Skip to main content

Full text of "Sextus Empiricus and Greek scepticism .."

See other formats


t''l 


!*' 








m\i;-ji, 








BOUGHT WITH THE INCOME 
FROM THE 

SAGE ENDOWMENT FUND 

THE GIFT OF 

1891 



An^^^^ ^X3. 



.\.?IJ..5. 
3081 



Date Due 



OCT t 9 l^g 



M 



5ii-2^197rMP 



"^S3^fc« 



■;3S3E3Ss5tt'5-*K*^.'" 



^^ I 



Cornell University Library 
B623 .P31 



Sextus Empiricus and Greek scepticism 




3 1924 029 002 561 




Cornell University 
Library 



The original of tliis book is in 
tine Cornell University Library. 

There are no known copyright restrictions in 
the United States on the use of the text. 



http://www.archive.org/details/cu31924029002561 



SEXTUS EMPIRIOUS 

AND 

GREEK SCEPTICISM 



SEXTUS EMPIRICUS 



AND 



GREEK SCEPTICISM 



A Thesis accepted for the Degree of Doctor of 

Philosophy in the University of Bern 

Switzerland, November 1897 



BY 



MARY MILLS PATEICK 

PRESIDENT OP THE AMERICAN COHEGE, CONSTANTINOPLE 
TURKEY 



This Thesis is accompanied by a Translation from the Greek 

of the First Book of the "Pyrrhonic Sketches" 

by Sextus Empiricus 



CAMBEIDGE 

DEIGHTON BELL & CO. 

LONDON GEORGE BELL & SONS 

189!) 



CAMBRIDGE 

PRINTED BY JONATHAN PALMER 

ALEXANDRA STREliT 



PREFACE 

The following treatise on Sextus Empiricus and 
Greek Scepticism has been prepared to supply 
a need much felt in the English language by 
students of Greek philosophy. For while other 
schools of Greek philosophy have been exhaust- 
ively and critically discussed by English scholars, 
there are few sources of information available to 
the student who wishes to make himself familiar 
with the teachings of Pyrrhonism. The aim has 
been, accordingly, to give a concise presentation 
of Pyrrhonism in relation to its historical develop- 
ment and the Scepticism of the Academy, with 
critical references to the French and German 
works existing on the subject. The time and 
manner of the connection of Sextus Empiricus 
with the Pyrrhonean School has also been dis- 
cussed. 

As the First Book of the Hypotyposes, or 
Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus, con- 
tains the substance of the teachings of Pyrrho- 
nism, it has been hoped that a translation of it 
into English might prove a useful contribution 
to the literature on Pyrrhonism, and this transla- 



PREFACE 

tion has been added to the critical part of the 
work. 

In making this translation, and in the general 
study of the works of Sextus, the Greek text of 
Immanuel Bekker, Berlin, 1842, has been used, 
with frequent consultation of the text of J. A. 
Fabrioius, 1718, which was taken directly from 
the existing manuscripts of the works of Sextus. 
The divisions into chapters, with the headings of 
the chapters in the translation, is the same as 
Fabricius gives from the manuscripts, although 
not used by Bekker, and the numbers of the 
paragraphs are the same as those given by both 
Fabricius and Bekker. Eeferences to Diogenes 
Laertius and other ancient works have been 
carefully verified. 

The principal modern authors consulted are 
the following: 

Ritter, Geschichte der Philosophie, II. Auf., Hamburg, 

18.36—38. 
Zeller, Philosophie der Griechen, III. Auf., Leipzig, 

1879—89. 
Lewes, History of Philosophy, Vol. I., London, 1866. 
Ueberweg, History of Philosophy, IV. ed., translated 

by Morris, 1871. 
Brochard, Les Sceptiques Grecs, Paris, 1877. 
Brochard, Pyrrhon et le Scepticism Primitive, No. 5, 

Ribot's Revue Phil., Paris, 188,5, 



PREFACE 

Saisset, Le Scepticism Aen^sidhme-Pascal-Kant, Paris, 

1S67. 
Chaignet, Histoire de la Psychologic des Grecs, Paris, 

1887—90. 
Haas, Leben des Sextus Empiricus, Burghausen, 1882. 
Natorp, Forschungen zur Geschichte des ErJcenntnis- 

problems bei den Alien, Berlin, 1884. 
Hirzel, Untersuchungen zu Cicero's philosopMschen 

Schriften, Leipzig, 1877 — 83. 
Pappenheim, Erldaterung zu des Sextus Empiricus 

Pyrrhoneischen Grundzugen, Heidelberg, 1882. 
Pappenheim, Die Tropen der Greichischen Skeptilcer, 

Berlin, 1885. 
Pappenheim, Lebensverhdltnisse des Sextus Empiricus, 

Berlin, 1887. 
Pappenheim, Ber angebliche Heraclitismus des Skep- 

tikers Aviiesidemos, Berlin, 1887. 
Pappenheim, Ber Sitz der Schule der Griechischen 

Skeptiker, Archiv fur Geschichte der Philosophic, 

I. 1, S. 47, 1887. 
MaccoU, The Greek Sceptics from Pyrrho to Sextus, 

London, 1869. 

My grateful acknowledgments are due to Dr. 

, Ludwig Stein, Professor of Philosophy in the 
University of Bern, for valuable assistance in 
relation to the plan of the work and advice in 
regard to the best authorities to be consulted. 
Thanks are also due to Dr. Louisos Iliou, of 
Eobert College, Constantinople, for kind sugges- 

• tions concerning the translation. 



OOl^rTEI^TS 

CHAPTER I. 

FAQE 

The Histoeicai Eelations of Sextds Empieicus ... 1 
Introductory paragraph. — The name of Sextus Empiricus. 
His profession. — The time when he lived. — The place of 
his birth. — The seat of the Sceptical School while Sextus 
was at its head.— The character of the writings of Sextus 
Empiricus. 

CHAPTER II. 

The Position and Aim of Pyerhonic Scepticism . . 23 
The subject-matter of the Hypotyposes. — The origin of 
Pyrrhonism. — The nomenclature of Pyrrhonism. — Its 
criterion. — Its aim. — iiroxh and hrapa^ia. — The standpoint 
of Pyrrhonism. 

CHAPTER III. 

The Sceptical Teopes 31 

Origin of the name. — The ten Tropes of iiroxll- — The First 
Trope.— The Second Trope.— The Third Trope.— The 
Fourth Trope.— The Fifth Trope.— The Sixth Trope.— 
The Seventh Trope.— The Eighth Trope.— The Ninth 
Trope. — The Tenth Trope. — The five Tropes of Agrippa. — 
The two Tropes. — The Tropes of Aenesidemus against 
Aetiology. 

CHAPTER IV. 

Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heeaclitus . . 63 
Statement of the problem. — The theory of Pappenheim. — 
The theory of Brochard. — Zeller's theory. — The theory of 
Hitter and Saisset. — The theory of Hirzel and Natorp. — 
Critical examination of the subject. 



CHAPTER V. 

Critical Examination oe Pyeehonism 81 

Pyrrhonism and Pyrrho. — Pyrrhonism and the Academy. 
Strength and weakness of Pyrrhonism. 



The Pikst Book of the Pyeehonic Sketches by Sextus 
Empieicus. Teahslated feom the Geeek .... 101 



CHAPTER I. 

The Historical Relations of Seodus Empiricus. 

Interest has revived in the works of Sextus Empiri- 
cus in recent times, especially, one may say, since the 
date of Herbart. There is much in the writings of 
Sextus that finds a parallel in the methods of modern 
philosophy. There is a common starting-point in the 
study of the power and limitations of human thought. 
There is a common desire to investigate the phenomena 
■of sense-perception, and the genetic relations of man to 
the lower animals, and a common interest in the theory 
of human knowledge. 

While, however, some of the pages of Sextus' works 
would form a possible introduction to certain lines of 
modern philosophical thought, we cannot carry the 
analogy farther, for Pyrrhonism as a whole lacked the 
essential element of all philosophical progress, which is 
a belief in the possibility of finding and establishing 
the truth in the subjects investigated. 

Before beginning a critical study of the writings of 
Sextus Empiricus, and the light which they throw on 
the development of Greek Scepticism, it is necessary to 
make ourselves somewhat familiar with the environ- 
ment in which .he lived and wrote. We shall thus be 
able to comprehend more fully the standpoint from 
which he regarded philosophical questions. 

Let us accordingly attempt to give some details of 
his life, including his profession, the time when he lived, 

1 



2 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

the place of his hirth, the country in which he taught, 
and the general aim and character of his works. Here, 
however, we encounter great difficulties, for although 
we possess most of the writings of Sextus well pre- 
served, the evidence which they provide on the points 
mentioned is very slight. He does not give us bio- 
graphical details in regard to himself, nor does he refer 
to his contemporaries in a way to afford any exact 
knowledge of them. His name even furnishes us with 
a problem impossible of solution. He is called ^efro? o 
ifj.Tj-eipiKO'i by Diogenes Laertius^ : 'HpoSoTov Se Bii]Kovae 
Si^TO<; 6 ejjmeipiKO's, oil koX to, Se/ca rSiv a-KSTniKtov 
Kol aWa KaXKt.c7Ta' ^e^Tov Se Bii^Kovcre ^aTopvivoi o 
Kvdrjvai, ifji'treipiKo's km avTo?. Although in this passage 
Diogenes speaks of Sextus the second time without the 
surname, we cannot understand the meaning otherwise 
than that Diogenes considered Sextus a physician of the 
Empirical School. Other evidence also is not wanting 
that Sextus bore this surname. Fabricius, in his edition 
of the works of Sextus, quotes from the Tabella de 
Sectis Medicorum of Lambecius the statement that 
Sextus was called Empiricus because of his position 
in medicine.^ 

Pseudo-Galen also refers to him as one of the 
directors of the Empirical School, and calls him ^'e'^ro?- 
6 e/ATT-etptKOs.^ His name is often found in the manu- 
scripts written with the surname, as for example at the 
end of Logic II* In other places it is found written 

' Diog. Laert. ix. 12, 116. 

■' Fabricius Testimonia, p. 2. 

' Pseudo-Galen Isag. 4 ; Fabricius Testimonia, p. 2. 

* Bekker Math. vjii. 481. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Em'pvricus. 3 

without the surname, as Fabricius testifies, where 
Sextus is mentioned as a Sceptic in connection with 
Pyrrho. 

The Sceptical School was long closely connected 
with the Empirical School of medicine, and the later 
Pyrrhoneans, when they were physicians, as was often 
the case, belonged for the most part to this school. 
Menedotus of Nicomedia is the first Sceptic, however, 
who is formally spoken of as an Empirical physician,^ 
and his contemporary Theodas of Laodicea was also 
an Empirical physician. The date of Menedotus and 
Theodas is difficult to fix, but Brochard and Hass 
agree that it was about 150 A.D.^ After the time of 
these two physicians, who were also each in turn at 
the head of the Sceptical School,' there seems to 
have been a definite alliance between Pyrrhonism and 
Empiricism in medicine, and we have every reason to 
believe that this alliance existed until the time of 
Sextus. 

The difficulty in regard to the name arises from 
Sextus' own testimony. In the first book of the Hy- 
potyposes he takes strong ground against the identity 
of Pyrrhonism and Empiricism in medicine. Although 
he introduces his objections with the admission that 
"some say that they are the same," in recognition of 
the close union that had existed between them, he goes 
on to say that " Empiricism is neither Scepticism itself, 
nor would it suit the Sceptic to take that sect upon 
himself,* for the reason that Empiricism maintains dog- 
matically the impossibility of knowledge, but he would 

> Diog. IX. 12, 115. ■■ Diog. ix. 12, 116. 

2 Brochard Op. elt. Livre iv. p. 311. * Byp. i. 236. 



4 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

prefer to belong to the Methodical School, which was the 
only medical school worthy of the Sceptic. " For this 
alone 6f all the medical sects, does not proceed rashly 
it seems to me, in regard to unknown things, and does 
not presume to say whether they are comprehensible 
or not, but it is guided by phenomena.^ It will thus 
be seen that the Methodical School of medicine has a 
certain relationship to Scepticism which is closer than 
that of the other medical sects."^ 

We know from the testimony of Sextus himself 
that he was a physician. In one case he uses the first 
person for himself as a physician,^ and in another he 
speaks of Asclepius as "the founder of our science,"* 
and all his illustrations show a breadth and variety of 
medical knowledge that only a physician could possess. 
He published a medical work which he refers to once 
as laTpiK^ VTrofivr^fiara,^ and again as i/xTreipiKa virojJLvri- 
fiara.^ These passages probably refer to the same 
work,^ which, unfortunately for the solution of the diffi- 
cult question that we have in hand, is lost, and nothing 
is known of its contents. 

In apparent contradiction to his statement in Hy- 
potyposes I., that Scepticism and Empiricism are 
opposed to each other, in that Empiricism denies the 
possibility of knowledge, and Scepticism makes no 
dogmatic statements of any kind, Sextus classes the 
Sceptics and Empiricists together in another instance, 
as regarding knowledge as impossible^ aX\' ol fiev ^aaiv 

1 Hyp. I. 237. 5 _4ii^^ ^iaik_ yii. 202. 

2 Eyp. I. 241. 6 Adv. Math. A. 61. 

s Hyp. II. 238. ' Zeller Op. cit. in. 43. 

* Adv. Math. A. 260. e Adv. Math. viii. 191. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 5 

avTa fir) KaraXafi^dveadai, aa-rrep ol avo t^9 e/jLiretpia'; 
larpol KOI 01 avro tij? tr/ceT^eo)? <j)iK6a-o<j}oi. In another 
case, on the contrary, he contrasts the Sceptics sharply 
with the Empiricists in regard to the aTroSei^K.^ ol Se 
ifj.rreipiKol avaipovaiv, ol Se (TKerrriKol iv sVo;)^^ tuvttjv 

Pappenheim thinks that Sextus belonged to the 
Methodical School, both from his strong expression in 
favor of that school in Hyp. I. 236, as above, and also 
because many of his medical opinions, as found in 
his works, agree with the teachings of the Methodical 
School, more nearly than with those of the Empiricists. 
Pappenheim also claims that we find no inconsistency 
with this view in the passage given where Sextus 
classes the Sceptics with the Empiricists, but considers 
that statement an instance of carelessness in expressing 
himself, on the part of Sextus.^ 

The position of Pappenheim is assailable for the 
reason that in dealing with any problem regarding an 
author on the basis of internal evidence, we have no 
right to consider one of his statements worthy of 
weight, and another one unworthy, on the supposition 
that he expressed himself carelessly in the second 
instance. Kather must we attempt to find his true 
standpoint by fairly meeting all the difficulties offered 
in apparently conflicting passages. This has been 
attempted by Zeller, Brochard, Natorp and others, with 
the general result that all things considered they think 
without doubt that Sextus belonged to the Empirical 

' 1 Mv. Math. Viii. 328. 
^ Lebenaverhdlinisse des Sex. Em. 36. 



6 Sextus Empiricus a/nd Greek Scepticism. 

School.^ His other references are too strong to allow 
his fidelity to it to be doubted. He is called one of 
the leaders of Empiricism by Pseudo-Galen, and his 
only medical work bore the title ifjnreipiKa virojjbvrnMaTa. 
The opinion of the writers above referred to is that the 
passage which we have quoted from the Hypotyposes 
does not necessarily mean that Sextus was not an 
Empiricist, but as he was more of a Sceptic than a 
physician, he gave preference to those doctrines that 
were most consistent with Scepticism, and accordingly 
claimed that it was not absolutely necessary that a 
Sceptic physician should be an Empiricist. Natorp con- 
siders that the dififerent standpoint from which Sextus 
judges the Empirical and Methodical Schools in his 
different works is accounted for on the supposition that 
he was an Empiricist, but disagreed with that school 
on the one point only." Natorp points out that Sextus 
does not speak more favourably of the medical stand of 
the Methodical School, but only compares the way in 
which both schools regarded the question of the possi- 
bility of knowledge, and thinks that Sextus could have 
been an Empiricist as a physician notwithstanding his 
condemnation of the attitude of the Empirical School 
in relation to the theory of knowledge. This difference 
between the two schools was a small one, and on a 
subtle and unimportant point ; in fact, a difference in 
philosophical theory, and not in medical practice. 

While we would agree with the authors above 
referred to, that Sextus very probably recognized the 

' Broohard Op. cit. Livre iv. 317 ; Zeller Op. cit. in. 16 ; Natorp Op. 
cit. p. 166. 

' Natorp Op, cit. 157. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 7 

bond between the Empirical School of medicine and 
Pyrrhonism, yet to make his possible connection with 
that school the explanation of his name, gives him 
more prominence as a physician than is consistent with 
what we know of his career. The long continued union 
of Empiricism and Scepticism would naturally support 
the view that Sextus was, at least during the earlier 
part of his life, a physician of that school, and yet it 
may be that he was not named Empiricus for that 
reason. There is one instance in ancient writiugs where 
Empiricus is known as a simple proper name.^ It may 
have been a proper name in Sextus' case, or there are 
many other ways in which it could have originated, as 
those who have studied the origin of names will readily 
grant, perhaps indeed, from the title of the above-named 
work, i/i'jreiptKa vTro/MvijfiaTa. The chief argument for 
this view of the case is that there were other leaders of 
the Sceptical School, for whom we can claim far greater 
influence as Empiricists than for Sextus, and for whom 
the surname Empiricus would have been more appro- 
priate, if it was given in consequence of prominence in 
the Empirical School. Sextus is known to the world 
as a Sceptic, and not as a physician. He was classed in 
later times with Pyrrho, and his philosophical works 
survived, while his medical writings did not, but are 
chiefly known from his own mention of them. More- 
over, the passage which we have quoted from the 
Hypotyposes is too strong to allow us easily to believe 
that Sextus remained all his life a member of the 
Empirical School. He could hardly have said, " Nor 

^ Pappenheim Zeb. Ver. Sex. Em. 6. 



8 Sextus Empiricus and Greek ScepticisTn. 

would it suit the Sceptic to take that sect upon him- 
self," if he at the same time belonged to it. His other 
references to the Empirical School, of a more favorable 
character, can be easily explained on the ground of the 
long continued connection which had existed between 
the two schools. It is quite possible to suppose that 
Sextus was an Empiricist a part of his life, and after- 
wards found the Methodical School more to his liking, 
and such a change would not in any way have affected 
his stand as a physician. 

In regard to the exact time when Sextus Empiricus 
lived, we gain very little knowledge from internal evi- 
dence, and outside sources of information are equally 
uncertain. Diogenes Laertius must have been a gene- 
ration younger than Sextus, as he mentions the disciple 
of Sextus, Saturninus, as an Empirical physician.^ The 
time of Diogenes is usually estimated as the first half 
I of the third century A.D.,^ therefore Sextus cannot be 
brought forward later than the beginning of the century. 
I j Sextus, however, directs his writings entirely against the 
'' 'Dogmatics, by whom he distinctly states that he means 
I the Stoics,' and the influence of the Stoics began to 
decline in the beginning of the third century A.D. A 
fact often used as a help in fixing the date of Sextus is 
his mention of Basilides the Stoic,* aWa koX ol oTcolKoif 
aii ol irepl lov Baa-iXelSrjv. This Basilides was supposed 
to be identical with one of the teachers of Marcus 
Aurelius.^ This is accepted by Zeller in the second 
edition of his History of Philosophy, but not in the 

1 Diog. IX. 12, 116. 4 ^dv. Math. vni. 258. 

2 Ueberweg Hist, of Phil. p. 21. ' Fatrioius Vita Sexti. 
s Syp. 1. 65. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 9 



third, for the reason that Sextus, in all the work from 
which this reference is taken, i.e. Math. vii. — xi., men- 
tions no one besides Aenesidemus, who lived later than 
the middle of the last century B.c.^ The Basilides 
referred to by Sextus may be one mentioned in a list 
of twenty Stoics, in a fragment of Diogenes Laertius, 
recently published in Berlin by Val Rose.^ Too much 
importance has, however, been given to the relation of 
the mention of Basilides the Stoic to the question of 
the date of Sextus. Even if the Basilides referred to 
by Sextus is granted to have been the teacher of Marcus 
Aurelius, it only serves to show that Sextus lived either 
at the same time with Marcus Aurelius or after him, 
which is a conclusion that we must in any case reach 
for other reasons. 

The fact that has caused the greatest uncertainty in 
regard to the date of Sextus is that Claudius Galen in 
his works mentions several Sceptics who were also 
physicians of the Empirical School,^ and often speaks 
of Herodotus, supposed to be identical with the teacher 
of Sextus given by Diogenes Laertius,* but makes no 
reference whatever to Sextus. As Galen's time passes 
the limit of the second century a.d., we must either 
infer that Sextus was not the well-known physician 
that he was stated to be by Pseudo-Galen, and con- 
sequently not known to Galen, or that Galen wrote 
before Sextus became prominent as a Sceptic. This 
silence on the part of Galen in regard to Sextus 
increases the doubt, caused by Sextus' own criticism 
of the Empirical School of medicine, as to his having 

' Zeller Op. cit. in. 8. ' Zeller, iii. 7. 

2 Brochard Op. cit. iv. 315. * Diog. xi. 12, 116. 



10 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

teen an Empiricist. The question is made more com- 
plicated, as it is difficult to fix the identity of the 
Herodotus so often referred to by Galen.^ As Galen 
■died about 200 A.D. at the age of seventy/ we should 
fix the date of Sextus early in the third century, and 
that of Diogenes perhaps a little later than the middle, 
were it not that early in the third century the Stoics 
began to decline in influence, and could hardly have 
excited the warmth of animosity displayed by Sextus. 
We must then suppose that Sextus wrote at the very 
latter part of the second century, and either that Galen 
did not know him, or that Galen's books were pub- 
lished before Sextus became prominent either as a 
physician or as a Sceptic. The fact that he may have 
been better known as the latter than as the former does 
not sufficiently account for Galen's silence, as other 
Sceptics are mentioned by him of less importance than 
Sextus, and the latter, even if not as great a physician 
as Pseudo-Galen asserts, was certainly both a Sceptic 
and a physician, and must have belonged to one of the 
two medical schools so thoroughly discussed by Galen — 
either the Empirical or the Methodical. Therefore, if 
Sextus were a contemporary of Galen, he was so far 
removed from the circle of Galen's acquaintances as to 
have made no impression upon him, either as a Sceptic 
or a physician, a supposition that is very improbable. 
We must then fix the date of Sextus late in the second 
■century, and conclude that the climax of his public 
career was reached after Galen had finished those of his 
writings which are still extant. 

' Fappenheim Zeieni. Ver. Sex. Em. 30. 
' Zeller Grundriaa der Gets, der Phil. p. 260. 



Historical Relations of Seodus Empiricus. 11 

Sextus has a Latin name, but he was a Greek ; we 
know this from his own statement.^ We also know that 
he must have been a Greek from the beauty and facility 
of his style, and from his acquaintance with Greek 
dialects. The place of his birth can only, however, be 
conjectured, from arguments indirectly derived from his 
writings. His constant references throughout his works 
to the minute customs of different nations ought to 
give us a clue to the solution of this question, but 
strange to say they do not give us a decided one. Of 
these references a large number, however, relate to the 
■customs of Libya, showing a minute knowledge in 
regard to the political and religious customs of this 
land that he displays in regard to no other country 
except Egypt.^ Fabricius thinks Libya was not his 
birth place because of a reference which he makes to it 
in the Hypotyposes — Opa/cwv Be koI TauTovkaiv {Ai^vcov 
Se edvoi TovTo).^ This conclusion is, however, entirely 
unfounded, as the explanation of Sextus simply shows 
that the people whom he was then addressing were not 
familiar with the nations of Libya. Suidas speaks of 
two men called Sextus, one from Chseronea and one 
from Libya, both of whom he calls Sceptics, and to one 
of whom he attributes Sextus' books. All authorities 
agree in asserting that great confusion exists in the 
works of Suidas ; and Fabricius, Zeller, and Pappenheim 
place no weight upon this testimony of Suidas.* Haas, 

» Adv. Math. A. 246; Mj/p. i. 162; Syp. in. 211, 214. 
2 Haas Op. cit. p. 10. 
' ffffp. III. 213. 

* Pappenheim Lebem. Ver. Sex. Em. 5, 22 ; Zeller Op. cit. in. 39 ; 
Fabricius Vita de Sextus. 



12 Sextus Evipiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

however, contends^ that it is unreasonable to suppose 
that this confusion could go as far as to attribute the 
writings of Sextus Empiricus to Sextus of Chseronea, 
and also make the latter a Sceptic, and he considers it 
far more reasonable to accept the testimony of Suidas, 
as it coincides so well with the internal evidence of 
Sextus' writings in regard to his native land. It is 
nevertheless evident, from his familiarity with the 
customs, language, and laws of Athens, Alexandria and 
Rome, that he must have resided at some time in each 
of these cities. 

Of all the problems connected with the historical 
details of the life of Sextus, the one that is the most 
difficult of solution, and also the most important for our 
present purpose of making a critical study of his teach- 
ing, is to fix the seat of the Sceptical School during the 
time that he was in charge of it. The Hypotyposes are- 
lectures delivered in public in that period of his life. 
Where then were they delivered ? We know that the 
Sceptical School must have had a long continued exis- 
tence as a definite philosophical movement, although 
some have contended otherwise. The fact of its exis- 
tence as an organized direction of thought, is demon- 
strated by its formulated teachings, and the list giverk 
by Diogenes Laertius of its principal leaders,^ and 
by references from the writings of Sextus. In the 
first book of Hypotyposes he refers to Scepticism- as 
a distinct system of philosophy, koI •rr}v StaKptaiv t-Q? 
aKer^ew; cltto tmv irapaKeifj.evwv avry <f>c\oao^ta>v.^ He 
speaks also of the older Sceptics,* and the later Sceptics.^' 

1 Haas Op. cit. p. 6. ' Diog. xi. 12, 115, 116. ^ ^j,^. i_ 5. 
* Syp. I. 36. 5 Byp. i. 164. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 13 

Pyrrho, the founder of the school, taught in Elis, his 
native village ; but even as early as the time of Timon, 
his immediate follower, his teachings were somewhat 
known in Alexandria, where Timon for a while resided.^ 
The immediate disciples of Timon, as given by Diogenes, 
were not men known in Greece or mentioned in Greek 
writings. Then we have the well-known testimony of 
Aristocles the Peripatetic in regard to Aenesidemus, that 
he taught Pyrrhonism in Alexandria^ — e%^fi9 ical irpoirjv 
iv 'AXe^avBpeia rrj Kar Atyvwrov Alpr]aiST]/j,6i Tt? ava- 
^(oirvpelv ijp^aro top vOKov tovtov. 

This was after the dogmatic tendency of the Academy 
under Antiochus and his followers had driven Pyrrhon- 
ism from the partial union with the Academy, which it 
had experienced after the breaking up of the school under 
the immediate successors of Timon. Aenesidemus taught 
about the time of our era in Alexandria, and established 
the school there anew ; and his followers are spoken of 
in a way that presupposes their continuing in the same 
place. There is every reason to think that the connec- 
tion of Sextus with Alexandria was an intimate one, 
not only because Alexandria had been for so long a 
time the seat of Pyrrhonism, but also from internal 
evidence from his writings and their subsequent his- 
torical influence; and yet the Hypotyposes could not 
have been delivered in Alexandria, as he often refers to 
that place in comparison with the place where he was 
then speaking. He says, furthermore, that he teaches 
in the same place where his master taught.^ ^Xeirmv 

• Chaignet Op. cit. 45. 

2 Aristocles of Euseb. Praep. Ev. xiv. e, 446. 

3 Byp. III. 120. 



14 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

re on ev6a 6 v<jyriy7jTr)^ 6 e/ios BieXiyeTo, evravda e^w vvv 
Sia\iyo/j,ai. Therefore the school must have been re- 
moved from Alexandria, in or before the time of the 
teacher of Sextus, to some other centre. The Hypoty- 
poses are from beginning to end a [direct attack on the 
Dogmatics; therefore Sextus must have taught either 
in some city where the dogmatic philosophy was strong, 
or in some rival philosophical centre. The Hypotyposes 
show also that the writer had access to some large 
library. Alexandria, Rome and Athens are the three 
places the most probable for selection for such a. 
purpose. For whatever reason the seat of the school 
was removed from Alexandria by the master of Sextus, 
or by himself, from the place where it had so long been 
united with the Empirical School of medicine, Athens 
would seem the most suitable city for its recontinuance, 
in the land where Pyrrhonism first had its birth. 
Sextus, however, in one instance, in referring to things 
invisible because of their outward relations, says in 
illustration, " as the city of Athens is invisible to us at 
present."^ In other places also he contrasts the Athen- 
ians with the people whom he is addressing, equally 
with the Alexandrians, thus putting Athens as well as 
Alexandria out of the question. 

Of the different writers on Sextus Empiricus, those 
who have treated this part of the subject most critically 
are Haas and Pappenheim. We will therefore consider, 
somewhat at length, the results presented by these two 
authors. Haas thinks that the Hypotyposes were 
delivered in Rome for the following reasons. Sextus* 

' Hyp. 11. 98. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 15 



lectures must have been given in some centre of philo- 
sophical schools and of learning. He never opposes 
Roman relations to those of the place where he is 
speaking, as he does in regard to Athens and Alexan- 
dria. He uses the name " Romans " only three times/ 
once comparing them to the Rhodians, once to the 
Persians, and once in general to other nations.^ In the 
first two of these references, the expression " among the 
Romans " in the first part of the antithesis is followed 
by the expression, "among us," in the second part, 
which Haas understands to be synonymous. The third 
reference is in regard to a Roman law, and the use of 
the word ' Roman ' does not at all show that Sextus was 
not then in Rome. The character of the laws referred 
to by Sextus as Trap' ■^/j-lv shows that they were always 
Roman laws, and his definition of law^ is especially a 
definition of Roman law. This argument might, it 
would seem, apply to any part of the Roman Empire, 
but Haas claims that the whole relation of law to 
custom as treated of by Sextus, and all his statements 
of customs forbidden at that time by law, point to 
Rome as the place of his residence. Further, Haas 
considers the Herodotus mentioned by Galen* as a pro- 
minent physician in Rome, to have been the predecessor 
and master of Sextus, in whose place Sextus says that 
he is teaching.^ Haas also thinks that Sextus' refuta- 
tion of the identity of Pyrrhonism with Empiricism 
evidently refers to a paragraph in Galen's Subfiguratio 

' Haas Op. cit. p. 15. 

2 Sj/p. I. 149, 152; m. 211. 

3 St/p. I. 146. 

« Galen depuls. iv. 11 ; Bd. viii. 751. ^ Bj/p. ni. 120. 



16 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

Empirica,^ which would be natural if the Hypotyposes 
were written shortly after Galen's Sub. Em,, and in the 
same place. Further, Hippolytus, who wrote in or near 
Eome very soon after the time of Sextus, apparently 
used the Hypotyposes, which would be more natural if 
be wrote in the same place. According to Haas, every 
thing in internal evidence, and outward testimony, 
points to Rome as having been the city where Sextus 
occupied his position as the head of the Sceptical School. 
Coming now to the position of Pappenheim on this 
subject, we find that he takes very decided ground 
against the seat of the Sceptical School having been in 
Rome, even for a short time, in his latest publication 
regarding it.^ This opinion is the result of late study 
on the part of Pappenheim, for in his work on the 
Lebensverhdltnisse des Sextus Em^piricus Berlin 1875, 
he says, "Dass Herodotus in Rom lebte sagt Galen. 
.Vermuthlich auch Sextus." His reasons given in the 
later article for not connecting the Sceptical School at 
all with Rome are as follows. He finds no proof of the 
influence of Scepticism in Rome, as Cicero remarks that 
Pyrrhonism is extinct,^ and he also gives weight to the 
well-known sarcastic saying of Seneca, Quis est qui 
tradat praecepta Pyrrhonis ! * While Haas claims 
that Sextus would naturally seek one of the centres of 
dogmatism, in order most effectively to combat it, 
Pappenheim, on the contrary, contends that it would 
have been foolishness on the part of Sextus to think of 

1 Galen Sui. Em. 123 b— 126 d. (Basileae, 1642). 

^ Pappenheim SiU der Skeptiachen ScJiule. ArcMvfUr Oeschickte der 
Mil. 1888. 

3 Cicero Se Orat. iii. 17, 62. ^ Seneca nat. qu. vii. 32. 2. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 17 

starting the Sceptical School in Rome, where Stoicism 
was the favored philosophy of the Roman Emperors; 
and when either for the possible reason of strife between 
the Empirical and Methodical Schools, or for some other 
cause, the Pyrrhonean School was removed from Alex- 
andria, Pappenheim claims that all testimony points to 
the conclusion that it was founded in some city of the 
East. The name of Sextus is never known in Roman 
literature, but in the East, on the contrary, literature 
speaks for centuries of Sextus and Pyrrho. The ITy- 
potyposes, especially, were well-known in the East, and 
references to Sextus are found there in philosophical 
and religious dogmatic writings. The Emperor Julian 
makes use of the works of Sextus, and he is frequently 
quoted by the Church Fathers of the Eastern Church.^ 
Pappenheim accordingly concludes that the seat of 
Pyrrhonism after the school was removed from Alex- 
andria, was in some unknown city of the East. 

In estimating the weight of these arguments, we 
must accept with Pappenheim the close connection of 
Pyrrhonism with Alexandria, and the subsequent influ- 
ence which it exerted upon the literature of the East. 
All historical relations tend to fix the permanent seat 
of Pyrrhonism, after its separation from the Academy, in 
Alexandria. There is nothing to point to its removal 
from Alexandria before the time of Menodotus, who is 
the teacher of Herodotus,^ and for many reasons to be 
considered the real teacher of Sextus. It was Menodo- 
tus who perfected the Empirical doctrines, and who 
brought about an ofiScial union between Scepticism and 

' Fabriciua <fo Sexto Empirico Testimonia. 
" Diog. IX. 12, U6. 

2 



18 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

^^mpiricism, and who gave Pyrrlionism in great measure, 
the ^clat that it enjoyed in Alexandria, and who 
appears to have been the most powerful influence in 
the school, from the time of Aenesidemus to that of 
Sextus. Furthermore, Sextus' familiarity with Alexan- 
drian customs bears the imprint of original knowledge, 
and he cannot, as Zeller implies, be accepted as simply 
quoting. One could hardly agree with Zeller,'^ that 
the familiarity shown by Sextus with the customs of 
both Alexandria and Rome in the Hypotyposes does 
not necessarily show that he ever lived in either of 
those places, because a large part of his works are com- 
pilations from other books; but on the contrary, the 
careful reader of Sextus' works must find in all of them 
much evidence of personal knowledge of Alexandria, 
Athens and Rome. 

A part of Sextus' books also may have been written 
in Alexandria. JT/so? ^vai,Kov<; could have been written 
in Alexandria.^ If these were also lectures, then Sextus 
taught in Alexandria as well as elsewhere. The history of 
Eastern literature for the centuries immediately follow- 
ing the time of Sextus, showing as it does in so many 
instances the influence of Pyrrhonism, and a knowledge 
of the Hypotyposes, furnishes us with an incontestable 
proof that the school could not have been for a long 
time removed from the East, and the absence of such 
knowledge in Roman literature is also a strong argu- 
ment against its long continuance in that city. It 
would seem, however, from all the data at command, 

• Zeller Op. cit. iii. p. 39. 

^ Pappenheim Sitz der Skeptiachen Schule ; Archiv fur Oeaehichte der 
Phil., 1888; Adv. Math. x. 15, 95. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 19 

that during the years that the Sceptical School was 
removed from Alexandria, its head quarters were 
in Rome, and that the Pyrrhonean Hypotyposes were 
delivered in Rome. Let us briefly consider the argu- 
ments in favour of such a hypothesis. Scepticism was 
not unknown in Rome. Pappenheim quotes the remark 
of Cicero that Pyrrhonism was long since dead, and the 
sarcasm of Seneca, Quis est qui tradat praecepta 
Pyrrhonis'? as an argument against the knowledge 
of Pyrrhonism in Rome. We must remember, however, 
that in Cicero's time Aenesidemus had not yet separated 
himself from the Academy; or if we consider the 
Lucius Tubero to whom Aenesidemus dedicated his 
works, as the same Lucius Tubero who was the friend 
of Cicero in his youth, and accordingly fix the date of 
Aenesidemus about 50 B.c.,^ even then Aenesidemus' 
work in Alexandria was too late to have necessarily been 
known to Cicero, whose remark must have been referred 
to the old school of Scepticism. Should we grant, how- 
ever, that the statements of Cicero and Seneca prove 
that in their time Pyrrhonism was extinct in Rome, 
they certainly do not show that after their death it 
could not have again revived, for the Hypotyposes 
were delivered more than a century after the death of 
Seneca. There are very few writers in Aenesidemus' 
own time who showed any influence of his teachings.^ 
This influence was felt later, as Pyrrhonism became 
better known. That Pyrrhonism received some atten- 
tion in Rome before the time of Sextus is nevertheless 
demonstrated by the teachings of Favorinus there. 

' Zeller Op. cit. HI. 10. ^ Zeller Op. cit. p. 63. 



20 Sextus Em'piricus and Greek Scepticism,. 

Although Favorinus was known as an Academician, 
the title of his principal work was tous (f>t\o<ro(f>ov/jLivov^ 
avTm Twf Xoymv, &v apiaToc ol Uvppdiveioi.?- Suidas 
calls Favorinus a great author and learned in all science 
and philosophy,^ and Favorinus made Rome the centre 
of his teaching and writing. His date is fixed by Zeller 
: at 80-150 A.D., therefore Pyrrhonism was known in 

Rome shortly before the time of Sextus. 
[ The whole tone of the Hypotyposes, with the 
I constant references to the Stoics as living present 
opponents, shows that these lectures must have been 
delivered in one of the centres of Stoicism. As Alex- 
andria and Athens are out of the question, all testimony 
points to Rome as having been the seat of the Pyrrho- 
nean School, for at least a part of the time that Sextus 
was at its head. We would then accept the teacher of 
Sextus, in whose place he says he taught, as the Hero- 
dotus so often referred to by Galen^ who lived in Rome. 
Sextus' frequent references to Asclepiades, whom he 
mentions ten different times by name in his works,* 
speak in favour of Rome in the matter under discussion, 
as Asclepiades made that city one of the centres of 
medical culture. On the other hand, the fact that 
there is no trace of the Hypotyposes in later Roman 
literature, with the one exception of the works of Hip- 
polytus, as opposed to the wide-spread knowledge of 
them shown in the East for centuries, is incontestable 
historical proof that the Sceptical School could not long 
have had its seat at Rome. From the two passages 
given above from Sextus' work against physics, he must 

' Zellpr Op. cit. p. 67. ^ Galen vrii. 751. 

2 Broohard Op. cit. 329. ■• Bekker Index. 



Historical Relations of Sextus Empiricus. 21 

either have written that book in Alexandria, it would 
seem, or have quoted those passages from some other 
work. May we not then conclude, that Sextus was at 
the head of the school in Rome for a short time, where 
it may have been removed temporarily, on account of 
the difficulty with the Empiricists, implied in Hyp. I. 
236-241, or in order to be better able to attack the 
Stoics, but that he also taught in Alexandria, where the 
real home of the school was certainly found ? There it 
probably came to an end about fifty years after the time 
of Sextus, and from that centre the Sceptical works of 
Sextus had their wide-spread influence in the East. 

The books of Sextus Empiricus furnish us with the 
best and fullest presentation of ancient Scepticism 
which has been preserved to modern times, and give 
Sextus the position of one of the greatest men of the 
Sceptical School. His works which are still extant are 
the Pyrrhonean Hypotyposes in three volumes, and the 
two works comprising eleven books which have been 
united in later times under the title of tt/jo? iJLa6r)fj,aTi- 
Kov'i, one of which is directed against the sciences in 
general, and the other against the dogmatic philoso- 
phers. The six books composing the first of these are 
written respectively against grammarians, rhetoricians, 
geometricians, arithmeticians, astronomers and music- 
ians. The five books of the latter consist of two 
against the logicians, two against physics, and one 
against systems of morals. If the last short work of 
the first book directed against the arithmeticians is com- 
bined with the one preceding against the geometricians, 
as it well could be, the two works together would be 
divided into ten different parts; there is evidence to 



22 Sextus JSmpiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

show that in ancient times such a division was made.^ 
There were two other works of Sextus which are now 
lost, the medical work before referred to, and a book 
entitled irepl ■^v^';. The character of the extant 
works of Sextus is similar, as they are all directed 
either against science or against the dogmatics, and 
they all present the negative side of Pyrrhonism. The 
vast array of arguments comprising the subject-matter, 
often repeated in the same and different forms, are 
evidently taken largely from the Sceptical works which 
Sextus had resource to, and are, in fact, a summing up 
of all the wisdom of the Sceptical School. The style of 
these books is fluent, and the Greek reminds one of 
Plutarch and Thucydides, and although Sextus does 
not claim originality, but presents in all cases the argu- 
ments of the Sceptic, yet the illustrations and the 
form in which the arguments are presented, often bear 
the marks of his own thought, and are characterized 
here and there by a wealth of humor that has not been 
sufiSciently noticed in the critical works on Sextus. Of 
all the authors who have reviewed Sextus, Brochard is 
the only one who seems to have understood and appre- 
ciated his humorous side. 

We shall now proceed to the consideration of the 
general position and aim of Pyrrhonism. 

' Diog. IX. 12, 116. 



CHAPTER TI. 

The Position and Aiin of Pyrrhonism. 

The first volume of the Pyrrhonean Hypotyposes 
gives the most complete statement found in any of the 
works of Sextus Empiricus of the teachings of Pyrrho- 
nism and its relation to other schools of philosophy. 
The chief source of the subject-matter presented is a 
work of the same name hy Aenesidemus/ either directly 
used by Sextus, or through the writings of those who 
followed Aen esidemus. The comprehensive title Uvppm- 
veiot, uTroTVTTtoo-et? was very probably used in general to 
designate courses of lectures given by the leaders of the 
Sceptical School. 

In the opening chapters of the Hypotyposes Sextus 
undertakes to define the position and aim of Pyrrho- 
nism.^ In introducing his subject he treats briefly of 
the differences between philosophical schools, dividing 
them into three classes; those which claim that they 
have found the truth, like the schools of Aristotle and 
Epicurus and the Stoics; those which deny the possibility 
of finding it, like that of the Academicians ; and those 
that still seek it, like the Sceptical School. The accu- 
sation against the Academicians, that they denied the 
possibility of finding the truth, was one that the Sceptics 
were very fond of making. We shall discuss the justice 
of it later, simply remarking here, that to affirm the 

• Diog. IX. 11, 78. 2 Bi/p. i. 3, 4. 



24 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

" incomprehensibility of the unknown," was a form of 
expression that the Pyrrhonists themselves were some- 
times betrayed into, notwithstanding their careful 
avoidance of dogmatic statements.^ 

After defining the three kinds of philosophy as the 
Dogmatic, the Academic and the Sceptic, Sextus re- 
minds his hearers that he does not speak dogmatically 
in anything that he says, but that he intends simply to 
present the Sceptical arguments historically, and as 
they appear to him. He characterizes his treatment of 
the subject as general rather than critical, including a 
statement of the character of Scepticism, its idea, its 
principles, its manner of reasoning, its criterion and 
aim, and a presentation of the Tropes, or aspects of 
doubt, and the Sceptical formulae and the distinction 
between Scepticism and the related schools of philo- 
sophy.^ 

The result of all the gradual changes which the 
development of thought had brought about in the out- 
ward relations of the Sceptical School, was to increase 
the earnestness of the claim of the. Sceptics to be simply 
followers of Pyrrho, the great founder of the movement. 
In discussing the names given to the Sceptics, Sextus 
gives precedence very decidedly to the title "Pyrrho- 
nean," because Pyrrho appears the best representative 
of Scepticism, and more prominent than all who before 
him occupied themselves with it.^ 

It was a question much discussed among philoso- 
phers in ancient times, whether Pyrrhonism should be 
considered a philosophical sect or not. Thus we find 

' Adv. Math. viii. 191. * S^p. i. 5, 6. 3 fff/p. i. 7. 



The Position and Aiin of Pyrrhonism. 25 

that Hippobotus in his work entitled irepX alpiaemv, 
written shortly before our era, does not include Pyrrho- 
nism among the other sects.^ Diogenes himself, after 
some hesitation remarking that many do not consider 
it a sect, finally decides to call it so.^ 

Sextus in discussing this subject calls Scepticism an 
aywyT], or a movement, rather than a a"peen<;, saying 
that Scepticism is not a sect, if that word implies a 
systematic arrangement of dogmas, for the Sceptic has \ 
no dogmas. If, however, a sect may mean simply the i 
following of a certain system of reasoning according to 
what appears to be true, then Scepticism is a sect.* 
From a quotation given later on by Sextus from 
Aenesidemus, we know that the latter used the term 
070)77?'.* Sextus gives also the other titles, so well known 
as having been applied to Scepticism, namely, ^rjTrjriKTJ, 
i<j)eKTiKi], and aTToprjTiKrj.^ The Swa/iis^ of Scepticism 
is to oppose the things of sense and intellect in every 
possible way to each other, and through the equal 
weight of things opposed, or laoa-Oeveia, to reach first 
the state of suspension of judgement, and afterwards 
ataraxia, or " repose and tranquillity of soul."^ The pur- 
pose of Scepticism is then the hope of ataraxia, and its 
origin was in the troubled state of mind induced by the 
inequality of things, and uncertainty in regard to the 
truth. Therefore, says Sextus, men of the greatest 
talent began the Sceptical system by placing in opposi- 
tion to every argument an equal one, thus leading to a 

* Diog. Pro. 19. 5 Syp, j. 7; Biog. ix. 11, 70. 

* Diog. iVo. 20. ^ St/p. I. 8. 

' Syp. I. 16, 17. ' Sw- 1- 10- 

* Byp. I. 210. 



26 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

philosophical system without a dogma, for the Sceptic 
claims that he has no dogma.^ The Sceptic is never 
supposed to state a decided opinion, but only to say 
what appears to him. Even the Sceptical formulae, 
such as "Nothing more,"^ or "I decide nothing,"^ or 
■"All is false," include themselves with other things. 
The only statements that the Sceptic can make, are in 
regard to his own sensations. He cannot deny that he 
is warm or cold or hungry. 

Sextus replies to the charge that the Sceptics deny 
phenomena by refuting it.* The Sceptic does not deny 
phenomena, because they are the only criteria by which 
he can regulate his actions. " We call the criterion of 
the Sceptical School the phenomenon, meaning by this 
name the idea of it."° Phenomena are the only things 
which the Sceptic does not deny, and he guides his life 
by them. They are, however, subjective. Sextus dis- 
tinctly affirms that sensations are the phenomena,^ and 
that they lie in susceptibility and voluntary feeling, 
-and that they constitute the appearances of objects.' 
We see from this that Sextus makes the only reality to 
consist in subjective experience, but he does not follow 
this to its logical conclusion, and doubt the existence of 
anything outside of mind. He rather takes for granted 
that there is a something unknown outside, about which 
the Sceptic can make no assertions. Phenomena are 
the criteria according to which the Sceptic orders his 
daily life, as he cannot be entirely inactive, and they 

» Syp. I. 12. " Syp. i. 19. 

2 Hyp. I. 14. « Hyp. i. 22; Diog. ix. U, 106. 

3 Byp. I. 14. ' Hyp. i. 22. 
* Hyp. I. 19. 



The Position and Ai/m of Pyrrhonism. 27 



affect life in four different ways. They constitute the 
guidance of nature, the impulse of feeling; they give 
rise to the traditions of customs and laws, and make 
the teaching of the arts important.^ According to the 
tradition of laws and customs, piety is a good in daily 
life, but it is not in itself an abstract good. The Sceptic 
■of Sextus' time also inculcated the teaching of the arts, 
as indeed must be the case with professing physicians, 
as most of the leading Sceptics were. Sextus says, 
" We are not without energy in the arts which we 
undertake."^ This was a positive tendency which no 
philosophy, however negative, could escape, and the 
Sceptic tried to avoid inconsistency in this respect, by 
separating his philosophy ft-om his theory of life. His 
philosophy controlled his opinions, and his life was 
governed by phenomena. 

The aim of Pyrrhonism was ataraxia in those things 
which pertain to opinion, and moderation in the things 
which life imposes.^ In other words, we find here the 
same natural desire of the human being to rise above 
and beyond the limitations which pain and passion 
impose, which is expressed in other forms, and under 
other names, in other schools of philosophy. The 
method, however, by which ataraxia or peace of mind 
could be reached, was peculiar to the Sceptic. It is a 
state of psychological equilibrium, which results from 
the equality of the weight of different arguments that 
are opposed to each other, and the consequent impossi- 
bility of affirming in regard to either one, that it is 
correct.* The discovery of ataraxia was, in the first 

' Syp. I. 23. '^ Syp. i. 24. ^ Byp. i. 25. « Syp. i. 26. 



28 Sextua Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

instance, apparently accidental, for while the Sceptic 
withheld his opinion, unable to decide what things were 
true, and what things were false, ataraxia fortunately- 
followed.^ After he had begun to philosophize, with a 
desire to discriminate in regard to ideas, and to separate 
the true from the false^ during the time of 67ro%»?, or 
suspension of judgement, ataraxia followed as if by 
chance, as the shadow follows the body.' 

The Sceptic in seeking ataraxia in the things of 
opinion, does not entirely escape from suffering from 
his sensations. He is not wholly undisturbed, for he is 
sometimes cold and hungry, and so on.* He claims, 
nevertheless, that he suffers less than the dogmatist, 
who is beset with two kinds of suffering, one from the 
feelings themselves, and also from the conviction that 
they are by nature an evil.^ To the Sceptic nothing is 
in itself either an evil or a good, and so he thinks that 
" he escapes from diflSculties easier."^ For instance, he 
who considers riches a good in themselves, is unhappy 
in the loss of them, and in possession of them is in fear 
of losing them, while the Sceptic, remembering the 
Sceptical saying " No more," is untroubled in whatever 
condition he may be found, as the loss of riches is no 
more an evil than the possession of them is a good.'^ 
For he who considers anything good or bad by nature 
is always troubled, and when that which seemed good is 
not present with him, he thinks that he is tortured by 
that which is by nature bad, and follows after what he 

' Bi/p. I. 26. < Hi/p. 1. 30. 

2 Diog. IX. 11, 107. « Syp. i. 30. 

3 Syp. 1. 29. « Spy. I. 30 ; Diog. ix. 11, 61. 

' Adv. Math. xi. 146—160. 



The Position and Aim, of Pyrrhonism. 29 

thinks to be good. Having acquired it, however, he is 
not at rest, for his reason tells him that a sudden change 
may deprive him of this thing that he considers a good.^ 
The Sceptic, however, endeavours neither to avoid nor 
seek anything eagerly.^ 

Ataraxia came to the Sceptic as success in painting 
the foam on a horse's mouth came to Apelles the painter. 
After many attempts to do this, and many failures, he 
gave up in despair, and threw the sponge at the picture 
that he had used to wipe the colors from the painting 
with. As soon as it touched the picture it produced a 
representation of the foam.^ Thus the Sceptics were 
never able to attain to ataraxia by examining the 
anomaly between the phenomena and the things of 
thought, but it came to them of its own accord just 
when they despaired of finding it. 

