Skip to main content

Full text of "An essay on mediaeval economic teaching"

See other formats


^pr^d 



CORNELL 

UNIVERSITY 

LIBRARY 




UNDERGRADUATE LIBRARY 



DATE DUE 




HB 79.013°™" ""'™™">"-"'"^ 

*" mSmmmm«i^''^' *"«'"°'"'«: teaching. 




3 1924 016 917 134 




Cornell University 
Library 



The original of tliis book is in 
tine Cornell University Library. 

There are no known copyright restrictions in 
the United States on the use of the text. 



http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924016917134 



MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 



AN ESSAY ON 

MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC 

TEACHING 



BY 

GEORGE O'BRIEN 

LITT.D., M.R.I.A. 

AUTHOB or 'THX XCOirOHIO HISTOBY OT IBSLAHD IS THE 

SSyKIII]IEI7TH OEHTUBT,' AHD 'iHB EOOITOMIC HISTOBY 

OT nCELAHD IN THK EIGHTEENTH OENTnBY ' 



LONGMANS, GREEN, AND CO. 
39 PATERNOSTER ROW, LONDON 

FOURTH AVENUE & 30TH STREET, NEW YORK 
BOMBAY, CALCUTTA, AND MADRAS 

1920 



LIBRARY 

OF 

EDWARD SCHUSTER 



hb 1 



/// ■ 



TO THE 

REV. MICHAEL ORONIN 

M.A., D.D. 
UNIVBBSIir OOIXEGE, DUBLIN 



AUTHOR'S NOTE 

I WISH to express my gratitude to the Rev. Dr. Cronin 
for his kindness in reading the manuscript, and for many 
valuable suggestions which he made ; also to Father T. A. 
Knlay, S.J., and Mr. Arthur Cox for having given me 
much assistance in the reading and revision of the 
proofs. 



CONTENTS 



CHAPTEK I 



INTRODUCTORY 

Section 1. Aim and Scope of the Essay 
Section 2. Explanation ov the Title 

§ 1. Mediseval 

§ 2. Eoonomio 

§ 3. Teaching 
Section 3. Valite of the Study of the StJbject 
Section 4. Division of the Subject 



PAOX 
1 
1 

3 

3 

6 

19 

28 

33 



CHAPTER II 

PROPERTY 41 

-Section 1. The Right to Procure and Dispense Property 41 
Section 2. Duties beoaeding the Acquisition and Use 

OF Peopeety 67 

Section 3. Peopeety in Human Beings .... 88 



CHAPTEB III 

DUTIES REGARDING THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 102 

Section 1. The Sale of Goods 102 

§ 1. The JviBt Price 102 

§ 2. The Just Price when Price fixed by Law . 106 

§ 3. The Just Price when Price not fixed by Law 109 
§4. The Just Price of Labour . . .120 

§ 5. Value of the Conception of the Just Price 123 

§ 6. Was the Just Price Subjective or Objective ? 127 

§ 7. The Mediseval Attitude towards Commerce 136 

§ 8. CamUum 165 



viii MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

SaonoN 2. The Salb of thb Use oe Monet 
§ 1. Usury in Greece and Rome 
§ 2. Usury in the Old Testament 
§ 3. Usury in the First Twelve Centuries of 

Christianity .... 

§ 4. The Medieeval Prohibition of Usury . 
§ 6. Extrinsic Titles .... 
§ 6. Other Cases in which more than the Loan 

could be repaid .... 
§ 7. The Justice of Unearned Income 
§ 8. Bent Charges ..... 

§ 9. Partnership 

§ 10. Concluding Remarks on Usury 
Section 3. The Machineby of Exchange 



PAOB 

159 
159 
163 

166 
173 

184 

193 
198 
203 
205 
212 
214 



CHAPTER IV 

CONCLUSION 222 

INDEX 232 



CHAPTER I 
INTRODUCTORY 

Section 1. — Aim and Scope of the Essay 

It is the aim of this essay to examine and present 
in as concise a form as possible the principles and 
rules which guided and regulated men in their 
economic and social relations during the period 
known as the Middle Ages. The faUure of the 
teaching of the so-called orthodox or classical 
pohtical economists to bring peace and security to 
society has caused those interested in social and 
economic problems to inquire with ever-increasing 
anxiety into the economic teaching which the 
orthodox economy replaced ; and this inquiry 
has revealed that each system of economic thought 
that has from time to time been accepted can be 
properly understood only by a knowledge of the 
earher system out of which it grew. A process 
of historical inquiry of this kind leads one ulti- 
mately to the Middle Ages, and it is certainly 
not too much to say that no study of modern 
European economic thought can be complete or 
satisfactory unless it is based upon a knowledge 
of the economic teaching which was accepted in 
mediaeval Europe. Therefore, while many wiU 
deny that the economic teaching of that period 
is deserving of approval, or that it is capable of 



2 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

being applied to the conditions of the present 
day, none will deny that it is worthy of careful and 
impartial investigation. 

There is thus a demand for information upon 
the subject dealt with in this essay. On the 
other hand, the supply of such information in the 
Enghsh language is extremely limited. The books, 
such as Ingram's History of Political Economy 
and Haney's History of Economic TJumght, which 
deal with the whole of economic history, necessarily 
devote but a few pages to the Middle Ages. 
Ashley's Economic History contains two excellent 
chapters deahng with the Canonist teaching ; but, 
whUe these chaptra's contain a mass of most 
valuable information on particular branches of 
the mediaeval doctrines, they do not perhaps 
sufficiently indicate the relation between them, 
nor do they lay sufficient emphasis upon 
the fundamental philosophical principles out 
of which the whole system sprang. One can- 
not sufficiently acknowledge the debt which 
Enghsh students are under to Sir WiUiam Ashley 
for his examination of mediaeval opinion on 
economic matters ; his book is frequently and 
gratefully cited as an authority in the following 
pages ; but it is undeniable that his treatment 
of the subject suffers somewhat on accoimt of 
its being introduced but incidentally into a 
work dealing mainly with Enghsh economic 
practice. Dr. Cunningham has also made many 
valuable contributions to particular aspects of 
the subject ; and there have also been published, 
principally in CathoUc periodicals, many im- 



INTRODUCTORY 3 

portant monographs on special points ; but so 
far there has not appeared in Enghsh any treatise, 
which is devoted exclusively to mediaeval eco- 
nomic opinion and attempts to treat the whole 
subject completely. It is this want in our eco- 
nomic literature that has tempted the author to 
pubUsh the present essay, although he is fuUy 
aware of its many defects. 

It is necessary, in the first place, to indicate 
precisely the extent of the subject with which we 
propose to deal ; and with this end in view to 
give a definition of the three words, ' mediceval, 
economic, teaching J 



Section 2. — Explanation of the Title 

§ 1. Mediceval 

Ingram, in his well-known book on economic 
history, following the opinion of Comte, refuses 
to consider the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries 
as part of the Middle Ages.^ We intend, however, 
to treat of economic teaching up to the end of 
the fifteenth century. The best modem judges 
are agreed that the term Middle Ages must not 
be given a hard-and-fast meaning, but that it is 
capable of bearing a very elastic interpretation. 
The definition given in the Catholic Encyclo- 
pcedia is : 'a term commonly used to designate 
that period of European history between the 
FaU of the Roman Empire and about the middle 
of the fifteenth century. The precise dates of 

1 History of Political Economy, p. 35, 



4 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

the beginning, culmination, and end of the Middle 
Ages are more or less arbitrarily assumed accord- 
ing to the point of view adopted.' The eleventh 
edition of the Encyclopcedia Britannica contains 
a similar opinion : ' This name is com monly given 
to that period__ol_European Tiisto^T which—lies 
be^eerTwHat are known as ancient aiidjnadem 
times, and^^TGaBTTias generally" been considered 
as^'extending from about the middle of the fifth 
to about the middle of the fifteenth centuries. 
The two dates adopted in old text-books were 
476 and 1453, from the setting aside of the last 
empierbr of the west until the fall of Constanti- 
nople. In reahty it is impossible to fix any exact 
dates for the opening and close of such a period.' 
We are therefore justified in considering the 
fifteenth century as comprised in the Middle 
Ages. This is especially so in the domain of 
economic theory. In actual practice the four- 
teenth and fifteenth centuries may have presented 
the appearance rather of the first stage of a new 
than of the last stage of an old era. This is 
Ingram's view. However true this may be of 
practice, it is not at all true of theory, which, 
as we shaU see, continued to be entirely based on 
the writings of an author of the thirteenth century. 
Ingram admits this incidentally : ' During the 
fourteenth and fifteenth centuries the Catholic- 
feudal system was breaking down by the mutual 
conflicts of its own official members, while the 
constituent elements of a new order were rising 
beneath it. The movements of this phase can 
scarcely be said to find an echo in any contem- 



INTRODUCTORY 5 

porary economic literattixe.' ^ We need not 
therefore apologise further for including a con- 
sideration of the fourteenth and fifteenth cen- 
turies in our investigations as to the economic 
teaching of the Middle Ages. We are supported 
in doing so by such excellent authorities as 
Jotirdain,^ Roscher,^ and Cossa.* Haney, in his 
History of Economic Thought,^ says : ' It seems 
more nearly true to regard the years about 1500 
as marking the end of mediaeval times. ... On 
large lines, and from the viewpoint of systems of 
thought rather than systems of industry, the 
Middle Ages may with profit be divided into two 
periods. From 400 down to 1200, or shortly 
thereafter, constitutes the first. During these 
years Christian theology opposed Roman institu- 
tions, and Germanic customs were superposed, 
until through action and reaction all were blended. 
This was the reconstruction ; it was the " stormy 
struggle " to found a new ecclesiastical and civil 
system. From 1200 on to 1500 the world of 
thought settled to its \e^ — Eexidaliara__and 
scholasticism, the corner-stones of medisevalism, 

emCTge 3"ah d weie domlixant.' — 

We shall not continue the study further than 
the beginning of the sixteenth century. It is true 
that, if we were to refer to several sixteenth- 

1 Op. cit., p. 35. 

2 Memoires sur les commencements de I'ieonomie politique dans les 
icoles du moyen Age, Aoad6mie des Inscriptions et Belles-Lettres, 
Tol. 28. 

^ Oeschichte zur National-Okonomik in DeuiscMand. 
* Introduction to the Study of Political Economy. 
» P. 70. 



6 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

century authors, we should be in possession 
of a very highly developed and detailed mass of 
teaching on many points which earUer authors 
left to some extent obscure. We deliberately 
refrain nevertheless from doing so, because the 
whole nature of the sixteenth-century literature 
was different from that of the fourteenth and 
fifteenth ; the early years of the sixteenth cen- 
tury witnessed the abrogation of the central 
authority which was a basic condition of the 
success of the mediaeval system ; and the same 
period also witnessed ' radical economic changes, 
reacting more and more on the scholastic doc- 
trines, which found fewer and fewer defenders in 
their original form.' ^ 

§ 2. Economic 

It must be clearly understood that the political 
economy of the medisevals was not a science, like 
modern political economy, but an art. ' It is a 
branch of the virtue of prudence ; it is half-way 
between morality, which regulates the conduct of 
the individual, and pohtics, which regulates the 
conduct of the sovereign. It is the morality of 
the family or of the head of the family, from the 
point of view of the good administration of the 
patrimony, just as politics is the moraUty of the 
sovereign, from the point of view of the good 

''■ Cossa, op. cit, p. 161. Ashley warns us that ' we must be careful 
not to interpret the writers of the fifteenth century by the writers 
of the seventeenth ' {Economic History, vol. i. pt. ii. p. 387). These 
later writers sometimes contain historicsil accounts of controversies 
in previous centiiries, and are relevant on this account. 



INTEODUCTORY 7 

government of the State. There is as yet ncr~ 
question of economic laws in the sense of his- 
torical and descriptive laws ; and pohtical eco- 
nomy, not yet existing in the form of a science, 
is not more than a branch of that great tree which 
is called ethics, or the art of living well.' ^ ' The 
doctrine of the canon law,' says Sir WiUiknT" 
Ashley, ' differed from modern economics in 
being an art rather than a science. It was a 
body of rules and prescriptions as to conduct, 
rather than of conclusions as to fact. All art 
indeed in this sense rests on science ; ^ut the 
science on which the canonist doctrine rested #ai^ 
theology. Theology, or rather that branch of it 
which we may call Christian ethics, laid down 
certain principlos of right and wrong in the 
economic sphere j| and it was the work of the 
canonists to apply them to specific transactions 

^ Rambaud, Histoire des Doctrines Eamondgues, p. 39. ' It is evideny 
that a household is a mean between the individual and the city olr 
Kingdom, since just as the individual is part of the household, so is 
the household part of the city or Kingdom, and therefore, just as 
prudence commonly so called which governs the individual is dis- 
tinct from political prudence, so must domestic prudence (oeoonomica) 
be distinct from both. Riches are related to domestic prudence, 
not as its last end, but as its instrument. On the other hand, the 
end of pohtical prudence is a good lite in general as regards the conduct 
of the household. In Ethics i. the philosopher speaks of riches as the 
end of political prudence, by way of example, and in accordance 
with the opinion of many.' Aquinas, Summa II. ii. 50. 3, and see 
Sent. III. xxxiii. 3 and 4. ' Practioa quidem scientia est, quae recte 
Vivendi modum ac disciplinae formam secundum virtutum institu- 
tionem disponit. Et haec dividitur in tres, soilioet : primo ethicam, 
id est moralem ; et secumdo oeconomicam, id est dispensativam ; et 
tertio politicam, id est civUem' (Vincent de Beauvais, Speculum, 
vn. i. 2). 



8 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

and to pronounce judgment as to their permissi- 
Ibility.' ^ The conception of economic laws, in 
the modern sense, was quite foreign to the mediae- 
val treatment of the subject. ) It was only in the 
middle of the fourteenth ceniEury that anything 
approaching a scientific examination of the phe- 
nomena of economic life appeared, and that was 
only in relation to a particular subject, namely, 
the doctrine of money. ^ ~) 

'' To say that the mediaeval method of approach- 
ing economic problems was fundamentally differ- 
ent from the modern, is not in any sense to be 
taken as indicating disapproval of the former. 
On the contrary, it is the general opinion to-day 
that the so-called classical treatment of economics 
has proved disastrous in its application to real 
Ufe, and that future generations jyiU. witness 
a retreat to the earlier position. JChe classical 
economists committed the cardinal error of 
subordinating man to wealth, and consumption 
to production. J In their attempt to preserve 
symmetry andorder in their generahsations they 
constructed a weird creature, the economic man, 
who never existed, and never could exist. ; The 
mediaevals made no such mistake. They in^ 
sisted that aU production and gain which did not / 
lead to the good of man was not alone wasteful,/ 
but positively evil ; and that man was infinitelyV 

'^ Op. oil., vol. i. part. ii. p. 379. — ''"'"^ 

^ Rambaud, op. dt., p. 83; Ingram, op. cit., p. 36. So marked 
was the contrast between the mediseval and modem conceptions of 
economics that the appearance of this one treatise has been said by- 
one high authority to have been the signal of the dawn of the Benais- 
sance (Espinas, Histoire des Doctrines Economques, p. 110). 



INTEODUCTORY 9 

more important than wealth. When he exclaims 
that ' Production is on account of man, not man 
of production,' Antoninus of Florence sums up 
in a few words the whole view-point of his age.^ 
' Consumption,' according to Dr. Cunninghain,. 
' was the aspect of human nature which attracted 
most attention. . . . -Bregii lating consumpt ion- 
wisely was the chief practical problem in mediae- 
val economics.' ^ The great practical benefits 
of such a treatment of the problems relating ter 
the acquisition and enjoyment of material wealth 
must be obvious to every one who is familiar with 
the condition of the world after a century of 
classical pohtical economy. ' To subordinate the 
economic order to the social order, to submit the 
industrial activity of man to the consideration 
of the final and general end of his whole being, 
is a principle which must exert on every depart- 
ment of the science of wealth, an influence easy 
to understand. \ Economic laws are the codifica- 
tion of the material activity of a sort of homo 
economicus ; of a being, who, having no end in 
view but wealth, produces all he can, distributes 
his produce in the way that suits him best, and 
consumes as much as he can. Self interest aloijer 
dictates his conduct.' ^ ■ Economics, far from 
being a science whose highest aim was to evolve 
a series of abstractions, was a practical guide to 
the conduct of everyday afEairs.*' ; The pre- 

' Irish Theologipal Quarterly, vol. vii. p. 151. 

" Christianity and Economic Science, p. 10. 

' Brants, Les Theories iconomiques awo xiii" et xiv^ siieles, p. 34. 

* Gide and Rist, History of Economic Doctrines, Eng. trans., p. 110. 



10 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

jeminence of morality in the domain of econo- 
mics constitutes at the same time the distinctive 
feature, the particular merit, and the great teach- 
ing of the economic lessons of this period.' ^ 
Lj)r. Cunningham draws attention to the fact 
that the existence of such a universally received 
code of economic moraHty was largely due to the 
comparative simplicity of the mediaeval social 
structure, where the relations of persons were aU 
important, in comparison with the modem order, 
where the exchange of things is the dominant 
factor. He further draws attention to the 
changes which affected the whole constitution 
of society in the sixteenth and seventeenth 
centuries, and proceeds : ' These changes had a 
very important bearing on aU questions of com- 
mercial morahty ; so long as economic dealings 
were based on a system of personal relationships 
they all bore an impMed moral charact^ To 
supply a bad article was morally wrong, to de- 
mand excessive payment for goods or for labour 
was extortion, and the right or wrong of every 
transaction was easily understood.' ^ {The appli- 
cation of ethics to economic transactions was 
rendered possible by the existence of one univer- 
sally recognised code of morahty, and the presence 
of one universally accepted moral teacher. ' In 
the thirteenth century, the ecclesiastical organisa- 
tion gave a unity to the social structure through- 
out the whole of Western Europe ; j over the area 
in which the Pope was recognise'S^as the spiritual 

^ Brants, op. dt, p. 9. 

' Qrcneth of English Industry and Commerce, vol. i. p. 465. 



INTRODUCTORY 11 

and the Emperor as the temporal vicar of God, 
political and racial differences were relatively 
unimportant. For economic purposes it is scarcely 
necessary to distinguish different countries from 
one another in the thirteenth century, for there 
were fewer barriers to social intercourse within the 
Umits of Christendom than there are to-day. . . . 
Similar ecclesiastical canons, and similar laws 
prevailed over large areas, where very different 
admixtures of civil and barbaric laws were in 
vogue. /Christendom, though broken into so 
many fragments politically, was one organised 
society for all the purposes of economic life, 
because there was such free intercommunication 
between its par^H.' ^ ' There were three great 
threads,' we reai.. later in the same book, ' which 
ran through the whole social system of Christeny 
dom. First of all there was a common religious 
li fe^j with the powerful weapons of spiritual cen- 
sure and excommunication which it placed in the 
hands of the clergy, so that they were able to 
errforce the line of policy which Rome approved. 
Mien there was the great judicial system of canon 
law, a common code with similar tribunals for the 
whole of Western Christendom, dealing not merely 
with strictly ecclesiastical affairs, but with many 
matters that we should regard as economic, such 
as questions of commercial morality, and also with 
social welfare as affected by the law of marriage 
and the disposition of property by will. . . .'-Iv 
' To the influence of Christianity as a moral 

1 Cunningham, Western Givilisation, vol. ii. pp. 2-3. 
« Ibid., p. 67. 



12 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

doctrine,' says Dr. Ingram, ' was added that of 
the Church as an organisation, charged with the 
appKcation of the doctrine to men's daily trans- 
actions. Besides the teaching of the sacred books 
there was a mass of ecclesiastical legislation pro- 
viding specific prescriptions for the conduct of 
the faithful. And this legislation dealt with the 
economic as weU as with other provinces of social 
activity.' ^ 

{ The teaching of the mediaeval Church, therefore, 
on economic affair's was but the appHcation to 
particular facts and cases of its general moral 
teaching. The suggestion, so often put forward 
by so-caUed Christian socialists, that Christianity 
was the exponent of a special social theory of its 
own, is imfoundedTJ The direct opposite would 
be nearer the truth. Far from concerning itseH 
with the outward forms of the pohtical or economic 
structure, Christianity concentrated its attention 
on the conduct of the individual. If Christianity 
can be said to have possessed any distinctive 
social theory, it was intense individualism. 
'Christianity brought, from the point of view of 
morals, an altogether new force by the distinctly 
individual and personal character of its precepts. 
Duty, vice or virtue, eternal ptmishment — all 
are marked with the most individuahst imprint 
that can be imagined. No social or pohtical 
theory appeared, because it was through the 
individual that society was to be regenerated. 
. . IWe can say with truth that there is not any 
Christian pohtical economy — in the sense in 

1 Op. cit., p. 27. 



INTRODUCTORY 13 

which there is a Christian morahty or a Christian 
dogma — any more than ther,^_^is_a Christian 
physic or a Christian medicine.2Jt;sin seeking to 
learn Christian teaching of the Middle Ages on 
economic matters, we must therefore not look for 
special economic treatises in the modern sense, but 
seek our principles in the works dealing with 
general morality, in the Canon Law, and in the ; 
commentaries on the Civil Law^' ' We find the 
first worked out economic theory for the whole 
Catholic world in the Corpus Juris Ganonici, that 
product of mediaeval science in which for so many 
centuries theology, jurisprudence, philosophy, and' 
pohtics were treated. . . .' ^ 

There is not to be found in the writers of the 
early Middle Ages, that is to say from the eighth 
to the thirteenth centuries, a trace of any atten- 
tion given to what we at the present day would 
designate economic questions. Usury was con- 
denmed by the decrees of several councils, but the 
reasons of this prohibition were not given, nor 
was the question made the subject of any dia- 
lectical controversy ; commerce was so unde- 
veloped as to escape the attention of those who 
sought to guide the people in their daily life ; and 

^ Bambaud, op. cit, pp. 34-5 ; Cunningham, Western, Civilisation, 
vol. ii. p. 8. 

2 Roscher, op. cit., p. 6. It must not be concluded that aU the 
opinions expressed by the theologians and lawyers were necessarily 
the official teaching of the Church. Brants says : ' It is not our 
intention to attribute to the Church all the opinions of this period ; 
certainly the spirit of the Church dominated the great majority of the 
writers, but one must not conclude from this that all their writings are 
entitled to rank as doctrinal teaching ' (op. cit., p. 6). 



14 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

money was accepted as the inevitable instru- 
ment of exchange, without any discussion of its 
origin or the laws which regulated it. 

The writings of this period therefore betray no 
sign of any interest in economic affairs. Jourdain 
says that he carefully examined the works of 
Alcuin, Rabanas Mauras, Scotus Erigenus, Hiiic- 
mar, Gerbert, St. Anselm, and Abelard — the 
greatest lights of theology and philosophy in the 
early Middle Ages — ^without finding a single 
passage to suggest that any of these authors 
suspected that the pursuit of riches, which they 
despised, occupied a sufl&ciently large place in 
national as weU as in individual life, to ofEer to 
the philosopher a subject fruitful in reflections 
and results. The only work which might be 
adduced as a partial exception to this rule is the 
Polycraticus of John of SaMsbury ; but even this 
treatise contained only some scattered moral 
reflections on luxury and on zeal for the interest 
of the pubUc treasury.^ 

\^o causes contributed to produce this almost 
total lack of interest in economic subjects. One 
was the miserable condition of society,' stiU only 
partially rescued from the ravages of the bar- 
barians, and half organised, almost without 
industry and commerce ; the other was the absence 
of all economic tradition. The existence of the 
Categories and Hermenia of Aristotle ensured that 
the chain of logical study was not broken ; the 
works of Donatus and Priscian sustained some 
gUmmer of interest in grammatical theory ; certain 

1 Jourdain, op. cit., p. 4, 



INTRODUCTORY 15 

rude notions of physics and astronomy were kept 
alive by the preservation of such ancient ele- 
mentary treatises as those of Marcian Capella ; 
but economics had no share in the heritage of the ■ 
past. Not only had the writings of the ancients, 
who dealt to some extent with the theory of wealth,; 
been destroyed, but the very traces of theirj 
teaching had been long forgotten. A good 
example of the state of thought in economic 
matters is furnished by the treatment which 
money receives in the Etymologies of Isidore of 
Seville, which was regarded in the early Middle 
Ages as a reliable encyclopaedia. ' Money,' accord- 
ing to Isidore, ' is so called because it warns, 
monet, lest any fraud should enter into its com- 
position or its weight. The piece of money is 
the coin of gold, silver, or bronze, which is called 
nomisma, because it bears the imprint of the 
name and likeness of the prince. . , . The pieces 
of money nummi have been so called from the 
King of Rome, Numa, who was the first among 
the Latins to mark them with the imprint of his 
^ image and name.' ^ Is it any wonder that the 
early Middle Ages were barren of economic 
doctrines, when this was the best instruction to 
which they had access ? 

In the course of the thirteenth century a great 
change occurred. The advance of civihsation, 
the increased organisation of feudalism, the 
development of industry, and the extension of 
commerce, largely under the influence of the 
Crusades, all created a condition of affairs in which 

1 Etyrnol.i xvi. 17. 



^6 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

economic questions could no longer be over- 
looked or neglected. At the same time the 
renewed study of the writings of Aristotle served 
'to throw a flood of new light on the nature of 
wealth. 

The Mhics and Politics oi Aristotle, although 
they are not principally devoted to a treatment of 
the theory of wealth, do in fact deal with that 
subject incidentally, jiwo points in particular 
are touched on, the utihty of money and the 
injustice of usury. The passages of the philo- 
sopher dealing with these subjectis are of par- 
ticular interest, as they may be said, with a good 
deal of truth, to be the true starting point of 
mediaeval economics.^ The writings of Aristotle 
arrested the attention, and aroused the admira- 
tion of the theologians of the thirteenth century ; 
and it would be quite impossible to exaggerate 
the influence which they exercised on the later 
development of mediaeval thought. Albertus 
Magnus digested, interpreted, and systematised 
the whole of the works of the Stagyrite ; and was 
so steeped in the lessons of his philosophic master 
as to be dubbed by some ' the ape of Aristotle.' 
Aquinas, who was a pupil of Albertus, also studied 
and commented on Aristotle, whose aid he was 
always ready to invoke in the solution of all his 
difficulties. With the single and strange excep- 
tion of Vincent de Beauvais, Aristotle's teaching 
on money was accepted by all the writers of the 
thirteenth century, and was followed by later 
generations. 2 The influence of Aristotle is appar- 

^ Jourdain, op. cit., p. 7. 2 Ihid., p. 12. 



INTRODUCTORY 17 

ent in every article of the Sumrrm, which was 
itself the starting point from which all discussion 
sprang for the following two centuries ; and it is 
not too much to say that the Stagyrite had a de- 
cisive influence on the introduction of economic 
notions into the controversies pf the Schools. /' We 
find in the writings of St. Thomas Aquinas,' says 
Ingram, ' the economic doctrines of Aristotle repro- 
duced with a partial infusion of Christian elements/}. 
In support of the account we have given of the 
development of economic thought in thp thir- 
teenth century, we may quote Cossa : '■ ' The 
revival of economic studies in the Middle Ages 
only dates from the thirteenth century. It was 
due in a great measure ,to a study of the Ethics 
and Politics of Aristotl^ whose theories on wealth 
were paraphrased by a considerable number of 
commentators. Before that period we can only 
find moral and rehgious dissertations on such 
topics as the proper use of material goods, the 
dangers of luxury, and undue desire for wealth. 
This is easily explained when we take into con- 
sideration (1) the prevalent influence of religious 
ideas at the time, (2) the strong reaction against 
the materialism of pagan antiquity, (3) the pre- 
dominance of natural economy, (4) the small 
importance of international trade, and (5) the 
decay of the profane sciences, and the meta- 
physical tendencies of the more solid thinkers of 
the Middle Ages.' ^ 

^ Op. oit, p. 27. Espinas thinks that the influence of Aristotle 
in this respect has been exaggerated. (Histoire des Doctrines Ewno- 
mques, p. 80.) 

^ Op. cit, p. 14 ; Espinas, op. eit, p. 80. 

B 



18 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

The teaching of Aquinas upon economic affairs 
remained the groundwork of all the later writers 
until the end of the fifteenth century. His 
opinions on various points were amplified and 
explained by later authors in more detail than 
he himself employed ; monographs of considerable 
length were devoted to the treatment of questions 
which he dismissed in a single article ; but the 
development which took place was essentially one 
of amplification rather than opposition. The 
monographists of the later fifteenth century treat 
usury and sale in considerable detail ; many 
refinements are indicated which are not to be 
found in the Summa ; but it is quite safe to say 
that none of these later writers ever pretended to 
supersede the teaching of Aquinas, who was 
always admitted to be the ultimate authority. 
' During the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, 
the general pohtical doctrine of Aquinas was main- 
tained with merely subordinate modifications.' ^ 
' The canonist doctrine of the fifteenth century,' 
according to Sir William Ashley, ' was but a de- 
velopment of the principles to which the Church 
had already given its sanction in earlier centuries. 
It was the outcome of these same principles work- 
ing in a modified environment. But it may 
more fairly be said to present a system of economic 
thought, because it was no longer a collection of 
unrelated opinions, but a connected whole. The 
tendency towards a separate department of study 
is shown by the ever-increasing space devoted to 
the discussion of general economic topics in 

^ Ingram, op. cii., p. 35. 



INTRODUCTORY 19 

general theological treatises, and more notably 
stiU in the manuals of casuistry for the use of the 
confessional, and handbooks of canon law for 
the use of ecclesiastical lawyers. It was shown 
even more distinctly by the appearance of a shoal 
of special treatises on such subjects as contracts, 
exchange, and money, not to mention those on 
usury.' ^ In aU this development, however, the 
principles enunciated by Aquinas, and through 
him, by Aristotle, though they may have been 
illustrated and apphed to new instances, were 
never rejected. The study of the writers of this 
period is therefore the study of an organic whole, 
the germ of which is to be found in the writings of 
Aquinas.^ 

§ 3. Teaching 

We shall confine our attention in this essay to 
the economic teaching of the Middle Ages, and 
shall not deal with the actual practice of the 
period. It may be objected that a study of the 
former without a study of the latter is futile and 

1 Op. cit., vol. i. pt. ii. p. 382. 

* The volume of literature which bears more or less on economic 
matters dating from the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries is colossal. 
By far the best account of it is to be found in Endemann's Studien in 
der Bomanisch-canonistischen Wirthschafts- und Eechtslehre, vol. i. 
pp. 25 et seq. Many of the more important works written during the 
period are reprinted in the TrcMtatus Universi Juris, vols. vi. and vii. 
The appendix to the first chapter of Rosoher's Oeschichte also contains 
a valuable account of certain tjrpical writers, especially of Langenstein 
and Henricus de Hoyta. Brants gives a useful bibUographical list of 
both mediaeval and modem authorities in the second chapter of his 
Theories iconomiqties aiiac xim' et xiif sihdes. Those who desire further 
information about any particular writer of the period will find it in 



20 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

useless ; that the economic teaching of a period 
can only be satirfactorily learnt from a study 
of its actual economic institutions and customs; 
and that the scholastic teaching was nothing 
but a casuistical attempt to reconcile the early 
Christian dogmas with the ever- widening exigencies 
of real Mfe. Endemann, for instance, devotes a 
great part of his invaluable books on the subject 
to demonstrating how impracticable the canonist 
teaching was when it was appHed to real life, 
and recounting the casuistical devices that were 
resorted to in order to reconcile the teachiQg of 
the Church with the accepted mercantile customs 
of the time. Endemann, however, in spite of his 
colossal research and tmrivaUed acquaintance 
with original authorities, was essentially hostile 
to the system which he undertook to explain, and 
thus lacked the most essential quahty of a satis- 
factory expositor, namely, sympathy with his 
subject. He does not appear to have reaMsed 
' that development and adaptabUity to new situa- 
tions, far from being marks of impracticabihty, 
are rather the signs of vitaHty and of elasticity. 
This is not the place to discuss how far the 
doctrine of the late fifteenth differed from that of 
the early thirteenth century ; that is a matter 
which will appear below when each of the leading 

Stintzing, LdteraturgescMchte des r'6m. Bechts, or in ChevaJIier's Biper- 
toire historique des Sources du moyen dge; Bio-hihliogra/phie. The 
authorship of the treatise De Begimine Principum, from which we shall 
frequently quote, often attributed to Aquinas, is very doubtful. The 
most probable opinion is that the first book and the first three 
chapters of the second are by Aquinas, and the remainder by another 
writer. (See Franok, Biformatewa et Pvblicistes, vol. i. p. 83.) 



INTRODUCTORY 21 

principles of scholastic economic teaching is 
separately considered ; it is sufficient to say here 
that we agree entirely with Brants, in opposition 
to Endemann, that the change which took place 
in the interval was one of development, and not 
of opposition. ' The law,' says Brants, ' re- 
mained identical and unchanged ; justice and 
charity — ^nobody can justly enrich himseH at the 
expense of his neighbour or of the State, but the 
reasons justifying gain are multipUed according 
as riches are developed.' ^ ' The canonist doc- 
trine of the fifteenth century was but a develop- 
ment of the principles to which the Church had 
already given its sanction in earlier centuries. It 
was the outcome of these same principles working 
in a modified environment,' ^ With these con- 
clusions of Brants and Ashley we are in entire 
agreement. 

Let us say in passing that the assumption that 
the mediaeval teaching grew out of contemporary 
practice, rather than that the latter grew out of 
the former, is one which does not find acceptance 
among the majority of the students of the subject. 
The problem whether a correct understanding of 
mediaeval economic life can be best attained by 
first studying the teaching or the practice is 
possibly no more soluble than the old riddle of 
the hen and the egg ; but it may at least be 
argued that there is a good deal to be said on both 
sides. The supporters of the view that practice 
moulded theory are by no means unopposed. 
There is no doubt that in many respects the 

* Brants, op. cit, p. 9. ^ Ashley, op. ciu, p. 381. 



22 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

exigencies of everyday commercial concerns came 
into conflict with the tenets of canon law and 
scholastic opinion ; but the admission of this 
fact does not at all prove that the former was the 
element which modified the latter, rather than 
the latter the former. In so far as the expansion 
of commerce and the increasing complexity of 
intercourse raised questions which seemed to 
indicate that mercantile convenience conflicted 
with received teaching, it is probable that the 
difficulty was not so much caused by a contra- 
diction between the former and the latter, as by 
the fact that an interpretation of the doctrine 
as applied to the facts of the new situation was 
not available before the new situation had actually 
arisen. This is a phenomenon frequently met with 
at the present day in legal practice ; but no 
lawyer would dream of asserting that, because 
there had arisen an unprecedented state of facts, 
to which the application of the law was a matter 
of doubt or difficulty, therefore the law itself was 
obsolete or incomplete. Examples of such a 
conflict are familiar to any one who has ever 
studied the case law on any particular subject, 
either in a country such as England, where the 
law is unwritten, or in continental countries, 
where the most exhaustive and complete codes 
have been framed. Nevertheless, in spite of the 
occiu-rence of such difficulties, it would be foohsh 
to contend that the laws in force for the time being 
have not a greater influence on the practice of 
mercantile transactions than the convenience of 
merchants has upon the law. How much more 



INTEODUCTORY 23 

potent must this influence have been when the 
law did not apply simply to outward observances, 
but to the inmost recesses of the consciences of 
believing Christians ! 

The opinion that mediaeval teaching exercised 
a profound effect on mediaeval practice is supported 
by authorities of the weight of Ashley, Ingram, 
and Cunningham,^ the last of whom was in some 
respects unsympathetic to the teaching the influ- 
ence of which he rates so highly. ' It has indeed,' 
writes Sir William Ashley, ' not infrequently been 
hinted that ah the elaborate argumentation of 
canonists and theologians was " a cobweb of the 
brain," with no vital relation to real life. Certain 
German writers have, for instance, maintained 
that, alongside of the canonist doctrine with 
regard to trade, there existed in mediaeval Europe 
a commercial law, recognised in the secular courts, 
and altogether opposed to the pecuhar doctrines 
of the canonists. It is true that parts of mer- 
cantile jurisprudence, such as the law of partner- 
ship, had to a large extent originated in the social 
conditions of the time, and would have probably 
made their appearance even if there had been no 
canon law or theology. But though there were 
branches of commercial law which were, in the 
main, independent of the canonist doctrine, there 
were none that were opposed to it. On the 
fundamental points of usury and just price, com- 
mercial law in the later Middle Ages adopted com- 

^ Even Endemann warns his readers against assuming that the 
canonist teaching had no influence on everyday life. (Studien, vol. ii. 
p. 404.) 



24 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

pletely the principles of the canonists. How 
entirely these principles were recognised in the 
practice of the courts which had most to do 
with commercial suits, viz. those of the towns, is 
sufficiently shown by the frequent enactments as 
to usury and as to reasonable price which are 
found in the town ordinances of the Middle Ages ; 
in England as well as in the rest of Western Europe. 
. . . Whatever may have been the effect, direct 
or indirect, of the canonist doctrine on legislation, 
it is certain that on its other side, as entering into 
the moral teaching of the Church through the 
pulpit and the confessional, its influence was 
general and persistent, even if it were not always 
completely successful.' ^ ' Every great change 
of opinion on the destinies of man,' says Ingram, 
' and the guiding principles of conduct must react 
in the sphere of material interests ; and the 
Catholic religion had a profound influence on the 
economic hfe of the Middle Ages. . . . The con- 
stant presentations to the general mind and 
conscience of Christian ideas, the dogmatic bases 
of which were as yet scarcely assailed by scepti- 
cism, must have had a powerful effect in morahs- 
ing life.' ^ According to Dr. Cunningham : ' The 
mediaeval doctrine of price was not a theory in- 
tended to explain the phenomena of society, but 
it was laid down as the basis of rules which should 
control the conduct of society and of individuals. 
At the same time current opinion seems to have 

1 Ashley, op. cit., vol. i. pt. ii. pp. 383-85. Again : ' The later 
canonist dialectic was the midwife of modem economics ' {ibid., p. 397). 

2 History of Political Economy, p. 26. 



INTRODUCTORY 25 

been so fully formed, in accordance with it that a 
brief enumeration of the doctrine of a just price 
will serve to set the practice of the day in clearer 
light. In regard to other matters, it is difficult 
to determine how far public opinion was swayed 
by practical experience, and how far it was really 
moulded by Christian teaching — ^this is the case 
in regard to usury. But there can be little doubt 
about the doctrine of price — which really under- 
lies a great deal of commercial and gild regulations, 
and is constantly implied in the early legislation 
on mercantile affairs.' ^ The same author ex- 
presses the same opinion in another work : ' The 
Christian doctrine of price, and Christian con- 
demnation of gain at the expense of another man, 
affected all the mediaeval organisation of municipal 
life and regulation of inter-municipal commerce, 
and introduced marked contrasts to the conditions 
of business in ancient cities. The Christian ap- 
preciation of the duty of work rendered the lot 
of the mediaeval villain a very different thing 
from that of the slave of the ancient empire. The 
responsibihty of proprietors, like the responsibility 
of prices, was so far insisted on as to place sub- 
stantial checks on tyranny of every kind. For 
these principles were not mere pious opinions, but 
effective maxims in practical life. Owing to the 
circumstances in which the vestiges of Koman 
civUisation were locally maintained, and the 
foundations of the new society were laid, there 
was ample opportunity for Christian teaching and 

^ Cunningham, Growth of English Industry and Commerce, vol. i. 
p. 252. 



26 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

example to have a marked influence on its develop- 
ment.' 1 In Dr. Cunningham's book entitled 
Politics and Economics the same opinion is ex- 
pressed : 2 ' Eeligious and industrial life were 
closely interconnected, and there were countless 
points at which the principles of divine law must 
have been brought to bear on the transaction of 
business, altogether apart from any formal 
tribunal. Nor must we forget the opportTjnities 
which directors had for influencing the conduct 
of penitents. . . . Partly through the operation 
of the royal power, partly through the decisions 
of ecclesiastical authorities, but more generally 
through the influence of a Christian public opinion 
which had been gradually created, the whole 
industrial organism took its shape, and the 
acknowledged economic principles were framed.' 
We have quoted these passages from Dr. 
Cunningham's works at length because they are 
of great value in helping us to estimate the rival 
parts played by theory and practice in mediaeval 
economic teaching ; in the first place, because the 
author was by no means prepossessed in favour 
of the teaching of the canonists, but rather un- 
sympathetic to it ; in the second place, because, 
although his work was concerned primarily with 
practice, he foTmd himseK obUged to make a study 
of theory before he could properly understand the 
practice ; and lastly, because they point par- 
ticularly to the effect of the teaching on just price. 
When we come to speak of this part of the subject 

1 Cunningham, Western Civilisation, vol. ii. pp. 9-10. 

2 P. 25. 



INTRODUCTOEY 27 

we shall find that Dr. Cunningham failed to 
appreciate the true significance of the canonist 
doctrine. If an eminent author, who does not 
quite appreciate the full import of this doctrine, 
and who is to some extent contemptuous of its 
practical value, nevertheless asserts that it exer- 
cised an all-powerful influence on the practice of 
the age in which it was preached, we are surely 
justified in asserting that the study of theory may 
be profitably pursued without a preliminary his- 
tory of the contemporary practice. 

But we must not be taken to suggest that there 
were no conflicts between the teaching and the 
practice of the Middle Ages. As we have seen, 
the economic teaching of that period was ethical, 
and it would be absiird to assert that every man 
who lived in the Middle Ages lived up to the high 
standard of ethical conduct which was propbsed 
by the Church.^ One might as well say that 
stealing was an unknown crime in England since 
the passing of the Larceny Act. All we do sug- 
gest is that the theory had such an important and 
incalculable influence upon practice that the study 
of it is not rendered futile or useless because of 
occasional or even frequent departures from it 
in real life. Even Endemaim says : ' The teach- 

1 The many devices which were resorted to in order to evade the 
prohibition of usury are explained in Dr. Cunningham's Qrowih of 
English Industry and Commerce, vol. i. p. 255. See also Delisle, 
Ij Ad/ministratimh financiire des TempUers, Aoad6mie des Inscriptions 
et Belles-Lettres, 1889, vol. xxxiii. pt. ii., and Ashley, Econondc 
History, vol. i. pt. ii. p. 426. The Summa Paatoralis of Raymond de 
Pennafort analyses and demolishes many of the commoner devices 
which were employed to evade ^ihe usury laws. On the part played 
by the Jews, see Brants, op. cit.. Appendix I. 



28 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

ing of the canon law presents a noble edifice not 
less splendid in its methods than in its results. 
It embraces the whole material and spiritual 
natures of human society with such power and 
completeness that verily no room is left for any 
other life than that decreed by its dogmas.' ^ 
' The aim of the Church,' says Janssen, ' in view 
of the tremendous agencies through which it 
worked, in view of the dominion which it really 
exercised, cannot have the impression of its great- 
ness effaced by the unfortunate fact that aU was 
not accompUshed that had been planned.' ^ The 
fact that tjnrarmy may have been exercised by 
some provincial governor in an outlying island of 
the Roman Empire cannot close our eyes to the 
benefits to be derived from a study of the code 
of Justinian ; nor can a remembrance of the 
manner in which EngUsh law is administered in 
Ireland in times of excitement, blind us to the 
political lessons to be learned from an examina- 
tion of the British constitution. 

Section 3. — Value of the Study of 
THE Subject 

The question may be asked whether the study 
of a system of economic teaching, which, even if 
it ever did receive anything approaching universal 
assent, has long since ceased to do so, is not a 
waste of labour. We can answer that question 
in the negative, for two reasons. In the first 
place, as we said above, a proper understanding 

' Die NatiorudSJconomischen Orundsatze der eanonistischkn Lehre, 
p. 192. 2 History of the German Peoph (Eng. trans.), vol. ii. p. 99. 



INTRODUCTORY 29 

of the earlier periods, j)f thff develnprnPTiti of a 
body "ot kaowlecige— is—faidispensable for a full 
appreciation o f the lat er, v Even if the canonist 
system were not worth stxidying for its own sake, 
it would be deserving of attention on account of 
the light -jt throws on the development of later 
economic doctrine. ' However The crarnomst theory 
may contrast with or resemble modern economics, 
it is too important a part of the history of human 
thought to be disregarded,' says Sir William 
Ashley. ' As we cannot f uUy understand the work 
of Adam Smith without giving some attention to 
the physiocrats, nor the physiocrats without 
looking at the mercantilists: -so the beginnings 
of mercantile theory are hardly inteUigible without, 
a knowledge of the canonist doctrine towards 
which that theory stands in the relation partly 
of a continuation, partly of a protest.' ^ 

But we venture to assert that the study^ol 
canonist economics, far from being useful simply 
as an introduction to later theories, is of great 
value in furnishing us with assistance in the 
solu tion of the economic and social problems of th e 
prese nt day . l^The last fifty years have witnesse.(3r 
a reaction against the scientific abstractions of the 
classical economists, and modern thinkers are 
growing more and more dissatisfied with an 
economic science which leaves ethics out of 
account.^ Professor Sidgwiek, in his Principles. 

^ Op. cit., vol. i. pt. ii. p. 381. 

2 We must guard against the error, which is frequently made, that, 
because the classical economists assumed self-interest as the sole motive 
of economic action, they therefore approved of and inculcated it. 



30 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

of Political Economy, published in 1883, devotes 
a separate section to 'The Art of Political Eco- 
nomy,' in which he remarks that ' The principles 
of Pohtical Economy are still most commonly 
understood even in England, and in spite of many 
protests to the contrary, to be practical principles 
— ^rules of conduct, public or private.' ^ The many 
indications in recent literature and practice that 
the regulation of prices should be controlled by 
principles of ' fairness ' would take too long to 
recite. It is sufficient tojrefer to the conclusion 
of Devas on this point : '/The notion of just price, 
worked out in detail by the theologians, and in 
later days rejected as absurd by the classical 
economists, has been rightly revived by modern 
economists. '^^ Not alone in the sphere of price, 
but in that of every other department of economics, 
the impossibility of treating the subject as an 
abstract science without regard to ethics is being 
rapidly abandoned. ' The best usage of the 
present time,' according to the Catholic Encyclo- 
paedia, ' is to make political economy an ethical 
science — ^that is, to make it include a discussion of 
what ought to be in the economic world as well 
as what is.' ^ We read in the 1917 edition of 
Palgrave's Dictionary of Political Economy, that 
' The growing importance of distribution as a 
practical problem has led to an increasing mutual 
interpenetration of economic and ethical ideas, 
which in the development of economic doctrine 

1 p. 401, and see Marshall's Preface to Price's Industrial Peace, ■ 
and Ashley, op. cit, vol. i. pt. i. p. 137. 
" PoUticai Economy, p. 268. » Tit., ' Political Economy.' 



