Skip to main content

Full text of "The critics of Herbartianism : and other matter contributory to the study of the Herbartian question"

See other formats


V 


U.  C.  L  A. 
EDUC.  DEPT. 


THE  LIBRARY 

OF 

THE  UNIVERSITY 

OF  CALIFORNIA 

LOS  ANGELES 


Digitized  by  tlie  Internet  Arcliive 

in  2007  witli  funding  from 

IVIicrosoft  Corporation 


littp://www.arcliive.org/details/criticsoflierbartOOIiaywiala 


THE   CRITICS    OF    HERBARTIANISM 

AND  OTHER  MATTER  CONTRIBUTORY  TO  THE 

STUDY  OF  THE   HERBARTIAN  QUESTION 


OTHER    WORKS  BY  DR.   F.   H.   HAYWARD. 

THE    ETHICAL   PHILOSOPHY   OF 
SIDGWICK. 

48.  6d. 

"  A  book  of  great  value  to  students  of  ethics." — Tlie  A  thenoeum. 

THE   STUDENT'S   HERBART. 
Is.  6d.  net. 

"This  delightful  account  of  Herbartianism." — Secondary 
Education. 

THE   REFORM  OF  MORAL  AND  BIBLICAL 
EDUCATION. 

48.  6d. 
"An  extremely  clever,  even  brilliant  book." — Education. 

[For  other  andfuUer  press  notices  see  end  of  mlume.'] 


^^  INTEREST  IS    THE  GREATEST   WORD   IN  EDUCATION^' 


THE 


CRITICS   OF   HERBARTIANISM 


AND  OTHER  MATTER  CONTRIBUTORY  TO  THE 


STUDY  OF  THE  HERBARTIAiN  QUESTION 


F.  H.  HAYWARD 

D.LiT.,  M.A.,  B.Sc.  (LoND.),  B.A.  (Cantab.) 

FELLOW  OF  THE  COLLEGE  OF  PRECEPTORS 


ASSISTED    BY 


M.    E.    THOMAS 

BATTERSEA    POLYTECHNIC 


LONDON 

SWAN    SONNENSCHEIN   &   CO.,  LTD. 

PATERNOSTER   SQUARE,  E.G. 


EDUC.  DEPT, 


U.  C.  L  A. 
EDUC.  DEPT, 


Library 

('  r  ^> .    7  . 

PREFACE. 


The  following  work  was  begun  at  Cambridge  as  a  thesis 
for  the  London  Doctorate  of  Letters,  was  continued  at  the 
Thuringian  centre  of  Herbartianism,  and  was  completed 
in  a  West  of  England  district  where,  with  every  passing 
day,  the  vital  need  for  an  Herbartian  propaganda  has 
become  to  the  author  more  and  more  pressing  and 
manifest. 

Scotsmen,^  with  an  educational  tradition  of  some  sort 
at  their  back,  may  afford  or  affect  to  disparage  Herbar- 
tianism, but  ft  Southron  who  knows  the  paralytic  con- 
dition of  education  in  his  own  country  and  district  will,  if 
wise,  hesitate  to  stand  aloof  from  a  system  which — alone 
among  systems  or  rudiments  of  systems — can  inspire, 
move  and  fascinate.  The  sun  in  the  heavens  is,  after  all, 
a  more  useful  luminary  than  any  nebula  to  be  generated 
a  billion  years  hence  by  the  clash  of  boreal  or  other 
meteorites. 

The  man  who  has  read  Herbart's  educational  works 
unmoved  has  read  them  either  without  understanding 
or  with  prejudice.  Of  Herbart's  psychology  one  may 
perhaps  say  with  some  justification  : — 

Shall  I  take  a  thing  so  blind, 
Embrace  her  as  my  natural  good, 
Or  crash  her,  like  a  vice  of  blood, 

tJpon  the  threshold  of  the  mind  ? 

^  Mr.  Darroch  is  dealt  with  in  the  Appendix. 

100G227 


vi  Preface 

But  Herbart's  educational  writings  are  another  matter. 
The  man  who  has  been  saved  from  sin  will  hesitate  to 
revile  the  means  of  his  salvation ;  the  man  who  has  found 
educational  light  in  the  pages  of  Herbart  will  hesitate  to 
call  the  light  an  illusion.  Extinguish  Herbartianism  and 
you  extinguish  for  a  century  the  hopes  of  education. 
Herbart  fascinates  ;    his  critics  do  not. 

Two  Herbartians  have  recently  died,  Professor  Lazarus 
and  Mr.  F.  G.  Eooper,  The  writer  cannot  avoid  taking 
the  opportunity  of  referring  to  the  educational  loss  in- 
volved in  the  death  of  the  latter.  The  ranks  of  ofl&cial 
educationists  are  distinctly  poorer  now  that  he  is  gone 
from  among  us. 

A  remark  as  to  the  use  of  the  term  "  Herbartianism  ". 
Purists  may  protest,  but  there  is  real  need  of  a  word  suf- 
ficiently general  to  embrace  the  entire  school  of  thought 
to  which  Ziller,  Dorpfeld  and  dozens  of  other  German 
thinkers,  and  a  fair  sprinkling  of  thinkers  outside  Germany, 
belong  or  have  belonged.  Professor  Adams,  Dr.  Eckoff 
and  other  writers  have  deliberately  employed  the  term 
"  Herbartianism,"  and  the  present  writer  therefore  feels 
but  few  scruples  of  conscience  in  following  suit. 

Again,  the  use  of  "  stupid "  as  a  translation  of 
"  stumpfsinnig "  is  not  without  its  drawbacks.  The 
writer  is  conscious  of  them  ;  having  said  so  much  he 
has  here  said  enough. 

The  work  is  not  precisely  a  unity,  it  is  rather  a  collection 
of  matter  dealing  with  the  historical  and  polemical  aspects 
of  Herbartianism.  British  educationists  will,  sooner  or 
later,  have  to  come  to  a  decision  upon  their  attitude  towards 
this  question,  and  it  is  hoped  that  the  matter  of  the  present 
volume  will  be  of  some  assistance  to  them  in  the  task. 
They  cannot,  at  any  rate,  complain  that  the  weaknesses, 
or  supposed  weaknesses,  of  Herbartianism  have  been  con- 


Preface  rii 

cealed.  At  last  we  know  the  worst ;  and  now  that  the 
worst  is  known  some  of  us  feel  that  the  best  shines 
brightly.  However,  be  it  repeated,  the  book  is  a  series 
of  contributions  rather  than  a  definite  unity.  But,  in 
view  of  the  fact  that  British  educational  thought  seems, 
for  the  moment,  to  have  a  predilection  for  crystallising 
itself  in  books  of  heterogeneous  essays,^  the  imperfections 
of  the  present  collection  may  perhaps  be  pardoned  if  not 
applauded. 

The  peculiar  form  of  the  Natorp  section  is  due  to  the 
fact  that  it  was  printed  separately  from  the  rest. 

Miss  Thomas  is  responsible  for  the  sections  on  Vogel 
and  Linde,  and  desires  to  express  her  appreciation  of  the 
help  given  by  Miss  A.  Kirby,  B.A.,  of  Pljrmouth  High 
School.  Miss  Thomas  has  also  read  through  the  whole 
work,  and  made  many  useful  suggestions  on  matters  of 
detail. 

Several  of  the  author's  Bristol  friends  have  again  helped 
him  by  reading  proofs ;  so  also  has  Mr.  J.  W.  Besley,  the 
able  Master  of  Moorland  School,  Okehampton  ;  Professor 
Alexander  and  Miss  Catherine  Dodd  (Owens'  College, 
Manchester)  also  deserve  his  thanks ;  and  to  Mr.  E.  H. 
Carter,  M.A.  (Board  of  Education),  whose  soundness  of 
judgment  and  knowledge  of  German  educational  thought 
have  been  of  much  assistance,  the  author  wishes  to  tender 
his  warm  gratitude. 

F.  H.  H. 

Okehampton,  June^  1903. 


1  Teaching  and  Organisation  (Longmans) ;  National  Education  (Murray) ; 
The  Nation's  Need  ^Constable),  etc.,  etc.,  etc. 


CONTENTS. 

Prbfacb ^ 

PART      I.  Introduction  to  the  Critics  op  Hebbabtiahibm       .  1 

PART    II.  Historical  Survey— 

1.  Herbart  (1776-1841) 86 

2.  Outline  of  Herbart's  Doctrines      ....  89 
3-5.  The  Revival  of  Herbartianism — 

Volkmar  Stoy  (1815-85) 48 

Priedrich  Wilhelm  Dorpfeld  (1824-93)      .         .  46 

Tuiskon  Ziller  (1817-82) 49 

6.  Outline  of  Ziller's  Doctrines 53 

7.  Reaction  and  Controversy 86 

8.  More  Controversy 62 

9.  Present  Position  of  Herbartianism  in  Germany   •  65 

10.  Herbartianism  in  Britain 69 

11.  Herbartianism  in  America  and  Elsewhere    .        .  76 
PART  III.  Herbartian  Literature  in  English    ....  77 

(1)  Translations 78 

(2)  Expositions  of  Herbartianism  as  Distinguished 

from  Translations      .        .        ...        .         .80 

(3)  Original  Works  Showing  the  Influence  of  Her- 

bp,rtian  Thought 83 

PART  IV.  The  Critics  op  Herbartianism — 

Section         I.  Dittes ,98 

Section       II.  Wesendonck 107 

Section     III.  Bartels 112 

Section     IV.  Ostermann 11? 

Section        V.  Rrchter 186 

Section     VI.  Vogel 130 

Section    VII.  Sallwiirk 147 

Section  VIII.  Hubatsch 164 

Section     IX.  Drews 168 

Section       X.  Christinger 166 

Section     XI.  Bergemann 169 

Section    XII.  Linde 178 

Section  XIII.  Natorp 178 

Section  XIV.  Kunz 203 

APPENDIX.     Propessob  Darboch  on  Hebbabtianism  .        .        .  209 

Index  I ^16 

Index  II 219 


PART  I. 

INTEODUCTION    TO    THE    CRITICS    OF 
HERBARTIANISM. 

DuBiNG  the  last  twenty  years  two  phenomena  have  been  notice- 
able to  observers  of  the  educational  world — a  steady  increase  in 
the  inj&uence  of  the  Herbartian  system,  and  a  series  of  vigorous 
attacks  upon  that  system  from  various  quarters  of  the  Father- 
land. The  former  phenomenon  has  been  patent  to  all,  the 
second  to  those  who  have  followed  the  course  of  events  abroad. 
It  is  Germany,  the  laud  in  which  Herbartianism  is  indigenous, 
which  has  presented  the  world  with  supposed  antidotes. 

These  supposed  antidotes,  it  would  be  no  great  exaggeration  to 
say,  have  received  no  notice  whatever  in  this  country.  Never  very 
enthusiastic  over  educational  problems,  especially  unenthusiastic 
over  such  as  are  not  obviously  "practical,"  the  British  nation 
as  a  whole,  and  many  even  of  its  professional  educationists, 
have  passed  two  decades  unconscious  of  the  fact  that  the  most 
complete  system  of  education  hitherto  given  to  the  world  has 
been  going  through  a  period  of  keen  hostile  criticism.  Even 
America,  where  Herbartianism  has  attained  a  position  of  honour 
and  influence,  knows  little  of  the  battles  it  has  to  fight  in  the 
home  of  its  birth. 

But  even  on  the  English  horizon  there  are  bright  spots. 
Herbartianism  itself  is  being  studied,  even  if  its  critics  are 
being  ignored.  This  is  as  it  should  be.  Whatever  its  alleged 
weaknesses,  Herbartianism,  as  even  its  enemies  admit,i  has  great 

1  Natorp,  Herhart,  Pestalozzi  und  die  heutigen  Aufgaben  der  Erziehungs- 
lehre.     Preface. 

I 


The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


stimulating  power,  and  can  teach  us  much.  May-be  it  is  not 
destined  to  survive  for  ever  as  the  rounded  and  completed 
system  which  it  appears  in  the  eyes  of  its  admirers.  Yet  the 
student  of  its  principles  is  wanting  in  ingenuousness  who  refuses 
homage  to  the  greatness  of  its  services. 

It  must,  therefore,  be  regarded  as  a  promising  fact  that  works 
expository  of  Herbart — such  as  those  of  Mr.  and  Mrs.  Felkin — 
are  being  published  and  read  to  an  increasing  extent.  These 
books,  it  is  true,  rarely  touch  upon  the  supposed  weaker  sides 
of  Herbartianism,  and  still  more  seldom  deal  historically  with 
the  criticisms  to  which  the  system  has  been  exposed.^  But  the 
reason  is  clear.  To  criticise  Herbart  would  have  been  useless 
until  his  name  and  his  principles  were  known.  It  is  impos- 
sible to  criticise  the  non-existent,  and  a  few  years  ago 
Herbartianism  among  us  was  virtually  in  this  condition.  The 
very  name  of  its  founder  was  only  known  in  narrow  philo- 
sophical circles  as  that  of  a  philosopher  somewhat  akin  to 
Locke,  not  as  that  of  an  educational  writer  of  first  rank.  But 
now  this  has  changed.  Herbartianism  is  in  a  measure  known, 
and  the  English  students  who  yearly  visit  Germany  in  general 
and  Jena  in  particular  seem  likely,  either  as  friends  or  as  foes, 
to  spread  its  fame  in  widening  circles. 

The  following  attempt  to  give  an  account  of  the  chief  criti- 
cisms of  Herbartianism  is  therefore  at  the  present  moment  not 
perhaps  untimely.  It  may  prove  of  service  to  the  more  thought- 
ful among  our  few  educational  students  by  stimulating  them  to 
grapple  with  the  question,  really  of  fundamental  importance, 
whether  or  not  Herbart  was  on  the  right  tack. 

"  To  the  more  thoughtful."  This  indicates  the  purpose  of  the 
work.  It  is  not  written  for  the  student  who  desires  in  brief 
compass  an  outline  of  the  Herbartian  system,  of  which  he  has 
heard,  perhaps,  vague  reports.  One  effect  it  may  have  upon 
such  a  student  will  be  a  feeling  that  these  Germans  are  masters 
at  splitting  straws  and  calUng  each  other  names.     And,  it  must 


^  One  criticism,  that  of  Voigt,  is  however  appropriately  included  in  Mr. 
and  Mrs.  Felkin's  Introdtiction. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianistn  3 

be  confessed,  such  an  impression  is  to  some  extent  correct. 
The  Germans  are  undisputed  masters  of  ponderous  controversy. 
The  present  writer  started  with  the  intention  of  translating 
verbatim  considerable  portions  (at  least)  of  the  critical  works 
and  articles  hereafter  mentioned,  but  he  has  relinquished  the 
task  in  favour  of  presenting  condensed  summaries  of  these  wordy- 
effusions.  Still,  admitting  the  appearance  of  triviality  which 
marks  some  of  the  vigorous  mental  life  of  Germany,  we  must 
never  lose  sight  of  the  fact  that  many  of  the  problems  which 
agitate  the  minds  of  these  controversiaHsts  are  really  the  great 
world-problems  of  unfaiUng  interest  and  vitahty. 

Let  us  take  a  pertinent  example.  Many  of  the  pages  which 
follow  will  deal  with  the  question  of  the  Will,  a  question  ever 
present  alike  to  exponents  and  to  opponents  of  the  Herbartian 
system.  Where  lie  the  real  springs  of  human  action  ?  There 
is  no  exaggeration  in  saying  that  this  is  not  only  the  most 
baflSing  of  speculative  problems  (as  evidenced  by  the  constant 
controversies  over  Libertarianism  and  Determinism),  but  the 
most  directly  practical  of  all  questions.  Only  when  it  is  solved 
can  we  be  certain  whether  our  methods  of  religious  and  moral 
education  are  not  so  much  beating  of  the  air. 

If  the  springs  of  action  lie  in  the  physiological  realm,  the 
realm  of  habit  and  instinct  (as  a  follower  of  Aristotle  or  a 
devotee  of  modern  science  is  likely  to  affirm),  then  it  is  clear 
that  moral  education  must  assimilate  itself  to  the  training  of 
plants  and  animals  ;  it  must  be  a  matter  of  drill.  If,  on  the 
other  hand,  we  affirm,  not  "Virtue  is  Habit,"  but  "  Virtue  is 
Knowledge,"  or  "  Virtue  is  based  on  Insight  "  (as  a  follower  of 
Socrates,  Plato,  or  Herbart  is  likely  to  maintain),  the  main  object 
of  the  educator  must  be  not  to  drill  but  to  enlighten.  It  is  not 
too  much  to  say  that  public  opinion  is  hopelessly  in  confusion 
over  this  fundamental  question.  We  find  a  laborious  piling  up 
of  statistics  supposed  to  prove  that  Board  Schools  are  emptying 
the  jails.  We  then  hear  of  these  same  statistics  ruthlessly  called 
in  question,  and  of  confident  assertions  that  knowledge  has  no 
moral  effect ;  that  only  a  thorough  course  of  drill,  accompanied 
by  rewards  and  punishments,  terrestrial  or  celestial,  can  suffice 


The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


to  keep  the  wayward  feet  of  man  in  the  narrow  path  of  virtue. 
Who  is  right  ?  Are  we  in  moral  education  to  be  Aristotelians 
or  Herbartians?  Are  we  to  put  faith  in  Habit  or  in  Know- 
ledge ? 

The  answer  probably  is,  that  Character  is  twofold.  It  has 
its  passive,  mechanical,  conservative,  and  preservative  side 
given  over  to  the  sway  of  Habit ;  hence  the  enormous  im- 
portance of  the  Aristotelian  factor  in  education,  a  factor 
emphasised  by  William  James  in  a  chapter  that  bids  fair  to 
become  a  psychological  and  educational  classic.^  But  Character 
has  also  its  active,  growing,  changing  side,  and  here  Knowledge, 
or,  to  use  Herbart's  favourite  word,  Insight,  is  supreme.'''  In 
the  treatment  of  this  latter  aspect  of  the  education  question 
Herbart  is  probably  matchless.  His  psychology  may  or  may 
not  be  faulty ;  his  view  may  be  hyper-intellectual  and  therefore 
one-sided ;  but  his  message  is  one  to  which  the  world,  sooner 
or  later,  must  give  heed.  Society  is  daily  manufacturing 
criminals  because  it  cannot  hear  his  warning  voice  crying : 
"  The  stupid  man  cannot  be  virtuous  ".  Nay,  if  it  hears  him 
above  the  babel,  it  rejects  his  words  as  blasphemous. 

The  above  is  an  illustration  of  the  genuinely  vital  nature  of 
some  of  the  problems  raised  in  the  following  pages.  Herbart's 
famous  declarations  that  "  all  action  springs  out  of  the  circle  of 
thought,"  that  "  the  stupid  man  cannot  be  virtuous,"  that  there 
should  be  "no  instruction  which  does  not  educate  the  character," 
are  no  mere  concatenations  of  syllables,  no  watchwords  for  hair- 
splitting competitions  between  rival  German  professors.  Even 
when  we  come  to  the  apparently  more  academic  question 
agitated  between  Natorp  and  the  Herbartians,  the  question 
whether  a  presentations-mechanism  is  an  adequate  explanation 

^  Tallis  to  Teachers,  ch.  viii.  See  also  his  larger  work,  Principles  of 
Psychology. 

^  There  is  the  analogy  of  a  tree  with  its  half-dead  stem  and  its  growing 
point.    Each  of  the  two  is  necessary. 

^  "  Presentation  "  is  a  very  general  word  for  "  impression,"  "  idea,"  etc.,  as 
most  readers  will  scarcely  require  to  be  told,  and  represents  the  German 
"  Vorstellung  ". 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  5 

of  mental  facts,  or  whether  a  higher  principle  is  involved  in 
what  we  call  self-consciousness  (really  another  form  of  the 
above  question),  the  problem  is  genuinely  vital.  If  we  solve  it 
in  the  Herbartian  sense,  and  accept  the  deterministic  hypothesis, 
the  task  thrown  upon  teachers  is  enormous. 

It  would  be  no  exaggeration  to  say  that  we  have  no  right 
either  to  hope  or  to  fear  for  the  human  race  until  this  and 
similar  questions  have  received  solution. 

And  here,  perhaps,  an  avowal  may  be  appropriately  made. 
When,  several  years  ago,  the  present  writer  began  to  study  the 
Herbartian  question,  two  briUiant  works,  destined  to  exercise  no 
small  influence  over  British  education,  had  not  then  appeared. 
These  were  Herbartian  Psychology  Applied  to  Education'^  by 
Professor  Adams,  and  Dr.  Findlay's  Principles  of  Glass  Teach- 
ing.^ The  former  is  probably  the  most  readable  book  on  educa- 
tion that  has  ever  been  written  in  English,^  and,  fortunately,  its 
raciness  and  readableness  are  by  no  means  purchased  at  the 
expense  of  solid  wisdom.  The  second  is  almost  the  only 
attempt  to  nationahse  Herbartianism  among  us  by  retaining 
its  most  valuable  features,  and  judiciously  supplementing  or 
correcting  its  defects.  With  neither  of  these  books  will  the 
present  work  essay  to  compete  ;  its  design  is,  in  fact,  as  different 
from  theirs  as  its  execution  may  seem  to  be  far  less  interesting 
to  the  majority  of  readers.  If,  then,  the  field  is  already  occupied 
by  two  brilliant  books  and  half  a  dozen  others,  perhaps  less 
brilliant  though  equally  necessary  and  valuable  (translations 
and  expositions  of  Herbart),  why  should  another  writer  enter 
the  field  with  one  or  two  additional  volumes  under  his  arm? 
Has  he  anything  fresh  to  contribute?  He  has,  even  if  the 
neglected  critical  side  of  the  Herbartian  question  had  not  been 
the  object  of  much  of  his  work. 

Enghsh  books  on  Herbartianism — including  the  two  most 
brilliant  of  all — seem  strangely  deficient  in  one  respect.  The 
moral  significance  of  the  system  is  well-nigh  ignored.     To  the 

1  Isbister.  2  Macmillan. 

^Though  the  works  of  Thring  and  James  "  run  it  close  ". 


The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


writers  Herbartianism  appears  as  a  thing  mainly  or  exclusively 
for  the  class-room  ;  they  rarely  convey  the  impression  that  it 
is  an  ethical,  social,  or  religious  propaganda,  and  one  that  bears 
upon  the  most  vital  problems  now  crying  for  solution.  But  this 
is  the  aspect  which  specially  strikes  the  present  writer.  When 
Herbart,  by  a  daring  flight  of  ethical  speculation,  put  "  Voll- 
kommenheit  "  among  the  "  moral  ideas,"  he  thereby  placed  the 
pedagogic  profession  on  the  "  sacred "  platform ;  Ufted  the 
pursuit  of  Culture  up  towards  the  level  of  the  pursuit  of  Virtue, 
or  rather — it  would  be  but  slightly  erroneous  to  say — identified 
within  limits  the  two  pursuits ;  and  mapped  out  a  plan  of 
social  reform  more  daring  and  more  positive — probably,  also, 
more  likely  to  prove  permanently  efifectual — than  the  crude 
plans  which,  under  the  name  of  "  philanthropy,"  go  far  to 
demonstrate  how  little  modern  society  cares  for  "  prevention  " 
so  long  as  "  cure  "  is  more  thrilling  and  dramatic. 

In  the  Sttodent's  Herbart^  this  aspect  of  Herbartianism — 
ignored  or  merely  suggested  by  British  writers  on  the  subject 
— has  been  especially  emphasised,  and  in  a  projected  larger 
book  the  question  may  be  considered  at  greater  length.  It  is 
because,  to -the  writer,  the  system  founded  by  Herbart  is  a 
moral  gospel  for  men  perishing  through  stupidity  and  absence 
of  ideas,  that  he  is  burrowing  into  its  often  unattractive  Uterature 
and  serving  up,  for  British  readers,  more  than  one  instalment 
of  the  product.  Even  when,  as  in  the  present  work,  which  is 
largely  critical  and  historical,  there  are  but  few  opportunities 
of  proclaiming  with  loud  and  emphatic  iteration  the  moral 
significance  of  Interest,  such  opportunities  as  present  them- 
selves should  not  be  ignored.  Much  will  Herbartianism  do  for 
the  school;  but  unless  it  succeed  in  transforming  that  insti- 
tution into  a  temple,  and  the  teaching  profession  into  a  pro- 
fession claiming  "  holy  orders,"  other  results  (e.g.,  the  unification 
of  the  curriculum)  will  be  of  but  small  moment.  Herbartianism 
in  its  claims  is  nothing  less  than  an  educational  High  Church 
movement  with  the  transubstantiation  of  ideas  into  virtue  as 

^  By  the  present  writer.     (Sonnenschein.) 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  7 

its  central  marvel;  it  is  not  (as  one  would  too  often  gather 
from  most  of  the  current  works  on  the  subject  ^)  merely  an 
academic  system  from  which  pedagogues  can  pick  up  a  few 
useful  hints. 

If  any  gospel  has  a  warning  message  that  gospel  is  Herbar- 
tianism, and  the  message  is  that  the  stupid  (stumpfsinnig)  man 
cannot — cannot — be  virtuous.  If  any  gospel  can  claim  to  be 
constructive  and  inspiring  it  is  that  one  which  hails  many-sided 
interest  as  "  a  protection  against  passions,  an  aid  to  one's  earthly 
activity,  and  a  salvation  amid  the  storms  of  fate  ".  If  any  gospel 
can  claim  powers  for  its  priests  it  is  the  one  which  proclaims 
how,  by  the  manipulation  of  the  principle  of  Apperception,  the 
interaction  of  a  group  of  ideas  will  be  made  to  generate  Interest 
and  pass  over  into  Virtue  and  Character.  In  the  present  work 
there  will  be  no  opportunity  to  expound  in  detail  this  magnifi- 
cent doctrine,  with  the  substantial  correctness  of  which  Her- 
bartianism must  stand  or  fall.  But  in  view  of  the  neglect  of 
this  aspect  of  the  Herbartian  question  there  was  good  reason 
for  emphasising  it  here.  If  Interest  is  really  a  protection  against 
evil,  nay,  itself  an  element  in  moral  good,  and  if  Herbart  has 
shown  how,  in  normal  cases,  such  Interest  can  be  aroused,  then 
Herbartianism  is  a  gospel  and  nothing  less.  And,  after  aU,  it 
is  more  important  that  Education  should  become  a  "gospel" 
than  that  it  should  become  a  "  science,"  though  when  seen 
through  an  Herbartian  medium  it  begins  to  appear  as  both. 

Some  even  of  the  enemies  of  the  system  admit  that  there  is 
a  certain  value  in  the  doctrine  of  many-sided  Interest.  But  on 
the  whole  the  gospel  is  a  new  one,  and  surely  as  necessary  as  it 
is  new.  When  at  Roman  Catholic  conferences  (and  the  same 
spirit  is  present  also  in  many  other  religious  assemblies),  we 
find  ecclesiastics  avowing  that  they  "  do  not  attach  much  im- 
portance to  the  teaching  of  arithmetic  or  geography  or  other 


^  The  reason  why  even  Professor  Adams  and  Dr.  Findlay  do  not  touch 
upon  this  side  of  the  question  is  perhaps  that  the  design  of  their  works 
scarcely  allows  of  it.  But  they  might  have  given  some  pointed  indication 
of  the  moral  significance  of  Herbartianism. 


8  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

subjects,"  ^  we  naturally  and  rightly  infer  that  any  teacher  who 
acquiesces  in  the  spirit  voiced  by  these  words  is  an  appendage 
rather  than  a  man.  Nine-tenths  of  his  work  is  work  to  which  "  he 
does  not  attach  much  importance  ".  What  a  chasm  separates 
the  holders  of  this  view  from  the  beHevers  in  Herbartianism ! 
The  Herbartians  attach  very  great  impartance  to  these  and 
other  despised  subjects.  An  Interest  in  such  things  is,  in 
their  view,  a  life-force  of  incalculable  value,  saving,  or  help- 
ing to  save,  from  many  a  sin,  which,  if  we  are  to  judge  from 
appearances,  all  the  sacraments  in  existence  seem  powerless  to 
suppress.  "  Arithmetic  "  and  "  geography  "  may  not  be,  on  the 
Herbartian  view,  so  character-forming  as  history  and  literature, 
but  no  Herbartian  would  rank  his  work  so  low  as  to  utter  words 
of  disparagement  concerning  even  the  humblest  subjects  in  the 
curriculum.  The  wonder  is  how  any  teachers  can  endure  to  be 
told  point-blank  by  their  ecclesiastical  leaders  that  their  work 
is  of  small  importance.  But  possibly  they  agree  with  their 
rulers.  "The  degree  of  estimation  in  which  any  profession  is 
held  becomes  the  standard  of  the  estimation  in  which  the 
professors  hold  themselves."  ^ 

The  Herbartian  believes  in  the  moral  value  of  "secular"  as 
well  as  "  sacred"  subjects  ;  he  beheves  in  many-sided  Interest; 
ipso  facto  he  beheves  in  himself  and  in  the  future  of  education. 
Interest  in  anything  worthy  is  a  moral  force  dominating  life, 
keeping  from  evil,  opening  up  vistas.  Interest  protects.  Interest 
guides.  Interest  elevates.  Two  boys  may  be  otherwise  identical, 
but  if  one  of  them  is  influenced  by  a  saving  Interest  in  natural 
science  or  in  history  which  the  other  does  not  possess,  such  an 
Interest  is  not  a  thing  to  which  Catholics,  or  any  other  people, 
ought  "  to  attach  httle  importance  ".  Many-sided  Interest  actually 
performs,  under  our  very  eyes,  the  task  which  the  sacraments 
profess  to  perform ;  it  builds  up  character  and  works  for  moral 
salvation. 

The  distinction  between  the    "  sacred  "  and  the   "  secular  " 


1  Bishop  of  Clifton  at  the  Newport  Conference,  22nd  September,  1902. 
^  Burke,  Reflections  on  tJie  French  Revolution. 


introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  9 

things  of  life  is  probably  the  most  fatally  mischievous  distinc- 
tion ever  drawn  by  the  perverse  ingenuity  of  man.  And  yet 
let  us  retain  it — though  with  a  changed  application.  There 
are  "  secular  "  things ;  there  are  "  sacred  "  things.  Nine-tenths 
of  the  Bible  reading  in  our  schools  is  practically  "secular," 
exerting  no  special  influence  whatever  upon  character.  Even 
the  sacraments  appear  every  whit  as  ineffective  and  "secular," 
if  we  are  to  judge  from  the  records  of  prisons,  poor-houses, 
and  inebriate  homes,  the  sacramentalists  often  contributing 
the  highest  percentage  of  inmates  to  these  institutions.  The 
question  is  whether  Herbartianism,  once  intelligently  and 
enthusiastically  grasped  and  applied  by  an  army  of  many 
thousand  teachers,  would  not  accomplish  more  for  the  moral 
elevation  of  man  than  the  devices  and  denunciations  of  many 
generations  have  accomplished. 

But  there  are  others  that  Herbartianism  hits  hard,  even  harder 
than  the  sacramentalists.  "  Save  the  drunkard,  rescue  the  fallen, 
shut  up  this,  abolish  that,"  are  the  cries  we  hear  from  our  very 
best  men,  the  salt  of  the  earth ;  men  who,  in  moral  fervour, 
are  often  miles  in  advance  of  such  persons  as  "do  not  attach 
much  importance  either  to  arithmetic  or  geography,"  or, 
often,  even  to  temperance  and  such  like  philanthropic  but 
"secular"  movements.  Yet  these  cries,  too,  sound  pitiably 
feeble  and  thin  when  once  the  sonorous  trumpet-call  of  many- 
sided  Interest  has  broken  upon  the  ear.  Modern  philanthropy 
is  almost  wholly  reformatory,  corrective,  and  negative :  in 
sharp  contrast  to  this  is  Herbartianism ;  ever  positive,  pre- 
ventive, constructive.  So  long  as  any  genuine  Herbartian  has  a 
voice  and  a  pen  he  will  urge  upon  an  unbelieving  public — which 
nominally  acknowledges  an  overruling  Benevolence,  but  daily 
reduces  him  to  moral  impotence  by  attributing  evil  to  any  cause 
except  the  mental  limitations  of  man — that  most  if  not  all 
moral  evils  are  gratuitous  and  unnecessary,  the  results  of  empti- 
ness of  mind,  unintelligence,  rigidity  of  thought,  absence  of 
wholesome  interests.  "Absurd  optimism,"  some  one  will  say; 
"a  Socratic  and  Platonic  error  long  ago  exploded."  Yet  evil 
must  be  absolute  if  it  is  not  ultimately  the  result  of  intellectual 


10  The  Critics  of  Herbartianisin 

defects,  such  as  ignorance  and  sluggish  or  diseased  imagination. 
"The  stupid  man  cannot  be  virtuous,"  and  conversely  the  en- 
tirely wwstupid  man  cannot  be  vicious  ;  or  if  he  can,  the  moral 
government  of  the  universe  is  a  delusion,  and  the  monarchs  of 
hell  may,  for  all  we  know,  be  holding  sway  in  the  councils  of 
heaven.  That  and  nothing  less  is  the  inference  we  must  draw  if 
the  great  central  doctrine  of  Herbartianism  is  false  :  the  doctrine 
that  "action  springs  out  of  the  circle  of  thought,"  and  that 
therefore  "  the  smaller  the  amount  of  mental  activity  the 
less  can  we  look  for  Virtue ".  In  the  strange  posthumous 
book  of  F.  W.  H.  Myers  ^  we  are  told  that  to  disembodied 
spirits  "  evil  seems  less  a  terrible  than  a  slavish  thing.  It  is 
an  isolating  madness  from  which  higher  spirits  strive  to  free 
the  distorted  soul."  Would  moral  evil  exist  but  for  ignorance 
and  but  for  mental  disease  ? 

When  the  Herbartian  seeks  to  penetrate  into  the  dim  recesses 
from  which  issues  the  human  Will,  he  discerns  there,  not  the 
form  of  a  fiend,  bafiling  daily  the  armies  of  heaven,  but  rather 
a  chaos  of  forces,  innocent  though  untamed  and  undirected, 
working  out  their  destiny  in  the  mysterious  gloom.  And  the 
Herbartian  asks,  with  wonder,  why  these  dark  recesses  shovdd 
remain  dark ;  and  why  a  nation  which  prays  for  deliverance 
"from  pride,  vainglory,  and  hypocrisy;  from  envy,  hatred,  and 
mahce,  and  all  uncharitableness,  from  fornication  and  all  other 
deadly  sin,"  forgets  that  these,  like  "hghtning  and  tempest," 
are  effects,  and  may  some  day  be  tracked  to  their  causes. 

It  takes  a  higher  order  of  mind  to  aim  at  the  prevention 
of  evil  than  at  its  cure.  The  first  is  the  high  aim  of  Her- 
bartianism, whereas  any  housewife,  provided  she  has  a  warm 
heart,  can  aim  at  cure — and  give  alms  to  every  beggar. 

"An  expansion  of  the  concept  of  moraUty  is  required,"  said 
Herbart  almost  at  the  outset  of  his  career  as  an  educational 
author.  The  battle  which  he  fought  was  that  of  the  claims  of 
"  culture  "  ;  the  same  battle  revived  years  ago  by  Matthew 
Arnold.     The  word  is  a  bad  one  and  rouses  many  a  prejudice. 

^Human  Personality  and  Its  Survival  of  Bodily  Death. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  1 1 

But  there  is  no  better  word  for  the  purpose,  and  apologies  are 
after  all  unnecessary,  for  the  strenuous  Hebraic  elements  sup- 
posed to  be  absent  from  the  notion  of  Culture  are  already  rooted 
in  our  midst  and  are  never  likely  to  leave  us.  Our  duty 
is  therefore  to  exalt  Hellenism  while  not  derogating  from  the 
glories  of  Hebraism.  And  "  Culture  "  in  the  eyes  of  its  English 
advocate  was,  after  all,  no  nerveless  dilettantism:  "there  is  a 
view  in  which  all  the  love  of  our  neighbour,  the  impulses 
towards  action,  help,  and  beneficence,  the  desire  for  removing 
human  error,  clearing  human  confusion  and  diminishing  human 
misery,  the  noble  aspiration  to  leave  the  world  better  and 
happier  than  we  found  it — motives  eminently  such  as  are 
called  social — come  in  as  part  of  the  grounds  of  culture,  and 
the  main  and  pre-eminent  part.  .  .  .  Culture  is  a  study  of 
perfection."  ^  This  is  Herbartian  Ethics  deprived  of  its  technical 
and  deterrent  form.  The  "  Culture  "  gospel  may  be  overdone, 
though  there  is  small  chance  of  this  in  Britain  ;  the  danger  is 
that  we  shall  ignore  rather  than  exaggerate.  But  we  ignore 
at  our  peril.  When  a  Herbart  can  tell  us  that  "stupid  men 
cannot  be  virtuous  "  ;  when  a  Matthew  Arnold  can  bewail  the 
moral  and  social  results  of  an  absence  of  mental  "flexibility," 
and  a  George  Meredith,  as  if  in  echo,  can  explain  much  of  the 
vioiousness  of  the  poor  as  a  result  of  the  "  dulness  and  im- 
penetrability of  their  minds,"  ^  it  is  time  for  us  to  ask  whether, 
after  all,  culture  and  morality  are  not  more  closely  connected 
than  we  have  dreamt. 

The  writer  has  elsewhere  ^  indicated  what  he  regards  as  the 
real  significance  of  Herbart's  "  second  moral  idea  ".  Practically 
speaking  that  idea  represents  the  forgotten  claims  of  Greek 
thought.  Greatness,  width  of  mind,  culture.  Interest  appear  on 
the  Herbartian  scene  as  demanded  by  the  moral  intuitions  of 
man.  Virtue  is  no  longer  abstinence,  but  an  effort  after  a  total 
perfection,  of  which  abstinence  is  only  a  phase. 


^  Culture  and  Anarchy,  pp.  5-6. 

2  Ordeal  of  Richard  Feverel.    But  does  Mr.  Meredith  say  this  for  himself? 

3  The  Student's  Herbart,  pp.  39  ff. 


12  The  Critics  oj  Herbartianism 


Objectors  will  say — Dittes  and  others  have  said  it  repeatedly 
— that  culture  and  many-sided  Interest  are  not  virtue.  •  Herbart 
never  said  that  they  were.  The  "second  moral  idea"  is  only 
one  of  five,  and  if  the  other  four  are  ignored  the  person  is  not 
"  virtuous  ".  But,  conversely,  a  person  is  not  completely  "  vir- 
tuous "  if  the  "second  idea"  be  ignored.  That  is  to  say,  an 
English  aristocrat  devoid  of  ideas,  a  country  ploughman  or  a 
humble  housewife  with  stunted  mental  development  and  no 
interests,  or  "daughters  of  well-to-do  parents,  whose  minds 
have  been  disciplined  by  no  harder  work  than  a  study  of  novels 
and  talk  about  the  clergy,"  ^  are  not  types  of  moral  perfection 
even  though  they  may  be  honest,  benevolent,  well-meaning, 
not  grossly  sensual,  and  so  forth.  They  may  keep  every  pro- 
hibitory commandment,  but  they  cannot  be  virtuous  in  the 
Herbartian  sense ;  a  chilling  numbness  rules  nine-tenths  of  their 
nature ;  a  fatal  paralysis  confines  them  in  a  moral  prison  house. 
"  Stumpfsinnige  konnen  nicht  tugendhaft  s&in." 

To  a  man  who  has  once  drunk  deep  of  the  Herbartian  spring 
mankind  appears  in  a  new  Hght,  no  longer  as  a  multitude  of 
beings  each  torn  by  an  internal  conflict  between  the  angel  and 
the  devil  within,  but  rather  as  a  multitude  of  sightless  hydrozoa 
immersed  in  an  inhospitable  medium  and  feeling  outwards  with 
every  tentacle  for  the  mental  nourishment  which  never  comes. 

Said  Gray  of  the  poor  of  England : — 

Knowledge  to  their  eyes  her  ample  page 
Rich  with  the  spoils  of  time  did  ne'er  unroll ; 

in  the  great  poem  whose  beauty  has  too  long  detracted  from 
its  educational  significance.  To  the  Herbartian,  the  poor 
— nay  the  rich  also,  scarcely  less  often — are  mutely  craving  for 
something  they  do  not  possess,  and  indeed  cannot  define,  but 
the  absence  of  which  shows  itself  in  a  moral  disease,  whose 
diagnosis  has  been  muddled  too  long  by  their  spiritual  physicians. 
"  Sin — sin — sin  "  has  been  shouted  from  every  pulpit,  and  the 

*  The  words  axe  Mr.  Rooper's  {School  and  Home  Life,  p.  315).  Many- 
sided  Interest  is  a  gospel  for  women  as  well  as  for  men,  and  would  do  much 
to  save  them  from  hysteria,  nervous  irritation,  self -concentration  and  self-love 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  13 

Herbartians,  careless  of  criticism  or  convention,  retort,  "  The 
stupid  man  cannot  be  virtuous  ".  Where  in  his  anaemic  mind 
and  palsied  will  lie  any  springs  of  noble  action  ?  Can  any  good 
thing  come  out  of  such  a  Nazareth  ?  > 

Evil  does  not  spring  from  nothing  or  from  Free  Will,  It  has 
its  causes.  It  is  a  disease  rather  than  a  miracle.  It  is  to  be 
cured  rather  than  inveighed  against. 

To  claim  Herbartianism  as  a  remedy  for  aU  the  evils  which 
aflflict  mankind  would  be  veritable  folly,  though  not  greater  folly 
than  to  claim  as  such  any  single  religious  or  economic  prescrip- 
tion. There  are  champions  of  both  the  latter.  The  Socialist 
traces  all  or  most  ills  to  poverty,  and  Gray  himself  rightly  saw 
in  poverty  one  cause  of  the  mental  and  moral  degradation  of  the 
poor. 

Chill  penury  repressed  their  noble  rage 
And  froze  the  genial  current  of  the  soul. 

But  it  is  certain  that  man  cannot  live  by  bread  alone,  and  the 
preacher,  seeing  this,  brings  forward  Ms  prescription,  and  traces 
all  or  most  ills  to  the  neglect  of  the  "  gospel ".  But  he,  too, 
sees  only  an  aspect,  and  a  superficial  aspect,  of  the  disease ; 
sees,  in  fact,  symptoms  rather  than  causes.  "  Men  will  not 
accept  the  gospel,"  we  are  told.  But  why  should  we  expect 
them  to  feel  the  historical  meaning  of  any  great  World-Tragedy, 
if  history  and  literature — the  "humanistic"  studies  which 
make  us  sensitive  to  nobleness,  to  pathos,  to  martyrdom,  to 
divinity — have  been  kept  afar  off?  Why  should  they  rever- 
ence Christ  if  they  are  never  taught  to  reverence  Alfred  or 
Sidney?  The  thing  is  absurd.  We  exclude  the  "  humanities  " 
from  the  school,  or,  what  is  worse,  we  teach  them  soullessly, 
or,  what  is  worse  again,  we  confuse  them  with  dates,  and 
grammar,  and  construing — and  then  we  complain  that  the 
"  gospel "  is  neglected. 

Tennyson  sings  truly  that  the  course  of  time  and  progress 
will — 

Crook  and  turn  upon  itself  in  many  a  backward  streaming  curve ; 
for  the  catechetical  Christian  schools  of  Alexandria  were  qen- 


14  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

turies  in  advance  of  modem  England  in  their  grasp  of  the 
problem  of  spiritual  education.  To  the  wise  Fathers  of  that 
city  there  were  laws  of  spiritual  apperception  long  since  for- 
gotten until  re-discovered  by  Tuiskon  Ziller.^  Greek  thought, 
prophetic  thought,  historical  study  were  necessary  preliminaries 
for  the  student  before  the  Christian  mysteries  and  spiritualities 
could  be  discerned.  There  was  less  said  about  the  "neglect 
of  the  gospel,"  and  rather  a  solemn  and  earnest  effort  to  show 
how,  in  the  view  of  these,  the  wisest  of  the  early  Christians, 
Christianity  was  a  culmination,  and  as  such  only  capable  of 
being  grasped  in  all  its  force  and  significance  by  minds  pre- 
pared. But  we  have  forgotten  the  lesson.  With  well-nigh 
every  humanistic  element  excluded  from  the  school ;  with  the 
fact  that,  when  viewed  in  the  light  of  the  vast  moral  importance 
of  the  subject,  history  is  practically  unknown  and  untaught 
in  modern  England ;  with  the  other  fact,  which  would  strike  an 
observer  as  equally  appalling,  were  it  not  ludicrous  in  its  very 
imbecihty,  that  great  literature  makes  no  appeal  to  the  modem 
Englishman  and  but  little  appeal  to  the  modern  English  woman ; 
we  still  have  the  audacity  to  complain  that  the  soul-message  of 
a  Tragedy,  enacted  in  some  unknown  country  called  Palestine, 
then  under  the  rule  of  an  unknown  nation  called  the  Eomans, 
but  formerly  under  kings  of  its  own,  unknown  except  by  name, 
warned  and  inspired  by  unknown  men  called  "  prophets  " — that 
a  Tragedy  taking  place  under  such  unknown  conditions  exerts 
but  little  attractive  force  on  mankind !  Again  be  it  said,  the 
thing  is  absurd.  If  we  wish  the  "gospel  story,"  or  any  other 
story,  or  any  other  humanistic  force,  to  act  upon  mankind,  we 
must  restore  the  "humanities"  to  the  school.  Thousands  of 
English  souls  are  hterally  perishing  from  lack  of  the  historical 
knowledge  which  humanises. 

Knowledge  to  their  eyes  her  ample  page 
Rich  with  the  spoils  of  time  did  ne'er  unroll. 

The  truth  is  that  the  preacher,  if  a  man  of  culture,  has  no 
^  Consider  the  iafe  position  of  the  Life  of  Christ  in  his  scheme  of  study. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  15 

point  of  contact  with  his  audience  ;  he  speaks  a  foreign 
language ;  he  talks  of  colours  to  the  blind.  The  "  apperception 
masses  " — the  requisite  ideas — of  his  auditors  are  so  few  and 
attenuated  that  he,  and  the  moralist,  may  appeal  for  a  life- 
time without  touching  any  inner  spring  of  action.  "  Dulness 
and  impenetrability,"  not  deliberate  choice  of  evil  for  good,  are 
the  causes  of  much  present-day  spiritual  decline  and  much  of 
the  desertion  of  the  churches  recently  revealed.  And  with  this 
"  dulness  and  impenetrability  "  towards  what  is  suggestive  of 
higher  things  goes  necessarily  a  heightened  susceptibility  to 
all  that  is  degrading.  "  If'  intellectual  interests  are  wanting, 
if  the  store  of  thought  be  meagre,  then  the  ground  lies 
empty  for  the  animal  desires."  So  says  Herbart,  wiser  a 
thousand  times  than  those  who  shout  "  sin — sin — sin  ". 

It  is  the  supreme  glory  of  Herbartianism  to  have  shown  how 
intimately  connected  are  Intelligence  and  Virtue,  Unintelligence 
and  Vice.  It  is  the  supreme  error  of  many  philanthropists  not 
to  have  recognised  that  the  secret  of  failure  is  often  absence  of 
ideas,  scrappiness  of  ideas,  feebleness  of  ideas.  The  intolerant 
man  is  intolerant  because  he  has  lived  only  in  one  mental  world ; 
the  cruel  man  is  cruel  often  because  his  imagination  is  weak ;  ^ 
the  impure  man  is  impure  largely  because  he  has  nothing  to 
interest  him  except  impurity;  the  Hooligan  is  a  Hooligan 
because  he  has  never  been  taught  to  be  anything  else. 

"Human  nature,"  says  Euskin,  "is  kind  and  generous,  but 
it  is  narrow  and  blind,  and  can  only  with  difficulty  conceive 
anything  but  what  it  immediately  sees  and  feels.  People 
would  instantly  care  for  others  as  well  as  for  themselves  if 
only  they  could  imagine  others  as  well  as  themselves."^ 

We  have  wandered  for  the  moment  from  the  doctrine  of 
many-sided  Interest  to  that  of  Gesinnungsunterricht  or  the 
teaching  of  "  humanities,"  and  to  that  of  "Apperception  ".  But 
in  truth  they  are  aU  connected.     The  moral  value  of  the  first 

1  Still  there  may  be  "  Schadenfreude,"  pleasure  in  another's  pain,  as 
Miss  Cobbe  urges.  {Contemporary,  May,  1902.)  But  probably  most  cruelty 
is  due  to  defective  imagination.     Schadenfreude  is,  let  us  hope,  insanity. 

^.Relation  of  Art  to  Morals.    (Quoted,  Felkin.) 


1 6  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


doctrine,  even  when  applied  to  subjects  such  as  arithmetic  and 
geography,  is  enormous ;  while  when  applied  to  humanistic 
studies  (history,  literature,  etc.)  it  becomes  incalculable.  The 
doctrine  of  Apperception  is,  of  course,  applicable  to  all  subjects, 
at  least  to  all  that  involve  the  imparting  of  knowledge  as  dis- 
tinct from  skill  or  dexterity.  A  few  words  more  upon  it  may 
therefore  not  be  wholly  useless,  in  view  of  the  fact  that  the 
majority  of  expositors,  with  all  their  lucidity,  fail  to  show  its 
moral  and  social  significance. 

This  significance  will  be  discovered  by  any  person  who  will 
take  the  trouble  to  try  or  to  conceive  an  experiment.  Let  him 
go  into  a  country  village  with  eager  heart,  pure  motives,  and 
boundless  energy.  He  is  determined  to  lay  before  the  people 
"  whatsoever  things  are  lovely "  in  religion,  in  literature,  in 
science,  in  history.  It  is  all  "  lovely  "  to  him ;  how  easy  it  must 
be  to  rouse  others  to  a  sense  of  the  same  loveliness  !  How  easy 
to  thrill  Englishmen  and  Christians  with  a  sense  of  the  grandeur 
of  their  national  history,  with  the  beauty  of  their  national  poetry, 
or  with  the  true  and  deep  pathos  of  that  scene  when  a  single  man 
inspired  the  Jews  in  their  mountain  fortress  to  throw  defiance  at 
Sennacherib  and  the  greatest  army  in  the  world !  Easy  !  Alas, 
it  is  not  easy  !  Mention  "Alfred,"  and  the  rustic  imagination 
remains  unkindled;  "Wessex,"  "Norseman,"  and  every  other 
proper  name  mentioned  falls  as  a  meaningless  sound :  the 
apperceiving  ideas  are  not  there,  and  Interest  is  not  awakened. 
Tell  of  the  origin  of  Adonais,  and  the  rustic  asks  "  Who  was 
Keats  ? "  and  the  expositor  has  to  begin  the  weary  task  at 
another  point ;  again  the  apperceiving  ideas  are  not  there,  and 
Interest  is  not  awakened.  Turn  at  last  to  the  Bible,  "  the  poor 
man's  book,"  the  common  heritage  of  Christians  ;  surely  here 
we  shall  find  something  that  the  rustic  can  appreciate !  Tell 
of  Sennacherib,  tell  of  Isaiah.  In  the  midst  of  the  narrative 
comes  the  question — if,  indeed,  an  ox-like  stare  be  not  the 
only  response  which  the  enthusiast  obtains — "Who  were  the 
Assyrians?"  Well-nigh  in  despair  the  speaker  produces  a 
map,  proceeds  to  point  out  Mesopotamia,  and — inter  alia — 
discovers  that  though  "religious  education  "  is  the  order  of  the 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  17 

day  not  one  person  out  of  ten  can  point  out  Palestine  on  the 
map  of  the  world  !  Sennacherib  and  Isaiah,  like  Guthrum 
and  Alfred,  awaken  no  interest  ;  there  is  no  background  of 
knowledge  into  which  the  new  material  can  be  received ;  the 
apperceiving  ideas  are  not  there,  and  Interest  is  not  aroused. 

Thus  we  come  back  to  the  old  place  ;  preaching,  teaching, 
exhortation,  books,  can  exert  but  little  influence  unless,  early 
in  Hfe,  vistas  have  been  opened  up  before  the  mind.  "  The 
conceptions  acquired  before  thirty  remain  usually  the  only  ones 
we  ever  gain."  ^  Immense  is  the  value  of  ideas.  The  man  who 
has  them  in  rich  abundance  may  perchance  sink,  on  occasion, 
into  debauchery  or  greed,  but  he  is  always  open  to  influences ; 
there  is  always  the  chance  of  revolutionising  his  character.  The 
hopeless  person  is  the  impenetrable  person,  the  man  whose 
"apperceiving  masses"  are  poor,  scanty,  or  non-existent.  Pro- 
fessor James's  jokes  at  the  expense  of  the  "  apperception " 
doctrine 2  are  therefore  out  of  place.  He  complains  that  "the 
conscientious  young  teacher  is  led  to  believe  that  it  contains  a 
recondite  and  portentous  secret ".  It  does  contain  a  secret, 
and  a  portentous  one. 

The  chief  aim  of  the  present  work — which  is  to  lay  before 
Anglo-Saxon  readers  the  critical  literature  bearing  on  Herbar- 
tianism— precludes  the  devotion  of  much  further  space  to  a 
panegyric  of  the  "Interest"  and  kindred  doctrines.  But  if 
these  doctrines  possess  vitality,  clearly  Herbartianism  has  by  no 
means  been  criticised  out  of  existence — an  impression  which 
might  possibly  arise  after  a  perusal  of  the  hostile  criticisms 
which  are  summarised  in  this  book.  No,  Herbartianism  lives 
and  moves  and  develops.  Its  critics  do  good  service  when 
they  point  out  possible  dangers  and  when  they  demonstrate 
obvious  errors,  but  as  the  system  is  grounded  upon  many  a 
deep  moral  and  psychological  truth,  though  its  outworks  may 
fall  to  ruin  its  main  walls  will  surely  stand. 

"  '  Interest — Interest — Interest ' ;  all  very  well :  but  let  us 
have  definite  practical  hints."     A  teacher  will  respond  in  this 

1  James,  Talks  to  Teachers,  p.  168.  ^Ibid.,  p.  156. 

2 


1 8  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

wise.  Well,  Herbartians  can  give  many,  but  the  truth  is  that 
British  Education  is  already  well  supplied  with  "  practical 
hints  "  (of  a  sort),  and  that  these,  so  far  as  they  are  good,  will 
find  their  proper  places  in  the  Herbartian  system.  The  need 
is  for  a  new  spirit,  a  definite  point  of  view,  a  programme,  a 
creed ;  precisely  these  are  provided  in  the  Interest  doctrine. 
Teachers  who  once  feel  that  in  creating  powerfid,  permanent 
Interests  they  are  regenerating  the  world  as  no  other  body  of 
professional  men  are  capable  of  doing,  will  soon  discover 
"  practical  hints "  for  themselves,  and  (far  more  important) 
they  will  realise  that  school  work  has  a  meaning;  that  the 
preparation  of  their  lessons  is  drudgery  no  longer,  but  truly 
a  preparation  for  the  "Kingdom  of  God  on  earth";  and  that 
they  have  a  right  to  look  in  the  face  of  the  clerical  and  the 
medical  professions  with  the  glance,  if  not  of  superiority,  yet 
at  least  of  equahty,  instead  of  with  the  cringing  glance  of 
conscious  abasement.  Is  this  nothing  ?  Cannot  we  balance 
a  good  many  "practical  hints"  against  such  a  boon?  The 
function  of  Herbartianism  is  not  to  add  a  new  and  equally  dreary 
set  of  "school-management"  books  to  the  lumber-room  of  a 
schoolhouse,  but  to  give  a  soul,  spirit,  Hfe,  and  meaning  to  the 
whole  of  the  schoolmaster's  work.  We  need  no  Herbartianism 
to  tell  us  how  geography  should  be  taught ;  even  now  we  teach 
it  fairly  well.  But  we  do  need  Herbartianism  to  explain  to  us 
in  what  spirit  we  should  teach  it ;  we  do  need  Herbartianism 
to  tell  us  we  are  a  profession ;  we  do  need  it  to  provide  us  with 
a  programme  for  the  future,  with  a  tradition,  with  a  philosophy, 
with  a  court  of  appeal,  with  self-respect,  with  leaders,  with 
encyclopaedias,^  with  stimulus,  with  hope,  with  zeal — with  every- 
thing, in  fact,  which  we  do  not  possess  and  which  the  medical 
profession  in  a  measure  does. 

One  parting  word  on  the  "  Interest  "  doctrine.     Is  there  any 


^It  is  not  without  significance  that  the  magnificent  Encyclopaedia  of 
Education,  published  at  Langensalza,  is  edited  by  the  modem  leader  of 
German  Herbartianism.  The  reference  is,  of  course,  to  Rein's  Encyclo- 
pcedisches  Handbvch  der  Padagogik  (16  volumes). 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  19 

truth  in  the  charge  brought  forward  by  Dittes  that  Herbartianism 
is  devoid  of  heroism  ?  Was  Herbart's  apathy,  at  a  time  when 
Fichte  and  other  Germans  were  engaged  in  the  war  against 
Napoleon's  aggression,  a  symptom  of  the  paralysis  which 
"Culture"  sometimes  induces,  and  a  gloomy  presentiment  of 
the  flabbiness  of  his  educational  system  ?  He  would  be  a  bold 
man  who,  in  face  of  Herbart's  spotless  life  and  the  enthusiasm 
of  his  followers,  would  seriously  claim  this.  But  there  may  be 
a  trace  of  truth  in  the  charge.  "Interest"  with  Herbart  was 
mainly  to  be  of  the  "involuntary"  kind.  An  Herbartian 
teacher,  consistent  to  the  doctrine  of  the  presentational-mech- 
anism, would  aim  mainly  at  the  smooth  working  of  the  forty 
or  sixty  presentational-mechanisms  sitting  before  him  in  class 
and  called  his  "  pupils  ".  "  We  have  of  late  been  hearing  much 
of  the  philosophy  of  tenderness  in  education ;  '  Interest '  must 
be  assiduously  awakened  in  everything,  difficulties  must  be 
smoothed  away.  Soft  pedagogics  have  taken  the  place  of  the 
old  steep  and  rocky  path  to  learning."  So  speaks  a  great 
American  writer,^  and  (must  we  not  admit  ?)  there  may  be  now 
and  then  an  absence  of  strenuousness,  vigour,  and  backbone  in 
Herbartianism ;  it  may  easily  degenerate  into  the  "  soft  peda- 
gogics "  said  to  be  prevalent  in  Herbartian  America.  It  may — 
or  it  may  not.  Professor  Adams's  reply  is  at  least  pertinent. 
"The  theory  of  Interest  does  not  propose  to  banish  drudgery, 
but  only  to  make  'drudgery  tolerable  by  giving  it  a  meaning."  ^ 
"Interest,"  says  Schurman,  "is  the  greatest  word  in  Educa- 
tion " ;  let  us  now  finally  add,  "  in  morals  and  religion  too  ". 

Some  further  remarks  will  be  of  service  in  calling  attention  to 
other  really  valuable  aspects  of  Herbartianism,  aspects  likely 
to  be  partly  lost  sight  of  during  an  examination  of  the  weak 
points  of  the  system.  Partly — not  entirely;  for  reasonable- 
minded  critics  like  Dittes,  Bartels,  and  Christinger  are  by  no 
means  insensitive  to  its  excellences. 

Connected  with  the  doctrines  of  Interest  and  Apperception  is 
the  one  that  Instruction  cannot  be  dispensed  with  or  safely 

*  James,  Talks  to  Teachers,  p.  54. 
^  Herbartian  Psychology,  pp.  262-63. 


The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


underestimated.  Ostermann  followed  the  example  of  his 
master  Lotze  in  attacking  Herbart's  presentational  psychology. 
That  psychology  is  probably  but  an  overdone,  over-systematised 
attempt  to  explain  the  fact  that  ideas  or  presentations  are  of 
supreme  importance  for  mental  life.  Now  the  strange  thing  is 
that  some  people  deny  this  to  be  a  fact  at  all. 

There  are  those  who  tell  us  that  "mere  knowledge"  is  of 
small  moment ;  that  the  main  thing  for  educationists  to  look 
after  is  training  in  good  habits,  not  Teaching  or  Instruction. 
They  tell  us  that  we  must  form  in  children  certain  tendencies 
rather  than  confer  upon  them  information.  Among  those  who 
adhere  to  this  view  are  the  ecclesiastical  and  other  worthies  who 
oppose  "  ethical  lessons  "  on  the  ground  that  "  virtue  cannot  be 
taught ".  To  the  same  group  belong  advocates  of  a  pre- 
dominantly classical  education  on  the  ground,  not  of  the  know- 
ledge it  confers,  but  of  the  "unrivalled  mental  gymnastic" 
which  is  provided  by  construing  Homer  and  composing  Latin 
verses.^  The  same  depreciation  of  knowledge  is  shown  by  the 
champions  of  the  "  heuristic  system  "  of  science  teaching,  who 
protest  against  "lecture  methods,"  and  declare  that  "the  great 
object  in  view  in  education  is  to  develop  the  power  of  initiative  " P- 

The  notion  is  that,  provided  certain  capacities  or  tendencies 
are  developed  in  our  pupils,  these  capacities  or  tendencies  will 
be  always  operative,  no  matter  whether  the  mind  be  filled  with 
mathematical,  classical,  or  other  knowledge,  or  with  httle 
knowledge  of  any  kind.  A  man  "trained"  in  the  classics  is 
ready  for  anything.  He  is  "knowing,"  even  though  he  may 
have  little  knowledge.     He  has  "Konnen"  if  not  "Kennen". 

What  are  we  to  say  to  this  ? 

There  are  two  opposite  dangers  to  be  faced  by  modern  educa- 
tionists. One  is  "didactic  materialism" — the  view  that  the 
more  knowledge  we  can  pile  up  (never  mind  how  1)  the  better. 

^"A  master's  business,"  says  Mr.  Benson,  "is  to  try  to  see  that  there  is 
mental  effort."  "  Not  a  bit  of  it,"  replies  Sir  Oliver  Lodge,  in  the  spirit  of 
a  genuine  Herbartian,  "a  master's  business  is  to  supply  proper  pabulum" 
{Nineteenth  Century,  December,  1902). 

*  Dr.  Armstrong's  Special  Report  on  the  Heuristic  Method. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianisni  2X 

Quantity  is  here  regarded  as  the  main  thing.  The  logical  out- 
come of  this  educational  poliqy  is  that  habits  of  initiative,  of 
independence,  and  so  forth,  are  not  cultivated.  Advocates  of 
"  training  "  rightly  protest  against  this.  "  Didactic  materialism  " 
is  the  present-day  creed  of  elementary  schools  and  of  all  other 
schools  influenced  by  the  tradition  of  examinations. 

The  opposite  danger  is  "  didactic  formalism  "  (if  the  coining 
of  the  phrase  may  beiallowed).  "Smash  up  the  knovsrledge 
idol,"  said  Edward  Thring,  "  Create  initiative"  is  the  watch- 
word of  "  didactic  formalism  ". 

Now  the  "  Artful  Dodger "  ^  and  many  of  his  fraternity 
possessed  "initiative  "  in  abundance  and  yet  there  was  some- 
thing seriously  deficient  in  their  characters.  Waiving  the 
question  of  innate  criminality  (with  which  the  normal  teacher 
has  little  to  do),  may  we  not  say  that  the  defect  in  the  Dodger's 
character  was  that  his  ideas  were  wrong  ? 

On  the  whole,  the  tendency  —  not  necessarily  the  actual 
result — of  Herbartianism  may  sometimes  be  in  the  direction  of 
"didactic  materialism".  If  "action  springs  out  of  the  circle 
of  thought,"  vast  importance,  perhaps  exaggerated  importance, 
will  be  attached  to  the  conferring  of  Knowledge.  There  may 
be  an  undervaluing  of  "  training,"  of  the  formation  of  habit  and 
of  the  strenuous  sides  of  character.  Herbartianism,  we  are  told, 
is  hyper-intellectual.     It  lays  too  much  stress  on  Instruction. 

Such  is  possibly  its  occasional  tendency.  But  the  Her- 
bartians  are  practical  men,  and  fully  alive  to  the  dangers  of 
their  presentational  psychology.  Thus  they  wage  war  against 
the  purely  "narrative"  method  of  teaching,  and  lay  stress 
on  " developing- presentative  Instruction"  (entwickelnd-darstel- 
lender  Unterricht)  because  of  the  mental  activity  this  is 
supposed  to  awaken.  As  shown  also  in  their  scheme  of 
"formal  steps,"  the  Herbartians  are  awake  to  the  problem  of 
method,  and   their  opposition  to  the   catechetical  and   memo- 


*  The  example  is  borrowed  from  Professor  Adams's  book,  Chapter  V.  of 
which  is  the  best  exposure  of  the  "  formal  education  "  delusion  in  our 
language. 


The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


rising  system  is  another  indication  that  mere  quantity  has  no 
attractions  for  them.  Moreover,  they  are  never  weary  of  telling 
us  that  the  only  legitimate  aim  of  education  is  the  formation  of 
a  strong,  moral  Will,  and  that  Instruction  which  fails  to  build 
up  such  a  Will  is  not  educative.  Lastly,  there  is  "  concentration  ". 
The  conclusion  arrived  at  is  that  Herbartianism  may  be  a 
wholesome  corrective  to  "  didactic  formalism,"  a  doctrine 
which,  though  less  prevalent  than  that  of  "  didactic  ma- 
terialism," is  every  whit  as  dangerous.  There  is  surely  vast 
truth  in  the  watchword  that  "action  springs  out  of  the  circle 
of  thought ".  Thus  one  great  lesson  Herbart  has  to  tell  us  is 
that  we  cannot  dispense  with  conferring  Knowledge.  Instruction 
is  vitally  important.  However  much  stress  we  may  rightly 
lay  on  "  heuristic  "  methods  and  the  awakening  of  mental 
activities,  we  cannot  ignore  the  scientific  giving  of  information. 
Man  is  not  always  in  a  pronouncedly  conative  state,  aggressively 
striving  towards  a  goal.  Mentally  as  well  as  physically  he 
must  sometimes  passively  receive  or  assimilate.  The  advocates 
of  "heuristic"  and  "gymnastic"  methods  forget  this.  Im- 
pressed as  they  are  by  the  great  mistake  of  former  generations 
of  teachers  who  regarded  the  minds  of  the  young  as  so  many 
tahula  rasa,  or  empty  receptacles,  the  new  apostles  have  swung 
to  the  opposite  extreme  and  would  fain  make  the  young  into 
perpetual  motion  machines.  Such  a  procedure  is  grimly  de- 
scribed by  Dorpfeld :  "  die  Schiiler  lernen  zwar  vortrefflich 
kauen,  aber  sie  ha  ben  nichts  im  Magen  ".  Which  error  is  the 
more  serious  it  is  difficult  to  say.  Mental  life  is  rhythmic ;  at 
one  moment  it  may  passively  receive,  at  another  it  must  actively 


Herbartianism  corrects  the  error  of  "didactic  formalism ".  In 
the  hands  of  unskilful  teachers  it  might,  perhaps,  as  already  said, 
degenerate  into  a  new  kind  of  "didactic  materialism,"  and 
indeed  Hubatsch^  has  boldly  avowed  that  Herbartianism  pre- 
fers easy  subjects  to  difficult.  Some  educationists,  on  the  other 
hand,  will  deny  that  there  is  any  tendency  in  Herbartianism 

I'  See  pp.  l§4  n. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  23 

towards  "  didactic  materialism  ".  Was  not  the  condemnatory 
phrase  itself  invented  by  an  Herbartian  ?  Does  not  methodology 
owe  much  to  the  Herbartians?  Do  not  the  Herbartians  lay 
enormous  or  exclusive  stress  upon  character-forming  ?  Yes,  but 
with  them  character-forming  has  to  take  place  mainly  through 
Instruction.  Herbart  had  "  no  conception  of  Education  without 
Instruction".  This  doctrine  is,  after  all,  the  very  essence  of 
his  teaching.  If  he  was  wrong  here  his  system  was  v^rong  as 
a  whole,  despite  possible  excellences  of  detail.  If  ideas  are  not 
vitally  important  then  Herbartianism  is  on  the  wrong  tack. 

Connected  with  the  fact  of  the  high  place  given  by  Herbartian^ 
to  Instruction  is  that  of  their  deprecation  of  the  policy  of  work- 
ing merely  on  the  Feelings.  Here  again  Ostermann  finds  fault 
with  the  reformers,  though  in  reality  the  practical  outcome  of 
Herbartianism  is  precisely  what  Ostermann  himself  desiderates  ; 
the  Feelings  are  touched,  but  via  ideas.  What  Herbart  specially 
protested  against  was  the  direct  "  swaying  of  the  feelings  by 
which  mothers  especially  so  often  beheve  they  are  educating 
their  children  ".  Such  a  procedure,  he  contended,  has  little 
permanent  result.  The  Feeling  comes,  and  goes  again  ;  the 
Character  remains  untouched.  Aim  at  the  circle  of  thought ; 
give  ideas,  so  that,  sooner  or  later,  the  apperceptive  reverber- 
ations of  these  ideas  may  generate  high  Feeling — many-sided 
Interest.  This  is  the  message  of  the  Herbartians.  Here 
again,  surely,  they  are  right,  sane,  and  suggestive.  The 
utter  powerlessness  of  certain  great  religious  revivals  per- 
manently to  reform  the  human  race  is  some  testimony  to  the 
inadequacy  of  appeals  to  pure  Feeling.  The  ebbing  tide  is  with 
feeling,  the  flowing  tide  is  with  ideas. 

Many  other  things  we  owe  to  Herbart.  There  are  the  five 
steps  of  Instruction,  called,  by  Ziller,  the  "  formal  steps  ".  The 
bitterest  critics  of  Herbartianism  do  not  deny  that  here  we  have 
a  valuable  contribution  to  educational  method.  True,  we  find 
the  "  steps "  already  suggested  by  Comenius,  but  the  main 
glory  of  working  them  out  is  undoubtedly  Herbart's  and  Ziller's. 
Yet  to  this  day,  despite  their  admitted  value,  they  are  unknown 
in  many  British  training  colleges  for  teachers  and  misunderstood 


24  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

by  expositors.^  For  many  a  decade  teachers  have  been  asking 
how  to  draw  up  notes  of  lessons.    The  Herbartians  can  tell  them. 

But  there  are  dangers.  The  formal  steps  must  not  be  applied 
unintelligently  to  all  subjects.  They  must  not  always  be  em- 
ployed in  the  same  order.  Frequently  one  or  more  steps  must 
be  omitted.  Still,  the  first  thing  necessary  is  to  know  them  ; 
after  that,  the  warnings  of  Karl  Eichter  ^ — who,  by  the  bye,  is 
one  of  the  sanest  of  the  critics  of  Herbartianism,  and  fully 
recognises  the  value  of  this  part  of  the  system — ^may  well  be 
attended  to. 

Then  there  is  the  "  concentration  "  ^  doctrine,  mainly  the 
work  of  Dorpfeld  and  Ziller,  but  distinctly  foreshadowed  in 
Herbart's  plea  for  "large  unbroken  masses  of  thought".  It 
is  out  of  such  masses,  says  Herbart,  that  moral  action  must 
spring.  It  is  by  building  up  such  masses  that  the  teacher 
will  work  efifectively  on  the  mind  of  his  pupils.  A  cmrriculum 
consisting  of  isolated  subjects  is  bound  to  be  not  only  unwieldy 
("  didactic  materialism  "  is  a  hard  master),  but  also  incapable  of 
arousing  Interest.     The  springs  of  Apperception  are  dried  up. 

There  are,  it  appears  on  examination,  two  elements  in  this 
"  Concentration  "  doctrine.  First  there  is  the  view  that  know- 
ledge should  be  a  whole  ;  that  hard  and  fast  lines  of  distinction 
between  one  subject  and  another  should  be  removed ;  that  one 
subject  should  throw  hght  upon  another.  This  doctrine  may 
be  called  that  of  "  unification  ".  Slowly  it  is  working  its  way 
into  British  schools.  The  walls  erected  between  history  and 
geography,  between  arithmetic,  algebra,  and  geometry  are  being 
broken  down.  Even  writers  who  do  not  claim  to  be  Herbartians 
are  moving  towards  this  standpoint.  Dr.  Armstrong  urges  us 
to  "  cease  to  be  slaves  to  a  rigid  time-table,  at  least  in  the  earlier 
years  of  school  life,"  and  rather,  at  each  stage,  "  to  do  incidentally 
what  is  necessary  "  for  the  matter  in  hand."*     Only  in  this  way 

1  See  p.  97.  2  See  pp.  125  fE. 

'  The  non-Herbartian  reader  must  be  warned  that  this  does  not  exactly 
refer  to  "  concentration  of  mind  ".     See  what  follows. 

*  Article  on  "  Science  in  Education  "  in  National  Education  (Murray), 
p.  119. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  25 

can  real  interest  be  aroused.  When,  in  the  course  of  a  history 
lesson,  the  name  of  a  place  is  mentioned,  the  map  must  be 
immediately  consulted.  The  history  teacher  must  not  say, 
"Geography  is  outside  my  province".  The  teaching  of  such 
subjects  as  these  must  be — let  us  admit  the  fact  boldly — 
more  diffuse  and  rambling. 