The intellectual preparation for producing ataraxia, 
consists in placing arguments in opposition to each 
other, both in regard to phenomena, and to things of the 
intellect. By placing the phenomenal in opposition to 
the phenomenal, the intellectual to the intellectual, and 
the phenomenal to the intellectual, and vice versa, the 
present to the present, past, and future, one will find 
that no argument exists that is incontrovertible. It is 
not necessary to accept any statement whatever as true, 
and consequently a state of cttox'? may always be main- 
tained.* Although ataraxia concerns things of the 
opinion, and must be preceded by the intellectual pro- 
cess described above, it is not itself a function of the 
intellect, or any subtle kind of reasoning, but seems to 

1 Myp. I. 27. ' Myp. i. 28. ^ 2rj(p. i. 28, 29. * Byp. i. 32—35. 



30 Sextus Empiricus avd Greek Scepticism. 

be rather a unique form of moral perfection, leading to 
happiness, or is itself happiness. 

It was the aim of Scepticism to know nothing, and 
to assert nothing in regard to any subject, but at the 
same time not to affirm that knowledge on all subjects 
is impossible, and consequently to have the attitude of 
still seeking. The standpoint of Pyrrhonism was ma- 
terialistic. We find from the teachings of Sextus that 
he affirmed the non-existence of the soul,^ or the ego, 
and denied absolute existence altogether.^ The intro- 
ductory statements of Diogenes regarding Pyrrhonism 
would agree with this standpoint.^ 

There is no criterion of truth in Scepticism. We 
cannot prove that the phenomena represent objects, or 
find out what the relation of phenomena to objects is. 
There is no criterion to tell us which one is true of all 
the difiierent representations of the same object, and of 
all the varieties of sensation that arise through the 
many phases of relativity of the conditions which con- 
trol the character of the phenomena. 

Every effort to find the truth can deal only with 
phenomena, and absolute reality can never be known. 

> Adv. Math. vii. 55 ; Syp. ii. 32. » Adv. Math. xi. 140. 

■• Diog. IX. U, 61. 



CHAPTER III. 

The Sceptical Tropes. 

The exposition of the Tropes of Pyrrhonism consti- 
tutes historically and philosophically the most important 
part of the writings of Sextus Empiricus. These Tropes 
represent the sum total of the wisdom of the older 
Sceptical School, and were held in high respect for 
centuries, not only by the Pyrrhoneans, but also by many 
outside the narrow limits of that School. In the first 
book of the Hypotyposes Sextus gives two classes of 
Tropes, those of eiroxn and the eight Tropes of Aeneside- 
mus against Aetiology. 

The Tropes of eTroxv are arranged in groups of ten, 
five and two, according to the period of the Sceptical 
School to which they belong ; the first of these groups 
is historically the most important, or the Ten Tropes of 
eTToxv, as these are far more closely connected with the 
general development of Scepticism, than the later ones. 
By the name rpoTro? or Trope, the Sceptic understood a 
manner of thought, or form of argument, or standpoint 
of judgement. It was a term common in Greek philo- 
sophy, used in this sense, from the time of Aristotle.^ 
The Stoics, however, used the word with a different 
meaning from that attributed to it by the Sceptics.^ 
Stephanus and Fabricius translate it by the Latin word 
nnodus,^ and rpoTro? also is often used interchangeably 

' Pappenheim Erlauterung Pyrrh. Grundzugen, p. 35. 

^ Diog. I. 76 ; Ad^. Math. viii. 227. * Fabricius, Cap. xiv. 7. 



32 Sextus ETnpiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

with the word \070s by Sextus, Diogenes Laertius, and 
others; sometimes also as synonymous with totto^,^ 
and TVTTos is found in the oldest edition of Sextus.^ 
Diogenes defines the word as the standpoint, or manner 
of argument, by which the Sceptics arrived at the 
condition of doubt, in consequence of the equality of 
probabilities, and he calls the Tropes, the ten Tropes of 
doubt.^ All writers on Pyrrhonism after the time of 
Aenesidemus give the Tropes the principal place in 
their treatment of the subject. Sextus occupies two 
thirds of the first book of the Hypotyposes in stating 
and discussing them ; and about one fourth of his pre- 
'sentation of Scepticism is devoted to the Tropes by 
Diogenes. In addition to these two authors, Aristocles 
,the Peripatetic refers to them in his attack on Sceptic- 
ism.* Favorinus wrote a book entitled Pyrrhonean 
Tropes, and Plutarch one called The Ten [roTroi) 
Topes of Pyrrho? Both of these latter works are lost. 
All authorities unite in attributing to Aenesidemus 
the work of systematizing and presenting to the world 
the ten Tropes of i-n-ox^' He was the first to conceive 
the project of opposing an organized philosophical 
system of Pyrrhonism to the dogmatism of his contem- 
poraries.* Moreover, the fact that Diogenes introduces 
the Tropes into his life of Pyrrho, does not necessarily 
imply that he considered Pyrrho their author, for 



' ff^p. I. 36. 

' Fabrieiua on Syp. i. 36 ; Cap. xiv. Q. 

3 Diog. IX. 11, 79—108. 

* Aristocles Euaeb. praep. ev. x. 14, 18. 

' Fabricius on Syp. i. 36. 

° Compare Saisset Op. eit. p. 78. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 33 

Diogenes invariably combines the teachings of the follow- 
ers of a movement with those of the founders themselves ; 
he gives these Tropes after speaking of Aenesidemus' 
work entitled Pyrrhonean ITypotyposes, and appar- 
ently quotes from this book, in giving at least a part 
of his presentation of Pyrrhonism, either directly or 
through the works of others. Nietzsche proposes a 
correction of the text of Diogenes ix. ii., 79, which 
would make him quote the Tropes from a book by 
Theodosius,-^ author of a commentary on the works of 
Theodas. No writer of antiquity claims for the Tropes 
an older source than the books of Aenesidemus, to 
whom Aristocles also attributes them.^ They are not 
mentioned in Diogenes' life of Timon, the immediate 
disciple of Pyrrho. Cicero has no knowledge of them, 
and does not refer to them in his discussion of Scepticism. 
Aenesidemus was undoubtedly the first to formulate 
these Tropes, but many things tend to show that they 
resulted, in reality, from the gradual classification of 
the results of the teachings of Pyrrho, in the subsequent 
development of thought from his own time to that of 
Aenesidemus. The ideas contained in the Tropes were 
not original with Aenesidemus, but are more closely 
connected with the thought of earlier times. The 
decidedly empirical character of the Tropes proves this 
connection, for the eight Tropes of Aetiology, which 
were original with Aenesidemus, bear a far stronger 
dialectic stamp, thus showing a more decided dialectic 
influence of the Academy than is found in the Tropes 
of iiroxv- Many of the illustrations given of the Tropes 

1 Brochard Op. cit. 254, Note 4. 

' AriBtocles Eus.praep. ev, xiv. 18. 8. 



34 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

also, testify to a time of greater antiquity than that of 
Aenesidemus. The name Trope was well known in 
ancient times, and the number ten reminds us of the 
ten opposing principles of Pythagoras, and the ten 
categories of Aristotle, the fourth of which was the same 
as the eighth Trope. The terminology, however, with 
very few exceptions, points to a later period than that 
of Pyrrho. Zeller points out a number of expressions 
in both Diogenes' and Sextus' exposition of the Tropes, 
which could not date back farther than the time of 
Aenesidemus.^ One of the most striking features of 
the whole presentation of the Tropes, especially as given 
by Sextus, is their mosaic character, stamping them not 
as the work of one person, but as a growth, and also an 
agglutinous growth, lacking very decidedly the sym- 
metry of thought that the work of one mind would have 
shown. 

At the time of the separation of Pyrrhonism from the 
Academy, no other force was as strong in giving life to 
the school as the systematic treatment by Aenesidemus 
of the Ten Tropes of eiroxv- The reason of this is 
evident. It was not that the ideas of the Sceptical 
Tropes were original with Aenesidemus, but because a 
definite statement of belief is always a far more powerful 
influence than principles which are vaguely understood 
and accepted. There is always, however, the danger to 
the Sceptic, in making a statement even of the prin- 
ciples of Scepticism, that the psychological result would 
be a dogmatic tendency of mind, as we shall see later 
was the case, even with Aenesidemus himself. That 

' Zeller Op. cit. p. 25. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 35 

the Sceptical School could not escape the accusation of 
dogmatizing, from the Dogmatics, even in stating the 
grounds of their Scepticism, we know from Diogenes.'- 
To avoid this dogmatic tendency of the ten Tropes, 
Sextus makes the frequent assertion that he does not 
affirm things to be absolutely true, but states them as 
they appear to him, and that they may be otherwise 
from what he has said.^ 

Sextus tells us that " Certain Tropes, ten in number, 
for producing the state of eTrox^ have been handed 
down from the older Sceptics."^ He refers to them in 
another work as the "Tropes of Aenesidemus."* There 
is no evidence that the substance of these Tropes was 
changed after the time of Aenesidemus, although many 
of the illustrations given by Sextus must have been of 
a later date, added during the two centuries that elapsed 
between the time of Aenesidemus and Sextus. In 
giving these Tropes Sextus does not claim to offer a 
systematic methodical classification, and closes his list 
of them, in their original concise form, with the remark, 
" We make this order ourselves."^ The order is given 
differently by Diogenes, and also by Favorinus.* The 
Trope which Sextus gives as the tenth is the fifth 
given by Diogenes, the seventh by Sextus is the eighth 
given by Diogenes, the fifth by Sextus, the seventh 
by Diogenes, the tenth by Diogenes, the eighth by 
Sextus. Diogenes says that the one he gives as the 
ninth Favorinus calls the eighth, and Sextus and 
Aenesidemus the tenth. This statement does not 

> Diog. IX. 11, 102. * Adv. Math. vii. 345. 

2 B^p. I. 4, 24. 5 Syp. i. 38. 

3 ffi/p. I. 36. " Diog. IX. 11. 87. 



36 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

correspond with the list of the Tropes which Sextus 
gives, proving that Diogenes took some other text than 
that of Sextus as his authority.^ The difference in the 
order of the Tropes shows, also, that the order was not 
considered a matter of great importance. There is a 
marked contrast in the spirit of the two presentations 
of the Tropes given by Sextus and Diogenes. The 
former gives them not only as an orator, but as one who 
feels that he is defending his own cause, and the school 
of which he is the leader, against mortal enemies, while 
Diogenes relates them as an historian. 

Pappenheim tries to prove^ that Aenesidemus origin- 
ally gave only nine Tropes in his Pyrrhonean Hypoty- 
poses, as Aristocles mentions only nine in referring to 
the Tropes of Aenesidemus, and that the tenth was 
added later. Had this been the case, however, the fact 
would surely have been mentioned either by Diogeoes 
or Sextus, who both refer to the ten Tropes of Aene- 
sidemus. 

The Tropes claim to prove that the character of 
phenomena is so relative and changeable, that certain 
knowledge cannot be based upon them, and as we have 
shown, there is no other criterion of knowledge for the 
Sceptic than phenomena.^ All of the Trop.es, except 
the tenth, are connected with sense-perception, and re- 
late to the difference of the results obtained through 
the senses under different circumstances. They may 
be divided into two classes, i.e., those based upon differ- 
ences of our physical organism, and those based upon 

1 Diog. IX. 11, 87. 

2 Pappenheim, Die Tropen der Oriechen, p. 23. 

3 Hyp. I. 22. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 37 

external differences. To the first class belong the first, 
second, third and fourth ; to the second class, the fifth, 
sixth, seventh and eighth, and also the ninth. The 
eighth, or that of relation, is applied objectively both 
by Sextus and Diogenes in their treatment of the Tropes, 
and is not used for objects of thought alone, but princi- 
pally to show the relation of outward objects to each 
other. The tenth is the only one which has a moral 
significance, and it has also a higher subjective value 
than the others ; it takes its arguments from an entirely 
different sphere of thought, and deals with metaphysical 
and religious contradictions in opinion, and with the 
question of good and evil. That this Trope is one of 
the oldest, we know from its distinct mention in connec- 
tion with the foundation theories of Pyrrho, by Dio- 
genes.^ In treating of the subjective reasons for doubt 
as to the character of external reality, the Sceptics were 
very near the denial of all outward reality, a point, how- 
ever, which they never quite reached. 

There is evidently much of Sextus' own thought mixed 
with the illustrations of the Tropes, but it is impossible 
to separate the original parts from the material that 
was the common property of the Sceptical School. 
Many of these illustrations show, however, perfect famil- 
iarity with the scientific and medical teachings of the 
time. Before entering upon his exposition of the Tropes, 
Sextus gives them in the short concise form in which 
they must first have existed^ — 

(i) Based upon the variety of animals, 
(ii) Based upon the differences between men. 

1 Diog. IX. 11, 61. " Hyp. i. 36—38. 



38 Sextus Errypiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

(iii) Based upon dififerences in the constitution of 
the sense organs. 

(iv) Based upon circumstances. 

(v) Based upon position, distance and place. 

(vi) Based upon mixtures. 

(vii) Based upon the quantities and constitutions 
of objects. 

(viii) Relation. 

(ix) Based upon frequency or rarity of occurences, 
(x) Based upon systems, customs and laws, 
mythical beliefs, and dogmatic opinions. 

Although Sextus is careful not to dogmatise regard- 
ing the arrangement of the Tropes, yet there is in his 
classification of them a regular gradation, from the argu- 
ments based upon differences in animals to those in 
man, first considering the latter in relation to the physi- 
cal constitution, and then to circumstances outside of 
us, and finally the treatment of metaphysical and moral 
differences. 

The First Trope} That the same mental repre- 
sentations are not found in different animals, may be 
inferred from their differences in constitution resulting 
from their diSerent origins, and from the variety in 
their organs of sense. Sextus takes up the five senses 
in order, giving illustrations to prove the relative results 
of the mental representations in all of them, as for 
example the subjectivity of color^ and sound.* All 
knowledge of objects through the senses is relative and 
not absolute. Sextus does not, accordingly, confine the 
impossibility of certain knowledge to the qualities that 

' Sffp. I. 40—61. ■" Syp. 1. 44—46. ^ ^j,^, ,_ gg. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 39 

Locke regards as secondary, but includes also the prim- 
ary ones in this statement.^ The form and shape of 
objects as they appear to us may be changed by pressure 
on the eyeball. Furthermore, the character of reflect- 
ions in mirrors depend entirely on their shape, as the 
images in concave mirrors are very different from those 
in convex ones; and so in the same way as the eyes 
of animals are of different shapes, and supplied with 
different fluids, the ideas of dogs, fishes, men and grass- 
hoppers must be very different.^ 

In discussing the mental representations of animals 
of different grades of intelligence, Sextus shows a very 
good comprehension of the philogenetic development of 
the organs of sense, and draws the final conclusion that 
external objects are regarded differently by animals, 
according to their difference in constitution.^ These 
differences in the ideas which different animals have of 
the same objects are demonstrated by their different 
tastes, as the things desired by some are fatal to others.* 
The practical illustrations given of this result show a 
familiarity with natural history, and cognizance of the 
tastes and habits of many animals,^ but were probably 
few of them original with Sextu-s, unless perhaps in 
their application ; that this train of reasoning was the 
common property of the Sceptic School, we know from 
the fact that Diogenes begins his exposition of the first 
Trope in a way similar to that of Sextus.'' His illustra- 
tions are, however, few and meagre compared with those 
of Sextus, and the scientific facts used by both of them 

• Syp. I. 47. * Syp. i. 55. 

2 Hyp. 1. 49. 6 B.yp. i. 55—59. 

3 Hyp. I. 54. « Diog. vs.. 11, 79—80. 



40 Sextus ETTipiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

may mostly be found in other authors of antiquity given 
in a similar way.^ The logical result of the reasoning 
used to explain the first Trope, is that we cannot com- 
pare the ideas of the animals with each other, nor with 
our own; nor can we prove that our ideas are more trust- 
worthy than those of the animals.^ As therefore an 
examination of ideas is impossible, any decided opinion 
about their trustworthiness is also impossible, and this 
Trope leads to the suspension of judgment regarding 
external objects, or to iiroxij-^ 

After reaching this conclusion, Sextus introduces a 
long chapter to prove that animals can reason. There 
is no reference to this in Diogenes, but there is other 
testimony to show that it was a favourite line of argu- 
ment with the Sceptics.* Sextus, however, says that 
his course of reasoning is different from that of most 
of the Sceptics on the subject,^ as they usually applied 
their arguments to all animals, while he selected only 
one, namely the dog.® This chapter is full of sarcastic 
attacks on the Dogmatics, and contains the special 
allusion to the Stoics as the greatest opponents of the 
Sceptics, which has been before referred to.' 

Sextus claims with a greater freedom of diction than 
in some apparently less original chapters, and with a 
wealth of special illustrations, that the dog is superior 
to man in acuteness of perception,^ that he has the 
power of choice, and possesses an art, that of hunting,® 



' Pappenheim Erlautermig Fyrr. GrundxUffe Far. 41. 

2 Byp. I. 69. « Hyp. i. 62—6 

3 Syp. 1. 61. ' Byp. i. 66. 
1 Eyp. I. 238. 8 Hyp. i. 64. 
^ Compare Brochard Op. dt. 266. » Syp. i. 66. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 41 

and, also, is not deprived of virtue,-^ as the true nature of 
virtue is to show justice to all, which the dog does by 
guarding loyally those who are kind to him, and keep- 
ing off those who do evil.^ The reasoning power of this 
animal is proved by the story taken from Chrysippus, of 
the dog that came to a meeting of three roads in follow- 
ing a scent. After seeking the scent in vain in two 
of the roads, he takes the third road without scenting 
it, as a result of a quick process of thought, which proves 
that he shares in the famous dialectic of Chrysippus,^ 
the five forms of avairoSeiKToi \6yoi, of which the dog 
chooses the fifth. Either A or B or C, not A or B, 
therefore C. 

The dog and other irrational animals may also 
possess spoken language, as the only proof that we have 
to the contrary, is the fact that we cannot understand 
the sounds that they make.* We have an example in 
this chapter of the humor of Sextus, who after enlarging 
on the perfect character of the dog, remarks, "For which 
reason it seems to me some philosophers have honoured 
themselves with the name of this animal,"^ thus making 
a sarcastic allusion to the Cynics, especially Antisthenes.® 

The Second Trope. Passing on to the second Trope, 
Sextus aims to prove that even if we leave the differen- 
ces of the mental images of animals out of the discussion, 
there is not a sufficient unanimity in the mental images 
of human beings to allow us to base any assertions upon 
them in regard to the character of external objects.'^ 

1 Hyp. I. 67. = Siyp. i. 72. 

2 Hyp. I. 67. * Diog. vi. 1, 13. 

3 Hyp. 1. 69 ; Hyp. ii. 156 ; Diog. vii. 1, 79. ' Hyp. i. 79. 

4 Hyp. I. 74. 



42 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

He had previously announced that he intended to 
oppose the phenomenal to the intellectual " in any way 
whatever,"^ so he begins here by referring to the two 
parts of which man is said to be composed, the soul and 
the body, and proceeds to discuss the differences among 
men in sense-perception and in opinion.^ Most of the 
illustrations givea of differences in sense-perception are 
medical ones; of the more general of these I will note 
the only two which are also given by Diogenes in his ex- 
position of this Trope,^ viz., Demophon, Alexander's table 
waiter, who shivered in the sun, and Andron the Argive, 
who was so free from thirst that he travelled through 
the desert of Libya without seeking a drink. Some 
have reasoned from the presence of the first of these 
illustrations in the exposition of the Tropes, that a part 
of this material at least goes back to the time of Pyrrho, 
as Pyrrho from his intimacy with Alexander, when he 
accompanied him to India, had abundant opportunities 
to observe the peculiarities of his servant Demophon.* 
The illustration of Andron the Argive is taken from 
Aristotle, according to Diogenes.^ 

Passing on to differences of opinion, we have another 
example of the sarcastic humor of Sextus, as he refers to 
the (j)vatoyv(o/jLoviKi] cro(f>la^ as the authority for believing 
that the body is a type of the soul. As the bodies of 
men differ, so the souls also probably differ. The differ- 
ences of mind among men is not referred to by Diogenes, 
except in the general statement that they choose 

' Si/p. 1. 8. " Syp. I. 80. 3 Dioj. ix. 11, 80—81. 

* Compare Pyrrhon et le Scepticism primitive, Sei'ite phil., Paris 1885, 
No. 5; Victor Brochard, p. 621. 

« Diog. IX. 11, 81. 8 Hyp. i. 86. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 43 

dififerent professions ; while Sextus elaborates this point, 
speaking of the great differences in opposing schools of 
philosophy, and in the objects of choice and avoidance, 
and sources of pleasure for different men.^ The poets 
well understand this marked difference in human 
desires, as Homer says, 

" One man enjoys this, another enjoys that." 

Sextus also quotes the beautiful lines of Pindar,^ 

" One delights in getting honours and crowns through stormfooted 

horses, 
Others in passing life in rooms rich in gold, 
Another safe travelling enjoys, in a swift ship, on a wave of the 

sea." 

The Third Trope. The third Trope limits the argu- 
ment to the sense-perceptions of one man, a Dogmatic, if 
preferred, or to one whom the Dogmatics consider wise,^ 
and states that as the ideas given by the different sense 
organs differ radically in a way that does not admit of 
their being compared with each other, they furnish no 
reliable testimony regarding the nature of objects.* 
" Each of the phenomena perceived by us seems to pre- 
sent itself in many forms, as the apple, smooth, fragrant 
brown and sweet." The apple was evidently the ordin- 
ary example given for this Trope, for Diogenes uses the 
same, but in a much more condensed form, and not with 
equal understanding of the results to be deduced from 
it.^ The consequence of the incompatibility of the men- 
tal representations produced through the several sense 

1 Eyp. I. 87—89. = Hyp, i. 86. ' Eyp. i. 90. 

* Hyp. I. 94. = Diog. ix. 11, 81. 



44 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

organs by the apple, may be the acceptance of either of 
the three following propositions: (i) That only those 
qualities exist in the apple which we perceive, (ii) 
That more than these exist, (iii) That even those per- 
ceived do not exist.^ Accordingly, any experience which 
can give rise to such different views regarding outward 
objects, cannot be relied upon as a testimony concerning 
them. 

The non-homogeneous nature of the mental images 
connected with the different sense organs, as presented 
by Sextus, reminds us of the discussion of the same 
subject by Berkeley in his Iheory of Vision. 

Sextus says that a man born with less than the usual 
number of senses, would form altogether different ideas 
of the external world than those who have the usual 
number, and as our ideas of objects depend on our 
mental images, a greater number of sense organs would 
give us still different ideas of outward reality.^ The 
strong argument of the Stoics against such reasoning as 
this, was their doctrine of pre-established harmony be- 
tween nature and the soul, so that when a representation 
is produced in us of a real object, a KaTaXrjirTiKf) 
(ftavTuaia,^ by this representation the soul grasps a real 
existence. There is a \6yo<; in us which is of the same 
kind, crvyyevos, or in relation to all nature. This argu- 
ment of pre-established harmony between the faculties 
of the soul and the objects of nature, is the one that 
has been used in all ages to combat philosophical teach- 
ing that denies that we apprehend the external world 
as it is. It was used against Kant by his opponents, 

1 Myp. I. 99. 2 Si/p. I. 96—97. ' Adv. Math. vii. 93. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 45 

■who thought in this way to refute his teachings.^ The 
Sceptics could not, of course, accept a theory of nature 
that included the soul and the external world in one 
harmonious whole, but Sextus in his discussion of the 
third Trope does not refute this argument as fully as he 
does later in his work against logic.^ He simply states 
here that philosophers themselves cannot agree as to 
what nature is, and furthermore, that a philosopher 
himself is a part of the discord, and to be judged, rather 
than being capable of judging, and that no conclusion 
can be reached by those who are themselves an element 
of the uncertainty.^ 

The Fourth Trope. This Trope limits the argu- 
ment to each separate sense, and the effect is considered 
of the condition of body and mind upon sense-perception / 
in relation to the several sense-organs.* The physical 
states which modify sense-perception are health and 
illness, sleeping and waking, youth and age, hunger and 
satiety, drunkenness and sobriety. All of these condi- 
tions of the body entirely change the character of the 
mental images, producing different judgments of the 
color, taste, and temperature of objects, and of the cha- 
racter of sounds. A man who is asleep is in a different 
world from one awake, the existence of both worlds 
being relative to the condition of waking and sleeping.^ 

The subjective states which Sextus mentions here 
as modifying the character of the mental representations 
are hating or loving, courage or fear, sorrow or joy, and 
sanity or insanity.® No man is ever twice in exactly 

' Ueberweg Op. eit. 195. * Hyp. i. 100. 

' Adv. Math. tii. 354. ' Syp. i. 104. 

^ Syp. I. 98—99. ^ Syp. i. 100. 



46 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

the same condition of body or mind, and never able to 
review the differences of his ideas as a sum total, for 
those of the present moment only are subject to careful 
inspection.^ Furthermore, no one is free from the in- 
fluence of all conditions of body or mind, so that he can 
be unbiassed to judge his ideas, and no criterion can be 
established that can be shown to be true, but on the 
contrary, whatever course is pursued on the subject, 
both the criterion and the proof will be thrown into the 
circulus in probanda, for the truth of each rests on 
the other. ^ 

Diogenes gives in part the same illustrations of this 
Trope, but in a much more condensed form. The marked 
characteristic of this train of reasoning is the attempt 
to prove that abnormal conditions are also natural. In 
referring at first to the opposing states of body and 
mind, which so change the character of sense-perception, 
Sextus classifies them according to the popular usage 
as Kara (pvatv and "jrapci <f)vcnv. This distinction was an 
important one, even with Aristotle, and was especially 
developed by the Stoics^ in a broader sense than 
referring merely to health and sickness. The Stoics, 
however, considered only normal conditions as being 
according to nature. Sextus, on the contrary, declares 
that abnormal states are also conditions according to 
nature,* and just as those who are in health are in a 
state that is natural to those who are in health, so also 
those not in health are in a state that is natural to 
those not in health, and in some respects according to 
nature. Existence, then, and non-existence are not 

^Syp. I. 112. '^Hyp.z.m. ^ Djog. yii. 1, 86. * Syp. \.10Z. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 47 

absolute, but relative, and the world of sleep as really 
exists for those who are asleep as the things that exist 
in waking exist, although they do not exist in sleep.^ 
One mental representation, therefore, cannot be judged 
by another, w^hich Ls also in a state of relation to exist- 
ing physical and mental conditions. Diogenes states 
this principle even more decidedly in his exposition of 
this Trope. "The insane are not in a condition opposed 
to nature ; why they more than we ? For we also see 
the sun as if it were stationary."^ Furthermore, in 
different periods of life ideas differ. Children are fond 
of balls and hoops, while those in their prime prefer 
other things, and the aged still others.^ The wisdom 
contained in this Trope in reference to the relative 
value of the things most sought after is not original 
with Sextus, but is found in the more earnest ethical 
teachings of older writers. Sextus does not, however, 
draw any moral conclusions from this reasoning, but 
only uses it as an argument for eVo^T;. 

The Fifth Trope. This Trope leaves the discussion 
of the dependence of the ideas upon the physical nature, 
and takes up the influence of the environment upon 
them. It makes the difference in ideas depend upon the 
position, distance, and place of objects, thus taking 
apparently their real existence for granted. Things 
change their form and shape according to the distance 
from which they are observed, and the position in which 
they stand.* 

The same light or tone alters decidedly in different 
surroundings. Perspective in paintings depends on the 

1 Hj(p. 1. 104. 2 Diog. IX. 11, 82. ^ Hyp. 1. 106. * Syp. i.\l8. 



48 Seodus Empiricus and Greeic Scepticism. 

angle at which the picture is suspended.^ With Dio- 
genes this Trope is the seventh,^ and his exposition of 
it is similar, but as usual, shorter. Both Sextus and 
Diogenes give the illustration^ of the neck of the dove 
differing in color in different degrees of inclination, an 
illustration used hy Protagoras also to prove the rela- 
tivity of perception by the senses. "The black neck 
of the dove in the shade appears black, but in the light 
sunny and purple."* Since, then, all phenomena are 
regarded in a certain place, and from a certain distance, 
and according to a certain position, each of which rela- 
tions makes a great difference with the mental images, 
we shall be obliged also by this Trope to come to the 
reserving of the opinion.^ 

The Sixth Trope. This Trope leads to eiro-x/i re- 
garding the nature of objects, because no object can 
ever be presented to the organs of sense directly, but 
must always be perceived through some medium, or in 
some mixture.® This mixture may be an outward one, 
connected with the temperature, or the rarity of the 
air, or the water' surrounding an object, or it may be a 
mixture resulting from the different humors of the 
sense-organs.® A man with the jaundice, for example, 
sees colors differently from one who is in health. "The 
illustration of the jaundice is a favorite one with the 
Sceptics. Diogenes uses it several times in his pre- 
sentation of Scepticism, and it occurs in Sextus' writings 

1 Syp. I. 120. * Diog. ix. 11, 85. 

3 Byp. 1. 120; Diog. ix. 11, 86. 

* Sekol. zu Arist. 60, 18, ed. Brandis; Fappen. Er. Pyrr. Onmdzuge 
p. 54. 

5 Hyp. I. 121. « Byp. i. 124. ' Byp. i. 126. » Byp. i. 126. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 49 

in all, as an illustration, in eight different places.^ The 
condition of the organ of the ■^•ye/jLoviKov, or the ruling 
faculty, may also cause mixtures. Pappenheim thinks 
that we have here Kant's idea of a priori, only on a 
materialistic foundation.^ A careful consideration of 
the passage, however, shows us that Sextus' thought 
is more in harmony with the discoveries of modern 
psychiatry than with the philosophy of Kant. If the 
sentence, tcro)? Se ical avrt] (^ '^lavoia] eTrifii^iav rtva 
ISiav TTOielrai Trpog to, vtto t&v aladtjcremv dva<y'ye\- 
XofjLeva,^ stood alone, without further explanation, it 
might well refer to a priori laws of thought, but the 
explanation which follows beginning with "because" 
makes that impossible.* " Because in each of the places 
where the Dogmatics think that the ruling faculty is, 
we see present certain humors, which are the cause of 
mixtures.'' Sextus does not advance any opinion as to 
the place of the ruling faculty in the body, which is, 
according to the Stoics, the principal part of the soul, 
where ideas, desires, and reasoning originate,^ but 
simply refers to the two theories of the Dogmatics, 
which claim on the one hand that it is in the brain, 
and on the other that it is in the heart.^ This subject 
he deals with more fully in his work against logic.'^ As, 
however, he bases his argument, in discussing possible 
intellectual mixtures in illustration of the sixth Trope, 
entirely on the condition of the organ of the intellect, it 
is evident that his theory of the soul was a materialistic 
one. 

' See Index to Bekker's edition of Sextus. 

2 Papp. JBr. JPyr. Gr. p. 55. = Diog. vii. 1, 159. 

, I. 128. « Hyp. I. 128. 

. I. 128. ' Adv. Math. vii. 313. 

4 



50 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

The Seventh Trope. This Trope, based upon the 
quantities and compositions of objects, is illustrated by- 
examples of different kinds of food, drink, and medicine, 
showing the different effects according to the quantity 
taken, as the harmfulness and the usefulness of most 
things depend on their quantity. Things act differently 
upon the senses if applied in small or large quantities, 
as filings of metal or horn, and separate grains of sand, 
have a different color and touch from the same taken 
in the form of a solid.^ The result is that ideas vary 
according to the composition of the object, and this 
Trope also brings to confusion the existence of outward 
objects, and leads us to reserve our opinion in regard 
to them.^ This Trope is illustrated by Diogenes with 
exceeding brevity.^ 

The Eighth Trope. The Trope based upon relation 
contains, as Sextus rightly remarks, the substance of 
the other nine,* for the general statement of the rela- 
tivity of knowledge includes the other statements made. 
The prominence which Sextus gave this Trope in his 
introduction to the ten Tropes leads one to expect here 
new illustrations and added^ arguments for iiroxv- We 
find, however, neither of these, but simply a statement 
that all things are in relation in one of two ways, either 
directly, or as being a part of a difference. These two 
kinds of relation are given by Protagoras, and might 
have been used to good purpose in the introduction to 
the Tropes, or at the end, to prove that all the others 
were really subordinate to the eighth. The reasoning 



p. 1. 129—131. ^ Syp. I. 39. 

2 Hyp. I. 134. 5 Syp. i. 135—140. 

3 Diog. IX. 11, 86. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 51 

is, however, simply applied to the relation of objects to 
each other, and nothing is added that is not found else- 
where as an argument for iiroxv-^ This Trope is the 
tenth by Diogenes, and he strengthens his reasoning 
in regard to it, by a statement that Sextus does not 
directly make, i.e., that everything is in relation to the 
understanding.^ 

The Nimth Trope. This is based upon the frequency 
and rarity of events, and refers to some of the phenomena 
of nature, such as the rising of the sun, and the sea, as 
no longer a source of astonishment, while a comet or an 
earthquake are wonders to those not accustomed to 
them.^ The value of objects also depends on their 
rarity, as for example the value of gold.* Furthermore, 
things may be valuable at one time, and at another not 
so, according to the frequency and rarity of the occur- 
rence.^ Therefore this Trope also leads to iiroxi]- Dio- 
genes gives only two illustrations to this Trope, that of 
the sun and the earthquake.® 

The Tenth Trope. We have already remarked on 
the difference in the character of the tenth Trope, deal- 
ing as it does, not with the ideas of objects, like the 
other nine Tropes, but with philosophical and religious , 
opinions, and questions of right and wrong. It was thej 
well-known aim of the Sceptics to submit to the lawsj/ 
and customs of the land where they were found, and 
to conform to certain moral teachings and religious 
ceremonies; this they did without either afifirming or 

> Mffp. I. 138—140. ■• J2Vjo. I. 143. 

3 Diog. IX. 11, 88. * M^p. I. 144. 

^Byp. I. 141—142. « Diog. ix. 11, 87. 



52 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

denying the truth of the principles upon which these 
teachings were based/ and also without any passion or 
strong feeling in regard to them,^ as nothing in itself 
can be proved to be good or evil. The tenth Trope, 
accordingly, brings forward contradictions in customs, 
laws, and the beliefs of different lands, to show that they 
are also changeable and relative, and not of absolute 
worth. The foundation-thought of this Trope is given 
twice by Diogenes, once as we have before stated in his 
introduction^ to the life of Pyrrho, and also as one of 
the Tropes.* As it is apparently one of the oldest of 
the Tropes, it would naturally be much used in discuss- 
ing with the Stoics, whose philosophy had such a wide 
ethical significance, and must also have held an import- 
ant place in the Sceptical School in all metaphysical 
and philosophical discussions. The definition^ in the 
beginning of Sextus' exposition of this Trope Fabricius 
thinks was taken from Aristotle, of schools, laws, customs, 
mythical beliefs and dogmatic opinions,^ and the defini- 
tion which Diogenes gives of law in his life of Plato'^ is 
similar. Pappenheim, however, thinks they were taken 
from the Stoics, perhaps from Chrysippus.^ The argu- 
ment is based upon the differences in development of 
thought, as affecting the standpoint of judgment in 
philosophy, in morals, and religion, the results of which 
we find in the widely opposing schools of philosophy, in 
the variety in religious belief, and in the laws and cus- 
toms of different countries. Therefore the decisions 



p. 1. 24. 6 JTyp. I. 145 — 147. 

^ Hyp. III. 235. ^ Fabricius, Cap. iv. h. 

3 Diog. IX. 11, 61. ' Diog. in. 86. 

* Diog. IX. 11, 83. " Pappenheim Gr. Pyrr. Grundztlge, p. 60. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 53 

reached in the world of thought leave us equally in 
doubt regarding the absolute value of any standards, 
with those obtained through sense-perception, and the 
universal conflict of opinion regarding all questions of 
philosophy and ethics leads us also according to this 
Trope to the reserving of the opinion.^ This Trope is 
the fifth as given by Diogenes, who placed it directly 
after the first four which relate more especially to human 
development,^ while Sextus uses it as the final one, 
perhaps thinking that an argument based upon the 
higher powers of man deserves the last place, or is the 
summation of the other arguments. 

Following the exposition of the ten Tropes of the 
older Sceptics, Sextus gives the five Tropes which he 
attributes to the "later Sceptics."^ Sextus nowhere 
mentions the author of these Tropes. Diogenes, how- 
ever, attributes them to Agrippa, a man of whom we 
know nothing except his mention of him. He was 
evidently one of the followers of Aenesidemus, and a 
scholar of influence in the Sceptical School, who must 
have himself had disciples, as Diogenes says, ol vepl 
'Aypl-mrav* add to these tropes other five tropes, using 
the plural verb. Another Sceptic, also mentioned by 
Diogenes, and a man unknown from other sources, 
named some of his books after Agrippa.^ Agrippa is not 
given by Diogenes in the list of the leaders of the 
Sceptical School, but^ his influence in the development 
of the thought of the School must have been great, as 
the transition from the ten Tropes of the "older 

• Myp. I. 163. * Diog. ix. II, 88. 

2 Diog. IX. 11. 83. * Diog. ix. 11, 106. 

3 Si/p. I. 164. ' Diog. IX. 12, 115—116. 



54 Sextus Empiricxis and Greek Scefticism. 

Sceptics " to the five attributed to Agrippa is a marked 
one, and shows the entrance into the school of a logical 
power before unknown in it. The latter are not a re- 
duction of the Tropes of Aenesidemus, but are written 
from an entirely different standpoint. The ten Tropes 
are empirical, and aim to furnish objective proofs of the 
foundation theories of Pyrrhonism, while the five are 
rather rules of thought leading to logical proof, and are 
dialectic in their character. We find this distinction 
illustrated by the different way in which the Trope of 
relativity is treated in the two groups. In the first it 
points to an objective relativity, but with Agrippa to a 
general subjective logical principle. The originality of 
the Tropes of Agrippa does not lie in their substance 
matter, but in their formulation and use in the Sceptical 
School. These methods of proof were, of course, not new, 
but were well known to Aristotle, and were used by 
the Sceptical Academy, and probably also by Timon,^ 
while the ttjoo? ti goes back at least to Protagoras. 
The five Tropes are as follows. 

(i) The one based upon discord. 

(ii) The regressus in infinitum. 

(iii) Relation. 

(iv) The hypothetical. 

(v) The circulus in probaiido. 

Two of these are taken from the old list, the first 
and the third, and Sextus says that the five Tropes are 
intended to supplement the ten Tropes, and to show 
the audacity of the Dogmatics in a variety of ways.^ 
The order of these Tropes is the same with Diogenes as 

' Compare Natorp. Op. eit. p. 302. 
2 Hyp. I. 177. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 55 

with Sextus, but the definitions of them differ sufficiently 
to show that the two authors took their raaterial from 
different sources. According to the first one everything 
in question is either sensible or intellectual, and in at- 
tempting to judge it either in life, practically, or " among 
philosophers,'' a position is developed from which it is 
impossible to reach a conclusion.'' According to the 
second, every proof requires another proof, and so on to 
infinity, and there is no standpoint from which to begin 
the reasoning.^ According to the third, all perceptions 
are relative, as the object is colored by the condition of 
the judge, and the influence of other things around it.* 
According to the fourth, it is impossible to escape from 
the regressus in infinitum by making a hypothesis the 
starting point, as the Dogmatics attempt to do.* And 
the fifth, or the circulus in probanda, arises when that 
which should be the proof needs to be sustained by the 
thing to be proved. 

Sextus claims that all things can be included in 
these Tropes, whether sensible or intellectual.^ For 
whether, as some say, only the things of sense are true, 
or as others claim, only those of the understanding, or 
as still others contend, some thin^ both of sense and 
understanding are true, a discord must arise that is 
impossible to be judged, for it cannot be judged by the 
sensible, nor by the intellectual, for the things of the 
intellect themselves require a proof; accordingly, the 
result of all reasoning must be either hypothetical, or 
fall into the regressus in infinitum or the circulus in 

1 Ei/p. I. 165. ■* Si/p. I. 168. 

2 Syp. I. 166. 5 j{yp_ I. 169. 

3 Svp. I. 167. 



56 Sextus Empirious and Greeh Scepticism. 

prohando} The reference above to some who say that 
only the things of sense are true, is to Epicurus and 
Protagoras ; to some that only the things of thought are 
true, to Democritus and Plato ; and to those that claimed 
some of both to be true, to the Stoics and the Peripatetics.^ 
The three new Tropes added by Agrippa have nothing 
to do with sense-perception, but bear entirely upon the 
possibility of reasoning, as demanded by the science of 
logic, m contrast to th6 earlier ones which related almost 
entirely, with the exception of the tenth, to material 
objects. Sextus claims that these five Tropes also lead 
to the suspension of judgment,^ but their logical result 
is rather the dogmatic denial of all possibility of know- 
ledge, showing as Hirssel has well demonstrated, far 
more the influence of the New Academy than the spirit 
of the Sceptical School.* It was the standpoint of the 
older Sceptics, that although the search for the truth 
had not yet succeeded, yet they were still seekers, and 
Sextus claims to be faithful to this old aim of the 
Pyrrhonists. He calls himself a seeker,^ and in re- 
proaching the New Academy for affirming that know- 
ledge is impossible, Sextus says, " Moreover, we say that 
' our ideas are equal as regards trustworthiness and un- 
trustworthiness."^ The ten Tropes claim to establish 
doubt only in regard to a knowledge of the truth, but 
the five Tropes of Agrippa aim to logically prove the 
impossibility of knowledge. It is very strange that 
Sextus does not see this decided contrast in the attitude 

1 Hyp. I. 170—171. 

2 Adv. Math. viii. 185—186; Tin. 56; vii. 369. 

3 Eyp. I. 177. « Hyp. i. 3, 7. 
* Hirzel Op. eii. p. 131. « Hyp. i. 227. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 57 

of the two sets of Tropes, and expresses his approval of 
those of Agrippa, and makes more frequent use of the 
fifth of these, o StaXXTjXo?, in his subsequent reasoning 
than of any other argument.^ 

We find here in the Sceptical School, shortly after 
the time of Aenesidemus, the same tendency to dogmatic 
teaching, that — so far as the dim and shadowy history of 
the last years of the New Academy can be unravelled, 
and the separation of Pyrrhonism can be understood, at 
the time that the Academy passed over into eclecticism — 
was one of the causes of that separation. 

It is true that the Tropes of Agrippa show great \ 
progress in the development of thought. They furnish 
an organisation of the School far superior to what went j 
before, placing the reasoning on the firm basis of the 
laws of logic, and simplifying the amount of material to 
be used. In a certain sense Saisset is correct in saying 
that Agrippa contributed more than any other in com- 
pleting the organisation of Scepticism,^ but it is not 
correct when we consider the true spirit of Scepticism 
with which the Tropes of Agrippa were not in harmony. 
It was through the very progress shown in the pro- 
duction of these Tropes that the school finally lost the 
strength of its position. 

Not content with having reduced the number of the 
Tropes from ten to five, others tried to limit the number 
still further to two.^ Sextus gives us no hint of the 
authorship of the two Tropes. Ritter attributes them 
to Menodotus and his followers, and Zeller agrees with 



' See Index of Bekker's edition of Sextus' works. 
» Saisset Op. cit. p. 237. ' Eyp. i. 178. 



58 Sextus Em-firicus and Greek Scepticism. 

that opinion,^ while Saisset thinks that Agrippa was 
also the author of these,^ which is a strange theory to 
propound, as some of the material of the five is repeated 
in the two, and the same man could certainly not appear 
as an advocate of five, and at the same time of two 
Tropes. 

The two Tropes are founded on the principle that 
anything must be known through itself or through 
something else. It cannot be known through itself, 
because of the discord existing between all things of the 
senses and intellect, nor can it be known through some- 
thing else, as then either the regressus in infinitum or 
the circulus in prohando follow.^ Diogenes Laertius 
does not refer to these two Tropes. 

In regard to all these Tropes of the suspension of 
judgment, Sextus has well remarked in his introduction 
to them, that they are included in the eighth, or that 
of relation.* 

The Tropes of Aetiology. The eight Tropes against 
causality belong chronologically before the five Tropes 
of Agrippa, in the history of the development of scepti- 
cal thought. They have a much closer connection with 
the spirit of Scepticism than the Tropes of Agrippa, 
including, as they do, the fundamental thought of 
Pyrrhonism, i.e., that the phenomena do not reveal the 
unknown. 

The Sceptics did not deny the phenomena, but they 
denied that the phenomena are signs capable of being 
interpreted, or of revealing the reality of causes. It is 

1 Zeller iii. 38 ; Ritter iv. 277. ' Spp. i. 178 -179. 
^ Saisset Op. eit. p. 231. * Hyp. i. 39. 



The Sceptical Tropes. 59 

impossible by a research of the signs to find out the 
unknown, or the explanation of things, as the Stoics 
and Epicureans claim. The theory of Aenesidemus 
which lies at the foundation of his eight Tropes against 
aetiology, is given to us by Photius as follows •} " There 
are no visible signs of the unknown, and those who be- 
lieve in its existence are the victims of a vain illusion." 
This statement of Aenesidemus is confirmed by a fuller 
explanation of it given later on by Sextus.^ If pheno- 
mena are not signs of the unknown there is no causality, 
and a refutation of causality is a proof of the impossi- 
bility of science, as all science is the science of causes, 
the power of studying causes from effects, or as Sextus 
calls them, phenomena. 

It is very noticeable to any one who reads the refu- 
tation of causality by Aenesidemus, as given by Sextus,* 
that there is no reference to the strongest argument of 
modern Scepticism, since the time of Hume, against 
causality, namely that the origin of the idea of causality 
cannot be so accounted for as to justify our relying upon 
it as a form of cognition.* 

The eight Tropes are directed against the possibility 
of knowledge of nature, which Aenesidemus contested 
againsst in all his Tropes, the ten as well as the eight.^ 
They are written from a materialistic standpoint. 
These Tropes are given with illustrations by Fabricius 
as follows : 

I. Since aetiology in general refers to things that are 
unseen, it does not give testimony that is incontestable 

1 Myriob. 170 b. 12. ^ Ueberweg Op. eit. p. 217. 

2 kdv. Math. VIII. 207. = Byp. i. 98. 

3 Hyp. I. 180—186. 



60 Sexttis Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

in regard to phenomena. For example, the Pythagor- 
eans explain the distance of the planets by a musical 
proportion. 

II. From many equally plausible reasons which 
might be given for the same thing, one only is arbitrarily 
chosen, as some explain the inundation of the Nile by 
a fall of snow at its source, while there could be other 
causes, as rain, or wind, or the action of the sun. 

III. Things take place in an orderly manner, but 
the causes presfented do not show any order, as for ex- 
ample, the motion of the stars is explained by their 
mutual pressure, which does not take into account the 
order that reigns among them. 

IV. The unseen things are supposed to take place 
in the same way as phenomena, as vision is explained 
in the same way as the appearance of images in a dark 
room. 

V. Most philosophers present theories of aetiology 
which agree with their own individual hypotheses about 
the elements, but not with common and accepted ideas, 
as to explain the world by atoms like Epicurus, by 
homoeomeriae like Anaxagoras, or by matter and form 
like Aristotle. 

VI. Theories are accepted which agree with indi- 
vidual hypotheses, and others equally probable are 
passed by, as Aristotle's explanation of comets, that 
they are a collection of vapors near the earth, because 
that coincided with his theory of the universe. 

VII. Theories of aetiology are presented which 
conflict not only with individual hypotheses, but also 



The Sceptical Tropes. 61 



with phenomena, as to admit like Epicurus an inclina- 
tion or desire of the soul, which was incompatible with 
the necessity which he advocated. 

VIII. The inscrutable is explained by things 
equally inscrutable, as the rising of sap in plants is ex- 
plained by the attraction of a sponge for water, a fact 
contested by some.^ 

Diogenes does not mention these Tropes in this 
form, but he gives a resum^ of the general arguments 
of the Sceptics against aetiology,^ which -has less in 
common with the eight Tropes of Aenesidemus, than 
with the presentation of the subject by Sextus later,^ 
when he multiplies his proofs exceedingly to show 
fj,r}Sev elvab airiov. Although the Tropes of Aeneside- 
mus have a dialectic rather than an objective character, 
it would not seem that he made the distinction, which is 
so prominent with Sextus,between the signs inrofivrjaTiKd 
and ivSeiKTi/cd,^ especially as Diogenes sums up his argu- 
ment on the subject with the general assertion, ^T^/j.elov 
ovK elvM^ and proceeds to introduce the logical con- 
sequence of the denial of aetiology. The summing up 
of the Tropes of Aenesidemus is given as follows, in the 
Hypotyposes, by Sextus: — "A cause in harmony with all 
the sects of philosophy, and with Scepticism, and with 
phenomena, is perhaps not possible, for the phenomena 
and the unknown altogether disagree."^ 

It is interesting to remark in connection with the 
seventh of these Tropes, that Aenesidemus asserts that 

1 Syp. I. 180—186; Fabrioius, Cap. xvii. 180 z. 

2 Diog. IX. 11, 96—98. ■• Adv. Math. viii. 151. 
8 Hyp. in. 24—28. « Diog. ix. 11, 96. 

= Hyp. I. 186. 



62 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

causality has only a subjective value, which from his 
materialistic standpoint was an argument against its 
real existence, and the same argument is used by Kant 
to prove that causality is a necessary condition of 
thought.^ 

Chaignet characterises the Tropes of Aenesidemus as 
false and sophistical,^ but as Maccoll has well said, they 
are remarkable for their judicious and strong criticism, 
and are directed against the false method of observing 
facts through the light of preconceived opinion.^ They 
have, however, a stronger critical side than sceptical, 
and show the positive tendency of the thought of 
Aenesidemus. 

> Compare Maccoll Op. cit. p. 77. ^ Chaignet Op. cit. 507. 

' Maccoll Op. cit. p. 88. 



CHAPTER IV. 

Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 

A paragraph in the First Book of the Hypotyposes 
which has given rise to much speculation and many 
di£ferent theories, is the comparison which Sextus makes 
of Scepticism with the philosophy of Heraclitus.^ In 
this paragraph the statement is made that Aenesidemus 
and his followers, ol irepi rov Aivrfaihrnxov, said that 
Scepticism is the path to the philosophy of Heraclitus, 
because the doctrine that contradictory predicates 
appear to be applicable to the same thing, leads the 
way to the one that contradictory predicates are in 
reality applicable to the same thing.^ ol irepl top 
Alv7jaiSr]/j,ov eXeyov oBov elvai rrjv CKeimicrfv dycoyfju 
ivrl TTjv 'RpaickevTeiov (fnXocotpiav, SioTi irpoT^yeiTat tou 
ravavTM irepl to avro xnrdp-)(eiv to TavavTia irepX to 
avTo ^aiveaOai. As the Sceptics say that contradictory 
predicates appear to be applicable to the same thing, 
the Heraclitans come from this to the more positive 
doctrine that they are in reality so.^ , 

This connection which Aenesidemus is said to have 
affirmed between Scepticism and the philosophy of 
Heraclitus is earnestly combated by Sextus, who de- 
clares that the fact that contradictory predicates appear 
to be applicable to the same thing is not a dogma of 
the Sceptics, but a fact which presents itself to all men, 
and not to the Sceptics only. No one for instance, 

• Hyp. I. 210. ' Hyp. i. 210. ' Hyp. i. 210. 



