Skip to main content

Full text of "Cognitive bias in strategic decision-making : some conjectures"

See other formats


UNIVERSITY  Of- 

ILLINOIS  LIBRARY 

AT  URBANA-CHAMPAIGN 

BOOKSTACKS 


H 


O/^*^  i>  ^  :> 


m 


H 


H 


,-<w- 


Digitized  by  the  Internet  Archive 

in  2011  with  funding  from 

University  of  Illinois  Urbana-Champaign 


http://www.archive.org/details/cognitivebiasins863schw 


FACULTY  WORKING 
PAPER  NO.  863 


Cognitive  Bias  in  Strategic  Decision-Making: 
Some  Conjectures 

Charles  R.  Schwenk 


itHE 


!i?'ye. 


"^^  or 


^f 


'^"'^'V/l..^/     'i., 


^'^^^P» 


College  of  Comm-rce  and  Business  Adrrinistraiion 
Bureau  ct  Economic  and  -Busirisss  Research 
University  of  illincis.  Urbana-Chanoaign 


"vfl.v: 


BEBR 


FACULTY  WORKING  PAPER  NO.  863 
College  of  Commerce  and  Business  Administration 
University  of  Illinois  at  Urbana-Champaign 
April  1982 


Cognitive  Bias  in  Strategic 
Decision-Making:   Some  Conjectures 


Charles  R.  Schwenk,  Assistant  Professor 
Department  of  Business  Administration 


ABSTRACT 

Strategic   decision-making  can  be  viewed  as  a  special   kind  of   decision- 
making under  uncertainty.     Researchers   in  a  variety  of   fields  have 
identified  a  number  of  cognitive  or  perceptual  mechanisms  by  which 
decision  makers  distort   information  from  the  environment   to  make   it 
appear  simpler   and  reduce  the  apparent  uncertainty  in  a  decision-making 
task.      Within  this   paper,    a  four-stage  model  of   strategic   decision-making 
is  developed  and  the  possible  effects  of  cognitive  biases   at   each  stage 
are  discussed.      Finally,    techniques   for   introducing  conflict   into   strategy 
formulation  are  proposed  as  ways  of  counteracting  the  effects   of   these 
biases. 


COGNITIVE  BIAS    IN  STRATEGIC 
DECISION- MAKING:      SOME   CONJECTUKES 


Strategic  decision-making  has  been  defined  as  a  special  kind  of  ill- 
structured  problem-solving  process  and  as  a  special  type  of  decision- 
making under  uncertainty  (Hofer  &  Schendel,  1978:46).  Because  of  the 
importance  of  strategic  decision-making,  much  effort  has  been  devoted 
to  developing  procedures  for  improving  the  effectiveness  of  the  process 
by  increasing  the  amount  of  data  considered  and  the  thoroughness  with 
which  it  is   evaluated     (Grant   &  King,   1979:104-122). 

A  number  of  recent  articles  in  the  strategic  management  field  have 
developed  and  validated  descriptive  models  of  the  strategic  decision- 
making process    (Mintzberg,   Raisinghanl,   &  Theoret  1976;   Glueck  1976; 
Mazzolini,   1981;   Hofer  &  Schendel,   1978).      These  models   involve  various 
numbers  of  stages   and  are  generally  similar  to  earlier  models  of  the 
organizational   decision-making  process    (Lang,   Dittrich,    &  White,   1978). 
The  decisional  activities  at  each  stage  have  been  examined  experimentally 
by   cognitive  psychologists  and  behavioral  decision  theorists  and  numerous 
biases  have  been  identified  which  limit  decisional  effectiveness.      An 
understanding  of  these  biases   is  necessary   for  the  design  of  effective 
strategic   decision-making  aids. 

Theorists   in  the  field  of  Strategic  Management  have  pointed  out 
that  human  cognitive  limitations  might  affect  strategic  decision-making 
(Steiner   &  Miner,   1977:226-231;   Mintzberg,   1973:45-46),   basing  their 
arguments  on  Simon's  notions   of  "bounded  rationality"  and   "satisficing. " 
They  have  pointed  out   that  strategic  decision-makers  are  subject   to 
bounded  rationality  and  do  not  optimize  in  their  decisions  but  have  not 


-2- 

discussed  the  specific  effects  of  bounded   rationality  on  decision- makers' 
perceptions  or   the  specific  decisional  behaviors  adopted  in  preference 
to  optimizing.     However,   some  researchers  have  discussed  the  effects  of 
specific  cognitive  biases  on  general  managerial  decision-making   (Taylor, 
1975;  Hogarth,   19  80)    and  on  the  use  of  forecasts    (Hogarth  &  Makridakis, 
1981). 

This   paper   develops   conjectures  about  possible  biases   in  strategic 
decision-making  by  drawing  on  literature  in  the   fields  of  cognitive 
psychology  and  behavioral  decision  theory  dealing  with  problem  formu- 
lation and  decision- making  under  uncertainty.      These  biases  allow  for 
some  specific  predictions  about   the  types  of  errors   to  which  decision 
makers  will  be  subject  in  various  activities  or  phrases  of  strategic 
decision-making.      Such  information  could  be  helpful  to  researchers   in 
attempting  to   explain  decisionad   failures  and  to  practitioners   inter- 
ested in  reducing  the  effects  of  these  biases   through  the  use  of  deci- 
sion aids.      This  paper  does  not,  of  course,   represent  an  exhaustive 
review  of  the  literature  in  these  fields.      Rather,   attention  is    focused 
on  some  of  the  more  widely  discussed  cognitive  biases. 

Research  on  these  biases  has   dealt  with   them  individually  and  has 
not   focused  on  the  interaction  between  then.      For  this   reason,   and  the 
fact   that  most  of  the  research  was   conducted  in  laboratory  settings 
using  relatively  simple  judgement  and  decision  tasks,   statements  about 
the  effects  of  these  biases   on  strategic  decision-making  must  remain 
speculative. 

In  this   paper,   a   general  model  of  the  strategic  decision-making 
process  will  be  synthesized  from  existing  models.      Cognitive  biases 


-3- 

which  may  operate  at  each  stage  of  the  process  will  then  be  discussed. 
Finally,  suggestions  for  future  research  on  cognitive  biases  and  for 
improving  strategic  decisions  will  be  offered. 

A  DESCRIPTIVE  MODEL  OF  THE  STRATEGIC  DECISION- MAKING  PROCESS 
The  strategic  management  literature  contains  a  number  of  strategic 
decision- making  models.   Since  cognitive  biases  will  be  discussed  in 
terms  of  their  effects  on  various  processes  in  strategy  formulation, 
it  is  necessary  to  generate  a  model  which  represents  the  essential 
features  of  the  most  prominent  models  in  the  field.  Hofer  &  Schendel 
(1978,  p.  47)  have  developed  a  model  which  builds  on  the  major  ana- 
lytical models  of  Andrews  (1965,  1980),  Ansoff  (1965),  and  others. 
It  includes  the  seven  steps  of  strategy  identification,  environmental 
analysis,  resource  analysis,  gap  analysis  (problem  identification), 
generation  of  strategic  alternatives,  strategy  evaluation,  and  stra- 
tegic choice. 

The  fact  that  such  processes  actually  occur  in  organizational 
decision-making  has  been  confirmed  by  Mintzberg,  Raisinghani,  & 
Theoret  (1977).   Several  of  the  stages  dealt  with  in  Hofer  &  Schendel's 
model  are  also  covered  by  Mintzberg,  et  al.   However,  their  model 
begins  with  the  identification  and  diagnosis  of  a  problem.   This  is 
followed  by  the  search  for  alternatives  and  information  related  to  the 
alternatives.   This  stage,  in  turn,  is  followed  by  the  evaluation  and 
selection  of  an  alternative.   This  is  an  iterative  model  involving 
numerous  feedback  loops  which  allow  decisional  activity  to  cycle 
from  later  to  earlier  stages  as  the  strategic  problem  definition  is 
progressively  refined. 


-4- 

It   may  be  that   the  two  rcdels  actually  describe  two   different  but 
equally  legitimate  types   of  strategic  decision-making.      Leotiades 
(1979:96-102)   distinguished  between  strategy   formulation  which   is  part 
of  a   regular  strategic  planning  cycle  and  strategy   formulation  which 
occurs  in  response  to  a  particular  problem  (for  example,   a  need  to 
make  a  particular  acquisition  decision).      Ihe   former  begins  with  at- 
tempts  to  systematically  collect   information  about   the  environment  and 
the  company's   resources  and  is  best  described  by  Hofer   &  Schendel's 
model.      The  latter,  which  begins   in  response  to  a  particular  problem, 
is   probably  best  described  by  Mintzberg's   model. 

Glueck   (1976)    proposed  a  model  which  included  the  stages  of  Appraisal 
(including  an  analysis  of  environmental  opportunities  and  threats   and 
company  resources).    Choice   (generation  and  consideration  of  alternative 
strategies   and  choice  among  the  alternatives),    Implementation,   and 
Evaluation.      Finally,   Mazzolini   (1981)    developed  a  nodel  involving  five 
major  activities  based  on  his  own  research  and  literature  review.      The 
five  activities   included  Decision-need  identification.   Search   for 
alternatives   for   action.    Investigation  of  courses   of  action.   Review  and 
approval,    and  Implementation. 

These  models  are  built  on  earlier  and  more  general  decision-making 

models  and  are  consistent  with  at  least  the   first   three  stages  of 

Simon's   four-stage  description  of  the  management   decision-making 

process    (1960:40-44). 

Decision  making  comprises  four  principal  phases: 
finding  occasions  for  making  a  decision,  finding  pos- 
sible courses  of  action,  choosing  among  courses  of 
action,  and  evaluating  past  choices. 


-5- 


The   first  phase  of  the  decision-niaking  process — 
searching  the  environment    for  conditions   calling  for 
decision — I  shall   call   intelligence   activity    (bor- 
rowing the  military   ireaning  of   intelligence).      The 
second  phase — inventing,    developing,   and  analyzing 
possible  courses   of  action — I   shall   call  design 
activity.      The  third  phase — selecting  a  particular 
course  of  action  from  those  available — I  shall  call 
choice  activity.      The  fourth  phase,   assessing  past 
choices,   I  shall  call   re\dew  activity. 

(Simon,  1960:40-41) 


As   a  basis   for  the  discussion  of  simplification  mechanisms,   a 
simplified  four-stage  model  of  the  strategy   formulation  process  has 
been  developed  based  on  earlier  models.      The   four  stages   in  the  present 
model  are  strategic  problem  identification,   strategic  alternatives 
generation,   evaluation  and  selection,   and  strategy  implementation. 
There  seems  to  be  a  good  deal  of  agreement  among  researchers  in  this 
field   (represented  by  those  whose  model  we  discussed)    that  at_  least 
these  basic  activities  characterize  strategic  decision-making.      How- 
ever,  this  model  is  not  intended  to  represent   the   full  complexity  of 
strategic  decision-making. 

Any  model  which  is   representative  of  the  more  popular  models   in 
the  field  would  have  to  include  the  notion  of  feedback  loops.      Thus 
in  this   derived  model,   decisional  activity  may  cycle  from  later  to 
earlier  stages  as  in  the  Mintzberg  et  al.   model. 

