Phil,  ii,  3;  Col.  iii,  12;  1  Pet. 
v,  5 ;  James  iv,  6].  Child-like  humility  aims  not  at  high 
things,  but  only  at  the  highest,  which  in  fact  are  accessible 
only  to  child-mind  edness, — retains  always  toward  God  its 
filial  character  [Matt,  xviii,  3,  4].  Humility  is  a  purely  Chris 
tian  virtue;  to  Greek  ethics  it  was  almost  unknown  (§  21). 

4.  Hope,  IXnlf,  mentioned  in  connection  with  faith  and  love 
as  a  high  virtue  [1  Cor.  xiii,  13],  directs  itself  with  firm  con 
fidence  toward  the  highest  good  as  the  goal  to  be  attained  to, 
toward  the  idea  of  the  good  [Rom.  viii,  24],  and  is  not  a  mere 
expecting  of  a  future  happiness,  but  a  joyful  trusting  faith- 
born  confidence  that  God  means  it  well  with  us,  and  will  also 
actually  enable  us  to  reach  our  moral  goal,  provided  we  hon 
estly  strive  toward  it, — is,  in  a  word,  that  moral  courage  in 
God  that  is  sure  of  its  victory,  and  that  has  consequently 
already  overcome  all  inward  obstacles  to  the  outward  victory ; 
it  is  not  merely  an  involuntary  state  of  feeling,  but  a  morally- 
acquired  good.  All  hope  is  faith  [Heb.  xi,  1],  but  it  is  also 
moral  self-surrender  and  child-like  humility,  for  it  expects  the 
victory  not  from  itself  but  from  God.  The  hope  that  is  fixed 
merely  upon  created  things  is  vain  and  sinful;  but  moral 
hoping  in  God  does  not  end  in  disappointment  [Rom.  v,  5], 
and  all  moral  courage  is  based  upon  it  [Psa.  ix,  10;  xxv,  2; 
xxxi,  15 ;  xl,  4 ;  Ivi,  4  sqq. ;  Ixii,  6 ;  xci,  2 ;  cxii,  7 ;  John  xvi, 
33;  Rom.  iv,  18;  v,  2,  4,  5;  xii,  12;  Phil,  iii,  1;  iv,  4; 


300  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  140. 

1  Cor.  i,  10 ;  iii,  12,  etc.].  God  is  a  God  of  hope  [Rom.  XT,  13], 
because  all  hope  is  based  on  him,  and  relates  to  his  promises. 
The  word  of  the  faithful  God  is  the  ground,  the  contents  and 
the  vitality  of  all  true  hope.  Hope  is  a  virtue  belonging  es 
sentially  only  to  the  kingdom  of  God ;  among  heathens  only 
the  Persians  have  as  much  as  a  darkly-groping  hope ;  the 
Greeks  looked  but  dismally  into  the  future,  and  their  ethics 
knows  nothing  of  hope  as  a  virtue ;  in  the  Old  Testament, 
however,  we  meet  with  it  almost  on  every  page ;  it  is  the 
key-note  of  the  religiously-moral  life,  constantly  bursting  out 
in  inspired  strains ;  the  Christian's  hope,  as  fulfilled  in  Christ, 
awakens  and  gives  ground  for  new  hope. 

As  all  virtue  Avhatever  is  a  force  and  a  motive  to  moral  ac 
tion,  much  more  is  this  true  of  the  piety-virtues.  All  moral 
action  directs  itself  essentially  toward  a  yet  to  be  attained 
good,  and  which  consequently  exists  primarily  only  in  thought ; 
hence  the  moral  motive  is  not  merely  love  to  an  existing  en 
tity,  but  at  the  same  time  also  love  to  a,  as  yet,  not  existing 
one,  to  a  merely  conceived  one,  the  realization  of  which,  how 
ever,  is,  in  virtue  of  our  love  to  the  truly  existing  primative 
ground  of  all  morality,  absolutely  sure  to  us, — hence  it  is, 
essentially,  faith  in  the  living  and  truthful  God,  and  hope  of 
the  realization  of  the  highest  good.  In  virtue  of  this  pious 
believing  and  hoping,  as  springing  from  our  love  to  God, 
fidelity  in  our  temporal  calling  becomes  joyous  perseverance  ; 
and  in  our  working  for  the  spiritual  and  the  eternal,  it  be 
comes  enthusiasm. 

Observation.  The  systematic  development  of  the  cardinal 
virtues  has  ever  been  one  of  the  most  weighty  and  difficult 
points  in  ethics.  Plato  was  the  first  to  present  the  four  vir 
tues,  which  were  adopted  by  Sts.  Ambrose  and  Augustine,  and 
which  then  held  sway  through  the  entire  Middle  Ages  and  up 
to  the  most  recent  times ;  and  to  these  were  added  and  super- 
ordinated,  without  any  clear  connection,  the  three  theological 
virtues  (§  31).  The  Greek  classification  of  the  virtires  is, 
however,  entirely  unadapted  to  the  Christian  notion  of  virtue, 
as  the  violent  construction  of  them,  to  which  even  Augustine 
had  to  resort,  abundantly  manifests ;  while  with  the  Greeks 
the  fundamental  virtue  was  wisdom,  in  Christianity  it  is  love, 
love  to  the  loving,  personal  God ;  this  love  to  God  was  en- 


§  140.]  PURE   ETHICS.  301 

tirely  lacking  to  the  Greeks,  because  with  them  its  certain 
object  was  also  lacking.     Protestant  ethics  sought  out,  there 
fore,  with  a  correcter  consciousness,  new  paths,  and  that  too 
from  the  very  beginning  (§  37).     The  three  cardinal  virtues 
of  Calvin :  sbbrietas,  justitia,  pietas,  do  not,  however,  exhaust 
the  material,  and  they  admit  of  no  proper  organic  union,  be 
cause  pietas  is  not  co-ordinate  to  the  other  two,  but  super- 
ordinate.     Scbleieniiacher's  cardinal  virtues  (§  48)  :  wisdom, 
love,  discretion  and  perseverance,  are,  in  spite  of  all  the  dia 
lectical  skill  bestowed  in  their  development,  of  a  merely  ar 
tificial  character,  and  are  least  of  all  adapted  to  Christian 
ethics, — to  which  in  fact  he  does  not  apply  them ;  the  Platonic 
virtues  admit  of  a  much  more  natural  development.     In  the 
system  of  Schleiermacher,  love  is  by  no  means  presented  in  its 
full  Christian  significancy,  least  of  all  as  love  to  God  (which 
is  in  fact  regarded  as  an  unapt  expression),  but  it  is  presented 
only  as  the  "vivifying  virtue,  as  working  forth  out  of  itself 
into  the  world,  namely,  into  nature," — as  manifesting  reason 
in  its  action  upon  nature ;  reason  is  the  loving  element,  nature 
the  loved ;  love  to  God  is  true  only  as  love  to  nature  (Syst. 
§§  296,  303  sqq.)  ;  this  is  almost  the  very  opposite  of  the  Chris 
tian  notion  of  love.     C.  F.  Schmid  accepts  this  classification 
under  a  more  Christian  form,  without,  however,  developing 
it  in  greater  fullness  (Christl.  Sittenl.,  p.  528). — Most  peculiar 
of  all  is  Rothe's  classification  (Eih.  1  ed.,  §  645  sqq.}.     He  gives 
two  virtues  of  the  self-consciousness  or  rationality,  and  two 
virtues  of  self-activity  or  freedom.     (1.)  Individually-determ 
ined  rationality  is  geniality, — aptness  for  an  absolutely  in 
dividual  cognizing,  so  that  the  same  can  absolutely  be  accom 
plished  by  no  other  person — the  artistic  virtue  proper;  to  it 
belong   courage,    cornposedness,   modesty,    grace, '  sympathy, 
confidence,    etc.     (2.)    Universally-determined  rationality   is 
wisdom — aptness  for  a  universal  cognizing,  so  that  the  same 
may  absolutely  be  accomplished  by  every  other  spirit  in  the 
same  manner ;  it  appears  under  the  forms  of  considerateness, 
impartialness,  sobriety,  instructiveness,  benevolence,  fairness, 
etc.     (3.)  Individually  determined  freedom  is  originality,  the 
virtue  which  specifically  qualifies  for  individual  forming, — the 
social  virtue  proper ;  to  it  belong  valor,  temperateuess,  chas 
tity,   dignity,    unselfishness,  fidelity,  etc.      (4.)   Universally- 


302  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  141. 

determined  freedom  is  the  strength  which  leads  to  a  universal 
forming,  that  is,  to  laboring  and  acquiring, — the  public  or 
civic  virtue  proper ;  it  appears  under  the  forms  of  persistence, 
patience,  self-control,  eloquence,  beneficence,  magnanimity, 
etc. 


II.  MORAL  COMMUNION  AS  A  FRUIT  OF  THE  MORAL 
LIFE. 

SECTION   CXLI. 

All  moral  activity  is  of  a  communion-forming  char 
acter,  and  all  true  communion  is  an  expression  of 
love, — in  nature  an  expression  of  immanent  divine 
love,  in  humanity,  an  expression  of  human  love. 
The  highest  end  of  the  moral  life  is  indeed  the 
full  morally-acquired  communion  with  God,  but  man, 
as  an  individual  being  placed  in  natural  and  spiritual 
relations  to  other  creatures,  fulfills  his  moral  destiny 
not  in  an  exclusive  communion  with  God,  but  only  in 
a  communing  at  the  same  time  with  the  children  of 
God,  and  hence  he  has  it  as  a  moral  duty  to  form 
this  his  relation  to  other  men  into  a  moral  com 
munion,  without  which  his  personal  perfection  cannot 
be  reached.  The  most  primitive  natural  communion 
is  sexual  communion,  from  which  naturally  arises 
the  second  form,  that  between  parents  and  children ; 
both  forms  are  to  be  raised  from  the  merely  natural, 
to  the  moral  communion  of  the  family. 

As  all  love  presupposes  some  form  of  communion,  though  it 
be  ante-moral  and  merely  natural,  hence  the  moral  forming  of 
this  communion  is  not  an  absolutely  new  creating  of  a  com 
munion,  but  the  spiritual  exalting  of  one  that  already  exists 
naturally.  Though  moral  communion  with  God  is  the  highest 
good,  still  this  does  not  exclude,  but  includes,  a  communing 
with  other  rational  creatures,  for  God  is  himself  in  communion 


§  141.]  PURE  ETHICS.  303 

with  them.  Mystical  quietism  is  but  a  refined  self-seeking, 
and  conflicts  with  the  essence  of  Christianity ;  for  God  did 
not'  create  mere  isolated  beings,  but  destined  them  for  each 
other;  "  it  is  not  good,"  not  in  harmony  with  the  moral  desti 
nation  of  the  race,  "  that  man  should  be  alone,"  for  an  isolated 
person  lacks  a  very  essential  sphere  of  moral  activity — that 
upon  which  he  can  not  only  (as  in  his  relation  to  God)  appro 
priate  and  obey,  and  not  only  (as  in  his  relation  to  nature) 
dominate,  but  also,  as  relating  to  beings  like  himself,  form 
and  appropriate  at  the  same  time  in  mutual  moral  reciprocity. 
Without  moral  communion  with  other  men  morality  cannot 
come  to  its  full  development ;  communion  is  not  a  mere  inact 
ive  condition,  but  it  is  a  productive  good,  a  condition  of  new, 
higher  morality.  This  of  itself  is  a  condemnation  of  the  her 
mit-life  ;  of  such  a  life  the  Scriptures  'know  nothing ;  solitude 
may  indeed  be  salutary  as  a  preliminary  preparation  for  a  call 
ing  that  requires  great  collection  of  soul  [Luke  i,  80],  as  in 
deed  the  Son  of  man  himself  resorted  thereto  for  a  while 
[Matt,  iv] ;  but  the  Sabbath-introspection  of  the  soul  cannot, 
as  opposed  to  an  active  life  among  men,  be  made  the  exclu 
sively-legitimate  life.  The  recluse  life,  even  where  the 
severest  discipline  is  exercised  against  the  sinful  nature,  is  an 
immoral  renouncing  of  the  moral  duties  of  man  toward  his 
fellows,  a  dissolving  of  the  kingdom  of  God  into  mere  atoms, 
into  mere  isolated  individuals,  and  hence  it  was  utterly  foreign 
to  the  earliest  Church. 

The  communion  of  man  with  his  fellows  is  primarily  of  a 
merely  natural  character;  but  man  is  to  have  in  his  whole 
being  and  nature,  and  above  all  in  his  spiritual  nature,  nothing 
which  he  has  merely  naturally  received  and  not  also  morally 
appropriated  to,  and  formed  for,  himself.  The  communion 
of  the  sexes,  as  well  as  that  between  parents  and  children,  is 
primarily  as  yet  extra-moral, — does  not  yet  distinguish  man 
from  the  brute ;  both  forms  of  communion  need  to  be  raised 
to  a  moral  character,  otherwise  they  will  sink  to  an  immoral 
one ;  even  parental  love  may  be  sinful. 


304  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  142. 

(a)  THE  FAMILY. 
SECTION  CXLII. 

Natural  sexual  love  is,  as  a  manifestation  of  the 
divine  love  ruling  in  nature,  per  se  a  type  of  moral 
communion,  but  it  does  not  itself  suffice  to  create  this. 
The  merely  natural,  and  hence  extra  moral,  element 
of  the  same  is  confined  entirely  to  the  unconscious 
natural  inclination  ;  the  exalting  of  the  mere  inclina 
tion'  to  real  love  is  never  an  ante-moral  or  extra- 
moral  process,  but  springs  of  moral  determination  ; 
the  actual  accomplishing  of  the  sexual  communion 
should  never  follow  upon  mere  natural  love,  but 
must,  as  a  free  act,  be  simply  a  manifestation  of  the 
already  realized  moral  communion  of  the  persons  in 
virtue  of  moral  love.  Without  this  condition  it  is 
not  extra-moral,  but  anti-moral,  as  an  actual  destruc 
tion  of  moral  communion. 

Sexual  communion  is  the  first  possible  communion,  and 
hence  has  in  nature  its  first  incitation.  As  man  was  not  an 
absolutely  other  and  new  creation  but  the  divinely-animated 
nature-creature,  so  also  is  the  first  moral  communion  not  one 
that  was  absolutely  new-created  by  man,  but  a  morally- 
exalted  natural  communion.  Sexual  love  prevails  throughout 
animated  nature, — is  its  highest  life-function,  and,  therefore, 
also  the  highest  manifestation  of  the  divine  love  as  ruling 
in  nature  The  flower  develops  in  its  sexual  bloom  its  highest 
force  and  splendor ;  the  brute  has,  in  sexual  love,  the  highest 
pleasure-feeling,  that  of  a  perfect,  mutually  life-unifying  har 
mony  with  its  like;  it  is  the  feeling  that  it  is  not  a  mere  iso 
lated  unit,  but  a  living  member  of  a  higher  whole.  It  is  not 
man's  duty  to  suppress  this  life-manifestation,  but  to  exalt 
it,  — to  raise  the  unconsciously-prevailing  love  of  the  animal 
into  a  conscious  and  moral  love.  Though  in  idea  the  same, 
the  sexes  are  in  reality  different,  mutually  complementing 
each  other  to  the  full  idea  of  man.  The  somewhat  clumsy 


§  142.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  305 

myth  as  to  the  original  androgynous  forms  of  humanity,  as 
given  in  Plato's  Symposium^  is  but  a.  distorted  echo  of  the 
thought,  much  more  suggestively  expressed  in  the  Biblical 
account,  of  the  formation  of  Eve  from  a  rib  of  Adam. 

Love,  according  to  its  inner  idea,  is  not  only  preservative 
but  also  communicative,  awakening  new  life  and  promoting 
it ;  hence  the  propagation  of  the  human  race  is  conditioned 
on  the  highest  earthly  love.  All  l<5ve  is  an  appropriating  and 
a  forming  at  the  same  time.  In  sexual  love  the  sexes  mutually 
appropriate  and  form  each  other  as  natural  beings,  though  in 
different  degrees;  the  spiritually  moral  appropriating  and 
forming  must,  however,  precede  the  natural,  as  its  moral 
consecration  and  conditionment ;  the  reversing  of  this  rela 
tion,  the  letting  the  moral  and  personal  love  simply  follow 
the  sexual  communion,  is  morally  impossible,  as  thereby  the 
latter  is  degraded  to  a  purely  bestial,  immoral  character,  and 
cannot  become  the  starting-point  of  a  moral  communion. 

A  possession  is  moral  only  as  property,  that  is,  in  virtue  of 
its  having  been  morally-acquired  and  appropriated ;  now  the 
communion  of  the  sexes  is  the  complete  giving  up  and  appro 
priating  of  each  party  as  the  property  of  the  other ;  hence 
when  it  is  not  a  manifestation  and  fruit  of  an  already-accom 
plished,  morally-personal,  spiritual  unity, — of  the  appropria 
tion  of  the  persons  as  moral  and  hence  as  permanent  inalienable 
property, — it  is  then  not  only  not  a  simply  natural  action  but 
an  immoral  throwing  away  of  one's  moral  personality,  an  ir 
remediable  ruining  of  th£  moral  personality  of  the  other. 
Lost  innocence  is  irrecoverable  ;  mere  sexual  communion 
without  moral  love  is  a  defamation.  But  moral  love  is  in  its 
very  essence  permanent ;  that  which  is  by  love  appropriated 
to  the  person  as  property  is  inalienable, — can  be  destroyed  only 
with  the  personality  itself.  Whoredom  is  not  mere  bestiality, 
but,  as  a  moral  self-abandonment,  it  is  below  bestiality;  for 
the  brute  does  not  throw  itself  away.  Even  in  the  case  of 
the  first  man,  moral  love  preceded  sexual  communion.  "  And 
Adam  said:  this  is  now  bone  of  my  bones  and  flesh  of  my 
flesh;  she  shall  be  called  woman,  because  she  was  taken  out 
of  man"  [Gen.  ii,  23  sqq.].  This  is  a  child-like,  natural  ex 
pression  of  moral  love,  the  full  consciousness  of  the  harmony 
and  unity  between  man  and  wife ;  the  wife  is  the  man's  other 
VOL.  11—21 


306  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§143. 

ego,  belongs  to  him,  is  destined  to  him  as  property,  as  also  he 
to  her;  she  is  of,  and  for,  him.  Hence  to  this  expression  of 
moral  love  joins  itself,  as  a  sequence,  the  further  thought : 
' '  therefore  shall  a  man  leave  his  father  and  his  mother  and  shall 
cleave  unto  his  wife,  and  they  shall  be  one  flesh  ;"  the  becom 
ing  one  in  the  flesh  follows  only  from  and  upon  the  being 
one  in  spirit ;  they  become  one  also  sexually,  because  they 
have  mutually  recognized  each  other  as  joined  in  a  personally- 
spiritual  unity.  The  moral  consciousness  of  the  personal  be 
longing  of  the  one  to  the  other,  the  free  recognition  of  their 
mutually-possessing  each  other  as  property,  is  the  indispens 
able  antecedent  moral  condition  of  sexual  communion.  With 
out  this  moral  condition,  that  which  is  the  acme  of  the  nature- 
life,  the  innermost  center  of  nature-mysteries,  the  synthesis 
of  all  that  is  wonderful  in  nature-force,  namely,  the  generative 
act, — which,  as  moral,  is  a  sacred  act, — becomes  an  absolutely 
immoral  one,  and  sinks  man  toward  the  brute  more  than  any 
other  natural  action. 