64 Sextus Emrpiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

whether he be a Sceptic or not, would dare to say that 
honey does not taste sweet to those in health, and bitter 
to those who have the jaundice, so that Heraclitus 
begins from a preconception common to all men, as to 
us also, and perhaps to the other schools of philosophy 
as well.^ As the statement concerning the appearance 
of contradictory predicates in regard to the same thing 
is not an exclusively sceptical one, then Scepticism is 
no more a path to the philosophy of Heraclitus than 
to other schools of philosophy, or to life, as all use 
common subject matter. " But we are afraid that the 
Sceptical School not only does not help towards the 
knowledge of the philosophy of Heraclitus, but even 
hinders that result. Since the Sceptic accuses Heraclitus 
of having rashly dogmatised, presenting on the one 
hand the doctrine of ' conflagration ' and on the other 
that ' contradictory predicates are in reality applicable 
to the same thing.' " ^ " It is absurd, then, to say that 
this conflicting school is a path to the. sect with which it 
conflicts. It is therefore absurd to say that the Sceptical 
School is a path to the philosophy of Heraclitus."^ 

This is not the only place in the writings of Sextus 
which states that Aenesidemus at some time of his life 
was an advocate of the doctrines of Heraclitus. In no 
instance, however, where Sextus refers to this remark- 
able fact, does he offer any explanation of it, or express 
any bitterness against Aenesidemus, whom he always 
speaks of with respect as a leader of the Sceptical 
School. We are thus furnished with one of the most 
difficult problems of ancient Scepticism, the problem 

• Syp. i. 211. ' Byp. i. 212. 3 Eyp. i. 212. 



Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 65 

of reconciling the apparent advocacy of Aenesidemus 
of the teachings of Heraclitus with his position in the 
Sceptical School. 

A comparison with each other of the references 
made by Sextus and other writers to the teachings of 
Aenesidemus, and a consideration of the result, gives us 
two pictures of Aenesidemus which conflict most de- 
cidedly with each other. We have on the one hand, 
the man who was the first to give Pyrrhonism a position 
as an influential school, and the first to collect and pre- 
sent to the world the results of preceding Sceptical 
thought. He was the compiler of the ten Tropes of 
e'Ko-)(ri, and perhaps in part their author, and the author 
of the eight Tropes against aetiology.^ He develops his 
Scepticism from the standpoint that neither the senses 
nor the intellect can give us any certain knowledge of 
reality."^ He denied the possibility of studying pheno- 
mena as signs of the unknown.^ He denied all possi- 
bility of truth, and the reality of motion, origin and 
decay. There was according to his teaching no plea- 
sure or happiness, and no wisdom or supreme good. 
He denied the possibility of finding out the nature of 
things, or of proving the existence of the gods, and 
finally he declared that no ethical aim is possible. 

The picture on the other hand, presented to us by 
Sextus and Tertullian, is that of a man with a system of 
beliefs and dogmas, which lead, he says, to the philosophy 
of Heraclitus. In strange contradiction to his assertion of 
the impossibility of all knowledge, he advocates a theory 



1 Syp. I. 180. 2 photius 170, B. 12. 

" Adv. Math. Till. 40. 



66 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

~ that the original substance is air/ which is most cer- 
tainly a dogma, although indeed a deviation from the 
teachings of Heraclitus, of which Sextus seemed uncon- 
scious, as he says, to re ov Kara rov 'HpaKKetrov arjp 
.ia-riv, £09 (prjalv 6 AivqcjihjiJLo^. Aenesidemus dogma- 
tised also regarding number and time and unity of 
the original world-stuff.^ He seems to have dogmatised 
further about motion,^ and about the soul.* 

If Sextus' language is taken according to its apparent 
meaning, we find ourselves here in the presence of a 
system of beliefs which would be naturally held by a 
follower of the Stoic-Heraclitan physics,^ and absolutely 
inexplicable from the standpoint of a man who advocated 
so radical a Scepticism as Aenesidemus. Sextus in the 
passage that we first quoted,^ expresses great indignation 
against the idea that Scepticism could form the path to 
the philosophy of Heraclitus, but he does not express 
surprise or indignation against Aenesidemus personally, 
or offer any explanation of the apparent contradiction ; 
and while his writings abound in references to him as a 
respected leader of the Sceptical School, he sometimes 
seems to include him with the Dogmatics, mentioning 
him with the Soy/iaTLKwv <piXo(r6<f)a)vJ In fact, the task 
of presenting any consistent history of the development 
of thought through which Aenesidemus passed is such 
a puzzling one, that Brochard brilliantly remarks that 
possibly the best attitude to take towards it would be 
to follow the advice of Aenesidemus himself, and suspend 

' Adv. Math. x. 233. * Compare Zeller Op. cit. in. p. 33. 

2 Ach). Math. ix. 337; x. 216. « Eyp. i. 210—212. 

3 Adv. Math. i.. 38. ' Ado. Math. viii. 8 ; x. 216. 
* Adv. Math. vii. 349. 



Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 67 

one's judgment altogether regarding it. Is it possible 
to suppose that so sharp and subtle a thinker as Aene- 
sidemus held at the same time such opposing opinions ? 

The conjecture that be was first a Heraclitan Stoic, 
and later a Sceptic, which might be possible, does not 
offer any explanation of Sextus' statement, that he 
regarded Scepticism as a path to the philosophy of 
Heraclitus. Nor would it be logical to think that after 
establishing the Sceptical School in renewed influence 
and power, he reverted to the Heraclitan theories as 
they were modified by the Stoics. These same theories 
were the cause of his separation from the Academy, for 
his chief accusation against the Academy was that it 
was adopting the dogmatism of the Stoics.^ The matter 
is complicated by the fact that TertuUian also attributes 
to Aenesidemus anthropological and physical teachings 
that agree with the Stoical Heraclitan doctrines. It is 
not strange that in view of these contradictory assertions 
in regard to the same man, some have suggested the 
possibility that they referred to two different men of 
the same name, a supposition, however, that no one has 
been able to authoritatively vindicate. 

Let us consider briefly some of the explanations 
which have been attempted of the apparent heresy of 
Aenesidemus towards the Sceptical School. We will 
begin with the most ingenious, that of Pappenheim.'^ 

Pappenheim claims that Sextus was not referring 
to Aenesidemus himself in these statements which he 
joins with his name. In the most important of these, 

1 Compare Zeller Op. cit. iii. p. 16. 

'' Die angebliche Seraclitismm des Skeptikers Ainesidemos, Berlin 1889. 



68 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

the one quoted from the Hypoty poses, ^ which represents 
Aenesidemus as claiming that Scepticism is the path to 
the philosophy of Heraclitus, the expression used is 
ol Trept rov Alvrfcrihrjfji.ov, and in many of the other places 
where Sextus refers to the dogmatic statements of 
Aenesidemus, the expression is either ol irepl rov Alvrj- 
a-lBrj/Mov, or Alvr](TiSr]fioi! kuO^ 'HpaxXeiTOV, while when 
Sextus quotes Aenesidemus to sustain Scepticism, he 
uses his name alone. 

Pappenheim thinks that Sextus' conflict was not 
with the dead Aenesidemus, who had lived two cen- 
turies before him, but with his own contemporaries. 
He also seeks to prove that Sextus could not have gained 
his knowledge of these sayings of Aenesidemus from any 
of Aenesidemus' own writings, as neither by the ancients, 
nor by later writers, was any book spoken of which could 
well have contained them. Neither Aristocles nor Dio- 
genes mentions any such book. 

Pappenheim also makes much of the argument that 
Sextus in no instance seems conscious of inconsistency 
on the part of Aenesidemus, even when most earnestly 
combating his alleged teachings, but in referring to 
him personally he always speaks of him with great 
respect. 

Pappenheim suggests, accordingly, that the polemic 
of Sextus was against contemporaries, those who accepted 
the philosophy of Heraclitus in consequence of, or in 
some connection with, the teachings of Aenesidemus. 
He entirely ignores the fact that there is no trace of 
any such school or sect in history, calling themselves 

1 Byp. I. 210—212. 



Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 69 

followers of "Aenesidemus according to Heraclitus," but 
still thinks it possible that such a movement existed in 
Alexandria at the time of Sextus, where so many dif- 
ferent sects were found. Sextus uses Aenesidemus' 
name in four different ways:— alone, ol irepl tov AlveaLhrj- 
fxov, Aiv7)a-lSr]/jiO'; Ka9' 'HpdicXeiTOv, and in one instance 
ol trepl TOV Alvrja-'ihrjiiov Kad' 'HpoLKKsLTov} 

Pappenheim advances the theory that some of these 
contemporaries against whom Sextus directed his argu- 
ments had written a book entitled Alvr]aiSr}/j,o<! kuS' 
'HpdickeiTov, to prove the harmony between Aenesi- 
demus and Heraclitus, and that it was from this book 
that Sextus quoted the dogmatic statements which he 
introduced with that formula. He claims, further, that 
the passage quoted from Hypotyposes I. even, is directed 
against contemporaries, who founded their system of 
proofs of the harmony between Aenesidemus and Herac- 
litus on the connection of the celebrated formula which 
was such a favourite with the Sceptics: "Contrary 
predicates appear to apply to the same thing," with the 
apparent deduction from this, that " Contrary predicates 
in reality apply to the same thing." Sextus wishes, ac- 
cording to Pappenheim, to prove to these contemporaries 
that they had misunderstood Aenesidemus, and Sextus 
does not report Aenesidemus to be a Dogmatic, nor to 
have taught the doctrines of Heraclitus; neither has 
he misunderstood Aenesidemus, nor consequently mis- 
represented him ; but on the contrary, these dogmatic 
quotations have nothing to do with Aenesidemus, but 
refer altogether to contemporaries who pretended to be 

' Adv. Math. viii. 8. 



70 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

Sceptics while they accepted the teachings ot Herac- 
litus. Sextus naturally warmly combats this tendency, 
as he wishes to preserve Pyrrhonism pure. 

Brochard advocates a change of opinion on the part 
of Aenesidemus as an explanation of the difficulty in 
question.^ He starts from the supposition, the reason- 
ableness of which we shall consider later, that Aene- 
sidemus had passed through one change of opinion 
already when he severed his connection with the New 
Academy ; and to the two phases of his life, which such 
a change has already made us familiar with, he adds a 
third. Aenesidemus would not be the fir.st who has 
accepted different beliefs at different periods of his life, 
and Brochard claims that such a development in the 
opinions of Aenesidemus is logical. He does not accuse 
Aenesidemus of having, as might seem from the perusal 
of Sextus, suddenly changed his basis, but rather of 
having gradually come to accept much in the teachings 
of Heraclitus. Aenesidemus modifies his Scepticism 
only to the extent of pretending to know something 
of absolute reality. The Sceptic says, "Contradictory 
predicates are apparently applicable to the same thing," 
and Aenesidemus accepts the Heraclitan result — " Con- 
tradictory predicates are in reality applicable to the 
same thing." From Sextus' report, Aenesidemus would 
seem to have renounced his position as a Sceptic in 
saying that Scepticism is the, path to the philosophy of 
Heraclitus. He does not, however, renounce Scepticism, 
but he finds it incomplete. In deliberating concerning 
the appearance of contradictory predicates in regard to 

' Brochard Op. cit. 272. 



Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraolitus. 71 

the same object, he would naturally ask, " Whence come 
these contradictory appearances ? " After having doubted 
all things, he wished to know wherefore he doubts. The 
system of Heraclitus offers a solution, and he accepts it. 
Contradictory predicates produce equilibrium in the 
soul because they are an expression of reality. 

As a Sceptic he claims that knowledge is impossible, 
and he does not find that the statement of Heraclitus 
disproves this, but rather that it supports his theory. 
He had denied the existence of science. • He still does 
so, but now he knows why he denies it. Brochard asks 
why it is any more impossible that Aenesidemus should 
have been a follower of Heraclitus than that Protagoras 
was so, as Protagoras was after all a Sceptic. In con- 
clusion, Brochard claims that the dogmatic theories 
attributed to Aenesidemus relate to the doctrine of the 
truth of contradictory predicates, which seemed to him 
a logical explanation of the foundation theories of 
Scepticism. It is right to call him a Sceptic, for he 
was so, and that sincerely ; and he deserves his rank 
as one of the chiefs of the Sceptical School. 

Coming now to the opinion of Zeller,^ we find that 
he advocates a misconception of Aenesidemus on the 
part of Sextus. The whole difficulty is removed, Zeller 
thinks, by the simple fact that Sextus had not under- 
stood Aenesidemus ; and as TertuUian and Sextus agree 
in this misconception of the views of Aenesidemus, they 
must have been misled by consulting a common author 
in regard to Aenesidemus, who confused what Aene- 
sidemus said of Heraclitus with his own opinion. Zeller 

' Zeller Op. cit. 111, pp.31 — 35; Grundriaader Geachichte der Griechia- 
ehm JPhil. p. 263. 



72 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

maintains that the expression so often repeated by 
Sextus — Alv7}ffihrjfji,o<; KaS" 'HpaKKeirov — shows that 
some one of Aenesidemus' books contained a report of 
Heraclitus' doctrines, as Aenesidemus was in the habit 
of quoting as many authorities as possible to sustain 
his Scepticism. To justify his quotations from Herac- 
litus, he had possibly given a short abstract of Heraclitus' 
teachings ; and the misconception advocated by Zeller, 
and found both in Tertullian and Sextus, refers rather 
to the spirit than to the words quoted from Aeneside- 
mus, and is a misconception due to some earlier author, 
who had given a false impression of the meaning of 
Aenesidemus in quoting what Aenesidemus wrote about 
Heraclitus. That is to say, Heraclitus was classed by 
Aenesidemus only among those who prepared the way 
for Scepticism, just as Diogenes-'-'mentions many philo- 
sophers in that way ; and that Soranus^ and Sextus both 
had the same misunderstanding can only be explained 
by a mistake on the part of the authority whom they 
consulted. 

This explanation, however, makes Sextus a very 
stupid man. Aenesidemus' books were well known, 
and Sextus would most certainly take the trouble to 
read them. His reputation as an historian would not 
sustain such an accusation, as Diogenes calls his books 
TO, SeKa Toiv crK€TrTt,K&v Kal d\Xa KoKXiara.^ Further- 
more, that Sextus used Aenesidemus' own books we 
know from the direct quotation from them in regard to 
Plato,* which he combines with the ideas of Menodotus^ 
and his own. 

' Diog. Laert. ix. 11, 71—74. '' Tertullian. » Diog. ix. 12, 116. 
< Syp. I. 222. ' Following the Greek of Bekker. 



Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 73 

Sextus' references to Aenesidemus in connection 
with Heraclitus are very numerous, and it is absurd 
to suppose that he would have trusted entirely to some 
one who reported him for authority on such a subject. 
Even were it possible that Sextus did not refer directly 
to the works of Aenesidemus, which we do not admit, 
even then, there had been many writers in the Sceptical 
School since the time of Aenesidemus, and they certainly 
could not all have misrepresented him. We must re- 
member that Sextus was at the head of the School, and 
had access to all of its literature. His honor would not 
allow of such a mistake, and if he had indeed made it, 
his contemporaries must surely have discovered it before 
Diogenes characterised his books as aaWto-ra. Whatever 
may be said against the accuracy of Sextus as a general 
historian of philosophy, especially in regard to the older 
schools, he cannot certainly be accused of ignorance 
respecting the school of which he was at that time 
the head. 

The opinion of Ritter on this subject is that Aene- 
sidemus must have been a Dogmatic.^ Saisset contends* 
that Aenesidemus really passed from the philosophy of 
Heraclitus to that of Pyrrho, and made the statement 
that Scepticism is the path to the philosophy of Heracli- 
tus to defend his change of view, although in his case 
the change had been just the opposite to the one he 
defends. Saisset propounds as a law in the history of 
philosophy a fact which he claims to be true, that 
Scepticism always follows sensationalism, for which he 
gives two examples, Pyrrho, who was first a disciple of 

' Eitter, Op. eit. p. 280. Book IV. ' Saisset, Op. cit. p. 206. 



74 Sextus Empiricus a^ad Greek Scepticism. 

Democritus, and Hume, who was a disciple of LocVe. 
It is not necessary to discuss the absurdity of such a 
law, which someone has well remarked would involve an 
a priori construction of history. There is no apparent 
reason for Saisset's conjecture in regard to Aenesidemus, 
for it is exactly the opposite of what Sextus has reported. 
Strange to say, Saisset himself remarks in another place 
that we owe religious respect to any text, and that it 
should be the first law of criticism to render this.^ Such 
respect to the text of Sextus, as he himself advocates, 
puts Saisset's explanation of the subject under dis- 
cussion out of the question. 

Hirzel and Natorp do not find such a marked 
contradiction in the two views presented of the theories 
of Aenesidemus, nor do they think that Sextus has 
misrepreseoted them. They rather maintain, that in 
declaring the coexistence of contradictory predicates 
regarding the same object, Aenesidemus does not cease 
to be a Sceptic, for he did not believe that the predicates 
are applicable in a dogmatic sense of the word, but are 
only applicable in appearance, that is, applicable to^ 
phenomena. The Heraclitism of Aenesidemus would 
be then only in appearance, as he understood the 
statement, that " Contradictory predicates are in reality 
applicable to the same thing," only in the phenomenal 
sense.^ Hirzel says in addition, that contradictory 
predicates are in reality applicable to those phenomena 
which are the same for all, and consequently true, for 
Aenesidemus considered those phenomena true that 
are the same for all.^ As Protagoras, the disciple of 

' Saisset Op. eit. p. 206. = Natorp Op. eit. 115, 122. 

3 Adv. Math. viii. 8 ; Hirzel Op. eit. p. 96. 



AeiiesideTmis and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 75 

Heraclitus, declared the relative character of sensations, 
that things exist only for us, and that their nature 
depends on our perception of them ; so, in the pheno- 
menal sense, Aenesidemus accepts the apparent fact 
that contradictory predicates in reality apply to the 
same thing. 

This explanation entirely overlooks the fact that we 
have to do with the word virdp'^^etv, in the statement 
that contradictory predicates in reality apply to the same 
thing ; while in the passage quoted where Aenesidemus 
declares common phenomena to be true ones, we have 
the word aXridfj, so that this explanation of the difiB- 
culty would advocate a very strange use of the word 
V7rdp')^eiv. 

All of these different views of the possible solution 
of this perplexing problem are worthy of respect, as the 
opinion of men who have given much thought to this 
and other closely related subjects. While we may not 
altogether agree with any one of them, they neverthe- 
less furnish many suggestions, which are very valuable 
in helping to construct a theory on the subject that 
shall satisfactorily explain the difficulties, and present a 
consistent view of the attitude of Aenesidemus. 

First, in regard to the Greek expression ol Trepl in 
connection with proper names, upon which Pappenheim 
bases so much of his argument. All Greek scholars 
would agree that the expression does not apply usually 
only to the disciples of any teacher, but ol irepl rbv 
AlvrjaiBrifiov, for instance, includes Aenesidemus with his 
followers, and is literally translated, " Aenesidemus and 
his followers." It is noticeable, however, in the writings 
of Sextus that he uses the expression oi irepl often for 



76 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

the name of the founder of a school alone, as Pappen- 
heim himself admits.^ We find examples of this in the 
mention of Plato and Democritus and Arcesilaus, as 
01 TTepi Tov UXdrceva Kal ArjfjbOKpnov^ and ot irepi tov 
'ApKecrlXaov,^ and accordingly we have no right to infer 
that his use of the name Aenesidemus in this way has 
an exceptional significance. It may mean Aenesidemus 
alone, or it may signify Aenesidemus in connection with 
his followers. 

In reply to Zeller's position, that Sextus and Ter- 
tullian have misunderstood Aenesidemus, and quote 
from some common author who misrepresents him, 
we would admit that such a misunderstanding might 
be possible where Sextus gives long explanations of 
Heraclitus' teachings, beginning with quoting Aene- 
sidemus, and continuing in such a way that it is not 
always possible to distinguish just the part that is 
attributed to Aenesidemus ; but such a misunderstand- 
ing certainly cannot be asserted in regard to the direct 
statement that Aenesidemus regarded Scepticism as the 
path to the philosophy of Heraclitus, for the reasons 
previously given. Neither would we agree with 
Brochard, whose solution of the difficulty is on the 
whole the most logical, i.e., that Aenesidemus had neces- 
sarily already passed through two phases of philosophical 
belief. It is possible to admit a gradual evolution of 
thought in Aenesidemus without supposing in either 
case a change of basis. His withdrawal from the 
Academy is an argument against, rather than in favor 



' Pappenheioi Op. cit. p. 21. ' Adv. Math. vm. 6. 

' Adv. Math. vil. 150. 



Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 77 

of, a change on his part, and was caused by the well- 
known change in the attitude of the Academy. 

Many of the teachings of the Sceptical School were 
taken directly from the Academy, belonging to those 
doctrines advocated in the Academy before the eclectic 
dogmatic tendency introduced by Antiochus. In fact, 
Sextus himself claims a close relation between the 
Middle Academy and Pyrrhonism.^ Aenesidemus, 
although he was a Sceptic, belonged to the Academy, 
and on leaving it became, as it were, a pioneer in 
Pyrrhonism, and cannot be judged in the same way 
as we should judge a Sceptic of Sextus' time. 

It seems a self-evident fact that during the two 
centuries which elapsed between the time of Aeneside- 
mus and Sextus, the standpoint of judgment in the 
Sceptical School had greatly changed. An example 
illustrating this change we find in a comparison of the 
presentation of Scepticism by. Diogenes with that of 
Sextus. The author whom Diogenes follows, probably 
one of the Sceptical writers, considers Xenophanes, Zeno, 
and Democritus, Sceptics, and also Plato,^ while Sextus, 
in regard to all of these men, opposes the idea that they 
were Sceptics.^ Diogenes also calls Heraclitus a Sceptic, 
and even Homer,* and quotes sceptical sayings from 
the Seven Wise Men ; ^ he includes in the list of Scep- 
tics, Archilochus, Euripides, Empedocles, and Hippoc- 
rates,® and, furthermore, says that Theodosius, probably 
one of the younger Sceptics, objected to the name 



1 Sj/p. I. 232. • Diog. IX. 11, 71. 

» Diog. IX. 11, 17—72. 5 Diog. ix. 11, 71. 

3 Syp. I. 213—214 ; i. 223—226. ' Diog. ix. 11, 71—73. 



78 Seodus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

' Pyrrhonean ' on the ground that Pyrrho was not the 
first Sceptic.^ 

We have given the testin\ony from many sources, 
to the effect that before the time of Sextus the Empiri- 
cal School of Medicine was considered identical with 
Scepticism, although not so by Sextus himself From 
all of these things we may infer a narrowing of the limits 
of Pyrrhonism in the time of Sextus. 

Let us accept with Brochard the development of 
thought seen in Aenesidemus from the beginning to 
the end of his career, without agreeing with him that 
Aenesidemus ever consciously changed his basis. He 
was a Sceptic in the Academy. He left the Academy 
on that account, and he remained a Sceptic to the end, 
in so far as a man can be a Sceptic, and take the 
positive stand that Aenesidemus did. 

Two things might account for his apparent dog- 
matism— 

(i) The eclectic spirit of his time. 

(ii) The psychological effect upon himself of this 
careful systemisation of the Sceptical teachings. 

Let us consider the first of these causes. Aeneside- 
mus, although not the first of the later Sceptics, was 
apparently the first to separate himself from the 
Academy. He was the founder of a new movement, 
the attempt to revive the older Scepticism as taught by 
Pyrrho and Timon, and separate it from the dogmatic 
teachings of the Stoics which were so greatly affecting 
the Scepticism of the Now Academy. It was the spirit 
of his time to seek to sustain all philosophical teaching 

1 Diog. IX. u. 70. 



Aenesidemus and the Philosophy of Heraclitus. 79 

by the authority of as many as possible of the older 
philosophers, and he could hardly escape the tendency 
which his training in the Academy had unconsciously 
given him. Therefore we find him trying to prove that 
the philosophy of Heraclitus follows from Scepticism. It 
is not necessary either to explain the matter, as both 
Hirzel and Natorp so ingeniously attempt to do, by 
claiming that the truth of contradictory predicates which 
Aenesidemus accepted from Heraclitus referred only to 
phenomena. The history of philosophy gives us abun- 
dant proof of the impossibility of absolute Scepticism, 
and Aenesidemus furnishes us with one example of many 
of this impossibility, and of the dogmatism that must 
exist in connection with all thought. In the case of 
Aenesidemus, who evidently gave the best efforts of his 
life to establish the Sceptical School, the dogmatism was 
probably unconscious. That he remained to the end 
a Sceptic is shown by the fact that he was known as 
such to posterity. Nowhere do we find a change of 
basis referred to in regard to him, and Sextus, in 
refuting the mistakes which he attributes to Aene- 
sidemus, does it, as it were, to point out something of 
which Aenesidemus had been unconscious. 

Let us consider here the second cause of Aeneside- 
mus' Dogmatism, the psychological effect upon himself 
of formulating Sceptical beliefs. The work that he did 
for the Sceptical School was a positive one. It occupied 
years of his life, and stamped itself upon his mental 
development. In formulating Scepticism, and in ad- 
vocating it against the many enemies of the School, 
and amidst all the excitement of the disruption from 
the Academy, and of establishing a new School, it was 



80 Sextus Empiricus and Greek ScepticisTn. 

inevitable that his mind should take a dogmatic ten- 
dency. He remained a Sceptic as he had always been, 
but must have grown dogmatic in his attitude towards 
the Sceptical formulae, and was thus able to adopt some 
of the teachings of Heraclitus, unconscious of their 
inconsistency. 

Where should we find a modern writer who is con- 
sistent in all his statements ? Could we read the works 
of Aenesidemus, we might better understand the con- 
nection between the apparently contradictory ideas in 
his teaching, but the inconsistencies in statement would 
probably remain. It is necessary to remember the 
position of Aenesidemus in breaking away from the 
Academy and in founding a new school, the full signi- 
ficance of which he could not foresee. There must 
necessarily be some crudeness in pioneer work, and some 
failure to see the bearing of all its parts, and a compiler 
like Sextus could point out the inconsistencies which 
the two centuries since the time of Aenesidemus had 
made plain. Aenesidemus was too positive a character 
to admit of absolute Sceptical consistency. He was 
nevertheless the greatest thinker the Sceptical School 
had known since the age of Pyrrho, its founder. In 
claiming a union between Pyrrhonism and the philo- 
sophy of Heraclitus, he recognised also the pre-Socratic 
tendency of the Sceptical School. The name of Socrates 
was all powerful in the Academy, but Aenesidemus com- 
prehended the fact that the true spirit of Pyrrhonism 
was of earlier origin than the Academic Scepsis. 



CHAPTER V. 

Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 

The distinct philosophical movement of which Pyrrho 
was the author bore his name for five centuries after his 
death. It had an acknowledged existence as a philo- 
sophical tendency, if indeed not a sect, for a great part 
of that time. Yet, when we carefully analyse the 
relation of Pyrrhonism, as presented to us by Sextus, 
to the teachings of Pyrrho himself, in so far as they 
can be known, we find many things in Pyrrhonism for 
which Pyrrho was not responsible. 

The foundation elements of the movement, the spirit 
of Empirical doubt that lay underneath and caused its 
development in certain directions rather than others, 
are due to Pyrrho. The methods of the school, however, 
were very foreign to anything found in the life or teach- 
ings of Pyrrho. Pyrrho was eminently a moralist. H4 
was also to a great degree an ascetic, and he lived his] 
philosophy, giving it thus a positive side wanting in the' 
Pyrrhonism presented to us by Sextus. Timon represents 
him as desiring to escape from the tedious philosophical 
discussions of his time — 

w yepop & Uipptav, itS)<s rj nroOev eKhvaiv evpe<; 
XaTpeirit Bo^&v Te K€VO(ppoa-vvr]^ re a-ocf>ia-To!)v ; 

6 



82 Sepctus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 



and again he speaks of his modest and tranquil life — 

toCto fioi, M TIvppwv, Ifieiperai ^rop uKOvaai 
TTWS TTOT dvTjp ET djeK; irdvTa ft,e6^ jjo'u^wj'; 
fiovvo^ S'dv6pay7roi<Ti 6eov Tpoirov •^yefioveveK 

^fjara fieff' rj<7V)(ir)^ 

alel d<ppovTlaT(o^ koX o.kiviJtq}'; KaTO. ravTa 
jMr] irpoae')^ IvhaXjjLol'i f)ZvK6<yov (jo^it)';} 

Pyrrho wished more than anything else to live in 
peace, and his dislike of the Sophists^ may well have 
made him try to avoid dialectic ; while, on the contrary, 
in the Pyrrhonean School of later times discussion was 
one of the principal methods of contest, at least after 
the time of Agrippa. Pyrrhonism seems to have been 
originally a theory of life, like the philosophy of Socrates, 
to whom Pyrrho is often compared,^ and Pyrrho, like 
Socrates, lived his philosophy. Our knowledge of 
Pyrrho is gained from Aristocles, Sextus Empiricus, 
and Diogenes, and from the Academic traditions given 
by Cicero. Diogenes gives us details of his life which 
he attributes to Antigonus of Carystius, who lived about 
the time of Pyrrho.* Pyrrho was a disciple and admirer 
of Democritus,^ some of whose teachings bore a lasting 
influence over the subsequent development of Pyrrho- 
nism. He accompanied Alexander the Great to India, 
where he remained as a member of his suite for some 
time, and the philosophical ideas of India were not 
without influence on his teachings. Oriental philosophy 

' Diog. IX. 11, 65. Giyen from MuUaoh's edition of Timon by 
Brochard, Fyrrlvm et le Scepticism primitive, p. 625. 

3 Diog. IX. 11, 69. 4 Diog. ix. 11, 62. 

3 Lewes Op. cit. p. 460. ^ Diog. ix. 11, 67. 



Critical ExamiTiation of Pyrrhonism. 83 

was not unknown in Greece long before the time of 
Pyrrho, but his personal contact with the Magi and the 
Gymnosophists of the far East, apparently impressed 
upon his mind teachings for which he was not unpre- 
pared by his previous study and natural disposition. 
In his indifference to worldly goods we find a strong 
trace of the Buddhistic teaching regarding the vanity 
of human life. He showed also a similar hopelessness 
in regard to the possibility of finding a satisfactory 
philosophy, or absolute truth. He evidently returned 
from India with the conviction that truth was not to 
be attained.-^ 

After the death of Alexander and Pyrrho's return 
to Greece, he lived quietly with his sister at Elis, and 
Diogenes says that he was consistent in his life, asserting 
and denying nothing, but in everything withholding his 
opinion, as nothing in itself is good or shameful, just or 
unjust.^ He was not a victim of false pride, but sold 
animals in the market place, and, if necessary, washed 
the utensils himself.^ He lived in equality of spirit, 
and practised his teachings with serenity. If one went 
out while he was talking he paid no attention, but went 
calmly on with his remarks.* He liked to live alone, 
and to travel alone, and on one occasion, being knocked 
about in a vessel by a storm at sea, he did not lose his 
imperturbability, but pointed to a swine calmly eating 
on board, and said that the wise man should have as 
much calmness of soul as that. He endured difiicult 
surgical operations with indifference,^ and when his 

1 Compare Maccoll Op. eit. * Diog. ix. 11, 63. 

2 Diog. IX. H, 61, 62. = Diog. ix. 11, 67. 

3 Diog. IX. 11, 66 



84 Sextus Empiricus and Oreek Scepticism. 

friend Anaxarchus was once unfortunate enough to fall 
into a morass, he went calmly by without stopping to 
help him, for which consistency of conduct Anaxarchus 
afterwards praised him. There are two instances given 
by Diogenes when he lost control of himself; once in 
getting angry with his sister, and once in trying to save 
himself when chased by a dog. When accused of incon- 
sistency, he said it was difficult to entirely give up one's 
humanity.^ He was greatly venerated by the people 
among whom he lived, who made him high priest, and 
on his account exempted all philosophers from taxation,^ 
and after his death erected a statue to his memory. 
These facts testify to his moral character, and also to 
fulfil the functions of high priest a certain amount of 
dogmatism must have been necessary. 

According to Diogenes, " We cannot know," said Pyr- 
rho, " what things are in themselves, either by sensation 
or by judgment, and, as we cannot distinguish the true 
from the false, therefore we should live impassively, and 
without an opinion." The term iiroxv, so characteristic 
of Pyrrhonism, goes back, according to Diogenes, to the 
time of Pyrrho.* Nothing is, in itself, one thing more 
than another, but all experience is related to pheno- 
mena, and no knowledge is possible through the senses.* 
Pyrrho's aim was arapa^ia and his life furnished a 
marked example of the spirit of indifference, for which 
the expression dirddeca is better suited than the later 
one, drapa^ia. The description of his life with his sister 
confirms this, where the term dSta<j)opla is used to 



' Diog. IX. H, 66. 3 Diog. ix. 11, 61. 

' Diog. IX. 11, 64. * Diog. ix. U, 61—62. 



Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism, 85 

describe his conduct.^ He founded his Scepticism on 
the equivalence of opposing arguments.^ 

The picture given of Pyrrho by Cicero is entirely 
different from that of Diogenes, and contrasts decidedly 
with it.^ Cicero knows Pyrrho as a severe moralist, not 
as a Sceptic. Both authors attribute to Pyrrho the 
doctrine of indifference and apathy, but, according to 
Cicero, Pyrrho taught of virtue, honesty, and the 
summ,um honum,, while Diogenes plainly tells us that 
he considered nothing as good in itself, ''and of all things 
nothing as true." * Cicero does not once allude to Pyrrho- 
nean doubt. We see on the one hand, in Cicero's idea 
of Pyrrho, the influence of the Academy, perhaps even 
of Antiochus himself,^ which probably colored the 
representations given of Pyrrho ; but, on the other hand, 
there is much in Diogenes' account of Pyrrho's life and 
teachings, and in the writings of Timon, which shows us 
the positive side of Pyrrho. Pyrrho, in denying the 
possibility of all knowledge, made that rather a motive 
for indifference in the relations of life, than the founda- 
tion thought of a philosophical system. His teaching 
has a decided ethical side, showing in that respect the 
strong influence of Democritus over him, who, like 
Pyrrho, made happiness to consist in a state of feeling.^ 
The one motive of all of Pyrrho's teaching is a positive 
one, the desire for happiness. 

The essence of Pyrrhonism as given by Timon is as 
follows :'^ Man desires to be happy. To realise his 

' Diog. IX. 11. 66. " Compare Natorp Op. eit. p. 71. 

' Diog. IX. 11. 106. * Zeller Grundriss der Grieohischen Phil, p. 70. 

3 De oral. HI, 62. '' Aristocles ap. Emebium Praep. Ev. xiv. 18. 
* Diog. IX. 11, 61. 



86 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

desire he must consider three things : 
(i) What is the nature of things ? 

(ii) How should man conduct himself in relation to 
them? 

(iii) What is the result to him of this relation ? 

The nature of things is unknown. Our relation to 
them must be one of suspension of judgment, without 
activity, desire, or belief, — that is, an entirely negative 
relation. The result is that state of having no opinion, 
called cTTO'xij, which is followed in turn by uTapa^la. 

^The problem of philosophy is here proposed very 
nearly in the terms of Kant, but not with the positive 
motive, like that of the great philosopher of Germany, 
of evolving a system to present the truth. Yet the im- 
portance of these questions shows the originality of 
Pyrrho. The earnestness of Pyrrho is further shown by 
an example given by Diogenes. Once on being found 
talking to himself alone, he said, when asked the reason, 
that he was meditating how to become a good man 
(p^pT/o-To?),^ thus showing an entirely different spirit 
from anything found in Sextus' books. The explanation 
of his life and teachings is to be found largely in his 
own disposition. Such an attitude of indifference must 
belong to a placid nature, and cannot be entirely the 
result of a philosophical system, and, while it can be 
aimed at, it can never be perfectly imitated. One of 
his disciples recognised this, and said that it was neces- 
sary to have the disposition of Pyrrho in order to hold his 
doctrines.^ Diogenes tells us that he was the first to 
advance any formulae of Scepticism,* but they must 

> Compare MaccoU Op.cit. p. 21. ^ Diog. ix. II, 70, 64. 

« Diog. IX. 11, 64. * Diog. ix. 11, 69; ix. 11, 61. 



Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 87 



have been very elementary, as Pyrrho himself wrote 
nothing. We find no trace of formulated Tropes in 
Pyrrho's teachings, yet it is probable that he indicated 
some of the contradictions in sensation, and possibly the 
Tropes in some rudimentary form. Of the large number 
of sceptical formulae, or ^avai, the three which seem to 
have the oldest connection with Scepticism are the di'Tt- 
\oyia, the ovBev opi^m, and the ol fwXKov} We know 
from Diogenes that Protagoras is the authority for saying 
that in regard to everything there are two opposing 
arguments.^ The saying " to determine nothing " is 
quoted from Timon's Python by Diogenes,^ and the 
other two mentioned are also attributed to him by 
Aristocles.* We have also in the ov (laXkov a direct 
connection with Democritus, although the difference in 
the meaning which he attributed to it is shown by 
Sextus.^ So while the expression is the same, the 
explanation of it given by Pyrrho must have been 
different. It would seem probable that Pyrrho used 
all of these three sayings, from the account of Diogenes, 
and that even then they gave rise to the accusation of 
the Dogmatics, that simply by possessing such sayings 
the Sceptics dogmatised,^ for the refutation of this used 
by Sextus occurs in the old account of the sayings, 
namely, that these formulae include also themselves 
in the meaning, as a cathartic removes itself together 
with other harmful objects.^ 

In comparing the later Pyrrhonism with the teach- 
ings of Pyrrho, we would sharply contrast the moral 

' Hyp. I. 202 ; Diog. ix. 8, 51 ; Photiua Bekker's ed. 280 H. 
2 Pholius Bekker's ed. 280 H. » Syp. i. 197 ; Diog. ix. 11. 76. 
» Aristoclea op. Emebium, Praep. Ev. xiv.18. ' Syp. i. 213. 

» Diog. IX. 11, 68—76. ' Diog. ix. 11, 76; Syp. i. 206. 



88 Sextus Empincus and Greek Sceptidsm. 

attitude of the two. With Pyrrho equilibrium of soul 
was a means to be applied to his positive theory of life ; 
with the later Pyrrhoneans it was the end to be attained. 
We would attribute, however, the empirical tendency 
shown during the whole history of Pyrrhonism to Pyrrho 
as its originator. He was an empirical philosopher, and 
the result of his influence in this respect, as seen in the 
subsequent development of the school, stands in marked 
contrast to the dialectic spirit of the Academic Scepsis. 
The empiricism of the school is shown in its scientific 
lore, in the fact that so many of the Sceptics were 
physicians, and in the character of the ten Tropes of 
iiroxv- We may safely affirm that the foundation 
principles of Pyrrhonism are due to Pyrrho, and the 
originality which gave the school its power. The 
elaborated arguments, however, and the details of its 
formulae belong to later times. 

Coming now to the relation of Pyrrhonism to the 
Academy, the connection between the two is difficult 
to exactly determine, between the time of Pyrrho and 
that of Aenesidemus. Scepticism in the Academy was, 
however, never absolutely identical with Pyrrhonism, 
although at certain periods of the history of the Aca- 
demy the difiference was slight. We can trace throughout 
the evolution of doubt, as shown to us in Pyrrhonism, 
and in Academic Scepticism, the different results which 
followed the difference in origin of the two movements, 
and these differences followed according to general laws 
of development of thought. Arcesilaus, who introduced 
doubt into the Academy, claimed to return to the dia- 
lectic of Socrates, and suppressing the lectures,^ which 
' Compare MaecoU Op. eit. p. 36. 



Critical Exatnination of Pyrrhonism. 89 

were the method of teaching in the later schools of 
philosophy, introduced discussions instead, as being 
more decidedly a Socratic method. Although, accord- 
ing to Sextus, he was the one leader of the Academy 
whose Scepticism most nearly approached that of 
Pyrrhonisna,'- yet underneath his whole teaching lay 
that dialectic principle so thoroughly in opposition to 
the empiricism of Pyrrho. The belief of Socrates and 
Plato in the existence of absolute truth never entirely 
lost its influence over the Academy, but was like a 
hidden germ, destined to reappear after Scepticism had 
passed away. It finally led the Academy back to Dog- 
matism, and prepared the way for the Eclecticism with 
which it disappeared from history. 

The history of Pyrrhonism and that of Academic 
Scepticism were for a time contemporaneous. The im- 
mediate follower of Pyrrho, Timon, called by Sextus the 
"prophet of Pyrrho,"^ was a contemporary of Arcesilaus. 
That he did not consider the Scepticism of the Academy 
identical with Pyrrhonism is proved from the fact that 
he did not himself join the Academy, but was, on the 
contrary, far from doing so. That he regarded Arcesilaus 
as a Dogmatic is evident from his writings.^ One day, 
on seeing the chief of the Academy approaching, he 
cried out, " What are you doing here among us who are 
free?"* After the death of Timon, the Pyrrhonean 
School had no representative till the time of Ptolemy 
of Gyrene,^ and Greek Scepticism was represented by 
the Academy. That Pyrrho had a strong influence 
over Arcesilaus, the founder of the Middle Academy, 

' Syp. I. 232. 2 Adv. Math. i. 53. ' Diog. iv. 6, 33, 34. 
* Diog. IX. 12, 114. '= Diog. ix. 12, 115. 



^ 



90 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

is evident^ ; but there was also never a time when the 
Academy entirely broke away from all the teachings of 
Plato, even in their deepest doubt.^ It is true that 
Arcesilaus removed, nominally as well as in spirit, some 
of the dialogues of Plato from the Academy, but only 
those that bore a dogmatic character, while those that 
presented a more decided Socratic mode of questioning, 
without reaching any decided result, men regarded as 
authority for Scepticism. 

Sextus does not deny that Arcesilaus was almost a 
Pyrrhonean, but he claims that his Pyrrhonism was 
only apparent, and not real, and was used as a cloak to 
hide his loyalty to the teachings- of Plato.' As Ariston 
said of him,* " Plato before, Pyrrho behind, Diodorus in 
the middle." Sextus also characterises the method of 
Arcesilaus as dialectic,^ and we know from Cicero that 
it was his pride to pretend to return to the dialectic of 
Socrates. 

It is interesting to note that Sextus, in his refuta- 
tion of the position that the Academy is the same as 
Pyrrhonism, takes up the entire development of Aca- 
demic thought from the time of Plato till that of 
Antiochus, and does not limit the argument to Scep- 
ticism under Arcesilaus. The claim made by some 
that the two schools were the same, is stated by him,* 
and the word 'some' probably refers to members of 
both schools at different periods of their history. Sextus 
recognises three Academies, although he remarks that 
some make even a further division, calling that of Philo 

' Diog. IT. 6, 33. » Diog. iv. 6, 33. 

2 Diog. IV. 6, 32. 5 Bpp. i. 234. 

» Sffp. I. 234. "> Syp. I. 220. 



Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 91 

and Charmides, the fourth, and that of Antiochus and 
his followers, the fifth. 

That many in the Academy, and even outside of it, 
regarded Plato as a Sceptic, and an authority for sub- 
sequent Scepticism, we find both from Sextus and 
Diogenes.^ As Lewes justly remarks, one could -well 
find authority for Scepticism in the works of Plato, as 
indeed the Academicians did, but not when the sum 
total of his teachings was considered. The spirit of 
Plato's teachings was dogmatic, as Sextus most de- 
cidedly recognises, and as Aenesidemus and Menodotus^ 
recognised before him.^ Sextus himself shows us that 
Plato's idealism and ethical teachings can have nothing 
in common with Scepticism, for if he accepts the 
desirability of the virtuous life, and the existence of 
Providence, he dogmatises ; and if he even regards 
them as probable, he gives preference to one set of 
ideas over another, and departs from the sceptical 
character. Sextus characterises the sceptical side of 
Plato's writings as mental gymnastics,* which do not 
authorise his being called a Sceptic, and affirms that 
Plato is not a Sceptic, since he prefers some unknown 
things to others in trustworthiness. The ethical differ- 
ence underlying the teachings of the Academy and 
Pyrrhonism, Sextus was very quick to see, and although 
it is very probable that the part of the Hypotyposes 
which defines the difference between the Academy and 
Pyrrhonism may be largely quoted from the introduc- 
tion to Aenesidemus' works, yet Sextus certainly gives 
these statements the strong stamp of his approval. He 

' Hyp. I. 221 ; Diog. ix. 11, 72. » Syp. i. 222. 

2 Bekker's edition of Hyp. i. 222. * Hyp. i. 223. 



92 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

condemns the Academy because of the theory that good 
and evil exist, or if this'cannot be decidedly proved, yet 
that it is more probable that what is called good exists 
than the contrary.^ 

The whole Academic teaching of probabilities con- 
tradicted the standpoint of the Sceptics — that our ideas 
are equal as regards trustworthiness and untrustworthi- 
ness,^ for the Academicians declared that some ideas 
are probable and some improbable, and they make a 
difference even in those ideas that they call probable. 

Sextus claims that there are three fundamental 
grounds of difference between Pyrrhonism and the 
Academy. The first is the doctrine of probability 
which the Academicians accept in regard to the supe- 
rior trustworthiness of some ideas over others.* The 
second is the different way in which the two schools 
follow their teachers. The Pyrrhoneaus follow without 
striving or strong effort, or even strong inclination, as a 
child follows his teacher, while the Academicians follow 
with sympathy and assent, as Carneades and Clito- 
machus affirm.* The third difference is in the aim, for 
the Academicians follow what is probable in life. The 
Sceptics follow nothing, but live according to laws, 
customs, and natural feelings undogmatically.^ 

The difference between the later teaching of the 
Academy and Pyrrhonism is evident, and Sextus treats 
of it briefly, as not requiring discussion,^ as Philo taught 
that the nature of facts is incomprehensible, and Antio- 
chus transferred the Stoa to the Academy. It is therefore 

' Bi^p. I. 226. * ffpp. I. 230. 

■' Hyp. I. 227. « Byp. i. 231. 

3 Hyp. I. 229. 8 Hyp. i. 236. 



Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 93 

evident, from the comparison which we have made, 
that we do not find in the Academy, with which Scep- 
ticism after the death of Timon was so long united, the 
exact continuance of Pyrrhonism. The philosophical 
enmity of the two contemporaries, Timon and Arcesilaus, 
the Academician who had most in common with Pyr- 
rhonism, is an expression of the fundamental incom- 
patibility between the two schools. 

During all the chequered history of the Academy 
the dormant idealism was there, underlying the outward 
development. Although during the time of Ai'cesilaus 
and Carneades the difference was so slight as to seem 
a mere matter of form of expression, yet the different 
foundations on which the two schools stood was always 
recognisable. On the one hand there was the germ of 
idealism which was destined to awake to a new life, 
and on the other, the attempt at absolute negation 
which was to result in the final extinction of Pyrrho- 
nism. We find in both, it is true, especially in the 
time of Arcesilaus, the aim of iiroxn-^ Both placed 
great weight on la-oadiveia, or the equal value of 
opposing arguments.^ The foundation of the eVoj^jJ 
was, however, different in the two cases. Arcesilaus 
founded his on dialectic, while Pyrrho's was empirical. 

The Pyrrhonean believed that ideas give us no 
knowledge of the outer world; the Academic Sceptic 
believed that we cannot distinguish between true and 
false ideas, so such knowledge is impossible. The 
Pyrrhonean denied that truth could exist in ideas 
because of their contradictory nature, and consequently 

'■ Syp. I. 232. ' Diog. ix. 73 ; Syp. ii. 130 ; iii. 65. 



94 Seodus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

the existence of all truth, fjurfiev ehai rfj aXrjdeia i-irl 
ircLVToov} The Academic Sceptic granted that the 
truth was possibly contained in ideas, but affirmed 
that it could never be known to us. The Pyrrhoneans 
prided themselves on still being seekers, for although 
ordinary ideas are too contradictory to give knowledge 
of the outer world, they did not deny that such know- 
ledge might be possible, but simply suspended the 
judgment regarding it. To the Pyrrhonean the result 
corresponded to the method. All ideas thus far known 
revealed nothing of the truth, therefore he still sought. 
The Academician tried logically to prove that the truth 
is impossible to find. It is the relation of the dialec- 
tician to the empiricist, and the two varieties of 
Scepticism are explained by their difference in origin. 
In Pyrrhonism there was no constructive element. In 
the Academic Scepsis such an element was found 
throughout all its history in the theory of Probability. 
Arcesilaus himself laid great stress upon this doctrine, 
which Sextus carefully shows us^ is utterly inconsist- 
ent with Pyrrhonism. Arcesilaus plainly teaches that, 
having suspended one's judgment in regard to matters 
of knowledge, one should control his choices, his refusals, 
and his actions by the probable.^ 

After Antiochus introduced Eclecticism into the 
Academy, Pyrrhonism was the only representative of 
Greek Scepticism, and it flourished for over two cen- 
turies after our era, and then also disappeared, no more 
to exist as a regular philosophical school. 

' Diog. IX. 11, 61. 3 Hyp. i. 229. 

3 Compare Maocoll Op. cii. 39. 



Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 95 

Having considered at length the essence of Pyrrho- 
nism as presented by Sextus Empiricus, it now remains 
to briefly note the characteristics that formed its strength 
and weakness, and the causes of its final downfall. 
Herbart says that every philosopher is a Sceptic in the 
beginning, but every Sceptic remains always in the 
beginning. This remark may well be applied to Pyr- 
rhonism. We find in its teachings many fundamental 
philosophical truths which might have formed the be- 
ginning of great philosophical progress, but which were 
never developed to any positive results. The teachings 
of Pyrrhonism were some of them well fitted to prepare 
the way to idealism. The great idea of the relativity of 
Vorstellungen is made very prominent by the ten Tropes 
of eTToxv- Aenesidemus, in his eight Tropes against 
aetiology, shows the absurdity of the doctrine of causality 
when upheld on materialistic grounds. That was to him 
final, iirel ovk ea-Tai aiTtov. He could not divine that 
although the result which he presented was logical, it 
only led to a higher truth. It was reserved for the 
greatest of modern philosophers to reveal to the world 
that causality is a condition, and a necessary condition, 
of thought. When Aenesidemus proved by his seventh 
Trope that causality is subjective, he regarded it as fatal 
to the doctrine ; yet this conclusion was a marked step 
in advance in critical philosophy, although Aesesidemus 
could not himself see it in all its bearings. The great 
difference between Aenesidemus and Kant is the differ- 
ence between the materialist and the believer in sub- 
, jective reality. Both agreed in the unknown nature of 
the Ding an sick, but this was to the Pyrrhonist the end 
of all his philosophy ; to Kant, however, the beginning. 



96 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

Pyrrhonism has rendered, notwithstanding its points 
of fatal weakness, marked service to the world in science, 
philosophy, ethics, and religion. It quickened scientific 
thought by emphasising empirical methods of investi- 
gation, and by criticising all results founded without 
sufficient data upon false hypotheses. If, instead of 
denying the possibility of all science because of the 
want of a criterion of the truth of phenomena, the 
Pyrrhonists had comprehended the possibility of a 
science of phenomena, they might have led the world 
in scientific progress.' Their service to philosophy lay 
in the stimulus to thought that their frequent attacks 
on dogmatic beliefs occasioned. Pyrrhonism brought 
together all the most prominent theories of the old 
schools of philosophy to test their weakness and expose 
their contradictions, and this very process of criticism 
often demonstrated the power of the truth which they 
contained. 

