Skip to main content

Full text of "Design for a brain; the origin of adaptive behavior"

See other formats


'fiiffiii 


m 

1 


warn  , 


Hi 


mm        m 

m  ■■  '■"■■'  tm  §1 

Is  I     B 

■■■■I 


'■'-:■■■■'.■'■■•' 


■■■■"•■' 


m 


WW 

liHll 


IHffN 


■■■■ 


■"■I 


■■■■ 

mm 

iliWIiil 


Hi 


DESIGN    FOR    A    BRAIN 


BY    THE    SAME    AUTHOR 

An  Introduction  to  Cybernetics 


/4  s. 


DESIGN   FOR   A   BRAIN 

The  origin  of  adaptive  behaviour 

W.    ROSS    ASHBY 

M.A.,  M.D.,  D.P.M. 

Director,  Burden  Neurological  Institute; 
Late  Director  of  Research,   Barnuood  House,  Gloucester 


SECOND   EDITION 
REVISED 


NEW  YORK 

JOHN  WILEY  &  SONS.  Inc. 

London:  CHAPMAN  <fe  HALL.   Limited 
1960 


First  Published  1952 

Reprinted  (with  corrections)     1954 
Second  Edition  (revised)  1960 

(C)    W.    ROSS    ASHBY    1960 


CATALOGUE    NO.    493/4 

Printed  in  Great  Britain  by  Butler  &  Tanner  Ltd.,  Frome  and  London 


Preface 

The  book  is  not  a  treatise  on  all  cerebral  mechanisms  but  a  pro- 
posed solution  of  a  specific  problem:  the  origin  of  the  nervous 
system's  unique  ability  to  produce  adaptive  behaviour.  The 
work  has  as  basis  the  fact  that  the  nervous  system  behaves  adap- 
tively  and  the  hypothesis  that  it  is  essentially  mechanistic;  it 
proceeds  on  the  assumption  that  these  two  data  are  not  irrecon- 
cilable. It  attempts  to  deduce  from  the  observed  facts  what  sort 
of  a  mechanism  it  must  be  that  behaves  so  differently  from  any 
machine  made  so  far.  Other  proposed  solutions  have  usually  left 
open  the  question  whether  some  different  theory  might  not  fit  the 
facts  equally  well:  I  have  attempted  to  deduce  what  is  necessary, 
what  properties  the  nervous  system  must  have  if  it  is  to  behave 
at  once  mechanistically  and  adaptively. 

For  the  deduction  to  be  rigorous,  an  adequately  developed  logic 
of  mechanism  is  essential.  Until  recently,  discussions  of  mechan- 
ism were  carried  on  almost  entirely  in  terms  of  some  particular 
embodiment — the  mechanical,  the  electronic,  the  neuronic,  and  so 
on.  Those  days  are  past.  There  now  exists  a  well  developed 
logic  of  pure  mechanism,  rigorous  as  geometry,  and  likely  to  play 
the  same  fundamental  part,  in  our  understanding  of  the  complex 
systems  of  biology,  that  geometry  does  in  astronomy.  Only  by 
the  development  of  this  basic  logic  has  the  work  in  this  book  been 
made  possible. 

The  conclusions  reached  are  summarised  at  the  end  of  Chapter 
18,  but  they  are  likely  to  be  unintelligible  or  misleading  if  taken 
by  themselves;  for  they  are  intended  only  to  make  prominent  the 
key  points  along  a  road  that  the  reader  has  already  traversed. 
They  may,  however,  be  useful  as  he  proceeds,  by  helping  him  to 
distinguish  the  major  features  from  the  minor. 

Having  experienced  the  confusion  that  tends  to  arise  whenever 
we  try  to  relate  cerebral  mechanisms  to  observed  behaviour,  I 
made  it  my  aim  to  accept  nothing  that  could  not  be  stated  in 
mathematical  form,  for  only  in  this  language  can  one  be  sure, 
during  one's  progress^  that  one  is  not  unconsciously  changing  the 


PREFACE 

meaning  of  terms,  or  adding  assumptions,  or  otherwise  drifting 
towards  confusion.  The  aim  proved  achievable.  The  concepts 
of  organisation,  behaviour,  change  of  behaviour,  part,  whole, 
dynamic  system,  co-ordination,  etc. — notoriously  elusive  but 
essential — were  successfully  given  rigorous  definition  and  welded 
into  a  coherent  whole.  But  the  rigour  and  coherence  depended 
on  the  mathematical  form,  which  is  not  read  with  ease  by  every- 
body. As  the  basic  thesis,  however,  rests  on  essentially  common- 
sense  reasoning,  I  have  been  able  to  divide  the  account  into  two 
parts.  The  main  account  (Chapters  1-18)  is  non-mathematical 
and  is  complete  in  itself.  The  Appendix  (Chapters  19-22)  contains 
the  mathematical  matter. 

Since  the  reader  will  probably  need  cross-reference  frequently, 
the  chapters  have  been  divided  into  sections.  These  are  indicated 
thus:  S.  4/5,  which  means  Chapter  ,4's  fifth  section.  Each  figure 
and  table  is  numbered  within  its  own  section:  Figure  4/5/2  is  the 
second  figure  in  S.  4/5.  Section-numbers  are  given  at  the  top  of 
every  page,  so  finding  a  section  or  a  figure  should  be  as  simple 
and  direct  as  finding  a  page. 

It  is  a  pleasure  to  be  able  to  express  my  indebtedness  to  the 
Governors  of  Barnwood  House  and  to  Dr.  G.  W.  T.  H.  Fleming 
for  their  generous  support  during  the  prosecution  of  the  work,  and 
to  Professor  F.  L.  Golla  and  Dr.  W.  Grey  Walter  for  much  help- 
ful criticism. 


VI 


Preface  to  the  Second  Edition 

At  the  time  when  this  book  was  first  written,  information  theory 
was  just  beginning  to  be  known.  Since  then  its  contribution  to 
our  understanding  of  the  logic  of  mechanism  has  been  so  great 
that  a  separate  treatment  of  these  aspects  has  been  given  in  my 
Introduction  to  Cybernetics  *  (which  will  be  referred  to  in  this  book 
as  /.  to  C).  Its  outlook  and  methods  are  fundamental  to  the 
present  work. 

The  overlap  is  small.  I.  to  C.  is  concerned  with  first  principles, 
as  they  concern  the  topics  of  mechanism,  communication,  and 
regulation;  but  it  is  concerned  with  the  principles  and  does  not 
appreciably  develop  their  applications.  It  considers  mechanisms 
as  if  they  go  in  small  discrete  steps,  a  supposition  that  makes  their 
logical  properties  very  easy  to  understand.  Design  for  a  Brain, 
while  based  on  the  same  principles,  mentions  them  only  so  far  as 
is  necessary  for  their  application  to  the  particular  problem  of  the 
origin  of  adaptive  behaviour.  It  considers  mechanisms  that 
change  continuously  (i.e.  as  the  steps  shrink  to  zero),  for  this 
supposition  makes  their  practical  properties  more  evident.  It  has. 
been  written  to  be  complete  in  itself,  but  the  reader  may  find 
/.  to  C.  helpful  in  regard  to  the  foundations. 

In  the  eight  years  that  have  elapsed  between  the  preparations 
of  the  two  editions,  our  understanding  of  brain-like  mechanisms 
has  improved  immeasurably.  For  this  reason  the  book  has  been 
re-arranged,  and  the  latter  two-thirds  completely  re-written. 
The  new  version,  I  am  satisfied,  presents  the  material  in  an  alto- 
gether clearer,  simpler,  and  more  cogent  form  than  the  earlier. 

The  change  of  lay-out  has  unfortunately  made  a  retention  of 
the  previous  section-numberings  impossible,  so  there  is  no  cor- 
respondence between  the  numberings  in  the  two  editions.  I 
would  have  avoided  this  source  of  confusion  if  I  could,  but  felt 
that  the  claims  of  clarity  and  simplicity  must  be  given  precedence 
over  all  else. 

*  Chapman  &  Hall,  London  :  John  Wiley  &  Sons,  New  York  ;  3rd  imp. 
1958.     Also  translations  in  Czech,  French,  Polish,  Russian  and  Spanish. 

vii 


Contents 


CHAPTER  PAGE 

Preface  v 

Preface  to  the  Second  Edition  vii 

1  The  Problem  1 

Behaviour,  reflex  and  learned.  Relation  of  part  to  part. 
Genetic  control.  Restrictions  on  the  concepts.  Conscious- 
ness.    The  problem. 

2  Dynamic  Systems  13 

Variable  and  system.  The  operational  method.  Phase- 
space  and  field.  The  natural  system.  Strategy  for  the  com- 
plex system. 

3  The  Organism  as  Machine  30 

The  specification  of  behaviour.  Organism  and  environment. 
Essential  variables. 

4  Stability  44 

Diagram  of  immediate  effects.  Feedback.  Goal-seeking. 
Stability  and  the  whole. 

5  Adaptation  as  Stability  58 

Homeostasis.  Generalised  homeostasis.  Survival.  Stability 
and  co-ordination. 

6  Parameters  71 

Parameter  and  field.  Stimuli.  Joining  systems.  Para- 
meter and  stability.     Equilibria  of  part  and  whole. 

7  The  Ultrastable  System  80 

The  implications  of  adaptation.  The  implications  of  double 
feedback.  Step-functions.  Systems  containing  step- 
mechanisms.     The  ultrastable  system. 

8  The  Homeostat  100 

The  Homeostat  as  adapter.  Training.  Some  apparent 
faults. 

9  Ultrastability  in  the  Organism  122 

Step-mechanisms  in  the  organism.  A  molecular  basis  for 
memory  ?  Are  step-mechanisms  necessary  ?  Levels  of  feed- 
back. Control  of  aim.  Gene-pattern  and  ultrastability. 
Summary. 


CONTENTS 
CHAPTER  PAGE 

10  The  Recurrent  Situation  138 

Accumulation  of  adaptations. 

11  The  Fully- joined  System  148 

Adaptation-time.     Cumulative  adaptation. 

12  Temporary  Independence  158 

Independence.     The    effects    of   constancy.     The    effects    of 
local  stabilities. 

13  The  System  with  Local  Stabilities  171 

Progression  to  equilibrium.     Dispersion.     Localisation  in  the 
poly  stable  system. 

14  Repetitive  Stimuli  and  Habituation  184 

Habituation.     Minor  disturbances. 

15  Adaptation  in  Iterated  and  Serial  Systems  192 

Iterated  systems.     Serial  adaptation. 

16  Adaptation  in  the  Multistable  System  205 

The  richly -joined  environment.     The  poorly- joined  environ- 
ment.    Retroactive  inhibition. 

17  Ancillary  Regulations  218 

Communication    within    the    brain.     Ancillary    regulations. 
Distribution  of  feedback. 

18  Amplifying  Adaptation  231 

Selection     in     the     state-determined     system.     Amplifying 
adaptation.     The  origin  of  adaptive  behaviour. 

APPENDIX 

19  The  State-determined  System  241 

The  logic  of  mechanism.     Canonical  representation.     Trans- 
formations. 


20 

Stability 

Probability  of  stability. 

253 

21 

Parameters 

Joining  systems.     The  state-determined  system. 

262 

22 

The  Effects  of  Constancy 

Ultrastability.       Temporary     independence.       Diagrams     of 
effects. 

272 

References 

281 

Index 

283 

IX 


77554 


CHAPTER   1 

The  Problem 

1/1.  How  does  the  brain  produce  adaptive  behaviour  ?  In 
attempting  to  answer  the  question,  scientists  have  discovered  two 
sets  of  facts  and  have  had  some  difficulty  in  reconciling  them. 
On  the  one  hand  the  physiologists  have  shown  in  a  variety  of  ways 
how  closely  the  brain  resembles  a  machine:  in  its  dependence  on 
chemical  reactions,  in  its  dependence  on  the  integrity  of  anatomical 
paths,  and  in  the  precision  and  determinateness  with  which  its 
component  parts  act  on  one  another.  On  the  other  hand,  the 
psychologists  and  biologists  have  confirmed  with  full  objectivity 
the  layman's  conviction  that  the  living  organism  behaves  typically 
in  a  purposeful  and  adaptive  way.  These  two  characteristics  of 
the  brain's  behaviour  have  proved  difficult  to  reconcile,  and  some 
workers  have  gone  so  far  as  to  declare  them  incompatible. 

Such  a  point  of  view  will  not  be  taken  here.  I  hope  to  show 
that  a  system  can  be  both  mechanistic  in  nature  and  yet  produce 
behaviour  that  is  adaptive.  I  hope  to  show  that  the  essential 
difference  between  the  brain  and  any  machine  yet  made  is  that 
the  brain  makes  extensive  use  of  a  method  hitherto  little  used  in 
machines.  I  hope  to  show  that  by  the  use  of  this  method  a 
machine's  behaviour  may  be  made  as  adaptive  as  we  please,  and 
that  the  method  may  be  capable  of  explaining  even  the  adaptive- 
ness  of  Man. 

But  first  we  must  examine  more  closely  the  nature  of  the 
problem,  and  this  will  be  commenced  in  this  chapter.  The  suc- 
ceeding chapters  will  develop  more  accurate  concepts,  and  when 
we  can  state  the  problem  with  precision  we  shall  not  be  far  from 
its  solution. 


Behaviour,  reflex  and  learned 

1/2.     The  activities  of  the  nervous  system  may  be  divided  more 
or  less  distinctly  into  two  types.     The  dichotomy  is  probably  an 

1 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  1/3 

over-simplification,  but  it  will  be  sufficient  until  we  have  developed 
a  more  elaborate  technique. 

The  first  type  is  reflex  behaviour.  It  is  inborn,  it  is  genetically 
determined  in  detail,  it  is  a  product,  in  the  vertebrates,  chiefly 
of  centres  in  the  spinal  cord  and  in  the  base  of  the  brain,  and  it  is 
not  appreciably  modified  by  individual  experience.  The  second 
type  is  learned  behaviour.  It  is  not  inborn,  it  is  not  genetically 
determined  in  detail  (more  fully  discussed  in  S.  1/9),  it  is  a  product 
chiefly  of  the  cerebral  cortex,  and  it  is  modified  markedly  by  the 
organism's  individual  experiences. 

1/3.  With  the  first  or  reflex  type  of  behaviour  we  shall  not  be 
concerned.  We  assume  that  each  reflex  is  produced  by  some 
neural  mechanism  whose  physico-chemical  nature  results  inevit- 
ably in  the  characteristic  form  of  behaviour,  that  this  mechanism 
is  developed  under  the  control  of  the  gene-pattern  and  is  inborn, 
and  that  the  pattern  of  behaviour  produced  by  the  mechanism  is 
usually  adapted  to  the  animal's  environment  because  natural 
selection  has  long  since  eliminated  all  non-adapted  variations. 
For  example,  the  complex  activity  of  '  coughing  '  is  assumed  to 
be  due  to  a  special  mechanism  in  the  nervous  system,  inborn  and 
developed  by  the  action  of  the  gene-pattern,  and  adapted  and 
perfected  by  the  fact  that  an  animal  who  is  less  able  to  clear  its 
trachea  of  obstruction  has  a  smaller  chance  of  survival. 

Although  the  mechanisms  underlying  these  reflex  activities  are 
often  difficult  to  study  physiologically,  and  although  few  are  known 
in  all  their  details,  yet  it  is  widely  held  among  physiologists  that 
no  difficulty  of  principle  is  involved.  Such  behaviour  and  such 
mechanisms  will  not  therefore  be  considered  further. 

1/4.  It  is  with  the  second  type  of  behaviour  that  we  are  con- 
cerned: the  behaviour  that  is  not  inborn  but  learned.  Examples 
of  such  reactions  exist  in  abundance,  and  any  small  selection 
must  seem  paltry.  Yet  I  must  say  what  I  mean,  if  only  to  give 
the  critic  a  definite  target  for  attack.  Several  examples  will 
therefore  be  given. 

A  dog  selected  at  random  for  an  experiment  with  a  conditioned 
response  can  be  made  at  will  to  react  to  the  sound  of  a  bell  either 
with  or  without  salivation.  Further,  once  trained  to  react  in 
one  way  it  may,  with  little  difficulty,  be  trained  to  react  later  in 

2 


1/5  THE     PROBLEM 

the  opposite  way.  The  salivary  response  to  the  sound  of  a  bell 
cannot,  therefore,  be  due  to  a  mechanism  of  fixed  properties. 

A  rat  selected  at  random  for  an  experiment  in  maze-running 
can  be  taught  to  run  either  to  right  or  left  by  the  use  of  an  appro- 
priately shaped  maze.  Further,  once  trained  to  turn  to  one  side 
it  can  be  trained  later  to  turn  to  the  other. 

Perhaps  the  most  striking  evidence  that  animals,  after  training, 
can  produce  behaviour  which  cannot  possibly  have  been  inborn 
is  provided  by  the  circus.  A  seal  balances  a  ball  on  its  nose  for 
minutes  at  a  time;  one  bear  rides  a  bicycle,  and  another  walks 
on  roller  skates.  It  would  be  ridiculous  to  suppose  that  these 
reactions  are  due  to  mechanisms  both  inborn  and  specially  per- 
fected for  these  tricks. 

Man  himself  provides,  of  course,  the  most  abundant  variety  of 
learned  reactions:  but  only  one  example  will  be  given  here.  If 
one  is  looking  down  a  compound  microscope  and  finds  that  the 
object  is  not  central  but  to  the  right,  one  brings  the  object  to 
the  centre  by  pushing  the  slide  still  farther  to  the  right.  The 
relation  between  muscular  action  and  consequent  visual  change 
is  the  reverse  of  the  usual.  The  student's  initial  bewilderment 
and  clumsiness  demonstrate  that  there  is  no  neural  mechanism 
inborn  and  ready  for  the  reversed  relation.  But  after  a  few  days' 
practice  co-ordination  develops. 

