Skip to main content

Full text of "A commentary on Mill's Logic Book I of names and propositions"

See other formats


uepary 


Naval  ;• :  ,    school 

monterey,  california  9394q 


NPS52-83-013 


NAVAL  POSTGRADUATE  SCHOOL 

Monterey,  California 


A 

COMMENTARY  ON 

MILL'S  LOGIC 

BOOK 

I 

OF 

NAMES  AND  1 

PROPOSITIONS 

Bruce  J.  MacLennan 

// 

October 

1983 

Approved  for  public  release;  distribution  unlimited 


Prepared  for: 
FedDocs 

D   208.14/2  Chief  of  Naval   Research 

NPS-52-83-013     Arlington,  VA     22217 


- 


NAVAL  POSTGRADUATE  SCHOOL 
Monterey,  California 

Rear  Admiral  J.  J.  Ekelund  D.  A.  Schrady 

Superintendent  Provost 


The  work  reported  herein  was  supported  in  part  by  the  Foundation 
Research  Program  of  the  Naval  Postgraduate  School  with  funds  provided  by 
the  Chief  of  Naval  Research. 

Reproduction  of  all  or  part  of  this  report  is  authorized. 
This  report  was  prepared  by: 


UNCLASSIFIED 


SECURITY   CLASSIFICATION   OF   THIS  PAGE  (When  Data  Entered) 


REPORT  DOCUMENTATION  PAGE 

READ  INSTRUCTIONS 
BEFORE  COMPLETING  FORM 

1.     REPORT   NUMBER 

NPS52-83-013 

2.  GOVT   ACCESSION  NO. 

3.     RECIPIENT'S  CATALOG  NUMBER 

4.     TITLE  (and  Subtltlm) 

A  Commentary  on  Mill's  Logic 

Book  I  -  Of  Names  and  Propositions 

5.     TYPE  OF  REPORT  *  PERIOO  COVEREO 

Technical    Report 

6.    PERFORMING  ORO.  REPORT  NUMBER 

7.     AUTHORfiJ 

Bruce  J.  MacLennan 

•  •     CONTRACT  ON  GRANT  NUMt€Rf»J 

9.     PERFORMING  ORGANIZATION   NAME  AND  ADDRESS 

Naval   Postgraduate  School 
Monterey,   CA     93943 

10.    PROGRAM  ELEMENT.  PROJECT.  TASK 
AREA  *  WORK  UNIT  NUMBERS 

61152N:    RR000-01-10 
N0001483WP30104 

11.     CONTROLLING  OFFICE   NAME   AND   ADDRESS 

Chief  of  Naval   Research 
Arlington,   VA     22217 

12.    REPORT  DATE 

October  1983 

•3.     NUMBER.  OF  P.»5ES 

64 

14.     MONITORING  AGENCY  NAME  ft    AODRESSf/f  dlllerent  from  Controlling  Olllca) 

IS.     SECURITY  CLASS,  (of  tnla  report) 

Unclassified 

15a.     DECLASSIFICATION/  DOWNGRADING 
SCHEDULE 

16.     DISTRIBUTION  STATEMENT  (of  thla  Report) 

Approved  for  public  release;   distribution  unlimited 

17.     DISTRIBUTION  STATEMENT  (of  the  abatract  entered  In  Block  20,  II  dltlerenl  /ram  Report) 

18.     SUPPLEMENTARY  NOTES 

19.     KEY  WORDS  (Continue  on  revetee  aide  If  nacaaaary  and  Identify  by  block  number) 

Mill's  Logic,  J.   S.   Mill,  epistemology,  philosophy  of  science,   scientific 
method,   logic,   propositions,  definitions,  universals,   intension,  extension, 
connotation,  denotation. 

20.     ABSTRACT  (Continue  on  raverae  aide  It  naceeaary  mnd  Identify  by  block  ^timber) 

Mill's  Logic  is  the  cornerstone  of  scientific  method;  yet,  aside  from 
Mill's  Methods  of  Induction,   its  contents  are  not  well    known.     This  report 
attempts  to  make  Book  I   of  Mill's  Logic  more  accessible  to  students  of 
science  and  the  philosophy  of  science.     Each  section  of  Mill's  work  is 
summarized.     Most  sections  also  include  comments  that  criticize  Mill's 
position,  or  relate  the  topic  to  more  recent  developments   in  the  philosophy 
of  science. 

2ZO 

mllrn 
70  2  ^ 

>.   Tl   's 

ic 

1  CD 


DD     1  JAN  73     1473  EDITION  OF    1  NOV  65  IS  OBSOLETE 

S/N  0102-  LF-0U-6601 


UNCLASSIFIED 


SECURITY  CLASSIFICATION  OF  THIS  PAGE  (Whan  Dmtm  Kntated) 


A  COMMENTARY  ON  MILL'S  LOGIC 

Book  I 
Of  Names  and  Propositions 

Bruce  J.  MacLennan 

CONTENTS 


Preface 


INTRODUCTION 


I.    OF  NAMES  AND  PROPOSITIONS 


1.   Of  the  Necessity  of  Commencing  with  an  Analysis  of  Language 


2.  Of  Names 6 

1.  Names  are  Names  of  Things      6 

2.  General  and  Singular  Names      6 

3.  Concrete  and  Abstract      8 

4.  Connotat  ve  and  Non-Connotative      9 

5.  Positive  and  Negative     13 

6.  Relative  and  Absolute     16 

3.  Of  the  Things  Denoted  by  Names 1? 


- 1 


1.  Necessity  of  an  enumeration  of  Nameable  Things     17 

2.  Feelings,  or  states  of  Consciousness     18 

3.  Feelings  must  be  distinguished  from  their  physical  antecedents     18 

4.  Perceptions     19 

5.  Volitions  and  Actions    20 

6.  Substance  and  Attribute    21 

7.  Body    21 

8.  Mind    22 

9.  Qualities    22 

10.  Relations    23 

11.  Resemblance    23 

12.  Quantity    24 

13.  Attributes  Concluded    25 

14.  Recapitulation    25 

4.    Of  Propositions       28 

1.  Nature  and  office  of  the  copula    28 

2.  Affirmative  and  Negative  Propositions     28 

3.  Simple  and  Complex    23 


-  li 


4.     Universal,  Particular,  and  Singular    30 

5.    Of  the  Import  of  Propositions 33 

1.  Is  Proposition  a  Relation  Between  Two  Ideas?    33 

2.  Is  a  Proposition  a  Relation  Between  the  Meanings  of  Two  Names?    33 

3.  Is  a  Proposition  an  Expression  of  Class  Membership?    34 

4.  What  it  Really  Is    35 

5.  What  it  Is  that  Propositions  Assert  or  Deny    36 

6.  Propositions  with  Abstract  Terms    39 

6.  Of  Propositions  Merely  Verbal 40 

1.  Essential  and  Accidental  Propositions    40 

2.  Essential  Propositions  are  Identical  Propositions    40 

3.  Individuals  Have  No  Essences    43 

4.  Real  Propositions,  How  Distinguished  from  Verbal    43 

5.  Two  Modes  of  Representing  the  Import  of  a  Real  Proposition    44 

7.  On  Classification  and  the  Predicables 45 

1.  Classification,  How  Connected  with  Naming    45 

2.  The  Predicables    46 

3.  Genus  and  Species    47 


-  Ill 


4.  Kinds  Have  a  Real  Existence  in  Nature    47 

5.  Differentia    49 

6.  Property    50 

7.  Accident    51 

B.   Of  Definition 52 

1.  A  Definition,  What    52 

2.  What  Names  can  be  Defined?    53 

3.  Complete  versus  Incomplete  Definitions     54 

4.  Complete  Definitions  versus  Descriptions    54 

5.  Real  Definitions  versus  Nominal  Definitions    55 

6.  Mathematical  Definitions    57 

7.  Definitions  Grounded  on  Knowledge  of  Corresponding  Things    58 

II.    REFERENCES       59 


-  IV 


Preface 
Preface 

Mill's  Logic  is  he  corne  :tone  of  scientific  method.  Yet,  except  for  Mill'  Methods  of 
Mduction,  its  contents  are  largely  unknown.  Although  Mill's  less  important  works  on 
sociological  and  political  topics  are  widely  reprinted,  it  is  often  difficult  to  find  a  copy 
of  his  Logic.  The  present  work  attempts  to  make  Mill's  magnum  opus  more  accessible 
to  students  of  science  and  the  philosophy  of  science. 

Mill's  Logic  presents  serious  difficulties  to  the  modern  reader.  The  work  is  long  and 
dwells  on  many  issues  whose  importance  has  declined.  Conversely,  there  have  been 
many  developments  in  the  philosophy  of  science  since  Mill's  time.  These,  of  course,  he 
can't  discuss.  Finally,  Mill's  Logic  makes  heavy  use  of  terms  which  are  no  longer 
current.   These  characteristics  all  decrease  its  accessibility  to  students. 

This  work  follows  the  same  outline  as  Mill's  Logic.  In  each  section  1  have  summar- 
ized Mill's  major  points.  Most  sections  also  include  comments  that  criticize  Mill's  posi- 
tion, or  relate  the  topic  to  more  recent  developments  in  the  philosophy  of  science. 

The  main  references  we  have  used  are  Mill's  Logic  (Mill,  1843),  Nagel's  editing  of 
Mill's  work  (Nagel,  1950),  and  Killick's  Student's  Handbook  to  Mill's  Logic  (Killick, 
1909).   The  latter  was  a  model  for  this  work. 

The  preparation  of  this  report  was  supported  in  part  by  the  Office  of  Naval  Research 
under  contract  number  N00014-B2-WR-20162. 


-1- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
INTRODUCTION 

Summary:  A  good  starting  place  for  a  definition  of  logic  is  Whately's  (1868):  Logic  is  the 
science  and  art  of  reasoning.  As  a  science  it  studies  the  mental  processes  that  must 
take  place  whenever  we  reason;  as  an  art  it  lays  down  rules,  based  on  this  analysis,  that 
must  be  followed  if  we  are  to  reason  correctly. 

Logic  is  concerned  with  inferences,  not  intuitive  truths.  By  the  latter  Mill  means 
our  direct  sensations,  whether  of  the  external  world  or  our  own  mental  states.  These 
intuitive  truths  are  beyond  doubt,  and  no  science  is  required  to  establish  their  truth. 
Further,  no  science  can  make  us  more  confident  of  them.  However,  we  must  be  careful 
not  to  mistake  very  rapid  inferences  for  these  intuitive  truths.  For  instance,  judging 
the  distance  to  something  we  see  is  a  very  rapid  inference  that  must  be  learned. 

Mill  states,  "The  province  of  logic  must  be  restricted  to  that  portion  of  our 
knowledge  which  consists  of  inferences  from  truths  previously  known,  whether  those 
antecedent  data  be  general  propositions  or  particular  observations  and  perceptions. 
Logic  is  not  the  science  of  belief,  but  the  science  of  proof  or  evidence.  Insofar  as  belief 
professes  to  be  founded  on  proof,  the  office  of  logic  is  to  supply  a  test  for  ascertaining 
whether  or  not  the  belief  is  well  grounded." 

Mill  explains  the  relation  of  logic  to  the  other  sciences  as  follows:  "Logic,  however, 
is  not  the  same  thing  with  knowledge,  though  the  field  of  logic  is  co-extensive  with  the 
field  of  knowledge.  Logic  is  the  common  judge  and  arbiter  of  all  particular  investiga- 
tions. It  does  not  undertake  to  find  evidence,  but  to  determine  whether  it  has  been 
found."   Thus  logic  is  the  science  of  science  itself. 

Comments:  Mill's  use  of  the  term  logic  is  much  wider  than  is  usual  now.  It  is  the  sci- 
ence of  inference,  which  includes  both  inference  from  generals  to  particulars,  or 
deduction,  and  inference  from  particulars  to  generals,  or  induction.  In  contemporary 
usage,  logic  is  taken  to  mean  deductive  logic,  and  usually  symbolic  logic  at  that.    A 


-2- 


INTRODUCTION 
better  term  for  what  Mill  calls  'logic'  would  be  'scientific  method'. 

Mill,  i.  the  traditic  n  of  the  sensationalistic  empiricists  (Locke,  Jerkeley,  and  Hume) 
takes  sensations  as  the  starting  point  for  knowledge.  This  is  also  the  position  of  the 
logical  empiricists  and  logical  positivists  (such  as  Mach  and  Schlick),  who  followed  Mill. 
This  view  commits  the  very  error  that  Mill  has  cautioned  us  against.  The  data  that  is 
directly  given  to  us  is  not  sensations,  but  perceptions,  i.e.,  organized  sensations.  That 
is,  the  basis  for  knowledge  is  not  classified  objects,  such  as  trees,  since  classification  is 
a  process  of  inference.  Nor  is  the  basis  unorganized  "patches  of  color."  Rather  we 
perceive  organized,  but  unclassified  entities.  It  is  only  by  a  later  process  of  analysis 
that  we  abstract  out  the  "patches  of  color"  that  the  sensationalists  say  are  the  basis  of 
knowledge.  We  must  start  our  analysis  with  perceptions  because  the  integration  of  sen- 
sations into  perceptions  is  an  automatic  process  performed  by  our  sensory  apparatus. 
Processes  not  under  our  control  are  not  the  proper  province  of  logic  (or  any  art). 


Mill's  Logic:   Of  Names  and  Propositions 
I.    OF  NAMES  AND  PROPOSITIONS 

1.   Of  the  Necessity  of  Commencing  with  an  Analysis  of  Language 

Summary:  Why  should  a  study  of  scientific  method  be  concerned  with  language? 
"Logic  is  a  portion  of  the  art  of  thinking;  language  is  evidently,  and  by  the  admission  of 
all  philosophers,  one  of  the  principal  instruments  or  helps  of  thought;  and  any  imper- 
fection in  the  instrument  or  in  the  mode  of  employing  it  is  confessedly  liable,  still  more 
than  in  almost  any  other  art,  to  confuse  and  impede  the  process  and  destroy  all  ground 
of  confidence  in  the  result."  An  even  more  fundamental  reason  for  studying  language  is 
that  we  need  this  study  to  examine  a  central  topic  in  logic,  the  import  of  propositions . 

This  is  a  central  topic  because  "Whatever  can  be  an  object  of  belief  or  even  of  disbe- 
lief must,  when  put  into  words,  assume  the  form  of  a  proposition."  That  is,  subjects  can 
be  conceived  but  not  believed;  only  propositions  can  be  believed  or  disbelieved.  A  pro- 
position is  "discourse  in  which  something  is  affirmed  or  denied  of  something."  A  pro- 
position has  three  parts: 

•  A  predicate,  which  is  a  name  indicating  what  is    ffirmed  or  denied; 

.     A  subject,  which  is  a  name  denoting  the  thing  which  the  predicate  is  affirmed  or 
denied  of; 

•  A  copula  (link),  which  is  the  sign  indicating  whether  there  is  affirmation  or  denial. 

Comments:  1  can  add  little  to  this  except  to  note  that  since  Mill's  time  the  study  of 
language  has  virtually  replaced  the  study  of  logic.  Hence,  in  the  following  sections  1  will 
often  emphasize  the  non-linguistic  aspects  of  the  subject. 

At  this  point  1  will  mention  that  it  is  a  common  fallacy  that  Aristotle's  analysis  of  the 
form  of  propositions  is  inadequate,  since  it  does  not  cover  all  cases.  First,  it  is  said 
that  it  excludes  relations,  such  as  less  than.  But,  if  we  consider  a  proposition  such  as 
'Two  is  less  than  three",  it  is  clear  that  this  fits  the  subject-copula-predicate  form:  'Two' 


Necessity  of  Analysis  of  Language 
is  the  subject,  'is'  is  the  copula  and  'less  than  three'  is  the  predicate.    Further  exam- 
ples will  ye  discussed  later. 


-5- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
2.   Of  Names 

1.    Names  are  Names  of  Things 

Summary:  Mill  begins  with  Hobbes'  definition  of  a  name:  "A  name  is  a  word  taken  at 
pleasure  to  serve  for  a  mark  which  may  raise  in  our  mind  a  thought  like  to  some 
thought  we  had  before,  and  which,  being  pronounced  to  others,  may  be  to  them  a  sign 
of  what  thought  the  speaker  had  or  had  not  before  in  his  mind."  Thus  names  serve 
both  to  identify  our  own  thoughts  and  to  communicate  our  thoughts  to  others. 

This  suggests  the  question,  "Are  words  the  names  of  things  or  of  our  ideas  of 
things?"  It  seems  most  proper  to  consider  names  to  be  the  names  of  things.  For 
example,  when  we  say  'The  sun  set'  we  intend  to  convey  something  about  the  sun  not 
our  idea  of  the  sun.  In  fact,  we  have  specific  linguistic  mechanisms  for  talking  about 
our  ideas,  as  when  we  say  'The  idea  of  the  sun  entered  my  mind.'  In  other  words,  pro- 
positions don't  just  inform  the  hearer  of  certain  conjunctions  of  ideas  in  our  mind;  they 
also  inform  the  hearer  about  what  we  believe  about  the  things  in  reality. 

Comments:  This  interpretation  is  necessary  if  science  is  to  be  of  any  value  to  us.  If  the 
propositions  of  science  are  to  be  valuable  to  technology,  and  life  in  general,  they  must 
be  propositions  about  the  world,  not  just  our  ideas  of  the  world. 

