Skip to main content

Full text of "Historical philosophy in France and French Belgium and Switzerland"

See other formats


I' 6 

-F6Z 


President  White   Library, 

CORNELL  UNIVERSITY. 


A.557/3 


l6/t/9f 


fib  ufa"'»iH  J£jS 


DATE  DUE 

JUN3     1950 

I 

11 1     UUN    0 107Q 

pee    ?  iVd\tais^:iL\i. 

<mrn:    i§m>f  > 

JAFL22  MSQ  KVt 
SEE— $-f959H"N      ' 


D    16.8.F62rne"  Universi,y  Li"rary 
"^JMULfiffia  and  Fren 


3   1924  027  777 


Cornell  University 
Library 


The  original  of  this  book  is  in 
the  Cornell  University  Library. 

There  are  no  known  copyright  restrictions  in 
the  United  States  on  the  use  of  the  text. 


http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924027777931 


PHILOSOPHY  OF  HISTOET 


"JTOO  SWIJET  ABBIYJBS   TOO   TARDY  AS   TOO   SLOW  " 

—  Shakespeare 


HISTORY 


OF  THE 


PHILOSOPHY    OF    HISTORY 


BY 


ROBERT    FLINT 


CORRESPONDING  MEMBER  OF  THE  INSTITUTE  OF  FRANCE; 

HONORARY    MEMBER    OF    THE    ROYAL    SOCIETY    OF    PALERMO; 

PROFESSOR  IN  THE  UNIVERSITY  OF  EDINBURGH,   ETC. 


NEW   YORK 

CHARLES   SCRIBNER'S   SONS 

1894 

[All  rights  reserved] 


"AS  THE  EARTH  BRINGETH  FORTH  HER  BUD,  AND  AS  THE  GARDEN 
CAUSETH  THE  THINGS  THAT  ARE  SOWN  IN  IT  TO  SPRING  FORTH  ;  SO  THE 
LORD  GOD  WILL  CAUSE  RIGHTEOUSNESS  AND  PRAISE  TO  SPRING  FORTH 
BEFORE    ALL   THE    NATIONS."  —  Isaiah. 


"DIE  GESCHICHTE  1ST  DAS  WISSEN  DER  MENSCHHEIT  VON  SICH,  IHRE 
SELBSTGEWISSHEIT. — SIE  1ST  NICHT  '  DAS  LICHT  UND  DIE  WAHRHEIT,' 
ABER  EIN  SUCHEN  DANACH,  EINE  PREDIGT  DARACF,  EINE  WEIHE  DAZU; 
DEM    JOHANNES    GLEIOH  :     oix    tJv    t4     <pG>S,    dNX*     &TI     papTVptflTTI   ircpl    TOW 

0wt6s."  —  Droysen. 


COPYRIGHT,  1894,  BY 
CHARLES  SCRIBNER'S  SONS 


HISTORICAL     PHILOSOPHY 


IN 


FRANCE 


AND 


FRENCH  BELGIUM  AND  SWITZERLAND 


BT 


ROBERT   FLINT 


NEW  YOKK 

CHARLES   SCRIBNER'S   SONS 
1894 

[All  rights  reserved] 


A.^713 


COPYRIGHT,  1894,  BY 
CHARI.ES  SCRIBNER'S  SONS. 


PKEFACE 


Almost  twenty  years  ago  the  Author  published  a 
volume  in  which  he  endeavoured  to  describe  and  criti- 
cise the  principal  attempts  which  had  been  made  in 
France  and  Germany  philosophically  to  comprehend 
and  explain  the  history  of  mankind. 

Had  he  not  been  called  soon  afterwards  to  a  position 
which  required  for  a  considerable  number  of  years  al- 
most exclusive  devotion  to  a  different  order  of  studies, 
that  volume  would  have  been  followed  by  one  dealing 
in  a  similar  way  with  the  course  and  succession  of 
historical  philosophies  in  Italy  and  England.  But  be- 
fore he  could  resume  the  work,  he  had  become  so  con- 
vinced of  the  necessity  of  altering  and  enlarging  his 
plan,  as  well  as  of  endeavouring  to  improve  the  execu- 
tion, that  he  has  allowed  the  volume  which  he  had 
published  to  remain  out  of  print  for  nearly  a  dozen 
years,  during  which  it  has  only  been  known  through 
the  excellent  French  translation  of  the  late  M.  Carrau. 

He  now  believes  himself  to  be  able  to  make  his  work, 
instead  of  simply  a  connected  series  of  studies,  a  real 
and  comprehensive  history ;  and,  if  life  and  strength 
be  granted,  to  carry  it  on  steadily,  although  not  per- 
haps rapidly,  to  completion. 


yiii  PREFACE 

"v 

For  the  reasons  stated  in  the  Introduction  the  Author 
deems  it  impossible  to  describe  the  course  of  historical 
philosophy  in  a  detailed,  orderly,  and  useful  manner, 
otherwise  than  by  tracing  it  in  the  first  place  in  its 
national  channels.  He  desires  so  to  do  this  that  his 
work  may  be  not  merely  a  history  of  a  department  of 
philosophy,  but  the  history  of  an  interesting  and  in- 
structive phase  of  the  intellectual  development  of  four 
great  nations  —  France,  Germany,  Italy,  and  England. 

Believing  that  in  few,  if  any,  spheres  of  activity  are 
national  tendencies  and  characteristics  more  clearly  dis- 
cernible than  in  that  of  historical  thought,  he  hopes 
that  the  present  volume  will  be  found  to  be  to  some 
extent  a  contribution  to  the  history  of  France,  as  well 
as  of  the  philosophy  of  history ;  and  will  equally  en- 
deavour to  give  to  subsequent  volumes  not  merely  a 
gerTeral  and  philosophical  but  likewise  a  special  and 
national  interest  and  value. 

The  volumes  being  so  far  relatively  distinct  will  be 
published  separately,  although  they  have  a  common 
subject. 

The  one  now  issued  has  been  a  considerable  time  pass- 
ing through  the  press.  Hence  some  writers  treated  of 
in  it  when  alive  are  now  dead.  Hence  also  a  consider- 
able number  of  books  which  would  probably  have  been 
referred  to  if  they  had  appeared  earlier  are  unnoticed. 

The  best  thanks  of  the  Author  are  due  to  his  learned 
friend,  the  Rev.  W.  Hastie,  B.D.,  for  his  assistance  in 
revising  the  proofs  of  the  entire  volume,  and  for  many 
helpful  suggestions. 

Johnstone  Lodge,  Craigmillar  Park, 
Edinbcrsh,  20th  November  1893. 


CONTENTS 

INTRODUCTION 
I. 

PAGE 

Aim  and  scope  of  the  present  work    .....  1 

The  historical  aim        .......  1 

The  critical  aim  .......  3 

Two  different  meanings  of  the  word  "history"         ...  5 

Distinction  between  history  and  nature  ....  7 

Some  definitions  of  history  examined  ....  8 

Historiography  is  an  art  with  a  history  of  its  own    .  .  .12 

Historical  literature  tends  to  become  increasingly  philosophical  .  13 
Growth  of  discussion  on  the  methods  of  historical  inquiry  .  .         14 

The  development  of  human  history  must  be  viewed  in  the  light 

of  all  science  .......         16 

Refutation  of  the  idea  that  there  is  no  Science  of  History   .  .        17 

And  that  there  is  no  Philosophy  of  History  .  .  .  .18 

The  relation  of  science  to  philosophy  ...  19 

How  history  is  both  a  science  and  a  philosophy         .  .  .21 

Why  the  author  does  not  state  at  the  outset  his  own  theory  of 

history        .......  23 

Plan  of  the  work  .  .  .  .  .  ...        24 

Consideration  of  objections  to  it        .  .  .  .  .25 

Importance  of  nationality  in  history  .....        26 


II. 

The  absolute  origin  of  historical  philosophy  cannot  be  discovered  .  28 

How  religious  belief  has  influenced  historical  speculation    .            .  29 
How  philosophy  includes  historical  speculation        .            .            .31 

How  political  disquisition  leads  to  historical  speculation      .            .  34 
The  dependence  of  historical  study  upon  the  general  advance  of 

science        ........  36 


X  CONTENTS 

PAGE 

Influence  of  economic  phenomena  upon  the  development  of  human 

society        ......•■        37 

Historical  philosophy  a  growth  of  history  itself        .  .  .40 


III. 

The  origins  of  historical  narrative      .....         42 
Political  conditions  in  Egypt  and  Assyria  unfavourable  to  the 

development  of  historiography     . 
Historiography  and  historians  in  China 
In  Japan  ...... 

And  in  India    ...... 

The  Jewish  historical  records 

The  Greeks  first  raised  history  to  the  dignity  of  an  independent  art 

Herodotus         ...... 

Thucydides       ...... 

Polybius  ...... 

The  idea  of  a  universal  history  was  the  result  of  the  universal 

empire  of  Rome    ..... 

Csesar  as  a  historian     ..... 

Sallust  ....... 

How  the  strength  of  national  feeling  among  the  Romans  influenced 

their  historiography  .... 

Livy       ....... 

Tacitus  ....... 

Christianity  introduced  the  consciousness  of  a  spiritual  unity  of  the 

human  race,  and  enormously  enriched  history   . 
Eusebius  and  the  early  Christian  historians  . 
How  Christianity  extended  the  field  of  history 
Wherein   the  medieval  chronicles   differed  from  those   of  early 

classical  writers     ..... 

Medieval  historiography  was  predominantly  ecclesiastical 
Gregory  of  Tours  ..... 

Bede       ....... 

Adam  of  Bremen  ..... 

Lambert  of  Hersfeld  and  Otto  of  Freisingen 
Matthew  Paris  ...... 

Vernacular  chronicles  ..... 

The  medieval  mind  had  not  sufficiently  comprehensive  acquaint- 
ance with  historical  facts  to  frame  a  philosophy  of  history 
It  was  also  credulous  of  such  evidence  as  it  possessed 
Inductive  use  of  historical  facts  began  to  be  made  only  at  a  late 

period         ...... 

The  importance  of  a  knowledge  of  Mohammedan  history 

Mohammedan  historiography  and  historians 

Tabari   .  .  . 

Mas'udi  ...... 

The  philosophy  of  history  in  Arabia  . 


CONTENTS  XI 


IV. 


The  growth  of  history  towards  a  scientific  stage  has  been  partly 
the  consequence  and  partly  the  cause  of  the  growth  of  certain 

ideas           ........  87 

I.  The  idea  of  progress  in  the  Oriental  world  .        .  .  .88 

In  Greece  and  Rome  the  course  of  human  history  was  conceived 
of  as  a  process  of  deterioration,  a  progress,  and  a  cycle, 

»    although  in  none  profoundly  or  consistently           .            .  90 

Illustrations  of  this  theory           .....  92 

Christianity  and  the  idea  of  progress      .  .  .  .96 

The  Gnostic  and  Montanist  creeds  .  .  .  .97 

The  Christian  Fathers      .            .                        ...  99 

The  idea  of  progress  in  the  Middle  Ages            .            .            .  101 " 

Roger  Bacon          .......  102 

The  Franciscan  conception  of  human  development       .            .  103 

II.  The  idea  of  progress  implies  that  of  unity  .        .            .            .  104 

Social  consciousness  is  manifested  in  the  lowest  stages  of 

humanity        .......  105 

Comparative  isolation  of  the  great  Oriental  states  inimical  to 

the  conception  of  human  unity        ....  106 

This  conception  in  Egypt,  China,  India,  and  Persia      .            .  107 

The  services  of  Greece  to  the  cause  of  human  unity      .            .  110 

Those  of  Rome      .......  112 

The  Greco-Roman  view  was  destitute  of  self-realising  power   .  114 
Christianity  and  the  idea  of  human  unity          .            .            .  115 
Gradual  realisation  of  the  idea  of  human  unity  in  the  Chris- 
tian world      .......  116 

III.  Freedom  results  from  the  full  realisation  of  all  the  powers  of 

humanity       .......  125 

Bodily  slavery  among  primitive  peoples              .            .            .  127 

Among  the  Jews,  Egyptians,  and  Indian  peoples           .            .  128 

Gradual  disappearance  of  bodily  slavery            .            .            .  129 

The  treatment  of  women  in  relation  to  the  growth  of  liberty  .  131 

Growth  of  liberty  in  its  higher  forms     ....  133 


V. 

Political  speculation  among  the  Greeks 

I.  Plato  failed  to  do  justice  to  historical  reality 

The  ideal  polity  of  his  '  Republic '  .  .  . 

Mr.  Newman's  statement  on  the  8th  and  9th  books  of  the 
'Republic'     ...... 

Some  defects  of  the  Platonic  ideal 
The  '  Laws ' :  Plato's  theory  of  the  development  of  society  and 
government    ...... 

The  '  Statesman '  . 


137 
138 
139 

143 

144 

145 
146 


II.    Aristotle  clearly  recognised  the  political  significance  of  history      147 


CONTENTS 


He  sometimes  abused  the  historical  method 

His  ideal  State      .  •  •  •  •  • 

The  theory  of  revolutions  his  chief  contribution  to  historical 

science  ...••■ 

Other  services  to  the  philosophy  of  history 

III.  Augustine's  intellectual  character 

The  purpose  and  scope  of  his  'De  Civitate  Dei' 
Summary  of  his  historical  theory 

In  spite  of  many  defects,  it  was  a  vast  improvement  on  pre 
vious  theories  of  history       . 

IV.  Ibn  Khaldun  :  sketch  of  his  career 

His  mind  was  not  of  a  speculative  cast  . 
The  value  of  his  '  Universal  History '      . 
Its  aim       ....••• 

His  views  on  society  in  general,  the  physical  basis  of  civilisa- 
tion, and  prophetism  .... 

On  the  civilisation  of  nomadic  and  half-savage  peoples 
On  the  Arabs         ...... 

On  the  rise,  government,  and  fall  of  empires 

On  public  spirit     ...... 

On  the  law,  course,  and  phases  of  history 
On  a  settled  and  concentrated  civilisation 
The  last  two  sections  of  the  work 


PAGE 

148 
149 

150 
151 
152 
152 
153 

158 
158 
161 
162 
163 

164 
165 
166 
168 
169 
170 
171 
172 


THE   PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Chapter  I.  —  THE  PROGRESS  OF  HISTORIOGRAPHY,  AND 
THE  BEGINNINGS  OF  HISTORICAL  PHILOSOPHY  IN 
FRANCE:    BODIN 

I. 


Medieval  historiography  was  almost  exclusively  in  the  hands  of 
ecclesiastics  ...... 

Rise  of  lay  chroniclers  ..... 

Consideration  of  the  works  of  Villehardouin,  Joinville,  Froissart, 
Monstrelet,  and  Commines  .... 

Place  to  be  assigned  to  Commines      .... 

The  influences  which  affected  French  historiography  in  the  six- 
teenth century       ...... 

De  Thou's  '  Historia  sui  temporis '     . 

The  political  treatises  of  La  Boetie  and  "Junius  Brutus"    . 

Hotman  made  the  first  attempt  to  found  th£  right  of  liberty  upon 
an  historical  basis  ..... 

Pasquier's  '  Researches '..... 

Thierry's  estimate  of  the  work 


176 
178 

179 
181 

184 
186 

186 

187 
188 
188 


CONTENTS 


II. 

Bodin  was  the  first  French  writer  who  took  a  philosophical  survey 

of  history  .... 
Aim  of  his  '  Methodus  ' 
Some  previous  works  on  historical  method 
The  place  he  assigns  to  human  history 
His  recognition  of  law  in  history 
His  recognition  of  progress  in  history 
He  attempted  to  explain  events  chiefly  by  physical  and  political 

causes         ...... 

He  developed  the-'Aristotelian  theory  of  revolutions 

His  theories  on  the  origin  of  nations,  and  on  epochs  in  history 

Popeliuiere's  '  History  of  Histories '  . 


190 
192 

192 
193 
195 
196 

193 
199 
199 
200 


Chapter  II.  — HISTORIOGRAPHY  AND  HISTORICAL  REFLEC- 
TION IN  FRANCE  IN  THE  SEVENTEENTH  CENTURY: 
BOSSUET 

I. 


Growth  of  absolutism  in  France 

Its  influence  upon  historiography 

Historical  value  of  the  "  Memoirs  "  of  this  period 

Ecclesiastical  historiography  . 

The  histories  of  Duplets  and  Mezeray 

Writers  on  historic  method     . 

Bayle's  influence  upon  historiography 

Influence  of  Cartesianism  on  historical  study 

The  idea  of  progress  in  Pascal,  Perrault,  Fontenelle,  &c 

The  controversy  as  to  the  relative  merits  of  the  ancients  and  moderns 


202 
203 
203 
204 
205 
206 
209 
210 
212 
213 


II. 

Bossuet :  his  character  and  beliefs      .... 

The  originality  of  his  conception  of  history  discussed 

The  aim  of  his  '  Discours '       . 

His  division  of  history  into  epochs     .... 

His  uncritical  use  of  the  Biblical  narrative   . 

His  delineation  of  the  course  of  religion 

His  main  thesis  regarding  it  not  established 

Attempted  to  explain  the  causes  of  the  rise  and  fall  of  empires 

Merits  and  defects        ...... 

The  true  and  the  false  in  his  attempt  to  rest  the  philosophy  of  his 

tory  on  the  doctrine  of  Providence 
He  erred  as  to  the  final  cause  of  history 
Did  justice  only  to  the  Christian  element  in  history 
Bossuet  defended  against  Mr.  Buckle's  criticisms 
Mr.  Huth's  defence  of  Buckle  considered 


216 
217 
218 
219 
220 
220 
222 
222 
223 

225 
227 
229 
230 
233 


XIV 


CONTENTS 


Chapter    III.  -  THE    EIGHTEENTH    CENTURY:     GENERAL 
SURVEY -MONTESQUIEU,   TURGOT,  AND  VOLTAIRE 


The  state  of  France  under  Louis  XIV.  and  his  successor     . 
Public  opinion,  though  long  submissive,  gradually  became  a  hostile 
power         .  •  •  •  •  •  • 

The  French  philosophy  of  the  eighteenth  century  was  practically 

identical  with  public  opinion       . 
Characteristics  of  this  philosophy :  — 

Rationalistic  and  revolutionary 
Empirical  and  materialistic  . 
Militant  and  positive  . 

Propagated    certain    great    and   hitherto   unappreciated 
truths      ....-■ 

Attempted  to  discover  meaning  in  history  . 
Condition  of  historiography  in  this  century  :  Montfaucon,  &c. 
Freret's  historical  and  critical  genius 
His    researches    in    ancient    chronology,   geography,  philosophy, 

mythology,  &c.      . 
The  general  histories  of  Daniel  and  Velly 
Rollin  and  Vertot         ...... 

Fresnoy  and  Rollin  on  historic  method 

Hardouin  and  historical  scepticism     .... 

Summary  of    the   debate    in    the   Academy   of    inscriptions    on 

historical  certitude  and  credibility  of  early  Roman  history 
Beaufort  ....... 

Niebuhr's  estimate  of  Beaufort's  work 


PAGE 

235 

238 

240 

241 
241 
242 

242 
243 
244 
246 

247 
249 
250 
251 
253 

255 
260 
261 


II. 

Montesquieu's  '  Lettres  Persanes '      .            .            .            .            .  262 

The  value  of  his  '  Considerations '     .            .            .            .            .  263 

The  originality  of  his  work  discussed             ....  265 

The  central  conception  of  the  '  Esprit  des  Lois '       .            .            .  266 
Montesquieu's  method  defective  inasmuch  as  he  did  not  systemati- 
cally compare  coexistent  and  consecutive  social  states  .            .  267 
Often   explained  historical  facts  when  he  failed  to  reach  their 

general  laws          .......  268 

The  accusation  that  he  confounded  fact  with  right  not  proved        .  269 

He  had  an  inaccurate  notion  of  inductive  law          .            .             .  269 
In  treating  of  the  influences  of  governments  he  confounded  two 

distinct  methods  .  .  .  .  .  .  .271 

Montesquieu  on  the  theory  of  the  three  powers  ;  his  eulogy  of  the 

British  Constitution          ......  273 

His   defective   method  led  him  to  exaggerate  the   influence  of 

physical  agencies,  and  to  overlook  that  it  is  chiefly  indirect      .  274 


CONTENTS  XV 

PAGE 

He  proved  and  applied  the  principle  that  the  course  of  human  his- 
tory is  chiefly  determined  by  general  causes       .            .            .  277 
He  introduced  the  economical  element  into  historical  science          .  277 
The  concluding  books  of  his  work      .....  278 
His  services  to  historical  philosophy  .....  279 

HI. 

Turgot's  character        .......  280 

His  views  on  the  services  rendered  by  Christianity  to  mankind  .  281 
He  first  made  the   idea  of  progress  the   "  organic  principle  of 

history"     .  .  .  .  ...  .281 

The  profundity,  comprehensiveness,  and  consistency  of  his  view  of 

human  progression            ......  283 

He  saw  clearly  that  progress  had  not  been  a  uniform  process          .  285 

His  sketch  of  a  '  Political  Geography '            .            .            .            .  286 

He  anticipated  Comte's  law  of  the  three  states          .            .            .  286 

But  gave  it  no  irreligious  application             ....  288 

IV. 

Why  such  different  estimates  have  been  formed  of  Voltaire's  char- 
acter and  influence           ......  289 

His  intellect,  aims,  and  attainirients  .            .            .            •            .  290 
His  '  Charles  XII.'  and  '  Siecle  de  Louis  XIV.'         .            .            .291 
How  the  design  of  his  '  Essai  sur  les  Mceurs '  differed  from  that  of 

Bossuet,  Montesquieu,  or  Turgot             ....  292 

His  so-called  '  Philosophy  of  History '            .            .            .            .  294 

Summary  of  it  .             .             .             .             .             .             •             •  295 

Qualities  displayed  in  his  '  Essai ' :  — 

Originality     ........  296 

Critical  spirit  <".  .  .  .  .297 

Independence  of  judgment   .....  298 

Mean  conception  of  human  nature  ....  299 

Imperfect  idea  of  civilisation            ....  300 

Hostility  to  religiou  ......  300 

Want  of  comprehensive  vision          ....  302 

And  of  philosophical  depth  .....  303 

The  'Essai'    showed  the  strength   and  weakness   of  Voltaire's 

intellect      .            . 304 


Chapter  IV.  —  EIGHTEENTH   CENTURY—  Continued: 
ROUSSEAU   TO   CONDORCET 

I. 

How  peaceable  reformation  might  have  been  accomplished  under  a 

strong  king  .......      305 

Influence  of  the  revolutionary  spirit  upon  historical  literature         .      307 


XVI  CONTENTS 

PAGE 

Rousseau's  character  and  influence    .....  307 

He  contended  that  the  sciences  and  arts  have  depraved  the  morals 

and  manners  of  mankind             .....  308 

Summary  of  his  '  Discourse  on  Inequality '  .            .             .             .  309 

Its  teaching  led  towards  anarchism  .....  311 

His  '  Social  Contract '  was  essentially  dogmatic  and  unhistorical    .  312 

How  Rousseau's  tenets  affected  social  speculation  and  practice       .  313 

Morelly's  social  theories         .                         ....  314 

Mably's  character  and  beliefs  .  .  .  .  .315 

His  social  and  historical  writings      .....  316 

Rousseau,  Morelly,  and  Mably,  founded  the  socialistic  theory  of 

history     .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .318 

Condillac's  'Universal  History'  was  defective  in  research  and  criti- 
cism        ........  318 

Represented  intellectual  progress  as  entirely  dependent  upon  the 

use  made  of  language     ......  319 

Some  attempts  to  explain  history  by  means  of  hypotheses  sug- 
gested by  science             ...                         .             .  320 

Raynal's  '  Settlements  and  Trade  of  Europeans '      .            .             .  322 

Volney's  '  Ruins '  summarised            .                                     .  323 

II. 

Condorcet :  the  circumstances  in  which  his  '  Sketch  of  the  Progress 

of  the  Human  Spirit '  was  written  ....       325 

Its  fundamental  idea .......      327 

The  nine  great  epochs  in  human  development  .  .  .      327 

Defects  of  this  division  ......      328 

Exaggerated  and  inconsistent  view  of  human  perfectibility  .      329 

Originality  and  importance  of  his  chapter  on  the  future  of  the 

human  race  .......      330 

He  maintained  the  direction  of  progress  to  be  towards  — 

(1)  the  destruction  of  inequality  between  nations; 

(2)  the  destruction  of  inequality  between  classes ;  and 

(3)  the  improvement  of  individuals. 

These  tendencies  considered  ....      331 

Discussion  of  his  doctrine  of  indefinite  perfectibility  .  .      334 

Walckenaer's  '  Essay  on  the  History  of  Humanity ' .  .339 


Chapter  V.  — THE   NINETEENTH    CENTURY:    GENERAL 
REMARKS  —  HISTORIOGRAPHY 

I. 

The  despotism  of  Napoleon  was  unfavourable  to  historical  science  340 

Some  conditions  which  fostered  the  growth  of  historical  theories : 

Change  in  philosophical  belief         ....  341 

Revival  of  religion  ....  342 


CONTENTS  XV11 

PAGE 

Rise  of  Romanticism  in  literature   ....  343 

Change  in  political  spirit      .....  344 

Tendency  toward  socialism  .....  345 
In  all  these  changes  France  was  affected  by  the  general  movement 

of  Europe 346 

II. 

Works  of  Daunou,  Ginguene,  and  Michaud  .            .            .  347 

Madame  de  StaeTs  influence  upon  historical  literature         .  348 

Works  of  Sismondi  and  Constant       ....  350 

Chateaubriand's  writings  and  influence         .                        .            .  351 
Augustin  Thierry  almost  perfected  historiography  as  a  literary  art ; 

his  works  ........  353 

De  Barante's  '  Dues  de  Burgogne '      .            .            .            .            .  354 

Mignet's  works  and  his  historical  theory       ....  355 

Thiers's  '  History  of  the  Revolution '  defended  against  Carlyle's 

criticisms  ........  356 

His  'History  of  the  Consulate  of  the  Empire'  marred  by  intensity 

of  patriotism         .......  358 

Erench  historical  workers  of  the  nineteenth  century            .            .  359 

Improvement  in  French  historiography          ....  360  ■ 

Historians  of  the  various  schools        .....  361 

Summary  of  the  contents  of  Daunou's  '  Cours  d'Etudes  Historiques '  363 

Cros-Mayreville  on  historical  methodology    ....  365 


Chapter  VI.  — THE  ULTRAMONTANIST  AND  LIBERAL 
CATHOLIC  SCHOOLS 

I. 

The  advocates  of  the  ultramontanist  school  were  moved  by  a  par- 
tisan purpose         .......  366 

Their  three  best  representatives  —  De  Maistre,  De  Bonald,  and  De 

Lamennais  .......  367 

Their  conception  of  the  principles  of  the  Revolution  .  368 

Their  antagonism  to  the  philosophy  of  sensation  .  .  369 

And  to  modern  philosophy      .....  370 

Their  defence  of  absolute  authority  as  the  basis  of  society  was 

founded  upon  their  theory  of  the  origin  and  nature  of  language  372 

Denial  of  the  doctrine  of  progress      ....  373 

Contempt  for  individual  reason  and  will       ....  374 

Theory  that  society  is  an  organic  system       ....  374 

Their  defence  of  the  authority  of  the  Church  .  .  .  376 

And  of  the  State  .......  378 

Professed  to  find  Biblical  support  for  their  theorems  .  .  378 

De  Bonald's  historical  formulae  .....  379 

Fall  and  reappearance  of  ultramontanism     .  .  380 


Xviii  CONTENTS 


II. 


III. 

Rise  of  the  Liberal  Catholic  School    . 
Why  it  failed  to  attain  its  ends 
It  produced  a  number  of  influential  historical  works 
Characteristics  of  Gratry's  '  Law  of  History ' 
Outline  of  his  theory  of  history 
He  pointed  out  the  dependence  of  political  and  social  progress  upon 
moral  progress 


PAGE 


Ferrand  and  the  theory  of  revolutions  ....  381 

Ballanche's  character  and  writings     .  382 

His  theory  of  historical  development  .  •  ■  383 

Recognised  in  history  the  combination  of  liberty  and  necessity      .  385 

His  eschatology  ....•••  386 


386 
387 
387 
389 
390 

392 


Other  historical  philosophers  of  the  Liberal  Catholic  School  .      393 

Chapter  VII.  — THE   SOCIALISTIC   SCHOOLS 


Distinctive  principle  of  Socialism  .....  394 
Saint-Simon's  character  and  works  .....  395 
His  indebtedness  to  other  writers  .....  397 
The  place  he  assigns  to  the  science  of  history  .  .  .      397 

His  law  of  two  states  from  which  Comte's  law  of  three  states  must 

have  been  derived  ......      398 

His  attempt  to  explain  history  by  physical  law         .  .  .      400 

He  raised  his  historical  philosophy   on   the  foundation   laid  by 

Condorcet .  ...  .  .  .  .402 

Its  leading  principle  is  that  general  intelligence  and  individual 

intelligence  are  developed  according  to  the  same  law,  and  pass 

through  precisely  parallel  stages  ....      402 

His  doctrine  of  the  alternation  of  organic  and  critical  periods  in 

history       ........      403 

He  attempted  to  arrange  the  facts  of  history  into  series  according 

to  the  chief  phases  of  human  nature  ....  404 
Saint-Simon  also  attempted  to  arrange  the  various  societies  of  men 

into  a  scale  graduated  according  to  their  various  degrees  of 

culture       ........      405 

He  assumed  that  the  lowest  stage  of  culture  was  representative  of 

the  oldest  ........      406 

His  views  on  the  social  future  were  optimistic  .  .  .      406 

His  religion  meant  simply  philanthropy        .  .  .      407 

Fourier's  works  and  characteristics    .....      408 

His  cosmogony  and  theology  in  relation  to  his  historical  speculations      410 


CONTENTS  xix 

PAGE 

His  law  of  passional  attraction          .            .            .  .            .411 

Divided  history  into  four  great  periods                      .  412 

The  successive  stages  of  the  infancy  of  the  human  race  413 

The  three  latter  periods         .                                     .  .419 

His  eschatology          .            .                                   .  420 


II. 

Literary  life  of  M.  Buchez     ......  422 

The  principles  and  purpose  of  his  '  Introduction  to  the  Science  of 

History'  ........  422 

His  definition  of  the  science  of  history  ....  423 

The  dependence  of  that  science  upon  the  ideas  of  humanity  and 

progress  .....  .  .  424 

His  views  on  the  methods  of  the  science  of  history  .                         .  425 
His  laws  of  historical  variation          .                                     .            .  427 
His  division  of  history  into  four  epochs,  each  initiated  by  a  reve- 
lation      .            .                                                  .  428 
General  estimate  of  his  work                                                  .  430 
The  career  of.Leroux             .                                     .            .  430 
His  '  Refutation  of  Eclecticism '                                              .  431 
The  theory  of    historical   development   expounded    in    his   'De 
l'Humanite '  rests  on  his  definition   of    man  — "  an   animal 
transformed  by  reason,  and  united  to  humanity  "     .  433 
His  view  of  continuous  progress        ....  433 

His  axiom  of  solidarity  and  doctrine  of  transmigration       .  435 
He  represented  progress  as  a  continuous  advance  towards  equality, 
with  three  stages  corresponding  to  the  three  chief  forms  of 

caste         ...  .  .  436 


III. 

L.  Blanc's  historical  philosophy        .  437 

Criticism  of  it  .  .  .  .  438 

Proudhon's  character  and  influence  .  .  439 

He  endeavoured  to  prove  that  religion,  philosophy,  and  science  are 

the  three  epochs  in  the  education  of  mankind  .  .  .  441 

His  views  on  history  .......  441 

Defined  progress  as  "the  self-justification  of  humanity  under  the 

impulsion  of  the  ideal "  .  .  .  .  .  .  443 

Held  an  extreme  view  of  the  all-sufficiency  of  moral  law     .  .  444 

Was  opposed  to  the  principle  of  nationality,  and  advocated  the 

establishment  of  small  industrial  communities  .  .  .  444 

His  relation  to  Comte  ....  445 

Odysse-Barot's  letters  on  war  and  peace        ....  446 

Regarded  the  great  European  States  as  factitious  nationalities  447 

Conceived  of  a  nationality  as  a  purely  geographical  fact      .  447 

Criticism  of  his  three  so-called  laws  .  ...  448 


XX  CONTENTS 

Chapter  VIII.  —  SPIRITUALISTIC  MOVEMENT:  SO-CALLED 
ECLECTIC  AND  DOCTRINARIAN  HISTORICAL  PHILOS- 
OPHY 

I. 

PAGE 

Cousin's  career  and  influence             .             .                         •  452 

The  services  rendered  by  him  to  philosophy                          .  453 

His  relation  to  Hegel  ....••  455 
His  view  of  the  connection  between  psychology  and  the  philosophy 

of  history             .....-•  456 

He  errs  in  substituting  human  reason  for  human  nature  .  .  458 
In  his  division  of  intelligence  into  spontaneous  and  reflective,  he 

confuses  a  number  of  distinctions  ....  459 
His  distribution  of  history  into  the  three  epochs  of  the  infinite, 

finite,  and  their  relation,  rests  on  an  inaccurate  analysis  of 

reason,  and  is  inconsistent  with  facts     ....  464 

His  optimism              .......  467 

His  views  regarding  the  influence  of  places  on  history  inconsistent 

and  erroneous      .            .                         ....  467 

His  theory  of  nations  and  of  war  469 

The  theory  of  nations  examined'                    .             .                         •  470 

The  theory  of  war  examined              .                         .  471 

His  theory  of  great  men                                  .  473 

Examination  of  it                               .                                      .  475 


II. 

Jouffroy's  character  and  writings      .             .                         .  479 

Summary  of  his  '  Reflections '  .      480 

Consideration  of  two  theories  contained  therein                    .  .      483 

Summary  of  his  essay  '  On  the  Present  State  of  Humanity '  .      484 

How  far  it  is  inconclusive      ...                         .  .      486 
Dissent  from  his  speculations  as  to  the  relation  of  England,  France, 

and  Germany  to  the  future  of  humanity                         .  .      487 

III. 

Connection  of  doctrinaire  politics  with  eclectic  philosophy  490 

Guizot's  relation  to  Cousin    .                         ...  490 

Guizot's  character  and  career                                                   .  491 

As  historian  and  historical  philosopher         .             .  492 

His  explanation  of  the  fall  of  the  Roman  empire     .             .  494 

His  essay  on  the  '  Representative  System  in  England '         .  .      496 

The  connection  between  his  two  '  Histories  of  Civilisation '  .      496 
Holds  French  civilisation  to  be  the  type  or  model  of  European 

civilisation  ...  ...       497 

This  opinion  shown  to  be  illusory     ...  .      499 

Statement  of  his  view  of  civilisation,  and  criticism  of  it      .  .       502 


CONTENTS 


XXI 


How  he  distinguishes  ancient  from  modern  civilisation 
His  vindication  of  the  idea  of  political  legitimacy     . 
Its  futility         ...... 

Summary  of  his  '  Course  of  1829 '       . 

The  scientific  spirit  and  character  of  his  method 

His  proof  of  the  existence  of  historical  science 


PAGE 

504 
505 
506 
508 
509 
510 


IV. 

Javary's  '  Idea  of  Progress '     .....  511 

Bouillier  affirms  the  existence  of  intellectual  progress,  but  denies 

that  of  moral  progress      .....  512 

Refuses  to  admit  that  there  can  be  a  law  of  progress  .  .513 

Fails  to  draw  the  true  distinction  between  the  progressive  and  un- 
progressive  in  the  species,  and  does  not  see  that  moral  gains 
are  constantly  being  transmitted  ....       514 

His  reason  for  denying  the  existence  of  a  law  of  progress  is  in- 
sufficient    ........       515 

Caro  on  progress  and  on  historical  philosophy  .  .  .       516 

Carrau's  delineation  of  the  course  of  progress  .  .  .       517 


Guizot's  influence  upon  succeeding  French  historians           .  519 

De  Tocqueville's  aversion  to  general  historical  speculation  .  519 

His  '  Democracy  in  America '  an  epoch-making  work           .            .  520 
His  forecasts  of  the  future       .            .            .            .            .            .521 

His  fears  for  the  self-arrestment  of  democracy  were  exemplified  in 

French  history      .......  522 

Need  not  necessarily  be  fulfilled         .....  523 

His  '  Old  Regime  and  the  Revolution  '  523 


VI. 

Barchou's  '  Essay  on  the  Philosophy  of  History ' 
His  Evolutionism  .... 

The  stages  of  history   .... 
His  historical  eschatology 
Lavollee  ..... 


524 
525 
526 
527 
528 


Chapter  IX.  — THE  DEMOCRATIC   HISTORICAL  SCHOOL 

I. 


Democracy  in  France  . 
Michelet's  early  writings 
How  he  was  influenced  by  Vico 


529 
530 
531 


XX11 


CONTENTS 


And  by  Guizot  .  .  .  •  • 

His  '  History  of  France ' 

His  treatment  of  the  French  Revolution 

The  '  Bible  of  Humanity ' 

The  relation  of  his  historical  philosophy  to  that  of  Hegel 

Represents  history  as  the  progressive  triumph  of  liberty 

His  account  of  the  course  of  human  progress 

It  wants  scientific  precision     . 


PAGE 

532 
533 
534 
536 
537 
538 
538 
541 


II. 

Career  and  early  works  of  Quinet       . 

How  he  was  influenced  by  Herder      .  .  .  • 

Regards  history  as  the  manifestation  of  freewill 

Inculcates  the  fraternity  of  nations    . 

Maintains  that  religion  is  the  generative  principle  of  civilisation 

His  protest  against  the  optimism  of  the  doctrinarian  historical 

philosophy  .... 

Its  substantial  justice  ... 
The  logical  error  of  the  doctrinarian  historians 
The  merits  and  defects  of  his  '  Revolution '   . 
The  essential  conception  of  '  The  Creation  '   . 
Its  leading  ideas  and  characteristics  . 
The  parallelisms  of  nature  and  humanity 
Quinet's  prophecy  of  the  future  of  humanity 
'  The  New  Spirit '         .  .  .  . 

Other  historical  theorists  of  the  democratic  school 


542 
543 
544 
546 
547 

548 
551 
552 
554 
556 
556 
558 
561 
562 
562 


III. 

How  the  Revolution  of  1848  and  the  succeeding  events  influenced 
historical  thought  in  France        .  .  .  .  . 

Romieu's  doctrine  of  force      ... 

Guchan  and  Troplong  on  Csesarism    .... 

Napoleon's  ' History  of  Julius  Csesar ' 

Democratic  writers  attempt  to  discredit  the  dominant  Csesarism 

De  Ferron  in  his  '  Theory  of  Progress '  combines  the  principles  of 
Vico  and  Saint-Simon,  and  combats  Csesarism  . 

The  aberrations  of  democracy  in  France  have  produced  a  number 
of  writers  critical  of,  and  hostile  to,  the  democratic  spirit 

D'Ussel's 'Public  Spirit  in  History'  .... 

His  view  of  the  advantages  and  dangers  of  democracy 

Benloew's  conception  of  the  laws  of  historical  movement     . 


563 
564 
565 
565 
567 

567 

569 
570 
571 
572 


CONTENTS  XX111 

Chapter  X.  —  HISTORICAL   PHILOSOPHY    OF    NATURALISM 
AND   POSITIVISM 

I. 

PAGE 

Revival  of  the  eighteenth-century  sensationalism  in  the  shape  of 

Naturalism  and  Positivism         ....  575 

Aim  and  method  of  Charles  Comte's  '  Treatise  on  Legislation '      .       576 
He  exaggerated  the  influence  of  physical  nature  upon  human  de- 
velopment .......       577 

Represented  civilisation   as  having   advanced  from  the  equator 

northwards  .......       578 

Failed  to  recognise  that  history  is  essentially  the  manifestation  of 

human  nature      ......  578 

Auguste  Comte's  life  and  system       ....  579 

He  was  virtually  ignorant  of  German  philosophy     .  582 

How  he  was    influenced    by   the    empirical    philosophy  of    the 

eighteenth  century  .....  583 

By  the  social  and  religious  reaction  under  the  First  Empire  .       583 

And  by  the  socialism  of  Saint-Simon  ....       584 

His  character  and  temperament        .  .       587 

General  aim  of  his  labours    .  .  .       588 

The  place  of  historical  philosophy  in  his  system  .  589 

He  attempts  to  combine  the  truths  of  order  and  of  progress,  and  so 
to  avoid  the  one-sidedness  both  of  the  reactionists  and  of  the 
revolutionists      .......       590 

In  his  social  statics  Comte  underestimates  the  value  of  individual 

independence       ....  .      591 

He  never  views  history  from  a  purely  scientific  standpoint,  but  is 

always  influenced  by  practical  interests  .  .  592 

His  theory  of  social  dynamics  represents  human  progress  as  con- 
nected with  progress  in  the  physical  world        .  .  .      593 
and  with  the  development  of  social  order  .            .  .       594 
directed  towards  the   gradual  triumph  of   reason   over 

instinct .......       594 

modified  in  the  rate  of  its  advance  by  various  causes        .       595 
invariable  in  its  general  direction  and  in  the  succession  of 

its  stages  ...  .595 

regulated  in  its  course  by  human  intellect .  595 

The  three  chief  laws  regulative  of  human  evolution  .  .       596 

The  laws  of  active  and  effective  evolution  are  worthless  .       599 

The  three  stages  of  intellectual  evolution     ....       599 

His  survey  of  universal  history  is  marred  by  insufficient  acquaint- 
ance with  facts    .......       600 

The  chief  points  in  this  survey  :  — 

1.  Leaves  out  of  view  all  central  and  eastern  Asia  .       601 

2.  Gives  an  extravagantly  laudatory  account  of  fetichism      602 

3.  The   "abstract  appreciation"   of    polytheism    is    ad- 

mirable ....  604 


II. 

Opposing  positivist  parties     ..... 

Littre's  relation  to  Comte      .  .  . 

He  restricts  the  application  of  Comte's  law  to  the  scientific  (i.e 
intellectual)  development  of  humanity  . 

Propounds  a  theory  of  four  states     .... 

In  his  criticism  of  the  "  law  of  three  states,"  Littre  contradicts  the 
central  truth  of  Comte's  system 

His  restrictions  would  make  Comte's  law  impossible  as  a  funda- 
mental law  of  history     ..... 

Spread  of  the  positivist  spirit  .... 

Its  influence  upon  historical  and  general  writers 

Sainte-Beuve's  methods  of  criticism  and  his  historical  works 

Kenan's  relation  to  the  Comtist  philosophy  . 

Recognises  the  importance  of  a  psychology  of  humauity  to  the  due 
understanding  of  history  .... 

His  delineation  of  the  general  features  of  the  Semitic  character 

He  acknowledges  the  derivative  and  modifiable  nature  of  race 

In  ascribing  to  the  Semitic  race  a  monotheistic  instinct,  he  meant 
merely  a  tendency  of  mind  favourable  to  monotheism  . 

The  characteristics  of  his  mental  organisation 

Taine's  philosophic  position  ..... 

He  does  not  regard  history  as  a  physical  process 

His  '  Essay  on  Livy '  . 

His  'French  Philosophers'  and  'Essays  on  Criticism  and  on  His 
tory'        ....... 

He  represents  the  progress  of  civilisation  as  determined  by  the  com 
bined  action  of  three  primordial  causes 

Asserts  the  correlation  of  the  component  parts  of  civilisation 

Taine's  conception  of  the  value  of  literature  as  a  source  of  com- 
parative psychology        ..... 


606 


xxiv  CONTENTS 

PAGE 

4.  Praises  the  social  spirit  and  institutions  of   Catholic 

monotheism      ....••       605 

5.  Treats  the  metaphysical  period   as  predominantly  a 

period  of  negation       .  .  .  .  • 

6.  Assumes  in  the  positive  stage  the  entire  subordination 

of  the  individual  to  society  ....  607 
Attempts  to  prove  the  unity  of  Comte's  life  and  doctrine  have  been 

unsuccessful  .....••  608 
In  his  "  law  of  three  states "  Comte   mistakes  three   coexistent 

states  for  three  successive  stages  of  thought      .  .  •       609 

Theology,  metaphysics,  and  positive  science  shown  to  have  always 

coexisted,  and  to  have  been  related  to  one  another       .  .       611 

The  partial  truth  of  the  "  law "         .  .  .  ■  •       612 

His  treatment  of  facts  inconsistent  until  it  involved  him  in  obvious 

self-contradiction  .  .  .  ■  .614 


615 
616 

617 
618 

618 

619 
620 
620 
621 
622 

623 

624 
625 

625 
626 
628 
628 
629 

630 

631 
632 

632 


CONTENTS  XXV 

PAGR 

How  far  his   '  History  of  English  Literature '  accomplished  its 

objects     ........  633 

He  fails  to  prove  that  history  is  simply  a  mechanical  problem         .  633 
His  three  causes  are  not  primordial,  but  themselves  require  his- 
torical explanation          ......  634 

He  does  not  fully  realise  the  difference  between  individual  and 

social  organisms              .....  635 

Exaggerates  the  psychological  value  of  literature    .            .            .  635 

The  defect  of  his  treatise  '  On  Intelligence '              ...  636 
The  value   and  influence  of  his   'Beginnings   of  Contemporary 

France'    ......  .637 

Veron,  Mougeolle,  and  Bourdeau      .....  639 


Chapter  XL  —  HISTORIC AL  PHILOSOPHY  OF  THE  CRITICAL 

SCHOOL 

I. 

The  doctrine  of  positive  philosophy  .  .  .  641 

It  is  superficial  and  inadequate         .  .  .  641 

The  creed  of  the  critical  school  .....  643 

Cournot's  philosophical  works  ....  644 

His  conception  of  the  nature  of  philosophy  .  .  .  644 

His  historical  philosophy  is  critical,  not  speculative  .  646 

He  regards  history  as  combining  fortuitous  and  necessary  events  .  647 

His  treatment  of  the  medieval  period  .  .  648 

The  plan  of  his  '  Considerations '      .  .  .  .  .  649 

Summary  of  the  author's  views  on  the  movements  of  the  nineteenth 
century : — 

the  exact  sciences     .  .  ...  650 

the  natural  sciences  .  .  .  650 

the  origin  of  species  .  .  .  .  651 

historical  work         ...  .  .  651 

philosophy    ...  .  .  652 

the  economic  revolution       .....  652 

socialism      .......  652 

public  law  and  political  institutions  .  .  .  653 

The  value  of  Cournot's  work  ...  .  654 

II. 

Renouvier  is  the  chief  of  French  criticists    ....  655 

He  claims  to  be  more  Kantian  than  Kant    ....  655 

His  conception  of  the  true  method  of  historical  study  .  .  656  • 

His  treatment  of  questions  relating  to  the  physical  origin  of  man  .  657 

His  method  of  inquiring  into  moral  origins  .  .  .  658 

He  rejects  the  error  that  primitive  man  may  be  assimilated  to  the 

modern  savage    .......  659 


XXVI 


CONTENTS 


/  PA6B 

The  primary  capacities  which  Kenouvier  attributes  to  the  first  men  660 
He  shows  that  it  is  only  by  the  exercise  of  his  liberty  that  man 

becomes  either  truly  good  or  truly  evil              .             .             •  661 
Treats  the  principles  of  morality  as  everywhere  present  and  opera- 
tive in  history     .......  662 

His  views  on  primitive  religions        .....  663 

And  on  the  origin  and  religions  of  the  Semites                    .             .  664 

His  conception  of  the  moral  effects  of  the  belief  in  progress            .  665 

Describes  progress  as  possible,  but  neither  continuous  nor  necessary  666 

How  he  supports  his  theories             ....  667 

His  '  Utopia  in  History '                                                                        .  670 

His  services  to  historical  philosophy             .             .             .  671 

His  influence  .....                         .  672 

Recent  French  works  on  historical  method  .            .             .  672 

Tardif  and  Seignobos             ......  672 

Tarde,  De  Coulanges  .  .  .  .  .673 


Chapter  XII.  —  HISTORIC AL  PHILOSOPHY  IN  BELGIUM  AND 
SWITZERLAND 


I. 

Political  and  social  conditions  in  Belgium    . 

Altmeyer's  conception  of  the  course  and  end  of  progress     . 

In  his  '  Cours '  he  adopts  the  Krausean  philosophy  of  history  in  its 

entirety    ....... 

Tiberghien      ....... 

Laurent's  contributions  to  historical  philosophy 

How  his  '  Philosophy  of  History '  is  related  to  his  '  Studies  on  the 

History  of  Humanity'  ..... 
It  deals  chiefly  with  the  moral  development  of  humanity  . 
And  surveys  history  from  a  religious  rather  than  from  a  scientific 

point  of  view  ..... 

Its  delineation  of  the  working  of  divine  Providence  in  history  is 

valuable  contribution  to  natural  theology 
Professor  Meyer's  criticism  of  it  considered 
Laurent's  conclusions  on  progress  in  history 
Moeller's  philosophy  of  history  is  in  the  main  a  theodicy  based  on 

history     ....... 

Laforet  .         .  • . 

Thonissen's  views  on  progress  . 

Summary  of  De  Colins's  socialistic  theory  of  historical  development 

The  statistical  investigation  of  Quetelet       .  .  .  . 

Brack's  attempt  to  establish  a  parallelism  between  magnetical  and 

historical  periods 
Father  de  Smedt's  '  Principles  of  Historical  Criticism  ' 


675 
677 

678 
679 
680 

681 
682 

683 

684 
685 


690 
690 
691 

692 
694 


CONTENTS  XXV11 


II. 

PAGK 

The  intellectual  position  of  French-speaking  Switzerland    .  697 

Vinet's  views  on  human  progress       .....  698 

Secre'tan's  historical  philosophy  claims  to  be  essentially  Christian  .  700 
Trottet  endeavours  to  show  that  the  whole  history  of  humanity 

has  been  a  necessary  preparation  for  Christianity                      .  701 

De  Rougemont           .....                         .  702 

The  critical  method  of  his  <  Two  Cities '       .             .  703 

His  theory  of  history  is  unsatisfactory          .                         .            .  704 

Malan's  doctrine  of  three  Divine  Economies                         .            ,  705 


PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY 


INTRODUCTION 


I 


The  aim  of  the  present  work  is  twofold — historical  and 
critical.  Its  primary  purpose  is  to  trace  the  course  of  human 
thought  in  its  endeavours  to  explain  human  history ;  or,  in 
other  words,  to  give  an  account  of  the  rise  and  progress  of 
reflection  and  speculation  on  the  development  of  humanity. 
The  task  must  be  amply  worth  an  effort  to  accomplish.  At 
a  time  when  all  history  is  tending  to  become  scientific,  and 
almost  all  science  is  availing  itself  of  the  assistance  of  his- 
tory ;  at  a  time  also  when  man  and  society  are  felt  as  never 
before  to  be  the  nearest  and  noblest  studies  of  mankind, — it 
requires  but  little  perspicacity  to  foresee  that  thoughtful 
minds  will  soon  be  far  more  generally  and  earnestly  engaged 
in  seeking  to  attain  a  philosophical  comprehension  of  his- 
tory than  they  have  ever  yet  been.  It  cannot,  therefore,  be 
inopportune  to  record  what  has  already  been  attempted  and 
achieved  in  this  department  of  intellectual  effort. 

During  the  past  century  and  a  half  a  very  considerable 
amount  of  thought  has  been  applied  to  ascertain  the  course, 
significance,  and  conditions  of  the  development  of  human 
society.  There  is  room  for  great  difference  of  opinion  as 
to  how  far  such  thought  has  been  wisely  or  successfully  ex- 
pended, but  there  can  be  no  reasonable  doubt  that  the  object 
sought  to  be  attained  by  it  is  a  legitimate  and  important  one. 
The  history  of  man  as  obviously  demands  and  deserves  scien- 
tific study  and  elucidation  as  the  history  of  nature.  Nothing  in 
the  world  is  intelligible  apart  from  its  history,  and  man  must 
be  of  all  things  the  least  so,  because  he  is  of  all  things  the  most 

1 


2  INTRODUCTION 

complex,  variable,  and  richly  endowed.     The  history  of  man 
is  clearly  a  phenomenon  which  not  only  deserves  to  be  accu- 
rately described  in  its  external  form  and  features,  but  which 
should  be  viewed  in  its  relations  to  coexistent  and  contiguous 
phenomena,  which  should  be  analysed  into  its  elements,  and 
which  should  have  the  operation  of  its  various  factors  and 
the  laws,  stages,  and  direction  of  its  movement  investigated. 
In  equivalent  terms,  it  is  a  phenomenon  which  should  be 
philosophically  and  scientifically  treated.     For  a  lengthened 
period  attempts  thus  to  deal  with  it  have  been  made  in  unin- 
terrupted and  rapid  succession.    Some  of  them  have  attracted 
great  attention  and  exerted  wide  influence.     They  have  of 
late  become  increasingly  numerous  and  have  gained  in  inter- 
est and  worth.     They  are  closely  connected  and  manifoldly 
related.     Hence  they  are  now  themselves  proper  subjects  and 
materials  for  a  history.      They  are  fragments,  rather  than 
stages,  of  a  process  which  is  strictly  historical  even  while 
essentially  philosophical  —  the  process  of  man's  reflection  on 
his  own  history.     To  trace  this  process  must  be  similarly  ser- 
viceable to  the  student  of  history  as  giving  an  account  of 
what  has  been  already  attempted  and  accomplished  in  other 
disciplines  — philosophy  or  theology,  ethics  or  aesthetics,  math- 
ematics, mechanics,  or  biology  —  is  to  those  who  at  present 
cultivate  them.     Whenever  any  department  of  knowledge  or 
process  of  thought  has  been  continuously  evolved  for  some 
length  of  time,  an  historical  survey  of  it  cannot  fail  to  be  of 
use.     It  must  help  us  to  see  where  and  why  there  has  been 
failure  or  success  in  the  past,  and  suggest  rules  and  cautions 
for  work  in  the  future.     In  the  words  of  Mr.  John  Morley, 
"  a  survey  of  this  kind  shows  us  in  a  clear  and  definite  man- 
ner the  various  lines  of  road  along  which  thinkers  have  trav- 
elled, and  the  point  to  which  the  subject  has  been  brought 
in  our  own  time.     We  are  able  to  contrast  methods  and  to 
compare  their  fruits.     People  always  understand  their  own 
speculative  position  the  better,  the  more  clearly  they  are 
acquainted  with  the  other  positions  which  have  been  taken 
in  the  same  matter."  1 

The  process  to  be  studied  is  one  of  thought  and  specula- 

1  Fortnightly  Review,  Sept.  1,  1874- Art.  "Mr.  Flint's  'Philosophy  of  His- 
tory.' " 


AIM   OF   THE   PKESEKT   WORK  o 

tion.  But  this,  as  has  been  indicated,  does  not  prevent  its 
being  also  as  strictly  one  of  history  as  any  external  or  visible 
process  whatever.  The  theories  of  thinkers  are  in  an  obvious 
sense  as  much  historical  facts  and  realities  as  births  and  deaths, 
treaties  and  battles,  the  changes  of  dynasties  and  the  revolu- 
tions of  peoples.  What  men  have  thought  about  history  is 
thus  itself  a  section  of  history ;  and,  like  all  that  is  history, 
it  should  be  treated  in  the  first  and  chief  place  simply  as  his- 
tory ;  that  is,  should  be  studied  solely  with  a  view  to  discover 
precisely  what  it  is  and  how  it  has  come  to  be  what  it  is. 
This  must  be  steadily  borne  in  mind  throughout  the  present 
work.  Our  primary  and  main  aim  is  to  describe  an  historical 
process  in  a  truly  historical  spirit  and  manner.  No  apology 
would  be  needed  were  no  more  than  this  attempted.  The 
historian  of  ideas  is  no  more  bound  to  constitute  himself  the 
judge  of  their  truth  or  falsity,  than  the  historian  of  events  is 
bound  to  pronounce  on  their  wisdom  or  folly,  Tightness  or 
wrongness.  The  sole  duty  of  the  historian,  alike  of  ideas 
and  events,  is  to  give  a  complete  history  of  them  —  such  a 
history  as  will  of  itself  imply  the  true  judgment  of  them. 

Such  being  the  case,  it  may  perhaps  be  thought  that  it 
would  be  wise  not  to  go  beyond  the  proper  sphere  of  the  his- 
torian, and  to  abstain  from  pronouncing  on  the  truth  or  falsity, 
probability  or  improbability,  of  the  speculations  gradually  un- 
folded. The  space  allotted  to  the  criticism  of  theories  and 
systems  is  apt  to  be  taken  from  that  required  for  their  ade- 
quate presentation.  Obviously,  the  danger  of  unfairness  is 
greatly  increased  when  the  historian  of  opinion  ventures  to 
become  its  judge.  The  characters  and  functions  of  the  his- 
torian and  the  critic  are  so  different  that  the  critic  may  easily, 
and  even  unduly,  discredit  the  historian.  There  is  much 
undeniable  truth  in  this  view.  The  risks  involved  in  attempt- 
ing to  discharge  the  two  distinct  offices  specified  cannot  be 
too  fully  recognised,  and  should,  as  a  general  rule,  be  avoided. 
One  who  undertakes,  for  instance,  to  write  a  history  of  phi- 
losophy or  of  theology  will  do  well  to  refrain  from  any  criti- 
cism except  such  as  seems  absolutely  necessary  to  make 
apparent  the  course  and  character  of  the  historical  develop- 
ment itself.    The  histories  both  of  philosophy  and  of  theology 


4  INTRODUCTION 

are  so  lengthened  and  comprehensive  that  to  attempt  more 
than  their  delineation  must  he  unprofitable  and  futile.  To 
imagine  that  any  service  will  be  rendered  either  to  philosophy 
or  theology  by  such  cursory  criticisms  as  their  historians  can 
append  to  their  expositions,  must  appear  almost  ludicrous 
when  one  considers  with  what  keenness,  and  from  how  many 
points  of  view,  the  cardinal  problems  of  philosophy  and  of 
theology  have  already  for  ages  been  discussed.  It  is  other- 
wise, however,  with  a  comparatively  recent  and  comparatively 
limited  department  of  knowledge,  such  as  the  philosophy  or 
science  of  history.  In  this  case  the  limits  of  the  history  leave 
room  for  the  criticism  of  the  theories.  In  this  case,  also,  a 
judicious  criticism  of  theories  may  reasonably  be  hoped  to 
be  of  real  and  immediate  service  to  the  new  discipline  which 
is  struggling  into  existence.  And  therefore,  in  this  case  the 
advantages  attainable  may  warrant  our  attempting  what  is 
not  generally  advisable.  But,  of  course,  care  must  be  taken 
that  the  historical  exposition  and  the  critical  appreciation  of 
the  theories  successively  submitted  to  examination  be  kept 
clearly  distinct,  and  that  the  former  be  never  obscured  6r 
perverted  in  order  to  give  relief  and  seeming  conclusiveness 
to  the  latter. 

I  mean,  then,  not  merely  to  pass  in  historical  review  the 
more  famous  of  the  many  attempts  which  have  been  made 
within  the  last  century  and  a  half  to  discover  the  laws  of 
order  which  regulate  human  affairs,  but  also  to  pronounce 
judgment  on  the  truth  or  falsity  of  what  is  essential  and 
characteristic  in  them,  and  to  indicate  their  chief  merits  and 
defects.  If  I  accomplish  this  twofold  purpose  with  the  slight- 
est measure  of  success,  the  conceptions  of  the  reader  as  to  the 
character,  scope,  and  method  of  the  philosophy  of  history,  as 
to  what  it  ought  to  do  and  how  it  ought  to  do  it,  should  be  con- 
stantly increasing  in  definiteness  and  accuracy  as  the  inquiry 
itself  advances.  It  may  be  that  even  at  its  close  there  will 
still  remain  possibilities  of  misapprehension  and  reasons  for 
uncertainty  as  to  the  precise  sphere  and  method  of  the 
philosophy  of  history ;  but  the  proper  place  to  remove  these, 
it  seems  to  me,  is  not  at  the  outset,  but  at  the  end  of  our 
historical  review,  when,  from  the  vantage-ground  gained  by  a 


NATTJKE   OF   HISTORY  5 

study  of  the  thoughts  and  labours  of  the  past  in  this  depart- 
ment of  research,  and  a  knowledge  of  its  failures  and  suc- 
cesses, we  may  hope  to  get  a  clearer  view  than  we  could 
otherwise  have  attained  of  the  duties  of  the  future,  of  the 
aims  which  a  philosophy  of  history  may  reasonably  propose 
to  itself,  and  of  the  processes  to  be  pursued  and  the  errors 
to  be  avoided  if  it  would  realise  them. 

The  term  ia-ropia  meant  in  early  Greek  usage  inquiry,  or 
learning  by  inquiry ;  and  hence  the  knowledge  so  obtained, 
information  acquired  on  any  subject.  Only  by  later  Greek 
writers  —  as,  for  example,  by  Polybius  and  Plutarch  —  was  it 
employed  to  denote  a  setting  forth  of  the  results  of  inquiry,  a 
written  account  of  information  obtained,  a  narrative.  Among 
the  Romans,  historia,  although  often  used  to  denote  any  nar- 
rative or  account,  any  tale  or  story,  acquired  also  the  more 
definite  meaning  of  a  narrative  of  past  events,  a  record  of  some 
course  of  human  actions.  With  us  the  word  "  history,"  like  its 
equivalents  in  all  modern  languages,  signifies  either  a  form  of 
literary  composition  or  the  appropriate  subject  or  matter  of 
such  composition  —  either  a  narrative  of  events,  or  events 
which  may  be  narrated.1  It  is  impossible  to  free  the  term  from 
this  doubleness  and  ambiguity  of  meaning.  Nor  is  it,  on  the 
whole,  to  be  desired.  The  advantages  of  having  one  term 
which  may,  with  ordinary  caution,  be  innocuously  applied  to 
two  things  so  related,  more  than  counterbalances  the  dangers 
involved  in  two  things  so  distinct  having  the  same  name.  The 
history  of  England  which  actually  happened  cannot  easily  be 
confounded  with  the  history  of  England  written  by  Mr.  Green  ; 
while  by  the  latter  being  termed  history  as  well  as  the  former, 
we  are  reminded  that  it  is  an  attempt  to  reproduce  or  represent 
the  course  of  the  former.  Occasionally,  however,  the  ambi- 
guity of  the  word  gives  rise  to  great  confusion  of  thought  and 

1  "  History  in  the  objective  sense  is  the  process  by  which  nature  and  spirit  are 
developed.  History  in  the  subjective  sense  is  the  investigation  and  statement  of 
this  objective  development.  The  Greek  words  ioropia  and  iuropelv,  being  derived 
from  eiteVu,  signify,  not  history  in  the  objective  sense,  but  the  subjective  activity 
involved  in  the  investigation  of  facts.  The  German  word  Geschichte  involves  a 
reference  to  that  which  has  come  to  pass  (das  Geschehene),  and  has  therefore 
primarily  the  objective  signification."  —  Ueberweg,  History  of  Philosophy,  vol.  i. 
p.  5.  As  to  the  etymology  of  the  term  ItrrapU,  the  learned  note  of  F.  Creuzer  in 
'Deutsche  Schriften,'  AM.  iii.  137,  may  be  consulted. 


6  INTRODUCTION 

gross  inaccuracy  of  speech.  And  this  occurs  most  frequently, 
if  not  exclusively,  just  when  men  are  trying  and  professing  to 
think  and  speak  with  especial  clearness  and  exactness  regard- 
ing the  signification  of  history  —  i.e.,  when  they  are  labouring 
to  define  it.  Since  the  word  history  has  two  very  different 
meanings,  it  obviously  cannot  have  merely  one  definition.  To 
define  an  order  of  facts  and  a  form  of  literature  in  the  same 
terms  —  to  suppose  that  when  either  of  them  is  defined  the 
other  is  defined  —  is  so  absurd  that  one  would  probably  not 
believe  it  could  be  seriously  done  were  it  not  so  often  done. 
But  to  do  so  has  been  the  rule  rather  than  the  exception.  The 
majority  of  so-called  definitions  of  history  are  definitions  only 
of  the  records  of  history.  They  relate  to  history  as  narrated 
and  written,  not  to  history  as  evolved  and  acted;  in  other 
words,  although  given  as  the  only  definitions  of  history  needed, 
they  do  not  apply  to  history  itself,  but  merely  to  accounts  of 
history.  They  may  tell  us  what  constitutes  a  book  of  history, 
but  they  cannot  tell  us  what  the  history  is  with  which  all  books 
of  history  are  occupied.  It  is,  however,  with  history  in  this 
latter  sense  that  a  student  of  the  science  or  philosophy  of  his- 
tory is  mainly  concerned.  History  as  a  form  of  literature  is  a 
.subject  of  primarj'-  interest  only  to  a  student  of  belles-lettres. 
History  as  it  happened  —  the  real  movement  of  history,  with 
its  events  and  laws  —  is  that  with  which  the  historical  scien- 
tist or  philosopher,  as  well  as  the  historian  himself,  has  directly 
to  do ;  and  to  history  in  this  acceptation,  every  definition  which 
contains  a  term  like  narratio,  reeit,  Darstellung,  record,  or  any 
phrase  equivalent  to  them,  is  plainly  inappropriate. 

If  by  history  be  meant  history  in  its  widest  sense,  the  best 
definition  of  history  as  a  form  of  literature  is,  perhaps,  either 
the  very  old  one,  "  the  narration  of  events,"  or  W.  von  Hum- 
boldt's, "  the  exhibition  of  what  has  happened  "  (die  Darstel- 
lung  des  Greschehenen).  The  excellence  of  these  definitions 
lies  in  their  clear  and  explicit  indication  of  what  history  as 
effectuated  or  transacted  is.  It  consists  of  events ;  it  is  das 
Greschehene.  It  is  the  entire  course  of  events  in  time.  It  is  all 
that  has  happened  precisely  as  it  happened.  Whatever  hap- 
pens is  history.  Eternal  and  unchanging  being  has  no  history. 
Things  or  phenomena  considered  as  existent,  connected,  and 


NATURE   OF    HISTORY  7 

comprehended  in  space,  compose  what  is  called  nature  as  dis- 
tinguished from  history.  And  history  as  distinguished  from 
nature  is  process  and  movement,  the  coming  of  things  and 
phenomena  into  being  or  into  successive  stages  and  states  of 
being,  the  flow  of  occurrences  in  time.  These  two  conceptions 
—  nature  and  history  —  are  thus  extremely  wide  and  compre- 
hensive. They  represent  the  universe  in  its  two  chief  aspects. 
Obviously  they  are  far  from  absolutely  separable ;  on  the  con- 
trary, they  are  essentially  interconnected.  They  are  only  dis- 
tinguishable as  correlatives.  Space  and  time  are  themselves 
related,  and  still  more  are  their  contents.  Nature  has  a  his- 
tory, and  it  is  a  characteristic  of  the  science  of  the  present 
day  to  seek  to  explain  nature  historically.  History  is  the 
evolution  of  nature,  and  it  is  also  a  characteristic  of  contem- 
porary science  to  endeavour  to  account  for  history  naturally. 
Yet  while  the  mind  is  unable  to  regard  nature  and  history  as 
absolutely  separate,  or  even  as  not  closely  and  variously  con- 
joined, it  cannot  fail  to  recognise  them  as  relatively  distinct. 
It  is  compelled\by  its  intellectual  constitution  to  contemplate 
the  universe  at  one  time  predominantly  in  the  one  aspect, 
and  at  another  time  in  the  other  aspect.  The  world,  or  any 
part  of  it,  apprehended  mainly  as  in  space  is  nature,  and  if 
apprehended  mainly  as  in  time  is  history.  It  is  unnecessary 
to  labour  to  give  more  definite  expression  to  the  distinction. 
Probably  Droysen  has  found  a  neater  and  terser  formula  for  it 
in  German  than  any  which  the  English  language  could  supply. 
Nature  he  describes  as  "das  Nebeneinander  des  Seienden,"  and 
history  as  "  das  Nacheinander  des  Gewordenen." 1 

By  distinguishing  history  from  nature,  we  get  the  most 
general  notion  of  history  which  can  be  formed.  If  we  would 
understand  what  is  meant  by  any  kind  or  species  of  history, 
we  must  distinguish  further,  and  give  precision  to  our  think- 
ing by  fixing  on  the  appropriate  differential  characteristic.  In 
the  present  work  such  delimitation  or  definition  is  obviously 
required.  Mediately  it  may  be  concerned  with  the  histories 
of  the  heavens  and  the  earth,  of  plants  and  animals,  but  it  is 
certainly  not  immediately  concerned  with  them.  The  only 
kind  of  history  with  which  we  have  here  directly  to  deal  is 

1  Grundriss  der  Historik,  p.  7. 


8  INTRODUCTION 

that  kind  of  it  to  which  the  name  is  generally  restricted,  his- 
tory par  excellence,  human  history,  what  has  happened  within 
the  sphere  of  human  agency  and  interests,  the  actions  and 
creations  of  men,  events  which  have  affected  the  lives  and 
destinies  of  men,  or  which  have  been  produced  by  men.  This 
is  the  ordinary  sense  of  the  word  history,  and  it  is  the  sense 
in  which  it  will  ordinarily  be  employed  in  these  pages.  No 
further  restriction  on  its  signification  will  be  imposed  or  im- 
plied. Indeed,  all  further  restrictions  must  mislead,  and  all 
definitions  which  involve  them  are  to  be  rejected.  History  is 
all  that  man  has  suffered,  thought,  and  executed — the  entire 
life  of  humanity  —  the  whole  movement  of  societies.  It  is 
history  thus  understood  which  is  the  subject  of  the  art,  and 
the  science,  and  the  philosophy  of  history,  —  of  the  art  which 
recalls  and  delineates  it,  of  the  science  which  analyses  it  and 
traces  its  laws,  and  of  the  philosophy  which  exhibits  it  in  its 
relations  to  the  general  system  of  the  universe.  To  attempt 
further  to  define  it  would  be  worse  than  useless.  It  would 
be  unduly  to  limit,  and  to  distort  and  pervert,  its  meaning. 
In  proof  of  this  a  few  brief  remarks  on  certain  typical  or 
■celebrated  definitions  of  history  may  perhaps  be  of  service. 

The  definition  given  in  the  Dictionary  of  the  French  Acad- 
emy —  "  l'histoire  est  le  recit  des  choses  dignes  de  me"inoire  " 
—  is  a  specimen  of  a  very  numerous  species.  According  to 
such  definitions  history  consists  of  exceptional  things,  of  cele- 
brated or  notorious  events,  of  the  lives  and  actions  of  great 
and  exalted  men,  of  conspicuous  achievements  in  war  and 
politics,  in  science  and  art,  in  religion  and  literature.  But 
this  is  a  narrow  and  superficial  conception  of  history.  His- 
tory is  made  up  of  what  is  little  as  well  as  of  what  is  great, 
of  what  is  common  as  well  as  of  what  is  strange,  of  what  is 
counted  mean  as  well  as  of  what  is  counted  noble.  The  ob- 
scure agency  of  the  masses  is  more  potent  in  forming  it  than 
the  brilliant  achievements  of  the  few.  Things  of  frequent 
recurrence  are  more  important  than  those  which  are  rare.  A 
history  of  wages  or  prices  is  at  least  as  instructive  as  a  his- 
tory of  battles  and  political  intrigues.  The  historian  has  no 
right  to  despise  the  smallest  incidents,  the  humblest  lives ; 
for  the  great  is  explained  by  the  little,  and  the  life  of  human- 


DEFINITIONS    OF    HISTORY  9 

ity  is  unfolded  not  merely  through  a  few  of  its  members  hut 
through  all. 

Dr.  Arnold's  definition  —  "  history  is  the  biography  of  a  soci- 
ety "  1  — has  been  often  praised.  Nor  altogether  undeservedly. 
For  it  directs  attention  to  the  fact  that  all  history  accords  with 
biography  in  supposing  in  its  subject  a  certain  unity  of  life, 
work,  and  end.  Unless  individuals  truly  form  a  society  there 
cannot  be  a  history  of  them  as  a  society,  whether  family  or 
tribe,  trade  or  corporation,  Church  or  nation,  but  only  a  collec- 
tion of  biographies  of  them  as  individuals.  It  does  not  follow, 
however,  that  biography  is  a  more  general  notion  than  history, 
and  history  only  a  species  of  biography.  In  fact,  it  is  not  only 
as  true  and  intelligible  to  say  that  biography  is  the  history  of 
an  individual  as  to  say  that  history  is  the  biography  of  a  society, 
but  more  so.  It  is  the  word  biography  in  the  latter  case  which 
is  used  in  a  secondary  and  analogical  sense,  not  the  word  his- 
tory in  the  former  case.  The  two  meanings  most  appropriately 
and  commonly  assigned  to  the  word  history  are  very  general 
ones,  whereas  the  only  meaning  of  the  word  biography  in  cur- 
rent use  is  a  very  different  one.  Therefore,  although  there 
may  be  no  harm,  or  even  may  be  gain,  in  giving  the  term  history 
at  times  a  special  meaning  for  the  special  purpose  of  opposing 
it  to  biography,  it  must  be  erroneous  to  represent  biography  as 
the  genus  and  history  as  the  species.  On  the  other  hand,  it 
is  perfectly  reasonable  to  regard  history,  even  when  meaning 
thereby  human  history,  as  a  genus  of  which  the  history  of  in- 
dividuals (biography)  is  one  species  and  the  history  of  societies 
another.  When  Dr.  Arnold  proceeds  to  represent  "  the  life  of 
that  highest  and  sovereign  society  which  we  call  a  State  or 
nation  "  as  especially  the  proper  subject  of  history,  he  seems  to 
us,  of  course,  to  go  still  further  astray  from  the  truth.  There 
is  no  real  reason  discoverable  for  such  exclusiveness.  The 
history  of  the  Church  is  as  much  history  as  the  history  of  the 
State.  The  history  of  philosophy  or  of  art  is  not  less  truly 
history  than  the  history  of  England  or  of  France. 

According  to  Mr.  Freeman,  "  history  is  past  politics  and  poli- 
tics are  present  history."  2  This  is  not  a  mode  of  definition 
which  any  logician  will  be  found  to  sanction.     It  is  equivalent 

1  Lectures  on  Modern  History,  p.  3.        2  Methods  of  Historical  Study,  p.  44. 


10  INTRODUCTION 

to  saying  that  politics  and  history  are  the  same,  and  may  both 
be  divided  into  past  and  present ;  but  it  does  not  tell  us  what 
either  is.  To  affirm  that  this  was  that  and  that  is  this  is  not  a 
definition  of  this  or  that,  but  only  an  assertion  that  something 
may  be  called  either  this  or  that.  Besides,  the  identification  of 
history  with  politics  proceeds,  as  has  been  already  indicated, 
on  a  view  of  history  which  is  at  once  narrow  and  arbitrary. 
Further,  it  is  just  as  true  that  mathematical  history  is  past 
mathematics  and  mathematics  are  present  history,  as  that  polit- 
ical history  is  past  politics  and  politics  are  present  history. 
The  present  state  of  every  species  of  knowledge  and  of  every 
form  of  action  is  only  a  moment  in  the  history  of  that  kind 
of  knowledge  and  action.  The  whole  of  human  science,  ex- 
perience, and  production  in  the  present  moment  becomes  his- 
tory—  past  history,  as  soon  as  the  moment  is  gone.  The 
whole  of  man's  past  was  once  present  thought,  feeling,  and 
action.  There  is  nothing  peculiar  to  politics  in  this  respect. 
Professor  Creighton,  while  pronouncing  Mr.  Freeman's  defi- 
nition "narrow,  and  therefore  misleading,"  refuses  to  accept 
the  view  that  history  "includes  everything  that  man  has  either 
thought  or  wrought,"  on  the  ground  that  it  is  "so  wide  as  to 
become  vague,  fixing  no  definite  limit  to  the  province  of  his- 
tory as  bordering  on  other  fields  of  learning."  He  deems  it 
better,  therefore,  "to  regard  history  as  the  record  of  human 
action,  and  of  thought  only  in  its  direct  influence  upon  action." 1 
This  attempt  at  mediation  does  not  seem  to  be  successful. 
Why  regard  history  in  the  way  described  rather  than  contrari- 
wise as  the  record  of  human  thought,  and  of  action  only  in  its 
direct  influence  on  thought  ?  The  development  of  thought  is 
no  more  to  be  understood  apart  from  the  development  of  action 
than  the  development  of  action  apart  from  the  development  of 
thought.  He  who  would  comprehend  the  movement  of  phi- 
losophy, for  example,  must  view  it  in  relation  to  the  course  of 
political  and  social  change  and  to  the  whole  general  history  of 
humanity.  Even  if  States  and  politics  could  be  shown  to  be 
what  Professor  Creighton  calls  them,  "the  chief  part  of  the 
subject  of  history,"  that  would  not  prove  them  to  be  more 
directly  or  truly  its  subject  than  anything  else  which  has  a  his- 

1  English  Historical  Review,  vol.  i.  pp.  2,  3. 


DEFINITIONS    OF   HISTORY  11 

tory.  In  itself  politics  is  no  more  history  than  is  theology  or 
metaphysics.  It  is  only  its  history  which  is  history,  and  their 
histories  are  also  history,  as  are  all  developments  of  the  mind 
and  will  of  man  in  time.  It  is  hence  as  easy  to  distinguish 
history  in  its  widest  sense  from  science,  as  in  its  narrowest. 
The  measure  of  comprehensiveness  assigned  to  the  word  his- 
tory is  not  what  affects  the  power  of  distinguishing  it  from 
science  ;  and  when  history  is  confounded  with  science  the  con- 
fusion is  not  one  of  degree  but  of  nature,  not  quantitative  but 
qualitative. 

M.  Bourdeau  thinks  history  should  be  denned  "  la  science  des 
developpements  de  la  raison."  x  Of  course,  history  itself  is  no 
more  a  science  than  an  art.  The  definition,  therefors,  is  only 
the  definition  of  the  science,  but  it  implies  that  history  itself 
consists  of  the  developments  of  reason.  Is  this  implication  cor- 
rect ?  Certainly  not  altogether.  There  is  much  else  in  man 
than  reason,  and  not  only  many  things  but  many  develop- 
ments in  his  history  which  must  be  referred  not  to  reason  but 
to  the  impulses  and  passions  which  so  often  seduce  and  subdue 
reason.  At  the  same  time  there  is  more  to  approve  than  to 
reject  in  M.  Bourdeau's  definition.  It  fixes  attention  on  what 
is  undoubtedly  the  main  cause  of  that  which  is  most  character- 
istic in  human  history,  its  marvellous  variety  and  its  inexhaust- 
ible progressiveness,  so  unlike  the  narrowly  determined  limits 
and  monotonously  recurring  phases  of  animal  life.  The  his- 
tory of  man  is  so  peculiar  and  significant  as  to  be  entitled"  to 
be  especially  called  history,  just  because  the  reason  which  is 
distinctive  of  man  is  essentially  a  principle  of  change  and 
progress.  M.  Bourdeau  has  seen  and  expressed  this  very 
clearly ;  not  more  so,  however,  than  was  done  by  Jouffroy 
almost  sixty  years  ago. 

Professor  Bernheim  defines  history  as  "  the  science  of  the 
development  of  men  in  their  working  as  social  beings."  2  This 
also  is  only  a  definition  of  written  history,  and  will  obviously 
not  even  apply  to  the  great  majority  of  written  histories.  It 
cannot  apply  to  mere  narration,  however  accurate  and  brilliant. 
It  applies  only  to  what  is  called  genetic  or  scientific  history. 
It  implies  that  there  is  no  other  form  of  written  history,  which 

1  L'Histoire  et  les  Historiens,  p.  5. 

2  Lehrbuch  der  historischen  Methode  (1889) ,  p.  4. 


12  INTRODUCTION 

is  a  supposition  contrary  to  fact.  Besides,  although  the  actual 
history  which  is  the  object  of  written  history  may  be  a  de- 
velopment, development  is  a  word  at  least  as  much  in  need 
of  definition  as  history.  Historical  development  is  so  unlike 
logical  and  biological  development,  that  it  must  have  a  dif- 
ferentia. Further,  scientific  history,  or  the  science  of  history, 
should  not  assume  but  prove  history  to  be  a  development.  To 
prove  development  in  history  by  exhibiting  its  precise  nature 
is  the  aim,  not  the  presupposition,  of  historical  science.  The 
last  words  of  the  definition,  "  in  their  working  as  social  be- 
ings," also  require  explanation.  Professor  Bernheim  gives  it. 
He  wishes  "working"  (Beihatigung)  to  be  understood  as 
inclusive  of  all  human  states  as  well  as  acts,  and  "  social " 
to  be  held  to  comprehend  rational,  spiritual,  political,  &c. 
With  his  desire  thus  to  embrace  in  his  definition  humanity  in 
all  its  aspects  I  entirely  sympathise ;  but  I  cannot  see  that 
the  terms  of  his  definition  in  themselves  do  justice  to  his 
thought. 

History,  understood  as  has  been  indicated,  may  be  dealt  with 
in  various  ways.  Thus,  in  the  first  place,  attempts  may  be 
made  to  recall  and  to  transmit  the  memory  of  it.  As  a  being 
who  looks  before  and  after,  man  is  naturally  interested  both  in 
the  past  and  in  the  future,  and  impelled  to  seek  to  relate  him- 
self with  both.  Hence  he  endeavours  to  communicate  the  tra- 
ditions which  he  has  received,  loves  to  narrate  his  experiences, 
and  labours  to  perpetuate  the  fame  of  his  achievements.  The 
minds  of  men  are  occupied  even  in  the  lowest  stages  of  exist- 
ence with  reminiscences  of  their  own  or  others'  past.  The 
speech  of  all  men,  and  especially  of  common  and  uneducated 
men,  is  largely  narrative.  Indeed,  the  history  which  has  thus 
history  for  its  subject  is  not  unjustly  described  by  Carlyle  as 
"  man's  earliest  and  simplest  expression  of  thought."  "  As 
we  do  nothing  but  enact  history,  so  likewise  we  say  little  but 
recite  it."  History  recorded  and  recited  attained  in  course  of 
time  a  literary  form ;  and  there  is  no  species  of  literature  which 
has  since  been  more  continuously  or  widely  cultivated,  which 
has  passed  through  more  stages,  assumed  more  shapes,  spread 
out  more  branches ;  which  has  responded  to  more  wants  and 
interests,  conveyed  a  greater  wealth  of  information,  reflected 
human   nature  more   fully,  or  presented  a  broader  surface 


HISTORIOGRAPHY  13 

to  the  light  of  truth.  History  as  a  species  of  literature  has 
therefore,  like  eloquence,  poetry,  the  drama,  or  romance, 
a  history  of  its  own,  and  one  which  is  most  extensive  and 
instructive.  It  is  not  my  purpose  to  attempt  to  write  a  his- 
tory of  history.  Others,  with  more  or  less  success,  have 
endeavoured  to  do  so,  in  whole  or  in  part.1  I  must,  how- 
ever, have  continuous  reference  to  the  course  and  charac- 
ter of  historical  literature  during  the  period  within  which 
historical  philosophy  has  been  developed.  Historical  literature 
tends  as  it  advances  to  become  increasingly  philosophical.  Per- 
fect delineation  presupposes  perfect  knowledge.  Excellence  in 
narration  must  be  in  proportion  to  the  accuracy  and  complete- 
ness of  acquaintance  with  the  facts  narrated.  But  science  or 
philosophy  is  simply  the  exactest  and  fullest  knowledge,  — 
knowledge  at  its  highest  and  best.  The  more  comprehensively, 
profoundly,  penetratingly,  and,  in  a  word,  truthfully,  histori- 
ans deal  with  their  themes,  the  more  entitled  are  they  to  rank 
as  historical  philosophers.  All  great  historians  have  looked  at 
the  events  which  they  narrated  from  general  points  of  view, 
and  have  formed  general  conclusions  as  to  the  interrelations 
and  significance  of  those  events.  They  have  had,  that  is  to  say, 
at  least  an  implicit  philosophy  of  the  history  which  they  have 
attempted  to  exhibit.  And  their  philosophy,  although  it  can 
claim  no  right  of  exemption  from  criticism,  is  entitled  to  be 
approached  with  the  respect  due  to  the  views  of  men  who 
speak  on  matters  with  which  they  are  specially  familiar.  It 
may  reasonably  be  expected,  therefore,  that  I  should  indicate 
to  some  extent  what  has  been  the  philosophy  implied  in  the 
writings.of  various  eminent  historians  who  have  made  no  claim 
to  philosophise  on  history,  or  who  have  even  professed  con- 
tempt for  historical  philosophy  in  every  form.  At  the  same 
time,  it  will  be  necessary  to  exercise  restraint  in  this  direction. 

1  There  is  no  adequate  account  of  the  development  of  historiography  as  a 
whole.  G.  Rosa's  '  Storia  della  Storia '  (Milano,  1884)  is  to  be  commended  as  a 
general  sketch.  Prof.  C.  K.  Adams's  '  Manual  of  Historical  Literature  '  (London, 
1882)  gives  good  descriptions  of  the  best  histories,  but  does  not  profess  to  be 
itself  a  history.  Wachler's  '  Geschichte  der  historischen  Forschung  und  Kunst 
seit  der  Wiederherstellung  der  literarischen  Kultur  in  Europa,'  treats  only,  as 
its  title  indicates,  of  the  modern  epoch,  and  was  published  so  long  ago  as  1812- 
20.  There  are  a  considerable  number  of  histories  of  special  periods  of  histori- 
ography, some  of  which  will  be  mentioned  when  reference  to  them  is  more 
appropriate. 


14  INTRODUCTION 

I  must  clearly  not  yield  to  the  temptation  to  write  essays  on 
the  characteristics  of  eminent  historians ;  and,  indeed,  cannot 
legitimately  do  more  than  attempt  to  elicit  and  exhibit  the 
distinctive  and  guiding  ideas  of  those  among  them  who  have 
shown  special  originality  and  insight  in  their  interpretations  of 
historical  phenomena.  As  a  rule,  the  historians  who  have  had 
no  explicit  philosophy  of  history  have  had  but  a  very  meagre 
implicit  one ;  and  the  aversion  which  they  have  shown  to  his- 
torical generalisation  has  had  its  source  mainly  in  their  own 
want  of  generalising  power.  Not  a  few  historians  of  repute 
,  owe  their  fame  entirely  to  their  critical  and  literary  talent, 
and  are  as  regards  scientific  and  philosophical  capacity  below 
mediocrity. 

•  Historiography  is  not  only  an  art  which  has  a  history,  but 
the  subject  of  a  process  of  theorising  which  has  also  a  history. 
How  should  history  be  studied  ?  How  should  it  be  presented  ? 
With  what  aims  should  it  be  written  ?  What  are  the  sources 
of  historical  knowledge,  and  how  are  we  to  judge  of  their 
genuineness,  integrity,  and  credibility?  What  are  the  aids, 
instruments,  conditions,  and  processes  of  historical  research  ? 
In  what  ways  are  the  materials  of  history  to  be  collected, 
sifted,  analysed,  compared,  and  distributed  ?  How  are  we  to 
trace  the  movement  of  history  as  an  organic  evolution,  to 
estimate  institutions  and  events  according  to  their  real  signifi- 
cance in  relation  to  one  another,  and  to  the  whole  of  which 
they  are  parts,  and  to  attain  to  a  clear  and  truthful  apprehen- 
sion of  the  spirit  of  history,  separated  from  which  all  else  in 
it  must  be  merely  shell  and  husk  ?  What  are  the  mental  re- 
quirements of  the  historian?  What  are  the  qualities  of  good 
historical  art,  and  the  style  appropriate  to  each  variety  of  his- 
torical composition  ?  To  answer  these  and  similar  questions 
is  the  office  of  Historic,  as  it  is  now  commonly  called.  Thev 
have  gradually  and  naturally  presented  themselves  with  the 
development  of  historiography  itself.  The  simplest  —  those  of 
least  interest  to  science — those  which  related  to  history  merely 
as  a  pleasant  art  or  useful  instrument  —  were  the  first  to  pre- 
sent themselves ;  and  antiquity  did  not  get  beyond  them.  On 
these  questions,  but  on  none  of  the  deeper  problems  as  to  the 
nature  and  methods  of  historical  inquiry,  Polybius  and  Plu- 


HISTORIC  15 

tarch,  Cicero  and  Quinctilian,  had  to  some  extent  reflected ; 
and  especially  Lucian,  whose  essay  on  "  How  to  write  His- 
tory," so  witty  in  its  banter  and  so  shrewd  in  its  advice,  is 
justly  celebrated,  devoid  although  it  be  of  philosophical  in- 
sight. It  was  only  with  the  Renaissance  that  treatises  on  the 
study,  composition,  and  uses  of  history  became  common,  and 
that  the  idea  began  to  spread  that  the  a/ie6oBo<;  v\rj  of  history 
might,  like  that  of  nature,  be  elaborated  into  science.  In  the 
sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries,  while  there  were  still 
hardly  any  good  modern  historians,  so  many  persons  had 
undertaken  to  show  how  history  should  be  written  that  Fres- 
noy  aptly  applies  to  the  situation  the  words  of  the  old  French 

poeii,  ,,  ka  qou1.  en  conseillers  foisonne, 

Mais  vient-on  &  1  'execution, 
On  ne  rencontre  plus  personne." 

There  has  ever  since  been  a  continuous,  and  at  times  a 
copious,  flow  of  writings  on  the  theory  of  historiography ;  but 
only  during  the  present  century  have  the  deeper  questions 
above  indicated — those  which  clearly  and  directly  concern  the 
science  or  philosophy  of  history  —  been  raised  and  dealt  with. 
In  particular,  the  essay  of  W.  v.  Humboldt,  "  Uber  die  Aufgabe 
des  Geschichtschreibers,"  initiated  a  more  thorough  and  fruit- 
ful investigation  into  all  the  relevant  problems.  The  literature 
of  Historic  must  therefore  not  be  wholly  ignored  by  us.  Its 
course  has  been,  on  the  whole,  one  of  advance  from  common- 
place reflection  on  history  towards  a  philosophical  comprehen- 
sion of  the  conditions  and  processes  on  which  the  formation  of 
historical  science  depends.  Practical  recognition  must  be 
given  to  this  fact  by  noting  the  more  important  phases  which 
Historic  has  assumed.  And  especially  must  due  attention  be 
given  to  those  recent  writings  on  Historic  which  are  of  a 
truly  philosophical  character,  and  which  expressly  treat  of  the 
methods  by  which  historical  truth  is  to  be  attained  and  his- 
torical science  constituted.  We  have,  however,  no  further 
concern  with  the  literature  of  Historic.  And  this  is  fortu- 
nate ;  for  a  very  large  portion  of  it  is  so  trivial  and  superficial 
that  it  can  hardly  ever  have  been  of  use  even  to  persons  of  the 
humblest  capacity,  and  may  certainly  now  be  safely  consigned 
to  kindly  oblivion,  while  of  the  not  wholly  worthless  remain- 


16  INTRODUCTION 

der  much  more  of  the  interest  is  literary  and  practical  than 
scientific  and  philosophical. 

It  is,  then,  neither  the  history  of  Historiography  nor  of  His- 
toric which  is  here  intended  to  be  traced.  It  is  that  of  the 
Science  or  Philosophy  of  History.  Human  history  may  be 
treated  as  the  subject  of  science  and  philosophy.  The  reign  of 
law  somehow  extends  over  human  affairs.  Events  are  con- 
nected by  some  determinate  relationships,  and  one  social  state 
arises  out  of  another  with  which  it  retains  some  correspond- 
ence in  character.  The  world  of  intelligent  and  moral  agency 
has  not  been  abandoned  to  caprice  and  chance,  is  not  mere 
anarchy  and  chaos,  but  is  embraced  within  a  system  of  order, 
more  or  less  perfect ;  and  amidst  all  its  apparent  confusion  and 
incoherence  there  has  been  some  sort  of  growth,  some  sort  of 
development  of  the  mind  and  spirit  of  the  human  race.  Much 
that  has  happened  in  history  has  sunk  into  oblivion,  or  is  im- 
perfectly known ;  but  there  is  nothing  known  in  history  which 
is  essentially  inexplicable,  nor  is  there  any  reason  to  suppose 
that  anything  has  ever  happened  in  history  which  was  from 
its  very  nature  incapable  either  of  being  clearly  apprehended 
or  fully  comprehended.  All  the  component  facts  of  history 
can  be  accounted  for  historically,  just  as  those  of  the  physical 
world  can  be  accounted  for  physically ;  and  the  whole  of  his- 
tory is  not  less  a  whole  of  law  and  order  than  that  of  nature. 
Besides,  just  as  the  world  of  plants,  for  example,  while  a  whole 
in  regard  to  its  own  parts,  is  itself  a  part  in  regard  to  the  uni- 
verse in  which  it  is  placed  and  by  the  fundamental  laws  of 
which  it  is  controlled,  so  the  world  of  history,  while  similarly 
a  whole,  is  also  similarly  a  part;  and  hence,  while  its  particular 
events  may  be  so  far  satisfactorily  explained  by  the  agencies 
which  operate  within  itself,  its  development  as  a  whole  can 
only  be  understood  when  viewed  in  connection*  with  all  other 
spheres  of  existence,  or,  in  other  words,  in  the  light  of  all 
science.  This  is  equivalent  to  saying  that  history  may  be  the 
subject  of  science  and  philosophy  in  the  only  sense  in  which 
it  is  assumed  in  this  work  that  there  is  any  science  or  phi- 
losophy of  history. 

There  has  been  a  considerable  amount  of  discussion  as  to 
whether  history  ought  to  be  regarded  as  the  subject  of  a  science 


SCIENCE   OR   PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  ?  17 

or  of  a  philosophy ;  in  other  words,  as  to  whether  the  highest 
form  of  the  study  of  history  —  its  study  as  an  orderly,  organic, 
intelligible  system  within,  and  related  to,  the  system  of  the 
universe  —  ought  to  be  called  the  Science  or  the  Philosophy  of 
History.  Some  who  believe  in  a  philosophy  of  history  deny 
that  there  can  be  any  science  of  history.  Goldwin  Smith, 
for  instance,  in  his  lectures  "  On  the  Study  of  History,"  lays 
down,  that  "  a  science  of  history  is  one  thing  and  a  philos- 
ophy another ;  a  science  of  history  can  rest  on  nothing  short 
of  causation,  while  a  philosophy  of  history  rests  upon  connec- 
tion;  such  connection  as  we  know,  and  in  every  process  and 
word  of  life  assume,  that  there  is  between  the  action  and  its 
motive,  between  motives  and  circumstances,  between  the  con- 
duct of  men  and  the  effect  produced  upon  their  character, 
between  historic  antecedents  and  their  results  " ; a  and  retying 
on  this  distinction,  he  proceeds  to  urge  a  vigorous  polemic 
against  the  position  that  there  is  a  science  of  history,  while 
earnestly  maintaining  that  there  is  a  philosophy  of  history. 
This  view,  and  all  views  of  the  same  class,  I  reject.  The 
notion  that  historical  results  are  connected  with  their  antece- 
dents, yet  uncaused  or  only  partially  caused  events,  is  almost 
too  unreasonable  for  discussion.  Results  or  events  not  fully 
caused,  are  no  more  conceivable  in  the  moral  and  social  world, 
than  in  the  mechanical  and  physical  world.  So  long  as  those 
who  believe  that  there  are  uncaused  or  imperfectly  caused 
events  in  history  fail  to  point  out  any  of  them,  reason  is  war- 
ranted in  seeking  for  causation  in  history  not  less  than  in 
nature.  Intelligent  defenders  of  free  agency  do  not  oppose 
it  to  causation,  but  represent  it  as  the  highest  type  of  causa- 
tion. Those  physical  studies  which  all  admit  to  be  sciences 
are  by  no  means  only  conversant  with  connections  of  causa- 
tion. Historical  connection  is  often  manifestly  as  strictly 
causal  as  chemical  or  biological  connection. 

There  are  authors  who  regard  mathematical  and  physical 
studies  as  alone  entitled  to  be  called  sciences,  and  who  would 
call. all  other  studies  philosophical.  It  seems  to  them  that  in 
the  sphere  of  mental  and  social  life  connection  is  so  vague,  and 
•causation  so  different  from  what  it  is  among  measurable  and 

1  The  Study  of  History,  p.  51. 


18  INTRODUCTION 

sensible  objects,  that  knowledge  of  such  connection  and  causa- 
tion ought  not  to  be  termed  science  at  all.  Hence,  as  historical 
phenomena  are,  on  the  whole,  mental  phenomena,  these  authors, 
while  willing  to  allow  that  there  is  a  philosophy  of  history,  will 
not  admit  that  there  is  any  science  of  history.  Of  all  ways, 
however,  in  which  it  has  been  proposed  to  draw  a  rigid  line  of 
separation  between  science  and  philosophy,  this  of  treating  all 
physical  studies  as  sciences  and  all  mental  studies  as  philos- 
ophy, is  probably  the  worst.  It  rests  on  a  confused  view  of 
the  nature  and  bearing  of  causation  in  psychology,  ethics,  and 
history.  It  shows  ignorance  of  what  constitutes  science,  of  the 
proper  character  and  office  of  philosophy,  and  of  how  science 
and  philosophy  are  related.  It  does  injustice  to  science  by 
implicitly  denying  that  it  has  anything  to  do  with  philosophy 
or  philosophy  with  it ;  and  injustice  to  philosophy  by  repre- 
senting it  as  an  inferior  kind  of  knowledge — as  knowledge 
which  is  not  scientific  because  vague  and  dubious. 

Some  writers,  on  the  other  hand,  would  only  speak  of  a 
Science  of  History.  The  name  of  Philosophy  of  History  has 
been  so  utterly  discredited  in  their  ears  by  the  character  of 
much  which  has  been  put  forth  as  such,  that  they  would  drop 
it  altogether,  and  keep  to  one  which  seems  to  them  more 
definite  and  less  liable  to  abuse.  It  is  not  difficult  to  under- 
stand this  view,  or  even,  in  a  considerable  measure,  to  sym- 
pathise with  it.  All  kinds  of  baseless  and  worthless  specu- 
lations—  even  the  merest  dreams  and  vagaries — have  been 
confidently  presented  as  philosophy.  The  most  unsubstantial 
and  fantastic  hypotheses  which  metaphysics  or  theology,  anal- 
ogy or  imagination,  could  supply  or  suggest,  have  been  pre- 
tentiously maintained  to  explain  the  course  and  meaning  of 
human  development.  Hence  a  certain  aversion  to  the  use  of 
the  term  philosophy  both  in  general  and  in  application  is, 
perhaps,  natural  and  excusable.  Wemust  not  allow  it,  how- 
ever, to  carry  us  too  far.  And  it  does  so  when  we  admit  no 
distinction  between  science  and  philosophy,  or,  indeed,  virtu- 
ally deny  that  there  is  any  philosophy.  If  we  might  thereby 
be  helped,  as  Mr.  Morley  says,  to  "  put  from  us  vague  modes 
of  historical  philosophising,"  we  would  also  be  in  danger  of 
getting  ensnared  in   the   prejudices  generated  by  scientific 


SCIENCE   OR   PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  '!  19 

specialism.  A  science  exclusive  of  philosophy  is  to  be 
shunned,  as  well  as  a  philosophy  exclusive  of  science. 
Science  is  not  to  be  dissociated  from  philosophy,  any  more 
than  philosophy  from  science.  Science  can  only  prosper 
when  it  strives  to  become  philosophic,  as  philosophy  can  only 
prosper  when  it  strives  to  become  scientific.  I  thus  no  more 
believe  in  a  mere  science  of  history  than  in  a  mere  philosophy 
of  history.  All  that  I  can  grant,  therefore,  to  those  who,  for 
the  reason  mentioned,  would  speak  only  of  a  science  of  his- 
tory, is  that  any  professed  philosophy  of  history  which  is  not 
in  accordance  with  and  even  demanded  by  the  science  of  his- 
tory— which  does  not  receive  real  confirmation  from  the  facts 
of  history  and  tend  to  the  true  elucidation  of  these  facts  — 
must  be  worthless  and  delusive. 

I  cannot  see  any  objection  to  often  employing  the  terms 
science  and  philosophy  interchangeably.  Rigidly  and  continu- 
ally to  distinguish  them  is  not  only  what  no  one  does,  but  what 
no  one  should  do,  inasmuch  as  it  tends  to  lead  readers  to  over- 
look the  intimate  connection  and  community  of  nature  of 
science  and  philosophy.  If  we  are  resolved  to  use  the  word 
philosophy  only  in  its  strictly  appropriate  technical  sense,  we 
must  bear  in  mind  that  there  is  but  one  sense  which  can  either 
historically  or  logically  make  good  its  claim  as  such.  And 
in  this  sense  philosophy  is  not  contradistinguished  from  the 
sciences  but  comprehensive  of  them,  —  not  a  branch  or  branches 
of  knowledge  growing  alongside  of  other  branches,  but  the  root 
and  trunk  out  of  which  all  the  branches  grow,  and  the  life  by 
which,  and  the  crown  to  which,  they  grow,  —  not  the  rational 
appreciation  of  particular  aspects  of  the  intelligible  world,  but 
of  that  world  as  a  whole.  In  a  word,  philosophy  in  this  sense 
is  the  knowledge  of  knowledge,  the  science  of  the  sciences,  uni- 
versal not  particular  science.  But  in  this  sense  manifestly  no 
special  science  or  study  can  claim  to  be  philosophy  as  against 
any  other  special  science  or  study.  In  this  sense  one  has  no 
more  right  to  speak  of  moral  philosophy  than  of  natural  phi- 
losophy, or  of  the  philosophy  of  history  than  of  the  philosophy 
of  botany.  In  this  sense  philosophy  is  one  and  indivisible, 
universal  and  all-pervading. 

It  follows  from  the  very  nature  of  philosophy  as  thus  un- 


20  INTRODUCTION 

derstood  that  no  special  science  or  particular  department  of 
knowledge  is  philosophy  strictly  speaking.  It  follows  not  less, 
however,  that  no  special  science  is  excluded  from  having  the 
closest  connection  with  and  interest  in  philosophy,  so  that  each 
special  science,  and  even  every  special  subject,  may  be  naturally 
said  to  have  its  philosophy ;  the  philosophy  of  a  subject  as  dis- 
tinguished from  its  science  being  the  view  or  theory  of  the 
relations  of  the  subject  to  other  subjects  and  to  the  known 
world  in  general,  as  distinguished  from  the  view  or  theory  of 
it  as  isolated  or  in  itself.  It  is  a  grievous  error  when  science 
renounces  and  discards  philosophy.  The  mere  scientist — the 
scientist  who  gazes  exclusively  at  his  subject  and  refuses  to 
look  at  its  surroundings  and  relationships — is  not  the  true 
scientist ;  the  philosophic  scientist  alone  is  the  true  scientist. 
Philosophy  and  science  should  be  combined.  Hence  we  may 
often  use  either  word ;  and  the  one  word  rather  than  the  other 
according  as  the  philosophical  or  scientific  mode  of  contempla- , 
tion  and  treatment  is  the  more  prominent.  Thus,  when  a 
department  of  knowledge  is  very  comprehensive ;  when  it  mani- 
festly cannot  be  properly  cultivated  otherwise  than  in  relation  to 
the  whole  of  knowledge ;  when  it  implies,  includes,  and  utilizes 
a  number  of  special  studies  or  disciplines,  themselves  entitled 
to  be  called  sciences,  —  the  name  of  philosophy  may  well  be  pre- 
ferred to  that  of  science  as  the  generic  part  of  its  designation. 
The  separate  physical  sciences,  far  from  rendering  unnecessary 
or  impossible,  afford  a  basis  for  and  require  as  a  means  of  uni- 
fying, supplementing,  and  harmonising  themselves,  a  general 
elucidation  of  the  physical  world,  to  which  the  name  philosophy 
of  nature  would  be  appropriate,  and  which  might  be  quite  free 
from  the  metaphysical  nonsense  which  discredited  the  Natur- 
philosophie  of  German  speculation.  There  are  a  large  number 
of  special  theological  disciplines  which  treat  only  of  aspects  or 
departments  of  religion,  and  these  may  certainly  be  more  ap- 
propriately called  sciences  than  philosophies;  but  there  is  also 
an  all-comprehensive  science  of  religion  —  one  which  treats  of 
religion  in  its  unity  and  entirety — one  which  alone  completely 
answers  to  the  idea  and  definition  of  theology,— and  this  one 
general  theological  science,  which  comprehends  and  dominates 
the  special  theological  sciences,  so  as  to  be  the  science  of  these 


SCIENCE   OE   PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY?  21 

sciences,  may  reasonably  enough,  in  accordance  with  the 
true  distinction  between  philosophy  and  science,  be  called 
philosophy  rather  than  science — the  philosophy  of  religion. 
In  the  same  way,  when  history  is  studied  as  a  whole  and  in 
all  relations,  it  may  be  spoken  of  as  rather  the  subject  of 
a  philosophy  than  a  science,  seeing  that  no  subject  is  vaster 
and  more  complex,  or  more  manifoldly  dependent  on  and 
intimately  connected  with  all  existence  and  all  science.  It 
may  be  true  that  the  full  knowledge  of  any  one  thing 
involves  a  knowledge  of  all  other  things  —  that  the  "little 
flower  in  the  crannied  wall "  cannot  be  completely  under- 
stood until  God,  man,  and  the  world  are  understood ;  but  this 
is  only  by  implication,  whereas  the  knowledge  of  history  is 
explicitly  encyclopedic  and  universal,  all  that  man  knows 
being  as  much  a  part  of  his  history  as  what  he  suffers  or 
achieves.  In  history  nature  and  mind  and  all  the  sciences  of 
both  meet,  and  so  meet  that  all  these  sciences  in  their  entire 
evolution  are  but  elements  of  history,  and  the  whole  state  of 
science  at  any  moment  is  but  a  moment  of  history,  that  being 
called  science  to-day  which  will  be  called  history  to-morrow. 
If,  therefore,  the  word  philosophy  is  not  to  be  confined  exclu- 
sively to  the  universal  —  if  it  may  be  applied  to  the  partic- 
ular at  all  —  it  may,  I  think,  be  most  fitly  applied  to  the 
thorough  and  comprehensive  study  of  history  in  its  entirety 
and  relationships.  So  far  from  agreeing  with  those  who 
think  that  the  designation  "  science  of  history  "  should  be  used 
to  the  exclusion  of  that  of  "philosophy  of  history,"  I  confess 
that  if  restricted  to  one  of  them  it  is  the  latter  which  I  should 
prefer.  But  I  can  see  no  reason  for  making  a  choice.  The 
only  mode  of  distinguishing  between  science  of  history  and 
philosophy  of  history  which  seems  to  me  at  all  admissible,  is 
that  which  assigns  to  the  science  of  history  the  task  of  ascer- 
taining the  course,  plan,  and  laws  of  history  itself,  and  to  the 
philosophy  of  history  that  of  tracing  the  relations  of  causa- 
tion and  affinity  which  connect  history  with  other  depart- 
ments of  existence  and  knowledge.  But  such  science  and 
philosophy  are  so  plainly  of  the  same  nature,  and  each  is  so 
manifestly  feeble  and  imperfect  without  the  other,  that  there 
can  only  be  an  occasional  call  to  separate  them,  and  ordina- 


22  INTRODUCTION 

rily  they  ought  to  be  combined,  whether  under  the  name  of 
science  or  philosophy  it  matters  little.1 

The  development  we  have  to  trace  is  that  of  the  two  in  con- 
junction. We  have  to  exhibit  the  progress  of  induction  and 
generalisation  from  the  data  of  history  proper,  and  also  to 
indicate  how  history  has  had  light  cast  upon  it  from  the  most 
various  regions  of  experience  and  thought.  In  a  word,  we 
must  beware  of  walking  in  the  narrow  path  of  a  science 
which  disowns  philosophy,  while  we  regard  as  false  all  philos- 
ophy which  does  not  accord  with  the  findings  or  promote  the 
advance  of  science. 

I  shall  not  inquire  further,  in  the  way  of  introduction,  into 
the  nature  of  the  philosophy  of  history.  Enough  has  been 
said  to  show  what  is  here  meant  by  it,  and  what  will  be  aimed 
at  in  this  attempt  to  trace  its  development. 

Any  more  strictly  formal  or  logical  definition  of  it  than  has 
already  been  given  seems  unnecessary.  Definitions,  indeed, 
are  in  such  a  case  of  small  account.  So  far  from  the  defini- 
tion of  a  science  being  capable  of  conveying  a  knowledge  of 
the  science,  it  is  the  knowledge  of  a  science  which  makes  the 
definition  of  it  intelligible.  The  definition  can  merely  name 
or  indicate  the  object-matter  of  the  science  defined;  knowledge 
of  the  real  nature  of  that  object-matter  must  come  gradually 
in  the  measure  that  the  science  itself  is  acquired.  The  defi- 
nitions of  political  economy,  ethics,  theology,  and  the  philos- 
ophy of  history,  can  tell  us  that  these  disciplines  treat  respec- 
tively of  wealth,  morality,  religion,  and  history;  but  what 
wealth,  morality,  religion,  and  history  are,  the  sciences  which 
deal  with  them  must  themselves  be  left  to  reveal.  To  do  so 
is  their  sole  and  whole  business.  Real  comprehension  of  the 
definition  of  any  science  is  not  a  presupposition  but  a  result 
and  reward  of  the  study  of  the  science. 

It  has  been  argued  that  the  author  of  the  present  work 
should  have  stated  at  the  outset  his  own  conceptions  as  to  the 

1  The  author  has  treated  more  fully  of  the  relations  of  science  to  philosophy  in 
a  paper  on  "Philosophy  as  Scientia  Scientiarum,"  published  in  the  'Princeton 
Review,'  November  1878.  With  it  may  be  compared  his  two  articles  on  "The 
Classification  of  the  Sciences,"  published  in  the  'Presbyterian  Review'  (New 
York  and  Edinburgh),  July  1885  and  July  1886.  He  purposes  expanding  and 
supplementing  these  papers  so  as  to  form  an  Introduction  to  Philosophy. 


CONSIDERATION   OF   OBJECTIONS  23 

sphere,  method,  and  conclusions  of  the  philosophy  of  history. 
It  has  been  urged  that  if  he  had  thus  begun  by  expounding  a 
theory  of  his  own  he  could  have  criticised  more  effectively 
and  concisely  the  various  theories  which  he  passed  in  review ; 
and  that  as  some  definite  knowledge  of  the  philosophy  of 
history  is  needed  to  render  its  history  fully  intelligible,  such 
knowledge  should  have  been  the  first  thing  imparted.  This 
view  may  be  plausible,  but  it  does  not  seem  to  me  to  be  correct. 

A  mere  sketch  of  a  theory  of  history  of  my  own,  or,  in  other 
words,  an  unreasoned  and  unconfirmed  statement  of  my  own 
convictions  and  conclusions  as  to  the  philosophy  of  history, 
could  serve  no  good  purpose.  It  could  not  fail  to  do  injustice 
to  my  own  theory.  I  cannot  doubt  but  that  the  most  concise 
and  effective  mode  of  stating  and  recommending  that  theory 
will  be  to  expound  and  defend  it  not  before  but  after  having 
given  reasons  for  rejecting  those  which  are  inconsistent  with 
it.  And  to  condemn  the  theories  of  others  because  they  did 
not  agree  with  an  unproved  theory  of  mine  would  be  a  most 
unreasonable  mode  of  dealing  with  them.  Indeed,  to  criticise 
the  theories  of  others  by  any  theory  of  my  own,  although  it 
might  undoubtedly  be  a  very  "concise  "  process,  could  not  be 
a  really  effective  one,  owing  to  its  manifest  injustice.  One 
theory  of  history  ought  not  to  be  judged  of  by  another,  but 
by  its  conformity  or  nonconformity  to  the  facts  of  history  and 
the  laws  of  reason.  These  are  the  only  criteria  by  which  I 
deem  myself  entitled  to  judge  the  theories  which  may  come 
before  me. 

On  the  other  hand,  to  hold  that  the  author  of  a  history  of 
the  philosophy  of  history  must  introduce  it  with  an  adequately 
developed  and  established  system  of  the  philosophy  of  history, 
seems  as  utterly  unreasonable  as  to  maintain  that  an  historian 
of  chemistry  must  begin  his  history  with  an  exposition  of  the 
science.  A  man  not  conversant  with  chemistry  ought  cer- 
tainly not  to  attempt  to  write  its  history,  and  must  even  read 
its  history  with  comparatively  little  profit.  Yet  the  historian 
of  chemistry  may  well  leave  it  to  other  men  to  publish  syste- 
matic treatises  on  chemistry,  and  to  his  readers  to  get  from 
other  teachers  than  himself  the  knowledge  necessary  to  peruse 
a  history  of  chemistry  with  intelligence  and  to  advantage.     It 


24  INTRODUCTION 

is  not  otherwise  as  regards  the  philosophy  of  history.  The 
man  who  would  write  a  history  of  it  should  make  himself 
acquainted  not  only  with  the  various  theories  of  history  which 
have  been  propounded,  but  as  far  as  he  can  with  history  itself 
and  with  all  that  throws  light  upon  it,  for  it  is  by  history 
itself  that  he  must  estimate  the  worth  of  the  theories  which 
profess  to  explain  it;  and  the  most  qualified  student  and  judge 
of  such  a  history  will  be  the  man  whose  knowledge  of  history 
is  most  extensive  and  profound.  There  are  no  lack  of  philos- 
ophies of  history  already  in  existence,  and  adding  another  to 
the  number  would  not  greatly  help  my  readers,  while  it  would 
probably  be  unduly  attractive  to  my  critics.  A  knowledge 
of  history,  and  reflection  on  the  problems  presented  by  history, 
will  be  found  to  be  the  best  preparation ;  but,  of  course,  the 
possession  of  such  preparation  must  be  here  presupposed.  It 
certainly  cannot  be  here  supplied. 

The  development  of  the  philosophy  of  history  has  taken 
place  chiefly  in  France,  Germany,  Italy,  and  Britain.  It  will 
be  traced  in  each  of  these  nations  separately.  In  connection, 
indeed,  with  French  historical  philosophy  the  Belgian  will  be 
surveyed,  in  connection  with  the  German  the  Dutch,  and  in 
connection  with  the  British  the  American.  But  the  division 
and  distribution  of  the  work  will  be  the  fourfold  one  indicated. 
i  Against  this  method  objections  will  readily  suggest  them- 
.selves.  It  will  be  said  that  it  must  destroy  the  unity  of  the 
Avork  and  break  the  flow  of  the  narrative  ;  that  it  ascribes  too 
much  to  the  influence  of  nationality  and  too  little  to  the 
common  and  collective  development  of  civilisation ;  and  that 
it  necessitates  undesirable  repetitions,  inasmuch  as  it  requires 
the  same  school  of  historical  philosophy  if  it  has  spread  into 
several  lands  to  be  described  more  than  once,  although  one 
comprehensive  view  of  it  would  be  in  every  respect  more 
satisfactory.  It  will  be  concluded  that  the  natural  and  philo- 
sophical method  of  procedure  must  be  not  the  national  but 
the  universal  method ;  one  which  would  begin  by  tracing  a 
complete  sketch  of  the  intellectual  development  of  an  epoch, 
and  then,  without  reference  to  the  difference  of  nationalities, 
bring  together  all  that  the  epoch  has  done  for  what  one  is 
accustomed  to  call  the  philosophy  of  history.     In  this  way,  it 


CONSIDERATION   OF   OBJECTIONS  25 

would  seem  that  the  influences  which  have  most  powerfully 
affected  the  interpretation  of  the  history  of  humanity  —  as, 
for  example,  the  progress  of  the  sciences,  the  spread  of  new 
ideas  and  theories,  general  social  changes,  and  political  events 
of  wide-reaching  significance  —  will  be  best  exhibited.1 

Now  I  fully  admit  that  these  considerations  are  not  only  very 
plausible  but  contain  a  certain  amount  of  truth.  They  caused 
me  to  adopt  with  reluctance  the  method  which  I  follow,  and 
only  after  I  had  tried  and  been  forced  to  abandon  the  alterna- 
tive method.  I  began  with  the  general  method,  and  found  it 
easy  to  proceed  according  to  it  until  the  nineteenth  century 
was  reached.  Then  the  objections  to  it  speedily  began  to  make 
themselves  felt,  and  gradually  I  was  shut  up  to  the  conclusion 
that,  in  my  hands  at  least,  it  would  yield  a  less  satisfactory 
result  than  that  to  which  it  had  at  first  sight  seemed  preferable. 
The  great  bulk  of  the  history  lies  within  a  very  limited  period 
—  some  sixty  or  seventy  years.  Yet  due  regard  must  be  had, 
as  in  all  history,  to  the  chronology.  But  how  can  this  be  done 
in  a  narrative  whieh  has  to  embrace  all  the  chief  peoples  of  our 
civilisation,  and  which  is  not  to  be  a  mere  outline  but  a  detailed 
account?  Not  otherwise  than  by  an  incessant  and  intolerable 
leaping  from  one  country  to  another,  which  must  far  more 
effectually  destroy  unity  of  work  and  continuity  of  narrative 
than  the  method  alleged  specially  to  produce  these  effects. 
The  view  even  of  the  course  of  causation  or  genetic  evolution 
of  the  history  will  thus  be  far  more  broken  up  and  obscured. 
Within  the  national  developments  all  the  causes,  general  and 
special,  work  continuously  and  organically,  so  that  their  action 
can  only  be  rightly  exhibited  in  a  complete  and  uninterrupted 
narrative.  The  general  development,  on  the  other  hand,  if  it 
fail  to  include  and  incorporate  the  national  developments, 
would  prove  itself  so  abstract  as  to  be  worthless ;  and  if  it 
do  justice  to  them,  it  must  constantly  lose  itself  in  them,  and 
cease  to  be  general  except  in  name. 

I  readily  acknowledge  that  in  tracing  the  history  of  philos- 
ophy, or  of  any  of  its  departments,  too  much  may  be  ascribed 
to  nationality  and  too  little  to  a  common  civilisation.  There 
is  no  more  fundamental  distinction  between  the  ancient  ethnic 

1  A.  Stern,  in  '  Revue  Historique,'  Janv.-Fev.  1877. 


26  INTRODUCTION 

world  and  the  modern  Christian  world  than  that  in  the  latter, 
nations  are  not,  as  they  were  in  the  former,  so  separated  and 
isolated  as  to  live  an  exclusively  national  life,  but  are  in  con- 
tinuous and  conscious  communion  with  each  other,  members 
of  a  vast  intellectual  and  spiritual  system,  participant  in  a 
general  culture.  In  the  ancient  world  Egypt  and  Assyria, 
India  and  China,  Israel  and  Greece,  were,  as  regards  thought 
and  belief,  philosophy  and  religion,  national  in  a  sense  and 
measure  in  which  in  modern  Europe  Italy  and  France,  Ger- 
many and  England,  are  not  and  cannot  be.  For  any  of  these 
latter  nations  to  have  a  purely  national  religion,  culture,  or 
philosophy,  like  the  nations  of  oriental  and  classical  antiquity, 
it  must  renounce  its  share  in  the  splendid  spiritual  inheritance 
of  the  great  family  of  peoples  to  which  it  belongs.  Modern 
thought  is  in  character,  substance,  development,  and  general 
direction,  common  and  identical;  the  modern  spirit  has  a 
unity  which  reveals  the  absolute  spirit ;  and  in  the  modern 
world  each  nation  can,  consequently,  only  hope  to  develop  and 
perfect  its  own  life  through  free  communion  with  other  nations 
and  participation  in  the  fulness  of  the  universal  life.  But  it 
does  not  follow  that  the  historian  is  entitled  to  treat  national- 
ity as  of  only  secondary  significance  in  the  modern  world.  It 
does  not  follow  that  it  has  become  an  intermittent  agency 
which  admits  of  no  continuous  history,  or  one  so  feeble  in  its 
influence  that  it  may  often  be  left  out  of  account.  In  fact  it 
is  still  the  most  permanent,  comprehensive,  and  potent  of 
historical  factors.  It  alone  so  acts  on  and  with  the  various 
general  elements  of  civilisation  as  to  give  them  real  existence 
in  a  concrete  and  organic  unity.  It  is  to  a  people  what  indi- 
viduality is  to  a  person,  and  therefore  to  history  what  individ- 
uality is  to  biography.  Wherever  character  tells  much  on  the 
development  of  thought,  no  other  power  can  compare  in  influ- 
ence with  it.  And  its  force  is  not  a  decreasing  one.  In  spite 
of  superficial  appearances  to  the  contrary,  nationalities  are  not 
disappearing  but  increasingly  developing  and  characterising 
themselves.  As  the  individual  steadily  attains  to  clearer  self- 
knowledge  and  greater  freedom  and  power  in  the  manifesta- 
tion of  his  true  self,  so  each  growing  nation  is  seen  gradually 
to  enter  more  fully  on  the  possession  of  its  genius,  and  grad- 


CONSIDERATION   OF   OBJECTIONS  27 

ually  to  reveal  more  distinctly  what  its  character  and  capacities 
are.  The  advancing  unity  of  civilised  humanity  is  reflected 
in  and  attained  through  the  increasing  originality  and  self- 
activity  of  the  nations  which  are  its  constituent  members. 

The  relation  of  nationality  to  history  being  what  it  is,  it 
seems  very  desirable  to  give  a  continuous  and  complete  account 
of  the  development  of  historical  philosophy  in  each  of  the  chief 
countries  in  which  such  philosophy  has  been  cultivated.  It 
is  only  thus  that  justice  is  likely  to  be  done  to  the  historico- 
philosophical  work  of  each  country.  It  is  only  thus,  perhaps, 
that  there  can  be  a  chronologically  consecutive  narrative  at  all. 
Rocholl,  who  has  chosen  the  other  method,  is  led  by  it  to  treat 
of  Bossuet  before  Macchiavelli,  of  Vico  before  Bacon,  of  Adam 
Smith  before  Bodin,  of  Voltaire  before  Leibniz,  of  Mamiani 
before  Condorcet,  &c.  Possibly  these  errors  need  not  have 
been  committed,  but  I  doubt  if  numerous  smaller  errors  of  a 
similar  kind  could  have  been  avoided,  and  errors  of  such  a 
kind  are  fatal  in  any  historical  narrative-  It  is  possible  to 
write  a  consecutive  uninterrupted  narrative  within  national 
limits.  In  doing  so,  it  may  and  ought  to  be  indicated,  so  far 
as  is  relevant,  in  what  ways  and  in  what  measure  each  nation 
has  been  influenced  by  others.  It  is  true  that  in  tracing  the 
development  of  historical  philosophy  according  to  this  method 
a  school  or  system  will  in  certain  cases  have  to  be  dealt  with 
more  than  once.  But  will  this  be  unnecessary  or  undesirable 
repetition  ?  What  school  or  system  of  historical  philosophy 
has  not,  when  brought  under  new  national  conditions,  greatly 
changed  its  nature  and  character  ? 

After  the  national  developments  of  historical  philosophy 
have  been  traced,  a  comprehensive  delineation  of  their  rela- 
tionships and  of  the  common  movement  will  still  be  required. 
But  when  a  competent  knowledge  of  the  particular  develop- 
ments can  be  presupposed,  the  general  survey  may  be  com- 
paratively brief.  The  reader  will  then  have  been  prepared 
fully  to  understand  it,  and  to  form  an  intelligent  and  inde- 
pendent judgment  regarding  it. 


28  INTRODUCTION 


II 


The  origin  of  the  philosophy  of  history,  its  absolute  origin 
or  commencement,  is  not  to  be  dated  from  the  time  when  it  be- 
gan to  be  cultivated  as  a  distinct  division  of  knowledge.  It 
is  at  a  comparatively  late  stage  that  any  science  definitively 
separates  itself  from  contiguous  fields  of  knowledge  and  as- 
sumes an  independent  form.  The  man  of  genius  who  is  called 
the  founder  of  a  science  merely  brings  together  its  already 
existing  elements,  its  disjecta  membra,  which  lie  far  and  wide 
apart  embedded  in  the  most  diverse  studies,  organically  unites 
them  through  some  great  thought,  some  happy  discovery,  and 
breathes  into  the  body  thus  formed  the  breath  of  life.  There 
is  no  science,  even  among  those  which  like  geology  or  politi- 
cal economy  we  in  one  sense  rightly  enough  call  recent,  whose 
history  is  all  in  the  daylight ;  there  is  none  which  has  come 
at  once  into  the  full  enjoyment  of  individual  existence  like 
a  Pallas  from  the  brain  of  Jove ;  the  origins  of  science,  like 
the  origins  of  all  things,  lie  beyond  the  utmost  limits  research 
has  yet  attained.  In  very  old  poetry,  and  in  the  very  oldest 
mythology,  there  are  rudimentary  geological  speculations. 
The  atomic  doctrine  of  Dalton  is  but  a  more  developed  form 
of  the  hypothesis  maintained  by  the  Hindu  Kanada  and  the 
Greek  Democritus.  The  development  theory  of  Darwin  goes 
clearly  back  not  only  to  Maillet  and  Lamarck,  but  to  Anaxi- 
mander  and  Empedocles.  Although  political  economy  estab- 
lished its  claims  to  be  a  separate  science  only  in  the  eighteenth 
century,  it  may  be  truly  said,  seeing  that  economical  laws 
have  always  operated  and  always  forced  men  to  take  some 
cognisance  of  them  and  yield  some  obedience  to  them,  to  have 
had  an  existence  under  one  form  or  another  always  and  every- 
where. The  philosophy  of  history  is  no  exception  to  the  rule 
which  every  other  science  has  obeyed ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is 
perhaps  its  most  striking  example.  "While  men  still  dispute 
as  to  the  reality,  and  even  as  to  the  possibility,  of  its  separate 
scientific  existence,  religion,  poetry,  speculation  of  various 
kinds,  political  movements,  the  cares  and  trials  of  common 
life,  have  for  countless  generations  been  bringing  its  problems 
in  manifold  forms  before  the  human  mind  and  into  contact  with 


RELIGION    AND    HISTORICAL   THEORY  29 

the  human  heart.  As  diffused  through  these  things  it  is,  and 
for  we  know  not  how  long  has  been,  widely  present.  There 
may  have  been  a  time  during  which  man  felt  in  no  degree  the 
mystery  of  his  own  being,  but  no  direct  records  remain  of 
such  a  time.  So  far  as  can  be  gathered  from  the  mere  literary 
monuments  of  our  race,  a  kind  of  philosophy  of  history  may 
have  been  as  old  as  history  itself,  and  the  first  question  man 
proposed  to  himself  may  have  been  that  which  Milton  puts 
into  the  mouth  of  Adam:  "How  came  I  thus,  how  here? " 

Religion  has,  at  least  to  some  extent,  its  source  in  the  same 
quest  of  causes  from  which  proceed  philosophy  and  science. 
The  lowest  forms  of  religion  are  not  mere  embodiments  of  the 
feelings  of  fear,  or  love,  or  dependence,  but  consist  in  part  of 
rude  speculations  as  to  the  making  and  the  meaning  of  nature 
and  of  man.  It  is  still  truer  of  Asiatic  than  of  European 
civilisations  that  they  are  based  on  religion,  and  that  the 
rationale  of  their  distinctive  institutions  is  to  be  sought  in 
their  theological  creeds.  In  all  the  chief  religions  of  the 
East  we  find  reflections  more  or  less  elevated  on  the  origin 
and  destiny  of  the  race ;  attempts  more  or  less  plausible  to 
tell  whence  man  has  come  and  whither  he  is  going ;  how  the 
present  is  related  to  the  past  and  future ;  how  the  lower  world 
is  connected  with  a  higher.  Brahmanism  and  Buddhism 
have  supplied  to  Schopenhauer  the  elements  of  his  historical 
pessimism.  The  dualistic  conception  of  nature  and  history 
which  was  the  kernel  of  the  Mazdaic  faith  has  also  been  the 
germ  of  various  philosophic  hypotheses.  The  Old  Testament 
representations  of  God,  of  His  relations  to  man,  and  His 
actings  in  history,  and  its  teachings  as  to  human  unity,  moral 
retribution,  future  redemption,  and  a  Messianic  kingdom, 
have  often  been  accepted  and  exhibited  as  the  explanation  of 
universal  history.  That  Christianity,  like  all  other  religions, 
contains  a  theory  of  history,  although  only  under  the  form 
proper  to  a  religion,  has  been  strikingly  stated  by  the  French 
philosopher  Jouffroy  as  follows :  "  There  is  a  little  book  which 
is  taught  to  children,  and  on  which  they  are  examined  in  the 
church.  If  we  read  this  book,  which  is  the  Catechism,  we 
shall  find  a  solution  of  all  the  problems  which  have  been 
proposed;   all  of  them  without  exception.     If  we  ask  the 


30  INTRODUCTION 

Christian,  whence  comes  the  human  race,  he  knows;  or 
whither  it  goes,  he  knows;  or  how  it  goes,  he  knows.  If 
we  ask  that  poor  child,  who  has  never  reflected  on  the  subject 
in  his  life,  why  he  is  here  below,  and  what  will  become  of 
him  after  death,  he  will  give  you  a  sublime  answer,  which 
he  will  not  thoroughly  comprehend,  but  which  is  none  the 
less  admirable  for  that.  If  we  ask  him,  how  the  world  was 
created  and  for  what  end ;  why  God  has  placed  in  it  plants 
and  animals ;  how  the  earth  was  peopled ;  whether  by  a  single 
family  or  by  many ;  why  men  speak  different  languages ;  why 
they  suffer,  why  they  struggle,  and  how  all  this  will  end,  he 
knows  it  all.  Origin  of  the  world,  origin  of  the  species, 
question  of  races,  destiny  of  man  in  this  life  and  in  the  other, 
relations  of  man  to  God,  duties  of  man  to  his  fellow-men, 
rights  of  man  over  the  creation, —  he  is  ignorant  of  none  of 
these  points ;  and  when  he  shall  have  grown  up,  he  will  as 
little  hesitate  with  regard  to  natural  right,  political  right, 
or  the  right  of  nations :  all  this  proceeds  with  clearness,  and 
as  it  were  of  itself,  from  Christianity." 1  It  was  most  natural 
that  the  philosophy  of  history  should  have  first  clearly  pre- 
sented itself  in  Christendom,  and  in  some  such  form  as  that 
in  which  it  appeared  in  the  '  De  Civitate  Dei '  of  Augustine. 
It  was  most  natural  also  that  in  medieval  Christendom,  domi- 
nated as  it  was  by  Christian  theology,  no  other  kind  of 
philosophy  of  history  should  have  arisen.  The  only  philoso- 
phy of  history  of  which  the  medieval  mind  could  conceive 
was  one  the  principles  of  which  were  Christian  dogmas.  In 
modern  times  the  relation  between  Christianity  and  this  phi- 
losophy, as  between  Christianity  and  philosophy  in  general, 
has  become  looser  and  more  indeterminate.  Philosophies  of 
history  are  now  written  from  all  possible  religious  and  anti- 
religious  points  of  view.  During  the  present  century  all 
forms  of  Christianity,  all  forms  of  religion,  have  been  sought 
both  to  be  proved  and  disproved,  glorified  and  discredited,  by 
means  of  historical  philosophy.  A  still  greater  change  is 
that  in  modern  times  many  endeavours  have  been  made  to 
explain  history  without  any  theological  or  religious  presup- 
positions, that  is,  in  a  purely  scientific  or  philosophic  manner. 

1  Jouffroy, '  Premiers  melanges  phil.,'  3d  e'd.,  pp.  330-371,  as  abridged  and  trans- 
lated by  Ripley  in  Introductory  Notice  to  Jouffroy's  '  Philosophical  Essays.' 


PHILOSOPHY    AND    HISTORICAL    THEORY  31 

This  mode  of  dealing  with  history  will  doubtless  increasingly 
prevail,  and  the  older  theological  method  of  procedure  grad- 
ually disappear,  but  there  can  never  come  a  time  when  a 
man's  convictions  as  to  religion  will  be  without  influence  on 
his  historical  theorising.  The  same  views  of  the  infancy  of 
humanity  cannot  be  entertained  by  those  who  accept  the  first 
twelve  chapters  of  Genesis  as  verbally  inspired  and  by  those 
who  do  not,  nor  of  its  future  by  those  who  regard  religion  as 
essentially  true  and  by  those  who  believe  it  to  be  essentially 
delusive.  The  course  of  historical  speculation  has  been 
continuously  influenced  by  the  course  of  religious  belief. 

Philosophy  does  not  assume  form  and  body  till  long  after 
religion,  and  it  does  so  at  first,  wherever  there  is  a  great 
religion,  on  the  basis  of  religion  and  not  on  a  foundation  of 
its  own.  India,  which  is  the  great  philosophical  land  of 
Asia,  had  such  a  religion,  and  the  philosophy  of  India  never 
severed  itself  from  its  religion.  Its  chief  systems,  the  six 
darsanas,  are  classed  as  orthodox  and  heterodox ;  five  of  them 
rest  on  the  Vedas ;  and  although  it  cannot  be  said  that  the 
Sankhya  acknowledges  the  authority  of  any  sacred  book,  it 
proposes  to  itself  for  final  end  a  religious  aim,  the  securing  of 
salvation  to  man,  and  recommends  the  pursuit  of  truth  only  as 
a  means  to  its  accomplishment.  It  was  otherwise  in  Greece. 
The  anthropomorphic  polytheism  of  the  Greeks,  although 
singularly  beautiful,  being  mainly  a  product  of  imagination 
and  the  aesthetic  sense,  with  no  depth  of  root  either  in  the 
reason  or  conscience,  with  feeble  philosophical  and  moral 
possibilities,  has  no  claim  to  be  regarded  as  a  great  religion, 
and  indeed  would  seem  to  have  been  in  some  measure  out- 
grown by  the  Greek  mind  even  when  Homer  wrote.  Hence 
Greek  philosophy  from  its  origin  kept  itself  essentially  dis- 
tinct from  Greek  mythology,  the  influence  of  which  upon  it 
at  the  strongest  was  only  secondary;  at  a  very  early  date  it 
began  not  only  silently  to  undermine  but  openly  to  assail 
it  as  irrational  and  immoral.  It  is  its  characteristic  and  glory 
that  from  first  to  last  it  was  free  and  independent,  acknowl- 
edging subjection  to  no  authority  save  that  of  reason  alone. 
This  philosophy  having  fulfilled  its  mission,  expired  in  a 
struggle  with  Christianity;  and  the  classical  world  and  its 


32  INTRODUCTION 

wisdom  gave  place  to  a  new  social  order  and  a  higher  wisdom. 
Another  world,  arose  of  which  Christianity  was  the  central 
power,  the  dominant  principle,  and  again  for  centuries  phi- 
losophy was  rested  on  theology,  as  it  had  been  in  ancient 
India.  Only  sloAvly,  and  with  difficulty,  and  in  compara- 
tively recent  times,  has  philosophy  once  more  recovered  its 
independence  and  ceased  to  be  the  handmaid  or  bondwoman 
of  theology.  The  Hindu  darsayas  and  the  scholastic  phi- 
losophies were,  then,  systems  of  philosophy  based  on  systems 
of  theology.  One  consequence  was,  that  in  a  sense  they  were 
as  comprehensive  as  the  theologies  with  which  they  were 
connected.  Whatever  problems  the  Vedas  were  supposed  to 
have  shed  light  on,  the  Hindu  philosophers  felt  emboldened 
to  deal  with.  Whatever  the  Church  received  as  doctrine, 
the  scholastic  philosophers  made  it  their  aim  to  develop  and 
apply.  In  the  Indian  and  medieval  philosophies  there  is, 
accordingly,  no  lack  of  historical  theory  of  a  sort,  as  there  is 
no  lack  of  any  kind  of  theory  of  which  the  germs  may  be 
discovered  in  the  authoritative  sources  of  Brahmanism  and 
Christianity. 

The  Greek  philosophies,  although  not  based  like  Hindu  and 
medieval  philosophies  on  religion,  none  the  less  attempted 
to  compass  the  explanation  of  the  entire  universe.  They  did 
not,  as  modern  philosophies  generally  do,  presuppose  the 
positive  sciences,  but  occupied  their  place.  These  sciences 
did  not  then  exist.  There  was  only  one  vast  vague  philoso- 
phy, at  least  until  Aristotle  broke  it  up  to  some  extent  into 
parts  and  laid  the  foundations  of  certain  sciences;  and  that 
philosophy,  although  ever  baffled,  ever  renewed  its  efforts  to 
explain  nothing  less  than  the  mystery  of  all  that  is.  It  has 
to  be  acknowledged  that  even  in  its  oldest  form,  its  rude 
Ionian  stage,  when  assuming  water  and  air  and  indeterminate 
matter  to  be  first  principles,  it  did  not  overlook  that  the 
origin  of  man,  the  existence  of  intelligence,  and  the  gradation 
of  intelligence,  required  to  be  accounted  for  no  less  than  the 
character  and  arrangement  of  the  material  portions  of  the 
universe.  In  the  course  of  its  development  it  perhaps  gained 
few  permanent  and  positive  results,  but  besides  educating 
the  human  faculties,  it  was  accompanied  by  an  ever-widening 


PHILOSOPHY   AND   HISTORICAL   THEORY  33 

view  and  ever-deepening  sense  of  the  difficulty  and  magni- 
tude of  the  problem  it  sought  to  solve.  Man  and  society,  in 
particular,  gradually  bulked  more  prominently  before  it,  and 
commanded  a  constantly  increasing  share  of  attention,  until 
at  length  Plato  from  the  standpoint  of  idealism,  and  Aristotle 
from  that  of  realism,  elaborated  those  two  memorable  theories 
of  society  which  at  once  summed  up  the  past  and  represented 
the  great  antagonistic  movements  of  political  life  in  the 
future. 

Philosophy  asserted  its  independence  of  theology  at  the 
Renaissance,  and  sought  the  basis  of  certitude,  not  in  author- 
ity or  revelation,  but  in  thought  and  experience.  It  was 
long,  however,  before  it  earnestly  applied  itself  to  the  in- 
terpretation and  elucidation  of  history.  Bacon,  Descartes, 
Locke,  Spinoza  had  no  historical  philosophy,  although  they 
have  exercised  more  or  less  influence  on  its  development. 
With  the  eighteenth  century  history  became  a  favourite 
subject  of  the  ratiocination  which  then  generally  passed  for 
philosophy ;  but  only  in  the  nineteenth  century  has  it  been 
sought  to  submit  it  to  a  profound  and  systematic  treatment 
as  the  appropriate  matter  of  a  constituent  department  of 
philosophy.  In  this  last  century  every  philosophical  school 
in  Germany  has  laboured  at  the  construction  of  a  philosophy 
of  history  in  accordance  with  its  own  principles.  Not  a  few 
of  the  systems  reared  in  consequence  are  already  fallen  into 
ruin,  but  a  great  general  result  has  notwithstanding  been 
attained  —  a  recognition  on  the  part  of  all  thoughtful  men 
of  the  necessity  under  which  philosophy  lies  to  explain,  if 
possible,  the  course  and  significance  of  human  development 
as  a  whole.  In  Britain,  until  recently,  what  was  called  phi- 
losophy was  little  more  than  psychology,  and  a  psychology 
which  confined  its  attention  almost  exclusively  to  the  analysis 
of  the  phenomena  of  the  individual  consciousness ;  but  now 
a  broader  and  worthier  conception  of  philosophy  prevails, 
and  its  direct  interest  in  the  study  of  the  collective  life  of 
mankind  is  in  consequence  generally  recognised.  Our 
Spencerians  and  Neo-Hegelians  are  at  one  in  holding  that 
a  philosophy  must  include  a  theory  of  history,  and  for  this 
view  they  have  been  able  to  secure  an  easy  triumph. 


34  INTRODUCTION 

It  is  obvious  that  there  can  scarcely  be  political  disquisi- 
tion without  historical  speculation.  As  soon  as  political 
thought  comes  forth  into  life  it  is  found  to  oscillate  between 
two  poles  —  between  despotism  and  anarchy  —  the  extreme 
of  social  authority  and  the  extreme  of  individual  independ- 
ence. Before  political  thought  awakens,  social  authority 
predominates.  The  man  as  an  individual  does  not  exist,  but 
is  merged  in  the  family,  clan,  city,  or  nation.  But  in  every 
progressive  society  there  comes  a  time  when  its  stronger 
minds  feel  that  they  are  not  merely  parts  of  a  social  organism, 
but  have  a  life  and  destiny,  rights  and  duties  of  their  own, 
and  simply  as  men.  There  are,  then,  two  principles  in  the 
world  —  the  principle  of  authority  and  the  principle  of  liberty, 
the  principle  of  society  and  the  principle  of  individualism. 
These  two  principles  coexist  at  first  in  a  few  individuals, 
but  in  process  of  time  they  come  not  only  to  coexist  in  some 
degree  in  all,  but  to  manifest  themselves  apart,  and  then 
there  are  not  only  two  principles  in  the  individual  but  two 
parties  in  the  State,  the  one  inclining  more  to  the  side  of 
social  authority,  and  the  other  more  towards  individual 
independence.  There  thus  arises  a  conservative  and  a  liberal 
party ;  each  party  existing  in  virtue  of  its  assertion  of  a  truth, 
but  existing  only  as  a  party  because  it  does  not  assert  the 
whole  truth ;  each  conferring  its  special  services ;  each  having 
its  special  dangers ;  each  being  certain  to  ruin  any  society  in 
which  it  succeeds  in  crushing  the  other ;  but  the  two  securing 
both  order  and  progress,  partly  by  counteracting  each  other, 
and  partly  by  co-operating  with  each  other.  Now  it  is  not 
until  these  two  parties  emerge  and  their  respective  claims 
come  into  open  conflict  that  there  is  any  active  political 
thought,  any  general  political  theory;  and  hence  political 
thought,  political  speculation  at  least,  is  from  the  very  first 
forced  on  historical  speculation.  The  problem  which  is  its 
root,  out  of  which  it  issues,  is  no  other  than  this,— What  is 
the  relation  of  the  past  to  the  present  ?  What  influence  ought 
the  past  to  have  over  the  present,  and  society  over  the  indi- 
vidual ?  Where  between  slavish  deference  to  all  that  is  and 
a  proud  and  wilful  rejection  of  it,  lies  the  golden  mean  at 
which  political  wisdom  aims  ?  But  this  problem  involves  a 
whole  philosophy  of  history. 


POLITICAL   DISCUSSION   AND   HISTORICAL   THEORY         35 

It  was,  therefore,  altogether  natural  that  historical  reflec- 
tion should  have  received  in  Greece  a  special  stimulus  from 
the  Sophists,  who  effected  in  philosophy  the  transition  from 
cosmological  to  psychological  speculation,  and  who  substi- 
tuted in  politics  the  principle  of  individualism  for  that  of 
social  authority;  whose  chief  merit  was  assertion  of  the 
rights  of  the  subject,  and  whose  radical  error  was  denial  of 
the  rights  of  the  object,  both  in  philosophy  and  politics.  It 
was  natural,  also,  that  the  clearest  and  deepest  political 
thinker  of  the  classical  world,  Aristotle,  should  have  been 
the  man  who  came  nearest  being  the  founder  of  the  philoso- 
phy of  history.  He  had,  it  is  true,  scarcely  a  conception  of 
progress,  and  still  less  of  laws  of  progress,  but  he  had  studied 
closely  the  constitution  of  all  the  Greek  States  and  surround- 
ing peoples ;  had  a  ful^  appreciation  of  the  importance  of  the 
analysis  and  comparison  of  different  forms  of  government, 
and  employed  with  rare  skill  and  success  both  processes ;  and 
had  a  most  remarkable  insight  into  the  requirements,  com- 
position, working,  and  influence  of  every  species  of  polity 
which  had  until  his  time  been  tried.  Hence  he  had  singu- 
larly correct,  profound,  and  comprehensive  conceptions  of 
that  social  stability  or  order  which  is  the  prime  condition  of 
social  progress. 

The  historical  theories  of  individual  thinkers  will  always 
be  found  largely  explicable  by  the  contemporary  political 
condition  of  the  communities  to  which  these  thinkers  belong. 
It  was  the  political  state  of  the  Italy  of  his  day  which  led 
Macchiavelli  to  treat  of  history  as  he  did.  It  was  the  civil 
strife  and  distraction  in  England  in  the  time  of  Charles  I. 
which  suggested  to  Hobbes  his  doctrine  of  the  origin  and 
development  of  society.  In  this  volume  we  shall  be  contin- 
ually required  to  note  how  the  political  changes  which  have 
taken  place  in  France  have  forced  men  to  reconsider  the  past 
in  the  light  of  the  present,  and  how  differently,  in  conse- 
quence, the  past  has  appeared  to  each  new  generation. 
Political  ideals  and  Utopias  have,  perhaps,  had  as  powerful 
an  influence  as  religious  ones  on  the  rise  and  spread  of  his- 
torical hypotheses.  Just  now,  for  example,  socialism  is  the 
source  of  a  vast  amount  of  historical  speculation.     Already 


36  INTRODUCTION 

almost  every  form  of  socialism  claims  to  have  a  philosophy  of 
history  of  its  own.  Political  reflection  and  historical  theory 
are  often  so  closely  connected  that  it  is  difficult  or  impossible 
to  decide  where  the  one  ends  and  the  other  begins. 

It  must  further  be  remarked  that  the  progress  of  historical 
study  is  largely  dependent  on  the  general  advance  of  science. 
The  study  of  history  cannot  be  scientific  in  an  unscientific 
age.  The  rise  of  a  science  of  history  must  be  preceded  by 
the  rise  of  sciences  less  difficult  of  formation.  A  satisfactory 
philosophy  of  history  presupposes  not  only  a  science  of 
history  but  sciences  of  all  related  things.  In  antiquity  only 
■the  Greeks  and  Romans  reached  the  stage  of  culture  at  which 
a  successful  treatment  of  history  as  an  art  became  possible. 
[  Only  in  the  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries  of  the  Chris- 
tian era  did  the  modern  mind  begin  to  entertain  the  hope 
that  history  might  yield  scientific  results  if  a  right  method 
of  seeking  them  could  be  devised.  And  it  was  long  after 
before  much  promise  appeared  of  the  hope  being  likely  to  be 
realised.  It  was  impossible  that  the  processes  of  induction 
could  be  successfully  applied  to  historical  materials  before 
the  mind  had  become  accustomed  to  their  use  in  the  various 
departments  of  physical  science  where  their  employment  is 
so  much  simpler.  It  is  chiefly  through  the  growth  of  physi- 
cal science  that  the  notion  of  law  in  human  development 
has  arisen,  and  chiefly  through  it  also  that  the  path  which 
leads  to  the  discovery  of  law  has  been  opened  up.  Not  till 
long  after  induction  was  familiar  to  physicists,  not  till  long 
after  Lord  Bacon  had  traced  its  general  theory,  was  it,  or 
could  it  be,  practised  to  any  considerable  extent  in  historical 
research. 

There  is  now  little  danger  of  the  dependence  of  historical 
science  on  other  sciences  being  entirely  ignored.  The  preva- 
lent tendency  at  present  is  to  consider  history  as  explicable 
to  a  far  greater  extent  than  it  really  is  by  the  laws  of  some 
naturally  antecedent  or  more  general  science.  Thus  it  has 
been  represented  as  a  mere  dependency  of  mathematics,  for 
actual  men  a  moyen  homme  being  substituted,  and  for  histori- 
cal criticism  and  research  statistical  tables  and  averages. 
According  to  another  view  history  is  "  a  problem  of  mechan- 


HISTORICAL   STUDY   AND   SCIENTIFIC   PROGRESS  37 

ics,"  one  the  difficulty  of  which  arises  partly  from  its  com- 
plexity, and  partly  from  the  illusion  that  there  is  such  a 
thing  as  free  will.  M.  Taine  regards  it  as  rather  a  sort  of 
chemistry,  all  so-called  virtues  and  vices  being  only  "  natural 
products  like  sugar  and  vitriol."  On  the  other  hand,  Dr. 
Draper  is  of  opinion  that  it  is  a  department  of  physiology, 
intellectual  development  being  a  physiological  process,  and 
the  epochs  of  history  stages  of  physiological  growth.  Some, 
like  Bagehot,  would  explain  history  by  biological  laws,  and 
others,  like  Buckle,  by  geographical  conditions.  All  these 
views  are  one-sided  and  exaggerated.  The  comprehension  of 
history  is  not  to  be  gained  exclusively,  or  even  mainly,  by 
deduction  from  the  laws  of  other  sciences ;  it  must  be  drawn 
chiefly  by  induction  from  the  facts  of  history  itself.  Yet  the 
views  referred  to  rest  on  a  considerable  basis  of  truth.  The 
various  sciences  to  which  appeal  is  made  are  really  fitted, 
each  in  its  place  and  measure,  to  contribute  to  the  formation 
of  the  science  and  philosophy,  of  history.  All  the  forces  and 
laws  of  the  universe  so  combine  and  co-operate  in  the  consti- 
tution and  life  of  man,  that  all  the  sciences  which  instruct 
us  as  to  their  nature  necessarily  help  us  to  understand  why 
the  course  of  history  has  been  what  it  actually  has  been. 

Some  even  of  the  physical  sciences  are  of  an  essentially 
historical  nature.  Geology  is  an  exposition  of  the  history  of 
the  earth,  and  Biology  of  the  history  of  life.  Geological  and 
biological  studies  have  thus  for  aim  to  recall  and  recount  an 
older  and  vaster  history  than  that  of  man,  one  on  which  the 
history  of  man  rests,  and  within  which  it  is  enclosed.  The 
method  followed  in  these  studies  is  the  same  as  that  which 
is  employed  in  human  history  —  the  method  which  elicits  a 
knowledge  of  facts,  and  of  the  order  and  mode  of  their  occur- 
rence, from  such  signs  or  traces  or  records  of  them  as  remain. 
They  are  closely  akin  to  the  science  of  history  alike  as  regards 
the  matter  of  which  they  treat,  and  the  manner  in  which  they 
treat  it. 

They  are  less  so,  however,  than  various  psychical  sciences, 
as,  for  instance,  comparative  psychology  and  comparative 
philology,  inasmuch  as  these  latter  must  consist  not  merely 
of  a  knowledge   of  facts  drawn  from  records,   but  of  facts 


38  INTRODUCTION 

which  are  human, —  the  products  of  man's  thought  and  will. 
Comparative  psychology  traces  hoAv  the  minds  and  characters 
of  races,  peoples,  and  nations  have  been  formed ;  comparative 
philology  traces  the  development  of  their  speech  through 
which  their  minds  and  characters,  their  thoughts  and  senti- 
ments, are  so  largely  disclosed.  Both  necessarily  follow  the 
historical  and  comparative  method  of  research,  not  otherwise 
than  ecclesiastical  and  political  history.  It  is  from  the 
advance  of  comparative  psychology  that  we  may  expect  to 
see  the  most  marked  progress  in  the  scientific  interpretation 
of  history  in  the  near  future.  < 

There  is  likewise  the  most  intimate  connection  between 
history  and  political ,  economy.  Anjr  system  of  political 
economy,  however  ingeniously  or  logically  constructed,  which 
does  not  rest  on  a  close  and  comprehensive  study  of  the  his- 
torical evolution  of  economic  phenomena,  must  be  unstable 
and  unsubstantial.  And  the  whole  political  and  moral, 
intellectual  and  spiritual,  development  of  society  largely 
depends  on  the  economic  phenomena  and  changes  which  it 
is  the  business  of  political  economy  to  explain.  The  general 
historical  movement  of  humanity  cannot  be  understood  by 
men  who  are  insufficiently  acquainted  with  the  various  phases 
of  economic  history,  and  with  the  laws  of  economic  facts. 
The  growth  of  science  and  philosophy,  the  culture  of  art  and 
literature,  the  development  of  morality  and  religion,  have 
all,  indeed,  richly  contributed  to  make  history  what  it  is ; 
but,  even  collectively,  they  have  only  in  part  determined  its 
course,  and  have  all  been  to  a  far  greater  extent  than  is  com- 
monly supposed  dependent  on  conditions  of  an  economic 
character.  The  science  of  history  and  of  political  economy 
are  therefore  so  closely  related,  that  one  of  them  cannot  exist 
in  any  well-developed  form  where  the  other  does  not.  They 
have  never  been  found  apart.  In  the  ancient  oriental  world 
neither  of  them  existed.  Nor  in  the  classical  world,  although 
there  both  clear  thought  on  economic  facts  and  the  power  to 
exhibit  and  explain  historical  movements  conspicuously  dis- 
played themselves.  Thucydides  owed  his  superiority  as  an 
historian  in  no  slight  degree  to  the  clearness  with  which  he 
saw  the  bearings  of  economic  circumstances  and  conditions 


POLITICAL   ECONOMY   AND   HISTORY  39 

on  the  course  and  fortunes  of  the  Peloponnesian  war.  Chris- 
tianity almost  spontaneously  and  inevitably  produced  a  sort 
of  philosophy  of  history;  but  a  philosophy  excessively  one- 
sided, owing  to  the  life  of  society  on  earth  being  viewed 
so  exclusively  in  relation  to.  religion  and  eternity,  that  the 
interests  of  time,  and  the  significance  of  industry,  commerce, 
and  wealth,  almost  faded  out  of  sight.  It  was  not  until  the 
eighteenth  century  was  far  advanced  that  the  foundations  of 
political  economy  were  laid.  The  rise  of  the  new  science 
was  a  fact  of  the  utmost  importance  for  the  scientific  study 
of  the  general  development  of  human  societies.  It  brought 
with  it  a  vast  change  in  the  very  mode  of  looking  at  history. 
Montesquieu,  Turgot,  Adam  Smith,  and  others,  made  appar- 
ent the  interconnection  of  the  two  sciences,  and  initiated  a 
new  epoch  in  the  treatment  of  both.  Socialism,  although  so 
far  a  reaction  from  the  economic  system  dominant  in  the 
eighteenth  century,  tended  still  more  to  fix  the  attention  of 
historical  students  and  historical  theorists  on  the  development 
of  industry  and  the  various  stages  through  which  the  class 
the  most  numerous  and  poor  has  passed.  Saint  Simon  con- 
templated the  entire  history  of  humanity  from  the  point  of 
view  of  the  progressive  amelioration  of  the  material  and  moral 
condition  of  the  proletariat.  And  there  can  be  no  doubt  that 
he  thus  gave  a  most  beneficial  impulse  to  historical  investi- 
gation and  speculation.  One  of  the  greatest  of  Auguste 
Comte's  services  as  an  historical  philosopher  was,  it  seems  to 
me,  the  ingenuity  and  ability  with  which  he  made  manifest 
how  the  industrial  movement  in  pervading  universal  history 
had  acted  on,  and  corresponded  to,  the  scientific,  aesthetic, 
moral,  and  religious  movements.  Had  his  exposition  of 
social  dynamics  possessed  even  no  other  merit  than  this,  it 
would,  I  think,  have  amply  entitled  him  to  a  very  distin- 
guished place  among  those  who  have  laboured  to  ascertain 
the  course  and  laws  of  social  development.  The  historical 
school  of  political  economy  arose  in  Germany  in  the  fourth 
decade  of  the  present  century;  and  its  principles  as  set  forth 
by  Roscher,  Hildebrand,  and  Knies,  rapidly  gained  wide 
acceptance  in  the  Fatherland.  The  writers  of  this  school 
regarded  economics  as  the  theory  of  the  laws  of  the  economic 


40  INTRODUCTION 

development  of  nations  —  the  "  Philosophic  der  Wirthschafts- 
geschichte."  Such  a  view  is  an  exaggeration ;  but,  unques- 
tionably, we  owe  to  it  a  multitude  of  researches  which  have 
vastly  increased  our  knowledge  of  almost  all  periods  of 
economic  history,  as  well  as  of  the  history  of  almost  all 
economic  conceptions  and  opinions.  There  is  no  longer  any 
danger  that  the  changes  which  have  occurred  in  the  produc- 
tion and  distribution  of  wealth  at  different  epochs,  and  their 
social  effects,  will  fail  to  attract  the  attention  of  historians, 
or  will  be  left  out  of  account  by  historical  theorists.  Indus- 
trial evolution  during  the  last  hundred  years  has  been  so 
marvellous  in  itself,  and  has  so  affected  the  whole  course  and 
transformed  the  whole  character  of  the  world  of  humanity, 
as  to  have  rendered  interesting  the  industrial  history  of  all 
peoples  and  ages. 

It  is  sufficient  merely  to  refer  to  a  large  group  of  studies 
or  sciences  which  are  obviously  and  directly  auxiliary  to 
history.  Such  are  geography,  chronology,  archeeology,  lin- 
guistics, criticism,  and  hermeneutics.  Without  an  adequate 
mastery  of  these  it  is  impossible  to  become  a  successful 
historian.  They  are  partly  the  materials  and  partly  the  tools 
of  the  historian ;  and  alike  as  materials  and  tools,  they  are 
indispensable  to  him.  The  study  of  history  cannot  be  more 
advanced  than  their  condition  permits.  For  example,  before 
the  histories  of  Brahmanism,  Buddhism,  Zoroastrianism, 
could  be  ascertained,  their  original  documents  had  to  be  read, 
and  before  that  could  be  done,  Sanscrit,  Pali,  and  Zend  had  to 
be  acquired.  The  primary  sources  of  a  knowledge  of  Egyp- 
tian and  Assyrian  history  are  in  hieroglyphic  and  cuneiform 
inscriptions,  and  were  unintelligible  until  these  were  deci- 
phered and  translated.  In  these  cases  history  had  to  wait  until 
the  work  of  linguistics  was  accomplished.  But  its  depend- 
ence on  criticism  has  been  in  recent  times  not  less  decisively 
shown.  The  fresh  sifting  of  old  materials  has  been  found  as 
productive  as  the  discovery  of  new.  For  instance,  the  views 
of  scholars  regarding  the  histories  of  two  of  the  most  important 
peoples  of  antiquity  — -  the  Romans  and  the  Hebrews  —  have 
been,  if  not  completely  revolutionised,  profoundly  altered  by 
the  criticism  to  which  their  national  records  have  been  sub- 
jected by  Niebuhr,  Ewald.  and  their  successors. 


HISTORICAL   PHILOSOPHY   A   GROWTH   OF   HISTORY       41 

Of  all  kinds  of  knowledge,  however,  it  is  history  itself 
which  is  in  closest  contact  with  the  science  of  history.  The 
science  of  history  is  not  a  something  separate  from  the  facts 
of  history,  but  a  something  contained  in  them.  The  more  a 
man  gets  into  the  meaning  of  them  the  more  he  gets  into  it, 
and  it  into  him;  for  it  is  simply  the  meaning,  the  rational 
interpretation,  the  knowledge  of  the  true  nature  and  essential 
relations  of  the  facts.  And  this  is  true  of  whatever  species 
or  order  the  facts  may  be.  Their  science  is  not  something 
separate  and  distinct  from  —  something  over  and  above  — 
their  interpretation,  but  simply  their  interpretation.  He  who 
knows  about  any  people,  epoch,  or  special  development  of 
human  nature,  how  it  has  come  to  be  what  it  is,  and  what  it 
tends  to,  what  causes  have  given  it  the  character  it  has,  and 
what  its  relation  is  to  the  general  development  of  humanity, 
has  attained  to  the  science  or  philosophy  of  the  history  of 
that  people,  epoch,  or  development.  It  is  inaccurate  to  speak, 
as  is  often  done,  of  scientific  history  as  a  Jcind  of  history. 
Every  kind  of  history  is  scientific  which  is  true  and  thor- 
ough; which  goes  closely  and  deeply  enough  to  work;  which 
shows  the  what,  how,  and  why  of  events  as  far  as  reason  and 
research  can  ascertain  them. 

History  always  participates  in  some  measure  of  philosophy : 
for  events  are  always  connected  according  to  some  real  or 
ideal  principle,  either  of  efficient  or  final  causation.  The 
dullest  mind  can  only  describe  them  on  that  condition ;  the 
most  confused  mind  must  have  some  sort  of  reason  of  selec- 
tion, and  any  sort  of  reason  followed  out  will  lead  to  some 
sort  of  philosophy.  The  more  the  mind  of  the  historian  is 
awake  and  active,  the  more,  of  course,  it  is  impelled  to  go 
in  search  of  the  connections  between  causes  and  effects, 
between  occurrences  and  tendencies.  The  longer  any  por- 
tion of  history  is  studied,  the  greater  the  number  of  minds 
attracted  to  its  consideration,  the  more  frequently  it  is 
worked  through  and  thought  over,  the  richer  in  reason  it  is 
found  to  be,  the  more  of  order  and  law,  of  permanent  forces, 
of  general  features,  of  pervading  spirit  and  principles,  it 
discloses.  And  this  is  just  equivalent  to  saying  that  as 
historical  research  and  reflection  advance,  historical  science 
naturally  and  necessarily  arises ;  that  history  surely,  although 


42  INTRODUCTION 

slowly,  and,  as  it  were,  of  itself,  leads  up  to  the  philosophy 
of  history;  that  in  each  new  epoch  of  its  own  development  it 
must  become  more  philosophical,  more  conscious  of  the  prin- 
ciples which  regulate  the  succession  of  human  affairs,  and  at 
once  more  comprehensive  and  definite  in  the  apprehension  of 
the  character,  causation,  and  significance  of  all  past  transac- 
tions. 

It  seems  to  follow  that  some  indication  should  here  be 
given  of  the  stages  through  which  historiography  has  passed 
from  its  origin  to  the  time  when  our  own  narrative  begins  — 
i.e.,  when  the  philosophy  of  history  commenced  to  be  culti- 
vated as  a  special  department  of  knowledge  in  the  chief 
nations  of  Europe.  The  sketch  will  be  very  brief,  and  it 
will  be  delineated  entirely  with  reference  to  the  particular 
end  in  view. 

Ill 

History,  we  may  be  certain,  did  not  begin  by  describing 
events.  That  was  a  task  to  which  in  infancy  her  powers  were 
incompetent,  and  her  resources  insufficient.  She  must  long 
have  been  confined  to  the  mere  indication  of  events  by  simple 
helps  to  memory,  or  rude  symbols.  Literature  made  its  first 
appearance  as  verse,  and  in  alliance  with  music.  In  the  dawn 
of  literature  the  man  of  genius  sang  what  he  had  to  say,  and 
his  words  thus  winged  for  far  and  long  flight  needed  neither 
chisel  nor  pen  to  give  them  enduring  publicity.  Poetry  pre- 
ceded prose,  and  among  the  oldest  forms  of  poetry  were  the 
ballad  and  the  epic.  In  these,  historical  elements  were  often 
present,  but  rarely,  if  ever,  in  a  pure  form.  The  myth  and 
legend  interest  primitive  man  more  than  real  fact.  His  vision 
is  more  largely  of  the  imagination  than  of  the  sense  or  judg- 
ment. It  is  an  error  to  regard  the  rude  minstrelsy  which  has 
everywhere  long  preceded  the  use  of  letters  as  essentially 
historical.  For  the  supposition  of  Buckle  that,  until  cor- 
rupted by  the  discovery  of  the  art  of  writing,  such  minstrelsy 
is  "  not  only  founded  on  truth,  but  strictly  true,"  there  is  no 
shadow  of  evidence.  Nothing  seems  more  easy,  but  few  things 
are  more  difficult,  than  to  look  naturally  at  historical  fact  so 
as  to  see  it  just  as  it  is.  The  power  to  do  this  is  not  a  gift 
of  nature,  but  a  result  of  culture,  and  no  race  or  nation  has 


ORIENTAL   HISTORIOGRAPHY  43 

possessed  it  until  it  reached  intellectual  maturity.  The  poetry 
most  akin  to  historical  composition  attained  a  wonderful  ex- 
cellence among  various  peoples  long  before  they  had  histories 
even  of  the  meanest  order.  India  can  boast  of  the  Ramayana 
and  Mahabharata,  but  is  without  an  historical  literature. 
Greece  had  Homer  long  before  Herodotus  appeared.  Italy 
had  Dante  long  before  Guicciardini  and  Macchiavelli.  In  the 
dramas  of  Shakespeare  a  skill  was  displayed  in  the  portrayal  of 
character  and  situations  which  has  never  been  equalled  before 
or  since :  and  yet,  at  least  until  the  age  of  Charles  II.,  Eng- 
lish historians  were  almost  wholly  lacking  in  art  of  the  kind. 
Only  slowly  could  the  intellect  of  antiquity  free  itself  from 
the  fetters  of  tradition,  myth,  and  rhyme,  so  as  to  be  able  to 
deal  with  historical  materials  in  a  natural,  truthful,  and  living 
manner. 

The  most  ancient  known  nations,  notwithstanding  the  gene- 
ral height  of  civilisation  to  which  they  attained,  failed  to  rise 
to  eminence  in  the  art  of  historiography,  even  when  they  assid- 
uously practised  it.  The  Egyptians  and  Assyrians  wrote  an  J 
enormous  amount  of  history  of  a  kind,  and  among  both  peo- 
ples it  was  history  of  much  the  same  kind.  Differing  in  many 
respects,  these  great  monarchies  yet  had  —  in  the  dependence 
of  enormous  populations  on  a  central  individual  will,  the  exist- 
ence of  a  learned  class,  the  concentration  of  population  in  vast 
and  crowded  cities,  and  other  characteristics  and  wants  of  the 
civil  and  political  life  inseparable  from  every  extensive  empire 
of  a  despotic  type  —  enough  in  common  to  account  for  the 
antiquity  and  authenticity  of  such  historical  records  as  they 
possess :  royal  genealogies,  registers  of  military  expeditions, 
and  treaties,  lists  of  tribute,  accounts  of  remarkable  events  and 
exploits,  court  chronicles,  and  laudations  of  kings.  But  the 
very  circumstances  which  originated  history  at  an  early  date 
in  these  empires  determined  also  that  it  should  never  rise 
above  the  humblest  stage,  —  the  dull,  dead  form  of  mere  regis- 
tration. It  has  never  been  found  to  flourish  even  in  the  mod- 
ified despotisms  of  modern  times ;  and  it  was  impossible  that 
it  should  develop  itself  with  any  vigour  on  a  soil  unfertilised 
by  any  living  springs  of  national  feeling,  and  in  the  withering 
atmosphere  of  ancient  oriental  tyranny.  History  of  the  kind 
found  in  these  countries  is,  accordingly,  both  very  superficial 


44  INTRODUCTION 

/  and  Very  narrow.  It  is  very  superficial,  because,  occupied  only 
with  the  outward  acts  and  fortunes  of  a  few  ruling  men,  and 
satisfied  with  the  mere  statement  of  certain  public  events 
severed  from  their  causes,  it  makes  no  attempt  to  understand 
the  character,  the  conditions,  the  social  development  of  the 
people  or  nation  itself.  It  is  very  narrow,  because,  in  addition 
to  being  thus  exclusively  conversant  with  a  small  class  or  caste 
of  persons  in  the  nation,  and  with  what  affects  their  interests, 
it  wholly  fails  to  realise  that  any  other  nation  can  have  his- 
torical significance.  A  spirit  of  intense  exclusiveness  and 
unlimited  pride  pervades  it,  and  often  finds  undisguised  ex- 
pression. The  monarchs  were  in  their  own  eyes  and. those  of 
their  subjects  veritable  gods  on  earth.  As  against  the  one  na- 
tion held  to  be  favoured  of  heaven,  neighbouring  peoples  were 
not  recognised  to  have  any  claims  to  independence,  respect,  or 
benevolence.  Alike  in  Assyria  and  Egypt  hypotheses  or  spec- 
ulations were  current  as  to  the  origin  of  the  world  and  of  man, 
as  to  the  great  divisions  of  time,  reigns  of  gods,  demigods, 
and  human  beings,  as  to  the  destruction  of  the  present  order 
of  things,  and  the  rise  of  a  new  cycle  of  existence  ;  but  they 
were  not  to  any  appreciable  extent  generalisations  from  the 
study  of  actual  history.  They  were  almost  entirely  deduc- 
tions from  mythical,  philosophical,  and  astronomical  premises. 
__  The  Chinese  have  undoubtedly  surpassed  all  other  great 
oriental  peoples  in  the  department  of  historical  literature.  To 
this  result  their  rare  sense  for  the  realities  of  common  life, 
their  reverence  for  ancestors  and  antiquity,  their  comparative 
lack  of  imagination,  their  moderation  of  judgment,  political 
good  sense,  and  social  virtues,  and  their  high  appreciation  and 
diligent  pursuit  of  learning  and  culture,  have  all  contributed. 
No  people  can  boast  of  so  lengthened  and  strictly  continuous 
a  series  of  historical  writers  ;  since  for  upwards,  apparently,  of 
2600  years  a  tribunal  has  been  established  in  the  capital  ex- 
pressly for  the  recording  of  events  supposed  to  be  of  national 
importance.  The  mass  of  Chinese  literature  is  immense.  It 
includes  the  histories  of  particular  dynasties,  annals  or  chron- 
ological summaries,  complete  records  or  general  histories, 
memoirs  of  many  kinds,  biographies  innumerable,  vast  histor- 
ical dictionaries  and  compilations.  It  exhibits  all  ages  and 
aspects  of  the  national  life,  and  much  of  it  is  written  in  a  style 


ORIENTAL   HISTORIOGRAPHY  45 

which  commends  itself  to' Chinese  taste  as  admirable.  But 
even  Chinese  historiography  scarcely  rises  above  the  stage  of 
annals.  It  diligently  collects  and  carefully  arranges  notices 
of  historical  fact,  but  it  does  not  critically  test  them,  and  still 
less  does  it  penetrate  into  the  inner  spirit  and  follow  the  essen- 
tial development  of  the  history.  It  lacks  the  thoroughness  of 
science  and  the  comprehensiveness  of  philosophy.  It  fails  to 
rise  to  any  truly  general  point  of  view.  It  is  cultivated  only  as 
a  nationally  useful  art ;  not  realised  to  be  the  mirror  in  which 
humanity  can  contemplate  the  reflection  of  its  own  nature. 

The  two  most  celebrated  historians  of  China,  although  sepa-  r 
rated  by  twelve  centuries,  bear  the  same  family  name.  Szema-  / 
Thsian  (born  about  B.C.  145)  wrote  'Historical  Records '  (Sze' 
Ke),  a  kind  of  encyclopedia  of  all  that  appeared  historically 
noteworthy  in  the  annals  of  China  from  the  reign  of  Hwang-te 
to  that  of  Wo-te — i.e.,  from  about  2697  before  the  Christian 
era  to  the  age  in  which  the  author  lived.  He  distributed  his 
materials  into  three  divisions,  and  various  subdivisions,  yet 
presented  them  as  far  as  possible  chronologically.  Hence  his 
work  bears,  as  has  been  said,  no  slight  analogy  to  Henry's 
'History  of  Great  Britain,'  or  the  'Pictorial  History  of  Eng- 
land.' It  has  served  as  a  model  to  many  subsequent  Chinese 
historians,  is  regarded  with  admiration  by  native  critics,  and 
has  been  highly  commended  by  such  eminent  European  author- 
ities as  Schott  and  Remusat.  Szema-Kwang,  often  styled  the 
"Prince  of  Literature,"  flourished  in  the  eleventh  century  of 
our  era,  and  produced  the  '  Universal  Mirror  for  Rulers  ' 
(Tsze  Che  Tung  Keen).  It  describes  a  period  of  1362  years, 
and  flows  on,  in  the  main,  as  a  single  continuous  stream  of 
narrative.  It  has  been  the  most  popular  of  Chinese  histories. 
It  has  been  often  added  to,  and  with  the  additions  bringing 
the  record  onwards  to  the  eighteenth  century,  it  was  trans- 
lated into  French  by  Father  Mailla,  and  published  by  Grosier 
and  Le  Roux  in  12  vols.,  1777-83. 

The  Japanese  have  been,  like  the  Chinese,  liberally  en-t 
dowed  with  the  historical  spirit.     The  present  royal  race  is  : 
held  by  native  historians  to  have  reigned  since  the  sixth 
century  before  the  commencement  of  the  Christian  era,  and 
is  undoubtedly  the  oldest  in  existence.     Whether  Japanese 
historiography  was  of  native  origin,  or  wholly  evoked  under 


46  INTRODUCTION 

Chinese  influence,  is  a  disputed  question;  as  also  how  far 
back  its  earliest  authentic  notices  go.  The  European  special- 
ists, who  are  presumably  more  critical  than  the  native  scholars, 
seem  now  generally  to  hold  that  authentic  Japanese  history 
does  not  go  farther  back  than  the  beginning  of  the  sixth  cen- 
tury, A.D.  The  oldest  Japanese  work,  the  Kojiki  (Records 
of  Ancient  Matters),  was  completed  in  a.d.  712.  This 
work,  which  has  been  translated  by  Basil  Hall  Chamberlain 
('  Transactions  of  the  Royal  Asiatic  Society  of  Japan,'  vol.  x., 
Appendix),  is  of  exceptional  interest,  both  as  being  the  most 
ancient  extant  literary  monument  of  what  is  called  the  Tura- 
nian, or  Altaic,  or  Sc3rthian  race,  and  as  the  least  adulterated 
expression  of  the  mythology  and  legendary  story  of  ancient 
Japan ;  but  I  have  not  been  able  to  see  anything  in  it  which 
looks  like  authentic  history.  The  Nihongi  (Chronicles  of 
Japan),  completed  a.d.  720,  is  a  work  of  similar  character, 
but  much  more  affected  by  Chinese  influence.  In  the  eighth 
and  ninth  centuries,  what  are  known  as  the  'Six  National 
Records '  were  ^composed  by  a  number  of  writers,  of  whom 
Sigwara  Michizane  has  left  the  highest  reputation.  From 
the  tenth  to  the  thirteenth  century  there  was  a  marked  ad- 
vance in  the  art  of  historical  composition  and  the  power  of 
historical  reflection.  Throughout  the  whole  of  the  Japanese 
feudal  period,  however,  as  in  the  European  feudal  period,  al- 
though there  were  numerous  chroniclers  there  were  very  few 
historians  in  the  stricter  sense  of  the  term.  Near  its  close 
there  appeared  a  vast  and  celebrated  historical  work,  the  Dai 
Nihonshi.  It  was  composed  by  the  Prince  of  Mito  (1622- 
1700),  aided  by  many  Japanese  and  Chinese  scholars.  It  cov- 
ered the  whole  ground  of  Japanese  history  down  to  1413.  The 
aim  of  the  prince  was  to  discredit  the  Shoguns  as  unrighteous 
usurpers,  and  to  exalt  the  Mikado  as  the  sole  source  of  legit- 
imate and  beneficent  authority ;  and  his  work  was  so  skilfully 
adapted  to  its  end,  and  produced  so  powerful  an  effect,  that 
he  may  be  regarded,  as  Mr.  Satow  has  said,  "as  the  real  author 
of  the  movement  which  culminated  in  the  revolution- of  1868." 
The  first  Japanese  author  who  attempted  to  raise  history  to 
the  rank  of  a  science,  or  to  form  a  philosophy  of  history,  was 
Arai  Hakuseki  (1657-1725).  He  is  regarded  by  his  country- 
men as  having  been  unsurpassed  by  any  thinker  of  their  nation 


OMENTAL   HISTOKlOGltAPHY  47 

in  originality,  comprehensiveness,  and  profundity ;  as  an  emi- 
nent scholar,  a  statesman  of  the  noblest  type,  and  a  creative 
genius  in  the  department  of  political  economy.  His  Tokushi 
Yorom  is,  says  Professor  Griffis,  "  a  most  valuable  philosoph- 
ical view  of  the  different  changes  which  have  taken  place  at 
various  times  in  the  distribution  of  the  governing  power  in 
Japan."  The  greatest  Japanese  historian,  however,  would 
appear  to  have  been  liai  Sanjo  (1780-1833).  He  is  acknowl- 
edged to  have  been  careful  and  critical  in  research,  and  of 
penetrating  insight  in  the  interpretation  of  eve'nts.  It  is 
impossible  to  read  even  the  extracts  which  have  been  trans- 
lated from  his  works  without  being  impressed  by  his  power 
of  graphic  and  dramatic  presentation.  He  was  obviously  a 
man  of  rare  genius.  It  is  interesting  to  observe  that,  although 
writing  in  the  present  century,  he,  like  Thucydides  and  Livy, 
puts  speeches  of  his  own  composing  into  the  mouths  of  the 
personages  brought  before  us  in  his  works. 

Modern  Japan  can  boast  of  a  truly  native  school  of  histori-' 
cal  criticism.  The  most  remarkable  treatises  which  have  pro- 
ceeded from  it  are  those  of  Motoori  Norinaga  (1730-1801), 
and  of  Hirata  Atsutane  (1776-1843),  relating  to  the  ancient 
national  chronicles.  Of  that  of  Motoori,  an  account  has  been 
given  by  Professor  Severini ;  but  notwithstanding  its  intrinsic 
interest,  it  would  be  irrelevant  to  treat  here  of  a  work  first  pub- 
lished during  the  last  century.  A  conspicuous  peculiarity  of 
Japanese  literature  is  the  multitude  of  its  historical  romances, 
many  of  them  dating  from  the  tenth  and  eleventh  centuries.1 

India  presents  us  with  a  far  richer  and  finer  literary  devel- 
opment than  any  of  the  nations  already  mentioned,  — its  poetry 
and  philosophy,  in  particular,  being  exceedingly  remarkable. 
But  the  unparalleled  mixture  of  races  contained  from  a  remote 
antiquity  within  it,  the  utter  want  of  any  extensive  political 
unity,  the  genius  and  character  of  its  leading  people,  and  their 

1  Any  opinion  which  I  have  been  able  to  form  of  Japanese  historical  writings 
rests,  of  course,  on  translations,  such  as  we  owe  to  Kosny,  Mitford,  Satow,  Aston, 
Chamberlain,  Valenziani,  Severini,  and  other  experts.  The  only  general  printed 
view  of  Japanese  historiography  with  which  I  am  acquainted  is  that  contained  in 
the  very  instructive  article  of  Professor  Grirfis  on  Japan  (Language  and  Literature 
of)  in  the  '  American  Cyclopaedia,'  vol.  ix. ;  but  I  have  had  a  fuller  list  of  the  his- 
torians, with  notes  as  to  their  characteristics,  kindly  furnished  me  by  a  Japanese 
friend,  Mr.  Korehiro  Kurahara. 


48  INTRODUCTION 

external  and  social  conditions,  were  all  unfavourable  to  the 
rise  of  historical  composition  ;  and  the  Hindus  have  no  ancient 
native  histories.  They  have  known  how  to  give  true  and  full 
expression  to  the  innermost  workings  of  their  minds,  and  have 
faithfully  delineated  all  the  features  of  their  character,  in  the 
Vedas,  the  Code  of  Manu,  the  Puranas,  the  Sutras  of  their 
philosophers,  and  especially  in  their  two  great  national  epics. 
But  they  have  neglected  and  despised  the  events  of  their  outer 
and  social  life,  and  allowed  the  memory  of  them  to  be  to  all 
appearance  hopelessly  lost.  Nothing  seems  less  promising 
than  the  attempt  to  separate  historical  fact  from  poetical  fic- 
tion, either  according  to  Lassen's  ingenious  process  of  symbol- 
ism and  interpretation,  or  Wheeler's  naively  simple  process  of 
selection  and  reduction.  Notwithstanding  the  extraordinary 
clearness  and  subtilty  displayed  by  the  Hindu  intellect  on 
some  subjects  —  e.g.,  grammar — it  scarcely  succeeded  in  distin- 
^  guishing  history  from  epic  poetry.  The  oldest  Hindu  compo- 
sitions which  can  by  any  possibility  be  classed  as  historical, 
date  only  from  the  eleventh  century  of  our  era,  and  are  of  a 
merely  ^wasi-historical  character.  The  best  known  of  them 
—  the  one  translated  by  I.  Chunder  Dutt,  under  the  title  of 
'  Kings  of  Kashmfra '  — is  more  poetical  and  fabulous  than  his- 
torical. Of  greater  historical  value,  perhaps,  are  some  family 
chronicles,  and  especially  Bilhana's  '  Vikra-mankadevacarita,' 
belonging  to  the  eleventh  century,  and  recently  discovered  and 
edited  by  Biihler.  But  the  native  historical  literature  of  India 
is  sparse  and  poor  in  the  extreme.  It  was  impossible  for  a  peo- 
ple so  ignorant  of  history  to  have  any  true  philosophy  of  history. 
/  Israel  had  a  unique  history  which  has  been  recorded  in  a 
juniqiie  manner.  The  historical  books  of  the  Old  Testament, 
and  their  constituent  portions,  vary  in  their  characteristics  and 
qualities,  but  they  form  a  whole,  and  as  such  they  are  incom- 
parably superior  to  those  of  any  other  Asiatic  people.  Those 
of  them  which  relate  to  the  primeval  history  of  man  and  to  the 
origins  of  the  Hebrew  nation  are  now  generally  held  by  the 
scholars,  whose  opinions  are  based  entirely  on  critical  and 
evidential  considerations,  to  have  been  elaborated  into  their 
present  shape  after  the  prophets  had  taught,  so  that  their 
exhibition  of  the  history  is  also  an  ideal  construction  of  it,  in 


ORIENTAL  HISTORIOGRAPHY  49 

accordance  with  the  principles  which  the  prophets  had  promul- 
gated, but  which  it  was  left  to  the  priests  and  scribes  to  apply. 
This  view  of  their  formation  —  of  which  Reuss  and  Kuenen, 
Wellhausen  and  Stade,  have  been  among  the  most  promi- 
nent advocates  —  does  not  deprive  them  of  any  of  those  rare 
merits,  either  of  contents  or  form,  for  which  they  justly  claim 
our  admiration.  The  unity,  consistency,  naturalness,  moral 
elevation,  and  spiritual  instructiveness  of  the  presentation  of 
histoiy  given  in  the  ancient  Hebrew  literature,  are  facts  which 
cannot  be  denied,  however  they  may  have  been  attained.  It 
reflected  with  wonderful  faithfulness  and  completeness  the 
theocratic  life  of  Israel,  of  which  it  was  an  outcome.  It  was 
pervaded  by  a  profound  sense  of  a  supernatural  presence,  and 
of  an  eternal  law  making  for  righteousness.  All  events  were 
exhibited  in  it  from  the  religious  point  of  view,  God  being 
set  forth  as  the  supreme  factor  of  history,  His  will  as  the 
standard  of  historical  judgment,  and  His  kingdom  as  the  goal 
of  historical  development.  Yet  human  nature  is  also  skilfully 
and  truthfully  delineated,  in  a  style  almost  always  simple  and 
natural,  often  vivid  and  strong,  and  at  times  pathetic  and 
sublime.  Characters  and  situations  the  most  varied  are  strik- 
ingly described.  Man  appears  nowhere  more  man  than  where 
God  is  represented  as  miraculously  at  his  side. 

History  has  been  denned  as  the  biography  of  nations,  but 
the  Jewish  histories  so  delineate  the  various  stages  and  for-/ 
tunes  through  which  "  the  peculiar  people  "  passed,  from  its\ 
origin  onwards,  that  they  read  like  the  successive  chapters  of 
an  autobiography.  The  feeling  of  their  own  national  signifi- 
cance, which  the  Jews  possessed  in  so  singular  a  degree,  and 
which  they  so  carefully  cherished,  was  grounded  in  their  view 
of  history,  which  had  consequently  the  most  vital  interest  for 
them.  Probably  no  people  has  ever  been  more  thoroughly- 
conscious  of  being  rooted  in,  and  of  growing  out  of,  a  mar- 
vellous past.  And  this  historical  self-consciousness  was  ac- 
companied with  a  sense  of  relationship  to  other  peoples  such 
as  had  not  been  previously  displayed.  The  national  exclu- 
siveness  of  the  Jews,  as  compared  with  European  peoples, 
either  ancient  or  modern,  is  an  undoubted  fact ;  but  it  should 
not  conceal  this  other  fact,  that  it  is  among  them  that  the 


50  INTRODUCTION 

conviction  of  the  unity  of  the  race,  of  the  filiation  of  all  the 
peoples  of  the  world,  and  of  a  common  and  hopeful  final 
destiny,  are  first  found  prevailing ;  and  that  among  them,  on 
the  basis  of  these  convictions,  history  first  rises  from  being 
particular  to  being  universal.  We  have,  it  is  true,  the  history 
of  the  Jews,  as  of  a  nation  under  a  special  discipline  and  with 
a  special  mission,  minutely  narrated,  but  it  is  exhibited  as 
only  an  offshoot  of  the  history  of  humanity ;  and  if  the  Jews 
thought  the  twig  greater  than  the  tree,  or  if  Christian  writers 
have  spoken  as  if  they  also  thought  so,  the  original  historians 
are  not  to  blame. 

History  as  it  is  in  the  Bible,  however,  is  not  mere  history, 
but  much  more  than  history.  It  exists  not  for  its  own  sake, 
but  for  the  sake  of  something  higher,  of  which  it  is  repre- 
sented as  merely  the  medium  and  manifestation.  It  may  thus 
be  said  to  be  as  history,  a  stage  of  transition  from  lower  to 
higher,  which  in  no  degree  interrupts  the  progress  or  violates 
the  order  of  development  in  this  kind  of  composition.  It 
contained  what  was  far  more  precious  than  anything  Greece 
possessed ;  and  yet,  looked  at  from  another  side,  it  fell  short 
of,  and  only  led  up  to,  history  as  we  find  it  among  the  Greeks, 
who  in  this,  as  in  so  many  other  provinces  of  intellectual  ac- 
tivity, asserted  an  unmistakable  pre-eminence,  an  unparalleled 
originality. 

On  the  classic  soil  of  ancient  Hellas  history  first  attained 
the  dignity  of  an  independent  art,  first  was  cultivated  for  its 
own  sake.  It  is  what  the  Lord  said,  and  the  Lord  did,  that  the 
Scripture  history  chiefly  aims  to  exhibit,  —  it  is  His  guidance 
of  a  particular  nation  in  an  essentially  special  way  that  is  its 
subject,  —  whereas  the  historians  of  Greece  set  before  them- 
selves for  end  simply  the  satisfaction  of  man's  curiosity  as  to 
the  actions  of  his  fellow-men.  "  These  are  the  researches  of 
Herodotus  of  Halicarnassus  which  he  publishes,  in  order  to 
preserve  from  decay  the  remembrance  of  what  men  have  done, 
and  to  prevent  the  great  and  marvellous  actions  of  the  Greeks 
and  barbarians  losing  their  due  meed  of  glory,  as  well  as  to 
state  the  causes  of  their  hostility."  "  Thucydides  of  Athens 
wrote  the  history  of  the  war  between  the  Athenians  and 
Peloponnesians  while  it  was  going  on,  having  begun  to  write 


HISTORY   AMONG   THE   GREEKS  51 

from  its  commencement  in  the  belief  that  it  would  turn  out 
great,  and  worthier  of  being  recorded  than  any  which  had 
preceded  it."  The  oriental  world  had  no  histories  written 
from  these  simple  natural  motives,  which  are,  however,  those 
distinctively  appropriate  to  the  historical  art.  That  art,  there- 
fore, as  its  own  true  self,  as  a  free  and  separate  form  of  litera- 
ture, and  not  the  mere  appendage  or  offshoot  of  something 
else,  first  grew  out  of  the  soil  of  Greek  culture,  and  after  a 
period  of  barrenness  and  dryness,  blossomed  and  ripened  into 
the  immortal  works  of  Herodotus  and  Thucydides.  There  it 
attained  a  perfection  of  form  which  has  perhaps  never  since 
been  surpassed.  Herodotus,  with  all  his  credulity  and  want 
of  criticism,  is,  through  the  wonderful  fulness  and  perennial 
freshness  of  his  information,  through  his  transparent  candour 
and  simplicity  of  spirit,  his  ease  of  narration,  vividness  of 
portraiture,  pathos  and  humour,  the  very  type  and  model  of 
one  great  class  of  historians ;  and  Thucydides,  by  his  accuracy 
of  investigation,  intense  realisation  and  austerely  graphic  rep- 
resentation of  events,  and  especially  by  his  deep  insight  into 
the  working  of  political  causes  and  social  forces,  is  almost  the 
ideal  and  exemplar  of  another. 

The  remarkable  many-sidedness  which  characterised  the 
Greek  genius,  and  showed  itself  at  the  very  origin  of  Greek 
literature  in  Homer  in  a  form  which  could  not  again  be  sur- 
passed, revealed  itself  in  the  historical  sphere  also,  worthily 
repeating  itself  in  Herodotus  to  gratify  the  curiosity  of  the 
most  inquisitive  and  philosophical  of  nations.  He  was  without 
any  abstract  notion  of  humanity,  or  any  term  to  express  it, 
but  nothing  human  was  alien  or  uninteresting  to  him.  He 
gave  due  honour  and  justice  to  barbarians  as  well  as  Greeks, 
and  described  with  sympathetic  zest  and  care  all  the  aspects 
and  manifestations  of  human  life, — the  natural  surroundings, 
the  cities,  the  monuments,  the  religions,  the  customs,  the  laws, 
the  revolutions  of  the  governments  and  royal  dynasties,  the 
wars,  exploits,  and  fortunes  of  men  of  all  varieties  of  race 
and  culture.  With  the  genius  of  a  great  artist  he  grouped 
round  a  central  idea  —  the  struggle  between  Asiatics  and 
Greeks  —  a  vast  mass  of  the  most  diverse  materials,  and  com- 
posed a  grand  and  symmetrical  whole.   The  historical  picture 


52  INTRODUCTION 

we  owe  to  him  is  large  and  attractive,  crowded,  yet  not  con- 
fused, impressive  as  a  whole,  and  lifelike  and  interesting  in 
every  part.  The  comprehensiveness  of  research,  the  com- 
bined ingenuity  and  naturalness  of  arrangement,  the  merits 
and  charm  of  style,  and  the  general  originality  of  conception 
and  execution,  displayed  by  Herodotus,  well  entitled  him  to 
be  called  "the  father  of  history."  His  chief  defects  were  that 
he  deemed  a  great  deal  to  be  true,  for  the  truth  of  which  he 
had  not  sufficient  evidence ;  that  his  ability  to  explain  events 
was  small  in  comparison  with  his  power  of  describing  them ; 
and  that  he  lacked  insight  into  the  working  of  general  causes, 
and  especially  of  political  forces.  The  most  general  point  of 
view  from  which  he  contemplated  history  was  religious,  not 
political.  His  faith  in  a  divine  Providence  had  not  been  un- 
dermined by  speculative  thought.     It  was  essentially  that  of 

i  Pindar,  iEschylus,  and  Sophocles.  So  he  saw  in  history  Deity 
as  the  chief  agent,  and  moral  retribution  as  the  chief  law. 
The  god,  according  to  Herodotus,  assigns  to  all  things  their 
order — to  empires  their  duration,  to  crimes  due  punishment; 
is  inexorably  severe  towards  impiety  and  perjury,  and  fails 
not  to  disappoint  rash  haste  or  to  prosper  self-restraint;  is 
just,  yea  jealous,  cutting  down  all  towering  things,  and  suf- 
fering none  but  himself  to  be  proud ;  and  intervenes  even 
supernaturally  in  human  affairs  through  oracles,  signs,  and 
prodigies.     Such  was,  in  substance,  his  historical  creed. 

-"  Tfrucydides  was  a  contemporary  of  Herodotus,  and  only  a 
few  years  younger.  Yet  his  work  when  compared  with  that  of 
Herodotus  seems  as  if  it  belonged  to  an  altogether  different 
and  much  later  age.  This  was  doubtless  chiefly  due  to  the  fact 
that,  while  Herodotus  was  a  Greek  of  Asia  Minor,  Thucydides 
was  an  Athenian,  when  the  growth  of  intellectual  life  in 
Athens  was  amazingly  rapid.  A  decade  at  Athens  in  the  age 
of  Pericles  was  equivalent  in  the  history  of  thought  to  a  veiy 
lengthened  stretch  of  ordinary  time  anywhere  else.  Thucy- 
dides had  felt  the  full  power  of  the  critical  and  sceptical  spirit 
there  and  then  prevalent.  To  represent -him  as  atheistical  or 
irreligious  is  unwarranted.  But  it  is  plain  that  he  had  re- 
solved not  to  allow  any  religious  faith  he  may  have  retained, 
to  colour  his  historical  vision,  or  influence  his  historical  judg- 


HISTORY   AMONG   THE   GREEKS  53 

ments.  He  wished  to  write  only  authentic,  strictly  true  his- 
tory. Hence  he  chose  a  limited  and  well-defined  field  of  study  , 
which  could  be  thoroughly  explored,  and  where  truth  could  ; 
be  attained  with  certainty.  He  took  as  his  subject  the  Pelo- 
ponnesian  war,  which  began  in  431  B.C.,  and  he  watched  and 
described  it  as  it  went  on  down  to  the  battle  of  CynossSma  in 
411.  He  rigidly  excluded  from  his  narrative  whatever  did 
not  bear  directly  on  its  theme  —  the  struggle  between  Athens 
and  her  allies  on  the  one  side,  and  Sparta  and  her  allies  on 
the  other ;  unlike  Herodotus,  who  drew  into  his  whatever  he 
thought  would  enhance  its  popular  interest.  As  an  impar- 
tial, independent,  critical  investigator,  he  stands  immeasurably 
above  all  preceding  historians,  and  probably  beneath  no  suc- 
ceeding one.  But  it  was  not  merely  as  a  narrator  that  he  ex- 
celled. He  was  equally  remarkable  for  the  clearness  and  depth 
of  his  insight  into  the  grounds  of  the  events  he  described.  He 
did  not  reason  about  occurrences,  but  he  so  exhibited  them 
as  convincingly  to  disclose  their  causation  and  development. 
The  only  immediate  agents,  of  course,  to  be  seen  in  the  Pelo- 
ponnesian  war,  were  the  States  engaged  and  the  men  who 
composed  them.  Thucydides  confined  himself  to  showing  why, 
in  the  circumstances  in  which  they  were  placed,  these  States 
and  men  acted  as  they  did.  He  could  be  sure  of  the  opera- 
tion of  these  causes — essential  human  motives  and  general 
political  interests  ;  and  he  carefully  exhibited  their  operation. 
At  the  same  time  he  saw  that  they  did  not  explain  everything ; 
that  history  was  not  wholly  self -explaining,  but  that  there  was 
in  it  more  or  less  of  contingency,  fortune,  fate  —  of  what  he 
called  Tv-ftr).  Beyond  this  he  did  not  think  he  was  entitled  as 
an  historian  to  go.  And  so  he  had  nothing  to  say  of  the  gods, 
or  of  their  intervention.  Too  much  may  easily  be  expected 
from  Thucydides.  He  sought  only  to  write  political  history, 
and  therefore  we  have  no  right  to  look  for  religious  reflections 
from  him,  or  even  for  information  as  to  how  the  intellectual, 
social,  and  spiritual  life  of  Greece  was  affected  by  the  Pelo- 
ponnesian  war.  Nor  did  he  undertake  to  write  a  history  of 
the  general  politics  of  the  period,  but  only  of  its  external  poli- 
tics as  involved  in  the  war ;  and  therefore,  instead  of  attempt 
ing  to  give  as  much  information  as  he  could  regarding  the 


54  INTRODUCTION 

internal  politics  of  the  belligerent  States,  he  gave  only  as 
much  as  was  necessary  to  explain  their  conduct  in  relation  to 
one  another.  So  of  the  chief  individual  actors  in  the  war,  he 
deemed  it  no  part  of  his  task  to  characterise  them  in  their  pri- 
vate capacities,  and  hence  his  delineations  of  them  are  apt  to 
seem  shadowy  and  defective,  although  they  are  substantial  as 
far  as  they  go  and  sufficient  for  their  purpose.  He  would  never 
have  been  the  almost  perfect  historian  he  was  if  he  had  not 
shunned  as  he  did  the  too  much  alike  in  matter  and  style.  It 
must  be  allowed  that  he  fell  into  error,  and  set  a  bad  example, 
when  he  attributed  to  persons  speeches  which  were  wholly  or 
largely  composed  by  himself.  Yet  these  speeches  are  not  only 
admirable  as  speeches,  but  also  as  means  of  conveying  ideas  of 
the  utmost  importance  for  the  understanding  of  the  history. 
They  hold  a  place  in  the  work  of  Thucydides  not  unlike  that 
of  the  songs  of  the  chorus  in  a  tragedy  of  iEschylus  or  Soph- 
ocles. They  gradually  disclose  the  latent  significance  of  the 
history,  and  the  views  and  motives  of  the  various  parties  en- 
gaged in  it.  They  save  the  author  from  the  necessity  and  risks 
of  theorising  in  his  own  name  on  the  course  of  events,  while 
yet  most  effectively  and  artistically  setting  forth  the  conclu- 
sions at  which  he  had  arrived.  At  the  same  time  they  are  not 
unjust  to  those  to  whom  they  are  assigned,  but  such  as  might 
most  appropriately  have  been  spoken  by  them.  Thucydides 
was  the  first  scientific  historian.  But  he  was  also  a  great  his- 
torical artist.  His  judicial  impartiality  and  calm  passionless 
objectivity  of  judgment  sprang  not  from  insensibility  but  from 
conscientiousness  and  self-restraint.  In  reading  his  pages  we 
perceive  that  he  felt  as  strongly  as  he  conceived  clearly.  The 
tone  of  austere  melancholy  which  pervades  his  work  corre- 
sponds perfectly  to  the  tragic  nature  of  the  story  which  is  its 
subject ;  and  we  are  made  to  realise  all  the  misery  and  pathos 
of  that  story.  His  style  has  nothing  of  the  ease,  flow,  and 
sweetness  of  that  of  Herodotus  ;  but  it  is  of  rare  strength  and 
conciseness,  moves  on  rapidly  and  directly  without  a  useless 
word  or  phrase,  varies  as  the  occasion  requires,  and  rises  at 
times  to  the  loftiest  heights.  "  It  has,"  to  use  the  words  of 
Professor  Jebb,  "  many  faults.  It  is  often  involved,  abrupt, 
obscure.     But  no  writer  has  grander  bursts  of  rugged  elo- 


HISTORY   AMONG   THE   GREEKS  bit 

quence,  or  more  of  that  greatness  which  is  given  by  sustained 
intensity  of  noble  thought  and  feeling." 

Thucydides  left  his  history  unfinished,  and  Xenophon 
attempted  to  complete  it.  But  his  continuation,  the '  Hellenica,' 
is  altogether  deficient  in  the  great  qualities  which  character- 
ise the  work  of  Thucydides.  It  is  dry,  ill  arranged,  super- 
ficial, prejudiced,  and  even  feeble  and  unattractive  in  style. 
The  fame  of  Xenophon  as  an  historian  must  rest  on  his 
'  Anabasis,'  and  there  it  may  rest  securely.  No  military  inci- 
dent has  ever  been  told  with  more  exquisite  simplicity  and 
fascinating  art  than  the  Retreat  of  the  Ten  Thousand. 

It  was  natural  that  it  should  be  a  Greek  who  first  tried  to 
realise  the  idea  of  a  universal  history.  Nevertheless,  it  could 
not  be  even  the  most  comprehensive-minded  Greek  of  the  age 
of  Herodotus  or  Thucydides  when  there  was  no  visible  unity 
of  any  kind  in  the  world,  but  one  who  had  the  spectacle  of  Rome 
before  his  eyes,  and  who  had  studied  her  steady  march  towards 
universal  empire,  as  far  at  least  as  the  period  when  "  the  affairs 
of  Italy  and  Africa  conjoined  with  those  of  Asia  and  Greece, 
and  all  moved  together  towards  one  fixed  and  single  point," 
Polybius,  who  spent  a  portion  of  his  life  at  Rome,  who  studied 
her  history  closely,  and  saw  clearly  that  her  success  was  no- 
accident,  but  the  natural  results  of  general  causes  —  her  unity, 
institutions,  and  character  —  who  beheld  her  triumph  over 
Carthage  and  Macedonia,  and  was  fully  conscious  that  his  own 
divided  and  demoralised  land  could  offer  her  no  resistance  — 
was  a  Greek  so  placed,  and  he  was  the  first  to  attempt  a 
universal  history.  He  did  so  with  the  distinctest  perception 
of  its  advantages  over  particular  histories,  which  he  tells  us 
"  can  no  more  convey  a  perfect  view  and  knowledge  of  the 
whole  than  a  survey  of  the  divided  members  of  a  body  once 
endued  with  life  and  beauty  can  yield  a  just  conception  of  all 
the  comeliness  and  vigour  which  it  has  received  from  nature." 
A  chief  object  with  him,  therefore,  was  to  show  by  what  stages 
and  in  what  ways  each  nation  had  reached  its  last  estate.  He 
assumed  that  the  real  had  been  the  rational,  and  that  Rome 
had  become  the  mistress  of  the  world  for  the  world's  good. 
Being  the  power  best  fitted  to  rule  over  the  nations,  Rome  had 
obtained  that  rule.    She  was  "  the  noblest  and  most  beneficent 


56  INTRODUCTION 

work  of  Fortune,"  but  of  a  Fortune  neither  blind  nor  unjust. 
Polybius  was  not  a  servile  flatterer  of  Rome,  but  his  whole 
view  of  history  necessarily  rendered  him  an  apologist  of  accom- 
plished facts,  and  of  Roman  success.  He  was  like  Thucydides 
in  that  he  endeavoured  to  exhibit  the  causes  of  events ;  but 
unlike  him  in  that  he  was  not  content  to  do  this  in  a  purely 
historical  manner,  but  reasoned  on  them  in  his  own  name,  and 
introduced  into  the  history  his  personal  impressions  and  reflec- 
tions. For  Polybius,  as  for  Thucydides,  the  motive  forces  of 
human  nature  were  the  great  factors  of  history.  He  disbe- 
lieved divine  interventions  in  history,  and  regarded  the  pop- 
ular religion  as  only  a  superstition  useful  to  awe  and  frighten 
the  multitude.  Thucydides  wrote  in  order  that  by  giving  an 
accurate  knowledge  of  the  past  he  might  supply  his  readers 
with  a  clue  to  that  future  which,  in  all  human  probability, 
will  repeat  or  resemble  the  past.  Polybius  himself  drew  from 
the  facts  he  narrated  such  lessons  as  he  deemed  would  be  of 
service  to  politicians.  As  his  work  thus  combined  practical 
political  teaching  with  an  exhibition  of  events  as  causes  and 
effects,  and  so  was  a  course  of  political  instruction  conveyed 
and  exemplified  through  a  record  of  actions,  he  called  it  a 
■n-payfiarela ;  and  he  is  often  described  as  the  originator  of 
pragmatic  historiography.  By  his  reflections  on  the  causes  of 
the  growth  of  the  power  of  Rome,  he  opened  up  a  path  after- 
wards followed  by  Macchiavelli,  Bossuet,  and  Montesquieu. 
He  was  perfectly  aware  of  the  necessity  of  attending  especially 
to  general  causes,  and  was  probably  the  first  to  make  a  serious 
study  of  the  spirit  and  history  of  the  Roman  constitution. 
That  he  fell  into  errors  on  the  subject  was  inevitable.  It  may, 
however,  be  doubted  if  any  later  writer  of  the  ancient  world 
treated  it  with  deeper  insight,  or  with  more  accurate  knowl- 
edge. 

The  idea  of  a  universal  history  was,  as  we  have  seen,  the 
reflection  and  result  of  the  universal  empire  of  Rome,  which 
made  the  known  world  externally  one,  a  single  great  political 
whole.  Rome  made  the  world  Roman  and  became  herself 
cosmopolitan.  The  indebtedness  of  history  to  Rome  as  exem- 
plifying that  unity  of  a  universal  government,  without  which 
there  could  never  have  arisen  any  notion  of  a  universal  his- 


THE   ROMAN   HISTORIANS  57 

tory,  is  Incalculable.  The  world  came  to  know  external  unity 
only  in  and  through  Rome.  The  universal  empire  of  pagan 
Rome  was  the  condition  and  foundation  of  the  universal  em- 
pire of  Catholic  Rome,  and  of  such  unity  as  Christendom  has 
retained  since  the  unity  of  Catholicism  was  broken.  After 
the  Macedonian  wars  no  extraordinary  genius  was  required  to 
discern  in  the  history  of  the  world  a  unity  centring  in  Rome. 
How  Polybius  saw  and  was  impressed  by  it  has  already  been 
indicated.  Among  Latin  writers  Cornelius  Nepos  was  the 
first  to  oompose  a  universal  history  —  omne  cevum  explicare. 
His  work  is  lost,  like  several  later  works  of  the  same  kind. 
None  of  the  general  histories  written  during  the  empire  were 
productions  of  much  merit.  No  Latin  author  showed  himself 
able  even  intelligently  to  continue  what  Polybius  had  begun. 
The  Roman  will  made  history  universal,  but  the  Roman  intel- 
lect was  deficient  in  the  qualities  requisite  for  treating  suc- 
cessfully of  universal  history.  It  was  not  in  this  department 
that  Roman  writers  acquired  fame  as  historians. 

The  pride  of  the  early  Romans  led  them  both  to  falsify  their 
own  history  and  to  take  some  measures  to  preserve  the  memory 
of  it.  Their  registers,  their  fasti  and  annals,  were  only  meagre 
and  unsatisfactory  materials  for  history.  As  an  art  history 
was  late  in  appearing  at  Rome.  The  rude  Roman  speech  was 
fashioned  with  difficulty  into  a  literary  instrument.  A  Roman 
literature  was  only  developed  under  Greek  influences.  The 
conquest  of  Greece  by  the  arms  of  Rome  was  followed  by  the 
conquest  of  Rome  by  the  mind  of  Greece  ;  and  in  Roman  lit- 
erature Grecian  and  Latin  qualities  were  inseparably  blended. 
The  first  Latin  work  entitled  to  be  called  a  history  would  seem 
to  have  been  the  '  Origines  '  of  Cato.  For  a  considerable  time 
Roman  historiography  was  uncritical  and  inartistic ;  and  it  was 
from  the  first  affected  by  a  vice  which  inhered  in  it  to  the  end 
—  namely,  a  tendency  to  subordinate  truth  to  what  was  sup- 
posed to  be  for  the  interest  of  the  State,  or  for  the  edification 
of  the  individual. 

Caesar  and  Sallust  were  the  first  Roman  writers  who  pro- 
duced works  displaying  historical  genius.  The  Commentaries 
of  Csesar  on  the  Gallic  and  Civil  Wars  are  not  only  invaluable 
for  the  information  which  they  contain,  but  are  composed  in 


58  INTRODUCTION 

a  style  perfect  in  its  kind  and  in  its  relation  to  the  subject. 
They  are  an  admirable  reflection  of  their  author's  mind,  —  one 
absolutely  clear  in  conception  and  observation,  completely 
master  of  itself  and  of  whatever  it  undertook  to  deal  with,  and 
which  moved  towards  the  end  it  aimed  at  in  the  most  direct, 
rapid,  and  decisive  manner.  But  they  are  simply  military 
narratives,  and  cannot  entitle  Caesar  to  a  place  in  the  highest 
rank  of  historians.  Of  historical  philosophy  of  any  kind,  or 
general  historical  ideas,  they  show  no  trace.  Caesar  was  far 
too  clear-sighted  to  state  what  was  false,  but  no  one  probably 
knew  better  how  to  make  silence  serve  his  purpose,  or  so  to 
present  his  facts  as  to  make  them  suggest  what  it  would 
hardly  have  become  him  to  have  said.  Handling  speech  with 
the  most  masterly  ease  and  naturalness  as  a  practically  use- 
ful instrument,  he  wisely  dispensed  with  literary  adornment 
and  elaboration. 

Hence  Sallust  may  justly  be  described  as  the  first  artistic 
historian  or  historical  artist  of  Rome.  His  Catilinarian  Con- 
spiracy and  Jugurthine  War  are  small  but  choice  and  care- 
fully finished  pieces,  in  which  their  author's  talents  alike  as 
historian  and  litterateur  are  seen  to  full  advantage.  In  the 
selection,  disposition,  and  general  treatment  of  his  subjects,  as 
also  in  his  style,  he  took  the  work  of  Thucydides  for  his  model. 
As  regards  the  highest  historical  qualities,  he  must  be  admitted 
to  have  fallen  much  beneath  his  great  exemplar.  Yet  few  who 
have  imitated  Thucydides  have  so  nearly  equalled  him  in  so 
many  respects,  while  surpassing  him  in  some.  He  had  neither 
the  originality  nor  the  greatness  of  Thucydides,  neither  his  con- 
scientiousness and  thoroughness  as  an  historical  investigator, 
nor  his  grasp  and  penetration  as  an  historical  thinker.  But  he 
had  remarkable  skill  in  combining  and  disposing  facts  into 
pictures,  in  drawing  characters  by  a  few  striking  traits,  and  in 
juxtaposing  and  contrasting  his  personages.  His  moral  reflec- 
tions may  be  irrelevant,  but  his  talent  for  moral  portraiture 
was  indubitable.  ,  He  had  a  power  of  psychological,  and  con- 
sequently of  moral,  analysis,  almost  equal  to  that  of  Tacitus, 
although  exercised  on  a  much  smaller  scale.  His  works  are 
from  their  own  merits  worthy  of  their  reputation ;  and  their 
relation  to  those  of  Thucydides  on  the  one  side,  and  to  those 


THE   KOMAN   HISTORIANS  59 

of  Tacitus  on  the  other,  give  them  a  special  interest  for  a 
student  of  the  development  of  historiography. 

But  it  was  neither  in  the  sphere  of  universal  nor  of  episo- 
dical history  that  the  Latin  historians  performed  their  most 
distinctive  work.  It  was  in  that  of  national  history.  The  men 
who  founded  Rome's  greatness,  who  won  for  her  by  endurance 
and  daring  the  empire  of  the  world,  were  not  men  of  broad 
but  of  narrow  ideas,  not  of  liberal  but  of  exclusive  feelings, 
men  animated  by  a  proud,  absorbing,  ruthless  patriotism.  It 
was  through  the  strength  of  their  national  feeling  that  the 
Romans  gained  the  universal  empire  in  which  they  lost  it ; 
and,  as  a  general  rule,  when  the  classical  scholar  thinks  of 
Roman  history  it  is  not  as  leading  to  even  an  imperfect  recog- 
nition of  human  brotherhood  —  to  a  sense  of  something  ge- 
neric in  man,  of  a  common  nature  in  virtue  of  which  all  men 
are  entitled  to  certain  legal  and  moral  rights  —  but  as  display- 
ing the  features  of  a  national  character  of  singular  strength 
and  interest.  And  certainly  in  that  respect  the  Roman  histo- 
rians have  a  very  special  claim  to  our  attention.  The  Greeks 
were  not  patriotic  in  the  same  sense  and  degree  as  the  Romans. 
And  Herodotus  and  Thucydides  are  not  national  historians 
in  the  same  sense  and  degree  as  Livy  and  Tacitus.  Indeed, 
Livy  and  Tacitus  might,  with  little  exaggeration,  be  described 
as  the  two  first  national  historians  on  a  large  and  prominent 
scale,  and  who,  it  may  be  added,  had  as  such  no  worthy 
successors  for  sixteen  hundred  years. 

Livy  narrated  the  events  of  Rome's  career  of  heroic  struggle 
and  achievement  with  the  colouring  and  in  the  tone  most 
adapted  to  inspire  the  youth  of  his  own  generation  with  rever- 
ence and  emulation  of  their  ancestors.  He  was  the  greatest 
prose  writer  of  his  age.  He  narrated  with  unfailing  vividness, 
sensibility,  and  charm,  and  could  picture  or  portray  with 
masterly  vigour  and  skill.  His  ethical  feeling  was  keen  and 
pure.  Patriotism  was  his  strongest  passion.  And  if  the  chief 
end  of  history  be,  as  he  obviously  supposed,  to  supply  examples 
and  stimuli  to  virtue  and  patriotism,  he  certainly  cannot  be 
accused  of  having  neglected  the  historian's  main  function. 
His  whole  work,  as  has  been  said,  was  "  a  triumphal  celebra- 
tion of  the  heroic  spirit  and  military  glory  of  Rome."     It  was 


60  INTRODUCTION 

natural  that  he  should  have  been  the  most  popular  of  the 
Roman  historians.  But  unfortunately  his  great  qualities 
were  combined  with  great  defects.  He  was  superficial  in 
research ;  easily  satisfied  in  regard  to  evidence ;  prone  to  take 
the  version  of  a  story  which  told  best ;  uncritical  in  the  choice 
and  use  of  authorities.  Dazzled  by  the  splendour  of  the  mili- 
tary history  of  Rome,  he  neglected  the  study  of  its  constitu- 
tional history.  He  lacked  political  insight.  He  lacked  still 
more  philosophical  comprehension.  Of  the  general  conditions 
and  causes  which  determined  the  course  of  Roman  history, 
and  of  any  law  or  plan  in  it,  he  had  no  glimpse.  He  was 
merely  an  annalist,  although  the  most  attractive  and  brilliant 
of  annalists.  Seneca  (Ep.  100)  tells  us  that  Livy  wrote  "  dia- 
logos,  quos  non  magis  philosophise  adnumerare  possis  quam 
historiae,  et  ex  professo  philosophiam  continentes  libros." 
Whatever  the  character  of  the  former  may  have  been,  we 
may  be  certain  that  the  subject  of  them  was  not,  as  Rouge- 
mont  has  supposed,  the  philosophy  of  history.  If  he  had  had 
any  conception  of  a  philosophy  of  history  he  could  not  have 
written  a  history  so  devoid  of  philosophy. 

Tacitus  was  very  unlike  Livy  in  almost  all  respects,  but  as 
an  historian  he  was  like  him  in  so  far  that  his  aim  too  was 
essentially  moral  and  patriotic.  The  darkness  without  was 
deeper,  however,  and  the  hope  within  less.  With  the  tragic 
pathos  of  a  despairing  patriot  and  the  righteous  indignation  of 
an  honest  man,  he  delineated  the  growth  of  social  corruption 
from  the  time  of  Tiberius  onwards,  in  order  to  deter  those  in 
whom  any  sense  of  moral  obligation  was  left  from  what  had  in- 
volved a  people  so  strong  and  virtuous,  so  glorious  and  free  as 
the  Roman,  in  such  misery  and  disgrace,  such  revolting  vice 
and  abject  slavery.  No  historian  has  given  so  large  a  place  to 
the  moral  element  in  history,  yet  without  ever  becoming  a  mere 
moralist  or  ceasing  to  be  an  historian.  No  one  has  shown  with 
the  same  power  and  vividness  what  moral  law  and  retribution, 
virtue  and  vice  and  their  concomitants  and  consequences,  are 
in  actual  historical  manifestation  and  evolution,  or  traced  with 
so  masterly  a  hand  the  connections  between  individual  char- 
acter and  the  character  of  public  rule.  His  strong  moral  feel- 
ings may  have  given  rise  in  certain  cases  to  harsh  judgments ; 


THE   ROMAN   HISTORIANS  61 

but  obviously  they  were,  in  general,  under  such  firm  control, 
that  this  must  be  deemed  only  a  possibility,  and  in  no  par- 
ticular instance  assumed  as  a  fact,  or  even  as  a  probability. 
From  what  he  knew  of  the  corruption  of  the  governing  classes 
of  Rome  he  may  have  drawn  inferences  as  to  the  corruption  of 
the  whole  social  body  which  are  not  to  be  accepted  without 
corroborative  evidence,  or  which  can  be  even  proved  exagger- 
ated ;  but  it  is  easy  to  attribute  to  Tacitus  errors  of  this  kind, 
which  are  really  only  mistakes  of  the  reader's  own,  consequent 
on  his  not  keeping  in  view  the  precise  limits  and  scope  of  the 
two  chief  works  of  Tacitus.  Notwithstanding  his  extraordi- 
nary intellectual  power,  Tacitus  attained  no  settled  convic- 
tions on  which  any  general  philosophy  of  history,  or  even  any 
general  conceptions  of  history,  could  be  rested.  He  had  obvi- 
ously no  confidence  either  in  any  metaphysical  or  religious 
theory  of  things.  His  moral  sense  often  breaks  down  his 
doubts,  and  impels  him  to  affirm  divine  intervention,  but  his 
reason  was  not  of  the  kind  which  carries  the  mind  above  what 
is  visible  and  concrete  or  positive.  He  confessed  himself  un- 
decided as  to  whether  human  affairs  are  governed  by  Provi- 
dence, or  fate  and  inevitable  necessity,  or  the  wild  rotation  of 
chance.  He  made  no  attempt  to  forecast  the  future  either  of 
humanity  or  of  the  empire.  Yet  he  is  justly  entitled  to  be 
regarded  as  a  scientific  or  philosophical  historian,  inasmuch 
as  he  traced  actions  back  to  their  motives,  events  to  then- 
causes,  and  penetrated  to  the  secret  springs  of  social  change. 
In  the  analysis  of  character  he  surpassed  all  the  historians  of 
antiquity.  Full  of  matter  as  his  narrative  is,  it  never  con- 
tains anything  trivial  or  superfluous.  His  style  fitly  exhibits 
the  force,  originality,  and  dignity  of  his  mind.  His  words 
are  singularly  pregnant  with  meaning,  and  few  of  them  could 
either  be  omitted  or  replaced  by  another  without  loss.  He  was 
unquestionably  far  the  most  eminent  of  the  Roman  historians. 

The  growth  of  Roman  historiography  had  been  slow;  its 
decay  was  rapid.  After  the  greatest  of  Roman  historians 
there  appeared  not  a  single  great  one.  Even  writers  like 
Suetonius  and  Florus  have  no  claim  to  a  place  in  this  sketch. 
We-  must  pass  onwards,  therefore,  into  the  Christian  world. 

The  political  unity  of  the  Roman  empire  contributed  both 


62  INTRODUCTION 

by  its  advantages  and  defects  to  prepare  the  mind  for  belief 
in  the  spiritual  unity  of  humanity  proclaimed  by  Christianity. 
The  Gospel  of  Christ,  with  its  new  views  of  God  and  of  man 
and  of  their  relationship  to  each  .other,  proved  to  be  the  germ 
of  a  new  world,  vaster  and  more  wonderful  than  that  ruled 
by  the  Cajsars.  It  did  not  preserve  the  Roman  empire  from 
dissolution,  or  arrest  the  decay  of  Roman  literature ;  it  failed 
to  inspire  a  strong  patriotism  or  to  produce  a  high  civic 
virtue ;  it  added  not  a  single  author  worthy  of  mention  to  the 
number  of  Roman  historians.  But  it  leavened  society,  created 
the  Church,  and  caused  religion  to  be  felt  as  one  of  the  most 
powerful  factors  of  history.  It  made  men  conscious,  as  they 
had  never  been  before,  that  they  were  spiritual  as  well  as 
political  beings,  and  even  more  spiritual  than  political  beings ; 
that  spiritual  life  was  the  most  important  form  of  life.  Sus- 
tained by  this  consciousness  the  Church  grew  stronger  as  the 
empire  grew  weaker,  and  remained,  when  the  political  unity 
of  Rome  was  shattered,  to  represent  and  uphold  religious 
unity,  — •  to  remind  separate  and  hostile  nations  that  they 
were  members  of  a  common  humanity  and  subject  to  the 
laws  of  a  divine  kingdom,  —  and,  it  must  be  added,  strenu- 
ously to  endeavour  to  make  the  kingdoms  of  the  earth  sub- 
missive to  its  own  will  and  subservient  to  its  own  interests. 

Christianity  by  creating  the  Church  enormously  enlarged 
and  enriched  history.  It  thereby  opened  up  a  central  and 
exhaustless  vein  in  the  mine  of  human  nature,  —  set  in  move- 
ment a  main  stream  in  the  flow  of  human  affairs.  The  rise 
of  ecclesiastical  history  was  more  to  historiography  than  was 
the  discovery  of  America  to  geography.  It  added  immensely 
to  the  contents  of  history,  and  radically  changed  men's  con- 
ceptions of  its'  nature.  It  at  once  caused  political  history  to 
be  seen  to  be  only  a  part  of  history,  and  carried  even  into  the 
popular  mind  the  conviction  —  of  which  hardly  a  trace  is  to 
be  found  in  the  classic  historians  —  that  all  history  must  move 
towards  some  general  human  end,  some  divine  goal. 

Ecclesiastical  historiography  was  first  cultivated  in  the 
Greek  Church.  The  author  of  the  Acts  of  the  Apostles  and 
Hegesippus  led  the  way.  Eusebius  (264-340)  gained  the  title 
of  Father  of  Church  History.     His  '  Ecclesiastical  History '  be- 


EARLY   CHRISTIAN   HISTORIANS  63 

gan  with  the  incarnation  of  Christ,  and  ended  with  the  triumph 
of  the  Church  by  the  help  and  favour  of  Constantine.  It  re- 
counted the  successions  of  the  apostles,  the  calamities  of  the 
Jews,  the  persecutions  and  martyrdoms  of  Christians,  the  ser- 
vices of  eminent  ecclesiastics,  the  heresies  and  controversies, 
and,  in  a  word,  the  chief  transactions  and  varying  conditions 
of  the  Church  during  the  first  324  years  of  its  existence.  The 
work  was  well  conceived,  judiciously  planned,  and  laboriously 
executed.  Although  largely  annalistic  and  often  loosely  con- 
structed, it  forms  on  the  whole  a  unity.  Its  materials  are  of 
themselves  sufficient  to  give  it  a  priceless  value.  They  are 
drawn  almost  entirely  from  Greek  sources,  and  so  the  work 
conveys  little  information  as  to  the  Latin  Churches.  Euse- 
bius  was  not  a  great  writer,  and  to  call  him,  as  has  often  been 
done,  "  the  Christian  Herodotus,"  is  more  apt  to  suggest  his 
inferiority  than  likeness  to  the  heathen  one.  He  was  as 
devoid  of  the  incomparable  art  of  the  son  of  Lgrxes,  as  of  his 
simplicity  and  richness  of  nature.  He  lived  in  a  time  when 
life  was  artificial  and  diseased,  and  although  he  had  many 
good  qualities,  intellectual  and  moral,  he  belonged  too  truly 
to  his  time.  He  was  a  courtier  bishop,  wanting  in  strength 
and  reality  of  character,  in  singleness  of  heart,  vision,  and 
speech.  He  was  honest,  but  not  impartial.  He  loved  religion 
better  than  truth,  and  conceived  of  religion  in  a  worldly  way. 
It  is  easy  to  explain  and  even  to  excuse  his  faults ;  it  is  a 
duty  gratefully  to  acknowledge  his  services  to  the  cause  of 
Christian  learning ;  but  it  is  difficult  to  respect  and  impossi- 
ble to  admire  him.  The  defects  of  his  character  have  left 
deep  traces  in  his  historical  works.  It  is  unnecessary  here  to 
notice  his  '  Life  of  Constantine.'  But  his  '  Chronicle,'  based 
on  a  chronological  labour  of  Julius  AfricanusV  undoubtedly 
deserves  mention.  It  consists  of  an  epitome  of  universal  his- 
tory, followed  by  chronological  tables  which  exhibit  in  parallel 
columns  the  successions  of  the  rulers  of  different  nations, 
accompanied  with  indications  of  the  years  of  the  more  remark- 
able events.  It  was  thus  the  expression  of  the  conception  of 
history  implied  in  the  claim  of  Christianity  to  be  the  end  of 
all  past  ages  of  divine  revelation,  and  of  human  search  and 
desire.     The  position  accorded  by  the  Christian  Church  to  the 


64  INTRODUCTION 

historical  books  of  the  Old  Testament  of  necessity  profoundly 
affected  the  mode  of  viewing  history.     It  caused  what  had 
been  deemed  general  history  by  the  classical  historians  to  be 
considered  only  a  kind  of  partial  or  particularist  history,  and 
the  history  of  the  human  race  as  a  whole  to  be  the  only  truly 
general  history.    The  Christian  historian  or  annalist  felt  bound 
to  look  back  to  the  creation,  to  trace  the  special  histories  of 
the  different  nations  as  divisions  of  one  comprehensive  history, 
and,  by  the  help  of  a  chronology,  derived  chiefly  from  Biblical 
data,  to  determine  how  the  special  histories  synchronised.    In 
this  there  was  manifest  gain  to  historiography.     The  underly- 
ing thought  was  the  great  one  that  the  history  of  man  was  a, 
divinely  ordered  system,  beginning  with  Adam,  centring  in 
Christ,  and  closing  in  a  day  of  judgment.     The  result  was  an 
immediate  and  decisive  transcendence  of  the  particularism  in 
the  treatment  of  history  characteristic  of  the  classical  authors. 
But  there  was  loss  as  well  as  gain.     The  Hebrew  historians 
were  regarded  as  above  criticism.     A  chronology   deduced 
from  texts  deemed  inspired  and  infallible  was  arbitrarily  im- 
posed on  the  histories  of  the  heathen  nations.     A  false  per- 
suasion of  knowledge  as  to  primeval  times  was  engendered.    A 
view  of  universal  history  was  formed,  specious  enough  to  gain 
unquestioning  acceptance  until  a  recent  period,  but  unable  to 
satisfy  the  demands  of  strict  criticism  and  inconsistent  with  the 
results  which  research  has  at  length  attained.     The  Chronol- 
ogy of  Eusebius  was  soon  translated  into  Latin  and  Armenian, 
and  often  both  abridged  and  continued.     It  was  the  basis  of  all 
the  chronological  work  undertaken  in  medieval  Christendom. 
Eusebius  had  several "  continuators  "  in  the  Eastern  Church 
— e.g.,  Theodoret,  Socrates,  and  Sozomen  in  the  fifth  century, 
and  Theodorus  and  Evagrius  in  the  sixth.     Those  named  all 
showed  care  and  diligence  in  the  collection  of  information 
and  considerable  general  sobriety  and  vigour  of  intellect,  but 
also  a  credulous  faith  in  divine  interpositions.     After  the 
sixth  century  the  Greek  Church  ceased  to  be  productive  in 
historiography,  or  in  any  other  department  of  knowledge. 
#  Rufinus  and  Jerome  made  the  historical  works  of  Eusebius 
known  to  the  Latin  Church.     Augustine,  in  his  '  De  Civitate 
Dei,'  attempted,  with  all  the  energy  and  resources  of  his  mag- 


EARLY   CHRISTIAN   HISTORIANS  65 

nificent  genius,  to  explain  the  facts  and  secrets  of  history  by 
the  principles  of  Christian  theology,  and  expounded  a  theory 
of  the  destinies  of  the  human  race  which  served  many  gen- 
erations as  their  only  philosophy  of  history.  What  may  be 
called  in  a  lax  and  general  way  the  Augustinian  philosophy 
of  history  was  substantially  the  only  one  known  in  medieval 
Europe ;  and  it  has  reappeared  in  modern  times  with  more 
or  less  important  modifications  under  the  hands  of  Bossuet, 
Schlegel,  and  many  others.  As  it  will  be  specially  treated 
of  in  the  last  section  of  our  Introduction,  this  mere  reference 
to  it  must  here  suffice. 

The  Spanish  presbyter,  Paulus  Orosius,  wrote  his  '  Histori- 
arum  libri  vii.  adversus  paganos,'  at  the  suggestion  of  Augus- 
tine, and  in  reply  to  the  same  charges  against  Christianity 
and  Christians  which  are  combated  in  the  '  De  Civitate  Dei.' 
The  chief  merit  of  the  work  is  its  endeavour  after  comprehen- 
siveness. It  gives  a  history  of  the  world  from  the  creation 
to  the  year  a.d.  410.  Its  central  thought  is  that  God  has 
raised  up  and  cast  down  kingdoms,  distributed  happiness  and 
misery,  and  disposed  all  human  affairs,  with  a  view  to  the 
spread  and  triumph  of  Christianity.  This  gives  it  what- 
ever elevation  of  tone  and  unity  of  plan  it  possesses.  The 
polemical  and  practical  purpose  to  which  it  owed  its  origin 
is  never  lost  sight  of,  and  so  it  abounds  in  denunciations  of 
ambition,  conquest,  and  idolatry,  and  in  moral  advice  and 
spiritual  consolation.  It  adds  nothing  to  the  historical  theory 
of  Augustine.  Ozanam  finds  in  it  "  un  veritable  talent,  quel- 
quefois  ce  souffle  inspire'  du  g£nie  Espagnol,"  which  I  am 
unable  to  discover.  Doergens  (' Aristoteles,'  p.  12)  desig- 
nates its  author  —  "der  erste  Philosoph  der  Geschichte." 
This  is  altogether  unwarranted.  No  one  has  a  right  to  distrib- 
ute blue  ribbons  in  such  a  way.  Great  titles  ought  to  be  con- 
ferred only  on  great  men  and  for  great  services.  Orosius  was 
no  historical  philosopher  at  all,  —  no  philosopher  of  any  kind. 

Amidst  the  confusion  and  destruction  caused  by  the  barba- 
rian invasions  and  the  downfall  of  the  Western  empire,  histo- 
riography like  all  other  literature,  nearly  disappeared.  Men 
had  not  the  heart  to  describe  events  which  filled  them  with 
despair.     All  culture  decayed  until  only  the  bare  rudiments 


66  INTRODUCTION 

of  knowledge  remained.  The  historical  art  of  medieval  Eu- 
rope began,  as  that  of  Greece  and  Rome  had  begun,  with  the 
rude  and  simple  chronicle.  Yet  there  was  a  most  important 
difference  between  the  cases.  When  history  began  to  be 
recorded  in  Greece  and  Rome,  the  Greeks  and  Romans  had 
become  unconscious  of  their  connection  with  the  past  of  the 
human  race,  —  with  a  history  preceding  and  underlying  their 
own.  It  was  not  so  with  medieval  Europe.  Its  continuity 
with  the  past,  and  the  sense  thereof,  were  unsundered ;  both 
the  classical  and  the  Christian  traditions  were  retained  in  its 
memory.  The  new  cycle  was  thus,  even  at  the  commence- 
ment, unlike  as  well  as  like  the  old  one  ;  and  hence,  however 
analogous  to  it  it  might  prove  to  be,  it  could  never  possibly 
be  a  repetition  of  it.  Besides,  the  materials  of  history  were 
in  the  medieval  period  immensely  increased  by\the  new 
peoples  destined  to  become  new  nations,  and  by  the  new 
institutions  and  forms  of  life  destined,  after  absorption  or 
commingling  with  the  old,  to  be  evolved  into  a  political  and 
social  system  profoundly  different  from  the  Roman,  inasmuch 
as  it  was  far  more  extensive  and  complex,  far  more  spiritually 
rich,  highly  developed,  and  manifoldly  productive. 

The  fierce  minds  of  the  barbarians  were  softened  and  sub- 
dued by  the  persuasions  and  terrors  of  the  Church.  The 
Christian  clergy  became  the  teachers  and  rulers  of  the  nations 
which  arose  on  the  ruins  of  the  fallen  empire.  Art  or  culture 
had  been  the  dominant  fact  in  Greek  life,  and  positive  law  or 
policy  in  Roman  life ;  religion  or  piety  as  understood  by  the 
Church  was  made  the  dominant  fact  in  medieval  life.  Lit- 
erature in  all  its  branches  became  predominantly  religious, 
and  religious  in  its  specially  medieval,  that  is,  ecclesiastical 
form.  Ecclesiastical  histories  outnumbered  all  other  his- 
tories. Biographies  of  saints,  bishops,  and  popes,  histories 
of  single  convents  and  monastic  orders,  &c,  abounded;  and 
even  general  or  political  histories  were,  with  few  exceptions, 
written  by  ecclesiastics  and  on  ecclesiastical  principles.  In- 
deed, no  sharp  or  marked  distinction  was  drawn  between 
ecclesiastical  and  general  or  political  history,  for  the  Church 
in  these  times  intervened  directly  and  powerfully  in  all 
affairs.    The  distinction  deemed  fundamental  in  the  medieval 


MEDIEVAL    HISTORIANS  67 

period  was  not  that  between  Church  and  State,  but  that  be- 
tween the  kingdom  of  God  and  the  kingdom  of  the  world  — 
the  civitas  Dei  and  civitas  diaboli  of  Augustine ;  and  as  men 
obeyed  or  disobeyed  the  Church,  as  affairs  were  favourable  or 
adverse  to  the  Church,  they  were  regarded,  at  least  by  almost 
all  Churchmen,  as  belonging  to  the  one  kingdom  or  the  other. 

The  mass  of  historical  writing  in  Latin  left  by  the  ecclesi- 
astics of  the  middle  age  is  enormous.  The  best  portion  of  it 
is  contained  in  the  vast  collections  of  Greevius,  Muratori, 
Bouquet,  Migne,  Guizot,  Pertz,  and  the  Master  of  the  Rolls. 
Much  more  of  it  has  seen  the  light  in  the  publications  of 
local  learned  societies.  Much  of  it  is  still  unpublished.  To 
those  who  would  make  a  special  study  of  it,  Potthast1  and 
Chevallier  2  may  serve  as  general  guides.  Surveys  have  been 
made  of  special  sections  of  it,  as  by  Wattenbach  3  and  Lorenz.4 
There  is  still  wanting,  however,  a  comprehensive  account  of 
medieval  historiography.  My  purpose  requires  me  only  to 
refer  to  a  very  few  of  the  most  representative  writers  and 
productions. 

Gregory  of  Tours,  who  died  in  594,  may  fitly  come  first.  As 
his  '  Historia  Francorum '  is  the  chief  original  source  of  infor- 
mation for  the  Merovingian  period,  he  is  often  called  the  father 
of  French  history ;  but,  of  course,  the  title  is  ambiguous,  and  by 
the  unlearned  apt  to  be  misunderstood.  In  a  small  and  feeble 
body  he  bore  a  large  and  strong  soul,  and  played  his  part 
bravely  and  skilfully  in  fearful  and  difficult  times.  His  'His- 
toria Francorum'  is  in  ten  books.  The  first,  beginning  with 
the  creation  of  Adam  and  Eve,  and  ending  with  the  death  of 
St.  Martin  of  Tours,  is  of  no  special  worth.  The  second  treats 
of  the  Frankish  conquest,  and  is  drawn  to  a  considerable  extent 
from  works  now  lost.  The  third  and  fourth  deal  with  events 
down  to  574,  two  years  after  Gregory  had  become  bishop,  and  are 
also  comparatively  meagre.  The  later  books  are  much  fuller; 
indeed,  the  last  four  are  occupied  with  a  period  of  only  seven 

1  Potthast  (A)  —  Bibliotheca  Historica  Medii  Aevi.    Berlin,  1862. 

2  Chevallier  (U)  — Repertoire  des  sources  historiques  du  moyen  age.  Paris, 
1877-84. 

8  Wattenbach  (W) — Deutschland's  Geschichtsquellen  im  Mittelalter  bis  zur 
Mitte  des  xiii.  Jahrhunderts.    4°  Aufl.    Berlin,  1877-78. 

4  Lorenz  (O) — Deutschland's  Geschichtsquellen  im  Mittelalter  seit  der  Mitte 
des  xiii.  Jahrhunderts.    3°  Aufl.    Berlin,  1886. 


68  INTRODUCTION 

years.  Gregory  was  not  in  the  least  a  literary  artist.  He  was 
quite  conscious  of  a  defective  acquaintance  with  grammar. 
"  Veniam  precor,"  he  says,  "  si  aut  in  litteris,  aut  in  syllabis 
grammaticam  artem  excessero,  de  qua  adplene  non  sum  ini- 
butus  "  ('  Hist.  Fr.'  iv.  1).  His  style  was  rude,  unformed,  dis- 
jointed, without  force,  precision,  or  elegance,  but  at  times  not 
devoid  of  a  certain  realistic  vividness.  Of  aptness  in  arrange- 
ment, skill  in  proportioning  parts  to  one  another  and  the  whole, 
or  judicious  subordination  of  local  to  general,  and  insignificant 
to  important  details,  his  work  shows  no  traces.  He  was  far 
from  unprejudiced  in  judgment,  or  critical  in  his  appreciation 
of  evidence.  He  was  a  credulous  believer  in  miracles,  and 
thought  very  leniently  of  monstrous  crimes  if  committed  by 
orthodox  princes,  very  severely  of  heresy  or  hostility  to  the 
Church ;  but  he  was  honest  and  earnest  according  to  his  light, 
and  showed  himself  so  by  the  ingenuousness,  candour,- and  ful- 
ness of  his  statements  of  fact.  He  made  no  attempt  to  analyse 
characters  and  actions,  to  trace  the  causes  of  events,  to  explain 
the  course,  tendencies,  and  issues  of  human  affairs.  His  hori- 
zon was  very  limited,  and  all  within  it  was  drifting  and  con- 
fused, seething  and  storm-tossed.  The  historical  world  around 
him  was  not  one  in  which  he  could  truly  see  order,  and  there- 
fore, the  best  thing  he  could  do,  probably,  was  to  describe  it  in 
all  the  disorder  in  which  he  saw  it,  instead  of  vainly  trying  to 
find  order  in,  or  force  order  upon,  it.  He  was  devoid  both  of 
historical  philosophy  and  of  historical  art,  but  he  has  preserved 
a  rich  store  of  materials  for  the  historical  philosophy  and  art 
of  later  times. 

Bede  (Baeda)  was  born  about  one  hundred  and  thirty  years 
after  Gregory  of  Tours.  Both  his  character  and  surroundings 
were  very  different  from  those  of  the  first  historian  of  the 
Franks.  He  spent  a  studious,  pious,  peaceful  life  in  the  monas- 
teries of  Wearmouth  and  Jarrow.  It  closed  with  a  beautiful 
death  in  735.  He  acquired  mastery  over  all  the  scholarship 
and  science  of  his  age,  and  composed  treatises  and  tracts  on  a 
wonderful  variety  of  subjects.  Burke  has  aptly  called  him  "  the 
father  of  English  learning."  Much  the  most  important  of  his 
works  is  the  one  which  here  concerns  us,  the  '  Historia  Ecclesi- 
astica  Gentis  Anglorum.'     Its  five  books  embrace  the  period 


MEDIEVAL   HISTORIANS  69 

from  Csesar's  invasion  to  731.  It  begins  to  be  of  value  with 
the  arrival  of  Augustine  in  597,  and  still  more  with  that  of 
Paulinus  in  630.  It  gives  a  deeply  interesting  and  most  trust- 
worthy account  of  the  way  in  which  the  Saxons  in  England  were 
Christianised,  and  also  a  large  amount  of  precious  information 
as  to  events  which  would  now  be  called  secular.  For  a  con- 
siderable portion  of  the  time  to  which  it  relates,  it  is  contempo- 
rary history.  It  shows  a  diligence  in  the  collection  of  materials, 
and  a  conscientiousness  in  the  use  of  them,  worthy  of  all  praise. 
Bede  was  so  judicious  in  the  selection  of  his  informants  that 
much  of  what  he  tells  us  on  the  authority  of  others  is  not  less 
to  be  credited  than  what  he  tells  us  on  his  own.  His  careful- 
ness to  let  his  readers  -know  who  the  authorities  for  his  state- 
ments are,  makes  his  honesty  obvious  even  when  he  is  most 
manifestly  in  error.  Thus,  although  he  never  seems  to  have 
thought  of  doubting  the  occurrence  of  a  miracle  vouched  for  by 
a  man  whose  character  he  esteemed,  as  he  seldom  or  never  fails 
to  mention  on  whose  testimony  he  relies,  no  ground  is  left  for 
suspicion  in  regard  to  his  own  veracity  even  when  under  the 
influence  of  superstition.  Most  of  what  is  known  of  the  cen- 
tury and  a  half  of  English  history  after  the  arrival  of  Augustine 
is  wholly  derived  from  Bede.  Later  annalists  and  historians 
treating  of  the  same  period  have  only  repeated  or  amplified  and 
altered  his  statements.  The  superiority  of  his  work  to  that  of 
Gregory  of  Tours  as  regards  literary  qualities  is  very  marked. 
It  is  a  true  whole,  although  occasionally  the  connection  of  its 
parts  is  loose  and  the  arrangement  is  determined  by  external 
suggestions.  Its  style  is  clear,  flowing,  attractive,  suitable  to 
the  subject,  and  a  natural  reflection  of  the  writer's  mind.  Par- 
ticular incidents  are  often  admirably  presented.  Bede  was  cer- 
tainly not  an  historical  philosopher,  but  he  was  as  certainly  an 
historical  artist  of  very  considerable  merit.  It  may  be  added, 
that  in  his  '  De  ratione  temporum '  he  at  least  set  a  good  exam- 
ple, in  occupying  himself  with  chronology;  and  that,  although 
no  originality  can  be  ascribed  to  his  '  De  sex  setatibus  seculi,' 
it  greatly  helped  to  transmit  and  spread  that  general  view  of 
the  development  and  stages  of  the  history  of  the  world  which 
Augustine,  Isidore  of  Seville,  and  others,  had  propounded. 
We  require  to  pass  into  another  land  and  onwards  into  the 


70  INTRODUCTION 

eleventh  century  before  we  come  to  a  writer  who  added  to  his- 
torical knowledge  in  anything  like  the  same  measure  as  Bede. 
Accordingly,  I  mention  next  the  author  of  the  '  Gesta  Hamena- 
burgensis  ecclesise  pontificum,'  generally  known  as  Adam  of 
Bremen.  His  work  was  written  between  1072  and  1076.  The 
archbishopric  of  Lund  was  not  then  founded,  and  all  the  Bal- 
tic regions  —  German,  Scandinavian,  and  Russian  —  lay  within 
the  archbishopric  of  Hamburg-Bremen.  Adam's  history  of 
this  ecclesiastical  province  is  the  chief  source  of  knowledge 
of  the  oldest  history,  both  religious  and  secular,  of  the  north 
of  Europe.  The  information  in  it  was  drawn  from  books  and 
documents  now  lost,  as  well  as  from  personal  research  dur- 
ing its  author's  journeys  for  missionary  purposes.  It  bears 
all  the  general  marks  of  trustworthiness  and  truthfulness, 
although  in  parts  much  fable  is  mixed  up  with^fact.  Its 
style  is  natural  and  vigorous.  Lappenberg  says  that  if  the 
author  had  only  written  in  his  own  tongue  he  would  have  been 
"  the  Herodotus  of  the  North." 

In  South  Germany  there  lived  a  contemporary  of  the  Canon 
of  Bremen  who  was  still  more  eminent  as  a  writer,  —  Lambert 
of  Hersfeld.  Mr.  Freeman  speaks  of  him  thus :  "  He  begins 
with  annals ;  he  gradually  enlarges  and  warms,  till  his  tale 
grows  into  that  precious  and  admirable  narrative  of  the  great 
struggle  between  Pope  and  Caesar,  that  narrative  so  clear,  so 
full,  so  wisely  treading  the  narrow  path  between  partisan 
writers  on  either  side,  that  it  has  won  for  a  monk  of  the  eleventh 
century  his  full  right  to  a  place  alongside  the  foremost  of  the 
so-called  ancients." 1  Perhaps  these  words  convey  too  high  an 
estimate  of  Lambert's  impartiality.  He  was,  indeed,  impartial 
as  compared  with  most  of  his  contemporaries,  but  that  his  im- 
partiality was  more  than  thus  relative,  may  fairly  be  doubted, 
and  has  been  denied  after  special  examination  by  critical 
historians  like  Ranke,  Flotto,  Geisebrecht,  and  Wattenbach. 
Probably  the  Pope  received  considerably  more,  and  Csesar 
considerably  less,  than  justice  from  him,  notwithstanding  the 
natural  independence,  moderation,  and  liberality  of  judgment 
which  cause  him  to  contrast  so  favourably  with  the  partisan 
writers  of  his  day.     No  one  will  deny  to  him  rare  literary 

1  Methods  of  Historical  Study,  pp.  164,  165. 


MEDIEVAL    HISTORIANS  71 

talent.  His  general  style  is  a  fine  combination  of  native  force 
and  cultured  elegance.  He  portrays  character  and  pictures 
incident  with  a  masterly  hand.  Many  of  his  pages  once  read 
can  never  be  forgotten. 

The  most  philosophical  of  the  medieval  chroniclers  was  Otto 
of  E'reisingen,  —  the  grandson  of  the  Emperor  Henry  IV.,  half- 
brother  of  Conrad  III.,  and  uncle,  confidant,  and  chosen  biog- 
rapher of  Frederick  I.,  the  famous  Barbarossa.  He  was  an 
earnestly  pious  man,  a  theologian,  a  monk,  an  ecclesiastical 
dignitary,  but  also  a  man  of  clear  and  sound  judgment,  con- 
versant with  political  affairs,  and  deeply  interested  in  the  for- 
tunes of  the  empire.  He  died  in  1158.  His '  Chronicon  '  was 
written  between  1143  and  1146.  It  consists  of  eight  books, 
the  first  six  of  which  were  largely  a  reproduction  of  the 
Universal  Chronicle  of  Ekkehard  of  Auraeh.  The  seventh 
book  is  original  work  of  great  merit  and  value.  The  two 
books  'De  gestis  Frederici  I.,'  which  may  be  viewed  as  con- 
tinuing it,  are  of  equal  quality,  and  of  even  higher  interest. 
It  is  from  these  books  that  the  author's  rank  among  historians 
must  chiefly  be  determined.  They  entitle  him  to  a  high  posi- 
tion. They  are  characterised  by  comprehensiveness  of  treat- 
ment, accuracy  of  statement,  clearness  of  insight.  They 
display  a  greater  impartiality  than  the  'Annales '  of  Lambert. 
They  are  excellent  in  style  and  arrangement.  They  are  lack- 
ing in  no  essential  historical  quality.  The  eighth  book  of  the 
'  Chronicle '  treats  of  the  coming  and  dominion  of  Antichrist, 
of  the  end  of  the  world,  of  the  resurrection  of  the  just  and 
unjust,  of  the  twofold  judgment,  of  the  condition  of  the  lost, 
and  of  the  life  of  the  blessed  in  heaven.  In  the  plan  of  Otto, 
it  was  a  most  essential  portion  of  the  work.  To  that  work  he 
himself  gave  a  title  which  at  once  expressed  its  leading  thought 
and  indicated  whence  the  thought  was  drawn,  —  "  De  rerum 
mundanarum  mutatione,  sive  de  duabus  civitatibus."  All 
in  it  turns  on  the  Augustinian  dualism  of  the  earthly  and 
heavenly  cities,  the  antagonism  of  the  kingdoms  of  man  to  the 
kingdom  of  Christ.  From  beginning  to  end  its  aim  is  to  make 
apparent  the  mutability,  the  vanity,  and  miseries  of  mundane 
life,  and  that  heaven  is*  the  only  true  refuge  and  home  of 
humanity.     The  contentions  of  the  time,  and  especially  the 


72  INTRODUCTION 

conflict  between  pope  and  emperor,  while  perplexing  his  mind 
and  grieving  his  heart,  served  to  confirm  him  in  a  belief  which 
he  shared  with  many  of  his  contemporaries,  that  the  consum- 
mation of  things  was  at  hand;  that  soon  Antichrist  would 
appear,  and  that  then  Christ  would  come  to  judgment  and 
take  to  Himself  all  power  and  dominion.  He  wrote,  accord- 
ingly, "  ex  amaritudine  animse,"  and  "  non  curiositatis  causa 
sed  ad  ostendendas  caducarum  rerum  calamitates."  His 
steady  contemplation  of  the  course  of  history  from  a  religious 
point  of  view  has  caused  his  work  to  be  described  as  "  the  first 
and  only  attempt  at  a  philosophy  of  history  made  in  the  middle 
age."  But  it  was  rather  an  attempt  to  establish  by  history  a 
thesis  in  theology.  Certainly  if  a  philosophy  of  history  at 
all  it  was  a  poor  one.  Instead  of  seeking  to  exhibit  the  in- 
trinsic significance  of  history,  it  sought  to  show  that  history 
had  no  intrinsic  significance.  A  pessimistic  view  of  life  in 
time  is  not  made  satisfactory  by  being  conjoined  with  an 
optimistic  conception  of  life  in  eternity. 

In  the  twelfth  and  thirteenth  centuries  there  flourished  in 
England  a  school  of  writers  who,  if  less  than  historians  proper, 
were  more  than  annalists  or  chroniclers.  They  took  the  classi- 
cal historians  as  their  models ;  sought  to  trace  the  relations 
of  cause  and  effect,  instead  of  servilely  following  the  mere 
sequences  of  time ;  treated  the  course  of  events  in  England 
as  not  unconnected  with  the  movement  of  affairs  abroad ;  and, 
in  a  word,  attempted  to  interpret  as  well  as  narrate,  while  also 
aiming  at  artistic  excellence.  This  school  was  inaugurated 
by  William  of  Malmesbury,  and  found  its  greatest  represents 
tive  in  Matthew  Paris.  "  In  Matthew  the  breadth  and  pre- 
cision of  the  narrative,  the  copiousness  of  his  information  on 
topics  whether  national  or  European,  the  general  fairness  and 
justice  of  his  comments,  are  only  surpassed  by  the  patriotic 
fire  and  enthusiasm  of  the  whole.  .  .  .  With  all  the  fulness 
of  the  school  of  court  historians,  such  as  Benedict  or  Hoveden, 
he  combines  an  independence  and  patriotism  which  is  strange 
to  their  pages.  He  denounces  with  the  same  unsparing  energy 
the  oppression  of  the  Papacy  and  the  king.  His  point  of  view 
is  neither  that  of  a  courtier  nor  of  *  Churchman,  but  of  an 
Englishman,  and  the  new  national  tone  of  his  chronicle  is  but 


VERNACULAR    CHRONICLES  73 

an  echo  of  the  national  sentiment  which  at  last  bound  nobles 
and  yeomen  and  Churchmen  together  into  an  English  people." 1 

It  is  unnecessary  to  trace  further  the  course  of  Latin  histo- 
riography. There  is  little  to  tempt  us  to  linger  on  the  Latin 
chronicles  or  histories  composed  in  the  later  centuries  of  the 
middle  age.  I  know  of  none  of  them  not  inferior  to  some  of 
those  which  have  been  already  noticed:  The  bonds  of  medi- 
eval Christendom  had  to  be  broken  before  there  could  be  any 
marked  advance.  The  next  revival  of  Latin  historical  liter- 
ature came  only  when  it  was  on  the  eve  of  being  generally 
abandoned.  In  the  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries  Poly- 
dore  Vergil,  Sleidan,  De  Thou,  and  others,  reflected  honour 
on  its  old  age.  Since  the  classic  world  passed  away,  Latin 
historiography  never,  perhaps,  reached  so  near  classic  excel- 
lence as  in  the  writings  of  these  men.  But  they  and  their 
works  do  not  fall  to  be  considered  here ;  they  lie  beyond  the 
limits  of  the  time  to  which  this  Introduction  refers. 

History  can  only  be  written  adequately  in  the  speech  of 
the  peoples  who  make  history.  Modern  history  required  to  be 
recorded  in  the  languages  of  the  modern  nations.  Away  from 
contact  with  Latin  and  the  remains  and  traditions  of  Roman 
civilisation,  the  Norse  people  grew  up  heroic  and  adventurous, 
and  the  Norse  tongue  developed  itself  in  freedom.  Nowhere 
in  Latinised  Christendom  did  men  write  as  well  as  the  Scandi- 
navian scalds  spoke  and  sang.  Hence  lonely  Iceland  can 
boast  of  its  Heimskringla,  that  immortal  story  of  the  Kings 
of  Norway,  by  Snorro  Sturleson,  murdered  in  1241,  compared 
with  the  pages  of  which  those  even  of  a  Matthew  Paris  are 
pale  and  tedious.  There  the  wild  Viking  life,  as  it  moved  on 
through  gloom  and  light,  calm  and  storm,  by  land  and  on  sea, 
in  domestic  scenes,  strange  adventures,  fierce  battles,  and 
cruel  tragedies,  for  more  than  three  hundred  years,  is  por- 
trayed with  the  truth  and  power  of  a  master  akin  in  genius 
to  Homer,  and  Scott,  and  Carlyle. 

England  can  claim  the  honour  of  having  had  the  earliest 
vernacular  chronicle ;  Russia  of  having  had  the  earliest  ver- 
nacular history;  France  of  having  had  the  earliest  series  of 
popular  chroniclers;    and  Italy  of  having  had  the   earliest 

1  Green's  Short  Hist,  of  the  Eng.  People,  pp.  142,  143. 


74.  INTRODUCTION 

historians  eminent  for  political  knowledge  and  philosophical 
insight.  The  general  and  intense  interest  excited  through- 
out Europe  by  the  Crusades  was  what  gave  the  chief  direct 
impulse  to  the  writing  of  history  in  the  speech  of  the  un- 
learned. Once  begun  various  causes  favoured  its  perpetua- 
tion, and  such  causes  continually  increased  in  number  and 
power  as  feudalism  fell  and  modern  nations  became  consti- 
tuted and  consolidated.  The  rise  and  growth,  however,  of 
historiography  in  the  French,  German,  Italian,  and  English 
languages,  must  not  be  treated  of  at  this  point,  but  in  con- 
nection with  the  development  of  historical  philosophy  in  the 
French,  German,  Italian,  and  English  nations. 

Medieval  Europe  produced  nothing  worthy  to  be  called  a 
philosophy  of  history.  And  this  was  natural,  for  medieval 
Europe  was  extremely  ignorant  alike  of  the  facts  and  the 
methods  which  an  adequate  philosophy  of  history  presupposes. 

First,  there  was  in  the  middle  ages  a  want  of  the  necessary 
facts,  and  a  want  of  knowledge  of  what  facts  there  were. 
Sciences  differ  greatly  from  one  another  as  to  the  number  of 
facts  which  they  require  for  a  foundation,  as  to  the  number  of 
observations  they  must  have  from  which  to  start.  In  some, 
the  phenomena  are  comparatively  simple  and  obviously  bound 
together  by  laws  productive  of  order  and  harmony  ;  in  others, 
the  phenomena  are  comparatively  complex,  and  the  connec- 
tions among  them  exceedingly  latent,  abstruse,  difficult  to 
trace.  Astronomy  is  a  science  of  the  former  kind ;  geology  of 
the  latter :  and  that  is  one  reason,  and  not  the  least  powerful 
reason,  why  the  one  is  so  ancient  and  the  other  so  recent.  But 
as  no  science  has  facts  so  complex,  so  diverse,  so  mobile,  so  in- 
termingled, to  deal  with  as  that  of  human  history,  manifestly 
none  needs  the  same  multiplicity  of  observations,  so  extensive 
and  varied  a  range  of  experience.  Confine  the  mind  within 
any  narrow  sphere,  and  in  vain  will  it  try  to  discern  the  prin- 
ciples which  pervade  it  and  connect  it  with  others ;  lay  before 
it  only  the  events  of  a  few  generations  or  nations,  and  in  vain 
will  it  strive  to  reduce  them  under  law.  "  It  must,"  to  use 
the  words  of  M.  Cousin,  "see  many  empires,  many  religions, 
many  systems,  appear  and  disappear  before  it  can  ascend  to  the 
general  laws  which  regulate  the  rise  and  fall  of  human  things; 


MEDIEVAL   HISTORICAL  THOUGHT  75 

it  must  survive  many  revolutions  and  must  go  through  much 
disorder  before  it  can  comprehend  that  above  and  around  all 
there  is  a  beautiful  and  beneficent  order."  But  how  narrow 
was  the  range  of  experience  and  real  information  accessible  to 
the  medieval  historian !  Till  the  East  and  West  came  into 
contact  through  invasions  and  crusades,  commerce  and  pil- 
grimages, little  was  known  in  Europe  of  the  oriental  world 
beyond  what  was  stated  in  the  Bible.  The  knowledge  even  of 
Roman  history  was  for  a  long  time  in  danger  of  being  lost,  and 
was  preserved  mainly  through  the  growth  of  those  *practical 
interests  which  necessitated  the  study  of  Roman  law.  The 
knowledge  of  Greek  history  was  virtually  lost  till  the  great  rev- 
olution known  as  the  Revival  of  Letters  took  place.  Although 
almost  all  possible  elements  and  forms  of  social  life  lay  around 
the  men  who  lived  in  that  age  of  anarchy  which  was  the  imme- 
diate consequence  of  the  victory  of  the  barbarians  over  the 
Romans,  they  were  so  intermingled  and  undeveloped  that  any 
adequate  insight  into  their  real  natures  and  issues  was  impossi- 
ble. The  sphere  of  historical  knowledge  thus  narrow  was  only 
capable  of  being  enlarged  by  a  long  series  of  events  in  history 
itself,  —  by  the  rise  and  progress  of  arts,  sciences,  forms  of 
government,  and  nations,  by  changes  of  creed  and  habits,  by 
manifold  inquiries  and  discoveries,  suggesting  or  succeeding 
one  another  in  an  order  determined  by  nature  and  reason. 