SECTION  CXLIII. 

Moral  sexual  love  being  a  love  of  the  persons  to 
each  other,  and  the  moral  personality  of  the  one 
being  per  se  equal  to  that  of  the  other  in  moral  worth, 
and  consequently  also  in  moral  rights,  hence  that 
giving  up  of  the  one  person,  as  a  complete  moral 
possession,  to  the  other,  which  is  required  by  sexual 
communion,  is  only  then  possible  when  this  sur 
render  is  a  mutual  one,  that  is,  when  the  two  persons 
belong  to  each  other  exclusively ;  and  hence  moral 
sexual  love  exists  only  in  the  marriage  of  two  per 
sons,  in  view  of  sexual  communion  and  consequently 
of  complete  personal  life-communion.  Polygamy  is 
morally  impossible, — is  but  legally  regulated  whore 
dom,  makes  a  real  personal  love-surrender,  and  hence 
marriage  itself,  impossible.  For  the  same  reason, 
marriage  is  morally  indissoluble.  Marriage  is  not  a 
mere  right,  is  not  simply  allowed,  but  it  is  a  divinely- 


§  143.]  PURE   ETHICS.  '  307 

willed  and  expressly  ordained  moral  communion,  and 
hence  the  entering  upon  it  is  not  a  merely  natural 
but  also  a  religious  action,  which,  standing  as  it  does 
under  the  express  promise  of  the  divine  blessing,  is 
very  naturally  invested  with  a  religious  consecration. 

The  extra-Christian  notion  of  polygamy  absolutely  excludes 
the  moral  essence  of  marriage  •,  in  it  the  woman  is  indeed  the 
man's  property,  but  not  man  the  woman's ;  this  involves  a  dif 
ference  in  the  moral  worth  and  rights  of  the  sexes,  which, 
from  a  moral  stand-point,  is  impossible;  for  it  denies  the 
moral  personality  of  the  woman ;  and  in  fact,  in  polygamy, 
woman  is  only  a  slave.  Of  the  polygamy  of  the  .Old  Testa 
ment  it  is  not  here  the  place  to  speak.  The  primitive  divine 
institution  of  marriage  recognizes  only  the  marriage  with  one 
woman,  and  the  New  Testament  presupposes  this  throughout 
[Matt,  xix,  3  sqq. ;  1  Cor.  vii,  2 ;  xi,  11 ;  Eph,  v,  28 ;  1  Tim. 
iii,  2]. 

As  marriage  rests  entirely  on  personal  love  to  a  person, 
hence  it  is  not  a  mere  legal  relation ;  and  as  in  it  the  persons 
belong  entirely  to  each  other, — are  to  each  other  a  mutual 
property,  the  essence  and  strength  of  which  is  love, — hence 
to  view  marriage  as  a  merely  legal  relation  not  only  falls  be 
low  the  moral  idea  of  marriage,  but  is  per  se  immoral,  for  a 
contract-relation  presupposes  the  non-presence  of  mutually- 
confiding  love, — excludes  a  perfect  moral  life-and-body-com- 
munion,  the  reciprocal  belonging  to  each  other  as  a  moral 
property ;  on  the  contrary,  such  a  contract  tends  to  raise  be 
tween  the  two  persons,  as  exclusively  bent  on  their  personal 
advantage,  the  separation-wall  of  distrust,  and  delivers  the 
one  consort  to  the  other  for  mere  stipulated  service  and  use. 
As  little  as  a  contract-relation  is  conceivable  between  parents 
and  children  in  their  mutual  family  duties,  just  so  little  is  it 
morally  possible  between  husband  and  wife.  Sexual  com 
munion  when  based  on  a  mere  legal  contract  is  only  respect 
able  concubinage ;  it  stands  essentially  on  an  equal  footing 
with  polygamy. — The  generating  of  children  is  not  so  much 
the  purpose  as  rather  the  blessing  of  marriage ;  its  purpose  is 
absolutely  the  fulfilling  of  moral  love ;  marriage  is  and  con 
tinues  in  full  validity  even  where  this  blessing  is  wanting. 


308  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§143. 

The  legal  principle  that  "the  chief  end  of  marriage  is  the 
generating  and  training  of  children,"  is  consistent  rather 
with  a  legalized  concubinage  or  with  polygamy  than  with  the 
moral  idea  of  marriage,  and  would  in  consistency  require  that 
barrenness  be  regarded  as  a  perfectly  valid  ground  for  di 
vorce. 

For  the  simple  reason  that  consorts  belong  to  each  other  as 
moral  property,  marriage  admits  morally  of  no  dissolution.  A 
moral  property  is  inseparably  united  with  the  moral  peculiarity, 
and  hence  with  the  personal  essence  of  the  individual, — is, 
like  this  essence,  inalienable.  It  is  as  impossible  morally  to 
dissolve  a  marriage  as  it  is  for  a  person  to  separate  from  his 
personal  life,  his  peculiar  character,  and  hence  from  his  own 
self;  and,  as  a  violent  internal  anarchy  of  the  spirit,  namely, 
in  insanity,  is  conceivable  only  in  a  sinfully-disordered  state, 
so  also  is  a  dissolution  of  marriage  conceivable  only  in  a  state 
of  sinfully  morbid  disorder, — it  is  in  fact  an  ethical  insanity, 
a  moral  ruin  of  the  two  self-separating  consorts.  Christ  affirms 
this  moral  impossibility  of  divorce  [Matt,  xix,  3-9],  and  bases 
his  doctrine  on  this  significant  reason:  "They  are  no  more 
twain,  but  one  flesh ;  what  therefore  God  hath  joined  together, 
let  not  man  put  asunder."  This  is  not  two  reasons  but  only 
one ;  God  has  joined  together  marriage  in  his  primative  institut 
ing  of  it,  that  is,  by  his  creative  will,  which  established  the  es 
sence  of  marriage  to  consist  in  the  fact  that  the  two  consorts 
should  be  one  flesh,  one  single  absolutely  inseparable  life  as 
to  soul  and  body,  even  as  every  living  body  is  a  single  in 
separable  whole,  and  any  dissevering  of  it,  the  death  of  the 
same.  The  indissolubility  of  marriage  is  still  more  strongly 
emphasized  by  Christ  by  his  citing  the  words  of  the  Creator 
at  its  institution :  ' '  For  this  cause  shall  a  man  leave  father 
and  mother,  and  shall  cleave  to  his  wife,  and  they  twain  shall 
l>e  one  flesh."  Man  is  not  to  abandon  his  father  and  mother 
with  his  love,  though  he  may  outwardly  withdraw  from  them 
in  order  ta  b,uild  up  a  family  of  his  own;  but  still  more  inti 
mate  than  the  bond  between  parents  and  children,  is  the  bond 
between  husband  and  wife,  who  mutually  fully  belong  to  each 
other.  Now  if  the  bond  of , love  and  unity  between  parents 
und  children  can  never  be  dissolved  without  great  moral  vio 
lence,  still  less  can  the  bond  between  husband  and  wife  be 


§  143.]  PURE   ETHICS.  309 

morally  dissolved.  The  unity  of  the  "flesh"  is  not  to  be 
understood  merely,  nor  even  chiefly,  of  the  bodily  union,  but 
alludes  to  the  highest  and  perfect  moral  union  of  the  whole 
life  of  both  body  and  soul.  A  merely  spiritual  unity  is  desig 
nated  by  jj-in  napSia  xai  ^v^  [Acts  iv,  32],  but  husband  and 
wife  are  also  elf  piuv  aapKa  [1  Cor.  vi,  16;  comp.  vii,  4;  Epb. 
v,  28  sqq."\.-  Adultery  alone  works  divorce,  and  all  divorce  is 
in  its  moral  essence  adultery  [comp.  1  Cor.  vii,  10],  and,  as  re 
lating  to  the  children,  a  ruthless  annihilating  of  the  family. 

It  is  of  high  significancy  that  the  Scriptures  expressly  affirm 
the  divine  institution  of  marriage,  and  give  to  moral  marriage 
a  promise  of  special  blessing  [Gen.  i,  28 ;  ii,  24 ;  ix,  7 ;  Matt. 
xix,  4;  comp.  Psa.  cxxviii,  3;  cxxvii,  3-5].  Hence  marriage 
cannot  in  any  sense  be  implicated  in  unsanctity  or  lowness,  so 
as  to  be  inconsistent  with  a  truly  spiritual  and  holy  life ; 
otherwise  God,  when  he  introduced  woman  to  man  as  called 
to  be  holy,  would  have  encouraged  him  to  turn  aside  from  his 
high  destination,  and  Adam  would  have  had  not  merely  the 
right  but  in  fact  also  the  duty  of  declining  this  gift  of  divine 
love ;  the  creation  of  the  woman  would  really  have  been  the 
first  temptation.  In  a  normal,  uncorrupted  state  of  humanity 
it  is  not  only  the  right,  but  also  the  duty,  of  the  morally  and 
corporeally  mature  individual  to  live  in  this  God-instituted 
state  of  marriage ;  it  is  not  marriage  itself  but  the  particular 
choice  of  the  consort  that  is  left  to  the  particular,  personal 
preference  of  love.  God's  declaration:  "It  is  not  good  that 
the  man  should  be  alone ;  I  will  make  him  an  help-meet  for 
him,"  distinctly  implies  that  celibacy  per  se  is  not  the  better 
but  the  less  good  state, — as  well  for  man,  for  he  ought  to  have 
a  help-meet,  as  also  for  woman,  for  her  express  destination  is 
to  be  a  help-meet  for  the  man.  Of  the  relations  of  marriage 
after  the  fall  into  sin,  it  is  not  here  the  place  to  speak. 

The  fact  that  in  all  not  totally  savage  nations  marriage  is 
not  constituted  simply  by  the  consent  of  the  two  persons,  but 
by  some  sort  of  solemn  and,  most  usually,  religious  ceremony, 
is  a  significant  implication  of  the  moral  essence  of  marriage ; 
and  the  importance  that  a  people  places  on  the  religiously- 
moral  consecration  of  marriage,  is  a  pretty  safe  criterion  of 
its  morality  in  relation  to  the  sexual  life. 


310  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  144. 

SECTION  CXLIV. 

The  two  consorts  stand  to  each  other,  as  moral  per 
sons,  on  an  equal  footing ;  they  both  find  their  union 
in  a  complete  devoted  love,  and  hence,  in  fact,  in  a 
loving,  free  subordination  to  the  moral  law.  The 
consorts  complement  each  other  also  in  spiritually- 
moral  respects;  and  it  is  only  in  respect  to  this  har 
mony-conditioning  complementing  that  the  woman  is 
in  many  things  rather  guided  than  self-determining. 
This,  however,  is  not  a  real  domination  of  the  man  over 
the  woman  as  over  a  subject,  but  only  a  conditional 
super-ordination  of  the  man  as  the  actively-guiding 
unity-point  of  the  common  life.  As  a  moral  relation 
marriage  rests  on  freedom,  that  is,  on  free  mutual 
choice ;  consequently  it  presupposes  the  moral  matu 
rity  of  the  two  lovers.  This  freedom  of  choice,  how 
ever,  is  not  irrational  caprice,  but  determines  itself 
in  view  of  the  true  life-harmonizing,  reciprocally-com 
plementing,  personal  peculiarity  of  the  two  parties, 
and  receives  its  moral  ratification  by  its  being  freely 
recognized  on  the  part  of  the  moral  community,  and 
primarily  of  the  family. 

But  moral  equality  is  not  sameness.  As  the  final  destina 
tion  of  all  moral  beings  is  the  same,  hence  a  difference  of  the 
moral  worth  of  the  sexes  is  not  conceivable  [Gal.  iii,  28 ; 
1  Pet.  iii,  7J.  The  inferior  position  of  the  female  sex  in  all 
non-Christian  nations  is  a  sign  of  moral  unculture,  which  even 
the  Greeks  did  not  entirely  put  off.  The  account  of  the  crea 
tion  of  woman  indicates  her  true  dignity ;  taken  from  man's 
heart,  she  belongs  to  man's  heart,  and  is  not  a  slave  at  his 
feet;  she  is  a  part  of  him, — is  not  merely  flesh  of  his  flesh 
but  also  soul  of  his  soul.  The  antithesis  of  sex.  which  is  not 
of  a  merely  bodily  character,  conditions  indeed  also  very  differ 
ent  moral  duties ;  but  these  duties  are  absolutely  equal  in 
moral  worth.  The  precedency  of  the  woman  in  the  interior 


§144.]  PURE   ETHICS.  311 

of  the  family  is  in  no  respect  less  than  that  of  the  man  in  the 
civic  sphere  ;  and  though,  in  virtue  of  this  difference,  the  wom 
an  is,  in  many  respects, — especially  in  those  of  the  external, 
public  life,  that  is,  of  the  outward-directed  activity, — prop 
erly  subject  to  the  man  as  the  natural  leader  in  this  sphere 
[Eph.  v,  22,  23],  yet,  as  an  offset  to  this,  the  man  is  in  his 
turn  properly  dependent  on  the  womaft  in  the  sphere  of 
female  activity;  it  is  not  to  the  credit  of  the  man  to  dominate 
in  the  kitchen  and  nursery.  Each  rules,  by  the  constitution 
of  nature,  in  his  own  sphere ;  and  it  is  perfectly  in  order  for 
the  woman,  in  her  sphere,  to  exercise  a  determining  influence 
on  the  man  (§  69).  The  historical  tyrant-relation  of  the  man 
over  the  woman  is  not  the  original  and  true  one,  and  is  incon 
sistent  with  true  confiding  love  and  with  the  dignity  of 
womanhood,  and  is  expressly  explained  in  the  Scriptures  as  a 
punishment  for  sin  [Gen.  iii,  16].  On  the  other  hand,  how 
ever,  a-  certain  guiding  super-ordination  of  the  man  is  the 
original  and  normal  relation,  and  is  in  no  respect  a  fruit  of  the 
fall ;  Adam  was  as  guilty  as  Eve ;  sin  was  effectual  only  in 
changing  the  original  normal  subordination  of  the  woman 
into  a  relation  of  senitude.  Though  the  woman  is,  in  more 
than  one  respect,  the  "  weaker  vessel "  [1  Pet.  iii,  7],  neverthe 
less  she  is  a  "  co-heir  of  grace ; "  and  she  has,  though  indeed 
another  and  peculiar,  yet  not  a  less  noble  moral  life-task  than 
the  man ;  as  the  help-meet  of  man  it  is  hers  faithfully  to  pre 
serve  and  foster  that  which  the  stronger  and  more  independ 
ent-willed  man  actively  creates.  The  strong  vital  initiative, 
the  fixing  of  the  goal,  and  the  task  of  producing,  are  the  work 
of  the  man ;  in  this  work  the  woman  is  to  be  for  him,  to  aid 
him,  to  have  him  for  the  vital  central-point  of  the  activity 
peculiar  to  her  [1  Cor.  xi,  8,  9].  Though  the  woman  had 
first  sinned,  and  the  man  was  thus  led  astray  by  her,  yet  the 
offended  and  sentencing  God  turns  himself  first  to  Adam,  and 
requires  account  of  him,  and  then  afterward  to  Eve;  Adam 
was  in  duty  required  to  strengthen  and  dissuade  the  yielding 
and  sinning  woman,  and  not  to  let  himself  be  led  by  her. 

The  contracting  of  marriage  is  neither  a  mere  business- 
transaction  nor  a  fruit  of  a  simple  falling  in  love ;  where 
moral  love  does  not  form  the  marriage,  there  it  is  desecrated. 
Hence  marriages  cannot  be  planned  and  brought  about  simply 


312  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  144. 

by  parents,  no  more  than  can  the  parents  practice  virtue  for 
their  children;  the  moral  must  be  accomplished  by  each  for 
himself.  The  free  personal  choice  that  is  absolutely  neces 
sary  to  marriage  proper  is  not  to  be  made  arbitrarily  or  by 
hap-hazard ;  it  aims  essentially  at  the  realization  of  the  com 
plete  life-unity  of  the  two  persons,  to  the  end  of  moral  com 
munion.  This  unity,  and  hence  this  perfect  harmony,  pre 
supposes  a  difference  and  at  the  same  time  a  similarity  of  the 
spiritually  and  bodily  self-complementing  persons.  The  dif 
ference  consists  in  the  normal  spiritual  and  corporeal  antithe 
sis  of  the  sexes  in  general,  and,  in  particular,  in  the  respective 
peculiarity  of  the  persons,  which  finds,  largely,  in  the  opposite 
peculiarity  its  complement,  and  hence  its  moral  satisfaction ; 
a  fiery,  impassioned  temperament  is  advantageously  comple 
mented  by  one  that  is  gentle  and  calm.  The  similarity  con 
sists  in  the  essential  agreement  of  the  persons,  not  merely  in 
their  moral  and  spiritual,  but  also  in  their  physical  peculiari 
ties, — a  similarity  which  can  well  exist  in  the  midst  of  large 
difference.  Without  the  similarity  there  would  be  no  una 
nimity  ;  without  the  difference  there  would  be  no  mutual  com 
plementing,  and  hence  no  mutual  attraction.  The  selecting 
for  marriage  is  a  finding  of  the  complementing  personality, 
and  is  free  and  unt'ree  at  the  same  time.  There  lies,  indeed, 
in  this  finding,  something  of  the  mysterious,  something  which 
transcends  the  dialectical  consciousness ;  and  an  anticipatory 
feeling  antecedes,  even  in  a  normal  state  of  things,  the  definite 
recognizing  of  the  person ;  the  matter  should  not  rest,  how 
ever,  at  the  stage  of  mere  feeling,  but  the  person  should  at 
once  exalt  it  to  a  rational  consciousness, — should  transfigure 
the  ante-moral  love-feeling  into  rational  love. 