2.    General  and  Singular  Names 

Summary:  They  are  many  ways  that  words  can  be  categorized.  First  we  can  distin- 
guish: 

•  Predicable  (categorematic)  terms,  which  can  be  used  alone,  either  as  the  subject  or 
the  predicate  of  a  proposition. 

•  Non-pre  die  able  (syncategorematical)  terms,  which  can  only  form  the  parts  of  other 
names. 

Thus,  predicable  terms  name  things,  while  non-predicable  terms  do  not.    Prepositions 


Of  Names 
and  adverbs  are  examples  of  non-predicable  words. 

Comments;  This  is  mostly  a  syntactic  distinction.  For  example,  adverbs  and  adjecth  ss 
denote  concepts  just  as  much  as  nouns,  it  is  just  that  the  syntax  of  our  language 
prevents  us  from  using  them  as  subject  or  predicate.  Instead  of  'Heavy  is  a  burden, ' 
we  must  say  "Heavy  things  are  a  burden.'  There  is  no  essential  difference  in  the  propo- 
sitions expressed. 

Even  prepositions  and  conjunctions  have  a  conceptual  meaning;  it  is  syntactic  limi- 
tations that  always  require  them  to  be  used  with  other  words.  There  are  some  words 
that  serve  a  syntactic  function  only;  these  are  the  only  truly  non-predicable  words. 

Summary:  There  are  two  broad  classes  of  names:  individual  and  general.  An  individual 
name  "is  a  name  which  is  only  capable  of  being  truly  affirmed,  in  the  same  sense,  of 
one  thing."  For  example,  proper  names  are  individual  names.  Now,  it  would  not  be 
possible  to  give  everything,  real  or  imaginary  of  which  we  might  have  cause  to  think,  an 
individual  name.  Hence,  we  give  general  names  to  broad  classes  of  things  (such  as 
'stone')  and  indicate  the  individual  in  which  we  are  interested  by  phrases  such  as  'this 
stone'  or  'the  stone  on  the  table.' 

This  is  not  the  most  important  function  of  general  names,  however.  "It  is  by  their 
means  that  we  are  enabled  to  assert  general  propositions,  to  affirm  or  deny  any  predi- 
cate of  an  indefinite  number  of  things  at  once."  A  general  name  is  "a  name  which  is 
capable  of  being  truly  affirmed,  in  the  same  sense,  of  each  of  an  indefinite  number  of 
things." 

It  is  necessary  to  distinguish  general  names  from  collective  names.  Collec  ive 
names  are  really  individual  names  in  which  the  individual  named  is  a  composite  entity 
made  of  other  individuals.  For  example  'The  US  Navy'  is  a  collective  name  for  a  partic- 
ular collection  of  people;  it  is  predicable  of  this  collection  as  a  whole,  and  only  this  col- 
lection; it  is  not  predicable  of  the  individual  persons  in  this  collection.    On  the  other 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
hand,  'member  of  the  US  Navy'  is  a  general  name  that  is  predicable  of  each  individual 
in  this  collection  and  not  of  the  collection  as  a  whole. 

Comments:  General  names  are  the  most  important  class  of  names,  because  it  is  these 
names  that  denote  concepts  or  universals.  Scientific  knowledge  would  not  be  very 
applicable  if  its  principles  and  laws  were  only  applicable  to  the  individuals  for  which  the 
laws  and  principles  had  been  verified.  If  this  were  the  case,  scientific  laws  would  only 
summarize  the  result  of  yesterday's  experiments;  they  would  not  give  us  principles 
that  can  be  applied  tomorrow.  Hence,  scientific  principles  are  expressed  in  terms  of 
concepts  or  universals  that  subsume  an  indefinite  number  of  individuals. 

Certainly  one  of  the  major  values  of  general  names  (and  the  concepts  they  name)  is 
economy.  Just  as  it  is  impossible  to  have  an  individual  name  for  everything,  so  it  is 
impossible  to  have  an  unlimited  number  of  propositions  to  express  the  properties  of  an 
unlimited  number  of  things.  General  names  allow  us  to  put  in  finite  form  knowledge 
about  an  infinite  number  of  things. 

Finally,  note  the  important  distinction  between  general  and  collective  names; 
modern  symbolic  logic  has  essentially  obliterated  this  distinction  by  calling  them  both 
sets.  The  importance  of  general  names  is  that  they  are  applicable  to  an  indefinite  (i.e., 
infinite)  number  of  individuals.  Hence  propositions  involving  general  names  are  true 
universally.  This  is  not  the  case  for  collective  names.  I  may  make  a  true  statement 
about  the  present  members  of  the  Navy  which  will  be  invalidated  by  the  very  next 
recruit.  Hence  propositions  concerning  collections  (whether  finite  or  infinite)  do  not 
have  the  universality  of  propositions  concerning  concepts.  Therefore,  in  science  and 
logic  we  are  mostly  concerned  with  general  names  and  general  propositions. 

3.    Concrete  and  Abstract 

Summary:  Mill  makes  a  number  of  other  distinctions  in  names,  most  of  which  are 
based  on  traditional  scholastic  logic.    He  defines  a  concrete  name  as  a  name  which 


Of  Names 
stands  for  a  thing,  and  an  abstract  name  as  a  name  which  stands  for  an  attribute  of  a 
thing.  This  distinction  is  orthogonal  to  that  between  general  and  singular  names.  We 
can  have  singular  abstract  names,  such  as  'visibleness'  and  'squareness',  which  denote 
a  single  attribute.  We  can  also  have  general  abstract  names,  such  as  'redness',  which 
apply  to  a  number  of  different  shades  of  red.  Note  that  'whiteness'  is  an  abstract 
name,  the  name  of  an  attribute,  while  'white'  is  a  concrete  name,  the  name  of  all  white 
things. 

4.    Connotative  and  Non-Cbnnotative 

Summary:  Mill  next  introduces  what  he  claims  is  one  of  the  most  important  distinc- 
tions: the  difference  between  connotative  and  non-connotative  names.  "A  non- 
connotative  term  is  one  which  signifies  a  subject  or  an  attribute  only.  A  connotative 
term  is  one  which  denotes  a  subject  and  implies  an  attribute."  Thus  'London'  and 
'whiteness'  are  non-connotative  terms.  'White'  is  a  connotative  term  because  it 
denotes  all  white  things,  and  implies  or  connotes  (con  =  with,  notare  =  to  mark)  the 
attribute  whiteness,  which  all  these  things  possess. 

Consider  the  word  'man'.  This  term  denotes  Tom,  Dick,  Jane,  and  an  indefinite 
number  of  other  men,  whether  alive  now  or  not.  The  term  'man'  connotes  a  number  of 
attributes,  namely  "corporeity,  animal  life,  rationality,  and  a  certain  external  form 
which,  for  distinction,  we  call  the  human."  These  attributes  are  essential  to  our  calling 
a  thing  'man';  anything  which  lacks  even  one  of  these  attributes  would  not  be  called 
'man'.  But  it  is  not  always  easy  to  decide  the  connotation  of  a  term:  "In  some  cases  it 
is  not  easy  to  decide  precisely  how  much  a  particular  word  does  or  does  not  connote; 
that  is,  we  do  not  know  (the  case  not  having  arisen)  what  degree  of  difference  in  the 
object  would  occasion  of  difference  in  the  name." 

An  important  problem  for  philosophers  and  scientists  is  to  discover  the  proper  con- 
notation of  a  term,  which  is  essentially  the  process  of  definition.  Mill  claims  that  when 
a  term  in  common  use  is  defined,  the  connotation  should  be  chosen  in  such  a  way  that 

-9- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
it  alters  as  little  as  possible  the  denotation  of  the  term  and  contradicts  as  few  as  possi- 
ble of  the  propositions  received  as  true  about  the  things  denoted. 

Comments:  It  is  not  clear  what,  exactly.  Mill  means  by  connotation.  He  frequently  says 
that  the  connotation  of  a  term  comprises  those  attributes  whose  presence  causes  us  to 
apply  the  term  to  a  thing.  This  might  suggest  that  the  connotation  of  a  name  is  the 
same  as  its  definition,  but  Mill  later  (Chapter  5)  states,  "In  defining  a  name,  however,  it 
is  not  usual  to  specify  its  entire  connotation,  but  so  much  only  as  is  sufficient  to  mark 
out  the  objects  usually  denoted  by  it  from  all  other  known  objects." 

An  alternate  interpretation  is  that  the  connotation  of  a  name  is  all  of  the  attributes 
implied  by  the  name.  Thus  the  connotation  of  man  would  include  rationality,  animal- 
ity,  his  distinctive  shape,  the  ability  to  use  language,  an  opposable  thumb,  and  so  on, 
for  an  unlimited  number  of  attributes.  This  is  not  Mill*  view,  however,  since  in  Chapter 
7  he  states,  "Of  all  the  innumerable  properties  known  and  unknown  that  are  common 
to  the  class  man,  a  portion  only,  and  of  course  a  very  small  portion,  are  connoted  by  its 
name;  these  few,  however,  will  naturally  have  been  thus  distinguished  from  the  rest 
either  for  their  greater  obviousness,  or  for  their  greater  supposed  importance."  Also, 
he  later  distinguishes  propositions  that  unfold  the  connotation  of  a  term,  such  as  'Man 
is  an  animal',  from  those  which  express  an  "accidental"  fact,  such  as  'Man  is  mortal'. 

How  can  we  tell  whether  or  not  a  given  attribute  is  connoted  by  a  name?  In  Killick 
(1909)  we  find,  "The  best  mode  of  determining  whether  a  name  connotes  a  given  attri- 
bute is  to  ask,  Whether,  if  that  attribute  were  removed,  the  name  would  still  be  applied 
to  the  subjects?  Does  'man'  connote  mortality?  The  test  is,  should  we  apply  the  name 
'man'  to  beings  exactly  like  men  in  other  respects,  but  not  mortal?"  Although  Killick 
does  not  answer  the  question  in  this  particular  case,  presumably  he  would  answer 
"Yes."  On  the  other  hand,  if  we  ask  whether  we  should  apply  the  name  'man'  to  beings 
exactly  like  men  in  other  respects,  but  not  rational,  presumably  he  would  answer  "No." 
I  dare  say  that  in  common  usage  we  would  more  likely  apply  the  name  'man'  to  an  irra- 

-10- 


Of  Names 
tional  being  otherwise  like  man,  than  to  an  immortal  being  otherwise  like  man. 

What,  then,  is  th<  -oot  of  Mill's  notion  of  connotation?  It  appear  to  be  that  the  ion- 
notation  "of  a  general  term  or  concept  A  [is]  made  up  of  all  those  general  terms  or 
concepts  B  for  which  'All  As  are  B'  is  a  necessary  truth  ...."  ['extension  and  intension' 
in  Flew  (1979)].  The  presumption  is  that  marine ss  necessarily  implies  rationality,  but 
only  contingently  (accidently)  implies  mortality.  Thus  Mill's  notion  of  connotation 
seems  to  hinge  on  the  distinction  between  necessary  and  contingent  truth,  a  distinc- 
tion which,  later,  I  will  argue  is  fallacious1.  For  the  time  being  the  reader  will  be  closer 
to  the  truth  if  he  takes  the  connotation  of  a  name  to  be  all  of  the  attributes  that  are 
truthfully  predicable  of  everything  denoted  by  the  name.  Thus,  the  connotation  of  man 
includes  rationality,  animality,  an  opposable  thumb,  the  potential  ability  to  cook  food, 
the  ability  to  fly  to  the  moon,  etc.,  etc.  This  is  the  interpretation  of  connotation  that  I 
will  use  throughout  this  work. 

Mill's  discussion  of  the  connotation  of  proper  names  is  also  unsatisfactory.  Joseph 
(1906)  says  about  it,  "He  confounded  different  distinctions,  and  raised  a  controversy 
about  the  connotation  of  proper  names,  to  which  there  has  been  no  satisfactory  issue, 
because  he  never  clearly  realized  to  himself  what  he  meant  by  connotation  ..."  The 
basis  of  Mill's  belief  that  proper  names  have  no  connotation  is  presumably  the  idea  that 
proper  names  do  not  imply  anything  in  a  necessary  way;  everything  we  know  about 
them  is  contingent.  Thus  the  name  'Caesar'  does  not  imply  necessarily  that  Caesar  is  a 
man.  But  observe  that  if  we  do  not  know  the  name  'Caesar',  then  for  us  it  neither  con- 
notes nor  denotes.  However,  if  we  know  the  individual  to  whom  t  is  name  refers  then 
we  know  both  the  i  me's  denotation  and  part  of  its  connotation  ^in  the  wider  seise  of 
connotation  suggested  above).  The  same  of  course  applies  to  general  names.  Hence, 
with  this  wider  notion  of  connotation  one  can  see  that  a  proper  name  has,  in  fact,  a 
very  rich  connotation,   since  an  individual  has   "more"   attributes  than  any  general 


1.    The  fallacy  of  the  necessary /contingent  dichotomy  is  discussed  in  PeikofT  (1979),  Quine  (1953)  and  Hempel 
(1954). 


-11- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
class.    (These  issues  are  discussed  at  some  length  in  Joseph  (1906),  Chapter  6.) 

Mill  identifies  a  very  important  point:  the  denotation  and  connotation  are  both 
essential  parts  of  a  (connotative)  term.  There  is  a  tendency  to  first  define  a  term  by 
identifying  certain  attributes  as  the  connotation  of  the  term,  and  then  to  replace  the 
term  by  its  definition.  This  ignores  the  fact  that  a  definition  is  wrong  if  it  substantially 
alters  the  denotation  of  the  term  (or,  at  very  least,  it  is  the  definition  of  some  other 
term).   Such  "denotation  shifting"  is  in  fact  a  logical  fallacy. 

It  can  be  argued  that  sometimes  a  definition  must  change  the  denotations  of  a  term. 
For  example,  traditionally  a  whale  might  have  been  considered  a  fish  because  of  its 
external  form  and  its  aquatic  habitat.  A  better  understanding  of  animal  life  later 
forced  us  to  remove  whales  from  the  denotation  of  'fish'.  This  is  of  course  correct:  we 
have  altered  the  denotation  of  'fish'  on  the  basis  of  new  evidence.  More  accurately,  we 
have  divided  fish  into  true-fish  and  aquatic  mammals.  When  we  define  these  terms,  we 
must  preserve  the  denotation  of  each.  If  a  definition  were  to  substantially  alter  the 
denotation  of  a  term,  then  a  new  term  would  be  called  for. 

We  can  take  Shannon's  Information  Theory  as  an  example  of  this  fallacy.  It  is  widely 
recognized  among  scientists  that  Information  Theory  has  little  to  do  with  information 
in  the  colloquial  sense,  and  that  Shannon's  measure  of  information  does  not  measure 
informative ness  (e.g.,  a  book  of  random  numbers  has  the  most  information).  To  one 
who  recognizes  the  limitations  of  formal  Information  Theory,  this  theory  can  be  a 
powerful  tool.  Nevertheless,  there  have  been  many  misapplications  of  Information 
Theory  resulting  from  an  identification  of  Shannon's  information  with  the  usual  infor- 
mation. Indeed,  books  mistakingly  making  this  identification  are  still  common  in  the 
popular  press. 

The  reader  is  also  likely  to  encounter  the  terms  intension  and  extension,  which  are 
often  used  as  synonyms  for  connotation  and  denotation,  although  some  writers  make 
slight  distinctions.   We  will  adhere  to  Mill's  terminology  in  this  work. 


■12- 


Of  Names 
5.    Positive  and  Negative 

Summary:  Names  can  also  be  divided  into  positive  and  negative.  Examples  of  positive 
names  include  man,  tree,  and  good;  examples  of  negative  names  include  not-man,  not- 
tree,  and  not-good.  The  distinction  between  positive  and  negative  names  is  not  a  dis- 
tinction of  form  (such  as  the  possession  of  a  negative  prefix  like  not-  or  un-),  but  a  dis- 
tinction of  meaning.  For  example,  the  word  inconvenient ,  though  negative  in  form,  is 
positive  in  meaning,  since  it  expresses  a  positive  attribute,  the  presence  of  some  cause 
of  discomfort  or  annoyance.  Similarly,  the  word  innocent,  although  positive  in  form,  is 
negative  in  meaning,  since  it  expresses  a  negative  attribute,  the  absence  of  an  illegal  or 
unethical  act. 

Comments:  The  distinction  between  positive  and  negative  names  is  crucial;  unfor- 
tunately Mill's  treatment  of  it  is  completely  inadequate.  In  particular  he  barely  treats 
the  question  of  what  makes  a  name  positive  or  negative. 

Since  the  distinction  between  positive  and  negative  terms  is  one  of  meaning  rather 
than  form,  it  has  largely  been  lost  from  modern  formal  logic.  We  will  see  later  that  this 
notion  is  crucial  to  the  understanding  of  inductive  proof. 

In  attempting  to  understand  the  difference  between  positive  and  negative  names,  we 
can  begin  with  Aristotle,  who  said  in  On  Interpretation  (ii.  16a30-33):  "The  expression 
'not-man'  is  not  a  noun.  There  is  indeed  no  recognized  term  by  which  we  may  denote 
such  an  expression,  for  it  is  not  a  sentence  or  a  denial.  Let  it  then  be  called  an 
indefinite  noun,  since  it  refers  to  all  kinds  of  things,  non-existent  as  well  as  existent." 