Sextus Empiricus was often charged by the Church 
Fathers with corrupting religious belief, and yet the 
greatest service which Pyrrhonism has rendered the 
world was in religious and ethical lines. This service 
did not, naturally, consist in destroying belief in abso- 
lute truth, as the Sceptic professed to do, but in preparing 
the way to find it. The bold attacks of Scepticism on 
all truth led men to investigate ethical and religious 
teachings, to examine the grounds of their belief, and 
to put in practical use the right of reason and free 
discussion. 

Scepticism was the antecedent of freedom of con- 
science and rational criticism,^ and the absolute right of 

* Compare Lewea Op. cit. p. 463. " Compare Chaignet Op, eit. p. 460. 



Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 97 

scientific thought. The Sceptics, however, reaped none 
of the benefits of their own system. They remained, as 
it were, always on the threshold of possible progress. 
With the keys to great discoveries in their hands, the 
doors of philosophical and scientific advancement were 
for ever closed to them by the limitations of their ojvn 
system. The inherent weakness of Pyrrhonism lay in its 
psychological inconsistency and in its negative character. 
I think that we may safely say that Pyrrhonism was the 
most consistent system of Scepticism ever offered to the 
world, and yet it proves most decidedly that complete 
Scepticism is psychologically impossible. A man may 
give up his belief in one set of ideas, and, if they are 
ideas that are popularly accepted, he will be called a 
Sceptic, as was the case with Hume. He must, however, 
replace these ideas by others equally positive, and then 
he is no longer a Sceptic, but a Dogmatic, for he believes 
in something. 

We have shown that the greatest thinkers of Pyrrho- 
nism, Pyrrho, Aenesidemus, and Agrippa, were not 
•examples of absolute Scepticism, and although Sextus 
Empiricus realised what consistency demanded in this 
respect, and affirmed on almost every page that he was 
asserting nothing, yet there is not a paragraph of his 
books in which he does not, after all, dogmatise on some 
subject. Complete Scepticism is contrary to the funda- 
mental laws of language, as all use of verbs involves ' 
some affirmation. The Pyrrhonists realised this, and 
therefore some of them wrote nothing, like Pyrrho, 
their leader, and others advocated a(j)a<ria^ as one of 
the doctrines of their system. 

1 Hyp, u 192, 

7 



98 Sextus Empiricus and Greek Scepticism. 

The very aim of Pyrrhonism was an inconsistent 
one. 'Arapa^la was only another name for happiness, 
and in one instance, even, is given as ■^Sovij, and thus, 
in spite of themselves, the Sceptics introduced a theory 
of happiness. Pyrrho, like others of his time, sought 
the highest good, and thought that he had found it in 
drapa^ta, the peace of mind that appears in other systems; 
of philosophy in other forms.- The difference of aim 
between the Pyrrhonists, Stoics, and Epicureans was 
more apparent than real. To them all philosophy was 
a path to lead to happiness. The method of Pyrrhonism 
was, however, negative. Its strength consisted in its 
attacks on Dogmatism, and not in any positive aim of 
its own, for its positive side could not be recognised 
according to its own doctrines. Therefore there was 
no real development in Pyrrhonism, for a negative 
thought cannot be developed. 

We find, accordingly, from the time of Pyrrho to 
Sextus, no growth in breadth of philosophical outlook, 
only improvement in methods. Philosophical activity 
can never have doubt as its aim, as that would form, as 
we have shown, a psychological contradiction. The true 
esseuce of Pyrrhonism was passivity, but passivity can 
never lead to progress. Much of the polemical work of 
Pyrrhonism prepared the way for scientific progress by 
providing a vast store of scientific data, but progress 
was to the Pyrrhonists impossible. They sounded their 
own scientific death-knell by declaring the impossibility 
of science, and putting an end to all theories. 

The life of all scientific and philosophic progress is 
in the attempt to find the hidden truth. To the Sceptic 
there was no truth, and there could be no progress. As. 



Critical Examination of Pyrrhonism. 99 

progress is a law in the evolution of the human race, so 
Scepticism as a philosophy could never be a permanent 
growth, any more than asceticism in religion can be a^ 
lasting influence. Both of them are only outgrowths. 
As the foundation principles of Scepticism were opposed 
to anything like real growth, it was a system that could 
never originate anything. Pyrrho taught from the 
beginning that the Sceptic must live according to law 
and custom ; not, however, because one law or custom 
is better than another in itself, but simply for the sake 
of peace. This basis of action was itself a death-blow 
to all reform in social or political life. It was a selfish, 
negative way of seeking what was, after all, a positive 
thing, the arapa^ia that the Sceptic desired. Life with 
the Pyrrhonist was phenomenal, and not phenomenal 
simply in regard to the outer world, but also subjec- 
tively, and no absolute knowledge of the subjective life 
or of personal existence was possible. 

The cause of the downfall of Pyrrhonism lay in the 
fact that it had nothing to ofier to humanity in the 
place of what it had destroyed. It made no appeal to 
human sympathies, and ignored all the highest motives 
to human action. The especial materialistic standpoint 
from which Pyrrhonism judged all that pertains to 
knowledge and life shut out the ideal, and all possi- 
bility of absolute truth. It was an expression of the 
philosophic decadence of the age when it flourished, 
and although it possessed some philosophic worth, yet 
it bore in itself the causes of its decay. 



PYERHOOTO SKETCHES 



BY 



SEXTUS EMPIEIOUS. 
BOOK I. 



PYRRHONIC SKETCHES, Book I. 

CHAPTER I. 

The Principal Differences between Philosophers. 

It is probable that those who seek after anything 
whatever, will either find it as they continue the search, 1 
will deny that it can be found and confess it to be out of 
reach, or will go on seeking it. Some have said, accordingly, 
in regard to the things sought in philosophy, that they ^ 
have found the truth, while others have declared it impossible 
to find, and still others continue to seek it. Those who 
think that they have found it are those who are especially 
called Dogmatics, as for example, the Schools of Aristotle 
and Epicurus, the Stoics and some others. Those who have ** 
declared it impossible to find are Clitomachus, Carneades, 
with their respective followers, and other Academicians. 
Those who still seek it are the Sceptics. It appears there- 
fore, reasonable to conclude that the three principal kinds ^ 
of philosophy are the Dogmatic, the Academic, and the 
Sceptic. Others may suitably treat of the other Schools, 
but as for the Sceptical School, we shall now give an out- 
line of it, remarking in advance that in respect to nothing 
that will be said do we speak positively, that it must be 
absolutely so, but we shall state each thing historically as 
it now appears to us. 

CHAPTER II. 

Ways of Treating Scepticism. 

One way of treating the Sceptical philosophy is called 5 
general, and the other special. The general method is that 



104 Pyrrhonio Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

by -whicli we set forth the character of Scepticism, declaring 
what its idea is, what its principles are, its mode of reason- 
ing its criterion, and its aim. It presents also, the aspects 
of doubt, ol rpoTToi t^? fVo^Tj?, and the way in which we 
should understand the Sceptical formulae, and the distinction 
between Scepticism and the related Schools of philosophy. 

6 The special method, on the contrary, is that by which we 
speak against each part of so-called philosophy. Let us then 
treat Scepticism at iirst in the general way, beginning our 
delineation with the nomenclature of the Sceptical School. 

CHAPTEE III. 

The Nomenclature of Scepticism. 

7 The Sceptical School is also called the "Seeking School,"! 
from its spirit of research and examination ; the " Suspend- 
ing School," from the condition of mind in which one is 
left after the search, in regard to the things that he has 
examined; and the "Doubting School," either because, as 
some say, the Sceptics doubt and are seeking in regard to 
everything, or because they never know whether to deny 
or affirm. It is also called the Pyrrhonean School, 
because Pyrrho appears to us the best representative of 
Scepticism, and is more prominent than all who before him 
occupied themselves with it. 

CHAPTER IV. 

WTiat is Scepticism? 

8 The BvvafMK of the Sceptical School is to place the 
! phenomenal in opposition to the intellectual " in any way 
! whatever," and thus through the equilibrium of the reasons 

and things {laoerOiveia t&v Xoyav) opposed to each 
other, to reach, first the state of suspension of judgment. 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 105 

i-TTO'^ij, and afterwards that of imperturbability, dra- 
pa^La. We do not use the word Bwu/jli'; in any 9 
unusual sense, but simply, meaning the force of the system. 
By the phenomenal, we understand the sensible, hence we 
place the intellectual in opposition to it. The phrase "in 
any way whatever," may refer to the word hvvaiu<; in 
order that we may understand that word in a simple sense 
as we said, or it may refer to the placing the phenomenal 
and intellectual in opposition. For we place these in 
opposition to each other in a variety of ways, the phenomenal 
to the phenomenal, and the intellectual to the intellectual, 
or reciprocally, and we say "in any way whatever," in 
order that all methods of opposition may be included. Or 
" in any way whatever " may refer to the phenomenal and 
the intellectual, so that we need not ask how does the 
phenomenal appear, or how are the thoughts conceived, but 
that we may understand these things in a simple sense. By 
"reasons opposed to each other,'' we do not by any means 10 
understand that they deny or affirm anything, but simply 
that they offset each other. By equilibrium, we mean 
equality in regard to trustworthiness and untrustworthiness, 
so that of the reasons that are placed in opposition to each 
other, one should not excel another in trustworthiness. 
iwo'xrj is a holding back of the opinion, in consequence 
of which we neither deny nor affirm anything, cnapa^ia 
is repose and tranquillity of soul. We shall explain how 
arapa^ia accompanies i'TO'^t) when we speak of the aim. 

CHAPTER V. 

The Sceptic. 

What is meant by a Pyrrhonean philosopher can be 11 
understood from the idea of the Sceptical School. He is a 
Pyrrhonean, namely, who identifies himself with this system. 



106 Pyrrhonic Sketches hy Sextus Empiricus. 



CHAPTER VI. 

The Origin of Scepticism. 

12 Scepticism arose in the beginning from the hope of 
attaining arapa^ia ; for men of the greatest talent were per- 
plexed by the contradiction of things, and being at a loss 
what to believe, began to question what things are true, 
and what false, hoping to attain arapa^ia as a result of the 
decision. The fundamental principle of the Sceptical sys- 
tem is especially this, namely, to oppose every argument 
by one of equal weight, for it seems to us that in this way 
we finally reach the position where we have no dogmas. 



CHAPTER VII. 

Does the Sceptic Dogmatise? 

13 We say that the Sceptic does not dogmatise. We do 
not say this, meaning by the word dogma the popular assent 
to certain things rather than others (for the Sceptic does 
assent to feelings that are a necessary result of sensation, 
as for example, when he is warm or cold, he cannot say 
that he thinks he is not warm or cold), but we say this, 
meaning by dogma the acceptance of any opinion in regard 
to the unknown things investigated by science. For the 

14 Pyrrhonean assents to nothing that is unknown. Further- 
more, he does not dogmatise even when he utters the 
Sceptical formulae in regard to things that are unknown, 
such as " Nothing more," or " I decide nothing," or any of 
the others about which we shall speak later. For the one 
who dogmatises regards the thing about which he is said 
to dogmatise, as existing in itself; the Sceptic does not 
however regard these formulae as having an absolute 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Seodus Empi/ricus. 107 

existence, for he assumes that the saying "All is false," 
includes itself with other things as false, and likewise the 
saying "Nothing is true"; in the same way "Nothing 
more," states that together with other things it itself is 
nothing more, and cancels itself therefore, as well as other 
things. We say the same also in regard to the other 
Sceptical expressions. In short, if he who dogmatises 
assumes as existing in itself that about which he dogmatises, 15 
the Sceptic, on the contrary, expresses his sayings in such a 
way that they are understood to be themselves included, 
and it cannot be said that he dogmatises in saying these 
things. The principal thing in uttering these formulae is 
that he says what appears to him, and communicates his 
own feelings in an unprejudiced way, without asserting 
anything in regard to external objects. 



CHAPTER VIII. 

Is Scepticism a Sect? 

We respond in a similar way if we are asked whether 16 
Scepticism is a sect or not. If the word sect is defined as 
meaning a body of persons who hold dogmas which are in 
conformity with each other, and also with phenomena, and 
dogma means an assent to anything that is unknown, then 
we reply that we have no sect. If, however, one means by 17 
sect, a school which follows a certain line of reasoning based 
on phenomena, and that reasoning shows how it is possible 
to apparently live rightly, not understanding "rightly" as 
referring to virtue only, but in a broader sense ; if, also, it 
leads one to be able to suspend the judgment, then we 
reply that we have a sect. For we follow a certain kind of 
reasoning which is' based upon phenomena, and which shows 
us how to live according to the habits, laws, and teachings 
of the fatherland, and our own feelings. 



108 Pyrrhonio Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

CHAPTER IX, 

Does the Sceptic Study Natural Science? 

18 We reply similarly also to the question whether the 
Sceptic should study natural science. For we do not study 
natural science in order to express ourselves with confidence 
regarding any of the dogmas that it teaches, but we take it 
up in order to be able to meet every argument by one of 
equal weight, and also for the sake of UTapa^ia. In the 
same way we study the logical and ethical part of so-called 
philosophy. 

CHAPTEE X. 

Do the Sceptics deny Phenomena? 

19 Those who say that the Sceptics deny phenomena 
appear to me to be in ignorance of our teachings. For as 
we said before, we do not deny the sensations which we 
think we have, and which lead us to assent involuntarily 
to them, and these are the phenomena. When, however, 
we ask whether the object is such as it appears to be, 
while we concede that it appears so and so, we question, 
not the phenomenon, but in regard to that which is asserted 
of the phenomenon, and that is different from doubting 
the phenomenon itself. For example, it appears to us 

20 that honey is sweet. This we concede, for we experience 
sweetness through sensation. We doubt, however, whether 
it is sweet by reason of its essence, which is not a question 
of the phenomenon, but of that which is asserted of the 
phenomenon. Should we, however, argue directly against 
the phenomena, it is not with the intention of denying 
their existence, but to show the rashness of the Dogmatics. 
For if reasoning is such a deceiver that it well nigh snatches 
away the phenomena from before your eyes, how should 
we not distrust it in regard to things that are unknown, so 
as not to rashly follow it 1 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 109 



CHAPTEE XI. 

The Criterion of Scepticism. 

It is evident that we pay careful attention to phenomena 21 
from what we say about the criterion of the Sceptical 
School. The word criterion is used in two ways. First, 
it is understood as a proof of existence or non-existence, in 
regard to which we shall speak in the opposing argument. 
Secondly, when it refers to action, meaning the criterion to 
which we give heed in life, in doing some things and 
refraining from doing others, and it is about this that we 
shall now speak. We say, consequently, that the criterion 
of the Sceptical School is the phenomenon, and in calling 22 
it so, we mean the idea of it. It cannot be doubted, as it 
is based upon susceptibility and involuntary feeling. Hence 
no one doubts, perhaps, that an object appears so and so, 
but one questions if it is as it appears. Therefore, as we 
cannot be entirely inactive as regards the observances of 
daily life, we live by giving heed to phenomena, and in an 
unprejudiced way. But this observance of what pertains 23 
to the daily life, appears to be of four different kinds. 
Sometimes it is directed by the guidance of nature, some- 
times by the necessity of the feelings, sometimes by the 
tradition of laws and of customs, and sometimes by 
the teaching of the arts. It is directed by the guidance of 24 
nature, for by nature we are capable of sensation and 
thought ; by the necessity of the feelings, for hunger leads 
us to food, and thirst to drink ; by the traditions of laws 
and customs, for according to them we consider piety a 
good in daily life, and impiety an evil ; by the teaching of 
the arts, for we are not inactive in the arts we undertake. 
We [say all these things, however, without expressing a 
decided opinion. 



110 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 



CHAPTER XII. 

What is the aim of Scepticism ? 

25 It follows naturally in order to treat of the iiim of the 
Sceptical School. An aim is that for which as an end all 
things are done or thought, itself depending on nothing, or 
in other words, it is the ultimatum of things to be desired. 
We say, then, that the aim of the Sceptic is aTupa^la in 
those things which pertain to the opinion, and moderatioa 

26 in the things that life imposes. For as soon as he began 
to philosophise he wished to discriminate between ideas, 
and to understand which are true and which are false, in 
order to attain arapa^la. He met, however, with contra- 
dictions of equal weight, and, being unable to judge, he 
withheld his opinion ; and while his judgment was in sus- 
pension drapa^ia followed, as if by chance, in regard to 

27 matters of opinion. For he who is of the opinion that 
anything is either good or bad by nature is always troubled, 
and when he does not possess those things that seem to 
him good he thinks that he is tortured by the things which 
are by nature bad, and pursues those that he thinks to 
be good. Having acquired them, however, he falls into 
greater perturbation, because he is excited beyond reason 
and without measure from fear of a change, and he does 
everything in his power to retain the things that seem to 

28 tim good. But he who is undecided, on the contrary, 
regarding things that are good and bad by nature, neither 
seeks nor avoids anything eagerly, and is therefore in a 
state of cnapa^ia. For that which is related of Apelles the 
painter happened to the Sceptic. It is said that as he was 
once painting a horse he wished to represent the foam of 
his mouth in the picture, but he could not succeed in 
doing so, and he gave it up and threw the sponge at thp 
picture with which he had wiped the colors from tha 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Seostus Empiricus. Ill 

painting. As soon, however, as it touched the picture it 
produced a good copy of the foam. The Sceptics likewise 29 
hoped to gain drapa^ia by forming judgments in regard 
to the anomaly between phenomena and the things of 
thought, but they were unable to do this, and so they 
suspended their judgment ; and while their judgment was 
in suspension ajapa^ia followed, as if by chance, as the 
shadow follows a body. Nevertheless, we do not consider 
the Sceptic wholly undisturbed, but he is disturbed by 
some things that are inevitable. We confess that some- 
times he is cold and thirsty, and that he suffers in such 
ways. But in these things even the ignorant are beset in 30 
two ways, from the feelings themselves, and not less also 
from the fact that they think these conditions are bad by 
nature. The Sceptic, however, escapes more easily, as he 
rejects the opinion that anything is in itself bad by nature. 
Therefore we say that the aim of the Sceptic is arapa^la 
in matters of opinion, and moderation of feeling in those 
things that are inevitable. Some notable Sceptics have 
added also suspension of judgment in investigation. 

CHAPTER XIII. 

The General Method of Scepticism. 

Since we have said that arrapa^ia follows the suspension 31 
of judgment in regard to everything, it behooves us to 
explain how the suspension of judgment takes place. 
Speaking in general it takes place through placing things 
in opposition to each other. We either place phenomena 
in opposition to phenomena, or the intellectual in opposi- 
tion to the intellectual, or reciprocally. For example, we 32 
place phenomena in opposition to phenomena when we say 
that this tower appears round from a distance but square 
near by ; the intellectual in opposition to the intellectual, 
when to the one who from the order of the heavens builds 



112 PyrrJwnic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

a tower of reasoning to prove that a providence exists, we 
oppose the fact that adversity often falls to the good and 
prosperity to the evil, and that therefore we draw the con- 

33 elusion that there is no providence. The intellectual is 
placed in opposition to phenomena, as when Anaxagoras 
opposed the fact that snow is white, by saying that snow 
is frozen water, and, as water is black, snow must also be 
black. Likewise we sometimes place the present in oppo- 
sition to the present, similarly to the above-mentioned 
cases, and sometimes also the present in opposition to the 
past or the future. As for example, when someone pro- 
poses an argument to us that we cannot refute, we say to 

34 him, " Before the founder of the sect to which you belong 
was born, the argument which you propose in accordance 
with it had not appeared as a valid argument, but was 
dormant in nature, so in the same way it is possible 
that its refutation also exists in nature, but has not yet 
appeared to us, so that it is not at all necessary for us to 

35 agree with an argument that now seems to be strong." In 
order to make it clearer to us what we mean by these 
oppositions, I will proceed to give the Tropes [rpoTroij, 
through which the suspension of judgment is produced, 
without asserting anything about their meaning or their 
number, because they may be unsound, or there may be 
more than I shall enumerate. 

CHAPTER XIV. 
The Ten Tropes. 

36 Certain Tropes were commonly handed down by the 
older Sceptics, by means of which iiroy(^i] seems to take 
place. They are ten in number, and are called synony- 
mously \6yoi and Tpoiroi. They are these : The iirst is 
based upon the differences in animals ; the second upon 
the differences in men; the third upon the difference in 



Pyrrhonic Sketches hy Sextus Empiricus. 113 

the constitution of the organs of sense ; the fourth upon 
■circumstances; the fifth upon position, distance, and place; 
the sixth upon mixtures ; the seventh upon the quantity 
and constitution of objects ; the eighth upon relation ; the 37 
ninth upon frequency or rarity of occurences ; the tenth 
■upon systems, customs, laws, mythical beliefs, and dog- 
matic opinions. We make this order ourselves. These 38 
Tropes come under three general heads : the standpoint 
•of the judge, the standpoint of the thing judged, and the 
■standpoint of both together. Under the standpoint of the 
judge come the first four, for the judge is either an animal, 
•or a man, or a sense, and exists under certain circumstances. 
Under the standpoint of that which is judged, come the 
seventh and the tenth. Under the one composed of both to- 
gether, come the fifth and the sixth, the eighth and the ninth. 
Again, these three divisions are included under the Trope 39 
of relation, because that is the most general one ; it includes 
the three special divisions, and these in turn include the 
ten. We say these things in regard to their probable 
number, and we proceed in the following chapter to speak 
■of their meaning. 

The First Trope. 

The first Trope, we said, is the one based upon the 40 
■differences in animals, and according to this Trope, different 
animals do not get the same ideas of the same objects 
throughj^the senses. This we conclude from the different 
■origin of the animals, and also from the difference in the 
constitution of their bodies. In regard to the difference in 
•origin, some animals originate without mixture of the sexes, 
while others originate through sexual intercourse. Of 41 
those which originate without intercourse of the sexes, 
some come from fire, as the little animals which appear in 
the chimneys, others from stagnant water, as musquitoes, 
■others from fermented wine, as the stinging ants, others 



114 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus HJmpiricus. 



from the earth, others from the mud, like the frogs, others 
from slime, as the worms, others from donkeys, as the 
beetles, others from cabbage, as caterpillars, others from 
fruit, as the gall insect from the wild figs, others from 
putrified animals, as bees from bulls, and wasps from 

42 horses. Again, of those originating from intercourse of 
the sexes, some come from animals of the same kind, as in 
most cases, and others from those of different kinds, as. 
mules. Again, of animals in general, some are born alive, 
as men, others from eggs, as birds, and others are born a 

43 lump of flesh, as bears. It is probable therefore, that the 
inequalities and differences in origin cause great antipathies 
in the animals, and the result is incompatibility, discord, 
and conflict between the sensations of the different animals. 

44 Again, the differences in the principal parts of the body, 
especially in those fitted by nature to judge and to per- 
ceive, may cause the greatest differences in their ideas of 
objects, according to the differences in the animals them- 
selves. As for example, those who have the jaundice 
call that yellow which appears to us white, and those 
who have bloodshot eyes call it blood-red. Accordingly, 
as some animals have yellow eyes, and others blood-shot 
ones, and still others whitish ones, and others eyes of other 
colors, it is probable, I think, that they have a different 

45 perception of colors. Furthermore, when we look steadily 
at the sun for a long time, and then look down at a book,, 
the letters seem to us gold colored, and dance around. 
Now some animals have by nature a lustre in their eyes, 
and these emit a fine and sparkling light so that they see at. 
night, and we may reasonably suppose that external things. 

46 do not appear the same to them as to us. Jugglers by 
lightly rubbing the wick of the lamp with metal rust, or 
with the dark yellow fluid of the sepia, make those who. 
are present appear now copper-colored and now black, 
according to the amount of the mixture used; if this be 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Seodus Em/pwicus. 115 

so, it is much more reasonable to suppose that because of 
the mixture of different fluids in the eyes of animals, their 
ideas of objects would be different. Furthermore, when 47 
we press the eye on the side, the figures, forms and sizes of 
things seen appear elongated and narrow. It is therefore 
probable that such animals as have the pupil oblique and 
long, as goats, cats, and similar animals, have ideas different 
from those of the animals which have a round pupil. 
Mirrors according to their different construction, sometimes 48 
show the external object smaller than reality, as concave 
ones, and sometimes long and narrow, as the convex ones 
do ; others show the head of the one looking into it down, 
and the feet up. As some of the vessels around the eye 49 
fall entirely outside the eye, on account of their protu- 
berance, while others are more sunken, and still others are 
placed in an even surface, it is probable that for this 
reason also the ideas vary, and dogs, fishes, lions, men, 
and grasshoppers do not see the same things, either of 
the same size, or of similar form, but according to the 
impression on the organ, of sight of each animal respec- 
tively. Thesamethingistrueinregard to the other senses; 50 
for how can it be said that shell-fish, birds of prey, animals 
covered with spines, those with feathers and those with 
scales would be affected in the same way by the sense of 
touch ? and how can the sense of hearing perceive alike in 
animals which have the narrowest auditory passages, and in 
those that are furnished with the widest, or in those with 
hairy ears and those with smooth ones ? For we, even, hear 
differently when we partially stop up the ears, from what 
we do when we use them naturally. The sense of smell 51 
also varies according to differences in animals, since even 
our sense of smell is affected when we have taken cold and 
the phlegm is too abundant, and also when parts around 
our head are flooded with too much blood, for we then 
avoid odors that seem agreeable to others, and feel as 



116 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

if we were injured by them. Since also some of the 
animals are moist by nature and full of secretions, and 
others are very full of blood, and still others have either 
yellow or black bile prevalent and abundant, it is reason- 
able because of this to think that odorous things appear 

52 different to each one of them. And it is the same in 
regard to things of taste, as some animals have the tongue 
rough and dry and others very moist. We too, when we 
have a dry tongue in fever, think that whatever we take 
is gritty, bad tasting, or bitter ; and this we experience 
because of the varying degrees of the humors that aie said 
to be in us. Since, then, different animals have different 
organs for taste, and a greater or less amount of the various , 
humors, it can well be that they form different ideas of the 

53 same objects as regards their taste. For just as the same 
food on being absorbed becomes in some places veins, in 
other places arteries, and in other places bones, nerves, or 
other tissues, showing different power according to the 
difference of the parts receiving it ; just as the same water 
absorbed by the trees becomes in some places bark, in other 
places branches, and in other places fruit, perhaps a fig or 

54 a pomegranate, or something else; just as the breath of 
the musician, one and the same when blown into the flute, 
becomes sometimes a high tone and sometimes a low one, 
and the same pressure of the hand upon the lyre sometimes 
causes a deep tone and sometimes a high tone, so it is 
natural to suppose that external objects are regarded 
differently according to the different constitution of the 

55 animals which perceive them. We may see this more 
clearly in the things that are sought for and avoided by 
animals. For example, myrrh appears very agreeable to 
men and intolerable to beetles and bees. Oil also, which 
is useful to men, destroys wasps and bees if sprinkled on 
them ; and sea-water, while it is unpleasant and poisonous 
to men if they drink it, is most agreeable and sweet to 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Etrifiricus. 117 

fishes. Swine also prefer to wash in vile filth rather than 56 
in pure clean water. Furthermore, some animals eat grass 
and some eat herbs ; some live in the woods, others eat 
seeds ; some are carnivorous, and others lactivorous ; some 
enjoy putrified food, and others fresh food; some raw 
food, and others that which is prepared by cooking; and 
in general that which is agreeable to some is disagreeable 
and fatal to others, and should be avoided by them. Thus 57 
hemlock makes the quail fat, and henbane the hogs, and 
these, as it is known, enjoy eating lizards ; deer also eat 
poisonous animals, and swallows, the cantharidae. More- 
over, ants and flying ants, when swallowed by men, cause 
discomfort and colic ; but the bear, on the contrary, what- 
ever sickness he may have, becomes stronger by devouring 
them. The viper is benumbed if one twig of the oak 58 
touches it, as is also the bat by a leaf of the plane-tree. 
The elephant flees before the ram, and the lion before the 
cock, and seals from the rattling of beans that are being 
pounded, and the tiger from the sound of the drum. Many 
other examples could be given, but that we may not seem 
to dwell longer than is necessary on this subject, we con- 
clude by saying that since the same things are pleasant to 
some and unpleasant to others, and the pleasure and dis- 
pleasure depend on the ideas, it must be that different 
animals have different ideas of objects. And since the 59 
same things appear difi"erent according to the difference in 
the animals, it will be possible for us to say how the 
external object appears to us, but as to how it is in reality 
we shall suspend our judgment. For we cannot ourselves 
judge between our own ideas and those of other animals, 
being ourselves involved in the difference, and therefore 
much more in need of being judged than being ourselves 
able to judge. And furthermore, we cannot give the 60 
preference to our own mental representations over those 
of other animals, either without evidence or with evidence, 



118 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

for besides the fact that perhaps there is no evidence, as 
we shall show, the evidence so called will be either mani- 
fest to us or not. If it is not manifest to us, then we 
cannot accept it with conviction; if it is manifest to us, 
since the question is in regard to what is manifest to 
animals, and we use as evidence that which is manifest to 
us who are animals, then it is to be questioned if it is true 

61 as it is manifest to us. It is absurd, however, to try to 
base the questionable on the questionable, because the 
same thing is to be believed and not to be believed, which 
is certainly impossible. The evidence is to be believed in 
so far as it will furnish a proof, and disbelieved in so far 
as it is itself to be proved. We shall therefore have no 
evidence according to which we can give preference to our 
own ideas over those of so-called irrational animals. Since 
therefore ideas differ according to the diiference in animals, 
and it is impossible to judge them, it is necessary to suspend 
the judgment in regard to external objects. 

Have the So-called Irrational Animals Season? 

62 We continue the comparison of the so-called irrational 
animals with man, although it is needless to do so, for in 
truth we do not refuse to hold up to ridicule the conceited 
and bragging Dogmatics, after having given the practical 
arguments. Now most of our number were accustomed to 
compare all the irrational animals together with man, but 

63 because the Dogmatics playing upon words say that the 
comparison is unequal, we carry our ridicule farther, 
although it is most superfluous to do so, and fix the dis- 
cussion on one animal, as the dog, if it suits you, which 
seems to be the most contemptible animal; for we shall 
even then find that animals, about which we are speaking, 
are not inferior to us in respect to the trustworthiness of 

64 their perceptions. Now the Dogmatics grant that this 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 119 

animal is superior to us in sense perception, for he perceives 
better through smell than we, as by this sense he tracks 
wild animals that he cannot see, and he sees them quicker 
with his eyes than we do, and he perceives more acutely by 
hearing. Let us also consider reasoning, which is of two 65 
kinds, reasoning in thought and in speech. Let us look 
first to that of thought. This kind of reasoning, judging 
from the teachings of those Dogmatics who are now our 
greatest opponents, those of the Stoa, seems to fluctuate 
between the following things : the choice of the familiar, 
and avoidance of the alien ; the knowledge of the arts that 
lead to this choice ; and the comprehension of those virtues 
that belong to the individual nature, as regards the feelings. 
The dog then, upon whom it was decided to fix the argu- 66 
ment as an example, makes a choice of things suitable to 
him, and avoids those that are harmful, for he hunts for 
food, but draws back when the whip is lifted up; he 
possesses also an art by which he procures the things that 
are suitable for him, the art of hunting. He is not also 67 
without virtue ; since the true nature of justice is to give 
to every one according to his merit, as the dog wags his 
tail to those who belong to the family, and to those who 
behave well to him, guards them, and keeps off strangers 
and evil doers, he is surely not without justice. Now if he 68 
has this virtue, since the virtues follow each other in turn, 
he has the other virtues also, which the wise men say, most 
men do not possess. We see the dog also brave in warding 
off attacks, and sagacious, as Homer testified when he 
represented Odysseus as unrecognised by all in his house, 
and recognised only by Argos, because the dog was not 
deceived by the physical change in the man, and had not 
lost the (fyavTacria KaTaXiqTmKrj which he proved that he 
had kept better than the men had. But according to 69 
Chrysippus even, who most attacked the irrational animals, 
the dog takes a part in the dialectic about which so much is 



120 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

said. At any rate, the man above referred to said that the 
dog follows the iifth of the several non-apodictic syllogisms, 
for when he comes to a meeting of three roads, after seeking, 
the scent in the two roads, through which his prey has not 
passed, he presses forward quickly in the third without, 
scenting it. For the dog reasons in this way, potentially 
said the man of olden time ; the animal passed through 
this, or this, or this ; it was neither through this nor this,. 

70 therefore it was through this. The dog also understands- 
his own sufferings and mitigates them. As soon as a sharp 
stick is thrust into him, he sets out to remove it, by rubbing 
his foot on the ground, as also with his teeth ; and if ever 
he has a wound anywhere, for the reason that uncleansed 
wounds are difficult to cure, and those that are cleansed are 

71 easily cured, he gently wipes off the collected matter ; and 
he observes the Hippocratic advice exceedingly well, for 
since quiet is a relief for the foot, if he has ever a wound in 
the foot, he lifts it up, and keeps it undisturbed as much 
as possible. When he is troubled by disturbing humours, 
he eats grass, with which he vomits up that which was 

72 unfitting, and recovers. Since therefore it has been shown 
that the animal that we fixed the argument upon for the 
sake of an example, chooses that which is suitable for him, 
and avoids what is harmful, and that he has an art by which 
he provides what is suitable, and that he comprehends his 
own sufferings and mitigates them, and that he is not 
without virtue, things in which perfection of reasoning in 
thought consists, so according to this it would seem that 
the dog has reached perfection. It is for this reason, it 
appears to me, that some philosophers have honoured them- 

73 selves with the name of this animal. In regard to reason- 
ing in speech, it is not necessary at present to bring the 
matter in question. For some of the Dogmatics, even, 

7 V have put this aside, as opposing the acquisition of virtue, 
for which reason they practiced silence when studying. 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 121 

Besides, let it be supposed that a man is dumb, no one 
would say that he is consequently irrational. However, 
aside from this, we see after all, that animals, about which 
we are speaking, do produce human sounds, as the jay and 
some others. Aside from this also, even if we do not 74 
understand the sounds of the so-called irrational animals, 
it is not at all unlikely that they converse, and that we do 
not understand their conversation. For when we hear the 
language of foreigners, we do not understand but it all 
seems like one sound to us. Furthermore, we hear dogs 75 
giving out one kind of sound when they are resisting some- 
one, and another sound when they howl, and another when 
they are beaten, and a different kind when they wag their 
tails, and generally speaking, if one examines into this, he 
will find a great difference in the sounds of this and other 
animals under different circumstances ; so that in all likeli- 
hood, it may be said that the so-called irrational animals 
partake also in spoken language. If then, they are not 76 
inferior to men in the accuracy of their perceptions, nor in 
reasoning in thought, nor in reasoning by speech, as it is 
superfluous to say, then they are not more untrustworthy 
than we are, it seems to me, in regard to their ideas. 
Perhaps it would be possible to prove this, should we direct 77 
the argument to each of the irrational animals in turn. As 
for example, who would not say that the birds are distin- 
guished for shrewdness, and make use of articulate speech ? 
for they not only know the present but the future, and this 
they augur to those that are able to understand it, audibly 
as well as in other ways. I have made this comparison 78 
superfluously, as I pointed out above, as I think I had 
sufficiently shown before, that we cannot consider our own 
ideas superior to those of the irrational animals. In short, 
if the irrational animals are not more untrustworthy than 
we in regard to the judgment of their ideas, and the ideas 
are different according to the difference in the animals, I 



122 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

shall be able to say how each object appears to me, but in 
regard to what it is by nature I shall be obliged to suspend 
my judgment. 

The Second Trope. 

79 Such is the first Trope of iiroxJi. The second, we said 
above, is based upon the differences in men. For even if 
one assent to the hypothesis that men are more trustworthy 
than the irrational animals, we shall find that doubt arises 
as soon as we consider our own differences. For since 
man is said to be composed of two things, soul and body, 
we differ from each other in respect to both of these things; 
for example, as regards the body, we differ both in form 

80 and personal peculiarities. For the body of a Scythian 
differs from the body of an Indian in form, the difference 
resulting, it is said, from the different control of the 
humors. According to different control of the humors, 
differences in ideas arise also, as we represented under the 
first Trope. For this reason there is certainly a great 
difference among men in the choice and avoidance of 
external things. The Indians delight in different things 
from our own people, and the enjoyment of different 
things is a sign that different ideas are received of the 

81 external objects. We differ in personal peculiarities, as 
some digest beef better than the little fish from rocky 
places, and some are affected with purging by the weak 
wine of Lesbos. There was, they say, an old woman in 
Attica who could drink thirty drachmas of hemlock without 
daijger, and Lysis took four drachmas of opium unhurt, 

82 and Demophon, Alexander's table waiter, shivered when 
he was in the sun or in a hot bath, and felt warm in the 
shade ; Athenagoras also, from Argos, did not suffer harm 
if stung by scorpions and venomous spiders ; the so-called 
Psylli were not injured when bitten by snakes or by the 
aspis, and the Tentyrites among the Egyptians are not 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Seodus Empiricus. 123 

harmed by the crocodiles around them ; those also of the 83 
Ethiopians who live on the Hydaspes river, opposite Meroe, 
■eat scorpions and serpents, and similar things without 
danger ; Eufinus in Chalcis could drink hellebore without 
•vomiting or purging, and he enjoyed and digested it as 
something to which he was accustomed ; Chrysermos, the 84 
Herophilian, ran the risk of stomach-ache if he ever took 
pepper, and Soterichus, the surgeon, was seized by purging 
if he perceived the odor of roasting shad ; Andron, ohe 
Argive, was so free from thirst that he could travel even 
through the waterless Libya without looking for a drink ; 
Tiberius, the emperor, saw in the dark, and Aristotle tells 
the story of a certain Thracian, who thought that he saw 
the figure of a man always going before him as a guide. 
While therefore such a difference exists in men in regard 85" 
to the body, and we must be satisfied with referring to a 
few only of the many examples given by the Dogmatics, it 
is probable that men also differ from each other in respect 
to the soul itself, for the body is a kind of type of the soul, 
as the physiognomical craft also shows. The best example 
•of the numerous and infinite differences of opinion among 
men is the contradiction in the sayings of the Dogmatics, 
not only about other things, but about what it is well to 
seek and to avoid. The poets have also fittingly spoken 86 
about this, for Pindar said — 

■" One delights in getting honors and crowns through storm-footed 

horses, 
Another in jiassing life in rooms rich in gold. 
Another still, safe travelling enjoys, in a swift ship, on a wave of 

the sea." 

-And the poet says — 

" One man enjoys this, another enjoys that." 

The tragedies also abound in such expressions, for instance, 

it is said — 

" If to all, the same were good and wise, 
Quarrels and disputes among men would not have been." 



124 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiriciis. 

And again — 

" It is awful indeed, that the same thing some mortals should please,. 
And by others be hated." 

87 Since therefore the choice and the avoidance of things, 
depends on the pleasure and displeasure which they give, 
and the pleasure and displeasure have their seat in perception- 
and ideas, when some choose the things that others avoid, 
it is logical for us to conclude that they are not acted upon 
similarly by the sa)ne things, for otherwise they would 
have chosen or avoided alike. Now if the same things act- 
upon different men differently, on account of the difference 
in the men, for this cause also suspension of the judgment 
may reasonably be introduced, and we may perhaps say 
how each object appears to us, and what its individual' 
differences are, but we shall not be able to declare what it 

88 is as to the nature of its essence. For we must either 
believe all men or some men ; but to believe all is tO' 
undertake an impossibility, and to accept things that are 
in opposition to each other. If we believe some only, let 
someone tell us with whom to agree, for the Platonist 
would say with Plato, the Epicurean with Epicurus, and 
others would advise in a corresponding manner ; and so as- 
they disagree, with no one to decide, they bring us round 

89 again to the suspension of judgment. Furthermore, he 
who tells us to agree with the majority proposes something- 
childish, as no one could go to all men and find out what 
pleases the majority, for it is possible that in some nations 
which we do not know the things which to us are rare are- 
common to the majority, and those things which happen 
commonly to us are rare. As for example, it might happen 
that the majority should not suffer when bitten by venomous 
spiders, or that they should seldom feel pain, or have other- 
personal peculiarities similar to those spoken of above. It 
is necessary therefore to suspend the judgment on account 
of the differences in men. 



Pyrrhonio Sketches by Sextus Em'pincus. 125 



The Third Trope. 

While, however, the Dogmatics are conceited enough 90 
to think that they should be preferred to other men in the 
judgment of things, we know that their claim is absurd, 
for they themselves form a part of the disagreement; and 
if they give themselves preference in this way in the judg- 
ment of phenomena, they beg the question before they 
begin the judgment, as they trust the judgment to them- 
selves. Nevertheless, in order that we should reach the 91 
result of the suspension of judgment by limiting the 
argument to one man, one who for example they deem 
to be wise, let us take up the third Trope. This is the 
one that is based upon differences in perception. That the 92 
perceptions differ from each other is evident. For example, 
paintings seem to have hollows and prominences to the 
sense of sight, but not to the sense of touch, and honey 
to the tongue of some people appears pleasant, but un- 
pleasant to the eyes; therefore it is impossible to say 
whether it is really pleasant or unpleasant. In regard 
to myrrh it is the same, for it delights the sense of smell, 
but disgusts the sense of taste. Also in regard to euphor- 93 
bium, since it is harmful to the eyes and harmless to 
all the rest of the body, we are not able to say whether 
it is really harmless to bodies or not, as far as its own 
nature is concerned. Eain-water, too, is useful to the eyes, 
but it makes the trachea and the lungs rough, just as oil 
does, although it soothes the skin; and the sea-torpedo 
placed on the extremities makes them numb, but is harm- 
less when placed on the rest of the body. Wherefore we 
cannot say what each of these things is by nature. It is 
possible only to say how it appears each time. We could cite 94 
more examples than these, but in order not to spend too 
long in laying out the plan of this book we shall simply 
say the following : Each of the phenomena perceived by us 



126 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

seems to present itself in many forms, as the apple, smooth, 
fragrant, sweet, yellow. Now it is not known whether it 
has in reality only those qualities which appear to us, or if 
it has only one quality, but appears different on account of 
the different constitution of the sense organs, or if it has. 
more qualities than appear to us, but some of them do not. 

95 affect us. That it has only one quality might be concluded 
from what we have said about the food distributed ia 
bodies, and the water distributed in trees, and the breath 
in the flute and syrinx, and in similar instruments ; for it. 
is possible that the apple also has only one quality, but 
appears different on account of the difference in the sense- 

96 organs by which it is perceived. On the other hand, that 
the apple has more qualities than those that appear to us, 
can be argued in this way : Let us imagine someone born 
with the sense of touch, of smell, and of taste, but neither 
hearing nor seeing. He will then assume that neither any- 
thing visible nor anything audible exists at all, but only 

97 the three kinds of qualities which he can apprehend. It is 
possible then that as we have only the five senses, we 
apprehend only those qualities of the apple which we are 
able to grasp, but it may be supposed that other qualities 
exist which would affect other sense organs if we possessed 
them ; as ,it is, we do not feel the sensations which would 

98 be felt through them. But nature, one will say, has 
brought the senses into harmony with the objects to be 
perceived. What kind of nature ? Among the Dogmatics 
a great difference of opinion reigns about the real existence 
of nature anyway ; for he who decides whether there is a 
nature or not, if he is an uneducated man, would be 
according to them untrustworthy ; if he is a philosopher, 
he is a part of the disagreement, and is himself to be 

99 judged, but is not a judge. In short, if it is possible that 
only those qualities exist in the apple which we seem to 
perceive, or that more than these are there, or that not 



Pyrrhonio Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 127 

even those which we perceive exist, it will Jti^'unknown to 
us what kind of a thing the apple is. The same argument 
holds for other objects of perception. If, however, the 
senses do not comprehend the external world, the intellect 
cannot comprehend it either, so that for this reason also it 
will appear that the suspension of judgment follows in 
regard to external objects. 



The Fourth Trope. 

In order to attain to cVckj^jJ by fixing the argument on lOO 
each separate sense, or even by putting aside the senses 
altogether, we take up the fourth Trope of eiro')(ri. This 
is the one based upon circumstances, and by circumstances 
we mean conditions. This Trope comes under consideration, 
we may say, with regard to conditions that are according 
to nature, or contrary to nature ; such as waking or sleep- 
ing, the age of life, moving or keeping still, hating or loving, 
need or satiety, drunkenness or sobriety, predispositions, 
being courageous or afraid, sorrowing or rejoicing. For 101 
example, things appear different as they are according to 
nature, or contrary to it ; as for instance, the insane and 
those inspired by a god, think that they hear gods, while 
we do not ; in like manner they often say that they per- 
ceive the odor of storax or frankincense, or the like, and 
many other things which we do not perceive. Water, also, 
that seems lukewarm to us, if poured over places that are 
inflamed, will feel hot, and a garment that appears orange- 
coloured to those that have blood-shot eyes, would not look 
so to me, and the same honey appears sweet to me, but 
bitter to those who have the jaundice. If one should say \q% 
that those who are not in a natural state have unusual ideas 
of objects, because of the intermingling of certain humors, 
then one must also say, that it may be that objects which 
are really what they seem to be to those who are in an 



128 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

unnatural condition, appear different to those who are in 
health, for even those who are in health have humors that 

103 are mixed with each other. For to give to one kind of 
fluid a power to change objects, and not to another kind, 
is a fiction of the mind ; for just as those who are in health 
are in a condition that is natural to those who are in health, 
and contrary to the nature of those who are not in health, 
so also those who are not in health, are in a condition con- 
trary to the nature of those in health, but natural to those 
not in health, and we must therefore believe that they also 

104 are in some respect in a natural condition. Furthermore, 
in sleep or in waking, the ideas are different, because we do 
not see things in the same way when we are awake as we 
do in sleep ; neither do we see them in the same way in 
sleep as we do when awake, so that the existence or non- 
existence of these things is not absolute, but relative, that 
is in relation to a sleeping or waking condition. It is there- 
fore probable that we see those things in sleep which in a 
waking condition do not exist, but they are not altogether 
non-existent, for they exist in sleep, just as those things 
which exist when we are awake, exist, although they do not 

105 exist in sleep. Furthermore, things present themselves 
differently according to the age of life, for the same air 
seems cold to the aged, but temperate to those in their 
prime, and the same color appears dim to those who are 
old, and bright to those in their prime, and likewise the 
same tone seems faint to the former, and audible to the 

106 latter. People in different ages are also differently disposed 
towards things to be chosen or avoided; children, for 
example, are very fond of balls and hoops, while those in 
their prime prefer other things, and the old still others, 
from which it follows that the ideas in regard to the same 

107 objects differ in different periods of life. Furthermore, 
things appear different in a condition of motion and rest, 
since that which we see at rest when we are still, seems to 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 129 

move when we are sailing by it. There are also differences 108 
which depend on liking or disliking, as some detest swine 
■flesh exceedingly, but others eat it with pleasure. As 
Menander said — 

" how his face appears 
Since he became such a man ! What a creature ! 
Doing no injustice would make us also beautiful." 

Many'also that love ugly women consider them very beauti- 
ful. Furthermore, there are differences which depend on 109 
hunger or satiety, as the same food seems agreeable to those 
who are hungry, and disagreeable to those who are satisfied. 
There are also differences depending on drunkenness and 
■sobriety, as that which we consider ugly when we are sober 
■does not appear ugly to us when we are drunk. Again, 110 
there are differences depending on predispositions, as the 
same wine appears sourish to those who have previously 
€aten dates or dried figs, but agreeable to those who have 
taken nuts or chickpeas ; the vestibule of the bath warms 
those who enter from without, but cools those who go out, 
if they rest in it. Furthermore, there are differences de- 111 
pending on being afraid or courageous, as the same thing 
.seems fearful and terrible to the coward, but in no wise so 
to him who is brave. There are differences, also, depending 
on being sad or joyful, as the same things are unpleasant 
to the sad, but pleasant to the joyful. Since therefore 112 
the anomalies depending on conditions are so great, and 
•since men are in different conditions at different times, it 
is perhaps easy to say how each object appears to each 
man, but not so of what kind it is, because the anomaly 
is not of a kind to be judged. For he who would pass 
judgment upon this is either in some one of the conditions 
mentioned above, or is in absolutely no condition whatever ; 
but to say that he is in no condition at all, as, for example, 
that he is neither in health nor in illness, that he is neither 
moving nor quiet, that he is not of any age, and also that 

9 



130 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

113 he is free from the other conditions, is wholly absurd. But 
if he judges the ideas while he is in any condition whatever,, 
he is a part of the contradiction, and, besides, he is na 
genuine critic of external objects, because he is confused 
by the condition in which he finds himself. Therefor© 
neither can the one who is awake compare the ideas of 
those who are asleep with those who are awake, nor can. 
he who is in health compare the ideas of the sick with 
those of the well ; for we believe more in the things that 
are present, and affecting us at present, than in the things. 

114 not present. In another way, the anomaly in such ideas, 
is impossible to be judged, for whoever prefers one idea to 
another, and one condition to another, does this either 
without a criterion and a proof, or with a criterion and a 
proof ; but he can do this neither without them, for he 
would then be untrustworthy, nor with them ; for if he 
judges ideas, he judges them wholly by a criterion, and he 

115 will say that this criterion is either true or false. But if it 
is false, he will be untrustworthy ; if, on the contrary, he 
says that it is true, he will say that the criterion is true 
either without proof or with proof. If without proof, he- 
will be untrustworthy ; if he says that it is true with proof, 
it is certainly necessary that the proof be true, or he will 
be untrustworthy. Now will he say that the proof which, 
he has accepted for the accrediting of the criterion is true, 

116 having judged it, or without having judged it ? If he says, 
so without judging it, he will be untrustworthy ; if he has 
judged it, it is evident that he will say that he has judged 
according to some criterion, and we must seek a proof for 
this criterion, and for that proof a criterion. For the proof 
always needs a criterion to establish it, and the criterion 
needs a proof that it may be shown to be true ; and a proof 
can neither be sound without a pre-existing criterion that 
is true, nor a criterion true without a proof that is shown 

117 beforehand to be trustworthy. And so both the criterion 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 131 

and the proof are thrown into the circulus in probando, by 
•which it is found that they are both of them untrustworthy, 
for as each looks for proof from the other, each is as un- 
trustworthy as the other. Since then one cannot prefer 
one idea to another, either without a proof and a criterion 
or with them, the ideas that differ according to different 
conditions cannot be judged, so that the suspension of 
judgment in regard to the nature of external objects 
follows through this Trope also. 

The Fifth Trope. 