The  medieval  mind  was,  further,  most  incapable  of  dealing 
rightly  with  the  historical  facts  which  were  accessible  to  it. 
The  primary  requisite  of  history  is,  of  course,  that  it  be  a 
true  record  of  events,  the  statement  only  of  what  happened, 
the  accurate  statement  of  what  happened.  But  that  supposes 
the  existence  and  exercise  of  qualities  in  which  the  medieval 
historian  was  specially  and  signally  deficient,  the  power  of 
truthful  observation,  the  habit  of  weighing  and  sifting  evi- 
dence, the  ability  to  throw  off  prejudice,  and  lay  the  mind 
open  to  receive  the  real  stamp  and  impression  of  the  actual 
occurrences.  He  was,  on  the  contrary,  in  the  highest  degree 
credulous,  uncritical,  and  prejudiced.  Ignorant  of  his  igno- 
rance, ignorant  of  what  knowledge  was,  he  readily  accepted 
fictions  as  facts,  and  believed  as  unquestionable  a  crowd  of 
legends  regarding  Greece  and  Rome,  and  even  the  States  that 


76  INTRODUCTION 

had  risen  on  the  ruins  of  Rome,  which  made  everything  like 
a  correct  notion  of  the  course  of  human  development  impos- 
sible. Imbued  with  the  spirit  of  his  age,  he  looked  at  all 
events  through  an  ecclesiastical  and  dogmatic  medium  which 
effectually  precluded  him  from  fairly  estimating  secular,  and, 
still  more,  heathen  life.  As^r-egards  stories  of  miracles,  men 
of  such  general  soundness^f  mind  as  Gregory  of  Tours  and 
~T3ede  were  utferlyunable  to  distinguish  truth  from  error. 
Thousands  on  thousands  of  miracles  were  vouched  for  by  the 
medieval  chroniclers,  and  yet  there  is  no  warrant  for  suppos- 
ing that  a  single  true  miracle  was  wrought  during  the  whole 
medieval  period.  Certain  writers  have  argued  that  some  of 
the  alleged  miracles  must  have  been  true,  otherwise  so  many 
false  ones  would  not  have  been  credited.  But  they  have  not 
ventured  to  point  out  which  were  true ;  and  the  supposition 
that  God,  by  performing  a  few  real  miracles,  provided  a 
support  for  faith  in  a  multitude  of  false  ones,  is  far  from  a 
probable  or  pleasant  hypothesis.  It  should  be  frankly  ac- 
knowledged that  in  the  middle  age  faith  was  to  a  large  ex- 
tent as  blind  as  it  was  sincere.  It  is  not  necessary,  however, 
to  dwell  on  this  point.  Buckle  has  collected,  in  the  sixth 
chapter  of  the  first  volume  of  his  '  History  of  Civilisation  in 
England,'  numerous  instructive  examples  of  the  credulity  of 
medieval  chroniclers,  and  has  proved  in  its  thirteenth  chapter 
that  the  free  and  impartial  criticism  of  testimony  failed  to 
penetrate  even  into  French  historiography  before  the  seven- 
teenth century.  Lecky  in  his  '  History  of  the  Rise  and  Influ- 
ence of  the  Spirit  of  Rationalism  in  Europe,'  Draper  in  his 
'  Intellectual  Development  of  Europe,'  and  Mazzarella  in  his 
'  Storia  della  Critica,'  while  furnishing  confirmatory  evidence, 
have  shown  how,  through  the  concurrent  action  of  many 
causes,  the  spirit  of  inquiry  grew  up  and  spread,  how  the 
fetters  of  theological  dogmatism  were  gradually  broken,  and 
how  the  prejudices  which  had  riveted  them  on  were  gradu- 
ally rooted  out.  The  art  and  theory  of  historical  criticism 
were  alike  unknown  to  the  medieval  historians. 

But  the  correct  ascertainment  of  the  facts  is  merely  the 
first  and  simplest  function  of  method ;  the  inductiyejjse  «f 
the  facts  is  a  more  difficult  one,-and  is  necessarily  later  in 


MEDIEVAL   HISTORICAL   THOUGHT  77 

appearing.  It  was  impossible  that  the  processes  of  induction 
could  be  successfully  applied  to  historical  materials  before 
the  mind  had  become  accustomed  to  deal  truthfully  and  inde- 
pendently with  these  materials  as  individual  phenomena,  and 
to  employ  these  processes  in  the  various  departments  of  the 
physical  sciences  where  their  employment  is  so  much  simpler. 
In  fact,  only  since  the  eighteenth  century  can  historians  be 
found  occupying  themselves  with  the  remote  causes  of  events, 
with  general  social  tendencies,  with  the  principles  of  intel- 
lectual and  political  development  which  circumscribe  and 
dominate  individual  wills.  The  historians  of  antiquity  aimed 
at  describing  events  in  a  truthful,  agreeable,  and  morally  and 
politically  profitable  manner ;  their  highest  ambition  was  the 
composition  of  works  beautiful  in  form  and  practically  edify- 
ing in  contents,  and  they  succeeded  to  admiration;  but  even 
the  profoundest  among  them  made  no  attempt  to  go  farther 
back  along  the  lines  of  causation  than  to  the  motives  of  the 
actors  engaged,  or  the  direct  influences  of  certain  social  insti- 
tutions. The  middle  ages  were  giving  place  to  the  modern 
era  before  the  search  for  causes  was  carried  even  thus  fa'r  by 
later  historians.  Mr.  Hallam  is,  I  believe,  correct  in  saying 
that  Philippe  de  Gommines  "  is  the  first  modern  writer  who 
in  any  degree  has  displayed  sagacity  in  reasoning  on  the 
characters  of  men  and  the  consequences  of  their  actions,  or 
who  has  been  able  to  generalise  his  observations  by  comparison 
and  reflection."  He  was  certainly  surpassed,  however,  both 
in  power  of  analysis  and  generalisation  by  his  Italian  con- 
temporary, Macchiavelli,  and  yet  even  this  great  writer,  al- 
though he  shows  in  his  '  Discorsi  sopra  la  prima  deca  di  T. 
Livio '  a  singular  clearness  and  keenness  of  insight  into  the 
proximate  causes,  both  political  and  psychological,  of  events, 
and  a  singular  power  of  reasoning  from  particulars  to  partic- 
ulars, from  ancient  to  modern  actions  and  institutions,  neg- 
lects remote  causes,  and  rests  content  with  analogies  instead 
of  laws,  —  analogies  which  he  has  often  exaggerated  and 
overstrained  in  order  to  convert  them  into  practical  lessons 
for  immediate  application.  Vico  and  Montesquieu  were  the 
morning  stars  of  a  brighter  and  broader  day,  the  light  of 
which  is  now  reflected  from  the  pages  of  almost  all  historians 


78  INTRODUCTION 

of  recognised  ability,  not  excluding  even  those  who  speak 
most  despairingly  of  everything  of  the  nature  of  historical 
science  or  philosophy.  It  is  now  generally  acknowledged 
that  the  historian  must  not  merely  give  correct  information 
as  to  particular  actions  and  agents,  hut  must  exhibit  them  in 
connection  withvthe  spirit,  tendencies,  and  interests  of  the 
age  to  which  they  belonged,  with  a  collective  life,  the  phases 
of  which  are  determined  by  forces  which  manifest  themselves 
more  or  less  in  individual  events  and  persons,  but  extend  far 
beyond,  behind,  and  beneath  them.  Thus  a  Grote  or  Curtius, 
a  Niebuhr  or  Mommsen,  casts  over  the  events  even  of  Greek 
and  Roman  history  a  kind  of  light1  not  to  be  found  in  Herodo- 
tus and  Thucydides,  Livy  and  Polybius,  and  which  is  essen- 
tially scientific  in  character,  because  due  to  the  knowledge  of 
laws  and  causes  discoverable  neither  by  the  mere  observation 
of  events  nor  insight  into  the  motives  of  individuals,  but 
only  by  an  elaborate  use  of  the  processes  and  resources  of  the 
inductive  method.  In  the  sphere  of  history,  analysis  and 
comparison  have  received  new  applications,  classification  and 
generalisation  increased  light  and  power,  with  the  result  that 
entire  new  departments  of  history  have  been  constituted. 
We  are  no  longer  content  with  records  of  external  transac- 
tions, but  seek  also  to  know  the  growth  of  reason  and  culture 
themselves,  —  the  development  of  humanity  in  all  its  aspects 
and  activities,  industrial,  aesthetic,  political,  moral,  religious, 
and  scientific.  But  all  this  is  modern.  The  men  of  medieval 
times  were  so  ignorant  of  scientific  law  and  method  as  to 
have  no  conception  of  any  of  the  forms  of  history  in  which  a 
knowledge  of  them  is  implied. 

It  must  not  be  forgotten,  however,  that  during  the  middle 
age  there  existed  a  Mohammedan  as  well  as  a  Christian  civili- 
sation, and  a  Mohammedan  as  well  as  a  Christian  historiog- 
raphy. In  the  seventh  century  Mohammed  founded  a  new- 
religion,  which  first  united  into  a  single  people  the  scattered 
tribes  of  Arabia,  and  then  spread  with  unparalleled  rapidity 
over  the  eastern  provinces  of  Rome,  Persia,  Scinde,  Egypt, 
North  Africa,  and  Spain.  It  everywhere  roused  and  quick- 
ened the  minds  of  its  believers;  and  for  several  centuries 
Moslim  civilisation  in  most  respects  equalled,  and  in  some 
surpassed,  the  Christian  civilisation  which  it  confronted. 


ARABIC   HISTORIANS  79 

There  were  no  historical  compositions  ( in  Arabic  before 
the  time  of  Mohammed.  The  Prophet  himself  was  the  first 
subject  of  historical  interest  and  treatment ;  the  next  was  the 
exploits  of  those  who  fought  in  his  cause.  For  about  a  cen- 
tury after  his  death  history  was  communicated  almost  exclu- 
sively by  spoken,  not  written  words.  Oral  tradition,  however, 
increasingly  disclosed  its  inadequacy ;  and  as  great  events 
rapidly  succeeded  one  another,  a  luxuriant  growth  of  histori- 
cal literature  naturally  followed.  That  literature  became  not 
only  of  vast  magnitude  but  of  great  value.  The  Christian 
medieval  world  was  only  a  part  of  the  medieval  world,  and 
a  part  imperfectly  intelligible  without  acquaintance  with  its 
Mohammedan  counterpart  and  complement.  It  may  be  safely 
affirmed  that  all  our  universal  histories,  histories  of  civilisation, 
and  philosophies  of  history,  suffer  from  their  authors'  defective 
knowledge  of  the  history  of  Mohammedanism.  Probably  no 
class  of  scholars  have  it  in  their  power  to  increase  more  the 
stock  of  generally  useful  historical  knowledge  than  those  who 
are  qualified  to  appreciate  and  utilise  the  Arabic  historians. 
The  histories  of  Mohammedan  countries  in  the  middle  age 
have  been  as  fully  recorded  by  Mohammedan  annalists  as 
those  of  the  various  regions  of  Christendom  during  the  same 
period  by  the  monkish  chroniclers ;  and  consequently,  a 
knowledge  of  the  former  as  exact  and  ample  as  of  the  latter 
is  recoverable,  and  may  equally  be  made  to  enter  into  the 
common  inheritance  of  educated  mankind. 

In  the  early  period  of  Mohammedan  historiography  a  promi- 
nent place  was  occupied,  as  has  been  said,  by  accounts  of 
Mohammed,  and  of  1;he  wars  in  which  his  immediate  followers 
were  engaged.  The  genealogies  of  Arab  tribes  and  families 
received  much  attention.  The  collection  of  the  traditions 
relating  to  the  Prophet  and  to  religious  beliefs  and  practices 
was  a  work  in  which  great  interest  was  felt  and  by  which  repu- 
tation was  most  easily  gained.  The  mode  in  which  the  written 
history  arose  out  of  oral  testimony  had  a  decisive  influence  on 
its  whole  form  and  character,  as  is  well  indicated  in  the  follow- 
ing remarks  of  De  Slane :  "  The  documents  relative  to  Muham- 
madan  history  were  transmitted  during  the  first  centuries  by 
oral  tradition  from  one  hdfiz  to  another,  and  these  persons  made 


80  INTRODUCTION 

it  an  object  of  their  particular  care  not  to  alter,  in  the  least 
degree,  the  narrations  which  they  had  received.  The  pieces 
thus  preserved  were  generally  furnished  by  eyewitnesses  of  the 
facts  which  are  related  in  them,  and  are  therefore  of  the  highest 
importance,  not  only  for  the  history  of  the  Moslim  people,  but 
for  that  of  the  Arabic  language.  The  hdfiz  who  communicated 
a  narration  of  this  kind  to  his  scholar  never  neglected  indi- 
cating beforehand  the  series  of  persons  through  whom  it  had 
successively  passed  before  it  came  down  to  him,  and  this  in- 
troduction, or  support  —  isndd,  as  the  Arabs  call  it  —  is  the 
surest  proof  that  what  follows  is  authentic.  The  increasing 
number  of  these  narrations  became  at  length  a  burden  to  the 
best  memory,  and  it  was  found  necessary  to  write  down  the 
more  ancient  of  them  lest  they  should  be  forgotten.  One  of 
the  first  and  most  important  of  these  collections  was  Ibn 
Ishak's  History  of  the  Moslim  Wars,  a  work  of  which  we 
possess  but  a  small  portion,  containing  the  life  of  Muhammad, 
with  notes  and  additions  by  a  later  editor,  Ibn  Hish&m ;  this 
is  a  book  of  the  highest  authority,  and  deservedly  so,  but  it 
is  unfortunately  of  great  rareness.  The  history  of  Islamisrn, 
by  At-Tabari,  was  formed  also  in  a  similar  manner;  being 
merely  a  collection  of  individual  narrations  preceded  by  their 
isndds;  many  of  them  relate  to  the  same  event,  and  from 
their  mutual  comparison  a  very  complete  idea  can  be  acquired 
of  the  history  of  that  early  period.  These  collections  of 
original  documents  were  consulted  by  later  historians,  such 
as  Ibn  Al-Ianzi,  Ibn  Al-Athir,  and  others,  and  it  was  from 
these  sources  that  they  drew  the  facts  set  forth  in  their 
respective  works.  It  may  be  laid  down  ks  a  general  principle 
that  Islamic  history  assumed  at  first  the  form  of  a  collection 
of  statements,  each  of  them  authenticated  by  an  isndd;  then 
came  a  writer  who  combined  these  accounts,  but  suppressed 
the  isndds  and  the  repetitions ;  he  was  followed  by  the  maker 
of  abridgments,  who  condensed  the  work  of  his  predecessor 
and  furnished  a  less  expensive  book  on  the  same  subject." J 

The  method  followed  by  Mohammedan  historians  in  the 
composition  of  their  works  compelled  them  from  the  first  to 
exercise  a  certain  kind  and  measure  of  historical  criticism. 
1  Ibn  Khallikan's  Biographical  Dictionary :  Introduction,  pp.  xxi,  xxii. 


ARABIC    HISTORIANS  81 

Proceeding  on  a  recognition  of  the  supreme  importance  of  the 
testimony  of  the  primary  witnesses,  it  required  an  examination 
of  the  claims  of  those  who  passed  for  such.  The  Mohammedan 
historian  could  not  fail  to  perceive  that  he  was  bound  to  satisfy 
himself  as  to  the  credibility  of  the  persons  whose  reports  he 
collected  and  recorded.  But  he  was  content  to  discharge  this 
duty  in  a  very  perfunctory  manner.  He  deemed  it  enough  to 
know  on  merely  general  and  external  grounds  that  they  were 
men  of  good  reputation,  without  any  careful  comparison  and 
sifting  examination  of  their  reports  themselves.  We  cannot 
credit  the  Arabic  historians  with  the  knowledge  or  practice 
of  historical  criticism  in  its  modern  sense.  Wakidi,  Tabari, 
Coteiba,  Mas'udi,  were  unacquainted  with  it.  Ibn  Khaldun 
stood  almost  alone  in  clearly  apprehending  its  nature  and 
realising  its  importance.  There  was  no  lack  of  need  for  its 
exercise.  An  enormous  number  of  false  traditions  were  early 
in  circulation ;  genealogies  were  at  an  early  date  largely  fabri- 
cated ;  the  early  chroniclers  readily  accepted  fictions  as  facts 
whenever  they  tended  to  glorify  the  Prophet  and  his  followers. 
At  a  later  period,  works  deliberately  falsifying  history  were 
written  to  serve  some  immediate  purpose,  and  ascribed  to  early 
annalists  of  good  repute.  A  number  of  writings  on  which 
European  authors  have  founded  as  genuine  productions  of  the 
older  Mohammedan  historians  are  spurious  or  mendaciously 
corrupted.  For  example,  the  Account  of  the  Conquest  of 
Syria,  attributed  to  Wakidi,  on  which  the  first  part  of  Ock- 
ley's  well-known  book  is  chiefly  based,  must  have  been  writ- 
ten in  the  time  of  the  Crusades ;  and  so  also  the  Historical 
Notices  on  the  Spiritual  and  Temporal  Powers  attributed  to 
Coteiba,  and  unfortunately  relied  on  as  his  by  Gayangos, 
Weil,  and  Amari. 

In  the  second  century  of  the  Mohammedan  era  Hisham  was 
the  most  renowned  of  the  genealogists.  Until  recent  research 
cast  suspicion  on  the  whole  assumption  of  the  soundness  of 
the  Arabic  genealogical  system,  he  was  credited  with  having 
laid  a  solid  foundation  for  the  labours  of  his  successors. 
Ma'mar  (ben  el-Muthana),  who  died  in  209  a.h.  (821  a.d.), 
published  about  200  works,  the  most  important  of  which 
treated  of  historical  subjects.     He  wrote  a  history  of  Mecca 


82  INTRODUCTION 

and  of  Medina,  but  showed,  like  so  many  Arabic  historiogra- 
phers, a  marked  preference  for  themes  relating  to  war.  In  one 
of  his  writings  he  commemorated  1200  of  the  days  on  which 
the  Arabs  had  been  engaged  in  battle.  He  was  himself  of 
Jewish-Persian  descent,  and  although  he  had  in  various  writ- 
ings glorified  the  achievements  of  the  Arabs,  he  gave  free  ex- 
pression to  his  hatred  of  themselves,  and  thereby  caused  great 
offence.  His  contemporary,  Wakidi  (d.  207  A.H.),  enjoyed 
immense  popularity  in  his  lifetime,  and  his  fame  as  an  his- 
torian has  in  the  East  never  waned.  He  was  a  man  of  inde- 
fatigable diligence.  He  is  said  to  have  kept  two  slaves  con- 
stantly employed  in  copying  and  transcribing  for  him,  and  to 
have  left  books  filling  600  chests,  each  of  which  required  two 
men  to  carry  it.  A  History  of  Mohammedan  Conquests  is 
his  most  important  work,  and  it  is  an  excellent,  almost  typi- 
cal, example  of  the  Arabic  historiography  of  the  time. 

Literature  in  many  forms  was  cultivated  with  great  zeal 
and  success  in  Mohammedan  lands  during  the  third  century 
after  the  Flight  (815-912  a.d.).  Among  the  historians  of  the 
period  it  may  suffice  to  mention  only  Bochari,  Coteiba,  and 
Tabari.  Bochari  acquired  high  fame  as  a  commentator  on  the 
Koran,  and  became  the  most  eminent  authority  on  the  subject 
of  tradition.  He  wrote  a  work  known  as  the  Great  History, 
on  the  trustworthy  and  untrustworthy  traditionists ;  and  drew 
up  the  Kit&b  as-Sahih,  a  collection  of  7275  traditions  which 
he  regarded  as  genuine.  The  latter  is  said  to  have  cost  him 
sixteen  years'  labour,  and  its  contents  to  have  been  selected 
from  a  mass  of  600,000  traditions.  The  traditions  accepted 
by  Bochari  are  generally  received  by  Mohammedans  without 
question,  his  discrimination  and  fairness  of  judgment  being 
deemed  by  them  to  have  been  as  extraordinary  as  his  memory 
and  erudition.  Coteiba  was  a  man  of  varied  literary  gifts,  and 
particularly  distinguished  as  a  philologist  and  exegete.  His 
'Book  of  Facts,'  or,  as  Wustenfeld  its  editor  calls  it,  'Hand- 
book of  History,'  and  his  '  Exquisite  Histories,'  are  allowed  to 
be  characterised  by  exceptional  keenness  and  comprehensive- 
ness of  research  and  accuracy  and  elegance  of  statement.  He 
showed  great  good  sense  in  avoiding  diffuseness,  refraining 
from  useless  repetitions,  and  silently  rejecting  uncertified  tra- 


ARABIC   HISTORIANS  83 

ditions.  Tabari  was  born  in  224  and  died  in  310  of  the 
Hegira.  His  Commentary  on  the  Koran  is  deemed  by  some 
judges  an  even  greater  work  than  his  Annals ;  but,  however 
this  may  be,  the  latter  work  has  made  his  name  one  of  the 
most  renowned  and  esteemed  in  Arabic  historiography.  It 
may  be  reckoned  the  first  General  History  written  from  the 
Mohammedan  point  of  view.  It  began  with  the  creation  and 
ended  with  302  a.h.  (914  a.d.).  It  was  planned  on  the 
largest  scale,  and  executed  with  great  skill  and  ability,  with 
unsparing  toil,  with  vast  information,  wifh  independence  of 
judgment,  with  attractiveness  of  style.  It  was  a  collection 
of  historical  traditions  and  documents  so  ample  yet  judicious, 
and  so  aptly  combined,  that  it  was  at  once  recognised  as  a 
substitute  for  many,  and  a  supplement  to  all,  previous  histori- 
cal works.  The  study  of  general  history  had  been  not  only 
neglected  by  the  early  Moslims,  but  purposely  shunned  as 
unlawful  and  dangerous.  This  prejudice  was  in  course  of 
time  overcome ;  and  after  the  appearance  of  Tabari's  Annals, 
general  surveys  of  history  became  common.  Of  course,  the 
authors  of  such  surveys  all  assumed  that  the  triumph  of  Islam 
was  the  goal  of  history.  Their  guiding  thread  through  the 
ancient  world  was  the  succession  of  generations,  and  espe- 
cially the  succession  of  prophets,  from  Adam  to  Mohammed, 
as  represented  in  the  Hebrew  records  and  Arabic  or  Persian 
traditions.  The  Mohammedan  view  of  ancient  history  had 
all  the  defects  of  the  medieval  Christian  view,  with  others 
peculiarly  its  own.  Tabari's  work  had  the  fault  of  being  far 
too  long.  The  Arabic  mode  of  writing  history  necessarily 
tended  to  excessive  bulk,  and  its  accompaniment  excessive 
cost.  Hence  there  was  a  demand  for  abridgments,  and  these 
often  practically  displaced  the  works  which  they  summarised. 
With  all  its  reputation  and  merits,  the  Chronicle  of  Tabari 
fell  almost  into  oblivion  after  it  had  been  abridged  and  con- 
tinued by  El-Makin  (Elmacin).  Considerable  portions  of  it 
have  been  translated  into  Latin  by  Kosegarten,  into  French 
by  Dubeux,'and  into  German  by  Noldeke. 

Another  historical  writer  of  great  celebrity  was  Mas'udi, 
whose  life  fell  mostly  within  the  tenth  century  of  our  era,  as 
he  died  in  345  or  346  a.h.    He  has  been  likened  to  Herodotus ; 


84  INTRODUCTION 

and  he  cannot  be  denied  to  have  had  a  curiosity  as  active  and 
universal,  and  to  have  acquired  an  even  larger  stock  of  knowl- 
edge of  all  kinds.  He  spent  a  large  portion  of  his  life  in 
travelling,  and  yet  left  an  enormous  mass  of  writing.  He 
visited  India,  Ceylon,  China,  Madagascar,  South  Arabia, 
Persia,  the  regions  about  the  Caspian  Sea,  Russia,  Syria, 
Egypt,  Morocco,  and  Spain ;  and  wherever  he  went,  geography, 
manners,  politics,  religion,  and  history,  were  alike  the  objects 
of  his  eager  investigation.  He  embodied  the  results  in  a 
'  History  of  the  Times,'  the  wonder  and  delight  of  the  East, 
yet  so  vast  that  it  has  never  been  printed.  He,  however, 
abridged  it  under  the  title  of  '  Meadows  of  Gold  and  Mines 
of  Gems,'  and  on  this  abridgment  his  fame  chiefly  rests.1  He 
showed  little  skill  in  methodising  the  enormous  stores  of  in- 
formation which  he  had  accumulated.  His  transitions  from 
one  subject  to  another  are  often  most  arbitrary.  He  was  devoid 
of  the  artistic  sense  which  enabled  Herodotus  to  combine  his 
varied  materials  into  an  admirable,  almost  dramatic,  whole. 
He  lacked  also  his  simple  grace  and  exquisite  naturalness  of 
style.  As  he  was  even  less  critical  and  more  credulous  than 
Herodotus,  he  received  on  hearsay  as  facts  a  host  of  fables. 
Yet  his  work  was  highly  valuable,  greatly  increasing  the  sum 
of  historical  knowledge,  and  even  displaying  more  genuine 
historical  interest  and  ability  than  any  work  produced  in 
Europe  in  the  same  century.  The  mere  indication,  however, 
of  the  variety  and  distribution  of  its  contents  may  be  more 
instructive  than  further  description.  The  first  six  chapters 
give  an  account,  drawn  from  the  Hebrew  Scriptures,  the  Koran, 
and  oriental  traditions,  of  the  period  between  the  creation  of 
the  world  and  the  birth  of  Mohammed,  which,  ludicrous  and 
legendary  as  it  in  great  part  is,  is  of  the  same  character  as 
what  still  passes  in  Mohammedan  lands  for  true  history.  The 
seventh  chapter  treats  of  the  Hindus,  their  scientific  knowl- 
edge, their  religious  opinions,  and  their  various  governments, 
but  shows  complete  ignorance  of  their  early  history.  It  is 
followed  by  seven  chapters  (8-14)  mainly  relating'to  physical 
and  historical  geography,  but  including  not  a  few  digressions 
and  marvellous  stories.     The  fifteenth  chapter  is  on  China, 

l  Macondi,  Les  prairies  d'or.    Texte  et  traduction  par  C.  Barbier  de  Maynard 
et  Pavet  de  Courteille.    T.  i.-ix.    Paris,  1861-77. 


ARABIC   HISTORIANS  85 

and  admirably  appreciative  of  the  character,  religion,  and 
polity  of  its  people,  although  the  views  which  it  gives  of  early 
Chinese  history  are  quite  mythical.     The  next  chapter  is  a 
strange  medley  on  seas  and  islands,  Spain  and  other  countries, 
and  perfumes.     It  is  followed  by  one  which  contains  much 
valuable  information  regarding  the  Caucasian  regions  and  their 
inhabitants,  and  a  good  deal  which  is  merely  curious  about 
apes  and  falcons.    Then  come  seven  chapters  (18-24)  weighted 
with  matter  imperfectly  sifted,  on  the  Assyrian  and  Persian 
kings.     They  are  succeeded  by  three  chapters,  respectively 
on  the  Greeks  and  their  history,  Alexander  in  India,  and  the 
Greek  kings  after  Alexander.     And  these  are  followed  up  by 
three  relating  to  the  Roman  Empire  —  the  first  treating  of  the 
period  before  Christianity  was  acknowledged  as  the  State 
religion,  the  second  of  the  Byzantine  emperors  prior  to  the 
rise  of  Islam,  and  the  third  of  the  emperors  who  reigned  from 
that  date  to  the  time  when  Mas'udi  wrote.     Egypt  and  Alex- 
andria are  dealt  with  in  two  chapters  (31-32)  ;  the  Sudanese, 
Slavonians,  Franks,  and  Lombards,  in  one  each  (33-36).     The 
•chapters  on  the  Adites  (37),  on  the  Themudites  (38),  and  on 
Mecca  and  the  Ka'aba  (39),  may  be  regarded  as  forming  an- 
other group.     They  are  followed  by  a  general  discourse  on  the 
various  countries  of  the  earth,  and  on  love  to  the  native  soil 
(40).     The  next  five  chapters  relate  to  Yemen  and  its  history. 
The  succeeding  six  form  a  treasury  of  information  on  the 
manners,  customs,  superstitions,  and  folk-lore  of  the  Arabs. 
After  giving  an  account  of  Seil  el  'Arem  (53),  Mas'udi  intro- 
duces an  erudite  and  elaborate  dissertation  on  the  months  of 
the  Arabs,  Kopts,  Syrians,  and  Parsis,  on  the  revolutions  of 
the  sun  and  moon,  and  on  opinions  as  to  the  influence  of  the 
heavenly  bodies  (54-62).     With  equal  fulness  he  treats  of  the 
sacred  houses  of  the  Hindus,  Greeks,  Romans,  Slavonians, 
Sabaeans,  and  Magians  (63-68).     The  sixty -ninth  chapter  is 
a  conspectus  of  chronology  from  the  beginning  of  history  to 
the  birth  of  Mohammed.      Five  chapters  are  occupied  with 
Mohammed  —  his  descent,  his  deeds,  his   mission,  and  his 
doctrines.     The  last  sixty-seven  chapters  are  a  history  of  the 
Khalifats  to  the  end  of  the  ninth  century. 

During  five  centuries  after  the  death  of  Mas'udi,  Arabic 


86  INTRODUCTION 

historiography  continued  to  be  diligently  cultivated.  It  was, 
perhaps,  the  last  branch  of  Mohammedan  literature  to  wither 
and  decay.  In  all  these  centuries  there  were  writers  who 
attempted  to  compose  universal  histories  on  the  model  of  that 
of  Tabari,  and  to  combine  geography  and  physical  science 
generally  with  history  after  the  manner  of  Mas'udi.  There 
were  others  who  rendered  eminent  services  by  working  within 
narrower  and  more  definite  limits,  as,  e.g.,  Biruni  (f  1038 
a.d.)  1  by  his  researches  into  the  history  of  India,  and  Abdal- 
latif  (f  1231  a.d.),  whose  well-known  description  of  Egypt  is 
very  remarkable  for  the  naturalness  and  simplicity  of  its 
style,  and  the  fulness  and  accuracy  of  its  information.  Local 
history  received  much  attention,  and  such  towns  as  Damascus, 
Bagdad,  Ispaham,  &c,  were  the  subjects  of  most  voluminous 
works.  Biography  was  especially  popular.  Even  biographi- 
cal dictionaries  were  numerous.  Most  of  them  were  special, 
some  treating  of  the  companions  of  Mohammed,  or  of  the  per- 
sons mentioned  in  the  collections  of  traditions  ;  others,  of  the 
princes  of  a  particular  dynasty,  or  of  the  famous  men  of  a 
particular  city,  or  of  classes  of  celebrated  persons — as,  e.g.,  of 
theologians,  jurists,  philosophers,  physicians,  or  poets.  Others 
were  general.  Of  these  the  most  successful  was  the  Bio- 
graphical Dictionary  of  Ibn  Khallikan  (f  1282  A.D.),  whom 
Sir  William  Jones  has  pronounced  to  be  perhaps  the  best 
writer  of  lives,  "et  certe"  copiosior  Nepote,  elegantior  Plu- 
tarcho,  Laertio  juncundior."  Shahrastani  (f  1153  a.d.)  de- 
serves to  be  gratefully  remembered  for  his  '  Book  of  Religious 
and  Philosophical  Sects.'  2 

While  Arabic  historiography  was  not  devoid  of  obvious 
merits,  it  never  reached  the  scientific  or  philosophical  stage. 
Among  the  many  who  cultivated  it,  none  got  much  beyond 
mere  description  and  annalistic  narration.  Athir  (1160-1232 
a.d.),  the  author  of  a  Universal  History  or  Chronicle,  edited 
in  ,14  vols,  and  partially  translated  (into  Swedish)  by  Torn- 
berg,  probably  comes  nearest  being  an  exception  to  this  state- 
ment.    He  was  not  content  merely  to  relate  events  in  the 

1  His  '  Chronology  of  Ancient  Nations '  has  been  translated  into  English  by 
C.  E.  Sachau.    Loudon,  1878. 

2  Edited  by  Cureton,  London,  1846,  and  translated  into  German  by  Haar- 
briicker,  Halle,  1850-51. 


HISTORICAL   IDEAS  87 

order  of  their  occurrence,  but  sought  also  to  discover  and 
exhibit  their  natural  antecedents  and  consequences.  Farther 
than  this,  however,  he  did  not  go  ;  he  made  no  endeavour  to 
obtain  an  insight  into  the  evolution  of  the  general  ideas  which 
pervade  history,  and  of  the  operations  of  those  deeper  causes 
of  social  change  by  which  its  immediate  and  visible  causes 
are  called  into  existence  or  conditioned  in  their  action. 

As  regards  the  science  or  philosophy  of  history,  Arabic 
literature  was  adorned  by  one  most  brilliant  name.  Neither 
the  classical  nor  the  medieval  Christian  world  can  show  one 
of  nearly  the  same  brightness.  Ibn  Khaldun  (a.d.  1332- 
1406),  considered  simply  as  an  historian  had  superiors  even 
among  Arabic  authors,  but  as  a  theorist  on  history  he  had 
no  equal  in  any  age  or  country  until  Vico  appeared,  more 
than  three  hundred  years  later.  Plato,  Aristotle,  and  Au- 
gustine were  not  his  peers,  and  all  others  were  unworthy  of 
being  even  mentioned  along  with  him.  He  was  admirable 
alike  by  his  originality  and  sagacity,  his  profundity  and  his 
comprehensiveness.  He  was,  however,  a  man  apart,  as  soli- 
tary and  unique  among  his  co-religionists  and  contemporaries 
in  the  department  of  historical  philosophy  as  was  Dante  in 
poetry  or  Roger  Bacon  in  science  among  theirs.  Arabic  his- 
torians had,  indeed,  collected  the  materials  which  he  could 
use,  but  he  alone  used  them.  Of  this  remarkable  man,  how- 
ever, and  of  his  views  on  history,  I  shall  treat  at  some  length 
in  the  last  section  of  this  Introduction. 


IV 

The  growth  of  history  towards  a  scientific  stage  has  been 
partly  the  consequence  and  partly  the  cause  of  the  growth  of 
certain  ideas,  without  a  firm  and  comprehensive  grasp  of  which 
no  philosophical  study  or  conception  of  history  is  possible.  It 
seems  necessary  to  indicate  what  has  been  the  history  of  some 
of  the  more  important  of  these  ideas,  to  the  period  when  our 
account  of  the  development  of  the  philosophy  of  history  begins. 
Farther,  there  is  no  need  at  present  to  go,  as  their  later  history 
is  included  in  that  of  the  philosophy  of  history  itself. 

By  ideas  is  not  here  meant  anything  mysterious  or  meta- 


88  INTKODUCTION 

physical,  but  only  general  thoughts  which  connect  and  render 
intelligible  a  certain  number  of  facts.  There  must  be  general 
thoughts,  there  must  be  appropriate  ideas,  before  facts  are  in- 
telligible. This  is  in  no  real  contradiction  to  the  obvious  truth 
that  thoughts  are  only  general  in  virtue  of  being  thoughts  of 
so  many  facts ;  that  ideas  are  only  appropriate  in  virtue  of 
being  appropriate  to  the  facts.  Professor  Roscher  of  Leipsic 
points  out,  in  his  work  on  Thucydides,  how  that  great  historian's 
usual  explanation  of  things  amounts  to  this  —  A  is  the  cause 
of  B,  and  B  is  the  cause  of  A.  And  it  is  more  or  less  so  with 
all  great  historians.  It  is  only  narrow  and  meagre  pragmati- 
cal historians,  or  rather  historical  logicians,  who  affirm  rigidly 
and  invariably  That  A  is  the  cause  of  B,  B  of  C,  and  C  of  D, 
&c.  Wherever  there  is  an  organism  like  a  living  body,  the 
mind  of  man,  or  even  a  society,  —  wherever  there  is  correlation 
•of  parts  and  functions  —  wherever  there  is  action  and  reaction, 

—  the  single  linear  series  of  causes  and  effects  is  not  found. 
A  is  the  cause  of  B  and  B  of  A,  inconsistent  as  it  may  seem 
to  be,  is  then  often  a  truer  formula  than  A  is  the  cause  of  B 
and  B  of  C,  consistent  as  it  may  seem  to  be.  The  case  in 
hand  is  an  instance.  Without  facts,  no  ideas.  Without  ideas, 
virtually  no  facts ;  nothing  that  is  a  fact  for  thought ;  nothing 
that  the  mind  can  make  any  use  of. 

I.  One  of  the  most  important  of  the  ideas  referred  to  is  that 
of  progress.  The  philosophy  of  history  deals  not  exclusively 
but  to  a  great  extent  with  laws  of  progress,  with  laws  of  evo- 
lution ;  and  until  the  idea  of  progress  was  firmly  and  clearly 
apprehended,  little  could  be  done  in  it.  Now  the  history  of 
that  idea,  within  the  period  which  at  present  concerns  us,  is 
nearly  as  follows. 

In  the  oriental  world  it  was  unknown,  or  denied,  or  appre- 
hended only  in  an  exceedingly  limited  degree.  The  common 
assertion  that  the  diametrically  opposite  idea  of  deterioration 

—  the  belief  that  the  course  of  human  affairs  is  from  good  to 
bad  and  from  bad  to  worse  —  pervaded  all  Asiatic  thought, 
whether  religious  or  political,  is  undoubtedly  an  exaggeration. 
The  safe  affirmation  is  that  a  definite  general  view  of  history 
was  seldom  formed,  and,  where  formed,  was  very  rarely  indeed, 
if  ever,  that  of  a  progressive  development. 


IDEA   OF   PKOGRESS  89 

It  was  not  to  be  expected  that  such  an  idea  should  originate 
and  prevail  in  China.  No  one,  it  is  true,  who  has  felt  interest 
enough  in  that  singular  nation  to  study  the  researches  and 
translations  of  Remusat,  Panthier,  Julien,  Legge,  Plath,  Faber, 
Eitel,  and  others,  will  hesitate  to  dismiss  as  erroneous  the 
commonplace  that  it  has  been  an  unprogressive  nation.  The 
development  and  filiation  of  thought  is  scarcely  less  traceable  • 
in  the  history  and  literature  of  China  than  of  Greece ;  and 
genuine  Chinese  historiography,  unperverted  and  uncorrupted 
by  the  mythological  fictions  of  Buddhism,  makes  no  extrava- 
gant pretensions  either  as  to  the  antiquity  or  dignity  of  the 
national  origin,  but,  with  rare  honesty  and  sobriety  of  judg- 
ment goes  back  to  the  small  and  barbarous  horde  in  the  forests 
and  mountains  of  Shensee,  which  Footsoushe  began  to  reduce 
to  settled  order  rather  more  than  three  thousand  years  before 
the  Christian  era.  Development  has  been,  however,  for  very 
long  slower  in  China  than  anywhere  else,  periods  of  decadence 
have  been  more  numerous,  reverence  for  the  past  has  been 
stronger  and  more  confirmed,  while  the  power  of  generalisa- 
tion, the  ability  to  take  comprehensive  views,  is  just  the  qual- 
ity in  which  the  Chinese  mind,  in  many  respects  admirably 
endowed,  is  most  deficient.  Among  the  Chinese,  as  among 
the  Egyptians,  Babylonians,  and  Hindus,  the  theory  of  cosmi- 
cal  and  human  cycles  has  appeared  in  various  forms.  As  the 
observation  of  history,  however,  seems  to  have  had  almost 
nothing  to  do  with  its  formation,  I  content  myself  with  refer- 
ring any  one  who  feels  an  interest  in  it  to  the  articles  of 
Remusat  in  the  -  Journal  des  Savants '  (Oct.,  Nov.,  Dec, 
1831),  and  to  the  learned  and  curious  dissertation  of  P. 
Leroux  in  his  '  De  rHumanite" '  (t.  ii.  ch.  viii.). 

In  India,  where  human  existence  was  regarded  as  a  mere 
stage  in  the  course  of  transmigration,  where  the  sense  of  the 
evil  and  transitoriness  of  life  has  for  ages  had  an  intensity  and 
depth  the  European  mind  can  perhaps  hardly  realise,  — in 
India,  the  home  of  pantheism,  fatalism,  and  caste,  — the 
•thought  of  social  progress  and  its  inspiring  hopes  could  never 
possess  the  heart.  Instead,  there  was  the  mythical  dream  of 
vast  chronological  cycles,  each  divisible  into  four  epochs, 
which  are  the  stages  through  which  the  universe  and  its  in- 


90  INTRODUCTION 

habitants  must  pass  from  perfection  to  destruction,  from 
strength  and  innocence  to  weakness  and  depravity,  until  a 
new  mahd-yuga  or  great  cycle  begins. 

The  old  Ormazd  religion  gave  expression  to  the  hope  that 
evil  would  not  last  for  ever,  —  that  the  Power  of  Darkness 
would  cease  on  some  predestined  day  to  struggle  with  his 
righteous  adversary,  and  bow  to  his  authority,  and  neither 
will  nor  work  wickedness  any  more ;  but  it  did  so  only  fitfully 
and  feebly,  sometimes  suggesting  the  opposite,  and  never 
connecting  with  the  hope  of  the  final  victory  of  goodness  any 
doctrine  of  gradual  progress. 

The  religion  of  Israel  was  of  its  very  nature  a  religion  of 
the  future,  a  religion  of  hope.  Expectation  was  throughout 
its  attitude ;  it  in  all  its  parts  pointed  forward  beyond  itself ; 
from  generation  to  generation  its  voice  was  that  of  one  cry- 
ing, Prepare.  Still  there  is  no  evidence  of  the  ancient  Jews 
having  attained  to  a  conscious  apprehension  of  the  idea  of 
progress,  noxus-there-any  distinct-enunciation  of  that  idea-ia- 
the  Old  Testament;. 

It  is  often  said,  and  even  by  those  who  ought  to  know  much 
better,  that  the  Greeks  and  Romans  conceived  of  the  course 
of  history  only  as  a  downward  movement,  whereas,  in  fact, 
they  conceived  of  it  in  all  ways  —  i.e.,  as  a  process  of  deterio- 
ration, a  progress,  and  a  cycle,  although  in  none  profoundly  or 
consistently.  The  natural  illusion  of  the  individual  that  the 
days  of  his  boyhood  were  brighter  and  better  than  those  of  his 
maturity,  is  also  an  illusion  natural  to  the  race,  natural  to 
nations,  one  which  many  circumstances  seem  to  confirm,  one 
which  can  only  be  adequately  corrected  by  such  a  survey  of 
bygone  generations  as  antiquity  had  not  the  power  to  make ; 
and  the  thought  of  a  deterioration  of  human  life  from  age  to 
age  certainly  often  meets  us  in  the  literatures  of  Greece  and 
Rome,  as  was  to  be  expected.  But  the  obtrusively  manifest 
fact  that  the  origins  of  all  things,  so  far  as  they  could  be 
traced,  were  small  and  feeble  —  the  knowledge  of  the  exist- 
ence of  various  rude  and  savage  peoples,  the  abundant  evi- 
dences which  a  Greek  of  the  age  of  Pericles,  or  a  Roman  of 
the  age  of  Augustus,  possessed,  of  the  civilisation  he  enjoyed 
having  been  evolved  out  of  a  comparatively  barbarous  social 


IDEA   OF   PROGRESS  91 

state,  suggested  also  to  many  thoughtful  minds  of  the  classical 
world  the  notion  of  progress.  And  the  circular  movements 
of  the  stars,  the  cycles  of  changes  through  which  the  lives  of 
all  plants  and  animals  pass  from  birth  to  death,  and  fatalistic 
and  pantheistic  principles,  led  to  the  inference  that  the  events 
of  human  history  fall  into  circuits,  which  resemble  or  repeat 
one  another.  It  is  necessary  to  establish  this  by  indicating 
the  most  interesting  and  decisive  proof -passages. 

Through  the  '  Works  and  Days '  of  Hesiod  there  breathes 
the  feeling  that  the  youth  and  glory  of  the  world  has  passed 
away ;  that  man  has  fallen ;  that  the  race  is  not  what  it  was ; 
that  existence,  once  easy,  innocent,  joyous,  has  become  diffi- 
cult, pervaded  by  evil,  full  of  woes.  And  this  change  for 
the  worse,  this  "  fall,"  is  explained  by  two  myths,  which  seem 
inconsistent  with  each  other:  the  one,  perhaps  of  Semitic 
origin,  introduced  into  Greece  through  Phoenicia,  tracing  the 
toils  and  miseries  of  life  to  the  box  of  Pandora  and  Prome- 
theus's  theft  of  fire  from  heaven ; 1  while  the  other,  which  is 
widely  diffused  among  the  Aryan  peoples,  refers  them  to  the 
gradual  degeneration  of  the  human  species  through  a  series 
of  ages.2  As  to  the  latter  myth,  it  is  to  be  remarked  that 
the  ages  are,  according  to  Hesiod,  the  golden,  the  silver,  the 
brazen,  the  heroic,  and  the  iron,  so  that  the  process  of  dete- 
rioration is  represented  as  not  quite  continuous,  there  being 
an  age,  named  after  no  metal,  better  than  that  which  preceded 
it,  and  thus  an  exception  to  what  is  otherwise  the  rule.  The 
most  obvious,  and  probably  the  true,  explanation  of  the 
exception  is,  that  the  heroic  age  could  not,  consistently  with 
the  traditions  which  represented  the  heroes  as  the  founders 
of  Greek  families  and  cities,  be  fitted  harmoniously  into  the 
series  represented'by  metals,  because  it  could  not  be  placed 
elsewhere  than  immediately  before  the  age  of  ordinary  mor- 
tals. Goettling  would  so  interpret  the  text  of  Hesiod  as  to 
make  it  an  expression  of  belief  in  the  theory  of  cycles,  but 
his  interpretation  seems  to  have  nothing  to  recommend  it 
except  ingenuity  in  error. 

Anaximander,  one  of  the  earliest  of  Greek  philosophers, 
working  out  his  idea  of  the  Infinite  or  Unconditioned  being 

1  'Epya  «<"  'Hfxepai,  42-105.  *  Ibid.,  109-201. 


92  INTRODUCTION 

the  first  principle  of  the  universe,  arrived  both  at  a  sort  of 
rude  nebular  hypothesis  and  a  sort  of  rude  development  hy- 
pothesis. From  the  aTreipov,  or  primitive  indeterminate  mat- 
ter, through  an  inherent  and  eternal  energy  and  movement 
the  two  original  contraries  of  heat  and  cold  separate ;  what  is 
cold  settles  down  to  the  centre  and  so  forms  the  earth,  what  is 
hot  ascends  to  the  circumference  and  so  originates  the  bright, 
shining,  fiery  bodies  of  heaven,  which  are  but  the  fragments  of 
what  once  existed  as  a  complete  shell  or  sphere,  but  in  time 
burst  and  broke  up  and  so  gave  rise  to  the  stars.  The  action 
of  the  sun's  heat  on  the  watery  earth  next  generated  films  or 
bladders,  out  of  which  came  different  kinds  of  imperfectly 
organised  beings,  which  were  gradually  developed  into  the 
animals  which  now  live.  Man's  ancestors  were  fishlike  crea- 
tures which  dwelt  in  muddy  waters,  and  only,  as  the  sun 
slowly  dried  up  the  earth,  became  gradually  fitted  for  life 
on  dry  land.1  A  similar  view  was  held  by  the  poet,  priest, 
prophet,  and  philosopher  Empedocles.  He  taught  that  out  of 
the  four  elements  of  earth,  air,  fire,  and  water,  and  under  the 
moving  power  of  Love  resisting  Hate,  plants,  animals,  and 
man  were  in  succession,  and  after  many  an  effort  and  many  a 
futile  conjunction  of  organs,  generated  and  elaborated  into 
their  present  shapes.2  This  kind  and  measure  of  belief  in 
progress  did  not,  however,  prevent  Anaximander  from  hold- 
ing also  that  generation  must  be  followed  by  destruction  in  a 
necessary  cycle,  that  "things  must  all  return  whence  they 
came  according  to  destiny;"  nor  did  it  keep  Empedocles  from 
teaching  that  the  souls  of  men  were  spirits  fallen  from  a  state 
of  bliss  in  heaven  and  doomed  to  wander  for  "  thirty  thousand 
seasons,"  tossed  from  element  to  element,  through  all  the 
changes  of  transmigration,  plant,  bird,  fish,  beast  or  human 
being,  in  this  "  over-vaulted  cave,"  this  "  gloomy  meadow  of 
discord,"  the  earth. 

With  the  theories  of  these  two  philosophers  may  be  con- 
nected what  ^Eschylus  makes  Prometheus  say  about  the  prim- 
itive state  of  men,  —  how  they  had  eyes  and  saw  not,  ears  and 

1  Plutarchus  de  Plac.  Phil.,  ii.  25,  iii.  16,  v.  19,  ap.  Buseb.  Prasp.  Evang.,  i. 
8,  &c. 

2  Mullach's  Empedodlis  Carmina,  314^316,  in  Frag.  Phil.  Gr.  or  Mlian  H.  A., 
xvi.  29,  and  Arist.  Phys.,  ii.  8. 


IDEA   OF   PROGRESS  93 

heard  not,  —  how  they  dwelt  in  the  sunless  depths  of  caves, 
were  ignorant  of  the  signs  of  the  seasons  and  the  simplest 
rudiments  of  art,  pursued  all  their  occupations  without  dis- 
cernment, and  left  their  entire  life  to  chance  and  confusion, 
till  he  taught  them  to  number,  to  write,  to  mark  the  risings 
and  the  settings  of  the  stars,  to  build  houses,  to  tame  and 
train  animals,  to  cure  diseases,  to  navigate  the  sea,  and  prac- 
tise the  various  modes  of  divination.1  Euripides  puts  similar 
language  into  the  mouth  of  Theseus  in  the  Suppliants.2 

The  oriental  doctrine  of  vast  chronological  cycles  or  world- 
years  reappeared  in  Greece,  perhaps  as  an  Orphic  legend,8  and 
certainly  as  a  tenet  of  Stoic  philosophy ;  for  the  advocates  of 
that  system,  reasoning  from  their  pantheistic  conviction  that 
God  is  the  creative  soul  of  the  world,  the  eternal  force  which 
forms  and  permeates  it,  the  spirit  of  ever-acting  and  living- 
fire,  which  manifests  itself  outwardly  as  matter  when  its  heat 
declines,  and  burns  up  matter  when  its  heat  is  intense,  con- 
cluded that  in  a  necessary  and  endless  succession  world  after 
world  was  created  and  destroyed,  each  new  world  being  ex- 
actly like  its  predecessor,  and  all  things  in  it  without  excep- 
tion running  round  in  the  same  order  from  beginning  to  end. 
In  the  words  of  Nemesius :  "  The  Stoics  taught  that  in  fixed 
periods  of  time  a  burning  and  destruction  of  all  things  take 
place,  and  the  world  returns  again  from  the  beginning  into 
the  very  same  shape  as  it  had  before,  and  that  the  restoration 
of  them  all  happens  not  once  but  often,  or  rather  that  the 
same  things  are  restored  an  infinite  number  of  times."  i 

It  is  likewise  certain  that  no  one  conception  of  the  course 
of  the  world's  histoiy  exclusively  possessed  the  Roman  mind. 
No  more  graphic  picture  of  man's  primitive  condition  as  a 
savage  state  is  to  be  found  in  any  literature,  and  no  more  in- 
genious or  consistent  conjectural  account  of  the  origination  of 
language,  laws,  customs,  institutions,  arts,  and  sciences,  than 
those  presented  in  the  last  five  hundred  and  thirty  lines  of 
the  fifth  book  of  Lucretius.5  Yet,  although  that  great  poet 
there  develops  in  its  entirety  the  theory  which  Sir  John  Lub- 

1  -Esch.  Pr.,  451-515.  2  Eur.  Supp.,  201-218. 

3  Creuzer's  Symbolik,  pt.  iii.  pp.  315-318. 

*  Nem.  de.  Nat.  Horn.,  c.  38;  Cicero,  Nat.  Deor.,  ii.  46;  Origen,  Con.  Cels.,  iv. 

5  De  Rer.  Nat.,  y.  925-1457. 


94  INTRODUCTION 

bock  and  so  many  others  are  now  urging  on  our  acceptance, 
he  elsewhere  teaches  us  that  the  world  like  all  things  mortal 
will  perish,  —  that  already  it  is  past  its  full  growth  —  can  no 
longer  produce  what  it  once  did  —  is  wasting  away,  worn  out 
by  age,  —  that  the  day  draws  near  which  shall  give  over  to 
destruction  seas,  lands,  and  heaven  :  — 

"  Multosque  per  annos 
Sustentata  ruet  moles  et  machina  mundi." x 

Ovid  gives  expression  with  great  beauty  to  the  popular  faith 
in  four  ages  of  continuous  deterioration,2  and  represents  Jove 
as  remembering  "  that  it  is  recorded  in  the  book  of  fate,  that 
the  time  will  come  when  the  sea,  and  the  earth,  and  the  palaces 
of  heaven  will  be  kindled  into  flame  and  glow  with  fervent 
heat,  and  the  laboured  structure  of  the  world  will  perish." 3 
Virgil  sings  of  a  golden  age,  a  Saturnian  time,  when  suffering 
and  sin  were  unknown,  when  men  had  all  things  in  common, 
and  Nature  poured  forth  her  bounties  abundantly  and  sponta- 
neously; but  he  believes  that  a  beneficent  purpose  underlay 
man's  fall  from  this  condition,  that  Jove  did  away  with  this  easy 
state  of  existence  in  order  that  man  might  be  forced  to  evolve 
the  resources  in  his  own  mind  and  in  outer  nature,  and  that 
experience  by  dint  of  thought  should  hammer  out  the  various 
arts  in  a  course  of  gradual  discovery  and  improvement.4  The 
poet  thus  combined  belief  in  a  fall  with  belief  in  progress ; 
perhaps  he  combined  belief  in  both  with  a  belief  in  world-cycles, 
and  he  has  certainly  given  marvellous  expression  to  the  hope 
that  the  simplicity,  peace,  and  happiness  of  the  golden  age 
would  be  restored.5     The  well-known  lines  of  Horace  — 

"Damnosa  quid  non  imminuit  dies? 
JEtas  parentum,  pejor  avis,  tulit 
Nos  nequiores,  mox  daturos 
Progenium  vitiosiorem,"  —  6 

have  been  often  quoted  as  embodying  the  single  and  entire 
feeling  of  classical  antiquity  regarding  the  course  of  humanity. 
But  they  cannot  fairly  be  understood  as  conveying  even  their 
author's  own  opinion  of  human  development  in  itself,  or  as 

1  De  Rer.  Nat.,  ii.  1148-1174;  v.  93-95.      2  Met.,  i.  89-150.      8  Ibid.,  i.  256-258. 
*  Georg.,  i.  120-149.  5  Eel.,  iv.  «  Odes,  book  iii.  ode  6. 


IDEA    OF    PROGRESS  95 

expressing  any  general  "  Weltanschauung  "  ;  they  are  merely 
the  utterance  of  complaint  against  the  religious  and  moral 
corruption  of  his  time ;  and  he  has  elsewhere  described  the 
first  men  as  mere  animals,  a  filthy  and  speechless  herd,  fighting 
with  their  nails  and  fists  for  acorns  and  lairs,  —  a  race  of  beings 
who  gradually  found  out  words,  and  gradually  learned  to 
refrain  from  theft,  adultery,  and  murder,  to  build  and  fortify 
towns,  and  establish  laws.1 

Passing  from  poets  to  prose  authors  we  find  that  Cicero, 
without  expressing  an  opinion  as  to  general  progress,  has 
declared  that  philosophy  is  progressive  ;  that  study  and  appli- 
cation are  rewarded  by  new  discoveries  ;  that  the  most  recent 
things  are  generally  the  most  precise  and  certain.2  Seneca 
has  declaimed  against  a  philosophy  which  would  aim  at  being 
useful,  against  mechanical  inventions,  wealth,  and  comfort,  in 
a  way  that  has  become  celebrated ; 3  and  yet  he  has  not  only 
insisted  on  the  past  progress  of  astronomical  science,  and 
avowed  his  belief  that  its  progress  would  continue,4  but  has 
declared  of  Nature  in  general  that  she  has  always  new  secrets 
to  disclose  to  those  who  seek  them,  that  she  unveils  her  mys- 
teries only  gradually  in  the  long  succession  of  generations  — 
and  of  truth  in  general,  that  although  we  fancy  ourselves  ini- 
tiated we  are  only  on  the  threshold  of  her  temple.6  The  elder 
Pliny  has  exhorted  us  "  firmly  to  trust  that  the  ages  go  on 
incessantly  improving."  6  And  still  more  remarkable  in  some 
respects  than  any  of  these  recognitions  of  progress  is  that 
contained  in  the  preface  to  the  '  Epitome  of  Roman  History ' 
by  Florus.  It  is  not  so  comprehensive  as  many  of  the  passages 
which  have  been  cited,  being  explicitly  confined  to  a  single 
nation;  but  it  is  obviously  drawn  more  from  history  itself, 
and  it  is  the  first  clear  enunciation  of  a  theorem  which  has 

1  Satires,  book  i.  sat.  8.  2  Academics,  i.  i ;  ii.  5 ;  De  Legibus,  i.  9. 

3  Ep.,  90.  4  Nat.  Quaest.,  vii.  25. 

5  Nat.  QuEest.,  vii.  31.  The  following  lines  of  a  tragedy— probably  Seneca's 
—  have  often  been  referred  to  as  an  unconscious  prophecy  of  the  discovery  of 

America : 

"  Venient  aonis  Bsecula  sens 
Quibus  Oceanua  vincula  rerum 
Laxet,  et  iagens  pateat  telluB, 
Tethysque  novos  detegat  orbeB; 
Nee  Bit  terris  ultima  Thule."  —Medea,  act  ii.  chorus. 

6  Hist.  Nat.,  xix.  1-4. 


96  INTRODUCTION 

since  been  presented  and  illustrated  in  numberless  ways,  — 
viz.,  that  nations  pass  through  a  succession  of  ages  similar  to 
those  of  the  individual.  "  If  any  one,"  he  says,  "  will  consider 
the  Roman  people  as  if  it  were  a  man,  and  observe  its  entire 
course,  how  it  began,  how  it  grew  up,  how  it  reached  a  certain 
youthful  bloom,  and  how  it  has  since,  as  it  were,  been  growing 
old,  he  will  find  it  to  have  four  degrees  and  stages  (quatuor 
gradus  processusque).  Its  first  age  was  under  the  kings,  and 
lasted  nearly  250  years,  during  which  it  struggled  round  its 
mother  against  its  neighbours;  this  was  its  infancy.  The 
next  extended  from  the  consulship  of  Brutus  and  Collatinus 
to  that  of  Appius  Claudius  and  Quintus  Fulvius,  a  period  of 
250  years,  during  which  it  subdued  Italy;  this  was  a  time 
entirely  given  up  to  war,  and  may  be  called  its  youth.  Thence 
to  the  time  of  Caesar  Augustus  was  a  period  of  200  years,  in 
which  it  reduced  to  subjection  the  whole  world;  this  may 
accordingly  be  called  the  manhood",  and,  as  it  were,  the  robust 
maturity,  of  the  empire.  From  Caesar  Augustus  to  our  own 
age  is  a  period  of  little  less  than  200  years,  in  which  through 
the  inactivity  of  the  Caesars  the  nation  has,  as  it  were,  grown 
old  and  feeble,  except  that  now  under  the  sway  of  Trajan  it 
raises  its  arms,  and,  contrary  to  the  expectation  of  all,  the 
old  age  of  the  empire,  as  if  youth  were  restored  to  it,  flourishes 
with  new  vigour." 

Enough  has  now  been  said  to  prove  that  the  notion  of 
progress  in  history  was  far  from  unknown  to  the  thinkers  of 
Greece  and  Rome,  but  was  one  of  various  notions  of  human 
development,  all  not  unfrequently  entertained ;  and  to  show 
at  the  same  time  that  it  was  only  apprehended  in  a  vague,  gen- 
eral way  —  never  denned,  never  analysed,  and  especially  never 
satisfactorily  derived  from  a  sufficiency  of  appropriate  facts. 
Often  as  we  meet  with  it  in  classical  antiquity,  we  never  find 
it  in  a  form  which  shows  that  it  had  been  comprehended  with 
scientific  precision  and  thoroughness.  It  is  not  otherwise  as 
regards  early  Christian  and  medieval  writers,  among  whom 
the  notion  was  never  wholly  lost,  yet  never  so  apprehended 
as  the  philosophy  of  history  presupposes  and  requires.  A  few 
sentences  will  suffice  to  show  this. 

It  was  no  part  of  the  mission  of  Christ  or  of  His  apostles  to 


IDEA   OF   PROGRESS  97 

teach  the  full  truth  on  such  a  subject  as  historical  progress ; 
but  it  came  within  their  purpose  to  indicate  the  general  rela- 
tion of  the  Gospel  to  the  past  state,  actual  wants,  and  future 
destiny  of  man.  And  the  antithesis  of  the  Sermon  on  the 
Mount,  the  general  reasoning  of  the  Epistle  to  the  Hebrews, 
the  principles  involved  in  several  of  St.  Paul's  arguments,  and 
some  of  his  explicit  statements,  affirm  or  imply  that  the  Gospel, 
although  a  power  descended  from  heaven,  had  been  prepared 
for  on  earth  from  the  beginning  of  history,  and  had  appeared 
only  when  the  fulness  of  the  time  was  come  ;  and  that  there  had 
been  certain  stages  of  progress  in  revelation,  a  certain  wisely 
graduated  divine  education  of  at  least  a  portion  of  mankind, 
conditioned  by  their  capacities,  adapted  to  their  necessities, 
and  completed  and  crowned  by  absolute  truth  and  a  perfect 
life  in  Christ.  Again,  another  class  of  passages,  and  especially 
the  parables  of  the  kingdom,  declared  that  the  manifestation  of 
God  in  His  Son  was  to  be  as  a  seed,  which,  although  it  might 
appear  to  human  eye  feeble  and  insignificant,  had  an  imperish- 
able and  inexhaustible  life  in  it,  which  would  not  fail  to  survive 
any  treatment,  to  overcome  all  obstacles,  and  gradually  grow 
and  progress  till  the  result  marvellously  surpassed  even  hope 
and  imagination,  and  was  to  operate  in  humanity  like  leaven 
in  meal  till  the  whole  mass  was  transformed. 

This  teaching  applied  directly  only  to  man  in  his  moral  and 
religious  relations,  and  did  not  contain  even  in  germ  a  doctrine 
of  his  industrial,  scientific,  aesthetic,  or  political  development, 
although  not  only  consistent  with  but  calculated  to  lead  on  to 
the  true  doctrine  thereof.  Its  being  thus  limited  was  fitted 
to  secure  its  being  understood,  but  failed  to  attain  that  end, 
as,  unfortunately,  from  the  first  what  had  been  spoken  of  the 
kingdom  of  God  was  misinterpreted  as  referring  to  the  Church, 
or  rather  the  kingdom  of  God  was  identified  with  the  Church ; 
and  thus  the  glorious  and  comprehensive  truth  set  forth  in 
the  parables  of  the  kingdom  was  for  centuries  either  ignored 
or  sadly  narrowed  and  perverted,  and  is,  in  fact,  very  defec- 
tively apprehended  even  at  the  present  day. 

The  Gnostics,  while  accepting  Christianity  as  a  divine  and 
redemptive  work,  sought  to  rise  above  it  by  explaining  it  on 
the  principles  of  oriental  speculation,  and  by  furnishing  the 


98  INTRODUCTION 

complete  solution  of  all  the  deepest  problems  of  religious 
thought, — -such  as,  how  the  material  is  related  to  the  spirit- 
ual universe ;  how  the  former  exists,  and  how  the  latter  has 
been  developed;  how  evil  is  to  be  accounted  for;  whither 
all  things  tend;  what  man's  place,  purpose,  and  destiny  are; 
and  what  the  religions  which  preceded  Christianity  meant 
and  effected.  They  touched,  in  consequence,  upon  many  of 
the  most  serious  themes  of  historical  as  well  as  of  religious 
philosophy.  But  it  was  in  a  false,  arbitrary,  fantastic  way, 
so  perversive  of  historical  facts  and  so  incompatible  with 
genuine  historical  generalisation,  that  all  their  daring  con- 
ceptions of  evolution,  emanations,  aeons,  dualism,  &c,  can 
scarcely  be  said  to  have  even  helped  towards  a  clearer  and 
truer  apprehension  of  the  notion  of  human  progress. 

The  Montanists  deemed  Christianity  incomplete  even  as  a 
revelation,  and  proclaimed  a  special  and  more  perfect  dis- 
pensation, the  reign  of  the  promised  Paraclete.  Tertullian, 
the  most  gifted  among  them,  applied  the  idea  of  progressive 
development  in  defence  of  his  heresy  to  the  whole  history  of 
religion  in  the  following  remarkable  manner:  "In  the  works 
of  grace,  as  in  the  works  of  nature,  which  proceed  from  the 
same  Creator,  everything  unfolds  itself  by  certain  succes- 
sive steps.  From  the  seed-corn  sprouts  forth  first  the  shoot, 
which  by-and-by  grows  into  the  tree;  this  then  puts  forth 
the  blossom,  to  be  followed  in  its  turn  by  the  fruit,  which 
itself  arrives  at  maturity  only  by  degrees.  So  the  kingdom 
of  righteousness  unfolded  itself  by  certain  stages.  First 
came  the  fear  of  God  awakened  by  the  voice  of  nature,  with- 
out a  revealed  law ;  then  the  childhood  under  the  law  and  the 
prophets ;  then  that  of  youth  under  the  Gospel ;  and  lastly, 
the  development  to  the  ripeness  of  manhood  through  the  new 
outpouring  of  the  Holy  Ghost,  consequent  upon  the  appear- 
ance of  Montanus  —  the  new  instructions  of  the  promised 
Paraclete.  How  is  it  possible  that  the  work  of  God  should 
stand  still  and  make  no  progressive  movement,  while  the 
kingdom  of  evil  is  continually  enlarging  itself  and  acquiring 
new  strength  ?  " l  It  requires  to  be  observed  that  Tertullian 
did  not  refer  the  progressive  development  of  religion  to  a 

1  De  virginibus  velandis,  u.  i. 


IDEA   OF    PROGRESS  99 

continuous  self-evolution,  but  to  a  continuous  succession  of 
extraordinary  revelations.  The  great  majority  of  the  early 
orthodox  Christians  agreed  with  the  Montanists  in  looking 
for  the  coming  of  a  material  millennial  kingdom,  an  expecta- 
tion which  rested  not  only  on  a  misinterpretation  of  scriptural 
promises,  but  on  the  feeling  that  the  reign  of  evil  could  only 
be  destroyed  by  a  supernatural  outward  manifestation,  and 
consequently  on  a  want  of  faith  in  the  inherent  ability  of 
Christianity  progressively  to  transform  and  sanctify  society. l 
Justin  Martyr  and  Clement  of  Alexandria,  although  taking 
liberal  views  of  the  relation  of  Christendom  and  heathendom, 
and  regarding  heathen  philosophy  as  a  providential  prepara- 
tion of  the  Gentiles  for  the  Gospel,  were  so  far  from  attaining 
to  a  comprehensive  conception  even  of  religious  progress,  that 
they  imagined  the  truths  taught  by  the  heathen  sages  had  been 
drawn  from  the  Jewish  Scriptures.2  The  speculations  of  Ori- 
gen  as  to  the  course  of  creation  and  history  were  essentially 
derived  from  heathen  sources,  although  greatly  modified  by 
Christian  doctrines  and  interests.  His  hypothesis  of  a  series 
of  worlds  successively  burnt  up  and  restored  differs  from  the 
Hindu  and  Stoic  hypotheses  to  the  same  effect,  chiefly  by  his 
conjoining  it  with  the  emphatic  assertion  of  free-will,  and,  in 
consequence,  maintaining  that  the  worlds  are  not,  so  far  at 
least  as  men  are  concerned,  mere  repetitions  of  one  another. 
Fanciful  as  may  be  his  supposition  of  the  earth  having  been 
peopled  by  fallen  angels,  there  is  undoubtedly  a  certain  gran- 
deur in  the  way  in  which  he  conceives  of  all  fallen  creatures 
being  on  their  way  back  to  unity  in  God,  "not  suddenly,  but 
slowly  and  gradually,  seeing  that  the  process  of  correction 
and  amendment  will  take  place  gradually  in  the  individual 
instances  during  the  lapse  of  countless  and  immeasured  ages, 
some  outstripping  others,  and  tending  by  a  swifter  course 
towards  perfection,  while  others  again  follow  close  at  hand, 
and  some  again  a  long  way  behind ;  and  thus,  through  the 

!For  the  literature  of  this  curious  subject,  see  the  articles  on  "Chiliasm," 
"Millennium,"  "  Millennarianism,"  and  "  Pre-Millennarianism,"  in  the  Biblical 
Cyclopaedias  of  Kittp,  Herzog,  or  M'Clintock  and  Strong.  Also  Prof.  A. 
Chiapelli's  Idee  millenarie  dei  Christian!  nel  loro  svolgimento  storico.  Napoli, 
1888. 

2  Justin,  Apol.,  ii.  13;  i.  46.  Dial.  con.  Tryph.,  c.48.  Clemens  Alex.  Stromata, 
i.  17-19;  vi.  17. 


1 00  INTRODUCTION 

numerous  and  uncounted  orders  of  progressive  beings  who 
are  being  reconciled  to  God  from  a  state  of  enmit}',  the  last 
enemy  is  finally  reached,  who  is  called  death,  so  that  he  also 
may  be  destroyed,  and  no  longer  may  be  an  enemy."1  At 
the  same  time,  it  will  be  observed  that  this  doctrine  is  wholly 
derived  from  speculative  principles,  is  incapable  of  inductive 
verification,  is  nowhere  distinctly  applied  to  the  movement 
of  human  society,  and,  in  a  word,  is  quite  unhistorical  in 
character.  Cyprian  held  that  the  world  was  growing  old, 
losing  its  vigour  and  excellence,  and  drawing  near  to  disso- 
lution, and  that  this  inflexible  divine  law  of  things  was  the 
true  cause  of  many  of  the  evils  which  his  contemporaries 
ascribed  to  the  impiety  of  the  Christians  towards  the  ancient 
gods.2 

Augustine's  views  regarding  progress  will  be  stated  in 
our  exposition  of  his  general  theory  of  the  course  and  plan 
of  human  history.  Their  influence  is  easily  traceable  in  the 
"  Commonitorium  adversus  prof  anas  omnium  novitates  hefe- 
ticorum  "  of  Vincent  of  Lerins.  Vincent  held  the  Scriptures 
to  be,  so  fa_r  &s  content  is  concerned;  a  true  and  adequate \\\\\\\\\\\w 
revelation,  from  which  nothing  is  to  be  subtracted  and  to 
which  nothing  is  to  be  added,  but  considered  that  as  most 
heretics  appealed  to  Scripture,  tradition  must  be  called  in 
to  decide  between  right  and  wrong  interpretations.  But 
how  can  it  do  so?  Only  if  genuine  tradition  can  be  easily 
discriminated  from  spurious,  catholic  tradition  from  heret- 
ical. This  Vincent  deemed  could  be  done,  inasmuch  as  the 
former  is  quod  ubique,  quod  semper,  quod  ab  omnibus  eredi- 
tum  est,  and  which  is  consequently  characterised  by  the  three 
marks  of  universalitas,  antiquitas,  and  consensio.  It  obviously 
follows  that  all  absolute  innovation  in  religious  faith  and 
doctrine  must  be  condemned.  Does  it  follow  that  there  can 
be  no  progress  therein  ?  Vincent  answers  clearly  and  decis- 
ively in  the  negative.  "  To  deny  or  oppose  progress  would 
show  malevolence  towards  men  and  impiety  towards  God. 
The  entire  Church,  and  each  believer,  arise,  grow,  and 
develop,  as  the  human'  body  does.  But  progress  (profectus) 
is  not  change  of  nature  (permutatio);   development  is  not 

1  De  Principiis,  iii.  6  (Crombie's  translation) .  2  Lib.  ad.  Demetr.  iii.-iv. 


IDEA   OF   PROGRESS  101 

compatible  with  loss  of  identity.  Man  only  reaches  the 
maturity  and  perfection  of  his  being  by  the  growth  of  powers 
which  were  all  contained  in  germ  in  the  child.  Wheat 
should  not  produce  tares,  the  rose-tree  of  the  Catholic  Church 
should  not  bear  thistles.  The  deposit  of  truth  confided  to 
the  Church  ought  to  be  elaborated  and  applied,  elucidated 
and  evolved,  hut  its  substance  must  be  preserved  in  integrity 
and  purity."1  The  theory  which  Vincent  thus  formulated, 
so  far  as  it  merely  refers  to  religious  progress,  is  that  which 
still  generally  prevails  both  in  the  Catholic  and  the  Protestant 
Church.  So  far  as  it  is  a  theory  as  to  the  ascertainment  of 
religious  truth,  it  is  chiefly  confined  to  the  former;  and 
whatever  artifices  of  exposition  may  be  employed  to  disguise 
its  real  nature,  it  necessarily  means  that  the  truth  or  falsity 
of  religious  belief  is  to  be  determined  by  the  extent  of  its 
prevalence ;  by  counting  opinions  instead  of  weighing  them ; 
by  abandoning  the  proper  search  of  truth  itself,  and  trying  to 
reach  it  instead  hy  discovering  what  has  been  supposed  to  be 
truth  by  the  majority  of  mankind.  The  theory  of  Vincent  of 
Lerins  as  to  the  development  of  the  Church  and  Christian 
doctrine  is,  taken  as  a  whole,  substantially  the  same  with 
that  which,  within  the  present  century,  De  Lamennais  has 
made  celebrated  in  France,  Mohler  in  Germany,  and  Newman 
in  England. 

The  general  conditions  of  life  and  thought  in  the  middle 
ages  were  extremely  unfavourable  to  the  growth  and  spread 
of  the  idea  of  progress.  In  the  abounding  ignorance  the  past 
was  little  known,  and  in  the  abounding  anarchy  and  con- 
fusion the  meaning  even  of  the  present  was  undiscoverable. 
The  principle  of  authority  was  maintained  in  the  Church  and 
the  State,  in  science  and  practice,  in  such  a  way  as  to  dis- 
courage and  condemn  the  hope  that  reason  might  achieve 
great  triumphs  in  the  future ;  and  study  and  reflection  were 
mainly  confined  to  theology  and  philosophy,  the  provinces 
of  knowledge  in  which  progress  is  least  visible.  Still  the 
idea  was  never  completely  lost.  It  has  often  been  stated 
that  in  the  tenth  century  there  was  a  universal  belief  that  the 
end  of  the  world  was  to  happen  in  the  year  1000  A.D.  This 
representation  has  recently  been  subjected  to  a  critical  scru- 

1  xxvi.-xxx. 


102  INTRODUCTION  "■ 

tiny  by  E^sen,1  "-kgc  Roy,2  and  Orsi,3  and  found  to  be  an 
unwarrantable  exaggeration.  It  would  be  still  less  appli- 
cable to  any  century  earlier  or  later  than  the  tenth.  A  con- 
viction of  the  impending  destruction  of  the  world,  however, 
was  not  uncommon  at  almost  any  period  of  the  middle  age. 
It  is  frequently  found  expressed  in  the  writings  of  Gregory 
of  Tours,  Fredegar,  Lambert  of  Hersfeld,  Ekkehard  of 
Aurach,  and  Otto  of  Freisingen. 

Hugo  of  St.  Victor  in  the  twelfth  century,4  and  Thomas 
Aquinas  in  the  thirteenth,5  both  recognised  progress  to  be  a 
universal  law  of  things,  and  all  knowledge  to  be  progressive. 
Both  also  insisted  that  revelation  had  been  gradually  unfolded 
/^so  as  to  suit  the  different  requirements  of  different  ages,  and 
that,  although  it  had  been  completed  through  Christ  and  the 
apostles,  room  had  been  left  for  continuous  growth  in  com- 
prehending and  realising  it.  The  man,  however,  who,  of  all 
medieval  philosophers,  saw  most  clearly  the  deficiencies  of 
antiquity,  and  cherished  the  most  rational  hopes  of  intellect- 
ual advance  in  the  fu»ture,  wag  Roger  Bacon.  He  felt  the 
imperative  necessity  of  subordinating  theories  and  abstrac- 
tions to  facts  and  their  history,  dogmas  and  theology  to  scrip- 
ture and  religion,  metaphysics  to  experimental  science.  He 
studied  Greek,  Hebrew,  and  Arabic  writers  in  their  own 
languages,  and  had  a  perception  of  the  proper  nature  and 
functions  of  philology  and  criticism,  such  as  was'extremely 
rare  in  the  thirteenth  century.  His  acquaintance  with 
physical  science  and  his  insight  into  its  possibilities  were 
still  more  wonderful.  He  showed  the  importance  of  mathe- 
matics in  relation  to  such  science;  attained  remarkable 
glimpses  of  truth  on  a  number  of  points,  optical,  mechanical, 
and  chemical,  as  to  which  his  contemporaries  were  in  igno- 
rance or  error ;  descanted  on  the  triumphs  which  investigation 
might  achieve  by  induction  and  experiment ;  and  anticipated 
inventions  akin  to  steam-travelling  by  land  and  water, 
balloons,    diving-bells,    suspension-bridges,   and  telescopes. 

1  Die  Legende  von  der  Erwartung  des  Weltuntergangs  und  der  Wiederkehr 
Christi  im  Jahre  1000  (Forschungen  z.  Deutsch.  Geschichte  Ba-  xiii.,  1883). 

2  L'An  Mille,  Paris,  1885.  »  L' Anno  Mille  (Rivista  Stor.  Ital.,  iv.,  1887). 
4  Summa,  lib.  i.  pt.  vi.,  and  De  Sacramentis,  lib.  i.  pt.  x. 

6  Summa  Theologies.    Prima  secundse,  qusest.  98,  106,  107. 


IDEA   OF   PROGRESS  103 

With  a  keen  sense  of  the  intellectual  poverty  of  his  age, 
and  a  deep  contempt  for  the  prevailing  scholasticism,  he 
had  strong  confidence  in  the  powers  of  the  human  mind,  and 
looked  forward  hopefully  to  rich  harvests  of  science  and  art 
being  gained  as  soon  as  better  methods  of  research  and  educa- 
tion were  adopted.1 

The  externality  and  corruption  of  the  Church  produced  in 
the  thirteenth  century  a  reaction  which  took  more  or  less  the 
form  of  mysticism,  and  which  found  its  chief  support  in  the 
monasteries,  and  especially  among  the  Franciscans.  It  rested 
on  the  belief  that  a  new  era  was  dawning,  in  which  the 
Gospel  would  appear  in  its  purity  and  perfection,  and  men 
would  seek  and  find  their  salvation  in  an  entire  renunciation 
of  worldly  ties  and  possessions,  and  in  complete  surrender  to 
the  direct  internal  guidance  of  the  Holy  Spirit.  It  originated 
the  boldest  conception  of  human  development  which  had  as 
yet  appeared,  that  which  is  associated  with  Amaury  of 
Chartres,  the  Abbot  Joachim  of  Floris,  the  Franciscan  Gen- 
eral John  of  Parma,  and  his  friend  Brother  Gerard,  the 
author  of  the  celebrated  'Introductorius  in  Evangelium 
Aeternum. '  According  to  these  men  and  their  adherents, 
universal  history  ought  to  be  divided  into  three  great  periods 
or  ages:  the  age  of  the  Old  Testament  or  kingdom  of  the 
Father,  the  age  of  the  New  Testament  or  kingdom  of  the  Son, 
and  the  age  of  the  eternal  Gospel  or  kingdom  of  the  Spirit. 
In  the  first,  God  manifested  Himself  by  works  of  almighty 
power,  and  ruled  by  law  and  fear;  in  the  second,  Christ  has 
revealed  Himself  through  mysteries  and  ordinances  to  faith ; 
and  in  the  third,  for  which  the  others  have  been  merely  pre- 
paratory, the  mind  will  see  truth  face  to  face  without  any 
veil  of  symbols,  the  heart  will  be  filled  with  a  love  which 
excludes  all  selfishness  and  dread,  and  the  will,  freed  from 
sin,  will  need  no  law  over  it,  but  be  a  law  unto  itself.  The 
theory  in  this  form  has  come  down  to  our  own  times,  chiefly 
through  the  influence  of  Lessing.  But  the  Joachimites  taught 
it  with  additions,  which  could  find  acceptance  only  while 
faith  in  the  mendicant  orders  was  as  yet  unshaken  by  experi- 

1  Opus  Majns,  and  Epistola  de  seoretis  artis  et  naturae  operibus.  E.  Charles  — 
Roger  Bacon,  sa  vie,  ses  ouvrages,  ses  doctrines,  d'apres  des  textes  inedites.    1861. 


104  INTRODUCTION 

ence.  For  instance,  the  reign  of  the  Father,  they  said,  had 
lasted  4000  years,  and  during  it  the  government  of  the  Church 
had  been  intrusted  to  married  persons ;  that  of  the  Son  had 
lasted  1200  years,  and  its  administration  had  been  in  the 
hands  of  the  secular  clergy;  while  that  of  the  Spirit,  inau- 
gurated by  Joachim  and  St.  Francis,  would  continue  to  the 
end  of  the  world,  and  have  for  its  priests  monks  devoted  to 
poverty,  penitence,  and  obedience.1 

It  would  not  be  difficult  to  collect  from  writings  of  the 
fifteenth  and  sixteenth  centuries  a  considerable  number  of 
partial  expressions  of  the  idea  of  progress ;  but  to  find  clear 
general  expressions  of  it,  we  must  pass  from  the  medieval 
into  the  modern  period  of  history.  It  was  only  with  that 
radical  change  in  the  attitude,  direction,  and  methods  of 
thought,  of  which  the  Renaissance  and  the  Reformation  were 
the  first  conspicuous  manifestations,  that  the  idea  of  progress 
could  enter  into  the  stage  of  development  in  which  its  signifi- 
cance in  all  departments  of  science  and  existence  has  gradually 
come  to  be  recognised.  This  new  era  began  by  four  illus- 
trious men  not  widely  separated  in  time  —  Bodin,  Bacon, 
Descartes,  and  Pascal  —  formulating  the  general  fact  of 
progress  in  language  so  striking  that  it  could  no  longer  be 
overlooked. 

II.  The  idea  of  human  unity  is  closely  connected  with  that 
of  human  progress.  Progress  implies  continuity,  and  con- 
tinuity unity.  In  order  to  be  progress  there  must  be  some- 
thing which  progresses ;  for  progress  is  an  attribute,  not  an 
abstraction,  and  that  something  must  remain  itself  under  all 
the  phases  which  it  assumes.  There  are  many  stages  between 
the  seed  and  the  perfect  tree,  the  ovum  and  the  perfect  ani- 
mal ;  but  stage  must  so  follow  on  stage,  that  the  continuity 

1  Of  the  literature  relative  to  the  movement  associated  with  the  name  of  the 

Calavrese  abate  Gioacchino, 
Di  Bpirito  profetico  dotato, 

it  may  suffice  to  mention  Renan's  essay,  'Joachim  de  Flore  et  l'Evangile 
Bternel,'  in  his  'Nouv.  Etudes  d'Hist.  Rel.,'  1884,  and  the  second  book  of 
F.  Tocco's  '  L'Eresia  nel  Medio  Evo,'  1884.  Preger's  attempted  proof  that  none 
of  the  writings  attributed  to  Joachim  are  genuine,  has  been  satisfactorily  refuted 
by  Reuter  in  his  '  Geschichte  der  religiosen  Aufklharung  im  Mittelalter,'  ii.  356- 
360.  On  John  of  Parma,  see  the  article  of  M.  Daunou  in  the  Hist.  lib.  de  la 
France,  torn.  xx. 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITY  105 

is  not  broken,  that  the  one  individual  existence  is  preserved 
throughout,  or  there  can  be  no  progress.  In  so  far  as  phe- 
nomena of  any  kind  are  isolated,  and  not  brought  into  con- 
nection with  one  another,  or  shown  to  be  manifestations  of 
something  which  has  a  certain  individuality  distinguishing 
it  from  everything  else,  they  are  unable  to  be  brought  into  a 
progressive  series.  It  was  impossible  that  men  could  recog- 
nise that  there  was  progress  in  history  before  they  recognised 
that  there  was  unity  in  history ;  that  is  to  say,  that  their  race, 
while  in  the  ceaseless  succession  of  generations,  nations,  and 
systems  ever  modifying  and  transforming  itself,  yet  ever  re- 
mains in  essential  nature  the  same.  And  only  slowly,  only 
by  innumerable  short  stages,  only  owing  to  the  consecutive 
and  concurrent  action  of  countless  causes,  has  humanity  fully 
awakened  to  the  consciousness  of  its  unity,  and  the  possibility 
been  admitted  of  surveying  the  whole  of  the  past  and  present 
of  society,  from  a  certain  single  lofty  point  of  view,  and 
rationally  co-ordinating  the  entire  series  of  human  events. 

This  unity,  the  apprehension  of  which  is  essential  to  the 
comprehension  of  history,  is  unity  of  nature,  not  of  origin. 
Unity  of  nature  may,  as  is  generally  believed,  involve  and 
prove  unity  of  origin;  but  as  the  reality  of  the  latter  unity 
is  still  keenly  contested  by  many  on  real  or  supposed  grounds 
of  science,  it  is  especially  desirable  to  remember  that  only 
the  recognition  of  the  former  is  needful  as  a  condition  of  the 
philosophical  study  of  history,  only  discernment  enough  to 
see  a  man  to  be  a  man,  to  have  the  characteristics  and  rights 
of  a  man.  It  is  the  perception  of  this  unity  which  has  been 
so  slowly  attained.  And  yet  men  have  never  been  found 
without  some  faint  sense  of  it.  Even  in  the  lowest  stage  of 
barbarism,  they  manifest  by  living  together  a  sort  of  con- 
sciousness of  the  bonds  which  unite  them,  but  of  course  it  is 
a  very  vague,  loose,  and  feeble  consciousness.  The  rudest 
savages  —  the  Bosjesmans,  for  example  —  do  not  live  in 
complete  isolation,  but  in  society;  their  society,  however, 
has  no  chiefs,  no  priests,  no  marriages,  no  institutions  or 
laws ;  it  is  a  loose  indefinite  mixture  of  tribe  and  family,  and 
owes  the  little  consistency  which  preserves  its  separate  exist- 
ence chiefly  to  fear  and  hatred  of  the  enemies  which  surround 


106  INTRODUCTION 

it.  In  all  the  succeeding  phases  of  this  social  state  —  that 
of  the  tribe  —  men  fanatically  regard  its  interests  beyond 
everything  else,  and  readily  sacrifice  to  them  everything  else ; 
they  do  not  recognise  that  men  belonging  to  other  tribes  have 
even  such  primary  rights  as  those  to  life,  liberty,  and  prop- 
erty. Tribes  and  clans  are  kept  together  not  by  the  mutual 
goodwill  of  their  members,  but  by  the  enmity  which  they 
bear  to  neighbouring  tribes.  It  is  mutual  hostility  which 
consolidates  them  into  some  sort  of  social  unity,  and,  no 
doubt,  that  is  the  final  cause  of  so  unamiable  a  passion  pre- 
vailing so  universally  in  the  lower  stages  of  human  develop- 
ment. A  truer  and  finer  feeling  would  be  less  powerful,  or 
rather  savage  man  would  not  and  could  not  entertain  it; 
and  therefore  Providence  makes  use  in  order  to  gain  its  end 
of  the  passion  which  will  be  effective,  although  that  be  one 
which  must  lose  its  influence  as  mind  and  morality  progress, 
as  the  thoughts  of  men  are  widened,  and  their  feelings 
purified. 

The  tribe  may  extend  into  the  State,  and  when  such  exten- 
sion takes  place  it  must  be  accompanied  by  a  wider  recogni- 
tion of  human  unity,  and  a  corresponding  growth  of  feeling, 
as  well  as  by  a  wider  conception  of  duty.  The  oldest  great 
States  known  to  us  are  those  of  Asia  and  the  Nile  valley. 
In  all  these  States  only  a  comparatively  few  individuals,  the 
kings,  great  warriors,  priests,  wealthy  and  high-born  chiefs, 
have  counted  as  individually  significant,  while  the  vast 
majority  of  the  population  have  been  either  slaves,  or  freemen 
so  poor  and  degraded  that  the  man  in  them  has  been  invisible 
even  to  their  own  eyes.  These  great  monarchies  were  also  so 
situated  geographically,  so  locally  isolated  —  their  histories 
flowed  in  channels  so  far  apart  and  apparently  divergent  — 
that  the  thought  of  a  comprehensive  and  pervasive  human 
unity  was  unlikely  to  suggest  itself  to  any  mind,  and  incapa- 
ble of  being  convincingly  verified.  Hence,  except  perhaps  in 
a  few  individuals,  there  was  in  these  kingdoms  no  national 
feeling  in  the  form  of  sympathy  or  affection  based  on  the 
recognition  of  community  of  character  and  interests,  and 
giving  unity  to  the  aspirations  and  aims  of  all  who  composed 
the  nation,  but  only  in  that  form  of  senseless  antipathy  which 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITY  107 

history  shows  us  that  peoples  rendered  brutal  by  oppressive 
governments  invariably  cherish  against  each  other.  Since 
the  recognition  and  sense  of  unity  did  not  rise  thus  high,  of 
course,  it  did  not  rise  higher  and  transcend  the  barriers 
of  race,  of  language,  of  government,  and  of  territory,  so  as  to 
embrace  the  whole  of  mankind  and  "  take  every  creature  in 
of  every  kind." 

The  isolation  of  these  nations,  however,  although  great  as 
compared  with  modern  European  nations,  was  not  complete : 
war,  commerce,  migrations,  and  religious  proselytism,  all  did 
something  to  connect  them ;  and  through  each  of  their  his- 
tories traces  of  a  tendency  towards  the  apprehension  of  human 
unity  as  such  may  be  detected.  Egypt,  notwithstanding  the 
dislike  of  foreigners  ascribed  to  its  inhabitants,  undoubtedly 
exerted  a  considerable  influence  on  the  development  of  the 
nations  near  it,  and  commingled  or  amalgamated  physically 
and  morally  various  originally  distinct  Asiatic  and  African 
peoples.  It  is  generally  admitted  that  M.  Ampere  (Rev. 
Arche'ol.,  ve.  anne"e)  has  proved  caste  not  to  have  been  an 
Egyptian  institution;  and  whatever  importance  may  have 
been  attached  to  class  distinctions  in  ancient  Egyptian  soci- 
ety, it  was  universally  believed  that  before  the  judgment- 
seat  of  Osiris  all  men  from  Pharaoh  to  the  poorest  slave  would 
be  equal,  and  that  each  would  receive  according  to  the  deeds 
done  in  his  body,  whether  good  or  evil.1 

It  is  now  known  that  China  has  been  much  less  isolated 
and  self-contained  than  was  long  supposed,  and  that  even  the 
internal  development  of  moral  thought  reached  to  a  recogni- 
tion of  the  duty  of  universal  benevolence  in  one  sage  at  least, 
the  philosopher  Mih-Teih,  who  lived  in  the  fourth  or  fifth 
century  before  Christ,  and  wrote  an  essay  expressly  to  prove 
that  all  the  evils  which  disturb  and  embitter  human  society 
arise  from  the  want  of  the  brotherly  love  which  every  man 
owes  to  every  other.  From  that  essay,  as  translated  by  Dr. 
Legge,  I  may  quote  these  words :  "  If  the  law  of  universal 
mutual  love  prevailed,  it  would  lead  to  the  regarding  another 
kingdom  as  one's  own,  another  family  as  one's  own,  another 

1  This  is  proved  by  the  texts  of  the  Funeral  Ritual,  the  hymns,  and  prayers, 
translated  by  M.  de  Rouge.  The  whole  of  the  "  Book  of  the  Dead  "  is  translated 
by  S.  Birch  in  Bunsen's  '  Egypt's  Place  in  Universal  History,'  vol.  v. 


108  INTRODUCTION 

person  as  one's  own.  That  being  the  case,  the  princes,  lovr 
ing  one  another,  would  have  no  battlefields;  the  chiefs  of 
families,  loving  one  another,  would  attempt  no  usurpations; 
men,  loving  one  another,  would  commit  no  robberies;  rulers 
and  ministers,  loving  one  another,  would  be  gracious  and 
loyal;  fathers  and  sons,  loving  one  another,  would  be  kind 
and  filial ;  brothers,  loving  one  another,  would  be  harmonious. 
Yea,  men  in  general  loving  one  another,  the  strong  would 
not  make  prey  of  the  weak:  the  many  would  not  plunder  the 
few ;  the  rich  would  not  insult  the  poor;  the  noble  would  not 
be  insolent  to  the  mean ;  and  the  skilful  would  not  impose 
upon  the  simple.  The  way  in  which  all  the  miseries,  usur- 
pations, enmities,  and  hatreds  in  the  world,  may  be  made 
not  to  arise,  is  universal  mutual  love."1  It  is  possible  that 
Mih's  universal  love  may,  as  Dr.  Legge  supposes,  have  rested 
on  no  idea  of  man  as  man,  and  been  inculcated  not  as  a  law 
of  humanity,  but  simply  as  a  virtue  which  would  find  its 
scope  and  consummation  in  the  good  government  of  China. 
I  cannot,  however,  think  this  a  probable  view.  The  doctrine 
of  Mih  was  assailed  by  the  celebrated  Meng-tseu  or  Mencius, 
on  the  ground  of  leaving  no  place  for  the  particular  affec- 
tions ;  yet  Mencius  saw  with  a  clearness  and  insisted  with 
an  emphasis  that  man,  by  the  very  frame  and  make  of  his 
constitution,  is  a  being  formed  for  virtue,  for  righteousness, 
for  benevolence,  which  make  him  also  in  some  degree  a 
witness  to  the  truth  of  the  essential  unity  of  men. 

In  Indian  Brahmanism  this  truth  was  and  is  directly 
denied;  but  the  denial  gave  rise  in  th,e  way  of  reaction  to 
the  grandest  affirmation  of  it,  perhaps,  to  be  found  in  heathen- 
ism, that  of  Buddhism.  Buddha  is  represented  as  animated 
by  a  boundless  charity,  an  affection  embracing  every  class  of 
society  and  every  living  creature;  as  voluntarily  foregoing 
for  myriads  of  years  final  beatitude,  and  voluntarily  enduring 
through  numberless  births  the  most  manifold  trials  and 
afflictions,  in  order  to  work  out  salvation  for  all  sentient 
beings ;  and  his  law  is  not  only  announced  as  thus  one  of 
good  news  for  all,  but  as  enjoining,  along  with  meekness, 
patience,  and  forgiveness  of  injuries,  a  love  and  pity  which 

1  The  Chinese  Classics,  ii.  106,  107. 


IDEA    OF    HUMANITY  109 

are  to  recognise  no  distinctions  of  race,  or  caste,  or  religion. 
While,  however,  Buddhism  thus  recognises  in  one  aspect  the 
essential  unity  of  men,  it  overlooks  other  aspects  thereof. 
Regarding  only  that  side  of  human  life  which  is  directly 
turned  towards  the  infinite  and  eternal,  it  is  blind  to  its 
temporal  and  social  sides;  it  enjoins  universal  love,  not, 
however,  that  men  may  thereby  have  their  whole  natures 
and  lives  sanctified  and  beautified,  but  that  they  may  be  the 
sooner  delivered  from  the  burden  of  personal  existence,  from 
the  ties  of  life  and  societ}*-  in  any  form.  Its  logical  conse- 
quence would  be  the  conversion  of  the  world  into  a  brother- 
hood, net  of  men  but  of  monks,  each  practising  charity  with 
a  private  and  selfish  aim,  which  makes  it  a  charity  without 
love,  or  a  form  of  love  without  soul. 

The  histories  of  India  and  China  have  always  flowed  in 
courses  of  their  own,  not  only  apart  from  each  other,  but  out- 
side of  the  main  stream  of  human  events.  A  multiplicity 
of  histories  first  met  and  commingled  in  that  of  Persia.  The 
Persian  empire  extended  itself  over  the  whole  of  Western 
Asia,  and  into  Europe  and  Africa;  it  drew  together  Bactria, 
Parthia,  Media,  Assyria,  Syria,  Palestine,  Phoenicia,  Asia 
Minor,  Armenia,  Thrace,  Egypt,  and  the  Cyrenaica.  The 
voice  of  the  great  king  was  law  from  the  Indus  on  the  east 
to  the  iEgean  Sea  and  the  Syrtian  gulf  on  the  west,  from  the 
Danube  and  the  Caucasus  on  the  north  to  the  Indian  Ocean 
and  the  deserts  of  Arabia  and  Nubia  on  the  south.  Xerxes 
led  the  soldiers  of  fifty-five  peoples  against  Greece.  In 
Persia  we  see,  therefore,  the  first  great  attempt  at  the  out- 
ward realisation  of  unity  through  military  conquest  in  the 
form  of  a  universal  empire ;  it  was,  however,  only  an  attempt, 
and  the  result  was  no  real  union  but  a  loose  aggregation 
of  nations.  The  empire  of  Alexander  which  displaced  it,, 
although  still  more  wondrous,  because  the  gigantic  concep- 
tion of  a  single  intellect,  the  gigantic  work  of  a  single  will, 
was  of  an  essentially  similar  character,  being  composed  of 
nearly  the  same  materials  connected  in  the  same  manner,  and 
so  it  naturally  soon  fell  asunder  and  crumbled  away.  Its 
great  service  was  the  diffusion  of  the  principles  of  Greek 
civilisation  throughout  the  conquered  nations. 


110  INTBODUCTION 

At  a  first  glance,  Greece  —  so  small  and  so  divided  —  may 
appear  scarcely  entitled  to  a  place  in  the  history  of  the  idea 
under  consideration.  The  majority  of  her  inhabitants  were 
slaves,  and  until  the  age  of  Pericles  the  predominant  and 
general  feeling  among  her  free  men  was  hatred  of  strangers, 
of  the  barbarians ;  love  of  Greece  as  such,  of  the  nation  in 
its  entirety,  either  existed  not  at  all,  or  no  farther  than  was 
involved  in  hatred  to  the  barbarians.  The  sympathies  of  the 
Greek  did  not,  previous  to  that  time,  go  beyond  his  city  and 
the  little  territory  around  it;  these  he  loved,  but  he  hated 
other  Greek  cities,  although  not  so  much  as  Persia.  In  the 
lifetime  of  Socrates  a  great  change  and  enlargement  of 
thought  occurred.  All  the  best  minds  of  the  immediately 
succeeding  generation  would  seem  to  have  realised  more  or 
less  that  the  affections  of  every  Greek  ought  to  embrace 
Greece  as  a  whole,  instead  of  being  confined  to  his  native 
city;  that  wars  between  Greek  cities  were  unnatural;  that 
all  Greek  men  should  constitute  one  brotherhood  or  family. 
Yet  even  Plato  and  Aristotle  were  imbued  with  prejudices 
against  foreigners.  Their  contemporaries,  Antisthenes  and 
Diogenes,  the  founders  of  the  Cynic  philosophy,  were,  how- 
ever, the  first  in  Greece  to  cast  off  such  prejudices ;  and  they 
did  so  completely,  falling  even  into  the  contrary  extreme. 
They  taught  that  to  the  wise  man  slavery  and  freedom,  and 
all  social  and  civil  regulations  and  institutions,  were  matters 
of  indifference;  that  to  him  virtue,  conformity  to  the  law 
of  nature,  was  the  only  and  all-sufficient  good;  and  that  he 
could  recognise  no  distinctions  of  city  or  nation,  but  must 
necessarily  be  a  citizen  of  the  world.  Hence,  as  Zeller  has 
well  remarked,  "the  leading  thought  of  their  extensive 
political  sympathies  was  far  less  the  oneness  and  the  union 
of  mankind  than  the  freedom  of  the  individual  from  the  bonds 
of  social  life  and  the  limits  of  nationality."  The  Stoics 
developed  and  improved  this  Cynic  doctrine,  and  diffused  it 
with  far  greater  authority  and  success.  Zeno,  Cleanthes, 
and  Chrysippus  taught  that  the  whole  race  of  mankind  should 
be  regarded  as  one  great  community,  the  members  of  which 
exist  for  the  sake  of  one  another,  under  subjection  to  the  law 
of  reason .     Fragments  which  have  been  preserved  of  Menander 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITY  111 

and  Philemon,  the  two  chief  poets  of  the  Greek  new  comedy, 
give  beautiful  expression  to  the  same  sentiment,  showing 
that  it  had  become  no  mere  tenet  of  a  philosophical  school, 
but  a  general  feeling.  What  had  brought  about  so  great  a 
change  in  so  short  a  time  ?  Doubtless  many  causes,  —  the 
internal  evolution  of  thought,  the  growth  of  a  general  refine- 
ment of  feelings  and  manners,  increased  intercourse  with 
foreigners,  experience  of  the  evils  of  wars  and  dissensions, 
and,  above  all,  the  reduction  of  the  various  separate  states  of 
Greece  under  the  sway  of  Philip  of  Macedonia,  followed  by 
the  wide  conquests  of  his  son  the  heroic  Alexander.  The 
Macedonian  power  broke  down  the  last  distinctions  which 
separated  Greeks  from  Greeks,  and  then  proceeded  to  destroy 
those  which  separated  Greeks  from  barbarians ;  and  the  later 
philosophy  and  poetry  of  Greece  in  teaching  universal  citi- 
zenship and  brotherhood  were  in  no  inconsiderable  degree 
the  reflections  of  the  prodigious  political  and  social  changes 
which  resulted  from  the  victories  of  Philip  and  Alexander.' 
A  unity  so  produced,  however,  could  not  be  other  than  most 
imperfect;  one  essentially  negative  and  abstract,  empty  and 
unreal.  Men  took  refuge  in  the  thought  of  citizenship  of 
the  Avorld,  because  actual  citizenship  had  everywhere  lost  its 
worth  and  dignity.  Their  sense  of  brotherhood  was  the 
result  of  common  misfortunes,  disgraces,  and  disillusions, 
and  was  merely  a  consciousness  of  there  being  in  every  man 
a  something  akin  to  every  other  underlying  and  independent 
of  all  that  is  outward  and  public  in  life,  accompanied  by  a 
feeling  of  the  litter  hopelessness  of  realising  this  unity  in 
actual  existence,  in  social  and  political  practice. 

The  greatest  service,  however,  which  Greece  rendered  to 
the  cause  of  human  unity  has  not  yet  been  mentioned.  It 
was  that  she  discovered  the  universal  principles  of  all  high 
purely  human  culture,  and  embodied  them  in  forms  of  almost 
perfect  beauty,  to  remain  as  objects  of  admiration  and  models 
for  imitation  to  educated  men  of  all  ages  in  all  lands.  In 
Greece,  man  felt  himself  for  the  first  time  conscious  of  his 
own  true  nature  as  a  free  rational  personality;  and  on  the 
basis  of  that  knowledge  he  laid  a  foundation  which  still 
endures  for  all  our  science,  for  philosophy,  for  mathematics, 


112  INTRODUCTION 

physics,  logic,  ethics,  and  politics.  Moreover,  he  there  pro- 
duced a  sculpture,  an  architecture,  a  poetical  and  dramatic, 
an  oratorical  and  historical  literature,  which  are  still  unsur- 
passed, as  well  as  varied  types  of  character  as  grand,  and 
many  achievements  as  glorious,  as  any  which  the  world  has 
witnessed,  —  a  few  only  excepted,  which  have  been  mani- 
festly due  to  a  special  spiritual  grace. 

The  science,  art,  and  literature  of  Greece  were  reflected  in 
and  imitated  by  those  of  Rome,  the  conquests  of  which  thus 
carried  Greek  culture  to  the  Atlantic  and  the  Tay,  as  those 
of  Alexander  had  previously  carried  them  to  the  Indian 
Ocean  and  the  Sutlej.  But  Rome,  as  I  have  already  had 
occasion  to  point  out,  did  far  more  than  this  for  the  idea 
under  consideration,  being  the  first  power  truly  to  realise  a 
vast  external  unity  of  empire  under  settled  law.  Rome  not 
only  conquered  the  world  by  the  sword,  but  organised  it  by 
her  policy.  By  tenacity  of  purpose,  valour,  and  discipline, 
practical  sense  and  legislative  capacity,  she  accomplished 
what  the  Persian  monarchs  had  sought  in  vain  to  effect  by 
hurling  countless  hosts  against  surrounding  nations,  and 
Alexander  the  Great  by  his  brilliant  strategy  and  resistless 
phalanx ;  till,  although  originally  small  as  a  grain  of  seed, 
she  overspread  the  earth,  ruled  during  many  generations  from 
the  rising  to  the  setting  sun,  and  bequeathed  laws  and  insti- 
tutions which  still  live,  and  which  promise  to  be  immortal. 
Her  progress  was  one  of  steady  growth,  of  gradual  incorpora- 
tion, of  giving  and  receiving,  of  concession  and  adaptation ; 
slow  but  sure  —  sure  because  slow ;  because  no  step  was 
taken  which  needed  to  be  retraced,  no  gain  made  by  the 
sword  which  was  not  secured  by  the  statute  and  the  plough- 
share; because  whatever  she  did,  if  worth  doing,  she  did 
thoroughly.  "When  we  see,"  says  M.  Comte,  "this  noble 
republic  devoting  three  or  four  centuries  to  the  solid  estab- 
lishment of  its  power  in  a  radius  of  under  a  hundred  miles, 
about  the  same  time  that  Alexander  was  spreading  out  his 
marvellous  empire  in  the  course  of  a  few  years,  it  is  not 
difficult  to  foresee  the  fate  of  the  two  empires,  though  the 
one  usefully  prepared  the  East  for  the  succession  of  the  other." 

The  progress  of  Rome  was  not  one  merely  of  external 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITY  113 

extension  but  of  internal  development;  a  growth  of  human 
thought  as  well  as  of  human  power.  The  substance  of  Roman 
history  is  not  to  be  found  in  her  military  achievements,  but 
in  the  elaboration  and  diffusion  of  her  laws,  the  spread  of 
Roman  citizenship  over  the  world,  the  gradual  and  succes- 
sive incorporation  of  the  plebs,  the  Latins,  the  Italians,  the 
provincials,  and  the  nations,  into  the  city,  Avhich  originally 
consisted  of  a  few  patricians  and  their  clients ;  a  result  only 
possible  because  Roman  law,  unlike  what  was  designated  by 
that  name  in  the  oriental  despotisms  and  the  Greek  democ- 
racies, was  a  thing  full  from  the  first  of  living  power,  and 
so  capable  of  immense  expansion,  and  of  adjusting  itself  to 
every  change  of  circumstances.  The  Roman  idea  which 
subordinated  everything  to  the  State,  may  be  said  to  have 
been  ruined  by  its  own  successes;  to  have  abolished  itself 
in  fulfilling  itself.  The  greater  the  extension  given  to  the 
citizenship,  the  more  it  lost  in  comprehension,  in  distinctive 
significance;  and  when  conferred  on  all  subjects  of  the 
empire,  nearly  the  only  thing  meant  by  it  was  what  had  been 
originally  most  suppressed,  least  acknowledged,  in  it  —  the 
conception  of  human  community,  of  men  having  a  worth  and 
rights  simply  as  men.  The  tie  of  citizenship  was  then  really 
done  away ;  but  that  was  not  before  a  certain  reverence  for  the 
natural  ties  which  bind  men  together  as  men  had  grown  up  and 
could  replace  it.  Apart  even  from  Christianity,  the  course 
of  history,  the  refining  influence  of  imaginative  literature, 
and  the  teaching  of  philosophy,  especially  of  the  Stoic  phi- 
losophy, raised  the  Roman  mind  to  recognise  that  there  was 
a  One  Law,  embracing  all  nations  and  all  times,  which  no  ■ 
senate  or  people  had  created  or  could  annul,  and  which 
enjoined  universal  justice  and  universal  benevolence.  That 
men  are  not  merely  citizens  —  that  every  man  is  debtor  to 
every  other  —  that  they  have  a  common  nature,  and,  in  con- 
sequence, reciprocal  rights  and  obligations  —  were  well- 
known  truths  in  the  time  of  Cicero,  and  commonplaces  in 
the  times  of  even  the  earlier  emperors.  The  evidence  for 
this  affirmation  is  so  abundant,  that  to  adduce  it  with  any- 
thing l*e  adequate  fulness  would  detain  us  too  long ;  there- 
fore I  merely  give  below  a  few  references  to  works  in  which 


114  INTRODUCTION 

fhe  labour  has  been  already  carefully  performed,  and  would 
venture,  at  the  same  time,  specially  to  recommend  the  perusal 
of  the  passages  indicated,  as,  from  ignorance  of  the  facts 
therein  collected,  Christianity  is  often  represented  as  having 
exclusively  originated  and  promulgated  truths  which  were, 
intellectually  at  least,  undoubtedly  recognised  in  pagan 
Rome.1 

By  means,  then,  of  Greek  philosophy  and  Roman  policy, 
the  human  mind  in  Europe  rose  to  an  apprehension  of  a  bond 
of  unity  between  all  mankind  independent  of  class  and 
national  distinctions.  Buddhism  has  to  some  extent  per- 
formed the  same  service  in  the  south  and  east  of  Asia.  It  is 
to  be  remarked,  however,  that  it  has  approached  the  idea  of 
human  unity  in  the  opposite  direction  to  that  followed  by  the 
classical  world,  and  has  seen,  as  it  were,  only  its  opposite 
side.  It  has  recognised  the  unity  of  men  in  relation  to  the 
infinite  source  and  ultimate  end  of  existence;  but  has  so 
concentrated  thought  and  affection  on  that  aspect  of  it  as  to 
have  overlooked  and  despised  its  merely  temporal  and  civil 
relationships.  It  has  accordingly  done  very  little  for  man's 
social  welfare,  for  political  freedom,  justice,  and  prosperity. 
The  Greco-Roman  world,  on  the  other  hand,  worked  upwards 
to  the  idea  on  its  purely  human  side,  and,  indeed,  mainly  by 
the  extension  of  the  notion  of  citizenship.  But  that,  too,  is 
an  imperfect  view,  a  single  aspect  of  a  whole,  both  sides  of 
which  are  most  important.  And  when  thus  imperfectly 
apprehended,  the  idea  is  devoid  of  self -realising  power;  the 
great  truths  it  involves  cannot  make  their  way  into  life,  but 
have  to  remain  in  the  state  of  dead  abstract  affirmations. 
This  the  Romans  discovered  by  the  most  painful  experience. 
The  corruption  of  the  empire  was  not  arrested  and  little 
delayed  by  the  growth  of  correct  views  of  man's  duties  to 
man ;  selfishness  and  injustice  seemed  to  increase,  self-sacri- 
fice and  magnanimity  to  decrease,  the  clearer  and  more  general 
became  the  perception  of  the  beauty  of  universal  benevolence 

1  Janet,  Histoire  de  la  Science  Politique,  t.  i.  lib.  i.  c.  iv.;  Denis,  Histoire  des 
Theories  et  des  Ide'es  Morales  dans  l'Antiquite',  t.  ii.  (Cice'ron  —  jStajgMoral  et 
Social  du  Monde  Gre'co-Romain  —  Conclusion) ;  Aubertin,  Seneque  et  Saint-Paul, 
especially  Deuxienie  Partie,  ch.  ix.  x.  and  xi.;  Laurent,  Etudes— Borne,  lib.  iii. 
ch.  ii.  and  iv. 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITY  115 

and  justice.  As  the  sense  of  this  contradiction  between  their 
theory  and  practice,  between  the  law  of  duty  in  itself  and  the 
respect  which  it  actually  received,  deepened,  the  hearts  of 
men  in  the  Greco-Roman  world  instinctively  turned  away 
more  and  more  from  the  ora  State  religion,  and  groped  after 
another  capable  of  satisfying  the  new  affections  and  breathing 
life  into  the  wider  thoughts  which  had  grown  up ;  instinc- 
tively turned  more  and  more  to  mysterious  Egypt  and  the 
religious  East.  Through  the  introduction  of  oriental  beliefs 
and  rites,  the  spread  of  the  Judeo-Alexandrian,  Neo-Pythag- 
orean,  and  Neo-Platonic  philosophies,  the  Western  mind  was 
brought  into  contact  with  the  Eastern,  and  enlarged  and 
benefited  by  the  contact.  It  only  found,  however,  what  was 
really  wanted  in  the  religion  which  had  been  long  provi- 
dentially prepared  and  was  at  length  wonderfully  manifested 
in  the  land  of  Palestine ;  a  religion  which  neither,  like  other 
religions  of  Asia,  unduly  lost  sight  of  the  finite  in  the 
infinite,  nor,  like  those  of  Greece  and  Eome,  of  the  infinite 
in  the  finite,  but  contained  the  principles  of  their  reconcilia- 
tion, proclaiming  the  universal  brotherhood  of  man,  and  en- 
joining, at  least  in  a  general  way,  all  the  virtues  which  the 
realisation  thereof  implies  —  while,  at  the  same  time,  by 
its  revelation  of  one  God  and  Father  of  all,  one  Saviour,  one 
law,  one  hope,  laying  open  the  fountains  of  moral  force  needed 
to  enable  men  to  carry  into  practice  their  convictions  of  the 
unity,  equality,  and  rights  to  love  and  justice,  of  all  men. 

With  the  conversion  of  the  Roman  empire  to  Christianity, 
the  human  mind  may  be  regarded  as  having  at  length  risen 
to  the  apprehension  of  human  unity  on  both  sides.  Christian 
authors  and  teachers  proclaimed  with  one  accordant  voice  the 
Fatherhood  of  God  and  the  brotherhood  of  men.  What 
progress,  then,  it  may  be  asked,  had  society  in  this  direction 
still  to  make?  If  it  had  really  advanced  so  far,  could  it 
advance  farther?  When  the  equality  of  all  men  before  God, 
and  the  universal  obligation  of  charity  and  justice,  were 
explicitly  acknowledged  and  enforced  by  the  most  powerful 
of  conceivable  considerations,  was  its  goal,  as  far  as  the 
development  of  this  particular  idea  was  concerned,  not 
reached  ?  Most  certainly  not.  On  the  contrary,  humanity 
had  then  only  set  its  foot  on  the  true  path,  and  had  the  whole 


116  INTRODUCTION 

length  thereof  before  it.  To  perceive  the  mere  general  out- 
lines of  an  idea  is  one  thing,  and  to  know  it  thoroughly,  to 
realise  it,  which  is  the  only  way  thoroughly  to  know  it,  is 
another  and  very  different  thing.  But  certainly  no  Christian 
writer,  and  still  less,  of  course,  any  other,  in  the  Roman 
empire,  can  be  credited  with  having  had  more  than  a  general 
and  abstract  conception  of  human  unity.  And  that  that  was 
to  have  only  a  vague,  partial,  and  inaccurate  conception  was 
conclusively  shown  by  the  false  separation  of  secular  from 
spiritual,  the  contempt  for  the  economical  virtues,  the  indif- 
ference to  industry,  commerce,  and  national  prosperity,  the 
submission  to  despotism  and  slavery,  the  unworthy  views  of 
marriage,  the  honour  given  to  celibacy,  the  admiration  of 
asceticism,  and  the  intolerance  of  difference  of  opinions, 
characteristic  even  of  the  greatest  Christian  thinkers  of  these 
times.  Origen,  Augustine,  Basil,  Chrysostom,  Cyprian, 
Jerome,  &c,  preached  unity,  universal  brotherhood,  justice, 
and  charity,  in  as  explicit  general  terms  as  have  ever  been 
employed  since ;  but  any  man  who  fancies  them  to  have  had 
therefore  other  than  the  most  imperfect  views  of  human 
unity,  the  most  imperfect  insight  into  what  man  as  man 
really  was,  may  be  assured  that  his  vocation  is  not  that  of 
tracing  the  growth  of  ideas.  The  Christian  Fathers  repeated 
what  they  had  learned  from  Christ  and  His  apostles,  scattered 
what  they  had  received;  but  that  as  regards  the  truth  of 
human  unity  was  only  seed  —  semina  rerum,  not  res  ipsas. 

That  Christian  truth  coul<i_only  act  immediately  and 
directly  on  individual  life,*only  mediately  and  indirectly 
on  social  life,  —  that  it  might  receive  the  assent  of  an  entire 
nation  and  yet  not  save  it  from  decrepitude  and  death, —  was 
proved  on  a  vast  scale  and  in  the  most  indisputable  manner 
by  the  example  of  the  Byzantine  empire.  Christianity  pre- 
sided over  the  foundation  of  that  empire,  and  ruled  in  it  to 
its  fall,  a  period  of  more  than  a  thousand  years ;  and  yet  the 
result  was  one  of  the  most  despicable  forms  of  civilisation 
the  world  has  ever  seen,  the  destruction  of  which  was  a  gain, 
even  although  it  was  replaced  by  Mohammedan  rule.  The 
spread  of  Christianity  in  the  West  did  certainly  little  to  delay, 
and  probably  even  hastened,  the  fall  of  Rome,  which  was 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITV  117 

taken  by  Alaric  scarcely  a  century  after  Christianity  had 
become  the  State  religion  of  the  Roman  empire. 

The  old  classical  world  was  exhausted.  It  was  only  on  a 
richer  and  fresher  soil  that  the  first  principles  of  the  Gospel 
and  the  highest  results  of  Greek  and  Roman  genius  could 
mingle  in  productive  union,  could  gradually  create  a  civili- 
sation in  which  the  new,  that  is,  the  true,  man  would  be 
manifested.  The  barbarians  were  needed,  and  the  barbarians 
came.  Their  invasions  broke  the  bonds  by  which  Rome  had 
succeeded,  after  so  many  centuries  of  exertion,  in  uniting 
together  the  various  parts  of  the  world,  and  reduced  the 
whole  social  system  of  which  she  had  been  the  soul  and 
centre  to  chaos,  but  a  chaos  necessary  as  an  antecedent  to 
the  rise  of  a  more  natural  and  harmonious,  a  richer  and 
freer,  social  organisation.  There  is  reason  to  believe  that  no 
single  idea  of  special  value  struck  out  by  the  Greek  or  Roman 
mind  Was  permanently  lost  in  consequence  of  the  temporary 
anarchy  caused  by  the  successes  of  the  barbarians,  and  cer- 
tainty that  no  truth  of  Christianity  was  lost.  It  was  the 
destiny  of  the  conquerors  to  be  in  course  of  time  conquered 
both  by  the  classic  and  Christian  spirit;  and  their  distinctive 
mission  to  invigorate  human  life  with  the  love  of  independ- 
ence, of  personal  liberty,  in  which  the  ancient  world  had 
been  so  deficient,  but  without  which  man  can  never  know  or 
be  his  true  self.  Rome  and  Christianity  both  tended  of  their 
very  natures  to  unity,  the  one  towards  civil  and  the  other 
towards  spiritual  unity.  But  unity,  however  legitimate,  is 
not  of  itself  sufficient;  individuality,  diversity,  is  as  neces- 
sary as  unity,  and  is  even  necessary  to  unity,  if  it  is  to  be  a 
true,  that  is,  not  an  abstract  and  dead  but  a  concrete  and 
living,  unity.  Individuality,  independence,  was,  however, 
precisely  what  was  most  characteristic  of  the  barbarous 
Germans. 

Since  the  human  mind  emerged  from  the  chaos  of  the 
invasions,  it  has  met  with  many  misadventures,  and  strayed 
into  many  wrong  paths  in  its  quest  of  true  unity,  but  has 
never  been  absolutely  arrested  in  its  advance,  —  has  always, 
on  the  conbrary,  got  correction  through  adversity  and  instruc- 
tion from  its  errors.      Thus  it  welcomed  the  growing  power 


118  INTBODUCTIQN 

of  the  Church,  was  with  it  in  its  struggles  for  dominion,  and 
made  of  it  a  thoroughly  organised  hierarehal  system  which 
bent  all  things  to  its  own  purposes,  and  ruled  with  despotic 
sway  over  millions  of  human  beings.  In  so  doing  there  is  no 
doubt  that  it  denied  in  part  the  unity  and  equality  of  men  in 
Christ,  and  established  an  institution  which  has  done  much 
to  separate  man  from  man,  and  to  enslave  the  many  to  the 
few.  Let  us  not  suppose  it,  however,  to  have  been  guilty  of 
mere  folly  in  the  matter.  The  Roman  Catholic  Church  has 
indeed  sinned  grievously  against  humanity,  but  it  has  also 
conferred  upon  it  some  great  services.  In  ages  of  violence 
it  asserted  that  another  law  than  that  of  brute  force,  the  law 
of  justice  and  charity,  was  the  rightful  law  of  all  men.  In 
the  darkest  days  there  went  up  from  it  solemn  reminders  of 
universal  duties,  hopes,  and  terrors :  • — 

"  Hora  novissima,  tempora  pessima  sunt,  vigilemus ; 
Ecce  minaciter  imminet  arbiter,  ille  supremus.' ' 

It  was  the  chief  instrumentality  through  which  "  the  powers 
of  the  world  to  come  "  acted  on  many  generations,  and  dis- 
played themselves  as  historical  forces.  It  linked  together  the 
community  of  European  peoples  by  the  ties  of  a  common 
creed,  authority,  and  interests.  It  preserved,  humanly  speak- 
ing, the  treasures  both  of  divine  wisdom  and  of  Greek  and 
Roman  genius.  It  admitted  freely  into  its  ranks  all  classes  of 
men  from  the  prince  to  the  serf,  and,  by  assigning  them  their 
places  according  to  their  merits  and  abilities,  gave  a  happy 
contradiction  to  all  its  implicit  denials  of  human  unity  and 
equality.  The  ascetic  and  monastic  ideal  of  life  which  it 
held  forth  and  recommended  with  such  wonderful  success, 
was  undoubtedly  a  narrow  one,  most  unsuited  for  man  as 
man,  and  one  even  which  led  to  monstrous  corruptions ;  yet 
it  was  also  not  only  a  natural  reaction  against  the  abounding 
evil  in  the  world,  but  a  most  emphatic  affirmation  of  the 
truth  that  the  worth  of  human  existence  lies  far  less  in 
enjoyment  than  in  self-sacrifice,  self-discipline,  and  aspira- 
tion towards  the  eternal  and  divine. 

Charlemagne  restored  for  a  short  time  the  Roman  tradition 
of  a  universal  civil  empire,  furthered  the  progress  of  the 
Papal  idea  of  a  universal  spiritual  empire,  closed  the  era  of 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITY  119 

barbaric  invasion,  and  secured  for  Christianity  and  Latin 
culture  their  due  influence  as  factors  in  the  more  complex 
civilisation  which  began  to  appear.  The  rapid  decomposi- 
tion of  his  vast  empire  into  small  parcels  of  soil,  each  with  a 
few  inhabitants  dependent  on  the  uncontrolled  will  of  a  petty 
tyrant,  is  apt  at  first  glance  to  seem  a  directly  and  exclu- 
sively retrograde  movement.  It  was  in  reality,  however,  a 
necessary  stage  of  transition  to  a  higher  unity.  It  preserved 
and  developed  that  love  of  personal  freedom  and  sense  of 
personal  obligations  and  rights  which  the  Germans  brought 
with  them  merely  in  germ,  merely  as  dispositions  and  ten- 
dencies. But  for  the  feudal  distribution  of  society,  these 
dispositions  and  tendencies  would  soon  have  disappeared,  and 
with  their  disappearance  would  have  vanished  all  rational 
hope  of  a  unity  to  be  attained,  not  through  the  mutilation 
and  destruction,  but  through  the  comprehension  and  satisfac- 
tion, of  man's  nature.  To  consider  the  love  of  personal 
independence,  the  fidelity  of  man  to  man,  the  sense  of  indi- 
vidual honour,  and  respect  for  women,  as  the  peculiar  and 
persistent  characteristics  of  the  German  race,  is  to  fall  into 
one  of  the  grossest  delusions  which  have  been  generated  by 
Teutonic  self-conceit.  Greco-Roman  and  Christian  influ- 
ences required  to  be  brought  to  bear  on  Germanic  disposi- 
tions, and  the  circumstances  of  society  needed  to  be  long- 
favourable,  in  order  that  civilisation  might  possess  these 
excellences.  There  is  a  wide  interval  between  any  quality 
of  barbarism  and  a  virtue  of  civilisation.  Now  feudalism, 
although  a  most  deplorable  system,  incompatible  with  the 
legitimate  claims  alike  of  authority  and  of  liberty,  and 
directly  opposed  to  the  impartial  justice  and  universal  charity 
of  the  Gospel,  was  specially  calculated  to  foster  the  virtues 
referred  to,  and  thereby  to  advance  humanity  in  the  way  of 
self-knowledge.  It  rooted  out  and  made  impossible  the 
return  of  the  feeling  so  predominant  in  the  classical  world, 
that  the  individual  man  had  no  rights  as  against  the  State. 
It  substituted  for  the  Greco-Roman  view  of  the  relation  of 
public  to  private  life  one  just  the  reverse,  and  which,  although 
quite  as  one-sided  as  that  which  it  temporarily  replaced,  had 
the  great  merit  of  widening  thought  by  bringing  to  light  the 
side  previously  unseen.     If  it  filled  the  heart  of  the  castle 


120  INTRODUCTION 

lord  with  pride  and  insolence,  it  also  trained  him  to  self- 
reliance,  decision  of  character,  and  prowess.  It  made  him 
far  more  dependent  for  his  happiness  on  his  wife  and  children 
than  ever  the  oriental,  Greek,  or  Roman  man  had  been,  and 
thus  contributed  to  the  moral  elevation  of  the  family. 
Besides,  the  isolated  and  scattered  castles  of  the  feudal 
chiefs  were  not  wholly  inaccessible  to  priest  and  lawyer, 
merchant  and  minstrel,  to  Christian  truth,  Roman  traditions, 
or  even  Saracenic  science.  Life  within  them  was  not  wholly 
uninfluenced  by  the  neighbouring  monastery  or  town,  by  the 
policy  of  pope  and  emperor,  and  the  general  movement  of 
history.  Under  the  action  of  these  powers,  feudalism  in  a 
measure  civilised  itself  and  flowered  into  chivalry.  Out  of 
what  had  been  originally  but  a  robber's  den,  the  court  of 
the  castle,  came  forth  courtship  and  courtesy,  a  new  ideal  of 
conduct  inspired  partly  by  piety  towards  God,  and  partly  by 
gallantry  towards  woman,  sentiments  of  love  and  honour  of 
a  delicacy  previously  unknown,  and  a  poetry  and  romance 
which  have  grown  into  the  national  literatures  of  almost 
every  country  of  Europe. 

Throughout  the  whole  existence  of  feudalism,  two  powers 
—  the  monarchy  and  the  Church  —  steadily  resisted  with 
such  strength  as  they  possessed  its  anarchical  and  anti- 
social tendencies.  Self-interest  constrained  them  to  strive 
for  order,  for  unity,  and  so  to  counteract  the  self-will  of  the 
nobility.  In  each  land  the  struggle  took  a  different  form; 
but  in  all  it  left  deep  and  ineffaceable  impressions.  The 
kings  of  France,  confining  their  energies  within  or  immedi- 
ately around  their  own  kingdom,  wrought  steadily  on  until 
they  had  concentrated  all  power  in  their  own  hands,  and 
produced  that  extreme  unity  of  administration  which  accounts 
for  so  much  both  of  good  and  evil,  of  achievement  and  failure, 
in  the  history  of  France.  The  kings  of  England  had,  from 
the  Norman  Conquest,  a  preponderance  of  power  which  not 
only  sufficed  to  hold  the  whole  nation  firmly  bound  together, 
but  compelled  the  nobility  to  ally  themselves  with  the  com- 
mons, and  this  laid  the  foundation  for  that  union  of  order 
and  liberty  which  has  been  realised  in  a-more  perfect  measure 
in  England  than  anywhere  else  in  the  world.  The  emperors 
of  Germany  cherished  the  idea  that  the  Roman  empire  still 


IDEA    OF    HUMANITY'  121 

subsisted  both  in  law  and  fact;  and  that  they,  as  the  suc- 
cessors of  the  Caesars,  were  the  rightful  heads  of  Christendom, 
and  entitled  even  to  choose  popes  and  invest  them  with  their 
temporal  sovereignty,  although  spiritually  their  subjects. 
The  dispute  between  the  Emperor  and  the  Pope  was  the  axis 
on  which  for  more  than  two  centuries  European  history 
revolved ;  it  was  productive  of  many  and  great  evils  to  Ger- 
many and  Italy,  but  productive  also  of  great  blessings  to 
Europe  in  general.  "If  it  had  been  possible,"  says  Ger- 
vinus,  "for  the  Empire  and  the  Papacy  to  have  united 
peaceably;  if  that  which  had  already  occurred  in  the  Byzan- 
tine kingdom  of  the  East  could  also  have  occurred  in  the 
Teutonic  Roman  kingdom  of  the  West,  and  could  the  com- 
bined secular  and  spiritual  power  have  rested  on  one  head, 
—  the  idea  of  unity  would  have  gained  the  preponderance 
over  that  of  national  developments ;  and  in  the  centre  of  this 
quarter  of  the  world,  in  Germany  or  Italy,  a  monarchical 
power  and  single  form  of  government  would  have  been  con- 
structed, which  would  have  thrown  the  utmost  difficulties  in 
the  way  of  the  national  and  human  progression  of  the  whole 
of  Europe."  Fortunately  a  union  of  the  two  powers  did  not 
take  place.  The  one  saved,  the  European  world  from  entire 
slavery  to  the  other.  Their  long  struggle  favoured  the  rise 
and  growth  of  independent  thought,  and,  by  preventing  the 
realisation  of  a  one-sided  and  external  unity,  furthered  the 
cause  of  a  full  and.  free  unity. 

The  Crusades  contributed  directly  and  indirectly  in  many 
ways  to  generate  and  diffuse  the  feeling  of  a  common  Chris- 
tendom, and  even  of  a  common  humanity.  They  united  in 
a  common  sentiment,  Norman  and  Saxon  and  Celt,  French- 
man and  Austrian,  Norwegian  and  Italian.  They  were  the 
first  events  of  universal  European  significance  which  rested 
on  a  European  public  opinion.  They  softened  in  some  meas- 
ure the  antipathies  of  the  races  and  peoples  which  gathered 
themselves  together  to  combat  for  a  common  cause.  They 
made  the  baron  feel  more  dependent  on  his  vassals,  and  raised 
the  serf  in  his  own  estimation  and  in  that  of  others ;  while, 
at  the  same  time,  they  strengthened  the  power  of  the  Crown, 
and  favoured  the  growth  of  the  communes  and  free  towns. 
They  widened  the  range  of  men's  ideas  and  tastes  and  desires; 


122  INTRODUCTION 

and  they  gave  an  impulse  to  science  and  art,  and  a  still 
greater  impulse  to  commerce.  Thus,  although  they  had  their 
origin  in  fanaticism,  and  were  accompanied  with  unspeakable 
horrors,  and  followed  by  numerous  most  serious  evils  which 
do  not  require  here  to  be  mentioned,  they  also  undoubtedly 
helped  in  no  slight  degree  to  emancipate  the  human  mind 
and  educate  the  human  heart.  Intermediate  between  the 
Germanic  invasions  and  the  Renaissance,  they  are  one  of  the 
three  great  medieval  incidents  by  which  the  more  thoughtful 
minds  in  Europe  were  brought  to  see  that  the  unity  of 
humanity  underlies  even  the  differences  of  Christianity, 
Mohammedanism,  and  heathendom ;  and  that  the  love  of  man 
to  man  enjoined  by  Jesus  in  the  parable  of  the  Good  Samaritan 
and  elsewhere,  must  not  be  limited  to  the  communion  of 
believers. 

To  trace,  however,  in  its  whole  length,  breadth,  and  depth, 
the  process  by  which,  from  this  point  to  that  where  the  pres- 
ent history  commences,  the  human  mind  advanced  in  self- 
knowledge,  and  consequent  recognition  of  the  unity  in 
variety  of  humanity,  would  be  to  write  the  entire  history  of 
Europe  throughout  the  intervening  time.  It  would  be  to 
follow  the  development  of  industry  in  country  and  town, 
explaining  how  the  labouring  population  had  been  affected 
by  changes  in  the  forms  of  tenure  of  property  and  by  changes 
in  the  general  government  of  society,  by  trade  corporations 
and  their  regulations,  by  the  Crusades,  the  communes,  the 
free  towns,  by  the  advance  of  the  industrial  and  fine  arts,  and 
the  extension  of  geographical  knowledge,  the  discovery  of 
America,  the  influx  into  Europe  of  the  precious  metals,  &c. ; 
and,  in  a  word,  to  show  how  the  fetters  on  industry  and 
commerce  began  to  be  broken  one  after  another,  honest  labour 
to  be  acknowledged  as  honourable  human  work,  the  labouring 
classes  to  gain  their  human  rights  and  recognition  on  the 
page  of  human  history,  and  a  Tiers  Mat  to  arise  to  which  kings 
and  nobles  were  at  length  to  become  servants.  It  would  be 
to  trace  the  development  of  the  arts  of  architecture,  music, 
sculpture,  painting,  poetry,  and  romance,  alike  under  the 
protection  of  the  Church  and  in  their  growth  to  independ- 
ence, and  to  show  in  doing  so  how  the  imagination  of  man 
had  been  educated,  the  sphere  of  his  activity  widened,  and 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITY  123 

his  history  enriched  with  new  elements.  It  would  be  to 
describe  the  toilsome  progress  of  science,  the  preservation 
and  revival  of  ancient  learning,  as  well  as  the  means  and 
institutions  devised  to  diffuse  science  and  learning ;  and  to 
estimate  what  the  cultivation  given  to  speculation  and  formal 
thought,  as  applied  by  the  theologians  and  philosophers  of 
the  middle  ages  to  the  highest  subjects,  had  done  for  the 
modern  intellect.  It  would  also  be  to  delineate  the  long 
series  of  attempts  to  deliver  revealed  truth  from  the  false 
glosses,  and  to  emancipate  the  religious  nature  of  man  from 
the  degrading  thraldom,  imposed  by  the  Roman  Church, —  a 
series  of  attempts  which  issued  in  that  great  and  successful 
movement  which  in  the  sixteenth  century  secured  for  a  half 
of  Europe  the  right  of  private  judgment  in  religion,  a  right 
which  is  the  condition  and  guarantee  of  all  other  rights  and 
of  all  liberty.  It  would  be  — ■  very  specially  —  to  trace  the 
formation  within  the  European  unity  of  national  individu- 
alities, since  the  formation  of  nations  has  unquestionably 
contributed  in  the  highest  degree  to  a  profound  and  exhaus- 
tive development  of  the  human  soul;  while  the  further 
progress  of  the  race  in  science,  in  art,  in  literature,  in 
philosophy,  and  in  religion,  is  dependent  upon  the  preserva- 
tion and  the  quickening  collision  of  the  resultant  variety  in 
unity.  It  would  be  necessary  to  do  all  this  and  more ;  for  it 
is  only  through  having  exerted  its  forces  persistently,  method- 
ically, and  heroically,  in  all  these  directions  and  various 
others,  that  the  human  spirit  has,  to  use  the  words  of  Mr. 
Goldwin  Smith,  "slowly  and  painfully  transcended  the 
barriers  interposed  by  dividing  mountains  and  estranging 
seas,  by  diversities  of  custom  and  language,  creed  and  polity, 
by  prejudices  of  race  and  class,  in  its  progressive  realisation 
of  the  glorious  truth  of  the  universal  brotherhood  of  man." 
It  is  only  through  an  immense  and  multiform  activity,  long- 
continued  and  strenuous  toil,  protracted  and  countless  sacri- 
fices, that  man  has  learned  to  recognise  what  a  vast  variety 
of  manifestations,  what  an  infinity  of  differences,  have  their 
ground  in  the  essential  human  unity,  without  prejudice  to 
aught  distinctive  of  manhood,  or  to  any  of  its  fundamental 
rights. 

As  late  as  the  sixteenth  century  —  that  in  which  this  his- 


124  INTRODUCTION 

tory  commences  —  even  the  European  mind  had  advanced 
but  a  little  way  along  most  of  these  routes,  and  had  only  the 
most  defective  apprehension  of  the  general  truth  towards 
which  they  converge.  There  was,  for  example,  nothing 
approaching  to  an  adequate  recognition  of  the  true  place  of 
industry  and  science  in  human  life,  and  of  the  industrial 
and  scientific  classes  in  human  society,  until  the  latter  half 
of  the  eighteenth  century.  It  was,  we  may  safely  say,  some- 
what late  in  modern  times  before  humanity  had  displayed 
the  variety  of  resources,  discarded  the  prejudices,  overthrown 
or  surmounted  the  barriers,  and  gained  the  triumphs,  indis- 
pensable to  a  perception  of  its  own  unity  in  multiplicity, 
sufficiently  accurate  and  comprehensive  to  support  a  philoso- 
phy of  history.  Throughout  the  whole  of  the  middle  age, 
and  even  long  after  its  close,  man's  knowledge  of  himself, 
man's  idea  of  humanity,  was  far  too  vague  and  general,  far 
too  narrow,  external,  and  superficial  to  be  available  and 
effective  in  so  difficult  a  scientific  enterprise. 

Probably  Vico  was  the  first  to  recognise  how  fundamental 
must  be  the  idea  of  humanity  in  historical  philosophy, —  the  / 
first  to  view  history  with  clearness,  comprehensiveness,  and 
profundity,  as  a  whole,  of  which  all  the  phases  in  space  and 
time  are  explicable  by  the  constitutional  activities  of  the 
common  nature  of  mankind.  While  not  denying  that  the 
order  of  the  civil  world  was  providential,  he  was  not  content, 
like  Augustine  and  Bossuet,  simply  to  trace  that  order  to  the 
divine  will,  but  strove  to  account  for  it  as  truly  the  work  of 
man,  and  intelligible  only  when  its  changes  and  laws  were 
properly  referred  to  the  powers  and  motives  of  the  mind  of 
man.  Hence  his  'Scienza  Nuova  d'intorno  alia  comune 
natura  delle  nazioni, '  is  a  science  of  history  based  on  the 
knowledge  of  humanity,  a  sociology  derived  from  a  compara- 
tive psychology.  Unfortunately,  even  as  regards  central 
conception,  it  was  marred  by  the  serious  errors  which  Cento- 
fanti,  Emerico  Amari,  and  others,  have  laboured  to  expel 
from  it.  In  1750,  twenty-five  years  after  the  appearance  of 
Vico's  treatise,  Turgot  made  an  admirable  application  of  the 
idea  of  humanity  to  history  in  his  'Discourses  '  at  the  Sor- 
bonne.  The  same  idea  is  implied  throughout,  yet  merely 
implied,  in  Lessing's  essay  on  'The  Education  of  the  Human 


IDEA   OF   HUMANITY  125 

Race. '  Herder's  genial  and  eloquent  '  Ideen  zur  Philoso- 
phic der  Geschich£>fler  Menscheit'  made  its  significance 
popularly  appreciated,  and  definitely  secured  it  its  rightful 
position  in  historical  science,  although  as  regards  even  the 
mere  idea,  leaving  much  to  be  done  in  the  way  of  definition 
and  development.  Herder  has  had  many  successors,  of  whom 
Lotze  may  perhaps  be  justly  held  to  have  been  at  once  truest 
to  the  spirit  of  his  teaching  and  the  wisest  amender  of  the 
defects  in  its  letter. 

The  accounts  of  the  growth  of  the  conception  of  human  unity 
given  in  the  'Rede '  of  Dr.  ^K.  H.  Hundeshagen,  'Ueber  die 
Natur  und  die  geschichtliche  Entwicklung  der  Humanitatsi- 
dee  '  (1852),  and  the '  Vortrag  '  of  Professor  W.  Preger  on  'Die 
Entfaltung  der  Idee  des  Menschen  durch  die  Weltgeschichte  ' 
(1870),  are  eloquent,  but  too  brief  and  slight  to  be  of  real  use. 

III.  There  is  another  idea  —  that  of  freedom  —  equally 
involved  in  history,  and  equally  implied  in  the  formation  of 
a  philosophy  of  history.  It  is  inseparable  from  the  idea  of 
humanity,  and  its  history  from  the  history  of  that  idea. 
Man  is  a  spirit,  and  therefore  is  not  merely  what  he  is  made 
to  be,  but  mainly  what  he  makes  himself  to  be;  humanity 
is  spiritual,  and  therefore  not  merely  the  passive  subject  of 
change  and  variation,  but  mainly  self-formed  and  self-devel- 
oped. The  exertion  by  which  man  makes  himself  to  be  — 
the  self-determination  and  self-realisation  of  humanity  —  is 
freedom.  It  is  not  merely  negative — the  absence  of  re- 
straint ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  primarily  positive  —  the  human 
spirit  itself  possessing,  revealing,  and  evolving  itself  as 
spirit.  The  freedom  in  which  the  historical  student  is 
interested  is  not  to  be  confounded  with  the  so-called  "  free- 
dom of  the  will,"  concerning  which  there  has  been  so  much 
controversy  among  psychologists  and  metaphysicians.  It  is 
not  a  purely  internal  and  personal  fact,  complete  in  itself 
apart  from  any  external,  social,  or  historical  manifestation; 
but  is  just  the  freedom  which  is  exhibited  in  history,  and  of 
which  all  history  shows  either  the  repression  or  expansion. 

Man  is  not  born  free,  but  he  becomes  free  in  the  measure 
in  which  he  becomes  man,  as  he  becomes  man  in  the  measure 
in  which  he  becomes  free.     And  only  as  he  becomes  himself 


126  INTRODUCTION 

can  he  learn  to  know  himself.  According  to  the  apparently- 
paradoxical  but  really  profound  and  suggestive  doctrine  of 
Vico,  truth  is  known  by  us  just  in  so  far  as  made  by  us ;  and 
obviously  man  can  only  know  the  truth  as  to  himself  when 
he  is  himself.  Humanity  can  only  be  the  object  of  its  own 
intelligence  in  the  measure  that  it  has  realised  itself,  and 
revealed  itself  to  itself,  by  its  exertions  and  achievements. 
Self-knowledge  and  self-comprehension  must  follow  on,  and 
can  merely  be  commensurate  with,  the  self-production  and 
self-development  which  are  due  to  freedom. 

A  knowledge  of  the  history  of  freedom  must  include  a 
knowledge  of  all  the  ways  and  forms  in  which  freedom  has 
been  restricted  and  repressed  in  the  various  nations  and  ages 
of  the  world,  and  of  how  it  has  gradually  affirmed  itself 
against  negations,  broken  through  restraints,  and  advanced 
towards  its  appropriate  goal.  That  goal  can  only  be  a  state 
in  which  humanity  fully  realises  all  its  powers,  or,  in  other 
words,  a  state  in  which  there  are  no  other  limits  to  the  exer- 
cise of  its  powers  than  the  very  conditions  of  their  complete 
and  proper  exercise,  —  the  laws  of  nature,  rationality,  and 
morality.  An  individual,  a  nation,  the  race,  can  only  be 
wholly  free  when  in  full  possession  of  a  true  and  entire  self, 
confined  by  no  unnatural  limits,  determined  by  no  alien 
forces,  ruled  by  no  external  master.  Whatever  diminishes, 
restrains,  or  injures  human  power  —  human  self-control  and 
self -sovereignty  —  lessens  and  impairs  human  freedom.  No 
laws  or  institutions  can  make  a  diseased  body,  an  ignorant 
mind,  a  vicious  heart,  free.  Every  increase  of  corporeal 
vigour,  of  command  over  nature,  of  insight  into  truth,  of 
virtue,  necessarily  brings  with  it  an  increase  of  freedom. 

The  history  of  freedom  is  a  vast  history.  Hegel,  in  his 
'Philosophy  of  History,'  Michelet,  in  his  'Introduction  to 
Universal  History, '  and  others,  have  treated  it  as  the  whole 
of  history,  freedom  being  regarded  by  them  as  "  the  substance 
and  subject  of  universal  history,  and  the  guiding  principle  of 
its  development,  so  that  historic  events  are  to  be  viewed  as 
products  of  it,  and  as  deriving  only  from  it  their  meaning 
and  character."  And  whether  this  be  precisely  true  or  not, 
certainly  the  struggle  to  repress  or  acquire  freedom  is  per- 
vasive of  the  entire  history  of  humanity ;  is  universal  history 


IDEA   OF   FREEDOM  127 

itself  —  the  whole  bodily,  intellectual,  moral,  political,  and 
religious  movement  of  humanity  itself  —  in  a  special  aspect. 
Its  history  to  the  time  when  historical  philosophy  began  to 
appear  in  a  distinct  form,  cannot  be  sketched  here  even  in 
brief  outline,  as  in  the  case  of  the  ideas  of  progress  and  of 
humanity.  To  keep  this  Introduction  within  due  limits,  I 
must  attempt  merely  to  give  some  indications  to  sources 
whence  a  conception  of  its  history  may  be  drawn. 

On  the  idea,  conditions,  and  forms  of  liberty,  on  the  right 
to  it  and  what  is  implied  therein,  and  related  themes,  a  num- 
ber of  works  have  been  written.  Those  of  Charles  Du- 
noyer,1  John  Stuart  Mill,2  Jules  Simon,3  and  Emile  Beaus- 
sire,4are  perhaps  the  most  important  and  interesting — Some 
of  thejn-eontain  a  considerable  amount-erf  information,  even 
aslio  the  growth  of  the  idea  of-lrberty. 

One  of  the  opposites  of  freedom  is  bodily  slavery,  —  the 
condition  in  which  a  man  is  not  the  master  of  his  own  physi- 
cal members  and  powers,  but  forced  to  exert  them  at  the 
commands  and  for  the  ends  of  another.  Such  slavery,  in 
one  form  or  another,  has  occupied  a  large  place  in  history. 

In  the  savage  state  both  licence  and  slavery  prevail,  but  of 
liberty  there  is  little.  The  savage  is  too  destitute  of  the 
higher  kinds  of  life  to  be  capable  of  the  higher  kinds  of  lib- 
erty. As  to  bodily  independence,  different  uncivilised  races 
display  very  different  dispositions,  and  are  found  in  very 
different  conditions ;  but  even  when  savages  are  resentful  of 
encroachments  on  their  own  freedom,  they  show  little  respect 
for  the  freedom  of  others.  Ambition,  pride,  hatred,  and  other 
passions,  lead  them  to  war ;  and  selfishness  and  avarice  induce 
the  conquerors  to  retain  or  sell  as  slaves  numbers  of  the  con- 
quered whom  they  would  otherwise  have  slain.  In  this  way 
slavery  has  undoubtedly  tended  and  served  to  save  life,  but 
it  has  also  increased  the  sacrifice  of  it  by  supplying  a  power- 
ful and  persistent  motive  for  undertaking  wars,  and  especially 
small  wars.  Then,  in  the  majority  even  of  savage  communi- 
ties there  are  rich  and  poor,  and  the  dependence  of  the  poor 

1  L'Industrie  et  la  Morale  considered  dans  lenr  Rapports  avec  la  Liberte 
(1825),  and  De  la  Liberte  du  travail,  &c,  3  vols.  (1845). 

4  On  Liberty.  s  La  Liberte',  2  vols. 

4  La  Libert^  dans  l'ordre  intellectuel  et  moral. 


128  INTRODUCTION 

on  the  rich  in  these  communities  often  issues  in  slavery. 
There  is,  so  far  as  I  know,  no  good  general  account  of  slavery 
among  uncivilised  peoples.  One  of  the  best  of  the  older 
accounts  is  perhaps  Bastholm's.1  Waitz  and  Gerland's 
'Anthropologic  der  Naturvolker, '  and  Letourneau's  'Evo- 
lution de  la  Propri^te" '  (1889),  contain  much  material,  and 
indicate  whence  it  has  been  derived. 

In  societies  of  a  nomadic  or  simple  agricultural  type,  what- 
ever be  the  race  to  which  those  who  compose  them  may  belong, 
slavery  is  not  prevalent,  and  is,  as  a  rule,  of  a  comparatively 
mild  character.  The  Aryans  of  India,  the  Romans,  and  the 
Teutons,  as  they  first  appeared  in  history,  may  be  referred 
to  in  proof.  Peoples  in  this  stage  may  have  the  love  of 
bodily  independence,  and  the  qualities  required  to  defend 
and  preserve  it,  and  even  to  vanquish  and  subdue  great 
and  cultured  nations,  in  the  highest  degree.  Freedom,  after 
having  been  driven  from  courts  and  cities,  senates  and  schools, 
has  found  a  refuge  in  deserts  and  forests,  and  reconquered 
the  world  by  the  arms  of  the  rude  men  who  dwelt  therein. 

From  the  writings  of  the  Old  Testament  a  fairly  distinct 
conception  can  be  formed  of  slavery  among  the  Hebrews. 
Many  modern  critics  hold  the  picture  presented  in  the  Book 
of  Genesis,  of  the  patriarchal  age,  its  slavery  included,  to  be 
not  a  transcript  of  reality,  but  an  idealisation  of  the  past. 
Whether  this  is  so  or  not,  can  only  be  properly  decided  by 
the  historico-critieal  investigations  of  specialists.  Although 
the  Hebrews  are  described  as  having  shown  extreme  ferocity 
in  the  conquest  of  Canaan,  their  legislation  as  to  slavery  was, 
on  the  whole,  considerate  and  humane.  Slaves  were  not 
numerous  among  them,  at  least  after  the  exile.  Hebrew 
slavery  has  naturally  been  the  subject  of  much  research  and 
controversy.  The  best  treatise  regarding  it  is  still  that  of 
Mielziner.2 

Slavery  in  the  great  military  empires,  which  arose  in 
ancient  times  in  anterior  Asia,  was  doubtless  of  the  most 
cruel  character;  but  we  have  no  good  account  of  slavery  in 

1  Historische  Nachriehten  z.  Kentniss  des  Menschen,  Bd.  i.  k.  16  (1818). 

2  Die  Verhaltnisse  der  Sklaven  bei  den  alten  Hebraern,  Kopenhagen,  185!). 
See  also  the  art.  in  Herzog's  R.-E.,  Bd.  xiv.,  and  Stade,  Geseh.  d.  Volkes  Israel, 
1  Th.,  Bd.  vii.  377-381. 


IDEA   OF   FREEDOM  129 

these  countries.  The  histories  of  Rawlinson,  Duncker, 
Ranke,  Ed.  Meyer,  and  Maspero,  tell  us  almost  nothing 
about  Chaldean,  Assyrian,  and  Medo-Persian  slavery.  Much 
more  is  known  as  to  slavery,  and  the  condition  of  the  labour- 
ing classes,  in  ancient  Egypt,  although  of  even  this  section 
of  the  history  there  is  much  need  for  an  account  in  which  the 
sources  of  information,  unsealed  by  modern  science,  will  be 
fully  utilised.  While  in  Egypt  there  were  not  castes,  in  the 
strict  sense  of  the  term,  classes  were  very  rigidly  defined. 
There  were  troops  of  slaves,  and  as  population  was  super- 
abundant, labour  was  so  cheap  as  to  be  employed  to  an  enor- 
mous extent  uselessly.  It  may  suffice  to  refer  to  Wilkinson,1 
Rawlinson,2  and  Buckle.8 

It  does  not  seem  certain  that  the  Vedic  Aryans  had  slaves 
before  the  conquest  of  India.  Those  whom  they  conquered 
became  the  Sudras,  and  a  caste  system  grew  up,  and  came  to 
be  represented  as  of  divine  appointment.  The  two  lower 
castes  of  the  Code  of  Manu  have  now  given  place  to  a  great 
many.  There  was  not  a  slave  caste,  but  individuals  of  any 
caste  might  become  slaves  in  exceptional  circumstances. 
Even  before  the  rise  of  Buddhism  there  were  ascetics  who 
rejected  the  distinction  of  castes.  Buddhism  proclaimed  the 
religious  equality  of  Brahmans  and  Sudras,  but  not  the  eman- 
cipation of  the  Sudras.  Its  attitude  towards  the  tyranny  of 
Hindu  caste  was  similar  to  that  of  Christianity  towards  Roman 
slavery  and  medieval  serfdom.4 

The  various  phases  of  slavery  in  Greece  and  Rome  have 
been  admirably  described  in  M.  Wallon's  'Histoire  de  l'Es- 
clavage  dans  l'Antiquite- '  (3  vols.).  The  growth  and  influ- 
ences of  slavery  can  be  traced  throughout  the  whole  history 
of  both  Greece  and  Rome;  and  in  both  its  injustice  and 
cruelty  came  in  course  of  time  to  be  recognised  by  the  best 
minds.6  Aristotle  declared  it  natural  and  legitimate;  but 
Zeno,  Antisthenes,  the  poets  Menander  and  Philemon,  Sen- 
eca, Epictetus,  Dion  Chrysostom,  and  others,  pronounced 
against  it.     The  Stoics  were  its  most  vigorous  assailants. 

1  Ancient  Egyptians.  2  Ancient  Egypt.  3  Hist,  of  Civ.,  vol.  i.  eh.  ii. 

4  Dubois,  Descrip.  of  the  People  of  India,  ch.  vi.  (Madras,  1862) ;  Elphinstone, 
Hist,  of  India,  i.  23-34,  103-109;  Buckle,  i.  ch.  ii.;  Oldenberg,  Buddha,  152-158. 

5  Denis,  Hist.  d.  Theories  et  des  Idees  Morales  dans  1' Antiquity,  t.  ii.  pp.  62-96, 
•&c. ;  Onken,  Die  Staateslehre  des  Aristoteles,  ii.  Hfte.,  29-36. 


130  INTRODUCTION 

Seneca,  in  particular,  condemned  it  with  a  directness,  clears 
ness,  and  fulness  which  we  look  for  in  vain  in  the  New 
Testament.  The  first  Christian  teachers  proclaimed  merely 
spiritual  liberty  and  equality,  the  oneness  in  Christ  of  the 
bond  and  the  free;  they  did  not,  like  the  Stoics,  maintain 
slavery  to  be  wrong,  or  emancipation  a  duty.  It  does  not 
follow  that  Christianity  was  not  by  the  new  views  which  it 
gave  of  God  and  man,  and  by  the  new  affections  and  virtues 
which  it  generated,  a  very  powerful  agency,  or  even  the  most 
powerful  of  all  agencies,  in  abolishing  slavery  and  effecting 
emancipation.  To  me  it  seems  that  in  this  connection  the 
influence  of  Stoicism  has  been  overestimated  by  Havet  in  his 
'Origines  du  Christianisme' ;  and  that  of  Christianity  by 
Troplong  in  'De  l'lnfluence  du  Christianisme,'  by  Allard 
in  'Les  Esclaves  Chretiens  depuis  les  premiers  temps  de 
l'Eglise  jusqu'a  la  fin  de  la  domination  romaine  en  Occident ' 
(1876),  and  by  juridical  writers  and  Christian  apologists 
generally. 

In  the  middle  ages  the  conviction  that  freedom  was  man's 
natural  state  found  frequent  expression,  yet  the  legitimacy 
of  slavery  in  the  actual  state  of  the  world  was  generally 
admitted  by  the  clergy  and  theologians,  although  they  opposed 
in  some  measure  its  abuses.  The  slaves  connected  with  the 
monasteries  were  probably  among  the  best  treated,  but  they 
were  also  among  the  last  to  be  emancipated.  In  the  gradual 
doing  away  with  slavery,  or  transforming  it  into  serfdom,  the 
growth  of  the  spirit  of  Christianity  co-operated  with  the  work- 
ing of  economic  causes :  the  power  of  the  former  was  great, 
but  has  more  frequently  been  exaggerated  than  fairly  stated ; 
while  that  of  the  latter,  which  was  not  less,  has  been  commonly 
overlooked  or  inadequately  appreciated.  By  the  fourteenth 
century  absolute  slavery  had  almost  entirely  passed  away. 
Medieval  slavery  has  found  a  learned  historian  in  Muratori.1 
Slavery  of  the  most  cruel  and  immoral  kind  was  revived  in 
the  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries  in  America  and  the 
European  colonies ;  was  defended  as  a  Christian  institution 
and  a  means  of  propagating  the  Christian  faith ;  and  has  only 
recently  been  extirpated.     This  later  slavery  does  not  fall 

i  Antich.  Ital.,  xiv.-xv.  See  also  Yanoski,  De  l'abolition  de  l'esclavage  ancien 
au  raoyen  age,  et  de  sa  transformation  en  servitude  de  la  glebe.    1860. 


IDEA   OP   EKEEDOM  131 

within  the  period  with  which  we  are  here  concerned,  but  I 
may  refer  to  the  able  and  comprehensive  view  of  it  given  by 
Ch.  Comte  in  his  "Traite"  de  Legislation,'  t.  iv.  pp.  106-536. 

The  merciless  oppression  of  the  labouring  classes,  the 
imposition  of  most  arbitrary  restrictions  on  industry,  and  the 
most  unequal  treatment  of  the  different  classes  of  society, 
continued  in  Europe  long  after  the  cessation  of  slavery 
strictly  so  called.  Even  serfdom  was  not  completely  swept 
away  in  England  until  the  reign  of  Charles  II.,  and  in  Scot- 
land not  till  the  middle  of  the  eighteenth  century.  At  the 
latter  date  more  than  half  of  the  German  people  was  in  a  state 
of  serfdom.  The  exactions  and  burdens  laid  upon  labour  had 
a  powerful  influence  in  producing  the  great  French  Revolu- 
tion. In  the  middle  age,  and  early  centuries  of  the  modern 
period,  however,  literature  and  history  show  that  the  labour- 
ing classes  were  far  more  conscious  of  their  rights  to  liberty, 
had  much  more  organisation  with  a  view  to  obtain  them,  and 
resisted  the  violence  of  the  powerful  and  the  vices  of  state- 
craft much  more  steadily  and  wisely  than  is  generally  known 
or  supposed.  On  this  section  of  the  history  of  the  develop- 
ment of  liberty,  such  sources  of  information  as  the  following 
may  be  referred  to:  Sugenheim's  'Aufhebung  der  Leibeigen- 
schaft,'  Zimmerman's  'Der  Bauernkrieg, '  Rogers's  'Six 
Centuries  of  Work  and  Wages,'  Bonnemere's  'Histoire  des 
Paysans,'  &c,  Dareste's  'Hist,  des  Classes  Agricoles,' 
Perrens's  'La  Democratic  en  France  au  Moyen  Age,'  &c. 

A  second  form  of  slavery  is  the  domestic, —  the  slavery  of 
women  and  children  to  the  male  head  of  a  family.  It  also 
has  been  world-wide,  long-enduring,  and  many-formed.  It 
has  appeared  in  savage,  in  civilised,  and  practically,  although 
not  confessedly,  even  in  Christian  lands.  It  has  been  said 
that  woman  was  first  treated  as  a  domestic  animal,  next  as 
a  slave,  afterwards  as  a  servant,  and  then  as  a  minor.  The 
generalisation  is  too  absolute  to  be  exact,  yet  there  is  a  great 
amount  of  truth  in  it.  Domestic  slavery  has  naturally  fol- 
lowed much  the  same  course  of  development  as  personal 
slavery,  and  they  have  acted  and  reacted  powerfully  on  each 
other.  The  well-known  researches  of  Bachofen,  Tylor,  Lub- 
bock, M'Lennan,  Morgan,  and  others,  have  thrown  light  on 
the  state  and  treatment  of  women  among  primitive  and  savage 


132  INTRODUCTION 

peoples.  The  light  has  been  collected  and.focussed  in  such 
works  as  'La  Sociologie, '  by  Letourneau,  and  'Die  Mens- 
chliche  Familie, '  by  Von  Hellwald.  The  treatise  of  L.  A. 
Martin  — '  Histoire  de  la  Femme  '  —  gives,  perhaps,  the  best 
account  of  the  condition  and  subjection  of  women  among  the 
ancient  Chinese,  Hindus,  Egyptians,  Hebrews,  Arabians,  &c. 
That  of  Legouve"  — '  Hist.  Mor.  des  Femmes  '  —  may  be 
consulted  along  with  it.  The  history  of  woman  in  Greece 
has  great  interest,  yet  much  less  than  her  history  in  Rome, 
where  it  began  with  a  state  of  entire  subjection,  and  ended 
with  one  of  greater  freedom  than  has  existed  even  in  Chris- 
tendom until  lately,  — ■  the  disappearance  of  tutory  and  manus, 
the  guaranteeing  of  dowry,  and  the  full  concession  of  rights 
over  personal  property.  For  a  view  of  this  portion  of  the 
history  of  the  family  in  relation  to  liberty,  may  be  read  Maine 
on  patria  potestas  in  his  'Ancient  Law,'  pp.  133-146,  and 
Muirhead's  'Roman  Law,'  24-36,  43-49,  64-69,  115-121, 
345-349,  414-419;  and,  for  the  earlier  period,  the  relevant 
chapters  and  sections  in  Carle's  '  Origini  del  Diritto 
Romano. '  1 

The  nature  and  extent  of  the  influence  of  primitive  Chris- 
tian teaching,  of  the  ascetic  and  monastic  ideals  of  life,  of 
Teutonic  sentiment,  of  feudalism,  chivalry,  and  the  worship 
of  the  Virgin,  on  the  freedom  and  elevation  of  woman,  are 
subjects  which  have  been  discussed  more  or  less  carefully  by 
many  writers,  and  on  which  a  great  variety  of  views  may  be 
plausibly  entertained.  Medieval  sentiment  and  practice  in 
regard  to  woman  were  so  full  of  contrasts  and  contradictions 
that  the  most  opposite  conceptions  of  her  position  and  treat- 
ment in  the  middle  ages  may  easily  be  formed,  and  utterly 
irreconcilable  representations  of  them  given.  The  Beatrice 
of  Dante  and  the  Madonna  di  San  Sisto  of  Raphael  are  prob- 
ably the  highest  and  purest  ideals  of  woman  ever  conceived 
by  the  human  heart,  and  expressed  by  human  art;  yet  the 
general*  tone  of  thought  and  feeling  as  to  woman,  as  mani- 
fested, for  example,  even  in  the  writings  of  the  clergy  and 
theologians  of  the  times  of  Dante  and  Raphael,  was  coarse 

1  The  position  of  women  in  ancient  Greece  and  Rome  is  the  subject  of  four 
articles  by  Principal  Donaldson  in  the  '  Contemporary  Review '  (vols,  xxxii., 
xxxiv.,  liii.,  liv.). 


IDEA    OP   FREEDOM  133 

and  base.  The  institutions  of  the  middle  ages  which  con- 
tributed most  to  the  cause  of  female  emancipation  and 
improvement,  affected  chiefly  women  of  wealth  and  rank, 
and  did  comparatively  little  for  the  poor  and  humbly  born. 
The  age  of  chivalry,  as  described  in  this  reference  by  many 
historians,  is  scarcely  less  mythical  than  the  age  of  gold.  It 
can  neither  be  dated  nor  located ;  in  every  country  and  cen- 
tury in  which  we  are  toid  it  existed,  the  general  state  of 
womankind  can  be  shown  to  have  been  one  of  enslavement 
■  and  endurance  of  wrong,  and  one  which  knights  and  trouba- 
dours did  much  more  to  aggravate  than  to  alleviate.1 

The  laws  of  modern  states  regulating  the  relations  between 
man  and  woman  in  marriage  have,  in  general,  been  extremely 
unjust  to  the  latter.  English  law  on  the  subject,  for  ex- 
ample, down  to  late  in  the  eighteenth  century,  proceeded 
avowedly  on  the  amazing  theory  that  man  and  woman  so 
became  one  in  marriage  that  she  lost  herself  in  him,  and  he 
remained  the  sole  person  and  the  sole  proprietor.  Thus  slow 
has  been  the  movement  towards  that  equality  of  rights  in 
man  and  woman  which  is  implied  in  the  true  liberty  of  both, 
while  clearly  distinguishable  from  the  equality  of  conditions 
inconsistent  with  nature  and  duty  demanded  by  certain  an- 
tinomian  and  socialistic  agitators.2 

There  are  higher  forms  of  liberty  than  those  directly 
assailed  by  physical  and  domestic  slavery;  there  is  spiritual 
liberty- — intellectual,  moral,  and  religious- — -involving  the 
rejection  of  superstition  and  authorities  founded  on  super- 
stition, the  independent  exercise  of  reason  and  conscience, 
untrammelled  research,  and  freedom  of  speech,  publication, 
worship  and  proselytism,  association  and  action,  so  far  as  the 
like  freedom  and  rights  of  others  are  not  thereby  interfered 
with.  Liberty  of  this  nature,  and  the  rights  which  it 
includes,  are  what  are  most  essential  to  man  as  man,  and  yet 
they  are  what  he  has  found  it  most  difficult  to  attain  and 
preserve. 

1  Michelet,  La  Sorciere,  61-69 ;  Bruce,  Gesta  Dei,  ch.  xii. 

2  E.  Laboulaye  wrote  '  Recherches  sur  la  condition  civile  et  politique  des 
femmes  depuis  les  Romains  jusqu'a  nos  jours.'  1843.  J.  S.  Mill's  '  Subjection  of 
Women '  (1869)  and  A.  Bebei's  '  Die  Frau  '  (1883)  may  be  referred  to  as  typical  ex- 
pressions, the  one  of  the  advanced  liberal  and  the  other  of  the  advanced  socialis- 
tic view  as  to  woman's  rightful  position  in  society. 


134  INTRODUCTION 

Almost  all  the  ancient  civilisations  were  of  the  theocratic 
type.  The  oriental  nations  knew  hardly  any  other  govern- 
ment than  that  of  rulers  who  pretended  to  be  delegated  or 
inspired  by  the  gods,  and  who  as  such  dictated  to  their 
subjects  what  they  should  believe  and  how  they  were  to  act. 
That  government  of  this  kind  rendered  important  services  to 
humanity  must  be  admitted,  but  that  it  naturally  ended  in 
the  ruin  of  every  people  which  failed  to  rise  above  it  is  also 
undeniable.  Regarding  it,  Flotard,1  Nicolas,2  and  Lippert,3 
may  be  consulted. 

Greece  owed  her  glory  chiefly  to  her  intellectual  independ- 
ence, the  freedom  with  which  her  citizens  examined  all  the 
problems  of  life  and  exercised  all  their  faculties  of  mind. 
Yet  even  in  Greece  an  Anaxagoras  was  banished  and  a 
Socrates  put  to  death.  The  Romans  acted  in  general  on  the 
principle  that  it  should  be  left  to  the  gods  themselves  to 
avenge  the  wrongs  done  to  them;  they  were  led,  however, 
to  violate  it  in  various  instances,  owing  to  their  subordina- 
tion of  religion  to  policy.  The  persecution  of  the  Christians 
in  the  Roman  empire  is  a  subject  which  has  been  often  and 
fully  discussed.4 

When  the  Christian  Church  ceased  to  be  persecuted  and 
acquired  the  power  to  persecute,  it  began  to  strive  to  crush 
free  thought  in  regard  to  matters  of  religion  by  physical 
force.  False  views  of  God  and  man,  of  the  efficacy  of  faith 
and  the  nature  and  conditions  of  spiritual  life,  zeal  for  eccle- 
siastical unity,  priestly  pride  and  ambition,  and  other  causes, 
rendered  the  history  of  religious  tyranny  and  intolerance  a 
lengthened  and  deplorable  one.  The  Reformers  proclaimed 
the  principle  of  religious  freedom — the  right  of  private 
judgment  • —  so  far  as  they  themselves  required  it  to  justify 
their  resistance  to  Rome,  but  not  in  its  purity  and  univer- 
sality. To  hold  that  the  magistrate  ought  not  to  employ  the 
sword  in  matters  of  religion  and  conscience,  seemed  to  them 
a  doctrine  incompatible  with  good  government,  and  equiva- 
lent to  an  assertion  that  all  religious  opinions  are  morally 

1  Etudes  sur  la  The'oeratie,  &c,  1861. 

2  De  la  The'oeratie  in  Essais  de  Philosophie,  &c,  1863. 

3  Allgemeine  Geschichte  des  Priestenthums,  2  B. 

4  Lecky's  Hist,  of  European  Morals,  chap.  iii. 


IDEA   OP   FREEDOM  135 

indifferent  and  socially  insignificant.  It  was,  in  reality, 
owing  to  the  wars  between  Catholics  and  Protestants,  and 
the  contentions  between  the  various  sects  of  Protestants,  that 
men  were  gradually  forced  to  recognise  religious  freedom  to 
be  a  right,  and  religious  toleration  to  be  a  duty.  Liberal 
thinkers  and  wise  statesmen  —  men  like  L'Hcipital,  Pasquier, 
Bodin,  De  Thou,  Henry  IV.  —  had  their  eyes  first  opened, 
and  so  at  length  had  even  most  zealous  religionists.  To 
Roger  Williams  belongs  the  honour  of  having  first  made 
religious  liberty  a  fundamental  principle  of  a  political  com- 
munity. "  The  conscience  belongs  to  the  individual,  not  to 
the  State."  Bossuet  was  not  far  from  the  truth  when  he 
said  that,  with  the  exception  of  Socinians  and  Anabaptists, 
all  Protestants  agreed  with  him  in  believing  that  the  civil 
magistrate  was  bound  to  punish  the  enemies  of  sound  doc- 
trine. It  is  chiefly  since  his  time  that  men's  thoughts  have 
so  widened  that  now  every  unbiassed  thinker  holds  that  no 
religious  opinion  may  be  dealt  with  by  secular  force,  and 
that  the  fullest  freedom,  far  from  being  dangerous  to  truth 
itself,  or  to  the  general  interests  of  society,  is  most  favour- 
able to  them.1 

Religious  superstition  and  bigotry  have  originated  numer- 
ous attempts  to  crush  intellectual  activity  and  independence. 
Of  these  attempts  against  the  liberty  which  is  the  very 
breath  of  life  to  philosophy  and  science,  a  general  account, 
written  with  vigour  and  animation,  but  unfortunately  not 
with  impartiality,  will  be  found  in  the  well-known  work  of 
Dr.  Draper,  misleadingly  entitled  a  'History  of  the  Conflict 
between  Religion  and  Science.' 

Political  history  has  been  mainly  the  history  of  the  struggle 
for  political  liberty,  —  the  liberty  of  all  the  members  of  a 
civil  community  to  take  part  in  its  government,  to  elect  or 
be  elected  its  rulers,  to  have  a  voice  in  regard  to  the  making 
of  its  laws  and  the  transaction  of  its  affairs,  while,  at  the 
same  time,  legally  and  adequately  guaranteed  and  protected 
against  all  invasions  on  their  individual  rights  and  private 
concerns.     All  so-called  general  histories  are,  for  the  most 

1  Bluntschli,  Geschichte  der  religiosen  Bekentnissfreiheit,  1867.  The  article 
on  "  Religious  Liberty  "  in  Schaff's  '  Encyclopedia '  gives  a  good  general  view  of 
the  history  of  the  subject,  and  references  to  sources  of  information. 


136  INTKODTJCTION 

part,  political  histories ;  and  of  all  the  kinds  of  special  his- 
tory the  political  is  by  far  the  most  numerous.  It  is  need- 
less, therefore,  to  give  particular  references  to  sources  of 
information  on  the  history  of  political  liberty.  In  treating 
of  various  philosophies  of  history,  I  shall  have  occasion  to 
consider  the  views  which  they  give  of  the  course  of  the  de- 
velopment of  such  liberty,  both  in  practice  and  theory.  It 
may  therefore  at  present  be  sufficient  merely  to  mention,  as 
specially  relevant,  Sir  Thomas  Erskine  May's  '  Democracy  in 
Europe  '  (2  vols.  1877),  and  Lord  Acton's  two  '  Lectures  on 
the  History  of  Liberty  in  Antiquity  and  Christendom  '  (1877). 
The  movement  towards  liberty  has  been  wide  as  history 
itself.  Its  arrest  and  repression  have  been  attempted  by 
force,  fraud,  and  seduction  of  all  kinds  and  in  all  ways,  but 
without  avail.  Man's  nature  has  developed  on  the  whole, 
and  it  has  only  developed  in  so  far  as  his  freedom  has  been 
extended  and  confirmed.  The  growth  alike  of  reason  and 
morality  has  been  a  growth  in  liberty.  Religious  progress 
also  essentially  means  progress  towards  full  spiritual  free- 
dom. Christianity  has  been  a  mighty  force  in  favour  of 
freedom,  although  Christian  Churches  have  often  been  hostile 
and  hurtful  to  it.  Christianity  did  not  explicitly  condemn 
bodily,  domestic,  or  political  slavery,  but  it  proclaimed  and 
conferred  spiritual  liberty.  It  was  of  the  very  substance  of 
its  teaching  that  freeman  and  slave  were  one  in  Christ, — 
that  every  slave  was  Christ's  freeman,  and  every  freeman 
Christ's  slave, —  that  all  men  were  so  bound  to  one  master 
that  they  could  be  bound  to  no  other.  Hence  the  triumph  of 
the  Christian  spirit  necessarily  implies  the  victory  of  human 
freedom.  The  freedom  which  humanity  now  enjoys  is  the 
outcome  of  its  entire  struggling  and  straining  through  the 
ages,  with  whatever  of  life  and  strength  it  has  received, 
against  the  matiifold  powers  which  have  opposed  it,  and 
tended  to  degrade  and  destroy  it.  The  words  of  Bryant  are 
as  truthful  as  they  are  spirited  and  inspiring :  — 

"  O  Freedom!  thou  art  not  as  poets  dream, 
A  fair  young  girl,  with  light  and  delicate  limbs, 
And  wavy  tresses  gushing  from  the  cap 
With  which  the  Roman  master  crowned  his  slave 
When  he  took  off  the  gyves.    A  bearded  man, 
Armed  to  the  teeth  art  thou ;  one  mailed  hand 


IDEA   OP   FREEDOM  137 

Grasps  the  broad  shield,  and  one  the  sword ;  thy  brow, 

Glorious  in  beauty  though  it  be,  is  scarred 

With  tokens  of  old  wars ;  thy  massive  limbs 

Are  strong  with  struggling.    Power  at  thee  has  launched 

His  bolts,  and  with  his  lightnings  smitten  thee ; 

They  could  not  quench  the  life  thou  hast  from  heaven. 

Merciless  power  has  dug  thy  dungeon  deep, 

And  his  swart  armourers,  by  a  thousand  fires, 

Have  forged  thy  chain ;  yet,  while  he  deems  thee  bound, 

Thy  links  are  shivered,  and  the  prison  walls 

Fall  outward ;  terribly  thou  springest  forth, 

As  springs  the  flame  above  a  burning  pile, 

And  shoutest  to  the  nations,  who  return 

Thy  shoutings,  while  the  pale  oppressor  flies." 

The  history  of  the  idea  of  liberty  is  inseparable  from  the 
history  of  liberty  itself.  The  collective  experience  and  the 
collective  intelligence  of  peoples  have  contributed  much  more 
to  it  than  the  insight  and  speculation  of  a  few  exceptional 
individuals.  The  reflections  of  philosophers  and  others  on 
liberty  have  been  to  a  much  greater  extent  consequences 
than  causes,  presupposing  and  corresponding  to  a  general 
condition  of  experience  and  attainment,  desire  and  opinion. 
In  the  sixteenth  century,  theory  and  practice  as  to  liberty 
were  in  all  respects  and  relations  most  imperfect.  The  idea 
of  its  nature  was  as  vague  as  the  actual  realisation  of  its 
nature  was  meagre.  So  far  as  the  philosophy  of  history, 
therefore,  depends  on  insight  into  the  nature  of  liberty,  a 
condition  of  its  existence  was  still  at  that  date  wanting. 
Nor  was  it  supplied  until  a  considerable  time  after.  The 
lack  of  it  goes  far  to  explain  how,  even  in  the  age  of  Louis 
XIV.,  the  nearest  approximation  to  historical  philosophy 
was  the  absolutist  and  theological  view  of  universal  history 
expounded  by  Bossuet. 

V 

Plato,  Aristotle,  Augustine,  and  l~bn  Khaldun  are  the  four 
writers  who  have  the  best  claims  to  special  notice  in  this 
Introduction.  Yet  those  of  Plato  and  Aristotle  are  not  very 
strong.  Neither  of  them  had  any  conception  of  a  science  or 
philosophy  of  history.  No  thinker  of  the  Greco-Roman  clas- 
sical world  had ;  not  one  regarded  history  as  the  subject  of  a 
science  or  of  a  distinct  department  of  philosophy;  not  one 
had  a  properly  scientific  or  philosophical  interest  in  history. 
But  Greece  was  the  cradle  and  early  home  of  political  science. 


138  INTRODUCTION 

Within  very  narrow  limits  of  time  and  space,  it  presented 
a  "wonderfully  rich  and  varied  field  of  political  experience 
capable  of  being  easily  surveyed,  and  afforded  the  most  abun- 
dant and  stimulating  opportunities  for  political  reflection.  A 
citizen  of  Athens,  Sparta,  or  Thebes,  was  as  inevitably  forced 
into  political  inquiries  and  discussions  as  a  French  deputy 
or  an  English  member  of  Parliament;  and  the  multitude  of 
remarkable  events,  the  number  of  revolutions,  and  the  variety 
of  forms  of  government  which  he  had  within  his  range  of 
vision,  afforded  a  copious  store  of  materials  for  political 
instruction  and  political  speculation.  In  all  probability,  no 
people  has  ever  been  more  generally  and  intensely  interested 
in  endeavouring  to  estimate,  for  example,  the  relative  advan- 
tages and  disadvantages  of  various  kinds  of  government  than 
the  Greek,  in  the  age  of  their  full  intellectual  development. 
As  political  thinkers  Plato  and  Aristotle  had,  consequently, 
many  predecessors.  But  they  surpassed  all  who  preceded 
them ;  and  are  the  most  eminent  political  writers  not  only  of 
Greece  but  of  the  whole  ancient  world, —  so  eminent  as  still 
to  afford  help  and  guidance  in  political  science  and  practice, 
— -as  "still  to  rule  our  spirits  from  their  urns."  It  was 
only  in  subordination  to  politics  that  they  in  some  measure 
theorised  on  history.  In  the  prosecution  of  their  political 
inquiries  and  reflections,  they  were  led  to  certain  generalisa- 
tions as  to  the  succession  and  changes  of  forms  of  government, 
as  to  the  causes  of  the  strength  and  weakness  of  States,  as  to 
the  conditions  of  social  order  and  welfare,  which  may  be 
regarded  as  contributions  or  approximations  to  historical 
philosophy.  Of  these  I  may  here  be  not  unreasonably  ex- 
pected to  give  some  brief  account. 

I.  The  philosophy  of  Plato  undoubtedly  failed  to  do  justice 
to  historical  reality.  It  even  tended  to  depreciate  and  dis- 
courage historical  study,  inasmuch  as  it  relegated  percep- 
tions, particulars,  phenomena,  to  the  limbo  of  mere  opinion. 
It  taught  that  truth  was  to  be  found,  not  in  the  changing 
and  individual,  but  in  the  unchanging  and  universal;  that 
there  is  no  science  of  phenomena,  but  that  to  reach  science 
the  mind  must  get  above  phenomena,  through  and  beyond 
them  as  it  were,  into  a  region  of  types,  exemplars,  ideas. 


PLATO  139 

Were  this  the  case,  there  could  be  no  science  of  history;  and 
that  it  is  the  case  is  the  general  tenor,  the  main  burden,  of 
Plato's  teaching.  Hence  the  Platonic  theory  of  ideas  has 
been  on  this  very  account  assailed  by  Schopenhauer  with 
characteristic  vehemence.  Hence  it  has  been  pronounced  by 
E.  Mayr  "im  Grunde  eine  geschichtsfeindliche  Doctrin." 
And  the  charge  is  substantially  true.  But  it  must  not  be 
overlooked  that  the  theory  had  another  aspect.  The  ideas 
were  also,  however  inconsistently,  represented  as  the  sources 
and  reasons  of  phenomena.  The  worlds  of  sense  and  history 
were  supposed  to  be  in  some  measure  participant  in  the 
ideas,  and,  in  consequence,  so  far  intelligible.  Plato,  it  must 
be  granted,  unduly  depreciated  phenomena;  but  neither  is 
it  to  be  denied  that  he  was  very  much  alive  and  awake  to  the 
importance  of  observing  them,  with  a  view  to  deriving  from 
them  suggestions  in  the  dialectic  search  after  truth.  He  had 
not  the  same  reverence  as  Aristotle  for  past  or  present  facts 

—  he  did  not  attach  to  them  nearly  the  same  value  —  but  he 
was  by  no  means  without  eye  for  them  or  interest  in  them. 
There  are  many  indications  that  he  had  closely  studied  the 
political  history  of  Greece. 

Three  political  writings  are  commonly  ascribed  to  Plato 
■■ — 'the  'Republic,'  the  'Laws,'  and  the  'Statesman.'  The 
first  is  undoubtedly,  and  the  second  is  in  all  probability,  his. 
That  he  was  the  author  of  the  third  seems  to  me  unlikely. 
The  'Republic'  is  grandly  original  in  conception,  and  beau- 
tiful in  execution.  The  matter  of  the  'Laws  '  is  abundant 
and  rich,  but  imperfectly  arranged  and  crudely  presented. 
The  'Statesman'  is  of  little  merit  or  value  in  any  respect. 

In  the  'Republic '  Plato  exhibited  his  ideal  of  the  State, 
his  scheme  of  a  perfect  polity.     It  was  most  natural  that  he 

—  the  great  idealistic  philosopher  —  should  have  an  ideal 
scheme  of  political  and  social  organisation.  He  would  have 
been  untrue  to  himself  and  his  philosophy  had  he  accepted 
a.ny  particular  existent  form  of  government  as  the  normal 
one,  or  had  he  not  sought  to  ascertain  the  ideal  of  society, 
the  absolute  truth  in  politics.  He  was  under  no  temptation 
to  such  inconsistency,  being  entirely  out  of  sympathy  with 
the  politics  and  politicians  of  his  age.  He  was  sensible  of 
the  narrowness  and  harshness  of  the  Lacedemonian  State, 


140  INTBODUCTION 

and  was  decidedly  opposed  to  the  Athenian  democracy. 
Every  extant  form  of  government  in  Greece  seemed  to  him 
to  be  degenerate  and  corrupt, —  to  be  tyranny,  oligarchy, 
and  mob-rule,  almost  at  their  worst.  All  of  them  appeared 
to  him  to  be  unjust,  and  consequently  incapable  of  satisfying 
human  nature,  to  which  justice  is  essential.  It  was  to  illus- 
trate and  exemplify  what  justice  was,  that  he  sketched  an 
ideal  State,  seeing  that  no  actual  State  is  just,  while  yet 
justice  in  the  individual  is  unintelligible  apart  from  its 
reflection  in  the  justice  of  the  State. 

According  to  Plato,  the  State  originates  in  want  —  the 
insufficiency  of  individuals  to  provide  for  themselves.  Yet 
it  is  not  something  foreign  or  accidental  to  human  nature. 
The  true  end  of  the  State  is  the  true  end  of  human  nature  — 
the  realisation  of  the  good.  The  constitution  of  the  perfect 
State  is  just  the  magnified  likeness  of  the  constitution  of  the 
normal  man.  The  State  is  an  organic  whole  like  the  indi- 
vidual, composed  of  analogous  parts  which  ought  to  aid  one 
another,  converge  to  a  common  centre,  and  co-operate  to  a 
common  end.  It  is  a  unity  which  springs  from,  and  is  exactly 
similar  to,  the  unity  of  the  soul  itself. 

In  the  State  there  ought  to  be  three  orders  of  men.  The 
first  is  the  order  of  operatives,  which  comprises  the  two 
classes  of  artisans  and  labourers.  Its  function  is  to'minister 
to  the  wants  of  the  community,  and  its  motive  is  self-interest 
or  gain.  It  is  not,  properly  speaking,  a  body  of  slaves. 
Plato  did  not  wish  slaves  in  his  commonwealth;  he  held 
that  Greeks  ought  not  to  enslave  Greeks;  and  although  he 
allowed  that  there  should  be  a  few  barbarian  slaves,  this  was 
permission,  not  injunction.  It  is  only  to  the  operatives  that 
he  concedes  the  possession  of  private  property.  He  saw  that 
they  needed  the  stimulus  of  self-interest  in  order  to  perform 
the  labours  expected  of  them,  and  therefore  confined  convnu- 
nism  to  the  two  higher  orders.  Of  these  the  one  immediately 
above  the  operatives,  is  that  of  the  guardians  or  warriors. 
Their  function  is  to  repress  internal  revolt  and  to  repel  for- 
eign aggression,  and  their  motive  is  the  love  of  glory.  They 
must  be  not  only  spirited,  swift,  and  strong,  but  thoughtful, 
temperate,  and  despisers  of  wealth ;  are  to  be  carefully  trained 
in  body  and  mind  with  a  view  to  the  formation  of  these 


PLATO  141 

qualities;  and  are  to  be  guarded  against  the  temptations 
of  their  station  by  holding  property,  women,  and  children  in 
common.  The  third  or  highest  order  in  the  State  is  that 
of  the  rulers  or  magistrates.  It  is  selected  from  the  second 
order,  and  prepared  for  its  duties  with  special  care.  It  con- 
sists not  of  priests,  as  did  the  ruling  class  in  the  oriental 
theocracies,  but  of  sages,  with  clear  insight  into  the  wants 
of  human  nature  and  society  and  how  they  were  to  be  sup- 
plied, somewhat  like  those  who  composed  the  Pythagorean 
brotherhood  which  ruled  in  Croton  and  other  cities  of  South 
Italy.  Each  of  the  orders  of  the  State  has  a  characteristic 
quality  or  virtue :  the  operatives  —  temperance ;  the  guardians 
—  courage ;  the  magistrates  — ■  wisdom.  Without  any  of  these 
a  State  cannot  exist;  without  their  prevalence  it  cannot 
nourish.  But  there  must  also  be  a  principle  or  power  which 
belongs  not  primarily  or  peculiarly  to  any  one  order,  but 
must  of  its  very  nature  pervade  the  whole  so  as  to  harmonise 
and  unify  all  its  parts  and  properties,  orders  and  qualities; 
and  this  is  none  other  than  justice,  the  virtue  which  deter- 
mines the  true  relation  of  all  things  and  persons  to  one 
another.  Precisely  so  is  it  in  the  soul.  In  each  individual 
mind  there  are  three  distinct  elements  —  reason,  will,  and 
appetite  —  corresponding  to  the  three  constituent  classes  of 
the  civic  community — -the  rulers,  guardians,  and  operatives. 
And  as  the  wisdom  of  the  city  dwells  in  its  rulers,  that  of 
the  individual  dwells  in  his  reason;  as  the  courage  of  the 
city  is  in  its  guardians,  that  of  the  individual  is  in  his  will ; 
as  "the  temperance  of  the  city  lies  in  the  self-restraint  and 
submission  of  its  operatives,  that  of  the  individual  lies  in  the 
control  and  subjection  of  his  appetites ;  while  justice  in  the 
individual,  as  in  the  city,  resides  in  all  the  parts  equally, 
existing  only  in  so  far  as  each  part  performs  its  own  func- 
tion without  encroaching  on  the  functions  of  other  parts. 

Plato  perceived  with  the  utmost  clearness  that  the  char- 
acter of  a  State  must  depend  on  the  characters  of  the  indi- 
viduals who  compose  it;  that  a  city  can  be  no  better  than 
are  its  citizens ;  that  a  perfect  republic  supposes  thoroughly 
virtuous  men.  No  charge  against  his  scheme  can  be  less 
applicable  than  the  common  one  that  he  hoped  to  make  men 
good  and  happy  by  laws  apart  from  morals.     In  his  eyes  the 


142  INTRODUCTION 

problem  of  government  was. mainly  a  moral,  and  therefore 
mainly  also  an  educational  problem.  He  acknowledged  that 
the  new  social  order  which  he  desired  to  introduce,  required 
a  new  generation  of  persons  formed  by  a  new  system  of 
education  implying  a  radical  change  in  Greek  art,  morality, 
and  religion.  The  plan  of  education  which  he  sketched 
assumed  throughout  the  political  revolution  contemplated  to 
be  inseparable  from  a  theological,  ethical,  and  even  literary 
or  aesthetic  revolution.  It  was  of  a  most  comprehensive 
character,  and  is  still  instructive  and  suggestive.  It  subor- 
dinated all  that  influences  human  life  and  all  social  activities 
to  the  supreme  art  —  that  of  the  true  statesman. 

Plato's  love  of  unity  led  him  to  sacrifice  individuality,  his 
sense  of  the  evils  arising  from  self-interest  to  recommend 
the  abolition  of  private  property  and  the  family,  his  dislike 
of  the  excesses  of  liberty  to  advocate  an  unnatural  equality. 
He  required  that  at  least  the  upper  classes  of  the  State,  the 
full  citizens,  should  live  wholly  for  it, — should  see  and  hear, 
feel  and  act,  as  it  were,  only  in  common, —  should  have  no 
separate  or  selfish  interests.  Perceiving  that  this  end  could 
not  be  attained  except  through  communism,  as  regards  both 
goods  and  women,  he  laid  down  rules  for  establishing  and 
maintaining  a  communistic  system,  for  guarding  it  against 
abuses  and  deriving  from  it  all  the  advantages  which  it  can 
yield.  Women  he  would  emancipate  and  equalise  with  men, 
by  giving  them  the  same  education  as  their  male  companions, 
relieving  them  from  domestic  labours,  and  assigning  to  them 
public  duties.  Although  the  Platonic  communism  is  in  vari- 
ous particulars  offensive  to  the  moral  sense,  its  general  moral 
spirit  is  earnest,  elevated,  and  even  severe.  It  contemplated 
not  the  indulgence  but  the  subjection  of  sense  and  passion, 
not  the  pleasure  of  the  individual  but  the  good  of  the  society. 

Of  special  interest  to  the  historical  philosopher  are  the 
eighth  and  ninth  books  of  the  'Republic'  The  exposition 
there  given  by  Plato  of  the  variety  of  forms  of  government, 
of  their  distinctive  principles,  of  the  excesses  and  defects 
peculiar  to  each,  of  the  general  order  of  political  change  in 
each  and  from  one  to  another,  and  of  its  causes,  laid  the 
foundation  for  all  subsequent  theorising  on  these  points. 
Aristotle,  Polybius,  Cicero,  the  author  of  the  'De  regimine 


PLATO  143 

principum,'  Macchiavelli,  Bodin,  Vico,  Montesquieu,  and  all 
their  followers,  have  built  upon  it. 

The  picture  which  Plato  had  drawn  of  an  ideal  State 
was  that  of  a  true  aristocracy,  and  this  is  presented  in  the 
'Republic '  as  the  only  normal  polity.  The  distinct  forms 
of  government  deviating  from  it  are  four:  timocracy  (ex- 
emplified in  Sparta  and  Crete),  oligarchy,  democracy,  and 
tyranny.  They  are  so  many  stages  of  departure  and  "degen- 
eration from  the  ideal,  and  are  produced  by  so  many  cor- 
ruptions of  the  minds  and  manners  of  the  citizens.  Mr. 
Newman's  statement,  however,  regarding  this  portion  of 
Plato's  work  is  so  excellent,  that  I  may,  to  the  advantage  of 
my  readers,  content  myself  by  quoting  it. 

"  The  review  of  actual  constitutions  given  in  these  books  is  designed 
to  show  that  all  States  other  than  that  in  which  justice  reigns  are  un- 
happy, and  increasingly  unhappy  the  further  they  are  removed  from  the 
ideal  model,  and  it  naturally  places  them  before  us  in  a  sombre  light. 
The  Lacedemonian  State  still  retains  a  few  features  of  the  ideal  commu- 
nity;  the  distinction  of  social  functions  (or  justice)  so  far  survives  there 
that  the  soldier  is  marked  off  from  the  cultivator  and  trader;  the  old 
respect  for  magistrates,  the  old  military  habits  of  life,  the  old  interest  in 
yv/wao-TiKiq  also  survive.  But  the  third  class  has  been  enslaved,  separate 
households  and  property  have  been  introduced,  the  class  of  'wise  men' 
has  been  corrupted  and  has  lost  its  hold  of  power.  The  State  is  in  the 
hands  of  men  in  whom  the  spirited  element  rules,  contentious  and  ambi- 
tious men  (<j>i,\6v£ikoi  kcu  (juXorifwi) .  The  regime  is  one  of  perpetual  war, 
and  love  of  money  has  come  in  with  the  decline  of  communism.  In  the 
oligarchy  the  money-getting  spirit  has  won  complete  mastery.  Rich  men 
rule  over  spendthrifts  whose  purses  they  have  drained :  all  but  the  rulers 
are  poor.  Functions  are  no  longer  distinguished ;  the  soldier  is  also  a 
cultivator  or  a  trader.  The  oligarchical  State  is  weak  for  war,  for  it  is 
really  two  States,  —  a  State  of  the  rich  and  a  State  of  the  poor  —  and  it 
does  not  arm  its  poor.  It  is  in  the  oligarchy  that  the  drone,  stinged  or 
stingless,  or  in  other  words,  the  idle  spendthrift,  is  first  engendered. 
Democracy  is  rather  the  rule  of  the  stinged  drones  than  of  the  many. 
There  are  three  classes  in  a  democracy :  the  drones,  stinged  and  sting- 
less; rich  money-making  orderly  men;  and  a  large  body  of  poor  labouring 
men,  who  seldom  assemble  together,  but  are  all-powerful  when  they  do. 
The  drones  of  a  democracy  are  far  more  formidable  than  those  of  an 
oligarchy,  being  now  admitted  to  office,  and  they  plunder  the  rich  for  the 
benefit  of  the  poor.  This  is  one  feature  of  a  democracy ;  another  is  its 
excess  of  liberty.  A  democracy  is  organised  anarchy.  We  do  not  learn 
why  the  supremacy  of  the  third  class  (the  ^p^aTicrTtKoi)  should  be 
accompanied  by  this  excessive  impatience  of  control.     Anarchy  leads  by 


144  INTRODUCTION 

a  natural  reaction  to  tyranny.  The  people  loves  to  have  a  champion ; 
democracy  commonly  means  the  supremacy  of  an  individual ;  and  the 
champion  easily  passes  into  a  tyrant.  Many  of  the  touches  in  Aristotle's 
well-known  picture  of  tyranny  will  be  found  to  have  been  drawn  from 
Plato's  sketch  of  the  tyrant,  if  the  two  are  compared.  Plato  speaks 
throughout  of  oligarchy,  democracy,  and  tyranny,  as  if  there  were  only 
one  form  of  each,  and  that  the  most  extreme  form.  He  is  naturally  led 
by  the  aim  he  has  in  view  to  make  the  worst  of  each  of  these  constitu- 
tions. We  must  not  look  for  scientific  exactness  in  these  vigorous 
sketches,  which  have  a  perennial  truth  and  value ;  Plato's  aim  is  rather 
to  show  the  misery  of  misrule  than  to  trace  with  accuracy  the  path  of 
constitutional  change,  or  to  reproduce  every  nuance  of  the  various  consti- 
tutions. When  Aristotle,  at  the  close  of  his  book  on  political  change, 
brings  his  unrivalled  knowledge  of  the  facts  of  constitutional  change  in 
Greek  States  to  bear  on  Plato's  brilliant  series  of  dissolving  views,  we 
feel  that  his  matter-of-fact  criticisms,  however  cogent  they  may  be,  are 
rather  thrown  away." 

In  one  passage  of  the  'Republic '  (iv.  12)  Plato  makes  a 
very  remarkable  extension  of  the  psychological  analogy  and 
historical  generalisation  on  which  his  political  ideai  is  so 
largely  based.  He  indicates  that  what  he  has  said  of  the 
orders  of  classes  of  men  in  a  city  also  applies  to  the  nations 
of  the  world ;  that  if  the  various  races  be  viewed  in  relation 
to  each  other,  intelligence  will  be  found  to  prevail  among 
the  Greeks,  courage  among  the  Thracians  and  the  Scythians 
(the  Northern  peoples),  and  the  love  of  gain  among  the 
Phoenicians  and  Egyptians  (the  Southern  peoples).  This 
was  an  approximation  to  regarding  the  world  of  nations  as 
one  naturally  fitted  to  be  a  vast  organic  whole,  a  city  of 
humanity.  It  was,  however,  only  a  transitory  and  excep- 
tional glimpse  of  a  far-off  truth,  and  passed  away  unimproved. 
In  the  delineation  of  the  ideal  State  Plato  had  merely  in  view 
a  Greek  city,  or  at  most  the  aggregation  of  Greek  cities,  but 
not  a  confederation  of  them,  still  less  a  Greek  nation,  and 
least  of  all  a  rightly  inter-related  system  of  nations,  a  har- 
monious realm  of  humanity. 

The  ideal  exhibited  in  the  'Republic '  had  obvious  and 
great  defects.  The  consideration  given  to  the  order  of 
labourers,  for  instance,  was  manifestly  insufficient.  Those 
who  composed  this  order  were  assumed  to  be  so  possessed  by 
self-interest  as  to  be  fit  only  for  industry  or  trade;  and  when 
it  had  been  laid  down  that  they  ought  not  to  be  allowed  to 


PLATO  145 

take  part  in  public  functions,  but  should  be  kept  in  obedi- 
ence to  their  betters,  all  that  was  essential  to  be  said  regard- 
ing them  was  supposed  to  have  been  said.  This  method  of 
dealing  with  a  most  important  portion  of  the  complex  problem 
which  Plato  had  before  him,  deprived  his  solution  of  it  to 
all  title  to  completeness.  Then,  as  regards  the  citizens  in 
the  proper  and  full  sense  of  the  term,  his  proposals  to  abolish 
private  property  and  the  family  are  liable  to  objections  which 
far  outweigh  any  reasons  that  can  be  urged  in  their  support. 
Further,  the  distinction  of  the  orders  in  the  State  was  drawn 
much  too  sharply  and  deeply.  These  orders,  as  described 
by  Plato,  are  not  indeed  castes ;  they  are  not  based  on  heredi- 
tary differences ;  the  lowest  is  not  composed  of  slaves,  and  the 
highest  is  drawn  from  that  below  it;  but  the  individual  is  so 
merged  in  his  order  as  to  be  stripped  of  much  of  his  man- 
hood. The  truth  that  a  man  is  not  to  be  treated  merely  as 
a  trader,  a  soldier,  or  a  ruler,  but  also  as  a  man,  with  all  the 
powers  and  rights  of  a  man,  is  ignored  and  virtually  denied. 
Perhaps  the  chief  defect  of  all  is  the  one  which  it  was  most 
difficult  for  a  Greek  thinker  in  the  age  of  Plato  to  escape  — 
a  great  and  cruel  sacrifice  of  the  individual  to  the  State. 
But  on  this,  as  on  the  other  defects  of  the  Platonic  ideal,  I 
have  no  need  to  dwell. 

Plato  was  fully  aware  that  his  ideal  of  a  best  State  was 
very  unlikely  to  be  realised  so  long  as  Greek  thought  and 
morality  continued  to  be  what  they  were.  There  was  no 
inconsistency,  therefore,  in  his  drawing  up  a  scheme  of  a 
second-best  State.     This  he  did  in  the  'Laws.' 

Here  he  acknowledges  it  useless  to  demand  in  existing 
circumstances  community  either  of  women  or  property,  and 
insists  merely  on  the  State  regulation  of  marriage  and  the 
equality  of  wealth.  He  also  lays  far  more  stress  on  religion 
and  far  less  on  philosophy  than  in  the  'Republic'  But  all 
that  we  require  to  note  in  the  'Laws  '  is  the  view  given  of 
the  development  of  society  and  government.  The  earth  is 
supposed  to  be  of  immense  age,  and  its  rational  inhabitants, 
with  their  arts  and  sciences,  to  have  been  repeatedly  destroyed 
by  physical  catastrophes.  Human  history  is  represented  as 
having  since  the  last  deluge  passed  through  these  stages,— 
(1)  single  families  of  shepherds  and  hunters,  with  pure  and 


146  INTRODUCTION 

simple  manners,  and  without  written  laws;  (2)  primitive 
societies  under  patriarchal  rule;  (3)  early  city  life,  based  on 
agriculture,  in  which  a  common  legislation  harmonises  oppo- 
site customs,  and  royalty  or  aristocracy  takes  the  place  of  the 
patriarchate ;  (4)  the  rise  of  maritime  cities,  with  commerce, 
war,  and  sedition  as  consequence ;  and  (5)  the  establishment 
of  States,  like  the  Lacedemonian  and  Cretan,  with  consti- 
tutions of  a  mixed  and  tempered  nature.  In  the  'Laws' 
democracy  and  monarchy  are  represented  as  the  two  primary 
or  "mother"  forms  of  government,  and  the  best  form  as  one 
in  which  the  distinctive  principles  of  both,  authority  and 
liberty,  are  so  combined  that  what  is  true  is  preserved,  and 
the  special  dangers  and  excesses  of  both  prevented.  In  it 
all  parts  of  the  State  are  regulated  by  reason,  and  there  is 
no  injustice  or  oppression.  It  is  a  unity  in  which  all  true 
principles  are  conciliated  and  co-ordinated.  Compared  with 
it  royalty,  aristocracy,  democracy,  and  tyranny  are  not  "  con- 
stitutions "  but  "factitious  coteries  "  (crTao-LWTeTaX). 

The  '  Statesman,'  although  probably  not  Plato's  composi- 
tion, is  Platonic  in  its  general  tenor.  Its  aim  is  to  ascertain 
the  nature  of  the  true  ruler.  The  result  arrived  at  is  to  the 
following  effect.  The  true  ruler  is  the  same  man  whether 
called  master,  economist,  politician,  or  king,  —  the  man  who 
governs  with  the  consent  of  the  governed,  but  according  to 
his  own  knowledge  and  insight,  —  the  wise  man  whose  policy 
rests  not  on  sophistry  but  on  genuine  philosophy.  Regal  gov- 
ernment is  a  science  —  a  judicial  and  presiding  science  — 
which  no  mob  of  persons  can  acquire  or  apply.  The  philos- 
opher-king will  reform  his  subjects  by  a  most  careful  and  com- 
prehensive system  of  education,  and  deal  with  the  diseases  of 
society  as  the  physician  does  with  those  of  the  body,  not 
sparing  the  patient  pain  when  it  is  needed.  Only  such  a  king 
can  restore  society  to  the  healthy  and  happy  condition  in  which, 
according  to  the  ancient  myth,  mankind  lived,  when  under  the 
immediate  guidance  of  the  gods,  in  the  cycle  of  Chronos.  The 
myth  of  world  cycles  set  forth  in  the  '  Statesman '  may  be  of 
theological  and  philosophical  interest;  but  it  is  of  no  value  as 
an  historical  hypothesis.  It  only  requires  to  be  added  that  in 
the  'Statesman'  governments  are  divided  into  monarchy,  of 
which  the  perversion  is  tyranny;  aristocracy,  of  which  the  per- 


PLATO  147 

version  is  oligarchy;  and  democracy,  which  is  good  or  bad. 
To  the  corrupt  form  of  democracy  Polybius  perhaps  first 
applied  the  term  "  ochlocracy."  The  distribution  of  govern- 
ments given  in  the  '  Statesman '  is  a  merely  formal  classifica- 
tion. No  attempt  is  made  to  trace  the  historical  relationships 
of  the  kinds  of  government  enumerated  to  one  another.1 

II.  Aristotle  was  as  far  as  Plato  from  perceiving  history  to 
be  the  subject  of  science  or  philosophy.  Had  he  conceived  of 
the  possibility  of  a  philosophy  of  history  he  would  not  have 
maintained  that  "poetry"  (epic  poetry)  "is  more  philosoph- 
ical and  earnest  than  history."  His  argument  for  this  conclu- 
sion rests  wholly  on  the  assumption  that  history  treats  only 
of  the  particular,  multiple,  and  isolated,  —  that  it  is  devoid  of 
unity  and  unconcerned  with  the  universal.  But  this  is  as  es- 
sentially an  untrue  and  unworthy  view  of  history  as  that  im- 
plied in  the  Platonic  doctrine  of  ideas.  In  reality,  philosophy 
can  never  exhaust  the  truth  and  significance,  or  art  fully  dis- 
close the  earnestness  and  pathos,  of  history.  Epic  poetry  is 
only  the  artistic  expression  of  the  same  kind  of  unity,  and  the 
suggestion  of  the  same  kind  of  universality,  as  are  to  be  found 
in  history  itself.  It  is  philosophical  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  a 
revelation  of  the  spirit  which  pervades  human  life  in  suffering, 
struggle,  and  achievement. 

Aristotle  saw,  however,  with  singular  clearness,  the  import- 
ance of  history  to  political  science  and  practice.  He  regarded 
politics  as  having  two  sources,  ethics  and  history,  the  latter 
supplying  it  with  the  matter  of  experience  needed  for  correct 
theorising.  He  sought  as  a  political  teacher  to  master  and 
utilise  all  past  political  experience.  He  made  a  close  and  de- 
tailed study  of  the  history  of  Greek  governments.  He  even 
compiled  a  "  Collection  of  the  constitutions  of  Greek  cities," 
which  summed  up  the  results  of  his  investigations  into  a  hun- 
dred and  fifty-eight  nroXiTeiat.  After  this  work  had  for  many 
centuries  been  supposed  to  have  been  irrecoverably  lost,  the 

1  Among  the  host  of  Greek  scholars  who  have  treated  of  the  political,  social,  and 
historical  theories  of  Plato,  it  may  he  sufficient  to  name  Hermann,  Stuhr,  Zeller, 
Hildenbrand,  Oncken,  Janet,  Fouille'e,  Grote,  Jowett,  L.  Campbell,  Newman,  &c. 
On  the  '  Statesman '  see  the  IStudes  sur  le  Politique  attribute  a  Platon,  par  M. 
Huit  (C.  R.  des  Se'ances  et  Travaux  de  l'Acad.  des  Sc.  Mor.  et  Pol.,  Oct.-Nov.  1877 
et  Janv.-Fev.  1888). 


148  INTRODUCTION 

portion  of  it  which  related  to  Athens  came  to  light,  although 
not  unmutilated,  in  1890,  and  is  now  before  the  public  as  ed- 
ited by  Mr.  Kenyon.  It  consists  of  two  sections.  The  first  of 
these  (ch.  1-41)  is  a  sketch  of  the  constitutional  history  of 
Athens,  and  the  second  (ch.  42-63)  is  an  account  of  the  means 
and  processes  of  government.  The  former  is  of  great  histori- 
cal interest.  It  seems  almost  to  entitle  us  to  call  Aristotle  the 
father  of  constitutional  history.  It  traces  the  constitution  of 
Athens  from  its  first  beginning  through  ten  stages  of  develop- 
ment into  its  eleventh  and  last  phase  of  existence,  the  re-estab- 
lishment of  democracy  after  the  expulsion  of  the  Thirty  and 
their  successors.  The  vision,  the  spirit,  and  the  method  of  a 
truly  scientific  historian  are  conspicuous  in  the  brief  but  pro- 
found and  dispassionate  account  which  Aristotle  has  therein 
given  of  the  rise  and  fall  of  the  most  interesting  democracy 
which  has  ever  run  its  course  on  earth. 

For  a  knowledge  of  his  historical  generalisations  and  deduc- 
tions, however,  we  must  still  have  recourse  to  his  '  Politics.' 
It  contains  ample  evidence  of  the  comprehensiveness  and 
thoroughness  of  his  investigations.  From  the  solidity  and 
massiveness  of  the  political  system  which  it  delineates  we 
can  discern  with  what  care  and  labour  and  mastery  of  method 
the  foundations  had  been  laid  and  the  materials  extracted  and 
tested.  It  was  not  merely  the  constitutions  of  Greek  cities 
which  had  been  studied ;  inquiries  had  been  instituted  even 
into  the  customs  of  barbarous  tribes.  The  whole  social  life 
of  mankind,  so  far  as  credible  knowledge  of  it  was  accessible 
to  him,  seems  to  have  been  closely  scanned  by  the  immortal 
Stagyrite.  It  is  not  too  much,  in  fact,  to  claim  for  him  the 
honour  of  having  studied  politics  according  to  the  historical 
method,  and  anticipated  "  comparative  politics." 

The  historical  method  may  be  abused.  Probably  most  of 
those  who  profess  to  follow  it  suppose  that  it  will  take  them 
farther  than  it  can.  It  is  necessarily  inadequate  to  the  proof 
of  natural  law  or  scientific  truth.  It  can  only  reach  histori- 
cal truth  —  only  show  that  such  and  such  events  have  taken 
place  in  such  and  such  an  order ;  it  can  never  establish  the 
naturalness  or  justice  of  the  order.  Aristotle  sometimes  over- 
looked this.  History  showed  him  that  slavery  had  been  uni- 
versal in  the  ancient  world,  as  much  so  as  the  family  or  the 


ARISTOTLE  149 

State,  and  he  inferred  that  slavery  was  a  law  of  nature,  — 
that  it  was  natural  in  the  sense  of  normal  and  right.  Every 
inference  of  the  kind  must  he  erroneous.  No  amount  of 
history  is  sufficient  to  prove  any  institution  to  be  a  law  of 
nature,  normal,  right.  All  that  history  can  show  regarding 
any  institution  is  how  long  and  how  widely  it  has  existed. 

Aristotle,  however,  being  no  mere  empiricist,  did  not  trust 
to  the  historical  method  alone  in  politics,  but  combined  it  with 
the  teleological.  He  traced  the  course  of  things  in  order  to 
determine  the  nature  of  things ;  but  he  was  guided  in  his 
manner  of  doing  so  by  a  general  conception  of  their  ends, 
holding  that  the  nature  of  things  is  the  realisation  of  their 
ends.  To  trace  the  development  of  things  was  regarded  by 
him  as  a  means  to  their  knowledge,  yet  as  only  possible  in 
the  light  of  a  certain  knowledge  of  their  natures  and  ends. 
Hence  he,  too,  like  Plato,  elaborately  endeavoured  to  deline- 
ate the  ideal,  of  a  best  State.  Three  books  of  the  '  Politics ' 
(iii.,  vii.,  viii.)  are  devoted  to  the  task.  But  the  ideal  deline- 
ated is  not  claimed  to  be  that  of  the  absolutely  best.  There 
is  no  government  which  is  the  best  for  all  races  in  all  circum- 
stances. Every  actually  best  government  must  conform  to 
actual  conditions  and  relations ;  and  the  actually  best,  the 
best  practicable  in  definite  circumstances,  is  that  which  the 
practical  politician  must  always  aim  at  realising.  The  ideally 
best  State  is,  therefore,  only  a  generally  best,  and  can  only  be 
described  in  a  general  manner.  It  is  the  State  so  organised 
as  to  enable  the  citizens  to  live  in  the  best  and  happiest  way. 
To  this  end  it  must  be  a  city  of  limited  size,  salubriously  situ- 
ated, near  enough  the  sea  to  have  a  harbour,  but  not  so  near 
as  to  attract  numerous  strangers.  It  must  have  slaves  to  till 
its  soil  and  man  its  navy.  All  engaged  in  trade  and  com- 
merce should  be  excluded  from  a  share  in  its  government. 
Each  citizen  ought  to  be  a  landowner,  but  not  very  rich,  and 
entitled  to  take  part  in  public  affairs  when  of  ripe  age.  The 
youths  are  to  be  subjected  from  the  seventh  to  the  twenty- 
first  year  to  a  course  of  instruction  fitted  to  make  them 
efficient  soldiers,  capable  citizens,  and  virtuous,  cultured, 
thoughtful  men.  Religious  worship  is  to  be  endowed  and 
regulated  with  a  view  to  the  promotion  of  the  general  good. 

Aristotle  made  no  attempt  to  draw  any  general  plan,  or  to 


150  INTRODUCTION 

form  any  general  picture  of  human  history.  He  did  not 
enunciate  any  general  law  of  historical  development.  But 
he  was  keenly  interested  in  the  political  history  of  Greece, 
and  that  he  saw  to  be  a  natural  process,  every  stage  and  change 
of  which  could  be  explained  by  their  social  antecedents.  Man 
is  represented  as  by  nature  a  social  being,  a  political  animal. 
Society  is  not  a  mere  outgrowth  of  egoism,  or  a  mere  inven- 
tion of  individuals.  Individuals  can  no  more  exist  without 
society  than  society  without  individuals.  The  first  form  of 
society  is  the  family ;  out  of  it  arises  the  village  community ; 
then  from  that  grows  up  the  State.  Hence  the  earliest  form 
of  political  government  is  the  patriarchal  or  regal ;  the  sort 
of  rule  which  is  characteristic  of  the  family  is  continued  into 
the  village,  and  thence  passes  into  the  State. 

The  State  itself  has  various  forms,  which  are  all  unstable, 
and  consequently  society  is  subject  to  many  revolutions. 
Aristotle's  chief  contribution  to  historical  science  is  to  have 
so  successfully  worked  out  the  theory  of  these  revolutions. 
Plato  had  indeed  already  presented  it  ingeniously  and 
grandly ;  but  Aristotle,  with  larger  knowledge  and  a  more 
critical  judgment,  tested  Plato's  conclusions  by  comparison 
with  the  relevant  facts,  reaffirmed  or  rejected  them,  added 
others  of  his  own,  and  in  all  respects  strengthened  and 
improved  the  doctrine.  His  classification  of  governments 
rests  on  the  two  principles  —  that  government  may  be  in  the 
hands  of  one,  or  of  a  few,  or  of  the  many,  and  that  it  may  be 
exercised. either  for  the  common  good  or  for  the  advantage  of 
the  rulers.  Hence  each  form  of  government  may  be  good  or 
bad,  and  good  or  bad  government  may  have  three  forms. 
Thus  the  States  or  forms  of  government  are  these  six  — 
monarchy,  aristocracy,  and  polity  (the  constitutional  repub- 
lic), and  tyranny,  oligarchy,  and  democracy.  Each  has  its 
peculiar  advantages  and  disadvantages,  facilities  and  difficul- 
ties, &c,  which  are  described.  Monarchy  might  be  the 
best  could  the  perfect  king  be  secured,  but  that  is  very 
improbable.  Aristocracy,  if  pure,  will  also  be  excellent,  but 
it  is  seldom  found  uncorrupted.  The  polity  is  the  best  gen- 
erally attainable  government.  Tyranny  is  the  worst  form  of 
government.     Democracy  is  never  good,  but  it  may  be  the 


ARISTOTLE  151 

least  bad,  and  will  become  a  necessity  whenever  wealth 
abounds  and  the  trading  classes  acquire  influence.  A  gov- 
ernment which  would  endure  must  avoid  one-sidedness,  the 
excessive  assertion  of  its  own  particular  principle  or  charac- 
ter ;  a  democracy  must  not  be  too  equalitarian,  an  oligarchy 
too  exclusive,  or  a  tyranny  too  despotic.  Political  stability 
requires  moderation  ;  the  more  wisely  mixed  a  political  con- 
stitution is,  the  more  durable  it  will  be.  Aristotle  exhibits 
the  general  and  special,  internal  and  external,  causes  of  politi- 
cal revolutions  ;  dwells  on  the  kinds  of  revolution  peculiar  to 
each  form  of  government ;  and  indicates  the  various  means 
by  which  political  stability  may  best  be  secured.  He  has 
neglected  to  trace  the  influence  both  of  war  and  religion  in 
effecting  political  change.  It  may  be  noted  that  by  his  theory 
of  the  three  powers  or  functions  of  government  —  the  legis- 
lative, executive,  and  judicial  —  he  anticipated  Montesquieu, 
and  by  his  reflections  on  tyranny  the  system  of  Macchiavelli. 

Aristotle's  vindication  of  the  principle  of  self-love  or  ele- 
ment of  individuality,  of  the  family,  and  of  property,  against 
the  attacks  of  Plato,  may  justly  be  regarded  as  a  service 
rendered  to  historical  as  well  as  to  political  truth. 

Like  Plato,  he  had  no  conception  of  a  nation  in  the  higher 
sense,  and  consequently  no  anticipation  of  the  part  which 
nationality  was  to  play  in  the  history  of  the  world.  Like 
Plato,  he  supposed  the  arts  and  institutions  of  civilisation  to 
have  been  many  times  invented  and  lost.  He  modified  the 
generalisation  of  Plato  as  to  the  characteristics  of  the  races 
of  mankind,  ascribing  to  the  northern  peoples  courage,  to  the 
eastern  peoples  intelligence,  and  to  the  Greeks  the  combina- 
tion of  courage  and  intellect. 

What  Aristotle  did  for  the  history  of  philosophy  should 
also  be  here  called  to  mind.  The  history  of  philosophy  and 
the  philosophy  of  history  are  so  intimately  connected,  that  a 
direct  service  to  the  former  must  be  at  least  an  indirect  ser- 
vice to  the  latter.  But  Aristotle  was  the  first  to  survey  the 
history  of  philosophy  with  a  philosophical  eye.  By  the  way 
in  which  he  traced  in  his  '  Metaphysics '  the  development  of 
Greek  speculation  through  the  systems  of  his  predecessors, 
he  established  a  right  to  be  regarded  as  the  originator  of  the 


152  INTRODUCTION 

philosophical  method  of  studying  and  presenting  the  history 
of  philosophy. 1 

III.  Christianity  assumed  and  involved  a  theory  of  history. 
In  the  writings  of  St.  Paul  and  various  of  the  Christian  fathers, 
the  theory  attained  to  partial  expression ;  in  the  '  De  Civitate 
Dei '  of  St.  Augustine  it  found  its  first  general  statement. 

Augustine  was  one  of  the  greatest  and  most  influential 
personalities  who  have  appeared  in  the  whole  history  of  the 
Church.  He  was  splendidly  endowed  both  intellectually  and 
spiritually.  His  rich  and  powerful  mind  contained  qualities 
which  are  seldom  united,  — fertility  of  imagination  and  keen- 
ness of  judgment,  speculative  subtilty  and  rhetorical  fervour, 
introspectiveness  and  practical  energy,  vehemence  and  tender- 
ness. He  passed  through  the  most  varied  phases  of  experi- 
ence ;  had  been  Aristotelian,  Manichean,  Sceptic,  Platonist, 
and  Neo-Platonist,  before  he  surrendered  himself  to  the 
guidance  of  Christ  and  Paul;  and  when  converted,  gave  him- 
self to  the  service  of  his  new  faith  with  passionate  devotion. 
He  was  saint,  philosopher,  orator,  man  of  letters,  man  of 
counsel,  man  of  action.  More,  perhaps,  than  any  of  the 
fathers,  of  the  schoolmen,  or  of  the  reformers,  he  has  influ- 
enced the  doctrinal  development  of  Christendom. 

The  '  De  Civitate  Dei '  is  his  most  elaborate  and  probably  his 
most  valuable  work,  —  the  one  which  cost  him  most  toil,  and 
gives  the  most  complete  conception  of  his  abilities.  It  was 
begun  about  413,  and  not  finished  before  426.  The  resolution 
to  write  it  was  occasioned  by  the  accusations  brought  against 
Christianity,  after  Rome  had  been  captured  by  Alaric  and  the 
Goths.  That  event  led  many  to  think  and  say  that  the  old 
religion  of  their  fathers  under  which  Rome  had  flourished  and 
become  the  mistress  of  the  world,  was  better  than  the  new  one, 
under  which  she  had  declined  and  become  the  prey  and  scorn 
of  barbarians.  Augustine  sought  to  repel  the  reproach.  He 
traced  the  causes  of  Rome's  fall  to  the  vices  of  paganism,  and 
ascribed  what  remained  to  her  of  good  to  the  saving  virtue  of 

1  On  the  political,  social,  and  historical  views  of  Aristotle  it  may  he  sufficient 
to  refer  merely  to  the  works  of  Oncken  (Die  Staatslehre  ties  A.)  and  Newman 
(Politics  of  A.) .  My  remark  relative  to  the  Metaphysics,  B.  xiii.  xiv.,  is  not  meant 
to  imply  that  Aristotle  gave  an  accurate  account  of  the  early  Greek  philosophies. 
It  refers  simply  to  his  mode  of  interpreting  and  exhibiting  them. 


AUGUSTINK  153 

the  Gospel ;  and  over  against  the  earthly  ideal  which  she  rep- 
resented he  set  the  divine  ideal  represented  by  the  Church  of 
Christ.  The  great  work  in  which  he  did  so  is  not,  as  Ozanam 
and  others  have  said,  a  philosophy  of  history,  nor  even  an 
attempt  at  a  philosophy  of  history ;  it  is  properly  neither  phil- 
osophical nor  historical,  but  theological  —  a  polemic  against 
paganism,  and  an  apology  for  Christianity  of  remarkable 
breadth  and  elevation  of  design,  of  remarkable  vigour  and 
skill  of  execution.  It  contains,  however,  a  nearer  approxi- 
mation to  a  philosophy  of  history  than  will  be  found  in  anv 
other  patristic  or  scholastic  treatise ;  and  a  statement  of  the 
characteristic  principles  of  the  historical  theory  set  forth  in  it 
may  here  be  reasonably  demanded. 

They  may,  perhaps,  be  thus  concisely  reproduced.  (1.)  The 
human  race  was  created  less  than  six  thousand  years  before  the 
capture  of  Rome  by  the  Goths.  All  documents  which  assign 
to  it  a  greater  antiquity  than  the  Biblical  records  (as  inter- 
preted on  this  point  by  the  Eusebian  chronology)  are  men- 
dacious ;  and  all  the  theories  which,  like  that  of  Apuleius, 
represent  men  as  having  always  been,  or  which,  like  that  of 
some  of  the  Stoics,  affirm  the  perpetual  revolution  of  all  things 
in  cycles  which  bring  men  with  the  rest  of  the  world  round 
again  to  the  same  order  and  form  as  at  first,  are  foolish.  Wiry 
men  were  not  created  sooner  is  an  inconsiderate  question, 
which  might  be  put  with  the  same  relevancy  and  force  no 
matter  when  they  were  created  (lib.  xii.  cap.  10-20). 

(2.)  The  human  race  is  a  single  species;  all  its  members 
are  descended  from  one  man,  and  therefore  bound  together, 
not  only  by  similarity  of  nature,  but  by  ties  of  kinship.  In 
that  one  first  man  the  whole  race  was  comprehended,  and  in 
him  God  foresaw  what  portion  of  it  was  to  live  according  to 
the  Spirit,  and  obtain  eternal  life,  and  what  to  live  according 
to  the  flesh,  and  incur  eternal  condemnation  (xii.  21  et  27). 

(3.)  God  who  has  everywhere  impressed  on  nature  regu- 
larity, beauty,  and  order — who  has  done  everything  in  the 
physical  world  according  to  number,  weight,  and  measure  — 
who  has  left  not  even  the  entrails  of  the  smallest  and  meanest 
living  creature,  the  feather  of  a  bird,  the  little  flower  of  a 
plant,  or  the  leaf  of  a  tree,  without  its  exquisite  harmony 
of  parts,  —  cannot  have  left  the  course  of  human  affairs,  the 


154  INTRODUCTION 

growth  and  decay  of  nations,  their  victories  and  defeats,  un- 
regulated by  the  laws  of  His  providence.1  The  vicissitudes 
of  empire  can  have  their  reason  neither  in  chance — i.e.,  the 
absence  of  a  cause,  or  the  action  of  causes  which  operate  in 
no  intelligible  order  —  nor  in  fate,  if  by  fate  be  meant  what 
happens  of  necessity  independently  of  the  will  of  God;  but 
only  in  that  will  itself,  in  a  divinely  foreordained  plan  em- 
bracing all  things  and  times,  yet  not  inconsistent  with  men 
doing  freely  whatever  they  feel  to  be  done  by  them  simply 
because  they  will  it  (v.  1,  8-11). 

(4.)  The  human  race,  naturally  one,  had  its  unity  broken 
by  the  fall  or  sin  of  Adam,  from  whom  have  issued  in  conse- 
quence two  kinds  of  men,  two  societies,  two  great  cities ;  the 
one  ruled  by  self-will  and  self-love,  the  other  by  the  love 
of  God  and  man,  —  the  one  subject  to  condemnation  and 
destined  to  eternal  misery,  the  other  UDder  grace  and  certain 
of  eternal  felicity.  Outwardly,  visibly,  bodily,  these  two 
societies  or  cities  of  men  may  be  confounded  ;  but  inwardly, 
really,  and  spiritually,  they  are  essentially  and  eternally  dis- 
tinct and  hostile.  No  other  division  of  men  can  compare  in 
importance  with  this ;  and  to  it  all  other  divisions,  whether 
based  on  distinctions  of  speech,  race,  or  government,  must  be 
subordinated  (xiv.  1,  28,  xv.  1). 

(5.)  Man  has  been  endowed  with  a  marvellous  capacity  of 
progress,  and  his  genius,  partly  under  the  stimulus  of  neces- 
sity, partly  from  its  own  inherent  inventiveness,  has  devised 
and  elaborated  countless  arts ;  has  made  amazing  advances 
in  weaving  and  building,  agriculture  and  navigation,  in  pot- 
tery, painting,  and  sculpture,  in  the  means  of  destruction  and 
the  appliances  of  healing,  in  exciting  and  satisfying  appetite, 
in  the  communication  of  thoughts  and  feelings,  in  music  and 
musical  instruments,  in  measuring  and  numbering,  in  the 
knowledge  of  the  stars  and  of  the  rest  of  nature,  and  in 
philosophical  subtlety  (xxii.  24,  sec.  3). 

(6.)  Like  the  education  of  an  individual,  that  of  the  race, 
as  represented  by  the  people  of  God,  has  advanced  through 
certain  epochs  or  ages,  in  order  that  the  human  mind  might 

1  The  beautiful  passage  (v.  11)  partially  translated  in  the  above  sentence 
must,  I  think,  have  suggested  another  equally  beautiful  in  Herder's  Preface  to 
his  '  Ideen. ' 


AUGUSTINE  155 

gradually  rise  from  temporal  to  eternal,  from  visible  to  in- 
visible things  (x.  14).  Augustine  has  made  great  use  of  this 
idea,  that  the  development  of  humanity  is  analogous  to  that 
of  the  individual,  while  at  the  same  time  aware  that  the  com- 
parison or  parallelism  was  not  absolutely  exact.  Indeed  he 
has  ill  several  of  his  works  distinctly  pointed  out  one  im- 
portant respect  in  which  it  fails  — viz.,  that  while  age  in  the 
individual  is  weakness,  in  humanity  it  is  perfection.  He  less 
distinctly  felt,  although  not  quite  unconscious  of  it,  that  differ- 
ent periods  may  coexist  in  the  development  of  the  race,  while 
they  must  necessarily  be  successive  in  that  of  the  individual. 
(7.)  The  epochs  of  history  are  sometimes  regarded  by 
Augustine  as  two,  sometimes  as  three,  and  sometimes  as  six. 
The  twofold  division  is  that  into  history  before,  and  history 
after  Christ ;  the  time  of  preparation  for  the  Gospel,  and  the 
time  of  its  diffusion  and  triumph.  The  threefold  division 
is  into  the  youth,  manhood,  and  old  age  of  humanity,  or  the 
reigns  of  nature,  law,  and  grace.  And  the  sixfold  division  is 
essentially  a  further  application  of  the  principle  which  under- 
lies the  threefold  division,  although  also  referred  to  a  fanciful 
analogy  between  the  epochs  of  history  and  the  days  of  crea- 
tion, which  has  often  been  reproduced  since  by  writers  who 
have  allowed  imagination  to  master  reason.  The  epoch  of 
youth  is  characterised  by  the  absence  of  law,  and  compre- 
hends the  two  periods  of  infancy  and  boyhood.  In  the  first, 
which  extends  from  Adam  to  Noah,  man  is  absorbed  in  the 
satisfaction  of  his  physical  wants,  and  soon  forgets  whatever 
happens  to  him  ;  in  the  second,  which  extends  from  Noah  to 
Abraham,  the  division  of  languages  takes  place,  and  memory 
begins  to  be  exercised  in  recalling  and  retaining  the  past. 
The  manhood  of  the  race,  or  reign  of  law,  extends  from 
Abraham  to  Christ.  It  is  marked  by  the  growth  of  reason 
and  of  the  sense  of  sin.  The  spirit  struggles  with  the  evil 
in  the  world,  and  through  defeat  is  made  conscious  of  its 
weakness  and  depravity.  This  epoch  may  be  regarded  as  em- 
bracing three  periods  :  the  first  reaching  from  Abraham  to 
David ;  the  second  from  David  to  the  Babylonian  captivity ; 
and  the  third  coming  down  to  the  birth  of  Christ.  In  the 
course  of  it  flourished  the  two  great  heathen  empires  of  As- 
syria and  Rome,  of  which  all  other  heathen  kingdoms  may  be 


156  INTRODUCTION 

viewed  as  appendages.  The  old  age  of  humanity,  or  reign  of 
grace,  is  the  whole  Christian  era.  It  is  the  time  in  which  the 
Church  is  enabled  through  the  power  of  the  Spirit  to  conquer 
the  world ;  and  it  will  last  until  the  victory  is  complete,  and 
the  saints  inherit  the  earth  in  eternal  blessedness.  No  fewer 
than  five  books  of  the  'De  Civitate  Dei'  (xv.-xix.)  are  de- 
voted to  trace  through  these  various  epochs  of  time,  the 
growth  and  progress  of  humanity  in  its  two  great  divisions, 
or,  in  other  words,  the  fortunes  of  the  heavenly  and  earthly 
cities :  but,  although  full  of  theological  interest,  there  will  be 
found  no  signs  in  them  of  the  presence  of  either  the  spirit  or 
the  method  of  historical  science ;  indeed,  they  consist  mainly 
of  comments  and  conjectures  on  the  Biblical  narrative.  The 
earthly  city  and  its  history  get  little  attention  and  still  less 
justice.  The  history  of  the  heavenly  city  itself,  although  dis- 
coursed of  in  these  books  at  great  length,  is  not  divided  into 
an  orderly  series  of  periods,  or  stages  of  development.  The 
division  which  I  have  just  described  can,  at  the  most,  be  only 
said  to  be  implied  in  the  exposition  given  in  the  '  De  Civitate 
Dei.'  Its  explicit  statement,  the  definite  limiting  and  char- 
acterising of  the  periods,  I  have  had  to  take  from  a  much 
earlier  work,  the  '  De  Genesi  contra  Manichaeos '  (i.  23). 

(8.)  Another  theorem  of  St.  Augustine  is,  that  although 
out  of  the  city  of  God,  or  apart  from  true  religion,  there  can 
be  no  true  virtue,  although  all  that  is  not  of  faith  is  sin,  and 
the  natural  virtues  of  heathen  peoples  must,  in  consequence, 
be  only  apparent  virtues,  still  such  virtues  may  merit  and  re- 
ceive increase  of  dominion  and  other  temporal  rewards,  as  well 
a§  serve  as  examples  and  incentives  to  Christians.  Of  this 
the  grand  proof  in  his  eyes  was  Rome ;  and  he  has  insisted 
with  singular  eloquence  that  the  ancient  Romans  deserved  for 
their  industry,  moderation,  freedom  from  luxury  and  licen- 
tiousness, skill  in  government,  and  even  desire  of  glory  — 
since  that,  although  a  vice  in  itself,  restrained  many  greater 
vices  —  to  be  raised  to  the  height  of  power  which  they 
reached ;  and  that  the  heroic  deeds  of  Brutus  and  Torquatus, 
of  Camillus,  Mucius,  and  Cincinnatus,  the  Decii,  Pulvillus, 
and  Regulus,  might  well  humble  even  the  most  devoted  of 
the  followers  of  Jesus  (vi.  12-20). 

(9.)  The  city  of  God,  which  has  from  the  first  grown  up 


AUGUSTINE  157 

alongside  of  the  kingdoms  of  this  world,  will  outlast  them  all ; 
and  although  they  have  often  despised  and  oppressed  it,  will 
appear  invested  with  immortal  beauty  and  honour  when  their 
glories  have  been  extinguished  for  ever.  Immutable  and 
invincible  amidst  all  the  instability,  agitation,  and  strife  of 
human  things,  it  is  continually  drawing  into  itself  its  pre- 
destined number  of  inhabitants  out  of  all  nations,  tribes,  and 
peoples.  When  the  unknown  hour  arrives  which  sees  their 
number  completed,  the  last  of  the  elect  passed  from  the  city  of 
the  world  into  that  of  God,  then  cometh  Christ  to  judge  the 
quick  and  the  dead,  and  finally  to  separate  the  good  from 
the  evil ;  and  at  His  word,  above  the  ruins  of  those  cities  of  the 
world  that  have  passed  away  into  the  darkness  of  their  eternal 
doom;  there  rises  in  the  light  of  God's  love,  on  a  new  and 
purified  earth,  a  new,  peaceful,  and  perfectly  happy  city, 
which  is  imperishable,  and  which  contains  all  the  truly  good 
men  who  have  ever  lived. 

These  are  the  leading  propositions  of  what  we  may  call  in  a 
lax  and  general  way  the  Augustinian  philosophy  of  history, 
which  was  substantially  the  only  one  known  in  medieval 
Europe,  and  which  has  reappeared  in  modern  times  in  many 
forms  and  with  more  or  less  important  modifications.  There 
are  still  those  who  accept  it  as  the  only  philosophy  of  history 
possible  or  desirable ;  but  the  vast  majority  of  thoughtful  minds 
are  now  probably  in  greater  danger  of  overlooking  than  of 
overestimating  its  worth  in  any  other  than  a  religious  refer- 
ence. Its  defects  are  numerous  and  obvious.  It  subordinates 
all  things  to  the  Church  in  a  false  and  misleading  way, 
depreciates  and  degrades  secular  life,  takes  no  account  at  all 
of  many  an  important  people,  and  of  the  very  greatest  of  those 
which  it  condescends  to  notice  gives  most  superficial  and 
partial  views.  Its  assertion  of  the  existence,  power,  and 
wisdom  of,the  First  Providential  Cause,  however  admirable 
it  may  be  in  itself,  is  unsupported  by  adequate  proof,  that 
being  only  attainable  by  the  investigation  of  secondary  causes, 
which  are  neglected.  It  virtually  identifies  the  history  of  a 
special  people,  the  Jewish,  as  recorded  for  a  special  purpose 
in  the  canonical  books  of  Scripture,  with  the  history  of  human- 
ity, so  far  as  recoverable  from  any  kind  of  genuine  monument 
or  memorial  by  any  kind  of  sound  research.     It  ignores,  or 


158  INTRODUCTION 

fails  worthily  to  appreciate,  art,  literature,  science,  philosophy, 
natural  and  ethnic  religion,  law,  politics,  and,  in  a  word,  almost 
every  phase  of  ordinary  human  life  and  culture.  Instead  of 
attempting  truly  and  impartially  to  explain  history,  it  seeks 
to  convert  it  into  an  illustration  and  verification  of  a  theo- 
logical system.  It  so  emphasises  the  distinction  between  elect 
and  non-elect  as  virtually  to  deny  the  unity  of  humanity.  It 
represents  the  kingdom  of  the  devil  as  not  less  enduring  and 
more  populous  than  that  of  God,  so  that  the  ultimate  goal  of 
history  is  for  the  majority  of  human  souls  one  of  eternal  sin 
and  suffering. 

With  all  its  defects,  however,  it  was  a  vast  improvement  on 
previous  theories  of  history,  or  rather  on  the  previous  want  of 
a  theory.  It  explicitly  affirmed  the  historical  unity  and'prog- 
ress  which  to  some  extent  it  implicitly  denied.  It  recognised 
the  importance  of  the  moral  and  spiritual  in  the  life  and  move- 
ment of  humanity.  It  represented  history  as  one  great  whole 
guided  by  principles  and  proceeding  to  solemn  issues  through 
an  orderly  series  of  stages.  It  made  apparent  that  the  knowl- 
edge of  history  bears  closely  on  the  highest  problems  of  specu- 
lation. The  ultimate  and  greatest  triumph  of  historical  philos- 
ophy may  not  unreasonably  be  expected  to  be  the  full  proof 
of  Providence,  the  discovery  by  the  processes  of  scientific 
method  of  the  divine  plan  which  unites  and  harmonises  the 
apparent  chaos  of  human  actions  contained  in  history  into  a 
cosmos.  The  historical  theory  of  Augustine  was  the  first  sus- 
tained and  comprehensive  attempt  to  trace  such  a  plan,  and 
although  far  from  scientific  in  its  character,  it  well  deserves, 
in  the  main,  the  admiration  which  it  has  received. 

IV.  The  first  writer  to  treat  history  as  the  proper  object 
of  a  special  science  was  Mohammed  Ibn  Khaldun.  Whether 
on  this  account  he  is  to  be  regarded  or  not  as  the  founder  of 
the  science  of  history  is  a  question  as  to  which  there  may 
well  be  difference  of  opinion ;  but  no  candid  reader  of  his 
'  Prolegomena '  (Mocaddemaf)  can  fail  to  admit  that  his  claim 
to  the  honour  is  more  valid  than  that  of  any  other  author 
previous  to  Vico. 

Our  knowledge  of  his  life  is  drawn  chiefly  from  an  auto- 
biography which  stops  short  at  the  year  1394  (a.h.  797), 


LBN    KHALDUK  159 

twelve  years  before  his  death.  It  seems  obviously  accurate 
and  honest,  and  is  sufficiently  full  and  detailed,  yet  reveals 
little  of  the  writer's  inner  self,  and  portrays  but  indistinctly 
his  outer  life  and  its  surroundings.  It  has  no  remarkable 
merits. 

Ibn  Khaldun  was  born  at  Tunis  in  1332.  He  descended 
from  an  ancient  Arab  tribe  of  Hadramaut,  and  from  a  family 
which  for  some  centuries  exercised  great  influence  in  Spain. 
On  the  fall  of  the  Ommayades  his  ancestors  settled  in  North 
Africa.  He  received  a  careful  education,  showed  great  apti- 
tude for  learning,  and  was  at  an  early  age  licensed  to  teach  a 
variety  of  subjects.  Among  his  acquirements  were  knowl- 
edge of  the  Koran,  of  ancient  Arabic  poetry,  of  the  religious 
traditions,  and  of  grammar,  logic,  mathematics,  jurisprudence, 
dogmatic  theology,  and  philosophy.  It  did  not  fall  to  his  lot 
in  life  to  have  much  learned  leisure,  but  his  thirst  for  knowl- 
edge and  his  love  of  literature  remained  always  keen  and 
strong.  At  the  age  of  twenty  he  began  his  political  career 
by  entering  the  service  of  the  Sultan  of  Tunis,  Ibn  Ishac  II. ; 
two  years  later  he  passed  into  that  of  the  Sultan  of  Fez,  Abu 
Einan.  The  favour  at  first  shown  him  by  the  latter  sover- 
eign gave  rise  to  jealousy  and  intrigues  which  led  to  his 
disgrace  and  imprisonment.  In  1359,  on  the  death  of  Abu 
Ei'nan,  he  was  released  by  Abu  Salem  and  appointed  secre- 
tary of  state.  He  was  still,  however,  the  object  of  envy  and 
calumny,  and  after  the  death  of  Abu  Salem,  his  intercourse 
with  the  powerful  Vizir  Omar  became  so  unpleasant  that  he 
left  the  Court,  and  soon  after  passed  into  Spain,  where  he 
was  received  with  great  favour  by  Ibn  El-Ahmer,  to  whom 
he  had  rendered  important  services  in  Africa.  In  the  follow- 
ing year  he  was  at  Seville  as  the  ambassador  of  El-Ahmer  to 
Peter  the  Cruel,  King  of  Castile,  by  whom  he  was  graciously 
treated. 

He  returned  to  Africa  in  1365  as  prime  minister  of  a 
former  friend,  Ibn  Abdallah,  who  had  made  himself  master 
of  Begeyi.  After  this  prince  was  slain  in  a  battle  against 
Abdul-Abbas,  Sultan  of  Constantine,  Khaldun  led  for  some 
years  a  very  unsettled  and  unsafe  life,  amidst  warring  kings, 
and  dependent  on  the  friendship  of  the  chiefs  of  certain  pow- 
erful and  independent  tribes.     From  1370  to  1374  he  was 


160  INTRODUCTION 

in  the  service  of  the  sovereign  of  Morocco,  and  especially 
engaged  in  negotiations  and  expeditions  with  the  Arab  tribes. 
In  the  latter  year  he  passed  a  second  time  into  Spain,  but  was 
soon  forced  to  return.  Thereupon  he  withdrew  from  public 
life  for  four  years,  and  applied  himself  exclusively  to  study 
in  a  large  solitary  castle,  of  which  the  ruins  are  said  still  to 
be  remaining,  on  an  affluent  of  the  Mina,  in  the  province  of 
Oran.  In  this  retreat  he  composed  his  'Prolegomena,'  and 
began  his  '  History  of  the  Arabs  and  Berbers.'  To  continue 
the  latter  he  required  to  have  access  to  large  libraries,  and 
this  was  one  of  the  reasons  which  induced  him  in  1378  to 
revisit  Tunis. 

He  was  received  with  distinction  by  the  Sultan  Abdul- 
Abbas  and  the  general  body  of  the  citizens,  and  with  enthu- 
siasm by  the  students,  who  constrained  him  to  give  them 
instruction;  but  also  with  suspicion  and  aversion  by  a  formid- 
able party  of  courtiers,  headed  by  the  chief  mufti,  Ibn  Arfa. 
The  machinations  of  his  enemies  caused  him,  after  he  had 
composed  his  '  History  of  the  Berbers,'  to  resolve  on  making 
the  pilgrimage  to  Mecca.  Having  obtained  permission  to  de- 
part, he  sailed  in  October  1382  for  Egypt,  landed  in  Novem- 
ber at  Alexandria,  and  after  a  month's  stay  there,  proceeded 
to  Cairo.  His  fame  had  preceded  him,  and  as  no  caravans 
left  for  Mecca  that  year,  he  yielded  to  the  persuasions  of  the 
Sultan  Barkuk  to  accept  a  professorship  and  postpone  his 
pilgrimage.  He  was  afterwards  raised  to  the  chief  Malekite 
cadiship.  In  this  office  his  rigid  justice  and  his  zeal  against 
abuses  made  him  many  enemies  among  the  official  class.  At 
the  same  time  a  terrible  calamity  befell  him.  The  vessel  bear- 
ing his  family  from  Morocco  to  Egypt  was  wrecked,  and  by 
one  stroke  he  lost,  as  he  says,  his  wealth,  his  children,  and  his 
happiness.  He  was  overwhelmed  with  affliction,  and  could 
only  find  consolation  in  prayer.  In  1387  he  made  the  jour- 
ney to  Mecca,  and  thence  returned  to  Cairo.  For  a  time  he 
gave  himself  up  entirely  to  study  and  teaching.  His  auto- 
biography was  composed  in,  and  ends  with,  1394.  In  1400  he 
followed  Ferruj,  Sultan  of  Egypt,  in  his  expedition  into  Syria 
against  the  famous  Timur  (Tamerlane),  and  was  among  those 
who  were  besieged  in  Damascus.  On  his  surrender  of  him- 
self to  the  conqueror  he  was  treated  with  great  respect  and 


IBN   KHALDUN  161 

generosity.  Timur  showed  the  utmost  appreciation  of  Khal- 
dun's  gifts  and  knowledge,  and  Khaldun  showed  himself  a 
courtier  of  consummate  skill.  The  Tartar  monarch  would 
fain  have  taken  the  historian  to  Turkistan,  but  the  seductive 
tongue  of  the  Arab  politician  dissuaded  him  from  carrying 
the  desire  into  effect.  Khaldun  returned  to  Cairo,  and  re- 
entered public  life  as  chief  cadi.  He  died  in  1406,  at  the 
age  of  seventy-four. 

Even  from  the  foregoing  brief  summary  of  the  chief  inci- 
dents in  his  career,  it  will  be  apparent  that  Ibn  Khaldun  must 
have  been  an  altogether  remarkable  man.  Living  amidst  cir- 
cumstances the  most  complicated,  combinations  shifting  from 
day  to  day,  plots  and  intrigues,  despotic  arbitrariness  and  mean 
jealousies,  he  played  an  active  and  prominent  part  in  many  sit- 
uations. Although  often  cast  down,  he  as  often  rose  speedily 
up  again;  and,  he  remained  from  youth  to  age,  through  all  the 
vicissitudes  of  a  difficult  and  eventful  career,  distinguished 
and  influential,  courted  or  persecuted,  dreaded  or  admired. 
He  was  a  skilful  politician,  an  accomplished  courtier,  a  bril- 
liant member  of  society,  a  man  subtle  in  counsel,  persuasive  in 
speech,  pliant  in  adapting  himself  to  circumstances,  qualified 
for  themost  diverse  offices,  a  proficient  in  almost  every  liberal 
art  and  every  department  of  science  cultivated  by  his  Moham- 
medan contemporaries.  He  was,  perhaps,  not  wholly  devoid 
of  the  spirit  of  intrigue,  somewhat  too  conscious  of  his  own 
superiority,  and  inclined  to  exercise  power  with  rather  high  a 
hand.  Obviously  he  was  ambitious  of  eminence  and  fame 
both  in  politics  and  literature;  but  he  cannot  be  charged  with 
disregard  of  moral  principles  or  indulgence  in  vicious  habits. 
He  was  a  devout  and  strict  Mussulman. 

He  adhered  to  no  metaphysical  or  speculative  system  of 
philosophy.  Previous  to  the  fourteenth  century,  philosophy, 
in  all  Mohammedan  lands,  had  fallen  into  utter  disrepute; 
theological  orthodoxy  had,  wherever  the  Koran  was  acknowl- 
edged as  the  supreme  religious  authority,  completely  crushed 
out  of  existence  independent  thought  on  fundamental  prob- 
lems. In  this  reference  Ibn  Khaldun  did  not  rise  above  the 
spirit  of  his  age.  In  all  questions  relating  to  the  supra-sensu- 
ous world  he  placed  little  faith  in  reason  and  full  confidence 
in  revelation.    He  has  devoted  a  chapter  of  his  '  Prolegomena ' 


162  INTRODUCTION 

to  prove  that  philosophy  is  science  falsely  so  called,  and  not 
only  incapable  of  fulfilling  its  promises,  but,  as  hostile  to  re- 
ligion, naturally  hurtful.  He  grants  merely  that  a  knowledge 
of  its  history  is  of  some  value,  and  that  the  study  of  it  helps 
to  sharpen  the  logical  understanding.  He  affirms,  however, 
that  it  should  not  be  cultivated  except  by  those  who  have  been 
well  grounded  in  Koranic  exegesis  and  Islamic  jurisprudence. 
He  highly  esteemed  the  positive  sciences,  and  he  accepted  the 
teaching  of  Mohammed  and  the  dogmatic  theology  based  on 
it  as  deserving  of  implicit  trust,  but  he  regarded  the  free  exer- 
cise of  reason  in  the  spheres  of  religion  and  metaphysics  as 
delusive  and  pernicious.  Believing  in  no  philosophy,  he  was, 
of  course,  under  no  temptation  to  attempt  the  explanation  of 
history  by  philosophy.  The  Koran  contained  few  germs  of 
historical  doctrine.  Hence  Khaldun  could  only  form  histori- 
.cal  theories  by  drawing  them  directly  from  historical  facts. 
His  knowledge  of  historical  facts,  at  least  so  far  as  attainable 
from  oriental  sources,  was,  however,  vast  and  profound,  prac- 
tical and  living,  —  the  product  both  of  learned  research  and 
personal  experience.  He  had,  further,  a  rare  power  of  seeing 
into  the  nature  and  significance  of  social  phenomena,  and  a 
remarkable  facility  in  detecting  their  conditions  and  tracing 
their  connections.  He  was  an  excellent  generaliser.  It  is 
entirely  to  these  qualities  that  we  must  ascribe  his  success  as 
an  historical  thinker,  —  not  at  all  to  his  speculative  capacity 
or  the  excellence  of  his  philosophical  principles. 

Ibn  Khaldun  wrote  on  various  subjects.  His  minor  trea- 
tises had  a  temporary  popularity,  but  have  been  long  forgot- 
ten. His  fame  rests  securely,  however,  on  his  magnum  opus, 
the  '  Universal  History,'  and  especially  on  the  first  part  of  it, 
the  '  Prolegomena.'  The  second  part  comprises  the  history 
of  the  Arabs,  Nabatseans,  Syrians,  Persians,  Israelites,  Copts, 
Greeks,  Romans,  Turks,  and  Franks.  The  third  or  last  part 
is  occupied  with  the  Berbers  and  neighbouring  peoples.  On 
these  two  latter  parts  —  the  strictly  historical  divisions  of  the 
work  —  only  a  very  few  specialists  can  be  entitled  to  pro- 
nounce a  judgment.  Their  author's  own  estimate  of  their 
originality,  conformity  to  the  requirements  of  science  and 
criticism,  and  value,  was  very  high.  There  can  be  little 
doubt  that  it  was  too  high.     The  most  competent  modern 


IBN   K.HALDUN  163 

critics  who  have  occupied  themselves  with  Ibn  Khaldun's 
'  Universal  History '  —  Dozy,  De  Slane,  and  Amari  —  agree 
in  recognising  that  as  an  historical  work  it  has  certain  seri- 
ous defects.  They  find  the  style  often  obscure  and  careless ; 
the  narrative  at  times  diffuse  and  impeded  in  its  motion  by 
superfluous  reasonings;  the  distribution  of  the  matter  or 
contents  such  as  leads  to  frequent  repetitions ;  and  the  tes- 
timony of  the  original  authorities  relied  on  not  always  cor- 
rectly reported.  All  this  may  very  probably  be  true.  Had 
Ibn  Khaldun  written  what  would  in  the  present  day  be 
deemed  a  truly  scientific  history,  he  would  have  performed  a 
far  more  extraordinary  feat  than  that  which  he  accomplished 
as  an  historical  theorist.  It  is  scarcely  conceivable,  indeed, 
that  such  a  history  could  be  written  in  a  Semitic  language. 

The  '  Prolegomena '  must  now  receive  our  exclusive  atten- 
tion. They  may  fairly  be  regarded  as  forming  a  distinct 
and  complete  work.  Of  this  work  I  proceed  to  give  a  brief 
account.1 

It  consists  of  a  preface,  an  introduction,  and  six  sections  or 
divisions. 

In  the  preface  the  general  subject  of  the  work  is  said  to  be 
"history,  a  species  of  knowledge  universally  esteemed,  largely 
cultivated,  and  manifoldly  useful."  History  is  described  as 
being  in  external  form  the  display  or  delineation  of  the  events 
which  occur  throughout  the  course  of  ages  in  the  experience 
of  peoples  and  dynasties,  and  in  its  internal  characteristics 
the  examination  and  verification  of  facts,  the  attentive  inves- 
tigation of  their  causes,  and  a  profound  and  comprehensive 
insight  into  the  way  in  which  social  phenomena  have  been 
produced.  When  it  corresponds  to  this  its  true  nature,  his- 
tory "  deserves  to  be  counted  among  the  sciences."  The  aim 
of  Ibn  Khaldun's  work  is  to  raise  history  to  the  rank  of  a 
science.  This  aim,  he  considered,  no  previous  writer  had 
made  a  deliberate  and  sustained  endeavour  to  accomplish. 

The  introduction  dwells  chiefly  on  the  uncriticalness  of  his- 
torians and  its  causes.  Various  instances  are  given  of  their 
credulity  in  the  acceptance  of  testimony,  and  of  the  fallacious- 

1  Prolegomenes  d'Ebn-Khaldoun,  texte  Arabe  public  par  M.  Quatremere,  in 
Notices  et  Extr.  des  MSS.,  t.  xvi.-xviii.  Paris,  1858.  —  Traduction  par  M.  De 
Slane,  in  Not.  et  Extr.,  t.  xix.-xxi.    Paris,  1862. 


164  INTRODUCTION" 

ness  and  insufficiency  of  their  attempted  explanations  of  the 
events  which  they  describe.  Masudi's  account,  drawn  from 
the  Pentateuch,  of  the  number  of  armed  Israelites  under  Moses 
in  the  wilderness,  is  among  those  subjected  to  criticism  in  this 
connection,  and  the  grounds  on  which  it  is  pronounced  in- 
credible are  nearly  the  same  as  those  with  which  Colenso  has 
made  us  in  the  present  day  so  familiar.  As  causes  of  histo- 
rians erring  as  they  have  done,  there  are  mentioned  the  over- 
looking of  the  differences  of  times  and  epochs,  the  judging 
too  hastily  from  analogies  and  resemblances,  opinionativeness, 
excessive  trust  in  one's  self  or  in  others,  servility,  and  a  want 
of  knowledge  of  the  nature  and  influence  of  civilisation.  The 
consideration  of  the  last  of  these  causes  leads  Ibn  Khaldun  to 
represent  the  inquiry  which  he  purposes  to  institute,  and  the 
results  which  he  hopes  thereby  to  attain,  as  a  science  of  civili- 
sation which  will  supply  a  criterion  of  truth  and  error  in  his- 
tory. It  will  form,  he  says,  "  a  new  science  as  remarkable  for 
its  originality  as  for  its  extent  and  utility."  It  will  be  at  once 
the  richest  result  and  the  surest  guide  of  history. 

The  First  Section  of  the  '  Prolegomena '  treats  of  society  in 
general,  and  of  the  varieties  of  the  human  race,  and  of  the 
regions  of  the  earth  which  they  inhabit,  as  related  thereto. 
It  starts  from  the  position  that  man  is  by  nature  a  social 
being.  His  body  and  mind,  wants  and  affections,  for  their 
exercise,  satisfaction,  and  development,  all  imply  and  demand 
co-operation  and  communion  with  his  fellows , —  participation 
in  a  collective  and  common  life.  This  collective  or  common 
life  passes  through  stages  of  what  is  called  culture  or  civili- 
sation; and  just  as  quantity  is  the  object  of  geometry,  the 
heavenly  bodies  of  astronomy,  and  the  human  frame  of  medi- 
cal science,  so  is  civilisation  or  culture  the  object  of  the  new 
science,  the  Science  of  History. 

There  follows  a  lengthened  description  of  the  physical  basis 
and  conditions  of  history  and  civilisation.  The  chief  features 
of  the  inhabited  portion  of  the  earth,  its  regions,  principal  seas, 
great  rivers,  climates,  &c,  are  made  the  subjects  of  exposition. 
The  seven  climatic  zones,  and  the  ten  sections  of  each,  are 
delineated,  and  their  inhabitants  specified.  The  three  climatic 
zones  of  moderate  temperature  are  described  in  detail,  and  the 
distinctive  features  of  the  social  condition  and  civilisation  of 


IBM    KHALDUN  165 

their  inhabitants  dwelt  upon.  The  influence  of  the  atmosphere, 
heat,  &c,  on  the  physical  and  even  mental  and  moral  pecu- 
liarities of  peoples  is  maintained  to  be  great.  Not  only  the 
darkness  of  skin  of  the  negroes,  but  their  characteristics  of 
disposition  and  of  mode  of  life,  are  traced  to  the  influence  of 
climate.  A  careful  attempt  is  also  made  to  show  how  differ- 
ences of  fertility  of  soil  —  how  dearth  and  abundance  —  mod- 
ify the  bodily  constitution  and  affect  the  minds  of  men,  and  so 
operate  on  society.  His  estimate  of  the  advantageousness  of 
abstemiousness  and  simplicity  as  regards  food  will  perhaps 
appear  to  most  persons  too  high.  It  has  to  be  kept  in  mind 
that  his  ideal  of  healthy  physical  life  for  man  was  one  drawn 
from  the  actual  life  of  the  Arabs  of  the  desert. 

The  section  closes  with  a  chapter  on  prophetism,  —  on  the 
apprehension  of  the  things  of  the  invisible  world  vouchsafed 
to  certain  specially  favoured  persons  for  the  instruction  of 
ordinary  mankind.  The  chapter  is  full  of  interesting  and 
instructive  matter,  but  will  not  improbably  seem  to  occidental 
readers  very  irrelevantly  placed.  It  must  not  be  forgotten, 
however,  that  to  the  Semitic  mind  prophetism  generally  pre- 
sents itself  as  the  chief  or  even  sole  source  of  religious  knowl- 
edge and  authority,  and  therefore  as  a  subject  the  discussion 
of  which  cannot  be  evaded  if  religion  is  to  be  maintained  to 
be  one  of  the  conditions  of  civilisation. 

The  Second  Section  of  the  'Prolegomena'  treats  of  the 
civilisation  of  nomadic  and  half-savage  peoples. 

In  it  Ibn  Khaldun  appears  at  his  best,  writing,  as  he  does, 
from  direct  and  full  knowledge.  He  begins  by  indicating  how 
the  different  usages  and  institutions  of  peoples  depend  to  a 
large  extent  on  the  ways  in  which  they  provide  for  their  sub- 
sistence. He  describes  how  peoples  have  at  first  contented 
themselves  with  simple  necessities,  and  then  gradually  risen 
to  refinement  and  luxury  through  a  series  of  states  or  stages 
all  of  which  are  alike  conformed  to  nature,  in  the  sense  of 
being  adapted  to  its  circumstances  or  environment.  He  shows 
how  the  condition  of  the  Arab  race  is  thus  natural. 

He  traces  the  connections  between  life  in  the  country  and 
life  in  towns.  The  former  precedes  the  latter,  it  is  the  cradle 
of  civilisation.  It  originates  towns,  supports  them,  and  sup- 
plies them  with  population.    He  insists  on  the  moral  superior- 


166  INTRODUCTION 

ity,  notwithstanding  their  greater  rudeness  of  manners,  of  the 
inhabitants  of  the  country  to  those  of  cities.  They  are,  in 
particular,  more  courageous.  This  is  largely  to  be  ascribed  to 
their  greater  independence  of  action,  —  their  exemption  from 
an  external  authoritative  regulation  of  human  conduct  which 
deprives  men  of  self-reliance  and  energy. 

The  conditions  of  social  life  in  the  desert  are  dwelt  upon  at 
length.  The  desert  tribe  requires  to  be,  above  all,  animated 
with  the  feeling  of  the  community.  Such  feeling  is  only  to  be 
found  in  sufficient  strength  among  persons  connected  by  blood- 
relationship  or  an  equivalent  tie ;  and  purity  of  blood  is  only 
to  be  found  in  the  desert  and  among  half -savage  tribes.  In 
such  tribes  the  right  of  government  must  be  in  one  family, 
and  that  the  most  powerful  of  the  tribe.  It  would  be  ruinous 
to  allow  it  to  pass  to  an  alien.  Only  among  families  united 
and  animated  by  a  strong  common  feeling  so  as  to  form  a 
powerful  and  distinguished  confraternity  is  nobility  a  reality. 
The  so-called  nobility  of  other  families  is  a  mere  semblance  of 
nobility,  a  something  metaphorical  or  conventional.  Among 
the  inhabitants  of  towns  there  are  no  families  noble  in  the 
primary  and  proper  sense,  although  there  are  virtuous,  influ- 
ential, and  respected  families.  A  family  is  not  noble  because 
descended  from  noble  ancestors,  but  because  possessed  of  the 
spirit  of  nobility.  The  Jews  are  de'scended  from  the  noblest 
family  on  earth,  and  may  boast  of  glorious  ancestors,  but 
there  is  now  no  family  nobility  among  the  Jews.  The  no- 
bility of  a  family  seldom  lasts  longer  than  four  generations. 
Scarcely  any  family  has  retained  nobility  throughout  six  gen- 
erations. The  only  men  truly  capable  of  ruling  are  those 
who  seek  to  distinguish  themselves  by  noble  qualities  and 
achievements. 