These  examples,  and  all  the  facts  of  which  they  are  representa- 
tive, show  that  the  nervous  system  is  able  to  develop  ways  of 
behaving  which  are  not  inborn  and  are  not  specified  in  detail  by 
the  gene-pattern. 

1/5.  Learned  behaviour  has  many  characteristics,  but  we  shall 
be  concerned  chiefly  with  one:  when  animals  and  children  learn, 
not  only  does  their  behaviour  change,  but  it  changes  usually  for 
the  better.  The  full  meaning  of  '  better  '  will  be  discussed  in 
Chapter  5,  but  in  the  simpler  cases  the  improvement  is  obvious 
enough.  '  The  burned  child  dreads  the  fire  ' :  after  the  experi- 
ence the  child's  behaviour  towards  the  fire  is  not  only  changed, 
but  is  changed  to  a  behaviour  which  gives  a  lessened  chance  of 
its  being  burned  again.  We  would  at  once  recognise  as  abnormal 
any  child  who  used  its  newly  acquired  knowledge  so  as  to  get 
to  the  flames  more  quickly. 
To  demonstrate  that  learning  usually  changes  behaviour  from  a 

3 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  1/6 

less  to  a  more  beneficial,  i.e.  survival-promoting,  form  would 
need  a  discussion  far  exceeding  the  space  available.  But  in  this 
introduction  no  exhaustive  survey  is  needed.  I  require  only 
sufficient  illustration  to  make  the  meaning  clear.  For  this  pur- 
pose the  previous  examples  will  be  examined  seriatim. 

When  a  conditioned  reflex  is  established  by  the  giving  of  food 
or  acid,  the  amount  of  salivation  changes  from  less  to  more.  And 
the  change  benefits  the  animal  either  by  providing  normal  lubri- 
cation for  chewing  or  by  providing  water  to  dilute  and  flush  away 
the  irritant.  When  a  rat  in  a  maze  has  changed  its  behaviour  so 
that  it  goes  directly  to  the  food  at  the  other  end,  the  new  behaviour 
is  better  than  the  old  because  it  leads  more  quickly  to  the  animal's 
hunger  being  satisfied.  The  circus  animals'  behaviour  changes 
from  some  random  form  to  one  determined  by  the  trainer,  who 
applied  punishments  and  rewards.  The  animals'  later  behaviour 
is  such  as  has  decreased  the  punishments  or  increased  the  rewards. 
In  Man,  the  proposition  that  behaviour  usually  changes  for  the 
better  with  learning  would  need  extensive  discussion.  But  in  the 
example  of  the  finger  movements  and  the  compound  microscope, 
the  later  movements,  which  bring  the  desired  object  directly  to 
the  centre  of  the  field,  are  clearly  better  than  the  earlier  move- 
ments, which  were  ineffective  for  the  microscopist's  purpose. 

Our  problem  may  now  be  stated  in  preliminary  form:  what 
cerebral  changes  occur  during  the  learning  process,  and  why  does 
the  behaviour  usually  change  for  the  better  ?  What  type  of 
mechanistic  process  could  show  the  same  self-advancement  ? 

1/6.  The  nervous  system  is  well  provided  with  means  for  action. 
Glucose,  oxygen,  and  other  metabolites  are  brought  to  it  by  the 
blood  so  that  free  energy  is  available  abundantly.  The  nerve 
cells  composing  the  system  are  not  only  themselves  exquisitely 
sensitive,  but  are  provided,  at  the  sense  organs,  with  devices  of 
even  higher  sensitivity.  Each  nerve  cell,  by  its  ramifications, 
enables  a  single  impulse  to  become  many  impulses,  each  of  which 
is  as  active  as  the  single  impulse  from  which  it  originated.  The 
ramifications  are  followed  by  repeated  stages  of  further  ramifica- 
tion, so  that  however  small  a  change  at  any  point  we  can  put 
hardly  any  bound  to  the  size  of  the  change  or  response  that  may 
follow  as  the  effect  spreads.  And  by  their  control  of  the  muscles, 
the  nerve  cells  can  rouse  to  activity  engines  of  high  mechanical 

4 


1/7  THE     PROBLEM 

power.  The  nervous  system,  then,  possesses  almost  unlimited 
potentialities  for  action.  But  do  these  potentialities  solve  our 
problem  ?  It  seems  not.  We  are  concerned  primarily  with  the 
question  why,  during  learning,  behaviour  changes  for  the  better: 
and  this  question  is  not  answered  by  the  fact  that  a  given  behaviour 
can  change  to  one  of4  lesser  or  greater  activity.  The  examples 
given  in  S.  1/5,  when  examined  for  the  energy  changes  before  and 
after  learning,  show  that  the  question  of  the  quantity  of  activity 
is  usually  irrelevant. 

But  the  evidence  against  regarding  mere  activity  as  sufficient 
for  a  solution  is  even  stronger :  often  an  increase  in  the  amount  of 
activity  is  not  so  much  irrelevant  as  positively  harmful.  If  a 
dynamic  system  is  allowed  to  proceed  to  vigorous  action  without 
special  precautions,  the  activity  will  usually  lead  to  the  destruction 
of  the  system  itself.  A  motor  car  with  its  tank  full  of  petrol  may 
be  set  into  motion,  but  if  it  is  released  with  no  driver  its  activity, 
far  from  being  beneficial,  will  probably  cause  the  motor  car  to 
destroy  itself  more  quickly  than  if  it  had  remained  inactive.  The 
theme  is  discussed  more  thoroughly  in  S.  20/10;  here  it  may  be 
noted  that  activity,  if  inco-ordinated,  tends  merely  to  the  system's 
destruction.  How  then  is  the  brain  to  achieve  success  if  its 
potentialities  for  action  are  partly  potentialities  for  self-destruction? 


The  relation  of  part  to  part 

1/7.  Our  basic  fact  is  that  after  the  learning  process  the  behaviour 
is  usually  better  adapted  than  before.  We  ask,  therefore,  what 
property  must  be  possessed  by  the  neurons  so  that  the  manifesta- 
tion by  the  neuron  of  this  property  shall  result  in  the  whole 
organism's  behaviour  being  improved. 

A  first  suggestion  is  that  if  the  nerve-cells  are  all  healthy  and 
normal  as  little  biological  units,  then  the  whole  will  appear  healthy 
and  normal.  This  suggestion,  .however,  must  be  rejected  as 
inadequate.  For  the  improvement  in  the  organism's  behaviour 
is  often  an  improvement  in  relation  to  entities  which  have  no 
counterpart  in  the  life  of  a  neuron.  Thus  when  a  dog,  given  food 
in  an  experiment  on  conditioned  responses,  learns  to  salivate,  the 
behaviour  improves  because  the  saliva  provides  a  lubricant  for 
chewing.  But  in  the  neuron's  existence,  since  all  its  food  arrives 
in  solution,  neither  '  chewing  '  nor  '  lubricant  '  can  have  any  direct 

5 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  1/8 

relevance  or  meaning.  Again,  a  maze-rat  that  has  learned  suc- 
cessfully has  learned  to  produce  a  particular  pattern  of  move- 
ment; yet  the  learning  has  involved  neurons  which  are  firmly 
supported  in  a  close  mesh  of  glial  fibres  and  never  move  in  their 
lives. 

Finally,  consider  an  engine-driver  who  has  just  seen  a  signal 
and  whose  hand  is  on  the  throttle.  If  the  light  is  red,  the  excita- 
tion from  the  retina  must  be  transmitted  through  the  nervous 
system  so  that  the  cells  in  the  motor  cortex  send  impulses  down 
to  those  muscles  whose  activity  makes  the  throttle  close.  If  the 
light  is  green,  the  excitation  from  the  retina  must  be  transmitted 
through  the  nervous  system  so  that  the  cells  in  the  motor  cortex 
make  the  throttle  open.  And  the  transmission  is  to  be  handled, 
and  the  safety  of  the  train  guaranteed,  by  neurons  which  can 
form  no  conception  of  '  red  ',  '  green  ',  '  train  ',  '  signal  ',  or 
'accident  '  !     Yet  the  system  works. 

Clearly,  '  normality  '  at  the  neuronic  level  is  inadequate  to 
ensure  normality  in  the  behaviour  of  the  whole  organism,  for  the 
two  forms  of  normality  stand  in  no  definite  relationship. 

1/8.  In  the  case  of  the  engine-driver,  it  may  be  that  there  is-  a 
simple  mechanism  such  that  a  red  light  activates  a  chain  of  nerve- 
cells  leading  to  the  muscles  which  close  the  throttle  while  a  green 
light  activates  another  chain  of  nerve-cells  leading  to  the  muscles 
which  make  it  open.  In  this  way  the  effect  of  the  colour  of  the 
signal  would  be  transmitted  through  the  nervous  system  in  the 
appropriate  way. 

The  simplicity  of  the  arrangement  is  due  to  the  fact  that  we 
are  supposing  that  the  two  reactions  are  using  two  independent 
mechanisms.  This  separation  may  well  occur  in  the  simpler 
reactions,  but  it  is  insufficient  to  explain  the  events  of  the  more 
complex  reactions.  In  most  cases  the  '  correct  '  and  the  '  incor- 
rect '  neural  activities  are  alike  composed  of  excitations,  of 
inhibitions,  and  of  other  processes  each  of  which  is  physiological 
in  itself,  but  whose  correctness  is  determined  not  by  the  process 
itself  but  by  the  relations  which  it  bears  to  other  processes. 

This  dependence  of  the  '  correctness  '  of  what  is  happening  at 
one  point  in  the  nervous  system  on  what  is  happening  at  other 
points  would  be  shown  if  the  engine-driver  were  to  move  over  to 
the  other  side  of  the  cab.     For  if  previously  a  flexion  of  the  elbow 

6 


1/8  THE     PROBLEM 

had  closed  the  throttle,  the  same  action  will  now  open  it;  and 
what  was  the  correct  pairing  of  red  and  green  to  push  and  pull 
must  now  be  reversed.  So  the  local  action  in  the  nervous  system 
can  no  longer  be  regarded  as  '  correct  '  or  '  incorrect  '  in  any 
absolute  sense,  and  the  first  simple  solution  breaks  down. 

Another  example  is  given  by  the  activity  of  chewing  in  so  far 
as  it  involves  the  tongue  and  teeth  in  movements  which  must 
be  related  so  that  the  teeth  do  not  bite  the  tongue.  No  move- 
ment of  the  tongue  can  by  itself  be  regarded  as  wholly  wrong,  for 
a  movement  which  may  be  wrong  when  the  teeth  are  just  meeting 
may  be  right  when  they  are  parting  and  food  is  to  be  driven  on 
to  their  line.  Consequently  the  activities  in  the  neurons  which 
control  the  movement  of  the  tongue  cannot  be  described  as  either 
4  correct  '  or  *  incorrect ':  only  when  these  activities  are  related  to 
those  of  the  neurons  which  control  the  jaw  movements  can  a 
correctness  be  determined;  and  this  property  now  belongs,  not  to 
either  separately,  but  only  to  the  activity  of  the  two  in  combination. 

These  considerations  reveal  the  main  peculiarity  of  the  problem. 
When  the  nervous  system  learns,  its  behaviour  changes  for  the 
better.  When  we  consider  its  various  parts,  however,  we  find  that 
the  value  of  one  part's  behaviour  cannot  be  judged  until  the 
behaviour  of  the  other  parts  is  known;  and  the  values  of  their 
behaviours  cannot  be  known  until  the  first  part's  behaviour  is 
known.  All  the  valuations  are  thus  conditional,  each  depending 
on  the  others.  Thus  there  is  no  criterion  for  '  better  '  that  can 
be  given  absolutely,  i.e.  unconditionally.  But  a  neuron  must  do 
something.  How  then  do  the  activities  of  the  neurons  become 
co-ordinated  so  that  the  behaviour  of  the  whole  becomes  better, 
even  though  no  absolute  criterion  exists  to  guide  the  individual 


neuron 


Exactly  the  same  problem  faces  the  designer  of  an  artificial 
brain,  who  wants  his  mechanical  brain  to  become  adaptive  in  its 
behaviour.  How  can  he  specify  the  '  correct  '  properties  for  each 
part  if  the  correctness  depends  not  on  the  behaviour  of  each  part 
but  on  its  relations  to  the  other  parts  ?  His  problem  is  to  get 
the  parts  properly  co-ordinated.  The  brain  does  this  auto- 
matically.    What  sort  of  a  machine  can  be  ^Z/-co-ordinating  ? 

This  is  our  problem.  It  will  be  stated  with  more  precision  in 
S.  1/17.  But  before  this  statement  is  reached,  some  minor  topics 
must  be  discussed. 

7 


DESIGN    FOR    A    BRAIN  1/9 

The  genetic  control  of  cerebral  function 

1/9.  In  rejecting  the  genetic  control  of  the  details  of  cerebral 
function  (in  adaptation,  S.  1/4)  we  must  be  careful  not  to  reject 
too  much.  The  gene-pattern  certainly  plays  some  part  in  the 
development  of  adaptive  behaviour,  for  the  various  species, 
differing  essentially  only  in  their  gene-patterns,  show  character- 
istic differences  in  their  powers  of  developing  it;  the  insects,  for 
instance,  typically  show  little  power  while  Man  shows  a  great  deal. 

One  difficulty  in  accounting  for  a  new-born  baby's  capacity  for 
developing  adaptations  is  that  the  gene-pattern  that  makes  the 
baby  what  it  is  has  about  50,000  genes  available  for  control  of 
the  form,  while  the  baby's  brain  has  about  10,000,000,000  neurons 
to  be  controlled  (and  the  number  of  terminals  may  be  10  to  100 
times  as  great).  Clearly  the  set  of  genes  cannot  determine  the 
details  of  the  set  of  neurons.  Evidently  the  gene-pattern  deter- 
mines a  relatively  small  number  of  factors,  and  then  these  factors 
work  actively  to  develop  co-ordination  in  a  much  larger  number 
of  neurons. 

This  formulation  of  how  the  gene-pattern  comes  into  the  picture 
will  perhaps  suffice  for  the  moment;  it  will  be  resumed  in  S.  18/6. 
(/.  to  C,  S.  14/6,  also  discusses  the  topic.) 

Restrictions  on  the  concepts  to  be  used 

1/10.  Throughout  the  book  I  shall  adhere  to  certain  basic 
assumptions  and  to  certain  principles  of  method. 

I  shall  hold  the  biologist's  point  of  view.  To  him,  the  most 
fundamental  facts  are  that  the  earth  is  over  2,000,000,000  years 
old  and  that  natural  selection  has  been  winnowing  the  living 
organisms  incessantly.  As  a  result  they  are  today  highly  special- 
ised in  the  arts  of  survival,  and  among  these  arts  has  been  the 
development  of  a  brain.  Throughout  this  book  the  brain  will  be 
treated  simply  as  an  organ  that  has  been  developed  in  evolution 
as  a  specialised  means  to  survival. 

1/11.  Conformably  with  this  point  of  view,  the  nervous  system, 
and  living  matter  in  general,  will  be  assumed  to  be  essentially 
similar  to  all  other  matter.  So  no  use  of  any  '  vital '  property 
or  tendency  will  be  made,  and  no  Deus  ex  machina  will  be  invoked. 

8 


1/14  THE     PROBLEM 

The  sole  reason  admitted  for  the  behaviour  of  any  part  will  be 
of  the  form  that  its  own  state  and  the  condition  of  its  immediate 
surroundings  led,  in  accordance  with  the  usual  laws  of  matter, 
to  the  observed  behaviour. 

1/12.  The  '  operational '  method  will  be  followed;  so  no  psycho- 
logical concept  will  be  used  unless  it  can  be  shown  in  objective 
form  in  non-living  systems;  and  when  used  it  will  be  considered 
to  refer  solely  to  its  objective  form.  Related  is  the  restriction 
that  every  concept  used  must  be  capable  of  objective  demonstra- 
tion. In  the  study  of  Man  this  restriction  raises  formidable 
difficulties  extending  from  the  practical  to  the  metaphysical. 
But  as  most  of  the  discussion  will  be  concerned  with  the  observed 
behaviour  of  animals  and  machines,  the  peculiar  difficulties  will 
seldom  arise. 

1/13.  No  teleological  explanation  for  behaviour  will  be  used.  It 
will  be  assumed  throughout  that  a  machine  or  an  animal  behaved 
in  a  certain  way  at  a  certain  moment  because  its  physical  and 
chemical  nature  at  that  moment  allowed  it  no  other  action.  Never 
will  we  use  the  explanation  that  the  action  is  performed  because 
it  will  later  be  advantageous  to  the  animal.  Any  such  explanation 
would,  of  course,  involve  a  circular  argument;  for  our  purpose 
is  to  explain  the  origin  of  behaviour  which  appears  to  be  teleo- 
logically  directed. 

1/14.  It  will  be  further  assumed  (except  where  the  contrary  is 
stated  explicitly)  that  the  fuctioning  units  of  the  nervous  system, 
and  of  the  environment,  behave  in  a  determinate  way.  By  this 
I  mean  that  each  part,  if  in  a  particular  state  internally  and  affected 
by  particular  conditions  externally,  will  behave  in  one  way  only, 
(This  is  the  determinacy  shown,  for  instance,  by  the  relays  and 
other  parts  of  a  telephone  exchange.)  It  should  be  noticed  that 
we  are  not  assuming  that  the  ultimate  units  are  determinate,  for 
these  are  atoms,  which  are  known  to  behave  in  an  essentially 
indeterminate  way;  what  we  shall  assume  is  that  the  significant 
unit  is  determinate.  The  significant  unit  (e.g.  the  relay,  the 
current  of  several  milliamperes,  the  neuron)  is  usually  of  a  size 
much  larger  than  the  atomic  so  that  only  the  average  property 
of  many  atoms  is  significant.   These  averages  are  often  determinate 

9 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  1/15 

in  their  behaviour,  and  it  is  to  these  averages  that  our  assumption 
applies. 