Whately  (1868)  also  calls  a  negative  term  indefinite  "in  respect  of  its  not  defining 
and  marking  out  an  object,  in  contradistinction  to  this,  a  positive  term  is  called 
Definite  ...  because  it  does  thus  define  or  mark  out."  In  other  words,  definite  terms 
mark  out  or  limit  our  view  to  one  particular  class  of  things,  or  one  thing,  while 
indefinite  terms  exclude  such  a  class  or  individual,  leaving  undetermined  the  individu- 


-13- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
als  of  which  we  speak. 

Several  logicians  have  noted  that  these  purely  negative  terms  have  a  limited  value. 
De  Morgan  (1847)  says,  "There  can  be  little  effective  meaning,  and  no  use,  in  a 
classification  which,  because  they  are  not  men,  includes  in  one  word  not-man,  a  planet 
and  a  pin,  a  rock  and  a  featherbed,  bodies  and  ideas,  wishes  and  things  wished  for." 
Given  the  questionable  value  of  negative  terms,  the  reader  might  wonder  why  1  dwell  on 
them.  The  reason  is  that  they  are  very  common  in  modern  symbolic  logic,  which  con- 
siders not-man  to  be  a  predicate  of  essentially  the  same  kind  as  man. 

Joseph  (1906)  explains  both  the  reason  for  negative  terms  and  the  fallacy  in  their 
use.  "Such  negative  terms  as  these  do  not  really  figure  in  our  thought;  they  are  'mere 
figments  of  logic';  Aristotle  long  ago  pointed  out  that  [not-man]  was  not  properly  a 
name  at  all  ...."  These  negative  terms  result  from  an  "attempt  to  reduce  negative  and 
affirmative  judgements  to  a  common  affirmative  type,  by  throwing  the  negative  into 
the  predicate  ...."  This  "is  not  really  defensible  for  the  negative  term  [not-man]  does 
not  signify  the  nature  of  anything,  and  so  is  not  really  a  term;  it  should,  if  it  were  a  gen- 
eral term  covering  everything  except  the  corresponding  positive,  be  predicable  of  all 
subjects  except  [men]  in  the  same  sense;  but  there  is  no  common  character  in  all  of 
these  which  it  is  intended  to  signify  ....  [I]t  is  clear  that  we  have  not  resolved  the  nega- 
tive into  the  affirmative  form,  when  such  affirmation  can  only  be  understood  by  res- 
toration to  the  negative." 

The  indefinite  character  of  negative  terms  has  led  logicians  to  distinguish  between 
contradictory  and  contrary  terms  (see,  for  example,  De  Morgan  (1847),  Joseph  (1906), 
Whately  (1868),  Jevons  (1919),  and  Creighton  (1906)).  Contradictory  terms  such  as 
man  and  not-man  divide  the  universe  into  two  mutually  exclusive,  exhaustive  classes; 
everything  is  either  man  or  not-man.  Contrary  terms  divide  some  class  within  the 
universe  into  mutually  exclusive,  exhaustive  subclasses.  For  example,  even-number 
and  odaWatmber  are  contrary  terms;  some  things  are  neither  even  numbers  nor  odd 


■14- 


Of  Names 
numbers,  for  example,  Eucalyptus  trees. 

Contrary  terms  can  also  be  characterized  as  positive  or  negative.  Consider  the 
terms  guilty  and  innocent;  these  are  contraries  rather  than  contradictories,  since 
there  are  things,  such  as  numbers,  that  are  neither  guilty  nor  innocent.  How  can  we 
distinguish  positive  and  negative  terms? 

Positive  terms  are  characterized  by  the  presence  of  certain  common  attributes  or 
qualities  possessed  by  the  things  denoted  by  the  term.  Negative  terms  can  only  be 
characterized  by  the  absence  of  such  common  attributes  and  qualities.  For  example, 
the  positive  term  man  is  characterized  by  the  conjunction  of  properties  such  as 
animality,  rationality,  and  human  form.  Couldn't  we  similarly  say  that  the  negative 
term  not-man  is  characterized  by  the  disjunction  of  properties  such  as  non-animality, 
non-rationality,  and  non-hurnan  form?  Yes,  but  notice  that  we  have  characterized  the 
positive  term  man  in  terms  of  other  positive  terms,  and  the  negative  term  not-man  in 
terms  of  other  negative  terms.  We  will  always  find  it  to  be  the  case  that  positives  can 
be  defined  by  positives,  but  that  a  negative  requires  at  least  one  negative  in  its 
definition. 

This  seems  to  result  in  an  infinite  regression;  to  avoid  it  we  must  know  by  some 
other  means  (other  than  definition  in  terms  of  positives  or  negatives)  whether  a  term  is 
positive  or  negative.  In  fact  we  can  know  this,  since  any  term  which  is  defined  osten- 
sively  (by  pointing)  is  by  its  nature  positive.  For  example,  to  define  the  term  blue  we 
can  pcint  out  a  number  of  blue  things.  The  hearer  can  then  abstract  out  the  common 
qualities  of  these  things  and  understand  what  we  mean  by  blue.  It  is  not  possible  to 
communicate  the  term  not-blue  by  pointing  to  things  that  aren't  blue,  because  there 
are  no  common  characteristics  that  the  listener  could  abstract. 

One  can  define  a  positive  term  by  pointing  to  things  that  have  some  quality;  one 
can't  define  a  negative  term  by  pointing  to  things  that  don't  have  a  quality.  Thus  the 
distinction  between  positive  and  negative  terms  ultimately  rests  on  the  presence  or 


■15- 


Mill's  Logic:   Of  Names  and  Propositions 
absence  of  definite  sensory  and  perceptual  qualities. 

6.    Relative  and  Mtsolute 

Summary:  The  fifth  leading  division  of  names  is  into  relative  and  absolute  (i.e.,  non- 
relative).  Examples  of  relative  names  are  'father',  'son',  'longer',  'shorter',  and  'equal'. 
Their  characteristic  property  is  that  they  are  always  given  in  pairs  (e.g.  'father',  'son'), 
although  in  some  cases  [reflexive  relations]  the  two  elements  of  the  pair  are  the  same 
(e.g.,  'equal',  'equal').  "Every  relative  name  which  is  predicated  of  an  object,  supposes 
another  object  (or  objects),  of  which  we  may  predicate  either  that  same  name  or 
another  relative  name  which  is  said  to  be  the  correlative  [or  converse]  of  the  former." 

The  major  reason  for  dwelling  on  relative  names  is  that  they  provide  insight  into  the 
nature  of  all  attributes.  "It  is  obvious,  in  fact,  that  if  we  take  any  two  correlative 
names,  father  and  son  for  instance,  though  the  objects  denoted  by  the  names  are 
different,  they  both,  in  a  certain  sense,  connote  the  same  thing.  They  don't  connote 
the  same  attribute,  but  rather  the  same  set  of  facts  which  we  mean  when  we  say  A  is 
the  father  of  B  and  B  is  the  son  of  A."  "In  this  manner  any  fact,  or  series  of  facts,  in 
which  two  different  objects  are  implicated,  and  which  is  therefore  predicable  of  both  of 
them,  may  be  either  considered  as  constituting  an  attribute  of  the  one,  or  an  attribute 
of  the  other.  This  set  of  facts  is  what  the  schoolmen  called  the  fundamentum  rela- 
tionis,  or  foundation  of  the  relation." 


■16- 


Of  the  Things  Denoted  by  Names 
3.   Of  the  Things  Denoted  by  Names 

1.   Necessity  of  an  enumeration  of  Name  able  Things 

Summary:  Mill  has  discussed  proofs,  the  constituents  of  proofs,  which  are  propositions," 
and  the  constituents  of  propositions,  which  are  names  -  "If,  therefore,  we  knew  what  all 
names  signify,  we  should  know  everything  which,  in  the  existing  state  of  human 
knowledge,  is  capable  either  of  being  made  a  subject  of  affirmation  or  denial  or  of 
being  itself  either  affirmed  or  denied  of  a  subject."  Thus  we  will  attempt  "an  enumera- 
tion of  all  kinds  of  things  which  are  capable  of  being  made  predicates  or  of  having  any 
thing  predicated  of  them  ..." 

Aristotle  was  the  first  to  attempt  an  enumeration  of  "all  things  capable  of  being 
named;  an  enumeration  by  the  summa  genera,  i.e.,  the  most  extensive  classes  into 
which  things  could  be  distributed  ..."  These  highest  predicates  were  called  the 
categories.   Table  1  is  Aristotle's  list  of  categories. 

TABLE  1.  Aristotle's  Categories 


Substance 

[e.g 

,  man  or  horse] 

Quantity 

[e.g 

,  one  foot  long] 

Quality 

[e.g 

,  blue] 

Relation 

[e.g 

,  double] 

Action 

[e.g 

,  to  cut] 

Passion 

[e.g 

,  to  be  cut] 

Place 

[e.g 

,  in  the  market-place] 

Time 

[e.g 

,  yesterday] 

Position 

[e.g 

,  sitting] 

State 

[e.g 

,  armed] 

Mill  says  that  this  list  of  categories  is  unphilosophical,  superficial,  redundant  and 
defective.  That  is,  m.ny  of  the  distinctions  are  merely  verbal,  several  of  the  categories 
overlap,  and  some  things  (such  as  states  of  consciousness)  do  not  fall  under  any  of  the 
categories. 

Comments:  In  Aristotle's  defense  it  should  be  noted  that  he  acknowledged  that  the 
categories  overlap,  and  never  claimed  that  the  list  was  exhaustive.  Also,  Greek  philoso- 
phy, like  many  modern  philosophies,  often  confused  linguistic  distinctions  with  logical 


•17- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
distinctions.    Finally,  as  I  will  discuss  later,  the  notion  of  a  summum  genus  is  itself  fal- 
lacious. 

2.  Feelings,  or  states  of  Consciousness 

Summary:  Mill  uses  feeling  in  a  philosophical  sense,  i.e.,  to  mean  any  state  of  cons- 
ciousness. "Feeling,  in  the  proper  sense  of  the  term,  is  a  genus,  of  which  sensation, 
emotion,  and  thought,  are  subordinate  species."  Mill  cautions  us  to  carefully  distin- 
guish objects  from  our  ideas  of  them.  "Even  imaginary  objects  (which  are  said  to  exist 
only  in  our  ideas)  are  to  be  distinguished  from  our  ideas  of  them." 

Similarly,  sensations  (which  are  mental  experiences)  are  distinguished  from  the 
objects  which  produce  them  and  from  the  attributes  of  these  objects  which  cause  them 
to  excite  these  sensations.  Thus,  the  sensation  of  white  must  be  carefully  distinguished 
from  the  objects  which  produce  this  sensation,  which  we  call  white,  and  from  the  qual- 
ity, which  we  call  -whiteness,  that  causes  these  objects  to  produce  this  sensation. 

3.  Feelings  must  be  distinguished  from  their  physical  antecedents 

Summary:  Another  distinction  that  must  be  carefully  maintained  is  that  "between  ths 
sensation  itself  and  the  state  of  the  bodily  organs  which  precedes  the  sensation  and 
which  constitutes  the  physical  agency  by  which  it  is  produced." 

Comments:  These  distinctions  -  between  sensations  and  the  objects  that  product  them, 
and  between  sensations  and  their  physical  antecedents  -  are  often  ignored  by  contem- 
porary philosophers.  The  important  point  is  that  sensations  are  primary;  it  is  these 
that  we  have  a  direct  awareness  of,  not  objects  or  nerve  impulses.  Before  we  can  be 
aware  that  there  even  are  nerves,  we  must  be  able  to  see,  so  that  we  can  look  through  a 
microscope  or  watch  an  oscilloscope  screen. 

To  reiterate,  epistemologically  sensations  are  primary:  experience  of  them  is  prior 
to  our  experience  of  objects  or  nerve  impulses.  Causally  (or  ontologically)  objects  and 
nerve  impulses  may  be  prior  to  sensations,  but  that  is  a  question  for  science  to  decide. 

-18- 


Of  the  Things  Denoted  by  Names 
To  accomplish  this,  scientists  will  make  use  of  the  sensations  they  experience. 

4.   Perceptions 

Summary:  Mill  comments  on  the  notion  of  a  perception  as  an  intermediate  link 
between  the  stimulation  of  our  sense  organs  and  the  resulting  sensation  in  our  minds. 
He  says  that  a  perception  "consists  in  the  recognition  of  an  external  object  as  the 
exciting  cause  of  the  sensation."  This  notion  is  dismissed  by  Mill:  "When  a  stone  lies 
before  me,  I  am  conscious  of  certain  sensations  which  1  receive  from  it;  but  if  1  say  that 
these  sensations  come  to  me  from  an  external  object  which  I  perceive,  the  meaning  of 
these  words  is  that,  receiving  the  sensations,  1  intuitively  believe  that  an  external  cause 
of  those  sensations  exists."  Mill  then  says  that  the  "laws  of  intuition  and  the  conditions 
under  which  it  is  legitimate"  fall  within  the  field  of  psychology  rather  than  logic. 

Comments:  The  notion  of  &  perception  is,  in  fact,  central  to  logic,  for  it  is  perceptions, 
not  sensations,  that  form  the  raw  data  of  observations.  Thus,  contrary  to  the  posi- 
tivists,  we  do  not  see  patches  of  isolated  colors.  Rather,  we  see  organized  groups  of 
sensations  that  are  automatically  integrated  by  our  visual  mechanism.  It  is  by  a  pro- 
cess of  abstraction  that  we  can  come  to  think  of  sensations  (such  as  the  color  red)  in 
isolation  from  the  perceptions  incorporating  them.  The  above  statements  are  vali- 
dated by  experiments  that  each  reader  must  perform  individually  in  the  laboratory  of 
his  own  mind.  That  perceptions  are  primaries  renders  invalid  any  alternate  attempt  at 
their  validation  (say,  by  studying  nerve  impulses). 

In  the  previous  paragraph,  we  have  used  perception  to  refer  to  an  automatically 
integrated  system  of  sensations.  There  is  no  reference  in  this  definition  to  the 
existence  of  external  causes.  Mill  is  correct  when  he  says  that  a  perception  does  not 
give  us  immediate  knowledge  of  an  external  object  —  we  are  all  familiar  with  the 
phenomenon  of  hallucinations.  In  a  wider  sense,  however,  every  perception  is  the 
result  of  an  external  condition:  the  relationship  between  our  perceptual  system 
(comprising,  so  far  as  we  know,  the  brain  and  the  sense  organs)  and  the  rest  of  the 

-19- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
external  world.    It  is  one  of  the  tasks  of  science  to  sort  out  those  characteristics  of  per- 
ception that  are  caused  by  our  perceptual  system  (which  is  part  of  the  external  world) 
from  those  characteristics  which  are  caused  by  the  objects  of  our  observation. 

Our  perceptual  system  is  the  instrument  through  which  we  observe  reality.  Like  any 
instrument,  it  has  a  definite  identity  and,  hence,  definite  limitations.  We  do  not  con- 
sider measurement  impossible  because  our  instruments  have  limitations.  Likewise, 
the  impossibility  of  knowledge  is  not  implied  by  the  existence  of  limitations  in  our  per- 
ceptual system. 

In  summary,  every  perception  has  a  cause  in  the  external  world.  That  cause  is  a 
complex  of  the  observer  and  the  observed.  We  will  see  later  that  a  major  task  of  sci- 
ence is  to  attribute  characteristics  of  a  perception  to  one  or  the  other  of  these  two 
external  objects. 

5.    Volitions  and  Actions 

Summary:  Mill  observes:  "When  we  speak  of  sentient  beings  by  relative  names,  a  large 
portion  of  the  connotation  of  the  name  usually  consists  of  the  actions  of  those  beings; 
actions  past,  present,  and  possible  or  probable  future."  What  is  an  action?  It  is  "not 
one  thing,  but  a  series  of  two  things:  the  state  of  mind  called  a  volition,  followed  by  an 
effect."  For  example,  when  I  form  the  volition  to  move  my  arm,  it  moves,  unless  it  is 
paralyzed  or  restrained. 

Comments:  Mill  alludes  to,  but  does  not  identify,  the  fact  that  a  volition  is  an  irreduci- 
ble primary,  just  like  a  perception.  That  is,  we  do  not  see  any  "substeps"  in  an  act  of 
perception.  That  is,  we  do  not  see  any  "substeps"  in  an  act  of  perception;  it  is  literally 
immediate  (no  mediate  steps).  This  epistemo logical  primacy  of  perceptions  does  not 
contradict  any  causal  primacy  that  might  be  identified  by  studying  physiology. 

Similarly,  a  volition  is  immediate;  I  observe  no  steps  between  my  volition  to  move 
my  arm  and  the  motion  of  my  arm.    There  is  of  course  nothing  mystical  or  superna- 


-20- 


Of  the  Things  Denoted  by  Names 
tural  about  the  irreducibility  of  a  volition;  it  is  an  epistemological  irreducibility,  not  a 
causal  (or  onLjlogical)  irreducibility.    Epistemological  irreducibility  uoes  not  contrad- 
ict any  explanation  by  science  of  volition  in  terms  of  nerve  impulses  or  other  physical 
phenomena. 

Thus,  we  can  call  a  perception  an  afferent  primary  and  a  volition  an  efferent  pri- 
mary. 