Problem  identification  includes  attempts   to  identify  the  com- 
pany's  current   implicit  and  explicit  goals,  objectives,   and  strategies 
as  well  as  an  assessment  of  the  significant  opportunities  and  threats 
in  the  environment,   and  the  company's   current  resources.      Assessment 
of  opportunities  and   threats   in  the  environment   is   a  preliminary  stage 
to   gap  analysis  and  often  requires    forecasting.      Problem  identification 


-6- 

also  includes  a  recognition  that  a  problem  exists.   This  presumably 
takes  the  form  of  a  gap  between  current  or  projected  future  perfor- 
mance and  the  explicit  and  implicit  goals  and  objectives  of  manage- 
ment.  The  problem  is  then  defined  and  clarified  as  causes  of  the 
gap  are  identified.   Alternatives  generation  involves  the  identifica- 
tion of  gap-dosing  options  and  their  development  to  a  state  of  re- 
finement in  which  they  can  be  evaluated  against  each  other.   The 
evaluation  and  selection  stage  involves  the  screening  and  evaluation 
of  alternatives  and  the  selection  of  the  alternative  which  best  solves 
the  problem  defined  in  the  preceding  stage.   Finally,  the  implementation 
stage  involves  carrying  out  the  strategy  chosen.   This  model,  along 
with  the  Mintzberg  et  al.,  Glueck,  Hofer  &  Schendel,  and  Mazzolini 
models,  is  presented  in  Table  1. 

Insert  Table  1  about  here 


Obviously,  all  of  these  stages  do  not  occur  in  all  decisions  in 
exactly  this  sequence.   In  fact,  Witte  (1972:179)  found  from  examining 
233  organizational  decision  processes  that  the  activities  related  to 
the  "stages"  of  gathering  information,  developing  alternatives,  eval- 
uating alternatives ,  and  making  choices  were  carried  out  in  approximately 
the  same  proportion  to  each  other  throughout  the  decision  process.   The 
phase  theorem  (i.e.,  the  theorem  that  decision-making  occurs  in  dis- 
tinct phases  or  stages)  postulates  that  activities  associated  with 
gathering  information  should  predominate  early  in  a  decision  process 
and  that  activities  related  to  choice  should  dominate  toward  the  end 
of  the  decision  process.   In  contrast,  Witte  found  that  there  was  a 


-7- 

relatively  high  level  of  the  activities  associated  with  all  four 
"stages"  at  the  beginning  of  the  decision  process,  a  lull  toward  the 
middle  of  the  process,  and  a  very  high  level  of  activity  toward  the 
end  of  the  process.   Witte  concluded  "we  believe  that  human  beings 
cannot  gather  information  without  in  some  way  simultaneously  devel- 
oping alternatives.   They  cannot  avoid  evaluating  these  alternatives 
immediately,  and  in  doing  this  they  are  forced  to  a  decision"  (Witte, 
1972:180). 

Therefore,  the  four  activities  in  the  derived  model  may  be  seen 
simply  as  decisional  processes  which  may  or  may  not  occur  as  stages. 
It  may  be  that  the  structured  process  which  often  characterizes  cyclical, 
formal  strategic  planning  makes  it  more  likely  that  the  phases  will  be 
executed  in  this  order  while  in  strategy  formulation  guided  by  a  par- 
ticular problem,  the  activities  are  less  likely  to  be  executed  sequen- 
tially. Normative  work  in  strategic  management  suggests  that  problem 
identification  should  be  based  on  detailed  data  which  reveals  gaps  be- 
tween performance  and  expectations,  numerous  strategic  alternatives 
should  be  generated,  and  these  should  be  thoroughly  and  objectively 
evaluated  prior  to  choice  (Hofer  &  Schendel,  1978).   However,  the 
complexity  and  uncertainty  involved  in  strategic  decision-making  makes 
it  unlikely  that  these  normative  prescriptions  will  be  carried  out. 

The  next  section  of  the  paper  will  discuss  cognitive  biases  which 
may  operate  to  reduce  the  apparent  complexity  and  uncertainty  in  a 
decision  situation  and  may  simultaneously  reduce  the  quality  of  the 
strategic  decision. 


-8- 

COGNITIVE  BIASES    IN  STRATEGIC   DECISION-MAKING 
Research   in  cognitive  psychology  and  behavioral   decision  theory 
has  identified  numerous  cognitive  biases  which  may  operate  in  strategic 
decision-making.      These  biases  may  not  operate  in  all  strategic  deci- 
sions.     However,   their  effect  may  help  to  explain  failure  in  strategic 
decision-making. 

In  the  next  section,   the  biases   identified  in  cognitive  psychology 
and  behavioral   decision  theory  research  have  been  classified  according 
to  strategic  decision-making  stage  they  seem  roost  likely   to  affect. 

Table  2   represents  the  stages  of  the  strategy   formulation  process 
and  the  cognitive  biases  which  may  operate  at   the   first  three  stages. 
The  biases  which  operate  at  each   stage  will  be  discussed,   as  well  as 
their  probable  effects  on  each  stage. 


Insert   Table  2   about  here 


Some  biases   nay  operate  to   reduce  decisional  effectiveness  at  more 
than  one  of  the  stages. 

Problem  Identification 

In  the  strategic  decision-making  models  previously  discussed,    the 
major  purpose  of  information  gathering  in  the  beginning  of  the  process 
is   to  identify   gaps  between  objectives  and  performance.      However,   such 
gaps  may   indicate  either  random  fluctuations  or  changes   requiring  revi- 
sions  in  strategy.      Decision-makers*   expectations  may  determine  how 
such   gaps  are  interpreted  or  even  whether  information  on  such   gaps  will 
be  accepted  and  used.      The  following  have  been  identified  as   cognitive 
biases  which  may  affect  problem  identification:     prior  hypothesis  bias. 


-9- 


adjustment  and  anchoring,    escalating  conmitinent,    the  illusion  of  con- 
trol,   reasoning  by  analogy,   salience,   and  misguided  parsimony    (see 
Table  2). 

Prior  Hypothesis  Bids 

Researchers  have  identified  a  number  of  biases  which  lead  decision- 
makers  to   ignore  or  misinterpret  information.      Levine   (1971),    Pruitt 
(1961)    and  Kason   (1960)   showed  that   individuals  who   formed  erroneous 
beliefs  or  hypotheses  about   the  relationship  between  variables   tended 
to  make  decisions  on  the  basis  of  these  beliefs  despite  abundant  evi- 
dence over  numerous   trials  that   they  were  wrong.      Further,    they  sought 
and  used  information  consistent  with  these  hypotheses   rather  than  dis- 
confirming  information.      Jervis    (1976:143-181)   has  also  provided  num- 
erous  examples   from  international   relations  of  peoples'    tendency  to 
accept  information  which  conforms   to  existing  expectations  and  beliefs. 
Under  the  effects  of  this  bias,   decision-makers  who  wish   to  believe 
that   the  company's   current  strategy  is  working  may   ignore  information 
suggesting  gaps   between  performance  and  expectation.      Conversely,   those 
who  wish  to  believe  it  is   failing  may  overweight  Information  on  such 
gaps. 

Adjustment  and  Anchoring 

Tversky   &  Kahneman   (1974)   discuss  another  bias  which  helps   decision- 
makers deny   gaps.      They   call  this   the  anchoring  bias.      In  strategic 
decision-making  individuals   must  often  make  initial  judgements  about 
values  of  variables   critical  in  particular  decisions  and  revise  these 
judgements   as  new  data  comes    in.      However,    the  adjustments  are   typically 


-10- 

insuf ficient.   Final  estimates  of  values  are  biased  toward  the  initial 
values.   Individuals  involved  in  the  ongoing  process  of  strategy  formu- 
lation may  attend  to  negative  information  about  the  success  of  present 
strategy  but  they  will  tend  not  to  make  full  use  of  it  in  revising 
their  predictions  of  company  performance  under  the  present  strategy. 
These  revisions  will  be  smaller  than  are  justified  by  the  new  infor- 
mation. 

Escalating  Commitment 

If  these  initial  biases  do  not  come  into  play,  and  the  gap  is 
recognized,  some  research  suggests  that  decision-makers  deny  the 
significance  of  the  gap  and  the  need  for  the  revision  of  strategy. 
That  is,  once  they  have  recognized  the  gap,  they  may  define  the  problem 
indicated  by  the  gap  as  one  which  does  not  require  a  change  in  strategy. 
Staw  (1976),  Staw  &  Fox  (1977),  Staw  &  Ross  (1978),  and  Fox  &  Staw 
(1979),  in  laboratory  studies  using  undergraduates  as  subjects  with 
simulated  investment  tasks,  demonstrated  escalating  commitment  to  a 
chosen  alternative  despite  negative  feedback.   They  found  that  once 
an  individual  commits  a  significant  amount  of  money  to  an  investment 
project,  he  will  tend  to  allocate  more  funds  to  the  project  if  he 
receives  feedback  indicating  that  the  project  is  failing  than  if  he 
receives  feedback  indicating  that  the  project  is  succeeding.   The 
feeling  of  personal  responsibility  for  the  project  apparently  induces 
decision-makers  to  remain  with  their  chosen  project  in  spite  of  evi- 
dence that  it  is  not  paying  off.   Staw  (1976)  found  a  much  weaker 
tendency  to  escalate  commitment  in  subjects  who  had  not  made  the 


-11- 

initial   commitir.ent  but  were  dealing  with  a  commitrQent  made  by  an 
earlier  decision-maker. 

Staw  &   Fox    (1979)   showed  that  when  decision-makers    face  a  series 
of  commitment  decisions  the  escalating  commitment  effect  is  strongest 
in  the  early  decisions  and  may  not  persist  over  time,  which  suggests 
that  decision-makers  may   decrease   their  assessment  of  the  probability 
of  recovering  losses  with   repeated  failure.      Thus,   decision-makers' 
perceptions  of  the  causes  of  failure  seem  to  be  important  determinants 
of  escalating  commitment.      Staw  &   Ross    (1978)   examined  the  effects  of 
information  indicating  either  exogenous  or  endogenous   causes  of  failure 
and  found  that  subjects   invested  more  resources   in  a  failing  project 
when  information  pointed  to  an  exogenous   rather  than  an  endogenous 
cavise  of  the  setback. 

Finally,   Fox  &   Staw   (1979)    found  that  escalating  commitment  was 
most  likely  to  occur  when  decision-makers  were  vulnerable  to  job  loss 
and  when  there  was  strong  organizational  resistance  to   the  chosen 
course  of  action.      An  excellent  review  of  these  studies  is   found  in 
Staw   (1981).      In  these  studies,   it  is  obvious  that   the  decision-makers 
perceive  the  discrepancy  indicating  a  project's   failure  since  they 
allocate  more  money   to  projects  which  appeared  to  be   failing.      However, 
they  did  not  use  this  perceived  discrepancy  to  alert  them  to  the  need 
to  change  their  strategy.      Rather,   they  seemed  to  interpret  the  nega- 
tive  feedback  as  a  signal  that   they  should  commit  more   funds   to  save 
the  project. 

Other  research   indicates  a  possible  hypothesis  which  decision-makers 
may  adopt   to  explain  a  perceived  discrepancy   in  such  a  way   that  it  appears 


-12- 

to  require  no  change  in  strategy.   They  may  explain  it  as  a  result  of 
chance  factors  rather  than  a  result  of  a  flaw  in  initial  strategy.   If 
they  adopt  this  interpretation,  they  are  likely  to  persist  in  the  cur- 
rent course  of  action  and  escalate  conmitment  to  it.   Staw  &  Ross  (1979) 
found  that  subjects  committed  significantly  more  funds  to  a  failing 
project  when  the  reason  for  the  failure  was  extrinsic  (a  chance  event 
which  could  not  have  been  foreseen)  than  when  the  reason  was  seen  to 
be  intrinsic. 