INTRODUCTORY 31 

during the last century and a half has taken 
various forms.' ^ The need for some principle by 
which just distribution can be attained has been 
rendered pressing by the terrible^ffects of a period 
of unrestricted competition. /' It has been widely 
maintained that a strictly competitive exchange 
does not tend to be really fair — some say cannot 
be really fair — ^when one of the parties is under 
pressure of urgent need ; and further, that the 
inequality of opportunity which private property 
involves cannot be fully justified on the principle 
of maintaining equal freedom, and leads, in fact, 
to grave social injusticK^ In other words, the 
present condition of affairs is admitted to be 
intolerable, and the task before the world is to 
discover some alternative^ JCThu duy when— eco- 
nomics can be divorced EFom ethics has passed 
away T"therB is a* world-Wide endeay ojjTta.estab- 
lish in th" p^ar»o ^f i.Vi e old, a new so cietv founds 
on an-.ethinail hasis,,^ jJ^There are "two, ' SfTdT" orOy" 
two, possible ways to the attainment of this ideal — 
the way of socialism and the way of Christiani;^ 
v/rhere can be no doubt the sociahst movement' 
derives a great part of its popularity from its 
promise of a new order, based, not on the unregu- 
lated pursuit of selfish desires, but on justice. 
' To this view of justice or equity,' writes Dr. 
Sidgwick, ' the sociaMstic contention that labour 
can only receive its due reward if land and other 
instruments of production are taken into pubHc 

1 Vol. iii. p. 138. 2 Ibid. 

' See Laveleye, Elements of Political Economy (Eng. trana.), pp. 7-8. 
On the general conflict between the ethical and the non-ethical schools 
of economists see Keynes, Scope and Method, pp. 20 et seq. 



32 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

ownersMp, and education of all kinds gratui- 
tously provided by Government — ^has powerfully 
appealed ; and many who are not socialists, nor 
ignorant of economic science, have been led by 
it to give welcome to the notion that the ideally 
" fair " price of a productive service is a price at 
least rendering possible the maintenance of the 
producers and their families in a condition of 
health and industrial efficiency.' 'This is not the 
place to enter iuto a discussion as to the merits , 
or practicability of any of the numerous schemes 
put forward by socialists ; ^it is sufficient to say 
that sociaHsm is essentially unhistorical, and that 
in our opinion any practical benefits which it 
might bestow on society would be more than 
counterbalanced by the innumerable evils which 
would be certain to emetge in a system based on 
imgaMsfactory foundations. 

' ^The other road to the estabhshment of a society 
based on justice is the way of Christianity, and, 
if we wish to attempt this path, it becomes 
vitally important to understand what was the 
economic teaching of the Church in the period 
when the Christian ethic was universally recog- 
nised. During the whole Middle Ages, as we have 
said above, the Canon Law was the test of right 
and wrong in the domain of economic activity ; 
production, consumption, distribution, and ex- 
change were all regulated by the universal system 
of law ; once before economic hfe was considered 
within the scope of moral regulation. It cannot 
be denied that a study of the principles which were 
accepted during that period may be of great 



INTRODUCTORY 33 

value to a generation which is striving to place 
its economic life once more upon an ethical 
foundation. 

One error in particular we must be on our guard 
to avoid. We said above that both the socialists 
and the Christian economists are agreed in their 
desire to reintroduce justice into economic life. 
We must not conclude, however, that the aims 
of these tw& schools are identical. One very 
frequently meets with the statement that the 
teachings of sociahsm are nothing more or less 
than the teachings of Christianity. This con- 
tention is discussed in the following pages, where 
the conclusion wlU be reached that, far from being 
in agreement, socialism and Christian economics 
contradict each other on many fundamental points. 
It is, however, not the aim of the discussion to 
appraise the relative merits of either system, or 
to applaud one and disparage the other. All 
that it is sought to do is to distinguish between 
them ; and to demonstrate that, whatever be 
the merits or demerits of the two philosophies, 
they are two, and not one. 

Section 4. — ^Division of the Subject 

The opinion is general that the distinctive 
doctrine of the mediaeval Church which per- 
meated the whole of its economic thought was the 
doctrine of usury. The holders of this view may 
lay claim to very influential supporters among 
the students of the subject. Ashley says that 
'/Sie prohibition of usury was clearly the centre 



34 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

of the canonist doctrine/^ Roscher expresses 
the same opinion in practically the same words ; ^ 
and Endemann sees the whole economic develop- 
ment of the Middle Ages and the Renaissance as 
the victorious destructionof the usury law by the 
exigencies of real life.^ fHowever impressed we 
may be by the opinions of such eminent authori- 
ties, we, nevertheless, cannot help feeling that on 
this point they are under a misconception. There 
is no doTlbt that the doctrine of the canonists 
which impresses the modern mind most deeply 
is the usury prohibition, partly because it is not 
generally reahsed that the usury doctrine would 
not have forbidden the receipt of any of the 
commonest kinds of unearned revenue of the 
present day, and partly because the discussion of 
usury occupies such a very large part of the 
writings of the canonists.,^ It may be quite true 
to say that the doctrine of usury was that which 
gave the greatest trouble to the mediaeval writers, 
on account of the nicety of the distinctions with 
which it abounded, and on account of the ingenuity 
of avaricious merchants, who continually sought 
to evade the usury laws by disguising illegal under 
the guise of legal transactions. In practice, there- 
fore, the usury doctrine was undoubtedly the 
most prominent part of the canonist teaching, 

1 Op. cit., vol. i. pt. ii. p. 399. 

2 ' Bekanntlioh war das Wucherverbot der praktisohe Mittelpunkt der 
ganzen kanonischen Wirthsohaftspolitik,' op. cit., p. 8. 

» StvMen, vol. i. p. 2 and ■passim. At vol. ii. p. 31 it is stated that 
the teaching on just price is a oorollaiy of the usury teaching. But 
Aquinas treats of usury in the article following his treatment of just 
price. 



INTRODUCTORY 35 

because it was the part which most tempted 
evasion ; but to admit that is not to agree with 
the proposition that it was the centre of the 
canonist doctrine. 

XjOwc view is ..that thfi_ teaching on usury was 
^oiply one of the appHcations of the doctrine that 
all voluntary exchanges of property must be 
regulated. by. the. precepts of commutative justice. 
^In one sense it might be said to be a corollary of 
the doctrine of just priceTJ This is apparently the 
suggestion of Dr. Cleary in his excellent book on 
usury : ' It seems to me that the so-called loan 
of money is really a sale, and that a loan of meal, 
wine, oil, gunpowder, and similar commodities — 
that is to say, commodities which are consumed 
in use — ^is also a sale. If this is so, as I believe it 
is, then loans of all these consumptible goods 
should be regulated by the principles which re- 
gulate sale contracts. A just price only may 
be taken, and the return must be truly equiva- 
lent.' ^ This statement of Dr. Cleary' s seems well 
warranted, and finds support in the analogy 
which was drawn between the legitimacy of in- 
terest — ^in the technical sense — and the legitimacy 
of a vendor's increasing the price of an article 
by reason of some special inconvenience which 
he would su£Eer by parting with it. Both these 
titles were justified on the same ground, namely, 
that they were in the nature of compensations, 
and arose independently of the main contract of 
loan or sale as the case might be. ' Le vendeur 
est en presence de I'acheteur. L'objet a pour 

1 TJte Clmrek and Usury, p. 186. 



36 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

lui une valeur particuliere : c'est iin souvenir, 
par exemple. A-t-il le droit de majorer le prix 
de vente ? de depasser le juste prix convenu ? 
. . . Avec Tunanimite des docteurs on peut 
trouver legitime la ma j oration du prix. L' evalu- 
ation commune distingue un double element dans 
I'objet : sa valeur ordinaire a laqueUe repond le 
juste prix, et cette valeur extraordinaire qui 
appartient au vendeur, dont il se prive et qui 
merite une compensation : il le fait pour ainsi 
dire I'objet d'un second contrat qui se superpose 
au premier. Cela est si vrai que le Supplement de 
prix n'est pas du au meme titre que le juste prix.' ^ 
The importance of this analogy will appear when 
we come to treat just price and usury in detail ; 
it is simply referred to here in support of the 
proposition thatXfar from being a special doctrine 
sui generis^the usury doctrine of the ChTorch was 
simply an application to the sale of consumptible 
things of the universal rules which applied to all 
sales. In other words, the doctrines of the just 
price and of usury were founded on the same 
fundamental precept of justice in exchange. If 
we indicate what this precept was, we can claim 
to have indicated what was the true centre of 
the canonist doctrine. ; 

;. The scholastic teaching on the subject of the 
rules of justice in exchange was founded on the 
famous fifth book of Aristotle's Ethics, and is 
very clearly set forth by Aquinas. In the article 
of the Summxi, where the question is discussed, 

^ Desbuquois, ' La Justice dans I'Eohange,' Smmne. Sooide de Frame, 
1911, p. 174. 



INTRODUCTORY 37 

' Whether the mean is to be observed in the same 
way in distributive as ia commutative justice ? ' 
we find a clear exposition : ' In commutations 
something is dehvered to an individual on account 
of something of his that has been received, as may 
be seen chiefly in selling and buying, where the 
notion of commutation is found primarily. Hence 
it is necessary to equalise thing with thing, so that 
the one person should pay back to the other just 
so much as he has become richer out of that which 
belonged to the other. The result of this will be 
equality according to the arithmetical mean, which 
is gauged according to equal excess in quantity. 
Thus 5 is the mean between 6 and 4, since it 
exceeds the latter, and is exceeded by the former 
by 1. Accordingly, if at the start both persons 
have 5, and one of them receives 1 out of the 
other's belongings, the one that is the receiver 
will have 6, and the other will be left with 4 : and 
so there wiU be justice if both are brought back 
to the mean, 1 being taken from him that has 6 
and given to him that has 4, for then both will 
have 5, which is the mean.' ^ In the following 
article the matter of each kind of justice is dis- 
cussed. We are told that : ' Justice is about 
certain external operations, namely, distribution 
and commutation. These consist in the use of 
certain externals, whether things, persons, or 
even works : of things as when one man takes 
from or restores to another that which is his : of 
persons as when a man does an injury to the very 
person of another . . . : and of works as when 

1 n. ii. 61, 2. 



38 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

a man justly enacts a work of another or does a 
work for him. . . . Commutative justice directs 
commutations that can take place between two 
persons. Of these some are involtmtary, some 
voluntary. . . . Voluntary commutations are 
when a man voluntarily transfers his chattel to 
another person. And if he transfer it simply so 
that the recipient incurs no debt, as in the case 
of gifts, it is an act not of justice, but of Uberahty. 
A voluntary transfer belongs to justice in so far 
as it includes the notion of debt.' Aquinas then 
goes on to distinguish between the difEerent kinds 
of contract, sale, usufruct, loan, letting and hiring, 
and deposit, and concludes, ' In aU these actions 
the mean is taken in the same way according 
to the equahty of repayment. Hence all these 
actions belong to the one species of justice, namely, 
commutative justice.' ^ 

This is not the place to discuss the precise 
meaning of the equahty upon which Aquinas 
insists, which will be more properly considered 
when we come to deal with the just price. What 
is to be noticed at present is that all the transac- 
tions which are properly comprised in a discussion 
of economic theory — sales, loans, etc. — are grouped 
together as being subject to the same regulative 
principle. It therefore appears more correct to ap- 
proach the subject which we are attempting to treat 
by following that principle into its various apphca- 
tions, than by making one particular appUcation of 
the principle the starting-point of the discussion. 

1 n. ii. 61, 3. The reasoning of Aristotle is oharaoteriBtioally rein- 
forced by the quotation of Matt. vii. 12 ; n. ii. 77, 1. 



INTRODUCTORY 39 

It will be noticed, however, that the principles of 
commutative justice aU treat of the commutations 
of external goods — ^in other words, they assume the 
existence of property of external goods in individ- 
uals. Commutations are but a result of private 
property ; in a state of communism there could be 
no commutation. This is well pointed out by Grer- 
son ^ and by Nider.^ It consequently is important, 
before discussing exchange of ownership, to discuss 
the principle of ownership itself ; or, ia other words. 



to study the static before the dynamic state.' 



7 



We shall therefore deal in the first place with 
the right of private property, which we shall show 
to have been fuUy recognised by the mediaeval 
writers. We shall then point out the duties 
which this right entailed, and shall estabhsh the 
position that the scholastic teaching was directed 
equally against modem sociahstic principles and 
modem unregulated individuaUsm. The next 
ppint with which we shall deal is the exchange of 
property between individuals, which is a neces- 
sary corollary of the right of property. We shall 
show that such exchanges were regulated by well- 
defined principles of commutative justice, which 
apphed equally in the case of the sale of goods 
and in the case of the sale of the use of money. 
The last matter with which we shall deal is the 

^ Be ContraetHms, i. 4 : ' Inventa est autem commutatio civilis post 
peocatum qaoniam status innocentise habuit omnia communia.' 

2 De OontrcMtihus, v. 1 : ' Nunc videndum est breviter unde originaliter 
proveniat quod rerum dominia sunt distincta, sic quod hoc dicatur 
meum et illud tuum ; quia illud est fundamentum omnis injustitiae 
in contractando rem alienam, et post omnis injustitia reddendo earn.' 

* See rAbb6 Desbuquois, op. dt., p. 168. 



40 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

machmery by which exchanges are conducted, 
namely, money. Many other subjects, such as 
slavery and the legitimacy of commerce, wiU be 
treated as they arise in the course of our treatment 
of these principal divisions. 

In its ultimate analysis, the whole subject may 
be reduced to a classification of the various duties 
which attached to the right of private property. 
The owner of property, as we shaU see, was bound 
to observe certain duties in respect of its acquisi- 
tion and its consumption, and certain other 
duties in respect of its exchange, whether it con- 
sisted of goods or of money. The whole fabric of 
mediaeval economics was based on the fotmdation 
of private property; and the elaborate and logical 
system of regulations to ensure justice in economic 
life would have had no purpose or no use if the 
subject matter of that justice were aboMshed. 

It must not be understood that the mediaeval 
writers treated economic subjects in this order, 
or in any order at all. As we have already said, 
economic matters are simply referred to in con- 
nection with ethics, and were not detached and 
treated as making up a distinct body of teaching. 
Ashley says : ' The reader wiU guard himself 
against supposing that any mediaeval writer ever 
detached these ideas from the body of his teaching, 
and put them together as a modern text-book 
writer might do ; or that they were ever presented 
in this particular order, and with the coimecting 
argument definitely stated.' ^ 

1 Op. dt., vol. i. pt. ii. p. 387. 



CHAPTER II 

PROPERTY 

Section 1. — The Eight to Procure and 
Dispense Property 

The teaching of the mediaeval Chtirch on the sub- 
ject of property was perfectly simple and clear. 
Aqiiinas devoted a section of the Summa to it, 
and his opinion was accepted as final by aU the 
later writers of the period, who usually repeat his 
very words. However, before coming to quote 
and explain Aquinas, it is necessary to deal with 
a difficulty that has occurred to several students 
of Christian economics, namely, that the teaching 
of the scholastics on the subject of property was 
in some way opposed to the teaching of the early 
Church and of Christ Himself. Thus Haney 
says : ' It is necessary to keep the ideas of Chris- 
tianity and the Church separate, for few will 
deny that Christianity as a religion is quite dis- 
tinct from the various institutions or Churches 
which profess it. . . .' And he goes on to point 
out that, whereas Christianity recommended com- 
mimity of property, the Chiirch permitted private 
property and inequahty.^ Strictly speaking, the 
reconciliation of the mediaeval teaching with that 

'■ Op. dU, p. 73. 

41 



42 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

of the primitive Church might be said to be out- 
side the scope of the present essay. In our 
opinion, however, it is important to insist upon 
the fundamental harmony of the teaching of 
the Church in the two periods, in the first 
place, because it is impossible to understand the 
later without an understanding of the earher 
doctrine from which it developed, and secondly, 
because of the widespread prevalence, even among 
CathoMcs, of the erroneous idea that the scholastic 
teaching was opposed to the ethical principle laid 
down by the Founder of Christianity. 

Amongst the arguments which are advanced 
by sociahsts none is more often met than the 
alleged socialist teaching and practice (if the early 
Christians. For instance, Cabet's Voyage en 
Icarie contains the following passage : ' Mais 
quand on s'enfonce serieusement et ardemment 
dans la question de savoir comment la societe 
pourrait etre organisee en Democratic, c'est-a- 
dire sur les bases de I'Egalite et de la Fratemite, 
on arrive k reconnaitre que cette organisation 
exige et entraine necessairement la communaute 
de biens. Et nous batons d'aj outer que cette 
communaute etait egalement proclamee par Jesus- 
Christ, par tous ses apQtres et ses disciples, par 
tous les peres de I'Eglise et tous les Chretiens des 
premiers siecles.' The fact that St. Thomas 
Aquinas, the great exponent of Cathohc teaching 
in the Middle Ages, defends in unambiguous 
language the institution of private property offers 
no difficulties to the socialist historian of Chris- 
tianity. He replies simply that St. Thomas wrote 



PEOPERTY 43 

in an age when the Church was the Church of the 
rich as well as of the poor ; that it had to modify 
its doctrines to ease the consciences of its rich 
members ; and that, ever since the conversion of 
Constantine, the primitive Christian teaching on 
property had been progressively corrupted by 
motives of expediency, until the time of the 
Summa, when it had ceased to resemble in any way 
the teaching of the Apostles.^ We must therefore 
first of all demonstrate that there is no such con- 
tradiction between the teaching of the Apostles 
and that of the mediaeval Church on the subject 
of private property, but that,--on the contrary, 
the necessity of private property was at^aU times 
recogniaedjand insisted on by the Cathohc Church. . 
As it is put in an anonymous article in the Dublin 
Review : ' Among Christian nations we discover 
at a very early period a strong tendency towards 
a general and equitable distribution of wealth 
and property among the whole body politic. 
Grounded on an ever-increasing historical evi- 
dence, we might possibly affirm that the mediaeval 
Church brought her whole weight to bear inces- 
santly upon this one singular and single point.' ^ 
The alleged communism of the first Christians 

''■ See, e.g., Nitti, Catholic Socialism, p. 71. ' Thus, then, according 
to Nitti, the Christian Church has been guilty of the meanest, most 
selfish, and most corrupt utilitarianism in her attitude towards the 
question of wealth and property. She was communistic when she 
had nothing. She blessed poverty in order to fill her own coffers. 
And when the cofEers were fuU she took rank among the owners of land 
and houses, she became zealous in the interests of property, and pro- 
claimed that its origin was divine ' ('The Fathers of the Church and 
Socialism,' by Dr. Hogan, Irish Ecclesiastical Record, vol. xxv. p. 226). 

2 ' Christian Political Economy,' Dvblin Review, N.S., vol. vi. p. 356. 



44 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

is based on a few verses of the Acts of the Apostles 
describing the condition of the Church of Jerusa- 
lem. ' And they that believed were together and 
had all things common ; And sold their posses- 
sions and goods, and parted them to all men, as 
every man had need.' ^ ' And the multitude of 
them that believed were of one heart and of one 
soul : neither said any of them that aught of the 
things which he possessed was his own ; but they 
had all things common. Neither was there any 
amongst them that lacked : for as many as were 
possessors of land or houses sold them, and 
brought the price of the things that were sold, 
And laid them down at the apostles' feet: and 
distribution was made unto every man according 
as he had need.' ^ 

It is by no means clear whether the state of 
things here depicted really amounted to com- 
munism in the strict sense. Several of the most 
enhghtened students of the Bible have come to 
the conclusion that the verses quoted simply 
express in a striking way the great liberality and 
benevolence which prevailed among the Christian 
fraternity at Jerusalem. This view was strongly 
asserted by Mosheim,^ and is held by Dr. Carlyle. 
' A more careful examination of the passages in 
the Acts,' says the latter,* ' show clearly enough 
that this was no systematic division of property, 
but that the charitable instinct of the infant 



1 ii. 44-45. 2 iv. 32, 34, 35. 

' Dissert, ad Hist. Eccles., vol. ii. p. 1. 

* 'The Political Theory of the Ante-Nicene Fathers,' Economio 
Review, vol. ix. 



PROPERTY 45 

Church was so great that those who were in want 
were completely supported by those who were 
more prosperous. . . . Still there was no syste- 
matic communism, no theory of the necessity of 
it.' Colour is lent to this interpretation by the 
fact that similar words and phrases were used to 
emphasise the prevalence of charity and benevo- 
lence in later communities of Christians, amongst 
whom, as we know from other sources, the right 
of private property was fully admitted. Thus 
TertuUian wrote : ^ ' One in mind and soul, we 
do not hesitate to share our earthly goods with 
one another. All things are common among us 
but our wives.' This passage, if it were taken 
alone, would be quite as strong and unambiguous 
as those from the Acts ; but fortunately, a few 
lines higher up, Tertulhan had described how the 
Church was supported, wherein he showed most 
clearly that private property was stiU recognised 
and practised: 'Though we have our treasure- 
chest, it is not made up of purchase-money, as of 
a rehgion that has its price. On the monthly 
collection day, if he Ukes, each puts in a small 
donation ; but only if he has pleasure, and only 
if he be able ; all is voluntary.' This point is 
well put by Bergier : ^ ' Towards the end of the 
first century St. Barnabas ; in the second, St. 
Justin and St. Lucian ; in the third, St. Clement 
of Alexandria, TertuUian, Origen, St. Cyprian ; 
in the fourth, Arnobius and Lactantius, say that 
among the Christians all goods are common; 

1 Apol. 39. 

2 DicHonnawe de Thkilogie, Paris, 1829, tit, ' Communaut6.' 



46 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

there was then certainly no question of a com- 
munism of goods taken in the strict sense.' 

It is therefore doubtful if the Church at Jeru- 
salem, as described in the Acts, practised com- 
munism at aU, as apart from great liberality and 
benevolence. Assuming, however, that the Acts 
should be interpreted in their strict Uteral sense, let 
us see to what the so-caUed communism amounted. 

In the first place, it is plain from Acts iv. 32 
that the communism was one of use, not of owner- 
ship. It was not until the individual owner had 
sold his goods and placed the proceeds in the 
common fund that any question of communism 
arose. ' Whiles it remained was it not thine own,' 
said St. Peter, rebuking Ananias, ' and after it 
was sold was it not in thine owji power ? ' ^ This 
distinction is particularly important in view of 
the fact that it is precisely that insisted on by 
St. Thomas Aquinas. There is no reason to 
suppose that the community of use practised at 
Jerusalem was in any way different from that 
advocated by Aquinas — ^namely, ' the possession 
by a man of external things, not as his own, but 
in common, so that, to wit, he is ready to com- 
municate them to others in their need.' 

In the next place, we must observe that the 
communism described in the Acts was purely 
voluntary. This is quite obvious from the rela- 
tion in the fifth chapter of the incident of Ananias 
and Sapphira. There is no indication that the 
abandonment of one's possessory rights was 

1 Eosoher, Poliiicdl Economy (Eng. trans.), vol. i. p. 246 ; Catholic 
EncyclopcBdia, tit. ' Communism.' 



PROPERTY 47 

preached by the Apostles. Indeed, it would be 
difficult to miderstand why they should have 
done so, when Christ Himself had remained silent 
on the subject. Far from advocating communism, 
the Founder of Christianity had urged the practice 
of many virtues for which the possession of private 
property was essential. ' What Christ recom- 
mended,' says Sudre,^ ' was voluntary abnegation 
or alms-giving. But the giving of goods without 
any hope of compensation, the spontaneous de- 
privation of oneself, could not exist except under 
a system of private property . . . they were one 
of the ways of exercising such rights.' Moreover, 
as the same author points out, private property 
was fuUy recognised under the Jewish dispensa- 
tion, and Christ would therefore have made use of 
explicit language if he had intended to alter the 
old law in this fundamental respect. ' Think not 
that I am come to destroy the law or the prophets : 
I am not come to destroy, but to fulfil.' ^ At the 
time of Christ's preaching, a Jewish sect, the 
Essenes, were endeavouring to put into practice 
the ideals of communism, but there is not a word in 
the Gospels to suggest that He ever held them up as 
an example to His followers. ' Commxmism was 
never preached by Christ, although it Was practised 
under His very eyes by the Essenes. This absolute 
silence is equivalent to an impUcit condemnation.'* 

^ Histoire du Cormmmisme, p. 39. * Matt. v. 17. 

' Sudre, op. dt., p. 44. On the Essenes see ' Historic Phases of 
Socialism,' by Dr. Hogan, Irish Ecclesiastical Record, vol. xxv. p. 334. 
Even Huet discounts the importance of this instance of coiaiuunism, 
Le Eigne social du Christianisme, p. 38. 



48 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

Nor was communism preached as part of 
Christ's doctrine as taught by the Apostles. In 
Paul's epistles there is no direction to the congre- 
gations addressed that they should abandon their 
private property ; on the contrary, the continued 
existence of such rights is esqpressly recognised 
and approved in his appeals for funds for the Church 
at Jerusalem.^ Can it be that, as Rosclier says,^ 
the experiment in communism had produced a 
chronic state of poverty in the Church at Jeru- 
salem ? Certain it is the experiment was never 
repeated in any of the other apostolic congrega- 
tions. The communism at Jerusalem, if it ever 
existed at all, not only f aUed to spread to other 
Churches, but failed to continue at Jerusalem 
itself. It is universally admitted by competent 
students of the question that the phenomenon was 
but temporary and transitory,^ 

The utterances of the Fathers of the Church 
on property are scattered and disconnected. 
Nevertheless, there is sufficient cohesion in them 
to enable us to form an opinion of their teaching 
on the subject. It has, as we have said, frequently 
been asserted that they favoured a system of 
communism, and disapproved of private ownership. 
The supporters of this view base their arguments 
on a number of isolated texts, taken out of their 
context, and not interpreted with any regard to 
the circumstances in which they were written. 

^ e.g. Rom. xy. 26, 1 Cor. xvi. 1. 

* Political Economy, vol. i. p. 246. 

* Sudre, op. cit. ; Salvador, Jiaus-Cfmst et aa Doctrinfi, vol. ii. p. 221, 
See More's Utopia. 



PROPERTY 49 

' The mistake,' as Devas says,^ ' of representing 
the early Christian Fathers of the Church as rank 
socialists is frequently made by those who are 
friendly to modern socialism; the reason for it 
is that either they have taken passages of ortho- 
dox writers apart from their context, and without 
due regard to the circumstances ia which they 
were written, arid the meaning they would have 
conveyed to their hearers ; or else, by a grosser 
blunder, the perversions of heretics are set forth 
as the doctrine of the Church, and a sad case 
arises of mistaken identity.' A careful study of 
the patristic texts bearing on the subject leads one 
to the conclusion that Mr. Devas' s view is without 
doubt the correct one.^ 

The passages from the writings of the Fathers 
which are cited by socialists who are anxious to 
support the proposition that sociaHsm formed 
part of the early Christian teaching may be 
roughly divided into four groups : first, passages 
where the abandonment of earthly possessions is 

1 Dvhlin Review, Jan. 1898. 

2 Dr. Hogan, in an article entitled ' The Fathers of the Church and 
Socialism,' in the Irish Ecclesiastical Secord, vol. xxv. p. 226, has 
examined all the texts relative to property in the writings of TertuUian, 
St. Justin Mart3Ti, St. Clement of Rome, St. dement of Alexandria, 
St. Basil, St. Ambrose, St. John Chrysostom, St. Augustine, and St. 
Gregory the Great ; and the utterances of St. BasU, St. Ambrose, and St. 
Jerome are similarly examined in ' The Alleged Socialism of the Church 
Fathers,' by Dr. John A. Byan. The patristic texts are also fully 
examined by Abb6 Calippe in ' Le Caract^re sociale de la Propri6t6 ' 
in La Semaine Sociale de France, 1909, p. 111. The conclusion come 
to after thorough examinations such as these is always the same. For 
a good analysis of the patristic texts from the communistic standpoint, 
see Conrad Noel, Socialism in Church History. 

D 



50 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

held up as a work of more than ordinary devotion 
— in other words, a counsel of perfection ; second, 
those where the practice of almsgiving is recom- 
mended in the rhetorical and persuasive language 
of the missioner — ^where the faithful are exhorted 
to exercise their charity to such a degree that it 
may be said that the rich and the poor have 
aU things in common ; third, passages directed 
against avarice and the wrongful acquisition or 
abuse of riches ; and fourth, passages where the 
distinction between the natural and positive law 
on the matter is explained. 

The following passage from G3rprian is a good 
example of an utterance which was clearly meant 
as a counsel of perfection. Isolated sentences 
from this passage have frequently been quoted to 
prove that Cyprian was an advocate of com- 
munism ; but there can be no doubt from the 
passage as a whole, that all that he was aiming at 
was to cultivate in his followers a high detach- 
ment from earthly wealth, and that, in so far as 
complete abandonment of one's property is re- 
commended, it is simply indicated as a work of 
quite unusual devotion. It is noteworthy that 
this passage occurs in a treatise on almsgiving, a 
practice which presupposes a system of individual 
ownership : ^ ' Let us consider wha,t the congre- 
gation of believers did in the time of the Apostles, 
when at the first beginnings the mind flourished 
with greater virtues, when the faith of beUevers 
burned with a warmth of faith yet new. Thus 
they sold houses and farms, and gladly and liber- 

^ De Opere et EUemoaynia, 2&. 



PROPERTY 51 

ally presented to the Apostles the proceeds to be 
dispersed to the poor ; selling and aUenating their 
earthly estate, they transferred their lands thither 
where they might receive the fruits of an eternal 
possession, and there prepared houses where they 
might begin an eternal habitation. Such, then, was 
the abundance in labours as was the agreement in 
love, as we read in the Acts — " Neither said any of 
them that aught of the things which he possessed 
was his own ; but they had all things common." 
This is truly to become son of God by spiritual 
birth ; this is to imitate by the heavenly law the 
equity of God the Father. For whatever is of 
God is common in our use ; nor is any one excluded 
from His benefits and His gifts so as to prevent the 
whole human race from enjoying equally the 
divine goodness and liberality. Thus the day 
equally enlightens, the sun gives radiance, the rain 
moisterts, the wind blows, and the sleep is one to 
those who sleep, and the splendour of Stars and 
of the Moon is common. In which examples of 
equahty he who as a possessor in the earth shares 
his returns and his fruits with the fraternity, while 
he is common and just in his gratuitous bounties, 
is an imitator of God the Father.' 

There is a much-quoted passage of St. John 
Chrysostom which is capable of the same inter- 
pretation. In his commentary on the alleged 
communistic existence of the Apostles at Jerusalem 
the Saint emphasises the fact that their com- 
munism was voluntary : ' That this was in con- 
sequence not merely of the miraculous signs, but 
of their own. purpose, is manifest from the case of 



52 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

Ananias and Sapphira.' He further insists on 
the fact that the members of this community were 
animated by unusual fervour : ' iVom the exceed- 
ing ardour of the givers none was in want.' 
Further down, in the same homily, St. John 
Chrysostdm urges the adoption of a communistic 
system of housekeeping, but purely on the 
grounds of domestic economy and saving of 
labour. There is not a word to suggest that a 
communistic system was morally preferable to a 
proprietary one.^ 

The second class of patristic texts which are 
rehed on by sociaUsts are, as we have said, those 
' where the practice of almsgiving is recom- 
mended in the rhetorical and persuasive language 
of the missioner — ^where the faithful are exhorted 
to exercise their charity to such a degree that it 
may be said that the rich and poor have aU things 
in common.' Such passages are very frequent 
throughout the writings of the Fathers, but we 
may give as examples two, which are most fre- 
quently relied on by sociahsts. One of these is 
from St. Ambrose : ^ ' Mercy is a part of justice ; 
and if you wish to give to the poor, this mercy 
is justice. " He hath dispersed, he hath given to 
the poor ; his righteousness endureth for ever." ^ 
It is therefore unjust that one should not be 
helped by his neighbour ; when God hath wished 

1 Horn, on Acts xi. That voluntary poverty was regarded as a 
counsel of perfection by Aquinas is abundantly clear from many 
passages in his works, e.g. Svmma, i. ii. 108, 4 ; n. ii. 185, 6; n. ii. 186, 3; 
8timma cont. Gent., iii. 133. On this, as on every other point, the 
teaching of Aquinas is in line with that of the Fathers. 

' Comm. on Ps, exviii., viiii 22. s Ps. oxii. 9. 



PROPERTY 53 

the possession of the earth to be common to all 
men, and its fruits to minister to all ; but avarice 
estabUshed possessory rights. It is therefore 
just that if you lay claim to anything as your 
private property, which is really conferred in 
common to the whole human race, that you should 
dispense something to the poor, so that you may 
not deny nourishment to those who have the right 
to share with you.' The following passage from 
Gregory the Great ^ is another example of this 
kind of passage : ' Those who rather desire what 
is another's, nor bestow that is their own, are to 
be admonished to consider carefuUy that the 
earth out of which they are taken is common to 
aU men, and therefore brings forth nourishment 
for all in common. Vainly, then, do they suppose 
themselves innocent who claim to their own 
private use the common gift of God ; those who 
in not imparting what they have received walk in 
the midst of the slaughter of their neighbours ; 
since they almost daily slay so many persons as 
there are dying poor whose subsidies they keep 
close in their own possession.' 

The third class of passages to which reference 
must be made is composed of the numerous 
attacks which the Fathers levelled against the 
abuse or wrongful acquisition of riches. These 
passages do not indicate that the Fathers favoured 
a system of communism, but point in precisely 
the contrary direction. If property were an evil 
thing in itself, they would not have wasted so 
much time in emphasising the evil uses to which 

* Lib. Beg. Past., iii. 21. 



54 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

it was sometimes put. The insistence on the 
abuses of an institution is an implicit admission 
that it has its uses. Thus Clement of Alexandria 
devotes a whole treatise to answering the question 
' Who is the rich man who can be saved ? ' in 
which it appears quite plainly that it is the 
possible abuse of wealth, and the possible too 
great attachment to worldly goods, that are the 
principal dangers in the way of a rich man's 
salvation. The suggestion that in order to be 
saved a man must abandon all his property is 
strongly controverted. The following passage 
from St. Gregory Nazianzen ^ breathes the same 
spirit : ' One of us has oppressed the poor, and 
wrested from him his portion of land, and wrongly 
encroached upon his landmarks by fraud or 
violence, and joined house to house, and field to 
field, to rob his neighbour of something, and has 
been eager to have no neighbour, so as to dwell 
alone on the earth. Another has defiled the land 
with usury and interest, both gathering where he 
has not sowed and reaping where he has not 
strewn, farming not the land but the necessity 
of the needy. . . . Another has had no pity on 
the widow and orphans, and not imparted his 
bread and meagre nourishment to the needy ; . . . 
a man perhaps of much property unexpectedly 
gained, for this is the most unjust of all, who finds 
his very bams too narrow for him, filling some 
and emptying others to buUd greater ones for 
future crops.' Similarly Clement of Rome advo- 
cates frugality in the enjoyment of wealth ; ^ and 
1 Orai., xvi. 18. « The Instructor, iii. 7. 



PROPERTY 65 

Salvian has a long passage on the dangers of the 
abuse of riches.^ 

The fourth group of passages is that in which 
the distinction between the natural and positive 
law on the matter is explained. It is here that 
the greatest confusion has been created by sociaHst 
writers, who conclude, because they read in the 
works of some of the Fathers that private property 
did not exist by natural law, that it was therefore 
condemned by them as an illegitimate institution. 
Nothing could be more erroneous. All that the 
Fathers meant in these passages was that in the 
state of nature — ^the ideahsed Golden Age of the 
pagans, or the Garden of Eden of the Christians 
— there was no individual ownership of goods. 
The very moment, however, that man fell from 
that ideal state, communism became impossible, 
simply on account of the change that had taken 
place in man's own nature. To this extent it is 
true to say that the Fathers regarded property 
with disapproval ; it was one of the institutions 
rendered necessary by the fall of man. Of course 
it would have been preferable that man should not 
have fallen from his natural innocence, in which 
case he could have hved a Ufe of communism ; 
but, as he had fallen, and communism had from 
that moment become impossible, property must 
be respected as the one institution which could 
put a curb on his avarice, and preserve a society 
of fallen men from chaos and general rapine. 

That this is the correct interpretation of the 
patristic utterances regarding property and natural 

1 Ad Eccles., i. 7. 



56 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

law appears from the following passage of The 
Divine Institution of Lactantius — ' the most ex'^ 
plicit statement bearing on the Christian idea of 
property in the first f oiir centuries ' : ^ ' " They pre- 
ferred to live content with a simple mode of life," 
as Cicero relates in his poems ; and this is peculiar 
to our religion. " It was not even allowed to mark 
out or to divide the plain with a boundary : men 
sought aU things in common," ^ since God had 
given the earth in common to aU, that they 
might pass their Hfe in common, not that mad and 
raging avarice might claim aU things for itself, 
and that riches produced for aU might not be 
wanting to any. And this saying of the poet 
ought so to be taken, not as suggesting the idea 
that individuals at that time had no private 
property, but it must be regarded as a poetical 
figure, that we may understand that men were 
so hberal, that they did not shut up the fruits of 
the earth produced for them, nor did they in 
sohtude brood over the things stored up, but ad- 
mitted the poor to share the fruits of their labour : 

" Now streams of milk, now streams of nectar flowed." ^ 
And no wonder, since the storehouses of the good 
hteraUy lay open to all. Nor did avarice intercept 
the divine bounty, and thus cause hunger and 
thirst in common ; but all aUke had abundance, 
since they who had possessions gave HberaUy and 
bountifully to those who had not. But after 
Satumus had been banished from heaven, and 

1 'The Biblical and Early Christian Idea of Property,' by Dr. V. 
Bartlett, in Property, its Duties and Rights (London, 1913). 
" Georg., i. 126. a Ovid, Met., i. iii. 



PROPERTY 57 

had arrived in Latium . . . not only did the 
people who had a superfluity fail to bestow a 
share upon others, but they even seized the 
property of others, drawing everything to their 
private gain ; and the things which formerly 
even individuals laboured to obtain for the com- 
mon use of all were now conveyed to the powers 
of a few. For that they might subdue others by 
slavery, they began to withdraw and coUect 
together the necessaries of life, and to keep them 
firmly shut up, that they might make the boimties 
of heaven their own ; not on account of kindness 
{humanitas), a feeling which had no existence for 
them, but that they might sweep together all the 
instruments of lust and avarice.' ^ 

It appears from the above passage that Lac- 
tantius regarded the era in which a system of 
communism existed as long since vanished, if 
indeed it ever had existed. The same idea emerges 
from the writings of St. Augustine, who drew a 
distinction between divine and human right. ' By 
what right does every man possess what he 
possesses ? ' he asks.^ ' Is it not by human right ? 
For by divine right " the earth is the Lord's, and 
the. fuUness thereof." The poor and the rich God 
made of one clay ; the same earth supports alike 
the poor and the rich. By human right, however, 
one says. This estate is mine, this servant is mine, 
this house is mine. By human right, therefore, is 
by right of the Emperor. Why so ? Because 
God has distributed to mankind these very human 

^ Lactantius, Div. Inst., v. 5-6. 
2 Tract in Joh. Ev., vi. 25. 



58 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

rights through the emperors and kings of the 
world.' 

The socialist commentatoi's of St. Augustine 
have strained this, and similar passages, to mean 
that because property rests on human, and not 
on divine, right, therefore it should not exist 
at aU. It is, of course true that what human 
right has created human right can repeal ; and 
it is therefore quite fair to argue that all the 
citizens of a community might agree to live a life 
of communism. That is simply an argument to 
prove that there is nothing immoral in communism, 
and does not prove in the very slightest degree 
that there is anything immoral in property. On 
the contrary, so long as ' the emperors and kings 
of the world ' ordain that private property shall 
continue, it would be, according to St. Augtistine, 
immoral for any individual to maintain that such 
ordinances were wrongful. 

The correct meaning of the patristic distinction 
between natural and positive law with regard to 
property is excellently summarised in Dr. Carlyle's 
essay on Property in Mediceval Theology : ^ " What 
do the expressions of the Fathers mean ? At 
first sight they might seem to be an assertion of 
communism, or denunciation of private property 
as a thing which is sinful or unlawful. But this 
is not what the Fathers mean. There can be 
little doubt that we find the sources of these words 
in such a phrase as that of Cicero — " Sunt autem 
privata nulla natura " ^ — and in the Stoic tradition 

I Property, Its Duties and Bights (London, 1913). 
^ De Off., i. 7. 



PROPERTY 59 

which is represented in one of Seneca's letters, 
when he describes the primitive Ufe in which men 
lived together in peace and happiness, when there 
was no system of coercive government and no 
private property, and says that man passed out 
of this primitive condition as their first innocence 
disappeared, as they became avaricious and dis- 
satisfied with the common enjoyment of the good 
things of the world, and desired to hold them 
as their private possession.^ Here we have 
the quasi-philosophical theory, from which the 
patristic conception is derived. When men were 
innocent there was no need for private property, 
or the other great conventional institutions of 
society, but as this innocence passed away, they 
found themsplves compelled to organise society 
and to devise institutions which should regulate 
the ownership and use of the good things which 
men had once held in common. The institution of 
property thus represents the fall of man from his 
primitive ianocence, through greed and avarice, 
which refused to recognise the common owner- 
ship of things, and also the method by which the 
blind greed of human nature might be controlled and 
regulated. It is this ambiguous origin of the in- 
stitution which explains how the Fathers could hold 
that private property was not natural, that it grew 
out of men's vicious and sinful desires, and at the 
same time that it was a legitimate institution.' 

Janet takes the same view of the patristic 
utterances on this subject : ^ ' What do the Fathers 

^ Seneca, Ep., xiv. 2. 

' Histoire de la Science politique, vol. i. p. 330. 



60 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

say ? It is that in Jesus Christ there is no mine 
and thine. Nothing is more true, without doubt ; 
in the divine order, in the order of absolute 
charity, where men are wholly wrapt up in God, 
distinction and inequahty of goods would be im- 
possible. But the Fathers saw clearly that such 
a state of things was not reaUsable here below. 
What did they do ? They established property on 
human law, positive law, imperial law. Commun- 
ism is either a Utopia or a barbarism ; a Utopia 
if one imagine it founded on universal devotion ; 
a barbarism if one imposes it by force.' ^ 

It must not be concluded that the evidence of 
the approbation by the Fathers of private property 
is purely negative or solely derived from the 
interpretation of possibly ambiguous texts. On 
the contrary, the lawfulness of property is em- 
phatically asserted on more than one occasion. 
' To possess riches,' says Hilary of Poictiers,^ ' is 
not wrongful, but rather the manner in which 
possession is used. ... It is a crime to possess 
wrongfully rather than simply to possess.' ' Who 
does not understand,' asks St. Augustine,^ 'that 
it is not sinful to possess riches, but to love 
and place hope in them, and to prefer them to 
truth or justice ? ' Again, ' Why do you reproach 
us by saying that men renewed in baptism ought 
no longer to beget children or to possess fields and 
houses and money ? Paul allows it.' * According 
to Ambrose,^ ' Riches themselves are not wrong- 

>- See also Jarrett, Medicevdl iSocioMsm. 

* Coram, on Matt. xix. 9. * Gonfra Ad., xx. 2. 

* De Mor. Ecd. Cath., i. 36. ' Epist., Ixiii. 92. 



PROPERTY 61 

ful. Indeed, " redemptio animse viri divitise 
ejus," because he who gives to the poor saves his 
soul. There is therefore a place for goodness in 
these material riches. You are as steersmen in 
a great sea. He who steers his ship well, quickly 
crosses the waves, and comes to port ; but he who 
does not know how to control his ship is sunk by 
his own weight. Wherefore it is written, " Pos- 
sessio divitum ci vitas firmissima." ' A Council 
in A.D. 415 condemned the proposition held by 
Pelagius that ' the rich cannot be saved unless 
they renounced their goods.' ^ 

The more one studies the Fathers the more one 
becomes convinced that property was regarded 
by^them asone of the normal and- legitimgite 
institutions of .human -soeiety. Benigni's con- 
clusion, as the result of his exceptionally thorough 
researches, is that according to the early Fathers, 
' property is lawful and ought scrupulously to be 
respected. But property is subject to the high 
duties of human fellowship which sprang from the 
equahty and brotherhood of man. Collectivism 
is absurd and immoral.' ^ Janet arrived at the 
same conclusion : ' In spite of the words of the 
Fathers, in spite of the advice given by Christ 
to the rich man to sell aU his goods and give to the 
poor, in spite of the communism of the Apostles, 
can one say that Christianity condemned property ? 
Certainly not. Christianity considered it a coun- 
sel of perfection for a man to deprive himself of 
his goods ; it did not abrogate the right of any- 

^ BeviK Arehiologique, 1880, p. 321. 

* L'Eamomia Sociale Christiana avanti Costantino (Grenoa, 1897). 



62 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

body.' ^ The same conclusion is reached by the 
Abbe Cahppe in an excellent article published in 
La Semaine Sociale de France, 1909. ' The right of 
property and of the property owner are assumed.' ^ 
' It is only prejudiced or superficial minds which 
could make the writers of the fotlrth century the 
precursors of modem communists or coUectivists.' ^ 
When we turn to St. Thomas Aquinas, we find 
that his teaching on the subject of property is not at 
all out of harmony with that of the earlier Fathers 
of the Church, but, on the contrary, summarises 
and consohdates it. 'It remained to elaborate, 
to constitute a definite theory of the right of pro- 
perty. It sufficed to harmonise, to collaborate, 
and to relate one to the other these elements 
furnished by the Christian doctors of the first four 
or five centuries ; and ^his was precisely the work 
of the great theologians of the Middle Ages, 
especially of St. Thomas Aquinas. ... In estab- 
lishing his thesis St, Thomas did not borrow 
from the Roman jurisconsults through the medium 
of St. Isidore more than their vocabulary, their 
formulas, their juridical distinctions ; he also 
borrowed from Aristotle the arguments upon 
which the philosopher based his right of property. 
But the ground of his doctrine is undoubtedly of 
Christian origin. There is, between the Fathers 
and him, a perfect continuity.' * ' Community 
of goods,' he writes, ' is ascribed to the natural 
law, not that the natural law dictates that all 

1 Ifistoire de la Science poUtigliie, vol. i. p. 319. 
^ P. 114. s P. 121. 

* Abb6 Calippe, op. cit., 1909, p. 124. 