Our  author  next  proceeds  to  argue  that  semi-barbarous 
nomadic  tribes  are  the  best  fitted  for  making  extensive  con- 
quests, provided  that  tribal  feeling  be  strong  in  them;  that 
they  are  moved  by  a  common  spirit  and  motive ;  and  that  they 
have  not  been  corrupted  by  sensuous  indulgence  or  debased 
by  servitude.  He  naturally  finds  the  chief  proof  of  this  thesis 
in  the  rapid  Spread  of  Arab  domination  under  Mohammed 
and  his  successors.  At  the  same  time,  he  points  out  that  the 
Arabs  have  only  succeeded  in  establishing  their  sway  over 


IBN   KHALDTJN  167 

the  inhabitants  of  the  plains,  but  have  failed  to  subdue  the 
Berbers  and  other  mountaineers. 

He  shows  himself  clearly  aware  of  the  defects  and  faults  of 
the  Arabs.  This  strikingly  appears  in  the  remarkable  chap- 
ter in  which  he  maintains  that  the  Arabs  have  rapidly  ruined 
every  country  which  they  have  conquered.  It  may  be  of 
interest,  perhaps,  and  serve  to  give  some  conception  of  his 
mode  of  thought  and  style  of  expression,  if  I  translate  a  con- 
siderable portion  of  this  chapter. 

"  The  habits  and  practices  of  nomadic  life  have  made  the  Arabs  » 
rude  and  savage  people.  Their  roughness  of  manners  has  become  to 
them  a  second  nature,  and  one  in  which  they  find  satisfaction,  seeing 
that  it  ensures  them  freedom  and  independence.  Such  a  disposition 
is  an  obstacle  to  the  progress  of  civilisation.  To  move  from  place  to 
place,  to  traverse  the  desert,  has  been  from  the  remotest  times  their 
chief  occupation.  The  nomadic  life,  however,  is  as  contrary  to  the  prog- 
ress of .  civilisation  as  the  sedentary  life  is  favourable  to  it.  Let  the 
Arabs  require  stones  to  place  under  their  cooking-vessels,  and  they  \\  ill 
not  hesitate  to  spoil  a  house  in  order  to  procure  them;  let  them  want 
wood  for  the  stakes  or  poles  of  their  tents,  and  in  order  to  get  it  they 
will  strip  from  an  edifice  its  roof.  Their  very  mode  of  life  renders  them 
hostile  to  anything  like  building,  yet  to  build  is  a  first  step  in  civilisation. 
Further,  they  are,  from  natural  disposition,  always  ready  to  seize  property 
by  violence,  to  seek  wealth  with  armed  hand,  to  rob  without  moderation 
or  restriction.  Whenever  they  cast  their  eyes  on  a  fine  flock,  or  an  article 
of  furniture,  or  a  useful  instrument,  they  carry  it  off  by  force  if  they  can. 
When,  having  conquered  a  province  or  founded  a,  dynasty,  they  are  in  a 
condition  to  satisfy  their  rapacity,  they  treat  with  contempt  all  laws 
designed  to  protect  property  and  wealth.  Under  their  rule  everything 
goes  to  ruin.  They  impose  on  tradesmen  and  artisans  intolerable  bur- 
dens, without  thought  of  conferring  on  them  any  compensating  advan- 
tages. And  yet  the  exercise  of  arts  and  trades  is  the  real  source  of 
wealth.  If  the  handicrafts  are  fettered  and  burdened,  they  cease  to  be 
profitable ;  the  hope  of  gain  is  extinguished,  and  labour  is  abandoned ; 
then  social  order  is  deranged,  and  civilisation  recedes.  Further,  the 
Arabs  neglect  all  the  functions  of  government ;  they  are  not  anxious  to 
prevent  crime  or  watchful  in  preserving  the  public  safety.  Their  sole 
care  is  to  draw  money  from  their  subjects,  either  by  exaction  or  violence ; 
if  they  can  succeed  in  attaining  this  end  they  have  no  other  anxiety. 
They  spend  not  a  thought  on  putting  order  into  the  administration  of  the 
State,  in  providing  for  the  welfare  of  their  subjects,  and  in  restraining 
malefactors.  In  accordance  with  a  custom  which  has  always  existed 
among  them,  they  substitute  fines  for  bodily  punishments,  in  order 
thereby  to  increase  their  income.  But  mere  fines  are  not  sufficient  to 
repress  crime  aud  deter  malefactors ;   on  the  contrary,  they  encourage 


168  INTRODUCTION 

wicked-minded  men,  who  care  little  for  pecuniary  forfeits,  if  they  can 
accomplish. their  nefarious  projects.  The  subjects  of  an  Arab  tribe,  in 
fact,  are  left  almost  without  government,  —  a  condition  of  things  alike 
destructive  to  the  population  and  prosperity  of  a  country.  .  .  .  Look  at 
all  lands  which  the  Arabs  have  conquered  from  the  remotest  times. 
Civilisation  and  population  have  disappeared  from  them,  and  their  very 
soil  seems  to  have  changed  its  nature.  In  Yemen  all  the  centres  of  popu- 
lation are  deserted,  with  the  exception  of  a  few  large  towns ;  in  Irac  it  is 
the  same,  and  the  richly  cultivated  fields  which  adorned  it,  when  under 
Persian  rule,  have  become  waste.  Syria  is  now  ruined ;  and  the  countries 
of  North  Africa  are  all  still  suffering  from  the  devastations  of  the  Arabs." 

In  the  next  chapter,  the  Arabs  are  depicted  as  the  most 
insubordinate,  jealous,  and  contentious  of  peoples ;  and  as, 
consequently,  the  one  in  which  there  is  least  cohesiveness, 
and  least  natural  capacity  for  the  founding  of  a  solid  and 
extensive  empire.  But  they  are  also  described  in  it  as  char- 
acterised by  a  simplicity  of  life,  an  energy  of  will,  a  spirit 
of  clanship,  and  a  reverence  for  divine  authority,  which 
make  them  of  all  peoples  the  one  most  likely  to  accept  the 
doctrine  and  follow  the  guidance  of  a  prophet  or  saint  of 
their  own  race,  with  readiness  and  enthusiasm.  It  is  only 
"when  animated  by  religious  zeal  that  the  Arabs  have  shown 
themselves  powerful  to  pull  down  and  set  up  empires.  But 
we  are  told  in  the  chapter  which  follows  the  one  just  referred 
to,  that  in  no  circumstances  have  they  shown  themselves 
capable  of  permanently  maintaining  them.  Even  when  they 
have  succeeded  in  founding  an  empire,  their  native  pride  and 
insubordinateness  soon  reassert  themselves,  while  their  re- 
ligious fervour  decreases,  or  becomes  extinct.  The  result  is, 
that  allegiance  to  the  central  authority  is  thrown  off  by  chief 
after  chief,  tribe  after  tribe,  and  that  the  original  semi-savage 
state  of  the  race  returns. 

The  Third  Section  of  Ibn  Khaldun's  '  Prolegomena '  treats 
of  the  rise,  the  government,  and  the  fall  of  empires.  It 
is  a  long  section,  and  a  considerable  portion  of  it  directly 
concerns,  not  historical,  but  political  science.  This  portion, 
occupying  the  middle  of  the  section,  may  be  regarded  as  a^ 
treatise  on  the  constitution  and  administration,  the  functions 
and  methods,  and  the  offices  and  departments,  of  a  Moham- 
medan government.  As  such,  it  is  full  of  instruction  and 
interest ;  but  it  does  not  properly  concern  us  here.     I  shall, 


IBN   KHALDTJN  169 

therefore,  merely  indicate  the  general  tenor  of  what  is  said 
in  this  third  section  as  to  how  empires  are  established  and 
destroyed,  —  how  dynasties  acquire  and  lose  power. 

The  force  which  public  spirit  imparts  is  represented  as  the 
prime  condition  of  acquiring  dominion.  When  the  individ- 
uals of  a  tribe,  or  army,  or  people,  are  so  united  and  animated 
by  common  feeling  and  aim  as  readily  and  rejoicingly  to  meet 
all  dangers  and  make  all  sacrifices,  their  leaders  can  easily 
found  an  empire.  They  must  not  trust,  however,  exclusively 
to  the  sympathy  and  enthusiasm  of  their  followers,  and  must 
even  be  careful  to  keep  in  due  restraint  arid  obedience  those 
through  whose  zeal  and  devotedness  they  rise  to  sovereignty. 
Only  through  establishing  a  good  administration,  preserving 
order  and  justice,  enacting  wise  laws,  maintaining  a  regular 
army,  and  attracting  to  themselves  and  their  families  the 
affections  of  their  subjects,  can  they  build  up  a  dynasty  which 
will  endure.  It  is  again  earnestly  argued  that  as  the  power 
of  a  religion,  revealed  through  a  prophet,  can  alone  cause 
jealousies,  dissensions,  and  rivalries  in  a  State  to  give  place 
to  unity,  mutual  aid,  and  generous  zeal,  there  can  be  no  other 
basis  of  authority  over  a  great  empire.  But  religious  enthu- 
siasm is  admitted  to  be  insufficient  unless  it  pervades  a 
large  and  strong  party.  God  never  gives  a  commission  of 
reformation  except  to  those  who  are  able  to  carry  it  into 
execution.  Those  who  are  not  widely  believed  are  not  His 
prophets.  General  assent  and  practical  success  are  evidences 
of  divine  truth.  These  positions  are  all  attempted  to  be 
illustrated  and  confirmed  by  historical  facts  related  in  oriental 
records. 

A  considerable  number  of  chapters  treat  of  the  duration  of 
empires.  It  is  indicated  how  they  may  fall  through  being 
too  large,  and  that  there  are  insuperable  obstacles  to  the 
establishment  of  a  universal  empire.  It  is  argued  that  the 
Arab  conquests  were  made  too  rapidly  to  be  lasting,  and 
that  Arab  kingdoms  had  been  dismembered  and  overthrown, 
owing,  in  a  considerable  measure,  to  their  extent.  The 
magnitude  and  duration  of  empires  founded  on  conquest 
must,  it  is  held,  be  in  proportion  to  the  number  and  force  of 
those  through  whom  the  conquest  is  effected.  The  course  of 
conquest  must  be  slow  in  countries  inhabited  by  numerous 


170  INTRODUCTION 

tribes.  Irac  and  Syria  were  easily  and  completely  subdued ; 
Morocco  only  with  difficulty  and  in  part.  The  tendencies  of 
sovereignties  to  despotism  and  to  luxury,  and,  through  these, 
to  corruption  and  ruin,  are  well  described.  For  generalisa- 
tion on  this  subject  oriental  history  supplied  data  in  abundance. 

Ibn  Khaldun  does  not  forget  to  search  for  a  law  of  the 
course  of  empires.  The  guiding  principle  of  his  inquiry  is 
analogy.  An  empire,  he  holds,  has  a  life  of  its  own  like  an 
individual.  As  a  rule,  its  life  does  not  last  longer  than  that 
of  three  generations  of  men  —  three  times  the  mean  life  of  a 
man;  in  a  word,  net  longer  than  one  hundred  and  twenty 
years.  This  alleged  law  or  fact  is  thus  explained :  In  each 
empire,  the  first  generation  of  its  people  possesses  in  full 
vigour  the  tribal  spirit,  the  hardy  and  warlike  character  of 
nomads ;  the  second  generation,  under  the  influence  of  power 
and  wealth,  generally  acquires  the  self-indulgent  and  depend- 
ent habits  of  sedentary  life,  and  loses  force  and  courage ;  and 
in  the  third  generation  the  distinctive  qualities  of  the  desert 
man  disappear,  and  the  dynasty  becomes  incapable  of  resist- 
ing the  attacks  of  a  formidable  enemy.  The  generalisation 
and  the  explanation,  it  will  be  observed,  are  alike  drawn  from 
the  data  most  accessible  and  patent  to  an  oriental.  They  are 
clearly  inapplicable  to  the  peoples  and  dynasties  of  Europe. 

In  the  section  of  the  work  at  present  under  consideration, 
Ibn  Khaldun  also  exhibits  history  as  a  process  of  continuous 
movement  and  change  with  remarkable  clearness.  Each  em- 
pire, he  maintains,  passes  through  several  phases  and  becomes 
subject  to  divers  general  modifications,  which  affect  all  the 
elements  of  society  and  influence  the  sentiments  and  modes  of 
thought  and  action  of  all  the  members  of  a  generation.  The 
general  character  of  a  people,  he  shows  himself  fully  aware, 
always  corresponds  to  its  epoch,  position,  and  relationships  in 
history.  In  this  respect  his  superiority  to  the  Christian  me- 
dieval chroniclers  is  most  conspicuous.  They,  almost  without 
exception,  were  manifestly,  as  G.  Monod  has  observed,  "  un- 
conscious of  the  successive  modifications  which  time  brings 
with  it."  Ibn  Khaldun  was  not  so.  He  expresses  repeatedly 
and  in  various  forms  the  general  truth  that  history  is  a  con- 
tinuous collective   movement,  an  incessant   and   inevitable 


IBN   KHALDUN  171 

development.  He  also  shows  the  thoroughness  of  his  reali- 
sation of  it  by  the  delineations  which  he  gives,  from  time  to 
time,  of  the  ways  in  which  one  stage  of  civilisation  generally 
passes  into  another.  These  sketches  remind  us  much  more 
of  the  pages  of  a  class  of  historico-philosophical  writers  of  the 
eighteenth  century  than  of  any  to  be  found  in  the  medieval 
historians  of  Europe. 

Let  us  pass  to  the  Fourth  Section  of  our  author's  works,  —  a 
section  which  need  not  detain  us  long.  It  relates  to  towns, 
the  sedentary  mode  of  life,  a  settled  and  concentrated  civili- 
sation. 

At  the  outset,  the  relation  of  the  foundation  and  dissolu- 
tion of  towns  to  the  rise  and  fall  of  kingdoms  is  discussed. 
Kingdoms,  it  is  argued,  are  the  first  established,  and  these 
originate  towns,  but  towns  may  either  perish  with  the  king- 
doms to  which  they  belong  or  survive  them.  The  causes 
which  lead  the  peoples  that  establish  kingdoms  to  found 
towns  are  exhibited,  and  the  circumstances  to  be  taken  into 
account  in  the  choice  of  towns  are  indicated.  Much  curious 
lore  is  here  accumulated  regarding  famous  towns,  mosques, 
temples,  and  large  constructions. 

In  this  section  also,  Ibn  Khaldun  shows  that  he  at  least  did 
not  overestimate  the  genius  and  achievements  of  his  own  peo- 
ple. Their  edifices  he  pronounces  unworthy  of  a  race  which 
had  possessed  such  power  and  wealth,  and  greatly  inferior  to 
those  of  the  nations  which  had  preceded  them.  He  holds  that 
the  Arabs  are  lacking  in  talent  for  architecture  and  the  arts. 
They  are,  he  affirms,  by  native  character  averse  to  magnificent 
building,  and  indifferent  to  elegance.  Their  constructions  are 
generally  without  solidity.  He  recognises,  however,  the  high 
perfection  to  which  the  arts  had  attained  among  the  Moslems 
in  Spain,  and  attributes  it  to  the  fact  that  Mohammedan 
civilisation  had  there  continued  unbroken  and  uninterrupted 
throughout  the  duration  of  an  exceptional  number  of  dy- 
nasties. 

In  subsequent  chapters  the  effects  of  towns  on  the  districts 
which  surround  them,  the  connection  between  their  fortunes 
and  those  of  particular  dynasties,  their  relations  to  popula- 
tion, wealth,  and  morality,  their  influences  on  culture  and 


172  INTRODUCTION 

the  arts,  the  social  and  political  changes  which  take  place 
within  them,  and  the  causes  of  their  decay  and  ruin,  are 
attempted  to  be  traced. 

The  Fifth  Section  of  the  '  Historical  Prolegomena '  treats  of 
the  means  of  procuring  national  subsistence  and  of  promot- 
ing national  prosperity,  and  of  the  various  arts  subservient 
thereto,  industrial,  economic,  medical,  recreative,  and  the  like. 
The  Sixth  Section  treats  of  the  sciences  in  an  almost  encyclo- 
pedic manner.  These,  the  last  two  sections  of  the  work,  are 
not  less  instructive  and  interesting  than  those  which  precede 
them.  It  would  take  us,  however,  altogether  out  of  our  way 
to  analyse  or  summarise  them.  Yet  it  has  to  be  observed 
that,  in  the  view  of  their  author,  they  were  by  no  means 
irrelevant  to  the  main  theme  of  his  book,  and  could  not  have 
been  consistently  omitted.  His  subject  was  the  science  of 
history ;  and  the  science  of  history  he  identified  with  the 
science  of  civilisation, — a  vast  and  imperial  science,  in  which 
all  particular  arts  and  sciences  may  be  included,  or  to  which 
they  are,  at  least,  all  subordinate. 

A  criticism  of  the  work  of  Ibn  Khaldun  is  unnecessary. 
The  chief  source  of  such  defects  and  errors  as  it  contains  was 
its  author's  very  imperfect  acquaintance  with  the  history  and 
civilisation  of  Europe.  Had  he  known  the  classical  and 
Christian  worlds  as  well  as  he  knew  the  Mohammedan  world, 
and  generalised  and  reasoned  on  them  also  with  the  same 
independence  and  insight,  the  treatise  which  he  might  have 
produced  would  have  been  one  of  the  greatest  and  most  valu- 
able in  literature.  The  one  which  he  has  left  is,  however, 
sufficiently  great  and  valuable  to  preserve  his  name  and  fame 
to  latest  generations. 


THE 


PHILOSOPHY  OF  HISTOET  IN  FEANCE 


CHAPTER   I 

THE  PROGRESS   OF   HISTORIOGRAPHY,  AND  THE  BEGINNINGS 
OF   HISTORICAL   PHILOSOPHY  IN   FRANCE:    BODIN 


Only  when  French  nationality,  civilisation,  and  literature 
had  reached  a  certain  stage  of  development  could  reflection 
on  history  make  its  appearance  in  France.  And  when  it  did 
appear,  the  form  in  which  it  presented  itself  and  the  course 
which  it  followed  were  largely  determined  by  the  historical 
processes  which  it  presupposed.  What  these  were  need  not 
be  here  described.  How  French  nationality  was  founded  — 
how  French  civilisation  gradually  acquired  the  character 
which  it  exhibited  in  the  sixteenth  century  —  from  what  be- 
ginnings and  through  what  stages  French  literature  grew 
onwards  to  the  same  time — must  be  learned  from  such  his- 
tories of  France  as  those  of  Michelet  and  Martin,  such  histo- 
ries of  French  civilisation  as  those  of  Guizot  and  Rambaud, 
and  such  histories  of  French  literature  as  those  of  Ampere, 
Villemain,  Nisard,  and  Demogeot.  All  that  can  here  be 
attempted  is  very  briefly  to  indicate  the  course  of  historical 
literature  in  France  from  its  origin  to  the  dawn  of  French 
historical  speculation.1 

1  The  documents  which  relate  to  the  early  history  of  France  are  presented  in 
the  following  collections  :  1.  Recueil  des  Historiens  des  Gaules  et  de  la  France. 
(Commence  par  les  Bene'dictins  de  la  congregation  de  Saint-Maur,  et  continue' 
par  1' Academic  des  inscriptions  et  belles-lettres.)  22  vols.,  1737-1865.  —  2.  Collec- 
tion des  Memoires  relatifs  a  l'histoire  de  France,  depuis  la  fondation  de  la  monar- 
chic francaise  jusqu'au  xiii"  siecle.  Avec  une  introduction,  des  supplemens,  des 
notices  et  des  notes,  par  M.  F.  Guizot.  31  toIs.,  1824-1835*  —  3.  Collection  des 
Chroniques  Nationales  Francaises  ecrites  en  langue  vulgaire,  du  xiiie  au  xvi'  siecle. 
Avec  notes  et  eelaircissements  par  J.  A.  Bouchon.  47  vols.,  1824-1829.  — i.  Collec- 
tion complete  des  Me'moires  relatifs  a  l'histoire  de  France,  depuis  le  regne  de 
Philippe-Augnste,  jusqu'a  la  Paix  de  Paris  conclue  en  1763.  Avec  des  notices  sur 
chaque  auteur  et  des  observations  sur  chaque  ouvrage,  par  M.  Petitot  et  M.  Mon- 
merque".     131  vols.,  1819-1829.  — 5.  Nouvelle  Collection  des  Memoires  pour  servir  a 

175 


176  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Until  somewhat  far  on  in  the  middle  ages  the  composition 
of  history  in  France,  as  elsewhere,  was  almost  exclusively  in 
the  hands  of  priests  and  monks.  This  accounts  for  many  of 
the  defects  and  faults  of  medieval  histories ;  but  is  also  a  fact 
which  manifestly  requires  to  be  itself  accounted  for.  The  ex- 
planation of  it  can  only  be  found  in  the  ignorance  of  the  laity 
and  the  predominance  of  ecclesiastical  views  and  interests  in 
those  ages.  The  clergy  almost  alone  wrote  history,  because 
very  few  others  could  write  it  or  wished  to  write  it,  and 
because  the  history  of  the  time  was  very  largely  Church  his- 
tory. The  secular  history  of  the  early  middle  ages,  crowded 
as  it  was  with  picturesque  and  tragic  incidents,  with  events 
fateful  for  the  whole  future  of  the  world,  and  with  the  most 
striking  displays  of  human  character,  force,  and  passion,  has 
strong  attractions  for  the  educated  man  of  the  present  day, 
but  it  was  too  tumultuous  and  chaotic,  too  dark  and  woful, 
for  the  most  reflective  and  best  informed  contemporaries  to 
take  pleasure  in  contemplating  and  describing  it  for  its  own 
sake.  The  Church  of  Christ  struggling  like  a  ship  amidst 
the  waves  of  a  stormy  sea,  the  monastery  shining  like  a  lamp 
through  surrounding  darkness,  lives  conspicuously  devoted  to 
the  service  of  God,  these  alone  carried  a  perceptible  signifi- 
cance in  them  even  to  the  few  who  possessed  such  scanty 
culture  as  was  then  attainable.  Secular  society  required  to 
develop  a  culture  of  its  own,  and  to  make  for  itself  an  intelli- 
gible history  of  its  own,  before  it  could  obtain  historians  of  its 
own. 

l'histoire  de  France  depuis  le  xiii"  siecle  jusqu'a  la  fin  du  xviii".  Precedes  de  notices 
pour  caracteriser  chaque  auteur  des  memoires  et  son  epoque ;  suivis  de  l'analyse  des 
documents  historiques  qui  s'y  rapportent.  Par  MM.  Michaud  et  Poujoulat.  32 
vols.,  1836-1839.  —6.  Socie'te'  de  l'Histoire  de  France.  130  vols.,  1833-1875.  There 
are  also  two  important  collections  which  may  be  regarded  as  complimentary  and 
supplementary  to  those  mentioned,  viz. :  1.  C.  Leber,  Collection  des  meilleurs 
Dissertations,  Notices  et  Traites  Particuliers  relatifs  a  l'histoire  de  France,  com- 
posee  en  grande  partie  de  pieces  rares,  ou  qui  n'ont  jamais  ete'  publiees  se'pare'ment, 
pour  servir  a  completer  toutes  les  collections  de  memoires  sur  cette  matiere.  20 
vols.,  1838. — 2.  Bibliotheque  de  l'Ecole  de  Chartes,  revue  d'erudition,  consacree 
specialement  a  l'etude  du  moyen  age  :  1839-1888.  Indispensable  as  a  guide  to 
the  contents  of  these  collections  and  to  the  original  authorities  on  the  history  ol 
France  is  the  bibliographical  work  of  M.  Alfred  Franklin,  Les  Sources  de  l'Histoire 
de  France,  1877.  Also  valuable  is  G.  Monod,  Bibliographie  de  l'Histoire  de 
France,  catalogue  methodique  et  chronologique  des  sources  et  des  ouvrages 
relatifs  a  l'histoire  de  France  depuis  les  origines  jusqu'en  1789 :  1888. 


PROGRESS   OF   HISTORIOGRAPHY  177 

The  monasteries  were  the  appropriate  cradles  of  medieval 
historiography.  They  could  not  dispense  with  written  memo- 
rials, and  they  afforded  leisure  and  means  of  knowledge.  It 
was  almost  a  necessity,  and  it  soon  became  the  rule,  for  each 
monastery  to  have  a  scribe  or  recorder  to  commemorate  what- 
ever happened  affecting  the  interests  and  obligations  of  the 
monastic  community;  and  with  these  events  there  gradually 
came  to  be  associated  others  of  greater  moment  and  wider 
influence.  These  records  were  added  to,  interpolated,  cor- 
rected, and  even  recast,  until  they  satisfied  the  heads  of  the 
institutions.  Thus  grew  up  the  monastic  chronicles.  In  close 
connection  with  them  appeared  another  and  more  popular  sort 
of  ecclesiastical  chronicles,  namely,  the  biographies  of  distin- 
guished churchmen  and  lives  of  the  saints.  These  naturally 
led  to  the  biographies  of  great  laymen  —  of  men  who  were 
recognised  to  have  done  things  worthy  of  being  recorded  even 
by  the  hands  of  ecclesiastics,  although  they  were  never  likely 
to  be  ecclesiastically  canonised.  Einhard's  Life  of  Charle- 
magne is  one  of  the  earliest  and  best  of  these  biographies. 

The  famous  abbey  of  St.  Denis  —  at  the  instigation,  it  is 
thought,  of  Abbot  Suger,  one  of  the  most  remarkable  men  in 
French  medieval  history1 —  took  the  important  step  of  making 
a  collection  of  the  best  and  most  esteemed  chronicles.  To 
it  new  ones  were  added  as  they  were  composed.  Thus  the 
deeds  of  the  kings  of  France  were  preserved  in  the  archives 
of  the  same  sacred  building  in  the  vaults  of  which  their  bodies 
reposed.  And  thus  were  formed  what  were  called  "  the  Great 
Chronicles  of  France,"  which  came  down  to  the  reign  of 
Louis  XL  Long  before  the  collection  was  completed,  trans- 
lations of  these  Latin  chronicles  into  the  vernacular  began  to 
be  made  for  the  laity.  As  was  to  be  expected,  the  earliest 
translated  was  the  most  fabulous  of  all,  that  of  the  pseudo- 
Turpin  concerning  Charlemagne  —  a  work  which  is  the  French 

1  Suger  (1082-1152)  himself  wrote  a  Vita  Ludovici  Grossi  Regis  which  will  be 
found  in  the  CEuvres  Completes  de  Suger,  recueillies,  annotees  et  publiees  d'apres 
les  manusorits,  par  A.  Legoy  de  la  Marche,  1867.  .  The  best  biographies  of  him 
are  those  of  F.  Combes,  L'Abbe  Suger,  Histoire  de  son  ministere  et  de  sa  re'gence, 
1853;  and  of  A.  Vetauld,  Vie  de  Suger,  Tours,  1871.  Also  may  be  mentioned  A. 
Huguenin,  Etude  sur  l'Abbe'  Suger,  1855 ;  the  sketch  in  M.  Louis  de  Carne's  Fon- 
dateurs  de  l'unite  francaise,  2  vols.,  1856;  and  Baudrillart's  Histoire  du  Luxe, 
torn.  iii.  ch.  5 :  Suger  et  son  role  dans  le  luxe. 


178  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

counterpart  of  our  Geoffrey  of  Monmouth's  History,  and  the 
chief  source  of  the  romantic  materials  so  skilfully  employed 
by  writers  like  Boccaccio  and  Ariosto.  What  are  now  called 
the  Chronicles  of  France,  or  the  Chronicles  of  St.  Denis,  are 
not  the  Latin  originals  collected  or  composed  by  the  monks  of 
St.  Denis,  but  the  French  translations  of  these  works,  executed 
by  the  monks  of  St.  Denis  or  under  their  supervision.1 

While  the  monks  of  St.  Denis  —  much  to  their  credit  — 
were  composing  chronicles  in  Latin  or  translating  them  into 
French,  lay  chroniclers  began  to  appear  who  wrote  of  secular 
things  in  a  secular  spirit,  and  in  the  vernacular  speech.  The 
earliest  was  Villehardouin,  and  he  was  followed  by  Joinville, 
Froissart,  Monstrelet,  and  Commines,  with  whom  the  series 
closed.  Villehardouin  died  in  1213  and  Commines  in  1509, 
so  that  about  three  hundred  years  separated  them.  During 
the  whole  period  England  had  no  lay  vernacular  histories ; 
and  even  Italy  had  none  before  the  fourteenth  century.  The 
vernacular  chronicle  —  variously  called  Saxon,  Anglo-Saxon, 
and  English  —  of  which  Britain  is  justly  proud,  and  that  of 
Nestor,  the  father  of  Russian  historiography,  long  preceded, 
indeed,  the  French  works  referred  to,  but  they  also  essentially 
differed  from  them  in  character.  Aimers  History  of  Norman 
warfare  in  Southern  Italy2  is  likewise  earlier,  but  it  can  only 
be  regarded  as  belonging  to  the  same  series  if  looked  at  merely 
from  the  linguistic  point  of  view.  It  was  in  France  that 
secular  society  first  found  truly  representative  historians. 
Yet  not  secular  society  as  a  whole ;  not  the  bourgeoisie,  and 
still  less  the  common  people.  Italy  produced  the  earliest 
historians  of  civic  communities.  Historians  just  and  sympa- 
thetic towards  the  humblest  classes  have  only  appeared  in 
recent  times.    The  early  French  vernacular  chroniclers  spoken 

1  On  the  Chronicles  of  France,  both  in  the  older  and  later  use  of  the  term,  see 
the  prefaces  of  M.  P.  Paris  to  his  edition  of  Les  Grandes  Chroniques  de  France, 
6  vols.,  1836-1838,  and  M.  de  la  Curne's  Memoire  sur  les  Principalis:  Monuments 
de  France  in  the  Acadeinie  des  Inscriptions,  torn.  xxii. 

2  L'Istoire  de  li  Normant  et  la  Chronique  de  Robert  Viscart,  par  Aime,  moine 
du  Mont-Cassin.  Publiees  pour  la  premiere  fois,  d'apres  un  manuscrit  francois 
inedit  du  xiii*  siecle,  appartenant  a  la  Bibliotheque  royale,  par  Champollion-Figeac, 
1835.  As  to  the  authorship  of  the  second  work,  see  R.  Wilmans,  1st  Amatus  von 
Monte  Cassino  der  Verfasser  der  Chronica  Roberti  Biscardi?  in  Pertz,  Archiv. 
(1849),  x. 


SCEPTICISM   AND   HISTORY  209 

The  philosophy  of  the  seventeenth  century  did  not  aim  at 
interpreting  and  comprehending  history ;  at  tracing  the  move- 
ment of  reason  through  the  complications  and  aberrations  of 
human  affairs.  It  showed  scarcely  any  interest  in  the  explana- 
tion of  social  phenomena.  A  thorough  and  fruitful  blending 
of  philosophy  and  history  was  as  yet  in  the  far  future;  a 
general  recognition  of  its  possibility  and  desirableness  will 
be  sought  for  in  vain  in  any  century  but  the  present. 

The  French  philosophy  of  the  seventeenth  century  assumed 
two  forms,  a  negative  orijceptical  and  a  positive  or  rational. 
The  scepticism  which  was  represented  in  the  sixteenth  cen- 
tury by  Rabelais,  Montaigne,  and  Charron,  was  propagated 
in  the  seventeenth  by  Le  Vayer,  Huet,  and  Bayle.  But 
Bishop  Huet,  although  a  sceptic  and  an  historian,  showed  no 
scepticism  as  an  historian.  It  was  otherwise  with  Le  Vayer, 
as  has  already  been  indicated,  and  especially  with  Peter 
Bayle,  the  famed  author  of  the  'Dictionnaire  Critique.' 
The  latter  is,  perhaps,  the  best  example  which  the  history  of 
literature  supplies  of  what  has  been  called  "  erudite  scepti- 
cism,"— the  scepticism  which  finds  in  historical  learning  an 
arsenal  of  weapons  both  for  defence  and  attack, —  the  scepti- 
cism which  Bayle  himself  designated  "historical  Pyrrhon- 
ism." He  had  an  insatiable  and  undiscriminating  curiosity 
regarding  facts  and  opinions,  wonderful  logical  dexterity, 
extreme  ingenuity  in  inventing  and  great  fondness  for  main- 
taining paradoxes.  With  but  feeble  cravings  either  for  fixed 
principles  or  for  unity  and  harmony  in  his  speculations,  a 
want  of  moral  delicacy,  and  no  profound  religious  emotions, 
he  was  animated  by  a  sincere  love  of  independence  of  thought, 
and  a  cordial  hatred  of  intolerance  and  persecution.  The 
whole  constitution  of  his  nature,  his  personal  experience 
of  life,  and  his  special  acquirements,  rendered  him  a  most 
powerful  assailant  of  dogmatism;  and  he  was  unsurpassed  in 
the  art  of  so  suggesting  and  accumulating  doubts  regarding 
particular  questions  and  opinions  of  every  kind  as  to  produce 
universal  doubt,  a  feeling  of  the  uncertainty  of  all  that  pro- 
fesses to  be  knowledge.  Under  cover  of  the  assumption  of 
the  opposition  of  reason  and  faith,  he  skilfully  laboured  to 
humiliate  both,  by  convicting  the  former  of  inability  to  dis- 
cover truth  with  certainty,  and  the  latter  of  teaching  absurd- 


180  PHILOSOPHY  OF   HISTORY  1ST  FRANCE 

few  general  reflections,  and  of  historical  or  other  speculation 
there  are  no  traces  in  his  pages.1 

Joinville  was  of  a  finer  and  richer  nature  than  his  prede- 
cessor and  possessed  of  true  literary  genius.  In  his  '  Histoire 
de  St.  Louis,'  written  in  1309,  the  style  is  no  longer,  as  in 
Villehardouin,  rough  and  unpliant,  but  easy,  flowing,  and 
flexible,  and  capable  of  expressing  reflections  and  feelings 
as  well  as  merely  conveying  events ;  and  the  superiority  as 
regards  mastery  over  the  materials,  the  co-ordination  of  the 
facts,  the  disposition  of  the  narrative,  is  no  less  decided.  He 
does  not  proceed  simply  narrating  what  he  witnessed ;  he 
also  judges  and  compares,  meditates  and  moralises,  finds 
expression  for  the  varying  moods  of  his  own  gay,  generous, 
vivacious  spirit,  and  gradually  and  skilfully  produces  an 
imperishable  portraiture  of  the  most  conscientious  and  pious 
man  who  ever  sat  upon  the  throne  of  France,  or,  perhaps, 
of  any  nation.2 

Villehardouin  is  little  more  than  a  chronicler;  Joinville, 
as  an  excellent  artist,  is  much  more.  But  Froissart,  who 
labourea  for  nearly  forty  years  in  the  latter  half  of  the  four- 
teenth century  on  the  brilliant  work  which  has  immortalised 
his  name,  daily  (to  use  his  own  words)  "  rentrant  dedans  sa 
forge,  pour  ouvrer  et  forger  en  la  haute  et  noble  mature  du 
temps  passeY'  openly  claims  to  be  an  historian  as  distinguished 
from  a  chronicler.  "  If  I  were  merely  to  say  such  and  such 
things  happened  at  such  times,  without  entering  fully  into 
the  matter,  which  was  grandly  horrible  and  disastrous,  this 
would  be  a  chronicle,  but  no  history."  The  work  of  Froissart 
describes  in  detail  the  great  enterprises  and  deeds  of  arms 
done    not   only  in    France,   but  in   England,  Scotland,  and 

1  The  best  editions  of  Villehardouin  are  those  of  M.  Paulin  Paris  and  M. 
Natalis  de  Wailly.  For  a  general  estimate  of  his  character  as  a  writer,  see 
Daunou,  Hist.  litt.  de  France,  1852,  xvii.  150-171,  and  Sainte-Beuve,  Causeries 
du  Lundi,  ix.  305-330.  Recently  the  trustworthiness  of  his  narrative  has  been 
seriously  assailed  by  Count  Riant  in  t.  xvii.,  xviii.,  and  xxiii.  of  the  Rev.  d. 
quest,  hist. ;  by  L.  Streit  and  J.  Tessier  in  special  brochures ;  and  by  E.  Pears, 
The  Fall  of  Constantinople,  1885.  There  is  a  sketch  of  his  character  taken  from 
the  new  point  of  view  by  M.  Ed.  Sayons  in  vol.  xxv.,  1886,  of  the  Cpte.  Rend.  d. 
Sean,  et  Trav.  de  l'Acad.  d.  Sc.  Mor.  et  Pol. 

2  On  Joinville  see  Vitet,  Rev.  d.  Deux  Mondes,  lxxv.,  132-163  (1868) ;  N.  de 
Wailly  in  Comptes  Rendus  d.  Acad.  Inscr.  et  Bel.-Let.,  1865;  and  Champollion- 
Figeac,  Mel.  Hist.,  i.  615-645. 


PROGRESS   OF   HISTORIOGRAPHY  181 

Ireland,  Spain  and  Portugal,  Germany  and  Italy,  and  even  in 
Poland  and  Turkey  and  Africa,  from  1326  to  1400,  with  a  live- 
liness, garrulity,  and  natural  grace,  which  recall  Herodotus, 
and  with  a  spiritedness  of  movement  and  a  splendour  and 
variety  of  incidents  which  remind  us  of  Walter  Scott. 
Never  had  been  seen  before  historical  painting  on  so  broad  a 
canvas,  so  crowded,  and  so  richly  coloured.  All  feudalism  is 
there,  and  in  all  its  magnificence.  Yet  Froissart,  notwith- 
standing his  inexhaustible  curiosity,  his  vast  memory,  his 
keen  interest  in  the  things  he  described,  his  rare  power  of 
graphic  portraiture,  and  his  skill  as  a  narrator,  was  not  a 
historian  in  any  strict  or  high  sense.  He  lacked  insight  and 
seriousness;  cared  little  to  distinguish  between  reality  and 
appearance,  between  the  vero  and  the  ben  trovato  ;  looked  with 
indifference  on  oppression  and  cruelty;  and  sought  as  an 
author  only  to  give  pleasure  and  to  gain  fame.1 

Monstrelet  began  his  Chronicle  with  the  year  1400,  —  i.e., 
where  that  of  Froissart  had  ended.  He  had  none  of  the 
brilliant  qualities  of  his  predecessor.  His  prolixity  makes 
him  tiresome,  notwithstanding  the  inherent  interest  of  many 
of  the  events  which  he  narrates.  His  general  truthfulness 
is  unquestionable,  although  he  favoured  the  house  of  Bur- 
gundy to  the  extent  of  omitting  or  passing  lightly  over  certain 
things  which  were  not  to  its  credit.  His  work  contains  much 
valuable  historical  information,  but  is  not  the  production  of 
an  historical  artist,  and  contains  little  historical  reflection  and 
no  historical  generalisations. 

Leaving  unnoticed  Christina  de  Pisa  and  Alain  Chartier,  we 
pass  to  Philip  de  Commines,  the  chamberlain  and  councillor  of 
Charles  the  Bold,  Duke  of  Burgundy,  and  afterwards  the  con- 
fident and  adviser  of  the  politic  and  unscrupulous  Louis  XI. 
The  latter  prince,  who  played  the  same  part  in  France  which 
his  contemporaries  Henry  VII.  and  Ferdinand  the  Catholic  did 
in  England  and  Spain  in  destroying  the  power  of  the  nobles 
and  raising  on  its  ruins  the  absolute  rule  of  the  monarch,  is  the 
hero  of  Commines'  Memoirs.     It  is  not  the  impetuous  Charles 

1  On  Froissart  see  Sainte-Beuve,  C.  d.  L.,  ix.  63-96;  Curne  in  Mem.  Acad. 
Inscr.  et  Bel.-Let.,  x.,  xiii.,  xiv. ;  and  K.  de  Lettenhove,  Froissart,  Etude  litte- 
raire  sur  le  xive  siecle,  Bruxelles,  1857. 


182  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

but  this  astute  Louis  that  the  historian  admires,  not  courage 
but  policy,  not  brilliant  feats  of  arms  but  successful  intrigues. 
With  him,  as  I  have  already  had  to  remark,  history  first 
became  political  and  reflective.  Unlike  the  older  chroniclers, 
he  was  not  content  to  narrate  merely  in  order  to  narrate  and 
please,  but  sought  even  more  to  explain  and  instruct.  He 
described  incidents  briefly,  but  was  careful  to  indicate  why 
things  happened  as  they  did,  and  what  effects  they  produced. 
Hence  his  style  was  comparatively  abstract,  and  he  reasoned  as 
well  as  recorded.  From  having  been  the  first  to  endeavour  of 
set  purpose  and  with  conspicuous  success  to  detect  and  disclose 
the  motive  principles  of  historical  personages  and  the  causal 
connections  of  historical  transactions,  he  has  some  righj.  to  the 
title,  which  has  been  so  often  given  to  him,  of  father  of  modern 
history.  He  made  a  distinct  step  beyond  simple  chronicling, 
and  towards  the  mode  of  writing  history  in  which  his  younger 
contemporaries,  Guicciardini  and  Machiavelli,  were  the  first 
greatly  to  excel.  He  was  not,  however,  the  intellectual  equal 
of  either  of  these  celebrated  Italians,  and  cannot  properly  be 
placed  on  the  same  level  with  either  as  an  historian.  He  wrote 
only  an  historical  memoir,  whereas  Guicciardini  gave  a  complete 
account  of  one  of  the  most  complicated  and  agitated  periods  of 
Italian  history.  The  practical  shrewdness  and  judiciousness 
of  his  estimates  of  persons  and  actions  deserve  due  apprecia- 
tion, but  they  are  not  to  be  compared  with  the  genius  of  a 
truly  scientific  kind  displayed  by  Machiavelli  in  his  treatment 
of  Roman  and  Florentine  history.  His  vision  was  clear  and 
keen  within  the  narrow  range  of  personal  experience,  but  he 
had  neither  conception  nor  feeling  of  the  working  of  a  general 
spirit,  laws,  and  tendencies  in  human  affairs.  Hence  the 
peculiarity  by  which  Dr.  Arnold  was  much  impressed,  his 
perfect  unconsciousness  that  the  state  of  things  which  he 
described  was  on  the  point  of  passing  away.  In  one  respect 
he  strikingly  resembled  Guicciardini  and  Machiavelli.  In  his 
!  eyes  as  in  theirs,  the  political  wisdom  which  it  was  the  chief 
use  of  history  to  teach  was  to  know  how  to  attain  political 
success.  He  was,  like  his  master  the  king,  a  Machiavellian 
before  Machiavelli.  Dr.  Arnold  has  said,  "Philip  de  Confines 
praises  his  master  Louis  the  Eleventh  as  one  of  the  best  of 


PROGRESS   OF   HISTORIOGRAPHY  183 

princes,  although  he  witnessed  not  only  the  crimes  of  his  life, 
but  the  miserable  fears  and  suspicions  of  his  latter  end,  and 
has  even  faithfully  recorded  them.  In  this  respect  Philip  de 
Comines  is  in  no  respect  superior  to  Proissart,  with  whom 
the  crimes  committed  by  his  knights  and  great  lords  never 
interfere  with  his  general  eulogies  of  them." 1  Along  with 
a  correct  statement  of  fact,  these  words  contain  a  misleading 
rapprochement  of  names.  The  conscience  of  Froissart  was 
perverted  by  prejudices  inherent  in  the  chivalry  which  he 
admired ;  that  of  Commines  by  an  estimate  of  statesmanship 
which  naturally  gained  acceptance  in  an  age  in  which  great 
and  even  beneficial  social  results  appeared  to  have  been  at- 
tained by  most  immoral  means.  Commines  was  not,  like 
Froissart,  indifferent  to  the  sufferings  and  the  rights  of  the  com- 
mon people ;  he  vigorously  and  feelingly  condemned  despotic 
government  and  arbitrary  taxation.  Nor  was  he  insensible 
that  the  ruler  who  violates  morality,  although  he  may  be 
approved  at  the  bar  of  history,  must  be  condemned  at  a  higher 
tribunal.  He  distinguished  between  the  politician  and  the 
man,  and  admitted  that  one  might  be  wise  as  a  politician  yet 
foolish  as  a  man.  The  masterly  account  which  he  gave  of  the 
last  illness  and  death  of  King  Louis  goes  far  to  compensate  for 
the  moral  laxity  which  he  had  shown  in  the  description  of 
some  of  his  actions.  His  not  unfrequent  references  to  God 
and  Providence  have  been  regarded  as  indications  that  he  had 
formed  a  general  and  so  far  philosophical  conception  of  his- 
tory. In  reality,  they  are  of  that  naive  and  simple  kind 
which  show  that  he  had  not.  He  made  such  references  only 
when  he  felt  experience  and  reason  fail  him  in  his  attempts  at 
historical  interpretation.2 

The  Hundred  Years'  War  between  the  French  and  the 
English  on  the  Continent  ended  about  the  middle  of  the 
fifteenth  century  with  the  English  being  driven  out  of  France 
and  the  French  being  united  into  a  large  and  powerful  nation. 

1  Lectures  on  Modern  History,  p.  119. 

2  On  Commines  may  be  consulted  Sainte-Beuve,  Caus.d.Lun.,i.  241-257;  Baron 
de  Lettenhove,  Lettres  et  Negoc.  de  Ph.  de  C,  Brux.  1867;  and  W.  Arnold,  Die 
ethisch-politisehen  Grundanschauungen  des  Philipp  von  Comynes,  Dresd.  1873. 
Villehardouin,  Joinville,  Froissart,  Monstrelet,  and  Commines  have  all  been  trans- 
lated into  English. 


184  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

So  long  as  France  was  engaged  in  the  struggle  for  existence 
on  her  own  soil  she  was  necessarily  but  little  affected  by  the 
intellectual  and  spiritual  movements  which  took  place  in 
other  countries.  When  she  came  forth  from  her  isolation, 
Europe  was  in  process  of  rapid  transformation.  Geographi- 
cal discovery,  mechanical  invention,  new  modes  of  thought 
and  research,  new  conditions  of  existence,  new  convictions 
and  aspirations,  had  begun  to  show  the  workings  of  a  new 
life  and  were  in  course  of  forming  a  new  world.  Industry, 
commerce,  war,  the  fine  arts,  literature,  government,  religion, 
science,  and  philosophy,  were  all  influenced  by  the  change. 
"  Novus  .  .  .  rerum  nascitur  ordo." 

The  sixteenth  century  brought  to  France  the  Renaissance 
with  its  passionate  study  of  the  ancient  classics  and  the 
Roman  jurists,  and  the  Reformation  with  its  violent  civil  and 
religious  strife  and  its  agitation  of  the  gravest  social  prob- 
lems. The  Renaissance  spread  from  Italy ;  the  Reformation 
from  Germany  and  Switzerland ;  and  in  France  their  influ- 
ences and  results  were  inextricably  blended.  They  pro- 
foundly affected  the  whole  history  of  France  in  the  sixteenth 
century,  and,  consequently,  also  the  character  of  its  historical 
literature. 

Italy  was  the  nation  first  quickened  by  the  modern  spirit,  and 
France  received  it  through  contact  with  her.  The  early  light 
of  Italian  culture,  however,  was  speedily  and  disastrously 
eclipsed  by  the  spread  of  priestly  obscurantism.  Hence 
already  in  the  sixteenth  century  France  had  outstripped  her 
instructress,  and  could  boast  of  having  in  Budaeus,  Turnebus, 
Lambinus,  Stephanus,  Scaliger,  and  Casaubon,  the  foremost 
scholars  of  their  age.  These  men  aimed  not  merely  at  master- 
ing the  languages  of  the  ancient  world,  but  at  comprehending 
its  entire  contents.  They  were  at  once  prodigies  of  philologi- 
cal and  historical  erudition  and  the  founders  of  philological  and 
historical  criticism.  Joseph  Scaliger,  in  particular,  rendered 
an  immense  service  to  historians  by  his  '  De  emendatione  tem- 
porum '  (1583)  —  the  first  scientific  treatment  of  chronology. 

The  flourishing  condition  of  jurisprudence  in  France  dur- 
ing the  sixteenth  century  must  also  be  noted  as  having  been 
highly  favourable  to  historical  study.     The  French  jurists  of 


PROGRESS   OF   HISTORIOGRAPHY  185 

that  age  would  appear  to  have  been  the  most  honourable  and 
meritorious  class  in  French  society,  if  we  may  judge  of  them 
from  those  of  their  number  whose  lives  have  been  recorded. 
They  were  not  more  remarkable  for  their  learning  and  ability 
than  for  their  independence  of  character  and  enlightened 
patriotism.  They  formed  the  chief  barrier  to  the  arbitrary 
power  of  the  kings,  and  were  often  the  best  exponents  of  the 
genuine  and  legitimate  aspirations  of  the  nation.  Men  like 
L'HSpital,  the  brothers  Pithou,  Hotman,  Bodin,  Pasquier, 
and  De  Thou,  were  drawn  to  historical  research  even  less  by 
their  love  of  knowledge  than  by  their  zeal  for  the  honour 
and  welfare  of  their  country  and  for  the  claims  of  justice  and 
humanity. 

The  doctrines  of  the  Reformation,  and  still  more  the  con- 
flicts to  which  they  gave  rise,  exercised  a  great  influence  on 
the  thought  of  France.  They  led  to  keen  discussion  of  the 
principles  on  which  government  and  society  rest.  They 
caused  the  competing  claims  of  State  and  Church,  of  civil 
authority  and  individual  conscience,  and  the  comparative 
merits  and  demerits  of  different  forms  of  religion  and  polity, 
to  be  debated  with  intense  interest  and  from  the  most  diverse 
points  of  view.  They  originated  a  multitude  of  pamphlets 
and  memoirs,  few  of  which  were  wholly  lacking  in  living 
force,  and  some  of  which  had  considerable  literary  merit. 
Through  them  the  opinions  and  passions  of  the  various  con- 
tending parties  found  direct  and  energetic  expression.  In 
the  pamphlets  the  theories  advocated  were  of  the  most  varied 
and  discordant  kinds :  all  opinions,  the  most  far-sighted  and 
the  most  short-sighted,  the  most  slavish  and  the  most  auda- 
cious, finding  defenders.  The  memoir  was  the  form  in  which 
history  was  chiefly  written  in  France  in  the  sixteenth  century ; 
and  the  memoirs  of  the  loyal  serviteur,  the  brothers  Du  Bellay, 
Gaspard  and  William  de  Tavannes,  Margaret  of  Valois,  Mont- 
luc,  D'Aubigne,  BrantSme,  and  others,  give  us  living  pictures 
of  their  authors  and  of  the  scenes  through  which  they  passed. 
They  contain  rich  stores  of  material  for  the  knowledge  of  an 
age  of  inexhaustible  interest. 

As  regards  general  history  Guicciardini  and  Machiavelli 
had  set  examples  very  difficult  to  imitate  with  success,  but 


186  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN"   FRANCE 

which  were  not  without  effect.  Bernard  Girard,  Seigneur  du 
Haillan,  born  at  Bordeaux  in  1537,  was  the  first  to  attempt 
to  write  a  general  history  of  France,  and  he  took  the  Italian 
writers  mentioned  as  his  models  in  regard  to  style  and  method. 
That  he  fell  far  below  them  was  due  not  to  want  of  will  but 
of  ability.  Concerning  Fauchet,  Du  Tillet,  Vignier,  De  Serres, 
and  others,  who  attempted  to  write  French  history  in  the 
French  language,  it  must  suffice  to  refer  to  the  interesting 
notices  of  them  given  by  Augustin  Thierry  in  his  '  Dix  Ans 
d'Etudes  Historiques.' 

The  only  really  eminent  French  historian,  if  the  term  be 
taken  in  its  strictest  sense,  belonging  to  the  sixteenth  century, 
was  De  Thou;  and  he  unfortunately  wrote  in  Latin.  His 
nobility  of  character,  his  experience  in  practical  affairs,  his 
singular  impartiality  of  judgment,  his  immense  capacity  of 
labour,  his  unswerving  love  of  truth,  rational  freedom,  and 
the  public  good,  his  vast  knowledge  of  all  kinds,  and  his 
natural  and  dignified  eloquence,  are  everywhere  displayed  in 
his  '  Historia  sui  temporis,'  and  amply  account  for  the  admira- 
tion with  which  it  has  been  regarded.  Its  defects  are  those 
inseparable  from  the  attempt  to  describe  modern  things  in  an 
ancient  language :  lack  of  pictorial  power  and  of  vision  for 
proportion  and  perspective ;  and  the  prolixity  due  to  exces- 
sive fulness  and  minuteness  of  detail.  The  author's  strength 
certainly  did  not  lie  in  aptitude  for  generalisation  or  philo- 
sophical insight.  Only  the  few  can  now  be  expected  to  read 
a  work  of  such  magnitude  as  this,  which  he  devoted  to  a 
period  of  only  sixty-three  years ;  but  so  long  as  history  con- 
tinues to  be  studied,  a  few  will  always  be  drawn  to  its  perusal 
either  by  inclination  or  duty,  and  these  will  not  fail  to  render 
it  the  praise  which  it  merits.1 

Two  political  treatises  published  in  France  in  the  sixteenth 
century  have  sometimes  been  referred  to,  but  erroneously,  as 
of  an  historico-philosophical  character  —  namely, '  Traite-  de 
la  Servitude  Volontaire  ou  Contre  un '  of  La  Boetie,  and  the 
'Vindicise  contra  tyrannos,  Stephano  Junio  Bruto  auctore.' 

1  On  De  Thou,  see  Collinson's  Life  of  Thuanus ;  Hallam,  Lit.  of  Europe,  vol.  ii. ; 
and  the  prize  discourses  of  MM.  Patin  et  Ph.  Chasles,  Sur  la  Vie  et  les  CEuvres 
de  J.  A.  de  Thou,  1824. 


PROGRESS   OF   HISTORIOGRAPHY  187 

The  former,  written  about  1548,  but  not  published  until  1578, 
is  little  more  than  a  vague  ardent  declamation  in  praise  of 
human  equality  and  republican  liberty,  forced  from  a  generous 
youthful  heart  by  contemplation  of  the  misrule  and  oppres- 
sion in  France  under  Henry  II.  It  is  not  in  the  least  learned 
or  profound,  but  it  has  lived  and  will  continue  to  live  because 
of  its  sincerity,  and  because  its  author  has  been  immortalised 
by  the  affection  of  Montaigne.1  The  "  Junius  Brutus  "  who 
wrote  "  against  tyrants  "  in  1579,  is  commonly  supposed  to 
have  been  Hubert  Languet,  although  some  still  contend  that 
he  was  Duplessis-Mornay.  His  theory  of  the  right  of  resist- 
ance to  monarchs  who  make  wrong  enactments  is  professedly 
based  on  Jewish  history  as  recorded  in  the  Old  Testament. 
The  book  is,  however,  almost  entirely  an  exposition  of  polit- 
ical doctrine.  There  is  little  history  in  it,  and  that  little  is 
treated  in  an  unhistorical  manner  and  spirit.2 

Two  other  works  have  to  be  noticed  which  concern  us  some- 
what more,  although  it  is  exaggeration  to  speak  even  of  them 
as  specimens  of  historical  philosophy.  The  'Franco-Gallia'  of 
the  famous  Protestant  jurist,  Francis  Hotman,  was  published 
in  1573 — the  year  after  the  Massacre  of  St.  Bartholomew.  It 
was  composed  hastily  and  in  the  most  adverse  circumstances, 
but  is  a  product  of  true  genius,  of  great  learning,  and  of  a 
singularly  manly  nature.  It  at  once  made  an  immense  im- 
pression, and  can  never  be  forgotten  in  the  history  either  of 
political  theory  or  of  constitutional  freedom.  It  was  the  first 
attempt,  and  a  most  vigorous  attempt,  to  show  that  freedom 
had  history  as  well  as  reason  on  its  side  ;  that  the  sovereignty 
of  the  people  as  displayed  in  the  choice  of  its  rulers  and  the 
limitation  of  their  powers,  could  be  traced  through  all  epochs 
of  French  history ;  and  that  the  despotic  claims  and  practices 
of  the  house  of  Valois  were  not  time-honoured  traditions,  but 

1  Leon  Feugere,  liitude  sur  la  Vie  et  les  Ouvrages  de  la  Boe'tie,  1845 ;  and  M. 
Payen,  Notice  sur  la  Boe'tie,  suivie  de  la  Servitude  Volontaire,  1853.  M.  Feugere 
edited  the  CEuvres  Completes  de  la  Boe'tie  in  1846. 

2  Lossen,  in  a  disquisition  in  the  Sitzungsberiehte  der  K.  Akad.  d.  Wissen- 
schaften  zu  Miinchen,  1887,  2,  maintains  that  Duplessis-Mornay  was  the  author 
of  the  'Vindioiae.'  It  seems  certain  that  the  edition  of  1579  was  not  printed  at 
Edinburgh,  as  alleged  on  the  title-page.  The  translation  into  English,  published 
in  1648,  is  said  to  have  been  the  work  of  Walker,  reputed  to  have  been  executioner 
of  Charles  I. 


188  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  IN   FKAMCE 

usurpations  similar  to  those  against  which  Gauls  and  Franks, 
Carlovingians  and  Capetians,  had  equally  protested.  In  a 
word,  the  thesis  which  Hotman  sought  to  establish  by  a  sur- 
vey of  the  history  of  France  was  the  same  which  has  gener- 
ally been  assumed  in  England  as  the  justification  of  popular 
liberties  — that  of  a  right  to  self-government,  which  was  not 
merely  an  abstract  dictate  of  reason,  but  a  something  so  real 
and  essential  that  it  had  always  been  contended  for  and  more 
or  less  possessed.  He  did  not  prove  all  that  he  believed  him- 
self to  have  proved — he  unquestionably  erred  in  details,  and 
made  insufficient  allowance  for  the  differences  of  the  various 
periods  —  but  he  made  good  what  was  of  most  importance  in 
his  contention,  and  brought  into  the  light  the  class  of  histori- 
cal facts  which  absolute  authority  had  the  strongest  interest 
in  seeing  left  in  obscurity.  -His  little  book,  containing  less 
than  two  hundred  pages,  and  with  three-fourths  of  it  quota- 
tions from  historians  and  chroniclers,  was,  on  the  whole,  a 
triumphant  exhibition  of  the  grounds  on  which  his  country- 
men were  entitled  to  deem  themselves  free-born,  not  merely 
as  men,  but  also  as  Frenchmen.  If  it  failed  to  show  that  the 
French  monarchy  had  been  elective,  it  at  least  succeeded  in 
proving  that  that  monarchy  had  begun  with  Louis  XI.  to 
enter  on  a  new  path  fatal  to  ancient  liberties.1 

Etienne  Pasquier  (1529-1615)  published  the  first  book  of 
his  '  Recherches  de  la  France  '  in  1560,  and  the  second  in 
1565 ;  five  others  were  added  during  his  lifetime,  and  three 
more  in  1643.  The  '  (Euvres  d'Etienne  Pasquier,'  published 
at  Amsterdam  in  1723,  consists  of  the  '  Recherches '  and 
'  Lettres.'  Of  the  former  Augustin  Thierry  has  thus  written : 
"  This  work  is  the  first  in  which  we  meet  with  what  has  since 
been  called  the  philosophy  of  history.  The  author,  a  disciple 
of  the  historical  school  founded  by  the  Italians,  and  a  great 
admirer  of  Paulus  Emilius,  does  not  confine  himself,  like  Du 
Haillan,  to  investigating  the  plot  of  political  intrigues,  or  to 
analysing  events  according  to  the  method  of  Machiavelli ;  he 

1  On  Hotman  see  the  two  articles  of  M.  Dareste  in  Rev.  Hist.  t.  ii.,  several 
articles  of  M.  Vigue  in  Renouvier's  Crit.  Rel.  1879, 1S80,  and  Etudes  Litte'raires 
sur  les  FiCrivains  Francais  de  la  Reformation,  par  A.  Sayous,  t.  ii.  1-57.  The  polit- 
ical views  oi  Hotman,  as  well  as  of  La  Boe'tie  and  the  author  of  the  '  Vindiciae,' 
will  be  found  stated  in  M.  Janet's  Hist.  d.  1.  Science  Politique. 


PROGRESS   OP   HISTORIOGRAPHY  189 

seeks  to  draw  from  history  moral  results,  and,  above  all,  to 
interpret  the  facts  in  a  new  manner  —  giving  them  a  signifi- 
cation more  general  and  more  favourable  to  the  freedom  of 
the  human  mind.  It  is  with  this  aim  that,  in  rather  a  dis- 
orderly fashion,  he  reviews  all  parts  of  the  history  of  France, 
events,  persons,  institutions,  manners,  customs,  language  ;  he 
reviews  them  all,  and  all  under  his  pen  assume  a  fresh  ap- 
pearance of  life.  Etienne  Pasquier  is  more  remarkable  for 
the  abundance  than  for  the  precision  of  his  ideas ;  his  criti- 
cism is  sometimes  subtle  instead  of  just ;  but  his  book  was 
calculated  strongly  to  stir  the  minds  of  his  contemporaries. 
It  is  the  only  erudite  work  written  in  the  sixteenth  century 
which  one  can  read  through  without  weariness,  and  it  was 
reprinted  even  in  the  last  century." 

Such  is  the  opinion  expressed  regarding  Pasquier's  'Re- 
searches '  by  an  eminently  competent  judge.  In  one  respect, 
however,  I  must  entirely  dissent  from  it.  There  is  no  phi- 
losophy of  history  in  Pasquier's  work.  His  ratiocinations  on 
historical  facts  sometimes  bear  a  superficial  resemblance  to 
those  of  Machiavelli  in  his  'Discorsi,'  but,  instead  of  being 
more,  they  are  much  less  philosophical  in  character  and 
scope ;  they  are  much  more  about  particulars,  and  show 
much  less  insight  into  the  general  causes  and  tendencies  of 
history.  The  real  and  distinctive  merit  of  Pasquier  is,  that 
he  was  the  first  to  make  a  serious  and  sustained  attempt  to 
trace  the  growth  of  the  institutions  of  France.  This  was  a 
very  important  departure,  —  the  inauguration  of  a  movement 
which  has  never  since  been  arrested  and  which  has  produced 
numerous  valuable  contributions  to  historical  knowledge. 
Pasquier  himself  must  be  admitted  to  have  collected  much 
useful  material  on  various  ancient  French  institutions.  Few, 
I  am  inclined  to  believe,  will  read  through  his  work  without 
weariness,  or  read  through  it  at  all ;  but  those  who  are  in 
quest  of  information  on  the  special  subjects  of  which  it  treats 
may  consult  it  with  profit. 

*  What  its  subjects  are  a  brief  summary  will  indicate.  The 
first  book  treats  of  the  character  and  culture  of  the  Gauls, 
and  the  causes  which  led  to  their  subjugation  by  the  Romans ; 
of  the  Frankish,  Gothic,  Burgundian,  and  Norman  invasions ; 
of  the  origin  of  the  Bretons  and  Gascons  ;  and  of  the  story  of 


190  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

the  descent  of  the  Franks  from  the  Trojans,  and  the  differ- 
ence of  opinions  as  to  the  nature  of  their  earliest  govern- 
ment. The  second  book  is  a  dissertation  on  the  old  French 
parliaments  and  provincial  assemblies,  the  functions  of  the 
great  officers  of  state,  the  feudal  nobility,  and  the  general 
distribution  of  society  into  classes,  prefaced  by  a  brief  dis- 
cussion as  to  whether  chance  or  policy,  fortune  or  prudence, 
had  contributed  most  to  the  building  up  of  the  kingdom  of 
France.  The  third  book  traces  the  growth  of  the  episcopate, 
the  gradual  assumption  of  supremacy  by  the  bishop  of  Eome, 
the  various  conflicts  between  the  Papal  See  and  the  Galli- 
can  Church,  the  introduction  of  ecclesiastical  abuses  into  the 
realm,  the  progress  of  the  sect  of  the  Jesuits,  and  the  course 
of  their  war  on  the  University.  In  chapter  44  there  is  in- 
serted the  famous  "pladoyer"  which  the  author  had  deliv- 
ered in  defence  of  the  University  and  against  the  Jesuits  in 
the  suit  before  the  Parliament  of  Paris  in  1564.  The  greater 
portion  of  the  fourth  book  treats  of  laws  and  judicial  cus- 
toms ;  the  rest  of  it  is  of  a  very  miscellaneous  character. 
The  fifth  book  relates  to  Clovis  and  his  descendants  of  the 
first  dynasty.  The  sixth  book  is  occupied  with  the  Capetian 
kings,  the  good  knight  Bayard,  the  fortunes  of  the  house  of 
Anjou,  and  sundry  marvellous  stories  which  Pasquier  had 
the  credulity  to  believe.  The  seventh  book  treats  of  French 
poetry.  The  eighth  book,  after  discussing  the  origin  of  the 
French  language,  attempts,  often  very  unsuccessfully,  to  ac- 
count for  many  peculiar  words,  idioms,  and  proverbs.  The 
ninth  book  contains  much  information  on  the  history  of  the 
University  of  Paris,  on  "  the  Faculties,"  and  on  the  spread  of 
Roman  law  and  its  prevalence  over  the  "droit  coutumier." 
The  last  book  examines  the  accusations  made  against  Queen 
Brunehaut  by  Fredegar,  Aimoin,  and  other  chroniclers,  and 
argues  that  they  are  to  be  deemed  calumnies.  The  foregoing 
summary,  short  and  general  although  it  be,  may,  by  showing 
what  Pasquier's  work  was,  also  show  what  it  was  not. 

t 
II 

The  first  French  writer  who  took  a  philosophical  view  of 
history  was  John  Bodin.  The  years  between  his  birth  in 
1530  and  death  in  1596  were  among  the  most  agitated  and 


BODIN  191 

eventful  in  the  history  of  France, — years  of  social,  politi- 
cal, and  religious  transition  and  strife,  which  naturally  led 
thoughtful  men  to  political  theorising.  And  of  all  who  in 
that  age  made  government  and  society  the  subject  of  reflec- 
tion, none  can  be  put  on  an  equality  with  Bodin  as  regards 
comprehensiveness,  depth,  and  truthfulness  of  insight.  The 
noble  moral  nature  of  L'Hcipital  enabled  him  to  apprehend 
as  clearly  some  of  the  great  practical  principles  of  social 
order,  and  especially  that  of  religious  toleration ;  but  neither 
L'HSpital  nor  any  other  had  such  enlarged  views  of  society 
as  an  object  of  science.  As  a  political  philosopher,  indeed, 
Bodin  had  no  rival  among  his  contemporaries,  and  none,  at 
least  in  his  own  country,  till  Montesquieu  appeared.  He 
had  great  native  force  of  intellect,  great  learning,  especially 
in  languages,  law,  and  history,  and  large  legal  and  political 
experience,  having  taught  jurisprudence  at  Toulouse,  prac- 
tised as  an  advocate  in  Paris,  shared  both  in  Court  favour  and 
disgrace  under  Henri  III.,  performed  admirable  service  as  a 
deputy  of  the  Tiers  Etat  in  the  Assembly  of  Blois,  and  filled 
various  important  offices  of  state.  It  is  a  striking  evidence 
that  even  the  greatest  men  may  not  be  exempt  from  the  most 
irrational  prejudices  of  their  age  that  this  broad  and  saga- 
cious thinker,  although  sceptical  as  to  all  positive  religions, 
should  have  been  an  extremely  credulous  believer  in  sorcery, 
the  virtues  of  numbers,  and  the  power  of  the  stars.  In  the 
sixteenth  century  it  was  still  most  difficult  for  the  mind  to 
emancipate  itself  from  these  delusions.1 

The  '  Republic,'  first  published  in  1576,  is  undoubtedly  by 
far  the  greatest  of  Bodin's  works.  In  the  history  of  the  phi- 
losophy of  government  and  legislation  there  are,  indeed,  few 
greater  works ;  perhaps,  as  Sir  Wm.  Hamilton  has  affirmed, 
none  in  the  whole  interval  between  the  appearance  of  the 
'  Politics '  of  Aristotle  and  that  of  the  '  Spirit  of  Laws '  of 
Montesquieu,  although  it  is  certainly  inferior  to  both  these 
treatises.2     The    '  Historic  Method '  (Methodus  ad  facilem 

1  The  superstitious  credulity  of  Bodin  is  most  completely  seen  in  his  Demono- 
manie  des  Sorciers,  1581 ;  and  his  religious  freethinking  in  his  Colloquium  Hepta- 
plomeres,  which  remained  in  manuscript  until  Guhrauer  published  extracts  of  it 
in  1841,  and  Noack  the  whole  work  in  18S7. 

2  Summaries  of  the  '  Republic '  sufficient  to  give  a  good  general  view  of  its 
character  are  to  be  found  in  Hallam's  Lit.  of  Europe,  vol.  ii.  (1st  ed.),  Lerminier's 


192  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

historiarum  cognitionem),  published  in  1566,  has  more  interest 
and  importance,  however,  for  the  student  of  the  philosophy  of 
history  than  the  '  Republic.'  Yet  it  is  not  a  philosophy  of 
history,  nor  does  it  even,  although  the  honor  is  one  which 
M.  Baudrillart  has  claimed  for  it,  lay  the  foundation  of  the 
philosophy  of  history.  It  makes  itself  no  pretension  of  the 
kind,  and  is,  what  it  professes  to  be,  not  a  philosophy  of 
history,  but  a  method  of  studying  and  appreciating  history. 

One  sign  of  the  general  awakening  of  interest  in  the  study 
of  history  which  took  place  throughout  Europe  in  the  six- 
teenth century,  was  the  appearance  of  publications  on  the  art 
of  writing,  reading,  and  judging  of  history.  A  few  works  of 
the  kind  preceded  the  treatise  of  Bodin.  One  of  the  earliest 
of  these  was  the  '  Theatrum  scribendse  historise  universae '  of 
Mylaeus,  published  at  Florence  in  1548  ;  the  most  popular  and 
interesting  was  Patrizi's  '  Delia  Storia  dialoghi  x.,'  published 
at  Venice  in  1560.  There  was  a  continuous  flow  of  such 
works  throughout  the  rest  of  the  sixteenth  and  almost  the 
whole  of  the  seventeenth  century.  The  'Penus  Artis 
Historicse,'  a  collection  of  eighteen  pieces  on  the  composition 
and  study  of  history,  all  with  two  or  three  exceptions  belong- 
ing to  the  sixteenth  century,  was  published  at  Basle  as  early 
as  1574.  The  treatise  of  Bodin  differs  from  the  other  "  historic 
methods  "  of  the  age,  not  in  essence  nor  as  to  design,  but  in 
involving  among  its  practical  directions  considerations  of 
scientific  value.  Its  aim  is  simply  to  teach  how  history  may 
be  read  in  an  orderly,  independent,  and  profitable  manner ; 
not  to  found,  and  still  less  to  elaborate  a  science :  a  great  and 
arduous  task,  however,  to  which  even  genius  is  only  competent 
when,  circumstances  favouring,  it  strenuously  exerts  itself 
with  conscious  and  definite  purpose,  and  an  exclusive  devotion 
to  its  fulfilment. 

In  the  following  account  of  Bodin's  treatise  I  shall  only 
seek  to  indicate  those  ideas  in  it  which  may  be  supposed  to 
have  some  interest  for  a  student  of  the  science  of  history. 


Introduction  a,  l'Histoire  du  Droit,  Heron's  History  of  Jurisprudence,  Bluntschli's 
Geschichte  des  Staatsrechts,  and  Janet's  Hist.  d.  1.  Sc.  Pol.;  while  that  in 
Baudrillart's  J.  Bodin  et  son  Temps  is  so  exceedingly  careiul  and  excellent  that 
scarcely  a  thought  of  any  value  in  the  original  has  escaped  heing  indicated. 


BODIN  193 

The  '  Methodus '  begins  with  a  preface  in  which  Bodin  dis- 
courses on  the  easiness,  pleasantness,  and  profitableness  of 
historical  study  —  "  de  facilitate,  oblectatione,  et  utilitate  his- 
torise."  Such  eulogies  of  history  were  coming  into  fashion 
when  he  wrote,  and  they  continued  to  be  much  in  fashion  for 
at  least  a  hundred  and  fifty  years  afterwards.  Perhaps  the 
one  now  best  remembered  is  Casaubon's  preface  to  Polybius 
(1609),  and  it  owes  the  honour  chiefly  to  the  merits  of  its 
Latinity.  The  only  real  present  value  of  any  of  them  is  as 
"  signs  of  the  times  "  in  which  they  appeared ;  they  show  us 
from  what  motives,  or  with  what  expectations  and  interests, 
the  men  of  the  sixteenth  and  seventeenth  centuries  turned  so 
eagerly  to  the  writing  and  reading  of  history.  Bodin  and 
his  contemporaries  turned  eagerly  to  history,  not  in  order  to 
explain  its  movement  or  ascertain  its  laws,  but  to  find  in  it 
intellectual  entertainment  and  practical  guidance,  materials 
for  their  literary  and  learned  pursuits,  and  especially  help  in 
moral  and  political  life.  They  conceived,  in  other  words,  of 
historical  knowledge  not  as  possibly  constitutive  of,  or  reduc- 
ible to,  science,  but  as  instrumental  and  subservient  to  some 
end  beyond  itself.  That  Bodin  should  have  believed  historical 
study  easy,  although  a  very  erroneous  opinion,  will  not  surprise 
us,  as  it  is  still  a  prevalent  delusion  both  among  the  writers 
and  readers  of  history.  As  soon  as  men  began  adequately  to 
realise  the  supreme  claims  of  truth  in  history  they  ceased  to 
write  eulogies  on  the  uses  of  history ;  and  at  the  same  time 
they  became  aware  that  truth  in  history  is  very  difficult  to 
reach.     This  stage  had  not  been  attained  in  Bodin's  day. 

His  '  Methodus '  contains  ten  chapters,  the  titles  of  which 
will  be  found  below.1  The  first  thing  in  it  to  be  noted  by  us 
—  keeping  our  special  aim  in  view  —  is  the  account  given  of 
the  nature  and  place  of  human  history.  History  in  itself  is 
represented  as  equivalent  to  true  narration  or  description. 
This  allows  of  its   being  divided  into  human,  natural,  and 

1  The  titles  referred  to  are :  1.  Quid  historia  sit,  et  quotuplex.  2.  De  ordine 
historiarum.  3.  De  locis  historiarum  recte  instituendis.  4.  De  historicorum 
delectu.  5.  De  recto  historiarum  judicio.  6.  De  statu  rerumpublicarum. 
7.  Confutatio  eorum  qui  quatuor  monarchias  aureaque  secula  statuunt.  8.  De 
temporis  universi  ratione.  9.  Qua  ratione  populorum  origines  haberi  possint. 
10.  De  historicorum  ordine  et  collectioue. 


194  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FKANCE 

divine.  Human  history  has  man  for  its  subject,  as  natural 
history  has  the  physical  world,  and  divine  history  God ;  or, 
more  definitely,  its  materials  are  the  free  actions  of  men  in 
the  widest  sense  of  the  term  action  —  all  human  "consilia, 
dicta,  facta."  The  distinctive  feature  of  human  history  is 
that  its  subject  is  constantly  changing,  whereas  God  and  na- 
ture change  not ;  they  remain  ever  the  same,  it  remains  no 
instant  the  same.  This  its  essential  characteristic,  incessant 
mutability,  has  given  rise  to  the  belief  that  no  principles  per- 
vade it ;  that  no  order  is  to  be  traced  in  it,  as  in  the  rest  of 
the  universe  and  in  other  kinds  of  knowledge.  But  that 
belief,  although  old  and  prevalent,  is  erroneous,  for  man  is  a 
soul  in  union  with  a  body,  an  immortal  spirit  immersed  in 
matter;  and  so,  although  through  the  influence  of  matter 
there  is  much  which  is  confused  and  contradictory  in  his 
actions,  yet  is  there  in  them  also  eternal  principles  which 
reveal  a  spirit  participant  of  the  divine  nature,  and  these 
principles  are  capable  of  being  apprehended.  It  may  be 
thought  that  there  can  be  no  need  for  going  to  human  history 
for  them, —  that  they  will  be  most  readily  apprehended  directly 
in  divine  history ;  but  no :  to  reason  from  the  divine  down  to 
the  human,  instead  of  rising  from  the  human  to  the  divine,  is 
to  reverse  the  true  order  of  study  and  begin  at  the  end.  Man 
ought  to  commence  his  inquiries  with  himself,  and  ascend 
gradually  to  the  supreme  and  ultimate  cause.  And  as  he  is  a 
compound  being  —  soul  and  body,  spiritual  and  material  — 
his  history  is  connected  with  that  both  of  nature  and  of  God; 
through  geography  with  nature,  through  religion  with  God. 
The  historian  of  man  must  take  careful  account  of  the  complex 
constitution  and  relationships  of  man,  and  trace  how  his  his- 
tory is  influenced  both  by  God  and  nature,  both  through  spirit- 
ual and  physical  forces.  Hence  two  sciences  are  requisite  to 
the  attainment  of  a  satisfactory  universal  history  of  man :  cos- 
mography, and  a  general  or  comparative  science  of  religions. 
Bodin  argues  that  history  should  be  studied  in  an  order  pro- 
ceeding from  general  to  particular  —  from  a  compendious  view 
of  universal  history  to  the  detailed  and  thorough  investigation 
of  its  several  portions  — in  such  a  manner  that  the  relations  of 
the  parts  to  one  another  and  the  whole  may  be  correctly  per- 


BODIN  195 

ceived.  He  has  much  to  say  on  collecting  and  recording 
under  appropriate  headings  the  utterances  and  incidents  fitted 
to  be  morally  or  politically  helpful.  He  devotes  considerable, 
space  to  observations  and  reflections  on  such  themes  as  the 
qualities  to  be  desired  in  the  historian,  the  rules  to'be  attended 
to  in  ascertaining  historical  facts  and  judging  of  historical 
evidence,  the  sources  of  the  prejudices  often  displayed  by 
historical  writers,  the  merits  and  defects  of  various  ancient 
and  modern  historians,  and  the  like.  These  are  seldom  very 
original  or  profound,  but  they  are  generally  judicious.  They 
show  that  Bodin  disliked  all  rhetorical  representations  of  his- 
tory ;  was  distrustful  of  those  writers  who  delighted  in  passing 
judgment  on  the  persons  and  transactions  they  described ; 
and  regarded  as  the  true  ideal  of  history  a  plain  and  exact 
exhibiti6n  of  what  had  happened  as  it  happened.  "  Historia 
nihil  aliud  esse  debeat  quam  veritatis  et  rerum  gestarum 
veluti  tabula." 

Sound  as  the  observations  just  referred  to  generally  are,  we 
seek  in  vain  among  them  for  traces  of  scientific  insight  into 
the  nature  of  historical  method.  Yet  Bodin  consciously  real- 
ised the  existence  of  historical  law.  He  felt  that  history  was 
pervaded  by  law.  He  owed  this  conviction  to  his  legal  studies. 
These  carried  his  inquisitive  and  thoughtful  mind  at  every 
instant  to  history,  and  soon  satisfied  him  that  law  and  history 
were  inseparably  bound  together  all  through  from  beginning 
to  end,  —  that  no  part  of  either  was  fully  intelligible  if  disso- 
ciated from  the  whole  of  the  other.  He  sets  himself  at  the 
very  outset — in  the  very  dedication  of  his  'Historic  Method' 
—  in  direct  and  declared  antagonism  to  those  who  claimed  to 
be  philosophical  jurists,  and  yet  confined  their  whole  attention 
to  the  law  of  Rome.  A  philosophical  jurist,  and  not,  like 
Cujas,  a  mere  interpreter  of  Latin  texts,  it  was  his  own  am- 
bition to  be ;  and  he  attacked  the  narrowness  of  his  renowned 
contemporary  not  so  much,  as  Hotman  did,  in  the  interest  of 
practical  utility,  as  of  scientific  truth.  No  study  of  Roman 
law,  he  argues,  however  complete  or  accurate,  can  give  more 
than  a  partial  notion  of  law.  It  is  absurd  to  make  Roman 
law  identical  with  or  the  measure  of  universal  law.  There  is 
a  universal  law,  in  which  all  codes  of  law  have  their  root  and 


196  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

rationale,  and  of  which  they  are  but  the  multiple  and  partial 
expressions  ;  but  to  reach  that  law  the  historians  must  be  con- 
sulted as  well  as  the  jurists,  in  order  that  Persians,  Greeks, 
Egyptians,  Hebrews,  Spaniards,  English,  Germans,  may  all 
find  their  due  place  by  the  side  of  the  Romans.  The  idea  of 
universal  law,  the  knowledge  of  which  can  only  be  reached 
through  the  methodical  study  of  history  as  a  whole,  is  central 
with  Bodin,  and  it  is  one  which  still  requires  to  be  urged, 
even  in  its  most  general  form,  on  the  thoughtful  consideration 
of  our  lawyers.  It  is  only  in  its  most  general  form  that  Bodin 
has  enunciated  it;  no  clear  distinction,  for  instance,  being 
anywhere  drawn  by  him  in  this  connection  between  natural 
and  positive  law.  He  clearly  saw  that  the  course  of  human 
things  was  an  orderly  process  or  development  naturally  and 
morally  conditioned  and  regulated,  but  he  had  only  the 
vaguest  conception  of  historical  law,  or  of  law  in  any  definite 
sense  of  the  term. 

Again,  Bodin,  as  I  have  already  had  occasion  to  mention, 
clearly  apprehended  and  stated  the  fact  that  history  has  been 
on  the  whole  a  course  of  progress.  The  seventh  chapter  of 
his  "  Method  "  is  on  this  account  of  special  and  permanent 
interest.  The  first  part  of  it  is  an  argument  to  the  effect  that 
whatever  may  be  meant  by  the  four  monarchies  of  the  prophet 
Daniel  —  and  Bodin  professes  himself  dissatisfied  with  all  the 
interpretations  —  it  is  not  meant  that  history  is  only  a  long 
course  of  intellectual  and  moral  deterioration.  Whatever 
these  monarchies  may  signify,  they  are  not,  as  some  suggested, 
the  four  ages  of  heathen  antiquity.  The  rest  of  the  chapter 
is  a  refutation  of  the  view  of  historical  development  which 
underlies  the  myth  of  the  four  ages,  the  view  that  mankind 
has  been  in  a  constant  movement  of  degradation,  from  an  age 
of  gold  to  an  age  of  iron,  becoming  ever  harder,  more  barren 
of  good,  more  audacious  in  evil.  Our  author  argues  that  this 
view  is  in  contradiction  to  the  Biblical  history,  which  tells  us 
so  early  of  the  Flood,  the  tower  of  Babel,  &c. ;  that,  from  all 
that  has  been  reported  to  us  by  heathen  poets  and  mythologers 
of  the  gods  and  heroes  of  the  so-called  golden  age,  it  would 
seem  to  have  been  the  true  age  of  iron ;  that  many  cruel  and 
unjust  customs  which  prevailed  in  the  palmiest  days  of  Greece 


BODIN  197 

and  Rome  had  come  to  be  seen  in  their  true  moral  light ;  that 
Christianity  had  brought  with  it  some  new  virtues  which  were 
leavening  the  world ;  that  even  the  barbarian  invasions  could 
be  seen  to  have  fulfilled  a  providential  purpose  ;  and  that 
modern  times  could  claim  such  inventions  as  the  compass  and 
printing,  had  discovered  a  new  world,  and  greatly  improved 
astronomy,  natural  history,  medicine,  and  industry.  He  com- 
pares the  advocates  of  the  continuous  deterioration  of  the  race 
—  those  who  fear  that  learning,  humanity,  and  justice  are  on 
the  point  of  disappearing  from  the  earth  to  return  to  their 
native  skies  —  to  old  men,  sick,  sad,  and  feeble,  the  burden  of 
whose  own  infirmities  leads  them  to  believe  that  the  world 
has  lost  all  its  virtue,  beauty,  and  goodness,  since  the  days 
when  they  were  young ;  and  to  sailors  who  should  fancy,  when 
launching  out  from  harbour  into  the  open  sea,  that  it  was  the 
capes  and  mountains,  the  houses  and  cities,  which  were  with- 
drawing. It  will  seem  strange  to  those  who  are  ignorant  how 
slow  has  been  the  growth  of  great  ideas,  that  with  so  clear  a 
perception  of  the  progress  which  had  pervaded  the  past,  he 
should  have  nowhere  affirmed  that  there  would  be  progress  in 
the  future.  His  whole  course  of  reasoning  seems  to  a  modern 
reader  to  involve,  to  necessitate,  this  affirmation ;  yet  nowhere 
is  it  made.  Nay,  instead  of  it  we  .find  phrases  (only  few,  it  is 
true,  and  these  vague  and  undecided)  indicating  a  belief,  or 
rather  suspicion,  that  human  affairs  might  return  to  where 
they  had  started  from,  might  revolve  in  a  cycle.  It  was  left 
to  a  still  greater  man,  born  thirty  years  later,  Lord  Bacon,  to 
give  prominence  to  the  aspect  of  progress  which  Bodin  over- 
looked ;  and  it  is  curious  to  observe  how  entirely  as  to  this 
matter  the  one  was  the  complement  of  the  other,  each  seeing 
only  the  half-truth.  Bodin  was  singularly  just  to  the  past, 
and  loved  to  dwell  on  it;  he  appreciated  even  the  middle 
ages,  which  were  so  misunderstood  and  calumniated  by  almost 
all  the  reformers,  both  of  religion  and  of  philosophy.  Bacon 
was  most  unjust  to  the  past,  being  quite  engrossed  with  the 
aspirations,  the  hopes,  the  ambitions  of  the  future ;  like  his 
great  contemporary  and  rival  in  renown,  Descartes,  he  despised 
the  olden  world  too  much  to  comprehend  it — his  eye  being 
riveted  on  prophetic  visions  of  the  new  world  which  shone 
before  him,  "  fresh  as  a  banner  bright  unfurled." 


198  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FEANCE 

Bodin,  it  must  be  further  observed,  does  not  stop  short 
in  merely  general  ideas,  but  aims  at  the  real  explanation  of 
events ;  he  does  not  rest  in  the  abstract,  but  tries  to  account 
for  the  concrete.  He  seeks  causes  and  endeavours  to  trace 
their  operations  in  the  complex  phases  of  history.  He  en- 
deavours especially  to  make  apparent  the  influence  of  two 
classes  of  causes, — physical  and  political  causes.  He  treats 
of  physical  causes  with  considerable  fulness  in  the  fifth  chap- 
ter of  the  '  Method,'  and  in  a  still  more  detailed  and  developed 
form  in  the  first  chapter  of  the  fifth  book  of  the  '  Republic' 
That  climate  has  an  influence  on  the  character  of  a  people, 
and  that  there  is  a  certain  correspondence  between  the  geog- 
raphy and  the  history  of  a  nation,  are  facts  so  obvious  that 
they  could  not  fail  to  be  noticed  very  early,  and  Hippocrates, 
Plato,  Aristotle,  Polybius,  and  Galen  stated  them  explicitly 
and  definitely ;  but  it  is  altogether  unfair  to  put  their  general 
enunciations  of  the  principle  that  physical  circumstances 
originate  and  modify  national  characteristics,  on  a  level  with 
Bodin's  serious,  sustained,  and  elaborate  attempt  to  apply  it 
over  a  wide  area  and  to  a  vast  number  of  cases.  Dividing 
nations  into  northern,  middle,  and  southern,  he  investigates 
with  wonderful  fulness  of  knowledge  how  climatic  and  geo- 
graphical conditions  have  affected  the  bodily  strength,  the 
.courage,  the  intelligence,  the  humanity,  the  chastity,  and,  in 
short,  the  mind,  morals,  and  manners  of  their  inhabitants; 
what  influence  mountains,  winds,  diversities  of  soil,  &c,  have 
exerted  on  individuals  and  societies ;  and  he  elicits  a  vast 
number  of  general  views,  many  of  which  indeed  are  false,  but 
many  of  which  also  are  true.  It  is  less  than  fair  to  Bodin  to 
say  merely,  as  Hallam  has  done,  that  "there  is  certainly  a 
considerable  resemblance  to  Montesquieu  in  the  chapter  on 
Climates  in  the  '  Republic' "  It  would  even  probably  be 
under  the  truth  to  say  that  one  half  of  the  propositions  main- 
tained in  books  xiv.-xviii.  of  '  The  Spirit  of  Laws '  are  dis- 
tinctly laid  down  in  that  chapter.  Ibn  Khaldun  excepted, 
with  whose  work  he  was  unacquainted,  Bodin  added  much 
more  to  what  his  predecessors  had  done  than  Montesquieu  to 
what  he  had  accomplished;  and  when  the  interval  of  time 
between  them,  and  their  consequently  different  opportunities 


BODIN  199 

of  amassing  appropriate  knowledge,  are  remembered,  his 
treatment  of  the  subject  must  be  deemed  the  more  remark- 
able of  the  two.  Indeed,  if  less  ingenious  than  Montesquieu, 
he  is  as  comprehensive,  and,  at  the  same  time,  not  chargeable 
with  obscuring  the  great  truth  that  man  is  free,  and,  through 
his  freedom,  fortified  by  virtue  and  education,  can  resist  and 
master  external  agencies. 

For  his  knowledge  of  the  working  of  political  causes  Bodin 
was  greatly  indebted  to  Aristotle.  But  he  made  use  of  what 
that  profound  thinker  and  keen  observer  taught  him  in  no 
servile  way,  and  added  to  it  extensively  from  his  own  reflec- 
tions, his  large  acquaintance  with  history,  and  his  varied  per- 
sonal experience.  He  divides  governments  into  democracies, 
aristocracies,  and  monarchies ;  and  tries  to  detect  and  deline- 
ate the  characteristics  and  conditions  of  each,  and  to  show 
how  they  originate  and  grow,  how'  they  strengthen  and  con- 
solidate themselves,  and  how  they  decline,  fall,  and  perish. 
He  distinguishes  revolution  from  anarchy,  the  former  being 
a  change  from  one  kind  of  government  to  another,  while  the 
latter  is  the  extinction  of  government;  and  he  accordingly 
finds,  since  the  distinct  forms  of  polity  are  three,  that  the 
kinds  of  revolution  are  six,  each  polity  being  capable  of  change 
into  two  others.  All  the  kinds  of  revolution  may  take  place 
from  different  causes,  and  may  be  prevented,  or  at  least 
delayed,  in  different  ways ;  and  he  investigates  the  manifold 
causes  and  counteractives  of  revolution  with  care  and  pene- 
tration, and,  wherever  his  astrological  superstitions  do  not 
lead  him  astray,  with  elevation  and  soundness  of  judgment. 
For  his  views  on  the  operation  of  physical  causes  the  sixth 
chapter  of  the  'Method'  ought  to  be  compared  with  the 
second,  third,  and  fourth  books  of  the  '  Republic,'  of  which  it 
seems  almost  like  a  risumi. 

Another  respect  in  which  the  '  Methodus '  of  Bodin  may 
interest  the  student  of  historical  science  is  that  in  the  eighth 
and  ninth  chapters  there  is  a  specimen  of  what  Dugald 
Stewart  has  called  conjectural  or  theoretical  history.  The 
eighth  chapter  is  an  inquiry  into  the  origin  of  the  world  and 
the  epochs  of  time,  and  the  ninth  into  the  origins  of  nations. 
Bodin  exaggerates  the  importance,  or  at  least  is  mistaken  as 


200  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

to  the  proper  position,  of  this  sort  of  research.  He  even  goes 
so  far  as  to  say  that  a  true  idea  of  the  origin  of  history  is  the 
thread  which  can  alone  guide  us  through  the  labyrinth  of 
history,  whereas  it  is  precisely  what  is  most  obscure  and  must 
remain  longest  unelucidated.  As  to  the  mode  in  which  he 
conducts  the  research,  there  is  at  least  as  much  to  praise  as 
to  censure.  He  tries  to  show  by  the  use  of  reason  alone  the 
truth  of  the  Mosaic  account  of  the  origin  of  the  world  as  a 
free  creation  by  God  in  time.  I  am  sorry  to  add  that  he  also 
concludes  that  the  world  must  have  been  created  in  Septem- 
ber, and  that  in  that  month  the  greatest  events  of  history  have 
taken  place.  He  likewise  maintains  that  there  will  be  an  end 
of  the  world,  and  refers  in  proof  to  the  reasons  given  by  "  the 
noble  mathematicians"  Copernicus,  Reinhold,  and  Stadius 
for  believing  that  the  earth  will  in  course  of  time  fall  into 
'the  sun.  In  an  independent  spirit  he  criticises  and  rejects  the 
divisions  of  history  into  epochs  which  were  prevalent  in  his 
time.  He  fails,  however,  to  make  a  satisfactory  distribution 
of  his  own.  The  one  which  he  favours  is  based  on  an  ethno- 
logical generalisation  set  forth  in  his  fifth  chapter,  referring 
the  achievements  and  fates  of  nations  to  their  racial  charac- 
teristics of  body  and  mind.  To  the  southern  peoples  he 
attributes  special  aptitudes  for  the  acquisition  of  knowledge 
and  wisdom,  to  those  of  the  middle  or  temperate  regions 
political  ability  and  commercial  activity,  and  to  those  of  the 
north  industrial  skill  and  military  enterprise  ;  and  accordingly, 
he  assigns  to  universal  history  three  corresponding  epochs,  the 
supremacy  of  southern  nations  ending  with  the  birth  of  Christ, 
and  that  of  the  middle  nations  with  the  Teutonic  invasions. 
He  shows  how  little  the  statements  of  historians  as  to  the 
origins  of  nations  are  in  general  to  be  relied  on.  It  cannot 
be  said,  however,  that  he  gives  much  evidence  of  insight  into 
the  principles  or  method  of  historical  criticism.  He  insists, 
at  considerable  length,  on  the  value  of  the  study  of  etymolo- 
gies as  a  means  of  throwing  light  on  facts  relative  to  which 
there  is  either  no  written  testimony  or  only  such  as  is  false. 

In  the  last  year  of  the  sixteenth  century  Lancelot  Voisin  de 
i>    la  Popeliniere,  a  zealous  Huguenot,  published  '  L'Histoire  des 


POPELINIEEE  201 

Histoires,  avec  l'id^e  de  l'histoire  accomplie,  plus  le  dessein  de 
l'histoire  nouvelle  des  Francois.'  The  work  consists  of  three 
parts,  • —  (1)  a  series  of  general  and  critical  remarks  on  previ- 
ous historians ;  (2)  a  delineation  of  the  character  and  duty  of 
a  true  historian ;  and  (3)  a  statement  of  objections  to  certain 
fables  and  hypotheses  current  as  to  the  origins  of  French  his- 
tory. It  shows  its  author  to  have  been  a  man  of  most  inde- 
pendent judgment.  The  classical  historians  are  boldly  denied 
to  be  entitled  to  pass  as  standards  or  models  for  modern  his- 
torians, whose  advantages  and  resources  are  described  as  far 
superior  to  theirs ;  and,  at  the  same  time,  modern  historians 
are  freely  censured  for  their  credulity  and  incompetence. 
This  remarkable  independence  of  mind  was,  however,  not 
supported  by  remarkable  talent,  or  extraordinary  research,  or 
literary  skill.  The  influence  of  Popelini^re's  work  was,  so 
far  as  I  can  trace  it,  neither  wide  nor  deep.  He  had  also 
published  in  1581  a  work  which  may  be  regarded  as  a  pre- 
cursor of  the  Universal  Histories  of  De  Thou  and  D'Aubigne", 
his  '  Histoire  de  France,  enrichie  des  plus  notables  occurrences 
survenues  en  provinces  de  l'Europe  et  pays  voisins,  soit  en 
paix,  soit  en  guerre,  tant  pour  le  fait  s^culier  qu'eccle"sias- 
tique,  depuis  l'an  1550  jusqu'a  ces  temps '  —  i.e.,  to  the  year 
1577.  De  Thou  consulted  it  with  profit;  D'Aubigne"  has 
spoken  of  it  in  terms  of  high  praise.1 

1  M.  Auguste  Poirson,  who  has  given  in  the  fourth  volume  of  his  'Histoire  du 
Kegne  de  Henri  IV. '  a  full  account  of  the  historiography  of  the  period  of  which 
he  treats  (pp.  272-341,  2d  ed.),  describes  Popeliniere  as  "  ce  Polybe  du  temps,  ce 
createur  de  l'histoire  generale,  aujourd'hui  a  peu  pres  ignore'  chez  nous,  a  notre 
honte." 


CHAPTER   II 

HISTORIOGRAPHY  AND  HISTORICAL,  REFLECTION  IN  FRANCE 
IN   THE   SEVENTEENTH   CENTURY:   BOSSUET 

I 

Henry  IV.,  notwithstanding  serious  faults  and  deep  in- 
consistencies of  character,  was  the  greatest  and  best  French 
monarch  of  modern  times.  By  his  military  skill,  his  politi- 
cal foresight,  his  enlightened  patriotism,  his  enforcement  of 
religious  toleration,  and  the  wisdom  of  his  administration, 
he  secured  to  his  country  internal  peace,  and  laid  the  founda- 
tion of  that  external  policy  which  saved  Europe  from  the 
despotism  of  the  house  of  Austria,  and  made  France  for  long 
the  leading  nation  in  the  world.  Richelieu,  under  Louis 
XIII.,  proceeded  on  the  same  lines,  with  a  clearness  of  view, 
a  persistency  of  purpose,  a  fertility  of  resource,  and  a  subtiltv 
in  the  employment  of  means  for  the  attainment  of  his  ends, 
probably  never  surpassed.  Unfortunately  he  also  crushed 
internal  liberties  in  a  way  which  Henry  IV.  would  not  have 
done,  and  which  proved  not  less  productive  of  disasters  in 
the  distant  future  than  of  immediate  advantages.  Mazarin 
adroitly  carried  out  the  plans  of  his  predecessor,  baffled 
personal  enemies,  and  suppressed  all  efforts  and  possibilities 
of  resistance  to  royal  authority.  On  Mazarin's  decease  in 
1661,  Louis  XIV.  took  all  power  into  his  own  hands,  and 
thenceforth  until  his  death  in  1715  ruled  entirely  according 
to  the  pleasure  of  his  own  will.  During  his  reign  France 
had  all  the  glory  which  absolute  monarchy  could  confer  upon 
her,  but  she  had  no  personality  apart  from  the  individuality 
of  her  sovereign.  His  will  was  her  law ;  and  he  might  well 
say,  "L'Etat,  c'est  moi."  The  throne  was  regarded  with  a 
servile  and  idolatrous  reverence  which  it  is  difficult  now  to 
realise.  The  king  was  feared  and  obeyed  as  if  he  were  a  god. 
202 


THE  SEVENTEENTH  CENTURY  203 

The  daily  atmosphere  in  which  he  lived  was  one  filled  with 
the  incense  of  semi-divine  honours.  Under  the  shadow  of 
the  throne,  and  in  close  alliance  with  it,  there  flourished  the 
tyranny  of  the  Church.  By  the  mass  of  the  nation  no  oppo- 
sition was  offered,  or  so  much  as  thought  of,  to  either ;  the 
most  abject  submission  was  demanded  and  unmurmuringly 
rendered.  Disbelief  and  discontent  were  not,  indeed,  extinct, 
but  they  dared  not  avow  themselves;  they  kept  silence  or 
expressed  themselves  in  guarded  whispers. 

The  history  of  France  in  the  seventeenth  century  was  sub- 
stantially the  history  of  the  growth  and  triumph  of  absolu- 
tism, —  an  absolutism  guided  by  statesmen  of  genius,  served 
by  great  administrators  and  famed  generals,  and  glorified  by 
orators,  authors,  and  artists  of  classic  excellence  and  world- 
wide renown.  This  fact  profoundly  influenced  the  develop- 
ment of  historiography  in  France  during  the  century.  The 
Muse  of  history  was  gradually  enticed  and  constrained  to 
become  a  lady  of  the  Court.  She  was  taught  to  attach 
supreme  value  to  dignity  of  deportment  and  elegance  of 
speech,  to  feel  more  ashamed  of  rusticity  than  of  mortal  sin, 
and  to  be  more  afraid  of  unpoliteness  than  of  untruthfulness. 
But,  it  must  be  added,  she  never  felt  fully  at  home  at  Court, 
and  prospered  there  much  less  than  most  of  her  sisters.  The 
historical  literature  of  the  age  of  Louis  XIV.  could  not,  for 
example,  compare  in  brilliance  with  its  oratorical  or  dramatic 
literature ;  indeed,  royal  patronage,  even  when  most  potent 
and  munificent,  called  into  existence  singularly  few  historical 
works  entitled  to  be  ranked  as  literature.  But,  under  the 
constraint  and  tuition  of  monarchs  and  ministers,  French 
historiography  gradually  lost  the  originality  and  audacity, 
and  the  sporadic  and  fragmentary,  passionate  and  polemic, 
character  which  it  had  in  the  sixteenth  century.  It  gradu- 
ally grew  tame,  methodical,  laboriously  erudite,  respectful 
and  even  servile  towards  authority. 

The  sixteenth  century  was  predominantly  an  age  of  pam- 
phlets and  occasional  writings  meant  for  defence  or  attack. 
The  seventeenth  century  was  predominantly  an  age  of  collec- 
tions and  compilations,  and,  in  a  lesser  degree,  of  works 
designed  to  gain  favour  as  literature.     The  "Memoir"  was 


204  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FEANCE 

common  to  both  centuries,  but  only  reached  its  full  maturity 
of  development  in  the  latter.  This  form  of  historical  compo- 
sition has,  in  fact,  never  in  any  land  or  age  been  cultivated 
with  so  much  success  as  in  France  during  the  seventeenth 
century.  Many  of  the  men  who  contributed  most  effectively 
to  the  making  of  the  history  of  France  in  the  seventeenth 
century  also  applied  themselves  to  describe  it  so  far  as  it 
affected  their  experience  or  was  affected  by  their  activity; 
and,  in  so  doing,  they  wrote  with  the  naturalness  of  men 
who  were  not  seeking  literary  fame,  and  with  the  freedom  of 
men  who  had  in  view  only  posthumous  publication.  The 
Memoirs  of  Sully,  Bassompierre,  Rohan,  Richelieu,  Retz, 
Rochefoucauld,  Saint-Simon,  and  of  many  others  who  might 
be  named,  are  inexhaustible  sources  of  psychological,  politi- 
cal, and  historical  instruction.  They  require,  indeed,  to  be, 
for  the  most  part,  used  with  caution  and  even  suspicion,  and 
strictly  tested  and  checked ;  but,  rightly  employed,  they  lead 
us  far  more  deeply  into  the  real  life  of  the  times  to  which 
they  relate  than  the  works  of  the  professional  or  official 
historians.  The  most  important  memoirs  written  in  the 
seventeenth  century  were,  of  course,  not  published  until 
the  arrival  of  times  of  greater  liberty. 

During  the  seventeenth  century  the  Jansenists,  still  more 
the  Jesuits  and  Oratorians,  and  most  of  all  the  Benedictines, 
distinguished  themselves  by  their  industry  and  zeal  in  his- 
torical research.  Their  services,  which  are  hardly  to  be 
overestimated,  cannot,  however,  be  here  described  or  even 
enumerated.  It  was  only  in  the  seventeenth  century  that 
the  study  of  medieval  history,  and  of  the  history  of  the 
Christian  Church,  began  to  be  prosecuted  with  comprehen- 
siveness and  thoroughness.  The  best  historical  work  done 
in  France  during  the  period  was  the  work  of  erudite  prepara- 
tion for  history,  —  that  of  such  men  as  Duchesne,  Ducange, 
Petau,  D'Achery,  Beluze,  Labbe,  Sismond,  Mabillon,  and 
their  many  worthy  associates.  Powerful  as  was  the  will 
of  the  Government,  it  could  not  prevent  independence  of 
judgment  and  the  exercise  of  criticism  in  regard  to  matters 
of  erudition.  It  was  unable  to  suppress  even  such  extreme 
scepticism  as  the  Abbe"  Hardouin  expressed  regarding  classi- 
cal and  medieval  history,  or  such  critical  boldness  as  Richard 


THE   HISTORIANS  205 

Simon  displayed  in  his  treatment  of  Biblical  history.  Both 
Gallicanism  and  Jansenism  exerted  a  good  effect  on  ecclesi- 
astical historiography;  and  the  ecclesiastical  historians  of  the 
period  were  at  least  equal  to  its  civil  historians.  Le  Nain  de 
Tillemont  showed  excellent  historical  qualifications,  although 
his  works  are  rather  compilations  drawn  with  the  most  accu- 
rate and  conscientious  diligence  from  the  best  sources,  sup- 
plemented by  learned  and  exact  investigation  of  questions  of 
difficulty,  than  finished  histories.  His  most  extensive  com- 
position, indeed,  professes  no  more,  as  its  very  title  indicates  : 
'Mdmoires  pour  servir  a  l'histoire  ecclesiastique  des  six 
premiers  siecles  ' ;  and  his  '  Histoire  des  Empereurs  '  is  of 
the  same  character. 

Scipion  Dupleix  and  Francois-Eudes  de  Mezeray  acquired 
reputation  in  the  department  of  civil  history.  The  popular- 
ity of  the  former  soon  passed  away.  He  wrote  'L'Histoire 
ge"nerale  de  la  France  avec  l'e"tat  de  l'Eglise  et  de  l'Empire  ' 
3  vols.,  (1621-43).  He  was  not  lacking  in  learning,  but  he 
was  credulous  and  bigoted.  He  accepted  a  large  amount  of 
fabulous  material  as  genuine  history;  did  not  even  hesitate 
to  represent  as  real  incidents  mere  inventions  of  his  own 
imagination;  and  judged  of  persons  and  events  under  the 
influence  of  strong  religious  and  political  passions.  He  had 
little  artistic  skill. 

The  popularity  of  Mezeray  as  an  historian  lasted  for  about 
a  century.  He  presented  his  work  to  the  public  in  two  forms, 
—  a  larger,  'Histoire  de  France  depuis  Faramond  jusqu'au 
R£gne  de  Louis  le  Juste '  (1621-1643,  3  vols,  fob),  and  a 
smaller,  'Abr£g<3  Chronologique  de  l'Histoire  de  France  ' 
(1668,  3  vols.).  The  latter  was  the  more  esteemed,  and  it 
passed  through  many  editions.  Mezeray's  was  the  first 
really  well- written  general  history  of  France;  and  it  was 
extremely  well  written,  — always  clear  and  natural  in  style, 
and  not  infrequently  animated  and  eloquent.  It  was,  fur- 
ther, a  truly  national  history,  describing  not  merely  the 
growth  of  the  French  monarchy,  but  of  the  French  people. 
It  portrayed  the  characters  and  conduct  of  kings  and  their 
ministers  with  rare  honesty;  it  neither  ignored  nor  glossed 
over  administrative  abuses,  and  the  wrongs  and  sufferings 
inflicted  on  the  peasantry  and  traders;  it  dwelt,  as  no  pre- 


206  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

vious  historical  work  had  done,  on  the  general  economic  and 
social  condition  of  the  community,  and  on  the  state  of  the 
towns  and  provinces.  It  showed  its  author  to  be  a  man  of 
honest,  humane,  and  sympathetic  heart;  and  it  displayed  an 
independence  of  mind  which  cost  him  his  pension  as  royal 
historiographer,  but  did  him  the  highest  honour.  It  had, 
however,  one  serious  defect  which  greatly  detracted  from  its 
value  and  necessarily  shortened  the  duration  of  its  reputation. 
Its  statements  cannot  be  relied  on ;  they  have  not  been  drawn 
from  primary  and  trustworthy  sources ;  tbey  are  unsupported 
by  evidence  sufficiently  tested ;  and,  in  fact,  they  are  almost 
as  often  false  as  true.  With  not  a  few  excellent  qualities, 
therefore,  the  work  cannot  be  pronounced  a  good  history ;  it 
wholly  fails  to  meet  th§  first  and  most  essential  of  historical 
requirements. 

Historical  art,  unlike  historical  research,  made  no  progress 
in  France  during  the  last  forty  years  of  the  seventeenth  cen- 
tury. The  works  of  writers  like  Maimbourg  and  Varillas 
were,  indeed,  widely  read,  but  they  deserved  little  of  the 
approbation  which  for  a  season  they  obtained.  They  are  to 
be  numbered  among  the  signs  of  that  moral  and  intellectual 
decay  which  Mr.  Buckle  has  so  conclusively  shown  to  have 
resulted  in  all  departments  of  literature  from  the  system  of 
government  in  operation  under  Louis  XIV. 

No  work  of  much  importance  on  historic  art  or  method 
appeared  in  France  during  the  seventeenth  century.  The 
subject  was  touched  on  by  many,  but  treated  with  depth  of 
insight  or  investigated  with  care  by  none.  La  Mothe  le 
Vayer,  courtier,  academician,  and  perceptor  of  the  brother  of 
Louis  XV.,  endeavoured  to  find  in  history  confirmation  and 
illustrations  of  scepticism.  He  sought  to  show  that  opinions 
and  practices  were  so  inconsistent,  and  that  reason  in  all 
directions  led  to  such  uncertain  results,  that  a  wise  man  will 
doubt  of  all  things  except  divinely  revealed,  truths.  He 
based  his  scepticism  on  history,  and  was  at  the  same  time 
sceptical  in  regard  to  history.  This  is  seen  most  clearly  in 
his  'Discours  du  peu  de  certitude  en  l'Histoire '  (1668). 
His  earlier  'Discours  de  l'Histoire  '  (1636)  is,  in  the  main, 
a  criticism  of  the  Spanish  historian  Sandoval  from  a  French 
point  of  view;  but  it  also  ridicules  effectively  the  way  in 


^RITERS   ON   HISTORIC   METHOD  207 

which  historians  were  accustomed  to  trace  the  descent  of 
noble  families  from  famous  personages  of  remote  antiquity, 
and  indicates  forcibly  how  the  judgments  of  historians  are 
perverted  by  national  prejudices  and  personal  interests.  He 
was  a  great  admirer  of  the  classic  authors,  and  urged  his 
contemporaries  to  take  the  Greek  and  Roman  historians  as 
their  models  in  historiography.  He  was  the  immediate  pred- 
ecessor, the  direct  precursor,  of  Bayle,  by  whom  his  writings 
are  often  quoted.1 

The  'Discours  des  conditions  de  l'Histoire  '  (1632)  of  De 
Silhon  calls  for  no  special  notice.  The  anonymous-  'La 
Science  de  l'Histoire  '  (1665)  has  an  attractive  title,  but  is  a 
poor  book.  It  contains  nothing  of  a  scientific  character.  It 
consists  of  twenty-two  short  chapters,  which,  with  the  excep- 
tion only  of  the  first  and  last,  refer  to  the  histories  of  par- 
ticular nations  and  provinces.  It  has  been  attributed  to 
Charles  Sorel,  but  erroneously,  as  I  infer  from  the  way  in 
which  Sorel  wrote  in  his  'Science  Universelle '  (torn,  iv.y 
pp.  90,  91),  published  in  1668. 

Father  Le  Moyne's  'De  l'Histoire,'  1670,  translated  into 
English  in  1694,  is  a  rhetorical  and  affected  composition, 
without  any  solid  merits.  The  judgments  pronounced  by  it 
on  historians  like  Thucydides  and  Sallust  are  unwarranted 
and  presumptuous.  One  of  the  seven  dissertations  of  which 
it  consists  is  a  defence  of  the  introduction  of  feigned  speeches 
into  history,  but  it  is  entirely  destitute  even  of  ingenuity  in 
error. 

The  Abbe"  De  Saint-Real  published  in  1671  a  treatise 
'De  l'usage  de  l'Histoire.'  It  proceeds  on  the  supposition 
that  history  is  unprofitable  if  treated  merely  as  a  record  of 
events,  and  only  of  value  in  so  far  as  it  enables  us  to  know 
men ;  and  that  to  know  men  is  to  know  their  motives,  pas- 
sions, follies,  and  illusions.  The  assumption  is  applied  in 
an  attempt  to  prove  that  brilliant  actions  have  often  originated 
in  extravagance  and  stupidity ;  that  human  sentiments  and 
deeds  have  been  largely  influenced  by  malignity ;  that  almost 
all  that  men  do  has  been  prompted  and  pervaded  by  vanity ; 

1  The  last  or  Dresden  edition  of  La  Mothe  le  Vayer's  works  consists  of  fourteen 
vols.  8vo,  1756-59.  There  is  a  good  monograph  — '  Essai  sur  la  Mothe  le  Vayer '  — 
by  L.  Etienne,  published  at  Rennes,  1849. 


208  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

and  that  universally  and  irresistibly  the  senses  of  men  have 
been  perverted,  their  reasons  deluded,  and  their  convictions 
determined,  by  the  force  of  prevalent  opinion.  In  a  word, 
according  to  Saint-Real,  the  proper  study  of  mankind  is  man, 
and  the  great  advantage  to  be  derived  from  the  study  is  a 
knowledge  of  the  meanness  and  contemptibleness  of  man. 

In  1677  Father  Rapin  published  his  'Instructions  sur 
l'Histoire.'  Having  carefully  read  the  various  compositions 
which  had  appeared  during  the  fifteenth  and  sixteenth  cen- 
turies on  the  wajr  in  which  history  should  be  written,  he 
adopted  what  was  valuable  in  them,  and  largely  supple- 
mented it  by  his  own  reflections.  The  result  was  a  treatise 
much  superior  as  regards  both  comprehensiveness  and  ju- 
diciousness to  any  of  its  predecessors;  the  first  fairly  ade- 
quate treatment  of  history  as  a  species  of  literature,  or  of 
what  has  been  called  the  rhetoric  of  history. 

It  is  in  the  latter  half  of  the  sixteenth  century  that  we  first 
meet  with  comparative  studies  in  literature.  Father  Rapin's 
'Comparaison  de  Thucydide  et  de  Live  '  (1681)  is  an  instance 
of  the  kind  in  the  department  of  historical  literature ;  but 
one  of  higher  merit  is  Saint-Evremond's  'Considerations  sur 
Salluste  et  Tacite.'  This  witty,  epicurean  habituS  of  the 
Court  of  our  Charles  II.  has  shown,  at  least  at  times,  a  keen- 
ness and  originality  of  observation  and  insight,  in  regard  both 
to  history  and  the  art  of  history,  very  exceptional  in  his  age. 
These  qualities  are  displayed  in  a  high  degree  both  in  his 
'Considerations  sur  le  Genie  du  peuple  Romain '  (1695)  and 
in  his ' Characterisations  of  Classical  and  French  Historians.' 

In  the  last  decade  of  the  century  the  Oratorian  priest, 
Father  Thomassin,  published  a  'Melhode  d'dtudier  et  d'en- 
seigner  chre'tienment  et  solidement  les  historiens  profanes.' 
It  is  divided  into  three  books.  The  first  is  a  sketch  of  the 
history  of  man,  of  the  succession  of  empires,  from  the  crea- 
tion of  the  world  to  the  establishment  of  Christianity;  the 
second  is  an  attempt  to  show  that  the  ancient  historians 
supply  confirmation  of  the  chief  truths  of  religion;  and  the 
third  endeavours  to  prove  that  they  equally  bear  witness  to 
the  validity  and  prevalence  of  the  principles  of  morality. 
The  work  gives  evidence  of  diligent  reading,  but  its  worth 
lies  almost  entirely  in  its  quotations. 


SCEPTICISM   AND   HISTOKY  209 

The  philosophy  of  the  seventeenth  century  did  not  aim  at 
interpreting  and  comprehending  history ;  at  tracing  the  move- 
ment of  reason  through  the  complications  and  aberrations  of 
human  affairs.  It  showed  scarcely  any  interest  in  the  explana- 
tion of  social  phenomena.  A  thorough  and  fruitful  blending 
of  philosophy  and  history  was  as  yet  in  the  far  future;  a 
general  recognition  of  its  possibility  and  desirableness  will 
be  sought  for  in  vain  in  any  century  but  the  present. 

The  French  philosophy  of  the  seventeenth  century  assumed 
two  forms,  a  negative  or||ceptical  and  a  positive  or  rational. 
The  scepticism  which  was  represented  in  the  sixteenth  cen- 
tury by  Rabelais,  Montaigne,  and  Charron,  was  propagated 
in  the  seventeenth  by  Le  Vayer,  Huet,  and  Bayle.  But 
Bishop  Huet,  although  a  sceptic  and  an  historian,  showed  no 
scepticism  as  an  historian.  It  was  otherwise  with  Le  Vayer, 
as  has  already  been  indicated,  and  especially  with  Peter 
Bayle,  the  famed  author  of  the  'Dictionnaire  Critique.' 
The  latter  is,  perhaps,  the  best  example  which  the  history  of 
literature  supplies  of  what  has  been  called  "  erudite  scepti- 
cism,"^—  the  scepticism  which  finds  in  historical  learning  an 
arsenal  of  weapons  both  for  defence  and  attack, —  the  scepti- 
cism which  Bayle  himself  designated  "historical  Pyrrhon- 
ism."  He  had  an  insatiable  and  undiscriminating  curiosity 
regarding  facts  and  opinions,  wonderful  logical  dexterity, 
extreme  ingenuity  in  inventing  and  great  fondness  for  main- 
taining paradoxes.  With  but  feeble  cravings  either  for  fixed 
principles  or  for  unity  and  harmony  in  his  speculations,  a 
want  of  moral  delicacy,  and  no  profound  religious  emotions, 
he  was  animated  by  a  sincere  love  of  independence  of  thought, 
and  a  cordial  hatred  of  intolerance  and  persecution.  The 
whole  constitution  of  his  nature,  his  personal  experience 
of  life,  and  his  special  acquirements,  rendered  him  a  most 
powerful  assailant  of  dogmatism;  and  he  was  unsurpassed  in 
the  art  of  so  suggesting  and  accumulating  doubts  regarding 
particular  questions  and  opinions  of  every  kind  as  to  produce 
universal  doubt,  a  feeling  of  the  uncertainty  of  all  that  pro- 
fesses to  be  knowledge.  Under  cover  of  the  assumption  of 
the  opposition  of  reason  and  faith,  he  skilfully  laboured  to 
humiliate  both,  by  convicting  the  former  of  inability  to  dis- 
cover truth  with  certainty,  and  the  latter  of  teaching  absurd- 


210  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOKY   IN   PRANCE 

ities  with  a  claim  to  impunity.  "My  talent,"  he  said,  "is 
to  form  doubts,  which  for  me  remain  merely  doubts ; "  and 
he  unquestionably  put  out  his  talent  to  usury,  suggesting 
and  spreading  doubts  with  a  success  unattained  by  any  man 
before  him  in  Christendom.  In  the  seventeenth  century  the 
talent  was  on  the  whole  a  valuable  one,  and  the  diligent  ex- 
ercise of  it  highly  beneficial.  It  was  so,  at  least,  as  regards 
historiography,  which  suffered  greatly  from  credulity  and 
submissiveness  to  traditional  and  dogmatic  authorities.  No 
man  of  the  seventeenth  century  contributed  so  much  to  the 
historical  scepticism  and  historical  criticism  of  the  eighteenth 
century  as  Bayle.  His  influence  was  felt  most  in  France, 
but  it  told  powerfully  also  in  England  and  Germany;  its 
range  was  European.1 

The  dominant  philosophy  in  France  in  the  seventeenth 
century  was  the  Cartesian.  In  1637  —  that  is,  eighty  years 
after  the  appearance  of  Bodin's  'Historic  Method'  —  Des- 
cartes published  his  'Discours  de  la  Mdthode.'  It  had  for 
avowed  aim  to  effect  a  general  revolution  in  human  thought, 
to  determine  once  for  all  the  method  of  rightly  conducting 
the  reason  in  the  search  for  scientific  truth,  and  to  prove 
convincingly  that  it  was  the  right  method  by  showing  the 
number  and  value  of  the  results  to  which  it  led.  It  so  far 
accomplished  its  end  that  the  name  of  Rend  Descartes  stands 
by  universal  consent,  along  with  that  of  our  own  Francis 
Bacon,  at  the  head  of  the  modern  epoch  of  philosophy.  With 
them  the  world  shook  itself  finally  loose  from  the  grasp  of 
scholasticism,  and  definitively  entered  on  the  path  which  it 
is  still  pursuing.  They  had  many  predecessors,  among  whom 
were  not  a  few  martyrs,  but  it  was  given  only  to  them  decis- 
ively to  succeed,  partly  owing  to  the  labours  of  others  and 
the  ripeness  of  the  times,  and  partly  owing  to  the  greatness 
of  their  own  abilities  and  the  merits  of  their  own  works. 

Vast,  however,  as  was  the  influence  of  Descartes,  it  cannot 
be  said  to  have  done  much,  directly  and  explicitly  at  least, 
for  the  study  of  history.  He  was  early  satisfied  that  he  had 
read  histories  enough ;  he  had  no  notion  of  a  science  of  his- 

1  A.  Deschamps,  'La  Genese  du  Scepticisme  erudit  chez  Bayle,'  Liege,  1878; 
L.  Feuerbacb,  'Pierre  Bayle:  Ein  Beitrag  zur  Geschichte  der  Pliilosophie  und 
Menschheit'  (Sammtliche  Werke,  Bd.  vi.). 


CAETESIANISM   AND   HISTORY  211 

tory ;  and  he  so  little  perceived  an  indwelling  reason  in  soci- 
ety pervading  and  determining  its  movements  and  changes 
that  he  could  expressly  declare  it  as  his  belief  that  "  laws 
which  have  grown  up  gradually  as  required  by  national  wants, 
as  suggested  by  experience  of  the  evil  effects  of  particular 
crimes  and  disputes,  must  necessarily  be  inferior  to  those 
which  have  been  invented  and  imposed  by  individual  wisdom 
and  authority,  just  as  buildings  which  different  persons  have 
tried  to  improve  by  making  use  of  old  walls  for  other  than 
their  original  purposes  must  be  inferior  to  buildings  designed 
and  executed  by  a  single  architect,  and  just  as  ancient  cities 
which,  from  being  at  first  only  villages,  have  grown  up  in 
the  course  of  time  into  large  towns,  cannot  compare  in 
regularity  and  symmetry  with  towns  which  have  been 
built  on  a  uniform  plan  devised  by  one  person."1  In  fact, 
Descartes  conceived  of  philosophy  in  a  way  which  scarcely 
allowed  of  there  being  any  philosophy  of  history,  and  which 
led  naturally  to  the  neglect  and  depreciation  of  all  historical 
study.  In  historical  research  the  mind  is  conversant  with 
contingent  phenomena,  and  must  content  itself  with  proba- 
ble evidence.  But  Descartes  placed  the  criterion  of  truth  in 
the  clearness  and  distinctness  of  the  convictions  of  the  indi- 
vidual mind,  and  insisted  that  reason  ought  to  be  satisfied 
only  with  necessary  truth  and  with  the  conclusions  which 
can  be  deduced  therefrom  with  mathematical  strictness. 
These  views,  with  his  contempt  for  antiquity,  and  confi- 
dence in  his  own  powers  and  method,  not  only  prevented  his 
recognising  the  interest  and  importance  of  historical  study, 
but  caused  him  to  regard  with  aversion  every  kind  of  erudi- 
tion which  historical  study  requires.  His  followers  in  gen- 
eral entertained  the  same  feeling.  Malebranche  reproached 
D'Aguesseau  for  wasting  his  time  in  reading  Thucydides. 
It  was  only  with  the  decay  of  Cartesianism  that  historical 
science  began  to  flourish  in  France.  And  in  Italy,  early  in 
the  eighteenth  century,  the  illustrious  Vico  is  found  com- 
plaining bitterly  that  the  spread  of  this  philosophy  has  been 
ruinous  to  the  cause  of  learning.  Undoubtedly  Cartesianism 
was  not  essentially  favourable  to  historical  study. 

It  was,  however,   not  altogether  unfavourable.     On  the 

1  Discours  de  la  Methode  (ed.  Simon),  p.  8. 


212  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

contrary,  it  demanded  and  fostered  an  independence  of  mind 
which  is  nowhere  more  needed  than  in  historical  inquiry  and 
speculation ;  it  spread  among  all  thoughtful  men  the  convic- 
tion that  the  infinite  variety  of  phenomena  in  the  universe 
might  be  reduced  to  a  very  few  simple  laws;  and  it  gave 
general  currency  to  the  idea  of  progress.  Descartes  shows 
incidentally  in  many  passages  of  his  writings  that  he  had 
looked  on  social  facts  with  a  clear  keen  eye.  And  so  does 
Malebranche.  Faith  in  progress,  confidence  in  the  powers  of 
the  human  mind  and  in  the  grandeur  of  the  future  destinies 
of  the  human  race,  associated,  as  in  Lord  Bacon,  with  con- 
tempt for  antiquity,  pervade  the  entire  philosophy  of  Des- 
cartes, and  frequently  find  expression  in  his  writings.  In 
Malebranche,  both  the  confidence  and  the  contempt  perhaps 
reached  their  height;  but  they  may  be  traced  in  some  meas- 
ure through  most  works  belonging  to  the  Cartesian  school. 
The  conception  which  Bacon  expressed  in  the  adage,  Anti- 
quitas  sceculi  juventus  mundi,  is  to  be  found  also  both  in 
Descartes1  and  Malebranche.2  Pascal,  however,  has  sur- 
passed all  others  in  his  felicitous  statement  of  it:  "The 
whole  succession  of  human  beings  throughout  the  whole 
course  of  ages  must  be  regarded  as  a  single  individual  man, 
continually  living  and  continually  learning;  and  this  shows 
how  unwarranted  is  the  deference  we  yield  to  the  philoso- 
phers of  antiquity;  for,  as  old  age  is  most  distant  from 
infancy,  it  must  be  manifest  to  all  that  old  age  in  the  uni- 
versal man  should  not  be  sought  in  the  times  near  his  birth, 
but  in  the  times  most  distant  from  it.  Those  whom  we  call 
the  ancients  are  really  those  who  lived  in  the  youth  of  the 
world,  and  the  true  infancy  of  man;  and  as  we  have  added 
the  experience  of  the  ages  between  us  and  them  to  what  they 
knew,  it  is  only  in  ourselves  that  is  to  be  found  that  antiquity 
which  we  venerate  in  others."3 

The  historian  of  the  idea  of  progress  will  find  ample 
materials  for  a  chapter,  both  amusing  and  instructive,  in  a 
controversy  which  gave  rise  to  much  heat  and  noise,  during 

i  Baillet,  Vie  de  Descartes,  vii.  10;  Discours  de  la  Methode  (ed.  Cousin),  pp. 
125,  126,  192-194,  219,  &c. 

2  Recherche  de  la  Verite,  11"  partie,  u.  v.  and  vi.,  &c. 
*  Pense'es,  i.  91-101  (ed.  Faugere). 


MEEJTS   OF   THE   ANCIENTS   AND   MODERNS  213 

the  seventeenth  century,  in  France  as  well  as  in  Italy  and 
England,  concerning  the  relative  merits  of  the  ancients  and 
moderns.  Some  knowledge  of  its  character  and  course  is 
well  worth  acquiring,  from  its  being  so  eminently  character- 
istic of  an  age  almost  equally  influenced  by  reformatory 
philosophic  tendencies  and  by  scholastic  and  classic  tradi- 
tions. In  no  former  age  had  men  ever  dreamt  of  contesting 
the  superiority  of  ancient  to  modern  literature.  That  a  large 
body  of  authors  of  moderate  abilities  and  of  no  extraordinary 
courage  should  now  have  ventured  to  attack  classical  authority 
in  the  rudest  and  crudest  manner,  proved  that  an  enormous 
change  had  taken  place  in  human  thoughts  and  habits.  A 
very  slight  acquaintance  with  the  dispute  suffices  to  show 
that  most  of  those  who  exalted  the  writers  of  antiquity,  and 
of  those  who  depreciated  them,  alike  did  so  on  false  grounds ; 
the  former  admiring  them  for  excellences  which  did  not 
exist,  and  the  latter  censuring  as  defects  what  were  really 
excellences.  It  would  be  out  of  place,  however,  to  treat  here 
of  the  merits  and  demerits  of  the  two  parties.  It  is  enough 
to  direct  attention  to  the  very  obvious  circumstance  that 
the  controversy  turned  on  the  idea  of  progress,  and  tended  to 
give  prominence  to  that  idea,  to  promote  its  circulation,  and 
to  make  it  the  subject  of  reflection  and  criticism.  Neces- 
sarily, it  found  frequent  expression,  and  not  seldom  exagger- 
ated expression,  from  those  who,  like  Boisrobert,  Perrault, 
Lamotte,  and  Terrason,  took  the  part  of  the  moderns.  The 
question  which  they  discussed  was  not  merely  the  vague  and 
futile  one  as  to  the  comparative  merits  of  ancient  and  modern 
authors,  but,  in  the  main,  the  question  as  to  whether  the 
movement  of  civilisation  was  towards  improvement  or  deteri- 
oration. One  regrets  to  find  that  a  man  of  the  knowledge 
and  talent  of  Macaulay  could  have  shown  himself,  in  his 
essay  on  Sir  William  Temple,  capable  only  of  perceiving  in 
the  controversy  a  "battle  of  the  books,"  and,  indeed,  only 
the  ridiculous  aspects  of  it  as  such.  He  had  simply  to  glance 
through  the  most  celebrated  book  published  in  the  contro- 
versy, Perrault's'Paralleleentreles  anciens  et  les  modernes  ' 
(1690),  and  he  must  have  seen  that  what  was  substantial  and 
vital  in  it  was  the  attempt  to  prove  by  a  survey  of  archi- 
tecture, sculpture,  painting,  eloquence,  history,  and  poetry, 


214  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

science,  philosophy,  and  religion,  that  men  ought  not  to  look 
back  to  the  age  even  of  Pericles  or  Augustus  for  models 
of  absolute  perfection  and  perpetual  imitation,  but  should 
proceed  on  the  conviction  that  inexhaustible  possibilities  of 
achievement  still  lay  before  them  in  all  directions.  This 
conclusion  cannot  be  set  aside  by  pointing  out  that  Perrault 
was  unacquainted  with  Greek,  and  had  the  bad  taste,  or, 
rather,  ignorant  audacity,  to  pronounce  Homer  inferior  to 
Scude'ri  and  Chapelain.  Perrault  accepted  all  that  Bacon 
and  Pascal  had  affirmed  of  progress,  and  dwelt  much  more 
distinctly  and  emphatically  on  the  indefinite  perfectibility 
of  human  nature,  which  he  strikingly  contrasted  with  the 
immobility  of  the  merely  animal  nature.  He  refused  to 
admit  that  the  progressive  movement  of  civilisation  had  ever 
met  with  any  real  interruption.  To  the  objection  that  ages 
of  barbarism  had  been  seen  to  succeed  ages  of  culture,  he 
replied  by  the  comparison  of  the  arts  and  sciences  to  those 
rivers  which,  after  precipitating  themselves  suddenly  into  an 
abyss,  flow  for  a  while  under  ground,  but  emerge  again  into 
the  light  with  undiminished  fulness  and  force :  "  Cette  inter- 
ruption n'est  qu'apparente ;  on  peut  comparer  les  sciences  et 
les  arts  a  ces  fleuves  qui  viennent  a  rencontrer  un  gouffre  oii 
ils  s'abiment  tout-a-coup,  mais  qui,  apres  avoir  coule'  sous 
terre,  trouvent  enfin  une  ouverture  par  ou  on  les  voit  ressortir 
avec  la  meme  abondance  qu'ils  y  e'tait  entries."  He  added, 
that  humanity  has  had  its  different  ages,  each  of  which  has 
passed  through  a  natural  series  of  phases ;  and  further,  that 
"  the  human  race  must  be  considered  as  an  eternal  man,  so 
that  the  life  of  humanity  has  had,  like  the  life  of  a  man,  its 
infancy  and  youth,  is  at  present  in  its  maturity,  and  will 
know  no  decline." 

Fontenelle,  whose  life  of  one  hundred  years'  duration  con- 
nected the  great  age  of  French  literature  under  Louis  XIV. 
with  that  which  preceded  the  Revolution,  took  part  in  the 
discussion,  and  displayed  his  characteristic  ingenuity.  He 
granted  that  the  lapse  of  ages  makes  no  considerable  differ- 
ence on  the  constitution  and  faculties  of  human  nature,  yet 
ascribed  to  the  moderns  a  superiority  over  the  ancients,  inas- 
much as  the  generations  which  arrive  late  on  the  stage  of 
existence  must  inherit  the  intellectual  advantages  acquired 


FONTENELLE   AND   SAINT-PIERRE  215 

by  the  toils  of  the  generations  which  preceded  them.  Draw- 
ing a  sharp  distinction  between  the  sciences  and  the  arts,  he 
argued  that  the  former,  being  dependent  on  experience,  can 
only  be  slowly  matured,  while  the  latter,  being  dependent 
chiefly  on  liveliness  and  force  of  imagination,  may  attain 
easily  and  rapidly  a  very  high  perfection.  He  likewise  threw 
out  a  conception  which  has  a  certain  interest  from  having 
been  substantially  reproduced  by  Saint-Simon  and  Littre', 
both  believing  it  to  be  an  important  original  discovery.  The 
conception  as  stated  by  Fontenelle  is  that  the  life  of  each 
nation  has  ages  corresponding  to  the  ages  of  the  life  of  an 
individual.  In  infancy  individuals  and  nations  are  absorbed 
in  the  satisfaction  of  their  physical  wants ;  in  youth  they  are 
chiefly  occupied  with  poetry  and  art ;  and  in  manhood  with 
science  and  philosophy.  Like  Perrault,  he  supposes  that 
humanity  will  escape  decay  and  extinction.  "This  man, 
who  has  lived  from  the  beginning  of  the  world  to  the  present 
time,  will  have  no  old  age ;  he  will  be  always  as  capable  as 
ever  of  doing  the  things  for  which  he  was  fitted  in  youth, 
and  he  will  be  more  and  more  able  to  accomplish  those  which 
are  appropriate  to  his  manhood;  in  other  words,  and  to  drop 
allegory,  men  will  never  degenerate."1 

The  Abbe"  de  Saint-Pierre  (1658-1743)  was  another  con- 
necting link  between  the  seventeenth  and  the  eighteenth 
century.  He  was  a  still  more  enthusiastic  believer  in  human 
perfectibility  and  in  historical  progress  than  Fontenelle. 
His  ardent  faith  in  them  led  him  to  devise  a  multitude  of 
schemes  for  individual  and  social  improvement  which  seemed 
to  most  of  his  contemporaries  mere  dreams,  but  which  were 
rarely  altogether  dreams,  and  which  even  when  dreams  were  of 
the  kind  that  precede  and  cause  awakening.  He  was  a  precur- 
sor of  Turgot  and  Condorcet.  Those  who  wish  to  make  them- 
selves adequately  acquainted  with  the  views  of  this  remark- 
able man, —  "this  dreamer  who,"  as  Madame  Sand  says,  "saw 
more  clearly  than  all  his  contemporaries,"  —  may  be  referred 
to  the  works  of  Molinari  ('L'Abbe"  de  Saint-Pierre,  savie  et 
ses  oeuvres  ')  and  of  Goumy  ('Etude  sur  la  vie  et  les  ecrits 
de  l'Abbe'  de  Saint-Pierre').  The  so-called  "querelle  des, 
anciens  et  des  modernes  "  was  not  merely  the  foolish  and 

1  CEuvros  (ed.  1764),  torn.  iv.  p.  126.    See  also  pp.  110-126,  and  pp.  88-113. 


216  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FF.ANCE 

unprofitable  controversy  which  it  is  widely  believed  to  have 
been.  In  the  course  of  it  the  idea  of  progress  was  greatly 
developed,  and  men's  views  as  to  what  were  and  were  not 
legitimate  inferences  from  it  became  much  more  correct  and 
definite.1 

II 

The  only  work  published  in  France  during  the  seventeenth 
century  which  has  any  claim  to  a  separate  and  special  consid- 
eration from  us  is  the  'Discours  sur  l'Histoire  Universelle  ' 
of  Bishop  Bossuet.  It  appeared  in  1681,  having  been  Written 
for  the  use  of  the  Dauphin  of  France  to  whom  Bossuet  was 
preceptor.  Its  author  was  a  man  of  lofty  and  comprehensive 
mind,  of  rare  practical  clearness  of  judgment,  of  a  strong  and 
disinterested  character;  the  brightest  glory  of  the  Gallican 
Church;  the  most  skilful  expositor  and  champion  of  the 
Catholic  faith  in  modern  times ;  and  a  sacred  orator  of  over- 
powering eloquence.  No  one  represented  more  perfectly  what 
was  attractive  and  imposing  in  the  age  of  Louis  XIV., 
realised  more  fully  its  ideal  of  intellectual  power  and  gran- 
deur, or  embodied  better  the  qualities  it  admired  most.  But 
he  did  not  rise  above  his  age;  his  was  not  a  prophetic  or 
creative  mind ;  his  spirit  was  not  of  the  kind  which  antici- 
pates and  dominates  the  future.  He  was  an  admirable 
believer,  much  inferior  as  a  seeker  of  truth,  incapable  of 
doubting,  and  without  sympathy  for  independence  of  opinion. 
He  estimated  authority  too  highly,  and  liberty  too  lightly ; 
he  was  too  much  of  the  courtier  and  the  bishop,  too  little  of 
the  man  and  the  citizen.  He  felt  certain  of  whatever  the 
Church  taught;  he  considered  the  exercise  of  force  and 
severity  against  heretics  as  conduct  agreeable  to  God;  he 
was  an  advocate  of  absolutism,  royal  and  sacerdotal ;  he  had 
for  the  monarchy  an  idolatrous  veneration,  which,  although 
common  in  his  age,  was  unworthy  of  any  man,  and  most 
unworthy  of  such  a  man.2 

1  There  is  a  very  learned  '  Histoire  de  la  querelle  des  anoiens  et  des  modernes  ' 
(1856),  by  Hippolyte  Rigault,  and  good  chapters  relating  to  it  in  A.  Michiel's 
'  Histoire  des  idees  litteraires  en  France  au  xix"  siecle.'  There  is  much  ingenious 
theorising  on  the  main  question  of  the  controversy  in  the  work  of  M.  Veron,  '  Du 
progres  intellectuel  dans  l'humanite.' 

2  Bossuet  has,  of  course,  a  prominent  place  in  all  histories  of  French  literature. 
The  most  important  of  the  biographical  works  regarding  him  are  Bausset's  '  His- 


BOSSUET  217 

The  '  Discourse '  is,  unquestionably,  characterised  by 
great  genius.  The  simplest  sentences  place  before  us  the 
sublimest  pictures.  Every  word  is  what  it  ought  to  be; 
every  line  has  a  majestic  grace ;  and  the  effect  of  the  whole 
is  singularly  impressive.  But  the  genius  displayed  is  not 
scientific  or  philosophical  but  oratorical  genius.  The  pro- 
fundity, the  penetration,  the  originality  which  have  been 
ascribed  to  the  book,  are  not  in  it.  What  one  really  finds  in 
it  are  elevation  of  thought,  admirable  arrangement,  and  a 
magnificent  style. 

While  it  is  an  error  to  ascribe  great  originality  to  the 
conception  or  plan  formed  and  carried  out  by  Bossuet,  it  is 
equally  an  error  to  deny  to  it  any.  True,  centuries  before 
him  the  writers  of  Scripture  had  plainly  taught  that  God 
rules  over  nations,  raises  up  and  casts  down  kings  and 
peoples  according  to  His  sovereign  pleasure,  and  purposes  to 
establish  on  earth  a  kingdom  of  holiness;  but  the  clearest 
and  most  emphatic  affirmations  to  this  effect  fall  far  short  of 
an  attempt  to  exhibit  the  series  of  the  ages  and  the  world  of 
empires  as  a  system  of  law  and  order  regulated  and  pervaded 
by  the  wisdom  and  will  of  Deity.  All  that  the  prophets  and 
apostles  declared  as  to  Divine  Providence  could  be  assented 
to  by  those  who  had  no  proper  conception  of  a  universal  his- 
tory, or  of  the  place  and  significance  of  nations  in  a  scheme 
of  human  development,  just  as  the  first  chapter  of  Genesis 
could  be  accepted  ages  before  the  origination  of  geology. 
Bossuet's  historical  doctrine  is  much  more  closely  connected 
with  that  of  Augustine  than  with  the  simple  germs  of  his- 
torical doctrine  contained  in  Scripture;  but  it  is  no  mere 
restatement  even  of  Augustine's  theory.  The  central  con- 
ception of  the  Augustinian  historical  doctrine  —  the  conflict 
of  the  two  cities  —  holds  a  very  subordinate  place  in  Bossuet's 
work,  and  is  only  present  at  all  in  a  greatly  modified  char- 
acter.    The  harsh  predestinarian  dualism  so  fundamental  and 

toire  de  Bossuet,'  4  vols.,  1819;  Tabaraud's  '  Supplement  aux  histoires  de  Bossuet 
et  de  Fenelon,'  1822;  Floquet's  'Etudes  sur  la  vie  de  Bossuet,'  3  vols.;  and 
Re'aume's  'Histoire  de  J.  B.  Bossuet  et  de  ses  CEuvres,'  3  vols.,  1869-70.  His 
historical  philosophy  has  been  touched  on  by  Sisraondi,  Cousin,  Jouffroy,  Caro, 
and  others,  and  treated  of  at  greater  length  by  Buckle  (Hist,  of  Civ.  in  England, 
vol.  i.),  Laurent  (Phil,  de  l'Histoire),  Rougemont  (Les  Deux  Cite"s,  vol.  ii.),  and 
Mayr  (Geschichtsauffassung  der  Neuzeit) . 


218  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

so  conspicuous  in  the  'De  Civitate  Dei'  has  almost  disap- 
peared from  the  'Discours.'  Further,  while  the  historical 
constituents  of  the  former  work  are  inextricably  commingled 
with  apologetic,  polemic,  mj'thological,  theological,  and 
moral  disquisitions,  in  the  latter  the  survey  of  history  stands 
out  with  comparative  purity  and  clearness.  The  history  is 
viewed  in  a  religious  light,  but  in  that  light  it  is  presented 
as  a  rationally  connected  and  orderly  developed  whole.  There 
is  nothing  in  Augustine's  work  which  corresponds  to  the 
Third  Part  of  Bossuet's,  which  is,  however,  to  the  historical 
philosopher  by  far  its  most  interesting  and  valuable  portion. 

Bossuet  was  not  endowed  with  the  originality  which  makes 
discoveries  and  produces  new  views,  but  only  with  such 
originality  as  apprehends  with  perfect  clearness  the  highest 
thoughts  in  general  circulation,  separates  them  with  extraor- 
dinary judgment  from  antiquated  and  inferior  notions,  and 
expresses  them  with  surpassing  skill.  He  had  not  the 
originality  which  would  have  placed  him  in  advance  of  his 
age,  and  at  a  distance  from  it,  but  simply  that  which  placed 
him  in  the  front  rank  of  the  men  of  his  age. 

The  primary  purpose  of  his  work  was,  he  informs  us,  to 
be  to  the  histories  of  particular  peoples  and  epochs  what  a 
general  map  is  to  maps  of  particular  countries ;  its  aim  was 
to  show  how  nation  is  bound  to  nation,  generation  to  gen- 
eration. It  only,  however,  accomplishes  this  purpose  very 
imperfectly,  since  scarcely  any  relations  are  exhibited  in  it 
except  theological  ones.  It  consists  of  three  parts,  —  a 
chronological  distribution  of  the  events  of  history  from  the 
creation  of  the  world  to  the  reign  of  Charlemagne,  a  sketch 
of  the  course  of  true  religion,  and  a  survey  of  the  rise  and 
fall  of  empires.  This  division  has  been  criticised  as  inar- 
tistic, and  involving  repetitions,  seeing  that  the  sacred  and 
secular  events  treated  of  together  in  the  first  part  are  in  the 
two  following  parts  again  dealt  with  separately.  But  it  has 
to  be  remembered,  that  although  Bossuet  was  a  great  artist, 
his  chief  design  in  writing  the  'Discourse  on  Universal  His- 
tory '  was  not  to  produce  a  work  of  art,  any  more  than  of 
science  or  philosophy,  but  to  attain  a  practical  and  educa- 
tional end.  His  aim  was  to  exhibit  history  in  such  a  light  as 
would  convey  to  his  pupil  and  his  readers  the  religious  and 


BOSSUET  219 

political  impressions  which  he  believed  history  to  be  espe- 
cially meant  to  impart.  His  work  could  not  be  better 
planned  with  a  view  to  the  attainment  of  his  end. 

In  the  First  Part  history  is  divided  into  twelve  epochs. 
Of  these,  the  first  is  said  to  have  begun  with  the  creation  of 
Adam,  B.C.  4004;  the  second  with  the  flood  of  Noah,  B.C. 
2348;  the  third  with  the  calling  of  Abraham,  B.C.  1921;  the 
fourth  with  the  giving  of  the  law  to  Moses,  B.C.  1491;  the 
fifth  with  the  capture  of  Troy,  B.C.  1124;  the  sixth  with 
the  dedication  of  Solomon's  temple,  B.C.  1004;  the  seventh 
with  the  foundation  of  Rome,  B.C.  784;  the  eighth  with  the 
restoration  of  the  Jews  by  the  edict  of  Cyrus,  B.C.  536;  the 
ninth  with  the  taking  of  Carthage  by  Scipio,  B.C.  200; 
the  tenth  with  the  birth  of  Christ;  the  eleventh  with  Con- 
stantine's  public  adoption  of  Christianity  (A.D.  312);  and 
the  twelfth  with  the  coronation  by  Pope  Leo  of  Charlemagne 
as  Emperor  of  the  Romans,  a.d.  800.  These  twelve  periods 
are  regarded  as  reducible  to  seven  ages,  which  are  said  to  have 
begun  respectively  with  Adam,  Noah,  Abraham,  Moses, 
Solomon,  Cyrus,  and  Christ.  Further,  both  epochs  and  ages 
are  regarded  as  included  in  three  great  periods:  namely, 
that  of  the  law  of  nature,  which  was  prior  to  Moses ;  that  of 
the  written  law,  which  extended  from  Moses  to  Christ;  and 
that  of  grace.  When  it  is  observed  that  seven  out  of  the 
twelve  epochs,  all  the  ages  and  all  the  periods,  are  dated 
according  to  Biblical  indications  and  with  reference  to  the 
fortunes  of  the  people  of  Israel,  it  will  be  understood  that 
the  'Discourse  '  of  Bossuet  is  very  far  from  answering  fully 
to  its  title,  or  from  really  dealing  with  universal  history. 

The  First  Part  of  Bossuet's  treatise  is  thus  to  a  large 
extent  a  summary  of  Biblical  history  as  recorded  in  the 
Biblical  books.  As  such  it  is  truly  admirable,  and  probably 
even  to  this  day  unsurpassed.  It  is  marvellous  how  much 
Bossuet  manages  to  say  in  a  few  words,  and  how  apt,  pic- 
turesque, and  impressive  these  are.  The  order  is  perfect; 
every  statement  is  in  its  place ;  every  fact  is  so  set  as  to  be 
seen  in  the  light  of  its  relationships.  There  is  no  over- 
crowding of  the  narrative  with  details,  or  compressing  together 
of  things  different  in  nature  and  unequal  in  significance. 


220  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Masterly   ease,    thorough   naturalness,    just   proportions,    a 
beautiful  harmony  are  everywhere  apparent. 

On  the  other  hand,  Bossuet  accepted  the  Biblical  books  as 
historical  authorities  in  an  uncritical  manner.  He  did  not 
suppose  that  any  inquiry  into  the  sources  and  character  of 
the  Biblical  histories  was  necessary,  or  even  permissible. 
He  supposed  that  their  authors  wrote  with  infallible  knowl- 
edge, and  that  there  could  be  no  error  in  their  statements. 
In  this  respect  he  fully  shared  the  general  belief  of  his  age, 
which  is  still  the  belief  of  the  Catholic  Church,  and  a  preva- 
lent belief  in  most  Protestant  Churches.  His  uncritical 
procedure  was  therefore  a  natural  and  venial  fault.  Still  it 
was  a  fault;  and  it  has  to  be  remembered  in  this  connection, 
that  Bossuet  took  a  prominent  and  deplorable  part  in  the 
attempt  to  suppress  a  work  far  superior  in  scientific  merit 
to  anything  which  he  was  himself  capable  of  producing — ■ 
namely,  the  first  history  of  the  Old  Testament  as  a  literary 
product,  the  '  Histoire  Critique  du  Vieux  Testament '  (1678) 
of  Richard  Simon.  Bossuet  had  not  that  complete  intellec- 
tual truthfulness  which  is  the  first  and  main  characteristic 
of  the  scientific  spirit,  and  therefore  he  could  not  bear  with- 
out pain  and  aversion  the  light  of  scientific  criticism. 

The  chronology  of  his  historical  sketch  has  been  much 
praised  by  some  writers.  In  reality,  it  was  simply  taken, 
without  acknowledgment,  from  Usher. 

The  Second  Part  of  the  'Discourse  '  delineates  the  course  of 
religion  —  la  suite  de  la  religion.  Religion  is  regarded  as  con- 
fined to  Jews  and  Christians.  In  heathendom  nothing  is  seen 
save  idolatry.  And  idolatry  is  viewed  as  utter  extravagance, 
the  strength  of  which  lies  in  what  its  foolishness  attests,  the 
weakness  of  reason.  To  this  cause,  aided  by  sense,  interest, 
ignorance,  a  false  reverence  for  antiquity,  policy,  philosophy, 
and  heresy,  the  extent  of  its  sway  and  the  difficulty  of  dislodg- 
ing it,  are  traced.  The  history  of  religion  is  for  Bossuet,  as  for 
Augustine,  the  history  of  the  people  of  God,  or  of  the  oivitas 
Dei;  but  he  does  not,  like  Augustine,  identify  the  people  of 
God  with  a  certain  number  of  persons  specially  predestinated 
to  eternal  life.  He  understands  the  civitas  Dei  to  be  a  really 
historical  community  and  kingdom,  the  people  of  Israel  under 
the  old  dispensation  and  the  Christian  Church  under  the  new. 


BOSSUET  221 

At  the  same  time,  he  does  not  contradict,  but,  on  the  contrary, 
he  accepts  the  Pauline  and  Augustinian  view  of  an  Israel 
within  Israel,  of  a  narrower  and  a  wider  election. 

In  the  Second  Part  of  his  work,  then,  Bossuet  seeks  to 
describe  "  the  different  states  of  the  people  of  God  under  the 
law  of  nature  and  under  the  patriarchs;  under  Moses  and 
under  the  written  law ;  under  David  and  under  the  prophets ; 
during  the  time  between  the  return  from  the  captivity  and 
Jesus  Christ;  and  finally,  under  Jesus  Christ  Himself  — 
that  is  to  say,  under  the  law  of  grace  and  under  the  Gospel ; 
in  the  ages  which  looked  forward  to  Messiah  and  in  those  to 
which  he  has  appeared;  in  those  in  which  the  worship  of 
God  is  confined  to  a  single  people  and  in  those  in  which,  as 
foretold  in  the  ancient  prophecies,  it  has  been  diffused  over 
the  whole  earth;  in  those,  in  fine,  when  men,  still  weak  and 
rude,  require  to  be  sustained  by  temporal  rewards  and  punish- 
ments, and  in  those  when  the  faithful,  more  fully  instructed, 
must  live  only  by  faith,  attached  to  the  blessings  of  eternity, 
and  suffering,  in  the  hope  of  obtaining  them,  all  the  evils 
which  can  exercise  their  patience."  Religion  is,  according 
to  Bossuet,  not  unprogressive,  but  passes  through  an  orderly 
suggestion  of  states,  and  from  feebleness  to  strength,  from 
infancy  to  maturity.  The  reality  of  progress  is  clearly  and 
practically  recognised  by  him  throughout  his  whole  work,  not 
excepting  even  the  portion  of  it  devoted  to  tracing  the  course 
of  religion.  He  represents  religion,  however,  as  having  been 
always  uniform,  or  rather  always  the  same,  the  same  God 
having  been  always  accepted  as  the  Author,  and  the  same 
Christ  as  the  Saviour,  of  the  human  race.  The  history  of  the 
Jewish  people,  and  the  history  of  the  Christian  Church,  are 
viewed  as  one  through  their  union  in  Jesus  Christ,  the 
former  finding  in  Him  its  consummation  and  the  latter  its 
commencement;  so  that,  either  as  expected  or  as  possessed, 
He  has  been  in  all  ages  the  hope  and  the  consolation  of  His 
children.  Bossuet's  delineation  of  the  course  of  religion  is, 
in  fact,  mainly  an  exposition  of  Biblical  history  and  a  defence 
and  application  of  Biblical  prophecy,  which  is  regarded  as 
the  key  to  the  interpretation  of  history.  Its  general  aim  is 
to  prove  that  religion  is  of  all  things  the  oldest,  the  least 
changeable,   the  noblest,    and  that  the   Church  over  which 


222  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

Innocent  XI.  presided  was  the  heir  of  all  the  ages,  the 
guardian  and  possessor  of  all  spiritual  truth ;  in  other  words, 
it  is  apologetic,  and  not  philosophical. 

So  far  as  the  second  division  of  Bossuet's  treatise  is  merely 
a  plea  for  prophecy  and  miracle,  for  the  Bible  or  Christianity 
or  the  Church,  I  do  not  require  to  pass  any  judgment  upon 
it.  Its  main  thesis,  however,  is  historical;  and  I  must 
express  my  conviction  that  Bossuet  has  failed  to  establish 
it,  and  that  history  is  not  favourable  to  it.  Religion  is 
found,  when  comprehensively  and  impartially  studied,  to 
have  been  as  changeable  as  any  other  historical  phenomenon. 
It  has  varied  from  age  to  age,  from  land  to  land,  just  as 
industry,  art,  and  philosophy  have  done.  It  has  a  certain 
unity  amidst  all  its  changes  as  they  have,  but  not  the  crude 
external  unity  which  Bossuet  fancied  it  to  possess.  The 
virtual  identification  of  religion  with  Jewish  and  Christian 
monotheism  rests  on  a  narrow  and  unworthy  conception  of 
religion,  so  far  excusable  in  Bossuet's  day,  yet  even  then 
seen  to  be  false  by  minds  otherwise  inferior  to  his  own.  It 
is  a  mere  illusion  to  regard  the  Church  as  having  been  more 
stable  or  less  continuously  in  motion  than  the  State.  The 
Roman  Catholic  Church  is  not  an  institution  of  any  extraor- 
dinary age,  and  was  already  in  decay  when  Bossuet  wrote. 
Its  claim  to  be  in  exclusive  possession  of  any  truth  is  inca- 
pable of  historical  proof. 

The  Third  Part  of  Bossuet's  'Discourse  '  treats  of  the  rise 
and  fall  of  empires  —  la  suite  des  empires.  In  it,  as  in  the 
entire  work,  the  central  thought  is  that  a  Divine  hand  trains 
and  guides  collective  humanity  for  the  religion  of  Christ, 
which  is  incorporated  in  the  Church ;  and  that  all  historical 
changes  may  be  co-ordinated  with  reference  to  a  single  end, 
the  good  of  the  Church.  "  God  has  made  use  of  the  Assyrians 
and  Babylonians  to  chastise  His  people ;  of  the  Persians  to 
restore  it ;  of  Alexander  and  his  immediate  successors  to  pro- 
tect it ;  of  Antiochus  the  Great  and  his  successors  to  exercise 
it;  and  of  the  Romans  to  maintain  its  liberty  against  the 
kings  of  Syria  bent  only  on  destroying  it,  to  avenge  its 
rejection  and  crucifixion  of  Christ,  and  to  secure  the  spread 
and  triumph  of  the  Christian  faith."  The  world  of  nations  is 
thus  like  the  world  of  nature,  a  connected  and  orderly  system 


BOSSTJBT  223 

ruled  by  the  will  and  revealing  the  wisdom  of  the  Author  of 
the  universe. 

But,  further,  in  this  portion  of  his  treatise,  Bossuet  indi- 
cates the  special  secondary  causes  which  under  the  hand  of 
Providence  determined  the  revolutions  of  Scythia,  Ethiopia, 
Egypt,  Assyria,  Media,  Persia,  Greece,  and  Rome.  He 
represents  the  various  nations  as  having  had  qualities 
assigned  to  them  suitable  to  the  missions  which  they  were 
to  fulfil.  "  And  as  in  all  affairs  there  is  that  which  prepares 
them,  which  determines  the  undertaking  of  them,  and  which 
causes  them  to  succeed,  the  true  science  of  history  is  to 
observe  in  each  period  of  time  those  secret  dispositions  which 
have  prepared  great  changes,  and  the  important  conjunctures 
which  have  brought  them  to  pass."  It  is  not  enough  to  look 
at  remarkable  events  and  decisive  revolutions  merely  as  they 
outwardly  appear ;  it  is  necessary  to  penetrate  to  the  inclina- 
tions, the  manners,  the  characters  of  the  peoples  and  persons 
that  have  effected  them.  There  is  no  such  thing  as  chance 
in  history,  and  fortune  is  a  word  devoid  of  meaning.  God 
alone  rules,  but  He  rules  through  second  causes,  through  men 
and  nations  being  what  they  are,  and  related  as  they  are, 
unless  in  certain  exceptional  cases  where  He  wills  that  His 
own  hand  should  be  seen  in  direct  intervention,  in  immediate 
action.  But  the  second  causes  of  historical  events  are  only 
superficially  investigated  by  Bossuet.  He  is  too  content  to 
explain  conquests  as  brought  about  by  God  inspiring  certain 
men  and  their  followers  with  invincible  courage,  and  causes 
terror  to  march  before  them;  useful  laws  by  His  giving  to 
legislators  the  spirit  of  wisdom  and  foresight;  peace  and 
order  by  His  restraint  of  human  passions;  and  strife  and 
revolution  by  His  letting  these  passions  loose.  He  con- 
stantly spares  himself  the  labour  of  explaining  historical 
changes  by  historical  agencies,  and  refers  them  instead  to 
those  eternal  counsels  of  God  with  which  he  so  confidently 
felt  himself  to  be  thoroughly  acquainted. 

There  can  be  no  difference  of  opinion  as  to  the  literary 
genius  and  artistic  skill  displayed  by  Bossuet  in  delineating 
the  features  and  tracing  the  succession  of  the  great  empires 
of  the  ancient  world.  The  panorama  exhibited  is  magnifi- 
cent; the  portraits  drawn  of  the  several  nations  are  marvels 


224  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   PRANCE 

of  beauty  and  power.  It  is  difficult  to  suppose  that  this 
portion  of  Bossuet's  work  will  ever  be  deprived  of  its  value 
or  attractiveness  by  the  increase  of  historical  knowledge.  As 
regards  it  he  cannot,  I  think,  be  said  to  have  had  any  prede- 
cessor, and  he  has  as  yet,  perhaps,  had  no  successful  rival. 
Its  chief  fault  hardly  affects  its  character  as  a  work  of  art, 
and  if  rather  inconsistent  with  its  author's  general  historical 
theory,  is  on  that  account  all  the  more  creditable  to  his  human 
sympathies.  The  defect  to  which  I  refer  is  that  his  portraits 
of  the  heathen  nations  are  more  or  less  nattering,  the  nobler 
traits  of  each  people  being  made  prominent,  while  their  baser 
features  are  left  indistinct  or  unindicated. 

On  whatever  subject  Bossuet  touches  in  tracing  the  course 
of  empires,  the  singular  appropriateness  of  his  language 
bears  witness  to  his  careful  study  of  the  matter  dealt  with. 
Says  Nisard,  "  Conde"  could  not  have  better  characterised  the 
impetuous  valour  of  the  Persians,  or  the  masterly  tactics  of 
the  Greeks,  or  the  rigidity  of  the  Macedonian  phalanx,  or  the 
shock  of  the  Roman  legion ;  he  could  not  have  painted  better 
his  own  models,  Alexander,  Hannibal,  Scipio,  and  Caesar. 
Colbert  could  not  have  appreciated  in  terms  more  appropriate 
and  exact,  or  viewed  from  a  higher  point  of  vantage  the  wise 
administration  of  the  Egyptians,  the  practical  grandeur  of 
their  arts,  the  economy  of  their  public  works.  A  statesman 
like  Richelieu  could  not  have  penetrated  more  keenly  into 
the  profound  policy  of  the  Roman  senate.  Machiavelli  could 
not  have  seen  more  clearly  into  the  rivalries  of  Greece,  even 
aided  by  the  spectacle  which  Italy,  agitated  by  similar 
rivalries,  presented  to  him.  Neither  Cujas  nor  Pothier  could 
have  shown  better  the  import  of  the  Roman  laws.  For  the 
understanding  of  general  relations  and  for  technical  propriety 
of  expression,  Bossuet  is  unequalled  in  our  language.  This 
great  writer  is  the  only  one  whom  I  know,  in  whom  one  can 
never  detect,  whatever  be  the  matter  of  which  he  treats, 
either  any  indecision  or  effort."1 

Bossuet  had  a  profound  admiration  for  the  character  and 
genius  of  the  Roman  people.  His  own  nature  was  of  a  grandly 
Roman  type,  and  he  had  entered  thoroughly  into  the  spirit  of 
Roman  institutions  and  of  the  great  Roman  writers.     Hence 

1  Hist,  de  la  literature  fran<;aise,  t.  iv.  pp.  266,  267  (ed.  1850). 


BOSSUET  225 

the  two  chapters  on  Rome  with  which  his  work  closes  are 
not  only  of  remarkable  merit  for  ease  and  power  of  descrip- 
tion, but  for  judicious  appreciation  of  the  causes  of  Roman 
grandeur  and  decline.  They  show  that  if  he  had  not  had 
other  aims  in  his  treatise,  he  might  have  done  much  for  the 
philosophy  of  history ;  and  they  make  us  regret  that  he  did 
not,  as  he  purposed  to  do,  compose  a  '  Discours '  on  the 
development  of  France  and  the  successes  and  decline  of 
Mohammedanism. 

As  we  have  seen,  Bossuet  regards  all  history  from  the 
religious  point  of  view.  His  entire  teaching  concerning  it  is 
based  on  the  thought  of  a  Divine  plan  determining  and  per- 
vading it ;  on  the  belief  that  God  rules  the  whole  course  of 
human  things  for  the  fulfilment  of  His  own  purposes.  This 
thought  in  itself,  or  when  not  unwarrantably  narrowed  and 
specialised,  is  just  the  idea  of  Divine  Providence,  and  it  will 
be  rejected  only  by  those  who  refuse  to  recognise  Divine 
agency  in  the  universe ;  this  belief  is  just  the  conviction 
that  the  Lord  reigneth,  and  that  the  destiny  of  man  is  being 
accomplished  under  the  guidance  of  the  Eternal,  and  it  will 
be  shared  by  all  who  acknowledge  a  purpose  and  plan  in  the 
structure  of  the  evolution  of  the  world.  Those  who  see  evi- 
dences of  Supreme  "Will  and  wisdom  in  physical  nature  will 
not  fail  to  see  its  traces  also  in  the  development  of  humanity. 
The  human  race  has  had  a  history.  Generations  after  genera- 
tions have  come  and  gone  like  the  leaves  of  the  forest ;  but 
that  history  has  proceeded  onwards  without  break,  without 
stoppage,  in  obedience  to  laws  the  knowledge  of  which  we 
are  only  yet  groping  after.  There  has  been  progress,  order? 
plan,  from  the  first  day  of  man's  creation  down  to  the  present 
hour,  yet  man  himself  has  been  ignorant  of  it,  and  heedless 
of  it.  The  very  conception  is  a  modern  one,  and  is  vague, 
inadequate,  and  in  manifold  ways  positively  erroneous,  even 
in  the  highest  minds  of  our  time.  Few  have  had  the  slightest 
glimpse  of  the  order  which  yet  embraced  their  every  action ; 
fewer  still  have  sought  to  conform  to  it.  From  first  to  last, 
from  the  beginning  of  human  history  until  now,  the  immense 
majority  of  our  race  have  set  before  them  ends  of  their  own, 
narrow  and  mean  schemes  merely  for  personal  good;  and  yet, 
although  it  has  been  so,  and  in  the  midst  of  confusion,  tumult, 


226  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

and  war,  the  order,  progress,  plan,  referred  to,  has  been  slowly 
and  silently  but  surely  built  up.  The  men  who  have  accom- 
plished it  have  not  meant  to  do  so ;  nay,  they  have  been  as 
ignorant  of  the  laws  of  the  vast  scheme  which  they  were 
realising  as  the  bees  are  of  the  mathematical  principles  on 
which  they  construct  the  cells  of  their  honeycombs ;  their 
reason  has  been  as  blind  as  any  brute's  instinct.  If,  when  we 
look  up  at  the  heavens  and  ponder  on  what  science  tells  us 
of  the  systems  of  worlds  above  us,  all  proceeding  in  their 
courses  with  perfect  regularity,  we  feel  humbled  in  adoration 
before  a  present  reigning  God,  we  shall  not  be  less  impressed 
with  a  sense  of  the  Divine  agency  when  we  observe  how 
order  and  the  common  good  are  brought  out  of  the  confusion 
and  conflict  of  millions  of  human  wills  which  seek  merely 
their  own  pleasure  and  interest.  The  denial  of  the  Divine 
presence  and  purpose  in  the  movements  of  human  society  is 
an  inference  from  atheism,  not  an  induction  of  science,  and 
least  of  all  a  special  result  of  the  science  of  history.  On  the 
contrary,  we  may  rather  say  with  Niebuhr,  that  "  history  is, 
of  all  kinds  of  knowledge,  the  one  which  tends  most  decidedly 
to  produce  belief  in  Providence." 

But  it  does  not  follow  that  because  an  idea  is  true  there  can 
be  no  application  of  it  which  is  illegitimate.  And  to  lay  this 
idea  of  a  Divine  Providence,  or  any  other  theological  idea,  as 
the  foundation  of  a  philosophy  of  history,  is  an  illegitimate 
application  of  it.  It  is  to  reverse  the  true  relation  of  science 
and  theology.  Religious  truths  are  inferences  from  scientific 
laws,  not  these  laws  themselves,  nor  the  rationale  of  them. 
It  is  only  where  science  ends  that  religious  philosophy  begins. 
The  results  of  science  serve  as  data  to  religious  philosophy. 
Science  shows  that  certain  laws  and  relations  hold  among 
phenomena,  and  whether  the  phenomena  be  inorganic,  organic, 
animate,  mental,  moral,  or  social,  this  is  all  which  science 
does ;  it  rests  in  the  laws,  the  ultimate  general  relations  of 
phenomena,  and  seeks  neither  by  intuition  nor  any  form  of 
inference  to  transcend  them.  It  leaves  to  religious  philoso- 
phy to  go  farther  and  higher  if  it  can,  to  avail  itself  of  the 
broadest  and  latest  scientific  generalisations,  and  to  consecrate 
them,  to  invest  them  with  a  halo  of  celestial  glory,  by  showing 
that  the  laws  and  relations  discovered  by  science — the  adjust- 


BOSSDET  227 

ments  and  harmonies  which  prevail  throughout  creation  — 
are  expressions  of  the  thoughts  of  an  Infinite  Intelligence  into 
communion  with  which  it  is  permitted  us  in  some  feeble 
degree  to  enter  —  are  revelations  of  the  character  of  the 
Creator.  These  truths  Bossuet  has  overlooked  or  disbelieved. 
He  accordingly  makes  what  is  an  inference  from  the  philoso- 
phy of  history  its  fundamental  premiss.  He  explains  by  the 
doctrine  of  a  Providence  the  very  conditions  from  which  we 
conclude  the  existence  of  a  Providence.  He  does  not  make 
an  independent  application  of  induction  to  the  facts  of  his- 
tory, but  he  attempts  to  account  for  these  facts  by  an  article 
of  his  theological  creed.  This  is  an  obviously  unscientific 
process.  It  is  to  make  what  ought  to  be  the  apex  of  an 
edifice  its  basis.  It  is  to  try  to  build  by  beginning  at  the  top. 
And  this  radical  error  is  the  radical  and  generative  principle 
of  Bossuet's  system. 

Besides,  many  who  believe  in  Providence  will  refuse  to  ac- 
cept Bossuet's  representation  of  it.  His  whole  mode  of  con- 
ceiving of  the  Divine  Being  and  government,  will  seem  to 
them  crudely  and  irreverently  anthropomorphic.  He  does 
not,  indeed,  ascribe  to  God  bodily  parts,  but  he  ascribes  to 
Him  human  passions,  petty  designs,  and  questionable  motives. 
Worse  than  his  idolising  of  Louis  XIV.  as  a  kind  of  god  on 
earth,  is  his  imagining  God  to  be  a  kind  of  Louis  XIV.  in 
heaven.  If  it  be  said  that  he  only  spoke  as  the  Hebrew 
prophets  had  taught  him,  the  answer  will  be  that  he  had  no 
right  to  employ  their  figurative  and  metaphorical  language  to 
express  essential  reality ;  no  right  to  confound  the  language 
of  religious  emotion  with  that  of  philosophical  thought.  The 
idea  of  Providence  is  as  central  in  the  historical  theory  of 
Vico  as  it  is  in  that  of  Bossuet,  but  it  is  wholly  different  in 
the  two  theories,  and  that  simply  because  Vico's  idea  of  God 
was  profound  and  reverent,  Bossuet's  comparatively  shallow 
and  irreverent. 

Further,  Bossuet  not  only  descends  from  Providence  to 
history  instead  of  rising  from  history  to  Providence,  but  he 
attributes  to  Providence  a  single  and  very  definite  design  or 
thought.  He  represents  the  sole  aim  of  Providence  in  history 
to  be  the  establishment  of  the  kingdom  of  Christ,  and  the 
kingdom  of    Christ  he  identifies  with  the   Roman   Catholic 


228  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Church.  Now,  even  if  he  had  not  thus  taken  a  narrow  and 
erroneous  view  of  the  Christian  religion  —  even  if  he  had  not 
thus  confounded  it  with  Romanism — his  reading  of  the  riddle 
of  Providence  might  be  seriously  questioned.  There  is  no 
room,  indeed,  for  reasonable  doubt  that  Egypt,  Assyria,  Persia, 
Greece,  and  Rome,  as  well  as  Judea,  contributed  to  prepare 
the  way  for  Christ,  for  the  reception  and  spread  of  the  Gos- 
pel, for  the  formation  and  diffusion  of  a  Christian  civilisation. 
This  is  a  fact  which  not  only  admits  of  convincing  historical 
proof,  but  which  has  been  admirably  proved  in  many  recent 
works :  for  instance,  in  the  introductions  to  the  Church  His- 
tories of  Neander,  Schaff,  and  Pressense",  and  Dollinger's 
'  Court  of  the  Gentiles.'  But  Bossuet,  like  so  many  before 
and  since,  was  not  content  to  abide  within  the  safe  limits  of 
a  statement  of  facts ;  or  rather,  while  believing  that  he  was 
doing  so,  he  maintained  instead,  as  identical  with  such  a 
statement,  an  assertion  which  is  in  reality  very  different,  far 
broader,  and  far  more  hazardous,  —  the  assertion  that  the 
world  exists  only  for  one  true  and  perfect  religion,  that  the 
rise  and  spread  of  that  religion  is  the  single  end  or  ultimate 
final  cause  of  all  history,  the  sole  ground  for  the  existence  of 
any  age  or  nation.  It  may  be  so,  but  what  is  our  evidence  for 
it?  Can  we  really  penetrate  so  far  into  the  depths  of  the 
Divine  counsels  as  to  know  the  full  purpose  of  God  in  the 
lives  of  all  nations,  in  the  events  of  all  time  ?  That  Egypt, 
Assyria,  Persia,  Greece,  and  Rome  were  all  meant  to  prepare 
the  way  for  Christianity  we  may  well  maintain,  for  history 
proves  that  they  did  so ;  but  that  these  nations,  and  still  more 
that  nations  like  India  and  China,  so  ancient,  so  populous,  so 
remarkable  and  peculiar  in  civilisation,  and  on  which  the 
beams  of  the  Gospel  shine  so  feebly  even  at  the  present  hour, 
have  existed  solely  or  mainly  for  Christianity,  is  an  entirely 
different  proposition,  and  one  which  we  may  reasonably  ques- 
tion. And  while  it  may  be  disputed  whether  the  final  end  of 
Providence  is  what  even  in  this  general  form  it  is  said  to  be, 
when  the  general  form  is  withdrawn  for  a  special,  and  the 
Roman  Catholic  Church  is  regarded  as  equivalent  to  the 
Christian  religion,  room  even  for  doubt  ceases,  and  the  ques- 
tionable gives  place  to  the  certainly  false.  Whether  history 
can  or  cannot  prove  that  humanity  exists  for  Christianity  may 


BOSSUET  229 

be  a  theme  for  controversy ;  but  nothing  in  history  is  surer 
than  that  it  does  not  exist  for  the  Church.  For  some  centuries 
now  the  whole  course  of  history  has  been  proving  that  conclu- 
sively to  all  who  are  willing  to  be  taught  by  it.  The  successive 
stages  of  progress  accomplished  during  these  centuries  have 
been  marked  by  the  successive  and  growing  deliverance  of  the 
State,  of  art,  of  literature  and  science,  of  the  individual  reason 
and  conscience, and  the  various  social  activities,  from  the  grasp 
and  authority  of  the  Church.  Into  her  bosom  they  will  never 
more  return.  She  will  never  more,  like  the  Church  of  the 
middle  ages,  have  their  power  to  yield.  It  has  cost  humanity 
too  much  to  separate  each  one  of  them  from  her  sway,  and 
humanity  has  gained  too  much  by  the  separation  for  it  to 
allow  of  anything  of  the  kind.  The  Church  has  lost  domin- 
ion over  all  these  things  for  ever,  and  her  loss  has  been  the 
gain  of  the  world  and  the  gain  of  religion. 

The  conception  entertained  by  Bossuet  of  the  final  cause  of 
history  could  not  fail  to  render  him  unjust  towards  many 
nations,  could  not  fail  to  make  him  overlook  their  significance 
in  the  world.  This  injustice  has  been  exposed  by  Sismondi, 
Cousin,  Buckle,  and  others,  who  have  seen  only  vaguely  the 
root-principles  of  it.  They  have  remarked  that  he  says  little 
of  Persia,  less  of  Egypt,  and  nothing  of  India  and  China,  and 
has  taken  no  account  of  art,  science,  and  industry  as  elements 
of  social  life,  which  is  quite  enough  to  show  that  he  was  far 
from  realising  the  comprehensiveness  and  wealth  of  history. 
If  he  did  not  see  in  it  only  religion,  religion  was  certainly  the 
one  element  of  which  he  had  a  clear  enough  apprehension 
to  be  able  to  trace  the  development.  Nor  could  he  do  that 
otherwise  than  most  imperfectly.  For,  first,  the  very  notion 
of  development  in  theology  was  then  scarcely  entertained  by 
Protestant,  and  altogether  alien  to  Catholic  divines.  And 
next,  he  had  not,  and  no  man  in  his  time  had,  sympathy 
enough  with  the  heathen  religions  of  the  world  to  discern 
the  truths  which  were  in  them,  their  affinities  to  the  human 
spirit,  and  their  relations  to  the  Christian  faith.  Classical 
mythology  was  then  only  a  mass  of  discordant  and  inde- 
cent absurdities ;  the  spiritual  life  of  the  Eastern  world  was 
shrouded  in  darkness;  and  the  history  of  Christianity  itself 
had  not  yet  been  written  with  much  of  critical  discrimination, 


230  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IX   PRANCE 

or  philosophic  insight,  or  that  imaginative  sympathy  which 
reanimates  and  re-embodies  the  past.  It  was  thus  inevitable 
that  Bossuet's  attempt  to  sketch  the  history  even  of  religion 
should  be  defective;  and  it  is  simplest  justice  to  him  to  re- 
member that  many  things  in  that  history,  familiar  now  even  to 
the  unlearned,  were  then  undreamt  of  even  by  scholars. 

It  is  also  to  be  remembered  that  Bossuet  in  attending  chiefly 
to  the  religious  element  in  history,  and  taking  little  account  of 
other  elements,  was  exercising  a  right  of  choice  to  which  he  was 
entitled.  Some  of  his  critics  have  judged  his  '  Discours '  as  if 
he  had  undertaken  to  treat  history  only  as  a  philosopher,  as  if 
he  had  engaged  to  write  a  systematic  treatise  on  the  science  of 
history.  In  that  case  we  should  have  been  warranted  to  de- 
mand that  every  historical  element  should  be  enumerated  and 
estimated  at  its  proper  value.  But  Bossuet  made  no  such  pro- 
fession, entered  into  no  such  engagement.  He  sought  primarily 
not  the  advancement  of  science,  but  practical  utility,  Christian 
edification ;  and  in  order  to  secure  this,  it  was  as  integral  a  part 
of  his  plan  to  show  the  perpetuity  and  enforce  the  claims  of 
Christianity  as  to  trace  the  rise  and  fall  of  empires.  It  is  con- 
sequently unfair  to  judge  him  as  if  he  had  professed  to  be  only 
either  an  historical  philosopher  or  a  philosophical  historian. 

When  speaking  of  justice  in  connection  with  the  criticism  of 
Bossuet's  '  Discourse,'  it  is  impossible  for  me  to  refrain  from 
saying  that  Mr.  Buckle's  criticism  of  it  appears  to  me  indefen- 
sible. It  is  true  that  Bossuet  has  sacrificed  other  nations  to  the 
Jews ;  but  serious  as  that  error  is,  it  is  not  more  fatal  to  a  truth- 
ful estimate  of  universal  history,  does  not  show  greater  inability 
to  rise  to  a  philosophical  view  of  history,  than  to  see  in  them 
only,  as  Mr.  Buckle  does,  "  an  obstinate  and  ignorant  race, 
which  owed  to  other  peoples  any  scanty  knowledge  they  ever 
attained."  Bossuet's  error  lay  not  so  much  in  exaggerating 
the  importance  of  the  Jewish  nation  in  history,  as  in  overlook- 
ing the  importance  of  other  nations.  Even  if,  rejecting  mira- 
cle and  special  revelation,  we  consent  to  regard  everything 
in  its  history,  legislation,  literature,  and  religion  as  merely  nat- 
ural, the  Jewish  nation  will  still  appear  to  the  intelligent  and 
unbiassed  student  as  the  most  remarkable  in  oriental  antiquary. 
Only  an  eye  incapable  of  distinguishing  between  outer  appear- 


BOSSUET  231 

ance  and  inner  reality,  between  material  and  spiritual  greatness, 
will  rank  it  as  lower  than  even  Egypt,  Assyria,  China,  or  India. 
Certainly  none  of  these  kingdoms  has  had  a  tithe  of  its  influence 
on  the  civilisation  of  Europe.  The  legislation  of  Rome,  it  must 
be  admitted,  has  affected  that  of  modern  states  more  powerfully 
than  even  that  of  Judea,  but  the  legislation  of  Rome  alone.  It 
would  be  difficult  to  decide  whether  the  political  spirit  of  clas- 
sical or  of  Jewish  antiquity  has  worked  most  infiuentially  in 
Christendom.  As  mere  literature,  the  Old  Testament  is  one  of 
the  wonders  of  the  world,  and,  in  particular,  there  is  nothing  in 
Greece  or  Rome,  nothing  in  all  the  East  or  West,  like  its  sacred 
poetry.  There  was  a  sense  of  moral  claims  and  moral  wants  de- 
veloped in  Israel  from  very  early  times  such  as  existed  nowhere 
else  before  the  diffusion  of  Christianity,  which  avowedly  based 
itself  on  Judaism.  As  a  religion,  many  will  refuse  to  regard  it  as 
a  supernatural  revelation ;  but  they  must  surely  admit  that  we 
are  entitled  to  adapt  to  it  the  language  in  which  Aristotle  speaks 
of  Anaxagoras,  "  that  the  man  who  first  announced  that  Reason 
was  the  cause  of  the  world  and  of  all  orderly  arrangement  in 
nature,  no  less  than  in  living  bodies,  appeared  like  a  man  in 
his  sober  senses  in  comparison  with  those  who  heretofore  had 
been  speaking  at  random  and  in  the  dark  ; "  and  to  say  that  the 
nation  which  had  a  pure  and  elevating  moral  and  monotheistic 
creed  for  many  centuries  before  any  other  had  risen  above  a 
degrading  and  fantastic  idolatry,  pantheism,  or  polytheism, 
appears  among  them  as  a  sober  and  sane  man,  awake  and  in 
the  daylight,  in  comparison  with  those  who  are  dreaming,  or 
drunk,  or  stumbling  in  the  dark.  In  Judaism  both  Christianity 
and  Mohammedanism  have  their  roots. 

The  way  in  which  Bossuet  treated  Mohammedanism  is 
severely  censured  by  Mr.  Buckle.  He  says  (vol.  i.  pp.  725, 
726,  first  ed.),  "  Every  one  acquainted  with  the  progress  of 
civilisation  will  allow  that  no  small  share  of  it  is  due  to  those 
gleams  of  light  which,  in  the  midst  of  surrounding  darkness, 
shot  from  the  great  centres  of  Cordova  and  Bagdad.  These, 
however,  were  the  work  of  Mohammedanism ;  and  as  Bos- 
suet had  been  taught  that  Mohammedanism  is  a  pestilential 
heresy,  he  could  not  bring  himself  to  believe  that  Christian 
nations  had  derived  anything  from  so  corrupt  a  source.     The 


232  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

consequence  is  that  he  says  nothing  of  that  great  religion, 
the  noise  of  which  has  filled  the  world ;  and  having  occasion 
to  mention  its  founder,  he  treats  him  with  scorn,  as  an  impu- 
dent impostor,  whose  pretensions  it  is  hardly  fitting  to  notice. 
The  great  apostle,  who  diffused  among  millions  of  idolaters 
the  sublime  verity  of  one  God,  is  spoken  of  by  Bossuet  with 
supreme  contempt;  because  Bossuet,  with  the  true  spirit  of 
his  profession,  could  see  nothing  to  admire  in  those  whose 
opinions  differed  from  his  own.  But  when  he  has  occasion 
to  mention  some  obscure  member  of  that  class  to  which  he 
himself  belonged,  then  it  is  that  he  scatters  his  praises  with 
boundless  profusion.  In  his  scheme  of  universal  history, 
Mohammed  is  not  worthy  to  play  a  part.  He  is  passed  by ; 
but  the  truly  great  man,  the  man  to  whom  the  human  race 
is  really  indebted  is  —  Martin,  Bishop  of  Tours.  He  it  is, 
says  Bossuet,  whose  unrivalled  actions  filled  the  universe 
with  his  fame,  both  during  his  lifetime  and  after  his  death. 
It  is  true  that  not  one  educated  man  in  fifty  has  ever  heard 
the  name  of  Martin,  Bishop  of  Tours.  But  Martin  performed 
miracles,  and  the  Church  had  made  him  a  saint ;  his  claims, 
therefore,  to  the  attention  of  historians,  must  be  far  superior 
to  the  claims  of  one  who,  like  Mohammed,  was  without  these 
advantages.  Thus  it  is  that,  in  the  opinion  of  the  only  emi- 
nent writer  on  history  during  the  power  of  Louis  XIV.,  the 
greatest  man  Asia  has  ever  produced,  and  one  of  the  greatest 
the  world  has  ever  seen,  is  considered  in  every  way  inferior 
to  a  mean  and  ignorant  monk,  whose  most  important  achieve- 
ment was  the  erection  of  a  monastery,  and  who  spent  the 
best  part  of  his  life  in  useless  solitude,  trembling  before  the 
superstitious  fancies  of  his  weak  and  ignoble  nature." 

In  order  to  enable  the  reader  to  estimate  this  criticism  at 
its  worth,  it  is  not  necessary  that  I  should  show  that  although 
the  Mohammedan  was  a  powerful  and  in  many  respects  ad- 
mirable movement,  it  yet  involved  no  great  original  idea,  the 
religious  truth  which  it  contained  and  diffused  being  drawn 
from  Jewish,  and  the  scientific  truth  from  Greek  sources ; 
that  even  if  Bossuet  had  tried  and  failed  to  appreciate  that 
movement,  his  failure  ought  to  be  ascribed  more  to  the  spirit 
of  his  age  than  to  the  spirit  of  his  profession ;  that  the  mean- 


BOSSUET  233 

ing  of  the  language  actually  employed  by  him  is  misrepre- 
sented and  caricatured ;  or  that  wrong  is  done  to  the  memory 
of  Martin  of  Tours,  whose  youth  and  manhood  were  spent 
not  in  useless  solitude  hut  in  the  Roman  camp,  who,  although 
sharing  in  the  superstitions  of  his  contemporaries,  certainly 
carried  into  his  later  life  of  monk  and  bishop  no  weakness  or 
ignobleness  of  nature,  but  a  heroic  courage  which  enabled 
him  to  face  death  often  in  his  struggle  with  Celtic  and  Latin 
paganism,  and  a  Christian  dignity  conspicuously  displayed 
before  an  emperor  surrounded  with  episcopal  adulations,  and 
who  is  known  not  only  as  the  founder  of  a  monastery  but  as 
the  advocate  of  religious  toleration,  as  a  man  who  protested 
by  word  and  deed  against  the  intervention  of  secular  power 
in  religious  matters,  and  branded  with  his  solemn  reprobation 
the  bishops  who  took  part  in  the  persecution  of  the  heretic 
Priscillian  and  his  disciples.  It  is  not  necessary  for  me  to 
prove  any  of  these  facts,  which  it  would  be  easy  to  do,  as 
there  are  two  still  more  conclusive  as  to  the  rashness  and 
unfairness  of  Mr.  Buckle's  accusation  —  viz.,  first,  that  all 
that  Bossuet  has  written  in  his  '  Discours '  about  Martin  of 
Tours  is  just  the  two  lines  which  Mr.  Buckle  quotes  ;  and  next, 
that  at  the  end  of  that  discourse  he  informs  us  he  meant  to 
write  another  in  order  to  explain  the  history  of  France  and 
the  rise  and  decline  of  Mohammedanism,  — "  Ce  meme  dis- 
cours vous  d^couvrira  les  causes  des  prodigieux  succ&s  de 
Mahomet  et  de  ses  successeurs :  cet  empire,  qui  a  commence 
deux  cents  ans  avant  Charlemange,  pouvait  trouver  sa  place 
dans  ce  discours ;  mais  j'ai  cru  qu'il  valait  mieux  vous  faire 
voir  dans  une  meTne  suite  ses  commencements  et  sa  decadence." 
It  would  almost  seem  as  if  it  might  be  as  difficult  for  a  nine- 
teenth-century positivist  to  be  completely  just  to  a  seven- 
teenth-century Catholic  bishop,  as  for  the  latter  to  appreciate 
truthfully  the  great  qualities  of  an  Arabian  "  faux  prophete."  l 

1  Mr.  Hath,  in  his  'Life  and  Writings  of  Henry  Thomas  Buckle,'  vol.  i.  pp. 
237-239,  has  replied  to  my  criticism  of  Buckle's  censure  of  Bossuet.  He  begins 
with  the  words :  "  I  have  hardly  found  in  Professor  Flint's  '  Philosophy  of 
History,'  or  in  his  account  in  the  '  Encyclopaedia  Britannica,'  a  single  word  in 
Buckle's  praise;  and  not  only  does  he  practically  adopt  many  of  Buckle's  views 
without  a  reference  to  him  (e.gr.,  Phil,  of  Hist.,  pp.  7,  27,  94, 101,  104, 128,  129), 
but  actually  goes  out  of  his  way  to  accuse  him  of  unfairness  and  dishonesty  in 


234  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IK   FRANCE 

his  account  of  Bossuet.  Mr.  Flint's  accusation  is  this:  that  it  is  untrue  that 
Bossuet  neglected  the  Mohammedans,  or  overrated  Martin  of  Tours;  and  he 
maintains  that  the  Jewish  nation  is  the  most  remarkable  in  antiquity."  I  am 
glad  to  have  the  opportunity  thus  afforded  me  of  stating  that  Mr.  Huth's  excellent 
biography  gave  me  a  much  higher  opinion  of  Mr.  Buckle  as  a  man  than  I  enter- 
tained before  I  became  acquainted  with  it.  I  had  been  led  in  a  way  which  it  is 
unnecessary  to  state  to  form  an  estimate  of  the  character  of  Mr.  Buckle  which  Mr. 
Huth's  book  at  once  convinced  me  must  be  erroneous.  Hence,  although  I  am  not 
aware  of  having  written  any  word  which  is  unjust  towards  Mr.  Buckle,  I  can 
readily  suppose  that  I  might  well  have  found  more  to  say  in  his  praise  than  I 
have  done.  On  the  other  hand,  I  cannot  see  any  ground  for  my  referring  to  Mr. 
Buckle  in  any  of  the  pages  which  Mr.  Huth  has  indicated.  There  is  no  view  in 
these  pages,  so  far  as  I  am  aware,  peculiar  to  Buckle,  or  specially  derived  from 
Buckle.  Then,  if  testing  the  accuracy  of  Buckle's  criticism  of  Bossuet's  his- 
torical philosophy  was  going  out  of  my  way  when  that  philosophy  was  precisely 
the  subject  which  I  had  under  consideration,  I  confess  I  do  not  know  what 
keeping  in  my  way  would  have  been.  Mr.  Huth  should  have  seen  that  I  had  not 
accused  Mr.  Buckle  of  "  dishonesty  in  his  account  of  Bossuet,"  or  of  any  other  kind 
of  unfairness  than  that  which  Buckle  himself  charges  on  Bossuet.  Further,  my 
accusation  was  not  "  that  it  is  untrue  that  Bossuet  neglected  the  Mohammedans, 
or  overestimated  Martin  of  Tours."  As  to  the  Mohammedans,  it  was,  that  Buckle 
ought  to  have  taken  due  account  of  Bossuet's  declared  intention  to  treat  specially 
of  the  progress  and  decay  of  Mohammedanism.  That  showed  that  Bossuet  was 
quite  aware  that  Mohammed  was  a  much  more  important  historical  personage 
than  Martin  of  Tours.  "But,"  says  Mr.  Huth,  "I  doubt  that  even  if  he  had 
written  the  continuation  he  proposed,  from  the  time  of  Charlemagne  to  Louis 
XIV.,  which  '  vous  decouvrira  les  causes  des  prodigieux  succes  de  Mahomet  et  de 
ses  successeurs,'  he  would  have  done  more  than  give  some  account  of  the 
Crusades."  Indeed!  Would  that  have  been  fulfilling  his  promise ?  Would  that 
have  been  disclosing  the  causes  of  the  marvellous  successes  of  Mohammed  and  his 
successors  ?  As  to  Martin  of  Tours,  what  I  charge  on  Buckle  is  that  he  under- 
estimated him  as  much  as  he  believed  Bossuet  to  have  overestimated  him.  As 
I  suppose  that  Bossuet  credited  Martin  with  having  performed  some  at  least  of 
the  miracles  ascribed  to  him,  I  suppose  also  that  he  overestimated  him,  my  own 
capacity  of  believing  in  miracles  being  small.  But  what  he  says  of  his  fame  is 
not  so  very  exaggerated.  What  Mr.  Buckle  says,  that  "  not  one  educated  man  in 
fifty  has  ever  heard  the  name  of  Martin,  Bishop  of  Tours,"  maybe  true  of  the 
present  age,  but  in  the  latter  part  of  the  fourth  century,  and  for  ages  afterwards, 
all  Western  Christendom  knew  it  well.  So  far  as  popular  fame  was  concerned, 
probably  no  pope,  bishop,  or  saint  of  those  times  equalled  him.  Dilating  on  this 
point,  Martin's  friend  and  biographer,  Sulpicius  Severus,  uses  words  which  I 
imagine  Bossuet  must  have  had  in  mind  when  he  wrote  the  words  on  which 
Buckle  has  so  severely  commented :  "  Hoc  iEgyptus  fatetur,  hoc  Syria,  hoc 
JEthiops  comperit,  hoc  Indus  audivit,  hoc  Parthus  et  Persa  noverunt :  nee  igno- 
rat  Armenia.  Bosporus  enclusa  cognovit  et  postremo  si  quis  aut  Fortunatas 
Insulas,  aut  Glacialem  frequentat  Oceanum "  (De  Virtutibus  Monachorum 
Orientalium,  1.  xix.) .  I  agree  with  Mr.  Huth  in  thinking  that  the  position  and 
influence  of  the  Jewish  nation  in  history  is  too  large  a  subject  to  be  discussed  in 
a  note. 


CHAPTER  III 

THE  EIGHTEENTH  CENTURY  :  GENERAL  SURVEY MONTES- 
QUIEU, TURGOT,  AND  VOLTAIRE 


The  age  of  Louis  XIV.  occupies  in  the  history  of  France 
a  place  analogous  to  that  of  the  age  of  Pericles  in  the  history 
of  Greece,  and  of  Augustus  in  the  history  of  Rome.  France 
was  then  indubitably  the  first  nation  of  Europe ;  the  Grand 
Monarque  was  the  most  powerful  king  on  earth ;  and  the 
Court  of  Versailles  was  the  most  brilliant  in  the  world.  A 
Colbert  strove  to  develop  the  internal  resources  of  the  king- 
dom ;  a  Louvois,  served  by  masterly  diplomatists,  directed  its 
external  policy;  and  a  Conde",  a  Turenne,  a  Luxembourg,  a 
Catinat,  a  Vendome,  led  her  armies  to  victory.  The  French 
language  attained  its  utmost  refinement ;  and  French  litera- 
ture acquired  a  perfection  of  form  which  rendered  it,  espe- 
cially in  the  departments  of  oratory  and  the  drama,  an  object 
of  admiration  and  of  envy  to  all  the  nations  of  Europe.  The 
arts  of  painting,  engraving,  and  architecture  flourished.  In 
spite  of  the  most  serious  impediments,  even  industry  pro- 
gressed and  commerce  expanded.  Religion  and  its  ministers 
were  treated  with  universal  and  almost  unlimited  deference. 
Looked  at  partially  and  superficially,  it  might  well  seem  that 

1  For  the  general  history  of  France  in  the  eighteenth  centnry  the  reader  may 
be  referred  to  Michelet's  'Hist,  de  France,'  torn,  xv.-xvii. ;  Martin's  'Hist,  de 
France,'  torn.  xv.  xvi.;  Blanc's  '  Hist,  de  la  Re'v.  Franc.,'  torn.  i.  ii. ;  and  M.  Taine's 
'  Les  Origines  de  la  France  contemporaine.'  The  chief  work  on  the  history  of 
French  philosophy  during  the  eighteenth  century  is  Damiron's  '  Me'moires  pour 
servir  a  l'Histoire  de  la  Philosphie  au  xviiie  siecle.'  The  two  histories  of  general 
literature  for  the  same  period  which  have,  perhaps,  the  highest  reputation,  are 
Hettner's  '  Litteraturgeschichte  des  18.  Jahrhunderts,'  2°  Theil,  and  Nisard's 
'  Hist,  de  la  Litterature  Francaise,'  t.  iv.  But,  of  course,  there  are  whole  libraries 
of  books,  good,  bad,  and  indifferent,  on  the  philosophy,  literature,  and  history  of 
the  eighteenth  century. 

235 


236  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

the  policy  of  Richelieu,  of  Mazarin,  and  of  Louis  XIV.  had 
amply  justified  itself,  and  that  absolutism  was  a  glorious 
success. 

But  there  is  another  side  to  the  picture ;  and  one  which 
shows  us  that  if  the  policy  initiated  by  Richelieu  may  be 
credited  with  leading  to  the  triumphs  of  the  age  of  Louis 
XIV.,  it  must  equally  be  held  to  have  contributed  to  bring 
about  the  disasters  of  the  Revolution.  The  omnipotence  of 
the  monarch  rested  on  the  powerlessness  of  his  subjects ;  the 
splendour  of  the  court  was  due  to  the  impoverishment  of  the 
nation.  The  cultivators  of  the  soil  were  loaded  with  burdens 
to  support  non-resident  proprietors,  and  to  pay  for  costly 
palaces,  extravagant  pensions,  needless  and  destructive  wars. 
The  nobles,  deprived  of  their  independence,  but  allowed  to 
retain  unjust  and  offensive  privileges,  acquired  frivolous  and 
corrupt  habits.  The  ordinary  priests  were  as  poor  as  the 
peasants,  and  without  hope  of  preferment,  while  the  higher 
offices  of  the  Church  were  filled  by  noblemen  and  courtiers, 
too  often  worldly  and  immoral  in  their  lives.  The  king  ruled 
as  the  absolute  master  of  the  nation,  and  used  its  resources 
according  to  the  pleasure  of  his  will.  All  local  liberties  were 
withdrawn ;  the  local  organs  of  self-government  were  super- 
seded by  the  administration  of  agents  of  the  Crown.  The 
provinces  languished,  and  the  capital  was  stimulated  into  un- 
healthy activity. 

The  system  of  absolutism  reached  its  full  development 
under  Louis  XIV.,  and  the  natural  effects  of  it  came  ever 
more  clearly  to  light  as  his  reign  was  prolonged.  Long  before 
his  death  the  demonstration  of  its  viciousness  as  a  species  of 
government,  and  of  its  incompatibility  with  the  healthy  growth 
of  a  nation,  was  complete.  Continuous  foreign  wars  ended 
in  exhaustion  and  disgrace.  Ceremonial  display  and  outward 
magnificence  merely  veiled  moral  meanness  and  inward  de- 
pravity. Punctilious  attention  to  the  rites  of  the  Church, 
and  a  blind  or  feigned  zeal  for  orthodoxy,  only  favoured  the 
spread  of  hypocrisy  and  of  a  secret  and  cynical  scepticism. 
The  unnatural  and  arbitrary  compression  practised  by  the 
Government  was  sorely  felt  by  all  classes  of  society.  The 
misery  of  the  great  mass  of  the  people  foreboded  a  terrible 


THE   EIGHTEENTH   CENTURY  237 

reckoning.  When  the  old  king  died  in  1715,  a  general  sense 
of  relief  was  felt  throughout  France,  and  even  in  some  places 
a  joy  which  expressed  itself,  as  Saint-Simon  says,  "with  a 
scandalous  6cla.tr 

But  the  monarchy  itself  was  unshaken  ;  its  principles  had 
not  even  been  assailed.  The  temper  of  the  French  people 
was  still  the  reverse  of  revolutionary  or  disloyal.  Religious 
incredulity  was  almost  confined  to  the  younger  generation  of 
courtiers,  and  a  small  class  of  Parisians.  If  Louis  XIV.  had 
been  succeeded  by  reforming  rulers  of  ability,  courage,  and 
virtue,  there  might  well  have  been  no  French  Revolution,  to 
the  great  advantage  both  of  France  and  of  humanity.  But 
with  such  successors  as  he  actually  had,  the  wonder  is  that  a 
revolution  did  not  occur  sooner. 

Louis  XV.,  the  great-grandson  of  Louis  XIV.,  was  in  1715 
only  five  years  of  age.  From  1715  to  1723,  the  Duke  of 
Orleans  was  as  regent  the  head  of  the  Government.  He 
began  by  making  some  urgently  needed  reforms,  but  soon 
disappointed  any  hopes  he  had  thus  raised.  He  made  a  fatal  i 
mistake  when  he  sided  with  the  hierarchy  in  favouring  the 
usurpations  of  the  Papacy  on  the  rights  of  conscience  and 
the  independence  of  the  nation.  His  life  was  one  of  open 
and  shameless  profligacy.  The  Duke  of  Bourbon,  who  was 
minister  from  1723  to  1726,  followed  in  the  same  path ;  and 
as  he  .added  to  vice  ignorance  and  stupidity,  he  made  himself 
even  more  despised.  Then  Fleury  succeeded  to  power,  and 
it  lasted  until  his  death  in  1743,  when  he  was  ninety-three 
years  of  age.  He  was  not  devoid  of  personal  virtues,  and  had 
intellect  enough  to  govern  the  king;  but  he  was  mean,  un- 
amiable,  bigoted,  and  without  sympathy  with  the  aspirations, 
or  comprehension  of  the  wants,  of  the  nation.  He  so  ruled 
as  most  effectively  to  promote  the  cause  of  scepticism  and  of 
hatred  of  the  Church. 

With  the  death  of  Cardinal  Fleury  the  personal  govern- 
ment of  Louis  XV.  began,  and  it  lasted  until  1774.  There 
have  been  few  more  hateful  and  shameful  Governments  in  all 
history.  The  Court  sank  into  ever  lower  depths  of  infamy. 
The  country  was  ruined  with  taxes.  The  clergy  and  the  par- 
liaments were  engaged  in  keen  strife ;   both  contested  the 


238  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOEY   IN   FKANCE 

royal  authority.  All  was  corruption  and  intrigue,  anarchy 
and  contention.  The  reign  ended  amidst  universal  execra- 
tion. The  ancient  monarchy  was  also  near  its  end.  It  was 
still  vigorous  in  1715 ;  it  was  decayed  to  the  core  in  1774. 

What  had  been  the  general  course  of  opinion  in  France 
during  the  period  to  which  I  have  been  referring  ?  It  was  at 
first  submissive  and  deferential  both  to  ecclesiastical  and  civil 
authority.  There  was  in  it  no  thought  of  resistance  to  either. 
Absolute  power,  it  was  hoped,  would  cure  the  evils  which  it 
had  caused.  This  feeling,  as  well  as  the  discontent  with 
which  it  was  associated,  found  their  earliest  and  clearest 
expression  in  the  political  romances  or  Utopias  which  were 
written  in  France  during  the  latter  part  of  the  seventeenth 
and  the  earlier  part  of  the  eighteenth  century.  The  '  Re"pub- 
lique  des  Se've'rrambes  '  of  Vairasse,  the  '  Testament '  of  Mez- 
lier,  the  '  Voyage  en  Salente '  in  the  '  Te"hJmaque  of  Fe'ne'lon,' 
and  the  'Voyages  de  Cyrus'  of  Ramsay,  are  examples.  These 
works  were  very  significant.  Hope  springing  immortal  in 
the  human  breast,  a  suffering  people  is  naturally  prophetic. 
It  is  in  their  times  of  sorest  depression  that  nations  usually 
indulge  most  in  dreams  of  a  better  future,  and  that  their 
imaginations  produce  most  freely  social  ideals  and  Utopias. 
But  all  the  ideals  or  Utopias  which  appeared  in  France  at  this 
period  had  a  common  character.  They  were  only  so  many 
forms  of  the  prophecy  of  a  perfect  commonwealth  centring 
in,  and  depending  on,  a  perfectly  wise  and  irresistibly  power- 
ful paternal  ruler. 

The  State  came  at  first  into  direct  and  open  conflict  with 
public  opinion  during  the  regency,  owing  to  the  part  it  took 
in  the  conflict  occasioned  by  the  publication  of  the  bull  Uni- 
genitus.  This  conflict  had  the  most  serious  consequences. 
By  it  the  French  Church  was  divided  into  two  parties,  the 
tranquillity  of  the  kingdom  disturbed,  violent  disputes  raised 
between  the  clergy  and  the  parliaments,  and  the  latter,  con- 
scious of  the  approval  of  the  majority  of  the  nation,  led  to  set 
at  defiance  the  royal  ordinances  commanding  submission  to 
the  Papal  decisions.  At  an  early  stage  in  the  course  of  it  the 
ecclesiastical  authorities  had  become  thoroughly  discredited 
in  popular  estimation ;  and  gradually  the  feelings  of  contempt 
and  aversion  with  which  the  Church  and  its  ministers  were 


PUBLIC    OPINION  239 

regarded  extended  to  Christianity  and  its  doctrines.  "  Free- 
thinking  "  passed  from  England  into  France,  there  to  find  a 
still  more  congenial  soil  and  a  more  luxuriant  development. 

The  State  was  soon  assailed,  however,  on  other  grounds  than 
its  action  in  relation  to  the  Church.  Exemplifying  all  vices, 
and  committing  all  varieties  of  folly  and  crime,  it  provoked 
attack  at  every  point.  Its  weakness  and  its  arbitrariness,  its 
carelessness  and  its  selfishness,  its  financial  prodigality,  the 
want  of  dignity,  decency,  or  shame  which  characterised  its 
Court,  the  incompetence  and  injustice  shown  in  every  depart- 
ment of  its  internal  administration,  and  the  want  of  patriotism 
manifest  in  its  dealings  with  foreign  Powers,  all  naturally 
drew  down  on  it  criticism  and  censure.  Without  ceasing  to 
be  a  tyranny,  it  ceased  to  be  feared ;  retaining  all  the  appa- 
ratus and  methods  of  despotism,  it  became  irresolute  and 
uncertain  in  the  application  of  them.  And  while  it  was 
rapidly  growing  weaker  and  more  timid,  the  popular  mind 
was  rapidly  growing  stronger  and  more  daring  ;  while  the  ex- 
tant institutions  were  rapidly  crumbling,  ideas  hitherto  latent 
were  vigorously  forcing  themselves  into  power ;  while  old 
methods  were  falling  into  discredit,  new  principles  were  rising 
into  honour.  Before  the  century  was  far  advanced  the  Govern- 
ment stood  face  to  face  with  a  hostile  authority  which  former 
ages  had  scarcely  known,  and  with  which  it  was  most  difficult 
to  cope.  This  was  that  public  opinion,  the  advent  of  which  j 
was,  perhaps,  the  most  distinctive  and  important  fact  in  the ! 
history  of  France  in  the  eighteenth  century.  There  had  not 
been  previously  in  France  a  public  opinion  strictly  so  called. 
Before  the  reign  of  Louis  XIV.  there  had  been  only  the  pas- 
sions and  interests  of  factions  and  classes ;  under  his  reign 
there  had  been  an  opinion  dominated  by  the  influence  of  the 
monarch ;  but  in  the  eighteenth  century  a  public  opinion 
which  was  truly  the  reflection  and  expression  of  the  general 
mind  working  freely  became  the  most  potent  factor  in  the 
national  life,  the  chief  source  of  reputation  and  success,  or  of 
disgrace  and  failure.  It  disturbed  the  judgment,  arrested  the 
will,  unnerved  the  arm  of  the  ruler ;  made  the  salon  and  the 
caf6  the  rivals  of  the  Court ;  rendered  every  speaker  or  writer 
formidable,  and  the  collective  influence  of  the  intelligent  and 
literary  portion  of  society  enormous.     Its  rewards  were  more 


240  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

to  be  desired  and  its  punishments  more  to  be  feared  than 
those  which  either  sovereign  or  pope  could  confer.  Under 
Louis  XIV.  the  displeasure  of  the  king  involved  ruin ;  under 
Louis  XV.,  to  criticise  and  ridicule  the  constituted  authorities 
with  dexterity  and  effect  was  the  shortest  and  easiest  route  to 
fame.1 

Out  of  this  public  opinion  arose  the  French  philosophy  or 
philosophism  of  the  eighteenth  century.  Hence  the  secret  of 
its  rapid  spread,  its  amazing  force,  its  prodigious  results.  It 
was  no  mere  importation  from  England,  or  even  essentially 
English.  If  it  had,  it  would  have  been  comparatively  feeble 
and  sterile.  Its  matrix. and  medium,  its  roots  and  life,  were 
French,  although  it  found  in  the  precepts  of  Bacon,  the  physics 
of  /ftfewton,  the  empiricism  of  Locke,  the  free-thinking  of  the 
Deists,  and  the  political  tenets  of  the  Whigs,  a  nutriment 
which  the  Cartesianism  so  long  dominant  in  France  could 
-'not  supply  to  it.  fia,rtesia.nisTnJ_hguig  out  of  accord  with  the 
general  state  of  sentiment  and  the  prevailing  spirit  of  the  time 
which  had  now  arrived,  iiaLiiTSny]decayed_.aniaisapj).eared_; 
and  thenelTTu^oiie'oTthought  rapidly  took  its  place.  Probably 
the  connection  between  philosophy  and  public  opinion  was 
never  closer  than  in  France  during  the  eighteenth  century. 
In  fact,  what  was  then  and  there  called  philosophy  was,  for 
the  most  part,  just  public  opinion  in  its  clearest  form.  Philos- 
ophy stooped  so  much  to  public  opinion  as  almost  to  cease  to 
be  philosophy,  but  with  the  result  that  public  opinion  went 
wholly  over  to  its  side,  and  the  public  believed  itself  to  have 
become  philosophical.  It  has  to  be  observed,  however,  that 
it  was  not  until  nearly  the  middle  of  the  eighteenth  century 
that  what  is  designated  the  French  philosophy  of  the  eigh- 
teenth century  became  a  power  in  France.  It  is  altogether 
erroneous  to  suppose  that  the  French  philosophers  produced 
the  spirit  which  caused  the  French  Revolution ;  they  were, 
in  the  main,  its  products.  But  certainly  they  did  a  vast  deal 
to  direct  and  diffuse  it ;  for  they  were  numerous,  talented, 

1  See  on  this  subject  Aubertin's  '  L'Esprit  public  au  dix-huitieme  siecle,'  and 
Roquain's  'L'Esprit  revolutionnaire  avant  la  Revolution.'  The  latter  work  is 
especially  important  for  the  understanding  of  the  mental  development  of  France 
during  the  period  from  1715  to  1789,  and  for  the  explanation  of  the  Revolution. 


PHILOSOPHY   OP   THE   EIGHTEENTH   CENTUKY  241 

passionately  in  earnest,  and  indefatigable   in  the  work   of 
propagandism. 

I  must  briefly  indicate  the  characteristics  of  the  French 
philosophy  of  the  eighteenth  century,  in  so  far  as  they  throw 
light  on  the  progress  of  French  historiography  or  affected  the 
nature  and  favoured  the  diffusion  of  French  historical  philos- 
ophy in  that  age. 

It  was  a  much  more  radical,  aggressive,  and  revolutionary 
philosophy  than  the  species  of  English  philosophy  to  which  it 
was  most  allied,  and  of  which  it  was  in  a  sense  the  develop- 
ment. It  was,  in  particular,  more  decided  and  sweeping  in  its 
rejection  of  authority,  recognising  none  save  that  of  reason, 
and  exempting  nothing  from  the  criticism  of  reason.  Ancient 
tradition,  common  consent,  faith  of  the  Church,  Scripture, 
were  held  to  be  worthless  except  in  so  far  as  conformed  to, 
and  vouched  for,  by  reason.  Specifically  Christian  doctrines 
were  treated  by  all  the  adherents  of  the  new  philosophy  as 
absurd  and  pernicious  superstitions  ;  and  although  the  prin- 
ciples of  theism  were  accepted  by  a  class  of  them  as  rationally 
warranted,  a  class  not  less  numerous  assailed  all  religious 
beliefs  as  delusions.  The  new  philosophy  was  eminently  ra- 
tionalistic. It  was  not,  however,  calmly  and  temperately,  but 
keenly  and  passionately,  so.  Few  of  its  representatives  dis- 
played moderation  in  their  discussions,  or  contended  in  the 
cause  of  reason  only  with  fair  reasoning ;  the  majority  of  them 
had  large  recourse  to  ridicule,  invective,  and  misrepresenta- 
tion, and  thereby  produced  an  incalculable  amount  of  mischief, 
for  which  they  cannot  be  held  to  have  been  irresponsible, 
although  they  may  not  have  foreseen  it. 

The  philosophy  in  question  was  empirical  as  well  as  ration- 
alistic, and  largely  also  materialistic.     Starting  from  the  posi-  { 
tion  of  Locke,  that  all  knowledge  is  derived  from  experience, 
it  traced  experience  wholly  to  external  sense,  and  explained  \ 
all  mental  states  and  processes  as  combinations  and  modifica-  \ 
tions  of  sensation.     It  despised  and  rejected  metaphysics.     It/ 
honoured  physical  science,  and  interested  itself  zealously  in[ 
its  diffusion.      Its  eyes  were  not  turned  intently  inwards  or 
upwards,  but  they  were    keenly  observant   of   surrounding 
physical  and  social  phenomena.     In  France  during  the  eigh- 
teenth century  remarkable  progress  was  made  in  mathematics, 


242  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

astronomy,  physics,  chemistry,  natural  history,  geography,  and 
medicine ;  and  the  causes  of  their  progress  were  to  a  consid- 
erable extent  the  same  to  which  were  due  the  prevalence  of 
the  philosophy  of  the  epoch.  The  rise  of  modern  atheistic 
materialism  dates  from  this  period,  and  from  its  first  appear- 
ance gained  ready  acceptance.  It  is  true  that  a  systematic 
and  entirely  unreserved  exposition  of  the  system  was  not  pub- 
lished until  1770 ;  and  even  then  it  created  a  sensation,  and 
drew  forth  from  Voltaire  a  cry  of  alarm  and  from  Frederick 
the  Great  a  refutation ;  but  there  were  many  who  found  in 
Holbach's  conclusions  only  their  own  opinions,  and  firmly 
believed  that  science  showed  there  could  be  no  God,  soul, 
freedom,  or  immortality. 

The  philosophy  under  consideration  was,  further,  one  eager 
for  action,  bent  on  proselytism  and  conquest,  ambitious  to 
reform  and  govern  society.  Unlike  Cartesianism,  it  was  mili- 
tant and  aggressive,  ethically,  politically,  and  religiously.  It 
aimed  not  only  at  displacing,  but  replacing,  the  powers  which 
had  hitherto  ruled  the  world.  It  intervened  in  everything, 
anxious  to  make  all  things  new,  and  with  little  distrust  of  its 
own  ability  to  do  so.  The  common  representation  of  it  as  a 
merely  negative  philosophy  is  quite  inadequate.  It  was  neg- 
ative, much  too  negative ;  but  it  was  also  essentially  positive, 
honourably  and  nobly  positive.  Its  chief  strength  was  drawn 
from  its  positive  ethical  and  political  convictions ;  from  its 
faith  in  justice,  toleration,  liberty,  fraternity,  the  sovereignty 
of  the  people,  the  rights  of  man.  Its  perception  of  the  mean- 
ing of  these  principles  was  not  always  perfect ;  its  application 
of  them  was  often  most  imperfect;  but  it  believed  in  them 
with  a  sincerity  and  intensity  unknown  for  centuries,  if  not 
from  the  beginning  of  historic  time.  It  so  believed  in  them 
as  the  prerogatives  of  all  men,  irrespective  of  religion,  or 
country,  or  condition. 

Former  generations  had  received  these  principles  very  coldly 
and  partially,  and  only  in  so  far  as  they  seemed  to  be  contained 
and  sanctioned  by  Christianity ;  now  they  were  accepted  en- 
thusiastically and  fully,  as  anterior  to  and  higher  than  Chris- 
tianity, as  laAvs  by  reference  to  which  all  religions  and  professed 
revelations,  all  institutions  and  authorities,  must  be  judged. 
The  adherents  even  of  doctrines  which  appear  to  tend  directly 


PHILOSOPHY    OF    THE    EIGHTEENTH    CENTURY  243 

and  inevitably  to  denial  of  morality  and  to  contempt  for  man  — 
the  atheists,  materialists,  and  sensationalists  of  philosophism 
— zealously  advocated  certain  grand  ethical  and  political 
truths,  which  the  ecclesiastical  writers  and  orators  of  the 
seventeenth  century  had  ignored  or  assailed;  and  they  at 
least  taught  men  to  think  not  less  highly  of  themselves  than 
they  ought  to  think.  The  same  authors  who  are  notorious 
for  the  crudeness  and  vehemence  with  which  they  rejected 
belief  in  God  and  the  soul,  denied  the  absoluteness  of  moral 
distinctions,  scoffed  at  hopes  of  a  spiritual  and  future  life, 
and  represented  man  as  a  merely  material  organisation,  pro- 
duced and  determined  by  a  blind  necessity,  primarily  endowed 
only  with  sensuous  impressibility,  and  destined-  soon  to  lose 
for  ever  the  consciousness  which  he  has  for  a  time  enjoyed, 
—  are  also  found,  with  a  remarkable  although  not  inexplica- 
ble inconsequentiality,  dilating  on  the  un  worthiness  of  exist- 
ing ambitions  and  interests ;  pouring  contempt  on  mundane 
glory;  defying  the  powers  and  ridiculing  the  idols  of  the 
world;  summoning  men  to  sincerity,  naturalness,  justice,  and 
beneficence;  and  demanding  for  the  humblest  of  the  human 
race  the  recognition  of  his  dignity,  the  security  of  his  per- 
son, the  inviolability  of  his  conscience,  and  the  freedom  of 
his  thought.  In  many  ways  the  French  philosophers  of  the 
eighteenth  century  grievously  erred,  but  they  are  fully  en- 
titled to  the  credit  of  having  been  signally  successful  propa- 
gators of  truths  of  the  utmost  practical  moment. 

Another  characteristic  of  these  philosophers  was  their  keen 
interest  in  the  study  of  history.  They  distrusted  speculation 
and  abstraction,  but  had  great  confidence  in  experience  and 
induction ;  they  were  indifferent  or  averse  to  the  theories  of 
metaphysics  and  the  dogmas  of  theology,  but  keenly  desirous 
of  knowing  the  laws  and  particulars  of  nature.  Hence  they 
turned  eagerly  for  entertainment  and  instruction  to  the  pages 
of  travellers,  physicists,  delineators  of  human  character, 
passions,  and  manners,  and  historians.  History  had  strong 
attractions  for  them.  They  fully  shared  in  the  conviction 
generally  diffused  among  their  contemporaries,  that  "the 
proper  study  of  mankind  is  man."  It  was  history  which 
seemed  to  them  to  enlarge  most  the  limits,  and  increase  most 
the  contents,  of  experience.     It  was  history  which  ministered 


244  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

most  directly  and  abundantly  to  the  satisfaction  of  the  feel- 
ing of  humanity,  that  sympathy  of  man  with  his  fellow-men 
simply  as  such,  the  prevalence  of  which  so  strikingly  dis- 
tinguishes the  eighteenth  century  from  the  theological  and 
scholastic  ages.  It  was  history  likewise  which  supplied  the 
philosophers  with  evidences  of  the  misrule  of  the  powers 
which  they  combated;  which  showed  them  how  the  peoples 
had  been  deluded,  wronged,  and  oppressed;  and  which  fur- 
nished them  with  the  most  effective  arguments  for  the  tenets 
which  they  were  most  anxious  to  propagate.  They  therefore 
betook  themselves  eagerly  to  the  study  of  history.  Into  its 
study,  however,  they  carried  their  passions  and  prejudices. 
Few  of  them  examined  it  in  a  strictly  historical  or  truly 
scientific  spirit.  Where  they  should  have  been  content  to 
narrate  or  explain  it,  they  often  strove  chiefly  to  make  it 
subservient  to  their  polemical  and  proselytising  zeal,  and,  in 
consequence,  frequently  misrepresented  and  misinterpreted 
it.  They  regarded  the  past  as  so  given  over  to  tyranny  and 
superstition,  so  overestimated  their  own  enlightenment,  and 
were  so  credulously  hopeful  as  to  the  future,  that  their  con- 
ceptions of  the  plan  of  history  were  necessarily  narrow,  un- 
just, and  inconsistent.  Their  unbelief  as  to  the  eternal  and 
invisible,  and  their  hostility  to  religion,  rendered  them  insen- 
sible to  the  agency  of  the  ultimate  cause  of  the  movement 
of  history,  and  satisfied  with  superficial  explanations.  Yet 
although  their  interest  in  history  was  generally  far  from 
pure,  and  their  treatment  of  it  far  from  always  appropriate, 
there  can  be  no  doubt  that,  on  the  whole,  they  greatly  fur- 
thered the  progress  of  historical  science.  Previously  only  a 
very  few  exceptional  and  isolated  thinkers  had  attempted 
to  discover  law  and  meaning  in  history;  now  it  became  the 
favourite  subject  of  theorising.  Almost  all  the  chief  intel- 
lects of  the  age  were  attracted  to  it,  with  the  result  that  in 
less  than  half  a  century  far  more  historico-philosophical  writ- 
ings appeared  than  in  all  previous  time. 

I  shall  proceed  to  a  consideration  of  the  most  important  of 
these,  as  soon  as  I  have  indicated  what  was  the  general  condi- 
tion of  French  historiography  in  the  eighteenth  century. 

The  view  has  often  been  expressed  that  historical  litera- 
ture was  at  a  low  ebb  in  France  in  the  eighteenth  century, 


LEARNED    HISTORY  245 

or  at  least  that  it  was  greatly  below  the  point  at  which  it 
had  stood  in  the  previous  century.  This  is  a  view  which  it 
will  be  found  difficult  or  impossible  to  prove.  The  study  of 
Greek,  the  most  useful  and  necessary  of  languages  to  the 
historian  of  ancient  times  and  peoples,  was,  indeed,  less 
generally  and  carefully  cultivated  than  it  had  formerly  been, 
although  strangely  enough  it  was  just  the  period  when  Greek 
ideas  had  most  influence,  and  when  the  great  ambition  of 
earnest  Frenchmen  was  to  resemble  the  sages  of  Athens  or 
the  heroes  of  Sparta.  Nor  is  it  to  be  denied  that  many  of  the 
popular  French  historians  of  the  eighteenth  century  were 
very  deficient  in  knowledge  and  research.  But  we  have  no 
right  to  contrast  such  authors  with  the  erudite  French  his- 
torical scholars  of  the  seventeenth  century,  and  to  ignore  the 
fact  that  there  were  in  France  during  the  eighteenth  century 
also  many  most  laborious  and  most  learned  workers  in  almost 
every  department  of  history.  The  Benedictine  Order  still 
supplied  erudite  historical  investigators  of  the  most  indefati- 
gable and  exemplary  type.  Montfaucon,  Martene,  Denis  of 
Saint-Marthe,  Bouquet,  and  their  associates,  performed  as 
students  of  history  services  of  the  highest  value.  They  had 
worthy  rivals  among  the  members  of  the  Academy  of  Inscrip- 
tions in  such  men  as  D'  Anville,  Breguigny,  Fr6ret,  La  Curne 
de  Saint-Palaye,  and  others,  perhaps,  not  less  entitled  to  be 
mentioned. 

Montfaucon  in  his  '  Palseographia  Grasca'  (1708)  made  an 
original  and  important  departure  in  the  field  of  classical  re- 
search, and  in '  L'  Antiquite"  explique"e  et  representee  en  figures ' 
(10  vols.,  1719-1724)  he  gave  to  the  world  a  still  more  epoch- 
making  work,  which  showed  not  only  the  abounding  interest  of 
the  history  of  ancient  art  in  itself,  but  to  how  great  an  extent 
the  remains  of  such  art  throw  light  on  all  the  developments  of 
ancient  history.  The  former  of  these  publications  is  a  worthy 
counterpart  and  admirable  complement  to  the  '  Diplomatica ' 
of  Mabillon ;  the  latter  is  an  almost  inexhaustible  treasury  of 
valuable  materials,  from  which  a  host  of  scholars  have  drawn 
instruction,  —  a  vast  and  noble  monument  of  its  author's  ex- 
traordinary knowledge,  of  his  singular  clearness  of  design  and 
arrangement,  and  of  his  untiring  and  methodical  and  wisely 
directed  industry.    Dom  Bouquet  in  his  '  Recueil  des  historiens 


246  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOKY   IN   PKANCE 

des  Gaules  et  de  la  France '  (8  vols.,  1738-1754),  and  Dom 
Rivet  by  his  'Histoire  litte"raire  de  la  France'  (1733),  laid  the 
foundations  on  which  the  histories  of  the  French  people  and 
of  French  literature  could  alone  be  satisfactorily  built  up.  I 
must  refrain  from  referring  to  the  services  rendered  to  the 
study  of  oriental  history  by  Fourmont  and  his  disciples,  of 
ecclesiastical  history  by  Martene  and  Durand,  of  secular 
medieval  history  by  La  Curiae,  and  of  the  sources  of  French 
history  by  Breguigny,  or  to  the  labours  of  sundry  meritorious 
local  and  special  historians,  and  of  those  who  distinguished 
themselves  in  geography,  chronology,  numismatics,  and  other 
disciplines  auxiliary  to  history;  but  I  cannot  leave  quite 
unnoticed  the  merits  of  Nicholas  Fr6ret,  perhaps  the  most 
remarkably  endowed  of  all  the  French  scholars  of  the  cen- 
tury with  the  genius  of  historical  criticism  and  research. 

He  was  born  in  1688  and  died  in  1749.  His  life  was  entirely 
that  of  a  student.  His  writings  first  appeared  in  the  form  of 
contributions  to  the  Academy  of  Inscriptions,  of  which  learned 
society  he  was  for  a  considerable  time  secretary.  The  collected 
edition  of  them — 'CEuvres  completes  de  Fre'ret'  (20  torn. 
12mo) — was  published  in  1798,  prefaced  by  the  excellent 
'  Eloge  de  Fre'ret '  of  M.  de  Bougainville,  a  scholar  of  kindred 
spirit,  brother  of  the  celebrated  navigator  De  Bougainville. 
Fre'ret  seems  to  have  taken  the  knowledge  of  all  antiquity 
for  his  province,  and  his  investigations  extend  into  all  parts  of 
this  vast  domain.  He  everywhere  displays  the  most  thorough 
and  varied  erudition,  great  ingenuity  in  research  and  inde- 
pendence of  judgment,  and  a  comprehensive,  vigorous,  and 
philosophical  intelligence.  The  results  of  his  investigations 
were  only  published  in  detached  and  fragmentary  communi- 
cations ;  but  the  identity  of  the  method  always  pursued  takes 
from  them  all  appearance  or  inconsistency  or  heterogeneous- 
ness.  The  method  is  just  that  of  the  severe  and  scientific 
criticism  of  the  present  day,  already  in  Fre"ret's  hands  as  clear, 
self-conscious,  and  unhesitating  in  regard  to  means,  processes, 
and  end,  as  in  those  of  the  foremost  living  historians.  His 
criticism  is  of  a  kind  which  had  entirely  thrown  off  the  fetters 
of  traditionalism  and  yet  kept  itself  free  from  the  excesses 
of  historical  Pyrrhonism ;  it  is  also  strictly  impartial  and  dis- 
interested, seeking  only  to  ascertain  the  truth.     I  shall  briefly 


FRERET  247 

indicate  the  range  and  scope  of  his  scientific  activity.  Pie 
gave  a  great  amount  of  attention  to  the  study  of  the  chro- 
nology of  the  ancient  world ;  and  the  results  of  his  researches 
in  this  department  are  embodied  in  eight  volumes  of  his  col- 
lected writings  (vii.-xiv.).  He  worked  with  a  full  knowledge 
of  the  labours  of  Scaliger,  Petau,  Masham,  and  Newton,  but 
also  with  the  conviction  that  their  methods  had  been  neither 
sufficiently  exact  nor  sufficiently  comprehensive.  There  can 
be  little  doubt  that  he  detected  not  a  few  errors  into  which 
they  had  fallen,  and  that  his  criticisms  of  their  processes  and 
conclusions  were  of  the  most  relevant,  objective,  and  useful 
kind.  It  is  admitted  by  competent  specialists  that  his  disser- 
tations on  the  general  questions  of  which  chronology  treats  are 
admirable  from  a  methodological  point  of  view ;  that  the  special 
dissertations  on  the  chronology  of  the  Assyrians,  Chaldeans, 
Lydians,  Egyptians,  Hindus,  Hebrews,  Greeks,  and  Romans, 
were  important  contributions  to  the  histories  of  these  peoples ; 
that  his  reduction  of  Chinese  chronology  to  approximately  true 
dimensions  was  a  brilliant  as  well  as  solid  achievement ;  and 
that  his  investigations  as  to  the  time  when  Pythagoras  lived, 
and  as  to  the  dates  of  the  battles  of  Marathon  and  of  Platea, 
of  the  taking  of  Athens  by  Sylla,  of  the  death  of  Herod  the 
Great,  &c,  deserve  careful  consideration.  The  '  Observations 
on  the  Two  Deluges  or  Inundations  of  Ogyges  and  Deucalion,' 
and  the  '  Reflections  on  an  ancient  celestial  Phenomenon  ob- 
served in  the  time  of  Ogyges '  (see  torn.  xvi.  of  the  '  CEuvres '), 
are  good  specimens  of  his  ingenuity  and  skill  in  combining 
scattered  data,  and  educing  from  them  a  significant  result. 
He  likewise  applied  himself  with  ardour  to  the  study  of  ancient 
geography,  collecting,  sifting,  comparing,  and  combining  an 
enormous  number  of  data  of  all  kinds  bearing  on  the  points 
discussed,  and  leaving  among  his  manuscripts  no  fewer  than 
1375  maps  embodying  the  results  of  his  inquiries  regarding 
the  geography  of  Gaul,  of  Greece  and  the  islands  of  the 
Archipelago,  of  Asia  Minor,  of  Persia,  and  of  Armenia.  In 
this  department  he  dealt  not  merely  with  particular  points  and 
problems,  but  also  with  general  questions,  the  method  of  in- 
vestigation, the  growth  of  geographical  knowledge  among  the 
ancients,  the  separation  of  truth  from  error  in  their  geographi- 
cal notions  and  statements,  the  various  measures  in  use  among 


248  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

the  peoples  of  antiquity,  &c.  His  fame  as  a  geographer,  like 
that  of  his  friend  Delisle,  has  been  too  much  eclipsed  by 
D' Anville's,  whose  boast  of  having  "  found  a  geography  made 
of  bricks,  and  left  one  of  gold,"  considerably  overshot  the 
mark.  Fre"ret  engaged  likewise  in  inquiries  into  the  rise  and 
progress  of  the  arts  and  sciences,  a  branch  of  history  which 
only  began  to  flourish  in  the  eighteenth  century.  His  '  Gen- 
eral Observations  on  the  study  of  Ancient  Philosophy '  (torn, 
xvi.)  deserve  to  be  specially  noted  in  this  connection,  owing 
to  the  clearness  with  which  they  show  that  the  traces  of  posi- 
tive scientific  knowledge  may  be  discovered  among  the  debris 
of  early  cosmogonical  and  speculative  systems.  He  at  least 
pointed  out  and  entered  on  the  path  which  Tannery,  Natorp, 
and  others  are  in  the  present  day  attempting  to  follow  up. 
The  history  of  religion  was  also  the  subject  of  his  earnest  and 
prolonged  inquiries  (torn,  xvii.-xviii.).  His  views  on  Greek 
mythology  were  far  in  advance  of  those  prevalent  in  the 
eighteenth  century.  He  saw  clearly  that  it  was  a  system  of 
a  very  composite  character,  formed  of  numerous  and  hetero- 
geneous elements  derived  from  diverse  sources,  and  that  it 
could  not  be  explained  by  any  single  principle  or  hypothesis, 
such  as  the  euhemeristic,  the  corruption  of  a  primitive  revela- 
tion, allegorising,  the  personification  of  physical  phenomena 
or  metaphysical  ideas,  &c.  He  was  among  the  first  to  obtain 
a  fairly  distinct  and  truthful  view  of  the  stages  through  which 
mythology  had  passed  in  Greece  before  there  were  any  his- 
torians to  record  them ;  and  this  was  because  he  was  among 
the  first  to  follow  exclusively  and  consistently  that  compara- 
tive method  which  can  alone  enable  us  to  discover  in  mythol- 
ogy its  own  history,  and  in  the  fables  of  the  gods  the  fates  of 
their  worship  and  worshippers.  He  was,  however,  so  aware 
of  the  difficulties  and  dangers  of  investigation  in  this  sphere 
that  he  confined  himself  to  research  into  particular  points  re- 
garding which  the  truth  seemed  not  unattainable.  Judged 
of  with  reference  to  the  requirements  of  method,  his  special 
inquiries  contrast  most  favourably  with  those  of  Banier, 
Gosselin,  and  other  mythologists  of  the  eighteenth  century. 
When  they  fail  to  lead  to  a  satisfactory  result,  the  cause  is 
not  that  they  have  been  unskilfully  or  unscientifically  con- 
ducted, but  that  essential  data  were  wanting,  and  could  only 


GENERAL   HISTORIANS  249 

be  found  in  the  Vedas  and  Avesta.  The  development  of  lan- 
guage was  another  subject  which  Freret  studied  in  a  thor- 
oughly philosophical  spirit.  He  had  a  general  knowledge  of 
many  languages  and  a  thorough  acquaintance  with  several. 
He  sought  to  classify  them  naturally,  and  to  distribute  them 
according  to  their  affiliation  into  families.  He  exposed  the  pre- 
vailing practices  of  haphazard  etymological  conjecturing,  and 
insisted  that  etymological  processes  should  be  tested  by  histor- 
ical criticism.  He  made  a  serious  study  of  Chinese,  and  is 
admitted  to  have  been  the  first  to  demonstrate  the  true  nature 
of  the  Chinese  written  language  and  of  Chinese  versification. 
There  remain  to  be  mentioned  his  dissertations  on  the  origins 
and  commingling^  of  ancient  nations,  on  the  history  of  the 
earliest  inhabitants  of  Greece,  on  the  different  primitive  peo- 
ples of  Italy,  on  the  populations  of  Northern  Europe,  on  the 
prodigies  reported  by  ancient  writers,  and  on  the  study  of 
ancient  histories  and  the  degrees  of  certitude  in  their  proofs. 
He  had,  moreover,  closely  studied  the  sources  of  French  his- 
tory ;  and  in  1714  he  read  before  the  Academy,  of  which  he 
Avas  to  be  afterwards  so  active  a  member,  an  essay  on  '  The 
Origin  of  the  Franks,'  sufficient  to  make  it  apparent  that 
the  royal  historiographer,  Father  Daniel,  was  by  no  means  so 
truly  critical  as  he  got  the  credit  of  being.  It  was  a  purely 
academic  piece  of  work,  but  on  account  of  it  Freret  was  thrown 
for  a  short  time  into  the  Bastille.  The  consequence  was  that 
his  first  contribution  to  French  history  was  also  his  last. 

The  two  general  histories  of  France  which  attained  the 
highest  place  in  popular  estimation  during  the  period  under 
consideration  were  those  of  Father  Gabriel  Daniel  and  of  Paul 
Francis  Velly.  The  former  was  published  in  three  volumes  in 
1713 ;  the  latter  was  begun  in  1755,  and  after  the  death  of  the 
author  in  1759,  by  which  time  eight  volumes  had  been  written, 
it  was  continued  by  various  hands.  Neither  Daniel  nor  Velly, 
however,  showed  remarkable  historical  talent.  It  is  doubtless 
true  that  Daniel  surpassed  his  predecessor  Mezeray  in  accuracy, 
and  made  some  meritorious  special  investigations ;  but  he  was 
really  inferior  to  Mezeray  on  the  whole.  He  distinguished 
very  imperfectly  between  the  essential  and  the  incidental  or 
even  superfluous,  between  the  important  and  the  trivial ;  he 
failed  to  follow  the  good  example  which  Mezeray  had  set  in 


250  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

trying  to  write  a  history  of  the  French  people,  and  not  merely 
of  their  rulers ;  and  he  indulged  far  too  largely  in  religious 
polemics  of  an  unenlightened  and  intolerant  kind.  He  real- 
ised the  obligations  of  the  historian  in  relation  to  the  study 
and  criticism  of  sources  much  better  than  Mezeray,  against 
whom  he  wrote  a  special  work  on  account  of  his  disregard  of 
them,  but  he  fulfilled  them  only  a  little  better  himself,  and 
often  entirely  neglected  them.  Velly  showed  himself  to  be  a 
man  of  more  modern  mind  and  speech.  He  wrote  under  the 
influence  of  the  philosophical  and  political  ideas  prevailing  in 
the  society  of  his  time,  and  sought  in  particular  to  utilise  in 
his  work  the  views  of  Montesquieu.  He  drew  still  less  than 
Daniel  from  the  original  sources ;  and  gave  his  readers  no 
correct  and  distinct,  not  to  say  vivid  or  animated,  conception 
of  the  various  epochs  of  which  he  treated. 

There  were  no  French  historians  of  the  eighteenth  century 
more  widely  popular  than  Charles  Rollin  and  Rene'  Aubert  de 
Vertot.  There  are  still  many  elderly  Frenchmen  and  even 
Englishmen  who  have  pleasant  and  grateful  recollections  of 
Rollin's  'Ancient  History 7  (1730)  and '  Roman  History '  (1739). 
Their  author  was  one  of  the  most  pious,  virtuous,  and  amiable  . 
of  men ;  singularly  ingenuous  and  unselfish ;  filled  with  a  sense 
of  the  divine  presence  and  purpose  in  the  movement  of  human 
affairs ;  anxious  not  only  to  instruct  the  minds,  but  to  improve 
the  lives,  of  his  readers.  The  charm  of  his  writings  flowed 
directly  from  the  beauty  of  his  character.  Such  simple  good- 
ness as  was  his  is  of  the  kind  which  elicits  affection,  disarms 
criticism,  and  makes  the  heart  its  partisan.  But  Rollin's 
Histories  have  lost  their  power  to  please ;  they  belong  to  a 
dead  past,  and  the  dead  has  buried  its  dead.  The  young  men 
of  the  present  day  are  little  tolerant  of  naivete  or  credulity ; 
and  probably  few  of  those  who  fifty  years  ago  read  Rollin's 
writings  with  delight  would  care  to  venture  on  doing  so  again 
lest  their  old  impressions  should  be  too  violently  disturbed. 
Rollin  was  the  last  French  historian  of  his  century  who  wrote 
secular  history  with  a  view  to  tracing  in  it  the  all-pervading 
agency  of  Providence,  the  continuous  manifestation  of  the 
wisdom,  justice,  and  goodness  of  God. 

Vertot  owed  his  reputation  to  other  qualities.     He  was 
richly  dowered  with  the  gifts  which  make  an  historical  artist. 


HISTORICAL   METHODOLOGY  251 

He  excelled  in  the  distribution  and  arrangement  of  his 
materials,  connected  events  in  a  natural  manner,  gave  free 
indulgence  to  an  easily  moved  sensibility,  and  so  touched  the 
emotions  of  his  readers.  He  possessed  a  lively  imagination, 
considerable  power  of  pictorial  and  dramatic  representation, 
and  a  remarkable  mastery  over  the  language  in  which  he 
wrote.  Such  an  author,  careful  as  he  was  to  select  for  the 
exercise  of  his  talents  the  historical  subjects  best  fitted  to 
display  them  to  advantage, — the  "revolutions  "  of  Portugal, 
of  Sweden,  of  the  Roman  Government,  &c,  — easily  succeeded 
in  gaining  immense  popularity.  But,  unfortunately,  he  was 
superficial  in  research  and  reflection,  inaccurate  and  unreliable 
in  his  statements,  apt  in  his  desire  to  present  facts  attractively, 
to  present  them  untruly.  Hence  his  works  have  fallen  into, 
perhaps,  a  deeper  oblivion  than  those  of  Rollin. 

We  may  fairly,  I  believe,  rank  three  ecclesiastical  historians 
—  the  Catholic  Fleury  and  the  Protestants  Beausobre  and 
Basnage  —  higher  in  the  scale  of  historical  merit  than  Daniel 
or  Velly,  Rollin  or  Vertot.  They  worked,  however,  in  a  field 
of  more  limited  interest ;  and  as  their  writings,  although  valu- 
able, were  in  no  respects  of  an  original  nature  or  epoch-making 
significance,  it  is  not  necessary  that  I  should  indicate  their 
characteristics. 

The  book  in  most  repute  in  the  eighteenth  century  on  the 
subject  of  historical  methodology  was  Lenglet  du  Fresnoy's 
'  Me'thode  pour  etudier  l'Histoire.'  The  first  edition  of  it  was 
published  in  1713 ;  a  second  and  much  enlarged  edition  ap- 
peared in  1729 ;  and  it  was  translated  into  Italian,  German, 
and  English.  The  author  was  a  worthy,  loyal,  and  religious 
man,  yet  he  was  five  times  imprisoned  in  the  Bastille.  He 
was  a  very  industrious  but  far  from  brilliant  writer.  The 
'  Historical  Methodology '  was  much  the  most  successful  of  his 
productions ;  it  supplied,  in  a  manner  which  was  generally 
deemed  to  be  satisfactory,  a  want  which  had  come  to  be  widely 
felt  early  in  the  eighteenth  century.  It  will  be  searched  in 
vain,  however,  for  anything  like  a  philosophical  view  of  the 
course  of  history,  or  of  any  epoch  thereof,  or  for  any  glimpses 
of  original  insight  into  the  nature  of  historical  investigation  or 
the  functions  of  historical  art ;  it  never  takes  us  much  below 
the  surface  or  away  from  the  commonplace.     Its  chief  merit 


252  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

lies  in  its  being  a  survey  of  the  whole  subject  of  historical 
method ;  if  not  the  first  systematic  Historic,  at  least  one  much 
more  systematic  than  any  which  had  previously  appeared.  It 
treats  of  the  end  or  office  of  history ;  points  out  how  geography, 
chronology,  the  knowledge  of  customs,  &c,  are  preparatory 
for,  and  auxiliary  to,  history ;  and  lays  down  precepts  for  the 
guidance  of  those  who  would  so  read  history  as  intellectually 
and  morally  to  profit  by  it  to  the  full.  There  follow  many 
pages  filled  with  remarks  on  the  histories  of  the  various  peo- 
ples, but  showing  no  special  knowledge  of  any  history  except 
that  of  France.  The  various  kinds  of  history  form  the  next 
subject  of  discourse.  The  aids  to  the  study  of  them,  and  the 
sources  whence  they  are  drawn,  are  afterwards  touched  upon. 
The  method  of  teaching  history  —  the  reasons  for  caution  in 
dealing  with  it  —  the  characteristics  of  good  and  bad  historians 
—  are  discussed.  Rules  are  laid  down  and  enforced  with  a  view 
to  guide  us  in  judging  of  historical  facts,  and  to  enable  us  to 
determine  whether  works  are  genuine  or  spurious.  Finally,  an 
attempt  is  made  to  show  in  what  way  and  to  what  extent  even 
false  reports,  spurious  and  doubtful  works,  and  prejudiced 
historians,  may  be  dealt  with  so  as  to  yield  instruction.  There 
are  appended  lists  of  historical  books  classified  according  to 
their  subject-matter,  the  countries,  provinces,  &c,  of  which 
they  treat.  These  were  doubtless  felt  to  be  very  serviceable 
at  the  time  when  the  work  appeared. 

Rollin  has  treated  of  the  study  of  history  at  considerable 
length  in  the  "third  part "  of  his  once  famous  work,  '  De  la 
maniere  d'enseigner  et  d'e'tudier  les  Belles  Lettres '  (1726-28). 
He  begins  by  showing  the  vast  importance  of  history  as  a 
means  of  enlarging  human  knowledge,  which  without  its  aid 
would  be  confined  within  extremely  narrow  limits.  He  repre- 
sents it  as  the  common  school  of  mankind  for  religious  and 
moral  instruction  and  discipline,  —  one  abounding  in  lessons  of 
warning  and  encouragement,  of  correction  and  improvement. 
He  lays  stress  on  its  function  as  a  judge,  before  whose  tribunal 
the  great  ones  of  the  earth  continually  stand,  and  hear  the 
truth  which  could  not  elsewhere  be  spoken  to  them.  He  dis- 
courses on  the  principles  according  to  which  actions  are  to  be 
judged,  and  how  true  greatness  and  goodness  in  actions  are  to 
be  discerned.    He  points  out  how  history  warns  nations  against 


HISTORICAL   SCEPTICISM  253 

vanity  and  boastfulness,  the  too  eager  pursuit  of  wealth  and  of 
external  advantages,  ambition  and  war.  Sacred  history  he 
describes  as  a  picture  of  the  divine  government  of  the  world 
and  of  the  course  of  the  education  of  the  human  race ;  and 
profane  history  as  also  essentially  religious  and  moral  in  its 
tendency  and  teaching.  He  insists  with  due  emphasis  that 
absolute  truthfulness  is  the  prime  requisite  of  history.  He 
indicates  the  importance  of  the  search  for  causes,  and  what 
care  is  needed  to  distinguish  real  from  apparent  causes ;  as  also 
the  special  claims  which  the  characters  of  great  men,  and  all 
that  relates  to  laws,  manners,  and  religion,  have  on  the  atten- 
tion of  the  historical  student.  He  attempts  to  apply  his  .prin- 
ciples to,  and  illustrate  his  precepts  by,  select  chapters  of 
sacred  and  profane  history ;  but  in  this  part  of  his  task  he  is 
not  very  successful.  As  to  Rollin,  then,  we  may  sum  up  thus : 
he  recommends  the  study  of  history  with  a  warm  and  earnest 
eloquence ;  his  reflections  on  history  are  morally  impressive 
and  religiously  edifying;  but  they  throw  no  light  on  the 
methodology  of  history. 

Historical  scepticism  appeared  in  a  very  extravagant  form 
in  the  publications  of  John  Hardouin  (1646-1729).  This 
Jesuit  Father  was  a  man  of  great  learning,  and  especially 
eminent  as  a  numismatist ;  but  he  was  of  a  very  singular 
character  of  mind  and  maintained  very  extraordinary  opinions. 
He  is  well  described  in  his  epitaph  written  by  his  friend 
De  Boze :  "  In  expectatione  judicii  hie  jacet  hominum  para- 
doxotatos,  natione  Gallus,  religione  Romanus,  orbis  literati 
portentum :  venerandse  antiquitatis  cultor  et  destructor,  docte 
febricitans,  somnia  et  inaudita  commenta  vigilans  edidit. 
Scepticum  pie  egit,  credulitate  puer,  audacia  juvenis,  deliriis 
senex."  Pere  Hardouin  had  enormous  vanity  and  ambition, 
and  the  utmost  contempt  for  the  abilities  and  views  of  other 
scholars.  He  placed  little  faith  in  books  or  documents,  but 
immense  trust  in  his  medals.  It  was  very  largely  from  medals 
that  he  sought  to  construct  the  chronology  and  history  of 
ancient  and  medieval  times.  The  ordinary  or  traditional  his- 
tory he  regarded  as  almost  entirely  the  invention  of  monks 
of  the  thirteenth  century  who  wished  to  substitute  for  Chris- 
tianity a  belief  in  fate.  These  monks,  he  held,  had  either 
entirely  or  virtually  fabricated  the  works  attributed  to  Thu- 


254  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

cydides,  Livy,  Terence,  Ovid;  and,  indeed,  all  the  so-called 
classical  writings  of  antiquity,  except  those  of  Homer  and 
Herodotus,  Cicero  and  the  elder  Pliny,  the  Georgics  of  Virgil 
and  the  Satires  and  Epistles  of  Horace.  The  chronicles  and 
documents  relating  to  the  Franks  he  likewise  pronounced  to 
be  forgeries.  These  and  suchlike  conclusions  confidently 
maintained  by  a  man  who  through  his  edition  of  the  '  Natural 
History'  of  Pliny  had  early  acquired  the  highest  reputation 
for  learning,  whose  industry  and  ingenuity  were  amazing, 
and  whose  publications  succeeded  one  another  in  an  incessant 
and  rapid  flow,  naturally  excited  agitation  and  controversy. 
His  ecclesiastical  superiors  feeling  the  faith  of  the  Church  in 
the  genuineness  and  antiquity  of  the  Scriptures  undermined 
by  his  scepticism,  compelled  him  in  1708  to  publish  a  retrac- 
tation, but  he  neither  changed  his  obnoxious  views  nor  ceased 
to  repeat  them.  All  through  the  first  quarter  of  the  eigh- 
teenth century  Hardouin's  hypotheses  were  under  dispute. 
They  were  generally  and  often  violently  condemned,  but  the 
controversies  to  which  they  gave  rise  also  made  manifest  the 
extent  to  which  scepticism  had  invaded  the  province  of 
history.  They  showed  that  not  a  few  people  were  disposed 
to  regard  the  bon  mot  ascribed  to  Fe"nelon,  "L'histoire  n'est 
qu'une  fable  convenue,"  as  an  arrow  which  nearly  hit  the 
mark.  They  helped  to  bring  into  due  prominence  questions 
as  to  historical  certitude  which  lie  at  the  basis  of  historical 
methodology :  How  far  is  historical  testimony  to  be  trusted 
at  all  ?  what  is  genuine  and  what  false  in  history,  and  how 
are  we  to  distinguish  between  them  ?  It  was  during  this 
period  that  these  questions  for  the  first  time  clearly  presented 
themselves  in  the  consciousness  of  historians.  Later  on  in 
the  century  they  became  familiar  even  to  the  common  mind. 

Of  much  greater  significance  and  influence  than  the  para- 
doxical arguments  of  Hardouin  was  the  discussion  carried  on 
during  a  series  of  years  in  the  Academy  of  Inscriptions.  It 
was  conducted  throughout  in  a  truly  scientific  spirit,  and  may 
not  unreasonably  be  held  to  mark  an  epoch  in  the  develop- 
ment of  historical  criticism. 

The  two  papers  of  Father  Anselm,  'Sur  les  monuments  qui 
ont  servi  de  Me"moires  aux  premiers  historiens,'  read  in  1720, 


DISCUSSION   IN   ACADEMY   OF   INSCRIPTIONS  255 

may  be  regarded  as  opening  the  discussion.  In  these  essays 
the  Abbd  endeavoured  to  establish  that  antiquity  had  not 
been  so  devoid  of  literary  and  other  means  of  recording 
events  as  had  been  represented,  and  that  the  most  ancient 
historians  had  based  their  narratives  on  memorials  of  various 
kinds.  The  only  merit,  however,  which  can  fairly  be  ascribed 
to  him,  is  that  of  having  seen  that  there  was  a  great  question 
as  to  historical  certitude  which  demanded  an  answer.  He 
did  not  examine  the  question  closely,  or  perceive  clearly  the 
conditions  to  be  fulfilled  by  any  one  who  would  answer  it. 
His  own  answer  to  it  is  loose  and  inconclusive. 

Much  more  important  was  the  '  Dissertation  sur  l'incerti- 
tude  de  l'histoire  des  quatre  premiers  si£cles  de  Rome,'  read 
by  M.  de  Pouilly  before  the  Acadamy  on  the  15th  December 
1722.  By  limiting  the  question  as  to  historic  certitude  to 
the  consideration  of  a  wisely  selected  special  period  of  his- 
tory, he  at  once  rendered  it  more  precise,  and  made  more 
apparent  how  vital  it  was.  As  a  general  question  the  time 
had  not  yet  come  for  its  profitable  discussion.  Controversy 
regarding  the  truth  or  falsity  of  the  story  of  the  first  four 
centuries  of  Rome  as  told  by  her  own  historians,  could  not 
fail  to  be  suggestive  and  useful.  Pouilly  was  not  the  first 
to  entertain  doubts  regarding  that  story.  Almost  with  the 
first  awakening  of  the  modern  critical  spirit  came  suspicion 
as  to  the  credibility  of  the  traditional  story  of  early  Rome. 
Lorenzo  Valla  gave  expression  to  it  in  the  fifteenth  century, 
and  Glareanus  in  the  sixteenth.  In  the  seventeenth  century 
Holland  possessed  a  school  of  learned  criticism  which  had  its 
chief  seat  at  Ley  den,  and  of  that  school  one  member,  Bochart, 
showed  that  the  traditions  as  to  iEneas  were  unhistorical ; 
another,  Gronovius,  argued  that  the  story  of  Romulus  was 
a  legend ;  and  a  third,  Perizonius,  brought  to  light  the  fre- 
quent contradictions  of  the  Roman  historians,  and  declared 
that  the  earlier  books  of  Livy  contained  traces  of  the  popular 
songs  of  primitive  Rome.  Just  in  the  year  previous  to  that 
in  which  Pouilly's  dissertation  was  read,  the  profound  and 
ingenious  Neapolitan  philosopher,  Vico,  had  begun  in  his 
'  De  Constantia  Jurisprudentis  '  to  propound  the  hypothesis 
as  to  early  Roman  history  which  he  afterwards  stated  in  a 


256  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

more  developed  form  in  the  first  edition  of  the  'Seienza 
Nuova '  (1725),  and  which  so  remarkably  anticipated  the 
conclusions  reached  by  Niebuhr,  Mommsen,  and  others  in 
the  present  century.  But  Pouilly  knew  nothing  about  Vico ; 
and  further,  his  criticism  is  merely  negative,  whereas  that 
of  Vico  was  but  a  clearing  of  the  ground  for  the  work  of 
construction.  He  begins  his  dissertation  by  laying  down  the 
general  proposition  that  ancient  history  is  so  filled  with  fic- 
tions that  all  the  annals  of  the  ancient  peoples  should  be  the 
subject  of  a  strict  criticism ;  and  then  he  undertakes  to  prove 
that  Roman  history  ought  to  be  regarded  as  uncertain  until 
the  time  of  the  wars  of  Pyrrhus.  In  doing  so  he  anticipates, 
but  expressly  denies,  the  applicability  of  the  charge  of  "  Pyr- 
rhonism," or  scepticism  in  an  unfavourable  sense;  he  merely 
refuses,  he  says,  to  assent  to  what  is  not  adequately  authenti- 
cated. The  earliest  writers  who  profess  to  give  an  account 
of  the  history  of  Rome  during  the  first  four  centuries  had  not, 
he  contends,  the  means  of  knowing  what  that  history  was. 
They  allow  it  to  appear  that  they  did  not  themselves  regard 
what  they  recounted,  to  be  certain.  They  only  worked  up 
the  traditions  and  legends  which  were  afloat  into  a  plausible 
continuous  narrative.  Their  accounts  do  not  agree.  Stories 
drawn  from  foreign  sources  have  been  incorporated  into  what 
is  described  as  native  history ;  such  events  as  the  birth, 
exposure,  and  death  of  Romulus,  the  deeds  of  the  Horatii 
and  Curiatii,  of  Curtms,  &c,  never  happened,  the  accounts 
of  them  being  merely  fictions  transplanted  from  Greece. 

The  Abbe"  Sallier  replied  in  two  discourses,  the  first  of  which, 
'  Suv  les  premiers  Monuments  historiques  des  Romains,'  was 
read  on  the  10th  of  April  1723 ;  and  the  second,  '  Sur  la  Cer- 
titude de  l'Histoire  des  quatre  premiers  siecles  de  Rome,'  on 
the  11th  of  February  1724.  In  the  former  he  maintained  that 
historical  records,  the  'Annales  Pontificum,'  '  Libri  Lintei,' 
&c,  had  been  kept  at  Rome  from  its  foundation ;  that  they 
had  survived  the  burning  of  the  city  by  the  Gauls  ;  and  that 
they  had  been  consulted  and  closely  followed  by  Fabius  and 
Cincius,  Livy  and  Dionysius,  so  that  the  extant  narratives  of 
the  two  last-named  historians  are  entitled  to  be  received  with 
respect  and  confidence.     In  other  words,  he  answered  Pouilly 


DISCUSSION  IN   ACADEMY   OF   INSCRIPTIONS  257 

in  substantially  the  same  manner  as  Wachsmuth  answered 
Niebuhr.  In  the  latter  discourse  he  argued  that  the  con- 
formity between  certain  features  of  Roman  and  Grecian 
history,  which  had  been  made  prominent  in  the  treatise  '  Of 
Greek  and  Roman  Parallels,'  ascribed  to  Plutarch,  afforded 
no  legitimate  presumption  against  the  credibility  of  the 
Roman  annals. 

M.  Fr^ret  intervened  in  the  debate  on  the  17th  March  1724, 
by  '  Reflexions  sur  l'e'tude  des  anciennes  histoires,  et  sur  le 
degre"  de  certitude  de  leurs  preuves.'  Acknowledging  that 
the  great  scholars  of  the  past  century  had  done  much  to  dispel 
the  darkness  over  ancient  history,  he  affirmed  that  much  still 
remained  to  be  done,  and  that  it  would  be  accomplished  if 
inquirers  would  lay  aside  their  preconceptions,  be  on  their 
guard  against  the  love  of  system,  start  only  from  well-ascer- 
tained particulars,  and  proceed  to  general  views  in  a  strictly 
inductive  manner.  He  has  some  admirable  pages  on  the  per- 
verting influence  of  the  spirit  of  system,  and  on  the  difference 
between  this  spirit  and  the  spirit  of  method,  the  philosophical 
spirit.  "  True  criticism,"  he  says,  "  is  nothing  else  than  the 
philosophical  spirit  applied  to  the  discussion  of  facts."  It  is 
equally  opposed  to  credulity  and  scepticism.  Credulity  has 
been  the  fault  of  previous  ages ;  scepticism  had  now  become 
the  danger.  To  avoid  both  it  is  necessary  to  have  correct 
views  of  historical  certitude  in  general,  and  of  degrees  of 
certitude.  This  is  the  subject,  accordingly,  of  which  Freret 
treats.  Historical  proofs,  he  says,  may  be  reduced  to  two 
classes  —  contemporary  testimonies  and  traditions.  The  for- 
mer are  of  various  kinds,  but  if  they  are  sufficiently  proved 
to  be  genuine,  and  their  authors  to  have  been  honest,  and  so 
circumstanced  as  to  be  able  to  know  the  truth,  they  are  ac- 
cepted by  all  reasonable  people.  Their  superiority  to  tradi- 
tions, those  popular  beliefs  which  rest  only  on  their  own 
persistence  and  prevalence,  and  cannot  be  traced  back  to  any 
contemporary  testimony,  is  denied  by  no  one.  It  is  only  tra- 
dition which  is  assailed.  And,  argues  Fre"ret,  tradition  is  not 
to  be  indiscriminately  or  wholly  rejected.  If  it  be,  we  shall 
have  little  left  us  to  believe  as  to  the  course  and  events  of  his- 
tory.    For  except  the  evidence  of  eyewitnesses  all  is  tradition 


258  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

in  history;  and  even  the  authority  of  contemporary  witnesses 
is  largely  dependent  on  tradition.  The  false  can  be  separated 
from  the  true,  the  incredible  from  the  credible,  the  more  from 
the  less  probable,  in  tradition ;  as,  indeed,  requires  to  be  done 
also  in  contemporary  written  history.  The  distinction  between 
the  two  classes  of  historical  proofs  is  not  absolute.  Testimony 
and  tradition  support  and  supplement  each  other.  Freret,  it 
seems  to  me,  does  not  in  this  part  of  his  memoir  show  his 
usual  clearness  and  independence  of  mind,  but  allows  his  judg- 
ment to  be  unduly  influenced  by  fear  of  the  consequences  which 
would  result  from  a  strict  application  of  the  rules  of  historical 
criticism  to  ancient  history.  He  concludes  by  endeavouring 
to  confirm  the  argumentation  of  the  Abbe"  Sallier  in  his  first 
discourse ;  to  prove  that  the  Romans,  like  other  ancient  peo- 
ples, had  contemporary  records,  in  the  form  of  inscriptions, 
acts,  treaties,  and  written  registers,  from  very  early  times. 