The  question  whether  the  nervous  system  is  composed  of  parts 
that  are  determinate  or  stochastic  has  not  yet  been  answered. 
In  this  book  we  shall  suppose  that  they  are  determinate.  That 
the  brain  is  capable  of  behaving  in  a  strikingly  determinate  way 
has  been  demonstrated  chiefly  by  feats  of  memory.  Some  of  the 
demonstrations  depend  on  hypnosis,  and  are  not  quite  sufficiently 
clear  in  interpretation  for  quotation  here.  Skinner,  however,  has 
produced  some  striking  evidence  by  animal  experiment  that  the 
nervous  system,  if  the  surrounding  conditions  can  be  restored 
accurately,  may  behave  in  a  strictly  reproducible  way.  By 
differential  reinforcement  with  food,  Skinner  trained  twenty 
young  pigeons  to  peck  at  a  translucent  key  when  it  was  illuminated 
with  a  complex  visual  pattern.  They  were  then  transferred  to  the 
usual  living  quarters  where  they  were  used  for  no  further  experi- 
ments but  served  simply  as  breeders.  Small  groups  were  tested 
from  time  to  time  for  retention  of  the  habit. 

'  The  bird  was  fed  in  the  dimly-lighted  experimental  apparatus 
in  the  absence  of  the  key  for  several  days,  during  which 
emotional  responses  to  the  apparatus  disappeared.  On  the 
day  of  the  test  the  bird  was  placed  in  the  darkened  box.  The 
translucent  key  was  present  but  not  lighted.  No  responses 
were  made.  When  the  pattern  was  projected  upon  the  key, 
all  four  birds  responded  quickly  and  extensively.  .  .  .  This 
bird  struck  the  key  within  two  seconds  after  presentation  of 
a  visual  pattern  that  it  had  not  seen  for  four  years,  and  at 
the  precise  spot  upon  which  differential  reinforcement  had 
previously  been  based.' 

The  assumption  that  the  parts  are  determinate  is  thus  not  un- 
reasonable. But  we  need  not  pre-judge  the  issue;  the  book  is  an 
attempt  to  follow  the  assumption  of  determinacy  wherever  it  leads. 
When  it  leads  to  obvious  error  will  be  time  to  question  its  validity. 

1/15.  To  be  consistent  with  the  assumptions  already  made,  we 
must  suppose  (and  the  author  accepts)  that  a  real  solution  of  our 
problem  will  enable  an  artificial  system  to  be  made  that  will  be 
able,  like  the  living  brain,  to  develop  adaptation  in  its  behaviour. 
Thus  the  work,  if  successful,  will  contain  (at  least  by  implication) 
a  specification  for  building  an  artificial  brain  that  will  be  similarly 
self-co-ordinating. 

10 


1/16  THE     PROBLEM 

The  knowledge  that  the  proposed  solution  must  be  put  to  this 
test  will  impose  some  discipline  on  the  concepts  used.  In  particular, 
this  requirement  will  help  to  prevent  the  solution  from  being  a 
mere  verbalistic  '  explanation  ',  for  in  the  background  will  be  the 
demand  that  we  build  a  machine  to  do  these  things. 

Consciousness 
1/16.  The  previous  sections  have  demanded  that  we  shall  make 
no  use  of  the  subjective  elements  of  experience;  and  I  can  antici- 
pate by  saying  that  in  fact  the  book  makes  no  such  use.  At 
times  its  rigid  adherence  to  the  objective  point  of  view  may 
jar  on  the  reader  and  may  expose  me  to  the  accusation  that  I  am 
ignoring  an  essential  factor.  A  few  words  in  explanation  may 
save  misunderstanding. 

Throughout  the  book,  consciousness  and  its  related  subjective 
elements  are  not  used  for  the  simple  reason  that  at  no  point  have  I 
found  their  introduction  necessary.  This  is  not  surprising,  for  the 
book  deals  with  only  one  of  the  properties  of  the  brain,  and  with 
a  property — learning — that  has  long  been  recognised  to  have  no 
necessary  dependence  on  consciousness.  Here  is  an  example  to 
illustrate  their  independence.  If  a  cyclist  wishes  to  turn  to  the 
left,  his  first  action  must  be  to  turn  the  front  wheel  to  the  right 
(otherwise  he  will  fall  outwards  by  centrifugal  force).  Every 
practised  cyclist  makes  this  movement  every  time  he  turns,  yet 
many  cyclists,  even  after  they  have  made  the  movement  hundreds 
of  times,  are  quite  unconscious  of  making  it.  The  direct  inter- 
vention of  consciousness  is  evidently  not  necessary  for  adaptive 
learning. 

Such  an  observation,  showing  that  consciousness  is  sometimes 
not  necessary,  gives  us  no  right  to  deduce  that  consciousness 
does  not  exist.  The  truth  is  quite  otherwise,  for  the  fact  of  the 
existence  of  consciousness  is  prior  to  all  other  facts.  If  I  perceive 
— am  aware  of — a  chair,  I  may  later  be  persuaded,  by  other 
evidence,  that  the  appearance  was  produced  only  by  a  trick  of 
lighting;  I  may  be  persuaded  that  it  occurred  in  a  dream,  or 
even  that  it  was  an  hallucination;  but  there  is  no  evidence  in 
existence  that  could  persuade  me  that  my  awareness  itself  was 
mistaken — that  I  had  not  really  been  aware  at  all.  This  know- 
ledge of  personal  awareness,  therefore,  is  prior  to  all  other  forms 
of  knowledge. 

11 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  1/17 

If  consciousness  is  the  most  fundamental  fact  of  all,  why  is  it 
not  used  in  this  book  ?  The  answer,  in  my  opinion,  is  that 
Science  deals,  and  can  deal,  only  with  what  one  man  can  demon- 
strate to  another.  Vivid  though  consciousness  may  be  to  its 
possessor,  there  is  as  yet  no  method  known  by  which  he  can 
demonstrate  his  experience  to  another.  And  until  such  a  method, 
or  its  equivalent,  is  found,  the  facts  of  consciousness  cannot  be 
used  in  scientific  method. 


The  problem 

1/17.  It  is  now  time  to  state  the  problem.  Later,  when  more 
exact  concepts  have  been  developed,  it  will  be  possible  to  state 
the  problem  more  precisely  (S.  5/14). 

It  will  be  convenient,  throughout  the  discussion,  to  have  some 
well-known,  practical  problem  to  act  as  type-problem,  so  that 
general  statements  can  always  be  referred  to  it.  I  select  the 
following.  When  a  kitten  first  approaches  a  fire  its  reactions  are 
unpredictable  and  usually  inappropriate.  It  may  walk  almost 
into  the  fire,  or  it  may  spit  at  it,  or  may  dab  at  it  with  a  paw, 
or  try  to  sniff  at  it,  or  crouch  and  '  stalk  '  it.  Later,  however, 
when  adult,  its  reactions  are  different.  It  approaches  the  fire  and 
seats  itself  at  a  place  where  the  heat  is  moderate.  If  the  fire  burns 
low,  it  moves  nearer.  If  a  hot  coal  falls  out,  it  jumps  away.  Its 
behaviour  towards  the  fire  is  now  '  adaptive  '.  I  might  have  taken 
as  type-problem  some  experiment  published  by  a  psychological 
laboratory,  but  the  present  example  has  several  advantages.  It 
is  well  known;  it  is  representative  of  a  wide  class  of  important 
phenomena;  and  it  is  not  likely  to  be  called  in  question  by  the 
discovery  of  some  small  technical  flaw. 

We  take  as  basic  the  assumptions  that  the  organism  is  mechan- 
istic in  nature,  that  it  is  composed  of  parts,  that  the  behaviour  of 
the  whole  is  the  outcome  of  the  compounded  actions  of  the  parts, 
that  organisms  change  their  behaviour  by  learning,  and  that  they 
change  it  so  that  the  later  behaviour  is  better  adapted  to  their 
environment  than  the  earlier.  Our  problem  is,  first,  to  identify 
the  nature  of  the  change  which  shows  as  learning,  and  secondly, 
to  find  why  such  changes  should  tend  to  cause  better  adaptation 
for  the  whole  organism. 


12 


CHAPTER  2 

Dynamic  Systems 

2/1.  In  the  previous  chapter  we  have  repeatedly  used  the  con- 
cepts of  a  system,  of  parts  in  a  whole,  of  the  system's  behaviour, 
and  of  its  changes  of  behaviour.  These  concepts  are  fundamental 
and  must  be  properly  defined.  Accurate  definition  at  this  stage 
is  of  the  highest  importance,  for  any  vagueness  here  will  infect 
all  the  subsequent  discussion;  and  as  we  shall  have  to  enter  the 
realm  where  the  physical  and  the  psychological  meet,  a  realm 
where  the  experience  of  centuries  has  found  innumerable  possi- 
bilities of  confusion,  we  shall  have  to  proceed  with  unusual  caution. 

That  some  caution  is  necessary  can  be  readily  shown.  We  have, 
for  instance,  repeatedly  used  the  concept  of  a  '  change  of 
behaviour  ',  as  when  the  kitten  stopped  dabbing  at  the  red-hot 
coal  and  avoided  it.  Yet  behaviour  is  itself  a  sequence  of  changes 
(e.g.  as  the  paw  moves  from  point  to  point).  Can  we  distinguish 
clearly  those  changes  that  constitute  behaviour  from  those  changes 
that  are  from  behaviour  to  behaviour  ?  It  is  questions  such  as 
these  which  emphasize  the  necessity  for  clarity  and  a  secure 
foundation.  (The  subject  has  been  considered  more  extensively 
in  /.  to  C,  Part  I;  the  shorter  version  given  here  should  be  sufficient 
for  our  purpose  in  this  book.) 

We  start  by  assuming  that  we  have  before  us  some  dynamic 
system,  i.e.  something  that  may  change  with  time.  We  wish  to 
study  it.  It  will  be  referred  to  as  the  '  machine  ',  but  the  word 
must  be  understood  in  the  widest  possible  sense,  for  no  restriction 
is  implied  at  the  moment  other  than  that  it  should  be  objective. 

2/2.  As  we  shall  be  more  concerned  in  this  chapter  with  prin- 
ciples than  with  practice,  we  shall  be  concerned  chiefly  with 
constructing  a  method  for  the  study  of  this  unknown  machine. 
When  the  method  is  constructed,  it  must  satisfy  the  demands 
implied  by  the  axioms  of  S.  1/10-15: 

(1)  The  method  must  be  precisely  defined,  and  in  operational 
form; 

13 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  2/3 

(2)  it  must  be  applicable  equally  readily  (at  least  in  principle) 

to  all  material  'machines',  whether  animate  or  inanimate; 

(3)  its  procedure  for  obtaining  information  from  the  '  machine  ' 

must  be  wholly  objective  (i.e.  accessible  or  demonstrable 
to  all  observers); 

(4)  it  must  obtain  its  information  solely  from  the  '  machine  ' 

itself,  no  other  source  being  permitted. 

The  actual  form  developed  may  appear  to  the  practical  worker 
to  be  clumsy  and  inferior  to  methods  already  in  use;  it  probably 
is.  But  it  is  not  intended  to  compete  with  the  many  specialised 
methods  already  in  use.  Such  methods  are  usually  adapted  to  a 
particular  class  of  dynamic  systems:  one  method  is  specially  suited 
to  electronic  circuits,  another  to  rats  in  mazes,  another  to  solutions 
of  reacting  chemicals,  another  to  automatic  pilots,  another  to 
heart-lung  preparations.  The  method  proposed  here  must  have 
the  peculiarity  that  it  is  applicable  to  all;  it  must,  so  to  speak, 
specialise  in  generality. 

Variable  and  system 

2/3.  In  /.  to  C,  Chapter  2,  is  shown  how  the  basic  theory  can 
be  founded  on  the  concept  of  unanalysed  states,  as  a  mother  might 
distinguish,  and  react  adequately  to,  three  expressions  on  her 
baby's  face,  without  analysing  them  into  so  much  opening  of  the 
mouth,  so  much  wrinkling  of  the  nose,  etc.  In  this  book,  however, 
we  shall  be  chiefly  concerned  with  the  relations  between  parts,  so 
we  will  assume  that  the  observer  proceeds  to  record  the  behaviour 
of  the  machine's  individual  parts.  To  do  this  he  identifies  any 
number  of  suitable  variables.  A  variable  is  a  measurable  quantity 
which  at  every  instant  has  a  definite  numerical  value.  A  '  grand- 
father '  clock,  for  instance,  might  provide  the  following  variables: 
— the  angular  deviation  of  the  pendulum  from  the  vertical;  the 
angular  velocity  with  which  the  pendulum  is  moving;  the  angular 
position  of  a  particular  cog-wheel;  the  height  of  a  driving  weight; 
the  reading  of  the  minute-hand  on  the  scale;  and  the  length  of 
the  pendulum.  If  there  is  any  doubt  whether  a  particular 
quantity  may  be  admitted  as  a  '  variable  '  I  shall  use  the  criterion 
whether  it  can  be  represented  by  a  pointer  on  a  dial. 

All  the  quantities  used  in  physics,  chemistry,  biology,  physio- 
logy, and  objective  psychology,  are  variables  in  the  defined  sense. 

14 


2/4  DYNAMIC     SYSTEMS 

Thus,  the  position  of  a  limb  can  be  specified  numerically  by  co- 
ordinates of  position,  and  movement  of  the  limb  can  move  a  pointer 
on  a  dial.  Temperature  at  a  point  can  be  specified  numerically 
and  can  be  recorded  on  a  dial.  Pressure,  angle,  electric  potential, 
volume,  velocity,  torque,  power,  mass,  viscosity,  humidity,  sur- 
face tension,  osmotic  pressure,  specific  gravity,  and  time  itself, 
to  mention  only  a  few,  can  all  be  specified  numerically  and 
recorded  on  dials.  Eddington's  statement  on  the  subject  is 
explicit:  '  The  whole  subject  matter  of  exact  science  consists  of 
pointer  readings  and  similar  indications.'  '  Whatever  quantity 
we  say  we  are  "  observing  ",  the  actual  procedure  nearly  always 
ends  in  reading  the  position  of  some  kind  of  indicator  on  a 
graduated  scale  or  its  equivalent.' 

Whether  the  restriction  to  dial-readings  is  justifiable  with  living 
subjects  will  be  discussed  in  the  next  chapter. 

One  minor  point  should  be  noticed  as  it  will  be  needed  later. 
The  absence  of  an  entity  can  always  be  converted  to  a  reading  on 
a  scale  simply  by  considering  the  entity  to  be  present  but  in 
zero  degree.  Thus,  '  still  air  '  can  be  treated  as  a  wind  blowing  at 
0  m.p.h. ;  4  darkness  '  can  be  treated  as  an  illumination  of  0  foot- 
candles  ;  and  the  giving  of  a  drug  can  be  represented  by  indicating 
that  its  concentration  in  the  tissues  has  risen  from  its  usual  value 
of  0  per  cent. 

2/4.  It  will  be  appreciated  that  every  real  '  machine  '  embodies 
no  less  than  an  infinite  number  of  variables,  all  but  a  few  of  which 
must  of  necessity  be  ignored.  Thus  if  we  were  studying  the  swing 
of  a  pendulum  in  relation  to  its  length  we  would  be  interested  in 
its  angular  deviation  at  various  times,  but  we  would  often  ignore 
the  chemical  composition  of  the  bob,  the  reflecting  power  of  its 
surface,  the  electric  conductivity  of  the  suspending  string,  the 
specific  gravity  of  the  bob,  its  shape,  the  age  of  the  alloy,  its 
degree  of  bacterial  contamination,  and  so  on.  The  list  of  what 
might  be  ignored  could  be  extended  indefinitely.  Faced  with 
this  infinite  number  of  variables,  the  experimenter  must,  and  of 
course  does,  select  a  definite  number  for  examination — in  other 
words,  he  defines  an  abstracted  system.  Thus,  an  experimenter 
once  drew  up  Table  2/4/1.  He  thereby  selected  his  variables, 
of  time  and  three  others,  ready  for  testing.  This  experiment 
being  finished,  he  later  drew  up  other  tables  which  included  new 

15 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


2/5 


Time 
(mins.) 

Distance  of 

secondary 
coil  (cm.) 

Part  of  skin 
stimulated 

Secretion  of 
saliva  during 

30  sees. 

(drops) 

Table  2/4/1 

variables  or  omitted  old.  These  new  combinations  were  new 
systems. 

2/5.  Because  any  real  '  machine  '  has  an  infinity  of  variables, 
from  which  different  observers  (with  different  aims)  may  reason- 
ably make  an  infinity  of  different  selections,  there  must  first  be 
given  an  observer  (or  experimenter);  a  system  is  then  defined  as 
any  set  of  variables  that  he  selects  from  those  available  on  the 
real  *  machine  '.  It  is  thus  a  list,  nominated  by  the  observer, 
and  is  quite  different  in  nature  from  the  real '  machine  '.  Through- 
out the  book,  '  the  system  '  will  always  refer  to  this  abstraction, 
not  to  the  real  material  i  machine  '. 

Among  the  variables  recorded  will  almost  always  be  '  time  ',  so 
one  might  think  that  this  variable  should  be  included  in  the  list 
that  specifies  the  system.  Nevertheless,  time  comes  into  the 
theory  in  a  way  fundamentally  different  from  that  of  all  the 
others.  (The  difference  is  shown  most  clearly  in  the  canonical 
equations  of  S.  19/9.)  Experience  has  shown  that  a  more  con- 
venient classification  is  to  let  the  set  of  variables  be  divided  into 
4  system  '  and  4  time  '.  Time  is  thus  not  to  be  included  in  the 
variables  of  the  system.  In  Table  2/4/1  for  instance,  '  the 
system  '  is  defined  to  be  the  three  variables  on  the  right. 

2/6.  The  state  of  a  system  at  a  given  instant  is  the  set  of  numerical 
values  which  its  variables  have  at  that  instant. 

Thus,  the  six-variable  system  of  S.  2/3  might  at  some  instant 
have  the  state:  —4°,  0-3  radians/sec,  128°,  52  cm.,  42-8  minutes, 
88-4  cm. 