The  morally-rational  character  of  the  contracting  of  mar 
riage  is  recognized  by  usages  prevalent  among  all  not  utterly 
uncultured  nations,  and  is  guaranteed  by  the  fact  that  it  is 
not  left  to  the  mere  discretion  of  the  individuals,  but  is  sub 
ject  to  the  ratifying  recognition  of  the  moral  community,  and 
hence  primarily  of  the  parents  concerned  [comp.  1  Cor.  vii, 
37].  Though  parents  are  not  entitled  so  far  to  represent  their 
children  as  to  choose  consorts  for  them,  yet  they  arc  perfectly 
entitled  to  ratify  the  choice  of  their  children  by  their 
approval. 


§145.]  PURE   ETHICS.  313 

SECTION  CXLV. 

Marriage  as  productive  is  the  basis  of  the  more  ex- 
tended  family ,  which,  like  marriage,  is  not  a  merely 
natural  but  essentially  a  moral  relation.  The  family 
members  stand  to  each  other  either  in  the  relation  of 
equality,  as  husband  and  wife  or  as  brothers  and  sis 
ters,  or  in  that  of  super-ordination  and  subordination, 
as  parents  and  children.  The  relation  between  par 
ents  and  children  is  the  iirst  inequality  among  men, 
and  the  presupposition  and  type  of  all  other  relations 
of  super-ordination  and  subordination.  Parents  and 
children  stand  to  each  other  in  the  relation  of  moral 
personalities,  and  hence  also  of  mutual  moral  duties ; 
parents  have,  in  relation  to  their  children,  prepon- 
deratingly  the  duty  of  forming,  and  hence  of  educat 
ing,  during  the  progress  of  which,  however,  the  con 
stantly  and  necessarily  therewith-connected  duty  of 
sparing,  rises  gradually  to  greater  prominence  as  the 
development  advances,  until  finally  it  predominates, 
and  the  child  has  attained  to  its  moral  majority.  As, 
however,  in  a  process  of  normal  development,  the 
parents  also  constantly  advance  spiritually  and  mor 
ally,  hence  they  always  retain  their  super-ordinate 
relation  to  the  children  even  as  matured ;  their  form 
ative  influence  on  the  children  can  never  cease,  and 
never  gives  place  to  a  relation  of  moral  equality  with 
them.  The  children,  on  their  part,  continue  always, 
though  not  in  a  constantly  like  manner,  subject  to 
the  parents  in  reverential  obedience,  which,  however, 
as  itself  resting  upon  love  to  God,  is  ever  also  con 
ditioned  thereby. 

The  difference  between  consorts  and  blood-relatives  rests  on 
the   difference  between  moral  and  natural  communion.     In 


314  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  145. 

both  cases  the  communion  is  not  only  spiritually-moral  but 
also  corporeally-natural.  With  consorts,  however,  the  bodily- 
natural  communion  rests  on  an  antecedent  moral  communion ; 
and  with  blood-relatives  the  moral  communion  rests  on  the 
precedent  corporeally-natural  communion;  the  former  become 
corporeally  one  because  they  love  each  other,  the  latter  love 
each  other  because  in  blood  they  are  already  one ;  the  former 
proceed  from  an  original  state  of  separation,  toward  union ; 
the  latter  tend  from  their  original  union  to  a  state  of  separa 
tion  ;  blood-relationship  proper  precludes  sexual  communion. 
The  fact  that  relatives  are  bound  to  each  other  by  especially 
clos£  bonds  of  love  [Gen.  xiii,  8,  9 ;  xiv,  14  sqq. ;  xviii,  23 
sqq. ;  xxix,  13  sqq. ;  Exod.  xviii,  5  sqq.  ;  Ruth  i;  ii,  20;  Luke 
i,  38,  40,  58;  comp.  Job  xix,  13;  Psa.  xxxi,  12;  Ixix,  8],Tloes 
not  conflict  with  the  more  general  love  of  neighbor. 

In  the  family  begins,  now,  moral  society  with  all  its  normal 
differences.  Husband  and  wife  do  not  as  yet  constitute  a  so 
ciety,  for  they  are  one  flesh ;  nor  do  parents  and  children  form 
one,  for  although  they  are  one  spirit,  yet  they  stand  to  each 
other  in  the  relation  of  super-ordination  and  subordination. 
Persons  who  are  entirely  alike,  and  who  stand  to  each  other  in 
absolutely  like  relations,  constitute  indeed  a  multitude,  but 
not  a  society;  where  there  is  no  vital  all-guiding  nucleus,  no 
throbbing  heart  for  the  body,  no  soul  for  the  acting  members, 
there  there  is  no  living  whole,  no  society.  Inequality,  unlike- 
ness,  lies  in  the  essence  of  every  moral  society, — not  an  in 
equality  of  the  moral  rights  of  personalities,  but  an  inequality, 
a  difference,  of  spiritually-moral  position  in  and  relation  to 
society.  Parents  are  the  first  princes,  and  true  princes  are  the 
fathers  of  their  people ;  patres  was  the  title  of  distinction  of 
the  Roman  senators ;  ' '  elders  "  is  used  in  a  like  sense  for  the 
leaders  of  moral  society  in  almost  all  the  free  constitutions  of 
antiquity  and  also  of  the  church.  Parents  are  the  guides  of 
their  children  by  the  grace  of  God,  for  children  are  a  gift  of 
divine  grace  [Gen.  xxi,  1 ;  xxv,  21 ;  xxix,  31 ;  xxx,  6,  17  sqq.; 
xxxiii,  5;  Exod.  xxiii,  26;  Deut.  vii,  14;  Ruth  iv,  13;  1  Sam. 
ii,  21;  Psa.  cxxvii,  3;  cxxviii,  3;  comp.  1  Tim.  ii,  15]; 
therein  lies  the  right  as  well  as  the  duty  of  the  parents. 
Guiding  the  children  in  God's  name,  standing  in  God's  stead 
for  them  [Eph.  vi,  1;  comp.  Lev.  xix,  32],  they  have  not  only 


§  145.]  PURE   ETHICS.  315 

a  right  to  reverential  obedience,  but  also  the  duty  of  rever 
ence-awakening  training.  Parental  love  is  per  se  strictly  nat 
ural,  hence  it  is  found  even  in  the  natural  man  [Gen.  xxi,  16 ; 
xxxi,  28,  43,  50,  55;  1  Kings  iii,  16  sqq.;  Isa.  xlix,  15;  Matt. 
ii,  18;  Luke  xv,  21  sqq. ;  John  iv,  47  sqq.],  and  consequently 
very  much  more  so  in  the  pious  [Gen.  ix,  26,  27;  xxi,  11,  12; 
xxii,  2;  xxiv;  xxviii,  1-4;  xxxvii,  3,  34,  35;  xlii,  36  sqq.; 
xliii,  14;  xliv,  22,  30;  xlv,  28;  xlvi,  30;  xlviii,  10  sqq.;  Exod. 
iij  2  sqq.;  2  Sam.  xii,  16  sqq.;  xiii,  30  sqq.;  xiv;  xviii,  33; 
xix,  1  sqq.;  Prov.  x,  1;  xv,  20;  Jer.  xxxi,  15;  Matt,  ii,  14; 
Luke  ii,  35,  44 ;  John  xix,  25]. 

It  is  the  part  of  parents  to  cultivate  their  children  into 
morally-matured  personalities ;  this  is  not  merely  a  right  of 
the  parents,  but  also  of  the  children,  and  hence,  for  the  for 
mer,  a  duty ;  they  are  to  impart  to  their  children  the  spiritu 
ally-moral  attainments  of  their  own  spiritual  development, 
and  consequently  also  those  of  humanity  in  general,  so  that 
the  children  shall  not  have  to  go  through  again,  in  the  very 
same  manner,  the  same  absolutely  new-beginning  develop 
ment  as  the  parents,  for  this  is  simply  the  manner  and  char 
acteristic  of  nature-objects,  but  that  they  may  place  them 
selves  in  the  current  of  history,  and  learn  and  appropriate  to 
themselves  its  spiritual  results,  and  then,  in  their  turn,  carry 
them  further  forward.  All  spiritual  forming  of  the,  as  yet, 
spiritually  immature  is  an  historical  working, — an  initiating  of 
the,  as  yet,  immature  spirit  into  the  current  and  working  of 
history.  Now,  as  the  child  is  in  fact  to  ripen  on  into  a  mor 
ally-mature  personality,  and  yet  from  the  start  already  is,  both 
in  essence  and  in  faculties,  a  moral  personality,  hence  the 
forming  of  the  same  by  the  parents  is  never  a  strictly  exclu 
sive  influencing,  and  hence,  on  the  part  of  the  child,  never  a 
merely  inactive  receiving,  but  always  also  a  spiritually-moral 
co-operating  of  the  child,  a  constantly  increasing  initiative 
self-forming  of  the  same,  so  that  consequently  from  the  very 
start  there  must  always'be  united  with  the  formative  activity 
upon  the  child,  also  a  sparing  bearing  toward  it ;  and  such  a 
forming  is  in  fact  education. — Education, — which,  as  aiming 
at  the  moral  goal,  namely,  harmony  with  God  and  with  the 
totality  of  moral  being,  must  always  be  at  the  same  time 
a  natural  and  a  spiritual,  a  special  and  a  general  forming, 


316  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  U5. 

directed  toward  bringing  the  child  to  God  and  to  God-sonship 
{Gen.  xviii,  19;  Deut.  vi,  7;  xi,  19;  xxxi,  12,  13;  xxxii,  46; 
Psa.  Ixxviii,  3  sqq. ;  xxxiv,  12;  Isa.  xxxviii,  19;  Eph.  vi,  4; 
cornp.  Luke  ii,  27], — is  a  characteristic  manifestation  of  ration 
ality  ;  the  brute  needs  no  education,  as  it  is  never  destined  to 
become  free  and  moral.  All  created  beings  are,  in  their  es 
sence,  naturally  good ;  but  it  is  only  by  education  that  they 
become  morally  good,  and  truly  rational  and  free.  Wherever 
the  morally  uncultured  and  unmatured  undertake  to  establish 
liberty,  there  it  soon  results  in  unbridled  license,  and,  as  an 
attendant  thereof,  in  the  coarse  tyranny  of  the  stronger.  In 
the  want  and  requirement  of  education  are  implied  a  recog 
nition  and  admission  that  the  entire  true  essence  of  the  child 
is  not  conferred  upon  it  immediately  by  nature,  but  must  be 
first  acquired  by  free  spiritual  acts,  and  that  too  not  by  merely 
individual  acts,  but  by  the  spiritual  appropriation  of  the 
already  extant  spiritual  attainments  of  humanity, — by  spir 
itual  obedience  toward  the  spiritually  and  morally  mature. 
The  child  cannot  educate  itself,  nor  can  it  on  the  other  hand 
simply  be  educated  without  its  own  moral  co-operation ;  but 
it  must  willingly  let  itself  be  educated. 

Reverence  for  parents,  and,  what  is  only  another  phase  of 
the  same  thing,  for  the  aged  in  general,  is  regarded  by  all 
nations,  with  the  exception  of  the  totally  savage,  as  a  sacred 
duty  [comp.  Gen.  ix,  23] ;  and  it  is  a  sure  sign  of  a  deep 
moral  corruption  of  the  spirit  of  a  people  where  there  is  a 
declension  in  the  reverence  of  children  for  parents,  and,  in 
general,  of  youth  before  old  age;  and  more  especially  so 
when  this  declension  is  not  undeserved.  In  a  morally-normal 
development-course  of  humanity  it  is  absolutely  inconceivable 
that  old  age  should  so  deeply  decline  as  to  fall  behind  the 
wisdom  and  moral  maturity  of  the  youth ;  the  superior  wis 
dom  and  knowledge  of  divine  and  human  things  would,  in 
virtue  of  the  higher  inner  and  outward  experience,  continue 
to  be  the  imperishable  possession  of  old  age ;  and  it  belongs 
among  the  most  distressing  evidences  of  the  sinful  disorder  of 
the  human  race,  that  in  fact  old  age  does  frequently  sink  back 
to  childishness,  and  needs  to  be  taken  under  the  guardianship 
of  the  children.  If  any  one  can  regard  this  as  the  natural 
order  of  life,  let  him  also  regard  as  foolish  and  groundless 


§  145.]  PURE   ETHICS.  317 

the  pain  which  every,  not  totally  perverse,  child's  heart 
experiences  at  the  sight  of  such  a  sinking  of  the  gray  head, 
before  which  it  would  fain  only  bow  in  reverence. 

Children  have,  toward  their  parents,  predominantly  the 
duty  of  appropriating,  which,  however,  gradually  passes  over 
more  and  more  into  a  self-forming,  though  without  ever 
entirely  breaking  off  from  the  formative  influence  of  the 
parents ;  and  the  sparing  bearing  of  the  children  toward  the 
parents  can  never,  save  under  utterly  corrupted  conditions,  be 
transcended  by  their  formative  bearing  toward  them.  The 
formative  influence  of  the  children  upon  the  parents,  that 
exists  indeed  from  the  very  beginning,  can,  even  after  they 
have  become  morally  mature,  assume  only  a  secondary  rank. 
This  predominatingly-receptive  relation  of  the  children  to  the 
parents  is  that  of  filial  reverence  [Gen.  xlv,  9  sqq. ;  Exod.  xx, 
12;  Lev.  xix,  3;  Prov.  xxx,  17;  Matt,  xv,  4;  Eph.  vi,  2], 
the  outward  expression  of  which  is  obedience  [Prov.  xxiii,  25 ; 
Eph.  vi,  1 ;  Col.  iii,  20].  Christ  himself  is  the  pattern  also  in 
this  [Luke  ii,  51;  John  xix,  26]. — Children,  when  entering  into 
wedlock  and  establishing  a  new  family,  enter  thereby  indeed 
into  a  greater  independence  of  the  parents  [Gen.  ii,  24],  but 
the  bond  between  parents  and  children,  the  duty  of  the  for 
mer  to  care  for  the  weal  and  the  honor  of  the  latter  [Gen.  xxxi, 
48  sqq.;  Deut.  xxii,  13  sqq.],  and  that  of  the  children  to  show 
reverence  for  the  parents,  is  not  thereby  dissolved. 

The  right  of  parents  to  obedience,  and  the"  duty  of  children 
to  show  it,  are,  however,  essentially  conditioned  on  the  agree 
ment  or  disagreement  of  the  parental  command  with  divine 
will,  and  can  never  become  per  se  and  unconditionally  bind 
ing.  For  this  right  is  not  a  merely  natural  but  a  moral  one ; 
the  merely  natural  dependence  of  children  on  their  parents 
extends,  as  with  brutes,  only  so  far  as  the  state  of  actual 
helplessness  and  need  extends;  the  moral  dependence,  how 
ever,  is  a.permaneut  one  that  is  never  to  be  dissolved.  The 
moral  right  of  the  parents  to  obedience  rests  on  the  fact  that 
they  do  not  represent  their  own  individual  will,  but  the 
divine  will.  And  for  this  very  reason  the  guilt  of  parents  is 
so  deep  when  they  misuse  their  moral  mission  to  educate  in 
God's  name,  and  lead  the  child  away  from  God,  placing  their 
own  sinful  will  in  the  stead  of  the  divine  will. 


318  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  146. 

SECTION  CXLVI. 

Brothers  and  sisters  sustain  toward  each  other,  in 
the  same  manner  as  consorts,  though  only  in  moral 
ly-spiritual  respects,  complementing  relations;  and 
their  mutual  love  forms  an  essential  element  in  the 
morality  of  the  family-life ;  but  this  complementing 
is,  because  of  the  predominant  like-character  of  the 
parties,  never  perfect  and  all-sufficient,  and  hence 
brothers  and  sisters  naturally  seek  for  complement 
ing  elements  also  outside  of  the  family-circle.  This 
form  of  love  which  passes  beyond  the  merely  natural 
communion  and  freely  selects  for  itself  the  com 
plementing  personality,  is  friendship. 

Also  the  mutual  love  of  brothers  and  sisters  is  primarily  of 
a  purely  natural  character  and  requires  to  be  exalted  to  a 
moral  one  [Gen.  xxxiii;  xxxiv;  xlii,  24  sq.  ;  xliii,  16  sqq.  ; 
xliv,  18  sqq.;  xlv,  1  sqq.;  1,  17  ;  Exocl.  ii,  4  sqq.;  Psa. 
cxxxiii,  1 ;  Luke  xv,  32].  Brothers  and  sisters  can  never 
personally  complement  each  other  to  such  an  extent  as  that 
the  need  of  friendship  outside  of  the  family-circle  should  not 
arise  ;  they  are  originally  too  homogeneous,  too  similar,  to  ren 
der  attainable  that  full  harmony  that  both  requires,  and  per 
fectly  consists  with,  large  difference.  Brother  and  sister 
complement  each  other  much  more  than  brother  and  brother 
or  sister  and  sister;  and  they  in  fact  usually  unite  themselves 
more  intimately  with  each  other  than  do  brothers  or  sisters 
among  themselves;  nevertheless  there  remains  also  here,  and 
especially  as  spiritual  maturity  draw's  near,  an  unbridged 
chasm,  and  there  is  felt  the  need  of  a  harmony  more  vital — 
one  that  is  conditioned  on  a  more  strongly  developed  antithe 
sis.  It  is  not  a  loveless  turning  away  from  the  family,  but  a 
strictly  legitimate  impulse,  when  the  boy  and  girl  seek  after 
outside  friendship.  This  does  not  interfere  with  the  family- 
love,  but  heightens  it.  Friendship  is  an  enlarged  brother- 
and-sister  love,  or  rather  it  is  its  complementing  of  itself  out 
side  of  the  family  proper ;  it  is  brotherly  love  as  resting  upon 


PURE   ETHICS.  319 

purely  spiritual  affinity.  Hence  friendship  is  usually  stronger 
in  the  period  of  transition  from  the  original  narrow  family- 
circle  into  new  and  more  independent  forms  of  life;  and  on. 
the  establishing  of  a  new  independent  family-circle  it  is 
usual  for  the  friendship  of  the  consorts  with  others  to  grow 
less  strong,  and  for  new  friendships  to  be  less  easily 
formed ;  wedlock-love  occasions  an  enfeebling  of  friendship ; 
he  who  in  youth  has  had  true  friendships  usually  turns  out  to 
be  an  affectionate  consort ;  and  friendship  with  persons  of  the 
other  sex  very  readily  develops  itself  into  real  sexual  love, 
and  is  consequently  not  without  its  essential  dangers. 