PROPERTY 63 

things should be possessed in common, and that 
nothing should be possessed as one's own ; but 
because the division of possession is not according 
to the natural law, but rather arose from human 
agreement, which belongs to positive law. Hence 
the ownership of possessions is not contrary to 
the natural law, but an addition thereto devised 
by human reason.' This is simply another way 
of stating St. Augustine's distinction between 
natural and positive law. If it speaks with more 
respect of positive law than St. Augustine had done, 
it is because Aquinas was influenced by the Aristo- 
telian conception of the State being itself a natural 
institution, owing to man being a social animal.^ 
The explanation which St. Thomas gives of the 
necessity for property also shows how clearly he 
agreed with the Fathers' teaching on natural 
communism : ' Two things are competent to man 
in respect of external things. One is the power 
to procure and dispense them, and in this regard 
it is lawful for a man to possess property. More- 
over, this is necessary to human life for three 
reasons. First, because every man is more care- 
ful to procure what is for himself alone than that 
which is common to many or to all : since each 
one would shirk the labour, and would leave to 
another that which concerns the community, as 
happens when there is a great number of servants. 

1- See Carlyle, Properti/ in Mediceval Theology, Community of goods 
is said to be according to natural law in the canon law, but certain 
titles of acquiring private property are also said to be natural, so that 
the passage does not help the discussion very much (Corp, Jur, Can., 
Dec. I. Dist. i. c. 7. 



64 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

Secondly, because human aflEairs are conducted 
in more orderly fashion if each man is charged 
with taking care of some particular thing himself, 
whereas there would be confusion if everybody 
had to look kfter any one thing indeterminately. 
Thirdly, because a more peaceful state is ensured 
to man if each one is contented with his own. 
Hence it is to be observed that quarrels more 
frequently occur when there is no division of the 
things possessed.' ^ It is quite clear from this 
passage that Aquinas regarded property as some- 
thing essential to the existence of society in the 
natural condition of human nattire — ^that is to 
say, the condition that it had acquired at the fall. 
It is precisely the greed and avarice of fallen man 
that renders property an indispensable institution. 
There was another sense in which property was 
said to be according to human law, in distinction 
to the natural law, namely, in the sense that, 
whereas the general principle that men should 
own things might be said to be natural, the 
particular proprietary rights of each individual 
were determined by positive law. In other words, 
the fundamentum of property rights was natural, 
whereas the titulus of particular property rights 
was according to positive law. This distinction 
is stated clearly by Aquinas : ^ ' The natural 
right or just is that which by its very nature is 
adjusted to or commensurate with another person. 
Now this may happen in two ways ; first, accord- 
ing as it is considered absolutely ; thus the male 
by its very nature is commensurate with the 

1 n. ii. 66, 2. 2 n. ii. 57, 3. 



PROPERTY 65 

female to beget offspring by her, and a parent is 
commensurate with the offspring to novirish it. 
Secondly, a thing is naturally commensurate with 
another person, not according as it is considered 
absolutely, but according to something resultant 
from it — for instance, the possession of property. 
For if a particular piece of land be considered 
absolutely, it contains no reason why it should 
belong to one man more than to another, but if 
it be considered in respect of its adaptability to 
cultivation,"^ and the unmolested use of the land, 
it has a certain commensuration to be the pro- 
perty of one and not of another man, as the 
Philosopher shows.' Cajetan's commentary on 
this article clearly emphasises the distinction 
between fundamentum and titulus : ' In the 
ownership of goods two things are to be discussed. 
The first is why one thing should belong to one 
man and another thing to another. The second 
is why this particular field should belong to this 
man, that field to that man. With regard to the 
former inquiry, it may be said that the ownership 
of things is according to the law of nations, but 
with regard to the second, it may be said to result 
from the positive law, because in former times 
one thing was appropriated by one man and 
another thing by another.' It must not be 
supposed, however, from what we have just said, 
that there are no natural titles to property. 
Labour, for instance, is a title flowing from the 
natural law, as also is occupancy, and in certain 
circumstances, prescription. AU that is meant 
by the distinction between fundamentum and 



66 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

titulus is that, whereas it can be clearly demon- 
strated by natural law that the goods of the 
earth, which are given by God for the benefit of 
the whole of mankind, cannot be made use of to 
their full advantage unless they are niade the 
subject of private ownership, particular goods 
cannot be demonstrated to be the lawful property 
of this or that person unless some human act has 
intervened. This human act need not necessarily 
be an act of agreement ; it may equally be an act 
of some other kind — ^for instance, a dectee of the 
law-giver, or the exercise of labour upon one's 
own goods. In the latter case, the additional 
value of the goods becomes the lawful property 
of the person who has exerted the labour. 
Aquinas therefore pronounced unmistakably in 
favour nf f\u£\^ji imf i xiy ^^^ and 

in doing so was in Jii11. a.gi:ftemTm4r^wu f,Ti ilnp, "F'a.iliP'. rs 
of the Church. He_jKas-.iollowed without hesi- 
tation by allltKeTater theologians, and it is abund- 
antly evident from their writings that the right 
of private property was the keystone of their 
whole economic system.^ 

Communism therefore was no part of the schol- 
astic teaching, but it must not be concluded from 
this that the medisevals approved of the unregu- 
lated individualism which modem opinion allows 
to the owners of property. The very strength of 

>■ A oommunity of goods, more or less complete, and a denial of the 
rights of private property was part of the teaching of many sects 
which were condemned as heretical — ^for instance, the Albigenses, the 
Vaudois, the B6gards, the Apostoli, and the Fratricelli. (See Brants, 
op. dt.. Appendix II. 



PROPERTY 67 

the right to own property entailed as a consequence 
the duty of making good use of it; and a clear 
distinction was drawn between the power ' of 
procuring and dispensing ' property and the power 
of using it. We have dealt with the former power 
in the present section, and we shaU pass to the 
consideration of the latter in the next. In a 
later chapter we shall proceed to discuss the 
duties which attached to the owners of property 
in regard to its exchange. 



Section 2. — Duties RBGABDma the Acquisi- 
tion AND Use of Pkopbrty 

We referred at the end of the last section to the 
very important distinction which Aquinas draws 
between the power of procuring and dispensing ^ 
exterior things and the power of using them. 
' The second thing that is competent to man with 
regard to external things is their use. In this 
respect man ought to possess external things, not t^ 
as his own, but as common, so that, to wit, he is 
ready to communicate them to others in their 
need.' ^ These words wherein St. Thomas lays 
down the doctrine of community of user of pro- 

^ Goyau insists on the importance of the words ' procure ' and ' dis- 
pense.' ' Dont le premier 6veille I'idde d'une oonstante sollicitude, et 
dont le second ^voque I'image d'une g6n6rosit6 sympathetique ' (Autour 
jdu Catholicisme Sociale, vol. ii. p. 93). 

^ n. ii. 66, 2. In another part of the Summa the same distinction 
is clearly laid down. ' Bona temporalia quee homini divinitus con- 
f eruntur, ejus quidem sunt quantum ad proprietatem ; sed quantum 
ad usum non solun^ desent ease ejus, sed aliorum qui en eis sustentari 
possunt en eo quod ei superfluit,' n. ii. 32, 5, ad 2. 



68 MEDL3EVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

perty were considered as authoritative by all 
later writers on the subject, and were univer- 
sally quoted with approval by them,^ and may 
therefore be taken as expressing the generally 
held view of the Middle Ages. They require 
careful explanation in order that their meaning 
be accurately understood.^ Cajetan's gloss on 
this section of the Summa enables us to under- 
stand its significance in a broad sense, but fuUer 
information must be derived from a study of other 
parts of the Summa itself. ' Note,' says Cajetan, 
' that the words that community of goods in 
respect of use arises from the law of nature may 
be understood in two ways, one positively, the 
other negatively. And if they are understood in 
their positive sense they mean that the law of 
nature dictates that aU things are common to aU 
men ; if in their negative sense, that the law of 
nature did not estabhsh private ownership of 
possessions. And in either sense the proposition 
is true if correctly imderstood. In the first place, 
if they are taken in their positive sense, a man 
who is in a position of extreme necessity may take 
whatever he can find to succour himself or another 
in the same condition, nor is he bound in such a 
case to restitution, because by natural law he has 

^ Janssen, op. cit., vol. ii. p. 91. 

^ The Abb6 Calippe sunmiarises St. Thomas's doctrine as foUows ; 
' Le droit de propri6t6 est un droit r6el ; mais ce n'est pas un droit 
illimit^, les propri6taires ont des devoirs ; ils ont des devoirs parce que 
Dieu qui a cr66 la terre ne I'a pas cr66e pour eux seuls, mais pour 
tous ' {Semaine Sociale de France, 1909, p. 123). According to 
Antoninus of Morence, goods could be evilly acquired, evilly distributed, 
or evilly consumed {Irish Theological Qvarterly, vol. vii. p. 146), 



PROPERTY 69 

but made use of his own. And in the negative 
sense they are equally true, because the law of 
nature did not institute one thing the property 
of one person, and another thing of another 
person.' The principle of community of user 
flows logically from the very nature of property 
itself as defined by Aquinas, who taught that 
the supreme justification of private property 
was that it was the most advantageous method 
of securing for the community the benefits of 
material riches. While the owner of property 
has therefore an ahsnlutp, f ijjrht to thfi goods he 
possesses, he must at the same time remember 
that this right is estabMshed primarily on his power 
to benefit his neighbour by his proper use of it, 
The best evidence of the correctness of this state- 
ment is the fact that the scholastics admitted 
that, if the owner of property was withholding it 
from the community, or from any member of the 
community who had a real need of it, he could be 
forced to apply it to its proper end. If the com- 
munity could pay for it, it was bound to do so ; 
but if the necessitous person could not pay for 
it, he was none the less entitled to take it. The 
former of these cases was illustrated by the 
principle of the dominium eminens of the State ; 
and the latter by the principle that the giving of 
alms to a person in real need was a duty not of 
charity, but of justice.^ We shall see in a moment 

^ On the application of this principle by the popes in the thirteenth 
and fifteenth centuries in the case of their own estates, see Ardant, 
Popes et Paysana, a work which must be read with a certain degree of 
caution (Nitti, OathoUc Socialism, p. 290). 



70 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

that the most usual apphcation of the principle 
enunciated by Aquinas was in the case of one 
person's extreme necessity which required alms- 
giving from another's superfluity, but, even short of 
such cases, there were rules of conduct in respect of 
the user of property on all occasions which were 
of extreme importance in the economic life of the 
time. 

These principles for the guidance of the owner of 
property are not collected under any single head- 
ing in the Summa, but must be gathered from the 
various sections dealing with man's duty to his 
feUow-men and to himself. One leading virtile 
which was inculcated with great emphasis by 
sf Aquinas was that of temperance. ' AU pleasur- 
able things which come within the use of man,' 
we read in the section dealing with this subject, 
' are ordered to some necessity of this hfe as an 
end. And therefore temperance accepts the 
necessity of this hfe as a rule or measure of the 
things one uses, so that, to wit, they should be 
used according as the necessity of this life re- 
quires.' 1 St. Thomas explains, moreover, that 
* necessary ' must be taken in the broad sense of 
suitable to one's condition of life, and not merely 
necessary to maintain existence.^ The principles 
of temperance did not apply in any special way to 
the user of property more than to the enjoyment 

1 n. ii. 141, 5. 

* Ibid., ad. 2. As Buridan puts it (Eth., iv. 4), ' If any man has more 
than is necessary for his own requirements, and does not give away 
anjrthing to the poor, and to his relations and neighbours, he is acting 
against right reason.' 



PROPERTY 71 

of any other good ; ^ but they are relevant as 
laying down the broad test of right and wrong in 
the user of one's goods. 

More particularly relevant to the subject before 
us is the teaching of Aquinas on Uberality, which ^ 
is a virtue directly connected with the user of 
property. Aquinas defines liberality as ' a virtue 
by which men use well aU those exterior things 
which are given to us for sustenance.' ^ The 
limitations within which liberality should be 
practised are stated in the same article : ' As St. 
Basil and St. Ambrose say, God has given to many 
a superabundance of riches, in order that they 
might gain merit by their dispensing them well. 
Few things, however, sufl&ce for one man ; and 
therefore the liberal man will advantageously 
expend more on others than on himself. In the 
spiritual sphere a man must always care for him- 
self before his neighbours ; and also in temporal 
things liberality does not demand that a man 
should think of others to the exclusion of himself 
and those dependent on him.' ^ 

' It is not necessary for liberality that one should 
give away so much of one's riches that not enough 
remains to sustain himself and to enable him to 
perform works of virtue. This complete giving 
away without reserve belongs to the state of the 
perfection of spiritual hfe, of which we shall treat 
lower down ; but it must be known that to give 

^ ' Rationalis oreaturse vera perfeotio est unamqnamque rem tanti 
habere quanti habenda est, eicut pluris est anima quam esca ; fides 
et sequitas quam peounia ' (Gerson, De. Cont.). 

2 n. u. 117, 1. » Ibid., ad. 1. 



72 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

one's goods liberally is an act of virtue which 
itself produces happiness.' ^ The author pro- 
ceeds to discuss whether making use of money- 
might be an act of hberahty, and replies that 
'as money is by its very nature to be classed 
among useful goods, because all exterior thiags 
are destined for the use of man, therefore the 
proper act of Uberality is the good use of money 
and other riches.' ^ Moreover, ' it belongs to a 
virtuous man not simply to use well the goods 
which form the matter of his actions, but also to 
prepare the means and the occasions to use them 
well ; thus the brave soldier sharpens his blade 
and keeps it in the scabbard, as well as exercisiag 
it on the enemy ; in Hke manner, the Hberal man 
should prepare and reserve his riches for a suitable 
use.' ^ It appears from this that to save part of 
one's annual income to provide against emer- 
gencies in the futiire, either by means of insur- 
ance or by investing in productive enterprises, is 
an act of hberahty. 
The question is then discussed whether hber- 

1 n. ii. 117, ad. 2. " lUd., ad. 3. 

' Ibid., ad. 2. ' Potest concludi quod aooipere et custodire modi- 
ficata sunt acta liberalitatis. . . . Major per hoo probatur quod 
dantem multotiena et consumentem, nihil autem accipientem et custo- 
dientem cito derelinqueret substantia temporalis ; et ita perirent 
omnis ejus actus quia non habent amplius quid dare et consumere. . . . 
Hie autem acoeptio et custodia sic modifioari debet. Primo quidem 
oportet ut non sit injusta ; seoundo quod non sit de cupiditate vel 
avaritia suspeota propter exoessum ; tertio quod non permittat 
labi substantiam propter defectum . . . Dare quando oportet et 
custodire quando oportet dare contrariantur ; sed dare quando 
oportet et custodire quando oportet non contrariantur ' (Buridan, 
Eth., iv. 2). 



PROPEETY 73 

ality is a part of justice. Aquinas concludes ' that 
liberality is not a species of justice, because 
justice renders to another what is his, but hber- 
ality gives him what is the giver's own. StiU, it 
has a Certain agreement with justice in two 
points ; first that it is to another, as justice also 
is ; secondly, that it is about exterior things like 
justice, though in another way. And therefore 
liberaHty is laid down by some to be a part of 
justice as a victue^ ajipjeKgd" 1^'i;T*sti'ee- as an acces- 
sory to a principal. 'J;__AgaiQT-' althougE liber- 
aUty supposes not any legal debt as justice does, 
still it supposes a certain moral debt considering 
what is becoming in the person himself who 
practises the virtue, not as though he had any 
obligation to the other party ; and therefore 
there is about it very little of the character of a 
debt.' 2 

It is important to draw attention to the fact 
that Uberalitas consists in making a good usei^ 
of property, and not merely in distributing it to 
others, as a confusion with the Enghsh word 
' Hberahty ' might lead us to beheve. It is, as we 
said above, therefore certain that a wise and 
prudent saving of money for investment would 
be considered a course of conduct within the 
meaning of the word Uberalitas, especially if the 
enterprise in which the money were invested were 
one which would benefit the commimity as a 
whole. ' Modem industrial conditions demand 
that a man of wealth should distribute a part 
of his goods indirectly -;- that is, by investing 

1 n. ii. 117, art. 5. ^ Ibid., ad. 1. 



74 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

them in productive and labour-employing enter- 
prises.' ^ 
^ The nature of the virtue of Uberalitas may be 
more clearly understood by an explanation of the 
vices which stand opposed to it. The first of 
these treated by Aquinas is avarice, which he 
defines as ' superfluus amor habendi divitias.' 
Avarice might be committed in two ways — ^by 
harbouring an undue desire of acquiring wealth, 
or by an imdue reluctance to part with it — 'primo 
autem superabundant in retinendo . . . secundo 
ad avaritiam pertinet superabundare in accipi- 
endo.' 2 These definitions are amplified in another 
part of the same section. Tor in every action 
that is directed to the attainment of some end 
goodness consists in the observance of a certain 
measure. The means to the end must be com- 
mensurate with the end, as medicine with health. 
But exterior goods have the character of things 
needful to an end. Hence human goodness in 
the matter of these goods must consist in the 
observance of a certain measure, as is done by a 
man seeking to have exterior riches in so far as 
they are necessary to his life according to his 
rank and condition. And therefore sin consists 
in exceeding this measure and trying to acquire 
or retain riches beyond the due hmit ; and this is 
the proper nature of avarice, which is defined to 
be an immoderate love of having.' ^ ' Avarice 
may involve immoderation regarding exterior 

^ Ryan, The Alleged SociaMsm of the Chwrch Faihers, p. 20, and see 
Goyau, Le Pa/pe e( la Question Sociale, p. 79. 
" n. ii. 118, 4. s /jj^j.^ ad. 1. 



PROPERTY 75 

things in two ways ; in one way immediately 
as to the receiving or keeping of them when one 
acquires or keeps beyond the due amoimt ; and 
in this respect it is directly a sin against one's 
neighbour, because in exterior things one man 
cannot have superabxmdance without another 
being in want, since temporal goods cannot be 
simultaneously possessed by many. The other 
way in which avarice may involve immoderation 
is in interior afEection. . . .' These words must 
not be taken to condemn the acquisition of large 
fortunes by capitaUsts, which is very often neces- 
sary in order that the natural resources of a 
country may be properly exploited. One man's 
possession of great wealth is at the present day 
frequently the means of opening up new sources 
of wealth and revenue to the entire community. 
In other words, superabiindance is a relative term. 
This, like many other passages of St. Thomas, 
must be given a contemporanea expositio. ' There 
were no capitalists in the thirteenth century, but 
only hoarders.' ^ 

It must also be remembered that what would 
be considered avarice in a man in one station of 
Mfe would not be considered such in a man in 
another. So long as one did not attempt to*' 
acquire an amomit of wealth disproportionate to 
the needs of one's station of life, one could not 
be considered avaricious. Thus a common soldier 
would be avaricious if he strove to obtain a 
uniform of the quaUty worn by an officer, and a 

1 Rickaby, Aguinaa Ethievs, vol. ji. p. 234. 



76 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

simple cleric if he attempted to clothe himself in 
a style only befitting a bishop.^ 
xf The avaricious man ofEended against liberahty 
by caring too much about riches; the prodigal, 
on the other hand, cared too httle about them, and 
did not attach to them their proper value. ' In 
affection while the prodigal faUs short, not taking 
due care of them, in exterior behaviour it belongs 
to the prodigal to exceed in giving, but to fail 
in keeping or acquiring, while it belongs to the 
miser to come short in giving, but to superabound 
in getting and in keeping. Therefore it is clear 
that prodigaUty is the opposite of covetousness.' ^ 
A man, however, might commit both sins at the 
same time, by being unduly anxious to acquire 
wealth which he distributed prodigally. ^ Prodi- 
gality could always be distinguished from extreme 
hberaUty by a consideration of the circumstances 
of the particular case ; a truly Mberal man might 
give away more than a prodigal in case of neces- 
sity.* Prodigahty, though a sin, was a sin of a 
less grievous kind than avarice.^ 

^ Aquinas, In Oral. Dom. Expos., iv. Ashley gives many quotations 
fiom early English literature to show how fully the idea of status was 
accepted {Economdo History, vol. i. pt. ii. p. 389). On the warfare 
waged by the Church on luxury in the Middle Ages, see Baudrillard, 
Histoire du Luxe privi et publique, vol. iii. pp. 630 et seq. 

2 n. ii. 119, 1. 

» Ibid., ad. 1. * Ibid., ad. 3. 

' Ibid., art. 3. ' Per prodigalltatem intelligimus habitum quo quis 
prseter vel contra dictamen rectae rationis circa peounias excedit in 
datione vel consumptione vel oustodia ; et per iUiberaJitatem intelli- 
gimus habitum quo quis contra dictamen rectae rationis deficit circa 
pecunias in datione vel consumptione, vel superabundat in acceptione 
vel custodia ipsarum ' (Buridan, Eth., iv. 3). 



PROPERTY 77 

In addition to the duties which were imposed 
on the owners of property in all circumstances 
there was a further duty which only arose on 
special occasions, namely, magnificentia, or munifi- ^ 
cence. This virtue is discussed by Aquinas, ^ 
but we shall quote the passages of Buridan which 
explain it, not because they depart in any way 
from the teaching of Aquinas, but because they ' 
are clearer and more scientific. ' By mtmificence,-^ 
we understand a habit inchning one to the per- 
formance of great works, or to the incurring of 
great expenses, when, where, and in the manner 
in which they are called for {fuerit opportunum), 
for example, building a church, assembling great 
armies for a threatened war, and giviag splendid 
marriage feasts.' He explains that ' munificence 
stands in the same relation to hberality as bravery 
acquired by its exercise in danger of death in 
battle does to bravery simply and commonly 
understood.' Two vices stand opposed to muni-SK 
ficentia: (1) parvificentia, 'a habit inclining one 
not to undertake great works, when circum- 
stances call for them, or to undertaking less, or 
at less expense, than the needs of the situation 
demand,' and (2) ^avova-Ca, ' a habit inclining one 
to undertaking great works, which are not called 
for by circumstances, or undertaking them on a 
greater scale or at a greater expense than is 
necessary.' ^ 

Both in the case of avarice and prodigahty the^ 
offending state of mind consisted in attaching 
a wrong value to wealth, and the inculcation of 
1 n. ii. 134. ^ Eth., iv, 7, 



78 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

the virtue of liberality must have been attended 
with good results not alone to the souls of indi- 
viduals, but to the economic condition of the 
community. The avaricious man not only im- 
perilled his own soul by attaching too much 
iftiportanoe to temporal gain, but he also injured 
the community by monopolising too large a share 
of its wealth ; the prodigal man, in addition to 
incurring the occasion of various sins of intemper- 
ance, also impoverished the community by wast- 
ing in reckless consumption wealth which might 
have been devoted to productive or charitable 
purposes. He who neglected the duty of munifi- 
cence, either by refusing to make a great expendi- 
ture when it was called for (parvificentia) or by 
making one when it was unnecessary {^avovtria) 
was also deemed to have done wrong, because in 
the one case he valued his money too highly, and 
in the other not highly enough. In other words, 
he attached a wrong value to wealth. Nothing 
could be further from the truth than the sug- 
gestion that the schoolmen despised or behttled 
temporal riches. Quite on the contrary, they 
esteemed it a sin to conduct oneself in a manner 
which showed a defective appreciation of their 
value. ^ Riches may have been the occasion of 
sin ; but so was poverty. ' The occasions of sin 
are to be avoided,' says Aquinas, ' but poverty 
is an occasion of evil, because theft, perjury, and 
flattery are frequently brought about by it. 

* ' Non videtur secundum humanam rationem esse boni et perfeoti 
divitias abjicere totaliter, sed eis uti bene et refioiendo superfluaa 
pauperibua subvenire et amicis ' (Buridan, Eth., iv. 3). 



PROPERTY 79 

Therefore poverty should not be voluntarily 
undertaken, but rather avoided.' * Buridan says : 
' There is no doubt that it is much more difficult 
to be virtuous in a state of poverty than in one 
of moderate affluence ; ' ^ and Antoninus of 
Florence expresses the opinion that poverty is in 
itself an evil thing, although out of it good may 
come.^ Even the ambition to rise in the world 
was laudable, because every one may rightfully 
desire to place himself and his dependants in a 
participation of the fiiUest human fehcity of which 
man is capable, and to rid himself of the necessity 
of corporal labour.* Avarice and prodigality 
alike offended against Uberality, because they 
tended to deprive the commimity of the maximum 
benefit which it should derive from the wealth 
with which it was endowed. Dr. Cunninghajn 
may be quoted in support of this view. ' One of 
the gravest defects of the Roman Empire lay in 
the fact that its system left little scope for indi- 
vidual aims, and tended to check the- energy of 
capitalists and labourers alike. JBut Christian 
teaching opened up an unending prospect before 
the individual personally, and encouraged him to 
activity and diligence by an eternal hope. Nor 
did such concentration of thought on a hfe be- 
yond the grave necessarily divert attention from 
secular duties ; Christianity did not disparage 
them, but set them in a new light, and brought 
out new motives for taking them seriously. . . . 
The acceptance of this higher view of the dignity 

^ Sitmma amt. Oemt., ili. 131. * Eth., iv. 3. 

* Swmma, iv. 12, 3. * Cajetan, Comm, on n. ii. 118, 1. 



80 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

of human life as immortal was followed by a fuller 
recognition of personal responsibility. Ancient 
philosophy had seen that man is the master of 
material things ; but Christianity introduced a 
new sense of duty in regard to the manner of 
using them. . . . Christian teachers were forced 
to protest against any employment of wealth that 
disregarded the glory of God and the good of 
man.' ^ It was the opinion of Knies that the 
peculiarly Christian virtues were of profound 
ecoiiomic value. ' Temperance, thrift, and in- 
dustry — ^that is to say, the s\m and rain of economic 
activity — ^were recommended by the Church and 
inculcated as Christian virtues ; idleness as the 
mother of theft, gambling as the occasion of fraud, 
were forbidden ; and gain for its own sake was 
classed as a kind of robbery.' ^ 
If The great rule, then, with regard to the user of 
property was liberahty. Closely aUied with the 
duty of hberahty was the duty of almsgiving — ' an 
act of charity through the medium of money.' ^ 
Almsgiving is not itself a part of liberality except 
in so far as liberality removes an obstacle to 
such acts, which may arise from excessive love 
of riches, the result of which is that one clings 
to them more than one ought. ^ Aquinas divides 

^ Western Civilisation, vol. ii. pp. 8-9. 

2 Politische Oehonomie vom Standpuncte der geschicMichen Mefhode, 
p. 116, and see Bambaud, Histoire, p. 769; Champagny, La Bible 
et TEccmomie poKHque ; Thomas Aquinas, Simima, n. ii. 50, 3 ; Sertil- 
langes, Sociaiisme et Ohristianisme, p. 53. It was nevertheless recog- 
nised and insisted on that wealth was not an end in itself, but merely 
a means to an end (Aquinas, Summa, i. ii. 2^ 1). 

' n. ii. 32, 1. « Ibid., ad. 4. 



PROPERTY 81 

alms-deeds into two kinds, spiritual and corporal, 
the latter alone of which concern us here. 
' Corporal need arises either during this hfe or 
afterwards. If it occurs during this life, it is 
either a common need in respect of things needed 
by all, or is a special need occurring through some 
accident supervening. In the first case the need 
is either internal or external. Internal need is 
twofold : one which is relieved by sohd food, viz. 
hunger, in respect of which we have to feed the 
hungry ; while the other is relieved by liquid 
food, viz. thirst, in respect of which we have to 
give drinJc to the thirsty. The common need with 
regard to external help is twofold : one in respect 
of clothing, and as to this we have to clothe the 
naked ; while the other is in respect of a dweUing- 
place, and as to this we have to harbour the harbour- 
less. Again, if the need be special, it is either the 
result of an internal cause like sickness, and then 
we have to visit the sick, or it results from an 
external cause, and then we have to ransom the 
captive. After this life we give burial to the dead.'' '^ 
Aquinas then proceeds to explain in what cir- 
cumstances the duty of almsgiving arises. ' Alms- 
giving is a matter of precept. Since, however, 
precepts are about acts of virtue, it follows that 
aU almsgiving «iust be a matter of precept in so 
far as it is necessary to virtue, namely, in so far 
as it is demanded by right reason. Now right 
reason demands that we should take into considera- 
tion something on the part of the giver, and some- 
thing on the part of the recipient. On the part 

* n. ii. 32, art. 2. 
F 



82 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

of the giver it must be noted that he must give 
of his surplus according to Luke xi. 4, " That 
which remaineth give alms." This surplus is to be 
taken in reference not only to the giver, but also 
in reference to those of whom he has charge (in 
which case we have the expression necessary to the 
'person, taking the word person as expressive of 
dignity). . . . On the part of the recipient it is 
necessary that he should be in need, else there 
would be no reason for giving him alms ; yet 
since it is not possible for one individual to reheve 
the needs of aU, we are not bound to reUeve aU 
who are in need, but only those who could not be 
succoured if we did not succour them. For in 
such cases the words of Ambrose apply, " Feed him 
that is dying of hunger ; if thou hast not fed him 
thou hast slain him." Accordingly we are bound 
to give alms of our surplus, as also to give alms to 
one whose need is extreme ; otherwise almsgiving, 
like any other greater good, is a matter of counsel.' ^ 
In replying to the objection that it is lawful for 
every one to keep what is his own, St. Thomas 
restates with enj^phasis the principle of community 
of user : ' The temporal goods which are given 
us by God are ours as to the ownership, but as 
to the use of them they belong not to us alone, but 
also to such others as we are able to succour out 
of what we have over and above our needs.' ^ 
Albertus Magnus states this in very strong 
words : ' For a man to give . out of his superflu- 
ities is a mere act of justice, because he is rather 
then steward of them for the poor than the 

1 n. ii. 32, art. 6. « lUi., ad. 2. 



PROPERTY 83 

owner ; ' ^ and at an earlier date St. Peter Damian 
had afl&rmed that ' he who gives to the poor re- 
turns what he does not himself own, and does not 
dispose of his owii goods.' He insists in the same 
passage that almsgiving is not an act of mercy, but 
of strict justice.^ In the reply to another objec- 
tion the duty of almsgiving is stated by Aquinas 
with additional vigour. ' There is a time when we 
sin mortally if we omit to give alms — on the part 
of the recipient when we see that his need is evi- 
dent and urgent, and that he is not hkely to be 
succoured otherwise — on the part of the giver 
when he has superfluous goods, which he does not 
need for the time being, so far as he can judge with 
probabiMty.' ^ 

The next question which St. Thomas discusses 
is whether one ought to give alms out of what one 
needs. He distinguishes between two kinds of 
' necessaries.' The first is that without which 
existence is impossible^ out of which kind of 
necessary things one is not boimd to give alms 
save in exceptional cases, when, by doing so, one 
would be helping a great personage or supporting 
the Church or the State, since ' the common good 
is to be preferred to one's own.' The second Idnd 
of necessaries are those things without which a 
man cannot live in keeping with his social station. 
St. Thomas recommends the giving of alms out 
of this part of one's estate, but points out that it 
is only a matter of counsel, and not of precept, 
and one must not give alms to such an extent as 

* Jarrett, Medieval Socialism, p. 87. 

2 Be Eleemosynis, cap. 1. " n. ii. 32, 5, ad. 3. 



84 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

to impoverish oneself permanently. To this last 
provision, however, there are three exceptions : 
one, when a man is entering religion and giving 
away aU his goods ; two, when he can easily 
replace what he gives away ; and, three, when he 
is in presence of great indigence on the part of an 
individual, or great need on the part of the com- 
mon weal. In these three cases it is praiseworthy 
for a man to forgo the requisites of his station 
in order to provide for a greater need.^ 

:- The mediaeval teaching on almsgiving is very 
weU summarised by Fr, Jarrett,^ as foUows : 
' (1) A man is obhged to help another in his extreme 
need even at the risk of grave inconvenience to 
himseH ; (2) a man is obliged to help another who, 
though not in extreme need, is yet in considerable 
distress, but not at the risk of grave inconvenience 
to himself ; (3) a man is not obhged to help an- 
other when necessity is sUght, even though the 
risk to himself should be quite trifling.' 

The importance of the duty of almsgiving 
further appears from the section where Aquinas 
lays down that the person to whom alms should 
have been given may, if the owner of the goods 
neglects his duty, repair the omission himself. 

jfAll things. are common property in a case of 
extreme necessity. Hence one who is in dire 
straits may take another's goods in order to 
succour himself if he can find no one who is willing 
to give him something.' ^ The duty of using 
one's goods for the benefit of one's neighbours 

^ n. ii. 32, 6. ' Medieeval Socialism, p. 90. 

» Ibid., art. 7 ad. 3. 



PROPERTY 85 

was a fit matter for enforcement by the State, 
provided that the burdens imposed by legislation 
were equitable. ' Laws are said to be just, both 
from the end, when, to wit, they are ordained to 
the common good — and from their author, that 
is to say, when the law that is made does not 
exceed the power of the law-giver — and from their 
form, when, to wit, burdens are laid on the sub- 
jects according to an equality of proportion and 
with a view to the common good. For, since every 
man is part of the community, each man in all 
that he is and has belongs to the community : 
just as a part in aU that it is belongs to the whole ; 
wherefore nature inflicts a loss on the part in order 
to save the whole ; so that on this account such 
laws, which impose proportionate burdens, are 
just and binding in conscience.' ^ 

There can be no doubt that the practice of 
the scholastic teaching of community of user, in 
its proper sense, made for social stability. The 
following passage from Trithemius, written at the 
end of the fifteenth century, is interesting as 
showing how consistently the doctrine of St. 
Thomas was adhered to two hundred years after 
his death, and also that the failure of the rich 
to put into practice the moderate communism 
of St. Thomas was the cause of the rise of the 
heretical communists, who attacked the very 
foundations of property itself : ' Let the rich 
remember that their possessions have not been 
entrusted to them in order that they may have 
the sole enjoyment of them, but that they may 

1 I. ii. 96, 4, 



86 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

use and manage them as property belonging to 
mankind at large. Let them remember that 
when they give to the needy they only give them 
what belongs to them. If the duty of right use 
and management of property, whether worldly 
or spiritual, is neglected, if the rich think that 
they are the sole lords and masters of that which 
they possess, and do not treat the needy as their 
brethren, there must of necessity arise an inner 
shattering of the commonwealth. False teachers 
and deceivers of the people wiU then gain influ- 
ence, as has happened in Bohemia, by preaching 
to the people that earthly property should be 
equally distributed among all, and that the rich 
must be forcibly condemned to the division of 
their wealth. Then follow lamentable conditions 
and civil wars ; no property is spared ; no right 
of ownership is any longer recognised ; and the 
wealthy may then with justice complain of the 
loss of possessions which have been unrighteously 
taken from them ; but they should also seriously 
ask themselves the question whether in the days 
of peace and order they recognised in the adminis- 
tration of these goods the right of their superior 
lord and owner, namely, the God of aU the earth.' ^ 
It must not, however, be imagined for a moment 
that the community of user advocated by the 
scholastics had anything in common with the 
communism recommended by modern Socialists. 
As we have seen above, the scholastic communism 
did not at aU apply to the procuring and dispens- 
ing of material things, but only to the mode of 

^ Quoted in Jaussen, op. eit, vol. ii. p. 91. 



PROPERTY 87 

using them. It is not even correct to say that 
the property of an individual was limited by the 
duty of using it for the common good. As 
Kambaud puts it : ' Les devoirs de charite, d'6quite 
naturelle, et de simple convenance sociale peuvent 
affecter, ou mieux encore, commander un certain 
usage de la richesse, mais ce n'est pas le meme 
chose que limiter la propriete.' ^ The community 
of user of the scholastics was distinguished from 
that of modern SociaHsts not less strongly by the 
motives which inspired it than by the effect it 
produced. The former was dictated by high 
spiritual aims, and the contempt of material goods ; 
the latter is the fruit of over-attachment to mate- 
rial goods, and the envy of their possessors.^ 

The large estates which the Church itseK owned 
have frequently been pointed to as evidence of 
hypocrisy in its attitude towards the common 
user of property. This is not the place to inquire 
into the condition of ecclesiastical estates in the 
Middle Ages, but it is sufficient to say that they 
were usually the centres of charity, and that in 
the opinion of so impartial a writer as Roscher, 
they rather tended to make the rules of using 

^ Op. eit., p. 43. The same -writer shows that there is no authority 
in Christian teaching for the proposition, advanced by many Christian 
Socialists, that property is a * social function ' {Odd., p. 774). The 
right of property even carried with it the jus abutendi, which, however, 
did not mean the right to atmse, but the right to destroy by consump- 
tion (see Antoine, Cours d'Economie sociale, p. 526). 

^ Roscher, op. cit., p. 5 : ' Vom neuern Sooialismus freilich unter- 
scheidet sich diese Auffassung nicht blosz durch ihre religiose Grundlage, 
sondem auch durch ihre, jedem Mammonsdienst entgegengesetze, 
Verachtung der materieEen Giiter,' 



88 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

goods for the common use practicable than the 
contrary.^ 

Section 3. — Pboperty rsr Humak Beings 

Before we pass from the subject of property, 
we must deal with a particular kind of property 
right, namely, that of one human being over 
another. At the present day the idea of one man 
being owned by another is repugnant to aU en- 
Hghtened pubhc opinion, but this general repug- 
nance is of very recent growth, and did not exist 
in mediseval Europe. In deahng with the schol- 
astic attitude towards slavery, we shall indicate, 
as we did with regard to its attitude towards 
property in general, the fundamental harmony 
between the teaching of the primitive and the 
mediaeval Church on the subject. No apology is 
needed for this apparent digression, as a com- 
parison of the teaching of the Chxirch at the two 
periods of its development helps us to understand 
precisely what the later doctruie was ; and, more- 
over, the close analogy which, as we shall see, 
existed between the Church's view of property 
and slavery, throws much hght on the true nature 
of both institutions. 

Although in practice Christianity had done a 
very great deal to mitigate the hardships of the 
slavery of ancient times, and had in a large degree 
abohshed slavery by its encouragement of emanci- 
pation,^ it did not, in theory, object to the institu- 

^ Rosoher, op. cit., p. 6. 

^ See Roscher, Political Economy, s. 73. 



PROPEETY 89 

tion itself. There is no necessity to labour a 
point so universally admitted by all students of 
the Gospels as that Christ and His Apostles did 
not set out to abolish the slavery which they 
found ever3rwhere around them, but rather aimed, 
by preaching charity to the master and patience 
to the slave, at the same time to lighten the 
burden of servitude, and to render its acceptance 
a merit rather than a disgrace. ' What, in fact,' 
says Janet, ' is the teaching of St. Peter, St. Paul, 
and the Apostles in general ? It is, in the first 
place, that in Christ there are no slaves, and that 
all men are free and equal ; and, in the second 
place, that the slave must obey his master, and 
the master must be gentle to his slave. ^ Thus, 
although there are no slaves in Christ, St. Paul 
and the Apostles do not deny that there may be 
on earth. I am far from reproaching the Apostles 
for not having proclaimed the immediate neces- 
sity of the emancipation of slaves. But I say 
that the question was discussed in precisely the 
same terms by the ancient philosophers of the 
same period. Seneca, it is true, proclaimed not 
the civil, but the moral equality of men ; but 
St. Paul does not speak of anything more than 
their equality in Christ. Seneca instructs the 
master to treat the slave as he would like to be 
treated himself.^ Is not this what St. Peter and 
St. Paul say when they recommended the master 
to be gentle and good ? The superiority of 
Christianity over Stoicisnj in this question arises 
altogether from the very superiority of the 

1 Eph., vi. 5, 6, 9. 2 Bp. ad Lac., 73. 



90 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

Christian spirit. . . .' ^ The article on ' Slavery ' 
in the Catholic Encyclopcedia expresses the same 
opinion : ' Christian teachers, following the ex- 
ample of St. Paul, impUcitly accept slavery as 
not in itself incompatible with the Christian law. 
The Apostle counsels slaves to obey their masters, 
and to bear with their condition patiently. This 
estimate of slavery continued to prevail until it 
became fixed in the systematised ethical teach- 
ing of the schools ; and so it remained without 
any conspicuous modification until the end of 
the eighteenth century.' The same interpretation 
of early Christian teaching is accepted by the 
Protestant scholar, Dr. Bartlett : ' The practical 
attitude of Seneca and the early Christians to 
slavery was much the same. They bade the indi- 
vidual rise to a sense of spiritual freedom in spite 
of outward bondage, rather than denounce the 
institution as an altogether illegitimate form of 
property.' ^ 

Several texts might be collected from the 
writings of the Fathers which would seem to show 
that according to patristic teaching the institu- 
tion of slavery was unjustifiable. We do not 
propose to cite or to explain these texts one by 
one, in view of the quite clear and unambiguous 
exposition of the subject given by St. Thomas 



1 Janet, op. cit., p. 317. 

" 'Biblical and Early Christian Idea of Property,' Property, Its 
Duties and Rights (London, 1915), p. 110; JVanok, Bifmrmteurs et 
Piiblicistes de V Europe : Moyen iJg'e— Renaissance, p. 87. On the whole 
question by far the best authority is volume iii. of Wallon's Histoire 
de VEsolavage dans VAntiguiti, 



PROPERTY 91 

Aquinas, whose teaching is the more immediate 
subject of this essay ; we shall content ourselves 
by reminding the reader of the precisely similar 
texts relating to the institution of property which 
we have examined above, and by stating that the 
corresponding texts on the subject of slavery are 
capable of an exactly similar interpretation. ' The 
teaching of the Apostle,' says Janet, ' and of the 
Fathers on slavery is the same as their teaching 
on property.' ^ The author from whom we are 
quoting, and on whose judgment too much 
reUance cannot be placed, then proceeds to cite 
many of the patristic texts on property, which we 
quoted in the section dealing with that subject, 
and asks : ' What conclusion should one draw 
from these different passages ? It is that in 
Christ there are no rich and no poor, no mine and 
no thine ; that in Christian perfection all things 
are common to all men, but that nevertheless 
property is legitimate and derived from human 
law. Is it not in the same sense that the Fathers 
condemned slavery as contrary to divine law, 
while respecting it as comformable to human law ? 
The Fathers abound in texts contrary to slavery, 
but have we not seen a great number of texts 
contrary to property ? ' ^ The closeness of the 
analogy between the patristic treatment of slavery 
and of property appears forcibly in the following 
passage of Lactantius : ' God who created man 
wiUed that all should be equal. He has imposed 
on aU the same condition of living ; He has pro- 
duced aU in wisdom ; He has promised immortality 

1 Op. cit., p. 318. '^ Ibid., p. 321. 



92 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

to all ; no one is cut off from His heavenly benefits. 
In His sight no one is a slave, no one a master ; for 
if we have aU the same Father, by an equal right 
we are all His children; no one is poor in the 
sight of God but he who is without justice, no 
one rich but he who is full of virtue. . . . Some 
one wiU say. Are there not among you some 
poor and others rich ; some servants and others 
masters ? Is there not some difference between 
individuals ? There is none, nor is there any other 
cause why we mutually bestow on each other the 
name of brethren except that we beUeve ourselves 
to be equal. For since we measure all human 
things not by the body but by the spirit, although 
the condition of bodies is different, yet we have 
no servants, but we both regard them, and speak 
of them as brothers in spirit, in religion as fellow- 
servants.' ^ Slavery was declared to be a blessing, 
because, like poverty, it afforded the opportunity 
of practising the virtues of humiUty and patience. ^ 
The treatment of the institution of slavery 
underwent a striking and important development 
in the hands of St. Augustine, who justified it as 
one of the penalties incurred by man as a result 
of the sin of Adam and Eve. ' The first holy 
men,' writes the Saint, ' were rather shepherds 
than kings, God showing herein what both the 
order of the creation desired, and what the deserts 
of sin exacted. For justly was the burden of 
servitude laid upon the back of transgression. 
And therefore in all the Scriptures we never read 

1 Div. Inst., V. 15-16. 

a Chiyet., Qenes., serm. V. i. ; Ep. ad Cor., horn. xis. 4. 



PROPERTY 93 

the word servus until Noah laid it as a curse upon 
his offending son. So that it was guilt, and not 
nature, that gave origin to that name. . . . Sin is 
the mother of servitude and the first cause of 
man's subjection to man.' ^ St. Augustine also 
justifies the enslavement of those conquered in 
war — ' It is God's decree to humble the conquered, 
either reforming their sins herein or punishing 
them.' ^ 

Janet ably analyses and expounds the advance 
which St. Augustine made in the treatment of 
slavery : ' In this theory we must note the 
following points: (1) Slavery is unjust according 
to the law of nature. This is what is contrary 
to the teaching of Aristotle, but conformable to 
that of the Stoics. (2) Slavery is just as a conse- 
quence of sin. This is the new principle pecuUar 
to St. Augustine. He has found a principle of 
slavery, which is neither natural inequality, nor 
war, nor agreement, but sin. Slavery is no more 
a transitory fact which we accept provisionally, 
so as not to precipitate a social revolution : it is 
an institution which has become natural as a result 
of the corruption of our nature. (3) It must not 
be said that slavery, resulting from sin, is de- 
stroyed by Christ who destroyed sin. . . . Slavery, 
according to St. Augustine, must last as long as 
society.' ^ 

Nowhere does St. Thomas Aquinas appear as 
clearly as the medium of contact and reconciUation 
between the Fathers of the Church and the ancient 

1 De Giv. Dei, xix. 14-15. ^ lUd. 

* Janet, op, ciU, p. 302. 



94 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

philosophers as in his treatment of the question 
of slavery. His utterances upon this subject are 
scattered through many portions of his work, but, 
taken together, they show that he was quite pre- 
pared to admit the legitimacy of the institution, 
not alone on the grounds put forward by St. 
Augustine, but also on those suggested by Aristotle 
and the Roman jurists. 