It  is  striking  how  from  various  unexpected  quarters  comes 
testimony  to  the  need  of  this  unification  or  concentration  doc- 
trine. The  recent  famous  report  on  the  education  of  army 
officers  declared  that  "  military  topography  is  treated  too  much 
as  if  it  was  a  subject  by  itself,  unconnected  with  tactics  ". 
From  writers  on  Sunday  Schools  comes  advice  that  maps  and 
geography  should  be  more  extensively  made  use  of  in  teaching 
the  Bible — very  necessary  advice  and  disgracefully  belated. ^  We 
are,  in  truth,  constantly  drawing  lines  and  erecting  barriers  where 
none  should  exist.  Subjects  like  history,  geography,  languages, 
biblical  literature,  and  so  forth,  are  so  mutually  connected  that, 
though  each  lesson  may  suitably  bear  a  special  name,  it  shoiild 
yet  make  use  of  whatever  pertinent  information  can  be  obtained 
from  the  other  subjects.  Thus,  though  the  time-table  need  not 
perhaps  be  abolished,  it  should  be  obeyed  in  no  slavish  spirit ; 
and  the  person  who  draws  it  up  should  take  care  that  the 
various  related  subjects  fit  into  each  other  so  far  as  possible.  It 
is  absurd  to  teach  the  geography  of  China  alongside  of  the 
history  of  Alfred. 

But  there  is  another  element  in  the  concentration  doctrine 
which  is  of  more  dubious  value.  Ziller,  as  is  well  known, 
placed  at  the  very  centre  of  his  curriculum  "  character-forming 
Instruction".  Everything  else  had  to  be  fastened  on  to  this. 
Simple  arithmetical  exercises  had  to  be  set  on  a  basis  of 
Grimm's  fairy  tales  and  the  life  of  Abraham.  The  history  of 
the  patriarchs  had  to  be  used  for  teaching  the  geography  of  the 
East.  Possibly  such  a  plan  involved  an  unjust  treatment  of  all 
subjects  except  the  favoured  one  at  the  centre ;  and  even  the 
supposed  advantage  of  the  plan — that  all  the  thoughts  of  the 

^  See  the  writer's  Stvdent's  Herbart  for  further  information  as  to  the 
progress  of  the  "  concentration  "  principle. 


26  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

pupil  would  gather  round  aaid  be  connected  with  the  "  character- 
forming  material " — was  an  illusory  advantage.  Fortunately, 
Ziller  and  most  of  his  followers  were  early  convinced,  as  a 
result  of  the  criticisms  directed  against  them,  that  their  plan  in 
the  above  crude  form  was  unworkable.  More  "  centres  "  than 
one  were  admitted  to  be  necessary,  and  the  claims  of  important 
subjects  like  science  for  a  respectful  treatment  could  not  be 
resisted.  Dorpfeld,  a  safer  and  saner  guide  than  Ziller,  placed 
ihreR  great  knowledge-departments  at  the  "  centre,"  those  which 
dealt  with  God,  with  man,  and  with  nature ;  to  these  three  had 
to  be  subordinated  or  connected  (1)  the  "formal"  studies  like 
mathematics  and  (2)  the  dexterities.  The  knowledge-depart- 
ments had,  likewise,  to  support  each  other. 

As  a  residuum  from  the  exaggerated  "concentration"  doctrine 
of  Ziller  we  find  left  to  us  :  (1)  that  all  subjects  which  really 
and  naturally  throw  light  upon  each  other  should  be  allowed  to 
do  so  ;  no  artificial  walls  of  separation  between  subjects  should 
be  permitted ;  (2)  that  character-forming  Instruction  should 
have  a  place  of  great  honour  in  the  curriculum  in  virtue  of  its 
enormous  importance;  (3)  that  possibly  "formal"  studies  and 
dexterities  should,  as  Dorpfeld  and  Dr.  Findlay  suggest,  be  made 
to  follow  the  fortunes  of  the  "  knowledge-departments  "  rather 
than  be  pursued  in  isolation ;  thus,  at  any  rate,  in  primary  schools. 

The  various  criticisms  which  have  been  directed  against  the 
usual  form  of  the  "  concentration  "  doctrine  will  be  found  on  a 
perusal  of  the  argument  of  Bartels. 

Then  there  is  the  "  culture  stages  doctrine  " — faintly  fore- 
shadowed by  Herbaxt,  and  applied  logically,  though  only  in 
part  successfully,  by  Ziller.  Here  again  criticisms  have  been 
copious  and  severe.  The  doctrine  in  its  abstract  form  is  un- 
doubtedly based  on  a  certain  amount  of  truth,  though  Dr. 
SaUwiirk  and  others  have  raised  some  weighty  objections. 
The  child  does  perhaps  tend  to  reproduce  the  history  of  the 
race,  and  educationists  should,  if  possible,  try  to  adapt  their 
instruction  to  the  different  stages  of  child-development. ^     But 

^  Certain  authors  oan  only  be  appreciated  by  persons  of  a  certain  age. 
Boys  of  twelve  love  Marryatt  and  Ballantyne.    Shakespeare's  works  do  not 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  27 

no  one  will  admit  that  Ziller's  proposals  are  entirely  satisfactory, 
though  a  few  of  them  may  represent  an  approximation  to  what 
is  advisable.  The  "  fairy-tale  "  proposal  for  the  first  school- 
year  is  easily  justified.  The  child  at  this  stage  is  scarcely 
yet  a  human  being ;  its  moral  judgments  are  poor  and  fleeting. 
The  moral  Hfe  rests  so  largely  on  ideas,  on  imagination,  on  the 
circle  of  thought,  that  the  best  way  to  support  this  life  in  its 
earliest  beginnings  may  be  to  feed  the  fancy  rather  than  to 
stimulate  artificially  the  nascent  moral  sense.  Unfortunately 
many  of  the  Zillerians  have  been  unfaithful  to  this  valuable 
part  of  their  own  doctrine,  and  have  tried  to  use  the  fairy-tales 
for  directly  moral  purposes,  an  attempt  which  critics  have  rightly 
ridiculed. 

Again,  Ziller's  startling  proposal  to  postpone  the  life  of  Christ 
to  the  end  of  the  school  course,  though  violently  attacked  by 
Lutherans,  is  slowly  coming  to  be  recognised  as  justified. 
When  we  find  American  Doctors  of  Divinity  declaring  that 
"  the  child  has  to  repeat  a  great  many  pre-Christian  stages  of 
evolution  in  its  own  life  "  because  "  Christianity  came  late  in 
the  history  of  the  world";  and  when  we  find  them  saying 
that  we  must  "  bring  the  stress  of  teaching  Christianity,  from 
the  New  Testament,  a  little  later  than  we  put  it,"  ^  are  we  not 
bound  to  admit  that  perhaps  Ziller  was,  after  all,  no  mere 
pedant,  but  a  man  with  true  scientific  insight  ? 

The  Eobinson  Crusoe  proposal  is  of  more  doubtful  value  as 
a  part  of  the  culture-stages  scheme,  though  the  pedagogical 
capacities  of  the  story  are  undoubted ;  but  the  general  plan  upon 
which  Ziller  has  worked  out  his  scheme  is  valid — that,  if  the 
Bible  be  retained  at  all,  the  child  must  work  through  it  in 
chronological  order,^  not  dart  in  and  out  among  the  books,  and 

appeal  viery  much  to  the  young,  and  it  is  doubtful  whether,  to  any  great 
extent,  they  should  be  employed  in  schools.  No  young  person  can  appreciate 
Thackeray.     Facts  like  these  are  inadequately  recognised. 

1  See  below,  p.  71. 

2  This  does  not  mean  necessarily  to  follow  the  order  of  the  books.  See  the 
writer's  Reform  of  Moral  and  Biblical  Edvfiation  for  a  scheme  essentially 
Zilleriau  at  basis. 


28  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

study  simultaneously  scraps  from  Samuel,  Genesis,  Isaiah,  etc. 
The  same  remark  also  applies  to  the  teaching  of  "  secular 
history  ".  On  this  question  our  school- managers  and  teachers 
would  profitably  study  Miss  Dodd's  book  The  Herbartian 
Principles  of  Teaching.^ 

Still,  when  all  the  merits  and  all  the  suggestiveness  of  the 
labours  of  Herbart  and  Ziller  have  been  admitted,  the  critics 
remain  undaimted.  They  insist  that  the  underlying  psychology 
is  wrong.  It  is  easy,  for  example,  to  ridicule  the  presentation- 
mechanism  of  Herbart.  It  is  easy  to  cry  aloud  for  a  soul  before 
whom  presentations  can  appear  ;  to  cry  aloud  for  self-activity,  for 
a  creative  principle.  These  demands  can,  possibly,  be  justified 
on  metaphysical  grounds.  But  for  the  educator  the  Herbartian 
conception  is,  far  and  away,  the  safer.  Assuming  that  the 
creative,  free-will,  or  self-activity  principle  is  metaphysically 
justifiable,  is  it  worth  anything  educationally  ?  Is  it  amenable 
to  systematic  guidance  ?  Examination  will  show  that  it  has 
no  existence  apart  from  presentations,  though  it  is  probably 
not  resolvable  into  these,  as  Herbart  thinks.  Now  presen- 
tations are  amenable  to  systematic  control,  and  though  they 
are  not  such  well-nigh  self-existent  entities  as  Herbartianism 
represents  them,  they  are,  in  a  measure,  capable  of  being 
treated  as  such.  They  have  number,  intensity,  quahty,  and 
so  forth  :  to  some  extent,  moreover,  they  appear  as  mechanical 
forces  in  mutual  interaction.  For  these  and  other  reasons  they 
are  capable  of  a  systematic  treatment  of  which  the  self-activity 
principle,  however  essential  to  a  complete  view  of  mental  life, 
is  not  capable.  In  fact  the  educator  must,  in  large  measure, 
view  his  pupil  as  a  presentation-mechanism  and  nothing  else. 
The  pupil  may  have  a  soul,  and  free-will,  and  transcendent 
faculties  of  all  kinds,  but  it  is  certain  that  these  faculties  have 
neither  existence  nor  significance  apart  from  presentations. 
Whether  Presentationalism  has  a  future  before  it  or  not  as 
psychology  or  philosophy — it  has  many  supporters  and  theh- 
number  is   not,  perhaps,  decreasing — it  will  probably   always 

'  Sounenschein, 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  29 

maintain  its  place  as  a  valuable  working-hypothesis  for  practical 
teachers. 

"But,"  it  may  be  objected,  "  your  presentations  are  no  good 
unless  they  touch  and  rouse  some  innate  tendencies  in  the 
pupil's  soul.  Apart  from  a  latent  or  patent  impulse,  your 
presentations  are,  to  use  a  homely  illustration,  '  so  much  water 
on  the  duck's  back'."  The  writer  was  once  discussing  the 
Herbartian  doctrine  of  Interest  with  a  highly  intelligent  man, 
gifted,  one  would  think,  to  an  unusual  degree  with  the  power 
of  rousing  "  interest  ".  "  There  is  my  son,"  he  said,  "  without 
interest  in  anything.  There  is  my  daughter,  keenly  intelligent. 
Approximately  they  have  received  the  same  '  presentations  '. 
Yet  the  one  feels  a  keen  interest  in  all  speculative  questions, 
the  other  feels  none."  An  example  like  this  reveals  the  weak- 
ness of  Presentationalism  as  a  completely  interpretative  system 
of  philosophy,  but  does  not  subvert  its  enormous  value  for 
educational  purposes.  What  answer  is  to  be  made  to  the 
objection  just  cited?  Simply  this,  that  innate  faculties  are 
beyond  the  reach  of  all  educational  systems — not  merely  of 
Herbartianism  ;  ^  but  that,  given  these  innate  faculties  in  what- 
ever degree,  Herbartianism  draws  them  forth  and  exercises 
them  as  no  other  system  does  or  can.^ 

This,  then,  is  the  answer  to  the  group  of  objections  which 
come,  strangely  enough,  from  two  very  opposed  schools.  The 
physiologist  or  the  materialist,  with  his  emphasis  on  brain- 
traces  and  heredity,  pours  contempt  upon  Herbart's  presenta- 
tion-mechanism, and  avows  that  it  cannot  explain  the  simplest 
cases  of  instinctive  action.  The  idealist,  with  his  emphasis  on 
self-consciousness,  self- activity,  freedom,  and  so  forth,  claims 
that  the  presentation-mechanism  cannot  explain  these  essential 
facts.     Each  contention  may  be  admitted.     But  the  Herbartian 


1 "  Doch  ist  kein  Zweifel  dass  der  Erzieher  lieber  seine  Macht  auf  den 
Zogling  liber-  als  unterschatzen  mochte."  Rein,  Padagogik  im  Grund- 
riss,  p.  76. 

^  Many,  as  we  have  seen,  would  deny  this,  and  claim  that  Herbartianism 
is  destructive  of  initiative. 


30  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

may  answer,  "  The  teacher  cannot  manufacture  heredity  or  make 
a  clean  sweep  of  brain-traces ;  he  has  no  recipe  for  creating 
self-consciousness,  no  text-book  for  freedom  of  will.  But  he  has 
the  power  of  giving  presentations,  and  this  is  his  work."  The 
other  factors,  as  being  incalculable  or  inevitable,  he  is  bound,  in 
some  measure,  to  neglect.  The  gardener  assumes  that  his  seeds 
contain  the  vital  principle — a  principle  beyond  his  power  of  pro- 
duction ;  his  work  is  to  give  soil  and  nourishment.  He  is  not 
disturbed  by  the  objection  that  all  his  efforts  can  neither  create 
a  seed  nor  cause  one  species  to  change  into  another.  He  answers 
that  upon  him  rest  the  alternatives  of  life  or  of  death  for  the 
seeds  committed  to  his  care. 

Educational  schools  which  lay  too  much  stress  upon  the  inner 
principle  inevitably  relapse  into  vagueness.  Frobel  is  no  match 
for  Herbart ;  Natorp's  criticism  of  Herbartianism  may  or  may 
not  be  metaphysically  sound,  educationally  it  is,  as  a  whole, 
worthless.  Let  us,  if  we  choose,  endow  the  Will  with  all  kinds 
of  mysterious  potentialities  instead  of  regarding  it,  with  Herbart, 
as  generated  out  of  the  movement  of  presentations.  What 
then  ?  Is  our  educational  system  revolutionised  a  single  whit  ? 
Is  the  importance  of  presentations  diminished  ?  Fliigel's  ^ 
answer  to  Natorp  seems  here  quite  conclusive :  "  Man  sehe  den 
Willen  als  ein  urspriingliches  Strebevermogen  an.  Die  Stellung 
der  Piidagogik  bleibt  voUkommen  dieselbe.  Der  Wille  sei  ein 
allgemeines  Strebevermogen  ohne  alle  Vorstellungen.  Als 
solches  ist  er  zunachst  schlafend,  unwirksam,  blinder  Trieb  oder 
wie  man  sich  ausdriicken  will,  jedenfalls  muss  die  schlummernde 
Kraft  geweckt,  ausgelost  werden.  Wodurch  geschieht  dies? 
Ohne  jede  Einwirkung  wiirde  sich  kein  Mensch  zu  einem 
denkenden,  fiihlenden,  woUenden  Geschopf  entwickeln.  Es 
miissen  also  Einwirkungen  von  aussen  kommen.  Von  seiten 
der  Natur  und  der  Menschen  geht  dieser  Einfluss  aus,  und  er 
besteht  allgemein  gesprochen  in  Vorstellungen."  It  matters 
not  for  educational  purposes  whether  we  regard  the  Will,  apart 
from  presentations,  as  sleeping  or  as  non-existent.     Ultimately, 

1  Zeitsehrift  fUr  Philosophie  und  PMagogik,  1899,  p.  273. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  3 1 


no  doubt,  there  is  an  important  and  fundamental  difference 
between  the  two  interpretations,  but  for  the  educationist  the 
difference  is  practically  negligible.  In  other  words,  Herbart's 
psychology  may  be  incorrectly  based,  yet  for  the  teacher  it  may 
be  the  best  psychology  in  existence.  Natorp  ^  ridicules  the  notion 
that  Herbart's  educational  system  can  be  accepted  as  approxi- 
mately valid,  while  at  the  same  time  its  supposed  metaphysical 
and  psychological  foundations  are  to  be  rejected.  Surely  he 
might  have  remembered  the  case  of  astronomical  science,  many 
of  the  practical  applications  of  which  involve  a  use  of  the  Ptole- 
maic terminology  and  conceptions  as  these  are  found  more  con- 
venient than  the  Copemican.^ 

But  need  one  be  so  apologetic  for  the  supposed  foundations 
of  Herbart's  system  ?  Certainly  it  is  no  time  to  dogmatise  in 
psychological  matters,  but  Presentationalism — in  the  persons  of 
Miinsterberg  and  others — is  sufficiently  alive  to  demand  re- 
spectful attention.  Many  of  the  phenomena  of  hypnotism  and 
mental  disease,  phenomena  such  as  "  fixed  ideas,"  and  so  forth, 
immediately  suggest  Herbart's  scheme. ^  No  doubt  Natorp 
would  reply  that  in  these  very  cases  self-consciousness  is  at  a 
minimum,  and  that  such  cases  are,  for  that  reason,  not  typical. 
He  is  right ;  but  until  he  has  discovered  the  laws  in  accordance 
with  which  self-consciousness  can  be  trained  apart  from  presenta- 
tions, his  observation  is  of  little  educational  value.  And,  be  it 
remembered,  the  Herbartian  principles  of  education  were,  after 
all,  never  deduced  from  the  doctrine  of  the  presentation- mecha- 
nism.    Critics  who  forget  this  merely  tilt  at  windmills. 

A  similar  answer  can  be  made  to  critics  of  another  stamp. 
Just  as  Natorp  entered  the  field  as  champion  of  the  Will  against 
Herbartian    Presentationalism,    so    Ostermann    has    appeared 

^  Herbart,  Pestalozzi  und  die  heutigen  Aufgaben  der  Erziehungslehre, 
p.  3. 

^"Auch  aus  falschen  Voraussetzungen  lassen  sich  mitunter  richtige 
Ergebnisse  ableiten,"  admits  one  of  Herbart's  critics.  Ostermann,  Die 
hauptsdchlicfisten  Irrtilmer  der  Herbartschen  Psychologie,  p.  37. 

2  See  the  remarks  of  various  modern  psychologists  on  the  "  tendency  of 
ideas  to  act  themselves  out,"  e.g.,  Stout,  Manual,  p.  468,  1st  edition. 


32  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

championing,  as  we  have  seen,  the  cause  of  Feeling.  Feeling, 
he  protests,  cannot  be  resolved  into  presentations  or  into  any 
combination  or  co-operation  of  presentations.  However  closely 
connected  it  may  be  with  these  latter,  it  has  peculiar  properties 
and  hence  demands  peculiar  treatment.  "  Wohl  sind  die  Gefiihle 
mit  den  Vorstellungen  eng  verkniipft,  aber  sie  sind  darum  keine 
blossen  Zustandsweisen  derselben,  sondern  stehen  neben  ihnen 
als  selbstandige  geistige  Vorgange  und  als  ureigne  Zustande  der 
Seele  selbst."^  He  therefore  urges  the  importance  of  direct 
appeals  to  the  feehngs  'per  se  through  the  medium  of  stirring 
stories  —  a  recommendation  which,  curiously  enough,  brings 
us  close  up  to  the  proposals  of  the  Herbartians;  witness 
the  doctrine  of  Gesinnungs-unterricht.  Here,  as  in  so 
many  other  points,  they  have  had  a  fine  sense  for  what 
is  genuinely  important  and  educative.  Their  presentation- 
mechanism  may  be  a  fiction,  but  it  has  shown  itself  an  inno- 
cent and  usefvJ  one.  A  feeling  may  not  be  a  presentation  or 
purely  the  result  of  presentations,  yet  it  is  closely  connected 
with  them  (as  Ostermann  admits  in  the  above  quotation),  and 
hence  the  Herbartian  emphasis  on  these  latter  does  not  in 
practice  lead  astray.  It  may  not  be  true  that  "  all  influence 
on  the  feelings  must  take  place  through  the  circle  of  thought," 
but  any  error  here  involved  is  more  than  counterbalanced  by 
the  priceless  element  of  truth, 

Herbart's  ethics  has  been  criticised  even  more  severely  than 
his  psychology.  There  seems  at  first  sight  an  artificiality 
appertaining  to  the  "  five  moral  ideas  "  as  great  as  that  which 
attaches  to  the  presentation-mechanism.  Why  five  ideas  ? 
Is  this  unity?  Why  accept  the  five  blindly  as  immediate 
intuitions  ?  Why  not  find  some  common  basis  for  them  all  ? 
These  questions  are  pertinent,  but  the  answer  to  them  is  that 
philosophers  have  for  centuries  been  trying  to  unify  ethics  and 
have  failed.  One  portion  of  the  moral  notions  of  man  may  be 
satisfactorily  "  reduced  to  lower  terms,"  but  another  invariably 

^  Die  hauptsHchlichsten  IrrtUmer  der  Herbartschen  Psychologic  und  ihre 
P&dagogischen  Konsequenzen,  p.  239. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  33 

escapes  such  reduction.  Individual  Perfection  is  one  moral 
end  ;  social  Justice  is  another  with  equally  urgent  claims,  and 
it  passes  the  ingenuity  of  philosophers  to  base  them  upon  a 
common  ground.  Intuitionism  has  vitality  yet,  and  Herbart's 
ethics  with  its  five  moral  ideas  intuitionally  apprehended  is  at 
the  present  moment  as  logically  defensible  as  any  other  system. 
One  of  the  most  searching  of  English  investigations  into  ethical 
problems  has  resulted  in  a  return  to  a  purified  Intuitionism 
in  which  the  ideas  of  Equity  and  Benevolence  hold  a  prominent 
place,  in  which  the  notion  (though  not  necessarily  the  fact)  of 
Freedom  is  regarded  as  essential  to  the  moral  life,  and  in  which 
the  notion  of  Perfection  cannot  be  got  rid  of  except  by  a 
desperate  effort .^  Here  are  four  ideas,  superficially  at  least 
similar  to  four  of  Herbart's,  yet  arrived  at  in  a  way  altogether 
different  from  his. 

"We  may  probably  say  with  considerable  truth  that  when  the 
student  of  education  first  dips  into  Herbartianism  he  is  entranced 
with  the  thoroughness  and  logical  connectedness  of  the  system. 
Then  comes  a  period  of  reaction  and  distrust ;  he  finds,  as  he 
thinks,  that  it  commits  him  to  fatalism,  that  personality  vanishes, 
that  a  consistent  Herbartian  is  cousin  to  a  materialist.  Then 
on  deeper  study  he  begins  to  see  the  astonishing — almost 
miraculous — adaptedness  of  this  system  for  educational  pur- 
poses and  for  social  reform  ;  he  begins  to  see  that  though  its 
metaphysical  basis  may  be  false,  and  even  its  psychology  de- 
ficient in  its  neglect  or  misinterpretation  of  the  consciousness- 
factor,  yet  those  aspects  in  which  the  system  is  strong  are 
precisely  those  which  touch  upon  the  work  of  the  teacher.  2  The 
student  can,  if  he  choose,  supply  the  supposed  deficiencies  of 
Herbartianism  by  adding  correlative  spiritual  factors  ;  his  mind 
will  then  be  at  rest,  and  he  can,  with  a  clear  conscientse,  call 
himself  a  reformed  Herbartian.  But  probably  the  best  features 
of  his  work  as  educationist  will  spring  out  of  the  original  Her- 

^  Sidgwick's  Methods  of  Ethics. 

^"  Herbartianism  has  its  weaknesses,  yet  it  seems  to  me  the  best  system 
for  application  to  education."  Professor  Adams,  Herbartian  Psychology, 
p.  14. 

3 


34  The  Critics  of  Herbariianism 

bartian  contribution — the  notion  of  the  presentation-mechanism 
and  of  its  intimate  connection  with  volition. 

The  primary  design  of  the  present  work  is  not  to  give  an 
exposition  of  Herbart's  principles.  The  English  reader  has 
now  ample  opportunities  for  becoming  acquainted  with  those 
principles,  and  if,  in  addition,  he  can  read  German,  he  will  find 
Herbart's  own  works  comparatively  easy,  once  he  has  acquired 
some  familiarity  with  the  leading  thoughts  and  the  technical 
expressions.  There  are,  of  course,  later  developments  of  Her- 
bartianism,  and  some  of  these  are  now  available  in  an  EngHsh 
form.i 

If  any  one  unacquainted  with  Herbartianism  should  take  up 
this  book  with  the  desire  of  mastering  the  details  of  that  system, 
he  will  thus,  in  some  measure,  be  disappointed.  The  design  of 
the  work  is  to  indicate  the  nature  of  the  present-day  educational 
controversies  over  Herbartianism,  and  in  this  way  to  pave  the 
way  to  an  impartial  judgment  upon  the  questions  at  stake. 

A  word  or  two  as  to  the  "  critics  ". 

The  sections  on  Wesendonck,  Bartels,  Hubatsch,  and  Chris- 
tinger  deal  largely  with  Ziller.  On  the  other  hand  the  attack 
of  Dittes  was  directed  exclusively  against  Herbart.  Because  of 
its  importance  it  has  been  given  in  some  fulness,  and  a  con- 
siderable number  of  footnotes  have  been  added  in  order  to 
ensure  that  both  sides  of  the  question  may  be  known. 

The  Eichter  section  deals  fully  with  the  "formal  steps"; 
Bergemann  is  suggestive  on  the  "  culture  steps  "  ;  while  Linde 
deals  well  with  the  question  of  "  developing  presentative 
Instruction  ". 

The  attack  of  Hubatsch  is  often  fresh  and  forcible,  as  when 
he  accuses  Herbartians  of  preferring  easy  subjects  to  hard. 
Natorp  is  treated  somewhat  fully,  mainly  because  of  the  recency 
of  the  attack  and  because  the  Herbartians  have  oflQcially  replied 
to  him  at  considerable  length.  But  Natorp's  treatise  is  mainly 
philosophical  and  does  not  deal  with  practical  problems  or,  to 
any  great  extent,  with  Ziller.     Ostermann's  psychological  criti- 

^  E.g.,  Rein's  Outlines  of  Pedagogy. 


Introduction  to  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism  35 

cism,  owing  to  the  nature  of  the  case  and  to  the  condensation 
rendered  necessary,  will  probably  be  found  hard ;  so  also  will 
Vogel's.  Sallwiirk  subjects  the  doctrine  of  "  culture  stages  " 
to  a  thorough  investigation ;  Drews  deals  with  Ziller's  peculiar 
prejudice  against  questioning  (in  a  few  matters  Ziller  was 
distinctly  a  reactionary) ;  while  Kunz  discusses  Herbartianism 
from  the  standpoint  of  a  Eoman  Catholic.  There  are,  by  the 
bye,  plenty  of  other  "critics"  awaiting  exposition — if  the  task 
is  worth  anyone's  performance. 

One  really  great  name  has  been  omitted  from  the  list — 
that  of  Dorpfeld.  But  Dorpfeld  himself  was  an  Herbartian, 
and  though  he  freely  criticised  some  of  Ziller's  proposals  it 
would  be  misleading  to  enrol  him  formally  among  the  critics  of 
Herbartianism.  From  one  point  of  view  he  may  be  regarded 
as  its  greatest  exponent.  Moreover  if  Dorpfeld  were  dealt  with 
at  all  he  ought  to  be  dealt  with  in  great  fulness.  It  is  only  be- 
cause, in  most  English  expositions,  Zillerianism  is  identified 
with  Herbartianism,  that  there  is  any  temptation  whatever  to 
deal  with  him  as  a  "  critic  ". 


PART  II. 

HISTOEICAL  SUEVEY. 

1.  Herbart  (1776-1841). 

Herbart  was  a  contemporary  of  Frobel  (1783-1852),  and  a 
younger  contemporary  of  Niemeyer  (1754-1828),  and  Pestalozzi 
(1746-1827). 

The  name  of  Pestalozzi  is  so  well-known  in  Britain  that  there 
is  little  need  to  enter  here  into  an  account  of  the  various  weighty 
reforms  of  educational  method  for  which  we  have  to  thank  the 
great  Swiss  philanthropist.  Still  less  need  is  there  to  go  further 
back  and  trace  the  connection  between  Herbart  and  Eousseau 
vid  Pestalozzi.  The  connection  has  much  historical  interest ; 
but,  pedagogicaUy,  Herbart's  ideas  are  remote  from  those  of 
Eousseau,  and  show  such  wide  divergences  even  from  those  of 
Pestalozzi  himself  ^  that  educationists  are  to  some  extent  divided 
on  the  question  whether  Herbart  was  in  any  sense  whatever 
faithful  to  the  Pestalozzian  tradition.  The  truth  appears  to  be 
that  the  significance  of  Pestalozzi  lies  less  in  the  concrete 
achievements  of  his  life  (though  these  were  important  and 
valuable)  than  in  the  stimulus  and  the  idealism  which  he  im- 
parted to  other  thinkers.  Frobel  and  Herbart  both  came  into 
contact  with  him  (Frobel,  1807-9,  Herbart,  1799),  and  upon 
both   of   them   his    Anschauung^   doctrine    had    effect,    giving 

^  For  example,  Pestalozzi's  work  was  lamentably  weak  on  the  side  of 
history,  whereas  history  is  all-important  in  the  Herbartian  system. 

^  It  is  useless  to  try  to  translate  this  word ;  accordingly  it  will  be  used, 
in  the  present  work,  as  it  stands.  "  Sense  Experience,"  "  Intuition," 
"  Observation,"  are  all  sorry  translations. 


Historical  Survey  37 


rise  to  the  Kindergarten  system  and  to  the  "  Apperception  " 
doctrine. 

The  name  of  Niemeyer  is  unknown  in  England,  but  the 
influence  of  this  writei*  upon  Herbart  was  apparently  consider- 
able. It  was  his  Principles  of  Edtication and  Instrtiction^  upon 
which  Herbart,  when  professor  at  Konigsberg  and  Gottingen, 
based  his  pedagogical  lectures,  and  to  which  frequent  references 
are  made  in  his  works. 

It  was  an  age  of  great  names.  Besides  Frobel,  Herbart  had 
for  contemporaries  the  idealistic  thinkers  Schelling  and  Hegel. 
As  an  older  contemporary  there  was,  as  we  have  seen,  Pesta- 
lozzi ;  there  were  also  Kant  and  Fichte.  In  England,  Lancaster 
and  Bell  ^  were  working ;  Arnold  was  born  in  1795  ;  Jacotot  in 
1770. 

Herbart  himself  was  bom  in  1776  at  Oldenburg.  He  early 
showed  signs  of  promise,  and  in  1794  entered  the  University  at 
Jena,  a  town  destined  to  become  in  later  years  one  of  the  three 
chief  centres  of  the  educational  propaganda  associated  with  his 
name.  Here  he  came,  via  Fichte,  under  the  influence  of  the 
then  predominant  Kantian  philosophy ;  we  must  probably  trace 
to  this  source  his  emphasis  upon  the  moral  end  of  education, 
an  emphasis  which  his  followers  have  even  increased.  From 
1797  to  1799  Herbart  was  in  Switzerland  as  private  tutor  to 
the  thi-ee  sons  of  Herr  von  Steiger,  and  the  letters  he  despatched 
relative  to  the  progress  of  these  boys  throw  much  light  upon 
the  growth  of  his  ideas.  In  1799  he  met  Pestalozzi  at  Burgdorf, 
and  in  the  same  year  he  was  to  be  found  at  Bremen  as  student 
of  philosophy.  Three  years  later,  having  taken  his  doctor's 
degree,  he  began  at  Gottingen  to  lecture  and  write  on  Philosophy 
and  Education.  A  little  earlier  he  had  written  (1801)  Ideas  on 
a  Pedagogical  Plan  of  Teaching  for  Higher  Classes,  and  now, 
located  at  Gottingen,  he  began  seriously  to  devote  himself  to 
working  out  an  educational  system.     In  1802  appeared  certain 

^  Niemeyer  was  Chancellor  of  Halle  University.  In  1836  his  book 
attained  its  ninth  edition. 

2  To  hear  of  Bell  among  "  great  "  men  sounds  strange.  But  some  nations 
have  to  be  thankful  for  small  mercies. 


38  The  Critics  of  Herbattianisftt 

works  whose  titles  suggest  at  once  his  interest  in  the  life-task 
of  Pestalozzi :  U-pon  Pestalozzi's  Newest  Work ;  How  Gertrude 
Teaches  her  Children;  and  Pestalozzi's  Idea  of  an  A  B  C  of 
Anschauung.  In  1804  appeared  his  Esthetic  Revelation  of  the 
World  as  the  Chief  Work  of  Education,  and  still  another 
brochure  dealing  with  Pestalozzi.  Two  years  later  he  came 
before  the  world  as  author  of  an  educational  masterpiece, 
General  Pedagogy,  deduced  from  the  Purpose  of  Edu^ation.^ 
Here  he  appeared  as  an  independent  thinker,  and  no  longer  in 
obvious  relation  to  Pestalozzi.  Works  on  logic,  metaphysics, 
and  moral  philosophy  also  came  from  his  pen.  It  is  clear,  from 
the  foregoing  sketch,  that  Herbart's  interests  were  primarily 
educational  and  only  secondarily  philosophical.  His  educa- 
tional system  was  no  deduction,  as  many  people  suppose,  from 
a  pre-arranged  and  artificial  philosophical  system ;  his  philo- 
sophical system  was  rather  an  artificial  structure  thrown  around 
or  placed  beneath  his  educational  system.  He  was  not,  like 
Kant,  philosopher  first  and  educationist  afterwards ;  education 
was  his  first  and  his  last  interest.  He  worked  at  psychology 
and  philosophy  partly  (perhaps  mainly)  in  order  to  gain  a 
foundation  for  his  pedagogical  ideas. 

In  1809  his  fame  was  such  as  to  cause  him  to  be  summoned 
to  the  most  distinguished  philosophic  chair  in  Germany,  that 
which  had  been  occupied  only  a  few  years  before  by  Immanuel 
Kant.  In  1810  Herbart  ventured  on  the  founding  at  Konigsberg 
of  a  College  or  Seminar  for  the  training  of  teachers,  an  estab- 
lishment which,  though  not  numerically  strong,  and  though 
fated  to  come  to  an  end  when  Herbart  left  for  Gottingen,  was 
full  of  significance  for  the  future.^  During  the  Konigsberg 
period  Herbart  published  various  works  on  philosophy,  psy- 
chology, and  metaphysics.  In  1833  he  went  back  to  Gottingen 
and  taught  again  with  success  and  considerable  fame.  In  1835 
appeared  his  Outline  of  Pedagogical  Lectures,  in  some  respects 


^  Referred  to  as  Science  of  Education  by  Mr.  and  Mrs.  Felkin. 
*  As  we  shall  see,  Stoy  and  Ziller  both  founded  "  Semmars  "  on  Herbart's 
plan. 


Historical  Survey  39 


a  more  important  work  than  the  General  Pedagogy  because 
representing  more  mature  views.  In  1841  he  died,  and  with 
him  Herbartianism  seemed,  for  the  time,  to  have  died  also. 

For  the  remarkable  feature  about  this  system  is  that  at 
Herbart's  death  it  possessed  but  little  authority  and  few  ad- 
herents, whereas  thirty  or  forty  years  later  it  had  risen  to  a 
commanding  position,  and  was  claiming  the  allegiance  of  hun- 
dreds if  not  of  thousands  of  German  teachers.  This  resuscitation 
was  the  work  mainly  of  three  men,  Stoy,  Dorpfeld,  and  Ziller. 

But  before  an  account  of  the  labours  of  these  giants  can  be 
thoroughly  intelligible,  the  leading  Herbartian  doctrines  must 
be  known  in  outline,  and  in  the  form  which  they  had  taken 
at  the  death  of  Herbart.  The  term  "  Herbartianism  "  covers  a 
wide  field  of  thought,  and  we  must  distinguish  the  contributions 
of  the  founder  from  those  of  his  followers. 

2.  Outline  of  Herbart's  Doctrines. 

(1)  Most  fundamental  is  Herbart's  view  that  "  Character  "  is 
the  end  of  true  Education.  "  Ethics  gives  the  goal,"  and  ethics, 
of  course,  is  the  science  of  Morality  or  Character.  Whatever 
does  not  contribute  to  the  moral  life  is  not  true  Education. 

[Needless  to  say,  this  view  has  met  with  abundant  opposition. 
Many  teachers  and  writers  claim  that  Education  has  several 
goals — Morality,  Knowledge,  Skill,  etc. — and  urge  that  these 
cannot  be  reduced  to  one.  But  the  most  characteristic  feature 
of  Herbartianism  is  the  denial  of  any  ultimate  multiplicity.] 

(2)  Character,  then,  is  the  end,  goal,  or  purpose  of  Education. 
But  how  is  the  goal  to  be  reached?  "  Ethics  gives  the  goal, 
psychology  gives  the  means."  Hence  teachers  must  know 
psychology  or  mental  science. 

(3)  But  z^/iic/i  psychology  ?  "Herbart's ;  and  the  characteris- 
tics of  this  psychology  are  that  the  soul  has  no  *  faculties  * 
in  the  ordinary  sense,  no  semi-independent  powers  of  Will, 
Feeling,  Memory,  etc.  ;  that  it  is  quite  empty  but  for  '  presenta- 
tions '  or  ideas ;  that  the  whole  life  of  the  soul  consists  in  the 
rise,  fall,  and  mutual  action  of  these  units.  Even  Will  is  only 
a  phase  in  the  movement  of  presentations." 


40  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


[But  what  about  heredity?  Here,  perhaps,  is  the  weakest 
side  of  Herbart's  psychology.  It  cannot  be  said  that  he  denies 
organic  facts  hke  heredity  and  variation  ;  he  admits  that  the 
soul,  on  becoming  united  with  a  bodily  organism,  receives  a 
special  individuality,  bent,  or  direction.  But  the  tendency  of 
Herbartianism,  and  indeed  of  most  educational  systems,  is  to 
minimise  these  facts.  And  such  is  natural.  An  educator  cannot 
influence  heredity ;  he  must  take  children  as  he  finds  them. 
Herbart's  psychology  was,  in  part  at  least,  elaborated  for  peda- 
gogical purposes,  and  thus  laid  more  stress  upon  environment 
and  Education  than  upon  such  elements  as  heredity  and  varia- 
tion, which,  unhke  "  presentations,"  are  quite  beyond  the  power 
of  the  teacher.^]  * 

(4)  Since,  in  accordance  with  (3),  presentations  are  of  supreme 
importance,  and  all  action  "  springs  out  of  the  circle  of  thought  " 
(i.e.,  out  of  presentations),  the  great  task  of  the  educator  must 
be  to  form  aright  this  thought-circle.  This  is  the  work  of 
"  Instruction  ".^  "  Education,"  ^  which  is  [see  (1)]  the  forming 
of  a  good  Will  or  good  Character,  must  rest  mainly  or  entirely  * 
upon  Instruction,  the  forming  or  culture  ^  of  the  circle  of  thought. 

[This  emphasis  on  Instruction  is  another  characteristic  of 
Herbartianism.  Opponents  have  not  been  remiss  in  criticising 
this  doctrine  ;  but  it  has  great  pedagogical  importance.] 

(5)  Though  "  the  one  and  the  whole  work  of  Education  may 
be  summed  up  in  the  concept  '  Morahty,'  "  yet  there  is  another 
concept  of  almost  equally  fundamental  importance,  that  of 
"  balanced,  many-sided  Interest  ".  If  the  pupil  has  attained 
to  this,  ipso  facto  he  has  advanced  a  long  way  towards  Virtue 
or  Morality.  Many-sided  Interest  is  of  enormous  moral  value, 
guiding  the  hfe,  keeping  from  evil,  building  Character.  "  If 
intellectual  interests  are  wanting,  if  the  store  of  thought  be 

^  Cf.  Locke,  Thcmghts  Concemhig  Ediccation,  §  1.  "  Of  all  the  men  we 
meet  with,  nine  parts  of  ten  are  what  they  are,  good  or  evil,  useful  or  not,  by 
their  Education." 

2  Unterricht.  '  Erziehwiig. 

*  These  alternatives  stand  for  one  of  the  ambiguities  of  Herbartianism. 

'  Bildwi^. 


Historical  Survey  41 


meagre,  the  ground  lies  empty  for  the  animal  desires.  .  .  . 
Stupid  people  cannot  be  virtuous."  Thus  it  matters  com- 
paratively little  which  of  the  two  goals  (Morality  or  Interest) 
we  regard  as  the  teacher's.  Interest  may  be  classified  as 
empirical,  speculative,  aesthetic,  sympathetic,  social,  and  re- 
ligious. 

[Here  again  opponents,  especially  Catholics  and  strong 
Lutherans,  have  objected.  They  have  claimed  that  between 
"  Virtue  "  and  "  many-sided  Interest  "  there  is  not  necessarily 
any  close  connection.  But  the  doctrine  is  characteristic  of 
Herbartianism.] 

(6)  This  "  many-sided  Interest,"  which  is  of  such  supreme 
educational  importance,  depends  upon  the  relation  of  new 
presentations  to  old.  An  absolutely  unfamiliar  object  or  event 
has  no  "Interest"  for  us;  hence  the  teacher's  task  must  be 
so  to  arrange  his  teaching-material  that  all  new  matter  may 
be  brought  into  relation  to  the  previous  acquisitions  of  the 
child.  The  new  must  be  "  apperceived  "  (grasped,  interpreted, 
assimilated)  by  the  old.  Apperception  is  the  process  by  which 
individual  ideas  are  brought  into  relation  to  our  previous  ex- 
perience, are  assimilated  with  it,  receive  meaning  from  it,  and 
are  thus  raised  to  a  position  of  significance. 

[Herbart  here  amplifies  the  Anschauung  doctrine  of  Pestalozzi 
by  showing  that  new  things  must  not  only  be  presented  in  con- 
crete forms,  but  also  be  seized  hold  of  by  the  previous  knowledge 
of  the  pupil.  One  probable  result  of  this  doctrine  is  the  eleva- 
tion of  those  subjects  that  confer  ideas  to  a  chief  place  in  the 
cmTiculum ;  for  Apperception,  and  therefore  Interest,  depend 
on  ideas.] 

(7)  In  working  out  this  doctrine  of  Interest  and  Apperception 
Herbart  arrived  at  his  doctrine  of  the  "formal  steps"  of 
Instruction.  This  doctrine  solves,  in  large  measure,  the  vexed 
question,  "  How  to  draw  up  notes  of  lessons  ".  The  steps  are, 
according  to  Herbart,^  (a)  Clearness  (the  analysis  of  previous 

1  Later  Herbartians  have  greatly  improved  Herbart's  terminology,  and 
have  divided  his  first  step  into  two.  But  they  have  not  essentially  altered 
his  doctrine. 


42  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

notions  and  the  addition  of  the  new  matter) ;  (6)  Association ; 
(c)  System  ;  (d)  Method.  At  the  second  stage  ^  (Association) 
similar  phenomena  are  brought  together,  compared,  and  con- 
trasted ;  at  the  third,  generaUsed  notions  are  attained ;  at  the 
last  practical  appHcations  are  made. 

[The  "formal  steps"  admittedly  constitute  one  of  the  most 
valuable  portions  of  Herbartian  pedagogical  doctrine.] 

(8)  Though  "Instruction"  is  the  main  work  of  Education 
(inasmuch  as  "  action  springs  out  of  the  circle  of  thought "),  yet 
Herbart  admits  (inconsistently?)  the  necessity  for  two  other 
tasks.  These  are  "  Government  "or  "  Discipline,"  and  "  Train- 
ing ".2  The  former  aims  at  the  preservation  of  external  order  in 
the  school;  though  it  is  a  necessity,  it  is  devoid  of  direct 
character-forming  significance  and  Herbart  therefore  hesitates 
to  include  it  under  Education  proper.  "Training"  includes 
various  processes  {e.g.,  certain  punishments)  which  cannot  be 
regarded  as  falUng  under  "  Instruction"  and  which  are  yet  of 
some  importance  for  Character. 

The  tasks  of  the  teacher  are  thus  Instruction,  Training,  and 
Disciphne. 

(9)  A  word  must  be  said  with  regard  to  Herbart's  ethical 
doctrines  which  were  of  an  intuitional  nature.  There  are,  he 
held,  five  moral  notions  which  we  intuitionally  recognise  as 
worthy  of  approval.  These  are  Inner  Freedom,  Perfection,^ 
Benevolence,  Right  (or  Justice),  and  Equity  (or  Fairness).  The 
first  of  these  is  almost  the  same  as  Conscientiousness,  the  har- 
mony of  one's  Will  with  one's  Moral  Insight.  The  second  is  of 
special  significance  to  the  educator,  inasmuch  as  it  is  closely 
related  to  the  doctrine  of  "  balanced,  many-sided  Interest ".    The 

^  Third  stage  with  Ziller. 

2 Mr.  and  Mrs.  Felkin  translate  Regierung  as  "Government"  and  Zucht 
as  "  Discipline ".  But  Regierung  really  stands  for  what  most  English 
teachers  would  call  "  Discipline,"  while  Zticht  may  be  very  roughly  trans- 
lated "moral  Training"  or  "Training".  In  this  book  Van  Liew  will  be 
followed ;  he  constantly  represents  Regierung  by  "  Discipline  "  and  Zucht 
by  "  Training  ". 

*Not  "perfection"  in  the  usual  vague  idealistic  sense.  It  represents 
efficiency  and  breadth  of  Will. 


Historical  Survey  4^ 


"  second  idea  "  really  puts  in  a  claim  for  culture,  breadth  of  out- 
look, strength  of  mind,  etc.,  as  "moral"  qualities.  The  re- 
maining three  ideas  are  somewhat,  though  by  no  means  exactly, 
congruent  with  popular  notions.  The  five  ideas  are  independent 
of  each  other  and  cannot  be  further  reduced  or  simplified.  On 
no  account,  says  Herbart,  are  we  to  try  to  represent  morahty  as 
a  calculation  of  consequences  such  as  pleasure  or  pain. 

3.  The  Bevival  of  Herbartianism. — Volkmar  Stoy  (1815-85). 

Though  Herbart's  educational  labours  had  not  passed  without 
recognition  during  his  lifetime,  there  seemed  no  likelihood,  in 
the  year  of  his  death  (1841),  that  his  system  would  ever  attain  a 
commanding  position.  True,  his  general  philosophy  had  won 
the  approval  of  a  circle  of  thinkers  whose  aversion  to  Hegel  had 
predisposed  them  to  a  "  reaUstic  "  system.  Among  the  philo- 
sophical followers  of  Herbart  were  Drobisch,  Striimpell, 
Lazarus,  Steinthal,  Nahlowsky,  Waitz,  Volkmann,  and  Gor- 
neHus,  from  whom  have  come  various  weighty  contributions  to 
philosophy,  more  especially  to  the  psychology  of  language  and 
of  the  feelings.  But  Herbart's  pedagogical  efforts  seemed  to 
have  borne  but  little  fruit.  Mager,  in  the  pages  of  the  Pada- 
gogische  Bevue,  and  in  an  important  work  on  the  teaching  of 
languages,  was  one  of  the  few  who,  during  the  decade  which 
followed  1841,  kept  alive  the  memory  of  the  master's  educational 
labours.  But  Mager  laid  down  his  pen  at  forty.  Waitz,  too, 
who  had  contributed  substantially  to  educational  theory,  and 
had,  among  other  things,  anticipated  Ziller's  approval  of  "  fairy 
tales,"  died  comparatively  young.  Herbart's  General  Pedagogy 
remained  a  first-edition  book. 

Why  this  neglect?  Partly,  perhaps,  because  Herbart's  edu- 
cational system  belonged,  or  seemed  to  belong,  to  a  great  philo- 
sophical scheme,  and  at  that  time  there  was  less  desire  for  such 
a  system  than  for  plain,  matter-of-fact,  unphilosophical  advice, 
for  "  common  sense  in  Education  ".  Previous  to  the  Napoleonic 
wars  Education  in  Germany  had  been  making  great  strides  ;  but 
it  was  seriously  affected  by  the  reaction  which  followed.  "  Ee- 
Ugious  Instruction  "  monopolised,  in  some  parts  of  Germany 


44  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

the  largest  space  in  the  curriculum,  and  interest  in  educational 
principles  'per  se  seems  to  have  flagged  to  a  considerable  extent. 
Not  wholly,  for  the  German  mind  even  in  its  most  unphilo- 
sophical  periods  cannot  brook  an  entire  separation  from  its 
favourite  pursuits,  and  thus  a  barren  empiricism,  such  as  we  in 
Britain  love  and  pride  ourselves  upon,  was  never  quite  possible 
in  Germany.  But  there  is  clear  evidence  that  the  days  of  the 
Holy  Alliance,  of  Louis  Philippe,  and  of  '48  were  not  days  of 
energetic  educational  thought. 

Moreover  we  must  remember  that  Herbart's  somewhat  tech- 
nical terminology  may  have  been  a  drawback  to  the  popularity 
of  his  system. 

But  the  revival  of  Herbartianism  came  at  length,  and  had  its 
seat  at  Jena. 

Karl  Volkmar  Stoy  was  born  at  Pegau  in  Saxony,  1815. 
After  studying  at  Leipzig  and  Gottingen,  he  became,  in  1839,  a 
teacher  at  Weinheim,  and  four  years  later  was  made  "  privat- 
docent"  in  philosophy  and  pedagogy  at  Jena.  In  this  Univer- 
sity he  deUvered,  for  many  years,  the  lectures  on  Education 
which  ultimately  made  his  name,  and  that  of  his  master  Her- 
bart,  famous  throughout  Europe.  Students  visited  Jena  from 
all  parts  of  the  world,  even  America  sending  its  contingent. 

But  Stoy  saw  that,  in  order  to  effect  permanent  results,  some 
facihties  for  practical  teaching  would  have  to  be  offered  to  the 
students  of  Education  who  had  gathered  around  him.  Accord- 
ingly a  pedagogical  society,  at  first  consisting  of  eleven  members, 
was  formed,  and  this  ultimately  grew  into  a  "Seminar"  with 
school  attached.  Here  lessons  were  given,  criticisms  proffered, 
and  conferences  held. 

Stoy  was  more  than  an  educationist ;  he  was  a  warm-hearted 
philanthropist  as  \vell.  His  sympathies  for  the  indigent  of 
Jena  were  so  keen  that,  partly  out  of  his  own  resources,  he 
founded  and  equipped  a  schoolhouse  for  poor  children.  Fruit 
culture,  gardening,  etc.,  were  undertaken ;  excursions  organised ; 
gratuitous  instruction  given.     Stoy  was  a  "  second  Pestalozzi  ". 

But,  hke  Pestalozzi,  he  was  not  to  hve  without  being  the 
object  of  criticism.     Although  in  1845  he  had  become  Professor 


Historical  Survey  45 


at  Jena,  and  in  1857  had  received  the  honourable  title  of 
"  Schulrath  "  in  recognition  of  his  many  services,  yet  in  1866 
he  felt  called  upon  to  remove  to  Heidelberg,  annoyed  at  certain 
attacks  which  had  been  made  upon  his  Seminar.  This  latter 
institution,  like  that  which  Herbart  had  founded  at  Konigsberg, 
fell  to  pieces  when  the  master's  hand  was  withdrawn.  But  in 
1874  he  was  recalled  to  his  old  sphere  of  labour,  and  his  return 
was  the  signal  for  a  certain  revival  in  the  success  of  his  Seminar. 
During  the  closing  years  of  his  life  he  came  to  be  recognised 
more  definitely  than  ever  as  one  of  the  leading  exponents  of 
educational  Herbartianism.     He  died  in  1885. 

He  and  his  followers  had  taken  up  a  position  of  friendly  but 
not  slavish  adherence  to  Herbart's  doctrines.  They  often 
objected  to  their  master's  somewhat  obscure  and  technical 
terminology.  The  "Interest"  doctrine — worked  out  by  the 
Zillerians  ^  into  a  veritable  gospel — occupied  a  more  modest 
place  in  the  programme  of  the  Stoy-Herbartians,  and  appeared 
in  the  form  of  a  doctrine  of  "  elaboration  of  the  thought  circle," 
quite  Herbartian  in  its  way,  but  not  daringly  ambitious  or 
propagandist.  Even  the  "  formal  steps  "  doctrine  was  freely 
criticised  ;  not  because  the  followers  of  Stoy  denied  its  value, 
but  because  they  feared  it  would  become  a  fetish,  and  check  all 
freedom  and  spontaneity  in  lesson- giving."^  They  laid  much 
stress  upon  the  personality  of  the  teacher,  and  also  upon  so 
treating  or  "  concentrating  "  the  material  of  Instruction  that 
related  elements  might  be  brought  together,  and  thus  time 
and  power  be  saved  by  making  use  of  psychological  laws  of 
"  similarity,"  etc.  But  Stoy  and  his  followers  rejected  the 
"concentration"^  doctrine  in  Ziller's  form,  and  likewise  the 
fabric  of  Gesinnungs-unterricht,"*  historical  "  culture-stages," 
and  so  forth.    "  The  notion  of  '  concentration,'  "  Stoy  said,  "  has 

1  See  p.  56. 
A  fear  justified  by  the  action  of  many  young  and  enthusiastic  Her- 
bartians. 

'^  See  below,  p.  54. 

^"Character-forming  Instruction" — a  technical  Zillerian  term.  See 
note,  p.  53. 


46  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

been  taken  possession  of  by  the  forces  of  superficiality."  "What 
is  new  in  Ziller's  proposals  is  not  good,  and  what  is  good 
is  not  new." 

4.    The.  Revival  of  Herbartianism — Friedrich  Wilhelm 
Dorpfeld  (1824-93). 

Dorpfeld  was  bom  at  Wermelskirchen,  Ehenish  Prussia,  in 
1824.  After  an  education  in  the  schools  of  the  locality  he 
occupied  several  successive  posts  as  teacher  previous  to  entering 
on  the  main  work  of  his  life.  It  was  in  1848  that,  though  still 
young,  he  was  appointed,  at  the  initiative  of  others,  to  the  office 
of  Principal  or  Eector  of  the  Lutheran  schools  in  Barmen 
(Ehenish  Prussia).  Other  more  lucrative  posts  he  might  have 
sought,  but  he  never  did  so.  His  conviction  of  the  true  dignity 
and  future  independence  of  the  educational  profession  was  un- 
usually intense.  Though  he  was  quite  aware  that  the  rewards 
it  proffered  were  mainly  subjective,  we  find  him  expressing  his 
conviction  of  this  dignity  in  a  letter  to  his  betrothed  (a  clergy- 
man's daughter),  who  had  not  hesitated  to  suggest  that  there 
were  better  things  in  the  world  than  schoolmastering. 

Dorpfeld  occupied  his  post  for  thirty-two  years  with  success 
and  ever-increasing  influence.  The  educational  works  which 
came  from  his  pen  were  extremely  numerous  and  obtained  a 
wide  circulation.!  In  1872  the  Minister  of  Education  (Falk), 
interested  in  Dorpfeld's  efforts  to  bring  about  a  unity  in  school 
work,  officially  invited  him  to  put  his  views  before  an  in- 
fluential educational  conference.  "Concentration"  was  then, 
thanks  to  Ziller  and  Dorpfeld,  "in  the  air".  The  compliment 
paid  to  Dorpfeld — an  elementary  schoolmaster — was,  as  he 
recognised,  no  small  one :  "  Ein  Schulmeister  im  Salon  des 
Ministerhotels — das  war  in  Preussen  ein  fast  erschreckendes 
Novum ! " 

^  They  are  now  published  in  ten  volumes  (Bertelsman,  Giitersloh).  The 
most  famous  are :  Thought  and  Memory  (five  editions),  Outlines  of  a  Theory 
of  a  Teaching-Plan  (two),  Didactic  Materialism  (three),  Tivo  Pressing 
Reforms  (three).  Dorpfeld's  literary  activity  hsbs  given  rise  to  several 
thousand  printed  pages. 


Historical  Survey  47 


In  1880  ill-health  caused  Dorpfeld  to  give  tip  his  work  at 
Barmen.     He  retired  on  his  pension,  and  died  in  1893. 

He  was  a  religious  man,  yet,  like  most  Herbartians,  he  often 
took  up  an  independent  position  relative  to  matters  of  Church 
and  theology.  He  objected  to  the  school  being  placed  under 
the  direct  control  and  inspection  of  ministers  of  religion.  To- 
wards the  end  of  his  life,  grieved  at  the  alienation  of  the 
cultured  classes  from  Christianity,  he  sought  to  discover  an 
ethical  common-ground  on  which  all  good  men  could  stand, 
one  that  was  independent  of  theological  opinions. 

As  an  Herbartian — though  a  critical  and  by  no  means  bigoted 
one — he  urged  the  need  of  "concentration,"  but  interpreted  this 
in  a  somewhat  different  sense  from  Ziller.  Indeed,  he  freely 
criticised  Ziller's  proposals,  though  he  recognised  the  brilliance 
and  suggestiveness  of  his  contemporary's  work.  Like  Ziller,  he 
urged  that  the  elementary  school  (people's  school,  Volksschule) 
should  not  confine  its  operations  to  the  "  3  E's  ".  Two  of  the 
"  3  E's  "  (Eeading  and  Writing)  are,  per  se,  mere  dexterities,  and 
do  not  contribute  directly  to  the  knowledge  and  character  of  the 
pupils,  while  the  third  (Arithmetic)  is  a  "formal"  study  and 
therefore,  though  highly  necessary,  is  also  deficient  on  the  same 
ground.  Apperception  and  many-sided  Interest  never  get  a  fair 
chance  in  such  schools.  The  most  important  of  all  subjects 
were,  on  Dorpfeld 's  view,  those  which  add  to  the  mental  and 
moral  riches  of  the  soul;  subjects  dealing  with  nature,  man, 
and  God.  In  quite  the  second  rank  come  dexterities  and  formal 
studies. 

His  greatest  service  was  probably  his  insistence  on  the  need 
of  a  Lehrplan,  a  definitely  thought-out  scheme  of  studies  in 
which  every  subject  should  have  an  organic  place.  He  had  no 
sympathy  or  patience  with  a  loose  aggregate  of  studies  such  as 
is  indicated  on  the  average  British  Time  Table.  In  his  own 
way  he  was  as  eager  for  "  concentration "  or  unification  as 
Ziller  himself.  Not  only  should  the  whole  curriculum  be  uni- 
fied, each  department  should  undergo  the  same  process.  Bible 
and  catechism,  for  example,  should  fit  into  each  other  and 
constitute  a  unity,  the  movement  of  thought  being  from  biblical 


48  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

stories  to  catechism,  i.e.,  from  concrete  to  abstract.  Character- 
formation  being  the  supreme  aim  of  Education,  "  Religious 
Instruction,"  though  not  of  a  narrow  dogmatic  t3rpe,  should 
have  a  central  place  in  the  curriculum,  or  rather  should  occupy 
the  central  place  in  company  with  the  two  other  knowledge- 
departments  above  mentioned. 

With  respect  to  the  other  Zillerian  doctrine,  that  of  "  culture 
stages,"  Dorpfeld  occupied  a  position  of  friendly  criticism.  He 
saw  that  to  limit,  as  Ziller  suggested,  each  year's  course  to 
a  definite  historical  circle  would  bring  about  a  vivid  and  deep 
comprehension  of  the  material ;  and  the  understanding  of  the 
child  would  broaden  out  securely  and  steadily  as  the  historical 
matter  advanced  from  step  to  step.  But,  on  the  other  hand, 
the  Zillerian  plan  left  Uttle  or  no  room  for  recapitulation,  and 
the  material  of  the  earlier  stages  would  be  easily  forgotten  when 
the  later  stages  were  being  studied.  Moreover,  these  earlier 
stages  were  less  morally  rich  than  the  later  ones.  Some  schools, 
again,  did  not  possess  eight  classes.  Dorpfeld  therefore  sug- 
gested a  combination  of  the  "  culture- stages  "  method  with  the 
rival  plan  of  "  concentric  circles,"  and  strongly  objected  to  the 
Zillerian  exclusion  of  the  New  Testament  from  the  lower  classes. 
He  criticised  likewise  the  •  strange  preference  Ziller  sometimes 
showed  for  the  employment,  in  class,  of  a  book  rather  than  the 
living  voice  of  the  teacher,  and  while  not  wholly  condemning 
the  proposal  to  substitute  fairy  tales  for  Bible  stories  in  the  early 
years,  he  questioned  the  advisability  of  proposing  so  violent  a 
change  when  other  less  contentious  reforms  were  pressing  for 
attention. 

We  have  seen  that  he  protested  against  the  elevation  of  purely 
"  formal "  instruction  ^  to  the  educational  throne.  He  protested 
equally  against  "  didactic  materiahsm,"  the  doctrine  which  only 
regards  the  quantity  of  subjects  or  of  matter  learnt,  and  ignores 

^  The  viQw  according  to  which  the  main  function  of  Education  must  be 
to  encourage  certain  habits  of  exactness,  initiative,  and  so  forth,  even 
though  little  knowledge  may  be  acquired.  The  extreme  advocates  of  the 
"classics,"  and  the  extreme  advocates  of  "  heuristic  methods,"  are,  as  we 
have  seen,  believers  in  "  formal  Education  ". 


Historical  Survey  49 


the  mode  of  learning  and  the  connection  of  subjects.  In  Den- 
ken  und  Geddchtnis  Dorpfeld  has  given  to  the  world  what  is, 
with  perhaps  one  exception,  the  best  exposition  of  the  appercep- 
tion process.  He  did  much,  also,  to  clarify  the  doctrine  of  the 
"  formal  steps  ". 

The  history  of  Education  presents  few  men  who  have  had  so 
clear  a  view  of  the  opposite  dangers  which  beset  the  path  of  the 
teacher. 

5.  The  Revival  of  Herbartianism — Tuiskon  Ziller  (1817-82). 

Tuiskon  Ziller  was  born  at  Wasungen  (Thuringia)  in  1817. 
After  a  careful  education  at  the  hands  of  his  father,  a  Protestant 
clergyman,  he  proceeded  to  the  gymnasium  (grammar-school) 
at  Meiningen,  and  subsequently  to  the  University  of  Leipzig. 
At  the  latter  he  studied  philology,  and  also  became  acquainted 
with  the  philosophy  of  Herbart  through  Hartenstein  and 
Drobisch.  But  he  was  no  narrow  specialist;  almost  every 
available  object  of  study  attracted,  to  a  certain  extent,  his 
versatile  mind.  But  the  death  of  his  father  occurred  and  this 
made  Tuiskon  the  chief  support  of  the  family.  Accordingly  he 
became  a  teacher  in  the  gymnasium  at  Meiningen  and  laboured 
at  this  work  for  five  years — apparently  with  success,  his  moral 
earnestness  and  energy  winning  for  him  the  high  esteem  of  his 
pupils.  The  fact  that  Ziller  was  no  mere  theorist  unacquainted 
with  scholastic  practice  deserves  to  be  kept  in  mind. 

Eeturning  to  Leipzig,  he  took  up  juristic  studies,  and  after  a 
brief  period  of  political  activity  became  a  "  privat-docent "  in 
Jurisprudence  (1853).  But  his  interest  began  to  turn  more  and 
more  to  the  working  out  of  the  Herbartian  principles  of  Educa- 
tion. In  1863  he  became  a  subordinate  Professor,  and  his 
inaugural  address  bore  witness  to  the  nature  of  the  task  upon 
which  he  had  now  embarked.  Its  title  was  "  The  Present-day 
Efforts  for  Educational  Eeform  according  to  Herbartian  Prin- 
ciples." 

But  it  was  in  1856  that  he  published  his  first  important  peda- 
gogical work.  Introduction  to  General  Pedagogy,  which,  how- 
ever, was  far  ecUpsed  in  power  and  popularity  by  the  epoch- 

4 


50  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

making  work  of  550  pages,  Foundation  of  a  System  of 
Educative  Instruction^  (1864),  a  work  of  which  Dorpfeld 
boldly  says  that  in  originality,  penetration,  and  richness  of 
thought  it  is  without  a  rival  in  pedagogical  Hterature.^  In  1857 
he  had  published  The  Discipline  of  Children,  while  in  1876 
followed  his  Lectures  on  General  Pedagogy.  This  work  has 
reached  a  third  edition. 

"Educative  Instruction."  The  phrase  conveys  no  meaning 
to  English  minds.  But  a  reference  to  section  2  will  make 
things  clear.  If  the  goal  of  Education  be,  as  Herbart  contends. 
Morality  or  Character,  and  if  the  chief  means  to  this  end  is 
Instruction,  then  any  Instruction  which  conduces  to  Character 
is  "  educative,"  and  arvy  Instruction  which  does  not  conduce  to 
Character  is  non-educative.  "Educative  Instruction " ^  is  In- 
struction which,  by  way  of  many-sided  Interest,  makes  for 
Character.  Here  we  have  the  keynote  to  Ziller's  work  and  the 
source  of  the  Herbartian  zeal. 

Like  Herbart  and  like  Stoy,  Ziller  had  no  intention  of  con- 
fining his  pedagogical  labours  to  lectures  and  authorship.  A 
"  Seminar  "  with  practising-school  was  brought  into  existence 
(1862).  But  difficulties  were  many.  The  University  gave  no 
support  to  the  project  of  training  teachers,  for  teaching,  in 
Germany  as  in  England,  had  always  been  a  sort  of  "poor  rela- 
tion "  among  the  professions.  The  State  was  equally  backward 
in  encouraging  the  reformer.  But  Ziller  was  a  man  of  un- 
bounded energy,  egotism,  and  self-confidence ;  aided  by  two 
citizens  of  Leipzig  he  succeeded  at  last  in  his  worthy  project. 
Criticism  lessons  were  given ;  conferences  were  held ;  enthusiasm 
grew.  Clearly  this  man  had  a  magnetic  personality,  otherwise 
he  could  never  have  generated  out  of  the  materials  at  his  dis- 
posal the  life  and  energy  which  were  soon  to  manifest  them- 
selves in  extreme  forms.  The  institution  itself  consisted  of  two 
or  three  moderate-sized  rooms  on  the  ground-floor,  a  limited 


^  Orundlegung  zur  Lehre  voni  Erziehenden  Unterricht.    (2nd  edition, 
1884.) 

'  Der  didaktische  Materialismus,  p.  3.  •*  Erziehender  Unterricht. 


Historical  Survey  51 


playground,  a  modest  garden  and — a  cellar  for  the  use  of 
teachers  !  The  gloomy  steps  leading  down  to  the  last-mentioned 
were  jestingly  compared  by  new-comers  with  the  "  formal  steps  " 
of  Instruction,  whose  obscurity  was  supposed  to  rival  that  of 
the  more  material  escalier.  Ziller's  chief  supporter  was  Dr. 
Barth,  formerly  head  teacher  in  Stoy's  Seminar  at  Jena. 

It  was  amid  such  unpromising  surroundings  that  Her- 
bartianism  experienced  its  second  birth.  The  extraordinary 
personality  of  Ziller  was  responsible  for  the  powerful  movement 
which  arose.  His  moral  Idealism  and  unconquerable  enthusi- 
asm drew  to  him  many  of  the  best  students  at  Leipsig.  He 
was  an  optimist  and  a  prophet.  He  had  no  doubts.  Education 
was  to  regenerate  the  world.  He  was  a  fervid  Christian,  yet 
no  bigot.  By  the  more  narrow-minded  among  the  Lutherans 
he  was  dubbed  "rationalist"  because  he  would  not  admit  that 
the  Bible  gave  the  key  to  every  science  and  because  he  refused 
to  approve  of  it  as  suitable  food  for  babes.  "Free-thinkers," 
on  the  other  hand,  despite  the  existence  in  Ziller's  system  of  a 
soupgon  of  Darwinism,  despised  him  as  a  "  pietist  ". 

More  momentous  in  some  respects  than  any  of  Ziller's  other 
achievements  was  his  founding  of  the  "  Union  for  Scientific 
Pedagogy  "  ^  (1868).  The  publications  of  this  society  and  the 
annual  reports  of  its  proceedings  introduced  Zillerianism  to  a 
wide  circle  of  readers.  But  the  chief  significance  of  the  matter 
lay  in  the  name  of  the  society.  The  claim  of  the  Zillerians  to 
be  "scientific"  teachers  was  pregnant  with  results.  Those 
who  refused  to  acknowledge  the  supremacy  of  the  new  Leipzig 
gospel  protested  vigorously,  often  bitterly,  against  the  claim. 
But  Ziller's  party  have  stuck  to  the  name.  Nay,  not  content 
with  thus  implicitly  reflecting  upon  the  methods  of  non- 
Zillerians,  they  have  gone  so  far  as  to  dub  their  critics  "  vulgar 
pedagogues," 2  "mere  practitioners,"  "mercenaries,"   "people 

1  Verein  filr  wissenschaftliche  Padagogik.  Stoy  and  his  adherents  be- 
longed to  it,  but  many  of  thena  gradually  seceded. 

^  Dr.  Wesendonck  (Die  Schule  Herbart-Ziller  und  ihre  Jilnger)  believes ' 
that  this  dyslogistic  phrase  originated  among  the  Stoy  section  of  Her- 
bartians. 


52  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

whose  mental  horizon  ends  with  their  noses,"  "  ignoramuses," 
and  "literary  nullities  "  to  whom  "  Pedagogy  is  an  El  Dorado 
of  Dilettantism !  " 

The  truth  is  that  most  reforming  movements,  especially  such 
as  are  inspired  by  a  warm  and  worthy  enthusiasm,  easily  come 
to  manifest  signs  of  arrogance  and  bigotry.  The  Zillerians  felt 
themselves  called  to  save  Germany  by  the  preaching  of  a  new 
educational  gospel.  They  felt  that  their  motives  were  good ; 
they  believed  that  their  methods  were  philosophical  and  scien- 
tific. Around  them  they  saw  apathy  and  empiricism.  They 
criticised ;  their  criticisms  were  thrown  back  upon  them  ;  they 
retorted;  the  tone  of  both  parties  became  more  and  more 
bitter ;  the  reformers  were  not  unjustly  dubbed  "  bigots  "  and 
"  fanatics  " ;  they  retorted  upon  their  critics  the  perhaps  equally 
just  charges  of  apathy,  ignorance,  and  narrow  professionalism. 
And  thus  the  controversy  has  gone  on  to  the  present  day. 

Herbartianism,  with  all  its  faults,  is  a  system,  apparently  the 
only  educational  system  in  existence  which  has  at  the  same 
time  a  definite  psychology,  a  vast  and  fairly  coherent  mass 
of  hterature,  a  considerable  number  of  journals  devoted  to 
its  cause,  a  series  of  great  names — above  all,  the  power  of  rous- 
ing enthusiasm  !  It  has  a  clearly  defined  aim :  it  knows  its 
mind :  it  is  in  earnest.  Unfortunately  its  arrogance  has  been 
almost  unbounded,  and  has  aUenated  thousands  of  teachers 
who,  had  they  not  been  scolded,  might  have  become  supporters. 
But  the  story  of  the  controversy  between  the  "  scientific  "  and 
the  "vulgar"  pedagogues  will  be  told  in  a  following  section 
and  need  not  here  be  anticipated.     Let  us  return  to  Ziller. 

His  Union  soon  numbered  five  hundred  members,  and  its 
influence  extended  into  Austria  and  Switzerland.^  Ziller 's 
success,  be  it  noted,  was  not  the  result  of  his  own  eloquence 
or  of  any  extraneous  assistance.  He  had  even  to  struggle 
for  the  correct  oral  utterance  of  his  thoughts ;  he  was  deaf. 
His  Seminar  was — what  we  have  seen !      Clearly,  then,   the 

1  Where  aji  Herbartian  journal  was  established  —  Swiss  Pages  for 
Educative  Instruction. 


Historical  Survey  53 


influence  of  this  man  was  due  either  to  the  force  of  his  ideas 
or  to  the  force  of  his  personality,  or  to  both.  A  Zillerian, 
wherever  he  goes  and  whatever  his  faults,  is  always  an  en- 
thusiast. 

In  1881  the  Leipzig  Seminar  celebrated  its  twentieth  birth- 
day. From  various  parts  of  Germany  came  past  students 
anxious  to  show  their  esteem  for  the  institute  and  its  chief. 
But  soon  after  this  an  apoplectic  stroke  reduced  that  chief  to 
comparative  inactivity.  He  struggled  on  with  the  production 
of  the  current  Year-book  of  his  Union,  and  died  at  his  task 
(1882). 

6.  Outline  of  Ziller's  Doctrines. 

Even  more  emphatically  than  Herbart,  Ziller  held  to  the 
view  that  the  true  end  of  Education  is  moral.  He  went  so 
far  as  to  define  it  as  the  establishment  of  the  "  Kingdom  of 
God  on  earth,"  conceived,  of  course,  after  the  manner  of  a 
cultured  Protestant  Lutheran. 

Herbart's  psychology  was,  as  we  have  seen,  a  presentational 
psychology.  "Action  springs  out  of  the  circle  of  thought"; 
hence  the  main  work  of  the  educator  is  the  formation  of  this 
"  circle  of  thought  ".  But  every  circle  has  a  centre,  and  if  the 
pupil's  "  circle  of  thought  "  is  to  be  orderly  and  truly  efifectual 
in  the  production  of  virtue,  its  centre  must  be  especially  rich  in 
"  educative  "  material.  Here  we  come  upon  a  characteristic 
Zillerian  doctrine ;  at  the  very  centre  of  aU  Instruction  must 
lie  "  Gesinnungs-unterricht,"  ^  character- building  Instruction. 