6.  Substance  and  Attribute 

Summary:  Having  dealt  with  feelings  (sensations,  thoughts,  emotions,  and  volitions), 
Mill  proceeds  to  the  two  remaining  classes  of  namable  things,  substances  and  attri- 
butes. Previous  logicians,  Mill  observes,  have  usually  drawn  this  distinction  on  the 
basis  of  a  word's  grammatical  function  (e.g.,  noun  or  adjective)  rather  than  on  the 
basis  of  distinctions  among  the  things  the  words  name.  In  answer  to  the  classical  ques- 
tion, whether  substances  can  exist  without  attributes,  or  attributes  without  substance, 
Mill  says,  "we  can  no  more  imagine  a  substance  without  attributes  than  we  can  imagine 
attributes  without  a  substance."  "Whiteness,  without  any  white  thing,  is  a  contradiction 
in  terms." 

7.  Body 

Summary:  Mill  defines  a  body  as  "the  external  cause  to  which  we  ascribe  our  sensa- 
tions." Are  we  justified  in  ascribing  our  sensations  to  an  external  cause?  Certainly  "a 
part  of  our  notion  of  a  body  consists  of  the  notion  of  a  number  of  sensations  of  our  own, 
or  of  other  sentient  beings,  habitually  occurring  simultaneously."  Is  there  any  reason 
to  presume  a  substratum  underlying  these  recurring  groups  of  sensations?  After 
reviewing  the  theories  of  Locke,  Hartley,  Hamilton,  and  Berkeley,  Mill  concludes  that 
"of  the  outward  world,  we  know  and  can  know  absolutely  nothing  except  the  sensations 
which  we  experience  from  it." 

Comments:   There  are  many  hypotheses  that  can  explain  our  sensations:   external 

-21- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
reality,  hallucinations,  perceptual  errors,  etc.   In  most  cases  the  simplest  hypothesis  is 
that  external  reality  is  the   cause   of  our  sensations.    Why  we   choose   the   simplest 
hypothesis,  and  how  we  judge  simplicity,  are  topics  we  take  up  in  Book  III,  Of  Induc- 
tion. 

8.  Mind 

Summary:  Mill  says  that,  just  "as  our  conception  of  a  body  is  that  of  an  unknown  excit- 
ing cause  of  sensations,  so  our  conception  of  a  mind  is  that  of  an  unknown  recipient  or 
percipient  of  them;  and  not  of  them  alone,  but  of  all  our  other  feelings."  "As  bodies 
manifest  themselves  to  me  only  through  the  sensations  of  which  I  regard  them  as  the 
causes,  so  the  thinking  principle,  or  mind,  in  my  own  nature  makes  itself  known  to  me 
only  by  the  feelings  of  which  it  is  conscious." 

Comments:  Recall  (Section  3)  that  perceptions,  not  raw  sense  data,  are  primary,  and 
that  perceptions  are  automatically  integrated  sensations  (both  external  and  internal). 
It  seems  that  our  notion  of  self  is  a  perception  automatically  integrated  from  internal 
sensations  of  our  own  mental  processes.  Thus,  our  notion  of  'self  is  an  epistemological 
primary.  (See  Nozick  (1981),  Chapter  1,  for  a  good  discussion  of  borderline  cases  in 
the  notion  of  'self'.) 

9.  Qualities 

Summary:  Mill  turns  from  substances  to  attributes,  which  he  says  are  of  three  kinds; 
qualities,  quantities  and  relations.  He  says  that  "if  we  know  not  and  cannot  know  any- 
thing of  bodies  but  the  sensations  which  they  excite  in  us  or  in  others,  those  sensations 
must  be  all  that  we  can,  at  bottom,  mean  by  their  attributes   ..." 

Mill  asks  what  it  is  that  we  mean  when  we  ascribe  a  quality,  such  as  whiteness,  to 
some  object,  such  as  snow.  Do  we  mean  only  that  when  snow  is  presented  our  sense 
organs  a  certain  sensation  (that  we  call  white)  is  experienced?  Or  do  we  mean  that  the 
object  possess  some  inherent  "potency,"  the  attribute  whiteness,  which  produces  in  us 

-22- 


Of  the  Things  Denoted  by  Names 
that  sensation?  In  short,  is  there  any  difference  between  a  quality  and  a  sensation? 

Although  Mill  says  that  this  distinction  is  not  important  to  logic,  he  does  claim  that, 
"when  we  say  that  snow  is  white  because  it  has  the  quality  of  whiteness,  we  are  only  re- 
asserting in  more  technical  language  the  fact  that  it  excites  in  us  the  sensation  of 
white.  If  it  be  said  that  the  sensation  must  have  some  cause,  I  answer,  its  cause  is  the 
presence  of  the  assemblage  of  phenomena  which  is  termed  the  object."  Mill  says  that 
there  is  no  point  in  interpolating  a  "potency"  between  the  object  and  the  sensation. 

10.  Relations 

Summary:  "The  qualities  of  a  body,  we  have  said,  are  the  attributes  grounded  on  the 
sensations  which  the  presence  of  that  particular  body  to  our  organs  excites  in  our 
minds.  But  when  we  ascribe  to  any  object  the  kind  of  attribute  called  a  Relation,  the 
foundation  of  the  attribute  must  be  something  in  which  other  objects  are  concerned 
besides  itself  and  the  percipient."  Two  things  can  be  said  to  be  related  when  "there 
exists  or  occurs,  or  has  existed  or  occurred,  or  may  be  expected  to  exist  or  occur, 
some  fact  or  phenomenon,  into  which  the  two  things  ...  both  enter  as  parties  con- 
cerned. This  fact,  or  phenomenon,  is  what  the  Aristotelian  logicians  called  the  fun- 
damentum  relationis.  " 

Relations  can  be  based  on  complicated  series  of  facts  (as  are  legal  relations),  or  can 
be  based  on  very  simple  facts.  An  example  of  the  latter  is  our  experience  of  two  events 
as  either  simultaneous  or  successive.  Mill  claims  that  these  latter  relations  are  per- 
ceptual primaries  that  canno    be  analyzed  further. 

11.  Resemblance 

Summary:  Mill  claims  that  two  other  sorts  of  relations,  likeness  and  unlikeness,  are 
also  primaries.  "Resemblance  is  evidently  a  feeling,  or  state  of  the  consciousness  of 
the  observer."  These  relations  are  not  capable  of  [epistemological]  analysis  because 
they  are  presupposed  in  every  analysis     "Likeness  and  unlikeness,  therefore,  as  well  as 


-23- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
antecedence,  sequence,  and  simultaneousness,  must  stand  apart  among  relations,  as 
things  sui  generis.  "  Certainly,  however,  complex  cases  of  likeness  and  unlike ness  can 
be  resolved  into  simpler  ones.  "All  likeness  or  unlikeness  of  which  we  have  any  cog- 
nizance resolve  themselves  into  likeness  and  unlikeness  between  states  of  our  own,  or 
some  other,  mind." 

Comments:  A  fundamental  requirement  of  good  science  is  to  recognize  epistemological 
primaries.  To  attempt  to  analyze  a  primary  is  an  error,  specifically,  a  category  error. 
This  is  because  it  is  an  error  to  attempt  to  base  an  epistemological  primary  upon 
something  that  is  not  a  primary. 

12.    Quantity 

Summary:  Mill  asks  us  to  consider  two  comparisons:  the  first,  between  a  gallon  of  water 
and  ten  gallons  of  water;  the  second,  between  a  gallon  of  water  and  a  gallon  of  wine.  In 
the  first  case  we  say  that  they  different  in  quantity,  in  the  second  in  quality.  Both  of 
these  assertions  are  grounded  on  differences  in  the  sensations  they  excite.  But  what  is 
the  distinction  between  a  quantitative  difference  and  a  qualitative  difference?  Mill 
says,  "This  likeness  and  unlikeness  1  do  not  pretend  to  explain,  no  more  than  any  other 
kind  of  likeness  or  unlikeness." 

Comments:  Certainly,  at  base,  our  notion  of  quantity  is  an  epistemological  primary, 
just  like  our  notions  of  color  and  shape.  Depending  on  circumstances  (such  as  arrange- 
ment) we  can  directly  perceive  numbers  up  to  about  a  dozen.  That  is,  our  perceptual 
system  tells  us  automatically  whether  some  number  of  objects  is  equal,  greater,  or  less 
than  some  other  number  of  objects.  This  automatic  perceptual  integration  is  the  basis 
for  our  recognition  of  quantity,  as  it  is  for  our  recognition  of  color,  shape,  etc. 

Of  course,  we  extend  our  notion  of  quantity  beyond  those  quantities  that  are 
immediately  perceivable,  just  as  we  extend  our  notions  of  color  and  shape  beyond  the 
immediately  perceivable.    (For  example,  certain  colors  and  shapes  are  indistinguish- 


-24- 


Of  the  Things  Denoted  by  Names 
able  on  a  direct  perceptual  basis.)  This  extension  of  ideas  from  the  directly  perceivable 
primaries  to  non-primaries  is  the  basis  for  measurement.  But,  to  understand  this 
extension  process,  we  must  investigate  more  carefully  what  distinguishes  quantity  from 
other  attributes,  which  we  will  do  in  the  comments  accompanying  Book  II,  Chapter  6 
(On  the  Science  of  Number). 

13.  Attributes  Concluded 

Summary:  "Thus,  then,  all  the  attributes  of  bodies  which  are  classed  under  quality  or 
quantity  are  grounded  on  the  sensations  which  we  receive  from  those  bodies  ...."  The 
same  applies  to  every  attribute  of  mind,  which  "consists  either  in  being  itself  affected 
in  a  certain  way  or  affecting  other  minds  in  a  certain  way."  This  provides  the  key  to 
the  analysis  of  attributes  such  as  'beauty':  "As  we  thus  ascribe  attributes  to  minds  on 
the  ground  of  ideas  and  emotions,  so  may  we  to  bodies  on  similar  grounds,  and  not 
solely  on  the  ground  of  sensations:  As  in  speaking  of  the  beauty  of  a  statue,  since  this 
attribute  is  grounded  on  the  peculiar  feeling  of  pleasure  which  the  statue  produces  in 
our  minds,  which  is  not  a  sensation,  but  an  emotion."  Thus,  all  attributes  are  ulti- 
mately grounded  on  feelings,  i.e.,  states  of  consciousness. 

14.  Recapitulation 

Summary:  In  summary,  the  things  which  can  be  named  are  in  three  categories.  First, 
there  are  feelings  (states  of  consciousness),  which  are  of  four  sorts:  sensations, 
thoughts,  emotions,  and  volitions.  Second,  there  are  substances,  which  are  of  two 
sorts:  bodies  and  minds.  Finally  there  are  attributes,  which  are  of  three  sorts:  quali- 
ties, relations,  and  quantities.  But,  Mill  has  argued  that  all  attributes  are  reducible  to 
sensations  or  states  of  consciousness.  These  considerations  lead  Mill  to  the  following 
enumeration  of  the  categories  of  all  namable  things: 

1.  Feelings,  or  states  of  consciousness. 

2.  Minds,  which  experience  those  feelings. 


-25- 


Mill's  Logic:   Of  Names  and  Propositions 

3.  Bodies,  or  external  objects  which  excite  certain  of  those  feelings. 

4.  Successions  and  coexistences,  likeness  and  unlikeness,  between  feelings  or  states 
of  consciousness. 

Mill  concludes  this  section  by  distinguishing  psychological  or  subjective  facts,  which 
are  composed  solely  of  feelings  or  states  of  consciousness,  from  objective  facts,  which 
also  incorporate  substances  and  attributes.  "We  may  say,  then,  that  every  objective 
fact  is  grounded  on  a  corresponding  subjective  one,  and  has  no  meaning  to  us  (apart 
from  the  subjective  fact  which  corresponds  to  it),  except  as  a  name  for  the  unknown 
and  inscrutable  process  by  which  that  subjective  or  psychological  fact  is  brought  to 
pass." 

Comments:  This  latter  view,  that  objective  facts  are  based  on  subjective  facts,  is  essen- 
tially the  view  of  British  empiricism,  in  the  tradition  of  Locke,  Berkeley,  and  Hume. 
The  intended  readers  of  this  work,  scientists,  generally  don't  need  to  be  convinced  that 
the  real  world  exists.  Nevertheless,  it  may  be  worthwhile  to  spend  a  few  sentences  to 
discuss  Mill's  subjective  empiricism.  Certainly,  if  one  doubts  the  existence  of  the  real 
world,  then  there  is  very  little  reason  to  engage  in  science,  since  the  purpose  of  sci- 
ence is  to  give  us  knowledge  about  the  real  world.  That  is,  the  existence  of  the  real 
world  is  a  presupposition  of  the  study  of  logic  or  the  scientific  method.  To  put  this 
another  way,  the  purpose  of  science  is  to  establish  true  propositions,  i.e.,  statements 
that  correspond  with  the  state  of  affairs  in  the  real  world  (the  so-called  correspon- 
dence theory  of  truth).  Without  the  real  world,  there  is  no  significance  to  truth. 
Hence,  we  will  assume  that  any  reader  interested  in  Mill's  scientific  method  does  not 
question  the  existence  of  reality. 

Although  it  is  certain  that  reality  is,  it  is  not  certain  what  it  is.  The  establishment  of 
the  nature  of  reality  (as  opposed  to  its  existence)  is,  of  course,  the  purpose  of  science. 
However,  the  only  way  we  know  reality  is  through  our  senses  (including  our  introspec- 
tive awareness  of  our  own  mental  states).    This  is  the  sense  in  which  Mill  is  correct: 

-26- 


Of  the  Things  Denoted  by  Names 
epistemologicalLy,  that  is,  in  the  order  in  which  we  gain  knowledge,  subjective  facts  are 
prior  to  objective  facts.   Indeed,  this  is  the  essence  of  objectivity:   we  only  believe  wh^ 
we  ultimately  can  see,   hear,  touch,   etc.,   either  directly  or  indirectly.    The  goal  of 
scientific  methodology  is  the  elaboration  and  refinement  of  the  previous  sentence. 


-27- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
4 .   Of  Propositions 

1.  Nature  and  office  of  the  copula 

Summary:  A  proposition  is  a  sentence  in  which  a  predicate  is  affirmed  or  denied  of  a 
subject.  To  accomplish  this  affirmation  or  denial,  a  copula  is  necessary  (usually  the 
verb  to  be).  Hence,  the  first  division  of  propositions  is  into  affirmative  and  negative. 
An  affirmative  proposition  is  one  in  which  the  predicate  is  affirmed  of  the  subject;  a 
negative  proposition  is  one  in  which  the  predicate  is  denied  of  the  subject. 

2.  Affirmative  and  Negative  Propositions 

Summary:  The  distinction  between  affirmative  and  negative  propositions  is  real.  Some 
writers,  such  as  Hobbes,  have  claimed  that  negative  propositions  are  just  disguised 
affirmative  propositions.  For  example,  'Caesar  is  not  alive'  is  really  a  disguised  form  of 
'Caesar  is  non-alive'.  But  this  analysis  has  just  replaced  one  proposition  denying  a  posi- 
tive predicate  with  another  affirming  a  negative  predicate.  This  has  accomplished 
nothing.  "The  distinction  between  affirming  and  denying  is  real  and  is  not  to  be  got  rid 
of  by  a  verbal  juggle."  Thus,  "when  we  affirm  a  negative  name,  we  really  affirm  the 
absence,  not  the  presence,  of  anything;  not  that  something  is,  but  that  it  is  not.  " 

Comments:  The  distinction  between  affirmative  and  negative  propositions  is  an  essen- 
tial one  that  has  been  abandoned  in  symbolic  logic.  The  value  of  this  distinction  will  be 
more  apparent  when  1  discuss  induction  and  scientific  method  in  Book  III.  As  Mill 
notes,  the  distinction  between  affirmative  propositions  is  grounded  on  the  distinction 
between  positive  and  negative  terms,  which  I  discussed  in  Chapter  2. 

3.  Simple  and  Complex 

Summary:  "A  simple  proposition  is  that  in  which  one  predicate  is  affirmed  or  denied  of 
one  subject.  A  [complex]  proposition  is  that  in  which  there  is  more  than  one  predicate, 
or  more  than  one  subject,  or  both."    Complex  propositions  in  turn  can  be  divided  into 


-28- 


Of  Propositions 
categorical  and  hypothetical  propositions.2 

Categorical  propositions  are  those  "in  which  the  assertion  is  not  dependent  on  a 
condition."  Categorical  complex  propositions  are  equivalent  in  meaning  to  two  or  more 
simple  propositions.   For  example,  'Caesar  is  dead,  but  Brutus  is  alive'  is  equivalent  to: 

1.  Caesar  is  dead. 

2.  Brutus  is  alive. 

3.  Propositions  1  and  2  should  be  thought  of  together. 

4.  There  is  a  contrast  between  propositions  1  and  2. 

The  function  of  the  particle  'but'  is  to  abbreviate  propositions  3  and  4. 

Unlike  the  categorical  complex  propositions  just  considered,  a  hypothetical  proposi- 
tion is  not  "a  mere  aggregation  of  simple  propositions."  Although  a  hypothetical  pro- 
position may  contain  several  subjects  and  several  predicates,  it  makes  only  one  asser- 
tion. Take  as  an  example  one  kind  of  hypothetical  proposition,  the  conditional  proposi- 
tion. The  conditional  proposition  'If  A  is  B,  C  is  D'  is  just  an  abbreviation  for  'The  propo- 
sition C  is  D,  is  a  legitimate  inference  from  the  proposition  A  is  B'.  The  latter  is  a  sim- 
ple proposition  whose  subject  is  'the  proposition  C  is  D'  and  whose  predicate  is  'a  legiti- 
mate inference  from  A  is  B'.  Thus,  a  conditional  proposition  is  a  simple  proposition 
whose  terms  are  the  names  of  propositions. 