SECTION  CXLVII. 

.%  _. 

The  necessity  of  the  complementing  of  family 
love  by  friendship,  indicates  of  itself  the  reason  of 
the  moral  impossibility  of  marriage  between  near 
Mood  relatives.  The  instinct  that  prompts  brothers 
and  sisters  to  seek  friendship  outside  of  the  narrower 
family-circle,  prompts  them  also  to  seek  for  them 
selves  consorts  outside  of  the  same.  The  requisite 
antecedent  condition  of  marriage,  a  difference  of  the 
bodily  and  of  the  spiritual  peculiarities  of  the  persons, 
exists  most  feebly  in  near  blood  relatives ;  and  mar 
riage  is,  in  its  very  essence,  a  free  moral  communion 
which  does  not  spring  from  a  natural  communion, 
but,  on  the  contrary,  itself  gives  rise  to  this.  As 
marriage  presupposes  a  moral  equality,  and  is  a  re 
lation  of  homogeneous  reciprocal  love,  hence  it  would 
be,  between  parents  and  children,  a  revolting  crime, 
inasmuch  as  here  the  relation  of  reverence  is  insu 
perable;  also,  as  between  brothers  and  sisters,  it  is,, 
for  all  save  the  second  generation  of  the  race,  abso 
lutely  inadmissible,  partly  for  the  reasons  already 
given,  and  in  part  because  of  that  deep  awe  of  the 
parental  blood  which  holds  good  also  as  towards 


320  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§141- 

brothers  and  sisters.  .The  antecedent  moral  presup 
position  of  marriage  is  riot  filial  or  brotherly  love,  but 
"friendship. 

The  obstacle  to  marriage  as  found  in  blood-relationship  is 
one  of  the  most  difficult  of  ethical  questions,  not  so  much, 
however,  because  of  any  kind  of  doubt  as  to  its  legitimacy, 
as  rather  in  reference  to  the  moral  grounds  for  this  recogni 
tion,  which  in  fact  is  almost  universal  and  which  prevails  in 
almost  all,  even  heathen,  nations.  With  the  adducing  of  mere 
outward  grounds  of  fitness,  such  as  the  avoidance  of  near- 
lying  temptation,  very  little  is  gained ;  also  it  is  difficult  to 
establish  this  prohibition,  as  a  nature-law,  from  the  practice 
of  animated  nature  in  general,  for  brutes  do  not  observe  it. 
The  grounds  lie  deeper  and  are  essentially  of  a  spiritually- 
moral  character.  In  the  first  place,  however,  a  distinction  is 
to  be  made  between  ascending  and  collateral  blood  relation 
ship.  Marriages  between  parents  and  children  and  within 
other  ascending  and  descending  degrees  of  relationship  are  an 
outrage  even  for  our  natural  feelings  in  general  [Lev.  xviii ; 
xx,  11  sqq. ;  ICor.  v,  1  sqq.  ;  comp.  Gen.  xix,  30  sqq.].  The 
insuperable  relation  of  reverence  between  children  and  parents 
[comp.  Gen.  ix,  23]  renders  morally  impossible  any  sexual 
mingling,  inasmuch  as  sexual  communion  rests  upon  the 
closest  confiding  equality  of  the  persons ;  whatever  conflicts 
with  filial  and  paternal  love  is  absolutely  immoral,  and  this 
would  unquestionably  be  attendant  upon  sexual  communion. 
The  same  is  of  course  true  of  grand-parents  and  grand-chil 
dren.  The  case  stood  originally  somewhat  different  as  far 
as  regards  marriage  between  brothers  and  sisters;  in  this  re 
spect  there  occur  in  the  general  consciousness  some,  though 
indeed  very  rare,  exceptions.  The  Peruvians  punished  such 
marriages  witli  death ;  and  yet  for  political  reasons  they  pre 
scribed  them  for  their  ruling  Inca.  In  the  case  of  the  children 
of  Adam,  God  made  an  exception  in  the  interest  of  the  indis 
pensably  essential  unity  of  the  human  race  (§  88).  And  the 
unconditional  prohibition  of  such  marriages  could  only  come 
into  force  when  the  possibility  of  other  alliances  was  fully 
realized.  In  the  legislation  of  Moses,  the  sexual  mingling  of 
brothers  and  sisters  was  visited  with  anathemas  and  death 


§  147.]  PURE   ETHICS.  321 

[Lev.  xviii,  9,  11 ;  xx,  17;  Deut.  xxvii,  22] ;  and  as  early  as  in 
the  time  of  Abraham  such  marriages  were  utterly  foreign  even 
to  the  heathen  consciousness,  as  is  evidenced  by  the  fact  that 
Abraham,  in  order  to  protect  himself,  caused  Sarah  to  pass  as 
his  sister  [Gen.  xii,  13;  xx,  2].  (That  Sarah  was  really  Abra 
ham's  half-sister  in  the  stricter  sense  is  not  proved  by  Gen. 
xx,  12,  as  the  expression  "daughter  of  my  father"  may  also 
designate  Terah's  grand-daughter,  and  it  is  not  improbable 
that  she  was  the  daughter  of  Haran,  Abraham's  brother,  and 
that  her  earlier  name  Iscah  [Gen.  xi,  29]  was  exchanged  for 
the  title  of  honor,  Sarai  [my  mistress,  my  wife] ;  in  verse  31 
she  is  called  Terah's  daughter-in-law,  which  would  hardly  be 
said  had  she  been  his  daughter ;  and  whatever  the  facts  may 
be,  the  contracting  of  this  marriage  falls  before  Abraham's 
call.) 

The  most  immediate  ground  for  the  inadmissibility  of  mar 
riage  between  brothers  and  sisters  lies  in  the  fact,  that  though 
here  the  requisite  likeness  of  disposition  in  the  parties  does 
exist,  yet  on  the  other  hand  there  is  lacking  that  degree  of 
difference  which  is  essential  to  a  vital  complementing  har 
mony;  brothers  and  sisters  are  entirely  too  homogeneous  in 
their  bodily  and  spiritual  natures  to  give  rise  to  a  vital,  fruit 
ful,  reciprocal  influencing.  Narcissus  fell  in  love  with  his 
own  image,  and  passed,  for  this  very  reason,  for  a  simpleton ; 
and  brother  and  sister  are  to  each  other,  each,  the  image  of 
the  other.  No  sensible  man  will  select  for  himself  as  a  friend 
one  who  is  only  his  strictly-resembling  second-self,  but,  on 
the  contrary,  such  a  one  as,  by  his  difference,  will  stimu- 
latingly-complement  himself ;  the  same  holds  good  of  husband 
and  wife ;  of  these,  because  of  their  constant  uniformity  of 
life  in  marriage,  it  holds  good  in  fact  in  a  still  higher  degree. 
This  explains  also  the  well-known  fact  that  an  actual  falling 
in  love  between  brother  and  sister  is  among  the  rarest  of  oc 
currences,  even  under  circumstances  where  moral  corruption 
has  taken  deep  root;  (illustrated  in  the  case  of  Amnon, 
2  Sam.  xiii,  1).  To  attempt  to  explain  this  natural  phenomenon 
simply  from  the  express  law  is  inadmissible,  and  for  this  rea 
son  among  others,  because  this  law,  as  existing  among  all 
cultured  heathen  nations,  can  in  fact  be  explained  only  from 
a  natural  conviction,  and  because  this  sentiment  prevails  even 
VOL.  11—22 


322  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS.  [§  147. 

where  in  general  no  regard  whatever  is  had  to  religious  and 
moral  laws.  This  reason,  however,  is  not  fully  sufficient,  be 
cause  while  indeed  it  has  reference  to,  and  accounts  for,  un 
happy  marriages,  yet  it  does  not  explain  why  some  marriages 
should  be  regarded  as  criminal ;  and,  besides,  in  many  cases, 
where  only  too  great  differences  exist  between  brothers  and 
sisters,  it  would  not  apply  at  all.  A  second  reason  for  this 
inadmissibility  reaches  deeper^ namely,  that  marriage  as  dis 
tinguished  from  a  merely  natural  communion,  must  rest  essen 
tially  upon  a  purely  moral  free  choice  and  act ;  it  exists  in  its 
truth  only  where  it  does  not  proceed  from  natural  communion 
as  developing  itself  into  complete  love,  but  where  it  first 
creates  this  natural  communion ;  its  purpose  is  to  create  love 
and  spread  it  abroad,  and  not  merely  to  affirm  a  love  which 
is  already  strong  from  nature.  Blood-relationship  and  mar 
riage  are  twro  different  moral  ordinances  and  bonds,  which 
are  not  to  be  intermingled  with  each  other;  marriage  looks  to 
the  uniting  of  a  previously  existing  antithesis  by  love,  and 
not  to  the  uniting  or  ratifying,  a  second  time,  of  an  already 
existing  natural  unity.  It  is  because  of  this  peculiarity  that 
marriage  forms  the  basis  of  all  moral  community-life,  and 
must  therefore  express  in  itself  the  essential  character  of  this 
life,  namely,  purely  spiritual  love.  If  the  marriage  of  brothers 
and  sisters  were  admissible,  then  the  family  would  tend  to 
hedge  itself  in  upon  its  purely  natural  basis, — would  grow  up 
animal-like  to  a  merely  natural,  but  not  to  a  purely  spiritual, 
communion.  There  is  need  of  the  general  dissemination  of 
love,  as  St.  Augustine  remarks,  and  this  would  be  obstructed 
by  the  possibility  of  marriage  between  brothers  and  sisters; 
and  family  self-seeking  in  narrow-hearted  seclusion  would  be 
come  almost  inevitable ;  marriage  looks  not  merely  to  the 
uniting  together  of  two  persons,  but  also  of  two  families. 
The  moral  development  of  a  people  as  a  whole  imperatively 
requires  this  breaking  down  of  the  walls  of  family  s*eclusive- 
ness,  namely,  the  non  permission  of  the  marriage  of  brothers 
and  sisters;  hence  this  prohibition  is  of  high  world-historical 
significancy. — The  chief  ground,  however,  and  one  which  ex 
presses  itself  chiefly  in  our  natural  feelings,  is  reverence  for 
the  parental  blood  which  has  passed  from  the  parents  over 
upon  the  children,  and  which  calls  for  a  respectful  avoidance 


§148.]  PURE  ETHICS.  323 

of  fleshly-sensuous  enjoyment.  Man  sees  in  his  brother  or 
sister  not  merely  the  image,  but  also  the  blood  of  his  parents 
[comp.  Lev.  xviii,  9;  vii,  8,  11  sgq.,  where  this  thought  is  im 
plied];  and  the  feeling  of  reverential  awe  and  shame  that, 
springs  from  this  consciousness  precludes  any  feeling  of 
sexual  love.  And  in  general  the  feeling  of  reverence  is  un 
congenial  to  sexual  love ;  and  when,  as  not  unf requently  occurs, 
a  maiden  has  stood  in  a  reverential  relation  to  the  man  who 
offers  himself  to  her  as  husband,  there  .the  transition  from  this 
feeling  of  reverence  to  that  of  conjugal  love  costs  her  a  severe 
and  poignant  struggle. — Where  sin  has  actually  taken  deep 
root,  there  arise  other  grounds  for  the  inadmissibility  of  the 
marriage  of  blood-relatives.  But  we  must  confine  ourselves 
here  to  the  expression  of  the  fundamental  idea. 

SECTION  CXLVIII. 

The  family  is  a  unitary  vital  whole  also  in  relation 
to  its  moral  property;  it  is  not  a  mere  sum  of  simply 
isolated  persons  of  like  name,  but  a  body  arid  a  soul 
— a  moral  person  with  a. common  moral  honor  and  a 
•possession  of  its  own,  iu  which  all  the  single  members 
participate. 

The  family  has  as  a  living  unity,  also  me  spirit,  a  common 
moral  life-purpose  and  a  common  moral  peculiarity  ;  the 
common  life-purpose  consists  in  the  mutual  promotion  of  the 
moral  life  in  one  God-inspired  spirit;  the  common  peculiarity 
is,  spiritually,  the  moral  honor  of  the  family,  and,  outwardly, 
its  temporal  possessions.  The  moral  acquirements  of  one  fam 
ily  member,  especially  of  the  head,  pass  over  to  the  whole 
family,  and  the  deserts  of  the  parents  bear,  in  virtue  of  the 
divine  order  of  the  world,  fruits  of  blessing  for  the  children, 
and  are  rewarded  upon  them  [Gen.  xxvi.  4,  5,  24;  xlix,  10,  26; 
Exod.  xx,  6 ;  Deut.  v,  10 ;  vii,  9 ;  2  Sam.  ix,  7 ;  xxi,  7 ;  1  Kings 
xi,  34>Psa.  xxv,  13;  xxxvii,  25  sqq.;  cxii,  2,  3  ;  Prov.  xiv, 
26;  xvii,  6;  xx,  7;  Jer.  xxxii,  18;  comp.  1  Cor.  vii,  14;  Kom. 
xi,  16] ;  and  the  sins  of  the  fathers  are  visited  upon  the  chil 
dren,  and  are  for  them  a  shame  and  a  misfortune  [Gen.  ix,  25 ; 
xx,  7,  17  sqq.;  xlix,  7;  Exod.  xx,  5;  xxxiv,  7;  Lev.  xxvi.  39; 


324  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  t§  149- 

* 

Num.  xiv,  18 ;  Deut.  v,  9 ;  vii,  9 ;  1  Kings  xi,  39 ;  2  Kings 
v,  27;  Job  v,  4;  xxi,  19;  xxvii,  14 ;  Psa.  xxxvii,  28;  cix,  9,  10; 
Prov.  xi,  21;  xvi,  5;  Isa.  xiv,  21;  Jer.  xviii,  21;  xxxii,  18; 
Lain,  v,  7 ;  Hos.  iv,  6  ;  comp.  Matt,  xxvii,  25],  and  the  sins  of 
the  children  upon  the  fathers,  as  their  disgrace  [Lev.  xxi,  9 ; 
Prov.  x,  1;  xvii,  25;  xxviii,  7;  comp.  Deut.  xxii  13  sqq.], — 
whereof  we  shall  speak  elsewhere  more  fully.  The  conscious 
ness,  deeply  rooted  in  all  cultivated  nations,  of  a  transmission 
of  deserts,  of  a  moral  nobility  of  family-lines,  has  a  profoundly 
moral  basis;  but  this  moral  solidarity  of  the  family  is  con 
ceived  even  by  the  Old  Testament  more  clearly  and  more  dis 
tinctly  than  was  ever  done  in  any  heathen  nation.  This  is 
morally  a  very  weighty  thought.  Man  is  made  to  feel  that  he 
does  not  live  and  act  as  a  merely  isolated  individual,  but,  on 
the  contrary,  every-where  and  always  as  a  member  of  a  moral 
whole,  — that  the  fruits  of  his  actions,  be  they  good  or  evil, 
pass  over  to  those  who  belong  to  him  and  with  whom  he  is 
morally  connected,  and  hence  that  in  sinning  he  commits  an 
injustice  not  merely  against  himself,  but  also  against  aZZwhom 
he  calls  his  own.  So  the  family  is  a  divine  ordinance,  so  is  the 
solidarity  of  moral  deserts  and  guilts  such  also ;  this  is  not 
injustice  but  sacred  justice,  for  the  simple  reason  that  man  is 
never  a  merely  isolated  individual.  That  which  is  true  of  the 
spiritually-moral  property  of  the  family  is  true  also  of  the 
material  property,  and  upon  this  rests  the  principle  of 
inheritance. 

(6)  MORAL  SOCIETY. 
SECTION  CXLIX. 

Moral  society  is  the  family  as  enlarged  by  its  own 
natural  growth  and  by  friendship,  but  which,  in  this 
enlarging,  assumes  also  an  essentially  different  char 
acter.  Social  communion  differs  from  family-com 
munion  by  the  greater  retreating  into  the  back-ground 
of  the  natural  unity  and  at  the  same  time  of  free  per 
sonal  choice;  society  itself  assumes  an  objective, 
and,  in  some  sense,  nature-character ;  and  the  place 


§  149.]  PURE   ETHICS.  325 

of  natural  and  free  moral  love  is  supplied  by  custom, 
which  becomes  more  or  less  an  objectively-valid 
power  over  the  individuals.  It  differs,  furthermore, 
from  the  family  in  this,  that  it  involves  a  communion 
of  a  far  more  general  character,  one  that  absorbs  into 
itself  the  individual  person  far  less,  and  requires 
and  brings  about  a  more  interrupted  and  only  occa 
sionally-exercised  moral  intercourse  of  its  members. 
The  members  of  society  sustain  to  each  other  the 
relation  Q*t  friendliness,  which  is  larger  in  extent,  but 
feebler  in  inner  quality. and  power,  than  friendship. 
That  form  of  love  which  manifests  itself  in  friendli 
ness,  and  which  consequently  constitutes  the  moral 
essence  of  society,  is  the  love  of  neighbor^  which,  as 
distinguished  from  more  intimate  love,  does  not  elect 
its  own  object,  and  is  not  directed  toward  particular 
persons  but  toward  man  in  general.  Social  com 
munion  realizes  itself  through  mutual,  spiritual  and 
natural,  communicating,  of  which  the  latter  form  is 
the  expression  and  the  medium  of  the  former.  Spirit 
ual"  communication  may,  however,  take  place  only 
within  the  limits  conditioned  by  the  family,  and 
hence  only  with  some  degree  of  moral  reserve, — 
should  never  become  family-confidentiality. 

The  family  throws  itself  open  indeed,  in  a  normal  state  of 
things,  to  and  for,  society,  but  it  does  not  merge  itself 
therein, — rather  is  it  the  uniform  and  indispensable  moral 
basis  and  presupposition  thereof;  it  is  a  morbid  state  of 
society  that  does  not  rest  on  the  family,  but  rather  throws  it 
into  the  back-ground,  and  more  or  less  assumes  its  place. 
Only  the  moral  integrity  and  the  deep-reaching  moral  nature 
of  the  fainily  give  to  society  moral  vitality;  without  these 
elements  society  declines  to  selfish,  enjoyment-seeking  char 
acterlessness. 