•He fully adopts the Augustinian argument in 
the Summa, where, in answer to the query, 
whether in the state of innocence aU men were 
equal, he states that even in that state there 
would still have been inequalities of sex, know- 
ledge, justice, etc. The only inequahties which 
woiild not have been present were those arising 
from sin ; but the only inequality arising from sin 
was slavery.^ ' By the words " So long as we are 
without sin we are equal," Gregory means to 
exclude such inequahty as exists between virtue 
and vice ; the result of which is that some are 
placed in subjection to others as a penalty.' ^ 
In the following article St. Thomas distinguishes 
between political and despotic subordination, and 
shows that the former might have existed in a 
state of innocence. ' Mastership has a twofold 
meaning ; first as opposed to servitude, in which 
case a master means one to whom another is 
subject as a slave. In another sense mastership 
is commonly referred to any kind of subject ; and 
in that sense even he who has the office of govern- 
ing and directing free men can be called a master. 
In the first meaning of mastership man would not 

1 i. 96, 3. ^ Ibid., ad. 1. 



PROPERTY 95 

have been ruled by man in the state of innocence ; 
but in the latter sense man would be ruled over by- 
man in that state.' ^ In De Regimine Princijmm 
Aquinas also accepts what we may call the Augus- 
tinian view of slavery. * But whether the dominion 
of man over man is according to the law of nature, 
or is permitted or provided by God may be 
certainly resolved. If we speak of dominion by 
means of servile subjection, this was introduced 
because of sin. But if we speak of dominion in 
so far as it relates to the function of advising and 
directing, it may in this sense be said to be 
natural.' ^ 

St. Thomas was therefore willing to endorse 
the argument of St. Augustine that slavery was 
a result of sin; but he also admits the justice 
of Aristotle's reasoning on the subject. In the 
section of the Summa where the question is dis- 
cussed, whether the law of nations is the same as 
the natural law, one of the objections to be met 
is that ' Slavery among men is natural, for some 
are naturally slaves according to the philosopher. 
Now " slavery belongs to the law of nations," as 
Isidore states. Therefore the right of nations is 
a natural right,' ^ In answer to this objection St. 
Thomas draws the distinction between what ' is 
natural absolutely, and what is natural secundum 
quid, the passage which we have quoted in 
treating of property rights.* He then goes on to 

1 i. 96, 4. 

* De Beg. Prin., iii. 9. This is one of the chapters the authorship 
of which is disputed, 

» n. ii. 57, 3. * Supra, p. 64. 



96 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

apply this distinction to the case of slavery. ' Con- 
sidered absolutely, the fact that this particular 
man should be a slave rather than another man, is 
based, not on natural reason, but on some result- 
ant utility, in that it is useful to this man to be 
ruled by a wise man, and to the latter to be helped 
by the former, as the philosopher states. Where- 
fore slavery which belongs to the law of nations 
is natural in the second way, but not in the first.' ^ 
It wiU be noted from this passage that St. Thomas 
partly admits, though not entirely, the opinion 
of Aristotle. In the De Begimine Principum he 
goes much further in the direction of adopting 
the fuU Aristotelian theory : ' Nature decrees 
that there should be grades in men as in other 
things. We see this in the elements, a superior 
and an inferior ; we see in every mixture that 
some one element predominates. . . . For we 
see this also in the relation of the body and the 
mind, and in the powers of the mind compared 
with one another ; because some are ordained 
towards ordering and moving, such as the under- 
standing and the will ; others to serving. So 
should it be among men ; and thus it is proved 
that some are slaves according to nature. Some 
lack reason through some defect of nature ; and 
such ought to be subjected to servile works 
because they cannot use their reason, and this 
is called the natural law.' ^ In the same chapter 
the right of conquerors to enslave their conquered 
is referred to without comment, and therefore 
impMcitly approved by the author. 

» n. ii. 67, ad, 2. « De Reg. Prin., ii. 10. 



PROPERTY 97 

' Thus,' according to Janet, ' St. Thomas admits 
slavery as far as one can admit it, and for all the 
reasons for which one can admit it. He admits 
with Aristotle that there is a natural slavery ; 
with St. Augustine that slavery is the result of 
sin ; with the jurisconsult that slavery is the 
result of war and convention.' ^ ' The author 
justifies slavery,' says Franck, 'in the name of 
St. Augustine, and in that of Aristotle ; in the name 
of the latter by showing that there are two races 
of men, one bom to command, and the other to 
obey ; in the name of the former in affirming that 
slavery had its origin in original sin ; that by sin 
man has forfeited his right to Uberty. Further, 
we must admit slavery as an institution not only 
of nature and one of the consequences of the 
fall, we must admit a third principle of slavery 
which appears to St. Thomas as legitimate as the 
other two. War is necessary ; therefore it is 
just ; and if it is just we must accept its conse- 
quences. One of these consequences is the abso- 
lute right of the conqueror over the life, person, 
and goods of the conquered.' ^ 

Aquinas returns to the question of slavery in 
another passage, ts^hich is interesting as showing 
that he continued to make use of the analogy 
between slavery and property which we have 
seen in the Fathers. ' A thing is said to belong 
to the natural law in two ways. First, because 
nature incHnes thereto, e.g. that one should not do 
harm to another. Secondly, because nature did 
not bring in the contrary ; thus we might say that 

1 Op. cit., vol. i. p. 431. * Franck, <yp cit., p. 69. 

G 



98 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

for man to be naked is of the natural law because 
nature did not give him clothes, but art invented 
them. In this sense the possession of aU things 
in common and universal freedom is said to be of 
the natural law, because, to wit, the distinction of 
possession and slavery were not brought in by 
nature, but devised by human reason for the 
benefit of human life. Accordingly, the law of 
nature was not changed in this respect, but by 
addition.' ^ 

iEgidius Romanus closely foUows the teaching 
of his master on the subject of slavery. ' What 
does ^gidius do ? He unites Aristotle and St. 
Augustine against human liberty. He declares 
with the latter that man has lost the right of 
belonging to himself, since he has fallen from the 
primitive order estabhshed by God Himself in 
nature. He admits with Aristotle the existence 
of two races of men, the one designed for liberty, 
the other for servitude. . . . This is not all — ^to 
this servitude which he calls natural, the author 
joins another, purely legal, but which does not 
seem to him less just, namely, that which is 
foimded on the right of war, and which obliges 
the conquered to become the slaves of the con- 
querors — to give up their hberty in exchange for 
their Uves. Our author admits it is just in itself, 
because in his opinion it is useful to the defence 
of one's country ; it excites warriors to courage 
by plgicing before their eyes the terrible conse- 
quences of cowardice.' ^ The teachings of St. 
Thomas and iEgidius were accepted by all the 

1 I. ii. 94, 6, ad. 3. " Pranok, op cit., p. 90. 



PROPEETY 99 

later scholastics.^ Biel, whose opinion is always 
very valuable as being that of the last of a long 
line, says that there are three kinds of slaves — 
slaves of God, of sin, and of man. The first kind 
of slavery is wholly good, the second wholly bad, 
while the third, though not instituted by, is 
approved by the jus gentium. He proceeds to 
state the four ways in which a man may become 
enslaved : namely, ex necessitate, or by being bom 
of a slave mother ; ex hello, by being captured in 
war ; ex delicto, or by sentence of the law in the 
case of certain crimes committed by freedmen; and 
ex pro'pria voluntate, or by the sale of a man of 
himself into slavery.^ 

It must not be forgotten that we are dealing 
purely with theory. In fact the Church did an 
inestimable amount of good to the servile classes, 
and, at the time that Aquinas wrote, thanks to 
the operation of Christianity in this respect, the 
old Roman slavery had completely disappeared. 
The nearest approach to ancient slavery in the 
Middle Ages was serfdom, which was simply a 
step in the transition from slavery to free labour.^ 
Moreover, the rights of the master over the slave 
were strictly confined to the disposal of his ser- 
vices ; the ancient absolute right over his body 
had completely disappeared. ' In those things,' 
says St. Thomas, 'which appertain to the dis- 
position of human acts and things, the subject is 

1 Franck, op. eif., p. 91. 

2 Biel, Invenfarium seu Bepertorivm g&mrale simper quabuor Ubroa 
SmUntiwum, TV. xv. 1 ; and see Carletus, Summa AngeUca, q. ooxii. 

8 WaUon, op. cit., vol. iii. p. 93 ; Brants, op. cit, p. 87. 



100 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

bound to obey his superior according to the reason 
of the superiority ; thus a soldier must obey his 
officer in those things which appertain to war ; 
a slave his master in those things which apper- 
tain to the carrying out of his servile works.' ^ 

v„' Slavery does not abohsh the natural equaUty of 
man,' says a writer who is quoted by the Catholic 
Encydopcedia as correctly stating the Cathohc 
doctrine on the subject prior to the eighteenth 
centiiry, ' hence by slavery one man is understood 
to become subject to the dominion of another to 
the extent that the master has a perfect right to 
the services which one man may justly perform 
for another.' ^ Biel, who lays down the justice of 
slavery so unambiguously, is no less clear in his 
statement of the hmitations of the right. ' The 
body of the slave is not simply in the power of the 
master as the body of an ox is ; nor can the 
master kill or mutilate the slave, nor abuse him 

' contrary to the law of God. The temporal gains 
derived from the labour of the slave belong to 
the master ; but the master is bound to provide 
the slave with the necessaries of hfe.' ^ Rambaud 
very properly points out that the reason that the 
scholastic writers did not fulminate in as strong 
and as frequent language against the tyranny of 
masters, was not that they felt less strongly on 
the subject, but that the abuses of the ancient 
slave system had almost entirely disappeared 
under the influence of Christian teaching.* 

On the other hand, it must not be imagined, as 

1 n. ii. 104, 6. 2 Gerdil., Comp. Inst. Civ. I., vii. 

' Biel, 023. cit., iv. xv. 5. * Op. cit., p. 83. 



PROPERTY 101 

has sometimes been suggested, that the slavery 
defended by Aquinas was not real slavery, but 
rather the ordinary modern relation between 
employer and employed. Such an interpreta- 
tion is definitely disproved by a passage of the 
article on justice where Aquinas says that ' induc- 
ing a slave to leave his master is properly an 
injury against the person . . . and, since the 
slave is his master's chattel, it is referred to 
theft.' 1 

^ n. ii. 61, 3. Brants, op. cit, pp. 87 et siq., is inclined to take a more 
liberal view of the scholastic doctrine on slavery, but we cannot agree 
with him in view of the contemporary texts. 



CHAPTER III 

DUTIES REGARDING THE EXCHANGE OF 
PROPERTY 

Section 1. — ^The Sale of Goods 

§ 1. The Just Price 

We dealt in the last chapter with the duties 
which attached to property in respect of its 
acquisition and use, and we now pass to the 
duties which attached to it in respect of its ex- 
change. As we indicated above, the right to 
jBXchange one's goods for the goods or the money 
of another person was, according to the scholastics, 
one of the necessary corollaries of the right of 
private property. In order that such exchange 
might be justifiable, it must be conducted on a 
basis of commutative justice, which, as we have 
seen, consisted in the observance of equality 
according to the arithmetical mean. We further 
'drew attention to the fact that exchanges might be 
divided into sales of goods and sales of the use of 
money. In the former case the regulating principle 
of the equahty of justice was given effect to by the 
observance of the just price ; in the latter by that 
of the 'prohibition of usury. We shall deal with 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 103 

the former in the present and with the latter in 
the following section. 

The mediaeval teaching on the just price, 
about which there has been so much discussion 
and disagreement among modern writers, was 
simply the application to the particular contract 
of sale of the principles which regulated contracts 
in general. Exchange originally took the form 
of barter ; but, as it was found impossible ac- 
curately to measure the values of the objects 
exchanged without the intervention of some 
common measure of value, money was invented 
to serve as such a measure. We need not further 
refer to barter in this section, as the principles 
which apphed to it were those that applied to 
sale. Indeed all sales when analysed are reaUy 
barter through the medium of money. That 
Aquinas simply regarded his article on just price ^ 
as an explanation of the appHcation of his general 
teaching on justice to the particular case of the 
contract of sale is quite clear from the article 
itself. 'Apart from fraud, we may speak of 
buying and selling in two ways. First, as con- 
sidered in themselves ; and from this point of view 
buying and selling seem to be estabhshed for the 
common advantage of both parties, one of whom 
requires that which belongs to the other, and 
vice versa. Now whatever is established for the 
common advantage should not be more of a 
burden to one part than to the other, and conse- 
quently aU contracts between them should observe 
equahty of thing and thing. Again, the quality 

1 n. ii. 77, 1. 



1 



104 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

of a tiling that comes into human use is measured 
by the price given for it, for which purpose money- 
was invented. Therefore, if either the price exceed 
the quantity of the thing's worth, or conversely 
the worth of the thing exceed the price, there is 
no longer the equahty of justice ; and conse- 
^ quently to sell a thiag for more than its worth, or 
to buy it for less than its worth, is in itself unjust 
and imlawful.' ^ When two contracting parties 
make an exchange through the medium of money, 
the price is the expression of the exchange value in 
money. ' The just price expresses the equiva- 
lence, which is the foundation of contractual 
justice.' 2 

The conception of the just price, though based 
on Aristotelian conceptions of justice, is essentially 
CSu-istian. The Roman law had allowed the 
utmost freedom of contract in sales ; apart from 
fraud, the two contracting parties were at com- 
plete hberty to fix a price at their own risk ; and 
selfishness was assumed and allowed to be the 
animating motive of every contracting party. 
The one Hmitation to this sweeping rule was in 
favour of the seller. By a rescript of Diocletian 

^ This opinion was accepted by all the later writers, e.g. Gerson, 
De ConU, ii. 6 ; Biel, op. cit., rv. xv. 10 : 'Si pretium exoedit quanti- 
tatem valoris rei, vel e converso tolleretur equalitas, erit contractus 
iniquus.' 

^ Desbuqudis, ' La Justice dans I'Echange,' Semaine Sociaie de 
France, 1911, p. 167. Gerson says : ' Contractus species est justitiae 
oommutativae quae respioit aequalitatem rei quae venditur ad rem 
quae emitur, ut servetur aequalitas justi pretii ; propter quam aequali- 
tatem faciUus observandum iuventa est moneta, yel numisma, vel 
peounia,' De Cont, H. 6. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 105 

and Maximian it was enacted that, if a thing were 
sold for less than half its value, the seller could 
recover the property, unless the buyer chose to 
make up the price to the fuU amount. Although 
this rescript was perfectly general in its terms, 
some authors contended that it applied only to 
sales of land, because the example given was 
the sale of a farm.^ However, the rescript was 
quoted by the Fathers as showing that even the 
Roman law considered that contracts might be 
questioned on equitable grounds in certain cases. ^ 
The distinctively Christian notion of just price 
seems to have its origin in a passage of St. Augus- 
tine ; ^ but the notion was not placed on a philo- 
sophical foundation until the thirteenth century. 
Even Aquinas, however, although he treats of the 
just price at some length, and expresses clear 
and categorical opinions upon many points con- 
nected with it, does not state the principles on 
which the just price itself should be arrived at. 
This omission is due, not to the fact that Aquinas 
was unfamiliar with these principles, but to the 
fact that he took them for granted as they were 
not disputed or doubted.^ We have conse- 
quently to look for enlightenment upon this point 
in writings other than those of Aquinas. The 
subject can be most satisfactorily understood if 

^ Hunter, Soman Law, p. 492. 

2 Ashley, op. eit, p. 133. 

' ' Soio ipse hominem quum venalis codex ei fuisset oblatus, pretiique 
-ejus ignarum ideo quiddam exiguum poscentem cemeret venditorem, 
justum pretium, quod multo ampUus erat nee opinanti dedisse ' (De 
Trin., xiii. 3). 

* Palgrave, Diotionary of Political Economy, tit. ' Justum Pretium.' 



106 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

we divide its treatment into two parts: first, a 
consideration of what constituted the just price 
in the sale of an article, the price of which was 
fixed by law ; and second, a consideration of what 
constituted the just price of an article, the price of 
which was not so fixed. 



§ 2. The Just Price when Price fixed by Law 

Regarding the power of the State to fix prices, 
the theologians and jurists were in complete 
_jt- agreement. According to Gterson : ' The law may 
justly fix the price of things which are sold, both 
movable and immovable, in the nature of rents 
and not in the nature of rents, and feudal and 
non-feudal, below which price the seller must 
not give, or above which the Ijuyer must not 
demand, however they may desire to do so. As 
therefore the price is a kind of measure of the 
equality to be observed in contracts, and as it is 
sometimes difficult to find that measure with 
exactitude, on account of the varied and corrupt 
desires of man, it becomes expedient that the 
medium should be fixed according to the judg- 
ment of some wise man. ... In the civil state, 
however, nobody is to be decreed wiser than the 
lawgiving authority. Therefore it behoves the 
latter, whenever it is possible to do so, to fix the 
just price, which may not be exceeded by private 
consent, and which must be enforced.' . . . ^ 
Biel practically paraphrases this passage of Ger- 
son, and contends that it is the duty of the prince 

1 De Gont., i. 19. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 107 

to fix prices, mainly on account of the difficulty 
which private contractors find in doing so.^ 

The rules which we find laid down for the 
guidance of the prince in fixing prices are very 
interesting, as they show that the mediaeval 
writers had a clear idea of the constituent elements 
of value. Langenstein, whose famous work on 
contracts was considered of high authority by 
later writers, says that the prince should take 
account of the condition of the place for which 
the price was to be fixed, the circumstances of 
the time, the condition of the mass of the people. 
The different kinds of need which may be felt for 
goods must also be considered, indigentice naturce, 
sixitus, voluptatis, and cwpiditatis ; and a dis- 
tinction drawn between extensive and intensive 
need — ^the former is greater ' quanto plures re 
ahqua indigent,' the latter 'quanto minus de 
iUa re habetur.' The general rule is that the- 
prince must seek to find a medium between 
a price so low as to render labourers, artisans, 
and merchants unable to maintain themselves 
suitably, and one so high as to disable the poor 
from obtaining the necessaries of life. When 
in doubt, Langenstein concludes, the price should 
err on the low rather than the high side.^ Biel 
gives similar rules : The legislator must regard the 
needs of man, the abundance or scarcity of things, 
the difficulty, labour, and risks of production. 
When all these things are carefully considered 
the legislator is in a position to fix a just price.^ 

^ Op. dt., IV. XV. 11. 2 Boscher, GeachichU, p. 19. 

= Op. dt,, IV. XV. 10. 



108 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

4^ccording to Endemaim, the labour of production, 
the cost and risk of transport, and the condition 
of the markets had all to be kept in mind when a 
fair price was being fixed. ^ We may mention in 
passing that the power of fixing the just price 
might be delegated ; prices were frequently fixed 
by the town authorities, the guilds, and the 
Church. 2 

The passage from Gerson which we quoted above 
shows that, when a just price had been fixed by 
the competent authority, the parties to a contract 
were bound to keep to it. In other words, the 
pretium legitimum was ipso facto the justum 
pretium. On this point there is complete agree- 
ment among the writers of the period. CaepoUa 

( says, ' When the price is fixed by law or statute, 
that is the just price, and nobody can receive 
anything, however small, in excess of it, because 
the law must be observed ' ; ^ and Biel, ' When a 
price has been fixed, the contracting parties have 
sufficient certainty about the equality of value 
and the justice of the price.' * Cossa draws 
attention to the necessity of the fixed price corre- 
sponding with the real price in order that it should 
maintain its validity. ' The schoolmen talk of 
the legitimate and irreducible price of a thing 
which was fixed by authority, and was for obvious 
reasons of special importance in the case of the 

1 necessaries of life. . . . The legitimate price of a 

1 Studien, vol. ii. p. 43. 

^ Endemann, Studien, vol. i. p. 40 ; Koscher, Political Economy, 
s. 114. 
' Be Contractibua Sirmdatia, 69. * Op. cit, iv. xv. 10. 



THE EXCHANGE OP PEOPERTY 109 

thing as fixed by authority had to be based upon 
the natural price, and therefore lost its validity 
and became a dead letter the moment any change 
of circumstances made it unfair.' ^ 



§ 3. The Just Price when Price not fixed by Law 

When the just price was not fixed by any out- 
side authority, the buyer and seller had to arrive 
at it themselves. The problem before them was 
to equalise their respective burdens, so that there 
would be equality of burden between them, or, 
in other words, to reduce the value of the article 
sold to terms of money. In order that we may 
understand how this equaUty was arrived at, it is 
important to kaow the factors which were held 
to enter into the determination of value. 

The first thing upon which the mediaeval 
teachers insist is that value is not determined by 
the intrinsic excellence of the thing itseK, because, 
if it were, a fly would be more valuable than a 
pearl, as beiag intrinsically more excellent.^ Nor 
is the value to be measured by the mere utility 
of the object for satisfying the material needs of 
man, for in that case, corn should be worth more 
than precious stones.^ The value of an object 
is to be measured by its capacity for satisfying 
men's wants. ' Valor rerum aestimatur secundum 

1 Of. eit., p. 143. 

" ' In justitia commutativa non estimatur pretium commutabilium 
Becundum naturalem valorem ipsorum, sic enim musoa plus valeret 
quam totus aurum mundi ' (Buridan, op. cit, x. 14). 

* Slater, ' Value in Theology and Political Economy,' Irish Ecclesi- 
astical Record, Sept. 1901, 



no MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

humanam indigentiam. . . . Dicendum est quod 
indigentia humana est mensura naturalis com- 
mutabilium ; quod probatur sic : bonitas sive 
valor rei attenditur ex fine propter quern exhi- 
betur : unde commentator secundo Metapby- 
sicae nihil est honum nisi 'propter causas finales ; 
sed finis naturalis ad quern justitia commutativa 
ordinet exteriora commutabiMa est supplementum 
indigentiae humanae . . . ; igitur supplementum 
indigentiae humanae est vera mensura com- 
mutabiUum. Sed supplementum videtuj- men- 
surari per indigentiam ; majoris enim valoris est 
supplementum quod majorem supplet indigentiam. 
, . . Item hoc probatur signo, quia videmus quod 
illo tempore quo viaa deficiunt quia magis indi- 
geremus eis ipsa fiunt cariora. . . .^ 
V The capacity of an object for satisfying man's 
needs could not be measured by its capacity for 
satisfying the needs of this or that individual, 
but by its capacity for satisfying the needs of the 
average member of the community.^ The Abbe 
Desbuquois, in the article from which we have 
already quoted, finds in this elevation of the 
common estimation an illustration of the general 
principle of the medisfevals, which we have seen 
at work in their teaching on the use of property, 

1 Biiridan, op. cit, v. 14 and 16. Antoninus of Morence says that 
value is determined by three factors, virtuositas, rwritas, and placi- 
bilitas {Svmma, ii. 1, 16.) 

> ' Indigentia istius horuinis vel iUius non mensurat valorem com- 
mutabiUum ; sed indigentia communis eorum qui inter se commutare 
possunt,' Buiidan, op. cit., v. 16. ' Prout commxmiter venditur 
in foro,' Henri de Gand, Quod Lib., xiv. 14; Nider, De CotU. 
Merc.fii. 1. 



THE EXCHAl^GE OF PROPERTY HI 

that the individual benefit must always be sub- 
ordinated to the general welfare. According to 
him, it is but one appUcation of the duty of using 
one's goods for the common good. ' In the same 
way, in allowing the right of exchange — a, right, 
let us remark in passing, which is but an apphca- 
tion of the right of property — and in allowing it 
as a means of life necessary to everybody, nature 
does not lose sight of the universal destination 
of economic goods. One conceives then that the 
variations of exchange are not permitted to be 
left to the arbitrary judgment of a single man, nor 
to be afEected by the whims and abuses of indi- 
viduals ; that value is defined in view of the 
general good. The exchange value, as it is in the 
general or social order, proceeds from the judg- 
ment of thB social environment {milieu social).' ^ 
The writers of the Middle Ages show a very 
keen perception of the elements which invest an 
object with the value which is accorded to it by 
the general estimation. In Aquinas we find 
certain elements recognised — 'diversitas loci vel 
temporis, labor, raritas' — ^but it is not until the 
authors of the fourteenth and fifteenth centuries 
that we find a systematic treatment of value. ^ 
First and foremost there is the cost of productionr 
of the article, especially the wages of all those 
who helped to produce it. Langenstein lays down 
that every one can determine for himself the just 
price of the wares he has to sell by reckoning what 
he needs to support himself in the status which 

1 'La Justice dans I'Eohange,' Semaine Sociah de France, 1911, 
p. 168. ' Brants, op. dt., p. 69. 



112 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

he occupies.^ According to the Catholic Encych- 
pcedia,^ the just price of an article included enough 
to pay fair wages to the worker — that is, enough to 
enable him to maintain the standard of living of 
his class. This, though not stated in so many 
words by Aquinas, was probably assumed by him 
as too obvious to need repetition.^ 'The cost 
of production of manufactured products,' says 
Brants, ' is a legitimate constituent element of 
value ; it is according to the cost that the pro- 
ducer can properly fix the value of his product 
and of his work.' * 

The cost of the labour of production was, 
however, by no means the only factor which was 
admitted to enter into the determination of value. 
The passage from Gerson dealing with the cir- 
cumstances to which the prince must have regard 
in fixing a price, which we quoted above, shows 
quite clearly that many other factors were 
recognised as no less important. This appears 
with special clearness in the treatise of Langeil- 
stein, whose authority on this subject was always 
ranked very high. Bernardine of Siena is careful 
to point out that the expense of production is only 
one of the factors which influence the value of an 
object.^ Biel explains that, when no price has 
been fixed by law, the just price may be arrived 

1 De Comt., quoted by Boscher, QescMchte, p. 20. 

^ Tit. ' Political Economy.' 

' Palgrave, Dietionary, tit. ' Justum Pretium.' 

* Brants, op. ctfc, p. 202. 

• ' Res potest plus vel minus valere taribus modis ; primo secundum 
suam virtutem ; secondo modo secundum suam caritatem ; tertio modo 
secundum suam placibilitatem et affeotionem. . . . Primo observat 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 113 

at by a reference to the cost of the labour of pro- .^ 
duction, and to the state of the market, and the 
other circumstances which we have seen above 
the prince was bound to have regard to in fixing 
a price. He also allows the price to be raised on 
accoimt of any anxiety which the production of 
the goods occasioned him, or any danger he 
incurred.^ 

It wiU be apparent from the whole trend of 
the above that, whereas the remuneration of the 
labour of all those who were engaged in the pro- 
duction of an article, was one of the elements to 
be taken into account in reckoning its value, and 
consequently its just price, it was by no means the 
only element. Certain. so-caUed Christian socialists 
have endeavoured to find in the writings of the 
scholastics support for the Marxian position that 
all value arises from labour.^ This endeavour is, 
however, destined to failure ; we shall see in a 
later chapter that many forms of unearned 
income were tolerated and approved by the 
scholastics ; but all that is necessary here is to 
draw the attention of the reader to the passages 
on value to which we have referred. One of the 
most prominent exponents of the untenable view 
that the medisevals traced aU value to labour is 

quemdam naturalem ordineiii utilium rerum, secundo observat quem- 
dam oommunem cursum copiae et inopiae, tertio observat perioulum 
et industriam rerum sen obaeqiiiomm ' (Funk, Zins und Wudier, p. 153). 

''■ ' Sollicitudo et periculum,' op. cit., iv. xv. 10. 

^ Even Ashley states that ' the doctrine had thus a close resemblance 
to that of modern Socialists ; labour it regarded both as the sole 
(human) cause of wealth, and also as the only just claim to the posses- 
sion of wealth ' (oy. cit., vol. i. part ii. p. 393). 

H 



114 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

the Abbe Hohoff, whose argument that there was 
a divorce between value and just price in the 
scholastic writings, is ably controverted by Ram- 
baud, who remarks that nobody would have been 
more surprised than Aquinas himself at the stig- 
gestion that he was the forerunner of Karl Marjc.^ 
The idea that the scholastics traced aU value to 
the labour expended on production is rejected by 
many of the most prominent writers on medi- 
aeval economic theory. Roscher draws particular 
attention to the fact that the canonist teaching 
assigned the correct proportions in production to 
land, capital, and labour, in contrast to aU the 
later schools of economists, who have exaggerated 
the importance of one or the other of these factors.^ 
Even Knies, who was the first modern writer to 
insist on the importance of the cost of production 
as an element of value, states that the Church 
sought to fix the price of goods in accordance 
with the cost of production (Herstellungskosten) 
and the consumption value {Gebraiwhswerte).^ 
Brants takes the same view. ' The expenses of 
production are iq practice the norm of the fixing 
of the sale price in the great majority of cases, 
above all in a very narrow market, where com- 
petition is hmited ; moreover, they can, for reasons 
of pubhc order, form the basis of a fixing that wOl 
protect the producer and the consumer against the 
disastrous consequences of constant oscHlations. 
The vendor can in principle be remunerated for his 

^ Op. cit., p. 50. * Political Economy, s. 48. 

' Politische Oekonomie vom Siandfuncte der geschidiUichen Methode, 
p. 116. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 115 

trouble. It is well that he should be so remuner- 
ated ; it is socially useM, and is used as a basis 
for fixing price ; but it cannot in. any way be said 
that this forms the objective measure of value, but 
that the work and expense are a sufficient title 
of remuneration for the fixing of the just price of 
the sale of a thing. Some writers have tried to 
conclude from this that the authors of the Middle 
Ages saw in labour the measure of value. This 
conclusion is exaggerated. We may fxiUy admit 
that this element enters into the sale price ; but 
it is in no way the general measure of value. . . . 
The expenses of production constitute, then, one 
of the legitimate elements of just price ; they are 
not the measure of value, but a factor often taflu- 
encing its determination.' ^ ' Labour,' according 
to Dr. Cronia, ' is one of the most important of 
aU the determinants of value, for labour is the 
chief element in cost of production, and cost of 
production is one of the chief elements ia deter- 
miaing the level at which it is useful to buy or sell. 
But labour is not the only determinant of value ; 
there is, e.g., the price of the raw materials, a price 
that is not wholly determined by the labour of 
producing those materials.' ^ 

The just price, then, in the absence of a legal 
fixing, was held to be the price that was in accord- 
ance with the communis estimatio. Of course, 
this did not mean that a plebiscite had to be taken 
before every sale, but that any price that was in 
accordance with the general course of deahng at 
the time and place of the sale was considered 

1 Op. cit, p. 112. ' Ethics, vol. ii. p. 181. 



116 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

substantially fair. ' A thing is worth what it 
can generally be sold for — at the time of the 
contract ; this means what it can be sold for 
generally either on that day or the preceding or 
following day. One must look to the price at 
which similar things are generally sold in the open 
market.' ^ ' We must state precisely,' says the 
Abbe Desbuquois, ' the character of this common 
estimation ; it did not mean the universal 
suffrage ; although it expresses the universal 
interest, it proceeds in practice from the evalua- 
tion of competent men, taken in the social en- 
vironment where the exchange value operates. 
If one supposes a sovereign tribunal of arbitration 
where all the rights of aU the weak and all the 
strong economic factors are taken mto accoimt, 
the just price appears as the sentence or decision 
of this court.' ^ ' For the scholastics, the com- 
mon estimation meant an ethical judgment of at 
least the most influential members of the com- 
munity, anticipating the markets and fixing the 
rate of exchange.' ^ 

It is quite incorrect to say, as has been some- 
times said, that the mediaeval just price was in 
no way different from the competition price of 
to-day which is arrived at by the higgling of the 
market. Dr. Cunningham is very exphcit and 
clear on this point. ' Common estimation is thus 
the exponent of the natural or normal or just 
price according to either the mediaeval or modern 
view ; but, whereas we rely on the higgling of the 

1 Caepolla, De, Cont. Sim., 72. * Op. eit, pp. 169-7(X 

' Fr. Kelleber in the Irish Theological Quarterly, vol. xi. p. 133. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 117 

market as the means of bringing out what is the 
common estimate of any object, mediseval eco- 
nomists beheved that it was possible to bring 
common estimation into operation beforehand, 
and by the consultation of experts to calctilate 
out what was the just price. If common esti- 
mation was thus organised, either by the town 
authorities or guilds or parliament, it was possible 
to determine beforehand what the price should be 
and to lay down a rule to this effect ; in modem 
times we can only look back on the competition 
prices and say by reflection what the common 
estimation has been.' ^ ' The common estima- 
tion of which the Canonists spoke,' says Dr. 
Ryan, ' was conscious social judgment that fixed 
price beforehand, and was expressed chiefly in 
custom, while the social estimate of to-day is in 
reahty an unconscious resultant of the higghng 
of the market, and finds its expression only in 
market price.' ^ The phrase ' res tanti valet 
quanti vendi potest,' which is so often used to 
prove that the mediseval doctors permitted full 
competitive prices in the modem sense, must be 
understood to mean that a thing could be sold at 
any figure which was within the Umits of the mini- 
mum and maximum just price. ^ 

The last sentence suggests that the just price 
was not a fixed and unalterable standard, but was 
somewhat wide and elastic. On this all writers 
are agreed. ' The just price of things,' says 
Aquinas, ' is not fixed with mathematical pre- 

^ Growth of English Industry and Commerce, vol. i. p. 353. 

2 Living Wage, p. 28. ^ Lessius, De Justitia et Jure, xxi. 19. 



118 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

cision, but depends on a kind of estimate, so that 
a slight addition or subtraction would not seem 
to destroy the equality of justice,' ^ Caepolla 
repeats this dictum, with the reservation that, 
when the just price is fixed by law, it must be 
rigorously observed.^ ' Note,' says Gerson, ' that 
the equaUty of commutative justice is not exact 
or unchangeable, but has a good deal of latitude, 
within the bounds of which a greater or less price 
may be given without justice being infringed ; ' ' 
and Biel insists on the same latitude, from which 
he draws the conclusion that the just price is 
constantly varying from day to day and from 
place to place.* Grenerally it was said that there 
was a maximum, medium, and minimum just 
price ; and that any price between the maximum 
and minimum was valid, although the medium 
was to be aimed at as far as possible. 

The price fixed by common estimation was 
therefore the one to be observed in most cases, 
and it was at aU times a safe guide to foUow. 
If, however, the parties either knew or had good 
reason to believe that the common estimation 
had fixed the price wrongly, they were not bound 
to foUow it, but should arrive at a just price them- 
selves, having regard to the various considerations 
given above. ^ 

It did not make any difference whether the 

1 n. u. 77, 1, ad. 1. a De. Cont. Sim., 58. 

* De Cont., ii. 11, * Op. eit., iv. xv. 10. 

° Nider, De Cont. Merc. ii. : 'Si vero soit vel credit comxauiiitatem 
erraie in estimatione pretii rei ; tunc nullo modo debet earn sequi ; 
qtiia etiam.si reciperet verum et justum pretiam, tamen faoeret contra 
ccmscientiam.' 



THE EXCHANGE OF PKOPERTY 119 

price was paid immediately or at some future 
date. To increase the price in return for the 
giving of credit was not allowed, as it was deemed 
usurious — as indeed it was. |t was held that the 
seller, in not taking his money immediately, was 
simply making a loan of that amoxmt to the 
huyer, and that to receive anything more than 
the sum lent would be usury. Aquinas is quite 
clear on this point. ' If a man wish to sell his 
goods at a higher price than that which is just, so 
that he may wait for the bjiy erjo pay^ it is mani- 
festly a case' oifusm-y; because this waiting for 
the' payment of the price has the cha.racter of a 
"loan, so that whatever he demands beyond the 
just price in consideration of this delay, is like a 
price for a loan, which pertains to usury. In 
hke manner, if a buyer wishes to buy goods at a 
lower price than what is just, for the reason that 
he pays for the goods before they can be delivered, 
it is likewise a sin of usury ; because again this 
anticipated payment of money has the character 
of a loan, the price of which is the rebate on the 
just price of the goods sold. On the other hand, 
if a man wishes to allow a rebate on the just price 
in order that he may have his money sooner, he is 
not guilty of the sin Of usury.' ^ If, however, the 
seller, by giving credit, suffered any damage, he 
was entitled to be recompensed ; this, as we shall 
see, was an ordinary feature of usury law. It 
could not be said that the price was raised. The 
price remained the same ; but the seller was 
entitled to something further than the price by 

^ n, ii. 78, 2, ad. 7. See Decret. Oreg., v. 19, de usuris, oc. 6 and 10. 



120 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

way of damages. 1 It was by the application of 
this principle that a seller was justified in demand- 
ing more than the current price for an article 
which possessed some individual or sentimental 
value for him. ' In such a case the just price will 
depend not only on the thing sold, but on the loss 
which the sale brings on the seller. . . . No man 
shotdd seU what is not his, though he may charge 
for the loss he suffers.' ^ On the other hand, it 
was strictly forbidden to raise the price on account 
of the individual need of the buyer. ^ 

§ 4. The Just Price of Labour 

Particular rules were laid down for determining 
the just price of certain classes of goods. These 
need not be treated in detail, as they were merely 
applications of the general principle to particular 
cases, and whatever interest they possess is in the 
domain of practice rather than of theory. In 
the sale of immovable property the rule was 
that the value should be arrived at by a consider- 
ation of the annual fruits of the property.* The 
only one of the particular contracts which need 
detain us here is that of a contract of service for 
wages {hcatio o'perarum). Wages were considered 
as ruled by the laws relating to just price. ' That 
is called a wage {merces) which is paid to any one 
as a recompense for his work and labour. There- 
fore, as it is an act of justice to give a just price 

1 Endemann, iS««dieTO, vol. ii. pp. 49 ; Desbuquois, op. cit., p. 174. 

" n. ii. 77, 1. s lUd. 

* Caepolla, de Cont. Sim., 78 ; Carletus, Summa Angelica, Ixv. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 121 

for a thing taken from another person, so also to 
pay the wages of work and labour is an act of 
justice.' 1 Again, ' Remuneration of service or 
work . . . can be priced at a money value, as 
may be seen in the case of those who offer for hire 
the labour which they exercise by work or by 
tongue.' 2 Biel insists that the value of labourer 
is subject to the same influences as the value of 
any other commodity which is offered for sale, 
and that therefore a just price must be observed 
in buying it.^ 

This, according to Brants,* is essentially a matter 
upon which more enlightenment wiU be found in 
histories of the working classes ^ than in books 
deahng with the enunciation of abstract theories ; 
nevertheless, it is possible to state generally that 
it was regarded as the duty of employers to give-r^ 
such a wage as would support the worker in accord- 
ance with the requirements of his class. In the 
great majority of cases the rate of wages was 
fixed by some pubUc — ^municipal or corporativefc' 
— authority, but Langenstein enunciates a rule 
which seems to approach the statement of a general 
theory. According to him, when a man has 



' Aquinas, Swmma, n. ii. 114, 1. ^ n. ii. 78, 2, ad. 3. 

' Op. dt., IV. XV. 10. Modern Socialists caricature the correct 
principle ' that labour is a commodity ' into ' the labourer is a com- 
modity ' — a great difference, which is not sufficiently understood by 
many present-day writers. (See Roscher, Political Economy, s. 160.) 

* Op. oit., p. 103. 

° An excellent bibliography of books dealing with the history of the 
working classes in the Middle Ages is to be found in Brants, op. dt., 
p. 105. The need for examining concrete economic phenomena is 
insisted on in Eyan's Livirig Wage, p. 28. 



122 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

something to sell, and has no indication of the 
just price from its being fixed by any outside 
authority, he must endeavour to get such a price 
as will reasonably recompense him for any outlay 
he may have incurred, and wiU enable him to 
provide for his needs, spiritual and temporal.^ 
It was not until the sixteenth century that the 
fixing of the just price of wages was submitted to 
scientific discussion ; ^ , in the fourteenth and 
fifteenth centuries there is httle to be found 
bearing on this subject except the passage of 
Langenstein which we have quoted, and some 
strong exhortations by Antoninus of Florence to 
masters to pay good wages. ^ The reason for this 
paucity of authority upon a subject of so much 
importance is that in practice the machinery 
provided by the guilds had the effect of preserving 
a substantially just remuneration to the artisan. 
When a man is in perfect health he does not 
bother to read medical books. In the same way, 
the proper remuneration of labour was so uni- 
versally recognised as a duty, and so satisfac- 
torily enforced, that it seems to have been taken 
for granted, and therefore passed over, by the 

^ De Cont. We have here a recognition of the principle that the 
value of labour is not to be measured by anything extrinsic to itself, 
e.g. by the value of the product, but by its own natural function and 
end, and this function and end is the supplying of the requirements 
of human life. The wage must, therefore, be capable of supplying 
the same needs that the expenditure of a labourer's energy is meant 
to supply. (See Cronin, Ethics, vol. ii. p. 390.) 

^ Brants, &p. dt., p. 118. 

' The passages from the Summa of Antoninus bearing on the subject 
are reprinted in Brants, op. cit., p. 120. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 123 

writers of the period. One may agree with Brants 
in concluding that, ' the principle of just price in 
sales was applied to wages ; fluctuations in wages 
were not allowed ; the just price, as in sales, 
rested on the approximate equality of the ser- 
vices rendered; and that this equality was esti- 
mated by common opinion.' ^ Of course, in the 
case of slave labour it could not be said that any 
wage was paid. The master was entitled to the 
services of the slave, and in return was boimd to 
furnish him with the necessaries of life.^ 



§ 5. Value of the Conception of the Just Price 

It is probably correct to say that the canonical 
teaching on just price was negative rather than 
positive ; in other words, that it did not so much 4- 
aim at positively fixing the price at which goods 
should be sold, as negatively at indicating the 
practices in bujong and selling which were unjust. 
' The doctrine of just price,' according to Dr. 
Ryan, ' may sometimes have been associated with 
incorrect views of industrial hfe, but aU com- 
petent authorities agree that it was a fairly sound 
attempt to define the equities of mediaeval ex- 
changes, and that it was tolerably successful in 
practice.' ^ The condition of mediaeval markets^ 
was frequently such that the competition was 
not really fair competition, and consequently the 
price arrived at by competition would be unfair 

1 Op. cit., p. 125. 

" Branta, op. cit, p, 116, quoting Le lAwe cbi Trkaor of Brunette 
Latini. ' Thx, Living Wage, p. 27. 



124 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

either to buyer or seller. ' This,' according to 
Dr. Cuimingham, ' was the very thing which 
mediaeval regulation had been intended to pre- 
vent, as any attempt to make gain out of the 
necessities of others, or to reap profit from un- 
looked-for occurrences would have been con- 
demned as extortion. It is by taking advantage 
of such fluctuations that money is most frequently 
made in modem times ; but the whole scheme of 
commercial life in the Middle Ages was supposed 
to allow of a regular profit on each transaction.' ^ 
There might be some doubt as to the positive 
justice of this or that price ; but there coidd be no 
doubt as to the injustice of a price which was 
enhanced by the necessities of the poor, or the 
engrossing of a vital commodity.^ Merely to buy 
up the whole supply of a certain commodity, 
even if it were bought up by a ' ring ' of merchants, 
provided that the commodity was resold within 
the hmits of the just price, was not a sin against 
justice, though it might be a sin against charity.^ 
If the authorities granted a monopoly, they must 
at the same time fix a just price.* A monopoly 
which was not privileged by the State, and which 
had for its aim the rising of the price of goods 
above the just price was regarded with imiversal 
reprobation.^ ' Whoever buys up com, meat, 
and wine,' says Trithemius, 'in order to drive 
up their price and to amass money at the cost of 

^ Orowth of English Industry and Commerce, vol. i. p. 460. 
^ Endemann, Studien, vol. il. p. 60. 

' Lessius, De JustMa et Jure, n. xx. 1, 21. * Ihid. 

" Langenstein, De Oont. ; Biel, op. cit., iv. xv. 11. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 125 

others is, according to the laws of the Church, 
no better than a common criminal. In a weU- 
governed community all arbitrary raising of prices 
in the case of articles of food and clothing is per- 
emptorily stopped ; in times of scarcity merchants 
who have suppUes of such commodities can be 
compelled to seU them at fair prices ; for in every 
community care should be taken that aU the 
members should be provided for, and not only a 
small number be allowed to grow rich, and revel 
in luxury to the hurt and prejudice of the many.^ 
Thus the doctrine of the just price was a deadly *ir' 
weapon with which to fight the 'profiteer.' The 
engrosser was looked upon as the natural enemy 
of the poor ; and the power of the trading class 
was justly reckoned so great, that in cases of doubt 
prices were always fixed low rather than high. 
In other words, the buyer — ^that is to say, the 
community — ^was the subject of protection rather 
than the seller.^ 

It must at the same time be clearly kept in 
mind that the seller was also protected. All the 
authorities are unanimous that it was as sinful 
for the buyer to give too little as for the seller to 
demand too much, and it is this aspect of the just 
price which appears most favourable in comparison 
with the theory of price of the classical economists. 
In the former case prices were fixed having regard 
to the wages necessary for the producer ; in the 
latter the wages of the producer are determined 
by the price at which he can sell his goods, exposed 

* Quoted in Janssen, Of. cit, vol. ii. p. 102. 
^ Roaoher, Geschichte, p. 12. 



126 MEDMIVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

to the competition of machinery or foreign — ^pos- 
sibly slave — ^labour. ^ According to the Catholic 
Encydopcedia : ' To the mediseval theologian the 
just price of an article included enough to pay fair 
wages to the worker — ^that is, enough to enable him 
to maintain the standard of living of his class.' ^ 
'The difference,' says Dr. Cunningham, 'which 
emerges according as we start from one principle 
or the other comes out most distinctly with 
reference to wages. In the Middle Ages wages 
were taken as a first charge ; in modern times the 
reward of the labourer cannot but fluctuate in 
connection with fluctuations in the utility and 
market price of the things. There must always 
be a connection between wages and prices, but in 
the olden times wages were the first charge, and 
prices on the whole depended on them, while in 
modem times wages are, on the other hand, 
directly affected by prices.' ^ Dr. Cunningham 
draws attention to the fact that the labouring 
classes rejected the idea of the fiLxing of a just 
price for their services when, from a variety of 
causes, a situation arose when they were able to 
earn by open competition a reward higher than 
what was necessary to support them according to 
their state in life.* Nowadays the reverse has 
taken place ; unrestricted competition has in 
many cases resulted in the reduction of wages to 
a level below the margin of subsistence ; and the 

1 Ashley, op. dt,, vol. i. pt. i. p. 129. 

' Art. ' PoUtioal Economy.' 

8 Growth of English Industry and Commerce, vol. i. p. 461. 

* Christianity and Economic Science, p. 29. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 127 

general cry of the working classes is for the com- 
pulsory fixing of minimum rates of wages which 
will ensure that their subsistence will not be 
liable to be impaired by the fluctuations of the 
markets. What the workers of the present day 
look to as a desirable, but almost unattainable, 
ideal, was the universal practice in the ages when 
economic relations were controlled by Christian 
principles. 