"Like  other  things,  a  proposition  has  attributes  which  may  be  predicated  of  it."  For 
example,  '  /hat  th  whole  is  greater  than  its  parts,  is  an  axiom  in  mathematics'  is  a  ]  re- 
position whose  subject  is  a  proposition. 

Another  common  kind  of  hypothetical  proposition  is  the  disjunctive,  for  example, 
either  A  is  B  or  C  is  D.  Whately  (1868)  and  others  have  shown  that  this  is  resolvable  into 
the  two  conditionals: 


2.    AH  simple  propositions  are  categorical. 


-29- 


Mill's  Logic:   Of  Names  and  Propositions 
.     If  A  is  not  B,  C  is  D. 

-     If  C  is  not  D,  A  is  B 

Comments:  Mill's  and  Whately's  explication  of  the  inclusive  or  connective  is  easy  to  see 
in  the  prepositional  calculus: 

(~P  -»  Q)  &  (~Q  ->  P) 
(~~P  V  Q)  &  (~~Q  V  P) 
(P  V  Q)  &  (P  V  Q) 
P  V  Q 

On  the  other  hand,  Mill's  definition  of  the  conditional  proposition  cannot  be  expressed 
in  symbolic  logic  because  it  mixes  the  object  language  and  metalanguage  levels.  That 
is,  it  is  a  proposition  about  the  inferability  of  propositions.  To  express  such  a  notion, 
we  have  to  use  techniques  like  Godel's  for  embedding  metalanguage  propositions  in  the 
object  language.  Traditional  logic  avoids  the  object  language /metalanguage  distinc- 
tion. 

4.    Universal,  Particular,  and  Singular 

Summary:  Propositions  may  be  divided  into  three  major  classes  on  the  basis  of  the 
degree  of  generality  which  the  subject  is  understood  to  have.   These  classes  are:  3 

Universal,  for  example,  Ml  men  are  mortal. 

Particular,  for  example  Some  men  are  mortal. 

•     Singular,  for  example,  Julius  Caesar  is  mortal. 

A  proposition  is  singular  when  its  subject  is  an  individual  name.  "When  the  name  which 
is  the  subject  of  the  proposition  is  a  general  name,  we  may  intend  to  affirm  or  deny  the 
predicate,  either  of  all  the  things  the  subject  denotes,  or  only  of  some."   In  the  former 

case    the    proposition    is    universal,    in    the    latter    particular.     Since    in    a    singular 

3.    Following  Mill,  we  have  used  the  traditional  terms,  although  Bain's  (Logic)  terms  total  and  partial  are 
perhaps  more  descriptive. 

-30- 


Of  Propositions 
proposition  the  predicate  is  affirmed  or  denied  of  the  entire  subject,  a  singular  propo- 
sition is  usually  considered  a  universal  proposition. 

Traditionally,  an  occurrence  of  a  name  is  said  to  be  distributed  when  it  stands  for 
each  and  every  individual  the  name  denotes  and  is  said  to  be  undistributed  otherwise. 
Thus,  in  a  universal  proposition  the  subject  is  distributed,  but  in  a  particular  proposi- 
tion the  subject  is  undistributed.  Clearly,  the  subject  is  distributed  in  a  singular  pro- 
position. 

Comments:  It  is  worth  adding  that  in  a  negative  proposition  the  predicate  is  distri- 
buted and  in  an  affirmative  proposition  the  predicate  is  undistributed.  Thus  we  have 
the  classification  shown  in  Table  2. 

TABLE  2.   Classification  of  Propositions 


Quantity 

Quality 

Distribution 

Example 

Subject 

Predicate 

universal 

affirmative 

D 

U 

All  S  and  P 

particular 

affirmative 

U 

U 

Some  S  are  P 

universal 

negative 

D 

D 

No  S  are  P 

particular 

negative 

U 

D 

Some  S  are  not  P 

TABLE  3.   Set  Expressions  Equivalent  to  Types  of  Propositions 


Quantity 

Quality 

Distribution 

Set  Expression 

universal 

affirmative 

DU 

S  £P 

particular 

affirmative 

UU 

S\P 

universal 

negative 

DD 

s  c~p 

particular 

negative 

UD 

S1~P 

Since  the  extension  of  a  general  term  is  a  class,  we  can  express  these  propositional 
forms  in  the  algebra  of  classes.  This  is  shown  in  Table  2.  Here  we  have  used  '5"  }  P'  as 
an  abbreviation  for  S  n  P*  0.  Notice  that  the  forms  containing  'C  distribute  the  sub- 
ject and  those  containing  '~'  distribute  the  predicate.  Furthermore,  note  that  if  we 
always  write  a  negative  term  with  a  '~'  sign  and  a  positive  term  without  one,  then  the 
form  of  the  proposition  will  be  obvious  regardless  of  "verbal  juggling."  Thus,  whether 
we  say  'some  men  aren't  mortal'  or  'some  men  are  non-mortal',  the  form  is  'men  \ 
~mortal'.     The    symbolic    notation    also    simplifies    transforming    propositions    into 

-31- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
equivalent  forms.  For  example,  since  S  c  ~P  is  equivalent  toPc  ~S  (as  we  can  con- 
vince ourselves  with  Venn  Diagrams),  we  know  that  'no  man  is  a  fish'  is  equivalent  to  'No 
fish  is  a  man'.  Of  course,  the  early  development  of  the  algebra  of  classes  by  De  Morgan 
and  Boole  took  place  after  Mill's  Logic  had  been  written,  so  he  didn't  have  the  benefit  of 
notations  such  as  this. 


-32- 


Of  the  Import  of  Propositions 
5.    Of  the  Import  of  Propositions 

1.   Is  Proposition  a  Relation  Between  Two  Ideas? 

Summary:  Mill  asks,  "What  is  that  which  is  expressed  by  the  form  of  discourse  called  a 
proposition,  and  the  conformity  of  which  to  fact  constitutes  the  truth  of  the  proposi- 
tion?" Since  a  proposition  consists  of  two  terms  (a  subject  and  a  predicate)  connected 
by  a  copula,  we  must  first  understand  what  the  terms  represent,  and  then  ask  what 
kind  of  connection  between  them  the  copula  asserts. 

Philosophers,  "from  Descartes  downward,  and  especially  from  the  era  of  Leibnitz 
and  Locke,"  have  taken  a  proposition  "to  consist  in  affirming  one  idea  of  another."  will 
disagrees  with  this  view.  "When  I  say  that  fire  causes  heat,  do  I  mean  that  my  idea  of 
fire  causes  my  idea  of  heat?  No,  I  mean  that  the  natural  phenomenon,  fire,  causes  the 
natural  phenomenon,  heat."  In  fact  he  claims  that  focusing  on  ideas  of  things  rather 
than  the  thin,  s  themselves  was  the  cause  of  much  of  the  sterility  of  pre-scientific  rea- 
soning. The  scientific  view  is  that  propositions  "are  not  assertions  respecting  our  ideas 
of  things,  but  assertions  respecting  the  things  themselves." 

2.    Is  a  Proposition  a  Relation  Between  the  Meanings  of  Two  Names? 

Summary:  Mill  next  addresses  Hobbes'  view  that  a  proposition  signifies  "the  belief  of 
the  speaker  that  the  predicate  is  a  name  of  the  same  thing  of  which  the  subject  is  a 
name."  When  we  assert  that  all  oxen  ruminate  it  is  certainly  true  that  all  the  individu- 
als denoted  by  the  name  'ox'  are  asserted  to  be  among  all  the  individuals  denoted  by 
the  name  'ruminating'.  Thus  Hobbes'  analysis  is  true  of  all  propositions.  And  in  fact  it 
is  the  entire  meaning  of  some  propositions,  which  "only  shows  what  an  extremely 
minute  fragment  of  meaning  it  is  quite  possible  to  include  within  the  logical  formula  of 
a  proposition." 

Mill  says  that  this  account  of  meaning  could  be  considered  adequate  only  because 
Hobbes,  in  common  with  the  nominalists,  sought  the  meaning  of  terms  entirely  in  their 


-33- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
denotation  and  ignored  their  connotation.  What  is  wrong  with  this  view?  As  explained 
earlier,  "the  meaning  of  all  names,  except  proper  names  and  that  portion  of  the  class 
of  abstract  names  which  are  not  connotative,  resides  in  the  connotation."  Otherwise 
we  could  not  explain  the  meaning  of  a  proposition  such  as  'diamonds  are  combustible'. 
Certainly  when  mankind  fixed  the  meaning  of  the  word  'combustible'  they  did  not  know 
that  the  individuals  denoted  by  'diamond'.  The  names  happen  to  fit  the  same  objects 
because  of  a  certain  fact,  which  fact  was  not  known  when  the  names  were  invented. 
Thus  "the  objects  are  brought  under  the  name  by  possessing  the  attributes  connoted 
by  it:  but  their  possession  of  the  attributes  is  the  real  condition  on  which  the  truth  of 
the  proposition  depends;  not  their  being  called  by  the  same  name.  Connotative  names 
do  not  precede,  but  follow,  the  attributes  which  they  connote." 

3.   Is  a  Proposition  an  Expression  of  Class  Membership? 

Summary:  "The  most  generally  received  notion  of  a  predication  decidedly  is  that  it 
consists  in  referring  something  to  a  class,  that  is,  either  placing  an  individual  under  a 
class,  or  placing  one  class  under  another  class.  ...  If  the  proposition  is  negative,  then  ... 
it  is  said  to  exclude  something  from  a  class."  This  is  essentially  the  same  as  Hobbes' 
theory,  since  "a  class  is  absolutely  nothing  but  an  indefinite  number  of  individuals 
denoted  by  a  general  name." 

Mill  believes  that  this  theory  is  an  example  of  a  common  logical  error,  hysteron  pra- 
teron4  (last  first),  or  "explaining  a  thing  by  something  which  presupposes  it."  This  is 
because,  only  after  having  judged  that  snow  is  white  and  several  other  objects  are  white 
do  I  gradually  begin  to  think  of  white  objects  as  forming  a  class.  ""We  place  the  indivi- 
dual in  the  class  because  the  proposition  is  true;  the  proposition  is  not  true  because 
the  object  is  placed  in  the  class."  Mill  claims  that  this  view  seems  to  treat  classes  as 
preexisting,  as  though  having  once  been  laid  down  by  the  framers  of  language.  Furth- 
ermore, we  must  think  of  the  meaning  as  constantly  changing  as  individuals  become  or 


4.    ixTTspov  irpoTtpov. 

-34- 


Of  the  Import  of  Propositions 
cease  to  be  members  of  the  class.   Thus,  a  name  would  have  no  definite  meaning.   "The 
only  mode  in  which  any  general  name  has  a  definite  meaning  is  by  being  a  nam    of  an 
indefinite  variety  of  things,  namely,  of  all  things,  known  or  unknown,  past  present,  or 
future,  which  possess  certain  definite  attributes."  Thus,  attributes  are  prior  to  classes. 

Mill  concludes  by  noting  the  dominance  of  these  two  erroneous  views:  "Since  the 
revolution  which  dislodged  Aristotle  from  the  schools,  logicians  may  almost  be  divided 
into  those  who  have  looked  upon  reasoning  as  essentially  an  affair  of  ideas  and  those 
who  have  looked  upon  it  as  essentially  an  affair  of  names." 

Comments:  This  trend  has  certainly  continued  through  the  20th  century,  although  the 
idea-oriented  viewpoint  has  tended  to  be  displaced  by  the  class-oriented  view  begun  by 
Boole,  Russell  and  Whitehead,  and  the  formal  view  that  descended  from  symbolic  logic. 
Although  these  views  capture  most  of  deductive  reasoning,  they  are  inadequate  for 
explaining  induction.  The  following  sections  present  Mill's  attempt  to  solve  these  prob- 
lems. 

4.    What  it  Really  Is 

Summary:  Consider  a  singular  proposition,  such  as  'Socrates  is  wise'.  The  meaning  of  a 
proposition  such  as  this  is  that  'the  individual  thing  denoted  by  the  subject  has  the 
attributes  connoted  by  the  predicate'.  Next,  consider  a  proposition  whose  subject  is 
connotative,  such  as  'All  men  are  mortal'.  In  this  case  we  are  also  asserting  that  the 
objects  denoted  by  the  subject  possess  the  attributes  connoted  by  the  predicate.  How- 
ever, in  this  case  the  objects  are  not  individually  pointed  out— they  are  idenufied  by 
some  of  their  attributes,  namely  those  connoted  by  the  name  'man'.  Thus,  a  proposi- 
tion of  this  form  means  that  "whatever  has  the  attributes  connoted  by  the  predicate; 
that  the  latter  set  of  attributes  constantly  accompany  the  former  set." 

Mill  carries  this  analysis  one  step  further  by  recalling  that  "every  attribute  is 
grounded  on  some  fact  or  phenomenon,  either  of  outward  sense  or  of  inward  conscious- 


-35- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
ness,  and  that  to  possess  an  attribute  is  another  phrase  for  being  the  cause  of,  or  form- 
ing a  part  of,  the  fact  or  phenomenon  upon  which  the  attribute  is  grounded.  ...    The 
proposition  which  asserts  that  one  attribute  always  accompanies  another  attribute 
really  asserts  ...  that  one  phenomenon  always  accompanies  another  phenomenon  ..." 

Comments:  There  are  two  ways  to  interpret  Mill's  explanation,  based  on  the  exact 
notion  of  connotation  we  adopt.  If  by  the  connotation  of  a  term  we  mean  all  the  attri- 
butes shared  by  the  individuals  denoted  by  that  term,  then  his  analysis  is  correct.  For 
example,  among  the  many  attributes  connoted  by  man  we  find  the  attributes  connoted 
by  mortal.  This  is  what  we  mean  when  we  say  'all  men  are  mortal'.  It  is  of  course  one 
of  the  tasks  of  science  to  determine  whether  the  attributes  connoted  by  mortal  are 
among  those  connoted  by  man. 

Another  interpretation  is  that  the  connotation  of  a  term  includes  only  certain  essen- 
tial attributes.  For  example,  the  connotation  of  man  might  by  rational  animal,  or 
featherless  biped.  In  this  case  the  connotation  of  man  does  not  include  the  connota- 
tion of  mortal.  By  this  view  'man'  can  be  considered  to  be  just  an  abbreviation  for 
'rational  animal'  or  'featherless  biped'.  This  analysis  can  easily  be  seen  to  be  inade- 
quate, since  we  can  easily  imagine  discovering  featherless  bipeds  that  we  would  not  be 
willing  to  call  men.  The  The  reason  is  that  they  would  not  share  the  other  attributes  of 
men,  such  as  rationality.   Thus  the  connotation  must  include  all  the  attributes. 

We  can  see  in  the  above  interpretation  a  different  class-oriented  analysis  of  proposi- 
tions. 'All  men  are  mortal'  does  not  mean  that  the  denotation  of  man  is  a  subclass  of 
the  denotation  of  mortal,  but  that  the  connotation  of  man  is  a  superclass  of  the  conno- 
tation of  mortal. 

5.    What  it  Is  that  Propositions  Assert  or  Deny 

Summary:  "The  object  of  belief  in  a  proposition,  when  it  asserts  anything  more  than 
the  meaning  of  words,  is  generally  ...  either  the  co-existence  or  the  sequence  of  two 


-36- 


Of  the  Import  of  Propositions 
phenomena."  For  example,  when  we  say,  "A  generous  person  is  worthy  of  honor,"  we 
"affirm  that  wherever  and  whenever  the  inward  feelings  and  outward  facts  implied  in 
the  word  generosity  have  place,  then  and  there  the  existence  and  manifestation  of  an 
inward  feeling,  honor,  would  be  followed  in  or  minds  by  another  inward  feeling,  appro- 
val." 

Although  propositions  asserting  sequences  and  co-existences  among  phenomena  are 
the  most  common,  "we  make  propositions  also  respecting  those  hidden  causes  of 
phenomena,  which  are  named  substances  and  attributes."  As  noted  previously, 
though,  "no  assertion  can  be  made,  at  least  with  a  meaning,  concerning  these  unknown 
and  knowable  entities,  except  in  virtue  of  the  phenomena  by  which  alone  they  manifest 
themselves  to  or  faculties."  Thus,  propositions  asserting  the  co-existence  or  the 
sequence  of  substances  and  attributes  reduce  to  propositions  concerning  the  co- 
existence and  sequence  of  phenomena.    [This  view  is  known  as  phenomenalism]. 

Besides  propositions  that  assert  co-existence  and  sequence,  there  are  those  that 
assert  simple  existence  and  causation.  Some  logicians,  such  as  Bain,  have  asserted 
that  the  concept  of  simple  existence  is  empty.  His  Law  of  Relativity  says  that  tilings 
can  be  perceived  or  apprehended  only  by  contrasting  them  with  other  things.  But, 
since  "we  have  no  other  class  to  oppose  to  Being,  or  fact  to  contrast  with  Existence," 
these  words  are  merely  "fictitious  and  unmeaning  language."  Mill  disagrees.  The 
meanings  of  existence  and  being  lie  in  the  fact  that  to  exist  is  to  excite,  or  be  capable 
of  exciting,  any  sensations  or  states  of  consciousness  ...."  A  thing  can't  be  without 
being  something .   Causation  and  existence  are  discussed  further  in  Book  III. 