Society  cannot,  from  its  very  nature,  require  as  large  a  per- 


326  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§  U9. 

sonal  giving  up  of  individual  peculiarities  as  does  the  family ; 
it  rests  essentially  on  a  greater  independence  of  its  individual 
members  to  each  other, — gives  greater  scope  to  the  equal 
right  of  the  individuals  to  independent  peculiarities,  than  is 
the  case  with  unreservedly-confiding  love  or  reverence ;  it  is 
made  up  therefore  strictly  only  of  the  truly  independent,  and 
hence  of-  the  spiritually  and  morally  mature ;  minors  should 
belong  predominantly  only  to  the  family,  and  should  not  as 
yet  enter  society ;  premature  ripeness  for  society  damagingly 
affects  not  only  the  taste  for  family-life  but  also  the  moral 
character  of  the  person ;  and  the  most  common  reason  for  the 
characterlessness  of  the  fashionable  world,  is  the  too  early  sup 
planting  of  the  family-life  by  society-life.  In  society  the  in 
dividuals  stand  less  in  a  strictly  personal  relation  to  each 
other, — stand  not  in  the  relation  of  a  special,  personal  love, 
personally  complementing  each  other,  but  rather  as  the  single 
members  of  a  more  extensive  generality.  Here  each  one  sees 
and  loves,  in  the  other,  not  so  much  the  special  personality  as 
rather  simply  a  single  representative  of  society  as  a  whole.  In 
order  to  the  exercise  of  social  virtue,  not  so  much  depends  on 
the  personal  choice  of  the  individual — on  the  fact  that  I  have 
to  do  with  precisely  this  or  that,  to  me,  congenial  personality 
— as  on  the  fact  that  the  person  be  simply  a  member  of 
human,  of  moral,  society  in  general.  Hence  the  members  of 
society  make  also  less  demands  upon  each  other  for  mutual 
devotion  and  confidentiality  than  the  members  of  a  family ; 
in  the  place  of  such  perfect,  mutual  self-devotion  as  the  prop 
erty  of  others,  come  tender  deference,  politeness,  friendliness 
and  complacency.  Politeness,  which  has  nothing  in  common 
with  hollow-hearted  pretense,  is  not  shown  to  the  person  as 
such  but  simply  as  a  member  of  society,  and  should  not  be 
confounded  with  a  manifestation  of  friendship,  as  this  re 
gards  only  the  person.  Forms  of  politeness  are  an  expression 
of  love,  of  friendliness,  of  humble  deference,  to  another ; 
they  arc  manifestations  of  honor  to  whom  honor  is  due,  and 
it  is  due  to  every  upright  man  [Horn  xii,  10;  xiii,  7;  1  Pet.  ii, 
17;  v,  5;  and,  for  examples,  see  Gen.  xviii,  2  sqq.;  xxiii,  7, 
12;  xxxii,  4,  18;  xxxiii,  3,  6,  7,  13,  14;  xliii,  26,  28;  xliv, 
18  sqq.  ;  Rom.  xv,  14,  15  ;  etc.]. 

The  boundary  lines  between  the  family  and  society  are  very 


§  149.]  PURE  ETHICS.  327 

delicate,  but  also  very  legitimate ;  and  he  who,  from  a  miscon 
ception  of  this  difference,  oversteps  these  limits  and  demeans 
himself  in  society  as  in  the  family,  that  is,  does  not  show  that 
proper  reserve  which  seeks  not  to  press  itself  upon  others, — 
in  a  word,  he  who  shows  himself  over-confidential,  is  regarded, 
and  rightly  so,  as  indelicate,  characterless,  or  impudent;  and 
when  the  person  so  acting  is  a  female,  she  is  looked  upon  as 
unwomanly  or  shameless.     French  gallantry,  for  which,  hap 
pily,  we  have  no  German  word,  is  a  treating  of  the  female 
members  of  society  as  if  they  were  family-members  ;  it  treats 
every  maiden  as  if  she  were  an  affianced  sweetheart ;  it  mani 
fests  the  appearance  of  love  where  neither  its  reality  nor  the 
design  of  realizing  it  exists ;  this  is  an  immoral  disintegration 
and  invasion  of  the  family  by  society,  a  breaking  down  of  the 
limits  between  them.     With  the  growth  of  gallantry  the  dis 
solution  of  the  family  usually  increases  also ;  and  the  gallant 
society-man  usually  is  or  turns  out  to  be  a  very  ungenial  hus 
band.     That  devotion,  that  full,  mutual,  spiritual  self-commu 
nicating,  and  that  confidentiality,  which,  within  the  family  as 
well  as  within  the  bounds  of  friendship,  are  not  only  a  right 
but  also  a  duty,  become  sinful  when  shown  to  society  at  large. 
Hence  the  personal  love  that  manifests  itself  in  the  family  is 
less  in  compass,  but  greater  intensity  in,  than  that  love  of 
neighbor  which  extends  to  all  members  of  society  without  ex 
ception,  as  well  as  also  without  choice,  and  which  manifests 
itself  in  the  equally  generally  due  spirit  oi  friendliness  [Matt. 
v,   47;  Gal.  v,  22;  1  Cor.  xiii,  4;  Eph.  iv,  2,  32;   Col.   iii, 
12;  2  Tim.  ii,   24;  Prov.  xii,  25;  Ruth  ii,  8  sqq.].     He  who 
loves  and  treats  the  members  of  his  family  merely  with  the 
friendliness  of  neighbor-love  sins  quite  as  much  as  he  who 
promiscuously  treats  any  or  every  one  he  meets  with  as  a  per 
sonal  friend  or  as  a  consort ;  and  this  holds  good  not  simply 
and  merely  of  society  as  sin-disordered,  though  of  course  the 
difference  is  here  much  greater  than  in  a  state  of  innocence. 
Christian  neighbor-love  is  indeed  designated  as  brother-love, 
and  the  members  of  the  moral  community  are  to  regard  each 
other  as' brethren,  even  as  also  Christ  calls  his  disciples  his 
brethren  [John  xx,  17;  Heb.  ii,  11]  or  his  friends  [John  xv, 
13,  14],  but  this  must  not  be  so  taken  as  to  do  away  witli  the 
difference  between  family-love  and  neighbor-love ;  but,  on  the 


328  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS. 

contrary,  it  rather  simply  implies  that  the  latter  is  a  form  of 
love  that  is  to  be  shaped  after  the  pattern  of  brotherly  love 
proper.  Society  is  to  be  progressively  more  closely  allied  to 
the  family, — is  to  be  more  and  more  affectionately  and  inti 
mately  united  together  on  the  basis  and  after  the  pattern  of 
the  family ;  and  the  closer  bonds  of  the  family  are  not  thereby 
relaxed  but  in  fact  confirmed.  The  Son  of  man  who  embraced 
entire  humanity  in  his  love,  loved  yet  his  disciples  with  a 
closer  love,  than  he  felt  for  others ;  and  even  among  the  disci 
ples  there  was  one  ''whom  the  Lord  loved  "  by  pre-eminence 
— who  lay  upon  Jesus'  bosom ;  and  also  Lazarus  was  a  special 
friend  of  the  Lord  [John  xi,  3,  33  sqq.],  although  Christ's  love 
to  these  persons  was  still  always  something  essentially  other 
than  human  friendship — the  Friend  never  predominating  over 
the  divine  Master.— Of  the  distinctions  that  naturally  form 
themselves  in  every  society,  and  hence  of  the  classes  of  call 
ings,  we  cannot  as  yet  here  treat,  as  their  sharper  separation 
springs  of  and  presupposes  a  sinful  perversion  of  humanity. 

As,  on  the  part  of  the  moral  person,  love  in  society  is  more 
of  a  general  and,  so  to  speak,  impersonal  character,  so  also  is 
this  love  met  from  without  by  the  objective  reality  of  the 
moral,  not  so  much  as  personal  love  in  a  personal  form,  as 
rather  under  a  general  and  impersonal  form — as  a  merely  spir 
itual  power,  as  custom.  Custom  is  indeed  upheld  by  the  in 
dividual  members  of  society,  but  it  does  not  proceed  from 
them  as  particular  single  persons,  but  rather  from  the  collec 
tive  public  spirit  of  the  whole.  Custom  is  a  fruit  of  the  moral 
life,  not  of  the  individual,  but  of  the  collective  public ;  it  is 
the  virtue  of  society  as  peculiarly-constituted ;  and,  as  such, 
it  has  a  right  to  be  respected  by  the  individual ;  and  the  duty 
of  the  individual  to  conform  to  custom  cannot  be  limited  by 
mere  caprice,  but  only  by  the  higher  moral  law  itself  and  by 
the  legitimate  peculiar  duty  of  the  individual  subject.  It  is 
not  requisite,  in  order  to  entitle  social  custom  to  the  right  of 
being  respected,  that  in  each  particular  case  a  definite  moral 
or  .other  rational  ground  be  readily  adducible  for  its  continu 
ance  ;  this  is  in  many  cases  even  impossible ;  and  though,  of 
course,  the  custom,  if  legitimate,  must  ever  have  its  sufficient 
reason,  yet  this  reason  is  not  always  a  universally-moral  one. 
A  respectful  deference  for  that  which  has  become  historical 


§  149.]  PUKE   ETHICS.  329 

in  society  is  a  high  moral  duty,  provided  simply  that  society 
itself  is  not  already  morally  perverted.  The  ebullient  juve 
nile  vigor  of  the  intensely  self-conscious  youth  gladly  recalci 
trates  against  the  historical  reality  of  society, — is  loth  to 
recognize  for  itself  any  other  limits  than  such  as  are  imposed 
by  the  general  and,  as  yet,  not  historically-determined  moral 
law.  The  moral  law,  however,  is  not  of  a  merely  universal 
character,  but  shapes  itself  in  society  into  a  particular  histor 
ical  form ;  moral  society  has  the  same  right  to  the  forming  and 
retaining  of  a  peculiar  character  as  has  the  individual  person ; 
and  as  the  individual  is  entitled  to  be  respected  and  spared  in 
his  moral  peculiarity,  so  is  entitled  also,  and  with  still  greater 
right,  the  moral  collective  whole  [Gen.  xxix,  26].  It  is  a  sign 
of  moral  crudity  when  individuals  disregard  social  custom  in 
cases  where  it  is  not  positively  evil,  and  oppose  themselves  to 
it  for  the  simple  reason  that  they  do  not  regard  it  as  abso 
lutely  necessary, — as,  for  example,  in  the  style  of  clothing 
and  in  the  forms  of  social  intercourse.  It  is  true,  each  indi 
vidual  is  entitled  to  his  own  moral  judgment  as  to  a  custom, 
and  an  immoral  or  irrational  custom  may  by  no  means  be 
spared  or  conformed  to ;  on  the  contrary,  there  arises  here  the 
duty  of  reformatorily  influencing  society  itself.  But  of  such  a 
perverted  state  of  things  we  are  not  as  yet  here  treating.  The 
proper  moral  respecting  of  custom  is  good-mannered  or  becom 
ing  behavior  [/coo/uof,  1  Tim.  ii,  9;  iii,  2].  The  female  mind 
embraces  the  moral  more  as  an  expression  of  custom ;  the 
male  more  as  that  of  the  law. 

As  all  communion  of  love  is  a  mutual  imparting,  so  is  it  also 
with  social  love ;  the  basis  and  at  the  same  time  the  moral 
limit  of  this  imparting  or  communicating,  is  the  family.  The 
family  throws  itself  open  occasionally  for  society, — imparts 
itself  to  society,  welcomes  its  members  hospitably  into  itself. 
Hospitableness  or  hospitality  [Gen.  xviii;  xix;  xxiv,  31  sqq.  ; 
Exod.  ii,  20 ;  Lev.  xix,  33,  34 ;  Judges  xix,  20,  21 ;  Job  xxxi, 
32;  Matt,  xxv,  35;  x,  41,  42;  Luke  xi,  6;  Acts  xxviii,  7  sqq.; 
1  Pet.  iv,  9 ;  Rom.  xii,  13 ;  1  Tim.  iii,  2 ;  v,  10 ;  Titus  i,  8 ; 
Heb.  xiii,  2J  is  properly  a  virtue  practiced  not  by  the  indi 
vidual,  but  predominantly  by  the  family.  It  is  the  occasional 
letting  in  of  society  into  the  family,  the  outward  manifesting 
of  the  love  that  prevails  in  the  family  toward  those  who  stand 


330  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§  150. 

to  us  simply  in  the  relation  of  members  in  society.  It  is  only 
the  family  that  can  exercise  true  hospitableness — that  can 
constitute  a  hospitable  house ;  this  manifests  itself,  even  in  our 
present  so  radically  perverted  state  of  society,  in  the  fact  that 
it  is  always  the  housewife  who  takes  the  lead  of  the  guest- 
circle,  and  gives  it  the  family-consecration.  Hospitality  is 
one  of  the  first  and  most  natural  manifestations  of  neighbor- 
love,  hence  it  is  highly  esteemed  even  among  many  uncultured 
nations ;  it  exists  always  in  its  highest  form  where  also  the 
family  is  preserved  in  high  moral  integrity,  as,  for  example, 
among  the  ancient  Germanic  races.  It  is  a  very  special  and 
important  characteristic  of  hospitality,  that  it  is  not  exercised 
merely  toward  friends  proper,  who  in  fact  already  belong  to 
the  outer  circle  of  the  family,  but  also,  and  historically  even 
primarily,  to  strangers  who  are  as  yet  not  known  personally 
at  all,  that  is,  to  man  simply  in  his  quality  of  neighbor. 


SECTION  CL. 

The  recognition  of  the  moral  character  of  a  per 
son  on  the  part  of  moral  society,  is  his  social  honor  • 
each  and  every  one  has,  normally,  a  moral  right  to 
such  recognition  by  every  other  morally  honorable 
person,  and  should  strive  to  obtain  and  retain  it. 
The  actual  manifestation  of  personal  honor,  as  a 
moral  possession,  is  personal  dignify.  No  honor  is 
morally  valid  save  in  so  far  as  it  is,  at  the  same  time, 
honor  before  God.  The  moral  society  into  which 
the  individual  is  incorporated  by  virtue,  on  the  one 
hand,  of  custom,  by  which  he  as  well  as  the  collect 
ive  society  is  influenced,  and  in  which  he  conse 
quently  recognizes  the  morality  of  society,  and,  on 
the  other  hand,  by  virtue  of  the  honor  which  he 
enjoys  in  the  eyes  of  society,  and  in  which  conse 
quently  his  morality  is  recognized  by  the  society,  is 
lor  him  his  moral  home. 


§150.]  PURE   ETHICS.  331 

Only  he  has  honor  who  has  acquired  a  moral  character ;  the 
characterless  is  honorless.  Horuor  is  the  reflection  of  the  per 
sonal  character  in  the  consciousness  of  society, — is  its  recog 
nition  by  the. same.  Honor  is  the  reverse  phase  of  love ;  only 
the  moral  man  can  rightly  love,  and  in  loving  he  thirsts  also 
to  be  loved,  and  hence  to  be  recognized  in  his  moral  person 
ality  by  others;  the  immoral  man  as  such  is  not  loved,  be 
cause  he  is  not  in  the  possession  of  honor.  Though  honor  is 
based  on  moral  character  yet  it  is  not  identical  therewith, — it 
is  character  as  having  become  objective  in  the  moral  con 
sciousness  of  society.  God's  honor  is  not  his  holiness  and  his 
divine  essence  themselves,  but  the  recognition  of  the  same  on 
the  part  of  rational  creatures;  and  as  God  vindicates  and 
seeks  his  own  honor  [Exod.  xiv,  4 ;  1  Sam.  ii,  30 ;  Psa.  xlvi, 
10;  Isa.  xlii,  8;  xlviii,  11;  Ezek.  xxviii,  22;  comp.  John  v, 
23 ;  Rom.  xi,  36 ;  xvi,  27],  so  also  the  moral  man  seeks,  and 
rightly  so,  his  honor,  but  only  such  as  is  at  the  same  time 
honor  before  God,  namely,  a  recognition  of  his  conduct  and 
spirit  as  those  of  a  child  of  God,  and  hence  an  honor  which 
is  at  the  same  time  the  witness  of  a  good  conscience  before 
God  [Psa.  iii,  3 ;  Ixxiii,  24 ;  cxii,  9 ;  John  v,  44 ;  xii,  26,  43 ; 
Roni.  ii,  6,  7,  10,  29;  v,  2;  1  Cor.  iv,  5;  2  Cor.  x,  18],— the 
pleasures  of  God  in  him  who  loves  Him  [2  Cor.  v,  9 ;  Col.  i, 
10].  In  this  sense  honor  before  men  and  the  children  of  God 
is  a  high  good  [Psa.  vii,  5 ;  xlix,  11 ;  Ixxxiv,  12;  Prov.  iii,  16, 
35;  viii,  18;.  xi,  16;  xxi,  21;  xxii,  4;  xxix,  23;  Phil,  ii,  29], 
and  to  disesteem  stick  honor  is  either  to  think  unworthily  or 
to  be  too  high-minded. 

Personal  honor  and  social  custom  condition  man's  moral 
home.  Society  and  country  are  only  in  so  far  a  home  as  they 
are  expressive  of  the  spiritually-moral  life  of  society.  My 
fatherland  is  not  where  I  am  outwardly  prosperous,  but  where 
I  enjoy  myself  morally, — feel  myself  vitally  at  one  with  a 
moral  community.  Mere  nature  forms  a  sort  of  home  only 
for  the  savage ;  a  true  home  is  of  a  spiritual  character,  and 
nature  is  such  only  as  brought  within  the  sphere  of  history,  as 
transformed  by  man.  It  is  at  home  that  man  enjoys  his  exist 
ence  ;  the  far-off  is  tempting  mostly  only  for  him  who  is  as  yet 
in  process  of  development  toward  spiritual  and  character- 
maturity  ;  the  seeking  of  a  new  home  is  in  normal  circum- 


332  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§151. 

stances  less  an  affair  of  the  single  individual  than  of  whole 
branches  of  a  nation,  namely,  in  cases  of  the  founding  of  new 
colonies ;  but  here  in  fact  the  moral  home  migrates  along. 
To  be  shut  out  from  one's  home  is  properly  regarded  as  a 
severe  misfortune ;  the  declaration  that  he  should  be  a  fugi 
tive  wanderer  in  the  earth  was  the  bitterest  element  in  the 
curse  upon  Cain ;  among  ancient  nations  Banishment  was 
the  severest  of  punishments. 


(c)  THE  MORAL  ORGANIZATION  OF  SOCIETY. 
SECTION  CLI. 