§ 6. Wa& the Just Price Subjective or Objective ? 

The question whether the just price was essenti- 
ally subjective or objective has recently formed 
the subject matter of an interesting and ably 
conducted discussion, provoked by certain re- 
marks in Dr. Cunningham's Western Civilisation.^ 
Dr. Cunningham, although admiring the ethical 
spirit which animated the conception of the just 
price, thought at the same time that the economic 
ideas underlying the conception were so unde- 
veloped and unsoTind that the theory could not 
be applied in practice at the present day. ' Their 
economic analysis was very defective, and the 
theory of price which they put forward was un- 
tenable ; but the ethical standpoint which they 
took is weU worth examination, and the practical 
measures which they recommended appear to 
have been highly beneficial in the circumstances 
in which they had to deal. Their actions were not 
unwise ; their common-sense morahty was sound ; 
but the economic theories by which they tried to 

1 Pp. 77-9, 



128 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

give an intellectual justification for their rules 
and their practice were quite erroneous. . . . 
LThe attempt to determine an ideal price implies 
that there can and ought to be stability in relative 
lvalues and stability in the measure of values — 
which is absurd. The mediaeval doctrine and its 
application rested upon another assumption which 
we have outlived. Value is not a quahty which 
inheres in an object so that it can have the same 
worth for everybody ; it arises from the personal 
preference and needs of difierent people, some of 
whom desire a thing more and some less, some 
of whom want to use it in one way and some in 
another. Value is not objective — ^intrinsic in the 
object — ^but subjective, varying with the desire 
and intentions of the possessors or would-be 
possessors ; and, because it is thus subjective, 
there cannot be a definite ideal value which every 
article ought to possess, and stiU more a just price 
as the measure of that ideal value.' In these 
and similar observations to be found in the Growth 
of English History and Commerce, Dr. Cunningham 
showed that he profoundly misunderstood the 
doctrine of the just price; the objectivity which 
he attributed to it was not the objectivity ascribed 
to it by the scholastics. It was to correct this 
misunderstanding that Father Slater contributed 
an article to the Irish Theological Quarterly^ 
pointing out that the just price was subjective 
rather than objective. This article, which was 
afterwards reprinted in Some Aspects of Moral 
Theology, and the conclusions of which were 

» Vol. iv. p. 146. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PKOPERTY 129 

embodied in the same writer's work on Moral 
Theology, was controverted in a series of articles 
by Father Kelleher in the Irish Theological 
Qwirterly.^ 

Father Slater draws attention to the fact that 
Dr. Cunningham overlooked to some extent the 
importance of common estimation in arriving at 
the just price. He points out that, far from^ 
objects being invested with some immutable ob- 
jective value, their value was in fact determined 
by the price which the community as a whole was 
willing to pay ;for them: 'As the value in ex- 
change will be determined by what the members 
of the community at the time are prepared to 
give, ... it will be determined by the social 
estimation of its utility for the support of life and 
its scarcity. It wiU depend upon its capacity to 
satisfy the wants and desires of the people with 
whom commercial transactions are possible and 
practicable. Father Slater then goes on cate- 
gorically to refute Dr. Cunningham's presentation 
of the objectivity of price : ' All that that doc-4 
trine asserts is that there should be, and that 
there is, an equivalent in social value between 
the commodity and its price at a certain time 
and in a certain place ; it says nothing whatever 
about the stabiHty or permanence of prices at 
different times and at different places. By main- 
taining that the just price did not depend upon 
the valuation of the individual buyer or seller 
the mediaeval doctors did not dream of making 

^ ' Market Prices,' vol. ix. p. 398 and vol. x. p. 163 ; and ' Father 
Slater on Just Price and Value,' vol. xi. p. 159. 

I 



130 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

it ia'trinsic to the object.' In the work on Moral 
Theology, to which we have referred, expi^essions 
occur which lead one to beUeve that Father Slater 
did not see any great difEerence between the 
mediaeval just price arrived at by common esti- 
mation and the modem normal or market price 
arrived at by open competition. Thus, ia en- 
deavouring to correct Dr. Cunningham's mis- 
imderstanding. Father Slater seems to have gone 
too far in the other direction, and his position has 
been ably and, in our judgment, successfully, 
controverted by Father Kelleher. 

The point at issue between the upholders of the 
two opposing views on just price is well stated by 
Father KeUeher in the first of his articles on the 
subject : ' We must try to find out whether the 
just and fair price determined the rate of exchange, 
or whether the rate of exchange, being determined 
without an objective standard and merely accord- 
ing to the play of human motives, determines 
what we call the just and fair price.' ^ We have 
already demonstrated that the common estima- 
tion referred to by the mediaeval doctors was some- 
thing quite apart from the modem higgling in 
the market ; and that, far from being merely the 
restdt of unbridled competition on both sides, it 
was rather the considered judgment of the best- 
, informed members of the community. As we 
have seen, even Dr. Cunningham admits that 
there was a fundamental difference between the 
common estimation of the scholastics and the 
modem competitive price. This is clearly demon- 

'^ Irish Theologieal Qwnrterly, vol. ix. p. 41, 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 131 

strated by Father Kelleher, who further estab- 
Hshes the proposition that the modem price is 
purely subjective, and that no subjective price can 
rest on an ethical basis. The question at issue 
therefore between what we may call the subjective 
and objective schools is not whether the sale price 
was determined by competition in the modem 
sense, but whether the common estimation of 
those best quahfied to form an opinion on the 
subject in itself determined the just price, or 
whether it was merely the most reMable evidence 
of what the just price in fact was at a particular 
moment. 

Father KeUeher draws attention to the fact 
that Aquinas in his article on price did not specifi- ' 
caUy affirm that the just price was objective, but 
he explains this omission by saying that the 
objectivity of the price was so well and universally 
understood that it was unnecessary expressly to 
restate it. Indeed, as we saw above, the teaching 
of Aquinas on price left a great deal to be supphed 
by later writers, not because he was in any doubt 
about the subject, but because the theory was so 
well understood. 'Not even in St. Thomas can 
we find a formal discussion of the moral obligation 
of observing an objective equivalence in contracts 
of buying and selling. He simply took it for 
granted, as, indeed, was inevitable, seeing that, up 
to his time and for long after, aU CathoHc thought 
and legislation proceeded on that h3rpothesis. 
But that he actually did take it for granted, he 
has given many clear indications in his article on 
Justice which leave us no room for reasonable 



132 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

doubt.' 1 As Father Kelleher very cogently 
points out, the discussion in Aquinas' s article on 
commerce, whether it was lawful to buy cheap and 
sell dear, very clearly indicates that the author 
maintained the objective theory, because if the 
just price were simply determined by what people 
were willing to give, this question could not have 
arisen. 

Nor is the fact that the just price admitted of a 
certain elasticity an argument in favour of its 
being subjective. Father Kelleher fuUy admits 
that the common estimation was the general 
criterion of just price, and, of course, the common 
estimation could not, of its very nature, be rigid 
and immutable. ' Commodities should, indeed, 
exchange according to their objective value, but, 
even so, commodities could not carry their value 
stamped on their faces. Even if we assume that 
the standard of exchange was the cost of produc- 
tion, there would still remain room for a certain 
amount of difference of opinion as to what exactly 
their value would be in particular instances. 
Suppose that the commodity offered for sale was 
a suit of clothes, in estimating its value on the basis 
of the cost of production, opinions might differ as 
to the precise amount of time required for making 
it, or as to the cost of the cloth out of which it was 
made. Unless recourse was to be had to an almost 
interminable process of calculations, nobody could 
say authoritatively what precisely the value was, 
and in practice the determination of value had 
perforce to be left to the ordinary human estimate 

^ Irish Theological Quarterly, voL x. p. 165. 



THE EXCHAITGE OF PROPERTY 133 

of what it was, which of its very nature was bound 
to admit a certain margin of fluctuation. Thus 
we can easily understand how, even with an 
objective standard of value, the just price might 
be admitted to vary within the limits of the 
maximum as it might be expected to be esti- 
mated by sellers and the minimum as it would 
appear just to buyers. The sort of estimation 
of which St. Thomas speaks is therefore nothing 
else than a judgment, which, being human, is 
liable to be slightly in excess or defect of the 
objective value about which it is formed,' ^ As 
Father Kelleher puts it on a later page, ' There is 
a sense certainly in which, with a solitary excep- 
tion in the case of wages, it may be said with 
perfect truth that the common estimation deter- 
mines the just price. That is, the common esti- 
mation is the proximate practical criterion.' ^ 

Father KeUeher uses in support of his conten- 
tion a very ingenious argument drawn from the 
doctrine of usury. As we said in the first chapter, 
and as we shaU prove in detail in the next section, 
the prohibition of usury was simply one of the 
apphcations of the theory of equivalence in con- 
tracts — ^in other words, it was the determination of 
the just price to be paid in an exchange of money 
for money. If, asks Father Kelleher, the common 
estimation was the final te^t of just price, why was 
not moderate usury allowed ? That the general ! 
opinion of the community in the Middle Ages was 
tmdoubtedly in favour of allowing a reasonable 
percentage on loans is shown by the constant 

^ Irish Theological QvmterJy, vol. x. p. 166. ^ P. 173. 



134 MEDMIVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

striving of the Church to prevent such a practice. 
Nevertheless the Church did not for a moment 
relax its teaching on usury in spite of the almost 
universal judgment of the people. Here, tiiere- 
fore, is a clear example of one contract in which 
the standard of value is clearly objective, and it 
is only reasonable to draw the conclusion that the 
same standard which appUed in contracts of the 
exchange of money should apply in contracts of 
the sale of other articles. 

Father KeUeher's contention seems to be com- 
pletely supported by the passage from Nider 
which we have cited above, to the effect that the 
common estimation ceases to be the final test of 
the just price when the contracting paa-ties know 
or beheve that the common estimation has erred. ^ 
This seems to us clearly to show that the common 
estimatibn was but the most generally received 
test of what the just price in fact was, but that 
it was in no sense a final or irrefutable criterion.^ 

The theory that the just price was objective 

seems to be accepted by the majority of the best 

modern students of the subject. Sir WitUam 

' Ashley says : ' The fundamental difference between 

the mediaeval and modem point of view is . . . that 

^ X>e Cont. Merc, n. xv. Nider was regarded as a very weighty 
authority on the subject of contracts (Endemann, StvMen, voL ii. p. 8). 

' The argument in favour of what we have called the ' objective ' 
theory of the just price is strengthened by the consideration that 
goods do not satisfy mere subjective whims, but supply real wants. 
For example, food supplies a real need of the human being, as also 
does clothing ; in the one case hunger is appeased, and in the other 
cold is warded o£E, just as drags used in medical practice produce real 
objective e£Eects on the person taking them. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 135 

with us value is something entirely subjective ; 
it is what each individual cares to give for a thing. 
With Aquinas it was entirely objective ; some- 
thing outside the will of the individual purchaser 
or seller ; something attached to the thing itseK, 
existing whether he liked it or not, and that he 
ought to recognise.' ^ Palgrave's Dictionary of 
Political Economy, following the authority of ELnies, 
expresses the same opinion : ' Perhaps the con- 
trast between mediaeval and modem ideas of value 
is best expressed by saying that with us value is 
usually something subjective, consisting of the 
mental determination of buyer and seller, while 
to the schoolmen it was in a sense objective, 
something intrinsically bound up with the com- 
modity itself. ' 2 Dr. Ryan agrees with this view : 
' The theologians of the sixteenth and seventeenth 
centuries assumed that the objective price would 
be fair, since it was determined by the social 
estimate. In their opinion the social estimate 
would embody the requirements of objective 
justice as ftdly as any device or institution that 
was practically available. For the condition of 
the Middle Ages and the centuries immediately, 
following, this reasoning was undoubtedly correct. 
The agencies which created the social estimate j 
and determined prices — ^namely the civil law, the 
guilds, and custom — succeeded fairly in estabUsh- ' 
ing a price that was equitable to aU concerned.' ^ 
Dr. Cleary says : ' True, the pretium legale is 

1 Op. cit, vol. i. pt. i. p. 140. ^ Art. ' Jiistum Pretium.' 

* ' The Moral Aspect of Monopoly,' by J. A. Ryan, D.D., Irish 
Theological Qwi/rterly, iii. p. 275 ; and see DislribvMve Justice, pp. 332-4. 



136 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

regarded as being a just price, but in order that 
it may be just, it supposes some objective basis — 
in other words, it rather declares than constitutes 
the just price.' ^ Haney is also strongly of opinion 
that the just price was objective. ' Briefly stated, 
the doctrine was that every commodity had some 
one true value which was objective and abso- 
lute.' 2 The greater number of modern students 
therefore who have given most care and attention 
to the question are inclined to the opinion that the 
just price was not subjective, but objective, and 
we see no vaMd reason for disagreeing with this 
view, which seems to be fully warranted by the 
original authorities. 

§ 7. The Mediceval Attitude towards Commerce 

Before passing from the question of price, we 
must discuss the legitimacy of the various occupa- 
tions which were concerned with buying and 
selling. The principal matter which arises for 
consideration in this regard is the attitude of the 
mediaeval theologians towards commerce. Aquinas 
discusses the legitimacy of commerce in the same 
question in which he discusses just price, and in- 
deed the two subjects are closely allied, because 
the importance of the observance of justice in 
buying and selling grew urgent as commerce ex- 
tended and advanced. 

In order to understand the disapprobation with 
which commerce was on the whole regarded in 

1 Op. cit., p. 193. 

2 History of Economic Thought, p. 75. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 137 

the Middle Ages, it is necessary to appreciate the 
importance of the Christian teaching on the dignity 
bf labour. The principle that, far from being a 
degrading or humiliating occupation, as it had 
been regarded in Greece and Rome, manual labour 
was, on the contrary, one of the most noble ways 
of serving God, efiEected a revolution in the eco- 
nomic sphere analogous to that which the Christian 
sanctification of marriage effected in the domestic 
sphere. The Christian teaching on labour was 
grounded on the Divine precepts contained in 
both the Old and New Testaments,^ and upon 
the example of Christ, who was Himself a work- 
ing man. The Gospel was preached amongst 
the poor, and St, Paul continued his humble 
labours during his apostolate.^ A life of idleness^ 
was considered something to be avoided, instead 
of something to be desired, as it had been in the 
ancient civilisations. G«rson says it is against 
the nature of man to wish to Uve without labour 
as usurers do,^ and Langenstein inveighs against 
usurers and aU who hve without work.* ' We 
read in Sebastian Brant that the idlers are the 
most foohsh amongst fools, they are to every 
people Uke smoke to the eyes or vinegar to the 
teeth. Only by labour is God truly praised and 
honoured ; and Trithemius says " Man is born to 
labour as the bird to fly, and hence it is contrary 

1 Gen. Hi. 19 ; Ps. cxxvii. 2 ; 2 Thess. iii. 10. The last- mentioned 
text is explained, in opposition to certain Socialist interpretations 
which have been put on it, by Dr. Hogan in the Irish Ecclesiastical 
Record, vol. xxv. p. 45. * WaUon, oy. dt., vol. iii. p. 401. 

» De Cmt., i. 13. * De Cont. 



138 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

to the nature of man when he thinks to hve -with- 
out work." ' 1 The example of the monasteries, 
where the performance of all sorts of manual 
labour was not thought inconsistent with the 
administration of the sacred offices and the pur- 
suit of the highest intellectual exercises, acted as 
a powerful assertion to the laity of the dignity 
of labour in the scheme of things.^ The value of 
the monastic example in this respect cannot be 
too highly estimated. ' When we consider the 
results of the founding of monasteries,' says Dr. 
Cunningham, ' we find influences at work that 
were plainly economic. These communities can 
be best understood when we think of them as 
Christian industrial colonies, and remember that 
they moulded society rather by example than by 
precept. We are so f amiUar with the attacks and 
satires on monastic life that were current at the 
Reformation period, that it may seem almost a 
paradox to say that the chief claim of the monks 
to our gratitude lies in this, that they helped to 
diffuse a better appreciation of the duty and dig- 
nity of labour.' ^ 

The result of this teaching and example was 
that, in the Middle Ages, labour had been raised 
to a position of unquestioned dignity. The 
economic benefit of this attitude towards labour 
must be obvious. It made the working classes 
take a direct pride and interest in their work, 
which was represented to be a means of sanctifi- 

'- Janssen, op. cit., vol. ii. pp. 93-4. 

" Levasseur, Histoire des Classes ouwUres en France, vol. i.. pp. 182 
et eeq. ' Western OiviHsation, vol. ii. p. 35. 



THE EXCHANCE OP PROPERTY 139 

cation. ' Laboiir,' according to Dr. Cunningham, 
' was said to be pregnant with a double advantage 
— ^the privilege of sharing with God in His work of 
carrying out His purpose, and the opportunity of 
self-disciphne and the helping of one'sfeUow-men.' ^ 
' Industrial work,' says Levassetir, ' in the times 
of antiquity had always had, in spite of the insti- 
tutions of certain Emperors, a degrading character, 
because it had its roots in slavery ; after the in- 
vasion, the grossness of the barbarians and the 
levelling of towns did not help to rehabilitate it. 
It was the Church which, in proclaiming that 
Christ was the son of a carpenter, and the Apostles 
were simple workmen, made known to the world 
that work is honourable as well as necessary. 
The monks proved this by their example, and thus 
helped to give to the working classes a certain 
consideration which ancient society had denied 
them. Manual labour became a source of sancti- 
fication.' ^ The high esteem in which labour was 
held appears from the whole artistic output of the 
Middle Ages. ' Many of the simple artists of the 
time represented the saints holding some instru- 
ment of work or engaged in some industrial 
pursuit ; as, for instance, the Blessed Virgin 
spinning as she sat by the cradle of the divine 
Infant, and St. Joseph using a saw or carpenter's 
tools. " Since the Saints," says the Christian 
Monitor, " have laboured, so shall the Christian 
learn that by honourable labour he can glorify 
God, do good, and save his own soul." ' ^ Work 

1 Christianity and Economic Science, pp. 26-7. 

^ Op. cit., vol. L p. 187. ' Janssen, op. eit., voL ii. p. 9. 



140 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

was, alongside of prayer and inseparable from it, 
the perfection of Christian life.^ 
^- It must not be supposed, however, that manual 
labour alone was thought worthy of praise. On 
the contrary, the necessity for mental and spiritual 
workers was fuUy appreciated, and aU kinds of 
labour were thought equally worthy of honour. 
' Heavy labourer's work is the inevitable yoke of 
punishment, which, according to God's righteous 
verdict, has been laid upon all the sons of Adam. 
But many of Adam's descehdants seek in aU sorts 
of cunning ways to escape from the yoke and to 
live in idleness without labour, and at the same 
time to have a superfluity of useful and necessary 
things ; some by robbery and plunder, some by 
usurious dealings, others by lying, deceit, and aU 
the countless forms of dishonest and fraudulent 
gain, by which men are for ever seeking to get 
riches and abundance without toil. But while 
such men are striving to throw off the yoke 
righteously imposed on them by God, they are 
heaping on their shoulders a heavy burden of sin. 
Not so, however, do the reasonable sons of Adam 
proceed ; but, recognising in sorrow that for the 
sins of their first father God has righteously 
ordained that only through the toil of labour shall 
they obtatu what is necessary to life, they take 
the yoke patiently on them. . . . Some of them, 
like the peasants, the handicraftsmen, and the 
tradespeople, procure for themselves and others, 
in the sweat of their brows and by physical work, 
the necessary sustenance of life. Others, who 

^ Wallon, op. ctt., voL i. p. 410. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 141 

labour in more honourable ways, earn the right 
to be maintained by the sweat of others' brows — 
for instance, those who stand at the head of the 
commonwealth ; for by their laborious exertion 
the former are enabled to enjoy the peace, the 
security, without which they could not exist. 
The same holds good of those who have the charge 
of spiritual matters. . . .' ^ ' Because,' says 
Aquinas, ' many things are necessary to human 
life, with which one man caimot provide himself, 
it is necessary that different things should be done 
by different people ; therefore some are tillers of 
the soil, some are raisers of cattle, some are 
builders, and so on ; and, because human life does 
not simply mean corporal things, but still more 
spiritual things, therefore it is necessary that sonae 
people should be released from the care of attend- 
ing to temporal matters. This distribution of 
different offices amongst different people is in 
accordance with Divine providence.' ^ 

All forms of labour being therefore admitted to 
be honourable and necessary, there was no diffi- 
culty felt about justifying their reward. It was 
always common ground that services of all kinds 
were entitled to be properly remimerated, and 
questions of difficulty only arose when a claim was 
made for payment in a transaction where the 
element of service was not apparent.^ The differ- 
ent occupations in which men were engaged were 
therefore ranked in a well-recognised hierarchy 

^ Langenstein, quoted in Janssen, op. cit, p. 95. 

* Swmma 'Cont. Qent, iii. 134. 

' Aquinas, Sutama, n. ii. 77, 4 ; Nider, op. cit., n. x. 



142 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

of dignity according to the estimate to wliicli they 
were held to be entitled. The Aristotelean divi- 
sion of industry iato artes possessivae and artes 
pecuniativae was generally followed, the former 
being ranked higher than the latter. ' The in- 
dustries called possessivae, which are immediately 
useful to the individual, to the family, and to 
society, producing natural wealth, are also the 
most natural as well as the most estimable. But 
all the others should not be despised. The natural 
arts are the true economic arts, but the arts which 
produce artificial riches are also estimable in so 
far as they serve the true national economy ; the 
commutation of the exchanges and the cambium 
being necessary to the general good, are good in so 
far as they are subordinate to the end of true 
economy. One may say the same thing about 
commerce. In order, then, to estimate the value 
of an industrial art, one must examine its rela- 
JftioQ to the general good.' ^ Even the artes posses- 
sivae were not aU considered equally worthy of 
praise, but were ranked in a curious order of pro- 
fessional hierarchy. Agriculture was considered 
the highest, next manufacture, and lastly com- 
merce. Roscher says that, whereas all the 
scholastics were agreed on the excellence of agri- 
culture as an occupation, the best they could say 
of manufacture was Deo non dispUcet, whereas of 
commerce they said Deo placere non potest ; and 
draws attention to the interesting consequence of 
this, namely, that the various classes of goods that 
took part in the difEerent occupations were also 

^ Brants, op, cit., p. 82. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 143 

ranked in a certain order of sacredness. Im- 
movables were thought more worthy of pro- 
tection against execution and distress than mov- 
ables, and movables than money. ^ Aquinas 
advises the rulers of States to encourage the artes 
possessivae, especially agriculture. ^ The fullest 
analysis of the order in which the different 
artes possessivae should be ranked is to be 
found in Buridan's Commentaries on Aristotle^ s 
Politics. He places first agriculture, which 
comprises cattle-breeding, tillage, and hunting ; 
secondly, manufacture, which helps to supply 
man's corporal needs, such as building and archi- 
tecture ; thirdly, administrative occupations ; and 
lastly, commerce. The Christian Exhortation, 
quoted by Janssen,^ says, ' The farmer must in all 
things be protected and encouraged, for all de- 
pend on his labour, from the monarch to the 
humblest of mankind, and his handiwork is in 
particular honourable and well pleasing to God.' 

The division of occupations according to their 
dignity adopted by Nicholas Oresme is some- 
what unusual. He divides professions into (1) 
honourable, or those which increase the actual 
quantity of goods in the community or help its 
development, such as ecclesiastical offices, the law, 
the soldiery, the peasantry, artisans, and merchants, 
and (2) degrading — such as campsores, mercatores 
monetae seu billonatores.^ 

^ Geschichte, p. 7. 

* De BegimiTie Prindpum, vol. ii. chaps, v. and vi. 
' Op. eit, Tol. i. p. 297. 

* Traetatus de Origine, etc., Monetarwm. 



144 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

No occupation, therefore, which involved labour, 
whether manual or mental, gave any ground for 
difl&culty with regard to its remuneration. The 
business of the trader or merchant, on the other 
hand, was one which called for some explanation. 
It is important to understand what commerce 
was taken to mean. The definition which Aquinas 
gives was accepted by aU later writers : ' A trades- 
man is one whose business consists in the exchange 
of things. According to the philosopher, exchange 
of things is twofold ; one natural, as it were, and 
necessary, whereby one commodity is exchanged 
for another, or money taken in exchange for a 
commodity in order to satisfy the needs of life. 
Such trading, properly speaking, does not be- 
long to traders, but rather to housekeepers or 
civil servants, who have to provide the house- 
hold or the State with the necessaries of life. The 
other kind of exchange is either that of money for 
money, or of any commodity for money, not on 
account of the necessities of hfe, but for profit ; 
and this kind of trade, properly speaking, regards 
traders.' It is to be remarked in this defini- 
tion, that it is essential, to constitute trade, that 
the exchange or sale should be for the sake of 
profit, and this point is further emphasised in a 
■ later passage of the same article : ' Not every one 
that sells at a higher price than he bought is a 
trader, but only he who buys that he may sell 
at a profit. If, on the contrary, he buys, not for 
sale, but for possession, and afterwards for some 
reason wishes to sell, it is not a trade transaction, 
even if he sell- at a profit. For he may lawfully 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 145 

do this, either because he has bettered the thing, 
or because the value of the thing has changed 
with the change of place or time, or on account of 
the danger he incurs in transferring the thing from 
one place to another, or again in having it carried 
by hand. In this sense neither buying nor selling 
is imjust.' ^ The importance of this definition 
is that it rules out of the discussion aU cases where 
the goods have been in any way improved or 
rendered more valuable by the services of the 
seller. Such improvement was always reckoned 
as the result of labour of one kind or another, and 
therefore entitled to remuneration. The essence 
of trade in the scholastic sense was selling the 
thing unchanged at a higher price than that at 
which it had been bought, for the sake of gain. ^ 

The legitimacy of trade in this sense was only 
gradually admitted. The Fathers of the Church 
had with one voice condemned trade as being 
an occupation fraught with danger to the soul. 
TertuUian argued that there would be no need of 
trade if there were no desire for gain, and that 
there would be no desire for gain if man were not 
avaricious. Therefore avarice was the necessary 
basis of aU trade. ^ St. Jerome thought that one 
man's gain in trading must always be another's 
loss ; and that, in any event, trade was a danger- 
ous occupation since it offered so many tempta- 

1 Tractatus de Origme, etc., Monetarum, ad. 2. 

^ ' Fit autem meroatio cniin non ut emptor ea utatur sed ut earn 
carius vendat etiam non mutatam suo aitiflcio ; ilia mercatio dlcitur 
proprie negotiatio ' (Biel, op. cit., iv. xv. 10.) 

3 De Idol, xi. 

K 



146 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

tions to fraud to the merchant.^ St. Augustine 
proclaimed all trade evil because it turns men's 
minds away from seeking true rest, which is only 
to be found in God, and this opinion was embodied 
in the Corpus Juris CanoniciJ ' This early view 
that aU trade was to be indiscriminately con- 
demned could not in the nature of things survive 
experience, and a great step forward was taken 
when Leo the Great pronounced that trade was 
neither good nor bad in itself, but was rendered 
good or bad according as it was honestly or dis- 
honestly carried on.' 

The scholastics, in addition to condemning 
commerce on the authority of the patristic texts, 
condemned it also on the Aristotelean ground that 
it was a chrematistic art, and this consideration, 
as we have seen above, enters into Aquinas's 
article on the subject.* 

The extension of commercial life which took 
place about the beginning of the thirteenth cen- 
tury, raised acute controversies about the legi- 
timacy of commerce. Probably nothing did more 
to broaden the teaching on this subject than the 
necessity of justifying trade which became more 
and more insistent after the Crusades.^ 

^ Ashley, op. cit, vol. i. pt. i. p. 129. 

' See Corpus Juris Oanonid, Deor. I. D. 88 o. 12, 

' Epist. ad Busticwn, c. ix. * Rambaud, op. cit., p. 52. 

" On the economic influence of the Crusades the following works 
may be consulted : Blanqui, Histoire de I'Eeonomie politique ; Heeren, 
Essai sur V Influence politique et sociaie des Croisades ; Soheier, Histoire 
du Commeroe ; Prutz, Culiurgeschiehle der Kreuzzilge ; Pigonneau, 
Histoire du Commerce de la France ; List, Die Lehrem der Handda- 
poUtischen Oeschichte. 



THE EXCHAIIGE OF PROPERTY 147 

By the time of Aquinas the necessity of com- > 
merce had come to be fully realised, as appears 
from the passage in. the De Begimine Principum : 
' There are two ways in which it is possible to 
increase the affluence of any State. One, which is 
the more worthy way, is on account of the fertility 
of the country producing an abundance of all 
things which are necessary for human Mfe, the 
other is through the employment of commerce, 
through which the necessaries of life are brought 
from different places. The former method can 
be clearly shown to be the more desirable. . . . 
It is more admirable that a State should possess 
an abundance of riches from its own soil than 
through commerce. For the State which needs a 
number of merchants to maintain its subsistence 
is liable to be injured in war through a shortage 
of food if communications are in any way impeded. 
Moreover, the influx of strangers corrupts the 
morals of many of the citizens . . . whereas, if 
the citizens themselves devote themselves to 
commerce, a door is opened to many vices. For 
when the desire of merchants is inclined greatly to 
gain, cupidity is aroused in the hearts of many 
citizens. . . . For the pursuit of a merchant is as 
contrary as possible to military exertion. For 
merchants abstain from labours, and while they 
enjoy the good things of life, they become soft in 
mind and their bodies are rendered weak and 
tmsuitable for mihtary exercises. ... It there- 
fore behoves the perfect State to make a moderate 
use of commerce.' ^ 

1 U.3. 



148 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

Aquinas, who, as we have seen, recognised the 
necessity of commerce, did not condemn all trade 
indiscriminately, as the Fathers had done, but 
made the motive with which commerce was 
carried on the test of its legitimacy : ' Trade is 
justly deserving of blame, because, considered in 
itself, it satisfies the greed for gain, which knows 
no Umit, and tends to infinity. Hence trading, 
considered in itself, has a certain debasement 
attaching thereto, in so far as, by its very nature, 
it does not imply a virtuous or necessary end. 
Nevertheless gain, which is the end of trading, 
though not implying, by its nature, anything 
virtuous or necessary, does not, in itself, connote 
anything sinful or contrary to virtue ; wherefore 
nothing prevents gain from being directed to some 
necessary or even virtuous end, and thus trading 
becomes lawful. Thus, for instance, a man may 
intend the moderate gain which he seeks to 
acquire by trading for the upkeep of his household, 
or for the assistance of the needy ; or again, a man 
may take to trade for some pubMc advantage — ^for 
instance, lest his country lack the necessaries of 
life — and seek gain, not as an end, but as payment 
for his labour.' ^ This is important in connection 
with what we have said above as to property, as 
it shows that the trader was quite justified in 
seeking to obtain more profits, provided that they 
accrued for the benefit of the community. This 
justification of trade according to the end for 
which it was carried on, was not laid down for the 
first time by Aquinas, but may be found stated 
1 n. ii. 77, 4. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 149 

in an English treatise of the tenth century en- 
titled The Colloquy of Archbishop Alfric, where, 
when a doctor asks a merchant if he wishes to 
sell his goods for the same price for which he has 
bought them, the merchant replies : ' I do not 
wish to do so, because if I do so, how would I be 
recompensed for my trouble ? but I wish to sell 
them for more than I paid for them so that I 
might secure some gain wherewith to support 
myself, my wife, and family.' ^ 

In spite of the fact that the earlier theory that 
no commercial gain which did not represent pay- 
ment for labour could be justified was stiU main- 
tained by some writers — ^for instance, Raymond de 
Pennaf ort ^ — ^the teaching of St. Thomas Aquinas 
wa,s generally accepted throughout the later 
Middle Ages. Canonists and theologians accepted 
without hesitation the justification of trade for- 
mulated by Aquinas.^ Henri de Gand,* Duns 
Scotus,^ and Frangois de Mayronis ^ unhesitatingly 
accepted the view of Aquiaas, and incorporated it 
in their works.' ' An honourable merchant,' says 
Trithemius, ' who does not only think of large 
profits, and who is guided in all his dealings by the 
laws of God and man, and who gladly gives to the 
needy of his wealth and earnings, deserves the 
same esteem as any other worker. But it is no 
easy matter to be always honourable in all mer- 

1 Loria, Anah/si de la 'pfcyprieHb eapitaUsta, ii. 168. 

* Svmma Theologica, n. vii. 5. 

^ Ashley, op. cit., p. 55. * Quodlih., i. 40. 

s Lib. Quat. Sent, xv. 2. • iv. 16, 4. 

' gee Jourdain, oj>. dt., p. 20 et aeq. 



150 medij:val economic teaching 

cantile dealings and not to become usurious. 
Without commerce no community can of course 
exist, but immoderate commerce is rather hurtful 
than beneficial, because it fosters greed of gain 
and gold, and enervates and emasculates the 
nation through love of pleasure and luxury.' ^ 
Nider says that to buy not for use but for sale at 
a higher price is called trade. Two special rules 
apply to this : first, that it should be useful to 
the State, and second, that the price should corre- 
spond to the dihgence, prudence, and risk under- 
taken in the transaction.^ 

-/-' The later writers in the fifteenth century seem 
to have regarded trade more liberally even than 
Aquinas, although they quote his dictum on the 
subject as the basis of their teaching. Instead of 

! condemning aU commerce as wrong unless it was 

! justified by good motives, they were rather in- 
clined to treat commerce as being in itself colour- 

i less, but capable of becoming evil by bad motives. 

i Carletus says : ' Commerce in itself is neither bad 
nor illegal, but it may become bad on account of 
ithe circumstances and the motive with which it 
is undertaken, the persons who undertake it, or 
the manner in which it is conducted. For instance, 
commerce undertaken through avarice or a desire 
for sloth is bad ; so also is commerce which is 
injurious to the repubhc, such as engrossing.' ^ 

' Quoted in Janssen, <yp. eit., vol. ii. p. 97. 

« Of. cit., iv. 10. 

* Summa Angelica, 169: 'Mercatio non est mala ex genere, sed 
bona, humane conyictui neoesaaria dum fuerit justa. Mercatio sim- 
plioiter non est peccatum sed ejus abusus.' Biel, op, cit., iv. zv. 10. 



THE EXCHANGE OP PROPERTY 151 

Endemami, having thoroughly studied all the 
fifteenth-century writers on the subject, says that 
commerce might be rendered unjustifiable either 
by subjective or objective reasons. Subjective 
illegality would arise from the person trading — ^f or 
instance, the clergy — or the motive with which 
trade was undertaken; objective iUegahty on 
account of the object traded in, such as weapons 
in war-time, or the bodies of free men.^ Specu- 
lative trading, and what we to-day call profiteer- 
ing, were forbidden in all circumstances. ^ 

We need not dwell upon the prohibition of 
trading by the clergy, because it was simply a rule 
of discipline which has not any bearing upon 
general economic teaching, except in so far as it 
shows that commerce was considered an occupa- 
tion dangerous to virtue. Aquinas puts it as 
follows : ' Clerics shotdd abstain not only from 
things that are evil in themselves, but even from 
those that have an appearance of evil. This 
happens in trading, both because it is directed to 
worldly gain, which clerics should despise, and 
because trading is open to so many vices, since " a 
merchant is hardly free from sins of the hps." ^ 
There is also another reason, because trading 
engages the mind too much with worldly cares, 
and consequently withdraws it from spiritual 
cares ; wherefore the Apostle says : * "No man 

>■ Siudien, vol. ii. p. 18. 

2 The Ayenbite of Inwit, a thirteenth-century confessor's manual, 
lays it down that speculation is a kind of usury. (Rambaud, Histoire, 
p. 56.) 

3 Eooles. xxvi. 28. * 2 Tim. ii. 4. 



152 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

being a soldier to God entangleth himself with 
secular business." Nevertheless it is lawful for 
clerics to engage in the first-mentioned kind of 
exchange, which is directed to supply the neces- 
saries of hfe, either by buying or by selling.' ^ 
The rule of St. Benedict contains a strong ad- 
monition to those who may be entrusted with the 
sale of any of the products of the monastery, to 
ayoid aU fraud and avarice. ^ 

On the whole, the attitude towards commerce 
seems to have grown more liberal in the course of 
the Middle Ages. At first aU commerce was con- 
demned as sinful ; at a later period it was said to 
be justifiable provided it was influenced by good 
motives ; while at a stiU later date the method of 
treatment was rather to regard it as a colourless 
act in itself which might be rendered harmful 
by the presence of bad motives. This gradual 
broadening of the justification of commerce is 
probably a reflection of the necessities of the age, 
which witnessed a very great expansion of com- 
merce, especially of foreign trade. In the earher 
> centuries remuneration for undertaking risk was 
prohibited on the authority of a passage in the 
Gregorian Decretals, but the later writers refused 
to disallow it.^ The following passage from Dr. 
Cunningham's Growth of English Industry and 
Commerce correctly represents the attitude of the 
Chxirch towards commerce at the end of the 
Middle Ages : ' The ecclesiastic who regarded the 

^ Svmim, n. ii. 77, 4, ad. 3. " lUg. St. Ben., 57. 

' Cunningham, Growth of English Industry and Cormmrtx, vol. i. 
p. 266. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPEHTY 153 

merchant as exposed to temptations in all his 
dealings would not condemn him as sinful unless 
it were clear that a transaction were entered on 
solely for greed, and hence it was the tendency for 
moralists to draw additional distinctions, and 
refuse to pronounce against business practices 
where common sense did not give the benefit of 
the doubt.' ^ We have seen that one motive 
which would justify the carrying on of trade was 
the desire to support one's self and one's famUy. 
Of course this motive was capable of bearing 
a very extended and elastic interpretation, and 
would justify increased commercial profits accord- 
ing as the standard of fife improved. The other 
motive given by the theologians, namely, the bene- 
fit of the State, was also one which was capable 
of a very wide construction. One must remember 
that even the manual labourer was bound not to 
labour solely for avaricious gain, but also for the 
benefit of his fellow-men. ' It is not only to 
chastise our bodies,' says Basil, ' it is also by the 
love of our neighbour that the labourer's life is 
useful so that God may furnish through us our 
weaker brethren ' ; ^ and a fifteenth-century book 
on morality says : ' Man should labour for the 
honour of Grod. He should labour in order to 
gain for himself and his family the necessaries of 
life and what will contribute to Christian joy, 
and moreover to assist the poor and the sick by 
his labours. He who acting otherwise seeks only 
the pecuniary recompense of his work does Ul, 
and his labours are but usury. In the words of 

1 p. 255. 2 ^gg_ j^_ Tract., xxxvn. i. 



154 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

St. Augustine, " thou shalt not commit usury 
with the work of thy hands, for thus wilt thou 
lose thy soul." ' i The necessity for altruism 
and regard for the needs of one's neighbour as well 
as of one's self were therefore motives necessary 
to justify labour as well as commerce ; and it 
would be wrong to conclude that the teaching of 
the scholastics on the necessity for a good motive 
to justify trade operated to damp individual 
enterprise, or to discourage those who were in- 
clined to launch commercial undertakings, any 
more than the insistence on the need for a similar 
motive in labourers was productive of idleness. 
What the mediaeval teaching on commerce really 
amounted to was that, while commerce was as 
legitimate as any other occupation, owing to the 
numerous temptations to avarice and dishonesty 
which it involved, it must be carefully scrutinised 
and kept within due bounds. It was more diffi- 
cult to insure the observance of the just price in 
the case of a sale by a merchant than in one by 
an artificer; and the power which the merchant 
possessed of raising the price of the necessaries of 
life on ihe poor by engrossing and speculation 
rendered him a person whose operations should be 
carefully controlled. 

Finally, it must be clearly understood that the 
attempt of some modern writers to base the medi- 
aeval justification of commerce on an analysis of 
all commercial gains as the payment for labour 
rests on a profound misunderstanding. As we 
have already pointed out, Aquinas distinctly 

^ Quoted in Janssen, op. cit., vol. ii. p. 9. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 155 

rules out of consideration in his treatment of 
commerce the case where the goods have been 
improved in value by the exertions of the mer- 
chant. When the element of labour entered into 
the transaction the matter was clearly beyond 
doubt, and the lengthy discussion devoted to the 
question of commerce by Aquinas and his followers 
shows that in justifying commercial gains they 
were justifying a gain resting not on the remunera- 
tion for the labour, but on an independent title. 

§ 8. Cambium 

There was one department of commerce, namely, 
cambium, or money-changing, which, while it did 
not give any difficulty in theory, involved certain 
difficulties in practice, owing to the fact that 
it was liable to be used to disguise usurious 
transactions. Although cambium was, strictly 
speaking, a special branch of commerce, it was 
nevertheless usually treated in the works on usury, 
the reason being that many apparent contracts of 
cambium were in fact veiled loans, and that it was 
therefore a matter of importance in discussing usury 
to explain the tests by which genuine and usurious 
exchanges could be distinguished. Endemann 
treats this subject very fuUy and ably ; ^ but for 
the purpose of the present essay it is not necessary 
to do more than to state the main conclusions at 
which he arrives. 

Although the practice of exchange grew up 
slowly and gradually during the later Middle 

n, vol. i. p. 75. 



156 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

Ages, and, consequently, the amount of space 
devoted to the discussion of the theory of ex- 
change became larger as time went on, never- 
theless there is no serious difference of opinion 
between the writers of the thirteenth century, who 
treat the subject in a fragmentary way, and those 
of the fifteenth, who deal with it exhaustively 
and systematically. Aquinas does not mention 
cambium in the Summa, but he recognises the 
necessity for some system of exchange in the De 
Begimine Principum.^ AQ the later writers who 
mention cambium are agreed in regarding it as a 
species of commerce to which the ordinary rules 
regulating aU commerce apply. Francis de May- 
ronis says that the art of cambium is as natural 
as any other kind of commerce, because of the 
diversity of the currencies in different kingdoms, 
and approves of the campsor receiving some 
remuneration for his labour and trouble. ^ Nicholas 
de Ausmo, in his commentary on the Summa 
Pisana, written in the beginning of the fifteenth 
bentury, says that the campsor may receive a gain 
from his transactions, provided that they are not 
conducted with the sole object of making a profit, 
and that the gain he may receive must be hmited 
by the common estimation of the place and time. 
This is practically saying that cambium may be 
carried on under the same conditions as any other 
species of commerce. Biel says that cambium 

1 ' Cum enim extraneae monetae communicantuT in permutationibus 
opoitet recunere ad artem campsoriam, cum talia numismata non 
tautum valeant in regionibus extraneis quantum in propriis (De ^e^, 
Prin., u. 13). " In Qwt. Lib.. Sent., iv. 16, 4. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 157 

is only legitimate if the campsor has the motive 
of keeping up a family or benefiting the State, 
and that the contract may become usurious if the 
gain is not fair and moderate.^ The right of the 
campsor to some remuneration for risk was only 
gradually admitted, and forms the subject of much 
discussion amongst the jurists. ^ This hesitation 
in allowing remimeration for risk was not pecuhar 
to cambium, but, as we have seen above, was 
common to aU commerce. Endemann points out 
how the theologians and jurists unanimously in- 
sisted that cambium could not be justified except 
when the just price was observed, and that, when 
the doctrine attained its f\xll development, the 
element of labour was but one of the constituents 
in the estimation of that price. ^ 

All the writers who treated of exchange divided 
it into three kinds ; ordinary exchange of the 
moneys of different currencies {cambium minutum), 
exchange of moneys of different currencies between 
different places, the justification for which rested 
on remuneration for an imaginary transport 
(cambium 'per Utteras), and usurious exchange of 
moneys of the same currency {cambium siccum). 
The former two species of cambium were justifi- 
able, whereas the last was condemned.* 

The most complete treatise on the subject of 
money exchange is that of Thomas da Vio, written 
in 1499. The author of this treatise divides money- 

1 Op. cit, IV. XV. 11. 

" Endemann, Studien, vol. i. pp. 123-36. 

s Ibid., p. 213. 

* LaurentiuB de Bodulfis, Be Vsuris, pt, iii. Nos. 1 to 5. 



158 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

changing into three kinds, just, unjust, and doubt- 
ful. There were three kinds of just change ; cam- 
bium minutum, in which the campsor was entitled 
to a reasonable remuneration for his labour; 
cambium per litteras, in which the campsor was 
held entitled to a wage {m£.rces) for an imaginary- 
transportation ; and thirdly, when the campsor 
carried money from one place to another, where it 
was of higher value. The unjust change was 
when the contract was a usurious transaction veiled 
in the guise of a genuine exchange. Under the 
doubtful changes, the author discusses various 
special points which need not detain us here. 

Thomas da Vio then goes on to discuss whether 
the justifiable exchange can be said to be a species 
of loan, and concludes that it can not, because aU 
that the campsor receives is an indemnity against 
loss aiid a remuneration for his labour, trouble, 
outlay, and risk, which is always justifiable. He 
then goes on to state the very important principle, 
that in cambium money is not to be considered 
a measure of value, but a vendible commodity, '^ 
a distinction which Endemann thinks was pro- 
ductive of very important results in the later 
teaching on the subject.^ The last question 
treated in the treatise is the measure of the 
campsor' s profit, and here the contract of exchange 
is shown to be on aU fours with every other con- 
tract, because the essential principle laid down 

1 ' Numisma quamvis sit mensura et instrumentom in permuta- 
tionibus ; tamen per se aliquid esse potest.' It is this principle that 
justifies the treatment of canMimii in this section rather than the next. 

^ StvMm, vol. ii. p. 212. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 159 

for determining its justice is the observance of the 
equivalence between both parties.^ 

Section 2. — The Sale of the Use of 
Money 

§ 1. Usury in Oreece and Rome 

The prohibition of usury has always occupied 
such a large place in histories of the Middle Ages, 
and particularly in discussions relating to the 
attitude of the Church towards economic ques- 
tions, that it is important that its precise founda- 
tion and extent should be carefuUy studied. The 
usury prohibition has been the centre of so many 
bitter controversies, that it has almost become 
part of the stock-in-trade of the theological mob 
orators. The attitude of the Church towards 
usury only takes a sUghtly less prominent place 
than its attitude towards Gahleo in the utterances 
of those who are anxious to convict it of error. 
We have referred to this current controversy, not 
in order that we might take a part in it, but 
that, on the contrary, we might avoid it. It is 
no part of our purpose in our treatment of this 
subject to discuss whether the usury prohibition 
was or was not suitable to the conditions of the 
Middle Ages ; whether it did or did not impede 
industrial enterprise and commercial expansion ; 
or whether it was or was not universally disre- 
garded and evaded in real Ufe. These are in- 
quiries which, though full of interest, would not 

1 Brants has a very luminous and interesting section on Camitiwm, 
oip. cit., p. 214 et seq. 



160 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

be in place in a discussion of theory. All we are 
concerned to do in the following pages is to indi- 
cate the grounds on which the prohibition of usury 
rested, the precise extent of its appMcation, and 
the conceptions of economic theory which it indi- 
cated and involved. 