"To  these  four  kinds  of  matter-of-fact  or  assertion  must  be  added  a  fifth,  resem- 
blance. This  was  a  species  of  attribute  which  we  found  it  impossible  to  analyze;  for 
which  no  fundamentum  distinct  from  the  objects  themselves  could  be  assigned."  Thus, 
a  statement,  such  as  "This  color  is  like  that  color,"  cannot  be  analyzed  [epistemologi- 
cally]  into  any  more  basic  propositions. 


-37- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
"It  is  sometimes  said  that  all  propositions  whatever  of  which  the  predicate  is  a  gen- 
eral name  do,  in  point  of  fact,  affirm  or  deny  resemblance."  There  is  only  a  slight 
degree  of  foundation  for  this  remark,  for  although  the  arrangement  of  things  into 
classes  in  based  on  resemblance,  it  is  not  a  mere  general  resemblance,  but  rather  a 
resemblance  that  "consists  in  the  possession  by  all  those  things  [in  the  class]  of  cer- 
tain common  peculiarities."  It  is  those  peculiarities  "which  the  terms  connote,  and 
which  the  propositions  consequently  assert,  not  the  resemblance." 

There  are  some  exceptional  classes  that  are  founded  on  general  unanalyzable 
resemblance.  "The  classes  in  question  are  those  into  which  our  simple  sensations,  or 
other  simple  feelings,  are  divided."  Thus  when  I  classify  things  as  white,  the  basis  for 
this  classification  is  an  unanalyzable  [i.e.,  epistemologically  primary]  sensation  of 
resemblance. 

"Existence,  co-existence,  sequence,  causation,  resemblance:  one  or  other  of  these 
is  asserted  (or  denied)  in  every  proposition  which  is  not  merely  verbal.  This  five-fold 
division  is  a  exhaustive  classification  of  matters-of-fact,  of  all  things  that  can  be 
believed  or  tendered  for  belief,  of  all  questions  that  can  be  propounded,  and  all 
answers  that  can  be  returned  to  them." 

Comments:  The  position  of  phenomenalism,  that  all  proposition  are  ultimately  proposi- 
tions about  sensory  phenomena,  has  developed  into  one  of  the  dominant  modern 
schools  of  the  philosophy  of  science,  the  logical  positivism  of  the  Vienna  Circle  ori- 
ginated by  Mach,  Schlick  and  others.  Against  this  position  we  can  use  Mill's  own  argu- 
ments (Section  1).  When  we  say  that  an  eclipse  is  caused  by  the  moon  coming  between 
us  and  the  sun,  we  clearly  intend  to  say  something  about  these  objects  in  reality  (i.e., 
the  sun,  moon  and  ourselves),  not  our  sensations  of  these  things.  We  use  different  ver- 
bal forms  to  talk  about  sensations.  For  example,  "Our  sensation  of  the  sun  is  caused 
by  its  light  falling  on  our  retina,  which  causes  impulses  to  travel  down  the  optic  nerve 
...,"  and  so  forth.    Mill  would  be  more  correct  in  saying  that  propositions  concerning 


-38- 


Of  the  Import  of  Propositions 
substances  and  attributes  are  in  fact  intended  as  statements  about  the  real  world,  but 
that  the  evidence  for  these  propositions  are  propositions  about  the  phenomena  we 
experience  directly. 

6.   Propositions  with  Abstract  Terms 

Summary:  In  the  previous  analysis  Mill  has  addressed  only  propositions  whose  terms 
are  concrete.  However,  since  the  meaning  of  such  a  proposition  is  based  on  the  attri- 
butes which  its  terms  connote,  it  is  easy  to  extend  the  analysis  to  propositions  whose 
terms  are  abstract,  since  abstract  terms  directly  denote  attributes.  For  example,  the 
proposition,  'Prudence  is  a  virtue',  in  which  the  terms  are  abstract,  may  be  rendered 
'All  prudent  persons,  in  so  far  as  prudent,  are  virtuous',  in  which  the  terms  are  con- 
crete. 

In  the  previous  section  Mill  showed  that  whenever  a  proposition  has  a  concrete 
predicate,  what  we  are  predicating  is  an  existence,  co-existence,  or  resemblance.  The 
interconvertibility  of  abstract  and  concrete  terms  leads  Mill  to  conclude  that  an  attri- 
bute is  necessarily  either  an  existence,  co-existence,  causation,  sequence  or  resem- 
blance." 

Comments:  Although  in  common  discourse  concrete  propositions  are  the  more  com- 
mon, the  above  analysis  suggests  that  semantically  abstract  propositions  are  more  fun- 
damental. This  is  because  abstract  terms  directly  denote  the  characteristic  attri- 
butes, whereas  concrete  terms  only  connote  them,  and  the  meaning  of  a  proposition  is 
based  on  these  attributes. 


-39- 


Mill's  Logic:   Of  Names  and  Propositions 
6.    Of  Propositions  Merely  Verbal 

1.  Essential  and  Accidental  Propositions 

Summary:  Mill  has  already  refuted  the  Conceptualists'  claim,  that  propositions  state 
relations  between  ideas,  and  the  Nominalists'  claim,  that  propositions  express  the 
agreement  or  disagreement  between  the  meanings  of  names.  He  has  claimed  that  pro- 
positions "assert  five  different  kinds  of  matters  of  fact,  namely,  Existence,  Order  in 
Place,  Order  in  Time,  Causation,  and  Resemblance.  ..." 

Mill  reminds  us,  however,  that  there  is  a  class  of  propositions  that  "do  not  relate  to 
any  matter  of  fact  ...  at  all,  but  to  the  meaning  of  names."  These  would  not  be  worth 
spending  much  time  on,  but  for  the  fact  that  they  occupy  "a  conspicuous  place  in  phi- 
losophy" and  that  some  philosophers  regard  them  as  expressing  the  most  essential 
truths. 

Comments:  There  are  two  senses  in  which  we  could  say  that  proposition  is  about  the 
meaning  of  names.  One  expresses  a  matter  of  fact  about  language,  namely,  that  a 
given  configuration  of  sounds  or  letters  refers  to  a  given  concept.  For  example,  when  I 
say  '6Lw$pomo<;  is  the  Greek  word  for  man',  I  assert  a  matter  of  fact  about  the  Greek 
language.  However,  when  I  assert  'man  is  the  rational  animal',  I  am  not  stating  a 
matter  of  fact  about  English.  Rather,  I  am  stating  a  fact  of  fundamental  importance 
about  the  entities  which  we  group  together  under  the  concept  man.  Such  a  definition 
is  more  than  simply  an  assertion  about  the  way  English  speakers  use  the  word  'man'. 

2.  Essential  Propositions  are  Identical  Propositions 

Summary:  The  Schoolmen  divided  the  attributes  as  anything  into  two  classes:  the 
essential  attributes  and  the  accidental  attributes.  The  essential  attributes  were  con- 
sidered to  be  part  of  the  essence  of  a  thing,  and  thus  go  deeper  than  the  accidents. 
For  example,  rationality  was  considered  part  of  the  essence  of  man,  whereas  that  he 
cooks  his  food  was  considered  an  accident  (i.e.,  not  essential).    This  theory  was  based 

-40- 


Of  Propositions  Merely  Verbal 
on  the  Schoolmen's  view  that  an  object  borrowed  some  of  its  properties  form  a  univer- 
sal substance  (an  essence)  and  that  the  rest  belonged  to  it  individually  (were  acciden- 
tal). Although  this  view  is  often  attributed  to  Aristotle,  Mill  notes  that  in  the  Categories 
Aristotle  expressly  denies  that  general  properties  inhere  in  a  subject;  they  are  merely 
predicated  of  it. 

Following  Locke,  Mill  claims  that  an  essential  proposition  only  unfolds  the  meaning 
of  a  term.  For  example,  the  word  man  connotes  all  of  man's  attributes,  including  cor- 
poreity, rationality,  and  being  living.  Thus,  when  we  say  'Man  is  rational'  we  have 
merely  singled  out  one  of  the  attribute  connoted  by  man.  Thus,  since  the  essences  of 
classes  are  merely  the  signification  of  their  names,  and  the  signification  of  a  name  is 
just  its  connotation,  we  can  see  that  all  propositions  that  have  been  called  essential  are 
in  fact  identical. 

Is  there  any  value,  then,  to  an  essential  proposition?  Since  it  states  part  of  the 
meaning  of  a  term,  it  can  only  be  informative  to  someone  who  does  not  already  know 
the  full  meaning  of  the  term.  Thus,  Mill  says  that  the  only  really  useful  kinds  of  essen- 
tial propositions  are  definitions.  Even  here  he  notes,  "In  defining  a  name,  however,  it  is 
not  usual  to  specify  its  entire  connotation,  but  so  much  only  as  is  sufficient  to  mark 
out  the  objects  usually  denoted  by  it  from  all  other  known  objects.  And  sometimes,  a 
merely  accidental  property,  not  involved  in  the  meaning  of  the  name,  answers  this  pur- 
pose equally  well." 

Comments:  What,  ther ,  can  we  make  of  this  distinction  between  essence  and  accident, 
between  verbal  and  real  propositions?  There  certainly  seems  to  be  a  distinction 
between  a  proposition  such  as  'Man  is  rational'  and  propositions  such  as  'Man  can  cook 
his  food,'  'Man  has  five  fingers,'  and  'Man  domesticates  animals.'  What  is  this 
difference?  They  all  state  properties  of  men,  but  some  seem  more  fundamental, 
(more  essential),  while  others  seem  less  fundamental.  What  makes  some  properties 
seem  more  fundamental? 


-41- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
As  noted  before,  one  aspect  of  this  distinction  is  explanatory  power.  The  rationality 
and  animality  of  man  implies  that  he  can  cook  food,  provide  shelter  for  himself,  com- 
pose symphonies,  design  computers,  etc.  Thus,  we  feel  we  have  got  to  man's  essence, 
when  we  realize  he  is  a  rational  animal.  Notice,  however,  that  in  this  sense  it  is  no 
accident  that  man  builds  houses;  it  is  a  consequence  of  his  rationality  and  animality. 

Some  properties  of  man  do  seem  to  be  accidents:  that  man  has  five  fingers  on  each 
hand  does  not  seem  to  be  a  consequence  of  him  being  a  rational  animal.  Further,  this 
property  doesn't  seem  to  explain  many  others:  it  gives  us  no  hint  why  he  cooks  or 
designs  computers.  Yet  having  five  fingers  is  no  less  a  property  of  man  than  is  having  a 
rational  faculty.   In  this  sense  there  is  nothing  accidental  about  it. 

Thus,  if  we  take  connotation  in  the  wide  sense,  to  mean  all  the  properties,  known 
and  unknown,  shared  by  the  members  of  the  denotation  of  a  term,  then  we  can  see  that 
any  true,  universal  affirmative  proposition  only  "unfolds"  what  is  already  contained  in 
the  connotation  of  the  subject.  Yet  we  can  hardly  call  such  propositions  "merely  ver- 
bal." 

Should  we  then  discard  the  notion  of  essential  properties?  No,  for  it  expresses  a 
useful  epistemological  fact:  that  at  given  point  in  our  understanding  of  a  subject  some 
propositions  have  greater  explanatory  value  than  others.  Peikoff  (1979)  says,  "To 
designate  a  certain  characteristic  as  'essential'  or  'defining'  is  to  select,  from  the  total 
content  of  the  concept,  the  characteristic  that  best  condenses  and  differentiates  that 
content  in  a  specific  cognitive  context."  Note  that  properties  are  not  inherently  essen- 
tial: whether  they  are  essential  or  not  depends  on  their  explanatory  value  relative  to 
our  knowledge.  "The  characteristic(s)  which  most  fundamentally  distinguishes  a  cer- 
tain type  of  entity  from  all  other  existents  known  at  that  time,  may  not  do  so  within  a 
wider  field  of  knowledge,  when  more  existents  become  known  and /or  more  of  the 
entity's  characteristics  are  discovered"  (Peikoff,  1979). 


-42- 


Of  Propositions  Merely  Verbal 
3.    Individuals  Have  No  Essences 

Summary:  Since  the  essence  of  a  term  is  its  connotation,  and,  as  described  earlier,  Mill 
claims  that  individual  terms  have  no  connotation,  it  follows  that  "individuals  have  no 
essences." 

Comments:  This  conclusion  results  from  taking  the  narrower  notion  of  connotation.  If 
we  take  connotation  to  refer  to  all  the  properties  of  a  thing,  then  clearly  individual 
terms  have  a  connotation.  But  do  they  have  essences?  The  essence  of  an  individual 
would  be  those  characteristics  that  explain  and  make  possible  the  largest  number  of 
the  rest.  In  many  cases  we  would  find  ourselves  in  agreement  with  the  Schoolmen  on 
the  essence  of  an  individual.  For  example,  the  essence  of  Julius  Caesar  is  the  same  as 
the  essence  of  man:   rationality  and  animality. 

4.   Real  Propositions,  How  Distinguished  from  Verbal 

Summary:  "An  essential  proposition,  then,  is  one  which  purely  verbal"  and  therefore 
"either  gives  no  information  or  gives  it  respecting  the  name,  not  the  thing.  Non- 
essential, or  accidental  propositions,  on  the  contrary,  may  be  called  real  propositions, 
in  opposition  to  verbal."  This  is  because  they  predicate  of  a  thing  "some  attribute  not 
connoted  by  [its]  name."   Thus,  they  tell  us  a  new  fact  that  we  didn't  know  before. 

Comments:  Although  Mill's  distinction  between  verbal  and  real  propositions  is  falla- 
cious, he  has  hinted  at  an  important  point.  When  we  are  told  something  we  already 
know,  we  consider  the  proposition  "merely  verbal"  since  it  tells  us  something  that  was 
already  part  of  our  understanding  of  the  meaning  of  the  subject.  In  this  sense,  it  only 
unfolds  the  meaning  of  that  term.  Thus,  a  proposition  is  verbal  to  me  if  it  expresses  a 
part  of  the  connotation  of  the  term  with  which  I  was  already  familiar.  In  contrast,  a 
real  proposition  is  one  that  tells  me  something  new,  something  that  adds  to  my 
knowledge  of  the  connotation  of  the  subject. 


-43- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
In  this  sense  'Man  has  five  fingers'  is  a  verbal  proposition  to  most  people,  since  most 
people  have  known  that  men  have  five  fingers  almost  as  long  as  they  have  grasped  the 
concept  man.  On  the  other  hand  'Man  is  a  rational  animal'  is  for  many  people  a  real 
proposition  the  first  time  they  hear  it,  since  it  tells  them  a  matter  of  fact  that  they 
might  not  have  previously  considered:  that  the  characteristic  most  distinctive  of  man 
and  that  explains  the  largest  number  of  his  other  characteristics,  is  that  he  is  rational. 

5.    Two  Modes  of  Representing  the  Import  of  a  Beat  Proposition 

Summary:  There  are  two  different  aspects  in  which  a  real,  universal  proposition  can  be 
considered,  One  "is  best  adopted  to  express  the  import  of  a  proposition  as  a  portion  of 
our  theoretical  knowledge";  the  other  is  useful  "when  the  proposition  is  considered  as 
a  memorandum  for  practical  use."  In  the  first  case  the  proposition  'All  men  are  mor- 
tal' "means  that  the  attributes  of  man  are  always  accompanied  by  the  attribute  mor- 
tality." In  the  second  case  it  "means  that  the  attributes  of  man  are  evidence  of,  are  a 
mark  of,  mortality.  ..."  The  latter  is  usually  the  most  useful  view  when  we  are  studying 
the  reasoning  process. 

Comments:  We  can  express  these  notions  symbolically  as  follows.  That  the  attributes 
of  man  are  always  accompanied  by  the  attribute  mortal,  means  that  mortal  is  one  of 
the  attributes  of  man,  mortality  e  attributes(man).  Alternately  we  can  say  that  the 
connotation  of  man  includes  the  connotation  of  mortal,  connotation(man)  D 
connotation(mortal).  The  second  interpretation  says  that  when  ever  we  find  something 
that  we  can  identify  as  man,  we  will  know  that  that  thing  has  the  attribute  mortal, 
man(x)  -*  mortal(x). 


-44- 


On  Classification  and  the  Predicables 
7.  On  Classification  and  the  Predicables 

1.    Classification,  How  Connected  with  Naming 

Summary:  Although  the  ideas  of  a  class  and  classification  play  an  important  role  in  the 
work  of  many  logicians,  Mill  does  not  stress  these  ideas.  This  is  because  he  takes  "gen- 
eral names  as  having  a  meaning,  quite  independently  of  their  being  the  names  of 
classes."  Usually  classes  owe  their  existence  to  general  names,  since  "[a]s  soon  as  we 
employ  a  name  to  connote  attributes,  the  things,  be  they  more  or  fewer,  which  happen 
to  possess  those  attributes,  are  constituted  ipso  facto  a  class.  But  in  predicating  the 
name  we  predicate  only  the  attributes;  and  the  fact  of  belonging  to  a  class  does  not,  in 
many  cases,  come  into  view  at  all."  Killick  (1909)  illustrates  this  as  follows:  "Suppose  1 
take  two  attributes,  'perfect  molecular  mobility'  and  'inelasticity'  and  devise  a  name 
'liquid',  which  shall  connote  or  mean  those  properties,  a  class  is  ipso  facto  formed  con- 
taining all  objects  possessing  those  two  attributes." 