The fifth Trope is that based upon position, distance, 118 
and place, for, according to each of these, the same things 
appear different, as for example, the same arcade seen 
from either end appears curtailed, but from the middle it 
looks symmetrical on every side ; and the same ship appears 
small and motionless from afar, and large and in motion 
near by, and the same tower appears round from a distance, 
but square near by. So much for distance. Now in refer- 119 
ence to place, we say that the light of the lamp appears 
dim in the sun, but bright in the dark; and the same 
rudder appears broken in the sea, but straight out of it ; 
and the egg in the bird is soft, but in the air hard ; and 
the lyngurion is a fluid in the lynx, but is hard in the air ; 
and the coral is soft in the sea, but hard in the air ; and a 
tone of voice appears different produced by a syrinx, and 
by a flute, and different simply in the air. Also in refer- 120 
ence to position, the same picture leaned back appears 
smooth, and leaned forward a little seems to have hollows 
and protuberances, and the necks of doves appear different 
in color according to the difference in inclination. Since 121 
then all phenomena are seen in relation to place, distance, 
and position, each of which relation makes a great difference 
with the idea, as we have mentioned, we shall be obliged 



132 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Seodus Empiricus. 

by this Trope also to come to the suspension of judgment. 
For he who wishes to give preference to certain ones of 

122 these ideas will attempt the impossible. For if he simply 
makes the decision without proof he will be untrustworthy. 
If, however, he wishes to make use of a proof, should he 
say that the proof is false, he contradicts himself, but if he 
declares the proof to be true, proof of its proof will be 
demanded of him, and another proof for that, which proof 
also must be true, and so on to the regressus in infinitum. 

123 It is impossible, however, to present proofs in infinitum, so 
that one will not be able to prove that one idea is to be 
preferred to another. Since then one cannot either with- 
out proof or with proof judge the ideas in question, the 
suspension of judgment results, and how each thing appears 
according to this or that position, or this or that distance, 
or this or that place, we perhaps are able to say, but what 
it really is it is impossible to declare, for the reasons which 
we have mentioned. 

The Sixth Trope. 

124 The sixth Trope is the one based upon mixtures, accord- 
ing to which we conclude that since no object presents 
itself alone, but always together with something else, it is 
perhaps possible to say of what nature the mixture is, of 
the thing itself, and of that with which it is seen, but of 
what sort the external object really is we shall not be able 
to say. Now it is evident, I think, that nothing from 
without is known to us by itself, but always with some- 
thing else, and that because of this fact it appears different. 

125 The color of our skin, for example, is different seen in 
warm air from what it is in cold, and we could not say 
what our color really is, only what it is when viewed 
under each of these conditions. The same sound appears 
different in rare air from what it is in dense, and aromas 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 133 

are more overpowering in the warm bath and in the sun 
than they are in the cold air, and a body surrounded by 
water is light, but by air heavy. Leaving aside, however, 126 
outer mixtures, our eyes have inside of them coatings and 
humors. Since then visible things are not seen without 
these, they will not be accurately comprehended, for it is 
the mixture that we perceive, and for this reason those 
who have the jaundice see everything yellow, and those 
with bloodshot eyes bloody. Since the same sound appears 
different in broad open places from what it does in narrow 
and winding ones, and different in pure air and in impure, 
it is probable that we do not perceive the tones unmixed ; 
for the ears have narrow winding passages filled with 
vaporous secretions, which it is said gather from places 
around the head. Since also there are substances pre- 127 
sent in the nostrils and in the seat of the sense of taste, 
we perceive the things smelled and the things tasted in 
connection with them, and not unmixed. So that because 
of mixture the senses do not perceive accurately what the 
external objects are. The intellect even does not do this, 128 
chiefly because its guides, the senses, make mistakes, and 
perhaps it itself adds a certain special mixture to those 
messages communicated by the senses ; for in each place 
where the Dogmatics think that the ruling faculty is situated, 
we see that certain humors are present, whether one would 
locate it in the region of the brain, in the region of the 
heart, or somewhere else. Since therefore according to 
this Trope also, we see that we cannot say anything re- 
garding the nature of external objects, we are obliged to 
suspend our judgment. 

The Seventh Trope. 
The seventh Trope is the one which, as we said, is based 129 
upon the quantity and constitution of objects, constitution 
commonly meaning composition. And it is evident that 



134 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Seoctus Empiricus. 

we are obliged to suspend our iudgment according to this 
Trope also in regard to the nature of things. As for 
example, filings from the horn of the goat appear white 
when they are seen separately and without being put 
together; put together, however, in the form of a horn, 
they look black. And the parts of silver, the filings that 
is, by themselves appear black, but as a whole appear 
white ; and parts of the Taenarus stone look white when 

130 ground, but in the whole stone appear yellow; grains of 
sand scattered apart from each other appear to be rough, 
but put together in a heap, they produce a soft feeling; 
hellebore taken fine and downy, causes choking, but it 

131 no longer does so when taken coarse ; wine also taken 
moderately strengthens us, but when taken in excess relaxes 
the body ; food similarly, has a different effect according to 
the quantity, at least, it often disturbs the body when too 

132 much is taken, causing dyspepsia and discharge. We shall 
be able here also to say of what kind the cutting from the 
horn is, and what many cuttings put together are, of what 
kind a filing of silver is, and what many of them put 
together are, of what kind the tiny Taenarus stone, and 
what one composed of many small ones is, and in regard 
to the grains of sand, and the hellebore, and the wine, and 
the food, what they are in relation, but no longer the nature 
of the thing by itself, because of the anomaly in the ideas 
which we have of things, according to the way in which they 

133 are put together. In general it appears that useful things 
become harmful when an intemperate use is made of them, 
and things that seem harmful when taken in excess, are not 
injurious in a small quantity. What we see in the effect 
of medicines witnesses especially to this fact, as an exact 
mixture of simple remedies makes a compound which is 
helpful, but sometimes when a very small inclination of 
the balance is overlooked, the medicine is not only not 

134 helpful, but very harmful, and often poisonous. So the 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 135 

argument based upon the quantity and constitution of 
objects, puts in confusion the existence of external objects. 
Therefore this Trope naturally leads us to suspend our 
judgment, as we are not able to delcare exactly the nature 
of external objects. 

The Eighth Trope. 
The eighth Trope is the one based upon relation, from 135 
"which we conclude to suspend our judgment as to what 
things are absolutely, in their nature, since every thing is 
in relation to something else. And we must bear in mind 
that we use the word is incorrectly, in place of appears, 
meaning to say, every thing appears to be in relation. 
This is said, however, with two meanings : first, that every 
thing is in relation to the one who judges, for the external 
object, i.e. the thing judged, appears to be in relation to 
the judge ; the other way is that every thing is in relation 
to the things considered together with it, as the relation of 
the right hand to the left. But we came to the conclusion 136 
above, that every thing is in relation to something, as for 
example, to the one judging ; each thing appears in relation 
to this or that animal, and this or that man, and this or 
that sense, and in certain circumstances ; as regards things 
considered together, also, each thing appears in relation to 
this or that mixture, and this or that Trope, and this or 
that composition, quantity and place. And in another way 137 
it is possible to conclude that every thing is in relation to 
something, as follows : does the being in difference differ 
from the being in relation, or not 1 If it does not difi'er, 
then it is the same as relation ; if it does differ, since every 
thing which diff'ers is in some relation, for it is said to be 
in relation to that from which it differs, those things which 
are in a difference are in a relation to something. Now 138 
according to the Dogmatics, some beings belong to the 
highest genera, others to the lowest species, and others to 



136 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

both genera and species at the same time ; all of these 
are in relation to something, therefore every thing is in 
relation to something. Furthermore, among things, some 
things are manifest, and others are hidden, as the Dogmatics 
themselves say, and the things that make themselves known 
to us are the phenomena, and the things that are made 
known to us by the phenomena are the hidden things, for 
according to the Dogmatics, the phenomena are the outward 
appearance of the unknown; then that which makes known, 
and that which is made known, are in relation to something ; 

139 every thing, therefore, is in relation to something. In 
addition to this, some things are similar to each other, 
and others are dissimilar, some are equal, and others are 
unequal. Now these things are in relation to something, 
therefore every thing is in relation to something, and 
whoever says that every thing is not in relation to some- 
thing, himself establishes the fact that every thing is in 

140 relation to something, for even in saying that every thing 
is not in relation to something, he proves it in reference to 
us, and not in general, by his objections to us. In short, 
as we have shown that every thing is in relation to some- 
thing, it is then evident that we shall not be able to say 
exactly what each object is by nature, but what it appears 
to be like in relation to something else. It follows from 
this, that we must suspend our judgment regarding the 
nature of things. 

The Ninth Trope. 

141 In regard to the Trope based on the frequency and 
rarity of events, which we call the ninth of the series, we 
give the following explanation: The sun is certainly a 
much more astonishing thing than a comet, but because we 
see the sun continually and the comet rarely we are so 
much astonished at the comet that it even seems an omen, 
while we are not at all astonished at the sun. If, however. 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 137 

we should imagine the sun appearing at rare intervals, and 
at rare intervals setting, in the first instance suddenly 
lighting up all things, and in the second casting everything 
into shade, we should see great astonishment at the sight. 
An earthquake, too, does not trouble those who experience 142' 
it for the first time in the same manner as those who have 
become accustomed to it. How great the astonishment of 
a man who beholds the sea for the first time ! And the 
beauty of the human body, seen suddenly for the first 
time, moves us more than if we are accustomed to seeing 
it. That which is rare seems valuable, while things that 143 
are familiar and easily obtained seem by no means so. If, 
for example, we should imagine water as rare, of how much 
greater value would it seem than all other valuable things ! 
or if we imagine gold as simply thrown about on the ground 
in large quantities like stones, to whom do we think it would 
be valuable, or by whom would it be hoarded, as it is now ? 
Since then the same things according to the frequency or 
rarity that they are met with seem to be now valuable and 
now not so, we conclude that it may be that we shall be able 144 
to say what kind of a thing each of them appears to be 
according to the frequency or rarity with which it occurs, 
but we are not able to say what each external object is 
absolutely. Therefore, according to this Trope also, we 
suspend our judgment regarding these things. 

The Tenth Trope. 

The tenth Trope is the one principally connected with 145 
morals, relating to schools, customs, laws, mythical beliefs, 
and dogmatic opinions. Now a school is a choice of a 
manner of life, or of something held by one or many, as 
for example the school of Diogenes or the Laconians. A 146 
law is a written contract among citizens, the transgressor 
of which is punished. A custom or habit, for there is no 



138 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Seoctus Empiricus. 

difference, is a common acceptance of a certain thing by 
many, the deviator from which is in no wise punished. 
For example, it is a law not to commit adultery, and it is 

147 a custom with us to fj,r) Brjfioaia yvvaiKi nlr/vvcr6ai. A 
mythical belief is a tradition regarding things which never 
took place, but were invented, as among others, the tales 
about Cronus, for many are led to believe them. A dog- 
matic opinion is the acceptance of something that seems to 
be established by a course of reasoning, or by some proof, 
as for example, that atoms are elements of things, and that 
they are either homogeneous, or infinitesimal, or of some 
other description. Now we place each of these things 
sometimes in opposition to itself, and sometimes in oppo- 

148 sition to each one of the others. For example, we place a 
custom in opposition to a custom thus : some of the Ethio- 
pians tattoo new-born children, but we do not, and the 
Persians think it is seemly to have a garment of many 
colors and reaching to the feet, but we think it not so. The 
Indians rat? yvvai^l hrjjjLoaia liiyvvvrat, but most of the 

149 other nations consider it a shame. We place a law in 
opposition to a law in this way : among the Eomans he 
who renounces his paternal inheritance does not pay his 
father's debts, but among the Rhodians he pays them in 
any case ; and among the Tauri in Scythia it was a law to 
offer strangers in sacrifice to Artemis, but with us it is 

150 forbidden to kill a man near a temple. We place a school 
in opposition to a school when we oppose the school of 
Diogenes to that of Aristippus, or that of the Laconians to 
that of the Italians. We place a mythical belief in oppo- 
sition to a mythical belief, as by some traditions Jupiter is 
said to be the father of men and gods, and by others 
Oceanus, as we say — 

" Oceanus father of the gods, and Tethys the mother." 

151 We place dogmatic opinions in opposition to each other. 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 139 

•when we say that some declare that there is only one 
■element, but others that they are infinite in number, and 
some that the soul is mortal, others that it is immortal ; 
and some say that our aifairs are directed by the providence 
•of the gods, but others that there is no providence. We 152 
place custom in opposition to other things, as for example 
"to a law, when we say that among the Persians it is the 
■custom to practice appevo/ii^iai, but among the Romans 
it is forbidden by law to do it ; by us adultery is forbidden, 
but among the Massagetae indifference in this respect is 
.allowed by custom, as Eudoxos of Cnidus relates in the ' 
first part of his book of travels ; among us it is forbidden 
jtrfrpdffi filyvvadai, but among the Persians it is the 
custom by preference to marry so ; the Egyptians marry 
.«isters also, which among us is forbidden by law. Further, 153 
we place a custom in opposition to a school, when we say 
that most men avaxcopovprev fiiyvvcovrai Tal^ eavTwv 
■^vvat^iv, 6 Se K.pdrrj'i ry 'Iinrap'xia Srifioaia, and Dio- 
genes went around with one shoulder bare, but we go 
around with our customary clothes. We place a custom 154 
in opposition to a mythical belief, as when the myths say 
that Cronus ate his own children, while with us it is the 
custom to take care of our children ; and among us it is the 
■custom to venerate the gods as good, and not liable to evil, 
but they are described by the poets as being wounded, and 
-also as being jealous of each other. We place a custom in 155 
■opposition to a dogmatic opinion when we say that it is a 
-custom with us to seek good things from the gods, but that 
Epicurus says that the divine pays no heed to us; Aristippus 
.also held it to be a matter of indifference to wear a woman's 
robe, but we consider it shameful. We place a school in 156 
■opposition to a law, as according to the law it is not allowed 
to beat a free and noble born man, but the wrestlers and 
boxers strike each other according to the teaching of their 
manner of life, and although murder is forbidden, the 



140 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

157 gladiators kill each other for the same reason. We plac& 
a mythical belief in opposition to a school when we say- 
that, althou£;h the myths say of Hercules that in company 
with Omphale — 

" He carded wool, and bore servitude," 
and did things that not even an ordinary good man 
would have done, yet Hercules' theory of life was noble. 

158 We place a mythical belief in opposition to a dogmatic- 
opinion when we say that athletes seeking after glory as a 
good, enter for its sake upon a laborious profession, but 
many philosophers, on the other hand, teach that glory is 

159 worthless. We place law in opposition to mythical belief 
when we say the poets represent the gods as working 
adultery and sin, but among us the law forbids those things. 

160 We place law in opposition to dogmatic opinion when we say 
that the followers of Chrysippus hold that it is a matter of 
indifference to marry one's mother or sister, but the law 

161 forbids these things. We place a mythical belief in oppo- 
sition to a dogmatic opinion when we say that the poets 
represent Jupiter as descending and holding intercourse; 
with mortal women, but the Dogmatics think this was. 

162 impossible ; also that the poet says that Jupiter, on account, 
of his sorrow for Sarpedon, rained drops of blood upon the 
earth, but it is a dogma of the philosophers that the divinCi 
is exempt from suffering ; and they deny the myth of the 
horse-centaurs, giving us the horse-centaur as an example. 

163 of non-existence. Now we could give many other examples- 
of each of the antitheses mentioned above, but for a brief 
argument, these are sufficient. Since, however, such anomaly 
of things is shown by this Trope also, we shall not be able: 
to say what objects are by nature, but only what each, 
thing appears to be like, according to this or that school,, 
or this or that law, or this or that custom, or according tO' 
each of the other conditions. Therefore, by this Trope- 
also, we must suspend our judgment in regard to tha 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empirious. 141 

nature of external objects. Thus we arrive at i'!ro)(^ through 
the ten Tropes. 

CHAPTER XV. 

The Five Tropes. 
The later Sceptics, however, teach the following five 164 
Tropes of iiroxv ■ first, the one based upon contradiction ; 
second, the regressus in infinitum ; third, relation ; fourth, 
the hypothetical; fifth, the circulus in probanda. The one 165 
based upon contradiction is the one from which we find, 
that in reference to the thing put before us for investigation, 
a position has been developed which is impossible to be 
judged, either practically, or theoretically, and therefore, 
as we are not able to either accept or reject anything, we 
end in suspending the judgment. The one based upon the 166 
regressus in infinitum is that in which we say that the proof 
brought forward for the thing set before us calls for another 
proof, and that one another, and so on to infinity, so that, 
• not having anything from which to begin the reasoning, 
the suspension of judgment follows. The one based upon 167 
relation, as we have said before, is that one in which the 
object appears of this kind or that kind, as related to the 
judge and to the things regarded together with it, but we 
suspend our judgment as to what it is in reality. The one 168 
based upon hypothesis is illustrated by the Dogmatics, 
when in the regressus in infinitum, they begin from something 
that they do not found on reason, but which they simply 
take for granted without proof. The Trope, circulus in 169 
probanda, arises when the thing which ought to prove the 
thing sought for, needs to be sustained by the thing sought 
for, and as we are unable to take the one for the proof of 
the other, we suspend our judgment in regard to both. 
Now we shall briefly show that it is possible to refer every 
thing under investigation to one or another of these Tropes, 
as follows : the thing before us is either sensible or intel- 



142 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

170 lectual ; difference of opinion exists, however, as to what it- 
is in itself, for some say that only the things of sense are 
true, others, only those belonging to the understanding, 
and others say that some things of sense, and some of 
thought, are true. Now, will it be said that this difference 
of opinion can be judged or cannot be judged 1 If it cannot 
be judged, then we have the result necessarily of suspension 
of judgment, because it is impossible to express opinion in 
regard to things about which a difference of opinion exists- 

171 which cannot be judged. If it can be judged, then we ask 
how it is to be judged ? For example, the sensible, for we 
shall limit the argument first to this — Is it to be judged by 
sensible or by intellectual standards ? For if it is to be 
judged by a sensible one, since we are in doubt about the 
sensible, that will also need something else to sustain it ; 
and if that proof is also something sensible, something else 
will again be necessary to prove it, and so on in infinitum. 

172 If, on the contrary, the sensible must be judged by something^ 
intellectual, as there is disagreement in regard to the 
intellectual, this intellectual thing will require also judg- 
ment and proof. Now, how is it to be proved ? If by 
something intellectual, it will likewise be thrown into 
infinitum ; if by something sensible, as the intellectual has 
been taken for the proof of the sensible, and the sensible 
has been taken for that of the intellectual, the circulus in 

173 probando is introduced. If, however, in order to escape 
from this, the one who is speaking to us expects us to take 
something for granted which has not been proved, in order 
to prove what follows, the hypothetical Trope is introduced, 
which provides no way of escape. For if the one who 
makes the hypothesis is worthy of confidence, we should in 
every case be no less worthy of confidence in making a 
contrary hypothesis. If the one who makes the assumption 
assumes something true, he makes it suspicious by using 
it as a hypothesis, and not as an established fact ; if it is 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextua Empiricus. 143 

false, the foundation of the reasoning is unsound. If a 174 
hypothesis is any help towards a trustworthy result, let 
the thing in question itself be assumed, and not something 
else, by which, forsooth, one would establish the thing 
under discussion. If it is absurd to assume the thing 
questioned, it is also absurd to assume that upon which it 
rests. That all things belonging to the senses are also in 17& 
relation to something else is evident, because they are in 
relation to those who perceive them. It is clear then, 
that whatever thing of sense is brought before us, it may 
be easily referred to one of the five Tropes. And we come 
to a similar conclusion in regard to intellectual things. 
For if it should be said that there is a difference of opinion 
regarding them which cannot be judged, it will be granted 
that we must suspend the judgment concerning it. In 17& 
case the difference of opinion can be judged, if it is judged 
through anything intellectual, we fall into the regressus in 
infinitum, and if through anything sensible into the drcidus 
inprobando ; for, as the sensible is again subject to difference 
of opinion, and cannot be judged by the sensible on account 
of the regressus in infinitum, it will have need of the intel- 
lectual, just as the intellectual has need of the sensible. 
But he who accepts anything which is hypothetical again 177^ 
is absurd. Intellectual things stand also in relation, because 
the form in which they are expressed depends on the mind 
of the thinker, and, if they were in reality exactly as they 
are described, there would not have been any difference of 
opinion about them. Therefore the intellectual also is 
brought under the five Tropes, and consequently it is 
necessary to suspend the judgment altogether with regard 
to every thing that is brought before us. Such are the 
five Tropes taught by the later Sceptics. They set them 
forth, not to throw out the ten Tropes, but in order to put 
to shame the audacity of the Dogmatics in a variety of 
ways, by these Tropes as well as by those. 



144 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

CHAPTER XVI. 
The Two Tribes. 

178 Two other Tropes of e-7To-)(;q are also taught. For as it 
appears that everything that is comprehended is either 
comprehended through itself or through something else, 
it is thought that this fact introduces doubt in regard to 
all things. And that nothing can be understood through 
itself is evident, it is said, from the disagreement which 
exists altogether among the physicists in regard to sensible 
and intellectual things. I mean, of course, a disagreement 
which cannot be judged, as we are not able to use a sensible 
or an intellectual criterion in judging it, for everything that 
we would take has a part in the disagreement, and is un- 

179 trustworthy. Nor is it conceded that anything can be 
comprehended through something else ; for if a thing is 
comprehended through something, that must always in 
turn be comprehended through something else, and the 
regressus in infinitum or the circulus in probanda follow. If, 
on the contrary, a thing is comprehended through some- 
thing that one wishes to use as if it had been comprehended 
through itself, this is opposed to the fact that nothing can 
be comprehended through itself, according to what we have 
said. We do not know how that which contradicts itself 
can be comprehended, either through itself or through 
something else, as no criterion of the truth or of compre- 
hension appears, and signs without proof would be rejected, 
as we shall see in the next book. So much will suffice for 
the present about suspension of judgment. 

CHAPTER XVII. 

WTiat are the Tropes for the overturning of Aetiology ? 

180 In the same manner as we teach the Tropes of eiro^-q, 
some set forth Tropes through which we oppose the Dog- 
matics, by expressing doubt in regard to the aetiology of 



Pyrrhdnic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 145 

"which they are especially proud. So Aenesidemus teaches 
eight Tropes, by which he thinks that he can prove all 
the dogmatic aetiology useless. The first of th«se Tropes 181 
lie said, relates to the character of aetiology in general, 
which does not give incontestable testimony in regard to 
phenomena, because it treats of unseen things. The "second 
Trope states that although abundant resources exist by 
"which to investigate the cause of a thing in question, some 
Dogmatics investigate it in one way only. The third Trope 182 
■states that the Dogmatics assign causes which do not show 
■any order for things which have taken place in an orderly 
manner. The fourth Trope states that the Dogmatics, 
-accepting phenomena as they take place, think that they 
•also understand how unseen things take place, although 
perhaps the unseen things have taken place in the same 
way as the phenomena, and perhaps in some other way 
peculiar to themselves. The fifth Trope states that they 183 
all, so to speak, assign causes according to their own 
hypotheses about the elements, but not according to any 
■commonly accepted methods. The sixth states that they 
often explain things investigated according to their own 
hypotheses, but ignore opposing hypotheses which have 
•equal probability. The seventh states that they often give 184 
reasons for things that not only conflict with phenomena, 
but also with their own hypotheses. The eighth states 
that although that which seems manifest, and that which is 
to be investigated, are often equally inscrutable, they build 
up a theory from the one about the other, although both 
are equally inscrutable. It is not impossible, Aenesidemus 185 
-said also, that some Dogmatics should fail in their theories 
•of causality from other combinations of reasons deducible 
from the Tropes given above. Perhaps also the five Tropes 
■of eVo;^?; are sufficient to refute aetiology, for he who pro- 
poses a cause will propose one which is either in harmony 
■with all the sects of philosophy, with Scepticism, and with 

10 



146 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

phenomena, or one that is not. Perhaps, however, it is. 
not possible that a cause should be in harmony with them, 
for phenomena and unknown things altogether disagree 

186 with each other. If it is not in harmony with them, the 
reason of this will also be demanded of the one who pro- 
posed it ; and if he accepts a phenomenon as the cause of 
a phenomenon, or something unknown as the cause of the 
unknown, he will be thrown into the regressus in infinitum ; 
if he uses one cause to account for another one, into the 
circulus in probanda ; but if he stops anywhere, he will 
either say that the cause that he proposes holds good so^ 
far as regards the things that have been said, and introduce 
relation, abolishing an absolute standpoint ; or if he accepts 
anything by hypothesis, he will be attacked by us. There- 
fore it is perhaps possible to put the temerity of the Dog- 
matics to shame in aetiology by these Tropes. 

CHAPTER XVIII. 

The Sceptical Formulae. 

187 When we use any one of these Tropes, or the Tropes of 
iTro')(rj, we employ with them certain formulae which show 
the Sceptical method and our own feeling, as for instance, 
the sayings, "No more,'' "One must determine nothing,"' 
and certain others. It is fitting therefore to treat of these 
in this place. Let us begin with "No more." 

CHAPTER XIX. 

The Formula "No more." 

188 We sometimes express this as I have given it, and 
sometimes thus, "Nothing more." For we do not accept, 
the "No more," as some understand it, for the examination 
of the special, and " Nothing more " foT that of the general, 
but we use " No more " and " Nothing more " without any 
difference, and we shall at present treat of them as one and. 



Pyrrhonio Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 147 

the same expression. Now this formula is defective, for 
as when we say a double one we really mean a double gar- 
ment, and when we say a broad one we really mean a 
broad road ; so when we say " No more " we mean really 
no more than this, or in every way the same. But some 189 
of the Sceptics use instead of the interrogation "No 1" the 
interrogation " What, this rather than this 1 " using the 
word "what" in the sense of "what is the reason," so that 
the formula means, " What is the reason for this rather 
than for this ? " It is a customary thing, however, to use 
an interrogation instead of a statement, as "Who of the 
mortals does not know the wife of Jupiter ? " and also to 
use a statement instead of an interrogation, as " I seek 
where Dion dwells," and " I ask why one should admire a 
poet." The word "what" is also used instead of "what 
for " by Menander — " (For) what did I remain behind ? " 
The formula "Not more this than this" expresses our own 190 
condition of mind, and signifies that because of the equality 
of the things that are opposed to each other we finally 
attain to a state of equilibrium of soul. We mean by 
equality that equality which appears to us as probable, by 
things placed in opposition to each other we mean simply 
things which conflict with each other, and by a state of 
equilibrium we mean a state in which we do not assent to 
one thing more than to another. Even if the formula 191 
" Nothing more " seems to express assent or denial, we do 
not use it so, but we use it loosely, and not with accuracy, 
either instead of an interrogation or instead of saying, 
" 1 do not know to which of these I would assent, and to 
which I would not." What lies before us is to express 
what appears to us, but we are indifierent to the words by 
which we express it. This must be understood, however, 
that we use the formula "Nothing more" without aflSrm- 
ing in regard to it that it is wholly sure and true, but we 
present it as it appears to us. 



148 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

CHAPTER XX. 

Aphasia. 

192 We explain Aphasia as follows : The word ^dai<; is used 
in two ways, having a general and a special signification. 
According to the general signification, it expresses affirma- 
tion or negation, as " It is day" or " It is not day" ; accord- 
ing to the special signification, it expresses an affirmation 
only, and negations are not called (^acret?. Now Aphasia 
is the opposite of (fidcrK in its general signification, which, 
as we said, comprises both afiirmation and negation. It 
follows that Aphasia is a condition of mind, according to 
which we say that we neither affirm nor deny anything. 

193 It is evident from this that we do not understand by 
Aphasia something that inevitably results from the nature 
of things, but we mean that we now find ourselves in the 
condition of mind expressed by it in regard to the things 
that are under investigation. It is necessary to remember 
that we do not say that we affirm or deny any of those 
things that are dogmatically stated in regard to the un- 
known, for we yield assent only to those things which 
affect our feelings and oblige us to assent to them. 

CHAPTER XXI. 

"Perhaps," and "It is possible,'' and "It may be." 

194 The formulae "Perhaps," and "Perhaps not," and "It 
is possible," and "It is not possible," and "It may be," and 
"It may not be," we use instead of "Perhaps it is," and 
" Perhaps it is not," and " It is possible that it is," and " It 
is possible that it is not," and " It may be that it is," and 
" It may be that it is not." That is, we use the formula 
" It is not possible " for the sake of brevity, instead of say- 
ing " It is not possible to be," and " It may not be " instead 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 149 



of "It may not be that it is," and "Perhaps not" instead' 
of "Perhaps it is not." Again, we do not here dispute 195 
about words, neither do we question if the formulae mean 
these things absolutely, but we use them loosely, as I said 
before. Yet I think it is evident that these formulae 
express Aphasia. For certainly the formula "Perhaps it 
is " really includes that which seems to contradict it, i.e. the 
formula " Perhaps it is not," because it does not affirm in 
in regard to anything that it is really so. It is the same 
also in regard to the others. 



CHAPTER XXII. 
iiro'x^ or the Suspension of Judgment. 

When I say that I suspend my judgment, I mean that 196 
I cannot say which of those things presented should be 
believed, and which should not be believed, showing that 
things appear equal to me in respect to trustworthiness 
and untrustworthiness. Now we do not affirm that they 
are equal, but we state what appears to us in regard to 
them at the time when they present themselves to us. 
eiro'x^ means the holding back of the opinion, so as neither 
to affirm nor deny anything because of the equality of the 
things in question. 

CHAPTER XXIII. 

The Formula "I determine Nothing.'' 

In regard to the formula "I determine nothing," we 197 
saj^ the following : By " determine " we mean, not simply to 
speak, but to give assent to an affirmation with regard to 
some unknown thing. For it will soon be found that the 
Sceptic determines nothing, not even the formula "I de- 



150 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

termine nothing," for this formula is not a dogmatic opinion, 
that is an assent to something unknown, but an expression 
declaring what our condition of mind is. "When, for ex- 
ample, the Sceptic says, "I determine nothing," he means 
this : " According to my present feeling I can assert or 
deny nothing dogmatically regarding the things under 
investigation," and in saying this he expresses what appears 
to him in reference to the things under discussion. He 
does not express himself positively, but he states what he 
feels. 

CHAPTER XXIV. 

The Formula "Every thing is Undetermined." 

198 The expression " Indetermination " furthermore shows 
a state of mind in which we neither deny nor affirm posi- 
tively anything regarding things that are investigated in a 
dogmatic way, that is the things that are unknown. When 
then the Sceptic says "Every thing is undetermined," he 
uses "is undetermined," in the sense of "it appears unde- 
termined to him." The words "every thing" do not 
mean all existences, but those that he has examined of the 
unknown things that are investigated by the Dogmatists. 
By "undetermined," he means that there is no preference 
in the things that are placed in opposition to each other, 
or that they simply conflict with each other in respect to 

199 trustworthiness or untrustworthiness. And as the one 
who says "I am walking" really means "It is I that am 
walking," so he who says "Every thing is undetermined" 
means at the same time, according to our teachings, "as 
far as I am concerned," or " as it appears to me," as if he 
were saying "As far as I have examined the things that 
are under investigation in a dogmatic manner, it appears 
to me that no one of them excels the one which conflicts 
with it in trustworthiness or untrustworthiness." 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 151 



CHAPTER XXV. 

The Formula "Every thing is Incomprehensible." 
We treat the formula "Every thing is incomprehensible" 200 
in the same way. For " every thing " we interpret in the 
same way as above, and we supply the words " to me " so 
that what we say is this : " As far as I have inspected 
the unknown things which are dogmatically examined, it • 
appears to me that every thing is incomprehensible." This is 
not, however, to affirm that the things which are examined 
by the Dogmatists are of such a nature as to be necessarily 
incomprehensible, but one expresses his own feeling in 
saying "I see that I have not thus far comprehended any 
of those things because of the equilibrium of the things 
that are placed in opposition to each other." Whence it 
seems to me that every thing that has been brought forward 
to dispute our formulae has fallen wide of the mark. 

CHAPTER XXVI. 
The Formulae "I do not comprehend" and "I do not 

understand." 
The formulae "I do not comprehend" and "I do not 201 
understand " show a condition of mind in which the Sceptic 
stands aloof for the present from asserting or denying 
anything in regard to the unknown things under investi- 
gation, as is evident from what we said before about the 
other formulae. 

CHAPTER XXVII. 

The Formula " To place an equal Statement in opposition 

to every Statement." 

Furthermore, when we say " Every statement may have 202 

an equal statement placed in opposition to it," by " every," 

we mean all the statements that we have examined ; we 

do not use the word "statement" simply, but for a 



152 PyrrJionic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

statement which seeks to prove something dogmatically 
about things that are unknown, and not at all one that 
shows a process of reasoning from premises and con- 
clusions, but something which is put together in any sort 
of way. We use the word " equal " in reference to trust- 
worthiness or untrustworthiness. "Is placed in opposi- 
tion " we use instead of the common expression " to conflict 

203 with,'' and we supply "as it appears tome." When therefore 
one says, "It seems to me that every statement which I 
have examined, which proves something dogmatically, may 
have another statement placed in opposition to it which 
also proves something dogmatically, and which is equal to 
it in trustworthiness and untrustworthiness,'' this is not 
asserted dogmatically, but is an expression of human 

204 feeling as it appears to the one who feels it. Some- 
Sceptics express the formula as follows : " Every state- 
ment should have an equal one placed in opposition to 
it," demanding it authoritatively thus: "Let us place 
in opposition to every statement that proves something 
dogmatically another conflicting statement which also 
seeks to prove something dogmatically, and is equal to 
it in trustworthiness and untrustworthiness." Naturally 
this is directed to the Sceptics, but the infinitive should be 
used instead of the imperative, that is, "to oppose" instead 

205 of "let us oppose." This formula is recommended to the 
Sceptic, lest he should be deceived by the Dogmatists and 
give up his investigations, and rashly fail of the arapa^ia 
which is thought to accompany eTroyrj in regard to every- 
thing, as we have explained above. 

CHAPTER XXVIII. 

General Observations on the Formulae of the Sceptics. 

206 We have treated of a suflScient number of these formulae 
for an outline, especially since what we have said about 



PyrrJionic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 153 

those mentioned applies also to others that we have 
omitted. In regard to all the Sceptical formulae, it must 
be understood in advance that we do not affirm them to be 
absolutely true, because we say that they can even refute 
themselves, since they are themselves included in those 
things to which they refer, just as cathartic medicines not 
only purge the body of humors, but carry off themselves 
with the humors. We say then that we use these formulae, 20T 
not as literally making known the things for which they 
are used, but loosely, and if one wishes, inaccurately. It 
is not fitting for the Sceptic to dispute about words, 
especially as it contributes to our purpose to say that 
these formulae have no absolute meaning ; their meaning 
is a relative one, that is, relative to the Sceptics. Besides, 208- 
it is to be remembered that we do not say them about all 
things in general, but about the unknown, and things that 
are dogmatically investigated, and that we say what appears 
to us, and that we do not express ourselves decidedly about 
the nature of external objects. By this means I think that 
every sophism brought against the Sceptical formulae can 
be overturned. We have now shown the character of 209 
Scepticism by examining its idea, its parts, its criterion 
and aim, and also the Tropes of etroxv, and by treating of 
the Sceptical formulae. We think it therefore appropriate 
to enter briefly into the distinction between Scepticism and 
the nearly related schools of philosophy in order to more 
clearly understand the Sceptical School. We will begin 
with the philosophy of Heraclitus. 

CHAPTER XXIX. 

In what does the Sceptical School differ from the Philosophy 
of Heraclitus ? 

Now that this school differs from ours is evident, for 210 



154 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricas. 

Heraclitus expresses himself about many unknown things 
dogmatically, which we do not, as has been said. Aenesi- 
demus and his followers said that the Sceptical School is 
the way to the philosophy of Heraclitus. They gave as a 
reason for this that the statement that contradictory 
predicates appear to be applicable to the same thing, leads 
the way to the statement that contradictory predicates are 
in reality applicable to the same thing ; and as the Sceptics 
say that contradictory predicates appear to be applicable 
to the same thing, the Heraclitans proceed from this to 
the doctrine that such predicates are in reality applicable. 
We reply to this that the statement that contradictory 
predicates appear to be applicable to the same thing is not 
a dogma of the Sceptics, but is a fact that presents itself 
not only to the Sceptics, but to other philosophers, and to 

211 all men. No one, for instance, would venture to say that 
honey does not taste sweet to those in health, and bitter 
to those who have the jaundice, so that the Heraclitans 
start from a preconception common to all men, as do we 
also, and perhaps the other schools of philosophy likewise. 
If, however, they had attributed the origin of the statement 
that contradictory predicates are present in the same 
thing to any of the Sceptical teachings, as, for example, to 
the formula "Every thing is incomprehensible," or "I 
determine nothing," or any of the other similar ones, it 
may be that which they say would follow ; but since they 
start from that which is a common experience, not only to 
us, but to other philosophers, and in life, why should one 
say that our school is a path to the philosophy of Herac- 
litus more than any of the other schools of philosophy, or 
than life itself, as we all make use of the same subject 

212 matter ? On the other hand, the Sceptical School may not 
only fail to help towards the knowledge of the philosophy 
of Heraclitus, but may even hinder it ! For the Sceptic 
attacks all the dogmas of Heraclitus as having been 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 155 

rashly given, and opposes on the one hand the doctrine of 
conflagration, and on the other, the doctrine that contra- 
dictory predicates in reality apply to the same thing, and 
in regard to every dogma of Heraclitus he scorns his 
dogmatic rashness, and then, in the manner that 1 have 
before referred to, adduces the formulae " I do not under- 
stand" and "I determine nothing," which conflict with 
the Heraclitan doctrines. It is absurd to say that this 
conflicting school is a path to the very sect with which 
it conflicts. It is then absurd to say that the Sceptical 
School is a path to the philosophy of Heraclitus. 



CHAPTER XXX. 

In what does the Sceptical School differ from the Philosophy 
of Democritus ? 

The philosophy of Democritus is also said to have 213 
■community with Scepticism, because it seems to use the 
same matter that we do. For, from the fact that honey 
iseems sweet to some and bitter to others, Democritus 
reasons, it is said, that honey is neither sweet nor bitter, 
;and therefore he accords with the formula "No more," 
which is a formula of the Sceptics. But the Sceptics and 
the Democritans use the formula "No more" differently 
from each other, for they emphasise the negation in the 
expression, but we, the not knowing whether both of the phe- 
nomena exist or neither one, and so we difi'er in this respect. 
The distinction, however, becomes most evident when 214 
Democritus says that atoms and empty space are real, for 
by real he means existing in reality. Now, although he 
begins with the anomaly in phenomena, yet, since he says 
.that atoms and empty space really exist, it is superfluous, 
I think, even to say that he diiFers from us. 



156 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

CHAPTEE XXXI. 

In what does Scepticism differ from the Cyrenaic Philosophy T 

215 Some say that the Cyrenaic School is the same as the- 
Sceptical, because that school also claims to comprehend 
only conditions of mind. It differs, however, from it, 
because, while the former makes pleasure and the gentle 
motion of the- flesh its aim, we make ajapa^ia ours, and 
this is opposed to the aim of their school. For whether 
pleasure is presenter not, confusion awaits himwhomaintains. 
that pleasure is an aim, as I have shown in what I said 
about the aim. And then, in addition, we suspend our 
judgment as far as the reasoning with regard to external 
objects is concerned, but the Cyrenaics pronounce the 
nature of these insqrutable. 

CHAPTEE XXXII. 

In what does Scepticism differ from the Philosophy of 
Protagoras ? 

216 Protagoras makes man the measure of all things, of 
things that are that they are, and things that are not that 
they are not, meaning by measure, criterion, and by things, 
events, that is to say really, man is the criterion for all 
events, of things that are that they are, and of things that 
are not that they are not. And for that reason he accepts 
only the phenomena that appear to each man, and thus he- 

217 introduces relation. Therefore he seems to have community 
with the Pyrrhoneans. He differs, however, from them, 
and we shall see the difference after we have somewhat 
explained how things seemed to Protagoras. He says, for 
example, that matter is fluid, and as it flows, additions are 
constantly made in the place of that which is carried away ; 
the perceptions also are arranged anew and changed. 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 157 

according to the age and according to other conditions of 
the body. He says also, that the reasons of all phenomena 218 
are present in matter, so that matter can be all that it 
appears to be to all men as far as its power is concerned. 
Men, however, apprehend differently at different times, 
according to the different conditions that they are in ; for 
he that is in a natural condition will apprehend those 
qualities in matter that can appear to those who are in a 219 
natural condition, while on the contrary, those who are in 
an unnatural condition will apprehend those qualities that 
can appear to the abnormal. Furthermore, the same 
reasoning would hold true in regard to differences in age, 
to sleeping and waking, and each of the other different 
conditions. Therefore man becomes the criterion of things 
that are, for all things that appear to men exist for men, 
and those things that do not appear to any one among 
men do not exist. We see that he dogmatises in saying 
that matter is fluid, and also in saying that the reasons for 
all phenomena have their foundation in matter, while 
these things are unknown, and to us are things regarding 
which we suspend our judgment. 

CHAPTER XXXIII. 

In what does Scepticism, differ from the Academic 
Philosophy ? 

Some say further that the Academic philosophy is the 220 
same as Scepticism, therefore it seems appropriate to me 
to treat of that also. There have been, as the most say, 
three Academies — the most ancient one, that of Plato and 
his followers ; the second and middle one, that of Arcesilaus 
and his followers, Arcesilaus being the pupil of Polemo ; the 
third and new Academy, that of Carneades and Clitomachus 
and their followers ; some add also a fourth, that of Philo 
and Charmides, and their followers ; and some count even a 



158 Pyrrhonic Sketches by 8extus Ernpiricus. 

fifth, that of Antiochus and his followers. Beginning thea 
from the old Academy, let us consider the difference between 

221 the schools of philosophy mentioned. Now some have 
said that Plato was a Dogmatic, others that he was a 
Sceptic, and others that he was in some things a Sceptic- 
and in some things a Dogmatic. For in the fencing dialogues, 
where Socrates is introduced as either making sport of 
someone or contending against the Sophists, Plato has, 
they say, a fencing and sceptical character, but he is- 
dogmatic when he expresses himself seriously, either 

222 through Socrates or Timaeus or any such person. In 
regard to those who say that he is a Dogmatic, or a 
Dogmatic in some things and a Sceptic in others, it would 
be superfluous, it seems to me, to speak now, for they 
themselves grant that he is different from us. The ques- 
tion as to whether he was really a Sceptic or not we treat 
more fully in the Memoranda, but here we state briefly 
that according to Menodotus and Aenesidemus (for these 
especially defended this position) Plato dogmatises when 
he expresses himself regarding ideas, and regarding the 
existence of Providence, and when he states that the 
virtuous life is more to be chosen than the one of vice. 
If he assents to these things as true, he dogmatises; or 
even if he accepts them as more probable than otherwise 
he departs from the sceptical character, since he gives a 
preference to one thing above another in trustworthiness 
or untrustworthiness ; for how foreign this is to us is 

223 evident from what we have said before. Even if when 
he performs mental gymnastics, as they say, he expresses, 
some things sceptically, he is not because of this a Sceptic. 
For he who dogmatises about one thing, or, in short, gives 
preference to one mental image over another in trust- 
worthiness or untrustworthiness in respect to anything 
that is unknown, is a Dogmatic in character, as Timon 

224 shows by what he said of Xenophanes. For after having 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 159 

praised Xenophanes in many things, and even after having 
dedicated his Satires to him, he made him mourn and 
say— 

" Would that I also might gain that mind profound. 
Able to look both ways. In a treacherous path have I been 

decoyed, 
And still in old age am with all wisdom unwed. 
For wherever I turned my view 
All things were resolved into unity ; all things, alway 
From all sources drawn, were merged into nature the same." 

Timon calls him somewhat, but not entirely, free from 
vanity, when he said — 

" Xenophanes somewhat free from vanity, mocker of Homeric deceit, 
Far from men he conceived a god, on all sides equal. 
Above pain, a being spiritualised, or intellect." 

In saying that he was somewhat free from vanity, he meant 
that he was in some things free from vanity. He called 
him a mocker of the Homeric deceit because he had scoflfed 
at the deceit in Homer. Xenophanes also dogmatised, con- 22& 
trary to the assumptions of other men, that all things are 
one, and that G-od is grown together with all things, that 
He is spherical, insensible, unchangeable, and reasonable, 
•whence the difference of Xenophanes from us is easily 
proved. In short, from what has been said, it is evident 
that although Plato expresses doubt about some things, so 
long as he has expressed himself in certain places in regard 
to the existence of unknown things, or as preferring some 
things to others in trustworthiness, he cannot be, it seems 
to me, a Sceptic. Those of the New Academy, although 22& 
they say that all things are incomprehensible, differ from 
the Sceptics, perhaps even in saying that all things are in- 
comprehensible (for they assert decidedly in regard to this, 
but the Sceptic thinks it possible that some things may be 
comprehended), but they differ evidently still further from . 
us in their judgment of good and evil. For the Academi- 
cians say that there is such a thing as good and evil, not 



160 Pyrrhonic Sketches hy Sexius Empiricus. 

as we say it, but more with the conviction that that which 
they call good exists than that it does not ; and likewise in 
regard to the evil, while we do not say anything is good 
or evil with the conviction that it is probably so, but we live 
our lives in an unprejudiced way in order not to be 

227 inactive. Moreover, we say that our ideas are equal to 
each other in trustworthiness and untrustworthiness, as 
far as their nature goes, while they say that some are 
probable and others improbable. They make a difference 
also between the improbable ones, for they believe that 
some of them are only probable, others probable and un- 
disputed, still others probable, undisputed, and tested. As 
for example, when a coiled rope is lying in a somewhat 
dark room, he who comes in suddenly gets only a probable 

.228 idea of it, and thinks that it is a serpent; but it appears to 
be a rope to him who has looked carefully around, and 
found out that it does not move, and that it is of such a 
color, and so on, according to an idea which is probable 
and undisputed. The tested idea is like this : It is said 
that Hercules led Alcestis after she was dead back again 
from Hades and showed her to Admetus, and he received 
an idea that was probable and undisputed regarding 
Alcestis. As, however, he knew that she was dead, his 
mind drew back from belief and inclined to disbelief. 

222 Now those belonging to the New Academy prefer the idea 
which is probable and undisputed to the simply probable 
one. To both of these, however, they prefer that which is 
probable, undisputed, and tested. If, however, both those 
of the Academy and the Sceptics say that they believe 
certain things, there is an evident difference between the 

530 two schools of philosophy even in this ; for "' to believe " is 
used in a different sense, meaning, on the one hand, not to 
resist, but simply to accept without strong inclination and 
approval, as the child is said to believe the teacher ; on the 
other hand, "to believe" is used to signify assenting to 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiriciis. 161 

something with choice, and, as it were, with the sympathy 
that accompanies strong will, as the prodigal follows the 
one who chooses to live a luxurious life. Therefore, since 
Carneades, Clitomachus, and their followers say that they 
are strongly inclined to believe that a thing is probable, and 
we simply allow that it may be so without assent, we differ 231 
from them, I think, in this way. We differ from the New 
Academy likewise in things concerning the aim ; for while 
the men who say that they govern themselves according to 
that School avail themselves of the idea of the probable in 
life, we live according to the laws and customs, and our 
natural feelings, in an unprejudiced way. We could say 
more regarding the distinction between the two schools if 
we did not aim at brevity. Nevertheless, Arcesilaus, who 232 
as we said was the leader and chief of the Middle Academy, 
seems to me to have very much in common with the 
Pyrrhonean teachings, so that his school and ours are 
almost one. For neither does one find that he expressed 
an opinion about the existence or non-existence of any- 
thing, nor does he prefer one thing to another as regards 
trustworthiness or untrustworthiness ; he suspends his 
judgment regarding all things, and the aim of his philo- 
sophy is eTToxVi which is accompanied by arapa^la, and 
this agrees with what we have said. But he calls the 233 
particular instances of ejroxn bona, and the particular in- 
stances of assent mala. The difference is that we say these 
things according to what appears to us, and not affirma- 
tively, while he says them as if speaking of realities, that 
is, he says that eTro'x^V is in itself good, and assent an evil. 
If we are to believe also the things that are said about him, 234 
he appeared at first sight to be a Pyrrhonean, but he was 
in truth a Dogmatic, for he used to test his companions by 
the method of doubt to see whether they were gifted enough 
to take in Plato's dogmas, so that he appeared to be a 
Sceptic, but at the same time he communicated the doctrines 

11 



162 Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 

of Plato to thoseof his companions who were gifted. Hence 
Ariston also said about him — 

" Plato in front, Pyrrhon behind, Diodorus in the middle," 

because he availed himself of the dialectic of Diodorus, but 

235 -was wholly a Platonist. Now Philo and his followers say 
that as far as the Stoic criterion is concerned, that is to say 
the (^avraaia KaToXtjiniKri, things are incomprehensible, 
but as far as the nature of things is concerned, they are 
comprehensible. Antiochus, however, transferred the Stoa 
to the Academy, so that it was even said of him that he 
taught the Stoic philosophy in the Academy, because he 
tried to show that the Stoic doctrines are found in Plato. 
The difference, therefore, between the Sceptical School and 
the Fourth and Fifth Academy is evident. 

CHAPTER XXXIV. 

Is Empiricism in Medi-cine the same as Scepticism? 

236 Some say that the medical sect called Empiricism is 
the same as Scepticism. Yet the fact must be recognised, 
that even if Empiricism does maintain the impossibility of 
knowledge, it is neither Scepticism itself, nor would it 
suit the Sceptic to take that sect upon himself. He could 
rather, it seems to me, belong to the so-called Methodic 

237 School. For this alone, of all the medical sects, does not 
seem to proceed rashly in regard to unknown things, and 
does not presume to say whether they are comprehensible 
or not, but is guided by phenomena, and receives from 
them the same help which they seem to give to the Scep- 
tical system. For we have said in what has gone before, 
that the every-day life which the Sceptic lives is of four 
parts, depending on the guidance of nature, on the necessity 
of the feelings, on the traditions of laws and customs, and 

238 on the teaching of the arts. Now as by necessity of 



Pyrrhonic Sketches by Sextus Empiricus. 163 

the feelings the Sceptic is led by thirst to drink, and 
by hunger to food, and to supply similar needs in the 
same way, so also the physician of the Methodic School is 
led by the feelings to find suitable remedies ; in constipation 
he produces a relaxation, as one takes refuge in the sun 
irom the shrinking on account of intense cold ; he is led 
by a flux to the stopping of it, as those in a hot bath who 
are dripping from a profuse perspiration and are relaxed, 
hasten to check it by going into the cold air. Moreover, 
it is evident that the Methodic physician forces those 
things which are of a foreign nature to adapt themselves 
to their own nature, as even the dog tries to get a sharp 
stick out that is thrust into him. In order, however, that 239 
I should not overstep the outline character of this work 
by discussing details, I think that all the things that the 
Methodics have thus said can be classified as referring to 
the necessity of the feelings that are natural or those that 
are unnatural. Besides this, it is common to both schools 
to have no dogmas, and to use words loosely. For as the 240 
Sceptic uses the formula "I determine nothing," and "I 
understand nothing," as we said above, so the Methodic 
also uses the expressions "Community," and "To go 
through," and other similar ones without over much care. 
In a similar way he uses the word "Indication" undog- 
matically, meaning that the symptoms of the patient 
either natural or unnatural, indicate the remedies that 
would be suitable, as we said in speaking of thirst, hunger, 
and other things. It will thus be seen that the Methodic 241 
School of medicine has a certain relationship to Scepticism 
which is closer than that of the other medical sects, 
speaking comparatively if not absolutely from these and 
similar tokens. Having said so much in reference to the 
schools that seem to closelj"^ resemble Scepticism, we con- 
clude the general consideration of Scepticism and the 
First Book of the Sketches. 