Illusion  of  Control 

It  may  be  that  decision-makers  tend  to  overestimate  the  role  of 
chance  in  their  failures.  This  speculation  is  supported  by  the  work 
of  Langer  and  Roth  (1975)  which  shows  that  decision-makers  tend  to 
attribute  unsuccessful  outcomes  to  chance  while  attributing  successful 
outcomes  to  their  own  skill. 

Lefcourt  (1973),  Langer  (1975)  and  Larwood  &  Whittaker  (1977) 
have  conducted  research  which  deals  with  decision-makers'  judgements 
about  the  role  of  chance  in  the  outcome  of  a  decision  and  have  defined 
a  bias  they  call  the  illusion  of  control.  Among  other  things,  the 
illusion  of  control  leads  decision-makers  to  attribute  desirable  out- 
comes to  internal  factors  (such  as  their  ovn  skill,  intelligence,  in- 
sight, etc.)  but  to  blame  such  external  factors  as  luck  for  failures. 
Decision-makers  who  note  gaps  between  performance  and  expectation  may 
tend  to  attribute  these  to  chance  if  the  gaps  tend  to  reflect  badly 
on  the  strategies  they  were  responsible  for  designing  earlier.   This 
would  cause  them  to  resist  changing  strategies  which  have  led  to  per- 
formance which  is  below  expectation,  strategies  which  are  failing. 


-13- 

Ihis  tendency  appears  to  be  stronger  in  individuals  who  have  expe- 
rienced a  string  of  successes  and  may  therefore  be  especially  strong 
in  upper- level  managers  involved  in  strategy  formulation.   Having 
risen  to  the  top  in  their  organizations,  they  would  tend  to  view 
themselves  as  successful  decision  makers  and  good  managers.   This 
would  increase  their  tendency  to  attribute  performance  gaps  to  chance 
rather  than  the  failure  of  their  strategies.   This  bias  also  has  a 
very  strong  effect  on  the  evaluation  of  alternatives,  as  will  be  dis- 
cussed in  the  section  on  alternatives  evaluation. 

Reasoning  by  Analogy 

Decision-makers  may  admit  that  the  gap  does  exist  and  that  it 
indicates  a  need  to  change  current  strategy.   If  this  happens,  there 
is  at  least  one  mechanism  which  helps  to  determine  the  manner  in  which 
the  problem  will  be  defined.  Steinbruner  (1974)  has  called  this  mech- 
anism reasoning  by  analogy.   Reasoning  by  analogy  involves  the  applica- 
tion of  analogies  and  images  from  one  problem  situation  to  another. 
In  strategic  decision-making,  it  typically  involves  the  application  of 
analogies  from  simpler  situations  to  complex  strategic  problems.   This 
mechanism  helps  to  reduce  the  aversive  uncertainty  perceived  in  the 
environment.   Reasoning  by  analogy  has  been  shown  to  be  effective  in 
generating  creative  solutions  to  problems  (Gordon,  1961;  Huff,  1980). 
However  in  strategic  decisions,  which  involve  a  great  deal  of  uncer- 
tainty and  complexity,  the  use  of  simple  analogies  is  likely  to  mis- 
lead the  decision-maker  into  an  overly  simplistic  view  of  the  situa- 
tion and  an  incorrect  definition  of  the  problem  (Steinbruner,  1974, 
p.  115).   - 


-14- 

A  major  problem  with  arguments    from  analogy   is    that   they  are  sub- 
ject  to  a  bias  which  Tversky   &  Kahneman   (1974)    call  availability.      Ac- 
cording to  Tversky  &  Kahneman,  decision-makers  assess   the  probability 
of  an  event  by  the  ease  with  which   instances  or  occurrences  can  be 
brought   to  mind.      In  any  strategic  decision  situation  there  are  poten- 
tially many  analogous  situations  which  may  occur  to  decision-makers. 
Which  analogy  will  decision-makers   choose?      It  may  be  that   they  will 
choose  the  analogy  which  most  readily  comes   to  mind.      Thus    for  example, 
the  analogy  chosen  may  be  influenced  by  a  decision-maker's   functional 
specialization.      Further,    recent  experiences  may  provide  the  most 
readily  available  analogies. 

Salience  and  Misguided  Parsimony 

If  decision-makers   do  not  use  simple  analogies   to  prematurely 
define  the  problem,  but   rather  attempt  to  locate  the  real  causes  of 
the  present  problem,   there  are  two  possible  biases  which  wovild  make 
it  less  likely  that   they  will  be  successful.      These  biases  are   dis- 
cussed by  Nisbett  &   Foss   (1980:115-130)   under  the  headings  of  salience 
and  misguided  parsimony.     According  to   these  authors,  highly  visible 
or  salient  events  or  variables  are  most  likely  to  be  taken  as  causes, 
leading  decision-makers   into  a  post  hoc,   ergo  propter  hoc   fallacy. 
The  availability  bias  will  cause  these  events   to  be  most  readily  re- 
called.     Citing  research  by  Pryor  and  Kriss    (1977),   and  Taylor  and 
Fiske   (1978),   they  argued  that  when  decision-makers  are  given  verbal 
information  about  events,   characteristics  of  the  message  can  deter- 
mine which  aspects  of  the  events  are  seen  as  causal   factors.     When 
decision-makers  observe  events  directly,  accidental   features  of  the 


-15- 

environment  or  their  own  position  in  it  can  be  important  in  deter- 
mining causal  interpretations. 

Regarding  misguided  parsimony,  Nisbett  &  Ross  suggest  that  decision- 
makers tend  to  believe  that  events  have  unitary  causes.   Because  of  this, 
they  may  fixate  on  the  first  plausible  cause  which  occurs  to  them  rather 
than  seeking  the  multiple  causes.  Essentially,  this  is  a  satisficing 
approach  to  determining  causality.  This  bias  may  have  been  identified 
first  by  John  Stewart  Mill  in  his  discussion  of  "the  prejudice  that  a 
phenomenon  cannot  have  more  than  one  cause"  (1843/1974,  p.  763). 
Nisbett  and  Ross  also  cite  a  statement  by  Kanouse  which  summarizes  the 
bias: 

individuals  may  be  primarily  motivated  to  seek  a 
single  sufficient  explanation  for  any  event,  rather 
than  one  that  is  the  best  of  all  possible  explana- 
tions.  That  is,  individuals  may  exert  more  cog- 
nitive effort  in  seeking  an  adequate  explanation 
when  none  has  yet  come  to  mind  than  they  do  in 
seeking  for  further  (and  possibly  better)  explana- 
tions when  an  adequate  one  is  already  available. 
This  bias  may  reflect  a  tendency  to  think  of  uni- 
tary events  and  actions  as  having  unitary  (rather 
than  multiple)  causes;  individuals  may  assume,  in 
effect,  that  no  more  than  one  sufficient  explana- 
tion is  likely  to  exist  for  a  single  phenomenon 
(Kanouse,  1972,  p.  131). 

Alternatives  Generation 

After  the  strategic  problem  has  been  defined,  the  next  stage  in 
the  normative  model  involves  the  generation  of  strategic  alternatives 
for  dealing  with  the  problem.  As  Alexander  (1979)  points  out,  alter- 
natives may  either  be  created  or  "found"  through  a  search  process. 
According  to  normative  theory,  a  large  scale  search  for  alternatives 
should  be  undertaken  at  this  point.   This  search  should  produce  a 


-16- 

large  number  of  alternatives  which  are  then  evaluated  in  order  to 
select  the  best.   However,  Cyert  &  March  (1963)  and  Lindblom  (1959) 
indicate  that  the  search  for  solutions  to  organizational  problems  does 
not  meet  these  demands.   Rather,  very  few  alternatives  are  evaluated 
in  any  depth.  Alexander  (1979)  found  support  for  this  assertion  in 
his  study  of  three  top-level  decisions.   He  concluded  "[the  three 
decisions']  most  salient  common  feature  is  the  rapid  convergence  of 
options,  both  in  number  and  in  range,  before  the  formal  evaluation 
process  ever  began"  (1979:  396).   In  some  cases  cognitive  biases  may 
lead  to  a  situation  in  which  there  is  no_  search  for  alternatives. 

Since  the  biases  discussed  in  this  section  tend  to  eliminate  the 
search  for  alternatives,  they  could  be  considered  biases  in  the  eval- 
uations stage.   However,  since  alternatives  generation  is  part  of 
most  normative  models,  these  biases  are  discussed  in  terms  of  their 
limiting  effects  on  alternatives  generation.   These  biases  include: 
single  outcome  calculations,  inferences  of  impossibility,  denying 
value  tradeoffs,  and  problem  sets  (see  Table  2). 

Single  Outcome  Calculation 

Steinbruner  (1974)  elaborates  on  Cyert  &  March's  notions  of 
problemistic  search  and  applies  it  to  individuals  as  well  as  organi- 
zations with  his  discussion  of  single  outcome  calculations  and  re- 
lated mechanisms  identified  in  behavioral  decision  theory  research. 
Rather  than  attempting  to  specify  all  relevant  values  and  goals  and 
all  alternative  courses  of  action  as  normative  decision  theory  would 
suggest,  decision-makers  may  focus  on  a  single  one  of  their  goals'or 
values  and  a  single  alternative  course  of  action  for  achieving  it. 


-17- 

Steinbruner  argues    that,   contrary   to  normative  models   of  organiza- 
tional decision-making,   uncertainty  is  not  resolved  in  most  instances 
by  probabilistic   calculations  of  the  outcomes   of  alternatives.      Rather, 
favorable  outcomes   are  inferred  for  preferred  alternatives  while  un- 
favorable outcomes  are  projected  for  non-preferred  alternatives.      Thus 
strategic  decision-making  involves  a  single-valued  problem  and  a. 
single-preferred  alternative  to  which  the  decision-maker  is  committed 
from  the  outset  of  the  decision  process    (1974,   pp.   122-123).      This   is 
an  extremely  powerful  simplification  bias  and  is   more  likely   to  be 
used  in  highly  complex  and  uncertain  decision  environments.      Since 
this   bias   allows   decision-makers   to  deny   the  unpleasant  value  trade- 
offs which  are  always  present  in  a  choice  between  alternatives    it 
significantly   reduces   the  stress  associated  with  ill-structured 
decision-making. 

Inferences  of  Impossibility 

Steinbruner  suggests  that   decision-makers   deal  with  non-preferred 
alternatives   through  inferences  of  impossibility.      In  contrast  to   the 
suggestions   from  normative  decision  theory,   Steinbruner  points  out 
that  decision-makers  may  devote  a  good  deal  of  effort   to   identifying 
the  negative  aspects  of  non-preferred  alternatives  and  attempting  to 
convince  themselves   that  they  are  not  possible  to   implement   (1974:119). 
Since  this   forces  premature  rejection  of  alternatives,   it  may  have 
disastrous   consequences   for  decision-makers  who  use  it.      They  will 
achieve  a  premature  closure  at   the  possible  cost  of  rejecting  the  most 
feasible  alternative. 