But  what  kind  of  Instruction  is  specially  "  Character- build- 
ing "  ?  Instruction  of  an  historical,  biographical,  or  narrative 
kind,  including  "  sacred  "  history,  and,  for  very  young  children, 
fairy  tales  and  sagas.  Ziller's  emphasis  on  the  character-form- 
ing function  of  such  material  is  to  some,  though  not  a  great 

1  There  is  no  possibility  of  an  exact  English  translation  of  this  phrase.  It 
is  a  technical  phrase,  peculiar  to  Herbartianism.  Its  meaning  will  become 
clearer  as  we  proceed.  Perhaps  "  humanities,"  as  Dr.  Findlay  suggests,  may 
be  the  best  translation. 


54  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

extent  in  agreement  with  the  old  "  humanistic  "  doctrine.  This 
material,  then,  must  be  the  very  centre  of  our  curriculum. 

But  our  Instruction  must  form  a  unity  if  Apperception  is 
to  take  place  and  Interest  to  be  created.  It  will  never  do 
to  allow  our  Gesinnungs-unterricht  to  be  separated  by  hard  and 
fast  lines  from  other  subjects.  We  must  unite  all  our  in- 
struction together  by  means  of  innumerable  connections,  and 
especially  unite  it  to  the  central  matter.  In  this  way  the 
pupil's  "  circle  of  thought  "  will  become  a  real  unity,  and  hence 
action  also  will  become  regular  and  precise.  On  the  other 
hand,  if  the  child  has  various  "  circles  of  thought  "  his 
character  must  necessarily  be  devoid  of  stability. 

[This  "  concentration "  doctrine  is  Zillerian ;  it  cannot  be 
found  in  Herbart,  though  possibly  it  can  be  deduced  from  his 
doctrine  that  large,  unbroken  masses  of  thought  are  necessary 
for  moral  action.  The  reader  must  note  the  significance  of  the 
result  thus  attained.  Certain  subjects  {e.g.,  Mathematics)  will 
cease  to  be  cultivated  in  the  school  as  independejit  departments 
of  activity ;  they  will  have  to  be  attached  to  the  central  matter 
and  be  dominated  by  this.  Ziller's  critics  strongly  objected  to 
such  a  proposal,  and  succeeding  Zillerians  have  gradually 
abandoned  or  modified  it.  Herbart  certainly  never  contem- 
plated a  positive  degradation  of  Mathematics.  On  the  other 
hand,  Mathematics  undoubtedly  gains  in  interest,  during  the  early 
stages,  by  being  kept  in  close  connection  with  the  concrete.] 

iVnother  characteristic  Zillerian  doctrine  is  that  of  "  histori- 
cal culture  stages,"  supposed  to  be  in  part  a  scientific 
corollary  from  Herbart's  "  apperception  "  teaching.  Matter 
has  to  be  presented  to  the  child  of  such  quality  and  amount 
as  to  be  readily  assimilated  or  "apperceived ".  Hence 
what  is  to  be  presented  to  the  child  of  six  must  be  very 
different  from  what  is  presented  to  the  child  of  twelve.  The 
child  goes  through  definite  stages  of  development  and  these 
stages,   according    to    Goethe   and    others,^   are    identical,   in 

1  E.g.,  Modem  biologists  par  excellence.  Spencer  says,  here  agreeing  in 
principle  with  Ziller :  "  The  education  of  the  child  must  accord  both  in 


Historical  Survey  ee 


epitome,  with  the  stages  through  which  the  race  has  gone 
historically.  The  two  lines  of  development  run  parallel.  Hence 
if  we  are  to  expect  easy  and  ready  "  apperception  "  on  the  part 
of  our  pupils,  we  must  reproduce,  in  our  school  instruction,  the 
stages  of  race  development.  The  teacher  must  present  to  very 
young  pupils  matter  similar  to  that  which  primitive  man  under- 
stood ;  with  older  pupils  matter  corresponding  to  later  stages  of 
civilisation  ;  and  so  on. 

[This  sweeping  doctrine — in  essence  perhaps  more  Frobelian 
than  Herbartian — is,  no  doubt,  "  scientific  "  in  conception, 
though  the  precise  proposals  of  Ziller  have  awakened  fierce 
criticism.] 

Coming  to  details  of  the  material  recommended  by  Ziller  for 

Gesinnungs-unterricht,  we  find  the  following  : — 

1st  school  year,  12  of  Grimm's  Marchen  (Fairy  tales). 

2nd  „  Robinson  Crusoe. 

3rd  ,,  The  Patriarchs.       \ 

4th  „  The  Judges.  _      .,         .^,   ,,         ,     „ 

_.,  „,      „.  Together  with  "  secular 

6th  „  The  Kmgs.  I      ,  .  ,  ,     .    ,    . 

6th  „  The  Life  of  Jesus. 

7th  ,,  The  Apostles. 

8th  ,,  The  Reformation. 

This  selection  is  regarded  by  Ziller  as  corresponding  to  eight 
stages  of  racial  development,  and  therefore  as  also  suitable  for 
the  instruction  of  children  at  eight  different  periods.  The 
above  material  has  to  form  the  very  centre  of  the  school  curri- 
culum. The  fairy  tales  represent  the  youth  of  the  world ;  Eobin- 
son  Crusoe  represents  primitive  man  learning  the  use  of  tools  ; 
the  patriarchs  represent  the  nomadic  stage,  and  so  forth. 

[There  is  here  ample  ground  for  criticism.  Is  the  matter  suit- 
ably selected  ?  Is  it  right,  say  Protestants,  to  exclude  the  Bible 
from  stages  (1)  and  (2),  and  to  give  only  one  year  (6)  to  the 
life  of  Jesus  ?  Catholics  will  object  to  stage  (8)  and  "  secu- 
larists "  to  any  use  of  the  Bible.] 

mode  and  arrangement  with  the  education  of  mankind  considered  his- 
torically. In  other  words,  the  genesis  of  knowledge  in  the  individual 
must  follow  the  same  course  as  the  genesis  of  knowledge  in  the  race," 
■  -Ediication,  p.  67. 


history  selected    in 
similar  manner. 


56  The  Critics  of  Herbartianistn 

Ziller  and  his  followers  enthusiastically  accepted  Herbart's 
scheme  of  "  formal  steps  "  and  improved  on  it. 

Ziller  also  accepted  the  "  Interest "  doctrine  and  elaborated 
it  greatly,  showing^  how  Interest  is  a  "protection  against 
passions,"  "an  aid  to  one's  earthly  activity,"  and  a  "salvation 
amid  the  storms  of  fate  ".  In  fact,  Interest  is  an  important 
stepping-stone  to,  or  ingredient  in,  Virtue. 

7.   'Reaction  and  Controversy } 

We  now  approach  the  most  critical  period  in  the  history  of 
Herbartianism,  the  years  1884-6. 

For  a  time  all  had  gone  well.  Stoy  at  Jena,  and,  still  more, 
Ziller  at  Leipzig  had  won  for  Herbartianism  or  neo-Herbar- 
tianism  a  position  of  influence.  In  the  Ehine  provinces  Dorp- 
feld  as  an  independent-minded  Herbartian  and  a  practical 
educationist  of  no  mean  ability,  had  exerted  an  influence  scarcely, 
if  at  all,  less  than  that  of  the  two  professors  further  east.  Ad- 
herents of  Herbartianism  were  reckoned  by  hundreds  and  pro- 
bably numbered  thousands.  Though  distinctively  Protestant 
in  inception,  the  new  creed  obtained  some  adherents  among 
Catholics;  Vogt,  the  successor  of  Ziller  in  the  Presidency  of 
the  "  Union  for  Scientific  Pedagogy,"  was  a  Catholic,  and  Will- 
mann,  a  Professor  at  Prague,  also  belonged  and  belongs  to  the 
older  church.  Though  Germany  was  the  headquarters  of  the 
system,  almost  every  country  of  Europe  (and  some  outside  of 
Europe)  had  its  contingent  of  Herbartian  students.  In  the  work 
entitled  Herhart  and  the  Herbartians  (published  by  Beyer  and 
Sohne,  Langensalza)  over  a  hundred  quarto  pages,  containing  no- 
thing but  a  list  of  Herbartian  literature,  German,  French,  Italian, 
Koumanian,  English  (or  rather  mainly  American),  Bohemian, 
Dutch,  Armenian,  Danish,  Swiss,  Croatian,  and  Hungarian,  bear 

^  In  an  exposition  extending  over  two  hundred  pages  of  his  Grundlegung 
zur  Lehre  vom  erziehenden  Unterricht. 

^It  was  during  the  controversies  mentioned  in  this  section  that  Dr. 
Klemm  arrived  in  Europe.  He  refers  to  them  in  his  work  European 
Schools.  "  I  left  the  bookstore  with  an  armful  of  pamphlets  and  books,  and 
poorer  by  thirty-five  marks  "  (p.  40). 


Historical  Survey  57 


witness  to  the  cosmopolitan  nature  of  the  movement.  But 
the  four  countries  into  which  the  Herbartian  influence  more 
especially  extended  appear  to  have  been  Switzerland,  Austria, 
Hungary,  and  America. 

Why  this  popularity?  Because,  as  already  pointed  out, 
Herbartianism  was  a  system,  and  there  was  no  other  well- 
marked  educational  system  in  existence,  though  fragments  of 
systems  were  plentiful.  Herbartianism  had  its  great  names  and 
great  ideas ;  above  all,  it  had  force  and  enthusiasm.  Possibly, 
too,  its  technical  terminology,  though  repellent  to  many 
students,  was  attractive  to  others,  and  the  enemies  of  the 
system  have  even  accused  its  supporters  of  a  love  of  obscurity 
for  its  own  sake,  or  for  the  sake  of  the  philosophic  depth  which 
obscurity  is  supposed  to  suggest. 

But  internal  dissensions  and  external  attacks  were  now 
imminent.  The  more  moderate  Herbartians  led  by  Stoy  gradu- 
ally found  themselves  more  and  more  outnumbered,  within  the 
"  Union  for  Scientific  Pedagogy,"  by  the  Zillerian  extremists. 
The  Herbartian  press  (which  at  present  numbers  eight  or  nine 
journals)  was  even  richer  in  production  then  than  now,  but  it 
was  very  largely  in  the  hands  of  Zillerians.^  Doctrines  like 
those  of  the  "historical  culture  stages"  and  "concentration 
centres  " — doctrines  not  very  distinctly  found  in  Herbart's  own 
works — won  but  little  acceptance  from  the  more  moderate 
section,  but  were  enthusiastically  championed  as  the  only 
orthodoxy  by  many  of  Ziller's  own  followers.  Among  these 
latter  were  Vogt,  Eein,  the  two  Wigets,  Barth,  Thrandorf, 
Just,  Zillig,  Ackermann,  Niederley,  Beyer,  Bliedner,  Grabs, 
Lange,  Fliigel,  Pickel,  Thilo,  Staude,  Conrad,  and  Florin,  while 
among  the  Herbartians  or  semi-Herbartians  who  refused 
slavishly  to  follow  Ziller  were  Dorpfeld,  Sallwiirk,  Striimpell, 
Kern,  Frick,  Wiessner,  Schumann,  Credner,  and  Frohhch ; 
some  of  these  would  be  regarded  as  followers  of  Stoy. 


^The  Year-books  of  the  Union  were  edited  by  Ziller;  Padagogische 
Stvdien  by  Rein  ;  Erziehungsschule  by  Barth.  Stoy's  own  journal,  Allge- 
meine  Schulzeitung,  expired  in  1882. 


58  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

The  great  offence  which  the  Zillerians  committed  was,  as  we 
have  seen,  to  claim  to  be  alone  "  scientific  ".  This  word  was 
inscribed  on  the  name  of  their  Union  and  on  the  covers  of  their 
journal.  Their  leader  had  pronounced  the  vast  majority  of 
German  teachers  to  be  "  vulgar  pedagogues,"  "  mercenaries," 
and  so  forth,  and  the  German  schools  to  be,  for  the  most  part, 
"  un-educative  "  (in  the  Herbartian  sense).  That  leader  died 
in  1882  before  the  storm  burst  in  full  fury.  On  his  death  his 
Seminar,  like  the  previous  ones  of  Herbart  and  Snoy,  ceased 
to  exist ;  but  the  "  Union  for  Scientific  Pedagogy  "  still  held 
its  ground,  Professor  Vogt  of  Vienna,  a  Catholic,  but  a  de- 
voted Zillerian,  taking  the  place  vacated  by  Ziller,  which,  in 
justice,  ought,  perhaps,  to  have  fallen  to  the  veteran  Stoy. 
But  the  breach  between  the  moderate  and  the  extreme  sections 
was  now  clearly  marked. 

As  early  as  1880  Dr.  von  Sallwurk,^  of  Carlsruhe,  though 
himself  a  member  of  Ziller's  Union,  had  protested,  in  an 
anonymous  work  entitled  Herhart  and  his  Disciples,  against 
the  arrogance  of  the  extremists  and  their  efforts  to  obtain 
patronage  from  the  State.  This  was  a  signal  for  a  number 
of  similar  attacks.  In  1881  Dr.  Bartels,  speaking  at  a  teachers' 
conference  in  Carlsruhe,  raised  objections  co  "  concentration  " 
and  other  doctrines  of  Ziller,  declaring  them  to  be  artificial  and 
impracticable.  Dr.  Sander,  of  Breslau,  raised  similar  protests, 
while  praising  in  no  stinted  terms  the  industry  and  enthusiasm 
of  Ziller.  Frohlich,  another  member  of  the  Union,  expressed 
(1883),  in  a  work  entitled  The  Scientific  Pedagogy  represented 
in  its  Fundamental  Doctrines  and.  elucidated  by  Examples,  his 
disapproval  of  the  arrogance  of  the  Zillerians.  He,  hke  Sall- 
wiirk,  had  once  been  a  follower  of  Ziller,  but  his  zeal  had 
cooled,  and  had  given  place  to  a  critical,  though  still  re- 
spectful, attitude  of  mind.  Especially  did  he  protest  against 
the  "  concentration  "  doctrine  as  containing  "  a  whole  nest  of 


Now  one  of  the  most  eminent  educationists  in  Germany,  editor  of 
Herbaurt's  works,  contributor  to  the  magnificent  Encyclopcedisches  Hand- 
buch  der  Padagogik,  etc. 


Historical  Survey  59 


singularities  ".^  The  "  historical  culture  stages  "  doctrine  and 
the  doctrine  of  Gesinnungs-unterricht  also  came  in  for  criticism. 

Even  enthusiastic  and  avowed  Zillerians  had  not  scrupled  to 
modify  the  proposals  of  their  master.  In  1878  and  the  following 
years  appeared  the  important  work  of  Dr.  Eein  and  his  colleagues, 
Theory  and  Practice  of  Instruction  in  the  Elementary  School 
according  to  Herbartian  Principles?  In  this  work,  perhaps 
the  most  comprehensive  and  laborious  which  has  proceeded 
from  the  Herbartian  school  (besides  a  copious  historical  and 
general  introduction  it  gives  complete  courses  for  all  eight 
school  years),  we  find  Ziller's  scheme  already  altered  in  several 
important  respects.  The  possibility  of  having  one  single  centre 
of  instruction  was  abandoned ;  that  is  to  say,  a  perfect  system 
of  "  concentration  "  was  admitted  to  be  impossible.  Even  Ziller 
himself  had  shown  signs  of  wholesome  and  increasing  modesty, 
and  had  admitted  {e.g.,  in  the  Year-book  of  1881,  and  earlier  in 
a  reply  to  Andreas,  1878)  that  "  concentration  "  in  the  original 
sense  could  not  be  carried  out,  and  that  each  subject  of  instruc- 
tion must  retain  its  own  character,  and  not  be  entirely  subordin- 
ated to  the  claims  and  methods  of  Gesinnungs-unterricht. 

But  a  more  pronounced  opponent  than  any  hitherto  mentioned 
was  now  coming  forward.  Dittes,  in  1870,  had  interrogated 
Ziller  as  to  certain  obscurities  in  the  "  Year-book  "  of  the  Union. 
Ziller's  reply  (in  Stoy's  Schulzeitung ,  1871)  is  declared  by  an 
anti-Zillerian  ^  to  have  been  "  angry  "  and  "  offensive  ".*  Other 
controversies  followed  between  the  two  ;  and  in  1881  Dittes,  in 
his  journal  Pddagogium,  called  attention  to  Sallwiirk's  attack 
(see  above),  and  in  1884  to  that  of  Frohlich.  Dittes,  who  was 
a  Vienna  educationist  of  no  mean  standing,  was  especially  in- 
dignant at  the  Zillerian  claim  to  be  alone  "  scientific  ". 

He  now  devoted  himself  to  a  thorough  criticism  of  the  Her- 
bartian principles.     His  chief  articles  upon  the  subject  appeared 

^  Ein  ganzes  Nest  von  Sonderbarkeiten. 

"^  Theorie  und  Praxis  des  Volksschul  -  unterrichts  nach  Herbartschen 
Grundscitzen. 

^  Wesendonck.     The  Schule  Herbart-Ziller,  p.  33, 
■*  "  Geharnischt "  and  "  widerwartig  ". 


6o  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

in  PMagogium,  1885-6.  They  were  the  signal  for  a  whole 
series  of  attacks  and  counter-attacks  distinguished  by  no  small 
degree  of  acerbity  on  both  sides. 

Frohlich,  who  had  hitherto  been  treated  with  frosty  indul- 
gence by  the  Zillerians,  now,  on  the  appearance  of  Dittes  in  the 
field,  came  in  for  his  share  of  condemnation.  Zillig,  one  of  the 
ablest  of  Ziller's  followers,  replied  to  the  ex-Zillerian  in  the 
pages  of  Pddagogischen  Studien  (1884) ;  while  the  pens  of 
Rein  {ibid.),  Beyer  (Erziehungsschule),  Thrandorf  (ibid.),  and 
Vogt  (in  the  "Elucidations"  of  the  "Year-book")  followed 
suit  in  the  Zillerian  defence.  The  controversy  was  a  typical 
one.  Dittes,  in  the  opinion  of  Thrandorf,  was  a  "pope" 
"hurling  thunderbolts,"  etc. ;  in  the  opinion  of  Vogt,  guilty  of 
"crafty  mendacity,"^  etc.,  and  deserving,  in  consequence  of  his 
"  radicalism,"  to  see  his  journal  (Padagogium)  confiscated  by 
a  respectable  Government  which  wages  war  against  socialism, 
anarchism,  and  other  destructive  forces. 

There  was  really  nothing  in  the  articles  of  Dittes  to  have 
called  forth  such  language.  He  was  scrupulously  respectful 
towards  Her  hart,  freely  and  frankly  admitting  the  value  of 
certain  of  his  proposals.  Not  a  word  of  abuse  or  ill-taste  can 
be  found  in  his  seven  or  eight  articles.  Why  then  the  severity 
of  the  Zillerian  rejoinder? 

We  must  take  the  Germans  as  we  find  them.  They  love 
controversy.  Their  minds  are  alive.  They  are  strong  parti- 
sans. Their  polemical  vocabulary  is  ample.  Their  methods 
are  such  as  would  scarcely  be  possible  in  England.  Whether, 
when  they  accuse  each  other  of  "mendacity,"  "ignorance," 
"folly,"  etc.,  they  are  to  be  taken  quite  seriously,  may  be 
doubted.  But  certain  it  is  that  the  amount  of  educational 
literature  in  Germany  is  so  enormous  as  to  betoken  an  interest 
in  Education  of  which  we  in  England  have  not  the  faintest 
conception.  Now  interest  in  a  subject  easily  degenerates  into 
fanaticism,  and  when,  as  with  the  Herbartian  movement,  a  deep 
moral  motive  is  present,  this  fanaticism  may  take  extreme  forms. 

^  Arglistige  Verlogenheit, 


Historical  Survey  6i 


In  these  controversies  the  best  of  the  argument  was  often  on 
the  side  of  the  Herbart-Ziller  party.  But  truth  compels  the 
confession  that  most  of  the  ill-manners  was  also  on  the  same 
side.  The  reason  we  have  seen.  The  zeal  of  these  men  was 
so  intense  as  to  generate  bitterness  and  intolerance  towards 
those  who,  less  earnest,  as  they  thought,  than  themselves,  were 
engaged  in  pouring  the  cold  water  of  criticism  upon  the  new 
Gospel.  "  Away  with  your  petty  criticisms  !  Men  are  perish- 
ing." Some  such  feeling  as  that  here  represented  lay  at  the 
base  of  Herbartian  intolerance. 

Probably  if  a  school  of  educational  workers  were  to  arise  in 
our  country  animated  by  the  same  spirit  of  moral  reform  which 
pervades  Herbartianism,  history  would  repeat  itself.  Apathy, 
ignorance,  professional  "  touchiness  "  and  conceit,  would  all  be 
thrown  into  the  scale  against  the  new  movement.  "Who  are 
you  that  you  should  try  to  teach  us  who  have  been  school- 
masters for  thirty  years  ?  "  would  be  the  cry  from  thousands  of 
teachers  who,  in  all  their  lives,  had  never  given,  or  perhaps 
had  never  had  the  opportunity  to  give,  an  hour's  serious  and 
independent  thought  to  their  professional  work.  Small  wonder 
if  the  new  enthusiasts  responded  with  accusations  of  narrow- 
mindedness  and  unintelHgence,  or  dubbed  the  critics  "vulgar 
pedagogues,"  "  mere  practitioners,"  "  people  whose  mental 
horizon  ended  with  their  noses,"  and  so  forth.  The  latter  label, 
indeed,  would  not  be  inappropriate  if  fixed  upon  some  present- 
day  schoolmasters,  who,  as  Professor  Adams  says,^  can  be  shown 
to  be,  with  all  their  modesty,  "  arrogant  and  intolerant  empirics  ". 

Considerations  such  as  these  throw  light  upon  Herbartian 
intolerance,  though  without  entirely  excusing  it.  A  body  of 
moral  and  educational  reformers  faced  by  the  problem  of  com- 
parative apathy  among  teachers,  and  yet  conscious  of  a  high 
mission,  almost  inevitably  developed  a  tone  of  arrogance  and 
contempt.  Their  earnestness  blinded  them  to  the  value  of  the 
work  of  non-Herbartians ;  they  became  morbidly  sensitive  to 
criticism,  and  could  see  nothing  in  it  but  the  selfish  cry  of  time- 
servers  and  mercenaries,  "  Trouble  us  not ". 


^  Herbartian  Psychology,  p.  5. 


62  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

8.  More  Controversy. 

To  resume  our  historical  survey. 

Little  need  be  said  as  to  the  progress  of  the  Herbartian 
movement  in  Switzerland.  The  Protestant  cantons  were  some- 
what receptive,  and  one  of  the  ablest  of  the  Zillerians,  Theodor 
Wiget,  founded  and  edited  a  journal  in  the  interests  of  the  new 
Gospel.^     A  critic  appeared  in  the  person  of  Kuoni  (1883). 

About  the  same  time  a  conference  of  Saxony  school  directors 
discussed  the  question,  "  How  far  are  the  Herbart-Stoy-Ziller 
principles  to  be  applied  in  the  higher  schools?"  and  reports 
came  in  from  various  sides.  On  the  whole  the  verdict  of  the 
conference  was  favourable,  though  Herbart's  psychology  was  con- 
demned as  one-sided  and  "  unchristian,"  and  certain  of  Ziller's 
proposals,  such  as  "concentration,"  came  in  for  criticism. 

Simultaneously  with  the  Pddagogium  articles  of  Dittes  ap- 
peared an  able  work  by  Dr.  Bartels,  entitled  The  Applicability 
of  the  Herhart-Z iller-Stoy  Principles  of  Teaching  to  Instruction 
in  Lower  Schools. 

Bartels  saw  the  good  points  in  Herbartianism,  but  showed 
that  many  of  its  doctrines  were  not  by  any  means  absolutely 
original.  He  put  in  a  word  for  the  doctrine  of  ' '  concentric 
circles  "^  (the  polar  opposite  of  the  "culture  epochs"  doctrine 
and  strongly  opposed  by  Zillerians).  He  approved  of  the 
"formal  steps"  doctrine,  though  he  saw  that  it  could  easily 
degenerate  into  rigid  formahsm.  The  "  culture  steps  "  doctrine 
he  attacked.  Finally  he  claimed  that  the  Zillerian  proposals 
could  not  possibly  be  carried  into  complete  execution.  "Not 
pretty  words  but  deeds  do  we  wish  to  see."  He  was  answered 
by  Gopfert. 

Eeaders  of  the  present  work  have  probably  now  learnt  enough 
upon  the  subject  of  the  Herbartian  controversies  in  Germany. 


^  Swiss  Pages  for  Edticative  Instruction. 

*  The  doctrine  that  the  youngest  pupils  should  be  taught  a  little  matter 
which  is  to  be  increased  and  recapitulated  as  they  go  up  the  school,  the 
instruction  widening  out,  so  to  speak,  from  a  fixed  centre.  The  Zillerians 
select  s^>ecial  matter  for  each  year. 


Historical  Survey  63 


In  truth  the  story  is  a  long  and,  to  some  extent,  a  wearisome 
one.  The  same  points  which  were  agitated  in  1882  are  being 
agitated  at  the  present  moment,  the  same  arguments  are  being 
brought  forward,  the  same  charges  being  made,  now  as  then. 
Wearisome,  truly,  and  yet  interesting  in  a  way,  for  such  a 
wealth  of  controversial  zeal  and  such  irrefragable  indications  of 
interest  in  education  are  simply  unintelligible  in  our  country. 
We  cannot  imagine  what  these  Germans  have  to  write  about. 
But  they  do  write,  and  they  do  think  ;  and  though  much  of  their 
writing  and  thinking  is  but  going  over  old  ground  it  is  not  old 
ground  to  British  readers. 

There  is  little  need  to  consider  the  controversies  which 
followed  upon  the  time  at  which  we  have  arrived,  though  one 
which  centred  round  the  name  of  Dr.  Just  of  Altenburg  (an 
able  Hving  Zillerian)  might  have  merited  some  attention. 

Eissmann's  name  should  also  be  mentioned.  Though  he  has 
contributed  no  large  work  to  the  Herbartian  question,  he  has 
vigorously  attacked  the  Zillerians  in  a  series  of  articles  which, 
commencing  in  1880,  have  appeared  in  various  journals  for 
years  past.  His  arguments  are  the  old  ones:  that  the  Zillerians 
are  arrogant,  their  theories  insecure  owing  to  the  comparative 
neglect  of  the  teachings  of  experience,  the  claims  of  society  are 
ignored  in  favour  of  those  of  the  individual,  and  so  forth.  Other 
anti-Zillerians  who  wrote  during  the  critical  years  of  Herbar- 
tianism  were  Willmann  (an  Herbartian  but  not  a  bigoted  one), 
Wesendonck  ^  (a  frequent  contributor  to  Dittes'  journal,  Pdda- 
gogium),  and  Ostermann.  The  latter  writer  pubhshed  in  1884 
a  very  important  and  valuable  criticism  of  the  psychology  of 
the  Herbartian  school  under  the  title,  The  Chief  Errors  of  the 
Herbartian  Psychology  and  their  Pedagogical  Consequences.^ 
This  was  a  very  necessary  piece  of  work ;  for  though  Herbart's 
psychology  had  often  been  criticised  by  professional  philoso- 


^  The  present  writer  is  much  indebted  to  Wesendonck's  articles  for  infor- 
mation on  the  history  of  the  Herbartian  controversy. 

^  Die  hauptsachlichsten  Irrtilmer  der  Herbartschen  PsycJvologie  und  ihre 
padagogisclien  Konsequenzen  (Schulzesche  Hof-Buchhandlung,  Oldenburg). 


64  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

phers,  and  though  incidental  criticisms  had  appeared  in  peda- 
gogical books  and  articles,  apparently  no  writer  had  attempted 
a  complete  popular  investigation  of  the  whole  psychological 
side  of  Herbart's  work.  Ostermann  performed  his  task  well. 
He  showed  how  impossible  it  was  to  resolve  the  whole  mental 
life  into  a  presentational  series :  how,  if  the  attempt  be  made, 
it  results  in  an  undervaluing  of  the  other  sides  of  mental  life 
(Feeling,  etc.)  and  also  an  undervaluing  of  physical  Education ; 
and  how  the  later  psychologists  of  the  Herbartian  school  have 
substantially  departed  from  the  purely  presentational  stand- 
point of  their  master.  He  draws  the  inference  that  this 
standpoint  is  clearly  an  impossible  one.  His  work  is  one  of 
the  few  which  are  absolutely  indispensable  to  the  student  of 
the  Herbartian  question. ^ 

And  so  the  controversy  has  gone  on  down  to  the  present 
time.  Men  come  forward  with  attacks  upon  Herbart's  psychology 
or  Ziller's  "  culture  steps  "  doctrine  :  they  retail  the  old  argu- 
ments ;  they  receive  the  same  answers.  What  happened  in 
the  case  of  Ostermann  happened  more  recently  in  the  case  of 
Professor  Paul  Natorp,  of  Marburg,  who,  in  1897,  delivered  a 
course  of  eight  pedagogical  lectures  during  the  vacation  at  that 
University.  He  took  for  their  title,  Herhart,  Pestalozzi  and  the 
Present-day  Problems  of  Educational  Doctrine  ;  ^  dealt  with  the 
question  mainly  from  the  philosophical  standpoint ;  claimed  (as 
a  Neo-Kantian)  that  Will  rather  than  presentations  should 
receive  the  chief  stress  in  any  educational  doctrine,  and  finally 
urged  that  Pestalozzi's  standpoint  was  sounder  and  more 
philosophic  than  Herbart's.  Natorp's  work  is  more  important 
from  the  standpoint  of  theory  than  from  that  of  practice  in 

^  The  Herbartian  defence  against  Ostermann  fell  to  Pastor  0.  Fliigel. 
In  1887  appeared  his  Ostermann  ilber  Herbarts  Psychologie  (Beyer,  Lan- 
gensalza)  ;  Ostermann  replied  with  Zur  Herbart-Frage  (Schulzesche  Hof- 
Buchhandlung,  Oldenburg,  1888) ;  Fliigel  followed  in  the  Zeitschrift  fiir 
Exacte  Philosophie,  1888 ;  and  Ostermann  gave  the  final  touches  in  the 
Pddagogischen  Jahresbericht,  1888. 

^  Herbart,  Pestalozzi  und  die  heutigen  Aufgaben  der  Erziehvmgslehre 
(Fromman,  Stuttgart). 


Historical  Survey  65 


the  narrower  sense,  and  he  hardly  mentions  Ziller.  This  is 
always  a  mistake  ;  for  the  Herbartian  system  is  'par  excellence 
a  pedagogical  system,  and  on  its  excellence  as  such  it  must 
stand  or  fall.  Doubtless  its  philosophical  "  foundations  "  have 
to  be  reckoned  with,  but  it  is  a  mistake  to  suppose  that  the 
imperfection  of  these  supposed  foundations  is  necessarily  trace- 
able also  in  the  superstructure.  Historically,  we  have  seen, 
Herbartianism  began  as  a  pedagogical  system,  and  its  philosophi- 
cal principles  were  sought  for  subsequently.  Possibly,  therefore, 
considerable  modifications  in  the  presentational  doctrine  of  the 
founder  may  be  made  without  any  danger  to  the  system  as  a 
whole. 

This  fact  is  not,  perhaps,  adequately  recognised  even  by  lead- 
ing Herbartians.  At  any  rate  Natorp's  attack,  hke  the  previous 
attacks  of  Dittes,  Ostermann,  and  others,  gave  rise  to  spirited 
rejoinders  from  the  leaders  of  the  school.  These  rejoinders 
appeared  in  the  Zeitschrift  fur  Philosophic  und  Pddagogik  of 
1899,  and  came  from  the  pens  of  Willmann,  Fliigel,  Just,  and 
Eein, 

Among  other  recent  opponents  of  the  new  school  of  pedagogy 
may  be  mentioned  Bergemann  and  Linde,  both  of  whom  have 
made  suggestive  criticisms,  though  most  of  these  may  be  found, 
if  sought  for,  in  earUer  writings.  Still,  a  student  interested  in 
the  most  recent  treatment  of  the  problems  may  be  referred  to 
these  two  writers,  who  show  a  welcome  tendency  to  avoid 
metaphysics.^ 

9.  Present  Position  of  Herbartianism  in  Germany. 

The  present  tendency  of  the  Herbartian  movement  is  in  the 
direction  of  a  practical  grappling  with  the  detailed  problems 
of  school  life.      From   Herbart's    "  reals  "  to  the  teaching  of 

^  Special  mention  should  be  made  of  Linde's  Der  darstellende  Unterricht 
(Brandstetter,  Leipzig)  and  Bergemann's  Die  Lehre  voji  den  formalen  und 
den  Kulturhistorischen  Stufen  (Haacke,  Leipzig).  Both  writers  have 
also  contributed  voluminously  to  Neue  Bahnen  and  other  anti-Herbartian 
journals. 

5 


66  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

Drawing  is  a  far  cry.  The  Herbartians  feel  this.  They  still 
enter,  on  occasion,  into  the  metaphysical  territory,  but  their 
main  interest  is,  as  it  should  be,  the  improvement  of  school 
method.  In  one  department  of  school  work  their  labours  have 
been  specially  notable — the  department  of  Eeligious  Instruction. 
Whatever  opinions  may  be  held  on  this  subject,  all  will  agree 
that  if  Eeligious  Instruction  be  given  at  all  it  should  be  given 
as  well  and  as  thoughtfully  as  possible.  The  Herbartians,  in 
their  zeal  for  character-forming,  have  noted  the  inefl&ciency  and 
absurdity  of  much  of  the  teaching  given  under  the  aegis  of  the 
Lutheran  Church.  Thus  they  have  attacked  catechism-teaching 
and  mechanical  memorising  as  unpsychological,  and  have  ad- 
vocated a  more  careful  selection  of  material  than  is  customary. 
Especially  have  Ziller's  proposals  roused  keen  discussion,  and 
improvements  are  bound  to  follow.  Dorpfeld,  too,  was  a  promi- 
nent advocate  of  reform  in  Eeligious  Instruction. 

The  result  is  that  from  the  Herbartians  have  come,  of  recent 
years,  many  first-class  school-books  dealing  with  this  subject. 
The  three-volumed  work  of  Dr.  Staude  {Preparations  for  the 
Biblical  History  of  the  Old  and  New  Testament)  has  gone 
through  eleven  or  twelve  editions ;  a  laborious  and  thorough 
work  it  is ;  orthodox,  yet  suggestive.  But  Thrandorf  and 
Meltzer  have  gone  further  than  Staude,  as,  for  example, 
in  their  work.  Religious  Instruction  at  the  Middle  Stage 
of  the  Lower  School  and  in  the  Lower  Classes  of  Higher 
Schools  —  Preparations  on  a  Psychological  Method.  Their 
"  method  "  is  not  only  psychological,  for  the  existence  of 
modern  critical  problems  is  by  no  means  unrecognised  in 
this  work,  and  great  theological  writers  like  Wellhausen  are 
frequently  referred  to.  The  second  volume  of  this  work  is 
devoted  to  the  prophets,  an  almost  wholly  unexplored  region 
for  English  teachers  and  pupils. 

Still  more  revolutionary  are  the  works  of  Dr.  Heyn.^  These 
are  for  the  teachers  of  the  highest  classes  in  schools.  There  is 
absolutely  nothing  in  English  which  is  comparable,  in  learning, 

^  Geschichte  Israels,  Geschichte  Jesu. 


Historical  Survey  67 


in  skilfulness  of  treatment,  and  in  rich  suggestiveness  with 
these  works.  The  youths  who  are  instructed  on  Dr.  Heyn's 
plan  must  become  equal  in  knowledge  of  the  Bible  to  the 
majority  of  English  ministers  of  religion.  Let  us  picture 
for  the  moment  boys  in  our  Grammar  Schools  being  in- 
oculated with  Holzmann,  Nippold,  Wellhausen,  Weiss,  and 
Harnack !  Such  a  procedure  may  be  wise  or  unwise ;  it  is 
certainly  striking.  ^ 

The  works  of  Staude,  Thrandorf,  Meltzer,  and  Heyn  are 
types  of  the  kind  of  school-book  now  being  yearly  brought 
out  by  the  Herbartians.  Each  lesson  is  worked  out  on  the 
"  formal  steps  "  principle.  But  merely  to  mention  the  various 
works  which  have  appeared  on  the  subject  of  biblical  teaching 
during  the,  past  four  or  five  years  would  fill  several  pages  of 
this  book.  Five  or  six  works  on  the  life  of  Jesus  appeared 
almost  within  a  single  year,  any  one  of  which  would  excel  in 
boldness  and  thoroughness  of  treatment  any  school-book  we 
possess  on  the  subject, 

EeUgious  Instruction  is  not  the  only  subject  at  which  the 
Herbartians  are  working  hard,  but  it  is  perhaps  the  one  in 
which  their  efforts  appear  most  original.  Articles  and  books 
come  almost  daily  from  their  press  dealing  with  every  depart- 
ment of  school  activity.  Metaphysics,  psychology,  and  ethics 
are  left  to  Pastor  Fliigel  and  other  recognised  veterans  who 
have  survived  the  older  battles ;  the  younger  Herbartians  are 
"  practical  men,"  only,  unlike  the  "  practical"  teachers  of  some 
countries,  these  young  Herbartians  have  principles  of  their  own. 
In  the  present-day  Herbartian  movement  Theory  and  Practice 
have  at  last  met  on  equal  terms. 

"What  then,"  it  may  be  asked,  "is  the  future  of  Herbar- 
tianism?"  The  question  is  no  easy  one  to  answer.  There  is 
much  difl&culty  in  ascertaining  the  precise  number  of  adherents 
which  Herbartianism  possesses  even  if  we  consider  only  its 
native  country.     The  difficulty  arises  from  two  facts.     First,  as 

^  Some  selections  from  Heyn  are  to  be  found  in  the  present  writer's  book 
published  last  year  {The  Reform  of  Moral  and  Biblical  Edtication). 


68  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

we  have  seen,  a  teacher  may  belong  to  an  Herbartian  Society — 
even  to  the  most  extreme  society,  Ziller's  Union — without 
being  committed  to  an  approval  of  all  the  proposals  put  forward 
by  the  leaders  of  the  movement.  Secondly,  there  is  every  reason 
to  believe  that  many  teachers  are  in  sympathy  with  Herbar- 
tianism who  are  quite  unconnected  with  any  organisation. 
These  two  facts  tend,  of  course,  to  neutralise  each  other.  Of 
the  two,  probably  the  second  is  the  more  important.  However, 
there  seems  every  reason  to  believe  that  several  thousands  of 
German  teachers  draw  their  inspiration  from  Herbart  and  his 
followers,  Stoy,  Ziller,  and  Dorpfeld.  Several  hundred  belong 
to  Ziller's  Union,  several  hundred  more  to  the  Westphalian  and 
Thuringian  Societies,  several  hundred  more  to  other  societies. 

Are  the  Herbartian  teachers  of  the  elementary  or  of  the 
secondary  grade?  Of  both.  Herbartianism  has  a  peculiar 
adaptedness  to  elementary  schools.  But  in  Germany,  as  in 
England,  teachers  in  such  schools  are  for  various  reasons  not  so 
able  or  willing  to  adopt  new  proposals  as  teachers  in  higher 
schools.  Still  an  appreciable  influence  has  been  exerted  by 
Herbartianism  upon  the  lower  grades  of  Education,  though 
possibly  a  still  greater  influence  has  been  exerted  upon  the 
higher  or  secondary  grades. 

The  second  test  of  the  condition  of  present-day  Herbartianism 
is  its  literary  output.  This  has  been  already  mentioned  in 
referring  to  Eeligious  Instruction.  But  a  few  further  rough 
statistics  may  be  given. 

Quoting  from  Die  Herbartische  Padagogik  in  der  Litteratur 
(a  supplement  to  Herbart  und  die  Herbartianer),  we  find  that 
from  1895  to  1899  about  200  books  or  articles  came  from  the 
Herbartian  School  dealing  with  general  pedagogical  questions ; 
about  160  dealing  with  the  various  parts  of  Gesinnungs-unter- 
richt,  especially  biblical  teaching  and  history ;  considerable 
numbers  dealing  with  drawing,  languages,  geography,  science, 
and  especially  mathematics.  Other  books  and  articles  deal 
with  discipline,  athletics,  the  philosophy  and  history  of  Educa- 
tion, and  so  forth. 

The  German  Herbartians  alone  produce  certainly  ten  times 


Historical  \  Survey  69 


as  many  serious  contributions  to  educational  literature  as  all 
the  teachers  of  Britain.  Under  "  serious  contributions  "  there 
is  no  need  to  include  "  reading- books,"  "  exercises  in  arith- 
metic," and  so  forth. 

New  men  have  taken  the  places  vacated  by  Stoy,  Dorpfeld 
and  Ziller.  Dr.  Eein  maintains  the  Zillerian  banner  at  Jena ; 
and  though  Dr.  Frick,  once  "the  best-hated  pedagogue  in 
Prussia,"  and  the  head  of  the  great  "Prancke  Stiftungen"  at 
Halle,  is  no  more,^  men  like  Ackermann,  Just,  Ufer,  Lange, 
Sallwiirk  and  Beyer  hve  on,  and  others  are  rising  to  hand  down 
the  Herbartian — in  some  cases  the  Zillerian — tradition.  Though 
its  pages  are  not  confined  to  Herbartian  writers,  the  Encyclojpdd- 
isches  Handbuch  der  Pddagogik  is  really  a  magnificent  tribute 
to  Herbartian  zeal. 

10.  Herbartianism  in  Britain. 

In  the  British  Isles  Herbartianism — mainly  in  the  form  of 
Zillerianism — obtained  a  precarious  foothold  some  years  ago. 
Precarious;  for  the  origin  of  the  movement  was  scarcely 
recognised  and  its  philosophical  meaning  almost  wholly  ignored. 
Still,  one  is  bound  to  recognise  in  the  scheme  adopted  some 
time  back  by  the  Halifax  School  Board  an  honest  attempt  to 
unify  or  "  concentrate  "  the  curriculum.  Thus  the  history  and 
geography  of  Scotland  were  taught  in  connection  with  each 
other ;  ancient  weapons  of  war  (used  at  Bannockburn,  etc.) 
were  to  be  drawn  by  the  children,  while  maps  of  the  Scottish 
river-basins,  plans  of  battles,  composition  themes,  reading- books, 
and  pieces  for  recitation  were  all  to  be  made  or  selected  in 
accordance  with  the  same  general  scheme.  Praiseworthy  though 
the  attempt  was,  it  does  not  appear  to  have  won  the  favour  of 
the  teachers  ;  whether  this  fact  is  a  reflection  on  the  scheme  or 
on  the  teachers  need  not  be  discussed.  In  other  places  a  more 
partial  "concentration"  has  been  or  is  being  attempted;  com- 

^  For  details  of  Dr.  Frick's  work  see  De  Garmo's  Herbart  and  the  Her- 
bartians,  and  Klemm's  European  Schools.  For  Dr.  Rein's  work  at  Jena 
consult  De  Garmo,  or  Miss  Dodd's  Introdvction. 


70  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

position  themes  are  being  selected  from  the  subject  matter  of 
other  lessons  ;  history  and  geography,  sometimes  literature 
also,  are  kept  more  or  less  in  relation  to  each  other.  But,  on 
the  whole,  though  Professor  Armstrong  may  pour  contempt 
upon  the  plan  of  "chopping  our  lives  up  into  three-quarters- 
of-an-hour  sections,  during  each  of  which  we  do  some- 
thing different,"  and  may  urge  the  necessity  for  assimilating 
scholastic  procedure  to  the  methods  of  ordinary  life,^  the 
rigidity  of  the  time-table  seems  to  defy  serious  attack.  Partly 
this  is  due  to  governmental  necessities,  but  largely  also  to  lack 
of  culture  and  want  of  mental  elasticity  on  the  part  of  teachers. 

In  the  higher  departments  of  educational  work  we  see  distinct 
signs  that  the  rigid  barriers  once  existent  even  between  kindred 
subjects  are  being  broken  down,  and  that  the  need  for  grouping 
together  such  subjects  is  becoming  recognised.  The  Matricula- 
tion Examination  of  the  University  of  London  has  borne  witness 
to  this  tendency,  as,  for  example,  when  history  and  geography 
were  grouped  together,  and  "  general  elementary  science " 
rather  than  any  definite  branch  of  science  was  prescribed. 
Workshop  practice,  "  Sloyd,"  etc.,  are  being  made  to  bear  upon 
the  needs  of  the  physical  laboratory ;  ^  reading  books  are  be- 
coming less  "  scrappy  "  ;  the  partitions  between  different 
branches  of  mathematics  are,  thanks  to  Mr.  Branford,^  Pro- 
fessor Perry,  and  others,  being  removed,  and  possibly  before 
long  the  absurdity  of  employing  a  science  teacher  distinct 
from  the  teacher  of  mathematics  will  become  obvious.  The 
increasing  importance  now  being  attached  to  a  general  subject 
like  "  Nature  Study  "  also  witnesses  to  a  growing  feeling  that 
knowledge  should  be  unified  to  the  highest  possible  degree,  and, 
indeed,  one  of  its  advocates  has  suggested  it  as  a  focus  for  the 
curriculum.^ 

The  other  Zillerian  doctrine — that  of  "  culture  stages  " — has 

1  Professor  Laurie  says  somewhere  in  Ms  Institutes,  "  life  and  the  school 
should  be  never  disjointed". 

^  Findlay,  Principles  of  Class  Teaching,  p.  359. 

^  Journal  of  Education,  September,  1898. 

*  Professor  Patrick  Geddes.  See  the  present  writer's  Student's  Herbart, 
p.  74. 


Historical  Survey  71 


also  obtained  some  recognition,  though  possibly  the  impulse  in 
this  case  has  not  come  exclusively  from  Germany,  but  has 
rather  resulted  from  the  general  spread  of  evolutionary  thought. 
Certain  it  is  that  Herbert  Spencer  proclaimed  the  essential 
features  of  the  doctrine  some  years  before  Zillerianism  became 
influential  in  Germany.  In  point  of  fact  the  claim  for  priority 
is  here  rather  ridiculous,  as  the  doctrine  is  traceable  in  many 
writers  who  Hved  long  before  either  Spencer  or  Ziller ;  in 
Goethe,  in  Lessing,  even  in  Clement  of  Alexandria. 

But  the  books  which,  written  in  EngUsh,  bear  the  clearest 
signs  of  Zillerian  influence  are  not  often  Enghsh  books,  except 
in  such  cases  as  that  of  Miss  Dodd's  Introduction  to  Herbartian 
Principles  of  Teaching,  where  the  influence  is  admitted  on  the 
title  page.  They  are  American.  Dr.  Adler's  book, ^  for  example, 
and  the  recently  pubhshed  collection  of  essays  on  Eeligious 
Education  edited  by  Bishop  Potter,^  could  scarcely  have  been 
produced  in  a  country  like  England,  where  neither  teachers  nor 
professors  of  Education  concern  themselves  with  problems  of 
the  kind  therein  discussed.^  Canon  Bell's  Beligious  Education  in 
Secondary  Schools  *  shows  what  might  be  thought  to  be  (when 
looked  at  through  a  magnifying  glass)  a  few  traces  of  Zil- 
lerianism, as  when,  for  example,  he  points  out  that  the  Old 
Testament  has  a  certain  affinity  with  the  moral  nature  of 
young  people.  Much  more  distinctly  is  the  "  culture  stages  " 
doctrine  recognisable  in  the  new  movement  for  reformed  mathe- 
matical and  science  teaching.  Men  are  beginning  to  preach 
that  the  child  in  its  educational  development  must,  to  a  certain 

^  The  Moral  Instruction  of  Children  (Arnold). 

^Principles  of  Beligious  ^dticaiicw. (Longmans).  See  Dr.  Stanley  Hall's 
essay  and  especially  the  words  already  quoted  :  "  The  child  has  to  repeat 
a  great  many  pre-Christian  stages  of  evolution  in  its  own  life,"  for 
"  Christianity  came  late  in  the  history  of  the  world."  We  must  "  bring 
the  stress  of  teaching  Christianity  a  little  later  than  we  put  it  ".  Clearly, 
Ziller  has  his  up-to-date  followers  ! 

^  Professor  Adams's  little  Primer  on  Teaching,  with  Special  Reference  to 
Sunday  School  Work  (T.  &  T.  Clark)  is  a  recent  and  welcome  exception  to 
this  statement. 

*  Macmillan. 


72  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

extent,  recapitulate  the  history  of  the  race,  discovering  anew 
the  composition  of  the  atmosphere,  passing  from  empirical 
mathematics  to  abstract,  and  so  forth.  The  doctrine  is  not 
without  its  difficulties  ;  but  it  is  also  not  without  a  rich  and 
almost  immeasurable  suggestiveness. 

But,  after  all,  "concentration"  and  "culture  stages"  are 
Herbartian  doctrines  only  in  a  derived  sense.  Absolutely  Her- 
bartian  are  the  doctrine  of  the  formal  steps,  the  doctrine  of 
many-sided  Interest,  and  the  emphasis  upon  the  value  of 
humanistic  subjects  (history,  literature,  etc.).  How  fare  these 
in  Britain  ?     The  answer  is  disappointing. 

True,  the  five  steps  of  Instruction  are  used  in  several  of  the 
training  institutions  connected  with  Universities  or  University 
Colleges,  and  recently  a  disappointing  book  of  lessons  supposed 
to  be  drawn  up  along  Herbartian  lines  has  been  published. 
But,  on  the  whole,  this  undoubtedly  valuable  part  of  the  Her- 
bartian system  has  been  neglected,  and  probably  will  continue 
to  be  neglected  until  the  nation  and  until  boards  of  managers 
definitely  ask  for  new  light  and  new  methods. 

The  great  central  Herbartian  doctrine  of  "many-sided 
Interest "  has  exerted  practically  no  influence  beyond  a  super- 
ficial one.  It  may  have  helped  to  make  lessons  easy  and 
"interesting,"  but  this  is  not  Herbartianism. ^  "Instruction 
requires  toil  on  the  pupil's  part."  The  vital  moral  bearings  of 
the  doctrine  have  scarcely  been  thought  of,  and  even  our  most 
brilliant  writers  on  the  system  seem  fearful  lest,  by  straying 
into  this  ethical  region,  they  will  earn  the  painful  reproach  of 
being  "  fanatical ".  The  lady  writers  on  the  subject  here  show 
a  good  example,  but,  on  the  whole,  confession  must  be  made 
that  the  proclamation  of  the  gospel  of  "many-sided  Interest" 
— a  gospel  of  moral  reform  and  spiritual  regeneration — has  been 
feeble  and  unworthy. 

Strangely,  sadly,  unaccountably  obtuse  have  we  been  to  the 
last  Herbartian  doctrine  here  to  be  mentioned — the  doctrine  of 
Gesinnungs-unterricht  or  "  character-forming  Instruction,"  the 

^  See  the  Studenfs  Herbart,  pp.  51-53. 


Mis  tor  teal  Survey  73 


doctrine  which  sees  enormous  and  unique  value  in  fairy  tale, 
legend,  history,  and  literature.  With  a  national  history  far 
surpassing  that  of  Germany  or  America  in  continuity  and  in 
capabilities  for  moral  instruction,  we  are  content  to  remain 
uninspired  by  its  lessons,  unmoved  by  its  great  names,  ignorant 
of  its  movements,  deaf  to  its  voices.  A  true  educationist,  when 
told  of  recent  revivals  of  "patriotism,"  can  but  smile  sardoni- 
cally when  he  contemplates  the  damning  facts  that  Alfred  the 
Great  and  Earl  Simon  are  practically  unknown  in  the  land 
they  loved ;  that  it  is  the  hardest  possible  task  to  get  a  "  patrio- 
tic "  audience  (or  any  other  audience)  to  read  the  history  of 
their  own  land,  still  more  that  of  any  other  land;  that  the 
elementary  schoolmaster,  called  upon  to  conduct  an  Evening 
Continuation  School,  may  babble  "  Commercial  Arithmetic," 
but  will  scarcely  even  dream  of  opening  the  sealed  book  of 
English  literature,  though  brought  down  to  our  very  alleys  in  a 
penny  form  ^ ;  that  our  very  Churches,  though  professedly  wor- 
shipping "whatsoever  things  are  true,  whatsoever  things  are 
honourable,  whatsoever  things  are  just,  whatsoever  things  are 
pure,  whatsoever  things  are  lovely,"  ^  show  by  their  weekly 
bills  of  fare  that  the  "  whatsoever  "  is,  for  them,  pitiably  poor ; 
that  the  secondary  schools  of  Britain  teach  more  Greek  and 
Latin  than  English,  and  that  the  English  they  teach  is  sometimes 
technical  and  uninspiring  ;  and  that  our  very  M.P.'s  would,  in 
the  opinion  of  an  eminent  authority,  make  fewer  mistakes  if 
they  knew  a  little  more  history.  ^  Astounding,  unaccountable, 
well-nigh  criminal  is  our  neglect  of  the  subjects  which,  above 
all  others,  are  culture-giving  and  character-forming.  But  it  is 
of  a  piece  with  our  whole  conduct.  With  one  voice  we  hail 
"  Eehgious  Instruction"  as  peculiarly  "sacred,"  and  proceed 
to  fence  it  off  and  deprive  it  of  interest ;  with  another  voice  we 
hail  all  other  Instruction  as  "secular,"  and  proceed  to  degrade 
it  to  base  utiHtarian  ends.  Pitman's  shorthand  displaces  his- 
tory! "commercial  arithmetic"  displaces  literature! 

^  Mr.  Stead's  Penny  Poets,  etc.  "^  Philippians  iv.  8. 

"  Address  of  the  President  of  the  Royal  Historical  Society,  20th  February, 
1902. 


74  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


Only  from  one  standpoint  is  the  outlook  satisfactory ;  Her- 
bartian  writings  are  now  fairly  copious  in  Britain,  and  are 
steadily  increasing  in  number.  Mr.  and  Mrs.  Felkin  deserve 
the  gratitude  of  all  educationists  for  their  pioneer  work  ^ ;  thanks 
mainly  to  them  Herbart  can  now  be  read  in  English,  and  their 
excellent  introductions  have  done  much  to  make  his  doctrines 
known.  Miss  MuUiner's  book^  is  not  so  well  known  as  it 
deserves  to  be  ;  Miss  Dodd's  ^  is  also  a  good  piece  of  work  on 
constructive  lines,  written  with  the  ardour  of  an  enthusiast. 
There  are  translations  of  Ufer,  Eein,  and  Lange  (in  each  case 
by  Americans) ;  there  is  Professor  De  Garmo's  Herbart  and  the 
Herbartians  ^  with  its  admirable  account  of  the  labours  of 
Herbart' s  followers,  Ziller,  Eein,  Lange,  Stoy,  and  Frick,  and 
of  the  progress  of  the  movement  in  America ;  there  is  the  little 
Student's  Herbart  ^  by  the  present  writer,  with  its  regressive 
treatment  of  the  whole  question;  above  all  these  are  two 
books  of  marked  originaUty,  that  of  Professor  Adams  and 
that  of  Dr.  Findlay.  The  former^  it  would  be  superfluous 
to  praise ;  it  is  unique.  The  latter,  •"  except  where,  incidentally, 
the  author's  knowledge  of  the  life  of  Nicholas  Nickleby 
shows  signs  of  excusable  rustiness,  is  also  admirable  in  every 
respect — nay,  in  certain  matters  markedly  original.  It  is  the 
very  book  which  British  Education  needs ;  mainly  Herbartian, 
as  when  it  lays  stress  upon  the  content  of  the  mind,  the  process 
of  apperception,  the  use  of  the  formal  steps,  the  value  of  history, 
and  so  forth;  but  boldly  departing  from  Herbartian  doctrine 
where  the  latter  reveals  its  weakness,  namely  in  that  department 
of  scholastic  work  which  deals  not  with  the  conferring  of  ideas, 
but  with  the  imparting  of  skill  in  speech  and  in  other  directions. 

^Herbart's  Science  of  Education,  and  Letters  and  Lectures  (Sonnen- 
schein) ;  also  Introduction  to  Herbart' s  Science  and  Practice  of  Education 
(Sonnenschein). 

*  Application  of  Psychology  to  Education  (Sonnenschein). 

^  Introduction  to  the  Herbartian  Principles  of  Teaching  (Sonnenschein). 

*  Heinemann.  "  Sonnenschein. 

'  Herbartian  Psychology  applied  to  Education  (Isbister). 
'  Principles  of  Class  Teaching  (Macmillan). 


Historical  Survey  75 


But  nowhere  in  Britain  is  there  an  Herbartian  school,  training 
college,  or  institute.  Nowhere,  at  least,  except  in  Manchester, 
where  Miss  Dodd,  with  the  usual  enthusiasm  of  a  Zillerian,  has 
succeeded  in  founding  a  practising  school  in  connection  with 
the  Day  Training  College  of  that  city.  It  is  significant  that 
Day  Training  Colleges,  unless  an  Herbartian  happens  to  be  in 
charge,  have  to  exist  without  such  an  institution. 

11.  Herbartianism  in  America  and  Elsewhere. 

Far  more  impressive  is  Herbartian  progress  in  America  than 
in  Britain.  The  reader  cannot  help  having  been  struck  by  the 
fact  that  a  number  of  the  works  above  mentioned  are  by 
Americans.  The  truth  is,  as  Dr.  Eckoff  says,^  "  American 
educators  have  begun  to  live,  move,  and  have  their  being  in 
an  atmosphere  of  Herbartianism  ".  That  this  has  its  dangers 
is  obvious  from  the  complaint  raised  by  some  critics  that  "  soft 
pedagogy  "  is  too  prevalent  west  of  the  Atlantic,  and  there  is 
little  doubt  that,  in  the  hands  of  extremists,  Herbartianism  can 
become  deficient  in  strenuousness  and  backbone.  But,  on  the 
whole,  the  new  movement  is  working  wonders.  It  makes 
teachers  into  enthusiasts,  and  any  movement  that  can  accom- 
pUsh  such  a  task  as  that  must  be  almost  infinitely  valuable. 

In  1892  a  "  Herbart  Club  "  was  organised  at  Saratoga,  and 
consists  mainly  of  teachers.  The  works  of  Lange  and  Ufer  and 
Herbart' s  Psychology  have  been  translated  by  members  of  this 
club.  Professor  De  Garmo,  one  of  its  leading  spirits,  has  also 
pubhshed  several  valuable  works  of  his  own  upon  the  subject.^ 
Dr.  McMurry  and  Colonel  Parker  have  contributed  to  the  theory 
and  practice  of  "  culture  stages  "  and  "  concentration  "  ;  to  the 
latter  of  which  American  history  somewhat  lends  itself  (periods 
of  settlement,  etc.).  Hiawatha  is  extensively  used  in  American 
schools,  and  its  use  is  to  an  extent  defended  on  Zillerian  or 


*  Herbart's  ABC  of  Sense  Perception,  p.  xiv.  (Arnold). 
^His  latest,  Interest  and  Ediication  (Macmillan),  presents  some  special 
features  of  importance.     See  pp.  96-7. 


76  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

Herbartian  principles.  Dr.  Dewey's  name  should,  of  course,  be 
mentioned  also.  But  it  would  be  superfluous  to  expatiate  furtfier 
upon  the  progress  of  the  movement  among  our  cousins. 

Nor  is  there  special  need  to  refer  to  its  progress  in  other 
countries.  If  we  are  to  judge  by  the  bibliography  of  Herbart- 
ianism, Austria,  Holland,  Scandinavia,  Hungary,  Switzerland, 
have  all  received  stimulus,  while,  on  the  other  hand,  Latin  and 
Sclavonic  nations  have  paid  but  little  attention  to  the  move- 
ment. It  represents  the  one  great  effort  of  the  Protestant  and 
Teutonic  world  to  make  Education  simultaneously  into  a  Science 
and  into  a  Gospel.  Say  what  we  will,  criticise  how  we  like,  it 
is  a  movement  to  be  reckoned  with. 


PART  III. 

HEEBAETIAN  LITEEATUEE  IN  ENGLISH. 

It  has  been  thought  well  to  give,  as  supplementary  to  the  pre- 
ceding historical  sketch,  notices  of  the  chief  works  in  English 
which  are,  partly  or  wholly,  Herbartian  in  spirit  or  origin. 
Such  works  may  be  divided  into  three  groups  : — 

(1)  Translations  of  the  writings  of  Herbart  and  his  followers  ; 
such  translations  are  generally  prefaced  by  expository  introduc- 
tions, and  may,  to  this  extent,  fall  in  group  two. 

(2)  Expositions  of  Herbartian  principles,  and  of  the  Herbar- 
tian movement  in  general. 

(3)  Works  which,  though  based  largely  or  wholly  on  Herbar- 
tian principles,  represent  independent  efforts  at  construction ; 
works  which  are  genuinely  national,  though  they  may  owe  much 
inspiration  to  foreign  writers. 

As  witnesses  to  the  progress  of  the  Herbartian  movement, 
the  third  group  is  the  most  important,  and  the  first  the  least 
important  of  the  three.  The  pioneer  work  of  translation  under- 
taken by  Mr.  and  Mrs.  Felkin  was  necessary,  but,  once  accom- 
plished, had  to  give  place  to  more  constructive  efforts  in  the 
direction  of  nationalising  Herbartianism.  Britain  will  scarcely 
borrow  the  Herbartian  system  en  bloc,  hence  the  most  signifi- 
cant books  on  the  subject  are,  at  the  present  moment,  those 
like  Dr.  Findlay's,  in  which  we  see  the  system  arraying  itself 
in  garments  not  obviously  foreign. 

In  the  following  notices  special  attention  will  therefore  be 
given  to  the  several  books  belonging  to  the  third  class,  less 
attention  to  those  of  the  second  class,  and  least  attention  of  all 


78  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

to  those  books,  however  valuable  in  themselves,  which  are  but 
translations  of  German  originals. 

(1)  Translations. 

The,  Science  of  Ediwation ;    Its   General   Principles  Deduced 
from   its   Aim  :    and   the  Esthetic  Bevelation  of  the 
World.       By   J.    F.    Herbart.       Translated    from    the 
German   with   a   Biographical   Introduction  by  Henry 
M.  and  Emmie  Felkin.      (Sonnenschein.) 
This  book  is  indispensable  to  the  genuine  student  of  education 
unless  he  is  able  to  read  Herbart  in  the  original ;  it  is  the  trans- 
lation of  Herbart's  masterpiece,  Allgemeine  Pddagogik.    But  the 
work  would  be  difficult  for  a  beginner,  though  the  translators 
have  added  a  useful  and  able  introduction. 

Letters  and  Lectures  on  Education.  By  J.  F.  Herbart.  Trans- 
lated from  the  German  and  Edited  with  an  Introduction 
by  Henry  M.  and  Emmie  Felkin.     (Sonnenschein.) 

Herbart's  letters,  here  translated,  are  those  he  wrote  to 
Herr  von  Steiger,  the  father  of  the  three  pupils  placed  under 
his  charge  during  the  years  1797-9.  They  represent  Herbart's 
earliest  thoughts  on  educational  matters,  but  are  otherwise 
unimportant. 

Herbart's  lectures,  on  the  other  hand,  represent  his  most 
mature  thought.  They  were  delivered  only  a  few  years  before 
his  death,  and  many  years  after  the  composition  of  the  Allge- 
meine Pddagogik.  They  are  considerably  easier  in  every  respect 
than  that  work. 

Outlines  of  Edu/iational  Doctrines.   By  J.  F.  Herbart.  Translated 
by  A.  F.  Lange.    Annotated  by  Charles  de  Garmo.    (The 
Macmillan  Company.) 
This  work,  despite  its  title,  is  really  a  translation  of  Herbart's 
Lectures,  and  is  thus  a  duplicate  of  the  last  work.     With  so 
much  Herbartian  territory  still  untrodden  {e.g.,  the  works  of 
Dorpfeld)  it  is  to  be  regretted  that  two  authors  should  under- 
take the  same  task. 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  79 

Still  this  translation  is  a  good  one  ;  moreover  Dr.  de  Garmo's 
notes  touch  upon  some  of  the  recent  advances  in  American 
pedagogy. 

Herhart's  A  B  G  of  Sense-Perception  and  Minor  Pedagogical 
Works.  Translated,  with  Introduction,  Notes  and 
Commentary,  by  W.  J.  Bckoff.  (Appleton,  New  York ; 
Arnold,  London.) 

This  is  a  translation  of  several  short  works  and  addresses 
produced  or  delivered  by  Herbart  a  few  years  after  the  com- 
position of  the  Steiger  letters.  They  are  specially  interesting 
as  dealing  with  Herhart's  early  views  upon  Pestalozzi  ;  the 
educationist  is  feeling  his  way  towards  a  more  complete  and 
scientific  system  than  that  of  his  great  contemporary  and  in- 
spirer.  The  chief  work  in  this  volume  [The  ABC  of  Anschauung) 
deals  with  the  teaching  of  mathematics. 

The  Application  of  Psychology  to  the  Science  of  Education.  By 
J.  F.  Herbart.  Translated  and  Edited  with  Notes  and 
an  Introduction  to  the  Study  of  Herbart  by  Beatrice  C. 
Mulliner.     (Sonnenschein.) 

These  letters  were  written  during  Herhart's  Kbnigsberg  period, 
and  represent  much  more  mature  views  and  wider  experience 
than  the  Steiger  letters,  the  early  works  published  at  Gottingen, 
and  even  the  Allgemeine  Pddagogik.  Many  of  the  passages  con- 
tained in  them  were  subsequently  employed  in  Herhart's  Text- 
book of  Psychology.  The  present  volume  will  be,  perhaps,  more 
attractive  to  the  majority  of  students  on  account  of  Miss 
Mulliner's  able  Introduction  than  on  account  of  the  letters 
themselves.  The  editor  has  illumined  the  subject  with  many 
wise  remarks  and  pertinent  references ;  she  writes  with  ardour 
and  force. 

A  Text-book  of  Psychology.  By  J.  F.  Herbart.  Translated  by 
Margaret  K.  Smith.  (Appleton,  New  York ;  Arnold, 
London.) 

Important  for  the  student  of  Herhart's  psychology,  but  re- 
pellant,  owing  to  its  very  condensation,  to  the  average  student. 


8o  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

Outlines  of  Pedagogics.     By  Prof.  W.  Eein.     Translated  by  C. 

C.  and  Ida  J.  van  Liew,  with  additional  notes  by  the 

former.  (Sonnenschein.) 
This  is  a  translation  of  Padagogik  im  Grundriss  by  the 
prominent  Herbartian  upon  whom  has  fallen  the  mantle  of 
Ziller.  It  is  brief,  but  clear  and  admirable,  and  will  convey  to 
most  readers  a  favourable  impression  of  modern  Zillerianism. 
The  translator,  in  a  few  brief  notes,  has  helped  to  show  the 
attitude  of  American  thought  towards  the  movement. 

Introduction  to  the  Pedagogy  of  Herbart.  By  C.  Ufer.  Author- 
ised Translation  from  the  Fifth  German  Edition  under 
the  auspices  of  the  Herbart  Club.  By  J.  C.  Zinser. 
Edited  by  Charles  De  Garmo.  (Heath,  Boston  ;  Isbister, 
London.) 
C.  Ufer  is  a  prominent  German  Zillerian.     His  work,  here 

translated  through  the  activity  of  the  American  "  Herbart  Club," 

is  similar  in  size  and  tone  to  Prof.  Rein's. 

Apperception.    A  Monograph  on  Psychology  and  Pedagogy.    By 
Dr.  K.  Lange.     Translated  by  members  of  the  Herbart 
Club.     Edited  by  Charles  de  Garmo.     (Heath,  Boston ; 
Isbister,  London.) 
This  magnificent  work  on  the  psychology  of  Apperception, 
and  on  the  pedagogical  consequences  and  the  historical  develop- 
ment of  the  doctrine,  needs  no  praise.     No  other  book,  except 
possibly  Dorpfeld's  Denken  und   Geddchtnis,   has   ever   dealt 
so  ably  with  the  subject.    At  the  same  time  the  translator's 
terminology  is  confusing  in  one  place,  the  word  "  perception  '* 
standing  for  what  most  British  psychologists  would  call  "  sen- 
sation ". 

(2)  Expositions  of  Hebbabtianism  as  Distinguished  FBOSf 
Tbanslations. 

An  Introduction  to  HerharVs  Science  and  Practice  of  Education. 
By  Henry  M..and  Emmie  Felkin.     (Sonnenschein.) 
This  important  work  is  probably  the  one  from  which  most 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  8 1 

British  students  of  Herbartianism  have  derived  their  first  know- 
ledge of  the  movement. 

Beginning  with  a  brief  account  of  the  present  influential 
position  of  the  Herbartian  system,  the  authors  pass  on  to  a 
discussion  of  the  psychological  basis  worked  out  by  the  founder. 
This,  and  the  following  chapter  on  ethics,  are  both  difificult,  and 
may  repel  many  "practical  teachers  "  who  are  pining  for  mere 
"  hints  " ;  though  the  writers  have  illuminated  the  somewhat 
technical  discussion  with  many  a  pertinent  quotation,  the  ques- 
tion presents  itself  whether  a  better  procedure  would  not  have 
been  to  put  the  educational  problem  in  the  foreground  and  to 
have  worked  backwards  to  psychology  and  ethics,  somewhat 
after  Herbart's  own  fashion. 

In  chapter  iii.,  where  "  practical  pedagogy  "  is  reached,  the 
meaning  of  "  educative  instruction  "  is  expounded  and  the  great 
doctrine  of  many-sided  Interest  introduced.  Then  comes  a  very 
full  section  on  the  "  formal  steps  "  and  another  on  the  "  dual 
theory  of  the  concentration  centres  and  historical  culture  epochs," 
that  is,  upon  Ziller's  development  of  Herbart's  principles.  Voigt's 
criticism  of  this  development  is  given  in  great  fulness  and  will 
be  found  highly  valuable,  as  will  also  the  full  examples  of 
Zillerian  procedure. 

The  writers  translate  Zucht  by  "  Discipline  "  and  Eegierung 
by  "  Government ".  While  carefully  pointing  out  (p.  156)  the 
ambiguity  in  the  word  "  DiscipHne  "  (used  by  many  British 
teachers  in  the  sense  of  mere  "  preservation  of  order  ")  they 
use  it  in  preference  to  "  Training  "  as  a  translation  of  Zucht. 
This  is  perhaps  a  mistake.  It  is  better  to  translate  Zucht 
"  Training "  or  "  Moral  Training,"  and  Eegierung  "  Dis- 
cipline ", 

Herbart    and     the    Herbartians.      By    Charles    de    Garmo. 
(Heinemann.) 

This  book  is  similar  in  size  and  design  to  the  last.  Its 
exposition  of  Herbart's  own  doctrines  is,  however,  less  full, 
but  this  is  compensated  for  by  a  good  treatment  of  some  of 
Herbart's  chief  successors,  Stoy,  Ziller,  Dr.  Eein,  Dr.  Lange 

6 


82  The  Critics  of  Herhartianistn 

and  Frick  (Dorpfeld  is  strangely  omitted),  and  by  four  chapters 
on  the  development  of  Herbartianism  in  America.  The  chapters 
on  Stoy  and  Frick  are  specially  noteworthy,  inasmuch  as  these 
two  Herbartians  are  practically  unknown  to  British  readers. 
Stoy,  as  already  pointed  out,  was  the  leader  of  the  moderate  and 
orthodox  Herbartians,  as  distingmshed  from  the  more  revolu- 
tionary Herbartians  who  followed  Ziller.  Frick  was  the  head 
of  the  great  "Francke  SH/tungen"  at  Halle,  and  in  that  capacity 
worked  out  the  application  of  Herbartian  principles  to  secondary 
schools,  in  which  Zillerian  "  concentration  "  would  be  obviously 
difficult. 

An  American  educationist,  whose  name  is  not  so  well  known 
in  Britain  as  it  should  be.  Colonel  Parker,  worked  out  (partly,  no 
doubt,  under  Herbartian  influence),  a  scheme  of  "concentration," 
very  different,  however,  in,  principle  from  Ziller's.  Eeaders  will 
find  details  of  this  in  Dr.  de  Garmo's  book. 

The  Student's  Herbart.  A  Brief  Educational  Monograph  dealing 
with  the  Movement  Initiated  by  Herbart  and  Developed 
by  Stoy,  Dorpfeld  and  Ziller.  By  F.  H.  Hayward. 
(Sonnenschein.) 

This  brochure  differs  from  most  expositions  of  Herbartianism 
in  several  respects.  It  is  brief.  Its  thought  moves  regressively  : 
starting  with  the  problem  of  moral  evil  the  author  works  back- 
wards to  the  need  for  Herbartian  Interest,  and  then  again 
backwards  to  Apperception,  Lastly,  it  contains  a  brief  summary 
of  the  supposed  weaknesses  of  Herbartianism. 

(3)  Oriqinaii  Wobks  Showing  the  Influence  of 
Hebbartian  Thought. 

The  Herbartian  Psychology  applied  to  Education.  By  J.  Adams, 
M.A.,  B.Sc.     (Isbister.) 