Two  states  are  equal  if  and  only  if  the  two  numerical  values  in 
each  pair  are  equal,  all  pairs  showing  equality. 


16 


2/7  DYNAMIC     SYSTEMS 

The  operational  method 

2/7.  The  variables  being  decided  on,  the  recording  apparatus 
is  now  assumed  to  be  connected  and  the  experimenter  ready  to 
start  observing.  We  must  now  make  clear  what  is  assumed  about 
his  powers  of  control  over  the  system. 

Throughout  the  book  we  shall  consider  only  the  case  in  which 
he  has  access  to  all  states  of  the  system.  It  is  postulated  that  the 
experimenter  can  control  any  variable  he  pleases:  that  he  can 
make  any  variable  take  any  arbitrary  value  at  any  arbitrary 
time.  The  postulate  specifies  nothing  about  the  methods:  it 
demands  only  that  certain  end-results  are  to  be  available.  In 
most  cases  the  means  to  be  used  are  obvious  enough.  Take  the 
example  of  S.  2/3:  an  arbitrary  angular  deviation  of  the  pendulum 
can  be  enforced  at  any  time  by  direct  manipulation;  an  arbitrary 
angular  momentum  can  be  enforced  at  any  time  by  an  appropriate 
impulse;  the  cog  can  be  disconnected  and  shifted,  the  driving- 
weight  wound  up,  the  hand  moved,  and  the  pendulum-bob  lowered. 

By  repeating  the  control  from  instant  to  instant,  the  experi- 
menter can  force  a  variable  to  take  any  prescribed  series  of  values. 
The  postulate,  therefore,  implies  that  any  variable  can  be  forced 
to  follow  a  prescribed  course. 

Some  systems  cannot  be  forced,  for  instance  the  astronomical, 
the  meteorological,  and  those  biological  systems  that  are  accessible 
to  observation  but  not  to  experiment.  Yet  no  change  is  neces- 
sary in  principle :  the  experimenter  simply  waits  until  the  desired 
set  of  values  occurs  during  the  natural  changes  of  the  system, 
and  he  counts  that  instant  as  if  it  were  the  instant  at  which  the 
system  were  started.  Thus,  though  he  cannot  create  a  thunder- 
storm, he  can  observe  how  swallows  react  to  one  simply  by 
waiting  till  one  occurs  '  spontaneously  '. 

It  will  also  be  assumed  (except  where  explicitly  mentioned)  that 
he  has  similarly  complete  control  over  those  variables  that  are 
not  in  the  system  yet  which  have  an  effect  on  it.  In  the  experi- 
ment of  Table  2/4/1  for  instance,  Pavlov  had  control  not  only  of 
the  variables  mentioned  but  also  of  the  many  variables  that  might 
have  affected  the  system's  behaviour,  such  as  the  lights  that 
might  have  flashed,  the  odours  that  might  have  been  applied,  and 
the  noises  that  might  have  come  from  outside. 

The  assumption  that  the  control  is  complete  is  made  because, 

17 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  2/8 

as  will  be  seen  later  (and  as  has  been  shown  in  /.  to  C),  it  makes 
possible  a  theory  that  is  clear,  simple,  and  coherent.  The  theories 
that  arise  when  we  consider  the  more  realistic  state  of  affairs  in 
which  not  all  states  are  accessible,  or  not  all  variables  controllable, 
are  tangled  and  complicated,  and  not  suitable  as  a  basis.  These 
complicated  variations  can  all  be  derived  from  the  basic  theory 
by  the  addition  of  complications.  For  the  moment  we  shall 
postpone  them. 

2/8.  The  primary  operation  that  wins  new  knowledge  from  the 
*  machine  '  is  as  follows : — The  experimenter  uses  his  power  of 
control  to  determine  (select,  enforce)  a  particular  state  in  the 
system.  He  also  determines  (selects,  enforces)  the  values  of  the 
surrounding  conditions  of  the  system.  He  then  allows  one  unit 
of  time  to  elapse  and  he  observes  to  what  state  the  system  goes 
as  it  moves  under  the  drive  of  its  own  dynamic  nature.  He 
observes,  in  other  words,  a  transition,  from  a  particular  state, 
under  particular  conditions. 

Usually  the  experimenter  wants  to  know  the  transitions  from 
many  states  under  many  conditions.  Then  he  often  saves  time 
by  allowing  the  transitions  to  occur  in  chains;  having  found  that 
A  is  followed  by  B,  he  simply  observes  what  comes  next,  and  thus 
discovers  the  transition  from  B,  and  so  on. 

This  description  may  make  the  definition  sound  arbitrary  and 
unnatural ;  in  fact,  it  describes  only  what  every  experimenter  does 
when  investigating  an  unknown  dynamic  system.  Here  are  some 
examples. 

In  chemical  dynamics  the  variables  are  often  the  concentra- 
tions of  substances.  Selected  concentrations  are  brought  together, 
and  from  a  definite  moment  are  allowed  to  interact  while  the 
temperature  is  held  constant.  The  experimenter  records  the 
changes  which  the  concentrations  undergo  with  time. 

In  a  mechanical  experiment  the  variables  might  be  the  positions 
and  momenta  of  certain  bodies.  At  a  definite  instant  the  bodies, 
started  with  selected  velocities  from  selected  positions,  are  allowed 
to  interact.  The  experimenter  records  the  changes  which  the 
velocities  and  positions  undergo  with  time. 

In  studies  of  the  conduction  of  heat,  the  variables  are  the 
temperatures  at  various  places  in  the  heated  body.  A  prescribed 
distribution  of  temperatures  is  enforced,  and,  while  the  tempera- 

18 


2/10  DYNAMIC     SYSTEMS 

tures  of  some  places  are  held  constant,  the  variations  of  the 
other  temperatures  are  observed  after  the  initial  moment. 

In  physiology,  the  variables  might  be  the  rate  of  a  rabbit's 
heart-beat,  the  intensity  of  faradisation  applied  to  the  vagus 
nerve,  and  the  concentration  of  adrenaline  in  the  circulating 
bloocj.  The  intensity  of  faradisation  will  be  continuously  under 
the  experimenter's  control.  Not  improbably  it  will  be  kept  first 
at  zero  and  then  increased.  From  a  given  instant  the  changes 
in  the  variables  will  be  recorded. 

In  experimental  psychology,  the  variables  might  be  '  the  number 
of  mistakes  made  by  a  rat  on  a  trial  in  a  maze  '  and  4  the  amount 
of  cerebral  cortex  which  has  been  removed  surgically  '.  The 
second  variable  is  permanently  under  the  experimenter's  control. 
The  experimenter  starts  the  experiment  and  observes  how  the 
first  variable  changes  with  time  while  the  second  variable  is  held 
constant,  or  caused  to  change  in  some  prescribed  manner. 

2/9.  The  detailed  statement  just  given  about  what  the  experi- 
menter can  do  and  observe  is  necessary  because  we  must  (as  later 
chapters  will  show)  be  quite  clear  about  the  sources  of  the  experi- 
menter's knowledge. 

Ordinarily,  when*  an  experimenter  examines  a  machine  he  makes 
full  use  of  knowledge  '  borrowed  '  from  past  experience.  If  he 
sees  two  cogs  enmeshed  he  knows  that  their  two  rotations  will  not 
be  independent,  even  though  he  does  not  see  them  actually  rotate. 
This  knowledge  comes  from  previous  experiences  in  which  the 
mutual  relations  of  similar  pairs  have  been  tested  and  observed 
directly.  Such  borrowed  knowledge  is,  of  course,  extremely  use- 
ful, and  every  skilled  experimenter  brings  a  great  store  of  it  to 
every  experiment.  Nevertheless  it  must  be  excluded  from  any 
fundamental  method,  if  only  because  it  is  not  wholly  reliable:  the 
unexpected  sometimes  happens;  and  the  only  way  to  be  certain 
of  the  relation  between  parts  in  a  new  machine  is  to  test  the 
relation  directly. 

2/10.  While  a  single  primary  operation  may  seem  to  yield  little 
information,  the  power  of  the  method  lies  in  the  fact  that  the 
experimenter  can  repeat  it  with  variations,  and  can  relate  the 
different  responses  to  the  different  variations.  Thus,  after  one 
primary  operation  the  next  may  be  varied  in  any  of  three  ways : 

19 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  2/11 

the  system  may  be  changed  by  the  inclusion  of  new  variables 
or  by  the  omission  of  old;  the  initial  state  may  be  changed; 
or  the  surrounding  states  may  be  changed.  By  applying  these 
variations  systematically,  in  different  patterns  and  groupings,  the 
different  responses  may  be  interrelated  to  yield  relations. 

By  further  orderly  variations,  these  relations  may  be  further 
interrelated  to  yield  secondary,  or  hyper-,  relations ;  and  so  on. 
In  this  way  the  'machine'  may  be  made  to  yield  more  and  more 
complex  information  about  its  inner  organisation. 

What  is  fundamental  about  this  method  is  that  the  transition 
is  a  purely  objective  and  demonstrable  fact.  By  basing  all  our 
later  concepts  on  jthe  properties  of  transitions  we  can  be  sure  that 
the  more  complex  concepts  involve  no  component  other  than  the 
objective  and  demonstrable.  All  our  concepts  will  eventually  be 
denned  in  terms  of  this  method.  For  example,  '  environment '  is 
so  defined  in  S.  3/8,  '  adaptation  '  in  S.  5/3,  and  '  stimulus  '  in 
S.  6/5.  If  any  have  been  omitted  it  is  by  oversight;  for  I  hold 
that  this  procedure  is  sufficient  for  their  objective  definition. 


Phase-space  and  Field 

2/11.  Often  the  experimenter,  while  controlling  the  external 
conditions,  allows  the  system  to  pass  from  state  to  state  without 
interrupting  its  flow,  so  that  if  he  started  it  at  state  A  and  it  went 
to  B,  he  allows  it  then  to  proceed  from  B  to  C,  from  C  to  Z), 
and  so  on. 

A  line  of  behaviour  is  specified  by  a  succession  of  states  and  the 
time-intervals  between  them.  The  first  state  in  a  line  of  behaviour 
will  be  called  the  initial  state.  Two  lines  of  behaviour  are  equal 
if  all  the  corresponding  pairs  of  states  are  equal,  and  if  all  the 
corresponding  pairs  of  time-intervals  are  equal. 

2/12.  There  are  several  ways  in  which  a  line  of  behaviour  may 
be  recorded. 

The  graphical  method  is  exemplified  by  Figure  2/12/1.  The 
four  variables  form,  by  definition,  the  system  that  is  being 
examined.  The  four  simultaneous  values  at  any  instant  define 
a  state.  And  the  succession  of  states  at  their  particular  intervals 
constitute  and  specify  the  line  of  behaviour.  The  four  traces 
specify  one  line  of  behaviour. 

20 


2/12 


DYNAMIC     SYSTEMS 


Sometimes  a  line  of  behaviour  can  be  specified  in  terms  of 
elementary  mathematical  functions.  Such  a  simplicity  is  con- 
venient when  it  occurs,  but  is  rarer  in  practice  than  an  acquaintance 
with  elementary  mathematics  would  suggest.  With  biological 
material  it  is  rare. 


r*~\ 


imimA0~%iwMJi  ■ ; 


Time  — *- 

Figure  2/12/1  :  Events  during  an  experiment  on  a  conditioned  reflex  in 
a  sheep.  Attached  to  the  left  foreleg  is  an  electrode  by  which  a  shock 
can  be  administered.  Line  A  records  the  position  of  the  left  forefoot. 
Line  B  records  the  sheep's  respiratory  movements.  Line  C  records 
by  a  rise  (E)  the  application  of  the  conditional  stimulus  :  the  sound 
of  a  buzzer.  Line  D  records  by  a  vertical  stroke  (F)  the  application  of 
the  electric  shock.     (After  Liddell  et  al.) 

Another  form  is  the  tabular,  of  which  an  example  is  Table  2/12/1. 
Each  column  defines  one  state;  the  whole  table  defines  one  line 
of  behaviour  (other  tables  may  contain  more  than  one  line  of 
behaviour).     The  state  at  0  hours  is  the  initial  state. 


Time  (hours) 

0 

1 

3 

6 

W 

7-35 

7-26 

7-28 

7-29 

u 

x> 

X 

156-7 

154-6 

1541 

151-5 

c8 

03 

y 

110-3 

116-7 

118-3 

118-5 

> 

z 

222 

153 

150 

14-6 

Table  2/12/1  :  Blood  changes  after  a  dose  of  ammonium  chloride,  w 
=  serum  pH  ;  x  =  serum  total  base  ;  y  =  serum  chloride  ;  z  =  serum 
bicarbonate  ;   (the  last  three  in  m.  eq.  per  1.). 

21 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


2/13 


The  tabular  form  has  one  outstanding  advantage:  it  contains 
the  facts  and  nothing  more.  Mathematical  forms  are  apt  to 
suggest  too  much:  continuity  that  has  not  been  demonstrated, 
fictitious  values  between  the  moments  of  observation,  and  an 
accuracy  that  may  not  be  present.  Unless  specially  mentioned, 
all  lines  of  behaviour  will  be  assumed  to  be  recorded  primarily 
in  tabular  form. 

2/13.  The  behaviour  of  a  system  can  also  be  represented  in. 
phase-space.  By  its  use  simple  proofs  may  be  given  of  many 
statements  difficult  to  prove  in  the  tabular  form. 


/O 


A) 


5- 


IO 


Figure  2/13/1. 


If  a  system  is  composed  of  two  variables,  a  particular  state 
will  be  specified  by  two  numbers.  By  ordinary  graphic  methods, 
the  two  variables  can  be  represented  by  axes ;  the  two  numbers 
will  then  define  a  point  in  the  plane,  Thus  the  state  in  which 
variable  x  has  the  value  5  and  variable  y  the  value  10  will  be 
represented  by  the  point  A  in  Figure  2/13/1.  The  representative 
point  of  a  state  is  the  point  whose  co-ordinates  are  respectively  equal 
to  the  values  of  the  variables.  By  S.  2/5  '  time  '  is  not  to  be  one 
of  the  axes. 

Suppose  next  that  a  system  of  two  variables  gave  the  line  of 
behaviour  shown  in  Table  2/13/1.     The  successive  states  will  be 

22 


2/14 


DYNAMIC     SYSTEMS 


graphed,  by  the  method,  at  positions  B,  C,  and  D  (Figure  2/13/1). 
So  the  system's  behaviour  corresponds  to  a  movement  of  the 
representative  point  along  the  line  in  the  phase-space. 

By  comparing  the  Table  and  the  Figure,  certain  exact  corre- 
spondences can  be  found.     Every  state  of  the  system  corresponds 


Time 

X 

y 

0 

5 

10 

1 

6 

9 

2 

7 

7 

3 

5 

4 

Table  2/13/1. 

uniquely  to  a  point  in  the  plane,  and  every  point  in  the  plane 
(or  in  some  portion  of  it)  to  some  possible  state  of  the  system. 
Further,  every  line  of  behaviour  of  the  system  corresponds 
uniquely  to  a  line  in  the  plane.  If  the  system  has  three  variables, 
the  graph  must  be  in  three  dimensions,  but  each  state  still  corre- 
sponds to  a  point,  and  each  line  of  behaviour  to  a  line  in  the  phase- 
space.  If  the  number  of  variables  exceeds  three,  this  method  of 
graphing  is  no  longer  physically  possible,  but  the  correspondence 
is  maintained  exactly  no  matter  how  numerous  the  variables. 


2/14.  A  system's  field*  is  the  phase-space  containing  all  the  lines 
of  behaviour  found  by  releasing  the  system  from  all  possible  initial 
states  in  a  particular  set  of  surrounding  conditions. 

In  practice,  of  course,  the  experimenter  would  test  only  a  repre- 
sentative sample  of  the  initial  states.  Some  of  them  will  probably 
be  tested  repeatedly,  for  the  experimenter  will  usuallv  want  to 
make  sure  that  the  system  is  giving  reproducible  lines  of  behaviour. 
Thus  in  one  experiment,  in  which  dogs  had  been  severely  bled 
and  then  placed  on  a  standard  diet,  their  body-weight  x  and  the 
concentration  y  of  haemoglobin  in  their  blood  were  recorded  at 
weekly  intervals.  This  two- variable  system,  tested  from  four 
initial  states  by  thirty-six  primary  operations,  gave  the  field  shown 
in  Figure  2/14/1.     Other  examples  occur  frequently  later. 

It  will  be  noticed  that  a  field  is  defined,  in  accordance  with 

*  Some  name  is  necessary  for  such  a  representation  as  Figure  2/13/1,  especially 
as  the  concept  must  be  used  incessantly  throughout  the  book.  I  hope  that  a 
better  word  than  4  field  '  will  be  found,  but  I  have  not  found  one  yet. 

23 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


2/14 


S.  2/9,  by  reference  exclusively  to  the  observed  values  of  the 
variables  and  to  the  results  of  primary  operations  on  them.  It 
is  therefore  a  wholly  objective  property  of  the  system. 

The  concept  of  4  field  '  will  be  used  extensively.  It  defines  the 
characteristic  behaviour  of  the  system,  replacing  the  vague  con- 
cept of  what  a  system  '  does  '  or  how  it  '  behaves  '  (often  describ- 
able  only  in  words)  by  the  precise  construct  of  a  '  field  '.     Further 


5  10  15 

Weight  of  dog   (kg.) 

Figure  2/14/1  :  Arrow-heads  show  the  direction  of  movement  of  the 
representative  point ;  cross-lines  show  the  positions  of  the  representative 
point  at  weekly  intervals. 

it  presents  all  a  system's  behaviours  (under  constant  conditions) 
frozen  into  one  unchanging  entity  that  can  be  thought  of  as  a 
unit.  Such  entities  can  readily  be  compared  and  contrasted,  and 
so  we  can  readily  compare  behaviour  with  behaviour,  on  a  basis 
that  is  as  complete  and  rigorous  as  we  care  to  make  it. 