As  single  persons  unite  themselves  into  a  family 
and  develop  in  it  a  vitally  organic  life  in  common,  so 
in  turn  society  unites  itselfinto  a  higher-organized  copy 
of  the  family,  into  a  society-family,  into  a  homoge 
neous  moral  organism, — organizes  itself  into  a  real 
unitary  life;  social  custom  rises  from  being  primarily 
a  purely  spiritual,  impersonal  power,  and  becomes  a 
real  personally-represented  and  actually  self-execut 
ing  power, — that  is,  it  becomes  social  right  as  ex 
pressed  in  law,  in  which  form  morality  becomes  for 
and  over  the  individual  an  objective  reality  and 
power,  and  is  not  a  mere  formula  but  is  in  fact- 
embodied  in  and  tested  and  executed  by  moral  per 
sonalities.  There  is  no  law  without  a  personal  repre 
sentative  and  executor  of  the  same. 

If  at  first  view  society  appears  as  a  mere  falling  apart  of  the 
family,  as  a  loosening  of  the  narrower  bond  of  love  and  duties 
as  existing  in  the  family  itself,  as  a  dissolution  of  the  family- 
generated  collective  spirit  into  mere  independent  individual 
spirits,  as  a  freer-making  of  the  single  individuals, — and  if  it 
is  nevertheless,  at  the  same  time,  a  necessary  progress  beyond 
the  mere  family-life, — still  there  can  be  no  resting  at  mere 
society  and  social  custom,  but  society  must  in  turn  in  its  fur- 


§  151.]  PURE   ETHICS.  333 

ther  development  return  back  to  the  fundamental  character  of 
the  family, — must  exalt  itself  to  the  ideal  of  the  family  and 
of  its  moral  organism,  even  as  the  plant,  when  unfolded  out 
of  the  seed  into  branches  and  leaves,  in  turn  generates  again 
in  the  fruit  the  original  seed.     This  return  of  society  to  the 
family  takes  place  not  merely  through  the  fact  that   society 
itself  becomes  the  occasion   to   constantly  new  unitings  of 
families,  but  essentially  by  the  fact  that  it  itself  takes  on  the 
character  of  a  -family  of  a  higher  grade, — that  custom  itself 
(which-  rules  in  society  only  as  a  bodiless  spirit)  assumes  full 
objective  reality,  attains  to  flesh  and  blood  and  vital  force,  so 
as  to  vindicate  and  execute  itself  against  whatever  individual 
will  may  oppose  it.     Social  custom  depends  for  its  realization 
entirely  on  its  favorable  recognition  on  the  part  of  individu 
als;  it  falls  away  powerless  where  it  meets  with  extended 
resistance ;  but  when  raised  to  the  state  of  social  right  or 
law,    it  can  itself  compel  recognition  in  the  face  of  such 
resistance, — can  force  its  opposers  to  submit  themselves  to 
general  rationality  as  incarnated  in  the  law.     Just  as  mere 
custom  is  society-virtue  as  sentiment,  so  is  law  society-c&ar- 
acter,  with  firm  will-force  for  carrying  itself  out.     Custom  is, 
as  it  were,    the   heart-rich  idealistic  bride-state   of    public 
morality ;  right  as  enunciated  in  law  is  its  marriage-state  with 
the  full  earnestness  of  obligation;  the  former  rests  on  the  dis 
cretion  of   the  individual;   the  latter  binds  the  individual 
unconditionally  and  with  the  power  of  active  compulsion. 
That  is  surely  a  very  bad  legal  condition  of  society  where 
right  is  accomplished  only  by  coercion  and  fear;    and  the 
normal  condition  of  society  is  that  where  the  law  is  inscribed 
in,  and  a  vital  force  of,  every  individual  heart,  and  that,  too, 
as  law  and  not  as  a  mere  and,  as  it  were,  simply  beseeching 
custom;  and  where  it  does  not  find  free  recognition,  there  it 
should  not  bow  its  head  and  suffer  in  silence,  but  it  has  been 
intrusted  by  God  with  the  sword  for  the  punishment  of  evil 
doers,  and  for  the  praise  of  them  that  do  well  [1  Pet.  ii,  14 ; 
Rom.  xiii,  1-4].     That  would  be  a  bad-ordered  family  where 
the  father,   as  against  his  disobedient  children,  merely  be 
wailed  in  inactivity, — where  he  should  not  virtualize  his  true 
moral  love  by  palpable  chastisement;  and  organized  society 
has,  as  the  higher-developed  family,  also  the  love-duty  of 


834  CHRISTIAN  ETHICS.  [§152. 

coercion  and  penal  chastisement.  Morality  cannot  and  ought 
not  to  have  a  merely  subjective  form;  it  should  attain  also  to 
objective  reality, — should  become  a  power  above  the  indi 
vidual  person,  and  that,  too,  not  as  merely  conceived,  but  as 
having  full  reality ;  and  this  condition  is  realized  only  in  the 
fact  that  right  or  objective  morality  is  not  a  mere  thought,  a 
mere  written  code,  but  that  it  has  its  personal  upholders  and 
executors;  this  is  not  merely  human  order,  it  is  divine  order. 
— As  the  highest  form  of  the  moral  community-life,  positively- 
organized  society  cannot  do  away  with  the  earlier  stages,  the 
family  and  society  in  the  larger  sense  of  the  word, — but  as  it 
is  itself  based  upon  them,  it  must  necessarily  contain  them  with 
in  itself,  and  foster  and  promote  them.  A  state  which,  as 
was  the  case  with  Plato's,  swallows  up  the  family  is  totally 
illegitimate  and  in  utter  conflict  with  the  moral  idea.  That 
unlimited  autocracy  of  the  state  which  assumes  to  be  the  sole 
and  absolute  source  of  right  is  a  heathen  notion,  and,  within 
the  Christian  world,  anti-moral. 


SECTION  CLII. 

The  difference,  as  necessarily  existing  in  every 
moral  communion,  of  the  morally-advanced  and  the 
morally  less-matured,  and  which  finds  its  first  ex 
pression  in  the  relation  of  parents  and  children,  forms 
also  the  basis  of  organized  society.  In  this  society 
the  duty  of  forming,  of  guiding  and  of  educating  falls 
mainly  to  the  former ;  that  of  appropriating  and 
obeying,  to  the  latter.  The  guiding  rests  entirely  on 
morally-religious  culture,  and  aims  by  general  form 
ing  to  make  of  society  a  moral  art-work,  a  moral 
organism.  The  difference  between  the  guiding  or 
ruling  ones  and  the  guided  and  obeying  ones,  is 
therefore  per  se  strictly  identical  with  the  difference 
between  the  morally  and  religiously  higher-developed 
(the  prophets  and  priests)  and  the  as  yet  to-be-de 
veloped,  namely,  the  general  public,  the  body  of 


§  152.]  PURE  ETHICS.  335 

society.  In  so  far  as  the  moral  organism  expresses 
the  antithesis  of  priest-prophets  and  people-con 
gregation  in  the  sphere  of  religion,  it  is  the  church; 
in  so  far  as  it  expresses  the  antithesis  of  the  ruling 
and  the  ruled  in  the  sphere  of  law  or  right,  it  is  the 
state.  In  a  normally  constituted  and  absolutely  sin- 
free  society  church  and  state  are  perfectly  identical, 
and  the  moral  organism  appears  as  a  theocracy  •  its 
definite  popular  form  would  be  a  fully  developed 
patriarchal  state.  The  religious  and  the  legal  com 
monalty  in  their  perfect  unity  are  the  morally  de 
veloped  family  ;  and  as  its  inner  law  and  essence  are 
absolutely  the  moral  law  itself,  which  rules  at  the 
same  time  as  a  vital  power  in  the  hearts  of  all  its 
members,  hence  the  theocratically-organized  relig 
iously-moral  society  is  the  historical  realization  of  the 
kingdom  of  God  on  earth,  and  its  perfecting  is  the 
goal  of  all  ra,tionally-moral  effort,  of  the  individual  as 
well  as  of  society  as  a  whole ;  and  the  spiritual  and 
moral  development  of  humanity  toward  this  ultimate 
end  forms  universal  history. 

We  have  nothing  to  do  here  with  the  actual  church  and  the 
actual  state,  which  are  both  essentially  conditioned  on,  and 
constituted  in  view  of  combating,  sin,  but  with  the  ideal  moral 
community-life  which  is  free  of  all  sin.  The  family  continues 
to  be  the  moral  basis  and  the  pattern.  The  inner  difference 
between  the  guiding  and  the  guided  can,  in  a  sinless  state  of 
things,  be  only  of  a  very  mild  and  a  merely  relatively  valid 
character.  In  a  perfect  religious  community  all  the  mature 
members  are  of  priestly  character,  are  invested  with  the  duty  of 
spiritual  guidance ;  and  in  a  perfect  civil  society  all  the  mature 
citizens  participate  in  the  spiritual  and  moral  guidance  of  the 
whole ;  and  the  more  perfect  the  collective  development  of  all 
the  members,  so  much  the  more  does  the  fundamental  rela 
tion  of  fathers  and  children  retire  into  the  back-ground,  and 


336  CHRISTIAN    ETHICS. 

assume  rather  the  form  of  the  gentler  antithesis  of  the  two 
sexes  in  marriage. 

As  in  the  normal  family,  religious  and  moral  life  are  united, 
and  the  father  is  also  the  spiritual  and  priestly  guide  of  the 
religious  life,  hence  in  the  ideal  social  organism,  church  and 
state  are  simply  one  and  the  same  thing ;  they  are  but  two 
absolutely  inseparable  phases  of  the  same  spiritual  life.  All 
religion  becomes  social  reality,  and  all  social  life  rests  on 
religion ;  the  normal  state  is  also  a  church,  and  the  true  church 
develops  out  of  kself  a  corresponding  social  community-life, 
— as  was  seen  in  the  early  Christian  church,  and  as,  in  recent 
times,  the  Unitas  Fratrum,  from  a  correct  presentiment  of  the 
goal  of  Christian  history,  lias  partially  carried  out.  That  the 
father  of  the  people  should  also  be  the  chief  bishop,  is  implied 
in  the  prototype  of  the  moral  commonalty ;  but  whether  in 
this  particular  the  ideal  is  to  be  applied  to  the  very  unideal 
present  reality  of  the  world,  it  is  not  here  the  place  to  decide. 
The  patriarchal  state  is  the  primitive  manner  of  morally  organ 
izing  society, — the  one  most  nearly  related  to  the  family  proto 
type  ;  and  the  family-chief  of  the  closely  related  tribe  is 
at  once  its  chief  leader  and  its  priest ;  he  represents,  however, 
not  his  single  personal  will,  but  the  moral  will  of  the  whole, 
which  is  in  turn  itself  a  faithful  expression  of  the  divine  will. 
For  this  simple  reason  the  ideal  form  of  the  social  state  is 
necessarily  and  essentially  a  theocracy ;  for  it  is  only  in  a  vital 
communion  with  God  that  the  rulers  of  the  people  have  their 
right,  their  law,  their  power;  and  it  is  not  the  mere  divine 
law  that  is  the  all-guiding  factor,  but  the  living  personal  God 
himself,  who  enlightens  and  guides  his  trusting  children,  and 
governs  directly  through  his  prophets  and  anointed  ones. 
The  divine  right  of  a  true  magistracy  is  based  on  this  idea, 
but  is  valid  as  a  moral  right  only  in  so  far  as  humble  submis 
sion  to  God  rules  in  the  hearts  of  the  rulers.  The  theocracy 
of  the  Old  Testament  [Exod.  xix,  3-6 ;  Deut.  vii,  6  sqq.  ; 
xxxiii.  5;  1  Sam.  viii,  6  sqq.;  Isa.  xxxiii,  22]  is  only  a  faint 
shadow  of  that  which  was  to  have  been  realized  in  sinless 
humanity,  and  of  which  as  partially  regained  through  re 
demption  only  glimpses  are  caught  in  prophetic  vision  [Isa. 
ii,  2;  iv,  2  sqq.;  ix,  6  sqq.;  xi,  1  sqq.;  xxxii,  15  sqq.;  Ixv, 
17  sqq.;  Ezek.  xxxiv,  23  sqq.;  xxxvi,  24  sqq.;  xxxvii,  24  sqq.]. 


§  152.]  PURE   ETHICS.  337 

The  mysterious  phenomenon  of  the  priest-king  of  Salem, 
Melchizedek  [Gen,  xiv,  18  sqq. ;  Heb.  vii,  1  sqq.  ;  Psa.  ex,  4], 
like  a  reminiscence  of  a  long-forgotten  better  age  floating 
down  into  a  totally  different  present,— perhaps  the  last  scion 
of  those  who  had  remained  faithful  to  the  Covenant  of  Noah 
outside  of  the  family  of  Abraham, — is  in  some  respects  the 
expression  of  a  true  theocracy  as  it  exists  in  a  higher  manner 
only  in  Christ.  With  the  Israelites  royalty  and  priesthood 
were  in  fact  separate;  Aaron  and  David  represent  the  two 
Bides  of  the  one  theocratical  idea ;  Samuel  approximated  this 
idea,  but  was  more  a  priest  than  a  king.  The  theocratical 
form  of  society  was  realized  in  Old  Testament  times  only  in 
its  first  beginnings,  in  the  family-state  of  the  patriarchs.  The 
people  of  Israel  was  both  outwardly  and  inwardly  too  little  at 
peace  both  with  the  world  and  with  God  to  be  able  to  sus 
tain  a  theocratical  form  of  government ;  it  is  only  in  "  Salem  " 
that  the  Prince  of  Peace  can  rule. 

The  moral  commonalty  in  its  double  form  as  church  and 
state  is,  on  the  one  hand,  a  complete  preserving  and  virtualiz- 
ing  of  the  personal  moral  freedom  of  the  individuals,  in  that 
the  collective  will,  as  manifesting  itself  in  laws  and  in  the 
government,  is  at  the  same  time  the  will  of  the  individual,  and 
on  the  other,  a  real  objective  presentation  of  the  moral  idea 
with  a  determining  power  for  and  over  the  individual,  but 
which  acts  as  a  limit  to  the  freedom  of  the  individual  only 
when  this  freedom  has  fallen  from  its  harmony  with  God  into 
irrational  caprice.  In  the  ideal  state  all  morality  becomes  right 
or  law,  and  all  law  is  a  pure  expression  of  morality.  When 
this  moral  commonalty  has  become  a  full  reality,  then  it  is- 
the  kingdom  of  God  as  having  attained  to  historical  form  and 
reality.  The  kingdom  of  God  comes  not,  it  is  true,  with  out 
ward  show  [Luke  xvii,  20,  21],  inasmuch  as  it  exists  primarily 
in  the  hearts  of  men ;  but  when  it  has  come  into  the  hearts  of 
men — when  God  has  assumed  form  within  them — then  will 
also  the  kingdom  of  God  itself  take  upon  itself  a  form,  and 
"the  collective  history  of  the  God-imbued  portion  of  humanity 
(the  true  church)  is  simply  this  gradually  self-developing 
form.  As  soon,  however,  as  sin  has  entered  into  reality,  then 
church  and  state  at  once  fall  apart,  and  dissolve  themselves 
in  turn  into  discordant  and  contradictory  subdivisions,  and 
VOL.  11—23 


338  CHRISTIAN   ETHICS.  [§152. 

the  kingdom  of  everlasting  peace  becomes  a  plurality  of  king 
doms  of  endless  strife.  The  moral  or  ideal  destination  of  uni 
versal  history  is,  to  be  the  uniformly  undisturbed  evolution  of 
the  kingdom  of  God;  to  confound  its  criminal  reality  with 
the  unclouded  ideal,  is  to  deny  ethical  moral  truth.  But  uni 
versal  history,  in  its  pure  and  normal  form,  is  the  develop 
ment  of  humanity  as  unitary  (§  88);  of  this  humanity  the 
statement  would  hold  good  in  the  most  perfect  manner,  that 
" the  whole  earth  was  of  one  language  and  of  one  speech" 
[Gen.  xi,  1]. 


GENERAL  INDEX  TO  VOLS.  I  AND  II. 


Aaron  vs.  David,  ii,  337. 

Abel,  ii,  231,  280. 

Abelard,  i,  205. 

Abortion,  in  Greece,  i,  66,  85,  119; 

as  viewed  by  the  Jesuits,  269. 
Abraham,  purpose  of  the  call  of, 

i,  157  ;  his  marriage,  ii,  321. 
"Accommodation,"  i,  260. 
Achilles,  i,  41,  63. 
Adiaphora,  i,  253 ;  ii,  123. 
Adornment,  ii,  242. 
Adultery,  Jesuitical   teachings  in 

regard  to,  i,  266  sqq. ;  ii,  309. 
.^Enesidemus,  i,  145. 
Agrippa  of  Nettesheim,  i,  281. 
Ahura-Mazda,  i,  60. 
"  Akosmism,"  i,  289. 
Albertus  Magnus,  i,  208. 
Alcuin,  i,  200. 
Allihn,  i,  357. 
Alsted,  i,  248. 
Ambrose,  i,  191. 
Amesius"  i,  247. 
Amiability,  i,  106. 
Ammon,  i,  338,  360. 
Amyraud,  i,  247. 
Andreas,  i,  248. 
Androgynism,  ii,  305. 
Anger,  i,  105,  108. 
Angra-mainyus,  i,  59. 
Animals,  ii,  202,  264,  267,  270. 
Anti-hero-worship,  of  the  Jews,  i, 

163. 

Antisthenes,  i,  72. 
Apocrypha,  ethics  of  the,  i,  1 69. 
Apollo,  i,  63. 
Apologia,  the,  ii,  44,  62. 
Appropriation   vs.  formation   and 

sparing,   ii,   180 ;   186 ;    sexual, 

189;  spiritual,  190;    214;   237; 

natural,  266. 

Architecture,  sacred,  ii,  207. 
Arnauld,  i,  274. 
Arndt,  John,  i,  249. 


Arrian,  i,  133. 

Aristippus,  i,  73. 

Aristotle,  i,  41,  89;  relation  to 
Plato,  92 ;  works  of,  92  sqq. ;  in 
fluence  on  the  Middle  Ages,  93 ; 
on  the  God-idea,  94 ;  on  virtue, 
96;  on  the  highest  good,  97; 
on  depravity,  102;  on  the  vir 
tues,  103  sqq. ;  on  the  contem 
plative  life,  109;  on  the  com 
munity-life,  110;  on  friendship, 
111;  on  democracy,  114;  on 
marriage,  1M) ;  on  education, 
120;  on  war,  121;  vs.  the  Chris 
tian  spirit,  124. 

Art,  ii,  205,  209;  271. 

Art-works,  ii,  184;  205  sqq. 

Asceticism,  Brahminic,  i,  51  ; 
Buddhistic,  54 ;  early  Christian, 
183;  ii,  268. 

Astesauus,  i,  222. 

Atheism,  i,  52  ;  of  the  Epicureans, 
129;  of  La  Mettrie,  320;  352 
sqq. 