We must remark in the first place that the pro- 
hibition of usury was in no sense pecuHar to the 
Catholic Church in the Middle Ages, but, on the 
contrary, was to be found in many other rehgious 
and legal systems— for instance, in the writings of 
the Greek and Roman philosophers, amongst the 
Jews, and the followers of Mohammed. We shall 
give a very brief account of the other prohibitions 
of usury before coming to deal with the scholastic 
teaching on the subject. 

We can find no trace of any legal prohibition 
of usury in ancient Greece. Although Solon's 
laws contained many provisions for the rehef of 
poor debtors, they did not forbid the taking of 
interest, nor did they limit the rate of interest that 
might be taken.^ In Rome the Twelve Tables fixed 
a maximum rate of interest, which was probably 
ten or twelve per cent, per annum, but which 
cannot be determined with certainty owing to the 
doubtful signification of the expression ' unciarum 
foenus.' The legal rate of interest was gradually 
reduced until the year 347 B.C., when five per cent, 
was fixed as a maximum. In 342 B.C. interest 
was forbidden altogether by the Grenucian Law ; 
but this law, though never repealed, was in prac- 
tice quite inoperative owing to the facility with 

^ Geaiy, The Church and Usury, p. 21. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 161 

which it could be evaded ; and consequently the 
oppression of borrowers was prevented by the 
enactment, or perhaps it would be more correct to 
say the general recognition, of a maximum rate 
of interest of twelve per cent, per annum. This 
maximum rate — ^the Centesima — ^remained in oper- 
ation until the time of Justinian. ^ Justinian, 
who was under the influence of Christian teaching, 
and who might therefore be expected to have 
regarded usury with unfavourable eyes, fixed the 
following maximum rates of interest — maritime 
loans twelve per cent. ; loans to ordinary persons, 
not in business, six per cent. ; loans to high per- 
sonages (illustres) and agriculturists, four per cent.^ 
While the taking of interest was thus approved 
or tolerated by Greek and Roman law, it was at 
the same time reprobated by the philosophers of 
both countries. Plato objects to usury because 
it tends to set one class, the poor or the borrowers, 
against another, the rich or the lenders ; and goes 
so far as to make it wrong for the borrower to 
repay either the principal or interest of his debt. 
He further considers that the profession of the 
usurer is to be despised, as it is an illiberal and 
debasing way of making money. ^ While Plato 
therefore disapproves in no ambiguous words of 
usury, he does not develop the philosophical bases 
of his objection, but is content to condemn it 
rather for its probable ill effects than on account 
of its inherent injustice. 

^ Hunter, Bcyman Law, pp. 652-53 ; deary, op. cit, pp. 22-6 ; 
Roscher, Political Economy, a. 90. 
2 Code 4, 32, 26, 1. » Laws, v. oh. 11-13. 

L 



162 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

Aristotle condemns usury because it is the most 
extreme and dangerous form of ohrematistic ac- 
quisition, or the art of making money for its own 
sake. As we have seen above, in discussing the 
legitimacy of commerce, buying cheap and sell- 
ing dear was one form of chrematistic acquisition, 
which could only be justified by the presence 
of certain motives ; and usury, according to the 
philosopher, was a stUl more striking example of 
the same kind of acquisition, because it consisted 
IQ making money from money, which was thus 
employed for a function different from that for 
which it had been originally invented. ' Usury 
is most reasonably detested, as the increase of our 
forttme arises from the money itself, and not by 
employing it for the purpose for which it was 
/ intended. For it was devised for the sake of 
exchange, but usury multiphes it. And hence 
usury has received the name of tokos, or 
produce ; for whatever is produced is itself like 
its parents ; and usury is merely money bom of 
money ; so that of all means of money-making it 
is the most contrary to nature.' ^ We need not 
pause here to discuss the precise significance of 
Aristotle's conceptions on this subject, as they are 
to us not so much of importance in themselves, 
as because they suggested a basis for the treat- 
ment of usury to Aquinas and his followers.^ 

In Rome, as in Greece, the philosophers and 
moralists were unanimous in their condemnation 
of the practice of usury. Cicero condemns usury 
as being hateful to mankind, and makes Cato say 

* Aristotle, PoUUca, i. 10, 2 Clesuy, op. cit, p. 29. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTYx 163 

that it is on the same level of moral obliquity as 
murder ; and Seneca makes a point that became 
of some importance in the Middle Ages, namely, 
that usury is wrongful because it involves the 
selling of time.^ Plutarch develops the argument 
that money is sterile, and condemns the prac- 
tices of contemporary money-lenders as unjust.^ 
The teaching of the philosophers as to the unlaw- 
fulness of usury was reflected in the popular feel- 
ing of the time.^ 

§ 2. Usury in the Old Testament 

The question of usury therefore attracted con- 
siderable attention in the teaching and practice 
of pagan antiquity. It occupied an equally im- 
portant place in the Old Testament. In Exodus 
we find the first prohibition of usury : ' If thou 
lend money to any of my people being poor, thou 
shalt not be to him as a creditor, neither shall ye 
lay upon him usury.' * In Leviticus we read : 
' And if thy brother be waxen poor, and his hand 
f aQ with thee ; then thou must uphold him ; as 
a stranger and a sojourner shall he Mve with thee. 
Take thou no money of him or increase, but fear 
thy God that thy brother may Uve with thee. 
Thou shalt not give him thy money upon usury, 
nor give him victuals for increase.' ^ Deuteronomy 
lays down a wider prohibition : ' Thou shalt not 
lend upon usury to thy brother ; usury of money, 
usury of victuals, usury of anything that is lent 

'^ Cleary, <yp. dt,, p. 29. * De Viiando Aere AUeno. 

' Espinas, op. cit., pp. 81-2 ; Boscher, PoUtical Economy, a. 90. 
* Exod. ?xii. 25. " Lev. xxv. 35. 



164 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

upon usmy ; unto a foreigner thou mayest lend 
upon usury, but unto thy brother thou mayest not 
lend upon usury.' ^ It will be noticed that the 
first and second of these texts do not forbid usury 
except in the case of loans to the poor, and, if we 
had them alone to consider, we could conclude 
that loans to the rich or to business men were 
allowed. The last text, however, extends the 
prohibition to all loans to one's brother — an 
expression which was of importance in Christian 
times, as Christian writers maintained the uni- 
versal brotherhood of man. 

It is unnecessary for us to discuss the im- 
derlying considerations which prompted these 
ordinances. Dr. Cleary, who has studied the 
matter with great care, concludes that: 'The 
legislator was urged mostly by economic con- 
siderations. . . . The permission to extract usury 
from strangers — a permission which later writers, 
such as Maimonides, regarded as a command — 
clearly favours the view that the legislator was 
guided by economic principles. It is more diffi- 
cult to say whether he based his legislation on the 
principle that usury is intrinsically imjust — ^that 
is to say, imjust even when taken in moderation. 
There is really nothing in the texts quoted to 
enable us to decide. The universahty of the 
prohibition when there is question solely of Jews 
goes t6 show that usury as such was regarded as 
ttnjust ; whilst its permission as between Jew 
and Grentile favours the contradictory hjrpo- 
thesis.' ^ Modem Jewish thought is inclined to 

1 Deut. xxiii. 19. 2 Op. cit, pp. 5-6. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 165 

hold the view that these prohibitions were based 
upon the assumption that usury was intrinsically 
unjust, but that the taking of usury from the 
Grentiles was justified on the principle of com- 
pensation ; in other words, that Jews might exact 
usury from those who might exact it from them.^ 
It is at least certain that ustiry was regarded by 
the writers of the Old Testament as amongst the 
most terrible of sins.^ 

The general attitude of the Jews towards usury 
cannot be better explained than by quoting Dr. 
Cleary's final conclusion on the subject : ' It 
appears therefore that in the Old Testament 
usury was universally prohibited between Israel- 
ite and Israehte, whilst it was permitted between 
Israehte and GentUe. Furthermore, it seems im- 
possible to decide what was the nature of the 
obligations imposed — ^whether the prohibition sup- 
posed and ratified an already existing universal 
obhgation, in charity or justice, or merely im- 
posed a new obhgation in obedience, binding the 
consciences of men for economic or pohtical 
reasons. So, too, it seems impossible to decide 
absolutely whether the decrees were intended to 
possess eternal vaUdity ; the probabilities, how- 
ever, seem to f avoxu" very strongly the view that 
they were intended as mere economic regulations 
suited to the circumstances of the time. This 
does not, of course, decide the other question, 
whether, apart from such positive regulations, 

>• Jewish EncyclopoBdia, art. ' Usury.' 

^ Ezek. xviii. 13 ; Jer. xv. 10 ; Ps. xiv. 5, oix. 11, cxii. 5 ; Prov. 
xxviii. 8 ; Hes. xviii. 8 ; 2 Esd. v. 1 et aeq. 



166 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

there already existed an obligation arising from 
the natural law ; nor would the passing of the 
positive law into desuetude affect the existence 
of the other obligation.' ^ 

Before we pass from the consideration of the 
Old Testament to that of the New, we may men- 
tion that the taking of interest by Mohammedans 
is forbidden in the Koran. ^ 



§ 3. Usury in the First Twelve Centuries of 
Christianity. 

The only passage in the Gospels which bears 
directly on the question of usury is a verse of St. 
Luke, the correct reading of which is a matter of 
considerable difference of opinion.^ The Revised 
Version reads : ' But love your enemies, and do 
them good, and lend, never despairing {nihil 
desperantes) ; and your reward shall be great.' 
If this be the true reading of the verse, it does 
not touch the question of usury at all, as it is 
simply an exhortation to lend without worrying 
whether the debtor fail or not.* The more gen- 
erally received reading of this verse, however, 
is that adopted by the Vulgate, ' mutuum date, 
nihil inde sperantes ' — ' lend hoping for nothing 
thereby.' If this be the correct reading, the 
verse raises considerable difficulties of interpre- 
tation. It may simply mean, as Mastrofini in- 

1 Op. cit., pp. 17-18. 

' ii. 30. This prohibition is universally evaded. (Bosoher, PoUUcal 
Economy, a. 90.) » Luke vi. 35. 

* deary, op. cit., p. 33, following Knabenbaur. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 167 

terprets it, that all human actions should be 
performed, not in the hope of obtaining any 
material reward, but for the love of God and our 
neighbour ; or it may contain an actual precept 
or counsel relating to the particular subject of 
loans. If the latter be the correct interpretation, 
the further question arises whether the recom- 
mendation is to renounce merely the interest of 
a loan or the principal as well. We need not here 
engage on the details of the controversy thus 
aroused ; it is sufficient to say that it is the 
almost unanimous opinion of modern authorities 
that the verse recommends the renunciation of 
the principal as well as the interest ; and that, if 
this interpretation is correct, the recommendation 
is not a precept, but a cotmsel.^ Aquinas thought 
that the verse was a counsel as to the repayment 
of the principal, but a precept as to the payment 
of interest, and this opinion is probably correct.^ 
With the exception of this verse, there is not a 
single passage ia the Gospels which prohibits the 
taking of usury. 

We must now give some account of the teaching 
on usury which was laid down by the Fathers and 
early councils of the Church ; but at the same 
time we shall not attempt to treat this in an 
exhaustive way, because, although the early 
Christian teaching is of interest in itself, it exer- 
cised little or no influence upon the great philo- 
sophical treatment of the same subject by Aquinas 
and his followers, which is the principal subject 
to be discussed in these pages. The first thing we 

1 aeary, op. cit., p. 34, " Ibid., p. 35. 



168 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

must remark is that the prohibition of usury was 
not' included by the Council of Jerusalem amongst 
the ' necessary things ' imposed upon converts 
from the Gentiles.^ This would seem to show 
that the taking of usury was not regarded as un- 
lawful by the Apostles, who were at pains ex- 
pressly to forbid the commission of offences, the 
evil of which must have appeared plainly from 
the natural law — ^for instance, fornication. The 
Didache, which was used as a book of catechetical 
instruction for catechumens, does not specifically 
mention usury ; the forcing of the repayment 
of loans from the poor who are unable to pay is 
strongly reprobated ; but this is not so in the case 
of the rich.^ Clement of Alexandria expressly 
hmits his disapprobation of usury to the case of 
loans between brothers, whom he defines as 
'participators in the same word,' i.e. feUow- 
Christians ; and in any event it is clear that he 
regards it as sin against charity, but not against 
justice.^ 

TertuUian is one of the first of the Fathers to 
lay down positively that the taking of usury is 
sinful. He regards it as obviously wrong for 
Christians to exact usury on their loans, and 
interprets the passage of St. Luke, to which we 
have referred, as a precept against looking for 
even the repayment of the principal.* On the 
other hand, Cjrprian, writing in the same century, 
although he declaims eloquently and vigorously 
against the usurious practices of the clergy, does 

"■ Acts XV. 29. ^ Didache, oh. i. ; Cleary, op. cit, p. 39. 

' Stromata, ii. 18. * Ad Mardon, iv. 17. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 169 

not specifically express the opinion that the taking 
of usury is wrong in itseK.^ 

Thus, during the first three centuries of Christi- 
anity, there does not seem to have been, as far as 
we can now ascertain, any definite and general 
doctrine laid down on the subject of usury. In 
the year 305 or 306 a very important step forward 
was taken, when the Council of Elvira passed a 
decree against usury. This decree, as given by 
Ivo and Gratian, seems only to have appHed to 
usury on the part of the clergy, but as given by 
Mansi it afiEected the clergy and laity alike. 
' Should any cleric be found to have taken usury,' 
the latter version runs, ' let him be degraded and 
excommunicated. Moreover, if any layman shall 
be proved a usurer, and shall have promised, when 
corrected, to abstain from the practice, let him be 
pardoned. If, on the contrary, he perseveres in 
his evil-doing, he is to be excommunicated.' ^ 
Although the Council of Elvira was but a pro- 
vincial Council, its decrees are important, as 
they provided a model for later legislation. Dr. 
Cleary thinks that Mansi' s version of this decree 
is probably incorrect, and that, therefore, the 
Council only forbade usury on the part of the 
clergy. In any event, with this one possible and 
extremely doubtful exception, there was no con- 
cUiar legislation affecting the practice of usury 
on the part of the laity until the eighth century. 
Certain individual popes censured the taking of 
usury by laymen, and the Council of Nice expressed 

* he, Lapaia, oh. 5-6 ; Cleary, op. cit., pp. 42-3. > 

^ Gleary, op. dt., p. 43. 



170 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

the opinion that such a practice was contrary to 
Christ's teaching, but there is nowhere to be foiind 
an imperative and definite prohibition of the 
taking of usury except by the clergy.^ 

The inconclusive result of the Christian teaching 
up to the middle of the fourth century is well 
summarised by Dr. Cleary : ' Hitherto we have 
encountered mere prohibitions of usury with little 
or no attempt to assign a reason for them other 
than that of positive legislation. Most of the 
statements of these early patristic writers, as 
weU as possibly aU of the early Christian legis- 
lative enactments, deal solely with the practice 
of usury by the clergy ; stiU, there is sufficient 
evidence to show that in those days it was repro- 
bated even for the Christian laity, for the Didache 
and TertuUian clearly teach or presuppose its 
prohibition, while the oecumenical Council of 
Nice certainly presupposed its illegality for the 
laity, though it faUed to sustain its doctrinal 
presuppositions with corresponding ecclesiastical 
penalties. With the exception of some very vague 
statements by Cjrprian and Clement of Alexandria, 
we find no attempt to state the nature of the 
resulting obligation — ^that is to say, we are not 
told whether there is an obligation of obedience, 
of justice, or of charity. The prohibition indeed 
seems to be regarded as universal ; and it may 
very well be contended that for the cases the 
Fathers consider it was in fact universal — ^for the 
loans with which they are concerned, being neces- 
sitous, should be, in accordance with Christian 

1 Cleary, op. eit., pp. 44-8. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 171 

charity, gratuitous — even if speculatively usurious 
loans in general were not unjust.' ^ 

The middle of the fourth century marked the 
opening of a new period — ' a period when ora- 
torical denunciations are profuse, and when con- 
sequently philosophical speculation, though fairly 
active, is of too imaginative a character to be 
sufficiently definite.' ^ St. Basil's Homilies on the 
Fourteenth Psalm contain a violent denunciation 
of usury, the reasoning of which was repeated by 
St. Gregory of Nyssa ^ and St. Ambrose.* These 
three Fathers draw a terrible picture of the state 
of the poor debtor, who, harassed by his creditors, 
falls deeper and deeper into despair, xaitil he 
finally commits suicide, or has to seU his children 
into slavery. Usury was therefore condemned 
by these Fathers as a sin against charity ; the 
passage from St. Luke was looked on merely as 
a counsel in so far as it related to the repayment 
of the principal, but as a precept so far as it 
related to usury ; but the notion that usury was 
in its very essence a sin against justice does 
not appear to have arisen. The natural sterihty 
of money is referred to, but not developed ; and 
it is suggested, though not categorically stated, 
that usury may be taken from wealthy debtors.^ 

The other Fathers of the later period do not 
throw very much light on the question of how 
usury was regarded by the early Church. St. 
Hilary ^ and Jerome ' still base their objection 

* Op. dt, pp. 48-9. * deary, op. (At., p. 49. 

' Contra Usurarios. * De Tobia. * CSIeary, op. eit., p. 62. 

• In Ps. xiv. ' Ad Ezeoh. 



172 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

on tlie ground of its being an ofEence against 
charity ; and St. Augustine, though he would hke 
to make restitution of usury a duty, treats the 
matter from the same poiat of view.^ On the 
other hand, there are to be found patristic utter- 
ances in favour of the legaUty of usury, and 
episcopal approbations of civil codes which per- 
mitted it. 2 The civil law did not attempt to 
suppress usury, but simply to keep it within due 
bounds.^ The restdt of the patristic teaching 
therefore was on the whole unsatisfactory and 
inconclusive. ' Whilst patristic opinion,' says Dr. 
Cleary, ' is very pronounced in condemning usury, 
the condemnation is launched against it more 
because of its oppressiveness than for its intrinsic 
injustice. As Dr. Funk has pointed out, one 
can scarcely cite a single patristic opinion which 
can be said clearly to hold that usury is against 
justice, whilst there are, on the contrary, certain 
undercurrents of thought in many writers, and 
certain exphcit statements in others, which tend 
to show that the Fathers would not have been pre- 
pared to deal. so harshly with usurers, did usurers 
not treat their debtors so cruelly. ... Of keen 
philosophical analysis there is none. . . . On the 
whole, we find the teachings of the Fathers crude 
and undeveloped.' * 
The practical teaching with regard to the taking 

1 deary, op. eit, p. 56. ^ lUd., pp. 56-7. 

* Jwtinian Code, iv. 32. 

* Op. dt., pp. 57-9. On the patristic teaching on usnry, see Eapinas, 
op. cit., pp. 82-4 ; Bosoher, Political Economy, a. 90 ; Antoine, Gmirs 
d'Econonde soaiale, pp. 588 et seq. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 173 

of usury made an important advance in the eighth 
and ninth centuries, although the philosophical 
analysis of the subject did not develop any more 
fuUy. A capitulary canon made in 789 decreed 
' that each and all are forbidden to give anything 
on usurjT^ ' ; and a capitulary of 813 states that 
' not only should the Christian clergy not demand 
usury, laymen should not.' In 825 it was de- 
creed that the counts were to assist the bishops in 
their suppression of usury ; and in 850 the Synod 
of Ticinum bound usurers to restitution.^ The 
underlying principles of these enactments is as 
obscure as their meaning is plain and definite. 
There is not a single trace of the keen analysis 
with which Aquinas was later to illuminate and 
adorn the subject. 

§ 4. The, Mediceval Prohibition of Usury 

The tenth and eleventh centuries saw no 
advance in the teaching on usury. The twelfth 
century, however, ushered in a new era. ' Before 
that century controversy had been mostly con- 
fined to theologians, and treated theologically, 
with reference to God and the Bible, and only 
rarely with regard to economic considerations. 
After the twelfth century the discussion was 
conducted on a gradually broadening economic 
basis— appeals to the Fathers, canonists, philo- 
sophers, the jus divirlkm, the jus naturale, the 

^ These are but a few of the enactments of the period directed 
against usury (Cleary, 033. cit,, p. 61 ; Favre, Le prit A intkrU dams 
Vanci&me France). 



174 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

jus humanum, became the order of the day.' ^ 
Before we proceed to discuss the new philosophical 
or scholastic treatment of usury which was in- 
augurated for all practical purposes by Aquinas, 
we must briefly refer to the ecclesiastical legis- 
lation on the subject. 

.In 1139 the second Lateran Council issued a 
very strong declaration against usurers. ' We 
condemn that disgraceful and detestable rapacity, 
condemned aUke by human and divine law, by 
the Old and the New Testaments, that insati- 
able rapacity of usurers, whom we hereby cut off 
from aU ecclesiastical consolation; and we order 
that no archbishop, bishop, abbot, or cleric shall 
receive back usurers except with the very greatest 
caution, but that, on the contrary, usurers are to 
be regarded as infamous, and shall, if they do not 
repent, be deprived of Christian burial.' ^ It 
might be argued that this decree was aimed against 
immoderate or habitual usury, and not against 
usury in general, but aU doubt as regards the 
attitude of the Church was set at rest by a decree 
of the Lateran Council of 1179. This decree runs : 
' Since almost in every place the crime of usury 
has become so prevalent that many people give 
up all other business and become usurers, as if it 
were lawful, regarding not its prohibition in both 
Testaments, we ordain that manifest usurers shall 
not be admitted to communion, nor, if they die 
in their sins, be admitted to Christian burial, and 
that no priest shall accept their alms.' ^ Mean- 

1 Bohm-Bawerk, Capital and Imterest, p. 19. 

" Qeary, op. cit., p. 64. s ji^ 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 175 

while, Alexander m., having given much atten-" 
tion to the subject of usury, had come to the 
conclusion that it was a sin against justice. This 
recognition of the essential injustice of usury 
marked a turning-point in the history of the 
treatment of the subject ; and Alexander m. 
seems entitled to be designated the ' pioneer of its 
scientific study.' ^ Innocent in. followed Alex- 
ander in the opinion that usury was unjust in 
itself, and from his time forward there was but 
httle further disagreement upon the matter 
amongst the theologians.^ 

In 1274 Gregory x., in the Council of Lyons, 
ordained that no community, corporation, or 
individual should permit foreign usurers to hire 
houses, but that they should expel them from their 
territory; and the disobedient, if prelates, were 
to have their lands put tmder interdict, and, if 
laymen, to be visited by their ordinary with 
ecclesiastical censures.^ By a further canon he 
ordained that the wiUs of usurers who did not 
make restitution should be invalid.* This brought 
usury definitely within the jurisdiction of the 
ecclesiastical courts.^ In 1311 the Council of 
Vieime declared all secular legislation in favour 
of usury nuU and void, and branded as heresy 
the belief that usury was not sinful.^ The pre- 
cise extent and interpretation of this decree have 
given rise to a considerable amount of discussion,' 

1 aeary, op. cit., p. 65. ^ lUd., p. 68. 

3 Liber Sextus, v. 5, 1. * Ibid., o. 2. 

* Ashley, op. cit, vol. i. pt. i. p. 150. 

' Ckmentinamm, v. 5, 1. ' Cleary, op. cit., pp. 74-8. 



176 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

which need not detam ns here, because by that 
time the whole question of usury had come under 
the treatment of the great scholastic writers, 
whose teachbig is more particularly the subject 
matter of the present essay. 

Even as late as the first half of the thirteenth 
century there was no serious discussion of usury 
by the theologians. WiUiam of Paris, Alexander 
of Hales, and Albertus Magnus simply pronounced 
it sinful on account of the texts in the Old and 
New Testaments, which we have quoted above. ^ 
It was Aquinas who really put the teaching on 
usury upon the new foundation, which was des- 
tined to support it for so many hundred years, 
and which even at the present day appeals to 
many sympathetic and impartial inquirers. Mr. 
Lecky apologises for the obscurity of his accotmt 
of the argument of Aquinas, but adds that the 
confusion is chiefly the fault of the latter ; ^ but 
the fact that Mr. Lecky failed to grasp the meaning 
of the argument should not lead one to conclude 
that the argument itself was either confused or 
illogical. The fact that it for centuries remained 
the basis of the Catholic teaching on the subject 
is a sufficient proof that its inherent absurdity 
did not appear apparent to many students at least 
as gifted as Mr. Lecky. We shaU quote the article 
of Aquinas at some length, because it was uni- 
versally accepted by aU the theologians of the 
fourteenth and fifteenth centuries, with whose 
opinions we are concerned in this essay. To 

'- Jourdain, op. cit., p. 16. 

"* Bise and Influeiux of Rationalism in Europe, vol. ii. p. 261. 



THE EXCHANGE OP PROPERTY 177 

quote later writings is simply to repeat in different 
words the conclusions at which Aquinas arrived. ^ 

In answer to the question ' whether it is a sin' 
to take usury for money lent,' Aquinas replies : 
' To take usury for money lent is unjust in itself," 
because this is to seU what does not exist, and this 
evidently leads to inequaUty, which is contrary 
to justice. 

' In order to make this evident, we must observe 
that there are certain things the use of which con- 
sists in their consumption ; thus we consume wine 
when we use it for drink, and we consume wheat 
when we use it for food. Wherefore in such-like 
things the use of the thing must not be reckoned 
apart from the thing itself, and whoever is granted 
the use of the thing is granted the! thing itself; 
and for this reason to lend things of this kind is to 
transfer the ownership. Accordingly, if a man 
wanted to sell wine separately from the use of 
the wine, he would be selling the same thing 
twice, or he would be selhng what does not exist, 
wherefore he would evidently commit ^ sin of 
injustice. In like manner he commits an in- 
justice who lends wine or wheat, and asks for 
double payment, viz. one, the return of the thing 
in equal measure, the other, the price of the use, 
which is called usury. 

' On the other hand, there are other things the 
use of which does not consist in their consump- 
tion ; thus to use a house is to dweU in it, not to de- 
stroy it. Wherefore in such things both may be 
granted ; for instance, one man may hand over 

* Endemann, Stttdien, vol. i. p. 17. 
M 



178 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

to another the ownership of his house, while 
reserving to himself the use of it for a time, or, 
vice versa, he may grant the use of a house while 
retaining the ownership. For this reason a man 
may la-wfuUy make a charge for the use of his 
house, and, besides this, revendicate the house 
from the person to whom he has granted its use, 
as happens in renting and letting a house. 
■^ ' But money, according to the philosopher,^ 
was invented chiefly for the purpose of exchange ; 
and consequently the proper and principal use of 
money is its consumption or ahenation, whereby 
it is sunk in exchange. Hence it is by its very 
nature unlawful to take payment for the use of 
money lent, which payment is known as usury ; 
and, just as a man is boimd to restore other ill- 
gotten goods, so he is bound to restore the money 
;which he has taken in usury.' ^ 

The essential thing to notice in this explanation 
is that the contract of mutuum is shoAvn to be a 
sale. The distinction between things which are 
consumed in use {res fungihiles), and which are not 
consumed in use (res non fungihiles) was familiar 
to the civil lawyers ; but what they had never 
perceived was precisely what Aquinas perceived, 
namely, that the loan of a fungible thing was in 
fact not a loan at aU, but a sale, for the simple 
reason that the ownership in the thing passed. 
Once the transaction had been shown to be a sale, 
the principle of justice to be applied to it became 
obvious. As we have seen above, in treating of 
sales, the essential basis of justice in exchange was 

1 Eth., V. Pol. 1. ' n. ii. 78, 1. 



THE EXCHANGE OP PROPERTY 179 

the observance of aeqiMlitas between buyer and 
seller — ^in other words, the fixing of a just price. 
The contract of mutuum, however, was nothing 
else than a sale of fungibles, and therefore the 
just price in such a contract was the return of 
fungibles of the same value as those lent. If the 
particular fungible sold happened to be money, 
the estimation of the just price was a simple 
matter — it was the return of an amount of money 
of equal value. As money happened to be the 
universal measure of value, this simply meant the 
return of the same amount of money. Those who 
maintained that something additional might be 
claimed for the use of the money lost sight of the 
fact that the money was incapable of being used 
apart from its being consumed.^ To ask for 
payment for the sale of a thing which not only 
did not exist, but which was quite incapable of 
existence, was clearly to ask for something for 
nothing — which obviously offended against the 
first principles of commutative justice. ' He that 
is not bound to lend,' says Aquinas in another 
part of the same article, ' may accept repayment 
for what he has done, but he must not exact more. 
Now he is repaid according to equality of justice. 

^ Aquinas did not lose sight of the fact that money might, in certain 
cases, be used apart from being consumed — ^for instance, when it was 
not used as a means of exchange, but as an ornament. He gives the 
example of money being sewn up and sealed in a bag to prevent its 
being spent, and in this condition lent for any purpose. In this case, 
of course, the transaction would not be a mutuum, but a locaMo et 
cond/ucUo, and therefore a price could be charged for the use of the 
money {QiMestkmes Biapviatae de Mah, Q. xiii. art. iv. ad. 15, quoted 
in Oronin's Ethics, vol. ii. p. 332). 



180 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

if he is repaid as much as he lent, wherefore, if he 
exacts more for the usufruct of a thing which has 
no other use but the consumption of its substance, 
he exacts a price of something non-existent, and 
so his exaction is unjust.' ^ And in the next 
article the principle that mutuum is a sale appears 

^ equally clearly : ' Money cannot be sold for a 
greater sum than the amount lent, which has to 
be paid back.' ^ 

)£'" The difficulty which moderns find in under- 
standing this teaching, is that it is said to be based 
on the sterility of money. A moment's thought, 
however, wiU convince us that money is in fact 
sterUe until labour has been applied to it. In 
this sense money differs in its essence from a cow 
or a tree. A cow will produce calves, or a tree 
wOl produce fruit without the application of any 

' exertion by its owner ; but, whatever profit is 
derived from money, is derived from the use to 

I which it is put by the person who owns it. This 
is aU that the scholastics meant by the sterility 

'of money. They never thought of denying that 
' money, when properly used, was capable of bring- 
'ing its employer a profit ; but they emphatically 

1 n. ii. 78, 1, ad. 5. 

' n. ii. 78, 2, ad. 4. Biel distinguishes three kinds of exchange : of 
goods for goods, or barter ; of goods for money, or sale ; and of money 
for money ; and adds, ' In his contractibus . . . generahter justitia 
in hoc consistit quod fiant sine fraude, et servetur aequahtas sub- 
stantiae, qualitatis, quantitatis in oommutatis (op. cit., iv. xv. 1). 
Buridan says that usury is contrary to natural law 'ex conditione 
justitiae quae in aequalitate damni et luori consistit ; quoniam injustum 
eat pro re semel commutata pluries pretium reoipere' (In Lib. PoL, 
iv. 6). 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 181 

asserted that the profit was due to the labour, and 
not to the money. 

Antoninus of Florence clearly realised this : 
' Money is not profitable of itself alone, nor can 
it multiply itself, but it may become profitable 
through its employment by merchants ' ; ^ and 
Bernardine of Siennia says : ' Money has not 
simply the character of money, but it has beyond 
this a productive character, which we commonly 
call capital.' ^ ' What is money,' says Brants, ' if 
it is not a means of exchange, of which the em- 
ployment and preservation will give a profit, if 
he who possesses it is prudent, active, and intelli- 
gent ? If this money is well employed, it will 
become a capital, and one may derive a profit 
from it ; but this profit arises from the activity 
of him who uses it, and consequently this profit 
belongs to him — ^it is the fruit, the remuneration 
of his labour. . . . Did they (the scholastics) say 
that it was impossible to draw a profit from a sum 
of money ? No ; they admitted fully that one 
might de pecunia lucrari ; but this lucrum does 
not come from the pecunia, but from the appli- 
cation of labour to the sum.' ^ 

Therefore, if the borrower did not derive any 
profit from the loan, the sum lent had in fact been 
sterile, and obviously the just price of the loan 
was the return of the amount lent ; if, on the 
contrary, the borrower had made a profit from it, 
it was the reward of his labour, and not the fruit 
of the loan itself. To repay more than the sum 

' Quoted in Brants, op. dt., p. 134. * Ibid. 

^ Brants, op. cit., pp. 133-5 ; Nider, De Cont. Merc. iii. 16. 



182 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

lent would therefore be to make a payment to 
one person for the labour of another.^ The ex- 
action of usury was therefore the exploitation of 
another man's exertion.^ 

It is interesting to notice how closely the rules 
applying in the case of sales were applied to usury. 
The raising of the price of a loan on account of 
some special benefit derived from it by the borrower 
is precisely analogous to raising the sale price of 
an object because it is of some special individual 
utility to the buyer. On the other hand, as we 
shall see further down, any special damage 
suffered by the lender was a sufficient reason for 
exacting something over and above the amount 
lent ; this was precisely the rule that applied in 
the case of sales, when the seller suffered any 
special damage from parting with the object sold. 
Thus the analogy between sales and loans was 
complete at every point. In both, equahty of 
sacrifice was the test of justice. 
^ " Nor could it be suggested that the delay in the 
repayment of the loan was a reason for increas- 
ing the amount to be repaid, because this reaUy 
amounted to a sale of time, which, of its nature, 
^ould not be owned.® 

^ Qerson, De Cont., iv. 16. 

2 Neumann, when he says that ' it was sinful to recompense the use 
of capital belonging to another ' {Ckschichte des Wiuihe,rs in DeutschUmd, 
p. 25), seems to miss the whole point of the discussion. The teaching 
of the canonists on rents and partnership shows clearly that the 
owner of capital might draw a profit from another's labour, and the 
central point of the usury teaching was that money which has been 
lent, and employed so as to produce a profit by the borrower, belongs 
not ' to another,' but to the very man who employed it, namely, the 
borrower. * Rambaud, op. cit, p. 63 ; Aquinas (?), De Vsuris, i. 4. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 183 

The scholastic teaching, then, on the subject was 
quite plain and unambiguous. Usury, or the ' 
payment of a price for the use of a sum lent in 
addition to the repayment of the sum itself, was 
in aU cases prohibited. The fact that the payment 
demanded was moderate was irrelevant ; there 
could be no question of the reasonableness of the 
amount of an essentially unjust payment.^ Nor 
was the payment of usiiry rendered just because 
the loan was for a productive purpose — in other 
words, a commercial loan. Certain writers have 
maintained that in this case usury was toler- 
ated ; ^ but they can easily be refuted. As we 
have seen above, mutuum was essentially a sale, 
and, therefore, no additional price could be 
charged because of some special individual ad- 
vantage enjoyed by the buyer (or borrower). It 
was quite impossible to distinguish, according 
to the scholastic teaching, between taking an 
additional payment because the lender made 
a profit by using the loan wisely, and taking it 
because the borrower was in great distress, and 
therefore derived a greater advantage from the_ 
loan than a person in easier circumstances. The 
erroneous notion that loans for productive pur- 
poses were entitled to any special treatment 
was finally dispelled in 1745 by an encyclical 
of Benedict xiv.^ 

' Jourdain, op. cit., p. 35. 

^ E.g. P6rin, Premiere Principes d'Economie 'politique, p. 305 ; daudio 
Jannet, Ca/pital Speculation et Finance, p. 83 ; De Metz-Noblat, Lois 
iconomiques, p. 293. 

" Bambaud, op. cit, p. 69. 



184 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

§ 5. Extrinsic Titles 

'' Usury, therefore, was prohibited in all cases. 

Many people at the present day think that the 

prohibition of usury was the same thing as the 

prohibition of interest. There could not be a 

Weater mistake. While usury \yas in all circum- 

, stances condemned, interest was in every case 

'{allowed. The justification of interest rested on 

precisely the same ground as the prohibition of 

usury, namely, the observance of the equahty 

of commutative justice. It was unjust that a 

greater price should be paid for the loan of a sum 

of money than the amount lent ; but it was no 

less unjust that the lender should find himself 

in a worse position because of his having made the 

loan. In other words, the consideration for the 

loan could not be increased because of any special 

benefit which it conferred on the borrower, but 

it could be increased on account of any special 

damage suffered by the lender — ^precisely the 

same ride as we have seen apphed in the case 

!' of sales. The borrower must, in addition to 
the repayment of the loan, indemnify the lender 
for any damage he had suffered. The measure 
of the damage was the difference between the 
lender's condition before the loan was made and 
after it had been repaid — ^in other words, he was 
entitled to compensation for the difference in 

.,^his condition occasioned by the transaction — id 
quod interest. 

Before we discuss interest properly so called, 
we must say a word about another analogous 



THE EXCHANGE OP PROPERTY 185 

but not identical title of compensation, namely, 
the 'poena conventionalis. It was a very general ' 
practice, about the legitimacy of which the scho- 
lastics do not seem to have had any doubt, to 
attach to the original contract of loan an agree- 
ment that a penalty should be paid in case of 
default in the repayment of the loan at the stipu- 
lated time.^ The justice of the poena conven- 
tionalis was recognised by Alexander of Hales,^ 
and by Duns Scotus, who gives a typical form of 
the stipulation as follows : ' I have need of my 
money for commerce, but shall lend it to you till 
a certain day on the condition that, if you do not 
repay it on that day, you shaU pay me afterwards 
a certain sum in addition, since I shall suffer much 
injury through your delay.' ^ The poena con- 
ventionalis must not be confused with either of 
the titles damnum emergens or lucrum cessans, 
which we are about to discuss ; it was distin- 
guished from the former by being based upon a 
presumed injury, whereas the injury in damnum 
emergens must be proved ; and for the latter 
because the damage must be presumed to have 
occurred after the expiration of the loan period, 
whereas in lucrum cessans the damage was pre- 
sumed to have occurred during the currency of 
the loan period. The important thing to remem- 
ber is that these titles were reaUy distract.* The 
essentials of a poena conventionalis were, stipu- 
lation from the first day of the loan, presumption 

''■ Ashley, op. cit, vol. i. pt. i. p. 399. 

* Biel, op. cit., iv. 15, 11. * Cleary, op. dt., p. 93. 

* Ibid., p. 95. 



186 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

of damage, and attachment to a loan whicli was 
itself gratuitous.^ The Summa Astesarm clearly 
maintained the distinction between the two titles 
of compensation,^ as also did the Summa ATigeUca.^ 
■■ The first thing to be noted on passing from the 
poena conventionalis to interest proper is that the 
latter ground of compensation was generally 
divided into two kinds, damnum emergens and 
lucrum cessans. The former included all cases 
where the lender had incurred an actual loss by 
reason of his having made the loan ; whereas the 
latter included aU cases where the lender, by 
\parting with his money, had lost the opportunity 
of making a profit. This distinction was made 
at least as early as the middle of the thirteenth 
century, and was always adopted by later writers.* 
The title damnum emergens never presented any 
serious difficulty. It was recognised by Albertus 
Magnus,'' and laid down so clearly by Aquinas 
that it was not afterwards questioned : ' A lender 
may without sin enter an agreement with the 
borrower for compensation for the loss he incurs 
of something he ought to have, for this is not to 
sell the use of money, but to avoid a loss. It 
may also happen that the borrower avoids a 
greater loss than the lender incurs, wherefore 
the borrower may repay the lender with what he 
lias gained.' ^ The usual example given to Dlus- 
trate how damnum emergens might arise, was the 

1 deary, op. cit., p. 94. 

* Endemann, Studien, vol. i. p. 20. * ooxl. 

* Ashley, op. cit, vol. i. pt. ii. p. 399. 

" Boscher, Oesdiichte, p. 27. • n. ii. 78, 2, ad. 1. 



THE EXCHANGE OP PROPEETY 187 

case of the lender being obliged, on account of 
the failure of the borrower, to borrow money 
himself at usury. ^ 

Closely allied to the title of damnum emergens 
was that of lucrum cessans. According to some 
writers, the latter was the only true interest. 
Dr. Cleary quotes some thirteenth-century docu- 
ments in which a clear distinction is made be- 
tween damnum and interesse ; ^ and it seems to 
have been the common custom in Germany at a 
later date to distinguish between interesse and 
schaden.^ Although the division between these 
two titles was very indefinite, they did not meet 
recognition with equal readiness; the title dam-- 
num emergens was universally admitted by all 
authorities ; while that of lucrum cessans was but 
gradually admitted, and hedged round with many 
hmitations.* ^■ 

The first clear recognition of the title lucrum 
cessans occurs in a letter from Alexander m., 
written in 1176, and addressed to the Archbishop 
of Genoa : ' You teU us that it often happens 
in your city that people buy pepper and cumamon 
and other wares, at the time worth not more than 
five pounds, promising those from whom they 

1 Ashley, op. cit., vol. i. pt. i. p. 400. ^ Op. cit., p. 95. 

' Ashley, op. cit., vol. i. pt. ii. p. 401. 

* Cleary, op. cit., p. 98 ; Endemann, Studien, vol. ii. p. 279 ; Bartolus 
and Baldus said that damnum emergena and lucrum cessans were 
divided by a very narrow line, and that it was often difficult to dis- 
tinguish between them. They suggested that the terms interesse 
proximum and interesse remotum would be more satisfactory, but 
they were not followed by other writers (Endemann, Studien, vol. ii. 
pp. 269-70). 



188 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

received them six pounds at an appointed time. 
Though contracts of this kind and under such a 
form cannot strictly be called usurious, yet, 
nevertheless, the vendors incur guilt, unless they 
are really doubtful whether the wares might be 
worth more or less at the time of payment. Your 
citizens will do well for their own salvation to 
cease from such contracts.' ^ As Dr. Cleary 
points out, the trader is held by this decision to 
be entitled to a recompense on account of a prob- 
able loss of profit, and the decision consequently 
amounts to a recognition of the title lucrum 
cessans.^ The title is also recognised by Scotus 
and Hostiensis.^ 

The attitude of Aquinas to the admission of 
lucrum cessans is obscure. In the article on 
usury he expressly states that ' the lender cannot 
enter an agreement for compensation through the 
fact that he makes no profit out of his money, 
because he must not sell that which he has not 
yet, and may be prevented in many ways from 
having.' * Two comments must be made on this 
passage ; first, that it only refers to making a 
stipulation in advance for compensation for profit 
lost, and does not condemn the actual payment of 
compensation ; ^ second, that the point is made 
that the probabiHty of gaining a profit on money 
is so problematical as to make it unsaleable. As 
Ashley points out, the latter consideration was 
peculiarly important at the time when the Summa 

1 Deor. Greg. v. 5, 6. " Op. cit., p. 67. 

* Ibid., p. 99. « n. ii. 78, 2, ad. 1. 

^ Bambaud, op. cit., p. 67. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 189 

was composed ; and, when in the course of the 
following two centuries the opportunities for 
reasonably safe and profitable business invest- 
ments increased, the great theologians conceived 
that they were following the real thought of 
Aquinas by giving to this explanation a pure 
contem'poraTiea expositio. The argument in favour 
of this construction is strengthened by a reference 
to the article of the Summa dealing with restitu- 
tion,^ where it is pointed out that a man may 
suffer in two ways — first, by being deprived of what 
he actually has, and, second, by being prevented 
from obtaining what he was on his way to obtain. 
In the former case an equivalent must always be 
restored, but in the latter it is not necessary to 
make good an equivalent, ' because to have a thing 
virtually is less than to have it actually, and to 
be on the way to obtain a thing is to have it merely 
virtually or potentially, and so, were he to be 
indemnified by receiving the thing actually, he 
would be paid, not the exact value taken from 
him, but more, and this is not necessary for salva- 
tion. However, he is bound to make some com- 
pensation according to the condition of persons 
and things.' Later in the same article we are 
told that ' he that has money has the profit not 
actually, but only virtually ; and it may be 
hindered in many ways.' ^ It seems quite clear- 
from these passages that Aquinas admitted the 
right to compensation for a profit which the lender 
was hindered from making on account of the loan ; 
but that, in the circumstances of the time, the 

» n. ii. 62, 4. * Ihid., ad. 1 and 2. 



190 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

probability of making such a profit was so remote 
that it could not be made the basis of pecuniary 
compensation. The probability of there being a 
lucrum cessans was thought smaU, but the justice 
of its reward, if it did in fact exist, was admitted. 
This interpretation steadily gained ground 
amongst succeeding writers ; so that, in spite of 
some lingering opposition, the justice of the title 
lucrum cessans was practically universally ad- 
mitted by the theologians of the fifteenth century.'- 
Of course the burden of proving that an oppor- 
tunity for profitable investment had been really 
lost was on the lender, but this onus was suffi- 
ciently discharged if the probability of such a 
loss were established. In the fifteenth century, 
with the expansion of commerce, it came to be 
generally recognised that such a probability could 
be presumed in the case of the merchant or trader.^ 
The final condition of this development of the 
teaching on lucrum cessans is thus stated by 
Ashley : ^ ' Any merchant, or indeed any person 
! in a trading centre where there were opportunities 
I of business investment (outside money-lending 
'iitself) could, with a perfectly clear conscience, 
and without any fear of molestation, contract to 
receive periodical interest from the person to 
whom he lent money ; 'provided only that he first 
lent it to him gratuitously, for a period that might 
be made very short, so that technically the pay- 

1 Ashley, op. cit., p. 99. Imorvm cessans was defined by Navarrus 
as ' amissio facta a oreditore per pecuniam sibi non redditam ' (Bnde- 
mann, Studiem, vol. ii. p. 279). 