M.  de  Pouilly  returned  to  the  subject  in  his  '  Nouveaux  Es- 
sais  de  Critique  sur  la  fidelite"  de  l'Histoire,'  read  Dec.  22, 1724. 
The  general  tenor  of  his  reasoning  may  be  indicated  as  follows: 
We  must  neither  grant  to  fables  the  credit  which  they  do  not 
deserve,  nor  deny  to  facts  the  credit  which  they  merit ;  we 
must  avoid  alike  credulity  and  scepticism.  Truth  and  error 
are  closely  intermingled  in  history,  but  there  are  marks  by 
which  they  may  be  distinguished  and  separated.  The  love  of 
the  marvellous,  interest,  vanity,  party-spirit,  and  other  causes, 
are  constantly  leading  to  the  falsification  of  history.  Neither 
testimony  nor  tradition  is  to  be  received  when  they  contradict 
experience.  The  intrinsic  probability  or  improbability  of  the 
things  reported  has  always  to  be  taken  into  account.  Au- 
thentic history  rests  on  the  testimony  of  contemporaries,  proved 
to  be  such  by  the  testimony  of  later  writers ;  and  a  chain  of 
witnesses  of  this  kind  is  intrinsically  different  from,  and  im- 
mensely more  reliable  than,  a  series  of  depositories  or  trans- 
mitters of  tradition.  In  judging  of  the  credibility  of  historians 
we  have  to  take  into  account  their  circumstances,  characters, 
the  estimates  formed  of  their  fidelity  by  those  best  qualified  to 
criticise  them,  and  how  far  they  agree  with  or  contradict  what 
other  historians  of  the  same  events  have  recorded.  "  Tradition 
is  a  popular  rumour  of  which  the  origin  is  unknown  ;  an  ac- 


DISCUSSION   IN   ACADEMY   OF   INSCRIPTIONS  259 

count  of  alleged  fact  transmitted  to  us  by  a  succession  of  men 
of  which  the  first  are  beyond  our  ken  ;  a  chain  of  which  we 
hold  one  end  but  of  which  the  other  is  lost  in  the  abyss  of  the 
past.  It  is,  therefore,  essentially  different  from  history.  We 
can  judge  of  an  historical  account  by  the  character  of  its 
author:  we  can  only  judge  of  a  tradition  by  its  age,  its  ex- 
tension, and  the  nature  of  its  content."  A  late  origin  and  a 
limited  diffusion  testify  to  the  falsity  of  a  tradition ;  but  re- 
moteness of  origin  and  wide  prevalence  are  no  evidences  of  its 
truth.  By  increasing  its  volume  it  does  not  increase  its  weight. 
As  to  the  nature  of  its  content  there  are  so  many  causes  of  be- 
lieving traditions  other  than  their  truth,  and  so  many  motives 
and  influences  which  alter  and  pervert  them,  that  it  speedily 
becomes  almost  impossible  to  ascertain  whether  there  is  any 
historical  truth  in  them,  or  what  it  is.  Traditions  are  not, 
indeed,  mere  fictions ;  it  is  even  sometimes  possible  to  perceive 
in  a  vague  manner,  in  dim  outline,  the  historical  facts  out  of 
which  they  originated.  "  As  regards,  for  example,  the  early 
history  of  Rome,  there  are  several  traditions,  which,  if  reduced 
to  simple  and  general  propositions,  cannot  reasonably  be  called 
in  question.  Those  which  relate  to  the  shameful  defeat  of 
the  Romans  near  the  Caudine  Forks,  the  seditious  retreats 
of  the  populace  because  of  the  cruelty  exercised  by  the  rich 
towards  the  poor,  and  various  others,  are  instances."  But 
such  instances  are  exceptions.  It  is  seldom  that  we  can  suc- 
ceed thus  far ;  and  we  can  never  be  certain  of  the  particulars 
of  traditional  story.  The  Greek,  Jewish,  Mohammedan,  Abys- 
sinian, Irish,  Scottish,  and  other  fabulous  histories  are  referred 
to  in  proof.  The  early  history  of  Rome  is,  then,  again  main- 
tained to  be  as  a  whole  untrustworthy ;  and  the  arguments 
which  had  been  employed  by  Sallier  and  Fre"ret  to  show  that 
it  was,  on  the  contrary,  credible  history  resting  on  contempo- 
rary testimonies,  are  examined  and  rejected. 

To  this  part  of  the  communication  Sallier  replied  in  his 
'  Troisidme  Discours  sur  la  certitude  de  l'Histoire  des  quatre 
premiers  siecles  de  Rome,'  read  on  the  10th  April  1725.  It 
closed  the  discussion,  so  far  as  the  Academy  was  concerned. 

The  debate  which  I  have  thus  summarised  did  honour  to 
all  who  took  part  in  it.     Its  special  problem  was  of  the  great- 


260  PHILOSOPHY   OF  HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

est  interest  and  importance,  and  it  was  dealt  with  in  a  truly- 
critical  and  historical  spirit  alike  by  De  Pouilly  and  his  an- 
tagonists. The  former  justly  repelled  the  charge  of  historical 
Pyrrhonism  which  the  latter  brought  against  him.  It  Avas 
entirely  without  foundation.  His  "views  were  reached  on 
purely  critical  and  historical  grounds.  There  is  no  historical 
scepticism  in  demanding  that  real  and  adequate  evidence  be 
produced  for  professedly  historical  statements ;  and  this  was 
all  that  De  Pouilly  did.  But  perhaps  the  interest  and  impor- 
tance of  the  debate  lay  as  much  in  the  general  question  which 
it  brought  to  light  as  in  the  special  question  with  which  it 
directly  dealt.  It  led  to  asking  for  the  first  time  in  a  clear 
and  general  form,  How  authentic  history  is  to  be  distin- 
guished from  merely  traditional  history?  What  are  the 
conditions  of  historical  credibility,  and  the  principles  of 
historical  evidence  and  certitude  ?  It  directed  attention  to 
the  fact  that  there  must  be  a  logic  of  historical  investigation 
to  which  historians  are  bound  to  conform,  and  which  they 
require  to  discover  in  order  that  they  may  be  able  to  conform 
to  it  in  the  prosecution  of  difficult  inquiries.  It  is  on  this 
account  that  I  have  spoken  of  the  debate  as  marking  an 
epoch  in  the  progress  of  Historic. 

Louis  de  Beaufort  followed  in  the  footsteps  of  De  Pouilly. 
In  his  '  Dissertation  sur  l'incertitude  des  cinq  premiers  siecles 
de  l'Histoire  Romaine,'  which  was  published  at  Utrecht  in 
1738,  he  maintained  substantially  the  same  views  as  the 
French  Academician.  He  expounded  and  defended  them, 
however,  more  elaborately,  and  was  more  successful  in  giving 
them  currency.  In  the  preface  to  his  treatise  he  acknowl- 
edges that  the  composition  of  his  work  was  suggested  by  the 
debate  between  De  Pouilly  and  Sallier.  The  treatise  itself 
consists  of  two  parts :  the  first  being  "  an  inquiry  concerning 
the  original  records,  memorials,  treaties,  and  other  monuments 
from  which  proper  materials  could  be  drawn  for  compiling 
the  history  of  the  first  ages  of  Rome,  and  of  the  historians, 
who  compiled  it ; "  and  the  second  being  "  an  examination  of 
some  of  the  principal  events  that  are  said  to  have  happened 
during  that  period,  wherein  the  inconsistencies  of  the  his- 
tories with  one  another,  and  with  the  few  original  pieces 


BEAUFORT  261 

which  were  saved  when  Rome  was  burned  by  the  Gauls,  is 
proved." 

Mebuhr,  who  has  made  no  mention  of  De  Pouilly,  has  thus 
written  regarding  Beaufort  and  his  book :  "  Beaufort  was  in- 
genious, and  had  read  much,  though  he  was  not  a  philologer. 
One  or  two  sections  in  his  treatise  are  very  able  and  satisfac- 
tory ;  others,  on  the  contrary,  feeble  and  superficial.  Bayle 
is  the  master  whom  he  implicitly  follows  throughout ;  the 
soul  of  his  book  is  scepticism ;  he  does  nothing  but  deny  or 
upset ;  or,  if  he  ever  tries  to  build,  the  edifice  is  frail  and  un- 
tenable. Yet  the  influence  and  reputation  of  his  book  spread 
extraordinarily.  For  Roman  history  had  almost  entirely 
escaped  the  attention  and  care  of  philologers ;  those  who 
chiefly  interested  themselves  about  it,  though  not  more  than 
about  that  of  other  nations,  were  intelligent  men  of  the 
world;  and  for  their  use  it  was  at  that  time  handled  by 
several  authors,  without  pretensions  or  view  to  learning  or 
research.  Such  of  these  as  did  not  wholly  overlook  the 
earlier  centuries,  under  the  notion  that  they  were  of  no  im- 
portance, were  so  well  satisfied  with  Beaufort's  inquiry  as  to 
give  them  up  altogether." 1  In  all  respects  but  one  Niebuhr 
has  in  these  words  very  justly  appreciated  his  precursor ;  but 
in  that  one  respect  he  is  entirely  wrong.  There  is  no  evi- 
dence for  thinking  that  Beaufort  implicitly  followed  Bayle, 
or  even  followed  him  at  all.  There  is  not  a  trace  of  Bayle's 
influence,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  in  his  book.  Nor  is  there  any 
warrant  for  saying  that  "  the  soul  of  his  book  is  scepticism." 
There  is  nothing  which  can  properly  be  called  "  scepticism  " 
in  it.  It  is  simply  a  critical  investigation  which  arrives  at  a 
result  that  is  on  the  whole  negative,  —  the  conclusion  that 
the  Roman  tradition  is  for  the  most  part  merely  a  legend,  not 
authentic  history. 

The  philosophical  spirit  of  the  eighteenth  century  first 
manifested  itself  conspicuously  in  the  treatment  of  history  in 
three  works  which  appeared  at  no  great  distance  in  time  from 
one  another:  Montesquieu's  'Spirit  of  Laws,'  published  in 
1748,  Turgot's  'Discourses  at  the  Sorbonne,'  published  in 
1750,  and  Voltaire's  'Essay  on  the  Manners  and  Spirit  of 
Nations,'  published  in  1756.     Montesquieu,  Turgot,  and  Vol- 

1  History  of  Rome,  preface,  p.  7  (Eng.  tr.). 


262  PHILOSOPHY'  OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

taire  were  the  chief  initiators  of  the  reflective  or  philosophical 
study  of  history  which  now  prevails.  It  is  therefore  incum- 
bent on  me  to  consider  what  these  three  remarkable  men 
accomplished  in  this  connection. 

II 

Charles  Louis  de  Seeondat,  Baron  de  Montesquieu,  was 
born  at  La  Br&de,  near  Bordeaux,  on  the  18th  of  January 
1689. 1  In  the  twenty-fifth  year  of  his  age  he  became  a 
councillor  in  the  parliament  of  Bordeaux,  and  two  years  later 
chief-justice  (president  d  mortier).  After  holding  the  latter 
office  for  two  years  he  resigned,  in  order  to  devote  himself 
entirely  to  study  and  literature.  The  law  of  France  was  at 
that  time  so  irrational,  and  even  brutal,  that  a  wise  and 
humane  man  like  Montesquieu  must  have  often  felt  the 
administration  of  it  hateful;  yet  his  practical  experience  as 
a  legislator  and  judge  was  doubtless  admirable  preparation 
for  the  literary  work  which  he  was  to  accomplish.  He  at 
first  occupied  himself  chiefly  with  subjects  belonging  to 
physics  and  natural  science,  and  by  1719  he  had  sketched  'A 
History  of  the  Earth. '  It  was  well  that  he  abandoned  this 
too  ambitious  scheme;  but  the  conception  of  it  did  him 
honour,  and  the  labour  spent  on  it  must  have  been  advan- 
tageous to  the  'Spirit  of  Laws.' 

At  the  age  of  thirty-two  he  published  the  'Lettres  Per- 
sanes  ' :  "ce  livre  si  frivole  et  si  aise"  a  faire,"  as  Voltaire 

1  As  to  the  biography  of  Montesquieu  and  the  bibliography  of  his  writings  and 
of  writings  regarding  him,  Vian's  (L.)  '  Histoire  de  Montesquieu '  (1878)  is  indis- 
pensable. M.  Brunetiere's  severe  criticism  of  the  work,  however,  is  not  essentially 
unjust  (Rev.  d.  Deux  Mondes,  1879).  Compare  Caro,  'La  Fin  du  dix-huitieme 
siecle,'  torn.  i.  ch.  2.  Bersot  and  Damiron  have  treated  of  Montesquieu's  general 
philosophy.  Lerminier,  Heron,  Bluntschli,  and  Janet  have  expounded  his  legal 
and  political  philosophy.  Auguste  Comte  and  Sir  O.  C.  Lewis  have  made  some 
most  valuable  remarks  on  his  historical  views,  by  which  I  have  endeavoured 
to  profit.  Villemain,  Sainte-Beuve,  Nisard,  and  many  others,  have  sought  to 
delineate  his  personal  and  literary  character.  The  best  edition  of  his  works  is 
Laboulaye's  in  7  vols.,  1873-79.  M.  Albert  Sorel's  'Montesquieu'  (1887)  is  an 
excellent  general  monograph.  Of  the  '  Deux  Opuscules  de  Montesquieu,  publics 
par  M.  le  Baron  de  Montesquieu '  (1891) ,  the  first,  '  Reflections  sur  la  monarchie 
universelle  en  Europe,'  which  was  printed  in  1725,  but  withheld  from  publication, 
contains  in  germ  a  considerable  number  of  the  ideas  which  attained  maturity  in 
'  L'Esprit  des  Lois.'  Baron  de  Montesquieu  has  since  published  '  Melanges  inedits 
de  Montesquieu,'  1892. 


MONTESQUIEU  263 

has  unjustly  said;  "ce  livre,  si  fort,  le"ger  en  apparence, 
d'une  gaietd  habile  et  profonde'ment  calcul^e,"  as  Michelet 
has  truthfully  characterised  it.  It  at  once  placed  its  author 
in  the  first  rank  of  the  French  writers  of  the  age,  and  made 
him  famous  throughout  Europe.  It  had  the  appearance  of 
an  ornamental  plaything  meant  merely  to  sparkle  and  please, 
but  it  was  in  reality  a  terrible  weapon  skilfully  contrived  to 
give  deep  and  incurable  wounds  to  foes  who  could  not  other- 
wise be  attacked,  or  only  ineffectually.  It  satirised  with 
consummate  art  both  the  Orient  and  France,  their  civil  and 
spiritual  governments,  their  authorities  and  traditions,  their 
follies  and  vices.  At  the  same  time,  it  was  a  book  essentially 
sound  and  true  in  spirit,  ethical  and  constructive  in  purpose. 
It  gave  evidence  of  a  singular  faculty  for  the  description  and 
analysis  of  social  life,  habits,  and  motives.  Many  of  the 
views  afterwards  developed  in  the  'Esprit  des  Lois  '  already 
found  expression  in  the  'Lettres  Persanes.' 

Montesquieu  sketched  the  plan  of  the  former  of  these 
works  as  early  as  1724 ;  and  after  admission  into  the  Academy 
in  1728,  he  went  abroad  for  several  years,  and  visited  Ger- 
many, Hungary,  Italy,  Switzerland,  Holland,  and  England, 
in  order  to  become  acquainted  with  their  manners  and  insti- 
tutions. His  residence  in  England  lasted  from  October 
1729  to  August  1731.  In  1734  he  published  his  'Considera- 
tions sur  la  grandeur  et  la  decadence  des  Romains.'  This 
work  may  perhaps  be  regarded  as  a  section  of  the  'Esprit  des 
Lois, '  detached  from  it  on  account  of  its  length ;  but  it  forms 
of  itself  so  perfect  a  whole,  and  has  such  speciality  of  char- 
acter, that  its  separate  publication  was  certainly  appropriate. 
It  is  the  only  strictly  historical  work  of  Montesquieu  which 
we  possess,  seeing  that  the  'Histoire  de  Louis  XL,'  if  ever 
completed,  or  not  burned,  has  at  least  not  yet  been  found. 
And  it  was  also  the  first  work  in  which  a  sustained  and  com- 
prehensive attempt  was  made  to  show  how  the  events  and  1 
course  of  history  have  been  determined  by  general  physical 
and  moral  causes.  It  is  even  at  the  present  day  one  of  the 
most  remarkable  of  the  numerous  studies  to  which  the  sur- 
passing interest  of  Roman  history  has  given  rise.  Its  origi- 
nality as  regards  all  that  had  been  previously  written  on  the 


264  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

same  subject  must  be  obvious  to  every  competently  informed 
person.  One  may  well  contrast,  but  one  cannot  reasonably 
compare,  it  with  what  Machiavelli  and  Vico  taught  as  to 
the  story  of  Rome.  Saint-Evremond  and  Saint-Re'al  may 
have  suggested  a  few  of  the  views  which  it  contains,  but 
they  just  as  likely  did  not,  and  they  had  at  the  most  only 
few  to  give.  Bossuet's  grand  sketch  may  be  even  more 
admirable  in  its  kind  than  that  of  Montesquieu,  but  it  is  of 
an  essentially  different  kind,  being  taken  from  a  point  of 
view  not  within  but  above  history.  Of  course,  in  the  pres- 
ent state  of  our  knowledge  neither  all  the  statements  as  to 
fact,  nor  all  the  explanations,  in  the  'Considerations'  can  be 
accepted;  but  were  the  particular  faults  of  the  work  much 
more  numerous  and  serious  than  they  are,  it  would  still  have 
to  be  accounted  a  production  of  rare  historical  merit  and 
value. 

Sixteen  years  elapsed,  and  the  'Esprit  des  Lois'  appeared. 
It  bore  on  its  front  a  claim  to  originality  in  the  epigraph: 
"Prolem  sine  matre  creatam."  The  secret  of  its  formation 
was  disclosed  in  these  words  of  its  preface:  "I  have  many 
times  begun,  and  as  often  abandoned  this  work.  I  have  a 
thousand  times  cast  to  the  winds  the  leaves  which  I  had 
written;  I  have  often  felt  my  paternal  hands  fall.  I  have 
followed  my  object  without  forming  a  plan ;  I  have  known 
neither  rules  nor  exceptions ;  I  have  found  the  truth  only  to 
lose  it  again.  But  when  I  once  discovered  my  principles, 
everything  I  sought  for  came  to  me;  and  in  the  course  of 
twenty  years,  I  have  seen  my  work  begun,  growing  up, 
advancing  towards  completion,  and  finished."  His  twenty 
years  of  labours  were  justified  and  rewarded  by  the  result. 
The  'Spirit  of  Laws  '  not  only  enjoyed  an  immediate  popu- 
larity which  carried  it  through  twenty-one  editions  in  eigh- 
teen months,  not  only  exerted  a  vast  and  beneficial  practical 
influence,  but  will  always  retain,  owing  to  the  comprehen- 
siveness, penetration,  and  ingenuity  of  the  treatment  of  its 
great  theme,  a  distinguished  place  among  the  few  works 
which  have  advanced  most  the  most  difficult  of  sciences. 

It  did  not,  however,  escape  unjust  criticism  and  bigoted 
hostility,  which  called  forth  from  Montesquieu  the  brilliant 


MONTESQUIEU  265 

and  ironical  'Defense  de  1' Esprit  des  Lois,'  published  in 
1750.  He  wrote  little  of  importance  after  this.  His  death 
occurred  at  Paris  on  the  10th  of  February  1755. 

He  was  a  man  of  shrewd  practical  sense,  of  social  tact,  and 
of  well-regulated  life,  although  not  of  untainted  imagination  ; 
neither  vain  nor  anxious  for  glory,  but  not  without  aristo- 
cratic pride,  a  keen  eye  to  his  own  interest,  and  the  full 
consciousness  of  his  own  worth  and  ability;  honourable, 
considerate  of  the  feelings  of  others,  and  charitable.  His 
love  of  liberty  and  justice  was  at  once  ardent  and  enlightened. 
His  intellect  was  alike  vigorous  and  alert,  comprehensive 
and  intense,  indefatigable  in  seeking  the  satisfaction  of  a 
boundless  curiosity,  and  tenacious  in  the  prosecution  of  a 
distant  aim.  He  was  not  less  eminent  as  a  literary  artist 
than  as  a  scientist. 

There  has  been  much  discussion  as  to  his  originality.  I 
believe  him  to  have  been  highly  endowed  with  that  most  val- 
uable sort  of  originality  which  enables  a  man  to  draw  with 
independence  from  the  most  varied  sources,  and  to  use  what 
he  obtains  according  to  a  plan  and  principles  and  for  a  purpose 
of  his  own,  —  the  originality  of  Aristotle  and  Adam  Smith. 
He  has  been  suspected  to  have  owed  much  to  Vico,  and  to 
have  concealed  his  obligations.  The  suspicion  only  proves 
that  those  who  entertained  it  had  little  knowledge  of  either 
author.  Montesquieu  may  possibly  have  read  Vico's  work. 
Although  a  conjecture  unsupported  by  any  positive  evidence, 
it  is  not  an  improbable  conjecture,  that  the  'Scienza  Nuova' 
came  into  his  hands  when  he  was  in  Italy,  or  that  he  learned 
to  know  it  at  a  later  date  through  his  friend  the  Abbe'  de 
Guasco.  But  if  he  ever  read  it,  the  impression  which  it 
produced  on  him  must  have  been  almost  confined  to  one  point. 
His  most  serious  defects  are  just  those  which  a  careful  study 
of  Vico  might  have  removed.  The  thoughts  which  give 
Vico  a  place  of  special  and  signal  honour  in  the  history  of 
science,  if  ever  known  to  Montesquieu,  were  not  appreciated 
by  him,  and  have  produced  no  effect  on  his  writings.  Sub- 
stantially the  whole  argument  for  his  indebtedness  to  the 
great  Neapolitan  rests  on  the  circumstance  that  he  was  pre- 
ceded by  him  in  distinguishing  from  the  form  of  government 


266  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOEY   IN   FftANCE 

the  fact  which  gives  it  birth  and  the  principle  which  gives  it 
force.  This  anticipation  of  the  theory  of  the  one  thinker  by 
the  other  is  indubitable  and  remarkable,  and  Vico  is  entitled 
to  whatever  honour  may  be  involved  in  it,  but  it  is  no  proof 
of  dependence  or  plagiarism  on  the  part  of  Montesquieu. 
The  range  of  his  obligations  was,  however,  very  wide, 
including  the  classical  writers,  the  Protestant  pamphleteers 
of  the  sixteenth  century,  such  as  Hotman,  Languet,  &c, 
Bodin,  Charron,  Machiavelli  and  Gravina,  Descartes  and 
several  of  his  school,  Locke  and  other  English  writers  par- 
ticularly on  politics,  physicists,  travellers,  &c. 

The  title  of  Montesquieu's  magnum  opus  expresses  well  its 
central  and  pervading  conception.  The  work  is  an  attempt 
to  discover  the  spirit  of  laws;  to  explain  them;  to  trace  how 
they  are  related  to  manners,  climates,  creeds,  and  forms  of 
government.  It  is  an  attempt  to  view  them  in  all  lights  in 
which  they  can  be  viewed,  so  as  to  show  how  they  arise; 
how  tbey  are  modified;  how  they  act  on  private  character, 
on  domestic  life,  on  social  forms  and  institutions ;  and,  in  a 
word,  so  as  to  elicit  their  full  meaning.  This  conception,  it 
will  be  observed,  is  entirely  different  from  that  of  Bossuet. 
He  took  a  theological  doctrine  to  begin  with,  and  tried  to 
show  how  all  history  had  been  the  exemplification  of  it.  He 
started,  that  is  to  say,  with  a  doctrine  which  he  had  not 
derived  from  history;  and  that  doctrine  he  introduced  into 
history  as  a  principle  of  explanation.  It  is  quite  otherwise 
with  Montesquieu.  He  assumes  no  doctrine  extraneous  to 
history,  but  begins  with  the  facts  of  history  themselves,  with 
the  positive  laws  which  either  are  or  have  been  on  the  earth. 
He  seeks  merely  to  account  for  these  laws  as  so  many  histori- 
cal facts.  The  difference  between  these  two  conceptions  is 
very  great ;  and  obviously,  so  far  as  science  is  concerned,  that 
of  Montesquieu  is  far  in  advance  of  that  of  Bossuet.  Scien- 
tifically, the  method  of  Bossuet  is  radically  wrong;  that  of 
Montesquieu  is  good  so  far  as  it  goes. 

But  how  has  Montesquieu  elaborated  and  applied  his  con- 
ception? He  has  done  so  in  various  respects,  with  great 
success  and  ability.  He  had  a  genuine  love  of  history  for 
its  own  sake,  and  a  singularly  keen  historic  insight;  he  had 


MONTESQUIEU  267 

a  calm,  unprejudiced,  fair  mind;  he  was  distinguished  by  a 
liberality  and  moderation  of  feeling  and  judgment,  which, 
while  it  did  not  exclude  a  true  though  tempered  zeal  for 
human  good,  gave  him  the  breadth,  and  steadiness,  and  dis- 
passionate clearness  of  view  which  his  subject  demanded. 
No  one  is  less  chargeable  than  Montesquieu  with  what  was 
a  common  fault  among  his  contemporaries,  one-sidedness, 
philosophical  sectarianism,  perversion  of  social  facts  from 
contempt  of  them  or  to  serve  a  party  purpose.  He  has 
accordingly  arrived  at  least  at  approximate  explanations  of  a 
host  of  social  phenomena. 

There  lay,  however,  a  danger  before  Montesquieu  which 
he  has  not  safely  escaped,  a  difficulty  which  he  has  not  over- 
come. It  was  that  of  looking  on  laws  too  much  as  isolated 
facts,  as  independent  phenomena,  as  stationary  and  complete  | 
existences.  It  was  that  of  ignoring  the  relation  not  only  of 
one  law  to  another,  but  of  one  stage  of  law  to  another,  and  of 
the  relation  of  each  stage  and  system  of  law  to  coexistent 
and  contemporaneous  stages  and  systems  of  religion,  art, 
science,  and  industry.  Social  phenomena  such  as  laws  are, 
cannot  be  explained  like  the  merely  physical  phenomena  of 
natural  philosophy  and  chemistry.  The  most  distinctive 
characteristics  which  they  possess  lie  in  their  capacities  of 
continuous  evolution  or  development ;  and  it  is  only  by  the 
study  of  their  evolution,  by  the  comparison  of  their  consecu- 
tive states,  and  of  each  state  with  the  coexisting  general 
conditions  of  society,  that  we  can  rationally  hope  to  reach 
an  adequate  knowledge  of  their  laws.  It  is  here  that  we  find 
the  chief  weakness  of  Montesquieu. 

He  was  most  industrious  in  the  collection  of  facts,  and  he 
had  a  quite  marvellous  quickness  and  keenness  of  intuition 
into  the  meaning  of  them,  but  he  had  no  appropriate  scien- 
tific method,  no  definite  notion  of  the  modifications  of  the 
inductive  process  which  the  peculiarities  of  historical  phe- 
nomena render  necessary.  He  made  little  use,  no  systematic 
use,  of  what  is,  however,  far  excellence,  the  expedient  of  his- 
torical philosophy,  the  comparison  of  coexistent  and  consecu- 
tive social  states.  He  paid  always  little  attention,  generally 
none,  to  the  chronology  of  his  facts,  which  is,  however,  the 


268  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FKANCB 

indispensable  condition  of  their  comparison.  The  reason 
was  that  he  did  not  perceive  the  importance  of  comparing 
them,  of  following  them  through  the  whole  course  of  their 
evolution;  but  this  is  only  saying  in  other  words  that  he 
attempted  to  construct  a  science  without  availing  himself  of 
the  only  method  by  which  it  could  be  done.  It  would  be 
unjust,  however,  to  censure  severely  this  error  of  Montes- 
quieu, although  it  is  fatal  to  his  system  as  a  complete 
explanation  of  the  class  of  social  phenomena  with  which  it 
deals;  for  while  true  that  Bodin  had  on  this  fundamental 
point  more  comprehensive  and  philosophic  views,  we  may 
well  excuse  any  man  of  the  eighteenth  century  for  ignorance 
the  most  entire  of  the  science  of  comparative  legislations, 
which,  like  the  comparative  study  of  religions,  is  a  creation 
of  the  nineteenth  century. 

Devoid  of  a  true  method  of  investigation,  Montesquieu 
could  not,  except  by  chance,  discover  the  general  laws  which 
[connect  social  facts.  The  laws  of  history  are  laws  of  devel- 
opment, and  if  we  ignore  the  development  of  any  fact,  we 
Jean  never  discover  the  law  according  to  which  it  has  come  to 
be  what  it  is.  What  then  has  Montesquieu  discovered? 
Not  the  general  laws  of  the  facts,  but  certain  special  reasons 
of  them.  That  was  to  a  considerable  degree  possible  to  him, 
notwithstanding  the  neglect  of  the  distinctive  characteristics 
of  social  phenomena.  Where  a  general  law  could  not  be 
reached,  an  intellect  so  keen  in  its  intuitions  might  still 
detect  a  force  or  forces  in  which  some  given  law  or  custom 
had  its  origin ;  and  this  was  what  Montesquieu  had  a  rare 
degree  of  success  in  doing.  His  quickness  of  perception,  his 
suggestiveness  of  thought,  his  intimate  acquaintance  with 
the  working  of  human  motives,  and  the  extent  of  his  reading 
in  history,  travels,  and  natural  science,  gave  him  a  quite 
marvellous  power  of  conjecture,  and  enabled  him  to  arrive  at 
approximate  explanations  of  social  usages  and  laws  in  a  vast 
number  of  cases  where  another  man  would  have  been  help- 
less. Still  no  faculty  of  guessing,  however  extraordinary 
and  felicitous,  can  supply  the  place  of  scientific  method,  or 
elicit  much  historical  philosophy  not  of  the  humblest  kind. 
And  although  it  may  happen  to  be,  as  it  was  in  Montesquieu, 


MONTESQUIEU  269 

fertile  in  a  kind  of  truths,  it  can  hardly  fail  to  be  fertile  also 
in  illusions.  If  it  often  seize  a  verity,  it  will  often  likewise 
impose  on  itself  a  fancy.  It  is  only  a  sound  method  which 
is  competent  to  the  uniform  and  consistent  discrimination  of 
truth  from  error.  This  is  fully  exemplified  in  the  case  of 
Montesquieu,  no  serious  student  of  whose  work  will  deny 
that  it  abounds  in  false  as  well  as  in  correct  generalisations. 
It  is  rich  in  truths,  yet  crowded  with  errors.  It  is  scarcely 
more  exuberant  in  the  one  respect  than  in  the  other. 

The  want  of  a  scientific  method  of  investigation  is  also 
the  source  of  the  confused  arrangement,  the  structural  dis- 
order, of  the  book.  There  are,  it  is  true,  those  who  have  not 
recognised  this  defect,  who  have  even  denied  that  it  exists, 
and  praised  the  plan  as  simple  and  grand;  but  this  only 
proves  that  they  have  studied  it  superficially.  There  is  an 
outward  order  of  a  loose  kind,  and  an  imposing  appearance 
of  order;  but  all  the  order  there  is,  is  of  the  outward  and 
surface  kind,  while  the  confusion  is  internal,  and  so  all-per- 
vading that  examination  finds  no  end  to  it.  Thoughts  are 
juxtaposited  not  organically  connected, because  they  have  been 
amassed  merely  by  industrious  collection  and  fertility  of  sug- 
gestion, and  not  elicited  and  collected  by  scientific  method. 

The  same  want,  and  the  consequent  dealing  with  laws  and 
customs  as  isolated  and  fragmentary  phenomena,  and  refer- 
ence of  them  to  particular  causes  not  to  general  laws,  have 
exposed  Montesquieu  to  the  commonest  charge  brought 
against  him,  —  that  of  confounding  fact  with  right,  the 
explanation  of  a  thing  with  its  justification.  This  charge 
has  been  often  expressed  in  an  exaggerated  way.  Perhaps  it 
should  even,  on  the  whole,  be  held  unproved,  and  Montes- 
quieu absolved.  It  is  certainly  not  applicable  to  him  in  the 
same  degree  as  to  Aristotle,  or,  to  take  a  modern  name,  Mr. 
Buckle.  The  frequently  recurring  phrase  "ought  to  be  "  is 
ambiguous  and  objectionable ;  it  is,  however,  almost  certainly 
meant  to  express  not  a  moral  or  rational  necessity,  but  only 
that  sort  of  actual  necessity  which  there  always  is  between  a 
cause  and  its  consequence.  His  mode  of  investigation,  how- 
ever, tended  towards  the  serious  confusion  imputed  to  him, 
and  he  has  undoubtedly  on  several  occasions  been  far  from 


270  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

sufficiently  careful  to  guard  himself  from  the  suspicion  of 
having  fallen  into  it. 

The  subject  of  Montesquieu's  book  being  laws,  he  very 
properly  begins  with  two  chapters  of  general  considerations 
on  the  nature  of  laws.  But,  unfortunately,  these  two  chap- 
ters, although  they  have  been  repeatedly  eulogised  beyond 
measure,  are  by  no  means  satisfactory.  The  language  of 
them  is  so  vague  as  to  apply,  when  it  does  apply,  not  only  to 
all  kinds  of  laws,  physical  and  moral,  natural  and  positive, 
proper  and  metaphorical,  but  to  many  things  which  never  go 
even  by  that  name.  There  is  no  attempt  to  disentangle  the 
perplexing  ambiguities  of  the  term  law;,  no  attempt  to  dis- 
tinguish and  define  the  different  kinds  of  laws.  And  under- 
lying this  confusion  there  is,  in  particular,  the  vaguest  and 
even  an  erroneous  conception  of  the  nature  of  an  inductive 
law.  These  two  chapters  show,  what  the  whole  treatise 
confirms,  that  Montesquieu  had  no  clear  or  correct  conception 
of  what  such  a  law  is. 

To  those  who  have  never  tried  to  trace  the  history  of 
ideas  this  may  seem  incredible ;  to  those  who  have,  it  will  be 
in  no  wise  strange.  A  distinct,  consciously  realised  notion 
of  law  in  its  present  scientific  acceptation  was  unknown  to 
Greece,  Rome,  or  the  middle  ages.  Of  the  seven  meanings 
which  Aristotle  attributes  to  the  word  principle,  not  one 
answers  to  the  modern  scientific  signification  of  law ;  and  of 
the  thirty  terms  defined  in  the  fourth  book  of  his  'Meta- 
physics, '  which  is  a  sort  of  philosophical  glossary,  law  does 
not  occur.  Law  was  thought  of  by  the  ancients  as  a  type 
or  idea  with  something  external  corresponding  to  it.  And 
Montesquieu's  thought  was  no  closer,  no  more  definite,  than 
that  laws  were  "  the  necessary  relations  which  arise  out  of 
the  nature  of  things."  A  metaphysician  or  theologian  may 
be  satisfied  with  that,  but  certainly  no  student  of  inductive 
science,  physical,  psychical,  or  social. 

Notwithstanding  the  defects  indicated,  it  must  be  admitted 
that  these  two  chapters  have  the  great  merit  of  insisting  that 
social  institutions  and  regulations  are  properly  no  mere  arbi- 
trary inventions,  but  ought  to  rest  on  reason,  on  the  nature  of 
things',  that  there  are  relations  of  equity  which  human  legis- 
lation does  not  create  but  presuppose ;  that,  varied  as  are  the 


MONTESQUIEU  271 

forms  which  society  assumes,  they  all  originate  in  and  are 
pervaded  by  the  principles  of  a  human  nature  common  to  all 
men.  They  have  the  farther  merit  that  along  with  this 
recognition  of  fundamental  unity  there  is  the  clearest  recog- 
nition likewise  of  superstructural  variety,  and  of  the  neces- 
sity of  laws  being  adapted  to  the  distinctive  peculiarities  of 
each  nation  and  age,  these  peculiarities  being,  in  the  opinion 
of  Montesquieu,  of  such  decisive  importance  that  the  laws 
which  are  good  for  one  people  will  rarely  suit  another.  He 
thus  separates  himself  on  the  one  hand  from  the  empty 
abstract  theorist,  and  on  the  other  from  the  rude  literal 
empiricist,  and  seeks  the  golden  mean  of  political  wisdom. 

By  the  spirit  of  a  law,  Montesquieu  means  the  whole  of 
the  relations  in  which  that  law  originates  and  exists.  A 
most  important  order  of  these  relations  comprises  those  in 
which  laws  stand  to  the  various  kinds  of  governments ;  and 
this  order  of  relations  is  the  general  subject  of  not  fewer  than 
nine  books,  besides  being  frequently  returned  to  in  others. 
Montesquieu  divides  governments  into  monarchies,  in  which 
a  single  person  governs  by  fixed  laws ;  despotisms,  in  which 
a  single  person  governs  according  to  his  own  will;  and 
republics,  in  which  the  sovereign  power  is  in  several  hands, 
being  a  democracy  when  the  nation  as  a  whole  possesses  it, 
and  an  aristocracy  when  only  a  part  thereof  shares  in  it.  He 
endeavours  to  characterise  these  various  governments,  to  dis- 
cover their  principles  or  motive  forces,  and  to  show  what 
laws  flow  from  their  respective  natures,  what  are  the  sources 
of  their  strength  and  weakness,  the  systems  of  education 
most  suitable  to  them,  and  the  causes  of  corruption  most 
powerful  in  them ;  and  how  with  the  variations  of  their  re- 
spective genius,  the  civil  and  criminal  codes,  sumptuary  laws 
and  laws  relative  to  women,  and  the  military  arrangements 
both  for  offensive  and  defensive  Avar,  must  likewise  vary.  In 
doing  so  he  arrives  at  a  large  number  of  consequences,  often 
very  remote  and  heterogeneous  consequences,  which  he  ex- 
presses mostly  in  the  form  of  general  and  absolute  proposi- 
tions.   Probably  as  many  of  these  propositions  are  false  as  true. 

But  there  is  in  this  part  of  the  work  a  still  greater  defect 
than  the  commingling  of  true  and  false  conclusions :  that,  in 
fact,   which   is  its  source,  —  the  blending  and  consequent 


272  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

confusing  of  two  methods.  If  we  wish  to  ascertain  the 
character  and  consequences  of  monarchy,  for  example,  we 
may  proceed  in  our  search  either  by  induction  or  deduction. 
In  the  former  case  we  endeavour  from  an  examination  of  all 
monarchies  to  generalise  what  is  common  to  them  in  virtue 
exclusively  of  being  monarchies.  In  the  latter  case  we  start 
from  a  definition  which  embodies  what  we  suppose  to  be  the 
distinctive  nature  of  monarchy,  and  logically  evolve  what  it 
implies.  If  in  the  former  case  the  induction  be  sufficiently 
extensive  and  careful,  and  if  in  the  latter  the  presupposition 
involved  in  the  definition  be  warranted  and  the  deduction 
rigorous,  the  results  of  the  two  methods  should  so  coincide  as 
to  afford  mutual  verification;  but  in  order  to  this  the  two 
processes  must  be  kept  separate  and  distinct  —  inductions 
must  not  be  passed  off  as  deductions,  nor  vice  versd  ;  the  ideal 
and  the  empirical  must  not  be  allowed  to  coalesce  until  they 
meet  at  the  definitive  point  of  union,  —  in  essential  reality. 
If  Montesquieu  had  either  done  so,  or  adhered  strictly  to 
either  method,  he  would  certainly  never  have  arrived  at  so 
many  general  theorems.  With  every  extension  of  his  in- 
ductive basis,  and  every  effort  at  rigid  verification,  he  would 
have  found  many  of  them  drop  away,  and  learned  that  it  was 
an  extremely  difficult  task  to  detect  the  characteristics  which 
are  the  pure  results  of  the  form  of  government.  With  a 
clear  consciousness  that  the  greater  part  of  his  reasoning  was 
deduction  from  hypothetical  premisses ;  and  that  consequently 
his  inferences,  however  correctly  drawn,  had  only  logical  and 
not  actual  validity,  except  in  so  far  as  the  hypotheses  assumed 
were  in  accordance  with  fact,  he  would  have  felt  bound 
strictly  to  inquire  whether  they  were  so  or  not,  and  would 
probably  have  speedily  perceived  that  monarchies,  despotisms, 
and  republics,  as  defined  by  him,  had  merely  an  ideal  exist- 
ence—  that  his  definitions,  and  the  classification  on  which 
they  rested,  had  nothing  either  in  the  history  of  the  past  or 
present  corresponding  to  them  otherwise  than  most  remotely. 
It  was  because  he  kept  neither  to  induction  nor  deduction, 
but  passed  from  the  one  process  to  the  other,  or  mixed  up  the 
one  with  the  other  in  an  illegitimate  way,  that  conclusions 
came  to  him  so  easily.  It  was  thus  that  he  was  able,  on  the 
one  hand,  to  believe  himself  to  be  extracting  and  concentrat- 


MONTESQUIEU  273 

ing  the  legislative  experience  of  mankind  in  his  descriptions, 
when  he  was  merely  making  affirmations  about  abstractions ; 
and,  on  the  other  hand,  to  raise  narrow  empirical  generalisa- 
tions almost  to  the  level  of  necessary  truths,  so  that  the 
peculiarities  of  the  French  monarchy  are  transformed  into 
essential  attributes  of  monarchy,  the  peculiarities  of  the 
oriental  despotisms  into  universal  attributes  of  despotism, 
and  the  peculiarities  of  the  Greek  republics  into  universal 
attributes  of  republicanism. 

While  Montesquieu  treated  of  governments  in  their  own 
natures  and  in  their  relations  to  one  another,  he  did  not,  like 
Aristotle  and  Bodin,  endeavour  to  trace  their  revolutions  and 
transformations.     He  propounded  no  theory  of  the  general  . 
movement  of  humanity,  nor  attempted  any  survey  of  the  \ 
course  of  universal  history. 

The  relation  of  laws  to  liberty  as  regards  the  political 
constitution,  the  security  of  the  citizen,  and  taxation,  is  the 
subject  of  the  eleventh,  twelfth,  and  thirteenth  books.  They 
are  all  celebrated,  and  especially  the  eleventh,  owing  to  its 
application  of  the  theory  of  the  three  powers — legislative, 
executive,  and  judiciary  —  to  the  explanation  of  the  constitu- 
tion of  England,  and  owing  to  its  eulogy  of  that  constitution. 
The  general  theory  of  the  three  powers  was  derived  by  both 
Locke  and  Montesquieu  from  Aristotle.  The  application  of 
it  made  by  Montesquieu  may  have  been  suggested  by  Locke's 
'Second  Treatise  concerning  Government,'  and  the  party 
pamphlets  of  the  Whigs  and  Tories  under  George  II. ;  but 
it  had  not  been  explicitly  made  by  Locke,  nor  has  it  been 
shown  to  have  been  so  made  by  any  of  the  English  Whig  or 
Tory  pamphleteers.  The  view  of  H.  Jansen  (Montesquieu's 
'Theory  von  der  Dreitheilung  der  Gewalten  im  Staate, '  p. 
26),  that  its  source  was  Swift's  'Discourse  of  the  Contests 
and  Dissensions  between  the  Nobles  and  the  Commons  in 
Athens  and  Rome '  (Swift's  Works,  vol.  iii.,  ed.  1814),  is 
altogether  erroneous.  Montesquieu  never  claimed  originality 
for  his  ideas  as  to  the  British  constitution,  but  it  was  attrib- 
uted to  them,  without  denial  or  discussion,  both  by  Conti- 
nental and  British  writers.  Blackstone  in  his '  Commentaries  ' 
(1765),  and  still  more  De  Lolme  in  his  'Constitution  of 
England'  (1775),  developed  them  into  what  continued  to  be 


274  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOBY   IN   FRANCE 

until  recently  the  accepted  theory  of  English  constitution- 
alism. 

Montesquieu's  eulogy  of  the  British  constitution  has  often 
i;  been  misunderstood  and  misrepresented.     It  referred  only  to 
its  relation  to  political  liberty;  to  the  provision  made  by  it 
['for  security  under  the  law.     Montesquieu  had  a  very  unfa- 
I  vourable  opinion  of  British  political  virtue,  honour,  and  re- 
.  gard  to  equality.     There  is  no  warrant  for  supposing  that  he 
imagined  that  even  political  liberty  could  be  gained  by  simply 
manipulating  the  political  constitution.     He  would  have  been 
most  inconsistent  if  he  had  taught,  either  expressly  or  implic- 
itly, that  the  transference  of  the  constitution  of  England  to 
France  would  be  an  adequate  remedy  for  the  evils  of  the  latter 
country.     It  was  of  the  very  essence  of  his  juridical  and 
political  doctrine  that  positive  institutions  and  laws  are  far 
more  the  effects  of  a  nation's  character  than  its  causes,  and 
that  it  is  vain  to  expect  any  good  from  transplanting  the  laws 
and  institutions  of  one  nation  to  another  differing  from  it  in 
race,  mental  and  moral  qualities,  historical  antecedents,  and 
physical  conditions. 

The  five  books  which  follow  treat  of  the  effect  of  physical 
agencies  on  social  institutions  and  changes.  What  ^ire  the 
influences  of  which  the  presence  would  be  most  easily  cfetected 
in  laws  and  customs  by  a  thinker  with  no  better  method  of 
investigation  than  that  which  Montesquieu  had  ?  There  can 
be  only  the  one  answer:  physical  influences.  Of  the  forces 
which  act  on  man  and  shape  his  destiny,  none  are  so  conspic- 
uous, and,  we  may  almost  say,  so  palpable.  Hence  it  was 
principally  by  them  that  Montesquieu  sought  to  explain  his- 
tory. How  has  civilisation  been  modified  by  the  action  of 
the  external  world?  How  are  the  laws  of  a  people  and  the 
other  products  of  its  social  and  moral  life  connected  with 
temperature,  soil,  and  food  ?  That  is  the  fundamental  prob- 
lem for  Montesquieu,  to  the  solution  of  which  he  devotes  all 
his  strength. 

It  would  be  absurd  to  say  that  he  has  solved  it.  We  know 
only  very  imperfectly,  even  at  present,  the  influence  of 
physical  agencies  on  man's  development.  The  meteorologist, 
chemist,  physiologist,  ethnologist,  and  political  economist, 
have  all  much  to  discover  before  the  historical  philosopher 


MONTESQUIEU  275 

will  be  able  to  pronounce  an  adequate  decision  on  this  large 
and  important  question.  The  errors  into  which  Montesquieu 
has  fallen  appear  to  be  chiefly  two.  And,  first,  he  has  drawn 
no  decided  distinction  between  the  direct  and  the  indirect 
influence  of  physical  causes,  which  is  a  quite  fundamental 
distinction.  The  direct  or  immediate  action  of  climate,  soil, 
and  food  is  probably  feeble,  and  its  working  is  certainly  very 
obscure.  Our  knowledge  of  it  is  both  little  and  dubious. 
Perhaps,  indeed,  not  a  single  general  proposition  regarding 
it  has  yet  been  conclusively  established.  The  indirect  influ- 
ence, on  the  other  hand,  or  that  which  physical  agencies  exert 
through  the  medium  of  the  social  wants  and  activities  which 
they  excite,  is  very  great;  and  since  the  time  of  Montesquieu 
not  a  little  has  been  accomplished  in  the  way  of  tracing  it. 
The  advance  of  geographical  knowledge,  for  instance,  on  one 
side,  and  of  the  science  of  political  economy  on  another,  now 
permits  us  to  survey,  with  a  comprehensiveness  and  clearness 
impossible  in  the  time  of  Montesquieu,  the  whole  range  of 
relationships  between  geographical  and  economical  facts ;  and 
no  one  will  deny  that  all  the  higher  orders  of  social  phenomena 
are  intimately  associated  with  the  latter  of  these. 

The  error  just  indicated  is  closely  connected  with  another. 
The  direct  action  of  physical  agencies  must  obviously  be  a 
necessary  mode  of  action, — one  which  is  independent  of 
volition, —  one  in  which  the  man  is  passive.  The  indirect 
action,  on  the  contrary,  presupposes  a  reaction  on  man's  part, 
and  a  development  of  his  nature  under  the  stimulus  of  the 
wants,  and  in  virtue  of  the  activities,  proper  to  it.  The 
confusion  of  the  two  forms  of  action  must  therefore  tend  to 
obscure  the  great  fact  of  human  freedom.  It  has  undoubtedly 
done  so  in  the  case  of  Montesquieu.  For  although  it  be  true 
that  he  has  explicitly  affirmed  his  belief  in  free  agency,  and 
repudiated  fatalism,  he  cannot  be  exonerated  from  having  at 
times  forgotten  this  profession  in  his  practice;  from  having 
if  not  directly  stated,  at  least  frequently  suggested,  the 
inference  that  laws  are  the  creatures  of  climate ;  from  having 
exhibited  the  nature  of  man  as  far  more  plastic  and  passive 
under  external  influences  than  it  is.  Thus  he  represents 
the  peoples  of  tropical  regions  as  having  been  doomed  by  the 
overmastering  power  of  physical  forces  to  inevitable  slavery 


276  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN  FRANCE 

and  misery.  Now  there  is  no  doubt  that  physical  conditions 
have  had  much  to  do  with  the  slavery  and  misery  of  tropical 
countries.  Where  outward  nature  is  exuberant,  gigantic, 
and  terrible,  she  is  apt  to  depress,  paralyse,  and  overpower 
man,  and  to  give  rise  to  an  unequal  distribution  of  wealth,  an 
excess  of  imagination,  and  a  prevalence  of  superstition  socially 
pernicious.  But  while  this  is  true  it  is  only  half  the  truth, 
and  it  will  be  practically  a  falsehood  if  separated  from  its 
correlative  truth  that  the  influence  of  physical  forces  on 
human  life  is  not  absolute  but  relative ;  that  they  are  advan- 
tageous or  the  reverse,  beneficial  or  pernicious,  according  to 
the  wealth  and  knowledge,  and  still  more  according  to  the 
energy  and  virtue,  of  those  on  whom  they  act ;  that  it  is  not, 
in  strict  propriety  of  speech,  nature  which  is  ever  at  fault, 
but  always  man.  "It  is  not  nature,"  says  a  thoughtful 
writer,  "  which  is  in  India  too  grand  —  not  nature  which  is 
in  excess,  but  man  who  is  too  little,  man  who  is  in  defect. 
Man  there  is  not  what  he  ought  to  be,  not  what  he  was  meant 
to  be,  not  properly  man;  he  wants  the  intellect  and  the 
energy,  the  love,  of  truth,  the  sense  of  personal  dignity,  the 
moral  and  religious  convictions  which  enter  into  the  consti- 
tution of  true  manhood,  and  therefore  it  is  that  nature  acts  as 
his  enemy :  but  let  him  have  these,  give  him  these,  and  nature 
will  come  round  to  his  side  at  once.  Nature  is  no  man's 
enemy  except  in  so  far  as  he  is  an  enemy  to  himself." J 

If  a  tendency  to  fatalism,  however,  makes  itself  felt 
throughout  these  books,  the  corrective  and  remedial  truth 
is  not  far  to  seek ;  it  is  established  and  applied  in  the  very 
next  book,  which  treats  expressly  of  laws  in  relation  to  the 
principles  which  form  the  general  spirit,  the  morals,  and 
manners  of  a  nation.  Savages  are  either  wholly  devoid  or 
very  slightly  participant  of  a  general  spirit,  and  in  conse- 
quence are  swayed  and  determined  irresistibly  by  physical 
forces ;  but  every  civilised  people  is  pervaded  by  a  common 
spirit,  which  is  in  fact  but  another  word  for  the  whole  of  its 
civilisation.  This  spirit  is  the  substance  of  the  people's  life, 
the  chief  source  of  their  actions,  carrying  along  with  it  those 
who  are  unconscious  of  it,  and  those  even  who  wish  to  resist  it; 
it  is  incapable  of  being  changed  otherwise  than  slowly  and  by 
1  M'Combie's  Modern  Civilisation  in  relation  to  Christianity,  pp.  50,  51. 


MONTESQUIEU  277 

the  concurrence  of  many  agencies,  and  is  feebly  modifiable  by 
laws,  while  so  powerfully  operative  on  them  as  to  be  able  to 
make  them  either  honoured  or  despised.  In  this  book  there 
is  the  enunciation,  proof,  and  varied  application  of  the  great 
principle  which  Montesquieu  had  already  exemplified  in  so 
masterly  a  manner  in  the  'Grandeur  et  Decadence  des 
Romani^ ' :  the  epoch-making  principle  that  the  course  of. 

Instoiy    is    nn    t^p    wVinlp    rlptprrpingd ^hy.-ggJPJ'8^    Causes,    by 

widespread  and  persistent  tendencies,  by  broad  and  deep 
undercurrents,  and  only  influenced  in  a  feeble,  secondary^ 
and  subordinate  degree  by  single  events,  by  definite  argu- , 
ments,  by  particular  enactments,  by  anything  accidental, 
isolated,  or  individual.  The  recognition  of  this  principle  is 
an  essential  condition  of  the  possibility  of  a  science  of  history. 
To  deny  it,  is  to  pronounce  every  notion  of  such  a  -science 
absurd ;  to  affirm  it,  is  to  express  the  conviction  that  with  the 
requisite  exertion  the  science  will  not  fail  to  arise ;  to  act  on 
and  apply  it,  is  to  labour  in  its  construction.  It  was  a  high 
service,  therefore,  to  historical  science,  that  Montesquieu 
apprehended  this  principle  with  a  clearness  and  comprehen- 
siveness of  view,  and  illustrated  it  with  an  ingenuity  and 
truthfulness,  which  have  perhaps  not  been  surpassed  since. 

The  next  four  books  deal  with  commerce,  with  money,  and 
with  population  in  their  relation  to  laws  and  social  changes. 
They  may  be  regarded  as  composing  a  group,  and  may  be  read 
in  connection  with  the  thirteenth  book,  which  treats  of  the 
relations  which  the  revenues  and  taxation  of  a  nation  have 
with  its  liberties.  These  books  introduced  the  economical 
element  into  historical  science, —  an  immense  service,  what- 
ever be  their  errors  of  economical  theory.  It  is  incorrect  to 
ascribe  the  honour  of  this  service,  as  has  been  done,  to  Tur- 
got,  or  Condorcet,  or  Saint-Simon,  or  Comte.  It  is  mainly 
due  to  Montesquieu.  Of  course,  in  order  not  to  give  him 
more  than  his  due,  we  must  remember  that  economical  science 
had  when  he  wrote  come  to  be  actively  cultivated  in  France ; 
that  Vauban,  Boisguilbert,  Dutot,  and  Melon  had  published 
important  works  on  it;  and  that  Quesnay  and  the  other 
founders  of  the  famous  physiocratic  school  were  his  contem- 
poraries. The  science  of  political  economy,  in  fact,  was  then 
passing  through  one  of  the  most  interesting  periods  of  its 


278  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

history,  one  which  reflected  a  change  in  the  history  of  society 
itself,  which  corresponded  to  a  great  national  movement,  the 
throwing  off  by  France  of  her  feudal  and  theocratic  bonds, 
and  her  eager  leap  towards  a  secular  and  industrial  polity. 
It  was  only  natural  that  Montesquieu  in  treating  of  economi- 
cal subjects  should  have  fallen  into  a  considerable  number  of 
errors  which  were  shortly  afterwards  convincingly  exposed, 
and  failed  to  observe  a  considerable  number  of  truths  which 
were  shortly  afterwards  conclusively  established,  by  Quesnay, 
Adam  Smith,  and  their  disciples.  He  occupies  a  very  impor- 
tant place  in  the  history  of  political  science ;  but  it  is  just 
where  two  orders  of  economical  ideas,  two  systems,  met  and 
crossed  each  other,  the  old  not  yet  dead  and  the  new  only 
struggling  into  life.  This  is  the  explanation  of  most  of  the 
inconsistencies  and  errors  which  have  been  discovered  in  his 
views  on  such  subjects  as  trade,  taxation,  money,  and  popu- 
lation. The  old  principles  and  the  new  —  those  of  mercan- 
tilism and  those  of  pbysiocracy  —  both  ruled  in  his  mind,  and 
he  was  unable  to  make  a  decisive  choice  between  them.  Yet 
his  intellectual  superiority  was  clearly  displayed  also  in  the 
department  of  economics.  His  great  and  distinctive  merit 
in  connection  with  it,  however,  was  that  he  first  brought 
economical  and  historical  science  together  in  such  a  way  as 
to  constrain  them  to  co-operate  in  the  explanation  of  social 
phenomena;.  He  thus  showed  that  a  new  path  of  inexhausti- 
ble research  lay  before  both;  and,  as  Roscher  expresses  it, 
"einen  grossartigen,  ebenso  nationalen  wie  universalen 
Forts  chritt  anbahnte . ' ' 

The  two  books  which  trace  the  influence  of  religious 
beliefs  and  institutions  on  laws  and  government,  although 
far  from  an  adequate  treatment  of  their  theme,  are  eminently 
judicious  so  far  as  they  go.  They  recognise  the  necessity 
and  importance  of  religion,  and  with  a  warmth  and  reverence 
markedly  in  contrast  to  the  tone  of  the  'Lettres  Persanes.' 
Reflection  and  experience  had  convinced  Montesquieu  that 
his  earlier  opinions  and  feelings  on  this  subject  had  been 
lacking  in  fairness  and  moderation ;  and  had  opened  his  eyes 
to  the  merits  of  Christianity,  and  especially  to  the  number 
and  magnitude  of  its  services  to  society.  Perhaps  the  chief 
errors  in  these  two  books,  as  in  the  preceding  book  —  that  on 


MONTESQUIEU  279 

population  —  regard  matters  of  fact.  As  it  is  simply  not  the 
case  that  in  warm  climates  the  proportion  of  male  to  female 
births  is  materially  different  from  what  it  is  in  cold  climates, 
and  polygamy  can  consequently  be  accounted  for  in  no  such 
way,  so  neither  is  it  the  case  that  orientals  are  indifferent 
about  religion  except  in  so  far  as  religious  change  may  involve 
political  change ;  and  hence  reasoning  to  and  reasoning  from 
that  supposition  are  alike  in  vain. 

The  twenty-sixth  and  twenty-ninth  books  concern  the 
jurist  much  more  than  the  historical  philosopher.  The 
twenty-seventh  book,  which  is  on  the  Roman  laws  of  suc- 
cession, is  historical,  but  probably  not  very  important. 

The  twenty-eighth  book,  which  is  on  the  origin  and  revo- 
lutions of  the  civil  laws  among  the  French,  and  the  two 
books  on  the  feudal  system  with  which  the  work  closes,  are 
at  once  intrinsically  valuable  and  not  less  interesting  to  the 
student  of  the  philosophy  of  history  than  of  law.  Although 
numerous  errors  of  fact  and  theory  have  been  detected  in 
them,  they  display  a  kind  of  learning  which  was  very  rare 
and  difficult  to  acquire  in  the  age  of  Montesquieu,  and  an 
originality  and  power  of  historical  combination  rare  in  any 
age.  They  have  undoubtedly  had  great  influence  in  evoking 
and  directing  later  research  into  the  origin,  formation,  and  con- 
sitution  of  the  feudal  system  and  of  French  medieval  society. 

Montesquieu  had  no  intention  of  founding  the  philosophy 
of  history ;  and  to  pronounce  him  its  founder,  as  Alison  has 
done,  is  extravagant  laudation.  It  appears  to  me  to  be  even 
eulogy  in  excess  of  the  truth  to  represent  him,  as  Comte, 
Maine,  and  Leslie  Stephen  have  done,  as  the  founder  of  the 
historical  method.  But  he  did  more  than  any  one  else  to 
facilitate  and  ensure  its  foundation.  He  showed  on  a  grand 
scale  and  in  the  most  effective  way,  that  laws,  customs,  and 
institutions  can  only  be  judged  of  intelligently  when  studied 
as  what  they  really  are,  historical  phenomena ;  and  that,  like 
all  things  properly  historical,  they  must  be  estimated  not 
according  to  an  abstract  or  absolute  standard,  but  as  concrete 
realities  related  to  given  times  and  places,  to  their  determin- 
ing causes  and  condition,  and  to  the  whole  social  organism  to 
which  they  belong,  and  the  whole  social  medium  in  which 
they  subsist.     Plato  and  Aristotle,  Machiavelli  and  Bodin, 


280  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

had  already,  indeed,  inculcated  this  historical  and  •political 
relativism;  but  it  was  Montesquieu  who  gained  educated 
Europe  over  to  the  acceptance  of  it.  His  success  was,  no 
doubt,  largely  due  to  the  ripeness  of  the  time,  but  it  was  also 
in  a  measure  due  to  his  own  genius  and  skill.  And  once  his- 
torical relativism  was  acknowledged,  the  rise  of  the  historical 
school,  the  development  of  the  historical  method,  and  the 
rapid  advance  of  historical  science,  naturally  followed. 


Ill 

The  '  Spirit  of  Laws '  was  only  completed  when  its  author 
was  nearly  sixty  years  of  age,  and  after  he  had  spent  on  it 
twenty  years  of  toil.  The  work  next  to  be  noticed  consists 
simply  of  two  Academic  discourses  delivered  at  the  Sorbonne 
in  1750  by  a  young  man  of  twenty-three,  and  some  sketches 
or  conspectuses  written  by  him,  either  when  a  student  of 
shortly  after.  That  young  man  was,  however,  Anne  Robert 
James  Turgot,  one  of  the  wisest  and  best  men  of  the  eigh- 
teenth century.1  He  was  pure  and  noble  in  his  private  life, 
a  zealous  philanthropist,  an  enlightened  philosopher,  a  hu- 
mane and  able  governor,  a  sagacious  statesman.  He  was  the 
friend  of  all  true  progress,  but  he  avoided  and  reproved  the 
excesses  which  were  advocated  in  its  name.  He  saw  and 
abhorred  the  sins  of  the  Church,  but  they  did  not  hide  from 
him  the  beauty  of  religion.  He  discriminated,  as  perhaps  no 
other  of  his  contemporaries  did,  not  even  Montesquieu,  be- 
tween the  good  and  evil  in  social  institutions,  and  between 
the  essential  and  accidental  in  all  things. 

1  The  following  are  among  the  best  works  on  Turgot:  (1)  Mastier  (A.),  'Tur- 
got, sa  vie  et  sa  doctrine  ' ;  (2)  Batbie  (A.) ,  '  Turgot :  philosophe,  economiste,  et 
administrateur '  (1861) ;  (3)  Foncin  (P.) ,  '  Essai  sur  le  ministere  de  Turgot ' 
(1877);  and  (4)  Neymark  (A.),  'Turgot  et  ses  doctrines,'  2  vols.  (1885).  The 
'  Eloge  de  Turgot '  of  Baudrillart;  the  two  lectures  on  '  Turgot:  his  Life,  Times, 
and  Opinions,'  by  Hodgson;  the  essay  on  Turgot  by  Morley  in  his  'Critical  Mis- 
cellanies ' ;  and  the  monograph  on  Turgot  by  L.  Say,  —  deserve  to  be  specially 
mentioned.  The  '  Correspondance  Ine'dite  de  Condorcet  et  de  Turgot '  (1770-1779), 
published  in  1883,  under  the  supervision  of  M.  Henry,  is  of  some  interest  to  a  stu- 
dent of  their  theories  of  history.  Eenouvier  has  made  a  careful  study  of  Turgot's 
theory  of  progress  in  the  '  Critique  Philosophique,'  annee  ix.,  torn.  ii.  385-396,  400- 
407,  annee  x.,  torn.  i.  17-27. 


TURGOT  281 

The  theme  of  the  first  of  his  discourses  at  the  Sorbonne 
was  "The  Benefits  which  the  establishment  of  Christianity 
has  procured  to  mankind."  Briefly  but  eloquently  he  con- 
trasts Christian  and  heathen  civilisation,  so  as  to  indicate 
the  superiority  of  the  former  over  the  latter,  and  the  unrea- 
sonableness of  the  exaggerated  admiration  of  antiquity,  and 
the  contemptuous  estimate  of  Christianity  which  had  begun 
to  prevail.  By  means  of  a  rapid  survey  of  the  general  and 
outstanding  facts  of  history,  he  seeks  to  show  that  the  Chris- 
tian religion  had  diffused  truth,  destroyed  errors,  promoted 
intellectual  progress,  evoked  and  enlarged  human  sympathies, 
improved  morals,  strengthened  what  was  good,  and  weakened 
what  was  evil  in  personal  and  social,  private  and  public  life, 
and,  in  particular,  afforded  the  needed  counterpoise  to  the 
universal  selfishness  from  which  proceeds  universal  injustice. 
The  chief  reason  why  Turgot's  view  of  the  course  of  history 
was  so  much  more  comprehensive,  and  so  much  more  con- 
sistent both  with  facts  and  in  itself,  than  that  of  Condorcet 
and  other  atheists  of  the  eighteenth  century,  was  that  he  was 
able,  and  they  were  not,  to  appreciate  in  a  fair  and  sympa- 
thetic spirit  the  services  which  Christianity  had  rendered  to 
mankind.  It  would  be  easy  to  overestimate,  however,  the 
intrinsic  worth  of  the  first  discourse.  For  while  it  is  high- 
toned  in  thought  and  eloquent  in  expression,  it  has  no  claim 
to  originality,  ingenuity,  or  thoroughness.  Its  purpose  and 
limits  did  not  allow,  indeed,  of  the  display  of  these  qualities. 

The  second  discourse,  which  had  for  its  subject  "  The  suc- 
cessive Advances  of  the  human  mind,"  was  much  more  im- 
portant. Here,  for  the  first  time,  the  idea  of  progress  was  , 
made,  as  M.  Caro  has  said,  "  the  organic  principle  of  history."  ' 
In  contrast  to  the  movement  of  the  physical  phenomena  of 
nature,  and  of  the  vegetable  and  animal  species,  through  con- 
stantly recurring  cycles  of  change,  history  is  represented  as 
the  life  of  humanity,  ever  progressing  towards  perfection, 
from  generation  to  generation,  from  stage  to  stage,  from 
nation  to  nation,  and  by  alternations  of  rest  and  agitation, 
success  and  failure,  decay  and  revival.  None  before  Turgot, 
and  few  after  him,  have  described  so  well  how  age  is  bound 
to  age,  how  generation  transmits  to  generation  what  it  has 
inherited  from  the  past  and  won  by  its  own  exertions.     The 


282  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PKANCE 

notion  of  progress  is  apprehended  by  him  with  a  fulness  as 
well  as  clearness  which  will  be  sought  in  vain  in  Bodin, 
Bacon,  Pascal,  or  any  other  predecessor.  In  him  what  we 
find  is  no  longer  a  simple  affirmation  or  general  view,  the 
identification  of  progress  with  the  advance  of  knowledge,  or 
with  anything  which  can  be  predicated  merely  of  specially 
favoured  nations  or  privileged  classes,  but  it  is  a  something 
which  embraces  all  space  and  time,  which  includes  all  the 
elements  of  life,  and  in  which  the  race  as  such  is  meant  to 
participate.  The  progress  of  humanity  means,  according  to 
Turgot,  the  gradual  evolution  and  elevation  of  man's  nature 
as  a  whole,  the  enlightenment  of  his  intelligence,  the  expan- 
sion and  purification  of  his  feelings,  the  amelioration  of  his 
worldly  lot,  and,  in  a  word,  the  spread  of  truth,  virtue, 
liberty,  and  comfort,  more  and  more  among  all  classes  of 
men.  He  seeks  to  prove  from  the  whole  history  of  the  past, 
that  there  has  been  such  progress ;  and  he  professes  his 
belief  that  there  will  be  such  progress  in  the  future,  on  the 
ground  that  mankind  seems  to  him  like  an  immense  arnvy 
directed  in  all  its  movements  by  a  vast  genius,  who  alone 
sees  the  end  towards  which  these  movements  advance  and 
converge.  As  a  picture  of  universal  history  taken  from  this 
high  and  hopeful  point  of  view,  his  second  discourse  is  so 
admirable  that  it  is  not  likely  to  be  surpassed  by  any  compo- 
sition on  the  same  scale. 

Turgot  formed  the  design  of  giving  full  expression  to  his 
thought  by  writing  an  elaborate  work  on  universal  history, 
or,  if  time  should  be  wanting  for  that,  on  the  progress  and 
vicissitudes  of  the  arts  and  sciences.  His  duties,  first,  as 
administrator  of  a  province,  and  afterwards  as  finance  minis- 
ter of  the  nation,  prevented  the  realisation  of  this  intention ; 
but  the  sketches  and  notes  committed  by  him  to  paper  in 
1750,  are  sufficient  to  show  us  how  he  meant  to  carry  it  out. 
There  can  be  no  reasonable  doubt  that,  even  if  the  smaller, 
but  especially  if  the  larger  scheme  had  been  accomplished, 
the  result  would  have  been  one  of  the  grandest  literary  and 
philosophical  productions  of  the  eighteenth  century,  —  a  work 
nobly  planned  and  richly  stored  with  facts  and  truths.  If 
the  philosophy  of  history  be  merely  a  scientific  representation 
of  universal  history  as  a  process  of  progressive  development, 


WG3.G&TI 


283 


Turgot  has  probably  a  better  claim  than  any  one  else  to  be 
called  its  founder.  Perhaps  this  was  all  that  Cousin  meant 
when  he  so  designated  him. 

This,  then,  was  the  great  service  of  Turgot  to  the  philoso- 
phy of  history,  that  he  definitively  showed  history  to  be  no 
mere  aggregate  of  names,  dates,  and  deeds,  brought  together 
and  determined  either  accidentally  or  externally,  but  an 
organic  whole  with  an  internal  plan  progressively  realised  by 
internal  forces.  He  so  apprehended  and  proved  this  truth  that 
it  may  fairly  be  called,  so  far  at  least  as  French  authors  are 
concerned,  his  conquest,  his  contribution  to  historical  science. 

The  mere  conception  of  progress  was,  when  Turgot  wrote, 
no  longer  novel.  Yet  it  had  become  dim  and  inoperative 
in  the  minds  even  of  the  leading  teachers  of  France ;  had 
been  extruded  by  the  inrush  of  the  new  ideas  of  liberty, 
fraternity,  justice,  and  equality,  and  the  expulsive  power  of 
the  new  affections  to  which  these  ideas  gave  rise.  Hence  in 
the  writings  of  Voltaire,  Montesquieu,  and  Diderot,  it  was 
conspicuous  only  by  its  absence,  and  in  those  of  Rousseau 
was  vehemently  assailed.  Turgot,  however,  not  only  restored 
it  to  honour,  but  so  deepened,  enlarged,  and  developed  it, 
that  it  acquired  with  him  a  profundity,  a  comprehensiveness, 
and  a  consistency  quite  novel. 

His  view  of  social  progress,  I  say,  was  profound.  It  was  a 
deep  glance  into  its  nature  as  a  process  of  self -development ; 
as  a  process  the  successive  phases  of  which  were  what  they 
were,  because  man  was  so  and  so  made  and  situated.  He 
not  merely  saw  the  fact  of  progress,  that  physical  and  polit- 
ical causes  greatly  affected  it,  and  that  like  every  other 
process  it  might  be  referred  to  the  will  of  the  great  First 
Cause ;  but  he  saw  likewise  how  it  was  connected  with  the 
essential  faculties  of  man,  and  the  constitutive  principles  of 
society.  No  one  before  him  had  perceived  with  anything 
like  the  same  clearness  how  the  mental  or  spiritual  movement 
in  history  underlies,  originates,  and  pervades  the  outwardly 
visible  movement.  M.  Martin,  whose  account  of  Turgot  is 
in  general  excellent,  errs  greatly  when  he  blames  him  "  for 
regarding  progress  too  much  as  the  result  of  external  phenom- 
ena, and  not  sufficiently  as  the  manifestation  of  the  internal 
energies  of  man."     This  charge  is  altogether  inapplicable,  as 


284  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

any  one  may  easily  convince  himself  by  reading,  for  instance, 
the  first  portion  of  the  '  Ebauche  du  Second  Discours.' 

As  regards  comprehensiveness,  Turgot's  view  embraced 
all  the  elements  of  social  life.  Science,  art,  government, 
manners,  morality,  religion,  were  all  held  by  him  to  be  the 
subjects  of  historical  progress,  and  consequently  of  historical 
philosophy.  At  the  same  time  he  was  quite  aware  that  none 
of  these  things  are  developed  isolatedly,  but  that,  on  the 
contrary,  the  position  of  any  one  of  them  at  any  given  time 
is  closely  related  to  that  of  all  the  others,  and  that  there  is 
a  perpetual  reciprocity  of  influence  between  all  the  forces  in 
the  social  organism,  a  constant  action  and  reaction  of  social 
facts  on  one  another.  The  entire  'Plan  du  Premier  Dis- 
cours '  shows  that  he  grasped  as  firmly  and  completely  the 
truth  of  the  consensus  as  of  the  sequence  of  social  changes, 
and  many  of  its  paragraphs  —  as,  e.g.,  those  descriptive  of  the 
hunting  and  pastoral  states  —  are  excellent  delineations  of 
what  constitutes  such  a  consensus. 

His  view  is  not  more  distinguished  for  comprehensiveness 
than  for  consistency.  This  can  be  in  no  way  better  brought 
out  than  by  comparing  it  with  that  of  Condorcet,  to  whom  so 
much  of  the  honour  properly  due  to  Turgot  has  been  often 
awarded.  Condorcet  believed  in  progress  and  perfectibility 
as  firmly  and  more  enthusiastically  than  Turgot,  but  his 
inferiority  as  regards  consistency  is  immense.  Indeed  his 
retrospect  of  the  history  of  the  race,  and  the  prospect  he 
deduces  from  it,  are  in  manifest  contradiction.  For,  while 
extolling  the  vast  superiority  of  his  own  age  over  all  those 
which  had  preceded  it,  and  picturing  a  glorious  future  as  at 
hand,  he  yet,  under  the  influence  of  his  philosophical  and 
religious  prejudices,  sees  only  the  evil  side  of  the  greatest 
ancient  and  medieval  institutions,  the  Church,  feudalism, 
and  monarchy,  for  instance;  and  by  attributing  to  them 
essentially  obstructive  and  pernicious  influences,  renders  the 
progress  which  he  glorifies  unintelligible,  or,  as  Comte  says,, 
a  perpetual  miracle,  an  effect  without  a  cause.  No  such 
charge  can  be  brought  against  Turgot.  With  him,  whatever 
superiority  is  ascribed  to  the  present  is  exhibited  as  the 
result  of  a  growth  which  has  slowly  and  intermittingly  but 
surely  pervaded  the  institutions  and  ages  of  the  past,  and 


TURGOT  285 

which  has  incorporated  into  its  each  succeeding  stage  what 
was  true  and  good  in  the  preceding,  so  as  never  to  be  in  con- 
tradiction to  itself. 

Turgot  did  not  represent  history  as  a  process  either  of 
uniform  or  uninterrupted  progress.  He  fully  acknowledged 
that  there  were  periods  of  intellectual  and  moral  dgggrirence, 
and  that  the  study  of  these  periods,  with  a  view  to  ascertain 
the  causes  of  retrogression,  was  highly  instructive.  He  did 
not  regard  such  progress  as  he  ascribed  to  history  to  imply 
that  men  are  born  with  more  genius  or  virtue  in  later  than  in 
earlier  ages,  or  necessarily  surpass  their  predecessors  in  every 
particular  form  of  excellence.  "  The  primitive  dispositions 
act  equally  in  barbarous  and  cultured  peoples ;  they  are 
probably  the  same  in  all  places  and  times.  Genius  is  scattered 
among  the  human  race  much  like  gold  in  a  mine.  The  more 
mineral  you  take  up,  the  more  metal  you  may  collect.  The 
more  men  there  are,  the  more  great  men,  or  men  capable  of 
becoming  great,  there  will  be.  The  hazards  of  education  and 
of  events  develop  them  or  leave  them  buried  in  obscurity,  or 
immolate  them  before  their  season  like  fruits  beaten  down 
by  the  winds.  We  must  admit  that  if  Corneille  had  been 
brought  up  in  a  village  and  had  guided  the  plough  all  his 
life,  or  Racine  had  been  born  in  Canada  among  the  Hurons 
or  in  Europe  during  the  eleventh  century,  neither  of  them 
would  have  displayed  their  genius.  If  Columbus  and  New- 
ton had  died  at  the  age  of  fifteen,  America  would  have  been 
discovered  perhaps  only  two  centuries  later,  and  we  should 
have  been  still  ignorant  of  the  true  system  of  the  world. 
And  if  Virgil  had  perished  in  infancy  we  should  have  had 
no  Virgil,  for  there  are  not  two  of  them.  Advances,  although 
necessary,  are  intermingled  with  frequent  decadences,  owing 
to  the  events  and  revolutions  which  interrupt  them.  They 
are  consequently  different  among  different  peoples."  They 
are  also,  according  to  Turgot,  different  in  different  periods. 
He  not  merely  saw  in  a  general  way  that  progress  had  not 
been  a  uniform  process,  but  quite  clearly  that  it  was  one 
which  had  varied  in  rate  from  age  to  age  greatly,  and  yet  not 
arbitrarily  or  inexplicably.  Hence  he  made  a  distinct  effort 
to  account  for  variations  of  rate  of  movement  in  history. 
And  it  was,  on  the  whole,  a  very  successful  effort.     On  no 


286  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOBY   IN   TRANCE 

point  relating  to  the  course  of  history,  indeed,  has  he  given 
expression  to  more  ingenious  and  suggestive  observations. 
The  larger  portion  of  the  '  Plan  du  second  discours '  might 
be  quoted  in  proof. 

While  Turgot  recognised  that  human  nature  was  in  all  its 
elements  the  subject  of  progress,  he  also  virtually  assumed 
that  the  intellect  was  the  dominant  and  directing  principle  in 
its  development,  and  that,  therefore,  intellectual  enlighten- 
ment is  the  ultimate  and  general  criterion  of  progress.  He 
did  not  discuss  any  of  the  objections  which  may  be  urged 
against  the  assumption.  Yet  he  gave  indications  of  not 
being  wholly  unconscious  that  there  were  facts  at  least  appar- 
ently in  some  measure  inconsistent  with  it.  He  saw  that 
enlightenment  and  virtue  did  not  perfectly  correspond  ;  and 
that  the  development  of  art  could  not  be  exactly  co-ordinated 
with  the  development  of  science.  He  did  not  submit,  how- 
ever, the  question  as  to  how  progress  is  to  be  appreciated  and 
measured  to  any  distinct  investigation.  It  was,  doubtless, 
only  vaguely  present  to  his  mind. 

Among  the  fragmentary  papers  of  Turgot  connected  with 
the  philosophy  of  history  is  the  sketch  of  a  '  Political  Geog- 
raphy,' which  shows  that  he  had  attained  to  a  broader  view 
of  the  relationship  of  human  development  to  the  features  of 
the  earth  and  to  physical  agencies  in  general  than  even  Mon- 
tesquieu. And  he  saw  with  perfect  clearness  not  only  that 
many  of  Montesquieu's  inductions  were  premature  and  inade- 
quate, but  that  there  was  a  defect  in  the  method  by  which  he 
arrived  at  them.  Hence  he  lays  down  as  a  principle  to  be 
followed  in  this  order  of  researches  that  physical  causes  being 
indirect  and  secondary,  or,  in  other  words,  causes  which  act 
in  and  through  mental  qualities,  natural  or  acquired,  ought 
not  to  be  had  recourse  to  until  mental  causes  have  been  fully 
taken  into  account.  The  excellent  criticism  of  Comte,  in  the 
fifth  volume  of  the  '  Philosophic  Positive,'  and  in  the  fourth 
volume  of  the  '  Politique  Positive,'  on  this  portion  of  Mon- 
tesquieu's speculations,  is  only  a  more  elaborate  reproduction 
of  that  of  Turgot,  and  is  expressed  in  terms  which  show 
that  it  was  directly  suggested  by  that  of  Turgot. 

There  is  among  the  many  pregnant  thoughts  of  Turgot 
one  which  was  destined  to  have  so  singularly  famous  a  history 


TURGOT  287 

that  it  is  necessary  to  state  it  in  his  own  words.  He  says  : 
"  Before  knowing  the  connection  of  physical  facts  with  one 
another,  nothing  was  more  natural  than  to  suppose  that  they 
were  produced  by  beings,  intelligent,  invisible,  and  like  to 
ourselves.  Everything  which  happened  without  man's  own 
intervention  had  its  god,  to  which  fear  or  hope  caused  a  wor- 
ship to  be  paid  conformed  to  the  respect  accorded  to  powerful 
men  —  the  gods  being  only  men  more  or  less  powerful  and 
perfect  in  proportion  as  the  age  which  originated  them  was 
more  or  less  enlightened  as  to  what  constitutes  the  true  per- 
fections of  humanity.  But  when  philosophers  pferceived  the 
absurdity  of  these  fables,  without  having  attained  to  a  real 
acquaintance  with  the  history  of  nature,  they  fancifully 
accounted  for  phenomena  by  abstract  expressions,  by  essences 
and  faculties,  which  indeed  explained  nothing,  but  were 
reasoned  from  as  if  they  were  real  existences.  It  was  only 
very  late  that  from  observing  the  mechanical  action  of  bodies 
on  one  another,  other  hypotheses  were  inferred,  which  mathe- 
matics could  develop  and  experience  verify."  This  is  as 
explicit  a  statement  as  can  well  be  imagined  of  what  the 
world  has  heard  so  much  about  as  Comte's  law  of  the  three 
states  —  viz.,  that  each  of  our  leading  conceptions,  each 
branch  of  our  knowledge,  passes  successively  through  three 
different  theoretical  conditions,  the  theological,  the  meta- 
physical, and  the  positive ;  the  mind,  in  the  first,  regarding 
phenomena  as  governed  not  by  invariable  laws  of  sequence, 
but  by  single  and  direct  volitions  of  a  superior  being  or 
beings ;  in  the  second,  referring  them  not  to  such  volitions 
but  to  realised  abstractions,  to  occult  qualities  and  essences ; 
while  in  the  final  stage  it  ceases  to  interpose  either  supernat- 
ural agents  or  metaphysical  entities  between  phenomena  and 
their  production,  but,  attending  solely  to  the  phenomena 
themselves,  seeks  simply  to  discover  their  relations  of  simil- 
tude  and  succession.  There  cannot  be  a  doubt  that  as  to 
the  general  conception  of  this  fundamental  principle  of  his 
system  Comte  has  been  anticipated  by  Turgot.  It  is  possible 
that  it  may  have  occurred  to  his  mind  independently,  but  it 
is  much  more  likely  that  it  was  suggested  by  the  passage 
in  Turgot.  There  is  a  good  deal  of  internal  evidence  that 
Comte  had  not  only  read  but  carefully  studied  what  Turgot 


288  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

had  written  on  history.  But  be  this  as  it  may,  certain  it  is 
that  Comte  did  not  originate  the  general  conception  of  the 
three  states.  What  he  distinctively  did  was  to  lay  it  down 
as  the  fundamental  law  of  historical  development,  to  make 
it  the  basis  of  a  most  elaborate  survey  of  the  whole  course 
of  that  development,  and  so  to  apply  it  to  the  explanation  of 
a  vast  number  of  social  facts.  Those  who  believe  it  to  be  a 
true  law  will  probably  say  that  even  thus  stated  the  service 
rendered  by  Comte  must  be  regarded  as  incomparably  more 
important  than  that  of  Turgot,  and  that  his  claim  to  be  a 
discoverer  really  remains  intact,  since  he  only  discovers  who 
proves.  Nor  against  this  have  I  any  objection  to  make.  It 
is  necessary  to  be  just  to  Turgot,  but  that  is  not  incompatible 
with  justice  nor  even  with  generosity  to  Comte,  whose  able 
and  laborious  endeavour  to  verify  the  idea  first  conceived  by 
Turgot  must,  by  those  who  are  most  convinced  of  its  failure, 
be  admitted  to  have  been  at  least  singularly  provocative  of 
fruitful  inquiry  and  discussion. 

The  notion  of  three  successive  stages  of  thought  in  the  in- 
terpretation of  nature  originated,  it  will  be  observed,  with  a 
man  to  whomi  the  true  interests  of  religion  were  sacred,  and 
to  whom  any  irreligious  application  of  it  would  have  been 
abhorrent ;  and  if  Comte  has  given  it  an  irreligious  bearing, 
that  is  one  no  less  certainly  illegitimate  than  irreligious. 
Grant  Comte's  alleged  law,  Turgot's  general  conception,  and 
grant  to  it  even  a  rigid  and  absolute  truthfulness  to  which  it 
has  probably  no  just  pretensions,  and  even  then,  if  it  be  con- 
fined not  only  to  the  five  sciences  which  are  all  that  Comte 
admits  to  be  sciences,  but  allowed  to  hold  true  of  all  the 
psychological  sciences  as  well,  it  must  be  perfectly  innocuous, 
if  it  can  be  shown  that  metaphysics  and  theology  are  not  co- 
ordinate, are  not  at  all  on  a  level  with  these  positive  or  induc- 
tive sciences.  It  is  not  Comte's  alleged  law  that  is  dangerous, 
but  the  dogmatic,  arbitrary,  unreasoned  assertion  which  he 
has  appended  to  it  that  five  positive  sciences  comprehend  all 
knowledge.  Theology  and  metaphysics  are  not  merely  par- 
ticular and  passing  stages  of  the  positive  sciences,  whether 
these  be  physical  or  psychological  sciences,  but  themselves 
sciences,  each  with  an  appropriate  sphere  of  its  own,  the  one 
underlying,  and  the  other  overlying,  the  positive  sciences. 


VOLTAIRE  289 

To  emancipate  physical  and  psychological  science  from  a 
theological  and  metaphysical  condition  is  no  less  a  service 
to  theology  and  metaphysics  than  to  physics  and  psychology. 
Every  science  must  gain  by  being  kept  in  its  own  place.  It 
is  wrong  to  mix  up  either  theological  beliefs  or  metaphysical 
principles  among  the  laws  of  the  positive  sciences.  But  we 
by  no  means  do  so  when  we  hold  that  both  physics  and  psy- 
chology presuppose  metaphysics,  and  yield  conclusions  of 
which  theology  may  avail  itself,  and  that  we  can  still  look 
on  the  whole  earth  as  made  beautiful  by  the  artist  hand  of 
the  Creator,  on  science  as  the  unveiling  of  His  wisdom,  and 
on  history  as  the  manifestation  of  His  providence. 


IV 

There  were  in  both  Montesquieu  and  Turgot  a  comprehen- 
siveness of  judgment,  a  candour  of  disposition,  and  a  calmness 
of  temperament  which  made  them  more  than  mere  typical 
representatives  of  the  age  in  which  they  lived.  It  was  in  a 
man  who,  although  richly  endowed  with  mental  gifts,  had  cer- 
tainly no  more  than  his  share  of  these  qualities  —  in  Francjois- 
Marie  Arouet,  so  celebrated  under  the  name  of  Voltaire  — 
that  all  its  distinctive  characteristics  and  tendencies  found 
their  completest  embodiment  and  clearest  expression.1  With 
as  much  truth  as  Louis  XIV.  had  said  "  L'Etat,  c'est  moi," 
might  Voltaire  have  said,  "  Le  Si£cle,  c'est  moi."  His  influ- 
ence during  the  fifty  years  of  his  literary  activity  was  as  great 
in  France   and  throughout  Europe  as  that  of  the  monarch 

1  The  literature  relative  to  Voltaire  is  enormous.  He  has  been  written  about 
from  all  possible  points  of  view.  The  best  biography  of  him  is  that  by  Des- 
noiresterres,  'Voltaire  et  la  Society  francaise  au  XVIII8  siecle,'  7  vols.,  Paris, 
1867-75.  Extensive  as  it  is,  it  is  not  too  much  so  considering  the  place  occupied 
and  the  influence  exerted  by  the  subject  of  it ;  and  it  is  never  tedious  or  filled  up 
with  irrelevant  matter.  Bungener's  'Voltaire  et  son  Temps,'  Arsene  Houssaye's 
'  Le  Roi  Voltaire,'  Pierson's  '  Voltaire  et  ses  Maitres,'  Strauss' '  Voltaire,'  Morley's 
'Voltaire,'  and  Hamley's  'Voltaire,'  deserve  to  be  specially  mentioned.  The 
views  given  of  Voltaire's  character  and  work  in  Hettner's  Litteraturgeschichte, 
2.  Th.,  and  in  the  histories  of  France  or  the  French  Revolution  by  H.  Martin, 
J.  Michelet,  and  L.  Blanc,  are  interesting.  The  general  philosophy  of  Voltaire  has 
been  treated  of  by  E.  Bersot,  '  La  Philosophie  de  Voltaire,'  and  A.  Gerard,  '  La 
Philosophie  de  Voltaire  d'apres  la  critique  Allemande ' ;  his  knowledge  of  physical 
science  by  Du  Bois-Reymond,  '  Voltaire  in  seiner  Beziehung  zur  Naturwissen- 
schaft ' ;  and  his  historical  philosophy  by  Schlosser,  Buckle,  and  Laurent.  There 
is  a  '  Bibliographie  des  CEuvres  de  Voltaire,'  in  4  vols.,  by  G.  Bengesco. 


290  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PKANCE 

during  his  lengthened  personal  reign.  He  was  as  much  the 
central  and  ruling  personage  in  the  movement  destructive  of 
absolutism,  as  the  king  had  been  in  that  of  its  development. 

The  estimate  formed  of  Voltaire  will  accordingly  always 
correspond  to  that  formed  of  the  eighteenth  century  itself. 
The  extravagantly  unjust  way  in  which  he  was  generally 
spoken  of  during  the  first  thirty  years  of  the  present  century 
was  chiefly  due  to  a  fanatical  hatred  of  all  the  ideas  which 
were  supposed  to  have  led  to  the  French  Revolution,  and  has 
been  disappearing  since  in  proportion  to  the  prevalence  of  a 
more  correct  appreciation  of  them.  He  is  still  underesti- 
mated by  those  who  believe  these  ideas  to  have  been  mere 
negations,  of  use  only  at  the  most  for  the  destruction  of  evil. 
On  the  other  hand,  he  was  not  only  overestimated  by  the  vast 
majority  of  his  contemporaries,  but  is  so  even  now  by  those 
who  do  not  perceive  that  although  the  truths  for  which  he 
contended  were  positive  principles  of  belief  and  morality, 
which  overthrew  the  old  order  of  things  only  because  they 
deserved  to  do  so,  and  which  have  survived  the  Revolution, 
and  entered  deeply  and  permanently  into  the  spirits  of  all 
the  leading  European  nations,  yet  that  they  were  also  princi- 
ples which  required  to  be  supplemented  by,  and  subordi- 
nated to,  others,  and  constituted  by  themselves  an  extremely 
one-sided  standard  of  judgment  and  conduct. 

The  intellect  of  Voltaire  was  not  original,  profound,  or 
impartial,  but  it  was  extraordinarily  energetic,  versatile,  and 
dexterous.  He  had  neither  philosophical  nor  poetical  genius, 
but  he  had  incomparable  talent,  and  easily  excelled  in  all 
varieties  of  literature.  His  activity  was  prodigious.  He  cap- 
tivated courtly  and  refined  society  by  the  wit  and  brilliancy 
of  his  conversation.  He  was  an  indefatigable  correspondent, 
and  in  no  capacity  appeared  to  more  advantage  or  exercised 
more  influence.  His  publications  appeared  in  rapid  succes- 
sion, were  of  the  most  manifold  kinds,  and  yet  rarely  failed 
to  produce  the  impression  which  their  author  desired.  He 
was  at  once  formidable  in  argument  and  terrible  in  raillery, 
and  was  often  in  passionate  and  deadly  earnest  when  simu- 
lating indifference  or  mirth.  With  light  weapons  he  could 
inflict  serious  or  fatal  wounds.  He  was  intensely  practical. 
To  judge,  of  him  simply  as  a  literary  man  is  as  erroneous  as  it 


VOLTAIRE  291 

would  be  so  to  judge  of  Luther.  He  was  primarily  a  reformer, 
a  revolutionist,  a  man  at  war  with  the  established  order  of 
things,  and  determined  to  bring  about  radical  changes  in  the 
principles  and  conduct  of  society.  The  chief  aim  of  his  life 
was  to  free  human  thought  from  what  he  regarded  as  slavery, 
superstition,  and  folly ;  to  spread  what  he  believed  to  be  free- 
dom, enlightenment,  and  reason ;  to  assail  dogmatism  and 
persecution,  injustice  and  inhumanity,  and  to  make  them  by 
all  effective  means  the  objects  of  hatred  and  contempt ;  and,  in 
particular,  to  crush  the  great  enemy  of  mankind,  the  Church, 
"  l'lnf&me."  To  accomplish  his  purpose  he  not  only  schemed 
and  struggled  himself,  but  he  also,  and  with  consummate  au- 
dacity and  skill,  directed  the  operations  of  a  league  of  con- 
spirators and  an  army  of  combatants  of  like  mind  and  spirit. 
His  success  was  vast.  He  made  Europe  largely  Voltairian, 
and  such  it  remains  in  no  slight  measure  even  to  this  day. 

He  is  entitled  to  have  the  highest  place  assigned  him  among 
those  historians  of  his  age  and  country  who  wrote  for  the 
instruction  of  the  general  public.  In  his  best  efforts  he  sur- 
passed them  all,  alike  as  regards  style,  research,  and  insight. 
He  narrated  with  ease,  alertness,  and  force.  He  had  a  vast 
and  intelligent  curiosity,  and  could  submit  to  severe  labour  in 
order  to  gratify  it.  He  had  a  clear  vision  to  a  certain  depth, 
a  naturally  truthful  judgment  within  a  certain  range.  No 
one  could  dispose  and  present  his  matter  so  attractively. 
Some  of  his  historical  compositions,  indeed,  were  hasty  and 
unsatisfactory  compositions,  meant  merely  to  serve  some  tem- 
porary purpose,  and  then  to  pass  into  kindly  oblivion.  These 
were,  however,  no  measure  of  his  talent,  and  need  not  be 
taken  into  account  in  our  estimate  of  him. 

His  '  Charles  XII.'  (1731)  was  a  brilliant  instance  of 
descriptive  history.  It  necessarily  involved  a  very  consider- 
able amount  of  original  investigation,  as  it  required  to  be 
drawn  almost  wholly  from  unpublished  sources.  The  view 
which  it  gave  of  the  character  and  career  of  the  Swedish 
monarch  is  extremely  vivid,  and  has  not,  it  seems,  been  shown 
to  be  inaccurate  in  any  essential  respects.  The  narrative 
style  of  Voltaire  is  seen  at  its  best  in  such  pictures  as  those  of 
the  retreat  of  Schulembourg  and  of  the  battle  of  Pultawa. 

The  'Si&cle  de  Louis  XIV.'  (1752)  is  a  work  of  much 


292  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

greater  intrinsic  value.  Its  subject  is  not  a  man  but  an  age, 
not  a  heroic  fool  but  a  great  and  eventful  epoch.  Its  plan 
has  often  been  censured  as  lacking  unity,  and  as  not  answer- 
ing to  the  strict  requirements  of  historical  composition.  But 
if  Voltaire  erred  at  all  in  not  confining  himself  to  a  single 
comprehensive  and  uninterrupted  narration,  it  was  because 
he  believed  that  by  such  limitation  he  would  have  ruined  his 
work.  To  give  a  series  of  pictures  of  the  various  phases  of 
the  civilisation  which  characterised  the  age  of  Louis  XIV. 
was  an  essential  part  of  the  plan  which  he  conceived  to  be 
the  most  appropriate.  The  civilisation  of  that  epoch  was 
what  chiefly  interested  himself,  and  to  exhibit  it  in  all  its 
general  aspects  was  his  chief  concern.  Could  he  have  so 
exhibited  it  as  well  as  he  did,  if  he  had  followed  another 
method  than  the  one  which  he  actually  pursued  ?  It  is  far 
from  obvious  that  he  could.  He  gave  at  least  full  justice  to 
the  king,  while  he  did  not  conceal  the  more  serious  of  his 
political  faults.  He  described  the  military  exploits  of  the 
age  with  spirit,  and  yet  did  not  assign  to  them  too  large  a 
place  or  undue  importance.  He  dwelt  with  sympathetic 
appreciation  and  patriotic  pride  on  the  advances  made  during 
the  period  in  literature,  art,  science,  and  social  refinement. 

His  '  Essai  sur  les  Mceurs  et  l'Esprit  des  Nations '  has,  how- 
ever, far  stronger  claims  on  our  attention.  This  great  work 
was  planned  and  written  for  Madame  de  CMtelet  about  1740, 
although  only  published  in  1756.  It  had  for  object  to  trace 
the  growth  of  national  manners,  the  progress  of  society,  the 
development  of  the  human  mind,  from  Charlemagne  to  Louis 
XIII.  The  merits  of  its  general  conception  or  organising 
thought  are  amply  sufficient  to  atone  for  not  a  few  failures  in 
execution ;  and  that  thought  being  to  a  considerable  extent 
original  as  well  as  true,  its  merits  must  in  justice  be  ascribed 
to  Voltaire  himself. 

Bossuet  had  preceded  him  in  looking  on  the  succession  of 

events  and  ages  as  rationally  connected,  but  he  sought  the 

principle  of  connection  in  the  purposes  of  the  Divine  Will, 

and  so  passed  at  once  from  the  domain  of  history  into  that  of 

^theology,  whereas  Voltaire,  on  the  contrary,  concentrated  his 

"attention  on  man,  not  on  Providence  —  on  the  secondary,  not 


VOLTAIRE  293 

the  primary  cause  —  striving  to  find  the  explanations  of 
events  in  the  opinions  and  feelings  of  men  themselves,  in  the 
forces  discoverable  by  analysis  and  induction,  without  rising 
above,  or  in  any  way  going  beyond,  history  proper.  So  far 
from  being  essentially  contradictory,  these  two  aspects  of 
history  are  mutually  complemental,  —  both  being  true  in 
themselves,  and  false  only  when  exaggerated  into  antagonism 
to  each  other;  still  they  are  different,  and  that  on  which 
Voltaire  insists  is  undoubtedly  that  to  which  the  science  of 
history  must  confine  itself  in  the  rigid  and  exclusive  exercise 
of  its  peculiar  and  distinctive  function. 

The  design  of  Voltaire  is  no  less  distinct  from  that  of  Mon- 
tesquieu both  in  the  '  Grandeur  et  Decadence  des  Romains ' 
and  in  the  '  Esprit  des  Lois.'  In  the  former  of  these  works 
Montesquieu  seeks  merely  to  establish,  if  we  may  so  speak, 
two  definite  historical  theses,  or  at  least  to  solve  two  definite 
historical  problems  by  exhibiting  first  the  causes  which  ac- 
counted for  the  marvellous  success  of  Rome,  and  then  those 
which  undermined  and  destroyed  her  strength  and  life.  In 
the  latter  he  examines  merely  a  particular  class  of  historical 
phenomena  —  viz.,  the  various  kinds  of  laws  —  in  all  lights, 
with  a  view  to  compass  if  possible  a  complete  explanation  of 
them.  Both  of  these  aims  are  essentially  different  from  the 
task  which  Voltaire  proposed  to  himself,  that  of  writing  the 
history  of  the  human  mind  and  of  human  society  during 
almost  nine  centuries. 

The  work  of  Voltaire  is  also  very  different  in  character 
from  that  of  Turgot.  The  latter,  as  we  have  seen,  is  merely 
a  sketch;  the  former  is  a  completed  production.  The  dis- 
tinction between  them  is  the  important  one  between  plan  and 
realisation,  between  discourse  on  history  and  history,  between 
the  abstract  and  the  concrete.  Besides,  what  Voltaire  accom- 
plished was  not  precisely  that  which  Turgot  planned.  It  was 
something  less  and  lower,  but  also  something  more  his  own. 
Turgot  sketched  a  scheme  of  universal  history  regarded  as  a 
progressive  development  of  human  nature,  as  the  gradual 
advancement  of  mankind  in  knowledge  and  virtue,  in  happi- 
ness and  power.  The  plan  he  traced  proceeded  from  and 
was  pervaded  by  a  single  all-inclusive  and  all-dominant  philo- 


294  PHILOSOPHY    OF    HISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

Efcophical  idea,  that  of  a  continuous  movement  towards  per- 
fection in  accordance  with  internal  natural  law.  Voltaire 
wrote  a  general  history  mainly  in  order  to  trace  the  course  of 
civilisation,  the  origins  and  manifestations  of  culture,  the 
"ways  in  which  peoples  had  passed  from  ignorance  and  rustic- 
ity to  enlightenment  and  refinement;  but  he  did  so  without 
reference  to  any  philosophical  idea,  and  without  representing 
history  as  subject  to  any  law,  internal  or  external,  natural  or 
providential.  While  he  treated  of  what  he  deemed  progress 
largely  and  with  all  the  enthusiasm  of  which  he  was  capable, 
he  regarded  it  as  merely  an  accident,  a  happy  but  wholly 
contingent  incident,  in  history.  He  has  repeatedly  expressed 
himself  as  if  there  were  no  law  in  human  affairs,  as  if  history 
were  the  domain  of  "  Sa  Majeste"  le  Hasard." 

While  Voltaire  gave  to  the  greatest  of  his  historical  works 
the  modest  title  of  '  Essai,'  to  one  of  slight  character  and  little 
merit  he  assigned  the  magnificent  designation  of  '  La  Philo- 
sophic de  l'Histoire.'  It  was  first  published  by  him  in  1765  as 
the  production  of  "  the  late  Abbe"  Bazin,"  and  afterwards  pre- 
fixed to  the  '  Essai '  as  an  introduction,  so  that  it  may  now  be 
regarded  as  a  part  of  it.  Apparently  Voltaire  was  the  first  to 
employ  the  expression  "philosophy  of  history,"  but  he  so  used 
it  as  to  show  that  he  had  no  worthy  conception  of  what 
has  a  claim  to  the  designation.  He  has  not  explained  or 
defined  what  he  meant  by  "philosophy  of  history,"  and  conse- 
quently, we  are  left  to  gather  his  meaning  from  an  exami- 
nation of  his  so-called  'Philosophy  of  History.'  A  glance 
through  the  series  of  brief  and  loosely  connected  chapters  of 
which  the  work  consists,  speedily  shows  us  at  least  what  he 
did  not  mean  by  it.  It  immediately  discloses  that  he  had  no 
conception  of  the  philosophy  of  history  as  an  essential  and 
organic  part  of  a  philosophical  system,  or  as  a  study  of  the 
laws  and  course  of  development  of  the  human  spirit,  or  as  an 
exhibition  of  the  rationality  of  history ;  and,  in  a  word,  that 
he  used  the  designation  in  a  quite  different  way  from  that  in 
which  it  has  come  to  be  employed  in  the  nineteenth  century. 
It  is  not,  perhaps,  quite  so  easy  to  determine  precisely  what 
he  did  mean  by  it.  Yet  I  think  we  may  with  confidence  hold 
that  it  was  simply  the  study  of  history  "  en  philosophe,"  as  a 


VOLTAIRE  295 

philosopher  should  study  it,  the  term  philosopher  being  under- 
stood in  its  popular  eighteenth-century  sense,  —  the  sense  in 
which  Voltaire  and  all  the  freethinkers  of  his  age  claimed  to 
be  philosophers.  In  fact,  the  philosophy  of  history,  according 
to  Voltaire,  is  neither  more  nor  less  than  the  treatment  of 
history  in  the  spirit  and  by  the  light  of  the  Aufklarung.  It 
presupposes  no  positive  system  of  thought,  and  may  lead  to 
none.  It  is  only  a  mode  of  viewing  history,  and  one  ever! 
which  is  mainly  negative.  It  consists  in  avoiding  credulous! 
ness,  exposing  superstition,  rejecting  the  myths  and  legends 
with  which  the  histories  of  all  peoples  are  disfigured,  refus- 
ing credence  to  all  accounts  of  miracles  and  all  pretensions  tc 
inspiration,  and  sifting  testimony  in  a  strictly  critical  manner 
It  is  a  part  of  the  polemic  against  positive  religion,  and  of  the 
apologetic  for  enlightenment. 

Understood  as  now  indicated,  the  title  '  Philosophy  of  His- 
tory '  is  not  inappropriate  to  the  work  to  which  it  is  assigned. 
Voltaire  begins  this  work  by  indicating  some  of  the  great 
changes  which  have  taken  place  on  the  earth's  surface,  and 
then  proceeds  to  remark  on  the  different  races  of  mankind, 
and  on  the  antiquity  of  nations.  He  holds  races  to  have  been 
entirely  distinct,  the  primitive  condition  of  men  to  have  been 
brutal,  and  the  formation  of  societies  and  languages  to  have 
been  slow.  At  the  same  time,  he  affirms  the  natural  rational- 
ity, sociability,  and  perfectibility  of  our  species.  Man  lived 
for  a  long  time  without  speech,  but  he  has  never  lived  in  isola- 
tion, nor  has  he  ever  been  devoid  of  pity  and  justice,  which 
are  the  foundations  of  society.  "  God  has  given  us  a  principle 
of  universal  reason,  as  He  has  given  feathers  to  birds  and  fur 
to  bears."  Voltaire  proceeds  to  dwell  on  the  difficulty  with 
which  primitive  men  have  formed  spiritual  and  metaphysical 
conceptions.  His  views  as  to  the  origin  and  causes  of  re- 
ligion are  much  the  same  as  those  which  are  now  prevalent 
among  anthropologists.  He  assigns  great  importance  in  this 
connection  to  dreams.  He  describes  how  small  peoples  had 
each  at  first  its  own  particular  gods,  its  local  tutelary  deities ; 
how  they  afterwards  came  to  borrow  and  naturalise  each 
other's  gods ;  how  at  a  still  later  period  the  apotheosis  of 
great  men  was'  introduced;  how  at  length  sages  rose  to  the 


296  PHILOSOPHY    OF    HISTORY    IN    FKANCE 

belief  in  One  God;  and  how  priests  have  corrupted  religion 
by  the  invention  of  theologies.  He  tries  to  indicate  the  dis- 
tinctive features  of  civilisation  in  those  ancient  nations  in 
whose  records  and  remains  it  can  first  be  distinctly  studied. 
In  delineating  the  characters  and  creeds  of  these  nations  he 
warmly  eulogises  the  Chinese,  and  is  fair  toward  the  Hindus, 
Babylonians,  Persians,  and  Egyptians,  but  shows  neither  jus- 
tice nor  mercy  towards  the  Jews.  He  enumerates  the  massa- 
cres and  other  enormities  which  they  committed ;  portrays 
them  as  "  execrable  brigands,  always  superstitious,  always 
barbarous,  abject  in  misfortune,  and  insolent  in  prosperity ;  " 
and  sneers  at  the  notion  that  they  have  been  "  the  sacred 
instruments  of  divine  vengeance  and  of  the  future  salvation 
of  the  human  race."  He  pours  out  all  the  vials  of  his  wrath 
on  Moses  and  the  prophets,  the  Bible  and  miracles.  The 
Jews  may  be  entitled,  he  thinks,  to  a  place  in  theology,  but 
they  are  entitled  to  none  in  history.  And  history  ought  to 
be  separated  from  theology,  and  treated  as  a  something 
entirely  natural  and  self-explanatory. 

What  Voltaire  sought  to  accomplish  in  his  '  Essai  sur  les 
Moeurs '  has  been  already  indicated.  His  design  cannot  be 
justly  denied  the  merit  of  originality.  It  was  essentially  dif- 
ferent from  what  Bossuet,  Vico,  or  Montesquieu  had  aimed 
at.  If  more  like  the  plan  of  Turgot,  it  was  yet  considerably 
different  from  it.  And  it  has  to  be  remembered  that  although 
Voltaire's  work  appeared  after  those  of  Montesquieu  and 
Turgot,  it  had  been  not  only  conceived  but  largely  composed 
long  before.  He  had  it  for  twenty  years  under  his  hands,  as 
it  was  in  great  part  written  for  Madame  du  CMtelet  in  1740, 
i.e.,  seventeen  years  previous  to  its  publication,  eight  years 
previous  to  the  appearance  of  Montesquieu's  '  Esprit  des 
Lois,'  and  ten  years  before  the  delivery  of  Turgot's  'Dis- 
cours '  at  the  Sorbonne.  To  understand  the  attraction  and 
influence  which  it  exercised  on  its  first  readers,  it  is  necessary 
to  bear  in  mind  its  novelty  of  plan  and  freshness  of  treatment. 
It  owes  to  them  also  in  a  great  measure  its  place  and  signifi- 
cance in  the  history  of  thought  and  literature.  Voltaire  was 
the  first  to  write  a  general  history  in  which  the  esprit  and 
mceurs  of  nations  were  throughout  regarded  asof  more  impor- 


VOLTAIRE  297 

tance  than  their  outward  fortunes  and  actions.  A  host  of 
writers,  —  French,  Italian,  English,  and  German,  —  have 
followed  his  example,  and  some  of  them  may  have  gone  much 
farther  than  he  did  along  the  path  which  he  opened  up  ;  still 
he  was  the  initiator  and  they  have  only  been  the  continuators. 

In  the  working  out  of  his  design  Voltaire  must,  I  think,  be 
admitted  to  have  rendered  most  important  services  both  to  the 
art  and  science  of  history.  The  greatest  undoubtedly  was 
that  he  applied  his  judgment  freely  and  independently  to  an 
order  of  facts  which  had  previously  been  left  almost  untouched 
by  critical  thought;  that,  devoid  of  learned  credulity,  and 
unawed  by  traditional  authority,  he  dared  to  demand  of  all 
that  passed  for  historical  both  what  evidence  there  was  that 
it  had  ever  taken  place,  and  what  was  the  worth  of  it  sup- 
posing it  had ;  and  that  he  was  not  deterred  by  the  mere 
circumstance  of  its  having  been  accepted  by  an  unbroken 
succession  of  historians  from  expressing  his  conviction  that  it 
had  never  occurred,  or  that  although  it  had  occurred,  it  was 
not  worth  recording  in  the  history  of  a  nation,  and  still  less 
in  the  history  of  humanity.  He  brought  such  light  as  there 
was  in  the  so-called  philosophy  of  his  time  directly  to  bear  on 
the  past ;  and  although  that  was  neither  a  full  nor  a  pure 
light,  it  sufficed  to  break  through,  and  in  great  measure  to 
dispel,  the  brooding  and  chaotic  night  of  credulity,  dogma- 
tism, and  absurdity  in  which  history  lay  shrouded. 

Voltaire  has  not  the  slightest  claim,  indeed,  to  be  regarded 
as  the  first  to  subject  the  materials  of  history  to  a  free  criticism. 
Vico,  Perizonius,  Simon,  Bayle,  Freret,  De  Pouilly,  Beaufort, 
and  others,  had  preceded  him.  Owing,  however,  either  to  some- 
thing in  the  matter  or  method  of  their  researches,  or  in  the  form 
and  style  in  which  they  presented  the  results  of  their  investi- 
gations, their  influence  in  diffusing  a  critical  spirit  into  the 
study  of  general  history  was  small  in  comparison  with  that 
which  he  exercised.  That  his  criticism  was  often  not  sup- 
ported by  what  the  best  historians  of  the  present  day  would 
consider  an  adequate  scholarship  must  be  admitted.  The 
standard  of  requirement  has  in  that  respect  greatly  risen  since 
he  wrote.  But  it  has  risen  through  the  spread  of  the  spirit 
which  he  did  so  much  to  introduce  into  historical  research  ; 


298  '    PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY  IN   FKANCE 

and  every  candid  and  competent  student  of  his  writings  will 
admit  that  as  to  the  whole  period  of  time  embraced  in  his 
'  Essai,'  and,  indeed,  as  to  all  periods  which  could  be  studied 
without  a  knowledge  of  Greek  and  the  oriental  languages,  his 
learning  was  for  the  age  not  only  great,  but  rested  to  an  ex- 
ceptional extent  on  original  authorities,  and  not  on  second- 
hand statements. 

Notwithstanding  all  that  had  been  done  by  his  predecessors, 
it  was  left  to  Voltaire  to  apply  the  critical  spirit  to  history 
on  a  scale  and  in  a  form  universally  interesting,  to  diffuse  it 
through  the  popular  mind,  and  to  discredit  effectually  and 
finally  the  blind  credulity  with  which  historical  writers  had 
been  accustomed  to  receive  whatever  had  been  recorded.  This, 
—  the  necessary  preparation  of  all  the  deeper  and  more  en- 
larged views  of  the  historian's  work  and  duties  which  now 
prevail,  —  he  most  successfully  accomplished,  partly  by  his 
unrivalled  wit  and  worldly  wisdom,  and  partly  by  independent 
research,  by  really  going  back  to  the  primary  witnesses,  and 
freely  testing  the  special  and  general  reasons  for  the  accept- 
ance or  rejection  of  their  evidence. 

The  historian  has  to  decide  on  the  worth  and  significance 
of  facts  no  less  than  on  the  evidence  for  the  reality  and  cir- 
cumstances of  their  occurrence,  and  Voltaire  showed  his  inde- 
pendence of  judgment  in  the  former  no  less  than  in  the  latter 
respect.  He  did  more  than  any  one  else  to  rescue  history 
from  the  purblind  pedants  who  confounded  it  with  an  unre- 
flective  and  chaotic  compilation  of  facts,  and  more  than  any 
one  else  to  show  that  it  had  better  work  than  to  dwell  in  courts 
and  camps,  and  to  describe  chiefly  intrigues  and  battles.  Per- 
fect in  the  use  both  of  ridicule  and  argument,  he  jeered  and 
reasoned  the  dull  story-telling  race  as  nearly  out  of  existence 
as  indulgent  nature  would  permit.  He  insisted  on  the  duty 
of  the  judicious  choice  of  facts,  and  exemplified  the  advantages 
of  attention  to  it.  He  showed,  both  by  precept  and  practice, 
that  the  aim  of  the  historian's  labours  was  to  trace  the  growth 
of  national  life  and  character,  and  that  the  end  should  deter- 
mine the  relative  importance  assigned  to  events  ;  and  he  suc- 
ceeded in  impressing  the  lesson  on  the  European  mind  better 
than  any  other  man  could  have  done.     The  value  of  this  ser- 


VOLTAIRE  299 

vice  should  not  be  denied  or  depreciated  because  his  judgment 
was  not  always  just,  or  because  he  did  not  always  estimate  the 
importance  and  bearing  of  events  without  bias.  The  indepen- 
dence of  his  judgment  was  a  merit  even  where  unaccompanied 
by  the  still  higher  merit  of  truth. 

He  is  not  to  be  ranked  among  historical  sceptics.  He  neither 
advocated  any  general  theory  of  historical  scepticism,  nor  even 
any  of  the  distinctive  principles  of  such  a  theory.  Indeed,  he 
has  nowhere  discussed  questions  as  to  the  rules  of  historical 
research,  or  as  to  the  validity  or  limits  of  historical  knowledge. 
His  essay,  entitled  'Pyrrhonisme  de  l'histoire,'  is  occupied 
with  special  not  general  questions,  with  questions  of  fact,  not 
of  theory.  It  is  simply  an  attempt  to  show  that  historians 
have  displayed  an  excessive  credulity  on  a  variety  of  points 
of  ancient  and  modern  history,  and  have  decided  without  or 
contrary  to  evidence. 

Michelet  considers  what  he  calls  le  sens  humain,  manifested 
in  the  '  Essai  sur  les  Moeurs '  to  be  its  most  marked  character- 
istic.    He  means  that  while  Voltaire  treats  external  agencies, 
social  customs,  and  positive  institutions  as  only  of  secondary 
and  subordinate  importance  in  history,  he  recognises  the  uni- 
versal properties  of  human  nature  itself,  and  especially  jus- 
tice and  pity,  to  be  primary  and  fundamental.     It  must  be 
admitted  that  this  is  true ;  but  it  must  also  be  acknowledged 
that  his  conception  of  human  nature  was  mean,  and  that  if 
he  had  more  humanitarian  feeling  than  was  common  among 
the  writers  of  the  age  of  Louis  XIV.,  he  had  less  of  it  than 
was  generally  to  be  found  among  those  of  the  latter  part  of 
the  eighteenth  century,  and  than  has  become  almost  univer- 
sally diffused  in  the  present  day.     While  he  had  a  heart  ready 
to  revolt  and  protest  against  injustice  and  cruelty  when  they 
came  before  him  in  distinct  forms  and  special  instances,  he 
was  only  moderately  endowed  with  the  love  of  man  as  man, 
or  with  love  of  the  class  the  most  numerous  and  poor.     HeJ 
believed  neither  in  the  unity  of  origin  of  the  human  species  I 
nor  in  the  equality  of  human  raees.     He  was  full  of  aristo-M 
cratic  contempt  for  ordinary  mankind.     The  vast  majority  ofA 
men  he  held  had  been  in  all  ages  weak  and  credulous  fools,  \ 
deservedly  the  dupes  and  slaves  of  the  intelligent  and  reso-  ' 


300  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

I  lute.  The  ruling  minority  he  deemed  to  have  consisted 
mostly  of  the  selfish  and  unscrupulous.  Human  sympathy 
often  displays  its  presence  in  the  'Essai';  but  not  more 
frequently  than  human  pride  and  disdain,  shown  in  the  con- 
viction and  feeling  that  humanity  is,  and  has  always  been, 

1  almost  entirely  composed  of  a  rabble  multitude  and  a  ras- 

|  cally  few,  la  canaille  et  les  fripons. 

Voltaire's  appreciation  of  civilisation  was  likewise  at  once 
very  sincere  so  far  as  it  went  and  yet  very  defective.  He 
had  a  genuine  enthusiasm  for  culture  of  a  kind ;  a  keen  sense 
of  the  worth  of  science,  art,  literature,  and  social  refinement. 
But  for  such  enthusiasm  and  susceptibility  he  would  never 
have  formed  the  design  of  tracing  the  stages  through  which 
European  society  had  passed  from  barbarism  to  civilisation. 
They  supplied  the  inspiration  of  what  is  best  in  his  work; 
they  account  for  the  superiority  of  its  later  to  its  earlier  vol- 
umes, and  for  the  spirit  and  the  brightness  of  the  descriptions 
of  the  advances  achieved  during  the  Renaissance,  and  under 
Charles  V.,  Henry  IV.,  and  Richelieu.  But  his  idea  of  civil- 
isation itself  was  most  imperfect.  It  excluded  all  earnest 
religious  faith,  and  included  nothing  higher  than  intellectual 
cleverness,  moral  respectability,  and  polished  manners.  It 
was  not  the  idea  of  a  civilisation  appropriative  of  all  that 
is  human,  comprehensive  of  all  that  educates  mental  and 
spiritual  life,  and  which  while  it  should  refine  and  discipline 
nature  should  likewise  preserve  its  simplicity,  respect  its 
freedom,  and  favour  individual  and  national  originality ;  but 
rather  that  of  a  civilisation  of  a  special  and  artificial  type, 
such  as  can  only  be  local  and  temporary,  and  as  was  to  be 
seen  in  all  its  glory  in  the  fashionable  salons  and  philosophic 
circles  of  Paris  in  the  Voltairian  period.  Civilisation,  in  fact, 
was  conceived  of  by  Voltaire  and  the  generality  of  his  con- 
temporaries in  a  way  which  goes  far  to  explain  how  Rousseau 
should  have  maintained  that  civilisation  was  a  curse  instead 
of  a  blessing,  and  had  been  the  destruction  of  the  innocence 
and  happiness  of  the  human  race,  and  why  he  should  have 
found  so  many  to  agree  with  him. 

One  of  Voltaire's  chief  disqualifications  as  an  historian  was 
his  incapacity  to  appreciate  with  sympathy  and  fairness  relig- 


VOLTAIRE  301 

ious  phenomena.  It  is  not  to  be  denied  that  he  saw  clearly 
and  accurately  some  of  the  causes  of  the  origination  and  spread 
of  religion,  and  some  of  the  influences  which  have  moulded 
its  forms ;  but  this  did  not  prevent  his  lamentably  failing  to 
do  justice  to  religion  and  its  forms,  even  regarded  simply 
as  historical  facts  and  forces.  He  was  naturally  prone  to  be 
bitter,  unmeasured,  and  unscrupulous  in  his  enmities,  and 
actually  was  all  these  in  his  enmity  to  positive  religion.  His 
fanatical  hatred  of  it  had,  as  it  could  not  but  have,  the  most 
disastrous  effect  on  his  character  even  as  an  historian,  which 
is  the  only  respect  in  which  I  am  here  regarding  him.  It  pre- 
vented his  attaining  to  any  correct  understanding,  or  truly 
philosophic  view,  of  the  deeper  spirit  of  history. 

All  doctrines  in  which  men  had  tried  to  express  their  sense 
of  the  Divine  in  things,  all  rites  seemingly  strange  and  bizarre 
springing  from  the  same  root,  and,  in  a  word,  all  manifestations 
of  religious  faith  and  sentiment  which  were  not  in  conformity 
with  his  narrow  prejudiced  rationalism  and  unsteady  abstract 
deism,  he  was  always  ready  to  pronounce  ridiculous  absurdities, 
gross  impostures,  wicked  lies  of  ambitious  priests  and  rulers, 
and  to  assume  that  when  once  this  was  done  his  business  with 
them  was  accomplished.  This  fault  may  be  so  far  excused 
inasmuch  as  Voltaire,  although  marvellously  qualified  to  be  the 
exponent  of  the  spirit  of  his  age,  possessed  no  exceptional 
strength  to  resist  it  or  to  rise  above  it ;  yet  none  the  less  it 
was  an  enormous  defect.  Religion  is  in  scarcely  any  of  its 
forms  so  wholly  false  as  he  supposed,  so  entirely  either  inven- 
tion or  illusion.  And  even  were  it  so,  the  historian's  task  as 
regards  religion,  far  from  being  finished  when  he  has  declared 
any  religious  system  false,  cannot  be  reasonably  considered  to 
have  been  then  even  begun.  It  is  no  part  at  all  of  the  his- 
torian's proper  work  to  judge  of  the  truth  or  falsity  of  any 
religion ;  it  is  for  the  religious  apologist  or  polemic,  for  the 
religious  evidentialist  or  controversialist,  to  do  that.  The 
historian  in  dealing  with  religion  is  only  required  impartially 
and  accurately  to  show  how  its  various  forms  and  institutions, 
doctrines  and  rites,  have  attained  historical  realisation ;  how 
they  have  influenced  the  intellects  and  the  characters  of  indi- 
viduals and  generations ;  how  they  have  affected  and  modified 


302  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  IN   FKANCE 

the  lives  of  societies  and  the  destinies  of  nations ;  and  how 
they  have  contributed  to  the  development  of  morality,  policy, 
art,  science,  and  philosophy.  Instead  of  doing  this,  Voltaire 
occupied  himself  throughout  his  '  Essai '  in  assaulting  positive 
religions  as  corruptions  of  natural  religion,  and  in  seeking  to 
find  in  history  the  means  of  discrediting  them. 

He  was  especially  embittered  against  Christianity.  Hence, 
whereas  Bossuet  had  sought  to  make  the  Christian  Church  the 
centre  of  all  history  and  the  source  of  all  that  is  good  in  his- 
tory, he  endeavoured  to  turn  all  history  into  a  polemic  against 
it,  and  represented  it  as  the  chief  source  of  the  evils  of  the 
ages  through  which  it  had  passed,  —  a  much  falser  position 
still,  and  one  more  incompatible  with  a  sound  comprehension 
of  the  nature  and  course  of  the  historical  movement.  He  has 
treated  Mohammedanism  with  more  favour  than  Christianity, 
and  has  represented  Confucianism  as  superior  to  them  both. 
The  care  with  which  he  showed  that  the  great  heathen  nations 
of  Asia  had  attained  to  no  inconsiderable  height  of  speculative 
knowledge  was  almost  as  much  owing  to  his  dislike  of  the 
Christian  faith  as  to  his  love  of  truth.  He  saw  little  else  than 
decadence  in  the  centuries  of  transition  from  Roman  paganism 
to  medieval  Christendom.  He  was  a  harsh  judge  of  the  mid- 
dle ages, — those  of  faith  and  of  an  undivided  and  all-powerful 
Church.  He  was  as  indulgent,  however,  towards  the  Church 
as  represented  by  Leo  X.  and  his  cardinals,  as  he  was  intol- 
erant towards  her  as  reformed  by  Luther,  Calvin,  and  their 
associates. 

Voltaire  failed  to  recognise  clearly  in  history  a  compre- 
/  hensive  plan,  a  pervasive  order,  such  as  implies  a  Divine  will 
operating  through  human  wills,  a  first  cause  working  through 
secondary  causes.  Blindness  in  this  regard  makes  itself  felt  in 
his  whole  treatment  of  the  subject,  and  gives  to  his  book,  not- 
withstanding conspicuous  excellences,  a  certain  character  of 
meanness  which  cannot  well  be  described,  but  which  produces 
a  sad  and  disheartening  impression.  The  defect  is  to  some  ex- 
tent an  inconsistency ;  for  among  the  few  principles  to  which 
he  clung  with  anything  like  steadiness,  was  belief  in  an  al- 
mighty and  righteous  God,  and  why  he  should  have  practically 
denied  that  history  presents  any  evidence  of  His  power  and 


- 


VOLTAIRE  303 

justice  is  not  at  first  apparent.  Yet  it  was  a  natural  result  of 
the  unworthy  conception  he  had  formed  of  Christianity,  and 
of  his  consequent  want  of  sympathy  with  the  spiritual  life  of 
the  past,  and  even  hostility  to  the  past  as  a  whole.  He  could 
paint  vividly  and  truly  certain  aspects  of  the  middle  ages ; 
but  he  could  not  possibly,  his  own  spirit  being  what  it  was, 
understand  its  real  spirit.  His  quick,  versatile,  widely  read, 
and  susceptible  mind  caught  many  glimpses  of  historical  truth, 
but  could  not  attain  to  a  steady  perception  of  the  rational- 
ity of  the  historical  development  in  its  entirety.  As  his  anti- 
religious  prejudices  blinded  him  to  the  power  and  operation 
of  the  higher  forces  of  history,  he  had  to  seek  the  explana- 
tion of  it  exclusively  in  its  own  lower  forces.  Hence  his 
inability  to  trace  the  outlines  of  a  general  plan  in  history. 
Hence  his  representation  of  human  nature  as  a  far  meaner 
thing  than  it  is.  Hence  his  ascription  to  small  causes  and_[ 
accidental  circumstances,  of  a  far  greater  power  over  the  lives 
of  nations  than  they  exert.  Hence  his  exhibition  of  supersti- 
tions, irrational  habits,  mere  brute  violence  as  the  great  min- 
isters of  destiny,  the  chief  moving  forces  of  history,  which  thus 
appears  as  a  badly  composed  drama,  half  tragedy  and  half  farce, 
a  burlesque  of  a  sacred  subject,  partly  hateful  and  partly  ridic- 
ulous. Hence  the  essential  truth  of  these  words  of  Carlyle : 
"  '  The  Divine  Idea,  that  which  lies  at  the  bottom  of  Appear- 
ance,' was  never  more  invisible  to  any  man.  History  is  for 
him  not  a  mighty  drama  enacted  on  the  theatre  of  Infinitude, 
with  Suns  for  lamps,  and  Eternity  as  a  background;  whose 
author  is  God,  and  whose  purport  and  thousandfold  moral  lead 
us  up  to  the  'dark  excess  of  light'  of  the  Throne  of  God;  but 
a  poor  wearisome  debating-club  dispute,  spun  through  ten 
centuries,  between  the  Encyclopedic  and  the  Sorbonne." 1 

There  is,  in  fact,  in  Voltaire's  '  Essai '  a  decided  want  of 
philosophy.  '  Keen,  clear,  boundlessly  clever  as  it  shows  its 
author  to  have  been,  there  is  little  trace  in  it  of  the  caution 
and  comprehensiveness  of  judgment,  the  patient  and  method- 
ical verification  of  opinions,  the  catholicity  of  feeling,  and 
control  over  temper,  which  all  philosophy  demands,  and  the 
philosophy  of  history  more  perhaps  than  any  other  kind  of 

1  Essays,  vol.  ii.  p.  135  (ed.  1872). 


304  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

philosophy.  He  got  much  deeper  into  his  subject  than  the 
historical  compilers  against  whom  he  waged  war ;  but  he  did 
not  get  near  to  the  heart  of  it,  nor  attain  a  rational  compre- 
hension of  it. 

Of  all  his  prose  works,  the  '  Essai '  is  the  most  remarkable 
and  the  most  valuable.  It  has  had  a  great  influence  on  the 
development  of  historical  literature,  and  will  always  have  a 
distinctive  place  assigned  to  it  in  every  impartial  survey  of 
that  literature.  It  shows  us,  perhaps,  more  completely  than 
any  of  his  other  writings,  at  once  the  strength  and  the  weak- 
ness of  his  intellect  when  fully  exerted  on  a  magnificent 
theme.  After  studying  that  intellect  as  there  exhibited,  it 
seems  to  me  impossible  to  characterise  it  with  more  accuracy 
and  force  than  Carlyle  has  already  done  in  these  few  words : 
"  Let  him  [Voltaire]  but  cast  his  eye  over  any  subject,  in  a 
moment  he  sees,  though  indeed  only  to  a  short  depth,  yet 
with  instinctive  decision,  where  the  main  bearings  of  it  for 
that  short  depth  lie ;  what  is,  or  appears  to  be,  its  logical 
coherence ;  how  causes  connect  themselves  with  effects  ;  how 
the  whole  is  to  be  seized,  and  in  lucid  sequence  represented 
to  his  own  or  to  other  minds.  But  below  the  short  depth 
alluded  to,  his  view  does  not  properly  grow  dim,  but  alto- 
gether terminates :  thus  there  is  nothing  further  to  occasion 
him  misgivings ;  has  he  not  already  sounded  into  that  basis 
of  boundless  darkness  on  which  all  things  firmly  rest?  What 
lies  below  is  delusion,  imagination,  some  form  of  superstition 
or  folly,  which  he,  nothing  doubting,  altogether  casts  away."1 

1  Essays,  vol.  ii.  p.  164. 


CHAPTER   IV 

EIGHTEENTH   CENTURY   CONTINUED:    ROUSSEAU   TO   CON- 

DORCET 


The  great  and  momentous  change  in  the  spirit  and  temper 
of  the  French  people  which  made  itself  outwardly  manifest 
immediately  after  the  death  of  Louis  XIV.,  became  always 
more  thorough  and  complete  until  the  Revolution,  which  had 
been  long  foreseen  and  often  foretold,  at  length  broke  forth. 
In  the  writings  of  Voltaire,  Montesquieu,  and  Turgot,  it 
showed  itself  in  a  stage  already  far  advanced,  yet  in  one  still 
essentially  moderate  and  reasonable.  As  time  passed  on, 
however,  and  as  the  degeneracy  of  the  ruling  classes  and  the 
effeteness  of  the  old  methods  of  government  became  always 
more  keenly  felt,  dangerous  passions  also  became  always 
increasingly  inflamed,  extreme  and  one-sided  views  more 
prevalent,  hatred  to  authority  intensified,  and  Utopian  theo- 
ries more  credulausly  accepted. 

The  old  order  of  society  could  not  endure.  The  only 
question  was,  How  was  it  to  give  place  to  another?  Was 
it  to  be  through  the  action  of  the  monarch  or  of  the  people  ? 
I  see  no  reason  for  believing  that  it  might  not  have  been 
brought  about  in  the  former  way;  that  the  Revolution  in 
the  form  which  it  actually  assumed  was  inevitable  even 
at  the  accession  of  Louis  XVI.  Had  the  ruler  then  given 
to  France  been  not  that  weak  well-meaning  monarch,  but 
a  clear-sighted  and  resolute  reforming  king;  a  man  with 
the  intellect  and  will  of  a  Cromwell  or  of  a  Frederick 
the  Great;  one  who  would  have  kept  his  wife  and  court- 
iers in  their  proper  places;  who  would  have  seen  to  the 
discipline,  and  made  sure  of  the  loyalty  of  his  army;  who 
would  have  steadfastly  supported  his  Turgots  and  other  like- 

305 


306  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

minded  ministers  and  administrators ;  who  would  have  called 
to  such  work  as  was  most  conducive  to  their  country's  good 
the  ablest  of  the  men  of  talent  at  that  time  abounding  in 
France,  instead  of  leaving  them  to  declaim  about  tyrants  and 
priests,  the  sovereignty  of  the  people  and  the  rights  of  men; 
who  would  have  removed  the  burdens  under  which  the  peas- 
antry groaned,  withdrawn  unnatural  restrictions  on  individ- 
ual energy,  and  abolished  unjust  and  offensive  distinctions 
and  privileges :  had  such  a  man  succeeded  to  the  throne  of 
France  when  Louis  XVI.  did,  there  would  have  been  no 
French  Revolution  like  that  which  actually  happened,  no 
taking  of  the  Bastille  or  "night  of  spurs,"  no  September 
massacres  or  Reign  of  Terror,  and  yet  all  the  principles  and 
strivings  which  led  to  the  Revolution  might  have  been  as 
fully  realised.  The  Revolution  may  have  no  more  added  to 
the  power  or  influence  of  the  stream  of  thought  and  tendency 
which  pervaded  and  characterised  the  eighteenth  century 
than  the  cataracts  of  Niagara  increase  the  force  or  volume  of 
the  St.  Lawrence. 

When  under  Louis  XVI.  the  incompetence  of  the  mon- 
archy to  accomplish  the  work  of  social  and  political  reform 
which  was  manifestly  indispensable  had  become  apparent  to 
all,  the  representatives  of  the  people  easily  seized  the  reins 
of  power.  They  eagerly  undertook  to  achieve  what  the 
sovereign  had  failed  to  effect.  But  their"  divisions,  their 
jealousies,  their  unfamiliarity  with  governmental  practice, 
their  want  of  appropriate  administrative  machinery,  the 
vagueness  of  their  theories  and  schemes,  the  extravagance  of 
their  expectations,  and  the  chaotic  excitement  of  the  public 
mind,  made  orderly  and  peaceable  reform  impossible,  fierce 
struggles  and  violent  measures  inevitable.  Hence  the  Revo- 
lution. With  that  event  the  ideas  and  passions  which  had 
produced  it  were  set  free  by  it  to  assume  even  the  strangest 
and  most  exaggerated  forms,  and  to  attempt  even  the  most 
fantastic  and  the  most  hideous  applications.  The  minds  of 
men  were  agitated  to  the  utmost.  They  were  tossed  between 
the  extremes  of  love  and  hate,  hope  and  despair,  as  they  have 
never  been  since,  and  as  they  had  not  been  for  more  than  two 
centuries  before.  The  fountains  of  emotion  in  the  human 
heart  were  laid  bare  as  if  by  an  earthquake. 


ROUSSEAU  307 

The  historical  literature  of  the  latter  portion  of  the  eigh- 
teenth century  was  deeply  influenced  by  the  then  prevailing 
state  of  public  opinion  and  feeling.  Indeed,  it  was  affected 
by  it  to  an  extent  most  injurious  to  its  character  both  as  his- 
tory and  literature.  Not  one  good  popular  history  was  pro- 
duced during  the  whole  period.  Impartiality,  self-restraint, 
self-forgetfulness,  strict  truthfulness,  objectivity,  and,  in  a 
word,  all  the  primary  historical  virtues,  nearly  disappeared. 
Argument  and  declamation  usurped  the  places  of  narration 
and  the  disclosure  of  causation  and  development.  Instead  of 
faithfully  delineating  the  movement  and  incidents  of  history, 
and  leaving  it  to  suggest  its  own  lessons,  the  writers  who 
professed  to  be  historians  presented  history  only  so  far  as  they 
could  make  it  seem  to  testify  to  the  truth  of  views  in  the 
service  of  which  their  passions  were  enlisted.  The  great 
bulk  of  the  so-called  historical  literature  of  the  period  was, 
consequently,  of  a  controversial  and  oratorical  nature;  and 
large  so-called  histories  were  often  only  bulky  political 
pamphlets.  We  have  here  to  do  with  such  literature  merely 
in  so  far  as  it  bears  on  the  development  of  historical  theory. 

The  influence  exerted  by  Rousseau  was,  perhaps,  not  in- 
ferior to  that  of  Voltaire.  Although  it  spread  less  widely,  it 
penetrated  more  deeply ;  although  it  acted  on  opinions  with 
less  direct  effectiveness,  it  impressed  the  imagination .  and 
feelings,  more  powerfully.  Voltaire  was  a  man  of  marvel- 
lously quick  and  clear  understanding;  of  many  and  varied 
talents  always  at  their  possessor's  command;  of  restless 
intellectual  curiosity  and  rapid  literary  productiveness;  of 
liveliest  interest  in  art  and  science,  culture,  and  refinement; 
of  aristocratic  feelings  and  manners ;  of  shrewdest  worldly  tact 
and  the  most  brilliant  social  qualities.  Rousseau  was  a  man 
of  great,  although  morbid,  genius;  of  brooding  imagination 
and  passionate  heart;  of  seductive  and  overpowering  elo- 
quence; a  skilful  and  often  sophistical  dialectician;  sus- 
ceptible to  high  ideals  and  divine  inspirations,  but  also  easily 
overcome  by  mean  temptations  and  sensuous  lusts ;  unsociable 
and  jealous  by  temperament,  while  inordinately  eager  for 
notoriety  and  praise;  plebeian  in  his  tastes  and  habits;  richly 
endowed  with  the  feeling  for  nature.  Both  were  the  sons  of 
their  age,  but  Voltaire  inherited  its  more  general  character- 


308  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

istics,  and  Rousseau  such  as  were  less  common.  Hence  the 
latter  is  often  erroneously  regarded  as  having  been  a  man  of 
greater  independence  and  originality  of  thought,  and  less 
imbued  with  the  spirit  of  his  time.  In  reality,  there  Avas 
little  substantial  novelty  in  his  teaching,  and  even  when  he 
opposed  certain  tendencies  of  the  age,  it  was  in  the  spirit  of 
the  age.  Had  he  been  more  original  he  would  have  been  less 
influential. 

He  was  not,  as  Voltaire  was,  an  eminent  historian ;  he  was 
not  an  historian  at  all,  and  had  little  accurate  historical 
knowledge.  Plutarch's  'Lives  '  had  profoundly  impressed 
him,  and  he  had  loosely  read  a  number  of  historical  books ; 
but  he  knew  no  portion  of  history  well,  nor  apprehended 
truthfully  the  spirit  of  any  single  people  or  epoch.  His 
admiration  of  Athens,  Sparta,  and  Rome  was  an  ignorant 
admiration;  his  aversion  to  the  middle  ages  and  to  modern 
institutions  a  not  less  ignorant. aversion.  Yet  his  literary 
genius,  favoured  by  prevailing  tendencies,  caused  the  most 
worthless  of  his  historical  judgments  to  be  received  by  mul- 
titudes of  his  contemporaries  as  oracles  revealing  the  truth 
and  significance  of  history,  and  thus  gave  them  an  impor- 
tance to  which  they  were  far  from  entitled  in  themselves. 

It  was  chiefly,  however,  by  his  eloquent  advocacy  of  certain 
historical  hypotheses  that  he  stimulated  historical  speculation. 
To  these  we  must  now  briefly  refer. 

His  literary  career  began  with  a  'Discours  sur  la  question: 
Le  progr&s  des  sciences  et  des  arts  a-t-il  contribue"  a  corrompre 
ou  a  e'purer  les  mceurs  ?  '  (1750),  to  which  the  Academy  of 
Dijon  had  awarded  the  prize  which  it  had  offered  for  the  best 
discussion  of  the  question :  "  Le  re'etablissement  des  lettres  et 
des  arts  a-t-il  contribue'  a  corrompre  ou  a  e'purer  les  mceurs?" 
Rousseau,  in  answer  to  the  question  stated  by  himself,  affirms 
that  the  sciences  and  arts  had  depraved  the  morals  and  man- 
ners of  mankind.  He  argues  that  they  had  originated  with 
the  birth,  and  grown  with  the  growth,  of  human  vices.  He 
represents  the  researches  of  science  as  unsuited  to  the  nature 
of  the  human  intellect  and  as  leading  to  conclusions  which 
yield  no  true  satisfaction  to  the  human  heart;  indicates  how 
the  arts  minister  to  vanity  and  luxury,   and  contribute  to 


ROUSSEAU  309 

corrupt  society  and  ruin  nations ;  and  dwells  on  the  mischiev- 
ous effects  of  immoral  and  irreligious  writings.  He  vaunts 
the  virtue  of  the  primitive  ages  in  which  ignorance  and  sim- 
plicity prevailed,  and  draws  gloomy  and  satirical  pictures  of 
the  moral  condition  of  the  periods  in  which  literature  and 
culture  have  flourished.  Most  of  what  he  says  in  support  of 
his  thesis  is  true,  hut  his  thesis  itself  is  not  true.  Such 
semblance  of  being  a  proof  of  it  as  the  Discourse  possesses, 
is  due  entirely  to  its  one-sidedness.  Rousseau  refers  exclu- 
sively to  the  abuses  of  the  arts  and  sciences,  and  assumes  that 
there  was  nothing  else  respecting  them  to  which  he  ought  to 
refer.  Few  men  have  been  more  liberally  endowed  with 
the  power  of  the  myopic  vision  characteristic  of  sincere  and 
successful  advocates  of  paradoxes. 

The  'Discours  sur  l'origine  et  les  fondements  de  l'megalit^ 
parmi  les  hommes '  (1754)  is  a  much  abler  production.  It 
generalises  and  develops  the  thesis  maintained  in  the  first 
Discourse;  and,  consequently,  attacks  civilisation  in  general 
as  the  cause  of  human  misery  and  corruption,  and  represents 
history  as  having  been  a  process  not  of  amelioration  but  of 
deterioration. 

It  denies  that  man  is  corrupt  by  nature;  it  affirms  that 
he  is  good  by  nature,  and  has  been  corrupted  by  society. 
Readers  of  Rousseau's  'Emile  '  are  aware  that  this  dogma  of 
the  natural  goodness  of  man  is  the  corner-stone  of  the  theory 
of  education  therein  expounded;  it  holds  the  same  place  in 
the  theory  of  the  rise  and  development  of  inequality  given  in 
the  work  under  consideration.  The  state  of  man  as  a  primi- 
tive savage  is  represented  as  having  been  better  than  his  state 
in  any  period  of  culture.  It  was  the  state  most  conformed 
to  his  constitution,  and  one  in  which  he  would  have  done 
well  to  remain.  He  remained  in  it  for  ages,  but  not  wholly 
without  change.  The  state  of  nature  had  itself  a  certain 
development;  it  had  epochs,  or  at  least  stages. 

At  first,  men  lived  solitary,  naked,  speechless,  without 
instruments,  without  religious  or  moral  notions,  impelled 
and  guided  only  by  their  senses,  instincts,  and  simplest  bodily 
appetites.  In  this  purely  animal  condition  they  were  strong 
and  healthy,  innocent  and  happy,  without  fictitious  wants, 


310  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

and  easily  able  to  satisfy  the  few  desires  which  they  experi- 
enced. Civilised  men  have  reason  to  look  back  to  it  with 
regret.  Why,  then,  should  primitive  men  have  abandoned 
it?  Rousseau  has  no  explanation  to  give.  He  tells  us, 
indeed,  that  "  the  specific  characteristic  which  distinguishes 
man  from  the  animal  is  a  faculty  of  perfectibility  almost 
unlimited;"  but  he  is  not  so  illogical  as  to  attempt  to 
account  for  continuous  actual  deterioration  by  the  possibility 
of  indefinite  amelioration ;  and  therefore,  he  does  not  conde- 
scend to  explain  at  all  how  men  were  seduced  to  fall  aWay 
from  their  estate  of  contented  animality.  He  describes  them, 
however,  as  in  fact  finding  out  such  inventions  as  hooks 
for  fishing,  bows  and  arrows  for  hunting,  and  how  to  warm 
themselves  by  the  aid  of  fire  and  to  clothe  themselves  with 
skins. 

Next,  men  are  represented  as  gradually  proceeding  to  form 
temporary  associations  for  the  sake  of  the  benefits  to  be  thereby 
attained.  They  are  thus  slowly  led  to  invent  language  which 
is  almost  indispensable  to  association.  It  is,  however,  a 
marvellous  invention ;  and  Rousseau,  far  from  attempting  to 
explain  it,  candidly  confesses  that  it  seems  to  him  inexplica- 
ble. "The  invention  of  speech  appears  to  require  speech." 
Among  the  earliest  manifestations  of  association  are  the  con- 
struction of  huts  and  the  formation  of  family  ties,  or,  in  other 
words,  the  institution  of  private  property  and  the  establish- 
ment of  domestic  society ;  and  these  lead  to  a  greater  differ- 
entiation of  the  sexes  and  their  occupations.  Then,  men 
group  themselves  into  village  communities;  and  not  only 
natural  differences  manifest  themselves,  but  inequalities  of 
conditions  appear,  with  love  and  jealousy  and  various  dis- 
turbing and  painful  passions.  Such  is  the  general  condition 
of  savages  at  present ;  one  by  no  means  without  drawbacks ; 
and  yet  one  superior  to  the  ordinary  lot  of  men  in  all  stages 
of  civilisation. 

With  the  use  of  metals  and  the  cultivation  of  the  ground, 
the  division  of  labour  was  developed  and  private  property 
became  a  fixed  and  general  institution.  The  result  was  "the 
civilisation  of  man  and  the  destruction  of  the  human  race." 
With  indignation  Rousseau  denounces  the  appropriation  of 


ROUSSEAU  311 

the  earth  and  the  bounties  of  nature  as  robbery  of  the  race  by 
the  individual.  "  The  land  belongs  to  no  one  person,  but  to 
all;  all  that  an  individual  acquires  beyond  subsistence  is  a 
social  theft  (vol  social).'1''  With  sombre  eloquence  he  describes 
the  consequences  flowing  from  this  primary  act  of  spoliation ; 
how  it  divided  society  into  rich  and  poor,  oppressor  and 
oppressed;  how  inequalities  increased,  how  violence  spread, 
and  how  the  natural  promptings  of  pity  and  the  as  yet  feeble 
voice  of  justice  were  extinguished  and  silenced.  The  great- 
ness of  the  evil  at  length  caused  the  necessity  for  a  remedy 
to  be  universally  felt.  This  led,  however,  to  no  real  improve- 
ment, for  the  rich  and  crafty  were  able  to  turn  the  desire  to 
arrest  the  usurpations  of  the  powerful  and  the  brigandage  of 
the  disinherited  to  their  own  advantage.  "  They  formed  a 
project  the  most  astute  that  ever  entered  the  human  spirit,  hy 
which  to  convert  their  adversaries  into  their  defenders,  to 
inspire  them  with  wholly  new  maxims,  and  to  introduce 
institutions  which  would  be  as  favourable  to  them  as  natural 
law  and  the  law  of  the  strong  were  the  contrary."  It  suc- 
ceeded; and  civilisation,  society,  and  laws  were  instituted, 
"  which  gave  new  fetters  to  the  feeble,  and  new  forces  to  the 
rich ;  which  destroyed  beyond  recovery  natural  liberty,  fixed 
for  ever  the  law  of  property  and  inequality,  converted  a 
clever  usurpation  into  an  irrevocable  right,  and,  for  the  profit 
of  a  few  ambitious  men,  subjected  henceforth  all  the  human 
race  to  servitude  and  misery." 

The  establishment  of  law  and  property  required  the  insti- 
tution of  magistrates,  and  their  authority,  although  at  first 
only  delegated,  naturally  became  absolute.  The  growth  of 
inequality  and  corruption  was  thereby  favoured  in  all  forms, 
and  at  last  resulted  in  the  despotism  of  one  and  the  slavery 
of  all  the  rest, —  the  extreme  of  inequality  engendered  by  the 
excess  of  corruption.  Instead  of  being  compensations  for 
the  evils  of  civilisation,  art,  science,  and  literature  are  simply 
the  gilding  of  the  chains  of  that  state  of  slavery  and  injustice 
to  which  the  name  of  civilisation  is  given. 

No  quite  consistent  inference,  perhaps,  could  have  been 
drawn  from  Rousseau's  teaching,  seeing  that  it  was  not  self- 
consistent;  but  the  least  inconsistent  would  have  been  the 


312  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

differential  tenet  of  the  theory  known  as  nihilism  or  anarch- 
ism. Rousseau  affirmed  the  premisses  of  this  system,  and  he 
should  have  drawn  its  conclusions.  That  is  to  say,  he  should 
have  inculcated  the  suppression  of  property,  the  dissolution 
of  the  family,  the  obliteration  of  social  distinctions,  the  abo- 
lition of  all  extant  laws  and  resistance  to  the  enactment  of 
new  ones,  the  overthrow  of  government  and  authority  in 
every  form,  and,  in  a  word,  a  return  to  primitive  savagery. 
But,  resolute  dialectician  though  he  was,  he  had  not  the 
courage  to  be  thus  consistent;  he  shrank  from  advocating 
mere  social  destruction,  and  even,  propounded  a  scheme  of 
social  reconstruction. 

The  scheme  is  delineated  in  his  famous  '  Contrat  Social ' 
(1762).1  It  is  not  only  no  legitimate  sequel  to  its  author's 
hypothesis  of  historical  development,  but  is  utterly  unhistori- 
cal  in  character,  —  a  product  of  conjecture,  abstraction,  and 
argumentation,  all  divorced  from  historical  experience.  The 
'  Contrat  Social '  is  an  essentially  deductive  and  dogmatic 
work.  Its  central  conception  is  borrowed  from  Hobbes,  but 
differently  applied,  yet  not  intrinsically  improved.  Political 
Rousseauism  may  be  said  to  be  reversed  but  unamended 
Hobbism.  Rousseau,  like  Hobbes,  would  organise  society 
on  the  basis  of  a  compact  which  makes  the  ruling  will  or 
sovereign  authority  indivisible,  unlimited,  and  unconditioned ; 
only  whereas  Hobbes  would  place  the  absolute  sovereignty 
in  an  individual  will,  Rousseau  would  assign  it  to  the  col- 
lective will.  The  ideal  delineated  in  Hobbes'  'Leviathan' 
is  that  of  a  monarchical  despotism,  and  the  ideal  delineated 
in  Rousseau's  '  Social  Contract '  is  that  of  a  democratic  des- 
potism, both  ideals   being  vitiated  by  the  same  error,  the 

1  The  Library  of  Geneva  possesses  a  MS.  of  Rousseau  which  contains  the  primi- 
tive text  of  the  '  Contrat  Social,'  and  was  written  apparently  between  1754  and 
1T56.  It  was  printed  in  1887  in  a  Russian  work  on  Rousseau  by  M.  Alexieff,  and 
is  interestingly  commented  on  by  M.  Bertrand  in  a  memoir  published  in  the 
'  Compte  Rendu  of  the  Acad,  of  Mor.  and  Pol.  Sciences,'  July  1891.  It  appears 
to  M.  Bertrand  to  show  that  Rousseau  at  the  date  of  its  composition  had  become 
aware  that  his  so-called  "  state  of  nature  "  had  never  really  existed,  but  deemed 
that  it  might  be  usefully  retained  as  a  hypothetical  and  ideal  antecedent  of  society. 
This  view  is  very  probable;  but  certainly  the  picture  drawn  of  "  the  state  of 
nature"  in  the  text  and  notes  of  the  Discourse  on  the  Causes  of  Inequality  is 
very  unideal,  and  the  notion  that  actual  history  can  be  truly  or  profitably  repre- 
sented as  commencing  with  instead  of  tending  towards  an  ideal  is  a  self-contra- 
dictory and  inconsiderate  one. 


ROUSSEAU  313 

ascription  of  absolute  sovereignty  to  human  will.  While 
Rousseau  does  not  prescribe  communism  or  equality  of  wealth 
in  his  ideal  commonwealth,  he  recommends  that  it  should  be, 
as  far  as  possible,  aimed  at ;  and  while  he  does  not  prohibit 
the  holding  of  private  property,  he  affirms  that  the  community 
is  entitled  to  dispose  of  the  goods  of  all  its  members. 

No  writer  of  the  eighteenth  century  contributed  so  much  as 
Rousseau  to  diffuse  the  following  beliefs:  that  human  nature 
was  originally,  and  is  intrinsically,  good;  that  science,  art, 
and  literature  are  essentially  unfavourable  to  morality ;  that 
laws  have  been  always  and  everywhere  instituted  for  the 
oppression  of  the  poor  and  weak;  that  private  property  is 
unjust,  and  has  necessarily  caused  incalculable  misery;  that 
equality  is  of  far  more  importance  than  liberty ;  that  the 
history  of  civilisation  has  been  a  process  of  illusion,  crime, 
and  suffering,  determined  almost  exclusively  by  the  action  of 
inexplicable  accidents  and  of  evil  passions ;  that  the  basis  of 
society  in  the  future  should  be  a  contract  in  which  an  absolute 
sovereignty  is  vested  in  the  community  by  the  unlimited  sac- 
rifice of  the  independence  of  individuals ;  and  that  majorities, 
as  the  organs  of  the  collective  will,  are  entitled  to  punish,  even 
with  death,  disobedience  to  any  behests  either  as  regards  civil 
or  religious  matters  which  they  see  fit  to  enact  and  impose. 
By  his  advocacy  of  these  and  kindred  tenets  he  profoundly 
affected  social  speculation  and  practice.  How  far  his  influence 
was  good  and  how  far  it  was  evil,  this  is  not  the  place  to 
inquire.  It  was  obviously  both.  It  is  not  inaccurate  to  say 
of  him,  as  Professor  Graham  has  done,  with  reference  to  the 
very  writings  which  have  been  under  our  consideration, — 
"the  poor  had  found  a  powerful  pleader,  the  dumb  millions  a 
voice,  democracy  its  refounder,  and  humanity  in  the  eigh- 
teenth century  its  typical  representative  man,  who  gave  vent 
to  its  inmost  sentiments,  troubles,  aspirations,  and  audacious 
spirit  of  revolt;"1  but  it  is  just  as  correct  also  to  say  that  in 
him  the  poor  had  found  a  persuasive  seducer,  the  dumb  mil- 
lions a  voice  which  by  the  follies  it  uttered  discredited  what 
was  reasonable  in  their  claims,  democracy  a  reconstructor  so 
unwise  as  to  choose  for  its  corner-stone  the  very  falsehood  on 
which  despotism  rests,  and  humanity  in  the  eighteenth  century 

1  Socialism  New  and  Old,  pp.  55,  56. 


314  PHILOSOPHY   OP    HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

the  great  literary  exponent  of  those  passions  and  errors  which 
were  "  the  seeds  of  the  guillotine,"  the  germs  of  the  infamies 
of  the  Reign  of  Terror.1 

The  Abbe"  Morelly  propounded  views  very  similar  to  those 
of  Eousseau,  although  on  the  whole  even  more  radical  and 
extreme,  first  in  the  'Basiliade'  (1753),  and  afterwards  more 
systematically  in  the  'Code  de  la  Nature'  (1756),  long  erro- 
neously attributed  to  Diderot.  His  social  theories  rest  on  a 
doctrine  of  materialistic  egoism.  Man,  in  his  eyes,  is  simply 
a  physical  and  sentient  organism,  whose  sole  end  and  summum 
bonum  is  pleasure.  Human  nature  is  in  itself  wholly  innocent 
and  good.  "Morality  implies  no  antagonism  between  the 
passions  and  duty,  for  the  former  are  legitimate  and  sovereign, 
and  would  cause  no  harm  if  allowed  free  play ;  it  is  just  by 
the  irritation  and  restraint  of  the  laws  and  institutions  which 
pretend  to  have  a  right  to  confine  and  regulate  them,  that 
they  are  rendered  corrupt  and  mischievous.  The  great  social 
problem  is  to  find  a  situation  in  which  the  passions  will  be 
fully  gratified,  while  it  will  be  almost  impossible  for  men  to  be 
tempted  or  depraved.  It  can  only  be  solved  through  the 
elimination  of  avarice,  the  only  vice  in  the  world,  the  universal 
pest  of  mankind,  the  slow  fever  or  consumptive  disease  of  so- 
ciety." And  this  can  only  be  effected  by  the  suppression  of 
private  property,  by  rendering  the  possession  of  all  wealth 
indivisible  and  collective  and  the  enjoyment  of  all  products 
common,  by  the  State  regulation  of  marriage,  and  by  the 
abolition  of  public  and  private  worship. 

The  view  which  Morelly  gave  of  the  place  and  functions 

1  The  chief  general  works  on  the  life  and  writings  of  Rousseau  are  those  of 
Musset-Pathay,  Morin,  Brackerhoff ,  Saint-Mare  Girardin,  and  Morley.  A  good 
account  of  his  religious,  political,  social,  and  educational  opinions  will  be  found 
in  Emil  Feuerlein's  three  articles  —  Rousseau 'sche  Studien  —  in  the  first  and 
second  volumes  of  the  'Gedanke.'  Bluntschli,  Barante,  Janet,  and  others,  have 
specially  expounded  his  views  on  the  origin  of  society,  social  contract,  natural 
rights,  &c. ;  and  Bourgeand  has  treated  of  his  religious  teaching  (J.  J.  Rousseau's 
Religionsphilosophie,  1883).  Of  exceptional  interest  are  the  following:  'J.  J. 
Rousseau  juge  par  les  Genevois  d'aujourdhui '  (Geneve,  1879) ;  '  Les  origines  des 
idees  politiques  de  Rousseau,'  par  M.  Jules  Vuy  (Geneve,  1882) ;  Baudrillard, '  J.  J. 
Rousseau  et  le  socialisme  moderne '  (in  Etudes  de  philosophie  morale,  1. 1) ;  Caro, 
'  Le  fin  d'un  siecle,'  1. 1,  c.  3,  4 ;  Renouvier's  articles  in  '  Crit.  Phil.,'  annee  xiii. ; 
and  Prof.  E.  Caird's  paper  in  '  Cont.  Rev.'  for  Sept.  1877.  Few  have  written  re- 
garding Rousseau  with  so  much  judgment  and  insight  as  P.  C.  Schlosser,  'Hist, 
of  the  Eighteenth  Century,'  vol.  i.  pp.  285-314,  Eng.  tr.  Rousseau  treats  of 
history  from  an  educational  point  of  view  in  '  Emile,'  iv.  1. 


MOEELLY —  MABLY  315 

of  the  passions  in  the  social  economy  has  a  special  claim  to 
be  remarked,  owing  to  the  use  which  was  made  of  it  by 
Fourier  and  his  followers.  Morelly  was  the  direct  and 
immediate  precursor  of  Fourier,  inasmuch  as  he  laid  the 
foundation-stone  of  Phalansterianism.  But  the  system 
which  he  himself  attempted  to  build  on  it  was  a  very  dif- 
ferent one ;  it  was  a  socialism  of  the  kind  which  has  become 
familiar  to  us  in  recent  times  as  Collectivism.  He  is,  per- 
haps, more  entitled  than  any  one  else  to  be  called  the  orig- 
inator of  the  theory  of  modern  Collectivism.  A  collectivist 
socialism  was  his  ideal  of  the  future  of  human  society.  As 
to  the  past,  the  course  of  actual  history,  he  represented  it  as 
having  been  essentially  a  process  of  falsehood  and  cruelty,  of 
folly  and  crime.  He  was,  like  so  many  of  his  contempora- 
ries, pessimist  as1  to  the  past  and  optimist  as  to  the  future ; 
that  he  was  a  social  revolutionist  followed  naturally  from  his 
non-recognition  of  the  continuity  of  history.1 

The  Abbe"  de  Mably  (1709-85)  was  a  man  of  a  very  dif- 
ferent type  of  character  than  either  Rousseau  or  Morelly,  but 
in  its  general  scope  and  direction  his  thinking  had  much  in 
common  with  theirs.  He  was  austere,  independent,  and  dis- 
interested ;  he  cared  little  for  pleasure,  power,  or  fame  ;  con- 
science was  his  stay  and  guide ;  he  saw  in  virtue  the  chief 
source  and  primary  condition  of  individual  and  social  pros- 
perity. None  of  his  contemporaries  insisted  so  strongly  on  the 
intimate  relationship  of  morals  and  politics ;  the  dependence 
of  the  latter  on  the  former  seemed  to  him  the  great  lesson 
taught  by  history.  He  was  not  a  believer  in  Christianity,  but 
he  had  a  steady  faith  in  God  and  the  moral  law.  Although 
in  his  earliest  publication  he  appeared  as  the  eulogist  of  abso- 
lute monarchy,  he  soon  afterwards  became  an  ardent  admirer 
of  the  republican  form  of  government,  and  he  did  much  to 
spread  and  confirm  republican  predilections  in  France.  His 
political  views  were  mainly  the  results  of  his  reflections  on 
ancient  history ;  the  institutions  of  classical  antiquity  seemed 
to  him  to  furnish  models  of  political  wisdom ;  and  the  lives 
of  illustrious  citizens  of  Greece  and  Rome  suggested  to  him 
ideals  of  political  virtue.     Sparta  was  the  special  object  of  his 

1  P.  Villegardelle,  '  Code  de  la  nature,  augmente  de  fragments  importants  de 
la  Basiliade,  avec  l'analyse  raisonne  du  systeme  sociale  de  Morelly.'    1847. 


316  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

idolatrous  veneration.  Of  course,  the  theatrical  antiquity  of 
which  he  was  the  panegyrist  never  existed  elsewhere  than  in 
excited  and  romantic  imaginations. 

He  has  expounded  his  political  and  juristic  creed  in  two 
treatises  of  considerable  interest,  the  '  Entretiens  de  Phocion ' 
(1763)  and  'De  la  Legislation'  (1776).  For  our  purpose  it 
is  sufficient  simply  to  note  the  following  points.  Mably  has 
enlarged  on  the  dependence  of  politics  and  legislation  on 
morality,  and  has  strongly  insisted  that  morality  cannot 
maintain  itself  in  a  society  devoid  of  religious  faith,  ex- 
pressly condemning  the  opinions  of  Machiavelli  and  Bayle 
to  the  contrary.  He  recommends  a  community  of  goods 
and  the  banishment  of  commerce  and  the  fine  arts  from  a 
republic.  He  represents  social  inequalities  as  unjust  and 
pernicious,  and  private  property  as  their  primary  cause.  He 
holds  that  equality  was  the  first  stage  of  society,  and  that 
it  will  be  also  its  final  form.  He  admits,  however,  that 
it  cannot  be  easily  or  immediately  attained,  and  therefore 
merely  advises  that  properties  be  kept  small,  luxury  in  its 
various  forms  repressed,  and  all  due  care  taken  to  prevent 
both  the  growth  of  pauperism  and  the  individual  accumula- 
tion of  wealth.  It  shows  the  extent  to  which  he  was  misled 
by  his  admiration  of  the  Greek  republics,  that,  in  despite  of 
his  socialism  and  equalitarianism,  he  would  exclude  artisans 
from  participation  in  public  affairs. 

Two  of  Mably's  smaller  treatises  belong  to  the  department 
of  Historic— the  'De  l'Etude  de  l'Histoire'  (1778),  and  'De 
la  maniere  d'e'crire  Histoire '  (1782).  Both  are  contained  in 
the  twelfth  volume  of  the  collected  edition  of  his  works. 
They  are  rather  commonplace  and  disappointing  produc- 
tions. The  first  mentioned,  written  for  the  use  of  the  young 
Prince  of  Parma,  dwells  on  the  benefits  which  a  ruler  may 
derive  from  the  study  of  history,  and  especially  from  the 
historical  study  of  law  and  government.  The  other,  which 
is  the  better  of  the  two,  especially  insists  on  the  importance 
to  an  historian  of  the  study  of  the  principles  of  morality  and 
politics.  This  latter  treatise  has  a  certain  measure  of  inter- 
est from  the  way  in  which  the  classical  historians,  Thucyd- 
ides,  Sallust,  Tacitus,  and  Plutarch,  are  upheld  as  models, 
while  De  Thou,  Voltaire,  Hume,  and  Robertson  are  subjected 


MABLY  317 

to  sharp  censures.  Voltaire's  'Essai  sur  les  Moeurs,'  for 
example,  is  pronounced  to  be  only  "une  pasquinade  digne 
des  lecteurs  qui  l'admirent  sur  la  foi  de  nos  philosophes  " 
(p.  445).  Of  modern  historians  Vertot  alone  is  praised  by 
Mably  with  warmth.  What  one  misses  above  all  in  the  trea- 
tises to  which  I  refer,  is  any  trace  of  reflection  on  the  condi- 
tions and  methods  of  historical  research.  No  attempt  is  made 
in  them  to  analyse  the  processes  of  historical  investigation, 
and  to  determine  what  requirements  ought  to  be  fulfilled 
in  sifting  and  appreciating  historical  evidence.  While  they 
belong,  therefore,  to  the  province  of  Historic,  they  cannot 
be  said  to  have  been  of  any  special,  and  certainly  not  of  any 
scientific,  importance  therein. 

Neither  Rousseau  nor  Morelly  gave  much  attention  to  the 
study  of  history.  Mably  did,  and  he  wrote  at  least  one  his- 
torical work  of  very  considerable  merit  —  '  Observations  sur 
l'Histoire  de  la  France '  (2  vols.  1T65,  with  posthumous  con- 
tinuation, 2  vols.  1790).  It  was  re-edited  by  M.  Guizot,  and 
well  deserved  the  honour,  owing  to  the  light  which  it  casts  on 
the  constitutional  history  of  France.  It  was  not  only  actu- 
ally drawn  from  the  primary  documents,  but  quoted  them 
throughout,  so  far  as  they  were  founded  on,  and  thus  the 
reader  can  judge  for  himself  whether  or  not  Mably  correctly 
interpreted  the  authorities  on  which  he  relied.  It  will  be 
found  that  he  frequently  did  not;  that  he  was  in  many  in- 
stances an  unsatisfactory  exegete ;  but  this  does  not  deprive 
him  of  the  merit,  the  rare  and  immense  merit,  of  always  ad- 
ducing for  his  statements  as  to  historical  fact  what  he  believed 
to  be  the  original  and  proper  evidence  for  them.  He  was 
among  the  first  of  historians  fully  and  practically  to  recog- 
nise that  what  is  of  prime  importance  to  a  student  of  history 
is  to  obtain  a  clear  view  of  the  evidence,  and  that  where  this 
is  not  given,  historical  narrative,  although  it  may  please  the 
imagination  or  exercise  faith,  cannot  train  the  judgment  or 
satisfy  the  appetite  for  truth.  The  defects  to  be  found  in 
Mably 's  treatment  of  French  history  arose  mainly  from  the 
rigidity  of  his  historical  ideal  and  the  narroAvness  of  his  histor- 
ical sympathy.  He  so  overestimated  the  pagan  type  of  virtue, 
that  he  could  not  fairly  appreciate  the  manifestations  of  Chris- 
tian life.    His  taste  was  so  exclusively  classical  that  medieval 


318  PHILOSOPHY    OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

manners  and  institutions  unduly  offended  him.  His  admira- 
tion of  the  Lacedemonian  republic  was  of  a  kind  which  ren- 
dered it  impossible  for  him  to  be  just  to  the  French  monarchy. 
All  modern  history  was  thus  in  his  eyes  a  decadence. 

By  the  way  in  which  Rousseau,  Morelly,  and  Mably  incul- 
cated and  diffused  the  idea  of  equality,  they  laid  the  foun- 
dation of  the  socialist  theory  of  history.  They  ignored,  or 
implicitly  denied,  progress  in  history ;  and  although  they 
may  have  here  and  there  verbally  affirmed  the  perfectibility 
of  man,  the  general  tenor  of  their  teaching  as  regards  the 
course  of  human  affairs  in  the  past  is  inconsistent  therewith. 
In  words,  they  glorified  liberty,  as  all  their  contemporaries 
did ;  but  they  showed  by  the  proposals  which  they  put  forth 
that  they  were  ready  to  sacrifice  it  in  any  sphere  of  life  and 
to  an  almost  unlimited  extent  if  the  realisation  of  equality 
could  thereby  be  promoted.  The  equality,  however,  which 
involves  the  sacrifice  of  liberty  must  be  also  destructive  both 
of  social  order  and  of  social  progress ;  and  consequently  its 
advocacy  must  be  inconsistent  with  the  admission  of  true 
conceptions  of  historical  development,  a  process  which  can 
only  be  natural  and  normal  where  there  is  a  due  combination 
and  correlation  of  factors  and  an  appropriate  interdependence 
and  co-operation  of  functions.  Hence  the  reason  why  socialist 
theories  of  history  are  so  generally  unsatisfactory ;  their  au- 
thors have  not  sufficiently  reflected  on  a  preliminary  question 
of  decisive  importance,  — -  the  question  which  Shakespeare 
puts  into  the  mouth  of  Ulysses :  — 

"How  could  communities, 
Degrees  in  schools,  and  brotherhoods  in  cities, 
Peaceful  commerce,  and  dividable  shores, 
The  primogenitive  and  due  of  birth, 
Prerogative  of  age,  crowns,  sceptres,  laurels, 
But  by  degree,  stand  in  authentic  place?  " 

The  brother  of  the  Abbe"  de  Mably,  the  Abbe"  de  Condillac 
(1715-80),  who  was,  in  the  opinion  of  his  contemporaries,  the 
philosopher  of  their  age,  and  the  truest  teacher  of  philosophy 
of  all  ages,  published  a  'Universal  History'  (1775)  in  thirteen 
volumes,  yet  a  few  lines  are,  perhaps,  all  to  which  he  is  here 
entitled.  His  '  Universal  History '  aimed  at  tracing  the  his- 
tory of  philosophical  opinions,  of  the  sciences,  and  of  civilisa- 


CONDILLAC 


319 


tion.  Its  author's  desire  to  select  and  present  what  was  likely 
to  be  instructive  and  improving  is  throughout  conspicuous ; 
and  his  constant  preoccupation  to  discover  and  indicate  the 
causes  and  effects  of  events  is  not  less  manifest.  But  the 
work  has  the  fatal  defect  of  being  altogether  wanting  in  re- 
search and  criticism.  The  facts  in  it  are  in  grains  and  the 
reflections  in  bushels.  The  course  of  historical  causation  is 
not  shown  to  have  been  in  the  historical  development  by 
exhibition  of  the  facts,  but  is  only  diffusely  declared  to  have 
been  so  in  the  opinion  of  the  author.  Besides,  the  statements 
of  fact  are  not  only  intolerably  few  in  comparison  with  those 
of  reflection,  but  they  are  obviously  drawn  from  such  works 
as  were  most  accessible,  not  from  such  as  had  most  claim  to 
be  consulted.  The  account  given  of  Greek  philosophy,  for 
example,  is  not  only  derived  from  Briicker,  but  so  derived 
from  him  as  to  leave  the  impression  that  Condillac  had  proba- 
bly never  taken  the  trouble  to  read  either  the  fragments  of  a 
pre-Socratic  Greek  philosopher  or  a  treatise  of  a  post-Socratic 
one.  If  he  had  at  any  time  thus  occupied  himself,  he  cer- 
tainly did  not  employ  the  knowledge  so  acqixired  to  control 
or  supplement  Briicker.  He  had  the  keenest  interest  in  psy- 
chological analysis,  but  he  had  no  taste  for  historical  criti- 
cism. He  adhered  to  historical  tradition  with  a  closeness 
very  uncommon  among  the  philosophers  of  the  eighteenth 
century ;  almost  alone  among  them,  for  instance,  he  accepted 
the  Biblical  accounts  of  antediluvian  times  and  miraculous 
occurrences. 

Condillac  has  treated  of  historical  progress  on  various  occa- 
sions with  characteristic  judiciousness;  but  in  one  respect 
only,  perhaps,  can  his  teaching  on  the  subject  claim  to  have 
been  original  or  distinctive  —  namely,  in  that  it  represented 
intellectual  progress  as  entirely  dependent  on  the  use  made  of 
language.  This  he  believed  was  what  no  one  before  him  had 
done.  Notwithstanding  his  acquiescence  in  the  Biblical  ac- 
count of  the  primitive  condition  of  man,  he  assumed  that  con- 
dition to  have  been  one  merely  animal.  The  cardinal  doctrine 
of  his  whole  philosophy  was  that  the  sole  root  of  mind  is  sense, 
and  that  all  the  contents  and  even  all  the  faculties  of  mind 
are  merely  transformed  sensations;  and  hence  he  naturally 
believed  that  all  the  mental  acquisitions  of  the  race  had  been 


320  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

attained  in  the  course  of  a  process  of  development  which 
originated  when  human  beings  were  more  ignorant  than  the 
most  ignorant  savages  are  at  present.  He  accordingly  sup- 
posed that  at  first,  and  for  long,  men  had  no  other  means  of 
making  their  impressions  or  desires  known  to  one  another  than 
cries  and  gestures ;  that,  like  the  beasts,  like  children,  and, 
according  to  reports  of  travellers,  like  certain  still  existing 
savage  peoples,  they  had  no  language  in  the  strict  sense  of  the 
term ;  and  hence,  that  language  does  not  constitute  an  absolute 
distinction  between  men  and  beasts,  being  merely  a  human 
invention,  although  the  greatest  of  human  inventions.  Lan- 
guage, properly  so  called,  he  viewed  as  the  result  of  a  slow 
development  from  the  instinctive  and  natural  modes  of  com- 
munication ;  but  it  is  scarcely  necessary  to  say  that  he  ignored 
the  very  serious  difficulties  which  must  be  disposed  of  before 
the  development  of  real  words  out  of  inarticulate  cries  can  be 
reasonably  regarded  as  proved,  or  even  as  intelligible.  He 
represented  the  discovery  of  language  as  a  decisive  epoch  in 
history,  and  argued  that  in  its  first  stage  it  had  been  a  chanted 
speech,  composed  of  sounds  variously  and  strongly  inflected. 
From  this  stage  of  it  sprang  music  and  poetry,  while  gesticula- 
tion gave  rise  to  dancing ;  whence  the  Greek  term  /movo-iio]  was 
inclusive  of  all  the  arts.  To  poetry  succeeded  prose  and  elo- 
quence, which  are  indispensable  to,  and  characteristic  of,  a 
still  more  advanced  stage  of  culture.  When  a  man  of  genius 
arises  and  so  manipulates  and  moulds  a  language  as  to  reveal 
its  merits  and  capabilities,  men  of  talent  hasten  to  use  it  as 
their  instrument ;  artistic  taste  and  ambition  of  all  kinds  are 
evoked ;  and  an  age  of  rich  and  refined  civilisation  appears. 
The  development  of  a  people's  language  and  that  of  its  intel- 
lect are  inseparable  and  always  accordant.1 

As  in  England,  Italy,  and  Germany,  so  in  France,  many  at- 
tempts were  made  in  the  eighteenth  century  to  explain  history, 
or  at  least  large  classes  of  historical  phenomena,  by  means  of 
hypotheses  suggested  by  science.  Nicholas  Boulanger  (1722- 
59),  when  pursuing  his  avocations  as  an  engineer,  was  greatly 
impressed  by  certain  geological  evidences   of  the  action  of 

1  Perhaps  almost  everything  of  value  written  by  Condillao  regarding  history 
is  contained  in  the  '  Logique  de  Condillac,  a  l'usage  des  c'leves  des  prytanees  et 
lyeees  de  la  republique  franeaise,'  par  Noel.    2  torn. :  1802. 


DXJPUIS  —  RAYNAL  321 

water,  which  he  felt  constrained  to  refer  to  a  tremendous  flood ; 
and,  being  a  man  of  lively  imagination  and  of  confused  erudi- 
tion, he  came  to  regard  this  flood  as  a  key  to  the  understand- 
ing of  all  ancient  history.  It  was  its  terrors,  he  supposed, 
which  had  originated  religion  and  despotism,  and  so  caused 
ancient  history  to  be  what  it  was.  The  history,  he  represented, 
as  having  passed  through  four  stages,  —  theocracy,  aristoc- 
racy, democracy,  and  monarchy.  He  was  probably  the  first 
Frenchman  influenced  to  any  considerable  extent  by  Vico.1 
Charles  Dupuis  (1742-1809),  author  of  the  once  famous  book 
'  L'Origine  de  tons  les  Cultes,'  made  an  elaborate  endeavour 
to  give  an  astronomical  solution  of  the  mythologies  and 
superstitions  of  the  human  race,  and  even  went  so  far  as  to 
deny  the  historical  existence  of  Christ,  explaining  the  events 
of  his  life  as  corresponding  to  the  course  of  the  sun,  and 
identifying  the  twelve  apostles  with  the  twelve  signs  of  the 
zodiac.  Court  de  Gebelin  (1727-84),  relied  on  linguistic 
hypotheses  in  his  efforts  to  throw  light  on  "  the  primitive 
world,"  and  to  resolve  mythologies  into  their  original  ele- 
ments. The  attempts  to  combine  science  and  history  just 
referred  to  were  far  from  successful,  yet  are  worthy  of  being 
mentioned,  as  they  were  attempts  in  a  right  direction.  More 
successful,  because  easier  of  accomplishment,  were  the  en- 
deavours made  to  combine  the  sciences  and  history  in  histories 
of  the  sciences.  Among  those  who  performed  work  of  this 
kind  Goguet  and  Bailly  especially  distinguished  themselves. 
Without  irrelevance  I  might  proceed  to  show  how,  in  the 
latter  part  of  the  eighteenth  century,  the  conception  of  his- 
torical progress  was  supplemented  by  that  of  a  universal  de- 
velopment of  nature,  and  to  describe  the  forms  in  which  this 
latter  hypothesis  displayed  itself.  Its  origination  was  due  to 
a  variety  of  causes,  and  especially  to  the  advances  of  physical 
science,  the  spread  of  theoretical  materialism,  and  the  in- 
creased freedom  and  boldness  of  speculation.  To  trace  its  his- 
tory, however,  even  as  it  appears  in  the  writings  of  Maillet, 

1  A  collected  edition  of  Boulanger's  works  (in  8  vols.)  was  published  in  1792. 
'  LAntiquite  devoilee  '  and  '  Le  Despotisme  oriental '  are  the  most  important. 
Several  of  the  irreligious  writings  ascribed  to  him  are  spurious.  '  Le  Christian- 
isme  devoile" '  was  fabricated  by  a  person  called  Damilaville. 


322  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOBY   IN   FRANCE 

Diderot,  Buffon,    Robinet,  Dom  Deschamps,  Lamarck,  &c, 
would  require  mucli  more  space  than  is  at  my  disposal. 

The  Abbe-  Raynal's  '  Philosophical  and  Political  History  of 
the  Settlements  and  Trade  of  Europeans  in  the  East  and  West 
Indies'  was  the  most  popular  of  all  the  historical  writings 
which  appeared  in  France  during  the  reign  of  Louis  XVI., 
and  also  one  of  the  most  representative  of  the  taste  and  spirit 
of  the  period.  Published  in  1771,  it  rapidly  passed  through 
twenty  editions,  and  was  translated  into  the  languages  of 
almost  all  civilised  peoples.  It  largely  owed  the  extraordi- 
nary favour  with  which  the  contemporaries  of  Raynal  received 
it  to  those  declamations  about  liberty  and  justice,  tyrants  and 
priests,  and  those  effusions  of  sentimentalism,  which  now  only 
give  offence.  These  purpurei  pcmni  interwoven  into  it,  and 
composed,  it  would  appear,  for  the  most  part  by  Diderot, 
although  they  greatly  contributed  to  its  immediate  success, 
have  led  to  its  undue  depreciation  by  posterity.  It  was  the 
fruit  of  twenty  years'  diligent  labour,  and,  intrinsically,  a 
highly  deserving  work,  containing  a  vast  amount  of  new  and 
valuable  information,  well"  arranged,  and  vividly,  although 
too  rhetorically,  presented.  It  was  the  first  book  which 
effectively  showed  how  important  a  factor  commerce  had 
been  in  modern  history.  The  way  in  which  this  was  done 
was  what  was  truly  philosophical  in  it,  not  the  general  and 
professedly  philosophical  reflections  which  it  contains,  and 
which  are  mostly  superficial  and  pretentious. 

During  the  progress  of  the  Revolution  two  works  were  pub- 
lished which  professed  to  delineate  philosophically  the  course 
of  history.  Both  were  written  by  enthusiastic  advocates  of 
the  principles  of  eighteenth-century  "enlightenment,"  and 
ardent  admirers  of  the  Revolution  as  a  grand  effort  to  realise 
the  true  ideal  of  social  life ;  by  men  closely  akin  in  convic- 
tions, spirit,  and  aim.  Yet  they  are  of  very  unequal,  merit ; 
and  while  the  one  may  be  very  briefly  dealt  with,  the  other 
will  require  a  comparatively  lengthened  treatment.  The  two 
works  referred  to  are  VolUey's  '  Ruins '  and  Condorcet's 
'  Sketch/ 

Constantine  Francis  Chassebceuf,  Count  Volney,  acquired 
fame  as  a  traveller,  an  orientalist,  and  an  historian.    Although 


VOLNEY  323 

very  hostile  to  religion,  he  was  a  sincere,  magnanimous,  virtu- 
ous man.  His  '  Ruins ;  or,  A  Survey  of  the  Revolutions  of 
Empires '  (1791),  is  the  work  by  which  he  is  best  known, 
although  it  is  much  inferior  in  real  value  to  his  '  Travels  in 
Syria  and  Egypt,'  his  '  Description  of  the  Character  and  Soil 
of  the  United  States,'  or  even  his  '  Researches  on  Ancient 
-History.'  It  is  a  sort  of  philosophy  of  history  and  of  religion 
based  on  tenets  of  Locke,  Condillac,  Rousseau,  and  Dupuis. 
A  general  summary  of  its  character  and  contents  may  be 
given  as  follows  :  — 

Contemplating  the  ruins  of  Palmyra,  the  author  meditates 
on  the  disappearance  of  extinct  empires,  and  foresees  a  similar 
fate  for  those  which  are  now  most  flourishing  and  powerful. 
The  genius  of  history  appears  to  him,  and  explains  that 
fatality  is  a  meaningless  word,  and  that  the  source  of  human 
calamities  is  in  man  himself,  his  passions  and  faults.  Appear- 
ing 011  earth  as  an  ignorant  savage,  man  gradually  emerges 
from  this  state  under  the  attraction  of  pleasure  and  the  repul- 
sion of  pain.  His  only  motive  of  action,  self-love,  renders 
him  at  once  social  and  industrious,  but  also,  growing  as  it 
does  with  the  growth  of  the  arts  and  of  civilisation,  leads  him 
to  confound  happiness  with  unregulated  enjoyment,  makes 
him  avaricious  and  violent,  and  causes  the  strong  to  oppress 
the  weak  and  the  weak  to  conspire  against  the  strong. 
Slavery  and  inequality,  war  and  corruption,  have  conse- 
quently followed  on  the  liberty  and  equality,  peace  and 
innocence,  of  primitive  times.  But  as  man  is  perfectible 
this  condition  of  things  cannot  be  permanent,  and  during 
the  last  three  centuries  there  has  been  great  progress :  intel- 
lects have  been  brought  into  communication  as  never  before  ; 
knowledge  has,  thanks  especially  to  printing,  been  marvel- 
lously diffused ;  discoveries  and  inventions  of  all  kinds  mul- 
tiplied and  utilised.  Humanity  is  now  fairly  started  on  a 
career  of  conquest ;  the  emancipation  of  the  mind  is  rapidly 
advancing.  Soon  morality  itself  will  come  to  be  rationally 
viewed;  individuals  and  nations  will  recognise  it  to  be  the 
object  of  a  physical  science ;  it  will  be  universally  acknowl- 
edged that  there  is  only  one  law,  that  of  nature ;  only  one 
code,  that  of  reason ;  only  one  throne,  that  of  justice ;  only 


324  PHILOSOPHY    OF    HISTORY   IN    FRANCE 

one  altar,  that  of  concord.  When  men  clearly  see  what 
morality  is,  and  consequently  clearly  see  that  it  is  their  own 
security  and  advantage,  they  will  not  fail  to  practise  it. 

Next,  the  ministers  and  interpreters  of  all  worships  are 
represented  as  convoked,  as  compelled  to  speak  on  behalf  of 
their  various  creeds,  and  in  doing  so,  as  contradicting  and 
refuting  one  another,  opposing  revelations  to  revelations, 
miracles  to  miracles,  authorities  to  authorities,  until  they 
render  it  evident  that  they  are  all  deceived  or  deceivers.  A 
naturalistic  explanation  is  given  of  the  way  in  which  nations 
rise  and  fall,  and  of  the  order  in  which  they  appear.  Religious 
ideas  are  maintained  to  spring  from  the  impressions  of  sense, 
and  to  assume  in  their  course  a  necessary  succession  of  forms. 
The  stages  through  which  religion  is  described  as  passing  are 
these :  (1)  worship  of  the  elements  and  physical  powers  of 
nature;  (2)  worship  of  the  stars,  or  Sabeism;  (3)  worship 
of  symbols,  or  idolatry;  (4)  worship  of  two  principles,  or 
dualism ;  (5)  mythical  or  moral  worship,  or  the  system  of  a 
future  state ;  (6)  worship  of  the  world  as  animated,  or  of  the 
universe  under  different  emblems ;  (7)  worship  of  the  soul 
of  the  world,  the  vital  principle  of  the  universe  ;  and  (8)  wor- 
ship of  the  demiurgus,  or  supreme  artificer.  Christianity  is 
represented  as  the  allegorical  worship  of  the  sun.  The  entire 
development  of  religion  is  exhibited  as  a  vain  and  illusory 
process ;  all  the  ideas  and  beliefs  which  it  implies  as  uncer- 
tain and  unverifiable.  Men  are,  consequently,  exhorted  to 
renounce  all  opinions  regarding  a  spiritual  world,  and  to 
concern  themselves  only  with  that  perceptible  world  of  which 
alone  they  can  know  anything. 

Among  the  last  words  of  the  work  are  these,  and  they  ex- 
press well  its  chief  conclusion :  "If  we  would  reach  uniformity 
of  opinion,  we  must  previously  attain  certainty,  and  verify  the 
resemblance  of  our  ideas  to  their  models.  Now  this  cannot 
be  done  except  in  so  far  as  the  objects  of  our  inquiry  can  be 
referred  to  the  testimony,  and  subjected  to  the  examination, 
of  our  senses.  Whatever  cannot  be  brought  to  this  trial  is 
beyond  the  limits  of  our  understanding ;  we  have  neither  rule 
to  try  it  by,  nor  measure  by  which  to  institute  a  comparison, 
nor  source  of   demonstration   and  knowledge  regarding  it. 


CONDORCET  325 

Whence  it  is  obvious  that,  in  order  to  live  in  peace  and  har- 
mony, we  must  consent  not  to  pronounce  upon  such  objects, 
nor  assign  to  them  importance.  We  must  draw  a  line  of 
demarcation  between  such  as  can  be  verified  and  such  as 
cannot,  and  separate  by  an  inviolable  barrier  the  world  of 
fantastic  beings  from  the  world  of  realities ;  that  is  to  say,  all 
civil  effect  must  be  taken  away  from  theological  and  religious 
opinions." 

Volney  was  one  of  the  many  precursors  of  Comte ;  and, 
indeed,  as  decided  a  positivist  as  Comte  himself,  in  all  respects 
except  in  name.1 

II 

Amidst  all  the  crimes  and  sufferings  of  the  Revolution 
many  of  the  sincerest  and  worthiest  of  its  partisans,  among 
whom  Condorcet  must  undoubtedly  be  numbered,  remained 
full  of  confidence  and  hope.  The  splendours  of  a  mirage 
gave  a  deceptive  beauty  to  the  waste  howling  wilderness 
before  them.  Faith  in  the  future  of  the  human  race  strength- 
ened them  to  bear  even  the  horrors  of  the  Reign  of  Terror ; 
faith  in  a  thorough  regeneration  of  the  world  and  a  blessed 
millennium.  It  was  "  a  time,"  says  Hegel,  "  in  which  a  spir- 
itual enthusiasm  thrilled  through  the  world,  as  if  the  recon- 
ciliation between  the  divine  and  secular  was  now  first  accom- 
plished"; "a  time,"  says  Wordsworth, — 

"  In  which  the  meagre,  stale,  forbidding  ways 
Of  custom,  law,  and  statute,  took  at  once 
The  attraction  of  a  country  in  romance  ! 
When  Reason  seemed  the  most  to  assert  her  rights, 
When  most  intent  on  making  of  herself 
A  prime  enchantress  —  to  assist  the  work 
Which  then  was  going  forward  in  her  name." 

The  'Esquisse  d'un  Tableau  Historique  des  Progres  de 
l'Esprit  Humain,'  written  by  Marie-Jean- Antoine-Nicolas 
Caritat,  Marquis  de  Condorcet,  in  1793,  is  thoroughly  char- 

1  Fr.  Picavet,  in  his  valuable  work  '  Les  Ideologues,  F-ssai  sur  l'histoire  des 
idees  et  des  theories  scientifiques,  philosopffiques,  religieuses,  etc.,  en  France 
depuis  1789'  (1891),  treats  of  Volney,  pp.  128-140;  of  Dupuis,  pp.  140-143;  'and  of 
Condorcet,  pp.  101-116. 


326  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  IS  FRANCE 

acteristic  of  the  time.1  Although  composed  when  its  author 
lay  concealed  from  the  emissaries  of  Robespierre  in  the  garret 
of  a  friend,  it  is  pervaded  by  a  spirit  of  excessive  hope- 
fulness, and  pictures  a  glorious  future  as  at  hand.  It  was 
with  the  vision  of  the  guillotine  before  him,  and  in  con- 
stant dread  of  a  violent  death,  that  this  brilliant  and  gener- 
ous, if  somewhat  fanciful  and  vacillating  man,  sincere  in  his 
love  and  strong  in  his  faith  towards  humanity,  comforted 
himself  after  all  other  religion  had  died  out  of  his  soul,  by 
trying  to  demonstrate  that  the  evils  of  life  had  arisen  from 
a  conspiracy  of  priests  and  rulers  against  their  fellows,  and 
from  the  bad  laws  and  bad  institutions  which  they  had  suc- 
ceeded in  creating;  but  that  the  human  race  would  finally 
conquer  its  enemies,  and  so  completely  free  itself  of  its  evils 
that  even  disease  and  suffering  should  almost  cease,  and  truth, 
liberty,  equality,  justice,  and  love  should  universally  abound. 
His  work  is  thus  a  sort  of  hymn  in  celebration  of  the  dignity 
of  man,  and  in  salutation  of  the  advent  of  a  reign  of  right- 
eousness and  peace,  which  cannot  fail  to  interest  and  move, 
were  it  only  from  the  fact  that  it  was  composed  almost  under 
the  axe  of  the  executioner. 

The  circumstances  in  which  it  was  written  were  thus  the 
most  unfavourable  that  can  well  be  imagined  for  minute 
accuracy  of  execution,  and  must,  in  the  eyes  of  a  candid 
critic,  go  far  to  excuse  its  numerous  errors  of  detail.  It 
would  be  ungenerous  to  insist  on  these,  and  it  would  be  for 
our  purpose,  or  any  good  purpose,  useless,  as  the  only  value 
which  can  reasonably  be  attributed  to  the  book  lies  in  its 
general  ideas.  It  must  be  considered,  as  its  author  wished 
it  to  be  considered,  as  a  mere  programme  of  principles  —  a 
sketch  to  be  filled  up  in  a  subsequent  and  elaborate  work 

1  On  Condorcet  as  an  historical  philosopher,  see  Auguste  Comte,  'Cours  de 
Philosophic  Positive,'  iv.  252-262,  and  '  Systeme  de  Politique  Positive,'  iv.,  appen- 
dice  general,  109-111;  Laurent,  'Etudes,'  xii.  121-126;  Morley's  "Condorcet"  in 
'  Critical  Miscellanies  ' ;  Mathurin  Gillet,  '  L'Utopie  de  Condorcet,'  1884 ;  Janet, 
ii.  682-692;  and  two  articles  of  Renouvier,  'Crit.  Phil.,'  annee  x.,  pp.  117-128, 
145-160.  I  have  restated  the  most  fundamental  of  Comte's  criticisms  on  pp.  328, 
329.  I  may  also  refer  to  my  article  on  Condorcet  in  '  Encycl.  Brit.'  In  the  inter- 
val between  the  publication  of  Turgot's  '  Discourses '  and  Condorcet's  '  Sketch,' 
there  appeared  writings  of  a  somewhat  kindred  nature  by  Iselin,  Wegelin,  Kant, 
and  Herder,  and  by  Ferguson,  Lord  Kames,  and  Priestley,  but  Condorcet's  work 
bears  no  traces  of  their  influence.  In  historical  philosophy  Turgot  was  his  imme- 
diate, and  almost  sole  teacher. 


CONDORCET  327 

could  the  guillotine  be  escaped,  which,  alas !  -was  not  possi- 
ble, except  by  suicide  in  prison. 

The  fundamental  idea  of  Condorcet  is  that  of  a  human  per- 
fectibility which  has  manifested  itself  in  continuous  progress 
in  the  past,  and  must  lead  to  indefinite  progress  in  the  future. 
Man,  he  endeavours  to  show,  has  advanced  uninterruptedly  at 
a  more  or  less  rapid  rate,  from  the  moment  of  his  appearance 
on  earth  to  the  present  time,  in  the  path  of  enlightenment, 
virtue,  and  happiness,  and  will  continue  to  advance  so  long 
as  the  world  lasts.  As  the  whole  intellectual  and  moral  life 
of  the  individual  is  developed  out  of  a  susceptibility  to  sen- 
sations, and  the  power  of  retaining,  discriminating,  and  com- 
bining them,  so  all  the  varieties  of  civilisation,  all  the  phases 
of  history,  are  but  the  collective  work  of  the  individuals  thus 
humbly  endowed.  Their  starting-point  is  the  lowest  stage  of 
barbarism :  the  first  men  possessing  no  superiority  over  the 
other  animals  which  did  not  result  directly  from  superiority 
of  bodily  organisation. 

The  stages  which  the  human  race  has  already  gone  through, 
or,  in  other  words,  the  great  epochs  of  history,  are  regarded 
as  nine  in  number.  Of  these  the  first  three  can  confessedly 
be  described  only  conjecturally  from  general  observations  as 
to  the  development  of  the  human  faculties  and  the  analogies 
of  savage  life.  In  the  first  epoch,  men  are  united  into  hordes 
of  hunters  and  fishers,  who  acknowledge  in  some  degree  pub- 
lic authority  and  the  claims  of  family  relationship,  and  who 
make  use  of  an  articulate  language,  "  invented  by  some  men 
of  genius,  the  eternal  benefactors  of  the  human  race,  but 
whose  names  and  countries  are  for  ever  buried  in  oblivion." 
In  the  second  epoch,  the  pastoral  state,  property  is  introduced, 
and  along  with  it  inequality  of  conditions,  and  even  slavery, 
but  also  leisure  to  cultivate  intelligence,  to  invent  some  of 
the  simpler  arts,  and  to  acquire  some  of  the  more  elementary 
truths  of  science.  In  the  third  epoch,  the  agricultural  state, 
as  leisure  and  wealth  are  greater,  labour  better  distributed 
and  applied,  and  the  means  of  communication  increased  and 
extended,  progress  is  still  more  rapid.  With  the  invention 
of  alphabetic  writing  the  conjectural  part "  of  history  closes, 
and  the  more  or  less  authenticated  part  commences.     By  an 


328  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FBANCE 

omission  still  greater  than  Bossuet's,  China,  India,  "the  five 
great  monarchies,"  Judea,  and,  in  fact,  all  nations  compre- 
hended in  the  oriental  world,  are  passed  unappreciated  and 
even  unnoticed;  and  the  fourth  and  fifth  epochs  are  repre- 
sented as  corresponding  to  Greece  and  Eome.  The  middle 
ages  are  divided  into  two  epochs,  the  former  of  which  ter- 
minates with  the  Crusades,  and  the  latter  with  the  invention 
of  printing.  The  eighth  epoch  extends  from  the  invention  of 
printing  to  the  revolution  in  the  method  of  philosophic  think- 
ing accomplished  by  Descartes.  And  the  ninth  epoch  begins 
with  that  great  intellectual  revolution  and  ends  with  the  great 
political  and  moral  revolution  of  1789,  and  is  illustrious 
through  the  discovery  of  the  true  system  of  the  physical  uni- 
verse by  Newton,  of  human  nature  by  Locke  and  Condillac, 
and  of  society  by  Turgot,  Price,  and  Rousseau. 

Now  nothing  can  be  more  important  in  any  attempt  at  a 
philosophical  delineation  of  the  course  of  history  than  the 
division  into  periods.  That  ought  of  itself  to  exhibit  the 
plan  of  the  development,  the  line  and  distance  already  trav- 
ersed, and  the  direction  of  future  movement.  It  should  be 
made  on  a  single  principle,  so  that  the  series  of  periods  may 
be  homogeneous,  but  on  a  principle  so  fundamental  and  com- 
prehensive as  to  pervade  the  history  not  only  as  a  whole  but 
in  each  of  its  elements,  and  to  be  able  to  furnish  guidance  to 
the  historian  of  any  special  development  of  human  knowledge 
and  life.  The  discovery  and  proof  of  such  a  principle  is  one 
of  the  chief  services  which  the  philosophy  of  history  may  be 
legitimately  expected  to  render  to  the  historians  of  science, 
of  religion,  of  morality,  and  of  art.  And  if  it  fail  to  render 
this  service,  this  can  only  be  because  it  has  failed  to  accom- 
plish its  own  distinctive  and  proper  work  —  failed  to  grasp 
and  follow  the  thread  that  guides  through  the  labyrinth  of 
history,  and  allows  the  mind  to  trace  in  some  measure  its 
plan,  and  to  conjecture  with  some  degree  of  probability  its 
purpose.  But  failure  is  very  possible,  success  very  difficult. 
No  superficial  glance  can  possibly  detect,  nor  happy  accident 
disclose,  the  true  principle  of  historical  division,  any  more 
than  of  botanical  "or  zoological  classification.  It  does  not  lie 
on  the  surface,  but  in  the  essential  nature  of  the  thing,  and 
implies  a  thorough  acquaintance  therewith,  a  profound  insight 


CONDOECET  329 

into  the  course  and  tendencies  of  history,  attainable  only- 
through  prolonged  and  patient  study,  and  after  repeated 
failures.  Condorcet  had  not  the  requisite  knowledge  of  the 
subject ;  had  not  gone  deep  enough  in  his  investigations  into 
historical  development,  to  apprehend  the  principle  by  which 
its  stages  or  periods  should  be  determined;  and  could  only 
seem  to  determine  them  by  fixing,  and  even  that  on  inadequate 
grounds,  on  certain  conspicuous  events  sufficiently  distant 
from  each  other  to  divide  the  whole  of  European  history  into 
a  few  ages,  and  yet  not  so  unequally  distant  that  the  inequal- 
ity should  of  itself  show  the  non-co-ordinacy  of  these  ages. 
And  not  only  is  there  no  proof  given  that  the  events  which 
are  thus  selected  as  the  origins  of  periods,  the  turning-points 
of  history,  are  all  of  the  same  rank  —  that  is,  on  a  level  as 
to  importance  or  influence;  but,  as  Comte  has  well  remarked, 
they  are  not  even  of  the  same  order,  one  being  industrial, 
another  political,  another  scientific,  another  religious. 

Another  defect  must  be  indicated.  Condorcet  belonged  to 
a  generation  which  was  narrow  and  unjust  in  its  judgment  of 
many  great  causes,  and  he  did  not  in  that  respect  rise  above 
the  general  spirit  of  his  time.  He  carries  into  his  estimate 
of  the  past  not  the  calm  catholic  spirit  of  the  philosopher,  but 
the  passionate  and  prejudiced  spirit  of  sectarian  fanaticism. 
He  sees  no  beauty  or  worth  in  philosophy  except  when  it 
attempts  to  explain  the  world  on  mechanical  and  sensational 
principles,  and  in  religion  none  at  all.  Idealism  and  Chris- 
tianity appear  to  him  as  simply  delusions ;  Monarchy  and  the 
Church  as  two  essentially  pernicious  institutions,  the  one  of 
which  has  persistently  tyrannised  over  men  by  brute  force, 
and  the  other  constantly  betrayed  them  with  lies.  These 
views  are  of  course,  ;both  uncharitable  and  inconsistent  with 
the  testimony  of  history.  They  are  inconsistent  even  with 
Condorcet's  own  fundamental  notions  of  progress  and  perfec- 
tibility. Progress,  continuous  and  indefinite  improvement, 
should  have  reasons.  But  what  reasons  for  them  can  there 
be,  if  all  the  most  powerful  and  durable  agencies  and  institu- 
tions in  history  have  been  essentially  obstructive  and  hurtful? 
How  coiies  it,  if  such  be  the  case,  that  retrogression  is  not 
the  characteristic  of  history  instead  of  progress  ?  It  might 
have  been  possible  for  Condorcet,  had  his  philosophy  been 


330  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

other  than  it  was,  to  have  evaded  if  not  avoided  this  difficulty 
by  ascribing  progress  to  a  power  inherent  in  human  nature, 
and  capable  of  not  only  dispensing  with  any  external  aid,  but 
of  triumphing  over  every  external  opposition  —  to  an  innate 
spontaneous  and  irresistible  faculty;  but  his  sensationalism 
and  denial  of  a  priori  principles  and  original  tendencies  pre- 
cluded his  having  recourse  to  this  explanation,  and  left  him 
no  escape  from  self-contradiction.  History  itself  is  less 
illogical;  never  contradicts  itself;  never  presents  anything 
good  or  bad  for  which  there  is  not  a  sufficient  cause.  If  there 
has  been  anywhere  improvement  in  the  world,  it  has  been 
because  there  the  forces  of  good  have  been  on  the  whole 
mightier  than  those  of  evil;  and  if  anywhere  deterioration, 
it  has  been  because  there  the  superior  strength  has  been  on 
the  side  of  evil. 

The  most  original,  and,  notwithstanding  its  errors,  the 
most  important  part  of  Condorcet's  treatise,  is  that  which  has 
been  most  censured  and  ridiculed,  the  last  chapter,  which 
has  for  subject  the  future  of  the  human  race.  There  the  idea 
that  generalisations  from  the  past  must  supply  data  for  pre- 
vision of  the  future  in  historical  as  well  as  in  physical  science, 
is  for  the  first  time  perhaps  adequately  insisted  on. 

"If  man,''  it  is  said,  "can  predict  with  almost  entire  confidence 
phenomena  when  he  knows  their  laws,  if  even  when  these  laws  are 
unknown  he  can  from  experience  of  the  past  foresee  with  great  proba- 
bility the  events  of  the  future,  why  should  it  be  deemed  chimerical  to 
attempt  to  picture  the  probable  destiny  of  the  human  race  in  accordance 
with  the  results  of  its  history?  The  sole  foundation  of  belief  in  the 
natural  sciences  is  the  idea  that  the  general  laws,  known  or'ignored, 
which  regulate  the  phenomena  of  the  universe,  are  necessary  and  con- 
stant ;  and  for  what  reason  should  this  hold  less  true  of  the  intellectual 
and  moral  faculties  of  man  than  of  the  other  operations  of  nature?" 
Since  opinions  formed  on  the  experience  of  the  past  are  the  rules  of 
conduct  adopted  by  the  wiser  portion  of  mankind,  why  should  the  philoso- 
pher be  forbidden  to  rest  his  conjectures  on  the  same  basis,  provided  he 
attribute  to  them  no  greater  certainty  than  the  number,  the  consistency, 
and  the  accuracy  of  his  observations  warrant? 1 

It  is  owing  to  his  having  at  once  distinctly  enunciated  this 
idea  and  sought  to  realise  it  that  both  Saint-Simon  aj$d  Comte 
have  assigned  to  his  work  a  place  among  the  most  important 

1  Esqnisse,  pp.  327,  328  (2d  ed.). 


CONDORCET  331 

productions  of  the  scientific  mind,  although  thoroughly  aware 
of  its  defects.  The  truth  of  the  idea  is  not  dependent  on  any- 
exaggerated  view  of  progress  as  the  continuous,  ubiquitous, 
inevitable  manifestation  of  an  inherent  faculty  or  force,  but 
on  the  simple  fact  of  progress  in  directions  which  can  be  traced ; 
nor  is  it  affected  by  mistakes  which  Condorcet  may  have  made 
in  his  delineation  of  the  future.  And  without  any  wish  to 
excuse  or  explain  away  his  mistakes  of  the  latter  kind,  I 
believe  they  have  not  only  been  'more  than  sufficiently  dwelt 
on,  but  greatly  exaggerated.  It  is  erroneous  to  represent 
him  as  assuming  the  rSle  of  prophet  farther  than  that  a  cer- 
tain sort  of  prevision  seemed  to  him  essentially  involved  in 
historical  science, —  farther  than  that  general  laws  regulative 
of  the  past  seemed  to  him  to  warrant  general  inferences  re- 
specting the  future.  He  confined  himself,  however,  entirely 
to  general  inferences,  and  never  pretended  to  predict  particular 
events.  He  confined  himself,  indeed,  to  infer  .from  the  entire 
history  of  the  past  three  tendencies  as  likely  to  be  character- 
istic features  of  the  future ;  and  to  believe  with  measure  in 
any  of  them  appears  to  involve  nothing  obviously  absurd  and 
Utopian. 

These  three  features  of  the  future,  or  tendencies  of  the 
present,  or  directions  of  progress,  are :  1,  The  destruction  of 
inequality  between  nations ;  2,  the  destruction  of  inequality 
between  classes;  and  3,  the  improvement  of  individuals. 
Now,  as  to  the  first,  the  destruction  of  inequality  between 
nations,  Condorcet  does  not  thereby  mean  that  nations  tend 
to  become,  or  ever  will  become,  in  all  respects  alike,  which 
would  really  amount  to  holding  that  nations,  as  nations,  must 
cease  to  exist.  Nationality  is  inconsistent  with  absolute 
equality.  But  only  inexcusable  carelessness  can  explain 
any  one's  supposing  him  to  believe  in  such  equality.  That 
which  he  speaks  of  is  equality  of  liberty  or  right,  the 
ordinary  signification  of  the  term  among  his  contempora- 
ries, and  that  which  is  found  in  the  legislation  of  the  period 
—  e.g.,  in  the  Codes  of  1791  and  1793.  Hence  when  he 
says  nations  tend  to  equality  he  means  simply,  as  he  him- 
self tells  us,  that  they  all  tend  to  freedom ;  that  liberty  is 
what  they  are  alike  entitled  to,  and  will  alike  enjoy ;  that 
nature  has  not  doomed  the  inhabitants  of  any  country  to 


332  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FKANCE 

slavery  either  of  body  or  mind,  but  made  them  for  indepen- 
dence and  the  exercise  of  reason.  The  differences  or  distinc- 
tions which  flow  from  the  very  use  of  reason  and  freedom  do 
not  seem  to  him  incompatible  with  equality,  but  only  those 
which  cannot  be  traced  to  the  true,  i.e.,  free  moral  personality 
as  their  ground;  only  those  which,  on  the  contrary,  attack 
and  seek  to  subvert  it,  by  denial  of  the  right  of  all  nations 
without  distinction  to  rational  freedom.  Nations,  he  thinks, 
are  equal  if  equally  free,  and  are  all  tending  to  equality 
because  all  tending  to  freedom. 

Thus  understood,  the  disappearance  of  inequality  between 
nations  implies  the  disappearance  of  inequality  between  the 
different  classes  of  citizens  in  a  nation.  It  presupposes  that 
the  right  to  freedom  does  not  divide  but  unite  men,  belonging 
of  its  very  nature  to  all ;  that 

"  Our  life  is  turned 
0»t  of  her  course,  wherever  man  is  made 
An  offering  or  a  sacrifice,  a  tool 
Or  implement,  a  passive  thing  employed 
As  a  brute  mean,  -without  acknowledgment 
Of  common  right  or  interest  in  the  end ; 
Used  or  abused,  as  selfishness  may  prompt." 

The  inequality  between  the  different  classes  in  a  nation  com- 
prises inequality  of  wealth  and  instruction;  and,  according 
to  Condorcet,  the  tendency  of  historical  progress  is  towards 
equality  as  regards  both.  In  saying  this  of  wealth,  he  does 
not  mean  that  the  time  is  coming  when  no  man  will  be  richer 
than  another,  but  simply  that  the  numerous  distinctions  be- 
tween men  according  to  their  wealth  which  have  been  origi- 
nated by  the  civil  laws,  and  perpetuated  by  factitious  means, 
are  destined  to  be  swept  away ;  and  that  their  abolition,  leav- 
ing property,  trade,  and  industry  entirely  free,  must  help  to 
destroy  all  fixed  class  distinctions  —  moneyed  inclusive  —  all 
casteship,  in  society.  He  may  have  been  mistaken.  Many 
think  that  the  experience  of  our  own  country  since  it  entered 
on  the  path  which  Condorcet  recommended  to  the  world,  goes 
to  show  that  wealth  left  to  itself  tends  not  to  equality  but  to 
inequality;  and  the  most  democratic  of  nations,  the  United 
States,  far  from  manifesting,  as  might  have  been  looked  for, 
an  equal  or  higher  faith  in  freedom  of  trade,  shows  a  singular 
aversion  to  it.     Under  the  English  rSgime  of  liberty,  the  rich 


CONDORCET  333 

are  always,  it  is  said,  growing  richer,  and  the  poor  poorer, 
and  so  the  distance  between  rich  and  poor  is  continually 
widening  instead  of  lessening.  But  does  the  little  wealth 
of  the  poor  tend  when  free  to  decrease  in  the  same  mode  and 
sense  that  the  much  wealth  of  the  rich  tends  to  increase  ?  Or 
must  not,  on  the  contrary,  when  free,  the  tendency  alike  of 
small  and  of  large  sums  be  to  increase ;  and  if  the  little  of 
the  poor  be  actually  seen  to  become  less,  must  it  not  be  owing 
to  some  disturbing  cause,  such  as  population  outgrowing 
capital,  and  neither  to  freedom  nor  the  increase  of  the  riches 
of  the  rich  in  a  state  of  freedom,  both  of  which  of  themselves 
only  tend  to  diminish  the  poverty  of  the  poor  ?  And  granting 
that  the  difference  of  fortune  between  the  wealthiest  and  the 
poorest  member  of  the  community  is  greater  at  present  than 
ever  it  was,  are  not  the  number  of  intermediate  fortunes,  their 
gradation,  and  the  way  in  which  they  pass  from  one  person  to 
another,  sufficient  notwithstanding  to  establish  the  existence 
of  that  tendency  to  equality,  even  as  regards  wealth,  for 
which  Condorcet  contended?  Further,  have  we  not  simply 
to  look  around  us  and  mark  how  rapidly  landed  property  is 
passing  out  of  noble  into  trading  and  mercantile  hands,  and 
how  vainly  the  new  proprietors  must  strive  to  gain  the  social 
position  of  their  predecessors,  in  order  to  convince  ourselves 
that  free  trade  is  a  most  democratic  thing,  surely  and  steadily 
pulling  the  higher  classes  of  society  down  to  a  lower  level  ? 
It  may  very  well  be  thought,  then,  that  in  this  respect  society 
is  tending  in  the  direction  indicated  by  Condorcet;  but  even 
if  not,  his  opinion  is  simply  erroneous,  and  neither  absurd 
nor  Utopian ;  a  proposition  for  discussion,  not  for  ridicule. 

So  when  he  speaks  of  a  tendency  in  history  to  equality  of 
instruction,  equality  must  again  be  understood  as  an  attri- 
bute of  liberty,  and  as  meaningless  or  mischievous  when 
detached  from  it  and  regarded  as  a  separate  or  co-ordinate 
principle.  He  in  the  plainest  terms  rejects  the  notion  that 
no  man  is  to  receive  more  learning  than  another,  but  all  are 
to  be  taught  the  same  things  and  to  the  same  extent.  The 
equality  of  instruction  for  which  he  contends  is  certainly  not 
that  which  would  give  all  men  the  same  amount  of  knowl- 
edge ;  it  is  only  that  which  will  suffice  to  destroy  all  slavish 


334  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

dependence.  He  holds  that  by  a  choice  of  the  appropriate 
kinds  of  knowledge  and  of  the  means  best  adapted  to  com- 
municate them,  the  entire  mass  of  a  people  may  be  instructed 
in  all  that  each  individual  needs  to  know  in  order  to  secure 
the  free  development  of  his  industry  and  faculties;  that 
equality  carried  thus  far,  the  inequality  of  the  natural  facul- 
ties of  each  would  benefit  all  as  regards  both  science  and 
practice ;  and  that  all  men  ought  to  receive  so  much  educa- 
tion, and  that  of  such  a  character,  as  will  enable  them  to  live 
as  men,  as  rational  and  free  beings,  and  not  as  brute  creatures 
which  are  driven  and  ruled  from  without  for  the  pleasure  and 
interest  of  a  master.  The  pages  in  which  he  states  what  he 
means  by  "  the  equality  of  instruction  which  we  can  hope  to 
attain,  and  with  which  we  ought  to  be  satisfied,"  and  indi- 
cates his  reasons  for  believing  that  it  would  be  favourable  to 
a  real  equality  in  every  sphere  of  life,  even  where  natural 
inequalities  are  allowed  free  development,  are  as  admirable 
for  their  lucidity  and  reasonableness  as  for  their  eloquence ; 
they  are  full  of  a  noble  enthusiasm,  but  contain  not  a  sen- 
tence which  warrants  the  accusation  of  utopianism. 

The  third  and  most  famous  inference  of  our  author  is  the 
indefinite  perfectibility  of  human  nature  itself,  intellectually, 
morally,  and  physically.  He  uses  even  the  term  infinite,  and 
Cousin  and  other  critics  have  taken  him  rigidly  at  his  word, 
but  very  unfairly,  as  he  clearly  shows  his  meaning  merely  to 
be  that  no  fixed  term  or  limit  is  assignable  to  progress.  He 
has  nowhere  denied  that  progress  is  conditioned  both  by  the 
constitution  of  humanity  and  the  character  of  its  surround- 
ings, but  he  affirms  that  these  conditions  are  compatible  with 
endless  progress ;  and,  in  fact,  only  a  being  not  absolute  and 
infinite,  but  conditioned  and  finite,  is  capable  of  progress 
of  any  kind.  An  absolutely  infinite  progress,  implying  the 
progress  of  an  absolutely  infinite  being,  is  a  contradiction  in 
terms ;  but  Condorcet  was  quite  right  in  thinking  that  the 
human  mind  can  assign  no  fixed  limits  to  its  own  advance- 
ment in  knowledge,  and  that  science  both  as  to  wealth  of 
results  and  improvement  of  methods  may  grow  more  and  more 
for  ever,  constantly  finding  its  horizon  recede,  constantly 
attaining  a  wider  and  clearer  range  of  vision.     The  very 


CONDORCET  335 

attempt,  indeed,  of  reason  to  assign  limits  to  its  own  prog- 
ress, is  the  same  sort  of  absurdity  as  would  be  a  man's  attempt- 
ing to  leap  out  of  or  into  his  own  body.  It  is  not  necessary, 
however,  here  to  have  recourse  to  the  metaphysical  reasoning 
which  establishes  this  fundamental  truth  of  metaphysical 
science;  it  is  enough  merely  to  ask  those  who  deny  it  to 
state  where  they  suppose  knowledge  is  necessitated  to  stop. 
Thus  far,  then,  Condorcet  was  on  firm  ground.  But  he  went 
farther;  he  supposed  that  intellectual  acquisitions  do  not 
entirely  pass  away  with  the  individuals  or  generations  which 
have  made  them,  but  are  to  some  extent  transmitted  or  inher- 
ited; and  that  in  consequence  there  is  in  the  course  of  ages  a 
gradual  increase  not  only  of  the  intellectual  wealth,  but  of 
the  intellectual  ability  of  men.  It  may  be  so.  The  opinion 
is  not  absurd,  not  indefensible.  It  seems  an  almost  neces- 
sary inference  from  the  theory  of  development  which  was  only 
struggling  into  existence  when  Condorcet  wrote,  but  which 
is  now  the  most  prevalent  and  influential  of  scientific  doc- 
trines. It  is  to  be  regretted  that  Condorcet  did  not  indicate 
the  reasons  for  his  opinion,  or  attempt  to  show  that  the  facts 
which  at  least  appear  to  contradict  it  in  reality  do  not. 
Doubtless  he  would  have  done  so  had  adverse  fate  not 
prevented  him.  The  want,  however,  of  any  proof  or  inves- 
tigation of  the  kind  does  not  affect  his  main  position.  The 
doctrine  of  the  indefinite  perfectibility  of  knowledge  is  quite 
distinct  from,  and  rests  on  quite  other  grounds  than,  the  doe- 
trine  of  the  indefinite  perfectibility  of  the  intellectual  consti- 
tution. Philosophy,  science,  poetry,  and  politics  may  have 
made  constant  progress  from  the  origin  of  history  to  the 
present  day;  and  yet  the  philosophic  genius  of  Plato,  the 
scientific  genius  of  Aristotle,  the  poetical  genius  of  Homer, 
and  the  political  genius  of  Pericles,  may  never  have  been 
surpassed  or  even  equalled. 

Condorcet  believed  as  firmly  in  the  indefinite  progress  of 
morality  as  of  knowledge.  He  thought  the  knowledge  of 
moral  truth  could  not  retrograde  or  remain  stationary  if  the 
knowledge  of  all  other  truth  advanced,  and  that,  as  in  other 
spheres  so  in  ethics,  action  would  correspond  to  knowledge. 
"Men  could  not,"  he  says,   "become  enlightened  upon  the 


336  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FBANCE 

nature  and  development  of  their  moral  sentiments,  upon  the 
principles  of  morality,  and  upon  the  natural  motives  for  con- 
forming their  conduct  to  their  interests,  either  as  individuals 
or  as  members  of  society,  without  making  an  advancement  in 
moral  practice  not  less  real  than  in  moral  science  itself." 
"Just  as  the  mathematical  and  physical  sciences  contribute 
to  improve  the  arts  that  are  employed  for  our  most  simple 
wants,  is  it  not  equally, "  he  asks,  "  in  the  necessary  order  of 
nature  that  the  progress  of  the  moral  and  political  sciences 
should  exercise  a  similar  influence  upon  the  motives  that 
direct  our  sentiments  and  our  actions  ?  "  The  problem  with 
which  he  had  to  deal,  however,  was  too  complex  and  difficult 
to  be  solved  in  so  simple  and  superficial  c  way.  He  was  in 
all  probability  right  in  holding  that  there  has  been  consider- 
able moral  progress  in  the  past,  and  may  be  illimitable  moral 
progress  in  the  future ;  right  in  maintaining  that  the  growth 
of  knowledge  is  naturally  favourable  to  the  diffusion  of 
virtue,  and  that  the  destruction  of  false  and  the  establishment 
of  true  beliefs  are  indispensable  to  the  improvement  of  laws, 
institutions,  and  manners ;  right,  in  short,  as  against  all  who 
have  represented  ignorance  as  the  condition  of  innocence, 
intellectual  progress  as  indifferent  or  prejudicial  to  moral 
advancement,  or  morality  as  having  been  wholly  or  nearly 
stationary.  On  the  other  hand,  he  was  as  probably  wrong 
in  supposing  that  the  progress  of  knowledge,  and  even  of 
knowledge  of  ethical  subjects,  necessarily  or  universally 
brings  with  it  improvement  of  conduct,  or  that  virtue  must 
be  in  proportion  to  general  enlightenment;  wrong  in  believ- 
ing, or  at  least  virtually  assuming,  that  moral  progress  is 
dependent  on  no  other  causes  than  intellectual  progress  and 
those  influences  to  which  such  progress  is  itself  due;  and 
wrong,  like  so  many  of  his  contemporaries,  in  regarding  man 
as  good  by  nature,  and  only  evil  owing  to  ignorance,  errone- 
ous instruction,  or  bad  institutions.  He  overlooked  the 
greatest  of  all  impediments  to  moral  progress,  those  which 
are  inherent  in  human  nature  itself,  in  the  lusts  of  the  flesh, 
in  the  passions  of  the  soul.  He  asked:  "  What  vicious  habit 
can  be  mentioned,  what  practice  contrary  to  good  faith,  what 
crime  even,  the  origin  and  first  cause  of  which  may  not  be 


CONDORCET 


337 


traced  in  the  legislation,  institutions,  and  prejudices  of  the 
country  in  which  we  observed  such  habit,  such  practice,  or 
such  crime  to  be  committed  ?  "  But  he  did  not  ask :  Whence 
have  legislation,  institutions,  and  prejudices  derived  the 
injustice  and  vice  which  are  in  them  ?  He  failed  to  perceive 
that  legislation,  institutions,  and  prejudices  are  effects,  not 
"first  causes." 

Admission  of  the  doctrine  of  indefinite  moral  progression 
does  not  necessitate  admission  of  the  doctrine  that  the  men 
of  later  generations  will  be  born  with  better  moral  disposi- 
tions than  those  of  earlier  times.  True  or  false,  this  latter 
doctrine  of  Condorcet  has  no  essential  connection  with  the 
former.  It  is  proper  to  add  that  he  himself  has  not  presented 
it  as  more  than  "  a  conjecture  which  enlarges  the  boundary 
of  our  hopes,"  and  which  "analogy,  an  investigation  of  the 
human  faculties,  and  even  some  facts,  appear  to  authorise." 

The  extension  of  the  doctrine  of  perfectibility  to  the  physi- 
cal constitution  of  man  is  its  most  doubtful  application ;  and 
Condorcet  at  this  point  must,  I  think,  be  admitted  to  have 
fallen  into  extravagance.  It  is  inexcusable,  indeed,  to  repre- 
sent him,  as  some  careless  or  unscrupulous  critics  have  done, 
as  holding  that  our  physical  constitution  may  be  so  perfected 
that  man  will  live  for  ever ;  he  expressly  says,  "  certainly  man 
will  not  become  immortal."  He  believes,  however,  that  the 
improvements  in  medicine,  sanitary  science,  political  econ- 
omy, and  the  art  of  government,  may  vastly,  and  even  inimit- 
ably, prolong  life ;  "  that  a  period  will  arrive  when  death  will 
be  nothing  more  than  the  effect  either  of  extraordinary  acci- 
dents or  of  the  increasingly  slow  destruction  of  the  vital 
powers;  and  that  the  duration  of  the  interval  between  the 
birth  of  man  and  this  destruction,  will  itself  have  no  assign- 
able limit."  The  distance  between  the  moment  in  which 
man  begins  to  exist  and  the  common  term  when,  in  the  course 
of  nature,  without  malady,  and  without  accident,  he  finds  it 
impossible  any  longer  to  exist,  will,  he  affirms,  for  ever 
increase,  unless  its  increase  be  prevented  by  physical  revolu- 
tions, either  in  conformity  to  a  law  by  which,  though  approach- 
ing continually  an  unlimited  extent,  it  could  never  reach  it, 
or  a  law  by  which,  in  the  immensity  of  ages,  it  may  acquire 


338  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

a  greater  extent  than  any  determinate  quantity  which  may  he 
assigned  as  its  limit.1 

Now  there  is  much  in  this  theory  which  is  true  and  reason- 
able. We  certainly  do  not  exactly  know  the  normal  limits 
of  human  existence,  and  cannot  precisely  tell  when  death 
must  necessarily  occur  even  in  the  undisturbed  course  of 
nature.  That  the  rate  of  mortality  diminishes  with  the. 
advance  of  medical  science  and  the  progress  of  civilisation  is 
a  proposition  which  had  probability  in  its  favour  when  Con- 
dorcet  wrote,  and  which  has  been  amply  established  since. 
However  difficult  it  may  be  to  prove,  it  is  easy  to  conceive, 
and  in  no  way  inherently  absurd  to  suppose,  that  a  time  will 
come  when  death  will  result  only  from  accidents  which  cannot 
be  foreseen  or  from  slow  decay.  Reason  may  not  be  able 
positively  to  authorise,  but  neither  is  it  entitled  positively 
to  forbid,  the  hope  that  the  actual  average  duration  of  human 
life  will  approximate  indefinitely  to  its  average  normal  or 
natural  duration.  If,  when  Condorcet  speaks  of  the  infinite 
prolongation  of  human  life,  he  speaks  merely  of  its  mean 
duration  approaching  indefinitely  its  natural  limits,  then  there 
is  hardly  anything  unreasonable  in  what  he  teaches  as  to  the 
physical  perfectibility  of  man.  And  even  according  to  so 
careful  an  expositor  as  M.  Janet  this  is  really  all  that  he 
teaches  on  the  subject.2  I  cannot,  however,  so  interpret  our 
author's  language.  He  appears  to  me  plainly  to  mean  that 
"la  dure*e  moyenne  de  la  vie,"  "la  dure"e  de  l'intervalle 
moyen,"  is  not  the  average  of  actual  but  of  normal  life  —  not 
the  distance  between  birth  and  death  as  it  is,  .but  "  la  distance 
entre  la  moment  ou  l'homme  commence  a  vivre  et  l'dpoque 
commune  ou  naturellement  sans  maladie,  sans  accident, 
il  e'prouve  la  difficult^  d'etre;"  an  average  and  distance, 
therefore,  which  can  only  be  indefinitely  prolonged  by  the 
indefinite  recession  or  retreat  of  such  death  as  is  the  natural 
limit  of  life.  That  death  will  indefinitely  recede,  and  the 
distance  between  the  natural  limits  of  life  illimitably  increase, 
is,  I  think,  his  doctrine;  and  it  is  one  for  which  I  cannot 
perceive  that  we  have  any  evidence.  The  decrease  of  the 
death-rate  of  a  country  is  no  indication  that  the  bodies  of  its 
inhabitants  are  becoming  endowed  with  more  enduring  powers 

1  Esquisse,  pp.  379-383.  2  II.  p.  689. 


WALCKENAEE 


339 


of  life.  Not  a  step  has  }ret  been  made  towards  proving  that 
there  is  an  organic  evolution  towards  longevity  at  work  either 
among  human  beings  or  mere  animals. 

Condorcet  was  aware  that  his  hopes  as  to  human  progress 
were  dependent  on  its  not  being  arrested  by  physical  revolu- 
tions, on  the  earth  retaining  its  situation  in  the  system  of  the 
universe,  and  on  no  change  occurring  which  would  prevent 
the  human  race  from  exercising  the  faculties  or  finding  the 
resources  which  it  at  present  possesses.  A  more  thorough 
and  searching  investigation  would  have  shown  him  that  soci- 
ety carries  within  itself  greater  dangers  to  its  progress  than 
any  which  it  is  likely  to  encounter  from  without,  and  that 
these  are  of  such  a  kind  that  we  cannot  foresee  to  any  great 
distance  the  future  of  humanity.  His  optimism  as  to  that 
future  was  as  uncritical  as  is  our  later  pessimism  regarding 
it.  It  was  not  a  legitimate  inference  from  his  science ;  it  was 
his  religion, —  the  faith  which  yielded  him  strength  and  con- 
solation after  other  faith  had  been  lost. 

The  erroneousness  of  Condorcet's  opinion  as  to  the  indefi- 
nite prolongation  of  human  life  is  clearly  pointed  out  in  the 
'Essai  sur  l'Histoire  de  l'Esp&ce  Humaine,'  par  C.  A.  Walck- 
enaer,  published  in  1798.  It  is  shown  that  bodily  growth  is 
otherwise  limited  than  social  progress,  and  that  although 
individuals  must  die  in  a  short  term  of  years,  it  may  be  pos- 
sible for  nations  to  live  for  an  indefinite  time.  The  work  is 
characterised  by  good  sense ;  gives  evidence  of  a  large  amount 
of  reading;  and  touches  instructively  on  a  great  number  of 
points.  It  is  not  so  important,  however,  as  to  call  for  an 
extended  notice.  It  distinguishes  and  distributes  the  stages 
of  social  development  according  to  the  modes  in  which  men 
obtain  their  subsistence.  Hence  the  first  period  of  history  is 
represented  by  peoples  who  nourish  themselves  chiefly  with 
the  spontaneous  productions  of  the  ground;  the  second  by 
peoples  that  live  chiefly  by  fishing  and  hunting ;  the  third  by 
pastoral  peoples ;  the  fourth  by  agricultural  peoples  unaided 
by  commerce  and  manufactures ;  the  fifth  by  peoples  at  once 
agricultural,  commercial,  and  industrial;  and  the  sixth  by 
peoples  in  the  decadence  of  the  arts,  manufactures,  and  trade. 


CHAPTER  V 


THE   NINETEENTH   CENTURY:    GENERAL   REMARKS  — 
HISTORIOGRAPHY 


The  Revolution,  after  passing  through  various  stages  dur- 
ing which  the  minds  of  men  were  too  engrossed  with  the 
events  of  the  day  to  be  able  to  study  those  of  bygone  ages, 
issued  in  the  military  despotism  of  Napoleon,  which  proved 
as  unfavourable  to  historical  science  as  democratic  disorder 
and  violence  had  been.  Napoleon  was  the  persistent  op- 
pressor of  free  thought.  He  feared  and  hated  speculation ; 
cherished  a  mean  jealousy  of  every  kind  of  intellectual 
superiority  which  he  could  not  enslave ;  and  exerted  the 
immense  force  which  his  genius  and  fortune  gave  him  to 
turn  reason  from  every  path  of  inquiry  which  might  lead  to 
conclusions  unfavourable  to  his  own  schemes  and  interests. 
He  made  France,  as  has  been  said,  one  soldier,  and  himself 
the  god  of  that  soldier ;  and  to  confirm  and  perpetuate  the 
idolatry,  he  strove  to  extinguish  light  and  to  crush  liberty. 
He  failed  as  he  deserved  to  do ;  and  was  signally  punished 
for  his  selfish  abuse  of  vast  powers,  and  for  preferring  a  bane- 
ful glory  to  loyal  service  in  the  cause  of  France  and  of 
humanity.  When  he  fell,  the  profusion  with  which  ideas 
burst  forth  showed  how  ineffective  all  his  efforts  at  the 
repression  of  thought  had  been.  By  partially  and  tempo- 
rarily checking  its  utterance  he  had  probably  rather  favoured 
than  hindered  its  formation.  During  the  period  of  compara- 
tive silence  which  he  enforced,  men  did  not  cease  to  investi- 
gate and  reflect,  although  they  had  to  keep  their  conclusions 
to  themselves.  Consequently  when  freedom  returned  with 
the  Restoration,  it  soon  appeared  that  there  had  been  grow- 
ing up  diverse  systems  of  opinion,  all  resting  on,  or  at  least 
involving,  general  theories  of  history. 
340 


GENERAL   KBMAEKS  341 

Before  reviewing  these  theories,  however,  I  must  indicate 
some  of  the  conditions  which  favoured  their  rise  and  affected 
their  development. 

A  change  which  took  place  in  philosophical  belief  was  one 
condition  of  the  kind.  What  little  philosophy  was  taught 
in  France  during  the  Empire  was  that  which  had  prevailed 
in  the  latter  half  of  the  eighteenth  century,  the  Condillacian 
ideology  which  derived  all  knowledge  from  impressions  of 
sense.  But  this  doctrine  was  already  in  decay  at  the  com- 
mencement of  the  nineteenth  century,  and  imperial  toleration 
did  not  tend  to  reinvigorate  it  or  to  increase  its  influence. 
Some  of  the  latest  representatives  of  ideology  were  accom- 
plished and  able  men,  but  they  required  to  discuss  only  safe 
themes  and  to  speak  as  under  authority;  they  could  not 
apply  their  principles  with  independence  to  the  solution  of 
religious,  political,  or  social  questions,  or  to  the  elucidation 
of  the  course  or  significance  of  history,  or,  indeed,  to  the  dis- 
cussion of  any  subject  of  great  and  general  interest.  Besides, 
their  doctrine  itself  was  increasingly  felt  to  be  barren  and 
unprofitable.  Imagination  and  feeling,  the  heart  and  spirit, 
metaphysics  and  religion,  made  more  and  more  emphatic 
claims  to  a  satisfaction  which  a  doctrine  reducing  everything 
to  sensation  and  using  only  analysis  could  not  give.  Ideol- 
ogy scarcely  survived  the  Empire.  The  modifications  made 
on  it  by  Laromiguidre  and  Maine  de  Biran  rendered  only 
more  apparent  its  radical  insufficiency.  Royer-Collard,  in 
opposing  to  it  the  philosophy  of  Reid,  showed  the  necessity 
of  getting  rid  of  it,  and  suggested  the  possibility  of  finding 
a  better  system.  Cousin  enthroned  in  its  stead  an  eclectic 
philosophy  which  professed  to  be  the  outcome  of  all  the  phi- 
losophies of  the  past;  to  reject  what  was  false  and  to  combine 
what  was  true  in  sensualism,  idealism,  scepticism,  and  mys- 
ticism; to  employ  as  its  method  close  internal  observation, 
strict  analysis,  and  careful  induction,  yet  to  rise  thereby  from 
psychology  to  ontology,  and  not  to  neglect  dealing  with  any 
of  the  great  problems  of  metaphysics  or  to  refuse  satisfaction 
to  any  of  the  real  interests  of  religion ;  to  welcome  light  from 
all  quarters,  and  to  stimulate  research  in  every  direction ;  and 
to  unite  philosophy  and  history  in  the  most  intimate  and  fruit- 


342  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

ful  co-operation.  A  spiritualist  philosophy  derived  from  or 
akin  to  the  eclecticism  of  Cousin  was  the  predominant  philos- 
ophy in  France  for  about  forty  years,  and  is  still  not  without 
vigour.  What  the  philosophical  situation  in  France  has  been 
during  the  last  thirty  years  need  not  be  at  present  described.1 
A  change  occurred  in  regard  to  religion  analogous  to  that 
as  to  philosophy.  Before  and  during  the  Revolution  a  fanati- 
cally anti-religious  spirit  prevailed.  But  this  spirit  was  dis- 
credited by  the  excesses  to  which  it  gave  rise,  as  well  as  by 
its  coldness,  poverty,  and  self-sufficiency.  A  reaction  ensued 
of  which  Napoleon  took  advantage,  and  to  which  Chateau- 
briand's '  Ge"nie  du  Christianisme  '  gave  an  immense  impulse, 
as  much  because  of  its  opportuneness  as  of  its  ability.  Crowds 
flocked  to  the  reopened  churches ;  Catholicism  regained  favour. 
Napoleon's  despotic  conduct  towards  the  Catholic  clergy  and 
the  Pope  seriously  injured  the  Gallicanism  which  he  sup- 
ported, greatly  strengthened  the  Ultramontanism  which  he 
opposed,  and  gave  popularity  and  influence  to  the  writings 
and  ideas  of  De  Maistre  and  De  Bonald.  The  sceptical  and 
atheistical  views  which  had  been  current  in  the  eighteenth 
century  were,  of  course,  widely  held  during  the  period  of 
the  Empire,  but  they  were  not  allowed  expression,  and  only 
found  vent  after  the  Restoration  when  clerical  and  political 
reactionaries  stirred  up  slumbering  revolutionary  passions. 
Madame  de  Stael,  Benjamin  Constant,  and  others  like-minded, 
while  not  acknowledging  supernatural  revelation,  warmly 
advocated  the  claims  of  religion,  and  insisted  that  religious 
faith  was  not  merely  intellectual  assent,  but  also  emotion, 
affection,  and  self-surrender,  a  conscious  experience  of  life  in 
God.  Since  the  Restoration  the  religious  condition  of  France 
has  been  very  unstable  and  fluctuating.  Religious  indepen- 
dence and  reasonableness  are  comparatively  little  diffused,  and 
those  who  possess  them  are  without  the  union,  the  organisa- 
tion, and  the  enthusiasm  necessary  to  spread  spiritual  truth 

1  On  the  history  of  philosophy  in  France  during  the  present  century  see  M.  Ph. 
Damiron,  '  Essai  sur  l'histoire  de  la  Philosophie  en  France  au  xixe  siecle,'  3d  ed. 
1835;  F.  Ravaisson, '  La  Philosophie  en  France  au  xixc  siecle,'  1867, 3d  ed.  1889;  and 
M.  Ferraz,  '  Histoire  de  la  Philosophie  en  France  au  xix»  siecle ' ;  '  Socialisme, 
Naturalisme,  et  Positivisme,'  1877 ;  '  Traditionalisme  et  Ultramontanisme,'  3d  ed. 
1880 ; '  Spiritualisme  et  Liberalisme,'  1887. 


GENERAL   REMARKS  343 

and  freedom  among  a  people.  Clericalism  is  admirably  or- 
ganised and  indefatigably  active.  It  abounds  in  means 
and  agents  of  propagandism,  and  can  point  to  many  good 
works  done  and  excellent  institutions  maintained;  but  it 
spreads  false  and  degrading  superstitions,  is  unscrupulous 
where  its  own  interests  are  concerned,  and  is  hopelessly 
committed  to  the  denial  of  rights  and  liberties  essential  alike 
to  individuals  and  to  nations.  The  more  it  gains  ground  and 
displays  its  true  character,  the  more  there  is  evoked  a  bitter 
and  passionate  spirit  of  unbelief  and  irreligion,  which  far 
overshoots  its  mark,  confounds  truth  and  error,  good  and 
evil,  and  by  its  blindness  and  violence  increases  and  consoli- 
dates the  power  of  the  enemy  which  it  seeks  to  destroy. 
Throughout  the  present  century  the  religious  question  has 
been  keenly  agitated  in  France  ;  and  the  course  of  its  discus- 
sion has  naturally  had  a  very  considerable  influence  on  the 
general  course  and  character  of  French  historical  reflection. 
All  thoughtful  Frenchmen  recognise  that  the  question  has  as 
yet  been  only  superficially  and  inadequately  answered.1 

The  changes  which  philosophy  and  religion  underwent  were 
accompanied  by  a  corresponding  change  in  literature.  For 
more  than  two  hundred  years  the  so-called  classical  style  had 
been  alone  cultivated.  The  boldest  innovators  of  the  eigh- 
teenth century  did  not  dream  of  emancipating  themselves  from 
the  rules  based  on  the  assumption  of  its  exclusive  legitimacj-. 
Rousseau  and  Diderot,  B.  de  Saint-Pierre  and  A.  Chenier, 
were,  indeed,  precursors  of  the  coming  change,  but  uncon- 
sciously. With  the  opening  years  of  the  present  century, 
however,  there  began  to  make  itself  felt  throughout  France,  as 
throughout  the  rest  of  Europe,  a  new  life  which  the  old  liter- 
ary forms  could  not  contain  or  satisfy.  It  was  a  freer  and 
richer,  a  more  natural  and  yet  subtler  life,  and  it  originated  a 
movement  of  revolt  against  the  inherited  traditions  and  con- 
ventions, —  a   movement  which  claimed   for  the  ideal  and 

1  De  Pressense"'s '  L'Eglise  et  la  Revolution,'  D'Haussonville's '  L'Eglise  romaine 
et  le  premier  Empire,'  and  A.  Leroy  Beaulieu's  'Les  Catholiques  liberaux  et 
l'Eglise  de  France  depuis  1830  a  nos  jours  '  ('Rev.  des  Deux  Mondes,'  torn.  lxiv. 
and  lxvi.),  form  a  good  introduction  to  a  study  of  the  religious  situation,  and  of 
the  successive  phases  assumed  by  the  ecclesiastical  question  in  France  during  the 
nineteenth  century. 


344  PHILOSOPHY   OF  HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

infinite  a  fuller  recognition,  and  for  imagination  a  wider 
sphere  of  activity,  which  did  not  hesitate  to  employ  hitherto 
unused  modes  of  expression  and  to  convey  hitherto  unfelt 
sentiments,  and  which  thus  at  once  enfranchised  speech  and 
enriched  thought.  Its  representatives,  with  Victor  Hugo  at 
their  head,  have  renewed  French  literature  in  all  its  forms, 
and  shown  that  the  French  mind  and  language  are  abundantly 
endowed  with  powers  which  they  were  not  previously  sus- 
pected to  possess.  Victor  Hugo  has  been,  perhaps,  as  much 
the  literary  king  of  the  nineteenth  century  as  Voltaire  was  of 
the  eighteenth.  Romanticism  greatly  affected  historiography; 
in  fact,  it  so  quickened  the  historical  imagination  and  so 
enlarged  historical  sympathy  as  almost  to  transform  history 
into  a  new  art.  It  is  not  likely  that  the  spirit  of  Romanti- 
cism, after  having  for  half  a  century  pervaded  and  leavened 
French  literature,  will  be  ever  again  wholly  expelled  from  it. 
But  during  the  last  twenty  years  it  has  ceased  to  be  its  chief 
inspiration.  At  present  Naturalism  or  Realism  is  predomi- 
nant in  all  departments  of  literary  art.1 

The  political  spirit  of  France  in  the  nineteenth  century  has 
likewise  not  been  what  it  was  in  the  eighteenth  century.  It 
has  been,  considerably  less  self-confident  and  dogmatic,  much 
more  hesitating  and  opportunist ;  it  has  learned  not  to  despise 
"  accomplished  facts"  and  "the  powers  that  be."  The  politi- 
cians of  the  Revolution,  and  the  philosophers  who  were  their 
teachers,  started  from  faith  in  certain  principles  which  they 
held  to  be  ultimate,  certain  rights  which  they  regarded  as 
inalienable,  and  from  these  they  deductively  reached  codes 
and  constitutions  which  they  deemed  alone  legitimate  and 
unconditionally  applicable.  They  laid  comparatively  little 
stress  on  historical  considerations.  It  is  a  common  notion,  at 
least  outside  of  France,  that  this  is  still  the  way  in  which 
Frenchmen  deal  with  political  questions  and  affairs,  owing  to 
an  inveterate  characteristic  which  unfavourably  distinguishes 
the  French  from  the  English  and  German  mind.  The  political 
history  of  France  in  the  present  century  does  not  support  this 
notion.  The  weakness  most  conspicuous  in  French  political 
practice  since  the  Restoration  has  been  excessive  distrust  of 

1  See  G.  Pellissier,  '  Le  Mouvement  Litte'raire  au  xix«  Steele,'  1889. 


GENERAL   REMARKS  345 

reason  and  principle,  excessive  deference  to  history  and  prece- 
dent. Whereas  in  the  revolutionary  period  men  too  commonly 
acted  as  if  free-will  were  omnipotent,  as  if  the  ideal  could  be 
realised  in  all  circumstances,  and  as  if  the  past  could  be  pre- 
vented from  influencing  the  present  or  the  future,  they  have 
since  very  widely  assumed  that  there  is  no  other  truth  than 
that  of  fact  and  success,  that  history  is  a  process  of  fatalistic 
evolution,  and  that  both  universal  rights  and  individual  efforts 
are  of  little  moment.  The  political  doctrines  which  have  found 
favour  in  France  among  our  contemporaries  and  their  imme- 
diate predecessors  have  been  mostly  based  on  the  interpreta- 
tion or  misinterpretation  of  history,  not  drawn  by  deduction 
from  true  or  false  principles.  The  connection  between 
history  and  politics  has  been  nowhere  so  close  as  in  France. 
While  in  Germany  the  course  of  historical  theorising  has 
been  mainly  determined  by  the  movement  of  philosophy,  in 
France  it  has  been  chiefly  affected  by  the  interests  and  vicissi- 
tudes of  politics. 

Further,  the  spirit  of  the  eighteenth  century  decidedly 
inclined  towards  individualism,  whereas  that  of  the  nineteenth , 
century  has,  on  the  whole,  tended  towards  socialism.  The 
great  aim  of  the  men  of  the  eighteenth  century  was  to  secure 
the  rights  and  liberties  of  individuals,  to  remove  burdens,  to 
destroy  privileges  and  inequalities,  to  weaken  the  power  of 
the  State  and  to  limit  the  sphere  of  its  action.  It  was  pre- 
dominantly negative  and  destructive.  When  the  Restoration 
allowed  opinion  freely  to  manifest  itself,  it  was  seen  that  this 
was  no  longer  its  general  character.  What  all  the  great 
parties  in  France  were  beheld  to  be  aiming  at  was  construc- 
tion, organisation.  The  Ultramontanists  or  Theocratists  were 
denouncing  the  ages  of  private  judgment ;  and  were  urging 
that  authority  should  be  re-established,  and  that  society 
should  be  built  up  anew,  on  the  basis  on  which  it  had  rested 
previous  to  the  Renaissance  and  the  Reformation.  The 
Socialists,  while  maintaining  these  ages  to  be  transitionally 
necessary,  and  denying  that  humanity  could  be  reasonably 
expected  to  return  to  its  medieval  condition,  admitted  that 
the  epoch  of  private  judgment,  the  critical  epoch,  ought  not 
to  be  prolonged,  but  that  an  organic  epoch  should  be  intro- 


346  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

duced :  hence  their  schemes  for  the  suppression  of  poverty 
through  the  organisation  of  industry.  The  Constitutionalists 
of  all  shades  were  at  one  in  maintaining  that  society  ought  to 
be  regarded  as  an  organic  system,  in  which  all  interests  should 
be  duly  recognised  and  guarded,  and  all  forces  properly  dis- 
tributed and  harmonised.  The  characteristic  referred  to  has 
been  especially  conspicuous  in  the  economic  domain.  The 
condition  of  the  labouring  population  in  France  became  soon 
after  the  Restoration  very  different  from  what  it  had  been 
previous  to  the  Revolution  or  under  the  Empire.  As  regards 
the  class  occupied  with  agriculture,  its  position  was  greatly 
improved  in  consequence  of  the  changes  effected  by  the 
Revolution.  But  it  lost  its  relative  importance.  Mechanical 
inventions,  chemical  discoveries,  and  the  applications  of 
steam,  electricity,  &c,  to  the  furtherance  of  production,  gave 
vast  dimensions  to  manufactures  and  trade,  led  to  a  redistri- 
bution of  population,  and,  in  fact,  brought  about  an  industrial 
revolution  as  socially  influential  as  the  political  one  which 
had  been  so  violent  and  manifest.  It  called  into  existence  a 
fourth  estate  more  formidable  than  the  third  estate,  in  the 
interests  of  which  mainly  the  Revolution  had  been  effected. 
It  raised  questions  which  no  legislation  about  land,  taxes,  or 
privileges  of  birth  and  rank  could  settle,  —  questions  as  to 
the  right  of  private  property  itself,  as  to  the  justice  of  the 
gains  of  capital  employed  by  individuals  in  any  circumstances, 
and  as  to  the  duty  of  attempting  to  reconstitute  and  reor- 
ganise society  with  a  view  to  the  suppression  of  competition 
and  the  extinction  of  poverty.  The  desire,  in  many  instances 
so  passionately  intense  as  to  be  akin  to  religious  fanaticism, 
for  a  revolution,  social  rather  than  political,  and  more 
comprehensive  and  constructive  than  that  with  which  the 
eighteenth  century  closed,  has  taken  a  general  and  tenacious 
hold  of  the  industrial  population  of  France  since  the  Restora- 
tion, and  has  been  the  cause  or  occasion  of  infinite  perplexity, 
of  great  calamities,  and  of  many  and  strange  speculations 
and  schemes. 

France,  in  passing  through  the  changes  indicated,  has 
moved  with  the  movement,  and  lived  in  the  life,  of  Europe. 
The  nations  which  constitute  the  European  system  have  never 


DAUNOU  347 

been  less  isolated,  or  more  manifoldly  and  intimately  con- 
nected, than  in  the  nineteenth  century.  And  France  has,  at 
least  since  1815,  been  singularly  open  and  susceptible  to  ideas 
and  influences  coming  from  without.  While  largely  giving  to 
the  nations  around  her,  she  has  as  largely  received  from  them. 
She  has  done  nothing  entirely  by  herself.  She  has  produced 
unaided  and  alone  neither  her  philosophy  nor  her  science, 
literature,  art,  or  industry.  Her  philosophy  has  been  drawn 
to  some  extent  from  Scottish,  English,  Spanish,  and  Italian 
sources,  and  to  a  still  greater  extent  from  German  sources. 
The  rise  of  romanticism  in  French  literature  was  due  to  causes 
which  affected  all  Europe,  and  which  made  themselves  felt  in 
Britain  and  Germany  even  earlier  than  in  France.  The  dis- 
cussion of  social  and  religious  questions  in  France  has  been 
influenced  by  their  agitation  in  neighbouring  countries.  The 
students  of  physical  science  and  of  historical  research  are 
throughout  all  Europe  in  incessant  communication,  fellow- 
workers  in  a  commonwealth  of  which  the  limits  are  far  wider 
than  those  of  nationality,  and  of  which  the  members  must  be 
on  the  alert  to  know  what  all  others  similarly  engaged  are 
accomplishing. 

The  foregoing  considerations  will  find  ample  confirmation 
in  the  succeeding  portion  of  this  volume. 

II 

The  rule  of  Napoleon  was  extremely  unfavourable  to  his- 
torical study;  but  even  under  his  reign  the  classical  and 
ideological  school  had  three  worthy  representative  historians 
in  Daunou,  Ginguene",  and  Michaud. 

Daunou  was  born  in  1761.  He  belonged  in  early  life  to  the 
Congregation  of  the  Oratory ;  played  an  active  and  honoura- 
ble part  in  the  Revolution ;  and  was  keeper  of  the  archives 
under  Bonaparte.  After  1819  he  taught  history  in  the  Col- 
lege of  France  for  many  years ;  was  elected  perpetual  secre- 
tary of  the  Academy  of  Inscriptions  in  1838;  was  raised  to 
the  peerage  in  1839 ;  and  died  in  1840.  He  was  thoroughly 
imbued  with  the  ideas  of  the  eighteenth  century,  while  a 
Benedictine  in  his  habits.     He  was  of  a  firm  and  indepen- 


348  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

dent  character ;  strongly  opposed  the  condemnation  of  Louis 
XVI.  to  death ;  and  was  the  reverse  of  subservient  to  Napo- 
leon, although  he  lent  him  important  aid  in  his  controversy 
with  the  Pope.  His  best  historical  work  was  done  in  connec- 
tion with  the  'Histoire  Litte"raire  de  France.'  The  'Discours 
sur  l'e"tat  des  Lettres  au  xiiie  sidcle,'  which  fills  most  of  the 
sixteenth  volume,  is  especially  remarkable;  and  that  not 
merely  for  its  erudition  and  clearness  of  exposition,  but  even, 
considering  its  author's  aversion  to  the  medieval  spirit,  for 
its  impartiality.1 

Ginguene"  (1748-1816)  was  also  a  contributor  to  the  'His- 
toire Litteraire  de  France,'  but  his  claim  to  remembrance  rests 
chiefly  on  his  'Histoire  Litteraire  d'ltalie'  (9  vols.,  1811-19). 
In  this  work  he  depicted  the  intellectual  development  of 
Italy  from  the  close  of  the  thirteenth  to  the  close  of  the 
sixteenth  century,  giving  a  full  and  interesting,  although  un- 
doubtedly a  generally  too  favourable,  account  of  the  literary 
products  of  the  whole  of  that  time.  His  work  is  indeed 
based  on,  and  even  largely  borrowed  from,  that  of  Tiraboschi, 
but  it  has  also  merits  exclusively  its  own,  and  is  still  a  book 
with  which  the  student  of  Italian  literature  cannot  dispense. 

Michaud  (1767-1839),  we  are  told  by  his  oollaborateur  and 
biographer  Poujoulat,  "spent  almost  every  moment  of  twenty 
of  the  best  years  of  his  life  "  on  his  'History  of  the  Crusades.' 
The  result  was  an  immense  addition  to  what  was  previously 
known  regarding  these  extraordinary  and  eventful  movements. 

Madame  de  Stael  and  the  Viscount  de  Chauteaubriand 
initiated  in  France  the  literature  distinctive  of  the  nineteenth 
century.  Both  exerted  a  powerful  influence  on  the  develop- 
ment even  of  French  historical  literature. 

Madame  de  Stael  (1746-1817)  has  a  place  apart  among  the 
illustrious  women  of  the  nineteenth  century.  As  a  literary 
artist  she  may,  perhaps,  have  been  equalled  or  surpassed  by 
George  Sand,  or  George  Eliot,  or  some  others  of  her  sex;  but 
not  in  personal  greatness  or  general  influence.  No  other 
woman  of  the  century  has  shown  the  same  force  of  intellect,  as 
wide  a  range  of  culture,  as  firm  and  comprehensive  a  grasp  of 
the  principles  on  which  social  stability  and  progress  depend, 

1  Daunou  has  been  admirably  appreciated  by  Mignet,  and  unjustly  depreciated 
by  Sainte-Beuve.    See  also  Picavet,  '  Les  Ideologues,'  pp.  399-408. 


MADAME   DE   STAEL  349 

or  a  will  as  energetic  in  defence  of  them,  and  as  resolutely  and 
righteously  defiant  towards  a  seemingly  omnipotent  despotism. 
She  owes  her  unique  position,  notwithstanding  some  French 
defects  and  feminine  weaknesses,  not  less  to  her  greatness 
and  generosity  of  heart,  and  her  strength  and  nobility  of 
character,  than  to  her  brilliance  and  vigour  of  intellect. 
Here,  of  course,  I  have  only  to  indicate  how  her  writings 
concern  the  art  or  the  science  of  history.  Her  'De  la  Lit- 
te"rature  considered  dans  ses  rapports  avec  les  institutions 
sociales '  (1800)  showed  how  much  she  had  been  influenced 
by  Rousseau  as  a  writer,  but  also  how  much  she  was  his  su- 
perior in  political  and  historical  intelligence.  It  assigned  to 
literature  its  due  place  in  society  and  history,  insisting  on  its 
importance  to  them,  and  pointing  out  how  poor  and  dull  they 
must  be  without  it.  It  exhibited  in  a  clear  light  the  close- 
ness of  the  connection  between  the  development  of  litera- 
ture and  of  society,  and  established  that  literature  could  not 
be  judged  of  aright  by  merely  examining  its  products  in 
themselves,  apart  from  the  social  medium  in  which,  and  the 
social  influences  under  which,  they  came  into  being.  It  thus 
made  manifest  the  insufficiency  of  literary  criticism  as  it  had 
hitherto  been  practised,  and  the  necessity  of  adopting  that 
comparative  and  historical  method  which  Villemain,  Sainte- 
Beuve,  Taine,  and  others,  have  since  so  successfully  employed. 
It  likewise  maintained  that  progress  in  literature  required  an 
originality  which  could  only  be  attained  by  having  recourse  to 
fresh  fountains  of  inspiration,  and  by  absorbing  new  elements 
of  life ;  and  that  French  literature,  in  particular,  needed  for 
its  reinvigoration  to  avail  itself  more  of  what  the  Christian 
spirit  and  Germanic  thought  and  imagination  could  supply 
it  with.  The  idea  that  the  history  of  literature,  like  that 
of  humanity  in  general,  is  ruled  by  a  law  of  perfectibility, 
pervades  the  whole  book,  and  is  presented  with  some  exag- 
geration. 'Corinne'  (1807),  although  a  romance,  helped  to 
correct  and  enlarge  historical  thought  by  the  views  which 
it  gave  of  the  significance  of  the  fine  arts  in  human  life, 
and  of  the  place  and  mission  of  Italy  among  the  nations. 
'  L'Allemagne '  (1810)  was  a  still  greater  event.  It  was  mar- 
vellously successful  in  revealing  to  Europe  the  originality 
and  interest  of  German  philosophy  and  literature,  and  in 


350  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

preparing  the  way  for  their  serious  and  sympathetic  study. 
It  broke  down,  as  Goethe  has  observed,  the  wall  of  intellectual 
separation  between  France  and  Germany,  to  the  great  benefit 
of  both.  The  'Considerations  sur  la  Revolution  francaise' 
(1818),  although  an  unfinished  book,  not  well  planned  or 
proportioned,  and  too  much  of  an  apotheosis  of  Necker,  is 
characterised,  on  the  whole,  by  a  power  of  insight  and  of 
comprehension  greater  even  than  had  been  displayed  in  any 
of  Madame  de  Stael's  previous  writings.  The  causes  of  the 
Revolution  are  accurately  indicated ;  its  principal  events  are 
impartially  judged ;  its  faults  and  crimes  are  condemned  as 
they  deserve,  while  due  allowance  is  made  for  circumstances ; 
its  bad  and  its  good  effects  are  alike  exhibited ;  and  the 
conditions  of  orderly  and  free  government  are  admirably 
expounded.1 

Madame  de  Stael  was  the  leader  and  inspirer  of  all  among 
her  French-speaking  contemporaries  who  held  fast  to  what 
had  been  true  in  the  Revolution,  and  who  maintained  the 
cause  of  unlicentious  liberty  and  constitutional  government. 
Two  of  her  friends  did  good  service  as  historians.  Sismondi 
(1773-1842)  devoted  almost  fifty  years  of  a  laborious  exist- 
ence to  historical  research  and  composition.  His  '  Histoire  des 
Republiques  Italiennes  du  Moyen  Age '  (16  vols.,  1807-1818) 
is  perhaps  his  best  work;  but  his  'Histoire  des  Francais'  (31 
vols.,  1821-1844)  was  much  superior  to  any  previous  history 
of  France.  Benjamin  Constant  (1767-1837)  was  a  practical 
politician,  not  a  professional  historian,  but  he  wrote  a  history 
of  religion  from  a  point  of  view  both  new  and'true.  His  '  De 
la  Religion,  considered  dans  sa  source,  ses  formes  et  ses  de"vel- 
bppements '  (5  yols.,  1824-1831),  traces  the  progress  of  the 
sentiment  which  he  holds  to  be  the  constituent  element  of 
religion,  as  it  purines  and  perfects  itself  without  ceasing,  and 
creates  and  destroys  a  multitude  of  dogmatic  and  ecclesias- 
tical systems  on  its  way  towards  full  satisfaction.  It  was  one 
of  the  earliest  attempts  to  treat  religion  simply  as  a  psycho- 
logical and  historical  phenomenon.  The  merits  of  the  con- 
ception may  atone  for  considerable  defects  of  execution. 