-18- 

Denying  Value  Tradeoffs 

In  addition,  as  both  Steinbruner  and  Jervis  point  out,  decision- 
makers over-value  their  favored  alternative  by  denying  value  tradeoffs 
(Jervis,  1976:128-136).   That  is,  they  attempt  to  interpret  facts  in 
such  a  way  that  the  favored  alternative  appears  to  serve  several  values 
simultaneously  and  appears  to  have  no  costs  associated  with  it.   They 
attempt  to  deny  that  there  are  tradeoffs  and  that  there  are  some  values 
which  may  not  be  served  by  their  favored  alternative. 

Problem  Sets 

Problem  set  is  another  decisioneil  bias  which  has  been  demonstrated 
in  laboratory  research  in  cognitive  psychology  (Anderson  &  Johnson, 
1966;  Newell  &  Simon,  1972).  Basically,  problem  set  is  demonstrated 
when  perceiving  an  object  serving  one  function  makes  it  more  difficult 
to  perceive  it  as  capable  of  serving  some  other  function  or  when  re- 
peated use  of  one  problem-solving  strategy  makes  it  more  difficult  to 
develop  other  strategies  (Anderson  &  Johnson,  1966,  p.  851).   Though 
this  bias  has  only  been  experimentally  demonstrated  using  relatively 
simple  and  discrete  problem-solving  tasks,  a  similar  process  may  be 
operating  when  strategic  decision-makers  become  strongly  committed  to 
a  set  of  assumptions  about  the  nature  of  their  business  and  appropriate 
solutions  to  its  problems.  Mason  &  MLtroff  (1981)  have  identified  this 
as  a  persistent  problem  in  corporate  strategy  formulation. 

Evaluation  and  Selection 

The  evaluation  of  strategic  alternatives  is  the  phase  of  the 
decision-making  process  in  which  the  limitations  of  Simon's  "Admin- 
istrative Man"  are  most  evident.   As  Simon  (1976)  points  out,  the 


-19- 

evaluation  and  selection  stage  of  administrative  decision-making  falls 
short  of  objective  rationality  in  at  least  three  ways. 

(1)  Rationality  requires  a  complete  knowledge  and 
anticipation  of  the  consequences  that  will  fol- 
low on  each  choice.   In  fact,  knowledge  of 
consequences  is  always  fragmentary. 

(2)  Since  these  consequences  lie  in  the  future, 
imagination  must  supply  the  lack  of  experienced 
feeling  in  attaching  value  to  them.  But  values 
can  be  only  imperfectly  anticipated. 

(3)  Rationality  requires  a  choice  among  all  possible 
alternative  behaviors.   In  actual  behavior,  only 

a  very  few  of  all  these  possible  alternatives  ever 
come  to  mind. 

(Simon,  1976:81) 

The  following  discussion  deals  with  biases  which  may  affect  the 
activities  of  evaluation  and  selection.   These  include:  representa- 
tiveness, the  illusion  of  control,  certainty  effects,  restriction  of 
evaluation  criteria,  focus  on  negative  criteria,  and  devaluation  of 
partially  described  alternatives. 

Representativeness 

Tversky  &  Hahnemann  (1974)  have  pointed  out  a  number  of  individual 
cognitive  biases  which  may  distort  judgements.   The  first  they  call 
the  representativeness  bias.   This  causes  a  decision-maker  to  over- 
estimate the  extent  to  which  a  situation  or  sample  is  representative 
of  the  situation  or  population  to  which  he  wishes  to  generalize.  This 
bias  may  be  responsible  for  the  fact  that  decision-makers  tend  to  view 
strategic  decisions  in  terms  of  simple  analogies.   It  also  causes  them 
to  overestimate  the  extent  to  which  the  past  is  representative  of  the 


-20- 

present  and  the  extent  to  which  solutions  offered  for  problems  in  the 
past  will  be  of  value  in  the  present  problem. 

Part  of  this  representativeness  bias  involves  insensitivity  to 
predictability.   In  making  predictions  of  the  effects  of  various 
courses  of  action  decision-makers  do  not  take  into  account  the  extent 
to  which  the  evidence  for  the  predictions  is  reliable,  or  the  extent 
to  which  the  criterion  is  related  to  the  cues  which  they  use  to  predict 
it  (Tversky  &  Kahnemann,  1974:1125), 

Decision-makers  are  also  insensitive  to  sample  size  in  making 
predictions.   Though  a  large  number  of  observations  are  necessary 
in  order  to  make  generalizations  to  a  population,  strategic  decision- 
makers are  often  unable  to  collect  data  on  a  large  number  of  past 
strategies  and  are  quite  willing  to  generalize  from  a  small  data 
base.  Further,  they  have  too  much  confidence  in  their  predictions 
from  small  amounts  of  data,  feeling  that  these  data  are  representative 
of  the  population  as  a  whole.  Tversky  &  Kahnemann  call  this  a  belief 
in  "law  of  small  numbers"  (Tversky  &  Kahnemann,  1974:1125).   Nisbett 
&  Ross  (1980:55-59)  have  suggested  that  decision-makers  are  especially 
susceptible  to  the  law  of  small  numbers  when  considering  one  or  a  few 
very  vividly  described  cases.   A  single  vivid  description  of  a  new  ven- 
ture's failure  in  a  particular  industry  may  influence  the  decision  about 
entering  the  industry  more  than  volumes  of  statistical  data  indicating 
high  success  rates  in  the  industry. 

Finally,  in  decision-making  tasks  which  involve  high  levels  of 
uncertainty,  decision-makers  should  be  aware  of  this  uncertainty  and  of 
their  inability  to  accurately  forecast  events  in  the  decision  environment. 


-21- 

Their  lack  of  ability  to  forecast  outcomes  should  make  them  wary  of  be- 
coming overcommltted  to  particular  courses  of  action  and  should  encourage 
them  to  develop  contingency  plans.   However,  decision-makers  tend  to  be 
overly  confident  in  their  ability  to  predict  outcomes  (Tversky  &  Kahnemann, 
1974:1129)  which  perpetuates  the  illusion  that  they  do  not  need  to  develop 
formal  contingency  plans.  Einhorn  &  Hogarth  (1978)  call  this  over- 
confidence  the  illusion  of  validity. 

Illusion  of  Control 

Langer's  illusion  of  control  may  also  affect  decision-makers' 
perceptions  of  the  need  for  contingency  plans.   They  will  overestimate 
the  extent  to  which  the  outcomes  of  a  strategy  are  under  their  personal 
control  and  may  assume  that  through  additional  effort  they  can  make 
their  strategy  succeed  should  problems  arise.   Langer  (1975)  conducted 
six  studies  which  showed  that  subjects  making  a  variety  of  decisions 
expressed  an  expectancy  of  personal  success  inappropriately  higher  than 
the  objective  probability  would  warrant.   They  tended  to  overestimate 
the  impact  of  their  skill  on  the  outcome  or  to  overestimate  their  skill. 
Larwood  &  I'Jhittaker  (1977)  comparing  management  students'  and  executives' 
performance  on  a  marketing  problem  found  further  evidence  for  the  illusion 
of  control.  The  management  students  tended  to  overestimate  their  abilities 
and  the  performance  of  the  hypothetical  firm  of  which  they  were  sales 
managers.  Managers  also  overestimated  performance  in  this  exercise  but 
showed  less  tendency  to  do  this  if  they  had  experienced  unsatisfactory 
results  in  earlier  planning  experiences. 


-22- 

Certainty  Effects 

Another  decisional  bias  which  may  be  related  to  the  desire  for 
control  over  the  environment  is  the  certainty  effect  (Kahnemann  & 
Tversky,  1979;  Tversky  &  Kahnemann,  1981).   Kahnemann  &  Tversky  sum- 
marize a  number  of  studies  which  show  that  people  exhibit  decisional 
biases  when  they  evaluate  outcomes  which  are  considered  certain  against 
to  outcomes  which  are  merely  probable.  When  given  a  choice  between  a 
certain  outcome  with  a  given  expected  value  and  a  probablistic  outcome 
with  a  slightly  higher  expected  value,  decision-makers  will  often  choose 
the  certain  outcome.   This  result  alone  might  simply  be  evidence  of  risk 
aversion.   However,  when  given  a  choice  between  a  certain  loss  of  a  small 
amount  and  the  probability  of  a  higher  expected  loss,  they  will  tend  to 
choose  the  probabilistic  loss.   As  Kahnemann  &  Tversky  point  out  (1979:269), 
these  results  are  incompatible  with  the  concept  of  risk  aversion  which 
holds  that  certainty  is  always  desirable.   Rather,  it  appears  that  cer- 
tainty increases  the  aversiveness  of  losses  as  well  as  the  desirability 
of  gains. 

These  results  may  be  explained  in  terms  of  the  desire  for  control 
over  the  environment  if  we  asstime  that  control  over  the  environment 
involves  the  ability  to  avoid  negative  outcomes.   People  will  choose 
certainty  when  faced  with  a  potential  gain  because  the  certain  outcome 
minimizes  the  possibility  of  a  zero  gain  which  is  aversive.   On  the 
other  hand,  when  people  are  faced  with  a  choice  of  alternatives,  one 
involving  a  potential  loss  and  one  involving  a  certain  loss,  they  will 
choose  the  alternative  which,  though  rasre  risky,  at  least  gives  them 
a  chance  of  avoiding  the  loss.   In  other  words,  they  are  risk  averse 


-23- 

with  respect  to  gains  and  risk  seeking  with  respect  to  losses.   It  is 
often  possible  to  formulate  a  problem  as  either  a  choice  between  los- 
ses or  a  choice  between  gains.   Thus,  these  authors  have  shown  that 
different  formulation  of  a  problem,  different  reference  points  against 
which  outcomes  are  evaluated,  may  result  in  different  choices. 

Criteria  Restriction  and  Negative  Forces 

Wright  (1974)  has  conducted  laboratory  research  which  reveals  two 
additional  biases  which  come  into  play  under  time  pressure  or  stress. 
Business  undergraduates  made  a  choice  among  a  number  of  car  models  based 
on  a  number  of  cues  with  time  pressure  and  distractions  varied.   The  re- 
sults support  the  claim  that  decision-makers  restrict  the  number  of  cues 
they  use  in  evaluating  the  quality  of  various  alternatives.  Further, 
they  tend  to  pay  most  attention  to  and  accentuate  negative  cues,  those 
which  provide  evidence  which  will  lead  to  the  rejection  of  alternatives. 
In  strategic  decision-making,  this  could  lead  to  the  rejection  of  alter- 
natives which  have  important  positive  features  but  which  have  perhaps 
one  negative  feature  (Wright,  1974:588-559). 

Devaluation  of  Partially  Described  Alternatives 

Finally,  Yates,  Jagacinski,  &  Faber  (1978)  demonstrated  a  pref- 
erence for  con^leteness  of  information  which  biases  decision-makers' 
evaluation  of  alternatives.  Among  a  group  of  strategic  alternatives, 
it  is  likely  that  the  probable  consequences  of  some  of  the  alterna- 
tives will  be  more  completely  described  than  others.  Yates,  et  al. 
fovmd  that  decision  makers  tend  to  devalue  the  alternative  that  is 
partially  described.   Since  partially  described  alternatives  involve 


-24- 

uncertainty  for  decision-makers,  they  tend  to  negatively  evaluate 
these  against  alternatives  which  are  better  described  and  therefore, 
resolve  more  uncertainties. 