CA&IBRIDOE 

FEINTED BY JONATHAN PALMKR. 

ALEXANDRA STREET 



A 

CLASSIFIED CATALOGUE 

OF 

EDUCATIONAL WORKS 

PUBLISHED BY 

GEORGE BELL ^ SONS 




LONDON : YORK STREET, COVENT GARDEN 

NEW YORK: 66, FIFTH AVENUE 

AND BOMBAY : 53, ESPLANADE ROAD 

CAMBRIDGE : DEIGHTON, BELL & CO. 

October, 1898 



CONTENTS. 

rAGX 

GREEK AND LATIN CLASSICS: 

Annotated and Critical Editions .... 3 

Texts 9 

Translations 10 

Grammar and Composition 15 

History, Geography, and Reference Books, etc. . 18 

MATHEMATICS : 

Arithmetic and Algebra 19 

Book-keeping 20 

Geometry and Euclid 21 

Analytical Geometry, etc 21 

Trigonometry 22 

Mechanics and Natural Philosophy ... 22 

MODERN LANGUAGES: 

English . . 24 

French Class Books 29 

French Annotated Editions 31 

German Class Books 31 

German Annotated Editions 32 

Italian 34 

Bell's Modern Translations 34 

SCIENCE, TECHNOLOGY, AND ART: 

Chemistry 35 

Botany 35 

Geology 36 

Medicine 36 

Bell's Agricultural Series 36 

Technological Handbooks 37 

Music 38 

Art 38 

MENTAL, MORAL, AND SOCIAL SCIENCES: 

Psychology and Ethics 39 

History of Philosophy 40 

Law and Political Economy 40 



History 



41 



Divinity, etc 43 

Summary of Series 45 



GREEK AND LATIN CLASSICS. 

ANNOTATED AND CRITICAL EDITIONS. 

AESCHYLUS. Edited by F. a. paley, m.a., ll.d., late Classical Exa- 
miner to the University of London. 4/A edition, revised. 8vo, 8j. 

[Bib. Class. 

— Edited by F. A. palev, m.a., ll.d. 6 vols. Fcap. 8vo, is. bd. 

\Camb. Texts with Notes. 
Agamemnon. Persae. 

Choephoroe. Prometheus Vinctus. 

Eumenides. Septem contra Thebas. 

ARISTOPHANIS Comoediae quae supersunt cum perditarum fragmentis 
tertiis curis, recognovit additis adnotatione critica, summariis, descriptione 
metrica, onomastico lexico hubertus a. holden, ll. d. [late Fellow of 
Trinity College, Cambridge]. Demy 8vo. 

Vol. I. , containing the Text expurgated, with Summaries and Critical 
Notes, \%s. 

The Plays sold separately : 
Acharnenses, 2s. Ayes, 2.s. 

Equites, u. 6d. Lysistrata, et Thesmophoriazu- 

Nubes, 2s. sae, 4;. 

Vespae, 2s. Ranae, zs. 

Pax, 2s. Plutus, 2s. 

Vol. II. OnomastiGon Aristophaneum continens indicem geographi- 
cum et historicum. 5^. 6d. 

— The Plutus. Edited, with Notes, by M. T. quinn, m.a., Lond. 3*. 6d. 

{Pub. Sck. Ser. 

— The Peace. A revised Text with English Notes and a Preface. By 

F. a. paley, m.a., I.L.D. Post 8vo, 2s. 6d. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— The Acharnians. A revised Text with English Notes and a Preface. 

By F. A. PALEY, M.A., LL.D. Post 8vo, 2s. bd. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— The Frogs. A revised Text with English Notes and a Preface. By F. A. 

PALEY, M.A., LL.D. Post 8vo, 2J. 6fli [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

CAESAR De Bello Gallico. Edited byGE0RGELONG,.M.A. New edition. 

Books I.-IIL, \s. bd. ; Books IV. and V., is. bd. ; Books VI. and VII., 

I J. bd. [Gram. Sch. Class. 

— De Bello Gallico. Book I. Edited by george long, m.a. With 

Vocabulary by w. F. R. shilleto, m.a. \s. bd. [Lower Form Ser. 

— De Bello Gallico. Book II. Edited by george long, m.a. With 

Vocabulary by w. F. R. shilleto, m.a. Fcap. 8vo, \s. bd. 

[Lower Form Ser, 

— De Bello Gallico. Book III. Edited by george long, m.a. With 

Vocabulary by w. F. R. shilleto, m.a. Fcap. 8vo, \s. bd. 

[Lower Form Ser. 

— Seventh Campaign in Gaul. B.C. 52. De Bello Gallico, Lib. VII. 

Edited with Notes, Excursus, and Table of Idioms, by rev. w. cook- 
worthy COMPTON, M.A., Head Master of Dover College. With 
Illustrations from Sketches by E. T. COMPTON, Maps and Plans, yd 
edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. bd. net. 

" A really admirable class book." — Spectator^ 

" One of the most original and interesting books which have been 
published in late years as aids to the study of classical literature. I think 



George Bell & Sons' 



C A E S A ^—centmued. 

it gives the student a new idea of the way in which a classical book may 
be made a living reality." — Sev. J. E. C. Welldon, Harrow. 

— Easy Selections from the Helvetian War. Edited by A. M. M. sted- 

MAN, M.A. With Introduction, Notes and Vocabulary. i8mo, is. 

[Primary Classics. 

CALPURNIUS SICULUS and M. AURELIUS OLYMPIUS 

NEMBSIANUS. The Eclogues, with Introduction, Commentary, 

and Appendix. By c. H. keene, m.a. Crown 8vo, 6s. 

CATULLUS, TIBULLUS, and PROPERTIUS. Selected Poems. 

Edited by the rev. a. h. WRATlSLAVir, late Head Master of Bury St 

Edmunds School, and F. N. sutton, b.a. With Biographical Notices of 

the Poets. Fcap. 8vo, zi. dd. \_Gram. Sch. Class. 

CICERO'S Orations. Edited by G. long, m.a. Svo. [Bii. Class. 

Vol. I. — In Verrem. %s. 

Vol. II.— Pro P. Quintio— Pro Sex. Roscio— Pro Q. Roscio— Pro M. 
Tullio^'Pro M. Fonteio — Pro A. Caecina — De Imperio Cn. Pompeii — 
Pro A. Cluentio — De Lege Agraria — Pro C. Rabirio. Sj. 
Vols. III. and IV. Out of print. 

— De Senectute, De Amicitia, and Select Epistles. Edited byoEORGE 

LONG, M.A. New edition. Fcap. Svo, 3^. [Gram. Sch. Class. 

— De Amicitia. Edited by GEORGE long, m.a. Fcap. Svo, is. td. 

\Camh. Texts with Notes. 

— De Senectute. Edited by GEORGE long, m.a. Fcap. Svo, is. 6d. 

[Cami. Texts with Notes, 

— Epistolae Selectae. Edited by george long, m.a. Fcap. Svo, is. 6d, 

[Camb. Texts with Notes. 

— The Letters to Atticus. Book I. With Notes, and an Essay on the 

Character of the Writer. By A. pretor, m.a., late of Trinity College, 
Fellow of St. Catherine's College, Cambridge, yd edition. Post Svo, 
V. 6d. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

CORNELIUS NEPOS. Edited by the late REV. J. F. macmichael, 
Head Master of the Grammar School, Ripon. Fcap. Svo, zs. 

[Gram. Sch. Class. 

DEMOSTHENES. Edited by R. whiston, M.A., late Head Master of 

Rochester Grammar School. 2 vols. Svo, 8j. each. \Bib. Class. 

Vol. I. — Olynthiacs — Philippics — De Pace — Halonnesus — Chersonese 

— Letter of Philip — Duties of the State — Symmoriae — Rhodians — Mega- 

lopolitans — Treaty with Alexander — Crown. 

Vol. II. — Embassy — Leptines — Meidias — Androtion — Aristocrates — 
Timocrates — Aristogeiton. 

— De Falsa Legatione. By the late R. shilleto, m.a.. Fellow of St. 

Peter's College, Cambridge. %th edition. Post Svo, ts. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— The Oration against the Law of Leptines. With English Notes. 

By the late B. w. beatson, m.a.. Fellow of Pembroke College, yd 
edition. Post Svo, y. 6d. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

EURIPIDES. By F. A. paley, m.a., ll.d. 3 vols. 2nd edition, revised. 
Svo, 8j. each. Vol. I. Out of print. [Bib. Class. 

Vol. II. — Preface — Ion — Helena — Andromache — Electra — Bacchae — 
Hecuba. 2 Indexes. 

Vol. III. — Preface— Hercules Furens—Phoenissae— Orestes— Iphi- 
genia in Tauris — Iphigenia in Aulide — Cyclops. 2 Indexes. 



Educational Catalogue. 



EVRIPIDES— continued. 

— Electra. Edited, with Introduction and Notes, by c. H. keene, m.a., 

Dublin, Ex-Scholar and Gold Medallist in Classics. Demy 8vo, lox. 6d. 

— Edited by F. a. paley, m.a., ll.d. 13 vols. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6<l. each. 

[Camb. Texts with Notes. 



Phoenissae. 
Troades. 
Hercules Furens. 
Andromache. 
Iphigenia in Tauris, 
Supplices. 



Alcestis. 
Medea. 
Hippolytus. 
Hecuba. 
Bacchae. 
Ion (2s.). 
Orestes. 

HERODOTUS. Edited by rev. j. w. blakesley, b.d. 2 vols. 8vo, I2j. 

IBib. Class. 

— Easy Selections from the Persian Wars. Edited by A. G. liddell, 

M.A. With Introduction, Notes, and Vocabulary. l8mo, is. dd. 

{Primary Classics. 
HESIOD. Editedby F. A. PALEY, M.A., LL.D. 2.nd edition, revised. 8vo, 5j. 

{Bib. Class. 

HOMER. Edited by F. A. paley, m.a., ll.d. 2 vols. 2nd edition, 

revised. 14J. Vol. II. (Books XIII. -XXIV.) may be had separately. 6j. 

{Bib. Class. 

— Iliad. Books I. -XII. Edited by F. A. paley, m.a., ll.d. Fcap. 8vo, 

4s. 6rf. 

Also in 2 Parts. Books I. -VI. 2s. td. Books VII. -XII. zs.dd. 

{Gram. Sch. Class. 

— Iliad. Book I. Edited by F. A. paley, m.a., ll.d. Fcap. 8vo, \s. 

{Camb. Text with Notes. 

HORACE. Edited by REV. A. J. macleane, m.a. 4/A edition, revised by 

GEORGE LONG. 8vo, %s. {Bib. Class. 

— Edited by A. j. macleane, m.a. With a short Life. Fcap. 8vo, y. 6d. 

Or, Part I., Odes, Carmen Seculare, and Epodes, 2J. ; Part II., Satires, 
Epistles, and Art of Poetry, 2.s. {Gram. Sch. Class. 

— Odes. Book I. Edited by a. j. macleane, m.a. With a Vocabulary 

by A. H. DENNIS, m.a. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. {Lower Form Ser. 

JUVENAL : Sixteen Satires (expurgated). By Herman prior, m.a., 

late Scholar of Trinity College, Oxford. Fcap. 8vo, 3/. (>d. 

{Gram. Sch. Class. 
LIVY. The first five Books, with English Notes. By J. prendeville. 

A new edition revised throughout, and the notes in great part re-written, 

by J. H. FREESE, M.A., late Fellow of St. John's College, Cambridge. 

Books I. II. III. IV. V. With Maps and Introductions. Fcap. 8vO, 

IS. 6d. each. 

— Book VI. Edited by E. s. weymouth, m.a., Lond., and G. if. Hamilton, 

B.A. With Historical Introduction, Life of Livy, Notes, Examination 
Questions, Dictionary of Proper Names, and Map. Crown 8vo, 2s. td. 

— Book XXI. By the rev. l. d. dowdall, m.a., late Scholar and Uni- 

versity Student of Trinity College, Dublin, B.D., Ch. Ch. Oxon. Post 
8vo, 2s. {Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— Book XXII. Edited by the REV. L. D. dowdall, m.a., B.d. Post 8vo, 

2s. [Pub. Sch. Ser, 



George Bell & Sons' 



LIVY — continued, 

— Easy Selections from the Kings of Rome. Edited by A. M. M. 

STEDMAN, M.A. With Introduction, Notes, and Vocabulary. l8mo, 
IS. dd. [Primary Class. 

LUCAN. The Pharsalia. By c. E. HASKINS, M.A., Fellow of St. John's 
College, Cambridge, with an Introduction by w. E. heitland, M.A., 
Fellow and Tutor of St. John's College, Cambridge. 8vo, 14^. 

LUCRETIUS. Titi Lucreti Cari De Rerum Natura Libri Sex. By 
the late H. A. J. mdnro, M.A., Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge. 
nth edition, finally revised. 3 vols. Demy 8vo. Vols. I., II., Introduc- 
tion, Text, and Notes, i&s. Vol. III., Translation, 6s. 

MARTIAL: Select Epigrams. Edited by F. A. paley, M.A., LL.D., 
and the late w. H. STONE, Scholar of Trinity College, Cambridge. With 
a Life of the Poet. Feap. 8vo, 4^. 6d. [Gram. Sch. Class. 

OVID: Fasti. Edited by F. A. paley, m.a., LL.D. Second edition. 

Fcap. 8vo, 3 J. 6d. [Cram. Sch. Class, 

Or in 3 vols, \s. 6d. each [Grammar School Classics'], or 2J. each [Camb, 

Texts with Notes], Books I. and II., Books III. and IV., Books V. 

and VI. 

— Selections from the Amores, Tristia, Heroides, and Metamor- 

phoses. By A. J. macleane, m.a. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. 

[Camb. Texts with Notes, 

— Ars Amatoria et Amores. A School Edition. Carefully Revised and 

Edited, with some Literary Notes, by J. Herbert Williams, m.a., 
late Demy of Magdalen College, Oxford. Fcap. 8vo, 3^. 6d. 

— Heroides XIV. Edited, with Introductory Preface and English Notes, 

by ARTHUR palmer, M.A., Professor of Latin at Trinity College, Dublin. 
Demy 8vo, 6s. 

— Metamorphoses, Book XIII. A School Edition. With Introduction 

and Notes, by chari.es haines keene, m.a., Dublin, Professor of 
Greek, Queen's College, Cork, /^th edition. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

— Metamorphoses. Book XIV. A School Edition. With Introduction 

and Notes, by c. H. keene, m.a. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

— Metamorphoses, Books XIII. and XIV. Edited by c. H. keene, m.a. 

Fcap. 8vo, 3J. 6d. 

— Epistolarura ex Ponto Liber Primus. With Introduction and Notes, 

by CHARLES HAINES KEENE, M.A. CrOwn 8vo, 3^. 
PLATO. The Apology of Socrates and Crito. With Notes, critical 
and exegetical, by wilhelm wagner, ph.d. \2th edition. Post 8vo, 
2J. 6d. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— Phaedo. With Notes, critical and exegetical, and an Analysis, by 

wilhelm WAGNER, PH.D. 11th edition. Post 8vo, $s. 6d. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— ^ Protagoras. The Greek Text revised, with an Analysis and English 

Notes, by W. wayte, m.a., Classical Examiner at University College, 

London. 1th edition. Post 8vo, 4r. 6d. [Pub. Sch, Ser, 

— Euthyphro. With Notes and Introduction by G. H. wells, m.a.. 

Scholar of St. John's College, Oxford ; Assistant Master at Merchant 
Taylors' School, yd edition. Post Svo, 3J-. [Pub. Sch. Ser, 

— The Republic. Books I. and II. With Notes and Introduction by 

G. H. wells, m.A. nth edition, with the Introduction re-written. Post 
Svo, Ss. [Put. Sck, Str. 

— Butbydemus. With Notes and Introdnction by a. H. wblls, m.a. 

Tost Svo, 4J. [Pub. Sch, Ser. 



Educational Catalogue. 



'P'L.Pi.'VO— continued. 

— Pbaedrus. By the late w. H. Thompson, d.d., Master of Trinity College, 

Cambridge. 8vo, 5j-. \^Bib. Class. 

— Gorgias. By the late w. H. Thompson, d.d., Master of Trinity College, 

Cambridge. New edition. 6s, [Pud. Sch. Ser, 

PLAUTUS. Aulularia. With Notes, critical and exegetical, by w. 
WAGNBR, PH.D. t,th edition. Post 8vo, 4j. W. \Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— Trinummus. With Notes, critical and exegetical, by wilhelm 

WAGNER, PH.D. ^th edition. Post 8vo, 4J. td. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— Menaechmei. With Notes, critical and exegetical, by wilhelm 

WAGNER, PH.D. -^rd edition. Post 8vo, 4J. 6d. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— Mostellaria. By E. A. sonnbnschein, m.a., Professor of Classics at 

Mason College, Birmingham. Post 8vo, 5^. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— Captivi. Abridged and Edited for the Use of Schools. With Intro- 

duction and Notes by J. H. FREESE, m.a., formerly Fellow of St. John's 

College, Cambridge. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. 
PROPERTIUS. Sex. Aurelii Propertii Carmina. The Elegies of 

Propertius, with English Notes. By F. A. paley, m.a., ll.d. 2nd 

edition. 8vo, fj. 
SALLUST : Catilina and Jugurtha. Edited, with Notes, by the late 

GEORGE LONG. New edition, revised, wiih the addition of the Chief 

Fragments of the Histories, by J. G. frazer, m.a. Fellow of Trin. Coll., 

Camb. Fcap. 8vo, y. 6d. , or separately, 2s. each. [ Gram. Sch. Class. 
SOPHOCLES. Edited by REV. F. H. blaydes, m.a. VoL I. Oedipus 

Tyrannus — Oedipus Coloneus — Antigone. 8vo, 8j. [Bib. Class. 

Vol. II. Philoctetes— Electra— Trachiniae— Ajax. By F. A. PALEY, 

M.A., LL.D. 8vo, 6j. 

— Trachiniae. With Notes and Prolegomena. By Alfred pretor, m.a., 

Fellow of St. Catherine's College, Cambridge. Post 8vo, 4?. (^d. 

[Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— The Oedipus Tyrannus of Sophocles. By B. H. Kennedy, d.d., 

Regius Professor of Greek and Hon. Fellow of St. John's College, Cam- 
bridge. With a Commentary containing a large number of Notes selected 
from the MS. of the late T. H. steel, m.a. Crown 8vo, 8j. 
A School Edition Post 8vo, 2s. 6d. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— Edited by F. A. paley, m.a., ll.d. J ^°^- Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. each. 

[Camb. Texts with Notes. 
Oedipus Tyrannus, Electra. 

Oedipus Coloneus. Ajax. 

Antigone. 
TACITUS : Germania and Agricola. Edited by the late rev. p. frost, 
late Fellow of St. John's College, Cambridge. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

[Gram. Sch. Class. 

— The Germania. Edited, with Introduction and Notes, by R. f. davis, 

M.A. Fcap. 8vo, IS. (td. 
TERENCE. With Notes, critical and explanatory, by wilhelm wagner, 
PH.D. yd edition. Post 8vo, 7^. 6rf. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— Edited by wilhelm wagner, ph.d. 4 vols. Fcap. 8vo, is. td. each. 

[Camb. Texts with Notes 
Andria, I Hautontimonimenos. 

Adelphi. | Phonnio. 



George Bell & Sons' 



THUCYDIDES, Book VI. By T. w. DOUGAN, M.A., Fellow of St. John's 
College, Cambridge; Professor of Latin in Queen's College, Belfast. 
Edited with English notes. Post 8vo, 2s. [Pub. Sch. Ser. 

— The History of the Peloponnesian War. With Notes and a careful 

Collation of the two Cambridge Manuscripts, and of the Aldine and 
Juntine Editions. By the late RICHARD shilleto, M.A., Fellow of 
St. Peter's College, Cambridge. 8vo. Book I. 6s. 6d. Book II. Sj. 6d. 
VIRGIL. By JOHN CONINGTON, M.A., and henry nettleship, late Corpus 
Professor of Latin at Oxford. 8vo. [Bib. Class. 

Vol. I. The Bucolics and Georgics. Sth edition, revised by F. haver- 
FIELD, M.A. los. bd. 

Vol. II. The Aeneid, Books I. -VI. 4/A edition. lor. dd. 

Vol. III. The Aeneid, Books VII. -XII. -yd edition, \os.fid. 

— Abridged from professor conington's Edition, by the rev. j. g. shep- 

PARD, D.C.L., H. NETTLESHIP, late Corpus Professor of Latin at the 
University of Oxford, and w. WAGNER, PH.D. 2 vols. Fcap. 8vo, 
4J. td. each. [Gram. Sch. Class. 

Vol. I. Bucolics, Georgics, and Aeneid, Books I. -IV. 
Vol. II. Aeneid, Books V. -XII. 
Also the Bucolics and Georgics, in one vol. 3^. 
Or in 9 separate volumes (Grammar School Classics, with Notes at foot of page), 
price is. 6d. each. 



Bucolics. 

Georgics, I. and II. 
Georgics, III. and IV. 
Aeneid, I. and II. 
Aeneid. III. and IV. 
Or in 12 separate volumes (Cambridge Texts with Notes at end), price 
\s. 6d. each. 



Aeneid, V. and VI. 
Aeneid, VII. and VIIL 
Aeneid, IX. and X. 
Aeneid, XL and XII. 



Bucolics. 

Georgics, I, and II. 
Georgics, III. and IV. 
Aeneid, I. and II. 
Aeneid, III. and IV. 
Aeneid, V. and VI. (price 2s.) 



Aeneid, VII. 
Aeneid, VIIL 
Aeneid, IX. 
Aeneid, X. 
Aeneid, XI. 
Aeneid, XII. 



— Aeneid, Book I. conington's Edition abridged. With Vocabulary 

by W. F. R. SHILLETO, M.A. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. [Lower Form Ser. 

XENOPHON : Anabasis. With Life, Itinerary, Index, and three Maps. 

Edited by the late J. F. macjiichael. Revised edition. Fcap. 8vo, 

y. 6d, [Gram. Sch. Class. 

Or in 4 separate volumes, price is, 6d. each. 

Book I. (with Life, Introduction, Itinerary, and three Maps) — Books 

II. and III.— Books IV. and V.— Books VI. and VII. 

— Anabasis, macmichael's Edition, revised by j. e. melhuish, m.a.. 

Assistant Master of St. Paul's School. In 6 volumes, fcap. 8vo. With 
Life, Itinerary, and Map to each volume, is. 6d. each. 

[Camb, Texts with Notes. 
Book L— Books II. and III.— Book IV.— Book V.— Book VI.— 
Book VII. 

— Cyropaedia. Edited by G. m. gorham, m.a., late Fellow of Trinity 

College, Cambridge. New edition. Fcap. 8vo, 3J. f>d. 

[Gram. Sch. Class. 



Educational Catalogue. 



XKiJOPHON^continueii. 

Also Books I. and II., is. 6d. ; Books V. and VI., is. 6ri. 

— Memorabilia. Edited by percival frost, m.a., late Fellow of St. 

John's College, Cambridge. Fcap. 8vo, y. [Gram. Sck. Class. 

— Hellenica. Book I. Edited by L. d. dowdall, m.a., b.d. Fcap. 8vo, 

2s. [Camb. Texts with Notes. 

— Hellenica. Book II. By L. D. dowdall, m.a., b.d. Fcap. 8vo, 2j. 

\Camb. Texts with Notes, 

TEXTS. 

AESCHYLUS. Ex novissima recensione F. A. paley, a.m., ll.d. Fcap. 
8vo, 2s. [Camb. Texts. 

CAESAR De Bello Gallico. Recognovit G. long, a.m. Fcap. 8vo, 
IS. 6d. [Camb. Texts. 

CATULLUS. A New Text, with Critical Notes and an Introduction, by 
J. P. postgate, m.a., litt.d.. Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge, 
Professor of Comparative Philology at the University of London. Wide 
fcap. 8vo, 3 J. 

CICERO De Senectute et de Amicitia, et Epistolae Selectae. Recen- 
suit G. LONG, A.M. Fcap. 8vo, is. dd. [Camb. Texts. 

CICERONIS Orationes in Verrem. Ex recensione G. long, a.m. 
Fcap. 8vo, 2,s. 6d. [Camb. Texts. 

CORPUS POETARUM LATINORUM, a se aliisque denuo recogni- 
torum et brevi lectionum vaiietate instructorum, edidit JOHANNES PERCI- 
val postgate. Tom. I. — Ennius, Lucretius, Catullus, Horatius, Vergilius, 
Tibullus, Propertius, Ovidius. Recogniti a L. MULLER, H. A. J. MUNRO, 
H. NETTLESHIP, J. GOW, E. HILLER, G. M. EDWARDS, A. PALMER, G. A. 
DAVIES, S. G. OWEN, A. E. HOUSMAN, JOH. P. POSTGATE. Large post 

4to, 21S. net. Also in 2 Parts, sewed, gs. each, net. 
^*^ To be completed in 4 parts, making 2 volumes. 
CORPUS POETARUM LATINORUM. Edited by walker. Con- 
taining : — Catullus, Lucretius, Virgilius, Tibullus, Propertius, Ovidius, 
Horatius, Phaedtus, Lucanus, Persius, Juvenalis, Martialis, Sulpicia, 
Statins, Silius Italicus, Valerius Flaccus, Calpumius Siculus, Ausonius, 
and Claudianus. I vol. 8vo, cloth, l8.r. 
EURIPIDES. Ex recensione F. A. paley, a.m., ll,d. 3 vols. Fcap. 
8vo, 2J. each. [Camb. Texts. 

Vol. I. — Rhesus — Medea — Hippoljrtus — Alcestis — Heraclidae — Sup- 
plices — Troades. 

Vol. 1 1. — Ion — Helena — Andromache — Electra — Bacchae — Hecuba. 
Vol. III. — Hercules Furens — Fhoenissae — Orestes — Iphigeniain Tauris 
— Iphigeniain Aulide — Cyclops. 
HERODOTUS. Recensuit j. G. blakesley, s.t.b. 2 vols. Fcap. 8vo, 
2s. 6d. each. [Camb. Texts. 

HOMERI ILIAS I.-XII. Ex novissima recensione F. A. paley, a.m., 
ll.d. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. [Camb. Texts. 

HORATIUS. Ex recensione A. J. macleane, A.M. Fcap. 8vo, u. 6</. 

[Camb. Texts. 
JUVENAL ET PERSIUS. Ex recensione A. j. macleane, a.m. 
Fcap. 8vo, IS. (sd. [Camb. Texts." 

LUCRETIUS. Recognovit H. A. j. munro, a.m. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 

[Ca>nb. Texts. 
A 2 



lo George Bell <2f Sons' 



P. OVIDI NASONIS OPERA ex Corpore Poetanim Latinomm a 
JOH. PKRCIVAL POSTGATE edito, separatim typis impressa. 3 vols. 2s. each. 

PROPERTIUS. Sex. Propertii Elegiarum Libti IV. recensuit A. 
PALMER, collegii sacrosanctae et individuae Trinitatis juxta Dublinum 
Socius. Fcap. 8vo, y. 6d. 

— Sexti Properti Carmina. Recognovit jOH. percival postgate, 
Large post 4to, boards, y. 6d. net. 

SALLUSTI CRISPI CATILINA ET JUGURTHA, Recognovit 

G. LONG, A.M. Fcap. 8vo, IS. 6d. [Camb. Texts. 

SOPHOCLES. Ex recensione F. A. paley, a,m., ll.d. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

[Camd. Texts. 
TERENTI COMOEDIAE. gul. wagner relegit et emendavit. Fcap. 

8vo, 2s. [Camb. Texts. 

THUCYDIDES. Recensuit j. G. Donaldson, s.t.p. 2 vols. Fcap. 

8vo, 2s. each. [Camb. Texts. 

VERGILIUS. Ex recensione J. conington, a.m. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 

[Camb. Texts. 
XENOPHONTIS EXPEDITIO CYRI. Recensuit j. F. macmichael. 

A.B. Fcap. 8vo, If. 61/. [Camb. Texts. 

TRANSLATIONS. 
AESCHYLUS, The Tragedies of. Translated into English verse by 
ANNA svrANVtricK. ^th edition revised. Small post 8vo, 5^. 

— The Tragedies of. Literally translated into Prose, by T. A. Buckley, b. a. 

Small post 8vo, 3^. 6d. 

— The Tragedies of. Translated by Walter headlam, m.a.. Fellow of 

King's College, Cambridge. [Preparing. 

ANTONINUS (M. Aurelius), The Thoughts of. Translated by 

GEORGE LONG, M.A. Revised edition. Small post 8vo, 3J. 6d. 
Fine paper edition on handmade paper. Pott 8vo, (>s. 
APOLLONIUS RHODIUS. The Argonautica. Translated by E. P. 

COLERIDGE, B.A. Small post 8vo, $s. 
AMMIANUS MARCELLINUS. History of Rome during the 
Reigns of Constantius, Julian, Jovianus, Valentinian, and Valens. Trans- 
lated by prof. c. d. yonge, m.a. With a complete Index. Small post 
8vo, 7^. 6d. 
ARISTOPHANES, The Comedies of. Literally translated by W. J. 
HICKIE. IVith Portrait. 2 vols. Small post 8vo, 5J. each. 

Vol. I. — Acharnians, Knights, Clouds, Wasps, Peace, and Birds. 

Vol. II. — Lysistrata, Tbesmophoriazusae, Frogs, Ecclesiazusae, and 
Plutus. 

— The Acharnians. Translated by w. H. Covington, b.a. With Memoir 

and Introduction. Crown 8vo, sewed, is. 

— The Plutus. Translatedby M. T. QUINN, M.A., Lond. Cr. 8vo, sewed, u. 
ARISTOTLE on the Athenian Constitution. Translated, with Notes 

and Introduction, by F. G. kenyon, m.a.. Fellow of Magdalen College, 
Oxford. Pott 8vo, printed on handmade paper, ztid edition, ^s. 6d. 

— History of Animals. Translated by richard cresswell, m.a. Sinall 

post 8vo, 5^. 
' — Organon : or, Logical Treatises, and the Introduction of Porphyry. With 
Notes, Analysis, Introduction, and Index, by the REV. o. F. OWEN, M.A. 
2 vols. Small post 8vo, 3J, 6d. each. 



Educational Catalogue. 1 1 

ARI STOTLE— <:o«rf»»«rf. 

— Rhetoric and Poetics. Literally Translated, with Hobbes' Analysis, &c., 

by T. BUCKLEY, E.A. Small post 8vo, 5^. 

— Nicomachean Ethics. Literally Translated, with Notes, an Analytical 

Introduction, &c., by the Venerable archdeacon bfowne, late Classical 
Professor of King's College. Small post 8vo, 5j. 

— Politics and Economics. Translated, with Notes, Analyses, and 

Index, by E. WALFORD, M.A., and an Introductory Essay and a Life by 
DR. GILLIES. Small post 8vo, 5j. 

— Metaphysics. Literally Translated, with Notes, Analysis, &c., by the 

REV. JOHN H. m'mahon, m.a. Small post Svo, 5j. 

ARRIAN. Anabasis of Alexander, together with the Indica. Trans- 
lated by E. J. CHINNOCK, M.A., LL.D.' With Introduction, Notes, Maps, 
and Plans. Small post Svo, 5^. 

CAESAR. Commentaries on the Gallic and Civil Wars, with the Supple- 
mentary Books attributed to Hirtius, including the complete Alexandrian, 
African, and Spanish Wars. Translated by w. A. m'devitte, b.a. 
Small post Svo, ^s. 

— Gallic War. Translated by w. A. m'devitte, b.a. 2 vols., with Memoir 

and Map. Cr. Svo, sewed. Books I. to IV., Books V. to VII., \s. each. 
CALPURNIUS SICULUS, The Eclogues of. The Latin Text, with 

English Translation by E. J. L. SCOTT, M.A. Crown Svo, 3^. 6d. 
CATULLUS, TIBULLUS, and the Vigil of Venus. Prose Translation. 

Small post Svo, t,s. 
CICERO, The Orations of. Translated by prof. c. d. yonge, m.a. 

With Index. 4 vols. Small post Svo, 5^. each. 

— On Oratory and Orators. With Letters to Quintus and Brutus. Trans- 

lated by the rev. j. s. watson, m.a. Small post Svo, 5^. 

— On the Nature of the Gods. Divination, Fate, Laws, a Republic, 

Consulship. Translated by prof. c. d, yonge, m.a., and Francis 
Barham. Small post Svo, $■?■ 

— Academics, De Finibus, and Tusculan Questions. By prof. c. d. 

YONGE, M.A. Small post Svo, 5j. 

— Offices ; or, Moral Duties. Cato Major, an Essay on Old Age ; Laelius, 

an Essay on Friendship ; Scipio's Dream ; Paradoxes ; Letter to Quintus 
on Magistrates. Translated by C. R. EDMONDS. With Portrait, y. dd. 

— Old Age and Friendship. Translated, with Memoir and Notes, by 

G. H. WELLS, M.A. Crown Svo, sewed, i.f. 
'DEMOSTHENES, The Orationsof. Translated, withNotes, Arguments, 
a Chronological Abstract, Appendices, and Index, by c. rann KENNEDY. 
5 vols. Small post Svo. 

Vol. I. — The Olynthiacs, Philippics, y. 6d. 

Vol. II. — On the Crown and on the Embassy. 5.;. 

Vol. III. — Against Leptines, Midias, Androtion, and Aristocrates. JJ. 

Vols. IV. and V. — Private and Miscellaneous Orations. 5^. each. 

— On the Crown. Translated by c. rann Kennedy. Crown Svo, 

sewed, is. 
DIOGENES LAERTIUS. Translated by prof. C. d. yonge, m.a. 

Small post Svo, $s. 
EPICTETUS, The Discourses of. With the Encheiridion and 

Fragments. Translated by GEORGE LONG, M.A. Small post Svo, Ji. 
Fine Paper Edition, 2 vols. Pott Svo, iQr. 6d. 



1 2 George Bell & Sons' 

EURIPIDES. A Prose Translation, from the Text of Paley. By 

E. P. COLERIDGE, B.A. 2 vols., 5^-. each. 

Vol. I. — Rhesus, Medea, Hippolytus, Alcestis, Heraclidse, Supplices, 
Troades, Ion, Helena. 

Vol. II. — Andromache, Electra, Bacchae, Hecuba, Hercules Furens, 
Phoenissae, Orestes, Iphigenia in Tauris, Iphigenia in Aulis, Cyclops. 

«*» The plays separately (except Rhesus, Helena, Electra, Iphigenia in 
Aulis, and Cyclops). Crown 8vo, sewed, is. each. 

— Translated from the Text ofDindorf. By T. A. BUCKLEY, B.A. 2 vols. 

Small post 8vo, 5j. each. 
GREEK ANTHOLOGY. Translated by George burges, m.a. Small 

post 8vo, 5^. 
HERODOTUS. Translated by the rev. henry CARY, M.A. Small post 

8vo, 3j. 6d. 

— Analysis and Summary of. By j. T. wheeler. Small post 8vo, 5^. 
HESIOD, CALLIMACHUS, and THEOGNIS. Translated by the 

REV. J. BANKS, M.A. Small post 8vo, 5j. 
HOMER. The Iliad. Translated by T. A. Buckley, b.a. Small post 
8vo, 5.V. 

— The Odyssey, Hymns, Epigrams, and Battle of the Frogs and 

Mice. Translated by T. A. Buckley, b.a. Small post 8vo, $s. 

— The Iliad. Books I. -IV. Translated into English Hexameter Verse, 

by HENRY SMITH WRIGHT, B.A., late Scholar of Trmity College, Cam- 
bridge. Medium 8vo, 5^. 
HORACE. A New Prose Translation by A. Hamilton bryce, ll.d. 
With Memoir and Introduction. Small post 8vo. 3^. 6d. 
Also in 4 vols. Crown 8vo, sewed, u. each. 
Odes. I. and II. Satires. 

Odes. III. and IV., with Epistles and Ars Poetica. 
the Carmen Seculare 
and Epodes. 

— Translated by Smart. Revised edition. By T. A. Buckley, b.a. Small 

post 8vo, 3^. 6d. 

— The Odes and Carmen Saeculare. Translated into English Verse by 

the late John conington, m.a., Corpus Professor of Latin in the 
University of Oxford, nth edition. Fcap. 8vo. y. 6d. 

— The Satires and Epistles. Translated into English Verse by PROF. 

JOHN conington, M.A. ith edition. Fcap. 8vo, 3J. 6d. 

— Odes and Epodes. Translated by SIR Stephen e. de verb, bart. 

'^rd edition, enlarged. Imperial i6mo. 7j. (3d. net. 
ISOCRATES, The Orations of. Translated by J. H. freese, m.a., late 

Fellow of St. John's College, Cambridge, with Introductions and Notes. 

Vol. I. Small post 8vo, ^s. 
JUSTIN, CORNELIUS NEPOS, and EUTROPIUS. Translated 

by the rev. j. s. watson, m.a. Small post 8vo, <s. 
JUVENAL, PERSIUS, SULPICIA, and LUCILIUS, Translated 

by L. EVANS, m.a. Small post 8vo, Sf . 
LIVY. The History of Rome. Translated by dr. spillan, c. edmokds, 

and others. 4 vols. Small post 8vo, 5j. each. 

— Books I., II., III., IV. A Revised Translation by J. h. freese, M.A., 

late Fellow of St. John's College, Cambridge. With Memoir, and Maps. 
4 vols. Crown 8vo, sewed, i^. each. 



Educational Catalogue. 1 3 

LIVY — continued. 

— Book V. and Book VI. A Revised Translation by e . s. Weymouth, 

M.A., Lond. With Memoir, and Maps. Crown 8vo, sewed, is. each. 

— Book IX. Translated by Francis storr, b.a. With Memoir. Crown 

8vo, sewed, \s. 
LUCAN. The Pharsalia. Translated into Prose by H. T. riley, m.a. 
Small post 8vo, 5^. 

— The Pharsalia. Book I. Translated by Frederick conway, m.a. 

With Memoir and Introduction. Crown 8vo, sewed, \s. 
LUCIAN'S Dialogues of the Gods, of the Sea-Gods, and of the 

Dead. Translated by HOWARD Williams, m.a. Small post 8vo, 5^. 
LUCRETIUS. TranslatedbytheREV. J. S.WATSON, M.A. Small post 8vo,5j. 

— Literally trans, by the late H. A. J. MUNRO, m.a. i^h edition. Demy 8vo, 6j. 
MARTIAL'S Epigrams, complete. Literally translated into Prose, with 

the addition of Verse Translations selected from the Works of English 
Poets, and other sources. Small post 8vo, Is. dd. 
OVID, The Works of. Translated. 3 vols. Small post 8vo, 5^. each. 

Vol. I. — Fasti, Tristia, Pontic Epistles, Ibis, and Halieuticon. 

Vol. II. — Metamorphoses. With hrontispiece. 

Vol. III. — Ileroides, Amours, Art of Love, Remedy of Love, and 
Minor Pieces. With Frontispiece. 

— Fasti. Translated by H. T. riley, m.a. 3 vols Crown 8vo, sewed, \s. each. 

— Tristla. Translated by H. T. riley, m.a. Crown 8vo, sewed, \s. 
PINDAR. Translated by dawson w. turner. Small post 8vo, S^f. 
PLATO. Gorgias. Translated by the late E. M. cope, m.a., Fellow 

of Trinity College, ind edition. 8vo, 7^. 

— Philebus. Translated by F. A. paley, M.A., ll.d. Small 8vo, 41. 

— Theaetetus. Translated by F. A. paley, m.a., ll.d. Small 8vo, 4J. 

— The Works of. Translated, with Introduction and Notes. 6 vols. Small 

post 8vo, 5^. each. 

Vol. I. — The Apology of Socrates — Crito — Phaedo — Gorgias — Prota- 
goras — Phaedrus — Theaetetus — Eutyphron — Lysis. Translated by the 
REV. H. cary. 

Vol. II.— The Republic— Timaeus—Critias. Trans, by HENRY DAVis. 

Vol. III. — Meno — Euthydemus — The Sophist — Statesman — Cratylus 
— Parmenides — The Banquet. Translated by G. burges. 

Vol. IV. — Philebus — Charmides — Laches — Menexenus — Hippias — Ion 
— The Two Alcibiades— Theages — Rivals — Hipparchus — Minos — Cli- 
topho — Epistles. Translated by G. surges. 

Vol. v.— The Laws. Translated by G. burges. 

Vol. VI. — The Doubtful Works. Edited by G. surges. With General 
Index to the six volumes. 

Apology, Crito, Phaedo, and Protagoras. Translated by the rev. h, 

cary. Small post 8vo, sewed, \s., cloth, \s. 6d. 

Dialogues. A Summary and Analysis of. With Analytical Index, giving 

references to the Greek text of modern editions and to the above transla- 
tions. By A. DAY, LL.D. Small post 8vo, 5J. 
PLAUTUS, The Comedies of. Translated by H. t. riley, M. A. 2 vols. 
Small post 8vo, 5^-. each. 

Vol. I. — Trinummus — Miles Gloriosus — Bacchides — Stichus — Pseudolus 
Menaechraei — Aulularia — Captivi — Asinaria — Curculio. 

Vol. II. — Amphitryon — Rudens — Mercator — Cistellaria— Truculentus 
Persa Casina — Poenulus — Epidicus — Mostellaria — Fragments. 



14 George Bell & Sons' 

PI^AUTVS— continued. 

— Trinummus, Menaechmei, Aulularia, and Captivi. Translated 

by H. T. RILEY, M.A. Small post 8vo, sewed, is., cloth, is. dd. 
PLINY. The Letters of Pliny the Younger. Melmoth's Translation, 

revised, by the rev. f. c. t. bosanquet, m.a. Small post 8vo, 5^. 
PLUTARCH. Lives. Translated by A. Stewart, m.a., late Fellow of 

Trinity College, Cambridge, and GEORGE long, m.a. 4 vols. Small post 

8vo, y. dd. each. 

— Morals. Theosophical Essays. Translated by c. w. king, m.a., late 

Fellow of Trinity College, Cambridge. Small post 8vo, 5-^ ■ 

— Morals. Ethical Essays. Translated by the rev. a. r. shilleto, m.a. 

Small post 8vo, 5J. 

PROPERTIUS. Translated by rev. p. j. f. gantillon, m.a., and 
accompanied by Poetical Versions, from various sources. Sm. post 8vo, 31. dd. 

PRUDENTIUS, Translations from. A Selection from his Works, with 
a Translation into English Verse, and an Introduction and Notes, by 
FRANCIS ST. JOHN THACKERAY, M.A., F.S.A., Vicar of Mapledurham, 
formerly Fellow of Lincoln College, Oxford, and Assistant-Master at 
Eton. Wide post 8vo, "Js. 6d. 

QUINTILIAN : Institutes of Oratory, or. Education of an Orator. 
Trans, by the rev. j. s. watson, m.a. 2 vols. Small post Svo, 5j. each. 

SALLUST, FLORUS, and VELLEIUS PATERCULUS. Trans- 
lated by J. s. WATSON, m.a. Small post Svo, $5. 

SENECA: On Benefits. Translated by A. stewart, m.a., late Fellow 
of Trinity College, Cambridge. Small post Svo, 3^. 6d. 

— Minor Essays and On Clemency. Translated by A. STEWART, m.a. 

Small post Svo, $s. 
SOPHOCLES. Translated, with Memoir, Notes, etc., by E. p. Coleridge, 
B.A. Small post Svo, 5^. 

Or the plays separately, crown Svo, sewed. Is. each. 

— The Tragedies of. The Oxford Translation, with Notes, Arguments, 

and Introduction. Small post Svo, ^s. 

— The Dramas of. Rendered in English Verse, Dramatic and Lyric, by 

SIR GEORGE YOUNG, BART., M.A., formerly Fellow of Trinity College, 
Cambridge. Svo, izs. 6d. 

— The CEdipus Tyrannus. Translated into English Prose. By PROF. B. 

H. KENNEDY. Crown Svo, in paper wrapper, is. 
SUETONIUS. Lives of the Twelve Caesars and Lives of the 

Grammarians. Thomson's revised Translation, by T. forester. Small 

post Svo, 5j. 
TACITUS, The Works of. Translated, with Notes and Index 2 vols. 

Small post Svo, Sj. each. 
Vol. I.— The Annals. 

Vol. II. — The History, Germania, Agricola, Oratory, and Index. 
TERENCE and PHAEDRUS. Translated by H. T. riley, m.a. Small 

post Svo, 5j. 
THEOCRITUS, BION, MOSCHUS, and TYRTAEUS. Translated 

bv the REV. J. BANKS, M.A. Small post Svo, 5.;. 
THEOCRITUS. Translated into English Verse by c. s. calverley, 

M. A., late Fellow of Christ's College, Cambridge. New edition. Crown 

Svo, Sj. 



Educational Catalogue. 1 5 

THUCYDIDES. The Peloponnesian War. Translated by the rev. H. 

DALE. WUh Portrait. 2 vols., 3^. 6a?. each. 
— Analysis and Summary of. By j. t. wheeler. Small post 8vo, Jj. 
VIRGIL. Translated by A. HAMILTON bryce, LL.D. With Memoir and 

Introduction. Small post 8vo, 3^. ()d. 

Also in 6 vols. Crown 8vo, sewed, is. each. 



GeoTgics. 
Bucolics. 
iEneid I.-III. 



iEneidlV.-VI. 

.ffilneid VII.-IX. 

jEneid X.-XII. 



XENOPHON. The Works of. In 3 vols. Small post 8vo, Ji. each. 

Vol. I The Anabasis, and Memorabilia. Translated by the rev. j. s. 

WATSON, M.A. With a Geographical Commentary, by W. F. ainsworth, 
F.S.A., F.R.G.S., etc. 

Vol. II. — Cyropaedia and Hellenics. Translated by the rev. j. s. 
WATSON, M.A., and the REV. H. DALE. 

Vol. III. — The Minor Works. Translated by the REV. J. S. 
WATSON, M.A. 

— Anabasis. Translated by the REV. j. s. WATSON, M.A. With Memoir 

and Map. 3 vols. 

— Hellenics. Books I. and II. Translated by the REV. H. DALE, M.A. 

With Memoir. 



SABRINAE COROLLA In Hortulis Regiae Scholae Salopiensis con 
texuerunt tres viri floribus legendis. 4/^ edition, revised and re-arrangea. 
By the late benjamin hall Kennedy, d.d., Regius Professor of Greek 
at the University of Cambridge. Large post 8vo, los. 6d. 

SERTUM CARTHUSIANUM Floribus trium Seculorum Contextum. 
Cura gulielmi haig brown, Scholae Carthusianae Archididascali. 
Demy 8vo, 5^-. 

TRANSLATIONS into English and Latin. By c. s. calverley, m.a., 
late Fellow of Christ's College, Cambridge. 4/A edition. Crown 8vo, S-f. 

TRANSLATIONS from and into the Latin, Greek and English. By 
R. C. jebb, litt.d., M.P., Regius Professor of Greek in the University of 
Cambridge, H. JACKSON, M.A., utt. d., Fellows of Trinity College, Cam- 
bridge, and w. e. currey, m.a., formerly Fellow of Trinity College, 
Cambridge. Crown 8vo. yd edition, ^s. 



GRAMMAR AND COMPOSITION. 

BADDELEY. Auxilia Latina. A Series of Progressive Latin Exercises. 
By M. J. b. baddeley, m.a. Fcap. 8vo. Part I, Accidence. sM 
edition. 2s. Part II. 5/,^ edition, is. Key to Part 11. zs. 6d. 

BAIRD. Greek Verbs. A Catalogue of Verbs, Irregular and Defective ; 
their leading formations, tenses in use, and dialectic inflexions, with a 
copious Appendix, containing Paradigms for conjugation, Rules for 
formation of tenses, &c., &c By J. S. baird, t.c.d. New edition, re- 
vised. 2s. 6d. 

Homeric Dialect. Its Leading Forms and Peculiarities. By J. s. BAIRD, 

T.C.D. JVew edition, revised. By the rev. w. gunion Rutherford. 
m.a., LL.D., Head Master at Westminster School, is. 



1 8 George Bell & Sons' 



STEDMAN (A. M. lA.)—conHnued. 

— Greek Vocabularies for Repetition, znd edition. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. 

— Greek Testament Selections for the Use of Schools, yl tdition. 

With Introduction, Notes, and Vocabulary. Fcap. 8vo, 2J-. dd. 

— Greek Examination Papers in Miscellaneous Grammar and Idioms. 

yd edition, zs. 6d. Key (for Tutors only), 6^-. net. 
THACKERAY. Anthologia Graeca. A Selection of Greek Poetry, 
with Notes. By rev. F. ST. JOHN Thackeray. 6th edition. i6tao,^.6d. 

— Anthologia Latina. A Selection of Latin Poetry, from Naevius to 

Boethius, with Notes. By rev. f. st. JOHN THACKERAY. Ith edition. 
i6nio, 4J-. 6d. 

— Hints and Cautions on Attic Greek Prose Composition. Crown 

8vo, 3j. 6d. 

— Exercises on the Irregular and Defective Greek Verbs, is. 6d. 
WELLS. Tales for Latin Prose Composition. With Notes and 

Vocabulary. By G. H. WELLS, M.A., Assistant Master at Merchant 
Taylor's School. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 



HISTORY, GEOGRAPHY, AND REFERENCE BOOKS, 

ETC. 

TEUFFEL'S History of Roman Literature, ^t/t edition, revised by 
BR. SCHWABE, translated by professor g. c. w. warr, m.a., King's 
College, London. Medium 8vo. 2 vols. 30^. Vol. I. (The Republican 
Period), \%s. Vol. II. (The Imperial Period), 15^. 

KEIGHTLEY'S Mythology of Ancient Greece and Italy. 4/A edition, 
revised by the late leonhard schmitz, ph.d., ll.d., Classical Examiner 
to the University of London. With 12 Plates. Small post 8vo, 5^. 

DONALDSON'S Theatre of the Greeks, loth edition. Small post 8vo, 

DICTIONARY OF LATIN AND GREEK QUOTATIONS; in- 
cluding Proverbs, Maxims, Mottoes, Law Terms and Phrases. With all 
the Quantities marked, and English Translations. With Index Verborum. 
Small post 8vo, 5-f. 

PAUSANIAS' Description of Greece. Newly translated, with Notes 
and Index, by A. R. shilleto, m.a. 2 vols. Small post 8vo, ^s. each. 

STRABO'S Geography. Translated by w. falconer, m.a., and H. c. 
HAMILTON. 3 vols. Small post 8vo, 5^. each. 

AN ATLAS OF CLASSICAL GEOGRAPHY. By w. hughes and 
G. LONG, M.A. Containing Ten selected Maps. Imp. 8vo, 3^. 

AN ATLAS OF CLASSICAL GEOGRAPHY. Twenty-four Maps 
by v\f. HUGHES and GEORGE LONG, M.A. With coloured outlines. 
Imperial 8vo, ts. 