There  are  not  many  British  books  on  education  that  deserve 
the  adjective  "  brilliant  ".  A  William  James  may  write  spark- 
ling Talks  with  Teachers,  but  William  James  lives  in  the  stimu- 
lating atmosphere  of  the  Western  Continent.     The  above  work 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  83 

by  the  Professor  of  Education  in  the  University  of  London  is 
British,  yet  it  sparkles.     It  is,  in  its  own  way,  unique. 

"  Herbartianism,"  says  the  writer,  "  has  weaknesses,  and 
some  of  its  rivals  have  points  of  superiority  ;  yet  it  seems  to 
me  the  best  system  for  application  to  education."  "  It  does 
not  follow  that  the  writer  is  a  Herbartian.  It  is  enough  that 
he  finds  this  system  fits  most  readily  into  his  own  experience, 
and  seems  to  him  best  suited  to  explain  educational  facts  to 
others." 

Prof.  Adams  has  little  patience  with  the  humdrum  empiri- 
cism of  the  average  schoolmaster,  which  impudently  claims  to 
be  "  practical  "  and  based  on  "  experience  ".  "  One  main  aim 
of  this  book  is  to  induce  the  cave-dwellers  to  move  their  heads. 
It  is  unwillingness  to  turn  round  and  look  about  them  that 
marks  the  true  cave-dweUer.  Many  teachers  are  content  to 
play  with  the  little  black  puppets  of  their  school  world,  and 
sturdily  refuse  to  look  beyond  the  school  walls,  or  even  to 
admit  that  there  is  a  beyond.  .  .  .  Certainly  all  that  they  know 
about  education  has  been  known  long  ago."  "  The  modest 
schoolmaster  is  an  arrogant  and  intolerant  empiric.  .  .  .  Such 
teachers  haughtily  resent  any  attempt  to  enlighten  them." 

The  author  proceeds  to  discuss  the  relation  between  psych- 
ology and  education,  reviewing,  in  passing  on  towards  Herbar- 
tianism, the  systems  of  Locke  and  Frobel. 

He  points  out — it  needed  very  much  to  be  pointed  out — 
that  Herbartianism  and  Frobelianism  are,  in  appearance  at  any 
rate,  diametrically  opposed.  Herbart  practically  starts,  not  with 
the  mind,  but  with  ideas. 

The  soul  which  he  posits  is  "no  more  a  real  soul  than  it  is  a 
real  crater  of  a  volcano.  It  has  absolutely  no  content.  .  .  . 
What  Locke  did  for  innate  ideas  Herbart  did  for  innate  facul- 
ties. .  .  .  What  he  has  taken  from  the  soul  he  has  transferred 
to  the  ideas ;  .  .  .  these  have  a  vitality  aU  their  own." 

The  author  follows  with  a  lucid  explanation  of  the  appercep- 
tion doctrine,  one  of  the  best  expositions,  in  a  brief  form,  to 
be  found  in  our  language.  He  shows  how  this  doctrine  goes 
beyond  mere  associationism ;  "  the  associationist  explains  very 


84  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

clearly  why  each  of  the  ideas  has  come  into  the  dome  of 
consciousness  in  which  it  is  found,  but  he  neglects  to  explain 
why  the  same  idea  does  not  follow  the  same  word  in  each 
case  ".  It  is  a  case  of  "  apperception  masses,"  not  of  mere 
associational  links.  Again,  "  if  Herbartianism  did  nothing  more 
than  emphasise  the  fact  that  no  two  people  ever  have  exactly 
the  same  idea,  and  particularly  that  no  master  and  pupil  can 
ever  have  the  same  idea,  it  would  justify  its  existence  ".  The 
cry  for  "  things,  not  words  "  would  only  "  substitute  one  fallacy 
for  another ;  things  are  not  a  whit  better  than  words  in  ensur- 
ing that  the  same  idea  shall  be  called  up  in  two  minds.  .  .  .  The 
average  child  does  not  see  what  the  master  is  showing  him.  .  .  . 
The  Herbartian  has  none  of  that  reverence  for  hard  facts  so 
characteristic  of  the  '  plain  man  '."  In  other  words,  the  "  ap- 
perception masses "  of  each  individual,  even  of  each  child, 
vitally  influence  the  cognition  of  any  new  experience  ;  "  unlike 
most  psychologies,  Herbart's  has  an  obvious  and  immediate 
bearing  upon  education,"  and  indeed  (though  Prof.  Adams 
merely  hints  at  this  and  does  not  work  it  out  into  detail)  upon 
morality  and  conduct.  "  If  the  idea  that  the  soul  ought  to 
choose  is  not  there  to  choose,  what  can  the  soul  do  but  choose 
amiss?  " 

Chapter  v.  deals  with  "  Formal  Education  "  and  is  immensely 
valuable,  in  view  of  the  pretensions,  alike  of  classical  teachers, 
of  advocates  of  "  heuristic  "  methods,  and  of  admirers  of  the 
"  three  E's  "  as  the  main  pabulum  of  the  primary  school. 
These  three  classes  are  united  in  discounting  knowledge  or 
ideas,  and  in  laying  stress  upon  certain  activities.  "  There  is 
a  prevailing  impression  .  .  .  that  it  really  does  not  matter  very 
much  what  one  learns.  The  culture  comes  all  the  same.  It  is 
not  the  what ;  it  is  the  how."  Prof.  Adams  exposes  the  fallacy 
of  all  this.  The  great  thing  is  ideas,  apperception-masses. 
Education  in  crime  is  "  formally  "  as  high  as  education  in  the 
classics  ;  orchard-robbing,  for  example,  calls  out  prudence,  fore- 
thought, caution,  observation,  firmness,  and  so  forth.  "  The 
soul  is  not  a  mere  knife  that  may  be  sharpened  on  any  whet- 
stone, and  when  sharpened  may  be  applied  to  any  purpose. 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  85 

The  knife  takes  the  character  from  the  whetstone."  "  We  can- 
not separate  the  mind  from  its  content.  .  .  .  Above  all,  it  is 
certain  that  we  cannot  exercise  the  mind  in  vacuo.  .  .  .  The 
choice  of  subjects  is  important ;  a  subject  must  be  chosen  for 
its  own  sake,  not  for  the  sake  of  its  general  effect  in  training 
the  mind." 

Then  follows  another  chapter  on  the  apperception  doctrine ; 
the  limitations  of  "observation"  are  pointed  out;  and  then 
come  several  other  luminous  chapters,  not  very  distinctively 
Herbartian. 

In  his  final  chapter,  that  on  Interest,  Prof.  Adams  discusses 
the  relation  between  Interest  and  Attention,  and  between 
Interest  and  Apperception  :  he  shows,  from  the  Herbartian 
standpoint,  the  folly  of  imposing  drudgery  on  children  in  order 
to  "  train  "  them  for  the  battle  of  life — the  theory  which  largely 
dominates  the  procedure  of  didactic  "  formalists  "  ;  "  the  theory 
of  interest,"  he  says,  "  does  not  propose  to  banish  drudgery,  but 
only  to  make  drudgery  tolerable  by  giving  it  a  meaning  "  :  in 
relation  to  this  he  again  lays  stress — as  every  Herbartian  does 
— on  a  worthy  content  for  all  studies ;  "  it  is  not  necessary 
to  go  to  Eome  in  order  to  learn  Latin,  .  .  .  but  it  is  necessary 
that  it  should  be  learnt  as  something  having  a  meaning  in 
itself,  not  as  a  mere  exercise  ". 

The  author  concludes  the  most  racy  book  on  education  in  the 
English  language  with  an  indication  of  how  Herbartianism  may 
be  destined  to  join  hands  ultimately  with  Frobel's  more  organic 
view  of  life.  "  The  latest  word  of  the  Herbartians  deposes 
interest  from  its  place  as  the  first  principle  of  education  and 
makes  it  rank  second  to  the  principle  of  self-realisation. 
Interests  must  be  tested  by  their  efifect  on  the  child's  develop- 
ment, viewed  in  connection  with  its  place  in  the  organic  unity 
of  the  world  in  which  it  has  to  live." 

Primer  on  Teaching,  with  Special  Beference  to  Sunday  School 

Work.    By  J.  Adams,  M.A.,  B.Sc,  Professor  of  Education 

in  the  University  of  London.     (T.  &  T.  Clark.) 

Herbartianism  in  the  Sunday  School !     In  this  little  book 

Prof.    Adams    applies    educational    principles — including   the 


86  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

Herbartian  "  formal  steps  " — to  the  work  of  Biblical  teaching. 
Probably  the  most  valuable  chapter  is  the  one  in  which  the 
"  steps "  are  expounded  and  illustrated  ;  and  the  section  on 
the  Socratic  method,  with  illustrations  in  Prof.  Adams's 
characteristic  style,  is  excellent. 

We  find,  as  we  should  expect,  the  usual  Herbartian  emphasis 
on  ideas  ;  "they  do  seem  to  have  a  power  of  their  own". 
"  Temptation  consists  in  the  effort  of  an  idea  to  realise  itself." 
We  find  likewise  the  Herbartian  emphasis  on  creating  healthy 
interests  rather  than  on  denouncing  evil ;  "we  must  fight  evil 
indirectly  by  supplying  ideas  of  good  ".  "  The  kind  of  apper- 
ception masses  in  the  mind  really  determines  what  kind  of  mind 
it  is."  Apperception  and  Interest  are  therefore  vital.  "  The 
business  of  the  teacher  is  so  to  arrange  the  ideas  in  the  mind  of 
the  pupil  that  apperceptive  attention  to  desirable  things  will  be 
aroused."  Even  the  sowing  of  almost  chance  ideas  may  result 
in  a  subsequent  harvest ;  "very  often  the  teacher  must  intro- 
duce ideas  into  the  mind  of  the  pupil,  not  so  much  for  their 
immediate  importance  as  for  the  use  to  be  made  of  them  at 
some  future  lesson  ". 

Herbartian  though  he  is,  and  strong  opponent  of  purely 
"formal"  teaching,  Prof.  Adams  recognises  some  value  in  the 
"training"  ideal  of  the  formalists.  "The  process  of  working 
for  the  rule  gives  the  mind  a  certain  amount  of  training.  The 
mind  is  a  better  mind  because  it  has  done  this  particular  bit  of 
work." 

Principles  of  Class  Teaching.     By  Dr.  J.  J.  Findlay.     (Mac- 

millan.) 

Though  he  admits  his  indebtedness  to  Herbartian  writers 
like  Prof.  Eein,  Dr.  Findlay  would  object  to  be  labelled  "  Her- 
bartian ".  The  label  might  be  regarded  as  implying  an  absence 
of  originality.  Nevertheless,  an  examination  of  his  book  reveals 
the  fact  that,  though  it  is  an  original  and  valuable  contribution 
to  British  educational  literature,  its  merits  are  entirely  those 
which  distinguish  Herbartian  books.  If  Dr.  Findlay  is  not  an 
Herbartian  there  are  no  Herbartians  in  existence. 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  87 

Character-forming  is  the  end  of  education ;  every  subject  in 
the  time  table  must  be  challenged  as  to  its  power  of  helping  to 
worthy  living.  "  We  acknowledge  the  final  supremacy  of  the 
ethical  ideal."  Technological  subjects  may  be  admitted  into 
the  upper  classes  of  the  school,  but  the  teaching  of  them  must 
be  distinguished  from  education  proper.  Currency  arithmetic 
should  be  excluded  except  from  upper  classes.  The  school  must 
no  longer  be  subjected  to  the  "  vulgar  ideals  of  the  nineteenth 
century  ".     Surely  this  is  the  voice  of  Herbart ! 

Dr.  Findlay  is  a  humanist,  though  other  claims  than  those  of 
humanism  are  recognised.  For  each  month  or  six  weeks  we 
should  select  "some  central  theme  of  great  humanistic  interest" 
capable  of  easy  correlation  with  other  groups.  He  approves  of 
fairy  tales  for  the  young,  but  prefers  to  regard  them  as  luxury 
rather  than  as  staple  food. 

Two  doctrines,  each  of  enormous  educational  importance,  stand 
out  clearly  in  Dr.  Findlay's  book,  the  two  doctrines  upon  which 
Ddrpfeld  laid  stress.  Our  writer  is  under  no  obligations  to 
the  Westphalian  schoolmaster,  but  he  has  arrived  at  the  same 
results. 

The  first  doctrine  is  that  the  conferring  of  skill  or  dexterity 
{e.g.,  in  language,  in  writing,  etc.)  obeys  a  different  set  of  educa- 
tional laws  than  the  conferring  of  knowledge ;  the  "  formal 
steps,"  which  are  valuable  in  the  latter  procedure,  are  inapplic- 
able to  the  former.  "  The  chief  error  of  the  strict  Herbartians 
seems  to  He  in  their  attempt  to  regard  the  Arts  as  subservient  to 
the  same  laws  of  method  which  apply  to  branches  of  knowledge. 
Music,  Drawing,  Eeading  are  all  brought  by  Ziller  and  Eein 
under  the  scheme  of  the  Five  Steps."  "  While  in  Instruction 
we  proceed  from  sense-observation  to  perception  and  conception, 
in  Performance  we  proceed  from  sense  observation  or  (to  use  a 
more  convenient  term)  from  contemplation  to  active  imitation." 
But  for  their  proper  task,  the  conferring  of  knowledge,  the  five 
steps  are  admirable,  though  they  have  their  dangers  ;  "  the 
followers  of  Herbart  in  Germany  have  here  achieved  results 
which  cannot  be  assailed  except  on  minor  points  ".  Dr.  Findlay's 
account  of  the  steps  is  one  of  the  clearest  and  most  judicial  in 


88  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

the  English  language ;  he  summarises  them  thus  :  "  first  ob- 
servation, then  varied  observation,  comparison  with  earlier 
observation,  and  finally — as  the  crown  and  completion  of  these 
particular  experiences — the  new,  higher  form  of  thought  ".  He 
conveniently  uses  the  word  "  Section "  as  equivalent  to  the 
German  "  method-unit ". 

The  second  doctrine  which  is  prominent  in  Dr.  Findlay's  book 
is  that  the  "  knowledge  "  subjects,  being  those  that  awaken  the 
keenest  interest  and  build  up  the  "  circle  of  thought "  (all  action 
springs  out  of  this  "  circle  "),  must  be  more  central  in  the  cur- 
riculum than  formal  subjects  and  dexterities.  This  was  precisely 
the  contention  of  Dorpfeld,^  and  Dr.  Findlay  works  it  out  in 
a  more  systematic  way  than  has  ever  yet  been  attempted  in 
English.  There  must  be  a  worthy  "content"  to  our  studies, 
worthy  and  rich  ideas.  Mere  mental  gymnastic  is  of  little  use 
unless  employed  upon  such  a  worthy  "  content  ". 

The  following  quotations  will  illustrate  Dr.  Findlay's  view  on 
this  question : — 

"  Cleverness  and  skill  in  the  forms  of  Art  degrade  the  worker 
unless  his  mind  and  heart  are  filled  with  worthy  '  content '  asso- 
ciated with  those  '  forms '."  If  there  is  anything  worthy  of  study 
in  the  life  and  hterature  of  the  French  people  let  us  learn 
French  ;  if  there  is  nothing  worthy  we  might  as  well  learn 
Fiji ;  the  latter  would  be  as  much  a  gymnastic  as  French. 
"  The  subject-matter  of  language  teaching  must  be  derived 
from  the  topics  familiar  to  the  child's  circle  of  ideas,"  e.g.,  the 
Humanities  and  the  Occupations ;  "  the  advantage  of  cor- 
relation is  obvious ".  Grammar,  likewise,  can  scarcely  claim 
independent  treatment  as  an  abstract  science ;  it  is  rather  to 
be  subordinated  to  practical  language  exercises  ;  it  is  a  mistake 
to  divorce  it  and  panegyrise  it  as  a  mental  gymnastic.  Similarly 
philology  must  be  subordinated  to  hterature ;  "  the  decay  of 
the  faculty-psychology  has  led  to  a  distrust  of  language  teach- 
ing as  a  special  medium  for  mental  discipline  ".  So  with  music, 
drawing,  and  other  more  or  less  "formal"  subjects;  unless 

^  Grundlinien  einer  Theorie  des  Lehrplans. 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  89 

they  are  associated  with  a  worthy  subject-matter  or  "  content  " 
their  value  is  slight.  Dr.  Findlay  "  distrusts  the  cultivation  of 
any  art  merely  for  its  own  sake  ".  We  must  (in  music)  start 
with  songs  possessing  a  worthy  content ;  an  interest  in  the 
technique  of  the  art  comes  later.  "  The  teacher  of  art  must 
be  permitted  to  take  the  child  step  by  step  through  the  exercises 
necessary  to  attain  skill,  but  in  the  choice  of  models  and  of 
subjects  he  is  bound  to  submit  to  the  suggestions  offered  from 
the  Humanities,  the  Occupations,  Nature-study,  etc.,  of  the 
general  syllabus." 

The  above  remarks  are  wholly  in  the  spirit  of  Dorpfeld ; 
subjects  which  convey  "ideas"  must  form  the  centre  of  the 
curriculum.  Many  of  Dr.  Findlay's  other  suggestions  are  in 
the  direction  of  "concentration"  or  "  correlation ".  He  is  up 
in  arms  against  any  syllabus — overcrowded,  as  is  usually  the 
case — whose  parts  are  scrappy  and  disconnected.  "  One  lesson 
per  week  in  Drawing  or  Science  is  bound  to  spell  failure,  especi- 
ally if  these  pursuits  are  conducted  without  relation  to  other 
studies."  Isolated  biographies  are  of  little  use.  It  is  "hopeless" 
to  teach  the  Bible,  or  anything  else,  in  scraps.  Geometrical 
Drawing  is  oflScially  separated  from  theoretical  Geometry! 
Miscellaneous  scrappy  "Eeaders"  are  rightly  being  discarded 
in  favour  of  books  called  Historical,  Geographical,  or  Science 
Eeaders,  which  correlate  the  acquirement  of  the  art  of  reading 
with  some  other  branch  of  study.  "  Concentration  "  will  help 
the  teacher  in  various  ways,  and  conduce  to  that  "  unity  of  the 
pupil's  life"  which  is  the  j&nal  goal  of  teaching.  The  teacher 
of  science  or  history  must  not  ignore  such  things  as  composi- 
tion. History  and  literature  should  be  brought  together  and 
treated  together ;  they  form  the  Humanities.  Natural  science 
depends  partly  for  its  success  on  being  correlated  with  practical 
work  in  workshops.  The  educational  value  of  practical  pursuits 
is  not  sufficiently  recognised;  "the  elementary  school  of  the 
nineteenth  century  has  created  a  gulf  between  the  pursuits  of 
home  and  the  pursuits  of  school  which  must  somehow  be 
bridged  over  ".  Sloyd  is  now  being  adapted  to  the  needs  of  the 
Physical  Laboratory. 


90  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

"  We  advocate  the  doctrine  of  Concentration  as  a  practical  and 
essential  contribution  to  the  theory  of  the  curriculum."  At  least 
in  the  case  of  young  children,  "  results  are  decisive  enough  to 
enable  us  to  speak  confidently  of  the  advantages  of  a  scheme  of 
study  which  centres  round  one  theme  ".  But  for  older  children 
"  the  utmost  we  can  do  is  to  be  prepared  for  such  associations 
as  present  themselves — to  put  our  mathematics,  for  example,  on 
a  basis  of  Physical  Science,  our  Arts  of  Expression  into  rela- 
tionship with  the  Humanities,  and  our  Arts  of  Eepresentation 
into  relationship  with  the  Humanities  and  with  Nature  Know- 
ledge ".1  Still  "  concentration  "  has  its  limits ;  "  some  pursuits 
cannot  by  any  ingenuity  be  brought  into  the  "  circle  ". 

Dr.  Findlay  has  been  criticised  for  attacking  the  "frankly 
empirical"  tone  of  most  British  works  on  education.  But  his 
standpoint  is  the  inevitable  one  for  any  educationist  influenced 
by  Herbart.  "  We  can  only  establish  education  as  a  profes- 
sional pursuit  by  devoting  to  its  study  the  same  elaborate  care, 
the  same  spirit  of  devotion  to  our  profession,  as  we  witness  in 
other  callings  which  have  won  the  confidence  of  the  public." 
We  must  seek  "  a  scientific  basis  for  our  work  ".  Every  new 
course  of  study  must  present  "  a  new  scientific  problem  ". 
DiflBcult  pupils  should  especially  awaken  in  the  professional 
teacher  a  sense  of  professional  pride.  "  There  is  an  immense 
field  of  exploration  awaiting  teachers  who  have  a  psychological 
equipment." 

School  and  Home  Life.    By  F.  G.  Eooper,  M.A.     (A.  Brown  & 

Sons.) 

Though  the  name  of  Herbart  is  scarcely  mentioned  once  in 
this  volume  of  high-toned  essays,  the  ideas  of  Herbart  and  his 
followers  are  everywhere  to  the  fore.  One  essay  ("  The  Pot  of 
Green  Feathers  ")  is  an  exposition,  carried  out  in  a  fresh  and 
untechnical  manner,  of  the  doctrine  of  Apperception.  Though 
the  book  makes  "  no  claim  for  originality,"  it  is  stimulating  and 
inspiring. 

^  This  sentence,  which  sunamarises  much  of  Dr.  Findlay's  book,  is  one  of 
the  most  important  in  recent  British  educational  literature. 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English         '  91 


There  are  so  few  educationists  who  are  in  earnest  over  the 
moral  aspects  of  education  that  Mr.  Eooper's  words — which 
remind  us  of  Ziller's  claim  that  mauy-sided  Interest  is  "  a  pro- 
tection against  passions  " — are  doubly  welcome.  "  You  want 
to  combat  drinking  and  gambling.  .  .  .  Many  youths  (though 
not  all)  may  be  induced  to  avoid  such  temptations  ...  if  you 
only  provide  them  with  other  occupations."  Mr.  Rooper,  in 
this  connection,  sees  much  value  in  manual  dexterities,  but 
his  argument  is  obviously  applicable  to  the  whole  curriculum. 
"  All  teachers  are  missionaries  by  profession  "  is  a  bold  state- 
ment, but  Mr.  Rooper  makes  it,  and  it  illustrates  the  spirit  of 
his  book. 

Many  of  his  best  suggestions  concern  manual  training,  Sloyd, 
the  kindergarten,  etc.  ;  manual  work  he  regards  as  a  necessary 
part  of  the  curriculum,  not  for  technical,  but  for  educational 
reasons.  But  Mr.  Rooper  remains  essentially  a  humanist  and 
an  Herbartian.  "  I  believe  that  an  intelligent  study  of  the  Bible 
and  Shakespeare,  and  of  classical  English  writers,  is  incom- 
parably more  important  than  .  .  .  manual  training."  Only 
through  literature  can  imagination  and  taste  be  developed. 
Cruelty  is  largely  due  to  defective  imagination.  Children  must 
be  "  assisted  to  admire  heroism  in  all  its  forms  ".  Fairy  tales, 
fables,  allegories,  etc.,  are  therefore  of  immense  value.  "  If 
any  one  thinks  that  it  would  be  better  if  the  child's  mind  could 
move  only  in  the  sphere  of  the  exact,  I  would  reply  (1)  that  this 
does  not  seem  to  be  nature's  process ;  (2)  that  looking  to  the 
mode  of  growth  of  the  mind  it  does  not  seem  even  possible ;  and 
(3)  that  if  you  try  to  keep  the  child's  mind  to  exactness  you 
may  clip  and  pluck  the  wings  of  imagination.  Now  without 
imagination  there  is  little  advance  in  knowledge,  little  discovery 
in  the  sphere  of  morality."  But  no  "  treatise  on  elementary 
ethics  "  is  advisable  for  schools. 

Mr.  Rooper's  Herbartianism  is  still  more  obvious  in  his 
suggestions  for  concentration  or  correlation.  Dislocation  in 
one's  thought-masses  results  in  inconsistencies  of  character ; 
the  child  does  not  grow  up  "  a  single  self "  ;  "a  man  may  become 
like  a  musical  box  which  can  play  two  quite  different  tunes  ", 


92  TTie  Critics  of  Herbartianistn 


Isolated  thoughts  are  powerless ;  apperception  must  take  place 
before  thoughts  can  rouse  interest  or  exert  influence.  "  The 
main  fault  of  the  present  routine  in  Standards  I.  and  II.  is  the 
isolated  way  in  which  each  subject  is  treated."  The  teacher 
must  "  find  ways  of  connecting  together,  not  merely  the  parts 
of  one  study,  but  different  studies  with  each  other ".  The 
science  of  number  must  be  kept  in  close  connection  with  natural 
history,  history,  geography,  and  even  stories  dealing  with  family 
life ;  the  intelligent  apprehension  of  number  has  been  hindered 
by  the  isolation  of  its  study,  an  isolation  which  was  opposed 
by  Frobel's  system.  Early  reading  lessons  should  be  based  on 
object  lessons  rather  than  on  "  readers  ".  Object  teaching, 
language  teaching,  drawing,  and  modelling  should  be  mutually 
connected.  Beading,  writing,  and  speaking  should  similarly  be 
interwoven.  Songs  should  be  connected  with  children's  studies 
and  occupations.  Natural  science,  philology  and  art  shoiild  be 
treated  as  one  subject  for  young  children.  Art  and  literature 
should  illustrate  each  other,  e.g.,  a  picture  may  serve  to  con- 
centrate a  number  of  studies.  Studies  in  natural  history  should 
contain  conduct  lessons.  The  motto  for  evening  schools  should 
be,  "  Concentrate  your  studies,  group  your  instruction  round 
one  central  subject  ". 

Not  mere  external  '*  discipline  "  or  "  training  "  will  make  a 
perfect  man.  Like  every  Herbartian,  Mr.  Eooper  lays  stress 
on  moral  insight  and  therefore  on  instruction.  *'  Good  habits 
are  not  by  themselves  a  complete  education."  His  own  scheme 
of  "  concentration  "  would  "  tend  to  humanise  children  ".  What 
studies  are  pre-eminently  character-forming?  Not  the  three  E's; 
they  cannot  be  regarded  as  the  essence  of  elementary  education, 
and  indeed  they  can  be  better  taught  if  the  curriculum  is  not 
confined  to  them.  "  For  the  three  E's,  I  substitute  Nature  and 
Human  Nature  as  the  epitome  of  educational  studies.  Of  these 
twins  neither  should  be  neglected,  although  the  latter  is  the 
more  important."  Pupils  must  be  made  acquainted  "through 
literary  studies  with  the  best  side  of  human  nature  ".  Stories 
from  Grimm,  stories  from  history,  and  so  forth,  are  of  supreme 
character-forming  importance, 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  93 

The  value  of  formal  grammar  is  not  great ;  even  as  a  guide 
to  speech  it  leads  astray  as  often  as  it  helps.  But  practice 
in  actual  composition  is  immensely  important. 

In  the  important  essay,  "  Drawing  in  Evening  Schools " 
(based  partly  on  the  researches  of  M.  Passy),  Mr.  Eooper 
traces  out  the  bearings  of  apperception  upon  elementary  draw- 
ing, and  shows  how  easily  the  senses  are  misled  when  a  draw- 
ing "  type  "  pre-exists  in  the  mind. 

Mr.  Eooper,  in  all  the  above  suggestions,  is  in  full  conformity 
with  Herbartianism.  His  conformity  is  less  when  he  bestows 
genuine  though  not  lavish  praise  upon  the  classical  curriculum 
of  public  schools.  "  The  teacher  (in  such  schools)  mistrusts  the 
growth  of  a  receptive  attitude  in  his  class."  Composing  in  Greek 
or  Latin  encourages  independent  mental  activity.  It  is  a  mis- 
take for  the  teacher  to  make  the  lesson  too  easy.  [Herbart 
himself  would  agree  with  this,  though  some  modern  Herbar- 
tians  tend  towards  "  soft  pedagogy  ".]  Mr.  Eooper  is,  however, 
strictly  Herbartian  when  he  points  out  that  "  feelings  are 
linked  together,  not  directly,  but  through  the  mediation  of 
thought,"  words  which  remind  us  of  the  dictum  that  "  action 
springs  out  of  the  circle  of  thought  ", 

Every  Herbartian  boasts  proudly  of  being  "  scientific  "  ;  he 
is  no  despiser  of  "  theory,"  no  worshipper  of  "  common-sense  ". 
Nor  is  Mr.  Eooper.  "  Common-sense  is  not  the  ordinary  judg- 
ment which  every  one  possesses,  but  the  rare  judgment  of  which 
every  one  approves."  "  I  believe  that  the  studies  of  German 
writers  on  education  help  to  solve  such  (educational)  mysteries; " 
there  exists  "  an  inexhaustible  gold  mine  of  educational  philo- 
sophy "  for  those  who  choose  to  biirrow  into  it. 

Introduction  to  the  Herbartian  Principles  of  Teaching.      By 
Catherine  I.  Dodd.     (Sonnenschein.) 

Miss  Dodd  sees  how  disastrously  un-educative  {i.e.,  non-forma- 
tive of  character)  most  of  our  schools  are,  and  enthusiastically 
advocates  reform  along  Zillerian  lines. 

The  book  possesses  one  defect.  The  authoress  too  closely 
identifies  the  Herbartian  movement  with  the  narrower  Zillerian 


94  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

movement ;  Herbart  is  described  as  an  advocate  of  the  "  culture 
epochs  "  doctrine  (which,  except  to  a  limited  extent,  he  scarcely 
was ;  in  fact  his  presentational  psychology  was  out  of  sympathy 
with  a  doctrine  essentially  one  of  heredity);  "the  Herbartians  " 
(instead  of  "  some  Herbartians  ")  are  said  to  "  place  history  as 
the  centre  of  all  the  subjects  to  be  studied  ".  Except  for  this 
defect — due  to  the  fact  that  great  Herbartians  like  Dorpfeld 
have  not  yet  attracted  the  attention  of  British  authors  to  the 
extent  that  Ziller  has — Miss  Dodd's  book  is  admirable,  and 
immensely  more  inspiring  and  suggestive  than  the  "  school- 
management  "  books  studied  by  most  teachers. 

The  great  feature  of  the  work  is  the  strong  case  it  presents 
for  the  teaching  of  fairy-tales,  history,  and  literature  ;  in  fact  for 
the  Gesinnungs-unterricht  of  the  Zillerians.  "  True  history 
teaching  should  place  before  all  the  children  in  the  country 
noble  and  great  men,  and  so  help  to  raise  them  to  a  higher  moral 
level.  ...  If  striking  examples  of  goodness,  courage,  truth, 
and  falsehood  from  the  pages  of  the  Bible  or  profane  history  are 
put  before  children  they  form  their  own  moral  judgments 
very  readily.  .  .  .  Our  Arthur,  Alfred,  Eichard  the  Lion-hearted, 
and  Cranmer  might  become  part  of  the  life  of  every  English 
child  if  we  gave  history  the  position  it  merits  in  our  primary 
schools." 

She  recommends  the  use,  when  possible,  of  original  historical 
sources ;  the  giving  of  some  definite  ideas  concerning  general 
historical  sequence ;  and  also  the  touching,  lightly  but  really, 
upon  the  history  of  other  countries  than  our  own.  With  history 
goes  literature.  "  The  reading  of  literature  in  school  has  a  high 
moral  influence,"  and  yet  "  rarely  do  children  acquire  either 
the  power  of  reading  aloud  intelligently  or  a  taste  for  good 
literature  ". 

Great  stress  is,  of  course,  laid  upon  "  concentration,"  inter- 
preted along  Zillerian  lines.  Isolation  and  scrappiness  are  the 
bane  of  biblical  and  similar  teaching.  Miss  Dodd's  detailed 
suggestions  for  "  concentration  "  in  the  lower  classes  are  excel- 
lent ;  Bobinson  Crusoe,  the^  story  of  the  Armada,  are  to  form 
centres  for  the  attachment  of  various  material.     But  why  "con- 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  95 

centrate  "  ?  One  readily  sees  various  advantages  ;  interest  is 
increased,  not  merely  transitory  interest,  but  true  permanent 
interest ;  memory  is  strengthened,  and  a  logical  memory  is 
developed;  the  pressure  of  an  overwhelming  number  of  sub- 
jects is  taken  off  the  time-table.  Concentration  will  help  us 
to  proportion  our  subjects  according  to  natural  relationships 
existing  between  them,  and  to  get  rid  of  quantities  of  irrele- 
vant subject-matter  which  text-books  are  constantly  offering. 
"  Isolated  ideas  are  feebly  impressed  and  easily  forgotten." 

The  "  culture-stages  "  doctrine  is  advocated  ;  "  children  are 
psychically  nearer  to  remote  ages  than  to  the  present ".  Like 
every  Herbartian,  Miss  Dodd  also  attacks  the  exaggerated  im- 
portance often  given  to  "  formal  studies  ".  "  They  are  only 
means  to  an  end."  "  We  read  because  we  want  to  get  at 
ideas." 

Nature    Studies   and    Fairy-Tales.       By   Catherine   I.    Dodd. 

(Nelson.) 

Miss  Dodd  is  the  best  English  writer  on  the  fairy-tale  ques- 
tion, and  her  suggestions  relative  to  the  employment  of  such 
tales,  together  with  nursery  rhymes,  Greek  legends,  and  similar 
matter,  would  have  been  referred  to  in  connection  with  her 
Introduction,  except  that  in  the  present  work  she  has  dealt 
much  more  fully  with  the  question.  There  can  be  no  doubt 
as  to  the  excellence  of  the  scheme  she  has  worked  out  for  the 
lower  classes  of  schools  Fairy-tales  offer  so  many  points  of 
contact  with  "  nature  "  that  there  is  every  reason  for  combining 
their  study  with  the  study  of  nature,  in  other  words,  of  apply- 
ing here  the  principle  of  "  concentration ".  Drawing  and 
plaster  work  are  also  suggested  as  further  applications  of  the 
concentration  principle. 

The  book  contains  a  whole  series  of  lessons  and  suggestions 
which  will  prove  of  great  value  to  the  teacher  of  junior  classes, 
while  for  educationists  in  general  Miss  Dodd's  lengthy  and  able 
defence  of  the  use  of  fairy-tales,  and  her  history  of  the  fairy-tale 
question  cannot  fail  to  be  of  interest.  She  makes  use  of  the 
"  five  steps  "  of  Herbart  and  Ziller. 


96  Tlu  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

Interest  and  Education.  By  Charles  de  Garmo.  (The  Mac- 
millan  Company.) 

This  book  marks  an  advance  from  what  may  be  called  the 
primitive  Interest  doctrine,  which  ignores,  or  passes  lightly 
over,  the  innate  outward-going  tendencies  of  the  child,  to  the 
more  advanced  form  of  the  doctrine,  which  eagerly  avails  itself 
of  these  tendencies.  The  work  thus  represents  a  kind  of 
synthesis  of  Herbartianism  with  FrobeUanism,  and  also,  be 
it  added,  with  the  "  heuristic  "  doctrine,  and  with  Spencer's 
doctrine  of  the  primary  importance  of  life-preserving  studies. 
In  fact  the  Herbartianism  of  the  book  is  observable  mainly  or 
solely  in  the  emphasis  on  Interest. 

This  "  Interest  "  is  to  be  a  form  of  "  self-expression  ".  "  This 
mental  activity,  taking  root  first  in  the  instincts  and  impulses 
of  the  physical  nature,  and  developing  into  conscious  desire  for 
the  realisation  of  certain  ends,  is  at  bottom  nothing  but  the 
effort  to  express  self  in  accordance  with  the  varying  ideals  im- 
planted by  physical  nature,  or  developed  by  growing  insight  into 
the  ideal  nature  of  the  man."  "  Interest  is  a  feeling  that  accom- 
panies the  idea  of  self-expression.  ...  It  has  its  primary  root 
in  inherited  impulse." 

Great  stress  is  laid  on  the  active  side  of  mental  Ufe.  "  Our 
greatest  lack  ...  is  the  meagreness  of  opportunity  for  vigorous 
outgoing  motor  expression."  The  writer  is  in  one  place  grimly 
humorous.  "It  is  some  comfort  to  the  teacher  to  know  that 
...  he  cannot  wholly  spoil  a  thoroughly  active  mind,  or  en- 
tirely counteract  the  influence  of  the  outside  world  of  achieve- 
ment. Yet  our  school  education  should  be  of  a  character  actively 
to  promote  the  quaUties  that  lead  to  survival."  "  Education  has 
to  give  permanent  and  strong  interests  in  the  realities  of  life." 

The  view  that  lays  stress  on  self-expression  corrects  two 
opposite  errors,  (1)  the  theory  of  effort,  "  that  the  sheer  dead 
lift  of  will  is  the  only  sure  means  of  getting  the  child  to  the  goal 
and  the  only  way  whereby  his  mind  can  be  trained  to  do  the 
hard  things  that  are  sure  to  confront  him  in  later  life  " ;  (2)  the 
method  of  coaxing  by  means  of  pleasurable  excitations. 

The  "  heuristic"  element  in  Dr.  de  Garmo's  book  is  seen  in 


Herbartian  Literature  in  English  97 

combination  with  the  Interest  doctrine.  "  As  soon  as  school 
work  assumes  the  form  of  problems  to  be  solved  by  the  self- 
activity  of  the  pupils,  we  have  at  once  a  concrete  application  of 
the  doctrine  of  interest."  But  the  school  has  not  to  engage  in 
"  mere  shadow  or  imitation  discoveries  ". 

l^otes  of  Lessons  on  the  Herbartian  Method.  {Based  on  Her- 
bart's  Plan.)  By  M.  Fennel  and  Members  of  a  Teaching 
Staff.     (Longmans.) 

It  is  painful  to  have  to  criticise  this  book.  Except  for  a  brief 
preface,  to  the  correctness  of  which  no  exception  can  be  taken, 
the  book  contains  scarcely  a  trace  of  Herbartianism  from  begin- 
ning to  end.  The  "  five  steps  "  employed  by  the  "  teaching 
staff"  are,  for  the  most  part,  not  Herbartian  steps  at  all.  "  Ee- 
capitulation,"  here  given  as  the  "fifth  step,"  is  not  recognised  as 
one  at  all  by  the  Herbartians  ;  a  "  step  "  implies  progress,  not 
movement  over  the  same  ground.  Again,  Ziller's  doctrine  that 
the  aim  of  the  lesson  should  be  clearly  stated  to  the  class  at 
or  near  the  beginning  of  the  lesson,  is  apparently  misunderstood 
by  the  authors,  though  a  saving  clause  has  been  introduced  into 
the  preface.  Thus  we  find  as  the  aim  of  the  first  lesson  in  the 
volume,  "To  exercise  imagination  of  class  and  lead  them  to 
know  the  origin  of  English  Prose  and  Poetry  ".  Conceive  of  a 
Zillerian  saying  to  his  pupils  :  "  Now  children,  the  aim  of  this 
lesson  is  to  exercise  your  imagination  !  "  In  a  so-called  "  object 
lesson  "  on  a  horse  (the  lesson  should  really  be  called  an  "  in- 
formation lesson,"  for  the  object  is  only  shown  in  a  picture)  the 
"  application  "  (step  four)  consists  of  such  mere  information  as 
that  when  alive  the  horse  is  the  chief  beast  of  burden  in  temper- 
ate climates.  This  may  be  an  "  application  "  of  the  horse,  but  it 
is  not  an  "  application  "  of  the  knowledge  acquired  in  a  lesson ; 
in  short,  the  writer  wholly  fails  to  grasp  the  meaning  of  "  appli- 
cation "  in  the  Herbartian  system. 

Clearly  Herbartianism,  like  Frobelianism,  will  have  to  be 
saved  from  those  supposed  friends,  who,  with  inadequate  know- 
ledge of  its  principles,  seek  to  guide  others  in  the  application 
of  them. 


PART  IV. 

THE  CRITICS  OF  HBRBARTIANISM. 

SECTION  I. 

DITTES. 

(1884-86.) 
References. 
Dittos.     Padagogium,  1884,  p.  296. 

1885,  pp.  437,  505,  573,  637. 

1886,  pp.  500,  580. 

Just.  Jahrhuch  des  Vereins  fUr  wissenschaftliche  PSdagogik,  1886,  p. 
212. 

Glockner.    Pddagogisclie  Studien,  1886,  p.  193.^ 

Thilo  and  Fliigel.  Dittes  ilber  die  praktische  und  theoretische  PhUosophie 
Herbarts  (Beyer,  Langensalza). 

In  the  history  of  the  Herbartian  question  the  Dittes  controversy 
is  one  of  first  importance  in  view  of  its  magnitude  and  virulence. 
It  sprang  up  during  the  two  or  three  critical  years  when  from 
almost  every  side  fierce  attacks  came  in,  and  when  the  two 
leaders  of  the  movement,  Stoy  and  Ziller,  could  no  longer 
engage  in  the  task  of  defence.  Herbartianism,  moreover,  was 
torn  by  internal  discord.  Men  like  Frohlich  and  Sallwiirk  had 
apostatized  from  Zillerianism ;  Stoy,  before  his  death,  had 
definitely  broken  with  the  extremists,  and  these,  in  response, 

^In  this  same  number  is  an  .article,  entitled,  "Dr.  Dittes  as  Director  of 
the  Vienna  Padagogium,"  intended  to  show  that  Dittes  was  a  man  "  without 
character,  without  conscience,  and  without  fidelity  to  duty  ". 


Dittes  99 

had  developed  an  acerbity  and  touchiness  which  were  excep- 
tional even  in  the  painful  annals  of  German  controversies.  The 
criticisms  offered  by  Dittes  were  studiously  moderate  in  tone ; 
the  retorts  of  his  antagonists  were  the  opposite.  He  was  guilty 
of  "  crafty  mendacity  "  and  unintelligence,  and  deserved  to  have 
his  journal  confiscated  for  its  "radical"  tendencies.  Dittes,  it 
should  be  remarked,  was  a  prominent  Vienna  educationist. 

The  first  article  in  Pddagogium  (1884)  was  a  review  of  the 
work  of  the  ex-Zillerian  Frohlich.  "  Where,"  asks  Dittes,  "  is 
this  boasted  '  scientific  pedagogy '  about  which  even  its  adherents 
quarrel  ?  It  seems  like  the  machine  of  which  some  one  said, 
'  It  is  very  good,  and  has  only  one  defect,  that  it  doesn't  work '." 

The  1885  articles  were  more  important. 

Beginning  with  Herbart's  psychology,  Dittes  shows  that  the 
doctrine  of  "  reals,"  according  to  which  the  soul  is  absolutely 
simple,  devoid  of  faculties,  etc.,  is  quite  useless.  In  fact,  the 
metaphysical  doctrine  of  Being  is  a  fatal  stumbling-block  to 
Herbart's  system.  He  constantly  oscillates  between  appearance 
or  happening  and  real  Being.  Ordinary  mental  processes  are 
mere  appearance  ;  the  "  real  "  soul  is  already  "  ripe  "  and  in- 
capable of  development.  Herbart  cannot  deny  experience,  but 
he  reduces  it  to  a  fiction. ^  Eeal  knowledge  lies  beyond  man's 
grasp. 

Dittes  then  reviews  Herbart's  ethics,  dealing  successively 
with  his  emphasis  on  the  "  aesthetic  judgment,"  with  the 
avowed  absence  of  a  single  unifying  idea,^  and  with  the 
inability  of  the  ethics  to  give  practical  guidance.  He  then 
proceeds  to  criticise  the  "  five  moral  ideas  ".     Logically,  Her- 


^  One  must  omit  most  of  the  metaphysical  discussion.  Dittes'  result  is 
probably  correct.  Herbart  here  appears  as  a  Kantian.  But  still  we  can  learn 
much  from  the  phenomenological  side  of  his  work. 

^  Herbart  expressly  warned  men  against  trying  to  make  ethics  into  a 
sham  unity.  Our  judgments  are  disparate  and  must  remain  so.  But 
Thilo  contends  that  Herbart's  ethics  really  has  a  unity,  inasmuch  as  it 
is  based  on  the  sesthetic  judgment  passed  on  will-relations.  All  harmony 
rests  on  diversity. 


loo  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


bart's  system  of  ideas  suffers  from  the  defect  that  the  first 
(Inner  Freedom)  stands  for  a  relation  of  Will  to  Insight,  not 
of  Will  to  Will.  The  real  content  of  morality  is  given  by  the 
other  four,  and  we  cannot  get  a  fifth  idea  out  of  the  relation 
of  the  Will  to  these  four.  Thus,  the  first  idea  is  not  co-ordinate 
with  the  others. 

Id&a  of  Perfection} — Unless  a  Will  be  morally  good,  its 
Perfection  (in  Herbart's  sense),  that  is  its  Intensity,  Extensity, 
and  Concentration,  arouses  no  approval.  We  do  not  praise  a 
strong-minded  robber.  Herbart's  second  idea  stands  rather  for 
physical  and  intellectual  than  for  moral  eminence. ^ 

Idea  of  Benevolence. — But  why  should  my  Will  devote  itself 
to  the  Will  of  another  person  ?  Surely  only  on  the  ground  of 
welfare  ?     Am  I  to  support  the  will  of  a  robber  ? 

Idea  of  Bight  or  Laio. — "  Strife  displeases."  Does  it  always  ? 
May  I  not  rightly  strive  to  save  something  imperilled  ?  Were 
prophets  and  reformers  wrong  in  stirring  up  strife?  Must  an 
assaulted  person  do  nothing  9^  Significant  that  when  Herbart's 
countrymen  were  struggling  against  Napoleon,  he  himself  re- 
mained in  his  empty  Konigsberg  classroom.  He  was  consistent 
with  his  doctrine  that  "  strife  displeases"  !  His  fourth  idea  is 
too  rigid.     We  must  not  forbid  strife  altogether. 


^  Better,  "  Breadth  and  efficiency  of  Will  ".  The  word  "  Perfection  " 
scarcely  suggests  Herbart's  meaning. 

2  This  raises  a  vastly  important  point.  Herbart  regarded  each  of  his 
five  ideas  as  unmoral  when  taken  alone,  in  abstraction.  He  explicitly  says 
[Lectures,  §  17)  that  the  second  idea  is  not  in  itself  adequate  to  determine 
virtue,  "for  that  can  never  be  done  by  any  one  practical  idea  alone". 
But  Herbart  regarded  strength  and  breadth  of  character  as  a  vital  element 
in  the  complete  moral  life.  Here  comes  in  his  stress  on  many-sided 
Interest,  a  notion  closely  related  to  the  second  moral  idea.  We  do  not 
value  hardness  in  a  diamond  if  the  latter  be  devoid  of  brilliance.  But 
each  quality  is  valuable  in  the  other's  company.  So  with  Ruskin's  Ideas 
of  Relation,  Ideas  of  Power,  etc.  Abstraction  is  not  separation.  Thus 
the  objection  of  Dittes  has  been  anticipated.  The  same  kind  of  answer 
is  to  be  made  in  connection  with  the  Idea  of  Benevolence. 

*  Again  the  same  answer.  There  are  five  ideas  ;  any  one  is  an  ab- 
straction. 


Dittes  loi 

Idea  of  Equity  or  Fairness. — Is  it  true  that  every  deed,  good 
or  bad,  must  be  recompensed  after  its  kind  ?  Does  an  un- 
compensated good  deed  displease  ?  Surely  not  !  It  shines 
with  an  added  brilliancy.  Again,  evil  deeds  do  not  displease 
because  unrequited,  but  because  evil.  One  evil  deed  recom- 
pensed by  another  !  Herbart  himself  admitted  that  the  difficult 
idea  of  Equity  may  conflict  with  that  of  Benevolence.^ 

Again,  can  "Taste"  be  a  sure  foundation  for  moraHty?^ 
Surely  one  person's  "  Taste "  may  conflict  with  another's  ! 
Have  the  ideas  any  force  ?  No,  they  are  powerless,  as  indeed 
is  Herbart's  entire  system  of  Ethics,  which  is  "  devoid  of  every 
trace  of  heroism  and  energy".^ 

Then,  as  to  Herbart's  pedagogy ;  does  this  rest  securely,  as 
he  says,  on  his  ethics  and  psychology  ?  In  point  of  fact  his 
psychology  gives  us  only  a  presentation-mechanism  which 
awakens  nothing  but  horror  and  which  excludes  soul-life  and 
real  development.  The  "  soul "  itself  remains  stiff  and  im- 
potent. Herbart's  ethics  likewise  give  us  nothing  to  aim  at. 
The  moral  ideas,  as  already  said,  have  no  force. 

Again,  the  distinction  of  Regierung  from  Zucht  is  of  dubious 
vaHdity.  The  former  appears  almost  as  a  stranger  living  at  the 
cost  of  its  two  companions,  Zucht  and  Unterricht.  Begierung 
is  said  to  care  only  for  the  present  while  Zucht  cares  for  the 
future — surely  an  unnecessary  distinction,  for  all  Education 
must  look  after  both  present  and  future.  If  Eegierung  is 
uneducative  why  mention  it?* 

^The  fifth  idea  is  certainly  a  difficult  one,  but  yet  it  seems  to  exist. 
What  else  do  we  mean  by  approving  of  Gratitude  and  (as  Butler  did)  of 
Resentment  ?  Let  us  remember  again  the  ahstractness  of  Herbart's  ideas ; 
they  are  not  to  be  taught  as  such  to  children. 

2 Herbart  merely  means  "immediate  Intuition".  The  ideas  are  not 
products  of  reasoning.     They  are  based  on  "insight". 

^  Surely  it  is  important  to  apprehend  the  moral  law,  though  it  is  equally 
important  for  our  inclinations  and  habits  to  conform  to  it  [Lectures,  §  9). 

■*  The  reply  of  Just  is  conclusive.  Herbart's  distinctions  are  useful  to 
be  known,  but  need  not  be  carried  as  such  into  practice.  Herbart's 
classification  shows  the  educator  where  the  needs  lie,  and  prevents  the 
errors  which  spring  from  mental  confusion.     A  "good  disciplinarian"  is 


I02  The  Critics  of  Herbartianisni 

Herbart  came  nearest  to  the  true  view  when  he  said  that  the 
Idea  of  Perfection  suggested  soundness  of  body  and  mind,  a 
"coming  to  the  full  "  of  a  child's  powers.  Why  did  he  not 
follow  out  this  Pestalozzian  concept,  "the  harmonious  develop- 
ment of  all  powers  "  ?  Herbart  answers  that  the  second  idea 
does  not  stand  for  the  whole  of  Virtue.  The  reason  is  that  he 
has  narrowed  it  down. 

He  lived  remote  from  the  world  and  did  not  know  children, 
hence  his  error  that  Virtue  is  the  only  end  of  Education;  hence 
also  his  dragging  in  of  aesthetic  and  religious  culture  under 
"  Interest  ";  likewise  his  reduction  of  Feeling  and  Will  to  pre- 
sentations, and  his  superficial  treatment  of  the  culture  of  the 
dispositions  and  of  the  body.  We  cannot  say  he  actually  forgot 
any  of  the  chief  ends  of  Education,  but  his  subordination  of 
them  to  Virtue  made  their  treatment  irrational.^ 

Herbart's  psychology  excluded  any  sensible  survey  of  mental 
life.     Facts  like  race,  nationality,  and  sex  were  ignored. 

He  laid  great  stress  on  Virtue  as  the  end  of  Education.  But 
has  he,  with  all  his  stress  on  "  educative  Instruction,"  shown 
us  the  path  to  Virtue  ?  No  ;  towards  the  end  of  his  life  his 
confidence  in  Instruction  grew  faint.  It  is  necessary,  he  tells 
us,  that  what  is  learnt  be  fdt.  Individual  differences  may 
hamper  our  task ;  the  things  learnt  may  be  forgotten ;  the 
environment  may  corrupt,  and  all  our  precautions  be  in  vain.^ 


not  necessarily  a  good  educator.  Herbart  expressly  says :  "  In  practice, 
Regierung  and  Zucht  combine  "  {Lectures,  §  42). 

^  Just  retorts  that  when  Dittes  divides  Education  into  aesthetic,  moral, 
etc.,  he  is  really  assuming  separate  faculties  and  separate  exercises  for 
each  faculty.  But  this  gets  rid  of  all  unity  in  Education,  and  may  even 
result  in  a  conflict  of  studies,  and  the  creation  of  distinct  "  circles  of 
thought ".  Moreover  such  a  division  encourages  Egoism  ;  Intellect  would 
be  encouraged  apart  from  Morality.  [There  is  truth  on  both  sides.  Certain 
practical  distinctions  must  be  made ;  but  still  the  Herbartian  doctrine  is 
useful  as  laying  stress  on  the  unity  of  all  education.  It  is  a  great  mistake 
to  isolate  different  departments,  e.g.,  "sacred  "  subjects.  Let  us  have  one 
"  circle  of  thought  "  if  possible.] 

■■'  That  Herbart  became  less  enthusiastic  towards  the  end  of  his  life  was 
not  surprising.    We  must  remember  that  the  General  Pedagogy  was  a 


Dittes  103 

His  original  view  of  moral  Education  was  spoilt  by  his  per- 
verted notion  of  the  origin  of  the  Will ;  he  overestimates  the 
value  of  intellectual  culture  and  therefore  of  Instruction. 

What  a  heterogeneous  mass  of  conceptions  he  gives  us  !  He 
tells  us  that  the  teacher  must  bring  singly  to  actuality  the  two 
members  of  Inner  [Freedom  (Insight  and  Will) ;  then  the  two 
must  be  connected.  Then,  as  a  fourth  step,  Effort  is  to  actualise 
morality  permanently.  As  further  factors  come  inclinations 
and  habits.^ 

At  one  moment  we  hear  of  "many-sided  Interest"  as  the 
goal,  at  another  of  "  Perfection  ".^  Good  maxims  are  said  to 
come  from  the  aesthetic  judgment,  but  this,  on  its  part,  only 
works  powerfully  when  woven  into  the  total  Interest. 

Whence  come  the  five  moral  ideas  ?  Herbart  says  the  soul 
is  absolutely  simple,  even  without  faculties ;  how  then  can  it 
give  rise  to  these  ideas  ?  Are  they  their  own  father  ?  And  how 
can  they  fuse  to  a  unity  ?  ^ 

Herbart   speaks   of    children  passing  judgments   on   others 


juvenile  book.  Glockner  retorts  on  Dittes  that  though  Herbart  may  have 
come  to  admit  the  feeble  influence  of  Instruction,  he  equally  emphasised 
the  v?eak  influence  of  Zucht  or  Training ;  and  he  never  denied  that  the 
Will  was  rooted  in  the  circle  of  thought. 

1  Just  replies  that  Dittes  is  again  regarding  distinctions  drawn  for  clear- 
ness' sake  as  separate  stages.  Moral  Insight  is  not  formed  apart  from  Feel- 
ing, and  this  is  brought  about  by  the  observation  of  images  of  human  action. 
The  aesthetic  judgment  is  not  cold,  but  involves  a  feeling  of  sympathy 
with  the  perceived  acts.  All  the  several  tasks  of  moral  Education  really 
go  on  side  by  side.  Attempt  and  Action  give  rise  to  Will,  and  this  renders 
Training  necessary.  [Herbart  expressly  says,  "  We  can  seldom  wait  for 
the  development  of  the  aesthetic  judgment";  Lectures,  §  27.  Dittes  has 
here  again,  as  in  his  criticisms  of  the  Moral  Ideas  and  of  Regierung  and 
Zucht,  regarded  abstract  distinctions  as  separate  stages,  quite  contrary  to 
Herbart's  intention.] 

^  The  second  moral  idea  is  undoubtedly  connected  closely  with  many- 
sided  Interest.  But  Glockner  rightly  replies  that  Herbart  never  put  for- 
ward either  of  these  notions  as  the  complete  goal  of  Education. 

^  Glockner  replies,  "  The  ideas  arise  along  with  their  objects.  Every  re- 
action must  be  different  for  each  different  experience.  If  the  soul  were 
not  simple  we  might  then  rightly  ask,  '  Whence  the  fusion  ? ' " 


104  "J^he  Critics  of  Herbartianisni 


before  themselves — thus,  of  judgment  apart  from  moral  dis- 
position. But  the  writer  has  never  seen  such  a  naked  judgment 
in  children.^ 

The  moral  ideas,  Herbart  tells  us,  are  without  force.  If  so, 
whence  comes  the  motive  force?  By  the  ideas  becoming 
involved  in  Interest,  we  are  told ;  Training  must  be  connected 
with  Instruction.  But  yet  Herbart  constantly  tells  us  that 
the  Will  is  rooted  in  presentations ;  so  whence  comes  the  real 
and  original  spring  of  the  moral  life  ?  Even  Interest  (rooted 
in  presentations)  cannot  yield  it.  His  doctrine  is  false  to  facts 
and  also  to  Christianity,  which  says  that  action  springs  from  the 
heart,  not  from  the  circle  of  thought.^ 

The  presentational  doctrine  is  false.  A  child  has  numberless 
pleasures,  pains,  desires,  etc.,  before  presentations. ^  Again  Effort 
is  not  always  directed  to  the  freeing  of  checked  presentations ; 
on  the  contrary,  it  often  aims  at  freeing  from  some  disagreeable 
presentation. 

Herbart's  whole  scheme  of  mental  statics  and  dynamics  is 
false,  and,  therefore,  his  scheme  of  "  educative  Instruction  "  is 
false  also.  Character-strength,  with  him,  rests  on  "  great  masses 
of  thought-material  which  work  a  deep  resultant  feeling  ".  Chris- 
tianity says,  "  Blessed  are  the  poor  in  spirit "  !  A  poor  peasant 
wife  may  have  a  finer  character  than  the  most  learned  professor.* 
Alas  for  men  if  the  most  precious  of  things  is  dependent  upon 
deep  thought !  Again,  it  is  not  true  that  opposed  presentations 
always  darken  and  check  each  other;  they  often  clarify  each  other. 

The  longer  Herbart  lived  the  more  he  came  to  see  that  other 

1  Just  retorts,  "  Then  Dittes  must  know  children  very  badly.  Any 
mother  or  teacher  will  confirm  Herbart."  [But  Dittes  probably  means, 
"Will  the  judgments  spring  up  spontaneously?"] 

2  Dittes'  criticism  is  here  probably  sound.  If  we  accept  pure  presenta- 
tionalism  and  deny  any  original  tendency  to  act  we  cannot  explain  volition. 
But  see  Introdiuition,  pp.  30-1. 

*  Glockner,  following  Herbart,  answers  that  a  feeling  may  be  presenta- 
tional at  basis,  i.e.,  due  to  a  multitude  of  obscure  stimuli.  [But  no  one  can 
prove  this.] 

*  Glockner  politely  replies  that  even  the  Devil  can  quote  texts  for  his 
purpose.    A  "  learned  prpfessor  "  may  be  "  poor  in  spirit ". 


DitUs  to5 

agencies  besides  Instruction  were  of  moral  value  ;  hobbies,  home 
training,  habituation,  etc.^  But  though  Herbart's  views  became 
more  sound,  he  never  abandoned  the  doctrine  that  punishments 
and  rewards,  which  imitate  nature,  do  not  serve  for  moral 
bettering.2 

Herbart  is  also  unfortunate  with  his  "  Interest "  doctrine. 
He  rightly  says,  "  Interest  is  self -activity,"  but  he  ought  to 
distinguish  its  two  elements  :  (a)  activity  ;  (6)  satisfaction.  His 
classification  of  Interests  is  also  illogical.  He  mixes  up  forms  of 
Interest  (Empirical,  Speculative,  Contemplative)  with  contents  of 
Interest  (objects  of  experience,  etc.).  Above  all  he  never  tells 
us  the  real  origin  of  Interest ;  his  psychology  prevents  him. 
Was  there,  or  was  there  not,  a  germ  of  Interest  before  the 
objects  of  Interest  came  to  be  known? 

Reform  of  Herbart's  Interest  Doctrine. — We  can  classify  In- 
terests, says  Dittes,  according  to  either  form  or  matter.  Form- 
ally we  should  have  Empirical,  Speculative,  Contemplative, 
Mnemonic,  Productive,  etc.  Herbart  himself  has  mentioned 
a  Systematic  and  a  Methodic  Interest.  We  could  also  speak 
of  an  Analytic  and  a  Synthetic  Interest.  According  to  Matter 
or  Content  we  could  classify  Interest  as  Esthetic,  Eeligious, 
Historic,  Agricultural,  Practical,  Scientific,  etc.  There  is  also 
Personal  Interest  (in  health,  etc.). 

Herbart  was  not  the  discoverer  of  the  Interest  doctrine. 
Comenius,  Pestalozzi,  Niemeyer  and  others  had  anticipated 
him.  Thus  Niemeyer  urged  teachers  to  excite  indwelling 
forces.  But  these  men  rightly  regarded  Interest  as  depending 
on  a  spontaneous  force  of  the  mind,  as  the  development  of  a 
natural  germ.  Herbart's  special  mechanism  does  not  really 
explain  Interest  at  all. 

He  makes  good  remarks  on  Attention  and  Apperception. 
This  is  the  best  part  of  his  work.     But  Comenius  long  ago 

^  Such  things,  says  Glockner,  come  under  Zucht  and  Regierung.  Her- 
bart never  discounted  them. 

^  Nor  do  they,  says  Glockner.  They  ser\'e  to  warn  and  admonish,  but 
equally  well  bad  men  and  good.  [Herbart  is  here  in  opposition  to  the 
doctrine  of  "  natural  punishments  "  advocated  by  Spencer  and  others.] 


io6  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

had  urged  that  all  Instruction  should  conform  naturally  to 
the  pupil's  standpoint.  Even  Herbart's  best  work  is  injured 
by  perversions  and  exaggerations,  which  mostly  arise  out  of 
his  false  mechanical  view  of  presentations. 

In  the  scheme  of  "  Formal  Steps  "  the  terms  "  System  "  and 
"Method"  are  ill  chosen;  and  the  terms  "Analysis"  and 
"  Synthesis  "  are  used  waveringly.  The  Herbartian  pedagogy 
not  only  rests  on  untenable  foundations,  and  is  a  failure  in  its 
outlines,  but  it  is  also  extremely  deficient,  obscure,  and  con- 
fused in  its  definitions  and  terminology.  Its  originality  consists 
mainly  in  its  unsuccessful  elucidations  of  old  thoughts,  and  in 
the  introduction  of  new  names  and  classifications  which,  for  the 
most  part,  are  badly  brought  forward,  have  no  value,  scientific 
or  practical,  and  are  also  precisely  adapted  to  cause  a  complete, 
confusion  of  concepts  and  language.  The  terminology  would 
prevent  any  communication  with  parents,  boards  of  managers, 
etc. 

Herbart's  suggestions  for  dealing  with  classics,  mathematics, 
and  geography  {e.g.,  his  recommendation  to  connect  this  last 
one  with  other  subjects)  are  good.  But  he  has  not  dealt  with 
modern  languages,  drawing,  and  singing.  His  remarks  on 
religious  Instruction  are  obscure.  Virtually  he  hands  the  sub- 
ject over  to  the  theologians.  Its  culmination,  he  says,  lies  in 
Confirmation  (accompanied  by  a  special  confession)  and  the 
Holy  Communion  (a  sign  of  general  brotherhood).  He  recom- 
mends Plato's  Krito  and  Apology  for  strengthening  religious  im- 
pressions. (What  will  religious  people  say  ?)  He  says  nothing 
of  fairy  tales,  neither  does  he  tell  us  whether  schools  should 
be  sectarian,  unsectarian,  or  governmental.  At  times  he  says 
some  hard  things  about  Church  arrogance,  but  he  finally  leaves 
the  Church  in  an  almost  impregnable  position.  His  metaphysic 
is  really  incompatible  with  Eehgion,  hence  he  bases  rehgion 
merely  on  practical  needs,  e.g.,  the  need  to  keep  the  mind 
humble.^ 

^  Glockner  shows,  by  quotations,  that  Herbart's  piety  was  warm  and 
sincere. 


Wesendonck  107 


SECTION  II. 

WESENDONCK. 
(1885.) 

Reference. 

Wesendonck.     Die  Schule  Herbart-Ziller  und  ihre  JUnger  vor  dem  Forum 
der  Kritik.    Pichlers  Witwe  und  Sohn,  Vienna  and  Leipzig,  1885. 

The  above  work  is,  in  part,  a  critique  of  Herbartian  and 
Zillerian  (chiefly  the  latter)  ideas,  but  its  main  interest  lies  in 
its  scathing  exposure  of  the  controversial  methods  of  the 
Zillerians.  The  author  shows  that,  with  all  their  zeal  and 
merits,  these  men  have  very  bad  manners.  Among  other  things, 
they  accuse  their  opponents  of  being  "vulgar  pedagogues," 
"mere  practitioners,"  "ignoramuses,"  "nullities,"  "people  to 
whom  pedagogy  is  an  El  Dorado  of  dilettantism,"  and  "  people 
whose  mental  horizon  ends  with  their  noses  ". 

Wesendonck  commences  with  an  historical  survey  of  the 
Herbartian  movement,  dealing  in  some  detail  with  the  work 
of  Stoy  and  Ziller.     He  criticises  Ziller  as  follows  : — 

He  was  not  devoid  of  merits.  He  had  much  knowledge, 
much  boldness,  and  a  warm  love  for  man.  But  he  did  not 
know  the  capacities  of  the  average  child,  nor  the  distinction 
between  the  desirable  and  the  attainable.  That  is  to  say,  he 
was  unpractical,  and  must  therefore  not  be  accepted  as  a  pope. 

When  he  approved  of  putting  the  whole  Bible  into  the 
hands  of  children  he  was  wrong ;  many  parts  are  unsuitable, 
indeed  unreadable. 

His  proposal  to  make  the  elementary  schools  schools  for  the 
poor  only,  was  thoroughly  bad.  It  would  degrade  these  schools, 
and  generate  pride,  envy,  etc.  Separate  schools  for  different 
ranks  would  be  not  only  unadvisable,  but  far  too  expensive  for 
any  State.  Still  special  schools  for  neglected  or  peculiar  children 
are  useful. 

His  condemnation  of  French  as  an  uneducative  language  is 


lo8  The  Critics  of  Herbartianisni 


unjust.  Ziller  was  prejudiced  against  modern  languages  and 
only  approved  of  giving  a  smattering  of  them  for  practical 
purposes,  e.g.,  to  future  merchants.  If  such  languages  are  to 
be  postponed  to  the  University  stage  they  vpill  never  be  learnt 
properly. 

He  rightly  demands  that  Syntax  be  learnt  inductively  during 
the  course  of  reading,  but  he  is  wrong  in  demanding  the  same 
for  Etymology.  Surely,  to  learn  the  conjugations,  etc.,  in  this 
way  would  be  wearisome  and  distracting.  What  a  vast  amount 
of  reading  would  be  necessary,  and  how  insecure  the  knowledge 
would  be !  The  first  thing  should  be  a  rapid  glance  at  the 
conjugations,  then  reading.  Herbart  was  here  more  sound 
than  Ziller. 

The  Zillerian  curriculum  is  overcrowded,  including  such 
things  as  reading  foreign  handwriting.  In  higher  schools 
musical  and  theatrical  exhibitions  are  to  take  place.  But 
where  are  the  buildings,  utensils,  etc.,  to  be  obtained?  Who  is 
to  bear  the  expense  ?  Ziller  recommends  that  in  the  accessory 
classes  of  upper  schools  medicine  should  be  taught  to  future 
physicians,  Hebrew  to  future  theologians,  etc.  But  surely  a 
school  should  be  on  general  lines ;  pupils  may  not  yet  know  their 
future  calling.     Science  would  do  the  theologians  more  good.^ 

Ziller  expected  vast  knowledge  from  his  teachers,  e.g.,  know- 
ledge of  foreign  forms  of  speech  (and  even  their  constituents) 
which  have  been  introduced  into  the  vernacular. 

He  objects  to  a  merely  "popular"  style  of  teaching.  But 
many  subjects  must  be  taught  "popularly"  or  not  at  all. 
Teachers  would  have  to  live  to  the  age  of  Methuselah  to  satisfy 
Ziller's  demands. 

Ziller 's  "  concentration  "  plan  would  really  lead  to  a  breaking- 
up  of  connected  matter.     The  pupil  would  only  acquire  scrappy 

^  Ziller  is  often  attacked  from  two  sides.  Some  critics  contend  that  a 
school  should  "  prepare  for  life  ; "  these  protest  against  his  claim  that 
schools  should  "  educate,"  i.e.,  form  character.  Others  protest  against  his 
admission  of  professional  subjects  in  upper  classes.  The  two  objections 
neutralise  each  other.  Ziller  was  right  in  laying  the  main  stress  on  "  Edu- 
cation," but  he  made  quite  sufficient  concessions  to  utilitarian  demands. 


Wesendonck  109 


knowledge,  not  connected  views  of  a  subject.  Only  the  "  con- 
centration "  material  at  the  centre  will  get  justice,  and  children 
will  even  get  tired  of  this  owing  to  its  constant  recurrence. 
To  use  the  story  of  the  "  seven  little  goats  "  for  purposes  of 
arithmetic,  geography,  etc.,  is  only  to  make  children  hate  the 
story.  Why,  after  all,  this  craving  for  "  concentration  "  ?  The 
child  hears  all  kinds  of  matter  and  yet  does  not  lose  his 
personality.  Besides,  where  is  the  "  concentration "  in  using 
twelve  fairy  tales  ?  And  is  there  any  proof  that  this  plan  of 
"concentration"  aids  character? 

The  fairy  tales  are  useful  aids  to  imagination  and  feeling,  but 
have  little  bearing  on  morality.  They  are  partly  survivals  from 
pagan  mythology,  partly  later  in  origin  ;  they  certainly  do  not 
represent  any  one  "culture  epoch".  But  even  if  they  did,  is 
it  necessary  to  lead  Christian  children  through  heathen  and 
Jewish  stages?^ 

Some  of  the  fables  positively  shook  our  moral  or  aesthetic 
feelings ;  others  appear  silly  even  to  the  young ;  in  other  cases 
the  lessons  deduced  from  them  are  beyond  children's  capacities, 
e.g.,  "Don't  judge  according  to  appearances".  (How,  then,  is 
a  child  to  judge  ?) 

Again,  as  FrohUch  has  shown,  the  Kobinson  Crusoe  stage  is 
not  suitable  for  children  of  seven,  for  things  like  sea,  ship- 
wreck, etc.,  are  beyond  them.  The  desire  for  travel  comes 
about  the  age  of  twelve,  and  then  the  story  has  much  value. 
But  it  represents  a  stage  of  culture  far  in  advance  of  the  patri- 
archal, and  is  also  morally  in  advance  of  it.  What  folly,  there- 
fore, to  put  it  before  the  patriarchal  period ! 

Whole  stages  are  missing  from  Ziller's  scheme,  e.g.,  the  pre- 
language  stage,  the  stages  of  fetichism,^  polytheism,  etc.  His 
scheme  is  not  even  orthodox ;  where  does  the  fall  of  man  come 
in?     The  present-day  stage  is  left  out  altogether,  though  the 


^  Yes,  says  (in  effect)  Dr.  Stanley  Hall.     See  p.  71. 

^  Dr.  Stanley  Hall  in  his  daring  contribution  to  Principles  of  Religious 
Education  recommends  "  nature  study  "  for  Sunday  Schools,  as  correspond- 
ing to  the  stage  of  fetichism  in  the  race. 


no  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

most  important  of  all.  Is  the  boy  of  fourteen  a  man  already  ? 
Apparently  so,  if  the  eighth  stage  is  the  final  one. 

Is  the  life  of  Jesus  a  "  stage,"  properly  speaking?  Is  it  to 
be  "  lived  through  "  ?  In  any  case  its  importance  is  under- 
estimated in  the  Zillerian  scheme.  Moreover  the  eighth  stage 
(the  Eeformation)  is  a  stage  of  heresy  for  Catholics. 

In  Ziller's  plan  there  is  an  absence  of  recognition  given  to 
such  principles  as  nationality,  patriotism,  the  rights  of  man,  the 
Hmitation  of  the  absolute  power  of  rulers,  the  extension  of  state 
power  in  the  interests  of  members,  tolerance,  love  of  men  in 
general.     Ziller's  selection  of  historical  material  is  arbitrary. 

Again  his  distinction  between  "educative"  and  "uneduca- 
tive  "  instruction  is  artificial ;  all  material,  properly  handled,  ought 
to  be  educative.  There  should  be  moral  ideas  in  it  all,  though  the 
pupils  may  not  be  conscious  of  them.i  But  some  departments 
are  better  than  others  for  moral  purposes.  History  (religious 
and  profane)  is  especially  good,  but  fables  (we  have  seen)  are 
not  so  good  as  Ziller  thinks  them  to  be. 

His  attempt  to  teach  modern  history  contemporaneously 
with  ancient  is  unpractical,  and  violates  true  concentration.  No 
wonder  some  of  his  followers  wish  to  teach  history  partly  back- 
wards, partly  forwards. 

Ziller  sometimes  appears  like  a  theologian  of  the  Middle  Ages 
in  his  overvaluation  of  the  Jews,  Greeks,  and  Eomans,  and  in 
his  admiration  for  Latin. 