The  reader  may  at  first  find  the  method  unusual.  Those  who 
are  familiar  with  the  phase-space  of  mechanics  will  have  no 
difficulty,  but  other  readers  may  find  it  helpful  if  at  first,  whenever 
the  word  '  field  '  occurs,  they  substitute  for  it  some  phrase  like 
4  typical  way  of  behaving  '. 


24 


2/15  DYNAMIC     SYSTEMS 

The  Natural  System 

2/15.  In  S.  2/5  a  system  was  defined  as  any  arbitrarily  selected 
set  of  variables.  The  right  to  arbitrary  selection  cannot  be 
waived,  but  the  time  has  now  come  to  recognise  that  both  Science 
and  common  sense  insist  that  if  a  system  is  to  be  studied  with 
profit  its  variables  must  have  some  naturalness  of  association. 
But  what  is  '  natural '  ?  The  problem  has  inevitably  arisen  after 
the  restriction  of  S.  2/9,  where  we  repudiated  all  borrowed 
knowledge.  If  we  restrict  our  attention  to  the  variables,  we  find 
that  as  every  real  4  machine  '  provides  an  infinity  of  variables, 
and  as  from  them  we  can  form  another  infinity  of  combinations, 
we  need  some  test  to  distinguish  the  natural  system  from  the 
arbitrary. 

One  criterion  will  occur  to  the  practical  experimenter  at  once. 
He  knows  that  if  an  active  and  relevant  variable  is  left  unobserved 
or  uncontrolled  the  system's  behaviour  will  become  capricious, 
not  capable  of  being  reproduced  at  will.  This  concept  may 
readily  be  made  more  precise.  We  simply  state  formally  the 
century-old  idea  that  a  '  machine  '  is  something  that,  if  its  internal 
state  is  known,  and  its  surrounding  conditions,  then  its  behaviour 
follows  necessarily.  That  is  to  say,  a  particular  surrounding 
condition  (or  input,  i.e.  those  variables  that  affect  it)  and  a 
particular  state  determine  uniquely  what  transition  will  occur. 

So  the  formal  definition  goes  as  follows.  Take  some  particular 
set  of  external  conditions  (or  input-value)  C  and  some  particular 
state  S  ;  observe  the  transition  that  is  induced  by  its  own  internal 
drive  and  laws  ;  suppose  it  goes  to  state  S{.  Notice  whether, 
whenever  C  and  S  occur  again,  the  transition  is  also  always  to 
St ;  if  so,  record  that  the  transitions  that  follow  C  and  S  are 
invariant.  Next,  vary  C  (or  S,  or  both)  to  get  another  pair — 
Cx  and  S1  say  ;  see  similarly  whether  the  transitions  that  follow 
C±  and  S1  are  also  invariant.  Proceed  similarly  till  all  possible 
pairs  have  been  tested.  If  the  outcome  at  every  pair  was 
4  invariant  '  then  the  system  is,  by  definition,  a  machine  with 
input.     (This  definition  accords  with  that  given  in  /.  to  C.) 

In  the  world  of  biology,  the  concept  of  the  machine  with  input 
often  occurs  in  the  specially  simple  case  in  which  all  the  events 
(in  one  field)  occur  in  only  one  set  of  conditions  (i.e.  C  has  the 
same  value  for  all  the  lines  of  behaviour).     The  field  then  comes 

25 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN 


2/15 


from  a  system  that  is  isolated.  Thus,  an  experimenter  may 
subject  a  Protozoon  to  a  drug  at  a  certain  concentration;  he  then 
observes,  without  further  experimental  interference,  the  whole  line 
of  behaviour  (which  may  be  long  and  complex)  that  follows.  This 
case  occurs  with  sufficient  frequency  in  biological  systems  and  in 
this  book  to  deserve  a  special  name;  it  will  be  referred  to  here  as 
a  state-determined  system. 


Time  (seconds) 

Line 

Variable 

0 

01 

0-2 

0-3 

X 

0 

0-2 

0-4 

0-6 

1 

y 

20 

21 

2-3 

2-6 

X 

-  0-2 

-  01 

0 

01 

2 

y 

2-4 

22 

20 

1-8 

Table  2/15/1. 

As  illustration  of  the  definition,  consider  Table  2/15/1,  which 
shows  two  lines  of  behaviour  from  a  system  that  is  not  state- 
determined.  On  the  first  line  of  behaviour  the  state  x  =  0, 
y  =  2-0  was  followed  after  0-1   seconds  by  the  state  x  =  0-2, 


Figure  2/15/1  :  Field  of  a  simple  pendulum  40  cm.  long  swinging  in  a 
vertical  plane  when  g  is  981  cm./sec.2.  x  is  the  angle  of  deviation  from 
the  vertical  and  y  the  angular  velocity  of  movement.  Cross-strokes 
mark  the  position  of  the  representative  point  at  each  one-tenth  second. 
The  clockwise  direction  should  be  noticed. 

26 


2/16  DYNAMIC     SYSTEMS 

y  =  2-1.  On  line  2  the  state  x  =  0,  y  =  2-0  occurred  again;  but 
after  0-1  seconds  the  state  became  x  =  0-1,  */  =  1-8  and  not 
x  =  0-2,  y  =  2-1.  As  the  two  states  that  follow  the  state  x  =  0, 
y  =  2-0  are  not  equal,  the  system  is  not  state-determined. 

A  well-known  example  of  a  state-determined  system  is  given 
by  the  simple  pendulum  swinging  in  a  vertical  plane.  It  is  known 
that  the  two  variables — (x)  angle  of  deviation  of  the  string  from 
vertical,  (y)  angular  velocity  (or  momentum)  of  the  bob — are 
such  that,  all  else  being  kept  constant,  their  two  values  at  a 
given  instant  are  sufficient  to  determine  the  subsequent  changes 
of  the  two  variables  (Figure  2/15/1). 

The  field  of  a  state-determined  system  has  a  characteristic 
property:  through  no  point  does  more 
than  one  line  of  behaviour  run.  This 
fact  may  be  contrasted  with  that  of  a 
system  that  is  not  state-determined. 
Figure  2/15/2  shows  such  a  field  (the 
system  is  described  in  S.  19/13).  The 
system's  regularity  would  be  established 
if  we  found  that  the  system,  started  at 

A,  always  went  to  A',  and,  started  at 

B,  always  went  to  B' .  But  such  a 
system  is  not  state-determined;  for  to 
say  that  the  representative  point  is 
leaving  C   is   insufficient   to   define   its 

future  line  of  behaviour,  which  may  go  to  A'  or  B '.  Even  if  the 
lines  from  A  and  B  always  ran  to  A'  and  B',  the  regularity  in  no 
way  restricts  what  would  happen  if  the  system  were  started  at 
C:  it  might  go  to  D.  If  the  system  were  state-determined,  the 
lines  CA',  CB\  and  CD  would  coincide. 


Figure  2/15/2  :  The  field 
of  the  system  shown  in 
Figure  19/13/1. 


2/16.  We  can  now  return  to  the  question  of  what  we  mean  when 
we  say  that  a  system's  variables  have  a  '  natural '  association. 
What  we  need  is  not  a  verbal  explanation  but  a  definition,  which 
must  have  these  properties: 

(1)  it  must  be  in  the  form  of  a  test,  separating  all  systems  into 

two  classes; 

(2)  its  application  must  be  wholly  objective; 

(3)  its  result  must  agree  with  common  sense  in  typical  and 

undisputed  cases. 

27 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  2/17 

The  third  property  makes  clear  that  we  cannot  expect  a  proposed 
definition  to  be  established  by  a  few  lines  of  verbal  argument: 
it  must  be  treated  as  a  working  hypothesis  and  used ;  only  experi- 
ence can  show  whether  it  is  faulty  or  sound.  (Nevertheless,  in 
J.  to  C,  S.  13/5,  I  have  given  reasons  suggesting  that  the  property 
of  being  state-determined  must  inevitably  be  of  fundamental 
interest  to  every  organism  that,  like  the  human  scientist,  wants 
to  achieve  mastery  over  its  surroundings.) 

Because  of  its  importance,  science  searches  persistently  for  the 
state-determined.  As  a  working  guide,  the  scientist  has  for  some 
centuries  followed  the  hypothesis  that,  given  a  set  of  variables, 
he  can  always  find  a  larger  set  that  (1)  includes  the  given  variables, 
and  (2)  is  state-determined.  Much  research  work  consists  of 
trying  to  identify  such  a  larger  set,  for  when  the  set  is  too  small, 
important  variables  will  be  left  out  of  account,  and  the  behaviour 
of  the  set  will  be  capricious.  The  assumption  that  such  a  larger 
set  exists  is  implicit  in  almost  all  science,  but,  being  fundamental, 
it  is  seldom  mentioned  explicitly.  Temple,  though,  refers  to 
4.  .  .  the  fundamental  assumption  of  macrophysics  that  a  com- 
plete knowledge  of  the  present  state  of  a  system  furnishes  sufficient 
data  to  determine  definitely  its  state  at  any  future  time  or  its 
response  to  any  external  influence  \  Laplace  made  the  same 
assumption  about  the  whole  universe  when  he  stated  that,  given 
its  state  at  one  instant,  its  future  progress  should  be  calculable. 
The  definition  given  above  makes  this  assumption  precise  and 
gives  it  in  a  form  ready  for  use  in  the  later  chapters. 

The  assumption  is  now  known  to  be  false  at  the  atomic  level. 
We,  however,  will  seldom  discuss  events  at  this  level;  and  as  the 
assumption  has  proved  substantially  true  over  great  ranges  of 
macroscopic  science,  we  shall  use  it  extensively. 


Strategy  for  the  complex  system 

2/17.  The  discussion  of  this  chapter  may  have  seemed  confined 
to  a  somewhat  arbitrary  set  of  concepts,  and  the  biologist,  accus- 
tomed to  a  great  range  of  variety  in  his  material,  may  be  thinking 
that  the  concepts  and  definitions  are  much  too  restricted.  As  this 
book  puts  forward  a  theory  of  the  origin  of  adaptation,  it  must 
show  how  a  theory,  developed  so  narrowly,  can  be  acceptable. 
In  this  connexion  we  must  note  that  theories  are  of  various 

28 


2/17  DYNAMIC     SYSTEMS 

types.  At  one  extreme  is  Newton's  theory  of  gravitation — at  once 
simple,  and  precise,  and  exactly  true.  When  such  a  combination 
is  possible,  Science  is  indeed  lucky  !  Darwin's  theory,  on  the 
other  hand,  is  not  so  simple,  is  of  quite  low  accuracy  numerically, 
and  is  true  only  in  a  partial  sense — that  the  simple  arguments 
usually  used  to  apply  it  in  practice  (e.g.  how  spraying  with  D.D.T, 
will  ultimately  affect  the  genetic  constitution  of  the  field  mouse, 
by  altering  its  food  supply)  are  gross  simplifications  of  the  complex 
of  events  that  will  actually  occur. 

The  theory  attempted  in  this  book  is  of  the  latter  type.  The 
real  facts  of  the  brain  are  so  complex  and  varied  that  no  theory 
can  hope  to  achieve  the  simplicity  and  precision  of  Newton's; 
what  then  must  it  do  ?  I  suggest  that  it  must  try  to  be  exact  in 
certain  selected  cases,  these  cases  being  selected  because  there  we 
can  be  exact.  With  these  exact  cases  known,  we  can  then  face 
the  multitudinous  cases  that  do  not  quite  correspond,  using  the 
rule  that  if  we  are  satisfied  that  there  is  some  continuity  in  the 
systems'  properties,  then  insofar  as  each  is  near  some  exact  case, 
so  will  its  properties  be  near  to  those  shown  by  the  exact  case. 

This  scientific  strategy  is  by  no  means  as  inferior  as  it  may 
sound;  in  fact  it  is  used  widely  in  many  sciences  of  good  repute. 
Thus  the  perfect  gas,  the  massless  spring,  the  completely  reflecting 
mirror,  the  leakless  condenser  are  all  used  freely  in  the  theories 
of  physics.  These  idealised  cases  have  no  real  existence,  but  they 
are  none  the  less  important  because  they  are  both  simple  and 
exact,  and  are  therefore  key  points  in  the  general  theoretical 
structure. 

In  the  same  spirit  this  book  will  attend  closely  to  certain 
idealised  cases,  important  because  they  can  be  exactly  defined  and 
because  they  are  manageably  simple.  Maybe  it  will  be  found 
eventually  that  not  a  single  mechanism  in  the  brain  corresponds 
exactly  to  the  types  described  here ;  nevertheless  the  work  will  not 
be  wasted  if  a  thorough  knowledge  of  these  idealised  forms  enables 
us  to  understand  the  workings  of  many  mechanisms  that  resemble 
them  only  as  approximations. 


29 


CHAPTER   3 

The  Organism  as  Machine 

3/1.  In  accordance  with  S.  1/11  we  shall  assume  at  once  that 
the  living  organism  in  its  nature  and  processes  is  not  essentially 
different  from  other  matter.  The  truth  of  the  assumption  will 
not  be  discussed.  The  chapter  will  therefore  deal  only  with  the 
technique  of  applying  this  assumption  to  the  complexities  of 
biological  systems. 

The  specification  of  behaviour 

3/2.  If  the  method  laid  down  in  the  previous  chapter  is  to  be 
followed,  we  must  first  determine  to  what  extent  the  behaviour 
of  an  organism  is  capable  of  being  specified  by  variables,  remem- 
bering that  our  ultimate  test  is  whether  the  representation  can 
be  by  dial  readings  (S.  2/3). 

There  can  be  little  doubt  that  any  single  quantity  observable 
in  the  living  organism  can  be  treated  at  least  in  principle  as  a 
variable.  All  bodily  movements  can  be  specified  by  co-ordinates. 
All  joint  movements  can  be  specified  by  angles.  Muscle  tensions 
can  be  specified  by  their  pull  in  dynes.  Muscle  movements  can 
be  specified  by  co-ordinates  based  on  the  bony  structure  or  on 
some  fixed  external  point,  and  can  therefore  be  recorded  numeric- 
ally. A  gland  can  be  specified  in  its  activity  by  its  rate  of 
secretion.  Pulse-rate,  blood-pressure,  temperature,  rate  of  blood- 
flow,  tension  of  smooth  muscle,  and  a  host  of  other  variables  can 
be  similarly  recorded. 

In  the  nervous  system  our  attempts  to  observe,  measure,  and 
record  have  met  great  technical  difficulties.  Nevertheless,  much 
has  been  achieved.  The  action  potential,  one  of  the  essential 
events  in  the  activity  of  the  nervous  system,  can  now  be  measured 
and  recorded.  The  excitatory  and  inhibitory  states  of  the  centres 
are  at  the  moment  not  directly  recordable,  but  there  is  no  reason 
to  suppose  that  they  will  never  become  so. 

30 


3/3  THE  ORGANISM  AS  MACHINE 

3/3.  Few  would  deny  that  the  elementary  physico-chemical 
events  in  the  living  organism  can  be  treated  as  variables.  But 
some  may  hesitate  before  accepting  that  readings  on  dials  (and 
the  complex  relations  deducible  from  them)  are  adequate  for  the 
description  of  all  significant  biological  events.  As  the  remainder 
of  the  book  will  assume  that  they  are  sufficient,  I  must  show  how 
the  various  complexities  of  biological  experience  can  be  reduced 
to  this  standard  form. 

A  simple  case  which  may  be  mentioned  first  occurs  when  an 
event  is  recorded  in  the  form  '  strychnine  was  injected  at  this 
moment  ',  or  '  a  light  was  switched  on  ',  or  '  an  electric  shock  was 
administered  '.  Such  a  statement  treats  only  the  positive  event 
as  having  existence  and  ignores  the  other  state  as  a  nullity.  It 
can  readily  be  converted  to  a  numerical  form  suitable  for  our 
purpose  by  using  the  device  mentioned  in  S.  2/3.  Such  events 
would  then  be  recorded  by  assuming,  in  the  first  case,  that  the 
animal  always  had  strychnine  in  its  tissues  but  that  at  first  the 
quantity  present  was  0  mg.  per  g.  tissue;  in  the  second  case,  that 
the  light  was  always  on,  but  that  at  first  it  shone  with  a  brightness 
of  0  candlepower;  and  in  the  last  case,  that  an  electric  potential 
was  applied  throughout  but  that  at  first  it  had  a  value  of  0  volts. 
Such  a  method  of  description  cannot  be  wrong  in  these  cases  for 
it  defines  exactly  the  same  set  of  objective  facts.  Its  advantage 
from  our  point  of  view  is  that  it  provides  a  method  which  can  be 
used  uniformly  over  a  wide  range  of  phenomena:  the  variable  is 
always  present,  merely  varying  in  value. 

But  this  device  does  not  remove  all  difficulties.  It  sometimes 
happens  in  physiology  and  psychology  that  a  variable  seems  to  have 
no  numerical  counter-part.  Thus  in  one  experiment  two  cards, 
one  black  and  one  brown,  were  shown  alternately  to  an  animal  as 
stimuli.  One  variable  would  thus  be  '  colour  '  and  it  would  have 
two  values.  <The  simplest  way  to  specify  colour  numerically  is  to 
give  the  wave-length  of  its  light ;  but  this  method  cannot  be  used 
here,  for  '  black  '  means  '  no  light  ',  and  '  brown  '  does  not  occur 
in  the  spectrum.  Another  example  would  occur  if  an  electric 
heater  were  regularly  used  and  if  its  switch  indicated  only  the 
degrees  '  high  ',  '  medium  ',  and  4  low  '.  Another  example  is  given 
on  many  types  of  electric  apparatus  by  a  pilot  light  which,  as  a 
variable,  takes  only  the  two  values  '  lit  '  and  '  unlit '.  More 
complex  examples  occur  frequently  in  psychological  experiments. 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  3/3 

Table  2/4/1 ,  for  instance,  contains  a  variable  '  part  of  skin  stimu- 
lated '  which,  in  Pavlov's  Table,  takes  only  two  values:  'usual 
place  '  and  '  new  place  '.  Even  more  complicated  variables  are 
common  in  Pavlov's  experiments.  Many  a  Table  contains  a 
variable  '  stimulus  '  which  takes  such  values  as  '  bubbling  water  ', 
1  metronome  ',  '  flashing  light  '.  A  similar  difficulty  occurs  when 
an  experimenter  tests  an  animal's  response  to  injections  of  toxins, 
so  that  there  will  be  a  variable  '  type  of  toxin  '  which  may  take 
the  two  values  4  Diphtheria  type  Gravis  '  and  '  Diphtheria  type 
Medius  '.  And  finally  the  change  may  involve  an  extensive 
re-organisation  of  the  whole  experimental  situation.  Such  would 
occur  if  the  experimenter,  wanting  to  test  the  effect  of  the  general 
surroundings,  tried  the  effect  of  the  variable  '  situation  of  the 
experiment '  by  giving  it  alternately  the  two*  values'  '  in  the 
animal  house  '  and  '  in  the  open  air  '.  Can  such  variables  be 
represented  by  number  ? 