* Ashley, op. cit., vol. i. pt. ii. p. 402. » Ibid. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 191 

ment would not be reward for the use, but com- 
pensation for the non-return of the money.' At 
a later period than that of which we are treating 
in the present essay the short gratuitous period 
could be dispensed with, but until the end of the 
fifteenth century it seems to have been considered 
essential. 1 

Of course the amount paid in respect of lucrum 
cessans must be reasonable in regard to the loss 
of opportunity actually experienced; 'Lenders,' 
says Buridan, ' must not take by way of lucrum 
cessans more than they would have actually made 
by commerce or in exchange ' ; ^ and Ambrosius 
de Vignate explains that compensation must only 
be made for ' the time and just interesse of the lost 
gain, which must be certain and proximate.' ^ 

There was another title on account of which 
more than the amount of the loan could be re- 
covered, namely, periculum sortis. In one sense- 
it was a contradiction in terms to speak of the 
element of risk in connection with usury, because 
from its very definition usury was gain without 
risk as opposed to profit from a trading partner- 
ship, which, as we shall see presently, consisted 
of gain coupled with the risk of loss. It could 
not be lost sight of, however, that in fact there 
might be a risk of the loan^ not being repaid 
through the insolvency of the borrower, or some 
other cause, and the question arose whether the 
lender could justly claim any compensation for 

1 Ashley, op. cit, vol. i. pt. ii. p. 402 ; Endemann, Studiem, vol. ii. 
pp. 253-4 ; Cleary, op. cit., p. 100. 
* Eth., iv. 6. ' De Umris, c. la 



192 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

the undertaking of this risk. ' Regarded as an 
extrinsic title, risk of losing the principalis con- 
nected with the contract of mutuum, and entitles 
the lender to some compensation for running ihe 
risk of losing his capital in order to oblige a 
possibly insolvent debtor. The greater the danger 
of insolvency, the greater naturally would be the 
charge. The contract was indifferent to the obr 
jecfc of the loan ; it mattered not whether it was 
intended for commerce or consumption ; it was 
no less indifferent to profit on the part of the 
borrower ; it took account simply of the latter's 
abihty to pay, and made its charge accordingly. 
It resembled consequently the contracts made by 
insurance companies, wherein there is a readi- 
ness to risk the capital sum for a certain rate 
of payment ; the only difference was that the 
probabilities charged for were not so much the 
likelihood of having to pay, as the likelihood 
of not receiving back.' ^ 

We have referred above, when dealing with the 
legitimacy of commercial profits, to the difl&culty 
which was felt in admitting the justice of com- 
pensation for risk, on account of the Gregorian 
Decretal on the subject. The same decree gave 
rise to the same difficulty in connection with the 
justification of a recompense for periculum sortis. 
There was a serious dispute about the actual 
wording of the decree, and even those who agreed 
as to its wording differed as to its interpretation.^ 
The justice of the title was, however, admitted by 
Scotus, who said that it was lawful to stipulate 

1 deary, op. ciu, p. 115. 2 Ibid. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 193 

for recompense when both the principal and 
surplus were in danger of being lost ^ ; by Car- 
letus ; 2 and by Nider.^ The question, however, 
was stiU hotly disputed at the end of the fifteenth 
century, and was finally settled in favour of the 
admission of the title as late as 1645.* 



§ 6. Other Cases in which more than the Loan 
could he repaid 

We have now discussed the extrinsic titles — 
poena conventionalis, damnum emergens, lucrum 
cessans, and periculum sortis. There were other 
grounds also, which cannot be reduced to the 
classification of extrinsic titles, on which more 
than the amount of the loan might be justly 
returned to the lender. In the fitrst place, the 
lender might justly receive anything that the 
borrower chose to pay over and above the loan, 
voluntarily as a token of gratitude. ' Repay- 
ment for a favour may be done in two ways,' says 
Aquinas. ' In one way, as a debt of justice ; and 
to such a debt a man may be boun,d by a fixed 
contract ; and its amount is measured according 
to the favour received. Wherefore the borrower 
of money, or any such thing the use of which is its 
consumption, is not bound to repay more than he 
received in loan ; and consequently it is against 
justice if he is obliged to pay back more. In 
another way a man's obhgation to repayment for 
favour received is based on a debt of friendship, 

' Cleary, op. cit., p. 117. ^ Smnma Angelica Usura, i. 38. 

8 De C<mt. Merc, m. 15. * Cleary, op. cit., p. 117. 

N 






194 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

and the nature of this debt depends more on the 
feeling with which the favotir was conferred than 
on the question of the favour itseM. This debt 
does not carry with it a civil obligation, involving 
a kind of necessity that would exclude the spon- 
taneous nature of such a repayment.' ^ 
r* It was also clearly understood that it was not 
wrongful to borrow at usviry under certain con- 
ditions. In such cases the lender might commit 
usury in receiving, but the borrower would not 
commit usury in paying an amount greater than 
the sum lent. It was necessary, however, in 
order that borrowing at usury might be justified, 
that the borrower should be animated by some 
good motive, such as the relief of his own or 
another's need. The whole question was settled 
once and for all by Aquinas : ' It is by no means 
lawftil to induce a man to sin, yet it is lawful to 
make use of another's sin for a good end, since even 
God uses aU sin for some good, since He draws 
some good from every evil. . . . Accordingly it 
is by no means lawful to induce a man to lend 
under a condition of usury ; yet it is lawful to 
borrow for usury from a man who is ready to do 
so, and is a usurer by profession, provided that 
the borrower have a good end in view, such as the 
rehef of his own or another's need. ... He who 
borrows for usury does not consent to the usurer's 
^ sin, but malces use of it. Nor is it the usui^r's 
acceptance of usury that pleases him, but his 
lending, which is good.' ^ 

We should mention here the monies pietatis, 

1 n. ii. 78j 2, ad. 2, « n. ii. 78, 4. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 195 

which occupied a prominent place among the 
credit-giving agencies of the later Middle Ages, 
although it is difficult to say whether their methods 
were examples of or exceptions to the doctrines 
forbidding usury. These institutions were formed 
on the model of the monies jirofani, the system of 
pubhc debt resorted to by many Italian States. 
Starting in the middle of the twelfth century, ^ 
the Italian States had recourse to forced loans 
in order to raise reserves for extraordinary ne- 
cessities, and, in order to prevent the growth of 
disaffection among the citizens, an annual per- 
centage on such loans was paid. A fund raised 
by such means was generally called a mons or heap. 
The propriety of the payment of this percentage 
was warmly contested during the fourteenth and 
fifteenth centuries — the Dominicans and Francis- 
cans defending it, and the Augustinians attacking 
it. But its justification was not difficult. In the 
first place, the loans were generally, if not uni- 
versally, forced, and therefore the payment of 
interest on them was purely voluntary. As we 
have seen, Aquinas was quite clear as to the 
lawfulness of such a voluntary payment. In 
the second place, the lenders were almost invari- 
ably members of the trading commimity, who were 
the very people in whose favour a recompense for 
lucrum cessans would be allowed.^ Laurentius de 
Rodulphis argued in favour of the justice of these 
State loans, and contended that the bondholders 
were entitled to sell their rights, but advised good 

^ Endemann, Siudien, voL i. p. 433. 
2 Ashley, op. cit., vol. i. pt. i. p. 448. 



196 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

Christians to abstain from the practice of a right 
about the justice of which theologians were ia 
such disagreement ^ ; and Antoninus of Florence, 
who was in general so strict on the subject of usury, 
took the same view.^ 

It was probably the example of these State loans, 
or monies profani, that suggested to the Francis- 
cans the possibility of creating an organisation 
to provide credit facilities for poor borrowers, 
which was in many ways analogous to the modem 
co-operative credit banks. Prior to the middle 
of the fifteenth century, when this experiment 
was initiated, there had been various attempts by 
the State to provide credit f acUities for the poor, 
but these need not detain us here, as they did not 
come to anything.^ The first of the monies pie- 
tails was founded at Orvieto by the Franciscans in 
1462, and after that year they spread rapidly.* 
The monies, although their aim was exclusively 
philanthropic, found themselves obhged to make 
a small charge to defray their working expenses, 
and, although one would think that this could be 
amply justified by the title of damnum emergens, 
it provoked a violent attack by the Dominicans. 
The principal antagonist of the monies pietatis 
was Thomas da Vio, who wrote a special treatise 
on the subject, in which he made the point that 

1 De Usuria. ^ Ashley, op. df., p. 449. 

* Cleary, op. eit., p. 108 ; Brants, op. eit., p. 159. 

* Peragia, 1467 ; Viterbo, 1472 ; Sevona, 1472 ; Assisi, 1485 ; 
Mantua, 1486 ; Cesana and Parma, 1488 ; Interamna and Lucca, 
1489 ; Verona, 1490 ; Padua, 1491, etc. (Endemann, Studien, vol. i. 
p. 463). 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 197 

the monies charged interest from the very begin- 
ning of the loan, which was a contradiction of all 
the previous teaching on interest.^ 

The general feeMng of the Church, however, was 
in favour of the monies. It was felt that, if the 
poor must borrow, it was better that they should 
borrow at a low rate of interest from philanthropic 
institutions than at an extortionate rate from 
usurers ; several monies were estabUshed under 
the direct protection of the Popes ; ^ and finally, 
in 1615, the Lateran Council gave an authori- 
tative judgment in favour of the monies. This 
decree contains an excellent definition of usury 
as it had come to be accepted at that date : ' Usury 
is when gain is sought to be acquired from the use 
of a thing, not fruitful in itself, without labour, 
expense, or risk on the part of the lender.' ^ 

It was generally admitted by the theologians 
that the taking of usury might be permitted by 
the civil authorities, although it was insisted that 
acting in accordance with this permission did not 
absolve the conscience of the usurer. Albertus 
Magnus conceded that ' although usury is contrary 
to the perfection of Christian laws, it is at least 
not contrary to civil interests ' ; * and Aquinas 
also justified the toleration of usury by the State : 
' Human laws leave certain things unpunished, 
on account of the condition of those who are 
imperfect, and who would be deprived of many 
advantages if all sins were strictly forbidden 

I De Monte PieteUis. * Cleary, op. cit., p. 111. 

8 Ashley, op. cit, vol. i. pt. ii. p. 461. 

* Bambaud, op. cit., p. 65 ; Espinas, op. cit., p. 103. 



198 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

and punisliments appointed for them. Wherefore 
human law has permitted usury, not that it looks 
upon usury as harmonising with justice, but lest 
the advantage of many should be hindered.' ^ 
Although this opinion was controverted by 
i^gidius Romanus,^ it was generally accepted 
by later writers. Thus Gerson says that ' the 
civil law, when it tolerates usury in some cases, 
must not be said to be always contrary to the law 
of God or the Church. The civil legislator, acting 
in the manner of a wise doctor, tolerates lesser 
evils that greater ones may be avoided. It is 
obviously less of an evU that shght usiiry should 
be permitted for the relief of want, than that men 
should be driven by their want to rob or steal, 
or to seU their goods at an unfairly low price.' ^ 
Bm-idan explains that the attitude of the State 
towards usury must never be more than one of 
toleration ; it must not actively approve of usury, 
but it may tacitly refuse to punish it.* 

§ 7. The Justice of Unearned Income 

Many modem socialists — ' Christian ' and other- 
wise — ^have asserted that the teaching of the 
Church on usury was a pronouncement in favoxir 
of the unproductivity of capital.^ Thus RudoK 
Meyer, one of the most distinguished of ' Christian 
socialists,' has argued that if one recognises the 
productivity of land or stock, one must also recog- 

1 n. iL 78, 1, ad. 3. « De Beg. Pnn., ii. 3, 11. 

» De Coni., u. 17. * Qvae^, swper. Lib. Eth., iv. 6. 

' Ashley, op. cit,, voL i. pt. ii. p. 427. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 199 

nise the productivity of money, and that there- 
fore the Church, in denying the productivity of the 
latter, would be logically driven to deny the pro- 
ductivity of the former.^ Anton Menger expresses 
the same opinion : ' There is not the least reason 
for attacking from the moral and religious stand- 
points loans at interest and usury more than any 
other form of unearned income. If one questions 
the legitimacy of loans at interest, one must 
equally condemn as inadmissible the other forms 
of profit from capital and lands, and particularly 
the feudal institutions of the Middle Ages. . . . 
It would have been but a logical consequence for 
the Church to have condemned aU forms of un- 
earned revenue.' ^ 

No such conclusion, however, can be properly 
drawn from the mediaeval teaching. The whole 
discussion on usury turned on the distinction 
which was drawn between things of which the use 
could be transferred without the ownership, and 
things of which the use could not be so transferred. 
In the former category were placed aU things 
which could be used, either by way of enjoyment 
or employment for productive purposes, without 
being destroyed in the process ; and in the latter 
all things of which the use or employment involved 
the destruction. 

With regard to income derived from the former, 
no difficulty was ever felt ; a farm or a house 
might be let at a rent without any question, the 

^ Der KajntaUsmus fin de sitde, p. 29. 

* Das Becht auf den Arbeiteratrag. See the Abb6 HohofE in Dhrno- 
oraUe CMtienne, Sept. 1898, p. 284. 



200 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

return received being universally regarded as one 
of the legitimate fruits of the ownership of the 
thing. With regard to the latter, however, a 
difficiilty did arise, because it was felt that a so- 
called loan of such goods was, when analysed, 
in reality a sale, and that therefore any increase 
which the goods produced was in reality the 
property, not of the lender, but of the borrower. 
That money was in all cases sterile was never 
suggested ; on the contrary, it was admitted that 
it might produce a profit if wisely and prudently 
employed in industry or commerce ; but it was 
felt that such an increase, when it took place, was 
the rightful property of the owner of the money. 
But when money was lent, the owner of this 
money was the borrower, and therefore, when 
money which was lent was employed in such a 
way as to produce a profit, that profit belonged to 
the borrower, not the lender. In this way the 
schoolmen were strictly logical ; they fully ad- 
mitted that wealth cotild produce wealth ; but 
they insisted that that additional wealth should 
accrue to the owner of the wealth that produced it. 
The fact is, as Bohm-Bawerk has pointed out, 
that the question of the productivity of capital 
was never discussed by the mediaeval schoolmen, 
for the simple reason that it was so obvious. The 
justice of receiving an income from an infungible 
thing which was temporarily lent by its owner, 
was discussed and supported ; but the justice of 
the owner of such a thing receiving an income from 
the thing so long as it remained in his own pos- 
session was never discussed, because it was uni- 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 201 

versally admitted.^ It is perfectly correct to say 
that the problems which have perplexed modern 
writers as to the justice of receiving an unearned 
income from one's property never occurred to 
the scholastics ; such problems can only arise 
when the institution of private property comes 
to be questioned ; and private property was 
the keystone of the whole scholastic economic 
conception. In other words, the justice of a 
reward for capital was admitted because it was 
unquestioned. 

The question that caused difficulty was whether 
money could be considered a form of capital. At 
the present day, when the opportunities of in- 
dustrial investment are wider than they ever 
were before, the principal use to which money is 
put is the financing of industrial enterprises ; but 
in the Middle Ages this was not the case, precisely 
because tiie opportunities of profitable investment 
were so few. This is the reason why the medi- 
aeval writers did not find it necessary to discuss in 
detail the rights of the owner of money who used 
it for productive purposes. But of the justice of 
a profit being reaped when money was actually 
so employed there was no doubt at all. As we 
have seen, the borrower of a sum of money might 
reap a profit from its wise employment; there 
was no question about the justice of taking such 
a profit ; and the only matter in dispute was 
whether that profit should belong to the borrower 
or the lender of the money. This dispute was 
decided in favour of the borrower on the ground 

"■ Gapital and Interest, p. 39. 



202 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

that, according to the true nature of the contract 
of mutuum, the money was his property. It was, 
therefore, never doubted that even money might 
produce a profit for its owner. The only differ- 
ence between infungible goods and money was 
that, in the case of the former, the use might be 
transferred apart from the property, whereas, 
in the case of the latter, it could not be so 
transferred. 

The recognition of the title lucrum cessans as a 
grovmd for remuneration clearly implies the recog- 
nition of the legitimacy of the owner of money 
deriving a profit from its use ; and the slowness 
of the scholastics to admit this title was pre- 
cisely because of the rarity of opportunities for 
so employing money in the earher Middle Ages. 
The nature of capital was clearly understood ; 
but the possibihty of money constituting capital 
arose only with the extension of commerce and 
the growth of profitable investments. Those 
scholastics who strove to abolish or to limit 
the recognition of lucrum cessans as a ground 
for remuneration did not deny the productivity 
of capital, but simply thought the money had 
not at that time acquired the charsicteristics of 
capital. '^ 

If there were any doubt about the fact that the 
scholastics recognised the legitimacy of unearned 
income, it would be dispelled by an imderstanding 
of their teaching on rents and partnership, in 
the former of which they distinctly acknowledged 
the right to draw an unearned income from one's 

^ See Ashley, op. dt., vol. i. pt. ii. pp. 434-9. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 203 

land, and in the latter of which they acknowledged 
the same right in regard to one's money. ^ 



§ 8. Rent Charges 

There was never any difficulty about admitting 
the justice of receiving a rent from a tenant in 
occupation of one's lands, because land was under- 
stood to be essentially a thing of which the use 
could be sold apart from the ownership ; and it 
was also recognised that the recipient of such a 
rent might seU his right to a third party, who could 
then demand the rent from the tenant. When 
this was admitted it was but a small step to ad- 
mit the right of the owner of land to create a 
rent in favour of another person in consideration 
for some payment. The distinctions between a 
census reservativus, or a rent estabUshed when the 
possession of land was actually transferred to a 
tenant, and a census constitutivus, or a rent created 
upon property remaining in the possession of the 
payer, did not become the subject of discussion 
or difficulty until the sixteenth century.^ The 
legitimacy of rent charges does not seem to have 
been questioned by the theologians ; the best 
proof of this being the absence of controversy 
about them in a period when they were undoubtedly 
very common, especially in Germany.^ Langen- 

^ On this discussion see Ashley, Economic History, vol, i. pt. ii. 
pp. 427 et seq. ; Rambaud, Histoire, pp. 57 et seq. ; Eunk, Zins und 
Wucher ; Arnold, Zur OescMchte des Eigenthums, pp. 92 et seq. ; Bohm- 
Bawerk, Capitai and Interest (Eng. trans.), pp. 1-39. 

2 Ashley, 033. cU., vol. i. pt. ii. p. 409. 

' Endemann, Stvdien, vol. ii. p. 104. 



204 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

stein, whose opinion on the subject was followed 
by many later writers,^ thought that the receipt 
of income from rent charges was perfectly justifi- 
able, when the object was to secure a provision 
for old age, or to provide an income for persons 
engaged in the services of Church or State, but 
that it was unjustifiable if it was intended to 
enable nobles to live in luxurious idleness, or 
plebeians to desert honest toil. It is obvious that 
Langenstein did not regard rent charges as wrong- 
ful in themselves, but simply as being the possible 
occasions of wrong. ^ 

In the fifteenth century definite pronounce- 
ments on rent charges were made by the Popes. 
A large part of the revenue of ecclesiastical bodies 
consisted of rent charges, and in 1425 several 
persons in the diocese of Breslau refused to pay 
the rents they owed to their clergy on the ground 
that they were usurious. The question was 
referred to Pope Martin v., whose buU deciding 
the matter was generally followed by aU subse- 
quent authorities. The buU decides in favour 
of the lawfulness of rent charges, provided certain 
conditions were observed. They must be charged 
on fiixed property ('super bonis suis, dominiis, 
oppidis, terris, agris, praediis, domibus et heredi- 
tatibus ') and determined beforehand ; they must 
be moderate, not exceeding seven or ten per cent. ; 
and they must be capable of being repurchased at 
any moment in whole or in part, by the repayment 
of the same sum for which they were originally 

"■ Endemann, Studien, vol. ii. p. 109. 
' Bosoher, Oeachichte, p. 20. 



THE EXCHANGE OP PROPERTY 205 

created. On the other hand, the payer of the 
rent must never be forced to repay the purchase 
money, even if the goods on which the rent was 
charged had perished — in other words, the con- 
tract creating the rent charge was one of sale, and 
not of loan. The bull recites that such conditions 
had been observed in contracts of this nature 
from time immemorial.^ A precisely similar 
decree was issued by Calixtus ni. in 1455. ^ 

These decisions were universally followed in the 
fifteenth century.^ It was always insisted that 
a rent could only be charged upon something of 
which the use could be separated from the owner- 
ship, as otherwise it would savour of usury.* In 
the sixteenth century interesting discussions arose 
about the possibility of creating a personal rent 
charge, not secured on any specific property, but 
such discussions did not trouble the writers of the 
period which we are treating. The only instance 
of such a contract being considered is found in 
a buU of Nicholas v. in 1452, permitting such 
personal rent charges in the kingdoms of Aragon 
and Sicily, but this permission was ptirely local, 
and, as the buU itself shows, was designed to meet 
the exigencies of a special situation.^ 

§ 9. Partnership 

The teaching on partnership contains such a 
complete disproof of the contention that the 

^ Extrav. Cmamun., iii. 5, i. ^ Ibid,., c. 2. 

3 Ashley, op. cit., vol. i. pt. ii. p. 410. 

* Biel, <yp. cit. Sent. iv. xv. 12. ^ Cleary, op. dt., p. 124. 



206 MEDIiSVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

mediaeval teaching on usury was based on the 
unproductivity of capital, that certain writers 
have endeavoured to prove that the permission 
of partnership was but a subterfuge, consciously 
designed to justify evasions of the usury law. 
Further historical knowledge, however, has dis- 
pelled this misconception ; and it is now certain 
that the contract of partnership was widely 
practised and tolerated long before the Church 
attempted to insist on the observance of its usury 
laws in everyday commercial life.^ However 
interesting an investigation into the commercial 
and industrial partnerships of the Middle Ages 
might be, we must not attempt to pursue it here, 
as we have rigidly limited ourselves to a considera- 
tion of teaching. We must refer, however, to the 
commenda, which was the contract from which the 
later mediaeval partnership {societas) is generally 
admitted to have developed, because the commenda 
was extensively practised as early as the tenth 
century, and, as far as we know, never provoked 
any expression of disapproval from the Church. 
This silence amounts to a justification ; and we may 
therefore say that, even before Aquinas devoted 
his attention to the subject, the Church fully 
approved of an institution which provided the 
owner of money with the means of procuring an 
unearned income. 

The commenda was originally a contract by 
which merchants who wished to engage in foreign 
trade, but who did not wish to travel themselves, 

^ Ashley, op. oil., voL i. pt. ii. p. 411 ; Weber, Handdagesdlsdiaften, 
pp. 111-14, 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 207 

entrusted their wares to agents or representatives. 
The merchant was known as the commendator 
or socius starts, and the agent as the commendor 
tarius or tractator. The most usual arrangement 
for the division of the profits of the adventure was 
that the commendatarius should receive one-fourth 
and the commendator three-fourths. At a slightly 
later date contracts came to be common in which 
the commendatarius contributed a share of capital, 
in which case he would receive one-fourth of the 
whole profit as commendatarius, and a proportion- 
ate share of the remainder as capitalist. This 
contract came to be generally known as colle- 
gantia or societas. Contracts of this kind, though 
originally chiefly employed in overseas enterprise, 
afterwards came to be utilised in internal trade 
and manufacturing industry.^ 

The legitimacy of the profits of the commen- 
dator never seems to have caused the shghtest 
difficulty to the canonists. In 1206 Innocent in. 
advised the Archbishop of Genoa that a widow's 
dowry should be entrusted to some merchant so 
that an income might be obtained by means of 
honest gain.^ Aquinas expressly distinguishes be ■ 
tween profit made from entrusting one's money to a 
merchant to be employed by him in trade, and 
profit arising from a loan, on the ground that in 
the former case the ownership of the money does 
not pass, and that therefore the person who de- 
rives the profit also risks the loan. ' He who 
lends money transfers the ownership of the money 

^ Ashley, op. cit, vol. i. pt. ii. pp. 412-14. 
2 Qreg. Deer., iv. 19, 7. 



208 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

to the borrower. Hence the borrower holds the 
money at his own risk, and is bound to pay it all 
back : wherefore the lender must not exact more. 
On the other hand, he that entrusts his money to 
a merchant or craftsman so as to form a kind of 
society does not transfer the ownership of the 
money to them, for it remains his, so that at his 
risk the merchant speculates with it, or the crafts- 
man uses it for his craft, and consequently he may 
lawfully demand, as something belonging to him, 
part of the profits derived from his money.' ^ 
This dictum of Aquinas was the foimdation of 
all the later teaching on partnership, and the 
importance of the element of risk was insisted on 
in strong terms by the later writers. According 
to Baldus, ' when there is no sharing of risk there 
is no partnership ' ; ^ and Paul de Castro says, 
' A partnership when the gain is shared, but not 
the loss, is not to be permitted.' ^ ' The legiti- 
macy,' says Brants, ' of the contract of commenda 
always rested upon the same principle ; capital 
could not be productive except for him who worked 
it himself, or who caused it to be worked on his own 
responsibility. This latter condition was realised 
in commenda.' * 

Although the contract of partnership was fully 
recognised by the scholastics, it was not very 
scientifically treated, nor were the different species 
of the contract systematically classified. The only 
classification adopted was to divide contracts of 

1 n. ii. 78, 2, ad. 5. ' Brants, op. oil., p. 167. 

' GonsiKa, ii. 55 ; also Ambrosius de Vignate, De Usuria, i. 62 ; Biel, 
op, cU., IV. XV. 11. * Op. cit., p. 172. 



THE EXCHANGE OP PROPERTY 209 

partnership into two kinds — those where both 
parties contributed labour to a joint enterprise, 
and those where one party contributed labour 
and the other party money. The former gave no 
difficulty, because the justice of the remuneration 
of labour was admitted ; but, while the latter 
was no less fully recognised, cases of it were 
subjected to careful scrutiny, because it was 
feared that usurious contracts might be concealed 
under the appearance of a partnership.^ The 
question which occupied the greatest space in the 
treatises on the subject was the share in which 
the profits should be divided between the parties. 
The only rule which could be laid down, in the 
absence of an express contract, was that the 
parties should be remunerated in proportion to 
the services which they contributed — a rule the 
application of which must have been attended 
with enormous difficulties. Laurentius de Rodul- 
phis insists that equality must be observed ; ^ 
and Angelus de Periglis de Perusio, the first mono- 
graphist on the subject, does not throw much more 
fight on the question. The rule as stated by this 
last writer is that in the first place the person 
contributing money miist be repaid a sum equal 
to what he put in, and the person contributing 
labour must be paid a sum equal to the value of 
his labour, and that whatever surplus remains 
must be divided between the two parties equally.^ 
The question of the shares in which the profits 
should be distributed was not one, however, that 

» Swmma Aetesana, iii. 12. * De Usuris, i. 19. 

° De Soeietatibus, i. 130. 

O 



210 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

frequently arose in practice, because it was the 
almost imiversal custom for the partners to make 
this a term of their original contract. Within 
fairly wide Hmits it was possible to arrange for 
the division of the profits in unequal shares — say 
two-thirds and one-third. The shares of gain 
and loss must, however, be the same ; one party 
could not reap two-thirds of the profit and bear 
only one-third of the loss ; but it might be con- 
tracted that, when the loss was deducted from the 
gain, one party might have two-thirds of the 
balance, and the other one-third.^ In no case, of 
course, could the party contributing the money 
stipulate that his principal should in aU cases be 
returned, because that was a mutuum. The party 
contributing the labour might vaUdly contract 
that he should be paid for his labour in any case, 
but, if this was so, the contract ceased to be a 
societas and became a locatio operamm, or ordi- 
nary contract of work for wages. In all cases, 
common participation in the gains and losses of 
the enterprise was an essential feature of the 
contract of partnership. ^ 

Before concluding the subject of partnership, 
we must make reference to the trinus contractiis, 
which caused much discussion and great difficulty. 
As we have seen, a contract of partnership was 
good so long as the person contributing money 
did not contract that he should receive his original 
money back in aU circumstances. A contract of 
insurance w&s equally justifiable. There was no 
doubt that A might enter into partnership with 

1 De Societatibus, i. 130. ' Und. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PEOPERTY 211 

B ; he could further insiire himself with C against 
the loss of his capital, and with D against damage 
caused by fluctuations ia the rate of profits. Why, 
then, should he not simultaneously enter into aU 
three contracts with B ? If he did so, he was stUl 
B's partner, but at the same time he was pro- 
tected against the loss of his principal and a fair 
return upon it — in other words, he was a partner, 
protected against the risks of the enterprise. The 
legitimacy of such a contract — ^the trinus con- 
tractus, as it was called — ^was maintained by 
Carletus in the Summa Angelica, which was pub- 
lished about 1476, and by Biel.^ Early in the 
sixteenth century Eck, a yoimg professor at 
Ingolstadt, brought the question of the legitimacy 
of this contract before the University of Bologna, 
but no formal decision was pronounced, and, had 
it not been for the reaction following the Refor- 
mation, the trinus contractus would probably 
have gained general acceptance. As it was, it 
was condemned by a provincial sjniod at Milan 
in 1565, and by Sixtus v. in 1585. ^ 

We should also refer to the contract of bottomry, 
which consisted of a loan made to the owner — or 
in some cases the master — of a ship, on the 
security of the ship, to be repaid with interest 
upon the safe conclusion of a voyage. This con- 
tract could not be considered a partnership, in- 

^ Op. cit, IV. XV. 11. Leoky attributed the invention of the trimia 
cmtractus to the Jesuits— who were only founded in 1634 (History of 
BaMcmalism, vol. ii. p. 267). 

2 Ashley, op, cit., vol. i. pt. ii. pp. 439 et aeqq, ; deary, op. oit., 
pp. 126 et seqq^. 



212 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

asmuch as the property in the money passed to 
the borrower ; but it probably escaped condemna- 
tion as usurious on the ground that the lender 
shared in the risk of the enterprise. The payment 
of some additional sum over and above the money 
lent might thus be justified on the grotind of feri- 
culum sortis. The contract, moreover, was really 
one of insurance for the shipowner, and contracts 
of insurance were clearly legitimate. In any 
event the legitimacy of loans on bottomry was 
not questioned before the sixteenth century.^ 



§ 10. Conclvding Remarks on Usury 

It is to be hoped that the above exposition of 
the mediaeval doctrine on usury wiU dispel the idea 
that the doctrine was foimded upon the injustice 
of unearned income. Far from the receipt of an 
unearned income from money or other capital 
beiag in all cases condemned, it was unanimously 
recognised, provided that the income accrued to 
the owner of the capital, and not to somebody else, 
and that the rate of remuneration was just. The 
teaching on partnership rested on the fundamental 
assumption that a man might trade with his money, 
either by using it himself, or by allowing other 
people to use it on his behalf. In the latter case, 
the person making use of the money might be 
either assured of being paid a fixed remuneration 
for his services, in which case the contract was one 

* Ashley, op. cit., vol. i. pt. ii. pp. 421-3 ; Palgrave, Dictionary of, 
PoUHcal Economy, ait. ' Bottomry ' ; Gonningham, Orowth of English 
Industry and Commerce, vol. i. p. 257. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 213 

of locatio operarum, or he might be wilUng to let 
his remuneration depend upon the result of the 
enterprise, in which case the contract was one of 
societas. In either case the right of the owner 
of the money to reap a profit from the operation 
was unquestioned, provided only that he was 
wiUing to share the risks of loss. But if, instead 
of making use of his money for trading either by 
his own exertions or by those of his partner or 
agent, he chose to sell his money, he was not 
permitted to receive more for it than its just price 
— ^which was, in fact, the repayment of the same 
amount. This was what happened in the case 
of a mutuum. In that case the ownership of the 
money was transferred to the borrower, who was 
perfectly at liberty to trade with it, if he so de- 
sired, and to reap whatever gain that trade pro- 
duced. The prohibition of usury, far from being 
proof of the injustice of an tacome from capital, 
is proof of quite the contrary, because it was 
designed to insure that the iacome from capital 
should belong to the owner of that capital and to 
no other person. ^ Although, therefore, no price 
could be paid for a loan, the lender must be pre- 
vented from suffering any damage from making 
the loan, and he might make good his loss by 
virtue of the implied collateral contract of in- 
demnity, which we discussed above when treating 
of extrinsic titles. If the lender, through making 
the loan, had been prevented from making a profit 
in trade, he might be indemnified for that loss. 
All through the discussions on usury we find 

1 See Bambaud, oj>. cit., p. 59. 



214 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

express recognition of the justice of the owner of 
money deriving an income from its employment ; 
all that the teaching of usury was at pains to 
define was who the person was to whom money, 
which was the subject matter of a mutuum, be- 
longed. It is quite impossible to comprehend how 
modem writers can see in the usury teaching of 
the scholastics a fatal discotiragement to the 
enterprise of traders and capitaUsts ; and it is 
equally impossible to understand how sociahsts 
can find itl that doctrine any suggestion of support 
for the proposition that all unearned income is 
immoral and unjust. 

Section 3. — The MAcnmEBY oe Exchange 

We have already drawn attention to the fact 
that there was no branch of economics about 
which such profound ignorance ruled in the earher 
Middle Ages as that of money. As we stated 
above, even as late as the twelfth century, the 
theologians were quite content to quote the ill- 
founded and erroneous opinions of Isidore of 
SeviEe as final on the subject. It will be remem- 
bered that we also remarked that the question 
of money was the first economic question to receive 
systematic scientific treatment from the writers 
of the later Middle Ages. This remarkable de- 
velopment of opinion on this subject is practi- 
cally the work of one man, Nicholas Oresme, 
Bishop of Lisieux, whose treatise, De Origine, 
Natura, Jure et Mutationihus Monetarum, is the 
earliest example of a pure economic monograph 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 215 

in the modern sense. ' The scholastics,' says 
Roscher, ' extended their inquiries from the 
economic point of view further than one is gener- 
ally disposed to believe ; although it is true that 
they often did so under a singular form. . . . We 
can, however, single out Oresme as the greatest 
scholastic ecoixomist for two reasons : on account 
of the exactitude and clarity of his ideas, and 
because he succeeded in freeing himself from the 
pseudo-theological systematisation of things in 
general, and from the pseudo-philosophical deduc- 
tion in details.' ^ 

Even in the thirteenth century natural economy ?i^ 
had not been replaced to any large extent by money 
economy. The great majority of transactions be- 
tween man and man were carried on without the 
intervention of money payments ; and the amount 
of coin in circulation was consequently small. ^ 
The question of currency was not therefore one 
to engage the serious attention of the writers of 
the time. Aquinas does not deal Mirith money in 
the Summa, except incidentally, and his references 
to the subject in the De Begimine Principum — 
which occur in the chapters of that work of which 
the authorship is disputed — simply go to the 
length of approving Aristotle's opinions on money, 
and advising the prince to exercise moderation in 
the exercise of his power of coining sive in mutando 
sive in diminuendo 'pondus.^ 

1 Quoted in the Introduction to Wolowski's edition of Oresme's 
Tradatus (Paris, 1864). 
'- Brants, op. cit., p. 179 ; Rambaud, op. cit., p. 73. 
« De Beg. Prin,, ii. 13. 



216 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

As is often the case, the discussion of the rights 
and duties of the sovereign in connection with the 
currency only arose when it became necessary for 
the pubhc to protest against abuses. Phihp the 
Fair of France made it part of his pohcy to increase 
the revenue by tampering with the coinage, a 
pohcy which was continued by his successors, 
until it became an intolerable grievance to his 
subjects. In vain did the Pope thunder against 
Philip ; 1 in vain did the greatest poet of the age 
denounce 

' liim that doth work 
With his adulterate money on the Seine.' ^ 

Matters continued to grow steadily worse until 
the middle of the fourteenth century. During 
the year 1348 there were no less than eleven 
variations in the value of money in France ; in 
1349 there were nine, in 1351 eighteen, in 1353 
thirteen, and in 1355 eighteen again. In the 
course of a single year the value of the silver 
mark sprang from four to seventeen hvres, and 
fell back again to four.^ The practice of fixing 
the price of many necessary commodities must 
have aggravated the natural evil consequences of 
such fluctuations.* 

This grievance had the good result of fixing 
the attention of scholars on the money question. 
' Under the stress of facts and of necessity,' says 
Brants, 'thinkers appUed their minds to the 

^ Le Blant, Traiti Mstoriqite des Monnaies de France, p. 184. 
' Dante, Paradiso, xiz. 

" Wolowski's Introduction to Oresme'a Tmctatus, p. xrvii. 
* See Endemann, Studien, vol. ii. p. 34. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 217 

details of the theory of money, which was the 
department of economics which, thanks to events, 
received the earhest illumination. Lawyers, 
bankers, money-changers, doctors of theology, and 
publicists of every kind, attached a thoroughly 
Justifiable importance to the question of money. 
We are no doubt far from knowing all the treatises 
which saw the hght in the fourteenth century 
upon this weighty question ; but we know enough 
to affirm' that the monetary doctrine was very 
developed and very far-seeing.' ^ Buridan ana- 
lysed the different functions and utilities of money, 
and explained the different ways in which its 
value might be changed.^ He did not, however, 
proceed to discuss the much more important 
question as to when the sovereign was entitled to 
make these alterations. This was reserved for 
Nicholas Oresme, who published his famous 
treatise about the year 1373. The merits of this 
work have excited the imanimous admiration 
of aU who have studied it. Roscher says that 
it contains ' a theory of money, elaborated in 
the fourteenth century, which remains perfectly 
correct to-day, under the test of the principles 
applied in the nineteenth century, and that with 
a brevity, a precision, a clarity, and a simplicity 
of language which is a striking proof of the supe- 
rior genius of its author.' ^ According to Brants, 
' the treatise of Oresme is one of the first to be 
devoted ex 'professo to an economic subject, and 

1 Op. cit., p. 186. 

^ Quaest. swper Lib. Eth., v. 17 ; Quaest. super Lib. Pol., i. 11. 

^ Quoted in Woloweki, op. cit,, and see Boscher, Qeschichte, p. 25. 



218 MEDIiEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

it expresses many ideas which are very just, more 
just than those which held the field for a long 
period after him, under the name of mercantiUsm, 
and more just than those which allowed of the re- 
duction of money as if it were nothing more than 
a cotmter of exchange.' ^ ' Oresme's treatise on 
money,' says Macleod, ' may be justly said to 
stand at the head of modern economic literature. 
This treatise laid the foundations of monetary 
science, which are now accepted by all sound 
economists.' ^ ' Oresme's completely secular and 
naturaUstic method of treatiag one of the most 
important problems of poUtical economy,' says 
Espinas, ' is a signal of the approaching end of the 
Middle Ages and the dawn of the Renaissance.' ^ 
Dr. Cunningham adds his tribute of praise : ' The 
conceptions of national wealth and national power 
were ruling ideas in. economic matters for several 
centuries, and Oresme appears to be the earhest 
of the economic writers by whom they were ex- 
pHcitly adopted as the very basis of his argument. 
. . . A large number of points of economic doctrine 
in regard to coinage are discussed with much 
judgment and clearness.' * Endemann alone is ° 
inclined to quarrel with the pre-eminence of 
Oresme ; but on this question, he is in a minority 
of one.^ 

The principal question which Oresme sets out 

1 Op. cit, p. 190. 

' History of Economics, p. 37. * Op. cit., p. 110. 

* Orowth of English Ivdusiiy and Commerce, vol. i. p. 359. 

* Grundsatge, p. 75. 

* See an interesting note in Brants, op. cit, p. 187. 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 219 

to answer, according to the first chapter of this 
treatise, is whether the sovereign has the rightf^ 
to alter the value of the money in circulation at 
his pleasure, and for his own benefit. He begins 
the discussion by going over the same ground as 
Aristotle in demonstrating the origin and utility 
of money, and then proceeds to discuss the most 
suitable materials which can be made to serve as 
money. He decides in favour of gold and silver, 
and shows himself an unquestioning bimetaUist. 
He further admits the necessity of some token 
money of small denominations, to be composed 
of the baser metals. Having drawn attention to 
the transition from the circulation of money, the 
value of which is recognised solely by weight, to the 
circulation of that which is accepted for its im- 
print or superscription, the author insists that the 
production of such an imprinted coinage is essen- 
tially a matter for the sovereign authority in the 
State. Oresme now comes to the central point 
of his thesis. Although, he says, the prince hasy 
undoubtedly the power to manufacture and control 
the coinage, he is by no means the owner of it 
after it has passed into circulation, because money 
is a thing which in its essence was invented and 
introduced in the interests of society as a whole. 

Oresme then proceeds to apply this central 
principle to the solution of the question which he 
sets himself to answer, and concludes that, as 
money is essentially a thing which exists for the 
public benefit, it must not be tampered with, 
nor varied in value, except in cases of ab- 
solute necessity, and in the presence of an un- 



220 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

controverted general utility. He bases his oppo- 
sition to unnecessary monetary variation on the 
perfectly sotind ground that such variation is 
productive of loss either to those who are bound 
to make or bound to receive fixed sums in pay- 
ment of obligations. The author then goes on to 

;;^ analyse the various kinds of variation, which he 
says are five — figurae, frofortionis, appellationis, 

-^onderis, and materiae. Changes of form (figurae) 
are only justified when it is found that the exist- 
ing form is liable to increase the damage which 
the coins suffer from the wear and tear of usage, 
or when the existing currency has been degraded 
by widespread illegal coining ; changes pro- 
-portionis are only allowable- when the relative 
value of the different metals constituting the 
coinage have themselves changed ; simple 
"Tshanges of name (appellationis), such as calling a 
mark a povind, are never allowed. Changes of 

— the weight of the coins (ponderis) are pronounced 
by Oresme to be just as gross a fraud as the 
arbitrary alteration of the weights or measxires 
by which com or wine are sold; and changes of 
"Tnatter (Tnateriae) are only to be tolerated when 
the supply of the old metal has become insufficient. 
The debasement of the coinage by the introduction 
of a cheaper alloy is condemned. 

In conclusion, Oresme insists that no alteration 
of any of the above kinds can be justified at the 
mere injunction of the prince ; it must be accom- 
plished per ipsam communitatem. The prince 
exercises the functions of the community in the 
matter of coinage not as principalis actor, but as 



THE EXCHANGE OF PROPERTY 221 

ordinationis publicae executor. It is pointed out 
that arbitrary changes in the value of money are 
really equivalent to a particularly noxious form of 
taxation ; that they seriously disorganise com- 
merce and impoverish many merchants ; and that 
the bad coinage drives the good out of circula- 
tion. This last observation is of special interest 
in a fourteenth-century writer, as it shows that 
Gresham's Law, which is usually credited to a 
sixteenth-century English economist, was per- 
fectly weU understood in the Middle Ages.^ 

This brief account of the ground which Oresme 
covered, and the conclusions at which he arrived, 
wiU enable us to appreciate his importance. 
Although his clear elucidation of the principles 
which govern the questions of money was not 
powerful enough to check the financial abuses of 
the sovereigns of the later Middle Ages, they 
exercised a profound influence on the thought of 
the period, and were accepted by aU the theo- 
logians of the fifteenth century.^ 

^ The best edition of Oresme's Tractatus is that by Wolowski, pub- 
lished at Paris in 1864, which includes both the Latin and French 
texts. 

2 Biel, op. cit, rv. xv. H ; De Monetarum Poteatate et UtiUtate, 
referred to in Jourdain, op. cit, p. 34. 



CHAPTER IV 

CONCLUSION 

We have now passed in review the principal 
economic doctrines of the mediaeval schoolmen. 
We do not propose to attempt here any de- 
tailed criticism of the merits or demerits of the 
aystem which we have but briefly sketched. All 
that we have attempted to do is to present the 
doctrines in such a way that the reader may be in 
a position to pass judgment on them. There is 
one aspect of the subject, however, to which we may 
be allowed to direct attention before concluding 
this essay. It is the fashion of many modem 
writers, especially those hostile to tiie CathoUc 
Church, to represent the Middle Ages as a period 
when all scientific advance and economic progress 
were impeded, if not entirely prevented, by the 
action of the Chtirch. It would be out of place 
to inquire into the advances which civilisation 
achieved in the Middle Ages, as this would lead us 
into an examination of the whole history of the 
period ; but we think it well to inquire briefly how 
far the teaching of the Church on economic matters 
was calculated to interfere with material pro- 
gress. This is the lowest standard by which we 
can judge the mediaeval economic teaching, which 
was essentially aimed at the moral and spiritual 

228 



CONCLUSION 223 

elevation of mankind ; but it is a standard which 
it is worth while to apply, as it is that by which 
the doctrines of the scholastics have been most 
generally condemned by modern critics. To test 
the mediaeval economic doctrine by this, the 
lowest standard, it may be said that it made for 
the establishment and development of a rich and^ 
prosperous community. We .may summarise thes^ 
aim of the mediaeval teaching by saying that, 
in the material sphere, it aimed at extended pro- 
duction, wise consumption, and just distribu- 
tion, which are the chief ends of all economic 
activity. 

It aimed at extended production throogiffEs 
insistence on the importance and dignity of manual 
labour.^ As we showed above, one of the prin- 
cipal achievements of Christianity in the social 
sphere was to elevate labour from a degrading 
to an honourable occupation. The example of 
Christ HimseK and the Apostles must have made 
a "deep impression on the early Christians ; but 
no less important was the living example to be 
seen in the monasteries. The part played by the 
great religious orders in the propagation of this 
dignified conception cannot be exaggerated. St. 
Anthony had adirised his imitators to busy them- 
selves with meditation, prayer, and the labour 
of their hands, and had promised that the fear of 
God would reside in those who laboured at cor- 
poral works ; and similar exhortations were to be 
found in the rules of Saints Macarius, Pachomius, 

'- See Sabatier, L'Egliae et le Travail taanud, and Antoine, Cours 
d'Economie soeiale, p. 159. 



224 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

and Basil. ^ St. Augustine and St. Jerome recom- 
mended that all religious should work for some 
hours each day with their hands, and a regulation 
t6 this effect was embodied in the Rule of St. 
Benedict.^ The example of educated and holy 
men voluntarily taking upon themselves the most 
menial and tedious employments must have acted 
as an inspiration to the laity. The mere economic 
value of the monastic institutions themselves must 
have been very great ; agriculture was improved 
owing to the assiduity and experiments of the 
monks ; ^ the monasteries were the nurseries of 
aU industrial and artistic progress ; * and the 
example of communities which consumed but a 
small proportion of what they produced was a 
striking example to the world of the wisdom and 
virtue of saving.^ Not the least of the services 
which Christian teaching rendered in the domain 
of production was its insistence upon the dominical 
repose.^ 

The importance which the scholastics attached 
to an extended and widespread production is 
evidenced by their attitude towards the growth of 
the population. The fear of over-population does 
not appear to have occurred to the writers of the 

^ Levasseur, Histoire des Glasses ov/mik'es en France, vol. i. pp. 182-S. 

^ Beg. St. Ben., c. 48. 

" List, National System of Political Economy, oh. 6. 

* Janssen, History of the Oerman People, vol. ii. p. 2. 