Another  defect  of  Herbartianism  is  its  cumbrous  terminology. 
Instead  of  "  Eegierung  "  why  not  say  "  outer  guidance  " ;  in- 
stead of  "Zucht,"  "inner  guidance"?  Moreover,  the  dis- 
tinction between  these  two  and  between  them  and  Instruction 
was  known  long  before  Herbart.  That  Instruction  should  not 
only  give  knowledge  but  also  form  character  is  no  new  dis- 
covery.    The  whole  Herbartian  school  sufifers  from  verbosity 


1  This  is  nonsense.  The  only  important  moral  part  played  by  mathe- 
matics is  that  the  study  may  possibly  function  as  a  life  interest.  But  history 
deals  with  man  as  such.  Ziller's  distinction,  though  only  a  rough  one,  is 
quite  justified. 


Wesendonck  1 1 1 


and  arrogance.  The  reader  of  the  writings  of  the  Herbartians 
requires  a  special  dictionary,  and  must  discount  their  claims  to 
be  the  only  educationists. 

Generally  it  may  be  said  that  the  Zillerians  overestimate  the 
value  of  Instruction,  owing  to  their  adherence  to  Herbart's 
presentational  psychology.  Parental  love,  family  love,  imita- 
tion, personality  of  the  teacher,  influence  of  companions  and 
books,  are  far  more  influential. 

Still,  the  Herbart-Ziller  system  has  certain  excellences,  among 
which  may  be  mentioned  (1)  its  insistence  on  many-sided 
Interest  as  contrasted  with  dry  knowledge  or  skill,  and  on  the 
rousing  of  involuntary  attention ;  (2)  its  insistence  on  the  view 
that  Instruction  must  be  "educative"  {i.e.,  from  character); 
but  supreme  authority  must  not  be  given  to  any  one  kind  of 
instruction-material ;  (3)  the  apperception  doctrine ;  (4)  the 
articulation  of  Instruction ;  here  come  in  the  "  formal  steps  " 
which  are  useful  but  must  not  be  slavishly  followed  ;  moreover 
they  are  not  exclusively  Herbartian ;  (5)  Ziller's  grand  design 
of  forming  a  teaching-plan,  in  place  of  a  mere  aggregate  of 
studies ;  he  carried  it  to  absurdities,  but  he  deserves  praise  for 
aiming  at  it;  (6)  Ziller's  recommendation  of  conversational 
rather  than  catechetical  methods  ;  Dittes  and  others  have,  how- 
ever, made  the  same  recommendation  ;  (7)  Ziller's  emphasis  on 
the  dignity  of  the  educational  calHng.  But  he  and  many  other 
Herbartians  think  too  much  of  home  education  and  regard 
schools  mainly  as  auxiliary  agents,  though  upon  them  he  some- 
times puts  too  great  demands.  Moreover  his  thoughts  were 
fixed  too  much  on  the  upper  classes  of  society. 

Wesendonck's  work,  as  already  said,  is  largely  devoted  to  an 
exposure  of  the  controversial  methods  of  the  Herbartians.  Vogt, 
successor  of  Ziller,  comes  in  for  special  castigation.  Because 
Dittes  had  written  a  critique — one  quite  free  from  offensive 
personalities — Vogt  must  needs  accuse  him  of  "  mendacity," 
"hostility  to  all  science,"  "plagiarism,"  "impiousness,"  "party 
spirit,"  and  so  forth,  and  urges  that  the  State  should  suppress 
all  forms  of  "  anarchism,"  such  as  those  represented  by  the 


112  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

"  radicalism  "  of  Dittes  and  his  "  terrorist  "  followers.  Yet 
Vogt  was  head  of  a  union  aiming  at  "educative  Instruction," 
i.e..  Instruction  that  makes  for  character  ! 


SECTION  III. 

BARTELS. 

(1885.) 

Reference. 
Bartels.    Die  Anwendbarkeit  der  Herbart-Ziller-Stoy'schen  didaktiscJien 
Grundsdtze  fUr  den  Unterricht  in  Volks-  und  Bilrgcrschulen.     Wittenberg, 
1885,  1888, 

It  was  to  Dr.  Bartels,  director  of  the  "  Biirgerschulen  "  of 
Gera,  that  Stoy  sent  the  epigrammatic  message  which  pro- 
claimed the  breach  between  the  moderate  and  the  extreme  (or 
Zillerian)  followers  of  Herbart.  "  "What  is  good  in  Ziller  is  not 
new,  what  is  new  is  not  good." 


Ziller's  doctrines  (says  Bartels)  are  defective  on  the  practical 
side.  Herbart  himself  had  recognised  the  important  part  played 
by  practice.  Speculation  and  psychology  are  not  the  only  things 
necessary  for  pedagogy.  We  may  recognise  Ziller's  services, 
yet  deny  them  to  be  very  Titanic. 

The  Herbartians  build  their  system  on  ethics  and  psychology. 
This  is  good,  but  insufficient.  Religion  has  independent  worth 
and  goes  far  beyond  the  "  moral  ideas  ".  Man  has  to  be  made 
into  God's  image  ;  he  must  be  "  saved  "  ;  this  is  not  the  same 
as  being  fed  with  a  number  of  Interests.  Even  Ziller,  though 
going  beyond  Herbart  in  recognising  the  claims  of  religion,  did 
not  sufficiently  emphasise  the  need  of  Christian  faith. 

The  defects  of  Herbart's  psychology  have  been  adequately 
exposed  by  Ostermann  and  others.  Whatever  Herbartians 
may  say,  the  soul  has  faculties,  and  cannot  be  resolved  into 
a  presentation-mechanism.  Attention  cannot  be  explained  on 
Herbart's  theory ;  though  occasioned  by  presentations,  it  ia 


Bartels  113 

something  more  than  they.  Herbart's  view  results  in  an 
exaggeration  of  the  power  of  education. 

''Educative,  Instruction" — The  Herbartians  lay  great  stress 
on  this  "  Instruction  which  forms  Character,"  and  strongly 
condemn  much  Instruction  and  many  Schools  as  really  "  un- 
educative ".  Very  good !  But  Luther,  Comenius,  Locke, 
Pestalozzi,  Niemeyer,  Diesterweg  had  all  urged  that  Instruc- 
tion should  make  for  Character,  and  Diesterweg's  views  were 
very  similar,  on  this  subject,  to  those  of  Herbart, 

"  Schools  do  not  Educate." — The  old  fashion  was  to  give  the 
"  Three  E's,"  plus  religious  Instruction  in  the  form  of  indigest- 
ible biblical  and  catechetical  material.  Then  science  came  to 
the  front,  and  there  occurred  a  heaping-up  of  new  subjects — 
"  didactic  materialism  " — but  no  principle  of  selection.  Hence 
"  Interest  "  was  not  aroused,  for  the  material  was  not  arranged 
in  accordance  with  the  child's  natural  capacities.  But ' '  Interest," 
say  the  Herbartians,  is  the  one  great  essential ;  it  is  an  end,  not 
a  mere  means ;  self-activity  must  be  roused. 

"Good,"  says  the  critic,  "but  not  original."  Pestalozzi, 
Niemeyer,  Diesterweg  saw  this.  Moreover,  the  Herbartians 
lay  exaggerated  stress  on  Instruction,  and  depreciate  such 
influences  as  personality,  family,  and  environment, 

"  Culture  stages." — Here  the  Zillerians  go  quite  beyond  Her- 
bart. Ziller  claims  that  language  shows  that  a  similar  develop- 
ment took  place  in  race  and  in  individual,  and  this  is  one  of  the 
supports  of  his  doctrine.  But  does  he  ever  really  prove  that  the 
individual  goes  through  the  stages  of  the  race  ?  Never !  Men 
like  Frohlich  claim  that  though  there  are  analogies  there  is  no 
real  parallelism.  Is  it  possible  to  believe  that  there  are  eight 
stages  of  racial  development  capable  of  being  represented  by 
the  eight  arbitrarily  selected  stages  of  a  German  elementary 
school  ?  Strange !  Dr.  Staude,  though  a  Zillerian,  has  ad- 
mitted that  the  stages  of  child  development  cannot  be  very 
exactly  defined,  and  Sallwxirk  has  attacked  Ziller's  plan  at 
many  points.  He  has  asked,  for  example,  whether  the  Protes- 
tant German  Empire  and  the  Lutheran  catechism  necessarily 
represent  the  highest  hitherto  attainable  stages  of  human  pro- 

8 


114  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


gress.  And  is  not  a  scheme  seriously  defective  if  it  is  only 
applicable  to  Protestant  children  ? 

Sallwiirk's  book  created  a  sensation,  and  Eein,  in  his  reply, 
had  to  modify  his  master's  scheme,  and  lay  stress  on  national 
rather  than  cosmopolitan  "culture  stages  ".  Dorpfeld  likewise, 
though  an  Herbartian,  has  only  accepted  the  "  culture  stages  " 
doctrine  on  condition  of  its  being  combined  with  the  "  concentric 
circles  "  plan. 

Let  us  consider  Ziller's  proposal  to  use  fairy  tales  as  the 
centre  of  the  first  year's  instruction.  These  tales  may  be 
useful,  but  they  cannot  take  the  place  of  religious  Instruction 
proper.  They  are  imagination-  and  /eeZm^-material,  and  work 
aesthetically,  not  morally.^  Moreover,  some  of  the  objections 
to  the  bibUcal  stories  {e.g.,  that  they  represent  sons  who  deceive 
their  parents)  hold  good  of  certain  fairy  tales.  Few  of  the  tales 
recommended  by  Ziller  have  moral  value  ;  some  are  positively 
pernicious,  and  represent  wrong  acts  being  rewarded.  But  how 
grandly  reward  and  punishment  are  represented  in  the  Bible  ! 
And  how  hollow  the  moral  lessons  deduced  from  the  twelve 
fairy  tales  !  Still  again,  how  absurd  to  subordinate  all  Instruc- 
tion in  the  first  year  to  these  twelve  stories,  a  plan  which 
unnaturally  spUts  up  Instruction !  Use  the  stories,  but  not  as 
material  for  moral,  arithmetical,  and  other  Instruction.  Avoid, 
moreover,  stimulating  the  fancy  too  much. 

Biblical  narratives  are  by  no  means  too  difiicult  for  young 
children;  indeed,  they  are  so  natm-al,  truthful,  simple,  and 
impressive  that  they  readily  seize  the  juvenile  mind.  Fables 
are  known  even  to  children  as  being  fictitious,  and  should  not 
be  used  for  religious  Instruction.  Doubtless  biblical  stories 
require  some  preparation,  but  this  has  already  been  provided 
in  Christmas  and  other  festivals. 

Then  as  to  Eobinson  Crusoe.  The  high  claims  put  forward 
on  behalf  of  this  story  (that  it  is  full  of  moral  value,  etc.)  cannot 
be  justified ;    moreover  the  story  ought  not  to   belong  to  the 

1  This  is  precisely  what  the  wiser  Zillerians  would  admit.  The  child  is 
too  young  to  be  fed  with  moral  or  religious  material  in  the  ordinary  sense. 


Battels  115 

second  school  year,  it  would  do  better  for  boys  of  thirteen 
craving  for  adventures  ;  Crusoe,  too,  is  an  eighteenth-century 
hero,  largely  fictitious  ;  he  does  not  represent  a  "  culture  stage  " 
earlier  than  the  patriarchal.  He  knows  agriculture,  the  com- 
pass, etc.  ;  no  child  at  the  age  supposed  possesses  the  requisite 
apperception-material,  and  if  he  did  he  would  get  tired  of  Crusoe, 
Crusoe,  for  a  whole  year.  Far  better  would  it  be  to  let  the 
children  "  begin  at  home  "  than  to  try  to  make  them  assimilate 
all  the  geographical  and  other  matter  presented  in  the  Crusoe 
story.  Herbart,  like  Eousseau,  approved  of  the  story,  but  not 
for  seven-year-olds.  Besides,  why  should  such  young  children 
have  to  "subject  nature  to  their  service"  as  Crusoe  did?  In 
fact  the  case  for  Crusoe  is  far  weaker  than  for  the  fairy  tales. 

Less  need  be  said  of  the  other  school  years,  for  which  the 
Zillerians  definitely  select  biblical  material.  But  the  problem 
still  rises  ;  is  there  the  parallelism  between  racial  and  individual 
development?  Do  the  "culture  stages"  correspond  to  real 
apperception  stages  of  the  child's  mind?  Especially  wrong  is 
the  giving  of  only  one  year  to  the  life  of  Christ,  and  the  long 
time  spent  on  the  Old  Testament.  Are  the  "  judges "  any 
advance  on  the  "patriarchs"? 

What  about  schools  in  which  the  year's  course  is  not  com- 
pleted— as  happened  even  at  the  practising  school  in  Leipzig ! 
Various  hindrances  may  prevent  a  child  from  reaching  the  first 
class.  Surely  a  scheme  should  meet  contingencies  like  these ! 
Again,  what  about  a  school  without  eight  classes  ?  In  a  four- 
class  school  are  we  to  dro'p  stages,  or  alternate  them  thus  : 
1880,  Fables  ;  1881,  Eobinson ;  1882,  Fables  ;  and  so  on  ?  But 
the  latter  plan  means  that  Eobinson  must  sometimes  precede 
Fables ! 

Beligious  Services. — As  the  Zillerians  reject  biblical  history 
for  the  earHer  years  they  compensate  for  the  loss  by  means  of 
rehgious  services  which,  however,  are  not  supposed  to  take  the 
form  of  "Instruction".  But  who  can  deal,  e.g.,  with  the  life 
of  Jesus  without  giving  "  Instruction  "  ?  Moreover,  to  separate 
devotion  from  Instruction  is  scarcely  conformable  with  the 
doctrine  of    "  Concentration  ".      Again,    these    services    will 


ii6  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

necessarily  be  either  beyond  the  younger  children  or  below  the 
older  ones — hence  weariness. 

"  Concentric  Circles." — The  Herbartians  are  severe  on  this 
plan,  that  of  making  each  "  school  year  "  take  up  much  the  same 
material  as  the  previous  one,  but  amplifying  it  in  ever  widening 
circles.  In  preference  to  this  the  Herbartians  recommend  a 
chronological  order  ("  culture  stages  "),  and  claim  that  "  con- 
centric circles  "  involve  weariness  and  satiety  owing  to  constant 
repetitions. 

But  (says  the  critic)  this  plan  of  "circles"  has  long  been 
approved  by  great  educationists,  like  Comenius,  and  even 
Herbartians  like  Dorpfeld  and  Lentz  approve  of  it,  though  in 
conjunction  with  the  rival  plan.  It  is  quite  right  to  begin  with 
some  simple  facts  and  then  make  them  more  definite  as  the  age 
of  the  pupil  iacreases  ;  thus  we  keep  the  old  material  safe  and 
sound  (which  the  Zillerians  are  in  danger  of  not  doing)  and  add 
each  year  fresh  material.     The  old  apperceives  the  new. 

Ziller's  plan  allows  of  all  kinds  of  thought-wanderings,  as 
when  the  mention  of  Bremen  is  supposed  to  awaken  such 
Interest  as  to  justify  a  geographical  discussion.  Surely  we 
ought  to  go  "from  near  to  far".  Instead  of  following  this 
sound  principle,  Ziller  allows  quite  young  children  to  learn 
about  the  geography  of  the  East,  and  to  discuss  all  kinds  of 
difficult  matters  (hke  hereditary  succession,  in  connection  with 
the  Judges).  The  plan  of  "concentric  circles,"  on  the  other 
hand,  allows  of  a  gradual  advance. 

If  the  ZiUerians  protest  against  everlasting  repetition,  we 
protest  against  neglect  of  repetition.  Again,  the  plan  of 
"  culture  stages  "  can  only  properly  be  applied  to  eight-class 
schools,  that  of  "concentric  circles  "  to  any  schools  ;  and  thus 
even  if  a  boy  has  to  leave  school  before  reaching  the  top  class 
this  is  not  so  serious  a  matter  in  the  second  case  as  in  the  first. 

"  Concentration." — The  Herbartian  psychology  ignores  the 
unity  of  the  self;  hence  an  artificial  "  concentration  "  has  to  be 
brought  about.  All  educators  admit  that  knowledge  should  be 
unified  as  far  as  possible.  But  instead  of  effecting  this,  Ziller's 
plan  really  brings  about  disunion,  for  each  department  of  study 


Ostermann  117 

that  is  subordinated  to  the  central  one  receives  only  a  scrappy 
treatment.  Thus  geography  has  to  follow  the  fortunes  of  the 
patriarchs  and  so  forth,  instead  of  pursuing  its  own  natural 
course.  Ziller  has  tried  to  deny  that  this  is  the  outcome  of  his 
proposals,  but  in  vain. 

It  is  quite  right  to  connect  together  related  material.  But 
the  tendency  of  Ziller's  plan  is  towards  a  merely  external  con- 
necting, as  when  the  burial  of  the  patriarchs  in  the  limestone 
hills  of  Canaan  is  used  as  a  peg  on  which  to  hang  a  lesson  on 
the  properties  of  chalk.  Surely  each  subject  should  be  allowed 
to  awaken  its  own  interest.  Many  even  of  his  followers  have 
modified  his  plan  so  as  to  introduce  several  "  centres,"  and  to 
give  independence  to  science,  etc.  Moreover  the  supposed  paral- 
lelism between  Jewish  and  profane  history  is  quite  imaginary. 

Still,  the  Zillerians  deserve  credit  for  having  insisted  on  the 
idea  of  "  concentration  ".  Lessons  should  fit  into  each  other 
and  throw  as  much  light  upon  each  other  as  possible.  All 
natural  and  useful  connections  should  be  made  use  of. 

The  Formal  Steps. — This  is  the  best  part  of  the  Herbartian 
system,  though  it  is  not  original.  Comenius  had  drawn  up  a 
very  similar  plan  :  Example,  Explanation,  Bule,  Exercise.  The 
teacher  must  not  become  enslaved  to  Herbart's  scheme.  The 
first  of  the  "  steps  "  is  often  unnecessary,  and  the  giving  of  the 
"  goal "  is  not  always  possible. 


SECTION  IV. 

OSTEEMANN. 

(1887.) 
Reference. 

Ostermann.  Die  hauptsdchlichsten  IrrtUmer  der  Herbartschen  Psy- 
chologie  und-ihre  pcidagogischen  Konsequenzen.  Oldenburg  and  Leipzig, 
1887. 

No   part  of    Herbart's   philosophy  has   been    more    violently 
attacked  ttan  his  psychology ;  a  work  dealing  with  the  "  Critics 


ii8  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

of  Herbartianism"  ought  therefore  to  include  a  discussion  of 
psychological  problems.  Ostermann's  attack  was  on  these 
lines,  and  also  touched  upon  pedagogical  matters. 

Herbart  thought  himself  driven  to  the  assumption  of  a 
multitude  of  absolutely  simple  "  reals,"  devoid  of  "  faculties," 
etc.,  by  the  contradictions  which  experience  offers,  e.g.,  the 
contradiction  involved  in  the  view  that  a  single  thing  can 
possess  a  multiplicity  of  qualities. ^ 

From  the  interaction  of  these  hypothetical  "  reals  "  arise  (on 
Herbart's  view)  presentations  or  ideas.  Once  a  presentation 
has  arisen  it  persists  unchanged  until  disturbed  by  others. 
With  these  it  may  enter  into  various  relations. 

(1)  Two  similar  tones  {e.g.)  ma^y  fuse  to  a  stronger  tone. 

(2)  Two  disparate  sensations  (colour,  smell,  etc.,  of  an  orange) 
may  complicate  or  unite. 

(3)  Two  contrary  presentations  may  check  each  other  so  far 
as  they  are  opposed,  and  unite  so  far  as  they  are  not  checked. 

No  presentation  is  ever  destroyed,  though  it  may  be  driven 
below  the  threshold  and  then  merely  strive  to  be  presented. 
The  amount  of  checking  it  experiences  depends  on  (1)  its  own 
native  strength ;  (2)  the  degree  of  opposition  exerted  by  other 
presentations. 

Apperception  occurs  when  a  new  presentation  is  passive 
relatively  to  old  presentations.^  Attention  is  largely  dependent 
on  Apperception  ;  it  is  the  energetic  and  lasting  self-maintenance 
of  a  presentation  in  consciousness. 

Ostermann  offers  various  criticisms  of  the  above  doctrine. 
Even  supposing  that  the  "  simple  "  soul  is  able  to  generate  pre- 
sentations, how  can  these  latter  persist  after  the  ceasing  of  the 
conjunction  which  brought  them  forth  ?  Herbart  regarded  the 
presentations  as  immortal,  but  the  analogy  of  the  first  law  of 
motion  is  not  to   the   point   ("  A   body  persists    .    .    . "),   for 

1  Ostermann's  discussion  of  Herbart's  metaphysics  must  here  be  almost 
entirely  omitted. 

2  Don  Quixote's  fixed  ideas  seized  hold  of  a  new  experience  (windmills) 
«|.nd  interpreted  or  apperceived  it, 


Ostermann  119 

presentations  are  inner  states,  not,  like  motion,  external  quali- 
ties of  a  body.  Surely  a  presentation  generated  out  of  the 
interaction  of  "  reals  "  must  cease  when  the  interaction  is 
over. 

Herbart  was  wrong  when  he  regarded  all  presentations  as 
having  definite  intensities  and  definite  amounts  of  mutual 
opposition.  The  memory-image  of  a  thunderclap  is  of  very 
different  intensity  from  that  of  the  sound  itself.  Again,  Wundt 
has  shown  experimentally  that  two  contrasting  impressions 
(black  and  white)  do  not  only  not  check,  but  actually  aid  each 
other.  So  also  with  concepts ;  what  easier  than  to  think  of 
opposites  ?  Herbart,  in  fact,  forgets  that  though  the  presenta- 
tion-contents may  be  opposed,  the  mental  activities  they  call 
forth  may  not  be  opposite  at  all. 

What  is  the  nature  of  the  supposed  "  checking "  between 
two  presentations  ?  He  regards  it  as  a  kind  of  mutual  me- 
chanical pressure.  But  is  this  a  tenable  view  ?  True,  the 
soul,  in  experiencing  the  two  opposed  presentations,  a  and  b, 
may  strive  to  remove  this  opposition  by  getting  rid  of  one  of 
them.  But  can  a  and  b  resist  each  other?  Are  they  in- 
dependent existences?  Herbart's  view  destroys  the  unity  of 
the  soul} 

Again,  what  meaning  can  be  attached  to  the  statement  that 
the  checked  presentations  show  a  "  striving  to  be  presented"? 
We  can  understand  it  if  we  regard  it  as  a  material  tension.  But 
presentations  are  mental  states  ;  how,  then,  can  they  be  in 
unconsciousness  ?  Herbart  was  driven  to  this  view  by  the 
stringency  of  his  metaphysics  ;  being  forbidden  to  assume 
"  faculties  "  he  had  to  assume  that  presentations  always  exist, 
even  in  unconsciousness.  But  on  our  theory  they  need  no  more 
exist  than  the  note  of  a  musical  string  need  always  be  sound- 
ing ;  the  conditions  of  reproduction  exist,  but  not  the  note  itself. 
Even  the  physiological  view  would  be  better  than  Herbart's, 


1  This  conclusion  is  probably  a  true  one.  Still,  we  must  not  forget  that 
Herbart's  metaphysical  "  real "  or  "  soul  "  is  supposed  to  be  existent  all 
this  time. 


The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


for  it  provides  a  substratum  (nerves,  etc.)  for  presentations. 
But  Herbart  will  neither  allow  of  this  nor  of  any  activity  of  the 
soul  itself.  With  him,  each  presentation  is  virtually  a  little  soul, 
and  the  total  soul-activity  is  divided  up  into  presentation- 
activities  ;  thus  there  is  no  unity,  and  we  cannot  understand 
how  presentations  come  ever  to  be  united.  Eeally  this  union 
is  the  work  of  the  soul,  but  Herbart  has  to  assume  links  between 
the  presentations;  each  of  the  latter,  however,  is,  for  him,  an 
entity  in  itself. 

He  conveniently  allows  that  the  action  and  suffering  of  the 
presentation  are  also  the  action  and  suffering  of  the  soul.  Thus 
we  appear  to  have  a  double  series  of  events. 

The  doctrine  of  mutual  "  checking  "  involves  either  that  the 
presentations  are  separate  entities  or  that  one  part  of  the  soul 
checks  another  part.  Each  view  destroys  the  unity  of  the  soul. 
Or  can  it  be  that  the  whole  soul  checks  itself?  Again,  how 
can  the  soul  itself  be  "unalterable"  if  all  these  processes  take 
place  in  it?  Herbart  insists  that  the  metaphysical  soul  takes 
no  part  in  mental  events  ! 

There  is  no  possible  way  of  explaining  mental  life  if  we 
assume  that  each  presentation  has  a  content  and  activity  of  its 
own.  No  theory  of  "  fusion  "  will  stiffice.  In  aU  mental 
processes  there  must  be  present  a  unitary  principle  which 
compares,  relates,  etc.,  the  different  presentations.  We  cannot 
explain  Intelligence  and  the  forming  of  general  ideas  as  a  result 
of  the  reproduction,  fusion,  and  checking  of  a  multitude  of 
similar  presentations.  The  concept  itself  cannot  be  "pre- 
sented"; it  is  abstract,  and  stands  for  certain  relations  estab- 
lished by  thought.  Thus  the  concept  "animal"  grasps  in  itself 
all  different  animals. 

Herbart  has  a  theory  of  "  collective  presentations  "  ^  which 
he  regards  as  stepping-stones  to  concepts  proper.  But  if  such 
presentations  existed  we  should  be  unable  to  revive  the  older 


^Generally  called  "generic  images"  by  English  psychologists.  Such 
an  image  {e.g.,  of  "  man  ")  is  supposed  to  be  the  vague  residual  image  left 
after  a  number  of  individual  images  of  men  have  been  superimposed. 


Ostermann  121 

single  ones,  for  their  special  traits  would  have  been  suppressed. 
Throughout  the  whole  of  Herbart's  system  the  unifying  function 
of  the  soul  is  ignored. 

Equally  unsatisfactory  is  his  treatment  of  Feeling  and  Desire, 
which  are  supposed  to  arise  out  of  presentations  according  as 
the  movements  of  these  favour  or  hinder  each  other.  Herbart 
infers  that  pedagogically  the  presentations  are  the  most  im- 
portant mental  elements,  while  joys  and  sorrows  are  but 
transitory.  Even  sensible  feelings,  according  to  Herbart,  rest 
ultimately  on  minute  presentational  units.  There  is  no  "  Feel- 
ing" faculty,  or  "Desire"  faculty;  all  depends  on  the  inter- 
actions of  presentations.  Desire  is  an  advancing  movement, 
Feeling  a  resting  condition. 

But  surely  (says  Ostermann)  Feeling  belongs  to  the  soul,  not 
to  presentations.  The  Herbartians  transfer  the  effect  of  the 
"checkings  "  to  the  soul  itself.  But  in  reality  what  one 
presentation  loses  in  activity  another  must  gain.  There  is  no 
gain  or  loss  for  the  soul  taken  as  a  whole ;  why  then  should  it 
experience  pleasure  or  pain  ?  Or  is  there  a  constant  oscillation 
of  pleasure  and  pain  corresponding  to  the  checking,  etc.,  of 
presentations?  Surely  we  must  posit  a  faculty  of  Feeling, 
which  is  quite  as  original  a  function  as  Presentation.  Presen- 
tations may  stimulate  this  faculty  into  operation,  hut  there  must 
first  he  the  faculty  itself.  How  otherwise  would  such  an  idea 
as  that  of  danger  give  rise  to  any  feeling  at  all  ?  Of  course  the 
faculty  is  not  separate  from  the  soul  itself.  Herbart's  attack 
was  directed  against  a  false  faculty  doctrine  which  separated 
the  "  facilities "  from  the  soul. 

There  are. many  sensory  pains,  etc.,  which  come  into  con- 
sciousness without  any  presentational  content.  Can  Herbart 
deny  or  explain  this  ?  ^  Again,  feelings  differ  in  colouring  as 
well  as  in  intensity  ;  compare  avarice  with  aesthetic  feeling. 
Ballauf  and  other  Herbartians  admit  this,  but  it  is  not  recon- 
cilable with  Herbart's  own  doctrine. 

Again,  if  it  be  true  that  those  presentations  which  rise  to  the 

1  He  posits  minute  presentational  elements  as  the  basis  of  such  pains, 

etc. 


The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


highest  clearness  bear  the  most  lively  feelings,  we  should  expect 
the  study  of  mathematics  to  be  intensely  emotional.  Facts  tell 
a  different  story.  Again,  the  clear  image  of  a  distant  friend 
awakens  melancholy,  not  pleasure.  The  Herbartian  theory 
ignores  the  content,  or  significance,  or  worth  of  presentations, 
and  considers  their  quantitative  relations  only.  Later  Her- 
bartians,  like  Ballauf  and  Sfcrumpell,  have  tended  to  admit  a 
"  Feeling  "  faculty,  thus  being  really  faithless  to  Herbart. 

The  Herbartians  are  right  in  emphasising  the  close  con- 
nection between  Desire  and  Presentation  ;  we  cannot  desire 
what  we  cannot  think  of.  But  we  do  not  desire  what  is 
actually  present,  whereas,  according  to  Herbart,  each  desire  is 
bound  to  a  present  content. 

Certain  cases  of  mental  disturbance  mentioned  by  Nathan 
prove  that  the  Will  can  control  the  course  of  presentations,  and 
is  therefore  not  a  mere  product  of  them. 

Tlfie  Will  and  its  Freedom. — Will  (according  to  Herbart)  is 
Desire  plus  Certainty.  Desire  is  a  product  of  the  presentation- 
mechanism  ;  so  also  must  Will  be.  But  if  moral  action  is 
dependent  on  an  estimation  of  value  (as  Herbart  affirms),  how 
can  this  be  reconciled  with  the  mechanical  view?  He  holds 
that  the  moral  judgment  must,  in  order  to  prevail,  be  connected 
with  a  strong  unified  mass  of  thoughts,  whose  mechanical 
strength  will  overcome  all  opposing  ideas.  Good !  But  where 
is  the  role  of  the  moral  judgment  ? 

Even  his  notion  of  a  fusion  of  repeated  volitions  (after  the 
manner  of  the  formation  of  concepts)  does  not  lift  us  out  of  the 
realm  of  mechanism.  Freedom,  in  fact,  is  entirely  excluded 
from  the  system.  No  doubt  he  speaks  of  Inner  Freedom 
(  =  volition  according  to  the  moral  judgments)  but  even  this 
seems  to  depend  on  the  mechanical  strength  of  presentation- 
masses.  Where  is  responsibility  ?  He  dismisses  the  question 
with  a  few  words.  Practically,  he  says,  we  must  not  go  beyond 
the  Will  in  passing  judgment.  But  as  he  resolves  Will  into  a 
mechanical  process,  he  really  gets  rid  of  responsibility.  We 
may  admit  that  the  question  is  a  difficult  one,  but  somehow  we 
must  preserve  responsibility. 


Ostermann  123 

The  *' Faculty"  Doctrine. — Herbart  was  right  in  protesting 
against  the  vulgar  "  faculty  doctrine,"  which  destroys  the  unity 
of  the  soul,  brings  on  the  scene  empty  powers  apart  from 
concrete  mental  life,  and  substitutes  for  a  scientific  explanation 
of  mental  facts  a  mere  appeal  to  a  suppositious  "faculty".  But 
Herbart  has  not  succeeded  in  explaining  mental  life  in  terms 
of  presentations,  and  by  analogies  derived  from  mechanics. 
Moreover,  certain  phenomena  point  to  a  distinct  "  memory 
faculty  "  as  possessed  by  certain  prodigies.  Again  there  are 
specific  differences  of  memory.  We  must  assume  that  the  soul 
has  other  modes  of  expressing  itself  than  Presentation,  though 
we  must  not  assume  any  faculty  separate  from  the  soul  itself. 

Pedagogical  Results. — Because  of  his  presentationalism,  Her- 
bart lays  great  stress  on  Instruction  and  upon  the  forming  of 
"large  unbroken  masses  of  thought".  The  energy  of  the 
moral  judgments  depends  upon  their  being  connected  with 
strong  thought-masses. 

Is  this  view  tenable  ?  The  fact  is,  there  must  be  an  original 
unity  such  as  is  not  provided  by  Herbart's  system  of  separate 
presentations.  The  "  concentration  "  doctrine  does  not  bring 
about  a  unity,  for  we  are  never  told  how  the  presentations  can 
fuse.  Nor  are  we  given  any  explanation  of  the  moral  life  ;  for 
whence  comes  the  notion  of  worth  if  the  whole  mental  life 
consists  of  presentations  ?  Still,  the  "  concentration  "  plan  has 
much  intellectual  value  ;  it  impresses  facts  on  the  memory  and 
conduces  to  culture ;  it  may  even  indirectly  help  character. 
But  character  depends  mainly  on  disposition,  not  on  presenta- 
tions. 

The  peculiar  "  concentration  "  and  "  culture  stages  "  doctrines 
of  the  Zillerians  are  highly  artificial,  and  would  probably  have 
been  condemned  by  Herbart  himself,  for  he  cautions  us  against 
aiming  at  an  artificial  unity,  and  against  disrupting  what  ought 
to  be  connected. 

The  "  Interest  "  doctrine  is  said  to  be  the  most  important  one 
in  the  Herbartian  scheme,  and  to  have  great  moral  significance. 
But  on  examination  we  find  that  Interest  is  a  form  of  "  in- 
voluntary attention,"  and  depends  upon  the  strength  of  pre- 


124  ^^"^  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

sentations.  Thus  we  are  brought  back  to  a  mechanical  view. 
At  times  we  are  told  that  Interest  finds  complete  satisfaction 
in  the  'present ;  at  other  times  that  it  compels  to  continuous 
self-activity  and  advance.  In  fact  the  Interest  doctrine  cannot 
be  reconciled  with  Herbart's  mechanical  scheme.  It  is  impos- 
sible to  regard  Feeling  as  a  transitory  modification  of  presenta- 
tions. 

The  Herbartians  lay  stress  on  the  need  of  Imagination. 
Actions  must  be  thought  about,  pictured ;  model  images  of 
actions  must  be  formed.  In  this  way  (we  are  told)  practical 
hindrances  will  be  conquered  when  they  arise.  There  is  truth 
in  this,  but,  after  all,  reflection  will  not  ensure  vigorous  action. 
Strong  Will  depends  mainly  on  natural  endowment  and  on 
practice  in  overcoming  difficulties. 

Even  the  Herbartians  feel  at  times  the  need  of  calling  forth 
energy,  as  when  they  recommend  that  at  the  beginning  of  each 
lesson  its  goal  should  be  stated,  so  that,  in  this  way,  the  pupil 
may  exert  all  his  powers.  But  where  are  these  powers  ?  How 
can  we  explain  them  if  each  presentation  has  a  definite  maximum 
of  energy,  and  there  is  no  real  energy  of  the  soul  itself  ?  The 
only  hope  of  the  Herbartians  is  in  "  concentrating  "  many  pre- 
sentations. But  in  reality  Will  power  arises  through  conflict, 
habit,  natural  endowment,  etc.  ;  moreover,  physical  exercises 
contribute  to  it,  as  the  English  have  recognised. 

But  a  Will  must  not  only  be  strong,  but  directed  to  the 
Good.  Here  again  Habit  is  important,  but  there  must  also  be 
Education,  and  a  rousing  of  Interest  in  what  is  good.  But 
Interest  is  rooted  in  Feeling,  hence  Education  must  confer  more 
than  mere  enlightenment.  How  are  we  to  touch  the  heart  ? 
Through  actual  occurrences,  human  life,  example.  The  main 
thing  is  not  Instruction,  hut  Inspiration.  Stories  from  history, 
songs,  poetry,  etc.,  are  useful ;  Instruction,  when  given,  must 
attach  itself  to  concrete  foundations,  to  definite  situations, 
events,  etc.^ 


^  Needless  to  say,  all  Herbartians  would  agree  with  this ;  they  lay  im- 
mense stress  on  history,  poetry,  etc, 


Richter  125 

The  Herbartians  reply  that  mere  appeals  to  Feeling  have  no 
permanent  effect,  for  feelings  are  but  transitory  modifications  of 
presentations.  But  their  psychology  is  wrong.  Feeling  is  as 
original  as  presentations,  and  leaves  behind  a  permanent  after- 
effect— Interest.  Still,  there  may  be  excess  even  here  ;  and  the 
Herbartians  are  right  in  emphasising  the  close  connection  of 
feelings  and  presentations. 

Herbartianism  has  furthered  educational  science  ;  it  has  pro- 
tested against  catechetical  methods;  it  has  urged  the  import- 
ance of  rousing  independent  and  connected  thought.  But  its 
goal  is  one-sided  ;  it  neglects  physical  education  ;  its  terminology 
is  artificial ;  its  selection  of  fairy-tales  for  moral  purposes  is  a 
mistake,  for  these  tales  are  not  moral ;  its  emphasis  on  "  con- 
centration "  is  overdone  ;  and  its  followers  tend  to  become  blind 
followers  of  their  master's  prescriptions. 


SECTION  V. 

RICHTER. 

(1887.) 

Reference, 

Richter.  Die  Herbart-Zillerschen  formalen  Stufen  des  Unterrichts,  nach 
ihrem  Wesen,  ihrer  geschichtlichen  Grundlage,  und  ihrer  Anwendung  im, 
Volksschulunterrichte.     Hesse,  Leipzig,  1887.     Second  edition,  1898. 

This  work  is  a  "  gekronte  Preisschrift,"  an  essay  which  won 
the  prize  offered  in  1886  by  an  educational  institute  in  Dresden 
for  the  best  work  on  the  subject,  "The  appHcability  of  the 
Herbart  -  Ziller  formal  steps  to  instruction  in  elementary 
schools  ". 

The  author  goes  into  the  whole  question  with  German 
thoroughness ;  shows  who  were  Herbart's  predecessors  (Com- 
enius,  etc.)  in  the  task  of  working  out  the  "  formal  steps  " ; 
compares  Herbart's  treatment  with  Ziller's  ;  and  finally  arrives 
at  the  result  that  they  are,  on  the  whole,  a  sound  contribution 


126  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

to  pedagogical  practice  inasmuch  as  they  rest  on  the  laws  of 
learning,  and  lighten  the  task  of  teaching  and  acquisition. 

More  valuable,  however,  than  these  portions  of  the  work  are 
the  author's  remarks  on  the  limitations  and  dangers  of  the 
"  formal  steps ".  But  the  reader  must  remember  that  the 
general  verdict  of  Eichter — into  the  exact  grounds  of  which  we 
cannot  here  go — is  favourable. 

The  chief  danger  which  the  author  urges  is  a  famiUar  one 
— that  mechanical  teachers  will  apply  the  "  steps  "  without 
judgment  and  discretion,  and  make  them  into  a  rigid  scheme 
which  will  check  rather  than  encourage  thought. 

Ziller  himself  has  aheady  pointed  out  certain  hmitations  of 
his  scheme.  It  is  inapplicable  to  such  material  as  is  already 
abstract  in  form,  e.g.,  a  scientific  reading  book,  a  grammar,  a 
catechism,^  an  historical  table,  a  portion  of  the  Bible  with 
direct  didactic  tendency  (Sermon  on  the  Mount,  etc.).  Such 
materials  already  represent  worked-up  results,  hence  they 
afford  no  opportunity  of  a  movement  from  Anschauung  to 
Denken  (thinking),  and  so  on.  Similarly,  the  correcting  or  the 
repetition  of  exercises,  and  various  accidental  occurrences  such 
as  may  happen  on  a  school  excursion,  cannot,  as  a  rule,  be 
treated  in  accordance  with  the  formal  steps.  So  also  with  the 
acquisition  of  skill  in  writing,  etc. 

In  point  of  fact,  Ziller's  excepting  of  catechetical  instruction 
from  the  scope  of  the  formal  steps  is  not  altogether  valid. 
Even  religious  instruction  should  start  from  the  concrete  and 
work  forward  towards  the  maxims  of  the  catechism,  in  full  accord- 
ance with  Herbart's  procedure,  which  starts  with  Anschauung, 
goes  on  to  Thinking,  and  finally  arrives  at  Application. 

The  Zillerians  attack  the  catechism  violently,  on  the  grounds 
that  it  omits  any  initial  statement  of  the  goal  of  the  lesson, 
checks  free  activity  by  the  way  it  throws  out  its  questions, 
makes  children  use  words  they  do  not  fully  understand  and 


1  The  common  teaching  of  the  catechism  proceeds  on  precisely  opposite 
principles  to  the  formal  steps.  The  child  learns  the  abstract  statement, 
and  then  this  is  illustrated  by  concrete  examples  when  possible. 


Richter  127 

judgments  not  arising  from  insight,  and  breaks  up  what  should 
be  in  connection.  This  assault  of  the  Zillerians  is  in  part 
justified,  but  they  ignore  the  fact  that  there  may  be  a  real  use 
for  the  catechism. 

They  also  undervalue  questioning  in  general,  and  prefer  to 
draw  out  children's  speech  by  such  words  as  "and,"  "but," 
etc.  Here,  again,  this  proposal  may  be  useful  in  certain  cir- 
cumstances, e.g.,  when  a  child  is  reproducing  something  already 
learnt ;  but  again  we  must  not  lay  down  any  rule. 

Children  have  small  powers  of  speech  and  of  mental  grasp ; 
we  tnust  use  questions ;  they  help  to  impress  facts.  At  higher 
stages  questions  involving  long  answers  are  good. 

Some  extreme  Zillerians  have  even  recommended  that  in 
teaching  writing  an  attempt  should  be  made  to  carry  out  the 
formal  steps ;  letters  have  to  be  analysed  into  their  elements, 
compared,  and  so  forth.  This  is  absurd.  Writing,  reading, 
drawing,  singing  are  matters  of  -practice,  and  must  be  treated 
as  such.^ 

Ziller  it  was,  not  Herbart,  who  used  the  expression  "  formal " 
in  connection  with  the  steps.  The  expression  implies  that  the 
material  is  neghgible.  This  is  not  so.  The  material  of  in- 
struction must  dictate  its  own  methods  of  treatment. 

The  Herbartians  underestimate  the  value  of  silent,  spon- 
taneous development.  The  object  itself  exerts  power  upon  the 
pupil. 

Ziller  recommends  the  division  of  a  lesson  into  method  units, 
each  of  which  is  to  be  worked  through  in  accordance  with  the 
formal  steps.  But  if  the  units  are  very  small,  great  artificiality 
and  weariness  result  from  such  a  treatment.  Ziller  tries  to 
avoid  this  by  recommending  movements  from  one  "  method 
unit "  to  another  and  back  again. 

Let  us  rather  consider  the  children's  capacities  in  dividing 


^  Dr.  Findlay  has  done  splendid  service  by  drawing  a  clear  line  of  de- 
marcation between  "  the  acquirement  of  knowledge  "  and  "  the  acquirement 
of  skill ".  It  is  to  the  former  process  that  the  "  formal  steps  "  are  applicable. 
Principles  of  Class  Teaching. 


128  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

up  our  material.  One  lesson  may  prepare  the  way  for  another; 
thus  the  latter  may  not  require  the  "first  step"  (preparation) 
at  all.  Now  one  step,  now  another,  may  be  omitted,  and 
various  other  modifications  of  the  scheme  be  made  according 
to  circumstances.  Sometimes  a  lesson  must  be  mainly  syn- 
thesis (step  two) ;  sometimes  "  application  "  may  be  impossible 
without  great  artificiality  (as  when  the  Herbartians  bring  moral 
considerations  on  the  scene  which  are  only  remotely  connected 
with  the  rest  of  the  lesson).  We  see  clear  signs  of  artificiality 
in  the  lessons  drawn  up  by  Eein,  Staude,  and  other  Her- 
bartians, especially  in  dealing  with  the  fifth  step,  which,  with 
them,  becomes  either  mere  repetition  or  goes  quite  beyond  the 
child. 

The  Herbartians  are  right  in  urging  that  abstraction  must  be 
preceded  by  apperception,  but  it  is  not  true  that  abstraction 
must  always  follow  apperception.  The  child  may  be  too  young 
to  go  beyond  the  stage  of  apperception.  But  the  Zillerians 
seem  to  think  that  all  the  five  stages  must  be  run  through  on 
every  occasion. 

They  also  urge  that  the  goal  of  the  lesson  should  be  held 
clearly  in  view  from  the  first,  and  that  it  must  be  given  by  the 
children — a  process  which  involves  (says  Eichter)  much  guess- 
work and  waste  of  time. 

The  Zillerians  say  that  the  goal  must  be  actual,  not  a  mere 
"  next  chapter,"  etc.  But  often  we  cannot  follow  out  this 
prescription,  for  to  do  so  would  be  actually  to  introduce  the 
new  matter,  which  is  forbidden.  The  Zillerian  rule  has  its 
utility,  but  often  cannot  be  carried  out. 

Ziller  also  recommends  that  at  the  first  stage  many  side- 
issues  may  be  permitted  to  be  suggested  by  the  pupils ;  this 
is  supposed  to  prepare  the  way  for  the  new  matter.  But  in 
point  of  fact  the  plan  merely  leads  to  useless  discursiveness. 
Herbart  has  actually  warned  us  against  such  a  danger. 

For  the  stage  of  synthesis  Ziller  makes  the  unexpected  pro- 
posal that  instead  of  the  teacher  presenting  the  new  matter 
to  the  pupils  it  may  be  read  by  the  pupils  out  of  a  book.  Here 
he  departs  from  Herbart,  and  men  like  Dorpfeld  have  rightly 


Richter  129 

protested  against  so  reactionary  a  proposal.  To  think  that  a 
child,  halting  and  stumbling  as  he  reads,  can  properly  assimilate 
the  new  matter  is  absurd. 

Again  Ziller  recommends  that  exercises  on  the  new  material 
be  imposed  on  individual  scholars — not  on  the  class  collectively. 
But  this  means  that  most  of  the  pupils  will  be  doing  nothing 
but  listening.  Surely,  questions — on  which  Ziller  does  not  look 
with  favour — 'will  engage  the  attention  of  the  whole  class. 

As  a  substitute,  Ziller  proposes  a  kind  of  discussion  or  dis- 
putation ;  without  this,  he  says,  the  pupils  do  not  become  fully 
conscious  of  what  they  know  and  can  do.  Strange  proposal ! 
This  mediaeval  disputation  method  has  long  been  banished  from 
the  Latin  school ;  here  is  Ziller  trying  to  introduce  it  into  the 
elementary  school !  But  how  is  the  method  possible  with  large 
classes?  Where  will  discipline  be?  How  are  we  to  prevent 
chattering,  or  to  draw  forth  the  silent  members  of  the  class  ? 

Ziller,  like  many  educationists,  objects  to  children  learning 
ready-made  scientific  results  from  text-books,  and  recommends 
that  they  start  from  the  concrete  and  work  towards  the  abstract 
results.  But  he  is  inconsistent  in  permitting  (at  the  stage  of 
"  system  ")  the  attained  results  to  be  compared  with  the  results 
in  a  book.  If  pupils  are  once  allowed  to  use  a  book  at  all  they 
will  have  curiosity  enough  to  use  it  for  other  purposes. 

At  the  last  stage  ("application")  Ziller  recommends  (in  con- 
nection with  the  treatment  of  "  Gesinnungsstoff ")  that  children's 
imagination  should  be  exercised  on  action ;  for  thinking  about 
action  aids  real  subsequent  action  by  helping  to  conquer  possible 
hindrances.  "What  would  you  have  done  in  Adam's  place? 
What  would  you  have  done  in  such  and  such  dangerous  circum- 
stances ?  " 

But  is  there  much  value  in  this?  Moralisings  are  of  little 
use.  Unless  children  have  had  considerable  life  experiences 
they  cannot  profit  by  such  discussions ;  or  they  may  even  be 
led  to  think  of  actions  of  dubious  value.  It  is  easy  to  imagine 
action  ;  but  though  spirit  may  be  willing,  flesh  is  weak. 

Many  of  the  "  applications  "  recommended  by  Zillerians  like 
Staude  are  quite  beyond  the  mental  capacity  of  children.     What 

9 


130  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

is  the  use  of  discussing  with  them  the  social  origin  of  revolu- 
tions or  the  rights  and  wrongs  of  polygamy  ? 

It  is  important  that  the  formal  steps,  when  used,  shall  be 
used  with  due  regard  to  the  nature  of  the  object  taught,  and 
of  the  pupil.  Some  children  are  more  capable  of  abstract 
thought  than  others  whose  minds  are  of  the  Anschauung  type. 
Some  heads  are  "  practical,"  others  "  theoretical  ".  Then, 
again,  differences  of  age  are  important.  We  must  not  with 
young  children  always  insist  on  the  third  and  fourth  stages, 
for  these  children  may  be  too  young  to  "  abstract "  correctly. 
Conversely,  older  pupils  we  must  not  always  force  into  infantile 
grooves  by  insisting  on  the  first  two  stages. 

After  school  days  are  over,  new  matter  is  not  acquired  in 
exact  accordance  with  the  "formal  steps".  The  new  often 
comes  as  already  abstract.  Schools  must  remember  that  they 
have  to  consider  the  future  of  their  pupils,  and  must  not  over- 
estimate the  value  of  any  scheme. 

Then  there  is  the  teacher.  The  formal  steps  afford  him 
useful  guidance,  and  he  ought  not  to  give  himself  over  to 
mere  lawlessness.  Still,  the  Herbartian  rules  are  only  general, 
and  cannot  give  precise  directions.  In  the  same  way  a  judge 
has  to  apply  general  laws  to  special  cases.  The  best  advice 
to  teachers  is — learn  the  rules  first,  and  afterwards  acquire  the 
necessary  freedom,     "  The  letter  killeth,  the  spirit  giveth  Hfe." 

SECTION  VI. 
VOGEL. 
(1887.) 

Reference. 
Vogel.    Herhart  oder  Pestalozzi.     Eine  kritische  Darstellung  und  Ver- 
gleichung    ihrer    Systeme    als    Beitrag    zur    richtigen    Wilrdigung    ihres 
gegenseitigen  Verhdltnisses.    Dr.  August  Vogel,  1887. 

"  HuBKAH  for  Herbart !  "  "  Hurrah  for  Pestalozzi !  "  are  cries 
we  hear  on  every  side.  It  is  important  that  we  should  decide 
as  to  the  respective  claims  of  these  leaders. 


Vogel  131 

Pestalozzi  was  a  genial  reformer  whose  life,  except  for  one 
brief  period  at  Burgdorf,  seemed  a  failure.  But  he  was  a  true 
pioneer.  Though  despised  by  many  of  his  contemporaries,  he 
is  now  regarded  by  mankind  as  one  from  whom  progress 
received  a  new  impulse.  But  a  second  impulse  was  required 
for  the  establishment  and  development  of  his  principles. 

Herbart  was  another  educational  philosopher  whose  views, 
like  those  of  Pestalozzi,  received  but  scant  recognition  in  his 
hfetime,  but  who,  nevertheless,  founded  a  school  of  thinkers. 
Its  earliest  adherents  misunderstood  his  system  and  engaged 
in  conflict  with  Pestalozzi's  followers ;  the  former  maintaining 
that  Herbart  was  the  first  to  employ  psychology  for  educational 
purposes,  the  latter  claiming  that  Pestalozzi  had  already  done 
this. 

Herbart' s  Starting  Point  in  Psychology. — Herbart  makes  the 
"  ego  "  the  starting  point  in  psychology  and  discovers  a  con- 
tradiction in  it,  a  contradiction  which  rests  entirely  upon 
his  assumption  that  Knowing  and  Being  are  irreconcilable  ; 
throughout  his  system,  as  the  bitter  opponent  of  Idealism,  he 
seeks  to  establish  this.  We  feel,  however,  Vogel  maintains, 
that  Being  in  its  highest  sense  is  known,  and  that  the  anti- 
thesis between  Being  and  Knowing  cannot  be  maintained; 
even  Herbart  is  not  prepared  to  uphold  it  logically ;  he  states 
that  the  beginning  of  knowledge  consists  in  ideas  and  that 
these  rest  on  experience  which  teaches  what  things  are.  Man 
lives  among  ceaseless  confusion  of  the  different  departments  of 
Being  and  Happening,  of  appearances  which  are  involved  in 
change,  and  feelings  consequent  on  these  changes  bring  ideas 
home  to  him.  The  foundation  doctrine  of  Herbart 's  Psychology 
is  that  feelings  or  perceptions  are  self-preservations  of  the  soul, 
and  this  means  that  the  soul  is  not  originally  a  power  for 
reflexion,  it  is  not  composed  of  real  and  ideal  activity ;  but 
rather  there  must  be  postulated  for  its  whole  spiritual  mani- 
foldness,  a  sufficient  number  of  presentations,  and  self-con- 
sciousness arises  only  from  these  and  exists  entirely  in  the 
relations  among  these ;  it  is  only  a  changed  relation  of  the  soul, 
yet  inner  experience   sufficiently  proves  that   the  I  and  self- 


132  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

consciousness  do  not  remain,  as  it  were,  on  the  periphery  of 
the  soul  as  on  accidental  relation.  They  are  rather  that  which 
constitutes  the  inmost  germ  of  it,  that  which  gives  it  its  worth 
and  supreme  importance.  If  we  take  self-consciousness  as  the 
essential  element  from  the  idea  of  the  soul,  it  fades  away  to  an 
uncertain  something  which  cannot  form  the  centre  of  the  whole 
inner  life  of  a  man  in  all  its  height  and  breadth.  The  necessary 
hypothesis  for  all  spiritual  and  moral  life  and  action  is  lacking 
in  a  soul  without  self-consciousness,  and  if  the  latter  is  a  matter 
of  accident  entirely,  every  scientific  explanation  of  the  spiritual 
life  is  thereby  rendered  impossible. 

The  Soul,  according  to  Herbart,  is  a  Real  Thing,  and  as 
such,  a  simple  essence,  subject  to  neither  time  nor  space ;  it 
has  talents  and  faculties  neither  to  receive  nor  to  produce 
anything,  and  its  Simple  Quale  is  and  remains  unknown. 

That  Time  and  Place  must  be  excluded  from  a  soul,  as  a 
simple  essence  existing  for  itself,  rests  on  easily  understood 
general  metaphysical  principles.  But  of  greater  importance  is 
Herbart's  assertion  that  the  Soul  in  its  absolute  being  can 
receive  nothing  from  without,  nor  produce  anything  of  itself, 
but  that  all  mental  life  arises  from  the  relations  between  several 
simple  essences  and  the  accidental  union  of  these. 

Now  Herbart's  real  soul  has  originally  neither  presentations 
nor  feelings,  nor  desires  ;  it  knows  nothing  of  itself  and  nothing 
of  other  things.  In  it  there  are  no  forms  of  thought,  no  laws 
of  wUling  and  acting,  and  no  sort  of  preparation,  however 
distant,  for  these.  Yet  in  spite  of  this  impressive  assurance, 
every  Real  essence  of  Herbart's,  and  therefore  also  the  real 
soul,  has  a  distinct  peculiar  quality  through  which  the  effects 
proceeding  from  the  union  of  several  essences  are  determined. 
Does  Herbart  then  mean  that  while  every  effect  can  only 
spring  from  the  union  of  several  essences,  one  by  itself  exer- 
cises no  effect  ?  If  he  does  not  mean  this,  he  must  maintain 
that  the  Quahty  peculiar  to  a  Real  essence  is  present  in  the 
union,  but  vanishes  in  the  non-union.  But  a  quality  which  is 
neither  a  power,  nor  a  faculty,  nor  anything  else  of  this  sort, 
must  be  nothing,  and  such  a  quahty  cannot  possibly  exercise 


Vogel  133 

any  influence  in  the  union  of  several  real  essences — not  even 
the  apparent  effect  of  Her  barf  s  ideas — nor  can  the  world  of 
Being  and  Happening  be  explained  by  means  of  such  essences. 
The  union  of  essences  which  presupposes  pressures  and  re- 
sistances, postulates  some  power  of  receiving  and  producing 
in  the  essences,  which  must  be  present  not  only  in  their  union, 
but  when  they  are  isolated  also. 

Psychology  and  Physiology. — Further,  it  seems  to  us  a  doubtful 
proceeding  to  try  and  explain  purely  psychical  events  by  such 
expressions  as  belong  to  mechanics  and  hydrostatics.  May 
they  always  remain  as  pictures  and  analogies,  not  as  true 
explanations !  And  when  Herbart  traces  analogy  between 
psychology  and  physiology,  and  asserts  that  as  the  latter 
constructs  the  body  from  fibres,  so  the  former  constructs  the 
soul  out  of  sets  of  presentations,  and  as  in  the  one  case  the 
excitability  of  the  fibres  is  a  much  disputed  point,  so  in  the 
other  case  is  the  excitability  of  the  sets  of  presentations ;  this 
is  again  an  indication  of  Herbart's  mechanical  comprehension 
of  the  soul's  functions. 

The  now  generally  received  hypothesis  of  the  indivisible  and 
therefore  simple  atoms  unchangeable  in  spite  of  all  apparent 
change,  certainly  explains  many  natural  appearances  more 
naturally  than  the  older  scientific  propositions;  yet  directly  it 
is  taken  over  into  the  territory  of  the  Soul,  it  sets  itself  in 
direct  opposition  to  scientific  axioms  as  well  as  to  Experience. 

Soul  Evolution. — The  soul  is  ever  forming  for  itself  higher 
and  broader  ideas,  which  furnish  the  undeniable  essentials  for 
the  perfecting  of  the  moral  life.  Least  of  all  then  should 
Herbart  call  the  soul  unchangeable  unless  he  mean  that  all 
progress  in  soul-life  is  but  appearance  and  deception,  and  this 
he  seems  to  argue. 

Herbart's  Theories  Preclude  Possibility  of  Progress. — That 
the  soul  steps  out  of  life  exactly  as  it  entered  it,  precludes  all 
possibility  of  evolution,  and  makes  the  perfecting  of  the  man, 
and,  therefore,  of  the  human  race,  an  illusion  and  deceptive 
appearance  only.  Ethics  and  psychology  are  then  unnecessary 
and  impossible.     A  psychology  which  denies  every  power,  every 


134  ^he  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

faculty,  and,  especially,  every  kind  of  evolution  of  the  Soul, 
cannot  include  in  its  survey  the  infinite  rich  life  of  the  latter, 
and  can  never  suffice  for  scientific  investigation,  or  guide  the 
teacher  and  moral  educator. 

With  Herbart,  the  real  Soul  is  at  the  basis  of  all  psycho- 
logical events,  and  in  its  accidental  union  with  other  reals,  it 
suffers  through  the  feelings  some  sort  of  disturbance,  then 
Presentation  results.  We  note  throughout  the  term  disturb- 
ance, not  exciting  or  inciting.  Herbart  makes  the  Soul  in- 
violable and  incapable  of  change,  but  the  man  who  sees  in 
these  outer  causes  the  first  beginnings  of  more  and  more  perfect 
development  of  the  human  soul,  the  proper  reason  of  which  lies 
in  itself,  will  not  only  not  regard  them  as  disturbances,  but  as 
necessary  and  blessed  incitement  to  the  further  evolution  of  a 
soul  that  is  capable  of  development,  and  only  from  this  stand- 
point can  the  perfecting  of  the  individual,  as  well  as  of  the 
whole  race,  be  logically  accepted  as  possible.  If  Herbart 
wishes,  as  he  does,  not  only  to  grant  the  possibility  of  this, 
but  to  declare  and  explain  it,  he  must  first  of  all  renounce  the 
rigid  unchangeableness  of  the  soul;  unchangeableness  and 
evolution  form  an  irreconcilable  antithesis,  although  this  very 
unchangeableness  and  self-preservation  premises  a  latent  power 
of  resistance,  but  we  do  not  agree  with  Herbart  when  he  says 
that  this  power  disappears  when  opposing  force  is  withdrawn. 
It  rather  is  real  and  active,  and  is  first  perceived  by  us  upon 
a  given  incitement.  Otherwise,  all  independence  and  freedom 
is  denied  to  man,  that  spark  of  the  Divine  Being  which  Nature 
called  into  existence  according  to  her  own  laws,  and  without 
which  all  presentations  due  to  other  reals  would  be  valueless 
to  its  own  life  and  development.  If  it  cannot  be  denied  that 
the  psychological  course  of  soul-hfe,  as  far  as  it  appears,  is 
subject  to  laws,  yet  it  must  also  be  granted  that  it  withdraws 
itself  from  these  natural  laws,  just  in  proportion  as  it  retires 
into  the  depths  of  its  proper  self. 

As  far  as  the  spirit  makes  use  of  the  wonderfully  constituted 
organism  of  the  body  for  its  activity,  so  far,  but  only  so  far,  is  it 
lawful  to  apply  the  laws  of  statics  and  mechanics,  as  well  as 


Vogel  135 

mathematical  calculation,  to  psychology.  No  laws  of  natvire 
apply  to  the  transcendental  Being  of  the  Soul.  The  man  who 
thinks  he  can  sound  the  depths  of  the  power  of  the  inner  soul- 
Hfe  by  an  example  in  arithmetic  is  a  materiahst,  and,  therefore, 
an  atheist. 

Innate  Special  Faculty. — Herbart  violently  contests  the  exist- 
ence of  innate  special  faculty.  We,  however,  contend  that  the 
faculties  themselves  are  different  modifications  of  the  one  soul, 
which  is  the  same  in  aU  of  them.  Just  as  many  coexist  in  the 
absolute,  as  the  members  in  an  organism,  as  ideas  in  criticism, 
so  are  the  faculties  related  to  the  soul. 

Even  Herbart,  in  spite  of  his  violent  polemic  against  soul 
powers,  cannot  do  away  with  the  necessity  of  vindicating  at 
least  three  powers  for  his  real  soul :  Perception,  Presentation, 
Eeproduction  or  Memory. 

With  Herbart  the  only  happening  that  takes  place  in  the 
soul  is  self-preservation  against  disturbance,  but  Desu-e  and  Will 
are  something  quite  different  from  self-preservation,  since  the 
soul  in  these  conditions  places  itself  in  connection  with  the  outer 
world.  With  Herbart  the  true  hfe  of  the  soul,  if  such  it  can  be 
called,  like  the  Buddhist-Nirvana,  continues,  in  spite  of  all  dis- 
turbance from  without,  to  all  eternity.  That  which  otherwise 
would  gladden  the  human  soul  or  sadden  it  to  death,  leaves  no 
trace  according  to  Herbart's  doctrine. 

The  Will. — In  considering  the  Will  we  enter  the  domain  of 
ethics,  and  if  Herbart  had  extended  his  metaphysical  and  psy- 
chological hypothesis  in  this  direction  it  would  have  been 
impossible  for  him  to  arrive  at  any  fundamental  ethical  ideas. 
How  could  an  essence  without  any  powers  or  activities  be 
made  responsible  for  any  thought  or  wish  or  deed  ?  Yet 
responsibihty  is  the  base  idea  of  all  ethical  considerations. 
Without  spontaneous  power,  the  soul  is  simply  a  sport  for 
that  chance  which,  according  to  Herbart,  is  supreme  throughout 
the  universe.  He  would  have  the  soul  in  its  inner  being  as 
little  moved  by  the  wildest  combat  of  conflicting  presentations 
as  the  centre  of  the  earth  by  the  thunder  of  cannon  or  the 
march  of  war-steeds.     It  is  not  the  Intellect  which  thinks  and 


136  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

observes,  not  the  Eeason  which  weighs  according  to  its  own 
principles,  not  the  Will  which  resolves,  but  presentations  in 
their  union  become  powers  independent  of  the  actionless,  and, 
therefore,  irresponsible  soul. 

Herbart's  Idea  of  God. — If  Herbart,  in  spite  of  all  this,  at- 
tributes five  moral  ideas — Freedom,  Perfection,  Benevolence, 
Right,  and  Equity — to  the  Soul,  according  to  which  it  judges 
an  expression  of  Will  as  being  pleasing  or  hateful,  moral  or  im- 
moral, good  or  bad,  this  is  indeed  opposed  to  his  whole  system, 
though  by  it  he  obtains  a  bridge  by  which  to  pass  over  into  the 
territory  of  ethics  and  aesthetics,  which  would  be  otherwise 
impossible — and  here  he  is  surely  guilty  of  inconsistency,  and 
according  to  his  metaphysics  God  is  also  a  simple  real  essence 
with  simple  quality,  who  like  every  other  real  soul  can  only 
arrive  at  thinking  through  union  with  other  souls,  and  therefore 
cannot  be  the  commanding  intelligence  or  the  Creator  of  Souls. 
Thus,  in  criticising  Herbart's  metaphysics,  Vogel  attacks  first 
his  premise  that  contradictions  form  the  beginning  and  the  end 
of  all  speculation,  and  that  these  contradictions  lie  in  the  forms 
of  the  data,  as  they  are  at  first  thought  of  by  means  of  ideas. 

His  Elaboration  of  Ideas. — He  contends  that  although  the 
notional  elaboration  of  the  data  or  of  experience,  especially  in 
the  case  of  the  beginner,  becomes  entangled  in  all  sorts  of  con- 
tradictions, these  do  not  arise  from  the  data.  Incorrect  results 
in  Science,  as  in  life,  rest  for  the  most  part  on  incorrect 
premises  which  have  been  obtained  by  a  superficial  or  hastily 
concluded  observation  of  the  data,  and  only  a  small  proportion 
are  due  to  insufficient  comparison  of  correctly  obtained  facts 
of  experience  or  to  purely  logical  mishaps.  Motive  for  thought 
cannot  be  sought  in  the  contradiction,  but  rather  in  the  strong 
impulse  which  is  woven  into  the  very  heart  of  man,  to  discover 
the  law,  which  lies  at  the  root  of  given  appearances,  i.e.,  the  truth, 
towards  which  insufficient  experience  can  be  no  starting  point 
at  all. 

"The  Method  of  Relations." — Herbart's  "Method  of  Rela- 
tions "  by  which  he  seeks  to  expand  ideas,  leads  too  soon  into 
the  airy  regions  of  purely  metaphysical  ideas,  and  away  from 


Vogel  137 

the  necessary  practical  experience,  and  though  professedly- 
starting  from  the  latter  he  soon  rejects  its  authority  as  being 
burdened  with  contradictions  which  only  thinking  is  able  to 
solve,  whereas  these  pretended  contradictions  should  be  elimin- 
ated at  once  by  means  of  closer  observation.  With  regard  to 
Herbart's  ideas  of  Things  themselves  and  to  the  idea  of  Being, 
as  a  kind  of  fixing,  it  is  easier  to  agree  with  him,  and  Kant  had 
already  established  the  same,  but  when  he  argues  that  the 
Real  does  not  lie  in  the  thing  thought  of,  but  in  the  thinking, 
he  places  Thinking  and  Being  in  irreconcilable  hostility. 

"Accidental  Helps  to  Vision." — He  sets  in  motion  with  his 
"accidental  helps  to  Vision"  and  his  construction  of  Ideas  an 
artificial  apparatus,  and  does  not  lead  up  to  real  explanations. 
He  leaves  us  to  put  "  accident "  in  the  place  of  real  cause,  but 
where  chance  reigns  laws  have  no  power,  and  where  no  law 
operates  there  is  an  end  of  science,  the  object  of  which  is  the 
discovery  of  laws  in  the  apparent  chaos  of  appearances. 

Herbart's  System  in  Opposition  to  Idealism. — Vogel  feels  that 
Herbart's  whole  system  is  the  exact  opposite  of  the  idealistic  in 
which  the  Ego  is  itself  the  only  true  Real  and  the  principle  of 
all  things,  therefore  of  the  so-called  objective  world.  Herbart 
does  not  recognise  a  Real  in  the  Ego,  but  only  a  relation  arising 
out  of  the  objective  presentations,  whereas  the  Ego,  as  well  as 
self-consciousness,  can  surely  neither  proceed  from  mere  pre- 
sentations of  the  Objective  world,  nor  can  these  presentations 
exist  without  a  presupposed  self-consciousness.  The  Ego  must 
be  a  thinking  subject,  and  thinking  without  self-consciousness  is  a 
contradiction.  Herbart  seems  to  limit  knowledge  to  accidental 
and  soulless  appearance,  not  to  agreement  of  Thinking  with 
Being,  and  instead  of  leading  up  to  truth,  seems  to  go  down  into 
the  darkness  of  doubt,  though  it  is  only  fair  to  say  that  Herbart 
at  times  commits  himself  to  a  contradiction  and  gives  glimmers 
of  the  Actual. 

Vogel's  Summing  Up. — In  summarising  his  criticism,  Vogel 
says,  "  We  cannot  recognise  either  Herbart's  principles  or  the 
deductions  therefrom  as  correct,  and  the  wearisome  tediousness 
of  his  expositions  and  terminology  militates  strongly  against 


t^S  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

their  acceptance  ".  The  latter  objection,  however,  Vogel  brings 
also  against  Kant  and  Fichte.  "  On  the  other  hand,  the  bold- 
ness of  Herbart's  thought  in  referring  the  whole  psychic  life  to 
the  presentation  as  the  final  cause,  must  exercise  effect  on 
every  thinker  who  is  seeking  for  final  causes,  and  all  hypotheses 
which  throw  light  on  the  way  to  these,  deserve  our  thanks  and 
recognition.  No  one  of  them  may  be  able  to  solve  the  pro- 
blem of  soul-life  or  the  riddles  of  the  world,  but  yet  may 
serve  to  guide  the  restless,  eager,  investigating  mind  towards 
the  solution  of  the  most  difficult  problems  that  are  presented 
to  the  minds  of  men." 

Pestalozzi's  Psychology :  The  Moral  Life. — While  claiming 
on  the  one  hand  that  the  animal  instincts  in  man  must  be  sub- 
dued in  order  that  the  human  may  evolve  unchecked,  on  the 
other  hand  Pestalozzi  argues  that  as  human  art  is  subordinate 
to  man's  spirit,  its  cultivation  is  imperative  upon  every  indi- 
vidual, and  the  germ  of  the  power  for  this  lies  in  the  inner  soul 
of  man  and  proceeds  from  the  union  of  spiritual,  moral,  and 
physical  powers,  powers  innate  in  man  and  endowed  with  the 
impulse  towards  development  and  perfection. 

A  Child's  Powers. — The  powers  of  a  child  are  immeasurable, 
but  for  healthy  evolution  must  develop  in  orderly,  organic 
unity,  the  unity  of  an  organism  in  which  the  God-hke  essence 
lives,  an  essence  which  is  free  and  autonomous,  and  which 
though  imbibing  hfe  from  its  sense-surroimdings  is  not  physi- 
cally bound.  At  first  it  exists  in  germ  only,  and  is  subject  to 
eternal,  immutable  laws  which  lie  at  the  basis  of  all  natural 
development ;  but  divine  love,  and  human  love  if  it  has  a  divine 
bias,  is  the  mainspring  which  directs  the  uplifting  of  man's 
sensual  and  animal  nature  through  his  spiritual  nature.  Faith 
and  love  unify  all  his  powers  of  knowing  and  acting,  and  are  to 
man  as  an  eternal  evolving  being,  as  the  roots  are  to  a  tree, 
giving  him  strength  to  draw  the  nourishment  necessary  for 
his  development. 

Cf.  Qui  que  tu  sois,  ramour  est  ton  maitre, 
II  Test,  il  le  fut,  et  il  le  doit  etre.    (Dumas.) 


t^ogel  139 

Motive  Powers  of  Development. — Pestalozzi  next  makes  a  fine 
distinction  between  animal  thinking  and  animal  art  (dependent 
on  the  perceptions  of  oux  race  from  purely  sensual  contemplation), 
and  human  power  of  thinking  (of  which  the  highest  results  of 
the  animal  are  no  sort  of  proof,  just  as  the  highest  technical 
excellence  may  be  possible  without  creative  power).  The  think- 
ing of  our  race,  as  human  thought,  certainly  does  not  proceed 
from  a  power  which  is  connected  with  the  delicate  fibres  of  our 
flesh  and  blood.  Our  thought,  in  so  far. as  it  is  truly  human, 
proceeds  from  the  divine  power  to  subject  our  flesh  to  our 
thought,  and  is  to  purely  animal  thinking  as  darkness  is  to 
Ught,  contradictory,  and  the  latter  leads  to  inhumanity. 

Man's  Innate  Power  of  Effort. — Then  Pestalozzi  maintains 
that  it  is  no  incentive  from  without,  no  foreign  will  outside  a  man, 
which  causes  the  development  of  his  powers.  It  is  his  own  will, 
his  own  innate  power  of  effort  which  effects  the  awakening  of 
his  heart  to  feeling,  his  mind  to  thinking,  or  his  physical  powers 
to  activity. 

Moral  Power. — By  means  of  his  moral  power  man  raises 
himself  to  the  position  of  highest  dignity  of  which  his  nature  is 
capable,  to  the  divine. 

Intellectual  Power. — The  intellectual  power  of  oiir  race 
Herbart  regards  as  a  power  of  the  humanity  of  om-  nature,  the 
component  powers  of  which  are  those  of  contemplation,  speech, 
and  thought.  The  power  of  contemplation,  if  not  unnatural, 
confused,  or  badly  regulated  leads  a  man  under  all  circumstances 
to  individual,  clear  presentations  about  the  objects  of  his  sur- 
roundings. Next  comes  the  need  of  expression,  and  the  gift  of 
speech  is  immeasurably  great,  and  is  essential  to  the  power  of 
thought ;  it  may  be  regarded  as  the  chief  help  whereby  the 
knowledge  won  through  contemplation  may  be  made  general 
and  fruitful. 