1  The  literature  regarding  Madame  de  Stael  is  vast.  The  best  works  belonging 
to  it  are  indicated  by  M.  Albert  Sorel  in  his  comprehensive  and  excellent  book, 
'  Madame  de  Stael,'  published  in  the  series  of  '  Les  Grands  Ecrivains  Francais.' 


CHATEATJBBIAND  351 

Chateaubriand  (1768-1848),  while  inferior  to  Madame  de 
Stael  in  understanding  and  character,  had  more  of  the 
temperament  of  genius,  more  of  the  spirit  of  poetry,  a  keener 
feeling  of  beauty,  higher  gifts  of  imagination,  and  finer 
powers  of  expression.  He  did  sore  injustice  to  his  real  great- 
ness by  an  inordinate  desire  of  appearing  great,  and  marred 
the  effect  even  of  chivalrous  and  magnanimous  actions  of 
which  few  but  himself  were  capable  by  his  excessive  love 
of  effect.  If  he  failed,  however,  as  a  politician,  he  succeeded 
in  exerting  vast  influence  as  a  man  of  letters.  His  earliest 
work,  the  '  Essai  sur  les  Revolutions '  (1797),  is  interesting 
to  a  student  of  his  personal  history  from  the  date  and  circum- 
stances of  its  composition,  its  sceptical  and  melancholy  tone, 
and  even  its  immature  and  chaotic  character;  but  as  a  treat- 
ment of  its  theme  it  can  only  be  regarded  as  an  incoherent 
rhapsody.  The  doctrine  of  perfectibility  is  scouted.  It  is 
declared  that  the  human  race  has  not  made  a  step  of  progress 
in  the  moral  sciences;  and  that  even  the  principles  of  the 
physical  sciences,  in  which  alone  there  has  been  any  advance, 
may  easily  be  denied.  His  '  Ge"nie  du  Christianisme  '  (1802) 
had  an  immense  effect  in  recommending  Catholicism  to  the 
popular  imagination  and  heart.  It  was  an  apology  for  Ca- 
tholicism, not  for  Christianity.  Par  from  attempting  to  dis- 
tinguish in  Catholicism  the  Christian  from  the  unchristian 
elements,  it  assumed  it  to  be  Christian  throughout,  and 
endeavoured  by  appeals  to  fancy  and  feeling  to  show  how 
beautiful,  consoling,  and  strengthening  it  had  been,  and  was 
fitted  to  be,  in  all  its  beliefs  and  practices.  It  was  most 
skilfully  accommodated  to  the  state  of  the  public  mind 
when  it  appeared,  exquisitely  adapted  to  secure  the  immediate 
end  which  it  actually  attained,  and  written  with  a  beauty  and 
charm  of  style  previously  unknown  in  French  prose ;  but  it 
lacked  the  inner  truthfulness  without  which  the  glory  of  art 
must  pass  away  before  the  scrutiny  of  reason  as  the  flower 
of  the  grass  withereth  under  the  heat  of  the  sun.  Its  influ- 
ence was,  therefore,  extensive  rather  than  intensive,  wide  but 
not  enduring.  No  work  published  in  France,  however,  con- 
tributed so  much  to  discredit  the  eighteenth-century  estimate 
of  the  middle  ages,  and  of  their  institutions.  The  '  Martyrs ' 
(1809)  were  the  opening  of  a  new  epoch  in  historical  compo- 


352  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

sition.  Greek  and  Christian  life  were  there  beautifully 
depicted,  and  the  Franks  marched  to  battle  fierce  and  terrible 
as  when  they  conquered  the  Gauls  and  the  Romans.  It  is  well 
known  how  the  vivid  descriptions  of  this  work,  and  Sir  Walter 
Scott's  '  Ivanhoe,'  acted  on  the  imagination  of  young  Augustin 
Thierry,  and  influenced  his  choice  of  a  career.  They  thus 
directly  contributed  to  give  to  France  the  greatest  of  his- 
torical narrators,  one  of  the  most  illustrious  chiefs  of  the 
modern  historical  school.  The  principal  historical  production 
of  Chateaubriand  is  his  'Etudes  Historiques,'  4  vols.,  1836 
(OEuvres  Completes,  iv.-vii.).  It  is  unfinished  and  fragmen- 
tary, and  has  been  the  least  read  of  his  works.  It  shows  want 
of  thoroughness  in  research,  numerous  marks  of  haste  in  the 
form  of  small  inaccuracies,  and  a  decided  preference  for 
striking  versions  of  incidents  to  those  which  are  more  prosaic 
but  better  authenticated.  On  the  other  hand,  as  regards  sim- 
plicity, vividness,  and  agreeableness  of  style,  it  is  surpassed 
by  few  histories  of  the  graphic,  narrative  kind.  The  preface, 
dated  1831,  is  of  special  interest.  It  indicates  the  character- 
istics of  a  large  number  of  French  historians.  It  gives  a 
slight  account  of  Vico's  historical  philosophy  (pp.  47-50). 
It  vigorously  criticises  and  refutes  the  fatalistic  theory  of 
history  attributed  to  Thiers  and  Mignet,  and  the  theory  of 
the  Terror  propounded  by  Jacobin  historians  (pp.  74-88). 
It  states  the  reasons  which  may  be  assigned  for  preferring 
any  of  the  various  species  of  history,  but  maintains  that  no 
one  is  exclusively  valid ;  that  they  may  be  profitably  com- 
bined ;  and  that  each  historian  should  follow  the  natural  bent 
of  his  own  genius.  The  book  professed  to  be  pervaded  and 
unified  by  a  comprehensive  and  original  philosophical  idea. 
It  claimed  to  rest  the  whole  system  of  humanity  on  the  triple 
basis  of  religious,  philosophical,  and  political  truth ;  to  judge 
of  the  progress  in  history  by  the  measure  of  the  appropriation 
of  these  three  kinds  of  truth ;  and  to  refer  to  them  all  the 
facts  of  history  according  as  there  is  between  them  conflict, 
separation,  or  harmony.  But  this  idea  is  left  vague  and 
undeveloped;  it  does  not  penetrate,  inspire,  or  mould  the 
history.  In  the  '  Etudes,'  I  may  add,  Chateaubriand  appears 
as  a   decided    believer   in    progress.     Notwithstanding    his 


THIERRY 


353 


faith  in  Legitimacy,  there  could  never  be  any  doubt  of  his 
regard  for  liberty.1 

The  great  masters  who  initiated  in  France  the  various 
forms  of  the  historiography  distinctive  of  the  nineteenth  cen- 
tury were  Augustin  Thierry,  De  Barante,  Guizot,  Mignet, 
Thiers,  and  Michelet. 

Augustin  Thierry  (1795-1826)  almost  perfected  historiog- 
raphy as  a  literary  art.  He  has  no  superior  as  an  animated 
and  picturesque  narrator.  There  is  in  his  style  and  mode  of 
treating  a  subject  a  simplicity,  breadth,  and  vividness,  a  charm 
and  a  force,  which  remind  us  of  Homer.  His  '  Conqu§te  de 
1'Angleterre  par  les  Normands '  casts  a  spell  over  the  reader 
not  unlike  that  of  '  Ivanhoe '  itself.  His  '  Re"cits  des  Temps 
Merovingiens  '  gave  to  ages  which  had  previously  seemed  the 
dullest  and  dreariest  imaginable  an  interest  which  has  stimu- 
lated to  various  fruitful  researches,  and  which  has  not  yet 
passed  away.  In  his  'Lettres  sur  l'histoire  de  France,'  he 
showed  with  rare  effectiveness  in  what  respects  the  older 
historians,  when  dealing  with  the  medieval  period  of  French 
history,  had  failed  to  satisfy  the  requirements  of  historical 
investigation  and  exposition ;  and  he  exhibited  in  the  clearest 
light  what  these  requirements  were.  In  his  maturest  work, 
the  '  Essai  sur  l'histoire  de  la  formation  et  des  progres  du  Tiers 
Etat,'  he  entered  on  a  path  which  Guizot  had  opened,  and 
followed  it  up  with  a  success  which  has  excited  many  to 
emulation.  He  fully  recognised  that  the  historian  should  be 
content  only  with  the  oldest  and  most  reliable  testimony ;  and 
he  constantly  referred  in  support  of  his  statements  to  what  he 
believed  to  be  such  testimony.  His  historical  criticism,  how- 
ever, was  weak.  He  often  failed  sufficiently  to  sift  the  evi- 
dence; often  took  false  for  true  witnesses;  often  failed  to 
observe  the  order  and  relationship  in  which  those  whom  he 
adduced  as  authorities  stood  to  one  another  and  to  the  facts. 
At  times  his  imagination  outran  his  knowledge.  And  even  his 
sympathy  with  the  weak  and  vanquished  exercised  a  disturb- 
ing influence  on  his  sense  of  historical  justice.    This  was  in  a 

i  On  Chateaubriand  see  Villemain, '  Le  Tribune  Moderne,  M.  de  Chateaubriand,' 
1858 ;  Sainte-Beuve,  '  Chateaubriand  et  son  Groupe  Litte'raire  sous  l'Empire,' 
1861 ;  and  the  article  on  Chateaubriand  in  Sir  A,  Alison's  Essays. 


354  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

considerable  measure  the  cause  why  he  represented  the  history 
of  England  to  so  exaggerated  an  extent  as  the  history  of 
a  conflict  between  Saxons  and  Normans,  and  that  of  France 
as  the  history  of  a  conflict  between  Gauls  and  Franks.  M. 
Amedde  Thierry,  by  his  '  Histoire  des  Gaulois,'  '  Histoire  de 
la  Gaule  sous  1' administration  romaine,'  '  Re"cits  de  l'histoire 
romaine  au  iv°  et  v°  si&cles,'  '  Histoire  de  Saint-Jerome,'  &c, 
has  rendered  scarcely  less  valuable  services  to  historical  study 
than  his  illustrious  brother. 

M.  de  Barante  (1782-1866)  published  in  1824  his  'Histoire 
des  Dues  de  Burgogne  de  la  maison  de  Valois.'  It  is  purely 
narrative,  and  composed  in  the  style,  and  largely  even  in  the 
words,  of  the  primary  authorities,  Froissart  and  other  chron- 
iclers of  the  fourteenth  and  fifteenth  centuries.  It  seemed  to 
him  that  the  history  of  the  period  with  which  he  had  under- 
taken to  deal  could  not  be  otherwise  reproduced  with  so  much 
exactness  and  circumstantiality,  so  much  natural  life  and  local 
colour.  He  did  not  deem  it  expedient  to  pronounce  on  the 
moral  character  of  the  events  which  he  describes ;  but  this  was 
not  owing  to  moral  indifference  in  himself,  but  because  he 
believed  that  when  events  are  properly  described  readers  may 
with  advantage  be  left  to  form  their  own  estimate  of  them. 
He  did  not  deny  that  other  methods  of  dealing  with  history 
than  his  own  were  legitimate,  so  long  as  they  involved  no 
perversion  of  facts  in  support  of  preconceived  opinions  and 
party  interests ;  he  only  held  that  the  method  which  he  him- 
self employed  ought  to  precede  others,  inasmuch  as  faithful 
narrative  is  what  is  fundamental  in  historiography.  He  fully 
recognised  the  necessity  of  a  strict  preliminary  criticism  of  the 
sources.  The  preface  to  his  work  expounds  the  theory  on 
which  he  proceeded,  and  deserves  careful  perusal.  Some 
of  his  critics  obviously  did  not  take  the  trouble  to  read  it.  In 
addition  to  his  chief  work,  he  wrote  a  widely  known  book  on 
the  French  literature  of  the  eighteenth  century,  histories  of 
the  National  Convention  and  of  the  Directory,  and  many 
Studes  of  an  historical  and  biographical  kind. 

A  new  era  in  the  philosophical  study  of  history  was  initiated 
by  Guizot,  of  whom  we  shall  have  to  treat  in  a  subsequent 
chapter. 


iUGNET  355 

M.  Mignet  (1796-1884)  held  for  sixty  years  the  first  place 
among  the  political  historians  of  his  country.  He  is  the  Ranke 
of  France,  and  his  works  display  the  same  admirable  qualities 
which  distinguish  those  of  the  great  German  historian.  They 
are  based  on  the  closest  study  of  sources  of  which  many  were 
previously  unknown  or  unused,  and  characterised  by  scrupu- 
lous accuracy  of  statement,  keen  and  comprehensive  disclosure 
of  the  causes  which  determine  the  course  of  events,  felicitous 
and  prudent  generalisation,  perfect  impartiality,  masterly  ar- 
rangement, and  a  style  which,  although  sparingly  coloured, 
unheated  by  passion,  and  seldom  irradiated  by  the  play  of 
imagination,  is  singularly  translucent,  harmonious,  and  grace- 
ful. Most  of  these  features  are  conspicuous  even  in  the  work 
of  his  youth,  the  'Histoire  de  la  Revolution  franchise,'  1824; 
they  are  still  more  so  in  those  works  which  relate  to  the  six- 
teenth century,  the  chief  field  of  his  researches,  —  'Antonio 
Perez  et  Philippe  II.,'  'Histoire  de  Marie  Stuart,'  '  Rivalite'  de 
Franc,ois  I"  et  de  Charles-Quint,'  '  Charles-Quint,  son  abdica- 
tion,' &c.  The  '  Memoire  sur  la  conversion  de  la  Germanie,' 
the  '  Mdmoire  sur  la  formation  territoriale  de  notre  pays,'  and 
the  '  Memoire  sur  l'e'tablissement  de  la  r^forme  religieuse  et 
la  constitution  du  Calvinisme  a  Geneve,'  are  fine  specimens 
of  philosophical  history.  Chateaubriand  accused  M.  Mignet,  as 
well  as  his  friend  M.  Thiers,  of  teaching  historical  fatalism. 
And  the  charge  has  been  repeated  by  other  critics.  A  sem- 
blance of  support  can  be  found  for  it  in  some  insufficiently 
guarded  expressions  of  '  The  History  of  the  French  Revolu- 
tion.' But  although  M.  Mignet  believed  in  the  action  of 
general  causes  and  the  po^er  of  general  ideas  and  passions 
in  history,  in  the  existence  of  laws  of  history,  and  in  the 
guidance  and  sovereignty  of  Providence,  and  may  have  at 
times  expressed  his  belief  in  them  even  too  absolutely,  no  one 
who  has  made  himself  acquainted  with  his  system  of  thought 
as  a  whole  can  doubt  that  he  also  held  the  free  agency  and 
moral  responsibility  of  individuals  as  unquestionable  truths. 
He  has,  in  fact,  repeatedly  insisted  that  it  is  an  historian's 
prime  and  imperative  duty,  while  exhibiting  order  and  causa- 
tion and  law  in  history,  not  to  leave  the  impression  that  they 
are  exclusive   of  contingency,  liberty,  and  merit  or  demerit. 


356  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOEY   IN   TRANCE 

It  is  sufficient  to  refer  to  the  'Eloge '  on  Hallam  as  of  itself 
conclusive  on  this  point.1 

Shortly  before  M.  Mignet's  '  Histoire  de  la  Revolution 
francaise '  appeared,  M.  Thiers  published  the  first  volume  of 
a  far  more  extensive  work  on  the  same  event.  M.  Thiers 
and  M.  Mignet  were  united  in  the  closest  friendship  and  were 
ardent  believers  in  the  same  political  principles.  Accord- 
ingly, their  Histories  gave  substantially  the  same  estimate 
of  the  Revolution.  But  otherwise  they  differed  greatly. 
M.  Mignet's  History  is  an  epitome  or  summary;  that  of 
M.  Thiers  is  a  detailed  narrative  and  exposition.  The  former 
is  written  in  a  style  remarkable  for  literary  finish ;  in  the 
latter  M.  Thiers  wrote  as  he  would  have  spoken  —  with 
marvellous  ease,  lucidity,  animation,  and  fulness  of  knowl- 
edge, but  also  with  the  faults  inseparable  from  extempori- 
sation, a  certain  looseness  of  arrangement,  diffuseness  of 
statement,  and  want  of  minute  accuracy.  M.  Thiers'  choice 
of  his  subject  was  obviously  determined  both  by  patriotic 
and  party  feeling.  He  wished  to  do  justice  to  a  great  event 
in  his  country's  history  and  as  much  harm  as  he  could  to  his 
political  opponents,  the  admirers  and  upholders  of  absolute 
authority  and  despotic  government.  He  succeeded,  perhaps, 
even  better  in  the  latter  aim  than  in  the  former.  The  work 
was  a  terrible  blow  to  the  royalist  reactionaries ;  its  immense 
popularity  was  an  overwhelming  revelation  of  the  hopeless- 
ness of  their  policy.  As  to  the  Revolution  itself,  he  did  it, 
in  my  opinion,  considerably  more  than  justice,  and  excused 
much  which  should  have  been  condemned.  At  the  same 
time  I  regard  it  as  substantially  just,  and  a  great  advance 
towards  complete  justice.  I  can  by  no  means  subscribe  to 
the  following  judgment  passed  upon  the  work  by  Mr.  Carlyle, 
writing  in  1837 :  "  Thiers'  History,  in  ten  volumes  foolscap 
octavo,  contains,  if  we  remember  rightly,  one  reference  ;  and 
that  to  a  book,  not  to  the  page  or  chapter  of  a  book.  It  has, 
for  these  last  seven  or  eight  years,  a  wide  or  even  high  repu- 
tation ;  which  latter  it  is  as  far  as  possible  from  meriting.  A 
superficial  air  of  order,  of  clearness,  calm  candour,  is  spread 

1  See  M.  Jules  Simon's  'Notice  sur  Mignet,'  and  M.  Edouard  Petit's  'Francois 
Mignet,'  1889. 


THIERS  357 

over  the  work ;  but  inwardly,  it  is  waste,  inorganic ;  no 
human  head  that  honestly  tries  can  conceive  the  French  Rev- 
olution so.  A  critic  of  our  acquaintance  undertook,  by  way 
of  bet,  to  find  four  errors  per  hour  in  Thiers  ;  he  won  amply 
on  the  first  trial  or  two.  And  yet  readers  (we  must  add), 
taking  all  this  along  with  them,  may  peruse  Thiers  with 
comfort  in  certain  circumstances,  nay  even  with  profit;  for 
he  is  a  brisk  man  of  his  sort;  and  does  tell  you  much,  if 
you  knew  nothing."  Mr.  Carlyle  did  not  recollect  rightly. 
M.  Thiers  may  have  given  too  few  references ;  he  tells  us 
that  he  gave  them  only  on  points  likely  to  be  disputed ;  but 
there  are  at  least  a  hundred,  and  most  of  them  are  sufficiently 
definite.  It  has  to  be  remembered  likewise  that  the  books  to 
which  he  could  refer  were  few;  that  his  sources  were  the 
'  Moniteur,'  some  Memoirs  nearly  all  unedited,  and  the  tes- 
timony of  ocular  witnesses;  and  that  it  was  his  work  and 
Mignet's  which  gave  rise  to  that  extraordinary  outpouting  of 
publications  on  the  French  Revolution  which  has  since  pro- 
ceeded without  interruption.  So  far  from  its  being  the  case 
that  "no  human  head  that  honestly  tries  can  conceive  the 
French  Revolution"  as  M.  Thiers  represented  it,  all  who 
have  come  after  him  (Mr.  Carlyle  included)  have  conceived 
the  great  bulk  and  main  course  of  the  events  composing  it 
so  ;  while  as  regards  interpretations  of  it,  M.  Thiers'  is,  after 
due  discount  for  exaggeration,  the  one  which  is  still  most 
widely  accepted,  whereas  all  Mr.  Carlyle's  genius  has  been 
unable  to  make  the  view  that  it  was  simply  a  hideous,  fan- 
tastic, and  meaningless  imbroglio,  essentially  sheer  chaos  and 
bankruptcy,  credible  to  any  thoughtful  human  being.  M. 
Thiers'  strong  point  was  not  accuracy  in  details,  and  his  His- 
tory was  disfigured  by  a  number  of  errors  due  to  haste  or 
carelessness ;  but  the  most  scrupulous  and  laborious  careful- 
ness would  not  have  saved  him  from  falling  into  many  errors 
which  would  be  obvious  to  critics  who  had  consulted  sources 
of  information  inaccessible  to  him.  Mr.  Carlyle  had  an 
immense  capacity  of  taking  pains ;  yet  after  M.  Louis  Blanc 
had  utilised  those  collections  of  pamphlets  and  documents 
in  the  British  Museum  at  which  Mr.  Carlyle,  standing  on  a 
ladder,  merely  looked,   a  reviewer  even   of  Mr.   Carlyle's 


358  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

'  French  Revolution '  could  have  no  difficulty  in  finding  in  it 
many  times  four  errors.  The  '  History  of  the  French  Revo- 
lution '  by  Thiers  will  not  only  tell  much  to  those  who  know 
nothing,  but  may  be  read  with  profit  even  by  those  who  have 
studied  the  Histories  of  Carlyle  and  Michelet,  Blanc  and 
Taine.  His  '  Histoire  du  Consulat  et  de  l'Empire  '  is  a  still 
abler  work.  It  is,  perhaps,  the  most  interesting  history  ever 
written  on  the  same  scale.  No  reader  of  it  felt  its  twenty 
volumes  to  be  too  many.  For  the  author  had  in  perfection 
the  art  of  presenting  a  vast  array  of  facts  in  their  natural 
order;  of  describing  a  multitude  of  incidents  in  a  most 
graphic  and  animated  manner,  while  never  allowing  the  unity 
of  the  whole  to  which  they  belonged  or  the  co-ordination  of 
its  facts  to  drop  out  of  sight.  He  had  above  all  men  the 
precise  kind  of  talent  required  adequately  to  exhibit  and  ex- 
plain the  military  achievements,  the  financial  measures,  and 
the  policy  of  Napoleon ;  and  he  did  full  justice  to  his  talent, 
being  only  too  much  in  love  with  his  theme.  His  '  History 
of  the  Consulate  and  the  Empire '  had  the  same  fault,  how- 
ever, as  his  'History  of  the  Revolution.'  The  fault  arose 
from  excess  of  a  virtue,  —  from  the  intensity  of  patriotism 
which  was  so  marked  a  characteristic  of  M.  Thiers.  He  was 
a  man  who  would  have  sacrificed  his  own  life  or  any  number 
of  lives,  broken  any  law,  or  crushed  any  nation,  if  he  could 
thereby  have  secured  the  safety  or  glory  of  France.  Moved 
by  his  predominant  passion  he  has  too  often  made  his  histo- 
ries apologies  for,  or  eulogies  of,  the  Revolution  and  Napoleon 
when  both  deserved  condemnation.  What  was  the  result? 
His  '  History  of  the  Revolution '  gave  an  immense  impulse 
to  a  delirious  apotheosis  of  the  Revolution  which  has  done 
incalculable  harm  to  France ;  his  '  History  of  the  Consulate 
and  the  Empire '  to  a  not  less  insane  and  pernicious  Caesar- 
ism  ;  and  his  own  public  life  was  largely  a  struggle  with  the 
two  monsters  of  which  he  had  been,  in  part  at  least,  the 
Frankenstein.  History  serves  patriotism  best  when  .  she 
maintains  a  severe  impartiality  and  critical  independence  of 
judgment,  and  tells  the  truth,  the  whole  truth,  and  nothing 
but  the  truth,  however  unpleasant  to  patriotism  that  maybe.1 

1  See  M.  Jules  Simon's  '  Notice  sur  Thiers,'  and  M.  Paul  de  Remusat's  ' Thiers.' 


HISTORICAL   WORK  IN  FRANCE  359 

Of  M.  Michelet's  work  as  an  historian  I  shall  have  to  treat 
at  a  later  stage. 

Most  of  the  initiators  of  the  French  historiography  of  the 
nineteenth  century  were  granted  long  lives  and  the  full  pos- 
session of  their  powers  of  mental  work  to  the  last.  Some  of 
them  have  only  recently  passed  away,  after  having  presided 
over  almost  its  whole  development.  I  shall  make  no  attempt 
to  trace  that  development,  or  to  give  even  the  most  general 
survey  of  the  historical  work  done  in  France  since  Thierry 
and  Guizot,  Thiers  and  Mignet,  commenced  their  labours. 
The  study  of  history  has  during  no  other  period  been  cultivated 
with  equal  enthusiasm  and  success.  And  among  the  nations 
which  have  most  fully  displayed  their  genius  in  this  form  of 
intellectual  activity  France  has  been  among  the  most  conspic- 
uous, and  probably  surpassed  only  by  Germany.  There  are 
few  fields  of  history  in  which  Frenchmen  have  not  made  fruit- 
ful investigations ;  few  epochs  or  great  events  of  history  on 
which  they  have  not  shed  fresh  light.  They  have  actively 
contributed  to  those  sciences  of  recent  growth  by  which  the 
darkness  shrouding  prehistoric  time  has  been  at  last  in  part 
dispelled;  and  to  those  sciences  which  have  been  from  of  old 
recognised  as  auxiliaries  to  historiography.  Knowledge  of  the 
history  of  China  has  been  promoted  by  such  scholars  as  Abel 
Rdniusat,  Reinaud,  Biot,  Julien,  Pauthier,  and  Pavie  ;  of  India 
by  Burnouf,  Langlois,  De  Tassy,  Foucaux,  Saint-Hilaire,  Feer, 
and  Regnaud ;  of  Persia  by  De  Sacy,  Defre"mery,  Mohl,  and 
Gobineau ;  of  Assyria  and  Babylonia  by  Oppert,  Fresnel,  Le- 
normant,  and  Me"nant;  of  Egypt  by  Champollion-Figeac, 
Letronne,  De  Rouge",  Mariette,  Chabas,  Naville,  and  Maspero ; 
and  of  the  Semitic  peoples  by  Munk,  Franek,  De  Perceval,  De 
Saulcy,  De  Slane,  Quatremere,  Sedillot,  Fournel,  Renan,  Reuss, 
Derembourg,  D'Eichtal,  and  Vernes.  As  regards  the  history 
of  the  classical  world,  the  names  of  Ampere,  Boissier,  Bouchl- 
Leclercq,  Brunet  de  Presle,  Coulanges,  Desvergier,  Duruy, 
Egger,  Girard,  Guigniaut,  Havet,  Le  Clerc,  Maury,  Perrot, 
Renier,  Waddington,  and  Wallon,  are  but  a  few  out  of  the 
many  names  which  recall  eminent  services  rendered  in  this 
department.  The  languages,  literatures,  institutions,  sciences, 
arts,  philosophies,  and  religions  of  classical  antiquity  have  all 


360  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN  FRANCE 

been  separately  treated  of  historically  in  numerous  learned 
Avritings.  It  is,  however,  the  history  of  France  itself  which 
has  been  most  cultivated.  Three  general  histories  of  France 
have  succeeded  Sismondi's,  —  those  of  Michelet,  Martin,  and 
Dareste.  Michelet's  is  a  work  of  great  but  unequal  genius, 
of  singular  merits  and  serious  faults ;  Martin's  is  not  a  work 
of  genius,  but  of  talent  of  a  high  order,  of  an  intelligence 
always  clear,  vigorous,  and  alert,  and  of  a  conscientiousness 
without  flaw ;  and  Dareste's,  also,  is  a  work  of  much  research 
and  ability.  There  is  likewise  a  general  '  History  of  French 
Civilisation '  by  M.  Alfred  Rambaud,  in  the  three  unpreten- 
tious volumes  of  which  is  to  be  found  more  of  vitally  impor- 
tant information  as  to  the  growth  of  France  than  in  any  twenty 
other  volumes  which  I  could  name.  The  study  of  the  medie- 
val period  of  French  history  in  all  its  aspects  is,  however,  that 
in  which  the  energies  of  Frenchmen  of  learning  have  been  most 
zealously  devoted  since  Guizot  and  Thierry  set  the  example, 
and  the  JScole  des  Chartes,  the  Comite  des  travaux  Mstoriques, 
and  the  SooiStS  de  Vhistoire  de  France,  were  founded.  Among 
the  names  which  most  readily  occur  to  me  in  this  connection 
are  those  of  Beugnot,  Boutaric,  Cheruel,  Coulanges,  Dareste, 
Delisle,  Haure"au,  Jubainville,  Levasseur,  Littre-,  Luce,  Lu- 
chaire,  Mas-Latrie,  Montalembert,  Gaston  and  Paulin  Paris, 
Perrens,  Picot,  Poinsignon,  Raynouard,  Ray,  and  Raoul 
Rosieres.  In  addition  to  Guizot,  Michelet,  Mignet,  and  Thiers, 
I  shall  mention  as  having  distinguished  themselves  by  works 
on  the  modern  history  of  France  only  the  Dukes  D'Aumale 
and  De  Broglie,  Louis  Blanc,  Aime"  Che"rest,  Claretie,  Pierre 
Clement,  Taxile  Delord,  Feillet,  Duvergier,  De  Hauranne, 
Mortimer-Terneaux,  Nettement,  Quinet,  Rousset,  Sainte- 
Beuve,  Sorel,  Taine,  and  Tocqueville.  We  owe  to  MM. 
Himly,  Geffroy,  Perrens,  Rambaud,  Rosseuw  Saint-Hilaire, 
and  Zeller  well  reputed  works  on  the  history  of  the  formation 
of  the  States  of  Central  Europe,  and  on  the  histories  of  the 
Scandinavian  States,  Florence,  Russia,  Spain,  and  Germany 
and  Italy. 

There  has  not  only  been  the  most  manifold  activity  in 
French  historiography  during  the  period  under  consideration, 
but  also   in   essential   respects  manifest  improvement.     To 


HISTORIANS   OF   THE   VARIOUS   SCHOOLS  361 

observe  it,  however,  we  must  not  look  from  a  merely  artistic 
point  of  view.  So  regarded,  Thierry's  '  Norman  Conquest '  and 
the  earlier  volumes  of  Michelet's  History  have  not  only  not 
been  surpassed,  but  have  not  been  equalled.  The  excellencies 
of  form  and  style  displayed  by  Mignet  and  Thiers  have  not 
reappeared  in  the  same  degree  in  any  of  their  disciples.  Yet 
there  has  been  progress,  and  even  great  progress.  There  has 
been  -the  progress  involved  in  a  continuous  subdivision  of 
labour  and  an  immense  multiplication  of  researches.  There 
has  been  a  decided  progress  in  method.  The  obligations  of 
the  historian  not  to  depend  on  secondary  sources  of  informa- 
tion, but  to  have  recourse  to  the  primary  sources,  and  as  far  as 
possible  to  master  and  exhaust  them  all,  have  been  steadily 
becoming  more  fully  recognised  ;  and  the  necessity  for  strin- 
gency in  criticism  and  exactitude  in  interpretation  has  been 
growingly  felt.  And  there  has  been  also  progress  in  truthful- 
ness and  impartiality  of  judgment.  One  reason  why  the  his- 
torians of  to-day  are  comparatively  averse  to  generalisation,  to 
high  colouring,  to  the  exercise  of  imagination,  and  to  eloquent 
writing,  is  that  they  are  more  conscious  than  their  predecessors 
of  the  extent  to  which  these  things  have  falsified  history. 
The  younger  race  of  historians  are  more  emancipated  than 
those  who  preceded  them  from  the  prejudices  of  party,  of 
country,  and  of  creed;  and  more  anxious  to  keep  all  their 
feelings  and  convictions  under  such  control  as  will  prevent 
them  vitiating  their  investigations.  They  have  come  to  learn 
that  the  supreme  law  of  history  is  not  to  be  attractive  and 
beautiful,  or  helpful  to  patriotism,  morality,  and  religion,  but 
to  be  wholly  and  exactly  true  ;  and  that,  therefore,  the  his- 
torian is  primarily  bound  to  be  critical  and  scientific,  and  only 
secondarily  bound  to  be  artistic  and  edifying. 

The  various  modes  or  systems  of  thought  which  have  in 
France  during  the  period  we  are  considering  given  rise  to 
theories  or  philosophies  of  history  have  likewise  produced 
histories.  The  histories  exemplify  in  their  own  way  the  prin- 
ciples maintained  in  the  theories.  And  therefore  it  seems 
desirable  to  indicate  the  chief  works  of  history  thus  connected 
with  the  theories  which  are  to  be  expounded  in  the  chapters 
that  follow. 


362  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN  PKANCE 

The  theocratist  and  ultramontanist  party  has  had  among  its 
adherents  in  France  no  historians  of  great  distinction.  Rohr- 
bacher,  author  of  an  ecclesiastical  history  in  twenty  volumes 
which  has  taken  the  place  of  the  much  more  deserving  work 
of  Fleury,  is,  perhaps,  the  most  eminent ;  but  he  is  deplorably 
wanting  in  candour  and  justice.  Liberal  Catholicism,  on  the 
other  hand,  has  had  among  its  representatives  such  historians 
as  Montalembert,  Ozanam,  Riancey,  and  De  Broglie.    • 

Louis  Blanc  is  by  far  the  greatest  historian  which  French 
Socialism  can  claim.  The  'Parliamentary  History  of  the 
Revolution '  drawn  up  by  MM.  Roux  and  Buchez  is  valuable 
on  account  of  the  documents  which  it  contains,  but  what  M. 
Buchez  contributed  to  it  of  his  own  is  very  incoherent  and 
extravagant  stuff.  M.  Benoit  Malon,  formerly  a  member  of 
the  International  and  the  Parisian  Commune,  has  written  a 
'  History  of  Socialism '  remarkably  full  of  information,  and 
laudably  fair,  except  to  those  who  are  wholly  outside  the 
household  of  the  socialistic  faith. 

A  large  number  of  French  historians  have  acknowledged 
Guizot,  the  chief  of  the  doctrinaire  school,  as  their  master. 
Once  the  acknowledgment  meant  that  those  who  made  it 
accepted  the  principles  of  the  historico-political  creed  which 
Guizot  maintained ;  latterly  it  has  seldom  meant  more  than 
that  those  making  it  regard  themselves  as  following  up  the 
path  of  historical  investigation  into  which  he  led  so  many. 
Historians  like  Count  de  Carne",  De  Tocqueville,  and  H. 
Martin  may  be  reckoned  among  his  disciples. 

The  Eclectic  school  had  for  basis  a  philosophical  doctrine, 
and  its  members  have  cultivated  the  history  of  philosophy 
with  more  zeal  and  success  than  those  of  any  philosophical 
school  of  this  century  except  the  Hegelian.  Cousin,  Jouffroy, 
De  Remusat,  Saisset,  Damiron,  Matter,  Wilm,  Saint-Hilaire, 
Franck,  Nourisson,  Janet,  Bouillier,  Caro,  Simon,  Vacherot, 
and  many  of  their  associates  and  disciples,  have  greatly  distin- 
guished themselves  as  historians  of  philosophy.  If  eclecticism 
has  exerted  any  perverting  influence  on  historical  research,  it 
has  been  very  slight  compared  with  that  of  Hegelianism. 

Positivism  has  had  its  best  representative  among  French 
historians  in  Littre" ;  and  Naturalism  in  Taine. 


HISTOBICAL   METHODOLOGY  —  DATJNOTJ  363 

Granier  de  Cassagnac  and  Mortimer-Terneaux  may  be 
named  as  historians  of  a  conservative  type,  desirous  of  sup- 
porting the  cause  of  authority.  Napoleon  III.  wrote  his 
'Histoire  de  Jules  Ce"sar'  in  order  to  recommend  Csesarism. 
Lamartine,  Michelet,  Quinet,  Barni,  Lanfrey,  and  others 
have  sought  to  spread  by  their  historical  writings  the  prin- 
ciples of  Liberalism. 

At  present  most  of  the  younger  historians  are  content  to 
be  simply  historians.  While  not  denying  the  legitimacy  of 
historical  generalisation,  they  carefully  refrain  from  treating 
history  as  subservient  to  the  establishment  of  extra-historical 
creeds  or  theories  of  any  kind.  It  is  historians  of  this  stamp 
who  are  the  contributors  to  such  periodicals  as  the  '  Biblio- 
theque  de  l'Ecole  des  Chartes  '  and  the  '  Revue  Historique.' 1 

It  is  necessary  to  notice  in  this  chapter  only  two  works 
which  treat  of  history.  The  first  is  the  '  Cours  d'fitudes 
Historiques '  of  Daunou,  who  has  been  already  under  our  con- 
sideration. This  '  Cours '  comprises  twenty  volumes  published 
between  1842  and  1849,  and  is  composed  of  the  lectures  which 
the  author  had  delivered  as  Professor  of  History  at  the  College 
of  France.  Some  of  the  earlier  volumes  alone  are  occupied 
with  the  methodology  of  history.  The  first  volume  deals 
directly  with  it.  In  the  introduction  it  is  maintained  that 
those  who  cultivate  the  mental  and  historical  sciences  should 
aim  at  being  as  scrupulously  exact  in  observation,  as  severely 
analytical  in  investigation,  and  as  impartial  in  judgment,  as 
the  students  of  physical  science ;  and  that  the  progress  of 
mental  and  historical  science  warrants  us  to  hope  that  this 
end  may  be  at  least  approximately  attained.  The  bulk  of  the 
volume  (Book  I.)  is  a  comprehensive  and  systematic  treatise 
on  historical  criticism.  It  discusses  the  following  subjects,  — 
the  certitude  or  probability  attainable  in  history  (chap,  i.) ; 
the  sources  of  history  (chap.  ii») ;  the  foundation  and  prop- 
agation of  traditions  (chap,  iii.) ;  the  traditional  histories  of 
the  most  celebrated  peoples  (chap,  iv.)  ;  the  rules  of  criticism 
applicable  to  the  traditional  past  of  history  (chap,  v.) ;  his- 

1  On  French  historiography  in  the  nineteenth  century,  see  '  Rapports  sur  les 
Etudes  Historiques,'  par  MM.  Geffroy,  Zeller,  et  Thienot:  1867. 


364  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

torical  monuments  (chap,  vi.)  ;  medals  and  inscriptions  (chap, 
vii.) ;  charters  or  pieces  of  archives  (chap,  viii.)  ;  records 
made  at  the  moment  when  the  facts  took  place  or  a  few  days 
after  (chap,  ix.)  ;  records  written  in  the  course  of  the  age 
when  the  events  occurred  or  shortly  afterwards  (chap,  x.) ; 
rules  of  criticism  applicable  to  contemporary  or  nearly  con- 
temporary records  (chap,  xi.) ;  and  historical  collections, 
abridgments,  and  extracts  (chaps,  xii.-xv.).  It  concludes  with 
a  summary  of  the  rules  of  historical  criticism,  a  statement 
of  the  importance  of  grammatical  criticism  to  the  histo- 
rian, and  observations  on  the  conditions  which  must  be  ful- 
filled in  order  that  history  may  become  a  science.  Almost  all 
the  matters  taken  up  are  carefully  and  judiciously,  learnedly 
and  independently,  dealt  with.  The  second  book  (torn.  ii. 
pp.  1-290)  is  on  the  uses  of  history.  Although  less  satis- 
factory than  the  first,  the  disquisitions  which  it  contains 
regarding  the  bearings  of  historical  study  on  moral  and  social 
science,  on  the  knowledge  of  human  nature  and  of  its  original 
and  acquired  tendencies,  on  perception  of  the  conditions  of 
domestic,  commercial,  and  civil  life,  and  on  political  theory 
and  practice,  as  well  as  of  the  bearings  of  these  things  on  it, 
are  generally  sound  and  luminous.  The  second  volume  from 
p.  291  to  its  close  treats  of  the  history  of  geography  and  of 
geography  as  auxiliary  to  history.  Volumes  iii.-vi.  form  an 
extremely  elaborate  and  erudite  work  on  chronology.  The 
bond  of  connection  between  these  studies  on  geography  and 
on  chronology  is  that  both  are  regarded  as  concerned  with  the 
classification  of  historical  facts  or  data  —  the  former,  namely, 
with  their  distribution  in  space,  and  the  latter  with  their 
arrangement  in  time.  Volume  vii.  is  a  treatise  on  the  expo- 
sition of  historical  facts,  or,  in  other  words,  on  the  art  of 
writing  history.  It  discusses  almost  all  the  relevant  points 
and  questions,  if  not  with  originality  or  profundity,  certainly 
with  thoughtfulness  and  gopd  sense.  The  subsequent  vol- 
umes contain  elaborate  disquisitions  on  the  characteristics  of 
eminent  historians,  and  on  the  contents,  merits,  and  defects 
of  their  works.  History  had  not  been  treated  of  before,  at 
least  in  France,  in  nearly  so  complete,  thorough,  and  practical 
a  manner  as  in  the  lectures  of  Daunou. 


CEOS-MAYKBVILLE  365 

The  second  work  referred  to  is  'La  Me'thodologie  des 
Sciences  Morales  et  Politiques  applique"e  a  la  Science  de 
l'Histoire '  of  M.  Cros-Mayreville,  published  in  1848.  While 
Daunou  regarded  history  and  all  questions  relating  to  it  from 
the  point  of  view  of  an  ideologist  of  the  eighteenth  century, 
Cros-Mayreville  looks  at  them  in  the  light  of  an  age  still 
present  with  us.  But  he  lacks  the  intellectual  thoroughness 
and  the  vast  special  knowledge  of  his  predecessor.  Hence 
his  work  is  comparatively  slight  and  unsatisfactory.  He 
treats  first  of  the  nature  of  historical  facts,  of  their  proofs, 
and  of  their  criticism  ;  next,  of  the  reproduction  of  the  facts, 
especially  in  the  form  of  general  history ;  then,  of  the  causa- 
tion, moral  succession,  and  moral  appreciation  of  the  facts ; 
further,  of  the  influence  of  the  teaching  of  general  history 
on  the  education  of  peoples,  and  of  the  organisation  of  this 
teaching ;  and,  finally,  of  the  desiderata  and  ultimate  con- 
clusions of  the  science  of  history.  On  all  these  points  he 
makes  good  and  useful  observations ;  yet  his  treatment  of 
none  of  them  is  otherwise  than  very  inadequate. 

The  views  on  history  of  various  writers  on  historical  science 
will  come  before  us  in  several  of  the  chapters  which  follow. 


CHAPTER   VI 


THE   TJLTRAMONTANTST   AND   LIBERAL   CATHOLIC    SCHOOLS 


The  historical  doctrine  of  what  is  variously  known  as  the 
traditionalist,  or  ultramontane,  or  theocratic  school  was  advo- 
cated in  defiance  of  Napoleon  during  the  whole  period  of  his 
reign,  and  appeared  to  triumph  in  his  fall.  Its  advocates  were 
moved  by  a  powerful  polemical  motive,  and  had  immediately 
in  view  a  partisan  purpose ;  they  were  as  unlike  as  could  be 
to  calm  labourers  in  the  field  of  science.  Hence  no  system- 
atic exposition  of  their  distinctive  historical  theory  is  to  be 
found  in  any  of  their  writings ;  nor  has  any  member  of  the 
French  division  of  the  theocratic  school  given  us  an  elabo- 
rated philosophy  of  history,  or,  indeed,  any  philosophy  of  his- 
tory simply  for  its  own  sake.  Their  views  of  the  course  and 
destination  of  human  history  must  be  disengaged,  disentan- 
gled, from  an  extensive  literature  composed  of  works  belong- 
ing chiefly  to  the  departments  of  theological  and  political 
polemics  or  apologetics.1 

I  shall  try  to  indicate  what  these  views  were  as  set  forth  in 
the  writings  of  the  three  best  representatives  of  the  party,  — 
De  Maistre,  De  Bonald,  and  De  Lamennais  during  the  earlier 
part  of  his  career.2 

1  Damiron  and  Ferraz  have  treated  of  the  traditionalist  and  ultramontanist 
school  in  the  works  already  mentioned,  and  Nettement  in  his  '  Histoire  de  la 
Restauration.'  I  may  refer  also  to  Principal  Fairbairn's  article  on  "  Catholicism 
and  Religious  Thought,"  in  '  Cont.  Rev.'  for  May  1885. 

2  A  learned  Danish  baron,  M.  d'Eckstein,  advocated  substantially  the  same 
views  as  De  Bouald,  De  Maistre,  and*  De  Lamennais,  in  the  pages  of  '  Le  Catho- 
lique,'  a  periodical  edited  and  for  the  most  part  written  by  himself.  He  was, 
however,  much  more  temperate  in  his  advocacy  of  them;  and,  indeed,  expressly 
says  of  the  three  chiefs  of  the  theocratic  party  that  "  their  fear  of  the  Revolution 
has  communicated  to  their  polemic  a  tincture  of  reaction  which  we  believe  to  be 
neither  necessary  nor  even  advantageous  to  the  maintenance  of  sound  doctrines" 
(torn.  i.  pp.  8, 9).     '  Le  Catholique '  began  to  appear  in  1826,  and  extended  to  twenty 

366 


MAISTRE  —  BONALD  —  LAMENNAIS  367 

Count  Joseph  de  Maistre  (1754-1821),  a  Savoyard  but  of 
French  descent,  was  a  man  of  strong  convictions  and  fiery 
zeal;  dogmatic,  intolerant,  and  paradoxical  in  his  judgments; 
a  sincere  hater  of  public  liberty,  and  a  decided  denier  of  his- 
torical progress ;  a  writer  of  great  directness  and  force,  with, 
as  has  been  said,  "  something  of  the  eloquence  of  Rousseau, 
and  something  of  the  wit  of  Voltaire ;  "  a  most  formidable 
polemic,  audacious  and  ingenious,  trenchant  and  sarcastic; 
and  in  his  private  and  domestic  character,  as  revealed  by  his 
letters,  tender  and  amiable  to  an  extent  which  the  reader  of 
his  books  alone  could  never  expect.  Viscount  Louis  de 
Bonald  (1754-1840)  began  his  literary  career  about  the  same 
time  as  De  Maistre,  and  maintained  substantially  the  same 
views,  but  his  method  of  thought  and  style  of  writing  were 
altogether  different,  the  former  being  exclusively  and  rigidly 
ratio cinative,  and  the  latter  slow  and  heavy  in  movement, 
although  occasionally  not  without  animation  and  force.  The 
Abbe-  de  Lamennais  (1782-1854)  was  a  greater  and  more 
interesting  personality  than  either  De  Maistre  or  De  Bonald. 
He  was  a  man  who  could  not  rest  in  doubt  or  probability ; 
who  could  not  tolerate  hesitation  or  indifference ;  who  must 
have  certitude,  and  give  himself  wholly  to  the  cause  which 
he  espoused.  He  had  a  soul  of  flame  in  which  reason  and 
passion  were  combined  as  light  and  heat  in  fire.  He  was  mas- 
ter of  a  commanding  eloquence  which  made  him  seem  a  second 
Bossuet.  His  '  Essai  sur  l'lndiffe'rence  '  (1818)  had  a  much 
greater  practical  influence  than  all  the  ultramontanist  writ- 
ings which  had  previously  appeared  in  France  put  together. 
It  is  only  the  general  theory  of  history  contained  in  the  works 
of  these  authors  which  requires  to  be  here  exhibited.1 

volumes,  of  which  I  have  only  seen  the  first  twelve,  those  being,  I  understand,  all 
that  the  library  of  the  British  Museum  possesses.  The  most  interesting  of  the 
studies  which  they  contain  are  perhaps  that  on  B.  Constant's  '  De  la  Religion,' 
in  vols.  i.  and  ii.,  and  that  on  'Industrialism,'  i.e.,  Saint-Simonism,  in  vol.  v. 
D'Eckstein  was  exceptionally  conversant  with  German  learning  and  speculation, 
and  his  periodical  must  have  contributed  somewhat  to  spread  the  knowledge  of 
them  in  France.  Philarete  Ghasles,  in  an  amusing  page  of  his  '  Memoires '  (torn.  i. 
p.  269),  gives  personal  reminiscences  of  '  Le  Catholique  '  and  its  editor. 

1  The  following  are  the  works  from  which  my  exposition  of  the  theocratic  theory 
is  drawn :  M.  de  Bonald,  '  The'orie  du  Pouvoir  Politique  et  Religieuse  dans  la 
Socie'te  Civile,'  1796;  'Essai  Analytique  sur  les  Lois  Naturelles  de  l'Ordre 
Social,'  1800;  and  'La  Legislation  Primitive,'  2d  ed.,  1821;  M.  de  Maistre,  'Con- 


368  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Like  all  decided  adherents  of  the  theocratic  creed,  they  had 
a  passionate  aversion  to  the  distinctive  tenets  of  the  eighteenth 
century.  They  looked  on  that  century  as  an  epoch  of  shame, 
closing  in  an  event  the  most  horrible  the  world  had  seen. 
They  stood  too  near  the  Revolution,  and  had  suffered  too 
much  through  it,  to  be  able  to  judge  it  impartially.  The 
terror,  the  religious  and  moral  delirium,  the  confiscations, 
banishment,  and  bloodshed,  which  accompanied  it,  seemed  to 
them  of  its  very  essence,  and  they  believed  that  they  could 
not  condemn  it  sternly  enough,  nor  assail  its  principles  too 
strongly,  nor  oppose  its  influences  too  resolutely.  To  meet, 
conquer,  and  crush  the  spirit  of  the  Revolution,  was  the  aim 
which,  under  a  sincere  sense  of  duty,  they  set  before  them. 

In  proposing  to  themselves  to  counteract  the  Revolution, 
to  root  out  its  principles  and  undo  its  effects,  they  were  not 
blind  to  the  magnitude  of  their  task.  They  hated  the  Revo- 
lution, but  they  did  not  despise  it ;  they  recognised  that  it 
was  no  product  of  petty  causes ;  they  believed  it  to  be  the 
inevitable  result  of  a  radically  erroneous  conception  of  man's 
relation  to  God  and  to  his  fellow-men  which  had  been  grow- 
ing and  spreading  into  wrong  habits  of  thought  and  action 
from  the  time  of  the  Renaissance  downwards,  till  at  length 
head,  heart,  and  every  member  of  the  body  politic  were  dis- 
eased and  corrupt.     De  Maistre,  indeed,  contended  that  the 

siderations  sur  la  France,'  1796;  '  Du  Pape,'  1819;  '  De  l'Eglise  Gallicane,'  1821; 
'  Les  Soirees  de  Saint  Petersbourg,'  1821 ;  and  '  Correspond ance ' ;  and  M.  de 
Laraennais,  '  Essai  sur  l'lndiffe'rence  en  Matiere  de  la  Religion,'  1817-23;  '  De  la 
Religion  considered  dans  ses  rapports  avec  l'Ordre  Politique  et  Civil,'  1825-26; 
'  Des  Progres  de  la  Revolution  et  de  la  Guerre  contre  l'Eglise,'  1829;  and  '  CEuvres 
Inedites.'  A  collected  edition  of  De  Bonald's  works  has  been  several  times 
printed.  On  De  Maistre  see  the  essay  of  Prof.  v.  Sybel  in  his  '  Kleine  Schriften,' 
and  that  of  Mr.  Morley  in  his  '  Critical  Miscellanies  ' ;  also  Janet's  '  Philosophie 
de  la  Revolution  francaise,'  pp.  30-44.  In  these  pages  M.  Janet  has  well  indicated 
the  indebtedness  of  De  Maistre  to  Saint-Martin  as  regards  his  views  of  the  Revo- 
lution. On  Saint-Martin  the  reader  may  consult  M.  Caro,  '  La  Vie  et  la  Doctrine 
de  Saint-Martin,'  and  M.  Franck,  '  La  Philosophie  Mystique  au  xviii"  Siecle.'  On 
Laraennais,  besides  the  'Essai  Biographique '  of  M.  Blaize  and  the  studies  of 
Sainte-Beuve,  there  are  various  articles  worth  consulting  —  e.g.,  Jules  Simon's  in 
'  Revue  des  Deux  Mondes,'  1841,  L.  Binaud's  in  same  periodical  (Nos.  for  Aug.  15, 
1860,  and  Feb.  1, 1861),  E.  Renan's  in  '  Essais  de  Morale  et  Critique,'  Prof.  Huber's 
in  his  '  Kleine  Schriften,'  and  Prof.  Dowden's  in  '  Fortnightly  Review,'  Jan.  1, 
1869.  Cardinal  Newman's  article  on  Lamennais  in  his  '  Critical  and  Historical 
Miscellanies  '  is  of  no  value  so  far  as  its  subject  is  concerned,  but  may  be  of  some 
interest  as  the  work  of  Newman. 


THEOCRATIC   HISTORICAL   THEORY  369 

Revolution  was  not  a  natural  event,  but  "  an  event  unique  in 
history,"  "  a  satanic  event,"  "  a  providential  event,"  "  a  mir- 
acle strictly  so  called,"  "a  predestinated  revolution,"  "a  rev- 
olution which  impelled  men  rather  than  they  it."  But  he 
thereby  meant  that  it  was  only  intelligible  when  referred  di- 
rectly to  the  divine  purpose  revealed  in  it;  when  viewed  as  an 
awful  expiation  for  enormous  sin.  He  did  not  mean  that  it 
was  an  accidental  or  isolated  event,  for  which  there  had  been 
no  historical  preparation.  He  and  De  Bonald,  even  in  their 
earliest  works  —  the  two  books  published  in  1796 — gave 
clear  expression  to  the  conviction  that  the  roots  of  the  Revo- 
lution went  far  deeper  down  and  farther  back  than  was  gen- 
erally supposed.  They  set  themselves  to  resist  it  with  the 
full  consciousness  that  it  was  but  a  startling  outward  phase 
of  an  internal,  moral,  and  social  revolution  which  began  when 
the  modern  world  emerged  from  the  medieval  world,  and  was 
really  what  had  to  be  combated  and  overcome.  They  believed 
that  it  could  only  be  opposed  successfully  if  opposed  in  its 
principles,  and  they  admitted  that  in  undertaking  so  to  oppose 
it  they  proposed  to  effect  a  far  greater  revolution  than  it  had 
itself  been,  even  nothing  less  than  resettling  and  reorganising 
society  on  a  foundation  from  which  it  had  been  gliding  with 
ever-increasing  velocity  for  three  centuries.  They  thus  delib- 
erately took  up  a  position  of  antagonism  to  modern  philosophy 
and  to  modern  history.  "  For  three  hundred  years,"  says  De 
Maistre,  "  history  has  been  a  continuous  conspiracy  against 
the  truth." 

In  sensationalism,  the  dominant  philosophy  in  France 
during  the  eighteenth  century,  the  writers  under  considera- 
tion saw  one  of  the  most  powerful  causes  of  the  Revolution 
and  of  the  crimes  associated  with  it.  Against  this  philosophy, 
therefore,  they  waged  an  unwearied  polemic,  charging  it  with 
degrading  man  to  the  level  of  the  brutes,  and  with  leading 
inevitably  to  immorality,  anarchy,  misrule,  and  impiety.  As, 
however,  they  attacked  it  solely  in  the  interests  of  the  prac- 
tical life,  or,  in  other  words,  not  as  false  but  as  evil,  they  not 
only  contributed  nothing  to  its  philosophical  refutation,  but 
assumed  and  asserted  its  causal  connection  with  the  vices 
which  they  denounced,  even  where  proof  was  most  incumbent 


370  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOEY   IN  PRANCE 

upon  them.  The  refutation  of  materialism  in  De  Bonald's 
'Recherches  sur  les  Premiers  Objets  de  nos  Connaissances 
Morales,'  if  an  exception  to  this  statement,  is  the  only  one. 

The  writers  in  question  did  not  stop  with  opposition  to 
sensationalism.  They  went  on  to  attack  modern  philosophy 
in  its  principle  and  entire  development.  De  Maistre  wrote  a 
book  to  prove  Bacon  a  scientific  charlatan,  and  laid  it  down 
as  a  principle  that  "  contempt  for  Locke  is  the  beginning  of 
knowledge."  De  Bonald  argued  that  the  history  of  philos- 
ophy was  nothing  else  than  a  history  of  the  variations  of 
philosophical  schools,  which  left  no  other  impression  on  the 
reader  than  an  insurmountable  disgust  at  all  philosophical 
researches.  A  considerable  portion  of  the  second  volume  of 
the  '  Essai '  of  Lamennais,  and  the  whole  of  its  '  Defense,'  were 
devoted  to  show  that  all  philosophy  since  Descartes  was 
radically  vicious,  —  that  its  method  was  identical  with  that 
employed  by  religious  heretics,  and  that  it  ended  inevitably 
in  scepticism. 

The  explanation  of  this  direct  and  conscious  antagonism  to 
modern  philosophy  is  not  far  to  seek,  and  takes  us  into  the 
very  heart  of  the  theocratic  theory.  The  philosophers  of  the 
eighteenth  century  had  advocated  the  rights  of  reason  or 
rights  of  man  in  a  one-sided  and  exaggerated  way :  they  had 
given,  that  is  to  say,  an  undue  prominence  to  the  principle  of 
individualism ;  had  pushed  it  too  far ;  and  had  forgotten  the 
claims  of  the  principle  which  limits  it.  The  consequences 
had  been  terrible.  This  caused  in  the  way  of  reaction 
another  party  to  arise,  who  could  see  only  the  evil  which  the 
principle  of  individualism  had  caused  or  occasioned,  and  who 
pushed  the  complementary  principle  of  authority  to  a  farther 
but  contrary  extreme.  They  saw  that  to  make  any  man, 
however  wise,  and  still  more  to  make  every  man,  however 
foolish,  believe  that  any  private  judgment  or  private  crotchet 
of  his  was  entitled  to  as  much  deference  as  great  institutions 
which  had  lasted  for  ages,  and  which  were  still  satisfying 
in  a  large  measure  the  reasons  of  vast  masses  of  men,  was  not 
only  to  make  them  believe  a  falsehood,  but  a  falsehood  dis- 
ruptive of  the  continuity  between  the  present  and  the  past  of 
humanity,  and  incompatible  with  the  existence  of  the  family, 


THEOCRATIC   HISTORICAL  THEORY  371 

the  Church,  or  the  State  ;  one  which  meant,  in  fact,  the  entire 
dissolution  of  society.  Hence  they  rushed  into  the  breach  to 
oppose  it. 

The  easiest  way,  however,  of  opposing  a  doctrine,  that  which 
first  suggests  itself,  and  which  at  first  sight  seems  the  most 
promising  of  success,  is  direct  denial  of  it  and  the  affirmation 
of  the  contrary, — the  assertion  and  defence  of  the  antagonis- 
tic principle  as  the  exclusive  truth.  And  this  was  how  the 
reaction  combated  the  Revolution.  The  principle  of  individ- 
ual independence  had  been  taught  so  as  to  be  scarcely  com- 
patible, if  not  altogther  incompatible,  with  that  of  social 
authority;  now  that  of  social  authority  was  so  taught  as  to 
be  incompatible  with  individual  independence.  Order  had 
been  sacrificed  to  progress ;  now  progress  was  sacrificed  to 
order.  The  present  had  been  glorified  at  the  expense  of  the 
past ;  now  the  past  was  glorified  at  the  expense  of  the  present. 
A  theocracy  was  held  forth  as  the  very  ideal  of  society,  and 
democracy  denounced  as  an  insanity.  Passive  obedience  was 
represented  as  the  source  of  all  virtue ;  the  exercise  of  indi- 
vidual independence  as  the  cause  of  all  evil ;  tradition,  super- 
natural in  its  origin,  as  the  source  of  all  truth;  and  free 
inquiry  as  the  source  only  of  error. 

Now,  which  of  these  two  doctrines,  thus  held  as  antagonistic 
and  mutually  exclusive,  was  the  truest  expression  of  the  spirit 
of  modern  thought?  There  could  be  but  one  answer.  The 
men  of  the  reaction  themselves  could  not  refuse  for  a  moment 
to  acknowledge  that  the  Revolution  was  the  legitimate  heir  of 
the  preceding  four  centuries, — the  completest  assertion  in 
politics  of  the  same  principles  which  the  Renaissance  had 
introduced  into  literature,  the  Reformation  into  religion,  and 
Cartesianism  into  philosophy.  They  felt  that  their  own  doc- 
trine was  ancient  as  opposed  to  modern,  and  they  were  too 
honest  to  conceal  or  disavow  what  they  felt.  On  the  con- 
trary, they  proclaimed  their  conviction  that  the  last  four  cen- 
turies were  wrong  in  root  and  branches,  and  nowhere  more 
obviously  wrong  than  in  philosophy,  which,  if  it  have  no  other 
merits,  has  at  least  that  of  being  ever  the  clearest  expression 
of  the  spirit  of  its  age.  Its  systems  seemed  to  them  to  con- 
tradict and  destroy  one  another,  and  to  leave,  as  they  passed 


372  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

in  rapid  succession,  not  a  wrack  behind,  because  all  were 
based  on  the  hopelessly  false  foundation  that  in  order  to  find 
truth  the  mind  must  seek  it  in  itself,  in  its  own  consciousness, 
and  differed  only  as  to  what  principle  of  the  mind,  what 
faculty  of  the  conscious  being,  should  be  supposed  to  have  in 
it  the  supreme  criterion  of  certainty,  whether  sense,  or  feel- 
ing, or  reason.  Cartesians  and  Baconians,  sensationalists  and 
idealists,  dogmatists  and  sceptics,  in  the  judgment  of  the 
writers  we  are  speaking  of,  alike  started  from  the  ego  or  indi- 
vidual consciousness;  and  to  reason  from  this  datum,  they 
were  agreed,  could  only  land  in  universal  scepticism,  if  the 
reasoning  were  carried  far  enough.1 

The  ground,  they  thought,  on  which  the  temple  of  truth 
ought  to  be  raised  must  be  sought  elsewhere, — not  in  man  but 
out  of  him.  And  the  criterion  of  truth,  they  thought,  must  be 
sought  not  in  the  individual  but  in  the  race.  The  individual, 
they  held,  has  no  true  life  or  light  except  in  the  race ;  and  the 
race  has  in  like  manner  no  true  life  or  light  except  in  God. 
The  general  reason  of  man  is  represented  by  them  as  the 
absolute  rule  of  every  particular  reason,  and  the  reason  of  God 
primitively  revealed  as  the  absolute  rule  and  only  true  foun- 
dation of  general  reason.  The  reason  of  the  individual  when 
it  seeks  to  guide  itself  wanders  in  darkness ;  and  only  by  re- 
nouncing itself,  only  by  the  self-denial  which  constitutes  faith 
in  tradition,  or  common  or  catholic  consent,  does  it  unite  itself 
to  its  kindred  and  its  Creator,  and  come  under  the  enlighten- 
ment of  the  true  light  which  shineth  in  darkness  and  lighteth 
every  man  that  cometh  into  the  world. 

It  was  as  a  supposed  philosophical  basis  for  this  doctrine 
that  the  theory  of  the  origin  and  nature  of  language  elaborated 
by  De  Bonald  appeared  to  the  theocratists  as  one  of  the  most 
important  of  scientific  achievements.  According  to  this  theory, 
man  was  the  passive  recipient  of  language,  and  with  language 
of  thought :  language  being  not  the  product  but  the  condition 
of  thought.  Language,  holds  De  Bonald,  contains  all  thought, 
and  man  can  have  nothing  in  his  thought  which  is  not  revealed 

1  All  the  arguments  used  by  Broussais  in  his  treatise  '  De  1' Irritation  et  de  la 
Folie '  (1828) ,  and  by  Comte  against  the  psychological  method,  the  inductive  study 
of  consciousness,  had  been  previously  employed  by  De  Bonald,  De  Lamennais, 
and  D'Eckstein. 


THEOCRATIC   HISTORICAL   THEOKY  373 

to  him  by  his  speech,  the  relation  of  thought  and  language  being 
like  that  of  light  and  the  organ  of  vision,  so  that  man  can  no 
more  think  without  words,  or  otherwise  than  words  will  allow 
him,  than  he  can  see  without  light  or  anything  else  than  light 
discloses  to  him.  Language,  which  is  thus  not  merely  the 
instrument  but  the  very  life  and  substance  of  intelligence,  he 
further  maintains,  is  of  miraculous  origin,  or  the  immediate,  as 
contradistinguished  from  the  mediate,  gift  ©f  God.  In  proof  it 
is  argued  that  it  cannot  have  been  invented  by  man's  reason, 
for  man  has  no  reason  until  he  has  language ;  that  Scripture 
represents  it  as  the  direct  gift  of  God  to  the  first  parents  of 
the  human  race ;  that  the  truth  of  the  Scripture  representa- 
tion is  confirmed  by  philological  research,  which  establishes 
the  original  unity  and  essential  identity  of  all  language ;  and 
that  an  examination  of  its  nature  clearly  shows  it  to  be  far 
too  complex  and  elaborate,  far  too  perfect  and  difficult,  to  be 
the  work  of  man.  This  hypothesis  of  De  Bonald  implies  the 
truth  of  the  fundamental  error  of  Condillac  —  namely,  that 
human  nature  is  mere  sense  and  purely  passive ;  it  proceeds 
on  a  view  of  the  relation  of  language  to  thought,  and  of 
revelation  to  reason,  which  is  not  only  unproved  but  inherently 
absurd;  and  it  is  defended  by  arguments  which  are  either 
unsound  or  irrelevant ;  but  it  was  very  natural  that  it  should 
be  readily  accepted  by  the  theocratists.  Its  explanation  of  the 
■origin  of  speech  was  equally  an  explanation  of  the  origin  of 
reason  and  of  society,  and  consequently  of  all  that  reason  has 
produced  and  society  has  experienced.  It  referred  all  these 
origins  to  revelation,  and  made  tradition  or  the  transmission  of 
revelation  the  substance  or  life  of  history,  the  law  and  limit  of 
rational  and  voluntary  activity.     It  led  directly  to  the  result 

which  the  theocratists  were  above  all  anxious  to  demonstrate 

viz.,  that  man  is  dependent  for  his  intelligence,  its  operations 
so  far  as  legitimate,  and  its  conclusions,  religious,  moral, 
political,  and  social,  so  far  as  true,  on  tradition  flowing  from 
a  primitive  revelation. 

They  were,  of  course,  hostile  to  the  hypothesis  that  man 
had  gradually  raised  himself  from  a  state  of  ignorance  and 
barbarism  to  one  of  science  and  civilisation.  They  treated 
this  even  then  prevalent  opinion  as  merely  a  popular  delu- 


374  PHILOSOPHY    OF    HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

sion,  le  rSve  favori.  The  primitive  age  was,  according  to 
them,  truly  the  golden  age ;  and  the  first  men  were  superior 
to  their  descendants  both  in  intellect  and  in  virtue.  In  the 
pagan  religions  and  philosophies  they  saw  only  more  or  less 
corrupt  forms  of  the  most  ancient  religion  and  science ;  and 
whatever  truths  they  contained  they  believed  to  have  de- 
scended from  the  revelation  communicated  to  the  earliest 
parents  of  mankind.  They  regarded  the  savage  state  as  in 
all  its  phases  and  degrees  the  result  of  a  process  of  degrada- 
tion and  of  departure  from  divine  truth  which  had  its  origin 
in  Adam's  sin.  They  considered  the  doctrine  of  the  Fall  as 
going  far  to  explain  history.  They  rejected  the  doctrine  of 
progress  as  a  presumptuous  falsehood  which  history  contra- 
dicted. 

They  were  equally  averse  to  the  theory  of  Rousseau  that 
society  originated  in  a  contract,  in  the  combination  and  com- 
promise of  a  number  of  individual  wills.  They  attached  but 
little  value  to  the  individual.  They  regarded  man,  apart  from 
society,  as  merely  a  potentiality  or  an  abstraction.  Man,  ac- 
cording to  their  view,  becomes  a  real  person,  an  actual  man, 
only  through  participation  in  the  life  of  society.  Not  indi- 
viduals, but  the  family,  the  State,  and  the  Church  are  the 
true  social  units.  Lamennais'  whole  doctrine  of  truth,  certi- 
tude, and  authority  implies  the  vanity  of  mere  individual  rea- 
son and  will.  "  It  is  not  individuals,"  says  De  Bonald,  "  which 
constitute  society,  but  society  which  constitutes  individuals, 
since  individuals  exist  only  in  and  for  society."  De  Maistre 
will  not  recognise  individuals,  "  men,"  at  all ;  they  seem  to 
him  only  abstractions.  Hence  he  pronounces  the  proclama- 
tion of  "  the  rights  of  man  "  one  of  the  most  foolish  acts  of 
the  Revolution.  "  There  is,"  he  writes,  "  no  man  in  the 
world.  I  have  seen  Frenchmen,  Italians,  Russians;  but  as 
for  man,  I  declare  that  I  have  never  met  him  in  my  life." 

The  theocratists  further  held  that  society  ought  not  to  be 
regarded  as  a  mechanism,  but  as  an  organism.  They  charged 
the  revolutionists  with  having  done  just  the  opposite  —  with 
having  supposed  that  laws  could  be  instituted,  constitutions 
made,  and  societies  created,  by  the  mere  will  and  wisdom  of 
men.     According  to  their  own  view,  on  the  contrary,  God 


THEOCRATIC   HISTORICAL   THEORY  375 

alone  institutes  laws ;  constitutions  are  not  made,  but  grow ; 
and  societies  are  natural  organisms  which  the  skill  of  man  is 
powerless  to  produce.  An  implicit  belief  to  this  effect  may  be 
safely  ascribed  to  the  whole  theocratic  party.  De  Bonald's 
theory  of  society  is  a  delineation  of  society  as  an  organic  sys- 
tem. De  Maistre,  however,  must  be  credited  with  having- 
alone  presented  the  view  with  appropriate  explicitness  and 
clearness.  Man,  he  tells  us,  although  capable  of  modifying 
all  that  lies  within  the  sphere  of  his  activity,  can  create  noth- 
ing either  in  the  physical  or  moral  world.  He  can,  for  ex- 
ample, plant,  tend,  and  train  a  tree ;  but  he  never  fancies 
that  he  can  make  a  tree.  He  has  no  more  reason  for  imag- 
ining that  he  can  make  a  constitution.  To  assign  to  any 
assembly  of  men  the  task  of  making  a  constitution  is  a  more 
insane  procedure  than  any  which  takes  place  in  lunatic  asy- 
lums. A  constitution  is  the  whole  of  the  organic  conditions 
necessary  to  the  life  of  a  people,  and,  therefore,  not  a  thing 
which  can  be  produced  at  will  or  made  to  order,  like  a  loom 
or  an  engine  or  an  article  of  furniture.  It  is  a  natural  thing, 
and  therefore  no  art  of  man  can  make  it :  art  can  only  produce 
artificial  things ;  nature  alone  can  do  natural  things.  It  is  a 
living  thing,  and  nothing  which  lives  is  the  result  of  human 
deliberation  or  human  decree.  The  rights  of  peoples  are 
never  written.  No  nation  which  has  not  liberty  can  give 
itself  liberty.  Nothing  great  is  great  to  begin  with.  All 
normal  social  movement  is  continuous  and  unconscious.  All 
healthy  social  institutions  are  the  products  of  time  and  history. 
Such  is  the  substance  of  De  Maistre's  teaching  in  the  sixth 
chapter  of  his  'Considerations  sur  la  France.'  It  will  be  ob- 
served that  it  is  identical  with  the  doctrine  of  what  is  known 
as  the  Historical  School.  De  Maistre  was  the  most  notable 
French  precursor  of  Savigny,  the  founder  of  that  school. 
And  so  far  as  general  principles  were  concerned,  Savigny  did 
not  add  to  what  De  Maistre  laid  down.  Yet  the  latter  dif- 
fered from  the  former  in  two  respects.  In  the  first  place,  he 
was  more  one-sided  and  extreme.  He  went  nearer  to  asser- 
tion of  the  uselessness  of  reflection  and  discussion  in  political 
life;  nearer  to  the  elimination  of  reason  from  among  the 
means  of  social  progress,  and  to  the  representation  of  history 


376  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

as  a  merely  instructive  process.  In  the  second  place,  whereas 
the  general  political  theory  of  Savigny  was  in  accordance 
with  the  doctrine  of  historical  continuity,  that  of  De  Maistre 
was  in  glaring  contradiction  to  it.  The  revolutionists  had 
endeavoured  to  throw  off  and  abolish  the  medieval  tradition 
of  authority  in  order  to  realise  the  modern  tradition  of  liberty 
which  had  been  growing  up  since  the  fifteenth  century;  and 
De  Maistre  and  those  whom  he  represented  were  bent  on  ob- 
literating this  later  tradition,  and  on  expelling  and  destroying 
the  spirit  of  the  centuries  which  had  nourished  and  strength- 
ened it.  But  manifestly  this  too  was  an  attempt  to  break  the 
continuity  of  history.  It  was  an  attempt  to  tear  out  of  his- 
tory the  centuries  nearest  to  his  own  time.  History  never 
shows  us  individuals  or  nations  going  back  to  the  ages  which 
they  have  outgrown. 

The  writers  with  whose  views  on  history  we  are  now  occu- 
pied detested  what  they  called  liberalism  or  indifferentism ; 
and  in  assailing  it  they  attacked  all  the  primary  rights  and 
essential  liberties  of  man.  They  represented  the  claim  to  ex- 
ercise private  judgment  as  impiety  towards  God  and  rebellion 
against  the  authorities  that  He  had  ordained ;  religious  tol- 
eration as  the  persecution  of  true  religion ;  the  concession 
of  freedom  of  speech  and  freedom  of  the  press  as  the  ap- 
proval of  all  their  possible  abuses ;  and  the  granting  of  elec- 
toral or  self-governing  powers  to  the  people  as  a  violation 
of  the  divine  order  of  society  sure  to  produce  anarchy  and 
ruin.  They  fought  against  liberty  in  every  form.  They 
combated  especially  the  independence  of  reason.  Faith,  not 
reason,  and  submission,  not  freedom,  seemed  to  them  the  true 
conditions  of  social  existence. 

They  defended  the  cause  of  absolute  authority  alike  in 
Church  and  State.  As  to  the  former,  Liberal  Catholicism, 
Protestantism,  deism,  atheism,  were  all  condemned  as  but  so 
many  stages  of  deviation  and  descent  from  the  true  religion, 
the  sure  and  eternal  basis  of  social  order.  Gallicanism  was 
keenly  attacked;  its  weaknesses  and  inconsistencies  were 
unsparingly  exposed.  The  right  of  the  State  to  limit  the 
sphere  or  control  the  action  of  the  Church  was  strongly  de- 
nied.    The  right  of   the  Church  to  freedom  was   strongly 


THEOCRATIC    HISTORICAL   THEORY  377 

affirmed ;  but  what  was  meant  by,  it  was  a  right  to  despotic 
licence,  the  right  of  the  hierarchy  to  usurp  the  rights  of  the 
other  members  of  the  Church,  and  even  to  lord  it  over  all 
mankind  in  matters  of  education,  morality,  and  religion.  De 
Bonald,  De  Maistre,  and  Lamennais  were  at  one  in  claiming 
for  the  Church  this  sort  of  freedom,  in  ascribing  to  it  this  sort 
of  authority.  They  differed  somewhat  as  to  where  the  free- 
dom and  authority  resided.  De  Bonald  was  not  strictly 
ultramontanist.  He  placed  infallibility  and  sovereignty,  not 
in  the  Pope,  but  in  the  Church  as  a  whole.  He  held  that  a 
general  council  was  superior  to  the  Pope.  But  he  was  decid- 
edly anti-Gallican  and  absolutist,  maintaining  the  unlimited 
authority  of  the  Church,  as  represented  by  a  general  council, 
even  in  the  political  sphere.  De  Maistre  maintained  the 
Pope  to  be  infallible  and  superior  to  a  general  council,  yet 
unable  to  dispense  with  the  bishops,  his  necessary  organs,  not 
instruments  that  he  may  use  or  not  as  he  pleases.  In  his 
famous  work,  'Du  Pape,'  he  argued  that  infallibility  was 
necessarily  implied  in  sovereignty,  and  that  the  sovereignty 
of  the  Pope  had  its  divine  warrant  in  the  manner  of  its  acqui- 
sition, in  the  history  of  the  growth  and  services  of  the  papacy. 
Hence  the  work  is  largely  an  account  of  the  development  of 
the  papal  power.  As  such,  we  can  only  admire  its  cleverness, 
but  may  readily  grant  it  to  be  much  truer  than  any  profess- 
edly historical  survey  which  traces  the  growth  of  the  papacy 
mainly  to  deceit  and  corruption.  History,  however,  can  only 
justify  historical  right,  and  historical  right  falls  infinitely 
short  of  absolute  right.  Whatever  history  gives  it  may  also 
take  away.  Lamennais  was  far  the  most  influential  advocate 
of  the  ultramontane  creed  in  its  entirety.  He  taught  with  a 
success  which  he  himself  soon  came  to  deplore,  but  the  effects 
of  which  he  was  unable  to  undo :  that  without  the  Pope  there 
can  be  no  Church,  without  the  Church  no  Christianity,  with- 
out Christianity  no  true  religion,  and  without  true  religion 
no  proper  social  order;  and  that,  therefore,  the  welfare  not 
only  of  the  Church  but  of  society  depended  on  the  Pope  as 
the  organ  of  the  divine  law,  of  which  kings  are  merely  the 
ministers.  He  inculcated  papal  infallibility  as  not  only  a 
religious  dogma,  and  necessary  to  the  safety  and  strength  of 


378  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOEY   IN   PB.ANCE 

the  Church,  but  also  as  the,  central  truth  of  political  science 
and  the  guiding  principle  of  history,  the  recognition  of  which 
can  alone  secure  peace,  stability,  and  prosperity  to  nations. 

As  to  the  State,  it  was  argued  that  sovereignty  in  the 
secular  sphere  corresponds  to  infallibility  in  the  religious 
sphere,  and  must,  like  it,  be  one  and  indivisible,  and  entitled 
to  unquestioning  submission.  "  The  revolution  of  the  six- 
teenth century,"  says  De  Maistre,  "  ascribed  the  sovereignty 
to  the  Church  —  i.e.,  to. the  people.  The  eighteenth  century 
carried  the  principle  into  politics.  It  is  the  same  system,  the 
same  folly,  under  another  name."  The  temporal  power,  it 
was  admitted,  ought  to  be  subject,  indeed,  to  the  spiritual 
power,  to  which  it  is  naturally  inferior,  because  a  more  distant 
and  a  feebler  emanation  from  the  divine  power ;  but  it  can 
only  be  limited  from  above,  not  from  below  —  only  by  the 
Pope,  not  by  its  subjects.  They  have  no  right  to  judge  it, 
and  still  less  to  resist  it  and  to  impose  conditions  on  it.  The 
constitutional  Government  of  Britain  was  in  this  light 
specially  offensive  to  the  genuine  representatives  of  the 
theocratic  school.  De  Maistre  contemptuously  pronounced  it 
"  an  insular  peculiarity  utterly  unworthy  of  imitation ;  "  and 
De  Bonald  calmly  said  that,  "  mainly  owing  to  its  defects, 
the  English  are  by  far  the  most  backward  among  civilised 
peoples."  De  Bonald's  own  type  of  a  good  government  was 
ancient  Egypt,  with  its  Pharaohs  surrounded  by  priests,  and 
seated  on  the  summit  of  an  organised  system  of  rigidly 
defined  castes.  The  adherents  of  the  theocratic  party  in 
general  adopted  the  social  ideal  of  the  medieval  hierarchy, 
and  glorified  the  personages  and  institutions  that  had  come 
nearest  realising  it. 

The  theocratists  sought  support  for  their  theorems  in  the 
Bible ;  but  they  had  to  misinterpret  and  misapply  its  state- 
ments in  order  to  seem  to  find  it.  De  Bonald's  hypothesis  of 
the  revealed  origin  of  speech  and  reason,  science,  art,  and 
government,  was  an  extravagant  exaggeration  of  a  few  words 
of  Scripture,  which  it  was  unreasonable  to  use  at  all  in  the 
discussion  of  a  scientific  problem.  De  Maistre  professed  to 
found  on  Scripture,  but  had  no  warrant  for  the  profession 
when  he  represented  all  the  evils  which  afflict  society  as  only 


THEOCRATIC   HISTORICAL   THEORY  379 

punishments,  and  punishments  of  original  sin.  Nothing  can 
be  more  intensely  unchristian,  as  well  as  inhuman,  than  his 
glorification  of  the  scaffold,  his  eulogy  of  the  Inquisition,  and 
his  vindication  of  war  as  an  eternal  ordinance  of  God  and  a 
fundamental  law  of  the  world.  Nothing  can  be  more  opposed 
both  to  the  spirit  and  to  the  letter  of  the  Gospel  than  to 
maintain,  as  he  does,  that  "the  earth  is  for  ever  crying  for 
the  blood  of  man  and  beast ; "  that  it  is  "  an  immense  altar, 
on  which  all  that  lives  must  be  immolated  without  ceasing 
and  without  end  until  the  consummation  of  ages,  the  extinc- 
tion of.  evil,  the  death  of  death ; "  and  that  God  has  laid  on 
man  the  charge  of  slaughtering  his  fellow-men,  and  has  made 
wars  and  battles,  the  incessant  effusion  of  human  blood,  a 
condition  of  divine  acceptance  and  mercy.  Yet  he  passes  off 
these  revolting  falsehoods  as  truths  derived  from  revelation. 
Lamennais,  in  his  references  to  Scripture,  generally  shows 
himself  a  loose  and  capricious  exegete. 

The  writers  whose  views  regarding  history  we  have  been 
endeavouring  to  set  forth  were  men  of  exceptional  abilities 
and  varied  gifts ;  but  they  were  also  men  of  utterly  unscien- 
tific minds.  They  were  essentially  dogmatists,  rhetoricians, 
preachers,  and  pleaders,  not  men  inclined  by  nature  or  quali- 
fied by  training  to  seek  truth  in  a  proper  and  rational  way. 
They  were  ignorant  of  what  science  and  scientific  method 
are,  and  also  ignorant  of  their  ignorance.  M.  de  Bonald  was 
the  acknowledged  philosopher  of  the  theocratic  school ;  but 
how  little  he  knew  of  true  science  is  decisively  shown  by  the 
fact  that  he  took  for  scientific  laws,  for  principles  explanatory 
of  real  things,  these  two  most  absurd  propositions  :  that  all 
things  are  included  under  one  or  other  of  the  three  terms  of 
thought,  —  cause,  mean,  and  effect,  —  and  that  what  the 
cause  is  to  the  mean  the  mean  is.  to  the  effect.  In  meta- 
physics, the  trinitarian  formula  appears  as  God,  mediator,  and 
man;  in  religion,  as  the  Church,  priests,  and  laity;  in  the 
State,  as  king,  ministers  or  nobles,  and  people ;  in  the  family, 
as  father,  mother,  and  child ;  and  in  the  individual,  as  soul, 
sense,  and  body.  All  these  special  formulae,  M.  de  Bonald 
holds,  correspond  to  one  another  in  virtue  of  their  common 
relation  to  the  general  formula;  so  that,  for  example,  the 


380  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOEY   IN   FRANCE 

king  is  in  the  State  and  the  father  in  the  family  what  God  is 
in  the  universe ;  and  further,  the  terms  of  each  formula  are 
related  to  one  another  as  the  terms  of  every  other,  the  cause 
being  always  to  the  mean  as  the  mean  to  the  effect.  The 
result  is  obvious,  and  yet  startling  —  a  complete  theory  of  the 
theocracy,  of  absolutism  in  Church,  State,  and  family,  capable 
of  being  expressed  in  algebra. 

The  ultramontanist  theory  of  history  need  not  be  traced 
farther.  The  Revolution  of  1830  showed  so  plainly  that  the 
French  people  would  not  tolerate  political  absolutism,  that 
for  a  time  those  who  had  been  advocating  it  in  the  name  of 
religion  deemed  it  prudent  to  be  silent.  A  Liberal  Catholi- 
cism arose,  and  strove  to  reconcile  the  Church  and  society  by- 
gaining  the  former  over  to  the  side  of  popular  rights  and 
liberties.  But  when  this  gradually  came  to  be  seen  to  be  a 
hopeless  task,  and  at  the  same  time  a  revolutionary  and 
socialistic  spirit  gained  ground,  ultramontanism  reappeared. 
Immediately  before  the  Revolution  of  1848,  and  during  the 
Second  Empire,  the  most  active  propagandist  of  its  principles 
was  the  violent,  domineering,  and  unscrupulous  publicist, 
M.  Louis  Veuillot,  editor  of  '  L'Univers,'  and  its  worthiest 
and  most  cultured  advocate  was  M.  Blanc  de  Saint-Bonnet, 
author  of  '  L'Unite-  Spirituelle,'  2d  ed.,  1845,  '  La  Restaura- 
tion  francaise,'  1851, '  De  l'Affaiblissement  de  la  Raison  et  de 
la  Decadence  en  Europe,'  2d  ed.,  1854,  'L'Infaillibilite'  au 
point  de  vue  me'taphysique,'  1861,  and  other  writings.  The 
works  of  M.  de  Saint-Bonnet  have  many  merits,  and  abound 
in  good  thoughts  and  wise  'counsels  lucidly  and  vigorously 
expressed.  But  so  far  as  historical  theory  is  concerned  they 
add  little,  if  anything,  to  what  had  been  said  by  De  Bonald, 
De  Maistre,  and  Lamennais.  The  historical  generalisations 
which  they  contain  show  neither  extensive  nor  accurate 
historical  knowlege,  and  his  judgments  on  particular  histori- 
cal events  are  generally  wanting  in  impartiality  and  modera- 
tion. 

The  '  Bibliotheque  nouvelle,'  edited  by  M.  Veuillot,  was 
begun  in  1850  with  a  work  '  De  la  Philosophie  de  l'Histoire ' 
by  M.  Roux-Lavergne.  In  this  work  the  philosophy  of  his- 
tory is  explicitly  identified  with  the  theology  of  history,  and, 


FEREAND  381 

in  fact,  is  practically  treated  as  a  branch  of  Catholic  apolo- 
getics. In  the  opinion  of  M.  Veuillot,  the  philosophy  of 
history  had  been  invented  in  order  to  destroy  Catholicism ; 
M.  Roux-Lavergne  attempts  to  compose  a  philosophy  of 
history  which  will  be  a  verification  of  Catholic  dogmas. 

II 

In  the  party  of  reaction  which  rose  into  prominence  at  the 
Restoration,  all  who  were  absolutists  in  politics  were  not  tra- 
ditionalists or  ultramontanists  in  religion.  Count  Ferrand 
(1758-1821),  as  a  historical  theorist,  represented  this  type  of 
opinion.  While  decidedly  opposed  to  allowing  the  people  any 
share  in  the  government  of  their  country,  and  a  sternly  hostile 
critic'of  the  creed  as  to  the  rights  of  man  proclaimed  by  the 
Revolution,  he  was  also  a  severe  judge  of  the  papacy  and  of 
its  policy.  Two  of  his  works  must  be  mentioned,  but  need  not 
be  dwelt  on.  The  'Esprit  de  l'Histoire,'  4  torn.,  1802,  is  an 
attempt  to  give,  in  the  form  of  letters  to  his  son,  a  general 
view  of  the  great  epochs  of  history,  and  to  trace  especially 
what  its  author  regards  as  the  true  substance  and  main  move- 
ment of  history:  the  progress  of  government  and  laws  and 
their  influence  on  manners  and  public  happiness.  Its  central 
idea,  perhaps,  is  that  political  law  rests  on  moral  law,  and 
moral  law  on  divine  law.  It  is  a  book  of  little  value.  The 
epochs  of  history  are  not  determined  in  it  according  to  any 
principle;  the  generalisations  in  it. are  few  and  insignificant; 
and  the  reflections  which  it  contains  are  commonplace  and 
superficial.  The  '  The'orie  des  Revolutions,'  4  torn.,  is  a  consid- 
erably better  work.  It  abounds  in  condemnation  of  Napoleon, 
and  hence,  although  printed  in  1811,  was  not  published  until 
1817.  It  treats  first  of  physical  revolutions  in  relation  to 
their  political  effects,  and  then  of  religious  revolutions  and 
their  political  effects ;  but  five  of  the  nine  books  of  which  it 
consists  deal  with  political  revolutions.  Such  revolutions  are 
described  as  "  moral  maladies  attached  to  empires  as  physical 
revolutions  to  the  human  species,  and  referable  to  causes  which 
produce  them  in  all  times  and  places,  although  always  with 
modifications  according  to  times  and  places."  Starting  from 
this  view  of  their  nature,  it  is  argued  that  there  must  be  a 


382  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

theory  of  revolutions,  just  as  there  is  a  theory  of  laws.  This 
theory  he  endeavours  to  supply  by  a  study  of  the  species, 
causes,  occasions,  pretexts,  motives,  immediate  effects,  and  en- 
during consequences  of  revolutions.  The  study  is  commend- 
ably  comprehensive,  but  generally  wants  thoroughness.  The 
most  interesting  portion  of  it  is  that  which  treats  of  the  effects 
of  revolutions  (vii.).  It  is  of  a  truthfulness  altogether  remark- 
able, and  obviously  drawn  directly  from  the  life.  The  rest  of 
his  work  a  study  of  history  under  the  guidance  of  Aristotle, 
Bossuet,  and  Montesquieu  might  have  enabled  him  to  write ; 
but  this  part  of  it  could  not  have  been  composed  had  he  not 
been  an  interested  and  observant  witness  of  the  tremendous 
revolution  through  which  his  country  passed  in  the  closing 
years  of  the  eighteenth  century.  Many  of  the  positions  laid 
down  by  him  regarding  that  revolution  have  since  been  elab- 
orately maintained  by  M.  Taine,  very  possibly  without  knowl- 
edge of  the  views  of  the  earlier  writer.  Also  specially  worthy 
of  being  noted  is  the  use  which  he  makes  (iv.  4)  of  Aristotle's 
distinction  between  absolute  and  proportional  equality.  He 
has  forcibly  shown  that  to  affirm  absolute  equality  as  a  politi- 
cal principle  must  destroy  liberty  and  establish  despotism. 
Count  Ferrand  was  an  uncompromising  opponent  of  the  spirit 
of  the  French  Revolution.  Its  chief  aim  he  believed  to  be  an 
impious  desire  to  destroy  the  religion  of  the  State,  and  all 
religion.  In  his  own  opinion  the  union  of  religion  and  of  the 
State  has  been  felt  in  all  times  and  countries  to  be  a  natural 
and  sound  principle,  and  is,  in  fact,  altogether  necessary  to  the 
preservation  and  welfare  of  communities.  Religion  is  the  true 
basis  of  civil  society,  of  policy,  and  of  legislation. 

It  must  further  be  observed  that  all  those  who  were  theoc- 
ratists  and  traditionalists  in  religion  were  not  absolutists  in 
politics.  M.  Ballanche  (1776-1847)  was  an  instance,  and  he 
too  was  among  the  historiosophists.  He  was  a  man  of  delicate 
and  easily  moved  sensibility  and  lively  imagination ;  of  gentle 
and  tolerant  disposition  ;  of  meditative  and  mystical,  not  rati- 
ocinative  or  dogmatic  mind.  He  was  fertile  in  peculiar  and 
ingenious  views,  but  very  sparing  of  proofs,  and  very  imper- 
fectly aware  of  when  they  were  needed.  He  was,  perhaps,  the 
only  Frenchman  who,  prior  to  Michelet,  had  gained  a  real 
insight  into  the  ideas  of  Vico ;  and  he  was  also  among  the  first 


BALLANCHE  383 

of  French  writers  sympathetically  to  appreciate  that  regenera- 
tion of  the  German  genius  which  showed  itself  in  Goethe  and 
Schiller,  Winckelmann  and  Herder,  Goerres  and  Schelling, 
and  Creuzer.  His  literary  career  began  in  1801,  with  a  book 
on  '  Sentiment  conside're'e  dans  ses  rapports  avec  la  Literature 
et  les  Arts.'  His  views  on  history  are  to  be  found  chiefly  in 
his  '  Essai  sur  les  institutions  sociales  dans  leurs  rapports  avee 
les  ide"es  nouvelles,'  1818,  and  '  Palinge"n6sie  Sociale,'  1823- 
30.  Two  unversified  poems  which  had  once  a  certain  celeb- 
rity, 'Antigone,' 1814,  and  the  '  Vision  d'Hebal,'  1831,  may 
be  regarded  as  so  far  complementary  to  them.  Ballanche  Avas 
in  all  respects  a  romanticist.1 

The  idea  which  pervades  and  unifies  his  historical  views  is 
that  history  is  a  progressive  rehabilitation  of  humanity  from 
the  evils  of  the  Fall,  marked  by  successive  initiations,  palin- 
geneses.  Man  gradually  raises  himself  from  the  state  into 
which  he  sank  through  his  first  sin,  by  a  series  of  acts  of  self- 
sacrifice  and  devotedness  which  unloose,  one  by  one,  the  bur- 
dens that  press  upon  him,  and  remove  the  obstacles  which 
nature  and  society  oppose  to  his  advancement.  These  acts  of 
redemption  and  deliverance  are  in  most  instances  performed 
by  individuals,  but  the  benefits  of  them  devolve  on  communi- 
ties in  accordance  with  the  law  of  revertibility  on  which  De 
Maistre  had  so  emphatically  insisted. 

As  regards  the  history  of  the  ancient  world,  he  was,  in  the 
main,  a  disciple  of  Vico.  Like  Vico,  he  deemed  the  struggle 
of  the  patricians  and  plebeians  to  be  the  key  to  its  explanation 
■ —  the  fact  which  determined  the  stages  of  historic  movement 
prior  to  the  establishment  of  Christianity.  Like  Vico  also,  he 
represented  mythology  as  being  a  kind  of  history  of  the  oldest 
societies,  and  saw  in  languages  the  most  ancient  archives  of 
the  human  race. 

As  regards  the  Christian  world,  Vico  could  no  longer  serve 
him  as  a  guide.  According  to  M.  Ballanche,  Christianity  is 
an  eminently  plebeian  religion.  It  is  the  law  of  emancipation 
and  of  grace  for  all;  it  secures  to  the  whole  human  race  the 

1  There  are  essays  on  Ballanche  by  Sainte-Beuve,  De  Laprade,  and  J.  J.  Ampere. 
His  general  system  of  thought  has  been  well  expounded  by  M.  Ferraz  ('  Tra- 
ditionalisme  et  Ultramontanisme'),  and  by  M.  Eug.  Blum  ('Crit.  Phil.'  of  30th 
June  1887). 


384  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOEY   IN   FEANCE 

right  to  liberty  and  equality.  Its  spirit  was  misunderstood  in 
the  middle  age,  and  it  is  vain  to  imagine  that  mankind  can  be 
satisfied  by  the  restoration  of  medieval  institutions.  It  is 
the  perfect  and  final  religion.  It  is  the  permanent  and  inex- 
haustible source  of  progress.  Within  it  there  is  room  for  the 
utmost  possible  progress.  "  Fundamentally  and  in  itself,  in- 
deed, religion  is  not,  and  cannot  be,  progressive.  But  in  the 
measure  that  time  moves  on,  the  veils  fall,  the  seals  of  the 
sacred  book  are  broken,  a  new  spirit  bursts  forth  from  under 
the  letter  of  the  old  texts,  and  things  appear  under  an  alto- 
gether fresh  light." 

Ballanche  supposed  the  material  of  all  truth  to  be  a  sacred 
tradition,  which,  while  ever  substantially  the  same,  was  also 
ever  varying.  He  fully  accepted  the  doctrine  that  language 
was  a  revelation ;  that  it  had  been  directly  and  immediately 
taught  by  God  to  the  first  man ;  that  the  words  of  God  were 
what  originally  communicated  thoughts  to  man ;  but  he  insisted 
on  the  gradual  alteration  and  development  both  of  the  contents 
and  form  of  this  revelation,  both  of  language  itself  and  the 
spiritual  truths  it  conveyed ;  and  even  divided  the  whole  move- 
ment of  history  into  epochs  corresponding  to  the  chief  phases 
through  which  language  had  passed.  First,  language  was 
merely  spoken.  This  was  when  man  was  in  his  naive  and 
graceful  childhood,  when  all  the  world  around  him  appeared 
in  the  colours  of  poetry,  when  religion  was  an  intuition  and 
inspiration,  when  reflection  had  scarcely  dawned  and  specula- 
tion and  doubt  were  unknown,  and  when  song  was  the  com- 
mon channel  by  which  the  divine  word  passed  from  heart  to 
heart.  In  this  stage  the  sacred  deposit  of  spiritual  truth 
transmitted  in  language  was  in  imminent  danger  of  being 
corrupted,  owing  to  the  vague  and  unfixed  character  of  its 
medium  or  form  or  vehicle,  and  society  had  to  be  distributed 
into  castes,  with  priests  and  poets  specially  set  apart  to  pre- 
serve and  diffuse  it  in  purity  and  power.  But  beautiful  and 
graceful  as  the  childhood  of  the  race  is,  it  must,  like  that 
of  the  individual,  be  outgrown.  In  the  course  of  time  thought 
ceases  to  be  mere  intuition,  poetry,  and  faith;  it  becomes 
reflective,  regular,  and  less  graceful,  but  more  powerful  and 
mature  ;  and  can,  consequently,  no  longer  be  left  to  be  merely 
uttered  by  the  voice,  merely  spoken,  but  must  be  fixed  in  a 


BALLANCHE  385 

visible  and  more  permanent  form,  must  be  written  as  well  as 
spoken.  In  this  second  stage  of  tradition,  which  is  also  the 
second  great  epoch  of  history,  the  priest  and  poet  no  longer 
suffice,  and  the  philosopher  rises  to  interpret  or  question  their 
message  and  share  in  their  authority.  At  the  same  time 
authority  is  weakened  by  being  divided,  inquiry  spreads, 
activity  finds  new  channels,  and  knowledge  grows  from  more 
to  more.  Writing  even  perfected  to  the  utmost  is  at  length 
found  insufficient  to  contain  and  convey  the  wealth  of  expe- 
rience and  ideas  which  has  been  acquired,  and  a  new  art  is 
sought  and  discovered  to  satisfy  the  new  demands  which  have 
arisen.  Thenceforth  thought  is  not  only  spoken  and  written, 
but  also  printed.  It  has  reached  its  majority  and  stands  no 
longer  in  need  of  protection.  It  claims  the  completest  free- 
dom within  the  limits  of  reason  and  justice,  and  will,  sooner 
or  later,  inevitably  secure  it.  All  castes  and  class  privileges 
will  disappear.  All  will  know  the  truth,  and  the  truth  will 
make  them  free.  Those  who  attempt  to  obstruct  humanity 
on  its  march  towards  its  goal — the  realisation  of  rational  free- 
dom —  must  fail  and  be  put  to  shame.  Such  is  the  general 
formula  of  historical  development  suggested  by  M.  Ballanche. 
It  implies  that  history  is  a  progressive  movement  or  growth, 
ever  advancing  and  spreading  into  a  broader  liberty,  always 
tending  towards  perfect  freedom  in  every  phase  of  life. 

Ballanche  recognises  in  history  the  combination  of  liberty 
and  necessity ;  of  the  free  agency  of  individuals  and  the  de- 
terminating influence  of  the  social  medium.  He  insists  at 
once  on  the  importance  of  personal  initiation  and  on  the  con- 
ditioning and  constraining  power  of  the  collective  movement ; 
both  on  the  ability  of  men  to  create  and  shape  the  future  for 
themselves,  and  on  the  certainty  that  every  future  will  neces- 
sarily correspond  to  the  past  and  present  from  which  it  pro- 
ceeds. Like  Hegel  and  Cousin  he  ascribes  a  vast  historical 
importance  to  great  personalities  —  revealers  and  initiators, 
prophets  and  heroes;  like  them  also  he  attributes  their  in- 
fluence and  significance  not  to  what  isolates  and  individual- 
ises them,  but  to  what  unites  them  with  their  fellows  and 
renders  them  the  fitting  instruments  and  organs  of  the  spirit 
of  their  age  and  people. 

He  does  not  confine  his  views  of  the  future  of  humanity  to 


386  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOBY   IK  FKANCE 

the  present  world,  but  represents  the  souls  of  men  as  passing 
after  death  through  many  lives  in  many  worlds,  gradually 
raising  themselves  by  their  own  efforts  into  ever  nobler  lives 
in  ever  brighter  worlds,  until  they  reach  at  length  the  glory 
which  is  immutable,  where  progress  must  cease.  This  portion 
of  his  teaching  —  his  doctrine  of  metempsychosis  —  took  root 
in  the  minds  of  Pierre  Leroux  and  Jean  Reynaud,  and  re- 
appeared in  their  writings. 

Ill 

The  Revolution  of  1830  was  a  heavy  blow  to  ecclesiastical 
as  well  as  to  political  absolutism.  In  striking  down  the 
latter  it  terrified  the  former  into  silence.  It  compelled  the 
admirers  of  theocratic  despotism  to  understand  that  an  open 
advocacy  of  their  cause  was  in  the  then  state  of  public  opin- 
ion the  worst  method  of  serving  it.  Accordingly  they  retired 
into  obscurity,  kept  quiet,  and  waited  for  an  opportune  season 
when  they  could  reappear.  The  place  from  which  they  had 
withdrawn  was  occupied  by  the  Liberal  or  Neo-Catholic  party, 
which  had  been  forming  and  growing  for  a  considerable  time 
previous  to  1830,  but  which  only  became  conspicuous  and 
influential  when  its  natural  ally,  constitutional  monarchy, 
triumphed  over  absolute  monarchy.  It  was  a  party  generous 
in  its  aims,  full  of  hope  and  courage,  lavish  in  promises,  and 
eager  for  action.  Its  chiefs  were  brilliantly  gifted,  thoroughly 
sincere,  nobly  self-denying,  and  inspired  with  the  enthusiasm 
both  of  patriotism  and  of  piety.  Their  followers,  largely 
composed  of  the  brightest  and  best  of  the  youth  of  France, 
were  every  way  worthy  of  such  leaders  as  Lamennais,  La- 
cordaire,  and  Ozanam,  as  Montalembert,  De  Falloux,  and  De 
Broglie. 

What  this  party  had  in  view  was  to  help  to  bring  back  into 
the  fold  of  the  Church  those  who  had  withdrawn  from  it,  to 
secure  and  set  forth  the  harmony  of  Catholic  doctrine  and  of 
modern  science,  and  to  reconcile  the  claims  of  the  hierarchy 
with  the  rights  of  the  laity  and  the  liberties  of  nations.  It 
was  certainly  a  grand  and  most  desirable  end ;  one  which  all 
who  believed  it  attainable  were  clearly  bound  to  strive  to 
reach.      And  although  to  realise  it  was  even  then  manifestly 


LIBERAL   CATHOLICISM  387 

a  most  arduous  task,  it  was  not  yet  a  wholly  visionary  and 
hopeless  one.  The  disastrous  pontificate  of  Pius  IX.,  the 
Syllabus,  the  decreeing  of  the  Infallibility  of  the  Pope  as  a 
dogma,  were  still  in  the  future.  But  it  is  easy  to  see  why 
the  work  so  earnestly  attempted  failed,  and  failed  so  utterly 
that  intelligent  men  are  never  likely  to  undertake  it  again. 
The  Church  had  for  ages  been  departing  from  truth,  justice, 
and  liberty,  and  could  only  return  to  them  by  an  act  of  self- 
humiliation  hardly  to  be  expected  from  any  great  world-power, 
and  especially  from  one  which  claimed  to  have  immunity  from 
error.  The  interests  of  those  who  ruled  it  were  directly 
opposed  to  restoring  to  the  lower  clergy  and  the  laity  the 
rights  of  which  they  had  deprived  them,  and  which  they  were 
able  to  retain  by  their  absolute  command  of  the  administration 
and  resources  of  the  Church.  The  great  majority  of  the  Cath- 
olic laity  were  too  ignorant  and  superstitious  to  take  the  side 
of  enlightenment  and  independence.  Many  even  of  the  edu- 
cated and  intelligent  minority  held  aloof  from  the  new  move- 
ment, either  because  they  doubted  of  the  practicability  of  its 
aims,  or  because  they  feared  lest  the  freedom  which  was 
sought  for  the  Church  would  be  employed  by  it  to  the  injury 
of  the  State.  And,  further,  the  advocates  of  Liberal  Cathol- 
icism were  not  themselves  prepared  to  assert  their  principles 
in  opposition  to  an  express  condemnation  of  them  by  the  Pope. 
With  the  exception  of  Lamennais,  they  were  all  found  at  the 
critical  moments  afraid  to  incur  for  their  convictions  the  risk 
of  excommunication,  the  danger  of  losing  their  souls  through 
separation  from  the  Church.  But  the  Pope  and  hierarchy 
must  always  prove  too  strong  for  those  who  are  thus  afraid  of 
their  condemnation. 

While  the  Liberal  Catholic  movement  utterly  failed  to 
attain  the  ends  towards  which  it  reached,  it  is  not  to  be  sup- 
posed that  it  was  wholly  in  vain.  It  greatly  stimulated 
intellectual  activity  and  quickened  spiritual  life  while  it 
lasted;  and  good  effects  of  it  remain.  The  truths  contended 
for  by  those  who  took  part  in  it  may,  even  where  dormant 
and  buried  now,  yet  "awake  to  perish  never." 

One  incidental  result  of  it  was  the  production  of  various 
historical  works  which  have  been  widely  read,  and  which  have 
had  considerable  influence  on  public  opinion.     Viewed  gen- 


388  PHILOSOPHY   Of   HISTORY   IK   FB.ANCE 

erally,  these  worts  are,  as  regards  style,  remarkably  eloquent; 
as  regards  spirit,  ardently  in  sympathy  with  what  is  noble 
and  good;  and  want  only  critical  thoroughness  and  impar- 
tiality to  be  excellent.  With  the  exception  of  eloquence, 
there  is  little  to  commend  in  the  'Vie  de  Saint-Dominique,' 
1840,  of  the  famous  Christian  orator,  Lacordaire.  It  conceals 
the  ferocious  fanaticism  of  the  persecutor  in  order  to  glorify 
the  piety  of  the  ascetic.  It  is  disappointing  to  find  that  so 
one-sided  and  unfair  a  book  could  be  written  b}'  so  eminent 
a  man.  The  'Vie  de  St.  Elisabeth'  of  Montalembert  is  a 
beautiful  piece  of  literary  composition,  but  scarcely  to  be 
regarded  as  a  biography  at  all.  Its  author  overlooked  the 
proper  sources  of  information,  gave  credence  to  legend,  and 
allowed  free  scope  to  his  feelings  and  imagination.  Hence  a 
very  erroneous  representation  of  the  facts  as  to  Elisabeth, 
and  an  ignoring  of  the  baneful  influence  of  the  infamous 
Conrad  of  Marburg,  papal  inquisitor-general,  upon  her  nature 
and  happiness.1  Montalembert's  chief  work,  'Histoire  des 
Moines  d'Occident, '  6  vols.,  is  of  high  value.  It  is  the  fruit 
of  lengthened  and  sympathetic  study.  Its  subject  is  one  of 
great  interest  and  importance,  and  amply  worthy  of  the  elo- 
quence and  learning  devoted  to  its  treatment.  It  is  avowedly 
apologetic  in  aim,  "  intended  to  vindicate  the  glory  of  one  of 
the  greatest  institutions  of  Christianity;  "  but  that  it  should 
be  so  is  much  better  than  if  it  had  been  hostile  and  deprecia- 
tory. The  reader,  however,  who  wishes  to  distinguish  fact 
from  legend  in  it  must  do  so  by  the  continuous  exercise  of 
his  own  critical  faculty,  as  the  author  is  very  sparing  in  the 
exercise  of  his.  Ozanam  was  richly  endowed  with  the  best 
qualities  of  a  historian.  Although  an  early  death  prevented 
his  executing  more  than  some  parts  of  the  great  work  which 
he  had  planned,  these  amply  prove  his  right  to  be  ranked 
among  the  best  historical  writers  of  his  country.  His  'His- 
toire de  la  Civilisation  au  5e  sidcle,'  1889,  and  'Etudes  Ger- 
maniques, '  1847-49,  are  the  products  of  rare  mental  and  of 
accurate  and  extensive  research.  Although  a  desire  to  do 
apologetic  service  to  the  Church  is  always  apparent  in  them, 
it  can  also  be  seen  to  have  been  kept,  on  the  whole,  well 

iFor  proof  see  Wegele's  art.,  "Die  heilige  Elisabeth  von  Thiiringen,"  in  v. 
Sybel's  '  Hist.  Zt.,'  Bd.  v.,  1861. 


ABBE   GRATRY  389 

under  control.  The  brothers  Charles  and  Henry  de  Riancey 
published  in  1838  an  'Histoire  du  monde,'  which  gave  a  gen- 
eral delineation  of  human  history  as  viewed  from  the  Liberal 
Catholic  standpoint.1 

None  of  those  who  took  an  active  part  in  the  Liberal  Catho- 
lic movement  wrote  on  the  philosophy  of  history  any  work 
which  calls  for  notice.  But  the  celebrated  Abbe"  Gratry 
(1805-72)  may  perhaps  be  considered  as  belonging  to  the 
Liberal  Catholic  party  in  virtue  of  his  enlightened  and  liberal 
opinions;  and  his  'La  Morale  et  la  loi  de  l'histoire, '  1868, 
2e  ed.,  1871,  ought  not  to  be  passed  over  in  silence.2  It  is, 
indeed,  more  the  production  of  a  preacher  than  of  a  philoso- 
pher, more  a  work  of  practical  edification  than  of  science. 
It  is  nevertheless  an  able  and  valuable  book  by  a  very  remark- 
able man.  While  unequal,  often  diffuse,  abounding  in  repe- 
titions, sometimes  rash  in  assertion  and  exaggerated  in 
expression,  and  bearing  other  traces  of  improvisation,  and  of 
an  intensity  and  fervour  of  conviction  not  conducive  to 
orderliness,  thoroughness,  or  accuracy  of  exposition,  it  is  also 
characterised  by  independence  and  considerable  originality  of 
thought,  as  well  as  by  impressiveness  and  vigour  of  style.  It 
presents  in  a  most  striking  manner  some  truths  of  vital 
importance  to  historical  philosophy,  and  contains  many  admir- 
able pages. 

Gratry  prefaced  the  first  edition  of  the  work  by  the  words : 
"  The  science  of  the  laws  of  history,  this  New  Science  which 
Vico  has  named,  but  could  not  know,  is  the  science  the  prin- 
ciples of  which  I  endeavour  to  teach  in  this  book."  Hence 
it  is,  I  suppose,  that  he  has  been  called  the  "  Christian  Vico  " 
and  the  "  Vico  of  the  nineteenth  century. "  He  had,  however, 
little  intellectual  resemblance  to  Vico ;  and,  notwithstanding 

1  There  are  English  biographies  of  Lacordaire,  Ozanam,  and  Montalembert  re- 
spectively by  Dora  Greenwell  (1867) ,  Kathleen  O'Meara  (1876) ,  and  Mrs.  Oliphant 
(1872),  the  first  two  of  which  are  good,  and  the  last  in  every  respect  admirable. 
The  French  biographical  writings  relating  to  the  leaders  of  the  Liberal  Catholic 
movement  are  numerous.  The  most  philosophical  history,  written  by  a  repre- 
sentative of  French  Liberal  Catholicism,  is  '  L'Eglise  et  l'Empire  Romain  au 
quatrieme  siecle  '  (6  vols.,  3°  ed.,  1860),  by  M.  Albert  de  Broglie.  It  is  charac- 
terised by  profound  insight  into  the  period  studied,  and  chargeable  neither  with 
want  of  critical  thoroughness  nor  of  impartiality. 

2  On  Gratry,  see  the  art.  "  Gratry  "  in  Franck's  'Diet,  des  Sci.  Phil.,'  and  the 
essay  of  M.  Caro  on  Gratry 's  religious  philosophy  in  '  Philosophie  et  Philosophes.' 
In  the  latter  work  there  is  also  a  most  interesting  notice  of  Ozanam. 


390  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

his  real  ability,  cannot  justly  be  represented  as  nearly  equal 
to  tbe  Italian  historiosophist  in  genius.  He  bad  read  Vico's 
'Seconda  Scienza  Nuova,'  and  mates  a  long  quotation  from 
its  fourth  book,  but  there  are  no  traces  of  his  having  studied 
it  closely  or  sympathetically.  The  fact  that  he  can  charge 
Vico  with  having  seen  in  history  only  the  political  movement, 
is  sufficient  to  show  that  he  did  not  really  understand  his 
system. 

Gratry  has  himself  delineated  what  he  calls  "  the  scientific 
framework  "  of  his  theory  of  history  in  words  which  I  shall 
reproduce  so  far  as  abbreviation  will  allow. 

"  The  new  science,  the  science  of  history,  is  one  greatly  needed  in  the 
present  age  of  restlessness,  uncertainty,  and  suffering,  for  it  is  the  science 
of  hope.  As  such  it  rests  on  this  solid  basis,  —  the  history  of  humanity 
has  its  laws,  or,  more  correctly,  its  law,  and  that  law  is  worthy  of  man 
and  worthy  of  God.  The  idea  of  law  and  the  idea  of  liberty  do  not  in 
any  way  exclude  each  other.  Law  and  fatality  are  not  the  same  thing. 
The  life  of  the  human  race  is  subject  to  a  law,  not  less  than  the  motions 
of  the  stars.  But  while  the  stars  obey  their  law  necessarily,  man  obeys 
his  law  freely.  As  inertia  is  the  essential  property  of  matter,  liberty  is 
the  essential  characteristic  of  man.  Man,  therefore,  can  do  what  matter 
cannot :  he  can  accept  or  resist  impulses,  and  alter  the  velocity  and  direc- 
tion of  his  movements.  He  can  struggle  against  the  law  of  his  life  and 
the  immense  force  which  inspires  and  directs  it.  He  can  choose.  He  can 
triumph  under  the  law,  or  break  himself  against  the  law.  But  the  law 
reigns  whether  it  breaks  or  glorifies  the  free  being  which  it  rules.  All 
the  movements  of  history  are  the  inevitable  effects  of  the  force  of  man 
acting  under  his  law,  to  follow  it  or  violate  it :  movements  of  life  or 
death,  of  progress  or  decadence,  according  to  the  way  in  which  the  force 
acts  under  the  law.  The  law  always  r-eigns ;  no  one  violates  it  in  itself. 
The  free  force  breaks  itself  against  the  law,  or  triumphs  under  the  law, 
but  it  is  always  in  virtue  of  the  law  that  it  is  either  triumphant  or  broken. 
The  law  always  reigns,  even  in  the  details  and  form  of  the  breakage  and 
failure,  as  attraction  always  reigns  through  all  so-called  perturbations : 
every  detail  of  perturbation  is  a  regular  effect  of  the  law."1 

"  What  is  the  law  of  history  ?  It  is  one  which  was  thus  formulated 
by  Jesus  :  '  All  things  whatsoever  ye  would  that  men  should  do  unto  you, 
even  so  do  ye  also  unto  them.'  This  formula  is  even  shorter  than  that 
of  the  law  of  attraction,  and  like  it  involves  a  whole  science.  It  is  the 
law  of  history  inasmuch  as  it  is  the  law  of  the  cause  which  produces  all 
the  facts  of  history.  But  as  in  astronomy  besides  the  law  of  attraction, 
the  law  of  the  cause,  there  are  three  secondary  laws,  inevitable  conse- 
quences of  the  attraction  acting  under  its  law,  which  describe  the  form 

1  T.  i.  4-6. 


ABBE   GKATRY  391 

of  its  movements,  so  in  history  besides  the  fundamental  law,  the  law  of 
the  force,  there  is  a  law  of  the  phases  of  progress,  and  of  the  form  of 
the  movements.  This  latter  law  has  likewise  been  formulated  by  Jesus, 
and  is:  'If  ye  abide  in  my  word,  ye  shall  know  the  truth,  and  the  truth 
will  make  you  free.'  Its  three  phases  or  moments  are  :  abiding  in  the  law, 
knowing  the  truth,  and  becoming  free  ;  and  they  are  the  effects  of  human 
force  acting  under  the  law.  If  man  does  not  abide  in  the  law,  instead  of 
advancing  to  the  knowledge  of  the  truth,  and  by  this  knowledge  attaining 
freedom,  he  will  go  into  darkness,  and  through  darkness  into  slavery."  1 

"  The  significance  of  the  law  of  the  force  and  of  the  law  of  the  form 
of  history,  however,  can  only  be  properly  realised  when  it  is  recognised 
that  man  is  born  into  three  worlds  in  which  they  apply,  —  the  physical 
or  natural  world,  the  human  or  social  world,  and  the  supreme  or  divine 
world.  Hence  the  true  division  of  his  duties  :  duties  towards  nature,  — 
towards  man,  —  and  towards  God.  He  has  to  increase,  multiply,  and 
replenish  the  earth ;  to  subdue  and  transform,  improve,  and  enrich  it,  by 
his  labour  and  science.  He  has  to  bring  society,  throughout  the  whole 
earth,  into  order  and  justice;  to  cause  war,  spoliation,  and  misery  every- 
where to  cease.  He  has,  further,  to  seek  the  kingdom  of  God  and  His 
righteousness ;  to  draw  by  faith,  piety,  and  religious  science,  from  the 
bosom  of  the  heavenly  Father,  the  infinite  source  of  life  and  energy,  those 
divine  forces  which  will  solve  the  problems  and  overcome  the  obstacles 
with  which  the  forces  of  nature  and  of  humanity  cannot  successfully 
cope.  These  tasks,  these  duties,  are  incumbent  on  all  generations  of 
men,  but  they  are  unequally  accomplished  at  different  periods.  Hence 
the  three  ages  of  history :  1.  The  struggle  against  nature ;  2.  The  strug. 
gle  for  justice  ;  and  3.  The  endeavour  after  the  freedom  and  perfection 
of  the  religious  life.  These  ages  are  inseparably  connected  and  inter* 
dependent.  For  men  find  that  in  order  to  subdue  the  earth  they  must 
establish  justice,  and  in  order  to  establish  justice  must  have  recourse  to 
God ;  and  that  then  they  must  recommence  their  labour  to  subdue  the 
earth  and  to  establish  justice.  These  are  the  three  great  historical  circles 
of  which  Vico  caught  a  glimpse,  without  being  able  to  distinguish  the 
special  content  of  each.  He  correctly  perceived  that  they  always  follow 
in  the  same  order,  and  then  recommence ;  but  not  that  they  also  always 
rise,  and  always  in  each  circle  lessen  labour  and  enlarge  the  range  of 
vision,  like  those  spiral  paths  which  mount  up  from  the  plain  to  the  tops 
of  mountains."  2 

"  This  law  of  progress  explains  the  history  of  the  Christian  world.  In 
its  first  phase,  the  Church  struggles  during  more  than  a  thousand  years 
against  Roman  paganism  and  German  barbfarism,  practising  the  word  of 
God  and  justice.  Next,  it  enters  into  the  phase  of  truth,  which,  at  first, 
was  entirely  theological  and  scholastical,  which  afterwards  illumined 
nature,  and  which,  in  our  days,  carries  light  into  the  social  world.  The 
third  phase,  that  of  liberty,  has  been  badly  inaugurated  by  the  French 

1  T.  i.  6-10.  2T.i.  11-18,  297-302 ;  T.  ii.  382-387,  &c. 


392  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Eevolution,  and  dates  only  from  the  present  day.  Humanity  hitherto 
passive  now  begins,  with  full  knowledge  and  entire  freedom,  to  take  into 
its  hands  the  management  of  the  affairs  of  the  world ;  it  enters  into  its 
age  of  manhood." 1 

Such  is  the  general  outline  of  Gratry's  historical  philoso- 
phy. That  philosophy  was  inspired  by  a  firm  faith  in  prog- 
ress, but  in  a  progress  which  is  the  work  of  freedom,  a 
"  facultative  "  progress.  Gratry  criticises  and  judges  severely 
society  as  it  actually  exists ;  some  of  his  chapters  are  on  fire 
with  a  fierce  indignation  against  the  enslavement  and  spolia- 
tion of  man  by  man,  the  unjust  and  homicidal  conduct,  which 
still  prevail;  and  he  sees  and  dreads  the  dangers  of  the  near 
future ;  but  his  general  view  of  the  duty  of  the  human  race 
is  characterised  by  a  hopefulness  which  may  very  possibly  be 
excessive.  At  least  he  has  not  proved  that  he  has  a  right  to 
suppose  that  the  powers  of  mankind  will  be  multiplied  so 
many  times  an  hundredfold  that  the  earth  will  nourish  mil- 
lairds  of  persons;  that  the  limits  of  life  will  be  greatly 
extended ;  that  the  stars  will  be  utilised  in  now  unsuspected 
ways ;  and  that  the  place  of  immortality  will  be  perceived. 
The  main  source  of  such  optimism  as  is  to  be  met  with  in  his 
view  of  the  course  which  history  has  to  run  was  obviously 
the  intensity  of  his  belief  in  providential  wisdom  and  good- 
ness. It  was  also,  doubtless,  in  part  derived  from  the  teach- 
ing of  the  celebrated  economist  Bastiat,  the  ingenious  and 
brilliant  opponent  of  socialism  and  protectionism.  For  that 
teaching  Gratry  had  great  admiration,  and  its  influence  is 
very  visible  in  the  work  under  consideration. 

The  chief  service  rendered  by  our  author  to  historical 
philosophy  is  the  demonstration  which  he  has  given  of  the 
dependence  of  political  and  social  progress  on  moral  progress. 
He  has  shown  with  singular  clearness  and  force  that  the  great 
obstacle  to  progress  is  vice ;  that  almost  all  the  evils  of  soci- 
ety would  be  removed  if  men  would  only  consent  to  refrain 
from  lying,  theft,  murder,  and  the  like ;  that  a  right  moral 
state  is  indispensable  to  economic  prosperity,  and  every  other 
kind  of  human  welfare;  and  that  if  nations  die  it  is  not 
inevitably,  but  because  they  are  guilty  of  preferring  death  to 

i  T.  i.  ch.  xiii. 


ABBE   GRATRY  393 

life.  It  is  especially  on  account  of  this  merit  that  Gratry's 
work  deserves  to  be  kept  in  remembrance;  and  it  is  not  to  be 
denied  to  it,  or  depreciated,  because,  not  content  with  repre- 
senting morality  as  the  condition  of  progress,  he  also  main- 
tained it  to  be  its  law.  This  latter  position  is  an  obvious 
error, —  one  too  obvious  to  require  refutation.  Any  truly 
ethical  law  must  be  essentially  distinct  from  a  merely  or 
strictly  historical  law. 

I  shall  only  add  that  the  worthy  Abbe'  strangely  says  noth- 
ing about  the  Reformation ;  is  refreshingly  satisfactory  and 
outspoken  for  a  Frenchman  in  regard  to  Louis  XIV. ;  passes 
a  judgment  on  the  Revolution  remarkable  for  the  courage, 
insight,  and  fairness  which  it  displays ;  and  attacks  Buckle, 
Malthus,  and  J.  S.  Mill  too  violently.1 

1  It  seems  desirable  to  mention  at  this  point  the  following  works :  — 

1.  Abbe'  Gabriel,  '  La  vie  et  la  inort  des  nations,'  1837.  Its  chief  thesis  is  that 
the  science,  art,  and  industry  of  the  present  day  tend  of  themselves  only  to  push 
society  to  the  abyss,  and  that  its  salvation  must  come  from  the  love  or  charity 
which  Christ,  the  Church,  and  sacraments  inspire  or  convey.  It  is  the  work  of 
a  pious  mystic,  and  written  not  without  eloquence,  but  is  hazy  and  uninstructive. 

2.  Abbe  Frere,  '  Principes  de  la  philosophie  de  l'histoire,'  1838.    Worthless. 

3.  Baron  A.  Guiraud,  '  Philosophie  catholique  de  l'histoire,'  1839.  The  author 
acquired  some  fame  as  a  poet,  and  was  a  member  of  the  French  Academy,  but 
the  book  named  is  of  a  positively  ludicrous  character,  dealing  only  with  such 
subjects  as  the  two  principles  of  good  and  evil,  creation,  universal  soul,  state  of 
man  before  sin,  alimentation  and  multiplication  of  men  before  sin,  and  various 
unprofitable  questions  unfortunately  suggested  by  the  first  chapter  of  Genesis  to 
an  over  imaginative  mind. 

4.  Abbe"  L.  Leroy,  '  Le  regne  de  Dieu  dans  la  grandeur,  la  mission  et  la  chute 
des  empires,  ou  Philosophie  de  l'histoire  consideree  au  point  de  vue  divin,'  1889. 
This  book  I  have  not  seen.     It  is  unfavourably  noticed  by  Rougemont,  t.  ii.  482. 

5.  L.  Lacroix,  '  Dix  ahs  d'enseignement  historique  a  le  Faculty  des  lettres  de 
Nancy,'  1865.  This  is  a  collection  of  "  opening  discourses."  Their  subjects  are 
respectively — the  union  of  religion  and  science;  the  law  of  history;  the  gener- 
ating principle  of  societies ;  Moses  as  historian  and  legislator ;  the  Greeks  and 
Persians  — the  Medic  wars;  Rome,  the  Empire,  and  the  Church;  Christianity 
and  Islamism  ;  and  the  dynastic  revolutions  of  France.  They  are  the  produc- 
tions of  a  cultured  and  scholarly  mind,  and  present  attractively  a  general  view 
of  the  course  of  history  as  seen  from  the  standpoint  of  Liberal  Catholicism ;  but 
they  fathom  no  depths  and  solve  no  difficulties. 

6.  Pere  Felix,  '  Le  Progres  par  le  Christianisme.  Conferences  de  Notre-Dame 
de  Paris,  1856-64.'  These  discourses  are  eloquent,  but  devoid  of  philosophical 
or  historical  value. 


CHAPTER  VII 


THE   SOCIALISTIC    SCHOOLS 


I  have  now  to  consider  the  historical  theories  of  a  class  of 
thinkers  who  felt  as  deeply  as  those  treated  of  in  the  preced- 
ing chapter  that  society  was  grievously  diseased  and  disor- 
ganised, but  who  held  very  different  views  both  as  to  the 
character  and  causes  of  the  evil  and  as  to  what  would  be  the 
appropriate  remedy.  Instead  of  being,  like  the  theocratic 
absolutists,  wholly  hostile  to  the  Revolution,  they  largely 
accepted  its  ideas  and  continued  its  spirit.  Equality  and 
fraternity,  in  particular,  they  regarded  as  the  highest  and 
most  sacred  truths,  the  latest  and  noblest  births  of  time. 
And  far  from  looking,  as  even  the  Catholic  Liberals  did,  to 
the  Church  for  inspiration  and  guidance,  they  believed  that 
it  had  long  ceased  to  be  a  life-giving  and  socially  beneficent 
institution.  All  the  powers  of  the  past,  they  thought,  had 
been  proved  incapable  of  regenerating  society,  of  raising  the 
masses,  of  extinguishing  injustice  and  misery;  and  so  a  new 
way  must  be  attempted  — ■  reorganisation  from  the  veiy  foun- 
dations, and  not  merely  some  reform  of  religion  or  philosophy, 
of  this  institution  or  of  that,  which  would  leave  the  world 
much  the  same  as  before.  It  was  also  essential,  these  thinkers 
believed,  to  carry  out  this  attempt  in  a  direct  way.  It  seemed 
to  them  very  unfortunate  that  religion  in  its  various  forms 
had  either  entirely  despaired  of  society,  and  aimed  only  at 
the  salvation  of  individuals,  or  had  assumed  that  society 
could  only  be  saved,  regenerated,  through  the  salvation, 
regeneration,  of  individuals.  Even  the  latter  view,  they 
said,  is  just  the  reverse  of  the  truth.  We  must  seek  to  regen- 
erate individuals  through  the  regeneration  of  society,  by  the 
establishment  of  new  social  arrangements  and  institutions; 
394 


SAINT-SIMON  395 

and  as  an  essential  condition  we  must  persuade  men  to  fix 
their  eyes  on  a  goal,  not  beyond  the  earth,  but  on  it;  and  to 
regard  religion,  like  everything  else,  as  of  value  only  in  so 
far  as  it  guides  society  to  the  great  object  of  ameliorating  the 
condition  of  the  class  the  most  numerous  and  poor.  It  was 
thus  that  Claude  Henri  de  Saint-Simon  and  Francois  Marie 
Charles  Fourier,  the  founders  of  modern  socialism,  were  led 
to  their  peculiar  speculations.  These  speculations,  of  course, 
only  concern  us  here  so  far  as  they  have  history  for  their 
subject.1 

Saint-Simon  was  born  in  1760.  He  belonged  to  a  family 
which  professed  to  be  descended  from  Charlemagne,  and 
claimed  to  be  better  entitled  to  the  throne  of  France  than  the 
Bourbons.  He  had,  however,  no  aristocratic  prejudices,  or 
family  pride,  and  was  even  deficient  in  self-respect.  Relig- 
ion had  a  slight  hold  on  him,  and  his  morality  was  lax. 
But  he  was  generous  and  benevolent,  athirst  for  glory,  and 
from  youth  to  old  age  resolutely  bent  on  doing  great  things 
for  mankind.  He  wandered  in  many  lands,  witnessed  ex- 
traordinary events  in  the  New  World  and  in  the  Old,  made 
acquaintance  with  all  conditions  of  men,  and  had  experience 
of  the  most  varied  phases  of  life  and  of  the  extremes  and 
vicissitudes  of  fortune.  He  acted,  experimented,  and  endured 
much  before  he  undertook  to  teach. 

The  literary  career  of  Saint-Simon  began  in  1803,  and  from 
1807  to  1825  was  characterised  by  uninterrupted  activity. 
From  1807  to  1814,  general  science  was  the  chief  subject  on 
which  his  mind  was  occupied;  from  1814  to  1824,  political 
and  social  organisation;  and  a  new  religion,  "le  nouveau 
Christianisme,"  was  its  latest  product.  He  died  in  1825. 
Of  his  works  those  which  have  most  interest  for  a  student  of 
the  development  of  historical  philosophy  are  the  'Introduction 
aux  Travaux  Scientifiques  du  xixe  sidcle,'  the  'Me"moire  sur 

l  On  the  general  history  of  socialism  in  France  the  following  are  among  the 
best  works  to  consult:  L.  Eeybaud,  'Etudes  sur  les  re'formateurs  contemporains,' 
4"  ed.,  1844;  A.  Sudre,  'Histoire  da  communisme,'  2°  ed.,  1887;  B.  Malon, 
'Histoiredusocialisme,'5  vols,  (the  second  volume) ;  L.  Stein,  'Der  Socialismus 
und  Communismus  des  heutigen  Frankreich,'  2  Aufl.,  1848 ;  K.  Griin,  '  Die 
sociale  Bewegung  in  Frankreich  und  Belgien,'  1845 ;  and  W.  L.  Sargant,  '  Social 
Innovators,'  1858. 


396  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

la  Science  de  l'Homme, '  and  the  'Travail  sur  la  Gravitation 
Universelle. '  They  all  belong  to  what  may  be  conveniently 
designated  the  scientific  period  of  Saint-Simon's  life,  the  first 
having  been  written  and  privately  circulated  in  1807-8, 
although  not,  properly  speaking,  published  till  1832;  and 
the  two  latter  having  been  written  and  privately  circulated 
in  1813  and  1814,  although  not,  properly  speaking,  published 
till  1859.  It  is  also  necessary,  however,  to  have  an  acquain- 
tance with  the  more  important  of  Saint-Simon's  other  writ- 
ings, as  well  as  with  the  celebrated  'Exposition  de  la 
Doctrine  Saint-Simonienne, '  published  in  1832,  and  chiefly 
the  work  of  M.  Bazard.1 

Saint-Simon  had  considerable  power  of  historical  insight 
and  historical  generalisation,  and  abounded  in  ingenious 
views  on  the  course  and  tendencies  of  human  development. 
He  was  a  lavish  sower  of  ideas.  He  was  not,  however,  spe- 
cially qualified  to  cultivate  and  reap  them.  He  had  a  sus- 
ceptible, original,  and  fertile  mind,  but  not  one  whose  habits 
of  thought  were  scientific ;  and  he  seldom  either  adequately- 
verified  or  developed  what  he  had  conceived.  He  was  in 
this  respect  a  contrast  to  M.  Comte,  whose 'distinctive  merits 
lay  much  less  in  wealth  and  originality  of  conception  than  in 
persistent  pursuit  of  scientific  certainty,  and  power  of  elab- 
orate co-ordination  and  construction.  Almost  all  Comte's 
leading  ideas  on  the  philosophy  of  history  may  be  found  more 
or  less  plainly  expressed  in  works  written  and  either  published 
or  privately  circulated  by  Saint-Simon  before  his  acquain- 
tance with  Comte,  which  began    in    1818,   and  came  to  a 

1  All  the  writings  of  Saint-Simon,  although  not  very  numerous,  are  only  to 
be  found  in  the  'CEuvres  de  Saint-Simon  et  d'Enfantin,'  a  publication  begun  in 
1865,  and  now  containing  at  least  40  volumes.  His  principal  works  are  to  be 
found  in  the  two-volumed  edition  of  Hubbard,  1857,  and  the  three-volumed 
edition,  published  at  Brussels  in  1859.  Booth's  '  Saint-Simon  and  Saint-Simon- 
ism,'  1871,  and  Janet's  '  Saint-Simon  et  le  Saint-Simonisme,'  1878,  are  excellent 
studies.  Probably  the  most  instructive  document  on  the  history  of  the  Saint- 
Simonian  school,  from  the  death  of  Saint-Simon  to  its  disruption,  is  the  "  Memoire 
sur  le  Saint-Simonisme,"  by  the  late  M.  H.  Carnot,  published  in  the  Compte- 
Rendu  de  l'Acad.  d.  Sc.  Mor.  et  Pol.,  1887  (7e  and  8"  livraisons).  See  also  the 
account  in  Louis  Blanc's  '  History  of  Ten  Years,'  B.  III.  ch.  3  (E.  T.).  Michelet 
has  some  interesting  pages  on  Saint-Simon  in  his  '  Histoire  du  xix°  siecle.' 
The  most  thorough  treatment  of  his  views  on  history  and  historical  progress 
will  be  found  in  four  articles  of  M.  Renouvier  in  the  'Critique  Philosophique,' 
Anne'e  x. 


SAINT-SIMON  397 

violent  close  in  1824.  The  Saint-Simonian  doctrine,  as  it 
came  to  be  received  in  the  Saint-Simonian  school,  went  far 
beyond  what  Saint-Simon  had  explicitly  taught,  and  much  of 
it,  perhaps,  he  would  have  refused  to  acknowledge. 

It  is  much  easier  to  exaggerate  Saint-Simon's  originality 
than  to  say  precisely  in  what  it  consisted.  It  was  not  origi- 
nality of  the  highest  order.  It  did  not  imply  extraordinary 
power  of  independent,  self-productive  thought,  deep  intel- 
lectual penetration,  or  the  apprehension  even  of  a  single  great 
entirely  unknown  truth.  It  sprang  chiefly  from  openness  of 
mind  to  novel  ideas  of  all  kinds,  and  readiness  to  perceive 
their  bearing  on  social  reorganisation,  the  absorbing  interest 
of  his  life.  He  has  himself  very  candidly  stated  how  much 
he  was  indebted  in  forming  his  system  not  only  to  the  writ- 
ings of  Vicq-d'Azir,  Cabanis,  Bichat,  and  Condorcet,  but  also 
to  the  friendly  instructions  of  Dr.  Burdin,  Dr.  Bougon,  and 
M.  Oelsner.  But  the  loans  acknowledged  made  up  a  very 
large  portion  of  his  whole  intellectual  capital.  It  is  enough 
to  refer  here  only  to  those  of  which  we  should  have  known 
nothing  but  for  his  own  statement.  He  owed  to  Dr.  Burdin 
those  views  as  to  the  nature  of  knowledge,  the  law  of  the 
development  of  thought,  and  the  order  of  the  evolution  of 
the  sciences,  which  Comte  appropriated,  and  made  the  basis 
of  the  system  of  Positivism.1  Dr.  Bougon  removed  his  doubts 
as  to  the  continuity  of  beings.  M.  Oelsner  convinced  him 
that  the  middle  age  was  not  a  period  of  retrogression. 

Saint-Simon  had  the  merit  of  assigning  to  the  science  of 
history  a  clearly  denned  place  in  the  general  system  of  the 
sciences.  The  science  of  history  forms,  according  to  him, 
the  second  part  of  the  science  of  man  —  that  part  which  treats 
of  the  human  species  or  race.  The  first  part  treats  of  man  as 
an  individual  composed  of  body  and  mind,  and  so  comprises 
a  physiological  and  psychological  section.  The  whole  science 
of  man,  however,  is  but  a  part  of  a  more'  comprehensive 
science,  physiology,  which,  as  understood  by  Saint- Simon, 
includes  biology,  psychology,  and  the  science  of  history. 
Mental  action  and  historical  evolution  are  both  regarded  by 

1  See  '  CEuvres  Choisis  de  C.  H.  de  Saint-Simon,'  1859,  t.  ii.  20-35.  The 
'  Me"moire  sur  la  Science  de  l'homme,'  in  which  the  passage  occurs,  was  first 
published  in  1813. 


398  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOBY   IN   PKANCE 

him  as  physiological  functions;  only  the  physiologist  can 
hope  to  study  either  with  success.  M.  Comte,  I  may  here 
remark,  partly  followed  and  partly  abandoned  this  view  of 
Saint-Simon,  merging  psychology  in  physiology,  and  yet 
including  historical  evolution  in  the  separate  and  final  science 
of  sociology.  But  surely  consistency  is  on  the  side  of  the 
earlier  thinker.  If  the  progress  of  the  individual  mind  be 
merely  a  biological  function,  how  can  the  collective  progress 
of  any  number  of  individual  minds  be  an  essentially  different 
sort  of  function,  the  subject  of  a  distinct  and  fundamental 
science  ? 

Physiology  understood  as  stated,  is  further  regarded  by 
Saint-Simon  as  the  last  of  a  series  of  sciences  which  have 
gradually  and  slowly  passed  one  after  another  out  of  a  con- 
jectural and  theological  state  into  a  positive  and  properly 
scientific  state.  The  entire  movement  of  thought  in  history 
is  from  the  one  to  the  other  of  these  states.  The  mind  passes 
through  a  succession  of  religious  phases, —  fetichism,  poly- 
theism, deism, —  and  steadily  substitutes  for  them  in  one 
department  of  inquiry  after  another  those  positive  and  scien- 
tific conceptions,  the  sum  of  which  Saint-Simon  designates 
by  the  word  physicism.  This  law  of  two  states  is  as  funda- 
mental in  the  system  of  Saint-Simon  as  the  more  celebrated 
law  of  three  states  in  that  of  Comte ;  and  the  latter  law  differs 
from  the  former  only  by  the  insertion  between  its  terms  of 
the  metaphysical  state.  M.  Littre"  was  bound  to  have  re- 
membered this  circumstance  when  denying  M.  Hubbard's 
statement  that  the  law  of  three  states  was  borrowed  from 
Saint-Simon.  He  was  correct  when  he  said  that  the  law  of 
three  states  is  not  enunciated  in  any  of  Saint-Simon's  writ- 
ings ;  but  as  there  is  undoubtedly  often  enunciated  and  con- 
stantly implied  a  law  of  two  states,  both  included  in  Comte's 
three,  he  was  quite  mistaken  when  he  affirmed  that  as  to  the 
origination  of  Comte's  historical  conception  Saint-Simon  is 
hors  de  cause.  So  little  is  that  the  case,  that  Comte's  own 
assertion  of  originality  cannot  be  allowed  for  a  moment  to 
weigh  against  the  opposing  texts  and  facts.  Comte  could 
not  but  have  learned  from  Saint-Simon  a  law  of  two  states 
substantially  the  same  as  that  which  has  become  so  closely 


SAINT-SIMON  399 

associated  with  his  own  name ;  one  to  which  he  only  added 
a  term  which  few  even  of  his  disciples  seem  to  think  on  a 
parity  with  the  other  two,  and  which  others  of  them  appear 
not  unwilling  altogether  to  extrude.  Comte  may  have  been 
quite  sincere  in  affirming  the  whole  conception  to  have  been 
his  own;  but  the  affirmation  itself  was  certainly  not  true,  and 
only  showed  how  little  either  his  memory  or  judgment  could, 
after  the  rupture  of  1822,  be  trusted  as  to  his  obligations  to 
his  former  friend  and  master. 

With  the  age  of  Bacon  and  Descartes,  according  to  Saint- 
Simon,  the  day  of  positive  science  began  to  dawn  out  of  the 
night  of  theological  conjecture.  And  first  astronomy,  with 
the  help  of  mathematics,  next  physics,  and  then  chemistry, 
came  under  the  beams  of  the  light;  the  reason  of  this  order 
being  that  the  facts  of  astronomy  are  the  simplest,  and  those 
of  chemistry  the  most  complicated.  Physiology,  more  con- 
crete and  complex  still  than  chemistry,  is  as  yet  partly  con- 
jectural and  partly  positive,  although  on  the  eve  of  becoming 
completely  positive.  When  it  has  done  so  philosophy  itself 
will  attain  to  positivity.  "  For  the  special  sciences  are  the 
elements  of  general  science ;  general  science,  that  is  to  say, 
philosophy,  could  not  but  be  conjectural  so  long  as  the  special 
sciences  were  so ;  was  necessarily  partly  conjectural  and  partly 
positive  when  one  portion  of  the  special  sciences  had  become 
special  while  another  was  still  conjectural,  and  will  be  quite 
positive  when  all  the  special  sciences  are  positive,  which  will 
happen  when  physiology  and  psychology  are  based  on  observed 
and  tested  facts,  as  there  is  no  phenomenon  which  is  not 
astronomical,  chemical,  physiological,  or  psychological.  We 
know,  therefore,  at  what  epoch  the  philosophy  taught  in  the 
schools  will  become  positive."  It  is  only  when  the  sciences 
have  all  become  positive  that  society  can  be  rationally  organ- 
ised; for  religion,  general  politics,  morality,  and  education, 
are  only  applications  of  principles  which  must  be  furnished 
by  science.  Such  is  Saint-Simon's  view  of  philosophy  or 
general  science,  and  of  the  place  occupied  therein  by  the 
science  of  history.  This  view  was  derived  from  Dr.  Burdin, 
and  is  substantially  the  same,  as  I  have  said,  with  that  of 
M.  Comte.     As  it  is  most  explicitly  stated  in  the  'Me"moire 


400  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

sur  la  Science  de  1'  Homme, '  written  five  years  before  the 
commencement  of  Comte's  intercourse  with  Saint-Simon, 
there  is  no  room  for  doubt  that  the  former  received  it  from 
the  latter.  It  is  quite  in  vain  to  say,  as  M.  Littre*  does,  that 
that  work  ought  to  be  regarded  as  non-existent,  seeing  that 
although  written  in  1813  and  sent  to  certain  persons  whose 
names  are  known,  it  was  not  published  till  1859 ;  for,  first, 
the  list  to  which  M.  Littre-  refers  contains  only  the  names  of 
twenty-eight  distinguished  public  men,  leaving  Saint-Simon, 
as  sixty  copies  of  his  book  were  printed,  thirty-two  to  dispose 
of  among  his  personal  friends  and  disciples  at  a  time  when 
these  were  very  few ;  and  further,  the  work  is  incontestable 
evidence  that  Saint-Simon- possessed  certain  ideas  in  1813, 
which  it  is  simply  impossible  to  believe  he  would  not  com- 
municate to  any  person  who  was  on  such  terms  of  intimacy 
with  him  as  Comte  was  some  years  later. 

It  will  be  obvious  from  what  has  been  said  that  Saint- 
Simon  was  aware  of  the  closeness  of  the  connection  between 
the  science  of  history  and  physical  science.  Indeed  he  con- 
ceived of  it  as  far  closer  than  he  was  warranted  to  do.  He 
regarded  the  science  of  history  as  a  physical  science ;  in  other 
words,  refused  to  recognise  the  distinctions  which  exist  be- 
tween the  physical  and  moral  worlds,  or  at  least  that  any  of 
these  distinctions  necessitate  essentialty  different  explana- 
tions of  physical  and  moral  phenomena.  He  had  consequently 
to  attempt  to  bring  physical  law  over  into  the  moral  world, 
and  into  history  a  province  of  the  moral  world.  His  attempt 
was  a  very  curious  one,  and  he  himself  came  to  acknowledge 
that  it  was  unsuccessful.  Fancying  that  the  unity  of  the 
system  of  nature  and  the  unity  of  science  implied  that  there 
was  one  all-pervasive  law  from  which  every  other  law  and  fact 
in  existence  might  be  derived,  he  was  led  by  obvious  and 
superficial  considerations  to  believe  gravitation  that  law,  and 
to  maintain  that  it  accounted  for  chemical  and  biological, 
and  even  mental  and  historical,  phenomena ;  that  gravitation 
was,  in  fact,  the  law  of  the  universe,  of  the  solar  system,  of 
the  earth,  of  man,  of  society,  or,  generally,  of  the  whole  and 
all  its  parts ;  and  that  if  other  laws  had  the  appearance  of 
independence,  it  was  only  because  they  had  not  yet  been 
reduced  under  or  deduced  from  it. 


SAINT-SIMON  401 

The  social  atmosphere  seems  to  have  been  full  of  ideas  of 
this  kind  when  he  wrote.  His  rival  Fourier  was  at  the  same 
time  insisting  with  much  greater  emphasis  that  the  central 
social  law  was  what  he  called  the  law  of  passional  attraction, 
which  he  believed  to  be  a  rigorous  deduction  from  Newton's 
law;  and  M.  Azais,  with  copious  speech  and  too  facile  pen, 
was  explaining  everything  in  the  material,  mental,  and  social 
worlds  by  expansion.  Of  course,  all  these  attempts  at  uni- 
versal explanation  must  be  regarded  as  utter  failures.  No 
explanation  of  the  kind  aimed  at  has  yet  been  reached  even 
for  the  physical  world,  and  there  seem  to  be  no  good  reasons 
for  supposing  that  any  such  explanation  ever  will  be  reached. 
Far  less  likely  is  it,  however,  that  the  mind  will  ever  attain 
to  a  unity  so  absolute  that  it  will  account  at  once  for  all  the 
phenomena  of  matter  and  of  spirit,  which  have  so  little  in 
common  and  so  much  in  contrast.  To  establish  that  the  law 
which  regulates  the  motions  of  material  masses  is  likewise 
that  which  reigns  in  the  reason,  conscience,  affections,  and 
will  of  man,  and  which  determines  their  evolution  in  history, 
must  be  regarded  as  a  task  far  surpassing  in  difficulty  any 
achieved  by  Newton ;  and  it  may  safely  be  said  that  neither 
Saint-Simon,  nor  Fourier,  nor  Azais  has  given  us  anything 
designed  to  that  end  which  has  even  the  semblance  of  long- 
sustained  reasoning  and  profound  truth.  They  had,  indeed, 
no  better  reason  for  their  transference  of  physical  law  into 
the  spiritual  world  than  the  existence  of  those  analogies 
between  the  physical  and  the  spiritual  the  recognition  of 
which  is  the  source  of  metaphorical  language.  To  talk  of  the 
gravitation  or  attraction,  or  expansion  of  the  thoughts  or 
feelings  of  the  individual,  or  of  the  successive  or  coexistent 
states  of  society,  is  purely  such  language;  and  the  whole 
argumentation  of  those  who  maintain  spiritual  fact  and  law 
to  be  reducible  to  material  fact  is  a  process  in  which  they 
cheat  their  minds  by  understanding  figurative  speech  literally. 

Serious  as  Saint-Simon's  error  was,  it  is  not,  as  M.  Littre" 
maintained,  conclusive  against  his  claims  to  be  ranked  among 
positivists.  It  has  nothing  to  do  with  that  claim,  but  is 
simply  a  case  of  false  explanation  of  phenomena.  It  differs 
from  Comte's  own  reduction  of  psychology  under  biology  only 
in  degree ;  it  is  a  greater  error,  but  the  same  sort  of  error. 


402  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

As  it  does  not  proceed  on  the  assumption  that  the  mind  can 
know  anything  beyond  phenomena  and  their  laws,  it  cannot 
be  pronounced,  on  the  mere  ground  of  falsity,  inconsistent 
with  positive  philosophy.  It  must  be  further  remarked  that 
Saint-Simon  does  not  appear  to  have  promulgated  the  idea  in 
any  of  his  works  written  subsequently  to  1814,  and  that  he 
stated  to  M.  Olinde  Rodrigues  that  he  had  found  reason  to 
abandon  it. 

In  the  judgment  of  Saint-Simon,  Vicq-d'Azir,  Cabanis, 
Bichat,  and  Condorcet  were  those  among  his  immediate  pre- 
decessors who  had  advanced  most  the  science  of  man;  and 
Condorcet  he  regarded  as  the  person  who  had  done  most  for 
that  part  of  the  science  of  man  which  is  conversant  with  his- 
tory. He  took,  in  fact,  precisely  the  same  view  of  the  spec- 
ulations in  Condorcet's  'Esquisse'  and  of  the  relation  of  his 
own  speculations  to  them  which  we  find  subsequently  taken 
and  expressed  by  Comte  in  both  of  his  great  works ;  that  is 
to  say,  while  censuring  the  exaggerations,  the  prejudices, 
the  manifold  errors  of  omission  and  commission  with  which 
the  book  abounds,  he  accepted  its  leading  principles,  that 
man  must  be  studied  as  a  species  no  less  than  as  an  individ- 
ual; that  generations  are  so  bound  to  generations  that  the 
species  is  progressive  and  perfectible;  that  human  develop- 
ment is  subject  to  law  and  passes  through  a  series  of  phases ; 
and  that  from  the  past  the  future  may  be  so  far  foreseen,  as 
true  and  fundamental,  as  requiring  only  development  and  a 
more  careful  application.  He  professed  to  do  no  more  than 
to  build  on  the  foundation  constituted  by  these  principles. 

The  idea  which  Condorcet  merely  incidentally  expresses, 
that  "  the  progress  of  society  is  subject  to  the  same  general 
laws  observable  in  the  individual  development  of  our  facul- 
ties, being  the  result  of  that  very  development  considered  at 
once  in  a  great  number  of  individuals,"  seems  to  me  the  cen- 
tral principle  of  the  Saint-Simonian  philosophy  of  history. 
"  General  intelligence  and  individual  intelligence  are  devel- 
oped according  to  the  same  law.  These  two  phenomena  differ 
only  as  regards  the  size  of  the  scales  on  which  they  have  been 
constructed."  This  being  his  guiding  thought,  Saint-Simon 
naturally  compares,  as  so  many  others  have  done,  the  periods 
of  human  life  to  the  stadia  of  history.     A  fondness  for  build- 


SAINT-SIMON  403 

ing,  digging,  using  tools,  seems  to  him  distinctive  of  child- 
hood in  the  individual,  and  of  the  Egyptians  in  the  race ;  a 
love  of  music,  painting,  and  poetay,  of  youth  from  puberty  to 
twenty-five,  and  of  the  Greeks ;  military  ambition,  of  most 
men  from  that  age  till  they  are  forty-five,  and  of  the  Romans 
among  nations;  while  at  forty-five  the  active  forces  of  the 
individual  begin  to  diminish,  but  his  intellectual  forces, 
imagination  excepted,  to  increase,  or  at  least  to  be  better 
employed  —  and  to  this  age  corresponds  the  era  of  humanity 
inaugurated  by  the  Saracens,  to  whom  we  are  indebted  for 
algebra,  chemistry,  physiology,  &c.  The  race  is  now  about 
the  middle  of  its  allotted  course,  or  at  that  epoch  when  the 
human  mind  is  in  fullest  possession  both  of  imagination  and 
reason.  Our  predecessors  had,  relatively  to  reason,  too  much 
imagination,  and  our  descendants  will  have  too  little.  A 
year  of  individual  life  probably  answers  to  about  two  cen- 
'  turies  in  that  of  the  species.  It  was  thus  that  our  author 
worked  out  a  parallelism  which  is  too  fanciful  to  require 
criticism.  But  his  principle  led  him  to  other  thoughts  which, 
whether  true  or  not,  are  at  least  suggestive. 

One  of  these  is  the  doctrine  of  an  ever-recurring  alternation 
of  organic  and  critical  periods  in  history.  It  is  constantly 
implied,  and  often  partially  stated  by  Saint-Simon ;  but  its 
clearest  expression  is  due  to  Bazard,  who  in  this  as  in  sev- 
eral other  instances,  has  expounded  his  master's  thought 
better  than  he  succeeded  in  doing  himself.  The  doctrine  is 
to  this  effect.  The  human  spirit  manifests  its  rational  activ- 
ity in  analysis  and  synthesis,  in  ascending  from  particulars 
to  generals,  and  in  descending  from  generals  to  particulars. 
These  are  the  two  directions  either  of  which  it  may,  and  one 
of  which  it  must,  take  when  it  reasons;  and  upward  and 
downward,  an  a  posteriori  and  a  priori  direction.  The  gen- 
eral process  inclusive  of  both,  Saint-Simon  proposed  should 
be  designated  by  the  rather  extraordinary  name  of  the  Des- 
cartes. The  twofold  procedure  of  reason  is  not  confined  to 
the  individual  mind,  but  regulates  the  development  of  the 
race  as  a  whole.  Societies,  like  individuals,  employ  some- 
times analysis  and  sometimes  synthesis ;  and  this  determines 
whether  the  epoch  which  they  pass  through  will  be  critical 
or  organic.     All  history  may  be  divided  into  critical  periods 


404  PHILOSOPHY    OF    HISTOBY   IN"   FRANCE 

and  organic  periods.  The  critical  periods  are  those  in  which 
the  minds  of  men  are  employed  in  investigating  the  principles 
of  the  government  under  which  they  live,  in  endeavouring 
to  amend  old  institutions  and  to  invent  new  ones ;  in  which 
no  creed  commands  the  assent  of  all,  so  that  society  is  without 
principles,  discontented,  changeful,  and,  in  a  word,  in  a  state 
of  anarchy.  Organic  periods,  on  the  contrary,  are  those  which 
possess  an  accepted  doctrine,  in  which  society  is  cemented  by 
the  synthesis  of  a  common  faith,  in  which  the  actual  institu- 
tions give  satisfaction  to  the  world,  and  men's  minds  are  at 
rest.  Thus  pre-Socratic  Greece  was  organic  —  post-Socratic 
Greece,  critical.  Roman  history  began  to  pass  from  organic 
to  critical  with  Lucretius  and  Cicero.  With  the  definite 
constitution  of  the  Christian  Church  in  the  sixth  century 
began  the  new  organic  period  of  feudalism;  and  in  the  six- 
teenth century  the  Reformers  inaugurated  another  critical 
period  which  the  philosophers  have  continued  until  the  pres- ' 
ent  time,  when  the  great  want  of  society  is  not  more  analysis, 
not  the  continuance  of  criticism,  but  a  new  synthesis,  a  new 
doctrine. 

The  correspondence  between  individual  and  social  develop- 
ment suggested  likewise  to  Saint-Simon  a  mode  of  giving 
increased  extension  and  precision  to  the  idea  of  progress  or 
perfectibility  which  Condorcet  had  insisted  on.  It  seemed 
to  him  that  that  idea  had  hitherto  been  barren,  because  there 
had  been  no  vigorous  attempt  in  presence  of  a  vast  variety  of 
the  facts  of  history  to  co-ordinate  them  into  homogeneous 
series  with  the  terms  so  connected  as  to  manifest  laws  of 
increase  or  decrease.  All  the  facts  of  history,  such  as 
equality,  liberty,  authority,  war,  industry,  could  be,  he 
thought,  thus  ranged,  so  as  to  show  regular  growth  or  deca- 
dence in  the  past,  and  such  as  might  therefore  be  anticipated 
in  the  future.  Hence,  besides  the  classification  of  the  facts 
of  history  into  critical  and  organic,  he  endeavours  to  exhibit 
three  great  subordinate  or  auxiliary  series,  answering  to  the 
three  great  phases  of  human  nature.  In  that  nature  there  are 
intelligence,  sentiment,  and  physical  activity.  The  products 
of  intelligence  are  the  sciences ;  of  sentiment,  religion  and  the 
fine  arts ;  of  physical  activity,  industry.  Saint-Simon  tries 
to  form  serial  co-ordinations  of  these  products  in  order  to  find 


SAINT-SIMON  405 

the  laws  of  development  of  the  principles  which  have  origi- 
nated them,  and  imagines  that  here  too  he  discovers  an  alter- 
native movement  of  analysis  and  synthesis,  of  the  a  posteriori 
and  a  priori  method. 

He  makes  another  important  use  of  the  series  when  he 
attempts  to  arrange  the  various  societies  on  the  earth  in  a 
scale  graduated  according  to  their  mental  development.  He 
points  out  that  every  degree  of  culture  from  the  lowest  bar- 
harism  to  the  highest  civilisation  is  represented  somewhere ; 
and  on  this  principle  describes  what  he  considers  the  different 
stages  or  terms.  The  lowest  he  illustrates  by  the  state  of 
the  savage  of  Aveyron  at  the  time  of  his  capture ;  the  second 
by  the  savages  of  Magellan  Straits,  without  fire,  without 
houses,  or  chiefs ;  the  third  by  some  tribes  on  the  north-west 
coast  of  America,  unable  to  count  beyond  three,  and  with  the 
merest  rudiments  of  a  language  and  chieftainship ;  the  fourth 
by  the  cannibal  New  Zealanders ;  the  fifth  by  the  inhabitants 
of  the  Friendly  Society  and  Sandwich  Islands ;  the  sixth  by 
the  Peruvians  and  Mexicans  as  discovered  by  the  Spaniards ; 
the  seventh  by  the  Egyptians ;  after  whom  the  series  becomes 
chronological  or  strictly  historical,  its  eighth  term  being  the 
Greeks;  its  ninth,  the  Romans;  its  tenth,  the  Saracens;  its 
eleventh,  European  society  founded  by  Charlemagne ;  and  the 
twelfth,  that  which  is  rising  on  its  ruins. 

A  general  glance  at  this  scale  or  series,  and  still  more  a 
close  study  of  the  fifty  pages  devoted  to  its  consideration, 
will  disclose  many  defects.  Some  of  them,  however,  were 
inevitable  in  the  wretched  condition  in  which  ethnologjr  was 
half  a  century  ago;  and  had  they  been  even  more  numerous, 
they  would  not  have  annulled  the  merits  of  the  general  con- 
ception and  of  the  attempt  to  realise  it ;  a  conception  on  which 
well-known  and  very  able  works  have  since  been  based,  and 
on  which  many  other  works,  we  may  safely  say,  will  be  based; 
a  conception  which  so  links  together  ethnology  and  history  as 
to  allow  of  their  giving  full  assistance  to  each  other.  The 
greatest  error  into  which  Saint-Simon  fell  in  connection  with 
it  seems  to  me  to  have  been  his  making  it  the  expression  of 
an  hypothesis,  instead  of  regarding  it  simply  as  a  mode  of 
arranging  facts  in  such  a  way  as  might  be  hoped  would  event- 
ually lead  to  the  scientific  proof  of  a  theory.     He  assumed 


406  PHILOSOPHY    OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

that  the  lowest  stage  of  culture  was  representative  of  the 
oldest;  that  man  made  his  first  appearance  on  earth  as  a 
speechless  and  disgusting  brute,  and  gained  his  present 
height  of  attainment  step  by  step.  It  may  be  so ;  but  that 
assumption  is  one  thing,  and  the  series  itself  is  another. 
And  it  cannot  be  regarded  as  otherwise  than  in  the  main  a 
misfortune  that  the  ruder  races  of  mankind  have  been  studied 
even  by  ethnologists  with  undue  reference  to  the  question, 
whether  or  not  barbarous  peoples  can  civilise  themselves. 
Theological  prepossessions  of  an  opposite  character  have  led 
some  to  affirm  and  others  to  deny  that  they  can,  with  an 
emphasis  and  assurance  out  of  all  proportion  to  the  evidence  ; 
and,  in  the  case  of  most  of  those  who  claim  to  speak  merely 
in  the  name  of  science,  with  a  singular  forgetfulness  that  its 
first  duty  must  be  to  collect  and  analyse  all  that  is  to  be 
learned  regarding  the  ruder  tribes  of  the  world,  and  its  next 
to  endeavour  without  prejudice  to  ascertain  what  are  the 
various  stages  of  social  elevation  or  degradation,  and  what 
the  laws  of  transition  from  the  one  to  the  other;  and  that 
only  through  the  accomplishment  of  these  two  duties  can  it 
hope  successfully  to  solve  the  problem  of  the  origin  of  civili- 
sation. 

Naturally  it  was  the  future  of  civilisation  which  interested 
Saint-Simon  most.  Naturally,  also,  his  views  as  to  the  future 
were  optimistic.  The  true  "age  of  gold,"  he  taught,  was 
not  in  the  past,  where  a  blind  tradition  had  placed  it,  but  in 
Z1  the  future.  The  reign  of  happiness  was  at  hand.  It  would 
give  full  satisfaction  to  all  the  wants  of  that  "flesh"  which 
Christianity  and  the  Church  had  so  mischievously  sought  to 
repress  and  crucify.  With  the  true  organisation  of  society 
there  would  be  a  rehabilitation  of  the  flesh  and  a  fuller  ap- 
preciation of  material  enjoyment.  It  is  with  a  view  to  the 
requirements  of  industry  and  to  the  attainment  of  earthly 
happiness  that  the  whole  process  of  organising  society  is  to 
be  effectuated.  Theocracy  and  feudalism,  the  ages  of  faith 
and  of  force,  of  the  priest  and  the  warrior,  have  irrevocably 
gone.  The  age  of  industrialism,  of  labour,  of  "the  exploita- 
tion of  the  globe  by  association,"  has  definitively  come. 
Henceforth  society  must  act  on  the  axiom  that  "as  industry 
does  all  things,  all  is  to  be  done  for  industry."     Industry 


SAINT-SIMON  407 

must  be  the  subject  of  administration,  and  those  who  govern 
society  ought  to   be   those   most  competent  to  administer 
industry,  to  act  as  the  officers  of  the  vast  army  of  labour  in 
which  every  citizen  should  be  assigned  his  place.     His  views 
as  to  the  character  and  composition  of  the  regulative  and 
administrative  body  passed  through  various   modifications, 
but  in  no  form  did  they  show  any  trace  of  a  demagogic  or 
revolutionary  spirit,  or  even  any  aversion  to  absolutism  or 
despotism  provided  it  succeeded  in  realising  desirable  ends. 
He   was   evolutionist  and  anti-revolutionist;  a  believer  in 
order  and  authority,  but  not  in  personal  rights  or  liberties. 
These  last  seemed  to  him  merely  metaphysical  abstractions. 
He  recognised  the  permanent  need  of  religion  as  a  social 
force.     But  he  had  no  belief  in  it,  or  appreciation  of  it,   as 
anything  more;  and,   in  fact,  he  meant  by  religion  simply 
philanthropy.      His    'Nouveau    Christianisme'    contains    no 
theology,  and  but  one  doctrine  —  namely,  that  "all  should 
labour  for  the  material,  moral,  and  intellectual  development 
of  the  class  the  poorest  and  most  numerous."     Catholicism 
and  Protestantism  are  represented  as  effete  and  injurious, 
because  they  forget  practice  in  speculation,  and  insist  on  more 
than  that  men  should  regard  themselves  and  labour  to  the 
utmost  for  their  common  happiness.     Conduct,   individual 
and  social,  philanthropically  directed,  is,  according  to  Saint- 
Simon,  the  destined  religion  of  the  future,   the  result  and 
goal  of  all  the  religions  of  the  past.     In  setting  forth  this 
"religion  "  in  the  latest  work  which  he  wrote,  he  did  not,  as 
has  often  been  alleged,  break  with  his  own  past,  and  take  up 
a  different  attitude  towards  religion.     In  the  first  of  his 
writings  he  is  found  applying  the  word  "religion  "  so  as  to 
give  a  sentimental  sanction  and  colouring  to  his  proposals 
for  social  reconstruction.     In  the  last  of  them  he  employed  it 
no'  otherwise.     In  commending  religion  he  always  used  the 
term  in  a  merely  rhetorical  or  metaphorical  manner,  not  in  its 
proper  signification.     It  was  probably  from  inattention  to 
this,  that  the  'Nouveau  Christianisme'  was  not  only  supposed 
to  contain  what  it  did  not,  religious  doctrine  in  the  ordinary 
sense  of  the  phrase,  but  that  a  suspicion  was  entertained  that 
the  Saint-Simonians  had  forged  the  work  and  published  it  in 
their  master's  name.     Wronski  told  M.  Rougemont  in  1831 


408  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

that  such  was  the  case;  and  the  latter  accepted  the  account.1 
There  can  be  no  reasonable  doubt,  however,  that  M.  Wronski 
had  been  misled.  The  direct  testimony  to  Saint-Simon's 
authorship  is  clear  and  decisive;  and  there  is  nothing  which 
really  renders  it  suspicious  in  the  contents  of  the  work. 

The  opinions  of  Saint-Simon  on  particular  events  and 
institutions  of  history,  on  individual  personages  and  various 
periods  and  nations,  always  show  independence,  and  often 
insight.  At  the  same  time  they  are  not  infrequently  vitiated 
by  prejudice,  and  are  perhaps  rarely  based  on  adequate 
research.  These  opinions,  however,  time  and  space  forbid 
my  examining. 

Charles  Fourier  was  born  in  1772,  twelve  years  after  Saint- 
Simon.  From  early  youth  to  the  age  of  sixty  he  was  engaged 
in  commerce,  although  he  had  the  greatest  repugnance  to  this 
mode  of  life,  owing  to  the  dishonesty  practised  in  it.  His 
works  are  the  'Theorie  des  quatre  mouvements,'  published 
in  1808,  the  'Association  domestique  agricole,'  published  in 
1822,  the  '  Nouveau  monde  industriel  et  societaire,'  published 
in  1829,  and  the  '  Fausse  industrie,'  published  in  1835.  Of 
these  works  the  first  contains  in  outline  or  germ  the  author's 
whole  system,  the  second  is  the  most  comprehensive  and  devel- 
oped account  of  it,  the  third  is  its  clearest  and  most  sensible 
exposition,  and  the  last  is  merely  an  application  of  it  and 
comparatively  to  the  others  of  little  importance.  Fourier 
died  in  1837.2 

Although  his  moral  creed  was  in  various  respects  objection- 

1  Rougemont,  '  Deux  Cites,'  ii.  439. 

4  Numerous  papers  of  Fourier  were  published  posthumously  in  '  La  Phalange.' 
Some  of  them  were  collected  under  the  title,  of  '  Mannscrits  de  Fourier.'  A  selec- 
tion of  them  was  translated  by  J.  R.  Morell,  and  edited,  with  notes,  biography, 
and  introduction,  by  Hugh  Doherty.  This  is  the  work  entitled  '  The  Passions-of 
the  Human  Soul,'  1851.  On  Fourier  and  his  system,  the  following  works  can  be 
recommended :  Dr.  C.  Pellarin,  '  Fourier—  sa  vie  et  sa  theorie,'  1"  ed.  1839,  5"  ed. 
1871 ;  H.  Renaud,  '  Solidarite,  vue  synthetique  sur  la  doctrine  de  Fourier,'  several 
editions ;  Victor  Considerant's  '  Destinee  sociale,'  1836-38 ;  P.  Janet,  '  Socialisme 
au  xixe  siecle  —  Charles  Fourier'  ('Rev.  d.  Deux  Mondes,'  1879);  A.  Brisbane, 
'Social  Destiny  of  Man,'  1840;  and  A.  Bebel,  'Charles  Fourier,  sein  Leben  und 
seine  Theorien,'  1888.  The  Fourierist  philosophy  of  history  was,  perhaps,  best 
developed  by  Fourier's  earliest  disciple,  Just  Muiron  (Virtomnius) ,  '  Transactions 
Sociales,'  2'  ed.  1860.  It  has  been  expounded  and  criticised  with  thoroughness  and 
impartiality  by  M.  Renouvier  ('  Grit.  Phil.,'  Annee  xii.). 


FOURIER  409 

able,  and  even  monstrous,  his  personal  conduct  was  strictly 
honourable.  He  was  disinterested  and  benevolent  to  a  rare 
degree.  He  had  a  more  original  and  a  far  more  ingenious  and 
powerful  mind  than  Saint-Simon,  to  whom  he' was  not  in  any 
way  indebted  for  his  ideas.  Whereas  Saint-Simon  did  little 
more  than  throw  out  general  views  and  vague  suggestions, 
Fourier  elaborated  a  vast  and  complicated  system,  and  dwelt 
with  even  ridiculous  minuteness  on  details.  Everywhere  in 
the  universe  and  throughout  society  he  fancied  that  he  saw 
definite  mathematical  relations  and  subtle  analogies.  His 
imagination  was  strong  and  exuberant  but  unchastened 
and  unregulated.  He  was  a  keen  critic  and  a  formidable 
polemic.  Shrewd  observations  and  sensible  practical  sug- 
gestions abound  in  his  writings  amongst  innumerable  absurd- 
ities. He  fully  respected  liberty,  and  made  no  appeal  to 
authority  either  for  the  establishment  or  support  of  his 
system.  Compulsion  is  not  to  be  employed  even  in  the 
nurseries  of  the  new  societary  world.  Attraction  is  to  do 
all.  He  was  logically  more  of  an  anarchist  than  a  socialist, 
but  can  only  properly  be  called  a  Fourierist.  He  hated  the 
French  Revolution ;  its  oracles  Voltaire  and  Rousseau ;  its 
leaders,  and  especially  Robespierre  and  his  abettors ;  and  its 
methods.  He  had  the  utmost  confidence  in  his  own  wisdom, 
and  in  the  importance  of  his  message  to  mankind.  He  started 
in  the  formation  of  his  system  with  what  he  calls  the  doute 
absolu,  —  i.e.,  the  conviction  that  the  social  world  as  at  pres- 
ent constituted  is  throughout  a  violation  and  reversal  of  the 
laws  of  nature  and  of  God;  and  the  Scart  absolu,  —  i.e.,  the 
adoption  of  an  entirely  original  procedure,  unlike  any  which 
had  hitherto  been  attempted.  We  may  learn  from  his  own 
words  how  he  thought  he  had  succeeded :  "  I  have  done  what 
a  thousand  others  might  have  done  before  me ;  but  I  have 
marched  to  the  goal,  alone,  without  acquired  means,  without 
beaten  paths.  Alone  I  have  put  to  confusion  twenty  centu- 
ries of  political  imbecility ;  and  it  is  to  me  alone  that  the  pres- 
ent and  future  generations  will  owe  the  initiative  of  their 
immense  happiness.  Before  me,  humanity  has  lost  several 
thousands  of  years  in  foolishly  struggling  against  nature ;  I, 
the  first  have  bowed  before  her  in  studying  attraction,  the 
organ  of  her  decrees ;  she  has  deigned  to  smile  on  the  only 


410  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

mortal  who  has  offered  her  incense  ;  she  has  given  up  to  him 
all  her  treasures.  Possessor  of  the  book  of  destinies,  I  come 
to  dissipate  political  and  moral  darkness,  and  on  the  ruins  of 
the  uncertain  sciences  I  raise  the  theory  of  universal  har- 
mony." Charles  Griin  and  others  have  called  Fourier  "the 
Hegel  of  France."  The  title  seems  to  me  unjust  to  Hegel. 
Fourier  would  have  deemed  it  the  reverse  of  a  compliment  to 
himself,  as  he  had  a  supreme  contempt  for  all  who,  like  Hegel, 
were  professors  of  les  sciences  incertaines,  ■ —  metaphysical, 
moral,  or  political.  He  resembled  Swedenborg  much  more 
than  Hegel.  He  had  the  same  materialistic  and  figurate 
style  of  thinking ;  the  same  kind  of  faith  in  universal  anal- 
ogy ;  and  the  same  sort  of  tendency  to  trace  correspondences 
between  the  most  heterogeneous  things.  The  character  of 
their  systematisation  and  the  cast  of  their  imaginations  were 
not  unlike. .  And,  I  must  candidly  avow,  they  seem  to  me  to 
have  resembled  each  other  in  the  want  of  full  mental  sanity. 
As  in  the  case  of  Swedenborg,  I  can  find  no  other  explana- 
tion of  much  that  he  wrote  than  a  strange  and  subtle  sort 
of  hallucination,  an  insane  belief  as  to  what  was  done  in  the 
world  of  spirits,  coexisting  with  great  general  strength  of 
mind  and  great  religious  discernment ;  so  in  that  of  Fourier, 
while  admitting  his  ability  and  perspicacit}r  in  certain  direc- 
tions, I  cannot  but  consider  him  to  have  been  under  the  sway 
of  a  deranged  imagination,  and  an  insane  belief  in  wonderful 
things  soon  to  happen  on  the  earth.  This  is  surely  not  an 
unfair  judgment  to  pass  on  a  man  who  believed  that  the  world 
was  to  be  improved  until  the  ocean  should  be  lemonade,  zebras 
as  much  used  as  horses,  and  herds  of  llamas  as  common  as 
flocks  of*  sheep  ;  until  men  should  live  three  or  four  hundred 
years,  and  there  should  be  on  the  globe  thirty-seven  millions 
of  poets  equal  to  Homer,  thirty-seven  millions  of  philoso- 
phers equal  to  Newton,  and  thirty-seven  millions  of  writers 
to  Moli&re. 

The  historical  speculations  of  Fourier  are  connected  with 
his  cosmogonical  speculations,  but  not  indissolubly.  He  him- 
self admitted  that  the  latter  were  neither  proved  nor  capable 
of  proof,  and  left  his  disciples  free  to  accept  or  reject  them. 
It  is  not  wonderful  that  they  should  have  generally  elected 


FOURIER  411 

to  reject  them,  and,  indeed,  should  have  said  very  little 
regarding  them.  Fourier's  cosmogony  is,  for  the  most  part, 
indescribably  absurd,  proceeding  on  the  supposition  that  the 
stars  are  animated,  sentient,  and  voluntary  beings,  who  pro- 
create their  own  species  and  exercise  their  generative  powers 
in  the  production  of  minerals,  plants,  and  animals ;  and  on 
other  assumptions  of  a  like  nature.  It  is  as  fantastic  as  the 
wildest  cosmogonical  dream  of  the  Hindu  mind.  At  the  same 
time,  it  is  not  wholly  without  coherence,  suggestive  views,  and 
thoughts  which  future  science  may  in  some  measure  confirm. 

The  theology  of  Fourier  is  also  connected,  and  very  inti- 
mately connected,  with  his  doctrine  of  human  destiny  and 
development  and  his  system  of  social  organisation.  He  was 
very  hostile  to  atheism  and  materialism ;  a  most  severe  judge 
of  what  he  regarded  as  the  irreligiousness  of  Owen  and  Saint- 
Simon  ;  and  not  merely  a  theist,  but,  in  his  own  opinion,  a 
good,  if  not  the  only  good,  Catholic.  It  is  obvious,  however, 
that  his  theology  was  not  the  root  of  his  sociology  but  a 
growth  from  it ;  not  a  primary  but  a  secondary  formation. 
It  was  what  it  was  because  his  views  of  men  and  of  society 
required  that  it  should  be  so.  He  conformed  his  idea  of  God 
to  the  requirements  of  his  social  theory,  and  then  argued  that 
his  social  theory  must  be  correct  because  it  was  implied  in 
his  idea  of  God. 

The  corner-stone  of  his  whole  system  is  a  curious  psychol- 
ogy, which,  though  essentially  erroneous,  is  not  unmixed 
with  important  truths.  He  claims  to  have  found  the  fun- 
damental law  of  society,  —  that  which  explains  its  past  and 
enables  us  to  foresee  its  future,  —  in  the  nature  and  workings 
of  the  passions,  which  he  reduces  to  twelve  primitive  ten- 
dencies, the  sources  of  all  action,  progress,  and  enjoyment. 
The  first  five  are  the  sensitive,  and  have  the  senses  for  organs 
and  stimulation  to  industry  for  function.  The  next  four 
consist  of  love,  friendship,  ambition,  and  familism,  which 
originate  the  smaller  social  groups  and  the  virtues  which  find 
therein  appropriate  exercise.  The  final  three  are  the  butter- 
fiyish  (papillonne),  or  craving  for  change,  the  spirit  of  party 
(passion  calaliste),  and  the  enthusiasm  caused  by  the  simul- 
taneous enjoyment  of  many  sensuous  and  mental  pleasures 


412  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

{passion  composite)  ;  they  have  hitherto  been  only  sources  of 
suffering  and  vice,  but  were  designed  to  combine  and  concil- 
iate the  sensuous  springs  of  action  with  the  social  affections, 
and  will  be  of  unspeakable  service  in  the  reign  of  harmony 
and  in  those  phalansteres  which  are  to  regenerate  the  world. 
The  satisfaction  of  all  these  tendencies  or  passions,  the  har- 
mony of  the  whole  inner  and  outer  man  with  himself  and 
the  world,  is  unitiisme  or  religion ;  and  the  law  according  to 
which  human  nature  moves  onward  to  its  realisation  is  their 
attraction  when  left  free  and  unthwarted. 

It  is  on  this  law,  the  law  of  passional  attraction,  a  deduc- 
tion from  the  Newtonian  law,  that,  according  to  Fourier,  the 
welfare  of  society  entirely  depends.  The  passions  are  not  to 
be  checked  and  resisted,  —  all  the  misery  in  the  world  has 
arisen  from  the  false  belief  that  this  is  necessary ;  they  are 
to  be  harmonised  and  allowed  full  scope,  and  they  will  pro- 
duce a  social  system  as  orderly  and  perfect  as  is  the  sidereal 
system.  What  has  to  be  done  is  not  to  curb  and  crush  the 
passions  into  conformity  with  the  social  medium,  but  to 
modify  that  medium  till  it  offers  no  opposition  to  the  freest 
and  fullest  development  of  the  passions.  Fourier  claims  to 
have  devised  a  social  mechanism,  according  to  the  diversity 
and  intensity  of  individual  attractions,  which  would  com- 
pletely secure  this  end  and  make  every  person  ineffably  happy. 

The  closest  and  most  comprehensive  connection  is  repre- 
sented as  existing  between  man  and  the  earth  on  which  he 
lives.  About  80,000  years  is  the  duration  assigned  to  both, 
and  the  history  of  the  one,  it  is  held,  will  be  found  to  cor- 
respond at  every  stage  with  that  of  the  other.  The  earth  is 
bad  when  man  is  bad,  —  contains  noxious  beasts  and  behaves 
itself  ill,  because  he  has  perverted  appetites  and  conducts 
himself  irrationally,  —  and  will  ameliorate  itself  as  he  grows 
better.  The  simple  change,  for  instance,  of  sea-water  into 
lemonade,  will  purge  the  ocean  by  a  sudden  death  of  legions 
of  useless  and  frightful  marine  monsters,  images  of  our  pas- 
sions ;  and  replace  them  with  a  crowd  of  new  creations, 
amphibious  servants  for  the  use  of  fishermen  and  sailors; 
while  a  boreal  crown  will  bring  about  marvels  as  great  for 
the  good  of  landsmen.     The  80,000  years  of  human  history, 


FOURIER  413 

we  are  further  told,  divide  themselves  into  thirty-two  periods, 
naturally  reducible  to  four  great  periods  which  correspond 
to  the  infancy,  youth,  manhood,  and  old  age  of  the  individual. 
The  whole  course  being  a  natural  movement  from  birth  to 
death  is  one  of  growth  and  decline ;  or,  as  Fourier  says,  of 
"  ascending  and  descending  vibrations  of  life,  the  two  first 
being  phases  of  ascent  and  the  two  last  phases  of  descent. 
The  ascent  and  the  descent  are  equal  in  length  —  i.e.,  about 
40,000  years  each."  The  notion  that  the  collective  move- 
ment of  humanity  is  like  the  course  of  the  individual  through 
infancy,  youth,  manhood,  and  age,  is  applied,  however,  to  the 
lesser  periods  of  history  as  well  as  to  its  total  development 
on  earth.  Each  of  these  lesser  periods  is  thus  like  Leibniz's 
monads  —  a  sort  of  mirror  of  the  whole.  From  what  has  just 
been  said  the  reader  will  perceive  that  Fourier's  general  con- 
ception of  the  historical  movement  was  not  one  merely  of 
progress ;  it  was  one  of  retrogression  as  well,  as  every  con- 
ception of  the  kind  founded  on  the  assumption  of  a  strict 
analogy  between  the  course  of  history  and  the  life  of  indi- 
viduals must  in  consistency  be. 

The  first  of  the  four  periods  of  history,  that  of  infancy, 
is  as  yet  nowhere  outgrown,  although  little  more  than  5000 
years  have  been  allotted  to  it.  To  represent  the  human  race 
as  having  existed  on  earth  so  short  a  time  as  this  implies,  is, 
of  course,  not  in  accordance  with  the  findings  of  modern 
science.  Fourier  is  only  concerned,  however,  to  vindicate 
Providence  for  its  having  been  so  long,  seeing  that  it  has  been 
almost  entirely  a  period  of  subversion  and  discord,  of  delusion 
and  misery.  The  first  and  the  last  periods  of  planetary  life  and 
of  historical  development,  he  argues,  ought  to  be  very  short 
relatively  to  the  intermediate  periods.  But  the  earth  and  the 
human  species  have  had  their  first  period  abnormally  prolonged 
by  two  misfortunes  :  "  The  scourge  of  the  Deluge,  by  which  the 
aromal  system  of  our  planet  was  vitiated  and  obstructed  with 
deleterious  germs,  which  horribly  impoverished  the  post- 
diluvial creations ; "  and  "  the  no  less  terrible  'scourge  of  the 
philosophic  or  twisted  mind,  the  obstinacy  in  neglecting  to 
study  the  divine  laws  and  passional  destinies  in  the  analysis 
and  synthesis  of  attraction."     However,  it  is  but  short,  we  are 


414  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOEY   IN   TRANCE 

assured,  compared  with  those  vast  stretches  of  happiness  which 
lie  before  humanity,  and  into  which  all  the  souls  which  have 
lived  in  "  the  state  of  limbo  or  subversion  "  will  live  many 
times  under  many  forms.  What  Fourier  teaches  as  to  the 
childhood  of  humanity  is  the  only  portion  of  his  historical 
theory  which  can  be  tested  or  verified.  All  that  he  says  of 
the  other  three  ages  is,  of  course,  prophecy ;  and  most  of  it 
is  prophecy  which  is  not  in  the  least  likely  to  be  fulfilled.  It 
is,  therefore,  with  this  first  period  that  we  here  chiefly  require 
to  occupy  ourselves. 

It  includes  seven  of  the  thirty-two  lesser  periods.  The 
first  is  Edenisme,  the  primitive  paradisiacal  state  in  which 
men  satisfied  their  simple  wants  without  artificial  production 
and  almost  without  exertion,  lived  in  peace,  and  enjoyed  a 
"shadow  of  happiness."  The  human  species,  according  to 
Fourier,  was  created  in  34  or  36  races,  of  which  only  about 
a  third  composed  the  happy  society,  the  remembrance  of  which 
has  been  transmitted  to  us  through  traditions  that  have  been 
greatly  vitiated.  Geologists,  archeologists,  and  philologists 
are  severely  censured  for  having  instituted  frivolous  investi- 
gations as  to  Adam  (the  primitive  collective  man)  and  the 
Edenic  state  while  neglecting  to  seek  to  ascertain  what  is  alone 
of  importance,  the  cause  of  the  primitive  social  happiness. 
Fourier  informs  us  that  it  was  "the  serial  system,  or  the  devel- 
opment of  the  passions  by  series,  graduated  into  ascending  and 
descending  groups,  an  order  which  a  certain  state  of  things 
rendered  practicable  in  the  first  ages  of  the  world,  and  which, 
having  become  impracticable  afterwards,  by  a  defect  of  the 
enlarged  industrial  system,  might  be  re-established  with 
splendour  in  the  present  day,  when  enlarged  industry  being 
fully  developed,  furnishes  to  the  societary  system  immense 
resources  that  did  not  exist  in  the  primitive  or  infantine 
ages  of  humanity."  The  happiness  of  Eden,  however,  did 
not  endure  long.  The  spontaneous  productivity  of  nature 
ceased  to  be  able  to  supply  the  wants  of  the  population  of 
Paradise  as  that  population  went  on  increasing.  Inventive- 
ness and  exertion,  science  and  instruments,  became  necessary, 
and  were  not  forthcoming.  Privation  began  to  be  felt;  dis- 
cord arose ;   selfishness   and  the   consciousness  of  superior 


FOURIER  415 

strength  suggested  to  the  men  to  make  the  women  labour  for 
them ;  the  reign  of  tyranny,  deceit,  and  injustice  originated. 
Offjjihis  fall  tradition  has  handed  down  an  account,  but  an 
erroneous  one,  man  having  taken  care  to  attribute  the  chief 
blame  of  it  to  woman.  Its  consequences  have  made  them- 
selves always  increasingly  felt  in  the  four  periods  which  fol- 
lowed, —  those  of  Sauvagerie,  JPatriarcat,  Barbarie,  and  Civil- 
isation. These  are  all  incoherent  and  unhappy  ages ;  times 
of  ignorance  and  of  a  philosophy  worse  than  ignorance,  of 
feebleness  and  poverty,  of  coercion  and  injustice ;  stages  of 
unnaturalness  and  untruths,  —  Echelons  de  faussete. 

The  character  of  the  second  period,  that  of  savage  hordes, 
is  drawn  with  little  exaggeration  or  passion,  and  certainly  not 
in  too  dark  colours.  The  common  lot  of  the  savage  man  is 
described  by  Fourier  as,  on  the  whole,  happier  than  the  com- 
mon lot  of  the  civilised  man.  He  represents  the  mass  of 
mankind  in  the  savage  state  as  in  possession  of  a  measure  of 
freedom  which  comparatively  few  enjoy  in  civilisation ;  and 
as  exercising  without  restraint  the  natural  rights  of  which  the 
vast  majority  of  men  have  now  come  to  be  almost  entirely 
deprived.  They  were  free  to  take  the  fruits  of  the  earth, 
to  fish,  to  hunt,  to  feed  animals  on  the  land  of  the  horde,  to 
share  in  all  that  was  involved  in  membership  in  the  horde,  to 
appropriate  whatever  lay  outside  its  common  property ;  and 
they  were  free  from  care.  But  while  Fourier  holds  that  the 
modern  proletarian  may  justly  envy  the  condition  of  the 
savage,  and  that  the  aversion  of  the  latter  to  change  his  state 
was  not  altogether  without  reason,  he  also  maintains  that  the 
freedom  and  the  happiness  of  the  savage  were  insecure  and 
insufficient  inasmuch  as  they  did  not  rest  on  industry  and 
passional  attraction.  Besides,  such  as  they  were  they  were 
only  possessed  by  the  males  of  the  tribe,  and  frequently  only 
by  these  while  in  the  vigour  of  life.  Women  were  excluded 
from  all  share  in  them ;  their  lot  was  slavery  and  misery. 
And  children  and  old  men  were  generally  harshly  dealt  with. 

In  the  third  period,  that  of  the  patriarchal  clans,  agriculture 
is  supposed  to  have  been  practised  to  some  extent ;  industry 
to  have  appeared  in  rudimentary  forms ;  a  certain  differentia- 
tion of  classes  to  have  been  developed  in  society ;  the  natural 


416  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

rights  of  men  to  have  been  encroached  on ;  and  the  condition 
of  women  to  have  been  ameliorated.  In  the  fourth  period, 
that  of  barbarism,  the  head  of  the  society  wielded  unlisted 
power ;  industry  was  pursued  on  a  large  scale ;  the  arts  sprang 
up ;  and  violence  and  perfidy  prevailed.  Fourier,  however, 
has  neither  clearly  distinguished  nor  carefully  characterised 
these  two  periods ;  indeed,  he  has  been  content  to  do  little 
more  than  represent  them  as  subversive  and  deplorable. 

Civilisation,  the  fifth  period  of  the  infancy  of  the  human 
race,  is  the  stage  at  which  the  more  advanced  nations  of  the 
world  have  now  arrived.  It  has,  of  course,  an  ascending  and 
descending  movement,  and  passes  through  four  stages,— 
childhood,  youth,  manhood,  and  old  age,  —  like  humanity 
itself.  In  the  first  stage  the  governing  authority  is  no  longer 
as  in  barbarism  absolute  and  undivided,  but  the  kingly  power 
is  limited  by  combinations  of  great  vassals,  the  feudal  nobil- 
ity. Slavery  has  also  generally  given  place  to  serfdom. 
Monogamy  is  recognised  as  the  foundation  and  law  of  the 
family,  women  attain  civil  rights,  and  wives  become  entitled 
to  participate  in  the  social  advantages  and  consideration  en- 
joyed by  their  husbands.  The  change  in  the  condition  of  the 
female  sex  which  distinguishes  civilisation  from  barbarism 
gives  a  new  tone  and  colouring  to  manners,  and  is  highly 
favourable  to  the  development  of  the  arts  and  sciences,  and 
especially  of  music  and  poetry.  The  ideals  of  chivalry  are 
the  illusions  of  this  epoch. 

Gradually,  however,  the  feudalism  which  was  the  cradle 
of  civilisation  was  outgrown.  There  was  a  development  of 
industry  and  trade,  of  art  and  science,  which  lessened  the 
power  of  the  nobility  while  it  increased  that  of  the  general 
population.  Guilds  became  strong,  townships  independent, 
and  even  agricultural  serfs  comparatively  free.  The  wealth 
and  organisation  of  the  burghers  enabled  them  to  resist  and 
rival  the  nobles,  and  to  wrest  from  kings  the  rights  and 
privileges  which  they  desired.  The  foundations  of  the  repre- 
sentative system  of  government  were  laid.  The  illusions  of 
freedom  displaced  those  of  chivalry  as  social  ideals. 

Civilisation  at  length  reached  the  highest  point  it  was  to 
attain.     Experimental  and  mechanical  science  succeeded  in 


FOURIER  417 

transforming  industry,  and  endowing  it  with  hitherto  un- 
known resources.  The  art  of  navigation  was  greatly  im- 
proved ;  geographical  discoveries  of  vast  importance  were 
made  ;  the  distribution  of  goods  was  facilitated ;  and  the 
world-market  was  opened  up.  The  consequences  are  to  be 
seen  in  the  destruction  of  small  industries  by  production  on 
a  large  scale  ;  in  the  disorganisation  of  agriculture  by  manu- 
factures ;  in  the  rise  of  an  industrial  feudalism  more  oppres- 
sive than  military  feudalism  ever  was  ;  in  wealth  becoming 
the  chief  object  of  desire,  and  the  chief  source  of  power;  in 
the  general  adulteration  of  goods,  systematic  and  shameless 
financial  swindling,  and  commercial  dishonesty  everywhere 
prevalent ;  in  the  rapid  and  constantly  accelerating  spread  of 
pauperism  and  misery ;  and  in  a  division  of  society  into  hos- 
tile classes  which  threatens  to  issue  in  a  terrible  proletarian 
revolution.  The  cherished  illusions  of  this  stage  of  civilisa- 
tion are  economic  illusions,  those  dear  to  the  egoistic  mercan- 
tile spirit. 

Whereas  the  predominant  characteristic  of  the  third  phase 
of  civilisation  is  mercantile  anarchy  or  false  competition,  that 
of  the  fourth  phase,  or  age  of  the  senility  or  decrepitude,  of 
civilisation,  is  a  species  of  false  regulation,  resulting  from  a 
general  monopoly  of  commerce  and  industry  by  an  oligarchy 
of  capital.  A  feudality  based  on  wealth  is  fully  developed, 
gains  the  command  of  all  labour,  regulates  all  the  movements 
of  trade,  monopolises  industrial  and  financial  enterprise,  con- 
trols governments,  and  by  its  system  of  loans  draws  to  itself 
the  revenues  of  nations.  The  mass  of  mankind  thus  find 
themselves  in  the  last  phase  of  civilisation  destitute  of  all 
the  natural  rights  which  the  savage  enjoyed,  including  that 
of  sharing  in  the  consumption  of  what  they  have  themselves 
produced.  The  earlier  servitude  of  individuals  has  only  been 
replaced  by  a  collective  servitude.  While  the  two  first  ages 
of  civilisation  diminished  and  abolished  personal  and  direct 
bondage,  its  two  last  ages  produce  an  increase  of  general  and 
indirect  bondage,  seeing  that,  as  population  grows  and  industry 
expands,  the  labouring  classes  become  more  and  more  depend- 
ent on  a  league  of  capitalists  who  have  the  wealth  of  society 
in  their  hands.     The  hopes  of  man  in  its  closing  phase  are 


418  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

placed  iii  association,  but  these  hopes  are  illusions,  for  the 
association  aimed  at  is  the  false  association  which  merely 
combines  capitals,  and  so  only  increases  their  power  of  absorp- 
tion; it  is  a  caricature  of  the  true  association  which  duly 
combines  capital,  labour,  and  talent. 

The  succession  of  the  aforesaid  states  of  society,  —  Eden- 
ism,  Savagery,  Patriarchalism,  Barbarism,  and  Civilisation, — 
shows  on  the  whole  declension,  or  decrease  of  good  and  in- 
crease of  evil.  In  the  first  only  a  shadow  of  happiness  was 
enjoyed,  and  the  other  four  have  been  subversive  and  anarchi- 
cal ages,  during  which  the  earth  has  been  the  abode  of  fraud, 
oppression,  falsehood,  and  misery. .  Fourier  treats  with  scorn 
the  upholders  of  the  theory  of  continuous  progress;  those 
who  look  upon  such  progress  as  the  law  of  history,  or  on  the 
actual  course  of  human  events  as  having  been  one  either  of 
necessity  or  of  wisdom,  either  in  accordance  with  nature  or 
approved  by  Providence.  He  admits,  however,  that  notwith- 
standing their  essential  incoherence  and  baseness,  they  pro- 
vide, by  developing  industry,  arts,  and  sciences,  important 
elements  and  means  for  the  true  organisation  of  society. 

His  delineations  of  the  periods  referred  to,  and  their 
sub-periods,  and  especially  of  civilisation  and  its  stages,  are 
regarded  by  his  disciples  as  "  veritable  masterpieces  of  obser- 
vation and  description."  They  are  certainly  instructive  and 
vigorous ;  and  they  may  be  justly  regarded  as  the  direct  or 
indirect  source  of  nearly  the  whole  historical  philosophy  on 
which  contemporary  socialism  rests.  It  is,  however,  in  his 
criticism  of  the  characteristics  and  tendencies  of  the  past  ages 
of  history,  and  especially  of  the  existing  constitution  of  soci- 
ety, that  his  intellectual  power  is  most  fully  displayed.  He 
censures  and  satirises  what  he  calls  the  periods  of  subversion 
and  misfortune,  and  above  all  modern  industrialism,  with 
extraordinary  keenness  and  force.  Rousseau  had  assailed 
society  with  eloquent  vituperation,  but  his  declamatory  anath- 
emas are  not  to  be  compared  with  the  methodical  and  com- 
prehensive, persistent  and  relentless  attack  of  Fourier.  No 
socialist  has  since  surpassed  our  author  in  the  vigour,  close- 
ness, and  bitterness  of  his  criticism  of  the  organisation  which 
he  wished  to  overthrow.     True,  his  picture  of  it  is  not  a 


FOURIER  419 

faithful  likeness  but  a  caricature.  It  is,  however,  a  caricature 
drawn  with  amazing  power ;  one  which  is  at  no  point  wholly 
without  resemblance  to  the  object  delineated,  while  it  so  gives 
prominence  to  every  weak,  discordant,  and  repulsive  feature 
thereof  as  most  effectively  to  produce  the  impression  desired. 

With  the  close  of  the  period  of  civilisation  a  process  of  im- 
provement sets  in.  The  next  period,  Guaranteeism,  is  the 
state  of  full  transition  between  false  and  true  organisation, 
"  between  limbo  and  harmony  " ;  the  stage  of  federation  among 
nations,  and  of  the  insurance  of  individual  interests  through 
collective  guarantees  against  risk  and  loss  in  all  departments 
of  social,  domestic,  and  industrial  economy.  This  sixth  period 
leads  to  a  seventh,  that  of  series  Sbauchees,  or  dawn  of  happi- 
ness ;  the  age  of  Seriosophy,  the  all-important  science,  hitherto 
so  irrationally  and  disastrously  neglected,  of  the  organisation 
of  society  by  attraction  or  pleasure  according  to  natural  groups 
and  series.  When  proficiency  in  this  science  has  been  attained 
the  earth  will  soon  be  covered  with  a  federation  of  phalan- 
nteres,  and  the  second  great  era  of  time,  the  adolescence  of 
humanity,  will  begin. 

At  this  point  humanity  "  makes  a  leap  (fait  un  mut)  out 
of  chaos  into  harmony."  Harmony  is  to  last  about  70,000 
years,  and  will  include  two  great  periods  of  about  35,000 
years  each:  those  of  the  youth  and  manhood  of  the  race ;  the 
former  consisting  of  nine  lesser  periods  of  gradually  increas- 
ing happiness ;  and  the  latter  of  the  same  number  of  such 
periods  of  gradually  decreasing  happiness.  The  height  or 
fulness  of  happiness  is  to  last  8000  years. 

Fourier  has  discoursed  with  even  more  fulness  and  minute- 
ness on  harmony  than  on  limbo.  It  was  his  principal  and 
favourite  theme,  and  he  has  dwelt  on  it  with  inexhaustible 
ingenuity  and  enthusiasm.  The  commingling  of  sense  and 
nonsense,  of  shrewd  practical  insight  and  of  extravagant 
credulity,  in  his  treatment  of  it,  is  phenomenal,  and  perhaps 
without  parallel.  It  is  no  part  of  my  task,  however,  to  ex- 
pound or  examine  his  theory  of  social  organisation.  Yet  I 
may  relevantly  express  my  disbelief  that  any  world  of  har- 
mony will  ever  be  raised  on  such  a  view  of  the  relationship 
of  reason  and  passion  as  that  which  he  has  given.     It  seems 


420  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

to  me  a  thoroughly  false  one.  It  led  Fourier  to  form  imagina- 
tions as  to  the  relations  of  the  sexes  in  harmony  which  have 
been  justly  condemned.  It  is  true  that  he  admits  that  these 
relations  would  be  altogether  wrong  in  civilisation,  and  that 
amorous  liberty  ought  not  to  be  exercised  until  harmony  is 
firmly  established;  but  moral  blindness  was  shown  in  his 
fancying  that  any  alteration  of  the  social  mechanism,  or  any 
effects  of  its  alteration,  could  make  immoral  relations  legiti- 
mate, vices  virtues.  Harmony  will  be  a  very  short  period 
indeed  if  on  this  point  Fourier  be  accepted  as  its  moral  legis- 
lator. Most  of  his  disciples,  it  is  right  to  add,  have  rejected 
this  part  of  his  teaching.  It  is  further  only  fair  to  himself  to 
state  that  he  has  often  written  very  worthily  of  the  rights 
of  woman  and  of  her  place  in  history.  For  example,  in  his 
'  Theory  of  the  Four  Movements,'  he  has  maintained  and  de- 
feuded  the  following  general  thesis :  "  Social  advances  take 
place  in  proportion  to  the  progress  of  women  towards  liberty; 
and  decadences  in  the  social  order  in  proportion  to  the  de- 
crease of  the  liberty  of  women.  .  .  .  Other  events  affect 
political  vicissitudes ;  but  there  is  no  cause  which  produces 
so  rapidly  social  progress  or  social  decline  as  change  in  the 
condition  of  women.  The  adoption  of  closed  harems  (sSraih 
fermes)  would  of  itself  render  us  in  a  short  time  barbarous, 
and  the  mere  opening  of  the  harems  would  make  the  barba- 
rians pass  into  civilisation.  In  fine,  the  extension  of  the 
privileges  of  women  is  the  general  principle  of  all  social  im- 
provements." 

When  the  close  of  the  third  great  period,  or  twenty-fifth 
lesser  period,  is  reached,  humanity  is  to  take  a  second  leap; 
but  this  time,  unfortunately,  out  of  harmony  into  chaos.  The 
epoch  of  its  old  age  will  begin.  And  it  will  go  on  declining 
through  seven  stages  corresponding  to  those  of  infancy,  but 
following  in  the  reverse  order,  thus  :  (1)  traces  of  happiness ; 
(2)  garantisme ;  (3)  civilisation;  (4)  barbarie;  (5)  patriar- 
cat;  (6)  sauvagerie;  and  (7)  series  confuses.  Fourier  gives 
us  no  particulars  as  to  any  of  these  periods ;  his  descriptive 
survey  of  the  course  of  human  history  ends  with  harmonisni. 

Life  at  length  ceases  to  manifest  itself  in  this  world,  our 
race  dies,  and  the  earth  bursts  up,  and  scatters  itself  in  frag- 
ments among  the  star-dust  of  the  Milky  Way.     But  this  is 


BUCHEZ  421 

far  from  making  an  end  either  of  it  or  of  us.  It  has  a  living 
soul,  and  that  soul,  carrying  with  it  all  the  souls  which  com- 
pose it  and  have  dwelt  in  it,  goes  into  a  comet  which  is  to 
become  a  planet  and  to  make  part  of  the  sidereal  harmony. 
The  soul  of  every  planet  has  a  multitude  of  successive  lives ; 
and  the  diminutive  souls  which  reside  within  it  often  come 
and  tabernacle  in  individual  bodies  born  on  the  planet,  al- 
though where  souls  outnumber  bodies  they  may  have  often 
to  wait  a  considerable  time  for  resurrections.  On  our  present 
globe  every  one  of  us  is  sure  of  enjoying  about  400  consecu- 
tive and  bodily  existences  in  the  course  of  a  career  estimated 
at  80,000  years.  Out  of  these  400  existences  seven-eighths 
(350)  will  be  happy.  The  material  death  of  the  soul  will 
only  transport  its  great  soul  and  its  partial  souls  to  a  planet 
of  higher  degree,  where  they  will  recommence  careers  of  fuller 
life  and  richer  happiness,  although  these  careers  will  conform 
to  the  same  law  of  birth,  development,  and  death,  of  ascend- 
ing and  descending  phases,  as  those  of  the  past.  Thus  the 
souls  of  men,  passing  from  existence  to  existence  in  the 
course  of  their  resurrections  on  this  globe,  and  then  rising 
from  star  to  star,  from  system  to  system,  in  the  more  fortu- 
nate path  which  they  will  traverse  during  eternity,  always 
uniting  themselves  with  matter,  and  clothing  themselves  in 
new  bodies,  will  experience  the  immensity  of  happiness  which 
God  has  in  store  for  them. 

Some  of  Fourier's  critics,  taking  into  account  only  his  views 
regarding  the  subversive  periods  of  history  on  our  earth,  have 
very  erroneously  represented  him  as  a  pessimist.  We  must 
judge  of  his  historical  theory  as  a  whole ;  and  considered  as 
a  whole  it  was  highly  optimistic.  His  faith  in  the  future 
was  not  affected  by  his  estimate  of  the  present;  it  was  an 
unbounded  confidence  that  all  men  were  destined  to  enjoy  in 
countless  existences  every  variety  of  pleasure  to  an  extent 
of  which  they  can  as  yet  form  no  conception. 

II 

The  direction  of  thought  inaugurated  by  Saint-Simon  and 
Fourier  was  followed  by  various  authors  who  applied  them- 
selves to  the  study  of  the  laws  of  history.     Three  of  them 


422  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTOE.Y  IN   PKANCE 

arrived  at  sufficiently  distinctive  results  to  have  a  claim  on 
our  attention.  They  were  Philippe  Joseph  Benjamin  Buchez, 
Pierre  Leroux,  and  Auguste  Comte.  I  shall  in  this  chapter 
speak  only  of  the  first  two. 

M.  Buchez  was  born  in  1796.  He  was  a  physician  by- 
profession,  a  very  ardent  republican,  and  a  copious  writer  on 
philosophy,  religion,  history,  and  politics.  He  was  for  some 
time  a  member  of  the  Saint-Simonian  society,  but  left  it  in 
consequence  of  aversion  to  the  strange  theological  dogmas  of 
its  spiritual  chief,  M.  Enfantin.  He  himself  devised  and  ad- 
vocated a  sort  of  Socialist  Catholicism,  in  which  traditional- 
ism, mysticism,  and  rationalism,  despotism  and  democracy,  the 
sovereignty  of  the  Pope  and  the  sovereignty  of  the  people, 
the  teaching  of  Christ  and  of  Robespierre,  of  De  Bonald  and 
of  Saint-Simon,  and  many  other  heterogeneous  and  incon- 
sistent things,  were  confusedly  thrown  together.  He  edited, 
along  with  M.  Roux,  the  '  Parliamentary  History  of  the  Early 
Periods  of  the  first  French  Revolution.'  He  began  his  philo- 
sophical career  in  1833  with  the  publication  of  his  '  Introduc- 
tion a  la  Science  de  l'liistoire,'  which  was  received  by  the 
public  with  considerable  favour,  and  very  warmly  commended 
by  the  eminent  jurist,  M.  Lerminier.  A  second  edition  ap- 
peared in  1842.  In  it  M.  Buchez  felt  at  liberty  to  dispense 
with  several  discussions  on  general  philosophical  problems 
which  he  thought  necessary  in  the  first  edition,  having  in 
the  interval  published  a  '  Traite-  de  Philosophic '  and  an 
'Introduction  a  l'e'tude  des  sciences  me'dieales,'  where  they 
found  more  appropriate  places.  He  added  much  more,  how- 
ever, than  he  retrenched,  and  so  expanded  into  two  volumes 
what  had  been  originally  one.  He  was  raised  by  the  Revolu- 
tion of  1848  to  the  presidency  of  the  National  Constituent 
Assembly.  The  honour  could  not  have  been  conferred  on  a 
more  sincere  republican  or  on  a  better-intentioned  man ;  but 
he  wanted  the  firmness,  decision,  and  political  capacity  needed 
in  a  situation  so  difficult  and  in  days  so  tempestuous.  On  the 
fall  of  the  second  French  Republic  he  retired  into  private  life. 
He  died  in  1866. 

His  general  philosophy  seems  to  me  of  very  small  value ; 
and  as  it  has  been  the  subject  of  studies  by  Simon,  Damiron, 


BUCHEZ  423 

and  Ferraz,  I  shall  say  nothing  regarding  it.  On  the  other 
hand,  his  '  Introduction  to  the  Science  of  History '  contains, 
I  think,  a  good  deal  which  deserves  to  be  clearly  indicated. 

The  work  commences  with  two  prefatory  chapters,  the  first 
describing  the  present  condition  of  society,  and  the  second  ex- 
plaining the  general  purpose  of  the  treatise,  the  thought  which 
gave  rise  to  it  and  rules  it.  The  picture  of  society  is  painted 
in  the  gloomiest  colours.  Distrust,  selfishness,  misery,  are 
described  as  spread  over  all.  Class  is  represented  as  at  war 
with  class ;  the  rich  as  restless  and  insecure ;  "the  poor  as 
envious  and  oppressed ;  women  as  frivolous,  unfortunate,  and 
enslaved;  religion,  moral  principle,  worthy  aspirations,  sure 
and  elevating  hopes,  as  lamentably  wanting.  The  sight  of 
the  evil  suggests  the  question,  Is  there  a  remedy  ?  The  con- 
sideration of  that  question  leads  to  inquiry  into  the  nature  of 
man  and  of  society,  and  that  to  the  search  for  a  science  of 
history.  It  is  history  which  shows  us  the  actions  of  human- 
ity; and  only  through  its  actions  can  we  know  its  nature, 
trace  its  past,  or  foresee  its  future  fortunes.  Hence  it  is  the 
science  of  history  which  must  discover  the  final  causes  of 
human  societies,  explain  their  revolutions,  account  for  their 
miseries,  and  suggest  the  appropriate  remedies. 

The  first  book  treats  of  the  design  and  foundation  of  the 
science  of  history,  and  consists  of  seven  chapters.  In  chap.  i. 
M.  Buchez  seeks  the  definition  of  the  science.  Science,  he 
argues,  is  a  systematised  whole  of  knowledge,  an  organised 
body  of  principles  and  consequences,  co-ordinated  in  relation 
to  an  end  or  purpose.  Science  can  only  be  defined  according 
to  its  end.  The  definition  of  a  science  ought  to  include  a 
statement  of  the  purpose  which  it  serves.  Like  Comte  and 
others  who  had  been  taught  in  the  school  of  Saint-Simon,  he 
insists  on  the  prevision  of  phenomena  as  the  test  of  true 
science.  He  defines,  accordingly,  the  science  of  histoiy  as  a 
science  which  has  for  end  the  prevision  of  the  social  future  of 
the  huftian  race  in  the  exercise  of  its  free  agency.  But  is 
prevision  possible  where  there  is  free  will?  or,  in  other 
words,  is  a  science  of  history  possible?  This  question  M. 
Buchez  discusses  in  chap.  ii.  under  the  impression  that  he  is 
the  first  who  has  done  so.     Leaving  its  more  thorough  inves- 


424  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOEY   IN   PKANCE 

tigation  to  other  parts  of  his  work,  he  here  treats  of  it,  however, 
only  in  the  most  general  way.  He  points  out  that  history  as 
a  whole  and  in  all  its  parts  is  not  stationary ;  that  it  is  a 
process  in  which  beliefs,  manners,  actions,  are  constantly 
varying ;  that,  in  a  word,  it  moves ;  further,  that  movement 
is  of  two  kinds,  fatalistic  and  free :  and  then,  having  endeav- 
oured to  establish  that  all  human  and  social  movements  tend 
towards  ends  which  are  not  arbitrary  but  determined  by  man's 
nature  and  rooted  in  the  reason  of  things,  he  concludes  that 
their  course  can  be  in  some  measure  foreseen  and  calculated. 
This  suffices,  he  thinks,  to  show  that  a  science  of  history  is 
possible. 

In  the  next  chapter  we  are  told  that  the  science  of  history 
rests  on  two  ideas,  — ■  that  of  humanity  and  that  of  progress. 
The  four  following  chapters  treat  of  these  two  ideas.  The 
former  is  but  feebly  dealt  with.  Humanity  he  explains  as 
meaning  the  whole  human  species,  the  entire  succession  of 
generations  and  the  entire  host  of  peoples,  regarded  as  one 
vast  society,  bound  together  by  manifold  ties  of  nature  and 
responsiblity;  participant  in  one  spiritual  life,  in  a  continuous 
education,  and  in  an  unbroken  tradition ;  and  predestined 
and  organised  for  the  realisation  of  one  great  aim.  He  em- 
ploys two  arguments  to  prove  the  truth  of  this  conception. 
The  first  is,  that  "  humanity  is  the  function  of  the  universe," 
—  a  grandiose  phrase,  by  which  M.  Buchez  means,  on  the  one 
hand,  that  humanity  is  not  self-existent  and  self-dependent, 
but,  as  geology,  physics,  physiology,  and  other  sciences  show, 
closely  related  to  the  various  orders  of  phenomena  amidst 
which  it  exists,  so  that  an  essential  alteration  in  any  of  them 
would  render  its  existence  impossible ;  and,  on  the  other 
hand,  that  the  whole  universe  is  subordinate  to  man.  His 
other  argument  is,  that  the  activity  of  the  individual  is  con- 
ditioned by  that  of  the  nation;  and  the  activity  of  the  nation 
by  that  of  the  race,  —  or,  in  a  word,  that  the  end  of  the  race 
determines  the  place  and  character  of  all  minor  ends.# 

The  idea  of  progress  is  treated  with  much  greater  ability 
and  success.  M.  Buchez  gives  in  a  special  chapter  a  better 
history  of  the  idea  than  any  one  had  given  before  him. 
Another  chapter  on  the  definition  of  the  idea  shows  that 


BUCHEZ  425 

Saint-Simon's  best  thoughts  on  the  subject  had  largely  fruc- 
tified in  his  disciple's  mind.  The  remarks  which  he  makes 
under  this  head  on  the  consequences  which  may  be  truly 
drawn  from  the  idea,  and  on  those  which  are  falsely  drawn 
from  it,  are  generally  both  just  and  useful ;  while  those  on 
the  resemblances  and  differences  between  mathematical  and 
historical  series,  successions  of  quantities  and  successions  of 
actions,  are  particularly  valuable.  Up  to  the  time  of  Saint- 
Simon,  progress  in  history  had  been  merely  stated  and  illus- 
trated as  a  fact ;  with  him  and  his  followers  it  began  to  be 
analysed.  The  impulse  to  analysis  came  from  natural  science, 
and  especially  from  physiological  science,  which  became 
aware  in  the  earlier  part  of  the  century  of  the  immense 
significance  of  the  ideas  or  facts  of  development  and  organic 
evolution.  In  this  connection  it  merits  remark  that  M. 
Buchez  is  careful  to  show  that  human  progress  is  a  part  of 
the  law  and  order  of  the  world ;  that  progress  is  not  merely 
an  historical  but  also  a  universal  fact. 

The  second  book  of  his  treatise  is  occupied  with  "  The 
Methods  of  the  Science  of  History."  The  following  is  a  very 
brief  summary  of  its  contents.  The  aim  of  all  scientific  inves- 
tigation is  to  discover  the  order  of  succession  of  phenomena, 
and  to  ascertain  their  relations  of  dependence,  so  that  one 
phenomenal  state  being  given,  those  which  precede  and  those 
which  will  follow  it  may  be  known.  Science  is  a  power  of 
prevision,  and  prevision  has  two  degrees,  —  a  lower,  founded 
on  the  knowledge  of  the  order  of  succession  of  phenomena  — 
and  a  higher,  founded  on  the  knowledge  of  the  law  of  their 
generation.  Both  imply  the  coexistence  and  presence  of  two 
conditions,  —  a  constant,  i.e.,  an  invariable,  principle  of  order 
in  the  production  of  phenomena,  and  variations  in  the  mani- 
festation. There  are  both  "  constants  "  and  "  variations  "  in 
history.  There  are  "  constants,"  because  the  faculties  of  men 
have  been  neither  increased  nor  diminished  in  number  in  the 
long  series  of  generations.  There  are  "  variations,"  because 
these  same  faculties  have  increased  in  energy  and  range  of 
action  both  as  regards  physical  nature  and  social  life.  The 
"  constants  "  originate  in  human  spontaneity,  and  all  the  active 
elements  subordinate  thereto ;   the  "  variations  "  are  the  ex- 


426  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

pression  of  all  the  difficulties  of  realisation,  of  all  man's  strug- 
gles against  the  inanimate  world  or  against  mankind  itself. 
If  we  take  the  various  social  constants  of  history,  make  of 
each  a  subject  of  special  study,  and  range  under  it  according 
to  the  dates  of  occurrence  all  the  variations  which  belong  to 
it,  the  result  will  be  so  many  linear  classifications  of  facts, 
identical  in  essence,  homological  in  character,  chronological 
in  order,  and  increasing  or  decreasing  in  some  relation  of 
proportion.  These  linear  classifications  or  series  give  some 
knowledge  of  the  course  of  succession  among  phenomena,  and 
some  power  of  prevision;  but  only  a  knowledge  which  is 
slight  and  imperfect,  only  a  power  of  prevision  of  the  feeblest 
and  lowest  kind.  It  is  of  the  very  nature  of  the  process  to 
overlook  the  great  facts  that  human  nature  is  a  whole,  and 
that  all  its  faculties,  all  the  social  constants,  act  simultaneously, 
act  and  react  at  every  instant  on  each  other.  In  order  to 
bring  events  under  a  common  heading,  it  has  to  separate  them 
from  all  other  kinds  of  events,  however  closely  connected  with 
them  in  reality.  It  does  not  enable  us  to  determine  the  nature, 
number,  or  relative  importance  of  the  different  social  constants 
and  the  series  dependent  on  them.  It  tells  us  nothing  except 
that  a  certain  order  of  facts  tends  to  increase  or  tends  to  dis- 
appear. It  needs  to  be  supplemented,  therefore,  by  another 
process  or  method,  —  one  which  will  put  us  in  possession  of 
the  law  of  the  generation  of  phenomena.     (I.-IV.) 

This  law  must  be  sought  among  the  laws  of  human  activity, 
—  the  cause  of  every  social  change,. —  and  these  in  its  modes 
of  manifestation  or  forms  of  production,  not  in  its  essence  or 
in  the  abstract  categories  of  reason.  Social  activity  is  simply 
the  sum  of  individual  activities,  and  cannot  be  essentially 
different  in  its  laws  and  characteristics  from  the  forces  which 
compose  or  engender  it.  The  law  of  the  generation  of  social 
phenomena  must  therefore  be  involved  in  the  analogy  between 
the  faculties  of  the  individual  and  of  humanity.  This  implies 
that  that  analogy  contains  both  a  law  of  constants  and  a  law 
of  variations.  The  first  of  all  social  constants  is  a  common 
end  of  activity,  a  consciousness  of  a  common  work  to  do  — 
not  merely  community  of  belief,  language,  or  locality.  It  is 
that  which  makes  a  society,  however  numerous  the  individuals 


BUCHEZ  427 

which  compose  it  or  the  ages  through  which  it  passes,  a  single 
living  and  acting  being.  It  is  that  also  which  gives  rise  to  all 
other  social  constants,  such  as  the  wants  of  spiritual  conser- 
vation, material  conservation,  individual  conservation,  good 
government,  right,  the  discharge  of  duty,  &c,  with  all  the 
institutions  which  correspond  to  them.  From  it,  the  true 
principle  of  social  synthesis,  of  social  life,  every  other  constant 
may  be  deduced,  and  only  through  such  deduction  can  they  be 
assigned  their  proper  places.     (V.-VI.) 

The  laws  of  variation  are  twofold  —  logical  and  tendential. 
The  movement  determined  by  logical  law  is  the  succession  of 
states  through  which,  an  end  of  activity  being  given,  history 
must  necessarily  pass  in  order  that  it  may  attain  outward  ex- 
istence and  embodiment.  There  is,  according  to  M.  Buchez, 
such  a  movement  in  the  individual  mind;  since  every  action 
which  has  for  end  to  manifest  externally  any  idea  or  spiritual 
principle  must  necessarily  pass  in  an  invariable  order  through 
the  three  stages  of  desire,  reasoning,  and  realisation.  This 
logical  law  is  universal.  There  is  another  which  is  more  lim- 
ited. Ideas  involving  a  doctrine,  plan,  project,  &c,  in  order 
to  be  realised  must  not  only  be  desired,  demonstrated,  and 
executed,  but  must  pass  through  two  secondary  states,  which 
may  be  called  the  one  theoretical  and  the  other  practical. 
These  two  movements  frequently  so  intersect  and  combine 
that  each  period  of  the  ternary  movement  may  be  decomposed 
into  two  periods,  according  to  the  binary  movement,  and  each 
period  of  the  binary  movement  into  three  periods,  according 
to  the  ternary  movement,  and  this  many  times.  Now  social 
activity  is  subject  to  the  same  conditions  and  laws  as  individ- 
ual activity.  It  passes  through  states  similarly  related,  similar 
in  character  and  functions,  and  passes  through  them  in  the 
same  order ;  although  what  lasts  but  an  instant  in  the  history 
of  the  individual  often  occupies  an  age  in  the  life  of  the  race. 
Thus  —  to  take  only  the  ternary  movement  —  every  great 
epoch  of  humanity,  which,  as  we  shall  presently  see,  M.  Buchez 
identifies  with  every  revelation,  has  three  periods  or  stages. 
There  is  first  that  of  the  revelation  of  the  principle,  that  in 
which  doctrines  are  imparted  and  accepted  as  immediate 
satisfactions  to  emotional  wants,  —  the  age  of  theology  ;  next 


428  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

that  of  rationalism,  of  scholastic  explanation  and  exposition ; 
and  finally,  that  of  practical  experience  and  application,  of  the 
close  study  and  skilful  utilising  of  all  kinds  of  facts, — the 
period  of  Christian  history,  for  example,  which  dates  from 
Bacon  and  Descartes.  The  first  corresponds  to  the  stage  of 
desire,  the  second  to  that  of  reasoning,  and  the  third  to  that 
of  execution  in  the  movement  of  individual  activity.  It  is 
unnecessary  to  describe  the  minute  and  complicated,  yet  regu- 
lar and  systematic,  subdivision  of  these  periods  through  binary 
and  ternary  decompositions.  Let  it  suffice  to  say  that  these 
decompositions  do  not  prevent  the  entire  social  development 
being  reducible,  as  Saint-Simon  taught,  to  organic  or  synthet- 
ical, and  critical  or  analytical  ages.     (VII.) 

The  principles  of  the  movement  called  tendential  are  spirit- 
ual appetencies  continuous  in  their  action,  indefinitely  pro- 
gressive, and  always  aspiring  after  an  end.  They  have  their 
foundation  in  the  social  constants,  and  constitute  the  variations 
which  form  the  elements  of  the  series ;  each  social  constant 
being  capable  of  becoming  the  basis  of  a  progressive  series. 
The  constants  may  be  viewed  as  regards  either  organised  cor- 
porations or  individuals,  and  this  leads  to  the  classification  of 
tendencies  through  their  relation  to  duties  and  rights.  But 
as,  after  reading  several  times  what  M.  Buchez  has  written 
concerning  these  tendencies,  I  find  myself  unable  to  under- 
stand it,  I  can  only  report  that  he  believes  he  has  discovered 
and  described  a  method  which  remedies  the  defects  inherent 
in  the  mere  analysis  of  history  into  separate  chronological 
series  of  similar  events  considered  as  a  means  of  attaining 
scientific  certainty  and  prevision.  His  remarks  on  the  con- 
version of  the  laws  of  the  logical  and  tendential  movements 
into  methods  of  historical  classification  and  prevision  are,  on 
the  whole,  both  intelligible  and  just.     (VIII.-IX.) 

The  third  book  is  devoted  to  the  consideration  of  four  of 
the  most  important  social  constants,  the  common  end  of  ac- 
tivity, art,  science,  and  physical  labour,  but  unfortunately  in 
the  way  of  mere  general  disquisition;  so  that  it  contains 
exceedingly  little  which  properly  belongs  to  a  philosophy  of 
history.  The  next  two  books  are  wholly  occupied  with  mat- 
ters still  more  extraneous  and  irrelevant ;  the  fourth  treating 


BUCHBZ  429 

of  the  idea  of  progress  as  a  means  of  forming  encyclopedias 
of  science  and  of  education;  and  the  fifth  propounding  a 
multitude  of  geological  speculations,  mostly  worthless. 

In  the  sixth  book,  M.  Buchez  reaches  the  sixth  day  of  the 
Mosaic  account  of  creation,  and  so  plants  his  foot  again  on  his- 
tory, or,  at  least,  on  what  he  calls  androgeny.  But  more  than 
the  half  even  of  this  book  is  occupied  with  discussions  regard- 
ing the  creation  of  man,  original  sin,  the  deluge,  &c.,  of  a  kind 
little  calculated  to  benefit  historical  science.  In  its  fourth 
chapter,  however,  we  come  to  what  may  perhaps  be  fairly 
considered  the  chief  doctrine  of  his  system.  It  is  that  divine 
intervention  has  been  the  great  motive  force  in  the  develop- 
ment of  humanity ;  that  the  principle  of  each  distinct  histor- 
ical synthesis,  of  each  complete  logical  epoch,  the  common  aim 
of  every  entire  civilisation,  is  only  to  be  found  in  a  revela- 
tion. History  is  represented  as  having  four  great  stages, 
each  initiated  by  a  universal  revelation  given  either  through 
the  inspiration  of  certain  men  by  God  or  the  incarnation  of 
God  in  man.  The  first  revelation  was  made  through  Adam ; 
and  founded  an  epoch  which  had  for  end  the  conversion  of 
its  precepts  enjoining  the  domestic  duties,  into  habits  and 
institutions.  The  second,  given  through  Noah,  founded  an 
epoch  which  had  for  end  the  realisation  of  the  more  compre- 
hensive class  of  duties  involved  in  the  relationships,  both 
internal  and  external,  of  tribes  and  races.  The  third  was 
imparted  to  some  great  prophet  who  lived  where  the  sons  of 
Japheth  were  in  contact  with  those  of  Shem,  so  that  its 
influence  might  extend  to  Egypt,  India,  China,  Greece,  and 
Rome,  and  was  designed  to  communicate  the  sentiment  of 
social  unity  and  the  idea  of  equality,  along  with  that  of  the 
diversity  of  functions.  And  the  last  of  all  was  the  perfect 
revelation  of  truth  and  life  in  Christ,  the  source  of  a  civilisa- 
tion which  has  lasted  eighteen  centuries,  and  has  still  before 
it  an  indefinite  future.  The  revelation  given  to  Moses  is 
not  included  in  the  series,  because,  although  most  important, 
it  was  not  universal  but  particular  —  i.e.,  designed  for  a 
single  people. 

The  seventh  book  is  a  succession  of  pictures  of  the  four 
great  epochs  of  history,  and  of  the  lesser  periods  which  they 


430  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

contain.  These  are  but  feebly  and  inaccurately  drawn. 
Perhaps  M.  Buchez  thought  that  the  'Essai  d'Histoire  Uni- 
verselle '  and  '  Histoire  des  Transformations  Religieuses  et 
Morales  des  Peuples  '  of  M.  Boullard,  and  the  '  Manuel  d'His- 
toire Universelle  '  of  Dr.  Ott,  both  friends  and  almost  disciples, 
rendered  it  unnecessary  for  him  to  bestow  much  care  on  this 
part  of  his  task. 

We  have  now  a  general  knowledge  of  what  M.  Buchez 
has  done  in  connection  with  the  science  of  history.  What 
judgment  are  we  to  pass  thereon  ?  My  findings  are  as  follows : 
First,  his  treatise  is  prolix,  wearisome,  and  in  some  places 
apparently  almost  devoid  of  meaning.  Second,  three  out  of 
its  seven  books  are  not  occupied  with  the  science  of  history 
at  all;  and,  entirely  irrespective  of  condensation,  by  the 
simple  exclusion  of  what  was  irrelevant,  it  could  have  been 
easily  and  most  advantageously  reduced  to  less  than  half  its 
actual  size.  Third,  what  is  most  distinctive  in  M.  Buchez's 
theory  —  the  division  of  historical  development  into  four 
great  epochs  originated  by  four  universal  revelations,  of 
each  epoch  into  three  periods  corresponding  to  desire,  reason- 
ing, and  performance,  and  of  each  of  these  periods  into  a 
theoretical  and  practical  age  —  is,  although  ingenious,  so 
erroneous  and  fanciful,  that  a  refutation  of  it  will  not  be  felt 
necessary  by  any  intelligent  reader.  Fourth,  the  truly  valua- 
ble part  of  the  work  of  M.  Buchez  is  that  which  treats  of  the 
aim,  foundation,  and  methods  of  the  science  of  history.  It 
appears  to  be,  on  the  whole,  worthy  of  much  commendation. 
As  a  contribution  to  the  methodology  of  historical  science  or 
philosophy  it  has  not  received  the  attention  and  recognition 
which  are  its  due. 

Pierre  Leroux  was  born  at  Paris  in  1798.  His  parents 
were  Breton  peasants,  and  his  sympathies  with  the  peasant 
class  were  always  keen  and  strong.  He  received  the  elements 
of  a  good  education  at  Paris  and  Rennes;  and  he  showed 
throughout  life  much  more  aptitude  for  learning  than  for 
practical  affairs.  After  having  been  for  some  time  a  printer, 
he  became  a  contributor  to  the  'Globe.'  With  the  other 
members  of  its  staff  he  helped  to  bring  about  the  July  Revo- 


LEEOUX  431 

lution  of  1830.  In  that  year  he  joined  the  Saint-Simonian 
school,  and  had  influence  enough  to  make  the  '  Globe '  its 
organ.  But  the  ideas  of  Enfantin  on  marriage  and  female 
messiahship  forced  him  to  secede  before  he  had  been  two  years 
in  the  society.  He  set  himself,  in  consequence,  the  more 
earnestly  to  deepen  and  extend  his  knowledge ;  to  examine 
the  systems  of  philosophy  which  had  acquired  most  reputa- 
tion in  the  past  or  were  enjoying  it  in  the  present ;  and  to 
elaborate  a  social  doctrine  of  his  own.  One  result  of  these 
studies  was  the  '  Refutation  de  l'dclectisme,'  1839,  a  severe 
criticism  of  the  principles  of  Cousin.  It  was  received  with 
great  favour  by  all  sections  of  the  socialistic  party,  and  was 
certainly  not  devoid  of  ability ;  but  it  lacked  moderation  and 
impartiality,  insight  into  the  nature  of  the  system  assailed 
and  power  of  philosophical  discrimination.  Being  far  from 
just  it  was  far  from  conclusive. 

Leroux  was  almost  industrious  publicist,  and,  between  the 
years  1834  and  1848,  edited  or  co-edited  the  '  Revue  Encyclo- 
pe"dique,'  the  '  Encyclope"die  Nouvelle,'  the  '  Revue  Inde"pen- 
dante,'  and  the  '  Revue  Sociale.'  He  issued  besides  many 
books,  of  which  it  may  suffice  to  name  the  following :  '  De 
1'EgaliteY  1838 ;  '  De  1'HumaniteV  1840,  2e  e"d.  1845 ;  '  Sept 
discours  sur  la  situation  actuelle  de  la  socie'te'  et  de  l'esprit 
humain,'  1841 ;  '  De  la  doctrine  de  la  perfectibility  et  du 
progr^s  continu,'  1845 ;  and  '  Du  Christianisme  et  de  ses 
origines  de"mocratiques,'  1848.  Through  these  works  he 
became  the  recognised  founder  of  a  form  of  socialism  called 
Humanitarianism,  which  was  much  the  fashion  in  Paris  for 
some  years,  and  which  had  one  persuasive  prophet  at  least, 
Madame  Georges  Sand. 

The  celebrity  he  had  thus  acquired,  and  the  character  of 
his  political  views,  led  to  his  being  elected  in  1848  a  member 
of  the  National  Constituent  Assembly.  There,  however,  he 
was  sadly  out  of  his  place ;  and,  it  was  affirmed,  rather  abused 
his  position,  by  giving  wearisome  expositions  of  iiis  system, 
and  even  reading  chapters  out  of  his  own  books,  instead  of 
speaking  to  the  points  under  discussion.  Hence  one  day  a 
member  gravely  moved  that  no  books  should  be  read  at  the 
tribune ;    and  on  another,  when  the  subject  of  debate  was 


432  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Algeria,  General  Lamorici&re,  rising  immediately  after  the 
philosopher,  remarked  that  M.  Leroux  had  taken  them  all 
through  the  histories  of  Greece  and  Rome,  but  had  forgotten 
the  Arabs,  and  he  hoped  the  Assembly  would  allow  him  to 
endeavour  to  supply  the  omission,  as  the  Arabs  were  some- 
what interested  in  questions  connected  with  Algeria.  Driven 
into  exile  in  1851,  he  lived  for  some  years  in  Jersey,  and 
afterwards  at  Lausanne,  until  the  general  amnesty  of  1869 
permitted  him  to  return  to  France.  He  was  a  genial  and 
benevolent  man,  who  had  amassed  much  knowledge,  and 
whose  brain  was  full  of  ideas  as  to  the  advancement  of 
science,  the  renovation  of  religion,  and  the  organisation  of 
society ;  but  he  was  a  hazy  and  confused  thinker,  very  apt 
not  to  prove  what  he  maintained,  and  often  laying  himself 
open  to  ridicule  by  the  absurdity  of  his  hypotheses.  He  died 
at  Paris  in  the  sad  and  evil  April  of  1871. 

The  most  important  of  his  works  is  the  '  De  l'HumaniteV 
It  contains  all  that  is  essential  in  his  social  and  historical 
theory,  but  the  '  Refutation  of  Eclecticism '  may  almost  be 
considered  as  an  introduction  to  it.  He  singled  out  eclecti- 
cism as  an  example  of  systems  based  on  the  psychological 
analysis  of  the  individual  consciousness ;  a  process  which  he 
held  could  only  lead  to  delusion,  the  individual  conscious- 
ness or  Ego  being  a  mere  abstraction,  devoid  of  real  exist- 
ence. The  fundamental  error  and  weakness  of  the  dominant 
philosophy,  he  thought,  was  forgetfulness  of  the  fact  that  the 
individual  mind  only  exists  as  a  part  of  a  whole,  and  can  only 
be  studied  in  the  whole  of  which  it  is  a  part.  The  life  of 
each  man,  he  insisted,  does  not  belong  to  him  absolutely,  and 
is  not  in  him  simply,  but  is  in  him  and  without  him,  through 
an  incessant  communication  with  his  fellows  and  the  uni- 
verse :  the  thoughts,  feelings,  principles,  beliefs  of  each  man 
do  not  spring  up  originally  in  the  individual  mind,  but  are 
received  as  a  part  of  the  universal  truth  of  mankind.  The 
history  of  humanity,  he  maintained,  is  the  direct  object  of 
philosophy,  the  true  basis  of  the  science  of  life.  He  took  up, 
in  fact,  much  the  same  attitude  towards  the  psychological 
method  in  philosophy  as  the  writers  of  the  theological  school 
and  M.  Comte. 


LEROTJX  433 

Now  we  may  grant  that  he  had  some  reason  for  doing  so, 
the  psychological  method  having  been  often  explained  and 
applied  in  a  narrow,  one-sided,  and  deceptive  way.  We  may 
grant,  and  I  believe  must  grant,  that  the  analysis  of  the  in- 
dividual consciousness  requires  to  'be  both  confirmed  and 
supplemented  by  objective  observation  of  various  kinds ;  that 
the  consciousness  of  the  race  and  not  of  the  individual  is  the 
true  subject  of  mental  science  in  all  its  branches ;  and  that  if 
it  attempt  to  proceed  entirely  from  within,  ignoring  the  com- 
binations of  human  nature  which  are  presented  in  history, 
literature,  and  language,  and  which  ought  to  be  employed  as 
the  materials  of  analysis  and  induction,  it  must  inevitably  fail. 
But  it  must  be  an  even  more  fatal  error  of  method  to  en- 
deavour to  discover  the  laws  of  human  nature  by  any  process 
which  has  not  psychological  analysis  as  its  basis  and  animating 
principle.  No  immediate  or  direct  apprehension  of  the  facts 
in  which  these  laws  are  manifested  is  possible  by  any  form  of 
outward  observation,  since  what  is  presented  to  outward  ob- 
servation is  always  mere  movements  of  matter,  not  facts  of 
human  nature  at  all.  The  signs  and  expressions  of  conscious- 
ness can  only  be  recognised  as  such,  and  interpreted,  through 
the  subjective  experience  of  conscious  states  corresponding 
to  those  signified  and  expressed.  In  opposing  one  error  of 
method,  then,  M.  Leroux  fell  into  another  and  greater  error. 

Passing  from  his  method  to  his  doctrine,  it  is  to  be  observed, 
in  the  first  place,  that  he  rests  his  theory  of  human  develop- 
ment on  a  definition  of  human  nature.  The  only  adequate 
definition  of  man,  according  to  him,  is  "  an  animal  transformed 
by  reason,  and  united  to  humanity."  Man  is  not  a  mere 
animal  —  i.e.,  a  being  endowed  simply  with  sensation  and 
sentiment,  nor  even  an  animal  with  reason,  an  animal  plus 
reason ;  he  is  a  unity  of  sensation,  sentiment,  and  reason,  and 
not  a  combination  of  them  formed  by  mere  addition.  M.  Le- 
roux attaches  the  greatest  importance  to  this  proposition,  and 
ascribes  most  of  the  failures  of  previous  systems  of  political 
and  historical  philosophy  to  the  denial  or  imperfect  apprehen- 
sion of  it.  Thus,  he  thinks,  Plato  saw  in  man  only  reason ; 
Hobbes,  only  appetite ;  and  Rousseau,  only  sentiment  or  will : 
and  these  three  errors  all  naturally  led  to  despotism  as  the 


434  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IK   FRANCE 

ideal  of  social  life ;  that  of  Plato  to  a  theocracy,  that  of  Hobbes 
to  an  absolute  monarchy,  and  that  of  Rousseau  to  the  unlimited 
subjection  of  the  individual  to  the  community.  He  (M.  Le- 
roux)  believes  himself  to  have  been  the  first  to  apprehend 
what  man  is,  at  once  in  the  unity  and  entirety  of  his  nature, 
and  so  to  have  been  the  first  to  enter  the  path  which  leads  to 
an  adequate  theory  of  historical  development  and  social  life. 

Man  is  not  only  an  animal  transformed  by  reason,  but "  united 
to  humanity."  The  end  for  which  he  is  destined  can  only  be 
known  through  a  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  humanity,  and 
is,  in  fact,  no  other  than  the  full  development  of  entire 
humanity  which  constitutes  progress,  and  in  which  the  Eternal 
Essence  and  the  Creative  Principle  of  the  universe  reveals 
itself.  M.  Leroux  is  a  firm  believer  in  continuous  progress.  He 
discards  the  Saint-Simonian  view  of  the  alternation  of  organic 
and  critical,  constructive  and  destructive  periods.  He  sup- 
poses that  where  intelligence  may  not  be  advancing  the  affec- 
tions are  growing,  and  that,  in  the  course  of  generations,  ideas 
are  changed  into  faculties,  which  would  remain  although  all 
the  products  of  human  reason  were  swept  from  the  face  of  the 
earth  by  some  great  convulsion  of  nature ;  and  that  thus, 
notwithstanding  many  appearances  to  the  contrary,  there  is 
everywhere,  and  always,  progress.1  He  records  what  Bacon, 
Descartes,  Pascal,  Fontenelle,  Herder,  and  others  have  done 
for  this  idea,  and  claims  to  crown  their  labours  by  what  he 
calls  the  axiom  of  solidarity.  It  is  a  rather  curious  axiom, 
has  extraordinary  consequences,  and  probably  needs  much 
more  exposition  than  I  can  afford  to  give  it.2 

It  means  that  entire  humanity  is  one  vast  society,  of  which 
all  nations,  tribes,  communities,  and  men,  are,  in  their  several 
places  and  degrees,  parts,  which  cannot  attempt  to  separate 
from  the  other  parts,  and  to  isolate  themselves,  without  violat- 
ing reason  and  producing  evil ;  but  it  means  more  —  viz.,  that 
men  are  fragments  or  portions  of  an  infinite   and  eternal 

1  See  '  De  l'Humanite,'  1.  i.  ch.  iv.,  and  especially  the  essay,  "  De  la  Loi  de 
Continuity, "  &c,  in  the  Rev.  Encye.,  1833. 

2  It  is  explained  at  length  in  '  De  l'Humanite,'  1.  iv.  v. ;  while  the  whole  of  the 
second,  and  a  considerable  part  of  the  first,  volume  of  that  work,  is  an  attempt  to 
prove  that  the  ancients  universally  believed,  more  or  less  clearly,  in  the  reappear- 
ance and  revival  of  the  individual  in  the  race,  of  man  in  humanity. 


LEROUX  435 

Being,  the  all-present,  all-pervading  world-soul,  and  identical 
in  essence  ;  so  that  in  seeing  one  man  we  see  all  other  men,  so 
that  in  seeing  Peter  we  see  also  Paul,  so  that  Confucius  and 
Newton  lived  in  one  another  no  less  than  in  themselves.  It 
means  that  the  men  of  the  present  are  the  very  men  who  were 
in  the  past,  and  who  will  be  in  the  future ; 1  that  a  child  born 
brings  with  it  into  the  world  only  a  soul  which  has  already 
lived ;  that  each  of  us  reappears,  after  death,  on  the  earth  in 
the  form  of  a  child.  The  solidarity  of  men,  as  taught  by 
M.  Leroux,  thus  involves  the  doctrine  of  the  transmigration  of 
souls,  and  represents  humanity  as  a  succession  of  generations, 
not  of  different  individuals,  but  of  the  same  individuals.2 
Humanity  is  immortal,  and  so  is  each  individual  of  which  it  is 
composed ;  but  humanity  has  no  destiny  except  on  the  earth, 
and  the  individual  no  destiny  except  in  humanity.  The  indi- 
vidual carries  with  him  into  each  new  stage  of  existence  no 
remembrance  of  what  he  experienced  in  anterior  states.  The 
remembrance  of  such  experience,  M.  Leroux  thinks,  would 
be  no  boon,  but  an  intolerable  burden.  Those  who  wish  it 
are  as  foolish  as  the  miser  who  desires  to  carry  his  gold  with 
him  when  he  dies.  Memory  is  but  a  superficial  property  ;  it 
belongs  not  to  our  essential  life.     The  old  Greeks  knew  its 

1  The  title  of  ch.  xii.  1.  5°,  'De  l'Humanite,'  runs  thus:  "Nous  sommes  non 
seulement  les  fils  et  la  posterite  de  ceux  qui  out  deja  vecu,  mais  au  fond  et 
reellement  ces  generations  anterieures  elles-memes." 

2  As  an  advocate  of  the  doctrine  of  transmigration,  M.  Leroux  was  far  sur- 
passed by  his  friend  M.  Reynaud  (1806-1863),  the  celebrated  author  of  'Terre  et 
Ciel.'  The  hypothesis  has  perhaps  never  been  presented  in  a  more  attractive 
form  than  in  this  work.  M.  Reynaud  does  not,  like  Leroux,  assign  to  souls  a 
succession  of  merely  terrestrial  lives.  Wonderfully  combining  science  and  imagi- 
nation, Ingenuity  and  eloquence,  he  argues  that  the  medieval  conception  of 
heaven,  earth,  and  hell  has  been  for  ever  discredited  by  the  enlarged  views  of 
the  universe  which  modern  science  has  given  us;  that  the  true  heaven  is  the 
heaven  of  astronomy,  the  heaven  of  stars  of  which  earth  is  one,  a  heaven  which 
has  no  limit  in  space  or  time ;  and  that  in  this  heaven  souls  pass  through  an  end- 
less and  ever-varying  existence,  the  path  of  the  just  being  ever  upwards,  from 
star  to  star,  as  they  continually  approach,  without  ever  completely  attaining  to, 
the  perfect  life  of  the  God-man  Christ,  while  failure  and  sin  involve  the  most 
manifold  deflections  from  the  straight  course,  with  the  sufferings  and  penalties 
which  follow  as  their  natural  consequences.  Into  our  planet  spirits  who  have 
transgressed  in  some  other  come  as  into  a  place  at  once  of  probation  and  of  ex- 
piation. All  of  them  share  in  the  guilt  and  punishment  of  the  sin  of  Adam, 
because  all  of  them  have  committed  it  in  a  distant  age.  M.  Reynaud's  book  had 
an  immense  success  in  France,  and  deserved  it.  However  erroneous  or  question- 
able its  teaching  may  be,  the  genius  which  it  displays  is  great  and  undeniable. 


436  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IF   FRANCE 

character  better  than  we,  when  they  represented  those  who 
went  into  the  under  world  as  drinking  out  of  Lethe,  the  river  ' 
of  forge tfuln ess.     The  slumber  and  oblivion  of  death  are  as 
refreshing  and  strengthening  as  those  of  nightly  rest.1 

It  is  obvious  that  the  axiom  of  solidarity,  as  explained  by 
M.  Leroux,  must  tend  to  magnify  the  importance  of  the  idea 
of  progress.  It  seemed  to  himself  to  raise  that  idea  to  the 
rank  of  a  religious  doctrine.  And  it  certainly  leaves  no  room 
for  any  other  religious  doctrines.  It  proves,  if  true,  that  no 
hopes  or  fears  are  warranted  except  those  which  are  involved 
in  the  earthly  destiny  of  collective  humanity.  All  hopes  and 
fears  not  thus  warranted  are  now,  according  to  the  teaching 
of  M.  Leroux,  unnecessary.  Morality  once  needed  the  stimu- 
lus of  everlasting  reward,  and  the  restraint  of  everlasting 
punishment,  but  faith  in  social  progress  is  now  sufficient. 
"  There  is  no  heaven  or  hell,"  cries  our  author :  "  the  wicked 
will  not  be  punished,  nor  the  good  rewarded ;  cease,  mortals, 
to  hope  or  fear.  Humanity  is  an  immortal  tree,  the  branches 
of  which  wither  and  fall,  one  after  another,  but  in  doing  so 
nourish  the  root  in  unfading  youth." 

The  course  of  progress  is  described  as  a  continuous  advance 
towards  equality.  It  is  apprehended  chiefly,  if  not  entirely, 
in  its  negative  aspect,  as  a  deliverance  from  class  distinctions, 
an  abolition  of  unjust  privileges.  It  has  had  three  great 
stages,  corresponding  to  the  three  chief  forms  of  caste.  In 
the  first,  the  task  of  humanity  was  its  self-deliverance  from 
the  slavery  of  the  family,  the  patriarchal  caste  of  the  oriental 
world ;  in  the  second,  from  the  despotism  of  the  state,  as  ex- 
emplified in  the  political  caste  of  Greece  and  Rome ;  and  in 
the  third,  from  the  tyranny  of  property,  and  all  the  medieval 
privileges  associated  therewith.  It  is  at  the  close  of  this 
third  epoch  that  we  are  standing  now ;  and,  with  a  view  to 
the  reorganisation  of  society  in  the  future,  it  specially  behoves 
us  to  remember  that  the  family,  the  state,  and  property,  are 
all  in  themselves  good,  and  that  only  when  they  assume  the 
form,  and  involve  the  distinctions  of  caste,  are  they  evil. 

1  M.  Leroux  devotes  three  chapters  to  repel  the  objection  to  his  doctrine, 
drawn  from  the  fact  that  men  have  no  remembrance  of  their  pre-existence ;  and 
to  maintain  that  the  want  of  such  remembrance  is  more  than  supplied  by  latent 
or  innate  powers,  and  new  conditions  of  existence.  —  L.  v.  c.  xiii.-xv. 


BLANC  437 

"  Tout  le  mal  du  genre  humain  vient  des  castes.  La  famille 
est  un  bien,  la  famille  caste  est  un  mai ;  la  patrie  est  un  bien, 
la  patrie  caste  est  un  mal;  la  propri^te"  est  un  bien,  la  pro- 
prie'te'  caste  est  un  mal."  Future  progress  must  lie  in  reject- 
ing the  evil  but  retaining  and  organising  the  good,  alike  in 
the  family,  the  state,  and  property.  Especially  is  organisa- 
tion of  the  good  needed  in  the  period  of  history  at  which 
we  have  arrived.  The  equality  of  all  men  before  the  law 
has  come  to  be  recognised.  The  greatest  of  revolutions,  the 
French  Revolution  of  1789,  established  it  as  a  principle,  and 
so  inaugurated  a  new  and  better  era  of  history.  The  new 
form  of  society,  however,  is  not  yet  constituted,  although  its 
principle  has  been  found.  The  generation  in  which  we  live 
is  one  without  faith,  law,  or  system.  The  old  order  is  broken 
down,  but  the  new  has  not  been  built  up.1 


Ill 

Louis  Blanc  (1813-1882)  is  entitled  to  a  prominent  place 
in  the  history  of  socialism,  inasmuch  as  he  greatly  advanced 
the  socialistic  cause  by  separating  the  problem  of  the  organi- 
sation of  labour  from  such  dreamy  and  fantastic  theories  as 
those  in  which  Fourier,  Buchez,  and  Leroux  indulged,  by 
putting  forward  so  definite  and  plausible  a  proposal  as  that  of 
State-aided  industrial  co-operation,  and  by  advocating  it  with 
remarkable  literary  and  oratorical  talent.  He  was  not,  how- 
ever, a  philosophical  thinker ;  and  his  philosophy  of  history 
does  not  deserve  more  than  the  briefest  statement.  The  fol- 
lowing sentences  taken  from  the  first  pages  of  the  'Histoire 
de  la  Revolution  Franchise '  present  it  to  us  in  his  own 
words :  — 

"History  nowhere  begins  or  ends.  The  facts  which  compose  the  con- 
tents of  the  movement  of  the  world  exhibit  such  confusion,  and  then- 
relations  with  one  another  are  so  obscure,  that  neither  the  first  cause 
nor  the  final  issue  of  any  event  can  be  indicated  with  certainty.  Their 
•beginning  and  ending  are  in  God  — that  is,  in  the  unknown."2 

"  Three  great  principles  have,  one  after  another,  ruled  the  world  and 

1  The  theory  of  M.  Leroux  regarding  the  historical  evolution  of  humanity  and 
its  stages  will  be  found  in  the  preface,  and  second  and  third  books,  of  'L'Human- 
ite','  but  more  fully  in  the  '  Essai  sur  l'l^galite. '  2  P.  1. 


438  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   EST   FRANCE 

history:  Authority,  Individualism,  and  Fraternity.  .  .  The  principle 
of  authority  is  that  which  rests  the  life  of  nations  on  beliefs  blindly 
accepted,  a  superstitious  regard  for  tradition,  and  inequality ;  and  which 
employs  constraint  as  its  means  of  government.  The  principle  of  indi- 
vidualism is  that  which  isolates  man  from  society ;  constitutes  him  the 
sole  judge  of  his  surrounding  and  of  himself ;  gives  him  a  lofty  opinion 
of  his  rights  while  not  pointing  out  to  him  his  duties;  abandons  him  to 
his  own  resources ;  and  proclaims  laisser-faire  as  the  sum  and  substance  of 
government.  The  principle  of  fraternity  is  that  which,  considering  those 
who  belong  to  the  great  family  of  mankind  members  one  of  another,  tends 
to  organise  societies,  the  work  of  man,  after  the  model  of  the  human  body, 
the  work  of  God ;  and  bases  government  on  persuasion,  on  the  voluntary 
consent  of  hearts.  Authority  has  been  employed  with  astonishing  eclat 
by  Catholicism;  it  prevailed  until  Luther  appeared.  Individualism,  in- 
augurated by  Luther,  developed  with  irresistible  force ;  and,  freed  from 
the  religious  element,  triumphed  in  France  through  the  publicists  of  the 
Constituent  Assembly.  It  rules  the  present;  it  is  the  soul  of  things. 
Fraternity,  announced  by  the  thinkers  of  the  Mountain,  disappeared  at 
that  time  in  a  tempest,  and  appears  to  us  even  at  present  only  in  the 
ideals  of  the  future ;  but  all  great  hearts  evoke  it,  and  already  it  illum- 
ines the  highest  sphere  of  intellects.  Of  these  three  principles,  the  first 
engenders  oppression  by  stifling  personality ;  the  second  leads  to  oppres- 
sion through  anarchy;  the  third  alone  brings  forth  liberty  through 
harmony." J  . 

What  M.  Blanc  here  represents  as  the  principles  of  author- 
ity and  of  individualism  are  merely  abuses  of  the  principles 
of  order  and  of  liberty:  two  principles  which  are  necessary 
to  each  other,  and  which  have  always  coexisted  to  some  extent. 
Authority  was  resisted  and  restrained  by  individualism  even 
in  the  middle  age.  Feudalism  was  a  manifestation  of  inde- 
pendence as  well  as  of  obedience ;  and  so,  although  in  another 
form,  was  the  Church.  No  institution  in  history  has  tended 
more  than  feudalism  to  isolate  and  individualise  men  of  the 
ruling  class ;  and  none  has  been  more  effective  than  the  Church 
in  limiting  the  sphere  of  the  State,  and  withdrawing  a  large 
portion  of  human  life  from  its  control.  The  honour  of  an- 
nouncing fraternity  ought  certainly  not  to  be  assigned  to  men 
who  so  lavishly  murdered  their  brethren  as  did  Robespierre 
and  the  so-called  penseurs  de  la  Montague.  No  one  has  ever 
proclaimed  the  principle  of  human  brotherhood  more  clearly 
and  fully  than  the  founder  of  the  Christian  Church,  and  that 

1  Pp.  9,  10. 


BLANC  —  PEOTJDHON  439 

Church  has  always  both  taught  and  practised  it  in  some 
measure. 

M.  Blanc  has  endeavoured  to  trace  the  rise  and  growth  of 
"  individualism  "  in  France  :  to  show  how  it  gradually  acquired 
supremacy  in  the  domains  of  religion,  philosophy,  politics,  and 
industry ;  how  it  sapped  the  authority  of  the  monarchy  and  , 
nobility,  and  made  the  bourgeoisie  the  ruling  power  in  the 
nation ;  and  how,  in  conjunction  with  the  spirit  of  fraternity,  ' 
it  produced  the  Revolution  and  destroyed  the  old  order  of  so- 
ciety. His  socialism,  however,  made  him  incapable  of  rightly 
appreciating  liberty,  and  caused  him  often  to  condemn  it  as 
individualism,  and  to  ascribe  to  it  evils  which  were  not  its 
natural  consequences,  or  which  even  arose  from  its  absence  or 
violation.  What  he  states  as  facts,  indeed,  are  almost  always 
real  facts  and  truly  stated ;  but  they  are  selected  and  often 
misinterpreted  facts,  insufficient  to  establish  the  general  con- 
clusions drawn  from  them.  M.  Blanc  obviously  comprehended 
very  imperfectly  the  teaching  of  Hus.  He  displays  little  of 
the  insight  into  the  genius  and  influence  of  the  Reformation 
and  of  Calvinism  so  conspicuously  manifested  both  by  Ranke 
and  Mignet.  He  indicates  well  the  services  of  Richelieu,  but 
overlooks  the  mischievous  tendencies  of  his  policy.  He  char- 
acterises the  historical  personages  whom  he  deems  the  repre- 
sentatives of  individualism  chiefly  by  their  defects ;  and  those 
whom  he  regards  as  the  prophets  of  fraternity  almost  entirely 
by  their  best  qualities,  or  their  mere  professions,  or  the  grand 
and  generous  intentions  which  he  himself  attributes  to  them. 
He  vigorously  denounces  the  Terror  as  at  once  wicked  and 
foolish,  yet,  in  part  and  by  implication,  justifies  it  in  repre- 
senting it  as  an  inevitable  fatality.  For  so  representing  it 
he  certainly  gives  no  solid  reasons.  Some  of  the  guiltiest  of 
the  Terrorists  he  portrays  as  the  prophets,  heroes,  and  martyrs 
of  the  faith  which  is  to  save  society  and  to  rule  the  future. 

The  historical  philosophy  of  M.  Blanc  is  so  feeble,  so 
meagre,  and  so  vague  that  I  must  npt  dwell  on  it  further. 

The  socialistic  theorists  whose  historical  speculations  have 
been  under  consideration  in  this  chapter  had  no  keener  or 
more  outspoken  opponent  than  P.  J.  Proudhon  (1804-69), 


440  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

who  was  commonly  regarded  as  himself  the  most  extreme 
and  dangerous  of  socialists,  although  he  was  really  much 
more  of  an  extravagant  individualist.     He  was  very  radical 
and  revolutionary :  his  social  ideal  was  an-archy,  —  absolute 
equality,  the  absence  of  government,  —  which  he  held  was 
not  to  be  confounded  with  anarchy  —  i.e.,  chaos  or  disorder. 
Possessed  of  rare  ability  as  a  polemic,  and  reckless  of  re- 
straints in  regard  to  the  manner  of  exercising  it,  he  assailed 
and  ridiculed  with  tremendous  effect  the  doctrines  of  the 
Saint-Simonians  and  Fourierists,  of  Leroux  and  Louis  Blanc. 
Unfortunately  he  was  as  indulgent  a  judge  of  his  own  ideas 
as  he  was  a  severe  critic  of  those  of  other  people.     Besides, 
he  changed  his  opinions  very  often  ;  indulged  most  liberally 
in   exaggerated  statements   and  in  self-contradiction ;  pro- 
claimed that  he  had  got  possession  of  truths  when  he  was 
merely  hoping  to  find  them  ;  and  never  did  attain  the  proved 
and  definitive  system  which  he  sought  for.     He  loved  to 
startle  the  public  by  audacious  propositions,  la  propriety,  c'est 
le  vol;  Dieu,  c'est  le  mal,  and  the  like,  —  regardless  of  the 
misconceptions  which  they  would  cause  and  of  the  needless 
offence  which  they  would  give.     Yet  he  was  not  only  a  man 
of  great  talent  but  of  many  estimable  qualities  of  character. 
In  the  most  violent  of  his  controversies  he  took  no  mean  ad- 
vantages and  showed  no  malignity;   although  intensely  in 
sympathy  with  the  working  classes,  far  from  flattering  them, 
like  Lamartine,   Ledru   Rollin,  Louis   Blanc,  and  so  many 
others,  he  never  hesitated  to  tell  them  the  most  disagreeable 
truths  in  the  plainest  way ;  notwithstanding  his  avowed  con- 
tempt for  women  in  general  he  showed  due  respect  for  them 
individually,  and  was  an  excellent  husband  and  the  affec- 
tionate father  of  two  daughters;  and  rigid  honesty,  abhor- 
rence of  licentiousness,  helpfulness  to  the  unfortunate,  and 
absolute  faith  in  justice,  were  among  his  most  prominent 
traits.     He  had  an  original  and  resourceful  intellect,  a  rich 
and  good  nature,  and  remarkable  literary  gifts,  but  was  so 
deficient  in  self-restraint  and  patience,  calmness  and  modera- 
tion, that  the  fruits  of  his  mind  and  activity  never  ripened, 
but  were  forced  to  appear  as  crude  and  undeveloped  thoughts, 
abortive  schemes  and  efforts,  or  even  outbursts  of  passion, 


PKOUDHON  441 

vanity,  and  impiety,  which  did  great  injustice  alike  to  his 
talents  and  to  his  deeper  and  better  self.1 

Proudhon  has  in  several  of  his  writings  treated  of  history. 
His  '  De  la  Creation  de  l'Ordre  dans  l'Humanite' '  (3d  ed., 
1849)  has  for  its  central  and  ruling  conception  an  historical 
hypothesis.  It  is,  however,  one  directly  borrowed,  although 
without  explicit  acknowledgment,  from  Comte.  Proudhon 
expressed  it  thus  :  "  Religion,  philosophy,  science ;  faith, 
sophistic,  and  method ;  such  are  the  three  moments  of  knowl- 
edge, the  three  epochs  of  the  education  of  the  human  race."  2 
He  endeavoured  to  prove  it  by  a  somewhat  lengthened  ex- 
amination of  religion  and  philosophy,  and  concludes  in  the 
following  terms :  — 

"  Without  religion  humanity  would  have  perished  at  its  birth;  without 
philosophy  it  would  have  remained  in  an  eternal  infancy :  but  the  opinion 
that  religion  and  philosophy  have  meant  anything  more  than  a  particular 
state  of  consciousness  and  intelligence  has  been  the  worst  malady  of  the 
human  mind.  Religion  and  philosophy,  conceived  of,  the  first  as  a  reve- 
lation of  divine  dogmas,  the  second  as  the  science  of  causes,  have  filled 
the  earth  with  fanatics  and  fools.  ...  A  little  of  philosophy  has  always 
mingled  with  religion ;  a  breath  of  religion  has  always  penetrated  phi- 
losophy. Christianity  was  a  philosophical  religion,  the  most  philosophi- 
cal of  religions :  Confucius,  Plato,  the  apostle  Paul,  Rousseau,  Bernardin 
de  Saint-Pierre,  Chateaubriand,  have  been  religious  philosophers.  Their 
writings  are  immortal :  but  of  all  the  things  which  it  most  concerns  us 
to  know,  and  of  which  they  have  sometimes  spoken  with  an  eloquence 
so  grand,  they  have  known  nothing,  and  have  taught  us  nothing;  and 
the  combination  of  contrary  qualities  which  we  observe  in  them  has  been 
without  profit  to  science.  How  great,  then,  is  the  illusion  of  those  who 
now  speak  of  uniting,  as  two  realities,  philosophy  and  religion  ?  Theology 
has  fallen,  sophistic  has  been  struck  dead  :  there  is  no  more  religion,  there 
is  no  philosophy."  8 

Having  reached  this  result  M.  Proudhon  forthwith  proceeds 
to  expound  a  philosophy  of  his  own,  akin  to  the  philosophy 
of  Comte,  although  directly  drawn  to  a  greater  extent  from 
the  teaching  of  Kant,  Fourier,  and  Ampere.  It  is  a  sort  of 
theory  or  logic  of  science,  and  he  calls  it  Metaphysics,  not 

1  The  character  of  Proudhon  can  be  best  studied  in  his  '  Correspondance,'  14 
vols.,  1875.    Besides  the  articles  of  Ferraz  (op,  cit.),  Renouvier  (Crit.  phil.),  and 
Franck  (Diet.),  see  Sainte-Beuve's  '  Proudhon,  sa  vie  et  sa  correspondance,'  1872. 
2  P.  10.  s  p.  96. 