CONJECTURES 
The  biases  discussed  in  the  preceeding  sections  form  the  basis 
for  some  conjectures  about  probable  errors  in  the  strategic  decision- 
making process.   These  conjectures,  which  are  numbered  below,  suggest 
the  specific  ways  in  which  strategic  decision-making  may  depart  from 
normative  prescriptions. 

Strategic  Problem  Identification: 

1)  Decision-makers  will  tend  to  perceive  fewer  gaps  than  their 
data  indicate  due  to  the  prior  hypothesis  and  adjustment  and  anchoring 
biases  (Levine,  1971;  Pruitt,  1961;  Wason,  1960;  Jervis ,  1976;  Tversky 
&  Kahnemann,  1974), 

2)  Decision-makers  will  minimize  the  significance  of  gaps  and  not 
use  the  gaps  as  a  basis  for  strategy  revision  due  to  the  escalating 
commitment  (Staw,  1976  &  1981;  Staw  &  Fox,  1977;  Staw  &  Ross,  1978; 
Fox  &  Staw,  1979). 

3)  Decision-makers  will  tend  to  attribute  unfavorable  gaps  to 
chance  due  to  the  illusion  of  control  (Langer,  1975;  Langer  &  Roth, 
1974;  Lefcourt,  1973;  Larwood  &  Whittaker,  1977). 

4)  If  the  significance  of  a  gap  is  recognized,  decision-makers 
will  tend  to  define  the  problem  causing  the  gap  through  an  analogy  to 
a  simpler  situation.   Recent  experience  is  most  likely  to  provide  the 
analogy  (Steinbrvmer,  1974;  Tversky  &  Kahnemann,  1974), 


-25- 

5)  Because  of   the  effects  of  salience  and  misguided  parsimony, 
decision-makers  who   do   seek  the  causes  of  a  strategic   problem  will 
tend  to   identify  a  single,  highly  visible  cause   (Nisbett  &  Ross,   1980; 
Pryor  &  Kriss,   1977;   Taylor  &  Fiske,   1978;   Kanouse,   1972;   Wilson  & 
Nisbett,   1978). 

Strategic  Alternatives  Generation 

6)  In  searching  for  a  solution  to  a  strategic  problem,   decision- 
makers will   tend  to   generate  a  single  alternative   rather  than  several 
alternatives   due  to  the  effects  of  the  bias  toward  single  outcome   cal- 
culation  (Steinbnmer,   19  74). 

7)  Decision-makers  will  tend  to  deal  with  non-preferred  alterna- 
tives by  denying  that   they  serve  any  values  better  than  the  preferred 
alternative  and  by  overestimating  the  difficulty  in  implementing  them. 
This   is  due  to   the  biases   toward  denying  value  tradeoffs  and  infer- 
ences of  impossibility   (Steinbruner,   1974), 

8)  Because  of  unchallenged  assumptions  and  problem  sets,  decision- 
makers who   attempt   to   generate  more  than  one  alternative  will   tend  to 
generate  very   few   (Anderson  &  Johnson,   1966;   Newell   &  Simon,   1972; 
Mason  &  Mitroff,   1981). 

Evaluation  and  Selection 

9)  Decision-makers  will  tend  to  over-estimate  the  accuracy  of 
their  predictions  of  the  consequences  of  alternatives  because  of  the 
representativeness  bias    (Tversky   &  Hahnemann,   1974;   Nisbett  &  Ross, 
1980). 


-26- 

10)  Decision-makers  will  tend  to  overestimate  the  importance  of 
their  own  actions   in  assuming  the  success  of  strategic  alternatives 
due  to   the  illusion  of  control    (Langer,   1975;   Langer   &  Roth,   1974; 
Lefcourt,   1973;   Larwood   &  I^ittaker,   1977). 

11)  Because  of  certainty  effects,   decision-makers  will  tend  to 
choose  more  certain  outcomes  when  attempting  to  maximize  gain  and 
riskier  alternatives  when  attempting  to  minimize  loss    (Kahnemann  & 
Tversky,   1979). 

12)  Decision-makers  will  exhibit  a  bias   toward  restricting  the 
number  of  evaluation  criteria  used  and  focusing  on  negative  evaluation 
criteria   (Wright,   1974). 

13)  Decision-makers  will  exhibit  a  preference   for  alternatives 
described  in  greater  detail,  even  though  partially  described  alterna- 
tives may  score  higher  on  the  decision-maker's   evaluation  criteria 
(Yates   et  al.,   1978). 

Though  most  of  these  biases  were   identified  in  research  on  indi- 
vidual decision-makers,   it   is  assumed  that   they  will   also  operate  in 
group  and  organizational  decisions.      This  assumption  is  by  no  means 
universally  held.      Indeed,   Nisbett  &  Ross    (1980,   pp.    249-254)   have 
suggested  that   collective  decision-making  may  be  a  way  of  reducing 
the  effects  of  some  cognitive  biases.      For  this   reason,  among  others, 
the  preceding  statements  about  the  effects  of  the  biases   are  stated  in 
the   form  of  conjectures. 

However,   there  is  some  support   for  the  assumption  that  these 
biases  may  actually  be  aggravated  by  group  and  organizational  processes 
which  serve  to   restrict  information  reaching  decision-makers. 


-27- 

Those  responsible   for  making  the  top-level  strategic   decisions 
may  not  be  those  who   collect   the  information  required   for  the  decision. 
Organizational  structures  and  processes  distort   the  information  reaching 
upper-level  decision-makers.      Crozier   (1963:51)    summed  up  the  problem 
in  the  following  way,    "Those  who  have  the  necessary  information  do  not 
have  the  power  to  decide,  and  those  who  have  the  power  to   decide  cannot 
get   the  necessary   information."     Information  passing  from  "experts"  to 
top  level  decision-makers   is   subject  to  hierarchical  distortion  in  both 
quantity  and  quality.      This  much   is  well-known  and  intuitively  plausible. 
However,   there  is   less   discussion  in  the  literature  about   the  direction 
this  bias  could  be  expected  to  take. 

First,   since  experts  may  act  as  mindguards,   protecting  decision- 
makers  from  potentially  threatening  information  (Janis,   1972;   Janis   & 
Mann,   1977)    information  threatening  to  top-level  decision-makers  or 
information  which   reflected  negatively  on  their  past  decisions  may  be 
distorted  or  omitted.      Second,   information  presented  by  experts   is 
often  presented  as   part  of  a  proposed  solution  to  a  problem  or  strategy. 
In  this  case,   information  might  be  distorted  in  favor  of  the  proposed 
solution. 

Carter   (1971)    documented  the  effects  of  the  use  of  experts   in 
strategy  formulation  when  he  attempted  to  apply  Cyert   &  March's    (1963) 
organizational   decision-making  framework  to  top  level   corporate  deci- 
sions.    He   examined  six  top  level  strategic  decisions  and   found  that 
these  decisions   differed  from  the  operational  decisions   described  by 
Cyert  and  March   in  two  ways.      First,   they  tended  to  involve  more  levels 
of  the  organization  and  second,   they  involved  people  of  more  vairying 


-28- 

backgrounds.      For  these  reasons,   proposals    for  solutions   to  top  level 
problems  were  often  presented  by  coalitions    to   top-level  corporate 
decision-makers   and  supported  by   staff  experts'    analysis. 

Carter  suggests   that  bias  will  be  added  to   the  appraisal  of 
proposed  problem  solution  by  technical  or   functional  staff  experts   to 
the  extent  that: 

a)  The  success   of  the  project  depends  on  the  top-level  decision- 
makers'   acceptance  of  the  staff's   representation  of  the 
relevant   issues   in  the  problem. 

b)  There  is   uncertainty  in  data  relevant   to   the  problem. 

c)  The  top-level  decision-makers  possess  much  less  knowledge  about 
the  problem  than  do   the  staff  people. 

d)  The  top-level   decision-makers   perceive  a  great   deal  of  un- 
certainty in  the  problem  and  a  need  for  the  expertise  of  the 
staff. 

All   four  of  these  conditions  are  likely  to  hold  in  strategic  decisions. 

Further,   Carter  suggests   that   the  amount  of  bias   added  to   data 
provided   for  the  evaluation  of  a   given  decision  and  the  amount  and 
type  of  data  provided  will  depend  on  the   following  factors: 

a)  UTiich   data  are  perceived  as  desired  by  higher  levels  of  manage- 
ment, 

b)  The  amount  of  data  necessary  to  gain  a  favorable  decision. 

c)  The  ease  of  developing  data. 

d)  The  extent   to  which   the  staff  people  or  their   departments  will 
be  held  accountable  for  the  consequences   of  decisions  which 
were  based  on   the  data. 


-29- 

The  actions  of  experts  or  mindguards  may  reinforce  biases  through 
the  restriction  of  information  necessary  to  adequately  fonmilate  the 
problem,  to  generate  feasible  alternatives,  and  to  evaluate  those  al- 
ternatives, 

CONCLUSIONS  AND  IMPLICATIONS 
In  this  paper,  research  on  selected  cognitive  biases  has  been 
summarized  and  conjectures  regarding  the  possible  effects  of  these 
biases  on  strategic  decision-making  have  been  developed.   In  this 
final  section  of  the  paper,  some  implications  for  research  and  prac- 
tice in  strategic  management  will  be  drawn. 

Fesearch  Implications 

Future  research  should  focus  on  documenting  the  presence  of  these 
biases  in  strategic  decision-making  and  assessing  their  effects. 

Uiere  are  those  who  argue  that  we  cannot  draw  inferences  about 
executives'  performance  at  real  world  decision-making  from  students 
and  laboratory  decision-making  tasks  (L\igson,  Braunstein,  &  Hall, 
1981).   They  hold  that  decision-making  abilities  required  to  rise  to 
a  position  of  strategic  responsibility  and  extensive  experience  with 
a  variety  of  complex  decisions  produce  generally  high-quality  decision- 
making performance  in  executives  which  is  relatively  free  from  bias. 
In  support  of  this  claim,  there  is  some  evidence  to  show  that  some 
groups  of  professional  decision-makers  such  as  weather  forecasters 
make  good  use  of  statistical  information  in  forecasting  do  not  exhibit 
a  high  degree  of  decisional  bias  (Hogarth,  1975,  pp.  277-278).   However, 
these  decision-makers  were  able  to  learn  from  their  mistakes  and  improve 


-30- 

their  performance  over  time  because  they  are  required  to  make  numerous 
predictions  based  on  clearly  identified  data  and  receive   continuous 
relatively  unambiguous   feedback  soon  after  they  make  their  predictions 
(Hogarth,   1975,   p.    278;   Nisbett  &  Koss,   1980,   p.    265).      It   could  be 
argued  that  none  of  these  conditions  hold  in  strategic  decision-making; 
that  such   decisions  occur  infrequently  and  Involve  ambiguous   data  and 
possibly  a  disagreement  about  which  data  are  relevant.      Further,   the 
feedback  about   the  success  of  the  strategy   is  often  ambiguous  since 
there  may  be  multiple  evaluation  criteria  applied  to  the  company's 
performance,   some  of  which  may  yield  contradictory  results  and  may 
not  be  available  for  years  after  the  implementation. 