Pestalozzi' s  Moral  Teaching. — In  agreement  with  Kant  as 
well  as  with  the  philosophical  idealism  of  later  times,  Pestalozzi 
is  entirely  opposed  to  Herbart  from  the  point  of  view  that  the 
faculties  and  powers  of  the  human  soul  do  not  spring  from  the 
influence  of  outward  accident,  but  are  rather  innate  and  im- 


k46  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

manent,  so  that  they  constitute  the  proper  inner  essence  of  the 
soul.  It  is  clearly  seen  that  he  regards  the  moral  power  as  the 
highest,  and  as  that  which  raises  man  above  the  animal  and  out- 
wards to  the  eternal  and  divine,  and  he  also  clearly  shows  to 
what  extent  moral  freedom  is  not  a  matter  of  free-wiU,  but  a  law 
of  order  and  harmony.  Thus,  Nature  must  obey  her  laws. 
She  has  no  will.  But  I  must  not  obey  the  law  within  me,  if 
I  do  not  will  it :  in  this  I  am  my  own  judge  and  therefore 
a  nobler  creature  than  all  nature  beside,  Man  finds  himself 
pledged  in  both  the  sensual  and  the  mental  worlds, — in  the 
one  through  his  body — in  the  other  through  his  will.  The  laws 
of  both  are  in  essence  the  same,  because  both  command  order 
and  harmony  in  the  worlds  ruled  by  them ;  natures  gifted 
with  this  Knowledge  obey  the  law  at  first  because  they  ought, 
and  then  because  they  wish  to  do  so.  Still  though  Pestalozzi 
shows  that  the  laws  of  nature  and  of  the  spirit  are  one  and  the 
same,  he  does  not  transport  mechanical  laws  of  nature  to  the 
mental  world,  and  he  claims  that  the  power  of  abstraction  is  the 
very  essence  of  thought  power. 

The  '  Soul '  as  Viewed  by  Pestalozzi  and  Compared  with 
Herbart's. — Vogel  thinks  Pestalozzi's  ideas  more  suitable  as  a 
basis  for  the  moral  ordering  of  the  world  and  a  natm-al  education, 
in  just  the  way  that  Herbart's  seem  unsuitable.  Herbart's  sovd 
seems  a  dead  thing,  without  life  and  effort ;  Pestalozzi's  is  the 
source  of  never-ending  Hfe.  In  the  one  case  we  have  a  soul 
which  in  its  absoluteness  neither  requires  nor  is  capable  of 
development ;  in  the  other,  one  whose  impulses  endeavour  to 
evolve  the  powers  slumbering  within  it  to  infinite  perfection. 
The  one  is  a  mechanism,  the  other  an  organism ;  the  one  repels 
all  force  from  without  as  disturbance,  the  other  in  joyous  and 
happy  action  grasps  after  what  is  beneficial  for  itself  and  its 
fellows.  Scarcely  greater  opposites  can  be  imagined,  and  they 
admit  of  no  compromise ;  the  educationist  may  decide  for  him- 
self which  is  the  most  inspiring  and  to  which  of  the  two  leaders 
he  will  entrust  the  soul  of  his  pupil — Herbart  or  Pestalozzi. 

Educational  Theories  of  Pestalozzi. — From  the  starting  point 
that  the  development  of  the  man  himself,  the  masterpiece  of 


Vogel  141 

creation,  is  the  common  need  of  humanity,  Pestalozzi  proceeds 
to  distinguish  sharply  the  training  of  the  animal  in  man  from  the 
training  of  the  human,  and  to  enforce  that  when  the  highest 
perfection  of  the  animal  is  attained  this  does  not  touch  the 
boundary  line  of  the  evolution  of  the  human.  To  satisfy  man's 
nature  only  in  regard  to  food,  warmth,  and  rest  is  to  make  him 
sensual,  selfish,  and  lazy. 

The  object  of  all  education  is  therefore  the  raising  of  man's 
nature  from  the  sensuous  selfishness  of  animal  existence  to  the 
height  of  blessedness  possible  for  him  through  the  harmonious 
building  up  of  his  heart,  mind  and  art.  The  peace  arising 
therefrom  is  the  first  requisite  for  all  human  development,  and 
with  Pestalozzi  the  only  eternal  foundation  for  this  evolution 
of  our  nature  towards  humanity  is  hove,  only  through  its  sacred 
power  does  man  rise  to  the  divine  that  lies  within  him.  The 
development  of  the  man  cannot  come  through  a  one-sided  brain 
development ;  mechanical  cleverness  counts  but  little  on  the 
whole.     Again  it  is  : — 

Qui  que  tu  sois,  I'amour  est  ton  maitre, 

II  Test,  il  le  fut,  et  il  le  doit  etre.     (Dumas.) 

Love  is  essentially  the  centre,  and  true  love  proceeds  only  from 
true  faith,  that  of  a  trustful  human  child  in  his  Divine  Father. 

This  basis  of  education  naturally  presupposes  the  free-will  as 
the  centre  of  all  the  powers,  and  thus  the  man  must  be  educated 
to  perform  all  his  duties  towards  God,  his  neighbour  and  him- 
self willingly,  readily,  cleverly,  through  the  activity  of  his  faith 
and  love ;  he  must  be  made  intelligent  for  all  the  business  of  life 
and  for  every  emergency,  and  accustomed  to  necessary  activity 
and  effort. 

Still,  however  important  training  for  vocation  and  position  in 
life  may  be,  education  must  not  make  this  its  all-important 
object ;  the  perfection  of  man's  whole  human  nature  is  its  goal. 
The  true  nature  of  man  is  in  itself  neither  good  nor  bad ;  its 
character  depends  upon  whether  it  can  freely  develop  according 
to  its  essence  and  destiny  or  not — no  man  ought  therefore  to  say 
man  is  abject  and  depraved — it  is  only  the  men  in  whom  the 
power  and  the  right  feeling  of  their  human  nature  have  be- 


142  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

come  annihilated  through  sensuality  and  negligence  who  are 
abject  and  depraved.  Nature  has  done  her  work  completely, 
man  must  do  his  ;  she  has  placed  within  him  in  rich  abundance 
the  germs  of  all  those  powers  which  are  necessary  for  our 
eternal  and  earthly  destiny.  What  we  have  to  do  is  to  assist 
their  natural  development  by  bestowing  upon  them  the  en- 
lightened love,  the  trained  intellect  and  art  of  our  race.  Human 
art  is  in  this  like  the  art  of  the  gardener  under  whose  care  a 
thousand  trees  bloom  and  grow,  but  to  none  of  which  does  he 
give  the  germs  of  development.  A  teacher  plants  no  power 
in  man,  nor  does  he  give  life  or  breath  to  any  power,  he  only 
takes  care  that  no  external  force  shall  check  or  disturb  their 
natural  development,  and  must  be  guided  in  so  doing  by  what 
centuries  of  experience  have  taught  our  race  of  human  power. 

Again,  though  the  educator  begins  with  the  individual  and 
his  special  needs,  he  must  embrace  and  have  for  his  aim  the 
whole  of  humanity ;  the  race,  not  the  individual,  is  the  cry  of  the 
Divine  voice  within  us,  in  the  hearing  and  following  of  which 
lies  the  true  nobility  of  human  nature ;  man  is  not  in  the  world 
for  his  own  sake,  but  that  he  may  perfect  himself  in  the  perfect- 
ing of  his  brethren.  The  art  of  training  men  is  the  highest, 
though  the  hardest,  possible  to  man ;  there  is  no  calling  on  earth 
which  calls  for  greater  culture  and  greater  skill  and  deeper 
knowledge  of  humanity  and  its  needs.  The  means  employed 
must  always  tend  to  strengthen  and  purify  the  moral-rehgious 
bond  which  unifies  all  man's  powers.  Faith  must  come  about 
through  faith,  and  thought  through  thought,  not  only  through 
knowledge  of  what  is  believed  and  thought ;  and  love  must  come 
through  love ;  and  all  can  come  about  only  through  the  training 
of  man's  powers  to  the  higher  laws  of  his  will ;  a  training  which 
must  be  consistent  for  each  individual  with  the  degree  of  develop- 
ment to  which  he  has  already  arrived. 

The,  Development  of  Power. — The  natural  development  of 
each  power  comes  through  the  use  of  the  same,  through  work 
and  industry — therefore  the  physical  activity  of  our  race  is  the 
true,  divinely  ordained  means  for  the  development  of  the  human 
nature  in  man.     Industry  forms  the  intellect  and  gives  force  to 


Vogel  143 

the  feelings  of  the  heart,  and  in  order  that  this  development  may- 
proceed,  encouragement  is  necessary,  and  in  certain  cases  cor- 
rection ;  hence  Pestalozzi  does  not  condemn  corporal  punishment, 
though  he  lays  stress  on  the  fact  that  the  consistent  daily  and 
hourly  conduct  and  example  of  those  around  them  is  the  highest 
incentive  for  children — they  cannot  be  kept  in  order  by  fear  of 
corporal  punishment,  but  should  be  moved  to  do  right  of  their 
own  free  will  out  of  gratitude  and  love,  because  it  is  right,  and 
for  the  sake  of  their  own  advantage. 

The  Moral  Power. — Only  as  a  moral  being  does  man  advance 
to  perfection,  and  the  educator  must  strive  to  awaken,  nourish 
and  strengthen  moral  and  religious  feeling  in  the  child.  This 
is  effected  first  by  the  mother's  sacred  care,  in  the  steady,  quiet 
satisfaction  of  the  child's  physical  needs,  as  this  begets  trust 
and  love,  the  foundation  of  morality ;  and  man  must  love,  trust, 
and  obey  man,  before  he  loves,  trusts,  and  obeys  God.  Moral 
instruction  is  not  so  much  the  Teacher's  as  the  Parent's  task. 
Man's  struggle  after  perfection  is  the  one  thing,  aided  by  Divine 
guidance,  that  is  capable  of  destroying  evil. 

The  Mental  Poz(;er.— This  is  entirely  one  of  the  humanity 
of  our  nature,  and  hence  its  development  is  especially  the 
educator's  goal.  The  child  likes  to  think  as  much  as  he  does 
to  walk,  to  learn  as  much  as  to  eat,  if  only  his  instruction 
is  as  well  prepared  as  his  food.  To  make  the  child  feel  "I  can 
do  something  "  is  the  teacher's  special  task,  and  the  feeling  one 
of  the  child's  greatest  rewards. 

The  Science  of  Teaching. — This  comprises  three  natural 
means : — 

Simple  Observation  :  Memory  and  Application  of  what  is 
Observed :  Imagination. — The  real  value  of  human  knowledge 
consists  in  this,  that  a  man  who  knows  a  great  deal  and  can 
apply  it,  must  be  able  to  harmonise  more  than  another  with  his 
circumstances  and  to  develop  himself  uniformly. 

Instruction  therefore  is  Subordinate  to  Training.  —  Great 
simplicity  should  characterise  the  Teaching  art,  that  is,  all 
imparting  of  knowledge  should  start  from  the  very  simple,  and 
lead  by  easy  stages  to  what  is  dif&cult,  keeping  pace  always  with 


144  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

the  growth  of  power  in  the  pupil,  always  encouraging,  never 
wearying  him.  The  range  of  subjects  should  be  neither  too 
wide  nor  too  narrow.  None  of  us  need  all  Knowledge.  The 
form  of  instruction  is  valuable  in  so  far  as  it  arouses  the  inde- 
pendent action  of  the  child.  Only  that  which  is  in  full  harmony, 
mental,  spiritual,  and  physical,  with  the  individual,  is  for  that 
individual  really  truth.  Catechising,  therefore,  is  a  most  natural 
form  of  instruction,  and  only  such  material  should  be  chosen  as 
can  appeal  to  a  child's  mind  and  give  him  real  pleasure  and 
interest.  Natural  objects,  pictures,  and  illustrations  are  most 
essential  to  the  forming  of  clear  ideas  in  a  child's  mind,  and  to 
his  being  able  to  express  the  same.  Correct  sense-impressions 
lead  to  knowledge.  The  art  of  Teaching  lies  in  showing  right 
relations  and  associations,  and  in  strengthening  these  im- 
pressions, and  the  power  to  express  the  same.  Independent 
imaginative  work  follows  naturally. 

The  Physical  -  or  Artistic  Power. — Knowledge  without  the 
power  to  use  it  is  a  fatal  gift  to  any  man.  The  physical  basis 
of  the  development  of  artistic  power  is  instinct ;  but  art  is 
needed  in  directing  this  development.  Just  as  the  theory  and 
practice  of  form  and  number  may  be  regarded  as  the  gymnastics 
of  the  mental  power,  so  the  mechanical  exercise  of  the  senses 
and  limbs  is  necessary  for  the  development  of  the  art  power. 
Here,  again,  the  germs  of  the  power  are  in  man,  and  the 
development  of  mechanical  skill  by  simple  exercises  leading  to 
more  difficult  ones  consistent  with  the  circumstances  of  the  indi- 
vidual child  is  all  that  is  needed,  till  practice  leads  to  correct 
performance,  and  then  to  freedom  and  independence  in  any 
art. 

Unity  of  the  Powers. — Again,  the  Moral,  Mental,  and  Physical 
Powers  are  not  contradictory,  they  are  united  by  a  sacred  and 
organic  inner  bond  towards  a  common  end,  i.e.,  the  evolution 
towards  perfection  of  the  humanity  in  man,  and  all  art  in  train- 
ing must  work  towards  this  goal,  the  ennobling  and  satisfaction 
of  our  human  and  Divine  nature.  Only  that  which  lays  hold 
of  the  man,  and  satisfies  his  heart,  mind,  and  hand  is  truly 
advantageous  to  him.     If  one  part  suffers,  all  suffer  with  it. 


Vogel  145 

Harmonious  development  is  the  key-note  of  Pestalozzi's  theories, 
and  though  no  one  man  can  be  said  yet  to  have  attained  thereto, 
he  would  have  us  "  press  forward,  if  haply  we  may  do  so  ". 

The  Science  and  Art  of  Education :  Herbart  and  Pestalozzi. 
— Vogel  points  out  to  us  that  those  who  wish  to  build  a  science 
of  education  on  experience  should  be  very  careful  to  observe 
how  many  times  it  is  necessary  to  try  the  same  experiment  with 
different  gradations,  before  a  resultant  average  can  be  obtained 
which  is  capable  of  giving  a  theory  and  a  working  hypothesis  in 
the  domain  of  those  sciences,  so  essentially  founded  on  experience, 
as  physics  and  chemistry.  Education,  as  a  science,  must  be 
distinguished  from  the  art  of  Education,  for  science  is  the  orderly 
arrangement  of  precepts  which  constitute  an  harmonious  whole, 
and  in  which  the  results  are  derived  from  axioms,  and  axioms 
from  first  principles ;  while  an  art  is  the  sum  total  of  exercises 
which  must  be  united  to  bring  about  a  certain  object.  Science, 
therefore,  demands  guidance  from  theorems  proceeding  from 
philosophic  thinking,  while  Art  demands  constant  action  cor- 
responding with  the  result  to  be  attained ;  and  the  application  of 
Science  to  Art  is  necessary  before  entering  upon  that  action  by 
means  of  which  the  final  artistic  result  is  to  be  attained.  Never- 
theless one  must  not  expect  to  turn  out  an  infallible  master  of 
any  art  by  following  a  specific  scheme  of  rules  arrived  at  by  such 
preparation,  nor  must  one  demand  from  it  infallible  directions 
as  to  treatment.  One  must  trust  one's  power  of  discovery  suf- 
ficiently to  be  able  to  do  the  right  thing  at  the  right  moment, 
and  if  this  be  the  case  in  mere  technical  art  so  much  more  is  it 
so  in  that  art  of  all  arts.  Education.  Here,  perhaps,  individual 
actions  of  the  trainer  may  seem  insignificant,  but  the  whole 
tenor  of  his  treatment  is  of  vital  importance. 

Great  Insight  into  Human  Nature  Necessary. — Pestalozzi 
compares  child-training  to  the  gardener's  art.  Herbart  rather 
calls  attention  to  the  distinctions  between  them  dependent  on 
the  complexity  of  child  nature.  We  feel  the  first  requirement 
of  the  educator  to  be  an  exact  knowledge  of  human  nature,  not 
within  its  ordinary  limitations,  but  in  its  infinite  capacity  for 
development,  and  with  this  an  understanding  of  the  relations  of 


146  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

all  kinds  of  knowledge  to  the  various  interests  of  humanity,  and 
a  tactful  application  of  the  same. 

Government  of  Children. — In  the  government  of  children  the 
great  consideration  is  the  training  of  the  Will,  so  that  it  may  not 
be  the  mere  creature  of  wild  impulses  leading  first  one  way  and 
then  another.  Force  may  have  present  results,  but  true  training 
makes  for  the  discipline  of  the  future.  The  best  training  is  that 
of  Love  and  Persuasion  ;  sympathy  is  a  potent  factor,  and  also 
brings  about  the  best  present  results,  for  though  willing  is  more 
important  than  knowing,  it  has  its  root  in  thought  and  in  in- 
struction, which  incites  mental  activity  and  interest,  through 
presentations  which  depend,  to  a  great  extent,  on  experience 
and  environment. 

Foundations  of  Educational  Systems. — These  should  be  based 
on  Ethics  and  Psychology,  and  if  on  the  latter,  Herbart's  is 
wrong.  Logically,  the  idea  of  training  does  not  enter  into  his 
system,  and  yet  he  contradicts  himself,  for  to  carry  out  his 
system  premises  the  existence  of  soul  powers.  The  chief  aim  of 
education  is,  according  to  Pestalozzi,  the  elevation  of  our  nature 
from  the  sensual  selfishness  of  our  animal  self,  to  humanity 
through  Faith  and  Love,  while  Herbart  would  inculcate  Virtue  or 
Morality.  But  it  seems  to  us  that  Virtue  and  Morality  are  to 
Faith  and  Love  as  the  stream  to  the  source,  as  effect  to  cause, 
and  as  greater  abstractions  they  may  have  less  soul  life  and  less 
power  to  excite  Will.  Spontaneous  free-will  must  be  premised  if 
humanity  is  to  be  raised ;  Faith  and  Love  make  all  things  possible. 
Herbart  practically  denies  the  spontaneity  of  Will ;  and  yet  the 
human  Will  must  be  raised  to  resignation  and  to  sacrifice  for 
truth  and  right  through  Faith  and  Love.  Pestalozzi  holds  that 
education  can  only  draw  out  from  the  mind  what  is  already 
there.  It  can  arouse  already  existing  powers,  it  cannot  implant 
them. 

Herbart  denies  to  the  man  every  faculty  and  every  power 
which  animals  and  plants  possess.  According  to  him  the  mind 
of  man  is  constructed  in  accordance  with  outer  circumstances, 
and  it  is  thus  the  task  of  art  to  take  care  that  this  construction 
will  follow  lines  which  will  cause  the  mind  to  correspond  to  the 


Sallwurk  147 

purpose  of  man's  being.  As  he  makes  the  soul  entirely  without 
spontaneity,  he  renders  it  like  any  other  machine,  capable  only 
of  elaborating  what  it  receives.  It  certainly  adds  to  the  responsi- 
bility of  the  educator,  since  in  accordance  with  this  theory  it  rests 
entirely  in  his  hands  whether  the  pupil  becomes  a  reasoning  per- 
son or  a  wild  animal.  This  may  be  the  logical  conclusion  from 
Herbart's  psychology,  yet,  as  a  working  hypothesis,  his  system 
has  much  to  recommend  it.  The  training  of  strength  and  breadth 
of  Character,  through  many-sided  Interest,  is  indeed  the  pre- 
eminent goal  of  the  educator.  Life  itself,  it  may  be  urged, 
affords  here  and  there  opportunity  for  the  unfolding  of  the 
human-divine  powers,  without  the  necessity  for  specific  guidance, 
but  it  cannot  be  denied  that  a  proper  guidance,  with  regularly 
planned  method,  is  a  far  more  certain  means  for  the  accom- 
plishment of  the  desired  end,  or  should,  at  least,  work  hand  in 
hand  with  life. 

We  owe  an  incalculable  debt  to  Pestalozzi  as  the  pioneer  who 
penetrated  to  the  profoundest  depth  of  human  nature,  and  laid 
bare  its  psychological  organism,  as  well  as  the  imperishable 
foundations  upon  which  rest  the  means  through  which  its 
powers  may  be  developed.  His  Teacher  and  Pupil  are  friends, 
while  Herbart's  are  rather  Master  and  Scholar.  Perhaps  in 
practice  both  relations  are  needed,  and  instruction  must  fill  the 
gaps  left  by  experience  and  environment,  and  ensure  concen- 
trated attention  and  many-sided  development. 

SECTION  VII. 

SALLWURK. 

(1887.) 

Reference. 
Sallwurk.    Gesinnungs-unterricht    und    Kulturgeschichte.     Beyer    und 
Sohne  (Langensalza),  1887. 

Db.  E.  von  Sallwubk  was  the  author  of  an  important  book, 
published  anonymously  in  1880  under  the  title  of  Herbart  und 


148  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

seine  Jiinger  (Herbart  and  his  disciples),  which  gave  rise  to  ani- 
mated controversies  between  the  extreme  Zillerians  and  their 
critics.  Other  works  followed  in  1885  and  subsequent  years ; 
the  most  important  of  these  is  probably  the  one  above.  Sall- 
wiirk's  own  attitude  is  that  of  a  moderate  Herbartian  severely 
critical  towards  Zillerian  proposals.  He  is  especially  good  in 
his  treatment  of  the  scientific  foundations  of  the  culture-stages 
doctrine. 

Character-forming  Instruction  (Gesinnungs-unterricht)  may 
take  various  forms. 

(1)  It  may  be  pragmatic,  making  an  attempt  to  provide  the 
pupil  with  guidance  and  teaching  for  each  contingency  of  life. 
But  the  worst  of  this  method  is  that  it  deals  largely  with  out- 
ward experience,  whereas  the  child  is  a  child  and  must  be 
treated  as  such. 

(2)  It  may  be  organic,  following  the  development  of  the 
presentation  world  of  the  pupil,  and  advancing  strictly  from 
simple  to  complex. 

(3)  The  third  method  may  be  called  genetic,  and  is  based  on 
the  maxim  that  the  moral  development  of  the  individual 
imitates  that  of  the  race.  Thus  a  course  of  instruction  in 
accordance  with  general  history  would  satisfy  the  needs  of  the 
child.  But  the  advocates  of  this  method  have  never  yet  proved 
the  maxim  upon  which  their  method  rests  ;  moreover,  one 
questions  whether  they  have  succeeded,  without  too  much  arti- 
ficiality, in  obtaining  from  history  material  for  instruction  which 
corresponds  to  the  step- by-step  development  of  the  normal  child. 

After  deahng  with  "  Character-forming  Instruction "  along 
pre-Herbartian  lines,  Sallwiirk  proceeds  to  discuss  the  proposals 
of  Ziller. 

Ziller's  most  dangerous  tendency  was  towards  a  hasty 
dogmatism.  This  is  shown  in  his  doctrine  of  culture  stages 
as  applied  to  the  central  matter  provided  for  "  Character- 
forming  Instruction  ". 

He  proposes  that  after  the  early  courses  of  fairy  tales,  Eobin- 
son  Crusoe,  etc.,  the  children  should  be  taught  along  two  paral- 


Sallwiirk  149 

lei  lines,  profane  history  and  sacred  history ;  German  Sagas 
being  taught  along  with  the  Patriarchs  ;  the  Niebelungen  along 
with  the  Judges  ;  the  founders  of  the  German  kingdom  (Henry  I., 
etc.)  along  with  the  Jewish  Kings  ;  the  Eeformation  along  with 
Jesus  and  the  Prophets  ;  the  War  of  Freedom  along  with  the 
Apostles  ;  and  the  recent  re-erection  of  the  German  Empire 
along  with  the  Lutheran  Catechism.  MeanwhUe  for  the  higher 
schools  Greek  thought  should  be  treated  in  a  similar  way  ;  thus 
the  Odyssey  would  be  taught  simultaneously  with  the  Niebe- 
lungen and  the  Judges,  while  Herodotus  would  accompany 
Kings,  etc. 

How  much  of  this  scheme  is  Herbart's  own  ?  Very  little  ; 
only  those  portions  which  deal  with  the  classics  (Odyssey)  and 
with  Robinson  Crusoe.  Practically  speaking,  the  scheme  is 
Ziller's.  Herbart  himself  put  Thucydides  after  the  younger 
Xenophon,  thus  reversing  the  historical  order  and  showing 
how  little  he  believed  in  the  "  culture-stages  "  doctrine. 

The  connecting  together  of  secular  and  profane  history  may 
be  morally  useful  as  showing  the  advance  of  inner  ethical  ideas, 
but  "  concentration  "  would  suffer,  and,  indeed,  historical  truth. 

Let  us  consider  Ziller's  arguments.  The  child,  we  are  told, 
has  to  begin  in  the  child  world  of  the  fairy  tales  ;  here  he  gets 
to  know  single  things  in  their  concrete  forms.  Then,  in  passing 
through  the  Eobinson  Crusoe  stage  (the  conquest  of  natural 
hindrances)  he  learns  the  necessity  for  mutual  help  and  for 
authority.  Next  he  becomes  like  the  tribal  dependents  of  the 
patriarchal  age.  Activity  springs  up  ;  the  powers  of  each  indi- 
vidual in  the  community  are  valued  and  used  ;  national  form  is 
assumed  (Judges  period).  There  comes  now  a  recognition  of  an 
ethical  order  among  the  free  individuals  of  the  State  (Kings 
period).  Then  out  of  obedience  there  springs  up  love  for  the 
highest  authority  ;  Christ  appears  and  tries  to  bring  God's  king- 
dom on  the  earth. 

Ziller  tries  to  show  the  significance  of  this  scheme  from  the 
point  of  view  of  Herbart's  five  moral  ideas.  But  inasmuch  as 
these  ideas,  however  valuable,  were  deduced  dialectically  and 
not  historically,  they  do  not  really  correspond  to  Ziller's  stages. 


150  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


He  correlates  "  Inner  Freedom  "  with  his  fairy-tale  period ; 
"  Perfection "  (VoUkommenheit)  with  his  Eobinson  Crusoe 
period  ;  and  Benevolence  with  his  patriarchal  period.  All  this 
is  fantastic.  If  any  one  idea  is  first,  it  is  that  of  "  Eight  or 
Law,"  for  we  come  into  the  world  as  members  of  society.  How- 
ever, Ziller,  taking  the  three  primary  ideas  and  the  five  social 
ideas,  obtained  eight  in  all,  and  imagined  that  these  corre- 
sponded to  his  eight  cultm'e  stages. 

Again,  though  he  speaks  of  "  culture  stages,"  his  teaching 
course  is  really  determined  by  one  kind  of  culture  only,  namely, 
ethico-religious,  and  even  that  along  Christian  lines  only,  except 
so  far  as,  in  highest  schools,  the  classics  are  studied.  Surely 
art,  science,  etc.,  must  bs  considered. 

The  child,  before  entering  school,  is  already  in  part  familiar 
with  Christianity.  How  is  it  possible,  then,  to  make  a  child 
"  live  through  "  the  pre-Christian  stages? 

Ziller's  followers  have  by  no  means  slavishly  adhered  to  his 
plan.  Thus  Willmann  admits  errors  in  the  master's  scheme, 
and  Staude  declares  it  to  be  a  piece  of  audacity  to  assume  that 
between  the  ages  of  six  and  fourteen  the  child  passes  through 
eight  apperception  stages,  each  stage  demanding  certain  ma- 
terial and  no  more.  It  is  inconceivable  that  the  eight  years 
passed  in  the  elementary  school  should  have  such  a  philosophic 
basis. 

Again,  Staude  criticises  Ziller  for  leaving  it  uncertain  whether 
children  do  in  any  case  pass  through  the  eight  stages,  or  whether 
this  only  happens  if  we  arrange  our  instruction  properly.  He 
also  points  out  that  the  various  stages  cannot  be  definitely  marked 
ofi"  from  each  other,  and  criticises  the  importance  attached  to 
the  Judges  period  and  to  the  periods  subsequent  to  Christ ;  the 
time  devoted  to  the  study  of  Christ  must  be  increased.  But 
the  fundamental  weakness  in  the  works  of  men  like  Ziller, 
Staude,  and  Eein,  is  that  they  never  prove  that  the  assumed 
congruence  between  racial  and  individual  development  really 
exists. 

O.  W.  Beyer  (Ueber  die  Naturwissenschaften  in  der  Erzie- 
hungsschule)  is  an  earnest  writer  upon  the  question  of  natural 


Sallwurk  151 

science  teaching.  He  is  convinced  that  the  above-mentioned 
congruence  exists ;  embryology  is  a  witness.  But  Ziller  never 
thought  of  applying  the  culture-stages  doctrine  to  the  teaching 
of  any  subject  except  historical  ones.     Beyer  goes  further. 

He  calls  attention  to  such  facts  as  children's  love  of  wandering, 
hunting,  looking  after  animals,  and  so  forth.  He  regards  these 
as  indications  that  the  child  is  reproducing  the  hunting,  nomadic 
and  other  primitive  stages  of  development.  In  this  connection 
school  excursions,  school  gardens,  school  workshops,  etc.  (the 
last  bear  closely  on  the  later  civic  stage)  are  important.  There 
is  something  of  the  vagabond  and  of  Eobinson  Crusoe  in  every 
child. 

Accordingly  Beyer  proposes  that  an  attempt  be  made  to  follow 
the  different  development-stages  of  human  work,  the  making 
and  preparation  of  food,  the  discovery  of  fire,  etc.  No  doubt 
these  stages  were  vastly  important  for  the  race,.  But  have  they 
any  significance  for  the  individual  ?  Is  there  any  close  relation 
between  them  and  his  mental  development,  his  presentational 
life  ?  Is  there  really  any  mental  stage  in  the  individual  corre- 
sponding to  the  discovery  of  fire  ? 

Beyer  thinks  there  is.  He  identifies  the  culture  stages  (stage 
of  the  use  of  fire,  etc.)  with  the  conditions  of  adaptation  in  Dar- 
win's scheme,  and  believes  that  the  earlier  stages  have  left 
especially  deep  traces,  because  of  their  length.  But  is  this  so  ? 
Have  the  various  culture-stages  (hunting,  agriculture,  etc.)  ever 
really  modified  the  bodily  structure  ?  ^  And  was  there  ever  any 
precise  separation  between  the  stages  ? 

Just  as  Beyer  has  applied  the  culture-stages  doctrine  to  science 
teaching,  another  Zillerian,  Menard,  has  applied  it  to  art. 

Examination  of  the  Scientific  Foundations  of  the  Culture- 
stages  Doctrine. — Ziller  has  never  applied  his  doctrine  to  the 
entire  realm  of  human  development,  only  to  the  ethical.  But 
surely  there  would  be  a  certain  charm  in  generalising  the  maxim, 
and,  drawing  inspiration  from  it,  to  carry  on  the  work  willed  by 
Providence.     Let  us,  however,  examine  it. 

1  Here  Sallwurk  touches  on  the  great  problem  whether  habits  are  tranS' 
mitted  to  offspring. 


152  TTu  Critics  of  Herhartianism 

The  culture-stages  doctrine  implies  that  racial  development  is 
a  real  development,  i.e.,  a  progression  from  a  lower  to  a  higher 
stage.  But  evolution  is  not  always  upward,  though  it  is  always 
in  the  direction  of  adaptation  to  environment.  Organs  have  to 
become  adapted  to  new  conditions.  Some  blind  animals  possess 
rudimentary  eyes  in  their  early  stages  of  existence ;  is  the  dis- 
appearance of  the  eyes  an  advance  ?  Surely  not,  in  the  sense  of 
the  culture-stages  doctrine,  though  in  the  sense  of  adaptation  to 
conditions  it  is  an  advance.  Culture  is  a  question  of  the  favour- 
able or  unfavourable  relations  in  which  the  surrounding  material 
world  places  those  wrestHng  with  it ;  culture  itself  may  not  alter 
the  bodily  or  mental  organisation ;  thus  previous  culture  stages 
may  not  have  been  handed  down  to  the  human  beings  of  the 
present  day,  and  therefore  education  need  not  pay  any  attention 
to  such  previous  stages.  Only  that  which  exists  in  the  present 
conditions  of  culture,  or  that  which  is  represented  in  present-day 
instincts,  can  be  attended  to  by  education.  Moreover,  the  human 
race  passed  through  many  stages  previous  to  the  historic  ones 
— hunting,  nomadic,  etc. — but  we  cannot  trace  them.  Again, 
human  culture  has  not  been  an  uninterrupted  advance :  it  has 
repeatedly  doubled  back  or  retrogressed  ;  or  an  older  culture,  it- 
self incapable  of  further  advance,  may  have  fertilised  a  younger 
culture.  Thus  oriental  culture  has  influenced  Greek  rather  than 
developed  continuously  along  its  own  lines. 

True,  the  development  of  the  individual  does  not  always  pro- 
ceed along  one  definite  line  ;  but  we  must  not,  for  this  reason,  imi- 
tate the  involved  and  perplexing  procedure  of  racial  development. 

Enough  has  been  said  in  connection  with  Beyer's  proposals 
to  show  that  we  must  not  imitate  the  forms  of  material  develop- 
ment, for  these  forms  (the  use  of  fire,  etc.)  merely  demonstrate 
incidentally  a  mental  and  ethical  advance,  but  are  in  themselves 
of  no  educational  significance,  however  great  their  significance 
for  the  race  as  a  whole. 

Let  us  proceed  to  consider  inner  development. 

Intellectual  Development. — There  are  great  difficulties  here  for 
the  culture  stages  theory ;  man  was  once  quite  devoid  of  science; 
are  we  to  imitate  this  stage  ?     The  question  of  speech  would 


Sallwurk  153 

oflfer  an  extraordinarily  good  field  for  study ;  but  even  with 
advanced  peoples,  speech  is  still  primitive  and  cannot  express 
logical  distinctions  very  clearly  ;  thus  in  English,  concretes  and 
abstracts  are  not  completely  distinguished,  and  in  most  lan- 
guages there  is  a  confusion  between  'post  hoc  and  propter  hoc 
{cf.,  the  particles  since,  quum,  nachdem,  puisque). 

Even  if  science  could  give  us  an  account  of  man's  intellectual 
development,  education  must  not  copy  it,  unless,  with  Eousseau, 
we  wish  to  lead  out  of  instead  of  into  culture.  Surely  we  shall 
teach  European  writing,  not  hieroglyphics  ;  developed  word- 
forms,  not  primitive  roots. 

Ethical  Development. — In  the  realm  of  ethical  thought  there 
has  been  no  change  in  the  moral  ideas,  though  much  change  in 
their  application  (marriage,  etc.);  from  the  first  dawn  of  culture 
man  seems  to  have  had  them.  Thus  family  life,  even  in  the 
crudest  form,  develops  all  the  ideas. 

Ziller's  strange  notion  of  developing  the  moral  ideas  one  after 
the  other  (Inner  Freedom  at  the  fairy-tale  stage,  VoUkommenheit 
at  the  Crusoe  stage,  and  so  on)  would  involve  a  dissection  of 
morality  ;  nay,  the  pupils  would  for  a  long  time  live  without 
morality,  for  Inner  Freedom  involves  insight  into  all  the  other 
ideas,  and  therefore  cannot  exist  alone.  It  is  clear  that  the 
simple  ideas  cannot  and  ought  not  to  develop  step  by  step ;  and 
further,  that  the  deduced  social  relations  are  beyond  the  capacity 
of  juniors,  so  that  the  imaginary  actions  the  latter  are  directed 
to  consider  would  be  fatal  to  earnestness. 

Further  Criticisms  of  Ziller's  Plan. — The  child's  nature  is 
rooted  in  the  present.  To  insist  that  the  child  should  live 
through  past  stages  is  to  rely  on  superficial  views  of  the  culture- 
stages  doctrine,  and  is,  indeed,  difiicult  to  be  justified  by  an  Her- 
bartian,  who  is  supposed  to  lay  much  stress  on  the  present  rela- 
tions of  the  pupils. 

Again,  can  we  parallel  sacred  history  with  the  real  culture 
development  of  man  ?  The  question  culminates  in  this  :  Are  the 
Protestant  German  Empire  and  the  Lutheran  Catechism  neces- 
sarily the  highest  stage  of  human  culture  ?  It  is  difficult  here 
to  share  Ziller's  optimism, 


1 54  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

Again,  Joseph,  David,  etc.,  are  introduced  to  the  pupil  after 
Eobinson  Crusoe  has  been  accompanied  over  the  world,  and 
after  questions  like  property,  obedience,  etc.,  have  been  intro- 
duced. In  point  of  fact,  Ziller  puts  Crusoe  much  too  early,  as 
some  Zillerians  admit. 

The  Zillerians  criticise  some  of  the  Old  Testament  stories  on 
various  grounds,  and  substitute  fairy  tales  for  them  in  the  first 
year.  Thus  the  narratives  of  the  Creation  and  Fall  have  to  be 
withheld  ;  all  sorts  of  limitations,  reservations,  and  exclusions 
are  proposed.  But,  in  reality,  if  the  Old  Testament  stories  are 
taught  simply  and  undogmatically  they  will  be  found  suitable 
enough,  and  better  than  the  fairy  tales  ;  and,  indeed,  these  latter 
are  altogether  too  childish  for  children  who  have  entered  school. 

We  must  not  base  extravagant  hopes  on  the  social  culture  of 
thirteen-year-old  pupils  who  are  still  under  home  protection. 
We  must  undertake  with  them  natural  and  remunerative  tasks, 
and  give  them  the  right  disposition  to  do  their  own  appointed 
work ;  to  go  beyond  this  will  be  a  mistake. 


SECTION  VIII. 

HUBATSCH. 
(1888.) 

Bsfer&nce. 

Hubatsch.      Gesprdche  ilber  die  Herbart-ZUlersche  PtLdagogik.     Kunzes 
Nachfolger,  Wiesbaden. 

This  violent  attack  upon  Herbartianism  is  in  the  form  of  con- 
versations between  a  supposed  juvenile  enthusiast  for  the  system 
and  educationists  of  a  disillusioned  type.  A  certain  vein  of 
cynicism  runs  through  this  critique.  Hubatsch  is  one  of  the  few 
critics  who  see  scarcely  anything  that  is  good  in  the  proposals  of 
the  reformers,  though  he  praises  Herbart's  strenuous  consist- 
ency. 


Hubatsch  155 

Herbart's  psychology  is  rejected  even  by  men  who  cling  to  his 
pedagogy.  It  sounds  impressive  owing  to  its  technical  ter- 
minology. But  the  ruin  of  the  psychology  involves  the  ruin  of 
the  pedagogy,  for  the  two  are  closely  connected.  Herbart's 
notion  of  a  simple  soul  and  of  a  presentational  mechanism,  with 
quantitative  laws  only,  is  purely  fanciful.  The  experiments  of 
Munk,  and  facts  such  as  the  loss  of  words  for  certain  ideas,  show 
that  the  brain  is  concerned  in  all  thought,  hence  a  system  which 
ignores  facts  like  the  brain  is  doomed.  A  psychology  suitable 
for  pedagogy  must  not  ignore  experience,  physiology,  etc. 

Ziller  indidges  in  prolix  declamations  but  ignores  important 
points.  He  was  ignorant  of  man  and  of  the  world,  yet  he 
abused  all  opponent's  as  fools.  He  said:  "  Woe  to  the  schools 
where  dexterities  and  knowledge  are  regarded  as  the  highest 
goals  to  aim  at,  where  '  practical '  interests,  future  usefulness, 
etc.,  are  primarily  regarded,  and  not  the  impiilse  to  know  and 
will ".  Is  this  the  utterance  of  a  man  who  knows  the  world  ? 
Do  we  live  in  a  Utopia  ?  Ziller  blames  the  schools  for  the 
absence  of  great  men ;  but  surely  if  any  schools  were  able  to 
produce  useless  and  helpless  men  those  schools  would  be 
Ziller' s,  with  their  constant  feeding  of  pupils  on  character- 
material. 

Following  Herbart,  ZiUer  recognised  three  classes  of  schools, 
Gymnasia,  Burgerschulen,  and  Volksschulen.  Each  has  to  be 
transformed  into  an  "  educative  school ".  No  doubt  he  admits  the 
claims  of  the  future  vocation,  etc.,  but  he  protests  against  the 
mixing  up  of  ideals.  The  "  chief  classes,"  devoted  to  "  educa- 
tion" proper,  must  be  distinguished  from  the  "subsidiary 
classes  "  devoted  to  professional  training.  But  surely  Ziller 
forgets  human  nature  when  he  draws  this  sharp  distinction, 
and,  in  point  of  fact,  the  "  subsidiary  classes  "  would  prove  the 
greatest  attraction. 

ZiUer  has  a  dream  of  small  school  communities,  unconnected 
with  State,  Town,  or  Church.  How  httle  he  knows  the  world  ! 
State  control  is  daily  increasing. 

He  urges  a  diminution  in  school  hours  and  in  home  lessons, 
and  many  breaks  in  the  school  lessons  for  open-air  exercise, 


156  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


This  would  be  possible,  he  says,  if  teachers  knew  better  how  to 
employ  the  pupil's  time  ...  if  ...  if  ...  if  "  concentra- 
tion," etc.,  were  effected.  Present-day  teachers  are  no  good; 
they  have  no  missionary  zeal.  But  Ziller  is  wrong.  Teachers 
must  limit  themselves  to  definite  narrow  goals.  If  wider  cul- 
ture were  possessed  by  them  criticism  would  awaken,  and  there 
would  be  system  no  longer.^  So  long  as  large  classes  exist  in 
schools,  it  is  no  good  to  "  talk  big  ".  Moral  education  must  rest 
mainly  on  habit,  rule,  custom,  obedience,  religious  instruction, 
influence,  etc.  Experience,  activity,  struggle  are  the  best 
teachers. 2 

When  you  have  obtained  your  finely  educated  teachers,  ac- 
quainted with  the  latest  researches,  will  they  choose  the 
lower  schools  ?  Surely  Ziller  ought  to  have  founded  a  philan- 
thropic "brotherhood".  Pedagogical  enthusiasm  is  rare;  so 
long  as  teachers  do  their  duty  that  is  enough.  A  day  has  only 
twenty-four  hours.  How  many  thousand  volumes  must  a  man 
read  before  becoming  a  Zillerian  teacher  ? 

"  Educative  Instruction."  Strange  terminology,  that  of  the 
Herbartians !  Preposterous  claims  to  have  discovered  a 
"  science "  of  pedagogy  !  Pedagogy  is  merely  an  art  with 
a  narrow  aim  ;  it  picks  up  its  knowledge  from  other  sources. 
To  give  the  name  of  science  to  a  pedagogy  founded  on  the  doc- 
trine of  a  presentational-mechanism — a  doctrine  which  ignores 
the  rich  life  of  the  soul,  its  secret  impulses,  the  thousand  riddles 
of  the  world — is  monstrous  ! 

Do  not  all  educators  try  to  educate  through  Instruction  ? 
The  Zillerians  answer,  "  Only  in  a  chance  way.  You  tried  to 
cultivate  the  Understanding,  the  Taste,  the  Imagination,  etc., 
but  you  forgot  that  Will  is  the  one  supreme  goal ;  you  should 
aim  at  creating  Virtue  and  Christian  Love,  and  the  Kingdom  of 
God  on  earth."  But  is  education  impossible,  then,  with  Jews, 
Moslems,  etc,  ?     It  was  Ziller  who  added  the  rehgious  notion 

^  In  other  words,  Hubatsch  pleads  for  a  narrow,  brutal  professionalism 
without  ideals. 

^  Yes,  and  how  many  pupils  sMCCMwi?  The  need  of  Instruction  is  the 
great  Herbartian  message,  a  far  more  valuable  one  than  that  of  Hubatsch. 


Hubatsch  157 

to  Herbart's  system  and  claimed  that  Christianity  alone  in- 
cludes all  that  is  humanly  good.  He  rejected  French  and  also 
various  classical  authors  (Horace)  as  not  truly  educative  ;  but 
surely  this  is  pure  fanaticism  ;  all  men  of  culture  must  know 
French,  Horace,  etc. 

"Action  depends  on  the  circle  of  thought,"  say  the  Herbar- 
tians.  This  is  really  Socrates  redivivus.  The  doctrine  is  wrong. 
Man  has  desires,  inclinations,  etc.  It  is  no  good  to  deny  inborn 
activities,  or  to  call  them  purely  "  formal ".  Darwinism  and  the 
inductive  method  show  that  "  faculties"  must  be  assumed,  such 
as  no  presentations  can  invert.  When  Dickens  described  pure- 
minded  children  amid  squalor  and  vice,  was  he  wrong  ?  Ziller 
and  Herbart  are  really  in  conflict  over  this  question  ;  Ziller  prac- 
tically admits  "  faculties  ". 

The  relation  between  "  many-sidedness  "  and  Virtue  is  not 
clear.  Sxirely  a  one-sided  person  may  be  virtuous,  and  vice 
versd.  "  Yes,"  says  Herbart,  "  but  Interest  must  be  awakened 
if  Instruction  has  to  bear  on  Virtue.  Moreover,  morality  is 
really  impossible  without  intelligence,  for  the  circle  of  thought 
limits  everything."  "  But  surely  many-sided  Interest  is  often 
connected  with  self-love,  pride,  etc."  "  No,"  says  Herbart, 
"the  Interest  is  not,  in  such  cases,  genuine."  "  Eeally,"  re-, 
sponds  the  critic,  "what  about  Voltaire,  Bacon,  Cicero,  Seneca?" 

Christianity  lays  stress  on  Faith  and  Love,  not  on  Knowledge 
and  many-sided  Interest.  Where  is  the  real  connection  between 
the  latter  and  Virtue  ? 

Interest,  say  the  Herbartians,  "  is  a  protection  against  pas- 
sions," which  often  spring  from  narrowness  of  mind  ;  it  is  a 
means  of  "  help  in  the  afl'airs  of  life,"  and  it  is  a  means  of 
"safety  amid  the  storms  of  fate,"  as  opening  up  new  paths.  But 
(says  the  critic)  a  owe- sided  Interest  is  often  more  satisfactory. 
There  are  many  gradations  between  stupidity  and  many-sided 
Interest. 

Herbart  denies  that  true  Interest  is  of  the  nature  of  Desire. 
It  is,  he  says,  a  peaceful  thing,  and  not  an  impatient  "  pressing 
forward  ".  But  (says  the  critic)  such  Interest  is  neither  fish  nor 
flesh.     And,  in  point  of  fact,  some  of  Herbart's  six  classes  of  In- 


158  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

terest  are  "  peaceful,"  some  are  not ;  his  whole  classification  is 
illogical.  "Speculative"  interest  is  not  "peaceful,"  as  "aes- 
thetic "  is.  Some  of  the  interests  are  interests  in  definite 
objects ;  others  in  relations.  Again,  religious  interest  easily 
passes  over  into  a  Feeling  (of  Fear,  Hope,  etc.). 

Then  the  "concentration"  and  "culture-stages  "  doctrines  are 
of  dubious  value,  and  scarcely  found  in  Herbart's  own  works. 
They  rest  on  bad  psychology  or  partial  analogies.  There  is  no 
history  of  mankind  in  general,  only  of  nations.  Fables  are  pro- 
ducts of  advanced  not  primitive  culture  ;  primitive  man  regarded 
animals  as  enemies,  whereas  the  fables  lay  stress  on  the  unity  of 
nature,  and  really  spring  from  a  time  when  animals  had  already 
been- tamed.  Sleeping  princesses,  etc.,  were  no  part  of  primi- 
tive man's  world.  He  thought  mainly  of  the  dreadful,  vast 
forces  of  nature.  It  is  impossible  to  extract  morals  out  of 
Marchen.  Moreover,  schools  have  to  teach  reality,  and  the 
imagination  must  not  be  over- stimulated. 

Again,  though  "  Eobinson  Crusoe  "  is  a  splendid  story  for 
children,  suggesting  self-power,  stimulating  imagination  (how  to 
act  in  hour  of  need),  sympathy,  etc.,  yet  the  story  does  not  re- 
present any  one  stage  of  development.  Men  did  not  make 
clothes,  etc.,  nor  live  alone  after  Eobinson's  fashion.  He  al- 
ready had  the  ideas  of  civilisation  in  his  mind.  How  different 
the  child  of  eight !  At  no  stage  ought  we  to  make  the  story  the 
centre  of  instruction,  the  story  brings  forward  foreign  and  excep- 
tional scenery.  But  the  story  is  an  excellent  one  for  reading  at 
a  certain  age. 

Others  of  Ziller's  stages  are  equally  dubious.  The  Odyssey 
stage  is  said  to  correspond  to  that  of  navigation ;  doubtless  selec- 
tions from  this  poem  are  useful,  but  not  as  the  centre  of  instruc- 
tion. What  a  medley  Ziller's  material  is,  animal  fables,  modern 
Eobinson,  ancient  patriarchs,  Greek  heroes,  etc. !  Many  of  the 
"  stages  "  (the  Livy  stage,  the  Anabasis  stage,  etc.)  may  be  use- 
ful in  school,  but  have  only  very  superficial  parallels  in  the  race. 
The  child  has  parents  whom  it  imitates  ;  how  differently  did  the 
race  learn !  Most  of  the  Zillerian  parallels  and  connections, 
e.g.,  between  Greek   and  Jewish  history  are  equally  artificial. 


Hubatsch  159 

How  absurd,  also,  to  begin  with  geography  of  Asia  (Ararat, 
etc.) !     We  should  begin  at  home. 

The  great  "  Interest  "  doctrine  !  The  Herbartians  make  In- 
terest an  end,  not  a  mere  means.  It  must  rest  on  involuntary 
attention,  itself  favoured  by  Begierung,  and  resting  on  sensible 
intensity  as  well  as  on  contrast,  newness,  expectation,  etc.  But, 
says  the  critic,  what  is  the  first  germ  of  Interest  ?  How  can 
Interest  be  generated  merely  out  of  presentations,  apart  from 
any  central  ego  ?  The  Herbartians  say,  "  Interest  arises  when 
presentations  come  forward  freely ;  without  this  freedom  there 
may  still  be  attention,  but  of  a  forced  kind  ".  In  point  of 
fact  the  whole  mathematical  theory  of  presentations,  their  inter- 
actions, etc.,  is  so  obscure  as  to  ruin  the  doctrine  of  Interest 
which  rests  on  it.  In  its  essence  it  is  materialistic  or  atomistic. 
But  presentations  are  not  atoms  ;  they  are  much  more  complex, 
and  cannot  be  treated  as  homogeneous.  A  tone  and  the  Koman 
Empire  cannot  be  treated  as  alike ;  some  presentations  are  highly 
complex ;  concepts,  too,  are  peculiar ;  yet  Herbart  lumps  all  these 
together  as  presentations. 

Again,  Herbart  lays  great  stress  on  primitive  and  apperceptive 
attention  ;  but  whence  comes  the  agency  in  this  ?  He  is  com- 
pelled to  admit  the  necessity  for  voluntary  attention ;  here  we 
have  the  agent,  the  Will.  Siirely  this  factor  is  important. 
Attention  is  a  function  of  the  Will.  It  may  be  voluntary  or 
involuntary.  It  is  this  WUl  that  explains  everything.  But 
Herbart  only  brings  it  on  the  scene  at  the  very  end  of  the  series 
— Attention,  Interest,  Will.  There  is  with  him  no  original 
Will.  According  to  him,  out  of  primitive  attention  there  arises, 
by  a  storing  up  of  presentations,  apperceptive  attention  ;  out  of 
this  finally  emerges  Interest.  But  why  not  reverse  the  process, 
and  say  that  the  living  will-power  of  the  soul  shows  itself  in 
impulses,  interest,  etc.  ?  The  Will  is  the  presupposition,  not  the 
result  of  Education ;  we  must  work  upon  the  Will  by  presenting 
to  it  suitable  objects  for  arousing  Interest.  Interest  presupposes 
Will,  not  vice  versd. 

The  Herbartian  emphasis  upon  immediate  interest  and  the 
partial  depreciation  of  mediate  interest  overlooks  the  fact  that 


i6o  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

we  cannot  gather  grapes  from  thorns  ;  we  must  take  men  as  we 
find  them.  Happy  if  we  can  awaken  even  mediate  interest. 
To  say,  "  Don't  interest  to  teach,  but  teach  to  awaken  Interest," 
is  sophistry.  The  teacher  can  only  awaken  Interest  by  being 
interesting.  How  can  you  awaken  an  interest  in  Latin  declen- 
sions except  by  first  conveying  the  impression  that  it  is  some- 
thing fine,  mighty,  worthy,  etc.,  to  know  Latin?  But  this  is 
mediate  Interest. 

Again,  Herbart  admits  that  Interest  depends  on  the  one  side 
on  natural  capacity  which  cannot  be  created.  But  if  so,  many- 
sided  Interest  is  unnatural.  He  and  Ziller  compare  education 
to  an  imaginary  process  in  which  an  angular  body  gradually 
approximates  to  the  spherical  form  by  the  excitation  of  many- 
sided  Interest.  But  the  illustration  will  not  serve.  Either  the 
angular  body  is  alterable  or  not.  If  unalterable,  many-sided 
Interest  has  no  influence ;  if  alterable,  the  individuality  vanishes. 
"  It  is  alterable,"  say  the  Zillerians,  "  but  mainly  so  in  youth, 
and  the  difficulty  of  alteration  increases  with  age ;  hence  the 
importance  of  Education."  They  teU  us  that  all  must  be 
amateurs  in  everjrthing,  virtuosi  in  one  department.  But  all 
cannot  be  amateurs  in  everything  ;  individuality  prevents  it.  A 
theory  which  professes  to  unite  individuality  with  many-sided 
Interest  is  so  absurd  as  to  be  impervious  to  attack. 

No  doubt  Herbart  contends  that  many-sided  Interest  is  a  foe 
to  fickleness  as  well  as  to  one-sidedness,  and  he  lays  stress  on 
Absorption  (Vertiefung)  as  well  as  Eeflection  (Besinnung).  But 
Absorption  really  presupposes  Interest,  and  this  depends  on 
innate  powers.  One  man  likes  Mathematics,  another  Languages, 
etc. 

The  Goal  of  Edvx^ation. — This  is,  according  to  Ziller,  the 
forming  of  ethico-religious  personalities  according  to  the  ideal 
of  the  Kingdom  of  God.  But  a  transcendent  goal  like  this  will 
not  do.  When  parents  send  their  children  to  school  what  do 
they  expect  ?  Surely  that  the  children  be  made  into  useful  and 
capable  persons.  Education  only  deals  with  the  preliminary 
part  of  life,  the  part  before  independence  is  reached.  The 
Herbartian  goal  may  be  very  good,  but  only  for  adults.     It  is 


Hubatsch  i6i 

no  good  to  rave  against  existent  schools.  All  their  attempts 
correspond  to  definite  needs  that  have  grown  up.  We  must 
be  practical  people.  The  age  will  not  stand  mere  "  culture 
ideals  ".     Education  has  several  distinct  tasks. 

"  No,"  say  the  Herbartians,  "  Instruction  must  not  be  separ- 
ated from  Education,  Knowledge  from  Morality.  Instruction 
must  serve  Education;  it  must  create  Virtue."  But  this  is  a 
great  mistake.  Owe  goal  is  not  enough.  There  must  be  as 
many  goals  as  there  are  directions  of  human  activity.  Moral 
and  intellectual  Education  are  two  different  things}  and  the 
latter  is  far  more  effective  than  the  former,  for  no  Education 
can  wash  a  Moor  white.  Moral  action  rests  on  impulses  deeply 
buried ;  the  teacher  is  not  responsible  for  them  ;  if  he  were  we 
should  punish  not  the  criminal  but  his  teacher.  ^ 

"No,"  says  Herbart,  "action  springs  out  of  the  circle  of 
thought."     But  character  cannot  be  altered  so  easily. 

"Formal  Culture." — Apart  from  the  rousing  of  aesthetic  and 
other  Interest,  and  the  formation  of  a  "  circle  of  thought," 
Herbart  despised  languages,  mathematics,  etc.  But  formerly 
people  believed  that  the  study  of  the  classics  was  a  fine  mental 
gymnastic,  a  fine  training  in  logic,  in  fact  fine  "  formal  culture  ". 
So  also  with  mathematics.  But  the  Herbartians  contend  that 
these  subjects  must  not  be  treated  in  independence.  Thus  these 
men  encourage  scattered,  superficial  thinking,  and  the  tearing 
apart  of  what  belongs  together.  The  true  principles  of  language 
and  mathematics  are  not  learnt.  Note  the  superficial  connec- 
tions established  by  Zillerians  ! 

History. — The  Herbartians  rightly  lay  great  stress  on  this 
subject,  but  mainly  because  of  its  moral  aspects.  But  this  view 
of  the  subject  will  conduce  to  the  encouragement  among  children 
of  premature  judgments  upon  characters.  A  sound  judgment 
upon  historical  characters  demands  severe  abstraction.  Far 
better  use  common  life  as  moral  material. 


1  Elsewhere  Hubatsch  says  that  there  are  three  aims  to  be  kept  in  view  : 
(1)  moral ;  (2)  intellectual ;  (3)  professional. 

^  In  other  words,  the  great  Herbartian  message  is  of  no  value  whatever. 

II 


1 62  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

The  new  pedagogy  uses  force  with  its  material.  It  is  like 
a  French  garden  in  which  nothing  is  allowed  to  grow  up 
naturally.  Language  is  subordinated  to  History  ;  Mathematics 
to  Nature  -  Knowledge.  But  formerly  we  thought  that  the 
hardest  subjects  were  the  best ;  the  Herbartians  put  the  easiest 
in  the  seat  of  honour. 

Herbart  seems  constantly  to  be  thinking  of  horriR  education ; 
here  there  is  some  sense  in  talking  of  analytical  Instruction,  etc., 
for  the  soul  of  the  one  pupil  is  an  open  book  to  the  tutor. 
Herbart  at  times  distinctly  depreciates  the  value  of  the  school. 
How  remote  his  ideas  from  modern  conditions  ! 

Then  the  "  formal  steps  ".  Comenius  urged  the  importance 
of  the  first,  as  also  of  others.  The  Zillerians  often  treat  the 
material  with  violence,  and  there  is  danger  that  the  pure  image 
of  the  object  studied  may  be  erased  owing  to  premature  com- 
parisons with  other  objects.  Let  the  teacher  ensure  clear 
Anschauung,  and  not   trust  too  much  to  words  and  "  steps  ". 

Analysis  is  the  main  thing  ;  synthesis  is  understood  of  itself ; 
the  third  step  (Association)  is  only  valuable  if  we  are  aiming  at 
some  inductive  result;  so  with  the  other  steps,  they  are  not 
always  necessary.  Herbart  never  intended  that  the  "  steps  " 
should  be  always  employed.  But  Ziller  has  insisted  on  this, 
and  has  even  invented  "  teaching  units  ".^  There  must  be  more 
consideration  of  the  individual  peculiarities  of  subject  and  pupil. 
Again,  the  fifth  step  (Application)  should  often  be  the  third  ;  it  is 
absurd  to  use  comparisons  until  the  material  itself  is  familiar. 

^Dr.  Pindlay  prefers  the  word  "section"  for  the  "teaching  unit"  of 
Ziller. 


Drews  163 

SECTION  IX. 

DREWS. 

(1890.) 

Bieference. 
Drews.    Die  Katechese  und  das  Lehrverfahren  der  Herbartianer.  Velhagen 
und  Klasing  (Bielefeld  and  Leipzig). 

This  brief  critique  is  directed  against  the  Zillerian  policy  of  depre- 
cating the  catechetical  or  questioning  method.  The  author,  who, 
however,  is  not  blind  to  the  merits  of  his  opponents,  attempts  to 
show  (what  ought  surely  to  be  in  no  need  of  proof)  that  the 
method  may  have  a  legitimate  place  in  school  work. 

It  is  at  first  sight  strange  that  the  Herbartians  should  make 
this  attack.  For  the  two  parties  are  at  one  in  their  objection  to 
mere  "learning  by  heart,"  in  their  approval  of  a  thorough 
working-in  of  material,  and  in  their  ideal  way  of  regarding  the 
work  of  education. 

Doubtless  the  catechetical  method  was  established  in  pre- 
psychological  days,  and  needs  to  be  looked  at  in  a  new  light. 
Still,  there  is  no  need  to  follow  the  Zillerians  in  their  policy  of 
wholesale  condemnation. 

We  agree  with  the  Herbartians  that  our  Instruction  must  act 
on  the  Will,  and  we  need  not  here  quarrel  with  them  as  to 
how  far  the  influence  of  the  Instruction  can  extend.  Neither 
need  we  quarrel  with  them  as  to  their  doctrine  of  many-sided 
Interest,  which,  after  all,  is  not  very  different  from  the  doctrine 
of  the  "  harmonious  development  of  all  faculties  ".  "  All 
faculties " ;  this  is  a  just  protest  against  mere  memorising. 
The  two  views  may  differ  fundamentally  in  their  philosophical 
foundations,  but  there  is  no  conflict  in  practice.  All  intelligent 
parties  wish  to  make  teaching  "  heuristic,"  that  is,  to  arouse  the 
mental  activity  and  independence  of  the  pupil.  The  catechetical 
method  really  arose  out  of  a  desire  to  get  rid  of  mere  me- 
morising.    The  example  of  Socrates  was  followed,  and  attempts 


164  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

made  to  educe  the  unknown  from  the  known,  a  procedure  only 
possible  when  the  "  known  "  already  contains  the  germ  of  the 
"unknown,"  and  impossible  of  application  to  subjects  which 
rest  on  experience.  This,  in  reality  the  catechetical  method, 
conforms  to  Ziller's  own  requirements. 

The  Herbartian  terminology  is  new,  but  the  facts  it  stands  for 
have  long  been  known.  Knowledge  is  for  life,  not  for  school. 
We  must  begin  with  Anschauung  (Intuition  or  Observation), 
and  go  on  to  Conception  ;  we  must  proceed  from  particulars  to 
generals.  Alike  in  the  catechetical  and  in  the  Herbartian  pro- 
cedure this  is  recognised,  and  likewise  a  final  stage,  that  of 
AppUcation.  The  catechetical  method  itself  is  not  to  blame  if, 
in  religious  teaching,  this  valid  principle  is  not  recognised ;  the 
fault  lies  with  tradition  and  authority. 

Ziller  divided  Anschauung  into  two  stages,  and  Abstraction 
into  two  also.  But  there  is  no  new  discovery  in  this.  Still,  the 
Herbartians  can  teach  us  something  here,  especially  with  regard 
to  history  and  religion,  subjects  in  which  there  are  often  given 
too  few  sense-impressions.  Ziller's  formal  steps  must  be  used 
with  great  discretion. 

Ziller  proposed  that  history  should  first  be  read  from  books, 
in  order  that  a  grasp  of  the  whole  story  might  be  acquired  ;  that 
then  the  history  should  be  gone  through  again,  this  time  from 
the  point  of  view  of  geography  and  the  history  of  culture  ;  and 
that  then  finally  the  psychological,  ethical,  and  religious  side  of 
the  narrative  should  be  considered  in  the  course  of  a  third 
perusal.  But  Dorpfeld  is  surely  right  in  claiming  that  the  oral 
teaching  of  new  matter  is  better  than  acquisition  from  books. 

The  catechetical  method  has  doubtless  been  too  abstract,  and 
has  not  paid  sufficient  attention  to  Anschauung,  and  to  number 
of  instances.  The  formal  steps  have  the  advantage  of  not 
overlooking  anything.  But  they  occasionally  verge  on  the 
unnecessary  ;  thus,  the  third  and  fourth  stages  lie  so  close 
together  that  they  scarcely  need  to  be  distinguished ;  com- 
parison of  several  objects  and  the  grasping  of  the  common 
features  are  so  closely  connected  that  to  make  of  them  two 
distinct  stages  would  conduce  to  weariness.     It  is  right  enough 


Drews  165 

to  compare  the  conflict  between  Gregory  VII.  and  Henry  IV. 
of  Germany  with  that  between  Samuel  and  Saul  ("Association" 
stage) ;  but  a  further  stage  ("  System  ")  is  scarcely  called  for. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  fifth  stage  ("  Application  ")  is  quite 
suitable,  though  when  cases  of  "  imaginary  action  "  are  being 
considered,  it  is  important  that  these  cases  be  not  too  remote, 
otherwise  the  procedure  degenerates  into  mere  babble.  In 
sum,  the  catechetical  method  may  well  make  a  discreet  use  of 
the  formal  steps. 

The  Zillerians  do  not  attack  questioning  •per  se,  for  they 
approve  of  a  method  of  discussion  or  disputation  (question  and 
answer).  What  they  object  to  in  the  catechetical  method  is 
that,  being  a  method  logically  developed  and  working  towards 
a  goal  chosen  by  the  teacher,  the  procedure  is  artificial,  and 
the  answers  of  the  children  spurious.  It  is  this  logical  sequence 
which  the  Zillerians  attack,  as  a  sequence  only  understood  by 
the  teacher,  not  by  the  pupil  himself.  All  acts  of  will  are 
directed  to  a  goal,  but  there  is  here  no  goal  before  the  pupil. 
The  Zillerians,  therefore,  rightly  contend  that  every  lesson  must 
have  its  goal  clearly  known  from  the  first,  and  advocates  of  the 
catechetical  method  may  learn  something  from  them. 

Another  objection  is  that  the  catechetical  method  does  not 
take  account  of  the  mental  condition  of  the  individual  child.  It 
is  the  teacher's  course  of  thought  that  is  followed.  Ziller's  plan, 
on  the  other  hand,  is  for  the  teacher  only  "  formally  "  to  lead 
the  talk,  entering  in  when  there  is  confusion  and  hesitation. 

But  this  objection  is  somewhat  exaggerated.  A  good  teacher 
will,  during  his  catechetical  procedure,  allow  children  to  discuss 
various  points :  "  What  do  you  think  of  that  ?  "  he  will  ask. 
But  it  is  doubtful  whether  there  is  any  need  of  so  minute  a 
consideration  of  each  child's  individual  nature  as  the  Zillerians 
suppose.  Experience  decides  here ;  and  so  long  as  children  are 
zealous  and  interested  the  method  cannot  have  been  unsuccess- 
ful. Ziller  under-estimates  the  rapidity  and  agility  of  the  child's 
mental  processes,  and  his  method  of  discussion  or  disputation 
would  really  be  one  of  laborious  weariness. 

In  short,  the  ZiUerians  should  not  break  with  the  past,  but 
rather  build  upon  it,  and  improve  it. 


1 66  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

SECTION  X. 

CHRISTINGER. 

(1895.) 

'Reference. 
Christinger.     Friedrich  Herbart's  Erziehungslehre  und  ihre  Fortbilder 
bis  auf  die  Gegenwart,  nach  den  Quellschriften  dargesteUt  und  beurteilt. 
Schulthess,  Zurich,  1895. 

The  above,  by  a  Swiss  educationist  who  claims  to  be  a 
"neutral"  in  the  Herbart-Ziller  controversy,  is  one  of  the 
sanest  and  most  judicious  works  with  which  the  writer  is 
acquainted. 

It  deals  biographically  with  Herbart  and  Ziller ;  discusses  the 
contributions  of  each  to  pedagogical  science  ;  passes  judgment 
without  any  signs  of  prejudice ;  gives  information  relative  to  the 
other  leading  exponents  of  Herbartianism ;  touches  briejfly  upon 
its  chief  opponents  ;  and  finally  gives  a  few  specimen  lessons 
on  Herbartian  lines. 

Critique  of  Herbart's  Pedagogy. — It  does  not  pay  sufiBcient 
attention  to  physical  education.  We  must  regard  man's  nature 
as  a  whole. 

Female  education  has  to  some  extent  special  ends — narrower 
than  those  of  man — in  view.     Herbart  scarcely  recognises  this. 

Education  for  the  practical  duties  of  life  is  neglected.  Unless 
children  are  successful  in  the  struggle  for  existence  their  mental 
and  moral  life  cannot  thrive.  Herbart  inadequately  recognises 
the  poverty  and  effort  which  are  the  lot  of  the  poor. 

Instead  of  aiming  at  "many-sided  balanced  Interest"  we 
must  recognise  that,  for  the  sake  of  efficiency,  a  single  interest 
must,  as  a  rule,  be  allowed  to  predominate,  though  it  may  not 
exclude  others. 

No  doubt  aesthetic  judgments  influence  character  and  act  as 
motives.  But  some  natures  are  rougher  than  others,  and  cer- 
tainly  there   are   two   other   things  which   influence  character 


Chrt  stinger  167 

profoundly — self-interest  and  religion.  Herbart  recognises  the 
force  of  religion,  but  not  of  Christianity  in  particular.  He  sees 
that  a  sense  of  humility  is  necessary,  but  scarcely  thinks  of 
making  "  children  of  God "  inspired  by  a  love  of  God.  Nay 
he  even  hands  over  the  richest  province  of  instruction  to 
theologians. 

One  cannot  admit  that  Herbart  was  ignorant  of  childhood  ;  he 
learnt  more  in  the  four  years  of  his  Steiger  tutorship  than  many 
men  would  learn  in  a  far  longer  time.  But  he  was  too  far 
removed  from  the  working  classes  and  their  cares ;  his  circle  was 
the  circle  of  the  cultured. 

But  his  excellences  outweigh  his  defects.  No  doubt  Education 
has  other  aims  than  Virtue  in  the  narrow  sense  ;  still  if  we  want 
one  word  to  describe  its  aim  "  Virtue  "  is  the  best;  it  will  then 
signify  all  human  excellences  of  understanding  and  disposition. 
We  must  not  only  give  knowledge,  we  must  educate ;  for  mere 
knowledge  leads  to  evil  unless  morality  be  uppermost.  Herbart 
has  convincingly  shown  how  presentations  come  to  the  help  of 
character,  and  how  they  are  far  more  important  than  punish- 
ments, etc.  But  he  never  worked  out  thoroughly  the  question 
of  habit. 

His  plan  of  "  formal  steps  "  is  also  of  imperishable  value, 
though  mechanical  teachers  may  abuse  it. 

Critiqtie  of  Ziller. — Ziller  had  more  practical  experience  than 
Herbart.  He  admitted  the  existence  of  innate  dispositions — 
which  Herbart  tended  to  deny  ;  he  urged  the  unity  of  moral 
and  religious  education,  and  regarded  Jesus  Christ  as  the  ideal 
which  we  should  place  before  us.  Ziller's  proposals  were  some- 
times right,  sometimes  wrong,  but  generally  both. 

He  was  wrong  when,  for  example,  he  deprecated  preparing 
children  for  the  tasks  of  practical  life.^  We  must  not  neglect 
this,  however  great  the  stress  we  lay  on  character-forming. 

His  schemes  of  small  school-communities,  and  of  schools  for 
distinct  social  groups,  were  retrograde. 

In  the  following  particulars  he  was  partly  right,  partly  wrong : — 

^  Except  in  the  upper  classes  of  schools. 


1 68  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

In  substituting  five  "  formal  steps  "  for  Herbart's  four  he 
was  right ;  but  there  is  some  danger  of  making  the  first  step 
too  lengthy  or  artificial.  Still  it  is  right  to  begin,  as  a  rule, 
with  analysis  :  "  from  known  to  unknown  ".  But  we  cannot 
always  state  the  goal  of  the  lesson ;  it  would  be  a  mere  word 
to  our  pupils.  Often  it  is  best  to  give  the  concrete  object  before 
the  name. 

As  to  "Concentration,"  Ziller  was  right  in  putting  character- 
forming  in  the  foreground.  Let  us  give  the  best  hours  of  the 
day  to  it,  and  let  us  throw  light  upon  it  from  all  departments  of 
study.  But  we  must  not  so  use  character-forming  instruction 
as  to  deprive  other  departments  of  their  own  claims.  If  we 
teach  arithmetic,  geography,  etc.,  in  connection,  e.g.,  with  biblical 
history,  the  former  subjects  will  be  unjustly  treated,  and  great 
gaps  will  be  left  in  them.  Moreover,  the  children  will  get  tired 
if  the  same  central  material  is  served  up  daily. 

The  fundamental  idea  of  "  culture  stages  "  is  right,  but  Ziller 's 
working-out  is  fantastical.  It  is  not  true  that  the  epic  fable  first 
occupied  the  mind  of  man  ;  the  religious  myth  was  still  earlier. 
Moreover,  mankind  as  a  race  was  never  in  Eobinson  Crusoe's 
condition,  with  his  advanced  knowledge  of  civilisation.  Further, 
neither  the  fables  nor  the  story  of  Crusoe  have  such  moral  value 
as  to  be  made  a  basis  of  "  character-forming  Instruction  ".  On 
the  other  hand,  the  life  of  Christ  requires  two  years  at  least. 

In  point  of  fact,  the  first  "  culture  stage  "  (properly  so  called) 
was  probably  the  one  when  men  first  began  to  care  for  the 
beautiful.  Before  this  time  they  thought  only  of  the  necessary, 
and  could  scarcely  be  regarded  as  possessing  culture  at  all. 
Later  came  care  for  the  useful — the  second  "  culture  stage ;  " 
later  again,  the  stage  of  seeking  truth;  still  later,  care  for  the 
Kingdom  of  God,  the  realisation  of  the  moral  ideal.  But  through 
the  later  stages  the  earlier  ones  still  persist. 