AN ATLAS OF CLASSICAL GEOGRAPHY. Twenty-two large 
Coloured Maps. With a complete Index. Imp. 8vo, chiefly engraved by 
the Messrs. Walker. Is. 6d, 



Educational Catalogtte. 1 9 

MATHEMATICS. 

ARITHMETIC AND ALGEBRA. 

BARRACLOUGH (T.). The Eclipse Mental Arithmetic. By titus 
BARRACLOUGH, Board School, Halifax. Standards I., II., and III., 
sewed, dd. ; Standards II., III., and IV., sewed, td. net ; Book III., 
Part A, sewed, /\d. ; Book III., Part B, cloth, \s. ftd. 

BEARD (W. S.). Graduated Exercises in Addition (Simple and Com- 
pound). For Candidates for Commercial Certificates and Civil Service 
appointments. By w. s. beard, f.r.g.s., Head Master of the Modern 
School, Fareham. yd edition. Fcap. 4to, \s. 

— See PENDLEBURY, 

ELSEE (C). Arithmetic. By the rev. c. elsee, m.a., late Fellow of 
St. John's College, Cambridge, Senior Mathematical Master at Rugby 
School, x^th edition. Fcap. 8vo, 3^. 6i/. [Camb. School and College Texts. 

— Algebra. By the rev. c. elsee, m.a. 'ith edition. Fcap. 8vo, 4^. 

\Camb. S. and C. Texts. 

FILIPOWSKI (H. E.). Anti-Logarithms, A Table of. By H. E. 
FILIPOWSKI. yd edition. 8vo, 15J. 

GOUDIE (W. P.). See Watson. 

HATHORNTHWAITE (J. T.). Elementary Algebra for Indian 
Schools. By J. T. hathornthwaite, m.a., Principal and Professor 
of Mathematics at Elphinstone College, Bombay. Crown 8vo, 2s. 

MACMICHAEL (W. F.) and PROWDE SMITH (R.). Algebra. 
A Progressive Course of Examples. By the REV. w. F. macmichael, 
and R. PROWDE SMITH, m.a. yh edition. Fcap. 8vo, 3^. 6d. With 
answers, ^. dd. \Camb. S. and C. Texts. 

MATHEWS (G. B.). Theory of Numbers. An account of the Theories 
of Congruencies and of Arithmetical Forms. By G. B. m athews, m.a.. 
Professor of Mathematics in the University College of North Wales. 
Part I. Demy 8vo, \2s. 

MOORE (B. T.). Elementary Treatise on Mensuration. By B. T. 
MOORE, M.A., Fellow of Pembroke College, Cambridge. 2,nd edition, 
revised. 3J. dd. 

PENDLEBURY (C). Arithmetic. With Examination Papers and 
8,000 Examples. By CHARLES pendlebury, m.a., f.r.a.s.. Senior 
Mathematical Master of St. Paul's. \Uh edition. Crown 8vo. Com- 
plete, with or without Answers, 4J. iid. In Two Parts, with or without 
Answers, 2,s. 6d. each. 

Key to Part II. 2nd edition. "Js. 6d. net. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

— Examples in Arithmetic. Extracted from Pendlebury's Aritlunetic. 

With or without Answers. 10th edition. Crown 8vo, 3^., or in Two Parts, 
IS. 6d. and 2s. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

— Examination Papers in Arithmetic. Consisting of 140 papers, each 

containing 7 questions ; and a collection of 357 more difficult problems. 

tfh edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. Key, for Tutors only, 5^. net. 
PENDLEBURY (C.) and TAIT (T. S.). Arithmetic for Indian 

Schools. By c. pendlebury, m.a. and T. s. tait, m.a., b.sc. 

Principal of Baroda College. 2nd edit. Cr. 8vo, 3^. [Camb. Math. Ser. 
PENDLEBURY (C.) and BEARD (W. S.). Commercial Arithmetic. 

By c. PENDLEBURY, M.A., and w. s. BEAiiD, F.R.G.S. 2nd edition. Crown 

8vo. 2i. (>d. 



20 George Bell & Sons' 

PENDLEBURY (C.) and BEARD CW .S.)— continued. 

— Elementary Arithmetic, yd edition. Ciown %vo, is, 6d. 

— Shilling Arithmetic. By CHARLES PENDLEBURY, M.A.,and W. S. BEARD, 

F.R.G.s. Crown 8vo, is. 

— Graduated Arithmetic, for Junior and Private Schools. In Seven Parts, 

in stiff canvas covers. Parts I., II., and III., ■^d. each; Paris IV., V., 
and VI., 41/. each ; Part VII., 6d. Answers to Parts I. and II., ^. ; Parts 
III. -VI I., 4^. each. 

— Arithmetic for the Standards. Standards I., II., III., sewed, 2d. each, 

cloth, ^d. each; IV., V., VI., sewed, 3(/. each, cloth, 40'. each; VII., 
cloth, 6d. Answers to I. and II., 4d., III. -VII., 4d. each. 

— Long Tots and Cross Tots, Simple and Compound. Paper cover, 2d., 

cloth, 30'. Answers, ^d. 

POPE (L. J.). Lessons in Elementary Algebra. By L. J. pope, b.A. 
(Lond. ), Assistant Master at the Oratory School, Birmingham. First Series, 
up to and including Simple Equations and Problems. Crown 8vo, is. 6d. 

PROWDE SMITH (R.). See Macmichael. 

SHAW (S. J. D.). Arithmetic Papers. Set in the Cambridge Higher 
Local Examination, from June, 1869, to June, 1887, inclusive, reprinted 
by permission of the Syndicate. By s. J D. shaw. Mathematical 
Lecturer of Newnham College. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. ; Key, 4s. 6d. net. 

TAIT (T. S.). See Pendlebury. 

WATSON (J.) and GOUDIE (W. P.). Arithmetic. A Progressive 
Course of Examples. With Answers. By J. watson, m.a.. Corpus 
Christi College, Cambridge, formerly Senior Mathematical Master of the 
Ordnance School, Carshalton. ytA edition, revised and enlarged. By w. 
p. GOUDIE, B.A. Lond. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. bd. [Ca7iib. S. and C. Texts. 

WHITWORTH (W. A.). Choice and Chance. An Elementary 
Treatise on Permutations, Combinations, and Probability, with 640 Exer- 
cises and Answers. By w. A. whitworth, m.a., late Fellow of St. 
John's College, Cambridge, /[th edition, revised and enlarged. Crown 
8vo, ts. \Camb. Math. Ser. 

— DCC. Exercises, including Hints for the Solution of all the Questions in 

"Choice and Chance." Crown 8vo, 6s. [Cami. Math. Ser. 

WRIGLEY (A.) Arithmetic. By A. wrigley, M.A., St. John's College. 

Fcap. 8vo, 3f. dd. [Camb. S. and C. Texts. 

BOOK-KEEPING. 

CRELLIN (P.). A New^ Manual of Book-keeping, combining the 
Theoiy and i?ractice, with Specimens of a set of Books. By Phillip 
CRELLIN, Chartered Accountant. Crown 8vo, 3^. td. 

— Book-keeping for Teachers and Pupils. Cr. 8vo, is. 6d. Key, 2s. net. 
FOSTER (B. W.). Double Entry Elucidated. By B. w. foster. 

l/^th edition. Fcap. 410, 3^. (>d. 
MEDHURST (J. T.). Book-keeping by Double Entry, Theoretical 
and Practical, including a Society of Arts Examination Paper fully 
worked out. By J. T. medhurst, a.k.c, f.s.s.. Fellow of the Society of 
Accountants and Auditors (incorporated), and Lecturer at the City of 
London College. Crown 8vo, l.f. 

— Examination Papers in Book-keeping. Compiled by john t. med- 

hurst, A.K.C, F.S.S. 4ih edition. Crown 8vo, 3^. Key, 2s. 6d. net. 
THOMSON (A. W.). A Text-Book of the Principles and Practice 
of Book-keeping. By PROFESSOtt A. w. Thomson, b.sc. Royal 
Agricultural College, Cirencester. 2nd edition, revised. Crown 8vo, 51. 



Educational Catalogue. 2 1 



GEOMETRY AND EUCLID. 
BESANT (W. H.). Conic Sections treated Geometrically. By w. 
H. BESANT, sc.D., F.R.S., Fellow of St. John's College, Cambridge. 
^th edition. Crown 8vo, 4^. dd. Key, <-,$. net. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

— Elementary Conies. Being the First Eight Chapters of the above. By 

W. H. BESANT, SC.D., F.K.S. Crown 8vo, 2J-. (id. [Camd. Math. Ser. 

BRASSE (J.). Ttie Enunciations and Figures of Euclid, prepared for 
Students in Geometry. By the UEV. j. brasse, d.d. New edition. 
Fcap. 8vo, \s. Without the Figures, bd. 

DEIGHTON (H.). Euclid. Books I.-VI., and part of Book XI., newly 
translated from the Greek Text, with Supplementary Propositions, 
Chapters on Modern Geometry, and numerous Exercises. By HORACE 
DEIGHTON, M.A., Head Master of Harrison College, Barbados. yh 
edition. 4r. 6(/., or Books I.-IV., 3J. Books V. -XL, 2J. 6t/. Key, 5j. net. 

{Camb. Math. Ser. 
Also issued in parts : — Book I., \s. ; Books T. and H., is. 6d. ; Books 
I. -in., 2J. (,d. ; Books III. and IV., is. 6d. 

DEIGHTON (H.) and EMTAGE (O.). An Introduction to Euclid, 
including Euclid I. 1-26, with explanations and numerous easy exercises. 
By HORACE DEIGHTON, M.A., and o. EMTAGE, B.A., Assistant Master of 
Harrison College. Crown 8vo, is. 6d. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

DIXON (E. T.). The Foundations of Geometry. By edward t. 
DIXON, late Royal Artillery. Demy 8vo, 6s. 

MASON (C. P.). Euclid. The First Two Books Explained to Beginners. 
By c. P. MASON, b.a. 2nd edition. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

McDowell (J.) Exercises on Euclid and in Modern Geometry, con- 
taining Applications of the Principles and Processes of Modern Pure 
Geometry. By J. Mcdowell, M.A., f.r.a.s. ^th edition. 6s. 

[Camb. Math. Ser. 

TAYLOR (C). An Introduction to the Ancient and Modern Geo- 
metry of Conies, with Historical Notes and Prolegomena. 15^. 

— The Elementary Geometry of Conies. By c. Taylor, d.d., Master of 

St, John's College, ^th ed., revised. Cr. 8vo, 4J. 6d. [Camb. Math. Ser. 
WEBB (R.). The Definitions of Euclid. With Explanations and 

Exercises, and an AppSndix of Exercises on the First Book, by R. webb, 

M.A. Crown 8vo, is. 6d. 
WILLIS (H. G.). Geometrical Conic Sections. An Elementary 

Treatise. By H. G. Willis, m.a., Clare College, Cambridge, Assistant 

Master of Manchester Grammar School. Crown 8vo, Sj. [Camb. Math. Ser, 

ANALYTICAL GEOMETRY, ETC. 

ALDIS (W. S.). Solid Geometry, An Elementary Treatise on. By w. 
s. ALDIS, M.A. sfh edition, revised. Crown 8vo,5j. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

BAKER (W. M.). Examples in Analytical Conies for Beginners. 
By w. M. BAKER, M.A., Formerly Scholar of Queen's College, Cam- 
bridge ; Head Master of the Military and Civil Department at Cheltenham 
College. Crown 8vo, is. 6d. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

BESANT (W. H.). Notes on Roulettes and Glissettes. By w. h. 
BESANT, sc.D., F.R.s. 2nd edition, enlarged. Crown Svo. Jj. 

[Camb. Math. Ser. 

CAYLEY (A.). Elliptic Functions, An Elementary Treatise on. By 
ARTHUR CAYLEY, Sadlerian Professor of Pure Mathematics in the Univer- 
sity of Cambridge. 2nd edition. Demy Svo. ip. 



22 George Bell & Sons 

TURNBULL(W. P.). Analytical Plane Geometry, An Introduction to. 
By w. P. TURNBULL, M.A., sometime Fellow of Trinity College. 8vo, I2J-. 

VYVYAN (T. G.). Analytical Geometry for Schools. By REV. T. 
VYVYAN, M.A., Fellow of Gonville and Caius College, and Mathematical 
Master of Charterhouse, dth edition. 8vo, 4J-. 61/. \Cainb. S. and C. Texts. 

— Analytical Geometry for Beginners. Part I. The Straight Line and 

Circle, 2nd edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

WHITWORTH (W. A.). Trilinear Co-ordinates, and other methods 
of Modern Analytical Geometry of Two Dimensions. By w. A. whit- 
worth, M.A., late Fellow of St. John's College, Cambridge. 8vo, l6s. 

TRIGONOMETRY. 

DYER (J. M.) and WHITCOMBE (R. H.). Elementary Trigono- 
metry. By J. M. DYER, M.A. (Senior Mathematical Scholar at Oxford), 
and REV. R. H. WHITCOMBE, Assistant Masters at Eton College. 2na 
edition. Crown 8vo, 4J. dd. \Camh. Math. Ser. 

PENDLEBURY (C). Elementary Trigonometry. By Charles 
PENDLEBURY, M.A., F.R.A.S., Senior Mathematical Master at St. Paul's 
School. 2nd edition. Crown 8vo, 4;. td. \Camb. Math. Ser. 

VYVYAN (T. G.). Introduction to Plane Trigonometry. By the 
REV. T. G. VYVYAN, M.A., Senior Mathematical Master of Charterhouse. 
yd edition, revised and augmented. Cr. 8vo, 3J. i>d, \Camb. Math. Ser, 

WARD (G. H.). Examination Papers in Trigonometry. By G. H. 
WARD, M. A., Assistant Master at St. Paul's School, yd edition. Crown 
8vo, 2J. td. Key, 5^. net. 

MECHANICS AND NATURAL PHILOSOPHY. 

ALDIS (W. S.). Geometrical Optics, An Elementary Treatise on. By 
w. s. ALDIS, M.A. $tk edition. Crown 8vo, 41. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

— An Introductory Treatise on Rigid Dynamics. Crown 8vo, +t. 

[Camb. Math. Ser. 

— Fresnel's Theory of Double Refraction, A Chapter on. 2nd edition, 

revised. 8vo, 2s, 
BASSET (A. B.). A Treatise on Hydrodynamics, with numerous 
Examples. By A. B. basset, m.a.,.f.r.s.. Trinity College, Cambridge. 
Demy 8vo. VoL I., price 10s. bd. ; Vol. II., \2s. 6d. 

— An Elementary Treatise on Hydrodynamics and Sound. Demy 

8vo, ^s. dd, 

— A Treatise on Physical Optics. Demy 8vo, i6s. 
BESANT(W. H.). Elementary Hydrostatics. By w. H. besant, SCD., 

F.R.s. I'jth edition. Cr. 8vo, 4J. 6^. Solutions, 5^. net. {Camb. Math. Ser. 

— Hydromechanics, A Treatise on. Part I. Hydrostatics. $th edition, 

revised and enlarged. Crown 8vo, Sj'. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

— A Treatise on Dynamics. 2nd ed. Cr. 8vo, los. 6d. [Camb. Math. Ser. 
CHALLIS (PROF.). Pure and Applied Calculation. By the late 

REV. J. CHALLIS, M.A., F.R.S., &c. Demy 8vo, 15J. 

— Physics, The Mathematical Principle of. Demy 8vo, Ji. 

— Lectures on Practical Astronomy. Demy 8vo, ioj. 

EVANS (J. H.) and MAIN (P. T.). Newton's Principia, The First 
Three • Sections of, with an Appendix; and the Ninth and Eleventh 
Sections. By j. H. evans, m.a., St. John's College. The sth edition, 
edited by P. T. MAIN, M.A., Lecturer and Fellow of St. John's College. 
Fcap. 8vo, ^. [Camb. S. and C. Texts, 



Educational Catalogue. 23 

GALLATLY (W.). Elementary Physics, Examples and Examination 
Papers in. Statics, Dynamics, Hydrostatics, Heat, Light, Chemistry, 
Electricity, London Matriculation, Cambridge B.A., Edinburgh, Glasgow, 
South Kensington, Cambridge Junior and Senior Papers, and Answers. 
By w. GALLATLY, M.A., Pembroke College, Cambridge, Assistant 
Examiner, London University. Crown 8vo, 4J. {^Camb. Math. Ser. 

GARNETT (W.). Elementary Dynamics for the use of Colleges and 
Schools. By William garnett, m.a., d.cl.. Fellow of St. John's 
College, late Principal of the Durham ColI?^e of Science, Newcastle-upon- 
Tyne, ^th edition, revised. Crown 8vo, ds. \Camb. Math. Ser. 

— Heat, An Elementary Treatise on. tth edition, revised. Crown 8vo, 

4J. td. \Camb. Math. Ser. 

GOODWIN (H.). Statics. By H. Goodwin, d.d., late Bishop of 

Carlisle. 2nd edition. Fcap. 8vo, 3^. [Camb. S. and C. Texts. 

HOROBIN (J. C). Elementary Mechanics. Stage L IL and IIL, 

IS. 6d. each. By j. c. horobin, m.a., Principal of Homerton New 

College, Cambridge. 

— Theoretical Mechanics, Division I. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

*»* This book covers the ground of the Elementary StE^e of Division I. 
of Subject VL of the " Science Directory," and is intended for the 
examination of the Science and Art Department. 

JESSOP (C. M.). The Elements of Applied Mathematics. In- 
cluding Kinetics, Statics and Hydrostatics. By c. M. jessop, m.a., late 
Fellow of Clare College, Cambridge, Lecturer "in Mathematics in the 
Durham College of Science, Newcastle-on-Tyne. 2nd edition. Crown 
8vo, 4r. 6d. [Camb, Math. Ser. 

MAIN (P. T.). Plane Astronomy, An Introduction to. By P. T. main, 
m.a., Lecturer and Fellow of St. John's College. (>th edition, revised. 
Fcap. 8vo, 4r. [Camb. S. and C. Texts, 

PARKINSON (R. M.). Structural Mechanics. By r. m. Parkinson, 
ASSOC. M.T.c.B. Crown 8v6, 4J. 6d. 

PENDLEBURY (C). Lenses and Systems of Lenses, Treated after 
the Manner of Gauss. By CHARLES pendlebury, m.a., f.r.a.s.. Senior 
Mathematical Master of St. Paul's School, late Scholar of St. John's 
College, Cambridge. Demy 8vo, ^s. 

STEELE (R. E.). Natural Science Examination Papers. By 
R. e, STEELE, M.A., F.C.S., Chief Natural Science Master, Bradford 
Grammar School. Crown 8vo. Part I., Inorganic Chemistry, 2s. td. 
Part II., Physics (Sound, Light, Heat, Magnetism, Electricity), 2s. td. 

[School Exam. Series. 

WALTON (W.). Theoretical Mechanics, Problems in. By w. Wal- 
ton, M.A., Fellow and Assistant Tutor of Trinity Hall, IJathematical 
Lecturer at Magdalene College, yd edition, revised. Demy 8vo, 16s. 

— Elementary Mechanics, Problems in. 2nd edition. Crown 8vo, 6s. 

[Camb. Math. Ser. 



DAVIS (J. F.). Army Mathematical Papers. Being Ten Years' 
Woolwich and Sandhurst Preliminary Papers. Edited, with Ansvfers, by 
J. F. DAVIS, D.LIT., M.A. Lond. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

DYER (J. M.) and PROWDE SMITH (R.). Mathematical Ex- 
amples, A Collection of Examples in Arithmetic, Algebra, Trigono- 
metry, Mensuration, Theory of Equations, Analytical Geometry, Statics, 
Dynamics with Answers, &c. For Army and Indian Civil Ser-vipe 



24 George Bell & Sons' 



Candidates. By J. M. DYER, M.A., Assistant Master, Eton College 
(Senior Mathematical Scliolar at Oxfdrd), and R. pkowde smith, m.a. 
Crown 8vo, 6s. [Camb. Math. Ser. 

GOOD\WIN (H.). Problems and Examples, adapted to "Goodwin's 
Elementary Course of Mathematics." By T. G. VYVYAN, M.A. yd 
edition. 8vo, 5J-. ; Solutions, yd edition, 8vo, gj. 

SMALLEY (G. R.). A Compendium of Facts and Formulae in 
Pure Mathematics and Natural Philosophy. By G. k. smalley, 
F.R.A.S. New edition, revised and enlarged. By J. MCDOWELL, M.A., 
F.R.A.s. Fcap. 8vo, zs. 

WRIGLEY (A.). Collection of Examples and Problems in Arith- 
metic, Algebra, Geometiy, Logarithms, Trigonometry, Conic Sections, 
Mechanics, &c., with Answers and Occasional Hints. By the rev. a. 
WRIGLEY. loth edition, 20lh thousand. Demy 8vo, 3^. 6d. 

A Key. By J. c. platts, m.a., and the rev. a. wrigley. 2nd edition. 
Demy 8vo, 5^. net. 

MODERN LANGUAGES. 

ENGLISH. 

ADAMS (E.). The Elements of the English Language. By ernest 

ADAMS, PH.D. 2.(ith edition. Revised by J. F. DAVIS, D.LIT., kLA. 

(lond.). Post Svo; 4J. dd. 
— The Rudiments of English Grammar and Analysis. By ERNEST 

ADAMS, PH.D. igrt thousand. Fcap. Svo, is. 
ALFORD (DEAN). The Queen's English : A Manual of Idiom and 

Usage. By the late henry alford, d.d.. Dean of Canterbury, dlh 

edition. Small post Svo. Sewed, \s. ; cloth, is. 6d. 
ASCHAM'S Scholemaster. Edited by professor J. E. B. MAYOR. Small 

post Svo, sewed, is. 
BELL'S ENGLISH CLASSICS. A New Series, Edited for use in 

Schools, with Introduction and Notes. Crown Svo. 
BROWNING, Selections from. Edited by k. ryland, M.A. 2.T 6d. 

— Strafford. Edited by e. h, hickey. With Introduction by s. k. Gardiner, 

I.L.D. 2^. 6d. 
BURKE'S Letters on a Regicide Peace. I. and 11. Edi-.ed by h. u. kekne, 

M.A., CLE. 3f. ; sewed, 2j. 
BYRON'S Childe Harold. Edited by h. g. keenb, m.a., c.i e., Author of "A 

Manual of French Literature," etc. 3^. 6d. Also Cantos I. and II. sewed, i.t. qd. 

Cantos III. and IV. sewed, is, gd. 

— Siege of Corinth. Edited by r. hordern, late Director of Public Instruction in 

Burma, is. 6cf. : sewed, is. 
CARLYLE'S " Hero as Man of Letters." Edited, with Introduction, by 
MARK HUNTER, M.A., Principal of Coipibatore College, qs. ; sewed, is. 6d. 

— " Hero as Divinity." By the same editor. 2j. ; sewed, i^. 6(^. 
CHAUCER'S MINOR POEMS, Selections from. Edited by j. n. 

lul.DERBECK, B.A,, Professor of English Literature, Presidency College, Madras. 

^nd edition. 2j. &d. ; sewed, is. t)d. 
DE QUINCEY'S Revolt of the Tartars and The English Mail-Coach. 

Edited by Cecil m. barrow, m.a.. Principal of Victoria College, Palghat, and 

MARK HUNTER, B.A., Principal of Coimbatore College. 3^. ; sewed, 2j. 
*„* Revolt of the Tartars, separately, sewed, is. 6d. 

— Opium Eater Edited by mark hunter, b.a. 4^. 6d. ; sewed, 3J. 6d. 
GOLDSMITH'S Good-Natured Man and She Stoops to Conquer. Edited 

by K. deighton. Each, ^s. cloth ; is. 6d. sewed. The two plays together, sewed, 
2j. 6d. 

— Traveller and Deserted Village. Edited by the rev. a. e. woodward, m.a. 

Cloth, 3J., or separately, sewed, lod. each. 



Edttcational Catalogue, 



25 



BELL'S ENGLISH C\^^^^\Q,^— continued. 

IRVING'S Sketch Book. EditeJ by r. g. oxENHAivr, ni.A. Sewed, \s. 6ti. 
JOHNSON'S Life of Addison. Edited by f. ryland. Author of " The Students* 
Handbook of Psychology," etc. 2s. 6ff. 

— Life of Swift. Edited by f. ryland, m.a. zs. 

— Life of Pope. Edited by f. ryland, M.a. 9.s. 6d. 
■*#* The Lives of Swift and Pope, together, sewed, 2.s. 6d. 

— Life of Milton. Edited by k. ryland, m.a. 2s. 6d. 

— Life of Dryden. Edited by r. ryland, m.a. 2.9. 6d. 
*n* The Lives of Milton and Dryden, togellier. sewed, -zs. 6d. 

— Lives of Prior and Congreve. Edited by r. ryland, m.a. 24'- 
LAMB'S Essays. Selected and Edited by ic. dkighton. 3^. ; sewed, 2s. 
LONGFELLOW, Selections from, including Evangeline. Edited by m. t. 

QUiNN, M.A., Principal and Professor of English Language and Literature, 
Pachaiyappa's College, Madras. 2J. Sd. ; sewed, ts. <^d. 
*^f* Evangeline, separately, sewed, i.f. 2^. 
MACAULAY'S Lays of Ancient Rome. Edited by p, hordern. 2s. 6d. : 
sewed, is. gd. 

— Essay on Clive. Edited by cecil barrow, m.a. 2J. ; sewed, is. 6d. 
MASSINGER'S A New Way to Pay Old Debts. Edited by k. deighton. 

3^. ; sewed, 2s. 
MILTON'S Paradise Lost. Books I H. and IV. Edited by r.g. oxeniiam, m.a., 
Principal of Elphinstone College, Bombay. 2s. ; sewed, is. 6d., or separately, 
sewed, lod. each. 

— Paradise Regained. Edited by k. deighton. zs. 6d. ; sewed, is. qd. 
POPE'S Essay on Man. Edited by f. ryland, m.a. is. 6d. 

POPE, Selections from. Containing Essay on Criticism, Rape of the Lock, 
Temple of Fame, Windsor Forest. Edited by k. deighton. 2S.6d. ; sewed, is. gd. 

SCOTT'S Lady of the Lake. Edited by the rev. a. e. woodwaud, m.a. Cloth, 
^s. 6d. The Six Cantos separately, sewed, 8^. each. 

SHAKESPEARE'S Julius Caesar. Edited by t. duffbarnett, b.a. (Lond.V 2s. 

— Merchant of Venice. Edited by t. dciff barnett, b.a. (Lond.). 2s, 

— Tempest. Edited by t. duff barnett, b.a. (Lond.). 2^. 
WORDSWORTH'S Excursion. Book I. Edited, with Introduction and Notes, 

by M. t. QUINN, m.a. Sewed, i^. ^d. 

Others to follow. 



BELL'S READING BOOKS. 

Infants. 
Infant's Primer. -1,(1. 
Tot and the Cat. dd. 
The Old Boathouse. dd. 
The Cat and the Hen. dd. 

Standard I. 
School Primer, dd. 
The Two Parrots, dd. 
The Three Monkeys, dl. 
The New-born Lamb. dd. 
The Blind Boy. dd. 

Standard II. 
The Lost Pigs. dd. 
Story of a Cat. dd. 
Queen Bee and Busy Bee. 612'. 
Gulls' Crag. dd. 

Standard III. 
Great Deeds in English History. 

IV. 

Adventures of a Donkey. \s. 



Post 8vo, cloth, illustrated. 
Grimm's Tales. \s. 
Great Englishmen. \s. 
Andersen's Tales. \s. 
Life of Columbus. \s. 

Standard IV. 
Uncle Tom's Cabin, ij. 
Swiss Family Robinson. \s. 
Great Englishwomen. \s. 
Great Scotsmen. \s. 
Edgeworth's Tales. \s. 
Gatty's Parables from Nature, is. 
Scott's Talisman, is. 

Standard V. 
Dickens' Oliver Twist, is. ' 
Dickens' Little Nell. is. 
Masterman Ready. i.v. 
Marryat's Poor Jack. \s. 
Arabian Nights, is. 
Gulliver's Travels, it. 
LyricalPoetry for Boys & jirls. \s. 
Vicar of Wakefield, is. 



26 



George Bell & Sons 



BELL'S READING "BOOVi^— continued. 



Standards VI. and VII. 
Lamb's Tales from Shakespeare. 

\s. 
Robinson Crusoe. \s. 



Tales of the Coast. \s. 
Settlers in Canada. \s. 
Southey's Life of Nelson, is. 
Sir Roger de Coverley. \s. 



BELL'S GEOGRAPHICAL READERS. 

WARD, M.A. ( Worcester College, Oxford). 



By M. J. BARRINGTON- 



The Child's Geography. Illus- 
trated. Stiff paper cover, 6fl?. 

The Map and the Compass. 
(Standard I. ) Illustrated. Cloth, 



The Round World. (StandavdII.) 

Illustrated. Cloth, \od. 
About England. (Standard III.) 
With Illustrations and Coloured 
Map. Cloth, \s. 4^. 
BELL'S ANIMAL LIFE READERS. A Series of Reading Books 
for the Standards, designed to inculcate the humane treatment of animals. 
Edited by edith carrington and ERNEST bell. Illustrated by 
HARRISON WEIR and others. * ^* Full Prospectus on application. 
BROWNlNG{R.). HandbooktoRobertBrowning's Works by MRS. Suther- 
land ORR. dth edition. Revised, with a bibliography. Fcap. 8vo. 6s. 
EDWARDS (F.). Examples for Analysis in Verse and Prose. Selected 

and arranged by F. Edwards. New edition. Fcap. 8vo, cloth, \s. 
GOLDSMITH. The Deserted Village. Edited, with Notes and Life, 

by C. P. MASON, B.A., F.c.P. 4M edition. Crown 8vo, \s. 
HANDBOOKS OF ENGLISH LITERATURE. Edited by J. w. 
HALES, M.A., formerly Clark Lecturer in English Literature at Trinity 
College, Cambridge, Professor of English Literature at King's College, 
London. Crown 8vo, 3J. 6d. each. 
The Age of Milton. (1632 — 1660). By the rev. j. H. b. mastbrman, 

M.A., with Introduction, etc., by J. bass mullinger, m.a. 
The Age of Dryden, (i66o — 1700). By r. garnett, ll.d., c.b. 

2,nd edition. 
The Age of Pope. (1700 — 1744). By john dennis. 2nd edition. 
The Age of Wordsworth. (1798 — 1832). By prof. c. h. herford, 

LITT.D. 2nd edition. 
The Age of Tennyson. (1830 — 1870). By prof, hugh walker. 
2nd edition. 

In preparation. 
The Age of Alfred. By h. frank heath, ph.d. 
The Age of Chaucer. By professor hales. 
The Age of Shakespeare. By professor hales. 
The Age of Johnson. By thomas seccombe. 
H AZLITT ( W. ). Lectures on the Literature of the Age of Elizabeth. 
Small post 8vo, sewed, \s. 

— Lectures on the English Poets. Small post 8vo, sewed, \s. 

— Lectures on the English Comic Writers. Small post 8vo, sewed, \s. 
LAMB (C). Specimens of English Dramatic Poets of the Time of 

Elizabeth. With Notes. Small post 8vo, 3^. (>d. 
MASON (C. P.). Grammars byC. P. mason, b.a., f.c.p.. Fellow of 
University College, London. 

— First Notions of Grammar for Young Learners. Fcap. 8vo. loy/j 

thousand. Cloth, \s, 

— First Steps in English Grammar, for Junior Classes. Demy i8nio. %r\ih 

thousand, is. 



Educational Catalogue. 2 7 

MASON (C. 'P.)—contimnd. 

— Outlines of English Grammar, for the Use of Junior Classes. igM 

edition, lo^jth thousand. Crown 8vo, 2s. 

— English Grammar; including the principles of Grammatical Analysis. 

38M edition, revised. 163rd thousand. Crown 8vo, green cloth, y. td. 

— A Shorter English Grammar, with copious and carefully graduated 

Exercises, based upon the author's English Grammar, wth edition. ^2nd 
thousand. Crown 8vo, brown cloth, 3^. 6d. 

— Practice and Help in the Analysis of Sentences. Price 2s. Cloth. 

— English Grammar Practice, consisting of the Exercises of the Shorter 

English Grammar published in aseparate form. 3rd edition. Crown 8vo, is. 

— Remarks on the Subjunctive and the so-called Potential Mood. 

6a?., sewn. 

— Blank Sheets Ruled and headed for Analysis, is. per dozen. 
MILTON : Paradise Lost. Books I., II., and III. Edited, with Notes 

on the Analysis and Parsing, and Explanatory Remarks, by c. P. MASON, 
B.A., F.c.p. Crown 8vo. is. each. 

— Paradise Lost. Books V. -VIII. With Notes for the Use of Schools. 

By C. M. LUMBY. 2J. 6(/. 

PRICE (A. C). Elements of Comparative Grammar and Philology. 
For Use in Schools. By A. c. price, m. a. , Assistant Master at Leeds 
Grammar School. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. 
SHAKESPEARE. Notes on Shakespeare's Plays. With Introduction, 
Summary, Notes (Etymological and Explanatory), Prosody, Grammatical 
Peculiarities, etc. By T. DUFF barnett, b.a. Lond., late Second 
Master in the Brighton Grammar School. Specially adapted for the Local 
and Preliminary Examinations. Crown 8vo, is. each. 

Midsummer Night's Dream. — Julius Caesar The Tempest. — 

Macbeth, — Henry V. — Hamlet Merchant of Venice. — King 

Richard II. — King John. — King Richard III. — King Lear. — 
Coriolanus. — Twelfth Night. — As You Like it. — Much Ado About 
Nothing. 

"The Notes are comprehensive and concht."— Educational Times. 

"Comprehensive, practical, and reWahXe." -^Schoolmaster. 

— Hints for Shakespeare-Study. Exemplifiedinan AnalyticalStudyof Jtiliiis 

Ceesar, By MARY grafton moberly. 2nd edition. Crown 8vo, sewed, ij'. 

— Coleridge's Lectures and Notes on Shakespeare and other English 

Poets. Edited by T. ashe, b.a. Small post 8vo, 3^. 6(/. 

— Shakespeare's Dramatic Art. The History and Character of Shake- 

speare's Plays. By DR. Hermann ulrici. Translated by l. dora 
SCHMITZ. 2 vols, small post 8vo, 3^. dd. each. 

— William Shakespeare. A Literary Biography. By KARL elze, PH.D., 

LL.D. Translated by L. DORA schmitz. Small post 8vo, 5^. 

— Hazlitt's Lectures on the Characters of Shakespeare's Plays. Small 

post 8vo, \s. 

— &« BELL'S ENGLISH CLASSICS. 

SKEAT (W. W.). Questions for Examinations ill English Litera- 
ture. With a Preface containing brief hints on the study of English. 
Arranged by REV. w. w. skeat, litt.d., Elrington and Bosworth Professor 
of Anglo-Saxon in the University of Cambridge, yd edit. Cr. 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

SMITH (C. J.) . Synonyms and Antonyms of the English Language. 
Collected and Contrasted by the Ven. c. J. SMITH, M.A. 2nd edition, 
revised. Small post 8vo, 5J. 



2 8 George Bell & Sons' 

SMITH (C. I.)— continued. 

— Synonyms Discriminated. A Dictionary of Synonymous Words in the 

English Language. Illustrated with Quotations from Standard Writers. 
By the late ven. c. j. smith, m.a. With the Author's latest Corrections 
and Additions, edited by rev. h. i'ercy smith, m.a., of Balliol College, 
Oxford, Vicar of Great Barton, Suffolk. 4M edition.. Demy 8vo, 14J. 

SMITHbON (D. J.). Elocution and the Dramatic Art. By david j. 
SMITHSON, formerly Lecturer on Elocution at the University of St. 
Andrews, and also at the Royal Polytechnic Institution, London. New 
edition, revised by charles reeve taylor, m.a., ll.b.. Lecturer in 
Public Reading and Speaking in King's College, London. Crown 8vo, 
pp. xvi-586, 3^. dd. 

TEN BRINK'S Early English Literature. Vol. I. (to Wiclif). Trans- 
lated into English by Horace m. Kennedy, Professor of German Literature 
in the Brooklyn Collegiate Institute. Small post 8vo, 3J. td. 

— Vol. II. (Wiclif, Chaucer, Earliest Drama, Renaissance). Translated by 

W. CLARKE ROBINSON, PH.D. Small post 8vo, 3.f. 6(/. 

— Vol. III. (to the Death of Surrey). Edited by professor Alois brandl. 

Translated by L. dora schmitz. Small post 8vo, y. 6d. 

— Lectures on Shakespeare. Translated by JULIA franklin. Small 

post 8vo, 3^. 6d. 
TENNYSON (LORD). A Handbook to the Works of Alfred Lord 

Tennyson. By morton luce. 2nd edition. Fcap. 8vo. 6s. 
THOMSON : Spring. Edited by c. P. mason, b.a., f.c.p. With Life. 

2nd edition. Crown 8vo, is. 

— Winter. Edited by c. p. mason, b.a., f.c.p. WithLife. Crown 8vo, ij-. 
TOVEY (REV. D. C). Reviews and Essays in English Literature, 

By the rev. duncan c. tovey, m.a., Rector of Worplesdon, Clark 
Lecturer at Trinity College, Cambridge. Crown 8vo, 5^. net. 

WEBSTER'S INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY of the English 
Language. Including Scientific, Technical, and Biblical Words and 
Terms, with their Significations, Pronunciations, Alternative Spellings, 
Derivations, Synonyms, and numerous illustrative Quotations, with various 
valuable literaiy Appendices, with 83 extra pages of Illustrations grouped 
and classified, rendering the work a Complete Literary and Scientific 
Reference-Book. New edition (1890). Thoroughly revised and en- 
larged under the supervision of noah porter, d.d., ll.d. i vol. (2,118 
pages, 3,500 woodcuts), 4to, cloth, 31J. 6d. ; half calf, £22s. ; halfrussia, 
£2 5j. ; calf, £2 8j. ; or in 2 vols., cloth, £1 ms. 

Prospectuses, with specimen ^ages, sent post free on application. 

WEBSTER'S BRIEF INTERNATIONAL DICTIONARY. A 
Pronouncing Dictionary of the English Language, abridged from Webster's 
International Dictionary. With a Treatise on Pronunciation, List of 
Prefixes and Suffixes, Rules for Spelling, a Pronouncing Vocabulary of 
Proper Names in History, Geography, and Mythology, and Tables of 
English and Indian Money, Weights, and Measures. With 564 pages 
and 800 Illustrations. Demy 8vo, y. 

WRIGHT (T.). Dictionary of Obsolete and Provincial English. 
Containing Words from the English Writers previous to the 19th century, 
which are no longer in use, or are not used in the same sense, and Words 
which are now used only in the Provincial Dialects. Compiled by THOMAS 
WRIGHT, M.A., r.s.A., etc. 2 vols., 5^. each. 



Educational Catalog7ie. 29 

FRENCH CLASS BOOKS. 

BOWER (A. M.), The Public Examination French Reader. With 
a Vocabulary to every extract, suitable for all Students who are preparing 
for a French Examination. By A. M. bower, f.r.g.s., late Master in 
University College School, etc. Cloth, y. dd. 

BARBIER (PAUL). A Graduated French Examination Course. 
By PAUL BARBIER, Lecturer in. the South Wales University College, etc. 
Crown 8vo, y, 

BARRERE (A.) Junior Graduated French Course. Affording Mate- 
rials for Translation, Grammar, and Conversation. By A. BARRJiRE, 
Professor R.M.A., Woolwich, is. dd. 

— Elements of French Grammar and First Steps in Idioms. With 

numerous Exercises and a Vocabulary. Being an Introduction to the 
Precis of Comparative French Grammar. Crown 8vo, 2s. 

— Precis of Comparative French Grammar and Idioms and Guide to 

Examinations. i,th edition, y. td. 

— Recits Militaires. From Valmy (1792) to the Siege of Paris (1870). 

With English Notes and Biographical Notices. Q,nd edition. Crown 8vo, y. 
CLAPIN (A. C). French Grammar for Public Schools. By the 
REV. A. c. CLAPIN, M.A., St. John's College, Cambridge, and Bachelier- 
^s-lettres of the University of France. Fcap. 8vo. Xi^h edition, is.td. 
Key to the Exercises, y. dd. net. 

— French Primer. Elementary French Grammar and Exercises for Junior 

Forms in Public and Preparatory Schools. Fcap. 8vo. nth edition, is. 

— Primer of French Philology. With Exercises for Public Schools. 

giA edition. Fcap. 8vo, is. 

— English Passages for Translation into French. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d, 

Key (for Tutors only), 41. net. 
DAVIS (J. F.) Army Examination Papers in French. Questions set 

at the Preliminary Examinations for Sandhurst and Woolwich, from Nov., 

1876, to June, 1890, with Vocabulary. By J. F. DAVis, D.LIT., M.A., 

Lond. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. 
DAVIS (J. F.) and THOMAS (F.). An Elementary French 

Reader. Compiled, with a Vocabulary, by J. F. davis, M.A., d.lit., 

and FERDINAND THOMAS, Assistant Examiners in the University of 

London. Crown 8vo, 2s. 
DELILLE'S GRADUATED FRENCH COURSE. 



The Beginner's own French Book, 
2s. Key, 2s. 

Easy French Poetry for Be- 
ginners. 2S. 

French Grammar. 3.?. Key, 3J. 



Repertoire des Prosateurs. -y. 6d. 
Modules de Poesie. 3j-. 6d. 
Manuel Etymologitjue. 2s. 6d. 
Synoptical Table of French 
Verbs. 6d. 



ESCLANGON (A.). The French Verb Newly Treated I'lJfWSaa^i 
Uniform, and Synthetic Method of its Conjugation. By A. Esclangon 
Examiner in the University of London. Small 4to, 5j. 

GASC (F. E. A.). First French Book; being a New, Practical, and 
Easy Method of Learning the Elements of the French Language. Jieset 
and thoroughly revised. 128M — i-yind thousand. Crown 8vo, ij. 

Second French Book ; being a Grammar and Exercise Book, on a new 

and practical plan, and intended as a sequel to the " First French Book." 
55M thousand. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. 



30 George Bell & Sons' 

GASC (F. E. A..)—c(mHmud. 

— Key to Fiistand Second French Books. Ith edition, Fcap. 8vo, y. 6d. net 

— French Fables, for Beginners, in Prose, with an Index of all the Words 

at the end of the work. 17M thousand. l2mo, is. 6d. 

— Select Fables of La Fontaine, igth thousand. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. 

— Histoires Amusantes et Instructives ; or, Selections of Complete 

Stories from the best French modern authors, who have written for the 
young. With English notes, l^th thousand. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 

— Practical Guide to Modern French Conversation, containing : — 

I. The most current and useful Phrases in Everyday Talk. II. Every- 
body's necessaiy Questions and Answers in Travel-Talk, l^th edition. 
Fcap. 8vo, ij. ()d. 

— French Poetry for the Young. With Notes, and preceded by a few 

plain Rules of French Prosody. S/A edition, revised. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. 

— French Prose Composition, Materials for. With copious footnotes, and 

hints for idiomatic renderings. 2yd thousand. Fcap. 8vo, 3^. 
Key. 2nd edition. 6s. net. 

— Prosateurs Contemporains ; or, Selections in Prose chiefly from con- 

temporary French literature. With notes, nth edition. i2mo, y. bd. 

— Le Petit Compagnon ; a French Talk-Book for Little Children. 14/A 

edition. l6mo, l^. 6d. 

— French and English Dictionary, with upwards of Fifteen Thousand 

new words, senses, &c., hitherto unpublished, ith edition, reset and con- 
siderably enlarged. In one vol. Large 8vo, cloth, 12s. 6d. In use at 
Harrow, Rugby, Shrewsbury, &c. 

— Dictionary of the French and English Languages. 1,124 pages, 

double columns. 8vo. 5j. 

— Pocket Dictionary of the French and English Languages ; for the every- 

day purposes of Travellers and Students. Containing more than Five 
Thousand modern and current words, senses, and idiomatic phrases 
and renderings, not found in any other dictionary of the two languages. 
/^leiv edition. ^*]th thousand. i6mo, cloth, 2J. dd. ■ 

GOSSET (A.). Manual of French Prosody for the use of English 
Students. By ARTHUR GOSSET, M.A., Fellow of New College, Oxford. 
Crown Svo, 3^^. 

GRANVILLE (W. E. M.). ABC Handbook of French Corre- 
spondence. Compiled by w. E. m. Granville. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

LE NOUVEAU TRESOR; designed to facilitate the Translation of 
English into French at Sight. ByM. E. s. iZth edition. Fcap. 8vo, is. 6d. 

STEDMAN (A. M. M.). French Examination Papers in Miscel- 
laneous Grammar and Idioms. Compiled by A. M. M. stedman, m.a. 

■- ..J^^ edition. Crown Svo, 2s. dd. A Key (for Tutors only), i>s. net. 

-^■^asy French Passages for Unseen Translation. 2nd edition. Fcap. 
Svo, IS. 6d. 

— Easy French Exercises on Elementary Syntax. Crown Svo, zs. 6d. 

— First French Lessons. Crown Svo, is. 

— French Vocabularies for Repetition. Fcap. Svo, is. 

— Steps to French. i8mo, Srf. 

WILLAN (J. N.). Scheme of French Verbs, with Verb Papers, is. 



Educational Catalogue. 



31 



FRENCH ANNOTATED EDITIONS. 
BALZAC. Ursule Mirouet. By honors db balzac. Edited, with 

Introduction and Notes, by jambs boielle, B.-is-L., Senior French 

Master, Dulwich College. 3^. 
CLARETIE. Pierrille. By jules CLARfiTiE. With 27 Illustrations. 

Edited, with Introduction and Note% by James boIellb, B.-es-L. zs. dd. 
DAUDET. La Belle Nivernaise. Histoire d'un vieux bateau et de son 

equipage. By alphonse daudet. Edited, with Introduction and 

Notes, by JAMES boielle, b.-^s-l. With Six Illustrations, is. 

FENELON. Aventures de T616maque. Edited by c. j. delille. 

a,th edition. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. td. 
GOMBERT'S FRENCH DRAMA. Re-edited, with Notes, by F. % 

GASC. Sewed, dd. each. 

MOLIERE, 



A. 



Le Misanthrope. 

L'Avare. 

Le Bourgeois Gentilhomme, 

Le Tartuffe. 

Le Malade Imaginaire. 

Les Femmes Savantes. 



Les Fourberies de Scapin. 
Les Precieuses Ridicules. 
L'Ecole des Femmes. 
L'Ecole des Maris. 
Le Medecin Malgr6 Lui. 



La Th^baide, ou Les Freres 

Ennemis. 
Andromaque. 
Les Plaideurs. 
Iphigenie. 



RACINE. 



Britannicus. 
Phfedre. 
Esther. 
Athalie. 



Le Cid. 
Horace. 



CORNEILLE. 

1 Cinna. 

I Polyeucte. 



VOLTAIRE.— Zaire. 
GREVILLE. Le Moulin Frappier By henry greville. Edited, 

with Introduction and Notes, by James boielle, B.-es-L. 3^-. 
HUGO. Bug Jargal. Edited, with Introduction and Notes, by James 

BOIELLE, B.-es-L. y. 

LA FONTAINE. Select Fables. Edited by F. e. a. gasc. \<)th 

thousand. Fcap. 8vo, \s. 6d. 
LAMARTINE. Le Tailleur de Pierres de Saint-Point. Edited with 

Notes by JAMES bo"ielle, B.-fe-L. 6ih thousand. Fcap. 8vo, is.6d. 
SAINTINE. Picciola. Edited by dr. dubuc. idth thousand. Fcap. 

8vo, IS. 6d. 
VOLTAIRE. Charles XII. Edited by L. direy. &th edition. Fcap. 

8vo, IS. 6d. 

GERMAN CLASS BOOKS. 

BUCHHEIM (DR. C. A.). German Prose Composition. Consist- 
ing of Selections from Modern English Writers. With grammatical notes, 
idiomatic renderings, and general introduction. ByC. A. BUCHHEIM, PH.D. 
Professor of the German Language and Literature in King's College, and 
Examiner in German to the London University. 1 5//; edition, enlarged and 
revised. With a list of subjects for original composition. Fcap. 8vo, 41, (>U, 



32 George Bell & Sons' 

BUCHHEIM (DR. C. A.)— continued. 

A Key to the ist and 2nd parts, ■^rd edition, y. net. To the 3rd and 
4th parts. 4J-. net. 

— First Book of German Prose. Being Parts I. and II. of the above. 

With Vocabulary by H. R. Fcap. 8vo, ij-. 6d. 
CLAPIN (A. C). A German Grammar for Public Schools. By the 
REV. A. c. CLAPIN, and F. HOLL-MULLER, Assistant Master at the Bruton 
Grammar School. 6th edition. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. dd. 

— A German Primer. With Exercises. 2nd edition. Fcap. 8vo, is. 
German. The Candidate's Vade Mecum. Five Hundred Easy Sentences 

and Idioms. By an Army Tutor. Cloth, \s. For Army Prelim. Exam. 
LANGE (F.). A Complete German Course for Use in Public Schools. 
By F. LANGE, PH.D., Professor R.M.A. Woolwich, Examiner in German 
to the College of Preceptors, London ; Examiner in German at the Victoria 
University, Manchester. Crown 8vo. 

— Concise German Grammar. With special reference to Phonology, 

Comparative Philology, English and German Equivalents and Idioms. 
Comprising Materials for Translation, Grammar, and Conversation. 
Elementary, 2s. ; Intermediate, 2j. ; Advanced, 3J. (>d. 

— Progressive German Examination Course. Comprising the Elements 

of German Grammar, an Historic Sketch of the Teutonic Languages, 
English and German Equivalents, Materials for Translation, Dictation, 
Extempore Conversation, and Complete Vocabularies. I. Elementary 
Course, 2J. II. Intermediate Course, 2s. III. Advanced Course. 
Second revised edition, is. dd. 

— Elementary German Reader. A Graduated Collection of Readings in 

Prose and Poetry. With English Notes and a Vocabulary. 4//^ 
edition, is. td, 

— Advanced German Reader. A Graduated Collection of Readings in 

Prose and Poetry. With English Notes by F. lange, PH.D., and 
J. F. DAVIS, D.LIT. 2nd edition. 3^. 
MORICH (R. J.). German Examination Papers in Miscellaneous 
Grammar and Idioms. By R. J. morich, Manchester Grammar School. 
2nd edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. A Key, for Tutors only. ^s. net. 
PHILLIPS (M. E.). Handbook of German Literature. By MARY 
E. PHILLIPS, LL.A. With Introduction by dr. a. weiss, Professor of 
German Literatui-e at R. M. A. Woolwich. Crown 8vo, 3J. 6d. 
■ STOCK (DR.). Wortfolge, or Rules and Exercises on the order of Words 
in German Sentences. With a Vocabulary. By the late FREDERICK 
STOCK, D.LIT., m.a. Fcap. 8vo, Is. bd. 



KLUGE'S Etymological Dictionary of the German Language. 
Translated by J. F. davis, d.lit. (Lond.). Crown 410, 7^-. dd. 

GERMAN ANNOTATED EDITIONS. 

AUERBACH (B.). Auf Wache. Novelle von berthold auerbach. 