Occasionally  the  opposite  process  takes  place:  classification  precedes  the  formation 
of  general  name.  This  occurs  when  "we  have  thought  it  useful  for  the  regulation  of  our 
mental  operations,  that  a  certain  group  of  objects  should  be  thought  of  together."  Mill 
cites  as  an  example  the  classes,  orders,  etc.  of  Cuvier's  classification  of  plants  and 
animals.  Yet,  even  in  these  cases  the  resulting  classes  are,  "as  much  as  any  other 
classes,  constituted  by  certain  common  attributes,  and  their  names  are  significant  of 
those  attributes,  and  nothing  else." 

Comments:  In  fact,  classification  usually  precedes  the  definition  of  a  general  name  in 
terms  of  essential  attributes.  For  example,  the  meaning  of  'liquid'  is  more  than  the 
two  properties,  'perfect  molecular  mobility'  and  'inelasticity.'  Indeed  we  knew  what 
liquids  were  long  before  we  recognized  that  they  are  characterized  by  these  two  pro- 
perties. And  it  is  possible  that  in  the  future  we  might  discover  a  substance  having 
these  two  properties  that  we  are  not  willing  to  classify  as  a  liquid,  because  it  is 
different  from  liquids  in  too  many  other  respects. 

-45- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
We  initially  form  a  class  on  the  basis  of  certain  perceived  similarities  between  the 
members  of  the  class,  that  is,  on  the  basis  of  certain  common  properties.  However,  the 
resulting  general  name  connotes  more  than  the  properties  that  originally  motivated 
the  formation  of  the  class.  The  general  term  denotes  all  of  the  individuals  possessing 
the  originally  identified  common  attributes,  and  connotes  all  of  the  common  properties 
of  these  individuals. 

For  example,  the  class  of  liquids  is  probably  formed  initially  on  the  basis  of  certain 
unanalyzable  resemblances.  The  denotation  of  'liquid'  is  all  liquids,  and  its  connotation 
(in  the  wider  sense)  is  all  the  properties  of  liquids.  Among  these,  we  may  later  dis- 
cover, are  perfect  molecular  mobility  and  inelasticity.  If,  within  the  context  of  our 
knowledge,  these  two  properties  seem  the  most  characteristic  of  liquids,  then  we  are 
justified,  for  now,  in  defining  a  liquid  as  an  inelastic  substance  with  perfect  molecular 
mobility.  We  could  then  say  that,  within  the  context  of  our  knowledge,  these  attributes 
are  the  essential  attributes  of  liquids. 

2.    The  Predicables 

Summary:  "The  predicables  are  a  fivefold  division  of  General  Names,  not  grounded  as 
usual  on  a  difference  in  their  meaning,  that  is  in  the  attribute  which  they  connote,  but 
on  a  difference  in  the  kind  of  class  which  they  denote."  The  predicables,  handed  down 
from  Aristotle,  are: 

•  Genus 

•  Species 

•  Differentia 

•  Property 

•  Accident 

These  distinctions  do  not  apply  to  general  names  in  isolation;  they  refer  to  all  the  ways 
that  a  name  cai    be  a  predicate  in  a  proposition.    "The  words  genus,  species,  &c,  are 

-46- 


On  Classification  and  the  Predicables 
therefore  relative  terms;  they  are  names  applied  to  certain  predicates,  to  express  the 
relation  between  them  and  some  given  subject  ...." 

3.    Genus  and  Species 

Summary:  In  popular  usage  genus  and  species  are  relative  terms.  Thus,  "any  two 
classes,  one  of  which  includes  the  whole  of  the  other  and  more,  may  be  called  a  Genus 
and  Species."  For  example,  man  is  a  species  of  the  genus  animal,  and  mathematician 
is  a  species  of  the  genus  man. 

The  Aristotelian  logicians  used  these  terms  in  a  more  restricted  sense.  "It  was 
requisite,  according  to  their  theory,  that  genus  and  species  should  be  of  the  essence  of 
the  subject."  Thus,  man  and  brute  could  be  considered  coordinate  species  under  the 
genus  animal,  but  biped  would  not  be  considered  a  genus  with  respect  to  man;  it  would 
be  considered  a  property  or  accident  only.  Does  this  distinction  make  any  sense?  The 
distinction  is  important,  but  the  recourse  to  essence  confuses  the  issue. 

Comments:  Full  comments  follow  the  next  section. 
4.    Kinds  Have  a  Real  Existence  in  Nature 

Summary:  When  we  consider  the  classes  denoted  by  general  names,  they  seem  to  be  of 
two  kinds.  "There  are  some  classes,  the  things  contained  in  which  differ  from  other 
things  only  in  certain  particulars  which  may  be  numbered,  while  others  differ  in  more 
than  can  be  numbered,  more  even  than  we  need  ever  expect  to  know."  For  example, 
the  class  of  white  things  is  distinguished  by  no  common  properties  other  than  white- 
ness. "But  a  hundred  generations  have  not  exhausted  the  common  properties  of 
animals  and  of  plants,  of  sulphur  or  of  phosphorus;  nor  do  we  suppose  them  to  be 
exhaustible   ..." 

"The  differences  [on  which  classification  is  based]  are  made  by  nature,  in  both 
cases,  while  the  recognition  of  those  differences  as  grounds  of  classification  and  of 
naming  is,  equally  in  both  cases,  the  act  of  man  ..."    However,  in  the  first  case  (e.g., 

-47- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
white)  the  act  of  classification  is  motivated  by  convenience;  in  the  second  (e.g.,  sulfur) 
nature  requires  us  to  form  the  class:    "the  ends  of  language  and  of  classification  would 
be  subverted  if  no  notice  were  taken  of  the  difference."    Hence  the  latter  classes  are 
called  real  kinds,  and  the  former  not^real  kinds. 

The  Aristotelian  logicians  considered  only  real  kinds  to  be  genera  and  species.  In 
particular,  the  lowest  real  kind  to  which  an  individual  is  referable  is  called  its  species: 
the  species  of  Isaac  Newton  is  man.  Although  Newton  belongs  to  many  other  classes 
(e.g.,  mathematician  and  Englishman)  these  are  not  species.  The  sexes,  races,  etc. 
would  be  considered  not-real  kinds  if  their  differences  turn  out  to  be  reducible  to  a  few 
primary  differences;  if  not,  then  they  must  be  considered  real  kinds  (i.e.,  species). 

In  summary,  a  real  kind  is  a  class  "which  is  distinguished  from  all  other  classes  by 
an  indeterminate  multitude  of  properties  not  derivable  from  one  another."  A  real  kind 
is  a  genus  or  species  or  both.  A  genus  is  a  real  kind  which  is  divisible  into  other  real 
kinds. 

Comments:  The  crux  of  the  problem  with  Mill's  distinction  between  real  and  not-real 
kinds  can  be  seen  in  the  class  sulfur.  Mill  calls  this  a  real  kind,  since  we  will  never 
exhaust  the  list  of  properties  shared  by  all  pieces  of  sulfur.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is 
quite  possible  that  we  may  find  that  one  property,  say,  its  atomic  structure,  is  the 
cause  and  explanation  of  all  the  rest.  Then  we  would  no  longer  be  able  to  consider  sul- 
fur a  real  kind.  Thus,  if  we  can  find  a  finite  number  of  properties  that  explain  all  the 
rest  (i.e.,  if  we  can  define  the  class)  then  it  is  a  not-real  kind.  A  kind  remains  real  only 
in  so  far  as  we  are  ignorant  of  it. 

A  class  is  initially  demarcated  on  the  basis  of  a  finite  number  of  properties.  As  we 
learn  more  about  the  class  we  continue  to  be  aware  of  only  a  finite  number  of  its  pro- 
perties. If  all  the  known  properties  are  explainable  in  terms  of  just  a  few,  then  we  con- 
sider it  a  not-real  kind.  If  this  is  not  the  case,  and  we  suspect  there  is  an  "inexhausti- 
ble supply"  of  more  unexplainable  properties,  then  it  is  a  real  kind.    By  this  reasoning 

-4B- 


On  Classification  and  the  Predicables 
electron  is  not  a  real  kind,  because  we  believe  all  an  electron's  properties  are  explain- 
able by  a  few  quantum  numbers.   This  illustrates  the  fact  that  the  real/not-real  distinc- 
tion is  at  best  an  inessential  one  that  is  a  reflection  of  our  current  knowledge  of  the 
class.    It  would  probably  be  best  to  discard  the  distinction  altogether. 

5.    Differentia 

Summary:  The  word  differentia  "is  correlative  with  the  words  genus  and  species,  and 
...  signifies  the  attribute  which  distinguishes  a  given  species  from  every  other  species 
of  the  same  genus."  Can  we  use  any  attribute  that  will  distinguish  the  given  species? 
The  Aristotelian  logicians  say  "No;"  the  differentia  must  be  of  the  essence  of  the  sub- 
ject. Thus  rationality  could  be  considered  the  differentia  of  man;  that  he  cooks  his 
food  could  not  be,  since  it  is  only  an  accidental  property.  Mill  rejects  this  notion  of 
differentia  since  it  is  based  on  the  fallacious  idea  of  essence.  What  then  distinguishes 
the  differentia  from  other  properties?  Mill  observes  that  the  connotation  of  a  species 
includes  the  connotation  of  its  genus.  Therefore,  since  he  has  said  that  the  essence  of 
a  name  is  just  its  connotation,  he  concludes  that  "the  Differentia  is  that  which  must  be 
added  to  the  connotation  of  the  genus,  to  complete  the  connotation  of  the  species." 

Comments:  With  regard  to  the  notion  that  the  differentia  is  added  to  the  genus  to  yield 
the  species,  Joseph  (1906)  says,  "Provided  it  is  not  supposed  that  the  differentia  is 
added  to  the  common  character  of  the  'larger  class'  in  the  same  extraneous  way  that 
sugar  is  added  to  tea,  there  is  no  fresh  harm  in  this  mode  of  expressing  oneself."  But 
if  the  differentia  is  not  an  extraneous  property  added  to  the  genus,  then  what  is  it?  We 
are  inclined  to  say,  with  the  Aristotelians,  that  the  differentia  should  in  some  way  be 
essential. 

If  we  take  essence  not  in  the  medieval  sense  of  an  essential  substance,  but  in  the 
sense  of  those  properties  which  cause  or  explain  most  of  the  rest,  then  the  essence  can 
be  the  source  of  the  differentia.  Joseph  (1906)  suggests  the  following  criteria  for  the 
characteristics  which  form  the  differentia:    "these  characteristics  should  be  (a)  of  the 

-49- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
same  general  kind  for  each  type  within  one  genus,  or  ...  variations  upon  the  same 
theme,  in  order  to  exhibit  the  mutual  relations  of  agreement  and  divergence  among 
the  various  types;  (b)  important,  or  ...  pervasive:  that  is,  they  should  connect  them- 
selves in  as  many  ways  as  possible  with  the  other  characters  of  the  species."  These 
issues  will  be  considered  further  when  we  discuss  definition,  in  the  next  chapter. 

6.   Property 

Summary:  In  the  Aristotelian  theory  genus  and  differentia  are  of  the  essence  of  the 
subject.  In  contrast,  properties  and  accidents  are  non-essential.  The  difference 
between  properties  and  accidents  is  that  properties  follow  necessarily  from  the 
essence,  whereas  accidents  do  not.  Thus,  that  man  uses  language  follows  necessarily 
from  his  having  a  rational  faculty,  and  is  thus  a  property.  That  man  has  five  fingers  on 
each  hand,  follows  neither  from  his  rationality  nor  his  animality,  and  is  thus  an 
accident. 

"One  attribute  may  follow  from  another  in  two  ways;  and  there  are  consequently  two 
kinds  of  [property].  It  may  follow  as  a  conclusion  follows  premises,  or  it  may  follow  as 
an  effect  follows  a  cause."  An  example  of  the  former  is  the  property  of  triangles  that 
their  angles  sum  to  180  degrees;  an  example  of  the  latter  is  the  property  of  man  that 
he  understands  language. 

Comments:  Since  the  distinction  between  essential  and  nonessential  attributes  is  a 
contextual  distinction,  the  distinction  between  properties  and  accidents  is  also  contex- 
tual. If  we  take  the  essence  of  a  name  to  be  those  attributes  which  explain  or  cause 
most  of  the  rest,  then  the  properties  are  those  attributes  that  the  essence  does 
explain,  and  the  accidents  are  those  attributes  that  i.t  doesn't.  Frequently  an  accident 
is  an  unexplained  property.  An  accident  may  also  be  an  attribute  which,  for  reasons  of 
cognitive  economy,  we  have  chosen  not  to  include  in  the  essence. 


-50- 


On  Classification  and  the  Predicables 
7.   Accident 

Summary:  Accidents  are  divided  into  two  classes,  separable  and  inseparable.  Separ- 
able accidents  are  attributes  that  are  universal  to  the  species,  but  not  necessary  to  it. 
For  example,  so  far  as  we  know,  all  crows  are  black,  but  this  does  not  follow  necessarily 
from  crowness.  And,  if  we  discovered  birds  otherwise  like  crows  but  being  white,  we 
would  call  them  'white  crows';  we  would  not  say  that  they're  not  crows. 

"Separable  Accidents  are  those  which  are  found,  in  point  of  fact,  to  be  sometimes 
absent  from  the  species;  which  are  not  only  not  necessary,  but  not  even  universal." 
For  example  being  red-haired  is  a  separable  accident  of  man,  since  some,  but  not  all, 
men  are  red-haired.  Similarly,  those  attributes  that  are  not  even  constant  in  an  indivi- 
dual, such  as  to  be  sitting  or  walking,  must  be  considered  separable  accidents. 


-51- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
a   Of  Definition 

1 .   A  Definition,  What 

Summary:  "The  simplest  and  most  correct  notion  of  a  definition  is,  a  proposition 
declaratory  of  the  meaning  of  a  word,  namely,  either  the  meaning  which  it  bears  in 
common  acceptation,  or  that  which  the  speaker  or  writer,  for  the  particular  purposes 
of  his  discourse,  intends  to  annex  to  it." 

Notice  that  this  means  that  words  with  no  meaning,  such  as  proper  names,  are  not 
susceptible  to  definition.  "In  the  case  of  connotative  names,  the  meaning  ...  is  the  con- 
notation, and  the  definition  of  a  connotative  name  is  the  proposition  which  declares  its 
connotation."  This  is  most  commonly  done  by  predicating  of  the  name  intended  to  be 
defined  "another  name  or  names  of  known  signification,  which  connote  the  same  aggre- 
gation of  attributes."  Since  analysis  means  the  resolution  of  a  "complex  whole  into  the 
elements  of  which  it  is  compounded,"  it  can  be  seen  that  a  definition  is  an  analysis. 

Comments:  It  is  certainly  counter-intuitive  to  say  that  proper  names  have  no  meaning, 
yet  this  follows  from  Mill's  notion  of  connotation.  As  discussed  earlier  (Chapter  2,  Sec- 
tion 4  and  Chapter  6,  Section  3),  if  we  take  connotation  in  the  wider  sense  then  we 
must  conclude  that  individuals  have  a  very  rich  connotation.  Thus,  as  the  connotation 
of  a  name  grows,  its  extension  narrows  until  the  name  becomes  individual.  Thus,  as  will 
be  discussed  below,  proper  names  can  be  defined  in  the  same  ways  as  general  names: 
by  ostension  (pointing)  or  by  genus  and  differentia. 

If  we  take  connotation  in  the  wide  sense,  as  referring  to  all  the  properties  possessed 
in  common  by  the  members  of  the  denotation,  then  it  is  clear  that  a  definition  cannot 
cite  all  of  the  connotation.  This  would  not  be  a  definition.  Rather,  it  would  be  a  catalog 
of  everything  known  about  the  subject,  and  it  would  still  be  incomplete.  For  a 
definition  to  serve  the  goals  of  cognitive  economy  it  must  condense  our  knowledge  of 
the  subject.   Thus  a  definition  should  be  in  terms  of  the  essential  characteristics  of  the 


-52- 


Of  Definition 
thing  defined.    One  way  to  accomplish  this  is  to  formulate  the  definition  in  terms  of 
genus  and  differentia. 

Several  differences  should  be  noted  between  this  notion  of  definitions  and  that  most 
common  among  modern  logicians.  The  modern  view  is  that  a  definition  is  merely  a  dev- 
ice for  specifying  the  meaning  of  a  word  or  phrase;  it  provides  a  sort  of  shorthand  for  a 
longer  phrase.  As  a  result,  the  word  defined  and  its  definition  are  completely  inter- 
changeable. 

The  view  here  is  that  the  meaning  of  the  name  is  probably  already  known;  in  any 
case  the  function  of  the  definition  is  not  to  inform  us  of  the  meaning  of  the  name.  If  we 
don't  know  what  a  liquid  is,  then  being  told  that  it  is  an  incompressible  substance  with 
perfect  molecular  mobility,  will  not  help  much.  Similarly,  if  we  don't  know  the  meaning 
of  man,  then  being  told  the  definition  'rational  animal'  won't  be  very  useful;  we  still 
won't  even  know  what  a  man  looks  like.  Since  a  definition  does  not  come  close  to 
exhausting  the  meaning  of  a  name,  it  can  be  seen  that  a  name  and  its  definition  are  not 
interchangeable. 