Some  pupils  are  more  talented  than  others  ;  girls  are  quicker 
than  boys ;  thus  the  stages  are  run  through  more  quickly  in  some 
cases  than  in  others. 

Ziller  is  right  in  claiming  that  in  schools  only  scientific  facts — 
not  hasty  theories — should  be  taught.    He  is  also  right  in  urging 


Bergemann  169 

that  pupils  in  the  upper  classes  of  a  school  should  be  trained  for 
the  definite  professional  duties  of  life.  [Still,  schools  must 
"  educate  "  ;  that  is  Ziller's  main  contention.] 

Above  all  he  is  right  in  his  goal.  Education  must  be  real ; 
must  rouse  activities  ;  must  form  character  and  power.  Mental 
culture  will  not  hurt  morality,  but  will  rather  help  it.  The  work 
of  education  is  to  implant  many  germs,  not  to  let  the  child  grow 
out  of  one,  as  Frobel  supposed. 


SECTION  XI. 

BERGEMANN. 

(1897.) 

Beferem-ces. 

(1)  Die  Lehre  von  den  formalen  und  den  Kultur-historischen  Stufen  und 
von  der  Kcmcentration  im  Lichte  der  unbefangenen  Wissenschaft  (Haacke, 
Leipzig,  1897). 

(2)  Der  entwickelnd-darstellende  Unterricht,  Neue  Bahnen,  1897,  p.  156. 

(3)  Die  Fabel  vom  ErzieJienden  Unterricht,  Die  Lehrerin,  1897,  p.  306. 

The  attainment  of  a  certain  degree  of  freshness  in  dealing 
critically  with  Herbartianism  may  be  placed  to  the  credit  of 
Dr.  Bergemann,  of  Jena. 

In  the  third  of  the  above  he  dismisses  "  educative  Instruc- 
tion "  as  a  mere  "fable".  Herbart's  psychology  is  exploded, 
and  no  longer  are  we  able  to  identify  Education  with  Instruction. 
There  is  really  no  proportion  between  many-sided  Interest  and 
Intelligence  on  the  one  side,  and  Virtue  or  Morality  on  the 
other.  Morality  is  only  one  aim  of  Education.  Where  is  the 
connection  between  morals  and  mathematics  ? 

What  does  science  say  ?  Is  human  nature  so  simple  that  it 
can  be  brought  under  one  formula  ?  Surely  man  is  a  product 
of  at  least  three  factors — heredity,  environment,  and  individual 
variation  ;  and  his  mind  is  complex  also,  functioning  in  three 
ways — Presentation,  Feeling,  Will.    Education  is  a  part  of  one's 


i7o  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

environment,  but  there  are  the  other  two  factors  (heredity  and 
variation)  over  which  no  control  can  be  exercised. 

The  first  thing  for  the  teacher  to  do  is  to  know  the  innate 
constitution  of  his  pupils.  With  regard  to  the  three  mental 
functions  there  may  be  great  differences  in  different  people. 
Presentation,  Feeling,  and  Will  do  not  stand  in  any  relation  to 
each  other.  Hence  it  is  absurd  to  talk  of  the  last  two  as  being 
modifications  of  presentations. 

"  Educative  Instruction,"  the  culture  of  the  thought-circle  so 
as  to  form  character,  is  a  fable.  The  teacher  must  look  after 
Feeling  and  Will,  as  well  as  the  thought-circle.  In  other  words, 
he  must  train  as  well  as  teach.  Teaching  may  give  prudence, 
but  cannot  make  men  better.  Morality  cannot  be  taught.  The 
main  thing  to  look  after  in  character-forming  is  Habit,  and 
connected  with  this,  reward,  punishment,  intercourse,  and 
example.^ 

The  Herbartians  mix  up  the  several  distinct  tasks  of  Educa- 
tion. Moral  Education  is  different  from  intellectual.  Action 
really  springs  out  of  the  depths  of  Feeling,  Impulse,  and  Will. 
These  are  independent  of  presentations.  Herbartianism  is  a 
bad  preparation  for  the  hour  of  trial.  What  is  the  good  of 
theoretical  morality  ? 

The  second  of  the  above  productions  deals  with  ' '  developing 
presentative  Instruction  "  which  the  Herbartians  prefer  to 
Instruction  in  the  form  of  narrative.  Pupils  must  be  encouraged 
by  gentle  hints  to  huild  up  the  material.  Thus  they  are  pro- 
ductively active,  instead  of  being  mere  recipients  of  information. 

But  (asks  Bergemann)  is  the  method  so  very  valuable  after  all? 
Surely,  when  a  pupil  listens  to  a  teacher  he  must  attend,  and 
this  is  a  form  of  mental  activity.  Moreover,  he  has  to  exercise 
his  imagination  actively  in  order  to  follow  the  teacher's  account. 
Herbartians  say  that  their  method  causes  more  pleasure  than 

1  This  argument  means  that  Herbartianism  is  nonsense,  and  that  the 
circle  of  thought  has  no  influence  on  character.  But  surely  it  is  not  nonsense. 
Though  Habit,  etc.,  are  important,  they  will  only  conduce  to  conservative 
Morality.    Moral  insight  must  be  aroused,  and  this  necessitates  "  teaching  ". 


Bergemann  171 

the  other;  but  surely  this  will  depend  on  the  teacher's  tact. 
Both  methods  may  be  useful. 

For  what  subjects  do  the  Herbartians  use  it  ?  Nature- 
knowledge,  geography,  history,  poetry. 

But  surely  in  the  case  of  nature-knowledge  it  is  far  better  to 
use  concrete  olives,  or,  at  least,  pictures  of  olives,  than  to  try  to 
build  up  the  notion  of  an  olive  through  imagination  !  ^  So  in  the 
case  of  geography  and  history  we  must  use  concrete  experience, 
pictures,  etc.,  as  much  as  possible,  otherwise  we  shall  merely 
encourage  lawlessness. 

But  the  method  is  useful  in  dealing  with  poetry,  for  here 
imagination  may  be  allowed  to  have  much  free  play,  and  facts 
are  at  a  discount. 

The  main  question  is,  whether  it  is  better  to  give  to  the  pupil 
the  image  or  to  let  him  build  it  up  for  himself.  The  Herbartians 
say,  "  The  latter,  because  in  this  way  activity  is  roused  ".  But 
surely  it  is  also  roused  when  the  child  has  to  attend.  The 
proposed  method  compels  the  child  to  attend  to  matter  and  form 
at  the  same  time — too  great  a  task.  In  fact,  the  proposed 
method,  though  not  without  its  uses,  can  easily  be  overdone. 

The  first  of  the  above  works  is  the  most  important. 

Bergemann  holds  that  the  Herbartians  neglect  formal  educa- 
tion, and  lay  most  stress  upon  heaping  up  knowledge.  Surely 
we  must  develop  the  intellectual  capacity  as  such,  and  here 
language,  as  connected  with  general  notions,  is  of  great  im- 
portance. Similarly,  it  is  important  to  cultivate  the  habit  of 
attention." 

The  "formal  steps"  are  useful,  but  must  not  be  used  slavishly. 
It  is  right  to  give  the  goal  of  the  lesson  at  the  beginning.  But 
the  Herbartians  ignore  the  value  of  repetition. 


^  Eight.  Pestalozzi  and  some  modem  Herbartians  would  here  be  at 
"  daggers  drawn  ". 

^Thus,  while  Herbart  thinks  highly  of  involuntary  attention,  Berge- 
mann lays  more  stress  on  voluntary,  as  having  more  significance  for 
character-forming  purposes. 


172  The  Critics  of  Herbariianism 

The  doctrine  of  "  culture  stages  "  is  defective  in  many  ways, 
though  no  doubt  it  represents  a  grain  of  truth. 

Man  was  once  a  cave-dweller.  Does  the  child  go  through  this 
stage  of  development  ?  If  so,  at  exactly  what  age  ?  According 
to  Ziller's  scheme,  the  child  passes  in  twelve  months  from  the 
nomadic  stage  to  the  next,  and  when  he  has  arrived  at  the  age 
of  fifteen  he  stands  at  the  stage  of  present-day  civilisation  !  In 
fourteen  years  he  has  recapitulated  the  history  of  the  race  ! 

At  the  age  of  six  he  is  at  the  fable  stage.  But  this  is  no  real 
stage  of  human  progress  at  all,  and  if  it  were  one,  it  would  be 
far  below  the  patriarchal. 

During  the  first  six  years  (i.e.,  before  he  goes  to  school)  he 
apparently  makes  no  progress  at  all,  while  in  the  eight  years  of 
school  life  he  passes  through  all  the  stages  from  remote  antiquity 
to  the  present  day  ! 

How  absurd  to  allow  a  child  at  the  fable  stage  to  read,  write, 
and  calculate,  if  this  stage  were  a  real  one  through  which 
primitive  man  once  passed  !  The  fables  are  devoid  of  moral 
value,  and  would  also  soon  become  wearisome. 

For  the  second  school  year  the  Zillerians  prefer  Eobinson 
Crusoe  (excluding  the  Bible).  This  is  to  cast  out  Satan  by 
means  of  Beelzebub. 

Is  the  parallelism  doctrine  really  true  ?  Great  men  may 
invent  wonderful  doctrines,  but,  after  all,  science  has  to  decide 
upon  their  truth.  And  science  decides  that  the  parallelism  be- 
tween race  and  individual  is  run  through  mainly  in  the 
embryonic  stage  of  the  individual.  As  soon  as  the  child  is 
born  he  is  ready  to  seize  hold  of  the  modern  world  which  lies 
around  him ;  he  is  not  at  some  pre-historic  cannibal  stage. 
Hence,  instead  of  the  teacher  trying  to  transplant  the  child  back 
into  a  long-vanished  past,  he  should  begin  with  the  concrete 
world,  and  only  subsequently  work  back  to  past  ages  when  the 
child's  curiosity  about  them  is  aroused.  The  Herbartians  claim 
that  the  past  is  simpler  and  more  fundamental  than  the  present. 
Not  so.  The  child  lives  in  the  present,  acquires  the  speech  of 
the  present,  learns  about  the  persons,  buildings,  etc.,  of  the 
present.     Thus  the   present  should    be  the   starting  point,  and 


Linde 


173 


imagination  must  build  on  this.  There  must  be  no  exaggerated 
stress  on  history ;  science  has  changed  all  views. 

Then  as  to  "  concentration  ".  This  rests  on  false  metaphysics, 
and  does  not  really  conduce  to  unity  of  character.  The  really 
natural  method  is  that  of  "  concentric  circles,"  a  plan  which  the 
Herbartians  object  to  as  conducing  to  weariness.  But  do 
children  really  weary  of  their  surroundings?  No,  they  gradually 
learn  more  and  more  about  them.  Home,  country,  etc.,  come 
to  be  loved.  Character  rests  on  Will,  Feeling,  etc.,  not  on 
Thought.  The  Herbartians  seem  to  think  that  giving  an  ideal 
is  the  only  thing  necessary ;  surely  training  is  more  important. 

Again,  the  Herbartians  refuse  to  approve  of  moral  instruction 
apart  from  religious.  This  is  a  mistake.  It  involves  that 
morality  is  not  the  same  for  all,  but  varies  according  to  sect. 
Moreover,  men  have  come  to  regard  the  God  of  Sinai  as  a  myth, 
and  thus  morals  are  in  danger  of  being  pulled  down  along  with 
religion. 


SECTION  XII. 

LINDE. 

(1899.) 

Reference. 
Linde.     Der  darstsllende  Unterricht  nach  den  Qrundsatzen  der  Herbart- 
ZillerscJien  Schule  und  vom  Standpunkte  des  Nicht-Herbartianers.     Brand- 
stetter,  Leipzig,  1899. 

This  is  an  able  and  impartial  discussion  of  the  so-called  method 
of  "  developing-presentative  Instruction  "  which  many  of  the 
Herbartians  prefer  to  the  method  of  description  and  narration. 
Instead  of  the  teacher  telling  and  describing,  he  leads  on  the 
pupils  by  suggestion,  illustration,  and  question  to  construct  for 
themselves  the  whole  scene  or  object  under  discussion.  This 
plan  is  supposed  to  encourage  mental  activity,  fluency  of  speech, 
and  other  desiderabilia. 

Linde  gives  an  account  of  the  views  of  Herbart,  Ziller,  and 
others  upon  this  question,  and  then  expresses  his  own  opinion. 


174  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

With  Herbart  there  were,  primarily,  two  kinds  of  instruction. 
One  kind  was  occupied  solely  with  widening  the  pupil's  know- 
ledge and  experience  ;  the  other  with  the  working  over  of  ex- 
istent stores  of  knowledge  so  as  to  arrive  at  general  relations. 
The  first  was  "  merely  presentative,"  the  second  "  analytic  ". 
There  was  a  third  kind,  in  which  not  only  was  new  knowledge 
conferred,  but  this  was  also  worked  over  systematically.  It  gave 
certain  elements  and  then  elucidated  the  relations  between 
them.     Such  instruction  was  "  synthetic  ". 

"  Merely  presentative  "  instruction  was  of  the  nature  of  "  tell- 
ing "  or  "describing".  It  might  take  the  form  of  an  informal 
talk,  for  the  living  voice  is  better  than  a  book.  Clearly  the  pupil 
must,  in  such  a  case,  have  already  had  much  experience  of 
reality,  or  he  cannot  understand  the  teacher's  references  ;  more- 
over, the  pupil's  vocabulary  must  correspond  to  his  experiences. 
If  his  vocabulary  be  narrow,  how  can  he  properly  appreciate  the 
teacher's  instruction? 

Ziller  uses  the  terms  "  analysis  "  and  "  synthesis  "  in  a  some- 
what different  way  from  his  master.  He  does  not  admit  that 
there  is  any  independent  "  analytical  "  method.  Analysis  is 
but  a  preparation  for  synthesis ;  it  is  the  first  of  the  "  formal 
steps  ".  The  pupil  is  led  to  search  among  his  already-acquired 
ideas  (analysis),  as  these  are  necessary  elements  in  the  appercep- 
tion of  new  ones  (synthesis).  In  Ziller's  "  analysis  "  there  is 
no  aiming  at  universal  principles  or  relations.  It  merely  reveals 
to  the  educator  the  already  acquired  knowledge  of  the  scholar. 
Similarly,  Ziller's  "synthesis"  involves  no  aiming  at  universal 
principles,  but  only  the  giving  of  concrete  material.^ 

Both  Herbart  and  Ziller  lay  stress  on  Association  and  System 
for  the  elaboration  of  new  ideas.  But  Ziller  lays  far  more  stress 
than  Herbart  on  the  relation  borne  by  the  already  possessed 
knowledge  to  the  new  material.     This  distinction  is  important. 

Ziller,  aiming  at  making  the  far-off  and  remote  vividly  known, 
sees  the  importance  of  using  the  knowledge  already  possessed. 


^  These  distinctions  desen-e  to  be  kept  in  mind  by  the  student  of  Herbart 
and  Ziller,  otherwise  much  confusion  is  likely  to  arise. 


Linde  175 

Thus  the  ideas  of  Sago  and  the  Eeed  Palm  can  be  obtained  by 
help  of  hothouse  varieties  as  a  basis.  Herbart  would  also  lead 
to  the  unknown  by  means  of  the  known,  but  he  laid  greater  stress 
than  Ziller  on  the  value  of  a  fluent,  inspiring  narrative  or  descrip- 
tion by  the  teacher.  The  blending  of  old  with  new  takes  place 
quietly  and  spontaneously  ;  but  to  Ziller  the  process  is  conscious, 
logical,  methodical.  The  process  of  appropriating  the  new  takes 
place  under  the  eyes  of  the  teacher,  who  has  gone  down  into  the 
soul  of  the  pupil,  brought  latent  ideas  to  light,  and  thus  illuminated 
what  is  new  and  strange.  This  is  Ziller's  "  presentative  In- 
struction ;"  it  makes  a  special  art  of  the  union  of  analysis  with 
synthesis. 

While  Herbart  thought  highly  of  narrative  and  description — 
the  method  of  monologue — Ziller  thought  more  of  dialogue  or 
conversation.  New  facts  are  not  to  be  told  to  the  child,  but  are 
to  be  led  up  to  from  those  he  already  knows.  Instead  of  saying, 
"  Joseph  and  Mary  went  south,"  the  teacher  says,  "Joseph  and 
Mary  went  in  the  same  direction  as  if  we  went  to  Bavaria  "  ; 
thereupon  the  children  will  say,  "  To  the  south  ".  Instead  of 
describing  in  his  own  words  the  inundations  of  the  Nile,  he 
leads  up  to  them,  and  then,  examining  the  map,  asks,  "  WiU  all 
Egypt  be  inundated  ?  "  Discovering  that  high  land  bounds  the 
Nile  valley,  the  children  will  decide  that  this  land  will  remain 
uncovered.  "  Where  are  the  people  likely  to  build  their 
houses  ?  "  On  this  high  land.  And  thus  the  class  develops 
the  subject,  and  finally  narrates  the  facts  arrived  at. 

The  "developing"  method  is  said  to  arouse  the  self-activity 
of  the  pupil  to  a  high  degree.  Children  construct  history.  Their 
wills  and  characters  are  supposed  to  be  influenced  by  the  method 
far  more  than  by  the  narrative  and  descriptive  method  of  Her- 
bart. The  teacher  should  never  do  what  the  scholar  himself  can 
perform.  The  pupil  must  deliberate,  and  state  his  own  ques- 
tions. Ziller  claimed  that  this  method  of  "  disputation  "  rouses 
keen  interest  and  joy,  and  also  conduces  greatly  to  fluency  of 
speech  on  the  part  of  the  pupils.  The  method  is  also  said  to 
bring  difficulties  easily  to  light  and  to  promote  co-operation. 

Ziller  and  his  friends  {e.g.,  Eein)  attack  the  descriptive  and 


176  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

narrative  method  as  being  defective  in  the  respects  just  indi- 
cated. This  last  method  is  supposed  to  check  the  activity  of 
the  pupils,  and  the  teacher  can  never  be  certain  that  the  pupils 
fully  grasp  or  apperceive  what  he  tells  them.  The  child  may 
join  false  ideas  to  what  the  teacher  says. 

But  in  point  of  fact,  though  the  "  developing"  method  some- 
times has  its  advantages,  the  "narrative  "  method  has  its  advan- 
tages also,  and  these  often  balance  the  others. 

The  aim  of  both  methods  is  to  represent  vividly  to  the  pupil's 
mind  something  not  actually  present,  e.g.,  a  palm,  %  storm  at  sea, 
an  historical  event. 

Now  often  the  narrative  or  descriptive  method  is  good  for  this 
purpose.  Men  like  Foltz  and  Dorpfeld  lay  stress  on  the  inspir- 
ing power  of  warm  and  eloquent  delivery,  and  the  latter  writer 
has  urged  that  there  are  moments  so  solemn  that  any  break  in  the 
teacher's  story  would  disturb  the  whole  process  of  apperception. 
The  pupil  must  simply  listen  in  silent  sympathy.  A  quiet  state 
like  this  is  often  highly  productive  ;  our  best  thoughts  then 
come,  and  the  ego  is  systematised  and  organised.  Speech  at 
such  a  moment  would  actually  check  the  creative  current.  The 
method  of  disputation  might  conduce  to  a  kind  of  outward  ac- 
tivity, but  the  depths  of  the  nature  might  be  unaffected.  There 
are  always  times  when  the  narrative  method  is  the  better  one  ; 
and  there  are  reserved  natures  which  cannot  express  themselves 
outwardly.  A  child  listening  to  a  narrative  is  active  in  a  sense, 
while  the  "much  speaking"  encouraged  by  the  "developing" 
method  is  no  clear  proof  of  deep  thought. 

The  "  developing  "  method  has  dangers  of  its  own.  It  shows 
a  tendency  to  bring  about  false  conjectures  or  guessing,  especi- 
ally in  the  case  of  young  children,  who,  not  yet  possessing  full 
power  to  combine  thought,  often  miss  the  crucial  point  of  the 
lesson. 

The  method  often  causes  many  ideas  to  be  summoned  up 
where  only  one  is  necessary.  In  order  to  lead  on  to  some  result 
(e.gr.,  the  image  of  a  foreign  product)  a  whole  series  of  objects 
are  called  to  mind.  The  teacher's  illustrations  may  not  really 
appeal  to  the  child  as  nearly  as  he  supposes.     It  may  have  been 


Linde  xii 

far  better  for  the  teacher  to  narrate  and  describe  and  let  the  child 
interpret  the  narrative  or  description  spontaneously,  using  his 
own  mental  resources.  In  fact,  the  teacher  cannot  control  the 
apperception  of  the  pupil  so  much  as  he  may  think. 

If  the  teacher  describes  or  narrates  with  vividness,  the  child 
will  readily  apperceive  the  new,  investing  it  with  familiarity  ac- 
cording to  his  own  knowledge.  This  may  be  a  better  plan  than 
a  piecemeal  method  of  disputation  and  dialogue. 

Another  difficulty  of  the  "  developing  "  method  is  that  the 
thoughts  uttered  by  one  child  may  not  resemble  those  of  the 
other  children. 

Again,  the  method  makes  very  great  demands  on  the  skill  of 
the  teacher. 

It  is  often  best  for  the  teacher  just  to  let  the  new  matter  have 
its  own  silent  course. 

Does  the  "  developing "  method  really  conduce  to  fluent 
speech  ?  Schmidt,  Dorpfeld,  and  others  have  denied  this.  A 
vivid  narrative  sets  forth  right  forms  of  speech  as  samples ;  these 
sink  into  the  child's  mind,  and  are  really  more  effective  than  the 
repartee  encouraged  by  the  "developing"  method. 

Hence  one  arrives  at  the  conclusion  that  though  the  "  develop- 
ing "  method  is  often  useful,  its  excellencies  are  shared  by  the 
other  method,  and  this  latter  has  certain  advantages  of  its  own. 
Hence  an  alternation  of  the  two  may  be  advisable. 

A  Few  Further  Points. -^There  is  some  difference  of  opinion 
among  Zillerians  as  to  whether  the  last  three  "  formal  steps  " 
should  be  regarded  as  belonging  to  presentative  instruction,  or 
whether  this  instruction  does  not  end  with  concrete  "  synthesis  " 
(the  second  step).  This  last  was  Ziller's  view  ;  the  processes  of 
abstraction  are  no  part  of  presentative  instruction. 

In  addition  to  the  dialogue  method,  Ziller  recommended  the 
extensive  use  of  reading.  Bible  history  had  to  be  taught  by  these 
means. 

In  very  many  cases,  instead  of  using  the  "  developing "  or 
the  narrative  methods,  the  best  plan  is  to  present  the  object 
itself,  or  a  picture  of  it,  to  the  pupils. 

12 


17^  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

SECTION  XIII. 

NATORP. 

(1899.) 

GAie/  'References. 

(1)  Natorp,  Herbart,  Pestalozzi  und  die  heutigen  Aufgaben  der  Erzie- 
hungslehre,  1899.     Fromman,  Stuttgart. 

(2)  Fliigel,  Just ,  and  Rein,  "  Herbart,  Pestalozzi  und  Herr  Professor 
Paul  Natorp".  Zeitschrift  filr  Philosophie  und  Pddagogik.  4th  vol. 
1899. 

(3)  Willmann,  "Der  Neukantianismus  gegen  Herbarts  Padagogik". 
Zeitschrift  filr  Phil,  und  Pad.     2nd  vol.     1899. 

(4)  Willmann,  "  Uber  Socialpadagogik ".  Jahi-btich  des  Vereins  filr 
wissenschaftliche  Padagogik.     1899. 

(5)  Natorp,  "  Kant  oder  Herbart  ?  Eine  Gegenkritik."  Die  Deutsche 
Schule.     July  and  August,  1899. 

One  of  the  most  recent,  and  in  many  respects  the  most  interest- 
ing, of  the  many  attacks  upon  Herbartianism  has  come  from  the 
philosophical  chair  of  Marburg.  Professor  Paul  Natorp  is  no 
neophytic  opponent  of  presentational  philosophy.  An  avowed 
follower  of  the  "transcendental"  movement  inaugurated  by 
Kant ;  an  author  of  works  upon  the  theory  of  knowledge ;  ^ 
editor  of  the  neo-Kantian  Philosophische  Monatshefte,  and  a 
frequent  contributor  to  its  pages,^  Professor  Natorp  has  long 
been  in  occupation  of  a  philosophical  standpoint  removed  toto 
coelo  from  that  of  Herbartianism.  A  criticism  from  such  a 
source  is  bound  to  be  far-reaching,  bound  to  assail  psychological 
principles  even  though  leaving  details  and  consequences  un- 
challenged. Such  indeed  is  the  nature  of  the  present  attack. 
It  assails  the  supposed  foundations  of  Herbartianism,  and  only 
touches  incidentally  upon  the  deductions  and  applications  of 
the  system. 

^  Descartes  Erkenntnisstheorie,  1882 ;  Forschungen  zur  Oeschichte  des 
Erkervntnissproblems  im  Alterthum,  1884, 

2"Einleitung  in  die  Psychologie  nach  Kritischer  Methods,"  1888; 
"  Analekten  zur  Geschichte  der  Philosophie,"  1882. 


Natorp  179 

The  controversy  initiated  (or  rather  resuscitated)  by  Professor 
Natorp  is  but  one  phase  of  the  controversy  which  perennially 
divides  philosophers  into  sharply  opposed  classes — the  con- 
troversy between  Spiritualism  and  Materialism,  Idealism  and 
Empiricism,  Spontaneity  and  Mechanism.  Though  Herbart  was 
no  materialist,  his  principles  have  a  greater  affinity  with  a 
thoroughly  mechanical  (if  not  materialistic)  view  of  the  universe 
than  with  the  opposite  views.  Presentationalist  he  was,  in  an 
emphatic  sense,  and  Presentationalism  is  an  ally  (though  a 
treacherous  one)  of  Materialism.  On  the  question  of  the  Free- 
dom of  the  Will,  Herbart's  attitude  was  likewise  quite  unam- 
biguous ;  he  was  avowedly  a  determinist.^  No  wonder  therefore 
that  Natorp,  a  Kantian  or  neo-Kantian,  devoted  to  the  ter- 
minology if  not  to  the  cause  of  Libertarianism,  could  see  little 
to  approve  of  in  the  principles  of  Herbart. 

Upon  the  central  problem  thus  indicated,  there  appears  no 
likelihood  of  a  philosophical  consensus.  Every  man,  we  are 
told,  is  born  either  a  Platonist  or  an  Aristotelian,  either  a 
Libertarian  or  a  Determinist,  we  may  even  say,  either  a  Nator- 
pian  or  an  Herbartian,  according  as  his  interests  and  impulses 
are  directed  to  the  active  and  moral  or  to  the  speculative  and 
natural  worlds.  Not,  of  course,  that  Herbart  was  indifferent  to 
moral  problems.  His  educational  system  is  pervaded  through 
and  through  by  a  sense  of  their  supreme  importance,  a  sense  so 
extreme  that  Natorp  has  to  protest  against  the  supposed  neglect 
of  the  logical  and  aesthetic  factors.  But  whereas  Natorp's 
emphasis  is  constantly  laid  upon  the  inner  principle  of  self, 
Herbart  works  from  without  inwards,  and  thus  reveals  his 
metaphysical  affinity  with  Locke  and  Empiricism.  Whichever 
side  the  reader  may  take  in  this  interminable  controversy  of 
philosophy,  he  will  not  fail  to  admire  the  rigorous  consistency 
with  which  Herbart,  starting  from  the  presentational  standpoint, 
works  2  upwards  to  an  elaborate  system  and  downwards  to  a 
multitude  of  practical  applications. 

iHis  emphasis  on  the  idea  of  "Inner  Freedom"  does  not  conflict  with 
this  statement. 

2  Of  course  Herbart  recognises  a  "  Soul ".  But  virtually  the  presenta- 
tion, not  the  soul,  is  his  unit. 


i8o  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

No  small  fluttering  occurred  in  the  Herbartian  dove-cote  when 
Professor  Natorp's  attack  saw  the  light.  Previous  attacks  there 
had  been,  e.g.,  those  of  Vogel,  Dittes,  Ostermann,  to  say  nothing 
of  the  more  academic  criticisms  ^  to  which  all  systems  of  philo- 
sophy are  exposed.  But  Natorp's  attack  touched  Herbartians 
at  tender  places.  Their  master  was  a  "dogmatist";  he  was 
unable  to  "  develop  "  a  thought ;  he  could  neither  understand 
nor  appreciate  Pestalozzi,  though  he  tried  to  patronise  his 
memory ;  his  philosophical  followers  were  few  and  (what  was 
worse)  were  antiquated  "  veterans  "  ;  in  short,  Herbart  was 
overrated  and  his  followers  were  old-fashioned. 

It  was  no  wonder,  therefore,  that  the  Herbartians  responded 
with  vigour  to  the  attack  opened  upon  them.  No  better  intro- 
duction can  be  found  to  present-day  educational  problems  of 
the  philosophic  type  than  a  perusal  of  the  two  sides  of  this 
controversy. 

The  most  systematic  reply  to  Natorp  is  contained  in  the 
fourth  volume  of  the  Z eitschrift  filr  Philosophie  und  Pddagogik, 
1899.  As  if  to  disprove  the  charge  of  numerical  inferiority 
(a  charge  certainly  based  on  very  slight  grounds)  the  reply 
came  from  several  hands. 

Pastor  Flvigel,  certainly  a  "  veteran  "  in  the  defence  of  Her- 
bartianism (he  had  defended  it  against  the  previous  strictures 
of  Dittes  and  Ostermann),  replied  to  the  more  specially  psycho- 
logical side  of  Natorp's  attack.  Dr.  Just,  well  known  as  an 
active  writer  on  the  Herbartian  side  and  as  director  of  an 
important  school,  defended  Herbart's  Ethic.  The  discussion 
of  the  pedagogical  aspects  of  the  question  fell  to  the  task  of 
Professor  Eein.  But  in  a  system  such  as  Herbartianism,  in 
which  the  Psychology,  Ethics  and  Pedagogy  are  connected 
with  some  degree  of  closeness,  the  three  defenders  necessarily 
intruded  on  each  other's  domain,  especially  in  their  discussion 
of  the  Will. 

In  the  discussions  which  follow,  the  portions  indicated  by  the 
letter  (A)  are  expository  of  Natorp's  criticism,  those  by  (B)  give 

^  E.g.,  those  of  Lotze  and  Trendelenburg. 


Natorp  i8i 

the  Herbartian  reply,  while  those  indicated  by  (C)  are  remarks 
of  the  present  writer. 

(1)  The  (supposed)  parlous  state  of  Herbartianism. 

(A)  Professor  Natorp  declares  himself  not  blind  to  the  value 
of  the  Herbartian  system.  He  attributes  to  it  much  stimulating 
power,  many  detailed  excellences  (more  especially  in  the  realm 
of  practice),  and  considerable  utility  for  the  teacher  who  is 
beginning  his  work.  It  is  the  system  as  a  whole  which  he  con- 
demns, and  it  is  its  theoretical  and  philosophical  aspects  which 
alone  he  feels  competent  to  discuss.     [Natorp,  p.  1.]  ^ 

He  is  astonished  at  the  enormous  and  apparently  increasing 
influence  of  Herbart,  an  influence  perhaps  equal  to  that  of  all 
other  educational  writers  put  together.^  Each  age  has  its 
problems,  and  a  dogmatist  like  Herbart  is  not  the  best  guide  in 
face  of  the  onward  movement  of  mankind.     [2.] 

The  strange  thing  is  that  Herbart's  influence  on  education 
remains  paramount  although  the  philosophical  foundations  of  his 
system  have  been  almost  abandoned.  Scarcely  a  single  active 
professional  philosopher  is  an  Herbartian,  though  a  few  veterans 
still  exist.  Even  enthusiasts,  while  confident  of  the  strength  of 
the  structure  raised,  admit  that  its  foundations  are  in  need  of 
change.  In  view  of  the  fact  that  almost  all  German  philoso- 
phers have  touched  upon  education,  why  this  peculiar  confidence 
in  Herbart  ?     [4.] 

Firstly  because  of  the  earnest  interest  he  felt  in  education,  and 
the  prominent  place  it  occupies  in  his  system.  Kant  treated 
pedagogy  as  a  secondary  matter;  with  him,  moreover,  the 
necessary  psychology  is  almost  non-existent,  and  his  ethic  shows 
a  lack  of  immediate  practical  applicability.     Fichte's  principles 

1  The  pages  of  the  works  consulted  are  given  for  the  convenience  of 
those  who  wish  to  refer  to  the  originals. 

2  He  considers  that  instead  of  going  to  Herbart  we  should  go  (1)  for  the 
end  or  goal  of  education,  to  Kant ;  (2)  for  ways  and  methods,  to  Pestalozzi 
at  his  best ;  (3)  for  questions  of  organisation,  to  Pestalozzi,  Fichte  and 
Schleiermacher, 


1 82  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

are  far  removed  from  the  workaday  world  of  education. 
Schleiermacher ,  however,  approaches  Herbart  more  closely,  and 
it  is  astounding  that  his  influence  is  so  small.  He  is  as  much 
a  psychologist  and  a  moralist  as  Herbart,  and  there  is  much  of 
immediate  practical  value  in  his  work ;  yet  he  has  founded  no 
school,  and  there  are  few  tolerable  works  which  deal  with  his 
pedagogical  labours,  while  Herbartian  literature  counts  its  hun- 
dreds of  volumes.  Doubtless  Schleiermacher' s  manner  is  at  the 
root  of  the  difference.     [5.] 

A  second  reason  for  Herbart's  influence  is  the  impressiveness 
of  his  manner.  He  employs  the  short,  measured  speech  of 
authority.  There  is  no  wearisome  weighing  of /or  and  against, 
no  doubt  or  hesitation,  such  as  we  find  in  Schleiermacher. 
Herbart's  ripe  results  shine  forth  like  fruit  on  a  tree,  and  only 
need  to  be  shaken  in  order  to  fall  into  the  basket.  The  talent 
of  authority  which,  as  a  practical  teacher,  he  possessed  in  an 
unusual  degree,  has  passed  into  his  theoretical  delivery.  Hence 
men  feel  that  he  lived  in  the  very  element  of  pedagogic  practice, 
and  as  he  was,  in  addition,  Philosopher,  Moralist  and  Psycholo- 
gist, he  has  aroused  unusual  confidence.     [6.] 

Then,  again,  his  educational  doctrines  have  proved  really 
fruitful  in  practice,  and  this,  with  many,  is  a  clear  sign  of  their 
truth.     [7.] 

To  appeal  to  the  practical  value  of  Herbart's  doctrine  is,  how- 
ever, tacitly  to  surrender  the  claim  that  they  are  philosophically 
established.  Away  with  his  theories  !  But  Herbart  himself 
would  scarcely  agree  to  having  the  useful  maxims  of  his  pedagogy 
picked  out  while  his  system  as  a  whole  is  renounced.  And  there 
Natorp  agrees  with  Herbart :  a  theoretical  foundation  is  neither 
superfluous  nor  of  secondary  importance.     [7.] 

Are,  then,  the  foundations  of  Herbart's  system  really  secure  ? 
If  they  are  not,  no  excellence  of  another  kind  can  compensate 
for  the  deficiency ;  neither  his  genuine  enthusiasm  for  education , 
his  love  for  human  beings,  nor  his  distinct  sense  for  the  useful 
and  appHcable.  Self-confidence  is  doubtless  necessary  for  the 
practical  man  ;  but  for  the  theorist,  self-criticism.  It  is  here  that 
Herbart  is  deficient.    We  distrust  his  dogmatic,  "It  is  so  ".    [8.] 


Natorp  183 

Criticisms  of  Herbartianism  have  not  been  wanting.  Attacks 
upon  special  points,  especially  upon  Ziller's  development  of 
the  system,  have  been  numerous,  and  Herbartians  themselves 
have  surrendered  or  greatly  modified  some  of  the  chief  parts 
of  their  master's  pedagogy.  Dittes  and  Ostermann  (the  latter 
from  approximately  the  standpoint  of  Lotze)  have  been 
among  the  chief  opponents ;  Ostermann's  direct  attack  upon 
Herbart's  psychology  comes  close  to  the  present  criticism.  In 
fact,  modern  psychology  is  leaving  Herbartianism  quite  behind. 
But  the  decision  of  the  question,  "  For  or  against  Herbart  ?  "  is 
really  not  so  much  a  psychological  question  as  one  concerning 
Logic,  Ethics  and  Esthetics,  for  it  is  these  studies  which  have 
to  decide  what  the  aim  of  education  is  to  be.  Even  from  the 
point  of  view  of  the  means.  Psychology  is  not  so  important  as 
adherents  and  opponents  of  Herbart  alike  suppose.  The  other 
three  studies  are  the  real  foundations  of  Pedagogy,  Knowledge, 
Morality  and  Esthetic  culture  being  the  ends  with  which  they 
are  concerned  ;  while  Psychology  may  be  regarded  either  as 
identical  with  these  (or  contained  in  them),  or  as  a  special 
study  which  informs  as  to  the  application  of  the  general  prin- 
ciples of  education  (ascertained  from  the  other  three  studies)  to 
each  special  case  in  its  peculiarity.  Thus,  while  the  human 
content  of  consciousness  —  with  its  three  aspects,  scientific, 
moral,  aesthetic — builds  itself  up  out  of  its  elements  in  accor- 
dance with  unchanging  laws — this  growth  may  be  hindered  in 
special  cases,  and  here  comes  in  the  value  of  Psychology  and 
Physiology.  Thus,  after  all,  the  value  of  Psychology  for  educa- 
tion is  but  slight,  and  in  any  case  is  quite  secondary  ;  hence 
even  if  Herbart's  psychological  presentation- mechanism  were  a 
valid  notion  (which  it  is  not),  it  would  be  no  basis  for  education. 
That  basis  cannot  be  found  in  Psychology  at  all.     [11.] 

(B)  The  defenders  of  Herbartianism  have  done  their  best  to 
answer  the  above  criticisms. 

Instead  of  Herbartianism  as  a  philosophical  and  psychological 
system  being  little  more  than  "historical,"  and  its  advocacy 
being  confined  to  "veterans,"  psychologies  of  the  Herbartian 


184  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

school  "  rule  the  present  market ".  Natorp's  emphasis  on  physi- 
ology has  no  point  for  Herbartians,  for  they  welcome  all  physio- 
logical and  psycho-physical  investigations.  (Fliigel,  pp.  257-9.) 
The  complaint  that  Herbart's  psychology  ignores  the  difficulties 
of  individual  cases  is  refuted  by  the  existence  of  Herbart's  letters 
on  the  application  of  Psychology  to  Pedagogy,  in  which  he  dis- 
cusses the  difficulties  arising  from  physiological  hindrances  ; 
and  also  by  the  zeal  of  Herbartians  like  Strtimpell,  Ufer, 
Triiper,  and  Koch  in  these  very  directions.  Natorp  claims 
that  Herbartian  psychology  is  useless  in  such  cases ;  in  reality 
he  himself  exaggerates  the  psychological  value  of  physiology. 
Contrast  his  view  with  that  of  the  psycho-physicist  Miinster- 
berg,  who  expUcitly  denied  that  his  favourite  study  can  throw 
real  light  on  mental  problems.     [259-60.] 

Herbart  was  not  a  "  dogmatist ".  He  emphasised  the  neces- 
sity for  scepticism  at  the  beginning  of  philosophical  thinking  as 
the  only  salvation  from  "  stupid  and  arrogant  dogmatism,"  and 
warned  teachers  against  impressing  their  own  modes  of  thinking 
on  their  scholars.  Instead  of  Herbart  being  incapable  of  doubt, 
he  once  exclaimed  :  "  Are  we  never  to  be  able  to  grasp  the  whole 
completely?  "     [Rein,  pp.  298-300.] 

(C)  The  charge  of  "  dogmatism  "  is  of  little  real  gravity ;  the 
exposition  of  any  systematic  scheme  must  appear  dogmatic 
unless  the  expounder  choose  to  qualify  and  apologise  in  every 
paragraph.  But  if  Herbart's  system  were  a  rigidly  fixed 
one  how  can  we  explain  the  varied  development  it  has  experi- 
enced from  his  followers?  Moreover,  no  men  have  done  more 
for  the  study  of  abnormal  mental  phenomena  manifested  in 
children  than  the  Herbartians. 

Still,  the  defenders  of  Herbart  serve  their  cause  ill  when  they 
try  to  defend  his  Psychology  en  bloc.  Natorp  is  right  in  re- 
garding it  as  scientifically  antiquated.  The  whole  tendency  of 
modern  psychological  thought  is  away  from  a  system  which, 
though  not  exactly  ignoring  biological  facts,  has  no  logical  place 
for  them,  and  which  was  elaborated  in  pre-Darwinian  times. 
Herbartian  psychologists  have  been  compelled  to  concede  that 


Natorp  185 

ideas  are  not  absolute  causes,  but  rather  occasions  of  volition. 
Still,  the  value  of  the  work  of  Striimpell,  Volkmann,  Waitz, 
Cornelius,  Nahlowsky,  and  other  Herbartians  is  admitted. 
Moreover,  a  presentational  Psychology  may  be,  after  all,  the 
best  for  a  pedagogue,  seeing  that  presentations  are  the  material 
with  which  he  works. 

(2)  The  "disconnectedness"  of  Herbart's  teaching. 

(A)  Herbart  was  devoid  of  the  power  of  developing  his  prin- 
ciples logically  and  consecutively.  Clear  in  details — indeed  a 
model  of  clearness — he  seems  to  have  had  no  feeling  that  these 
must  hang  together  in  indissoluble  connection.  Will  it  never  be 
the  lot  of  a  true  thinker  to  influence  the  teachers  of  the  rising 
generation  ?     [Natorp,  p.  8.] 

(B)  What  a  contrast  between  the  above  opinion  of  Natorp 
and  that  expressed  in  the  Herbart  Recollections,  which  describe 
Herbart's  maxims  as  "  bound  together  as  closely  as  the  mem- 
bers of  a  mathematical  demonstration !  "     [Eein,  p.  300.] 

(C)  The  above  objection  of  Natorp  is  probably  the  most 
unfounded  of  any  in  his  book.  There  is  no  system  of  philosophy 
in  existence  of  a  more  unitary  character  than  Herbart's.  The 
unit  is  the  presentation,  and  everything  hangs  upon  this.  There 
is  no  "  Will-faculty,"  etc.,  to  introduce  disturbing  factors  ;  Her- 
bart, indeed,  was  a  vigorous  opponent  of  every  "faculty" 
doctrine.  His  system  may  be  right  or  wrong,  but  that  it  is 
thoroughgoing  and  systematic  in  the  highest  degree  few  will 
deny. 

(3)  Attitude  and  relation  of  Herbart  to  Pestalozzi. 

(A)  Pestalozzi  is  the  only  educationist  at  present  held  in  a 
reverence  at  all  commensurable  with  that  given  to  Herbart. 
But  he  is  not  reckoned  as  a  philosopher.  People  tell  us  that 
Herbart  has  methodically  embodied  in  his  own  system  the  best 
of  Pestalozzi — the  principles  which  the  great  Swiss  teacher  had 
arrived  at  in  a  half-dreaming  manner.     Keally  this  is  not  so, 


1 86  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

There  is  a  great  contrast  between  the  two,  and  Herbart  never 
did  justice — could  not  do  justice — to  his  predecessor  ;  though 
he  praises  and  patronises  him  often  enough,  he  alters  his 
thoughts  and  subordinates  them  to  his  own.     [Natorp,  p.  5.] 

Whereas  Herbart,  as  seen  above,  subordinated  everything  to 
the  moral  aim,  Pestalozzi  insisted  on  the  necessary  unity  of  the 
culture  of  "  Head,  Heart  and  Hand,"  of  Intellect,  "Will  and 
Artistic  ability.     [12.] 

He  insisted,  too,  upon  the  necessity  of  an  investigation  of  the 
elements  of  mental  hfe  and  then  upon  a  steady  advance  to  the 
complex  content  of  consciousness.     [12.] 

In  these  two  points  Pestalozzi  is  in  full  agreement  with 
Kant,  as  also  in  others,  such  as  his  emphasis  on  the  fimda- 
mental  concept  of  Anschauung  and  his  ethical  views.  He  had 
scarcely  read  Kant,  but  perhaps  he  had  learnt  some  of  his 
fundamental  thoughts  from  conversation  with  Fichte.  From 
the  point  of  view  of  sociology  and  social  pedagogy  he  even  went 
beyond  Kant.  Pestalozzi  was  no  dreamer  ;  he  had  investigated 
the  fundamental  springs  and  form  of  human  nature,  and  it  was 
for  this  reason  that,  though  he  fell  into  errors  of  detail,  he 
anticipated  so  accurately  the  further  developments  of  mankind. 
[13.] 

Herbart,  on  the  contrary,  stands  in  pronounced  contrast  to 
Pestalozzi.  He  was  excellent  as  a  practitioner  of  education  ; 
Pestalozzi  was  not.  He  was  well  versed  in  all  kinds  of  science, 
and  was  a  clear  thinker  in  matters  of  detail.  But  he  was  in- 
capable of  forming  systematic  and  all-embracing  views,  even 
incapable  of  understanding  them  when  offered  by  others  (Kant, 
Fichte,  Pestalozzi).     [13-4.] 

The  two  men  did  not  mean  the  same  thing  when  they  spoke 
of  psychology,  and  it  is  not  true  that  Herbart  supphed  the 
desiderated  psychological  foundation  for  his  predecessor's  views. 
Pestalozzi  meant  the  fundamental  laws  by  which  the  content 
of  human  culture  grows  from  its  elements,  these  elements  being 
deduced  from  Ethics,  Logic  and  Esthetics.  Contrast  this  with 
Herbart's  presentational-mechanism !     [14-5.] 


Natorp  187 

(B)  Herbart  constantly  confesses  his  indebtedness  to  Pesta- 
lozzi,  as  can  be  seen  by  any  unprejudiced  reader  of  those 
writings  of  Herbart  which  deal  with  his  predecessor's  work. 
In  addition  to  obligations  of  a  minor  character  ^  no  one  had 
a  finer  understanding  than  Herbart  of  the  Pestalozzian  doctrine 
of  Apperception-Instruction.  He  even  remained  true  to  his 
master  when,  long  ago,  men's  enthusiasm  for  the  latter  had 
waned.  Natorp  with  his  illegitimate  formula  "  Herbart  or 
Pestalozzi "  implies  an  opposition  between  them,  but  in  point 
of  fact  Herbart  worked  on  the  lines  of  his  predecessor,  and  the 
true  formula  is  "  Herbart  and  Pestalozzi  ".  Natorp' s  formula 
has  been  invented  by  the  enemies  of  Herbartianism,  who  use 
Pestalozzi's  name  for  controversial  purposes.    [Eein,  pp.  296-7.] 

Natorp  is  thoroughly  prejudiced  against  Herbart,  while  to- 
wards Pestalozzi  his  attitude  is  equally  prejudiced  but  in  the 
opposite  direction.  He  completely  passes  over  Pestalozzi's 
many  obscurities  and  inconsistencies.  But  apart  from  this, 
he  always  sees  Pestalozzi  through  the  spectacles  of  his  own 
theory  of  knowledge,  just  as  Niederer  had  thrown  the  doctrine 
of  the  great  Swiss  into  confusion  by  a  dragging  in  of  the 
philosophy  of  Fichte.  It  is  a  service  of  Wiget  to  have  revealed 
the  additions  of  Niederer.  'Natorp  appears  ignorant  of  Wiget's 
work.  Apparently  Natorp's  prejudice  against  Herbart  is  due 
to  the  impossibility  of  fitting  the  clear  unambiguous  thoughts 
of  the  latter  into  the  structure  of  a  ready-made  theory  of  know- 
ledge, while  Pestalozzi's  ambiguities  are  much  more  adaptable 
for  such  a  purpose.      [300-1.] 

The  Pestalozzian  doctrine  of  Anschauung  has  really  but 
little  affinity  with  that  of  Kant.  Pestalozzi  understood  by 
Anschauung  the  impression  of  an  outer  object  upon  our  senses, 
not,  as  Natorp  thinks,  the  generation  of  the  mathematical  form  of 
anschaubar  things  out  of  the  pure  elements  of  our  Anschauung 
itself  (an  addition  of  Niederer).  Pestalozzi  would  have  rejected 
Natorp's  interpretation  as  readily  as  he  did  Niederer's.    [301-2.] 

Along  with  this  must  go  Natorp's  undervaluing  of  Psychology 

^  Such  as  the  use  of  transparent  plates  of  horn. 


i88  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

and  his  exaltation  of  criticism  of  knowledge  into  the  first  place, 
by  which  choice  he  condemns  himself  to  unfruitfulness.  More- 
over, Pestalozzi  would  never  have  founded  his  system  upon  the 
notion  of  a  pure  spontaneity.     [302.] 

(A)  Natorp  in  his  reply  (Die  Deutsche  Schule,  August,  1899) 
justifies  his  greater  severity  towards  Herbart  on  the  ground  that 
the  latter's  professions  are  greater  than  those  of  Pestalozzi,  and 
are  therefore  to  be  judged  accordingly.  He  also  stoutly  main- 
tains the  existence  of  Kantianism  in  Pestalozzi  previous  to  the 
influence  of  Niederer.  There  is  no  real  contradiction  in  appeal- 
ing to  experience  and  at  the  same  time  to  deduction  (vide 
Kant,  Pestalozzi,  etc.). 

(C)  The  present  writer's  reading  leads  him  here  to  side  again 
with  the  Herbartians.  There  is  nothing  "  condescending  "  about 
Herbart's  treatment  of  his  great  predecessor.  The  principle  of 
Anschauung  was  "the  grand  idea  of  its  discoverer,  the  noble 
Pestalozzi ".  Herbart  seized  hold  of  it  gratefully,  and,  in  the 
opinion  of  the  vast  majority  of  educationists,  developed  it 
successfully  into  the  Apperception  doctrine  by  showing  the 
essential  contribution  of  the  mental  factor. 

(4)  The  aim  or  goal  of  Education. 

(A)  In  considering  the  aim  or  goal  of  education  we  find  that 
Herbart  lays  great  stress  upon  Ethics.  Morality  is  the  goal  of 
education.  But  this  is  a  one-sided  view.  Logic  and  .Esthetics 
have  a  right  to  insist  upon  their  aims,  Knowledge  and  .Esthetic 
culture.     [Natorp,  p.  11.] 

In  point  of  fact  education  must  rest  on  Philosophy  as  a  whole, 
not  upon  two  fragments  of  it.  Psychology  and  Ethics,  Will, 
Intellect,  ^Esthetic  imagination — all  three  must  be  considered, 
along  with,  of  course,  their  respective  psychologies.     [11-2.] 

(B)  Natorp  would  be  right  if  the  three  goals  (Ethical,  Intel- 
lectual and  Esthetic)  were  of  equal  worth.  But  they  are  not 
so.     There  is  only  one  absolute  goal,  as  Kant  himself  points 


Natorp  189 

out ;  a  good  and  moral  Will  is  always  good,  while  Esthetic  or 
Intellectual  power  may  be  devoted  to  evil  purposes.  Hence 
Ethics  alone  gives  the  goal  of  Education.  Logic  and  Esthetics 
have  a  subordinate  use  only. 

Even  Natorp  himself  in  another  place  [p.  72]  admits  (here 
contradicting  himself)  that  the  Ethical  end  is  the  highest  educa- 
tional goal,  not  merely  as  the  most  elevated  but  also  as  including 
and  controlling  the  others.  The  difference  between  the  two 
men  is  that  while  with  Natorp  the  place  of  the  highest  educa- 
tional aim  (Morality)  remains  a  mere  phrase,  for  Logical  and 
^Esthetic  culture  go  their  own  ways — with  Herbart  the  latter 
appear  as  preliminary  steps  or  means  to  the  moral  goal.  Here, 
too,  Pestalozzi  is  in  full  agreement  with  Herbart.  He  declares 
that  only  by  a  subordination  of  all  the  other  claims  of  our  nature 
to  the  higher  claims  of  Morality  is  a  harmony  of  our  powers 
possible.     [Just,  pp.  277-8.] 

(C)  The  question  above  mooted  is  no  easy  one  to  answer,  and 
its  solution  has  as  much  philosophical  interest  as  pedagogical. 

Moralists  {e.g.,  Sidgwick,  Methods  of  Ethics,  6th  edition,  pp. 
399-402)  have  frequently  found  a  difficulty  in  considering  the 
possible  conflict  of  the  Moral  with  the  Logical  goal.  Suppose 
that  on  a  complete  view  of  the  universe  we  became  convinced 
that  it  was  essentially  cruel  or  purposeless,  would  it  be  our  duty 
to  proclaim  the  truth  ?  Would  not  the  claims  of  the  moral  life 
be  endangered  by  such  a  proclamation  ?  If  so,  have  we  to  risk 
the  subversion  of  morality  ?  Or  have  we  to  regard  Morality  as 
the  highest  end  and  endeavour  to  subordinate  everything,  even 
Truth,  to  that  ?  Such  ultimate  questions  cannot  be  solved  to 
the  satisfaction  of  every  one ;  some  controversialists  will  insist 
that  Truthfulness  is  an  absolute  duty,  others  will  subordinate 
it  to  Morality,  while  others  again  will  be  so  bold  as  to  deny  the 
possibility  of  a  conflict.  Similar  questions  arise  with  respect 
to  the  relations  of  Art  and  Morality. 

The  question  is,  therefore,  not  merely  one  between  Herbart 
and  Natorp,  but  one  of  perennial  interest. 

With  regard  to  the  pedagogical  aspect  of  the  question,  it  may 


190  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

be  pointed  out  that  English  teachers,  who  for  the  most  part 
have  not  yet  been  appreciably  touched  by  the  Herbartian  spirit, 
do  not  feel  the  importance  of  the  issue  thus  raised.  Their  ideals 
are  those  of  imparting  knowledge  and  dexterity — mainly  the 
Logical  and  Esthetic  ideals.  So  far  as  the  Moral  ideal  affects 
them  at  all,  its  operations  are  confined  to  a  few  definite  "  re- 
ligious "  lessons ;  it  does  not  permeate  their  whole  work.  The 
two  aims  remain  separated  by  conventional  barriers  ;  hence, 
when  a  teacher  is  asked  to  instil  "  temperance  "  or  "  humani- 
tarianism  "  he  frequently  regards  these  subjects  as  "  outside 
his  province  ".  But  such  a  confession  is  virtually  an  exaltation 
of  the  Logical  and  .Esthetic  ideals  at  the  expense  of  the  Moral. 
The  case  just  cited  probably  represents  the  usual  attitude  of  the 
English  teacher.  The  two  ideals  are  conventionally  held  apart 
in  the  "  Time  Table,"  but  when  there  is  any  possibility  of  mutual 
interference  the  "  Moral "  has  to  give  way. 

The  agitations  for  "  religious"  education  are  in  large  measure 
an  outcome  of  this  hard  and  fast  separation  which  is  made 
between  "  sacred  "  and  "  secular  "  subjects,  a  separation  which 
is  itself  due  to  a  non-recognition  of  the  moral  value  of  "secular" ^ 
subjects  and  an  ignorance  of  the  psychology  of  human  motive. 

The  great  service  of  Herbartianism  has  been  to  break  down 
the  barrier  above  indicated.  "Secular"  instruction  loses  its 
stigma  if  it  can  be  shown  to  enter  into  the  field  of  motive  and 
action.  This  it  does  when  Apperceptive  Interest  has  been 
aroused.  Geography,  Mathematics,  Science  become  moral  forces, 
for  as  sources  of  "Interest"  they  draw  or  impel  the  pupil  in 
the  direction  of  an  elevated  life.  Even  on  a  lower  view  they 
may  be  regarded  as  moral  forces  so  far  as  they  may  have  the 
effect  of  keeping  the  pupil  throughout  his  Hfe  fi'om  the  debasing 
pursuits  which   the  ignorant   man  almost  inevitably  follows. 

1 "  Abgesehen  vom  Religions-unterricht,  von  dem  man  vermdge  seines 
Inhalts  einen  einfluss  auf  Gemiit  und  Willen  des  Zoglings  erwartet,  ver- 
folgen  die  Unterrichts-gegenstande  einen  selbstandigen  Zweck,  namlich 
die  Aneignung  eines  bestimmten  Wissens  und  Konnens,  damit  der  Zogling 
dereinst  im  Leben  sich  gut  forthelfen  konne.  .  .  .  Eine  solche  Auffassung 
ist  .  .  .  unhaltbar."    Beiu,  Padagogik  im  Orundriss,  pp.  78-9. 


Natorp  191 

"  The  stupid  man  cannot  be  virtuous,"  for  he  has  no  springs  of 
action  except  such  as  lead  to  vice.  The  man  with  a  vital 
interest  in  Art,  or  Science,  or  History  has  an  enormously 
greater  chance  of  being  "  virtuous  "  (using  this  word  even  in 
the  usual  narrow  sense)  than  the  man  devoid  of  such  interest. 
Positively  these  interests  are  springs  of  worthy  volition  ;  nega- 
tively they  keep  from  vice. 

In  short,  "  Interest "  is  the  bridge  from  the  Intellectual  to 
the  Moral  realm — a  bridge  which  popular  theology,  with  its 
hard  and  fast  separation  of  the  "  sacred  "  from  the  "  secular," 
is  daily  rejecting.  It  is  the  imperishable  work  of  Herbart  to 
have  discovered  (the  word  is  not  too  strong)  this  bridge,  and  to 
have  arrayed  Esthetic  and  Scientific  culture  under  the  banner 
of  Virtue.  If  many-sided  Interest  be  so  important,  so  vital,  as 
Herbartians  allege,  then  the  demonstration  of  the  unitary  nature 
of  Herbart's  goal  is  his  crowning  achievement.  The  teacher  of 
Mathematics  is  the  teacher  of  Virtue,  and  there  is  no  longer  any 
need  to  regard  Education  as  having  three  or  more  conflicting 
ends  in  view. 

(5)  Herbart's  mistaken  separation  of  "  Training  "  from 
"  Discipline  ". 

(A)  Eeserviug  for  future  consideration  the  very  important 
question  of  the  relation  of  Instruction  (culture  of  the  Under- 
standing) to  Education  as  a  whole  (culture  of  the  Will),  we 
have  now  to  consider  the  validity  of  Herbart's  distinction  be- 
tween the  other  two  agencies.  Training  (Zucht)  and  Discipline 
(Eegierung).      [Natorp,  pp.  48-9.] 

Herbart  lays  stress  upon  the  fact  that  Instruction  (the  culture 
of  the  Understanding  or  the  formation  of  the  "circle  of 
thought ")  is  the  chief  agency  for  the  culture  of  the  Will  also. 
"  There  ought  to  be  no  Instruction  which  does  not  educate." 
By  Training  he  means  whatever,  apart  from  Instruction 
proper,  cultivates  the  Will.  But  what  then  remains  for 
Discipline?  Something  comparatively  unimportant;  indeed 
something,  according  to   Herbart  himself,  hardly  belonging  to 


192  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

Education  but  yet  not  entirely  separable  from  it.  The  purpose 
of  Discipline  lies  in  the  present,  not  in  the  future  ;  it  aims 
merely  at  outward  order,  which  is  a  prerequisite  of  education, 
but  not  in  itself  educative.  No  doubt  Discipline  immediately 
influences  the  pupil's  state  of  mind,  but  it  serves  no  ulterior 
purpose.  Punishment  (under  Discipline)  ignores  the  intention 
of  the  agent,  and  considers  only  the  act  itself ;  while  genuinely 
educative  punishment  considers  intention  also.     [49-50.] 

Natorp  holds  that  his  separation  of  Training  from  Discipline 
is  utterly  untenable,  and  points  out  that  even  Herbartians  have 
remodelled  it.      [50.] 

Discipline  is  supposed  to  regulate  merely  the  outer  behaviour 
of  the  pupil.  But  surely  outer  behaviour  is  subject  to  the  laws 
of  morality !  The  question  is,  whether,  in  connection  with 
education,  the  merely  "  right "  relation  apart  from  the  moral 
can  be  of  any  value.  Surely  not.  External  order  is  necessary, 
but  only  for  the  sake  of  the  internal  moral  order.  The  educator 
cannot  separate  himself  into  a  moral  and  into  a  merely  "  right " 
being.  A  punishment  which  aims  at  subjection  pure  and  simple 
and  does  not  address  itself  to  the  will  of  the  pupil  is  imper- 
missible. Even  outer  order  must  only  be  preserved  through 
moral  means,  and  the  pupil,  though  himself  ignorant  of  the 
right  way,  must  willingly  confide  in  the  guidance  of  the  tutor. 
[51.] 

Herbart  seems  to  think  that  at  such  a  stage  the  child  is 
devoid  of  will ;  but  surely  it  has  a  will  in  process  of  becoming  ; 
and  this  very  fact  makes  the  psychical  influences  upon  it  of  great 
importance.  The  smallest  influence  has  not  only  a  momentary 
but  a  permanent  result.     [52.] 

Certainly  we  may  admit  that  there  are  permanent  and 
momentary,  moral  and  merely  right,  positive  and  negative 
influences ;  influences  through  the  will  of  the  pupil  and  through 
merely  momentary  excitations.  But  the  latter  must  be  abso- 
lutely subordinated  to  the  former.  Hence  the  separation  of 
Training  from  Discipline  is  untenable,  and  we  are  left  only 
with  Training  and  Instruction.     [53.] 


Natorp  193 

(B)  Natorp  declares  that  Herbart's  doctrine  of  "  Discipline  " 
is  in  no  single  point  tenable.  But  this  is  to  shoot  beyond  the 
mark.  Herbartians  have  already  modified  Herbart's  doctrine, 
and  instead  of  the  three  divisions,  Training,  Disciphne  and  In- 
struction, now  adopt  two,  Guidance  (Fiihrung)  and  Instruction. 
But  Herbart's  differentiation  of  Training  from  Discipline  has 
still  some  theoretical  and  practical  significance.  Natorp  himself 
admits  the  distinction  between  negative  and  positive  modes  of 
action  in  connection  with  the  training  of  children ;  merely 
"  right "  as  contrasted  with  genuinely  "  moral "  ;  momentary  as 
contrasted  with  lasting ;  modes  which  make  use  of  momentary 
stimuli  as  contrasted  with  those  which  act  through  the  Will. 
Here,  then,  is  the  distinction  between  "Discipline"  and 
"  Training  "  ;  both,  however,  ought  to  be  subsumed  under  the 
concept  of  "Guidance".     [Eein,  p.  303.] 

(C)  Despite  the  partial  recantation  of  Herbartians  from  the 
triple  classification  of  their  master,  this  classification  can 
frequently  be  illustrated  in  the  concrete  from  English  methods 
of  teaching.  The  functions  of  "Discipline"  pure  and  simple 
seem  in  no  danger  of  being,  absorbed  in  those  of  the  other 
two,  so  far,  at  any  rate,  as  Elementary  Schools  are  con- 
cerned. 

In  view  of  the  large  classes  which  are  usual  rather  than 
exceptional  in  these  schools,  the  necessity  of  firm  Discipline  is 
all-important.  "Are  you  a  good  disciplinarian?"  is  the  first 
question  asked  of  a  candidate  for  a  pedagogic  post,  and  the 
meaning  of  the  question  is,  "  Are  you  able  to  maintain  a  system 
of  military  precision? " 

The  question  of  punishments  is  the  most  important  in  this 
connection.  The  punishments  of  Discipline  are  based  mainly 
on  the  Eetributive  and  Exemplary  theories ;  while  those  of 
Training  (in  the  Herbartian  sense)  rest  on  the  Eeformatory 
theory.  In  this  country  of  large  classes,  the  Exemplary  theory 
is  the  prevalent  one  in  school  life ;  and  the  chief  scholastic 
offences  are  not  "  moral  offences"  at  all,  but  offences  against 
a  rigid  code  of  military  rules  which  have  no  existence  or  utility 

13 


194  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

outside  of  school  life,  and  which  would  have  none  in  school  but 
for  the  exigencies  of  the  large-class  system. 

It  would  be  no  exaggeration  to  say  that  in  the  English 
elementary  school — 

"  Discipline  "  is  regarded  as  all-important. 

"Training"  (in  the  Herbartian  sense)  is,  except  so  far  as  it 
comes  under  "religious  influence,"  almost  non-existent. 

"  Instruction  "  is  plentiful,  but  its  genuinely  educative  (i.e., 
will-forming)  character  is  unrecognised  owing  to  the  artificial 
separation,  based  largely  on  theological  prejudices,  between 
"sacred"  and  "secular"  subjects,  and  an  almost  complete 
ignoring  of  the  Herbartian  doctrine  that  action  springs  out 
of  the  circle  of  thought,  and  that,  through  the  mediation  of 
"  Interest,"  "  secular  "  instruction  can  become  a  moral  force  and 
pass  into  action. 

It  may  therefore  be  said  that  Herbart's  much  criticised  three- 
fold classification  has  still  some  significance,  though  in  practice 
there  is  sometimes  no  precise  separation  between  the  three 
agencies,  and  with  the  majority  of  teachers  no  clear  recognition 
of  their  essential  differences. 

(6)  The  Herbartian  doctrine  of  "  Educative  Instruction  " — The 
distinction  between  Instruction  (Unterricht)  and  Training 
{ZuAiht). 

(A)  At  first  one  would  be  inclined  to  understand  these  latter 
in  the  following  sense  : — 

Instruction — the  culture  of  the  Understanding. 

Training — the  culture  of  the  Will. 
But  tliis  cannot  be  Herbart's  meaning,  for  he  refuses  to  admit 
the  dist  notion  between  the  three  soul  faculties,  Understanding, 
Feeling  and  Will.  Moreover,  he  insists  that  there  should  be 
no  Instruction  which  does  not  educate  [i.e.,  form  the  Will),  and 
the  final  aim  of  Education  must  be,  in  accordance  with  this, 
an  ethical  aim.  With  Herbart  the  Will  has  no  territory  of  its 
own  in  the  mental  life,  and  is  a  pure  result  of  the  movement 
of  the  presentation-masses;   thus  the  whole  culture  of   the 


Natorp  195 

Will — or  nearly  the  whole — depends  on  the  culture  of  the 
Understanding,  the  formation  of  the  circle  of  thought — in  other 
words,  on  Instruction. 

What  then  remains  for  Training  ?  Only  the  supplementary 
and  secondary  influences  which  come  through  the  stimulus 
of  pleasure  and  pain  so  far  as  these  influences  are  directed  to 
Will-Culture,  and  are  not  merely  on  account  of  Discipline. 
[Natorp,  pp.  54-5.] 

The  close  connection  or  virtual  identity  between  the  culture 
of  the  Will  and  that  of  the  Understanding  is  the  essence  of 
Herbart's  famous  theory — that  of  Educative  Instruction.  No 
doubt,  with  Pestalozzi,  in  spite  of  his  emphasis  on  the  Instruction 
of  "  Head,  Heart  and  Hand,"  the  final  goal  of  Education  is  the 
Morality  of  the  Will,  an  aim  in  which,  according  to  him,  the 
other  possible  aims  unite.  Still  the  culture  of  the  Intellect  or 
of  the  Esthetic  faculty  has  with  him  a  relative  independence. 
But  this  view  is  departed  from  by  Herbart  and  stiU  more  by  the 
Herbartians.  They  seem  to  ignore  the  claims  of  the  intellectual 
and  aesthetic  and  to  exaggerate  those  of  the  moral  nature  of 
man.  But  surely  a  thing  may  be  intellectually  true  or  false, 
aesthetically  correct  or  incorrect,  quite  apart  from  moral  con- 
siderations.    [55-6.] 

It  is  said  that  Knowledge  and  Ability  (Konnen)  are  dead 
possessions  provided  they  do  not  influence  the  culture  of  the 
moral  Will.  But  we  are  not  speaking  of  a  "  dead  "  Knowledge 
or  Ability,  but  of  living  and  creative  processes.  Doubtless, 
the  kind  of  consciousness  connected  with  them  is  also  related 
closely  to  Will  consciousness  ;  Morality  indeed  is  the  pro- 
minent point  towards  which  these  others  point ;  still  there  is  a 
kind  of  independence  in  the  three.  It  was  Kant  who  established 
this  threefold  classification  ;  Schiller  and  Pestalozzi  agreed 
with  it ;  while  Herbart,  and  still  more  his  adherents,  are  in 
danger  of  destroying  it.     [56.] 

We  must  not  wonder  if  reactionaries  welcome  Herbart's 
doctrine  as  a  reason  for  refusing  satisfaction  to  the  intellectual 
and  aesthetic  needs  of  the  people.     [56-7.] 

The  real  reproach,  however,  only  attaches  to  Herbart  himself 


196  The  Critics  of  Herbartianistn 

in  a  small  degree.  In  fact  it  is  diflficult  to  reconcile  clearly  his 
exaggerated  stress  upon  the  Will  when  the  aim  of  education 
is  being  considered  with  his  extraordinary  minimising  of  the 
8ignij5cance  of  the  Will  in  general.  The  culture  of  the  Will 
depends  not,  of  course,  on  the  Will  itself,  but,  in  accordance 
with  his  Ethics,  upon  Taste.  Hence  one  would  expect  him  to 
put  .3j]sthetic  culture  at  the  summit;  yet  he  reaUy  almost  ignores 
it.  The  Will,  according  to  him,  depends  on  the  movement  of 
presentations,  hence  the  formation  of  the  "  circle  of  thought " 
is  "everything  to  the  educator".  Only  a  small  task  is  left  to 
the  feeling-influences  of  Training,  the  task  of  "  making  a  path 
for  instruction  ".     [57-8.] 

Thus  we  find  that  when  Herbart  considers  the  aim  of 
education  he  lays  an  exaggerated  emphasis  on  the  culture  of 
the  moral  Will,  and  ignores  the  claims  of  intellectual  and 
aesthetic  culture  ;  but  when  he  considers  the  means,  he  lays  an 
equally  exaggerated  emphasis  on  Instruction  (Understanding- 
culture).     [58.] 

(B)  Natorp's  criticism  is  based  on  a  caricature  of  Herbart's 
doctrine.  He  has  omitted  Herbart's  central  thought,  that  of 
Interest.  It  is  this  concept  which  connects  the  Instruction  goal 
(culture  of  the  Understanding)  with  the  goal  of  Education  in 
general  (culture  of  the  Will).  It  is  true,  Natorp  refers  to 
"  Interest "  (p.  64),  but  strangely  regards  it  as  a  side  goal  of 
Education,  and  he  does  not  enter  upon  the  psychological  rela- 
tions of  the  factor  of  Interest  to  Presentation  and  Willing. 
Interest  is  the  fundamental  concept  of  the  theory  of  Educative 
Instruction,  and  it  possesses  a  permanent  worth  even  if  the 
practical  details  of  Herbartianism  were  abandoned.  Moreover, 
"  Interest "  supplies  the  very  element  of  inner  activity  which 
Natorp  finds  missing  in  Herbart's  system,  and,  moreover,  brings 
Herbart  into  close  connection  with  Pestalozzi.  He  declares 
that  his  chief  effort  was  identical  with  that  of  his  predecessor, 
namely,  to  find  out  the  best  order  of  succession,  the  best  fitting- 
together  of  the  teaching  material,  so  that  the  attention  of  the 
children  may  be  seized  and  enchained.     It  was  with  this  aim  in 


Natorp  197 

view  that  Pestalozzi  tried  to  understand  the  normal  process  of 
man's  development,  individual  and  racial,  and  this  work  has 
been  taken  up  by  Herbartians  (witness  their  doctrine  of "  culture 
steps").     [Rein,  pp.  304-5.] 

(C)  The  judgment  upon  the  above  issue  must  probably  be  of 
a  mixed  character. 

Natorp  has  undoubtedly  committed  a  most  serious  oversight 
— perhaps  the  worst  of  all  in  his  work — in  not  recognising  the 
central  position  of  Herbart's  "  Interest "  doctrine.^  It  is  this 
doctrine  which  bridges  over  the  gap  between  intellectual  and 
moral  Education.  It  is  Interest  which  converts  an  intellectual 
apprehension  of  History  or  of  Natural  Science  into  a  moral 
force,  a  force  which  not  only  negatively  keeps  the  pupil  "  out  of 
mischief,"  but  positively  moulds  his  future  conduct  and  pursuits. 
Interest  (provided  we  do  not  mean  by  it  a  merely  momentary 
feeling  of  pleasure)  is  the  greatest  moral  force  in  existence,  we 
might  almost  say,  the  only  moral  force  if  we  except  the  re- 
wards and  punishments  of  "  Training  "  and  "  Discipline  ".  It  is 
safe  to  say  that  a  pupil  who  has  a  keen  interest  in  Literature 
or  in  some  social  or  cosmic  question  (we  must  not  ignore  the 
"many-sidedness"  of  Herbart's  concept  of  Interest)  is  certain. 


1  Natorp  replies  [Die  Deutsdie  Schule,  August,  1899,  pp.  507-8)  that  he 
only  is  following  Herbart's  own  exposition  {Allgemeine  Pcidagogik,  Book  I., 
chapter  ii.),  according  to  which,  though  Morality  is  the  chief  goal  of 
education,  "  many-sided  Interest "  is  another  goal  not  necessarily  entirely 
identical  with  the  other.  Moreover,  Herbartian  "  Interest "  is  not,  as  Eein 
thinks,  a  "  forward-willing  "  directed  to  the  future  (and  therefore  constitut- 
ing the  missing  element  desiderated  by  Natorp),  but  is,  according  to  Her- 
bart,  strictly  dependent  on  the  perceptions  of  the  moment.  It  works  from 
without,  not  from  within,  and  hence  is  quite  a  different  thing  from  what 
Natorp  demands. 