442  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

improbably  just  because  of  Comte's  repudiation  of  the  term. 
He  next  treats  of  what  he  designates  Political  Economy,  but 
by  which  he  means  all  science  that  bears  on  economical, 
political,  and  social  organisation.  The  laws  of  Political 
Economy  thus  understood  he  holds  to  be  the  laws  of  his- 
tory :  and  thus  is  led  to  set  forth  his  views  on  history  (pp. 
340-404). 

He  defines  it  as  "  the  succession  of  states  through  which 
the  mind  and  society  pass  before  the  former  attains  pure 
science  and  the  latter  the  realisation  of  its  laws."  He  argues 
that  it  is  properly  speaking  not  science,  but  only  matter  of 
science ;  and  that  it  is  an  evolution  the  laws  of  which  are 
those  that  Political  Economy  ought  to  ascertain  and  expound. 
He  throws  out  a  considerable  number  of  interesting  remarks 
and  plausible  generalisations  regarding  the  movement  of  his- 
tory under  the  action  of  these  laws,  and  the  perturbations 
which  follow  from  their  violation;  but  he  fails  to  combine 
them  into  any  consistent  whole.  The  general  impression 
produced  is  confused  and  disappointing.  He  follows  Saint- 
Simon  and  Fourier  in  attempting  to  elucidate  history  by  the 
conception  of  the  series,  and,  as  he  supposes,  Hegel  by  apply- 
ing to  its  evolution  the  formula  of  thesis,  antithesis,  and 
synthesis. 

In  the  work  just  referred  to,  Proudhon  has  treated  of  the 
notion  and  fact  of  progress  at  considerable  length,  but  with 
arbitrary  ingenuity,  uselessly  quibbling  over  mere  words  and 
phrases,  and  arriving  at  no  clear  general  result.  He  has,  how- 
ever, dealt  with  the  subject  in  a  far  more  able  and  satisfactory 
manner  in  his  later  and  much  more  important  work,  '  De  la 
Justice  dans  la  Revolution  et  dans  l'Eglise.'  Here  he  has 
shown  with  great  effectiveness  the  vagueness,  superficiality, 
and  exaggerations  of  the  representations  given  of  progress  by 
ordinary  theorists  and  eulogists ;  and  has  traced  them  to  their 
source,  a  want  of  insight  into  what  human  progress  really  is. 
It  does  not  follow  that  there  must  be  such  progress  because 
population  or  wealth  is  increasing,  or  because  the  arts  and 
sciences  are  advancing.  While  any  or  all  of  these  things  are 
happening,  man  himself  may  be  deteriorating;  he  may  be 
losing  in  independence,  in  virtue,  in  manhood.     But  the  true 


PEOUDHON  443 

progress  of  man  implies  the  true  progress  of  men  ;  and,  there- 
fore, can  only  be  their  own  work,  and  must  be  inclusive  espe- 
cially of  what  distinguishes  them  as  men.  Its  chief  criteria 
must  be  found  not  in  what  is  external  to  or  independent  of 
man,  but  in  what  is  most  essentially  his  own  and  constitutive 
of  himself,  —  liberty  and  justice.  All  development  which  is 
not  due  to  man's  own  energy,  and  which  does  not  tend  towards 
justice  in  all  the  relations  of  life,  must  be  merely  an  illusory 
semblance  of  progress.  True  historical  progress,  having  for 
its  condition  freedom  and  for  its  end  the  establishment  of  jus- 
tice, may  be  denned  as  "  la  justification  de  l'humanite"  par  elle- 
m§me  sous  l'excitation  de  l'ide'al."  It  is  no  organic  evolution 
or  inevitable  necessity :  decadence  is  possible,  and  has  often 
occurred;  it  takes  place  whenever  justice  is  only  feebly  and 
partially  sought  for,  or  when  any  other  ideal  is  preferred  to 
that  of  justice.  For  Proudhon,  justice  consists  of  equality, 
and  whatever  creates  inequality  is  unjust.  Hence,  while  a 
decided  opponent  of  communism,  he  was  also  an  enemy  of 
property  in  land,  of  the  exclusive  possession  by  individuals 
of  the  instruments  of  labour,  and  of  the  remuneration  of  work 
according  to  any  other  scale  than  duration.  He  clearly  saw, 
however,  what  communists  have  almost  always  failed  to  see, 
that  the  pursuit  of  equality  as  the  ideal  of  justice  could  not 
lead  to  wealth  but  to  indigence  :  that,  for  example,  were  his 
ideal  obtained,  the  annual  income  of  France  could  not  give 
more  than  three  francs  per  day  to  each  French  family  of 
four  persons;  and  consequently,  that  the  existing  state  of 
variety  of  fortunes  in  the  nation  would  be  replaced  not  by  one 
of  abundance  for  all,  but  by  one  of  universal  poverty.  But 
this  caused  him  neither  fear  nor  regret.  Always  poor,  always 
laborious,  he  never  complained  either  of  poverty  or  of  labour. 
He  held  that  labour  requires  poverty  and  that  poverty  is  the 
condition  of  labour;  that  they  are  naturally  conjoined,  and 
that  both  are  necessary  to  the  moral  development  of  man. 
He  indulged  in  no  excesses  of  sentimentalism  over  the  toils 
and  hardships  of  the  poor ;  he  -was  fierce  in  his  denunciations 
of  the  frivolity,  the  luxury,  and  the  immorality  of  the  rich. 
Wealth,  not  poverty,  was  in  his  eyes  the  evil  which  had  to 
be  overcome ;  the  evil  which  corrupts  individuals  and  ruins 
communities. 


444  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Proudhon's  intense  conviction  of  the  reality  and  supremacy 
of  moral  law  was  what  gave  its  chief  attraction  and  value  to  the 
historical  theory  expounded  in  his  '  De  la  Justice.'  A  narrow 
and  extreme  view  of  its  all-sufficiency  and  exclusive  legitimacy 
was  the  source  of  its  most  pervading  defect.  He  unnaturally 
opposed  justice  to  piety,  morality  to  religion.  He  contended 
that  the  decay  of  faith  was  the  indispensable  condition  of  the 
development  both  of  reason  and  of  virtue  ;  and  that  all  history 
teaches  the  necessity  of  getting  rid  of  religion.  His  histori- 
cal theory  is  thus,  while  profoundly  moral,  thoroughly  anti- 
religious.  The  book  in  which  he  has  most  fully  expounded 
it  is  a  continuous  assault  on  religion;  representing  it  as  a 
power  which  invariably  perverts  reason  and  conscience,  and 
produces  weakness  and  disorder  in  society.1 

In  his  '  La  Guerre  et  la  Paix,'  Proudhon  committed  himself 
to  a  defence  of  the  right  of  force  and  of  conquest  which  cannot 
be  reconciled  with  faithful  adherence  to  the  principle  of  jus- 
tice. The  view  which  he  has  there  given  of  war  as  a  means 
of  peace  is  one  which  history  certainly  does  not  confirm. 

He  was  a  strenuous  opponent  of  the  principle  of  nationality, 
which  has  attracted  so  much  attention  and  exerted  so  much 
influence  in  the  nineteenth  century.  He  did  not  regret  the  de- 
struction of  Poland,  and  he  regarded  the  restoration  of  Italy 
as  a  deplorable  error.  He  believed  the  dissolution  of  all  ex- 
tant nationalities  into  small  communities  to  be  indispensable 
to  the  attainment  of  a  truly  free  and  just  condition  of  society. 
The  State  he  regarded  as  incompatible  with  liberty  and  equality, 
and  as,  like  religion,  a  most  formidable  obstacle  to  progress. 
He  believed  that  what  was  needed  was  its  destruction,  not  its 
mere  reformation ;  that  social  life  could  only  be  what  it  ought 
to  be  when  the  very  idea  of  the  State  had  been  cast  out  of  the 
mind  as  a  pernicious  idol,  and  when  all  that  had  been  built  on 
it — legislation  and  administration,  kings,  senates,  tribunals, 
diplomacy,  armies,  &c.  —  had  disappeared.     He  wished  that 

1  Proudhon's  teaching  in  favour  of  the  separation  of  morality  from  religion  and 
philosophy  was  adopted  by  a  school  or  party  which  had  for  some  years  an  organ 
in  the  weekly  press  of  Paris,  'La  Morale  Inde'pendante,'  1865-69.  Its  chief  con- 
tributors were  Mme.  Coignet  and  MM.  Massol  and  Morin.  For  an  examination 
of  the  fundamental  theses  maintained  in  it,  see  E.  Caro,  '  Problemes  de  Morale 
Sociale,'  ch.  i.-iii. 


PROUDHON  445 

there  should  be  no  social  authority  whatever;  that  there  should 
be  only  free  associations  of  workmen.  It  was  because  he  held 
this  doctrine  that  he  called  himself  an  an-arohist.  As  he  was 
the  first  to  present  it  with  clearness,  he  has  the  best  claim  to 
be  considered  the  founder  of  Anarchism.1 

The  Anarchism  of  Proudhon  forms  a  striking  contrast  to  the 
Positive  Sociocracy  of  Comte.  These  two  systems  represent 
the  antithetic  extremes  of  social  theorising.  The  one  springs 
from  an  exaggerated  and  exclusive  conception  of  liberty,  and 
the  other  from  an  equally  exaggerated  and  exclusive  concep- 
tion of  authority.  Yet  both  led  their  authors  to  contemplate 
with  satisfaction  the  prospect  of  national  dismemberment. 
They  agreed,  although  on  very  different  grounds,  in  desiring 
that  existing  nations  should  be  broken  up  into  smaller  com- 
munities concerning  themselves  chiefly  or  entirely  with  indus- 
trial interests.  Wherein  they  differed  was  that  while  Comte 
approved  of  states  of  small  size,  because  only  such  could,  in 
his  opinion,  be  adequately  influenced  and  effectively  con- 
trolled by  the  positivist  priests  and  bankers  in  whose  hands 
he  hoped  to  see  all  spiritual  and  civil  authority  invested, 
Proudhon  desired  communes  of  limited  extent,  because  he 
believed  that  only  such  could  dispense  with  authority  and 
organise  themselves  freely  by  association.2  Proudhon  has 
expounded  his  theory  in  a  special  work,  '  De  la  F^ddration.' 
And  the  theory  there  presented  as  the  complement  of  Anar- 
chism has  had  a  far  greater  influence  on  practical  politics  than 
when  exhibited  in  its  Comtist  form  as  a  corollary  from  Soci- 
ocracy ;  but  its  influence  has  been  the  reverse  of  beneficent. 
Propagated  by  so  fanatical  and  reckless  an  apostle  as  Bakunin, 
arid  adopted  by  Russian  anarchists,  Parisian  communists,  and 

1  Anarchism  has  gained  a  large  host  of  adherents,  and  assumed  a  variety  of 
forms.  Russia,  owing  to  easily  perceptible  causes,  has  been  its  chief  hotbed  and 
nursery.  Its  history,  so  full  of  political  and  pathological  interest,  has  necessarily 
as  yet  been  only  very  partially  and  superficially  traced.  Almost  all  self-conscious 
revolutionary  radicalism  is  in  the  present  day  either  anarchist  or  collectivism 
Anarchists  look  for  no  good  from  the  State,  and  seek  to  destroy  it.  Collectivists 
expect  everything  from  the  State,  and  strive  to  make  it  omnipotent. 

2  Fourier,  by  his  advocacy  of  the  division  and  distribution  of  Europe  into 
phalansteres,  had  preceded  Comte  and  Proudhon  in  sacrificing  historical  nations 
to  small,  independent,  and  self-sufficing  industrial  societies,  federatively  con- 
nected. 


446  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Spanish  Federalists,  it  has  been  a  source  of  serious  disturb- 
ance and  disaster  in  the  Europe  of  recent  years. 

The  doctrine  favourable  to  small  states  or  communities  has 
found  at  least  three  ingenious  and  cultured  advocates  in 
France,  the  geographer  Elise  Reclus,  and  the  journalists 
Justin  Drommel  and  Odysse-Barot.  It  has  been  expounded 
with  special  attractiveness  and  skill  in  the  '  Lettres  sur  la 
philosophie  de  l'histoire,'  1864,  of  the  last-mentioned  writer, 
and  with  the  consideration  of  it  as  there  presented  I  shall 
conclude  my  account  of  the  historical  speculations  to  which 
French  socialism  has  given  rise.1 

The  first  nine  letters  of  M.  Barot  deal  with  war  and  peace, 
military  genius,  the  superiority  of  Frederick  the  Great  to 
Caesar  and  Napoleon,  diplomacy,  treaties,  and  congresses. 
Their  connecting  thought  is  that  society  is  constituted  by 
two  principles  —  force  and  justice — of  which  the  former 
leads  to  war  and  finds  expression  in  battles,  while  the  latter 
tends  to  peace  and  finds  expression  in  treaties.  These  two 
principles  are  compared  to  positive  and  negative  electricity, 
the  warm  and  cold  currents  of  the  Gulf  Stream,  the  ebb 
and  flow  of  the  sea,  the  male  and  female,  &c.  They  are  held 
to  be  equally  necessary,  since  the  one  supplements  and  com- 
pletes the  other,  since  right  without  force  and  force  without 
right  are  alike  nugatory  and  sterile.  But  force  is  described 
as  the  more  prevalent.  M.  Barot  has  counted,  he  says,  the 
years  of  war  and  peace  and  the  treaties  concluded  and  broken 
from  the  fifteenth  century  before  Christ  to  the  present  time, 
and  has  found  that  there  have  been  3130  years  of  war  to  227 
of  peace,  and  8397  treaties  sworn  to  be  eternally  observed, 
the  mean  duration  of  the  eternities  of  which  has  been  two 

1  M.  Odysse-Barot  was  an  active  coadjutor  Oi"  the  late  M.  Emile  de  Girardin  in 
'LaPresse,'  '  La  Liberte,'  and  'La  France.'  In  1871,  he  was  secretary  of  Gus- 
tave  Flourens  and  editor  of  '  Le  Fe"deraliste ' ;  and  from  1871  to  1874,  an  exile 
in  England.  His  '  Histoire  de  la  litterature  contemporaine  en  Angleterre,'  1864, 
is  a  work  of  exceptional  merit.  His  '  Letters  on  the  Philosophy  of  History '  ap- 
peared at  first  in  'La  Presse,'  and  were  addressed  to  M.  de  Girardin,  whose 
criticism  of  them  is  appended  to  the  volume  of  the  '  Bibliotheque  de  Philosophie 
Contemporaine,'  in  which  they  were  republished  in  1864.  As  the  criticism  as- 
sumes that  there  is  no  difference  between  fact  and  right,  and  some  other  peculiar 
fancies  of  M.  de  Girardin,  it  is  even  less  satisfactory  than  the  theory  criticised. 


ODYSSE-BAROT  447 

years.  War,  lie  contends,  is  not  accidental  or  contingent, 
but  universal  and  necessary,  having  its  primary  cause  in  the 
essential  nature  of  man,  and  its  final  cause  in  the  essential 
nature  of  things.  The  progress  of  civilisation  has,  in  his 
opinion,  no  tendency  to  destroy  or  even  to  diminish  it. 

With  the  tenth  letter  we  reach  the  kernel  of  his  theory. 
He  here  tells  us  that  historical  study  has  three  stages,  the 
empirical,  the  critical,  and  the  philosophical,  or  the  stages  of 
fact,  method,  and  law,  of  observation,  classification,  and  gen- 
eralisation ;  that  it  has  now  reached  the  second  but  not  the 
third  of  these  stages ;  that  important  materials,  however,  for 
a  philosophy  of  history  have  been  collected  and  prepared ; 
and  that  the  general  conclusion  which  he  himself  proposes 
to  expound  is  the  result  of  ten  years'  research  and  reflection. 
He  then  attacks  the  notion  that  France  is  a  single  national- 
ity, and  that  French  unity  has  existed  for  ages.  He  insists 
that,  on  the  contrary,  France  is  only  a  geographical  expres- 
sion, and  French  unity  a  quite  recent  creation. 

In  the  next  letter  M.  Barot  proceeds  with  his  proof.  He 
regards  every  State  in  Europe,  except  Portugal,  Belgium, 
Holland,  and  Switzerland,  as  not  a  nationality,  but  "  a  com- 
posite  of  heterogeneous  elements,  a  Macedonia  of  peoples,  an 
ethnological  harlequin,  a  social  mosaic."  He  tells  briefly 
the  story  of  the  formation  of  the  British  empire  through  the 
union  of  Wales,  Ireland,  and  Scotland  with  England;  and 
gives  a  very  interesting  account  of  the  slow  and  painful 
process  by  which  what  is  called  France  was  built  up  on  the 
ruins  of  the  independence  of  Normandy,  Provence,  Guienne, 
Gascony,  Lorraine,  and  Brittany.  Of  course,  he  lays  the 
greatest  possible  emphasis  on  the  fact  that  each  of  the  differ- 
ent peoples  incorporated  into  Britain  and  France  still  retains 
its  distinctive  character  and  feelings. 

He  commences  the  twelfth  letter  with  the  prophecy  that 
perhaps  before  the  end  of  the  century,  and  certainly  before  a 
hundred  years  have  passed,  the  great  States  of  Europe  will 
be  dismembered ;  that  factitious  nationalities  will  have  given 
place  to  real  nationalities ;  that  Britain,  for  example,  will  be 
redistributed  into  four  kingdoms,  and  France  broken  up  into 
five  States  —  France  proper,  Brittany,  Aquitaine,  Burgundy, 


448  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

and  Lorraine.  Such  is  the  inevitable  conclusion,  he  argues, 
of  two  principles  which  have  taken  root  in  the  world,  and 
can  neither  be  arrested  nor  eradicated,  —  the  principle  of  de- 
centralisation and  the  principle  of  nationalities ;  the  former 
meaning  dismemberment,  and  the  latter  the  system  of  small 
or  natural  States,  as  opposed  to  that  of  artificial  or  agglom- 
erated States.  But  what  is  a  natural  State  ?  a  true  or  simple 
nationality?  It  is,  M.  Odysse-Barot  asserts,  neither  a  lin- 
guistic, nor  an  ethnological,  nor  a  religious,  nor  a  moral  fact, 
nor  a  combination  of  these  four  orders  of  facts,  but  a  purely- 
geographical  fact.  "  Une  nationality,  c'est  un  bassin."  The 
centre,  the  axis,  of  a  real  nation  is  a  river.  This,  we  are  told, 
is  a  law  which  has  no  exception ;  and  an  attempt  is  made  to 
show  that  geology  and  climatology  accord  with  history  in 
recommending  the  distribution  of  peoples  according  to  basins. 

In  the  following  chapter  a  second  so-called  law  is  deduced 
from  the  first:  "Une  frontidre,  c'est  une  montagne."  The 
two  alleged  laws  are  said  completely  to  define  what  a  natural 
nationality  is.  Then  a  third  law  is  laid  down  as  determining 
the  whole  course  of  the  historical  movement.  "  The  world 
oscillates  between  two  systems  of  society;  simple  and  com- 
pound societies;  natural  nationalities  and  artificial  agglom- 
erations ;  peoples  with  frontiers  and  peoples  without  them ; 
the  system  of  small  states  and  the  system  of  great  empires." 
These  two  systems,  according  to  M.  Barot,  regularly  alternate, 
and  historical  progress  is  little  else  than  the  periodical  return 
of  the  same  facts  and  ideas.  The  system  of  agglomeration 
or  of  great  empires  being  at  present  at  its  height,  must  be 
speedily  succeeded  by  that  of  true  nationalities.  A  confed- 
eration of  such  nationalities  is  what  Europe  will  present  in 
the  near  future.  Small  and  natural  States  are  those  which 
are  most  favourable  to  civilisation  and  liberty,  to  material 
and  moral  wellbeing. 

Such  is  the  theory  of  M.  Odysss-Barot.  It  seems  to  me 
that  he  has  wholly  failed  to  establish  it.  He  has  been  partic- 
ularly unfortunate  in  his  search  for  "  laws."  The  first  two 
of  his  so-called  laws  are  plainly  not  of  the  nature  of  laws  at 
all ;  they  are  merely  attempts,  and  very  unsuccessful  attempts, 
at  definition.  The  third  might  reasonably  pass  for  a  law  were 
it  proved ;  but  it  is  not  proved. 


ODYSSE-BAEOT  449 

"  Nationality  is  a  river-basin."  This  is  affirmed  to  be  a  law 
without  exception.  In  reality,  it  is  a  paradoxical  assertion 
forced  to  serve  as  a  definition.  To  give  it  some  appearance 
of  truth,  our  author  finds  it  requisite  to  deny  that  there  are 
any  but  three  real  nations  in  Europe.  Perhaps  he  should 
have  gone  further,  and  denied  that  there  are  any  real  nations 
in  the  world.  Even  Egypt  is  not  with  strictness  a  basin, 
being  bounded  not  by  mountains  but  by  a  desert  and  a  sea. 
If  Great  Britain  were  divided  according  to  basins,  it  would 
contain  far  more  States  than  four.  But  Great  Britain  never 
was  divided  in  that  way ;  nor,  so  far  as  I  can  discover,  has 
any  country  of  Europe  been  so  divided  within  historical 
times ;  and  certainly  none  has  since  national  feeling  made  its 
appearance  in  history. 

"  A  natural  boundary  is  a  mountain."  This  so-called  law 
is  of  precisely  the  same  character  as  the  previous  one :  an 
attempt  not  to  formulate  a  law  but  to  define  a  fact,  and  an 
attempt  which  fails.  Any  line  of  demarcation  whatever  be- 
tween two  nations  is  a  natural  boundary ;  for  what  makes  a 
boundary  natural  is  nothing  in  itself,  but  the  circumstance 
that  it  separates  distinct  nations.  The  line  of  contact  is  the 
natural  boundary,  whether  it  be  mountain,  or  river,  or  sea,  or 
even  merely  a  hedge  or  ditch.  M.  Odysse-Barot  regards  the 
sea  as  an  unnatural  boundary ;  but  assuredly  the  inhabitants 
of  Great  Britain  will  not  be  found  to  agree  with  him.  It  is 
deeply  to  be  regretted,  indeed,  that  the  principle  of  national- 
ity should  ever  have  been  associated  with  the  dogma  of  so- 
called  natural  boundaries.  The  association,  or  confusion, 
may  be  traced  chiefly  to  an  obscure  and  unscrupulous  party 
in  France  before  the  Franco-German  war,  who  wished  their 
country  to  have  the  Rhine  for  a  boundary ;  and,  under  the 
name  of  the  Monroe  doctrine,  to  a  similar  party  in  America, 
who  wished  the  whole  North  American  continent  to  become 
the  seat  of  a  single  great  republic.  The  theory  advocated  by 
these  parties  amounted  to  the  virtual  affirmation  of  an  almost 
universal  right  of  international  robbery,  since  Russia,  Prus- 
sia, Bavaria,  Austria,  and  many  other  nations,  have  no  more 
natural  boundaries  than  the  United  States  or  France.  The 
theory  of  M.  Barot,  although  it  equally  conjoins  the  principle 


450  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

of  nationality  with  the  hypothesis  of  natural  boundaries,  is 
not  fairly  chargeable  with  affording  either  a  provocation  to 
international  robbery,  or  a  justification  of  such  robbery.  The 
nations,  however,  which  venture  to  act  on  it  cannot  fail  to 
be  thereby  involved  in  the  horrors  of  civil  war. 

The  two  fictitious  laws  referred  to  reduce  nationality,  as 
M.  Barot  himself  says,  to  "  a  geographical  fact."  But  who 
does  not  see  that  this  is  a  one-sided  and  exaggerated,  a  mean 
and  narrow,  view  of  nationality;  and  that  geography,  like 
race,  language,  religion,  and  unity  of  government,  is  merely 
one  of  the  factors  which  contribute  to  form  nationality? 
Geographical  limits,  identity  of  race  and  descent,  community 
of  speech  and  faith,  the  same  government  and  the  same  polit- 
ical antecedents,  participation  in  the  same  triumphs  and  the 
same  disasters,  all  conduce  to  the  rise  and  growth  of  nation- 
ality. Yet  not  one  of  them  constitutes  it,  and  not  one  of  them 
will  infallibly  and  in  all  circumstances  generate  it.  It  arises 
from  the  action  of  many  and  various  causes.  It  is  no  natural 
quality,  and  no  necessary  product  of  natural  forces,  but  a 
spiritual  creation,  a  result  of  intellectual  and  moral  develop- 
ment, merely  influenced  by  natural  forces  and  outward  cir- 
cumstances. To  this  extent  all  nationality  is  artificial,  and  it 
suffices  to  show  that  the  distinction  between  natural  and 
artificial  nationalities  as  drawn  by  M.  Barot  is  inherently 
untenable. 

For  the  third  alleged  law  —  "  the  world  oscillates  between 
a  system  of  small  States  and  a  system  of  great  empires "  — 
no  historical  proof  is  attempted.  But  without  ample  proof  we 
must  decline  to  accept  a  proposition  which  identifies  progress 
with  oscillation,  development  with  the  incessant  recurrence  of 
the  same  facts  and  ideas.  M.  Odysse-Barot  has  so  much  faith 
in  its  truth  that  the  prevalence  of  the  system  of  large  States 
appears  to  him  enough  of  itself  to  warrant  his  prediction  of  the 
near  advent  of  a  system  of  small  States.  It  does  not  seem  to 
have  occurred  to  him  that  the  former  system  is  a  natural 
expression  of  economical  and  social  conditions  which  are  not 
likely  to  pass  away  in  the  course  of  a  century ;  that  it  is  im- 
plied in  railways  and  telegraphs,  and  the  gigantic  proportions 
of  modern  industry  and  commerce,  as  well  as  of  modern  war, 


ODYSSE-BAROT  451 

and  will  prevail  so  long  as  these  continue.  Divide  France  into 
five  independent  nations  to-day,  and  the  work  of  unification, 
by  fair  means  and  foul,  by  force,  fraud,  and  honest  exertion, 
will  commence  to-morrow.  A  great  empire  is  now  not  more 
difficult  to  govern  than  a  small  State  was  formerly,  while  the 
disadvantages  of  small  States  are  more  numerous  and  decided. 

A  great  European  war  would  obviously  tend  not  to  destroy 
but  to  develop  the  prevalent  system.  The  disintegration  or 
dismemberment  which  is  predicated  will  require  to  be  realised, 
therefore,  by  an  internal  movement,  by  the  irresistible  enthu- 
siasm of  the  populations  of  large  empires  for  reorganisation 
according  to  "  basins."  But  are  "  basins  "  at  all  likely  so  to 
inflame  the  imaginations  of  men?  Is  "a  banner  with  the 
strange  device  "  "  Basins  "  at  all  likely  so  to  terrify  or  so  to 
charm  the  powers  that  be  in  Russia,  Prussia,  and  Austria,  in 
France,  and  Italy,  and  England,  that  they  will  hasten  to  parcel 
out  their  kingdoms  into  "  natural  nationalities,"  and  forthwith 
retire  in  favour  of  Governments  which  can  have  only  a  frac- 
tion of  their  strength  ?  What  probability  is  there  of  Russia 
dividing  herself  according  to  river-basins,  even  if  she  possessed 
mountains  enough  to  serve  as  natural  boundaries  to  the  terri- 
tories through  which  they  flow  ?  And  if  Russia  does  not,  how 
can  Prussia  ?     And  if  Prussia  does  not,  how  can  France  ? 

It  is  true,  as  M.  Odysse-Barot  points  out,  that  a  general 
movement  in  favour  of  decentralisation  is  discernible.  But 
why  should  it  end,  as  he  infers  it  must,  in  dismemberment  ? 
Most  peoples  are  suffering  more  or  less  from  undue  centrali- 
sation, and  nature  and  reason  are  prompting  them  to  seek  a 
remedy  for  the  evil.  But  the  remedy  for  one  evil  is  not  another 
evil,  although  its  contrary.  The  remedy  for  the  evils  of  exces- 
sive centralisation  is  not  dismemberment,  but  simply  a  reason- 
able decentralisation,  the  limitation  of  the  central  power,  and 
the  leaving  to  provinces  and  municipalities  the  management 
of  properly  provincial  and  municipal  affairs.  It  is  to  add  to 
the  advantages  of  general  unity  those  of  local  and  personal 
liberty,  and  to  avoid  excesses  on  either  side. 


CHAPTER  VIII 

SPIRITUALISTIC   MOVEMENT:     SO-CALLED   ECLECTIC   AND 
DOCTRINARIAN   HISTORICAL   PHILOSOPHY 


The  Theocratic  movement  in  the  France  of  the  nineteenth 
century  was  mainly  a  reaction  from  the  mode  of  treating  relig- 
ion and  religious  authority  prevalent  in  the  eighteenth  cen- 
tury. The  Socialistic  movement  originated  in  a  recoil  from 
the  ethical  and  politico-economic  principles  and  ideals  which 
gained  ascendancy  in  the  same  period.  There  was,  however, 
another  and  profounder  movement ;  one  which  started  with 
rejection  of  the  exclusive  sensationalism  and  negative  ration- 
alism implied  in  the  religious  and  social  theories  against 
which  Theocracy  and  Socialism  were  protests. 

This  movement  of  philosophical  reaction  and  revival  found 
a  brilliant  leader  in  Victor  Cousin  (1792-1867).  He  began 
to  teach  philosophy  when  twenty-three  years  of  age,  and  in 
singularly  conspicuous  and  influential  positions.  His  philo- 
sophical studies  had  been  brief  and  slight,  so  that  he  had 
largely  to  learn  what  he  taught  while  teaching  it,  and  in  the 
intervals  of  leisure  which  a  jealous  Government  gave  him  by 
suspending  his  courses.  He  had  to  borrow  largely  from  such 
sources  as  were  most  easily  accessible  to  him,  and  probably 
often  required  to  extemporise  his  thoughts  as  well  as  his 
words.  When  forty  years  of  age  his  career  as  a  public  teacher 
of  philosophy,  and  also  as  a  productive  speculative  thinker, 
was  brought  to  a  close,  and  gave  place  to  one  of  political  and 
administrative  activity.  Thenceforth,  although  he  long 
powerfully  influenced  the  fortunes  of  philosophy  in  France, 
it  was  as  an  educational  reformer,  the  defender  of  the  liberties 
of  the  university  against  the  assaults  of  Ultramontanism,  the 
dispenser  of  the  patronage  of  chairs  of  philosophy,  and  the 
452 


cousin  453 

incessant  and  sagacious  exciter  of  others  to  philosophical 
research  and  labour.  That  the  philosophy  which  he  pro- 
pounded in  the  courses  of  lectures  delivered  by  him  between 
1815  and  1833  should  have  been  one  far  from  quite  consistent 
with  itself  at  all  stages  of  its  evolution,  or  either  thoroughly 
thought  out  as  a  whole,  or  carefully  enough  tested  in  many 
of  its  details,  was  inevitable.  But  that  it  had  also  remark- 
able merits  which  go  far  to  explain  and  justify  its  extraor- 
dinary success,  and  that  its  influence  on  the  thought  of 
France  was  in  the  highest  degree  stimulating,  must  in  justice 
be  admitted. 

Cousin  made  apparent  how  inadequate  the  theory  of 
knowledge  of  the  ideologists  was  in  itself,  and  as  a  basis 
for  philosophy.  He  set  forth  with  a  powerful  and  attractive 
eloquence  a  view  of  philosophy  which  showed  how  compre- 
hensive and  important  it  really  is,  and  what  its  true  place 
and  functions  are  in  human  life  and  universal  history.  He 
contended  for  a  method  of  philosophical  investigation  appro- 
priate in  its  character  to  the  nature,  and  conformed  in  its  proc- 
esses to  the  variety  and  vastness,  of  philosophy  itself;  and 
traced  to  defectiveness  of  method  what  is  erroneous  in  empiri- 
cism and  transcendentalism,  scepticism  and  mysticism.  He 
showed  more  truthfully  than  had  been  previously  done  how 
philosophy  is  related  to  its  own  history.  He  drew  a  luminous 
and  masterly  general  sketch  of  that  history,  and  instituted 
into  special  points  and  particular  sections  of  it  original  in- 
vestigations which  were,  perhaps,  none  the  less  fruitful  for 
being  fragmentary.  He  translated  and  interpreted  Plato; 
commented  on  Aristotle ;  edited  Proclus,  Abelard,  and  Des- 
cartes; promoted  the  study  in  France  of  Reid,  Stewart,  and 
Hamilton,  of  Kant,  Schelling,  and  Hegel;  and  instigated 
a  host  of  gifted  men  to  rethink  for  the  benefit  of  their  con- 
temporaries all  past  philosophies, — -to  reproduce,  criticise, 
and  judge,  in  new  conditions  and  under  fresh  and  fuller 
lights,  the  views  and  systems  of  the  great  thinkers  of  human- 
ity in  all  lands  and  ages.  He  expounded  with  consummate 
literary  skill  in  the  most  celebrated  of  his  philosophical 
writings,  'Du  Vrai,  du  Beau,  et  du  Bien,'  the  main  conclu- 
sions at  which  he  had  arrived  in  psychology,  in  metaphysics 


454  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

and  theodicy,  in  ethics,  and  in  esthetics.  As  regards  psy- 
chology, his  proof  of  the  irreducibility  of  sensation,  will,  and 
reason  to  a  single  principle  was  of  vital  importance;  his 
account  of  intelligence  as  spontaneous  and  reflective  had  much 
influence ;  and  his  theory  of  the  impersonality  of  reason  was 
worthy  of  all  the  attention  which  it  has  received.  As  to 
metaphysics  and  theodicy,  he  based  them  on  the  most  solid 
foundations,  gave  prominence  to  the  truths  which  deserved 
it,  and  committed  himself  to  the  defence  of  few  untenable 
positions.  Alike  as  regards  spirit  and  substance  his  ethical 
teaching  was  admirable.  And  although  his  solutions  of  the 
chief  problems  of  esthetics  were  vague  and  inadequate,  his 
criticisms  of  antecedent  and  contemporary  theories  were 
relevant  and  decisive,  and  prepared  the  way  for  such  inves- 
tigations as  those  to  which  we  owe  the  'Cours  d'Esthe'tique' 
of  Jouffroy  and  'La  Science  du  Beau'  of  LSvSque. 

Notwithstanding  what  I  have  just  said,  I  admit  that 
Cousin  was  much  better  qualified  to  draw  up  philosophical 
programmes  than  to  realise  them ;  that  he  showed  little  taste 
for  psychological  research;  that  he  was  not  a  metaphysician 
of  the  first  order;  that  he  overlooked  the  connections  of 
physical  science  with  philosophy;  and  that  he  sometimes 
made  fine  words  pass  for  great  thoughts,  and  displayed  his 
rhetorical  gifts  to  excess.  Hence  in  the  representation  of 
him  given  by  Taine  and  Lewes  there  is  the  modicum  of  truth 
which  is  indispensable  to  give  verisimilitude  to  caricature. 
A  gross  caricature,  however,  it  is,  and  not  a  portrait  of  the 
man,  who  is  justly  entitled  to  be  regarded  as  the  most  nota- 
ble and  influential  personage  in  far  the  most  comprehensive 
and  fruitful  philosophical  movement  which  France  has  felt 
in  the  nineteenth  century.1 

1  See  on  Cousin  the  '  Eloges '  of  Mignet  and  Jules  Favre ;  Taine, '  Philosophes 
fran9ais ' ;  Renan,  '  Essais  de  morale  et  de  critique  ' ;  Frauck,  '  Moralistes  et 
philosophes,'  and  '  Nouveaux  essais  de  critique  philosophique ' ;  Caro,  '  Philo- 
sophic et  philosophes ' ;  and  especially  Paul  Janet,  '  Victor  Cousin  et  son  oeuvre,' 
1885,  and  Jules  Simon,  '  Victor  Cousin,'  1887.  His  general  philosophy  has  been 
treated  of  by  Damiron,  Bersot,  Alaux,  Secretan,  Ravaisson,  Ferraz,  &c.  He  has 
himself  described  in  the  famous  prefaces  to  the  first  two  editions  of  his  '  Frag- 
ments '  the  successive  steps  of  his  philosophical  career  with  great  candour,  and 
with  a  truth  which  can  be  easily  substantiated  by  an  examination  of  bis  works 
in  their  chronological  order. 


COTJSLN  455 

The  greatest  service  rendered  by  Cousin  to  philosophy 
was  one  which  was  also  a  direct  service  to  the  philosophy  of 
history.  It  was  the  impulse  which  he  gave  to  a  truly  philo- 
sophical and  at  the  same  time  truly  historical  study  of  the 
history  of  philosophy.  With  marvellous  success  he  induced 
men  to  interest  themselves  in  the  history  of  philosophy  as 
being  philosophy  itself  in  the  process  of  evolution;  and  to 
study  it  as  such  in  a  free,  critical,  and  impartial  spirit.  It 
will  be  said,  and  with  perfect  justice,  that  Hegel  had  preceded 
him  in  so  conceiving  of  the  relation  of  philosophy  to  its  his- 
tory ;  and  that  he  had  even  applied  his  conception  by  treating 
of  the  history  of  philosophy  with  a  profundity  and  subtlety 
of  which  Cousin  was  incapable.  But  in  this  reference  a  very 
important  difference  between  them  must  be  noted.  Hegel 
went  to  the  history  of  philosophy  in  order  to  show  that  its 
whole  evolution  was  an  exemplification  of  the  philosophy 
which  he  had  elaborated;  Cousin  went  to  it  in  order  to  be 
guided  to  a  philosophy  which  he  wished  to  discover.  Hegel 
construed  the  history  to  make  it  conform  to  his  speculative 
conclusions;  Cousin  was  content  to  study  it  without  any 
other  assumption  than  that  if  examined  impartially  and  com- 
prehensively it  would  lead  to  the  discovery  of  a  catholic 
eclecticism  which  would  separate  the  true  from  the  false  in 
,  all  anterior  systems,  and  harmonise  all  truths  in  them  which 
had  hitherto  appeared  inconsistent  and  antagonistic.  This, 
however,  is  equivalent  to  saying  that  Hegel's  method  of 
treating  the  history  of  philosophy  was  directly  anti-scientific 
and  unreasonable,  while  Cousin's  was  legitimate  and  appro- 
priate. 

It  was  in  the  lectures  delivered  at  Paris  in  1828  to  an 
admiring  audience  of  two  thousand  persons  that  he  pro- 
pounded his  historical  theories ;  and  it  is  only  with  that  part 
of  his  system  which  relates  to  history  that  I  mean  to  deal. 
It  was  the  last  part  added,  and  it  is  that  on  which  the  influ- 
ence of  Hegel  is  most  apparent.  As  regards  this  influence, 
it  must  be  remembered  that  although  Hegel's  'Philosophy  of 
History '  was  only  published  in  1837,  Cousin  was  not  only 
acquainted  with  the  outlines  of  world-history  contained  in 
the  '  Encyclopaedia '  (1817)  and  the  '  Philosophy  of  Right ' 


456  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOEY   IN   FRANCE 

(1820);  but  during  a  stay  of  some  months  at  Berlin  in 
1824-25  had  met  Hegel,  and  become  intimate  with  some  of 
his  most  zealous  disciples,  Gans,  Hotho,  Henning,  and 
Michelet ;  and  again  in  1827  had  enjoyed  a  month  of  Hegel's 
society  in  Paris.  It  is  very  probable,  therefore,  that  Cousin 
derived  his  views  on  historical  optimism,  war,  great  men, 
and  some  of  the  other  subjects  treated  by  him. in  the  'Cours 
de  1828 '  directly  or  indirectly  from  Hegel.  Certainly  his 
intercourse  with  Hegel  must  have  confirmed  him  in  them. 
As  he  has  generally  stated  them  with  more  clearness  and  more 
appearance  of  proof  than  Hegel,  I  shall  discuss  them  as  he 
has  presented  them,  and  shall  not  consider  it  necessary  to 
dwell  on  them  when  Hegel  comes  under  review. 

The  general  aim  of  the  first  three  lectures  is  to  determine 
the  place  of  philosophy  and  of  its  history  within  universal 
history.  Psychological  analysis  is  maintained  to  be  indis- 
pensable to  the  accomplishment  of  the  task.  The  various 
manifestations  and  phases  of  social  life  are  all  traced  back  to 
the  tendencies  of  human  nature  from  which  they  spring;  to 
five  fundamental  wants,  each  of  which  has  corresponding  to  it 
a  general  idea.  The  idea  of  the  useful  gives  rise  to  mathe- 
matical and  physical  science,  industry  and  political  economy; 
the  idea  of  the  just  to  civil  society,  the  State,  and  jurispru- 
dence ;  the  idea  of  the  beautiful  to  art ;  the  idea  of  God  to 
religion  and  worship ;  arid  the  idea  of  truth  in  itself,  in  its 
highest  degree  and  under  its  purest  form,  to  philosophy. 
These  ideas  are  argued  to  be  simple  and  indecomposable ;  to 
coexist  in  every  mind ;  to  constitute  the  whole  foundation  of 
humanity;  and  to  follow  in  the  order  mentioned.  But  if 
human  nature  manifests  itself  in  the  individual,  it  manifests 
itself  also  in  the  race,  the  history  of  which  is,  in  fact,  but  the 
representation  of  human  nature  on  a  great  scale.  There  is  in 
the  race  only  the  elements  which  are  in  the  individual.  The 
unity  of  civilisation  is  in  the  unity  of  human  nature;  its 
varieties  are  in  the  variety  of  the  elements  of  that  nature. 
All  that  is  in  human  nature  passes  into  the  movement  of 
civilisation,  to  subsist,  organise  itself,  and  prospers,  if  essen- 
tial and  necessary,  but  soon  to  be  extinguished  if  accidental 
and  individual.     Therefore,  as  human  nature  is  the  matter 


cousin  457 

and  the  base  of  history,  history  is,  so  to  speak,  the  judge 
of  human  nature,  and  historical  analysis  is  the  counterproof 
of  psychological  analysis.  History,  called  in  to  the  help  of 
analysis,  shows  us  that  civilisation — the  magnified  image  of 
human  nature  —  includes  at  all  epochs  a  philosophic  element, 
which  has  a  distinct,  always  subsisting,  and  continually 
increasing  part  or  history  on  the  stage  of  the  world ;  and  that 
what  philosophy  is  to  the  other  elements  of  human  nature  and 
civilisation,  the  history  of  philosophy  is  to  the  other  branches 
of  universal  history.  It  shows  us  that  the  history  of  philoso- 
phy is  the  last  of  all  the  developments  of  history,  but  superior 
to  them  all, —  the  only  one  in  which  humanity  knows  itself 
fully,  with  all  its  elements  borne,  as  it  were,  to  their  highest 
power,  and  set  in  their  truest  and  clearest  light. 

In  the  fourth  lecture  M.  Cousin  treats  of  the  psychological 
method  in  history.  He  argues  that  the  historical  method  can 
be  neither  exclusively  empirical  nor  exclusively  speculative, 
by  which  he  means  deductive,  but  both  in  union ;  and  that, 
combining  speculation  with  empiricism  in  a  legitimate  man- 
ner, it  must  start  from  the  human  reason,  enumerate  com- 
pletely its  elements,  reduce  them  by  a  severely  scientific 
analysis  to  the  lowest  number  possible,  determine  their 
relationship,  and  follow  their  development  in  history,  with 
the  hope  of  discovering  that  the  historical  development  is  an 
expression  of  the  internal  development  of  reason.  Accord- 
ingly, he  sets  about  laying  the  foundation  of  this  method  by 
a  study  of  the  categories  of  thought.  He  reaches  the  result 
that  in  the  last  analysis  the  constitutive  and  regulative 
principles  of  reason  are  three :  the  idea  of  the  infinite,  other- 
wise called  unity,  substance,  the  absolute,  &c. ;  the  idea  of 
the  finite,  likewise  designated  plurality,  difference,  phenom- 
enon, relative  existence,  the  conditioned,  &c. ;  and  the  idea 
of  the  relation  between  the  infinite  and  the  finite,  a  relation 
which  so  unites  the  two  terms  that  they  are  inseparable,  and, 
along  with  itself,  constitute,  at  the  same  time,  a  triplicity 
and  an  indivisible  unity.1 

1  It  has  been  considered  expedient  to  distinguish  the  expository  and  critical 
portions  of  this  chapter  by  printing  the  former  in  larger,  and  the  latter  in 
smaller,  print. 


458  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FBANCE 

Cousin  had  the  great  merit  of  seeing  that  psychology  and  the  philos- 
ophy of  history  are  intimately  related.  He  perceived  that  the  latter  has 
its  root  in  the  former ;  that  the  science  of  history  is  properly  a  psycho- 
logical science;  that  it  presupposes  a  knowledge  of  the  fundamental 
powers,  affections,  and  laws  of  the  human  mind  and  character ;  and  that 
historical  analysis  may  supplement  and  correct,  but  can  neither  be  severed 
from  nor  substituted  for  psychological  analysis.  Probably  no  one  before 
him  had  seen  so  clearly  that  "  necessity  of  connecting  all  our  generalisa- 
tions from  history  with  the  laws  of  humau  nature,"  the  honour  of  recog- 
nising which  J.  S.  Mill  most  erroneously  ascribed  to  "M.  Comte  alone, 
among  the  new  historical  school." 

It  must  be  admitted,  however,  that  Cousin  was  far  from  entirely  faith- 
ful to  his  own  doctrine.  Indeed,  he  had  no  sooner  enunciated  it  than  he 
to  a  large  extent  implicitly  withdrew  it  by  surreptitiously  substituting 
human  reason  for  human  nature.  What  warrant  is  there  for  this?  Why 
limit  the  field  from  which  deductions  applicable  to  history  may  be  drawn 
to  reason,  a  single  part  or  faculty  of  human  nature?  Why  exclude  any- 
thing truly  belonging  to  that  nature?  Cousin  does  not  give  any  explicit 
reasoned  answer.  He  makes  an  attempt  to  show  that  in  every  act  of 
consciousness  the  three  terms  or  ideas  which  have  been  specified  are  in- 
volved as  conditions,  and  forthwith  proceeds  to  argue  as  if  he  had  thereby 
reduced  all  the  phenomena  of  consciousness  to  these  terms,  in  strange 
obliviousness  of  there  being  a  great  difference  between  the  detection  of 
the  formal  or  metaphysical  conditions  of  consciousness  and  the  analysis 
of  consciousness  into  its  real  or  psychological  elements.  It  does  not 
appear  to  have  occurred  to  him  that  he  might  have  succeeded  in  dis- 
covering the  ultimate  categories  of  reason,  and  yet  have  the  inquiry  into 
human  nature  as  the  basis  of  history  to  begin ;  that  the  conditions  im- 
plied in  the  possibility  of  reason  are  not  the  laws  of  the  development  of 
reason,  and  still  less  of  those  principles  which  are  distinct  from  reason. 
He  abandons,  in  fact,  without  seeming  to  know  that  he  is  doing  so,  the 
great  truths  with  which  he  starts  :  that  the  matter  of  history  is  human 
nature  in  its  entirety,  in  all  its  wants,  faculties,  and  principles ;  and  that 
a  science  of  history  can  be  founded  on  no  narrower  basis  than  the  whole 
of  psychological  science  supplies.  He  seeks  to  build  not  on  the  whole 
mind,  but  on  reason  alone,  or  rather  not  even  on  reason,  as  a  positive 
principle  of  the  mental  constitution  and  life  —  which  is  the  only  sense  in 
which  it  is  a  true  factor  of  history — but  on  abstract  ideas  of  reason  with 
which  metaphysics  is  conversant,  but  with  which  the  science  of  history 
has  tio  more  to  do  than  the  science  of  chemistry.  He  thus  sacrifices  in 
practice  the  important  truths  which  he  holds  in  theory. 

The  next  three  lectures  treat  of  the  fundamental  ideas  of 
history,  the  great  epochs  of  history,  and  the  plan  of  history. 
The  reduction  of  reason  into  three  ideas  is  supposed  to  have 
already  determined  all  the  conclusions  to  he  come  to  on  these 


cousin  459 

points,  and  the  course  of  actual  history  is  referred  to  only  as 
affording  illustrations  of  truths  obtained  independently  of  the 
study  of  it.1 

The  development  of  intelligence  is  described  as  of  a  two- 
fold nature,  spontaneous  and  reflective.  The  spontaneous 
development,  taking  place  in  all  men  without  exception, 
instinctively  and  involuntarily,  is  a  primitive,  impersonal, 
and  universal  fact.  The  reflective  development,  displaying 
itself  in  a  marked  degree  only  in  the  philosophical  few,  is 
a  secondary,  personal,  and  particular  fact.  Reflection  pre- 
supposes and  is  occasioned  by  spontaneity.  It  is  a  sort  of 
reversal  of  the  spontaneous  process,  a  going  over  it  again 
from  the  opposite  point,  an  analysing  of  it,  a  scrutiny  of  its 
conditions  and  rules.  It  adds  nothing  new,  nothing  of  its 
own,  to  it ;  but  only  seeks  to  account  for  it,  to  find  how  it 
has  reached  its  present  stage  and  character,  out  of  what  prin- 
ciples it  has  grown  up,  and  what  elements  it  includes.  To 
effect  this  end  it  is  necessitated  to  decompose,  separate,  dis- 
tinguish. To  apprehend  clearly  the  different  constituent 
elements  which  are  all  confusedly  united  in  spontaneous 
consciousness,  it  must  apprehend  them  one  by  one,  and  while 
intent  on  the  contemplation  of  any  one  must  extrude  the 
others  from  its  sight. 

Hence  clearness,  but  hence  also  error.  Error  is  one  of 
the  elements  of  thought  taken  for  the  whole  of  thought ;  an 
incomplete  truth  converted  into  absolute  truth.  No  other 
error  is  possible,  because  thought,  if  it  exist  at  all,  must 
possess  some  one  of  the  elements  which  constitute  it,  some 
element  of  reality.  Reflection,  therefore,  always  includes 
truth,  and  almost  always  error,  because  it  is  almost  always 
incomplete.  And  error  necessitates  difference  between  men. 
The  primitive  unity  of  spontaneous  intelligence,  not  suppos- 
ing distinction,  admits  neither  of  error  nor  difference;  but 
reflection,  in  discriminating  the  elements  of  thought,  and 
considering  them  separately  and  exclusively,  produces  error, 

1 1  leave  unnoticed,  as  properly  falling  within  the  provinces  of  the  theologian 
and  metaphysician,  what  is  said  in  these  lectures  as  to  the  ideas  of  the  infinite, 
finite,  and  the  relation  of  the  infinite  and  finite,  belonging  not  to  man,  but  to 
absolute  intelligence,  constituting  the  nature  of  Deity,  and  necessitating  and 
explaining  the  creation  of  the  universe. 


460  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

and  variety  of  error  or  difference.  Hence  the  different  epochs 
of  individual  existence,  which  are  only  the  stages  caused  by 
a  change  in  ideas,  by  variations  in  the  points  of  view  of  re- 
flection. 

Hence,  further,  the  differences  of  men  compared  with  one 
another.  It  is  impossible  for  them  to  agree  together  to  con- 
sider at  the  same  time  the  same  side  of  thought  and  of  things, 
and  so  they  necessarily  differ,  fail  to  comprehend  one  another, 
and  even  despise  one  another.  •  He  who  is  exclusively  pre- 
occupied with  the  idea  of  unity  and  infinity,  pities  the  man 
who  enjoys  the  finite  world,  life  in  its  movement  and  variety; 
and  he  who  is  wholly  attached  to  the  interests  and  pleasures 
of  this  world,  regards  as  a  fool  the  man  whose  thoughts  and 
affections  are  centred  on  the  invisible  principle  of  existence. 
Most  men  are  thus  merely  halves  or  quarters  of  men,  and  can 
become  entire  men  only  by  delivering  themselves  from  the 
exclusiveness  which  renders  them  unable  to  comprehend 
others,  and  by  realising  in  themselves  all  the  elements  of 
humanity. 

It  is  with  the  human  race  as  with  individuals.  What 
reflection  is  to  the  individual,  history  is  to  the  race.  It  is 
the  condition  of  the  successive  evolution  of  all  the  essential 
elements  of  humanity,  and  has  consequently  epochs,  an  epoch 
being  nothing  else  than  the  predominance  of  one  of  the  ele- 
ments of  humanity  during  the  time  necessary  for  it  to  display 
all  the  powers  which  are  in  it,  and  to  impress  itself  upon 
industry,  the  State,  art,  religion,  and  philosophy.  As  the 
essential  elements  of  thought  are  three,  no  more  and  no  less, 
the  epochs  of  history  must  be  three,  no  more  and  no  less. 
The  three  elements  are,  indeed,  to  some  extent  in  each  epoch; 
but  each  one  of  them,  in  order  to  run  through  its  whole  de- 
velopment, must  have  an  epoch  to  itself.  The  three  epochs 
succeed  each  other  in  a  necessary  order.  It  is  not  man  him- 
self, not  the  sentiment  of  the  me  and  of  liberty,  which  is 
dominant  in  new-born  reflection,  but  the  sense  of  feebleness, 
the  consciousness  of  dependence  upon  the  infinite,  upon  God: 
and  as  it  is  thus  in  the  individual  life,  so,  too,  the  first  epoch 
of  humanity  is  necessarily  pervaded  with  the  sentiment  of  the 
misery  and  nothingness  of  man,  and  filled  with  the  idea  of 
the  infinite,  of  unity,  of  the  absolute,  and  of  eternity.     The 


cousin  461 

growth  of  reflection  in  the  individual  gives  rise  to  a  feeling 
of  personal  freedom  and  power ;  and  equally  the  exercise  of 
liberty  leads  humanity  to  feel  the  charm  of  the  world  and 
of  life,  and  to  yield  itself  up  exclusively  thereto,  which  is 
the  reign  of  personality,  the  epoch  of  the  finite.  Having 
exhausted  the  extremes,  there  is  nothing  left  either  for  the 
individual  or  the  race  but  to  unite  and  harmonise  them ;  and 
so  the  two  epochs  of  the  infinite  and  finite  are  necessarily 
succeeded  by  a  third  which  reconciles  them  and  sums  them 
up,  impressing  everywhere  upon  industry,  the  State,  art, 
religion,  and  philosophy,  the  relation  of  the  finite  and  the 
infinite,  and  thus  gives  to  that  relation  its  own  expression  in 
history,  its  own  empire. 

Such  are  the  epochs  of  history,  and  the  order  of  their 
succession;  but  under  the  relation  of  succession  lies  one  of 
generation.  The  first  epoch  of  humanity  begets  the  second, 
and  the  fertile  residua  of  the  two  first  epochs  combine  to  pro- 
duce the  third.  Although  the  different  epochs  of  humanity 
are  wholes  which  have  each  a  life  of  its  own,  humanity  itself 
is  an  active  and  productive  force  which  pervades  them  all, 
and  an  organic  whole  which  comprehends  them  all.  The 
truth  of  history  is  therefore  not  a  dead  truth,  or  one  confined 
to  any  particular  age,  but  a  living  and  growing  truth,  which 
comes  forth  gradually  from  the  harmonious  work  of  ages,  and 
which  is  nothing  less  than  the  progressive  birth  of  human  ity. 
It  is  more.  History  reflects  not  merely  the  movement  of 
humanity,  but  of  God's  action  on  and  in  humanity.  It  is 
the  government  of  God  made  visible.  And  as  His  govern- 
ment must  be  like  His  character,  perfect,  everything  in  his- 
tory must  be  in  its  place,  must  be  reasonable,  and  for  the 
greatest  good  of  all  things. 

This  is  M.  Cousin's  celebrated  theory  of  historical  development, 
stated,  as  far  as  possible,  in  the  words  of  its  author.  It  is  impossible 
to  deny  to  it  a  certain  sort  of  grandeur  and  plausibility ;  but  it  fails  at 
almost  every  point  to  satisfy  the  legitimate  demands  of  science. 

The  distinction  between  spontaneity  and  reflection  with  which  it  starts 
was  one  to  which  M.  Cousin  attached  great  importance,  but  which  he 
never  succeeded  in  clearly  and  distinctly  apprehending.  He  regarded 
spontaneous  reason  as  reason  in  itself,  as  absolute  or  impersonal  reason, 
as  consequently  incapable  of  error,  and  a  sure  foundation  for  the  author- 
ity of  universal  beliefs ;  and  reflective  reason  as  that  which  is  modified 


462  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

and  guided  by  will,  the  principle,  according  to  him,  in  which  personality 
consists  ;  and  therefore  as  individual,  variable,  and  subject  to  error. 
Now  this  is  untenable.  Spontaneous  thought  does  not  differ  from  reflec- 
tive thought  by  being  unaccompanied  and  uninfluenced  by  will.  The 
progress  of  spontaneous  thought,  like  all  progress  in  thought,  implies 
throughout  the  active  concurrence  of  the  will  with  the  intelligence.  In 
the  course  of  that  progress,  which  embraces  human  history  in  all  its 
length  and  breadth,  arts  have  been  invented  and  sciences  evolved,  poems 
written,  moral  creeds  elaborated,  religions  established,  complex  and  dur- 
able civilisations  built  up  :  and  although  the  mind  has  not  proceeded 
along  this  lengthened  road  with  a  clear  perception  of  the  goal  to  which 
it  leads,  neither  has  it  taken  steps  in  utter  darkness ;  and  as  little  has  it 
been  driven  on  by  any  fatalistic  force  either  over  it  or  within  it.  It  has 
had  light  and  freedom  sufficient  to  make  it  responsible  for  each  suc- 
cessive step,  as  it  became  right  that  it  should  be  taken.  The  will  has 
everywhere  been  present?  choice  everywhere  called  for,  error  everywhere 
possible.  To  speak,  as  M.  Cousin  does  of  spontaneous  intelligence  as 
instinctive,  is,  taken  literally,  no  less  absurd  than  to  speak  of  white 
blackness  or  a  circular  square. 

Further,  M.  Cousin,  instead  of  drawing  a  consistent  distinction,  has 
merely  mixed  up  and  confounded  a  number  of  distinctions.  When  he 
distinguishes  spontaneous  from  reflective  intelligence  by  characterising 
the  former  as  immediate,  involuntary,  and  incapable  of  error,  the  only 
real  mental  fact  which  corresponds  to  it  is  perception  external  or  internal, 
and  reflection  includes  the  whole  of  what  is  commonly  called  thought. 
This,  however,  was  by  no  means  the  distinction  which  he  wished  to  draw. 

While,  however,  a  part  of  what  we  are  told  of  the  distinction  between 
spontaneity  and  reflection  is  true  only  of  the  distinction  between  percep- 
tion and  thought,  another  part  of  it  is  true  only  of  that  between  ordinary 
and  scientific  thought,  or,  more  accurately,  between  the  lower  and  higher 
stages  of  thought.  When  spontaneous  intelligence  is  described  as  com- 
paratively obscure  and  confused,  reflective  intelligence  as  comparatively 
clear  and  distinct ;  when  it  is  admitted  that  the  former  really,  although 
slowly,  progresses  through  the  ages,  and  constitutes  the  thinking  of  the 
mass  of  men,  while  the  latter  is  characteristic  of  the  philosophic  few,  — 
a  difference  of  degree  is  presented  to  us  as  a  distinction  of  kind.  Science 
differs  from  ordinary  knowledge  not  absolutely  or  specifically,  but  relar 
tively  and  in  degree.  Science  has  grown  out  of  ordinary  knowledge,  and 
ordinary  knowledge  is  on  the  way  to  become  science.  The  knowledge 
which  enables  the  rudest  savage  to  satisfy  his  simplest  wants,  and  the 
broadest  and  best-established  generalisations  of  the  most  advanced  living 
astronomer  or  chemist,  are  merely  the  extremes  of  a  process  which  has 
been  continuous,  and  which  has  gradually  filled  up  the  whole  distance 
between  them. 

Then,  another,  a  third  distinction  seems  to  be  the  only  one  which  will 
answer  to  that  part  of  M.  Cousin's  account  which  refers  the  origin  of 
religion  and  poetry  to  spontaneity,  and  of  philosophy  to  reflection  —  viz., 


cousin  463 

the  distinction  between  thought  combined  with  and  thought  separated 
from  emotion.  This,  also,  is  only  a  difference  of  degree;  for  a  complete 
severance  of  thought  from  emotion  is  impossible ;  and  it  is  further,  prop- 
erly speaking,  no  division  of  thoughts  themselves  into  kinds. 

And  there  is  at  least  another,  a  fourth  distinction  with  which  that 
under  consideration  is  identified :  that  of  thought  which  works  on  objects 
given  to  it,  and  of  thought  which  makes  itself  its  own  object ;  of  thought 
which  deals  with  exterior  things  in  order  to  ascertain  their  natures  and 
laws,  and  of  thought  which  studies  and  analyses  its  own  processes.  This 
is  a  distinction  of  kind  and  not  of  mere  degree ;  for,  thus  understood, 
reflection  is  not  the  continuance  of  spontaneity,  not  a  further  stage  of  the 
same  process,  although  it  presupposes  and  is  occasioned  by  it ;  but  is  a 
sort  of  reversal  of  it,  a  going  over  it  again  from  an  opposite  point  and 
with  an  opposite  aim.  It  is  only  when  M.  Cousin's  distinction  of  spon- 
taneous and  reflective  intelligence  is  understood  as  equivalent  to  this 
distinction  that  the  statement  that  reflection,  in  going  over  the  processes 
of  spontaneous  thought,  adds  to  them  nothing  new,  and  not  a  few  other 
statements  which  he  has  made,  can  be  received  as  true.  Perhaps  the 
general  impression  his  account  leaves  is  that  this  was  the  distinction  he 
had  in  view,  but  that  he  altogether  failed  to  steady  his  eye  upon  it.  It 
was  certainly,  I  think,  the  distinction  which  he  should  have  drawn,  and 
to  which  he  should  have  exclusively  adhered. 

But  then,  if  this  be  "the  distinction,  spontaneous  intelligence  may  be 
very  clear  and  precise,  and  reflective  intelligence  very  obscure  and  con- 
fused. The  great  mass  of  thought  will  be  what  is  called  spontaneous 
thought,  and  it  need  not  necessarily  be  vaguer,  or  shorter,  or  easier  than 
reflective  thought.  There  is  probably  no  psychological  analysis  which 
has  displayed  so  much  perspicacity,  vigour,  concentration,  and  persever- 
ance of  mind,  as  the  discovery  of  the  law  of  gravitation,  an  achievement 
of  spontaneous  research.  The  spontaneous  intelligence,  in  this  accepta- 
tion of  the  term,  originates  not  only  the  simplest  but  the  subtlest  inven- 
tions ;  apprehends  not  only  the  most  obvious  but  the  most  recondite  truths. 
It  is  to  it,  and  not  to  reflective  intelligence,  thus  distinguished,  that  the 
world  owes  its  religions,  its  legislations,  its  arts,  its  industries,  its  sciences, 
and  even  far  the  larger  portion  of  its  philosophy. 

M.  Cousin  has  not  succeeded,  then,  in  distinguishing  between  sponta- 
neous and  reflective  intelligence,  although  there  is  a  real  distinction  be- 
tween them  on  which  he  has  occasionally  touched.  Had  he  apprehended 
it  more  clearly  and  consistently,  he  would  have  seen  that  it  could  not 
possibly  be  applied  to  history  in  the  way  he  attempted.  If  reflection  be 
restricted  to  denote  that  kind  of  thought  which  has  its  origin  in  the  con- 
viction that  processes  of  mind  require  explanation  no  less  than  processes 
of  matter ;  and  that  if  the  mind  will  only  turn  its  eye  inwards  —  will  only 
bend  its  attention  back  upon  itself,  and  study  these  processes  —  an  expla- 
nation of  them  may  be  reached ;  and  if  spontaneity  be  understood  as 
comprehending  all  other  thought ;  the  notion  that  the  whole  mass  of 
thought  in  individuals,  nations,  and  humanity  is  set  in  motion  and  kept 


464  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   PRANCE 

in  motion  by  the  action  of  reflection,  ceases  to  be  in  any  degree  plausible. 
Reflection  must  then  be  admitted  to  be  a  kind  of  thought,  which,  instead 
of  setting  all  other  thought  in  motion,  makes  its  own  appearance  only 
when  most  other  kinds  of  thought  have  already  run  a  lengthened  course; 
only  after  notable  results  have  been  reached  in  science,  art,  morals,  and 
religion.  Instead  of  determining  the  general  movement  of  thought,  it 
must  be  determined  by  it ;  and  instead  of  imposing  a  law  of  movement 
on  spontaneous  thought,  a  law  of  movement  already  there  must  compre- 
hend and  regulate  its  own  movement.  But  this  means  ruin  to  M.  Cousin's 
theory ;  it  is  the  pulling  out  of  its  foundation-stone.  If  true,  whatever 
be  the  cause  of  historical  movement,  that  cause  cannot  be  the  decompo- 
sition of  spontaneous  thought  into  its  essential  elements  under  the  action 
of  reflection ;  and  whatever  be  the  law  of  historical  movement,  that  law 
cannot  be  the  inability  of  reflection  to  think  more  than  one  of  these  ele- 
ments at  a  time,  or  in  any  other  order  than  that  of  infinite,  finite,  and 
relation  of  finite  and  infinite.  Both  cause  and  law  must  be  looked  for 
elsewhere.  The  attention  must  no  longer  be  confined  to  the  relation  of 
one  kind  of  thought  to  another;  but  the  whole  movement  of  thought 
must  be  studied  in  itself,  and  in  relation  to  nature. 

But  may  not,  it  will  be  said,  spontaneous  thought,  although  it  move 
independently  of  the  impulse  of  reflection,  still,  in  the  course  of  its  move- 
ment, manifest  one  of  its  elements  after  another,  so  that  each  element 
shall  have  an  epoch  to  itself  after  the  manner  indicated  by  Cousin?  I 
think  not.  If  spontaneous  intelligence  develop,  and  if  there  are  certain 
elements  so  essentially  constitutive  of  it  as  to  be  included  in  its  every 
act,  it  is  hard  to  see  how  all  these  elements  can  fail  to  be  continuously 
and  contemporaneously  developed,  and  especially  how  they  can  be  so 
separated  as  to  be  the  distinctive  principles  of  historical  epochs  of  im- 
mense duration.  And  whether  such  a  successive  development  of  the 
elements  of  reason  be  possible  or  not,  obviously  every  presumption  ad- 
duced by  M.  Cousin  in  its  favour  is  swept  away  by  the  dispersion  of  the 
confused  augmentation  on  which  he  rests  it.  Any  presumptions  or  prob- 
abilities which  remain  point  to  the  opposite  conclusion.  Thus  the  specu- 
lative grounds  on  which  Cousin  bases  his  hypothesis  of  a  successive 
separate  development  of  the  elements  of  intelligence  in  successive  histori- 
cal epochs  are  undermined ;  and  it  is  on  these  grounds  that  he  has  chiefly 
rested  it.  Indeed  it  may  be  said  to  have  been  exclusively  on  these  grounds, 
there  being  nothing  else  adduced  in  its  favour  except  a  passing  assurance 
that  the  actual  course  of  history  is  found  to  confirm  the  conclusion  which 
they,  according  to  him,  support. 

The  ultimate  appeal,  however,  must  be  to  the  facts  themselves.  What, 
then,  do  they  say?  Do  they  substantiate  the  notion  of  three  historical 
epochs,  the  first  characterised  by  the  supremacy  of  the  infinite,  the  second 
of  the  finite,  and  the  third  of  the  relation  of  the  infinite  and  finite  ?  To 
my  thinking,  they  do  not.  The  epoch  of  the  infinite,  according  to  M. 
Cousin,  was  that  of  the  East,  where  everything  was  more  or  less  immo- 
bile, industry  feeble,  the  arts  gigantic  and  monstrous,  the  laws  of  the 


cousin  465 

State  fixed  and  immutable,  religion  a  longing  after  absorption  in  the 
invisible,  and  philosophy  the  contemplation  of  absolute  unity.  Well,  was 
the  East  in  any  form  in  which  this  description  can  be  regarded  as  even 
approximately  true,  the  first  epoch  of  history?  Is  it  possible  for  us 
seriously  to  hold  it  was?  M.  Cousin,  while  believing  in  a  primitive  reve- 
lation, an  age  of  gold,  the  Eden  of  poetry  and  religion,  discarded  the 
question  of  a  primitive  people,  as  more  embarrassing  than  important,  and 
as  not  properly  belonging  to  history,  which,  strictly,  is  only  where  differ- 
ence and  development  are.  So  be  it.  But  there  was  no  long  interval,  no 
time  of  difference  and  development,  of  struggle  and  evolution,  no  epoch 
between  Eden  and  the  East  described  by  M.  Cousin  ?  Did  the  latter 
spring  immediately  out  of  the  former  ?  There  was,  we  may  be  certain,  a 
long  interval,  and  no  immediate  connection,  or  even  sudden  growth.  The 
East  presents  us  with  several  elaborate  and  artificial  civilisations,  but  with 
none  which  we  have  reason  to  suppose  dates  from  Eden  ;  on  the  contrary, 
we  have  more  or  less  evidence  of  their  having  developed  gradually  from 
simple,  if  not  barbarous,  conditions  of  society.  But  rude  and  simple 
peoples,  still  more  barbarous  peoples,  are  never  found  absorbed  in  the 
contemplation  of  the  infinite,  and  of  absolute  unity.  The  Brahmins  and 
Buddhists  of  Asia  may  be  so ;  but  the  low  and  sensuous  populations  which 
the  Aryans  encountered  in  India  on  their  arrival  were  not;  and  these 
Aryans  themselves  —  the  Vedic  hymns  show  us  —  were,  so  far  from  being 
at  first  weighed  down  with  a  sense  of  the  infinite,  feebly  and  dimly  con- 
scious of  any  such  feeling,  while  keenly  alive  to  the  phases  and  impressions 
of  nature,  and  to  the  interests  of  a  life,  healthy,  varied,  mobile,  active,  and, 
in  a  word,  all  that,  according  to  M.  Cousin,  life  in  the  epoch  of  the  infinite 
should  not  have  been. 

This  is  not  all.  M.  Cousin  applies  his  description  of  the  epoch  of  the 
infinite  to  the  East.  But  the  East  is  a  very  wide  word.  Did  M.  Cousin 
realise  how  comprehensive  it  was  ?  A  little  inquiry  shows  us  that  he  did 
not.  His  description  of  the  East  is  to  a  considerable  extent  true  of  India, 
after  the  definite  establishment  of  Brahminism,  but  of  no  other  Eastern 
nation ;  it  characterises  not  very  inaccurately  a  stage  of  Hindu  life,  but  it 
most  unwarrantably  professes  to  be  a  delineation  of  the  whole  life  and 
history  of  Asia  plus  Egypt.  There  is,  for  instance,  no  country  in  Europe 
to  which  that  description  of  the  East  applies  less  than  to  China.  It  is 
true,  indeed,  that  China  affords  a  good  example  of  comparative  immo- 
bility; but  nothing  can  be  more  absurd  than  to  suppose  that  immobility 
due  to  the  absorption  of  the  Chinese  mind  in  the  study  of  the  infinite 
and  the  absolute.  That  mind  is  exceptionably  indifferent  and  dead  to 
these  things ;  strangely  atheistic  and  materialistic ;  engrossed  in  the  finite ; 
indefatigable  in  the  pursuit  of  earthly  gains ;  greedy  of  sensuous  joys.  It 
might  readily  be  shown  that  M.  Cousin's  description  also  fails  to  answer 
to  the  monarchies  of  Middle  Asia  and  to  Egypt.  And  although  it  should 
be  granted  that  the  Jewish  people  was  distinguished  by  its  consciousness 
of  the  presence  of  an  infinite  and  eternal  God  and  Judge,  it  must  at  the 
sametime  be  maintained  that  that  consciousness  elicited  instead  of  crush- 


466  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

ing  the  sense  of  personality,  freedom,  responsibility ;  and  that  it  proved 
itself  to  be  in  no  wise  incompatible  with  vigour  and  enterprise. 

There  is  yet  another  difficulty.  The  epoch  of  the  infinite  comes  to  an 
end.  When  Y  M.  Cousin  answers  :  When  the  infinite  is  exhausted  in  every 
direction.  And  it  appears  not  to  have  occurred  to  him  that  there  need  be 
any  hesitation  in  accepting  the  answer.  But  surely  it  is  a  most  mysterious, 
if  not  a  self-contradictory  one,  and  the  very  reverse  of  explanatory.  How 
can  the  infinite  be  exhausted  in  any  direction  ?  and  much  more,  in  every 
direction  ? 

The  epoch  of  the  finite  M.  Cousin  finds  in  the  history  of  classical 
antiquity.  In  describing  it,  however,  he  keeps  his  eye  exclusively  fixed 
on  Greece ;  and  yet  entirely  overlooks  the  obvious  difficulty,  that  if  the 
finite  realised  itself  so  admirably  in  Greece,  it  should  not  have  reappeared 
in  a  less  perfect  form  in  Rome.  This  difficulty  he  could  not  have  got  over 
by  saying  that  in  Greece  the  finite  did  not  impress  itself  on  all  the  phases 
of  life,  and  therefore  had  to  continue  itself  in  Rome ;  because,  according 
to  his  own  teaching,  the  last  phase  of  life  on  which  an  idea  can  impress 
itself  is  the  philosophical ;  and  it  is  certainly  not  true  that  Rome  was, 
and  Greece  was  not,  a  philosophical  nation.  In  order  that  the  finite 
should  have  had  all  its  development,  he  tells  us  that  it  must  have  had  an 
almost  exclusive  development,  unhindered  by  any  movement  of  the  infi- 
nite ;  and  accordingly  he  describes  Greece  as  having  been  wholly  dominated 
by  the  idea  of  the  finite.  But  he  thereby  only  shows  how  dangerous  is 
the  kind  of  historical  speculation  in  which  he  indulges.  For  the  sake  of 
his  formula,  he  has  to  ignore  the  plainest  teaching  of  such  expressions  of 
Grecian  life  as  the  mysteries,  metaphysics,  and  tragedy ;  has  to  mutilate 
the  facts,  or  notice  only  those  which  suit  the  foregone  conclusion,  seeing 
that,  looked  at  fairly  and  fully,  they  would  show  Greece  to  have  contrib- 
uted very  greatly  to  the  development  of  the  ideas  of  the  infinite  and  of  the 
absolute.  Greece  certainly  did  not  represent  the  infinite  less  than  China, 
nor  did  it  even  represent  the  finite  more.  The  superiority  of  Greece  over 
the  East  lay,  not  in  carrying  the  finite  farther  —  which  would  have  been  no 
merit  or  progress  —  but  in  having  a  truer  sense  of  beauty  of  form,  of  pro- 
portion, of  harmony.  Of  course  finiteness  and  form  are  very  different 
things  ;  and  a  graceful  form  is  no  more  finite,  or  suggestive  of  the  finite, 
than  one  which  is  the  reverse. 

To  the  modern  world  —  the  third  epoch  —  is  assigned  the  task  of 
apprehending  and  expressing  the  relation  of  the  infinite  and  finite.  How 
this  can  be  done,  apart  from  the  development  of  the  related  ideas,  M. 
Cousin  does  not  show.  Neither  does  he  show  that  the  effort  to  reconcile 
these  two  ideas  is  really  distinctive  of  the  modern  world.  And  this  for 
the  good  reason  that  such  is  not  the  case.  It  is  impossible  to  study  the 
Hindu  philosophies  without  coming  to  the  conclusion  that  their  object 
was  not  the  infinite  to  the  exclusion  of,  but  in  relation  to,  the  finite; 
nor  the  Greek  philosophies  without  similarly  discovering  that  their  object 
was  not  the  finite  in  itself,  but  in  its  connection  with  the  infinite. 

Tested,  then,  by  the  facts,  this  distribution  of  epochs  is  found  to  be 


cousin  467 

false.  Whatever  be  the  plan  of  history,  it  cannot  be  that  drawn  by 
M.  Cousin.  And  there  is  some  comfort  in  this  reflection,  seeing  that 
he  denies  our  race  a  future.  There  can  be,  he  tells  us,  no  new  epoch  of 
history.  "Try,"  he  says,  "to  add  a  fourth.  It  is  not  in  the  power  of 
thought,  I  do  not  say  to  succeed  in  it,  but  even  to  attempt  it ;  for  thought 
is  able  to  conceive  of  anything  only  by  reason  of  the  finite,  of  the  infinite, 
and  of  their  relation."  Had  there  been  no  other  objection  to  M.  Cousin's 
theory  than  that  it  logically  involved  the  dogmatic  denial  of  the  possi- 
bility of  any  new  epoch  of  history  in  the  future,  I  should  consider  that  in 
itself  to  outweigh  any  reasons  he  has  given  for  it.  It  is  true  he  tries  to 
break  the  force  of  the  objection  by  saying  that  the  present  epoch  is  only 
emerging  from  the  stage  of  barbarism.  This  assertion,  however,  is  not 
only  unsupported  by  any  appeal  to  facts,  but  is  in  manifest  contradiction 
to  his  account  of  what  determines  the  completion  of  an  epoch,  and  to  the 
character  which  he  ascribes  to  his  own  philosophy  as  an  all-comprehensive, 
all-reconciling  eclecticism. 

M.  Cousin,  as  I  have  indicated,  concludes  his  exposition  of  the  plan  of 
history  by  a  profession  of  his  faith  in  historical  optimism .  "  History  is 
the  government  of  God  made  visible  ;  and  hence  everything  is  there  in 
its  place:  and  if  everything  is  there  in  its  place,  everything  is  there  for 
good ;  for  everything  arrives  at  an  end,  marked  by  a  beneficent  power." 
It  is  marvellous  how  our  author  could  fancy  he  was  entitled  to  believe  so 
great  a  theory  on  such  a  faint  appearance  of  reason.  There  are  things 
without  number  which,  our  intellects  and  consciences  testify,  appear  to 
be  indubitably  out  of  place,  bad,  and  mischievous.  If  it  can  be  shown 
that  they  are  not  what  they  appear  to  be  —  not  really  bad,  but  really  good 
—  let  it  be  done  ;  but  let  us  not  ignore  the  facts,  or  affirm  without  exam- 
ination, that  they  are  just  the  opposite  of  what  they  seem,  on  no  better 
ground  than  an  enthymeme  so  contemptible  as  that  God  is  good,  and 
therefore  everything  is  good. 

There  are  still  three  lectures  of  Cousin  to  notice,  and  they 
treat  of  places,  nations,  and  great  men ;  because  these  are  the 
three  things  by  which  the  spirit  of  an  epoch  manifests  itself, 
— the  three  important  points  on  which  the  historian  ought 
to  fix  his  attention. 

As  to  the  first — places,  the  part  of  geography  in  history, 
which  is  the  subject  of  the  eighth  lecture  —  the  substance  of 
M.  Cousin's  teaching  is  as  follows  :  Everything  in  the  world 
has  a  meaning;  nothing  is  insignificant;  and  consequently 
every  place  necessarily  represents  an  idea,  —  one  of  the  ideas 
which  underlie  and  connect  all  other  ideas.  The  relation  of 
man  to  nature  is  not  one  of  effect  to  cause;  but  man  and 
nature  are  two  great  effects  of  the  same  cause,  so  harmoni- 


468  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

ously  correspondent  to  each  other  that,  given  a  country,  you 
may  tell  what  the  people  will  be,  or,  given  a  people,  what 
sort  of  country  they  must  inhabit.  No  place  represents  more 
than  one  idea.  The  three  great  epochs  must  therefore  have 
three  different  theatres.  If  we  consider  what  these  must  be, 
we  shall  be  forced  to  conclude  that  the  theatre  of  the  epoch 
of  the  infinite  can  only  be  an  extensive  continent  with  vast 
plains  and  almost  impassable  mountains,  and  bordering  upon 
the  ocean ;  that  of  the  finite,  countries  comparatively  small, 
on  the  shores  of  some  inland  sea ;  and  that  of  the  relation  of 
the  finite  to  the  infinite,  a  continent  of  considerable  size, 
bordering  on  the  ocean,  yet  possessing  inland  seas,  sufficiently 
yet  not  too  compact,  and  varied  in  its  configuration  and 
climate.  In  other  words,  these  theatres  must  be — for  the 
infinite,  Asia;  for  the  finite,  Greece  and  Italy;  and  for  the 
relation  of  the  finite  to  the  infinite,  Europe. 

The  following  remarks  may  be  made  on  this  theory.  First,  Although 
M.  Cousin  starts  with  the  affirmation  that  everything,  and  consequently 
every  place,  in  the  world,  has  a  meaning,  or  represents  an  idea,  the 
result  of  the  survey  which  he  takes  of  the  earth  to  illustrate  it  is,  that 
the  greater  part  of  Africa  and  the  whole  American  continent  have  no 
meaning  and  represent  no  idea.  Two  contradictory  propositions  pervade 
the  lecture.  The  one  is,  God  made  every  place  to  represent  an  idea; 
and  the  other  is,  He  made  only  some  places  to  represent  ideas,  —  or, 
in  other  words,  made  some,  and  notably  America  —  to  represent  none. 

Secondly,  Although  everywhere  nature  influences  man  and  man  nature 
—  although  everywhere  man  conforms  his  habits  to  his  habitat,  and 
modifies  matter  to  serve  his  ends  —  and  everywhere  the  character  of  a 
land  impresses  itself  on  the  intellect,  imagination,  and  feelings  of  its 
inhabitants,  and  so  enters,  as  it  were,  into  their  moral  being  and  national 
life,  —  it  is,  nevertheless,  great  exaggeration  to  say,  as  M.  Cousin  does, 
"  Give  me  the  map  of  a  country  —  its  configuration,  its  climate,  its  waters, 
its  winds,  its  natural  productions,  its  botany,  its  zoology,  and  all  its 
physical  geography — and  I  pledge  myself  to  tell  you  what  will  be  the 
man  of  this  country,  and  what  place  this  country  will  occupy  in  history." 
Man  has  other  relations  than  to  nature,  and  some  as  important ;  and  to 
judge  of  him  by  that  one  relationship  alone  can  never  lead  us  to  the 
knowledge  of  what  he  is,  nor  of  what  his  history  must  be. 

Thirdly,  The  way  in  which  M.  Cousin  conceives  of  the  relation  of 
nature  to  man  is  vain  and  fanciful.  It  is  not  as  a  relation  of  cause  and 
effect,  of  action  and  reaction,  of  mutual  influence,  but  of  effects  designed 
to  correspond  to  each  other,  of  a  pre-established  harmony  like  that  which 
Leibniz  supposed  to  exist  between  the  body  and  the  soul.     This  notion 


cousin  469 

is  not  only  puvely  conjectural,  but  inconsistent  with  the  innumerable 
facts  which  manifest  that  nature  does  influence  man,  and  that  man  does 
modify  nature.  It  is  impossible  to  hold,  either  in  regard  to  the  body 
and  soul,  or  in  regard  to  nature  and  man,  both  the  theory  of  mutual  influ- 
ence and  of  pre-established  harmony.  All  that,  in  either  case,  proves  the 
former,  disproves  the  latter.  The  belief  in  a  pre-established  harmony 
between  man  and  nature  is,  indeed,  considerably  more  absurd  than  in  a  pre- 
established  harmony  between  the  body  and  soul ;  for  when  a  body  is  born 
a  soul  is  in  it,  which  remains  in  it  till  death,  and  is  never  known  to  leave 
it  in  order  to  take  possession  of  some  other  body :  but  every  country  is 
not  created  with  a  people  in  it,  nor  is  every  people  permanently  fixed  to 
a  particular  country.  Imagination  may  be  deceived  for  a  moment  by  an 
obvious  process  of  association  into  this  belief  of  certain  peoples  being 
suited  for  certain  lands,  independently  of  the  action  of  natural  causes  — 
the  Greeks,  let  us  say,  for  Greece,  the  Indian  for  the  prairies  and  forests 
of  America,  the  Malayan  for  the  islands  of  the  Indian  Archipelago  ;  but 
a  moment's  thought  on  the  fact  that  the  Turk  has  settled  down  where 
the  Greeks  used  to  be,  that  mighty  nations  of  English-speaking  men  are 
rising  up  where  the  Indian  roamed,  and  that  Dutchmen  are  thriving  in 
the  lands  of  the  Malayan,  should  suffice  to  disabuse  us. 

Besides,  just  as  the  dictum  "Marriages  are  made  in  heaven  "  is  seriously 
discredited  by  the  great  number  that  are  badly  made,  so  the  kindred 
opinion  that  every  country  gets  the  people  which  suits  it,  and  every 
people  the  country,  as  a  direct  and  immediate  consequence  of  their  pre- 
established  harmony,  is  equally  discredited  by  the  prevalence  of  ill-as- 
sorted unions,  a  great  many  worthless  peoples  living  in  magnificent  lands, 
while  far  better  peoples  have  much  worse  ones. 

The  ninth  lecture  treats  of  nations.  They  exist,  we  are 
told,  to  represent  ideas  comprehended  under  the  general  idea 
of  the  epoch  to  which  they  belong.  In  order  to  understand  a 
nation,  the  philosophy  of  history  must  ascertain  the  idea  it  is 
meant  to  represent;  the  stage  it  has  reached  in  the  realisation 
of  that  idea ;  the  evolution  of  the  idea  in  industry,  laws,  art, 
religion,  and  philosophy ;  and  the  order  of  sequence  and  sub- 
ordination among  these  elements.  It  is  only  through  reach- 
ing the  truth  on  all  these  points  that  we  can  escape  partial 
and  narrow  views.  The  nations  of  an  epoch  necessarily  have 
resemblances  greater  than  their  differences  since  they  belong 
to  the  same  epoch,  but  necessarily  have  differences  since  they 
have  separate  or  independent  existence.  Philosophy,  seeing 
that  the  differences  of  nations  —  that  is,  their  particular  ideas 
—  are  incomplete  truths,  can  look  upon  them  all  not  only 
with  toleration  but  with  favour ;  and  humanity  will  be  taught 


470  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

to  do  the  same  by  its  own  history  in  the  course  of 
Nations  themselves,  however,  cannot  fail  to  regard  their 
particular  ideas  as  absolute  and  complete  truths,  entitled  to 
universal  and  exclusive  dominion.  Hence  the  origin  of  war, 
which  is  simply  the  violent  encounter  or  collision  of  the  par- 
ticular ideas  of  different  nations.  The  certain  and  inevitable 
result  of  war  is  the  triumph  of  the  stronger  over  the  weaker 
idea  —  of  the  nation  which  has  its  time  to  serve  over  that 
which  has  served  its  time.  War  is  necessary  and  beneficial, 
because  it  is  the  condition  and  means  of  progress.  A  battle 
is  nothing  else  than  the  combat  of  error  with  truth,  and  vic- 
tory nothing  else  than  the  triumph  of  the  truth  of  to-day 
over  the  truth  of  yesterday,  which  has  become  the  error  of 
to-day.  It  is  a  mistake  to  speak  of  chance  in  war  —  the  dice 
are  loaded ;  humanity  loses  not  a  single  game ;  not  one  battle 
has  taken  a  turn  unfavourable  to  civilisation.  Nor  is  war 
only  necessary  and  useful:  it  is  also  just.  The  conquered 
party  always  deserves  its  fate ;  and  the  conquering  party 
triumphs  because  it  is  better,  more  provident,  wiser,  braver, 
and  more  meritorious  than  its  foe.  War  is  action  on  a  great 
scale,  and  as  such  the  test  and  measure  of  a  nation's  worth. 
In  the  military  history  and  military  organisation  of  a  people 
its  whole  spirit  and  character  may  be  studied. 

Such  is  M.  Cousin's  celebrated  theory  of  nations,  and  the  still  more 
celebrated  doctrine  of  war  which  he  deduced  from  it.  Both  seem  to  me 
very  inadequate,  very  false.  As  to  the  nature  of  nations,  the  important 
preliminary  investigation  as  to  what  a  nation  is  not,  is  altogether 
omitted ;  and  (partly  in  consequence  thereof)  there  is  no  investigation 
into,  or  description  of,  the  conditions  and  characteristics  of  national 
existence.  M.  Cousin,  simply  for  an  a  priori  dogmatic  reason,  differen- 
tiates nations  by  their  supposed  final  causes,  the  purposes  for  which 
he  imagines  them  to  have  received  existence,  telling  us  that  there  are 
different  nations  because  there  are  different  ideas;  that  each  nation 
represents  one  idea  and  not  another;  and  that  that  idea  represents  for 
that  nation  the  whole  truth.  This  kind  of  thought  is  essentially  anti- 
scientific.  It  proceeds  upon  an  obviously  illegitimate  use  of  the  principle 
of  final  causes.  Besides,  it  is  no  excellence  in  a  nation  to  be  dominated 
by  a  single  idea,  and  no  nation  seems  to  have  been  meant  to  realise  only 
a  single  idea.  A  monomaniac  nation  must  be  far  more  than  a  mono- 
maniac man.  Instead  of  the  apprehension  of  one  idea  and  the  applica- 
tion of  one  idea  being  that  for  which  nations  exist,  it  is  the  very  thing 


cousin  471 

they  need  to  be  most  on  their  guard  against.  They  are  all  prone  to  be 
one-idea'd  and  one-sided.  The  characters  which  the  circumstances, 
physical  and  historical,  in  which  nations  are  placed  in  the  earlier  stages 
of  their  existence  tend  to  form  are  narrow  and  defective  characters, 
their  ends  very  definite  and  distinctive,  but  also  very  low  and  selfish 
ends;  and  nations  have  only  to  isolate  themselves  from  one  another, 
and  yield  each  to  its  own  exclusive  tendencies,  and  concentrate  itself  on 
its  favourite  aim  and  private  good,  and  they  will  undoubtedly  soon  repre- 
sent and  realise  only  one  idea.  But  this  is  just  what  nations  should  not 
do.  It  was  because  the  nations  of  antiquity  thus  isolated  and  narrowed 
themselves,  that  they  ceased  to  serve  an  end  in  the  world  and  passed 
away.  It  is  because  such  isolation  is  not  to  anything  like  the  same  extent 
the  law,  or  such  selfishness  the  motive  principle,  of  modern  nations,  that 
we  see  reasons  of  hope  that  they  may  never  cease  to  promote  noble  ends 
and  never  require  to  pass  away.  One-idea' dness,  one-sidedness,  is  shown 
most  explicitly  by  all  history  to  be  full  of  danger ;  a  thing  which  nations 
ought  to  strive  strenuously  to  be  delivered  from,  and  in  working  against 
which  they  are  certainly  not  resisting  the  providential  law  which  rules 
over  their  destinies. 

The  doctrine  of  war  which  M.  Cousin  has  appended  to  his  theory  of 
nations  was  borrowed  by  him  from  Hegel.  It  is  precisely  the  teaching  of 
the  most  worthless  of  the  old  Greek  sophists,  that  nature's  right  is  might, 
and  justice  the  advantage  of  the  stronger. 

War,  according  to  M.  Cousin,  is  the  violent  concussion  of  the  particular 
ideas  of  different  nations,  and  is  caused  by  nations  regarding  their 
particular  ideas  as  complete  truths,  instead  of  what  they  really  are  — 
incomplete  truths.  This  account  of  the  origin  of  war  is  scarcely  plaus- 
ible, and  not  at  all  accurate.  Try  to  apply  it,  and  its  inadequacy 
immediately  becomes  obvious.  M.  Cousin  did  not  venture  to  make  the 
attempt.  Had  it  been  true,  he  would  have  been  able  to  point  out  what 
were  the  particular  ideas  of  different  nations  living  in  the  same  epoch, 
and  how  these  ideas  were  what  made  these  nations  rush  violently  against 
each  other ;  what  particular  apprehensions  of  the  relation  of  the  infinite 
to  finite,  for  example,  have  been  peculiar  to  England,  France,  and  Ger- 
many, and  how  they  have  made  them  fight  so  much  with  one  another, 
and  with  so  many  other  nations.  He  was  not  able,  because  it  was  not 
true ;  because  it  has  not  been  the  particular  ideas  of  different  nations, 
nor  even  the  particular  characters  of  different  nations,  which  have  made 
them  go  to  war,  but  certain  evil  passions  common  to  all  nations,  common 
to  all  men.  That  the  French  nation  has  one  character  and  represents 
one  idea,  and  the  German  nation  has  another  character  and  represents 
another  idea,  no  more  accounts  for  the  wars  they  have  waged  against 
each  other,  than  that  men  have  another  character  and  represent  another 
idea  than  women,  necessitates  war  between  men  and  women.  The  true 
causes  of  war  are  those  so  well  described  by  Hobbes,  —  competition,  dis- 
trust, and  glory,  —  or,  in  other  terms,  greed,  jealousy,  and   ambition, 


472  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTOKY   IN   PKANCE 

making  men  invade  for  gain,  for  safety,  and  for  reputation.  They  are 
those  indicated  by  St.  James :  "  From  whence  come  wars  and  fightings 
among  you  ?  Come  they  not  hence,  even  of  your  lusts  that  war  in  your 
members?" 

The  primary  cause  of  war  is  never  anything  so  excellent  as  even 
imperfect  truth,  is  never  even  the  humblest  form  of  good,  but  always 
evil,  some  evil  lust.  War  is  murder  on  a  gigantic  scale ;  and  the  true 
sources  of  it  are  those  selfish  and  hateful  passions  of  avarice,  envy,  ambi- 
tion, and  pride,  out  of  which  murder  issues.  This  is  not  to  say  that  war 
either  can  or  ought  always  to  be  avoided.  On  the  contrary,  evil  should 
be  opposed,  despotisms  overthrown,  mutinies  quelled,  invasions  driven 
back,  the  oppressed  liberated,  might  violating  right  punished  by  the 
sword  if  nothing  else  will  do  —  by  the  sword,  taken  up  as  a  last  sad 
necessity,  to  be  cast  down  with  joy  as  soon  as  its  harsh  work  is  over. 
But  although  men,  although  nations,  may  have  to  go  to  war  for  the  sake 
of  truth,  justice,  or  mercy,  it  is  never  these  things  that  are  the  real 
causes  of  war,  but  their  opposites  —  the  evil  lusts  which  have  produced 
their  opposites,  those  wrongs  that  must  be  righted.  It  follows  that  those 
who  argue  that  war  is  just  because  it  is  necessary,  reason  badly.  Strictly 
or  philosophically  speaking,  war  is  not  necessary  any  more  than  injustice 
is  necessary.  Popularly  speaking,  or  as  a  matter  of  fact,  it  is  necessary, 
but  only  because  of  the  existence  of  injustice.  It  is  not  necessary  in 
any  sense  incompatible  with  injustice  on  both  sides,  £>nd  is  only  necessary 
in  a  sense  which  involves  injustice  on  one  side. 

The  notion  that  the  inevitable  result  of  war  is  the  triumph  of  truth 
—  that  civilisation  gains  by  every  battle  —  is  simply  the  revival  and  ex- 
tension of  the  medieval  superstition  which  originated  the  judicial  duel. 
People  in  that  age  ignorantly  supposed  that  if  the  justice  of  heaven  were 
thus  directly  appealed  to,  it  would  infallibly  declare  itself  in  the  vindica- 
tion of  the  innocent  and  punishment  of  the  guilty.  There  is  no  more 
reason  for  believing  that  in  a  duel  of  nations  the  one  which  has  most 
truth  and  justice  on  its  side  will  conquer,  than  that  in  a  duel  of  persons 
the  good  man  will  overcome  the  bad.  Since  wicked  Cain  killed  righteous 
Abel,  history  has  supplied  unbroken  testimony  to  the  possibility  of  the 
innocent  suffering,  even  to  the  loss  of  life.  The  Romans  succeeded  less 
easily  in  their  just  than  in  their  unjust  wars,  sustaining  many  serious 
defeats  in  the  former  and  very  few  in  the  latter.  No  amount  of  truth  or 
justice  could  have  prevented  Poland  from  being  partitioned  or  Denmark 
from  being  despoiled. 

So  far  from  civilisation  gaining  by  every  battle,  a  main  cause  of  nu- 
merous tribes  of  men  being  still  uncivilised  has  been  their  constant  war- 
ring against  one  another.  Civilisation  surely  suffered  from  the  wars 
which  laid  Italy  beneath  the  feet  of  Spanish,  French,  and  German  inva- 
ders. Was  Germany  the  better  of  the  Thirty  Years'  War?  Did  the 
victories  of  Napoleon  contribute  greatly  to  spread  the  truths  of  the  Revo- 
lution, or  truth  of  any  kind  ?    Has  his  influence  not  been  on  the  whole 


cousin  473 

baneful,  and  especially  so  to  France  ?  Further,  although  every  war  may 
have  been  followed  by  some  good,  and  many  wars  by  much  good,  that 
good  may  have  been  only  seldom,  and  in  a  small  degree,  the  direct  or 
proper  effect  of  the  antecedent  war.  And,  in  fact,  the  only  good  which 
can  directly  and  truly  result  from  war  is  the  redress  of  some  wrong,  the 
punishment  of  some  injustice.  All  other  advantages  —  all  that  really 
does  much  for  civilisation  —  must  follow,  not  from  war  itself,  but  from 
things  associated  with  it ;  so  that  war  is  not  the  cause  but  the  occasion 
thereof  —  an  evil  overruled  to  produce  good,  as  any  evil,  whether  pain  or 
sin,  may  be  overruled  to  do.  Thus  the  greater  part  of  the  good  which 
can  be  shown  to  have  some  connection  with  war  cannot  be  shown  to 
have  any  causal  connection  with  it,  says  nothing  for  the  goodness  of  war, 
and  is  no  justification  of  the  men  who  engage  in  it,  although  it  may 
testify  to  the  wisdom  and  goodness  of  Providence. 

The  argument  that  war  is  always  just,  because  the  party  which  is 
defeated  always  deserves  to  lose,  and  the  party  which  conquers  to  gain,  is 
fallacious.  There  is  no  truth  in  the  assumptions  on  which  it  rests  —  that 
a  nation  which  cannot  defend  its  existence  must  needs  be  corrupt,  de- 
graded, unworthy  to  exist,  and  that  a  nation  must  be  superior  in  virtue 
to  every  neighbour  which  it  can  conquer  in  war.  Virtue  does  not  neces- 
sarily tend  to  victory,  or  vice  to  defeat.  Honesty  may  stand  in  the  way 
of  a  nation's  seizing  wealth  and  power.  Many  nations  have  grown 
strong  by  deceit,  by  violence,  by  abominable  means.  The  man  who 
knows  the  histories  of  Rome,  of  France,  of  England,  of  Prussia,  and  yet 
denies  this,  must  be  wanting  in  clearness  of  moral  vision.  It  is  not 
merely  foresight  and  self-denial  which  will  help  a  nation  to  become  a 
great  military  power :  revenge  and  greed,  a  servile  spirit  in  its  masses, 
and  ambition  and  lust  of  rule  in  its  nobles,  will  help  also.  I  deny  not 
that  justice  will  carry  it  over  injustice  in  the  end,  the  good  cause  triumph- 
ing in  some  future  age,  although  perhaps  a  very  distant  one,  and  the  good 
man  in  a  better  world  ;  I  deny  not  that  there  are  in  virtue  higher  possi- 
bilities even  for  war  than  in  vice  ;  —  but  more  than  this  I  do  deny,  and 
especially  that  the  conquerors  in  war  are  necessarily  more  meritorious 
than  the  conquered. 

In  the  tenth  lecture  M.  Cousin  theorises  on  great  men,  and 
reaches  the  following  results :  First,  The  great  man  is  not 
an  arbitrary  or  contingent  existence  —  not  a  creature  which 
may  or  may  not  be  —  but  the  representative,  more  or  less 
accomplished,  which  every  great  nation  necessarily  produces. 
Second,  The  great  man,  like  everything  truly  sublime  and 
beautiful,  combines  universality  with  individuality.  He  rep- 
resents the  general  spirit  of  his  nation  and  times,  —  this  is 
the  stuff  of  which  he  is  made,  what  unites  him  with  all,  and 


474  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

enables  him  to  influence  and  dominate  all ;  but  he  represents 
it  under  the  finite  and  particular  form  of  his  own  person  or 
individuality;   so  that  the  particular  and   the  general,  the 
original  and  the  ordinary,  the  finite  and  the  infinite,  mingle 
in  him  in  that  measure  and  harmony  which  is  true  human 
greatness.     Third,  Great  men  so  sum  up  nations,  epochs, 
and  humanity,  that  universal  history  is  but  their  united  biog- 
raphies.    Fourth,  The  great  man  comes  to  represent  an  idea 
so  long  as  it  has  force  and  is  worth  the  representing  —  not 
before  and  not  after ;  is  born  and  dies  at  the  proper  time ; 
and  feels  himself  more  or    less  the  instrument  of  a  power 
which  is  not  his  own,   of   an  irresistible  force,  of  destiny. 
Fifth,  The  sign  of  a  great  man  is  great  success ;  and  from 
great  success  results  first  great  power,  and  next  great  glory 
—  things  which  are  never  awarded  to  those  who  have  not 
merited  them.     Sixth,  A  great  man  is  great,  and  he  is  a  man. 
What  makes  him  great  is  his  relation  to  the  spirit  of  his 
times  and  to  his  people  ;  and  this  alone  properly  belongs  to 
history,  which  is  bound  to  pass  over  what  is  merely  individual 
and  temporary,  and  to  attach  itself  to  what  is  great  and  per- 
manent, what  has   made  a  man  historical,  and  given  him 
power  and  glory.     What  makes  him  a  man  is  his  individu- 
ality; and  this  may  be  small,  vicious,  almost  contemptible, 
but  should  be  abandoned  to  biography.     Seventh,  The  epoch 
of  the  infinite,  where  the  absolute  reigned  to  the  suppression 
of  individuality  and  liberty,  was  unfavourable  to  the  develop- 
ment of  great  men;   the  epoch  of  the  finite  so  especially 
favourable,  that  it  may  be  called  the  heroic  age  of  humanity ; 
and  the  epoch  of  the  relation  of  the  finite  with  the  infinite 
produces  them  in  equal  abundance,  but  less  distinct  and  bril- 
liant.    Eighth,  and  last,  Industry  is  the  sphere  of  life  least 
favourable  to  the  manifestation  of  great  men ;  war  and  phi- 
losophy are  the  spheres  most  favourable :  because  the  two 
chief  modes  of  serving  humanity  are,  to  cause  it  to  advance  a 
step  in  the  path  of  truth,  by  elevating  the  ideas  of  an  age  to 
their  highest  expression,  or  by  impressing  these  ideas  on  the 
world  by  the   sword,  and  by  making   for  them  extensive 
conquests. 


cousin  475 

I  have  compressed  a  very  able,  very  eloquent  lecture  into  these  eight 
propositions,  in  order  to  be  able  to  indicate  in  the  briefest  possible  way 
how  far  the  theory  therein  contained  seems  to  need  correction.  Proposi- 
tion the  first,  then,  may  be  true,  but  it  has  not  been  proved  true.  It 
might  be  proved  true  in  two  ways,  and  only  two,  — viz.,  by  showing  that 
all  existence  is  necessary  —  or,  in  other  words,  that  there  is  no  such  thing 
as  contingency  or  freedom  ;  or  by  discovering  some  necessary  law  which 
determines  the  appearance  and  disappearance  of  great  men.  M.  Cousin 
does  neither,  and  no  one,  in  fact,  has  yet  succeeded  in  either.  Necessita- 
rianism has  still  libertarianism  strong  and  defiant  in  front  of  it.  The 
necessary  law  of  the  coming  and  going  of  great  men,  if  there  be  such  a 
law,  is  still  to  seek ;  and  no  step  even  has  been  taken  which  promises  to 
lead  to  the  finding  of  it.  Was  there  any  other  law  for  the  birth  of 
Luther  than  for  those  of  his  father  and  mother,  the  miner  of  Mohra  and 
his  wife?  Who  can  tell  why  a  great  man  has  been  born  here  and  not 
elsewhere,  at  one  moment  of  time  and  no  other  ?  Why  one  generation 
has  been  favoured  with  a  crowd  of  great  men,  and  other  generations 
refused  one  in  seasons  of  greatest  need?  In  every  great  nation  great 
men  have  been  produced;  but  that  the  great  nations  have  necessarily 
produced  them  is  what  our  profound  ignorance  of  the  conditions  of  their 
production  should  prevent  us  from  asserting. 

The  second  proposition  may  be  regarded  as  M.  Cousin's  definition  of 
the  nature  of  the  great  man.  It  contains  most  important  truth;  above 
all,  it  gives  due  prominence  to  this  truth,  that  a  man  cannot  be  really 
great  merely  by  some  single  aptitude  or  ability,  by  what  is  isolating  and 
distinctive,  but  by  greatness  of  nature  as  a  whole,  greatness  of  mind, 
greatness  of  heart,  so  that  the  roots  of  his  being  strike  deeper  and  wider 
into  the  life  of  his  nation  and  time  and  humanity  itself,  than  those  of 
other  men.  But  it  does  not  express  truth  only :  on  the  contrary,  it  is 
a  serious  error  to  represent  generality  and  individuality  as  two  things 
which  are  combined  or  mingled  in  the  great  man ;  to  maintain  that  he  is 
great  by  the  one  and  a  man  by  the  other ;  and  so  to  separate  the  great- 
ness from  the  man  and  the  man  from  the  greatness.  The  greatness  of 
the  great  man  is  not  an  element,  but  a  predicate  of  him  —  a  predicate  of 
him  as  a  man,  an  individual,  a  whole  human  being. 

I  regard  the  third  proposition,  which  will  be  recognised  as  the  expres- 
sion of  almost  the  entire  positive  substance  of  Mr.  Carlyle's  philosophy 
of  history,  as  in  the  main  untrue.  There  is  the  valuable  truth  in  it,  that 
general  causes,  as  they  are  called,  are  not  omnipotent,  not  independent  of 
individual  intelligences  and  wills,  or  irresistible  over  them ;  that  these 
latter  have  spheres  of  action  of  their  own,  and  when  powerful,  wide 
spheres  of  action.  But  everything  more  which  it  contains  is  exaggera- 
tion and  error.  The  greatest  man's  work  is  but  an  addition  to  the  sum 
of  work  done  by  his  fellow-men,  and  in  no  respect  the  sum  itself.  Great 
men  are  in  no  special  way  representative  men  —  nay,  the  completest  rep- 
resentative men  are  invariably  mediocre  men.     The  great  man  depends 


476  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

on  others  just  as  they  depend  on  him  ;  improves  and  develops  what  others 
have  done,  and  leaves  his  own  work  to  be  in  the  same  way  improved  and 
developed  by  others.  Newton  was  perhaps  the  greatest  man  who  has 
appeared  in  the  history  of  mathematical  and  physical  science;  and  it 
may  be,  as  Mr.  Mills  thinks,  "  that  if  Newton  had  not  lived,  the  world 
must  have  waited  for  the  Newtonian  philosophy  until  there  had  been 
another  Newton  or  his  equivalent ; "  but  a  long  succession  of  far  lesser 
men  have  followed  him  and  added  to  what  he  did,  as  a  long  series  of 
labourers  preceded  him  whose  results  made  his  possible.  It  is  by  no 
means  so  certain  that  some  succession  or  combination  of  eminent  men 
might  not  in  the  lifetime  of  the  first  or  second  generation  after  Newton 
have  found  out  the  law  of  gravitation  without  his  help,  as  it  is  that  New- 
ton himself,  with  the  whole  thought  and  theory  of  his  great  discovery  in 
his  head,  had  to  wait  for  sixteen  years,  unable  to  accomplish  its  proof, 
till  Picard,  by  correctly  measuring  an  arc  of  the  meridian,  gave  him  the 
true  length  of  the  earth's  radius,  a  necessary  element  in  his  reasoning. 
I  readily  grant,  however,  that  a  great  man  may  accomplish  what  no  com- 
bination of  lesser  men,  not  even  the  united  efforts  of  the  whole  human 
race  besides,  can  effect ;  but  then,  on  the  other  hand,  a  small  combina- 
tion of  men  far  from  great,  may  equally  be  able  to  accomplish  what  he 
cannot.  The  work  which  an  age  has  given  it  to  do  may  only  be  achieva- 
ble under  the  guidance  of  a  great  man ;  and  yet  more  work  may  be 
allotted  to  be  done,  and  actually  be  done,  by  an  age  of  merely  ordinary 
men.  The  age  of  Voltaire  was  not  an  age  of  great  men,  but  it  accom- 
plished work  both  for  good  and  evil,  in  a  measure  equalled  by  few  other 
ages  in  the  world's  history.  In  a  word,  those  who  vindicate  for  great 
men  a  place,  and  even  a  large  place,  in  history,  defend  the  interests 
of  truth ;  but  those  who  represent  history  as  only  their  united  biog- 
raphies or  the  connected  series  of  their  actions,  only  resuscitate  an  old 
error  which  died  and  was  buried  long  ago,  —  that  narrow,  superficial, 
and  false  notion  which  caused  a  justly  forgotten  race  of  authors  to 
suppose  the  history  of  nations  was  merely  the  history  of  their  kings 
and  nobles. 

The  fourth  proposition  into  which  I  have  condensed  M.  Cousin's  doc- 
trine of  great  men  asserts  that  they  are  born  and  die  at  the  proper  time, 
,  but  no  criterion  is  given  of  what  is  the  proper  time.  It  is,  consequently, 
so  far  a  vague  unverified  assertion.  And  when  it  adds  that  the  great  man 
is  always  more  or  less  of  a  fatalist,  it  passes  into  positive  error.  Fatalism 
may  be  an  article  of  a  great  man's  creed,  an  element  of  his  faith,  but 
nevertheless  is  a  weakness,  and  no  sign  of  greatness.  In  so  far  as  a  man 
is  possessed  by  a  blind  feeling  of  being  an  instrument  of  destiny,  used  by 
an  irresistible  force  he  knows  not  to  what  end,  instead  of  being  rationally 
conscious  of  having  a  mission  to  accomplish,  a  worthy  work  to  do,  he  is  a- 
man  whose  claims  to  leadership  ought  to  be  distrusted.  There  have  been 
two  men  in  the  present  century  who  have  demanded  to  be  received  as 
political  Messiahs  on  this  ground  of  being  "  men  of  destiny,"  Napoleon  I. 


cousin  47  T 

and  Napoleon  III.,  one  of  them  undoubtedly  a  very  great  man,  the  other 
not  an  ordinary  man  ;  and  have  not  both,  like  blind  men  leading  the 
blind,  led  those  who  followed  them  into  the  ditch  ?  Fortune,  fate,  one's 
star  —  belief  in  these  things  may  have  characterised  Wallenstein,  Napo- 
leon, and  many  other  great  men  as  well  as  small;  but  certainly  not  all 
great  men,  and  not  the  greatest  of  great  men,  the  wisest  and  best  among 
them. 

The  fifth  proposition  contains  probably  the  most  dangerous  error  of 
any  in  the  whole  theory,  and,  at  the  same  time,  truth  enough  to  give  it 
plausibility.  A  great  man  must  certainly  be  a  man  who  can  do  great 
things ;  the  greatness  of  his  work,  all  hindrances  duly  taken  into  account, 
must  be  the  truest  sign  of  the  greatness  of  his  character.  But  success  is 
another  matter.  The  greatest  man  may  be  sent  into  the  world  either  too- 
soon  or  too  late  to  succeed.  "  The  noble  army  of  the  martyrs  "  has  num- 
bered in  its  ranks  the  wisest  and  bravest,  the  greatest  and  most  heroic  of 
our  race.  He  who  was  the  perfect  type  of  greatness  and  the  author  of  the 
greatest  thing  on  earth,  had  no  success  in  the  sense  meant,  and  founded 
His  work  on  a  death  not  of  glory  but  of  shame.  "  Give  me  an  instance," 
says  M.  Cousin,  "  of  unmerited  glory ;  "  as  if  times  without  number  the 
cry  of,  "Not  this  man,  but  Barabbas,"  had  not  ascended  from  the  earth, 
absolving  the  vile  and  criminal,  and  dooming  to  death  the  hero  and  the 
sainf ;  and  again,  "whoever  does  not  succeed  is  of  no  use  in  the  world, 
leaves  no  great  result,  and  passes  away  as  if  he  had  never  been,"  as  if 
there  had  not  been  many  sad  defeats  worth  far  more  than  many  brilliant 
triumphs,  and  as  if  the  blood  of  a  Polycarp  and  a,  Hus,  an  Arnold  of 
Brescia  and  a  Savonarola,  and  all  the  host  of  those  who  have  died  for 
faith,  for  science,  for  freedom,  for  country,  had  been  shed  in  vain  because 
shed  for  a  good  afar  off,  and  not  for  that  glory  which  our  author  tells  us 
is  ■"'  almost  always  contemporaneous  with  a  great  action,  and  never  far  dis- 
tant from  a  great  man's  tomb.''  M.  Cousin  speaks  in  a  higher  and  truer 
strain  when  he  says,  "  We  should  despise  reputation,  the  success  of  a  day 
and  the  trifling  means  that  lead  to  it.  We  should  think  of  doing,  doing- 
much,  doing  well  —  of  being,  and  not  appearing ;  for  it  is  an  infallible 
rule,  that  all  which  appears  without  being,  soon  disappears  ;  but  all 
which  exists,  by  virtue  of  its  nature,  sooner  or  later  must  appear."  But 
'this  is  not  only  inconsistent  with  the  tenor  of  all  that  goes  before  it 
and  follows  after  it  in  the  lecture  under  consideration,  but  is  still 
merely  partially  true,  dubious,  incapable  of  verification.  Evil  is  no 
empty  appearance,  but  a  strong  reality  which  can  struggle  with  good 
on  not  unequal  terms ;  which  has  conquered  good  almost  or  altogether 
as  often  as  it  has  been  conquered  by  it ;  and  which  equally  with 
good  has  powers  and  laws  by  which  it  grows  and  spreads.  There  are 
lies  and  vices  dating  from  the  first  man,  which  are  as  strong  to-day 
as  ever  they  were,  as  flourishing  as  anything  to  be  seen  in  this  world ; 
and  those  who  tell  us  they  are  unreal,  mere  appearances,  which  must 
soon  vanish   away,  are  confident  as   to  the  future  only  from  having 


478  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

failed  to  look  at  the  facts  of  the  past  and  to  study  the  powers  of  the 
present. 

The  sixth  proposition  rests  on  the  error  contained  in  M.  Cousin's 
third  proposition.  There  ought  to  be  no  such  distinction  admitted  as 
that  which  it  draws.  The  meannesses  of  great  men  cannot  be  so  separated 
from  their  greatness  :  on  the  contrary,  their  every  meanness  is  a  deduc- 
tion from  their  greatness ;  their  vices  are  as  historical  as  their  virtues ; 
some  of  them  have  been  as  great  for  evil  as  for  good.  The  right  of  every 
man  to  be  judged  fairly,  charitably,  not  by  single  acts  and  features,  and 
especially  not  by  single  facts  and  failures,  but  by  his  character  and  works 
in  their  entirety,  is  enough  for  the  greatest  man.  And  those  who  like 
Hegel,  like  Carlyle,  like  Cousin,  claim  for  the  great  man  more  than  this, 
—  as  that  he  shall  be  judged  by  another  standard  than  his  fellow-men, 
that  his  greatness  shall  be  counted  goodness,  that  his  strength  shall  be 
held  to  be  its  own  law,  that  his  sins  against  humanity  shall  be  blotted 
out  from  the  page  of  history  and  only  what  redounds  to  his  glory  recorded, 
and  the  like,  —  simply  advise  us  to  falsify  history,  to  delude  ourselves,  and 
to  set  up  idols  and  worship  them.  When,  going  farther,  they  sneer  at 
those  who  reject  their  advice  as  "  small  critics,"  or  "  psychological  peda- 
gogues," or  "  valet-souls,  incapable  of  recognising  the  worth  of  a  hero," 
they  show  a  foolish  contempt  for  reason  and  conscience,  and  a  foolish 
respect  for  what  is  precisely  the  valet's  creed,  —  that  belief  in  power  and 
consequent  disbelief  in  the  primacy  of  right  which  make  mean  and  igno- 
ble souls.  By  such  a  creed  no  man  ever  has  been,  or  ever  will  be,  helped 
to  be  heroic. 

The  seventh  proposition  involved  in  M.  Cousin's  theory  must  be  dis- 
carded with  the  division  of  the  course  of  history  on  which  it  depends. 
Even  the  so-called  epoch  of  the  infinite  produced  many  great  men. 
The  founders  of  all  the  great  religions  belonged  to  it ;  and  they  have 
influenced  humanity  not  less  than  either  philosophers  or  conquerors. 
But  the  East  had  also  philosophers  who  thought  out  profound  sys- 
tems of  speculation,  and  conquerors  who  created  and  destroyed  vast 
empires.  Egypt  and  Assyria  must  have  had  many  men  of  genius  in 
the  spheres  of  art  and  industry.  The  authors  of  the  Book  of  Job  and 
of  the  Bamayana  must  be  allowed  to  rank  high  among  the  world's 
great  poets. 

The  last  proposition  suggests  a  question  which  M.  Cousin  should  not 
have  overlooked  :  Is  there  any  standard  by  which  we  can  compare  the 
great  men  of  different  spheres  of  life,  the  poet  and  the  mechanical 
inventor,  the  founder  of  a  religion  and  the  conqueror,  the  painter  or 
musician,  and  the  mathematician  or  philosopher,  —  and  if  so,  what  is  it? 
How  are  we  to  measure  the  relative  magnitudes  of  Aristotle,  Casar, 
Raffaelle,  Luther,  Shakespeare,  and  Newton?  Individual  preference  is 
obviously  worth  little,  as  each  individual  is  more  able  to  appreciate  some 
excellences  than  others,  and,  by  constitution  and  habits,  prone  to  over- 
estimate certain  merits  and  to  underestimate  others.     Popular  opinion  is 


JOUFFBOY  479 

obviously  worth  little  move,  based  as  it  invariably  is  on  a  superficial 
acquaintance  with  facts.  And  even  were  both  far  more  reliable  than 
they  are,  it  could  only  be  through  their  conforming  to  a,  standard,  a  real 
or  objective  rule  of  measurement.  Till  this  is  discovered,  therefore,  —  and 
it  is  not  likely  to  be  easily  discovered,  —  all  discussion  as  to  which  sphere 
of  life  has  been  adorned  with  the  greatest  men  must  be  fruitless,  and  all 
decisions  in  favour  of  one  over  another  arbitrary  and  premature. 


II 


M.  Theodore  Jouffroy  (1796-1842)  shared  many  of  M. 
Cousin's  ideas,  without  detriment  to  his  own  independence, 
originality,  and  ingenuity  as  a  thinker.  He  could  not  rival 
Cousin  in  producing  broad  general  effects,  but  he  had  greater 
influence  on  a  select  class.  He  was  almost  as  remarkable  as  a 
literary  artist,  while  his  style  was  characteristically  different. 
He  was  much  more  interested  in  psychology,  and  less  in  gen- 
eral metaphysics  ;  indeed,  for  him  philosophy  was  the  science 
of  man,  and  its  chief  problem  was  to  determine  the  destiny  of 
man.  Cousin  was  enthusiastic  in  seeking  and  setting  forth  the 
truth,  but  apt  to  be  much  too  easily  convinced  that  he  had  got 
it,  and  to  proclaim  his  views  with  a  confidence  and  unquali- 
fiedness  more  consonant  to  an  oratorical  than  a  philosophical 
temperament.  Jouffroy  was  an  unresting  and  indefatigable 
inquirer,  distrustful  of  himself,  and  prone  to  doubt.  His  early 
beliefs  had  failed  him,  and  he  was  not  inclined  to  adopt  others 
without  a  thorough  sifting.  At  the  same  time  he  was  a  nat- 
urally pious,  earnest,  and  truthful  soul.  Hence  his  short 
and  sad,  yet  beautiful  and  useful,  life,  was  mainly  a  pathetic 
struggle  to  overcome  his  own  intellectual  scepticism.1 

He  repeatedly  touched  the  subject  of  historical  philosophy 
with  all  his  natural  superiority  of  thought  and  style.  In  the 
first  series  of  his  '  Melanges  philosophiques '  (1833)  he  has 
brought  together,  under  the  heading  of  '  Philosophie  de  l'his- 
toire,'  the  following   essays,  which  had  for  the   most   part 

1On  Jouffroy  may  be  consulted,  Mignet,  '  Eloges  historiques  ' ;  Ad.  Gamier  in 
Franck's '  Diet.  d.  Sc.  phil.' ;  Taine, '  Philosophes  francais ' ;  Ferraz, '  Spiritualisme 
et  liberalisme  ' ;  and  Caro,  '  Philosophie  et  philosophes.' 


480  PHILOSOPHY   Or   HISTOKY    IN   1TEANCE 

appeared  in  the  '  Globe '  from  1825  to  1827 :  1.  How  dog- 
mas come  to  an  end ;  2.  The  Sorbonne  and  the  philosophers ; 
3.  Reflections  on  the  philosophy  of  history ;  4.  Bossuet,  Vico, 
and  Herder;  5.  The  part  of  Greece  in  the  development  of 
humanity ;  6.  The  present  state  of  humanity.  All  these 
essays  are  attractive  and  suggestive  reading ;  but  only  the 
third  and  sixth  are  of  a  sufficiently  general  nature  to  warrant 
our  giving  an  account  of  them. 

Here  is  a  summary  of  the  Reflections :  The  great  difference 
between  man  and  the  other  animals  is,  that  while  their  con- 
dition remains  from  age  to  age  the  same,  his  is  continually 
changing.  History  is  the  record  of  these  changes,  and  the 
philosophy  of  history  is  the  investigation  of  their  cause  and 
law.  Now  human  mobility  cannot  have  its  principle  in  the 
outward  world,  which  acts  on  the  brutes  not  less  than  on  man, 
and  besides,  changes  not;  nor  in  the  animal  instincts  and 
passions,  which  are  the  same  in  all  lands  and  ages;  but  in 
that  which  is  essentially  changeable  in  the  constitution  of 
man  —  the  ideas  of  his  intelligence.  The  changes  which 
take  place  among  ideas  originate  all  other  changes  which 
take  place  in  the  condition  of  man ;  or,  in  other  words,  all 
the  changes  of  history ;  so  that  the  sole  object  of  history  is  to 
trace  the  development  of  human  intelligence,  as  it  is  mani- 
fested by  the  outward  changes  which  it  at  different  epochs 
produces.  But  as  ideas,  which  are  invisible,  can  only  be 
inferred  from  facts  which  are  visible,  history,  to  accomplish 
its  single  aim,  must  solve  these  three  problems:  1°,  What 
has  been  the  visible  form  of  humanity  from  the  beginning  to 
the  present  time  ?  2°,  What  has  been  the  development  of  the 
ideas  of  humanity  from  the  beginning  to  the  present  time? 
and,  3°,  How  these  two  developments  have  corresponded  — 
how  the  development  of  ideas  has  produced  the  development 
of  the  visible  form  of  humanity  from  the  beginning  to  the 
present  time. 

The  majority  of  historians  have  confined  their  attention 
to  the  facts,  and  frequently  to  the  least  important  classes  of 
facts.  The  authors  who  introduced  the  history  of  manners 
and  institutions  into  general  history  accomplished  a  revolu- 
tion, but  did  not,  as  was  at  first  supposed,  get  at  the  root  of 


jouffkoy  481 

• 
the  matter,  the  cause  of  these  causes  being  now  seen  to  be  the 
succession  of  ideas.  A  time  may  be  anticipated  when  this 
also  will  be  regarded  as  a  secondary  and  subordinate  cause, 
and  valued  chiefly  as  leading  to  the  discovery  of  the  fixed  and 
immutable  law  of  the  succession.  That  reached,  history  will 
lose  its  independent  existence,  and  be  resolved  into  science ; 
but  the  day  is  obviously  distant,  since  even  the  events,  insti- 
tutions, religions,  and  manners  of  different  epochs  and  coun- 
tries are  imperfectly  known,  and  their  immediate  cause  —  the 
succession  of  ideas  —  far  more  imperfectly  still.  To  ascertain 
the  development  of  ideas  is,  and  will  long  be,  the  grand 
desideratum. 

In  the  individual,  in  society,  and  in  humanity,  there  is  a 
twofold  movement  of  intelligence ;  the  natural  or  spontane- 
ous, and  the  voluntary  or  reflective ;  the  former  regulative  of 
common  thought,  and  the  latter  of  philosophical  thought. 
The  reflective  movement  is  always  in  advance  of  the  spon- 
taneous movement,  the  few  who  deliberately  seek  truth 
necessarily  finding  it  sooner  than  the  many  who  do  not. 
Both  movements  proceed  towards  the  same  end  and  in  obedi- 
ence to  the  same  law,  but  differing  in  velocity,  and  yet  acting 
on  each  other,  the  more  rapid  accelerating  the  slower,  and 
the  slower  retarding  the  more  rapid;  so  that  the  velocity  of 
the  development  of  humanity  is  the  resultant  of  the  unequal 
velocities  of  these  two  movements.  This  combination  of 
movements  in  the  generation  and  succession  of  ideas,  and  in 
the  transformation  of  ideas  into  laws,  institutions,  and  man- 
ners, is  a  beneficent  necessity,  since,  if  the  movement  of  the 
masses  retards  that  of  the  philosophers,  it  also  renders  it  more 
certain  and  fruitful,  prevents  mistakes,  and  secures  correct- 
ness. 

The  great  question  whether  the  movement  of  humanity  is 
necessary  or  not,  can  only  be  determined  by  a  consideration  of 
the  two  elements  or  principles  which  enter  into  the  produc- 
tion of  all  human  events  —  the  passions  of  human  nature  and 
the  ideas  of  human  intelligence.  If  reason  always  ruled  in 
an  individual  we  could  foresee  his  conduct ;  that  we  so  often 
cannot  foresee  it  is  because  we  cannot  divine  how  far  he 
will  listen  to  passion,  and  because  passion  is  so  variable  and 


482  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

• 

capricious  in  its  working  that  its  movements  cannot  be  cal- 
culated. Passion  has,  however,  less  influence,  and  reason 
more,  on  the  conduct  of  peoples  than  of  individuals.  The 
passions  of  individuals  in  a  community  neutralise  one  another 
by  their  opposition ;  and  so  leave  the  general  ideas,  on  which 
all  are  agreed,  to  rule  with  comparatively  little  resistance. 
Hence  the  conduct  of  peoples  is  far  more  conformed  to  their 
ideas  than  the  conduct  of  individuals,  and  can  be  far  more 
easily  foreseen.  Hence,  also,  the  ease  and  accuracy  with 
which  the  conduct  of  nations  can  be  calculated  are  in  propor- 
tion to  their  freedom  and  self-government,  since  the  greater 
the  influence  of  public  opinion  in  a  nation,  and  the  less  the 
direction  of  the  nation  depends  on  the  will  of  certain  indi- 
viduals, the  greater  is  the  ascendancy  of  ideas,  which  conform 
to  law  and  logic,  and  the  less  the  ascendancy  of  the  passions, 
which  contravene  law  and  are  contrary  to  logic.  "  But,  in 
every  case,  the  influence  of  individual  passions  can  reach  only 
events  of  a  secondary  and  transient  importance.  Great  events 
are  always  beyond  it ;  for  nothing  great,  nothing  permanent, 
can  ever  be  produced  among  a  people,  whatever  be  its  govern- 
ment, except  by  the  force  and  with  the  support  of  the  convic- 
tions of  that  people.  All  that  the  passions  of  individuals 
can  attempt  and  accomplish  in  opposition  to  these  convictions 
is  speedily  swept  away.  No  despot,  no  favourite,  no  man  of 
genius,  may  neglect  these  convictions  in  his  enterprises  and 
institutions ;  nay,  more,  no  one  can  be  a  successful  despot  or 
a  great  statesman  except  by  obeying  them.  In  fine,  passion 
acts  only  on  the  surface  of  the  history  of  nations,  while  the 
foundation  is  in  ideas."  It  is  unwarrantable,  then,  to  explain 
everything  in  history  by  the  inevitable  development  of 
ideas,  as  some  moderns  do;  but  it  is  still  more  unwar- 
rantable to  explain  everything  by  individual  characters  and 
passions,  like  the  ancients.  The  truth  lies  between  these 
two  extremes. 

The  passions  of  individuals,  however,  really  exerted  a 
greater  power  in  ancient  than  they  do  in  modern  times.  The 
necessary  progress  of  intelligence  is  what  Bossuet  called 
Providence,  and  what  others  call  destiny,  or  the  force  of 
things.      Bossuet's  word  is  good,  but  not  in  the  sense  of 


JOUFFROY  483 

an  actual  interposition  of  God,  who  acts  with  regard  to 
humanity,  no  less  than  with  regard  to  the  heavenly  bodies, 
through  fixed  and  certain  laws,  although  He  acts  differ- 
ently, since  the  laws  which  determine  the  development  of 
humanity  presuppose  reason  and  liberty,  and  operate  through 
them. 

Further,  the  movement  of  humanity  is  not  in  a  circle,  like 
that  of  the  stars,  but  progressive.  The  sentiments  of  an 
age  as  to  the  Good,  Beautiful,  and  True,  are  expressed  with 
greatest  vividness  by  the  poets.  True  poets  are  always  the 
children  of  their  age.  It  is  the  mission  of  philosophers  to 
comprehend  their  age,  to  advance  before  it,  and  to  prepare 
the  future ;  and  a  few  of  them  have  risen  to  so  lofty  a  point 
of  view,  and  seen  so  much  of  the  course  to  be  traversed  by 
man  through  time,  as  to  have  become  intelligible  only  after 
ages  of  progress. 

As  a  work  of  art,  M.  Jouffroy's  essay  is  almost  perfect.  And  the 
thoughts  which  it  conveys  are,  on  the.  whole,  both  true  and  important, 
well  worthy  of  the  beautiful  expression  which  they  have  received.  At  the 
same  time,  they  are  too  general,  and,  so  to  speak,  external,  to  constitute 
a  philosophy  of  history.  They  are  simply  what  they  profess  to  be  — 
"  reflections  on  the  philosophy  of  history,"  —  nothing  more. 

Regarded  as  such,  there  is  only  one  point  to  which  we  feel  compelled  to 
take  decided  objection.  M.  Jouffroy  adopted  M.  Cousin's  division  of 
intelligence  into  spontaneous  and  reflective,  without  improvement  or  modi- 
fication; and  hence  what  has  been  said  on  this  subject  with  respect  to  M. 
Cousin  is  equally  applicable  with  respect  to  M.  Jouffroy.  The  two  sections 
of  his  essay  which  he  devotes  to  the  exposition  of  the  distinction  are  con- 
fused and  inaccurate.  All  that  he  says  of  spontaneous  intelligence  pro- 
ceeds on  the  absurd  and  self-contradictory  supposition  of  its  being  "  blind 
and  involuntary."  Almost  all  that  he  says  of  reflective  intelligence  is 
true  only  if  it  be  no  separate  mode  of  intelligence,  as  it  is  described  to 
be,  but  only  an  extension  of  spontaneous  intelligence.  Thus  M.  Jouffroy 
insists  that  reflective  intelligence  is  always  in  advance  of  spontaneous 
intelligence  in  the  discovery  of  truth ;  whereas,  in  the  only  sense  in 
which  reflection  can  be  with  any  propriety  described  as  a  distinct  mode  of 
thought,  it  never  is,  and  never  can  be,  in  advance  of  spontaneous  thought, 
since  that  thought  is  its  object. 

On  another  point  M.  Jouffroy  has  expressed  himself  too  absolutely. 
It  is  a  very  important  truth,  when  properly  understood,  that  the  principle 
of  the  mobility  of  human  things  is  in  the  mobility  of  the  ideas  of  human 
intelligence ;  but  an  adequate  comprehension  of  it  will  lead  us  to  guard 


484  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

and  qualify  it,  and  not  to  affirm,  with  M.  Jouffroy,  that  the  whole  of  his- 
tory is,  in  the  last  analysis,  only  the  history  of  ideas.  Feelings  presuppose 
ideas  —  they  cannot  operate  without  ideas  ;  it  does  not  follow  that  they 
have  no  real  existence,  that  they  can  be  resolved  into  ideas,  or  even  that 
they  are  less  powerful  factors  of  history  than  ideas.  The  development  of 
intelligence  is  of  primary  importance  in  the  philosophical  study  of  history, 
not  because  intelligence  is  the  only,  or  even  the  most  powerful,  element 
in  history,  but  because  it  holds  such  a  position  in  the  human  mind  that 
all  other  principles  are  dependent  on  it,  and  can  only  be  studied  as  de- 
pendent on  it.  The  dependence  of  the  emotional  principles  of  human 
nature  on  the  intellectual,  however,  is  not  due  to  their  inferior  power, 
but  to  the  character  of  their  power  —  the  need  which  they  have,  owing 
to  their  blindness  as  mere  impulses,  of  the  enlightenment  and  guidance 
which  intellect  alone  can  supply. 

The  title,  'De  l'^tat  actuel  de  l'humanite', '  is  an  inadequate 
and  inaccurate  designation  for  an  essay  which  is,  in  reality,  an 
attempt  to  forecast  the  future  of  our  race.  The  author  glances 
over  the  world  of  humanity,  and  sees  it  divided  into  two  very 
unequal  portions,  barbarous  tribes  and  civilised  nations. 
History,  he  thinks,  warrants  him  at  once  to  conclude  that  the 
former  are  destined  to  become  civilised;  and  he  asks,  Will 
this  be  through  a  new  system  of  civilisation,  arising  from 
the  bosom  of  barbarism,  or  through  the  triumph  of  the  already 
■existing  systems  of  civilisation  over  barbarism?  He  finds 
in  the  progressive  advance  of  our  present  civilisation  —  the 
gradual  diminution  of  barbarism  —  the  relatively  small  num- 
ber of  savages — their  division  into  feeble  and  unconnected 
portions  —  and  the  neighbourhood  and  pressure  of  civilised 
peoples,  more  powerful  and  active,  —  so  many  obvious  proofs 
that  the  number  of  systems  of  civilisation  is  finally  settled ; 
and  that  it  is  the  destiny  of  the  savage  portion  of  human- 
ity to  be  amalgamated  with  the  civilised  masses  already 
formed. 

He  surveys  these  masses  and  discovers  that  they  fall  into 
three  groups,  or  belong  to  three  different  systems  of  civilisa- 
tion, based  on  three  different  religions  or  philosophies,  the 
Christian,  the  Mohammedan,  and  the  Brahminic.  The  radi- 
cal difference  between  savages  and  civilised  nations  is  that 
the  former  have  only  crude  and  vague  ideas  on  the  great 


JOUFFROY  485 

questions  which  interest  humanity,  while  the  latter  have 
complete  and  coherent  religions,  which  involve  not  only  a 
certain  mode  of  worship,  but  an  entire  system  of  civilisation, 
bearing  to  the  religion  the  relation  of  effect  to  cause.  M. 
Jouffroy  then  compares  the  three  systems,  and  finds  that 
Christianity  alone  is  at  present  endowed  with  expansive  life, 
—  with  the  twofold  zeal  of  improvement  and  proselytism; 
that  while  the  Christian  system  is  making  progress,  and  the 
nations  which  compose  it  are  daily  becoming  more  united  and 
powerful,  Mohammedanism  and  Brahminism  make  no  con- 
quests, resist  the  invasion  of  Christianity  chiefly  by  their 
inertia,  sap  the  strength  of  the  nations  which  receive  them, 
and,  in  a  word,  manifest  all  the  symptoms  of  decay.  Hence, 
he  concludes  that,  if  the  Christian  system  of  civilisation  be 
not  destroyed  by  internal  defects,  it  will  gain  possession 
of  the  world, —  that  its  future  involves  the  future  of  the 
world. 

Then,  looking  more  closely  at  the  movement  of  Christian 
civilisation,  he  seems  to  himself  to  see  that  it  is  led  by  three 
nations,  France,  England,  and  Germany;  all  other  nations 
imitating  what  is  already  realised  in  these,  while  they, 
although  finding  much  to  imitate  in  each  other,  have  yet  in 
certain  respects  reached  a  height  from  which  they  can  make 
further  advances  only  by  invention.  Each  of  these  nations 
has  a  special  faculty  in  which  it  excels,  each  has  its  peculiar 
employment  in  the  work  of  civilisation,  but  the  distribution 
of  their  gifts  is  for  the  good  of  the  world,  their  labours  tend 
towards  a  common  and  beneficent  end,  and  there  exists  be- 
tween them  an  involuntary  alliance,  truly  majestic  and  holy, 
having  for  object  the  progress  of  humanity.  Germany  is  the 
learned  nation,  distinguished  by  patience  of  intellect,  accum- 
ulating with  a  laborious  curiosity  and  prodigious  memory 
all  the  facts  of  history  and  science,  and  thus  supplying  the 
Taw  materials  of  ideas.  France  is  the  philosophical  nation, 
distinguished  by  clearness  of  understanding,  by  the  power  of 
drawing  from  facts  what  is  general  and  suitable  in  them  with 
accuracy,  order,  and  acumen, —  in  a  word,  of  forming  ideas 
into  shape  and  rendering  them  popular.      England  is  the 


486  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOKY   HST   FRANCE      - 

practical  nation,  distinguished  by  public  spirit,  industry, 
and  the  excellence  of  her  institutions,  and  having  for  task 
the  application  of  ideas  to  the  concerns  of  life.  The  true 
statesman  in  each  of  these  nations  should  look  beyond  the 
good  of  his  own  country,  the  worn-out  end  of  its  aggrandise- 
ment and  the  abasement  of  its  neighbours,  to  the  advantage 
of  the  union  of  Europe,  and  of  the  civilisation  of  the  world 
by  the  union  and  the  ideas  of  Europe.  "  The  politics  of  our 
day  should  look  not  to  the  balance  of  Europe,  but  to  the 
future  of  humanity.  The  civil  wars  of  Europe  are  ended; 
the  rivalship  of  the  peoples  which  compose  it  is  about  to  cease, 
as  the  rivalship  of  the  cities  of  Greece  ceased  under  the  sway 
of  Alexander,  as  the  diversities  of  the  provinces  of  France 
disappeared  under  the  unity  of  the  monarchy." 

It  would  be  most  unreasonable  to  object  to  the  speculations  of  ■which 
a  summary  has  now  been  given  that  they  are  merely  general ;  that  they 
involve  no  conclusions  as  to  particular  contingencies,  no  predictions  of 
particular  occurrences.  In  carefully  refraining  from  all  such,  M.  Jouf- 
froy  has  shown  his  wisdom,  his  knowledge  of  the  limits  within  which 
historical  prevision  is  possible.  The  science  of  history,  whatever  it  may 
in  the  future  become,  is  as  yet  very  far  from  being  an  exact  science  like 
astronomy.  It  furnishes  us  with  no  means  of  calculating  the  courses  of 
nations  with  precision  and  definiteness  like  the  courses  of  the  stars;  of 
foretelling  that  at  this  or  that  period  of  future  time  a  nation  will  do  this 
or  that  action,  as  we  can  foretell  that  at  a  certain  date  a  star  will  arrive 
at  a  certain  point.  To  forecast,  through  reasoning  on  the  general  ten- 
dencies of  nations,  the  general  character  and  direction  of  their  future 
movements,  is  the  utmost  that  can  be  accomplished,  and  even  this  can- 
not be  done  without  difficulty,  and  without  considerable  probability  of 
error.  Perhaps  M.  Jouffroy,  notwithstanding  the  caution  of  procedure 
which  has  been  noted,  and  his  exceptional  clearness  and  penetration  of 
intellect,  has  not  entirely  escaped  error. 

The  inference  that  what  remains  of  barbarism  cannot  give  rise  to  any 
great  and  independent  religion  or  philosophy,  nor,  consequently,  to  any 
great  and  independent  civilisation,  appears  irrefragable.  The  inference 
that  the  Christian  system  is  —  even  looking  exclusively  to  historical  con- 
siderations —  incomparably  superior  to  the  Brahminical  and  Mohamme- 
dan systems  in  all  the  elements  of  life  and  power,  and  must  conquer  and 
destroy  them  if  the  struggle  be  sufficiently  prolonged,  appears  equally 
obvious  and  certain,  although  the  number  of  adherents  of  Brahminism 
and  the  extent  and  possibilities  of  Mohammedan  proselytism  may  have 
been  understated.     But  it  is  not  legitimate  to  identify,  as  M.  Jouffroy 


JOUPFROY  487 

has  virtually  done,  the  conditional  conclusion  that  the  Christian  system 
will  gain  possession  of  the  world  if  not  destroyed  by  internal  defects, 
with  the  positive  and  unconditional  conclusion  that  the  Christian  system 
will  gain  possession  of  the  world.  The  former  conclusion  is  alone  proved 
by  M.  Jouffroy,  and  because  it  is  proved  the  latter  is  falsely  supposed  to 
be  proved.  In  order  to  reach  the  latter  conclusion  —  in  order  to  make 
out  the  probability  of  the  Christian  system  destroying  every  other  and 
becoming  universal  —  it  was  incumbent  on  our  author  to  show  that  the 
hypothesis  contained  in  the  former  conclusion  might  be  rejected ;  that 
there  was  no  probability  of  the  Christian  system  perishing  through  inter- 
nal defects.  The  neglect  to  attempt  this  was  a  serious  omission.  It  is 
precisely  at  this  point  that  all  European  thinkers  who  doubt  or  deny  that 
the  future  will  belong  to  Christianity  diverge  and  differ  from  those  who 
believe  and  affirm  it.  They  do  not  imagine  that  the  Christian  system 
will  be  overcome  by  Mohammedanism  or  Brahminism ;  but  they  pretend 
that  it  is  a  combination  of  truth  and  error,  that  it  has  defects  as  well  as 
merits,  and  must  eventually  give  place  to  a  more  complete  and  determi- 
nate system  of  solutions  to  the  problems  which  interest  humanity.  They 
look  especially  to  science,  which  has  in  recent  times  made  such  wonderful 
and  rapid  progress  in  so  many  directions,  to  bring  forth  a  general  doc- 
trine capable  of  supplying  all  the  wants  and  guiding  all  the  activities  of 
man  in  a  more  satisfactory  way  than  any  religion.  The  aim  of  M.  Jouf- 
froy's  argument  required  him  to  prove  such  hope  an  illusion,  and  to  con- 
vict those  who  indulge  in  it  of  turning  away  from  the  highest  and  most 
comprehensive  truth  to  one  lower  and  narrower,  from  the  ultimate  and 
complete  to  a  derivative  and  partial  good.  This  requirement  he  has 
failed  to  fulfil,  —has  failed  even  to  see  that  it  existed. 

Dissent  must  further  be  expressed  from  that  portion  of  M.  Jouffroy's 
speculations  which  concern  the  relation  of  England,  France,  and  Ger- 
many to  humanity  and  its  future.  Although  his  views  on  this  subject 
are  the  reflections  of  a  just  and  generous  nature,  include  some  important 
truths,  and  are  very  generally  entertained,  they  are,  as  a  whole,  not  true ; 
and  it  is  most  undesirable  that  they  should  longer  continue  to  be  re- 
ceived so  implicitly  and  widely  as  they  are.  That  England,  France,  and 
Germany  are,  if  all  things  be  taken  into  account,  at  the  head  of  Euro- 
pean civilisation,  is  doubtless  true ;  and  that  each  excels  the  other  two  in 
some  respects,  and  is  inferior  in  others,  is  likewise  true :  but  there  is  a 
wide  interval  between  the  first  of  these  truths  and  the  assumption  that 
the  nations  mentioned  will  retain  in  the  future  the  same  rank  relatively 
either  to  each  other  or  to  other  nations  which  they  occupy  at  present ; 
and  a  wide  interval  also  between  the  second  truth  and  the  assumption 
that  their  excellences  and  defects  are  due  to  the  presence  or  absence  of 
special  faculties  which  mark  out  for  them  their  proper  and  peculiar 
employment  in  the  work  of  human  progress. 

What  guarantee  is  there  that  England,  France,  and  Germany  will  long 
retain  their  present  relative  positions  ?    What  certainty  is  there  for  any 


488  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

one  of  them,  that  a  hundred  years  hence  it  will  be  in  the  first  rank  of 
nations?  What  probability  is  there  that  no  other  nation  will  have 
reached  an  equal  height  ?  Italy,  so  far  behind  them  when  M.  Jouffroy 
wrote,  is  already  nearly  on  a  line  with  them,  being  probably,  of  all  the 
nations  of  Europe,  that  which  has  made,  in  the  present  generation,  the 
greatest  progress  of  a  truly  satisfactory  kind;  and  this  in  the  main,  not 
through  following  or  imitating  any  foreign  state,  but  by  advancing  along 
a  path  of  her  own,  by  the  development  of  her  own  proper  life.  We  have 
but  to  recall  the  names  of  Manzoni,  Pellico,  Niccolini,  Giusti,  and  Balbo, 
of  Kosrnini,  Gioberti,  and  Mamiani,  of  Cavour  and  D'Azeglio,  of  Manin, 
Mazzini,  and  Garibaldi,  and  of  the  other  noble  men  whom  Italy  has  pro- 
duced during  the  present  century  with  such  wonderful  profusion,  to  con- 
vince ourselves  that  she  has  been  for  more  than  a  generation,  in  one 
respect  at  least,  first  among  the  nations  —  viz.,  in  the  intensity  of  her 
desire  to  impress  the  image  of  her  own  national  individuality  alike  on 
her  philosophical  speculations,  her  works  of  art  and  literature,  and  her 
political  action.  And  why  should  Italy  not  advance  as  far  on  her  way  as 
England,  France,  or  Germany  on  theirs?  For  peace  and  war,  for  adven- 
ture by  land  and  sea,  for  science  and  art,  prose  and  poetry,  political  subt- 
lety, religious  fervour,  and  heroic  self-sacrifice,  the  Italian  genius  is 
inferior  to  no  other  in  Europe.  Further,  there  are  two  nations  which  in 
strength  are  perhaps  even  at  present  equal  to  those  which  M.  Jouffroy 
described  as  bearing  with  them  the  whole  race  of  mankind;  which  are 
growing  more  rapidly  than  they;  which  are  so  situated  as  to  be  safer 
than  the  safest  of  them  from  permanent  conquest ;  and  which  appear  to 
be  far  more  distant  from  their  natural  limits  of  increase.  The  possibili- 
ties before  the  United  States  and  Russia  are  so  grand  that  no  mortal  has 
a  right  to  deny  that  the  time  may  come  when  the  mightiest  power  by  sea 
at  present  will  be  doomed  to  stand  before  the  one,  and  the  mightiest  on 
land  before  the  other,  like  Hector  before  Achilles,  able  only  in  presence 
of  the  stronger  and  more  heaven-favoured  foe  to  resolve,  "not  inglorious 
at  least  shall  I  perish,  but  after  doing  some  great  thing  that  may  be 
spoken  of  in  ages  to  come." 

"  M17  fiiiv  acnrovSet  ye  tcai  clkKclSh  airoKoturjV , 
'AMa  fLeya  pe£as  Tt  Kal  eacrOfnevourL  TrvBecrdat.*' 

To  speak  of  the  distinctive  merits  of  nations  as  due  to  the  operation 
of  special  faculties,  also  appears  erroneous  and  misleading.  Literally 
and  strictly  understood,  indeed,  it  is  so  obviously  absurd  as  to  be  inde- 
fensible, since  every  man  of  sane  mind  has  the  same  faculties  as  every 
other.  In  order  to  get  from  it  a  credible  meaning,  we  must  understand 
by  faculty  merely  an  aptitude  resulting  from  the  circumstances  in  which 
a  people  has  been  placed,  a  facility  of  thought  or  action  which  has 
required  time,  long  or  short,  to  form.  To  affirm  that  a  nation  has  a 
special  faculty  in  this  sense,  is  not  only  to  make  a  loose  and  confused 


JOUFFROY  489 

application  of  language,  but  to  state  what,  if  true,  obviously  both  de- 
mands and  admits  of  explanation  instead  of  being  itself  the  sufficient 
explanation  of  anything,  since  such  a  faculty  is  an  effect,  may  be  even 
of  recent  origin,  or  capable  of  being  easily  acquired.  To  attribute  to  a 
nation  a  special  faculty  in  any  other  sense,  has  no  warrant  either  in  rea- 
son or  facts.  Undoubtedly  there  is  more  learning  in  Germany  than  in 
France  or  England :  but  the  causes  plainly  are  not  special  faculties  for 
learning  granted  to  Germans  and  denied  to  Frenchmen  and  Englishmen, 
or  even  the  same  faculties  in  any  exceptional  measure,  quicker  apprehen- 
sions, more  capacious  memories,  greater  love  of  knowledge  for  its  own 
sate,  more  patience  of  intellect  or  more  energy  of  will;  but  the  superior- 
ity of  the  arrangements  and  institutions  in  that  country  for  the  promo- 
tion of  secondary  and  higher  education,  the  monopoly  of  all  military  and 
political  power  by  the  nobility,  the  comparatively  small  dimensions  of 
German  trade  until  quite  recently,  and  other  general  social  circumstances 
which  concur  either  in  drawing  or  driving  the  elite  of  the  middle  and 
lower  classes  in  Germany  into  some  department  of  learning  as  the  most 
accessible  and  promising  sphere  of  ambition,  whereas  in  France  and 
England  the  most  varied  and  powerful  influences  combine  to  attract 
them  elsewhere.  While  the  best  minds  among  the  youth  of  Germany 
are  permanently  gained  to  the  service  of  science  by  being  drawn  into  the 
professoriate  of  its  numerous  .local  and  rival  universities,  similar  minds 
are  in  France  drawn,  as  by  the  suction  of  a  maelstrom,  into  the  vortex 
of  Parisian  society,  and  there  lost  to  learning  through  absorption  in 
financial  speculation,  political  intrigue,  journalistic  ambitions,  and  all  the 
caprices,  aims,  disappointments,  and  successes  of  a  fleeting  and  feverish 
day.  But  the  juristical  school  of  Cujas,  the  philosophical  school  of  Des- 
cartes, the  French  Benedictines,  the  French  mathematicians  and  physi- 
cists who  adorned  with  such  profusion  the  earlier  part  of  the  present 
century;  and,  in  a  word,  persons  and  works  without  number,  have  con- 
clusively proved  that  Frenchmen  are  not  necessarily,  or  in  virtue  of  any 
essential  characteristics  of  their  nature,  either  less  profound  or  less  in- 
dustrious, less  original  or  less  persevering,  than  Germans.  Similarly, 
there  is  no  conclusive  evidence  that  the  English  genius  is  in  itself  either 
less  scientific  and  philosophical  or  more  worldly-wise  and  practical  than 
the  German. 

Had  M.  Jouffroy  lived  to  the  present  day,  it  is  most  improbable  that  he 
would  repeat  either  that  civil  wars  were  ended,  or  that  the  wars  of  the 
peoples  were  about  to  cease.  We,  who  have  so  recently  seen  civil  war  in 
America,  France,  and  Spain,  will  not  venture  to  say  it  may  not  be  seen 
again  even  in  England  or  Germany.  And  the  peoples  are  arming  and 
preparing  for  war  in  a  way  which  can  scarcely  fail  to  be  followed  by  an 
enormous  effusion  of  human  blood. 


490  philosophy  op  History  in  feancb 


III 


The  eclectic  philosophy  had  its  counterpart,  or  rather  com- 
plement, in  doctrinaire  politics.  What  the  one  was  in  specu- 
lation, the  other  was  in  action.  The  former,  regarding  all 
antecedent  philosophies,  sensualistic,  idealistic,  sceptical,  and 
mystical,  as  composed  of  truth  and  error,  as  never  wholly 
false  but  only  incomplete,  sought  to  separate  what  was  true 
in  each  from  what  was  false,  and  so  to  combine  the  truths 
thus  obtained  as  to  produce  a  complete  philosophy,  a  com- 
plete expression  of  consciousness  and  reality.  The  latter, 
in  precisely  the  same  way,  treated  all  antecedent  political 
theories,  monarchical,  aristocratical,  and  democratical,  as 
right  in  themselves,  but  wrong  in  relation  to  other  theories, 
—  wrong  in  their  exclusiveness  ;  and  attempted,  by  selec- 
tion, by  compromise,  and  by  combination,  to  do  justice  to 
all  the  forces  of  society,  and  to  secure  their  complete  rep- 
resentation and  their  harmonious  development.  They  may 
thus  be  almost  considered  as  the  two  sides  of  one  system, 
or  as  different  applications  of  the  same  principles.  But  as 
philosophy  and  politics,  however  closely  connected,  remain 
always  very  distinct  departments  of  activity,  and  require 
very  distinct  and  special  talents  for  their  successful  culti- 
vation, it  was  only  natural  that  the  chief  representatives 
even  of  the  eclectic  philosophy  and  doctrinaire  politics 
which  flourished  in  France  forty  years  ago,  should  not  have 
been  the  same  persons ;  that  MM.  Cousin  and  Jouffroy  should 
have  attained  eminence  as  philosophers,  and  M.  Guizot  and 
the  Due  de  Broglie  as  politicians. 

Yet  M.  Guizot  was  drawn  as  directly  and  strongly  to  his- 
torical research  and  meditation  by  his  political  convictions 
and  sentiments  as  M.  Cousin  by  his  philosophical  principles 
and  aims.  He  felt  himself  compelled  to  seek  in  the  past  a 
vindication  of  the  legitimacy  of  the  various  forces  which  had 
ruled  society,  and  a  proof  of  the  various  articles  of  the  politi- 
cal creed  which  he  believed  ought  to  regulate  the  conduct  of 
statesmen  in  the  present  and  future ;  just  as  M.  Cousin  felt 


GUIZOT  491 

himself  compelled,  to  seek  in  it  the  truths  contained  in  pre- 
vious philosophies,  in  order  to  compose  a  philosophy  which 
would  he  final  because  complete.  The  result  was  in  both 
cases  most  favourable  to  historical  inquiry  and  speculation. 
Indeed,  eclecticism  did  more  for  the  history  of  philosophy  than 
for  philosophy  itself,  and  doctrinairism  more  for  political  his- 
tory than  for  political  science.  As  the  philosophical  spec- 
ulations of  M.  Cousin,  although  brilliant,  are  wanting  in 
thoroughness  and  logical  severity,  so  the  political  disquisi- 
tions of  M.  Guizot,  notwithstanding  their  elevation  of  tone 
and  breadth  of  thought,  are  almost  always  somewhat  super- 
ficial. M.  Cousin  and  M.  Guizot  both  showed  great  skill  in 
constructing  a  symmetrical  and  elegant  system,  the  one  of 
philosophy  and  the  other  of  policy,  and  both  failed  to  rest 
their  systems  firmly  on  sure  foundations.  Hence  the  eclec- 
ticism of  the  one  and  the  doctrinairism  of  the  other  have 
suffered  change  and  loss.  The  impulse,  however,  which 
they  gave  to  historical  study  still  operates.  In  this  con- 
nection no  fair  judge  will  deny  them  the  heartiest  gratitude 
and  admiration. 

The  story  of  the  life  of  Francis  Guizot  (1787-1874)  is 
known  to  all  educated  men,  for  he  lived  long  full  in  the 
world's  eye,  was  not  sparing  of  personal  explanations  and 
reminiscences,  and  had  his  character,  words,  and  actions 
closely  scrutinised  from  many  points  of  view.  His  name 
recalls  to  us  a  most  distinguished  and  influential  career,  a 
varied  and  indefatigable  activity,  important  political  services 
rendered  when  in  opposition,  great  political  ability  displayed 
when  in  power,  dignity  and  fortitude  in  the  bearing  of  ad- 
versity, brilliant  oratorical  achievements,  numerous  literary 
works,  some  of  which  are  of  high  intrinsic  value,  while  all 
are  admirable  in  aim,  and  the  most  rigid  probity  and  pro- 
priety of  personal  conduct.  It  recalls  also,  unfortunately, 
other  things  and  qualities  —  lamentable  mistakes,  serious 
inconsistencies,  faults  which  were  almost  crimes.  He  was  a 
man  of  powerful  intellect,  imperious  will,  pure  and  noble 
sentiments,  strong  and  austere  character ;  but  he  was  de- 
ficient in  practical  political  wisdom  and  tact,  inventiveness 
and  resourcefulness.     After  a  perusal  of  his  '  Memoirs '  the 


492  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

deepest  impression  left  is  one  of  regret  that  a  man  so  largely 
endowed  with  many  of  the  gifts  of  the  statesman  should 
have  been  so  incapable  of  seeing  how  to  apply  the  truths 
which  he  could  expound  so  well,  and  to  distinguish  what 
was  comparatively  insignificant  in  affairs  from  what  was 
vital.  Here,  however,  we  only  require  to  treat  of  him  in 
that  capacity  in  which  he  won  his  purest  and  highest  dis- 
tinctions, —  in  his  character  of  philosophical  historian.1 

All  the  best  qualities  of  M.  Guizot's  mind  are  seen  to  their 
fullest  advantage  in  his  historical  works,  —  accuracy  in  inves- 
tigation, thoroughness  of  scholarship,  a  laboriousness  which 
leaves  nothing  necessary  undone,  comprehensiveness  of  view 
and  moderation  of  judgment,  insight  into  political  causation, 
elevation  of  moral  sentiment,  religious  reverence  and  con- 
viction. He  is  not,  however,  strictly  speaking,  a  great 
historian.  He  wants  the  narrative  and  descriptive  power, 
the  pictorial  and  dramatic  imagination,  the  interest  for  what 
is  individual  in  characters  or  actions,  without  which  no  man 
can  be  a  great  historical  artist..  He  is,  however,  what  is 
still  rarer  and  not  less  important,  a  great  historical  thinker 
or  philosopher. 

Perhaps  we  cannot  fix  more  precisely  what  he  is  and  what 
he  is  not,  than  by  availing  ourselves  of  the  distinctions 
which  he  has  himself  drawn  in  the  admirable  estimate  of 
Savigny's  '  History  of  the  Roman  Law  in  the  Middle  Ages,' 
given  in  the  eleventh  lecture  of  the  '  Cours  de  1829 ' :  — 


"  Every  epoch,  every  historical  matter,  may,  so  to  speak,  be  considered 
in  three  different  aspects,  and  imposes  on  the  historian  a  threefold  task. 
He  can  —  nay,  ought  —  first  seek  the  facts  themselves,  collecting  and 
bringing  to  light,  without  any  other  aim  than  exactitude,  all  that  has 
happened.  The  facts  once  recovered,  it  is  necessary  to  know  what  laws 
have  governed  them ;  how  they  were  connected ;  what  causes  have 
brought  about  those  incidents  which  are  the  life  of  society,  and  which 
propel  it  in  certain  paths  towards  certain  ends.  I  wish  to  mark  clearly 
and  precisely  the  difference  of  the  two  studies.  Facts,  distinctively  so 
called,  outward  and  visible  events,  are  the  body  of  history — the  mem- 

1  He  has  been  studied  in  this  aspect  by  Mr.  J.  S.  Mill,  '  Discussions,'  vol.  i. ;  by 
Sir  Archibald  Alison,  '  Essays,'  vol.  iii. ;  by  M.  Renouvier,  '  La  Critique  Pbilo- 
sophique,'  torn.  i.  and  iii. ;  and  by  Perraz. 


GTJIZOT  493 

bers,  bones,  muscles,  organs,  material  elements  of  the  past;  and  the 
knowledge  and  description  of  them  form  what  may  be  called  historical 
anatomy.  But  for  society,  as  for  the  individual,  anatomy  is  not  the  only 
science.  Facts  not  only  exist,  but  are  connected  with  one  another  ;  they 
succeed  one  another  and  are  engendered  by  the  action  of  certain  forces, 
which  operate  under  the  empire  of  certain  laws.  There  is,  in  a  word,  an 
organisation  and  life  of  societies  as  well  as  of  individuals.  This  organi- 
sation has  also  its  science,  the  science  of  the  secret  laws  which  preside 
over  the  course  of  events.  This  is  the  physiology  of  history.  But  neither 
historical  physiology  nor  anatomy  is  complete  and  veritable  history. 
You  have  enumerated  the  facts  and  traced  the  internal  and  general  laws 
which  produced  them.  Do  you  also  know  their  external  and  living 
physiognomy  f  Have  you  before  your  eyes  their  individual  and  animate 
features?  This  is  absolutely  necessary,  because  these  facts,  now  dead, 
once  lived  —  the  past  has  been  the  present ;  and  unless  it  again  become  so 
to  you,  if  the  dead  be  not  resuscitated,  you  know  it  not — you  know  not 
history.  Could  the  anatomist  and  physiologist  guess  what  man  was  if 
they  had  never  seen  him  alive  ?  The  investigation  of  facts,  the  study  of 
their  organisation,  the  reproduction  of  their  form  and  motion,  these  con- 
stitute what  is  truly  history.  And  every  great  historical  work,  in  order 
to  be  assigned  its  true  position,  should  be  examined  and  judged  of  in 
these  relations." 


When  we  examine  the  historical  labours  of  M.  Guizot 
himself  from  these  three  points  of  view,  we  find  that  he  is 
certainly  not  seen  to  great  advantage  under  the  third.  If 
we  wish  to  know  the  external  and  living  physiognomy  of 
Merovingian  and  Carlovingian  France  —  to  have  a  truthful 
transcript  of  the  individual  features  and  incidents  of  medieval 
life  —  we  must  turn  not  to  his  pages  but  to  those  of 
M.  Augustin  Thierry  or  M.  Michelet.  As  a  work  of  art,  his 
'  History  of  the  English  Revolution '  is  certainly  cold  and 
colourless  if  compared  with  what  Mr.  Carlyle  has  written  on 
the  same  theme.  With  a  correct  and  dignified  style,  with  an 
eloquence  which  never  fails  and  sometimes  rises  high,  he  yet 
shows  comparatively  little  of  the  power  which  reproduces 
the  form  and  motion  of  history,  its  local  hues,  its  poetical 
truth,  its  dramatic  aspects,  the  feelings  of  the  hour,  the 
peculiarities  of  individuals.  It  is  altogether  different  in  the 
other  two  relations.  M.  Guizot  is  very  great  as  an  historical 
anatomist,  and  still  greater  as  an  historical  physiologist.  He 
may  not,  indeed,  in  the   former  respect,  rank  as  high  as  a 


494  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

Savigny,  but  the  reason  obviously  is  not  inferiority  of  ability, 
but  merely  want  of  the  time  and  leisure  which  the  Berlin 
professor  enjoyed.  He  gives  ample  evidence  of  possessing  in 
a  most  eminent  degree  all  the  faculties  which  are  called  into 
action  in  the  ascertainment,  criticism,  distribution,  and  com- 
parison of  facts.  Then,  no  one  will  say  of  him  what  he 
justly  says  of  Savigny  —  viz.,  that  he  overlooked  the  internal 
concatenation  of  facts,  the  organisation  and  laws  of  the  social 
movement.  It  is  in  laying  bare  that  concatenation  and  the 
motive  forces  of  the  social  organism  that  his  merits  are  most 
conspicuous.  He  shows  a  singular  faculty  for  apprehending 
the  ideas  which  underlie  facts,  the  inner  changes  which 
determine  outer  changes,  for  detecting  the  social  and  intel- 
lectual tendencies  of  an  epoch,  for  tracing  the  operation  of 
the  larger  and  more  lasting  causes  which  chiefly  influence 
human  affairs,  and  yet  which  escape  the  ordinary  historian's 
vision.  In  a  word,  he  has  not  been  surpassed  as  an  historical 
physiologist,  as  a  student  of  the  general  and  progressive 
organisation  of  social  facts. 

The  fame  of  M.  Guizot  as  a  philosophical  historian  rests 
chiefly  on  his  '  Histoire  gdne*rale  de  la  civilisation  en  Europe,' 
and  '  Histoire  de  la  civilisation  en  France,'  which  consist  of 
lectures  delivered  at  the  Sorbonne  in  the  years  1828, 1829, 
and  1830.  The  'Essais  sur  l'histoire  de  France'  (1st  ed. 
1823 ;  5th  ed.  1841)  is  the  substance  of  discourses  delivered 
at  an  earlier  period,  and  contains  little  which  may  not  he 
found  in  a  more  elaborate  form  in  those  two  works.  Indeed, 
four  of  the  six  essays  which  it  contains  —  viz.,  those  on 
"The  Origin  and  Establishment  of  the  Franks  in  Gaul," 
"  The  Causes  of  the  Fall  of  the  Merovingians  and  Carlovin- 
gians,"  "  The  Social  State  and  Political  Institutions  of  France 
under  the  Merovingians  and  Carlovingians,"  and  "  The  Politi- 
cal Character  of  the  Feudal  Rigime  "  —  are  simply  the  first 
drafts,  as  it  were,  of  the  views  which  he  afterwards  expounded 
more  perfectly  in  the  Lecons. 

The  remaining  two  —  the  first  and  last  essays  in  the  volume 
—  contain  a  little  more  of  distinctive  matter.  In  the  former, 
"  Concerning  Municipal  Government  in  the  Roman  Empire 
during  the  fifth  century  of  the  Christian  Era,"  M.  Guizot 


guizot  495 

discusses  a  great  problem  which  he  has  only  touched  on  else- 
where, and  which,  as  the  translator  and  annotator  of  Gibbon's 
immortal  work,  he  was  specially  prepared  successfully  to 
discuss.  The  problem  was  to  explain  the  fall  of  the  Roman 
empire.  It  had  already  occupied  the  minds  of  many  thinkers, 
including  a  Montesquieu  and  Gibbon,  and  yet  it  received 
for  the  first  time  perhaps  even  an  approximate  solution  from 
M.  Guizot.  His  predecessors  had  merely  treated  of  the 
general  causes  of  Roman  decadence  in  a  general  way,  and 
had  therefore  merely  talked  round  and  round  about  the  par- 
ticular problem.  They  had  referred  the  fall  of  the  empire  to 
the  institution  of  slavery,  to  the  despotism  of  the  emperors, 
the  decline  of  religious  faith,  luxury  and  moral  corruption ; 
and  overlooked  that,  although  all  these  things  doubtless  did 
indirectly  contribute  to  the  result,  they  must  have  done  so 
only  indirectly,  since  they  were  in  full  operation  centuries 
before,  when  the  empire  was  in  all  the  glory  of  its  strength. 
When  Rome  fell  she  was  not  more  dependent  on  slave  labour 
than  when,  under  Scipio  and  Caesar,  her  legions  vanquished 
Hannibal  and  conquered  Gaul ;  a  religion  infinitely  superior 
to  any  she  had  ever  had  before,  had  won  for  itself  general 
acceptance ;  and  poverty  prevented  luxury  from  being  nearly 
so  widely  spread  as  in  former  generations  when  the  barbarians 
caused  her  no  fear.  It  was,  accordingly,  a  distinct  and 
decided  step  towards  a  solution,  although  certainly  not  a 
complete  or  exhaustive  solution,  when  M.  Guizot,  leaving 
vague  generalities,  fixed  attention  on  the  circumstance  that 
the  empire  was  an  agglomeration  of  towns  held  together  by 
the  central  sovereign  power,  and  showed  how,  by  tracing 
Roman  legislation  regarding  the  curiales,  —  the  class  which 
managed  municipal  affairs,  and  not  only  paid  all  municipal 
expenses,  but  collected  and  were  responsible  for  the  revenue 
of  the  State  —  the  landed  but  unprivileged  class,  the  middle 
class,  of  Roman  society,  —  they  could  be  proved  to  have 
gradually  sunk  under  their  burdens,  and  at  last  to  have  dis- 
appeared. With  their  extinction  the  central  authority  had 
no  longer  resources ;  the  legions  could  not  be  recruited  with 
Roman  men ;  the  cities  were  unable  to  support  one  another  or 


496  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

defend  themselves  ;  internal  decay  had  ensured  the  success  of 
external  violence. 

The  last  essay  of  the  volume  is  on  "  The  Causes  of  the 
Establishment  of  a  Representative  System  in  England."  It 
describes  and  explains  the  characteristics  which  distinguish 
the  political  development  of  England  from  that  of  France ; 
how  the  history  of  England  antecedent  to  the  Norman  con- 
quest, and  the  circumstances  of  that  conquest,  had  for  result 
an  equality  of  strength  between  royalty,  aristocracy,  and  the 
commons,  unknown  elsewhere;  and  how  the  simultaneous 
unfolding  of  these  different  social  elements  enabled  England 
to  attain  a  government  at  once  orderly  and  free,  earlier  than 
any  Continental  nation,  and  called  forth  that  political  good 
sense,  that  spirit  of  political  compromise,  which  has  long 
been  one  of  her  most  conspicuous  qualities.  Ever  since 
Montesquieu  and  some  of  his  contemporaries  gave  popularity 
to  the  study  of  English  political  institutions,  the  British 
Constitution,  or  at  least  what  was  supposed  to  be  the  British 
Constitution,  has  had  admirers  in  France  anxious  to  see  it 
transplanted  to  their  own  country.  The  possibility  and 
desirableness  of  such  transplantation  were  fundamental 
articles  of  the  doctrinaire  creed  adopted  by  M.  Guizot. 
They  explain  his  predilection  for  the  study  of  English  con- 
stitutional history,  shown  not  only  by  his  elaborate  researches 
regarding  the  English  Revolution,  but  by  his  having  devoted 
early  in  his  political  and  professorial  career  an  entire  course 
of  lectures  to  the  development  of  the  views  contained  in  the 
essay  just  mentioned.  I  refer  to  the  '  Cours  de  1822  sur  les 
origines  et  les  deVeloppements  de  la  constitution  Anglaise,' 
which  was  published  in  1851  as  the  second  volume  of  the 
'  Histoire  des  origines  du  gouvernement  representatif  en 
Europe.'  It  is  a  work  kindred  in  character  and  spirit  to 
Hallam's  'Constitutional  History  of  England,'  although  less 
elaborate.  It  may  very  profitably  be  read  before  Mr. 
Hallam's  work,  and  in  connection  with  it,  as  it  leaves  off 
about  the  period  at  which  the  other  begins. 

The  '  History  of  Civilisation  in  Europe,'  and  the  '  History 
of  Civilisation  in  France,'  are  closely  connected  works ;  indeed 
they  may  be  regarded  as  one  work.     The  former  is,  as  it  were, 


guizot  497 

an  introductory  volume  to  the  five  volumes  of  which  the  lat- 
ter consists.  It  is  a  summary  statement  of  the  positions,  which 
they  elucidate  with  all  the  illustrations,  and  confirm  with  all 
the  proofs,  deemed  essential.  It  is  indispensable  to  any  right 
understanding  of  what  M.  Guizot  has  attempted  and  achieved 
as  an  historical  philosopher,  that  we  apprehend  accurately  the 
relation  of  these  works  to  each  other  ;  and  in  the  first  lecture 
of  the  '  Cours  de  1829  '  he  has  been  carefully  explicit  on  the 
subject. 

What  he  says  is  to  the  following  effect.  In  the  lectures 
delivered  in  1828  he  gave  a  general  view  of  the  history  of 
European  civilisation,  and  promised  to  study  it  in  following 
years  in  detail.  When  he  set  about  attempting,  in  the  lec- 
tures for  1829,  to  fulfil  his  promise,  he  found  he  had  to  choose 
between  two  methods.  He  might  recommence  the  Course  of 
1828,  and  proceed  to  go  over  in  detail  what  had  been  gone 
over  in  almost  breathless  haste.  But  to  that  two  insuperable 
objections  presented  themselves,  —  the  difficulty  of  maintain- 
ing unity  in  a  history  so  extensive,  and  the  difficulty  of  mas- 
tering the  immense  extent  and  variety  of  knowledge  which  it 
required.  He  decides,  therefore,  to  adopt  the  other  method, 
that  of  abandoning  the  investigation  of  the  general  history  of 
European  civilisation  in  all  the  nations  which  have  shared  in 
it,  and  confining  himself  to  the  civilisation  of  one  country, 
while  yet  so  marking  the  differences  between  it  and  other 
countries,  that  it  may  reflect  an  image  of  the  whole  destiny 
of  Europe.  Although  difficult,  it  is  yet  possible  to  acquire 
and  use  the  knowledge  necessary  to  proceed  thus,  and  possi- 
ble also  to  pass  from  fact  to  fact  without  losing  sight  of  the 
whole  picture  —  to  preserve  unity  of  narrative  along  with  an 
adequate  study  of  particulars.  The  important  question  here 
arises,  Which  country  ought  to  be  selected  ?  M.  Guizot  an- 
swers —  France.  Why  ?  Because  France  is  the  country  in 
which  civilisation  has  appeared  in  its  most  complete  form, 
where  it  has  been  most  diffusive  or  communicative,  and 
where  it  has  most  forcibly  struck  the  European  imagination. 
The  superiority  of  French  civilisation  to  that  of  other  coun- 
tries is  shown  not  merely  in  there  being  greater  amenity  in 
social  relations,  greater  gentleness  of  manners,  a  more  easy 


498  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

and  animated  life  in  France  than  elsewhere,  but  still  more 
decisively  by  the  fact  that  there  the  essential  elements  of 
civilisation  —  the  intellectual  and  social  developments  — 
have  progressed  more  equally,  and  at  a  shorter  distance 
from  each  other,  than  elsewhere.  "  In  England  the  devel- 
opment of  society  has  been  more  extensive  and  more  glorious 
than  that  of  humanity ;  social  interests  and  social  facts  have 
there  maintained  a  more  conspicuous  place,  and  exercised 
more  power  than  general  ideas ;  the  nation  seems  greater 
than  the  individual;  its  great  men,  even  its  philosophers, 
belong  to  the  practical  school."  "  In  Germany  the  develop- 
ment of  civilisation  has  been  slow  and  tardy,  and  the  intel- 
lectual development  has  always  surpassed  and  left  behind 
social  development;  the  human  spirit  has  there  been  much 
more  prosperous  than  the  human  condition."  "  In  Italy  civ- 
ilisation has  been  neither  essentially  practical  as  in  England, 
nor  almost  exclusively  speculative  as  in  Germany ;  but  it  has 
been  weighed  down  and  impeded  from  without,  and  the  two 
powers  — speculative  genius  and  practical  ability  —  have  not 
lived  in  reciprocal  confidence,  in  correspondence,  in  continual 
action  and  reaction."  "  In  Spain  neither  great  minds  nor 
great  events  have  been  wanting,  but  they  have  appeared 
isolated  and  scattered  like  palm-trees  in  a  desert."  "In 
France,  on  the  contrary,  alongside  of  great  events,  revolu- 
tions, and  public  progress,  we  always  find  universal  ideas 
and  corresponding  doctrines.  Nothing  has  passed  in  the  real 
world  but  the  understanding  has  immediately  seized  it,  and 
thence  derived  new  riches ;  nothing  has  occurred  within  the 
dominion  of  understanding  which  has  not  had  in  the  real 
world,  and  that  almost  always  immediately,  its  echo  and 
result.  This  twofold  character  of  intellectual  activity  and 
practical  ability,  of  meditation  and  application,  is  shown  in 
all  the  great  events  of  French  history,  and  in  all  the  great 
classes  of  French  society,  and  gives  them  an  aspect  which  we 
do  not  find  elsewhere.  To  France,  therefore,  must  be  ascribed 
the  honour,  that  her  civilisation  has  reproduced  more  faith- 
fully than  any  other  the  general  type  and  fundamental  idea 
of  civilisation." 


guizot  499 

M.  Guizot,  then,  it  will  be  observed,  when  he  found  himself  compelled 
to  study  the  history  of  civilisation  in  one  great  European  nation  instead 
of  in  all,  did  not  abandon  the  idea  with  which  he  started,  that  of  trac- 
ing the  general  history  of  European  civilisation.  He  concentrated  his 
faculties  and  researches  on  France,  but  only  because  he  thought  he 
could  thus  arrive  more  quickly  and  surely  at  the  desired  result.  The 
positions  which  he  sought  to  establish  in  the  volumes  on  the  history  of 
civilisation  in  France,  were  just  those  which  he  had  previously  laid  down 
in  the  volume  on  the  history  of  civilisation  in  Europe.  The  more  elabo- 
rate work  was  meant,  notwithstanding  its  more  special  title,  to  be  really 
as  wide  in  its  scope  as  the  other,  and  to  be,  in  fact,  the  continuation  and 
development  of  the  other. 

But  at  this  point  a  doubt  presents  itself  which  M.  Guizot  has,  perhaps, 
not  satisfactorily  dispelled.  Does  the  civilisation  of  any  one  European 
nation  give  us  the  general  type,  or  image,  or  fundamental  idea  of  Euro- 
pean civilisation  as  such?  Is  the  history,  for  example,  of  France  essen- 
tially the  history  of  Europe?  Can  the  whole  be  discovered  in  any  single 
part,  or  even  in  less  than  all  the  parts?  I  think  M.  Guizot  should  have 
put  these  questions  quite  clearly  and  distinctly  to  himself  —  more  so, 
certainly,  than  he  did  —  and  that  if  he  had  he  would  have  answered  them 
differently.  Had  he  simply  maintained  that,  by  noting  the  differences 
and  resemblances  between  the  civilisation  of  one  European  country  and 
the  others,  a  view  of  the  general  civilisation  of  Europe  could  be  acquired, 
there  would  have  been  no  ground  for  objection.  In  that  case  the  general 
view  would  be  obtained,  not  from  a  particular  civilisation  itself,  but  from 
its  comparison  with,  and  contrast  to,  the  other  particular  civilisations. 
Any  of  the  more  important  countries  of  Europe  might  be  chosen  as  the 
fixed  term  for  this  sort  of  comparison  and  contrast.  Italy,  Germany, 
England,  France,  would  obviously  all  equally  serve  the  purpose  —  the 
truth  and  value  of  the  result  depending,  not  on  which  civilisation  is  made 
the  centre  of  comparison,  but  on  the  accuracy  and  thoroughness  of  the 
process  of  comparison.  But  M.  Guizot  goes  much  further.  He  takes  up 
the  position  that  there  is  a  particular  civilisation  which  answers  to  the 
idea  of  general  civilisation  ;  that  there  is  one  country  in  Europe,  the  civil- 
isation of  which  is  so  much  more  perfect  than  that  of  the  other  countries, 
that  it  may  be  regarded  as  the  normal  form  of  the  civilisation  of  Europe, 
an  approximation  to  the  absolute  standard  of  civilisation,  a  practical 
standard  by  which  to  measure  civilisation  everywhere  else.  Now,  a  grave 
suspicion  is  raised  against  the  legitimacy  of  this  assumption  by  the  fact, 
that  those  who  make  it  differ  widely  as  to  which  nation  is  to  be  deemed 
the  pattern  nation.  Guizot  argues  that  it  must  be  France  ;  but  Gioberti 
writes  a  book  to  prove  that  it  must  be  Italy ;  Hegel,  and  the  Germans  as 
a  body,  quietly  assume  or  confidently  affirm  that  the  whole  of  what  is 
called  Christian  civilisation  may  equally  be  called  Germanic  civilisation ; 
and  Mr.  Buckle  has  no  doubt  that  the  history  of  England  is  that  which 
shows  most  clearly  "  the  normal  march  of  society,  and  the  undisturbed 


500  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

operation  of  those  great  laws  by  which  the  fortunes  of  mankind  are 
ultimately  regulated." 

It  is  not  enough  to  refer  this  variety  of  discordant  decisions  to  the 
operation  of  national  prejudices.  The  question  still  remains,  Why  is  it 
—  how  is  it  —  that  national  prejudices  have  in  this  instance  such  power? 
And  the-  only  satisfactory  answer  to  this  question  is,  —  because  no  par- 
ticular civilisation  is  normal,  or  answers  as  a  whole  to  the  idea  of  civil- 
isation. It  can  only  be  made  to  appear  so  by  narrowing  the  idea  of 
civilisation  to  suit  the  pretensions  put  forth  on  its  behalf.  By  a  similar 
narrowing  of  the  idea,  quite  as  warranted,  another  standard  may  be 
obtained  which  will  be  as  favourable  to  some  other  civilisation.  Grant 
that  in  the  civilisation  of  France  intellectual  activity  and  practical  ability, 
meditation  and  application,  have,  as  M.  Guizot  says,  progressed  more 
equally,  and  at  a  shorter  distance  from  each  other,  than  in  England  — 
and  what  then  ?  Does  it  follow  that  it  reproduces  better  the  general  type 
and  fundamental  idea  of  civilisation  than  the  civilisation  of  England? 
No ;  but  merely  that  it  reproduces  it  better  in  one  respect.  It  may  repro- 
duce it  much  worse  in  some  equally  essential  respect.  And  an  English- 
man looking  at  it  in  that  respect  may  quite  as  fairly  conclude  it  to  be 
inferior  to  English  civilisation,  as  M.  Guizot  has  concluded  it  to  be 
superior. 

This  is  precisely  what  Mr.  Buckle  has  done.  He,  like  M.  Guizot, 
found  himself  compelled,  by  the  magnitude  of  the  task,  to  write  the 
history,  not  of  general  civilisation,  but  of  the  civilisation  of  a  single 
people ;  and  he  has  endeavoured,  still  more  elaborately  than  M.  Guizot,  to 
show  that  he  could  realise  the  larger  design  within  the  narrower  compass.1 
He  fixes,  however,  on  England  as  the  nation  which  has  approached 
nearest  to  a  complete  and  perfect  pattern,  chiefly  on  the  ground  that,  "of 
all  European  countries,  England  is  the  one  where,  during  the  longest 
period,  the  government  has  been  most  quiescent,  and  the  people  most 
active;  where  popular  freedom  has  been  settled  on  the  widest  basis; 
where  each  man  is  most  able  to  say  what  he  thinks,  and  to  do  what  he 
likes ;  where  every  one  can  follow  his  own  bent,  and  propagate  his  own 
opinions ;  where,  religious  persecution  being  little  known,  the  play  and 
flow  of  the  human  mind  may  be  clearly  seen,  unchecked  by  those  re- 
straints to  which  it  is  elsewhere  subjected;  where  the  profession  of 
heresy  is  least  dangerous,  and  the  practice  of  dissent  most  common; 
where  hostile  creeds  flourish  side  by  side,  and  rise  and  decay  without 
disturbance,  according  to  the  wants  of  the  people,  unaffected  by  the 
wishes  of  the  Church,  and  uncontrolled  by  the  authority  of  the  State; 
where  all  interests  and  all  classes,  both  spiritual  and  temporal,  are  most 
left  to  take  care  of  themselves ;  where  that  meddlesome  doctrine  called 
Protection  was  first  attacked,  and  where  alone  it  has  been  destroyed; 
and  where,  in  a  word,  those  dangerous  extremes  to  which  interference 

i  Hist,  of  Civilisation  in  England,  i.  209-221,  1st  ed. 


GUIZOT  501 

gives  rise  having  been  avoided,  despotism  and  rebellion  are  equally  rare, 
and  concession  being  recognised  as  the  groundwork  of  policy,  the  national 
progress  has  been  least  disturbed  by  the  power  of  privileged  classes,  by 
the  influence  of  particular  sects,  or  by  the  violence  of  arbitrary  rulers." 
Now,  the  reason  which  Mr.  Buckle  thus  gives  for  choosing  English  civil- 
isation as  normal,  may  be  no  better  than  M.  Guizot's  for  choosing  French 
civilisation,  but  neither  is  it  worse.  It  presupposes  a  different  standard, 
but  one  quite  as  good.- 

And  this  holds  true  even  if  we  grant  the  accuracy  of  the  objection 
which  M.  Guizot  makes  to  English  civilisation  —  viz.,  that  it  has  been  more 
favourable  to  the  development  of  society  than  of  humanity,  of  the  nation 
than  of  the  individual.  It  is  an  objection,  however,  I  may  remark,  which 
Englishmen  at  least  will  certainly  not  grant,  and  in  which  probably  few 
candid  foreigners  even  will  concur.  "We  in  England  are  generally  under 
the  belief  that  historical  and  social  conditions  have  been  in  no  Conti- 
nental nation  so  favourable  to  the  development  of  individuality  as  here ; 
and,  with  all  due  distrust  of  national  judgments,  as  exceedingly  likely 
indeed  to  be  baseless  prejudices,  I  think  this  is  one  the  truth  of  which 
few  competent  third  parties  will  contest.  I  am  quite  unable  to  see  that 
the  great  men  of  England  have  belonged  more  exclusively  to  the  practical 
school  than  those  of  France.  Its  philosophers  do  not  seem  to  me  to  have 
done  so,  and  I  profess  to  have  studied  most  of  the  philosophers  of  both 
countries. 

I  might  proceed  to  show  that  claims  as  strong  might  be  put  forward 
on  behalf  of  the  civilisation  of  Italy  and  Germany,  as  those  which  Guizot 
has  produced  for  that  of  France,  and  Mr.  Buckle  for  that  of  England. 
Was  not  Italy  from  the  fall  of  the  Roman  Empire  to  the  Reformation,  on 
the  whole,  the  most  civilised  nation  of  Europe,  and  that  which  exerted, 
through  religion,  learning,  art,  industry,  and  commerce,  the  greatest  influ- 
ence on  the  civilisation  of  other  nations  ?  The  time  which  has  elapsed 
since  is  comparatively  short.  While  France  developed  her  civilisation 
along  the  path  of  centralisation,  Germany  seemed  to  retrograde  by  trav- 
elling in  the  opposite  direction  ;  but  does  it  not  remain  to  be  seen  which 
path  is  really  the  best,  and  whether  France,  after  having  apparently 
moved  straight  up  to  the  goal,  may  not  have  to  retrace  her  steps  and 
come  back  by  another  way  before  she  can  truly  reach  it  ?  That  Germany 
has  gone  round  about  and  France  straight  forward,  by  no  means  of  itself 
proves  that  the  French  course  has  been  the  better  one,  and  still  less  that 
it  is  the  only  right  one.  A  straight  line  is  in  practice  often  the  greatest 
distance  between  two  points.  I  deem,  then,  the  claims  made  on  behalf 
of  various  civilisations  to  be  regarded  as  the  exclusive  representatives  of 
general  civilisation  no  less  inadequate  and  illusory  than  they  are  invid- 
ious. If  true  in  what  they  affirm,  they  are  false  in  what  they  deny. 
Alike  in  France,  Germany,  England,  and  Italy,  civilisation  has  had  a 
special  and  one-sided,  not  a  general  and  normal  development.  It  cannot 
be  fairly  judged  of  in  any  one  of  them  by  what  it  is  in  any  other.     If 


502  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

we  would  know  the  general  type  of  civilisation  we  must  study  all  the 
specimens  of  civilisation,  and  especially  all  its  chief  specimens.  A  part 
can  never  be  the  whole. 


The  first  three  lectures  of  the  Course  of  1828  —  that  on 
"The  General  History  of  Civilisation  in  Europe"  —  contain 
the  preliminary-observations  which  M.  Guizot  deemed  neces- 
sary. They  are  a  statement  of  views  and  principles  essential 
to  a  right  understanding  of  his  labours  in  the  department  of 
historical  philosophy.  He  begins  in  the  most  natural  manner 
—  viz.,  with  an  attempt  to  fix  the  meaning  of  the  terms 
"European  civilisation."  That  is  his  subject.  It  presents  a 
very  wide  field  for  research,  beyond  which  he  has  not  attempted 
to  range.  He  has  never  sought  to  construct  a  philosophy  of  his- 
tory — ■  he  has  never  professed  to  have  discovered  a  universal 
law  of  history ;  he  has  attempted  only  to  analyse  the  civilisa- 
tion of  Christian  Europe  into  its  elements,  and  to  trace  the 
causes  and  stages  of  its  development.  In  this  reference  noth- 
ing can  be  more  accurate  or  succinct  than  the  words  of  Mr.  Mill : 
"  His  subject  is  not  history  at  large,  but  modern  European  his- 
tory ;  the  formation  and  progress  of  the  existing  nations  of  Eu- 
rope. Embracing,  therefore,  only  a  part  of  the  succession  of 
historical  events,  he  is  precluded  from  attempting  to  determine 
the  law  or  laws  which  preside  over  the  entire  evolution.  If 
there  be  such  laws — if  the  series  of  states  through  which 
human  nature  and  society  are  destined  to  pass,  have  been  deter- 
mined more  or  less  precisely  by  the  original  constitution  of 
mankind,  and  by  the  circumstances  of  the  planet  on  which  we 
live  —  the  order  of  their  succession  cannot  be  discovered  by 
modern  or  by  European  experience  alone ;  it  must  be  ascer- 
tained by  a  conjunct  analysis,  so  far  as  possible,  of  the  whole 
of  history,  and  the  whole  of  human  nature.  M.  Guizot  stops 
short  of  this  ambitious  enterprise ;  but,  considered  as  prepara- 
tory studies  for  promoting  and  facilitating  it,  his  writings  are 
most  valuable.  He  seeks,  not  the  ultimate,  but  the  proximate, 
causes  of  the  facts  of  modern  history;  he  inquires  in  what 
manner  each  successive  condition  of  modern  Europe  grew  out 
of  that  which  next  preceded  it;  and  how  modern  society- 
altogether,  and  the  modern  mind,  shaped  themselves  from 


GUIZOT  503 

the  elements  which  had  been  transmitted  to  them  from  the 
ancient  world."  1 

M.  Guizot  uses  these  terms  "  European  civilisation,"  he 
says,  because  it  is  evident  that  there  is  a  European  civilisation  ; 
that  a  certain  unity  pervades  the  civilisation  of  the  various 
European  states  ;  that,  notwithstanding  infinite  diversities  of 
time,  place,  and  circumstance,  this  civilisation  takes  its  first 
rise  in  facts  almost  wholly  similar,  proceeds  everywhere  upon 
the  same  principles,  and  tends  to  produce  almost  everywhere 
analogous  results.  He  insists  that  civilisation  is  as  really  a 
fact  as  any  material  and  visible  individual  event;  a  general, 
hidden,  complex  fact,  difficult  to  describe,  difficult  to  trace 
the  progress  or  history  of,  but  which  none  the  less  exists,  with 
a  right  to  be  described  and  to  have  its  history  written.  What, 
then,  he  asks,  is  involved  in  this  complex  fact  which  we  call 
civilisation  ? 

He  answers,  that,  in  the  first  place,  it  involves  progress,  im- 
provement, amelioration ;  but,  in  proof,  he  merely  appeals  to 
"the  natural  good  sense  of  mankind,"  to  "general  instinct." 
As  regards  the  progress  of  which  he  says  that  civilisation  con- 
sists, he  represents  it  as  comprehending  two  facts  or  conditions : 
the  development  of  society,  the  perfecting  of  civil  life,  on  the 
one  hand ;  and  the  development  of  the  individual  or  internal 
life  of  man  himself,  his  faculties,  sentiments,  and  ideas,  on  the 
other  hand.  And  these  two  conditions,  these  two  movements 
—  the  progress  of  society  and  the  progress  of  humanity  —  are, 
he  argues,  so  connected,  that,  sooner  or  later,  whatever  im- 
proves or  degrades  the  internal  man  turns  to  the  profit  or  hurt 
of  society,  and  whatever  affects  the  development  of  society 
similarly  affects  the  individual.  The  progress  of  humanity  is 
the  end ;  that  of  society  the  means. 


It  has  been  said  that  M.  Guizot  forgets  this  distinction  in  practice,  and 
studies  exclusively  the  progress  of  society.  Those  who  have  urged  the 
charge,  however,  have  overlooked  the  Course  of  1829,  which  is  the 
only  complete  course  of  the  three,  and  in  which  there  is  a  care- 
ful examination,  not  merely  of  the  political  but  of  the  intellectual 
state    of    Europe    during    the    period  of    which    it   treats ;    and  that 

1  Dissertations  and  Discussions,  ii.  223-4. 


504  PHILOSOPHY   OF   flISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

the  lectures  of  1828  and  1830  did  not  embrace  more  than  polit- 
ical and  social  development,  simply  because  the  Courses  of  these 
years  were  unfinished, — the  former  having  been  begun  late,  and  the 
latter  prematurely  broken  off  in  consequence  of  political  events. 

More  might  be  said  for  an  attack  on  the  distinction  itself. 
Humanity  —  internal  life  —  intellectual  development,  are  hardly  synony- 
mous expressions,  and  they  are  neither  logical  antitheses  nor  co-or- 
dinates to  society  —  civil  life  —  political  development.  But  it  must 
be  considered  that  a  logically  satisfactory  division  is  here  scarcely 
possible,  and  that  whatever  faults  that  of  M.  Guizot  may  have  had, 
it  was  not  only  much  better  than  none,  but  very  tolerably  served  his 
purpose. 

The  appeal  to  "natural  good  sense"  or  "general  instinct"  for 
proof  of  civilisation  implying  progress  is  plainly  illegitimate.  They 
have  no  right  to  pronounce  civilisation  to  be  progress,  or  even  progress 
to  be  an  essential  and  universal  characteristic  of  civilisation.  The 
truth  or  falsity  of  these  propositions  must  be  determined  by  facts; 
and  the  facts  happen  to  establish  that  both  are  false.  A  very  large 
part  of  the  civilisation  of  the  world  is  stationary  or  declining.  Pro- 
gressive civilisation  is  probably  not  the  rule  but  the  exception.  It  is 
only  progressive  civilisation  which  involves  the  notion  of  progress. 
But  although  progress  is  not  essentially  implied  in  the  idea  of  civ- 
ilisation, the  opinion  of  Guizot  to  the  contrary  exerts  no  evil  influence 
on  the  course  of  his  speculations,  seeing  that  European  civilisation, 
the  real  subject  of  his  studies,  is,  viewed  as  a  whole,  undoubtedly 
progressive. 

He  shows  in  the  second  lecture  that  modern  civilisation  is 
distinguished  from  ancient  civilisation  by  being  much  less  sim- 
ple, much  more  diversified  and  complicated,  by  the  continued 
■coexistence,  conflict,  and  co-operation  of  a  vast  variety  of  powers 
and  interests  which  in  the  ancient  world  were  found  apart. 
He  insists  that  this  in  great  part  accounts  for  its  superiority. 
And  he  explains  it  by  the  great  diversity  of  the  elements  from 
which,  and  of  the  circumstances  under  which,  modern  society 
was  formed.  When  Rome  fell,  she  left  behind  her  the  muni- 
cipal system,  the  idea  of  imperial  majesty,  and  a  body  of 
written  law ;  nor  did  she  drag  down  with  her  the  Christian 
Church,  an  organisation  resting  on  religious  doctrines  and 
convictions,  and  possessed  of  a  regular  government  and  defi- 
nite aims.  Alongside  of  the  Church  was  the  barbaric  inva- 
sion, animated  by  a  spirit  of  personal  liberty  and  of  voluntary 
association  previously  unknown.     Thus,  at  the  beginning  of 


GUIZOT  505 

modern  civilisation,  there  were  almost  all  the  elements  which 
have  united  in  its  progressive  development;  three  societies 
—  the  municipal,  a  legacy  of  the  Roman  Empire,  the  Chris- 
tian, and  the  Barbaric  society  —  very  variously  organised, 
founded  upon  wholly  different  principles,  and  inspiring  men 
with  wholly  different  sentiments.  "We  find  the  craving 
after  the  most  absolute  independence  side  by  side  with  the 
most  complete  submission ;  military  patronage  side  by  side 
with  ecclesiastical  dominion;  the  spiritual  and  temporal 
powers  everywhere  present;  the  canons  of  the  Church,  the 
learned  legislation  of  the  Romans,  the  almost  unwritten  cus- 
toms of  the  barbarians;  everywhere  the  mixture,  or  rather 
the  coexistence  of  the  most  diverse  races,  languages,  social 
situations,  manners,  ideas,  and  impressions."  This  lecture 
has  justly  been  the  object  of  special  admiration.  The  theory 
it  contains  is  not  only  indubitably  true  as  a  whole,  but  highly 
important  and  beautifully  expounded. 

M.  Guizot  proceeds  in  the  third  lecture  to  point  out  that 
although  the  facts  are  as  he  has  stated,  an  opinion  directly  to 
the  contrary  prevails,  and  each  element,  each  system,  has  put 
forth  a  claim  to  have  alone  ruled  society.  "  A  school  of  feu- 
dal publicists,  represented  by  M.  de  Boulanvilliers,  pretends 
that  after  the  fall  of  the  Roman  Empire,  the  conquering 
nation,  afterwards  become  the  nobility,  possessed  all  powers 
and  rights,  which  they  have  lost  only  through  the  usurpation 
of  kings  and  peoples ;  a  school  of  monarchists,  represented  by 
the  Abbe*  Dubos,  maintains,  on  the  other  hand,  that  all  the 
acquisitions  of  the  nobility  have  been  unjustly  wrung  from 
the  German  kings,  who,  as  the  heirs  of  the  Roman  emperors, 
alone  ruled  legitimately ;  a  democratic  school,  represented  b}r 
the  Abbe"  de  Mably,  argues  that  nobles  and  kings  have  only 
risen  to  power  on  the  ruins  of  popular  freedom,  and  that  the 
government  of  society  primitively  belonged  to,  and  still  prop- 
erly belongs  to,  the  people ;  while  above  all  these  monarchi- 
cal, aristocratical,  and  popular  pretensions,  rises  theocratical 
pretension,  the  claim  of  the  Church  to  rule  society  in  virtue 
of  her  divine  title  and  mission."  This  leads  our  author  to 
insist  first  on  what  he  calls  the  idea  of  political  legitimacy. 
All  powers  claim  to  be  legitimate.     They  all  refuse  to  admit 


506  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FKANOE 

themselves  founded  on  force.  They  all  thereby  profess  to 
rest  on  right,  justice,  reason.  And  this  is  why  they  also 
claim  long  duration,  a  high  antiquity;  for  the  mere  fact  that 
a  power  has  long  existed  is  itself  a  ground  for  believing  that 
reason  and  right  have  in  some  measure  belonged  to  it.  "  From 
the  mere  fact  of  its  enduring,  we  may  conclude  with  certainty 
that  a  society  is  not  completely  absurd,  insensate,  or  iniqui- 
tous —  that  it  is  not  utterly  destitute  of  those  elements  of  rea- 
son, truth,  and  justice  which  alone  can  give  life  to  society. 
If,  further,  the  society  develops  itself  —  if  its  principle  grows 
in  strength  and  is  daily  accepted  by  a  greater  number  of  men 
—  that  convincingly  proves  that  in  the  lapse  of  time  there 
has  been  progressively  introduced  into  it  more  reason,  jus- 
tice, and  right.  It  is  this  introduction  of  right  and  truth 
into  the  social  state  which  has  given  rise  to  the  idea  of  poli- 
tical legitimacy;  it  is  thus  that  it  has  been  established  in 
modern  civilisation." 

M.  Guizot  is  here  —  what  he  very  rarely  is  —  obscure;  the  reason 
of  which  no  doubt  is,  the  mysterious  nature  of  the  subject,  the  inscrut- 
able profundity  of  the  idea  of  political  legitimacy.  It  is  only  in  the 
dark  that  such  a  spectre  of  a  thought  can  show  itself.  The  light  causes 
it  to  vanish  —  makes  apparent  its  nonentity.  It  pretends  to  be  a  some- 
thing—a right  to  authority  —  a  claim  to  obedience;  but  the  slightest 
criticism,  the  slightest  explanation  even,  shows  it  to  be  in  and  of  itself 
absolutely  nothing.  The  right  of  any  power  to  rule  in  society  depends 
solely  on  the  truth  and  justice  of  the  reasons  on  which  the  right  is 
rested ;  legitimacy  is  a  word  which  may  be  allowably  used  to  express  a 
conviction  that  these  reasons  are  in  a  given  instance  satisfactory,  but 
not  to  denote  a  reason  in  itself,  nor  anything  apart  from  the  reasons, 
anything-  added  to  or  developed  out  of  the  reasons.  Of  course,  if  this 
were  admitted,  there  would  be  an  end  of  what  is  spoken  of  as  political 
legitimacy  in  France. 

A  French  legitimist  is  a  man  who  argues  that  the  claims  of  his 
party  to  rule  are  good  because  of  legitimacy,  not  that  they  are  legiti- 
mate exclusively  because,  and  only  in  so  far  as,  they  are  good.  Legiti- 
macy is  a  fiction  which  he  interposes  between  his  own  mind  or  the 
public  mind  and  reasons  which  he  half-consciously  suspects  to  be  an 
insufficient  basis  for  his  theory ;  a  fiction  which  serves  to  conceal  their 
insufficiency  from  himself  and  others.  It  is  curious  to  see  a  mind  like 
that  of  M.  Guizot  under  the  sway  of  so  poor  an  idol ;  curious  to  see  how, 
instead  of  "casting  it  to  the  moles  and  bats,"  he  decks  and  dresses  it  up 
anew  for  public  homage.     To  M.  de  Boulanvilliers,  feudalist ;  the  Abbe' 


GUIZOT  507 

Dubos,  monarchist ;  the  Abbe  de  Mably,  democrat ;  and  the  Comte  de 
Maistre,  defender  of  the  theocracy,  he  virtually  says,  —  "I  admit  all  your 
claims ;  you  are  all  right  in  what  you  affirm,  and  wrong  only  in  what  you 
deny  — the  powers  which  you  severally  defend  are  all  legitimate:  and  my 
system,  which  comprehends  and  harmonises  them  all,  is  consequently  pre- 
eminently legitimate.  It  is  a  great  word  —  a  great  idea  —  legitimacy." 
And  there  is  a  certain  impartiality  and  comprehensiveness  in  the  answer 
which  makes  it  attractive  and  plausible.  Yet  none  the  less  is  it  erroneous 
and  ensnaring.  The  cobweb  may  not  be  so  perceptible  when  thus  drawn 
out  wider  and  thinner,  but  that  is  all,  —  it  is  still  there.  The  truth  in 
this  case  is  not  to  be  found  in  a  general  affirmation,  but  in  a  general  nega- 
tion. The  claims  which  different  parties  have  made  under  the  name  of 
legitimacy  have  not  had  their  source  in  the  facts  and  reasons  which  truly 
entitle  these  parties  to  a  certain  measure  of  authority;  but  in  the  insuffi- 
ciency of  their  facts  and  reasons  as  a  title  to  all  the  authority  which  they  desire 
to  exercise.  Instead,  therefore,  of  all  the  claims  being  granted,  all  ought 
to  be  repelled  and  this  truth  affirmed  —  that  no  power  has  any  other 
legitimacy  than  its  reasonableness  and  its  utility.  This,  besides  being 
a  truth,  will  be  found  at  least  as  impartial  and  comprehensive  a  conclu- 
sion as  M.  Guizot's. 

He  next  maintains  that  "  the  very  dispute  which  has  arisen 
between  the  various  systems  that  have  a  share  in  European 
civilisation  upon  the  question  which  predominated  at  its  ori- 
gin, proves  that  then  they  all  coexisted,  without  any  one  of 
them  prevailing  generally  enough,  or  certainly  enough,  to 
give  to  society  its  form  and  its  name."  He  points  out  that 
this  was  precisely  the  characteristic  of  the  barbarian  epoch. 
"It  was  the  chaos  of  all  elements,  the  infancy  of  all  systems, 
a  universal  turmoil,  in  which  even  strife  was  not  systematic." 
The  work  of  the  centuries  which  have  since  elapsed  has  been 
to  effect  in  some  measure  the  reconciliation  of  these  elements, 
the  amalgamation  of  these  systems,  and  to  bring  order  and 
peace,  with  their  products,  out  of  this  chaos  and  turmoil. 
And  the  task  which  M.  Guizot  proposed  to  himself  was  to 
trace  the  progress  of  the  work  of  the  centuries. 

Other  labours  —  other  duties  —  prevented  the  complete 
performance  of  what  he  intended ;  but  he  accomplished  suffi- 
cient to  show  both  the  excellence  of  his  method  of  operation 
and  the  superiority  of  his  intellect.  The  history  of  Europe 
from  the  fall  of  the  Roman  Empire  is  divided  into  three 
periods:  the  period  of  confusion,  the  feudal  period,  and  the 


508  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

modern  period.  The  outlines  of  the  development  of  civilisa- 
tion during  these  three  periods  were  twice  drawn  by  M.  Gui- 
zot,  first  in  the  'Essais'  and  next  in  the  'Cours  de  1828. '  But 
he  rightly  felt  that  outlines  were  not  enough  —  that  what 
was  above  all  needed  was  a  thorough,  a  detailed,  an  exhaus- 
tive analysis  of  civilisation.  In  the  '  Cours  de  1829 '  he 
undertook  and  accomplished  such  an  analysis  of  civilisation, 
so  far  as  it  was  represented  by  the  civilisation  of  France,  for 
the  period  of  confusion  —  for  the  five  centuries  between  Clovis 
and  the  end  of  the  Carlovingian  dynasty.  In  the  following 
year  he  entered  on  the  analysis  of  the  feudal  period ;  and  was 
carrying  it  forward  on  the  same  comprehensive  scale,  and 
with  an  ability  and  success  no  less  remarkable,  when  his 
Course  was  abruptly  terminated  before  it  was  half  finished  — 
before  the  speculative,  religious,  and  literary  characteristics 
of  the  period  had  been  brought  under  review.  Beyond  that 
point  the  work,  unfortunately,  never  got.  The  last  or  strictly 
modern  period  of  European,  or  even  French  history,  was  never 
taken  up  at  all.  Thus  the  Course  of  1829  is  the  only  one  in 
which  the  method  of  M.  Guizot  is  seen  fully  exemplified;  in 
which  a  period  of  civilisation  is  analysed  with  the  thorough- 
ness and  exhaustiveness  which  he  deemed  essential.  It  is 
especially  in  it  that  his  historical  philosophy  is  to  be  seen  in 
operation.     Let  us  recall  what  he  does  there. 

After  the  preliminary  lecture  to  which  I  have  already  had 
occasion  to  refer,  he  describes  the  social  and  intellectual,  the 
civil  and  religious,  state  of  society  in  Gaul  prior  to  the  Ger- 
man invasion,  at  the  end  of  the  fourth  and  the  beginning  of 
the  fifth  century  (L.  2-6);  then  the  dispositions,  the  manners, 
and  institutions  of  the  Germans  before  they  began  to  take 
possession  of  the  lands  of  the  Celt  and  the  Roman  (7);  and 
next,  the  invasion  and  conquest  itself,  its  character,  the 
changes  it  caused  in  the  distribution  of  society,  its  various 
immediate  consequences  (8).  These  are,  as  it  were,  the  three 
scenes  of  the  first  act  of  the  drama.  After  having  delineated 
them,  our  author  turns  to  trace  through  the  two  follow- 
ing centuries  the  action  and  reaction  of  the  Barbarian  and 
Romanised  societies,  their  progressive  development  and  amal- 
gamation, alike  in  the  civil,  the  religious,  and  the  intellec- 
tual order  of  things.     As  to  the  civil  order,  he  shows  how 


G0IZOT  509 

the  Barbarian  codes  of  law  arose  and  how  the  Roman  law  was 
perpetuated  (9-11).  As  to  the  religious  order,  he  explains 
the  internal  organisation  of  the  Church,  the  varieties  of  grade 
and  function  among  its  regular  and  secular  clergy,  its  rela- 
tions with  civil  society,  its  aims,  its  tendencies,  its  influence 
(12-15).  And,  as  illustrative  of  the  intellectual  life  of  the 
period,  he  analyses  and  describes  its  scanty  literature,  both 
sacred  and  profane  (16-18). 

The  fall  of  the  Merovingian  and  the  rise  of  the  Carloving- 
ian  dynasty  about  the  middle  of  the  eighth  century  intro- 
duced a  third  epoch,  a  third  act.  After  showing  the  nature 
and  causes  of  that  revolution  (19),  M.  Guizot  dwells  upon 
the  position  and  significance  of  the  reign  of  Charlemagne  — 
on  the  character  and  designs  of  that  great  monarch  —  on  his 
influence,  direct  and  indirect,  on  outward  affairs,  legislation, 
and  the  development  of  mind.  Thence  he  proceeds  to  trace, 
step  by  step,  the  operation  of  the  causes  which  decomposed 
his  vast  empire,  and,  at  the  same  time,  produced  the  feudal 
system  (20-25).  Nor  does  he  forget  to  study  either  the  his- 
tory of  the  Church  (26-27)  or  the  movement  and  manifesta- 
tions of  reflective  thought  (28-29)  during  the  same  period. 

In  fact,  he  analyses  the  entire  constitution  and  development 
of  society  during  these  five  centuries ;  lays  bare  all  its  essential 
elements,  all  its  chief  forces;  traces  them  all  continuously 
from  the  beginning  to  the  end  of  the  period  investigated ; 
traces  them  separately,  yet  also  in  connection,  never  forget- 
ting that  they  are  the  component  parts  or  principles  of  a  sin- 
gle self-dependent  and  active  whole. 

The  originality  of  M.  Guizot's  work  consists  in  the  truly 
scientific  spirit  and  character  of  his  method.  He  was  the 
first  to  dissect  a  society  in  the  same  comprehensive,  impar- 
tial, and  thorough  way  in  which  an  anatomist  dissects  the 
body  of  an  animal,  and  the  first  to  study  the  functions  of  the 
social  organism  in  the  same  systematic  and  careful  manner 
in  which  the  physiologist  studies  the  functions  of  the  animal 
organism.  Before  him  there  had  been  a  vast  amount  both 
of  historical  research  and  historical  speculation ;  states,  ages, 
classes,  individuals,  had  had  their  histories,  some  of  which 
were  excellent;  the  development  of  laws,  manners,  sciences, 
arts,  letters,  had  been  traced,  and  in  some  cases  not  only 


510  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

learnedly  but  with  considerable  insight  into  causation;  and 
there  had  even  been  systems  not  a  few  as  to  the  course,  and 
plan,  and  laws  of  history  as  a  whole ;  yet  he  was  fully  enti- 
tled, I  think,  to  speak  of  the  work  he  accomplished  as  new. 
It  was  not  conceived  of  before  the  eighteenth  century.  It 
was  first  truly  commenced  by  himself.  And  what  a  noble 
commencement  he  made!  Of  course  in  a  work  so  extensive, 
so  difficult,  every  careful  student  must  find  something  to 
criticise,  something  to  dissent  from ;  yet  few  will  deny  that 
it  is  a  model  of  scientific  skill,  comprehensively  treating  of 
all  the  vast  variety  of  facts  included  in  civilisation,  while 
never  allowing  to  drop  out  of  sight  the  unity  of  life  that 
underlies  the  multiplied  manifestations ;  that  it  is  not  only 
wonderfully  true  and  satisfactory  as  an  organic  whole,  but 
that  it  has  illuminated  a  multitude  of  particular  points  and 
dispelled  a  multitude  of  serious  errors ;  that  it  disclosed  in 
every  order  of  social  phenomena  a  significance  unnoticed 
before,  by  the  manner  in  which  it  showed  them  in  constant 
contact  with  the  other  orders  of  phenomena. 

The  application  which  M.  Guizot  made  of  his  method  to  a 
portion  of  history  was  conclusive  evidence  that  the  same 
method  could  be  applied  to  all  history.  It  was,  however, 
more.  It  was  a  practical,  irrefragable  proof  of  the  existence 
of  a  science  of  history,  not  indeed  in  every  sense  of  the  word 
science,  but  in  the  most  usual  sense,  the  only  sense  in  which 
there  is  a  science  of  geology  or  of  physiology.  He  applied 
the  same  sort  of  method,  the  same  rules  of  method,  which  are 
employed  in  these  sciences,  and  he  obtained  results  as  cer- 
tain, as  comprehensive,  as  important,  as  those  which  are 
reached  through  geological  or  physiological  research.  The 
term  science  may  be  so  strictly  defined  that  branches  of 
knowledge  like  geology  and  physiology  have  no  right  to  be 
called  sciences ;  the  term  law  is  very  often  so  defined  that 
no  geological  or  physiological  truth  is  entitled  to  the  name ; 
but  if  science  and  law  be  used  so  as  to  include  such  divisions 
of  knowledge  and  to  designate  their  highest  truths,  there  can 
be  no  reasonable  doubt  of  the  existence  of  historical  science 
and  historical  law.  M.  Guizot  has  proved  their  existence,  as 
Columbus  proved  the  existence  of  the  New  World  when  he 
sailed  onwards  until  he  reached  it. 


JAVAIIY  5H 


IV 


It  is  especially  by  their  researches  into  the  history  of  philos- 
ophy that  those  who  are  regarded  as  followers  of  Cousin  have 
contributed  to  the  philosophical  study  of  history,  and  to  a 
profounder  and  more  enlarged  conception  of  the  development 
of  humanity.  They  have  not  attempted  to  construct  philos- 
ophies of  history ;  but  several  of  them  have  dealt  with  special 
aspects  and  problems  of  historical  philosophy ;  and,  in  partic- 
ular, with  the  idea  of  progress.  I  shall  briefly  notice  some 
of  the  most  interesting  of  the  works  which  treat  of  this  theme. 

In  1851  M.  Javary  (1820-56)  published  his  '  Ide"e  de  Pro- 
gress. '  It  was  the  first  really  good  general  treatment  of  its 
subject.  It  was  at  once  an  important  contribution  to  the 
history  of  the  idea  of  progress,  a  careful  analysis  of  the  nature 
of  progress,  and  a  judicious  criticism  of  the  chief  erroneous 
views  prevalent  regarding  progress. 

Its  author's  independence,  as  well  as  soundness,  of  judg- 
ment is  everywhere  apparent.  Although  accepting  the  gen- 
eral principles  of  Cousin's  philosophy,  he  does  not  hesitate 
to  reject  his  particular  conclusions.  He  vigorously  opposes 
the  historical  optimism  which  Cousin  derived  from  Hegel 
and  endeavoured  to  propagate  in  France.  He  solidly  refutes 
such  dicta  as  that  "  whatever  is  is  good,"  and  that  "  evil  neces- 
sarily produces  good";  combats  the  fatalistic  theory  of  his- 
tory; and  maintains  that  human  progress  is  not  the  inevitable 
result  of  natural  laws  and  forces,  but  that  it  largely  depends 
on  how  individuals  and  societies  employ  the  freedom  with 
which,  they  have  been  endowed  whether  there  will  be  prog- 
ress or  decadence.  He  indicates  with  special  clearness  the 
moral  and  religious  conditions  which  are  implied  in  healthy 
social  development.  The  distinctive  characteristic  of  true 
progress  is  represented  by  him  as  advance  towards  a  complete 
realisation  of  human  nature  through  its  own  spiritual  energy ; 
that  is,  through  the  victory  of  the  rational  and  moral  will 
over  the  passions  which  war  against  the  higher  life  of  the 
soul. 


512  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Iii  M.  Javary's  work  we  may  not  find  any  absolutely  orig- 
inal ideas ;  but  we  never  fail  to  find  important  and  carefully 
considered  ideas.  Like  his  '  De  la  Certitude,'  it  is  a  book 
which  no  one  specially  studying  its  subject  can  afford  to 
neglect. 

The  question  of  progress  has  also  been  treated,  and  with 
characteristic  ingenuity,  by  M.  Bouillier,  the  eminent  author 
of  the  '  History  of  Cartesianism. '  In  his  '  Morale  et  Progres, ' 
he  seeks  to  determine  how  far  there  has  been  progress,  and 
how  far  there  has  not.  The  investigation  is  throughout  con- 
ducted with  reference  to  the  positions  regarding  progress 
maintained  by  Mr.  Buckle  in  his  '  History  of  Civilisation  in 
England,'  and  the  discussions  to  which  they  gave  rise. 

M.  Bouillier  describes  progress  as  a  legacy  or  inheritance 
which  is  transmitted  from  generation  to  generation,  and 
which  increases  with  the  advance  of  the  ages.  Only  what 
can  be  transmitted  and  accumulated  is  susceptible  of  prog- 
ress. He  draws  a  distinction  between  the  elements  or  mat- 
ter and  the  conditions  or  means  of  progress.  Its  elements  are 
intellectual  facts,  the  various  kinds  of  knowledge.  Its  con- 
ditions are  the  qualities  of  the  will,  —  character,  virtue.  The 
former  are  perfectible  in  the  species ;  the  latter  are  perfecti- 
ble only  in  the  individual.  The  acquisitions  of  intellect  do 
not  disappear  with  the  death  of  those  who  make  them. 
Truths  once  discovered,  inventions  once  found  out,  have  only 
to  be  made  known,  and  the  knowledge  of  them  "wakes  to 
perish  never."  If  a  great  physicist  through  his  labours 
extends  the  limits  and  increases  the  treasures  of  science, 
advances  the  industrial  arts,  facilitates  the  production  of 
wealth,  and  enriches  civilisation,  he  does  so  for  the  good  of 
the  world  in  all  time.  Any  young  man  with  a  turn  for  phy- 
sical science  may  easily  serve  himself,  heir  to  the  whole  of 
the  intellectual  legacy  which  he  bequeathed  to  the  race.  The 
gains  of  intellect  being  thus  transmitted  from  person  to  per- 
son, from  generation  to  generation,  are  constantly  accumu- 
lating; the  intellectual  capital  of  mankind  grows  steadily 
vaster ;  and  those  who  live  latest,  and  are  the  heirs  of  all  the 
ages,  are  the  richest.     In  a  word,  intellectual  progress  is  a 


BOUILLIER  513 

fact.  Moral  acquisitions,  however,  are  not  transmitted  and 
accumulated.  They  are  entirely  personal.  Virtue  is  not 
heritable.  There  is  no  evidence  that  the  force  of  will  neces- 
sary for  conformity  to  moral  law  is  increased  in  the  course  of 
ages ;  or  that  the  men  of  to-day  act  up  to  their  standard  of 
duty  more  faithfully  than  those  of  the  earliest  times.  There 
is,  therefore,  not  a  growth  of  virtue  in  the  species,  as  there 
is  of  knowledge.  We  are  not  entitled  to  affirm  the  existence 
of  moral  progress. 

Thus  far  the  conclusions  at  which  M.  Bouillier  arrives  are 
the  same  as  those  of  Mr.  Buckle,  although  the  reasons  which 
he  gives  both  for  admitting  intellectual  progress  and  for 
denying  moral  progress  are  different.  Yet  even  the  general 
point  of  view  from  which  he  surveys  history,  and  the  spirit 
in  which  he  judges  it,  are  in  one  respect  very  unlike  those 
of  the  English  writer.  Buckle  represents  the  intellect  as 
not  only  alone  perfectible,  but  as  the  alone  active  and  impor- 
tant factor  in  history ;  and  morality  as  not  stationary  but  with- 
out influence  and  significance  in  social  development.  In  his 
eyes  the  great  fact  in  history  is  progress;  and  the  essence  of 
progress  is  enlightenment,  and  the  cause  of  enlightenment  is 
the  triumph  of  intellect  over  ignorance  of  nature  and  faith. 
This  mode  of  thought  does  not  at  all  commend  itself  to 
Bouillier;  it  seems  to  him  uncritical  and  superficial.  Prog- 
ress he  thinks  over-praised;  and  enlightenment  as  well. 
Severed  from  virtue  they  are  really  of  slight  account.  Ages 
intellectually  cultured  but  morally  corrupt  are  not  great  ages, 
and  they  initiate  weakness  and  decay.  Without  the  impulse 
and  support  of  virtue  progress  cannot  sustain  itself,  and 
knowledge  fails  to  benefit  those  who  possess  it.  Although 
will,  force  of  character,  does  not  itself  make  progress  in 
humanity,  it  is  the  motive  power  of  all  human  progress. 

While  M.  Bouillier  acknowledges  progress  to  be  a  fact,  he 
refuses  to  admit  that  there  is  or  can  be  a  law  of  progress. 
Law  implies  necessary  causation,  but  history  and  progress 
are  effectuated  through  causes  which  are  not  necessary,  — 
through  free  agents,  free  wills. 

I  shall  make  only  a  very  few  observations  on  the  views 
thus  indicated. 


514  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

The  description  given  of  progress  as  constituted  by  the 
transmission  and  accumulation  of  truths,  experiences,  and 
acquisitions  is  clear  and  accurate.  The  criticism  of  Buckle's 
glorification  of  intellect  and  of  progress,  and  of  his  deprecia- 
tion of  the  function  and  significance  of  morality  in  history, 
is  incisive  and  conclusive.  That  there  is  not  sufficient  evi- 
dence to  warrant  the  affirmation  that  the  men  of  the  present 
day  are  more  virtuous  than  those  of  early  times  is  probably 
to  be  admitted,  if  by  virtue  be  meant  fidelity  to  the  law  of 
duty  so  far  as  it  is  apprehended,  conscientiousness,  meritori- 
ousness.  Thus  far  M.  Bouillier  seems  to  me  to  establish 
what  he  maintains. 

Yet  he  has  failed,  I  think,  to  draw  the  true  distinction 
between  what  is  progressive  and  unprogressive  in  the  species. 
That  distinction  is  not  the  distinction  between  intellect  and 
virtue,  but  the  more  general  distinction  between  the  powers 
or  internal  principles  of  the  mind  and  their  products  or 
external  results.  There  is  insufficient  evidence  for  holding 
that  any  of  the  former,  whether  intellectual  or  moral,  are 
capable  of  being  transmitted  and  accumulated.  We  can  no 
more  prove  that  the  Europeans  of  to-day  surpass  the  primi- 
tive Aryans  in  power  of  reason  or  imagination  than  we  can 
prove  that  they  surpass  them  in  force  of  will,  virtue  of  char- 
acter. We  can  no  more  show  that  the  great  men  of  ancient 
Greece  and  Rome  were  not  intellectually,  than  we  can  show 
that  they  were  not  morally,  the  equals  of  the  great  men  of 
modern  France  and  England.  It  seems  to  me  irrelevant  to 
discuss  in  connection  with  history  the  question  whether  or 
not  there  has  been  a  growth  of  virtue  in  a  sense  of  which 
history  can  tell  us  nothing.  Such  a  discussion  may  be  neces- 
sary in  ethics  and  theology,  but  it  cannot  in  the  least  decide 
whether  or  not  there  has  been  moral  progress. 

It  is  obvious  that  moral  gains,  in  the  form  of  thoughts, 
sentiments,  examples,  influences,  customs,  and  institutions, 
not  only  can  be,  but  are  constantly  being  transmitted ;  and 
that  in  consequence  the  moral  wealth  pi  mankind  is  increased 
from  age  to  age.  The  fundamental  principles  of  morality  are 
few,  and  may  have  all  been  discovered  in  very  early  times,  but 
their  applications  are  innumerable,  and  no  limit  can  be  set 
to  their  development.     Justice  and  charity  are  as  capable  of 


BOUILLIER  515 

an  endless  and  ever-varying  evolution  in  conduct  and  insti- 
tutions as  truth  and  beauty  are  in  the  sciences  and  fine  arts. 
The  poets  have  contributed  immensely  to  enrich  and  refine 
the  moral  feelings  of  mankind.  Grand  moral  examples  can 
be  as  effectively  perpetuated  as  great  scientific  discoveries  or 
important  mechanical  inventions.  Socrates  lives  for  ever  in 
the  pages  of  Plato  and  Xenophon,  and  Jesus  in  those  of  the 
Evangelists.  The  children  of  the  earliest  fetish-worshippers 
may  have  been  born  with  as  honest  and  good  hearts  as  those 
of  Christian  parents  in  the  nineteenth  century,  but  they  were 
certainly  born  to  a  far  poorer  moral  heritage ;  and,  relatively 
to  their  lights,  means,  and  opportunities,  they  may  have 
lived  as  faithfully  and  virtuously,  but  their  lights,  means,  and 
opportunities  were  vastly  different  and  vastly  inferior. 

The  reality  of  free  agency  is  not  a  sufficient  reason  for 
denying  that  progress  can  have  a  law.  Progress  implies  law, 
inasmuch  as  it  implies  order  and  development.  But  it  im- 
plies only  such  law  as  is  involved  in  order  and  development, 
not  a  law  of  mere  mechanical  causation ;  only  such  law  as 
can  be  discovered  by  observation  and  analysis,  not  such  law 
as  can  be  dealt  with  by  deduction  and  calculation.  There 
is,  however,  no  fact  in  history  which  is  of  such  a  nature  that 
it  cannot  be  traced  to  a  cause,  or  even  which  is  not  neces- 
sarily just  what  it  was  caused  to  be.  The  freedom  of  the 
human  will  does  not  imply  that  the  connection  between  the 
actions  and  the  effects,  which  are  the  only  components  of 
history,  has  not  been  a  necessary  connection,  but  only  that 
there  might  have  been  other  actions  which  would'  necessarily 
have  had  quite  other  effects.  If  free-will  be  admitted,  we 
must  infer  that  there  might  have  been  a  very  different  human 
history  than  the  actual  one ;  but  not  that  the  actual  one  is 
other  than  the  result  of  all  the  causes  which  really  acted. 
Free  agency  transcends  history;  only  realities,  not  possibili- 
ties,—  only  actual  volitions  and  their  effects, —  compose  his- 
tory, and  the  connection  between  them  must  be  acknowledged 
to  be  a  necessary  connection.1 

1  There  is  a  valuable  essay  by  M.  Bouillier  on  an  important  historical  theme, 
La  justice  historique,  in  the  '  Compte  Rendu  de  l'Acad.  d.  Sc.  mor.  et  pol.,'  t.  xxv., 
1886;  and  a  sagacious  discussion  of  the  question  Ya-t-il  une  philosophie  de  I'his- 
toire?  in  '  Rev.  phi].,'  t.  xxi.,  pp.  329-347. 


516  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY    IN   FRANCE 

Spiritualistic  philosophy  has  had  no  more  accomplished 
expositor  and  defender  in  France  during  the  present  genera- 
tion than  the  late  M.  Caro.  The  greatest  problems  of  thought, 
those  which  lie  at  the  very  foundation  of  theodicy,  ethics,  and 
sociology  —  of  belief  in  God,  the  soul,  duty,  and  immortality 
—  were  those  on  which  his  interest  was  especially  concen- 
trated. He  was  brilliant  alike  as  a  lecturer  and  a  writer. 
Hardly  in  any  age  has  there  appeared  so  consummate  a  mas- 
ter of  the  art  of  philosophical  polemic.  The  lucidity  and 
grace,  the  exquisite  blending  of  naturalness  and  refinement, 
and  the  perfect  accordance  of  thought  and  feeling  with  their 
expression,  which  characterise  all  his  compositions,  are  reflec- 
tions of  the  harmony  and  beauty  of  his  personality,  expres- 
sions of  the  light  and  sweetness  of  a  most  lovable  character.1 

He  has  devoted  four  chapters  of  his  '  Probl&mes  de  la 
Morale  Sociale, '  1876,  to  the  consideration  of  social  progress. 
He  first  gives  a  general  view  of  the  history  of  the  idea,  and 
dwells  particularly  on  its  transformations  in  the  nineteenth 
century.  He  had  studied  closely  the  growth  of  the  theory 
of  evolution,  or  of  physiological  determinism,  as  applied  to 
history,  and  his  observations  on  the  forms  which  it  had 
assumed  under  the  hands  of  Comte  and  Littre",  of  Buckle, 
Bagehot,  and  Spencer,  are  of  special  interest.  He  further 
treats  of  the  laws  and  limits  of  progress  in  science,  industry, 
institutions,  morality,  and  art.  The  discussion  is  through- 
out marked  by  comprehensiveness  and  penetration  of  view, 
by  caution  and  sureness  of  judgment,  by  ingenuity  and  elo- 
quence. All  its  main  conclusions  seem  to  me  sound.  In 
the  portion  of  it  relating  to  moral  progress  the  criticism  of 
the  theory  of  M.  Bouillier  deserves  to  be  noted. 

Two  other  chapters  of  the  same  volume  concern  historical 
philosophy.  The  first  (chap,  vi.)  is  an  examination  of  the 
evolutionist  hypothesis  of  the  origin  and  future  of  societies. 
The  relevancy  and  the  gravity  of  the  objections  which  he 
urges  against  it  are  only  too  obvious ;  but  it  is,  perhaps,  to 

1  Regarding  the  life  and  writings  of  M.  Caro,  see  the  Notices  of  M.  Constant 
Martha  (in  vol.  i.  of  '  Melanges  et  Portraits '),  of  M.  Ch.  Waddington  (in  '  Compte 
Rendu  de  l'Acad.  d.  Sci.  mor.  et  pol.,'  Mai-Jnin  1889),  and  of  M.  Jules  Simon  (in 
January  No.,  1890,  of  same  publication).  Also  Art.  of  M.  Brunetiere  in  'Rev. d. 
Deux  Mondes,'  1  Juin  1888. 


CAEEAIT  517 

be  desired  that  he  had  more  distinctly  indicated  what  is  true 
or  probable  in  it,  as  he  might  quite  consistently  have  done. 
The  other  chapter  (xv.)  is  that  with  which  the  work  closes. 
Its  subject  is  "human  destiny  according  to  the  scientific 
schools."  The  conception  of  human  destiny  implied  in  those 
positivist,  evolutionist,  and  pessimist  systems,  which  repre- 
sent faith  in  the  Divine  as  incompatible  with  the  findings  of 
science,  is  strikingly  exhibited,  and  it  is  maintained  to  be 
such  as  of  itself  renders  these  systems  very  doubtful.  In 
the  working  out  of  this  argument,  skilful  use  is  made  of  the 
painfully  interesting  volume  ('  Poe'sies  philosophiques  ')  in 
which  a  woman  of  genius  (Madame  Ackermann)  has  made 
apparent  how  terribly  the  science,  falsely  so  called,  at  present 
prevalent,  may  darken  and  disorder  even  a  vigorous  mind. 

I  pass  to  another  author  whose  memory  is  also  dear  to  me, 
the  late  M.  Ludovic  Carrau.  His  life  was  brief  but  fruitful. 
He  early  made  himself  known  to  the  philosophical  world  by 
his  important  work  '  Morale  utilitaire, '  which  was  followed 
by  'Etudes  sur  revolution'  and  '  Philosophie  religieuse  en 
Angleterre.'  The  works  testify  to  the  thoroughness  of  his 
studies,  the  amplitude  and  accuracy  of  his  information,  and 
the  clearness,  strength,  and  acuteness  of  his  understanding.1 

While  engaged  on  the  translation  of  my  '  Philosophy  of 
History  in  France  and  Germany, '  he  wrote,  partly  with  refer- 
ence to  it,  an  interesting  and  able  article  on  the  subject  of 
progress  in  the  '  Revue  des  Deux  Mondes  '  (Oct.  1875).  In 
this  essay  he  indicates  and  characterises  the  various  ways  in 
which  progress  has  been  conceived  of,  and  in  which  it  has 
been  attempted  to  reach  and  formulate  its  law.  He  fully 
recognises  the  difficulties  of  determining  with  sufficient  pre- 
cision its  law,  or  even  its  conditions  and  end.  But  he 
holds  that  the  reality  of  progress  is  certain.  Evolution,  as 
a  mass  of  evidence  shows,  has  been  a  feature  of  all  nature, 
" the  universal  formula  of  existence;"  and  historical  prog- 
ress is  a  variety  or  department  of  evolution.  The  course  of 
evolution,  although  for  countless  ages  mainly  physical  and 
animal,  was  always  upwards,   and  issued  at  length  in  the 

1  See  M.  Fr.  Pioavet's  '  M.  Ludovic  Carrau,'  1889. 


518  PHILOSOPHY  OP  HISTORY  IN  PRANCE 

appearance  of  man ;  its  interest  since  has  been  chiefly  spirit- 
ual, and  its  direction,  so  far  as  it  has  yet  gone,  has  been  still 
more  clearly  that  of  elevation  and  improvement.  It  is  true, 
however,  that  man  is  not  borne  upward  and  forward  by  any 
fatalistic  or  physically  necessary  law;  he  is  a  rational  and 
free  being,  and  his  progress  is  just  the  triumph  of  reason  and 
moral  liberty  over  nature  and  necessity.  Man  has  been  so 
constituted  in  intellect  and  in  heart  that  he  cannot  but  form 
ideals  of  truth,  beauty,  happiness,  and  perfection  which  he 
feels  drawn  and  bound  to  strive  to  reach  and  to  realise.  It 
is  through  the  general  yielding  of  mankind  to  this  sense  of 
attraction  and  of  obligation  that  the  history  of  humanity  is 
a  movement  of  growing  approximation  towards  a  goal  which 
will  never  be  completely  reached,  but  every  step  towards 
which  means  fuller  knowledge,  greater  reasonableness,  a 
richer  enjoyment  of  beauty,  a  more  perfect  righteousness,  a 
purer  and  more  diffused  happiness.  There  is  no  evidence 
that  the  course  of  nature  and  of  history  will  be  reversed,  so 
as  to  tend  towards  unreason,  unrighteousness,  and  misery, 
towards  death,  darkness,  and  chaos.  If  the  power  which 
made  and  rules  the  world  and  humanity  be  rational  and 
righteous  such  a  reversal  is  incredible.  The  main  conclu- 
sion, in  short,  reached  by  M.  Carrau  is  one  to  which  an  Eng- 
lish poetess  has  given  magnificent  expression ;  the  conclusion 
that  we  may  well 

"  Rest  in  faith 
That  man's  perfection  is  the  crowning  flower, 
Towards  which  the  urgent  sap  in  life's  great  tree 
Is  pressing,  —  seen  in  puny  blossoms  now, 
But  in  the  world's  great  morrows  to  expand 
With  broadest  petal  and  with  deepest  glow." x 


1  George  Eliot,  '  The  Spanish  Gypsy.'  All  M.  Carrau's  '  Etudes  sur  la  the'orie 
de  revolution '  hear  on  historical  philosophy,  and  are  eminently  judicious  and 
instructive.  They  treat  of  the  following  subjects :  (1)  the  origin  of  instinct  and 
of  thought;  (2)  the  origin  of  man;  (3)  the  origin  of  belief  in  a  future  life;  (4)  the 
origin  of  primitive  worships;  (5)  the  origin  of  the  moral  sense;  and  (6)  the 
origin  of  language.  The  essay  noticed  in  the  text  was  republished  in  the  volume 
entitled  '  La  conscience  psychologique  et  morale  dans  l'individu  et  dans  l'his- 
toire,'  1888,  which  contains  several  articles  on  subjects  closely  akin  to  those  dealt 
with  in  the  '  Etudes.' 


DE  TOCQTJEVILLE  519 


The  influence  of  Guizot  is  perceptible  on  almost  all  later 
French  historians.  It  is  easily  traceable  in  the  writings  of 
many  who  were  personally  and  politically  hostile  to  him,  as, 
e.g.,  Michelet  and  Quinet.  Those  who  rejected  his  doctrina- 
rianism  were  often  more  doctrinarian  than  himself,  and  that 
in  fashions  which  bore  his  impress.  Like  the  eclecticism  of 
Cousin,  the  doctrinarianism  of  Guizot,  in  its  strictest  accep- 
tation, was  almost  confined  to  its  propounder,  but  in  a  wider 
yet  very  real  sense,  or,  in  other  words,  in  its  general  spirit 
and  principles,  it  also,  like  eclecticism,  entered  very  widely 
into  the  creed  of  studious  men.  His  analytic  and  inductive 
method  of  dealing  with  history  as  a  complex  and  ever-vary- 
ing, an  organic  and  spiritual  development,  was  followed  to  a 
still  greater  extent.  In  the  present  chapter  I  shall  refer  only 
to  one  of  the  philosophical  historians  influenced  by  Guizot, 
but  to  one  of  the  most  celebrated  and  most  esteemed. 

Alexis  de  Tocqueville  (1805-58)  was  a  high-minded  and 
pure-hearted  man,  of  rare  beauty  of  character  and  life.  He 
was  a  moderate  and  judicious,  profound  and  sagacious 
thinker.  His  faith  in  the  liberalism  of  his  Church  was  a 
natural  and  amiable  illusion.  Some  political  mistakes  into 
which  we  may  think  he  fell  should  not  cause  us  to  withhold 
from  him  the  admiration  due  to  the  political  wisdom  of  which 
he  gave  ample  proof.1 

He  had  no  belief  in  the  easy  discovery  of  general  laws  of 
historical  evolution.  He  did  not  profess  to  have  discovered, 
or  even  to  be  aware  of,  any  such  laws  himself;  although,  as 
he  jocularly  observed,  he  heard  almost  every  morning  that 
somebody  had  been  more  fortunate,  and  had  found  a  hitherto 

\Mt.  Henry  Reeve  has  enriched  our  literature  with  an  excellent  translation  of 
De  Tocqueville's  writings.  They  have  nowhere  found  more  appreciative  readers 
and  reviewers  than  in  Britain.  I  have  felt  bound  to  refrain  from  dwelling  on 
their  general  merits  and  characteristics,  work  well  performed  already  by  Alison, 
Mill,  and  others,  and  simply  to  indicate  their  relation  to  historical  philosophy. 
'The  Memoir,  Letters,  and  Remains  of  Alexis  de  Tocqueville,  translated  from  the 
French  by  the  translator  of  Napoleon's  Correspondence  with  King  Joseph,'  2  vols., 
1861,  renders  into  English  the  charming  work  of  M.  Gustave  de  Beaumont,  and 
supplements  it  with  large  and  interesting  additions. 


520  PHILOSOPHY  OF  HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

unknown  fundamental  law  of  history  by  means  of  which  the 
most  wonderful  social  improvements  were  to  be  brought 
about.  He  had  a  constitutional  aversion  to  all  general  his- 
torical speculation,  because  it  could  not  be  based  on  a  full 
and  accurate  knowledge  of  the  whole  time  and  space,  of  the 
whole  mass  of  facts,  covered  by  its  conclusions.  He  could 
always  find  scope  enough  for  his  powers  of  acquisition  and 
reflection,  great  as  they  were,  within  a  comparatively  limited 
area;  and  he  preferred  cultivating  a  small  and  distinctly 
defined  territory  thoroughly,  to  cultivating  a  vast  and  vague 
one  superficially. 

But  notwithstanding  this  jealousy  of  general  historical 
philosophy,  both  his  'De  la  Democratic  en  Arnerique,'  1835, 
and  his  'L'Ancien  Regime  et  la  Revolution,'  1856,  have 
great  interest  and  value  for  the  historical  philosopher.  The 
former  especially  is  an  original  and  masterly  application  of 
the  inductive  method  to  the  study  of  history.  Never  before 
had  the  social  characteristics  of  a  country  been  so  faithfully 
observed  and  skilfully  analysed,  or  so  ingeniously  yet  impar- 
tially compared  with  those  of  a  country  very  different  in  its 
history,  and  very  differently  circumstanced  in  many  ways,  in 
order  to  discover  the  real  workings  of  certain  dispositions  or 
tendencies  of  spirit  which  they  possessed  in  common.  As  an 
admirable  exemplification  of  the  logical  processes  by  which 
social  and  historical  science  is  to  be  obtained,  the  work  is 
invaluable,  independently  of  the  worth  of  its  results.  Most 
of  these  processes,  indeed,  Guizot  had  already  successfully 
practised  in  his  examination  of  the  development  of  European 
civilisation :  but  it  fell  to  De  Tocqueville  to  employ  them 
with  a  fulness  of  illustration,  a  thoroughness,  and  a  detail, 
only  possible  within  a  more  limited  and  manageable  sphere ; 
and  to  show  that  a  smaller  field  with  a  more  intensive  and 
elaborate  culture  would  yield  a  harvest  of  results  not  less 
rich  and  precious  than  a  much  larger  one  less  carefully  and 
skilfully  tilled. 

De  Tocqueville's  work  had  an  immense  success.  It  set 
a  vast  number  of  persons  to  theorising  on  the  tendencies  of 
democracy,  and  to  studying  the  institutions  of  the  United 
States.     To  the  interest  which  it  excited  and  the  impulse 


DE  TOCQITEVILLE  521 

which  it  gave,  we  owe  a  multitude  of  works  on  democracy 
and  on  America,  some  of  which  are  of  great  value,  as,  e.g.,  to 
mention  only  the  two  best  of  those  which  have  lately  ap- 
peared, the  '  De  la  De"mocratie  '  of  Laveleye  and  the  'Ameri- 
can Commonwealth '  of  Prof.  Bryce.  They  have  all  derived 
to  some  extent  their  existence,  and  even  the  best  of  them 
much  of  their  merit,  from  the  epoch-making  treatise  of  De 
Toequeville. 

A  part  of  the  task,  however,  which  he  attempted  in  that 
treatise  was  one  which  the  human  intellect  can  as  yet  accom- 
plish with  only  very  partial  success,  namely,  the  forecasting 
of  the  future.  Induction  from  the  facts  of  history  is  too 
difficult,  and  deduction  from  its  tendencies  too  hypothetical, 
to  allow  of  this  being  done  with  much  certainty  or  precision ; 
hence  it  is  not  to  be  wondered  at  that  several  of  his  anticipa- 
tions or  prophecies  have  not  yet  been  confirmed,  and  seem 
now  less  probable  than  when  they  were  first  enunciated.  It 
is  more  remarkable  that  he  should  have  been  so  often  and  so 
far  right ;  and  that  he  should  have  been  always  so  conscious 
that  he  might  very  probably  be  mistaken.  Adequately  to 
appreciate  the  latter  merit,  we  have  only  to  contrast  him  with 
a  man  like  Auguste  Comte,  almost  wholly  destitute  of  humil- 
ity, and  consequently  always  sure  that  every  vaticination  of 
his  would  be  fulfilled,  yet  almost  never  making  even  a  toler- 
ably successful  guess  as  to  the  course  which  events  were 
about  to  take  either  in  France  or  elsewhere.  Humility  is 
essential  to  foresight;  and  De  Tocqueville's  foresight  was 
largely  due  to  his  humility. 

He  shared  in  democratic  convictions,  but  with  intelligence 
and  in  moderation.  He  acknowledged  that  democracy  at  its 
conceivable  best  would  be  the  best  of  all  forms  of  government ; 
the  one  to  which  all  others  ought  to  give  place.  And  he  was 
fully  persuaded  that  all  others  were  rapidly  making  way  for 
it ;  and  that  the  movement  towards  it  which  had  been  so  visi- 
bly going  on  for  at  least  a  century  could  by  no  means  be 
arrested.  He  elaborated  his  proof  of  the  irresistibility  and 
invincibility  of  the  democratic  movement,  and  he  emphasised 
and  reiterated  the  conclusion  itself,  because  he  deemed  it  to 
be  of  prime  importance  that  men  should  be  under  no  illusion 


522  PHILOSOPHY  OF  HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

on  the  matter.  He  succeeded  at  once  in  getting  the  truth 
generally  accepted;  and  there  has  been  so  much  confirmation 
of  it  since  1835  that  probably  no  one  will  now  dream  of  con- 
testing it.  At  present  Russia  and  Turkey  are  the  only  abso- 
lute monarchies  in  Europe,  and  it  seems  impossible  that  they 
should  long  retain  their  exceptional  positions.  There  is  no- 
where visible  on  the  earth  in  our  day  any  power  capable  of 
resisting  or  crushing  democracy.  If  there  be  none  such  it 
does  not  follow  that  it  will  not  be  arrested  in  its  progress; 
but  it  follows  that  it  will  only  be  arrested  by  itself. 

That  it  may  be  thus  arrested  De  Tocqueville  saw;  that 
it  would  be  thus  arrested  he  feared.  While  sensible  of  its 
merits  he  was  also  aware  of  its  defects,  and  keenly  alive  to 
its  dangers.  While  he  recognised  that  it  might  possibly  be 
the  best  of  all  governments,  he  also  recognised  that  it  could 
easily  be  the  worst,  and  that  it  was  the  most  difficult  either 
to  make  or  to  keep  good.  The  chief  aim  of  his  work,  indeed, 
was  to  demonstrate  that  democracy  was  in  imminent  peril  of 
issuing  in  despotism ;  and  that  the  more  thoroughly  the  dem- 
ocratic spirit  did  its  work  in  levelling  and  destroying  social 
inequalities  and  distinctions,  just  so  much  the  less  resistance 
would  the  establishment  of  despotism  encounter,  while  at  the 
same  time  so  much  the  more  grievous  would  be  its  conse- 
quences. As  regards  France,  his  gloomiest  forebodings  were 
realised.  She  had  shown,  by  the  Revolution  of  July  1830, 
that  she  would  submit  neither  to  autocratic  nor  to  aristo- 
cratic government ;  and  in  1835  she  was  chafing  under  pluto- 
cratic rule,  rapidly  becoming  more  democratic,  and  getting 
largely  imbued  with  the  socialistic  spirit  which  insists  not 
only  on  equality  of  rights  but  on  equality  of  conditions. 
The  Guizot  Ministry  (1840-48),  by  blindly  and  obstinately- 
refusing  to  grant  the  most  manifestly  just  and  reasonable 
demands  for  electoral  reform,  greatly  contributed  to  augment 
the  strength  and  violence  of  the  democratic  movement,  until 
at  length  it  overthrew  the  monarchy,  and  raised  up  a  repub- 
lic, one  of  the  first  acts  of  which  was  to  decree  universal 
suffrage.  But  in  1852  the  workmen  and  peasants  of  France 
made  use  of  their  votes  to  confer  absolute  power  on  the  author 
of  a  shameful  and  sanguinary  coup  d'Stat;  and  Caesarism  was 


DE  TOCQTJEVILLE  523 

acclaimed  by  7,482,863  Ayes  as  gainst  238,582  Noes.  There 
could  be  no  more  striking  exemplification  or  impressive  warn- 
ing of  the  liability  of  democracy  to  cast  itself  beneath  the  feet 
of  despotism.  Yet  history,  so  far  as  it  has  gone  since  De 
Tocqueville  wrote,  has  not,  on  the  whole,  shown  that  democ- 
racy is  more  than  liable  thus  to  err;  has  not  tended  to  prove 
that  it  must  necessarily  or  will  certainly  thus  err.  For  the 
last  twenty  years  France  has  been  organising  herself  as  a  de- 
mocracy according  to  the  principles  of  constitutional  liberty. 
America,  even  while  passing  through  a  great  war,  gave  not 
the  slightest  intimations  of  desire  for  a  Caesar.  Instead  of 
there  being  less  there  is  far  more  inequality  of  conditions 
in  the  United  States  to-day  than  there  was  in  1835.  In  no 
other  country,  in  fact,  have  such  inequalities  of  wealth  been 
developed  during  the  last  half-century;  and  inequality  of 
wealth  necessarily  brings  with  it  other  kinds  of  inequality. 
In  no  country  is  the  establishment  of  a  despotism  so  improb- 
able. It  should  be  observed,  however,  that  the  only  way  in 
which  we  can  conceive  of  such  an  event  being  brought  about 
is  one  which  would  be  in  accordance  with  De  Tocqueville's 
theory.  Let  the  conflict  between  labour  and  capital  in  Amer- 
ica proceed  until  the  labourers  attempt  to  employ  their  polit- 
ical power  in  the  expropriation  of  the  capitalists;  let  the 
democracy  of  America  become  predominantly  socialistic,  in 
the  sense  of  being  bent  on  attaining  the  equality  which  re- 
quires the  sacrifice  of  justice  and  of  liberty;  and  there  will 
happen  in  America  what  happened  about  two  thousand  years 
ago,  in  the  greatest  republic  of  the  ancient  world,  a  Caesar 
will  be  called  for  and  a. Caesar  will  appear,  and  democracy 
will  be  controlled  by  despotism. 

'L'Ancien  Regime  et  la  Revolution, '  owing  to  the  death 
of  its  gifted  author,  was  left  incomplete.  The  differences 
between  French  society  before  and  after  the  Revolution  are 
not  brought  out  in  it,  nor  are  their  causes.  The  influence 
of  the  literary  men  of  the  eighteenth  century  on  opinions  and 
events  is  passed  over  unestimated.  Still  the  work  accom- 
plished much,  although  not  all  that  it  sought  to  accomplish. 
It  investigated  the  causes  of  the  catastrophe  which  cast  to 
the  ground  the  old  French  monarchy,  in  a  manner  far  more 


524  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

sifting  and  trustworthy  than  had  previously  been  displayed. 
The  inductions  it  contained  were  based  on  the  most  labori- 
ous and  conscientious  study  of  original  testimonies,  the 
accounts  and  correspondence  of  intendants,  parochial  regis- 
ters, parliamentary  decisions,  and  contemporary  memoirs.  It 
was  the  least  declamatory,  and  yet  the  most  terrible,  expos- 
ure of  the  incompetency  and  oppressiveness  of  the  monarchy 
which  had  appeared,  as  well  as  the  most  convincing  demon- 
stration that  the  Revolution  had  left  essentially  unaltered  far 
more  of  the  governmental  system  of  the  monarchy  than  was 
supposed.  It  showed  that  while  the  fall  of  the  monarchy 
was  the  natural  consequence  of  its  faults,  the  Revolution  had 
affected  the  course  of  the  development  of  French  history 
much  less  than  was  believed,  and  much  less  than  was  to  have 
been  desired.  It  showed,  in  particular,  the  absurdity  of 
attributing  to  the  Revolution  the  administrative  centralisa- 
tion of  France ;  and,  at  the  same  time,  the  folly  of  the  pro- 
moters of  the  Revolution  in  maintaining  centralisation  while 
desirous  of  fostering  liberty. 

VI 

"We  shall  conclude  this  chapter  with  Barchou  de  Penhoen 
(1801-57),  one  of  the  few  French  writers  who  have  attempted 
to  treat  of  the  philosophy  of  history  as  a  whole.  He  attained 
considerable  eminence  in  general  literature,  and  was  a  mem- 
ber of  the  French  Academy.  His  mind  being  of  a  naturally 
imaginative  and  speculative  cast,  found  a  special  satisfaction 
in  the  study  of  German  idealism.  Besides  special  labours 
on  Fichte  and  Schelling,  he  published  an  '  Histoire  de  la 
philosophic  allemande  depuis  Leibnitz  -jusqu'a  Hegel '  (2 
vols.,  1836).  In  1849  he  sat  in  the  National  Assembly  as  a 
Catholic  and  Legitimist ;  but  his  Catholicism  and  Legitimism 
were  both  of  a  very  broad  and  liberal  kind.  He  protested 
against  the  coup  d'etat.  His  most  ambitious  work  is  the 
'  Essai  d'une  philosophie  de  l'histoire  '  (2  torn.,  1854).  It  is 
characterised  by  literary  grace,  poetical  feeling,  moral  eleva- 
tion, and  considerable  philosophical  originality.  As  to  the 
order  and  nature  of  its  contents,  the  following  remarks  may 
suffice. 