A  correct  definition  results  from  a  scientific  analysis  of  the  things  named.  The  50a! 
of  this  analysis  is  to  determine  the  essential  attributes  of  these  things.  Of  course,  as 
our  scientific  knowledge  expands,  we  may  find  that  in  a  wider  context  the  attributes  we 
thought  were  essential  can  no  longer  be  considered  so.  We  will  then  have  to  find  attri- 
butes that  are  essential  in  this  wider  context.  Thus,  a  definition  is  a  kind  of  scientific 
law  and  must  be  validated  like  other  scientific  law. 

2.    What  Names  can  be  Defined? 

Summary:  "A  name,  ...  whether  concrete  or  abstract,  admits  of  definition,  provided  we 
are  able  to  analyze,  that  is,  to  distinguish  into  parts,  the  attribute  or  set  of  attributes 
which  constitute  the  meaning  both  of  the  concrete  name  and  of  the  corresponding 
abstract:  if  a  set  of  attributes,  by  enumerating  them;  if  a  single  attribute,  by  dissect- 
ing the  fact  or  phenomenon  (whether  of  perception  or  internal  consciousness)  which  is 

-53- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
the    foundation    of    the    attribute."    "The    only    names    which    are    unsusceptible    of 
definition,  because  their  meaning  is  unsusceptible  of  analysis,  are  the  names  of  the 
simple  feelings  themselves."    For  these  "we  are  obliged  to  make  a  direct  appeal  to  the 
personal  experience  of  the  individual  whom  we  address." 

3.  Complete  versus  Incomplete  Definitions 

Summary:  The  only  scientific  definition  of  a  name  is  one  which  declares  the  whole  of 
the  facts  that  the  name  involves  in  it  signification.  Most  people  do  not  want  such  a 
scientific  definition  however;  they  are  seeking  a  guide  to  the  correct  use  of  a  term. 
There  are  two  sorts  of  these  unscientific  definitions.  The  first  is  an  essential  but  incom- 
plete definition,  which  defines  a  name  on  the  basis  of  some  but  not  all  of  the  connota- 
tion of  the  name.  An  example  is  the  definition,  'Man  is  the  rational  animal'.  "Such 
definitions  ...  are  always  liable  to  be  overthrown  by  the  discovery  of  new  objects  in 
nature."  For  example,  if  we  discovered  a  species  of  rational  fish,  we  might  have  to 
revise  our  definition  to  'Man  is  the  rational  mammal'. 

Incomplete  definitions  are  what  the  logicians  had  in  mind  when  they  said  a  definition 
should  be  by  genus  and  differentia.  The  differentia  is  seldom  all  that  is  peculiar  about 
the  species;  it  is  usually  just  one  of  many  peculiar  attributes. 

Comments:  In  fact,  almost  all  practical  definitions  are  incomplete.  As  discussed  previ- 
ously; (Section  1)  a  definition  does  not  simply  define  an  abbreviation  for  a  set  of  attri- 
butes; it  specifies  the  essential  attributes  —  those  distinguishing  attributes  that  best 
explain  the  other  distinguishing  attributes.  Guidelines  for  the  choice  of  a  differentia 
have  been  discussed  in  the  commentary  accompanying  Chapter  7,  Section  5. 

4.  Complete  Definitions  versus  Descriptions 

Summary:  The  second  kind  of  unscientific  definition  is  the  accidental  definition,  or 
description,  which  bases  the  definition  of  a  name  on  something  which  is  not  part  of  the 
connotation  at  all,  but  still  "enables  us  to  discriminate  the  things  denoted  by  the  name 

-54- 


Of  Definition 
from  all  other  things."  "What  would  otherwise  be  a  mere  description  may  be  raised  to 
the  rank  of  a  real  definition  by  the  peculiar  purpose  which  the  speaker  or  writer  has  in 
view."  In  this  case  the  author  is  in  fact  giving  to  some  general  name,  "without  altering 
its  denotation,  a  special  connotation,"  and  then  defining  the  name  in  terms  of  this  spe- 
cial connotation.  An  example  is  Cuvier's  definition  of  Man  as  "a  mammiferous  animal 
having  two  hands."  "Scientific  definitions,  whether  they  are  definitions  of  scientific 
terms,  of  of  common  terms  used  in  a  scientific  sense,  are  almost  always  of  [this]  kind;" 
"their  main  purpose  is  to  serve  as  landmarks  of  scientific  classification.  And  since  the 
classifications  in  any  science  are  continually  modified  as  scientific  knowledge  advances, 
the  definitions  in  the  sciences  are  also  constantly  varying." 

Comments:  This  discussion,  although  based  on  Mill's  incorrect  idea  of  connotation, 
correctly  points  out  the  contextual  nature  of  definitions:  the  correct  definition  of  a 
term  depends  on  the  context  in  which  that  definition  is  to  be  used.  This  does  not  mean 
that  definitions  are  arbitrary;  rather,  it  means  that  the  correctness  of  a  definition  is 
relative  to  a  context.  Within  a  given  context  of  knowledge  and  purpose,  a  correct 
definition  cites  those  properties  that  explain  and  make  possible  the  greatest  number  of 
other  attributes. 

5.    Real  Definitions  versus  Nominal  Definitions 

Summary:  Mill  next  turns  to  an  ancient  doctrine,  that  there  are  two  kinds  of 
definitions:  definitions  of  names  and  definitions  of  things.  "The  former  are  intended  to 
explain  the  meaning  of  a  term;  the  latter,  the  nature  of  a  thing,  the  last  being  incom- 
parably the  most  important."  Mill  notes  that  the  nominalist  trend  in  his  time  was  tend- 
ing to  discard  the  notion  of  real  definitions  (definitions  of  things)  in  favor  of  nominal 
definitions  (definitions  of  names).   [This  trend  has  continued  to  the  present.] 

Mill  takes  all  definitions  to  be  nominal.  "We  apprehend  that  no  definition  is  ever 
intended  to  'explain  and  unfold  the  nature  of  a  thing.'  "  His  basis  for  this  is  that  no  one 
has  ever  been  able  to  distinguish  a  definition  of  a  tiling  from  a  proposition  about  that 

-55- 


Mill's  Logic:  Of  Names  and  Propositions 
thing.  Hence  he  concludes  that  "All  definitions  are  of  names,  and  of  names  only  ...." 
But  in  some  definitions,  "besides  explaining  the  meaning  of  the  word,  it  is  intended  to 
be  implied  that  there  exists  a  thing  corresponding  to  the  word."  For  example,  the 
definitions  of  geometrical  figures  both  give  names  to  these  figures  and  assert  that  they 
exist.  If  they  didn't  do  the  latter,  it  would  be  impossible  to  deduce  true  theorems  from 
them.  For  example,  when  we  say  'a  triangle  is  a  figure  bounded  by  three  straight  lines', 
we  are  really  making  two  statements  in  one  package: 

1.  There  exists  a  figure  bounded  by  three  straight  lines. 

2.  We  will  call  such  a  figure  by  the  name  'triangle'. 

Comments:  I  disagree  with  Mill  on  this  point.  If  we  consider  a  definition  such  as  'Man  is 
the  rational  animal'  it  becomes  apparent  that  if  we  hadn't  previously  known  the  mean- 
ing of  'man'  then  this  definition  wouldn't  have  been  very  useful.  We  still  wouldn't  know 
the  most  rudimentary  things  about  men,  such  as  their  appearance.  Rather,  when  we 
assert  'Man  is  the  rational  animal'  we  are  generally  assuming  that  the  hearer  knows  the 
meaning  of  'man'.  This  means  that  he  is  aware  of  a  substantial  part  of  its  denotation 
and  connotation.  That  is,  he  can  recognize  men  when  he  encounters  them,  and  he 
knows  a  number  of  the  properties  of  men. 

What,  then,  is  the  purpose  of  a  definition  such  as  'Man  is  the  rational  animal'?  Since 
it  is  not  to  inform  us  of  the  meaning  of  the  word  'man',  we  can  only  conclude  that  it  is 
to  inform  us  of  some  fundamental  fact  about  men.  Thus  against  Mill  I  claim  that,  with  a 
few  trivial  exceptions,  there  are  no  nominal  definitions;  the  only  definitions  of  interest 
in  science  and  logic  are  real  definitions. 

Mill's  objection  to  real  definitions,  that  there  is  no  way  to  distinguish  a  real  definition 
from  any  other  proposition  asserting  a  property  of  the  thing,  can  be  answered  as  fol- 
lows. He  is  right  in  the  following  sense:  there  is  no  way,  once  and  forever,  to  pick  out 
one  or  a  few  of  an  object's  properties  as  the  defining  properties.    This  would  imply 


-56- 


Of  Definition 
omniscience  about  the  thing.    As  discussed  previously,  a  real  definition  should  be  in 
terms  of  essential  properties.   But  which  properties  are  essential  and  which  are  not  is  a 
contextual   issue:     it  must   be   settled  relative   to   the   available   knowledge   and  the 
intended  use  of  the  definition. 

6.    Mathematical  Definitions 

Summary:  What  is  the  meaning  of  a  mathematical  definition?  Consider  a  definition 
such  as  'A  circle  is  a  plane  figure  bounded  by  a  line  all  the  points  of  which  are  at  an 
equal  distance  from  a  given  point  within  it'.  This  cannot  be  considered  an  assertion 
about  real  circles,  since  in  no  real  circle  are  the  radii  exactly  equal.  Some  people  have 
said  "that  the  subject-matter  of  mathematics,  and  of  every  other  demonstrative  sci- 
ence, is  not  things  as  they  really  exist,  but  abstractions  of  the  mind.  A  geometrical 
line  is  a  line  without  breadth;  but  no  such  line  exists  in  nature;  it  is  a  notion  merely 
suggested  to  the  mind  by  its  experiences  of  nature." 

Mill  disagrees  with  this  view,  since  he  claims  the  mind  "cannot  conceive  length 
without  breadth;  it  can  only,  in  contemplating  objects,  attend  to  their  length, 
exclusively  of  their  other  sensible  qualities,  and  so  determine  what  properties  may  be 
predicated  of  them  in  virtue  of  their  length  alone."  Thus,  "the  postulate  involved  in  the 
geometrical  definition  of  a  line  is  the  real  existence,  not  of  length  without  breadth,  but 
merely  of  length,  that  is,  of  long  objects." 

Comments:  Another  way  of  saying  this  is  that  a  line  is  a  thing  whose  breadth  is  negligi- 
ble. When  is  a  thing's  breadth  negligible?  That  depends  on  circumstances;  for  some 
purposes  a  thing's  breadth  will  be  negligible,  while  for  others  it  won't.  Thus,  whether  a 
real  thing  is  considered  a  line  or  not  is  a  contextual  issue.  This  is  the  case  with  most 
mathematical  concepts.  All  mathematical  concepts  are  models  of  the  real  world  that 
attend  to  the  significant  aspects,  and  ignore  the  negligible  aspects,  of  some  real 
phenomena.  Indeed,  mathematics  can  be  defined  as  the  systematic  ignoring  of  the 
negligible . 

-57- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
7.    Definitions  Grounded  on  Knowledge  of  Corresponding  Things 

Summary:  "Although,  according  to  the  opinion  here,  definitions  are  properly  of  names 
only,  and  not  of  things,  it  does  not  follow  from  this  that  definitions  are  arbitrary.  How 
to  define  a  name,  may  not  only  be  an  inquiry  of  considerable  difficulty  and  intricacy, 
but  may  involve  considerations  going  deep  into  the  nature  of  the  things  which  are 
denoted  by  the  name."  These  inquiries  are  not  "so  much  to  determine  what  is,  as  what 
should  be,  the  meaning  of  a  name  ...." 

It  often  happens  that  names  are  applied  to  things  solely  on  the  basis  of  resem- 
blance; the  names  have  no  distinct  connotations  in  the  minds  of  their  users.  "This,  as 
we  have  seen,  is  the  law  which  even  the  mind  of  the  philosopher  must  follow,  in  giving 
names  to  the  simple  elementary  feelings  of  our  nature;  but,  where  the  things  to  be 
named  are  complex  wholes,  a  philosopher  is  not  content  with  noticing  a  general  resem- 
blance; he  examines  what  the  resemblance  consists  in[,]  and  he  only  gives  the  same 
name  to  things  which  resemble  one  another  in  the  same  definite  particulars.  The  philo- 
sopher, therefore,  habitually  employs  his  general  names  with  a  definite  connotation." 
To  accomplish  this  requires  an  inquiry  into  matters  of  fact. 

"In  giving  a  distinct  connotation  to  the  general  name,  the  philosopher  will  endeavor 
to  fix  upon  such  attributes  as,  while  they  are  common  to  all  the  things  usually  denoted 
by  the  name,  are  also  of  greatest  importance  in  themselves;  either  directly,  or  from 
the  number,  the  conspicuousness,  or  the  interesting  character,  of  the  consequences  to 
which  they  lead."  He  will  select  those  differentiae  that  lead  to  the  greatest  number  of 
interesting  properties.  But  this  may  be  "one  of  the  most  difficult  of  scientific  prob- 
lems" —  and  one  of  the  most  important.  "[S]ome  of  the  most  profound  and  most  valu- 
able investigations"  in  philosophy  have  "offered  themselves  under  the  guise  of  ••• 
inquiries  into  the  definition  of  a  name." 


-58- 


REFERENCES 
IL   REFERENCES 

Aristotle.    Categories,  On  Interpretation,  and  Prior  Analytics  (trans.  H.  P.  Cooke).    Loeb 
Classical  Library,  Cambridge:  Harvard  University  Press,  1973. 

Creighton,  J.  E.   An  Introductory  Logic.   New  York:  MacMillan,  1906. 

De  Morgan,  A.  Formal  Logic:  or,  The  Calculus  of  Inference,  Necessary  and  Probable. 
London:  Taylor  and  Walton,  1847. 

Flew,  A.   A  Dictionary  of  Philosophy.    New  York:  St.  Martin's  Press,  1979. 

Frank,  P.  G.    The  Validation  of  Scientific  Theories.    New  York:  Collier  Books,  1954. 

Hempel,  C.  G.   A  Logical  Appraisal  of  Operationism,  in  Frank  (1954). 

Jevons,  W.  S.  Elementary  Lessons  in  Logic:  Deductive  and  Inductive.  New  York:  Mac- 
Millan, 1919. 

Joseph,  H.  W.  B.  An  Introduction  to  Logic.  Oxford:  Clarendon  Press,  1906,  second  edi- 
tion. 

Killick,  A.  H.  The  Student's  Handbook  Synoptical  and  Explanatory  of  Mr.  J.  S.  Mill's 
System  of  Logic.  London:  Longmans,  Green,  and  Co.,  1909. 

Mill,  J.  S.  A  System  of  Logic,  Ratiocinative  and  Inductive,  being  a  connected  view  of 
the  principles  of  evidence  and  the  methods  of  scientific  investigation.  London: 
Longmans,  Green,  and  Co.,  1843,  eighth  edition. 

Mill,  J.  S.  John  Stuart  Mill's  Philosophy  of  Scientific  Method,  edited  with  an  introduc- 
tion by  Ernest  Nagel,  New  York:  Hafner,  1950. 

Nozick,  R.  Philosophical  Explanations.  Cambridge:  The  Belknap  Press  of  Harvard 
University  Press,  1981. 

Peikoff,  L.  The  Analytic-Synthetic  Dichotomy,  in  Rand  (1979). 

Quine,  W.  V.    From  a  Logical  Point  of  View.    Cambridge:  1953. 


-59- 


Mill's  Logic:    Of  Names  and  Propositions 
Rand,  A.    Introduction  to  Objectivist  Epistemology.    New  York:  New  American  Library, 
1979. 

Whately,   R.    Elements  of  Logic.    London:   Longmans,   Green,  Reader  and  Dyer,    186B, 
ninth  edition. 


-60- 


INITIAL  DISTRIBUTION  LIST 


Defense  Technical  Information  Center  2 

Cameron  Station 
Alexandria,  VA  22314 

Dudley  Knox  Library  2 

Code  0142 

Naval  Postgraduate  School 

Monterey,  CA  93943 

Office  of  Research  Administration  1 

Code  012A 

Naval  Postgraduate  School 

Monterey,  CA  93943 

Chairman,  Code  52Hq  40 

Department  of  Computer  Science 
Naval  Postgraduate  School 
Monterey,  CA  93943 

Professor  Bruce  J.  MacLennan,  Code  52M1  12 

Department  of  Computer  Science 
Naval  Postgraduate  School 
Monterey,  CA  93943 

Dr.  Robert  Grafton  1 

Code  433 

Office  of  Naval  Research 

800  N.  Quincy 

Arlington,  VA  22217 

A.  Dain  Samples  1 

Computer  Science  Division  -  EECS 
University  of  California  at  Berkeley 
Berkeley,  CA  94720 

Professor  Douglas  Smith,  Code  52Sc  1 

Computer  Science  Department 
Naval  Postgraduate  School 
Monterey,  CA  93943 


-61- 


DUDLEY  KNOX  LIBRARY 
III  II  II  I 


3  2768  00337507  2