Augustine,  ii,  192  ;  on  grace  and  on 
the  will,  193;  on  the  principle 
of  virtue,  194;  on  the  four  car 
dinal  and  the  three  theological 
virtues,  195 ;  on  the  divine 
counsels,- 196. 

Autonomy,  ii,  7,  9,  18. 

Avesta,  the,  i,  59. 

Awe,  ii,  173. 

Azorio,  i,  256. 

Baader,  i,  342,  375. 
Babylonians,  the,  i,  54. 
Bacon,  i,  303. 
Balduin,  i,  251. 
Banishment,  ii,  332. 
Barnabas,  i,  181. 
Basnage,  i,  248. 
Basedow,  i,  322. 
Basil,  i,  190. 


340 


INDEX. 


Bauer,  G-.  L.,  i,  152;    Bruno  and 

Edgar,  354. 
Bauny,  i,  257,  263. 
Baumgarten,  Alex.,  i,  '298;  Jacob, 

325. 

Baumgarten-Crusius,  i,  361. 
Baxter,  i,  248. 
Beautiful,  the,  i,  63 ;  ii,  9. 
Beauty  vs.  morality,  i,  65 ;  vs.  the 

ethical,  80;  ii,  242. 
Becoming,  the,  ii,  210. 
Bede,  i,  199. 
Beneke,  i,  357. 
Bernard,  St.,  i,  206,  224. 
Bertling,  i,  325. 
Besombes,  i,  376. 
Besser,  i,  257. 
Bliss,  ii,  283. 
Blood-relationship  vs.  marriage,  ii, 

320  sqq. 
Bohme,  i,  342. 
Boethius,  i,  197. 
Bolingbroke,  i,  312. 
Bona,  i,  275. 
Bonaventura,  i,  224. 
Brahma,  i,  41,  42,  45;  ii.  184. 
Brahminism,  i,  48  sqq. 
Braudis,  i,  107,  123. 
Braniss,  i,  VII. 
Breithaupt,  i,  255. 
Brothers  vs.  sisters,  ii.  318. 
Bruno,  i,  281. 
Buddseus,  i,  324. 
Buddhism,  i,  41,  48,  52  sqq. 
Buchner,  i,  354. 
Busenbaum,  i,  257. 
Butchering,  moral  influence  of,  ii, 
268. 

Cain,  ii,  231,  285,  332. 
Calixt,  i,  250. 

Calvin,    i,    242 ;    o»    the   virtues, 
%  243;  ii,  301. 

Cana,  the  marriage  at,  ii,  188. 
Canz,  i,  298,  325. 
Caste,  i,  49,  83,  120. 
Castration,  i,  269 ;  ii,  265. 
Casuistry,  i,  199,  221,  250,  255. 
"  Categorical   imperative,"  the,   i, 

330;  ii,  33,   52,  83. 
"Celestial  kingdom,"  the,  i,  45. 
Celibacy,  i,  188.  189,  254. 


Chalybaus,  i,  357. 
hase,  the,  and  war,  i,  121. 
hastity  i,  181. 
Childhood,  ii,  69,  263. 
hild-innocence,  ii,  152. 
!hildren  vs.  parents,  ii,  313. 
Chinese,  ethics,  i,  43 ;  virtue,  46 ; 

marriage,  47. 

hrist,  the  nature  of  his  moral  pre 
cepts,  ii,  87  ;  his  comeliness,  243. 
Christian  ethics,  i,  173,  328 ;  ii,  1 ; 

threefold  form  of,  2. 
hristianity,     scientific      impulse 

given  by,  i,  179. 
Chrysostom,  i,  190. 
Church  vs.  state,  ii,  335. 
Chytrseus,  i,  242. 
Cicero,    i,    132,   149;    on  collision 

of  duties,  150;  280. 
Clarke,  i,  306. 
Clavasio,  i,  222. 
Cleanliness,  ii,  242  sqq. 
Clemens  Alexandrinus,  i,  186. 
Clothing,  ii,  245  sqq. 
Collins,  i,  310. 
Collision  of  duties,  5,  150;  ii,  136, 

292. 

Commands  vs.  prohibitions,  ii,  124. 
Communism  of  Plato,  i,  84 ;  of  the 

Stoics,  141. 
Community-life,    the,    5,    82,    110, 

220;  ii,  76,  302. 
Compassion,    Buddhistic,    i,     53; 

286. 

Concini,  i,  376. 
Concilia  vs.  prcecepta,  ii,  113. 
Concubines,  i,  65;  ii,  307. 
Condillac,  i,  314. 
Confession,  ii,  223. 
Confidence  vs.  distrust,  ii,  261. 
Confucius,  i.  44. 
Consanguinity,  ii,  155. 
Conscience,  i,  339 ;    ii,  99  sqq. 
Considerateuess,  ii,  282. 
Consorts  vs.  blood-relatives,  ii,  313. 
Constance,  the  Council  of,  i,  260. 
Contemplative  life,  the,  favored  by 

Aristotle,    i,    115;    by  St.  Vic 
tor,  224. 

Continence,  i,  108. 
Contract-marriage,  ii,  307. 
Corporeality,  ii,  60. 


INDEX. 


341 


Courage,  i,  103;  ii,  291,  292,  296. 
Counsels,  the,  i,  196,  215,  242. 
Culture  vs.  savagery,  ii,  288. 
Creation,  to  be  completed  by  the 

creature,  ii,  274. 
Crell,  i,  281. 
Criiger,  i,  325. 
Crusius,  i,  299,  326. 
Cudwortli,  i,  306. 
Cumberland,  i,  305. 
Culmann,  i,  375. 
Custom,  ii,  325 ;  vs.  law,  333. 
Customariness,  i,  21,  348. 
Cynics,  i,  72. 

Cynics  vs.  Cyrenaics,  i,  73. 
Cyprian,  i,  189. 
Cyrenaics,  i,  73. 

Damascenus,  John,  i,  198. 

Damiani,  i,  200. 

Danasus,  i,  247 ;  ii,  57. 

Dance,  the,  ii,  247. 

Dannhauer,  i,  251. 

Darwinism,-  ii,  154. 

Daub,  i,  344,  351. 

Death,  Epicurean  view  of,  i,  138 ; 

ii,  67. 

Dedekenn,  i,  352. 
Decalogue,  the,  ii.  28. 
Deism,  i,  302,  312. 
Depravity,  i,  38,  42 ;    Plato's  ex 
plication  of,  78,  79;    Aristotle's 

remedy  for,  114;  123. 
Descarl.es,  i,  282,  288. 
Determinism,  i,  282,  293. 
Devotedness,  ii,  298. 
De  Wette,  his  works,  i,  37  ;  360. 
Diana,  i,  264,  270. 
Diderot,  i,  319. 
Dignity,  ii,  330. 
Diligence,  ii,  294. 
Diodorus,  quoted,  i,  57. 
Diogenes,  i,  74  ;  ii,  279. 
Dionysius  the  Areopagite,  5,  198. 
Discretionary,   the  sphere  of  the, 

i,  155 ;  ii,  122. 
Distrust, -ii,  261. 
Divorce,  i,  85 ;  vs.  barrenness,  ii, 

308.  ' 
Dogmatics,  vs.  ethics,  i,   22  sqq. ; 

the    presupposition    of   ethics, 

180;  ii,  31. 


Domestic  animals,  ii,  264. 
Dualism,  i,  60,  62,  63,  87;    Stoic, 

133;  Schellingian,'  341  sqq. 
Diirr,  i,  250. 

Duns  Scotus,  i,  217;  ii,  85. 
Dunte,  i,  251. 
Duties,  the,  i,  296;    all  duties  are 

duties  to  God,  ii,  148. 
Duty,    i,    345;    ii,    336   sqq.;    vs. 

right,  139. 

Eberhard,  i,  298. 

Ebionites  aud  Gnostics,  i,  185. 

Ecclesiastes,  the  Book  of,  i,  168. 

Eckart,  i,  225 ;  ii,  20.   ' 

Eden,  ii,  51,  275. 

Education,  Platonic,  i,  84;  Aris 
totelian,  119  sqq. ;  ii,  198  sqq. 

Egyptian  ethics,  i,  55  sqq. 

Egyptians,  the,  i,  54;  ii,  191. 

Elvenich,  i,  357. 

Empirical  ethics,  i,  28. 

End,  the,  sanctifies  the  means,  i, 
260;  ii,  179. 

Endemann,  i,  326. 

Endurance,  Buddhistic,  i,  53. 

Enthusiasm,  ii,  173;  vs.  the  ideal, 
174;  206. 

Epictetus,  i,  132. 

Epicurean  view,  of  the  highest 
good,  i,  129;  of  pleasure,  130, 
of  right  and  wrong,  of  religion, 
of  death,  of  the  universe,  129- 
131 ;  ii,  55. 

Epicureanism,  principle  of,  i,  128 
sqq. ;  realistic,  142 ;  vs.  Chris 
tianity,  1*3. 

Epicurus,  i,  128. 

Equanimity,  i,  105. 

Erasmus,  i,  279,  281. 

Erigena,  i,  201,  223. 

"Eros,"i,  79. 

Escobar,  i,  257. 

Ethics,  defined,  i,  13;  Harless'and 
Schleierrnacher's  definition,  15; 
Platonic,  79  sqq. ;  Aristotelian, 
93  sqq. ;  Epicurean,  129;  Stoic, 
141 ;  Old  Testament,  151 ;  Chris 
tian,  173;  heathen,  177;  vs. 
dogmatics,  180  ;  Patristic,  181 ; 
mediaeval,  199;  Protestant,  235; 
I  Reformed  vs.  Lutheran,  244 


342 


INDEX. 


sqq. ;  Roman  Catholic,  255,  375; 
Spinozistic,  m  281;  Leibnitzian, 
290;  Wolfian,  292;  Lockean, 
303;  materialistico-French,  314 
sqq. ;  Kantian,  327 ;  Fichtean, 
338;  Schellingian,  342;  He 
gelian,  345  sqq. ;  Schleiermache- 
rian,  361 ;  Rothean,  371 ;  classi 
fication  of,  ii,  23-34. 

"Eudaemonia,"  i,  97,  109. 

Eudemonism,  i,  328;  ii,  176. 

Eve,  ii,  103,  249. 

Evil,  i,  13,  42;  Plato'3  view  of, 
78;  origin  of,  156. 

Example,  ii,  86,  260. 

Fables,  ii,  267. 

Fairness,  i,  107. 

Faith,    i,    153,    212;    ii,    10;    vs. 

knowledge,  12;    215;    as  a  vir 
tue,  298. 
Fall,    the,    in  Persia,  i,   60;    true 

nature  of,  ii,  166. 
Falsehood,  i,  85;  ii,  192  sqq. 
Family,   the,  in  China,   i,  46 ;   in 

India,   51;    in  Greece,  85,  110 

sqq. ;  in  Israel,  1 65. 
Family-honor,  ii,  323. 
Fatalism,  i,  115. 
Fear  of  God,  ii,  89. 
Feder,  i,  301. 
Feeling,  ii,   13,  49,  98,  159,  249; 

its  perfection,  ii,  283. 
Fenelon,  i,  276. 
Ferguson,  i,  312. 
Feuerbach,  i,  351. 
Fenerleiri,  i,  37.  • 

Fidelity,  ii,  293. 
Fichte,  i,  338 ;    his  moral  canon, 

339  ;  J.  H.,  358. 
Fischer,  i,  358. 
Filliucci,  i,  257. 
Flatt,  i,  360. 

Formation,  ii,  180,  198  sqq. 
Frederick  the  Great,  i,  320. 
Freedom,  i,  38 ;  true,  ii,  280. 
"Free  love,"  i,  85. 
Friendship,  i,  111  sqq. ;  Christian, 

ii,  318;  vs.  friendliness. 
Fulbert,  i,  200. 
Future  life,  i,  41 ;  Egyptian  view 

of,    57 ;     Aristotle's    view    of, 


95  ;   why  not  prominent  in  the 
Mosaic  law,  161  sqq. 

Gallantry,  ii,  319,  327. 

Garve,  i,  301. 

Gassendi,  i,  314. 

Gellert,  i,  300. 

Genettus,  i.  272. 

Gerhard,  i/252. 

"  German  Theology,"  i,  229. 

Gerson,  i,  228. 

Gifts,  i,  125;  ii,  259. 

Giving,  ii,  258. 

Goal,  the  Chinese,  i,  44 ;  the  Brah- 
minic,  49  ;  the  Buddhistic,  53  ; 
the  Persian,  60;  the  Platonic, 
91;  the  Aristotelian,  96;  the 
Mosaic,  154 ;  the  Christian, 
174;  220;  ii,  7,  24,  30, 149,  274. 

God,  the  basis  and  measure  of 
the  moral,  ii,  9  ;  his  free  immu 
tability,  85;  145;  232. 

God-consciousness,  the,  ii,  80. 

God-fearing,  ii,  172;  vs.  tjrod-trust- 
ing,  173. 

God-likeness,  i,  77;  ii,  164. 

God- worship,  ii,  276. 

Gonzales,  i,  262. 

Good,  the,  i,  13,  40;  among  the 
Chinese,  42  ;  among  the  Greeks, 
43;  among  the  Indians,'  47; 
according  to  Plato,  77;  accord 
ing  to  Aristotle,  96 ;  according 
to  Peter  Lombard,  206;  ii,  5, 
sqq. ;  vs.  the  moral,  10;  three 
phases  of,  91. 

Gossip,  ii,  261. 

Grace-saying,  ii,  188. 

Graffiis,  i,  272. 

Grecian,  the,  his  unseriousness,  i, 
67 ;  his  presumption,  68 ;  hia 
virtues,  293. 

Gregory,  of  Nyssa,  of  Nazianzum, 
i,  190;  the  Great,  198. 

Guion,  Madame,  i,  276. 

Gutzkow,  i,  362. 

Gymnastics,  ii,  241. 

Habit,  i,  99;  ii,  290. 
Hales,  i,  208. 
Hanssen,  i,  325. 
Happiness,  ii,  175. 


INDEX. 


343 


Harless,  i,  XII,  22,  374;  ii,  28. 

Hartenstein,  i,  357. 

Hatred,  ii,  161  sqq. 

Heart,  ii,  101.  ' 

Heathen  ethics,  ground-character 

-of,  i,  38,  177;  ii,  175. 
Heathenism,  i,  39,  64,  86,  155. 
Hebrew  ethics,  i,  156. 
Hegel,  his  view  of  ethics,  i,  20 ; 

345 ;  on  State  and  Church,  349. 
Heidegger,  i,  248. 
Helvetius,  i,  314. 
Hemming,  i,  242. 
Hengstenberg,  i,  VI. 
Henriquez,  i,  256. 
Hellene,  the,  i,  64  sqq. 
Help-meet,  the  idea  of,  ii,  309. 
Herbart,  i,  356. 
Hermaphrodite,  ii.  75. 
Heroic  virtue,  i,  108. 
Heydenreich,  i,  336. 
Highest  good,  the,  i,  97,  159,  161, 

176,  209,  365;  ii,  6,  43;  276. 
Hildebert,- i,  204. 
Hirsoher,  i,  376;  ii,  117. 
Hobbes,  i,  304. 
Holbach,  i,  321. 
Holiness,  ii,  285,  286. 
Home,  significance  of,  ii,  331. 
Honor,  ii,  183,  253. 
Hope,  i,  212;  as  a  virtue,  ii,  299. 
Hospitality,  ii,  196. 
Human  flesh,  the  eating  of,  i,  270. 
Humanism,  i,  '279. 
Humanity,  i,  38,  121. 
Hume,  i,  311. 
"  Humanitarianism,"   i,    66,    121 ; 

ii,  255. 
Humility,  i,  175 ;    as  a  virtue,  ii, 

298. 

Hunger,  ii,  187. 
Huss,  i,  231. 
Hutcheson,  i,  310. 

Ideal,  the,  vs.  the  real,  ii,  82. 

Illuminism.  i,  302,  322,  327,  337; 
ii,  20. 

Image,  the,  of  God,  ii,  37,  42. 

Immortality,  ii,  51. 

Incarnation,  conditional  or  un 
conditional,  ii.  86.  ' 

Incomprehensibility  of  God,  ii,  44. 


Innocence  vs.  holiness,  ii,  285. 
Intercession,  ii,  224. 
Irenasus,  i,  185. 
Isenbiehl,  i,  376. 
Isidore,  i,  190,  198. 
Islamism,  i,  171. 

Israel,  the  world-historical  sig 
nificance  of,  i,  157  sqq. 

Jacob,  i,  159;  L.  H.,  336. 

Jacobi,  i,  342,  344. 

Jansenism,  i,  273. 

Jealousy,  ii,  196. 

Jerome,  i,  192. 

Jesuits,  i,  256  sqq. ;  their  Pelagian- 
ism,  260;  their  moral  laxity, 
264;  on  equivocation,  266;  on 
adultery,  268;  ii,  178. 

Jocham,  i,  376. 

John,  of  Salisbury,  i,  220  sqq. ;  of 
Goch,  231. 

Jovinian,  i,  192. 

Judaism,  i,  171,  282. 

Judas,  i,  343. 

Judith,  the  Book  of,  i,  171. 

Justin,  i,  186. 

Just  mean,  the,  i,  45  ;  of  Aristotle, 
100. 

Justness,  i,  81,  106;  ii,  294. 

Kahler.  i,  361. 

Kant,  i,  324,  327;  his  ethical 
works,  329;  his  canon  of  mo 
rality,  330  ;  criticised,  333 ;  hia 
second  canon,  334;  ii,  22,  39, 
44,  52,  83;  on  prayer,  222. 

Keckermajjjn,  i,  247. 

Kiesewetter,  i,  336. 

Kingdom  of  God,  the,  i,  156;  ii, 
276. 

Kiss,  the,  significance  of,  ii,  356. 

Klein,  i,  344. 

Knowledge  vs.  faith,  ii,  12. 

Konig,  i,  251. 

Kostlin,  ii,  266. 

Krause,  i,  344. 

Labor,  fi,  203,  271. 

Lactantius,  i,  191. 

La  Mettrie,  i,  320.  f 

Lampe,  i,  248. 

Lauge,  S.  G.,  i,  338. 


INDEX. 


Latin  theology  vs.  Grecian,  i,  193. 

Law,  ii,  90. 

Laymarm,  i,  257. 

Leibnitz,  i,  278,  290;  his  theodicy, 
291. 

Less,  i,  257,  326. 

Liberality,  i,  104. 

Libtrum  arbitrium,  ii,  45. 

Life-stages,  ii,  67. 