BARCHOU  525 

It  begins  with  the  Absolute,  with  necessary  Being,  with 
God.  He  is  the  source  and  the  end  of  all ;  everywhere  pres- 
ent; essentially  self-conscious;  infinitely  and  eternally  opera- 
tive. In  the  divine  nature  there  is  an  intellectual  evolution 
so  far  explicable  by  the  evolution  of  human  thought;  the 
birth  of  an  ideal  world  which  is  also  a  real  world.  God 
manifests  Himself  in  the  universe.  Time,  space,  and  mat- 
ter are  forms  of  the  divine  activity;  time  of  its  suocessivity, 
space  of  its  simultaneity,  and  matter  of  their  combination,  as 
it  partakes  alike  of  the  mobility  of  time  and  the  immobility 
of  space.  Primitive  matter  is  the  ether.  With  it  the  mate- 
rial creation  starts,  and  from  it  it  is  evolved;  in  it  the  im- 
ponderable fluids  originate ;  out  of  it  arise,  under  the  influence 
of  causes  as  yet  unknown  to  us,  the  solar  and  planetary  bodies. 
In  space  the  universe  is  infinite ;  in  time  it  is  a  continuous 
evolution.  Being  the  expression  of  the  thought  and  of  the 
activity  of  God,  it  has  no  limit  either  in  extension  or  dura- 
tion. Our  earth  has  not  a  definite  relation  to  it  as  a  drop  of 
water  has  to  the  ocean;  for  while  the  ocean  is  finite  and  con- 
tains a  finite  number  of  drops,  the  universe  is  infinite  and 
comprises  an  infinity  of  worlds  which  arise  and  perish,  coex- 
ist with  or  succeed  one  another,  in  infinite  series.1 

M.  Barchou  proceeds  to  trace  the  general  course  of  cos- 
mical,  geological,  and  especially  biological  evolution.  He 
denies  the  fixity  of  species.  He  affirms  that  life  has  always 
and  everywhere  existed,  instead  of  originating  in  a  particu- 
lar spot  at  a  particular  date.  He  believes  in  spontaneous 
generation  so  far  as  consistent  with  the  universality  and 
eternity  of  life.  And  he  decidedly  maintains  transformism, 
although  admitting  that  it  must  have  taken  place  not  by  in- 
sensible gradations,  but  "by  leaps."1 

He  next  takes  up  historical  development.  Man,  he  con- 
tends, must  have  arrived  on  earth  not  as  a  child  but  as  a 
complete  man.  Society  was  not  invented  by  men  but  con- 
stituted by  them.  The  hypothesis  of  Rousseau  and  other 
eighteenth-century  philosophers  which  assign  to  society, 
religion,  and  language,  an  intentional  or  artificial  origin,  are 
baseless ;  these  things  are  the  products  of  nature  and  spon- 

1  Essai,  t.  i.  1-31.  2  T.  i.  35-81. 


526  PHILOSOPHY  OF  HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

taneity,  not  of  chance  or  reflection.  Man  is  endowed  with 
a  threefold  life,  which  has  revealed  itself,  first,  in  speech, 
religion,  and  association ;  next,  in  the  relations  of  peace  and 
war  between  peoples ;  and,  further,  in  the  struggle  with 
nature.  There  is  a  continuous  evolution  of  the  threefold  life 
of  humanity  towards  perfection;  and  this  evolution  is  the 
substance  of  history,  and  the  immediate  object  of  the  philos- 
ophy of  history.1 

In  delineating  the  first  stage  of  history,  le  monde  primitif, 
our  author  follows  Vico  and  Ballanche,  and  represents  the 
earliest,  societies  as  having  been  ruled  and  organised  by  divine 
dynasties,  by  inspired  legislators.  The  reign  of  the  gods,  he 
argues,  was  a  universal  fact,  rendered  necessary  by  the  very 
constitution  of  human  intelligence.  No  other  rational  ac- 
count, he  maintains,  can  be  given  of  the  origins  of  religion, 
industry,  science,  and  art.2 

According  to  Barchou  the  life  of  each  people  is  presided 
over  by  a  distinctive  fundamental  idea.  Thus  China,  India, 
and  Persia  represent  three  phases  or  elements  of  oriental  civil- 
isation. In  the  lives  of  all  three  the  idea  of  the  Divine  is 
dominant;  but  in  China  its  power  is  seen  in  the  annihilation 
of  personality,  in  India  in  the  separation  of  social  functions, 
and  in  Persia  in  religious  proselytism.  Persia  was  the  link 
between  the  East  and  West,  and  the  commencement  ef  uni- 
versal history.3 

The  other  stages  of  universal  history  are  the  Hellenic 
world,  the  Eoman  world,  the  Barbarian  world,  the  Feudal 
world,  the  world  of  the  Renaissance,  and  the  Modern  world. 
To  each  of  these  M.  Barchou  devotes  a  book.  All  this  por- 
tion of  his  work  is  excellent.  Each  world  has  obviously 
been  carefully  and  impartially  studied ;  has  obviously  been 
made  the  subject  of  prolonged  inquiry  and  reflection.  It  has, 
further,  been  allowed  naturally  and  slowly  to  disclose  its 
own  character  and  significance.  It  has  not  been  interpreted 
by  means  of  extraneous  and  alien  principles  or  in  favour 
of  preconceived  opinions ;  and  it  is  vividly,  accurately,  and 
artistically  delineated.  In  a  word,  the  books  referred  to  bring 
before  us  a  succession  of  luminous,  faithful,  and  effective 

1  Essai,  t.  i.  85-136.  2  T.  i.  139-203.  8  T.  i.  207-294. 


BARCHOTJ  527 

pictures,  full  of  interest  and  instruction,  of  attractiveness 
and  suggestiveness.  They  are  at  once  truly  historical  and 
truly  philosophical.1 

From  them  we  are  led  to  the  consideration  of  a  world  in 
which  there  are  as  yet  no  facts,  and  consequently  no  data  for 
inductions.  In  treating  of  this,  the  world  of  the  future,  M. 
Barchou  necessarily  proceeds  deductively,  and  arrives  only 
at  vague  and  uncertain  conclusions.  Seeing  in  the  develop- 
ment of  society  from  the  dawn  of  history  to  the  present  time 
the  realisation  of  individuality,  he  regards  it  as  the  germ  of 
the  societies  of  the  future,  the  forms  and  conditions  of  which 
are  still  unknown.  New  hierarchies,  new  distributions  of 
social  functions,  will  arise.  The  work  of  society  will  be 
chiefly  accomplished  by  association ;  it  will  be  an  exploita- 
tion in  common  which  becomes  more  and  more  detached  from 
possession.  Wealth  will  be  completely  mobilised;  the  war 
between  labour  and  capital  will  cease;  competition  will  give 
place  to  harmony ;  nature  will  be  rendered  entirely  docile  to 
the  will  of  man;  and  the  peoples  of  the  earth  will  be  united 
in  the  same  faith  and  participant  in  the  same  civilisation. 
The  unity  of  the  future  will  be  far  richer  and  more  compre- 
hensive than  that  of  the  middle  age.  Christianity  will  reign 
in  the  world  far  more  powerfully  than  it  has  ever  yet  done. 
The  kingdom  of  God  on  earth  will  fully  come.2 

But  our  thoughts  and  expectations  should  not  be  confined 
to  the  earth.  Man  is  related  to  the  entire  universe.  The 
terrestrial  globe  is  only  a  portion  of  the  universe,  and  far 
even  from  being  either  its  centre  or  crown.  There  is  life  in 
the  rest  of  the  universe  as  well  as  on  earth.  Humanity  is 
only  the  fragment  of  the  immense  system  of  animated  crea- 
tion on  and  beyond  the  earth.  Evolution,  the  general  law 
of  nature,  will  not  stop  at  the  present  order  of  things,  or 
come  to  a  close  with  the  earth.  There  are  forces  in  operation 
which  will  bring  the  planetary  and  solar  bodies  into  collision 
and  form  vaster  masses,  an  endless  series  of  mightier  worlds, 
each  with  their  appropriate  types  of  inhabitants.  Beyond  the 
universal  resurrection  of  which  Christianity  speaks,  on  other 
earths  and  under  other  heavens,  mankind  will  accomplish 

1  Essai,  t.  i.  299;  t.  ii.  372.  2  T.  ii.  375-444. 


528  PHILOSOPHY  OP  HISTORY  IN  PRANCE 

other  social  functions  in  the  kingdom  of  God.  Life  and  rea- 
son, the  universe  and  humanity,  are  ever  rising  upwards, 
ever  drawing  nearer  to  the  Eternal.1 

In  the  historical  philosophy  of  Barchou  de  Penhoen  it  is 
easy  to  distinguish  what  must  be  referred  to  historical  gen- 
eralisation from  what  has  had  its  source  in  Christian  faith, 
socialistic  convictions,  and  sympathy  with  socialism  and  evo- 
lutionism, German  transcendentalism  and  French  spiritual- 


1  Essai,  t.  ii.  447-478. 

2  M.  Renee  Lavollee  is  the  author  of  a  work  which  bears  two  titles,  '  La  morale 
dans  l'histoire:  etude  sur  les  principaux  systemes  de,  philosophic  de  l'histoire 
depuis  l'antiquite  jusqu'a  nos  jours,'  1892.  The  former  title  is  altogether  inap- 
propriate. After  devoting  sixty  pages  to  a  general  view  of  the  historical  theories 
promulgated  in  antiquity,  the  middle  ages,  and  the  period  of  the  renaissance,  M. 
Lavollee  treats  of  those  of  modern  times  in  three  books.  In  the  first  of  these  books 
he  expounds  the  views  of  Bossuet  and  Leibniz  on  history ;  in  the  second,  those  of 
Vico,  Montesquieu,  Voltaire  and  Rousseau,  Turgot,  Herder,  and  Condorcet ;  and 
in  the  third,  those  of  the  Catholic  school,  and  of  what  he  calls  "  the  German 
school "  and  "  the  Contemporary  school."  His  knowledge  of  the  history  which 
he  has  undertaken  to  trace  is  obviously  inadequate.  One  page  is  all  that  he 
assigns  to  Auguste  Comte ;  and  Fr.  Schlegel  is  set  before  us  by  him  as  the1  repre- 
sentative of  historical  philosophy  in  Germany  during  the  nineteenth  century. 
At  the  same  time  his  book  is  written  in  an  agreeable  style,  and  is  substantial  and 
satisfactory  in  most  of  its  parts.  Its  faults  are  chiefly  of  omission.  M.  Lavollee 
thinks  that  four  great  laws  have  been  discovered  and  formulated  by  the  philoso- 
phy of  history :  "  the  absence  of  chance  in  the  concatenation  of  facts;  the  unity 
of  the  human  race  ;  the  continuity  of  events  and  of  beings;  and  the  perfectibility 
of  man  and  the  continuous  progress  to  which  history  testifies,"  pp.  382,  383. 


CHAPTER   IX 

THE   DEMOCRATIC    HISTORICAL   SCHOOL 


France  has  become  a  democratic  country  within  a  com- 
paratively short  period.  For  many  ages  it  was  ruled  by 
princes  almost  or  entirely  independent  of  the  kings  from 
whom  they  held  their  fiefs.  Then  it  was  slowly  transformed 
into  the  most  centralised  and  absolute  of  monarchies.  It  was 
not  until  the  eighteenth  century  that  public  spirit  and  national 
consciousness  were  so  developed  that  there  could  properly  be 
said  to  be  a  French  people,  as  well  as  a  French  State.  The 
spirit  of  democracy  in  France,  —  the  feeling  of  the  French 
people  of  its  own  unity  and  of  its  right  to  govern  itself, — 
first  became  practically  and  conspicuously  apparent  in  the 
Revolution  of  1789.  It  was  crushed  and  flattered,  used  and 
abused,  by  Buonaparte.  It  had  under  the  reign  of  Charles 
X.  distinguished  representatives, —  a  man  like  Lafayette, 
orators  like  Foy  and  Manuel,  a  publicist  like  Carrel,  poets 
like  Bdranger  and  Delavigne,  and  an  historian  like  Sismondi. 
Under  Louis  Philippe  these  multiplied  into  a  host.  One  of 
the  first  acts  of  the  Provisional  Government  of  1848  was  to 
decree  universal  suffrage;  and  neither  the  Second  Empire 
nor  any  of  the  Governments  which  have  succeeded  it,  has 
ventured  to  revoke  or  restrict  the  right  thus  conferred,  al- 
though it  is  only  since  the  re-establishment  of  the  Republic 
that  there  has  been  full  freedom  in  exercising  the  right.  At 
the  present  day  no  European  country  is  more  democratic  than 
France. 

In  this  chapter  I  shall  endeavour  to  show  how  history  has 
been  exhibited  and  interpreted  by  some  of  the  advocates  of 
democracy  most  distinguished  for  historical  insight.  In 
doing  so  I  shall  refer,  so  far  as  is  necessary,  to  the  theories 

529 


530  PHILOSOPHY  OP  HISTOKY  IK  FRANCE 

of  those  who  have  sought  to  defend  by  historical  considera- 
tions the  cause  either  of  imperialism  or  of  aristocracy,  and  to 
discredit  that  of  democracy. 

Democracy  had  two  fearless,  zealous,  and  brilliant  cham- 
pions in  Jules  Michelet  and  Edgar  Quinet.  The  name  of 
either  can  hardly  be  pronounced  without  recalling  that  of  the 
other,  as  for  half  a  century  they  were  close  companions  in 
arms,  and  intimately  bound  to  each  other  by  joy,  sorrow,  and 
labour,  the  same  triumphs  and  defeats,  the  same  convictions 
and  hopes.  Their  lives  were  so  associated  that  death  could 
not  separate  their  memories. 

M.  Michelet  was  born  at  Paris  in  1798.  His  parents  were 
poor,  and  he  was  inured  in  youth  to  privation  and  labour; 
but  they  were  too  noble  to  sacrifice  his  future  to  their  own 
interests,  and  so  he  was  sent  to  the  Lyceum  instead  of  being 
apprenticed  to  a  trade.  He  showed  extraordinary  aptitude 
for  study.  At  the  age  of  twenty-three  he  was  appointed  a 
professor  of  history  and  philosophy  in  the  College  Rollin,  and 
began  to  display  that  marvellous  power  of  influencing  and 
impassioning  youth  which  he  afterwards  exercised  in  more 
conspicuous  positions. 

His  first  important  publications  appeared  in  1827.  One  of 
them  was  merely  a  summary  and  the  other  only  a  translation. 
But  the  summary, '  Precis  d'histoire  moderne, '  was  one  which 
only  a  true  historian  of  exceptional  knowledge  and  still  more 
exceptional  insight,  a  man  of  genius  with  the  powers  of  a 
great  literary  artist,  could  have  made.  And  the  translation 
was  still  more  important.  By  his  '  Principes  de  la  philoso- 
phic de  l'histoire,  traduites  de  la  Scienza  Nuova  de  Vico,' 
Michelet  may  almost  be  said  to  have  made  the  great  Neapol- 
itan philosopher  known  to  France,  and,  indeed,  helped  con- 
siderably to  make  him  known  to  all  the  rest  of  Europe,  Italy 
excepted.  The  dissertation  prefixed  to  the  volume  gave  a 
decidedly  truer  estimate  of  Vico's  position  in  the  history  of 
speculation,  of  his  merits  and  services,  than  had  ever  been 
given  before.1 

1  "Michelet,"  I  have  elsewhere  said,  "most  wisely  renounced  the  idea  of  a 
literal  rendering,  and  applied  himself  to  reproduce  with  faithfulness  and  vivid- 


MICHBLET  531 

The  mind  of  M.  Michelet  was  naturally  much  influenced 
by  his  study  of  the  '  Scienza  Nuova, '  one  of  the  profoundest, 
greatest  of  books, —  the  philosophical  complement  of  Dante's 
'  Divina  Commedia.'  "I  am  born,"  he  said,  "of  Virgil  and 
of  Vico."  Vico  taught  him  that  divine  ideas  are  manifested 
through  human  actions ;  that  the  providence  of  God  permeates 
the  world  of  nations ;  that  the  idea  of  God  is  the  productive 
and  conservative  principle,  of  civilisation ;  that  as  is  the  re- 
ligion of  a  community,  so  will  be,  in  the  main,  its  morals, 
its  laws,  its  general  history:  and  all  such  truth  as  this  he 
eagerly  imbibed,  notwithstanding  that  he  had  drunk,  even 
too  deeply,  of  the  wine  of  Voltaire. 

He  presented  his  work  on  Vico  to  Cousin ;  and  it  was  at 
the  house  of  Cousin  that  he  first  met  Quinet,  who,  by  a  curi- 
ous coincidence,  had  shortly  before  presented  to  the  chief  of 
the  eclectic  school  a  translation  of  Herder's  'Ideas  towards  a 
Philosophy  of  the  History  of  Mankind. '  They  were  drawn 
to  each  other  at  once  as  by  a  moral  magnetism.  They  had 
already  become  engrossed  in  the  same  subjects,  and  were 
dealing  with  them  in  the  same  spirit.  Their  principles, 
their  aspirations,  their  intellectual  interests,  their  moral 
sympathies,  their  tastes,  were  in  full  accordance.  While 
both  were  men  of  genius  and  of  strong  will,  finely  cultured, 
widely  learned,  poetical,  imaginative,  of  delicate  emotional 
susceptibility,  and  ardently  patriotic,  yet  the  gifts  of  each 
were  so  distinct,  the  individuality  of  each  so  marked,  that 
rivalry  between  them  was  impossible. 

The  philosophy  of  Vico  is  a  generalisation  of  the  history 
of  Rome ;  and  hence  the  student  of  Vico  must  have  the  his- 
tory of  Rome  always  before  his  mind.  Not  unnaturally, 
therefore,  we  find  Michelet  visiting  Rome  in  1830,  and  pub- 
lishing in  1831  an  '  Histoire  romaine. '  It  is  a  work  in  which 
inaccuracies  are  not  difficult  to  discover;  yet  one  which 
shows  a  great  power  of  divination  and  peculiar  charms  of 
style.     In  the  same  year  appeared  his  '  Introduction  a  l'his- 

ness  the  substance  and  spirit  of  his  author.  He  so  succeeded  that  the  great 
majority  even  of  persons  capable  of  reading  the  original  will  find  it  much  more 
profitable  to  read  his  translation,  itself  a  work  of  genius.  It  has  its  defects  and 
inaccuracies,  but  to  emphasise  these  (as  many  critics  have  done)  is  not  only  un- 
generous but  unjust."  — '  Vico,'  p.  230. 


532  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FKANCE 

toire  universelle. '  It  is  the  work  of  his  which  has  most  inter- 
est for  us  in  our  present  research ;  and  I  shall  soon  return  to  it. 
In  1833  he  began  the  publication  of  the  magnum  opus  of 
his  life,  his  '  Histoire  de  France.'  In  the  following  year, 
Guizot  appointed  him  his  substitute  in  the  Chair  of  History 
at  the  Faculte"  des  Lettres.  At  this  time,  and  for  several 
years  after,  his  mind  was  much  under  the  influence  of  Gui- 
zot's  historical  views.  He  speaks  of  him  as  his  "  illustrious 
master  and  friend ; "  he  it  was,  he  says  in  the  preface  (of 
1833)  to  the  '  History  of  France, '  who  taught  him  to  "  trace 
the  course  of  ideas  underneath  the  course  of  events  '* ;  he  it 
was,  he  says  in  his  Inaugural  Discourse  at  the  Sorbonne, 
who,  "freeing  science  from  all  ephemeral  passions,  all  par- 
tiality, all  falsehood  of  matter  and  style,  raised  history  to  the 
dignity  of  law."1  In  1838  he  was  appointed  to  the  Chair  of 
History  and  Morals  at  the  College  of  France.     The  volumes 

1  M.  Miehelet  published  in  1837  a  work  on  which  he  himself  set  a  high  value, 
but  in  which  there  is  a  good  deal  that  is  of  a  rather  whimsical  character,— 
'  Origines  du  droit  francais  cherchees  dans  les  symboles  et  les  formules  du 
droit  universel.'  It  was  designed  to  show  how  laws  were  developed  by  society 
in  their  earliest  shape,  when  the  processes  of  thought  which  they  contain  were 
latent  in  symbols,  in  significant  imagery.  Its  central  idea  was  derived  from 
Vico,  and  a  considerable  portion  of  its  materials  from  the  stores  of  erudition  of 
Jacob  Grimm.  The  following  passage  of  the  preface  gives  a  general  conception 
of  its  philosophy:  "There  are  two  questions  with  respect  to  legal  symbols— 
their  nationality  and  their  age.  The  latter  is  of  difficult  decision.  It  has  been 
well  said  that  there  are  three  ages  in  history;  the  sacred,  the  heroic,  and  the 
human,  or,  in  other  words,  the  sacerdotal,  the  military,  and  the  critical.  In 
the  first  age  law  appears  as  a  substance,  as  an  immovable  symbol ;  in  the  second 
as  an  act;  in  the  third  as  an  intention.  But  generally  one  nation  expresses 
strongly  only  one  of  these  three.  Thus,  among  Asiatic  peoples,  India  represents 
the  sacred  age,  Persia  the  heroic  age,  and  Judea  the  human  or  critical  age.  It 
is  not  always  easy  to  determine  to  what  age  a  symbol  should  be  referred.  One 
may  generally  recognise  clearly  enough  a  sacerdotal  or  heroic  character;  but 
rarely  can  one  assign  dates  to  symbols.  Their  origin  was  so  natural  and  so 
necessary  that  they  seemed  to  have  existed  always.  Whilst  they  were  in  use 
they  were  unregarded,  and  as  soon  as  they  became  obsolete  they  were  forgotten. 
But  that  which  renders  it  specially  difficult  to  fix  the  age  of  symbols  is,  that 
such  a  particular  symbol,  such  a  poetic  fact,  which  might  naturally  be  attributed 
to  a  very  ancient  epoch,  is  discovered  in  modern  barbarism.  .  .  .  We  have 
studied  the  juridical  symbol  under  the  two  points  of  view  of  its  age  and  its 
nationality,  which  diversify  it  infinitely.  Nevertheless,  whatever  variety  may 
be  discovered,  unity  predominates.  It  is  an  imposing  spectacle  to  find  the 
principal  legal  symbols  common  to  all  countries,  throughout  all  ages.  .  .  .  Unlike 
the  sceptic  Montaigne,  who  so  curiously  ferreted  out  the  customs  of  different 
nations  to  detect  their  moral  discordances,  I  have  found  a  consentaneous  harmony 
among  them  all." 


MICHELBT  533 

of  his  '  History  of  France  '  appeared  in  regular  succession  till 
1844  —  the  sixth  volume,  which  was  published  in  that  year, 
closing  with  the  reign  of  Louis  XI.  These  six  volumes  are 
the  most  perfect  portion  of  his  historical  writings.  In  them 
we  find  an  historical  philosophy  on  the  whole  sound,  wedded 
to  an  art  of  historical  painting  the  most  wonderful,  and 
producing  a  true  resuscitation  of  the  past,  both  in  body  and 
spirit.  They  are  the  creations  of  a  subtle,  varied,  powerful 
imagination,  working  patiently  on  all  the  data  which  a  vast 
erudition  could  supply,  and  under  the  guidance  of  elevated 
and  comprehensive  ideas.  They  are  free  from  all  traces  of 
party  bias  and  sectarian  passion ;  just  towards  all  classes  and 
institutions  of  medieval  France.  They  exhibit  the  life  and 
mind  of  the  people  in  each  age,  their  hopes  and  anxieties, 
enthusiasms  and  sorrows,  with  a  distinctness  and  vividness 
far  superior  to  all  former  histories.  If  they  show  that  their 
author  had  certain  prejudices,  these  do  not  much  affect  the 
accuracy  of  his  narrative.  Generalisations  so  abound  that 
many  may  be  doubtful,  but  all  are  suggestive. 

Instead  of  proceeding  uninterruptedly  with  the  publication 
of  his  '  History  of  France, '  Michelet  made  a  gigantic  leap  for- 
wards from  the  age  of  Louis  XL  to  the  French  Revolution, 
the  history  of  which  appeared,  in  seven  volumes,  between 
1847  and  1853.  The  reason  which  he  himself  gives  for  this 
is  that  he  felt  he  could  not  comprehend  the  monarchical  ages 
without  establishing  in  himself  the  soul  and  faith  of  the  peo- 
ple. Another  reason,  doubtless,  was  that  the  French  Revo- 
lution had  become  the  burning  topic  of  the  day;  and  still 
another,  that  he  and  Quinet  had  become  engaged  in  a  severe 
struggle  with  the  priest  party  on  the  question  of  the  freedom 
of  university  teaching,  and  were  opposing  the  Revolution  to 
Ultramontanism.  The  assailants,  Veuillot  and  his  coadju- 
tors, were  characteristically  violent  and  unscrupulous  in 
their  attacks ;  and  the  assailed,  not  content  to  stand  merely 
on  the  defensive,  turned  on  their  foes,  and  exposed  their 
cause  and  aims  by  lectures  on  "  The  Jesuits, "  and  "  Ultra- 
montanism" (Quinet),  and  on  "Priests,  Women,  and  Fami- 
lies" (Michelet),  and  kindred  themes.  The  excitement 
produced  was  immense.     The  Government,  represented  by 


534  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Guizot  and  Salvandy,  vainly  tried  at  first  to  control  the 
storm,  and  then  suppressed  the  courses  of  the  two  belligerent 
professors.  Michelet  was  suspended  from  his  office  in  1847. 
It  was  under  the  influence  of  the  feelings  natural  to  this 
struggle  with  the  priests  and  the  doctrinarian  ministers  of 
State,  that,  abandoning  for  a  time  the  older  history  of  France, 
he  threw  himself  into  the  study  of  the  French  Revolution. 
The  result  was  a  great  work,  which  represents  the  inner 
movement,  the  emotional  life  of  the  time,  in  a  succession  of 
pictures  as  remarkable,  from  an  artistic  point  of  view,  as 
those  in  which  Carlyle  has  represented  its  outward  move- 
ment, its  external  agitation.  The  whole  soul  of  the  author 
is  in  it.  It  glows  through  every  page.  Of  all  histories  of 
the  Revolution,  Michelet's  is  the  warmest  and  most  ani- 
mated, the  most  engrossing  and  exciting.  Yet  it  lacks 
order,  comprehensiveness,  and  evidence ;  does  not  give  a  con- 
tinuous and  full  account  of  the  facts,  and  rarely  indicates 
proofs  even  where  they  are  most  needed.  Although  no  one 
doubts  that  it  was  preceded  by  an  eager  and  laborious  inves- 
tigation of  the  sources,  it  contains  numerous  inaccuracies. 
In  every  volume  there  are  not  only  the  most  masterly  pic- 
tures, flashes  of  insight  which  certify  their  own  truth,  keen 
and  fine  psychological  observations,  and  all  the  marks  of  a 
rare  genius  and  a  rich  humanity,  but  also  numerous  and 
manifest  traces  of  caprice,  of  morbid  susceptibility,  and  of 
prejudice.  The  unquestionable  sincerity  of  Michelet  did 
not  prevent  his  showing  himself  in  this  work  lamentably 
unjust.  His  hatred  of  England  led  him  into  only  a  few 
erroneous  judgments :  his  hatred  of  the  priest  caused  him  to 
take  an  utterly  false  view  of  the  Revolution  as  a  whole,  and 
to  represent  it  as  essentially  opposed  to  Christianity,  and 
itself  the  appropriate  object  of  a  higher  worship.  Most  of 
the  prominent  actors  in  the  Revolution  who  did  not  belong 
to  the  '  Mountain  '  are  treated  by  him  ungenerously.  The 
venality  and  other  faults  of  Mirabeau  are  extenuated.  The 
crimes  of  Danton  are  sought  to  be  explained  away,  imaginary- 
merits  are  assigned  to  him,  and  his  faculties  and  character 
immoderately  glorified.  Michelet  claims  to  have  been  the 
first  to  write  the  history  of  the  Revolution  from  the  point  of 
view  "not  of  any  party  or  man,  the  Constituents,  Girondists, 


JI1CHELET  535 

or  Robespierre,  but  from  that  of  the  principal  actor,  the 
anonymous  hero,  the  people."  And  there  is  a  considerable 
measure  of  truth  in  the  claim.  Love  to  the  people  was  his 
predominant  passion,  and  it  inspires  every  page  of  his  his- 
tory of  the  Revolution.  He  has  continuously  tried  to  con- 
sider the  Revolution  in  relation  to  the  people,  and  has  often 
succeeded  in  this  better  than  his  predecessors  had  done.  He 
has  not  attributed  it  to  a  party  to  the  same  extent  as  Lamar- 
tine  attributed  it  to  the  Girondists,  or  identified  it  with  a 
man  as  fully  as  Louis  Blanc  idehtified  it  with  Robespierre. 
Nevertheless  he  has  by  no  means  made  good  his  promise. 
He  has  generally  conceived  of  and  represented  the  people  in 
a  sectarian  and  partisan  way ;  as  the  poor  in  opposition  to 
the  rich.  To  justify  the  people  he  has  palliated  the  crimes 
of  sanguinary  ruffians.  To  personify  the  people  he  has  con- 
verted into  an  idol  the  memory  of  the  demagogue  who  en- 
couraged the  perpetrators  of  the  massacres  of  September,  who 
instigated  the  creation  of  the  Revolutionary  tribunal,  and  who 
did  more  even  than  Robespierre  to  transform  the  Revolution 
into  the  Terror. 

The  Revolution  of  1848  restored  Michelet  to  his  professor- 
ship for  a  short  time,  but  he  was  again  silenced  in  1851. 
After  the  coup  d'Stat  he  refused  to  take  the  oaths  of  alle- 
giance to  Louis  Napoleon,  and  was,  in  consequence,  dismissed 
from  his  offices.  In  1855  he  resumed  his  'History  of  France  ' 
at  where  he  had  left  off,  and  carried  it  on  to  where  his  'His- 
tory of  the  Revolution '  began,  eleven  volumes  filling  up  the 
intervening  void.  These  volumes  show  no  decrease  of  tal- 
ent. They  abound  in  original  and  lucid  views.  Many  of 
their  pages  are  beautiful  and  precious,  and  even  those  which 
offend  us  interest  us.  But  they  also  show  us  their  author, 
instead  of  correcting  his  faults,  persisting  in  them  and  add- 
ing to  them.  He  continues  to  leave  his  authorities  unindi- 
cated;  he  gives  himself  up  still  more  to  divinations,  often 
baseless  and  fanciful ;  he  judges  persons  more  according  to 
his  likes  and  dislikes,  and  explains  events  more  by  referring 
them  to  trivial  causes ;  at  times  even  he  makes  very  infelici- 
tous applications  of  sickly  and  semi-prurient  conceptions, 
akin  to  those  which  he  has  expounded  in  "L'Amour"  and 
"LaFemme." 


536  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   PRANCE 

I  need  not  speak  of  Michelet's  incomparable  prose  poems 
on  "The  Bird,"  "The  Insect,"  "The  Sea,"  and  "The  Moun- 
tain." His  '  Bible  de  rhumanite", '  1865,  concerns  us  more, 
yet  need  not  detain  us.  Each  great  civilisation  is  regarded 
as  a  verse  written  by  the  life  of  a  people  in  a  universal,  eter- 
nal, ever-advancing  Bible,  or  gospel  of  humanity.  India, 
Persia,  Egypt,  Judea,  Greece,  Rome,  Christianity,  are  delin- 
eated as  stages  of  this  revelation  of  reason  and  justice ;  and 
are  set  before  us  in  a  series  of  pictures  loosely  strung 
together.  Some  of  these  pictures,  as,  e.g.,  those  of  India, 
Persia,  and  Greece,  are  beautiful  and  moderately  accurate; 
but  none  of  them  presuppose  in  their  composition  sustained 
labour  or  comprehensive  reflection.  Christianity  is  poorly 
described,  and  is,  indeed,  caricatured.  The  Stoic  is  exalted 
above  the  Christian.  Men  are  exhorted  to  turn  their  backs 
on  the  mystic  ideas  which  religions  present  to  them,  and  to 
put  their  trust  in  science,  industry,  and  moral  enlightenment. 

In  the  last  years  of  his  life  Michelet  was  occupied  with 
the  history  of  France  in  the  nineteenth  century.  He  died  on 
the  9th  of  February  1874. 1 

I  return  to  the  work  in  which  he  has  presented  his  histori- 
cal philosophy  in  its  most  general  form — the  'Introduction 
to  Universal  History.'  It  belongs  to  the  period  of  his 
spiritual  health,  when  Vico  and  Guizot  had  great  influence 
over  his  mind,  although  he  had  a  faith  in  progress  unknown 
to  Vico,  and  democratic  sympathies  which  Guizot  never  felt. 
It  is  brief,  unlaboured;  it  touches  only  the  summits  of  things, 
aims  merely  at  fixing  the  positions  which  the  chief  nations 
of  the  world  have  occupied,  or  still  occupy,  in  the  history  of 
humanity.  When  its  author  says  that  he  might  as  well  have 
entitled  it  an  '  Introducion  to  the  History  of  France,'  because 
"  logic  and  history  "  have  proved  to  him  that  his  "gjorious 
country  is  henceforth  the  pilot  of  the  vessel  of  humanity," 
and  assures  us  that  patriotism  has  had  no  share  in  his  reach- 
ing this  conclusion,  we  can  only  smile  at  his  naivete",  and 
suggest  that  France  may  find  quite  enough  to  do  in  steering 
her  own  bark. 

1  Michelet,  'Ma  Jeunesse';  Gabriel  Monot),  'Jules  Michelet,'  1875;  Jules 
Simon,  '  Notice  historique  sur  M.  Michelet,'  1877. 


MICHELBT  537 

The  point  of  view  from  which  Michelet  surveys  universal 
history  had  been  previously  occupied  by  Hegel.  What  he 
sees  is  in  great  part  what  Hegel  had  seen,  as  it  is  in  great 
part  what  every  eye  must  see  which  looks  from  the  same  posi- 
tion. Whether  or  not  he  borrowed  from  Hegel  I  cannot  ven- 
ture to  determine.  His  book  appeared  in  the  year  in  which 
Hegel  died;  but  at  that  date  Hegel's  views  on  the  course  of 
history  were  only  known  to  the  public  by  a  very  brief  and 
dry  summar}'  of  them  in  his  '  Grundlinien  der  Philosophie 
des  Eechts,'  published  in  1821.  If  we  compare  Michelet'.s 
essay  with  that  summary  we  must  fail,  I  believe,  to  find  in 
any  sentence  of  the  former  a  reflection  or  echo  of  any  expres- 
sion in  the  latter.  And  we  cannot  reasonably  compare  it 
with  any  of  the  works  in  which  Hegel's  views  on  history 
were  more  fully  expounded,  as  these  were  all  posthumous 
publications.  His  '  Philosophie  der  Geschichte '  first  ap- 
peared in  1837. 

The  real  inspirer  of  Michelet  with  the  conception  that  his- 
tory is  the  progressive  development  of  freedom  was  very 
probably  his  friend  Quinet,  to  whom  it  had  occurred  when 
occupied  with  the  translation  of  Herder,  as  being  a  funda- 
mental truth  overlooked  by  that  author.  In  the  '  Introduc- 
tion '  to  his  translation,  published  in  1825  (i.e.,  four  years 
later  than  Hegel's  '  Philosophie  des  Rechts,'  and  six  years 
earlier  than  Michelet's  essay),  Quinet  gave  eloquent  expres- 
sion to  his  opinion  that  Herder  required  to  be  thus  corrected ; 
and  that,  to  use  his  own  words,  "  History  is,  from  beginning 
to  end,  the  drama  of  liberty,  the  protest  of  the  human  race 
against  the  world  which  enchains  it,  the  triumph  of  the  infi- 
nite over  the  finite,  the  freedom  of  the  spirit,  the  reign  of 
the  soul."  This  view  Quinet  certainly  did  not  derive  from 
a  knowledge  of  Hegel,  but  from  dissatisfaction  with  Herder. 
As  he  had  it,  however,  and  expressed  it  with  the  utmost 
clearness,  at  the  date  mentioned,  there  seems  to  be  no  reason 
for  supposing  that  Michelet  got  it  from  any  one  else.  Hegel 
must  be  credited  with  the  priority  of  conception ;  but  there 
is  no  warrant  for  regarding  Quinet  or  Michelet  as  indebted 
to  him  for  the  conception. 

At  the  outset  of  the  work  now  under  consideration,  Miche- 


538  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

let  declares  history  to  be  the  story  of  the  interminable  war 
between  man  and  nature,  between  the  spirit  and  matter, 
liberty  and  fatality.  He  laments  that  the  doctrine  of  fatal- 
ism is  taking  possession  of  science,  philosophy,  and  history.1 
Pronouncing  that  doctrine  pernicious  in  history  as  else- 
where, he  undertakes  to  show  that,  notwithstanding  many 
appearances  to  the  contrary,  history  is  the  progressive  tri- 
umph of  liberty.  Nature,  he  says,  remains  always  the  same, 
but  man  changes  for  the  better.  The  Alps  have  not  in- 
creased, but  we  have  made  a  path  across  the  Simplon.  The 
winds  and  wayes  are  as  capricious  as  ever,  but  steam  has  ren- 
dered us  independent  of  their  caprices.  If,  following  the 
course  of  the  sun  and  the  magnetic  currents,  we  proceed  from 
east  to  west,  from  India  to  France,  the  fatal  power  of  nature 
will  be  found  showing  itself  less  at  each  station. 

Michelet  starts  with  India,  and  describes  man  as  there 
utterly  overpo.vered  by  nature  —  as  like  a  feeble  child  on  its 
mother's  breast,  alternately  spoiled  and  beaten,  and  intoxi- 
cated rather  than  nourished  by^  a  milk  too  strong  and  stimu- 
lating for  it.2  He  passes  onwards  to  show  us  Persia  as  the 
country  in  which  liberty  commences  to  manifest  itself  in 
fatality.  The  Persian  discards  with  hatred  the  Hindu  mul- 
tiplicity of  gods,  and  takes  refuge  in  the  thought  of  a  divine 
power  of  pure  and  intellectual  light  which  will  eventually 
conquer  the  principle  of  darkness  and  matter.  The  next 
stage  is  Egypt.  The  very  soil  of  Egypt  is  the  gift  of  the 
Nile,  and  the  Egyptian  necessarily  felt  himself  entirely 
dependent  on  nature,  yet,  thanks  to  his  faith  in  the  immor- 
tality of  the  soul,  he  did  not  wholly  sacrifice  to  it  .his  per- 

1  In  a  note  he  expressly  exempts  Guizot  from  the  reproach  of  favouring  the 
belief  in  historical  fatalism.  He  afterwards  concurred  with  Quinet  in  represent- 
ing him  as  specially  censurable  on  this  ground. 

2  Michelet  is  like  Hegel  in  following  the  course  of  the  sun,  but  unlike  him  in 
starting  with  India  instead  of  China.  But  why,  we  naturally  ask,  pass  over 
China,  which  is  still  farther  east  than  India?  Is  it  not  because  man  is  less 
enslaved  in  China  than  in  India,  less  the  victim  either  of  superstition  or  of 
despotism  ?  If  so,  the  course  of  history  fails  at  its  very  outset  to  coincide  with 
the  course  of  the  sun.  We  naturally  ask  also,  Why  should  the  course  of  history 
coincide  with  the  course  of  the  sun?  How  comes  it  that  freedom  should  follow 
the  same  path  with  an  object  the  movement  of  which  is  mechanically  necessitated  ? 
Is  freedom,  then,  but  an  appearance,  and  really  subject  to  fatality?  How  is  it 
that  there  is  even  an  appearance  of  such  subjection?  Michelet  gives  no  answer 
to  these  questions. 


MICHELET  539 

sonality;  the  aspirations  crushed  in  this  world  betook 
themselves  to  another.  Human  liberty  next  pursues  its 
course  from  Egypt  to  Judea  —  which  is  placed  in  the  East 
only  to  curse  it  and  all  its  creeds  in  the  name  of  unity  and 
the  spirit.  Among  the  Jews  nature  is  dethroned  in  the 
sphere  of  religion,  and  God  is  recognised  as  apart  from  and 
ahove  nature.1 

Proceeding  with  his  argument,  our  author  points  out  that 
Asia  is  a  comparatively  uniform  mass :  that  Europe  is  vastly 
more  articulated;  that  it  is  consequently  more  perfectly 
organised;  and  that  it  shows  its  superiority  by  a  higher 
development  of  freedom.  He  compares  and  contrasts  Greece 
and  Rome  with  Asia  and  with  each  other.  Much  as  both 
did  —  beautiful  as  was  the  one,  and  sublime  and  strong  as 
was  the  other  —  they  left  the  arts  of  peace  to  the  conquered 
and  enslaved,  and  so  that  victory  of  man  over  nature  which 
is  called  industry  was  pursued  by  them  but  a  little  way. 
Rome  dreamed  that  she  had  subdued  the  world  and  succeeded 
in  building  up  a  universal  and  eternal  city;  but  the  slave, 
the  barbarian,  and  the  Christian  protested  each  in  their  own 
way  that  she  was  deceived,  and  each  in  their  own  way  con- 
tributed to  destroy  the  delusive  unity  which  bore  her  name. 
While  she  dreamed,  her  physical  and  moral  dissolution  has- 
tened on ;  Greece  and  Asia,  whom  she  had  vanquished  by  her 
arms,  invaded  and  conquered  her  by  their  beliefs.  Among 
the  religions  which  reached  her  from  Asia  was  one  profoundly 
different  from  the  rest;  one  which  immolated  the  flesh  and 
glorified  the  spirit,  while  the  others  immersed  and  defiled 
man  in  matter.  It  —  Christianity  —  is  still  the  only  refuge 
of  a  religious  soul.  "  L'autel  a  perdu  ses  honneurs,  l'huma- 
nite'  s'en  eloigne  peu  a  peu;  mais,  je  vous  en  prie,  oh!  dites- 
le  moi,  si  vous  le  saves,  s'est-il  eleve"  un  autre  autel?" 

After  referring  to  the  barbarian  invasions,  the  kingdom  of 
Charlemagne,  the  Crusades,  the  medieval  organisation  of  the 
Church  or  empire  of  the  spirit,  and  of  the  State  or  empire 
of  force,  and  affirming  that  the  Me,  liberty,  the  heroic  prin- 

1  Michelet  wisely  overlooks  the  fact  that  Judea  is  not  situated  to  the  west  of 
Egypt.  He  wisely  lets  go  consistency,  and  so  escapes  erring  like  Hegel,  who, 
rather  than  allow  that  freedom  could  run  in  any  other  than  a  straight  line,  made 
Palestine  an  appendage  of  Persia. 


540  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

ciple  of  the  world,  has  slowly  but  gradually  triumphed,  as  is 
evident  alike  in  science,  religion,  and  industry,  Michelet 
proceeds  to  show  what  part  the  political  persons  named  Ger- 
many, Italy,  England,  and  France,  have  taken  in  the  enfran- 
chisement of  the  human  race.  This  is  much  the  most  carefully 
executed  portion  of  his  work,  and  it  is  illustrated  and  sup- 
plemented by  very  interesting  notes. 

He  starts  with  the  thought  that  Europe  is  a  complex  organ- 
ism, of  which  the  unity,  soul,  and  life  are  not  in  this  or  that 
part,  but  in  the  disposition  or  relationship  and  interaction  of 
its  parts,  so  that  any  one  part,  any  one  of  its  peoples,  is  only 
to  be  understood  through  the  others.  Then  he  delineates  the 
character  of  Germany  as  it  has  expressed  itself  in  history, 
literature,  and  manners.  The  renunciation  of  self,  the  devo- 
tion of  man  to  man  and  of  man  to  woman,  sympathy,  inde- 
cision, mysticism,  pantheism,  —  these  are,  he  thinks,  its  chief 
features.  Germany  is  "the  India  of  Europe,  vast,  vague, 
unsettled,  prolific,  like  the  pantheistic  Proteus,  its  god." 

The  Italian  genius  he  regards  as  forming  in  almost  all 
respects  a  contrast  to  the  German ;  as  not  less  strongly  and 
persistently  individual  and  independent  than  the  other  is  soft 
and  easily  disciplined.  The  Italian  cannot  consent  to  sacri- 
fice his  personality  even  to  God,  and  much  less  to  man ;  he 
is  capable  of  the  highest  devotion  to  a  definite  cause  or  inter- 
est, but  not  to  an  individual,  nor  in  the  service  of  a  vague 
idea  or  feeling.  He  is  the  man  of  the  city,  not  of  the  family, 
or  tribe,  or  country.  Politics,  jurisprudence,  art  of  the  kind 
which  is  passionate  yet  severe,  are  the  departments  in  which 
he  excels.  Michelet  insists  strongly  on  the  perpetuity  of  the 
Italian  character,  its  essential  identity  in  ancient  and  modern 
times.  He  maintains  that  the  German  influence  on  it  has 
been  but  external  and  superficial ;  and  that  the  inhabitants 
of  the  different  districts  of  Italy  still  display  the  same  pecu- 
liarities of  talent  and  disposition  by  which  they  were  distin- 
guished in  the  days  of  the  Roman  Republic. 

In  Germany  and  Italy,  he  goes  on  to  say,  fatality  is  still 
strong ;  moral  freedom  is  still  borne  down  by  the  powerful 
influences  of  race,  locality,  and  climate ;  in  both,  races  and 
ideas  are  imperfectly  or  unequally  mixed.  The  civilisation 
which  is  the  least  simple  and  natural,  the  most  complex  and 


MICHELET  541 

artificial,  the  most  European,  the  most  human  and  free,  is 
that  of  France.  France  is  much  more  a  person  than  Ger- 
many or  Italy,  better  organised,  greatly  more  centralised,  — 
indeed,  France  only  has  a  true  centre  and  head.  French 
genius  is  essentially  social  and  active;  its  bent  is  towards 
war,  politics,  argument.  What  it  seeks  in  war  is  not  selfish 
gain  but  proselytism,  the  assimilation  of  intelligences,  the 
conquest  of  wills.  In  literature  it  displays  itself  to  most 
advantage  in  rhetoric  and  eloquence;  it  is  unequalled  in 
prose,  but  deficient  in  poetical  feeling.  The  spirit  of  the 
French  people  is  profoundly  democratic,  and  has  always  been 
so  in  a  large  measure. 

England  is  the  antithesis  of  France,  and  explains  France 
by  contrast.  England  is  "  human  pride  personified  in  a  peo- 
ple." Its  pride  punishes  itself  by  internal  self-contradiction, 
the  antagonism  of  feudalism  and  industry,  two  powers  which 
agree  only  in  an  insatiable  thirst  for  gain  that  leads  to  life- 
weariness  and  despair.  The  Satanic  school  is  the  most  repre- 
sentative phase  of  English  literature.  The  English  genius 
is  aristocratic  and  heroic.  England  entered  first  among 
modern  nations  into  the  field  in  the  struggle  for  liberty,  but 
has  no  real  love  of  liberty.  It  wishes  liberty  without  equal- 
ity, which  is  a  selfish  and  impious  liberty;  whereas  France 
seeks  liberty  with  equality,  which  is  alone  a  just  and  sacred 
liberty.  It  is  France,  therefore,  which  must  inaugurate  the 
coming  era  of  a  new  unity,  which  will  this  time  be  a  free 
unity.  Every  solution  either  of  social  or  intellectual  prob- 
lems is  sterile  and  unsuccessful  until  it  has  been  interpreted, 
translated,  and  popularised  by  France.  France  is  the  word 
of  Europe  as  Greece  was  of  Asia. 

Perhaps  few  of  these  positions  as  to  Germany,  Italy,  Eng- 
land, and  France  are  wholly  true;  probably  a  considerable 
number  of  them  are  not  far  from  being  wholly  false.  Yet 
if  they  had  been  all  true,  if  Michelet's  whole  book  had  been 
irreproachable  both  in  its  reasonings  and  facts,  we  would 
obviously  not  have  had  a  science  of  history  before  us,  but 
only  an  account  of  a  single  aspect  of  history,  of  one  phase 
of  its  development.  Even  that  aspect  or  phase  is  merely 
described,  not  explained.  We  are  told  that  liberty  has  pro- 
gressed from  age  to  age ;  that  nation  after  nation  has  contrib- 


542  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOPvY   IN   FRANCE 

uted  more  or  less  to  its  growth :  we  are  not  shown  the  course 
of  causation  through  which,  in  each  age  and  nation,  the 
result  has  been  brought  about.  A  line  of  thought  is  run 
through  history  just  sufficient  to  connect  the  principal  States 
which  have  risen  and  fallen  with  the  lapse  of  time,  and  the 
general  truth  is  established  that  all  the  arts  of  oppression 
have  ever  been  found  insufficient  permanently  to  prevent  the 
advance  of  liberty.  This  is  a  high  and  consoling  truth ;  one, 
it  may  well  be,  than  which  history  can  show  us  none  nobler  or 
more  precious ;  but  it  wants  the  precision  of  a  scientific  law, 
and  is  certainly  insufficient  of  itself  to  constitute  a  science. 
History  shows  us  a  progressive  realisation  of  freedom.  It 
does  not  follow  that  history  is  the  realisation  of  freedom  — 
that  and  nothing  more.  In  the  progressive  realisation  of 
freedom  there  may  be  an  historical  truth,  yet  not  the  whole 
truth  of  history,  not  the  definition  of  history.  Growth  in 
freedom  is  only  one  of  several  facts  all  equally  essential  to 
humanity  and  its  development.  Truth,  beauty,  and  morality 
can  no  more  be  resolved  into  freedom  than  freedom  into  any 
of  them.  Yet  they  belong  no  less  than  it  to  the  substance  of 
mind,  and  their  evolution  belongs  no  less  than  its  to  the  sub- 
stance of  history. 


II 

Edgar  Quinet  was  born  at  Bourg  in  1803.1  His  father,  a 
firm  republican,  devoted  to  scientific  research,  just,  inde- 
pendent, and  austere  in  character,  was  an  army  commissioner 
under  the  Republic  and  during  the  early  years  of  the  Empire. 
His  mother,  born  near  Gevena,  a  Protestant  but  of  most 
catholic  spirit,  and  a  woman  of  clear  cultured  intelligence 
and  of  rare  sweetness  and  richness  of  disposition,  was  the 
centre  of  her  son's  affections,  and  the  light  and  inspiration 

1  The  student  of  Quinet  should  consult,  in  addition  to  the  works  which  I  have 
brought  under  review,  M.  Quinet's  'Histoire  de  mes  idees,'  'Correspondence: 
Lettres  a  sa  mere,'  and  'Lettres  d'exil';  Madame  Quinet's  'Me'moires  d'exil,' 
and  '  Paris,  Journal  du  Siege ' ;  C.  L.  Chassin's  '  Edgar  Quinet,  sa  vie  et  son 
ceuvre,'  1859;  Richard  Heath's  'Edgar  Quinet,  His  Early  Life  and  Writings,' 
1881 ;  and  Prof.  Dowden's  '  Studies  in  Literature,'  1883.  It  would  be  a  valuable 
contribution  to  our  literature  if  Mr.  Heath  were  to  give  us  '  Edgar  Quinet,  His 
Later  Life  and  Writings,'  as  no  one  has  treated  of  Quinet  with  more  knowledge, 
insight,  and  sympathy  than  he  has  done. 


QUINET  543 

of  his  early  life.  Both  parents  hated  Napoleon,  and  refrained 
from  even  mentioning  his  name,  yet  their  boy  soon  became  one 
of  his  idolaters.  It  was  only  with  a  painful  struggle,  after 
he  had  reached  middle  life  and  contributed  to  create  and 
spread  the  Napoleonic  legend,  that  he  was  able  to  emancipate 
himself  from  the  tyranny  which  the  memory  of  the  Conqueror 
exercised  over  his  imagination.  He  was  educated  at  Cha- 
rolles,  Bourg,  Lyons,  and  Paris.  He  early  began  to  cultivate 
poetry,  history,  and  philosophy;  to  study  diligently  many 
subjects;  to  read  the  best  books  in  various  languages;  and 
to  form  literary  projects.  As  he  began,  so  he  continued. 
His  whole  life  was  a  course  of  self-education,  carried  on 
through  meditation,  the  study  of  books,  the  close  observation 
of  events,  and  foreign  travel.  His  pen  was  seldom  at  rest, 
and  its  products  were  very  varied  —  poems,  political  pam- 
phlets, histories,  impressions  of  travel,  philosophical  and 
theological  disquisitions,  &c. 

In  1823  an  English  translation  of  Herder's  '  Philosophy 
of  the  History  of  Humanity  '  fell  into  Quinet's  hands.  It 
led  him  to  learn  German,  and  to  translate  the  work  of  Her- 
der into  French.  This  translation  (1825-27),  prefaced  by  an 
able  Introduction,  was  his  first  publication  of  importance. 
In  1827-28  he  was  in  Germany,  and  deeply  immersed  in  the 
study  of  German  philosophy,  literature,  and  art,  intimate 
with  Creutzer,  occupied  wih  Schelling,  and  enthusiastic  over 
Tieck.  When  at  Heidelberg  in  1827  he  published  an  '  Essai 
surles  ceuvres  de  Herder.'  As  this  'Essai '  and  the  'Intro- 
duction a  la  philosophie  de  l'histoire, '  not  only  show  us  how 
thoroughly  he  had  adopted  and  assimilated  what  was  true  in 
Herder,  but  exhibit  to  us  his  own  historical  philosophy  in  a 
general  form  and  at  its  earliest  stage,  they  demand  from  us 
special  attention. 

Quinet  may  almost  be  said  to  have  found  himself  in  Her- 
der; to  have  had  himself  revealed  to  himself  by  Herder's 
book  as  in  a  mirror.  Herder  is  in  some  measure  at  the  bottom 
of  all  that  he  has  attempted  and  accomplished.  He  accepted 
Herder's  central  thoughts  as  his  principles,  Herder's  aims 
as  his  own  purposes.  He  thus  came  to  the  study  of  history 
with  the  same  comprehensive  conception  as  Herder  of  man's 
relation  to  nature  and  of  humanity  in  itself,  and  with  the 


544  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

same  catholic  spirit.     Almost  all  that  is  true  in  Herder  is 
presupposed  in  Quinet. 

But  there  was  a  weak  side,  an  element  of  error,  in  Herder. 
He  was  right  in  holding  that  all  nature  is  related  to  man, 
and  conditional  of  the  histroy  of  man;  but  wrong  in  that 
he  exaggerated  the  power  of  nature  over  man,  and  left  the 
impression  that  the  moral  world  is  only  the  product  of  the 
natural  world,  the  laws  of  history  simply  the  laws  of  nature 
manifesting  themselves  through  a  particular  organism.  Qui- 
net, however,  was  even  from  the  first  no  servile  disciple  of 
Herder,  but  a  free  critic  and  impartial  judge  as  well  as  a  dis- 
ciple, and  he  not  only  never  fell  into  this  grave  error,  but 
assigned  the  utmost  importance  to  its  antagonistic  truth. 
He  founds  on  the  truth  which  is  in  Herder,  but  at  least  as 
much  on  the  truth  which  Herder  overlooks.  Far  from 
regarding  human  history  as  merely  natural  history  (eine 
reine  Naturgeschichte),  he  insists  that  there  is  in  it  a  some- 
thing altogether  peculiar  and  distinctive  —  a  something  no- 
where found  in  nature,  but  which  struggles  against,  subdues, 
and  uses  nature.  What  this  something  is  we  know  and  can 
name,  because  we  have  it  within  us  and  can  feel  it.  It  is 
the  Will.  The  Will  which  we  are  conscious  of  in  our- 
selves, and  in  virtue  of  which  we  resist  the  force  of  circum- 
stances, the  seductions  and  oppression  of  society,  was  also  in 
our  earliest  ancestors,  to  render  them  capable  of  resisting  the 
tyranny  of  physical  nature.  When  Cato  slew  himself  in 
order  to  escape  from  a  world  where  he  could  no  longer  be  his 
own  master,  when  More,  and  Russell,  and  others  ascended 
the  scaffold  for  a  cause  which  they  deemed  worthy  of  their 
blood,  their  actions  may  have  been  more  heroic  than  that  of 
the  first  man  who,  in  the  exercise  of  his  free-will,  confronted 
unintelligent  nature,  and  strove  to  determine  his  own  future; 
but  although  different  in  form,  these  two  orders  of  action 
were  one  in  principle,  alike  springing  from  the  activity  of 
the  mind  itself.  This  internal  self-activity  is  no  prodigy 
which  heaven  creates  for  a  daj-  and  never  renews,  is  no 
special  gift  conferred  only  on  highly  favoured  individuals, 
but  what  is  most  essential  in  man  and  the  root  of  all  his 
history.  History  is  from  beginning  to  end  the  development 
and  display  of  liberty,   the  continuous  protestation  of  the 


QUINET  545 

mind  of  the  human  race  against  the  world  which  oppresses 
and  enchains  it,  the  process  through  which  the  soul  gradu- 
ally secures  and  realises  its  freedom. 

Thus  regarding  history  as  the  manifestation  of  free-will, 
Quinet  pronounces  against  subjecting  it  to  any  rigid  formula. 
Its  course  is  not  a  straight  line,  but  tortuous ;  instead  of  mov- 
ing direct  to  its  end,  it  has  gone  back  upon  itself  a  hundred 
times.  There  is,  however,  a  general  movement  which  is  on 
the  whole  upward  and  onward.  The  Me  only  gradually  dis- 
engages itself  from  the  universe  which  surrounds  it,  as  the 
sculptor  only  gradually  disengages  from  his  block  of  marble 
the  image  which  originally  existed  merely  within  himself. 
It  rejects  by  degrees  all  that  is  foreign  to  itself,  all  that  is 
contrary  to  a  complete  display  of  its  nature,  to  perfect  free- 
dom. It  progresses  in  a  path  which  is  substantially  a  vast 
and  unending  evolution  from  the  general  to  the  particular. 

Human  personality  at  first  diffuses  itself  through  the  im- 
mensities of  space  and  time,  animating  with  its  own  life  the 
-wandering  hosts  of  heaven,  the  mighty  seas,  the  teeming 
earth,  the  mountains,  forests,  and  floods.  In  this  stage  of 
his  existence  —  one  which  may  be  studied  in  India  —  man, 
embracing  all,  adoring  all,  forgetting  only  himself,  has  a 
cosmogony  and  a  theogony,  but  no  proper  history.  With- 
drawing from  the  waste  vagueness  of  the  physical  universe, 
the  spirit  then  proceeds  to  confine  itself  in  empires  —  Media, 
Persia,  Egypt,  Assyria  —  with  which  its  existence  is  so 
bound  up  that  it  has  no  individual  force  or  worth.  Another 
step,  and  personality,  although  still  half  confounded  with 
the  city  and  borrowing  thence  its  vigour,  is  seen  to  have 
gained  greatly  b}r  concentration.  With  Greece  and  Rome 
the  city  is  broken,  and  now  the  Me,  the  spirit,  alone  with 
itself,  finds  in  itself  an  infinity  surpassing  that  with  which 
it  started,  the  true  infinity,  the  Christian  universe.  This 
infinite  it  again  proceeds  to  divide,  to  analyse,  seeking  to 
explain  and  derive  it  wholly  from  its  own  self.  Hence  the 
Reformation,  Cartesianism,  the  Revolution  have  been,  and 
an  unknown  future  will  be.  Humanity  wanders  like  Ulysses 
from  land  to  land,  from  sea  to  sea,  from  adventure  to  adven- 
ture, in  quest  of  a  lost  home.  Impelled  and  guided  by  an 
invisible  hand  and  divine  instincts,  it  never  rests  long  con- 


546  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   FKANCE 

tent  in  any  dwelling-place.  India  and  China,  Babylon, 
Palmyra,  Ecbatana,  Memphis,  Athens,  Rome,  and  other 
countries  and  cities,  it  has  lodged  in  for  some  hour  of  its 
life,  some  age  of  time ;  but  finding  in  none  of  them  what  it 
sought,  it  has  forsaken  them  one  after  another,  and  is  still  in 
search  of  its  Ithaca. 

It  is  a  natural  consequence  of  Quinet's  attaching  the  im- 
portance which  he  does  to  the  fact  of  will  or  personality  in 
history,  that  he  should  strongly  insist  on  the  necessity  of 
every  man  who  would  understand  history  studying  his  own 
nature.  He  who  would  comprehend  the  life  of  a  hero,  or  of 
a  nation,  or  of  humanity,  must  seek  the  principles  of  expla- 
nation within  himself.  He  has  there  the  key  to  all  history. 
If  we  would  give  a  true  basis  to  historic  science,  we  must 
"start  from  the  narrow  sphere  of  the  individual  Me,  and 
thence  ascend,  step  by  step,  along  the  succession  of  empires 
and  peoples,  up  to  the  hut  of  Evander,  the  tent  of  Jacob,  and 
the  palm-tree  of  Zoroaster." 

In  1829,  Quinet  was  in  Greece,  as  member  of  a  scientific 
commission  sent  to  explore  the  Morea;  in  1832-33  he  travelled 
in  Italy;  and  in  1834  he  was  again  in  Germany.  Wherever 
he  went,  it  was  not  as  an  ordinary  sight-seer,  but  as  an  earn- 
est and  sympathetic  student  of  nature,  of  historical  monu- 
ments, of  literature,  of  men  and  their  ways.  The  fruits  of 
his  travels  in  the  years  indicated,  and  of  those  in  later  years, 
have  not  been  lost  to  posterity.  They  have  gone  to  enrich  a 
number  of  admirable  and  important  writings  which  have 
exercised  a  powerful  influence  on  modern  thought.  The 
writings  to  which  I  refer  have  for  their  common  aim  to  show 
the  significance  of  nationality  in  itself  and  in  relation  to 
cosmopolitanism;  to  explain  and  delineate  the  spirit  and 
characteristics  of  the  nationalities  of  Europe ;  and  to  stir  up 
in  the  peoples  of  Europe  a  sense  both  of  their  own  rights  and 
of  their  duties  to  one  another.  Nowhere  else  has  the  frater- 
nity of  nations  been  more  sympathetically  and  effectively 
inculcated.  Modern  Greece,  Roumania,  Poland,  Italy,  Spain, 
Holland,  have  good  reason  to  honour  his  name.  His  ardent 
patriotism  was  singularly  free  from  jealousy  and  exclusive- 
ness ;  his  love  of  France  only  helped  him  the  more  fully  to 


QUINET  547 

realise  the  sacredness  of  the  independence  and  rights  even  of 
the  weakest  among  the  peoples.1 

In  1839,  Quinet  became  Professor  of  Foreign  Literatures 
of  the  Faculty  of  Letters  at  Lyons ;  and  as  such  delivered, 
during  the  years  1839  and  1840,  a  course  of  lectures  on  the 
Civilisations  of  Antiquity.  It  contained  the  materials  out 
of  which  he  composed  his  '  Ge"nie  des  Religions, '  published 
in  1841.  In  this  work  he  has  carefully  developed  an  idea 
which  he  regarded  as  of  prime  importance  to  the  right  under- 
standing of  history:  the  idea  that  the  fundamental  and  gen- 
erative principle  in  civilisation  is  the  religious  principle; 
that  the  political  form  assumed  by  society  is  universally 
determined  by  its  religious  beliefs,  and  moulded  on  its  reli- 
gious institutions.  He  insists  that  what  raises  man  above 
an  animal  subject  to  mere  natural  laws  and  forces,  and  by 
uniting  man  to  man  originates  society,  is  the  apprehension 
of  divinity;  that  the  fetich  assemblies  around  it  the  tribe, 
and  a  national  god  brings  forth  a  nation ;  that  religious  unity 
founds  political  unity;  and  that  all  the  revolutions  which 
have  taken  place  in  the  social  relations  of  human  beings  have 
been  owing  to  the  modification  of  their  thoughts  about  God. 
Later  works  —  'Le  Christianisme  et  la  Revolution  frangaise, ' 
'Les  J^suites,'  'L'Ultramontanisme,'  and  'La  Revolution' 
—  are  pervaded  by  the  same  principle,  and  apply  it  to  the 
elucidation  of  medieval  and  modern  civilisation.  The  high- 
est point  of  view  from  which  the  works  of  this  group  can  be 
surveyed  collectively,  and  in  connection,  is  as  an  attempted 
demonstration  of  the  doctrine  that  the  idea  of  divinity  is  the 
root  of  civilisation,  and  the  gradual  apprehension  of  that 
idea  the  regulative  principle  of  the  history  of  civilisation. 
Quinet  was  not  the  first  to  avow  the  doctrine.  It  had  pre- 
viously found  some  measure  of  expression  through  Fichte, 
Baader,  and  Krause,  Goerres  and  Steffens,  Schelling  and 
Hegel,  &c.     To  some  extent  it  underlay  the  whole  teaching 

1  No  man  has  done  more  than  Quinet  to  delineate  and  explain  the  spirit  and 
characteristics  of  the  nationalities  of  Europe.  In  proof  it  is  sufficient  to  refer  to 
the  following  works:  in  vol.  iv.  of  his  'CEuvres  Completes,'  "Les  Revolutions 
d'ltalie; "  in  vol.  v.,  "  La  Grece  moderne,"  "  Marnix  de  Sainte  Aldegonde,"  and 
" Fondation  de  la  Republique  des  Provinces-Unies ;  "  in  fi.,  "  Les  Roumains,"  and 
"  Allemagne  et  Italie ;  "  in  ix.,  "  Mes  vacances  en  Espagne ;  "  and  in  xi.,  "  Reveil 
d'un  grand  Peuple." 


548  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOEY   IN   FBANCE 

of  the  Theocratic  School.  It  first  received  from  Quinet,  how- 
ever, its  adequate  historical  proof  and  illustration. 

In  1841,  he  was  transferred  from  Lyons  to  a  chair  of 
Southern  Literature,  instituted  expressly  for  him  at  the  Col- 
lege of  France.  His  teaching  excited  great  enthusiasm 
among  the  students  of  Paris,  but  brought  him  into  conflict 
with  the  clerical  party  and  the  Government.  He  was  sus- 
pended from  his  office  in  1845,  about  two  years  before  his 
friend  Michelet  was  similarly  silenced.  In  1848,  he  was 
among  the  first  to  enter  the  Tuileries,  gun  in  hand.  He  was 
restored  by  the  Republic  to  his  chair,  and  chosen  by  the  elec- 
tors of  his  native  district  to  represent  them  in  the  National 
Assembly.  From  1848  to  1 851  he  laboured  by  speech  and 
writing  to  prevent  the  faults  committed  by  his  own  party, 
and  to  counteract  the  operations  of  anarchists  and  reaction- 
ists. He  did  what  he  could  to  prevent  that  wicked  act,  the 
French  expedition  to  Rome.  He  foresaw  the  triumph  of 
Louis  Napoleon,  as  he  had  foreseen  the  fall  of  Louis  Philippe. 
The  coup  d^itat  cast  him  into  exile;  and  for  twenty  years  it 
was  his  lot  to  suffer  those  pains  which  none  but  the  banished 
patriot  himself  can  know.  Sustained,  however,  by  a  good 
conscience  and  by  the  perfect  sympathy  of  the  worthy  com- 
panion of  his  life,  he  laboured  without  ceasing  through  all 
these  weary  years  for  the  instruction  of  his  countrymen  and 
of  his  race. 

Of  the  writings  which  he  published  during  his  exile  sev- 
eral directly  relate  to  the  Philosophy  of  History.  The  first 
two  requiring  to  be  mentioned  are  specially  occupied  with 
the  history  of  France.  One  of  them  is  the  article  published 
in  the  'Revue  des  Deux  Mondes  '  (Jan v.  1855)  under  the 
title,  "Philosophie  de  l'Histoire  de  France;"  the  other,  'La 
Revolution,'  is  an  elaborate  work,  the  product  of  ten  years' 
labour.  Both  grew  out  of  their  author's  meditations  on  the 
national  demoralisation  visible  in  the  collapse  of  the  Repub- 
lic and  the  rise  of  the  Second  Empire.  The  review  article, 
owing  to  its  wider  scope, has  the  greater  claim  on  our  attention. 

It  was  an  eloquent  and  impassioned  protest  against  the 
dominant  historical  philosophy  in  France,  as  from  beginning 
to  end  an  affirmation  of  the  fatalism  of  facts,  and  a  denial  of 
the  claims  of  justice  in  estimating  the  character  of  national 


QUTNET  549 

events.  That  philosophy  is  affirmed  to  be  at  once  a  symptom 
and  cause  of  the  sickness  of  society  in  France.  Nations,  it 
is  said,  had  irretrievably  fallen  much  more  frequently  through 
their  infatuated  faith  in  false  ideas,  or  infatuated  rejection  of 
the  truth,  than  through  the  power  of  their  enemies :  and  as 
France  was  cherishing  a  number  of  grave  errors  regarding 
her  own  past,  she  was  in  imminent  danger,  if  every  man  who 
could  use  a  pen  did  not  come  forward  in  defence  of  the 
simple  truth  which  was  discarded  and  dishonoured ;  if  every 
thoughtful  Frenchman  were  not  willing  to  have  his  night  of 
the  4th  of  August,  and  loyally  sacrifice  for  his  country  his 
errors  in  history,  philosophy,  and  science.  But  one  of  the 
greatest  and  most  pernicious  of  these  errors  is  an  immoral 
historical  optimism,  which  rests  on  two  sophisms  that  have, 
unfortunately,  come  to  be  accepted  as  axioms:  viz.,  that  des- 
potism leads  to  liberty,  and  that  men  always  do  the  opposite 
of  what  they  suppose  they  are  doing. 

This  doctrinarian  optimism  M.  Quinet  has  described  as 
applied  to  the  history  of  France,  in  a  way  which  may  be  thus 
summarised.  At  the  very  commencement  of  French  history 
it  is  found  pronouncing  the  Gauls  incapable  of  self-educa- 
tion, of  self-civilisation,  and  vindicating  their  conquerors  in 
the  name  of  the  future  of  France  and  of  humanity.  It  teaches 
that  it  was  necessary  for  the  progress  of  both,  that  the  Gauls 
should  first  be  trampled  under  foot  by  the  Romans,  and  after- 
wards, along  with  the  Romans,  by  the  Franks;  that  not 
otherwise  than  through  violence  and  slavery  could  order  and 
freedom  be  reached.  In  a  word,  it  begins  by  justifying  con- 
quest, representing  wrong  as  necessary,  might  as  inherently 
■right,  and  thus  discrediting,  as  far  as  it  can,  the  holy  idea 
of  justice.  As  it  begins,  so  it  continues.  It  maintains  that 
it  was  most  fortunate  that  the  Albigenses  and  Waldenses,  and 
other  protesters  against  Papal  and  feudal  tyranny,  who,  even 
in  the  twelfth  century,  proclaimed  such  great  truths  as  that 
every  believer  is  a  priest,  did  not  succeed,  and  that  their 
ideas  were  effaced  in  blood,  till  the  world,  some  generations 
later,  was  prepared  for  them.  Thus  it  makes  irrational  any 
■such  thing  as  pity  for  the  fate  of  the  victims  of  Toulouse 
and  Beziers.  It  maintains  equally  that  the  success  of  the 
j.struggles  of  the  provinces,  the  communes,  and  the   third 


550  PHILOSOPHY   OP  HISTORY  IN  PliANCE 

estate,  which  began  so  early  and  terminated  so  late,  would 
in  every  case  have  been  disastrous  to  France;  and  that,  in 
fact,  France  owes  its  very  existence,  and  almost  all  its  great- 
ness and  glory,  to  the  victory  of  the  monarchy  over  these  op- 
ponents, the  victory  of  unity  and  despotism  over  liberty  and 
self-government.  When  it  comes  to  deal  with  the  struggles 
which  arose  out  of  the  spread  of  the  principles  of  the  Refor- 
mation, instead  of  acknowledging  that  France  went  griev- 
ously wrong  in  rejecting  Protestantism,  —  that  her  policy 
with  regard  to  the  new  faith,  under  Francis  I.,  and  Henry 
III.,  and  Charles  IX.,  and  Henry  IV.,  and  Richelieu  and 
Louis  XIV.,  was  at  once  unjust  and  foolish,  criminal  and 
pernacious,  —  it  pretends  that  the  real  significance  of  the 
wars  of  religion,  and  of  the  measures  pursued  relative  to  the 
Reformed,  was  not  whether  France  should  be  Protestant  or 
Catholic,  but  whether  it  should  be  feudal  or  monarchical; 
and  that,  as  the  triumph  of  Protestantism  would  have  in- 
volved the  victory  of  the  nobles  over  the  crown,  and  the 
recovery  of  their  medieval  powers  and  privileges,  it  was 
necessary,  for  the  welfare  of  France,  that  Protestantism 
should  be  defeated  and  suppressed.  Arrived  at  the  age  of 
Louis  XIV.,  it  salutes  it  with  boundless  enthusiasm,  as  the 
glorious  consummation  of  all  the  bloodshed,  and  usurpations, 
and  oppression  of  the  centuries  which  preceded  it,  as  the  end 
which  sanctified  all  the  means  which  led  to  it,  as  the  crown- 
ing of  the  edifice  of  centralised  authority.  It  finds  a  place 
for  the  Revolution  on  the  ground  that  freedom  ought  to  be 
developed  after  authority,  but  justifies  all  the  governments 
which  followed,  on  the  plea  that  they  were  occupied  in 
organising  those  liberties  which  the  Revolution  proclaimed. 
From  first  to  last,  it  finds  that  France  has  committed  no  folly, 
and  perpetrated  no  wrong ;  that  what  ought  to  have  been  has 
always  been ;  that  the  successful  cause  has  uniformly  been  a 
just  cause. 

From  this  whole  view  of  French  history,  which  he  regards 
as  the  official  and  universally  accepted  view  —  that  taught  in 
every  school  where  French  history  was  taught  at  all —  Quinet 
dissents  and  protests,  severely,  and  almost  violently.  France, 
he  maintains,  far  from  showing  herself  either  infallible  or 
impeccable,   really  erred  and  sinned  grievously,  preferred 


QUINET  551 

darkness  to  light,  and  sowed  for  herself  the  seeds  of  a  vast 
harvest  of  evils,  in  the  instances  referred  to,  and  many  others, 
where  historical  doctrinarianism  vindicates  her  conduct.  And 
the  first  act  of  her  regeneration,  he  declares,  must  be  that  she 
confess  her  sins  and  repent  of  the  iniquities  of  her  fathers. 

An  attack  so  direct,  so  sweeping,  and  so  little  conciliatory, 
on  what  was  widely  accepted  as  established  historical  doc- 
trine, naturally  excited  considerable  anger,  which  found  vent 
in  counter-protestation.  It  was  not  shown,  however,  and 
could  not,  I  believe,  be  shown,  to  be  other  than  substantially 
just  and  greatly  needed.  Historical  optimism  is  an  evil  so 
subtle  and  seductive,  that  perhaps  few  historians  in  any 
country  do  not  occasionally,  and  to  some  extent,  yield  to  its 
influence,  while  it  wholly  masters  and  possesses  many  with- 
out their  being  aware  that  such  is  the  case.  Any  historical 
philosophy  which  commits  itself  to  an  absolute  or  uncondi- 
tional defence  of  social  institutions  as  they  are,  which  iden- 
tifies the  real  of  any  given  time  with  the  rational,  must  be 
optimistic,  fatalistic;  must  identify  the  real  with  the  rational 
throughout  all  time.  For  the  present  is  the  necessary  prod- 
uct of  the  past.  The  present  could  not  have  been  precisely 
what  it  is  had  not  the  past  been  precisely  what  it  was.  The 
true  and  adequate  explanation  of  any  social  fact  or  institu- 
tion can  be  found  only  in  its  actual  historical  antecedents, 
and  will  be  found  there.  But  if  we  absolutely  approve  the 
end,  it  is  absurd  not  to  approve  the  means  which  necessarily 
led  to  it.  If  we  accept,  for  example,  as  the  best  thing  which 
could  have  happened  to  France,  precisely  what  happened,  in 
the  early  and  complete  triumph  of  the  monarchy  over  its 
enemies,  in  the  centralisation  of  all  powers  in  the  hand  of 
the  king,  it  is  utterly  unreasonable  to  regret  the  measures 
which  arrested,  say,  the  south  of  France  in  that  career  of 
national  development,  of  independent  religious  thought,  and 
independent  literary  activity,  on  which  it  entered  so  early, 
—  or  any  of  the  other  measures,  however  sanguinary  and 
treacherous,  by  which  local  independence,  and  personal,  poli- 
tical, and  religious  liberties,  were  crushed  down  and  rooted 
out.  The  historian  is,  in  fact,  in  all  circumstances,  in  dan- 
ger of  confounding  the  necessary  connection  which  he  finds 
between  institutions  and  their  antecedents,  with  the  moral 


552  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   FKANCB 

necessity  which  is  a  moral  justification,  or  the  physical  neces- 
sity which  takes  away  moral  responsibility ;  and  the  histori- 
cal philosopher  who  sets  to  work  with  the  political  aims 
which  Hegel  had  as  regards  Germany,  and  Guizot  as  regards 
France,  leaves  himself  not  even  a  chance  of  escape.  Guizot 
by  no  means  escaped  without  injury,  although  he  did  not 
drive  his  bark  on  the  rock  with  full  sail,  like  Hegel  or  his 
own  friend  and  colleague,  Cousin.  He  did  not  explicitly 
maintain  that  the  real  world  of  history  was  just  what  it  ought 
to  be,  but  he  suggested  that  conclusion.  He  did  not  censure 
the  instinctive  protests  of  conscience  against  triumphant 
wrong  as  "subjective  fault-finding;  "  but  the  whole  drift  of 
his  reasoning  tended  to  prove  that  the  wrong  had  a  right  to 
be  triumphant,  and  that  it  would  have  been  unfortunate  for 
humanity  if  events  had  occurred  in  a  way  which  would  have 
pleased  conscience  better.  He  found  each  event  necessary 
to  that  which  had  succeeded  it,  onwards  to  a  state  of  things 
which  he  regarded  with  complete  satisfaction,  and  virtually 
justified  the  entire  series,  on  account  of  this  necessary  con- 
nection between  antecedents  and  consequents.  The  accusa- 
tion brought  by  M.  Quinet  against  the  doctrinarian  philosophy 
of  history  was  thus  not  irrelevant,  not  misapplied. 

Where,  however,  was  the  logical  error  committed  by  doc- 
trinarian historical  philosophers  ?  It  lay  in  two  things.  The 
first  was  the  accepting  any  actual  state  of  society  as  a  state  of 
realised  reason.  The  real  in  history  is  never  the  rational,  but 
only  more  or  less  of  an  approximation  to  the  rational,  never 
identical  with,  but  only  participant  in,  reason.  No  fact,  no 
group  of  facts,  no  social  state,  has  that  absolute  goodness  in 
virtue  of  which  it  can  be  regarded  as  an  end  which  justifies 
the  means  absolutely  necessary  to  attain  it.  We  can  always 
ask,  Might  society  not  have  been  better,  and  would  it  not 
have  been  better,  had  antecedent  acts  and  events  been  better? 
But  that  is  what  the  doctrinarians  never  ask.  They  accept 
a  certain  state  of  society  as  above  criticism,  as  entirely  con- 
formed to  the  standard  of  reason,  and  then  show  that  it  was 
precisely  what  the  actual  past  was  capable  of  producing. 
Their  primary  assumption  is  erroneous.  Let  any  state  of 
society  be  critically  examined,  and  its  defects  and  evils  will 
testify  to  what  the  crimes  of  the  past  have  done  for  it.     M. 


QUINET  553 

Guizothad  no  difficulty  in  showing  that  what  M.'Qurnet, 
giving  expression  to  the  natural  voice  of  human  conscience, 
has  denounced  as  crimes,  were  the  steps  which  led  to  the 
early  unification  of  France  and  the  centralisation  of  power 
in  the  person  of  the  monarch ;  and  these  results  he  was  en- 
titled to  hold  had  been  in  many  respects  beneficial  to  France, 
and  probably  the  chief  reasons  why  she  so  early  became  the 
leading  nation  in  Europe;  but  he  ought  not  to  have  over- 
looked as  he  did  the  debtor  side  of  the  account,  the  terrible 
price  which  France  has  already  paid,  and  must  still  pay,  for 
the  glories  of  the  monarchy  and  the  advantages  of  adminis- 
trative centralisation.  Otherwise  he  could  hardly  have  failed 
to  perceive  that  France  might  have  been  much  happier  and 
stronger  if  her  history  had  been  quite  other  than  it  was ;  if 
the  natural  development  of  the  different  divisions  of  France 
had  not  been  violently  arrested ;  if  liberty  had  earlier  been  more 
successful ;  if  Protestantism  had  conquered  as  it  deserved ;  if 
unification  had  been  later,  and  centralisation  less  complete. 

The  second  error  implied  in  historical  optimism  was  the 
failing  to  recognise  that  freedom  of  choice  and  action  is  com- 
patible with  necessary  connection  between  historical  phe- 
nomena. That  the  present  is  precisely  what  the  past  has 
made  it  is  true ;  but  not  more  true  than  that  the  men  of  the 
past  had  it  in  their  power  every  hour  so  to  act  as  would  have 
given  us  a  different  present.  We  do  not  need  to  deny  the 
connection  between  actions  and  their  effects  to  be  necessary 
because  we  hold  actions  to  be  free ;  and  it  is  only  actions  and 
their  effects  which  history  shows  us.  Necessity  runs  through 
actual  history  from  beginning  to  end,  yet  actual  history  rests 
on  free  choice  from  beginning  to  end ;  on  choice  out  of  manjr 
possibilities,  some  better  and  some  worse.  It  is  from  ignor- 
ing this  latter  fact,  from  confining  their  regards  solely  to 
actuality,  that  so  many  historical  philosophers  have  found  in 
their  systems  no  room  for  conscience. 

Quinet,  then,  performed  excellent  service  by  insisting  on 
the  rights  of  conscience  in  relation  to  historical  speculation. 
Perhaps  it  would  not  have  hurt  his  own  cause,  and  it  would 
only  have  been  just  to  his  opponents,  if  he  had  acknowledged 
that  his  objections  applied  less  to  the  substance  of  their  his- 
torical philosophy  than  to  assumptions  associated  with  it. 


554  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Suppose  all  that  he  has  urged  against  the  historical  philos- 
ophy of  Guizot,  for  example,  to  hold  true,  the  value  of  that 
philosophy  as  an  explanation  of  the  actual  course  of  events 
remains  intact.  The  optimism  and  fatalism  implied  in  it 
must  go,  if  Quinet  be  right ;  but  these  will  not  carry  away 
with  them  any  of  its  explanations  as  to  how  fact  gave  rise 
to  fact,  how  social  revolutions  succeeded  one  another,  in  the 
history  of  France. 

'  La  Revolution '  (1865)  is  much  less  a  history  than  a 
philosophical  study  on  history.  It  is  a  remarkably  able 
attempt  to  understand  and  judge  the  Revolution :  to  ascer- 
tain precisely  what  was  aimed  at  by  it;  to  discriminate 
between  the  good  and  the  evil  in  it;  to  assign  to  its  various 
parties  and  agents  only  what  they  were  really  responsible 
for;  and  to  show  why  it  had  deplorably  failed  to  realise  the 
hopes  in  which  it  originated.  By  writers  like  Lamartine 
and  Michelet  the  Revolution  had  been  treated  as  a  sort  of 
sacred  mystery  and  divine  incarnation,  an  object  of  faith  and 
adoration,  rather  than  as  simply  an  historical  and  human 
phenomenon  which  should  be  judged  of  conformably  to  the 
ordinary  laws  of  historical,  rational,  and  moral  criticism. 
Quinet  was  as  sincerely  attached  as  they  were  to  what  he 
deemed  the  principles  of  the  Revolution;  but  1852  con- 
vinced him  of  the  folly  of  looking  at  the  Revolution  itself 
through  the  medium  of  sentiment  and  imagination.  Hence 
he  sought  in  the  work  mentioned  to  exhibit  it  solely  in  the 
light  of  reality,  reason,  and  conscience;  to  clear  away  the 
legends  which  had  grown  up  as  to  Girondists  and  Jacobins ; 
to  unmask  Mirabeau,  Danton,  Robespierre,  and  other  popu- 
lar heroes;  and  to  expose  the  errors  and  crimes  which  had 
been  committed,  to  account  for  them,  and  to  trace  their  con- 
sequences. A  book  so  thoroughly  honest,  dispelling  so  many 
illusions  and  shattering  so  many  idols,  necessarily  gave  wide 
offence;  but  it  was  immensely  useful. 

At  the  same  time  it  was  not  without  defects.  Its  author, 
holding  that  a  political  and  social  revolution  must  depend  on 
a  religious  revolution,  and  that  the  principles  of  Roman 
Catholicism  were  irreconcilable  with  those  of  the  French 
Revolution,  was  naturally  led  to  discuss  at  length  the  ways 
in  which  the  men  of  1789  and  1793  dealt  with  the  religions 


QTJINET  555 

question.  The  discussion  occupies  j;wo  books  of  his  work, 
and  is  the  portion  of  it  which  has  attracted  most  attention. 
It  is  ingenious,  and  abounds  in  excellent  observations  and 
suggestions;  but  it  is  inconclusive.  The  general  finding 
implied  is  that  the  politicians  of  the  Revolution,  even  al- 
though not  Protestants  by  conviction,  should,  in  order  to 
counteract  and  destroy  Catholicism,  have  established  Protes- 
tantism as  the  national  religion  of  France.  But  it  was  surely 
most  excusable  that  those  of  them  who  were  not  Protestants 
should  not  have  seen  how  this  could  be  their  duty.  There 
were  more  atheists  and  deists  than  Protestants  among  the 
leaders  of  the  revolutionary  movement.  The  former  natur- 
ally sought  to  establish  atheism  (le  eulte  de  la  raisofi) ;  the 
latter  deism  (le  culte  de  Vllltre  SuprSme').  They  failed.  If 
Protestants,  and  especially  if  merely  pretended  Protestants, 
had  tried  to  establish  Protestantism,  they  must  equally  have 
failed.  The  faith  of  a  nation  cannot  be  altered  of  a  sudden 
or  at  will.  By  merely  political  devices  no  great  religious 
changes  can  be  effected. 

Further,  Quinet  ignored  to  a  regrettable  extent  the  most 
obvious  and  powerful  of  all  the  causes  of  the  failure  of  the 
French  Revolution :  the  toleration  and  encouragement  given 
in  it  to  violence  and  crime,  to  brutal  and  sanguinary  mobs, 
to  conspirators  and  ruffians.  None  of  its  chiefs  showed  any 
adequate  sense  of  the  importance  of  law,  morality,  and  order 
to  society.  All  its  parties  connived  at  and  countenanced 
disorders  and  excesses,  the  most  hateful  in  themselves  and 
the  most  dangerous  to  society,  when  they  seemed  to  tend  to 
their  own  political  advantage.  Those  aspects  of  the  Revolu- 
tion on  which  Taine  has  almost  exclusively  dwelt,  Quinet 
has  almost  entirely  overlooked. 

In  the  seventh  year  of  his  exile  Quinet  left  Belgium,  and 
took  up  his  abode  in  Switzerland,  settling  at  Veytaux,  near 
Montreux  and  Chillon,  on  the  Lake  of  Geneva.  Isolated 
from  society,  he  made  the  Alps  his  companions,  questioned 
them  as  to  their  secrets,  and  studied  the  history  of  the  earth. 
Nature,  which  "never  betrays  the  heart  that  loves  her," 
rejuvenated  his  spirit,  invigorated  his  mind,  and  opened  up 
to  him  new  vistas  of  thought. 

He  soon  saw  that  the  inquiries  which  now  engaged  him 


556  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

were  not  alien  to  those  with  which  he  had  hitherto  been 
occupied,  but  intimately  connected  with  them;  and  he  set 
himself  to  trace  out  the  relations  between  them.  For  ten 
years  he  was  thus  employed.  The  conclusions  at  which  he 
arrived  are  presented  in  the  work  which  he  himself  calls  "  the 
ripe  fruit  of  his  life  "  —  'La  Creation'  (2  vols.,  1870). 

This  work,  so  admirable  by  the  simplicity  of  its  plan,  the 
grandeur  of  manj'  of  its  ideas,  the  vividness  and  impressive- , 
ness  of  its  descriptions,  the  serenity  of  its  tone,  and  the 
beauties  of  its  style,  gives  a  synthetic  view  of  nature  and 
humanity  as  they  appear  in  the  light  of  modern  science  and 
of  rational  speculation.  Its  essential  conception  is  that  the 
history  of  nature  enlightens  that  of  man,  and  the  history  of 
man  that  of  nature ;  that  these  two  species  of  history  exem- 
plify the  same  laws,  and  that  the  sciences  conversant  with 
them  must  follow  the  same  method;  that,  although  natural- 
ists and  historians  have  long  worked  apart,  without  mutual 
recognition  or  understanding,  indifferent  or  hostile,  they 
have  at  length  met,  found  themselves  to  have  been  engaged 
in  the  same  task,  exchanged  their  torches,  and  combined  their 
forces;  and  that  they  will  henceforth  be  powerful  and  suc- 
cessful in  the  measure  that  they  consciously  realise  their  alli- 
ance. To  awaken,  deepen,  and  guide  this  consciousness,  is 
the  main  aim  of  the  book. 

The  pictures  of  geological  epochs  in  books  m.-v.  are  bril- 
liant products  of  a  constructive  imagination  which  had  been 
long  exercised  in  the  sphere  of  history,  and  which  submitted 
itself  to  scientific  control.  In  order  to  compose  them  Quinet 
made  himself  thoroughly  acquainted  with  the  works  of 
Alphonse  de  Candolle,  Pictet  de  la  Rive,  Oswald  Heer, 
Agassiz,  Lyell,  Darwin,  Huxley,  and  other  great  palaeonto- 
logists and  naturalists.  They  form  an  appropriate  and  mag- 
nificent introduction  to  what  he  has  to  say  of  man,  but  they 
are  not  introduced  solely  to  serve  that  end,  and  still  less  for 
their  own  sake:  on  the  contrary,  their  chief  design  is  to 
show  the  identity  of  two  methods  of  research  commonly  con- 
sidered distinct;  and  the  unity  of  nature  and  history,  which 
although  long  separated  and  contrasted,  are  now  ascertained 
to  be  only  two  divisions  or  branches  of  history.  The  discov- 
ery by  modern  science  of  this  identity  and  unity  Quinet  re- 


quenet  557 

as  the.  greatest  fact  of  modern  times ;  the  one  which 
must  revolutionise  most  the  realm  of  intellect,  and  effect 
the  most  momentous  changes  on  our  conceptions  of  the  world 
and  man,  of  life  and  death. 

He  entirely  rejects  the  hypothesis  of  multiple  creations, 
of  repeated  interventions  of  supernatural  power ;  and  he  fully 
accepts  the  general  doctrine  of  transformism  and  develop- 
ment. In  the  book  (vi.)  devoted  to  "the  Ape  and  Man," 
he  indicates  the  differences  and  resemblances  between  them, 
and  infers  that  there  must  have  been  an  intermediate  type 
which  soon  entirely  disappeared.  Once  separated,  however 
slightly,  from  the  simian  stock,  man  rapidly  removed  from 
it,  underwent  decisive  consecutive  changes  in  his  principal 
organs,  and  speedily  reached  the  final  or  fully  human  type, 
which  has  alone  survived.  Primitive  man  had  scarcely  time 
to  leave  his  impression  on  the  earth.  Men  are  of  one  type, 
origin,  and  blood,  in  a  sense  and  measure  in  which  the  apes 
are  not.  There  is  but  one  human  family ;  there  are  many 
simian  families.  Millions  of  ages  separate  the  origins  of 
man  and  the  ape.  A  variety  of  considerations  are  adduced 
to  prove  that  the  human  race  appeared  before  the  great  ice 
age;  not  on  an  island  but  a  continent;  and  in  a  subtropical 
climate.  Its  relations  to  the  large  vertebrate  animals  of  the 
quaternary  and  tertiary  epochs,  as  well  as  such  glimpses  into 
the  psychology  of  fossil  man  as  the  crania  which  have  been 
discovered  seem  to  give,  are  the  subjects  of  ingenious  and 
suggestive  remark.  Universal  life  is  shown  to  concentrate 
itself  in  man  alone ;  all  the  vicissitudes  of  its  history  to  pass 
into  and  be  continued  in  his ;  all  the  revolutions  of  the  earth 
to  have  left  their  traces  and  their  echoes  in  the  human  heart. 

In  books  vn. -viii.  the  man  of  the  glacial  period,  the  ages  of 
the  lacustrine  city,  and  the  social  and  religious  consequences 
of  the  discovery  of  fire,  are  the  chief  subjects  discussed. 

The  next  book  (ix.)  treats  of  the  palaeontology  of  lan- 
guages, and  of  the  laws  of  life  and  speech.  It  abounds  in 
hypotheses,  not  a  few  of  which  may  be  mere  conjectures. 
They  are  always,  however,  of  the  kind  necessary  to  scientific 
progress.  Max  Miiller  has  argued  that  the  science  of  lan- 
guage is  not  a  mental  (or,  as  the  French  say,  moral)  or  histori- 
cal science  but  a  physical  science.     Quinet  maintains  that  it 


558  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

is  both  a  physical  and  historical  science ;  and  endeavours  to 
show  that  comparative  philology  is  intimately  connected 
with  comparative  anatomy.  In  the  origin,  growth,  and 
decay  of  languages,  he  sees  exemplified  the  general  laws  of 
life.  He  traces  language  back  from  the  inflectional  to  the 
agglutinative,  and  from  the  agglutinative  to  the  monosyl- 
labic stage,  and  conjectures  what  it  was  on  the  lips  of  fossil 
man.  After  Buffon  and  Herder,  and  in  opposition  to  Max 
Miiller,  he  refers  the  origin  of  its  primitive  radicals  to  imita- 
tion of  the  voices  of  animals  and  of  the  sounds  produced  by 
natural  agents.  His  chapters  on  the  songs  or  languages  of 
birds,  their  varieties  or  dialects,  are  at  least  curious  and  in- 
genious. In  discussing  the  application  of  the  laws  of  natu- 
ral history  to  linguistic  science  and  of  those  of  linguistic 
science  to  natural  history,  he  represents  the  monosyllable  as 
the  organic  cell ;  compares  the  succession  of  the  chief  branches 
of  human  speech  to  that  of  the  chief  divisions  of  the  animal 
kingdom;  and  explains  the  formation  of  such  idioms  as  the 
Neo-Latin  as  a  process  of  the  same  kind  as  the  modification 
and  ramification  of  biological  species.  The  causes  which 
limit  the  power  of  languages  to  unite  in  the  production  of 
other  languages  are  akin  to  those  which  condition  the  fer- 
tility of  races  inter  se. 

The  tenth  and  eleventh  books  are  of  special  interest. 
Their  author  undertakes  to  establish  in  them,  by  tracing  the 
parallelisms  of  nature  and  humanity,  the  principles  of  a  new 
science.  He  claims  to  have  entered  a  virgin  forest,  full  of 
mysteries  and  of  promises,  and  where  no  one  had  previously 
been.  I  must  be  content,  however,  to  indicate  merely  a  few 
of  the  ideas  which  he  has  set  forth  in  this  portion  of  his  treatise. 

Progress  in  nature  and  history,  we  are  told,  is  not  effected 
along  a  single  line,  but  on  as  many  parallel  lines  as  there  are 
organised  beings  and  human  races.  It  does  not  always  pro- 
ceed in  the  same  direction  or  at  the  same  rate ;  nor  is  it  even 
continuous.  There  are  times  of  relapse,  aberration,  and 
decadence.  Not  every  new  species  or  generation  is  an  im- 
provement on  that  which  preceded  it.  The  march  of  nature 
and  humanity  is  less  rigidly  and  narrowly  regulated,  and  is 
nobler  and  freer,  than  is  supposed.  Yet  the  thread  of  organic 
life  and  of  civilisation  is  never  severed.     The  vital  force 


QUINET  559 

passes  from  one  genus  or  empire  to  another ;  it  is  circulated 
and  transformed,  not  lost.  When  the  capability  of  further 
development  ceases  in  one  genus  or  nation,  it  leaves  them 
in  a  condition  of  immobility  akin  to  decline,  and  passes  to 
others  which  spring  into  life,  bearing  in  their  bosoms  an 
incommensurable  future. 

"Humanity  is  an  embryo  always  growing,  and  which  suc- 
cessively assumes  diverse  forms.  The  epochs  through  which 
it  travels  are  marked  by  the  peoples  which  there  stop  in  their 
course,  ceasing  to  advance,  but  not  to  exist.  Thus  they  all 
coexist  on  the  earth  at  the  same  time:  the  first  beginnings 
among  the  Chinese,  the  age  of  stone  among  the  savages,  that 
of  Egypt  among  the  fetichists  of  Senegal,  that  of  Abraham 
among  the  nomadic  Arabs,  &c.  The  diversity  of  epochs 
gives  rise  to  the  diversity  of  societies.  Corresponding  to 
these  stages  of  arrest  in  the  development  of  humanity  are 
species  in  the  development  of  the  organic  world." 

Natural  and  human  history  are  subject  to  common  laws. 
Both,  for  instance,  imply  the  law  of  unity  of  composition  and 
correlation  of  parts.  It  is  only  through  the  practical  recog- 
nition of  this  law  that  either  palseontological  or  archselogical 
research  has  been  prosecuted  with  success.  The  palaeonto- 
logist and  the  archaeologist  alike  have  often  before  them 
merely  the  slightest  fragments  of  organic  or  social  systems 
which  have  disappeared,  and  yet  they  are  able  to  divine  what 
these  systems  were.  They  have  a  sure  guiding  thread  in  the 
principle  that  every  organic  whole,  animal  or  social,  is  of  a 
definite  type,  with  parts  mutually  dependent  in  their  growth 
and  development,  and  the  characters  of  each  part  related  to 
those  of  all  the  rest.  This  law  was  recognised  and  acted  on  by 
historians  before  it  was  formulated  by  Geoffrey  Saint-Hilaire. 

The  law  of  unity  of  composition  has  its  complement  in  the 
law  of  specialisation  of  functions,  which  also  prevails  in  the 
social,  as  well  as  in  the  vegetable  and  animal,  world.  In- 
deed it  was  in  the  social  world,  and  especially  in  the  sphere 
of  economics,  that  its  working  and  importance  were  first  dis- 
tinctly recognised.  The  division  of  labour  in  industry  is 
only  an  exemplification  of  the  differentiation  which  is  now 
recognised  to  be  a  law  alike  of  natural  and  of  human  devel- 
opment; but  it  is  the  one  which  was  first  studied  with  care. 


560  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PKANCE 

The  struggle  for  existence,  as  exhibited  by  Darwin,  is,  in 
like  manner,  a  generalisation  of  the  law  of  social  order  on 
which  Malthus  had  laid  so  much  stress.  It  is  the  extension  to 
the  whole  domain  of  living  nature  of  an  hypothesis  which  had 
been  employed  to  explain  the  economic  condition  of  mankind. 

Further,  progress  is  not  universal  either  in  nature  or  his- 
tory ;  selection  does  not  act  alike  on  all ;  it  is  chiefly  in  the 
higher  grades  or  orders  of  being  that  improvement  is  to  be 
observed.  The  simplest  of  living  beings  are  the  oldest. 
Molluscs  and  zoophytes  are  now  much  what  they  ever  were. 
The  masses  of  the  human  race  have  advanced  little  in  com- 
parison with  its  leading  classes.  It  is  by  its  head  that  human- 
ity is  progressive.  Duration  is  no  evidence  of  the  superiority 
of  a  species  or  of  a  civilisation.  The  glory  of  Greece  far  sur- 
passes that  of  China.  When  an  empire  declines,  what  is 
noblest  in  it  is  what  becomes  earliest  atrophied :  first,  thought ;. 
next,  art ;  then  industry ;  and,  finally,  military  power. 

The  phenomena  of  atrophy  are  as  apparent  in  human  socie- 
ties as  in  the  organisms  of  which  botany  and  zoology  treat. 
The  law  of  atavism,  the  tendency  to  return  to  the  primitive 
type,  is  also  a  sociological  not  less  than  a  biological  law. 
Yet  nature  and  humanity  never  simply  retrace  their  steps ; 
never  recommence  their  work  ab  ovo.  Nature  never  employs 
again  a  mould  which  it  has  once  broken ;  nor  does  humanity 
ever  reinvest  itself  with  a  social  form  which  it  has  once  aban- 
doned. But  although  the  doctrine  of  progress  has  been 
exaggerated  by  historians,  and  requires  to  be  corrected  and 
brought  into  accordance  with  the  teaching  of  naturalists, 
progress  is  the  rule.  A  general  rise  of  creation,  a  gravita- 
tion towards  spirit,  is  traceable.  The  successive  generations 
of  individuals,  both  human  and  animal,  work  out  a  plan  of 
which  they  have  no  consciousness  or  discernment,  yet  one 
which  is  an  onward  and  upward  development,  a  realisation 
of  vast  and  lofty  ends. 

The  problem  of  the  origin  of  life  itself  is  dealt  with.1  It 
is  maintained  that  life  is  cosmical,  not  merely  terrestrial; 
that  it  did  not  originate  on  the  earth  at  a  given  time  out  of 
non-living  matter,  but  that  the  earth  carried  it  along  with 
it  from  the  mass  from  which  it  was  detached.     Life,  it  is 

1  xi.  ch.  2. 


QUINET  561 

argued,  is  not  confined  to  certain  points  of  space  or  periods 
of  time,  but  is  coextensive  and  coeval  with  the  universe. 
The  same  germs  which  were  in  the  outer  layers  of  the  primi- 
tive nebula  of  a  solar  system,  may  take  different  forms  appro- 
priate to  each  planet  of  the  system.  The  earth  has  no  more 
given  itself  life  than  it  has  given  itself  light.  The  first 
living  being  had  its  ancestor  in  the  infinite.  This  theory 
had  been  previously  suggested,  we  have  seen,  by  Barchou 
cle  Penhoen ;  since  it  was  propounded  by  Quinet  it  has  been 
advocated  by  Preyer  and  several  other  scientists. 

The  work  closes  with  "a  prophecy  of  science."1  The 
natural  science  of  the  present  day  utters,  we  are  told,  a 
prophecy  far  more  remarkable  than  any  to  be  found  in  Isaiah 
or  Ezekiel ;  one  which  has  respect  not  to  some  petty  empires 
condemned  to  speedy  destruction,  but  to  all  nature  and  to 
all  humanity.  It  leaves  us  with  the  assurance  that  creation 
is  unfinished,  and  will  be  completed;  with  the  prediction 
that  the  human  race  will  pass  away,  and  give  place  to  one 
which  is  higher  and  nobler. 

Looking  at  the  course  of  things  in  the  past  as  disclosed  by 
science,  M.  Quinet  anticipates  that  the  future  will  be  in 
the  same  direction,  and,  therefore,  better  and  more  glorious 
than  the  past.  It  may  be  so ;  it  is  even  a  not  unnatural 
inference  that  it  will  be  so.  But  there  is  no  necessity  or 
certainty  that  it  will  not  be  quite  otherwise.  What  the  dis- 
tant future  will  be,  and  whether  the  final  consummation  of 
things  will  be  glorious  or  the  reverse,  the  fulness  of  life  or 
the  nothingness  of  death,  mere  natural  science,  science 
detached  from  religious  faith,  has  as  yet  assuredly  not  ascer- 
tained. The  hope  of  the  optimist  may  be  less  unreasonable 
than  the  despair  of  the  pessimist;  but  it  cannot  justly  claim 
to  be  vouched  for  by  positive  science. 

On  the  fall  of  the  Empire  in  1871  Quinet  hastened  to  Paris 
to  encourage  his  countrymen  and  to  share  in  their  privations. 
He  was  reinstated  in  his  Chair,  and  offered  an  indemnity  for 
having  been  illegally  driven  from  it;  but  he  refused  any 
recompense.  While  Paris  was  being  besieged,  his  'Creation' 
was  translated  into  German  by  a  distinguished  naturalist, 
Professor  B.  von  Cotta  of  Freiburg;  and  when  the  siege  was 

1  xii.  eh.  11. 


562  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   FBANOE 

raised  a  copy  of  this  translation  was  one  of  the  first  things 
which  reached  him. 

Notwithstanding  failing  health,  and  the  harassing  labours 
of  a  representative  and  legislator  in  a  time  of  sore  civil 
troubles,  he  continued  to  study  and  write.  'L'Esprit  Nou- 
veau, '  the  last  of  his  works  published  in  his  lifetime, 
appeared  in  1874.  It  completes  and  crowns  'La  Creation.' 
There  are  various  matters  in  it  worthy  of  being  dwelt  on 
which  I  must  leave  unconsidered:  e.g.,  his  views  on  the 
place  of  justice  in  history,  its  relation  to  love,  and  how  it  is 
that  it  holds  its  own,  and  even  triumphs  in  the  struggle  for 
existence,  notwithstanding  the  advantages  of  the  wicked; 
his  explanation  of  the  decadence  of  aristocracies ;  his  remarks 
on  the  falsification  of  history  by  servility  of  spirit;  and 
especially  his  brilliant  exposition  of  the  causes  and  refuta- 
tion of  the  theories  of  recent  pessimism. 

Edgar  Quinet  died  on  the  26th  of  March  1875.  Few  have 
lived  in  any  age  a  life  so  singularly  unselfish,  so  conspicu- 
ously pure  and  high  in  aims,  so  earnest  in  endeavours,  so 
fruitful  in  works,  and  so  profoundly  religious  in  spirit.1 

1  Democracy  in  France  has  had  among  its  adherents  many  historical  theorists 
besides  Miehelet  and  Quinet.    I  shall  mention  here  only  the  following :  — 

1.  Lamennais  (during  the  last  period  of  his  life).  He  entered  on  this  stage  ol 
his  career  with  the  '  Paroles  d'un  croyant,'  1833,  a  work  written  with  an  intensity 
of  sympathy  and  passion  hardly  surpassed  in  any  book  of  Hebrew  prophecy;  anil 
he  followed  it  up  by  various  attacks  on  civil  and  ecclesiastical  absolutism,  and 
appeals  on  behalf  of  freedom  and  religious  and  social  renovation.  To  the  same 
period  belongs  his  chief  philosophical  production,  the  '  Esquisse  d'une  philosophie,' 
4  vols.,  1840-46.  It  is  the  most  speculative,  the  most  serene  and  dispassionate, 
and  the  most  artistically  constructed  of  all  his  writings.  Its  first  principle  is 
Absolute  and  Infinite  Being,  and  from  it  all  knowledge  and  existence  are  repre- 
sented as  naturally  and  rationally  derived.  It  gives  evidence  of  earnest  study, 
abundant  ingenuity,  and  remarkable  architectonic  power;  but  also  of  lack  of 
critical  insight  and  caution.  With  all  his  gifts  Lamennais  was  constitutionally 
incapable  of  being  wisely  sceptical.  The  third  volume  of  his  '  Esquisse '  is  the  one 
which  is  of  most  interest  to  an  historical  student.  It  treats  of  the  development 
of  the  powers  of  humanity,  and  of  their  manifestations.  Its  best  chapters  are 
those  on  the  evolution  of  the  various  arts,  and  especially  of  architecture,  sculp- 
ture, painting,  poetry,  and  oratory.  No  light  was  thrown  by  Lamennais  on  the 
nature  of  beauty,  or  the  psychology  of  our  aesthetic  sentiments,  hut  he  was  ex- 
ceptionally successful  in  showing  how  the  history  of  art  has  been  related  to  the 
history  of  religion,  and  to  history  in  general. 

2.  Eugene  Pelletan  has  been  an  ardent  advocate  of  the  democratic  cause.  He 
is,  perhaps,  best  known  by  his  eloquent  exposition  and  advocacy  of  the  theory 
of  indefinite  progress  in  his  'Profession  de  foi  du  xix"  siecle,'  1850.  His  view  as 
there  set  forth  having  been  criticised  in  one  of  the  '  Entretiens '  of  Lamartine,  he 
defended   and   reiterated  them  in  'Le  Monde  marche,'  1856.     Progress  means. 


C^ESARISM  563 


III 


The  revolution  of  1848,  the  troubles  which  followed,  and 
the  triumph  of  imperialism  in  1851,  greatly  influenced  his- 
torical thought  in  France.  They  caused  the  past  history  of 
France  and  of  humanity  to  assume  to  many  Frenchmen  a 
much  altered  aspect.  The  events  and  personages  of  bygone 
ages  were  viewed  through  the  media  of  the  experiences  and 
feelings  of  the  actual  time ;  and  the  consequence  was  in  not 
a  few  cases  an  entire  change  of  opinion  as  to  their  character 
and  significance.  One  result  was  the  spread  of  distrust  in 
democracy,  and  in  democratic  interpretations  of  history — ■ 
i.e.,  in  such  readings  of  it  as  conclude  in  favour  of  the  self- 
government  of  nations  and  the  rightful  liberty  of  individuals. 
Absolute  rule  found  a  larger  number  of  admirers.  Some 
openly  proclaimed  force  to  be  the  law  of  society.  There 
came  forward  authors  who  sought  to  convert  all  history  into 
an  apology  for  Csesarism.     They  represented  the  fortunes  of 

according  to  him,  the  increase  of  life.  Its  motive  force  is  desire.  He  combats  the 
ascetic  theory  of  progress,  founded  on  self-renunciation,  and  so  generally  approved 
by  the  Church.  At  the  same  time,  he  rests  his  own  doctrine  on  faith  in  God  and 
immortality.  As  God  is  the  source  of  all,  man  tends  continually  to  approach  Him. 
And  God  through  His  various  attributes  is  continually  expanding  His  empire  in 
time ;  continually  building  up  that  divine  kingdom  of  which  the  best  formula  is 
Liberty,  Equality,  and  Fraternity.  While  not  a  mechanical  evolutionist  or  trans- 
formist,  he  maintains  that  progress  is  continuous  and  unending.  Life  continuously 
ascends  from  the  fluid  to  the  mineral,  from  the  mineral  to  the  vegetable,  from  the 
vegetable  to  the  animal,  and  from  the  animal  to  man,  the  final  term  of  life ;  but 
human  life  is  immortal,  and  will  have  infinite  space  for  its  place  of  pilgrimage. 
"Man  will  go  always  from  sun  to  sun,  ever  mounting,  as  on  Jacob's  ladder,  the 
hierarchy  of  existence  "  ('  Prof,  de  foi,'  376,  3"  e'd.) . 

3.  Lamartine.  In  opposition  to  Pelletan,  he  took  a  desponding  view  of  the 
future  of  humanity,  and  doubted  if  faith  in  moral  progress  could  justify  itself 
before  reason  and  history.  His  '  Histoire  des  Girondins,'  1847,  originated  in  zeal 
for  the  spread  of  democratic  ideas  and  aspirations.  No  book  had  a  greater  im- 
mediate popularity  and  influence ;  but  it  was  nearly  all  that  an  historical  work 
should  not  be. 

i.  Victor  Hugo.  It  seems  to  me  that  in  the  ancient  world  there  were  two  poets 
whose  thoughts  on  the  order  and  course  of  human  affairs  might,  without  irrele- 
vancy, be  treated  of  at  length  in  a  history  of  the  philosophy  of  history  —  namely , 
the  author  of  the  Book  of  Job  and  iEschylus ;  and  that  in  the  modern  world  there 
have  been  three,  Dante,  Shakespeare,  and  Victor  Hugo.  As  in  Dante  the  '  Ge- 
schichtsanschauungen '  of  Catholicism,  and  in  Shakespeare  those  of  Humanism, 
so  in  Hugo  those  of  Democracy,  have  found  their  noblest  and  fullest  poetical 
expression.  I  refer  especially  to  his  '  Legende  des  Siecles '  and  similar  poems. 
To  write  profitably,  however,  of  Hugo  in  this  connection,  would  require  an  extent 
of  space  which  is  not  at  my  disposal. 


564  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

mankind  as  dependent  on  a  few  individuals  of  commanding 
genius,  in  whose  hands  Providence  places  the  whole  force 
of  the  nations  in  which  they  appear;  and  they  regarded 
opposition  to  the  wills  of  these  predestined  "  saviours  "  as 
folly  and  impiety. 

This  theory  was  set  forth  in  the  most  outspoken  and  cyni- 
cal fashion  by  M.  Romieu  in  his  'Ere  des  Caesars, '  1850.  The 
Csesarism  advocated  by  him  is  the  incarnation  of  sheer  force ; 
the  rule  of  an  absolute  personal  will  which  despises  ideas 
and  principles,  and  relies  on  swords  and  guns.  It  differs 
from  monarchy  precisely  in  that  it  thus  subsists  of  itself  and 
by  itself,  while  the  latter  is  maintained  only  on  the  condi- 
tion of  inspiring  belief.  The  root  of  monarchy  is  a  faith  born 
in  the  infancy  of  nations,  and  subsequently  developed  and 
■exalted  into  a  dogma,  but  which  dies  in  late  and  rationalistic 
ages.  These  call  for  strong,  and  not  for  hereditary,  power. 
As  soon  as  any  people  accepts  "  the  insensate  dogma  of  rea- 
son, "  and  seeks  to  govern  itself  by  free  discussion  and  parlia- 
mentary methods,  it  shows  that  it  has  become  insane  and 
Tequires  to  be  ruled  by  force  in  the  hands  of  a  man  who  sub- 
stitutes deeds  for  words.  "Force  is  the  inevitable  issue  of 
all  the  debates  in  which  words  entangle  nations;  it  is  the 
decisive  and  potent  corollary  of  every  contradictory  theorem 
engendered  by  the  spirit  of  disputation  —  call  it  philosophy, 
reason,  or  liberty ;  it  is  the  solution  of  all  the  problems  pro- 
pounded in  every  age  by  pretended  reformers;  it  is,  in  a 
word,  the  ultima  ratio  of  all  human  calculations,  which  can 
come  to  nothing  without  force.  And  when  I  say  force,  I 
mean  that  very  force  of  which  people  complain,  and  of  which 
they  blame  the  excess." 

While  thus  avowing  his  preference  of  force  to  reason  and 
liberty,  Romieu  professes  great  respect  for  what  he  calls  holi- 
ness and  Christianity,  and  declares  that  he  has  written  in 
their  interest.  "Mankind  has  two  sorts  of  respect, —  respect 
for  holiness,  and  respect  for  power.  The  element  of  holi- 
ness has  ceased  to  exist  in  the  present  age;  the  element  of 
strength  is  of  all  ages,  and  can  alone  restore  the  other.  This 
is  why  I  have  pleaded  the  cause  of  force  in  this  book,  which 
may  be  deemed  coarse  (brutal).  .  .  .  Christianity  so  com- 
pletely embodies  all  the  aspirations  of-  the  soul,  that  it  must 


C^SAEISM  565 

revive  once  more,  sooner  or  later,  after  the  mad  doctrines 
which  have  usurped  its  place  are  abandoned.  If  there  be  in 
the  word  progress  any  sense  applicable  to  our  order  of  ideas, 
it  must  be  sought  for  in  the  rehabilitation  of  the  most  sublime 
of  creeds.  He  who  said,  'Blessed  are  they  that  mourn,' 
uttered  the  one  great  maxim  of  humanity.  Whenever  that 
maxim  shall  be  universally  believed,  all  codes,  all  laws  may 
be  destroyed,  and  the  world  will  go  on  smoothly  of  itself." 

Romieu  presents  us  in  proof  of  his  theory  with  a  survey  of 
Roman  history,  and  endeavours  to  make  out  that  the  Euro- 
pean world  is  in  the  same  position  as  the  Roman  world  was 
when  it  found  relief  and  rest  under  Augustus.  His  predic- 
tion, that  "in  1852,  if  no  event  hurries  on  the  catastrophe," 
France  would  freely  seek  salvation  in  the  way  which  he 
recommended,  showed  that  he  possessed  a  considerable  meas- 
ure of  perspicacity.  It  has  to  be  remembered,  however, 
that  he  was  one  of  the  band  of  Caesarian  conspirators  who 
were  striving  to  bring  about  the  catastrophe  of  which  he 
announced  the  approach. 

M.  Dubois  Guchan  likewise  attempted,  in  his  'Tacite  et 
son  siScle,'  1851,  to  find  in  the  history  of  Rome  the  justifi- 
cation of  Caesarism  in  France.  He  contrasted  the  Republic 
and  the  Empire  to  the  disadvantage  in  almost  all  respects  of 
the  former ;  maintained  that  the  Caesars  were  not  only  useful 
but  necessary  men;  and  sought  to  discredit,  as  far  as  he 
could,  the  reputation  of  the  immortal  historian  who  had 
shown  what  Roman  Caesarism  actually  was.  With  the  same 
aim,  and  with  the  same  desire  to  recommend  himself  to  the 
new  Caesar,  the  celebrated  jurist  M.  Troplong,  in  his  study 
'Sur  les  fautes  et  les  crimes  qui  precipiterent  la  chute  de 
larepublique  romaine'  ('Rev.  Con.,'  t.  xxi.,  xxiii.,  xxviii.), 
gave  a  most  unfavourable  view  of  all  those  who  had  opposed 
the  great  Julius.  He  showed  in  it  a  want  of  moral  percep- 
tion, an  inability  to  distinguish  right  and  wrong  from  failure 
and  success,  most  deplorable  in  a  judge  and  jurist. 

The  best  book  of  the  class  under  notice  was  the  'Histoire 
de  Jules  Caesar'  (2  vols.,  1865),  written  by  Napoleon  III. 
himself.  While  not  displaying  great  .talent  of  any  kind,  it 
bore  abundant  traces  of  carefulness  and  industry,  and  em- 
bodied the  results  of  special  surveys  and  researches  which  the 


566  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN  .FRANCE 

author  had  caused  to  be  made.  It  is  undoubtedly  of  consid- 
erable value.  It  was  avowedly  written  with  the  intention 
of  proving  "that  when  Providence  raises  up  such  men  as 
Caesar,  Charlemagne,  and  Napoleon,  it  is  to  trace  out  to  peo- 
ples the  path  which  they  ought  to  follow ;  to  stamp  with  the 
seal  of  their  genius  a  new  epoch ;  and  to  accomplish  in  a  few 
years  the  work  of  many  centuries."  "Happy  are  the  peoples 
which  comprehend  and  follow  them!  Woe  to  those  that 
misunderstand  and  oppose  them!  Like  the  Jews,  they 
crucify  their  Messiah."  The  personal  interest  of  the  author 
obviously  determined  his  choice  of  this  thesis ;  but  there  is 
nothing  to  complain  of  in  the  way  in  which  he  maintains  it, 
which  is  ingenuous  and  dignified,  and  free  from  aught  akin 
to  the  insolence  of  Romieu  or  the  servility  and  spitefulness 
of  Troplong.  The  admiration  which  he  professes  for  Caesar 
is  immense,  but  obviously  sincere,  and  not  altogether  with- 
out discrimination;  and  if  his  estimate  of  the  character  and 
policy  of  his  hero  may  be  in  various  respects  questioned,  it 
can  at  least  be  said  for  it  that  it  is  substantially  identical 
with  that  of  Mommsen  and  Froude,  and  not  decisively  dis- 
provable.  He  shows  himself  to  us  as  a  worshipper  of  political 
genius ;  as  a  believer  in  fate  or  destiny,  which  he  confounds 
with  Providence ;  and  as  a  vague  and  hazy  thinker,  with  a 
tendency  to  speculation  but  no  real  aptitude  for  it. 

In  all  the  works  just  noticed,  Roman  history  is  treated  as 
the  norm  or  type  of  universal  history;  and  it  is  compared 
with  the  historj^  of  France,  in  order  that  the  Napoleons  may 
have  a  place  assigned  them  therein  corresponding  to  that  of 
the  Caesars  in  the  history  of  Rome.  There  could  hardly  be 
a  more  superficial  way  of  regarding  history,  or  a  feebler 
method  of  attempting  to  refute  the  historical  doctrine  of 
republican  liberalism  and  to  justify  imperialism.  It  was, 
in  fact,  not  only  a  logical  inconsistency  but  a  strategical 
blunder  in  the  party  of  force  and  action  to  appeal  to  reason 
and  betake  itself  to  discussion  at  all.  For,  although  it  had 
gained  possession  of  the  will  and  sabre  of  France,  it  had  not 
succeeded  in  appropriating  her  intellect  and  pen.  With  few 
exceptions,  her  eminent  thinkers  and  distinguished  writers 
were  in  the  opposing  camp,  irreconcilably  hostile  to  the 
Empire  and  to  its  principles  and  methods.     The  advocacy  of 


ANTI-CLESARISM  567 

Csesarism  on  historical  grounds  in  the  interests  of  the  Empire 
afforded  democratic  publicists  and  historians  a  welcome  op- 
portunity of  assailing  it,  and  indicated  how  this  might  be 
done.  The  theory  which  sought  its  vindication  in  the  his- 
tory of  Julius  Caesar  could  be,  with  more  relevancy  and  effect, 
attacked  through  the  history  of  Napoleon  I. ;  and  every  such 
attack,  if  skilfully  and  vigorously  conducted,  could  not  fail 
to  tell  heavily  against  Napoleon  III. 

It  is  not  to  be  wondered  at,  therefore,  that  during  the  reign 
of  Napoleon  III.  a  favourite  subject  of  historical  study 
among  the  democratic  writers  of  Fiance  should  have  been 
Napoleon  I.,  or  that  they  should  have  scrutinised  his  char- 
acter and  action  with  at  least  no  prejudice  in  his  favour. 
When  Napoleon  III.  ordered  the  publication  of  the  'Corre- 
spondance  de  Napoleon  I.,'  he  rendered  a  great  service  to 
the  cause  of  historical  truth,  but  the  reverse  of  &  service  to 
Napoleonism ;  he  rendered  easy  the  task  of  the  hostile  critics 
of  the  first  Emperor,  and  impossible  any  moral  admiration 
of  him.1  Of  the  anti-Bonapartist  historical  literature  which 
appeared  under  the  Second  Empire,  such  studies  as  those  of 
Charras,  Quinet,  and  Littre-  on  the  campaigns  of  1815,  had 
for  aim  to  indicate  the  limitations  of  the  military  genius  of 
Napoleon,  and  the  faults  which  he  had  committed  even  as  a 
commander.  The  'Napoleon  et  son  historien,  M.  Thiers,' 
of  Jules  Barni,  was  a  vigorous,  severe,  and  effective  attack 
both  on  Napoleon  and  on  the  most  brilliant  historian  of  his 
Consulate  and  Empire.  The  'Histoire  de  Napoleon  lcr '  of 
M.  Paul  Lanfrey  was  a  very  able  counterpart  of  the  work  of 
M.  Thiers ;  not  more  impartial,  but  written  under  a  contrary 
bias;  and  not  more  a  perfect  or  definitive  history,  but  one  in 
which  the  moral  side  of  Napoleon's  life  is  more  adequately 
and  faithfully  represented,  and  in  which  an  important  class 
of  documents  too  much  neglected  by  M.  Thiers  are  utilised. 
It  had  an  immense  effect  on  public  opinion. 

All  the  works  just  referred  to  were  intended  to  discredit 
the  dominant  Csesarism.  The  'Th<k>rie  du  ProgreV  1867, 
of  M.  de  Ferron  has  the  same  aim,  but  is  more  general  in  its 

1  The  letters  in  the  first  fifteen  volumes  (embracing  the  period  from  1793  to 
1809)  were  printed  "  without  alteration  or  suppression."  In  the  succeeding  vol- 
umes were  allowed  to  appear  "  only  what  the  Emperor  would  have  printed." 


568  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOKY   IN   FBANCE 

scope,  and  distinctively  philosophical  in  nature.  It  begins 
with  a  sketch  of  the  history  of  the  theory  of  progress,  in 
which  Vico  and  Saint-Simon  are  treated  with  special  appre- 
ciation. The  doctrine  of  Vico  is  elaborately  expounded. 
M.  de  Ferron  combines  Vico's  conception  that  historical 
development  has  had  three  stages,  the  divine,  the  heroic,  and 
the  human,  with  Saint-Simon's  conception  that  organic  and 
critical  periods  have  succeeded  each  other.  These  two  gen- 
eralisations, when  united,  seem  to  him  to  determine  what  is 
the  line  or  course  of  human  progress.  He  makes  a  sustained 
endeavour  to  show  that  they  are  warranted  by  history. 
Greece,  Rome,  France,  and  England  are  represented  as  hav- 
ing had  their  theocratic,  aristocratic,  and  democratic  phases, 
and  the  histories  of  law,  art,  religion,  and  science,  as  having 
exemplified  the  alternation  of  organic  and  critical  epochs. 
Although  unable  to  accept  this  composite  theory,  I  shall  not 
here  discuss  it,  as  I  have  already  dealt  with  the  conception 
of  Saint-Simon,  and  hope,  at  the  appropriate  time,  to  exam- 
ine that  of  Vico. 

Greece  and  Rome  not  only  reached  a  democratic  stage, 
but  they  passed  through  it  into  Csesarism.  The  nations  of 
Europe  either  have  reached,  or  will  reach,  the  same  stage. 
Can  they  avoid  the  same  fate?  That  depends  upon  what 
organisation  can  be  given  to  democracy,  which  again  implies 
a  knowledge  of  the  conditions  and  means  of  progress.  How 
has  progress  been  brought  about  in  the  past?  Has  it  been 
by  authority  or  by  freedom?  M.  de  Ferron  goes  directly  to 
history  in  order  to  discover  what  answer  should  be  returned 
to  this  question.  He  institutes  an  independent  investiga- 
tion into  the  influence  of  the  control  of  society  by  the  State 
on  progress  under  the  Romans  and  in  modern  times,  on  the 
one  hand,  and  into  the  influence  of  liberty  in  France  and 
England,  on  the  other.  His  finding  is  that  the  political 
lessons  Avhich  have  been  inculcated  by  Madame  de  Stael, 
Benjamin  Constant,  M.  de  Tocqueville,  and  M.  Laboulaye, 
in  France,  and  by  John  Locke,  Lord  Macaulay,  and  J.  S. 
Mill,  in  England,  are  alone  those  which  history  warrants; 
while  the  Csesarists,  Saint-Simon,  Louis  Blanc,  and  Thomas 
Carlyle,  recommend  us  to  follow  a  path  which  history  abun- 
dantly proves  to  be  one  of  shame  and  death.     His  argumen- 


THEORISTS   AND   CRITICS    OF   DEMOCRACY  569 

tation  is  always  able,  and  even  where  not  decisive  it  is 
valuable.  In  the  main,  or,  in  other  words,  as  a  proof  from 
facts  of  the  pernicious  tendencies  and  effects  of  Csesarism,  it 
is  entirely  conclusive. 

M.  de  Ferron's  'The'orie  du  Progress  '  is,  then,  an  excellent 
specimen  of  a  legitimate  combination  of  historical  and  politi- 
cal science,  or  of  the  application  of  the  historical  method  to 
the  confirmation  of  political  truth.  In  later  writings  he  has, 
with  equal  solidity  and  judiciousness,  employed  the  same 
method  to  solve  other  political  problems  of  vital  importance.1 

The  deplorable  aberrations  of  democracy  in  1848  and  1871 
damped  and  moderated  a  too  enthusiastic  faith  in  its  prom- 
ises, revealed  its  defects,  and  deepened  and  diffused  a  sense 
of  its  dangers.  While  not  arresting  the  spread  of  democracy 
in  France,  they  taught  all  teachable  men  in  it  that  the  dem- 
ocratic movement,  like  every  other  great  social  movement, 
carries  within  it  terrible  possibilities  of  evil;  and  that  the 
exclusive  and  entire  realisation  of  the  ordinary  democratic 
ideal  of  society  would  be  neither  the  perfection  of  govern- 
ment nor  a  goal  worthy  of  history.  The  results  are  to  be 
seen  even  in  literature  in  various  forms. 

For  instance,  it  has  led  some  sincere  and  thoughtful 
democrats  to  labour  earnestly  to  give  greater  precision,  con- 
sistency, and  completeness  to  the  democratic  ideal;  and 
especially  to  seek  to  trace  the  conditions  —  educational,  in- 
dustrial, political,  moral,  juridical,  and  religious — requi- 
site to  secure  a  gradual,  peaceable,  and  beneficent  approxima- 
tion to  it.  This  has  been  the  origin  of  various  interesting 
and  instructive  works ;  one  of  the  ablest  and  most  typical  of 
the  class,  perhaps,  being  the  'De'niocratie '  of  the  eminent 
philosophical  thinker,  M.  Vacherot.2 

1 '  Institutions  municipales  et  provinciates  compare'es  dans  les  differents  Etats 
de  l'Europe,'  1883.  From  the  historical  and  comparative  study  of  these  institu- 
tions, M.  de  Ferron  draws  conclusions  as  to  how  they  should  he  reformed  and  de- 
veloped. 'De  la  division  du  ponvoir  le'gislatif  eu  deux  Chambres,'  1885.  In  this 
work  we  have  first  a  lengthened  historical  account  of  the  division  of  legislative 
power  in  antiquity,  the  middle  age,  the  different  countries  of  modern  Europe,  and 
the  United  States ;  and  next  a  theoretical  and  practical  discussion  of  the  ques- 
tion as  to  the  expediency  of  the  division,  and  as  to  the  best  form  and  method  of 
making  it.  All  who  think  either  of  ending  or  mending  the  House  of  Lords  would 
do  well  to  consider  M.  de.  Ferron's  facts  and  arguments. 

2  The  first  edition  of '  La  Democratic,'  published  at  Paris  in  1859,  was  seized  and 
suppressed  as  treasonable  and  dangerous  to  public  order.    The  author  was  sen- 


570  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Others,  again,  have  probed  the  sores  and  studied  the  dis- 
eases of  contemporary  democracy  with  a  view  to  discover  the 
appropriate  remedies.  They  have  sought  to  substitute  for 
Utopian  socialistic  schemes  legitimate  sociological  generalisa- 
tions based  on  the  close  and  methodical  investigation  of  facts. 
A  powerful  impulse  to  inquiry  of  this  kind  was  given  by  F. 
Le  Play  through  his  'Ouvriers  Europeans,'  1855,  'Biforme 
Sociale, '  1864,  and  '  Organisation  du  travail, '  1870. 

Then  there  are  those  who  have  dealt  with  the  history  and 
theory  of  democracy  in  a  severely  critical  or  positively  hostile 
spirit.  The  late  M.  Renan,  under  the  impressions  pro- 
duced by  the  disasters  of  France  in  her  last  war  with  Ger- 
many, maintained  that)  she  owed  all  her  greatness  in  the  past 
to  the  monarchy,  clergy,  nobility,  and  upper  portion  of  the 
third  estate,  and  her  weaknesses  in  the  present  to  the  pre- 
dominance of  a  democracy  aiming  at  equality  of  material 
advantages;  and  insisted  that  she  could  only  renew  her 
strength  and  regain  her  proper  place  among  the  nations  by 
the  adoption  of  measures  of  education  and  discipline  too 
severe  and  heroic  to  be  other  than  displeasing  to  the  popular 
mind.1  The  volumes  of  M.  Taine  on  the  'Revolution '  have 
been  extremely  unpalatable  reading  to  the  host  of  people  in 
France  who  idealise  and  idolise  that  great  catastrophe. 
Never  before  had  so  fierce  a  light  been  thrown  on  the  confu- 
sion, violence,  and  misery  of  the  time ;  nor  had  the  characters 
of  the  most  typical  and  prominent  of  the  revolutionists  been 
dissected  with  such  merciless  severity.  Although  his  work 
is  one-sided,  and  not  strictly  a  history  of  the  Revolution, 
it  is  a  brilliant  study  on  it,  an  incisive  and  powerful  criti- 
cism of  it,  and  a  valuable  contribution  to  its  psychology. 

Another  keen  critic  of  democracy  is  the  Viscount  Ch. 
d'Ussel  in  his  'Essai  sur  l'esprit  public  dans  l'histoire,' 
1877.     His  work  is,  however,  of  wider  scope  than  those  of 

tenced  by  the  Tribunal  correctionnel  de  Paris  to  twelve  months'  imprisonment. 
The  Gour  impgriale  reduced  the  term  of  imprisonment  to  three  months.  In  the 
second  edition,  published  at  Brussels  in  1861,  all  the  incriminated  passages  are  left 
unaltered  and  printed  in  italics.  The  book  is  throughout  an  unimpassioned  philo- 
sophical discussion. 

1 '  La  Reforme  intellectuelle  et  morale,'  1871.  Compare  Mazzini's  profoundly 
interesting  estimate  of  this  work  in  the  essay,  "M.  Renan  and  France,"  'Fort- 
nightly Review,'  February  1874. 


d'ussel  571 

Eenan  and  Taine,  to  which  we  have  referred,  and  lies  more 
within  the  sphere  of  philosophy.  A  few  words  must  be  said 
regarding  it.  It  is  an  attempt  to  delineate  the  fundamental 
and  ruling  common  thought  or  social  ideal  of  each  of  the 
chief  successive  phases  of  civilisation,  —the  Hebrew,  Greek, 
Roman,  medieval,  modern,  and  contemporary  phases.  Its 
introductory  observations  on  the  origin,  spread,  and  influence 
of  social  ideals,  or,  in  other  words,  on  public  spirit  in  general, 
are  striking  and  good ;  but  the  few  pages  which  are  all  that 
are  devoted  to  "the  general  laws  of  history"  are  altogether 
inadequate.  We  are  told  that  there  is  "  a  law  of  community 
of  the  ideal  in  each  society,"  "a  law  of  speciality  in  the 
vocations  of  peoples, "" a  law  of  cycles,"  "a  law  that  the 
military  and  religious  spirit  are  powerful  in  prosperous 
■epochs,"  and  "a  law  that  intelligence  survives  after  the  loss 
of  the  other  qualities  of  nations  " ;  but  it  is  neither  proved  that 
there  are  such  laws,  nor  even  explained  with  precision  what 
is  meant  by  them.  M.  d'Ussel  shows  an  enthusiastic  admi- 
ration for  the  military  ideal  or  spirit  of  the  warrior.  I  can 
agree,  in  the  main,  with  what  he  says,  understanding  him 
to  speak  of  just  war  and  of  true  soldierly  virtue;  but  he 
might  advantageously,  I  think,  have  dwelt  a  little  on  the 
criminality  of  unjust  war,  and  on  the  baseness  and  selfish- 
ness of  the  motives  which  have  so  often  been  conspicuous  in 
the  prosecution  of  war.  The  chapter  on  the  ideal  of  the 
Hebrews  suffers  from  its  author's  obvious  want  of  acquaint- 
ance with  the  history  of  Hebrew  sacred  literature.  It  is 
not  permissible,  in  the  present  state  of  Biblical  science,  to 
assume,  and  reason  on  the  assumption,  that  the  Pentateuch 
was  written  about  the  sixteenth  century  before  our  era,  or 
to  quote  Bishop  Bossuet  as  an  authority  on  any  question  of 
Old  Testament  criticism.  The  chapters  on  Greece  and 
Rome  are  good;  and  those  on  the  middle  ages,  modern  times, 
and  the  contemporary  period,  are  still  better.  They  abound 
in  just  and  even  original  views,  expressed  with  vividness 
and  force.  But  the  last  chapter  —  that  on  democracy  —  is  the 
most  interesting.  The  rapid  growth  of  democracy  is  fully 
recognised,  and  its  universal  triumph  regarded  as  not  im- 
probable.    The  characters  common  to  it  are  attempted  to  be 


f 


\ 


572  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOKY   IN   FBANCE 

ascertained  by  an  examination  of  its  manifestations  and 
effects  in  countries  where  it  is  dominant  or  becoming  so, — 
Switzerland,  the  United  States,  South  America,  China, 
France,  and  England.  That  there  is  reasonableness  in  its 
principle,  the  equality  of  individuals,  and  in  its  law,  the 
will  of  the  majority,  is  admitted ;  as  also  that  it  tends  to  good 
by  favouring  sociability,  producing  respect  for  labour,  pre- 
venting oppression  of  the  poor  by  the  rich,  and  bringing  the 
means  of  comfort  within  easier  reach  of  all.  On  the  other 
hand,  it  is  strenuously  maintained  that  a  logical  development 
of  the  democratic  principle,  or  an  exclusive  endeavour  to  real- 
ise the  democratic  ideal,  over-excites  selfishness  and  the  de- 
sire of  material  enjoyment,  lowers  the  standard  of  intellect, 
discourages  originality,  independence,  and  genius,  demor- 
alises political  leaders,  and  renders  life  mean  and  prosaic. 
Many  will,  perhaps,  disapprove  of  this  part  of  M.  d'Ussel's 
teaching.  I  am  not  of  the  number.  I  am  convinced  that 
any  absolute  or  exclusive  democracy,  or,  in  other  words,  any 
democracy  which  does  not  sufficiently  appreciate  the  truth 
and  value  of  the  principles  which  theocracy,  monarchy,  and 
aristocracy  erred  not  by  honouring  but  by  exaggerating  and 
misapplying,  will  come  to  an  ignominious  end.  The  de- 
mocracy which  has  so  much  faith  in  the  sovereignty  of  the 
people,  in  the  right  of  majorities,  and  in  the  equality  of 
individuals,  as  to  have  none  in  the  supremacy  of  the  divine 
law,  in  the  necessity  of  a  strong  central  authority  to  main- 
tain peace  or  conduct  war,  and  in  the  justice  and  expediency 
of  giving  free  scope  to  all  inequalities  which  are  not  contrary 
to  but  rooted  in  human  nature,  cannot  fail  to  have  an  inglo- 
rious career,  and  is  likely  to  have  a  short  one. 

This  chapter  may  be  brought  to  a  close  with  a  glance  at  the 
'Lois  de  l'histoire,'  1881,  of  M.  Louis  Benloew.  The  title  is 
appropriate,  for  the  direct  and  main  aim  of  the  work  is  to 
ascertain  and  trace  the  laws  of  historical  movement.  Unfort- 
unately, it  is  just  its  chief  aim,  I  think,  which  it  is  least 
successful  in  accomplishing.  M.  Benloew  starts,  as  many 
others  have  done,  with  the  thought  that  humanity  is  an  evolu- 
tion between  the  successive  stages  of  which  and  those  of  the 
life  of  the  individual  there  is  an  analogy,  so  that  each  great 


BENLOEW  573 

stage  of  history  shows  features  like  to  those  which  characterise 
the  chief  periods  of  personal  development.  The  human  infant 
is  a  heing  in  an  embryonic  state,  in  which  nutrition  is  its  chief 
preoccupation.  But  in  the  measure  that  the  soul  unfolds  itself 
it  is  always  the  more  clearly  seen  to  function  through  its  three 
principal  faculties— sensibility,  will,  and  reason.  These  facul- 
ties imply  each  other,  yet  although  coexistent  are  distinct,  and 
each  in  its  turn  obtains  predominance.  In  youth  sensibility 
rules,  in  mid-life  the  will,  and  in  mature  age  the  reason.  So 
is  it  with  humanity.  It  existed  at  first  in  an  embryonic  state, 
a  period  of  preparation,  in  which  order  was  only  the  product  of 
force.  The  stages  which  follow  are  three :  the  first,  that  of 
sensibility,  ruled  by  the  Ideal  of  the  Beautiful;  the  second, 
that  of  will,  ruled  by  the  Ideal  of  the  Good ;  and  the  third, 
that  of  reason,  ruled  by  the  Ideal  of  the  True. 

The  embryonic  or  preparatory  period  of  which  M.  Benloew 
treats,  is  not,  as  we  might  naturally  expect  it  to  be,  the  pre- 
historic age,  one  of  unknown  but  certainly  vast  duration ;  it  is 
only  a  so-called  primitive  age,  which  extended  from  about  the 
year  4200  to  1200  B.C.,  the  primitive  times  of  Egypt  and  the 
oldest  Asiatic  States.  The  cycle  of  the  Ideal  of  the  Beautiful 
runs  from  B.C.  1200  to  A.r>.  300.  Greece  was  its  glory,  the 
most  perfect  realisation  of  its  ideal.  The  last  600  of  the  1500 
years  assigned  to  it  are  represented  as  a  time  of  transition  to 
the  cycle  of  the  Good.  The  chief  part  of  the  work  of  Rome  is 
regarded  as  having  been  the  mediation  of  this  transition.  The 
cycle  of  the  Good  comprises  also  1500  years :  it  stretches  from 
a.d.  300  to  A.D.  1800.  The  China  of  Confucius,  Buddhism, 
and  later  Hinduism,  Bactria,  and  Persia,  are  represented  as 
having  displayed  imperfect  forms  of  its  ideal ;  Israel  the  per- 
fectible form  ;  Jesus  of  Nazareth  the  perfect  form  ;  and  Islam 
a  secondary  form :  and  we  are  told  how  that  ideal  displayed 
that  of  the  Greco-Roman  world;  evolved  itself  into  medieval 
Christendom;  and  then  passed  into  the  phase  of  decadence. 
The  period  from  the  Renaissance  and  the  Reformation  to  the 
Revolution  is  considered  to  have  been  that  of  transition  to 
the  cycle  of  the  Ideal  of  the  True,  the  highest  form  of  the 
Good.  The  characteristics  of  this  cycle,  the  features  of  this 
new  world,  are  interestingly  delineated.     The  growth  of  self- 


574  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

government  is  traced.  Democracy,  it  is  maintained,  may 
already  safely  feel  confident  that  the  future  belongs  to  it. 
The  work  which  it  is  now  called  to  undertake  is  described  as 
being  to  constitute  the  confederation  of  the  States  of  Europe, 
to  enlighten  and  moralise  the  proletariat,  to  organise  a  vast 
system  of  colonisation,  to  civilise  all  barbarous  peoples,  and 
to  fashion  the  globe  into  a  rich  and  beautiful  habitation  for 
man.  In  a  word,  M.  Benloew  shows  himself  a  democrat  of 
firm  and  hopeful  faith. 

It  seems  to  me  that  he  has  altogether  failed  to  prove  what 
he  regards  as  the  great  law  of  history.  But  had  it  been  prova- 
ble I  am  quite  inclined  to  believe  that  he  would  have  proved 
it.  He  has  distinguished  himself  in  various  departments  of 
philology,  literature,  and  erudition.  The  book  under  our 
consideration  itself  shows  an  exceptionally  wide  and  intimate 
familiarity  with  history.  It  contains  many  luminous  and  in- 
genious views,  and  various  excellent  sections.  Its  estimate 
of  the  significance  of  the  chief  phases  of  Christian  civilisa- 
tion is  especially  remarkable  for  the  insight  and  impartiality 
which  it  displays.  Rarely,  I  should  suppose,  has  a  Jew, 
warmly  attached  to  the  ancient  faith  of  his  race,  appreciated 
so  justly  and  sympathetically  the  influence  of  Christianity 
on  the  history  of  humanity. 

M.  Benloew,  I  may  add,  makes  an  interesting  attempt  (pp. 
291-300),  to  prove  a  law  of  evolutions  of  fifteen  years.  M. 
Soulavie  had  previously  attempted  to  show  that  such  a  law 
was  traceable  in  the  history  of  France  during  the  eighteenth 
century.1  M.  Benloew  maintains  that  it  can  be  verified 
throughout  the  whole  history  of  France,  and  also,  although 
less  distinctly,  in  the  histories  of  most  countries  which  have 
been  drawn  into  the  general  movement  of  civilisation.  I 
shall  consider  laws  of  this  kind  when  I  examine  the  histori- 
cal theories  of  the  late  Joseph  Ferrari. 

1  '  Pifeces  inedites  sur  les  regnes  de  Louis  XIV.,  Louis  XV.,  et  Louis  XVI.,'  1809. 


CHAPTER   X 

HISTORICAL  PHILOSOPHY  OP  NATURALISM  AND  POSITIVISM 


The  sensationalism  or  empiricism  of  the  eighteenth  cen- 
tury was  cast  down  but  not  destroyed,  widely  displaced  but 
not  extinguished,  by  the  religious  and  philosophical  reaction 
■which  set  in  against  it  early  in  the  present  century.  When 
least  popular  it  had  still  some  adherents.  Ideology  contin- 
ued to  be  the  psychology  most  in  favour  with  physicists.  It 
found  a  home  in  the  School  of  Medicine.  It  was  the  source 
whence  the  Saint-Simonians  and  Fourierists  derived  the 
principles  on  which  they  based  their  sociological  construc- 
tions. It  has  survived  the  attacks  of  the  theocratists,  roman- 
ticists, and  spiritualists  of  all  shades  and  schools,  and  has 
even  renewed  its  vigour,  assumed  new  forms,  undertaken 
fresh  enterprises,  and  regained  much  of  the  ground  which  it 
had  lost.  The  representatives  of  the  antagonistic  philosophy 
overlooked  the  necessity  of  giving  an  adequate  place  in  their 
system  of  thought  to  physical  science.  The  seriousness  of 
this  error  has  made  itself  increasingly  felt  with  every  marked 
advance  and  new  development  of  the  physical  sciences,  and 
such  advances  and  developments  have  been  unprecedentedly 
numerous  in  the  present  century.  Hence  sensationalism  has 
to  a  large  extent  regained  its  empire,  and  is  very  prevalent 
in  the  forms  of  Naturalism  and  of  Positivism.  Both  owe 
what  favour  they  enjoy  mainly  to  what  measure  of  plausibil- 
ity they  have  been  able  to  give  to  their  pretensions  to  be  sys- 
tems of  philosophy  founded  on  the  methods  and  conclusions 
of  the  natural  or  positive  sciences.  It  is  not  my  business  to 
discuss  these  pretensions  in  a  general  form,  or  these  systems 
in  themselves.  It  is  only  necessary  for  me  to  treat  of  the 
historical  theorising  to  which  the  principles  and  tendencies  of 

575 


576  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

French  Naturalism  and  Positivism  have  given  rise.  The  first 
two  thinkers  who  have  to  be  brought  under  consideration  both 
bore  the  name  Comte,  but  were  not  related  by  birth,  and  were 
very  unlike  each  other,  intellectually  and  morally. 

Charles  Comte  (1782-1837),  one  of  the  founders  of  Natu- 
ralism, was  born  sixteen  and  died  twenty  years  earlier  than 
Auguste  Comte,  the  founder  of  Positivism.  As  editor  of 
the  '  Censeur, '  and  as  a  member  of  the  Chamber  of  Deputies, 
he  maintained,  in  the  face  of  opposition  and  even  persecution, 
the  principles  of  political  justice  and  liberty  with  a  courage 
and  consistency  which  did  him  infinite  honour.  As  a  man 
he  was  conscientious  and  generous ;  unselfish,  unpretentious, 
and  unambitious;  not  subtle,  profound,  or  brilliant,  but  of 
vigorous  and  sound  judgment,  much  learning,  and  indefatiga- 
ble industry. 

His  "Traite"  de  Legislation '  (4  vols.,  1822-23)  has  been 
deservedly  commended  by  judges  so  competent  as  Sir  G.  C. 
Lewis  and  Mr.  Buckle.  Both  had  found  in  it  aid  and  in- 
struction, as  all  may  do  who  are  engaged  in  the  study  of  his- 
torical and  political  science.  It  is  not,  and  does  not  profess 
to  be,  an  abstract  or  theoretical  treatise  on  legislation. 
Neither  is  it  quite  what  it  does  profess  to  be,  "an  exposition 
of  the  general  laws  according  to  which  peoples  prosper,  per- 
ish, or  remain  stationary,"  seeing  that  it  cannot  be  said  to 
have  established  any  laws  of  the  kind  strictly  so  called.  It  is 
rich  in  instructive  facts  and  judicious  reflections,  but  it  con- 
tains few,  if  any,  properly  historical  laws.  Had  it  realised 
its  author's  aim  it  would  have  been  a  system  of  historical 
philosophy ;  but  this  it  certainly  is  not. 

Charles  Comte  contends  for  the  application  of  the  same 
method  of  study  to  the  moral  world  which  had  been  found 
successful  in  the  case  of  the  physical  world.  His  only  aim, 
he  tells  us,  is  "to  trace  back  the  sciences  of  legislation  and 
morals  to  the  simple  observation  of  facts,  and  so  to  give  to 
them  the  same  certainty  which  has  been  given  to  others  less 
important."  But  he  recognises  such  facts  only  as  are  not  of 
an  individual  but  of  a  social  character ;  only  the  manners  and 
history  of  nations,  not  states  of  personal  consciousness.  Like 
Auguste  Comte,  he  treats  the  introspective  or  psychological 


CHARLES   OOMTB  577 

method  as  illegitimate  and  futile.  To  study  aright  those 
external,  social,  or  historical  facts  which  are  alone,  in  his 
view,  to  be  relied  on,  he  insists  on  our  examining  them  with- 
out prejudices  of  any  kind,  and  uninfluenced  by  religious 
beliefs,  moral  convictions,  or  philosophical  speculations.  He 
overlooks  to  what  a  vast  extent  historical  development  is  a 
psychological  process,  and,  therefore,  only  explicable  by  psy- 
chological analysis  and  induction.  Not  exclusive  attention 
to  fact,  but  failure  to  recognise  an  immense  department 
of  fact,  is  the  sole  source  and  whole  secret  of  his  "nat- 
uralism." 

It  is  impossible,  he  thinks,  to  account  for  the  origin  of 
society.  The  attempt  of  Rousseau  to  do  so  he  subjects  to  a 
criticism  perhaps  the  most  searching  and  severe  which  it  has 
ever  received.  It  is  more  crushing  than  any  which  came  from 
the  theocratic  school,  inasmuch  as  it  is  more  unimpassioned. 
While  implacably  calm,  it  leaves  unexposed  hardly  anything 
that  is  false  in  the  alleged  facts,  sophistical  in  the  pretended 
arguments,  hollow  or  exaggerated  in  the  declamations,  or 
pernicious  in  the  doctrines,  of  the  author  of  the  'Contrat 
Social. ' 

C.  Comte's  discussion  of  the  questions  which  relate  to  the 
influence  of  physical  nature  on  human  development  must  have 
been  the  fruit  of  long  and  careful  study.  It  was  as  great  an 
advance  on  Montesquieu's  treatment  of  the  subject  as  Mon- 
tesquieu's had  been  on  that  of  Bodin.  It  disproved,  corrected, 
or  confirmed  a  host  of  Montesquieu's  observations  and  con- 
clusions. It  showed  that  he  had  ascribed  too  much  to  cli- 
mate, and  too  little  to  the  configuration  of  the  earth's  surface, 
the  distribution  of  mountains  and  rivers,  &c. ;  and  that  he 
had  conceived  vaguely,  and  even  to  a  large  extent  errone- 
ously, of  the  modes  in  which  climate  and  the  fertility  or  ste- 
rility of  soil  affect  human  development.  But  while  Comte 
thus  justly  criticised  Montesquieu,  he  himself  exaggerated 
the  efficiency  of  physical  agencies.  Indeed,  he  virtually  traced 
to  their  operation  the  whole  development  of  historjr.  And 
this  he  could  not  consistently  avoid  doing.  Having  assumed 
that  human  nature  was  essentially  sensation  conditioned  by 
organisation,  and,  consequently,  essentially  passive,  he  could 


578  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOKY  IN  FRANCE 

not  logically  avoid  holding  also  that  the  development  of 
human  nature  and  the  evolution  of  human  society  have  been 
absolutely  determined  by  the  factors  which  modify  the  bodily 
organisation  and  act  on  the  bodily  senses  of  men.  Accord- 
ingly he  has  assumed  that  physical  agencies  ultimately 
account  for  historical  change  and  movement,  for  public  in- 
stitutions and  laws.  To  the  influence  of  race  he  has  ascribed 
only  a  secondary  and  subordinate  place  among  these  agencies. 
He  maintains  that  the  distinctions  of  race  are  not  primary  or 
specific,  but  explicable  by  the  action  of  climate  and  the  physi- 
cal medium. 

Various  authors  have  represented  civilisation  as  advancing 
from  east  to  west.  According  to  Charles  Comte  it  has  spread 
from  the  equator  northwards.  "  When  we  watch  the  course 
of  civilisation  on  each  of  the  chief  divisions  of  the  earth,  we 
see  enlightenment  at  first  acquired  in  warm  climates;  then 
expand  into  temperate  climates;  and  at  length  stop  at,  or 
hardly  penetrate  into,  cold  climates."  Had  he  proved  this 
proposition  he  would  not  have  demonstrated  a  law,  but  have 
simply  indicated  a  general  fact,  presupposing  law  and  re- 
quiring explanation.  But  he  has  not  proved  it.  There  is 
no  evidence  that  civilisation  originated  at  the  equator;  no 
likelihood  even  that  it  originated  either  in  the  moister  or  the 
drier  parts  of  the  torrid  zone,  alike  unfavourable  as  they  are 
to  the  development  of  man.  The  lands  earliest  civilised, 
Comte  says,  were  China,  Hindostan,  Persia,  a  part  of  Arabia, 
Egypt,  and  Asia  Minor.  But  none  of  these  lands  are  on  the 
equator;  and  most  of  them  are  a  long  way  from  it.  Further, 
it  is  not  certain  that  the  civilisation  of  any  of  these  countries 
was  original,  or  how  their  civilisations  were  related  to  one 
another.  The  oldest  remains,  indeed,  of  great  cities  are  to 
be  found  in  these  lands;  but  civilisation  must  surely  have 
long  preceded  architectural  achievements,  which  are  in  many 
cases  as  remarkable  as  those  of  the  present  day. 

Charles  Comte  fully  recognises  that  the  same  physical 
medium  has  a  very  different  influence  on  different  genera- 
tions ;  and  that  institutions  and  laws,  education  and  manners, 
and,  in  a  word,  all  the  constituents  of  the  social  medium, 
have  as  real  an  influence  on  the  development  of  history  as 
those  of  the  physical  medium.  Yet  he  assumes  the  latter  to 


AUGUSTE   GOMTE  579 

be  the  first,  although  to  a  large  extent  only  indirect,  causes 
of  the  whole  amount  of  change  effected.  A  human  nature  in 
itself  utterly  empty  and  passive  must  be  built  up  through  the 
senses  from  without.  It  may  be  the  subject  of  history,  but 
it  cannot  be  also  its  chief  factor.  Here  lay  Charles  Comte's 
radical  error.  He  failed  to  perceive  that  the  intelligence, 
the  imagination,  the  passions,  the  conscience,  and  the  will 
of  man  are  more  direct  and  powerful  historical  agencies  than 
climate  or  soil.  The  human  soul  itself  is  the  main  and  dis- 
tinctive source  of  history.  History  is  essentially  the  work 
and  manifestation  of  human  nature.  A  true  science  of  his- 
tory can  only  be  attained  through  the  investigation  of  history 
as  a  psychological  phenomenon, —  a  product  of  mind,  influ- 
enced but  not  generated  by  the  physical  medium  in  which  it 
appears.1 

Auguste  Comte  was  born  at  Montpellier  in  1798.  Al- 
though both  his  parents  were  Legitimists  and  Catholics,  he 
had  become  at  fourteen  years  of  age  a  republican  and  an  un- 
believer. He  was  educated  at  the  Lyceum  of  Montpellier 
(1807-14),  and  at  the  Polytechnic  School  of  Paris  (1814-16), 
from  which  he  was  expelled  on  account  of  insubordination. 
As  a  student  he  was  diligent  but  intractable;  he  excelled 
especially  in  mathematics,  but  gave  proofs  of  a  generally 
powerful  intellect,  and  devoted  much  time  to  private  reading 
and  reflection.  While  at  the  Polytechnic  School  he  perused 
the  works  of  most  of  the  leading  philosophical  writers  of  the 
eighteenth  century.  Shortly  after  his  expulsion  from  it  he 
began  his  literary  career.2     From  1817  to  1824  he  was  closely 

1  The  fourth  volume  of  the  '  Traits '  is  one  of  the  best  studies  on  slavery  and 
its  effects  ever  published. 

2  The  earliest  essay  of  Comte  which  has  been  published,  '  Mes  reflexions,'  is 
of  date  June  1816.  It  is,  for  the  most  part,  a  parallel  between  "  the  tyrants  of 
the  Terror  and  the  tyrants  of  the  Restoration,"  in  which  "  eleven  points  of 
resemblance  "  are  insisted  upon.  It  displays  an  intense  hatred  of  Louis  XVIII. 
It  gives  expression  also  to  that  aversion  to  Napoleon  which  Comte  retained  to 
the  end  of  his  life,  and  which  led  him  to  recommend,  in  the  fourth  volume  of 
the  '  System  of  Positive  Polity,'  that  the  ashes  of  the  Conqueror  should  be  sent 
back  to  St.  Helena,  his  column  in  the  Place  Vendome  cast  down,  and  "  a  noble 
statue  of  Charlemagne,  the  incomparable  founder  of  the  Western  Republic " 
substituted  for  it.  This  essay  first  appeared  in  Renouvier's  'Crit.  phil.'  for 
June  1882.  The  Appendix  to  the  fourth  volume  of  the  'System'  contains  a 
series  of  essays  'originally  published  at  various  dates  between  1819  and  1828, 
including  that  of  1822,  in  which  Comte  first  stated  what  he  regarded  as  his  great 


580  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

associated  with  Saint-Simon.  In  1826  he  began  to  expound 
his  philosophy  in  a  course  of  lectures,  which  was  interrupted 
for  a  lengthened  period  by  insanity.  The  first  volume  of  his 
'Cours  de  philosophic  positive '  appeared  in  1830,  and  the 
last  (sixth)  in  1842.  This  is  far  the  most  important  of  his 
works ;  and  is  even,  perhaps,  notwithstanding  many  imper- 
fections, the  most  important  work  which  had  appeared  up  to 
the  time  of  its  publication  in  one  great  department  of  philoso- 
phy —  philosophy  as  the  theory  of  the  sciences,  or,  as  Comte 
calls  it,  positive  philosoph)^.  And  whatever  else  philosophy 
may  or  should  be,  it  is  clearly  bound  to  be  what  Comte,  in 
his  great  work,  represents  it  with  so  much  ability  and  general 
truthfulness  as  being  —  namely,  science,  yet  not  merely  a 
special  science,  but  the  science  which  has  the  processes  and 
results  of  all  the  special  sciences  for  its  data :  the  general  or 
universal  science  which  has  so  risen  above  the  special  and 
particular  in  science  as  to  be  able  to  contemplate  the  sciences 
as  parts  of  a  system  which  reflects  and  elucidates  a  world  of 
which  the  variety  is  not  more  wonderful  than  the  unity. 
With  the  completion  of  his  'Cours  '  Comte  worthily  closed 
the  first  period  or  phase  of  his  philosophical  career.  He  had, 
as  he  thought,  elaborated  a  strictly  scientific  philosophy,  based 
on  the  co-ordination  and  generalisation  of  all  the  sciences, 
and  established  and  evolved  in  a  truly  rational  manner.  He 
held  that  he  had  transformed  science  into  philosophy  by  a 
self-consistent  and  comprehensive  logical  process  which  ad- 
vances from  the  general  to  the  special,  from  the  universe  to 
man ;  and  this  so  as  to  show  the  falsity  and  futility  of  all 
theological  and  metaphysical  philosophy,  and  to  provide  an 

discovery  of  the  law  of  the  Three  States.  These  essays  are  very  interesting, 
exhibit  the  best  qualities  of  their  author's  mind,  and  form  the  best  introduction 
to  his  other  writings.  They  were  collected  and  republished  by  him  in  order  to 
prove  that  his  "  political  system,  far  from  being  opposed  to  his  philosophy,  is  so 
completely  its  outcome,  that  the  latter  was  created  as  the  basis  of  the  former." 
He  had  published  others  which  have  not  yet  been  identified ;  and  which  he  did 
not  wish  to  be  brought  to  light,  for  the  reason  given  in  the  following  naive  and 
suggestive  words:  "Those  alone  are  preserved  which  reveal  any  characteristic 
aspirations,  all  such  being  set  aside  as  betray  the  unfortunate  personal  influence 
that  overshadowed  my  earliest  efforts.  ...  I  disavow  any  other  edition,  and  I 
have  destroyed  the  unpublished  materials."  —  See  Special  Preface  to  General 
Appendix.  My  quotations  from  the  '  System  '  are  from  the  English  translation, 
which  is  an  almost  perfect  rendering  of  the  original. 


AUGUSTE   COMTE  581 

indispensable  and  solid  basis  for  a  definitive  doctrine  of 
social  organisation,  such  as  he  had  from  the  beginning  of  his 
connection  with  Saint-Simon  had  in  view.  But  he  had  still 
to  work  out  this  doctrine.  To  do  so  was  the  task  to  which 
he  devoted  the  second  part  of  his  life  —  that  in  which  the 
following  works  were  produced:  'Discours  sur  l'ensembledu 
positivisme, "  1848,  'SystSme  de politique  positive,'  1851-54, 
'Cate'chisme  positiviste, '  1852,  and  'Synthese  subjective,' 
1856.  The  'SystSme  '  embodies  nearly  the  whole  thinking 
of  Comte's  life  during  the  second  period.  It  was  deemed  by 
its  author  his  chief  work,  and  is  generally  so  regarded  by 
orthodox  Comtists  —  a  judgment  in  which  I  cannot  at  all 
concur.  The  general  results  which  had  been  reached  in  the 
'Cours '  are  retained  in  the  'Syst&me, '  and  the  end  to  which 
the  former  was  designed  to  be  a  preparation  is  in  the  latter 
directly  sought  to  be  realised ;  but  the  points  of  view  taken 
up  in  the  two  works  are  opposed,  the  methods  followed  are 
different,  and  the  general  character  of  the  doctrine  in  passing 
from  the  one  to  the  other  has  been  profoundly  changed.  In 
the  later  years  of  his  life  Comte  was  absorbed  in  the  exercise 
of  his  functions  as  "the  high  priest  of  humanity,"  and  in 
endeavouring  to  gain  converts  to  his  system  of  polity  and 
worship.  He  died  on  the  5th  September  1857,  in  Paris,  at 
Rue  Monsieur-le-Prince  10  —  the  most  sacred  spot  on  earth 
in  the  eyes  of  the  religious  positivists  of  all  lands.1 

Comte's  philosophy  of  nature  and  of  history  originated  in 
the  interaction  within  his  mind  of  the  chief  intellectual  and 

1  As  to  the  life,  system,  and  influence  of  Comte,  in  addition  to  his  own  works 
already  mentioned,  his  letters  to  Valat,  and  his  '  Testament,'  the  following 
writings  may  be  indicated  as  among  those  most  worthy  of  being  consulted: 
Littre",  'Auguste  Comte  et  la  philosophie  positive,'  and  'Fragments  de  philo- 
sophic positive ' ;  Eobinet,  '  Notice  sur  l'ceuvre  et  sur  la  vie  d'A.  Comte '  ; 
'Revue  Occidentale,'  1878-92;  C.  de  Blignieres,  'Exposition  de  la  philosophie 
positive '  ;  Ch.  Pellarin,  '  Essai  critique  sur  la  philosophie  positive ' ;  Poey, 
'Le  positivisme';  Lewes,  'Philosophy  of  the  Sciences';  J.  S.  Mill,  'Auguste 
Comte  and  Positivism ' ;  E.  Caird,  '  The  Social  Philosophy  and  Religion  of 
Comte';  and  Hermann  Gruber,  S.  J., 'August  Comte,  der  Begriinder  des 
Positivismus,'  and  '  Der  Positivismus  vom  Tode  August  Comte's  bis  auf  unsere 
Tage'  (1857-1891).  Among  the  host  of  pamphlets,  lectures,  and  essays  on 
Comtism  which  have  appeared  in  this  country,  those  of  Bridges,  Congreve,  Har- 
rison, Huxley,  Martineau,  Spencer,  Tulloch,  Whewell,  &c,  are  too  well  known  to 
require  to  be  more  exactly  specified.  Similar  publications  have  been  at  least  as 
numerous  in  France,  and  not  rare  in  Germany,  Italy,  and  America. 


582  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

social  movements  in  the  France  of  his  age.  It  was  a  sort 
of  synthesis,  instructive  even  in  its  inconsistency  because 
reflecting  the  incoherence  and  self-contradiction  of  a  disor- 
ganised and  transitional  epoch.  It  can  only  be  understood 
aright  when  viewed  in  relation  to  the  movements  and  ten- 
dencies to  which  it  owed  its  being  and  form. 

Comte  was  thoroughly  French,  the  direct  and  immediate 
influences  which  moulded  his  life  and  doctrine  being  almost 
exclusively  French.  He  was  very  slightly  affected  by  Ger- 
man thought.  He  was  to  the  end  of  his  life  virtually  igno- 
rant of  German  philosophy.  In  1843  he  consulted  Mr.  Mill  as 
to  the  advisability  of  making  some  general  acquaintance  with 
German  philosophical  doctrines,  but,  on  being  dissuaded, 
abandoned  the  idea.1  It  is  true  that  in  1824  his  friend  M. 
d'Eichtal  sent  him  from  Berlin  a  translation  which  he  had 
made  for  him  of  Kant's  short  essay,  "Idea  of  a  Universal 
History,"  and  that  Comte  expressed  in  reply  the  warmest 
admiration  of  it;  but  in  1824  he  had  already  discovered  his 
sociological  laws,  and  his  political  convictions  were  defini- 
tively formed.  There  are  no  traces  in  his  writings  of  ac- 
quaintance with  either  the  metaphysical  or  ethical  works  of 
Kant.  It  is  quite  certain  that  his  classification  of  the  sciences 
was  not  suggested,  as  J.  D.  Morell  and  others  have  supposed, 
by  acquaintance  with  Schelling's  successive  "potences"of 
the  Absolute.  He  once  pronounced  Hegel  "un  homme  de 
me"rite,"  but  it  was  when  he  hoped  he  might  be  made  use  of 
to  spread  positivism  in  Germany;  and  he  has  .assigned  him 
a  place  in  the  'Positivist  Calendar,'  but  as  the  coequal  of 
Sophie  Germain.  Any  coincidences  which  have  been  pointed 
out  between  the  views  of  Comte  and  Hegel  are  of  such  a 
nature  as  would  not,  although  multiplied  fifty-fold,  prove  in 
the  least  that  the  former  had  borrowed  from  the  latter.  They 
relate  to  views  of  which  Hegel  was  neither  the  author  nor 
the  sole  proprietor,  which  he  only  shared  with  hundreds  of 
other  thinkers,  and  which  were  current  in  the  catholic  and 
socialistic  medium  in  which  Comte  lived.  Why  label  as 
"  Hegelian  "  what  were  commonplaces  among  the  adherents 
of  socialism  and  the  theological   reaction?     Why  suppose 

1  Littre,  '  Auguste  Comte,'  pp.  446,  447. 


AUGTJSTE   COMTE  583 

Comte  to  have  derived  from  a  distance  opinions  which  were 
floating  in  the  intellectual  atmosphere  around  him,  and  to  be 
had  for  the  inbreathing  ? x 

The  generation  which  lived  under  the  First  Empire  knew 
no  other  philosophy  than  that  which  had  become  prevalent 
before  the  Revolution.  Comte  came  under  the  influence  of 
this  philosophy  in  early  youth ;  at  the  Polytechnic  School  he 
read  the  works  of  most  of  its  leading  representatives.  He 
accepted  its  cardinal  principle  that  "thought  depends  on 
sense,  or,  more  broadly,  on  the  environment";  he  became 
imbued  with  its  aversion  to  metaphysics  and  theology,  and 
with  its  ardent  faith  in  physical  science ;  and  he  set  himself 
to  build,  up  all  the  materials  of  knowledge  into  one  grand 
and  solid  edifice,  resting  on  the  foundation  which  it  had  laid. 
Considered  simply  as  a  philosophy,  the  positivism  of  Comte 
is  essentially  a  continuation  of  the  empirical  philosophy  of 
the  eighteenth  century,  any  superiority  over  earlier  forms  of 
that  philosophy  being  mainly  due  to  the  remarkable  develop- 
ment of  the  several  sciences  which  have  been  combined  by  it 
into  a  single  theoretical  system.  It  is  otherwise  with  posi- 
tivism as  a  social  doctrine.  Social  and  religious  reactions 
generally  precede  philosophical  reactions.  In  France  the 
social  and  religious  reaction  was  in  full  force  before  the  phil- 
osophical reaction  made  itself  felt.  Comte  yielded  to  it. 
Hence  two  contrary  and  contending  currents  of  thought  met 
and  mingled  in  his  mind,  and  made  of  his  intellectual  life 
an  inherent  and  permanent  contradiction.  He  was  intensely 
hostile  to  what  he  regarded  as  the  anarchical  and  revolution- 
ary tendencies  of  the  eighteenth  century.  He  hated  individ- 
ualism, laisser  /aire,  and  such  "  rights  of  man  "  as  private 
judgment,  human  equality,  and  sovereignty  of  the  people. 

1  Comte  owed  more  to  Scottish  than  to  German  writers.  Hume  he  acknowl- 
edges to  have  been  his  "  chief  philosophical  precursor  " ;  and  he  often  so  refers  to 
Mm  as  to  show  that  he  had  studied  both  his  '  Essays  '  and  his  '  History.'  He  avows 
his  indebtedness  to  Adam  Smith's  '  Wealth  of  Nations ' ;  and,  writing  in  1825, 
says  of  the  '  Philosophical  Essay  on  the  History  of  Astronomy ' :  "  This  work,  too 
little  known  on  the  Continent,  and  generally  insufficiently  appreciated,  is  more 
positive  in  its  character  than  the  other  productions  of  Scottish  philosophy,  those 
of  Hume  excepted.  Remarkable  in  its  day,  it  may  even  yet  be  studied  with 
great  advantage."  —  Pos.  Pol.,  iv.  591.  He  has  given  both  Robertson  and  Fergu- 
son a  place  in  the  '  Positivist  Calendar.'       * 


584  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

His  sympathies  were  more  with  the  reaction  than  with  the 
Revolution.  He  speaks  of  the  services  rendered  by  the 
representatives  of  the  former  with  an  enthusiastic  recogni- 
tion which  he  never  manifests,  except  in  the  case  of  Con- 
dorcet,  to  those  of  the  latter.  He  thought  revolutionary  ideas 
had  overdone  their  work;  that  destruction  had  been  carried 
to  excess ;  and  that  construction  was  much  more  needed.  For 
his  estimate  of  the  medieval  type  of  society,  and  of  medieval 
institutions,  he  was  indebted  to  writers  of  the  theocratic 
school..  He  showed  for  De  Maistre  a  somewhat  excessive 
admiration :  '  Le  Pape '  was,  I  think,  the  source  of  more  of 
his  ideas  than  any  other  single  book.  It  was  De  Maistre 
and  De  Bonald,  he  has  said,  who  taught  him  that  "  the  past 
as  a  whole  could  not  be  understood  unless  it  be  steadily 
respected."1  Yet  he  had  no  sympathy  with  the  deeper  and 
truly  spiritual  convictions  and  feelings  of  the  theocratists ; 
with  their  faith  in  God  and  Christ,  their  sense  of  sin  and 
craving  for  sanctity,  their  consciousness  of  the  need  of 
redemption  and  divine  guidance,  and  their  aspiration  tow- 
ards a  real  immortality.  In  one  respect,  however,  he  saw 
more  clearly  than  they:  he  never  fell  into  their  illusion  that 
the  future  of  society  would  be  essentially  a  reproduction  of 
the  past.  He  perceived  that  mere  reaction  must  have  always 
a  very  temporary  success;  that  humanity  never  simply 
returns  to  a  position  which  it  has  once  abandoned.  Natur- 
ally he  showed  himself  more  conscious  of  the  retrograde 
character  of  the  teaching  of  the  reactionists  in  the  earlier, 
than  in  the  later  period  of  his  life:  and  yet  he  became 
increasingly  dependent  on  them,  and  indebted  to  them,  as 
he  became  more  retrograde  in  his  own  aims,  more  zealous 
and  ambitious  to  be  accepted  as  the  supreme  legislator  of 
humanity :  or,  in  other  words,  as*  he  advanced  in  the  trans- 
formation of  his  system,  into  an  atheistical  Popery,  with 
himself  for  chief  priest  and  sole  prophet. 

The  connection  of  positivism  with  socialism  was  of  the 
closest  kind.  The  socialistic  movement  aimed  at  the  rejec- 
tion of  what  was  false  and  the  retention  and  development  of 
what  was  true  both  ir^the  reactionary  an&in~the  revolution- 

1  Pos.  Pol.,  iii.  527.  The  literffl  rendering  of  "tne  last  words  of  the  sentence  is, 
"  without  an  unchangeable  veneration." 


AUGUSTE   COMTE  585 

ary  movement.     It  sought  to  overcome  the  existing  anarchy 
and  to  organise  society  by  following  the  guidance  and  em- 
ploying the  methods  of  modern  science.     Positivism  arose 
directly  and  entirely  out  of  this  movement.     It  is  an  offshoot 
or  variety  of  socialism,  and,  indeed,  of  Saint-Simonian  social- 
ism.    The  socialism  of  Saint-Simon  contained  all  the  germs 
of  the  positivism  of   Comte.      Almost   every  leading  idea 
which  Comte  expounded  and  applied  had  been  previously 
enunciated  by  Saint-Simon.     Comte  was  to  the  end  of  his 
days,  as  regards  the  cardinal  principles  of  his  system,  a  dis- 
ciple of  Saint-Simon,  although  a  very  ungrateful  one,  jeal- 
ously anxious  to  be  supposed  not  to  have  been  indebted  to 
him.     Let  us  recall  to  mind  in  a  general  way  what  Saint- 
Simon  preceded  Comte  in  teaching.     Repeatedly  he  used  the 
term  positif  in  the  sense  which  suggested  the  formation  of 
the  .term  positivism.      He   employed  habitually  the   word 
"philosophy"  to  denote  precisely  what  Comte  meant  by  it. 
Thus  he  says :  "  The  particular  sciences  are  the  elements  of 
the  general  science  to  which  we  give  the  name  of  philosophy ; 
so  philosophy  has  necessarily  had,  and  always  will  have,  the 
same  character  as  the  particular  sciences."     Then,  just  as 
Comte  afterwards  did,  he  insisted  that  the  only  legitimate 
method  of  finding  truth  is  the  immediate  investigation  of 
facts,  the  data  of  the  senses ;  and  he  equally  inferred  that 
knowledge  is  limited  to  the  relative  and  phenomenal,  and 
that  belief  in  aught  absolute  or  supersensuous,  in  entities  or 
substances,  in  efficient  or  final  causes,  in  God  or  soul,  must 
be  mystical  and  chimerical.     Instructed  by  Dr.  Burdin,  he 
further  taught  that  science  as  a  whole  and  all  its  divisions 
pass  from  a  conjectural  into  a  positive  state,  from  theolo- 
gism  into  positivism,  through  a  transitional  state  partly  con- 
jectural and  partly  positive;   that  the   chief   divisions    of 
science  have  done  so  in  an  order  determined  by  the  degree  of 
the  generality  and  complexity  of  their  objects;  that  these 
sciences  are  mathematics,  astronomy,  chemistry,  and  phys- 
iology; and  that  the  order  of  their  discovery  is  also  that  in 
which  they  should  be  studied.     Psychology  he  represented 
as  a  mere  derivative  from  physiology,  not  as  an  independent 
science,  or  one  of  a  distinct  group.     Physiology  he  main- 
tained had  at  length  passed  into   the   positive  stage,   and 


586  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FKANCE 

morals  and  politics  were  about  to  do  so.  Philosophy  he 
asserted  could  not  become  positive  until  the  several  funda- 
mental sciences  had  become  positive,  and  could  not  fail  to 
become  so  when  that  happened.  Comte  only  reaffirmed  and 
developed  what  he  said  on  all  these  points.  When  we  pass 
from  general  philosophy  to  sociology  we  find  that  Comte  was 
here  also,  in  the  main,  a  disciple  of  Saint-Simon.  Comte 
followed  Saint-Simon  when  he  represented  the  development 
of  humanity  as  having  been  throughout  subject  to  unal- 
terable laws  of  nature  which  excluded  the  intervention  of 
any  wills  higher  than  human;  when  he  took  Condorcet's 
'Esquisse '  as  the  work  to  be  resumed,  revised,  and  com- 
pleted by  the  true  historical  philosopher;  and  when  he 
showed  in  what  ways  the  attempt  made  in  it  might  be  sur- 
passed. Saint-Simon  conceived  of  the  course  of  history  as 
passing  through  three  phases  or  periods  —  one  credulous  and 
theological,  another  critical  and  incoherent,  and  a  final 
stage  which  is  scientific  and  organic;  he  thus  made  it  easy 
for  Comte  to  formulate  and  apply  "the  law  of  the  three 
states."  Saint-Simon  further  subdivided  the  theological 
period  into  fetichistic,  polytheistic,  and  monotheistic  epoch; 
and  in  this  likewise  he  was  followed  by  Comte.  Again,  one 
of  the  thoughts  which  Saint-Simon  most  frequently  ex- 
pressed, and  which  exercised  most  influence  on  his  life  and 
theorising,  was  that  the  organisation  of  society  could  only 
be  achieved  through  the  organisation  of  the  sciences  into  a 
general  science  or  true  philosophy.  Only  sensitive  vanity 
and  prejudice  can  account  for  Comte  denying  this,  and  alleg- 
ing that  Saint-Simon  had  proposed  "to  put  the  cart  before 
the  horse."  When  Comte,  avowedly  as  the  disciple  of 
Saint-Simon,  wrote  the  essay  published  in  1824  as  a  "Pros- 
pectus of  the  scientific  labours  necessary  for  the  reorganisa- 
tion of  society,"  Saint-Simon  praised  it  as  a  plan  of  the 
scientific  part  of  his  system,  but  pointed  out  as  a  defect  that 
it  dealt  with  science  without  reference  to  religion  and  senti- 
ment. He  showed  his  own  sense  of  the  importance  of  pro- 
viding satisfaction  to  the  religious  nature  and  the  social 
sentiments  when,  in  the  last  of  his  writings,  he  propounded 
a  new  religion,  and  tried  to  put  humanity  in  the  place  of 
God.     How  unable  Comte  was  to  emancipate  himself  from 


ATJGTJSTE   COMTE  587 

Saint-Simonian  principles  was  clearly  shown  as  soon  as  he 
came  face  to  face  with  the  problem  of  social  organisation, 
and  had  the  question  as  to  how  the  moral  and  emotional 
principles  of  human  nature  are  to  be  satisfied  forced  upon 
him.  He  had  no  other  solution  to  give  than  that  which 
Saint-Simon  had  already  given.  Even  in  devising  a  scheme 
of  worship,  a  positivist  "  cult, "  he  had  not  merely  to  borrow 
from  Catholicism,  but  to  become  an  imitator  of  the  Saint- 
Simonian  P£re  Enfantin,  whose  pretensions  and  sickly 
absurdities  he  once  thoroughly  despised.  In  a  word,  Comt- 
ism  must  be  admitted  to  be,  as  a  whole,  a  modified  and 
developed  Saint-Simonianism. 

It  is  quite  consistent  with  the  truth  of  all  that  has  just 
been  stated,  to  hold  that  the  disciple  was  in  most  respects 
much  greater  than  the  master.  And  he  undoubtedly  was 
so.  Although  Saint-Simon  had  the  most  genial  affinity  for 
novel  and  interesting  ideas,  he  had  scarcely  any  other 
remarkable  intellectual  qualities,  and  was  quite  incapable  of 
developing,  as  Comte  did,  either  a  philosophy  of  the  sciences 
or  a  theory  of  society. 

Comte  was  not  a  discoverer  or  eminent  specialist  in  any  of 
the  sciences,  not  even  in  mathematics ;  nor  had  he  the  ency- 
clopaedic knowledge  of,  for  example,  Amp&re  or  Whewell 
among  his  contemporaries.  It  has  been  shown  by  competent 
■critics  that  his  knowledge  of  astronomy,  optics,  chemistry, 
and  biology,  was  in  various  respects  not  up  to  date  when  he 
published  his  'Cours';  his  psychology  was  of  the  crudest 
kind;  and  his  social  dynamics  had  many  faults  which  arose 
from  an  inexcusable  ignorance  of  history.  A  man,  how- 
ever, who  takes  all  the  sciences  for  his  province,  cannot  be 
expected  to  know  that  enormous  province  as  minutely  as 
those  who  confine  their  studies  to  a  single  science  or  por- 
tion of  a  science  should  know  the  limited  field  of  their 
choice.  And  when  all  deductions  have  been  made  in  esti- 
mating Comte,  he  must  be  allowed  to  have  been  a  very  excep- 
tional and  remarkable  man.  He  had  a  capacious  memory,  a 
powerful  and  logical  intelligence,  a  wide  acquaintance  with 
scientific  facts,  and  a  firm  grasp  of  the  scientific  generalisa- 
tion to  which  he  attained.  The  truly  philosophical  charac- 
ter of  his   mind   appeared    in   his   constant  striving   after 


588  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FBANCE 

comprehensiveness  and  completeness  of  view,  his  insight- 
into  the  unity  and  relationships  of  the  sciences,  and  his  pro- 
found study  of  scientific  method.  The  power  which  most 
distinguished  him  was  that  of  systematisation,  one  not  to  be 
confounded  with  mere  aptitude  for  classification,  but  com- 
prising all  the  qualities  which  constitute  ability  to  connect 
and  distribute  facts  and  truths  according  to  their  natural 
affinities,  even  on  the  most  extensive  scale.  Few  have 
possessed  this  power  in  a  higher  degree  than  Comte ;  and  he 
employed  it,  so  far  as  his  properly  philosophical  task  was 
concerned,  to  excellent  effect.  In  resolving  to  elaborate  a 
doctrine  so  complete  and  comprehensive  that  it  should  em- 
brace all  knowledge  and  action,  he  proposed  to  himself  a 
magnificent  aim;  with  a  noble  tenacity  he  adhered  to  his 
purpose;  and  in  labouring  to  realise  it  he  displayed  a 
devotedness,  perseverance,  ingenuity,  and  constructive  power 
most  worthy  of  admiration.  The  work  which  he  left  behind 
him  has  already  exerted,  and  will  probably  long  exert,  a- 
great  and  stimulating  influence  on  the  minds  of  men;  for 
although  much  of  it  will  probably  perish,  much  of  it  may  as 
probably  endure.  In  the  character  of  Comte  there  was  much 
to  respect  and  much  to  regret.  His  will  was  strong;  but  so, 
likewise,  was  his  wilfulness.  He  was  self-denying,  but 
also  self-assertive.  The  absorbing  affection  for  a  woman, 
which  revealed  to  him  the  significance  of  emotion  and  the 
power  of  religion,  testify  to  greatness  of  heart;  but  the 
testimony  is  weakened  and  stained  by  extravagance  and 
sickly  sentimentalism.  The  love  of  humanity  which  in- 
spired his  labours  reflects  the  purest  glory  on  his  life;  but, 
unhappily,  it  was  never  dissociated  from  an  inordinate  self- 
esteem  —  an  exorbitant  pride  and  vanity.  It  is  .difficult  to' 
do  full  justice  to  the  real  merits  of  a  man  so  full  of  the  con- 
ceit of  his  own  incomparable  superiority,  so  suspicious  of 
rivalship,  so  unable  to  bear  contradiction  and  criticism,  as 
Comte  was.  A  nature  so  devoid  as  his  of  true  self-knowl- 
edge and  humility  may  seem  "the  normal  type  of  human 
nature  "  to  a  small  sect  of  peculiarly  minded  persons ;  but  to 
men  in  general  it  cannot  fail  to  seem  a  saddening  spectacle, 
whatever  be  its  powers  and  excellences.  These  words  are 
not  irrelevant.     We  can   only  explain  aright  the  despotic 


ATJGUSTE   COMTE  58&> 

features  of  the  Comtian  polity  and  the  deplorable  foolishness 
of  the  Comtian  religion  by  tracing  them  primarily  to  those 
defects  of  Comte's  character  and  temperament  to  which  I 
have  referred  as  briefly  as  I  could. 

It  was  not  Comte's  endeavour  merely  to  discover  special 
subordinate  laws;  or  to  expound  isolated  ideas,  however 
admirable ;  or  to  establish  in  any  department  of  study  truths 
of  detail ;  but  to  construct  a  system  of  thought  so  wide  and 
well  arranged,  that  not  only  every  science,  but  every  large 
scientific  generalisation  and  every  great  social  force,  would 
thereby  have  its  proper  place  assigned  it  and  full  justice 
done  to  it :  a  system  in  which  nothing  should  be  arbitrary, 
but  everything  determined  by  a  few  closely  connected  laws 
proved  by  the  concurrent  application  of  deduction  and  induc- 
tion. This  was  a  perfectly  legitimate  and  rational  under- 
taking, the  accomplishment  of  which  would  be  the  fulfilment 
of  one  of  the  great  functions  of  philosophy,  although  not,  as 
Comte  thought,  of  its  only  function. 

In  the  Comtian  system  the  philosophy  of  history  ranks  not 
as  a  science,  but  as  a  division  of  a  science,  —  the  second 
part  of  Social  Physics  or  Sociology.  Social  Physics  is  rep- 
resented as  ruled  by  biological  laws,  yet  not  a  mere  corollary 
of  biology,  but  an  independent  science,  which  has  a  distinc- 
tive and  dominant  method  of  its  own,  the  historical  method. 
It  is  the  function  of  this  method  to  compare  the  various  con- 
ditions through  which  humanity  passes  in  its  entire  histori- 
cal development.  It  is  only  by  such  comparison  that  any 
social  condition  can  be  understood.  The  particular  is  unin- 
telligible without  some  measure  of  knowledge  of  the  whole. 
The  laws  of  social  sequence  and  concomitance,  however, 
which  are  discovered  by  the  historical  method,  ought  always 
to  be  connected  with  the  positive  theory  of  human  nature 
established  by  biological  science.  Comte  regarded  socio- 
logical laws  as  not  merely  empirical  but  rational,  as  capable 
not  merely  of  inductive  but  also  of  deductive  demonstration. 
He  denied,  of  course,  that  law  can  be  rational  in  the  sense  of 
being  traceable  to  any  innate  principle,  or  to  any  metaphysi- 
cal principle,  as  power,  force,  efficient  causality,  or  that  it 
can  be  anything  deeper  than,  or  different  from,  a  uniform 
relation   of  sequence  or  resemblance   between   phenomena. 


590  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

But  he  affirmed  that  laws  may  be  rational  in  the  sense  of 
being  deducible  and  deduced  from  wider  laws  as  well  as 
empirically  ascertained  by  an  induction  from  instances;  and 
that  in  this  sense  —  the  only  sense  in  which  the  word  rational 
can,  consistently  with  the  principles  of  positivism  be  used 
in  connection  with  law  —  the  fundamental  laws  of  sociology 
are  actually  rational.  Besides  the  historical  method,  the 
methods  of  the  antecedent  sciences  are  represented  as  more 
or  less  applicable  in  sociological  study.  Being  the  most  com- 
plex of  the  sciences,  sociology  admits  of  and  requires  the 
employment  of  all  the  processes  and  resources  of  research 
and  reasoning.  Comte  had  no  sympathy  with  historical 
scepticism,  which  he  denounces  as  sophistry  and  traces  to 
unwillingness  to  admit  the  credibility  of  the  Bible.  He  had 
little  sympathy,  indeed,  even  with  the  critical  spirit  either 
in  sociology  or  any  other  department  of  science.  He  warned 
thinkers  against  inquiring  "too  closely  "  into  the  exact  truth 
of  scientific  laws ;  and  pronounced  worthy  of  "  severe  repro- 
bation "  those  who  break  down,  "by  too  minute  an  investi- 
gation," generalisations  which  they  cannot  replace.  Yet 
there  is  little  to  criticise  and  much  to  admire  in  his  treat- 
ment of  sociological  and  historical  method.  It  was  not  the 
original  and  exhaustive  exposition  of  the  logic  of  social  and 
historical  science  which  it  has  often  been  represented  to  be ; 
but  it  was  a  very  judicious  and  useful  contribution  to  it. 
Of  novelty  and  subtlety  in  it  there  is  almost  none,  but  of 
solid  truth  and  good  sense  abundance. 

Social  physics  (sociology)  is  divided  into  social  statics  and 
social  dynamics.1  Social  statics  is  the  theory  of  the  spon- 
taneous order  of  human  society,  and  social  dynamics  the 
theory  of  its  natural  progress.  The  one  exhibits  the  condi- 
tions of  the  social  existence  of  the  individual,  the  family, 
and  the  species,  and  the  other  the  course  of  human  develop- 
ment. It  is  essential,  Comte  insists,  to  regard  these  two 
theories  as  supplementary  or  complementary  of  each  other. 
The  ideas  of  order  and  progress  correspond  in  sociology  to 
the  ideas  of  organisation   and   life   in  biology,  and  are  as 

1  Holding  that  sociology  is  not  a  physical  science,  I,  of  course,  object  to  its 
being  designated  "social  physics,"  or  divided  into  "social  statics"  and  "social 
dynamics." 


AUGTJSTE   COMTE  591 

rigorously  inseparable.  The  combination  of  them  is  the 
grand  difficulty  of  the  science,  but  of  primary  importance. 
It  was  because  he  thought  he  had  succeeded  in  combining 
them  that  Comte  claimed  to  be  the  founder  of  sociology. 
He  admitted  that  Aristotle  had  almost  wrought  out  the 
theory  of  social  order,  and  that  for  nearly  a  century  that  of 
progress  had  been  receiving  a  continuous  elaboration ;  but  he 
held,  notwithstanding,  that  order  and  progress  had  never 
been  exhibited  in  their  true  relationship,  but,  on  the  con- 
trary, set  in  radical  opposition  to  each  other.  And  his  own 
view  of  his  position  as  a  sociological  theorist  was  that,  stand- 
ing between  two  extremes  of  hitherto  antagonistic  opinion, 
he  could  not  merely  effect  a  makeshift  compromise  between 
them  like  the  eclectics  and  the  doctrinaires,  but  could  estab- 
lish on  a  truly  scientific  foundation  a  doctrine  which  would 
definitely  settle  the  strife  between  the  advocates  of  order  and 
progress,  and  help  to  settle  the  wider  and  deeper  strife  in 
society  itself,  of  which  that  was  but  the  expression  in  specu- 
lation. He  flattered  himself  that  his  theory  of  society  con- 
tained all  the  truth  that  had  been  said  on  behalf  of  order  by 
the  reactionary  school,  and  all  the  truth  that  had  been  said 
on  behalf  of  progress  by  the  revolutionary  school ;  while  it, 
further,  so  reconciled  the  claims,  and  exhibited  the  relation- 
ship of  order  and  progress,  that  order  would  henceforth  be 
seen  to  be  the  basis  of  progress,  and  progress  to  be  the 
development  of  order. 

It  would  be  out  of  place  to  discuss  here  the  doctrine 
expounded  in  the  social  statics.  But  we  may  relevantly  say 
that  it  is  an  appropriate  introduction  to  the  social  dynam- 
ics, and  a  valuable  contribution  to  politics.  The  conclu- 
sions which  it  embodies  as  to  the  relations  of  the  individual 
and  society,  of  egoism  and  altruism,  of  intellect,  action,  and 
affection,  of  the  family,  the  state,  and  government,  of  worldly 
and  spiritual  power,  of  education  and  morals,  are  generally 
excellent;  and  even  when  questionable  or  erroneous,  tbey 
are  serviceable  from  their  suggestiveness.  Its  moral  spirit 
is,  on  the  whole,  sound  and  invigorating.  It  certainly  does 
not  flatter  or  foster  the  evil  tendencies  most  prevalent  in 
the  present  age.  But  it  is  unquestionably  a  reactionary  doc- 
trine.    Comte  has  not  held  the  balance  of  judgment  justly 


592  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FKANCE 

poised,  but  has  thrown  more  weight  into  the  scale  of  social 
authority,  and  given  less  to  that  of  individual  independence, 
than  is  due.  Instead  of  rejecting  only  what  was  false,  and 
retaining  only  what  was  true  in  the  conflicting  doctrines  of" 
Rousseau  and  De  Maistre,  he,  in  reality,  gave  up  what  was 
true  in  the  doctrine  of  the  former  for  what  was  false  in  that 
of  the  latter.  Rousseau  ascribed  worth  to  the  individual 
alone ;  Comte  followed  De  Maistre  in  denying  all  worth  to 
the  individual,  and  in  representing  him  as  owing  everything 
to  society;  and,  as  he  expressly  says,  as  being  apart  from 
society  a  mere  abstraction.  He  will  not  allow  that  the  indi- 
vidual has  any  right,  except  the  right  of  doing  his  duty ;  or, 
in  other  words,  that  he  has  any  rights  properly  so  called. 
Hence  he  consistently  objects  to  the  use  of  the  word  right  al- 
together, and  maintains  that  it  "  ought  to  be  excluded  from 
political  language  as  the  word  cause  from  truly  philosophi- 
cal language."  Comte  was  a  genuine  socialist.  He  was 
hostile  to  freedom  of  thought  and  action ;  so  impressed  with 
a  sense  of  the  importance  of  authority,  that  he  could  not  ven- 
ture to  recommend  any  guarantees  against,  or  restrictions  on, 
its  abuse,  in  the  least  likely  to  be  effectual.  This  explains- 
the  chief  faults  both  of  his  social  statics  and  his  social 
dynamics. 

Comte  expounded  his  theory  of  social  dynamics  first  in  the 
'Cours, '  and  afterwards  in  the  'SystSme.'  So  far  as  re- 
gards the  history  of  the  past,  although  the  two  expositions 
bear  witness  to  a  change  in  the  spirit  and  point  of  view 
of  their  author,  they  differ  little  in  their  matter,  or  as  to 
principles,  laws,  general  conclusions,  periods,  &c.  With 
these  we  shall  deal  in  the  first  place,  and  chiefly.  The  pecul- 
iar opinions  as  to  the  social  and  religious  future  of  human- 
ity, set  forth  in  the  works  which  belong  to  Comte's  second 
period,  concern  us  comparatively  little.  It  must  be  here 
observed,  however,  that  at  no  period  did  Comte  look  upon 
history  from  a  purely  scientific  point  of  view.  He  was 
always  influenced  in  his  treatment  of  it  by  practical  inter- 
ests. From  the  outset  of  his  career  as  an  author,  his  mind 
was  possessed  and  ruled  by  the  fundamental  principles  of 
socialism.  What  was  the  chief  end  of  life  to  Saint-Simon 
became  also  his :  the  reorganisation  of  society  through  the 


AUGUSTE   COMTE  593 

■establishment  of  a  "new  spiritual  power  "  capable  of  giving 
unity  and  direction  to  opinion  and  action.  He  gave  clear 
expression  to  this  aim  in  his  early  essays ;  and  its  influence 
is  evident  throughout  the  entire  system  of  his  positive  phi- 
losophy, but  especially  in  that  part  of  it  which  explains  the 
historical  evolution  of  humanity.  The  judgments  he  passes 
on  institutions  have  a  double  reference, —  one  to  what  has 
been,  another  to  what  he  has  decided  ought  to  be  and  will 
be  in  the  future.  Thus  the  grounds  of  his  extremely  favour- 
able estimate  of  medieval  Catholicism  were  not  merely 
•certain  considerations  of  a  partly  sentimental  and  partly 
historical  nature,  but,  still  more,  the  belief  that  although  the 
•Catholic  doctrine,  like  every  other  theological  doctrine,  was 
to  be  rejected,  the  Catholic  organisation  was  to  be  retained 
and  extended  by  positivism,  with  such  modifications  as  the 
substitution  of  a  scientific  for  a  theological  creed  might 
render  necessary.  And  his  aversion  to  Protestantism  and 
modern  philosophy  had  for  one  main  reason  the  fact  that 
they  had  broken  up  the  external  unity  of  the  Catholic  or 
medieval  form  of  social  organisation,  and  were  hostile  to  its 
restoration. 

Social  dynamics  studies  the  changes  which  society  under- 
goes in  the  course  of  ages ;  the  development  of  humanity  in 
time.  It  is  the  science  of  history.  Social  changes  follow 
one  another  in  a  natural  order  of  filiation,  each  state  of 
society  necessarily  arising  from  its  antecedent  state,  and 
necessarily  determining  the  character  of  its  consequent  state. 
Human  development  could  not  have  been  other  than  it  is. 
History  is  a  process  subject  to  fixed  and  unalterable  laws, 
which  manifest  their  presence  with  ever-growing  clearness 
as  the  effects  of  merely  transient  and  particular  influences 
are  eliminated.  This  process  has  obviously  been  one  of  prog- 
ress, —  one  in  which  human  nature  has  gradually  come  to 
the  knowledge  and  possession  of  itself,  and  shown  what  it  is 
and  is  capable  of. 

Progress  is  a  law  of  the  physical  world  as  well  as  of 
human  history.  There  is  progress  from  plant  to  animal, 
from  animal  to  man;  and  progress  within  the  vegetable, 
animal,  and  human  kingdoms.  Social  evolution  succeeds 
to  and  implies  organic  evolution;   historical  progress  is  a 


594  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN    FKANCE 

form  of  biological  progress,  and  presupposes  it.  Yet  social 
or  historical  evolution  and  progress  are  distinct  from  organic 
or  biological  evolution  or  progress.  There  is  a  solution  of 
continuity  between  them.  For  although  man  is  merely  the 
highest  animal,  he  is  not  any  lower  animal  transformed  by 
development  or  modification.  There  are  distinctions  between 
things  for  which  development  and  modification  cannot  ac- 
count. The  lower  never  explains  the  higher:  it  is  at  once 
the  differential  characteristic  and  the  fundamental  error  of 
materialism  to  have  ignored  or  denied  this  principle.  Omne 
vivum  ex  vivo  is  a  truth  which  no  really  scientific  man  will 
question.  The  doctrine  of  the  fixity  of  species  must  be 
firmly  maintained  against  the  Lamarckian  theory  of  develop- 
ment. Man  is  sui  generis.  All  the  lower  creatures  are  rude 
and  partial  embryonic  prefigurations  or  sketches  of  man. 
All  the  laws  of  the  universe  meet  and  rule  in  him.  And 
yet  he  has  a  nature  of  his  own,  with  its  distinctive  qualities 
and  laws.  And  what  is  true  of  himself  is  equally  true  of 
his  history. 

Comte's  conception  of  human  progress  is  not  only  con- 
nected with  that  of  progress  in  general,  but  with  that  of 
social  order.  While  accepting,  as  a  whole,  the  previous 
elaboration  of  the  conception  of  human  progress  by  his  pred- 
ecessors, he  added  to  it  not  a  little  which  they  had  over- 
looked when  he  defined  progress  as  the  development  of  order, 
and  prefaced  his  treatment  of  it  with  an  investigation  into 
the  conditions  of  order.  Progress  thus  viewed  must  not 
only  never  violate  but  always  involve  the  principles  of  social 
stability,  personal  morality,  a  naturally  regulated  family  life, 
and  subordination  to  organised  authority  in  the  State.  Ac- 
cording to  this  conception  of  progress,  the  character  of  all 
social  changes  may  be  ascertained  from  their  influence  on 
these  the  fundamental  principles  of  social  existence. 

The  direction  of  progress  is  represented  as  being  the  estab- 
lishment of  the  supremacy  of  the  distinctively  human  facul- 
ties of  man  over  his  merely  animal  faculties.  According 
to  Rousseau  the  natural  man  is  a  self-dependent  being, 
guided  by  infallible  instinct.  The  man  who  thinks,  he 
said,  is  a  depraved  animal.  According  to  Comte,  although 
reason  and  the  sympathetic  feelings  are  at  first  weak  in  man, 


AUGUSTE   COMTE  595 

while  instinct  and  the  personal  desires  are  strong,  the  former, 
nevertheless,  constitute  his  true  nature,  and  human  progress 
is  the  process  by  which  they  attain  supremacy.  It  is  the 
triumph  of  mind  over  sense,  of  reason  over  appetite,  of  the 
altruistic  or  social  over  the  egoistic  or  selfish  affections. 

The  rate  of  progress  is  represented  as  determined  by  vari- 
ous causes,  of  which  some  are  primary  and  universal,  and 
others  secondary  and  particular.  Among  the  former  are 
changes  in  the  human  organism  and  the  media  in  which  it 
is  developed.  Among  the  latter  are  the  mean  duration  of 
human  life  and  the  natural  increase  of  population.  Were 
the  mean  duration  of  life,  for  example,  a  thousand  years, 
progress  would  be  necessarily  much  slower  than  it  is,  for  the 
conservative  tendencies  of  age  would  be,  relatively  to  the 
innovating  tendencies  of  youth,  far  stronger  than  at  present. 
A  rapid  increase  of  population  produces  a  rapid  progress  by 
rendering  necessary  a  more  specialised  and  intense  activity. 

In  social  progress  there  is,  according  to  Comte,  no  varia- 
tion either  of  the  general  direction  or  of  the  order  in  which 
the  stages  succeed  each  other.  As  to  the  latter,  however, 
he  holds  that  progress  or  retrogression  may  be  so  rapid  that 
the  intermediate  stages  may  be  imperceptible.  Hence  he  ex- 
pects that  the  fetichistic  communities  which  have  survived  to 
the  present  day  will,  under  the  systematic  guidance  of  the 
positivist  priesthood,  pass  straight  into  positivism,  without 
halting  in  polytheism,  monotheism,  or  a  metaphysical  mode 
of  thought.  Further, the  movement  of  progress  is,  in  his  view, 
not  rectilineal  but  oscillatory  around  a  mean  movement  which 
is  never  widely  departed  from.  Nor  is  it,  as  Condorcet  and 
others  have  held,  unlimited.  Humanity  is  equally  an 
organism  with  the  individual  man ;  and,  like  every  organ- 
ism, it  must  decay  and  die.  As  yet  it  is  only  emerging  from 
the  preparatory  period  of  its  existence ;  and,  therefore,  we 
may  be  certain  that  ages  of  vigorous  and  progressive  life  are 
still  before  it.  It  is  useless  to  conjecture  when  decay  will 
set  in  or  death  arrive. 

Comte  regarded  progress  as  a  development  of  the  whole 
man,  intellect,  activity,  and  affection;  and  therefore,  as  a 
general  development  comprehensive  of  various  particular 
and  correlative  developments.     He  not  only  saw' that  there 


■596  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

was  an  industrial  development,  an  intellectual  development, 
a  moral  development,  and  an  aesthetic  development ;  but  that 
there  must  be  a  general  historical  development  inclusive 
of  these  particular  developments;  and  that  the  particular 
developments  must  be  not  mere  stages  of  the  general  develop- 
ment, but  movements  pervasive  of  it  from  beginning  to  end, 
and  parallel  to  one  another.  He  saw  that  the  elements  of 
the  social  evolution  are  throughout  connected  and  always 
acting  on  one  another.  His  perception  of  the  fact  that  social 
evolution  is  a  general  or  collective  movement,  inclusive 
throughout  its  whole  length  of  certain  distinct  special  and 
particular  movements,  caused  him  to  infer  that,  though  the 
elements  of  the  historical  process  are  connected,  and  always 
acting  and  reacting  on  one  another,  one  must  be  preponder- 
ant in  order  to  give  impulse  to  the  rest,  and  to  guide  them 
all  in  the  same  direction.  He  saw  that  only  on  this  condi- 
tion could  there  be  a  general  collective  movement,  correlation 
between  the  particular  constituent  developments,  a  com- 
mon goal,  and,  in  a  word,  the  unity  presupposed  by  science. 
And  accordingly,  he  inquired  which  was  the  guiding  ele- 
ment. The  conclusion  he  came  to  was,  that  it  must  be  that 
element  which  can  be  best  conceived  of  apart  from  the  rest, 
while  the  consideration  of  it  enters  into  the  study  of  the 
others  —  i.e.,  the  intellect.  The  history  of  society, he  argued, 
must  be  regulated  by  the  history  of  the  human  understanding. 
Thought  is  that  which  determines  and  guides  the  course  of 
society.  "  It  is  only  through  the  ever-increasingly  marked 
influence  of  the  reason  over  the  general  conduct  of  man  and 
of  society,  that  the  gradual  march  of  our  race  has  attained 
that  regularity  and  persevering  continuity  which  so  radically 
distinguish  it  from  the  desultorj'  and  barren  expansion  of 
even  the  highest  orders  of  animals,  which  share,  and  share 
with  intensest  strength,  the  appetites,  passions,  and  even 
the  primary  sentiments  of  man." 

If  these  views  be  correct,  the  fundamental  law  of  history 
must  be  sought  for  in  the  evolution  of  the  intellect.  Comte 
believed  that  he  had  found  it  in  what  he  called  the  law  of 
the  three  states,  or  the  law  of  historical  filiation.  It  affirms 
"  the  necessary  passage  of  all  human  theories  through  three 
successive  stages :  first,  the  theological  or  fictitious,  which  is 


AUGUSTS   COMTB  597 

provisional;  secondly,  the  metaphysical  or  abttract,  which  is 
transitional;  and,  thirdly,  the  positive  or  scientific,  which 
alone  is  definitive."  "This  law,"  we  are  told,  "is  the  most 
precious  intellectual  acquisition  of  the  human  mind.  "With 
its  ascertainment  that  long  search  after  the  laws  of  the  uni- 
verse, which  began  with  Thales  at  the  first  awakening  of  the 
reason,  is  completed.  The  immutable  order  which  had  been 
proved  to  rule  throughout  the  entire  physical  world,  extends 
its  reign  over  the  world  of  liberty."  "What  is  called  "the 
law  of  hierarchical  generalisation  or  of  the  encyclopaedic 
scale "  may  either  be  combined  with  the  law  of  the  three 
states,  or  reckoned  as  a  second  law.  It  is  manifestly  the 
complement  of  it.  It  runs  thus :  "  Our  subjective  concep- 
tions reach  the  scientific  or  positive  stage  in  the  order  of 
their  dependence  on  each  other,  which  is  that  of  decreasing 
generality  and  increasing  complexity."  Hence  the  funda- 
mental sciences  —  mathematics,  astronomy,  physics,  chemis- 
try, biology,  sociology,  and  morals  —  have  become  positive 
in  the  order  in  which  they  have  just  been  named.1 

If  the  fundamental  law  of  intellectual  evolution,  the  law 
of  the  three  states,  and  its  complementary  law,  the  law  of 
hierarchical  generalisation,  be  reduced  to  one,  the  second 
general  law  of  historical  progression  will  be  the  law  of  the 
active  evolution  of  human  nature.  But  according  to  Comte, 
the  evolution  of  the  active  or  practical  life  was  in  its  initial 
stage  one  of  offensive  war  or  conquest,  in  its  transitional 
stage  one  of  defensive  war,  and  has  become  in  its  final  stage 
industrial.     "These  three  consecutive  modes  of  activity  — 

conquest,   defence,    and   laboui correspond    exactly  to   the 

three  stages  of  intelligence  — fiction,  abstraction,  and  dem- 
onstration. This  fundamental  correlation  gives  us  also  the 
general  explanation  of  the  three  natural  ages  of  humanity. 
Its  long  infancy,  covering  all  antiquity,  had  to  be  essen- 
tially theological  and  military ;  its  adolescence  in  the  middle 
age  was  metaphysical  and  feudal ;  and  lastly,  its  maturity, 
which  only  within  the  last  few  centuries  has  become  at  all 
distinguishable,  is  necessarily  positive  and  industrial." 

The  affective  evolution  of  human  nature  has  not,  accord- 

1 1  have  examined  Comte's  view  of  the  evolution  of  the  sciences  in  the  last  of 
*e  papers  indicated  in  the  note  on  p.  22. 


598  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

ing  to  Comte,  the  independence  either  of  the  intellectual  or 
the  active  evolution,  seeing  that  the  affective  region  of  the 
brain  is  not,  like  those  of  contemplation  and  action,  in  any 
direct  contact  with  the  external  world ;  but  it  is  none  the 
less  of  immense  importance.  Feeling  is  at  once  the  source 
and  end  of  progress.  It  is  the  only  standard  by  which  we 
can  properly  measure  civilisation.  It  has  also  its  law: 
"Feeling  has  its  three  successive  stages,  the  spontaneous 
correspondence  of  which  with  those  of  intellect  and  activity 
is  now  recognised  as  the  necessary  consequence  of  the  joint 
influence  of  those  two  evolutions.  In  other  words,  the  social 
instinct  had  to  be  purely  civic  in  antiquity,  collective  in  the 
middle  age,  and  universal  in  the  final  state,  as  its  modern 
aspirations  indicate." 

The  three  chief  laws  regulative  of  human  evolution  are 
thus  represented  as  belonging  respectively  to  the  three  ele- 
ments of  human  nature  —  speculation,  action,  and  affection. 
As  such  evolution  must  comprehend  these  elements,  and  the 
historical  developments  to  which  they  may  give  rise,  we 
must  acknowledge  that  Comte  deserved  credit  for  attempting 
to  formulate  the  laws  of  their  developments,  and  to  indicate 
at  once  the  course  and  the  correlation  of  these  developments. 
But  the  man  who  fancies  that  the  attempt  was  successful  as 
regards  either  the  active  or  the  affective  evolution  must 
be  excessively  easy  to  satisfy.  Their  so-called  "laws"  are 
beneath  criticism ;  they  are  of  a  kind  which  any  moderately 
ingenious  person  may  devise  by  the  dozen.  Human  activity 
was  not  first  military  and  then  industrial,  but  has  always 
been  more  or  less  both.  The  social  organisation  of  ancient 
Egypt,  India,  China,  Phenicia,  &c,  was  affected  at  least  as 
powerfully  by  labour  as  by  war.  That  war  should  ever  have 
been  more  offensive  than  defensive,  or  defensive  than  offen- 
sive, is  a  saying  hard  to  understand.  That  the  social  in- 
stinct was  "purely  civic  in  antiquity"  is  an  affirmation  in 
which  the  terms  "civic"  and  "antiquity"  are  both  ambigu- 
ous. That  it  was  more  "collective  "  in  the  middle  age  than 
in  the  ancient  empires  in  which  the  system  of  castes  pre- 
vailed would  be  difficult  to  prove.  And  that  it  has  not  been 
"  universal "  in  its  aspirations  since  the  spread  of  Christian- 
ity and  the  conquest  of  the  world  by  Rome  is  not  in  accord- 


ATJGUSTE   COMTE  599 

ance  with  facts.  Comte,  it  must  be  added,  has  made  no 
serious  endeavour  to  prove  his  alleged  laws  of  active  and 
affective  evolution. 

We  readily  admit  that  such  considerations  as  those  just 
stated  are  not  fatal  to  his  historical  doctrine,  but  only  indic- 
ative of  its  incompleteness.  If  the  law  of  intellectual  evo- 
lution be  satisfactorily  made  out,  that  doctrine  will  be 
substantially  established,  however  uncertain  or  erroneous 
any  of  its  supposed  supplementary  laws  may  be  found  to  be. 
The  law  of  the  three  states  is  the  nceud  essentiel  of  Comte's 
philosophy  of  history,  as  it  is  of  his  general  philosophy.  It 
is  necessary  that  we  have  it  principally  in  view  both  in  our 
exposition  and  in  our  criticism. 

The  three  states  are  the  successive  stages  through  which 
the  mind  of  man  is  maintained  to  pass  in  the  course  of  his- 
tory in  nations,  individuals,  and  each  order  of  conceptions. 
The  first  state  is  the  theological.  Theology  preceded  either 
metaphysics  or  science ;  it  goes  back  as  far  as  history  will 
take  us ;  there  is  reason  to  believe  it  coeval  with  man.  In 
this  state  the  facts  and  events  of  the  universe  are  attributed 
to  supernatural  volitions,  to  the  agency  of  beings  or  a  being 
adored  as  divine.  The  lowest  and  earliest  form  of  this  stage 
is  fetichism,  in  which  man  conceives  of  all  external  bodies 
as  endowed  with  a  life  analogous  to  his  own.  Astrolatry  is 
a  connecting  link  between  fetichism  and  polytheism,  there 
being  a  generality  about  the  stars  which,  connected  with 
their  other  characteristics,  fits  them  to  be  common  fetiches. 
Polytheism  is  directly  derived  from  fetichism;  and  it  is  the1 
second  stage  or  phase  of  the  theological  state.  It  is  either 
conservative  and  theocratic,  as  that  of  Egypt,  or  progressive 
and  military,  as  those  of  Greece  and  Rome,  the  one  of  which 
was  of  an  intellectual,  and  the  other  of  a  social  type.  It  gradu- 
ally concentrates  itself  into  monotheism,  which,  growing  out 
of  different  forms  of  polytheism,  is  of  different  kinds.  Thus 
the  monotheism  of  the  Jews  differs  from  that  of  Europe, 
because  evolved  out  of  a  conservative  instead  of  a  progres- 
sive polytheism.  The  contact  of  these  gave  rise  to  Chris- 
tianity, which  culminated  in  Catholicism,  the  last  and 
highest  type  of  monotheistic  development.  With  it  the 
long  infancy  of  human  thought  terminates. 


600  PHILOSOPHY  OP   HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

The  metaphysical  spirit  which  has  been  operative  in  some 
degree  through  almost  the  whole  theological  period,  bringing 
about  even  the  transition  from  fetichism  to  polytheism,  and 
still  more  from  polytheism  to  monotheism,  and  which  has 
been  constantly  growing  in  strength,  now,  as  there  is  noth- 
ing beyond  monotheism  but  a  total  issue  from  theology, 
throws  theology  off  altogether,  and  establishes  a  metaphysical 
state.  Theology  dies,  and  the  intellect  of  humanity  which 
has  passed  away  from  it  embodies  itself  in  another  form.  In 
this  second  state,  abstract  forces  are  substituted  for  super- 
natural agents.  Phenomena  are  supposed  to  be  due  to 
causes  and  essences  inherent  in  things.  First  causes  and 
final  causes,  these  are 'what  the  mind  in  this  state  longs  and 
strives  to  know,  but  in  vain ;  and  it  begins  slowly  and  gradu- 
ally to  recognise  in  one  sphere  of  nature  after  another  that  a 
knowledge  of  these  is  unattainable  to  it. 

It  thus  at  length  reaches  a  third  and  final  state,  that  of 
positive  science.  In  this  state  the  mind  surrenders  the  illu- 
sions of  its  infancy  and  youth,  and  ceases  to  fancy  it  can 
transcend  nature,  or  know  either  the  first  cause  or  the  end 
of  the  universe,  or  ascertain  about  things  more  than  experi- 
ence can  tell  us  of  their  properties  and  their  relations  of 
coexistence  and  succession.  It  is  a  state  of  learned  igno- 
rance, in  which  intelligence  sees  clearly  and  sharply  its  own 
limits,  and  confines  itself  within  them.  Within  these  limits 
lie  all  the  positive  sciences ;  beyond  them  lie  theology  and 
metaphysics,  the  two  chief  forms  of  pseudo-science  or  false 
belief. 

Comte  has  elaborated  and  applied  these  thoughts ;  and  in 
doing  so  he  has  traced  the  course  of  the  general  history  of 
mankind,  viewed  as  exemplif3Ting  the  law  of  the  three 
states,  and  its  correlative  laws.  The  picture  of  universal 
history  which  he  unfolds  is  one  drawn  with  great  skill  and 
vigour,  and  in  which  there  are  many  true  and  striking 
features.  In  various  respects  it  surpassed  all  previous 
attempts  of  the  kind. 

The  ability  with  which  it  is  executed  is  apt,  indeed,  to 
conceal  the  fault  in  it  which  is  least  excusable,  such  un- 
truthfulness as  is  due  to  its  author's  insufficient  acquaintance 
with  history.     Now,  Comte  is  not  to  be  blamed  for  having 


AUGUSTE   COMTE  601 

resolved  to  exhibit  not  the  concrete  but  the  abstract  in  his- 
tory; for  seldom  mentioning  particular  events,  persons,  or 
dates ;  for  confining  himself  almost  exclusively  to  the  delinea- 
tion of  main  currents  and  movements,  of  general  features  and 
tendencies.  On  the  contrary,  he  deserves  credit  for  having 
so  clearly  seen  that  only  thus  could  history  be  treated  in  a 
philosophical  manner,  or  a  philosophy  of  history  be  reached. 
But  he  erred  greatly  when  he  failed  to  recognise  that  a  real 
knowledge  of  the  abstract  and  general  in  history  can  only  be 
acquired  through  a  careful  and  extensive  study  of  its  concrete 
and  particular  contents ;  that  a  philosophy  of  history  ought 
not  to  be  based  on  views  as  to  the  facts  of  history  hastily 
adopted  without  due  criticism  and  verification.  According 
to  his  own  statement,  he  "rapidly  amassed  in  early  youth  the 
materials  which  he  thought  he  would  need  in  the  great 
elaboration  of  which  he  had  already  conceived  the  design, 
and  thenceforth  read  nothing  likely  to  have  an  important  bear- 
ing on  the  subjects  with  which  he  was  himself  to  be  occu- 
pied." This  abstinence  from  reading  he  imposed  on  himself 
under  the  name  of  "cerebral  hygiene,"  "in  order  not  to  hurt 
the  originality  and  homogeneity  of  his  meditations,"  and  as 
"necessary  to  elevate  the  views  and  give  impartiality  to  the 
sentiments."  He  adhered  to  it  with  special  care  when 
it  was  peculiarly  unreasonable  and  pernicious  —  namely, 
when  engaged  in  theorising  on  the  history  of  humanity. 
His  historical  philosophy  is  a  wonderful  testimony  to  the 
extraordinary  power  of  reflection  and  systematisation  which 
enabled  him  to  make  so  much  theory  out  of  so  little  knowl- 
edge. But  while  we  may  admire  the  power  which  he  thus 
displayed,  we  must  regret  the  excessive  self-confidence  which 
made  him  unconscious  of  the  extent  of  his  ignorance  of  the 
subjects  on  which  he  dogmatised.  His  absolute  faith  in  his 
own  thoughts,  his  neglect  of  research,  and  his  ability  in  con- 
structive theorising,  make  him  a  dangerous  guide  to  unwary 
readers. 

We  can  only  touch  very  briefly  even  on  the  chief  points  in 
Comte's  survey  of  historical  development. 

1.  It  is  not  altogether  a  survey  of  universal  history  even 
in  its  most  general  or  abstract  form.  It  leaves  out  of  view 
all  central  and   eastern  Asia,   with  its   great   empires   and 


602  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN  PRANCE 

peculiar  civilisations.  By  this  omission  Comte  evaded  the 
difficulty  of  verifying  his  fundamental  law  where  there  is 
least  appearance  of  evidence  for  it,  as  it  cannot  be  pretended 
that  the  peoples  of  that  portion  of  Asia  have  ever  been  out 
of  the  theological  state.  And  even  as  regards  theologism, 
if  he  had  taken  India  into  account  he  could  hardly  have 
excluded,  as  he  has  done,  pantheism  from  the  series  of  theo- 
logical phases.  It  is  as  distinct  a  phase  of  theology  as  any 
of  those  on  which  he  dwells.  On  the  other  hand,  if  he  had 
recognised  it  his  series  of  theological  phases  would  have 
received  an  addition  which  would  not  fit  into  his  scheme  of 
general,  and  especially  of  European,  history.  Nay,  more, 
acknowledge  pantheism  as  a  phase  of  theological  develop- 
ment, and  it  becomes  apparent  that  the  idea  of  the  Divine 
as  One  may  be  reached,  and  has  been  reached,  by  another 
route  than  that  which  led  to  monotheism.  But  this  raises 
the  question,  Is  there  any  single  necessary  linear  series  of 
theological  phases  or  historical  states  ?  It  forbids  our  assum- 
ing that  there  is.  If,  like  Comte,  we  affirm  that  there  is,  we 
must,  unlike  him,  prove  the  affirmation. 

2.  Fetichism  was,  according  to  Comte,  the  earliest,  and 
at  the  same  time  the  purest  and  best,  of  the  forms  to  which 
man's  religious  tendencies  have  given  rise.  He  thought 
there  were  traces  of  it  to  be  observed  in  the  actions  of  the 
animals  immediately  below  man  in  the  scale  of  organisation. 
In  the  infancy  of  our  race,  according  to  his  representation, 
the  spontaneous  activity  of  the  human  brain  predominated 
over  the  mechanical  influence  of  the  external  world,  and 
consequently  imagination  over  observation,  sentiment  over 
experience;  and  man  was  therefore  necessitated  to  invent 
causes  instead  of  seeking  laws.  But  these  causes  could  only 
be  reflections  of  himself,  the  one  being  which  he  knew.  He 
ascribed,  therefore,  to  all  objects  his  own  nature,  thoughts, 
motives,  and  feelings.  Everything  was  to  him  living,  vol- 
untary, intelligent;  everything,  in  a  word,  was  to  him 
divine.  All  was  god;  all  was  fetich.  Fetichism  is  the 
basis  of  all  theology  and  of  all  metaphysics.  And  it  is  akin 
to  positivism  itself.  "Where  the  fetichist  sees  life,  the 
positivist  sees  spontaneous  activity. "  Positivism  must  go 
back  to  fetichism  in  order  to  become  popular.     The  panthe- 


ATJGTJSTE   COMTE  603 

ism  of  Germany  is  only  a  generalised  and  systematised  fetich- 
ism.  In  spirit  it  is  inferior  to  the  primitive  doctrine.  "  The 
general  progress  of  the  human  intellect  was  in  no  way  re- 
tarded by  the  necessary  impotence  of  fetichism  as  regards 
the  highest  speculations.  In  the  eyes  of  a  true  philosopher, 
the  artless  ignorance  which  in  this  respect  characterises  the 
humble  thinkers  of  Central  Africa  is  worth  more  even  in 
point  of  rationality  than  the  pompous  verbiage  of  the  proud 
doctors  of  Germany.  For  it  proceeds  from  a  real,  though 
confused,  feeling  that  any  one  who  remains  unfurnished 
with  the  scientific  basis  is  unripe  for  such  speculations ;  and 
of  this  basis  our  metaphysicians  are  more  disgracefully  igno- 
rant than  the  lowest  negroes." 

In  both  of  his  chief  works  Comte  has  treated  of  "  the  age 
of  fetichism,"  or  what  he  calls  "the  spontaneous  rSgirne  of 
humanity,"  devoting  to  it  in  the  'Cours  '  more  than  eighty, 
and  in  the  'Syst&me  '  more  than  sixty,  pages.  It  is  highly 
probable  that  he  never  read  a  dozen  pages  regarding  it  writ- 
ten by  any  other  person  than  himself.  His  discussion  of 
fetichism  displays  a  combination  of  historical  ignorance  and 
speculative  ingenuity  unsurpassed  by  any  of  those  "  doctors 
of  Germany  "  on  whose  pride  he  looked  down  with  at  least 
equal  pride.  He  employs  the  term  "fetichism,"  as  Saint- 
Simon  had  done,  in  an  unusual  and  improper  sense;  and 
does  not  seem  to  have  been  aware  what  its  usual  and  proper 
sense  was.  As  he  uses  the  term,  it  means,  when  stripped 
of  exaggeration,  simply  nature-worship ;  and  in  this  sense  it 
may  be  very  plausibly  maintained  that  fetichism  was  the 
earliest  form  of  religion,  but  only  on  psychological  and 
theoretical  grounds.  There  is  no  strictly  historical  evidence 
that  it  was  the  first  phase  of  religion ;  and  it  is  quite  certain 
that  it  is  not  the  theology  of  "  the  humble  thinkers  of  Cen- 
tral Africa,"  or  the  faith  most  prevalent  among  any  known 
rude  savage  tribes.  Comte  knew  exceedingly  little  about 
fetichists,  and  those  whom  he  supposed  to  be  fetichists. 
And  yet  he  theorised  on  their  motives  and  beliefs  with  a 
confidence,  ingenuity,  and  seeming  profundity,  not  unlikely 
to  deceive  to  some  extent  even  experts  in  comparative  the- 
ology, and  almost  certain  thoroughly  to  mislead  ordinary 
readers.     His   extravagant    laudation   of    fetichism   is  due 


604  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

partly  to  the  ignorance  which  left  him  free  to  evolve  his 
idea  of  it  out  of  his  own  inner  consciousness,  and  partly  to 
the  affinity  between  the  idea  of  it  thus  evolved,  and  that  of 
positivism  as  he  coneeived  of  it.  Of  course,  if  where  fetich- 
ism  sees  life  positivism  sees  spontaneous  activity,  they  are 
very  like  indeed.  They  are  in  that  case  about  equally  fanci- 
ful, and  both  directly  anti-scientific.  Had  Comte  not  been  al- 
most as  ignorant  of  the  opinions  of  "  the  doctors  of  Germany  " 
as  of  those  of  "the  thinkers  of  Central  Africa,"  he  would 
have  perceived  that  modern  pantheism  was  not  mere  general- 
ised and  systematised  fetichism,  but  presupposed  some  such 
development  of  monotheism,  metaphysics,  and  science  as  that 
which  history  shows  to  have  actually  occurred. 

3.  Polytheism  he  has  treated  of  with  fulness,  regarding  it 
as  the  most  prolonged  of  the  theological  phases.  Its  rise  he 
attributes  to  the  gradual  concentration  of  fetichism,  and  to 
the  growth  of  self-consciousness  and  will.  On  the  one  hand, 
man  necessarily  comes  in  the  course  of  his  observation  of 
objects  to  perceive  that  they  have  permanent  attributes  and 
relations,  and  is  thus  enabled  to  group  them  into  genera. 
On  the  other  hand,  he  also  comes  to  feel  his  distinctness  from 
nature,  to  oppose  his  will  to  the  action  of  external  things,  to 
struggle  with  the  world  in  order  to  subdue  and  utilise  it,  and 
to  seek  auxiliaries  in  this  struggle.  In  other  words,  he  is 
led  both  to  consider  the  qualities  common  to  several  objects 
as  independent  of  each  of  them,  and  to  separate  the  Divine 
from  objects,  or  to  refer  phenomena  to  invisible  supernatural 
Wills.  Thus  fetiches  give  place  to  gods  who  are  generalisa- 
tions personified,  matter  being  thenceforth  looked  on  as  inert, 
objects  as  passive.  In  this  process  of  transition  the  working 
of  the  metaphysical  spirit  already  shows  itself  at  once  modi- 
fying and  undermining  theology.  While  Comte  deems 
polytheism  inferior  to  fetichism  as  a  religion,  he  fully  recog- 
nises it  to  have  been  much  more  favourable  to.intellectual  cul- 
ture. He  points  out  with  remarkable  insight  and  ingenuity 
how  it  contributed  to  the  rise  and  development  of  science, 
art,  and  industry;  and  how  it  was  related  to  the  military 
spirit,  priestly  influence,  slavery,  political  organisation,  &c. 
All  the  general  portion  of  his  treatment  of  polytheism  • —  what 
he   calls  his  "abstract  appreciation"  of   it  —  is  admirable. 


ATJGUSTE   COMTE  605 

His  "concrete  appreciation  "  of  it  is  the  special  treatment  of 
what  he  describes  as  its  three  chief  forms:  the  Egyptian, 
which  is  conservative  and  theocratic;  the  Greek,  which  is 
progressive  and  intellectual ;  and  the  Roman,  which  is  also 
progressive  but  predominantly  military  and  social.  It  is  also 
rich  in  excellent  observations  and  truly  philosophical  views, 
but  it  likewise  contains  many  errors,  mostly  due  to  inade- 
quate study  of  the  facts.  While  its  merits,  however,  are  rare 
and  conspicuous,  of  exceptional  value,  and  of  essential  sig- 
nificance, its  defects  are,  in  general,  merely  blemishes,  more 
disfiguring  than  destructive,  which  may  be  overlooked  or 
eliminated.  When  attempting  to  account  for  the  transition 
from  polytheism  to  monotheism,  Comte  falls  into  some  of  his 
worst  mistakes.  Nothing  need  here  be  said  to  show  how 
baseless  are  such  hypotheses  as  that  the  Jews  were  a  mono- 
theistic colony  from  Egj'pt  or  Chaldea;  that  Christ  was 
"no  extraordinary  type  of  moral  perfection,"  but  simply 
"one  of  the  many  adventurers  who  were  constantly  making 
efforts  to  inaugurate  monotheism,  and  aspiring,  like  their 
Greek  forerunners,  to  the  honours  of  persomal  apotheosis ; " 
and  that  Paul,  "perceiving  the  useful  purpose  to  which  the 
dawning  success  of  Christ  might  be  turned,  voluntarily  sub- 
ordinated himself  to  Him,"  and  became  the  true  founder  of 
Catholicism. 

4.  We  thus  reach  the  age  of  Catholic  monotheism.  Comte 
shows  slight  esteem  for  its  monotheistic  doctrine,  but  high 
admiration  of  its  social  spirit  and  institutions.  The  claim 
has  been  put  in  for  him  that  he  was  the  first  worthily  to 
appreciate  the  middle  age.  It  is  a  claim,  I  need  scarcely  say, 
which  cannot  be  seriously  maintained.  He  himself  expressly 
ascribes  the  honour  to  those  to  whom  it  was  more  due,  the 
chiefs  of  the  theological  school,  whose  reaction,  however,  in 
this  as  in  other  respects  was  but  a  sign  of  a  general  change 
in  the  current  of  European  thought,  which  began  in  Ger- 
many, and  only  reached  France  after  having  passed  through 
England.  But  although  the  claim  be  absurd,  and  although 
it  be  strange  that,  after  Thierry's  celebrated  account  of  the 
rise  and  spread  in  France  of  correct  views  as  to  the  middle 
ages,  it  should  have  been  made,  yet  Comte  is  entitled  to  the 
honour  of  having  estimated  their  character  and  significance 


606  PHILOSOPHY  OP  HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

on  the  whole  well,  and  even  in  some  respects  better  than 
any  of  his  predecessors.  The  medieval  Church,  feudalism, 
and  scholasticism,  are  appreciated  in  their  general  relations 
and  influences  with  comprehensiveness  and  truthfulness; 
and,  in  fact,  all  the  great  systems  of  speculation  and  religion 
belonging  to  Western  Europe  down  to  the  Keformation  are 
judged  of,  so  far  as  they  can  be  regarded  merely  as  histori- 
cal phenomena,  with  a  fairness  and  insight  surprising  in  a 
man  whose  own  views  as  to  speculation  and  religion  were 
so  peculiar.  I  wish  this,  however,  to  be  understood  as 
merely  a  general  judgment,  and  as  not  inconsistent  with  the 
conviction  that  there  are  great  errors  even  in  his  analysis  of 
medieval  society.  The  good  accomplished  by  the  Catholic 
Church  in  the  middle  ages  cannot  be  justly  ascribed  to  the 
extent  which  he  had  done  merely  to  the  merits  of  its  organi- 
sation and  the  wisdom  of  its  priesthood.  The  Christian 
truth  contained  in  its  doctrine  must  be  allowed  to  have  done 
far  more  than  simply  " lent  itself  to  the  situation."  What 
Comte  admired  in  the  medieval  world  was  its  order  and  dis- 
cipline ;  whatever  in  it  tended  to  establish  and  preserve  the 
unity  of  its  faith,  to  discourage  doubt,  and  to  repress  intel- 
lectual and  spiritual  independence.  It  owed  its  greatness 
in  his  eyes  to  its  having  made  faith  the  first  of  duties  and 
shown  no  tolerance  to  dissenters.  In  this  respect  his  view 
of  it  was  as  one-sided  and  reactionary  as  that  of  De  Maistre ; 
and,  in  addition,  logically  most  inconsistent,  and  morally 
most  equivocal,  seeing  that  he  had  himself  no  belief  in  the 
truth  of  the  doctrine  for  the  support  of  which  he  deemed  that 
falsehood  and  persecution  had  been  laudable. 

5.  "The  theological  philosophy  and  military  polity,  su- 
preme in  antiquity,  and  modified  and  enfeebled  in  the  middle 
age,  decline  and  dissolve  in  the  transitional  modern  period, 
in  preparation  for  a  new  and  permanent  organic  state  of 
society."  This  traditional  modern  period  is  the  epoch  of 
that  "metaphysical  philosophy"  which  substitutes  for  deities 
entities,  for  personifications  abstractions.  It  is,  according  to 
Comte  distinctively  a  period  of  negation,  criticism,  and  anar- 
chy. Of  its  spirit  and  ideals  he  shows  a  cordial  dislike.  On 
its  chief  forces  and  institutions  he  seldom  looks  with  an  im- 
partial or  favourable  eye.  To  the  philosophy  of  the  eighteenth 


ATJGTJSTE   COMTE  607 

century  and  to  Protestantism,  for  example,  he  is  decidedly- 
unjust,  seeing  both  only  on  their  negative  side,  and  regard- 
ing them  as  stages  of  a  merely  critical  and  destructive  move- 
ment. There  was  a  great  deal  more  than  that  to  be  seen  in 
them.  The  philosophy  of  the  eighteenth  century  had  seri- 
ous faults  and  disastrous  consequences ;  but  it  also  signally 
promoted  principles  and  ideas  of  incalculable  value.  The 
work  which  it  accomplished  was  not  one  of  mere  negation, 
or  of  simple  transition,  but  one  which  is  likely  to  be  as  en- 
during as  the  future  of  humanity  itself.  If  Protestantism 
rejected  and  discarded  much,  it  was  in  the  interest  of  truths 
displaced,  disfigured,  and  almost  extinguished  by  what  it 
renounced;  and  if  it  insisted  on  the  rights  of  reason,  it 
equally  insisted  on  the  claims  of  legitimate,  i.e.,  reasonable 
spiritual  authority,  both  divine  and  human.  The  reader 
must  not  suppose,  however,  that  Comte's  treatment  of  the 
metaphysical  period  was  exclusively  negative  and  censorious ; 
it  was  only  predominantly  so.  He  has  not  failed  to  realise 
that  alongside  of  the  negative  movement  there  was  a  positive 
movement,  directly  tending  to  and  preparing  for  a  definitive 
and  perfect  reorganisation;  nor  did  he  fail  to  attempt  to 
indicate  its  course  and  results  both  as  an  industrial  and  an 
intellectual  development. 

6.  In  the  third  or  positive  stage  of  history  the  mind  recog- 
nises, according  to  Comte,  that  it  can  only  know  phenomena 
and  their  relations  of  succession  and  coexistence  or  laws ;  that 
it  is  vain  for  it  to  seek  acquaintance  with  divine  volitions, 
substances,  forces,  or  final  causes.  His  account  of  this  stage 
is  largely  also  a  theory  of  the  future  of  man.  It  is  to  be  found 
in  what  he  regarded  as  its  definitive  form  in  his  'Positivist 
Catechism, '  '  Positivist  Calendar, '  and  especially  in  the 
fourth  volume  of  his  'System  of  Positive  Polity.'  I  have 
no  wish  to  enter  into  an  examination  of  the  scheme  of  faith 
and  discipline,  of  intellectual  and  industrial,  spiritual  and 
social  organisation,  expounded  in  these  works.  I  readily 
admit  that  there  is  a  good  deal  which  is  true  and  valuable  in 
it;  but,  as  a  whole,  it  seems  to  me  a  most  monstrous  combi- 
nation of  fetichism,  scepticism,  and  Catholicism,  of  sense  and 
folly,  of  science  and  sentimental  drivel.  It  assumed  as  a 
fundamental  truth  that  belief  in  the  entire  subordination  of 


608  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

the  individual  to  society,  which,  more  than  any  other  error, 
vitiated  the  political  philosophy  and  political  practice  of 
classical  antiquity,  and  from  which  Christianity  emancipated 
the  European  mind.  It  proposed  to  organise  the  definitive 
society  of  the  future  according  to  the  medieval  pattern ;  to 
intrust  the  government  of  it  to  a  temporal  and  spiritual 
power  —  a  patriciate  and  a  clergy  —  the  former  centring  in  a 
supreme  triumvirate,  and  the    latter  in  a  supreme  pontiff, 

—  and  the  two  conjointly  regulating  the  whole  lives,  bodily 
and  mental,  affective  and  active,  private  and  public,  in 
minute  conformity  to  the  creed  of  Comte ;  and  even,  while 
forbidding  belief  in  the  existence  of  God  and  of  the  immor- 
tality of  the  soul,  to  impose  a  varied  and  elaborate  worship.1 

The  great  aim  of  Comte  in  the  latest  period  of  his  life  — 
i.e.,  from  1847  until  his  death  in  1857  —  was  to  transform  his 
philosophy  into  a  religion,  and  to  apply  his  religion  to  the 
regulation  and  systematisation  of  all  the  activities  and  insti- 
tutions of  humanity.  The  doctrine  which  he  inculcated  dur- 
ing this  period  was  largely  evolved  from  that  which  he  taught 
in  his  earlier  and  more  sober-minded  period;  but  it  was  also 
largely  a  reaction  from  it,  and  irreconcilable  with  it.     Dr. 

1  It  is  when  treating  of  the  positivist  age  and  the  organisation  of  the  future 
that  Comte  expounds  what  he  calls  his  "  fundamental  theory  of  the  Great  Being  " 

—  i.e.,  Humanity  (Pos.  Pol.,  vol.  iv.  ch.  1).  The  pretentious  way  in  which  he 
states  his  conclusions  is  very  characteristic,  and  their  futility  is  very  obvious. 
"The  Great  Being"  is  defined  as  "the  whole  constituted  by  the  beings,  past, 
future,  and  present,  which  co-operate  willingly  in  perfecting  the  order  of  the 
world;"  and  more  succinctly  as  "the  continuous  whole  formed  by  the  beings 
which  converge. ' '  It  is,  we  are  informed,  a  real  and  indivisible  Being,  more  distinct 
and  definite  than  the  family  or  the  country,  and  has  laws  of  its  own  both  internal 
and  external.  It  does  not  consist  of  all  human  individuals.  Its  "  unworthy 
parasites  in  human  form  "  are  to  be  "  eliminated  "  ;  and  it  must  be  judged  of  by 
its  adult  state,  which  is  just  "beginning,"  not  by  its  childhood  and  adolescence, 
which  we  have  as  yet  only  before  us.  Although  "  every  gregarious  animal  race  " 
answers  so  far  to  the  definition  of  "humanity,"  we  are  justified  in  overlooking 
such  races  ;  but  we  must  recognise  "  as  integral  portions  of  the  Great  Being  the 
animals  which  voluntarily  aid  man."  Humanity  consists  chiefly  of  the  dead,  who- 
are  "  the  patrons  and  protectors  of  the  living."  "  The  dead  alone  can  represent 
humanity;  they  collectively  really  constitute  humanity;  the  living,  born  her 
children,  as  a  rule  become  her  servants,  unless  they  degenerate  into  mere  para- 
sites." The  dead  have  no  objective  existence,  but  they  have  "a  subjective  life, 
which  is  the  true  sphere  of  the  soul's  superiority."  "  No  amount  of  superiority, 
however,  can  call  the-  subjective  life  into  existence,  or  give  it  permanence :  for 
this  it  is  dependent  on  the  objective."  It  is  on  the  ground  of  such  teaching  as  this 
that  Comte  claims  to  have  developed  and  completed  "the  preliminary  apercus  of 
Pascal,  Leibnitz,  and  Condorcet." 


ATJGUSTE   COMTB  609 

Bridges,  and  many  other  positivists  of  the  so-called  orthodox 
school,  have  laboured  to  make  out  the  unity  of  Comte's  life 
and  doctrine.  It  seems  to  me  that  they  have  failed.  They 
have  satisfactorily  proved,  indeed,  "that  the  conception  of 
an  organised  spiritual  power  was  not  one  of  Comte's  later 
speculations,  but  one  of  his  earliest;  that  social  reconstruc- 
tion was  from  the  first  and  to  the  last  the  dominant  motive 
of  his  life;  and  that  the  'Philosophie  Positive'  was  con- 
sciously wrought  out  not  as  an  end  in  itself,  but  as  the  neces- 
sary basis  for  a  renovated  education,  the  foundation  of  a  new 
social  order."  But  this  has  never  been  denied,  and  is  not 
at  all  the  thesis  which  they  require  to  establish.  The  Comt- 
ist  religion  is  not  to  be  confounded  with  the  Comtist  polity. 
The  chief  doctrines  of  the  polity  were  certainly  among  the 
earliest  published  speculations  of  Comte,  and  even  if  false, 
are  false  inferences  from  the  philosophy.  It  is  not  so  with 
the  chief  doctrines  of  the  religion.  The  polity,  as  conceived 
by  Comte  before  the  change  produced  on  his  mind  by  his 
affection  for  Madame  Clotilde  de  Vaux,  aimed  at  the  organi- 
sation of  society  by  reason  and  science.  The  religion  is  based 
on  the  assumption  of  the  supremacy  of  imagination  and  feel- 
ing. It  enjoins  humanity,  instead  of  putting  away,  to  take 
back  the  childish  things  it  had  outgrown.  It  undertakes  the 
spiritual  organisation  of  society,  while  admitting  itself  to 
be  only  a  sort  of  poetical  creation,  a  product  of  self-illusion. 
The  Comtist  polity  may  thus  be  regarded  as  a  defective  struct- 
ure insecurely  founded  on  the  philosophy.  The  Comtist 
religion  cannot  be  regarded  as  founded  on  the  philosophy  at 
all.  Now  it  admits  of  no  doubt  that  the  doctrines  which 
constitute  the  religion,  as  such,  are  among  the  latest  specu- 
lations of  Comte,  —  those  which  originated  in  what  he  char- 
acterised as  "the  revelation  of  power,  purity,  genius,  and 
suffering  "  made  to  him  through  Madame  de  Vaux.  It  was 
the  inspiration  flowing  from  that  revelation  which  filled  him 
with  the  ambition  of  "  rendering  to  his  race  the  services  of  a 
St.  Paul,  after  having  already  conferred  on  it  those  of  an 
Aristotle." 

What  are  we  to  think,  however,  of  "  the  law  of  the  three 
states"  itself?  It  seems  to  me  that  there  is  a  certain  meas- 
ure of  truth  in  it.     There  are  three  ways  of  looking  at  things, 


610  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

—  a  religious,  a  metaphysical,  and  a  scientific.  It  is  natural 
for  the  mind  to  believe  that  things  and  the  successions  of 
things  tell  something  about  a  Being  in  or  beyond  them  with 
faculties  analogous  to  those  which  it  possesses  itself.  It  is 
natural  for  it  also  to  speculate  on  the  reason  and  mode  of  the 
existence  of  things,  and  to  ask  a  number  of  questions  about 
them  which  cannot  be  immediately  answered  from  observa- 
tion of  their  properties  and  ascertainment  of  their  relations 
of  coexistence  and  succession.  It  is  natural  for  it  no  less  to 
observe  these  properties  and  study  these  relations.  It  is 
natural  for  it  to  do  all  three,  and  even  all  three  about  the 
same  things;  in  other  words,  things  may  be  looked  at  in 
three  aspects.  But  three  aspects  are  not  three  successive 
states.  From  the  fact  that  it  is  natural  for  the  mind  to  look 
at  things  in  all  those  three  ways,  it  in  no  wise  follows  that 
it  is  necessary  or  even  natural  to  look  at  them  one  after  an- 
other. Nay,  just  because  it  is  so  natural  to  look  at  things 
in  all  these  three  ways,  it  is  not  natural  to  suppose  that  the 
one  mode  will  be  exhausted,  gone  through,  before  the  other 
is  entered  on,  but  that  they  will  be  simultaneous  in  origin 
and  parallel  in  development;  or  at  least  that  the  religious 
and  positive  will  be  so,  however  the  metaphysical,  as,  so  to 
speak,  the  least  natural  and  imperative,  may  lag  somewhat 
behind  them. 

Now,  what  say  the  facts  ?  Comte  believes  that  man  started 
with  a  religion.  He  attempts  a  refutation  of  those  who  sup- 
posed a  state  prior  to  all  religion,  even  to  fetichism.  But, 
I  ask,  had  man  no  positive  conceptions  even  then?  Did  he 
live  by  fetichism  alone  ?  How  could  he  build  a  hut,  or  cook 
his  food,  or  shoot  with  precision,  otherwise  than  by  atten- 
tion to  the  physical  properties  and  relations  of  things? 
Without  some  conceptions  identical  in  kind,  however  differ- 
ent in  degree,  with  the  latest  discoveries  of  positive  science, 
life  were  impossible.  Positive  conceptions,  then,  instead  of 
only  beginning  in  modern  times,  began  with  the  beginning 
of  human  history.  And  they  have  been  increasing  and  grow- 
ing all  through  it.  True  generalisations  as  to  the  physical 
properties  and  relations  of  things  were  multiplied  and 
widened  by  one  generation  after  another  in  the  so-called 
theological  and  metaphysical  states.     Then,  as  to  metaphys- 


AUGTTSTE   COMTE  611 

ics,  according  to  Comte's  own  account,  it  pervaded  almost 
the  whole  theological  state.  Fetichism  passed  into  polythe- 
ism, and  polytheism  into  monotheism,  from  the  impulse  of 
the  metaphysical  spirit,  and  under  the  influence  of  meta- 
physical conceptions.  And  Comte,  however  inconsistent,  is 
here  obviously  quite  correct.  Nothing  has  so  powerfully 
affected  theological  development  as  speculative  philosophy ; 
and  that  such  philosophy  may  flourish  at  a  comparatively 
early  stage  of  theological  development,  ancient  India  and 
Greece,  with  their  marvellously  subtle  metaphysics  coex- 
isting with  the  most  imaginative  of  polytheisms,  are  surely 
indubitable  proofs. 

Now,  what  does  this  amount  to  ?  Why,  that  Comte  has 
mistaken  three  coexistent  states  for  three  successive  stages 
of  thought,  three  aspects  of  things  for  three  epochs  of  time. 
Theology,  metaphysics,  and  positive  science,  instead  of  fol- 
lowing only  one  after  another,  each  constituting  an  epoch, 
have  each  pervaded  all  epochs, —  have  coexisted  from  the 
earliest  time  to  the  present  day.  There  has  been  no  passing 
away  of  any  of  them.  History  cannot  be  invoked  to  show 
that  theology  and  metaphysics  are  purely  of  her  past  domain, 
merely  preparatory  for  positive  science,  stages  in  the  inter- 
pretation of  nature  through  which  the  mind  required  to  pass 
from  infancy  to  maturity.  History  certifies,  on  the  contrary, 
that  positive  science  and  they  began  at  the  same  time,  that 
they  and  it  have  developed  together  through  all  history,  and 
still  continue  to  exist  together.  Her  own  birth  and  theirs 
were  simultaneous,  and  she  has  not  yet  had  to  record  the 
death  of  any  of  them. 

But  it  is  said  science  has  been  continually  gaining,  theol- 
ogy and  metaphysics  continually  losing,  ground:  science  has 
been  gradually  expelling  both  theology  and  metaphysics  from 
one  region  of  knowledge  after  another,  until  they  will  soon 
have  no  foot  of  ground  to  stand  on.  I  ask,  however,  for 
proof  of  this  assertion,  and  not  only  cannot  find  it,  but  feel 
confident  it  cannot  be  found.  There  is,  indeed,  a  fact  which, 
confusedly  apprehended,  has  given  a  certain  degree  of  plau- 
sibility to  it;  but  this  same  fact,  correctly  apprehended,  is 
really  its  refutation.  The  fact  I  refer  to  is,  that  in  the  early 
history  of  the  race  the  three  leading  aspects  of  things  are  not 


612  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FKANCE 

clearly  distinguished.  Theological,  metaphysical,  and  posi- 
tive conceptions  are  commingled  —  their  developments 
thoroughly  entangled;  often  so  commingled  and  entangled 
that  it  is  impossible  to  determine  whether  they  would  be 
better  described  as  bad  theology,  bad  metaphysics,  or  bad 
science,  being  really  all  three.  But  the  effect  of  progress 
here,  as  everywhere,  is  differentiation,  the  increasing  separa- 
tion of  things  really  and  properly  distinct,  the  inclusion  of 
each  within  its  own  sphere,  and  consequent  exclusion  from 
those  of  others.  Theology  is  driven  more  and  more  out  of 
metaphysics  and  physics;  metaphysics  out  of  theology  and 
physics ;  and  physics  no  less  out  of  metaphysics  and  theology. 

Comte  says  fetichism  is  the  first  and  lowest  stage  of  human 
development.  What,  then,  precisely  is  fetichism  as  de- 
scribed by  himself?  Just  the  chaotic  union  of  theological, 
metaphysical,  and  positive  thought.  It  may  be  described 
equally  well  either  as  a  physical  theology  or  a  theological 
physics,  and  it  is  at  the  same  time  obviously  a  metaphysics, 
an  attribution  of  vital  essences  and  personal  causes  as  inher- 
ent in  inanimate  things.  But  thought  has  come  out  of  this 
chaos,  and  how?  By  the  continuous  evolution  of  all  the 
three  orders  of  conceptions,  by  an  ever-growing  comprehen- 
siveness and  distinctness  of  vision  as  to  the  proper  spheres 
of  all  three.  Each  has  been  gradually  emancipating  itself 
from  the  interference  and  control  of  the  others.  It  is  not 
more  true  that  physics  began  with  being  theological  and 
metaphysical,  than  that  metaphysics  began  with  being  physi- 
cal and  theological,  and  theology  with  being  physical  and 
metaphysical.  The  law  of  the  three  states  is  to  about  the 
same  extent  true  of  all  the  three  developments,  only,  of 
course,  the  arrangement  of  the  states  is  different  in  each. 
It  is  only  in  a  very  general  .way  that  it  is  true  of  any  of 
them,  and  in  such  a  way  it  is,  with  the  necessary  change  of 
terms,  true  of  all. 

I  have  no  objection,  then,  to  admit  that  in  a  very  general 
way  the  so-called  Comtist  law  of  the  three  states  is  true  of 
most  orders  of  properly  positive  conceptions ;  and  I  should 
hold  as  strongly  as  Comte  himself  that  every  order  of  prop- 
erly positive  conceptions  ought  to  be  freed  from  the  inter- 
ference and  intermixture  either  of  theology  or  metaphysics. 


ATTGUSTE   COMTE  613 

The  confusion  of  either  with  positive  science  is  illegitimate 
and  mischievous ;  and  the  expulsion  of  them  from  a  domain 
which  is  foreign  to  them  must  be  beneficial  to  them  no  less 
than  to  the  science  whose  rightful  province  it  is.  Now  it  is 
only  this  sort  of  expulsion,  and  the  restriction  consequent  on 
it,  which  history  shows  them  ever  to  have  met  with.  In 
every  other  way,  each  advance  of  science,  instead  of  being  a 
limitation  of  either,  has  been  an  extension  of  both.  So  far 
from  metaphysics  and  theology  having  been  driven  from  any 
region  of  nature  by  science,  no  science  has  arisen  without 
suggesting  new  questions  to  the  one  and  affording  new  data 
to  the  other.  Each  new  science  brings  with  it  principles 
which  the  metaphysician  finds  it  requisite  to  submit  to  an 
analytic  examination,  and  in  which  he  finds  new  materials 
for  speculation;  and  also,  in  the  measure  of  its  success, 
results  in  which  the  theologian  finds  some  fresh  disclosure  of 
the  thoughts  and  character  of  God.  Underneath  all  science 
there  is  metaphysics,  above  all  science  there  is  theology; 
and  these  three  are  so  related  that  every  advance  of  science 
must  extend  the  spheres  both  of  true  metaphysics  and  true 
theology.  Comte  has  failed  entirely  to  prove  that  theology 
and  metaphysics  are  mere  passing  phases  of  thought,  illu- 
sions of  the  infancy  and  youth  of  humanity,  which  have  no 
sphere  of  reality  corresponding  to  them.  The  testimony  of 
history  is  all  the  other  way ;  it  gives  assurance  that  they  have 
always  been,  and  grounds  of  hope  that  they  will  always  be ; 
that  they  represent  real  aspects  of  existence,  and  respond  to 
eternal  aspirations  in  the  human  heart. 

My  reason  for  holding  it  true  only  in  a  very  general  way, 
or,  in  other  words,  only  very  partially  true,  that  positive 
science  has  passed  through  a  theological  and  metaphysical 
state,  must  be  obvious  from  what  has  been  already  said. 
There  must  have  been  some  conceptions  positive  from  the 
first.  It  is  impossible  to  conceive  of  an  exclusively  theo- 
logical cooking,  hunting,  or  hut-building;  for  although  many 
tribes  of  savage  men  believe  that  food  and  fire,  bows  and 
arrows,  &c,  have  souls,  they  must  none  the  less  attend  to 
the  positive  properties  of  these  things  in  order  to  make  use 
of  them.  There  are  other  conceptions  which,  although  they 
may  or  must  have  been  late  in  being  discovered,  must  yet 


614  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

have  been  at  their  discovery  apprehended  as  positive.  It  is 
most  improbable  that  either  arithmetical  or  geometrical 
truths  were  first  apprehended  as  either  theological  or  meta- 
physical. It  is  true  that  even  arithmetical  and  geometrical 
truths  had  been  theologically  and  metaphysically  regarded, 
as  by  Laotseu,  the  Pythagoreans,  and  Eleatics ;  but  in  these 
cases  the  theology  and  metaphysics  were  by  subtle  efforts  of 
speculative  ingenuity  associated  with,  grafted  on,  positive 
conceptions.  In  mathematics,  the  positive  stage  is  the  first, 
and  spontaneous,  and  only  natural  stage. 

This  is  so  obvious  that  Comte  and  his  disciples  have  been 
unable  altogether  to  ignore  it;  yet  they  have,  notwithstand- 
ing, adhered  to  their  law  as  if  it  were  unaffected  by  such 
facts.  A  more  inconsistent  and  futile  expedient  could  not 
be  imagined.  By  having  recourse  to  it  they  have  exposed 
themselves  to  the  charge  of  the  crassest  ignorance  of  what  is 
meant  by  a  law  of  nature.  A  law  which  does  not  apply  to  a 
class  of  phenomena  is  surely  not  the  law  of  these  phenom- 
ena; and  even  a  so-called  law,  which  only  sometimes  or  in 
part  applies  to  a  class  of  phenomena,  can  surely  be  no  true 
law.  The  most  elementary  notion  of  a  law  of  nature  is  a 
rule  without  exceptions  —  a  uniformity  of  connection  among 
coexistent  or  successive  facts.  And  yet  Comte,  although 
maintaining  his  law  of  the  three  states,  three  mutually  ex- 
clusive phases  of  thought,  to  be  the  law  of  historical  evolu- 
tion, an  invariable  and  necessary  law,  can  write  thus :  — 

"Properly  speaking,  the  theological  philosophy,  even  in  the  earliest 
infancy  of  the  individual  and  society,  has  never  been  strictly  universal. 
That  is,  the  simplest  and  commonest  facts  in  all  classes  of  phenomena 
have  always  been  supposed  subject  to  natural  laws,  and  not  ascribed  to 
the  arbitrary  will  of  supernatural  agents.  The  illustrious  Adam  Smith 
has,  for  example,  made  the  very  felicitous  remark,  that  there  was  to  be 
found  in  no  age  or  country  a  god  of  weight.  And  even  in  more  compli- 
cated cases  the  presence  of  law  may  be  recognised  whenever  the  phe- 
nomena are  so  elementary  and  familiar  that  the  perfect  invariability 
of  their  relationships  of  occurrence  cannot  fail  to  strike  even  the  least 
educated  observer.  As  to  things  moral  and  social,  which  some  would 
foolishly  exclude  from  the  sphere  of  positive  philosophy,  there  has 
necessarily  always  been  a  belief  in  natural  laws  with  regard  to  the  sim- 
pler phenomena  of  daily  life  —  a  belief  implied  in  the  conduct  of  the 
ordinary  affairs  of  existence,  —  since  all  foresight  would  be  impossible 
on  the  supposition  that  every  incident  was  due  to  supernatural  agency, 


LAFPITTB  615 

and  in  that  case  prayer  would  be  the  only  conceivable  means  of  influ- 
encing the  course  of  human  actions.  It  is  even  noticeable  that  the  prin- 
ciple of  the  theological  philosophy  itself  lies  in  the  transference  to  the 
phenomena  of  external  nature  of  the  first  beginnings  of  the  laws  of 
human  action ;  and  thus  the  germ  of  the  positive  philosophy  is  at 
least  as  primitive  as  that  of  the  theological  philosophy  itself,  though 
it  could  not  expand  till  a  much  later  time.  This  idea  is  very  im- 
portant to  the  perfect  rationality  of  our  sociological  theory;  because, 
as  human  life  can  never  present  any  real  creation,  but  only  a  gradual 
evolution,  the  final  spread  of  the  positive  spirit  would  be  scientifically 
incomprehensible,  if  we  could  not  trace  its  rudiments  from  the  very 
beginning." x 

1  consider  these  remarks  excellent,  but  excellent  as  a  proof 
that  there  is  no  such  law  as  the  so-called  law  of  three  states. 
If  they  be  true,  as  I  have  no  doubt  they  are,  it  cannot  possi- 
bly be  in  any  recognised  or  proper  sense  of  the  term  the  law, 
the  fundamental  law  of  history;  it  can  at  the  most  be  only 
the  law  of  some  historical  phenomena  which  Comte  should 
have  carefully  discriminated  from  other  phenomena,  in  order 
not  to  impose  on  himself  and  his  readers  a  secondary  and 
special  in  place  of  a  primarjr  and  general  law.  If  true,  he 
was  logically  bound  entirely  to  recast  his  statement  of  his 
supposed  law,  and  to  acknowledge  that,  if  a  law  at  all,  it 
was  by  no  means  one  so  important  as  he  had  at  first  imagined. 
He  failed  to  take  this  course,  and  involved  himself,  in  con- 
sequence, in  obvious  self-contradictions  on  which  I  need  not 
insist,  as  they  have  been  clearly  pointed  out  by  many  of  his 
critics.2 

II 

Auguste  Comte  left  behind  him  a  school  of  disciples  who 
accepted  his  system  in  its  entirety, —  its  philosophy,  polity, 
and  religion.  The  head  of  this  school,  the  immediate  suc- 
cessor of  Comte,  and  the  present  pontiff  of  "  the  religion  of 
humanity,"  is  M.  Pierre  Laffitte.  He  is  a  learned  man,  well 
acquainted  with  the  sciences  in  favour  among  positivists, 
and  intimately  conversant  with  the  doctrine  in  which  he 
believes  that  social  salvation  can  alone  be  found.     He  has 

'Phil.  Pos.,  iv.  491. 

2  See  Prof.  Shield's  '  Philosophia  Ultima,'  vol.  i.,  pt.  ii.,  ch.  ii.,  pp.  287-314; 
Prof.  Caird's  '  Social  Philosophy  of  Comte,'  &c. 


616  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

earnestly  laboured  to  propagate  the  creed  and  realise  the 
aims  of  his  master.  He  has  written  some  works  which 
expound  and  so  far  supplement  and  develop  the  historical 
theories  of  Comte,  but  which  do  not  substantially  add  to 
them.  A  mere  reference  to  these  works  will,  I  think,  be 
sufficient.1 

There  is,  further,  an  extreme  positivist  party,  a  so-called 
"party  of  strict  observance."  In  the  eyes  of  its  members  M. 
Laffitte  is  deficient  in  zeal,  orthodoxy,  and  priestliness.  They 
accept  Comte's  wildest  absurdities  as  precious  certainties, 
and  would  rigidly  obey  all  his  injunctions.  They  are,  be- 
sides, very  irascible,  and  much  given  to  impute  bad  motives 
to  those  whose  faith  does  not  coincide  with  their  own.  Drs. 
Audiffrent,  Robinet,  and  Se'me'rie  are  representatives  of  the 
French  section  of  these  positivist  puritans.  The  way  in 
which  they  assailed  those  who  stated  and  proved  the  harm- 
less and  easily  verifiable  historical  fact  that  Comte's  "law  of 
the  three  states  "  was  not  an  altogether  original  discovery, 
is  too  characteristic  of  their  party. 

Far  the  most  eminent  of  Comte's  disciples  in  France  was 
the  late  Emile  Littr6  (1801-1881).  By  the  orthodox  posi- 
tivists  he  was  fanatically  hated,  and,  no  doubt  conscien- 
tiously, habitually  calumniated.  What  unprejudiced  persons 
•could  only  have  ascribed  to  his  love  of  truth,  they  unhesitat- 
ingly attributed  to  hatred  of  Comte.  He  seems  to  me  to 
have  shown  himself  as  loyal  to  Comte  as  loyalty  to  conscience 
would  allow  him  to  be.  He  did  more  than  all  the  orthodox 
positivists  combined  have  done  to  recommend  and  diffuse 
what  was  true  or  plausible  in  the  doctrine  of  Comte.  A 
wonderful  amount  of  admirable  work  was  accomplished  by 
this  modest,  indefatigable,  most  virtuous,  and  highly  gifted 
man.  Much  of  it,  and  the  best  part  of  it,  however,  owed  little 
or  nothing  to  Comte,  although  he  himself  thought  other- 
wise.    His  philosophy  only  was  derived  from  Comte.     And 

1 '  Cours  philosophique  sur  l'histoire  generale  de  1'humanite','  1859 ;  '  Les  grands 
types  de  1'humanite,'  1874-75 ;  '  Considerations  generales  sur  I'ensemble  de  la 
civilisation  chinoise,'  1861;  and  the  outlines  of  his  lectures  on  "the  third  phi- 
losophy" in  the  'Rev.  Occid.'  for  1886  and  1887.  The  'Revue  Oeeidentale,'  the 
official  organ  of  the  positivist  priesthood,  is  a  bi-monthly  publication,  and  has 
appeared  since  May,  1878.  A  chair  of  General  History  of  the  Sciences  has  been 
created  for  M.  Laffitte  at  the  "  College  de  France." 


LITTEB  617 

that  as  a  general  doctrine  I  require  neither  to  expound  nor 
criticise.1  But  I  must,  of  course,  consider  the  account  which 
he  gives  of  "the  law  of  the  three  states,"  and  his  attempt  to 
improve  on  it. 

He  at  first  accepted  it  just  as  it  had  been  presented  by 
Comte.  But  in  his  'Paroles  de  philosophie  positive,'  pub- 
lished in  1859,  he  maintained  that,  although  it  must  be  held 
to  be  a  true  law,  the  discovery  of  which  had  founded  sociol- 
ogy, it  was  only  an  empirical  law,  a  mere  general  statement 
of  historical  fact ;  and  accordingly,  he  proposed  to  substitute 
for  it  a  law  of  four  states,  as  at  once  of  a  deeper  and  more 
comprehensive  character,  as  inclusive  of  Comte's  law,  and 
entitled,  in  consequence  of  explaining  the  development  of 
humanity  by  the  development  of  the  individual  mind,  to  the 
designation  of  rational.  In  his  much  more  important  work, 
'Auguste  Comte,'  published  four  years  later,  he  confessed 
to  have  discovered  in  the  interval  that  a  law  very  similar  to 
that  which  he  had  proposed  had  been  enunciated  by  Saint- 
Simon  so  far  back  as  1808.  Still  maintaining,  however,  the 
great  importance  and  substantial  originality  of  his  own  con- 
ception, he  not  only  adhered  to  his  criticism  of  the  Comtiari 
law,  but  greatly  extended  it.  He  denied  that  that  law 
applied  to  the  development  of  industry,  morality,  or  art ;  and 
affirmed  that  it  held  true  only  of  the  development  of  science. 
"This  criticism,"  he  says,  "I  uphold;  however,  I  wish  not 
to  be  misunderstood  and  supposed  to  reject  the  law  of  the 
three  states.  I  do  not  reject  it,  I  restrict  it.  So  long  as  we 
keep  within  the  scientific  order,  and  consider  the  conception 
of  the  world  as  at  first  theological,  then  metaphysical,  and 
finally,  positive,  the  law  of  the  three  states  retains  all  its 
validity  for  the  guidance  of  historical  speculations.  .  .  . 
But  all  that  is  in  history  is  not  confined  within  the  scientific 
order.  M.  Comte,  who  has  somewhere  said  that  we  must 
suppose  some  notions  to  have  been  always  neither  theologi- 
cal nor  metaphysical,  has  indicated  the  germ,  I  shall  not  say 
of  my  objection,  but  of  my  restriction.     In  fact,  the  law  of 

'For  a  masterly  exposition  and  criticism  of  it,  see  Caro's  'M.  Littre  et  le 
Positivisme,'  1883.  The  positivism  of  Littre  had  for  its  literary,  organ  '  La 
Philosophie  Positive,'  a  review  founded  in  1867,  and  which  appeared  until  the 
close  of  1883.  Among  its  most  active  contributors  were,  besides  Littre',  Wyrou- 
t>off,  Robin,  Naquet,  De  Koberty,  &c. 