Natorp  has  done  good  service  in  pointing  out  the  elements  of  hesitation 
in  Herbart  (though  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  these  elements  can  be  recon- 
ciled with  a  charge  of  "dogmatism").  But  undoubtedly  "  Interest "  and 
the  close  connection  between  "  Interest  "  and  character  form  the  essence 
of  Herbartian  doctrine,  and  this  essence  stands  firm  even  though  Herbart 
may  momentarily  or  provisionally  have  raised  doubts. 


198  The  Critics  of  Herbartianisnt 

other  things  being  equal,  to  grow  up  more  moral  than  indi- 
viduals devoid  of  such  interests. 

Again,  Natorp's  reproach  that  Herbart,  in  considering  the 
ways  and  means  of  Education,  lays  undue  stress  upon  Intel- 
lectual culture  (just  as,  conversely,  in  considering  the  aim  of 
Education,  he  lays  undue  stress  upon  Morality)  is  rebutted  by 
the  point  just  mentioned,  viz.,  the  very  wide  meaning  attached 
by  Herbart  to  the  notion  of  "  Interest ".  If  "  Interest "  meant 
with  Herbart  "Empirical"  and  "Speculative  Interest"  only, 
Natorp  s  strictures  might  be  well  justified.  But  one  of  the  most 
characteristic  features  of  Herbart' s  doctrine  is  that  Interest 
must  be  many-sided.  Empirical  and  Speculative  Interest  are 
only  two  varieties  out  of  the  six  he  enumerates,  the  others 
being  ^Esthetic,  Sympathetic,  Social  and  Eeligious. 

It  may  be  admitted,  however,  on  Natorp's  side,  that  though 
Apperceptive  Interest  is  always  a  moral  agency,  some  varieties 
are  morally  educative  m  a  greater  degree  than  others.  The 
connection  between  Mathematics  and  Morahty  is  less  close  than 
that  between  Literature  and  Morality.  Doubtless,  as  pointed 
out  before,  each  of  these  studies  has  a  moral  influence  of  two 
kinds  :  (1)  An  interest  in  tiiem  keeps  their  possessor  "  out  of 
the  mischief  "  which  results  from  emptiness  of  mind  and 
absence  of  engrossing  pursuits.  (2)  An  mterest  in  them  leads 
on  to  a  life  of  genuinely  elevated  character.  But  beyond  this, 
virtue,  m  the  narrower  sense,  is  not  appreciably^  influenced 
by  mathematical  study  owing  to  the  abstract  nature  of  the 
subject  and  the  absence  in  it  of  the  humanistic  factor. 

There  are,  in  point  of  fact,  two  concepts  of  Virtue.  The 
Greek  concept  is  a  wide  one,  and  is  inclusive  of  Wisdom  and 
Culture.  The  Puritanical  concept  omits  these  latter  elements. 
There  can  be  no  doubt  but  that  Herbart  accepted  the  wider 
ideal,  and  hence  he  could,  with  perfect  appropriateness,  connect 
Instruction  with  Virtue  and  Morality,  and  regard  the  latter  as 


^  Perseverance,  exactness  and  similar  qualities  are,  no  doubt,  cultivated, 
but  they  are  not  "  virtuous  "  in  the  narrower  sense,  though  there  is  plenty 
of  room  for  them  vrithin  the  larger  ideal. 


Natorp  199 

springing  directly  out  of  the  "  circle  of  thought "  which  it  is 
the  work  of  Instruction  to  form.  Even  on  an  acceptance  of 
the  narrower  ideal,  the  connection  between  Morality  and  In- 
struction is  important,  and  Herbart  has  won  an  immortaUty  of 
fame  by  working  it  out.  Still,  in  this  latter  case  the  connection 
is  less  striking  and  direct,  though  surely  real  enough  to  merit 
the  solemn  attention  of  teachers  and  reformers.  A  vast  amount 
of  evil  is  directly  traceable  to  emptiness  of  mind,  and  philanthro- 
pists may  with  good  reason  devote  their  efforts  to  creating  healthy 
interests  and  impulses,  rather  than  to  removing  the  necessary 
after-results  of  this  emptiness. 

(7)  The  Herbartian  Theory  of  the  Will,  considered  ethically. 
Kant  and  Herbart. 

(A)  Herbart  constantly  waged  war  against  certain  Kantian 
doctrines,  though,  in  Natorp  s  opinion,  these  doctrines  are  the 
only  secure  basis  for  Ethics  and  Pedagogy. 

Kant's  central  thought  was  the  Autonomy  of  the  moral  Will.^ 
The  moral  Will  must  not  be  determined  by  anything  external  to 
itself ;  any  command,  impulse,  or  desire.  It  must  be  determined 
by  itself  alone,  and  be  not  only  an  executive  but  a  law-giving 
Will.  Its  only  principle  is  that  of  harmony  or  consistency  with 
itself,  and  this  principle  is  clearly  a,  formal  one.  [Similarly  with 
Understanding  ;  that  which  is  objectively  true  is  consistent ;  in 
both  cases,  conflict  or  contradiction  is  the  test  of  untruth.]  The 
strongest  appeal  that  can  ever  be  made  to  the  human  Will  re- 
sults from  this  fact  of  self-judgment.  Surely  Education  should 
recognise  this  fact  and  demand  the  highest  thing  possible  from 
man.  Was  it  not  a  retrogression  when  Herbart  surrendered 
this  point  of  view  ?     [19-22.] 

His  reasons  for  doing  so  were  psychological.  How  can  such 
a  faculty  of  absolute  self-determination  be  thought  of?  Will 
must  depend  on  presentations  ;  there  is  no  Will  per  se ;  hence 

^  Kant's  famous  "  categorical  imperative  "  was,  "  Act  only  on  such  a 
maxim  as  you  can  at  the  same  time  will  to  be  a  universal  law  ".  In  other 
words,  "  Never  make  exceptions  for  yourself  ". 


2O0  Ttie  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


the  Will  cannot  sit  in  judgment  on  the  Will.  But  surely  (re- 
plies Natorp)  though  no  single  act  of  Will  can  give  the  law  to 
another  act,  yet  there  is  the  formal  law  of  the  Will ;  the  har- 
mony  of  the  Will  with  itself.  Herbart  ignores  this.  Harmony 
of  willing  is  the  ultimate  test  of  morahty,  just  as  harmony  of  be- 
lief is  the  ultimate  test  of  truth.     [22-5.] 

(B)  The  above  question  is  the  fundamental  one  in  the  present 
discussion.  Natorp  is  a  libertarian ;  the  Will  is,  with  him,  a 
causeless  spontaneity.  It  is  the  one  vital  element  in  man  and 
the  universe  ;  it  is  the  norm  of  the  moral  life.    [Fliigel,  p.  261.] 

Kant's  great  service  was  to  reject  the  pleasure-theory  of 
morals,  and  to  lay  emphasis  on  the  forw,  of  willing.  Did 
Herbart  really  depart  from  Kant's  position  ?  No.  He  still 
opposed  the  pleasure  theory,  and  held  that  moral  worth  can 
only  be  found  in  the  form  of  wilUng.  [Just,  pp.  279-80.]  Her- 
bart and  Natorp  both  feel  that  it  is  necessary  to  find  somewhere 
a  judgment  upon  the  Will,  in  order  to  know  whence  comes  its 
worth  and  dignity.  Natorp  finds  that  the  Will  is  good  so  far  as 
it  is  autonomous — devoid  of  all  motive  except  itself.  Thus,  the 
good  Will  is  the  one  which  suppresses  every  momentary  desire 
or  makes  it  conform  to  itself.  But  surely  this  is  possible  with 
great  sinners  as  well  as  great  saints !  An  avaricious  or  ambitious 
man  may  will  with  perfect  consistency.     [Fliigel,  p.  263.] 

No  doubt  "harmony  of  the  Will  with  itself"  is  aesthetically 
pleasing.  Napoleon's  will  was  in  harmony  with  itself,  but,  being 
egoistic,  was  immoral.  If  the  good  Samaritan  had  made  a 
general  rule  of  hating  the  Jews,  would  he  have  been  immoral 
in  relieving  the  distressed  man  ?  Mere  harmony  of  Will  does 
not  prove  morality  of  Will ;  there  must  be  a  general  type  of 
worthy  willing.     [Just,  p.  282.] 

Herbart,  quite  as  strongly  as  Kant,  insisted  that  the  moral 
Will  must  be  free  from  external  motives,  sensuous  impulses, 
etc.  But  he  rightly  rejected  absolute  self-determination,  which 
means  merely  caprice,  and  is  devoid  of  moral  quaUty.  There 
must  be  some  standard  outside  the  Will  itself.  Here  we  come 
to  the  "  moral  ideas  "  which  Herbart  enunciated.  [Just,  p.  280.] 


Natorp  20 1 

Kant's  Ethics  were  the  product  of  an  age  which  strove  after 
independence.  MoraUty  appeared  as  mere  self-rule  or  Egoism . 
Nietzsche  drew  the  logical  consequence  from  Kant's  system. 
[Willmann,  Zeitschrift.] 

(C)  The  above  discussion  may  appear  academic,  but  it  is 
really  of  deep  philosophic  interest.  Whence  are  we  to  derive 
our  standard  of  moral  action  ?  Kant,  Herbart,  and  Natorp 
agree  that  a  mere  formless  thing  like  "pleasure"  which  may 
arise  from  any  one  of  a  multitude  of  causes,  cannot  provide  such 
a  standard. 

Are  we  then,  with  Kant  and  Natorp,  to  fall  back  on  a 
formal  principle  of  mere  consistency  or  universality?  The 
difficulty  here  is  that  an  immoral  man  may  be  very  "  consistent" 
indeed.^ 

Herbart  was,  therefore,  driven  on  to  seek  some  other  ground 
for  morality,  and  he  found  it  in  the  "  five  moral  ideas,"  in- 
tuitively or  aesthetically  apprehended.  He,  like  Sidgwick,  was 
"forced  to  recognise  the  need  of  a  fundamental  ethical  intui- 
tion ".""  The  two  writers  are  agreed  that  only  by  postulating  one 
or  more  spontaneous  intuitions,  each  incapable  of  logical  proof, 
can  a  moral  standard  be  acquired.  The  "  aesthetic  judgments" 
of  Herbart  are  essentially  similar  in  nature  to  the  "  intuitive  " 
judgments  of  Sidgwick. 

(8)  The  Herhartian  Theory  of  the  Will  considered  Psycho- 
logically.    The  Doctrine  of  "  Faculties  ". 

(A)  Men  frequently  regard  the  faculties  of  Presentation, 
Feeling,  and  Will  as  more  or  less  external  to  each  other. 
Herbart  was  at  great  pains  to  abolish  this  separation  and  to 
base  mental  life  on  one  foundation  only — the  complex  inter- 
action of  innumerable  presentations.  Herbart  was  correct  so 
far  as  he  contended  that  the  three  fundamental  faculties  are  not 

1 "  The  Rational  Egoist  .  .  .  might  accept  the  Kantian  principle  and 
remain  an  Egoist."     (Sidgwick,  Metliods  of  Ethics,  preface.) 
•^Ibid. 


The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


self-sufl&cient  or  mutually  hostile.  Man  is  never  merely  a 
presentative,  merely  a  feeling,  or  merely  a  volitional  being ;  all 
three  aspects  coexist,  though  one  may  be  predominant.  Herbart 
did  great  service  in  calling  attention  to  the  errors  of  the  vulgar 
"  faculty  "  doctrine.     [40.] 

True,  his  own  view  is  wrong.  He  makes  his  presentations 
into  powers  or  activities,  and  bases  Feeling  and  Will  upon  them. 
This  is  to  ignore  the  fact  that  the  latter  are  as  fundamental  as 
presentations ;  Herbart,  however,  obscures  the  illegitimacy  of 
his  doctrine  by  constantly  regarding  presentations  as  already 
forces  or  powers.     [41.] 

If  once  we  recognise  Will  as  a  peculiar  content  of  conscious- 
ness, we  must  infer  that  it  goes  beyond  the  mere  presentation 
of  an  object  in  consciousness ;  it  presses  forward  beyond  the 
sphere  of  the  given.  All  this  is  unintelhgible  on  Herbart's 
view,  which  regards  Will  as  rooted  in  presentations,  and  not  as 
being  a  law  to  itseK,  and  thus  "  free  ".     [42-3.] 

(B)  When  Natorp  tries  to  establish  the  doctrine  of  there 
being  something  peculiar  to  the  Will,  he  does  so  by  pointing 
out  the  supposed  endlessness  of  the  Will.  I  pull  my  boots  on 
in  order  to  go  to  the  post,  in  order  to,  .  .  .  in  order  to  .  .  . 
But  this  only  lands  us  in  the  pleasure-theory.  [Fliigel,  pp. 
265-6.] 

(C)  It  seems  impossible  to  accept  Herbart's  view  of  the  mind 
as  being  fundamentally  presentational.  Why  should  not  Feeling 
and  Will  be  as  ultimate  as  Presentations  ?  Again,  we  are 
conscious  of  the  phenomenon  mentioned  by  Natorp — an  or- 
ganisation of  our  whole  life  in  accordance  with  some  voluntary 
plan,  a  plan  which,  though  modified  by  new  circumstances,  is 
not  abrogated,  but  rather  receives  these  circumstances  into 
itself.  Will  does  not  appear  as  a  mere  product  of  presentations, 
but  often  as  dominating  these,  and  pressing  on  beyond  them. 
It  is  extremely  difficult,  on  Herbart's  theory,  to  explain  the 
unity  of  consciousness  which  is  manifested  in  facts  like  these. 

But  the  reader  of  Natorp's  strictures  might  possibly  imagine 


Kunt  263 

that  Herbart  had  been  the  victim  of  inadvertence.  This  was  not 
so.  His  psychology  may  be  wrong,  but  it  was  dehberately 
adopted.  Herbart  saw  the  fallacy  of  the  vulgar  "  faculty  "  doc- 
trine, and  also  serious  pedagogical  errors  which  follow  from  a 
recognition  of  distinct  "  faculties  ".  Accordingly  he  sought  for  a 
unitary  principle,  and  found  it  (he  thought)  in  presentations. 
Thus  his  error,  if  error  it  is,  must  not  be  regarded  as  one  arising 
out  of  blindness  or  ignorance. 

After  all,  the  presentational  doctrine  has  much  value  for  the 
teacher.  Just  as  a  house  builder  presupposes  that  the  force  of 
gravity  will  wo^  be  absent  and  that  earthquakes  and  eruptions 
will  be  absent  during  the  building  of  a  house,  so  the  teacher 
assumes  normal  conditions  in  his  pupils,  and  thinks  mainly  of 
the  one  factor  which  is  definitely  within  his  own  power  to  confer 
— presentations,  which  constitute  his  -bricks  and  mortar.  If  the 
child  is  normal,  the  normal  impulses,  etc.,  will  be  called  forth  by 
the  presentations.  Thus  Herbart's  Psychology  lays  stress  pre- 
cisely upon  those  mental  processes  which  are  under  the  control 
of  the  teacher. 

These,  then,  are  the  main  points  raised  by  the  controversy  be- 
tween Natorp  and  the  Herbartians.  However  philosophically 
important,  they  have  only  an  indirect  bearing  on  pedagogical 
questions.  Indeed,  Natorp  makes  no  pretensions  of  being  an 
educationist,  and  Professor  Eein  condemns  him  on  this  ground. 


SECTION  XIV. 
KUNZ. 
(1900.) 

Kunz.    Zur  Wilrdigung  der  Herbart-Zillerschen  Padagogik.    Eberle  and 
Rickenbach,  Einsiedeln,  Switzerland,  1900. 

Hebbartianism  is  essentially  Protestant  in  its  inception,  and 
many  of  Ziller's  proposals  bear  this  fact  upon  their  face.  .  Thus, 


ao4  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 


for  example,  the  recognition  of  the  German  Reformation  as  a 
distinct  "culture  stage"  would  be  unwelcome  or  impossible  to 
anyone  but  a  Lutheran. 

A  few  Roman  Catholics  have  identified  themselves  with  the 
movement,  among  them  Vogt,  the  successor  of  Ziller  in  the 
headship  of  the  Union  for  Scientific  Pedagogy,  and  Willmann, 
a  professor  at  Prague.  Such  men  would,  of  course,  have  to 
withhold  approval  from  certain  details  of  Ziller's  plan. 

Some  interest  may  attach  itself  to  a  consideration  of  the  point 
of  view  adopted  by  intelligent  CathoUcs  towards  the  Herbartian 
system  as  a  whole. 

Director  Kunz  has  many  good  words  to  say  for  the  system. 
It  is  pervaded  by  a  noble  spirit,  and  it  stimulates  to  a  deeper 
grasp  of  the  teacher's  task,  especially  to  a  consideration  of  how 
to  base  Instruction  on  psychological  foundations  and  to  carry 
it  out  with  a  definite  goal  in  view.  It  also  rightly  places  religious 
instruction  in  a  central  place  (except  in  the  first  two  years,  where 
the  central  matter  is  not  religious). 

But,  no  system  resting  on  natural  Ethics  and  psychology  can 
endure.  A  divine  revelation  is  necessary  if  we  are  to  understand 
the  human  soul,  and  from  it  we  learn  about  man's  creation  in 
God's  image,  his  fall,  and  his  divine  goal.  Revelation  Hkewise 
gives  us  in  Jesus  Christ  the  true  ideal  to  set  before  us.  Such 
matters  as  these  cannot  be  discovered  by  reason.  Pedagogy 
must  be  based  on  Theology  and  Christianity. 

Hence  the  defect  of  Herbartianism.  To  Her  hart  an  act  was 
good  if  it  agreed  with  the  five  moral  ideas ;  to  Christianity  it  is 
good  if  it  corresponds  to  God's  will.  The  aesthetic  judgment  in 
the  one  case,  God  in  the  other,  gives  the  verdict.  To  Herbart, 
man  is  his  own  lawgiver,  and  there  are  no  supernatural  laws. 

Even  Protestants  have  objected  to  Herbart's  exclusive  stress 
upon  the  aesthetic  judgment ;  thus  Christinger  holds  that  while 
this  judgment  can  give  a  motive,  belief  La  God  is  a  far  stronger 
one.  In  reality,  Christianity  goes  far  deeper  than  Herbartianism. 
The  real  goal  of  education  must  be  the  restoration  of  the  original 
communion  with  God. 


Kunz 


205 


Herbart  rather  late  in  life  (1831)  admitted  that  Higher  help 
was  necessary,  but  both  he  and  his  follower  Ziller  regarded 
religion  rather  as  a  complement  to  morality  than  as  its  founda- 
tion. The  goal,  he  says,  is  strength  of  character;  but  surely 
this  must  rest  on  Eeligion.  Ziller  went  rather  further  than 
Herbart  and,  far  more  explicitly  than  his  master,  regarded  the 
goal  of  education  as  moral  and  religious. 

Many  useful  points  can  be  gathered  from  the  Herbartian 
system,  but  it  is  essentially  Protestant,  and  quite  ignores  the 
Catholic  sacraments ;  while  Catholic  pedagogy  regards  these 
latter  as  communicating  supernatural  blessing. 

The  Herbartians  rightly  protest  against  schools  which  do  not 
educate,  i.e.,  form  character.  They  say  rightly  that  knowledge 
without  virtue  has  no  value,  and  that  the  latter  should  be  the 
one  goal  of  education.  But  this  was  no  new  discovery.  The 
old  Fathers  (Augustine,  Gregory,  and  others)  said  this. 

Herbart' s  psychology  deprives  the  soul  of  all  original  powers. 
Character  rests  on  presentations  or  ideas.  But  this  doctrine 
conflicts  with  Christian  and  pre-Christian  thought;  it  destroys 
the  freedom  of  the  will  and  moral  responsibility,  likewise  the 
unity  of  the  person.  The  mind  is  but  a  presentational  mechan- 
ism. Herbart  expressly  approved  of  Locke's  tabula  rasa,  though 
not  in  the  sense  that  foreign  impressions  can  be  made  upon  it. 
The  materialist  says,  "Man  is  a  product  of  parents,  etc."; 
Herbart  says,  "  Man  is  a  product  of  the  influence  of  his  outer 
world  ".  The  teacher,  for  Herbart,  is  no  longer  a  loving  gar- 
dener, guiding  the  unfolding  of  an  inner  life,  but  a  technologist 
controlling  a  machine,  or  a  chemist  bringing  together  and  mixing 
certain  materials. 

The  Herbartians  rightly  lay  stress  on  Interest,  and  show  how 
by  a  psychological  procedure  this  is  aroused ;  here  come  in  the 
"  formal  steps  ".  But  surely  it  must  not  be  a  balanced  Interest ; 
some  Interests  are  more  important  than  others,  those  of  sym- 
pathy are  more  important  than  those  of  knowledge.  Especially 
essential  are  the  moral  and  religious,  while  Interest  in  knowledge 
is  less  important. 

How  does  Virtue  come  out  of  Interest?    Here  the  Herbartians 


2o6  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

overvalue  Instruction,  for  though  presentations  influence  the  Will 
they  do  not  compel  it.  The  Will  is  free,  and  may  go  counter 
to  insight. 

The  scheme  of  "  formal  steps  "  has  been  but  little  opposed, 
and  on  the  whole  is  useful.  Kehr,  however,  has  insisted  that 
we  must  not  have  one  model  for  everything  ;  each  subject  and 
each  class  requires  special  treatment ;  moreover,  the  scheme 
manifests  signs  of  hairsplitting.  The  formal  steps  are  based  on 
psychological  principles,  but  are  inapplicable  in  some  cases,  e.g., 
the  correction  and  repetition  of  exercises  ;  description ;  the  work- 
ing over  of  any  material  already  arranged  in  encyclopaedic  form 
(catechism.  Sermon  on  the  Mount,  history  tables,  grammar, 
etc.). 

"  Gesinnungsstoff." — This  phrase  ("  character-forming  ma- 
terial ")  is  not  well  chosen;  it  places  religious  teaching  on  the 
same  level  with  profane  history,  whereas  it  is  quite  unique,  a 
supernatural  bread. 

"  GtiUure  Stages.'' — This  doctrine  is  a  mere  figment.  Ziller's 
stages  are  (1)  Darwinian,  (2)  Protestant,  (3)  German.  But  we 
do  not  agree  with  "scientific  pedagogy,"  or  with  the  Eeforma- 
tion,  or,  being  Swiss  republicans,  with  German  imperialism  as 
the  one  ideal  of  state  life.  A  child  from  six  to  fourteen  cannot 
run  through  many  stages  of  human  development,  only  those 
of  childhood.  Sallwiirk  has  rightly  contended  that  the  child  is 
rooted  in  the  present ;  Frohlich,  likewise,  that  the  present-day 
Christian  view  rather  than  the  view  of  men  ages  ago  should  be 
the  one  given  to  the  child. 

Eein  and  others  have  modified  Ziller's  scheme  mainly  by 
choosing  national  culture  stages  (except  in  the  case  of  bib- 
lical instruction).  But  the  whole  doctrine  is  dubious.  We 
must  start  from  the  present,  the  near.  What  is  early  and 
primitive  is  really  far  removed  from  the  child,  and  we  should 
never  make  a  spring  into  the  past  except  (1)  when  this  is 
necessary  to  explain  the  present,  (2)  when  points  of  contact 
already  exist  in  the  child's  mind.  Moreover,  many  "  stages  " 
really  occur  simultaneously. 

Ziller's  detailed  scheme  is  defective  in  the  following  aspects. 


Kunz  207 

(1)  The  fairy  tales  are  not  primitive,  but  very  late  material. 

(2)  Children  know  that  these  stories  are  untrue  ;  what  im- 
pression, then,  will  be  made? 

(3)  The  stories  delight  and  rouse  the  imagination,  but  have 
no  religious  value  ;  often  they  are  immoral.  The  baptized 
child  has  a  right  to  Christian  teaching.  It  is  true,  Ziller  and 
Eein  propose  that  there  should  be  "children's  services"  devoid 
of  systematic  instruction  ;  but  surely  instruction  is  necessary  for 
any  real  influence  to  be  exerted.  And  it  is  not  true  that  biblical 
stories,  properly  selected,  are  too  hard  for  children.  True,  even 
fairy  tales  sometimes  have  a  moral  kernel. 

(4)  Eobinson  Crusoe  is  a  late  and  foreign  story,  and  is  beyond 
the  interest  of  seven  to  eight  year  old  children.  Many  Zil- 
lerians  reject  it.  Willmann  does,  on  the  ground  that  it  is  neither 
classical  nor  national ;  it  deals  with  foreign  regions  and  must  in 
any  case  be  seriously  modified  before  being  used.  Still,  it  has 
its  value  as  material  for  free  reading  with  pupils  of  ten  to  twelve. 

The  very  early  history  of  the  world  has  no  place  in  the  Zillerian 
plan  of  Bible  study,  which  begins  with  the  patriarchs  ;  but  surely 
this  history  is  essential.  The  Zillerians  omit  it  because  they 
cannot  force  it  into  their  eight  stages. 

Only  one,  year  for  Catechism  !  Surely  this  would  be  in- 
adequate even  if  all  the  preceding  years  had  been  a  preparation 
for  it. 

The  Niebelungen  song  may  be  useful  for  upper  schools,  but  is 
scarcely  so  for  the  people's  school,  least  of  all  for  the  lower 
grades  (third  and  fourth  years).  The  notion  that  love  rewards 
with  suffering  is  beyond  young  children.  Moreover,  though 
there  is  exemplified  much  fidelity,  courage,  etc.,  the  song 
abounds  also  in  betrayal,  hate,  revenge,  etc. 

There  is  no  repetition  in  the  Zillerian  plan  ;  each  year 
involves  fresh  work.  Surely,  Christ  ought  to  be  the  centre  of 
all,  not  the  mere  end  of  the  course.  Dorpfeld  himself  admits 
that  there  is  some  need  of  repetition,  such  as  occurs  in  the 
plan  of  "concentric  circles". 

The  notion  of  concentration  is  good,  but  on  Ziller's  plan  there 
is  an  actual  tearing  asunder  of  material,  though  at  times  Ziller 


2o8  The  Critics  of  Herbartianism 

admitted  (here  contradicting  himself)  that  each  department  of 
study  must  assert  its  independent  claims. 

Rein  and  others  have  modified  some  of  ZUler's  details. 
Gesinnungs-unterricht  has  to  be  a  centre  for  the  geography, 
nature  study,  and  language  study.  But  only  in  the  first  year  is 
arithmetic  connected  up  with  Gesinnungs  unterricht ;  drawing 
only  in  the  first  three  years  ;  singing  not  at  all  except  so  far  as 
the  words  are  concerned.  Real  connections  are  largely  ignored 
in  Ziller's  plan.  Interest  is  deadened ;  monotony  is  produced  ; 
the  lesson  is  split  into  tiny  units. 

Surely  spatial  matters  (geography  and  natural  knowledge) 
form  a  better  basis  than  temporal  matters  (history  and  nar- 
ratives). Every  action  presupposes  a  place.  The  Zillerian 
plan  has  been  condemned  by  Bartels,  Frick,  Stoy,  Frohlich, 
Weissmer,  Wehmann,  Wesendonck,  Ruegg,  Sallwiirk,  and 
others. 

The  goal  aimed  at  by  Ziller  can  be  reached  in  another  way 
— by  ethical  concentration.  Moral  and  religious  matters  must 
always  be  kept  in  the  forefront.  The  religious  standpoint  gives 
us  an  ideal  point  of  view  and  a  deep  grasp  of  all  other  subjects. 
A  world-view  must  pervade  everything  ;  religious  instruction 
must  not  be  isolated. 

Natural  concentration  is  good ;  related  departments  may  be 
unified.  The  reading  book  is  valuable  as  connecting  instruction 
in  language  with  instruction  in  things. 

Ziller's  plan  is  quite  impracticable  ;  it  demands  eight  years 
and  a  separate  teacher  for  each.  What  about  schools  which 
have  only  one  class  ?  It  is  true  Hollkamm  has  tried  to  apply 
Zillerianism  even  here,  dividing  the  course  into  four  sections  and 
various  subsections,  and  combining  the  catechism  stage  with 
biblical  history. 


APPENDIX. 

PEOFESSOR  DARROGH  ON  HERBARTIANISM. 

Quite  recently  a  British  critic  has  appeared^  in  the  person  of  Mr. 
(now  Professor)  Darroch,  who,  apparently  since  the  present  writer's 
visit  to  the  University  of  Edinburgh  in  the  autumn  of  1901,  has 
realised  the  capacities  of  the  subject  that  had  been  already,  at  that 
time,  avowedly  selected  for  research  by  the  visitor. 

The  most  prominent  feature  of  Mr.  Darroch's  criticism  is  its  per- 
sistent irrelevancy.  Acquainted  with  the  objections  raised  by  Lotze  to 
Herbart's  psychology  (these  are  given  here  under  "  Ostermann "),  Mr. 
Darroch  reproduces  them  at  some  length  under  the  impression  that  he 
is  thus  damaging  Herbart's  pedagogy.  The  psychology  is,  according 
to  him,  the  foundation  of  the  pedagogy.  The  latter  is  "derived," 
"deduced,"  or  " developed "  from  the  former,  which  is  its  "starting- 
point,"  the  "  point  of  departure,"  containing  the  "  original  assumptions  " 
upon  which  the  pedagogy  is  "  based  "  or  "  ostensibly  founded  ".  Would 
any  reader  believe,  after  this,  that,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  Herbarfs  psychology 
was  elaborated  years  after  his  chief  educational  works  were  written  ? 

Professor  James  is  right.  "  Even  where,  as  in  the  case  of  Herbart, 
the  advancer  of  the  art  of  teaching  was  also  a  psychologist,  the  peda- 
gogics and  the  psychology  ran  side  by  side,  and  the  former  was  not 
derived  in  any  sense  from  the  latter,"  ^  Moreover  the  present  writer 
had  already  hinted  that  "  Herbart's  presentational  mechanism  was  by 
no  means  the  starting-point  of  his  educational  proposals  ".^  The  whole 
question  is  dealt  with  somewhat  fully  in  the  present  work.* 

It  should  not,  however,  be  inferred  that  Mr.  Darroch  has  completely 


^  Herbart ;  a  Criticism  (Longmans,  1903) ;   also  Journal  of  Education^ 
March,  1903. 

2  Talks  with  Teachers,  p.  8. 

8  The  Student's  Herbart,  p.  8.  *  Pp.  28-32. 


2io  Appendix 

ignored  The  Student's  Herbart.  That  little  work,  with  its  list  of  twenty 
or  more  objections  to  Herbartianisra  collected  after  considerable  stixdy  of 
German  educational  literature,  has  clearly  proved  of  immense  service 
to  him.  Mr.  Darroch  never  admits  this  service,  his  only  references  to 
the  work  being  hostile.  But  his  respect  for  the  book  is  such  that  not 
only  does  he  apparently  reproduce  one  after  another  its  arguments  and 
ideaa,  but  he  does  so  even  when  these  arguments  and  ideas  are  perhaps 
of  dubious  validity. 

A  few  of  the  following  instances  may  be  irrelevant —of  that  the  reader 
must  judge  ;  but  the  rest  are  surely  obvious  enough  ;  and,  as  Mr. 
Darroch  has  chosen  to  criticise  The  Stvdent's  Herbart,  a  reply  from  the 
author  of  that  book  will  not  be  out  of  place. 

The  one  writer  speaks  of  "  an  apperceiving  machine  which  responds 
smoothly  and  immediately "  (p.  53);  the  other  follows  suit  with  "an 
apperceiving  machine  which  responds  easily  and  smoothly "  (p.  41). 
The  one  writer  points  out  that  "  two  opposite  dangers  face  our  schools," 
the  first  represented  by  "  heuristic "  advocates,  the  second  by  the 
"didactic  materialism"  to  which  Herbartianism  in  some  of  its  forms 
may  perhaps  tend,  and  goes  on  to  say  that  "  educationists  must  avoid 
both  extremes,"  seeing  that  "  mental  life  is  rhythmic  "  (pp.  25-26) ;  the 
other  writer  follows  suit  with,  "  As,  on  the  one  hand,  the  Herljartians 
lay  the  emphasis  upon  the  one  aspect  of  our  mental  life,  so  in  like 
manner  the  extreme  advocates  of  the  heuristic  method  lay  the  emphasis 
on  the  other,  but  the  truth  lies  in  neither  extreme,  but  in  realising 
clearly  the  twofold  aspect  of  all  intellectual  process  "  (p.  44  ;  stultified 
on  p.  123).  The  one  writer  quotes  the  objection  that  a  robber  exem- 
plifies the  "second  moral  idea"  (p.  50);  the  other  follows  suit  with 
"the  successful  swindler  and  cracksman"  (p.  75).  The  one  writer 
complains  that  "  even  the  much  vaunted  '  Nature  Study '  may  be 
scrappy  and  ineffective  "  (p.  54) ;  the  second  is  tortured  by  the  fact  that 
"  there  is  at  the  present  day  so  much  teaching  of  nature  knowledge  and 
of  elementary  science  of  a  purely  desultory  kind  "  (p.  100).  The  one 
writer  refers  to  Professor  Patrick  Geddes  as  an  advocate  of  placing 
Nature  Study  "  at  the  centre  of  the  circle  of  knowledge  "  (p.  74)  ;  the 
second  writer — apparently  regarding  his  countryman  as  a  representative 
Herbartian — speaks  of  "  some  enthusiasts  "  who  would  "  make  Nature 
Study  the  centre  of  the  circle  of  knowledge  "  (p.  131  ;  also  p.  144),  the 
plain  truth  being  that  no  avowed  Herbartian  has  ever  made  such  a  pro- 
posal. The  one  writer  refers  to  Miss  Ravenhill's  advocacy  of  the  claims 
of  Hygiene  (p.  74) ;  the  second  seems  to  dignify  her  likewise  with  Her- 
bartian honours  (p.  144).  The  one  writer,  omitting  the  original  meaning 
of  "  didactic  materialism  "  (the  term  was  invented  by  Dorpfeld  to  stand 


Appendix  211 

for  the  blind  policy  of  heaping  up  subject  after  subject  in  response  to 
utilitarian,  ecclesiastical  and  other  demands),  uses  the  term  in  a  slightly 
and  allowably  modified  sense  (p.  25) ;  the  second  writer  faithfully 
follows  suit  with  the  same  omission  and  the  same  definition  ;  ^  "  didactic 
materialism,"  says  the  one,  "is  a  belief  in  quantity  apart  from  quality" 
(p.  21) ;  says  the  other,  "  it  looks  to  the  quantity  of  knowledge  acquired 
rather  than  to  its  quality  "  (p.  108).  The  first  writer  ventured  on  a 
new  and  possibly  erroneous  interpretation  of  Herbart's  Ethics,  regarding 
it  as  an  attempt  to  expand  the  concept  of  Virtue  by  the  inclusion  of 
elements  "not  always  included"  in  that  concept  (p.  40);  the  spcond 
writer  discovers  that  Herbart,  "  as  it  seems  to  me  rightly,  extends  the 
conception  (of  morality)  to  include  more  than  mere  goodness"  (p.  66). 
The  first  writer  describes  the  "  second  moral  idea  "  as  "  puzzling  "  (p.  40) ; 
by  some  strange  fatality  the  second  writer  also  finds  it  "  somewhat 
diflicult  to  understand  "  (p.  73).  Still,  when  the  first  writer,  beginning 
to  see  daylight,  suggests  that  the  idea  stands  for  "  greatness,  or  at  least 
a  notion  very  much  like  it,"  in  fact  for  "  strength  and  richness  of  mind  " 
(pp.  40-1),  the  second  also  describes  it  as  one  01 "  greatness  "  or  "  strength 
of  character"  (p.  74),  in  this  case  inserting  quotation  marks  (though 
without  giving  the  source  of  his  quotation.  When  the  one  writer, 
making  a  possibly  erroneous  conjecture,  said,  "  Herbart  felt  that  moral 
reformers  were  too  negative  in  their  views,"  their  chief  message  being 
"  avoid — avoid — avoid  "  (p.  42),  he  was  attempting,  on  his  own  account, 
an  interpretation  of  the  historical  genesis  of  "  second  moral  idea  "  which, 

1  Not  that  Mr.  Darroch  never  strays  into  originality.  He  invents  the 
hybrid  "  didactive  "  ;  he  gives  an  alternative  metaphysical  explanation  of 
the  term  "  materialism  "  (p.  21),  an  explanation  which  the  inventor  Dorpfeld 
would  have  smiled  at ;  lastly  he  avows  that  "  one  section  of  the  (Herbartian) 
school"  has  already  "logically  reached"  the  standpoint  of  "didactic 
materialism".  It  was  rather  questionable  policy  on  the  part  of  the  pre- 
sent writer  to  claim  that  Herbartianism  itself  might  tend  towards  "  didactic 
materialism,"  the  term  itself  having  been  invented  by  an  Herbartian  as 
one  condemnatory  of  a  system  against  which  Herbartianism  was  a  protest : 
however,  questionable  or  not,  the  second  writer  follows  suit,  and  even  brings 
into  existence  a  "section"  of  the  school  which  has  already  reached,  by  a 
"logical  process,"  the  standpoint  here  referred  to  (p.  108).  Will  Mr. 
Darroch  give  some  information  as  to  the  whereabouts  of  this  "  section," 
so  completely  unknown  to  the  present  writer  ?  A  subtle  and  quite  pro- 
blematic tendency  is  one  thing ;  an  arrival  by  "  logical "  process  is  another. 
There  is  not,  and  there  never  has  been,  a  single  Herbartian  who  has  ever 
"  logically  reached  "  the  standpoint  of  "  didactic  materialism  "  ;  Mr.  Darroch 
is  here  challenged  to  mention  one. 


212  Appendix 

whether  correct  or  not  as  an  interpretation,  was  at  any  rate  novel.  In 
point  of  fact  he  knew  as  little  as  Mr.  Darroch  as  to  the  actual  motives 
and  convictions  which  led  Herbart  to  the  enunciation  of  his  system  of 
Ethics.  However,  it  is  satisfactory  to  know  that  the  second  writer  sup- 
ports— though  without  referring  the  interpretation  to  its  original  source 
— the  view  put  forward  by  his  predecessor.  "  Herbart,"  says  Mr.  Darroch, 
"  insists  on  the  positive  aspect  of  virtue  ;  it  is  not  a  mere  not-doing,  but 
a  doing  "(p.  70). 

Again  and  again  the  arguments  and  counter-arguments  of  The  Student's 
Herbart  seem  to  be  reproduced  by  Mr.  Darroch  without  any  acknowledg- 
ment of  their  origin.  The  one  writer  warns  against  confusing  pleasantry 
with  Interest  (p.  51) ;  the  other  feels  called  upon  to  utter  a  similar  warning 
(p.  46).  The  one  writer  defends  Herbart  against  the  "  robber  "  argument 
by  pointing  out  that  "  the  robber  is  not  moral,  for  there  is  a  '  third  moral 
idea '  namely  Benevolence,  and  a  '  fourth  moral  idea '  namely  Justice, 
and  two  others  "  (p.  50) ;  the  other  writer  reproduces  this  without  quoting 
his  source  :  "  against  the  criticism  of  Herbart  it  has  been  more  than  once 
advanced  i  that  we  must  take  into  account  the  other  moral  ideas.  .  .  . 
For  Herbart  also  laid  down  that  we  should  aim  at  Benevolence,  at 
Justice,  at  Equity"  (p.  76).  The  one  writer,  in  his  list  of  supposed 
errors  in  Herbartianism,  says,  "  Herbartianisui  confuses  culture  and 
many-sided  Interest  with  Virtue "  (p.  86) ;  the  second  is  harrowed  by 
the  thought  that  "  the  Herbartian  theory  tends  to  identify  virtue  with 
culture  "  (p.  83).  The  one  writer  points  out  that  Herbartians,  in  the 
eyes  of  some  people,  "  undervalue  difficult  formal  studies  "  (pp.  88-9)  and 
"  lay  too  great  stress  on  Instruction  "  (p.  87)  ;  the  second  writer  bewails 
that  "  along  with  the  overvaluing  of  instruction  we  have  the  under-esti- 
mation,  and,  in  some  cases,  the  almost  total  neglect  of  formal  studies  " 
(p.  112).  The  one  writer  replies  to  his  own  objection — that  there  may 
be  in  Herbartianism  a  subtle  tendency  towards  "  didactic  materialism  " 
— by  referring  to  the  "formal  steps"  as  a  proof  that  the  Herbartians 
are  no  mere  pilers-up  of  indiscriminate  knowledge  (pp.  53,.  89) ;  the 
other  writer's  exposition  takes  the  same  direction  :  "the  Herbartian  may 
reply :  what  about  the  five  formal  steps  of  method  which  form  an  in- 
tegral and  fundamental  part  in  the  theory  ?  "  (p.  109).  The  one  writer, 
after  discussing  ZiUer's  plan  of  "  concentration,"  concludes  that  we  must 
"  keep  in  close  touch  with  each  other  those  subjects  which  throw  light 
upon  each  other  "  (p.  67)  or  "  belong  to  each  other  "  (p.  72) — "  we  must 

1 '» More  than  once."  Yes,  in  Germany.  Phrases  like  these,  so  suggestive 
of  an  encyclopaedic  study  of  Herbartianism,  are  characteristic  of  Mr, 
Darroch's  work.    See  p.  74,  "Napoleon  and  Bacon". 


Appendix  213 

follow  wherever  the  laws  of  Association  naturally  lead  us"  (p.  73) ;  the 
second  writer,  posing  as  a  "critic  of  Herbartianism,"  comes  to  the  same 
conclusion  :  "  the  only  safe  rule  for  the  teacher  is  that  wherever  there 
is  or  has  been  real  relation  between  two  facts  or  groups  of  facts  the 
nature  of  the  relation  should  be  unfolded  and  enforced  "  (p.  133).  The 
one  writer  warns  against  the  artificial  forms  of  "  concentration "  which 
would  "divorce  materials  which  should  naturally  be  united  together" 
(p.  67) ;  the  second  warns  against  "  bonds  of  an  imaginary  nature  "  and 
urges  us  to  be  "  sure  that  there  is,  or  has  been,  a  real  connection  between 
the  facts  which  he  seeks  to  conjoin"  (pp.  1 46-7).  The  one  writer  urges  that 
"subjects  differ  greatly  in  importance"  (p.  73),  some  being  of  "  supreme," 
others  of  "  moderate,"  others  of  "  small "  importance  (p.  22)  ;  the  second 
writer  is  impressed  by  the  fact  that  "  some  subjects  are  more  valuable  in 
the  education  of  the  child  than  others  "  (p-  145)  and  traces  the  recogni- 
tion of  this  truth  to  the  enunciation  of  the  "concentration"  principle. 

Mr.  Darroch  introduces  an  occasional  variation  by,  to  all  appearance, 
borrowing  ideas  from  other  writers  than  the  present.  Page  100  is  a 
supreme  example  of  his  powers.  The  first  complete  thought  is  from 
The  Student's  Herbart,  the  next  two  are  based  on  Professor  Adams's 
chapters  "  Formal  Education "  and  "  Observation,"  and  the  last  two 
on  Professor  James's  chapter  "Apperception".  "Apperception,"  says 
the  latter,  "  means  nothing  more  than  the  act  of  taking  a  thing  into 
the  mind."  "  Apperception,"  says  Mr.  Darroch,  after  having  impressed 
the  same  lesson  as  his  American  original,  "  means  nothing  more  than 
the  act  of  taking  a  thing  into  the  mind,"  an  act  which,  clearly,  Mr. 
Darroch  is  well  able  to  perform.  He,  at  any  rate,  does  not  despise 
"  Instruction  ". 

Idea  after  idea,  argument  after  argument,  conclusion  after  conclusion, 
even  phrase  after  phrase,  does  Mr.  Darroch  seem  to  borrow — almost  ex- 
clusively from  Herbartian  writers  ;  but  his  only  references  to  the  men 
who  have  saved  his  book  from  vacuity  are  hostile. 

What  is  the  conclusion  of  the  matter  1  Mr.  Darroch  has  nothing  fresh, 
original,  or  stimulating  to  present  to  the  teachers  of  Britain.  His 
criticisms  of  Herbartianism  are  either  irrevelant  or  antiquated.  His 
positive  suggestions  are  mainly  those  made  by  the  present  writer 
several  months  before  his  own  essays  appeared,  or  by  other  Herbartian 
or  semi-Herbartian  writers.  Surely  it  is  not  right — not  fair — for  men  to 
borrow  suggestion  after  suggestion  from  a  system  and  then  profess  to  be 
its  critics.  Yet,  after  all,  these  critics  are,  though  unwillingly,  witnesses 
for  the  defence  ;  whenever  they  prepare  to  grapple  with  practical 
educational  problems  they  cannot  help  first  refreshing  themselves  from 
the  Herbartian  spring. 


214  Appendix 

The  writer  has  no  objection  to  Mr.  Darroch,  or  any  one  else,  using 
his  work,  but  he  thinks  the  bounds  of  legitimate  use  are  passed  when 
no  acknowledgment  is  made,  and  when,  to  cover  the  service,  an  attack 
is  made  upon  the  very  book  that  has  proved  so  serviceable.  The  public 
must  judge. 

After  all,  Herbartianism  works.  Education  is  more  an  art  than  a 
science,  and  a  system  of  education  must  be  judged  by  its  fruits.  Perus- 
ing such  a  work  as  Mr.  Darroch's,  an  Herbartian  will  impatiently  re- 
call the  words  of  Edmund  Burke  :  "  Applaud  us  when  we  run ;  console 
us  when  we  fall ;  cheer  us  when  we  recover ;  but  let  us  pass  on — for 
God's  sake  let  us  pass  on  "} 

P.S. — Mr.  Darroch's  reply  is  that  his  Journal  of  Education  article 
was  printed  before  the  University  booksellers  at  Edinburgh  procured 
The  StudenVs  Herhart.  Comment  on  this  is  hardly  necessary  in  view  of 
the  facts  (1)  that  the  quotations  given  above  are  entirely  taken  from 
Mr.  Darroch's  hook,  not  his  article ;  (2)  that  his  book  followed  The 
Student's  Herhart  at  an  interval  of  six  months  ;  (3)  that  in  it  he  refers 
three  times  by  name  to  The  Student's  Herhart. 

The  fact  is,  Mr.  Darroch  wrote  in  a  hurry,  and  did  not  do  justice 
either  to  himself  or  to  the  men  from  whom  he  hastily  gathered  ideas. 
He  is  surely  capable  of  better  things  than  this. 

1  Speech  at  Bristol,  1780. 


INDEX  I. 


Herbart,  life  of,  37-9. 
Herbartianism 

as  left  by  Herbart,  39-43. 

its  unpretentious  position  at  his 
death,  39,  43-4. 

attitude  of  Stoy  and  his  followers, 
45-6. 

attitude  of  Dorpfeld,  47-9. 

leading  doctrines  of  Ziller,  53-6. 

rupture  between  the  Zillerians  and 
the  other  Herbartians,  45-6,  51, 
67-8. 

Herbartianism  outside  of  Ger- 
many, 52,  56-7,  62,  75-6. 

controversies  over  Herbartianism, 
66. 

reasons  for  the  influence  of  Her- 
bartianism, 52,  57. 

present  position  of  Herbartianism 
in  Germany,  65-9. 

in  Britain,  69-75. 

V.  Frobelianism,  30,  55,  83,  85, 
96. 

unpractical  or  overpractical  ?  102, 
107,  108,  112,  129,  155-6,  160-1, 
166,  167. 

and  physical  facts  and  ciilture, 
102. 

Christianity  and  religious  instruc- 
tion, 104,  106, 107, 109,  112,  114, 
115,  157,  167,  204. 

admitted  excellences,  105-6,  111, 
125,  147,  204. 

reactionary  elements,  110,    128-9, 
129,  164,  167. 
The  Moral  Significance  of  Herbar- 
tianism, 5-19  (especially  8,  18), 
84,  87,  195. 

moral  importance  of  ideas  owing 
to  their  connection  with  Voli- 
tion, 4,  7,  10,  17,  27,  41,  47,  92, 
103,  124,  129. 


The  Moral  Significance  of  Herbar- 
tianism (continued). 

generation  of  Virtue  out  of  ideas 
by  way  of  Apperception  and  In- 
terest, 6-7,  12,  15,  18,  19,  40,  56, 
91,  146,  190-1,  197-9. 

generation  of  Vice  out  of  ignorance 
or  poverty  of  ideas,  7,  9-10,  11, 
12,  13,  15,  17,  91,  191. 

evil  an  effect,  not  an  entity,  10-13. 

Habit  V.  Insight,  3-4,  92,  101,  124, 
129,  170. 

the  Interest  doctrine,  6,  7,  8,  9, 
18,  40,  45,  56,  72,  91,  105,  111, 
113,  123,  157-8,  159-60,  169,  190, 
196-7,  197-8,  205. 

Herbartianism  a  gospel  of  positive 
moral  reform,  9, 10, 11,  86, 198-9. 

"  Educative  instruction "  versus 
"  technological  instruction,"  60, 
87,  91,  102,  110,  111,  112,  113, 
156,  161.  167,  169,  176,  194-5, 
196-7,  205. 

Herbartianism  and  "  soft  peda- 
gogics " ;  supposed  absence  of 
strenuousness,  19,  75,  96,  100, 
101,  162,  171,  175-6. 

Herbartianism  and  the  gymnastic 
doctrine  or  fallacy,  20,  21,  22-3, 
85,  88-9,  96-7,  161,  162,  163. 
Herbart's  Ethics,  42-3. 

apparent  artificiality  of  Herbart's 
ethics ;  absence  of  unity,  32,  99, 
103,  123. 

Herbart  and  Sidgwick,  33,  201. 

the  "  second  moral  idea  "  and  its 
importance,  11,  12,  100,  102. 

no  "moral  idea"  valid  in  isola- 
tion, 12,  100-1. 

Herbart's  Ethics  based  on  "  taste  " 
or  the  "  aesthetic  judgment,"  99, 
101,  122,  123,  136,  149,  153,  200. 


2l6 


Index 


HerharVs  Ethics  {continued). 

character  the  one  end  of  educa- 
tion, 39,  53,  87,  102,  194-9. 

inability  to  give  practical  guidance, 
99. 

the  five  ideas  not  co-ordinate,  100. 

criticism  of  the  "five  ideas,"  100- 
101. 

Determinism  and  Libertarianism, 
5,  122,  134,  141,  146-7,  179,  205. 
Herbart's  Psychology  and  Philo- 
sophy. 

metaphysical  doctrine,  99,  118, 
131. 

his  Preseptationalism  versus  a 
Spiritualistic  Psychology,  4-5, 
28-9,  39,  101,  112,  118-23,  131-6, 
179,  201-3,  205. 

possible  weaknesses,  4,  20,  21,  29- 
31,  32,  33,  64,  104,  112,  118-25, 
133-5,  155,  201-3. 

the  "faculty"  doctrine,  39,  112, 
121,  123,  133-5,  157,  201-3,  205. 

Herbart's  educational  doctrines 
not  deduced  from  his  psychology, 
31,  38,  65,  Appendix. 

value  of  Presentationalism  for 
educational  purposes,  28-31,  32, 
33,  40,  83,  84. 

consequent  value  of  Instruction 
in  the  Herbartian  system;  the 
"content"  of  studies,  the  con- 
ferring of  knowledge,  are  impor- 
tant, 40-1,  84-5,  86,  88-9,  92,  95, 
102,  103,  104-5,  110,  113,  121, 
123,  143,  156,  161,  169,  173,  196, 
205-6. 

place  of  Discipline  and  Training 
in  the  Herbartian  system,  42, 92, 
101,  110,  146,  156,  170,  173,  191, 
193-4,  195-6. 

vitality  of  Presentationalism,  31. 

Presentationalism,  Heredity, 
Physiology  and  Physical  Edu- 
cation, 29,  40-1,  94,  133,  155, 
160,  166,  167,  169-70. 

punishments,  105,  193-4. 

relation  of  feelings  to  ideas,  32, 
121-2,  124. 

uselessness  of  working  merely  on 
the  feelings,  23,  125. 

"  developing -presentative  Instruc- 
tion," 21,  170-1,  173-7. 


Herbarfs  Psychology  and  Philosophy 

(continued). 
Didactic     Materialism,     Didactic 

Formalism,  20-1,  48,  84,  86,  93, 

95,  113,  161,  162,  171. 
Apperception. 

meaning  of,  41,  118. 

significance  of,  14-17. 

relation  to  Anschauung,  36-7,  41, 

188. 
relation  to  Association,  83-4. 
relation  to  Interest  and  Attention, 

16-17,  92,  105,  118. 
"  Oesinnungsstoff"      {=  humanistic 

material). 
importance  of,  8,  26,  53-4, 72-3,  87, 

91,  92,  94-5,  110,  161,  168,  206. 
neglect  of,  13,  14,  72-3. 
The  "  Formal  Steps  "  of  Instrtiction, 

21,  23-4,  41-2,  45,  49,  56. 87-8,  95, 

97, 106,  111,  117, 124, 125-30, 162, 

164, 167-8, 171,  174-5,  177,  205-6. 
modifications  and  dangers  of,  24, 

87,  117,  126-30,  162. 
inapplicable  to  the    teaching    of 

dexterities,  74,  87,  127. 
inapplicable  to  certain  other  cases, 

126,  206. 
The  Doctrine  of  "  Culture  Stages," 

14,  26,  45,  48,  54,  71-2,  95,  109, 

113-6,  123,  148-54,  158,  168,  197, 

206. 
scientific  basis  of  the  doctrine,  26- 

7,  95,  113,  148,  148-51,  172. 
"  fairy  tales,"  the  Odyssey,   etc., 

27,  43,  48,  55,  87,  91,  94,  95, 106, 

109,   114,   125,  149,  153-4,  158, 

168,  172,  207. 
Robinson  Crusoe,  27,  55,  94,  109, 

114,  149,  154,  158,  168,  172,  207. 
The  Old  Testament,  154. 
postponement  and  abbreviation  of 

the  life  of  Christ,  27,  48,  110, 

115,  150,  168,  207. 

the   Reformation   stage,   55,   110, 

114-5. 
advantages,  48. 
difficulties,  48,  55,  109-10,  113-6, 

123,    149-50,   158,  164-5,   167-8, 

172,  206-7. 
repetition  ignored,  171,  207. 
"concentric  circles,"  48,  62,  114, 

116, 173,  207. 


Index 


217 


The  Doctrine,  of  "  Concentration"  24, 

45-6,  47,  53-4,  58,  88-90, 91-2,  94- 

5,  106,  110,  116-7,  123,  149,  158, 

168,  173,  207-8. 
need  for  "  concentration,"  24,  54, 

89,  91-2,  94-5. 
two  interpretations,  24-5. 
increasing  recognition  of  the  need 

for  unification  of  studies,  24-5, 

70,  92. 
limits    of    ♦'  concentration,"    90, 

116. 
"  concentration "      according      to 

Ziller,  25-6,  54. 


The    Doctrine    of   "  Concentration " 

(continued). 

difficulties  and   modifications    of 

Ziller's   scheme,  26,  59,   108-9, 

116,  161,  208. 

"  concentration,"      according     to 

Dorpfeld,  26,  47. 
"  concentration "     according     to 

Stoy,  45-6. 
"  concentration  "  according  to  Dr. 

Findlay,  88. 
rational  concentration,  26. 
The  teaching  of  dexterities,  87. 
Practical  purswits,  89,  91. 


INDEX  II. 

References  to  Herbart  and  Ziller  are,  except  in  a  few  imtances,   omitted. 


ACKERMANN,  57,  69. 

Adams,  5,  7,  19,  21,  33,  61,  71,  74, 

82-6,  Appendix. 
Adler,  71. 
Andreas,  59. 
Armstrong,  20,  24,  70. 
Arnold,  10-11. 
Augustine,  205. 

Bacon,  157. 

Ballauf,  121,  122. 

Bartels,  19,  26,  34,  58,  62,  112-7,  208. 

Barth,  51,  57. 

Bell,  37. 

Bell,  Canon,  71. 

Benson,  20. 

Bergemann,  34,  65,  169-73. 

Beyer,  57,  60,  69,  150-1,  152. 

Bliedner,  57. 

Branford,  70. 

Burke,  8,  Appendix. 

Butler,  101. 

Christinqer,  19,  34,  166-9,  204. 

Cicero,  157. 

Clement,  71. 

Clifton,  Bishop  of,  8. 

Cobbe,  Miss,  15. 

Comenius,  23,  105, 113, 116,  117, 126, 

162. 
Conrad,  57. 
Cornelius,  43,  185. 
Credner,  57. 

Darroch,  Preface  and  Appendix. 

Darwin,  151. 

De  Garmo,  69,  74,  75,  78,  79,  80,  81-2, 

96-7. 
Dewey,  76. 


Dickens,  157. 

Diesterweg,  113. 

Dittes,  12, 19,  34,  59,  98-106,  111,  112, 

180  183 
Dodd,  28,  69,  71,  74,  75,  93-5. 
Dorpfeld,  22,  24,  26,  35,  39,  50,  56,  57, 

66,  78,  80,  87-9,  94,  114, 116, 138, 

164,  176,  207. 

—  Life  of,  46-7. 

—  Doctrines  of,  47-9. 
Drews,  163-6. 
Drobisch,  43. 

EcKOPF,  75,  79. 

Felkin,  2,  38,  42,  74,  78,  80. 
Fennel,  97. 

Fichte,  37,  138,  181,  186,  187. 
Findlay,  5,  7,  26,  53,  70,  74,  86-90, 

127. 
Florin,  59. 
Plugel,   30,  57,  64,  65,  67,  98,  180, 

183-4,  200,  202. 
Foltz,  176. 

Frick,  57,  69,  82,  208. 
Frbbel,  30,  36,  83,  85,  92,  96,  169. 
Frohlich,  57,  58,  59,  60,  98,  99,  109, 

113,  206,  208. 

Glockne'r,  98,  103,  104,  105,  106. 

Goethe,  54,  71. 

Gopfert,  62, 

Grabs,  57. 

Gray,  12,  13. 

Gregory,  205. 

Hall,  71. 

Hayward,  6,  11,  25,  27,  67, 72,  74,  82. 


330 


Index 


Herbart,  2,  3,  4,  6, 19,  23,  24,  26,  etc. 

—  Life  of,  36-9. 

—  Doctrines  of,  39-43. 
Heyn,  66-7. 
Hollkamm,  208. 
Hubatsch,  22,  34,  154-62. 

James,  4,  5,  17,  19,  82,  Appendix. 
Just,  57,  63,  65,  69,  98,  101,  102,  103, 
104,  180,  188-9,  200. 

Kant,  38, 138, 139, 178, 181,  186, 195, 

199-201. 
Kehr,  206. 
Kern,  57. 
Klemm,  56,  69. 
Koch,  184. 
Kunz,  203-8. 
Kuoni,  62. 

Langb,  a.  F.,  78. 

Lange,  K.,  57,  69,  74,  76,  80. 

Laurie,  70. 

Lazarus,  Preface,  43. 

Lentz,  116. 

Lessing,  71. 

Linde,  34,  173-7. 

Locke,  2,  40,  113,  179,  205. 

Lodge,  20. 

Lotze,  20,  180. 

Luther,  113. 

Maoeb,  43. 
McMurray,  75. 
Menard,  151. 
Meredith,  11. 
Mulliner,  74,  79. 
Munk,  155. 
Miinsterberg,  31,  184. 
Myers,  10. 

Nahlowsky,  43,  185. 

Nathan,  122. 

Natorp,  1,  4,  30,  31,  34,  64,  178-203. 

Niederer,  187,  188. 

Niederley,  57. 

Niemeyer,  36,  37, 105,  113. 

Nietzsche,  201. 

OsTERMANN,  10,  23,  31,  32,  34,  63-4, 
112,  117-25,  180,  183. 

Parkbb,  76,  82. 


Perry,  70. 

Pestalozzi,  36,  37,  88,  44,  79, 102, 105, 

113,  130,  131,  138-47,  180,  181, 
185-8,  195,  196. 

Pickel,  57. 
Plato,  3. 
Potter,  71. 

Rein,  18,  29,  34,  57,  59,  60,  65,  69, 74, 
80,  86,  114,  128,  150,  175,  180, 
184,  185,  187,  190,  193,  196-7, 
203,  206,  207,  208. 

Richter,  24,  34,  128-30. 

Rissmann,  63. 

Rooper,  Preface,  12,  90-3. 

Rousseau,  36,  115,  153. 

Ruegg,  208. 

Ruskin,  15,  100. 

Sallwurk,  26,  57,  58,  59,  69,  98, 113, 

114,  147-54,  206,  208. 
Sander,  58. 

Schiller,  195. 
Schleiermacher,  181,  182. 
Schmidt,  177. 
Schumann,  57. 
Seneca,  157. 
Shurman,  19. 
Sidgwick,  33,  189,  201. 
Smith,  79. 

Socrates,  3,  157,  163. 
Spencer,  54-5,  71,  96. 
Staude,  57,  66,  113,  128,  129,  150. 
Stead,  73. 
Steiger,  37,  78. 
Steinthal,  43. 
Stout,  31. 

Stoy,  38,  39,  51,  56,  57,  82,  98,  112, 
208. 

—  Life  of,  44-5. 

—  Doctrines  of,  45-6. 
Striimpell,  43,  57,  122,  184,  186. 

Tennyson,  Preface,  13. 
Thilo,  57,  98,  99. 
Thrandorf,  57,  60. 

—  and  Meltzer,  66. 
Thring,  5,  21. 
Trendlenburg,  180. 
Triiper,  184. 

Upeb,  69,  74,  75,  80, 184. 


Index 


22t 


Van  Liew,  42,  80. 

Vogel,  35,  130-47,  180. 

Vogt,  56,  57,  58,  60,  112,  114,  204. 

Voigt,  2,  81. 

Volkmann,  43,  185. 

Voltaire,  157. 


Waitz,  43,  185. 
Wehmann,  208. 
Weissmer,  208. 
Wesendonck,  34,  51,  59,  63,  107-12, 

208. 
Wiessner,  57. 
Wiget,  57,  62,  187. 


Willmann,  66,  63,  65,  150,  201,  204, 

207. 
Wundt,  119. 

ZiLLEB,  14,  23,  24,  26,  27,  38,  39,  54, 
56,  57,  59,  etc. 

—  Life  of,  49-53. 

—  Characteristics,  49-53,  107. 

—  Doctrines  of,  53-6. 

—  on  school  organisation,  107. 

—  on  naodern  languages,  107-8. 

—  on    inductive    methods    of    lan- 

guage-teaching, 108. 
Zillig,  57,  60. 
Zinser,  80. 


THE   ABEBDEEK   UNIVEBSITT   PBESS  LIMITED, 


BY  THEiSAME  AUTHOR 

THE  REFORM  OF  MORAL  AND  BIBLICAL  EDUCATION 

ON    THE    LINES    OP    HERBARTIANISM,    GKITICAL    THOUGHT 
AND   THE   ETHICAL  NEEDS   OF   THE   PRESENT  DAY. 


EDUCATION. — "An  extremely  clever,  even  brilliant  book  ;  also  distinctly  novel 
and — we  feel  tempted  to  say — therefore,  distinctly  welcome.  .  .  .  Interesting  from 
cover  to  cover." 

WESTERN  TIMES.— "  Almost  as  exciting  and  exhilarating  as  Jnles  Verne,  .  .  . 
An  admirable  volume  of  exposure  and  suggestion." 

THE  SCHOOL  WORLD. — "This  book,  as  we  should  have  expected,  is  interesting 
from  cover  to  cover.  .  .  .  There  was  room  for  Dr.  Hay  ward's  book,  and  with  the 
main  contentions  we  are  wholly  in  agreement.  ...  A  thorough  lighting  book." 

WESTMINSTER  REVIEW.— "The  newly  constituted  authorities  must  stand  in 
need  of  help  and  guidance  in  arranging  their  schemes  for  instruction  in  elementary 
schools,  and  we  learn  from  Mr.  Frank  H.  Hayward  how  urgent  this  need  is.  .  .  . 
We  unhesitatingly  urge  all  teachers  and  all  members  of  committees  of  management 
to  study  his  book." 

TIMES. — "Dr.  Hayward  is  an  Herbartian  and  an  enthusiast  who  is  aghast  at 
the  lack  of  method  and  enlightenment  in  the  teaching  of  religion  and  the  training 
of  character,  especially  in  primary  schools.  His  solution  of  the  religious  difficulty 
is  '  Neither  Church  nor  Dissent,  but  Educationists, '  and  this  maxim  he  urges  in  a 
number  of  racy  chapters  criticising  the  present  practice,  and  giving  a  useful 
'Scheme  of  Instruction'." 

THE  LITERARY  WORLD. — "The  Moral  Instruction  League  can  congratulate 
itself  on  having  a  protagonist  so  able  and  so  fearless." 

Mr.  W.  T.  STEAD  in  the  "  Review  of  Reviews  ". — "  Mr.  Hayward  has  flung  into 
the  educational  arena  one  of  the  brightest,  brainiest  and  breeziest  books  that  it  has 
been  my  good  fortune  to  read  for  some  time.  ...  It  would  be  easy  to  fill  pages 
with  extracts  from  his  incisive  and  audacious  frontal  attack  upon  the  system  of 
instruction  which  both  the  defenders  and  the  opponents  of  the  Education  Act  seem 
to  regard  as  beyond  criticism." 

WESTERN  DAILY  MERCURY.— "  A  bold  book,  an  outspoken  book.  There  is 
audacity  in  its  views  and  its  language,  but  it  is  the  audacity  of  an  apostle's  fervour. 
...  A  book  emphatically  worth  the  reading." 

WEDNESBURY  HERALD.—' '  The  writer  is  a  perfect  master  of  his  subject.  The 
book  ought  to  be  read  at  this  juncture  by  every  teacher  in  day  and  Sunday  schools, 
by  members  of  town  and  county  councils,  and  all  to  whom  the  new  Education  Act 
appeals  for  the  exercise  of  some  amount  of  common-sense  in  putting  this  much- 
neglected  branch  of  education  upon  a  proper  footing." 

WESTERN  MORNINQ  NEWS.—"  We  would  urge  every  one  interested  in  educa- 
tion to  examine  Mr.  Hayward' s  scheme." 

SCOTSMAN. — "An  able  study  of  the  remediable  errors  in  existing  methods  of 
education." 

YORKSHIRE  POST. — "Mr.  Hay  ward's  book  contains  much  sound  criticism  and 
advice,  and  many  original  suggestions  ;  it  is  conceived  in  the  right  spirit  and 
appears  at  the  right  time," 

BRISTOL  TIMES,— "An  original  work  by  Dr.  Hayward  which  cannot  be  too 
widely  read.  His  arm  stretches  wide  and  his  spade  digs  deep,  and  there  is  probably 
not  an  educationist  living  who  would  not  find  therein  innumerable  suggestions." 

WESTERN  DAILY  PRESS.— "It  is  a  bold  step  he  has  taken,  but  it  may  fairly 
be  said  that  he  has  laid  his  plans  on  a  broad  and,  as  far  as  possible,  inotfensivo 
basis.  ...  He  does  not  deal  merely  in  generalities.  He  has  set  forth  a  scheme  of 
character-forming  instruction  which  must  have  been  the  work  of  much  labour  and 
time.  .  .  .  Dr.  Hay  ward's  book  is  very  readable." 

GLASGOW  HERALD. — "The  book  contains  a  very  well-informed  discussion  of 
this  subject,  and  presents  in  a  remarkably  vivid  way  many  topics  well  worthy  of 
the  serious  consideration  of  teachers  and  school  managers." 

DUNDEE  ADVERTISER.—"  Apart  from  its  important  subject,  this  book  is 
written  in  a  very  lively  style.  ,  .  .  Every  school  board  member  should  peruse  this 
volume,  if  it  be  only  for  the  purpose  of  mortifying  the  flesh  by  taking  the  conceit 
out  of  himself." 


THE  REFORM  OF  MORAL  AND  BIBLICAL  mmM-cmtinued. 

BRISTOL  MERCURY  (Leading  Article).— "A  well-studied  contribution  to  the 
science  of  education  in  tlie  domain  which  alone  gives  real  trouble." 

EAST  ANQLIAN  DAILY  TIMES.—"  The  Herbartian  doctrine  or  method  .  .  . 
is  presented  by  Mr.  Hay  ward,  in  the  constructive  portion  of  his  work,  with  an 
attractiveness  which  some  will  find  irresistible." 

NEW  AQE. — "Some  admirable  criticisms  on  present-day  methods  of  moral  and 
religious  teaching.  .  .  .  We  commend  this  volume  to  the  serious  attention  of  school 
managers  and  teachers." 

THE  PRESIDENT  ELECT  OF  THE  NATIONAL  UNION  OF  TEACHERS  (Q. 
Sharpies,  Esq.),  who  quoted  from  the  booii  at  the  Buxton  Conference,  says : 
"  No  book  has  moved  me  so  profoundly  for  many  years  as  this  startling  work.  It 
should  be  read  by  every  educationist  in  the  country." 

ETHICS. — "We  can  strongly  recommend  it.  Its  exposure  of  the  utter  inade- 
quacy of  present  educational  methods  towards  moral  ends  is  most  scathing.  .  .  . 
The  book  is  packed  with  useful  information,  proceeds  from  a  scholarly  mind,  has 
moral  power,  and  has  many  practical  and  detailed  suggestions  in  the  direction  of 
reform." 

THE    STUDENT'S    HERBART. 

A  BRIEF  EDUCATIONAL  MONOGRAPH  DEALING  WITH  THE 
SYSTEM  INITIATED  BY  HERBART  AND  DEVELOPED  BY 
STOY,  DORPPELD  AND  ZILLER. 


Professor   ADAMS,  Professor  of  Education  in  the   University  of  London, 

writes:  "I  read  with  much  interest  y  ova  Student's  Herhart.  It  is  an  admirable 
bird's-eye  view  of  the  Herbartian  Pedagogy,  and  cannot  fail  to  be  of  great  service 
to  students.  Perhaps  its  most  valuable  feature  is  the  perspective  it  affords  of  the 
important  and  the  unimportant.  The  selection  and  arrangement  are  excellent. 
For  the  size  of  the  book  it  is  amazingly  complete.  You  have  certainly  rendered  a 
great  service  to  the  theory  of  education  in  England  by  giving  us  this  brightly 
written  and  instructive  monograph.  I  look  forward  mth  much  interest  to  your 
promised  work  on  the  Critics  of  Herbartianism." 

EDUCATION. — "The  terse,  direct  and  forceful  manner  in  which  Dr.  Hayward 
tells  us  what  he  has  to  say  attracts  and  rivets  one's  attention.  .  .  .  We  trust  that 
those  who  have  not  yet  perused  its  pages  will  do  so." 

THE  LITERARY  WORLD. — "A  concise  and  lucid  exposition  of  the  great  re- 
former's principles  which  are  winning  more  and  more  enthusiastic  adherents  in  the 
ranks  of  educationists." 

UNIVERSITY  EXTENSION  JOURNAL.— "  This  delightful  little  book.  .  .  . 
Written  in  a  clear,  popular  manner,  it  will  do  much  to  enable  the  student  of 
Herbartian  literature  to  grasp  the  main  principles  of  the  great  master,  and 
appreciate  the  changes  which  have  been  introduced  by  modern  writers  " 

SECONDARY  EDUCATION. — "  It  is  quite  impossible  to  give  here  a  satisfactory 
abstract  of  this  delightful  account  of  Herbartianism.  We  can  only  say  that  few, 
we  think,  can  read  the  little  book  without  receiving  encouragement,  stimulus  and 
practical  help  in  their  work." 

GLASGOW  HERALD. — "Teachers  and  school  board  members  should  read  this 
short  and  vigorous  exposition  of  a  very  earnest  thinker  and  writer  on  education." 

WESTMINSTER  REVIEW.— "No  better  introduction  than  this  to  the  study  of 
the  works  of  the  master  could  be  desired." 

MANCHESTER  GUARDIAN.— "  Any  one  wishing  to  gain  a  little  knowledge  of 
Herbartianism  rapidly  cannot  do  better  than  read  The  StudenVs  Herbart  by  Dr. 
F.  H.  Hayward.  The  writer  has  caught  some  of  the  enthusiasm  of  Herbart  and 
his  followers,  but  is  not  blind  to  their  weaknesses,  devoting  one  of  his  tive  sections 
to  the  consideration  of  them." 

THE  GUARDIAN. — "  One  can  only  wish  that  there  were  equally  clear  and  concise 
monographs  on  other  educationists. " 


University  of  California 

SOUTHERN  REGiONAL  LiBRARY  FACILITY 

405  Hiigard  Avenue,  i^s  Angeles,  CA  90024-1388 

Return  this  material  to  tiie  library 

from  wliich  it  was  borrowed. 


UC  SOUTHERN  REGIONAL  LIBRARY  FACILITY 


I  III    I  II    II    II  I  I  II  I    II  I  II       III  I     I 

i         A     000  961  534     5 


Education 

Library 

LB 
6kQ 
H33c 
cop«2