These  considerations  make  the  existence  of  these  cognitive  biases 
in  organizational  decision-making  more  plausible.      Further  support   for 
their  existence  and  effects  comes  from  the  fact   that  several  of  these 
biases  have  been  found  to  operate  in  private  and  public  sector 
decision-makers    (Steinbruner,   19 74;    Staw,   1981;   Larwood  &  Whittaker, 
1977;   Einhom   &  Hogarth,   1981), 

At  this  point,    it  is   tempting  to  suggest  that   researchers  attempt 
to  identify  possible  examples  of  each  bias  in  the  literature  describing 
well-known  business  decision-making  failures.      Indeed,   books   such  as 
Hartley's  Marketing  Mistakes    (1976)    and  Smith.' s   Corporations   in  Crisis 
(1963)   offer  numeroios   potential  examples  of  some  of  these  biases.      How- 
ever,  there  is   a  consideration  which  suggests   that   such  examples  may 
be  of  little  value.      Since  most  of  the  biases  have  been  identified  in 
laboratory  settings  very  different   from  businesses,   their  existence 
in  strategic   decision-making  is  still  to  some  extent  a  matter  of 


-31- 

conjecture.  This  being  the  case,  effort  should  be  made  to  document 
the  existence  of  these  biases  in  managerial  decision-making  through 
more  detailed  data  including  interviews  with  managers  or  records  of 
meetings.  Records  of  business  decisions  such  as  those  found  in  the 
above-mentioned  books  merely  demonstrate  behavior  on  the  part  of  the 
managers  which  appears  consistent  with  the  biases  and  which  may  (or 
may  not  be)  the  result  of  these  biases.  These  reports  are  insuffi- 
cient, by  themselves,  to  demonstrate  the  biases'  existence. 

Future  research  on  these  potential  biases  should  take  two  direc- 
tions.  First,  since  many  have  been  examined  exclusively  in  laboratory 
research,  an  attempt  should  be  made  to  document  their  existence  and 
effects  in  field  settings.   Researchers  may  be  able  to  identify  the 
biases  in  executives'  detailed  descriptions  of  problem  solving  pro- 
cesses such  as  those  collected  by  Mintzberg,  et  al.  (1976),   Field 
observation  of  decision  processes  may  also  provide  insights  into  the 
effects  of  these  biases. 

A  second  approach  would  involve  further  laboratory  research  in- 
vestigating these  biases  in  laboratory  tasks  more  representative  of 
the  ill-structured  problems  encountered  in  strategic  decision-making. 
Such  concurrent  laboratory  and  field  research  has  been  advocated  in 
the  most  fruitful  approach  to  research  for  several  questions  In 
strategic  management  (Schwenk,  1982). 

Implications  for  Practice 

It  is  necessary  to  establish  that  these  biases  do  in  fact  exist 
in  strategic  decision-making  before  making  strong  recommendations  to 
managers  regarding  techniques  for  avoiding  them.   However,  practitioners 


-32- 

who  suspect  that  any  of  these  biases  may  be  adversely  affecting  their 
decisions  have  a  wide  variety  of  techniques  available  for  reducing 
their  effects.   Schwenk  and  Thomas  (1982)  have  summarized  research 
on  a  number  of  techniques  for  reducing  cognitive  biases,  three 
examples  of  which  will  be  discussed  here.   For  improving  the  collec- 
tion and  use  of  information  in  problem  identification  a  technique 
called  Strategic  Assumption  Analysis  has  been  recommended  (Emshoff  & 
Finnel,  1978;  Emshoff  &  Mitroff,  1978;  Mason,  1969;  Mason  &  Mitroff, 
1981;  Mitroff  &  Emshoff,  1979;  Mitroff,  Emshoff,  &  Kilmann,  1979). 
This  technique  involves  the  structured  presentation  and  analysis  of 
divergent  assumptions  about  data  relevant  to  a  problem. 

There  are  a  variety  of  creativity  stimulants  which  have  been 
proven  useful  In  stimulating  the  generation  of  alternative  solutions 
(Gordon,  1961;  Huff,  1980;  Stanford  Research  Institute,  1969;  Warfleld, 
1975),   The  focus  of  such  techniques  is  typically  the  suspension  of 
critical  processes  and  the  encouragement  of  unusual  associations. 
Finally,  for  improving  the  evaluation  of  alternatives,  the  use  of  the 
devil's  advocate  technique  has  been  proposed  (Cosier,  1978,  1980; 
Cosier  &  Aplin,  1980;  Cosier  &  Rose,  1977;  Cosier,  Ruble,  &  Aplin, 
1978;  Herbert  &  Estes,  1977;  Janls,  1972;  Jervls,  1976;  Schwenk  & 
Cosier,  1980),   This  technique  involves  the  development  of  critiques 
questioning  the  wisdom  of  a  preferred  alternative  and  the  challenging 
of  data  and  analysis  supporting  this  alternative. 

Schwenk  and  Thomas  point  out  that  dec is ion- makers  must  be  aware 
of  the  nature  of  the  strategic  decison-making  process  in  order  to 
make  effective  use  of  these  aids.   Since  the  process  is  iterative  and 


-33- 
cyclical,    techniques    designed   to   improve   performance  at  one  stage  may 
have  impacts   at   other  stages   as  well.      For  example,   decision-makers 
using  the  devil's   advocate  approach  to   improve   the  evaluation  of  alter- 
natives  may   find   that   its   use  leads   to   the   generation  of  new  alter- 
natives  and  identification  of  new  strategic   problems.      Of  course,    this 
can   greatly  increase  the  time  and  effort   involved   in  reaching  a  deci- 
sion.     Thus,    the  use  of  any  of  these  decision  aids  may   reduce  biases 
at  all   stages   of  the  strategic  decision-making  process   as  well   as    in- 
creasing decision   time.      Practitioners   should  be  aware  of   this    trade- 
off  relationship  in  making  use  of   them. 


-34- 


References 

Alexander,  E.  R.,  The   design  of  alternatives  in  organizational  contexts. 
A  pilot  study.   Administrative  Science  Quarterly.  1979,  24_,  382-404, 

Anderson,  B.  F.  &  W.  Johnson,  Two  kinds  of  set  in  problem  solving. 
Psychological  Reports.  1966,  19_,  851-858. 

Andrews,  K,,  The  Concept  of  Corporate  Strategy.   Revised  Edition, 
Homewood,  Illinois;  Irwin,  1980, 

Andrews,  K. ,  E.  Learned,  C.  R.  Christensen,  &  W.  Guth,  Business 
Policy;  Texts  and  Cases.   Homewood,  Illinois:   Irwin,  1965 

Ansoff,  H.  I.,  Corporate  Strategy.   New  York;  McGraw-Hill,  1965, 

Carter,  E.  E. ,  The  behavioral  theory  of  the  firm  and  top-level  corporate 
decisions.   Administrative  Science  Quarterly,  1971,  16,  418-428, 

Cosier,  R.  A. ,  The  effects  of  three  potential  aids  for  making  strategic 
decisions  on  prediction  accuracy.  Organizational  Behavior  and 
Human  Performance,  1978,  22^  295-306. 

Cosier,  R.  A.,  Inquiry  method,  goal  difficulty,  and  context  effects  on 
performance  and  satisfaction.  Decision  Sciences.  1980,  11,  1-16. 

Cosier,  R.  A.  &  J.  C.  Aplin,  The  application  of  dialectical  inquiry 

to  strategic  planning:  A  critical  view.   To  appear  in  Strategic 
Management,  1980,  1_,  343-356, 

Cosier,  R.  A,  &  G.  L.  Rose,  Cognitive  conflict  and  goal  conflict 

effects  on  task  performance.   Organizational  Behavior  and  Human 
Performance.  1977,  19,  378-391. 

Cosier,  R.  A.,  T.  L.  Ruble,  &  J.  C.  Aplin,  An  evaluation  of  the 

effectiveness  of  dialectical  inquiry  systems.  Management  Science, 
1978,  24^  1483-1490. 

Crozier,  M. ,  The  Bureaucratic  Phenomenon.   Chicago:   University  of  Chicago 
Press,  1964. 

Cyert,  R.  M.  &  J.  G.  March,  A  Behavioral  Theory  of  the  Firm.   Englewood 
Cliffs,  New  Jersey:  Prentice-Hall,  1963. 

Einhorn,  H.  J.  &  R.  M.  Hogarth,  Confidence  in  judgement:   Persistence 
of  the  illusion  of  validity.   Psychological  Review,  1978,  85, 
395-416. 

Emshoff,  J.  R.  &  A.  Finnel,  Defining  corporate  strategy:  A  case 
study  using  strategic  assumption  analysis.  Wharton  Applied 
Research  Center.  Working  paper.  No.  8-78,  October,  1978. 


-35- 


Emshoff,  J.  R.  &  I.  I.  Mitroff,  Improving  the  effectiveness  of 
corporate  planning.  Business  Horizons,  1978,  21,  49-60. 

Fox,  F.  V.  &  B.  M.  Staw,  The  trapped  administrator:   Effects  of  job 
insecurity  and  policy  resistance  upon  comm.itment  to  a  course  of 
action.  Administrative  Science  Quarterly,  1979,  24,  449-471. 

Glueck,  W.  F.,  Business  Policy:  Strategy  Formulation  and  Management 
Action.   New  York:  McGraw-Hill,  1976, 

Gordon,  W.  J.  J.,   Synectics.   New  York:  Harper  &  Row,  1961. 

Grant,  J.  &  W.  King,  Strategy  formulation:  Analytical  and  normative 
models .   In  Strategic  Management;   A  New  View  of  Business  Policy 
and  Planning,  pp.  104-122.   Edited  by  D.  Schendel  and  C.  Hofer. 
Boston:  Little,  Brown  and  Co.,  1979. 

Hartley,  R.  F. ,  Marketing  Mistakes.   Columbus,  Ohio:   Grind,  Inc.,  1976. 

Herbert,  T.  T.  &  R.  W.  Estes,  Improving  executive  decisions  by 

formalizing  dissent:  The  corporate  devil's  advocate.  Academy 
of  Management  Review,  1977,  _2,  662-667. 

Hofer,  C.  W.  &  D.  Schendel,  Strategy  Formulation:  Analytical  Concepts. 
St.  Paul,  Minnesota:  West,  1978. 

Hogarth,  R.  M. ,  Cognitive  processes  and  the  assessment  of  subjective 
probability  distributions.  Journal  of  the  American  Statistical 
Association.  1975,  70_,  271-289. 

Hogarth,  R.  M.,  Judgement  and  Choice:  The  Psychology  of  Decision. 
Chichester,  England:  Wiley,  1980. 

Hogarth,  R.  M.  &  S.  Makridakis ,  Forecasting  and  planning:  An 
evaluation.  Management  Science.  1981,  22,  115-138. 

Huff,  A.  S. ,  Evocative  metaphors.  Human  Systems  Management.  1980,  _1, 
1-10. 

Janis,  I.  L.,  Victims  of  Groupthink.  Boston,  Houghton-Mifflin,  1972. 

Janis,  I.  L.  &  L.  Mann,  Decision-Making:  A  Psychological  Analysis  of 

Conflict,  Choice,  and  Commitment.   New  York:  The  Free  Press,  1977. 

Jervis ,  R. ,  Perception  and  Misperception  in  International  Politics. 
Princeton,  New  Jersey:   Princeton  University  Press,  1976. 

Kahneman,  D.  &  A.  Tversky,  Prospect  theory:  An  analysis  of  decision 
under  risk.   Econometrica,  1979,  47,  263-291. 