In  some  of  the  examples,  the  variables  might  possibly  be  speci- 
fied numerically  by  a  more  or  less  elaborate  specification  of  their 
physical  nature.  Thus  '  part  of  skin  stimulated  '  might  be 
specified  by  reference  to  some  system  of  co-ordinates  marked  on 
the  skin ;  and  the  three  intensities  of  the  electric  heater  might  be 
specified  by  the  three  values  of  the  watts  consumed.  But  this 
method  is  hardly  possible  in  the  remainder  of  the  cases ;  nor  is  it 
necessary.  For  numbers  can  be  used  cardinally  as  well  as 
ordinally,  that  is,  they  may  be  used  as  mere  labels  without  any 
reference  to  their  natural  order.  Such  are  the  numberings  of  the 
divisions  of  an  army,  and  of  the  subscribers  on  a  telephone  system ; 
for  the  subscriber  whose  number  is,  say,  4051  has  no  particular 
relation  to  the  subscriber  whose  number  is  4052:  the  number 
identifies  him  but  does  not  relate  him. 

It  may  be  shown  (S.  21/6)  that  if  a  variable  takes  a  few  values 
which  stand  in  no  simple  relation  to  one  another,  then  each  value 
may  be  allotted  an  arbitrary  number;  and  provided  that  the 
numbers  are  used  systematically  throughout  the  experiment,  and 
that  their  use  is  confined  to  the  experiment,  then  no  confusion 
can  arise.  Thus  the  variable  '  situation  of  the  experiment  ' 
might  be  allotted  the  arbitrary  value  of  '  1  '  if  the  experiment 
occurs  in  the  animal  house,  and  '  2  '  if  it  occurs  in  the  open  air. 

Although  '  situation  of  the  experiment  '  involves  a  great  number 
of  physical  variables,  the  aggregate  may  justifiably  be  treated  as 

32 


3/5  THE     ORGANISM    AS     MACHINE 

a  single  variable  provided  the  arrangement  of  the  experiment  is 
such  that  the  many  variables  are  used  throughout  as  one  aggre- 
gate which  can  take  either  of  two  forms.  If,  however,  the 
aggregate  were  split  in  the  experiment,  as  would  happen  if  we 
recorded  four  classes  of  results: 

(1)  in  the  animal  house  in  summer 

(2)  in  the  animal  house  in  winter 

(3)  in  the  open  air  in  summer 

(4)  in  the  open  air  in  winter 

then  we  must  either  allow  the  variable  '  condition  of  experiment ' 
to  take  four  values,  or  we  could  consider  the  experiment  as 
subject  to  two  variables;  'site  of  experiment'  and  'season  of 
year  ',  each  of  which  takes  two  values.  According  to  this  method, 
what  is  important  is  not  the  material  structure  of  the  technical 
devices  but  the  experiment's  logical  structure. 

3/4.  But  is  the  method  yet  adequate  ?  Can  all  the  living 
organisms'  more  subtle  qualities  be  numericised  in  this  way  ?  On 
this  subject  there  has  been  much  dispute,  but  we  can  avoid  a  part 
of  the  controversy;  for  here  we  are  concerned  only  with  certain 
qualities  defined. 

First,  we  shall  be  dealing  not  with  qualities  but  with  behaviour: 
we  shall  be  dealing,  not  with  what  an  organism  feels  or  thinks, 
but  with  what  it  does.  The  omission  of  all  subjective  aspects 
(S.  1/16)  removes  from  the  discussion  the  most  subtle  of  the 
qualities,  while  the  restriction  to  overt  behaviour  makes  the 
specification  by  variable  usually  easy.  Secondly,  when  the  non- 
mathematical  reader  thinks  that  there  are  some  complex  quantities 
that  cannot  be  adequately  represented  by  number,  he  is  apt 
to  think  of  their  representation  by  a  single  variable.  The  use  of 
many  variables,  however,  enables  systems  of  considerable  com- 
plexity to  be  treated.  Thus  a  complex  system  like  '  the  weather 
over  England  ',  which  cannot  be  treated  adequately  by  a  single 
variable,  can,  by  the  use  of  many  variables,  be  treated  as  ade- 
quately as  we  please. 

3/5.  To  illustrate  the  method  for  specifying  the  behaviour  of  a 
system  by  variables,  two  examples  will  be  given.  They  are  of 
little   intrinsic  interest;   more  important  is  the  fact  that  they 

33 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


3/5 


demonstrate  that  the  method  is  exact  and  that  it  can  be  extended 
to  any  extent  without  loss  of  precision. 

The  first  example  is  from  a  physiological  experiment.  A  dog 
was  subjected  to  a  steady  loss  of  blood  at  the  rate  of  one  per  cent 
of  its  body  weight  per  minute.     Recorded  are  the  three  variables : 

(x)  rate  of  blood-flow  through  the  inferior  vena  cava, 
(y)     »      „  „  „  »     muscles  of  a  leg, 

(2)      „      „  „  „  „     gut. 

The  changes  of  the  variables  with  time  are  shown  in  Figure  3/5/1. 
It  will  be  seen  that  the  changes  of  the  variables  show  a  charac- 
teristic pattern,  for  the  blood-flow  through  leg  and  gut  falls  more 
than  that  through  the  inferior  vena  cava,  and  this  difference  is 
characteristic  of  the  body's  reaction  to  haemorrhage.     The  use 

z 


4  8 

Figure  3/5/1  :  Effects  of  haemor- 
rhage on  the  rate  of  blood-flow 
through  :  x,  the  inferior  vena  cava; 
y,  the  muscles  of  a  leg  ;  and  2,  the 
gut.     (From  Rein.) 


Figure  3/5/2  :  Phase-space  and 
line  of  behaviour  of  the  data 
shown  in  Figure  3/5/1. 


of  more  than  one  variable  has  enabled  the  pattern  of  the  reaction 
to  be  displayed. 

The  changes  specify  a  line  of  behaviour,  shown  in  Figure  3/5/2. 
Had  the  line  of  behaviour  pointed  in  a  different  direction,  the 
change  would  have  corresponded  to  a  change  in  the  pattern  of 
the  body's  reaction  to  haemorrhage. 

The  second  example  uses  certain  angles  measured  from  a 
cinematographic  record  of  the  activities  of  a  man.  His  body 
moved  forward  but  was  vertical  throughout.  The  four  variables 
are: 

(w)  angle  between  the  right  thigh  and  the  vertical 


(x) 


left 


34 


3/7 


THE     ORGANISM    AS     MACHINE 


(y)  angle  between  the  right   thigh  and   the  right  tibia 
(z)       „  „  „     left         „         „       „     left 

In  w  and  x  the  angle  is  counted  positively  when  the  knee  comes 
forward:  in  y  and  z  the  angles  are  measured  behind  the  knee. 
The  line  of  behaviour  is  specified  in  Table  3/5/1.  The  reader  can 
easily  identify  this  well-known  activity. 


Time  (seconds) 

0 

01 

0-2 

0-3 

0-4 

0-5 

0-6 

0-7 

0-8 

V 

IV 

45 

10 

-  10 

-  20 

—  35 

0 

60 

70 

45 

X 

-  35 

0 

60 

70 

45 

10 

-  10 

-  20 

-  35 

> 

y 

170 

180 

180 

160 

120 

80 

60 

100 

170 

z 

120 

80 

60 

100 

170 

180 

180 

160 

120 

Table  3/5/1. 

3/6.  In  a  physiological  experiment  the  nervous  system  is  usually 
considered  to  be  state-determined.  That  it  can  be  made  state- 
determined  is  assumed  by  every  physiologist  before  the  work 
starts,  for  he  assumes  that  it  is  subject  to  the  fundamental  assump- 
tion of  S.  2/15:  that  if  every  detail  within  it  could  be  determined, 
its  subsequent  behaviour  would  also  be  determined.  Many  of  the 
specialised  techniques  such  as  anaesthesia,  spinal  transection, 
root  section,  and  the  immobilisation  of  body  and  head  in  clamps 
are  used  to  ensure  proper  isolation  of  the  system — a  necessary 
condition  for  it  to  be  state-determined  (S.  2/15).  So  unless  there 
are  special  reasons  to  the  contrary,  the  nervous  system  in  a  physio- 
logical experiment  can  usually  be  assumed  to  be  state-determined. 

3/7.  Similarly  it  is  usually  agreed  that  an  animal  undergoing 
experiments  on  its  conditioned  reflexes  is  a  physico-chemical 
system  such  that  if  we  knew  every  detail  we  could  predict  its 
behaviour.  Pavlov's  insistence  on  complete  isolation  was  intended 
to  ensure  that  this  was  so.  So  unless  there  are  special  reasons  to 
the  contrary,  the  animal  in  an  experiment  with  conditioned 
reflexes  can  usually  be  assumed  to  be  state-determined. 


35 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  3/8 

3/8.  These  two  examples,  however,  are  mentioned  only  as 
introduction;  rather  we  shall  be  concerned  with  the  nature  of  the 
free-living  organism  within  a  natural  environment. 

Given  an  organism,  its  environment  is  defined  as  those  variables 
whose  changes  affect  the  organism,  and  those  variables  which  are 
changed  by  the  organism's  behaviour.  It  is  thus  defined  in  a  purely 
functional,  not  a  material,  sense.  It  will  be  treated  uniformly 
with  our  treatment  of  all  variables :  we  assume  it  is  representable 
by  dials,  is  explorable  (by  the  experimenter)  by  primary  opera- 
tions, and  is  intrinsically  state-determined. 


Organism  and  environment 

3/9.  The  theme  of  the  chapter  can  now  be  stated:  the  free- 
living  organism  and  its  environment,  taken  together,  may  be 
represented  with  sufficient  accuracy  by  a  set  of  variables  that 
forms  a  state-determined  system. 

The  concepts  developed  in  the  previous  sections  now  enable  us 
to  treat  both  organism  and  environment  by  identical  methods, 
for  the  same  primary  assumptions  are  made  about  each. 

3/10.  As  example,  that  the  organism  and  its  environment  form 
a  single  state-determined  system,  consider  (in  so  far  as  the  activities 
of  balancing  are  concerned)  a  bicycle  and  its  rider  in  normal 
progression. 

First,  the  forward  movement  may  be  eliminated  as  irrelevant, 
for  we  could  study  the  properties  of  this  dynamic  system  equally 
well  if  the  wheels  were  on  some  backward-moving  band.  The 
variables  can  be  identified  by  considering  what  happens.  Suppose 
the  rider  pulls  his  right  hand  backwards:  it  will  change  the 
angular  position  of  the  front  wheel  (taking  the  line  of  the  frame  as 
reference).  The  changed  angle  of  the  front  wheel  will  start  the 
two  points,  at  which  the  wheels  make  contact  with  the  ground, 
moving  to  the  right.  (The  physical  reasons  for  this  movement 
are  irrelevant:  the  fact  that  the  relation  is  determined  is  sufficient.) 
The  rider's  centre  of  gravity  being  at  first  unmoved,  the  line 
vertically  downwards  from  his  centre  of  gravity  will  strike  the 
ground  more  and  more  to  the  left  of  the  line  joining  the  two 
points.  As  a  result  he  will  start  to  fall  to  the  left.  This  fall  will 
excite  nerve-endings  in  the  organs  of  balance  in  the  ear,  impulses 

36 


3/11  THE     ORGANISM     AS     MACHINE 

will  pass  to  the  nervous  system,  and  will  be  switched  through  it, 
if  he  is  a  trained  rider,  by  such  a  route  that  they,  or  the  effects 
set  up  by  them,  will  excite  to  activity  those  muscles  which  push 
the  right  hand  forwards. 

We  can  now  specify  the  variables  which  must  compose  the 
system  if  it  is  to  be  state-determined.  We  must  include:  the 
angular  position  of  the  handlebar,  the  velocity  of  lateral  movement 
of  the  two  points  of  contact  between  wheels  and  road,  the  distance 
laterally  between  the  line  joining  these  points  and  the  point 
vertically  below  the  rider's  centre  of  gravity,  and  the  angular 
deviation  of  the  rider  from  the  vertical.  These  four  variables  are 
defined  by  S.  3/8  to  be  the  '  environment  '  of  the  rider.  (Whether 
the  fourth  variable  is  allotted  to  '  rider  '  or  to  '  environment  '  is 
optional  (S.  3/12).  To  make  the  system  state-determined,  there 
must  be  added  the  variables  of  the  nervous  system,  of  the  relevant 
muscles,  and  of  the  bone  and  joint  positions. 

As  a  second  example,  consider  a  butterfly  and  a  bird  in  the  air, 
the  bird  chasing  the  butterfly,  and  the  butterfly  evading  the  bird. 
Both  use  the  air  around  them.  Every  movement  of  the  bird 
stimulates  the  butterfly's  eyes  and  this  stimulation,  acting  through 
the  butterfly's  nervous  system,  will  cause  changes  in  the  butter- 
fly's wing  movements.  These  movements  act  on  the  enveloping 
air  and  cause  changes  in  the  butterfly's  position.  A  change  of 
position  immediately  changes  the  excitations  in  the  bird's  eye, 
and  this  leads  through  its  nervous  system  to  changed  movements 
of  the  bird's  wings.  These  act  on  the  air  and  change  the  bird's 
position.  So  the  processes  go  on.  The  bird  has  as  environment 
the  air  and  the  butterfly,  while  the  butterfly  has  the  air  and  the  bird. 
The  whole  may  reasonably  be  assumed  to  be  state-determined. 

3/11.  The  organism  affects  the  environment,  and  the  environ- 
ment affects  the  organism :  such  a  system  is  said  to  have  i  feed- 
back '  (S.  4/14)- 

The  examples  of  the  previous  section  provide  illustration.  The 
muscles  in  the  rider's  arm  move  the  handlebars,  causing  changes 
in  the  environment;  and  changes  in  these  variables  will,  through 
the  rider's  sensory  receptors,  cause  changes  in  his  brain  and 
muscles.  When  bird  and  butterfly  manoeuvre  in  the  air,  each 
manoeuvre  of  one  causes  reactive  changes  to  occur  in  the  other. 

The  same  feature  is  shown  by  the  example  of  S.  1/17 — the 

37 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  3/11 

type  problem  of  the  kitten  and  the  fire.  The  various  stimuli 
from  the  fire,  working  through  the  nervous  system,  evoke  some 
reaction  from  the  kitten's  muscles;  equally  the  kitten's  move- 
ments, by  altering  the  position  of  its  body  in  relation  to  the  fire, 
will  cause  changes  to  occur  in  the  pattern  of  stimuli  which  falls 
on  the  kitten's  sense-organs.  The  receptors  therefore  affect  the 
muscles  (by  effects  transmitted  through  the  nervous  system),  and 
the  muscles  affect  the  receptors  (by  effects  transmitted  through 
the  environment).  The  action  is  two-way  and  the  system  possesses 
feedback. 

The  observation  is  not  new: 

4  In  most  cases  the  change  which  induces  a  reaction  is  brought 
about  by  the  organism's  own  movements.  These  cause  a 
change  in  the  relation  of  the  organism  to  the  environment: 
to  these  changes  the  organism  reacts.  The  whole  behaviour 
of  free-moving  organisms  is  based  on  the  principle  that  it 
is  the  movements  of  the  organism  that  have  brought  about 
stimulation.' 

(Jennings.) 

'  The  good  player  of  a  quick  ball  game,  the  surgeon  con- 
ducting an  operation,  the  physician  arriving  at  a  clinical 
decision — in  each  case  there  is  the  flow  from  signals  inter- 
preted to  action  carried  out,  back  to  further  signals  and  on 
again  to  more  action,  up  to  the  culminating  point  of  the 
achievement  of  the  task  '. 

(Bartlett.) 

1  Organism  and  environment  form  a  whole  and  must  be 
viewed  as  such.' 

(Starling.) 

It  is  necessary  to  point  to  the  existence  of  feedback  in  the 
relation  between  the  free-living  organism  and  its  environment 
because  most  physiological  experiments  are  deliberately  arranged 
to  avoid  feedback.  Thus,  in  an  experiment  with  spinal  reflexes, 
a  stimulus  is  applied  and  the  resulting  movement  recorded;  but 
the  movement  is  not  allowed  to  influence  the  nature  or  duration 
of  the  stimulus.  The  action  between  stimulus  and  movement  is 
therefore  one-way.  A  similar  absence  of  feedback  is  enforced 
in  the  Pavlovian  experiments  with  conditioned  reflexes:  the 
stimulus  may  evoke  salivation,  but  the  salivation  has  no  effect 
on  the  nature  or  duration  of  the  stimulus. 

Such  an  absence  of  feedback  is,  of  course,  useful  or  even  essen- 

38 


3/11  THE     ORGANISM     AS     MACHINE 

tial  in  the  analytic  study  of  the  behaviour  of  a  mechanism, 
whether  animate  or  inanimate.  But  its  usefulness  in  the  labora- 
tory should  not  obscure  the  fact  that  the  free-living  animal  is  not 
subject  to  these  constraints. 