* DubUn Review, N.S., vol. vi. p. 365 ; see Gioyau, Aviour du Calholi- 
cisme soeiale, vol. ii. pp. 79-118 ; Gasquet, Henry VIII. and the English 
Monasteries, vol> ii. p. 495. 

' DvhUn Bedew, vol. xxxiii. p. 305. See Goyau, Aubmr dv, CafhoU- 
dstae so(mle, vol. ii, pp. 93 et seq. 



CONCLUSION 225 

Middle Ages ; ^ on the contrary, a rapidly increas- 
ing population was considered a great blessing for 
a country. 2 This attitude towards the question 
of population did not arise merely from the fact 
that Europe was very sparsely populated in the 
Middle Ages, as modern research has proved that 
the density of population was much greater than 
is generally supposed.^ 

The mediaeval attitude towards population was 
founded upon the sanctity of marriage and the 
respect for human life. The utterances of Aquinas 
on the subject of matrimony show his keen appre- 
ciation of the natural social utility of marriage 
from the point of view of increasing the population 
of the world, and of securing that the new genera- 
tion shaU be brought up as good and valuable 
citizens,* While voluntary virginity is recom- 
mended as a virtue, it is nevertheless distinctly 
recognised that the precept of virginity is one 
which by its very nature can be practised by only 
a small proportion of the human race, and that 
it should only be practised by those who seek 
by detachment from earthly pleasures to regard 

* Brants, op. cit., p. 235, quoting Sinigaglia, La Teoria Economica 
deUa Populazione in Italia, Arohivio Giuridico, Bologna, 1881. 

^ Caiholic Encyclopaedia, art. ' Population.' Brants draws attention 
to the interesting fact that a germ of Malthusianism is to be found in 
the mnch-disoussed Songe Alt Vergier, book ii. chaps. 297-98, and 
Franciscus Patricius de Senis, writing at the end of the fifteenth 
century, recommends emigration as the remedy against over-popula- 
tion (Z>e Instifiitione BeipuhUcae, ix.). 

* Bureau de la Malle, ' IKmoire sur la Population de la France au 
xiv° Siecle,' Mkmmrcs di I'Acadlmie des Inscriptions et BeUes-Letlres, 
vol. xiv. p. 36. 

« Svmma CmU. Omt., in. 123, 136. 



226 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

divine things. ^ Aquinas further says that large 
famihes help to increase the power of the State, 
and deserve well of the commonwealth,^ and 
quotes with approbation the Biblical injunction 
to ' increase and multiply.' ^ i:Egidius Romanus 
demonstrates at length the advantages of large 
famihes in the interests of the family and the 
future of the nation.* 

The growth of a healthy population was made 
possible by the reformation of family hfe, which 
was one of the greatest achievements of Chris- 
tianity in the social sphere. In the early days of 
the Church the institution of the family had been 
reconstituted by moderating the harshness of the 
Roman domestic rule {patria potestas), by raising 
the moral and social position of women, and by 
reforming the system of testamentary and in- 
testate successions ; and the great importance 
which the early Church attached to the family as 
the basic unit of social life remained unaltered 
throughout the Middle Ages.^ 

The Middle Ages were therefore a period when 
the production of wealth was looked upon as a 
salutary and honourable vocation. The wonder- 
ful artistic monuments of that era, which have 
survived the intervening centuries of decay and 
vandalism, are a striking testimony to the per- 
fection of production in a civilisation in which 

1 Svmma, n. ii. 161 and 152. « De Beg. Prin., iv. 9. 

3 Gen. i. 28. * De Beg. Prin., ii. 1, 6. 

' ' Troplong, De VInfluenee du Ghriatianisme sur le Droit civil des 
Bomains; Cossa, Guide, p. 99; Beyas, , Politicdl Economy, p. 168; 
F6rin, La Bichesse dans ks Sociitis ekriUennea, i. 641 et seq. ; Hettinger, 
Apologie du Christianisme, v. 230 et seq. 



CONCLUSION 227 

work was considered to be but a form of prayer, 
and the manufacturer was prompted to be, not a 
drudge, but an artist. 

In the Middle Ages, however, as we have said 
before, man did not exist for the sake of production, 
but production for the sake of man ; and wise 
consumption was regarded as at least as important 
as extended production. The high estimation in 
which wealth was held resulted in the elaboration 
of a highly developed code of regulation as to the 
manner in which it should be enjoyed. We do 
not wish to weary the reader with a repetition 
of that which we have already fuUy discussed ; it 
is enough to call attention to the fact that the 
golden mean of conduct was the observance of 
liberality, as distinguished, on the one hand, from 
avarice, or a too high estimation of material 
goods, and, on the other hand, from prodigaUty, 
or an undue disregard for their value. Social 
virtue consisted in attaching to wealth its proper 
value. 

Far more important than its teaching either on 
production or consumption was the teaching of 
the mediaeval Church on distribution, which it 
insisted must be regulated on a basis of strict 
justice. It is in this department of economic 
study that the teaching of the medisevals appears 
in most marked contrast to the teaching of the 
present day, and it is therefore in this department 
that the study of its doctrines is most valuable. 
As we said above, the modern world has become 
convinced by bitter experience of the imprac- 
ticability of mere selfishness as the governing 



228 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

factor in distribution ; and the economic thought 
of the time is concentrated upon devising some 
new system of society which shall be ruled by 
justice. On the one hand, we see sociaHsts of 
various schools attempting to construct a Utopia 
in which each man shaU be rewarded, not in accord- 
ance with his opportunities of growing rich at the 
expense of his fellow-man, but according to the 
services he performs ; while, on the other hand, 
we find the Christian economists striving to induce 
a harassed and bewildered world to revert to an 
older and nobler social ethic. 

It is no part of our present purpose to estimate 
the relative merits of these two solutions for our 
admittedly diseased society. Nor is it our pur- 
pose to attempt to demonstrate how far the system 
of economic teaching which we have sketched in 
the foregoing pages is applicable at the present day. 
We must, however, in this connection draw atten- 
tion to one important consideration, namely, that 
the mediaeval economic teaching was expressly 
designed to influence the only constant element 
in human society at every stage of economic 
development. Methods of production may im- 
prove, hand may give place to machine industry, 
and mechanical inventions may revolutionise all 
our conceptions of transport and communication ; 
but there is one element in economic activity that 
remains a fixed and immutable factor throughout 
the ages, and that element is man. The desires 
and the conscience of man remain the same, what- 
ever the mechanical environment with which he 
is encompassed. One reason which suggests the 



CONCLUSION 229 

view that the mediaeval teaching is still per- 
fectly applicable to economic life is that it 
was designed to operate upon the only factor of 
economic activity that has not changed since the 
Middle Ages — ^namely, the desires and conscience 
of man. 

It is important also to draw attention to the 
fact that the acceptance of the economic teaching 
of the mediaeval theologians does not necessarily 
imply acceptance of their teaching on other matters. 
There is at the present day a growing body of 
thinking men in every country who are full of 
admiration for the ethical teaching of Christianity, 
but are unable or unwiUing to beheve in the 
Christian rehgion^ The fact of such unbehef or 
doubt is no reason for refusing to adopt the 
Christian code of social justice, which is founded 
upon reason rather than upon revelation, and 
which has its roots in Greek philosophy and B>oman 
law rather than in the Bible and the writings of 
the Fathers. It has been said that Christianity 
is the only religion which combines religion and 
ethics in one system of teaching ; but although 
Christiar. religious and ethical teaching are com- 
bined in/ the teaching of the CathoUc Church, they 
are not, inseparable. Those who are willing to 
discuss the adoption of the Sociahst ethic, which is 
not combined with any spiritual dogmas, should 
not refuse to consider the Christian ethic, which 
might, equally be adopted without subscribing to 
the Christian dogma. 

As we said above, it is no part of our intention 
to estimate the relative merits of the solutions of 



230 MEDIAEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 

our social evils proposed by socialists and by 
Catholic economists. One thing, however, we 
feel bound to emphasise, and that is that these 
two solutions are not identical. It is a favourite 
device of socialists, especially in Catholic countries, 
to contend that their programme is nothing more 
than a restatement of the economic ideals of the 
Cathohc Church as exhibited in the writings of the 
mediaeval scholastics. We hope that the fore- 
going pages are sufficient to demonstrate the in- 
correctness of this assertion. Three main prin- 
ciples appear more or less clearly in all modem 
sociahstic thought: first, that private ownership 
of the means of production is unjustifiable ; second, 
that all value comes from labour ; and, third, that 
all unearned income is unjust. These three great 
principles may or may not be sound ; but it is 
quite certain that not one of them was held by the 
mediaeval theologians. In the section on property 
we have shown that Aquinas, following the 
Fathers and the tradition of the early Church, was 
an uncompromising advocate of private property, 
and that he drew no distinction between fhe means 
of production and any other kind of wealth ; in 
the section on just price we have sho vn that 
labour was regarded by the medisevals as but a 
single one of the elements which entered iuto the 
determination of value ; and in the section on 
usury we have shown that many forms of un- 
earned income were not only tolerated^; but 
approved by the scholastics. 

We do not lose sight of the fact that soc ialism 
is not a mere economic system, but a philosophy. 



CONCLUSION 231 

and that it is founded on a philosophical basis 
which conflicts with the very foundations of Chris- 
tianity. We are only concerned with it here 
in its character of an economic system, and all we 
have attempted to show is that, as an economic 
system, it finds no support in the teaching of the 
scholastic writers. We do not pretend to suggest 
which of these two systems is more likely to bring 
salvation to the modem world ; we simply wish 
to emphasise that they are two systems, and not 
one. One's inability to distinguish between Christ 
and Barabbas should not lead one to conclude 
that they are really the same person. 



INDEX 



Abelabd, 14. 

Acts of the Apostle), 168. 

communism in, 44, 46. 

Adam, 140. 

and Eve, slavery the result of 

their sin, 92. 

Administrative occupations, posi- 
tion in artes possessivae, 143. 

Aegidius Romanus, 98, 197, 225. 

Agriculture, position in a/rtee posset- 
aivae, 142, 143." 

its encouragement recom- 
mended, 143. 

AlbertuB Magnus, 16, 82, 176, 186, 
197. 

Albigenses, the, belief in com- 
munism, 66. 

Alcuin, 14. 

Alexander of Hales, 176, 185. 

Alexander III., Pope, 187. 

attitude to usury, 174. 

Alfric, see Colloquy of Archbishop, 
The. 

Almsgiving, as justice, not charity, 
69. 

duty of, 80. 

enforcement by the State, 85. 

summary of medieeval teach- 
ing on, 84. 

the early Church on, 52. 

Ambition, a virtue, 79. 
Ambrosius de Yignate, 191, 208. 
Ananias, 46, 52. 
Ancients, loss of economic teaching 

of, 15. 
Angelus de Feriglis de Perusio, 

209, 210. 
Antoine, 87, 172, 223. 
Antoninus of Florence, 9, 68, 79, 

110, 122, 181, 196. 
Ape of Aristotle, the, see Albertns 

Magnus. 
Apostles, the, attitude to manual 

labour, 223. 

attitude to private property 

and communism, 48. 

attitude to usury, 168. 



Apostles, the, fornication expressly 
forbidden by, 168. 

teaching regarding slavery, 

89. 

Apostoli, the, belief in commun- 
ism, 66. 

Aquinas, tee Thomas Aquinas. 

Aragon, personal rent charges per- 
mitted in, 205. 

Architecture, see Manufacture. 

Archivio Qiuridico, 225. 

Ardant, 69. 

Aristotle, 14, 16, 36, 97, 98, 142, 
146, 169, 215, 219. 

as source for Thomas Aquinas, 

62. 

attitude of Thomas Aquinas to 

his opinion, Si et seq. 

Cossa on his influence, 17. 

his principles maintained 

through Thomas Aquinas, 19. 

his theory of slavery opposed 

to that of St. Augustine, 93. 

influence on controversies of 

the schools, 17. 

influence on mediaeval thought, 

16. 

renewed study of, 16. 

Arnold, 203. 

Artes pecuniativae, 142, 

Artes possessivae, 142. 

encouragement recom- 
mended by Aquinas, 143. 

ArnobiuB, 45. 

Ashley, Sir W. H., 3, 6, 7, 18, 21, 
23, 27, 29, 30, 33, 40, 76, 105, 113, 
126, 134, 146, 149, 175, 185, 186, 
187, 188, 190, 191, 195, 196, 197, 
198, 202, 203, 205, 206, 207, 211, 
212. 

Augustinians, the, 195. 

Ausmo, Nicholas de, 156. 

Avarice, an offence against liberal- 
ity, 79. 

a sin towards the individual 

himself and the community, 78. 

relativity of, 75. 



INDEX 



233 



Avarice, theneoesBarybaBisof trade, 

145. 
Aymbite oflnwit. The, 151. 

Baldus, 187, 208. 

Pavovaia, a sin, 77, 78. 

Barabbas, 231. 

Bartlett, Dr. V., 56, 90. 

Bartolus, 187. 

Baudrillard, 76. 

Beauvaia, Vincent de, 7, 16. 

B^gards, the, belief in communism, 

66. 
Benedict xiv., Pope, an encyclical 

of, 183. 
Benigni, 61. 
Bergier, 45. 

Bemardine of Siena, 112, 181. 
Biel, 99, 100, 104, 106, 107, 108, 112, 

118, 121, 124, 145, 150, 156, 180, 

185, 205, 208, 211, 221. 
Bimetallism, Oreame'a support of, 

219. 
Blanqui, 146. 
Bohemia, communistic teaching in, 

86. 
Bohm-Bawerk, 174, 200, 203, 211. 
Bottomry, contract of, 211. 
Brant, Sebastian, 137. 
Brants, V. L. J. L., 9, 10, 13, 19, 

21, 66, 101, 111, 112, 114, 121, 

122, 123, 142y 159, 181, 208, 215, 

216, 217, 218, 225. 
BreSlau, refusal to pay rent in, 204. 
Brunetto Latini, 123. 
Building, see Manufacture. 
Buridan, 70, 72, 76, 77, 78, 109, 110, 

143, 180, 191, 198, 217. 

Cabet, 42. 

CaepoUa, 108, 118, 120. 

Cajetan, 65, 79. 

on the Swmma, 68. 

Calippe, AbW, 49, 62. 

on Thomas Aquinas, 68. 

Cabxtus III., Pope, decree regard- 
ing rent, 205. 

Gambium, 165. ' 

conditions justifying, 157- 

dealt with by Brants, 159. 

minutum, 157, 158. 

; motives justifying, 157. 

per litteras, 157, 158. 

siccum, 167. 

the three kinds of, 157, 158. 

when justifiable, not a loan, 

158. I 



Campsor, the, his remuneration ap- 
proved, 156. 

Canon law the source of knowledge 
of Christian economic teaching, 
13. 

Canonist doctrine, dealt with by 
Sir W. Ashley, 2. 

Dr. Cunningham's esti- 
mate of its importance, 27. 

its impracticability de- 

. monstrated by Endemann, 20. 

value of the study of, 29. 

Canonists, the, 117. 

Capital, question of the productiv- 
ity of, 198 et seq. 

CarletuB, 120, 150, 193, 211. 

Carlyle, Dr., 44, 58, 63. 

Castro, Paul, 208. 

Catholic Encyclopaedia, The, defini- 
tion of ' Middle Ages,' 3. 

— — on Communism, 46. 

on Just Price, 112, 126. 

on Political Economy, 30. 

on Population, 225. 

on Slavery, 90, 100. 

Cato, 162. . 

Cattle-breeding, see Agriculture. 

Census constitutivus, 203. 

reservativus, 203. 

Centesima, the maximum rate of 
interest in Rome, 161. 

Cesana, monies pietatis at, 196. 

Champagny, 80. 

Change, see Camhiwm. 

Chevallier, 20. 

Christ, 42, 231. 

a working man, 137. 

attitude to manual labour, 223. 

to private property and 

communism, 47. 

teaching regarding slavery, 89. 

Christendom, economic unity of, 
11. 

Christian economic teaching, 13. 

economists, their attempts to 

reinstitute mediseval economics, 
228. 

Christian Monitor, The, 1 39. 

Christian Exhortation, The, on the 
protection of the farmer, 143. 

Christianity, as providing an ethical 
basis of society, 31. 

attitude to manual labour, 137, 

223. 

attitude to slavery, 88. 

foundations and origin of iti 

code of social justice, 229. 



234 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 



Christianity, influence in abolition 
of Boman slavery, 99 et seq. 

possibility of adopting ethics 

without dogmas of, 229. 

reformation of family life by, 

226. 

relation of economic teaching 

of, to socialism, 33. 

social theory of, 12. 

Church, economic teaching of the 
mediseval, 12. 

the, attitude to commerce at 

end of the Middle Ages, 152. 

the, attitude to monies pietatis, 

197. 

the, effect of economic teach- 
ing of, on material progress, 
223. 

the, necessity for understand- 
ing economic teaching of, 32. 

the, principles followed by, in 

fixing price, 114. 

the, prohibition of usury not 

peculiar to, 160. 

the, socialist view of iti teach- 
ing on usury, 198. 

the early, 230. 

teaching on usury, 167 et 

eeq. 
Cicero, 56, 58, 162. 
Civil Law, Commentaries on, a 

source of knowledge of Christian 

economic teaching, 13. 
Civilisation, result of its advance 

in the thirteenth century, 15. 
Classical economists, recent reaction 

against, 29. 
Cleary, Dr., 35, 135, 160, 161, 162, 

163, 164, 165, 166, 167, 168, 169. 

17d, 171, 172, 173, 174, 175, 185, 

186, 187, 188, 191, 192, 193, 196, 

197, 205. 
Clement of Alexandria, see St. 

Clement. 

of Borne, see St. Clement. 

Clergy, the, and usury, 169. 

the, prohibition of trading by, 

151. 
Coinage, see Money. 
Collegantia, 207. 
Oolloquy of Archbishop Alfric, The, 

149. 
Oommenda, the, 206. 
Commendatarius, the, 207. 
Oommendator, the, 207. 
Common estimation, of just price 

not the final criterion, 134. 



Commerce, attitude of later fifteenth 
century to, 150. 

attitude of mediaeval theolo- 
gians to, 136. 

attitude of the Church at end 

of Middle Ages, 152. 

condemnation of, by early 

Christians, 145. 

condemnation of, by scholastics, 

146. 

dangerous to virtue, 145, 151. 

definition of, 144. 

extension of, in thirteenth 

century, 15. 

factors making for its illegal- 
ity, 151. 

gradual change of mediaeval 

attitude to, 152. 

justification of, not based on 

payment for labour, 154. 

legitimacy dependent on 

methods, 146. 

legitimacy dependent on 

motives, 148. 

motives regarded as justify- 
ing, 153. 

necessity for, realised, 147. 

necessity of controlling its 

operations, 154. 

not dealt with by early writers, 

position in the artes potsessivae, 

143. 
prohibition of speculative, 151. 

rules applyiJig to, defined by 

Kider, 150. 

Communism, alleged, of early Chris- 
tians, 43. 

not part of scholastic teaching, 

66. 

Community of user, doctrine of, 85. 

no relation to modern 

socialistic communism, 86. 

Commutations, see Exchange. 

Compensation, for failure to repay 
loans by date stipulated, 185. 

for profit hindered, 189. 

Competition, effect of unrestricted, 
31. 

Comte, his definition of ' Middle 
Ages ' followed by Dr. Ingram, 3. 

Conquerors, their right to enslave- 
ment of the conquered adopted 
by Aquinas, 96. 

Constantine, 43. 

Constantinople, fall of, regarded 
as end of the Middle Ages, 4. 



INDEX 



235 



Consumption, regulation of, 32. 

'wisa, importance of, 227. 

wise, the aim of mediaeval 

teaching, 223. 
Contract, Thomas Aquinas On, 38. 
Corinthians, Epistle to the,, 48. 
Corpus Juris Canonici, 13, 146. 
Cossa, L., 5, 6, 17, 108, 220. 
Credit, 119. 
Crusades, the, influence of, 15. 

the, influence on trade, 146. 

Cunningham, Dr. W., 2, 9, 10, 11, 

13, 23, 24, 26, 27, 79, 116, 122, 

124, 126, 127, 128, 129, 130, 138, 

139, 152, 212, 218. 
Currency, see Money. 
Cyprian, 168, 170. 
attitude to property, 50. 

Damnum emebqens, 185, 196. 

nature of, 186. 

universal admission of, 187. 

Dante, 216. 

De Begimine Principwm, doubtful 
authorship of, 20. 

Delisle, 27. 

Dimocratie Ghritienne, 199. 

Deposit, Thomas Aquinas on, 38. 

Desbuquois, Abb6, 36, 39, 104, 110, 
116, 120. 

Deuteronomy, 163. 

Devas, 30, 49, 226. 

Dictionary of Political Economy, 30, 
105, 112, 135, 212. 

Dictionnaire de Thiologie, 45. 

Didache, the, attitude to usury, 168, 
170. 

Diocletian rescript, regarding sales, 
104. 

Distribution, just, the aim of medi- 
aeval teaching, 223. 

need for just, 31, 227. 

regulation of, 32. 

Dominicans, the, 195, 196. 

Dominium eminens of the State, 69. 

Donatus, 14. 

Dublin Review, The, 43. 

Duns Scotns, 149, 185, 188, 192. 

Dureau de la Malle, 225. 

Ecclesiastes, 151. 

Eck, 211. 

' Economic,' interpretation of, 3, 6 

et aeq. < 

• Economic Man,' imaginary figure 

conceived by classical economists, 

8. 



Economic Review, The, 44. 

Economics, causes of lack of interest 
in, 14. 

Elvira, the Council of, decree against 
usury, 169. 

Emperor, the, temporal vicar of 
God, 11. 

Encyclopaedia Britannica, The, de- 
finition of ' Middle Ages,' 4. 

Endemann, 19, 20, 23, 27, 34, 108, 
120, 124, 134, 151, 155, 157, 158, 
177, 186, 187, 190, 191, 195, 196, 
203, 204, 216, 218. 

Ephesians, Epistle to the, 89. 

Equality, of men, 94. 

Esdras, 165. 

Espinas, A., 8, 17, 163, 197, 218. 

Essenes, the, and communism, 47. 

Ethics, error of disregarding in 
economics, 29. 

Eve, see Adam and. 

Exchange, regulation of, 32. 

justice in, 36 et seq. 

theory of, see Oambivm. 

Exodus, 163. 

Ezekiel, 165. 

Fatheks, the, see Church, the early. 

Eavre, 173. 

Feudalism, increased organisation 
of, in thirteenth century, 15. 

Fornication, expressly forbidden by 
the Apostles, 168. 

Franciscans, the, 195, 196. 

Franciscua Fatricius de Seulis, 225. 

Franck, A., 20, 90, 97. 

Fratricelli, the, belief in commun- 
ism, 66. 

Fundamentum, distinction from titu- 
lus, 64 et seq. 

Funk, Dr., 113, 172, 203. 

Galileo, 159. 

Gand, Henri de, 110, 149. 

Garden of Eden, private property 
in, 55. 

Gasquet, 224. 

Genesis, 137, 226. 

Genoa, the Archbishop of, 207. 

letter from Alexander 

III. to, 187. 

Gentile, prohibition of usury be- 
tween Jew and, 164. 

Gentiles, prohibition of usury not 
imposed on converts from, 168. 

— . — taking of usury ftom, justified, 
165. 



236 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 



Genucian Law, the, interest prohi- 
bited by, 160. 

Gerbert, 14. 

Gerdilius, 100. 

Geraon, 39, 71, 104, 106, 108, 112, 
118, 137, 182, 197. 

Gide and Rist, 9. 

Golden Age, the, private property 
in, 55. 

Gospel, the, preached to the poor, 
137. 

Gospels, the, on usury, 166. 

Goyau, G.,67, 224. 

Haney, L. H., 2, 5, 41, 136. 

Heeren, A. H. L., 146. 

Hettinger, 226. 

Hilary of Poictiers, 60. 

Hincmar, 14. 

Hiring, Thomas Aquinas on, 38. 

Hogan, Dr., 43, 47, 49, 137. 

Hohoff, Abb6, 114, 199. 

Hoatiensis, 188. 

Hoyta, HenricuB de, 19. 

Huet, 47. 

Hunter, W. A., 105, 161. 

Hunting, see Agriculture. 

Idleness, contrasted attitudes of 
ancient and Christian civilisa- 
tions to, 137. 

Income, unearned, approved by 
scholastics, 113. 

justice of, 198 et seg. 

socialist theory of its in- 
justice not supported by scholas- 
tics, 214. 

recognition of, 212. 

Individualism, of Christianity, 12. 

Industry, development of, in thir- 
teenth century, 15. 

Ingolstadt, 211. 

Ingram, Dr. J. K., 2, 3, 4, 12, 17, 
18, 23, 24. 

Innocent ill.. Pope, attitude to 
usury, 175. 

in favour of unearned income, 

207. 

Insurance, a contract of, 210. 

Interamna, monies pietatis at, 196. 

Interesse proximum, suggested alter- 
native term to damnum emergens, 
187. 

Inttresse remotum, suggested alter- 
native term to lucrum ceiswns, 
187. 

Interest, justification of, 184. 



Interest, laws regarding, in Rome, 

160. 
takingofgdiaapproved byGreek 

and Roman philosophers, 161. 

see also Usury. 

Irish Ecclesiastical Record, The, 43, 

47, 49, 109, 137. 
Irish Theological Quarterly, The, 9, 

68, 128, 129, 130, 132, 135. 
Isidore, 95. 
Isidore of Seville, 15. 
his opinions on money 

regarded as final, 214. 
Italian States, forced loans in the, 

196. 
Ivo, 169. 

Janet, P. A. R., 59, 61, 89, 91, 93, 

97. 
Jannet, Claudio, 183. 
Janssen, J., 28, 68, 86, 125, 138, 

139, 141, 143, 150, 154, 224. 
Jarrett, Fr., 83, 84, 
Jeremiah, 165. 
Jerusalem, the Church of, social 

system in, 44 et seq. 
St. Paul's appeal for funds, 

48. 
the Council of, prohibition of 

usury not imposed on converts 

by, 168. 
Jesuits, the, invention of trinus 

contractus attributed to, 211. 
JeiBxshEncyclopaedia, The,oa usury, 

165. 
Jews, attitude to usury, 160, 165. 
■ — — prohibition of usury between, 

164. 
John of Salisbury, 14. 
Jourdain, 5, 14, 16, 149, 176, 183, 

221. 
Jus ahiiiendi, 87. 

divinum, 173. 

kumanum, 174. 

Tiaturale, 173. 

Just price, a Christian conception, 

104. 
authorities empowered to 

fix, 108. 
comparison of mediseval 

theory with that of classical econ- 
omists, 125. 
difference from modern 

competition price, 116. 

elasticity of, 117. 

factors determining, 109 

tt seg. 



INDEX 



237 



Just price, fixed by common esti- 
mation, 115 et seq. 

fixing of, by law, 106. 

in money-lending, 179. 

mediseTalteachingon,103. 

necessity for adhering to, 

108. 

of wages, see Wages. 

rules for guidance in fixing 

by law, 107. 

nature of, 127 et seq. 

value of canonical doc- 
trine, 123. 

Justiniafi, rates of interest fixed 
by, 161. 

Justinian Code, 28, 172. 

Kellbhbe, Father, 129, 130, 131, 

132, 133, 134. 
Knabenbaur, 166. 
B:nies, 80, 114, 135. 
Koran, the, the taking of interest 

forbidden in, 166. 

Labour, as title to property, 65. 

Christian teaching on its dig- 
nity, 137. 

division into honourable and 

degrading, 141. 

necessity and honourableness 

of all forms of, 140. 

only one constituent in the 

estimation of just price, 157. 

— ^ relative importance of, in de- 
termining value, 113. 

the motives which should ac- 
tuate, 153. 

Lactantius, 45, 56 et seq., 91. 

Langenstein, 19, 107, 111, 112, 121, 
122, 124, 137, 141, 203. 

Larceny Act, the, 27. 

Lateran Council, the, judgment in 
favour of montesjiielatis, 197. 

Councils, the, of 1139 and 

1179, declaration against usurers 
by, 174. 

Laurentius de Eodiilphis, 157, 195, 
209. 

Law, natural and positive, in rela- 
tion to property, 64. 

Le Blant, 216. 

Lecky, 176, 211. 

Leo the Grreat, 146. 

Lessius, 117, 124. 

Letting, Thomas Aquinas on, 38. 

I^evaaseur, 138, 139, 224. 

Leviticus, 163. 



Liberalitai, its opposing vices, 74. 

meaning of, 73. 

Liberality, relation to justice, 73. 
Lisieux, Bishop of, see Oresme, 

Nicholas- 
List, 146, 224. 

Loan, Thomas Aquinas on, 38. 
Loans, analogy between sales and, 

182. 
forced, in the Italian States, 

195. 

the real nature of, 178. 

Locatio operarum, 210, 213. 
Logic, mediasval study of, 14. 
Loria, 149. 

Lucca, montes pietatis at, 196. 
Lucrum cessans, 185, 186, 195, 202. 
recognition of, 187 et 

seq. 
Lyons, Council of, ordinances 

against usurers, 175. 

Maoleod, 218. 

Magnificentia, duty of, 77. 

Maimonides, 164. 

Malthusianism, 225. . 

Mansi, 169. 

Mantua, monies pietatis at, 196. 

Manufacture, position in the artes 

possessivae, 142 et seq. 
Marcian Capella, 15. 
Marriage, attitude of Thomas 

Aquinas towards, 225. 
Marshall, 30. 
Martin v.. Pope, his bull on rent, 

204. 
Marx, Karl, theory of value not 

supported by scholastics, 113, 114. 
Mastrofini, his interpretation of a 

verse of St. Luke, 166. 
Maximian, rescript regarding sales, 

105. 
Mayronia, Francois de, 149, 156. 
Mediaeval, interpretation of, 3 et 

seq. 
Menger, Anton, 199. 
Merchant, the, necessity for control 

of, see Commerce. 
Metz-Noblat, de, 183. 
Meyer, Rudolph, 198. 
Middle Ages, definition of the term 

by various authorities, 3 et teq. 
early writers of, no re- 
ference to economic questions, 13. 
Milan, 211. 
Mohammed, prohibition of usury by 

his followers, 160. 



238 MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 



MohammedanB, taking of interest 
by, forbidden, 166. 

Monasteries, the, their example in 
manual labour, 138, 223. 

Money, as a form of capital, 201. 

a vendible oommodity, 158. 

changing, aee Cambium. 

different kinds of variation of, 

219 et seq. 

ignorance of early Middle Ages 

regarding, 214 et aeq. 

invention of, 103. 

most suitable metals for, 219. 

not discussed by early medi- 

aBval writers, 14. 

sterility of, 180. 

the sovereign's power in rela- 
tion to, 219. 

treatment of, by Isidore of 

Seville^ 15. 

utility of, as treated by Aris- 
totle, 16. 

variations in value of, 216 et 

seq. 

value of, not to be changed un- 
necessarily, 219. 

Monopolies, mediaeval views on, 
124. 

Monies pietatis, 194. 

attitude of the Church to, 

197. 

controversy over interest 

charged by, 196. 

Montes prqfani, 195 et seq. 

Moral theology, 130. 

Morality, economic, in the Middle 
Ages, 10. 

More, Sir Thomas, 48. 

Mosheim, 44. 

Munificence, duty of, 77. 

Mutuum, 202, 210, 213, 214. 

nature of, 178, 183. 

risk involved in, 192. 

KaturaIi eights, distinction be- 
tween absolute and commensurate 
in slavery, 95. 

Navarrus, 190. 

Necessaries, twokinds distinguished 
by Thomas Aquinas, 83. 

Neumann, 182. 

New Testament, the, 176. 

cited in support of pro- 
hibition of usury, 174. 

Nice, Council of, on usury, 169, 170. 

Nicholas v., Pope, bull on personal 
rent charges, 205. 



Nider, 39, 110, 118, 134, 150, 181, 

193. 
NittijF. S., 43, 69. 
Noel, Conrad, 49. 
Numa, as origin of ' nummi, ' 15. 

OocupANOV, as title to property, 
65. 

Old Testament, the, 176. 

attitude to usury, 163, 

165. 

cited in support of pro- 
hibition of usury, 174. 

Oresme, Nicholas, 143, 215, 216, 
219. 

his influence, 221. 

his work on money, 214, 

217 et seq. 

Origin, 45. 

Or vieto, first m,ontes pietatis started 
at, 196. 

Ownership, see Property. 

Padita, myites pietatis at, 196. 

Palgrave, 30, 105, 112, 135, 212. 

Parma, mantes pietatis at, 196. 

Partnership, division of remunera- 
tion, 209. 

scholastic teaching on, 202, 

205 et seq. 

the two kinds of, 209. 

Parmficentia, a sin, 77, 78. 

Patria potestas, 226. 

Pelagius, views condemned by Coun- 
oU, A.D. 415, 61. 

Pennafort, Raymond de, 27, 149. 

Periculum sortis, 191, 192, 212. 

P6rin, 183, 226. 

Perugia, montes pietatis at, 196. 

Philip the Fair, his method of in- 
creasing the revenue, 216. 

Philosophers, the, their condemna- 
tion of usury, 161. 

Pigonneau, 146. 

Plato, his objection to usury, 161. 

Plutarch, attitude to usury, 163. 

Poena conventionalis, 185. 

difference from interest, 

186. 

Political economy, errors of classi- 
cal school, 8. 

difference between medi- 
aeval and modern methods, 6. 

Pope, the, his denunciation of 
Philip the Fair, 216. 

the spiritual vicar of God, 

10. 



INDEX 



239 



Popes, the, and almsgiving, 69. 

,, pronouncements by, on rent, 

;> 204. 

their protection of rnorUes pie- 

tatis, 197. 

Population, medieeval attitude to, 
224. 

Poverty, as the cause of sin, 78. 

Prescription, as title to property, 
65. 

Price, just, see Just price. 

Friscian, 14. 

Prodigality, an offence against 
liberality, 79. 

a sin towards the individual 

and the community, 78. 

distinction from liberality, 76, 

Production, an honourable vocation. 
226. 

cost of, as a factor in deter- 
mining value. 111 et seq. 

extended, the aim of mediseval 

teaching, 223. 

regulation of, 32. 

Professions, see Labour. 

Profit, of the campsor to be deter- 
mined by just price, 158. 

' Profiteer,' the, doctrine of just 
price a weapon against, 125. 

Profiteering, prohibition of, 151. 

Property, duties attaching to, 69. 

duties in respect of exchange 

of, 102. 

immovable, rule for determin- 
ing value, 120. 

in human beings, 88. 

private, duties attaching to, 

40. 

right of, 39. 

teaching of mediseval 

Church, 41 et seq. 

the foundation of medi- 
aeval economics, 40. 

the keystone of economic 

system of later theologians, 66. 

Proverbs, 165. 

Prutz, 146. 

PscUms, 137, 165, 171. 

Rabanas Maubas, 14. 

Rambaud, 7. 8, 13, 80, 87, 100, 114, 

146, 151, 182, 183, 188, 197, 203, 

213, 215. 
Reformation, the, 211. 
attacks on monastic life durmg, 

138. 
Renaissance, the, 218. 



Rent, pronouncements on, by the 

Popes, 204. 
refusal to pay, in Breslau, 204. 

scholastic teaching on, 202 

et teq. 

Eevue ArcMologique, La,, 61. 

Riches, the early Church on their 
abuse, 53. 

Rickaby, 75. 

Risk, remuneration for, 152, 157, 
191. 

Rist, see Gide. 

Roman Empire, the, fall of, re- 
garded as beginning of Middle 
Ages, 3. 

jurists, their views on slavery 

accepted by Thomas Aquinas, 94. 

Romans, Epistle to the, 48. 

Rome, condemnation of usury by 
the philosophers of, 162, 

laws regarding interest in, 160. 

Numa, King of, 16. 

policy of, enforced by clergy, 

the attitude to manual labour 

in, 137. 
Rosoher, W. G. F., 5, 13, 19, 34, 

46, 48, 87, 88, 107, 108, 112, 114, 

121, 125, 142, 163, 166, 172, 186, 

204 215 217. 
Ryan,' Dr.' J. A., 49, 74, 117, 123, 

135. 

Sabatub, 223. 

St. Ambrose, 49, 52, 60, 82, 171. 

•■ quoted by Aquinas, 71. 

St. Anselm, 14. 

St. Anthony, advice to his followers, 

223. 
St. Augustine, 49, 57, 60, 63, 92, 

93, 97, 98, 105, 146, 154, 172, 

224. 
theory of slavery analysed by 

Janet, 93. 
views on slavery accepted by 

Aquinas, 94 et seq. 
St. Barnabas, 45. 
St. Basil, 49, 153, 171, 224. 

quoted by Aquinas, 71. 

St. Benedict, 152. 

Rule of, 224. 

St. Clement of Alexandria, 45, 49, 

54, 168, 170. 
St. Clement of Rome^ 49, 54. 
St. Cyprian, 45, 50, 168, 170. 
St. Gregory Nazianzen, 54. 
8t. Gregory of Nyssa, 171. 



240 



MEDIEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 



St. Gregory the Great, 49. 

St. Hilary, 171. 

St. Isidore, 62. 
• St. Jerome, 49, 145, 171, 224. 

St. John Chrysostom, 49, 51, 52. 

St. Joseph, represented as a carpen- 
ter, 139. 

St. Justin, 45. 

St. Justin Martyn, 49. 

St. Luoian, 45. 

St. Luke, 82. 

St. Luke, doubtful meaning of a 
verse in, 168. 

interpretation of a doubtful 

verse in, 168, 171. 

St. Macharius, 223. 
St. Matthew, 38, 47. 
St. Pachomius, 223. 
St. Paul, 137. 

attitude to private property 

and communism, 48. 

on possession, cited by St. 

Augustine, 60. 

' teaching on slavery, 89. 

followed by Chris- 
tian teachers, 90. 

St. Peter, 46. 

teaching on slavery, 89. 

St. Peter Damian, 83. 

St. Thomas, see Thomas Aquinas. 

Sale, Roman law as applied to, 104. 

Thomas Aquinas on, 38. 

treatment by fifteenth-century 

writers, 18. 

Sales, analogy between loans and, 
182. 

Salvador, 48. 

Salvian, 55. 

Sapphira, 46, 52. 

Saturnus, result of banishment from 
heaven, 56. 

Saving, an act of liberality, 72 et 
seq. 

Soberer, 146. 

Scotus, Duns, see Duns. 

ScotuS Erigenus, 14. 

Semaine SocicUe de France, La, 49, 
62, 68, 104, 111. 

Seneca, 59, 89, 90. 

view of usury, 163. 

Serfdom, 99. 

Sertillanges, 80. 

Servua, St. Augustine's theory of 
origin, 93. 

Sevona, montes pietatit at, 196. 

Sicily, personal rent charges per- 
mitted in, 205. 



Sidgwiok, Professor Henry, 29, 31. 

Sinigaglia, 225. 

Sixtus v., Pope, condemnation of 
trinus contractus, 211. 

Slater, Father, 109, 128, 129, 130. 

Slavery, analogy with property, 97. 

attitude of Christianity to, 88. 

limits of master's rights, 100. 

three kinds of, 99. 

views of Christian Church and 

philosophers reconciled by Aqui- 
nas, 93 et acq. 

Smith, Adam, 29. 

Societas, 206, 207, 210, 213. 

Socialism, as providing an ethical 
basis of society, 31. 

danger of, 32. 

relation of its economic teach- 
ing to Christianity, 33. 

Socialists, claim to authority of the 
early Christians, 49 et teq. 

attempts to 'construct Utopia, 

228. 

their communism ttjt the 'com- 
munity of user' advocated by 
scholastics, 86. 

their interpretations of St. 

Augustine, 58. 

their main principles, 230. 

their philosophy at variance 

with Christianity, 231. 

their principles not derived 

from mediaeval teaching, 230. 

their view of the Church's 

teaching on usury, 198. 

Sociua stans, 207. 

Solon, laws of, as affecting usury, 
160. 

Songe du Vergier, 225. 

Stagyrite, the, see Aristotle. 

Stoic tradition, the, 58. 

Stoicism, inferiority to Christian 
teaching on slavery, 89. 

Stoics, the, 93. 

Stintzing, 20. 

Sudre, 47, 48. 

Summa Angelica, 186. 

Astesana, 186. 

Pisana, 156. 

Superabundance, relativity of, 75. 

'Teaching,' interpretation of, 3, 
19 et seq. 

mediaeval, its relation to prac- 
tice, 21. 

ethical nature of, 27. 

Temperance, in the use of goods, 70. 



INDEX 



241 



TertnUian, 45, 49, 145, 168, 170. 

Theisaloniant, Epistle to the, 137. 
Thirteenth century, progress made 
in the, IS, 

Thomas Aquinas, 7, 16, 17, 18, 19, 
20, 36, 41, 42, 46, 52, 62 et seq., 
67, 69, 70, 71 et seq., 74 et seq., 
77, 78, 80, 81, 82, 83, 84, 85, 91, 
93, 94, 95, 96, 97, 99, 101, 105, 
111, 112, 114, 117, 119, 121, 131, 
132, 133, 135, 136, 141, 143, 144, 
146, 147, 148, 149, 150, 151, 154, 
156, 162, 167, 173, 174, 176, 182, 
186, 188, 189, 193, 194, 195, 197, 
206, 207, 208, 215, 230. 

Ticinum, Synod of, decree on usury, 
173. 

Tillage, see Agriculture. 

Time, the sale of, 182. 

Tvmothy, 151. 

Titid'os, distinction from fimda- 
mentum, 64. 

Tmctatus Universi Juris, 19. 

Tradesman, see Commerce. 

Trade, tee Commerce. 

Troplong, 226. 

Trimis contractus, 210, 211. 

Trithemius, 85, 124, 137, 149. 

Twelve Tables, the, maximum rate 
of interest fixed by, 160. 



Uneiarwmfcenus, doubtful meaning 

of, 160. 
Usufruct, Aquinas on, 38. 
Usurers, see Usury. 
TTsury and the clergy, 169. 

a sin against justice, 175. 

attitude of the Apostles, 168. 

attitude of various religious 

and legal systems, 160. 
borrowing at, ciroumstanceB 

justifying, 194. 
broader basis of discussion 

after twelfth century, 173. 
dealt with by ecclesiastical 

courts, 175. 

condemned by Councils, 13. 

by philosophers, 161, 162. 

as a sin against charity, 

168, 171. 
controversies over prohibition, 

159. 

definition of, by Lateran Coun- 
cil, 197. 

doubt as to Gospel teaching 

on, 167. 



Usury, ecclesiastical legislation on, 
174. 

inconclusive teaching of the 

early Church, 172. 

increased payment for credit 

regarded as, 119. 

injustice of, according to 

Aristotle, 16. 

in the Old Testament, 163. 

not suppressed by civil law, 

172. 

patristic and episcopal utter- 
ances in favour of, 172. 

not permitted by civil autho- 
rities, 197 et seq. 

popular attitude to, 163. 

prohibition of, 133, 173, 183, 

184. 

proof of justice of un- 
earned income, 213. 

position in canonist doc- 
trine, 33. 

not imposed on converts 

from Gentiles, 168. 

secular legislation j^i" favour of, 

declared void, 175. 

teaching of the early Church, 

167 el seq. 

treatment by fifteenth-century 

writers, 18. 



Value, factors determining, 129. 
not systematically treated till 

fourteenthand fifteenth centuries, 

111. 

See also Price. 

Vaudois, the, belief in communism, 

66. 
Verona, montes pietatit at, 196. 
Viennei Council of, 175. 
Vio, Thomas da, 196. 
Virgin, the Blessed, represented 

spinning, 139. 
Virginity, recommended for the 

few, 225. 
Viterbo, montes pietaiis ttt, 196. 



Wages, rules determining, 120._ 

as factor in cost of production, 

111. 

attitude of mediaeval and mod- 
ern working classes towards 
fixing, 126 et seq. 

fixed by a public authority, 

121. 



242 MEDLEVAL ECONOMIC TEACHING 



Wages, paucity of authority on, 
before sixteenth century, 121. 

Wallon, 90, 137, 140. 

Wealth, theory of, according to 
Aristotle, 16. 



Wealth, not an end in itieU 

80. 
Weber, 206. 
William of Paris, 176.' 
Wolowski, 216, 217, 221. 



Printed by T. snd A. Oonbtasli, Fiintera to Hig H^jeity 
at the EdiDbuigh nnivenitr Preii, Scotland 



OTHER WORKS BY GEORGE O'BRIEN 

Published by Maunsel & Co., Dublin and London. 



THE ECONOMIC HISTORY OF IRELAND IN THE 
SEVENTEENTH CENTURY 

' A volume quite indispensable to the student of Irish affairs.' 

— Wtstminster Gazitie. 

' Mr, O'Brien handles his theme soberly and without bias ; and his calm, 
unflinching analysis and his devotion to the best traditions of scholarship 
make this volume a memorable contribution to Irish economic literature.' 

—Tie Nation. 

' Dr. O'Brien is to be congratulated. . . . The most illuminating account 
of the social and economic life of seventeenth-century Ireland we have ever 
seen, written in an unusually non-partisan spirit.' — The Athtnaeum. 

' Whether the Irish are economical or not, they have produced an economist 
in the person of Dr. O'Brien.'— 7X« Pilot (Boston). 



THE ECONOMIC HISTORY OF IRELAND IN THE 
EIGHTEENTH CENTURY 

' Mr. O'Brien is no political hot-gospeller ; on the contrary, he writes with 
scrupulous moderation, and is less anxious to make points for a side than to 
state and analyse essential facts.' — The Nation. 

' Mr. O'Brien has made a most valuable contribution to the study of Irish 
history, and his book deserves to be widely read,' — Nem Witness. 

' Mr. O'Brien has produced a sincere and useful piece of work,' 

— Manchester Guardian. 

'Mr. O'Brien's book is worthy of its important theme.' 

— Aberdeen Free Press. 

' Mr. O'Brien's scholarly volume is an interesting refutation of the theory, 
which Mr. Bernard Shaw has recently reiterated in public lectures in Dublin, 
that the young Nationalists are romantic dreamers unacquainted with the 
economics of history.' — TAe Z>>a/(New York). 

' It is not every man of strong political opinions who is able to set himself 
as Mr. G. O'Brien has done to examine each element of economic life in its 
bearing for good or for evil on the prosperity of the whole community.' — Hints 
en thi Study of English Economic History, by the late Dr. Cunningham.