618  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

the  three  states  applies  neither  to  the  industrial  development, 
nor  to  the  moral  development,  nor  to  the  aesthetic  develop- 
ment."1 The  law  which  Littre"  imagined  to  comprehend  and 
supplement  that  of  Comte,  he  stated  thus :  "  It  seems  to  me 
that  history  is  divisible  into  four  fundamental  ages :  the  most 
ancient  is  that  in  which  humanity  is  under  the  preponderat- 
ing sway  of  its  wants  and  appetites;  the  next,  or  age  of 
religions,  is  that  in  which  the  development  of  the  moral  nat- 
ure produces  civil  and  religious  creations ;  the  third,  or  age 
of  art,  is  that  in  which  the  sense  of  the  beautiful,  becomes 
in  its  turn,  capable  of  gratification,  gives  rise  to  aesthetic 
constructions  and  poems;  finally,  the  fourth  age,  or  age  of 
science,  is  that  in  which  reason,  ceasing  to  be  exclusively 
exercised  in  the  accomplishment  of  the  three  foregoing  func- 
tions, works  for  itself  and  proceeds  in  the  search  after  ab- 
stract truth." 

I  much  prefer  Comte's  law  of  the  three  states  to  the  one 
thus  formulated  by  Littre'.  Certainly  the  latter  is  remarka- 
bly similar  to  that  which  Saint-Simon  had  laid  down  half  a 
century  earlier,  when  he  maintained  that  the  development, 
both  of  the  race  and  of  the  individual,  might  be  divided  into 
four  stages — -viz.,  1st,  Infancy,  characterised  by  delight  in 
construction  and  handiwork;  2d,  Puberty,  characterised  by 
artistic  aspirations ;  3d,  Manhood,  characterised  by  military 
ambition ;  and  4th,  Age,  characterised  by  the  love  of  science. 
Of  course,  Littre"  has  endeavoured  to  show  that  his  law  is 
much  superior  to  that  proposed  by  Saint-Simon.  It  seems 
to  me  that  there  is  very  little  to  choose  between  them;  and, 
indeed,  that  both  are  so  bad  that  it  would  be  mere  labour  lost 
to  try  to  ascertain  which  is  best  or  worst.  Every  so-called 
law  which  represents  the  elements  of  consciousness  as  taking 
what  is  colloquially  called  turn  about  in  ruling  the  historical 
evolution,  one  element  being  the  superior  principle  in  one 
age  of  the  world,  and  another  in  another,  is  utterly  unsatis- 
factory. And  the  reason  of  this  is  that  all  such  laws  implic- 
itly contradict  the  truth  which  Comte  had  the  wisdom  to  lay 
down  as  the  very  corner-stone  of  his  historical  philosophy. 

Believing  as  he  did  the  continuous  homogeneousness  of 
the  collective  movement  of  humanity  to  be  an  indispensable 

1 '  Auguste  Comte,'  pp.  49,  50. 


LITTRE  619 

presupposition  to  the  construction  of  a  philosophy  of  history, 
he  could  not  have  failed  to  be  astounded  at  any  one  who 
denied  it  fancying  he  nevertheless  accepted  his  philosophy 
of  history  on  the  whole.  Such  is,  however,  the  position 
taken  up  by  Littre",  when  he  maintains  that  the  law  of  the 
three  states  regulates  only  the  intellectual,  or,  as  he  gener- 
ally calls  it,  the  scientific  development ;  and  that  expressly 
on  the  ground  that  the  industrial,  moral,  and  aesthetic  devel- 
opments are  separate  from,  and  antecedent  to,  the  intellectual 
development,  instead  of  being,  as  Comte  so  strongly  insisted, 
dependent  on,  correspondent  to,  and  contemporaneous  with 
it.  Comte  had  a  clear  recognition  of  the  truth  that  the  spe- 
cial developments  of  human  activity  are  not  successive 
epochs  of  history.  Littre" 's  distinctive  theory  affirms  that 
they  are  so.  To  me  Littre"  seems  entirely  wrong,  and  Comte 
thoroughly  right. 

Littre-  believed  his  law  to  have  the  advantage  over  Comte's 
of  being  not  only  empirical  but  rational.  Comte,  however, 
held  the  law  of  the  three  states  to  be  rational  as  well  as  em- 
pirical. He  has  explicitly  and  repeatedly  argued  that  it  can 
be  reached  by  deduction  no  less  than  by  induction,  and  is 
not  merely  a  description  of  the  ascertained  course  of  human 
events,  a  general  statement  of  historical  fact,  but  a  law  of 
which  the  a  priori  reason  is  known,  and  which  is  the  expres- 
sion not  simply  of  what  has  happened,  but  of  what,  from  the 
very  nature  of  the  human  mind,  must  have  happened.  In 
contrasting  the  law  of  the  three  states  with  a  law  of  four 
states  as  an  empirical  with  a  rational  law,  Littre"  overlooked 
both  the  direct  claims  made  by  Comte  on  behalf  of  the  first- 
mentioned  law,  and  the  numerous  passages  in  which  he 
attempted  to  assign  its  logical,  moral,  and  social  grounds. 
He  may  have  failed  to  prove  it  to  be  rationally  or  philosophi- 
cally necessary ;  but  he  certainly  took  much  more  trouble  in 
endeavouring  to  do  so  than  Littre"  himself  took  in  connection 
with  the  alleged  law  of  four  states. 

It  is  only  necessary  further  to  remark  that  the  law  of  the 
three  states  so  restricted  as  Littre"  would  restrict  it  cannot 
possibly  be  a  fundamental  law  of  history.  If  it  be,  as  he 
represents  it,  empirical  in  character  in  the  humblest  sense  of 
the  term,  and  confined  to  a  single  sphere  of  human  activity, 


620  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

and  to  one  of  the  four  ages  of  history,  it  can  only  be  at  the 
most  a  law  of  secondary  importance,  and  the  pretensions  put 
forth  by  Comte  in  connection  with  it,  and  unanimously  and 
enthusiastically  endorsed  by  his  disciples,  must  have  been 
highly  extravagant.  However,  even  after  all  his  admissions 
and  restrictions,  instead  of  confessing  that  what  Comtists 
had  hitherto  so  exultingly  proclaimed  as  the  greatest,  most 
fundamental,  most  distinctive  discovery  of  their  master,  the 
so-called  central  law  of  social  evolution  as  much  as  gravita- 
tion is  of  the  solar  system,  had  been  found  to  be  a  very 
imperfect  and  incomplete  achievement,  the  recognition  of  a 
mere  fragment  or  section  of  the  truth,  Littre"  showed  him- 
self quite  unconscious  that  any  such  confession  was  needed. 

The  mode  of  thought  which  found  expression  in  the  natu- 
ralism of  Charles  Comte  and  the  positivism  of  Auguste 
Comte  became  the  predominant  one  in  France.  For  nearly 
half  a  century  it  has  been  more  prevalent  and  powerful  than 
any  other.  We  can  see  the  effects  of  it  everywhere, —  in 
the  tone  of  society,  in  the  conduct  of  life,  in  politics,  in 
poetry  and  other  arts,  in  fiction,  and  in  the  aims  and  efforts 
of  science  and  speculation.  But  this  is  largely  owing  to  its 
having  escaped  from  the  confinement  of  a  particular  philo- 
sophical school,  and  dissociated  itself  from  any  very  definite 
or  much  developed  doctrine.  The  positivism  which  now 
prevails  in  France  and  elsewhere,  is  indistinguishable  from 
naturalism,  experientialism,  and  materialism;  is  indefinitely 
variable  in  its  forms ;  and  is  pledged  only  to  the  acknowledg- 
ment of  a  few  rather  vague  general  principles.  It  is  little 
more  than  a  mode  of  thought,  a  tendency  of  spirit.  Its  most 
obvious  characteristic  is  its  distrust  of  all  pretensions  to  the 
possession  of  absolute  truth ;  its  aversion  to  all  belief  in  the 
supersensuous ;  its  contentment  with  a  reference  of  phenom- 
ena of  any  kind  to  antecedent  and  contiguous  phenomena 
as  an  adequate  elucidation.  Positivism  thus  understood  has 
penetrated  into  all  departments  of  history,  and  made  its  in- 
fluence strongly  felt  within  them  all. 

It  has  undoubtedly  Contributed  to  the  spread  and  enlarge- 
ment of  historical  study-  but  it  has  also,  I  think,  considera- 
bly biassed  and  depraved  it.     The  positivist  spirit  necessarily 


SAINTE-BEUVE  621 

looks  at  all  things  historically,  and  treats  as  history  what- 
ever can  be  so  treated ;  but  it  also  naturally  loves  to  attach 
itself  specially  to  the  consideration  of  those  sections  or 
phases  of  human  history  which  it  can  most  easily  represent 
as  being  developments  of  merely  natural  history,  and  from 
which  it  can  most  plausibly  conclude  that  there  is  no  essen- 
tial and  immutable  truth  in  thought,  religion,  or  morality. 
This  largely  accounts  for  the  predilection  which  writers 
imbued  with  it  have  shown  for  anthropology,  ethnology,  pre- 
historic archaeology,  and  the  comparative  study  of  religions 
and  of  languages,  as  well  as  for  a  want  of  scientific  impar- 
tiality too  often  apparent  in  their  works.  M.  Hovelacque, 
Lefevre,  Letourneau,  Topinard,  E.  Ve"ron,  and  many  others, 
might  be  referred  to  in  proof  and  illustration  of  the  state- 
ment. The  treatises  which  they  have  produced  in  the 
departments  of  historical  study  mentioned,  although  in  vari- 
ous respects  highly  useful  and  meritorious,  are  far  from 
being  uniformly  trustworthy,  the  anti-theological  and  anti- 
metaphysical  fanaticism  of  their  authors  having  frequently 
led  them  not  only  to  draw  their  conclusions  hastily,  but  to 
collect  their  data  uncritically. 

The  power  of  the  positivist  and  naturalist  tendencies  of 
the  age  has  made  itself  deplorably  conspicuous  in  France,  by 
giving  rise  to  a  school  or  rather  generation  of  UttSrateurs 
whose  ambition  has  been  to  make  even  their  novels  studies 
in  natural  history,  delineations  of  individual  and  social  exist- 
ence, from  which  all  spiritual  elements  and  ethnical  motives 
have  been  carefully  eliminated,  while  bestial  passions  and 
physiological  or  pathological  laws  are  exhibited  as  the  sole 
springs  of  human  action,  the  forces  which  really  sway  human 
nature.  That  it  should  also  have  shown  itself  in  the  trans- 
formation of  certain  disciplines  which  had  previously  been 
treated  as  theoretical  or  practical  into  historical  was  what 
was  to  be  expected.  The  most  striking  example,  perhaps, 
of  a  change  of  this  kind,  is  that  which  was  mainly  effected 
by  Sainte-Beuve  in  literary  criticism. 

Charles  August  Sainte-Beuve  (1804-69)  must  be  ac- 
knowledged to  have  been  among  the  most  eminent  of  the 
literary  critics  of  the  present  century,  even  if   we  restrict 


6  22  PHILOSOPHY  OF  HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

the  signification  of  literary  criticism  to  appreciation  of  the 
phenomena  or  products  of  literature ;  for  incessant  and  com- 
prehensive study,  and  the  varied  and  careful  culture  of  a 
pliant  and  penetrating  judgment  and  delicate  aesthetic  sen- 
sibilities, had  given  him  a  vast  and  exquisite  familiarity 
with  the  achievements  of  art  through  the  instrumentality  of 
language.  He  was,  however,  even  more  an  historian  than 
a  critic;  occupied  himself  more  with  authors  than  their 
books.  Each  literary  work  seemed  to  him  to  be  a  product 
of  mind  only  capable  of  being  understood  by  a  study  of  the 
character,  genius,  temperament,  bodily  constitution,  educa- 
tion, ancestry,  race,  country,  and  intellectual,  moral,  and 
social  surroundings  of  the  individual  who  produced  it. 
Such  is  the  positivist  method  as  it  was  applied  to  criticism 
by  a  man  of  fine  taste  and  rare  talent,  and  applied  in  the 
freest  and  most  genial  way,  without  any  systematic  exclu- 
siveness  or  dogmatic  narrowness.  It  may,  perhaps,  be  justly 
held  that  the  method  was  at  times  unfavourable  even  to 
Sainte-Beuve's  work  as  a  critic;  and  that,  in  that  capacity, 
he  would  not  infrequently  have  been  more  profitably  occu- 
pied in  the  direct  study  of  the  writings  under  his  examina- 
tion than  in  the  collection  of  biographical  and  historical  data, 
with  the  hope  of  being  thereby  able  to  throw  a  fuller  light 
on  them  than  that  which  they  possessed  in  themselves.  But 
it  cannot  be  doubted  that,  owing  to  his  predilection  for  the 
method,  we  have  in  his  'Portraits  Litte"raires, '  'Causeries  du 
Lundi,'  and  'Nouveaux  Causeries,'  taken  collectively,  one  of 
the  richest  contributions  made  to  history,  and  especially  to 
literary  history,  by  any  single  individual  in  this  age.  His 
'Histoire  of  Port-Royal'  (6  vols.)  is  not  merely  a  complete 
account  of  the  famous  Jansenist  community  immortalised  by 
the  genius  and  piety  of  the  Arn<u^|ds,  of  Saint-Cyran,  Pascal, 
De  Sacy,  and  their  friends,  but  the  most  brilliant  and  in- 
structive representation  yet  given  of  the  religious  life  of 
France  in  the  days  of  Louis  XIV. 

The  late  M.  Renan  (1823-92)  entertained  a  very  poor 
opinion  of  A.  Comte  and  his  philosophy.  He  was  of  too 
tolerant  a  temperament  and  too  familiar  with  doubts  and 
difficulties  to  have  any  sympathy  with  a  nature  so  arrogant 


RENAN  623 

and  dogmatic.  He  was  too  learned  to  be  able  to  overlook 
Comte's  ignorance  of  historical  and  other  facts  which  he  pre- 
tended to  reduce  under  rigid  laws.  He  had  too  delicate  a 
perception  of  the  fitnesses  of  things  not  to  be  shocked  by  the 
want  of  common-sense  and  ordinary  foresight  shown  in  many 
of  the  doctrines  and  prophecies  of  the  founder  of  "  the  relig- 
ion of  humanity."  A  writer  of  the  lightest  and  deftest 
touch,  master  of  a  style  so  simple  and  graceful  that  it  never 
ceases  to  charm  and  enliven  the  reader,  he  naturally  re- 
garded the  strong  and  original  but  lumbering  and  overloaded 
sentences  of  Comte  as  "bad  French."  He  rejected  "the  law 
of  the  three  states,"  and,  so  far  as  I  know,  all  Comte's  other 
laws,  as  generalisations  faulty  in  excess;  and  he  thought 
that  such  truths  as  he  had  expressed,  Descartes,  Voltaire, 
D'  Alembert,  and  others,  had  uttered  before  him  in  more  appro- 
priate language. 

Yet  M.  Renan  may,  without  any  substantial  injustice, 
be  numbered  among  positivists.  He  discarded  theology  and 
metaphysics  as  entirely  as  Comte.  Only  positive  science,  he 
held,  could  supply  men  with  the  truths  without  which  life 
would  be  insupportable  and  science  impossible.  He  believed 
in  the  ideal  but  not  in  the  supernatural ;  in  God  and  Provi- 
dence, but  as  "categories  of  thought."  What  may  be  called 
his  pantheism  is  neither  more  nor  less  inconsistent  with 
positivism  than  was  Comte's  ascription  of  self -activity  to 
matter,  and  of  divinity  to  humanity;  it  was  a  belief  that 
there  is  a  latent  living  reason  in  everything,  and  that  in  the 
course  of  millions  of  years  the  universe  may  evolve  an  abso- 
lute consciousness,  and  so  bring  forth  God,  although  there  is 
at  present  no  trace  either  in  nature  or  history  of  any  will 
higher  than  the  human. 

History  has  been  Renan's  favourite  department  of  study; 
and  in  historical  study  he  has  sought  to  employ  the  method 
of  the  natural  sciences.  He  early  saw,  and  set  forth  with 
admirable  clearness  of  view  and  statement,  the  fact  that  nat- 
ure has  had  a  history  as  well  as  humanity,  and  that  evolution 
is  a  conception  of  fundamental  significance  both  in  the  physi- 
cal and  human  sphere.  At  the  same  time  he  rejected  fatal- 
ism and  necessitarianism,  accepting  the  belief  in  freedom  as 
sufficiently  attested  by  consciousness.     Nor  can  he  be  charged 


624  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

with  having  identified  the  physical  and  the  spiritual,  or 
having  unduly  subordinated  the  latter  to  the  former,  as  so 
many  positivists  and  naturalists  have  done.  On  the. con- 
trary, it  is  one  of  his  chief  merits  to  have  clearly  seen  that 
history  must  be  explained  from  within,  not  from  without. 
No  one  has  more  fully  recognised  that  it  cannot  be  justly 
considered  to  have  been  understood  until  it  has  yielded  a 
psychology  of  humanity  —  i.e.,  led  to  a  scientific  knowledge 
of  the  formation  and  growth  of  consciousness,  or  of  the  devel- 
opment of  mind,  on  earth.  His  predilection  for  the  study 
of  languages  and  of  religions  was  intimately  connected  with 
his  interest  in  human  nature  and  his  sense  of  the  importance 
of  a  psychology  of  humanity.  Languages  and  religions  are 
the  clearest  and  most  truthful  mirrors  of  the  mind  and  heart 
of  man.  They  are  those  products  of  the  human  spirit  from 
which  the  elements  of  a  comparative  psychology,  a  psychol- 
ogy entitled  to  be  regarded  as  the  fundamental  historical 
science,  may  be  most  easily  and  abundantly  drawn. 

The  'Histoire  G6ne"rale  des  Langues  Semitiques, '  1855, — 
the  best,  I  think,  of  all  M.  Renan's  writings, — •  is  to  a  large 
extent  a  study  in  comparative  psychology,  an  attempt  to 
delineate  the  characteristics  of  the  Semitic  race.  It  was 
meant  to  have  been  completed  by  a  Comparative  Grammar 
of  the  Semitic  Languages,  which  never  appeared,  possibly 
because  the  task  contemplated  —  namely,  the  unfolding  of 
"  the  internal  history  of  these  languages,  the  organic  develop- 
ment of  their  processes,  their  comparative  grammar  viewed 
not  as  an  immutable,  but  as  a  subject  of  incessant  changes," 
—  was  found  too  difficult  of  accomplishment.  It  is  at 
least  a  task  which  remains  unaccomplished,  no  German 
orientalist  even  having  as  yet  taken  it  in  hand,  and  the  work 
on  Semitic  Comparative  Grammar  of  the  late  Prof.  Wright 
being  merely  linguistic,  without  any  direct  historical  or 
psychological  interest.  Many  of  the  views  first  expressed 
in  the  'Histoire  G^nerale  '  he  found  occasion  to  reiterate 
and  develop  in  his  subsequent  publications. 

His  delineation  of  the  Semitic  mind  must  not  be  judged 
of  as  an  attempt  exactly  to  portray  actual  reality,  but  as  one 
merely  meant  to  convey  a  generally  correct  impression  of  a 
type  of  character  more  commonly  manifested  in  the  Semitic 


•  RENAN  625 

group  of  peoples  than  in  those  of  any  co-ordinate  group. 
Through  overlooking  this,  his  critics  have  often  interpreted 
his  statements  too  absolutely,  and  censured  them  unjustly. 
In  my  opinion,  he  has  rightly  attributed  to  the  Semites  a 
peculiar  genius  for  religion ;  rightly  maintained  their  inferi- 
ority to  the  Aryans  as  regards  both  imagination  and  specu- 
lation; and  rightly  indicated  how  their  inferiority  in  these 
respects  favoured  their  attainment  of  a  simpler,  more  ele- 
vated, and  more,  ethical  idea  of  the  Divine.  He  has  well 
shown  how  the  Semitic  mind  is  at  once  reflected  in  Semitic 
speech,  and  restricted  by  its  imperfections  as  an  instrument 
of  thought,  the  Semitic  languages  being  in  vocables,  inflec- 
tions, qualifying  and  copulative  terms,  as  a  rule,  far  poorer, 
more  mechanical  in  their  applications,  and  more  limited  in 
their  capabilities,  than  the  Aryan,  while  the  words  them- 
selves are  more  sensuous,  less  ideal.  Notwithstanding  errors 
of  detail,  he  has,  on  the  whole,  correctly  as  well  as  strikingly 
delineated  the  general  features  of  the  Semitic  character  and 
genius  in  the  chief  spheres  of  human  life, — in  practical  affairs, 
in  political  conduct,  in  literature,  in  art,  in  science,  in  philos- 
ophy, and  in  religion.  The  attempts  which  have  been  made 
by  Steinthal,  Max  Muller,  Grau,  Hommel,  Von  Kremer, 
Noldeke,  Le  Bon,  Fairbairn,  and  others,  to  trace  these  feat- 
ures, have  been  so  far  due  to  the  interest  excited  by  that  of 
Renan,  and  but  for  it  would  have  been  of  less  value  than  they 
are.  The  results  at  which  they  have  arrived,  although,  per- 
haps, more  definite  and  developed  than  his,  seem  to  me  to  be 
for  the  most  part  substantially  the  same. 

.  While  Renan  has  represented  races  as  important  factors  in 
history,  and  specially  endeavoured  to  show  how  the  mental 
characteristics  of  one  of  those  races  have  manifested  themselves 
therein  and  affected  the  destinies  of  humanity,  he  cannot  be 
fairly  charged  with  having  sought  to  explain  history  merely  by 
the  principle  of  races,  or  with  having  treated  races  as  species, 
their  aptitudes  as  exclusive  properties,  and  their  influences  as 
necessary  and  invariable.  He  has  so  repeatedly  expressed  him- 
self to  a  contrary  effect,  so  fully  recognised  the  derivative  and 
modifiable  nature  of  race,  that  this  common  misrepresentation 
of  his  teaching  is  hardly  excusable. 

His  celebrated  hypothesis  attributing  to  the  Semitic  race  a 


626  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PEANCE  9 

monotheistic  instinct,  generated  by  living  in  the  solitude  of  the 
desert,  can  certainly  not  be  accepted  strictly  or  literally.  Com- 
parative psychology  has  nowhere  found  an  instinct  or  faculty 
which  is  the  exclusive  possession  of  any  one  portion  of  human- 
ity. A  vast  sandy  desert  could  never  of  itself  impress  on  the 
human  mind  an  idea  of  the  oneness  of  God.  All  the  Semitic 
peoples  have  been  at  some  time  or  other  polytheists,  and  several 
of  them  were  never  monotheists.  But  these  admissions  do  not 
dispose  of  the  hypothesis.  Fairly  interpreted,  M.  Renan  will 
not  be  found  to  have  meant  by  a  monotheistic  instinct  more 
than  a  tendency  towards  monotheism,  or,  more  precisely,  more 
than  a  mode  of  conceiving  of  the  Divine  favourable  to  monothe- 
ism. Although  it  is  far  from  certain  that  the  childhood  of  the 
Semites  was  spent  in  the  desert,  it  can  hardly  be  doubted  that 
just  as  the  manifoldness  and  wealth  of  nature  around  the  early 
Aryans  must  have  contributed  greatly  to  their  looking  upon 
nature  and  its  processes  in  a  way  which  led  them  both  to  their 
polytheism  and  their  pantheism,  so  the  surroundings  of  the 
early  Semites  equally  favoured  the  rise  and  growth  of  the 
simpler  and  sterner  faith  which  their  names  for  the  Divine 
clearly  attest  that  they  held  before  they  separated  and  became 
distinct  peoples.  Renan  was  not  only  fully  aware  of,  but  freely 
accepted,  the  facts  as  to  Semitic  polytheism ;  and  he  could  con- 
sistently do  so,  inasmuch  as  he  had  never  assigned  to  the  early 
Semites  a  distinct,  much  less  a  developed  monotheism,  but 
merely  an  undefined  germinal  monotheism,  which  consisted 
simply  in  a  vague  consciousness  of  the  Divine  powers  or  Elo- 
him  as  undivided,  separate  from  the  world  and  man,  and  essen- 
tially superior  to  them.  The  oldest  and  most  prevalent  Semitic 
names  for  the  Divine  are  sufficient  to  prove  that  long  before  the 
Semites  had  any  written  records,  they  had  a  conception  of  the 
Divine  markedly  distinct  from  the  corresponding  conception 
among  the  Aryans,  and  one  which  tended  more  towards 
monotheism. 

M.  Renan  claimed  to  have  "  the  facility  of  reproducing  in  him- 
self the  intuitions  of  past  ages,"  —  "the  faculty  of  comprehend- 
ing states  very  different  from  that  in  which  we  live."  And  it 
must  be  admitted  that  he  really  possessed  such  a  facility  or 
faculty  in  an  exceptional  degree.  His  mental  organisation  was 
at  all  points  sensitive  and  sympathetic ;  it  was  readily  and  deli- 


KENAN  627 

cately  responsive  to  very  varied  kinds  of  impressions.  He  was 
quick  to  perceive  the  beauty,  to  divine  the  truth,  and  to  appre- 
ciate the  good,  presented  in  many  forms,  and  under  many  dis- 
guises and  corruptions.  Yet  this  fine  gift,  this  enviable  power, 
was  far  from  perfect.  It  partook  of  the  limits  and  defects  of 
his  nature,  which,  with  all  its  eminent  and  attractive  qualities, 
lacked  depth  and  earnestness,  was  more  aesthetic  than  moral, 
more  finely  cultured  than  seriously  religious.  He  was  a  stranger 
to  the  spiritual  experiences  without  which  great  religions,  their 
prophets  and  apostles,  and  even  their  doctrines  and  practices, 
cannot  be  understood  adequately,  and  from  within.  And  he 
did  not  so  understand  them.  Scholarly  and  ingenious,  always 
interesting  and  in  many  respects  valuable,  and  inimitably  grace- 
ful in  diction,  as  are  his  volumes  on  the  origins  of  Christianity 
and  the  History  of  Israel,  they  are  somewhat  superficial,  inas- 
much as  they  have  grown  less  out  of  realisation  of  the  inner  his- 
tory or  life-development  of  Christianity  and  of  Israel  than  out  of 
a  critical  interest  in  intricate  historical  problems  and  an  artistic 
interest  in  subjects  admirably  adapted  for  effective  delineation. 
For  Eenan  philosophy  was  simply  a  noble  style  of  thinking, 
and  religion  but  a  superior  kind  of  poetry.  Absolute  truth 
and  goodness  he  regarded  as  only  ideals,  to  be  sought  merely 
for  the  pleasure  of  seeking  them ;  and  their  appearances  he 
deemed  wholly  relative  and  ever  varying.  Hence  he  dis- 
liked decided  affirmations  and  negations,  and  delighted  in 
nuances  of  thought  and  expression  suggestive  of  the  uncer- 
tainty and  illusoriness  which  must  prevail  in  a  world  of  which 
the  universal  law  is  "  an  eternal  fieri."  He  had  temptations, 
which  less  richly  endowed  artistic  natures  are  spared,  to 
sacrifice  critical  rigour  and  historical  precision  to  beauty  of 
form,  and  to  supply  from  imagination  what  was  wanting  in 
facts  to  make  a  picture  lifelike  or  a  story  dramatic.  But  if 
sometimes  led  astray  by  the  characteristic  qualities  of  his 
genius,  he  was  also  enabled  by  them  to  render  to  the  studies 
to  which  he  devoted  himself  services  far  beyond  the  power  of 
men  of  mere  talent  and  learning  to  confer.  His  works  lack 
merits  which  those  of  Reuss,  Pressense\  and  ReVille  possess, 
but  they  have  a  greater  vitality,  originality,  and  charm,  and 
have  exercised  a  far  wider  influence.1 

1 M.  Renan's  philosophical  views  are  to  he  found  chiefly  in  his  '  Dialogues  et 


628  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   1ST  FRANCE 

Not  a  few  of  my  readers  may  think  that  Renan  should  not 
have  been  treated  of  in  the  present  chapter.  But  that  M.  Taine 
should  ha\e  a  place  in  it  no  one  will  dispute ;  for  there  can  be 
no  doubt  as  to  which  camp  he  belongs  to.  "  La  verite-,"  accord- 
ing to  M.  Renan,  "  reside  tout  entidre  dans  les  nuances."  If 
such  be  the  case,  M.  Taine  obviously  knows  nothing  about  "la 
venteV'  "  Les  nuances  "  are  not  at  all  in  his  line.  Indefinite- 
ness  and  indecision  are  faults  of  which  he  is  entirely  guiltless. 
On  the  contrary,  he  is  in  his  own  way  as  one-sided  and  dog- 
matic, as  confident  and  uncompromising,  as  were  our  Scotch 
Covenanters  of  the  seventeenth  century  in  their  Calvinistic 
and  Presbyterian  fashion.  He  is  a  thorough-going  experi- 
mentalist, starting  from  sensation,  and  explaining  all  things 
by  a  mechanically  necessitated  evolution.  While  philosoph- 
ically more  akin  to  Littre"  than  to  any  other  older  French 
thinker,  he  is  still  more  closely  related,  perhaps,  to  our  British 
empiricists  the  Mills  and  Dr.  Bain,  and  to  our  British  evolu- 
tionists Darwin  and  Spencer.  His  great  distinction  as  a  man 
of  letters,  his  vigour  as  a  thinker,  his  scientific  culture,  his  la- 
borious industry  in  historical  research,  and  the  zeal  which  he 
has  shown  for  psychological  study,  have  made  him  the  most 
eminent  representative  of  contemporary  French  experimen- 
talism.  M.  Th.  Ribot,  editor  of  the  '  Revue  Philosophique,' 
and  many  of  the  contributors  to  that  invaluable  periodical, 
honour  him  as  their  chief. 

M.  Taine  has  said  that  "  virtue  and  vice  are  to  be  regarded 
as  products,  just  like  sugar  and  vitriol;"  and  that  "man  may 
be  considered  as  an  animal  of  a  superior  species,  who  manu- 
factures poems  very  much  as  silk-worms  make  their  cocoons 
and  bees  their  hives."  These  rather  unguarded  words  have 
been  probably  more  frequently  quoted  than  any  others  which 
he  has  written ;  and  because  of  them  he  has  often  been 
represented  as   identifying  chemistry  and  morality,  and  as 

Fragments  Philosophiques '  and  'L'Avenir  de  la  Science.'  The  extraordinary 
conception  of  a  gradual  growth  and  organisation  of  God,  evolution  dUfique,  which 
he  sets  forth  in  the  former  of  these  works,  is  a  sort  of  counterpart  to  Comte's 
dogma  of  the  Virgin-Mother,  which  some  of  his  followers  regard  as  the  central 
article  of  the  Positivist  religious  creed.  Renan  has  been  to  a  considerable  extent 
his  own  biographer.  See  his  '  Souvenirs  d'Enfance  et  de  Jeunesse,'  &c.  Sir 
Mounstuart  E.  Grant  Duff  gives  a  very  appreciative  estimate  of  his  character  as 
a  man,  and  a  very  comprehensive  view  of  his  activity  as  an  author,  in  'Ernest 
Renan  —  In  Memoriam,'  1S93. 


TAINE  629 

■attempting  to  study  history  as  a  physical  or  physiological 
process.  I  shall  not  do  him  the  injustice  of  attributing  to 
him  anything  so  absurd.  He  is,  of  course,  quite  aware  that 
virtues  and  vices  cannot  be  subjected  to  the  same  tests  and 
processes  as  chemical  substances;  that  poets  are  a  very 
.superior  species  of  creature  indeed  to  silk-worms  and  bees, 
which  by  no  means  differ  so  peculiarly  from'  one  another  as 
Shakespeare  from  Be'ranger,  or  Milton  from  Alfred  de  Musset ; 
and  that  the  instruments  and  artifices  employed  by  us  in  the 
investigation  of  cocoons  or  hives  would  not  help  us  to  explain 
■or  appreciate  Spenser's  "  Fairy  Queen  "  or  Tennyson's  "  In 
Memoriam."  He  can  only  have  meant  that  moral  and  social 
facts  should  be  studied  according  to  the  same  general  method 
•as  those  of  a  physical  and  physiological  kind,  and  that  the  his- 
tory of  humanity  will  never  be  truly  described  or  elucidated 
if  the  precautions  and  rules  which  all  successful  inquirers  into 
the  history  of  nature  recognise  to  be  imperative  are  neglected  or 
violated ;  and  this  is  what  few  will  deny.  He  has  certainly  not 
shown  himself  capable,  any  more  than  have  other  inquirers,  of 
studying  psychological  phenomena  otherwise  than  psychologi- 
■cally,  i.e.,  through  consciousness  and  psychical  (not  physical) 
analysis. 

Most  of  M.  Taine's  works  are  of  a  psychologico-historical 
•character.  That  by  which  he  made  his  dibut  in  literature  — 
the  'Essai  sur  Tite  Live,'  crowned  by  the  French  Academy  in 
1855,  and  published  in  1856  — is  of  this  nature.  It  traces  "  the 
■conditions  of  light  and  liberty  "  in  which  the  mind  of  Livy 
was  developed ;  indicates  the  sources  of  his  information  and 
the  examples  which  inspired  and  guided  him ;  examines  and 
appreciates  his  work  from  three  points  of  view  —  the  critical, 
philosophical,  and  artistic  ;  and  endeavours  to  determine  and 
formulate  the  essential  character  of  his  genius.  While  Livy 
is  its  central  and  main  subject,  its  general  theme  is  history 
itself ;  and  so  it  is  divided  into  two  "  parts," — the  first  devoted 
to  "  history  considered  as  a  science,"  and  the  second  to  "  history 
considered  as  an  art."  In  dealing  with  history  as  a  science, 
M.  Taine  treats  of  historical  criticism  in  itself,  and  as  ex- 
emplified in  the  writings  of  Livy,  Beaufort,  and  Niebuhr, 
and  of  the  philosophy  of  history  in  general,  and  as  traceable 
m  the  works  of  Livy,  Machiavelli,  and  Montesquieu.    In  dis- 


630  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

coursing  of  history  as  an  art  he  has  comparatively  little  to  say  of 
historical  art  as  such,  but  his  characterisation  of  the  historical 
art  of  Livy  is  strikingly  just  and  brilliant.  In  the  conclusion 
of  the  work  he  sets  forth  an  idea  which  has  reappeared  in 
almost  all  his  subsequent  writings :  the  idea,  namely,  that 
the  character  or  genius  of  a  man,  as  also  of  a  society  or 
a  nation,  may.be  summed  up  in  a  formula,  owing  to  that 
character  or  genius  being  an  organic  unity  all  the  parts  of 
which  are  interdependent,  and  act  according  to  a  unique  law 
under  the  influence  of  a  single  dominant  principle,  unefacultS 
maitresse.  His  formula  for  Livy  is :  "His  oratorical  genius, 
accordant  with  his  character,  which  is  that  of  a  patriot  and 
a  man  of  honour,  Roman  like  his  character,  explains  all  else." 
This,  he  holds,  sums  up  Livy,  and  explains  his  work;  so 
expresses  his  nature  and  the  law  of  his  activity  that  what 
he  was  as  a  man  and  accomplished  as  an  historian  may  be 
deduced  or  construed  from  it.  M.  Taine  himself  has,  however, 
neither  deduced  nor  construed  anything  from  it.  He  has  not 
even  been  able  to  state  it  in  a  self-consistent  form,  but  in  one 
which  manifestly  implies,  if  it  does  not  explicitly  state,  that 
Livy's  oratorical  genius  presupposed,  and  was  conditioned  by, 
the  very  character  which  it  is  alleged  to  explain. 

In  1857  his  '  Philosophes  Frangais  du  xix°  Sidcle  '  appeared. 
It  showed  that  he  was  already  a  decided  ideologist,  a  lineal 
successor  of  Condillac  and  De  Tracy,  who  had  been  en- 
thusiastically studying  physical  science,  and  was  in  full 
sympathy  with  the  naturalistic  tendencies  of  the  time.  His 
criticism  of  Eclecticism  and  its  chief  representatives  was  in 
some  respects  just,  superabounded  in  force,  and  displayed  a 
characteristic  lack  of  comprehensiveness  of  vision  and  moder- 
ation of  judgment.  It  is  at  once  the  strength  and  the  weak- 
ness of  M.  Taine  that  he  must  always  study  not  simply  to 
know  but  also  to  prove  a  thesis,  and  that  he  so  concentrates 
his  mind  on  the  proof  of  his  thesis  that  he  loses  sight  of 
everything  in  his  subject  which  does  not  serve  his  purpose : 
this,  one  might  almost  say,  is  his  faculte  maitresse.  In  the 
last  two  chapters  of  the  work  he  set  forth  views  as  to  method 
which  he  has  since  somewhat  more  fully  developed.  The 
'  Essais  de  Critique  et  d'Histoire '  appeared  in  the  following 
year.     All  the  studies  contained  in  this  volume  are  able  and 


TAINE  g31 

interesting,  and  exemplify  the  method  which  their  author 
regarded  as  fitted  to  disclose  the  natural  history  of  the  soul 
in  an  individual  or  nation.  The  preface  is  a  defence  of 
the  method  against  the  criticisms  of  Sainte-Beuve,  PreVost- 
Paradol,  and  others.  It  is,  however,  in  the  introduction  to 
his  great  work,  the  '  Histoire  de  la  Litte'rature  Anglaise '  (5 
vols.,  1864),  that  we  find  the  most  explicit  and  matured 
statement  of  his  theory  of  history. 

It  is  to  the  following  effect.  In  historical  study  documents 
are  to  be  regarded  only  as  a  clue  to  the  reconstruction  of  the 
visible  or  outer  man,  and  he  only  as  a  clue  to  the  discovery 
of  the  inner  invisible  man.  The  state  and  actions  of  this 
latter  man  have  their  causes  in  certain  general  modes  of 
thought  and  feeling, — certain  characteristics  of  the  intellect 
and  the  heart  common  to  men  of  one  race,  age,  and  country. 
The  mechanism  of  human  history  is  always  the  same.  The 
mainspring  is  constantly  some  very  general  disposition  of 
mind  and  soul,  innate  and  attached  by  nature  to  the  race, 
or  acquired  and  produced  by  some  circumstance  acting  on 
the  race;  and  it.  produces  its  effects  inevitably  and  gradually, 
bringing  a  nation  into  a  succession  of  conditions,  religious, 
literary,  social,  economic,  sometimes  good,  sometimes  bad,  act- 
ing sometimes  quickly,  sometimes  slowly,  and  so  forth.  The 
whole  progress  of  each  distinct  civilisation  may  thus  be  re- 
garded as  the  effect  of  a  permanent  force,  which,  at  every 
stage,  varies  its  operation  by  modifying  the  circumstances 
of  its  action.  There  are  three  primordial  forces  which  by 
their  combination  produce  a  civilisation  and  all  its  trans- 
formations through  the  ages  by  a  succession  of  natural  and 
necessitated  impulses:  the  race,  the  medium,  and  the  moment. 
Race  includes  the  innate  and  hereditary  dispositions  which 
man  brings  with  him  into  the  world,  which  are,  as  a  rule, 
united  with  marked  differences  in  the  temperament  and 
structure  of  the  body,  and  which  vary  with  various  peoples. 
The  medium  comprises  all  physical  and  social  circumstances 
and  surroundings.  Besides  the  forces  within  and  without, 
there  is  the  work  which  they  have  already  produced  together, 
and  which  itself  contributes  to  produce  that  which  follows. 
This  work  is  the  moment,  or  epoch,  the  momentum  acquired 
at  a  given  period,  and  resulting  from  the  permanent  impulse 


632  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

and  the  medium  in  which  it  has  operated.  These  primordial 
forces  produce  a  system  of  effects  which  is  a  civilisation  in  its 
various  stages.  "  History  is  a  mechanical  problem ;  the  total 
effect  is  a  result,  depending  entirely  on  the  magnitude  and 
direction  of  the  producing  causes.  The  only  difference  which 
separates  it  from  a  purely  physical  problem  is  that  it  cannot 
be  measured  or  computed  by  the  same  means,  or  denned  in 
an  exact  or  approximative  formula.  As  in  both,  however,  the 
matter  is  the  same,  equally  made  up  of  forces,  magnitudes, 
and  directions,  we  may  say  that  in  both  the  final  result  is 
produced  after  the  same  method." 

In  history,  as  everywhere,  the  law  of  the  mutual  depend- 
ence, or  correlation  of  parts,  holds  an  important  place.  "As 
in  an  animal,  instincts,  teeth,  limbs,  bony  structure  and  mus- 
cular envelope,  are  mutually  connected,  so  that  a  change  in 
one  produces  a  corresponding  change  in  the  rest,  and  a  skilful 
naturalist  can  by  a  process  of  reasoning  reconstruct  out  of  a 
few  fragments  almost  the  whole  body;  even  so  in  a  civilisa- 
tion, religion,  philosophy,  the  organisation  of  the  family, 
literature,  the  arts,  make  up  a  system  in  which  every  local 
change  induces  a  general  change,  so  that  an  experienced  his- 
torian, studying  some  particular  portion  of  it,  sees  in  advance 
and  half  predicts  the  rest."  Hence  one  great  phase  or  fact 
of  history  thoroughly  understood  is  sufficient  to  enable  us  to 
understand  those  concomitant  with  it,  and  largely  to  antici- 
pate the  future.  The  main  work  of  the  historian  is,  accord- 
ingly, to  determine  what  moral  condition  produced  a  given 
literature,  philosophy,  society,  or  act,  and  how  the  race,  the 
medium,  and  the  moment,  produced  that  condition. 

History  is  psychology  developing  itself  in  time  and  space. 
It  may  be  best  studied  in  the  documents  which  bring  human 
sentiments  and  their  evolution  most  clearly  and  fully  to  light; 
and  these  are  just  those  which  constitute  literature.  It  is 
chiefly  by  the  study  of  literature  that  one  may  construct  a 
history  of  mind  and  gain  a  knowledge  of  the  psychological 
laws  from  which  events  spring.  "In  this  respect  a  great 
poem,  a  fine  novel,  the  confessions  of  a  man  of  genius,  are 
more  instructive  than  a  crowd  of  historians  with  their  pile  of 
histories.  I  would  give  fifty  volumes  of  charters,  and  a  hun- 
dred volumes  of  diplomatic  documents,  for  the  Memoirs  of 


TAINE  633 

Cellini,  the  Epistles  of  St.  Paul,  Luther's  Table-Talk,  or  the 
Comedies  of  Aristophanes.  .  .  .  Literature  resembles  those 
admirable  apparatuses  of  extraordinary  sensibility  by  which 
physicians  disentangle  and  measure  the  most  obscure  and 
delicate  changes  of  a  body.  Constitutions  and  religions  do  not 
approach  it  in  importance ;  the  articles  of  a  code  of  laws  and  of 
a  creed  only  show  us  the  spirit  roughly  and  without  delicacy." 
It  was  in  order  to  exhibit  the  psychology  of  the  English 
people  in  the  various  stages  through  which  it  has  passed,  and 
to  show  how,  in  accordance  with  the  theory  of  historical  devel- 
opment just  indicated,  these  stages  were  naturally  and  inevi- 
tably evolved,  how  great  political,  religious,  and  literary  works 
were  produced,  and  how  the  Saxon  barbarian  was  transformed 
into  the  Englishman  of  the  present  day,  that  M.  Taine  wrote 
his  '  History  of  English  Literature.'  By  the  way  in  which  he 
performed  the  task  he  has  rendered  both  France  and  England 
greatly  his  debtor.  There  is  no  other  history  of  the  subject 
which  displays  so  much  talent  and  the  same  combination  of 
excellences.  It  is  everywhere  characterised  by  freshness  and 
independence  of  thought,  brilliancy  and  vigour  of  style,  and 
fulness  and  accuracy  of  information.  It  is  eminently  success- 
ful in  almost  all  respects  except  one  — ■  namely,  the  proof  of 
the  theory  on  which  it  proceeds.  As  regards  that,  it  is  a 
signal  failure.  Sometimes,  indeed,  M.  Taine  is  to  be  seen 
in  it  struggling  vaguely  and  spasmodically  to  establish  the 
theory  he  had  laid  down,  and  he  is  still  oftener  to  be  heard 
proclaiming  that  he  has  succeeded ;  but  he  brings  it  to  a  close 
without  any  real  fulfilment  of  his  promise. 

For  such  assertions  as  that  all  events  are  necessitated,  that 
history  is  simply  a  mechanical  problem,  and  that  freewill  is  an 
illusion,  he  produces  no  evidence.  These  assertions,  although 
the  very  foundations  of  his  theory,  are  allowed  to  remain  to  the 
end  of  his  work  the  mere  assumptions  which  they  were  at  its 
commencement.  They  are  metaphysical  dogmas  only  capable 
of  being  proved,  if  provable  at  all,  by  metaphysical  reasonings ; 
certainly  not  by  historical  research.  M.  Taine  seems  to  think 
their  truth  so  manifest  that  to  attempt  any  kind  of  proof  of 
them,  or  even  to  answer  the  most  obvious  objections  to  them, 
is  unnecessary. 

He  has  equally  failed  to  make  out  that  either  the  individual 


634  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

or  the  collective  mind  is  like  a  machine  or  an  organism  ruled  by 
a  central  and  dominant  force  from  which  all  the  other  forces  may- 
be inferred,  and  by  which  its  whole  activity  may  be  explained ; 
and  that,  accordingly,  the  entire  character  and  work  of  a  man 
or  a  nation  may  be  summed  up  in  a  formula  which  indicates 
the  chief  motive,  principle,  or  distinctive  quality  of  that  man  or 
nation.  There  is  no  machine  or  organism  of  the  kind.  Even 
a  timepiece  is  not  explicable  merely  by  its  mainspring.  To 
affirm  that  "  man  is  a  walking  formula  "  may  be  tolerable  as 
a  joke,  but  it  is  execrable  as  a  definition,  and  ludicrous  as  a 
philosophical  thesis.  M.  Taine  would  improve  his  admirable 
study  on  Shakespeare  were  he  to  leave  out  the  meaningless 
paragraph  in  which  he  pretends  to  resolve  "  the  whole  genius  " 
of  the  great  dramatist  into  "  a  complete  imagination."  All 
paragraphs  of  the  same  kind  in  his  work,  —  e.g.,  those  refer- 
ring to  the  spring-  (ressort)  Milton,  the  spring-Macaulay,  the 
spring-Dickens,  the  spring-Carlyle,  &c,  are  equally  worthless. 
Fortunately  they  are  far  fewer  than  his  theory  logically  re- 
quires, easily  separable  from  the  rest  of  the  book,  and  too  mani- 
festly futile  to  mislead  an  intelligent  reader.  So  far  as  I  know, 
they  have  not  misled  —  that  is,  convinced  —  a  single  mortal. 
The  three  causes  which,  according  to  M.  Taine,  originate 
history  and  determine  its  form  and  development  are  unques- 
tionably real  and  influential  historical  factors ;  yet  they  are 
not  so  powerful  as  he  represents  them  to  be.  They  are  not 
the  only  causes  which  act  on  history,  and  they  are  improperly 
asserted  to  be  "  primordial."  Behind  and  beneath  the  acquired 
peculiarities  of  the  race  are  the  essential  and  universal  qualities 
of  the  man.  This  man,  to  whom  M.  Taine's  theory  does  such 
scant  justice,  yet  to  whom  belongs  the  reason,  will,  conscience, 
and  feelings  common  to  all  races,  is  the  prime  and  main  agent 
in  history,  and  its  sole  subject.  How  he  was  differentiated 
into  races  is  itself  a  difficult  historical  problem.  The  medium, 
in  so  far  as  it  is  social,  is  wholly  of  human  formation,  and 
largely  so  even  as  physical,  wherever  man  is  an  active  histori- 
cal agent.  The  moment  is  only  another  name  for  history  itself 
at  a  given  time ;  and  cannot  cause  or  account  for  itself.  Race, 
medium,  and  moment,  therefore,  far  from  being  the  primordial 
sources  of  historical  explanation,  need  to  be  either  wholly  or 
largely  historically  explained. 


TAINE  635 

Further,  M.  Taine  should  not  merely  have  insisted  that  each 
people  is  an  organism,  and  the  history  of  each  people  an  organic 
development ;  he  should  also  have  sufficiently  explained  what 
that  meant.  It  is  easier  to  understand  what  a  society  or  nation 
is,  than  to  recognise  how  it  is  an  organism ;  and  what  history  is, 
than  wherein  its  organic  development  consists.  In  order  not 
to  be  chargeable  with  explaining  the  ignotum  by  the  ignotius, 
our  author,  instead  of  being  content  merely  to  carry  the  terras 
and  notions  of  "  organism  "  and  "  organic  development "  from 
biology  over  into  sociology,  from  natural  history  over  into 
human  history,  should  have  also  shown  what  changes  in  signi- 
fication they  underwent  in  the  transference.  He  has  made  no 
serious  attempt  of  the  kind ;  and  that  obviously  because  he 
has  not  clearly  seen  how  great  are  the  differences  between 
individual  and  social  organisms  —  between  wholes  in  which 
each  part  is  merely  a  part,  and  wholes  in  which  each  part  is 
a  free  and  rational  individual.  While  there  are  relations  be- 
tween the  civilisation,  religion,  philosophy,  and  literature,  &c, 
of  a  nation,  just  as  there  are  between  the  various  organs 
and  members  of  an  animal,  they  are  relations  of  a  very  differ- 
ent kind,  and  change  in  a  very  different  manner.  Prevision  is 
consequently  much  more  difficult  in  the  case  of  the  historian 
than  of  the  naturalist.  It  has  to  be  observed,  also,  that  hu- 
manity, if  an  organism,  is  most  unlike  other  organisms,  in  that 
it  is  single  and  unique,  whereas  they  are  multiple  and  reducible 
to  classes.  Its  history  is  a  whole  of  which  all  particular  his- 
tories are  merely  sections,  or  stages,  or  phases. 

M.  Taine's  'History  of  English  Literature '  is  in  the  main  of 
a  truly  psychological  nature ;  it  exhibits  the  operation  not  of 
his  so-called  primordial  forces  but  of  the  actual  proximate 
mental  causes.  To  this  happy  inconsistency  it  owes  much  of 
its  value.  Unquestionably  it  is  an  important  contribution 
to  comparative  psychology.  Yet  not  more  so  than  Renan's 
'  History  of  the  Semitic  Languages.'  Literature  regarded  as 
a  source  of  comparative  psychology  is  by  no  means  so  superior 
to  language  or  religion  as  M.  Taine  supposes.  Literature, 
indeed,  is  the  fullest  revelation  of  the  minds  of  certain  men ; 
but  it  is  not  as  direct  a  revelation  as  language  or  history  of 
collective  mind,  the  mind  of  races  and  nations.  No  History 
of  English  Literature  can  be  an  exhibition  of  the  mind  of  the 


636  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOBY   IN   PKANOE 

English  people,  or  of  more  than  the  minds  of  English  men 
of  letters.  To  attribute  to  the  English  mind  any  quality  of 
the  genius  of  Shakespeare  or  Byron  is  a  fallacious  procedure,, 
if  it  have  no  other  warrant  than  a  study  of  the  works  of  these 
authors.  From  overlooking  this  fact  M.  Taine,  notwithstand- 
ing his  wide  and  minute  knowledge  of  England  as  well  as  of 
France,  has  represented  many  peculiarities  of  no  great  gen- 
erality as  traits  which  differentiate  English  from  French 
thought  and  character.  Comparative  Psychology  must  seek 
its  data  primarily  in  language,  general  beliefs,  common  cus- 
toms, &c. 

Between  the  years  1865  and  1869  M.  Taine  was  actively 
occupied  in  attempting  to  apply  his  naturalistic  principles 
and  historical  theory  to  the  elucidation  of  the  nature  and 
development  of  Art. 1 

In  1870  appeared  his  subtle  and  influential  treatise,  '  De 
l'lntelligence.'  In  the  preface  he  thus  points  out  its  relation 
to  the  works  to  which  we  have  just  been  referring :  "  History 
is  applied  psychology,  psychology  applied  to  more  com- 
plex cases.  The  historian  notes  and  traces  the  total  trans- 
formations presented  by  a  particular  human  molecule  or  group 
of  human  molecules  ;  and  to  explain  these  transformations, 
writes  the  psychology  of  the  molecule  or  group ;  Carlyle  has 
written  that  of  Cromwell ;  Sainte-Beuve  that  of  Port  Royal ; 
Stendhal  has  made  twenty  attempts  on  that  of  the  Italians ; 
M.  Renan  has  given  us  that  of  the  Semitic  race.  Every 
perspicacious  and  philosophical  historian  labours  at  that  of  a; 
man,  an  epoch,  a  people,  or  a  race  ;  the  researches  of  linguists, 
mythologists,  and  ethnographers  have  no  other  aim ;  the  task 
is  invariably  the  description  of  a  human  mind,  or  of  the  char- 
acteristics common  to  a  group  of  human  minds  ;  and  what 
historians  do  with  respect  to  the  past,  the  great  novelists  and 
dramatists  do  with  the  present.  For  fifteen  years  I  have  con- 
tributed to  these  special  and  concrete  psychologies ;  I  now 
attempt  general  and  abstract  psychology."  He  concludes  the 
treatise  thus  :  "  The  reader  has  seen  how  cognitions  are  formed, 
and  by  what  adjustments  they  correspond  to  things.  They 
have,  as  materials,  sensations  of  various  kinds,  some  primitive 

1 '  Philosophie  de  l'Art,'  '  Philosophie  de  l'Art  en  Italie,'  '  Philosophic  de  l'Art 
dans  les  Pays-Bas,'  &c. 


TAINB  637 

and  excited,  others  spontaneous  and  reviving,  attached  to  one 
another,  counterbalanced  by  one  another,  purposely  organised 
by  their  connections  and  their  antagonism,  composed  of  ele- 
mentary sensations  smaller  than  themselves,  these  again  of  still 
smaller  ones,  and  so  on,  till  their  differences  are  finally  effaced 
and  permit  us  to  divine  the  existence  of  wholly  similar  infini- 
tesimal elements  whose  various  arrangements  explain  their 
various  aspects.  Thus  in  a  cathedral,  the  ultimate  elements 
are  grains  of  sand  agglutinated  into  stones  of  various  forms, 
which,  attached  in  pairs,  form  masses,  whose  thrusts  oppose  and 
balance  each  other ;  all  these  associations  and  all  these  pres- 
sures being  co-ordinated  in  one  grand  harmony.  Such  is  the 
simplicity  of  the  means,  and  such  the  complication  of  the  effect, 
and  both  the  simplicity  and  the  complication  are  as  admirable 
in  the  mental  as  in  the  real  edifice."  No  words  could  be 
better  fitted  to  suggest  the  radical  and  pervading  defect  of  the 
treatise.  The  analysis  by  which  M.  Taine  reduces  intelli- 
gence entirely  into  infinitesimal  elementary  sensations  is  pre- 
cisely of  the  same  illegitimate  and  illusory  nature  as  that 
which  would  resolve  a  cathedral  into  the  grains  of  sand  of 
which  its  stones  are  composed.  The  latter  analysis,  in  order 
to  arrive  at  its  ridiculous  result,  must  leave  out  of  account  the 
intelligence  and  skill  to  which  the  simplicity  and  complica- 
tion, the  proportion  and  harmony,  of  the  cathedral  are  directly 
due ;  the  former  similarly  leaves  out  of  account  the  presence, 
laws,  and  conditions  of  the  mental  activity  which  makes  of 
sensational  elements  conscious  states  and  works  them  up  into 
intellectual  edifices.  In  both  forms  alike,  the  analysis,  instead 
of  really  and  honestly  explaining  the  phenomenon  to  which 
it  is  applied,  overlooks  or  attempts  to  explain  away  what 
is  absolutely  essential  to  the  existence  and  intelligibility  of 
the  phenomenon. 

M.  Taine's  greatest  work,  'Les  Origines  de  la  France  Con- 
temporaine,'  began  to  appear  in  1875,  and  four  volumes  have 
since  been  published.  It  bears  no  traces  of  that  historical 
theory  to  which  our  attention  in  treating  of  M.  Taine  has  of 
necessity  been  chiefly  directed.  It  disclaims  party  preposses- 
sions, and  even  political  principles.  Of  the  latter  the  author 
says  that  he  has  tried  to  find  them,  but  as  yet  has  discovered 
only  one,— namely,  "that  human  society,  and  especially  modern 


638  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  IN   FKA2TOE 

society,  is  vast  and  complicated  —  difficult  to  know  and  to 
understand,  but  more  easily  known  and  understoood  by  the 
cultivated  than  by  the  uncultivated  mind,  and  by  him  who  has 
studied  it  than  by  him  who  has  not."  The  volume  on  the 
'  Ancien  Regime '  gave  great  offence  to  Conservatives  by  its 
trenchant  and  thorough  criticism  of  the  old  monarchy.  The 
three  volumes  on  the  Revolution  excited  the  wrath  of  demo- 
crats by  their  full  exhibition  of  those  facts  which  Thiers  over- 
looked, which  Louis  Blanc  slurred  over,  and  which  Michelet 
refused  to  contemplate,  but  a  clear  recognition  of  which  is  in- 
dispensable as  a  protection  against  lying  legends  which  have 
done  incalculable  mischief  to  France.  The  volume  which  treats 
of  Napoleon  displeased  imperialists  by  its  searching  analysis 
of  the  character  of  the  Emperor.  Hence  numerous  have  been 
the  complaints  of  one-sidedness  brought  against  the  work,  and 
copious  the  talk  of  critics  about  its  lack  of  lofty  impartiality 
and  sobriety  of  judgment.  A  certain  kind  of  one-sidedness  in 
it  I  fully  admit  that  there  is ;  but  I  consider  that  it  is  of  a  kind 
which  is  here  scarcely  a  fault.  What  right  had  the  critics  of 
M.  Taine  to  expect  from  him  a  complete  history  ?  None.  They 
had  a  right  only  to  expect  a  history  true  so  far  as  it  goes;  one 
in  which  what  are  stated  as  facts  are  true  and  important  facts; 
and  that  they  have  got.  The  work  of  M.  Taine  may  be,  perhaps, 
in  the  strictest  sense,  not  a  historj^  at  all,  but  rather  a  study 
on  history,  a  series  of  demonstrations  of  historical  and  psycho- 
logical theses;  but  it  will  be  none  the  less  entitled  to  be  regarded 
as  one  of  the  most  important  historical  treatises  produced  in  the 
present  age :  a  treatise  admirable  for  its  fearless  honesty,  for  its 
extensive  original  research,  and  for  the  psychological  penetra- 
tion and  the  power  of  delineation  which  it  displays.  Any 
history  of  the  period  of  which  it  treats  which  would  not  give 
serious  offence  to  political  parties  in  France,  would  require  to 
be  written  from  a  stand-point  of  impartiality  so  lofty  that  all 
clear  vision  from  it  would  be  impossible,  and  with  a  sobriety 
of  judgment  closely  approximating  to  total  abstention  from 
judgment.1 

1  The  foregoing  pages  on  M.  Taine's  historical  philosophy  were  written  prior  to 
his  death.  I  have  left  them,  however,  unaltered,  in  the  belief  that  their  contro- 
versial character  will  not  to  any  great  extent  conceal  my  sincere  admiration  of 


TAINE  639 

the  illustrious  man  whose  death  is  so  vast  a  loss  to  France  and  to  European 
literature.  For  general  estimates  of  his  character  I  may  refer  to  the  articles  of 
.St.  Faguet  in  the  '  Eevue  Bleue'  of  March  11,  of  M.  Lolie'e  in  the  'Nouvelle 
Kevue '  of  March  15,  and  (especially)  of  M.  Gabriel  Monod  in  the  '  Contemporary 
Review'  for  April. 

The  following  authors  have  theorised  on  history  in  accordance  with  naturalist 
or  positivist  principles :  — 

1.  Eugene  Veron.  —  He  is  a  well-known  publicist,  who  has  written  a  number  of 
able  works,  and  is  the  chief  editor  of  the  journal  'L'Art.'  His  'Progres  Intel- 
lectual dans  l'humanite:  Superiorite'  des  arts  modernes  sur  les  arts  anciens' 
(1862),  is  of  most  interest  for  the  historical  philosopher.  The  alternative  title 
indicates  what  is  its  chief  theme;  but  a  philosophical  view  of  the  history  of 
humanity  is  also  presented.  That  history  is  supposed  to  have  commenced  with 
the  lowest  stage  of  savagery ;  to  be  divisible  into  two  great  periods  —  the  first  the 
period  of  objectivity,  and  the  second  the  period  of  subjectivity;  and  to  be  indefi- 
nitely or  infinitely  progressive.  On  this  very  slender  thread  M.  Veron  has  con- 
trived to  hang  a  wonderful  amount  of  ingenious,  and  even  of  true  thought.  In 
regard  to  Art  and  its  history  he  is  especially  informative  and  suggestive.  His 
later  writings  '  L'Esthetique,'  '  La  Mythologie  dans  l'Art,'  '  Histoire  naturelle  des 
Religions,'  and  '  La  Morale,'  are  also  largely  historical ;  and  necessarily  so,  seeing 
that,  like  Comte,  he  despises  introspection  and  psychological  analysis.  Of  course, 
he  has  often  recourse  to  them,  although  unconsciously  and  inconsistently. 

2.  Paul  Mougeolle.  — His  '  Statique  des  Civilisations '  is  an  elaborate  attempt 
to  prove  that  civilisation  has  developed  from  the  equator  towards  the  poles.  This 
thesis  I  have  already  had  to  refer  to  in  treating  of  Charles  Comte.  '  Les  Pro- 
blemes  de  l'Histoire'  (1886)  of  M.  Mougeolle  is  a  pleasant  book  to  read,  being 
written  in  a  light  and  lively  style ;  contains  a  great  many  interesting  ideas  and 
facts,  suggestions  and  criticisms ;  and  is  comprehensively  planned,  and,  externally 
at  least,  well  arranged.  It  is  divided  into  four  parts.  The  First  Part  treats  of 
"  the  Facts,  or  the  matter  of  the  Drama,"  and  is  composed  of  three  books,  which 
treat  respectively  of  the  facts  in  relation  to  one  another,  in  relation  to  time,  and 
in  relation  to  space.  As  regards  their  relations  to  one  another,  he  dwells  on  the 
proportionality,  equivalence,  and  constancy  of  these  relations.  As  regards  their 
relations  to  time,  he  assails  the  theory  of  the  fall  or  decadence,  and  the  theory  of 
cycles,  and  argues  in  favour  of  the  theory  of  progress.  And  as  regards  their 
relations  to  space,  he  seeks  to  establish  (unsuccessfully,  I  think,)  what  he  calls  the 
law  of  altitudes  not  the  law  of  latitudes  —  meaning  thereby  that  the  earliest  cities 
were  built  on  hill-tops  and  that  the  plains  were  only  built  on  comparatively  late, 
and  that  civilisation  has  spread  from  the  equator  towards  the  poles.  The  so- 
called  law  of  longitudes,  which  affirms  that  civilisation  has  moved  from  east  to 
west,  he  maintains,  and,  in  my  opinion,  on  much  stronger  grounds,  to  be  a  false 
generalisation.  The  Second  Part  treats  of  "Men,  or  the  actors  of  the  Drama," 
and  is  divided  into  three  books,  which  have  for  their  several  subjects  Individuals, 
Societies,  and  Races.  Kings  and  political  leaders,  founders  of  religion  and  their 
apostles,  poets,  philosophers,  scientists,  and  inventors,  are  represented  as  having 
had  far  less  influence  on  history  than  is  supposed.  The  biographical  method 
which  has  hitherto  prevailed  in  the  writing  of  history  is  strongly  condemned ;  and 
it  is  maintained  that  it  must  give  place  to  the  democratic  method,  which  sees  in 
history  the  work  not  of  a  few  great  individualities  but  of  the  innumerable  multi- 
tude of  individuals  which  have  made  up  the  successive  generations  of  mankind. 
The  refutation  of  the  theory  which  explains  history  by  the  action  of  races  is,  per- 
haps, the  most  satisfactory  portion  of  M.  Mougeolle's  work.  The  Third  Part 
expounds  his  own  theory.  It  treats  of  "  the  Medium,  or  the  author  of  the  Drama." 
"The  medium,"  we  are  told,  "makes  men."    The  stable  elements  and  the  shift- 


640  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOBY   IN   FRANCE 

ing  scenes  which  surround  humanity  compose  and  evolve  the  drama  of  history, 
and  even  create  and  train  the  actors  in  it;  such  is  the  hypothesis  which  alone 
finds  favour  in  M.  Mougeolle's  eyes.  The  Fourth  Part  is  on  "  Historians,  or  the 
critics  of  the  Drama."  These  are  distributed  into  three  schools,  —  the  German, 
British,  and  French,  —  on  grounds  which  are  very  worthy  of  consideration, 
although  they  may  be,  perhaps,  not  quite  conclusive.  M.  Mougeolle  touches  on  a 
great  many  of  the  problems  of  history  in  an  exceptionally  interesting  way,  but  too 
lightly  to  reach,  except  rarely,  sound  solutions  of  them.  The  chief  defects  of  his 
work,  I  must  add,  are  clearly  indicated  in  the  "Preface"  to  it,  written  by  M. 
Yves  Guyot.  It  might  be  of  great  public  advantage  if  authors  generally  were  to 
get  their  works  prefaced  by  such  perfectly  candid  friends. 

3.  Louis  Bourdeau.  —  He  is  the  author  of  one  very  remarkable  and  important 
book,  which  I  have  had  special  occasion  to  study  in  another  connection.  I  refer 
to  his  '  Theorie  des  Sciences '  (2  vols.  1882),  an  elaborate  attempt  to  improve  and 
advance  the  work  of  Comte,  in  the  spirit  of  Comte,  and  to  expound  an  "  integral " 
or  universal  science  into  which  shall  enter  no  metaphysical  or  theological  concep- 
tion. In  his  '  Histoire  des  Arts  Utiles '  he  has  made  a  valuable  contribution  to 
the  history  of  industry.  But  his  '  L'Histoire  et  les  Historiens '  (1888)  is,  on  the 
whole,  disappointing.  M.  Bourdeau  considers  that  of  true  history  there  is  as  yet 
almost  none,  and  that  the  foundations  of  a  science  of  history  have  still  to  be  laid. 
He  begins  his  treatise  by  attempting  to  define  history,  with  the  result  which  I 
have  already  noticed  on  page  11.  He  then  discourses  on  "  the  agents  "  and  "  the 
facts  "  of  history ;  and  strongly  complains  that  historians  have  attended  exclu- 
sively to  celebrated  personages  and  to  striking  or  singular  events,  not  seeing  that, 
in  reality,  the  human  race  is  only  to  be  known  aright  by  studying  it  in  its  average 
condition,  and  in  its  general,  regular,  or  functional  facts.  He  devotes  only  six 
pages  to  "the  methodical  analysis"  or  "rational  distribution"  of  history,  and 
more  than  two  hundred  to  an  attack  on  "  the  narrative  method."  He  would  have 
been  well  advised,  I  think,  if  he  had  done  just  the  reverse.  Thierry,  Buckle,  and 
others  have  sufficiently  entertained  us  with  accounts  of  the  blunders  and  defects 
of  the  older  historians.  And  if  M.  Bourdeau's  collection  of  instances  of  error  and 
of  prejudice  on  their  part  had  been  even  a  hundredfold  more  copious  than  it  is, 
it  would  not  have  justified  the  historical  scepticism  ■  into  which  he  falls  —  a 
scepticism  almost  as  extreme  and  irrational  as  that  of  Father  Hardouin. 
Strange  to  say,  none  of  his  instances  are  drawn  from  the  pages  of  modern 
historians  imbued  with  the  critical  spirit,  although  it  is  surely  manifest  that 
before  condemning  the  historical  method  hitherto  exclusively  employed  as  alto- 
gether untrustworthy  and  useless,  it  was  its  latest  and  most  accredited  practition- 
ers whom  he  was  especially  bound  to  expose  and  discredit.  To  the  narrative 
method  he  would  substitute  a  mathemetical  or  numerical  method,  the  statistical 
method.  It  is  only  by  this  method  —  by  measurement,  enumeration,  and  calcula- 
tion—  that,  in  his  opinion,  true  history  can  be  obtained,  and  a  positive  science  of 
history  established.  He  eulogises  the  method,  and  explains  how  he  would  apply 
it,  but  he  shows  no  perception  of  the  proper  limits  of  its  applicability.  He 
does  not  seem  to  have  studied  its  history,  logic,  or  relationships ;  to  know  any- 
thing of  the  researches  and  discussions  of  a  Guerry,  Dufau.  Guillard,  Legoyt, 
or  Leplay,  of  an  Engel,  Wappaus,  Wagner,  Drobisch,  von  Oettingen,  &c.  He 
treats,  in  conclusion,  of  the  laws  of  history:  first,  of  its  special  laws,  which  are 
either  laws  of  order  or  of  relation ;  next,  of  its  general  law,  the  law  of  progress ; 
and  then,  of  the  demonstration  of  the  laws.  The  law  of  progress  he  represents 
as  a  necessary  law,  and  as  of  a  mathematical  nature  like  other  laws ;  the  theory 
of  progress  as  still  an  hypothesis,  like  Newton's  theory  cif  attraction ;  and  the 
formula  of  progress  as  one  analogous  to  that  of  gravitation. 


CHAPTER   XI 

HISTORICAL  PHILOSOPHY  OF  THE  CRITICAL  SCHOOL 


Positive  philosophy,  in  the  acceptation  of  the  positivists, 
is  a  legitimate  stage  or  form  of  philosophy.  All  the  various 
special  sciences  aim  merely  at  the  extension  of  knowledge  of 
a  particular  kind,  at  the  acquisition  of  truth  in  regard  to  cer- 
tain specific  objects.  Each  of  them  is  confined  within  a  sphere 
of  its  own,  and  has  its  own  class  of  specialists.  And  yet  not 
one  of  them  is  entirely  independent  and  self-sufficient.  They 
have  all  a  community  of  nature,  and  are  in  various  ways 
related.  There  are  precedence  and  subordination,  order  and 
harmony,  among  them,  so  that  many  and  diverse  as  they  are 
they  imply  a  whole  not  less  than  do  the  objects  of  which  they 
severally  treat,  a  system  in  which  each  of  them  should  find 
its  appropriate  place.  But  this  whole  or  system  when  discov- 
ered by  a  scientific  investigation  of  the  limits,  methods,  affini- 
ties, and  inter-relations  of  the  sciences,  will  be  itself  a  science 
equally  with  the  sciences  which  it  presupposes,  and  of  which 
it  is  the  theory  or  doctrine.  It  will  be  of  the  same 'nature  as 
they  are,  and  differ  from  them  only  as  general  from  special 
science,  or  as  an  organism  from  its  members.  There  is  mani- 
festly not  only  room  but  need  for  such  a  science,  even  if  it  be 
nothing  more  than  such  a  doctrine  of  the  sciences  as  affords 
a  synthesis  and  organisation  of  them.  And  such  a  science  or 
doctrine  is  what  the  positivists  call  positive  philosophy. 
Their  philosophy  is  a  science  of  the  sciences  which  is  a  nec- 
essary complement  of  special  science,  and  yet  of  the  same 
nature,  at  least  in  their  view.  It  assumes  the  special  sciences, 
and  builds  itself  up  on  what  these  sciences  teach. 

Now  this  is  well  so  far  as  it  goes,  but  it  does  not  go  far 
enough.     It  is  unsatisfactory,  not  because  it  is  false,  but  inas- 

641 


642  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PKANCE 

much  as  it  is  superficial  and  inadequate.  Positive  philosophy, 
understood  as  indicated,  in  basing  itself  on  the  special  sciences 
assumes  their  assumptions.  It  assumes  that  we  know  what 
knowledge  and  science,  certainty  and  probability,  are;  that 
truth  of  various  kinds  is  within  the  reach  of  the  human  mind ; 
that  it  is  to  be  sought  by  certain  methods ;  and  that  there  are 
fundamental  ideas  and  fixed  laws  of  thought  on  which  we  can 
rely  in  our  investigations.  All  the  special  sciences  make  these 
assumptions,  and  must,  if  they  are  unsound,  fall  to  the  ground, 
and  bring  down  the  positive  philosophy  of  which  these  sciences 
are  at  once  the  sole  supports  and  the  sole  objects.  Neither  such 
science  nor  such  philosophy  is  thorough,  or  capable  of  satisfy- 
ing a  completely  rational  being.  A  fully  awakened  mind  is  one 
awakened  from  the  dogmatic  slumber  which  accepts  assump- 
tions without  examination :  assumptions  which  may  be  denied 
not  less  than  affirmed,  and  of  which  the  affirmation  and  the  de- 
nial alike  require  justification.  "  Scientific  thought,"  to  use 
here  words  which  I  have  elsewhere  employed,  "  is  not  neces- 
sarily self-criticising  thought ;  on  the  contrary,  mere  scientific 
thought,  however  rigid  and  methodical,  is  essentially  dogmatic 
thought.  It  is  not  dogmatism,  but  it  is  dogma.  It  is  reasoned, 
yet  unreflective.  It  builds  up  what  is  admitted  to  be  knowledge, 
but  it  does  not  inquire  what  so-called  knowledge  is  or  is  essen- 
tially worth.  Positive  philosophy  is  such  thought  at  its  highest 
perfection,  or  in  its  purest  and  most  comprehensive  form,  but 
it  has  all  the  essential  defects  of  such  thought.  It  is  merely 
an  advance  on  special  science,  as  special  science  itself  is  on 
ordinary  knowledge,  and  ordinary  knowledge  on  crude  sensa- 
tion. Along  the  whole  line  the  mind  never  changes  its  attitude 
towards  its  objects ;  at  the  end  this  is  just  what  it  was  at  the 
beginning.  The  scientist  often  fancies  that  he  is  a  man  who 
takes  nothing  on  trust;  in  reality,  he  takes  everything  on  trust, 
because  he  accepts  without  question  or  reservation  thought  it- 
self as  naturally  truthful  and  its  laws  as  valid.  Whatever  a 
multitude  of  superficial  scientists  may  suppose  to  the  contrary, 
the  fact  is  that  the  entire  procedure  of  science,  and  of  philos- 
ophy in  so  far  as  it  is  simply  a  generalisation  of  science,  is  as- 
sumptive and  dogmatic.  At  bottom,  science,  which  is  so  often 
contrasted  with  and  opposed  to  faith,  is  mere  faith,  implicit 


HISTORICAL   PHILOSOPHY   OF   THE   CRITICAL   SCHOOL      643 

faith,  and  in  the  view  of  a  serious  and  consistent  scepticism 
must  be  blind  faith.  Thought  may  assume,  however,  and  is 
bound  to  assume,  a  very  different  attitude  towards  itself  and 
towards  its  objects.  It  may  pass,  and  ought  to  pass,  from  a 
believing  to  an  inquiring,  from  a  dogmatic  to  a  critical  stage. 
It  may  turn,  and  ought  to  turn,  its  attention  and  force  from  a 
study  of  the  relations  of  the  known  to  an  examination  of  the 
conditions  and  guarantees  of  knowledge."1 

The  need  for  a  critical  philosophy  was  made  apparent  by  the 
destructive  work  of  Hume.  Reid  and  his  followers  saw  what 
was  wanted,  but  only  imperfectly  supplied  it.  Kant  gave  the 
first  general  yet  profound  exposition  of  philosophy  as  a  criti- 
cism of  knowledge.  The  French  critical  school  consists  of 
thinkers  who  have  deeply  felt  the  influence  of  Kant,  and  who 
for  the  most  part  accept  his  principles  even  when  they  reject 
his  conclusions.  In  the  view  of  its  representatives  the  inquiry 
neglected  by  the  positivists,  the  inquiry  into  the  conditions  of 
experience  and  the  assumptions  of  the  sciences,  is  of  primary 
importance.  They  recognise  the  absurdity  of  a  man  excluding 
metaphysics  and  theology  from  the  sphere  of  knowledge,  and 
including  physics  and  sociology  within  it,  although  he  has 
never  taken  the  trouble  to  ask  what  knowledge  is,  whether  it 
is  attainable  at  all  or  not,  and  if  attainable  what  its  criteria 
and  limits  are.  And,  as  a  consequence  of  thus  differing  from 
the  positivists,  they  aim  likewise  at  being  more  severely 
scientific ;  are  much  more  exacting  and  difficult  to  satisfy  in 
regard  to  proof ;  and  have  a  keener  sense  of  the  uncertainty 
latent  in  general  theories  and  complex  inquiries,  and  less  re- 
spect for  the  mere  name  of  science  and  for  much  of  what  passes 
as  science.  They  are  not  so  positive  as  the  positivists  in  the 
sense  of  being  prone  to  make  either  decided  affirmations  or 
negations.  They  are  well  aware  that  for  such  intellects  as  the 
human  the  domain  of  probability  is  far  more  extensive  than 
that  of  certainty,  and  are  perhaps  even  apt  to  suppose  that 
rational  certainties  are  fewer  than  they  are.  The  positivist 
is  a  dogmatist  even  when  he  calls  himself  an  agnostic.  The 
criticist  is  not  as  such  a  sceptic,  but  he  is  more  likely  to  fall 
into  scepticism  than  into  dogmatism.     The  criticist  often  holds 

1  Presbyterian  Review,  July  1885,  p.  2. 


\\ 


644  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   PBAKCE 

phenomenalism  and  relativism  as  narrowly  and  exclusively  as 
the  positivist,  but  he  has  always  more  reason  for  holding  them, 
and  a  clearer  conception  of  what  he  means  by  them. 

The  criticist  mode  of  thought  has  found  in  France  its  two 
most  typical  representatives  in  the  late  M.  Cournot  and  M. 
Renouvier.  Both  have  occupied  themselves  with  historical 
philosophy.  They  have  written  in  entire  independence  of 
each  other.  While  both  may  be  regarded  as  in  a  general  way 
disciples  of  Kant,  neither  has  sacrificed  to  Kant,  or  any  other 
thinker,  his  own  rights  of  private  judgment. 

M.  Augustin  Cournot  (1801-77)  had  a  remarkable  capacity 
both  for  speculative  thought  and  scientific  research.  He  filled 
difficult  and  important  educational  positions.  He  wrote  valued 
works  on  the  higher  branches  of  mathematics.  The  treatises 
in  which  he  attempted  to  apply  mathematics  to  economics 
have  been  allowed  by  competent  judges  to  be  among  the  most 
ingenious  and  successful  of  their  kind.  He  expounded  his 
philosophical  opinions  in  the  '  Essai  sur  les  fondements  de  nos 
connaissances,'  2  vols.,  1851 ;  the  'Traite-  de  l'enchainement  des 
idees  fondamentales  dans  les  sciences  et  dans  l'histoire,'  2  vols., 
1861 ;  and  '  Considerations  sur  la  marche  des  ide"es  et  des 
eVenements  dans  les  temps  modernes,'  2  vols.,  1872.  These 
are  all  most  instructive  and  suggestive  books,  such  as  could 
only  be  produced  by  a  mind  of  rare  intellectual  sincerity, 
thoroughly  disciplined  in  exact  science  and  in  the  practice  of 
analysis,  and  with  a  grasp  of  facts  at  once  capacious  and  firm : 
books  not  written  with  a  view  to  being  easily  read,  and  to  please, 
impress,  or  astonish ;  not  written  for  a  vulgar  and  thoughtless 
public,  but  for  the  only  public  worthy  of  them,  one  which 
earnestly  seeks  truth  precisely  as  it  is,  truth  in  its  purity, 
naked,  un  exaggerated,  and  unadorned.  The  last  mentioned 
of  them  is  of  most  interest  for  the  philosophical  historian. 

Cournot's  conception  of  philosophy  is  peculiar.  He  does 
not  admit  it  to  be  a  science,  inasmuch  as  he  holds  it  neither 
to  have  a  definite  object  nor  to  be  capable  of  furnishing 
demonstrative  proof  or  certainty.  To  represent  it  as  being, 
or  capable  of  being,  science  can  only  tend,  in  his  opinion,  to 
spread  and  confirm  the  pernicious  impression  that  it  is  nothing 


COURNOT  645 

Teal  at  all,  but  merely  a  pretentious  illusion.  It  has  no  par- 
ticular object,  for  whatever  objects  there  may  be  they  are  the 
proper  subjects  of  particular  sciences,  mathematical,  physical, 
biological,  noological,  or  political.  Nor  does  it  deal,  as  Comte 
taught,  with  the  whole  of  the  generalities  of  the  sciences,  the 
sum  of  certainties  established  by  the  sciences :  these  generali- 
ties and  certainties  must  always  belong  to  the  sciences  which 
prove  them.  Philosophy  is  an  indispensable  element  of  all  ( 
the  sciences,  a  spirit  which  inspires  and  vivifies  them.  Its 
conclusions  are  not  certainties.  Every  philosophy,  so  far  as 
it  embodies  itself  in  doctrines,  is  only  a  whole  of  more  or  less 
probable  views  relative  to  the  order  and  the  reason  of  things. 
€ournot's  conception  of  philosophy  is  thus  entirely  different 
from  Auguste  Comte's.  The  latter  would  have  all  problems 
which  do  not  admit  of  a  positive  solution  wiped  out ;  all  ques- 
tions which  cannot  be  definitely  settled  by  experience  and 
scientific  proof  denied  the  right  of  being  put.  He  was  by 
nature  and  on  system  intolerant  of  doubts,  questionings,  hesi- 
tations of  belief.  Cournot  shows  himself  profoundly  conscious  \\ 
that  a  finite  intellect  must  be  a  fallible  intellect ;  that  man  as 
a  conditional  being  cannot  have  a  strictly  absolute  certainty ; 
that  it  is  not  merely  human  to  err,  but  that  the  possibility  of 
«rror  is  so  involved  in  the  very  constitution  of  the  human  mind 
that  it  cannot  be  thought  of  as  absent  from  it;  that  in  all 
perception,  all  consciousness,  all  reasoning,  there  lurks,  and 
must  ever  lurk,  this  possibility;  and  that  we  must  often 
Tesign  ourselves  to  be  guided,  even  in  matters  of  high  con- 
cern, by  low  probabilities.  In  his  view  all  that  we  can  say  of 
the  most  completely  verified  laws  of  nature  is  that  they  are 
infinitely  probable  ;  and  "speaking  physically,  infinite  proba- 
bility is  equivalent  to  reality,  but  logically  speaking  it  is  never 
more  than  a  probability."  It  is  just  those  questions  which 
most  interest  and  concern  humanity  which  are  generally 
least  susceptible  of  scientific  treatment;  and  therefore  it  is 
no  disparagement  to  philosophy  to  represent  it  as  occupied 
with  such  questions.1 
Cournot's  philosophy  of  history  is   merely  an  historical 

1  There  is  a  good  study  on  the  general  philosophy  of  Cournot  hy  T.  V.  Char- 
pentier,  in  the  '  Eev.  Phil.,'  t.  xi. 


646  PHILOSOPHY  OF  HISTORY  IN  PRANCE 

etiology,  an  analysis  and  discussion  of  the  causes  and  con- 
catenations of  causes  which  have  concurred  to  bring  about 
the  events  of  which  history  presents  us  with  the  picture.  It 
is  not  simply  the  history  either  of  civilisation  or  of  humanity, 
for  universal  history  has  its  etiology  just  as  have  the  histories 
of  religion,  science,  morality,  policy,  art,  and  industry,  or,  in 
other  words,  the  special  historical  developments  which  it  in- 
cludes. Nor  is  it  the  ambitious  and  hypothetical  teleology  of 
history,  to  which  the  name  of  philosophy  of  history  has  been 
so  often  given.  M.  Cournot  does  not  contest  that  the  course 
of  humanity  proceeds  according  to  a  fixed  plan  and  towards  a 
decreed  or  designed  end ;  but  he  thinks  that  all  attempts  to 
trace  such  a  plan  and  determine  such  an  end  are  plainly  de- 
fective and  unreliable,  and  that  the  most  celebrated  of  them, 
like  those  of  Hegel  and  Cousin,  although  they  might  be  received 
with  applause  around  a  professorial  chair,  are  worthless  before 
criticism,  the  only  good  kind  of  philosophy.  He  abjures  for 
his  own  part  such  venturesomeness.  His  historical  philosophy 
is  critical,  not  speculative.  It  allows  the  use  of  hypotheses 
only  in  so  far  as  they  suggest,  or  are  suggested  by,  inductions. 
Cournot  rejects  the  Comtian  law  of  the  three  states,  and, 
succinctly  but  conclusively,  shows  its  inconsistency  with  facts. 
He  does  not  attempt  to  replace  it  by  another ;  he  does  not  even 
venture  to  affirm  that  there  is  any  law  of  history.  Denning  a 
law  of  nature  to  be  "a  constant  mathematical  relation  between 
two  variable  quantities,"  he  finds  nowhere  in  history  laws  cor- 
responding to  his  definition.  It  is  not  laws,  therefore,  which 
he  seeks  in  history,  but  causes  or  reasons,  connections  and 
relations.  "  Whether  there  are  or  are  not  laws  in  history,  it 
is  enough  that  there  are  facts,  and  that  these  facts  are  some- 
times subordinate  to  one  another,  sometimes  independent  of 
one  another,  in  order  that  there  may  be  room  for  a  criticism 
designed  to  trace  out  in  the  one  case  the  subordination  and  in 
the  other  the  independence.  And  as  this  criticism  cannot  pre- 
tend to  irresistible  demonstrations,  such  as  produces  scientific 
certainty,  but  is  restricted  to  the  setting  forth  of  analogies  and 
inductions,  like  those  with  which  philosophy  must  be  content 
(otherwise  it  would  be  a  science,  as  so  many  people  have  vainly 
pretended  it  to  be,  and  not  philosophy),  it  follows  that  we  are 


cournot  647 

quite  entitled  to  give  this  criticism  of  which  we  are  speaking, 
and  which,  notwithstanding  its  uncertainties,  is  of  so  much  in- 
terest, the  name  of  'philosophy  of  history.'  The  same  holds  of 
the  history  of  peoples  as  of  the  history  of  nature,  which  is  not 
to  be  confounded  with  the  science  of  nature,  seeing  that  the 
one  has  chiefly  for  object  facts  and  the  other  laws,  but  facts 
which  may  be  on  so  great  a  scale,  and  have  consequences  so 
vast  and  durable,  that  they  appear  to  us  to  have,  and  really 
have,  the  same  importance  as  laws.  None  the  less  reason 
recognises  a  radical  difference  between  laws  and  facts:  the 
former  valid  always  and  everywhere,  by  a  necessity  inherent 
in  the  permanent  essence  of  things ;  the  latter  brought  about 
by  a  concurrence  of  anterior  facts,  and  determining  in  their 
turn  the  facts  which  are  to  follow  them." 1 

Cournot  considers  it  essential  to  a  correct  understanding  of 
history  to  distinguish  between  necessary  and  fortuitous  events, 
and  to  assign  a  considerable  place  to  the  latter.  He  holds  that 
the  idea  of  chance  or  hazard  is  not  a  mere  phantom  evoked  by 
the  mind  to  hide  from  itself  its  own  ignorance,  or  to  express 
the  imperfection  of  its  knowledge  in  certain  circumstances  and 
conditions,  but  the  notion  of  a  fact  true  in  itself,  demonstrable 
in  some  cases  by  reasoning,  and  more  commonly  confirmed  by 
observation.  The  fact  which  it  implies  is  the  independence  of 
series  of  causes  which,  although  unrelated,  do  in  fact  concur  to 
produce  certain  phenomena  or  events,  which  are  on  this  account 
appropriately  termed  fortuitous.  Such  independence  of  series 
of  causes  Cournot  regards  as  quite  consistent  with  belief  in  their 
common  suspension  to  a  single  primordial  ring  beyond,  or  even 
within  the  limits  to  which  our  reasonings  or  observations  can 
attain.  There  is,  in  his  view,  no  opposition  between  chance 
properly  understood  and  Providence,  between  hazard  and  Di- 
vine Will  or  Fate.  An  accidental  fact  does  not  mean  an  effect 
without  a  cause,«or  a  fact  which  human  wisdom  cannot  in  any 
measure  foresee  or  provide  against,  but  a  fact  brought  about  by 
the  interaction  of  chains  or  groups  of  facts  which  are  not 
naturally  connected.  Were  there  no  facts  of  this  kind  there 
could  be  no  history,  but  only  science.  Were  all  facts  of  this 
kind  there  could  equally  be  no  history,  but  only  annals.     His- 

1  Page  i  of  Preface. 


648  PHILOSOPHY  OF   HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

tory  properly  so  called  implies  the  commingling  of  fortuitous 
and  necessary  facts.  The  part  of  fortuity,  according  to  Cournot, 
is  especially  large  in  political  history,  as  the  action  of  excep- 
tional and  superior  personalities  has  there  most  effect;  it 
diminishes,  however,  as  general  causes,  the  collective  reason 
and  will,  attain  ascendancy.  Inasmuch  as  the  efficiency  of  for- 
tuitous events  may  be  extensive  and  even  permanent,  partic- 
ularly in  the  political  sphere,  the  student  of  historical  etiology 
must  be  on  his  guard  against  overlooking  them  ;  at  the  same 
time,  political  history,  in  which  hazard  has  most  influence,  is  for 
the  historical  etiologist  not  the  first  but  the  last  department 
of  history,  the  most  superficial,  particular,  and  external.  On 
this  very  account,  however,  political  history  is  always  the  chief 
object  of  interest  to  the  ordinary  historian,  constitutionally 
incapable  of  general  and  philosophical  views. 

With  characteristic  caution  M.  Cournot  refrains  from  at- 
tempting to  survey  the  course  of  history  as  a  whole,  and 
confines  his  reflections  chiefly  to  modern  times.  He  has,  how- 
ever, some  introductory  chapters  on  the  medieval  period ;  and 
in  these  he  characterises  with  remarkable  sagacity  its  general 
spirit,  its  scientific  condition,  its  scholastic  philosophy,  its 
ecclesiastical  organisation,  and  it  feudal  constitution.  He 
shows  very  clearly  how  it  ought  to  be  differentiated  from 
ancient  and  modern  history.  It  is  to  be  regretted  that  the 
late  Professor  Freeman  did  not  become  acquainted  with  his 
observations  on  the  division  of  history  into  "ancient"  and 
"  modern."  He  could  hardly  have  failed  to  learn  from  them 
that  there  was  more  to  be  done  in  relation  to  that  division 
than  simply  to  assail  it  and  condemn  its  abuses ;  that  it  was 
also  necessary  to  inquire  how  far  it  is  legitimate,  and  what  the 
terms  ancient  and  modern,  old  and  new,  when  applied  to  history 
and  historical  phenomena,  really  mean. 

Even  of  the  limited  period  of  history  selected  by  him  for 
investigation,  Cournot  does  not  attempt  to  give  a  systematic 
survey,  to  trace  in  it  the  operation  of  laws,  or  to  formulate  its 
characteristics  and  results.  His  treatment  of  it  is  comprehen- 
sive, but  not  deductive  or  constructive  ;  it  has  no  other  unity 
than  that  which  arises  from  sameness  of  spirit  and  method.  His 
conclusions  are  the  results  of  careful  analysis  and  reflection,  but 


COTTRNOT  649 

they  do  not  pretend  to  be  more  than  "  considerations,"  probabili- 
ties, generalities.  To  detach  them  from  the  discussions  to  which 
they  belong,  and  to  force  them  into  more  definite  and  rigid  forms 
than  the  author  himself  has  given  them,  would  be  to  falsify  his 
thought.  Cournot's  disquisitions  hardly  even  admit  of  useful 
abridgment,  as  there  is  no  diffuseness  of  language  in  them  to 
prune  away,  and  the  probabilist  traits  of  the  reasoning  in  them 
require  for  their  exhibition  almost  exact  reproduction. 

Each  century  of  modern  European  history  —  the  sixteenth, 
seventeenth,  eighteenth,  and  nineteenth  —  has  assigned  to  it  a 
separate  book ;  and  in  each  book  the  general  plan  followed  is 
the  same.  What  that  plan  is  will  be  best  stated  in  the  au- 
thor's own  words :  "  If  we  were  treating  of  some  ancient  or 
remote  civilisation,  it  would  be  proper  to  present  first  the 
ethnographical  data  which  are  chiefly  supplied  by  the  study 
of  languages ;  then  we  should  occupy  ourselves  with  geographi- 
cal data,  with  the  conditions  of  climate  and  of  soil ;  and,  the 
medium  or  theatre  of  the  civilisation  having  been  thus  denned, 
we  should  successively  pass  in  review  the  different  elements  of 
this  civilisation,  the  religion,  morals,  customs,  political  institu- 
tions, poetry,  philosophy,  art,  industry,  sciences,  in  the  order  of 
their  antiquity  and  originality,  as  nature  regulates  it,  when 
there  are  no  abnormal  causes  of  a  hasty  or  a  tardy  develop- 
ment, or  even  of  a  complete  atrophy.  But  for  our  purpose, 
whether  we  take  account  of  peculiarities  of  origin  or  have 
regard  to  its  final  term,  a  nearly  inverse  order  is  to  be  followed. 
We  must  give  the  first  place  in  our  plan  to  what  truly  con- 
stitutes the  common  substratum  of  European  civilisation ;  that 
which  has  been  the  least  altered  or  repressed  in  its  progress  by 
elements  of  a  more  variable  nature;  that  which  will  have  for 
future  generations  the  most  persistent  interest.  We  shall 
therefore  give  the  positive  sciences  priority  to  philosophical 
systems,  and  even  philosophical  systems — notwithstanding 
their  following  one  another  so  rapidly,  although  in  a  circle  deter- 
mined by  the  immutable  constitution  of  the  human  mind — pri- 
ority to  religious  doctrines,  which,  humanly  considered,  depend 
much  more  on  historical  conjunctures,  a  circumstance  which 
does  not  hinder  them  from  exerting  an  influence  far  more 
penetrating,  general,  and  enduring.     And  we  shall  assign  the 


650  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   FRANCE 

last  place  in  our  plan  to  all  that  directly  tells  of  the  diver- 
sities of  origin,  genius,  and  customs,  among  the  nations  which 
participate  in  our  European  civilisation;  concluding  with 
views  on  the  great  historical  events  in  which  accidents  have 
certainly  more  effect  than  elsewhere,  although  not  so  much 
as  to  compel  us  to  despair  of  recognising  in  them  any  traces 
of  order  and  regular  concatenation." 1 

As  any  book  of  the  treatise  under  consideration  will,  accord- 
ingly, serve  as  well  as  any  other  to  exemplify  Cournot's  general 
method  of  procedure,  let  us  select  for  the  purpose  the  fifth, 
which  treats  of  our  own  century. 

"The  exact  sciences  in  the  nineteenth  century"  are  the 
subjects  of  its  first  chapter.  These  sciences  —  mathematics, 
physics,  chemistry,  &c.  —  have,  we  are  told,  so  extended  and 
ramified,  so  developed  and  subdivided,  that  the  possibility  of 
writing  a  history  of  them  has  almost  vanished.  It  is  only 
possible  to  record  their  achievements  from  day  to  day  in  a 
multitude  of  journals  and  in  their  own  technical  language. 
Their  historical  interest  has  decreased  with  the  general  dim- 
inution of  their  intelligibility.  Mathematics  has  been  rela- 
tively losing  its  supremacy.  Its  progress  has  not  been  so 
closely  and  entirely  connected  with  the  advances  of  the  physical 
sciences  in  the  present  as  in  the  two  previous  centuries.  It 
has  been  becoming  not  less  but  more  apparent  that  the  key 
to  the  knowledge  of  all  physical  nature  will  not  be  found 
in  mathematics  themselves,  or  even  in  mathematics  conjoined 
with  mechanics.  Physicists  are  learning  that  they  must  trust 
less  to  mathematics  and  more  to  their  own  combined  efforts ; 
mathematicians  are  realising  that  they  must  occupy  them- 
selves more  exclusively  with  perfecting  their  science  for  its 
own  sake.  Physics  has  been  growing  more  experimental,  and 
mathematics  more  speculative.  Astronomy  from  being  almost 
entirely  mathematical  has  largely  developed  into  a  natural  sci- 
ence, thereby  gaining  greatly  in  cosmological  interest. 

Passing  over  what  is  said  of  the  condition  and  historical  bear- 
ings of  optics,  thermology,  and  chemistry,  we  come  tothesecond 
chapter,  which  is  on  "  the  progress  of  the  natural  sciences  in 
the  nineteenth  century."     The  chief  question  discussed  in  it  is 

1  '  Considerations,'  t.  i.  pp.  34,  35. 


COURNOT  651 

whether  or  not  the  development  of  these  sciences  has  tended 
to  show  that  organic  nature  admits  of  a  merely  mechanical 
explanation.  Cournot  contends  that  it  has  not ;  that  it  has 
even  confirmed  the  distinction  between  the  organic  and  inor- 
ganic, and  made  apparent  that  "vitalism  is  the  .true  renovating 
principle  of  philosophy  in  the  nineteenth  century."  Matter, 
Life,  and  Reason  are,  in  his  view,  three  distinct  stages  of  reality; 
the  higher  of  which,  while  implying,  are  inexplicable  by  the 
lower.  Indicating  the  significance  of  the  advances  in  the  know- 
ledge of  nature  represented  by  the  origination  of  such  new  dis- 
ciplines as  embryology,  teratology,  and  botanical  and  zoological 
geography,  he  describes  these  advances  as,  strictly  and  distinc- 
tively speaking,  more  historical  than  scientific.  He  holds  that 
there  will  always  be  a  natural  history,  as  well  as  a  human  his- 
tory, incapable  of  being  raised  to  the  rank  of  science,  yet  none 
the  less  important  on  that  account.  In  every  form  history  has 
more  affinity  than  exact  science  with  the  genius  of  democracy. 

The  question  of  the  origin  of  species  and  the  Darwinian  hy- 
pothesis come  under  consideration  in  the  next  chapter.  The 
question  is  shown  to  be  of  the  widest  and  most  far-reaching 
significance.  Darwin's  hypothesis  is  argued  to  be  very  partial 
and  defective,  yet  to  have  the  great  value  of  indicating  or  sug- 
gesting ways  in  which  the  problem  should  be  attacked. 

The  following  chapter  is  a  discourse  on  "  the  historical  la- 
hours  of  the  nineteenth  century."  Prominence  is  given  to  the 
fact  that  the  history  of  man  and  of  society  has  been  in  the 
present  age  attached  more  closely  to  that  of  nature ;  and  an- 
thropology, ethnology,  and  linguistics  are  referred  to  in  con- 
firmation of  it.  Cournot  agrees  with  Max  Miiller  in  regarding 
the  Science  of  Language  as  a  natural  science  ;  and  only  regrets 
that  he  has  made  too  much  concession  to  "  the  cavilling  logi- 
cians of  the  country  in  which  he  writes,"  by  admitting  that 
what  is  said  of  the  life  of  languages  is  merely  to  be  under- 
stood metaphorically.  According  to  Cournot's  own  view,  the 
use  of  the  term  life  in  linguistics  is  not  properly  metaphori- 
cal, or  more  metaphorical  than  the  terms  force,  attraction,  or 
affinity  in  physics.  Surveying  the  jurisprudence,  politics,  and 
economics  of  the  historical  school,  the  historical  criticism  of 
art  and  religion  characteristic  of  our  age,  and  the  prevalence 


652  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTOKY   IN   FRANCE 

of  the  naturalistic  or  historical  spirit  in  almost  all  spheres,  he 
comes  to  the  conclusion  that  the  nineteenth  century  may  be 
justly  affirmed  to  have  been,  on  the  whole,  a  century  of  his- 
torical reaction  and  renovation. 

The  philosophy  of  the  nineteenth  century  is  brought  up  for 
review  in  the  next  chapter.  This  philosophy  is  also  represented 
as  haviug  been,  in  the  main,  a  reaction  and  a  renovation.  The 
judgment  which  our  author  pronounces  on  Electicism  is  more 
severe  than  that  which  he  passes  on  Positivism,  but  he  points- 
out  with  clearness  and  effect  the  errors  even  of  the  latter,  and 
comes  to  the  conclusion  that  it  has  no  claim  to  be  called  posi- 
tive in  the  sense  of  scientific. 

The  sixth  chapter  treats  of  "the  economic  revolution  in 
the  nineteenth  century."  That  revolution  is  argued  to  have 
been  due  to  the  natural  and  concurrent  developments  of  me- 
chanics, chemistry,  and  geology,  and  to  have  owed  nothing 
to  the  great  catastrophes  which  happened  in  France  at  the 
close  of  the  previous  century,  or  to  any  other  political  changes. 
Some  of  its  moral  and  political  effects  are  indicated.  It  has 
largely  contributed  to  make  the  pursuit  of  wealth  the  princi- 
pal aim  of  men,  and  to  raise  industry  above  all  other  interests* 
It  has  in  various  ways  exerted  a  socially  levelling  influence,, 
and  has  favoured  the  growth  of  democracy.  On  intellect  and 
morality  it  has  worked  in  some  respects  for  evil,  in  others 
for  good. 

The  economic  revolution  of  the  age  has  produced  the  So- 
cialism of  the  age.  Hence  the  next  chapter  treats  of  "  Social- 
ism." In  contemporary  Europe  there  are,  according  to  Cour- 
not,  three,  and  only  three,  great  parties  face  to  face:  one 
which  would  revive  the  old  religious  faith,  and  on  that  basis- 
build  up  and  maintain  the  social  system ;  another  which  puts 
its  trust  in  democratic  institutions,  more  State  control,  en- 
larged municipal  powers,  and  the  like ;  and  a  third  which  ab- 
hors the  Church,  and  sets  slight  value  on  individual  rights  or 
popular  liberties,  but  deems  it  intolerable  that  a  few  should 
be  wealthy  while  many  are  poor,  and  urges  as  a  remedy  for 
this  evil  the  appropriation  by  the  community  of  the  means 
of  production  and  of  exchange,  for  the  common  benefit.  The 
conflict  between  Liberalism  and  Socialism  he  describes   as 


COUENOT  653 

one  of  the  conspicuous  characteristics  of  the  nineteenth 
century.  Socialism  is  the  younger  force,  and  its  advent 
and  development  are  peculiarly  worthy  of  study.  Its  pro- 
gress has  been  remarkable,  and  there  are  obvious  reasons 
why  it  should  have  been  so ;  but  the  socialistic  idea  is  only 
capable  of  partial  realisation.  It  is  impossible  to  eliminate 
economic  competition  ;  manifestly  impossible,  for  example,  to 
get  rid  of  it  between  nations,  and  if  impossible  to  get  rid  of  it 
between  them,  necessarily  also  impossible  to  get  rid  of  it  within 
them.  The  protection  which  Socialism  offers  is  a  symptom  of 
relative  feebleness.  Those  who  are  desirous  of  it  must  be 
wanting  in  that  individual  energy  which  is  after  all  the  source 
of  national  energy ;  and  it  is  not  likely  that  they  will  exercise 
the  chief  influence  on  the  future  of  civilisation.  The  principles 
of  economic  liberty  are,  indeed,  much  less  scientifically  estab- 
lished theorems  than  postulates  necessary  to  the  establishment 
of  economic  science.  Such  postulates,  however,  they  are  ;  and 
Socialism,  which  denies  them,  has  not,  and  cannot  have,  any 
economic  science  properly  so  called. 

In  the  eighth  chapter  the  movement  of  opinion  during  the 
present  century  in  relation  to  public  law  and  political  insti- 
tutions is  the  subject  under  consideration.  It  is  maintained 
that  in  this  sphere  also  it  is  necessary  to  distinguish  between 
the  effects  of  general  causes  and  those  of  a  particular  cause 
however  powerful,  —  between  the  consequences  of  the  spirit  of 
the  age  and  of  a  revolutionary  accident.  In  confirmation  it  is 
argued  that  the  removal  of  political  inequalities  and  religious 
disabilities,  the  extinction  of  slavery,  &c,  far  from  having  been 
directly  and  mainly  due  to  the  French  Revolution,  have  been 
chiefly  accomplished  by  those  who  have  been  least  in  sympathy 
with  that  Revolution.  The  present  age  is  held  to  be  even  more 
democratic  and  mare  levelling  in  its  tendencies  than  the  pre- 
ceding, but  to  be  so  owing  to  internal,  intellectual,  and  economic 
transformations  of  society  brought  about  by  causes  independ- 
ent of  the  Revolution.  Various  changes  in  law  and  govern- 
ment are  traced  to  a  general  change  which  has  taken  place  in 
thought  and  feeling  towards  humanity.  Humanity  has  become, 
to  a  large  extent,  the  object  of  a  sort  of  religious  worship, 
hased,  however,  not  on  the  Christian  idea  of  an  incarnation  of 


654  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  1ST  FRANCE 

God  in  humanity,  but  on  faith  in  a  self-perfecting  development 
of  humanity  which  will  end  in  a  realisation  of  its  immanent 
divine  ideal.  The  present  age,  as  compared  with  that  which 
preceded  it,  is,  further,  described  as  being  somewhat  indifferent 
to  liberty,  and  more  ready  to  submit  to  encroachments  on  it 
which  promise  to  be  generally  advantageous.  This  is  traced  in 
part  to  weakened  spiritual  faith  and  to  loss  of  enthusiasm,  but 
chiefly  to  the  confidence  which  the  people  have  acquired  that 
their  liberty  can  no  longer  be  seriously  endangered.  Of  the 
last  chapter  I  shall  merely  say  that  it  treats  of  "  the  European 
political  system  in  the  nineteenth  century,  and  the  advent  of 
the  principle  of  nationalities ; "  and  that  its  conclusions  are  of 
a  kind  which  there  would  be  little  or  no  advantage  in  merely 
stating. 

It  would  be  foolish  to  recommend  the  work  of  Cournot  to 
general  readers  of  any  type  or  class.  He  probably  never  wrote 
a  paragraph  for  such  readers,  and  certainly  none  of  them 
would  ever  care  to  read  any  book  of  his.  I  strongly  recommend 
the  work,  however,  to  the  attention  of  thoughtful  students  of 
history.  They  will  find  that  every  page  bears  the  impress  of 
patient,  independent,  and  sagacious  thought.  I  believe  I  have 
not  met  with  a  more  genuine  thinker  in  the  course  of  my 
investigations  into  the  development  of  historical  speculation. 
My  admiration  of  his  merits  as  a  thinker,  I  must  add,  does  not 
arise  from  any  very  close  accordance  between  my  own  opinions 
and  his.  I  decidedly  reject  his  view  of  philosophy.  In  my 
opinion  philosophy  has  definite  objects,  may  attain  certainties, 
and  is  as  properly  of  the  nature  of  science  as  are  the  special 
sciences.  His  probablism,  like  all  other  probabilist  systems, 
seems  to  me  an  inconsistent  scepticism.  I  do  not  think  that 
his  doctrine  of  the  accidental  in  history  has  either  the  degree 
of  truth  or  the  measure  of  importance  which  he  attaches  to  it. 
The  contingency  which  pervades  and  characterises  history 
ought,  in  my  judgment,  to  be  traced  mainly  to  human  free- 
dom, not  to  such  accidents  as  he  emphasises,  which  are  simply 
necessities  that  men  cannot  foresee  or  avert.  The  chief  defect 
of  Cournot's  treatment  of  history  is  an  insufficient  apprecia- 
tion of  the  power  and  efficiency  of  conscience  and  moral  free- 
dom in  history.     The  answers  which  he  gives  to  the  particular 


RENOUVIER  655 

questions  he  discusses  are  naturally  often  disputable.  But  he 
was  nevertheless  a  man  of  the  finest  intellectual  qualities,  of 
a  powerful  and  absolutely  truthful  mind ;  and  his  writings 
will  richly  repay  careful  study. 


II 

The  chief  of  French  criticists  is  M.  Charles  Renouvier. 
Like  Auguste  Comte,  he  was  born  at  Montpellier,  and  edu- 
cated at  the  Ucole  Poly  technique  of  Paris,  where  he  was  distin- 
guished by  his  proficiency  in  mathematics.  He  has,  however, 
far  greater  power  of  abstract  thought  and  of  logical  and  psycho- 
logical analysis  than  Comte  possessed,  as  well  as  a  far  wider 
and  more  thorough  general  culture.  He  has  also,  what  Comte 
had  not,  a  healthy  and  harmonious  mental  constitution.  Hav- 
ing an  independent  fortune  he  has  never  worked  for  bread 
or  gain ;  but  he  has  been  a  most  indefatigable  worker  in  the 
cause  of  truth.  He  has  been  a  voluminous  publicist.  In 
theorising  he  has  never  lost  sight  of  ethical  and  practical  aims. 
His  philosophical  conception  of  the  universe  is  a  pre-eminently 
moral  conception  of  it.  Liberty  is,  in  his  view,  the  essence  of 
man,  and  the  ground  of  certitude ;  and  the  moral  law  is  the  one 
fixed  point  beyond  phenomena,  the  first  of  all  truths,  and  the 
warrant  for  all  such  belief  in  God,  the  soul,  and  immortality, 
as  men  need  in  order  that  they  may  live  a  life  of  duty.  The 
treatises  in  which  he  has  expounded  his  philosophy  present  to 
us  a  wide  territory  ;  but,  as  Dr.  Shadworth  H.  Hodgson  has 
said,  "  the  crowning  peak  of  the  whole  land,  the  glorious  sun- 
lit summit  to  which  its  roads  have  led  him,  and  from  which 
we  obtain  no  uncertain  glimpses  of  the  promised  future  of 
humanity,  is  the  '  Science  de  la  Morale.'  " 1 

M.  Renouvier  has  sought  to  be  more  Kantian  than  Kant ; 
to  correct  and  complete  the  thought  of  Kant ;  to  rethink  and 
revise  his  criticism  and  its  results,  and  to  develop  and  apply 
what  is  true  in  them.     He  claims  to  have  freed  the  doctrine 

1 M.  Renouvier's  philosophy  was  almost  unknown  in  England  until  Dr.  Hodgson 
called  attention  to  it  by  his  articles  in  '  Mind '  (vol.  iv.).  My  own  acquaintance 
with  it,  however,  began  much  earlier.  There  are  two  excellent  articles  on  "  M. 
Renouvier  et  le  Criticisme  Francaise  "  by  M.  Beurier,  in  the  '  Rev.  Phil.,'  t.  iii. 


.656  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   PRANCE 

of  which  Kant  established  the  principles  from  the  contradic- 
tions and  errors  into  which  Kant  fell,  and  to  have  given  it 
by  a  new  analysis  of  the  laws  of  thought  and  means  of  knowl- 
edge what  it  previously  lacked,  a  truly  positive  character  and 
a  complete  and1  harmonious  systematic  unity.  He  resolutely 
rejects  "noumena,"  "  things-in-themselves,"  "substances," 
"  the  absolute,"  &c,  under  all  forms  and  disguises.  He  has 
reasoned  out  with  a  comprehensiveness  and  consistency  prob- 
ably unequalled  a  doctrine  of  phenomenism,-  distinct  from 
empiricism  and  positivism  in  almost  all  respects  except  one,  — 
the  reduction  of  knowledge  to  the  laws  of  phenomenism.  Of 
this  doctrine  he  has  given  a  full  and  systematic  exposition  in 
the  works  indicated  below.1 

The  fourth  of  M.  Renouvier's  "Essais  de  la  Critique  Gen- 
e"rale  "  is  entitled  '  Introduction  a  la  Philosophic  Analytique  de 
l'histoire.'  It  was  published  in  1864.  A  second  edition  of 
it  may  be  expected  soon  to  appear;  and  it  will  doubtless, 
like  the  second  editions  of  the  other  "  Essais,"  largely  alter 
and  add  to  the  earlier  edition.  In  its  present  form  the 
work  must  be  regarded  as  a  very  imperfect  expression  of 
its  author's  views  on  the  subjects  discussed  in  it.  All  these 
subjects,  and  many  of  a  kindred  nature,  have  been  often  dealt 
with  by  him  since  in  the  pages  of  the  '  Critique  Philosophique,' 
or  elsewhere.  The  '  Critique  Philosophique,'  which  appeared 
fortnightly  from  1872  to  1889  inclusive,  was,  for  the  most 
part,  the  joint  production  of  M.  Renouvier  and  his  friend 
M.  Pillon.  It  is  a  remarkable  monument  of  their  energy 
and  talent,  and  an  abundant  source  of  information  as  to  the 
New  Criticism,  and  its  founder's  views  on  philosophy,  politics, 
and  history.2 

M.  Renouvier  indicates  in  the  opening  sentences  of  his 

11  Essais  de  Critique  Generale,'  i  vols.,  1854r-64.  Of  this  work  there  has 
appeared  a  second  edition  of  the  ' Logique,'  3  torn.,  1875;  of  the  'Psychology,' 
3  torn.,  1875 ;  and  of  the  '  Principes  de  la  Nature,'  2  torn.,  1891.  '  La  Science  de 
la  Morale,'  2  vols.,  was  published  in  1869;  and  the  'Esquisse  d'une  Classification 
Systematique  des  Doctrines  Philosophiques,'  2  vols.,  in  1886. 

2  It  has  been  succeeded  by  the  '  Annee  Philosophique,'  which,  under  the 
editorship  of  M.  Pillon,  has  appeared  since  1890.  From  1879  to  1883  MM. 
Renouvier  and  Pillon  edited  '  La  Critique  Religieuse,'  which  contains  many  very 
remarkable  dissertations  on  religious  questions,  both  of  a  •  theoretical  and  prac- 
tical character. 


EENOUVIER  657 

Fourth  Essay  —  the  '  Introduction  to  the  Analytical  Philoso- 
phy of  History '  —  its  general  aim.  "  History,"  he  says, "  is  the 
experience  which  humanity  has  of  itself.  Approached  without 
criticism,  history  can  only  multiply  and  magnify  those  inco- 
herent phenomena  which  exclusively  individual  experience 
yields  when  the  moral  law  does  not  rule  the  conduct  and  the 
judgment.  Treated  according  to  an  a  priori  system,  it  disfig- 
ures or  despises  the  facts ;  it  rejects  some  or  inserts  others,  in 
order  to  arrange  them  with  more  ease  into  series.  The  neces- 
sity of  a  so-called  organic  development  is  thus  substituted  for 
the  simple  and  strong  light  of  consciousness,  which,  for  the 
universal  as  for  the  particular,  is  incomparably  the  best  means 
of  judging  the  data  of  experience,  of  assigning  them  their  true 
place,  and  even  of  supplying  at  need  the  want  of  them.  But 
history  studied  without  a  foregone  conclusion,  without  a  cos- 
mical,  or  theological,  or  physiological  hypothesis,  without  a 
plan  drawn  up  in  ignorance  and  prejudice  beforehand,  history 
supported  entirely  on  an  impartial  registration,  and  guided  by 
the  simple  laws  of  judgment  and  of  morality,  must  enlarge  the 
range  of  personal  experience,  respecting  the  knowledge  of 
humanity,  by  all  the  distance  which  separates  general  facts 
from  individual  phenomena."  By  these  words  we  are  told 
that,  in  the  opinion  of  their  author,  reliable  and  useful  views 
of  history  are  only  to  be  obtained  by  a  careful  analysis  of  the 
contents  of  history,  —  one  uninfluenced  by  any  a  priori  prin- 
ciples or  hypotheses,  but  which  conforms  to  the  laws  of  infer- 
ence and  does  not  contradict  primary  moral  perceptions. 

Questions  and  hypotheses  relating  to  the  physical  or  physio- 
logical origin  of  man  are  not  discussed  in  the  Fourth  but  in 
the  Third  Essay  — '  The  Principles  of  Nature '  — the  most  ap- 
propriate place,  as  they  refer  rather  to  the  general  kingdom 
of  nature  than  to  the  special  province  of  human  history.  They 
are  discussed  by  M.  Renouvier  with  entire  independence,  and 
rare  profundity  and  penetration.  He  has  studied  most  care- 
fully evolutionism  in  its  various  forms,  and  especially  in  its 
chief  English  exponents.  In  treating  of  such  themes  as  onto- 
genic,  embryogenic,  and  palseontological  progress,  physical 
evil,  species,  transformism,  the  struggle  for  existence,  the  de- 
scent of  man,  his  primitive  unity  or  plurality,  the  conditions 


658  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

and  mode  of  his  advent  on  earth,  he  steadily  regards  them 
in  a  critical  spirit,  or,  in  other  words,  from  the  point  of  view  of 
the  logician,  not  of  the  fanciful  deviser  of  hypotheses,  or  of 
either  the  affirmative  or  negative  dogmatist.  He  would,  of 
course,  be  untrue  to  his  own  principles  if  he  failed  to  show 
himself  fully  aware  that  all  conclusions  on  these  obscure  and 
complicated  topics  must  be  of  a  dubious  character,  and  stand 
in  need  of  continuous  revision.  This  charge,  however,  can- 
not be  brought  against  him.  He  may  have  been  at  times 
too  severe  a  critic  of  others,  but  he  has  certainly  been  also  a 
strict  critic  of  himself,  and  shown  himself  ready  to  modify  his 
opinions  into  accordance  with  the  evidence. 

The  reader  of  the  Fourth  Essay  must  also  bear  in  mind  that 
it  implies  the  Second  —  the  '  Psychology.'  It  rests  upon  the 
doctrine  of  human  nature  which  is  there  carefully  expounded. 
It  may  seem  to  assume  without  proof,  or  to  adopt  without 
adequate  confirmation,  disputable  and  peculiar  views  as  to 
human  sensibility,  intelligence,  passion,  volition,  liberty,  and 
their  relations ;  but  these  views,  it  must  be  remembered,  have 
been  argued  at  length  in  the  earlier  and  more  fundamental 
treatise.  It  is  in  this  treatise  also  that  the  theory  of  his- 
torical certitude,  as  included  in  the  general  theory  of  certitude, 
one  which  M.  Renouvier  has  discussed  very  earnestly  and  in- 
geniously, is  expounded ;  and  that  the  probabilities  concern- 
ing the  moral  order  of  the  world,  the  grounds  of  faith  in 
immortality  and  in  God,  which  are  of  essential  moment  and 
intensest  interest  to  the  historical  philosopher,  are  set  forth. 

The  Fourth  Essay  begins  with  an  inquiry  into  "  moral 
origins,"  or,  in  other  words,  into  the  principles  of  the  rise  and 
development  of  good  and  evil  in  humanity.  M.  Renouvier 
fully  recognises  the  difficulty  of  the  inquiry.  The  question  of 
pure  origins  is  one  always  of  inscrutable  obscurity.  The 
question  even  of  such  relative  origins  as  those  which  he  has 
here  in  view  refers  to  a  period  concerning  which  there  are  no 
records  or  testimonies.  It  is,  therefore,  peculiarly  necessary 
in  discussing  it  to  maintain  a  critical  attitude  towards  all 
attempts  to  deal  with  it  in  an  easy,  dogmatic,  hypothetical, 
<£w<m'-scientific  manner.  Yet  of  a  directly  and  strictly  scientific 
solution  it  does  not  seem  to  admit.    The  only  available  method 


KENOUVIER  659 

of  grappling  with  it,  M.  Renouvier  thinks,  is  by  the  aid  of 
inductions  drawn  from  the  nature  of  man  as  that  is  known  to 
us  in  our  own  experience,  but  reduced  to  its  essential,  gen- 
eral, and  simplest  elements,  those  elements  which  there  is 
every  reason  to  believe  are  invariable. 

He  has  always  seen  with  exceptional  clearness  the  inherent 
unreasonableness,  so  prevalent  among  scientists,  of  assimilating 
primitive  man  to  a  modern  savage,  and  arguing  directly  from 
the  latter  to  the  former.  Primitive  man  may  have  been  su- 
perior to  savage  man,  while  yet  destitute  of  advantages  which 
the  savage  possesses.  The  primitive  man,  just  because  primi- 
tive, although  endowed  with  a  good  intellect,  heart,  and  will, 
could  have  no  traditions,  acquisitions,  or  habits,  no  words 
except  those  which  he  invented,  no  tools  or  rudiments  of  art 
not  of  his  own  devising,  no  beliefs  not  attained  by  personal 
exertion.  As  regards  language,  implements,  arts,  and  amount 
of  experience,  even  the  lowest  savages  may  reasonably  be  held 
to  have  been  superior  to  primitive  man,  and  yet  their  manhood 
may  as  reasonably  be  supposed  to  be  inferior  owing  to  their 
intellectual  perversion  and  moral  corruption.  The  modern 
savage  is  to  a  very  large  extent  a  creature  of  traditions  and 
habits ;  and  to  that  extent  he  is  not  primitive.  You  must 
strip  your  savage  of  all  that  he  has  inherited  or  acquired  be- 
fore you  can  get  at  anything  primitive  in  him.  But  this  means 
that  you  must  take  from  him  all  the  corrupt  tendencies  he  has 
inherited,  all  the  evil  habits  which  he  has  formed,  all  the  be- 
liefs in  which  he  has  grown  up,  the  language  which  he  has 
learned,  tribal  customs  and  usages,  &c.  But  when  you  have 
done  all  this,  where  is  your  savage  ?  He  is  clean  gone  as  a 
savage.  There  remains  nothing  of  him  but  those  rudiments 
of  humanity  which  are  common  to  him  and  to  yourself.  And 
these  you  must  obviously  study  in  yourself,  seeing  that  it  is 
only  of  yourself  that  you  have  direct  knowledge,  immediate 
experience.  But  the  knowledge  and  experience  of  yourself 
must  be  so  analysed  and  generalised,  that  what  is  individual 
and  peculiar,  secondary  and  factitious  in  it,  may  be  eliminated. 
The  primitive  man'  must  be  conceived  of  as  a  true  and  whole 
man,  yet  only  as  an  abstract  or  generic  man,  without  racial  or 
individual  determinations.     And  the  history  to  be  elucidated 


660  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

must  be  of  a  corresponding  character.  "This  history,  with 
which  I  am  about  to  deal,  is  that  which  considers  human 
determinations  of  the  most  general  kind,  and  which  holds 
collective  ideas  and  beliefs  to  be  the  most  important  of  all, 
inasmuch  as  they  are  the  common  coefficients  of  any  individ- 
ual whatsoever.  But  these  great  intellectual  facts  must  not 
be  separated  from  the  passions  and  from  morality :  from  the 
passions  which  are  the  stimulants  and  very  matter  of  life ;  or 
from  morality,  of  which  the  form  modified  by  contact  with 
various  external  and  internal  phenomena,  acts  on  beliefs  and 
ideas,  and  then  experiences  their  reactions." 

M.  Renouvier  attributes  to  the  first  mien  the  primaiy  capaci- 
ties of  sensitivity  and  the  simple  emotive  tendencies  of  human 
nature,  and  also  reason  and  freewill,  but  the  latter  only  in  the 
state  of  potentialities,  or  powers  as  yet  unformed  by  exercise 
and  experience.  Without  these  they  would  not  be  men.  To 
come  forth  from  the  instinctive  condition  which  is  character- 
istic of  the  animal,  they  must  have  been  endowed  with  reason 
in,  so  to  speak,  an  instinctive  state,  and  with  liberty  as  a  power 
of  representing  their  determinations  as  possible.  The  passage 
from  potentiality  to  actuality  is  the  fundamental  fact  of  the 
history  of  primitive  man ;  and  the  chief  traits  of  it  may  be 
ascertained,  with  a  fair  measure  of  probability,  through  intro- 
spective analysis  and  induction.  In  order  to  exhibit  the  more 
clearly  his  views  on  this  point,  and  as  to  the  general  moral 
condition  of  primitive  man,  Renouvier  introduces  them  by  an 
examination  of  those  propounded  by  Kant  in  his  '  Conjectural 
Commencement  of  the  History  of  Mankind,'  and  in  his  '  Criti- 
cism of  Religion  within  the  Limits  of  Mere  Reason.'  It  is  a 
searching  investigation,  and,  on  the  whole,  a  most  successful 
attempt  to  distinguish  between  the  true  and  the  false  ele- 
ments in  Kant's  theory  of  the  moral  origins  of  humanity:  a 
theory,  according  to  Renouvier,  far  more  profound  and  in- 
structive than  that  of  any  other  philosopher  on  the  same  sub- 
ject, yet  hopelessly  inconsistent,  and  burdened  with  serious 
errors,  owing  to  Kant  having  had  a  narrow  conception  of  lib- 
erty, failed  to  recognise  the  law  of  moral  solidarity,  and  dealt 
with  his  problem  in  a  way  contrary  to  critical  principles. 

Renouvier  proceeds  otherwise  than  Kant.     He  begins  with 


EENOUVIEE  661 

complete  moral  persons  —  i.e.,  complete  in  the  elements  of 
manhood,  or,  as  having  in  indissoluble  conjunction  passions 
and  affections,  conceptions,  and  will.  He  posits  no  original 
antagonism  between  the  law  and  the  affections,  or  serious 
contrariety  among  the  affections  themselves.  He  does  not 
assume  that  the  law  is  ever  unrelated  to,  or  unconnected  with, 
some  affection ;  or  that  it  is  realised  in  the  consciousness  of 
primitive  men  in  its  distinctness  and  generality,  or  otherwise 
than  as  vaguely  and  obscurely  blended  with  particular  feel- 
ings and  passions,  and  as  associated  with  particular  acts ;  or 
that  it  is  felt  to  have  been  promulgated  by  any  power  external 
to  humanity,  or  to  have  penal  sanctions  attached  to  it.  He 
is  content  to  suppose  the  reverse  of  all  this  to  have  been 
characteristic  of  the  primitive  state,  although  a  state  thus 
simple  and  indeterminate  could  hardly,  he  thinks,  have  been 
of  long  duration. 

Thus  conceiving  of  primitive  man  he  does  not  find  it  neces- 
sary to  think  of  him  as  either  originally  good  or  originally  evil, 
but  only  as  innocent  and  peccable.  It  is  by  the  exercise  of  his 
liberty  that  man  becomes  either  truly  good  or  truly  evil. 
"  The  conflict  of  the  passions  arises  inevitably  from  the  plural- 
ity of  the  ends  which  man  from  the  very  constitution  of  his 
nature  sets  before  him.  Evil  never  tempts  him  as  evil ;  but  a 
good  which  he  pursues  is  often  unattainable  without  detriment 
to  another  good,  so  that  each  of  these  goods  appears  an  evil 
with  reference  to  the  other.  Conscience  is  therefore  bound  to 
choose  between  them  by  its  self-determining  activity.  The 
commonest  form  of  the  opposition  occurs  in  relation  to  time, 
when  two  goods,  both  really  good  relatively  to  the  agent  yet 
incompatible,  concern  different  periods  and  imply  more  or  less 
of  duration  or  of  generality;  or  in  relation  to  persons,  when  the 
good  of  the  agent  excludes  that  of  the  beings  connected  with 
him,  and  particularly  of  his  fellows  and  kindred,  those  with 
whom  he  recognises  himself  to  be  in  communion.  The  first  of 
these  cases  is  of  prime  importance  for  the  development  of  each 
man  and  of  his  worth  as  a  man.  It  is  there  that  the  virtues 
and  vices  which  specially  concern  the  agent  himself  have  their 
origin.  For  example,  experience  has  soon  taught  him  that  the 
eager  and  obstinate  pursuit  of  a  certain  end,  without  any  con- 


662  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

sideration  of  what  may  result  from  it  or  what  it  may  lead  to, 
brings  dangers  and  evils,  that  is  to  say,  excludes  other  goods 
either  essential  to  him,  or  which  will  be  of  great  consequence 
to  him  in  the  course  of  his  life.  According  as  he  will  learn  by 
an  effort  of  reflection  and  of  will  to  measure  his  acts  and  to 
moderate  his  present  affections,  or  will  abandon  himself  with- 
out reserve  to  the  passions  which  animate  him,  he  will  train 
himself  to  prudence  or  contract  the  vices  which  follow  the 
habit  of  yielding  without  reflection  to  the  precipitate  move- 
ments of  the  soul." 1  As  with  prudence  so  with  temperance, 
fortitude,  benevolence,  justice,  and  their  opposites,  —  with  all 
the  virtues  and  all  the  vices.  They  are  all  the  products  of 
liberty  in  given  historical  conditions.  By  accumulated  acts 
habits  are  formed,  and  with  the  habits  the  virtue  or  vice.  The 
fall  of  primitive  man  is  thus,  according  to  Renouvier,  intelli- 
gible ;  but  it  is  not  to  be  understood  as  a,  fall  from  the  height 
of  a  developed  morality  or  from  the  virtue  acquired  by  ante- 
rior efforts.  Analysis  of  the  data  of  moral  experience  shows, 
he  thinks,  that  it  must  mean  that  man  instead  of  reflectively 
and  voluntarily  accomplishing  a  possible  ascent  in  good  from 
innocence  to  virtue,  everywhere  worked  out  a  real  descent 
from  innocence  to  vice. 

My  limits  do  not  allow  me  to  indicate  how  he  describes  the 
processes  originative  of  the  virtues  and  vices,  or  how  he  char- 
acterises the  phases  of  the  development  of  moral  qualities. 
Suffice  it  to  say  that  the  method  which  he  follows  is  critical, 
psychological,  historical;  that  it  shuns  all  metaphysical  as- 
sumptions, all  speculations  unverifiable  by  experience ;  that  it 
treats  the  growth  of  morality  as  throughout  an  historical  move- 
ment, and,  indeed,  as  comprehensive  and  regulative  of  the 
general  movement  of  history.  The  whole  history  of  man  is 
viewed  by  Renouvier  as  the  product  of  the  use  or  abuse  of 
freedom ;  the  outcome  of  the  moral  agency  of  man.  The  prin- 
ciples of  morality  he  represents  as  necessary  to  the  very  exist- 
ence of,  and  pervasive  of  the  entire  evolution  of,  society,  and 
everywhere  present  and  operative  in  history  as  law  is  present 
and  operative  in  its  applications.  No  one  else  has  brought  the 
Science  of  Morality  and  the  Philosophy  of  History  into  such 
1  Quatrifcme  Essai,  p.  56. 


KENOUVIER  663 

close  conjunction.  For  him  the  former  is  the  central  and 
ruling  science,  and  the  latter  one  of  its  dependencies.  Hence 
his  great  work  —  perhaps  his  greatest — 'La  Science  de  la 
Morale,'  is  at  almost  all  points  in  contact  with,  and  the 
complement  of,  the  work  now  under  our  consideration. 

I  regret  that  I  must  not  attempt  even  to  summarise  M.  Re- 
nouvier's  admirable  observations  on  the  law  of  solidarity  in 
good  and  evil,  the  formation  of  ethic  races,  and  the  principles 
of  the  perversions  of  justice,  although  they  are  novel  and  of 
much  interest  for  an  understanding  of  history.  After  he  has 
set  forth  his  views  on  the  various  subjects  to  which  I  have 
now  referred,  he  deems  it  expedient  to  contrast  them  with  the 
divergent  or  antagonistic  views  of  some  notable  and  influential 
thinkers,  and  is  thus  led  to  criticise  the  moral  theses  of  Kant, 
the  historical  series  of  Hegel,  the  doctrine  of  the  Saint-Simo- 
nian  school,  the  Positivist  theory  of  history,  and  the  concep- 
tions of  Fourier  as  to  history  and  social  organisation. 

I  have  already  had  occasion  to  observe  that,  in  taking  account 
of  the  historical  philosophy  of  Renouvier,  the  Fourth  Essay 
must  not  alone  engage  our  attention ;  but  I  must  still  in  con- 
nection with  this  first  part  of  it  refer  to  the  valuable  series 
of  papers  in  the  '  Critique  Philosophique  '  on  "  the  psychol- 
ogy of  primitive  man."  Their  criticisms  of  the  arguments  of 
those  who  maintain  the  primitive  brutality  of  man,  or  who 
identify  the  primitive  man  with  the  modern  savage,  are 
among  the  best  which  have  been  anywhere  presented.  The 
examination  to  which  they  subject  the  hypotheses  that  have 
been  set  forth  by  Comte,  Darwin,  Lubbock,  Tylor,  Spencer, 
Bagehot,  Romanes,  and  others,  as  to  the  origin  of  intelligence, 
speech,  morality,  religion,  civilisation,  and  progress,  is  always 
relevant  and  acute,  and  often,  I  think,  either  to  a  large  ex- 
tent or  wholly,  just  and  decisive. 

The  second,  third,  and  fourth  parts  of  his  treatise  are  devoted 
to  the  study  of  the  history  of  religious  beliefs  and  ideas.1  He 
holds  that  in  religions  are  contained  nearly  all  that  we  know 
of  remote  antiquity ;  that  they  have  always  been  intimately 
connected  with  the  state  of  moral  sentiment  and  even  intellec- 

1  The  early  history  of  language  he  treats  of  in  the  '  Psychologies  t.  i.,  pp. 
136-139,  2d  ed. 


664  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

tual  speculation ;  that  the  only  proper  method  of  investigating 
them  is  that  of  comparison,  analysis,  induction ;  and  that  all 
a  priori  philosophies  of  history  have  arbitrarily  and  excessively 
simplified  their  course  and  succession, —  their  slow,  multiple, 
unequal,  and  troubled  march.  He  gives  us  his  views  of  the 
duties  and  laws  of  historical  criticism  when  applied  to  religions, 
and  especially  when  required  to  deal  with  miracles,  revelations, 
and  prophets,  with  myths,  symbols,  and  legends.  He  sets  aside 
various  erroneous  or  inadequate  hypotheses  as  to  primitive  re- 
ligion, inquires  as  to  how  the  primitive  man  probably  looked 
upon  nature,  and  endeavours  to  define  and  account  for  fetichism. 
He  shows  that  it  is  not  at  all  necessary  to  suppose  that  religion 
originated  with  fetichism ;  and  he  describes  the  tribal  religions 
—  African,  Boreal,  Polynesian,  and  American  —  in  which  fet- 
ichism has  prevailed.  He  compares,  and  analyses  somewhat 
minutely,  the  religious  and  ethical  systems  of  the  Chinese  and 
Egyptians. 

The  whole  of  the  third  part  is  occupied  with  the  religions 
(understood  as  inclusive  of  the  ethical  and  speculative  con- 
ceptions or  theories)  of  the  Aryan  world,  —  chiefly,  indeed, 
with  those  of  India,  Greece,  and  Rome,  but  also  with  those  of 
the  Germans,  Celts,  &c. 

The  fourth  part  deals  exclusively  with  the  religions  of  the 
Semitic  world.  Here  M.  Renouvier  begins  by  instituting  an 
inquiry  as  to  the  chronological  data,  the  traditions,  and  the 
documents  which  have  to  be  taken  into  account.  This  in- 
quiry he  conducts  in  the  spirit  of  the  higher  criticism,  and  with 
an  obvious  desire  not  to  yield  to  any  theological  bias.  He 
then  discourses  on  the  unity,  divisions,  and  characteristics  of 
the  Semites.  He  thinks  that,  on  merely  physiological  grounds, 
no  one  would  pronounce  the  Semites  and  Aryans  essentially 
distinct;  that  their  intellectual  and  moral  differences,  both 
negative  and  positive,  are,  on  the  other  hand,  strongly  marked, 
although  they  are  not  of  such  a  character  that  we  cannot  easily 
suppose  them  to  have  originated  at  a  greater  or  less  distance 
from  a  basis  of  common  qualities ;  but  that  the  grammatical 
system  common  to  the  Aryan  languages  and  that  of  the  Sem- 
itic tongues  are  irreducible,  and  require  us  to  regard  the 
Aryan  and  Semitic  peoples  as  primitive,  until  much  stronger 


RENOUVIER  665 

reasons  to  the  contrary  have  been  adduced  than  has  yet  been 
done.  He  proceeds  carefully  to  characterise  the  Semitic  race 
both  intellectually  and  morally ;  to  lay  bare  the  roots  of  its 
idea  of  Deity,  and  to  determine  the  content  of  that  idea,  by 
the  analysis  of  its  names  for  Deity  ;  and  to  connect  the  chief 
intellectual  and  moral  division  of  the  Semites  with  a  "  cruel 
scission,"  going  back  to  the  remotest  age  of  which  they  re- 
tained any  recollection.  This  "  scission  "  may  have  been  com- 
paratively slight  at  first,  but  becoming  ever  deeper,  it  in  time 
produced  profound  ethical  and  spiritual  changes,  and  parted 
the  race  into  two  branches  —  the  one  monotheistic  and  the 
other  polytheistic.  He  is  thus  naturally  led  to  treat  specially, 
first,  of  Semitic  monotheism ;  and,  secondly,  of  Semitic  poly- 
theism. 

M.  Renouvier  does  not  carry  his  study  of  religions  beyond 
what  he  calls  primary  epochs.  He  does  not  follow  them  into 
secondary  epochs,  those  in  which  beliefs  are  developed  into  fully 
formed  dogmas ;  or  into  tertiary  epochs,  those  in  which  faith  is 
revolutionised  by  the  progress  of  science  and  the  commingling 
of  peoples.  But  the  field  of  his  investigation,  even  when  thus 
limited,  is  a  wide  one.  The  number  of  distinct  inquiries  which 
he  institutes  is  very  great.  And  they  are  carefully,  learnedly, 
and  ably  conducted.  At  the  same  time,  their  relations  to  one 
another  and  their  bearings  on  the  general  aims  of  the  Essay, 
are  never  lost  sight  of.  Notwithstanding  the  merits,  however, 
of  the  contributions  to  the  Science  of  Religions  contained  in 
his  treatise,  M.  Renouvier  must,  of  course,  find,  in  re-editing 
it,  a  good  deal  to  alter  in  them,  owing  to  the  great  advances 
made  by  this  science  in  all  directions  since  1864. 

In  the  last  division  of  his  history  M.  Renouvier  sums  up  the 
conclusions  to  which  his  investigations  have  led  him.  His  ex- 
position of  his  views  of  progress  is  of  special  interest.  The 
subject  is  treated  with  the  earnestness  which  naturally  springs 
from  a  clear  view  of  its  importance.  He  recognises  how 
strongly  the  belief  in  progress  differentiates  the  present  from 
preceding  ages,  and  how  inevitably  it  must  be  either  invig- 
orating or  enervating,  either  a  source  of  virtue  or  a  cause  of 
demoralisation,  according  as  it  is  of  a  rational  and  moral 
character,  or  the  reverse.     If  it  be  a  belief  in  a  progress 


G66  PHILOSOPHY   OF  HISTORY  IN  FRANCE 

which  produces  good  of  necessity,  which  uses  men  as  mere 
instruments,  which  does  not  require  their  self-devotion,  their 
watchfulness,  restraint,  endurance,  and  labour,  and,  in  a  word, 
their  virtue,  it  must  be  prejudicial  to  virtue,  and  to  progress 
itself.  Profoundly  convinced  of  this,  M.  Eenouvier  has  been 
indefatigable  in  contending  for  truth  and  in  assailing  errors  as 
to  progress.  What  he  says  on  the  subject  in  the  Fourth  Essay 
is  but  a  small  part  of  what  he  has  written  concerning  it.  His 
papers  in  the  '  Critique  Philosophique '  on  the  various  questions 
connected  with  it  are  very  numerous.  In  fact  no  writer  has 
treated  the  theme  with  equal  closeness  or  fulness.  He  is  quite 
entitled  to  hold  that  his  predecessors  have  in  general  dealt  with 
it  very  superficially,  his  own  treatment  of  it  being  so  much  more 
searching  and  profound.1 

All  forms  of  the  doctrine  of  a  continuous  progress,  and  all 
theories  of  physical  and  mechanical,  fatalistic  and  predesti- 
narian,  necessitarianism,  from  which  it  derives  support,  have 
found  in  him  a  most  formidable  assailant.  He  has  been  always 
ready  to  expose  the  optimistic  illusions  which  abound  on  the 
subject.  He  admits  the  possibility  of  progress.  "  We  must 
work  for  progress,  therefore  it  is  possible,  and  necessary  at  least 
that  we  believe  it  possible."  It  is  possible  for  individuals  and 
nations,  in  all  spheres  of  human  life  and  activity.  And  it  is 
not  only  possible,  but  the  analysis  of  facts  shows  that  it  has 
actually  taken  place  during  certain  periods  in  the  history  of 
many  peoples.  No  facts  warrant  us,  however,  to  ascribe  to  it 
universality,  continuity,  or  necessity.  Deterioration  has  been 
as  prevalent  as  amelioration.  There  has  not  been  anywhere  or 
in  any  respect  uninterrupted  progress.  If  we  compare  medieval 
Europe  with  ancient  Greece  and  Rome  in  their  prime,  and 
apply  proper  criteria  in  an  impartial  manner,  the  former  must 
be  acknowledged  to  have  been  on  a  lower  intellectual  and 
moral  level.  If  we  examine  into  the  history  even  of  such  a 
phenomenon  as  slavery,  it  will  be  found  that  for  long  periods 
and  over  wide  spaces  it  was  not  liberty  which  gained  ground. 

1  In  the  series  of  papers  entitled  "Politique  et  Socialisme,"  published  in  the 
'  Critique  Philosophique,'  he  has  passed  in  review  the  systems  of  the  chief  theor- 
ists of  progress,  —  Herder,  Kant,  Hegel,  Turgot,  Condorcet,  Saint-Simon,  Fourier, 
Comte,  and  Spencer.  —  See  Annees  ix.,  t.  xi. ;  x.,  t.  i.-xi. ;  and  xii.,  t.  i.-xi. 


KENOUVIEK  667 

Europe  is  no  more  entitled  to  believe  herself  at  present  secure 
against  future  slow  decadence  or  rapid  collapse  than  Asia  was 
when  in  her  glory.  France  still  requires  to  struggle  with 
anxiety  if  she  would  even  retain  the  liberties,  rights,  and 
advantages  which  she  has  with  so  much  labour  and  difficulty 
gained.  Those  who  have  discoursed  on  progress  have  gener- 
ally erred  as  to  its  point  of  departure.  They  have  supposed 
it  to  have  started  from  conditions  which  can  only  have  been 
gradually  produced.  They  have  imagined  a  perfectible  bru- 
tality for  which  there  is  no  evidence  to  be  found  in  history. 
They  have  not  deemed  it  necessary  to  inquire  by  what  marks 
societies  are  to  be  ranked  as  superior  or  inferior  to  others.  They 
have  not  seriously  endeavoured  to  determine  what  constitutes 
progress,  and  have,  consequently,  failed  to  see  how  inseparable 
it  is  from  morality,  and  how  necessarily  it  must  be  the  work  of 
individuals  and  of  societies  themselves.  They  have  announced, 
so-called  laws  of  progress,  but  they  have  not  proved  that  there 
is  any  such  law  in  the  proper  sense  of  the  term,  any  necessary 
rule  and  invariable  succession  of  phenomena.  Those  which 
they  have  propounded  either  do  not  apply  to,  or  are  contra- 
dicted by,  numbers  of  facts. 

These  theses,  and  others  of  a  kindred  nature,  Renouvier  has 
laboured  on  many  occasions,  and  with  great  ability,  to  establish 
by  critical  and  analytical  disquisitions  on  the  relevant  data. 
A  mere  statement  of  them  can  do  scarcely  any  justice  to  his 
theory  of  progress.  To  make  it  fully  intelligible  would  require 
a  long  series  of  quotations,  and  of  long  quotations,  such  as 
wouldshowthe  character  of  the  method,  and  the  general  course 
of  the  argumentation,  pursued.  I  must  content  myself  with  a 
single  extract  from  the  Fourth  Essay.  By  simply  transcribing 
the  author's  words  I  shall  enable  my  readers  to  form  some  con- 
ception of  his  style  as  a  philosophical  writer,  —  a  style  to 
which  neither  a  literal  nor  a  free  translation  will  do  justice. 

"Ce  n'est  qu'apres  avoir  parcouru  les  periodes  principales  des  faits, 
des  idees  et  des  croyances  dans  les  differentes  senes  de  l'humanite  que 
je  pourrai  justifier  en  quel  sens  et  sur  quels  sujets,  dans  quelles  limites, 
pour  quelles  raisons,  il  y  a  eu  progres  jusqu'a  nous,  et  en  quoi  nous 
devons  esperer  que  ee  progres  se  continuera  a  l'avenir.  Les  prestiges 
de  la  loi  fatale   se  dissipant   a  nos   yeux,   avec   les   fausses   relations 


668  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

historiques,  qui  ont  etd  imaginees  pour  la  servir,  nous  verrons  cette 
gratide  loi  se  reMuire  pour  l'experienee  a  un  fait  de"ja  bien  considerable, 
savoir  que  la  civilisation  europdenne  est  heritiere  des  conquStes  morales 
et  des  travaux  de  plusieurs  grandes  races  diversement  douses  et  diverse- 
ment  meritantes;  qu'elle  est  parvenue  sur  ce  fondement  a  prendre  la 
conscience  et  la  possession  de  ses  propres  fonctions  a  un  degre"  jusqu'ici 
inconnu,  a  s'appuyer  sur  la  notion  meme  du  progres,  et  a  cre"er  des 
m^thodes,  a  composer  graduellement  des  sciences  et  des  arts  qui 
deviennent  k  leur  tour  des  aides  puissants  de  son  perfectionnement. 

"  Au-dessus  de  ce  fait  immense,  mais  auquel  rhumanite"  tout  entiere 
est  si  loin  d'avoir  participe,  on  peut  ensuite  concevoir  deux  lois ;  l'une 
serait  la  donnee  divine  et  providentielle  d'une  destinee  pour  les  hommes 
envisages  en  un  seul  corps,  destinee  qu'ils  attendraient  independam- 
ment  des  fluctuations  de  la  liberte",  et  peut-dtre  par  l'organe  de  certains 
d'entre  eux  seulement.  L'autre  serait  une  simple  loi  psychologique 
en  vertu  de  laquelle  Taction  constante  des  bons  mobiles,  des  bonnes 
passions  fondamentales  de  la  nature  humaine,  jointe  a  l'accumulation 
des  merites  et  des  connaissances,  pendant  que  toutes  les  determina- 
tions fausses  ou  perverses  de  la  volonte  se  de"truirait  mutuellement 
ou  ne  produiraient  que  des  ondulations  bientot  interrompues,  condui- 
rait  infailliblement  les  soci^tes  k  Tamelioration  croissante  de  leurs 
relations  et  k  la  moralite  de  plus  en  plus  grande  de  leurs  membres. 

"La  croyance  a  une  destinee  est  de  l'essence  de  toute  religion  deve- 
lopp^e.  Mais  la  fin  que  l'humanite  doit  atteindre,  selon  les  croyances 
de  ce  genre,  n'est  pas  toujours  terrestre;  elle  n'est  jamais  promise  a 
tous  les  hommes  sans  conditions;  elle  n'est  pas  attendue  de  leur  seule 
vertu,  mais  il  faut  l'intervention  d'un  Dieu.  Un  but  infaillible  n'est 
fixe  religieusement,  soit  a  un  homme,  soit  a  une  socie"te,  qu'autant  que 
Ton  croit  k  Paction  divine  sur  l'ame  ou  sur  le  monde.  Sans  cela  les 
vertus  humaines  individuelles  ne  suffiraient  point,  et  les  vices,  k  plus 
forte  raison,  demeureraient  un  empechement.  La  destinee  en  ce  sens 
ne  peut  done  etre  ni  afnrme'e,  ni  combattue  que  dans  la  sphere  des 
religions  et  de  la  critique  religieuse.  En  un  mot,  ce  ne  saurait  etre  une 
loi  reconnaissable  de  l'histoire.  Mais  ceux  qui  posent  la  destined  tem- 
porelle  sur  une  notion  vague  d'optimisme,  avec  une  idee  vague  de  Dieu 
pour  garant,  ou  plutofc  n'ayant  pour  tout  Dieu  que  le  Progres  meme, 
ceux  qui  d'ailleurs  effacent  l'individu  et  son  vrai  caractere,  qui  mecon- 
naissent  la  liberte  et  ses  ceuvres,  qui  extfhment  le  mal  en  le  declarant 
indifferent  a  l'obtention  definitive  du  bien,  ceux-la  ne  sortent  du 
fatalisme  vulgaire  que  par  une  religiosite  sans  base  oil  manquent 
les  elements  essentiels  de  la  foi  aussi  bien  que  de  la  science  et  de 
l'histoire. 

"Au  premier  apercu,  une  loi  psychologique,  telle- que  je  l'indiquais, 
paraitrait  se  distinguer  du  fatalisme.  Les  produits  de  la  liberte  y 
sont  recue  a  condition  de  se  neutraliser  quand  ils  se  dirigent  en  sens 
contraire  du  bien  et  du  progres ;  et  il  est  tres-vrai  que  l'accumulation 


RENOTJVIER  669 

des  actes  favorables,  tant  pour  le  me'rite  morale  que  pour  les  con- 
naissances  acquises  et  les  oeuvres  realisees,  ehez  les  nations  comme 
chez  les  individus,  est  une  loi  qui  se  oomprend  clairement,  et  d'ail- 
leurs  s'observe  et  se  verifie.  Or,  cette  loi  est  precisement  le  progres. 
II  serait  certain  et  se  continuerait  inddfiniment  si  le  mal  ne  venait 
point  a  la  traverse,  si  les  erreurs,  les  vices,  les  crimes  n'avaient  aussi 
leur  resultats  et  leurs  accumulations,  chez  les  nations  comme  chez  les 
individus.  Mais  la  croissance  du  mal  se  concoit  non  moins  aisdment 
que  la  croissance  du  bien.  Les  exemples  n'en  sont  pas  rares :  on  en 
trouve  sur  toute  echelle,  dans  l'homme,  dans  le  monde,  dans  l'histoire. 
II  m'est  done  impossible  d'admettre  que  les  actes  de  deviation,  en  egard 
a  la  loi  et  aux  Veritas  morales,  soient  necessairement  et  par  leur  nature 
appeles  a  s'annuler  mutuellement  et  a  disparaitre  dans  les  resultantes. 
Au  contraire,  je  crois  avoir  moutre'  comment  les  lois  de  l'habitude 
et  de  la  solidarity  e'tendent,  generalisent  et  prolongent  les  effets  des 
premieres  aberrations  de  la  conscience,  dans  une  serie  quelconque 
de  determinations  iudividuelles  ou  sociales.  L'experience  la  plus  som- 
maire,  un  seul  regard  sur  la  vie  des  peuples  conflrment  suffisament  ici 
l'analyse  psychologique,  pour  tout  esprit  que  ne  dominent  pas  de  fortes 
preventions. 

"II  est  incontestable,  et  e'est  encore  un  fait  qu'on  peut  hardiment 
appeler  historique  et  general,  aussi  bien  que  singulier  et  d'experience 
personelle,  que  ces  premieres  aberrations  dont  je  parle,  n'ont  6t6  epar- 
gnees  aux  auteurs  d'aucune  race.  II  s'ensuit  de  la  que  la  loi  du  progres, 
sur  quelques  pointes  qu'elle  porte,  et  quelles  que  soient  les  nations 
assez  heureuses  pour  s'Stre  affermies  dans  la  voie  du  bien,  ne  saurait 
en  tout  cas  exister  simplement,  naturellement,  et  s'etre  manifested  des 
le  point  de  depart  de  la  conscience.  C'est  au  contraire  une  ddcheance 
morale  qui  s'est  caracterisee  partout  a  l'origine  ou  des  les  premiers 
termes  de  l'exercise  de  l'arbitre  humaine.  Je  suppose,  en  efiet,  que 
l'homme  a  du  commencer  sa  carriere  en  tant  qu'homme,  e'est-a-dire  sous 
la  loi  de  moralite  et  sous  l'impression  de  cette  loi.  Je  le  suppose,  faute 
de  pouvoir  comprendre  un  autre  commencement,  une  autre  nature  pre- 
miere, ou  un  passage  de  cette  premiere  a  une  seconde  nature ;  et  parce 
qu'il  faut  de  toute  necessite,  independamment  de  toute  hypothese  sur 
les  origines  physiques,  envisager  quelque  part  et  de  quelque  maniere  un 
commencement  moral  pour  un  etre  moral,  et  des  donnees  historiques 
primitives  de  conscience,  de  reflexion,  de  raison,  de  justice,  pour  un 
etre  qui  a  developpe  tout  cela  dans  l'histoire." 

M.  Renouvier  has  supplemented  the  exposition  of  his 
analytical  philosophy  of  history  by  an  original,  if  not  unique, 
attempt  to  reconstruct  history  hypothetically,  in  order  to 
illustrate  how  it  might  have  been  quite  other  than,  and  much 
better  than,   it  has   been.     Many   authors   have   delineated 


670  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

Utopias  which  they  located  in  the  future  ;  M.  Renouvier  has 
ventured  on  the  much  more  difficult  but  also  much  more  in- 
structive task  of  picturing  a  Utopia  in  the  past,  and  as  realised 
under  historically  probable  conditions,  while  yet  most  unlike 
what  actually  occurred.  I  refer  to  his  '  Uchronie  (L'Utopie 
dans  l'Histoire),'  1876,  which  bears  the  alternative  and  ex- 
planatory title,  '  An  Historical  and  Apocryphal  Sketch  of 
European  Civilisation,  not  as  it  was,  but  as  it  might  have  been.' 

The  design  of  the  work  is  to  help  its  readers  to  realise  the 
superficiality  and  unreasonableness  of  historical  optimism  and 
necessitarianism.  To  attain  this  end  it  presents  us  with  the 
outline  of  an  apocryphal  or  hypothetical  history,  feigned  to 
have  been  written  at  the  beginning  of  the  seventeenth  century 
by  a  free-thinking  monk  on  the  eve  of  being  burned  by  the 
Inquisition  at  Rome.  In  this  sketch  the  whole  course  of 
European  civilisation,  from  the  age  of  Marcus  Aurelius  to  that 
of  the  supposed  author  of  the  narrative,  is  described  as  having 
been  altogether  different  from  the  course  which  it  actually  took. 
The  ancient  civilisation  which  was,  in  fact,  left  to  decline  and 
die  through  the  unchecked  growth  of  its  corrupt  and  destruc- 
tive tendencies,  is  set  before  us  as  having  been  restored  to 
health  and  vigour  by  the  wise  and  steady  application  of 
remedial  and  reformatory  measures.  Christianity,  which  in 
fact  displaced  it,  but  under  a  debased,  superstitious,  and  in- 
tolerant form,  is  represented  as  having  been  thrown  back  into 
the  East,  and  as  only  readmitted  into  the  West  long  after- 
wards, when  it  could  be  received  in  its  true  character  into  a 
society  ordered  on  principles  of  reason.  The  ideal  of  society 
which  the  best  minds  of  the  present  day  are  still  only  striving 
after,  is  pictured  and  prefigured  as  one  which  had  been  already 
reached.  In  appendices,  dated  1658  and  1709,  and  notes  of  an 
assumed  editor  of  the  present  day,  the  reader  is  reminded  of 
what  was  the  actual  and  "  worse  "  course  of  history,  which  he 
is  expected  to  compare  with  the  hypothetical  and  better  one. 

The  '  Uchronie '  makes  no  pretension  to  disprove  the  doc- 
trines of  historical  necessitarianism  and  optimism.  It  is  ob- 
vious that,  strictly  speaking,  no  doctrine  can  be  either  proved 
or  disproved  by  the  inventions  and  constructions  of  imagina- 
tion.   But  imagination  may,  by  ingeniously  elaborating  and 


EENOUVIER  671 

supporting  in  opposition  to  a  doctrine  which  is  merely  an 
hypothesis,  without  any  real  warrant  in  facts,  a  counter-hypoth- 
esis, cause  the  arbitrariness  and  baselessness  of  a  prevalent 
assumption  to  be  vividly  seen,  and  may  thus  both  effectively 
and  legitimately,  discredit  it.  This  is  what  M.  Renouvier 
has  attempted,*and  accomplished,  in  the  '  Uchronie.' 

I  shall  offer  no  criticisms  on  his  historical  doctrine.  It  is 
one  to  which,  in  all  its  fundamental  principles  and  positions,  I 
assent.  I  do  not  know  any  other  writer  with  whose  views  on 
the  chief  problems  of  historical  philosophy  my  own  are  so 
much  in  accordance.  And  he  has,  in  my  opinion,  rendered 
to  that  philosophy  one  service  so  inestimable,  that  in  any 
account  of  its  development  his  name  deserves  to  be  placed  in 
the  very  foremost  rank  of  its  cultivators.  He  has  shown,  far 
more  profoundly  and  conclusively  than  anyone  else,  the  close- 
ness of  the  connection  between  history  and  morality;  that 
neither  is  intelligible  or  realisable  without  the  other;  that 
history  is  an  ethical  formation  and  morality  an  historical  pro- 
duction. He  has  made  apparent  by  a  critical  analysis  of  the 
historical  process  itself  that  it  is  in  the  exercise  of  rational 
freedom  that  societies,  as  well  as  individuals,  have  risen  or 
sunk,  elevated  or  debased  themselves.  He  has  disclosed  the 
manner  in  which  families,  tribes,  and  nations  have  acquired 
for  themselves  a  common  character,  fixed  habits  and  manners. 
He  has  explained  how  ethic  races  are  formed,  and  of  how  much 
greater  significance  they  are  for  the  understanding  of  history 
than  merely  ethnic  races,  or  the  external  causes  which  originate 
or  modify  these  latter  races.  He  has  refuted,  in  a  way  at  once 
original,  profound,  and  conclusive,  those  theories  which  repre- 
sent history  as  a  mechanically  necessitated  product,  or  an  inev- 
itable dialectic  movement,  or  a  simple  organic  growth,  or  the 
natural  consequence  of  a  struggle  for  existence  between  indi- 
viduals and  societies,  or  a  fundamentally  economic  evolution. 
He  has  proved  it  to  be,  on  the  contrary,  an  essentially  ethical 
creation,  the  formation  of  the  world  of  humanity  by  free  indi- 
vidual wills,  always  conscious  of  moral  law,  while  always 
working  in  given  conditions  of  time  and  space,  of  heredity 
and  solidarity,  and  always  influenced  by  interests  and  pas- 
sions, by  physical  and  spiritual  surroundings. 


672  PHILOSOPHY   OF  HISTORY  IN  PRANCE 

It  would  not  be  appropriate  to  discuss  in  this  work  the 
general  philosophy  of  M.  Renouvier. 

His  teaching  for  a  long  time  attracted  little  attention. 
During  the  last  twenty  years  its  influence  on  the  philosophi- 
cal, theological,  and  political  thought  of  France  has  been  con- 
siderable ;  and  it  can  hardly  fail  to  increase.  "The  number  of 
what  would  be  called  his  disciples  is  not  large,  and  may  never 
be  so.  M.  Pillon  has  most  completely  assimilated  his  doctrine, 
and  is  a  very  able  expositor  of  it.  In  part  and  in  applications 
it  has  been  widely  adopted.  M.  Lavisse's  '  Vue  g6ne"rale 
de  l'Histoire  politique  de  l'Europe  '  may  be  referred  to  as  a 
fine  exemplification  of  its  principles  in  the  purely  historical 
sphere. 

Little  has  been  done  for  Historic  in  France  during  recent 
years.  M.  Tardif's  '  Notions  FAe"mentaires  de  Critique  His- 
torique,'  1883,  presents  us  with  a  mere  outline  of  the  subject. 
M.  Rabier,  in  the  second  volume  of  his  '  Lecons  de  Philoso- 
phie,' 1  has  treated  with  characteristic  judiciousness  of  "  tes- 
timony," "historical  criticism,"  and  "the  method  of  social 
science  "  ;  but  he  has  not  left  the  beaten  path  and  attempted 
to  explore  new  territory.  M.  Seignobos,  in  his  articles  on 
"  Les  conditions  psychologiques  de  la  connaissance  en  histoire," 
in  the  '  Revue  Philosophique,' 2  has  made  a  careful  study  of  the 
problem,  How  is  any  particular  historical  proposition  to  be 
reached?  In  dealing  with  it  he  inquires  as  to  (1)  the  character 
of  historical  knowledge,  (2)  its  materials,  (3)  the  conditions 
necessary  to  disengage  any  historical  proposition,  (4)  the  con- 
ditions necessary  for  attaining  a  proposition  which  is  certain, 
(5)  what  vices  of  method  lead  to  false  or  uncertain  proposi- 
tions, and  (6)  in  what  sense  history  is  verifiable.  Thus,  al- 
though he  excludes  from  consideration  the  question  as  to  how 
general  propositions  in  history  are  to  be  attained,  his  investi- 
gation is  not  wanting  either  in  breadth  or  interest.  He  reaches 
the  following  conclusions.  "  Historical  knowledge  is  an  indi- 
rect knowledge  only  attainable  by  reasoning.  The  documents 
which  supply  the  ctarting-points  of  the  reasonings  only  make 
known  to  us  psychological  operations.  History  arrives  at  a 
conclusion  only  through  the  reconstitution  of  these  operations. 

1  Ch.  xvii.,  pp.  316-345.  2  Douzifeme  Ann^e,  Nos.  7  and  8. 


CEITICIST   SCHOOL  673 

It  can  do  so  only  by  means  of  a  series  of  psychological  analyses 
and  of  analogical  reasonings  of  which  the  major  premisses  are 
borrowed  from  descriptive  psychology.  Almost  all  faults  of 
method  proceed  from  errors  of  psychology."  M.  Seignobos 
has  clearly  recognised  the  importance  of  the  study  of  the  his- 
torical method.  "  Almost  all  that  we  know  of  men  and  of 
societies  is  reducible  to  historical  knowledge.  The  historical 
method  not  only  rules  in  the  sciences  called  historical  which 
operate  on  ancient  phenomena,  but  in  all  the  psychological 
and  social  sciences,  because  they  operate  on  fleeting  and  com- 
plex phenomena.  It  is  necessary  not  only  to  the  historians 
of  the  past,  but  to  every  one  who  studies  human  societies. 
History  is  only  entitled  to  a  small  place  in  the  whole  of 
knowledge ;  but  the  logic  of  the  sciences  should  give  a  large 
place  to  the  study  of  the  historical  method,  for  it  is  the  method 
of  all  indirect  knowledge."  I  cannot  entirely  subscribe  to  these 
words,  inasmuch  as  it  seems  to  me  that  history,  properly  un- 
derstood, is  coextensive  with  the  historical  method ;  but  then- 
author  is  entirely  right  as  to  the  wide  range  of  the  historical 
method,  and  the  importance  of  its  study.  It  is  deplorable 
that  historians  should  show  so  little  interest  as  they  actually 
manifest  in  "  the  logic  of  the  sciences,"  or  even  of  the  science 
which  they  themselves  cultivate.  It  is  no  valid  excuse  for 
them  that  almost  all  other  classes  of  scientists  are  in  the  same 
respect  chargeable  with  the  same  fault.1 

1  In  the  writings  of  M.  Fouillee  and  of  the  late  M.  Guyan  an  interesting  form 
of  criticist  thought  is  allied  with  remarkably  original  and  ingenious  sociological 
speculations.  They  are  rich  in  fresh  and  suggestive  views,  brilliantly  expounded, 
relating  to  the  evolution  of  morals,  law,  art,  and  religion,  and  undoubtedly  fall- 
ing within  the  sphere  of  historical  philosophy.  My  not  attempting  to  give  in  this 
place  any  account  of  these  views  is  not  owing  to  want  of  appreciation  of  their 
importance,  but  because  I  wish  to  contrast  and  compare  the  most  distinctive  and 
fundamental  of  them  with  the  correlative  evolutionist  conclusions  of  Mr.  Herbert 
Speneer. 

M.  Tarde,  well  known  by  his  studies  in  criminology  and  the  philosophy  of  penal 
law,  has  also  published  a  most  original  and  ingenious  treatise  on  Sociology, 
entitled  'Les  Lois  de  l'Imitation,'  1890.  He  has  dedicated  it  to  the  memory  of 
Cournot,  and  he  is,  although  not  a  pupil  or  disciple  of  that  author,  a  thinker  of  the 
same  order.  He  seems  to  me  to  have  been  very  fairly  successful  in  his  endeavour 
to  "delineate  a  General  Sociology  of  which  the  laws  are  applicable  to  all  societies 
actual,  past,  or  possible,  as  the  laws  of  General  Physiology  are  to  all  species  liv- 
ing, extinct,  or  conceivable."  He  has  at  least  shown  that  there  is  another  sort  of 
Sociology  than  the  merely  descriptive  study  commonly  so  called.  In  reducing  the 
social  world  to  imitations  and  their  laws,  and  history  to  initiatives  which  have 


674  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   FRANCE 

been  the  most  imitated,  he  has  begun  to  render  to  Sociology  a  service  of  the  same 
kind  as  the  associationists  have  rendered  to  Psychology.  It  is  to  be  hoped  that 
he  may  himself  follow  up  the  investigations  which  he  has  begun,  and  that  he  may 
also  have  not  a  few  imitators.  I  shall  not  now  summarise  the  views  which  he  has 
set  forth  in  his  sociological  treatise,  most  able  and  valuable  although  it  be,  as,  if 
permitted  to  carry  this  work  to  completion,  I  shall  have  to  take  special  account 
of  them  when  I  attempt  to  determine  the  relation  of  Sociology  to  History  and  its 
Philosophy. 

The  works  of  the  late  M.  Fustel  de  Coulanges  are  among  the  most  brilliant 
exemplifications  of  a  strictly  critical  and  historical  method.  They  are  eminently 
worthy  of  study  even  from  the  merely  methodological  point  of  view.  As  regards 
their  general  characteristics,  and  the  light  which  they  have  thrown  on  the  trans- 
formations of  society  in  general,  and  of  the  early  history  of  French  institutions 
in  particular,  it  may  be  enough  to  refer  to  the  Notices  of  M.  Sorel  in  vol.  35,  and 
of  M.  Jules  Simon  in  vol.  37  of  the  '  Travaux  de  l'Acade'mie  des  Sciences  Morales 
et  Politiques.' 


CHAPTER    XII 

HISTORICAL    PHILOSOPHY   IN    BELGIUM    AND     SWITZERLAND 

I 

The  geologists  of  Belgium  have  shown  that  their  country 
had  human  inhabitants  many  thousands  of  years  before  history 
began  to  be  recorded  in  writing.  When  Caesar  conquered 
Gaul,  the  most  powerful  and  warlike  portion  of  its  population 
were  the  Belgians,  comprising  a  number  of  peoples,  partly  of 
Celtic  and  partly  of  Teutonic  origin,  and  occupying  the  terri- 
tory north  of  the  Seine  and  the  Marne.  Every  part  of  the 
soil  of  the  Belgium  of  to-day  is  historic  ground ;  its  towns  and 
provinces  have  had  long,  changeful,  and  eventful  histories, 
and  have  not  lacked  chroniclers  to  record  what  happened  in 
them  worthy  of  remembrance.  The  historical  spirit  was  early 
awakened  in  Belgium.  I  have  already  had  occasion  to  refer 
to  Eginhard  and  Suger,  to  Froissart  and  Comines  ;  but  Bel- 
gium can  claim  them  at  least  as  justly  as  France.  Here,  how- 
ever, I  shall  not  go  farther  back  than  to  the  origin  of  the 
kingdom  of  Belgium ;  and  that  is  of  quite  recent  date. 

In  1830  the  provinces  of  which  it  is  composed  seceded  from 
the  Netherlands,  and  succeeded  in  becoming  an  independent 
state.  This  result  was  accomplished  through  a  combination 
of  clericals  and  liberals ;  and  the  Constitution  of  the  new  king- 
dom was  necessarily  a  compromise  between  two  irreconcilable 
parties  which  have  since  been  in  constant  and  often  keen  con- 
flict. It  was  a  Constitution  framed  with  wisdom ;  one  which 
safeguarded  the  rights  of  individuals  and  of  associations,  and 
which  allowed  extensive  powers  of  self-government  to  com- 
munes and  provinces;  and  although  it  has  been  repeatedly 
attacked,  and  been  often  in  serious  danger,  it  has,  owing  to 
the  intelligence  and  patriotism  of  Leopold  I.  and  Leopold  II., 
the  sagacity  of  its  political  leaders,  and  the  general  good  sense 

675 


676  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   BELGIUM 

of  an  exceptionally  enlightened  and  energetic  people,  remained 
unviolated.  Under  it  the  nation  has  not  only  prospered 
greatly,  but  greatly  distinguished  itself  in  all  the  chief  depart- 
ments of  human  activity. 

The  Belgian  people  is  composed  of  two  races,  the  one 
mainly  of  Celtic  and  the  other  mainly  of  Teutonic  extraction. 
It  has  three  languages :  Flemish,  closely  allied  to  Dutch ; 
Walloon,  an  old  dialect  of  French;  and  French.  In  all  these 
languages  there  is  a  considerable  amount  of  literature,  but 
only  in  French  is  there  any  literature  of  the  kind  which  here 
concerns  us.  Belgian  thought  has  been  greatly  affected  both 
by  French  and  German  influences,  but  more  by  the  former 
than  by  the  latter.  Belgium  has  offered  a  safe  asylum  to  the 
victims  of  party  violence  who  have  fled  to  it  from  other  lands, 
and  a  favourable  soil  for  the  propagation  of  new  ideas  and  the 
application  of  new  systems  of  a  social  and  practical  character. 
Speculative  philosophy  has  not  found  in  it  a  congenial  home. 
Owing  to  its  connection  with  Holland,  Belgium  started  well 
as  regards  education ;  and  it  continues  to  be  a  relatively  well- 
educated  country,  although  instruction  is  too  much  under  the 
control  of  the  clergy,  and  the  extent  of  illiteracy  is  consider- 
able. It  has  numerous  gymnasia  and  diocesan  seminaries, 
and  four  universities  —  Ghent,  Liege,  Brussels,  and  Louvain ; 
the  two  former  being  state  institutions ;  that  of  Brussels  inde- 
pendent both  of  Church  and  State ;  and  that  of  Louvain  under 
the  direction  of  the  episcopate.  In  Ghent  history  is  taught 
by  seven  professors,  in  Liege  by  five,  in  Brussels  by  four,  and 
in  Louvain  by  three,  exclusive  of  those  who  teach  history  of 
philosophy,  of  literature,  of  law,  &e.  Historical  research  has 
been,  like  science,  literature,  and  art,  greatly  indebted  to  the 
Royal  Academy  of  Belgium.  The  Roman  Catholic  Church 
contains  the  vast  majority  of  the  professing  Christians  of  Bel- 
gium ;  but  its  power  is  to  a  large  extent  counterbalanced  by 
the  prevalence  of  religious  rationalism  and  scepticism.  The 
most  enlightened  and  energetic  portion  of  the  nation  is  anti- 
clerical. Nowhere  has  the  religious  question  been  a  more 
burning  question  than  in  Belgium;  and  nowhere  has  history 
been  more  discussed  in  connection  with  it.  That  Socialism 
should  have  widely  spread  in  a  country  so  densely  peopled 


ALTMEYER  677 

as  Belgium,  and  with  such  large  and  concentrated  masses 
of  poorly  paid  workmen,  is  altogether  natural.  It  had 
adherents  among  those  who  founded  the  new  kingdom ;  has 
been  engaged  ever  since  in  more  or  less  successful  propagand- 
ism;  and  is  very  prevalent  and  active  at  present.  I  have 
thus  referred  to  these  facts,  elementary  although  they  be, 
because  they  are  really  those  which  have  had  most  influence 
on  the  development  of  historical  thought  in  Belgium. 

There  has  been  displayed  in  Belgium  since  1830  remarkable 
activity  in  the  department  of  historiography,  and  especially  of 
national  historiography.  A  comprehensive  and  graphic  picture 
of  that  activity  and  its  results  has  been  drawn  by  the  skilful 
hand  of  M.  Ch.  Potvin  in  '  Cinquante  Ans  de  Liberte" '  (torn, 
iv.)  ;  and  to  it  I  must  be  content  simply  to  refer  my  readers.1 

The  first  writer  in  Belgium  to  draw  general  attention  to  the 
philosophy  of  history  was  J.  J.  Altmeyer  (1804-75).  When 
the  University  of  Brussels  was  created  he  was  appointed 
professor  of  history;  and  in  1836  he  published  a  brief  'Intro- 
duction a  l'fitude  philosophique  de  l'histoire  de  l'humaniteV 
It  consists  of  a  discourse  supplemented  with  notes.  He  him- 
self speaks  of  the  discourse  as  "  ce  chant " ;  and  it  is  certainly 
of  a  rather  lyrical  and  militant  strain.  It  recalls  in  spirit, 
content,  and  form  Michelet's  'Introduction  to  Universal 
History.'  It  also  shows  traces  of  the  influence  of  Vico, 
Ballanche,  Buchez,  Conside"rant,  Lamennais,  Gerbet,  and  other 
historical  philosophers.  "  History,"  he  says,  "  is  the  dialectic 
of  the  spirit,  the  universal  judgment,  the  story  of  the  gradual 
progress  of  humanity  towards  its  physical,  intellectual,  and 
moral  amelioration.  This  progress  has  caused  a  struggle 
between  two  hostile  elements,  spirit  and  matter,  moral  force 
and  brutal  force ;  elements  which  combat,  dethrone,  and  sub- 
jugate each  other.  This  struggle  is  as  old  as  the  world;  yet 
it  is  not  infinite ;  but  no  mortal  can  pretend  to  predict  when 

1 '  Cinquante  Ans  de  Liberte",'  4  vols.,  1881-82,  shows  what  had  been  accom- 
plished in  Belgium  from  1830  to  1880  in  all  the  chief  departments  of  human 
activity.  The  scheme  of  distribution  is  as  follows :  Vol.  i.,  Political  Life,  by  Count 
Goblet  d'Alviella ;  Education,  by  Emile  Greyson ;  Political  Economy,  by  Julian 
Schaar.  Vol.  ii.,  Physical  and  Mathematical  Sciences,  by  Ch.  and  E.  Lagrange ; 
Natural  Sciences,  by  A.  Gilkinet.  Vol.  iii.,  Painting  and  Sculpture,  by  C.  Lermon- 
aier;  Music,  by  Ad.  Samuel.    Vol.  iv.,  History  of  Literature,  by  Ch.  Potvin. 


678  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   BELGIUM 

it  will  cease ;  that  is  covered  with  the  veil  of  the  Egyptian 
Isis."  In  this  work  Altmeyer  shows  no  evidence  of  ac- 
quaintance with  the  doctrine  of  Krause,  to  which  he  was  so 
soon  to  become  a  convert ;  but  he  shows  a  certain  prepared- 
ness of  spirit  for  its  reception  in  his  ardent  faith  in  a  divine 
kingdom  of  harmony  to  result  from  realisation  of  the  provi- 
dential plan  which  pervades  history.  "  The  highest  degree  of 
perfection,"  he  says,  "  to  which  man  is  destined,  arises  from 
the  complete  and  free  development  of  his  personality  in  the 
kingdom  of  truth,  beauty,  and  goodness,  and  in  the  closest 
union  with  his  fellow-men.  The  principle  of  perfectibility 
must,  therefore,  introduce  a  state  in  which  matter  and  spirit, 
reconciled,  reunited,  and  commingled,  will  form  a  beautiful, 
grand,  and  finished  harmony;  in  which  all  specialities  will 
find  their  object,  and  occupy  their  proper  sphere  of  activity ; 
in  which  men,  instead  of  exhausting  their  forces  in  fighting 
one  another,  will  employ  them  to  complete  the  subjugation  of 
nature ;  in  which  the  injury  done  to  one,  being  of  advantage 
to  no  other,  will  be  regarded  as  injurious  to  the  whole  society; 
in  which  the  annihilation  of  evil  will  put  an  end  to  the  war 
between  good  and  evil,  a  war  of  which  there  will  survive  only 
a  generous  emulation  among  the  good  when  there  is  oppor- 
tunity for  doing  good ;  a  state,  in  short,  of  rest  which  will  not 
be  inaction,  and  a  state  of  action  which  will  not  be  tumultu- 
ous agitation." 

Four  years  later  Altmeyer  published  a  larger  work,  his 
'  Cours  de  Philosophie  de  l'Histoire,'  1840.  It  is  composed 
of  fifteen  lectures,  which  were  delivered  before  500  hearers. 
It  is  said,  there  would  have  been  3000  of  an  audience  if  a 
large  enough  hall  could  have  been  found.  The  interest  in 
them  thus  manifested  was,  doubtless,  partly  due  to  the  fact 
that  the  war  between  liberalism  and  clericalism  was  at  that 
time  intensely  keen,  and  had  penetrated  into  the  universities, 
so  that  Brussels  was  arrayed  against  Louvain,  "chair  against 
chair,  tribune  against  tribune."  Between  the  '  Introduction ' 
and  the  '  Cours '  there  was  one  great  difference,  owing  to 
the  fact  that  in  the  interval  between  their  publication 
Altmeyer  had  been  completely  converted  by  his  colleague, 
the  celebrated  German  jurist,  Henry  Ahrens,  to  Krauseanism. 


ALTMEYER — TIBERGHIEN  679 

The  latter  work,  accordingly,  is  essentially  an  exposition  of 
the  Krausean  theory  of  human  development,  and  a  detailed 
application  of  it  to  the  stage  of  development  represented  by 
the  oriental  world.  In  the  first  lecture  he  himself  thus 
speaks:  "The  theory,  gentlemen,  of  which  I  have  just 
expounded  the  first  principles,  and  which  I  shall  have  the 
honour  to  develop  to  you  in  its  entirety,  before  applying  it 
to  the  special  facts,  belongs,  in  substance,  to  a  philosopher 
still  little  known,  but  the  greatest  that  can  be  cited  since 
Leibniz ;  to  Krause,  whose  high  significance  my  honourable 
colleague,  M.  Ahrens,  has  made  known  and  felt.  Great 
theologians,  illustrious  philosophers,  from  Bossuet  to  Hegel, 
have  treated  eloquently,  profoundly,  one  or  several  parts  of 
the  philosophy  of  history;  but  in  their  writings  you  will 
vainly  seek  a  complete  system,  a  satisfactory  theory,  on  the 
development  of  humanity.  Krause  is  the  first  who  has  laid 
down  a  priori  the  laws  to  which  humanity  is  providentially 
submitted,  and  which  it  must  accomplish  in  the  full  exercise 
of  its  freedom ;  and  he  has  shown  how  these  laws  are  related 
to  the  general  movement  of  humanity.  When  this  theoretical 
exposition  is  concluded,  we  shall  set  out  on  our  march  from 
the  high  regions  of  Asia,  and  try  to  follow  step  by  step  in  the 
path  of  the  human  race,  across  time  and  space,  along  the 
movement  of  ideas,  passions,  and  facts;  confronting  with 
the  discoveries  of  Krause  the  development  of  the  peoples,  and 
in  verifying  them  if  we  can,  to  recognise  a  new  title  of  glory 
in  a  man  who  has  already  so  many  others,  and,  in  particular, 
that  of  having  lived  a  martyr  to  his  convictions."  The  first 
eight  lectures  contain  the  exposition  of  the  theoretical  part 
of  the  Krausean  philosophy  of  history,  and  the  seven  which 
follow  inquire  as  to  the  truth  of  it  so  far  as  that  can  be 
ascertained  from  the  history  of  the  Asiatic  people.  A  com- 
plete philosophical  survey  of  history  was  contemplated,  but 
the  intention  was  not  realised. 

The  most  eminent  Belgian  representative  of  the  school  of 
Krause  is  M.  Guillaume  Tiberghien.  He  was  born  in  1819; 
was  a  pupil  of  Ahrens  and  Altmeyer ;  and  as  professor  of 
philosophy  has  long  adorned  the  University  of  Brussels.  He 
has  published  treatises  on  almost  all  the  chief  departments 


680  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN  BELGIUM 

of  philosophy  —  metaphysics,  logic,  psychology,  ethics,  and  the 
theory  of  religion.  They  are  characterised  by  clearness  and 
consistency  of  thought,  and  by  elegance  and  precision  of  lan- 
guage. Most  of  them  have  been  translated  into  Spanish,  and 
some  of  them  into  Portuguese.  He  has  greatly  contributed  to 
the  diffusion  of  the  principles  of  Krause,  not  only  in  Belgium, 
but  also  in  the  Iberian  peninsula.  No  one,  indeed,  has  pre- 
sented the  doctrine  of  Krause  in  a  more  attractive  form. 

In  his  '  Introduction  a  la  Philosophie  '  there  is  a  masterly 
sketch  of  the  philosophy  of  history  as  it  is  to  be  seen  in  the 
light  of  the  philosophy  of  Krause.  All  the  chief  traits  of  the 
movement  of  humanity,  when  so  contemplated,  are  there  admi- 
rably indicated  in  the  brief  compass  of  150  pages.  I  can,  of 
course,  here  merely  refer  to  them,  as  I  must  reserve  what  I 
have  to  say  of  the  Krausean  philosophy  of  history  until  I  reach 
Krause  himself.  It  is  not  inappropriate,  however,  to  add  that, 
both  in  the  work  just  named  and  in  his  celebrated  'Essai 
the'orique  et  historique  sur  la  Ge'ne'ration  des  Connaissances 
Humaines,'  M.  Tiberghien  has  striven  to  show  by  a  survey  and 
criticism  of  all  the  chief  systems  of  philosophy  that  that  of 
Krause  alone  satisfies  all  the  requirements  of  science  and  all 
the  aspirations  of  the  age  which  has  at  length  arrived,  the 
age  of  the  maturity  of  humanity,  the  age  of  harmony  and  of 
organisation. 

I  now  pass  to  one  whose  work  must  be  longer  under  our 
consideration.  Francois  Laurent  was  born  at  Luxembourg  in 
1810 ;  studied  at  the  Universities  of  Louvain  and  Liege ;  was 
appointed  professor  at  Ghent  in  1836  ;  published  from  1 850 
to  1870  the  eighteen  volumes  of  'fitudes  sur  l'histoire  de 
I'humaniteY  to  which  he  owes  his  fame  as  an  historical  philos- 
opher, and  from  1869  to  1879  the  thirty-two-volumed  work, 
'  Principes  de  Droit  Civil ' ;  likewise,  a  '  Cours  e'le'mentaire  de 
Droit  Civil,'  4  vols.,  *  Droit  Civil  International,'  8  vols.,  and 
numerous  pamphlets,  mostly  of  a  polemical  character.  His 
activity  was  not  confined  to  his  labours  as  professor  and  pub- 
licist, but  showed  itself  also  in  those  of  a  communal  coun- 
cillor, an  organiser  of  workmen's  societies,  and  a  director  of 
evening  schools.  Singularly  disinterested  and  self-sacrificing, 
he  lived  almost  as  an  anchorite,  dressed  almost  as  a  peasant, 


LAUfiENT  681 

and  devoted  his  entire  time  and  strength  to  propagate  his  faith 
and  to  promote  the  good  of  his  fellow-men.  He  retired  from 
his  professorship  in  1882,  and  died  in  1887.1 

The  work  of  Laurent  with  which  we  are  concerned  is  his 
'  Studies  on  the  History  of  Humanity.'  Its  publication,  as  has 
been  already  stated,  extended  over  twenty  years.  Its  author  was 
privileged  to  study  every  stage  of  human  history  known  to  us 
through  written  documents  leisurely  and  long  enough  to  enable 
him  to  master  the  contents  of  the  original  sources  of  information, 
and  of  the  principal  treatises  of  the  more  eminent  scholars  of 
all  times  and  countries ;  to  trace,  age  after  age,  with  indepen- 
dence and  profundity,  the  development  of  society,  and  of  the 
ideas  most  influential  in  preserving  and  regulating  it ;  and  to 
communicate  to  the  world  the  results  of  his  researches  and 
reflections  in  a  long  series  of  volumes,  each  devoted  to  some 
great  epoch  of  time  —  the  East,  Greece,  Rome,  Christianity, 
the  Barbarians  and  Catholicism,  the  Papacy  and  the  Empire, 
Feudalism  and  the  Church,  the  Reformation,  the  Wars  of  Re- 
ligion, &c.  In  this  vast  monument  of  toil  and  talent,  moral 
earnestness,  independence  of  judgment,  and  diligence  in  re- 
search are  conspicuous  qualities ;  and  equally  so  is  the  desire  to 
comprehend  the  meaning  and  purpose  of  facts,  to  discover  the 
ideas  which  underlie  events.  In  facts  by  themselves,  facts  out 
of  which  no  thoughts  can  be  extracted,  M.  Laurent  manifested 
no  interest ;  in  all  facts,  on  the  other  hand,  which  could  be 
seen  to  have  influenced  the  essential  destiny  of  man,  to  have 
helped  or  hindered  the  human  race  in  its  struggle  for  freedom 
and  justice,  he  showed  an  almost  too  passionate  interest. 

The  last  volume  of  the  work  is  entitled  '  La  Philosophic  de 
l'Histoire.'  It  is  partly  a  resumS  of  the  volumes  which  pre- 
ceded it.  It  also  expounds  the  general  doctrine  involved  and 
established  in  those  volumes.  That  it  is  thus  the  summary 
and  conclusion  of  such  a  series  of  elaborate  and  masterly 
"  studies  "  confers  on  it  an  authority  which  it  could  not  have 
possessed  had  it  stood  alone.  It  not  only  speaks  for  itself,  but 
all  its  predecessors  speak  for  it  and  through  it.     The  same  cir- 

1  See  the  article  of  M.  Ernest  Nys  on  "  Francois  Laurent,  sa  vie  et  ses  oeuvres," 
in  the  '  Rev.  de  Droit  International,'  t.  xix.  M.  Nys  is  himself  the  author  of 
learned  '  Kecherches  sur  l'Histoire  de  Droit,'  of  interest  to  students  of  the  history 
of  historical  philosophy. 


682  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY  IN   BELGIUM 

cumstance,  however,  which  greatly  enhances  its  value  in  one 
respect,  has  not  proved  favourable  to  it  in  another ;  and  is, 
indeed,  the  chief  reason  why  it  falls  so  far  short  of  being  a 
philosophy  of  history.  M.  Laurent's  work  has  for  alternative 
title  '  History  of  the  Law  of  Nations  and  of  International 
Relations.'  That  title  is  too  narrow,  and  the  author  did  well 
to  take  the  more  general  one  of  '  Studies  on  the  History  of 
Humanity';  still  these  "studies"  are  mainly  on  the  moral 
history  of  humanity,  on  its  progress  in  the  knowledge  and 
practice  of  justice  and  benevolence,  on  the  growth  of  man's 
insight  into  and  reverence  for  the  law  of  conscience  both  as 
regards  himself  and  his  fellow-men.  Now,  notwithstanding  its 
title,  M.  Laurent's  '  Philosophy  of  History '  is  so  much  the 
summary  of  the  "  studies  "  that  it  deals  exclusively  with  the 
same  phase  of  human  development,  and  overlooks  the  scientific, 
the  aesthetic,  and  the  industrial  evolution  of  society.  It  is, 
consequently,  not,  properly  speaking,  the  philosophy  of  history, 
not  the  scientific  comprehension  of  history  as  a  whole. 

It  was  doubtless,  in  part  at  least,  owing  to  the  same  circum- 
stance, that  M.  Laurent  made  no  attempt  to  determine  the 
problem  of  the  philosophy  of  history,  to  define  or  describe  what 
that  philosophy  ought  to  do ;  none  to  lay  for  it  a  foundation  in 
the  science  of  human  nature,  or  even  to  indicate  its  relationship 
to  the  science  of  human  nature ;  none  to  fix  its  general  position 
among  the  sciences ;  and  none  to  ascertain  the  methods  required 
for  its  successful  study.  These  are  serious  omissions  in  a  work 
professing  to  be  a  philosophy  of  history.  They  are  explained 
in  the  case  of  M.  Laurent's  volume  by  its  author  having  pro- 
ceeded at  once  to  enunciate  the  general  theory  which  had 
underlain  and  directed  his  anterior  labours. 

In  the  Introduction  he  expounds  his  own  views  regarding 
the  immanence  of  God  in  humanity,  the  coexistence  of  divine 
Providence  and  human  liberty,  and  the  reality  of  progress, 
moral  and  religious  progress  not  excluded;  and  attacks  the 
views  of  those  who  would  banish  God  from  history,  or  acknow- 
ledge the  working  of  the  devil  in  history.  He  argues  that 
there  can  be  no  philosophy  of  history  unless  it  be  admitted  that 
God  is  present  in  the  minds  and  hearts  of  all  men,  controls  and 
guides  the  entire  series  of  events,  and,  while  respecting  human 


LAURENT  683 

freedom,  is  continually  raising  the  human  race  to  higher  stages 
of  being.  Naturally  we  ask,  —  Does  not  history,  then,  prove 
these  truths?  And  to  our  astonishment  we  find  that  M. 
Laurent  not  only  believes  it  does,  but  believes  that  these  truths 
•with  their  proofs  actually  constitute  the  philosophy  of  history. 
Why  the  philosophy  of  history  should  presuppose  what  it  can 
prove,  or  even  how  it  can  presuppose  what  it  is  the  proof  of,  he 
does  not  explain.  And,  in  fact,  his  conception  of  the  relation 
of  theology  or  theodicy  to  the  science  of  history  appears  to  be 
just  the  reverse  of  the  truth.  He  represents  the  science  of 
history  as  a  department  of  natural  theology,  when  all  that  can 
be  properly  maintained  is,  that  there  is  a  department  of  natural 
theology  the  truths  of  which  may  be  legitimately  inferred  from 
the  findings  of  the  science  of  history.  The  science  of  itself  — 
i.e.,  in  its  strictest  and  narrowest  sense,  or  as  distinguished  from 
the  philosophy  of  history,  — •  neither  requires  nor  admits  of  any 
theological  presuppositions. 

M.  Laurent  conceives  of  the  philosophy  of  history  as  a 
theodicy.  His  point  of  view  is  not  the  scientific  as  exclusive 
of  the  religious,  but  the  religious  as  inclusive  of  the  scientific. 
It  may,  perhaps,  be  too  little  scientific,  too  much  religious. 
The  principle  of  final  causes  was  a  ruling  one  in  Laurent's 
mind.  Each  event,  each  institution,  suggests  to  him  the  ques- 
tions —  What  was  the  design  of  it  ?  What  did  man  intend  by 
it  ?  What  did  God  intend  by  it  ?  The  ideas  of  efficient  causa- 
tion and  of  law  are  much  less  prominent.  He  is  more  concerned 
to  know  why  events  happened  than  how  they  happened.  He 
does  not  neglect  to  inquire  into  how  great  social  changes  were 
effected,  but  his  chief  interest  in  the  inquiry  is  that  he  may  be 
helped  thereby  to  understand  why  these  changes  were  brought 
about,  what  their  place  and  significance  were  in  the  providential 
plan  of  the  universe. 

It  is  altogether  with  reference  to  his  own  historical  theodicy 
that  Laurent  treats  of  the  historical  theories  of  his  predecessors. 
He  makes  no  attempt  to  give  any  general  survey  of  the  course 
of  the  philosophy  of  history,  or  even  any  general  estimate  of 
the  chief  systems  of  that  philosophy.  He  simply  chooses  cer- 
tain representative  specimens  of  those  historical  doctrines  which 
imply  the  truth  of  miracle,  chance,  or  fatalism  ;  which  deny,  ex- 


684  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   BELGIUM 

plicitly  or  implicitly,  the  immanence  of  God,  and  the  progres- 
sive, providential,  non-miraculous  education  of  man  through 
the  Spirit  of  God  acting  on  reason  and  free-will ;  and  these  he 
subjects  to  a  severe  and  hostile  criticism.  In  Bossuet  he  sees 
only  an  advocate  of  the  miraculous  government  of  Providence ; 
in  Vico,  of  ancient  fatalism ;  in  Voltaire  and  Frederick  II.,  of 
chance ;  in  Montesquieu,  of  the  fatalism  of  climate ;  in  Herder, 
of  that  of  nature ;  in  Renan,  of  that  of  race ;  in  Thiers,  of 
revolutionary  fatalism ;  in  Hegel,  of  pantheistic  fatalism ;  in 
Comte,  of  positivist  fatalism ;  and  in  Buckle,  of  the  fatalism 
of  general  laws.  He  regards  them  only,  in  other  words,  as  the 
teachers  of  false  and  mischievous  doctrines ;  and  as  such  he 
assails  them  earnestly  and  indignantly.  I  fully  admit  that  he 
had  a  right  so  to  proceed.  I  regard  the  notion,  at  present 
so  prevalent,  that  all  criticism  ought  to  be  sympathetic,  and 
occupy  itself  chiefly  in  the  discovery  of  merits  or  excuses  as  a 
superficial  conceit  of  a  literary  dilettanteism,  itself  the  product 
of  unbelief  in  truth  and  morality.  But  it  is  not  to  be  denied 
that  an  exclusively  negative  and  polemic  criticism,  however 
legitimate  or  even  necessary  it  may  sometimes  be,  has  always 
its  dangers.  It  is  apt  to  be  passionate  and  extreme;  to  over- 
look conditions  and  limitations  which  ought  to  be  taken  into 
account ;  to  fancy  it  finds  error  where  there  is  none,  or  at  least 
more  of  it  than  there  is.  It  seems  to  me  that  this  is  to  a 
considerable  extent  true  of  Laurent's  criticism  of  the  historical 
theories  which  he  examines.  At  the  same  time,  it  is  thoroughly 
honest  and  remarkably  able  criticism. 

He  proceeds  to  attempt  to  prove,  by  an  examination  of  the 
facts  of  history  as  a  whole,  that  God  has  been  ever  present 
therein  in  wisdom,  and  justice,  and  power.  Taking  up  in  suc- 
cession antiquity,  Christianity,  and  the  barbarian  invasionst 
feudalism,  the  Reformation,  and  the  Revolution,  he  strives  to 
show  in  each  case  that  what  man  willed  was  not  what  God 
willed,  and  has  accomplished,  but  something  lower,  something 
less,  if  not  even  something  contrary.  Man  has  been  continually 
growing  in  the  knowledge  of  God's  will ;  but  even  yet  he  has 
no  more  than  a  vague  and  dim  perception  of  the  general  plan 
of  His  providence,  although  in  looking  back  he  can  clearly 
enough  see  there  was  a  plan  underlying  events  which  those 


LAURENT  685 

who  took  part  in  them  never  dreamt  of,  being  engrossed  in  far 
other  plans  of  their  own.  Laurent  has  attempted  to  establish 
this  by  an  examination  of  the  actual  facts  of  history,  and  by 
what  is  entitled  to  be  regarded  as  a  most  minute  and  searching 
examination  of  these  facts,  seeing  that  the  argument  summed 
up  in  book  i.  chap.  ii.  of  this  eighteenth  volume  has  been 
carried  through  all  the  previous  seventeen  volumes.  In  doing 
so  he  seems  to  me  to  have  made  a  most  valuable  contribution 
not  only  to  historical  philosophy  but  also  to  natural  theology ; 
to  have  successfully  shown,  what  professed  natural  theologians 
have  so  strangely  overlooked,  that  not  less  than  the  heavens 
and  earth  —  nay,  that  much  more  than  either  —  does  history 
declare  the  glory  of  God. 

The  conclusiveness  of  his  argumentation  has  been  chal- 
lenged by  Professor  Jiirgen  Bona  Meyer,  but  on  quite  in- 
sufficient grounds.1  The  first  of  the  two  objections  urged 
by  the  professor  is  as  follows :  "  The  fact  that  the  conse- 
quences of  human  actions  are  frequently  not  those  which  the 
agents  willed,  and  that  in  virtue  of  this  contradiction  between 
the  willed  and  the  accomplished,  men  obtain  against  their 
wills  what  is  best  for  them,  is  capable  of  explanation  from 
the  natural  reaction  and  counteraction  of  the  appropriately 
arranged  forces  of  the  physical  and  moral  worlds.  The  ex- 
amination of  history  enables  us  only  to  recognise  this  natural 
antagonism  of  the  forces  which  it  comprehends  ;  and  to  refer 
their  order,  their  disposition,  to  a  divine  power,  is  an  act  of 
faith  not  involved  in  the  historical  investigation.  In  order 
to  help  in  strengthening  faith  in  a  divine  government  of  the 
world,  the  study  of  history  would  require  to  lead  to  results 
which  admit  of  no  sufficient  explanation  from  the  natural  con- 
catenation of  what  has  happened,  or  from  the  free  wills  of  men. 
But  such  results  are  just  those  to  which  M.  Laurent's  point 
of  view  does  not  lead." 

It  is  inexplicable  how  Professor  Meyer  —  usually  a  most 
careful  writer  —  could  have  so  misunderstood  M.  Laurent's 
argument  as  he  has  here  done  ;  and  how  he  could  have  over- 
looked the  numerous  passages,  the  pages  after  pages,  in  which 
M.  Laurent  had  done  all  that  was  possible,  and  far  more  than 

i  Von  Sybel's  HistrfHsche  Zeitschrift,  Bd.  xxv.  s.  377. 


686  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY  IN   BELGIUM 

seemed  necessary,  to  make  misunderstanding  of  the  kind  im- 
possible. The  argument  of  M.  Laurent  is  that  the  examina- 
tion of  history  discloses  a  plan  pervading  human  affairs 
which  has  been  realised  through  the  operation  of  the  forces 
of  the  physical  and  moral  worlds,  through  the  actions  of 
human  beings  influenced  by  their  surroundings,  but  which  is 
not  their  plan:  a  plan  which  has  not  originated  with  man, 
which  has  not  originated  with  matter,  which  cannot  be  the 
work  of  chance,  which  cannot  be  an  effect  without  a  cause, 
and  which  must  therefore  be  ascribed  to  God.  Again  and 
again  he  states  his  argument  substantially  so ;  and  yet  Pro- 
fessor Meyer  thinks  it  relevant  to  object  that  the  fact  that 
what  is  wished  is  often  not  what  is  attained  can  be  explained 
from  the  natural  reaction  and  counteraction  of  the  ap- 
propriately arranged  historical  forces,  as  if  M.  Laurent  had 
failed  to  raise  the  question,  Who  arranged  these  forces  ?  and 
as  if  he  had  never  argued  that  it  could  not  be  nothing,  could 
not  be  chance,  could  not  be  nature,  could  not  be  general  laws, 
could  not  be  man,  but  must  be  God.  What  is  the  avowed 
purpose  of  the  whole  237  pages  of  introduction  and  criticism 
which  precede  his  examination  of  the  facts?  Here  is  an 
abridgment  of  what  he  himself  says:  "We  have  passed 
in  review  all  the  theories  imagined  by  philosophers  and 
historians  to  explain  the  mysterious  fact  that  there  is  in  the 
life  of  a  man  unfolded  in  history  a  succession,  a  plan,  a  de- 
velopment which  cannot  be  referred  to  man  himself.  Some, 
despairing  from  the  outset  to  find  a  solution,  make  of  their 
ignorance  a  blind  power  which  they  call  hazard.  Evidently 
that  is  no  solution.  Hazard  is  a  word,  and  nothing  more. 
Other  writers — the  majority  of  writers  —  say  that  this 
mysterious  power  is  nature,  under  the  form  of  climate,  or 
races,  or  the  whole  of  the  physical  influences  which  aot  on 
the  moral  world. .  But  what  is  nature  ?  Whence  has  it  this 
power,  this  foresight,  this  intelligence,  which  are  so  con- 
spicuous in  the  course  of  our  destinies?  If  nature  is  matter, 
and  nothing  but  matter,  that  too  is  no  answer.  Who  will 
believe  that  matter  acts  with  wisdom,  with  intelligence? 
Where  there  is  intelligent  action  there  must  be  an  intelligent 
being ;   therefore  nature  leads  us  to  God.     Finally,  there  are 


LAURENT  687 

those  who  substitute  for  nature  general  laws.  But  do  not 
laws  suppose  a  legislator?  And  who  can  this  legislator  be 
if  not  God?"1  These  are  the  conclusions,  I  repeat,  which 
M.  Laurent  devotes  the  first  237  pages  of  his  work  to  en- 
force,—  partly  by  expounding  his  own  views,  and  partly 
by  assailing  those  of  others.  And  then  he  occupies  the  134 
pages  which  follow  with  an  examination  of  the  facts  of  history 
as  a  whole,  undertaken  expressly  and  exclusively  to  show 
that  they  necessitate  the  same  conclusions.  In  these  circum- 
stances, Professor  Meyer's  objection  must  be  held  quite 
unreasonable.  And  indeed  it  seems  to  me,  no  objection  can 
possibly  apply  to  M.  Laurent's  reasoning  which  would  not 
equally  apply  to  every  form  of  theistical  argument  from  effect 
to  cause,  from  plan  to  designer,  from  course  of  procedure  to 
character  of  the  agent.  He  does  not  pretend  that  history 
proves  to  us  the  presence  of  God  as  it  proves  to  us  that  a  cer- 
tain battle  took  place,  or  that  a  certain  law  was  passed,  but 
that  it  proves  it  as  clearly  as  nature  does.  He  takes  no  notice 
of  objections,  like  those  formulated  by  Kant,  against  all  theo- 
logical reasonings  which  are  based  on  empirical  facts,  and 
assume  the  validity,  beyond  the  bounds  of  experience,  of  the 
principles  either  of  efficient  or  final  causes ;  but  against  all 
less  sweeping  and  radical  objections  he  has  made  his  position 
quite  secure. 

Professor  Meyer  proceeds :  "  Laurent's  point  of  view  is  like- 
wise suspicious,  since  it  leads  to  misinterpretation  of  the  will 
of  men,  in  order  thereby  to  exalt  so  much  the  more  the  will  of 
God.  He  has  fallen  into  this  error,  for  example,  when  he 
maintains  that  Christ  had  not  the  intention  of  founding  a  new 
religion,  but  of  preparing  men  for  the  near  end  of  all  things. 
Indeed  he  has  been  misled  throughout  by  his  false  point  of 
view  to  follow  the  course  of  the  human  will  mainly  in  the 
direction  of  perversity  and  evil." 

Now  it  is  true  that  M.  Laurent  has  maintained  that  Christ 
in  preaching  the  gospel  of  the  kingdom  willed  what  God  did 
not  will,  and  has  accomplished  not  what  He  Himself  willed, 
but  what  God  willed.  The  cause  of  that,  however,  was  not 
the  general  point  of  view  from  which  he  argued  for  the  pres- 

1  Pp.  239,  240. 


688  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY  IN  BELGIUM 

ence  of  God  in  history,  but  simply  the  fact  that  for  the  reasons 
which  he  gives  in  the  fourth  volume  of  his  work,  that  entitled 
'  fitude  sur  le  Christianisme,'  he  rejected  Christianity  as  a  spe- 
cial divine  revelation.  "We  may  regret  that  a  man  who  in  every 
page  of  his  work  shows  so  profound  and  living  a  sense  of  the 
presence  and  providence  of  God,  should  not  have  had  a  deeper 
insight  into  the  character  and  mission  of  Christ ;  but  there  are 
no  grounds  for  attributing  his  defective  vision  to  his  historical 
"  point  of  view." 

The  general  assertion  of  Professor  Meyer,  that  M.  Laurent's 
point  of  view  has  led  him  throughout  to  seek  chiefly  the  evi- 
dences of  perversity  and  evil  in  the  motives  of  men,  is  utterly 
baseless.  What  M.  Laurent  really  seeks  chiefly  throughout  his 
work  are  the  evidences  of  man's  progressive  apprehension  of 
the  plan  and  purposes  of  God  in  human  life,  of  his  own  rights 
to  liberty  and  equality,  of  religious  truth  and  moral  duty.  His 
argument  requires  him  to  lay  no  undue  stress  on  the  perver- 
sity and  wickedness  of  men's  wills.  It  is  enough  for  it  that 
men's  wills  have  not  been  coincident  with  God's  will;  that 
their  purposes  have  been  narrower  and  meaner  than  His  plans ; 
that  high  as  are  the  heavens  above  the  earth,  so  high  have 
been  His  thoughts  above  their  thoughts. 

The  second  and  last  book  of  M.  Laurent's  '  Philosophy  of 
History '  treats  of  progress  in  history.  It  is,  in  fact,  an  induc- 
tive proof  of  the  reality  of  the  progress  of  man,  individually 
and  nationally,  in  all  ethical  directions.  In  a  chapter  on  "  The 
Individual  and  his  Rights,"  the  author  traces  the  growth  of 
liberty  and  equality  in  the  oriental  theocracies,  in  the  classical 
nations,  in  the  Christian  Church,  in  Germanic  and  feudal 
society ;  and  concludes  by  warning  against  the  individualism 
which  denies  the  rights  of  the  State,  and  the  socialism  which 
denies  the  rights  of  the  person.  In  the  second  chapter  —  "  The 
Individual  and  his  Duties  "  —  he  argues  that  the  facts  of  his- 
tory viewed  along  its  whole  course  indubitably  establish  that 
there  has  been  both  a  religious  and  a  moral  progress  in  the 
personal  lives  of  men,  —  a  growth  in  spiritual  truth  and  an 
emancipation  from  spiritual  errors,  a  growth  in  purity  and 
delicacy  of  feeling  as  to  relations  between  the  sexes,  a  decrease 
of  cruelty,  &c.     From  individuals  with  their  rights  and  duties 


LAURENT  689 

he  passes  to  nations  and  their  relations.  The  third  chapter 
dwells  on  the  significance  of  nationality,  and  gives  an  historical 
exposition  of  the  formation  of  nationalities  in  humanity,  or 
of  the  differentiation  of  humanity  into  nationalities.  Here 
Laurent  shows  how  the  variety  of  nations  in  the  unity  of  hu- 
manity contributes  to  the  profound  and  exhaustive  development 
of  the  soul,  and  to  the  advancement  of  the  race  in  knowledge 
and  morality  ;  how  different  from  true  national  feeling  were 
the  sentiments  which  united  the  subjects  of  Asiatic  despotisms 
and  the  inhabitants  of  Greek  cities,  and  which  impelled  the 
Romans  to  constant  aggression  on  their  neighbours ;  how  the 
principle  of  nationality  was  affected  by  Christianity  and  the 
Papacy;  how  it  was  furthered  by  the  Renaissance  and  the 
Reformation  ;  how  its  course  was  modified  by  the  Monarchy, 
the  Revolution,  and  Napoleon ;  and  how,  in  still  more  recent 
times,  it  has  made  itself  known  and  felt  in  all  directions  as 
never  before,  seeing  that  in  peace  and  war  the  peoples  are 
everywhere  appearing  with  the  assertion  of  their  right  to  decide 
for  themselves,  to  be  themselves  the  central  and  conspicuous 
figures  in  whatever  drama  Providence  composes  for  them.  t 
^Along  with  the  idea  of  nationality  itself  there  gradually  grows 
up  this  other,  that  nation  is  bound  to  nation  by  ties  of  justice 
and  nature ;  that  they  have  rights  and  responsibilities,  mutual 
obligations  and  interests ;  that  they  are  members  of  humanity, 
a  brotherhood,  a  family,  and  that  a  wrong  done  by  one  to 
another,  by  the  strongest  to  the  weakest,  is  fratricidal  and  un- 
holy. The  growth  of  this  idea,  or,  in  other  words,  the  growth 
of  a  true  recognition  of  the  moral  relations  in  which  nations 
stand  to  one  another,  of  how  they  ought  to  feel  and  act  towards 
one  another,  is  traced  from  the  earliest  to  the  latest  times 
in  the  last  chapter  of  M.  Laurent's  work,  and  certain  specula- 
tions connected  therewith  bearing  on  the  future  prospects  of 
humanity  are  discussed.  A  hopeful,  yet  not  Utopian,  spirit 
characterises  all  his  speculations  as  to  the  future. 

The  conclusions  relative  to  progress,  which  have  their  evi- 
dence summarily  stated  in  these  four  chapters,  and  presented  in 
the  seventeen  volumes  of  the  '  fitudes '  with  a  fulness  never 
before  equalled,  are  far  from  composing  a  complete  philosophy 
of  history,  or  even  of  historical  progress ;  but  they  are  most 


690  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTOKY   IN   BELGIUM 

important  conclusions,  which  every  philosophy  of  history  must 
undoubtedly  recognise.  Laurent  is  entitled  to  be  remembered 
with  all  gratitude  for  the  enormous  labour  he  bestowed  on 
their  demonstration. 

While  Altmeyer  and  Laurent  treated  history  in  the  manner 
described,  the  Churchly  or  Catholic  theory  also  found  exposi- 
tors and  defenders  in  Belgium. 

The  first  Professor  of  General  History  in  the  Catholic  Uni- 
versity of  Lou  vain  was  J.  Moeller,  a  Danish  convert,  who  had 
studied  under  Niebuhr  and  Walter  at  Bonn,  and  under  Boeckh 
and  Hegel  at  Berlin.  The  notes  of  his  lectures,  published  by 
his  son,  the  present  occupant  of  the  same  chair,  in  the  '  Traite" 
des  Etudes  Historiques,'  1892,  enables  us  to  form  a  fairly 
adequate  conception  of  what  his  teaching  must  have  been. 
Obviously  it  was  comprehensive,  systematic,  solid,  and  useful 
teaching.  The  'Conferences  sur  la  synthase  de  l'histoire,' 
with  which  the  work  closes,  present  to  us  in  a  general  way  his 
views  as  to  the  philosophy  of  history.  The  definition  given  of 
history  is  one  afterwards  made  popular  by  Dr.  Arnold — viz., 
"  the  biography  of  humanity."  The  two  great  factors  of  history 
are  maintained  to  be  Providence  and  Free  Agency ;  its  end  is 
said  to  be  the  divine  glory ;  its  chief  work  is  represented  as 
consisting  in  the  preparation  for,  and  the  conservation  of,  the 
Church  of  the  true  God.  Moeller's  philosophy  of  history  is, 
in  the  main,  a  theodicy  based  on  history.  He  obviously  believed 
that  the  Church  had  not  been  seriously  at  fault  in  any  contro- 
versy or  conjuncture ;  but  none  of  his  utterances,  so  far  as 
published,  give  evidence  of  intolerance  or  fanaticism. 

Mgr.  Laforet  (1823-72),  who  was  for  a  time  Rector  of  the 
University  of  Louvain,  wrote  an  '  Histoire  de  la  Philosophie,' 
which  led  up  to  the  conclusion  that  what  philosophy  seeks  is 
only  to  be  found  in  the  teaching  of  the  Church ;  also  an  elabo- 
rate defence  of  that  teaching  in  its  historical  and  practical  as 
well  as  speculative  relations,  — '  Les  Dogmes  Catholiques,'  &c, 
4  vols. ;  and  a  treatise  of  which  the  special  object  is  to  prove 
that  Christianity  has  been  the  chief  source  of  all  that  is  best  in 
European  culture  and  life,  — '  Etudes  sur  la  Civilisation  Euro- 
pe"enne  conside're'e  dans  ses  rapports  avec  le  Christianisme,' 


THONISSEN  691 

1852.  MM.  Dechamps  and  Lefebre  replied  to  and  attacked 
the  '  Etudes '  of  Laurent. 

The  late  M.  Thonissen  (1817-91)  was  a  very  liberal  and 
estimable  representative  of  the  Catholic  School.  He  was  a  man 
of  varied  knowledge,  who  occupied  himself  much  with  history, 
and  was  especially  distinguished  as  a  jurist.  He  held  during 
forty  years  the  Chair  of  Criminal  Law  at  Louvain,  and  was  in 
1844  Minister  of  the  Interior  and  of  Public  Instruction.  His 
interest  in  social  questions  led  him  to  a  serious  study  of  Social- 
ism, and  in  1850  he  published  a  critical  account  of  the  system 
in  his  '  Socialisme  et  ses  promesses '  (2  vols.),  and  somewhat 
later  a  history  of  it,  — '  Le  Socialisme  depuis  1'antiquite"  jusqu'a 
la  constitution  franchise  de  1852 '  (2  vols.,  1852).  The  most 
valuable  of  his  works  is  generally  admitted  to  be  his  '  History 
of  Criminal  Law  among  ancient  peoples.'  It  displays  exten- 
sive research,  sound  judgment,  and  a  humane  and  generous 
spirit.  It  has  very  considerable  philosophical  interest,  and  it 
has  been  much  commended  by  those  who  have  made  a  special 
study  of  its  subject. 

The  question  of  progress  was  submitted  by  Thonissen  to  a 
special  examination  in  his  '  Considerations  sur  la  Thdorie  du 
Progress  inde'fmi  dans  ses  rapports  avec  l'histoire  de  la  civilisa- 
tion et  les  dogmes  du  Christianisme.' L  The  treatise  is  not 
marked  by  originality  or  profundity,  but  it  is  learned  and 
judicious.  It  is  mainly  a  sketch  of  the  course  and  a  history  of 
the  doctrine  of  progress ;  but  the  author  has  always  in  view 
the  refutation  of  those  who  represent  progress  as  necessary  and 
unlimited,  —  Schelling,  Hegel,  Leroux,  Reynaud,  Laurent, 
and  especially  Pelletan,  whom  he  regards  as  the  most  brilliant 
and  persuasive  advocate  of  the  theory  which  he  combats.  He 
rejects  the  opinion  that  man's  primitive  condition  was  one 
of  barbarism,  simply  on  the  ground  that  it  is  contrary  to 
Scripture  and  tradition.  He  points  out  the  weaknesses  in 
the  civilisations  of  India,  Egypt,  Greece,  and  Rome,  and 
cites  express  or  implied  denials  of  progress  made  by  their 
chief  thinkers.  He  refers  all  that  is  true  in  the  theory  of 
progress  to  the  first  preaching  of  the  Gospel,  and  traces  the 

1  First  published  in  '  Memoires  de  la  Acad.  Roy.  de  Belgique,'  t.  x.,  1859,  and 
afterwards  as  a  separate  volume  in  1867. 


692  PHILOSOPHY   OP   HISTORY   IN   BELGIUM 

development  of  the  theory  in  the  middle  age  and  in  modern 
times.  He  admits  that  during  the  historical  period  progress 
has  been  on  the  whole  continuous  as  a  matter  of  fact,  al- 
though not  of  necessity.  God  wills  it;  and  it  is  a  law  of 
history.  There  is  no  incompatibility,  he  maintains,  between 
Christianity  and  progress.  Those  who  affirm  that  there  is,  on 
the  ground  that  Christianity  teaches  immutable  dogmas  them- 
selves profess,  he  reminds  them,  immutable  principles.  The 
real  question  is,  Are  the  dogmas  of  Christianity  in  their  own 
nature  inconsistent  with  progress  ?  This  question  he  answers 
in  the  negative,  and  represents  the  views  of  rationalists  to  the 
contrary  as  mere  prejudices,  due  to  ignorance  of  what  the 
spirit  and  teaching  of  Christianity  actually  are. 

The,socialists  of  Belgium  have  taken  their  historical  philos- 
ophy for  the  most  part  from  the  founders  of  French  socialism 
and  the  leaders  of  German  socialism.  The  historical  theories 
of  the  former  I  have  already  described;  those  of  the  latter  will 
be  examined  in  the  next  volume.  The  only  Belgian  socialist 
to  whom  it  is  necessary  here  to  refer  is,  I  think,  Baron  de 
Colins  (1783-1859),  the  originator  of  a  form  of  collectivism 
called  by  his  disciples  "  rational  socialism."  Considered  simply 
as  a  socialist,  the  author  of  a  scheme  of  comprehensive  and 
detailed  social  reorganisation,  he  must  be  acknowledged  to 
rank  among  the  most  ingenious  and  perspicacious  of  the  class. 
But  he  has  little  claim  to  notice  in  any  other  connection. 
What  he  propounded  as  his  philosophy  centres  in  such  dogmas 
as  that  there  is  no  personal  God,  no  other  God  than  the  uni- 
versal, impersonal  Reason;  that  men  possess,  however,  "im- 
material sensibilities  "  or  "  souls  "  which  are  eternal,  and  pass 
through  endless  series  of  lives  in  other  worlds;  that  these 
souls  carry  with  them  into  each  new  life  original  sin  and 
original  merit;  that  the  lower  animals  are  insentient  auto- 
mata, &c.  His  historical  philosophy  is  not  of  a  kind  which  it 
would  be  justifiable  to  present  otherwise  than  briefly.  I  shall 
content  myself  with  quoting  the  summary  account  of  it  given 
by  M.  de  Laveleye :  — 

"  At  the  first,  the  supremacy  of  brute  force  is  established :  the  father 
of  the  family  rules,  the  strongest  of  the  tribe  commands.     But  in  a 


colins  693 

tolerably  large  community,  this  kind  of  supremacy  can  never  long 
endure,  for  he  who  is  at  one  time  the  strongest  cannot  always  remain 
such.  What  does  he  do,  then?  In  order  to  continue  master,  he  con- 
verts, as  Rousseau  says,  his  strength  into  a  right,  and  obedience  to  him 
into  a  duty.  With  this  object  in  view,  he  asserts  that  there  exists  an 
anthropomorphic  almighty  being,  called  God;  that  God  has  revealed 
rules  of  action,  and  has  appointed  him  the  infallible  lawgiver  and 
interpreter  of  this  revelation;  that  God  has  endowed  every  man  with 
an  immortal  soul ;  and,  finally,  that  man  will  be  rewarded  or  punished 
in  a  future  life,  according  as  he  has  or  has  not  regulated  his  conduct  by 
the  revealed  law.  ■ 

"  It  is  not  enough,  however,  for  the  legislator  to  assert  these  dogmas ; 
he  must  further  preserve  them  from  examination,  and  this  is  done  by 
maintaining  ignorance  and  repressing  thought.  Theocratic  sovereignty, 
or  the  divine  right  of  kings,  is  thus  established,  and  a  feudal  aristocracy 
arises.  This  is  the  historic  period  called  by  Rational  Socialism  'the 
period  of  social  ignorance  and  of  compressibility  of  examination.' 

"After  a  longer  or  shorter  interval,  in  consequence  of  the  growth 
of  intelligence,  the  discoveries  thereby  made,  and  the  increasing  facility 
of  communications  between  nations,  it  becomes  impossible  to  repress 
all  examination  entirely.  Then  the  superhuman  basis  of  society  is 
disputed,  and  its  authority  falls  to  the  ground.  The  divine  right  of 
kings  loses  its  theocratic  mask,  and  the  government  is  transformed  into 
a  mere  supremacy  of  force  — that  is  to  say,  of  the  majority  of  the  people. 
Aristocratic  society  becomes  bourgeois,  and  enters  upon  the  historic  period 
of  '  ignorance  and  incompressibility  of  examination.' 

"  Society,  then,  becomes  profoundly  agitated  and  disorganised.  The 
principles  which  used  to  insure  the  obedience  of  the  masses  lose  their 
sway.  Everything  is  examined,  and  scepticism  prevails.  This  unfettered 
examination  ends  in  the  denial  of  all  supernatural  sanctions,  of  the 
personality  of  the  Deity,  and  of  the  immortality  of  the  soul  (to  mention 
only  these  points),  and  leads  to  the  affirmation  of  materialism.  Then, 
personal  interest  becomes  a  stronger  force,  with  an  ever-increasing  num- 
ber of  individuals  than  ideas  of  order  and  of  devotion  to  principle,  and 
a  situation  is  brought  about  thus  defined  by  Colins  :  '  An  epoch  of  social 
ignorance,  in  which  immortality  increases  in  proportion  to  the  growth 
of  intelligence.' 

"As  pauperism  simultaneously  increases  in  the  same  proportions,  it 
follows  that  the  bourgeois  form  of  society  cannot  last.  In  one  way  or 
another  it  soon  falls  to  pieces,  and  the  supremacy  of  divine  right  is 
restored,  until  a  new  revolution  ushers  in  once  more  the  triumph  of 
the  bourgeoisie.  Society  cannot  escape  from  this  vicious  circle  in  which 
it  has  revolved  from  the  first,  until,  as  the  result  of  the  invention  and 
development  of  the  press,  and  of  the  absolute  impossibility  of  restricting 
the  examination  of  old  beliefs  consequent  thereon,  all  reversion  to  the 
theocratic  form  of  government  has  become  radically  impossible.     When 


694  PHILOSOPHY   OF    HISTORY   IN   BELGIUM 

that  time  comes,  humanity  must  either  perish  in  anarchy,  or  organise 
itself  conformably  to  scientific  reason.  It  is  then  that  humanity  will 
enter  on  the  last  period  of  its  historical  development,  the  period  of 
'  knowledge,'  which  will  endure  as  long  as  the  human  race  can  exist  on  the 
globe.  According  to  Colins,  then,  a  theocratic  regime  is  order  founded 
on  despotism,  a  democratic  regime  is  liberty  engendering  anarchy,  while 
the  rational  or  '  logocratic '  regime  would  secure,  at  the  same  time,  both 
liberty  and  order. 

"Hereafter,  according  to  the  Belgian  socialist,  society  will  be  defini- 
tively organised  as  follows :  All  men  being  by  right  equal,  they  ought 
all  to  be  placed  in  the  same  position  with  regard  to  labour.  Man  is 
free,  and  his  labour  should  be  free  also.  To  effect  this,  matter  should 
be  subordinated  to  intelligence,  labour  should  own  both  land  and  capital, 
and  wages  would  be  at  a  maximum.  All  men  are  brothers,  for  they 
have  a  common  origin;  hence,  if  any  are  unable  to  provide  for  them- 
selves, society  should  take  care  of  them.  In  the  intellectual  world  there 
should  be  a  social  distribution  of  knowledge  to  all,  and  in  the  material 
world  a  social  appropriation  of  the  land  and  of  a  large  portiou  of  the 
wealth  acquired  by  past  generations,  and  transformed  into  capital." 1 

In  M.  Quetelet  (1796-1874)  Belgium  had  the  most  re- 
nowned statistician  of  his  time.  He  has  unquestionably  done 
more  than  any  one  else  to  render  statistics  auxiliary  to  histor- 
ical science.  He  was  the  first  to  reveal  how  wonderful  in 
their  comprehensiveness  and  definiteness  are  the  regularities 
which  prevail  among  moral  and  social  phenomena.  These 
regularities  themselves,  the  real  discoveries  of  his  laborious 
and  brilliant  researches,  are  now  universally  acknowledged, 
and  are  too  well  known  to  require  to  be  stated  here.  But  as 
regards  the  precise  interpretation  to  be  put  on  them,  the  place 
to  be  assigned  them  in  historical  philosophy,  their  compati- 
bility or  incompatibility  with  free  will,  and  their  right  to 
be  regarded  or  not  as  properly  laws,  there  is  great  room  for 
difference  and  variety  of  opinion.  On  these  points  Quetelet 
can  only  be  credited  with  raising  questions  which  will  come 
before  us  in  connection  with  German  historical  thought  after 
they  had  been  under  searching  discussion,  and  when  they  can 
be  more  fully  and  conveniently  considered  by  us.2 

1  Socialism  of  To-day,  pp.  249,  250. 

2  The  most  important  of  Quetelet's  sociological  works  are,  '  Sur  l'Homme  et  le 
developpement  de  ses  faculty's,'  2  torn.,  1835;  'Lettres  sur  la  theorie  des  proba- 
bilities,' 1846  ;  "  La  Statistique  Morale  "  in  '  Me'n.  de  l'Acad.  Roy.  de  Belgique,' 
t.  xxi.,  1848  ;  '  Du  Systfeme  Sociale,'  1848  ;  and  '  De  la  Statistique  considered  sous 


BRUCK  695 

A  Belgian  physicist,  Captain  Brack,  who  devoted  himself 
specially  to  the  study  of  magnetism,  believed  that  he  had  found 
the  key  of  history  in  his  favourite  science.  In  a  work  enti- 
tled '  L'humanit^,  son  deVeloppement,  et  sa  dure'e,'  he  attempts 
to  establish  a  parallelism  between  magnetical  and  historical 
periods,  which,  in  his  opinion,  reveals  the  law  of  history.  An 
**  exclusively  historical  investigation  proves,  he  maintains,  that 
there  has  been  a  continuous  succession  of  peoples  on  the  earth 
throughout  historical  time,  and  that  each  of  them  has  exer- 
cised during  a  certain  period  a  maximum  of  action,  and  then 
yielded  up  the  supremacy  to  another.  Each  of  these  chief 
peoples  gives  its  character  to  an  historical  period.  Hence  the 
world's  great  historical  periods  have  been  —  1.  the  Assyrian ; 
2.  the  Egyptian ;  3.  the  Jewish-Phoenician ;  4.  the  Greek ; 
5.  the  Roman;  6.  the  Frankish;  7.  the  Catholic;  and  8.  the 
French.  Each  of  the  peoples  corresponding  to  these  periods 
successively  and  gradually  asserted  itself,  passed  through  a 
phase  of  intellectual  or  material  maximum  of  power,  and  then 
grew  feeble  in  transmitting  its  acquisitions  to  its  successor. 
The  period  of  supremacy  of  each  dominant  people  has  hith- 
erto, according  to  Briick,  been  constant,  the  same  for  all,  last- 
ing about  five  centuries,  a  half  of  the  people's  entire  life. 
Tables  are  given  designed  to  show  that  the  principle  life- 
epochs  of  the  peoples  which  have  reappeared  in  succession  on 
our  continent  —  those  of  their  foundation,  organisation,  apo- 
gee, and  end  or  renewal  —  reproduce  themselves  periodically 
at  a  distance  of  a  little  more  than  five  centuries.  But  purely 
physical  investigation,  Briick  maintains,  shows,  besides  an 
extremely  slow  magnetic  displacement  from  East  to  West, 
due  to  the  precession  of  the  equinoxes,  a  quinquasecular 
movement,  fixed  by  him  at  516  years.  And  these  two  periods, 
he  argues,  have  their  analogues  in  the  slow  displacement  of 
the  centre  of  civilisation  from  East  to  West,  and  especially 
in  the  quinquasecular  evolution  found  by  analysis  to  be  char- 
acteristic of  the  course  of  history  itself.1 

le  rapport  du  physique,  de  la  morale,  et  d'intelligence  de  l'homme,'  1860.  As  re- 
gards Quetelet  himself,  see  the  Notice  by  Ed.  Mailly  in  the  Annuaire  of  the  Acad. 
Roy.  de  Belgique  for  1875. 

1  Any  knowledge  which  I  possess  of  Captain  Briick  and  his  treatise  has  been 


696  PHILOSOPHY  OP  HISTORY  IN  BELGIUM 

The  learned  Bollandist,  Father  Charles  de  Smedt,  S.J. 
(1794-1887),  did  honour  to  his  country  and  his  order  by  his 
historical  labours.  He  began  his  literary  career  with  a  His- 
tory of  Belgium,  1821,  and  afterwards  edited  the  important 
'Corpus  Chronicorum  Flandriae.'  He  is  the  author  of  a  justly 
famed  '  Introduction  to  Ecclesiastical  History,' 1  almost  indis- 
pensible  to  students  of  that  branch  of  historical  knowledge.  * 
It  indicates,  classifies,  and  appreciates  the  sources,  auxiliaries, 
and  literature,  with  great  learning  and  sound  judgment.  I 
mention  Father  de  Smedt  here,  however,  especially  on  account 
of  his  '  Principes  de  la  Critique  Historique,'  published  in  1883, 
and  composed,  for  the  most  part,  of  articles  which  had  ap- 
peared in  a  French  religious  periodical  in  1869  and  1870.  It 
is  one  of  the  best  books  on  its  subject ;  attractive  in  style ; 
manifestly  inspired  by  a  conscientious  and  liberal  spirit ;  and 
the  fruit  of  thorough  learning  and  of  long  experience.  In  a 
manner  always  sensible  and  useful  it  treats  of  the  utility  of 
studying  the  rules  of  criticism,  of  the  dispositions  required  in 
the  critic,  of  the  nature  of  historical  certainty,  of  the  authen- 
ticity, interpretation,  and  authority  of  the  texts,  of  oral  and 
popular  tradition,  of  the  negative  argument,  of  conjecture,  of 
unwritten  testimony,  and  of  arguments  a  priori.  Besides,  it 
touches  on  a  number  of  particular  disputed  points  luminously, 
although  briefly.  At  the  same  time,  it  is  far  from  adequate  to 
its  subject  or  sufficient  for  the  wants  of  students.  It  is  in  no 
way  a  systematic  treatise,  and  does  not  at  all  penetrate  into 
the  psychology  or  even  the  logic  of  historical  processes.  It  is 
only  just  to  describe  it  as  still  one  of  the  best  books  on  the 
principles  of  historical  criticism;  but  it  is  little  to  the  credit 
of  historians  that  we  should  require  or  be  able  so  to  de- 
scribe it.2 

derived  entirely  from  the  '  History  of  the  Physical  and  Mathematical  Sciences  in 
Belgium,'  by  MM.  Ch.  and  E.  Lagrange  —  see  '  Cinquante  Ans  de  Liberte,'  t.  11, 
pp.  171-195.  My  failure  to  procure  his  work  is  probably  not  much  to  be  regretted. 
I  could  certainly  not  have  formed  an  intelligent  opinion  regarding  his  magnetic 
periods  of  516  years,  and  would  have  been  most  sceptical  as  to  his  historical 
periods  of  518  years.  MM.  Lagrange  speaks  in  the  highest  terms  of  the  scientific 
genius  and  the  self-sacrificing  labours  of  Captain  Briick. 

1  Introductio  generalis  ad  historian  ecclesiasticam  critice  tract andam.  Oandavi, 
1876. 

3  There  is  an  interesting  sketch  of  the  life  of  Father  de  Smedt  by  Father  de 
Decker  in  the  Annuaire  for  1888  of  the  Royal  Academy  of  Belgium. 


VINET  69T 


II 


French-speaking  Switzerland  is  not,  as  some  suppose,  intel- 
lectually a  mere  province  of  France.  It  has  a  character  of  its 
own;  one  which  has  been  developed  under  peculiar  political 
conditions,  and  profoundly  modified  by  the  action  of  religion. 
It  lies  open,  however,  to  all  French  influences ;  and  what  is  said 
and  done  at  Paris  is  immediately  known  and  felt  at  Geneva  and 
Lausanne.  At  the  same  time  it  readily  receives  and  assimilates 
German  ideas,  owing  partly  to  its  Protestantism  and  partly  to 
its  close  connection  with  German-speaking  Switzerland.  As 
regards  literature  and  science  it  will  bear  honourable  compar- 
ison, relatively  to  its  extent  and  population,  with  any  other 
portion  of  Europe.  It  is  characterised  by  great  intellectual, 
as  well  as  industrial  and  commercial  activity.  It  has  pro- 
duced a  large  number  of  historians,  although  none,  perhaps, 
of  the  highest  rank.  Among  the  best-known  names  are  those  of 
Beza,  Theodore  Agrippa  D  Aubigne",  Mallet-Dupan,  Sismondi, 
B.  Constant,  Merle  DAubigne",  De  Felice,  Chastel,  Sayous, 
Roget,  &c.  As  regards  its  historical  theorists  there  is  not 
much  now  to  tell.  Rousseau,  Madame  de  Stael,  and  Benjamin 
Constant,  have  already  been  under  our  notice.1 

Alexander  Vinet  (1797-1847)  has  been  the  most  influen- 
tial of  the  Swiss  Protestant  writers  of  this  century;  and 
deservedly,  being  the  man  of  most  original  individuality,  of 
purest  genius,  of  intensest  conviction,  of  most  striking  and 
searching  eloquence.  He  has  nowhere  specially  treated  of 
the  philosophy  of  history,  but  he  has  often  touched  upon  it ; 
and  M.  Asti^  has  diligently  collected  the  thoughts  expressed 
on  these  occasions,  and  skilfully  composed  of  them  a  chapter 
.  of  a  book  widely  known  to  English  readers  as  Vinet's  '  Out- 
lines of  Philosophy.'  From  that  chapter  I  shall  make  a  few 
quotations. 

1 M.  Virgile  Rossel's  '  Histoire  Litteraire  de  la  Suisse  Eomande  des  origines  a 
nos  jours,'  2  torn.,  1889,  seems,  so  far  as  I  can  judge,  to  fulfil  its  promise  of  pre- 
senting "  a  faithful  and  complete  picture  of  the  intellectual  life  of  all  the  French- 
speaking  cantons  from  its  commencement  to  the  present  time." 


G98  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   SWITZERLAND 

"  History  in  its  highest  signification  is  but  the  manifestation  of  the 
idea  of  progress,  whether  we  refer  that  progress  to  the  nature  of  things 
and  the  course  of  time,  or  whether  we  seek  it  in  what  Bossuet  calls  the 
development  of  religion,  or  lastly,  whether  we  view  it  as  a  result  of  these 
two  causes  combined.  In  all  these  cases,  progress  can  only  be  the 
advance  of  the  intelligent  world  towards  truth,  which  exclusively  and 
infallibly  contains  goodness.  If  the  law  of  progress  do  not  exist,  there 
is  no  meaning  in  history,  nor  in  the  world  either,  and  each  alike  is  only 
fit  to  be  thrown  aside  as  mere  rubbish." 

"There  is  one  sense  in  which  truth  knows  no  laws  except  its  own,  is 
never  overcome,  never  retarded,  and  always  triumphs.  It  always  realises 
itself,  either  in  the  free  submission  of  the  moral  being  or  in  his  chastise- 
ment. The  believing  and  the  unbelieving,  the  saints  and  the  ungodly, 
equally  do  it  honour.  Error,  which  combats  it,  affords  it  at  the  same 
time,  at  its  own  cost,  a  striking  confirmation ;  it  is  its  natural  counter- 
proof." 

"  The  fall  of  heavy  bodies  is  not  subject  to  more  rigorous  laws  than 
the  course  of  the  idea  in  the  human  mind  and  in  society.  A  principle 
bears  all  its  consequences  within  itself,  as  a  plant  does  all  its  posterity. 
Men  may  choose  the  time  to  agitate  a  question;  they  may  defer  pro- 
posing it;  but,  once  proposed,  they  cannot  prevent  the  questions  it 
contains  proposing  themselves  one  after  the  other.  .  .  .  Truth  and 
necessity  only  make  one,  and  the  logic  of  the  ideas  lay  beforehand 
in  the  facts.  God  has  granted  us  no  nobler  spectacle  than  that  of 
times  when  these  two  logics  reunite.  Nothing  is  so  indefatigable, 
obstinate,  and  powerful,  as  a  principle.  It  gradually  brings  all  thoughts 
into  captivity  to  its  obedience ;  and  even  before  it  has  subjected 
thoughts,  it  has  subjected  facts.  As  everything  is  connected  in  a  true 
system,  as  the  whole  truth  is  included  in  each  particular  truth,  one 
point  gained,  the  whole  is  gained." 

"  If  in  the  destinies  of  humanity  as  a  whole,  or  even  of  a  single 
nation,  the  weight  of  individualities  is  but  little  felt;  if  in  so  vast 
a  calculation  their  value  is  hardly  appreciable;  they  do  for  all  that 
tell  in  the  limits  of  a  given  century ;  and  the  historians  of  the  fatalist 
school,  who  are  very  right  in  an  extended  horizon  only  to  take  count 
of  general  causes,  and  to  refer  results  immediately  to  laws,  are  wrong 
when  they  transport  their  system  within  narrower  bounds.  Nothing 
prevents  them,  or  rather  nothing  excuses  them  from  assigning  to  human 
liberty,  to  diversity  of  character,  and  to  special  providence,  a  part,  and 
a  considerable  part  too,  in  the  production  of  events.  Let  them  abstract 
these  on  a  less  limited  scale ;  they  may  do  so  without  endangering  the 
dogma  of  divine  liberty,  while  in  dealing  with  the  annals  of  one  or  of 
a  few  centuries,  their  method  compromises  at  one  blow,  together  with 
the  liberty  of  man,  the  liberty  of  God." 

"  It  seems  written  in  the  book  of  national  destiny  that,  in  the  advance 


VINET  699 

of  social  facts,  thought  and  action  shall  never  move  with  equal  step; 
thought  invariably  limps  breathlessly  after  action,  or  action  after  thought 
—  each  is  alternately  too  slow  or  too  precipitate.  This  incurable  disease 
of  society,  springing  as  it  does  from  an  incurable  disease  of  human 
nature,  is  a  fertile  principle  of  political  disturbances.'' 

"  Although  a  social  truth  lies  at  the  bottom  of  all  struggles,  yet  this 
truth,  under  its  general  and  absolute  form,  only  manifests  itself  to  the 
generation  that  comes  when  the  struggle  is  over.  Posterity  alone  knows 
why  the  conflict  took  place,  and  would  tell  it,  were  that  possible,  to  those 
by  whom  the  conflict  was  carried  on  ;  for  no  theory  has  appeared  in  the 
world  anterior  to  facts ;  it  is  the  facts  that  have  engendered  the  theory : 
thus  it  is  that  all  social  truths,  created  one  by  one  both  by  necessity  and 
opportunity,  have  come  down  to  us;  thus  it  is  that  our  children  will 
know  better  than  we  what  it  was  we  really  aimed  at.  It  is  only  God 
who  knows  beforehand  what  He  wills  and  what  He  does." 

"  Influenced  by  the  recollections  of  a  thousand  generous  revolts  which 
have  asserted  in  our  world  the  rights  of  God  over  the  pretensions  of 
men,  the  rights  of  truth  over  the  pretensions  of  error,  in  short  those  of 
virtue  over  vice,  I  have  said,  and  I  still  say,  that  it  is  from  revolt  to 
revolt  that  societies  go  on  to  perfection,  that  justice  reigns,  and  truth 
flourishes.  Yet,  although  history  teaches  that  almost  all  the  great  ques- 
tions that  have  agitated  society  have  had  a  violent  solution,  it  is  the 
duty  of  social  man  to  start  from  an  opposite  hope,  to  spare  society  too 
sudden  transformations,  and  to  smooth  the  incline  by  which  humanity 
advances  to  new  destinies." 

"All  progress  leads  to  discontent;  it  is  not  misery  that  plants  the 
standard  of  revolutions.  What !  is  progress,  then,  to  be  always  a  sub- 
ject of  alarm?  Will  it  always  rouse  some  confused  idea  of  crime  and 
impiety?  Will  it  always  find  a  great  number  of  the  most  honourable 
members  of  society  distrustful  of  and  almost  in  league  against  it  ?  Yes ; 
so  long  as  the  progress  of  the  human  heart  —  that  heart  which,  according 
to  Scripture,  is  desperately  wicked,  and  whose  wickedness  taints  all 
things  —  does  not  correspond  with  the  progress  of  laws,  arts,  and  even 
morals.  Humanity  seems  to  forget  that  the  first  inventions,  the  first 
progress,  occurred  in  the  family  of  Cain." 

"  Nothing  in  God's  eyes  is  progress  in  humanity  except  what  restores 
in  humanity  the  image  of  God.  The  Christian,  too,  who  sees  all  with 
God's  eyes,  iii  God's  light,  gives  the  name  of  progress  to  nothing  else ; 
for  society,  being  neither  external  to  humanity  nor  to  the  plan  of  God, 
must  tend  towards  the  same  end  to  which  man  is  summoned  to  aim : 
we  may  very  easily  deduce  from  this  that  equality  is,  in  the  eyes  of 
the  Christian,  neither  the  whole  of  progress,  nor  even  an  essential  part 
of  the  true  progress,  but  at  most  (and  this  remains  to  be  discussed)  one 
of  the  consequences,  or  one  of  the  signs  of  true  progress.  For  a  man 
who  has  become  the  equal  of  all  other  men  is  not  for  that  reason  more 


700  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   SWITZERLAND 

like  to  God ;  and  a  society  where  the  most  absolute  equality  was  estab- 
lished would  not  by  that  alone  correspond  any  better  with  the  divine 
idea." 

M.  Charles  Secre"tan  felt  the  influence  of  Vinet,  but  he  also, 
when  a  student  at  Munich,  came  under  the  spell  of  Schelling ; 
and  his  chief  work,  '  La  Philosophie  de  la  LiberteY  reminds 
us  on  every  page  of  the  religious  earnestness  of  the  former, 
and  of  the  speculative  venturesomeness  of  the  latter.  The 
system  expounded  in  it,  however,  is  based  on  Kant's  doctrine 
of  the  supremacy  of  the  practical  reason.  Its  central  idea  is 
that  of  Absolute  Liberty.  He  protests  against  its  being 
described  as  an  a  priori  metaphysical  deduction ;  but  it  is, 
at  least,  a  boldly  constructive  philosophy,  very  ambitious  in 
its  aim,  and  all-comprehensive  in  its  range,  —  "  a  synthesis," 
as  its  author  himself  avers,  "  of  theism  and  pantheism,  of 
monism  and  of  monadology,  of  dogmatism  and  of  criticism, 
of  history  and  of  reason,  under  the  sovereign  direction  of  the 
moral  idea."  Its  themes  are  God,  nature,  and  man ;  and  it 
comprehends  a  kind  of  philosophy  of  history,  which  claims  to 
be  essentially  Christian,  inasmuch  as  it  discovers  in  Chris- 
tianity the  only  true  satisfaction,  and  the  only  adequate 
explanation  of  the  condition  and  course  of  human  affairs. 

In  the  exposition  of  his  historical  doctrine,  as  of  his  system 
in  general,  M.  Secre"tan  displays  a  vigorous  and  original 
intelligence,  and  gives  expression  to  many  fine  and  striking 
thoughts.  But  the  doctrine  itself  need  not  detain  us.  It 
consists  not  of  properly  historical  theses,  but  of  essentially 
theological  hypotheses,  mostly  incapable  either  of  rational 
proof  or  of  inductive  verification.  It  contains  very  disputable 
views  regarding  God  conceived  of  as  absolute  and  infinite 
liberty ;  the  origination  of  the  universe  and  of  humanity  in 
a  perfect  ideal  unity;  the  disruption  of  that  unity  into  an 
indefinite  number  of  individualities ;  a  primordial  fall,  or 
original  sin,  before  time  and  development,  anterior  to  nature, 
exterior  to  history,  and  the  source  alike  of  physical  and  of 
moral  evil;  the  struggling  and  suffering  of  the  Restorative 
Will  of  God  in  conflict  with  matter ;  the  tending  of  the 
humanity-species   to   incarnation;    the   Word  becoming   an 


SECKETAN  —  TBOTTET  701 

individual  in  Christ,  expiating  sin,  and  sanctifying  the  race ; 
the  return  of  mankind  to  the  absolute  unity  through  the 
Church ;  and  similar  themes. 

In  M.  Secre"tan's  latest  book,  '  Mon  Utopie,'  1892,  he  has 
delineated  his  ideal  of  the  future.  It  is  one  which  includes 
the  solution  of  the  economic  problem  by  the  collectivisation 
of  property  in  land ;  of  the  social  question  by  the  complete 
enfranchisement  of  women,  the  equalisation  of  the  sexes ;  and 
of  the  religious  problem  by  the  severance  of  religion  from 
theology,  the  organisation  of  a  Church  without  dogma  or 
confession. 

Another  pupil  of  Vinet  was  J.  P.  Trottet  (1818-62).  He 
studied  four  years  in  Germany,  and  was  for  a  long  time 
pastor  at  Stockholm,  and  for  a  shorter  period  at  the  Hague. 
He  was  warmly  religious,  while  free  and  vague  as  regards 
his  theology.  His  chief  work,  '  Le  Ge"nie  des  Civilisations,' 
2  vols.,  appeared  in  1862,  shortly  before  his  death.  It  treats 
only  of  antiquity ;  bears  marks  of  having  been  brought  hur- 
riedly to  a  close;  and  gives  no  indications  of  how  it  was 
intended  to  be  worked  out.  It  testifies  to  wide  reading  and 
prolonged  reflection,  but  is  often  more  ingenious  than  clear 
or  convincing.  Its  arrangement  is  rather  loose :  for  example, 
the  note  regarding  "  the  first  cause  of  the  formation  of  races  " 
at  the  end  of  the  first  volume,  and  the  last  chapter  of  the 
second  volume  as  to  "  the  natural  relations  between  human 
civilisations  and  the  configuration  of  the  places  which  have 
served  as  their  theatre,"  should  have  been  included  in  the 
introduction.  It  proceeds  on  the  conviction  that  the  entire 
development  of  each  people  springs  from  its  distinctive 
spiritual  principle,  and  is  only  to  be  understood  through  a 
study  of  its  religion  ;  that  the  destinies  of  nations  are  deter- 
mined by  their  modes  of  representing  and  revering  the  Divine. 
It  treats  especially  of  the  constitutive  period  of  each  of -the 
societies  brought  under  consideration.  The  patriarchal  fam- 
ily, the  patriarchal  tribe,  patriarchal  humanity  as  represented 
by  China,  the  city-empires  of  Babylon,  Nineveh,  and  Carthage, 
the  sacerdotal  realm  of  India,  the  pagan  monarchies  of  Egypt 
and  Iran,  the  ancient  republics  of  Greece  and  Rome,  and  the 


702  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   SWITZERLAND 

Jewish  theocracy,  are  successively  passed  in  review,  with  the 
purpose  of  showing  that  the  whole  history  of  humanity  has 
been  the  necessary  preparation  for  Christianity ;  that  the 
mythological  religions  were  stages  of  education  suited  to  the 
wants  of  the  human  mind  at  each  epoch  of  its  development ; 
that  Christian  consciousness  is  the  final  and  perfect  form  of 
humanitarian  consciousness.  But  the  conclusion  is  not  fully 
reached.  The  work  is  a  fragment,  and  we  are  not  enabled 
to  form  any  satisfactory  conception  of  the  whole  in  which  it 
was  meant  to  be  included. 

The  late  M.  Frederick  de  Rougemont  (1807-76)  of  Neu- 
chatel  was  a  layman,  but  of  far  more  rigid  orthodoxy  than 
Vinet  or  Trottet ;  a  most  vigorous  theological  polemic ;  a 
man  widely  acquainted  with  science,  of  immense  learning,  of 
indefatigable  activity,  of  unswerving  conscientiousness,  and 
of  unfaltering  courage.  He  never  hesitated  to  call  to  strict 
account  the  most  eminent  of  his  fellow-countrymen,  such  as 
Agassiz,  Vinet,  and  M.  de  Gasparin,  when  they  seemed  to 
him  to  fall  into  heresies.  His  absolute  faith  in  the  inerrancy 
of  the  Scriptures  was  accompanied  by  a  faith  almost  as  strong 
in  the  inerrancy  of  his  own  deductions  from  them.  At  one 
period  of  his  life  he  was  a  disciple  of  Hegel,  and  although  he 
abandoned  Hegelianism  when,  to  use  his  own  words,  "he 
took  his  seat  at  the  feet  of  Christ,"  he  retained  to  the  last 
some  Hegelian  peculiarities  of  thought  and  speech.  He 
regarded  Germany  as  "  his  intellectual  fatherland." 

Among  Rougemont's  numerous  works  are  two  very  erudite 
treatises  —  the  one  intended  to  establish  his  views  regarding 
"  the  primitive  people," a  and  the  other  to  prove  his  hypothesis 
of  the  Semitic  origin  of  Western  civilisation.2  With  these 
are  closely  connected  '  Les  Deux  Cite"s  —  La  Philosophic  de 
l'Histoire  aux  differents  ages  de  l'HumaniteY  2  torn.,  1874.3 
This  last  is  much  the  more  important.  The  second  volume 
is  especially  valuable.     The  account  which  it  gives  of  the 

1  LeJ'euple  Primitif,  sa  religion,  son  histoire,  et  sa  civilisation,  3  vols.,  1885-87. 

2  L'Age  du  bronze,  ou  les  Semites  en  Occident,  1866. 

8  It  was  published  a  month  or  two  later  than  my  '  Philosophy  of  History  in 
France  and  Germany.' 


KOUGEMONT  703 

doctrine  of  historical  theorists  from  the  Renaissance  to  our 
own  day  is  the  fruit  of  enormous  and  conscientious  reading. 
So  far  as  the  historical  narrative  is  concerned,  there  is  much 
that  is  excellent  in  the  first  volume  also,  although  there  is 
likewise  a  good  deal  that  is  irrelevant  or  erroneous.  But 
while  '  Les  Deux  Cit6s  '  is  a  very  remarkable  and  meritorious 
work,  it  has  at  least  two  serious  defects. 

The  first  obtrudes  itself  on  us  in  almost  every  page.  M. 
Rougemont  is  far  from  being  as  considerate  and  fair  in  judg- 
ing of  the  theories  and  systems  which  he  brings  before  us  as 
he  is  in  simply  presenting  them.  The  secret  of  this  fact  is 
not  only  an  open  one,  but  one  which  he  has  taken  care  that 
we  shall  learn  from  himself.  In  bringing  his  work  to  a  close, 
he  tells  us  that  "  he  has  weighed  the  historical  philosophers 
of  all  times  in  the  balance  of  the  sanctuary,  and  put  on  his 
left  hand  those  who  are  light ;  that  no  one  has  a  right  to  pro- 
test against  this  balance,  seeing  that  every  one  has  his  own ; 
and  that  the  only  difference  between  himself  and  the  philoso- 
phers is  that  their  balances  are  of  earthly  fabrication,  and  have 
been  adopted  without  due  consideration,  whereas  his  is  that 
of  Christ,  and  has  been  carefully  selected."  There  may  be 
Helvetian  candour  in  this  declaration,  but  there  is  neither 
modesty  nor  reasonableness  in  it.  Criticism  conducted  on 
such  a  plan  is  a  continuous  petitio  principii  in  the  critic's  own 
favour.  Without  any  disrespect  to  "  the  balance  of  the  sanc- 
tuary," its  fitness  for  weighing  philosophical  theories  and  his- 
torical generalisations  may  be  doubted.  "What  other  balance 
for  weighing  these  things  can  there  be  than  reason  taking  fair 
and  full  account  of  all  the  relevant  facts  ?  There  is  no  other 
instrument,  no  other  method,  of  dealing  justly  with  the 
opinions  and  systems  either  of  those  "  deists,  pantheists,  ma- 
terialists, positivists,  and  sceptics,"  whom  Rougemont  so  dicta- 
torially  waives  to  the  left,  or  of  those  "  believing  theologians  " 
to  whom,  as  arbitrarily,  he  assigns  a  place  of  honour  on  his 
right.  Then,  is  it  really  "  the  balance  of  the  sanctuary  "  which 
he  employs  ?  That  is  very  doubtful.  What  he  certainly  does 
employ  as  a  balance  is  just  his  own  historical  philosophy. 
True,  he  fathers   that  philosophy  on   the   prophets  Isaiah, 


704  PHILOSOPHY   OF   HISTORY   IN   SWITZERLAND 

Ezekiel,  Nahum,  and  Daniel,  and  on  the  apostles  St.  Paul  and 
St.  John ;  but,  then,  he  founds  the  claim  on  the  most  arbitrary 
and  improbable  interpretations  of  their  writings.  His  so- 
called  "  balance  of  the  sanctuary  "  is  largely  of  his  own  fabri- 
cation ;  it  is  his  own  private  theory  of  history. 

The  unsatisfactoriness  of  that  theory  is  the  second  of  the 
two  defects  referred  to  as  lessening  the  value  of  '  Les  Deux 
Citfe.'  It  consists  to  a  large  extent  of  hypotheses  associated 
with  rather  than  founded  on  the  Bible,  and  of  Biblical  doc- 
trines or  declarations  misapplied.  It  is  not  necessary,  I  think, 
to  subject  it  to  a  critical  examination.  The  following  quota- 
tion will  give  some  general  idea  of  it,  and  of  the  plan  of  M. 
de  Rougemont's  work :  — 

"  Knowing  the  problems  of  historiosophy,  all  the  false  solutions 
which  reason  can  give  them,  and  the  only  true  one,  that  which  is 
taught  us  in  Holy  Scripture,  we  shall  exhibit  the  order  of  succession 
of  the  revelations  of  God  and  of  the  errors  of  man  from  age  to  age. 
The  revelations  are  three  in  number :  that  of  God  the  Creator,  Elohiui, 
to  the  psychical  humanity  sprung  from  Adam ;  that  of  Jehovah  to  the 
Hebrew  people  born  of  Sem ;  that  of  Jesus  Christ  to  the  spiritual 
humanity  which  is  His  issue  by  faith.  The  errors  are  of  two  oppo- 
site natures,  and  of  two  epochs  separated  by  thousands  of  years;  the 
myths  of  the  ancient  East  and  the  philosophical  systems  of  the  modern 
West.  Between  these  systems  and  these  historiosophic  myths  there 
intervenes  in  time  and  space  the  science  of  the  biology  of  nations 
created  by  the  human  mind  among  the  Hellenes.  The  division  of 
our  work  is  thus  very  simple.  The  first  book  has  for  its  subject  the 
traditions  which  primitive  humanity  has  transmitted  to  us  regarding 
its  origins  and  the  revelations  of  God.  There  are  there  the  founda- 
tions of  historiosophy.  The  two  books  which  follow  comprehend  the 
pagan  peoples  of  the  East  and  the  Hebrews.  The  pagans  wander 
astray  among  myths  which  have  no  value  for  our  science,  but  which 
all  proceed  from,  and  thereby  bear  witness  to,  the  primordial  truths  of 
humanity.  The  most  curious  of  these  myths  are  the  cyclical  histories 
of  the  universe.  The  Hebrews  receive  from  God  a  second  revelation 
which  confirms  the  first,  and  which  is  summed  up  in  the  promise  of 
the  Messiah.  Then  come  Greece  and  Rome,  which,  while  losing  sight 
of  the  history  of  humanity,  discover  the  formulae  of  the  succession 
of  governments  in  the  different  ages  of  their  republican  cities.  The 
following  books,  which  comprise  the  historiosophy  of  the  Christian 
world,  show  us :  first,  Jesus  Christ   and  His   apostles  completing  the 


MALAN  705 

divine  revelations ;  then  on  one  side,  the  believing  thinkers  explain- 
ing by  the  great  principles  of  the  faith,  and  by  the  prophecies  the 
history  of  humanity;  and  on  another  side,  the  rationalistic  philoso- 
phers striving  in  vain  to  comprehend  its  course  and  plan,  and,  by 
the  very  vanity  of  their  efforts,  as  well  as  by  their  studies  in  histori- 
cal biology,  coming  slowly  to  confess  that  the  revealed  historiosophy 
is  the  most  rational  of  philosophies.  Primitive  humanity  is  the  thesis ; 
Israel  of  the  race  of  Sem  and  the  Japhetic  Hellenes  form  the  anti- 
thesis of  the  divine  revelations  and  of  human  science;  the  Christian 
world  is  called  to  accomplish  or  at  least  to  prepare  for  the  definitive 
synthesis  of  faith  and  of  reason." l 

The  work  of  Csesar  Malan,  entitled  '  Les  Grands  Traits  de 
THistoire  religieuse  de  l'HumaniteY  1883,  will  please  and  in- 
terest its  readers  by  its  eloquence,  its  sincerity  of  tone,  and  the 
truth  and  worth  of  many  of  the  thoughts  and  facts  which  it 
conveys.  But,  I  imagine,  it  will  find  few  disposed  to  accept 
its  formula  of  historical  development,  its  distribution  of 
historical  time.  It  represents  humanity  as  passing  through 
three  stages,  or  Divine  Economies,  —  the  Economy  of  the 
presence  of  God  on  earth,  the  Economy  of  revelation,  and 
the  Economy  of  palingSnesie,  or  of  the  redemption  of  man 
and  the  restoration  of  the  kingdom  of  God.  Thus  to  force 
the  matter  of  history  into  the  mould  of  an  antiquated  the- 
ology is  surely  imprudent.  M.  Malan's  work  is  derived  in  a 
considerable  measure  from  the  '  Humanitat  und  Christen- 
thum '  of  the  Danish  theologian,  Dr.  Scharling,  which  will 
come  before  us  in  our  next  volume. 

Secre"tan,  Rougemont,  and  Malan  seem  to  me  to  have  one 
fault  in  common,  that  of  fancying  themselves  to  know  a  great 
deal  more  about  the  beginning  and  end  of  history  than  they 
really  do,  or  even  than  it  has  been  given  to  man  in  his 
present  state  to  know.  All  three  might  have  sat  with  advan- 
tage at  the  feet  of  that  gifted  Swiss  maiden  —  Mile.  Alice  de 
Chambrier  —  whose  thoughts  incessantly  tended  to  the  immor- 
tality to  which  she  was  so  early  called  away,  and  who  felt  so 
deeply  that  the  life  of  man  on  earth  is  but  a  slender  gleam 
of  light  between  immensities  of  darkness. 

i  Pp.  32,  33. 


706  PHILOSOPHY   OP  HISTORY  IN  SWITZERLAND 

"  Ou  done  la  vie  humaine  a-telle  pris  sa  source? 
Vers  quel  but  inconnu  son  cours  est-il  pousse? 
Vers  d'autres  univers  portons-nous  notre  course  ? 
L'avenir  sera-t-il  l'image  du  passe? 

Mystere  de  la  vie,  6  grand  pourquoi  des  choses  ! 
Arche  immense  d'un  pont  sur  les  siecles  construit, 
Et  dont  les  deux  piliers,  les  effets  et  les  causes, 
Plongent,  l'un  dans  le  vague  et  l'autre  dans  la  nuit !  " 


THE   END 


NottoooS  yrcBB : 

J.  S.  Cushing  &  Co.  —  Berwick  &  Smith. 

Boston,  Mass.,  U.S.A.