Sometimes  systems  which  seem  at  first  sight  to  be  one-way 
prove  on  closer  examination  to  have  feedback.  Walking  on  a 
smooth  pavement,  for  instance,  seems  to  involve  so  little  reference 
to  the  structures  outside  the  body  that  the  nervous  system  might 
seem  to  be  producing  its  actions  without  reference  to  their  effects. 
Tabes  dorsalis,  however,  prevents  incoming  sensory  impulses  from 
reaching  the  brain  while  leaving  the  outgoing  motor  impulses  un- 
affected. If  walking  were  due  simply  to  the  outgoing  motor 
impulses,  the  disease  would  cause  no  disturbance  to  walking.  In 
fact,  it  upsets  the  action  severely,  and  demonstrates  that  the 
incoming  sensory  impulses  are  really  playing  an  essential,  though 
hidden,  part  in  the  normal  action. 

Another  example  showing  the  influence  of  feedback  occurs  when 
we  try  to  place  a  point  accurately  (e.g.  by  trying  to  pass  a  wire 
through  a  small  hole  in  a  board)  wrhen  we  cannot  see  by  how 
much  we  are  in  error  (e.g.  when  we  have  to  pass  the  wire  through 
from  the  far  side,  towards  us).  The  difficulty  we  encounter  is 
precisely  due  to  the  fact  that  while  we  can  affect  the  movements 
of  the  wire,  its  movements  and  its  relations  to  the  hole  can  no 
longer  be  communicated  back  to  us. 

Sometimes  the  feedback  can  be  demonstrated  only  with  diffi- 
culty.    Thus,  Lloyd  Morgan  raised  some  ducklings  in  an  incubator. 

The  ducklings  thoroughly  enjoyed  a  dip.     Each  morning, 

at  nine  o'clock,  a  large  black  tray  was  placed  in  their  pen, 

and  on  it  a  flat  tin  containing  water.     To  this  they  eagerly 

ran,  drinking  and  washing  in  it.     On  the  sixth  morning  the 

tray  and  tin  were  given  them  in  the  usual  way,  but  without 

any  water.     They  ran  to  it,  scooped  at  the  bottom  and  made 

all  the  motions  of  the  beak  as  if  drinking.     They  squatted 

in  it,  dipping  their  heads,  and  waggling  their  tails  as  usual. 

For  some  ten  minutes  they  continued  to  wash  in  non-existent 

water  .  .  .' 

Their  behaviour  might  suggest  that  the  stimuli  of  tray  and  tin 

were  compelling  the  production  of  certain  activities  and  that  the 

results  of  these  activities  were  having  no  back-effect.     But  further 

experiment  showed  that  some  effect  was  occurring: 

'The  next  day  the  experiment  was  repeated  with  the  dry  tin. 

39 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  3/12 

Again  they  ran  to  it,  shovelling  along  the  bottom  with  their 
beaks,  and  squatting  down  in  it.  But  they  soon  gave  up. 
On  the  third  morning  they  waddled  up  to  the  dry  tin,  and 
departed.' 

Their  behaviour  at  first  suggested  that  there  was  no  feedback. 
But  on  the  third  day  their  change  of  behaviour  showed  that,  in 
fact,  the  change  in  the  bath  had  had  some  effect  on  them. 

The  importance  of  feedback  lies  in  the  fact  that  systems  which 
possess  it  have  certain  properties  (S.  4/16)  which  cannot  be  shown 
by  systems  lacking  it.  Systems  with  feedback  cannot  adequately 
be  treated  as  if  they  were  of  one-way  action,  for  the  feedback  intro- 
duces properties  which  can  be  explained  only  by  reference  to  the 
particular  feedback  used.  (On  the  other  hand  a  one-way  system 
can,  without  error,  be  treated  as  if  it  contained  feedback:  we 
assume  that  one  of  the  two  actions  is  present  but  at  zero  degree 
(S.  2/3).  In  other  words,  systems  without  feedback  are  a  sub- 
class of  the  class  of  systems  with  feedback.) 

3/12.  As  the  organism  and  its  environment  are  to  be  treated  as  a 
single  system,  the  dividing  line  between  '  organism  '  and  '  environ- 
ment '  becomes  partly  conceptual,  and  to  that  extent  arbitrary. 
Anatomically  and  physically,  of  course,  there  is  usually  a  unique 
and  obvious  distinction  between  the  two  parts  of  the  system;  but 
if  we  view  the  system  functionally,  ignoring  purely  anatomical 
facts  as  irrelevant,  the  division  of  the  system  into  '  organism  '  and 
4  environment  '  becomes  vague.  Thus,  if  a  mechanic  with  an 
artificial  arm  is  trying  to  repair  an  engine,  then  the  arm  may  be 
regarded  either  as  part  of  the  organism  that  is  struggling  with 
the  engine,  or  as  part  of  the  machinery  with  which  the  man  is 
struggling. 

Once  this  flexibility  of  division  is  admitted,  almost  no  bounds 
can  be  put  to  its  application.  The  chisel  in  a  sculptor's  hand 
can  be  regarded  either  as  a  part  of  the  complex  biophysical 
mechanism  that  is  shaping  the  marble,  or  it  can  be  regarded  as 
a  part  of  the  material  which  the  nervous  system  is  attempting  to 
control.  The  bones  in  the  sculptor's  arm  can  similarly  be  regarded 
either  as  part  of  the  organism  or  as  part  of  the  '  environment  '  of 
the  nervous  system.  Variables  within  the  body  may  justifiably 
be  regarded  as  the  '  environment  '  of  some  other  part.  A  child 
has  to  learn  not  only  how  to  grasp  a  piece  of  bread,  but  how  to 

40 


3/14  THE     ORGANISM     AS     MACHINE 

chew  without  biting  his  own  tongue ;  functionally  both  bread  and 
tongue  are  part  of  the  environment  of  the  cerebral  cortex.  But 
the  environments  with  which  the  cortex  has  to  deal  are  sometimes 
even  deeper  in  the  body  than  the  tongue:  the  child  has  to  learn 
how  to  play  without  exhausting  itself  utterly,  and  how  to  talk 
without  getting  out  of  breath. 

These  remarks  are  not  intended  to  confuse,  but  to  show  that 
later  arguments  (in  Chapters  15  and  16)  are  not  unreasonable. 
There  it  is  intended  to  treat  one  group  of  neurons  in  the  brain 
as  the  environment  of  another  group.  These  divisions,  though 
arbitrary,  are  justifiable  because  we  shall  always  treat  the  system 
as  a  whole,  dividing  it  into  parts  in  this  unusual  way  merely  for 
verbal  convenience  in  description. 

It  should  be  noticed  that  from  now  on  '  the  system  '  means 
not  the  nervous  system  but  the  whole  complex  of  the  organism 
and  its  environment.  Thus,  if  it  should  be  shown  that  '  the 
system  '  has  some  property,  it  must  not  be  assumed  that  this 
property  is  attributed  to  the  nervous  system:  it  belongs  to  the 
whole;  and  detailed  examination  may  be  necessary  to  ascertain 
the  contributions  of  the  separate  parts. 

3/13.  In  some  cases  the  dynamic  nature  of  the  interaction 
between  organism  and  environment  can  be  made  intuitively  more 
obvious  by  using  the  device,  common  in  physics,  of  regarding  the 
animal  as  the  centre  of  reference.  In  locomotion  the  animal 
would  then  be  thought  of  as  pulling  the  world  past  itself.  Pro- 
vided we  are  concerned  only  with  the  relation  between  these  two, 
and  are  not  considering  their  relations  to  any  third  and  inde- 
pendent body,  the  device  will  not  lead  to  error.  It  was  used  in 
the  '  rider  and  bicycle  '  example. 

By  the  use  of  animal-centred  co-ordinates  we  can  see  that  the 
animal  has  much  more  control  over  its  environment  than  might  at 
first  seem  possible.  Thus,  while  ^a  frog  cannot  change  air  into 
water,  a  frog  on  the  bank  of  a  stream  can,  with  one  small  jump, 
change  its  world  from  one  ruled  by  the  laws  of  mechanics  to  one 
ruled  by  the  laws  of  hydrodynamics. 

Essential  variables 
3/14.     The  biologist  must  view  the  brain,  not  as  being  the  seat  of 
the  4  mind  ',  nor  as  something  that  4  thinks  ',  but,  like  every  other 

41 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  3/14 

organ  in  the  body,  as  a  specialised  means  to  survival  (S.  1/10). 
We  shall  use  the  concept  of  '  survival  '  repeatedly;  but  before  we 
can  use  it,  we  must,  by  S.  2/10,  transform  it  to  our  standard 
form  and  say  what  it  means  in  terms  of  primary  operations. 

Physico-chemical  systems  may  undergo  the  most  extensive 
transformations  without  showing  any  change  obviously  equivalent 
to  death,  for  matter  and  energy  are  indestructible.  Yet  the  dis- 
tinction between  a  live  horse  and  a  dead  one  is  obvious  enough. 
Further,  there  can  be  no  doubt  about  the  objectivity  of  the 
difference,  for  they  fetch  quite  different  prices  in  the  market. 
The  distinction  must  be  capable  of  objective  definition. 

It  is  suggested  that  the  definition  may  be  obtained  in  the 
following  way.  That  an  animal  should  remain  '  alive  ',  certain 
variables  must  remain  without  certain  '  physiological  '  limits. 
What  these  variables  are,  and  what  the  limits,  are  fixed  when 
the  species  is  fixed.  In  practice  one  does  not  experiment  on 
animals  in  general,  one  experiments  on  one  of  a  particular  species. 
In  each  species  the  many  physiological  variables  differ  widely  in 
their  relevance  to  survival.  Thus,  if  a  man's  hair  is  shortened 
from  4  inches  to  1  inch,  the  change  is  trivial ;  if  his  systolic  blood- 
pressure  drops  from  120  mm.  of  mercury  to  30,  the  change  will 
quickly  be  fatal. 

Every  species  has  a  number  of  variables  which  are  closely 
related  to  survival  and  which  are  closely  linked  dynamically  so 
that  marked  changes  in  any  one  leads  sooner  or  later  to  marked 
changes  in  the  others.  Thus,  if  we  find  in  a  rat  that  the  pulse- 
rate  has  dropped  to  zero,  we  can  predict  that  the  respiration  rate 
will  soon  become  zero,  that  the  body  temperature  will  soon  fall  to 
room  temperature,  and  that  the  number  of  bacteria  in  the  tissues 
will  soon  rise  from  almost  zero  to  a  very  high  number.  These 
important  and  closely  linked  variables  will  be  referred  to  as  the 
essential  variables  of  the  animal. 

How  are  we  to  discover  them,  considering  that  we  may  not  use 
borrowed  knowledge  but  must  find  them  by  the  methods  of 
Chapter  2  ?  There  is  no  difficulty.  Given  a  species,  we  observe 
what  follows  when  members  of  the  species  are  started  from  a 
variety  of  initial  states.  We  shall  find  that  large  initial  changes 
in  some  variables  are  followed  in  the  system  by  merely  transient 
deviations,  while  large  initial  changes  in  others  are  followed  by 
deviations  that  become  ever  greater  till  the  '  machine  '  changes 

42 


3/15  THE     ORGANISM    AS     MACHINE 

to  something  very  different  from  what  it  was  originally.  The 
results  of  these  primary  operations  will  thus  distinguish,  quite 
objectively,  the  essential  variables  from  the  others. 

3/15.  The  essential  variables  are  not  uniform  in  the  closeness  or 
urgency  of  their  relations  to  lethality.  There  are  such  variables 
as  the  amount  of  oxygen  in  the  blood,  and  the  structural  integrity 
of  the  medulla  oblongata,  whose  passage  beyond  the  normal  limits 
is  followed  by  death  almost  at  once.  There  are  others,  such  as 
the  integrity  of  a  leg-bone,  and  the  amount  of  infection  in  the 
peritoneal  cavity,  whose  passage  beyond  the  limit  must  be  regarded 
as  serious  though  not  necessarily  fatal.  Then  there  are  variables, 
such  as  those  of  severe  pressure  or  heat  at  some  place  on  the  skin, 
whose  passage  beyond  normal  limits  is  not  immediately  dangerous, 
but  is  so  often  correlated  with  some  approaching  threat  that  is 
serious  that  the  organism  avoids  such  situations  (which  we  call 
'  painful  ')  as  if  they  were  potentially  lethal.  All  that  we  require 
is  the  ability  to  arrange  the  animal's  variables  in  an  approximate 
order  of  importance.  Inexactness  of  the  order  is  not  serious,  for 
nowhere  will  we  use  a  particular  order  as  a  basis  for  particular 
deductions. 

We  can  now  define  '  survival  '  objectively  and  in  terms  of  a 
field :  it  occurs  when  a  line  of  behaviour  takes  no  essential  variable 
outside  given  limits. 


43 


CHAPTER   4 

Stability 

4/1.  The  words  l  stability  ',  '  steady  state  ',  and  '  equilibrium  ' 
are  used  by  a  variety  of  authors  with  a  variety  of  meanings, 
though  there  is  always  the  same  underlying  theme.  As  we  shall 
be  much  concerned  with  stability  and  its  properties,  an  exact 
definition  must  be  provided. 

The  subject  may  be  opened  by  a  presentation  of  the  three 
standard  elementary  examples.  A  cube  resting  with  one  face 
on  a  horizontal  surface  typifies  '  stable  '  equilibrium ;  a  sphere 
resting  on  a  horizontal  surface  typifies  'neutral'  equilibrium; 
and  a  cone  balanced  on  its  point  typifies  '  unstable  '  equilibrium. 
With  neutral  and  unstable  equilibria  we  shall  have  little  concern, 
but  the  concept  of  '  stable  equilibrium  '  will  be  used  repeatedly. 

These  three  dynamic  systems  are  restricted  in  their  behaviour 
by  the  fact  that  each  system  contains  a  fixed  quantity  of  energy, 
so  that  any  subsequent  movement  must  conform  to  this  invari- 
ance.  We,  however,  shall  be  considering  systems  which  are 
abundantly  supplied  with  free  energy  so  that  no  such  limitation 
is  imposed.     Here  are  two  examples. 

The  first  is  the  Watt's  governor.  A  steam-engine  rotates  a  pair 
of  weights  which,  as  they  are  rotated  faster,  separate  more  widely 
by  centrifugal  action;  their  separation  controls  mechanically 
the  position  of  the  throttle;  and  the  position  of  the  throttle 
controls  the  flow  of  steam  to  the  engine.  The  connexions  are 
arranged  so  that  an  increase  in  the  speed  of  the  engine  causes  a 
decrease  in  the  flow  of  steam.  The  result  is  that  if  any  transient 
disturbance  slows  or  accelerates  the  engine,  the  governor  brings 
the  speed  back  to  the  usual  value.  By  this  return  the  system 
demonstrates  its  stability. 

The  second  example  is  the  thermostat,  of  which  many  types 
exist.  All,  however,  work  on  the  same  principle:  a  chilling  of 
the  main  object  causes  a  change  which  in  its  turn  causes  the 
heating  to  become  more  intense  or  more  effective;  and  vice  versa. 

44 


4/3 


STABILITY 


The  result  is  that  if  any  transient  disturbance  cools  or  overheats 
the  main  object,  the  thermostat  brings  its  temperature  back  to 
the  usual  value.  By  this  return  the  system  demonstrates  its 
stability. 

4/2.  An  important  feature  of  stability  is  that  it  does  not  refer 
to  a  material  body  or  '  machine  '  but  only  to  some  aspect  of  it. 
This  statement  may  be  proved  most  simply  by  an  example  showing 
that  a  single  material  body  can  be  in  two  different  equilibrial 
conditions  at  the  same  time.  Consider  a  square  card  balanced 
exactly  on  one  edge;  to  displacements  at  right  angles  to  this  edge 
the  card  is  unstable;  to  displacements  exactly  parallel  to  this 
edge  it  is,  theoretically  at  least,  stable. 

The  example  supports  the  thesis  that  we  do  not,  in  general, 
study  physical  bodies  but  only  entities  carefully  abstracted  from 
them.  The  matter  will  become  clearer  when  we  conform  to  the 
requirements  of  S.  2/10  and  define  stability  in  terms  of  the  results 
of  primary  operations.     This  may  be  done  as  follows. 

4/3.  Consider  a  corrugated  surface,  laid  horizontally,  with  a  ball 
rolling  from  a  ridge  down  towards  a  trough.  A  photograph  taken 
in  the  middle  of  its  roll  would  look  like 
Figure  4/3/1.  We  might  think  of  the 
ball  as  being  unstable  because  it  has 
rolled  away  from  the  ridge,  until  we 
realise  that  we  can  also  think  of  it  as 
stable  because  it  is  rolling  towards  the 
trough.  The  duality  shows  we  are 
approaching  the  concept  in  the  wrong 
way.  The  situation  can  be  made  clearer 
if  we  remove  the  ball  and  consider  only  Figure  4/3/1 

the  surface.  The  top  of  the  ridge,  as 
it  would  affect  the  roll  of  a  ball,  is  now  recognised  as  a  position 
of  unstable  equilibrium,  and  the  bottom  of  the  trough  as  a  position 
of  stability.  We  now  see  that,  if  friction  is  sufficiently  marked 
for  us  to  be  able  to  neglect  momentum,  the  system  composed  of 
the  single  variable  '  distance  of  the  ball  laterally  '  is  state-deter- 
mined, and  has  a  definite,  permanent  field,  which  is  sketched  in 
the  Figure. 

From  B  the  lines  of  behaviour  diverge,  but  to  A  they  converge. 