-36- 


Kanouse,  D.  E.  Language,  labeling,  and  attribution.  In  E.  E.  Jones, 
et  al.  (Eds.).  Attribution;  Perceiving  the  Causes  of  Behavior. 
Morristown,  New  Jersey:   General  Learning  Press,  19  72, 

Lang,  J.  R.,  J.  E.  Dittrich,  &  S.  E.  I^ite,  Managerial  problem-solving 
models:   A  review  and  a  proposal.  Academy  of  >!anagement  Review, 
1978,  3,  354-865, 

Langer,  E.  J.,  The  illusion  of  control.   Journal  of  Personality  and 
Social  Psychology.  1975,  32^  311-328, 

Langer,  E,  J,  &  J,  Roth,  The  effect  of  sequence  of  outcomes  in  a  chance 
task  on  the  illusion  of  control.   Journal  of  Personality  and  Social 
Psychology.  1975,  32,  951-955, 

Larwood,  L.  &  W,  I-Zhittaker,  Managerial  myopia:   Self-serving  biases 

in  organizational  planning.   Journal  of  Applied  Psychology,  1977, 
67_,  194-198, 

Lefcourt,  H.  M,,  The  function  of  the  illusions  of  control  and  freedom, 
American  Psychologist.  1973,  28,  417-425, 

Leontiades,  M.,  Strategies  for  Diversification  and  Change,  Boston: 
Little,  Brown,  &  Co.,  1980, 

Levine,  M.,  Hypothesis  theory  and  nonleamlng  despite  ideal  S-R  re- 
inforcement contingencies.   Psychological  Review.  1971,  78, 
130-140. 

Llndblom,  C.  E.  ,  The  science  of  "muddling  through".   Public  Administra- 
tion Review,  Spring,  1959, 

March,  J.  G.  &  H.  A.  Simon,  Organizations.   New  York:  Wiley,  1958, 

Mason,  R,  0.,  A  dialectical  approach  to  strategic  planning.  Management 
Science.  1969,  15,  B403-B414, 

Mason,  R.  0,  &  I,  I,  Mitroff,  Challenging  Strategic  Planning  A-ssumptlons, 
New  York:  Wiley,  1981. 

Mazzollni,  R.,  How  strategic  decisions  are  made.  Long  Range  Planning, 
1981,  14,  85-96, 

Mill,  J.  S,  A  System  of  Logic  Ratioclnatlve  and  Inductive,  Toronto: 
University  of  Toronto  Press,  1974  (originally  published  in  1843). 

Mlntzberg,  H.,  Strategy-making  In  three  modes.  California  Manager:ent 
Review.  1973,  Winter,  44-53, 

Mlntzberg,  H.,  P.  Raisinghani,  &  A.  Theoret,  The  structure  of 

"unstructured"  decision  processes.  Administrative  Science 
Quarterly.  19  76,  21,  246-275. 


-37- 


Mltroff,    I.   I.    &  J.    R.    Emshoff,    On  strategic   assumption-making:      A 

dialectical  approach   to   policy  and  planning.      Academy  of  >fenagem-ent 
Review,    1979,   4_,    1-12. 

Mitroff,  I.  I.,  J.  R,  Emshoff,  &  R.  H.  Kilmann,  Assumptional  analysis: 
A  methodology  for  strategic  problem-solving.  Management  Science, 
1979,   25_,    583-593. 

Newell,   A.    &  H.   A.   Simon,   Human  Problem  Solving.      Englewood  Cliffs, 
New  Jersey:      Prentice-Hall,   19  72. 

Nisbett,  R.  &  L.  Ross,  Human  Inference.  Englewood  Cliffs,  New  Jersey: 
Prentice-Hall,   1980. 

Pruitt,   D.   G.,    Informational  requirements   in  making  decisions.      American 
Journal  of  Psychology.   1961,   74_,   433-439. 

Pryer,    J.   B.   &  M.   Kriss.      Cognitive  dynamics  of  salience  in  the  attribu- 
tion process.      Journal  of  Personality  and  Social   Psychology,   1977, 
35.,   49-55. 

Schwenk,   C.    R.      Why  sacrifice  rigor   for  relevance?     A  proposal   for 

combining  laboratory  and  field  research   in  strategic  management. 
Strategic  Management  Journal    (forthcoming). 

Schwenk,   C.    R.    &  R.   A.   Cosier,    Effects  of  the  expert,   devil's  advocate, 
and  dialectical   inquiry  methods  on  prediction  performance. 
Organizational  Behavior  and  Human  Performance,   1980,   26,   409-423, 

Schwenk,   C.    R.   and  H.   Thomas.      Fonnulating  the  mess:     The  role  of 

decision  analysis  and  other  decision  aids   in  problem  formulation. 
Unpublished  manuscript.   University  of  Illinois,   1982. 

Simon,  H.  A.,  Administrative  Behavior  (Third  Edition).  New  York:  The 
Free  Press,   1976. 

Simon,   H.  A. ,   The  New  Science  of  Management  Decision.      Englewood   Qiffs, 
New  Jersey:      Prentice-Hall,   1960. 

Smith,   R.   A.      Corporations   in  Crisis.      Garden  City,   New  York:      Doubleday, 
1963. 

Stanford  Research  Institute.      Structured  Approaches  to  Creativity. 
Menlo  Park,   California,   1969. 

Staw,   B.    M.,   Knee  deep  in  the  Big  Itaddy:      A  study  of  escalating  coo- 
mitment  to  a  chosen  course  of  action.      Organizational  Behavior 
and  Human  Performance,   1976,   16,   27-44. 

Staw,  B.  M.,  The  escalation  of  commitment   to  a  course  of  action. 
Academy  of  Management  Review,   1981,   6_,    577-587. 


-38- 


Staw,  B.  M.  &  F.  V.  Fox,  Escalation:   The  determinants  of  commitment 
to  a  course  of  action.   Human  Relations,  1977,  30,  431-450. 

Staw,  B.  M,  &  J.  Ross,  Commitment  to  a  policy  decision:  A  multi- 
theoretical  perspective.  Administrative  Science  Quarterly,  1978, 
23,  40-64. 

Steinbruner,  J.  D.,  The  Cybernetic  Theory  of  Decision.  Princeton, 
New  Jersey:   Princeton  University  Press,  1974. 

Steiner,  G.  A.  &  J.  B.  Miner,  Management  Policy  and  Strategy. 
New  York:  McMillan,  1977. 

Taylor,  R.  N.,  Psychological  determinants  of  bounded  rationality: 

Implications  for  decision-making.   Decision-Sciences ,  1975,  6_, 
409-429. 

Taylor,  S.  E.  &  S.  T.  Fiske.  Salience,  attention  and  attribution: 
Top  of  the  head  phenomena.  In  L.  Berkbwltz  (Ed.)  Advances  in 
Experimental  Social  Psychology.  New  York:  Academic  Press,  1978. 

Tversky,  A.  &  D.  Kahneman,  Judgement  under  uncertainty:  Heuristics 
and  Biases.   Science.  1974,  185.  1124-1131. 

Tversky,  A.  &  D.  Kahneman,  The  framing  of  decisions  and  the  psychology 
of  choice.   Science.  1981,  211.  453-458. 

Ungson,  G.  R.,  D.  N.  Braunstein,  &  P.  D.  Hall,  Managerial  information 
processing:  A  research  review.  Administrative  Science  Quarterly, 
1981,  26,  116-134. 

Warfleld,  J.  N.,  Methods  of  Idea  Management.   Academy  for  Contemporary 
Problems,  1975. 

Wason,  P.  C,  On  the  failure  to  eliminate  hypotheses  in  a  conceptual 

task.   Quarterly  Journal  Experimental  Psychology,  1960,  l^.,  129-140. 

Wilson,  T.  D.  &  R.  E.  Nisbett.  The  accuracy  of  verbal  reports  about 
the  effects  of  stimuli  on  evaluations  and  behavior.   Social 
Psychology,  1978,  4^,  118-131. 

Witte,  E, ,  Field  research  on  complex  decision-making  processes — The 

phase  theorem.   International  Studies  of  Management  and  Organization. 
1972,  59,  555-561. 

Wright,  P.,  The  harassed  decision  maker:  Time  pressures,  distractions, 
and  the  use  of  evidence.  Journal  of  Applied  Psychology.  1974,  59, 
555-561. 

Yates,  J.  R.,  Evaluation  of  partially  described  multiattribute  options. 
Organizational  Behavior  and  Human  Performance.  1978,  21,  240-251. 

M/C/265 


01 

-5 

u 

<u 

Q 


CO 
CO 

u 

w 

? 

§ 

M 
M 
U 
U 
O 


U 

H 
CO 


o 

CO 

1-3 

Q 


•H 


O  00 

N  <J\ 

Sd. 

CO  ^-^ 


3  ox 
r-}  H 


4-1 

(U 
4-1 

c 
s 


0) 

•a 

d 

(U 
o  ^-s 

CO  00 

r^ 

<^  ox 

.H 
H  ^-^ 
<U 
U-l 

o 

pa 


o 

CO 


(3) 


eg 


<*-i 


o 
u 


fl 
^ 


I 

a 
o 

•H 
CO 

•H 
O 
(U 

Q 


0) 

•a 


o 


ctt 
O 
•H 


T3     C 
0)    (U 

3  M 


03 


(U 

CO 

c 
o 

•H 
4J 

n3 

CJ 
•H 
«4-l 
•H 

4J 

<u 

T3 
1-1 


<u  a 

a  g 

a 
o 
ca   (u  }4 

H    4J   -H 

a.  (u  > 

D.'O    c 
q 


00 

o 
a 
<u 
u 

CO 


CO 


4J 

o 

a. 
a. 
o 


0) 

.5 

4J 

eg 
u 
n] 

i* 
o 
u 


^     CO 


>. 

CO 

G 

+J 

CO 

c 

CU 

CO 

e 

> 

o 

T3 

y 

CO 

CJ     CO 
Q  Q 


o 


CO 

u 


to 
u 

a 

(Si 

B 


to 

CO 


CO 
•H 
CO 

CO      (U    rH 


CO  M-l    C  -H    o    to 


OJ 


o 


CO    u 
>>    3 


CO     C    -H   iH     O 

^J     <U    >    to    to    O. 