Ligorio,  i,  375. 

Lipsius,  i,  281. 

Lobkowitz,  i,  271. 

Locke,  i,  303. 

Lombard,  Peter,  i,  206. 

Love,  Platonic,  i,  99 ;  Christian,  ii, 
213;  vs.  hatred,  161  sqq. ;  vs. 
fear,  172;  vs.  happiness-seek 
ing,  176;  a  duty,  178;  201,257. 

Luther,  i,  235 ;  ii,  109. 

Lutheran  ethics,  i,  244. 

Magic,  ii,  157. 

Magnanimity,  i,  105;  portrayed 
by  Aristotle,  1 24  sqq. 

Majority,  i,  168 ;  civil  vs.  moral,  ii, 
70. 

Malder,  i,  272. 

Mandula,  i,  271. 

Manichees,  ii,  268. 

Manliness,  i,  81. 

Manu,  the  Laws  of,  i,  48. 

Marcus  Aurelins,  i,  133. 

Mariana,  i,  269. 

Marriage,  moral  presuppositions 
of,  ii,  304  sqq. 

Masculinity,  ii,  75. 

Marheineke,  i,  37,  146,  352. 

Marriage,  Brahminic,  i,  5l ;  Gre 
cian,  66;  Platonic,  85;  Aris 
totelian,  118;  Stoic,  140;  Isra- 
elitic,  165;  early  Christian,  181; 
"irresistible  aversion"  in,  ii, 
169;  Christian.  310  sqq. ;  re 
quires  diverse  qualities  iii  con 
sorts.  321. 

Martensen,  i,  358. 

Martin,  i,  376. 

Materialism,  ii,  61. 

Maxim  vs.  law,  ii,  133. 

Maximus,  i,  198. 

Mehmel,  i,  341. 

Meier,  i,  250,  299. 


Meiner,  i,  37. 

Melanchthon,  i,  236;  his  works, 
237  ;  on  will-freedom,  239. 

Melchizedek,  ii,  336. 

Mengering,  i,  251. 

Mexicans,  the,  i,  43. 

Michelet,  i,  351. 

Middle- way,  the,  i,  100. 

Minority,  ii,  68. 

Miracles,  i,  158. 

Moderation,  ii,  189. 

Moral  element,  the,  of  an  action, 
ii,  178. 

Morality,  Chinese,  i,  50 ;  Buddhis 
tic,  52  sqq. ;  Persian.  62;  Gre 
cian,  63;  Socratic,  70;  Platonic, 
79;  Israelitic,  154;  Christian, 
174;  Patristic,  181;  Hegelian, 
347;  ii,  8  ;  vs.  religion,  15  ;  cen 
trifugal.  17. 

Moller,  i,  344. 

Mohammed,  i,  172. 

Moleschott,  i,  354. 

Molinos,  i,  275;  ii,  20. 

Monasticism,  beginnings  of,  i,  183; 
200. 

Monkery,  ii,  280. 

More,  i,"306.     ' 

Morus,  i,  326. 

Motive,  general  nature  of,  ii,  159; 
179. 

Moses,  i,  164. 

Mosheim,  i,  15,  326. 

Miiller,  i,  351. 

Mummies,  significance  of,  5,  57. 

"  Must "  and  "  should,"  antagonist 
ic,  i,  14;  ii,  90;  167. 

Mysticism,  i,  198,  224,  231,  273, 
275,  341  ;  ii,  18,  20. 

Name-giving,  ii,  39. 

Name-interchanging,  ii,  260. 

Narcissus,  ii,  321. 

Natalis,  i,  272. 

Nationalities,  ii,  73. 

Naturalism,  i,  144;  Greek,  122; 
Epicurean,  129;  288. 

Nature,  its  destination,  ii,  156 ;  du 
ties  toward,  264;  symbolism  in, 
266;  abuse  of,  272. 

Navarra,  i,  265. 

Neander,  i,  37. 


INDEX. 


345 


Nebuchadnezzar,  i,  58. 
Neighbor-love,  ii,  254. 
Neo-Platonism,  i,  144,  147;    Pan 
theistic,  148;  mystical,  149. 
Nicole,  i,  274. 
Nimrod,  i,  58. 
"Nirvana,"  i,  40. 
Nitzsch,  i,  24 ;  P.,  ii,  58. 
Nobility,  ii,  324. 
Normality,  moral,  ii,  286. 
Nudity,  in  art,  ii,  244. 

Obedience,  ii,  288. 

Objective  morality,  i.  86. 

Official  morality,  ii,  78. 

Old  age,  ii,  68." 

Olearms,  i,  251. 

Ontology,  Chinese,  i,  44;  Brah- 
minic.  48 ;  Buddhistic,  52 ; 
Egyptian,  55  ;  Semitic,  57 ;  Per 
sian,  59;  Grecian,  63;  Platonic, 
78;  Aristotelian,  94;  Epicu 
rean,  131,  142;  Stoic,  133,  142; 
Hebrew,  153;  Neo-Platonic, 
201;  Spinozistic,  282;  Leibnitz- 
ian,  290;  Kantian,  329;  Fich- 
tean,  338;  Schellingian,  342; 
Hegelian,  345  sqq. 

Opera  supererogatoria,  i,  234. 

Origen,-i,  187. 

Ornamentation,  ii,  244. 

Osiander,  i,  251. 

Osiris,  i,  56. 

Palmer,  i,  29,  374. 

Pain,  ii,  60. 

Pantheism,  Indian,  i,  47 ;  Neo-Pla 
tonic,  147;  mediasval,  198;  of 
Erigena,  201;  of  Eckart,  225; 
of  Spinoza,  282  ;  of  Fichte,  337 : 
of  Sclielling,  341 ;  of  Hegel,  346; 
of  Strauss,  352 ;  ii,  47 ;  moral 
tendency  of,  81  sqq. ;  vs.  prayer, 
222. 

Paradise,  i,  45 ;  true  significance 
of,  ii,  197;  212. 

Parents  vs.  children,  ii,  313. 

"  Parrhassia,"  ii,  297. 

Pascal,  i,  274. 

Patuzzi,  i,  376. 

Peace,  ii,  163. 

Pederasty,  i,  141. 


Pelagianism,  i,  260,  279. 

Pennaforti,  i,  222. 

Peraldus,  i,  219.  * 

Perazzo,  i,  272. 

Perfection,  moral,  i,  278. 

Perkins,  i,  248. 

Pericles,  i,  65. 

•Personal  honor,  ii,  330. 

Peru,  ii,  121. 

Petition,  ii,  224. 

Pharisaism,  i,  136.  232. 

Philosophical  ethics,  i.  16,  27 ;  vs. 
theological,  28;  355. 

Physiognomies,  ii,  243. 

Piccolomini,  i,  256. 

Piety,  i,  81;  ii,  15;  vs.  morality, 
147;  170. 

Pietism,  i,  252,  337. 

Piety-virtues,  the,  ii,  297. 

Plant-sparing,  ii,  184. 

Plato,  i,  75;  his  works,  76;  on 
the  virtues,  81 ;  on  the  state, 
82  ;  on  caste,  83  ;  on  property, 
84;  on  divorce,  85 ;  on  religion, 
91 ;  on  reading  Homer,  92. 

Play,  ii,  128. 

Pleasure,  i,  109;  Epicurean,  130. 

Plotinus,  i,  147. 

Plutarch,  i,  151. 

Polanus,  i,  247. 

Politeness,  impersonal,  ii,  326. 

Polygamy,  ii,  306. 

Pomponatius,  i,  281. 

Pontas,  i,  272. 

Porphyry,  i,  147. 

Prayer,  i,  177;  ii,  147,  218;  Kant 
on,  222. 

Predestinarianism,  i,  242,  273. 

Presentiment,  ii,  226. 

Prierias,  i,  222. 

Priest  vs.  layman,  ii,  334. 

Proclus,  i.  147. 

Probabilism,  i,  255,  261. 

Property,  Plato  on,  84;  ii,  279,  280. 

Prophecy,  ii,  226. 

Proverbs,  the  Book  ofj  i,  167. 

Prudence,  ii,  282. 

Pyramids,  the,  significance  of,  i,  57. 

Pyrrho,  i,  145. 

Quesnel,  i,  274. 

Quietism,  i,  273,  275 ;    ii,  18,  303. 


346 


1  INDEX. 


Race,  the  human,  its  unity,  ii,  153. 

Radicalism,  i,  346. 

Rationalistic  ethics,  i,  37,  322, 
324;  ii,  22. 

Rationality,  ii.  6 ;  vs.  morality,  9  ; 
41. 

Raymond  of  Toulouse,  i,  230. 

Reynauld,  i,  257. 

Reason,  i,  329;  the  practical,  331. 

Recluse-life,  the,  ii,  303. 

Redemption,  progressively  reveal 
ed,  i,  166,' 

Reformation,  the,  i,  232,  233. 

Reinhard,  i,  360. 

Religion  vs.  morality,  ii,  15;  cen 
tripetal,  17. 

Repentance,  i,  286. 

'.'  Republic,"  the,  of  Plato,  i,  82 ; 
criticised,  290;  ii,  276,  334. 

"Rescuer"  of the-Persians,  i,  61. 

Reservatio  mentalis,  i,  255,  266,  271. 

Resurrection,  the,  ii,  66. 

Reusch,  i,  325. 

Reuss,  i,  326. 

Reverence  for  elders,  ii,  316. 

Right,  three  stages  of,  291  ;  345, 
347;  vs.  duty,  ii,  139;  vs.  law, 
332. 

Rixner,  i,  250. 

Rodriguez,  i,  257. 

Roman  philosophy,  i,  149. 

Rothe.  i,  XII,  9 ;  on  the  scope  of 
ethics,  18;  25,  30;  on  heter 
odoxy,  31;  criticised,  32  sqq. ; 
359  ;  on  church  and  state,  372 ; 
ii,  10,  21,  24;  on  conscience, 
104;  110,  129,  168,  264;  on  the 
virtues,  301. 

Rousseau,  i,  37,  280;  his  ethical 
views,  317;  222. 

Rudeness,  ii,  184. 

Ruisbroch,  i,  228. 

Sa.  i,  265. 

Sabbath,   the,  idea  of,   i,   155;    ii, 

212  sqq. 

Sacrifice,  ii,  218  sqq. 
Sailer,  i,  376. 
St.  Victor,  i,  224. 
Sakya-Muni,  i,  52. 
Salat,  i,  245. 
Sales,  Francis  de,  i,  275. 


Sanchez,  i,  251. 
Sarah,  ii,  321. 
Sanctification,  ii,  285,  287. 
Savages  vs.  history,  ii,  191. 
Scavini,  i,  376. 
Sartorius,  i,  24,  374, 
Satanology,  i,  344. 
Savonarola,  i,  231. 
Schleiermacher,   i,    XII,    317 ;    on 

Spinoza,  290;    361  sqq. ;   ii,   24 

sqq.,  39,  63,  110,  129. 
Scholling,  i,  280;  his  ontology  and 

ethics. ,341-344;  ii,  47. 
Schenkel,  i,  337 ;  ii,  107. 
Schenkl,  i,  376. 
Scblegel,  i,  362. 
Schliephake,  i,  358. 
Schmid,  i,  336  ;  J.  W.,  338  ;  C.  R, 

374. 

Schmidt,  i,  338. 
Scholasticism,  i,  200,  203. 
Schopenhauer,  i,  358. 
Schubert,  i.  325. 
Schwarz,  i,  360 ;  ii,  24,  141. 
Schweitzer,  ii,  58. 
Self-culture,  ii,  248. 
Self-love,    false    vs.    the    true,   i, 

175;  vs.  God-love,  ii,  165. 
Self-mortification,  i,  50,  274. 
Secret-keeping,  ii,  193. 
Seneca,  i,  132  ;  on  suicide,  139. 
Senility,  ii,  71. 
Senses,  the,  ii,  63. 
Service-rendering,  ii,  261. 
Servile-mindedness,  ii,  185. 
Sex,  ii,  74  ;   in  nature,  304. 
Sextus  Empiricns,  i,  145. 
Sexual  relations.  Jesuitical  teach 
ings  as  to,  i,  266. 
Shaftesbury,  i,  308. 
Shame,  i,  106;   ii,  239. 
Sin,  its  historical  origin,  i,   156; 

Christian  view  of,  176,  215. 
Sismond,  i,  264. 

Sirach,  the  Book  of,  i,  169;    ii,  46. 
Skepticism,  i,  144  sqq. ;  ii,  13. 
Slavery,  Grecian,  i,  66 ;  Aristotle's 

apology  for,  117  ;  ii,  152. 
Sleep,  i,  14. 
Smith,  i,  311. 
Snell,  i,  336. 
Soeinianism,  i,  281. 


INDEX. 


347 


Socrates,  i,  65,  69,  70,  72 ;  vs.  his 
wife,  72 ;  advances  made  by, 
127. 

Solidarity,  ii,  324. 

Solon,  i,  66. 

Sparing,  ii,  180  ;  its  objects,  183  ;. 
232,  252. 

Speculation,  theological,  i,  30. 

Spener,  i,  252. 

Spinoza,  i,  31,  278;  his  Ethica, 
281 ;  vs.  Calvin,  ii,  47. 

Stackhouse,  i,  326. 

Stalil,  i,  358 ;  ii,  130. 

Stapf,  i,  376. 

Staudlin,  i,  36,  338. 

Stapfer,  i,  324. 

Stattler,  i,  376. 

Steinbart,  i,  323. 

Stiruer,  i,  354. 

Strauss,  i.  352. 

Strigel,  i,'  242. 

State,  the  Chinese,  i,  47  ;  the  Pla 
tonic,  82 ;  the  Hegelian,  345, 
349. 

Stoicism,  i,  131 ;  vs.  Epicureanism, 
132,  145;  errors  of,  141;  vs. 
Christianity,  143,  182. 

Stoic  view,  of  virtue,  i,  131 ;  of  the 
life-goal,  and  of  the  norm  of 
truth,  133 ;  of  the  good,  134 ; 
of  religion,  136;  of  compassion, 
137  ;  of  death,  138  ;  of  suicide, 
139;  of  marriage,  140. 

Suarez,  i,  257. 

Subjectivism,  i,  144. 

Suicide,  i,  139. 

Summon  casuum,  i,  222. 

Supererogatory  works,  i,  234 ;  ii, 
1 1 4  sqq. 

Supralapsarianism,  ii,  46. 

Symbolical  forming,  ii,  209. 

Symbolism,  ii.  206. 

Table-luxuries,  ii,  189. 

Table-pleasures,  ii,  241. 

Talmud,  the,  i,  171. 

Tamburini,  i,  257. 

Taste,  ii,  195. 

Tauler,  i,  226  ;    on  three  kinds  of 

works,  227  ;  ii,  20. 
Temperaments',    the,   ii,   71  ;    four 

of  them,  73,  292. 


Temperateness,  i,  81,  104 ;  ii,  291, 

295. 
Tertullian,   i,   187 ;   on  marriage, 

188. 

Thankfulness,  ii,  262,  294. 
Thanksgiving,  ii,  223. 
Theological  ethics,  i,  21,  27 ;    vs. 

philosophical,  35  ;    as  a  distinct 

science,    247;    250,    359,    371; 

ii,  1. 
Theocracy,  the,  in  Israel,  i,  166; 

ii,  335. 

Theosophy,  i,  30,  341,  375. 
Thomas  a  Kempis,  i,  229. 
Thomas  Aquinas,  i,  208 ;    on  the 

will.   209  ;  on  virtue,   211 ;  on 

the  virtues,  212. 
Thomasius,  i,  298. 
Tieflrunk,  i,  336. 
Titans,  the,  i,  64. 
Tittmann,  i,  326. 
Tollner,  i,  326. 
Tolet,  i,  256.    . 
Tournley,  i,  376. 
Trendelenburg,  ii,  107. 
Trust,  ii,  173. 
Tweston,  i,  364. 
Typhon,  i,  56. 
Tyranny,  of  man  over  woman,  ii, 

311. 
Tyrant-murder,  Jesuitical  code  of, 

i,  269. 

Unitas  Fratrum,  ii,  336. 
Unity  of  mankind,  ii,  152. 
Utilitarianism,  ii,  203. 

Vatke,  i.  351. 

Vasquez,  i,  256. 

Vedas,  the,  i,  48. 

Venial  sins,  i,  188,  265. 

Vergier,  i,  275. 

Virginity,  ii,  190. 

Virtue,  Brahminic,  i,  49  ;  Chinese. 
50;  Platonic,  77,  81:  essence 
of,  207;  339,  366;  ii,  177,  274; 
New  Testament,  idea  of,  290. 

Virtues,  the  cardinal,  i,  195;  207, 
239,  243 ;  four  chief,  290 ;  the 
Platonic,  ii,  292 ;  different  clas 
sifications  of,  300. 

Vogel,  i,  338. 


348 


INDEX. 


Vogt,  i,  354. 

Volition,  ii,  250. 

Yoltaire,    i,   28 ;    superficiality  of 

his  ethics,  319. 
Von  Eitzen,  i.  248. 
Von  Henning,  i,  251. 

Waibel,  i,  376. 

Walaeus,  i,  247. 

\Valdenses,  the,  i,  231. 

Weber,  Dr.  A.,  i,  VIII. 

Wedlock-love,  ii,  121. 

Werner,  i,  376. 

Wickliffe,  i,  231. 

Will,  the,  the  sphere  of  the  moral, 

ii,  10. 
Will-freedom,  i,  14 ;    in  Aristotle, 

96;    threefold,    206;    209,    224, 

239,  335  ;  ii,  13,  45,  84. 
Wirth,  i,  357. 
Wisdom,  i,  81.  107  ;    practical,  ii, 

133 ;   true,  286. 


Wisdom,  the  Book  of,  i,  170. 

"  Wise  men,"  the,  i,  69. 

Wolf,  i,  278,  292  sqq. 

Wollaston,  i,  308. 

Womanliness,  ii,  75. 

'.'  Woman's  rights,"  Plato's   view 

of,  i,  86 ;    the  author's  view  of, 

ii,  310  sqq. 

Worship,  i,  369;    ii,  215. 
Writing,  the  art  of,  ii,  191. 
Wuttke,    sketch   of  his   life    and 

works,  i,  VII ;    his  confessional 

position,  VIII ;  his  life-task,  IX ; 

his   relation    to    Hengstenberg, 

X  ;  character  of  his  ethics,  XII ; 

scope  of  the  same,  35. 

Youth,   prone    to    revolution,   ii, 
329. 

Zeno,  i,  131  sqq. 
Zockler,  ii,  266. 


XS3Z.44