Der Gefrorene Kuss. Novelle von otto roquette. Edited by a. a. 

macdonell, M.A. , PH.D. 2nd edition. Crown 8vo, 2j-. 
BENEDIX (J. R.). Doktor Wespe. Lustspiel in fiinf Aufziigen von 

JULIUS KODERICH BENEDIX. Edited by PROFESSOR F. LANGE, PH.D. 

Crown Svo, 2s. bd. 



Educational Catalogue. 33 

EBERS (G.). EineFrage. Idyll von georg ebers. Edited by p. store, 
B.A., Chief Master of Modern Subjects in Merchant Taylors' School. 
Crown 8vo, is. 

FREYTAG (G.). Die Journalisten. Lustspiel von gustav freytag. 
Edited by PROFESSOR F. lange,ph.d. ^hrevisededition. CrownSvo, 2^.60?. 

— SOLL UND HABEN. Roman von gustav freytag. Edited by 

w. hanby crump, m.a. Crown 8vo, 2s. (sd. 

GERMAN BALLADS from Uhland, Goethe, and Schiller. With Intro- 
ductions, Copious and Biographical Notices. Edited by c. L. Bielefeld. 
<ith edition. Fcap. 8vo, is. hd. 

GERMAN EPIC TALES IN PROSE. I. Die Nibelungen, von 
A. f. c. vilmar. II. Walther und Hildegund, von albert richter. 
Edited by KARL neuhaus, PH.D., the International College, Isleworth. 
Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

GOETHE. Hermann und Dorothea. With Introduction, Notes, and Argu- 
ments. By E. BELL, M.A., and E. wolfel. yd edition. Fcap. 8vo, u. 6a?. 

— Faust. Part I. German Text with Hayward's Prose Translation 

and Notes. Revised, with Introduction by c. A. buchheim, PH.D., 
Professor of German Language and Literature at King's College, London. 
Small post 8vo, 5-r. 

GUTZKOW (K.). Zopf und Schwert. Lustspiel von karl gutzkow. 
Edited by professor f. lange, ph.d. Crown 8vo, 2s. dd. 

HEY'S FABELN FUR KINDER. Illustrated by o. speckter. 
Edited, with an Introduction, Grammatical Summary, Words, and a com- 
plete Vocabulary, by professor f. langb, PH.D. Crown 8vo, \s. 6d. 

— The same. With a Phonetic Introduction, and Phonetic Transcription of 

the Text. By professor f. langb, ph.d. Crown 8vo, 2s. 
HEYSE (P.). Hans Lange. Schauspiel von PAUL heyse. Edited by 

A. A. MACDONELL, M.A., PH.D., Taylorian Teacher, Oxford University. 

Crown 8vo, 25. 
HOFFMANN (E. T. A.). Meister Martin, der Kiifner. Erzahlung 

von E. t. a. HOFFMANN. Edited by f. lange, ph.d. 2nd edition. 

Crown 8vo, is. td. 
MOSER (G. VON). Der Bibliothekar. Lustspiel von G. von moser. 

Edited by F. lange, ph.d. i^h edition. Crown 8vo, 2s. 
ROQUETTE (O.). .Sm Auerbach. 
SCHEFFEL (V. VON). Ekkehard. Erzahlung des zehnten Jahr- 

hunderts, von victor von scheffel. Abridged edition, with Intro- 
duction and Notes by HERMAN hager, ph.d.. Lecturer in the German 

Language and Literature in The Owens College, Victoria University, 

Manchester. Crown 8vo, 3^, 
SCHILLER'S Wallenstein. Complete Text, comprising the Weimar 

Prologue, Lager, Piccolomini, and Wallenstein's Tod. Edited by dr. 

BUCHHEIM, Professor of German in King's College, London. 6th edition. 

Fcap. 8vo, $s. Or the Lager and Piccolomini, 2J-. 6d. Wallenstein's 

Tod, 2s. td. 
Maid of Orleans. With English Notes by DR. wilhelm wagner. yd 

edition. Fcap. 8vo, \s. 6d. 
Maria Stuart. Edited by v. kastner, b.-4s-l.. Lecturer on French 

Language and Literature at Victoria University, Manchester, yd edition. 

Fcap. 8vo, IS, 6d, 



34 George Bell & Sons' 

ITALIAN. 
DANTE. The Infemo. A Literal Prose Translation, with the Text of the 
Original collated with the best editions, printed on the same page, and 
Explanatory Notes. By JOHN A. carlyle, m.d. With Portrait. 2,nd 
edition. Small post 8vo, e^s. 

— The Purgatorio. A Literal Prose Translation, with the Text of Bianchi 

printed on the same page, and Explanatory Notes. By w. s. dugdale. 
Small post 8vo, 5^. 

BELL'S MODERN TRANSLATIONS. 
A Series of Translations from Modern Languages, with Memoirs, 

Introductions, etc. Crown 8vo, is. each. 
DANTE. Inferno. Translated by the rev. h. F. car Y, M. A. 

— Purgatorio. Translated by the REV. H. F. cary, m.a. 

— Paradiso. Translated by the rev. h. f. cary, m.a. 
GOETHE. Egmont. Translated by anna swanwick. 

— Iphigenia in Tauris. Translated by ANNA swanwick. 

— Goetz von Berlichingen. Translated by sir Walter scott. 

— Hermann and Dorothea. Translated by B. A. BOWRING, c.B. 
HAUFF. The Caravan. Translated by s. mendel. 

— The Inn in the Spessart. Translated by s. mendel. 
LESSING. Laokoon. Translated by e. c. beasley. 

— Nathan the Wise. Translated by R. Dillon eoylan. 

— Minna von Bamhelm. Translated by ernest bell, m.a. 

V 

MOLIERE. The Misanthrope. Translated by c. heron wall. 

— The Doctor in Spite of Himself. (Le Medecin malgre lui.) Trans- 

lated by C. HERON wall. 

— Tartuffe ; or, The Impostor. Translated by c. heron wall. 

— The Miser. (L'Avare.) Translated by c. heron wall. 

— The Shopkeeper turned Gentleman. (Le Bourgeois Gentilhomme.) 

Translated by C. HERON WALL. 

— The Affected Ladies. (Las Precieuses Ridicules.) Translated by c. 

HERON WALL. 

— The Learned Women. (Les Femmes Savantes.) Translated by c. 

HERON WALL. 

— The Impostures of Scapin. Translated by c. heron wall. 
RACINE. Athalie. Translated by R. bruce boswell, m.a. 

— Esther. Translated by r. bruce boswell, m.a. 

— Iphigenia. Translated by R. bruce boswell, Ma. 

— Andromache. Translated by R. bruce boswell, m.a. 

— Britannicus. Translated by R. bruce boswell, m.a. 
SCHILLER. William Tell. Translated by sir Theodore martin, 

K.c. B., LL.D. New edition, entirely revised. 

— The Maid of Orleans. Translated by anna swanwick. 

— Mary Stuart. Translated by J. MELLISH. 

— Wallenstein's Camp and the Piccolomini. Translated by j. churchill 

and S. T. COLERIDGE. 

— The Death of Wallenstein. Translated by s. T. Coleridge. 

,*„ For other Translations of Modern Languages, see the Catalogue of 
Bohn's Libraries, which will be forwarded on application. 



Educational Catalogue. 35 



SCIENCE, TECHNOLOGY, AND ART. 

CHEMISTRY. 

COOKE (S.). First Principles of Chemistry. An Introduction to 
Modern Chemistry for Schools and Colleges. By SAMUEL cooke, M.A., 
B.E., Assoc. Mem. Inst. C. E., Principal of the College of Science, Poena. 
dih edition, revised. Crown 8vo, 2s. 6d. 

— The Student's Practical Chemistry. Test Tables for Qualitative 
Analysis, ^rd edition, revised and enlarged. Demy 8vo \s. 

STOCKHARDT (J. A.). Experimental Chemistry. Founded on the 
work of J. A. STOCKHARDT. A Handbook for the Study of Science by 
Simple Experiments. By C. w. heaton, f.i.c, f.c.s., Lecturer in 
Chemistry in the Medical School of Charing Cross Hospital, Examiner in 
Chemistry to the Royal College of Physicians, etc. Revised edition, ^s. 

BOTANY. 

GROOM (P.). Elementary Botany. By Percy groom, m.a. (Cantab, 
et Oxon.), F.L.S., Examiner in Botany to the University of Oxford. 
With 275 Illustrations. 2nd edition. Crown 8vo, y. td. 

HAYWARD (W. R.). The Botanist's Pocket-BooR. Containing in 
a tabulated form the chief characteristics of British Plants, with the 
botanical names, soil, or situation, colour, growth, and time of flowering 
of every plant, arranged under its own order ; with a, copious Index. 
By w. R. HAYWARD. ^th edition, revised. Fcap. 8vo, cloth limp, 4J. td. 

LONDON CATALOGUE of British Plants. Part I., containing the 
British Phaenogamia, Filices, Equisetaceae, Lycopodiacese, Selaginellacese, 
Marsileaceae, and Characeae. f)th edition. Demy 8vo, (>d. ; interleaved 
in limp cloth, is. Generic Index only, on card, 2d. 

MASSEE (G.). British Fungus-Flora. A Classified Text-Book of 
Mycology. By GEORGE massee. Author of "The Plant World." With 
numerous Illustrations. 4 vols, post 8vo, ^s. dd. each 

SOWERBY'S English Botany. Containing a Descripaon and Life-size 
Drawing of every British Plant. Edited and brought up to the present 
standard of scientific knowludge, by T. boswell (late syme), ll.d., 
F.L.s., etc. yd edition, entirely revised. With Descriptions of all the 
Species by the Editor, assisted by N. E. brown. 12 vols., with 1,937 
coloured plates, ^24 3^. in cloth, £2(i II J. in half-morocco, and £-^0 gj. 
in whole morocco. Al^o in 89 parts, 5J., except Part 89, containing 
an Index to the whole work, is. dd. 

^ A Supplement, to be completed in 8 or 9 parts, is now publishing. 
Parts* I., If., and III. ready, %s. each, or bound together, making 
Vol. XIII. of the complete work, 17^. 

TURNBULL (R.). Index of British Plants, according to the London 
Catalogue (Eighth Edition), including the Synonyms used by the principal 
authors, an Alphabetical List of English Names, etc. By ROBERT 
TURNBULL. Paper cover, 2s. 6d., cloth, 3^. 



38 George Bell & Sons' 



MUSIC. 
BANISTER (H. C). A Text Book of Music: By H. c. banister, 
Professor of Harmony and Composition at the R. A. of Music, at the Guild- 
hall School of Music, and at the Royal Normal Coll. and Acad, of Music 
for the Blind, i^ik edition. Fcap. 8vo. $s. 

This Manual contains chapters on Notation, Harmony, and Counterpoint, 
Modulation, Rhythm, Canon, Fugue, Voices, and Instruments ; together 
with exercises on Harmony, an Appendix of Examination Papers, and a 
copious Index and Glossary of Musical Terms. 

— Lectures on Musical Analysis. Embracing Sonata Form, Fugue, 

etc. Illustrated by the Works of the Classical Masters, znd edition, 
revised. Crown 8vo, ^s. (yd. 

— Interludes. Six Popular Lectures on Musical Subjects. By the late 

HENRY c. BANISTER, Professor in the Royal Normal College and Academy 
of Music for the Blind, in the Guildhall School of Music, and in the 
Royal Academy of Music. Collected and Edited by Stewart mac- 
PHERSON, Fellow and Professor of the Royal Academy of Music. With 
Portrait. Crown 8vo, 5^. net. 

— Musical Art and Study : Papers for Musicians. Fcap. 8vo, at. 
HUNT (H. G. BONAVIA). A Concise History of Music, from the 

Commencement of the Christian era to the present time. For the use of 
Students. By REV. H. G. bonavia hunt, Mus. Doc. Dublin ; Warden 
of Trinity College, London ; and Lecturer on Musical History in the same 
College. 15M edition, revised to date (1 898). Fcap. 8vo, 3^. td. 

ART. 

BARTER (S.) Manual Instruction — Woodwork. By s. barter 
Organizer and Instructor for the London School Board, and to the Joint 
Committee on Manual Training of the School Board for London, the City 
and Guilds of London Institute, and the Worshipful Company of Drapers. 
With over 300 Illustrations. Fcap. 4to, cloth. "Js. (id. 

BELL (SIR CHARLES). The Anatomy and Philosophy of Expres- 
sion, as connected with the Fine Arts. By sir Charles bell, k.h. 
7//4 edition, revised. fyS, 

BRYAN'S Biographical and Critical Dictionary of Painters and 
Engravers. With a List of Ciphers, Monograms, and Marks. Anew 
Edition, thoroughly Revised 'and Enlarged. By R. e. graves and 
WALTER ARMSTRONG. 2 volumes. Imp. 8vo, buckram, £'i 3^. 

CHEVREUL on Colour. Containing the Principles of Harmony and Con- 
trast of Colours, and their Application to the Arts, yd edition, with 
Introduction Index and several Plates. 5^. — With an additional series 
of 16 Plates in Colours, 7 J. td. 

DELAMOTTE (P. H.). The Art of Sketching from Nature. By P. 
H. DELAMOTTE, Professor of Drawing at King's College, London. Illus- 
trated by Twenty-four Woodcuts and Twenty Colom-ed Plates, arranged 
progressively, from Water-colour Drawings by prout, e. w. cooke, r.a., 
GIRTIN, VARLEY, DE WINT, and the Author. New edition. Imp. 4to, 2IJ. 

FLAXMAN'S CLASSICAL COMPOSITIONS, reprinted in a cheap 
form for the use of Art Students. Oblong paper covers, 2s. bd. each. 
Homer. 2 vols. — ^schylus. — Hesiod. — Dante. 

— Lectures on Sculpture, as delivered before the President and Members 

of the Royal Academy. With Portrait and 53 plates, bs. 



Educational Catalogue. 39 

HARRIS (R.). Geometrical Drawing. For Army and other Examina- 
tions. With chapters on Scales and Graphic Statics. With 221 
diagrams. By R. HARRIS, Art Master at St. Paul's School. New 
edition, enlarged. Crown 8vo, 3J. (yd. 

HEATON (MRS.). A Concise History of Painting. By the late MRS. 
CHARLES HEATON. New edition. Revised by coSMO monkhouse. 5j. 

LELAND (C. G.). Drawing and Designing. In a series of Lessons 
for School use and Self Instruction. By CHARLES G. leland, M.A., 
F. R.L.S. Paper cover, \s.; or in cloth, is.dd. 

— Leather Work : Stamped, Moulded, and Cut, Cuir-Bouille, Sew^n, etc 

With numerous Illustrations. Fcap. 4to, 5^. 

— Manual of Wood Carving. By CHARLES G. leland, m.a., f.r.l.s. 

Revised by J. J. holtzapffel, a.m.inst.c.e. With numerous Illustra- 
tions. Fcap. 4to, 5^. 
Metal Work. With numerous Illustrations. Fcaj). 4to, S^- 

LEONARDO DA VINCI'S Treatise on Painting. Translated from 
the Italian by J. F. rigaud, r.a. With a Life of Leonardo and an 
Account of his Works, by J. w. brown. With numerous Plates, ^s. 

MOODY (F. W.). Lectures and Lessons on Art. By the late F. w. 
MOODY, Instructor in Decorative Art at South Kensington Museum. With 
Diagrams to illustrate Composition and other matters. A new and cheaper 
edition. Demy 8vo, sewed, 4J. ()d. 

PENNELL (J.). Modern Illustration : Its Methods and Present Con- 
dition. By JOSEPH PENNELL, Author of " Pen Drawing and Pen 
Draughtsmen," etc. With 171 Illustrations. Student's Edition. Post 
8vo, Ts. 6d. 

STRANGE (E. F). Alphabets : a Handbook of Lettering, compiled for 
the use of Artists, Designers, Handicraftsmen, and Students. With com- 
plete Historical and Practical Descriptions. By edward f. strange. 
With more than 200 Illustrations. 3rd edition. Crown 8vo. 5^. 

WHITE (GLEESON). Practical Designing: A Handbook on the 
Preparation of Working Drawings, showing the Technical Methods em- 
ployed in preparing them for the Manufacturer and the Limits imposed on 
the Design by the Mechanism of Reproduction and the Materials employed. 
Edited by GLEESON WHITE. Freely Illustrated, yd edition. Crown 8vo,Sj. 
Contents : — Bookbinding, by H. ORRiNSMiTH — Carpets,, by Alexander 
MILLAR— Drawing for Reproduction, by the Editor— Pottery, by w. P. 
RIX— Metal Work, by R. LL. rathbone— Stained Glass, by selwyn 
IMAGE — Tiles, by owen carter — Woven Fabrics, Printed Fabrics, and 
Floorcloths, by ARTHUR silver— Wall Papers, by G. c. HAiTt. 

MENTAL, MORAL, AND SOCIAL 
SCIENCES. 

PSYCHOLOGY AND ETHICS. 

ANTONINUS (M. Aurelius). The Thoughts of. Translated literally, 
with Notes, Biographical Sketch, Introductory Essay on the Philosophy, 
and Index, by GEORGE long, m.a. Revised edition. Small post Bvo, 
y. 6d. , or new edition on Handmade paper, buckram, 6j. 

BACON'S Novum Organum and Advancement of Learning. Edited, 
with Notes, by j. devey, m.a. Small post 8vo, S^. 



40 George Bell & Sons' 

EPICTETUS. The Discourses of. With the Encheiridion and Frag- 
ments. Translated with Notes, a Life of Epictetus, a View of his Philo- 
sophy, and Index, by george long, m.a. Small post 8vo, 5^., or new 
edition on Handmade paper, 2 vols,, buckram, los. 6d. 

HEGEL'S Philosophy of Right. Translated by s. w. dyde,^ d.sc. 
Professor of Mental Philosophy in Queen's College, Kingston, Canada. 
Large post 8vo, 7^. 6d. 

KANT'S Critique of Pure Reason. Translated by J. M. D. meiklejohn. 
Professor of Education at St. Andrew's University. Small post 8vo, $s. 

— Prolegomena and Metaphysical Foundations of Science. With 

Life. Translated by E. belfort bax. Small post 8vo, 5^. 

LOCKE'S Philosophical Works. Edited by j. a. st. john. 2 vols. 
Small post 8vo, 3^. ()d. each. 

RYLAND (F.). Psychology, an Introductory Manual for University 
Students, designed chiefly for the London B.A. and B.Sc. By 
F. RYLAND, M.A., late Scholar of St. John's College, Cambridge, ^th 
edition, rewritten and enlarged. With lists of books for Students, and 
Examination Papers set at London University. Crown 8vo, 4J. 6d. 

— Ethics : An Introductory Manual for the use of University Students. 

With an Appendix containing List of Books recommended, and Exami- 
nation Questions. Crown 8vo, 3i. 6d. 

— Logic. An Introductory Manual for the use of University Students. 

Crown 8vo, 4J. 6d. 
SCHOPENHAUER on the Fourfold Root of the Principle of Suffi- 
cient Reason, and On the Will in Nature. Translated by madame 

HILLEBRAND. Small pOSt 8vO, S^. 

— Essays. Selected and Translated. With a Biographical Introduction 

and Sketch of his Philosophy, by E. BELFORT BAX. Small post 8vo, S^. 
SMITH (Adam). Theory of Moral Sentiments. With Memoir of the 

Author by DUGALD STEWART. Small post 8vo, y. 6d. 
SPINOZA'S Chief Works. Translated, with Introduction, by R. H. M. 
ELWES. 2 vols. Small post 8vo, 5^. each. 

Vol. I. — Tractatus Theologico-Politicus — Political Treatise. 
II. — Improvement of the Understanding — Ethics — Letters. 

HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. 

BAX (E. B.). Handbook of the History of Philosophy. By B. bel- 
fort BAX. znd edition, revised. Small post 8vo, 5^. 

DRAPER (J. W.). A History of the Intellectual Development of 
Europe. By JOHN WILLIAM DRAPER, M.D., LL.D. With Index. 2 
vols. Small post 8vo, ^s. each. 

FALCKENBERG(R.). History of Modern Philosophy. BymcHARD 
falckenberg. Professor of Philosophy in the University of Erlangen. 
Translated by Professor A. c. Armstrong. DemySvo, its. 

HEGEL'S Lectures on the Philosophy of History. Translated by 
J. SIBREE, M. A. Small post 8vo, Sj. 

LAW AND POLITICAL ECONOMY. 
KENT'S Commentary on International Law. Edited by j. T. aedy, 
LL.D., Judge of County Courts and Law Professor at Gresham College, 
late Regius Professor of Laws in the University of Cambridge. 2nd 
edition, revised and brought down to a recent date. Crown 8vo, io,r. 6a?. 



Educational Catalogue. 41 



MONTESQUIEU'S Spirit of Laws. A New Edition, revised and 
corrected, witii D'Alembert's Analysis, Additional Notes, and a Memoir, 
by J. V. PRITCHARD, A.M. 2 vols. Small post 8vo, Is. 6d. each. 

PROTHERO (M.). Political Economy. By michabl prothero, m.a. 
Crown 8vo, 4r. (>d, 

RICARDO on the Principles of Political Economy and Taxation. 
Edited by B. c. K. Conner, m.a., Lecturer in University College, 
Liverpool. Small post 8vo, 5^-. 

SMITH (Adam). The Wealth of Nations. An Inquiry into the Nature 
and Causes of. Reprinted from the Sixth Edition, Vi\\h an Introduction 
by ERNEST BELFORT BAX. 2 vols. Small post 8vo, y. 6d. each. 

HISTORY. 

BOWES (A.). A Practical Synopsis of English History; or, A 

General Summary of Dates and Events. By ARTHUR bowes. nth 

edition. Revised and brought down to the present time. Demy 8vo, is. 
COXE (W.). History of the House of Austria, 1218-1792. By 

ARCHDN. COXE, M.A., F.R.s. Together with a Continuation from the 

Accession of Francis I. to the Revolution of 1848. 4 vols. Small post 

8vo. 3J. 6d. each. 
DENTON (W.). England in the Fifteenth Century. By the late 

REV. w. DENTON, M.A., Worcester College, Oxford. Demy 8vo, 12s. 
DYER (Dr. T. H.). History of Modern Europe, from the Taking of 

Constantinople to the Establishment of the German Empire, A.D. 1453- 

1871. By DR. T. H. DYER. A new edition. In 5 vols. £2 \2,s. dd. 
GIBBON'S Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire. Complete and 

Unabridged, "with Variorum Notes. Edited by an English Churchman. 

With 2 Maps. 7 vols. Small post 8vo, y. 6d. each. 
GREGOROVIUS' History of the City of Rome in the Middle Ages. 

Translated by annie HAMILTON. Vols. I., II., and III. Crown 8vo, 6s. 

each net. Vols. IV. , V. , and VI. , each in two parts, 4f . dd. net each part. 
GUIZOT'S History of the English Revolution of 1640. Translated by 

WILLIAM HAZLITT. Small post 8vo, 3^. 6d. 

— History of Civilization, from the Fall of the Roman Empire to the 

French Revolution. Translated by WILLIAM HAZLItt. 3 vols. Small 
post 8vo, 3J. 6d. each. 
HENDERSON (E. F.). Select Historical Documents of the Middle 
Ages. Including the most famous Charters relating to England, the 
Empire, the Church, etc., from the sixth to the fourteenth centuries. 
Translated and edited, with Introductions, by ERNEST F. HENDERSON, 
A.B., A.M., PH.D. Small post 8vo, $s. 

— A History of Germany in the Middle Ages. Post 8vo, 71. 6d. net. 
HOOPER (George). The Campaign of Sedan : The Downfall of the 

Second Empire, August-September, 1870. By George hooper. With 
General Map and Six Plans of Battle. Small Post 8vo, y. 6d. 

— Waterloo : The Downfall of the First Napoleon : a History of the 

Campaign of 1815. With Maps and Plans. Small post 8vo, 3^-. f>d. 
LAMAR'flNE'S History of the Girondists. Translated by H. T. ryde. 
3 vols. Small post 8vo, y. 6d. each. 

— History of the Restoration of Monarchy in France (a Sequel to his 

History of the Girondists). 4 vols. Small post Svo, 3^. 6d. each. 

— Histoiy of the French Revolution of 1848. Small post Svo, 3^^. 6d. 



42 George Bell & Sons' 

LAPPENBERG'S History of England under the Anglo-Saxon 
Kings. Translated by the late B. THORPE, F.s.A. New edition, revised 
by E. c. OTTfi. 2 vols. Small post 8vo, y. 6ii. each. 

MACHIAVELLI'S History of Florence, and of the Affairs of Italy 
from the Earliest Times to the Death of Lorenzo the Magnificent : together 
with the Prince, Savonarola, various Historical Tracts, and a Memoir of 
Machiavelli. Small post 8vo, y. 6d. 

MARTINEAU (H.). History of England from 1800-15. By HARRIET 
MARTINEAU. Small post 8vo, 3^. 6d. 

— History of the Thirty Years' Peace, 1815-46. 4 vols. Small post 8vo, 

3 J. 6d. each. 
MAURICE (C. E.). The Revolutionary Movement of 1848-9 in 

Italy, Austria, Hungary, and Germany. With some Examination 

of the previous Thirty-three Years. By c. EDMUND MAURICE. With an 

engraved Frontispiece and other Illustrations. Demy 8vo, i6j. 
MENZEL'S History of Germany, from the Earliest Period to 1842. 

3 vols. Small post 8vo, 3^. 6d. each. 
MICHELET'S History of the French Revolution from its earliest 

indications to the flight of the King in 1791. Small post 8vo, 3.?. 6d. 
MIGNET'S History of the French Revolution, from 1789 to 1814. 

Small post 8vo, 3^. 6d. , 

PARNELL (A.). The War of the Succession in Spain during the 

Reign of Queen Anne, 1702-1711. Based on Original Manuscripts 

and Contemporary Records. By COL. THE HON. ARTHUR PARNELL, 

R.E. Demy 8vo, 14;. With Map, etc. 
RANKE (L.). History of the Latin and Teutonic Nations, 1494- 

1514. Translated by P. A. ashworth. Small post 8vo, 3s. 6d. 

— History of the Popes, their Church and State, and especially of their 

conflicts with Protestantism in the 1 6th and 17th centuries. Translated 
by E. FOSTER. 3 vols. Small post 8vo, 3j. ()d. each. 

— History of Servia and the Servian Revolution. Translated by MRS. 

KERR. Small post 8vo, y. 6d. 
SIX OLD ENGLISH CHRONICLES: viz., Asser's Life of Alfred 

and the Chronicles of Ethelwerd, Gildas, Nennius, Geoffrey of Monmouth, 

and Richard of Cirencester. Edited, with Notes and Index, by J. A. 

GILES, D.c.L. Small post 8vo, 5^-. 
STRICKLAND (Agnes). The Lives of the Queens of England ; 

from the Norman Conquest to the Reign of Queen Anne. By AGNES 

STRICKLAND. 6 vols. $5. each. 

— The Lives of the Queens of England. Abridged edition for the 

use of Schools and Families. Post 8vo, 6s. 6d. 

THIERRY'S History of the Conquest of England by the Normans; 
its Causes, and its Consequences in England, Scotland, Ireland, and the 
Continent. Translated from the 7th Paris edition by William hazlitt. 
2 vols. Small post 8vo, 3^. dd. each. 

WRIGHT (H. F.). The Intermediate History of England, with Notes, 

Supplements, Glossary, and a Mnemonic System. For Army and Civil 

Service Candidates. By H. F. WRIGHT, M.A., LL.M. Crown 8vo, ts. 

For other Works of value to Students of History, see Catalogue of 

Bohn's Libraries, sent post-free on application. 



Educational Catalogue. 43 



DIVINITY, ETC. 

ALFORD (DEAN). Greek Testament. With a Critically revised Text, 
a digest of Various Readings, Marginal References to verbal and idio- 
matic usage. Prolegomena, and a Critical and Exegetical Commentary. 
For the use of theological students and ministers. By the late henry 
ALFORD, D.D., Dean of Canterbury. 4 vols. 8vo. £i'2.s. Sold separately. 

— The New Testament for English Readers. Containing the Authorized 

Version, with additional Corrections of Readings and Renderings, Marginal 
References, and a Critical and Explanatory Commentary. In 2 vols. 
£2 I4r. dd. Also sold in 4 parts separately. 

AUGUSTINE de Civitate Dei. Books XI. andXII. By theREV. henry 
D. GEE, B.D., F.s.A. I. Text only. 2s. II. Introduction andTranslation. 3^. 

— In Joannis Evangelium Tractatus XXIV-XXVII. Edited by the 

REV. HENRY GEK, B.D., F.S.A. I. Text only, \s. 6d. II. Translation 
by the late rev. canon h. brown, is. 6d. 

BARRETT (A. C). Companion to the Greek Testament. By the late 
A. c. BARRETT, M. A., Caius College, Cambridge, yhedition. Fcap. 8vo, 5j. 

BARRY (BP.). Notes on the Catechism. For the use of Schools. By 
the RT. REV. BISHOP BARRY, D.D. lltk edition. Fcap. 2s. 

BLE&K. Introduction to the Old Testament. By friedrich bleek. 
Edited by JOHANN BLEEK and ADOLF kamphausen. Translated from 
the second edition of the German by G. H. venables, under the super- 
vision of the REV. E. VENABLES, Residentiary Canon of Lincoln. 2nd 
edition, with Corrections'. With Index. 2 vols. Small post 8vo, y. each. 

BURGON (DEAN). The Traditional Text of the Holy Gospels Vindi- 
cated and Established. By the late ;ohn william burgon, b.d.. Dean 
of Chichester. Arranged, completed, and edited by EDWARD miller, m. a., 
Wykehamical Prebendary of Chichester Cathedral. DemySvo, 10s. 6d. net. 

— The Causes of the Corruption of the Traditional Text of the Holy 

Gospels. Edited by the rev. kdward miller, m.a. Demy 8vo, 
10s. 6d. net. 
BUTLER (BP.). Analogy of Religion. With Analytical Introduction 
and copious Index, by the late RT. rev. dr. steere. Fcap. 3s. 6d. 

EUSEBIUS. Ecclesiastical History of Eusebius Pamphilus, Bishop 
of Ceesarea. Translated from the Greek by rev. c f. cruse, m.a. 
WithNotes, a Life of Eusebius, and Chronological Table. Sm. postSvo, 5^. 

GREGORY (DR.). Letters on the Evidences, Doctrines, and Duties 
of the Christian Religion. By dr. olinthus Gregory, f.r.a.s. 
Small post 8vo, 3^-. 6d. 

HUMPHRY (W. G.). Book of Common Prayer. An Historical and 
Explanatory Treatise on the. By w. G. Humphry, b.d., late Fellovir of 
Trinity College, Cambridge, Prebendary of St. Paul's, and Vicar of St. 
Martin's-in-the-Fields, Westminster. 6tA edition. Fcap. 8vo, 2s. 6d. 
Cheap Edition, for Sunday School Teachers, is. 

JOSEPHUS (FLAVIUS). The Works of. whiston's Translation. 
Revised by REV. A. R. SHILLETO, M.A. With Topographical and Geo- 
graphical Notes by COLONEL SIR c. w. WILSON, K. c. B. $ vols. 3J. 6d. each. 

LUMBY (DR.). Compendium of English Church History, from 
1688-1830. With a Preface by J. rawson lumby, d.d. Crown 8vo, 61, 



44 George Bell & Sons' 

MACMICHAEL (J. F.). The New Testament in Greek. With 
English Notes and Preface, Synopsis, and Chronological Tables. By the 
late REV. J. F. MACMiCHAitL. Fcap. 8vo {730 pp.), 4-r. 6d. 

Also the Four Gospels, and the Acts of the Apostles, separately. 
In paper wrappers, 6d. each. 

MILLER (E ). Guide to the Textual Criticism of the New Testament. 
By REV. E. MILLER, M.A., Oxon, Rector of Bucknell, Bicester. Cr. 8vo, 4^. 

NEANDER (DR. A.). History of the Christian Religion and 
Church. Translated by J. TORREY. 10 vols. Small post 8vo, 3^. 6(/. each. 

— Life of Jesus Christ. Translated by J. McCLlNTOCKand c. blumenthal. 

Small post 8vo, y. dd. 

— History of the Planting and Training of the Christian Church by 

the Apostles. Translated by J. E. ryland. 2 vols. y. td. each. 

— Lectures on the History of Christian Dogmas. Edited by DR. JACOBI. 

Translated by J. E. ryland. 2 vols. Small post 8vo, y. (sd. each. 

— Memorials of Christian Life in the Early and Middle Ages. Trans- 

lated by J. E. RYLAND. Small post 8vo, 3^-. td. 
PEARSON (BP.). On the Creed. Carefully printed from an Early 

Edition. Edited by K. walford, m.a. Post 8vo, Si. 
PEROWNE (BP.). The Book of Psalms. A New Translation, with 

Introductions and Notes, Critical and Explanatory. By the RIGHT REV. 

J. J. STEWART PEROWNE, D.D., Bishop of Worcester. 8vo. Vol. I. 

%th edition, revised. i8j. Vol. II. Ith edition, revised. i6s. 

— The Book of Psalms. Abridged Edition for Schools. Crown 8vo. 

^th edition, ^s, 

SADLER (M. F.). The Church Teacher's Manual of Christian Instruc- 
tion. Being the Church Catechism, Expanded and Explained in Question 
and Answer. For the use of the Clergyman, Parent, and Teacher. By the 
RBV. M. F. SADLER, late Prebendary of Wells, and Rector of Honiton. 
43rfl' thousand. 2s. 
,*, A Complete List of Prebendary Sadler's Works will be sent on 
application. 

SCRIVENER (DR.). A Plain Introduction to the Criticism of the New 
Testament. With Forty-four Facsimiles from Ancient Manuscripts. For 
the use of Biblical Students. By the late F. p. scrivener, m.a., d.cl., 
LL.D., Prebendary of Exeter. 4ih edition, thoroughly revised, by the REV. 
E. MILLER, formerly Fellow and Tutor of New College, Oxford. 2 vols. 
DemySvo, 32J. 

— Novum Testamentum Graece, Textus Stephanici, 1550. Acceduntvariae 

lectiones editionum Bezae, Elzeviri, Lachmanni, Tischendorfii, Tregellesii, 
curante F. H. A. scrivener, A.M., D.C.L., LL.D. Revised edition. ^.6d. 

— Novum Testamentum Graece [Editio Major] textus Stephanici, 

A.D. 1556. Cum variis lectionibus editionum Bezae, Elzeviri, Lachmanni, 
Tischendorfii, Tregellesii, Westcott-Hortii, versionis Anglicanae emendato- 
rum curante F. H. A. scrivener, a.m., D.C.L., LL.D., accedunt parallela 
s. scripturae loca. Small post 8vo. 2nd edition. Js. 6d. 

An Edition on writing-paper, with marginfor notes. 4to, half bound, I2X. 

WHEATLEY. A Rational Illustration of the Book of Common 

Prayer. Being the Substance of everything Liturgical in Bishop Sparrow, 

Mr. L'Estrange, Dr. Comber, Dr. NichoUs, and all former Ritualist 

Commentators upon the same subject. Small post 8vo, 3s. 6d. 



Educational Catalogue. 45 



SUMMARY OF SERIES. 

BiBLIOTHKCA ClASSICA. 

Public School Series. 

Cambridge Greek and Latin Texts. 

Cambridge Texts with Notes. 

Grammar School Classics. 

Primary Classics. 

Bell's Classical Translations. 

Cambridge Mathematical Series. 

Cambridge School and College Text Books. 

Foreign Classics. 

Modern French Authors. 

Modern German Authors. 

Gombert's French Drama. 

Bell's Modern Translations. 

Bell's English Classics. 

Handbooks of English Literature. 

Technological Handbooks. 

Bell's Agricultural Series. 

Bell's Reading Books and Geographical Readers. 

BIBLIOTHECA CLASSICA. 

AESCHYLUS. ByDR. PALEY. is. 

CICERO. By G. long. Vols. I. and II. 8j. each. 

DEMOSTHENES. By r. whiston. 2 Vols. 8j. each. 

EURIPIDES. ByDR. PALEY. Vols. II. and III. 8j. each. 

HERODOTUS. By DR. BLAKESLKY. 2 Vols. lis. 

HESIOD. By dr. paley. y. 

HOMER. ByDR. PALKY. 2 Vols. 14^. 

HORACE. By a. j. macleane. 8j. 

PLATO. Phaedrus. By dr. Thompson. 5J. 

SOPHOCLES. Vol. I. By f. h. blaydes. 5J. 

— Vol. II. By DR. PALEY. 6f. 

VIRGIL, By CONINGTON AND NETTLESHip, 3 Vols. ioj.6tf.each. 

PUBLIC SCHOOL SERIES. 

ARISTOPHANES. Peace. By dr. paley. is.td. 

— Acharnians. By dr. paley. its. 6d. 

— Frogs. By dr. paley. 2j. 6d. 

— Plutus. By M. T. QUINN. 3J. td. 

CICERO. Letters to Atticus. Book 1. By a. pretor. 41. 6d. 
DEMOSTHENES. De Falsa Legatione. By r. shilleto. 6s. 

— Adv. Leptinem. By B. w. deatson. 3^. 6d. 

LIVY. Book VI. By e. s. WEYMOUTH and G. F. HAMILTON. 2Sf6d. 

— Books XXI. and XXII. By l. d. dowdall. is. each. 

PLATO. Apology of Socrates and Crito. By dr. w. wagner. 3*. 6d and 
2f . 6a. 

Phaedo. By dr. w. wagner. sf. 6d. 

Protagoras. By w. wavte. 45. 6d. 

Gorgias. By dr. Thompson. 6s. 

Euthyphro. By G. h. wells. 3J. 

Euthydetnus. By g. h. wells. 4J. 

Republic. By G. h. wells. 5^. 

PLAUTUS. Aulularia. By dr. w. wagner. ^s.6d, 

Trinummns. By dr. w. wagner. 4J. 6d. 

Menaechmel. By dr. w. wagner. \s 6d. 

Mostellaria. By e. a. soknenschein 5*. 



46 George Bell & Sons' 

PUBLIC SCHOOL SKRlES—^:cn/inual. 

SOPHOCLES. Trachlniae. By a. febtos. 41. 6d. 

— Oedipus Tyrannus. By B. H, Kennedy, m. 6d. 
TERENCE. By dh. w. wagnbr. js. 6d. 
THUCYDIDES. Book VI. By t. w. dougan. m. 

CAMBRIDGE GREEK AND LATIN TEXTS. 
ABSCHYI.US. BysR. FAUtv. u. 
CAESAR. By G. long. u. bi. 

CICERO. De Senectute, de Amicitia, et Bpistolae Selectae. By G. long. 
IS. id. 

— Orationes in Verrem. By g. long. 2^. td, 
EURIPIDES. ByDK. PALEY. 3 Vols. m. each. 
HERODOTUS. By DK. blakeslev. 2 Vols. 21. 6rf. each. 
HOMER'S Iliad. ByoR. palby. li. Si 

HORACE. By A. j. macleane. ij. td. 

JUVENAL AND PERSIUS. By a. ;. macleane. ii. 6rf. 

LUCRETIUS. By H. A. J. MUNRO. 21. 

OVID. By DR. POSTGATB and Others. 3 vols. 2£. each. 

SALLUST. By G. long. ij. td. 

SOPHOCLES. ByDE. PALEY. is. fid. 

TERENCE. By DR. w. WAGNER, it. 

THUCYDIDES. By dr. Donaldson. 2 Vols. 2J. each. 

VIRGIL. By PROF, conington. is. 

XENOPHON. By j. f. macmichael. li. td. 

NOVUM TESTAMENTUM GRAECE. By dr. scrivener, ^s.td. 

CAMBRIDGE TEXTS WITH NOTES. 

AESCHYLUS. By dr. palby. 6 Vols. w. 6rf. each 

EURIPIDES. By dr. PALEY. 13 Vols. (Ion, 2j.) ij. 6<^. each, 

HOMER'S Iliad. By dr. paley. is. 

SOPHOCLES. ByDE. PALEY. 5 Vols. li. 611!. each. 

XENOPHON. Hellenica. By rev. l. d. dowdall. Books Land II. zr. each. 

— Anabasis. By j. f. macmichael. 6 Vols. u. td. each. 

CICERO. De Senectute, de Amicitia, et Epistolae Selectae. By g. long. 

3 Vols. If. td. each. 
OVID. Selections. By A. j. macleanb. rs. td. 

— Fasti. By dr. paley. 3 Vols. is. each. 
TERENCE. By DR. w. WAGNER. 4 Vols. ij. 6rf. each. 
VIRGIL. By prof, conington. 12 Vols. \s. td. each. 

GRAMMAR SCHOOL CLASSICS. 

CAESAR, De Bello Gallico. By g. long. 41., or in 3 parts, ii. 6<i. each. 
CATULLUS, TIBULLUS, and PROPERTIUS. By a. h. wratislaw 

and F. n. SUTTON, is. td. 
CORNELIUS NEPOS. By j. f. macmichael. 21. 

CICERO. DeSenectute,De Amicitia, and Select Epistles. ByG. long. 31. 
HOMER. Iliad. By dr. paley. Books I.-XII. 4s. td., or in 2 Parts, 21. td. each. 
HORACE. By A. j. macleane. 3J. td., or in 2 Parts, 21. each. 
JUVENAL. By HERMAN PRIOR. 2^. td. 
MARTIAL. By dr. paley and w. H. stone. 4^. td. 
OVID. Fasti. By dr. paley. 3s. td., or in 3 Parts, is. td. each. 
SALLUST. Catilina and Juguptha. By g. long and j. g. feazer. y. td. 

or in 2 Part.s, 2;.each. 
TACITUS. Germania and Agricola. By p. frost, is. td. 
VIRGIL, conington's edition abridged. 2 Vols. Afi. td. each, or in 9 Parts, 

\s. td. each. 

— Bucolics and Georgics. conington's edition abridged. 35. 
XENOPHON. By J. F. macmichael. 3^. 6<;., or in 4 Parts, li. 6rf. each. 

— Cyropaedia. By g. m. gorham. 3^. td., or in i Parts, is. td. each. 

— Memorabilia. By percival frost. 3^. 

PRIMARY CLASSICS. 

EASY SELECTIONS FROM CAESAR. By A. M. M. stedman. m. 
S^IX l^^fn.'SiSf ,f ""^^ "VY. By A. M. M. stedman. is. td. 
EASY SELECTIONS FROM HERODOTUS. By a. g. liddell ii 6<A 



Educational Catalogue. 47 

BELL'S CLASSICAL TRANSLATIONS. 

AESCHYLUS. By waltbr hbadlam. 6 Vols. {/h tit ^nsi. 

ARISTOPHANES. Acharoians. By w. h. covihgton. ii. 

— PlutUS. By M. T. QUINN. IS. 

CAESAR'S Qallic War. By w. a. hcdbvitte. 2 Vols. zs. each. 
CICERO. PriendBhip and Old Age. By g. h. welu. ii. 
DEMOSTHENES. On the Crown. By c. rann Kennedy. i«. 
EURIPIDES. 14 Vols. By E. r. COLEEIDGE. is. each. 
HORACE. 4 Vols. By A. Hamilton bkvce, ll.d. ii. each. 
LrlVY. Books I. -IV. By j. h. freese. is. each. 

— Book V. and VI. By B. s. weymouth. ij. each. 

— Book IX, By F. stoer. is. 

LUCAN : The Pharsalia. Book I. By f. conwav. is, 
OVID. Fasti. 3 Vols. By H. T. RILEY, u. each. 

— Tristia. By h. t. riley. is. 

SOPHOCLES. 7 Vols. By E. p. COLERIDGE II. each 
VIRGIL. 6 Vols. By A. Hamilton bryce. ii. each. 
XENOPHON. Anabasis. 3 Vols. By j. ». watson. ii. each. 

— Hellenics. Books I. and II. By h. dale. ii. 

CAMBRIDGE MATHEMATICAL SERIES. 

ARITHMETIC. By c. pendlebury. 41. 61I., or in a Parts, ai. 6d. each. 
Key to Part II. js. 6d. net. 

EXAMPLES IN ARITHMETIC. By u. pendlebury. 31.. or m a Parts, 
II. 6d. and 21. 

CPMMERCIAL ARITHMETIC, Bye, pendlebury and w, s, beard, ss.td. 

ARITHMETIC FOR INDIAN SCHOOLS. By pendlebury and tait, 31, 

ELEMENTARY ALGEBRA. By j. t, hathornthwaite. 21. 

CHOICE AND CHANCE. By w. a. whitworth, 61. 

D C C EXERCISES (a companion to "Choice and Chance"). By w. a, whit- 
worth, 6s. 

EUCLID. By H. DEIGHTON. 41, 6rf,, or Books I. -IV,, 31. : Books V,-XI., 21. td. 
or Book I., II, ; Books I. and IL, 11. 6rf, ; Books I.-III., 21. 6<f. ; Books III, 
and IV,, II, 6d. Key. 51. net. 

INTRODUCTION TO EUCLID. By h. deighton and emtage. ii. W. 

EXERCISES ON EUCLID, &c. By j, Mcdowell, 61. 

ELEMENTARY MENSURATION. By B. T. moore, 31. Srf, 

ELEMENTARY TRIGONOMETRY. By c. pendlebury. 41. 6rf. 

ELEMENTARY TRIGONOMETRY. By dyer and whitcombe. 41, 6rf, 

PLANE TRIGONOMETRY, By t, g, vyvyan. v. td. 

ANALYTICAL GEOMETRY FOR BEGINNERS Parti. By t. c 

VYVYAN. 21. 6d. 

EXAMPLES IN ANALYTICAL CONICS, By w, m. baker. 21. 6rf. 
ELEMENTARY GEOMETRY OF CONICS. By dr. taylor. ^s. 6d. 
GEOMETRICAL CONIC SECTIONS. By dr. w, h, besant. 41. 6d. 

Key, 51. net. 
ELEMENTARY CONICS. By dr. w. H. besant. 21. 6rf. 
GEOMETRICAL CONIC SECTIONS. By H. G. willis. 51. 
SOLID GEOMETRY. By w. s, ALDIS, 61, 
GEOMETRICAL OPTICS, By w. s, ALDIS. 41., 
ROULETTES AND GLISSETTES. By DR. w. H. besant. 51. 
ELEMENTARY HYDROSTATICS. By dr. w. h, besant, 41, erf. 

Solutions, SI, net 
HYDROMECHANICS, Part L Hydrostatics. By dr. w. h. besant. 51. 
DYNAMICS. By DR. w. H. BESANT. los. 6d. 
RIGID DYNAMICS. By w, s. ALDIS. 41. 
ELEMENTARY DYNAMICS. By DR. w, garnktt, 6s. 
ELEMENTARY TREATISE ON HEAT. By dr. w. garnett. ^s. 6d. 
ELEMENTS OF APPLIED MATHEMATICS. By c. M. JESSOP. 41 6d 
PROBLEMS IN ELEMENTARY MECHANICS. By w. walton 61 
EXAMPLES IN ELEMENTARY PHYSICS. By w. gallatly. 41 ' 
MATHEMATICAL EXAMPLES. By dyer and prowde smith. 61. 

CAMBRIDGE SCHOOL AND COLLEGE TEXT BOOKS. 

ARITHMETIC. Bye. ELSEE. y. 6d. 
By A. wKiGLEV. 31. 6d. 



48 George Bell & Sons' Educational Catalogue. 

CAMBRIDGE SCHOOL TEXTS— cmtittueii. 

EXAMPLES IN ARITHMETIC. By watson and goudie. m. 6d. 
ALGEBRA. Bye. elsek. 41; ,, 

EXAMPLES IN ALGEBRA. By macmichakl and pkowdb smith. 3s. 6d 

and 4^. 6ei. 
PLANE ASTRONOMY. By p. T. maim. 41. 
STATICS. By bishop Goodwin. 31. 
NEWTON'S Principia. By bvans and main. 41. 
ANALYTICAL GEOMETRY. By T. G. vyvyan. 4f. 6<f. 
COMPANION TO THE GREEK TESTAMENT. By A. c. eaerett. 5* 
TEXT BOOK OF MUSIC. By H. c. banister. 5s. 
CONCISE HISTORY OF MUSIC. By DK. H. o. BONAViA HUNT. 3s. 6d. 

FOREIGN CLASSICS. 

FENELON'S Tfl^maque. By c. j. delille. 2s. 6d. 

LA FONTAINE'S Select Fables. By f. e. a. gasc. is. 6d. 

LAMARTINE'S Le Tailleur de Pierres de Saint-Point. By j. boIelle. 

IS. 6d. 
SAINTINE'S Picciola. By dr. dubuc. is. 6d. 
VOLTAIRE'S Charles XII. By l. direy. is. 6d. 
GERMAN BALLADS. By c. L. Bielefeld, is. 6d. 

GOETHE'S Hermann und Dorothea. By E. bell and e. wolfel. ij. 6d. 
SCHILLER'S Wallenstein. By dr. buchheim. sj., or in 2 Parts, 2J. 6rf. each. 

— Maid of Orleans. By dr. w. wagner. is. 6d. 

— Maria Stuart. By v. kastner. is. 6d, 

MODERN FRENCH AUTHORS. 

BALZAC'S Ursule Mirouet. By j. boielle. 3*. 
CLARETIE'S Pierrille. By j. boielle. ^. 6d. 
DAUDET'S La Belle Nivernaise. By j. boielle ij. 
GREVILLE'S Le Moulin Frappier. By j. boielle. 31. 
HUGO'S Bug Jargal. By j. boielle. 3s. 

MODERN GERMAN AUTHORS. 

AUERBACH'S Auf Wache, and Roquette's Der Gefrorene Kuss. By 

A. A. MACDONELL. 2J. 

BENEDIX'S Doktor Wespe. By prof, lange. 21. 6d. 

EBERS' Eine Fraffe. By f. storr. 2s. 

FREYTAG'S Die Journalisten. By prof, lange. 2s. td. 

— Soil und Haben. By w. h. chump. 2s. 6d. 
GERMAN EPIC TALES. By dr. karl neuhaus. 2s. 6d. 
GUTZKOW'S Zopf und Schwert. By prof, langk. is. 6d. 
KEY'S Fabeln fiir Kinder. By prof, lange. is. 6d. 

with Phonetic Transcription of Text, &c. 2S. 

HEYSE'S Hans Lange. By a. a. macdonell. 25. 
HOFFMANN'S Meister Martin. By prof, lange. is. 6d. 
MOSER'S Der Bibliothekar. By prof, lange. is. 
SCHEFFEL'S Ekkehard. By dr. h. hager. 3s. 

The following Series are given in full in the body of the Catalo^e. 

BELL'S Agricultural Series. Seepage 36. 

BELL'S English Classics. Seepf. 24, 25. 

BELL'S Modern Translations. See page -n. 

BELL'S Reading Books and Geographical Readers. See i>i>. 2^ afi 

GOMBERT'S French Drama, ste page 31. 

HANDBOOKS OF ENGLISH LITERATURE. Seepage2b 

TECHNOLOGICAL HANDBOOKS. See page 31. 



CHISWICK PRESS : — C. WHITTINGHAM AND CO. TOOKS COURT, CHANCERY LANK 






'i- fr '. , ill 




v. C