4J  -a   c   fi   (ji  to 
'  W  <  PS  o 


ca 


CM 


CO   »J- 


CO 

> 

CJ   -H 
•H    4-) 

CO  to 

Q)  c: 

4J    n 

to  <u  <u 

!-i    W    fl 

CO   5 

CO 
0) 

> 

•H 
4J 

Id 


a 
o 

•H 

4J 

CO 
U 


(U 
CJ) 


(J 

4-1 
to     l4 

<u   o    _ 

en    VH    IH 


CS 


c 
o 

•H 

4-1 

o 

<: 

V4 

o 


<0 
CO 


PU 

0) 

•  •    Tj 

0)  -H 
CJ  CO 
•H    C 

2  o 
CJ  v_/  ca 


CO 

(U 

cj.^ 


00  CO 

(u  a 

4->  )4 

to  (U 

u  u 


0) 
CO 

to 

Xi 

4J 

c: 

0) 

E 
a 
o 
i-i 

(U 

> 

(U 
Q 


^ 

C3 

CJ 

00 

u 

•H 

to 

CO 

<u 

<U 

CO 

Q 

n  ,y 


m 

(U 

> 

CJ 

•H 

•H 

4J 

00 
CU 

s 

4-1 

U 

to 

<U 

u 

4J 

CO    ^ 


a 
o 


o 


rH  0) 

>    C    0) 
W    CO   CO 


O 


U  CO 

to  (U 

00  CO 

•H  H 

4J  3 

CO  O 


> 

o 
u 


c 
o 

•H 

4J 
..      -      CJ     _ 
(U   CJ   ■<  -H 
>  >  T3 

c  <+-!  u-i  a)  c 
-1  o  o  p4  a 


en 


M 
M 

(U 
CO 

to 

JZ  (U 

Pi  ^ 

4J   ^~« 

••  0)   00 

oj  CO   0) 

CJ  o  u 

•H  O    CO 

o  x:  1^ 

^  CJ    w 

CJ  v-'    CO 


5 


0) 

s 

0) 

rH 


C3 
O 
•H 
4-1 
CO 
4J 

c 


M 


m 


o 


CO 

4J 
C 

(U 


c 
o 


CO 
3 
i-l 


c 

o 

■H 

ti 

U 

<u 

o 

to 

M 

•H 

N 

CO 

4J 

•H 

x: 

a 

3 

M 

(U 

0) 

O 

0) 

T-l 

42 

c 

h 

CO 

4J 

o 

CJ 

> 

3 

•H 

CO 

W 

<: 

4-1 

CJ 

••s 

•-\ 

rf—N 

<U 

• 

• 

• 

rH 

m 

vO 

r* 

(U 

CO 

c: 

CO  u 

sg 

to    rH 

U    to 
CO   W 


>x 

00 

4J     O 

CO  -H 
V"    o 

*J  J= 

CO    CJ 


< 


H 
M 

> 


a 

M 


o 

M 
CO 
l-l 

u 

Q 


O 
H 


H 
CO 

O 

u 

u 


a: 


CO 
CO 

< 


O  4J 

•H  a 

4J  (1) 

0)  U-l 

0) 
CO 


M  T3 

M  C 

0) 

00  c 

CO  O 

W  T-l 

CO  4J 


rH  CO 

cd  CO 

>  -H 

H  PQ 


o  u 

•W  CJ 

4J  (1) 

CO  U-i 

U  <J-I 

<u  w 

c 

CO 

<u 

> 


u 

M     C 

M     U 

(U 

OOr-l 

to  < 
u 

CO     CJ 


00 
<u 

4-1 

CO    CO 
1.1    CO 

CO  m 


c 

O  i-t 

•H  a 

U  0) 

to  >*-i 

CJ  IM 

T-l  w 
<4H 


01 

•o 

M 

M 

0) 

s 

00 

(U 

to 

rH 

iJ 

J3 

CO 

O 

W 

PU 

00 

<u 
u 

to    en 

U    CO 

4J    -H 

CO  eq 


AJ  O 

to  -H 

3  CJ 

U  -H 

O  'O 

to  (U 

M  C^    O 


<u 

CJ 

c 
<u 

3 

cr 

(U 

CO 

c 
o 

CJ 


t-l                                       U  ' 

^   9i                           Q)  c  -a 

o  4-1             m             j3  o   uj 

rH                       Q)                •     e  -H      to 

(UAJtO  <4-i>  iU3iJ3 

4->  c             o  1-1        a  c:  CO 

to    OJ  iJ-i      .           4J           C  3 

00    CO     to     a)     0}  r-l 

^    ^        >-i   <u  to 

Q)    (J  > 

3  CU 


CO 


0  o 
m 

to      CO 

to   to   to 

"tO.HtOMiH"4-i;ja)t*^VJ 


a   to 

CJ 


1   a; 


4J     cO    4-1   '+-I     O*    T3 


1-icO^iCf^tOtOD.PiOO 


4J 


CM 


1 

to 

4-1 

1 

c 

CO 

to 

Q) 

to 

c 

CO 

<a 

(U 

c 
3* 

s 

a 

> 

•H 

K    4J  x^  ^^ 


o 


4-1    CO         m 
0)  -H    CO    <U    3 
to    > 
C  -H    O 

03 


&a  ^ 


^^ 


to 

Q) 

> 

to 

•H 

4J 

4J 

CJ 

CO 

•H 

g 

4J 

<U 

CO 

4J 

tS 

to 

S  fi 

4J      O 

3  tH 
O    4J 

to 

Q)  rH 
M)   O 

C  rH 
•H  to 
CO    O 


•a 

T3 

(U 

<U 

> 

Vl 

iH 

o 

(U 

s 

u 
u 

•H 

9i 

a. 

tu 

CJ 

4J 

c: 

o 

<u 

c 

•a 

•H 

CO 

^ 

o. 

CO 

oo 

I 

o 

^^ 
pa 
u 

O  CO 
•H  -H 
W     CO 

Pd   a» 


<4H 

o 

a 

O  iH 

•w  o 

CO  U 

3  4J 

rH  C 

ri  8 


CM 


<4-l  0) 

o  (U 

^  > 

Vj     O  4J 

3  -H  to 

4J    4J  C 

gU  )H 

«  (U 

<U   -ri  4J 

>l     fl)  rH 

ill     >-l  CO 


<w 

>» 

o 

4J 

•H 

CO 

rH 

(U 

•H 

o 

J3 

c 

•H 

01 

CO 

J-! 

to 

0) 

O 

VH 

o. 

•s 

•a 

M 


CO 


CO  U 

4J  0) 

>-l  <4H 

(U  >4-l 

U  01 


c 
o 

C  -H 
O    U 

•H    CO  • 

4J    3  CO 

O    rH  -H 

•H    Id  M 

H    >  0) 

4J     0)  4J 

OB  -H 

O;   MH  >H 

«    O  O 


e»i 


o 


0)  Id 

>  3 

4J  « 

0  >  . 

01  01  cd 

T-)  -H 

0  o  a> 

1  '<-■ 

d  0)  -H 

O  to  h 

3  3  O 


en 
m 

<4H 
14H 

o 

0) 

(d 

00  H 

(3 
•H    <U 

5>   =^ 
C    rH 

0)   cd 

Q  > 


CI 


"o) 

^ 

(4-1 

0) 

Cd 

s 

a 

_tn 

OD 

CO 

(0 

D. 

> 

tw 

to 

■H 

o 

J2 

4J 

M 

Cd 

0) 

o 

0) 

a. 

g 

•H 

<u 

O 

4J 

u 

6 

3 

Cd 

0) 

u 

c  • 

<U  CO 

to  0) 

-      0)  > 

C     3    ^1  -rl 

td 


o 


C   rH     C 


O  VI    0) 

•n  >H  O  4J 

0)    4J  O    rH 

pj    CO  cx  Id 


in 


vo 


to 

>»       • 

0)      • 

C   rH           <U 

>  T3 

B 

O    rH             > 

•H    0) 

o     • 

tH     Cd   "O   -H 

W    *J 

c 

lU   -H     Cd 

4J    -H     a>    4J 

Id   u 

o 

>    4J  iH 

rt  4-1  j3  g 

3    M   -H    C 

a  -H 

•H    cd    n 

VI    Vi 

la 

4J    3    0> 

rH      cd     Vl     Vl 

0)    4J 

3 

td    rH     4J 

<d   o.  u  01 

4-1   a 

o 

00    Cd   -rl 

>        to  u 

:^2 

o 

0)    >    VI 

0)    VH     OJ   rH 

p^ 

C    0)    o 

Q    O  13    cd 

a 

0> 
•— 1 

ca 

o 

4J 

Vl 

0> 

CU 

CO 

9 


• 

rH 

13    Id 

* 

c 

U 

0)    Vl 

13 

o 

O 

•H    4J 

1 

0) 

«k 

•H 

0) 

t4H    MH      ID 

Vl    m 

• 

N 

13 

1 

to 

Vl 

O  iH 

flj   D.'a 

0,1 

a. 

01 

Vl           0> 

•^ 

VI 

*J    0, 

T3   td 

J 

4J 

Cd 

•H 

4J 

1       0>            4-1 

o 

0)    B    U 

C   oo 

> 

CJ   -H 

o 

00  (M 

o 

CO   >        Id 

0) 

u 

to    0,    cd 

3 

•H 

§.s 

a 

•H 

B 

•HO       «  •rl 

Vl 

13 

3  13   •H 

» 

OJ 

<4H 

4J 

g    ^-'^-v     Vl 

4J 

0) 

to  -H    Vl      • 

(U   -o 

o 

o   6 

gs 

•  o 

c 

53  13* 

13  a 

g3 

o 

•H 

y  _  &  B 

U    0) 

Vl 

•H 

13 

0) 

E   T3     0)    O 

c 

<4H 

S   o  o 

C    N 

« 

<4H      D. 

u 

Qi    CO 

13 

0)    0> 

01     0,    -rl     Vl 

0) 

•H 

0)    0)    Vl  •rl 

a  -H 

o. 

•rl     CO 

4-1 

CO    0, 

•H 

4J    to 

rH     C    rH     O. 

4J 

0) 

4J 

rH  rH  O-  a 
OO^    CV  ^H 

13   rH 

a'* 

to 

•H    oa 

2-^ 

j3  -H  a.  o. 

td 

m 

B 

•H   -H 

4J 

u 

>    3 

4-1 

o  <*H    6   td 

Vl 

3 

0) 

B  O  d  > 
•H    Vl    B    a> 

^^ 

o 

■H   <4H 

4-1 

0)   td 

o 

4J      OJ 

Vl    0,   -rl     C 

4-1 

c3 

13 

c: 

CO     O 

CO 

M   (L> 

c 

to    Vl 

Ph    13     to    -rl 

CO 

■H 

to     O.  •rl     Vl 

rf'^ 

^-> 

•-N 

^\ 

•-s 

^^ 

CM 

tn 

(0 

60 

a 

to    C 

in 

4J 

vO 

r*. 

00 

cd 

•H 

0)    o 

•rl 

d 

•H 

13 

CJ   -H 

rH 

•H 

P3 

Vl  UH 

3    4J 

•rl 

4J    VI 

OO  4-1 

Id  o 

CO   -H 

>^  ^     >» 

C    O 

a  c 

4J 

Q)  d 

4J 

00  00  Cd  y 

13    >» 

0)   J= 

•rl      0) 

Vl 

Vl    0) 

C     O    rH     C 

01 

0)    B 

e  CJ 

'V)      5 

0) 

13    o 

rH 

O    D--H   rH   -H     0) 

o 

Si 

(D    ■< 

3 

CO     iJ 

CU 

C   -H 

O 

•rl     S 

C   td   Cd   o 

c 

rH    -H 

to  i 

3 

g  3 

Vl 

4J 

V*    o 

P-1   u 

§.§^S 

0) 

•H 

ml  CO 

-rro 

CJ    B 

rH 

a 

cd 

rH 

to    Vl 

•o  c 

^8 

^*^ 

"-^  rH 

o 

•-S  ^*\ 

0)     >»^-s^-s 

Cd 

g£ 

«3^     Cd 

to 

ja  M 

u 

td  ^ 

Di  ^  td  ^ 

CO 

CM 


CO 


in 


•iiftJi'ii'': '!,?■■(;';■ 


1,'^mi'i 


mmmm&^mm 


ECKMAN 

NDERV  INC. 

JUN  95         ,