45 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  4/4 

We  conclude  tentatively  that  the  concept  of  '  stability  '  belongs 
not  to  a  material  body  but  to  a  field.  It  is  shown  by  a  field  if 
the  lines  of  behaviour  converge.     (An  exact  definition  is  given  in 

S.  4/8.) 

4/4.  The  points  A  and  B  are  such  that  the  ball,  if  released  on 
either  of  them,  and  mathematically  perfect,  will  stay  there. 
Given  a  field,  a  state  of  equilibrium  is  one  from  which  the  repre- 
sentative point  does  not  move.  When  the  primary  operation  is 
applied,  the  transition  from  that  state  can  be  described  as  '  to 
itself '. 

(Notice  that  this  definition,  while  saying  what  happens  at  the 
equilibrial  state,  does  not  restrict  how  the  lines  of  behaviour  may 
run  around  it.  They  may  converge  in  to  it,  or  diverge  from  it, 
or  behave  in  other  ways.) 

Although  the  variables  do  not  change  value  when  the  system 
is  at  a  state  of  equilibrium,  this  invariance  does  not  imply  that 
the  '  machine  '  is  inactive.  Thus,  a  motionless  Watt's  governor 
is  compatible  with  the  engine  working  at  a  non-zero  rate.  (The 
matter  has  been  treated  more  fully  in  /.  to  C,  S.  11/15.) 

4/5.  To  illustrate  that  the  concept  of  stability  belongs  to  a 
field,  let  us  examine  the  fields  of  the  previous  examples. 

The  cube  resting  on  one  face  yields  a  state-determined  system 
which  has  two  variables: 

(x)  the  angle  at  which  the  face  makes  with  the  horizontal,  and 
(y)  the  rate  at  which  this  angle  changes. 

(This  system  allows  for  the  momentum  of  the  cube.)  If  the  cube 
does  not  bounce  when  the  face  meets  the  table,  the  field  is  similar 
to  that  sketched  in  Figure  4/5/1.  The  stability  of  the  cube 
when  resting  on  a  face  corresponds  in  the  field  to  the  convergence 
of  the  lines  of  behaviour  to  the  centre. 

The  square  card  balanced  on  its  edge  can  be  represented  approxi- 
mately by  two  variables  which  measure  displacements  at  right 
angles  (a?)  and  parallel  (y)  to  the  lower  edge.  The  field  will 
resemble  that  sketched  in  Figure  4/5/2.  Displacement  from  the 
origin  0  to  A  is  followed  by  a  return  of  the  representative  point 
to  -O,  and  this  return  corresponds  to  the  stability.  Displacement 
from  O  to  B  is  followed  by  a  departure  from  the  region  under 

46 


4/5 


STABILITY 


o  O  O  D  o  o  o 

Figure  4/5/1  :  Field  of  the  two-variable  system  described  in  the  text. 
Below  is  shown  the  cube  as  it  would  appear  in  elevation  when  its  main 
face,  shown  by  a  heavier  line,  is  tilted  through  the  angle  x. 

consideration,  and  this  departure  correspond^to  the  instability. 
The  uncertainty  of  the  movements  near  O  corresponds  to  the 
uncertainty  in  the  behaviour  of  the  card  when  released  from  the 
vertical  position. 

The  Watt's  governor  has  a  more  complicated  field,   but  an 
approximation  may  be  obtained  without 
difficulty.     The  system  may  be  specified 
to  an  approximation  sufficient  for  our 
purpose  by  three  variables: 

(x)  the  speed  of  the  engine  and 
governor  (r.p.m.), 

(y)  the  distance  between  the  weights, 
or  the  position  of  the  throttle, 
and 

(z)  the  velocity  of  flow  of  the  steam. 

(y  represents  either  of  two  quantities  because  they  are  rigidly 
connected).  If,  now,  a  disturbance  suddenly  accelerates  the 
engine,  increasing  x,  the  increase  in  x  will  increase  y;  this  increase 
in  y  will  be  followed  by  a  decrease  of  z,  and  then  by  a  decrease  of 
x.     As  the  changes  occur  not  in  jumps  but  continuously,  the  line 

47 


Figure  4/5/2. 


DESIGN    FOR    A    BRAIN  4/6 

of  behaviour  must  resemble  that  sketched  in  Figure  4/5/3.     The 

other  lines  of  the  field  could  be  added  by  considering  what  would 

^  happen  after  other  disturbances 

(lines  starting  from  points  other 
than  A).  Although  having 
different  initial  states,  all  the 
lines  would  converge  towards  0. 

4/6.  In  some  of  our  examples, 
for  instance  that  of  the  cube,  the 
lines  of  behaviour  terminate  in  a 
point  at  which  all  movement 
ceases.  In  other  examples  the 
movement  does  not  wholly  cease ; 
many  a  thermostat  settles  down, 
when  close  to  its  resting  state, 

Figure  4/5/3  :   One  line  of  behav-  to    a    regular    small    oscillation, 

iour  in  the  field  of  the  Watt's  We  shall  seldom  be  interested  in 

governor.  For  clarity,  the  resting  ..        ,   .    .,        „       ,     .    , 

state  of  the  system  has  been  used  the   details   ot   what   happens   at 

as  origin.     The  system  has  been  the  exact  centre, 
displaced  to  A  and  then  released. 

4/7.  More  important  is  the  underlying  theme  that  in  all  cases 
the  stable  system  is  characterised  by  the  fact  that  after  a  displace- 
ment we  can  assign  some  bound  to  the  subsequent  movement  of  the 
representative  point,  whereas  in  the  unstable  system  such  limita- 
tion is  either  impossible  or  depends  on  facts  outside  the  subject  of 
discussion.  Thus,  if  a  thermostat  is  set  at  37°  C.  and  displaced 
to  40°,  we  can  predict  that  in  the  future  it  will  not  go  outside 
specified  limits,  which  might  be,  in  one  apparatus,  36°  and  40°. 
On  the  other  hand,  if  the  thermostat  has  been  assembled  with  a 
component  reversed  so  that  it  is  unstable  (S.  4/14)  and  if  it  is 
displaced  to  40°,  then  we  can  give  no  limits  to  its  subsequent 
temperatures;  unless  we  introduce  such  new  topics  as  the  melting- 
point  of  its  solder. 

4/8.  These  considerations  bring  us  to  the  definitions.  Given 
the  field  of  a  state-determined  system  and  a  region  in  the  field, 
the  region  is  stable  if  the  lines  of  behaviour  from  all  points  in  the 
region  stay  within  the  region. 

Thus,  in  Figure  4/3/1  make  a  mark  on  either  side  of  A  to  define 
a  region.     All  representative  points  within  are  led  to  A,  and  none 

48 


4/10 


STABILITY 


can  leave  the  region;  so  the  region  is  stable.  On  the  other  hand, 
no  such  region  can  be  marked  around  B  (unless  restricted  to  the 
single  point  of  B  itself). 

The  definition  makes  clear  that  change  of  either  the  field  or  the 
region  may  change  the  result  of  the  test.  We  cannot,  in  general, 
say  of  a  given  system  that  it  is  stable  (or  unstable)  unconditionally. 
The  field  of  Figure  4/5/1  showed  this,  and  so  does  that  of  Figure 
4/5/2.  (In  the  latter,  the  regions  restricted  to  any  part  of  the 
?/-axis  with  the  origin  are  stable;  all  others  are  unstable.) 

The  examples  above  have  been  selected  to  test  the  definition 
severely.  Often  the  fields  are  simpler.  In  the  field  of  the  cube, 
for  instance,  it  is  possible  to  draw  many  boundaries,  all.oval,  such 
that  the  regions  inside  them  are  stable.  The  field  of  the  Watt's 
governor  is  also  of  this  type. 

A  field  will  be  said  to  be  stable  if  the  whole  region  it  fills  is 
stable ;  the  system  that  provided  the  field  can  then  be  called  stable. 

4/9.  Sometimes  the  conditions  are  even  simpler.  The  system 
may  have  only  one  state  of  equilibrium  and  the  lines  of  behaviour 
may  all  either  converge  in  to  it  or  all  diverge  from  it.  In  such  a 
case  the  indication  of  which  way  the  lines  go  may  be  given  suffi- 
ciently by  the  simple,  unqualified,  statement  that  '  it  is  stable  ' 
(or  not).  A  system  can  be  described  adequately  by  such  an 
unqualified  statement  (without  reference  to  the  region)  only  when 
its  field,  .i.e.  its  behaviour,  is  suitably  simple. 


4/10.  If  a  line  of  behaviour  is  re-entrant  to  itself,  the  system 
undergoes  a  recurrent  cycle.  If 
the  cycle  is  wholly  contained  in  a 
given  region,  and  the  lines  of  be- 
haviour lead  into  the  cycle,  the 
cycle  is  stable. 

Such  a  cycle  is  commonly  shown, 
by  thermostats  which,  after  correct- 
ing any  gross  displacement,  settle 
down  to  a  steady  oscillation.  In 
such  a  case  the  field  will  show, 
not  convergence  to  a  point  but 
convergence  to  a  cycle,  such  as 
is  shown  exaggerated  in  Figure  4/10/1, 

49 


Figure  4/10/1. 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


4/11 


4/11.  This  definition  of  stability  conforms  to  the  requirement 
of  S.  2/10;  for  the  observed  behaviour  of  the  system  determines 
the  field,  and  the  field  determines  the  stability. 


The  diagram  of  immediate  effects 

4/12.  The  description  given  in  S.  4/1  of  the  working  of  the 
Watt's  governor  showed  that  it  is  arranged  in  a  functional  circuit : 
the  chain  of  cause  and  effect  is  re-entrant.  Thus  if  we  represent 
1  A  has  a  direct  effect  on  B  '  or  '  A  directly  disturbs  B  '  by  the 
symbol  A  — >  B,  then  the  construction  of  the  Watt's  governor  may 
be  represented  by  the  diagram: 


Speed  of 
engine 

Distance 
between 
weights 

\     / 

\ 

/ 

/ 

Velocity 

of  flow 

of  steam 

■ 

(The  number  of  variables  named  here  is  partly  optional.) 

I  now  want  to  make  clear  that  this  type  of  diagram,  if  accurately 
defined,  can  be  derived  wholly  from  the  results  of  primary  operations. 
No  metaphysical  or  borrowed  knowledge  is  necessary  for  its 
construction.  To  show  how  this  is  done,  take  an  actual  Watt's 
governor  as  example: 

Each  pair  of  variables  is  taken  in  turn.  Suppose  the  relation 
between  '  speed  of  engine  '  and  '  distance  between  weights  '  is 
first  investigated.  The  experimenter  would  fix  the  variable 
4  velocity  of  flow  of  steam  '  and  all  other  extraneous  variables  that 
might  interfere  to  confuse  the  direct  relation  between  speed  of 
engine  and  distance  between  weights.  Then  he  would  try  various 
speeds  of  the  engine,  and  would  observe  how  these  changes  affected 
the  behaviour  of  '  distance  between  the  weights  '.  He  would 
find  that  changes  in  the  speed  of  the  engine  were  regularly  followed 
by  changes  in  the  distance  between  the  weights.  Thus  the  transi- 
tion of  the  variable  4  distance  between  weights  '  (one  distance 
changing  to  another)  is  affected  by  the  value  of  the  speed  of  the 

50 


4/13 


STABILITY 


engine.  He  need  know  nothing  of  the  nature  of  the  ultimate 
physical  linkages,  but  he  would  observe  the  fact.  Then,  still 
keeping  4  velocity  of  flow  of  steam  '  constant,  he  would  try  various 
distances  between  the  weights,  and  would  observe  the  effect  of 
such  changes  on  the  speed  of  the  engine;  he  would  find  them  to 
be  without  effect.  He  would  thus  have  established  that  there  is 
an  arrow  from  left  to  right  but  not  from  right  to  left  in 


Speed  of 
engine 


Distance 
between 
weights 


This  procedure  could  then  be  applied  to  the  two  variables 
'  distance  between  weights  '  and  '  velocity  of  flow  of  steam  ', 
while  the  other  variable  '  speed  of  engine  '  was  kept  constant. 
And  finally  the  relations  between  the  third  pair  could  be  established. 

The  method  is  clearly  general.  To  find  the  immediate  effects 
in  a  system  with  variables  A,  B,  C,  D  .  .  .  take  one  pair,  A  and 
B  say;  hold  all  other  variables  C,  D  .  .  .  constant;  note  B's 
behaviour  when  A  starts  at  Ax\  and  also  its  behaviour  when  A 
starts  at  A2.  If  these  behaviours  of  B  are  the  same,  then  there  is 
no  immediate  effect  from  A  to  B.  But  if  the  J5's  behaviours  are 
unequal,  and  regularly  depend  on  what  value  A  starts  from, 
then  there  is  an  immediate  effect,  which  we  may  symbolise  by 
A-+B. 

By  interchanging  A  and  B  in  the  process  we  can  then  test  for 
B  — >  A.  And  by  using  other  pairs  in  turn  we  can  determine  all 
the  immediate  effects.  The  process  consists  purely  of  primary 
operations,  and  therefore  uses  no  borrowed  knowledge  (the  process 
is  further  considered  in  S.  12/3).  We  shall  frequently  use  this 
diagram  of  immediate  effects. 


4/13.  It  should  be  noticed  that  this  arrow,  though  it  sometimes 
corresponds  to  an  actual  material  channel  (a  rod,  a  wire,  a  nerve 
fibre,  etc.),  has  fundamentally  nothing  to  do  with  material  con- 
nexions but  is  a  representation  of  a  relation  between  the  behaviours 
at  A  and  B.  Strictly  speaking,  it  refers  to  A  and  B  only,  and  not 
to  anything  between  them. 

That  it  is  the  functional,  behaviourial,  relation  between  A  and 
B  that  is  decisive  (in  deciding  whether  we  may  hypothesise  a 
channel  of  communication  between  them)  was  shown  clearly  on 

51 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


4/14 


that  day  in  1888  when  Heinrich  Hertz  gave  his  famous  demon- 
stration. He  had  two  pieces  of  apparatus  (A  and  B,  say)  that 
manifestly  were  not  connected  in  any  material  way ;  yet  whenever 
at  any  arbitrarily  selected  moment  he  closed  a  switch  in  A  a 
spark  jumped  in  B,  i.e.  B's  behaviour  depended  at  any  moment 
on  the  position  of  A's  switch.  Here  was  a  flat  contradiction: 
materially  the  two  systems  were  not  connected,  yet  functionally 
their  behaviours  were  connected.  All  scientists  accepted  that 
the  behavioural  evidence  was  final — that  some  linkage  was 
demonstrated. 

Feedback 
4/14.     A  gas  thermostat  also  shows  a  functional  circuit  or  feed- 
back ;  for  it  is  controlled  by  a  capsule  which  by  its  swelling  moves 
a  lever  which  controls  the  flow  of  gas  to  the  heating  flame,  so  the 
diagram  of  immediate  effects  would  be : 


Temperature 

Diameter 

of  capsule 

of  capsule 

> 

«, 

> 

t 

Size  of 
gas  flame 

Position 
of  lever 

j 

^ 

■> 

f 

Velocity 

Position 

of  gas 

>  flow 

of  gas 

tap 

The  reader  should  verify  that  each  arrow  represents  a  physical 
action  which  can  be  demonstrated  if  all  variables  other  than  the 
pair  are  kept  constant. 

Another  example  is  provided  by  '  reaction  '  in  a  radio  receiver. 
We  can  represent  the  action  by  two  variables  linked  in  two  ways : 


Amplitude  of 

oscillation  of  the 

anode-current 

Amplitude  of 

oscillation  of  the 

grid-potential 

The  lower  arrow  represents  the  grid-potential's  effect  within  the 
valve  on  the  anode-current.  The  upper  arrow  represents  some 
arrangement  of  the  circuit  by  which  fluctuation  in  the  anode 

52 


4/15  STABILITY 

current  affects  the  grid-potential.  The  effect  represented  by  the 
lower  arrow  is  determined  by  the  valve-designer,  that  of  the 
upper  by  the  circuit-designer. 

Such  systems  whose  variables  affect  one  another  in  one  or  more 
circuits  possess  what  the  radio-engineer  calls  '  feedback  ' ;  they  are 
also  sometimes  described  as  '  servo-mechanisms  '.  They  are  at 
least  as  old  as  the  Watt's  governor  and  may  be  older.  But  only 
during  the  last  decade  has  it  been  realised  that  the  possession  of 
feedback  gives  a  machine  potentialities  that  are  not  available  to  a 
machine  lacking  it.  The  development  occurred  mainly  during  the 
last  war,  stimulated  by  the  demand  for  automatic  methods  of 
control  of  searchlight,  anti-aircraft  guns,  rockets,  and  torpedoes, 
and  facilitated  by  the  great  advances  that  had  occurred  in  elec- 
tronics. As  a  result,  a  host  of  new  machines  appeared  which 
acted  with  powers  of  self- adjustment  and  correction  never  before 
achieved.  Some  of  their  main  properties  will  be  described  in 
S.  4/16. 

The  nature,  degree,  and  polarity  of  the  feedback  usually  have 
a  decisive  effect  on  the  stability  or  instability  of  the  system.  In 
the  Watt's  governor  or  in  the  thermostat,  for  instance,  the  con- 
nexion of  a  part  in  reversed  position,  reversing  the  polarity  of 
action  of  one  component  on  the  next,  may,  and  probably  will, 
turn  the  system  from  stable  to  unstable.  In  the  reaction  circuit 
of  the  radio  set,  the  stability  or  instability  is  determined  by  the 
quantitative  relation  between  the  two  effects. 

Instability  in  such  systems  is  shown  by  the  development  of  a 
'  runaway  '.  The  least  disturbance  is  magnified  by  its  passage 
round  the  circuit  so  that  it  is  incessantly  built  up  into  a  larger 
and  larger  deviation  from  the  central  state.  The  phenomenon  is 
identical  with  that  referred  to  as  a  '  vicious  circle  '. 

4/15.  The  examples  shown  have  only  a  simple  circuit.  But  more 
complex  systems  may  have  many  interlacing  circuits.  If,  for 
instance,  as  in  S.  8/2,  four  variables  all  act  on  each  other,  the 
diagram  of  immediate  effects  would   be  that   shown  in   Figure 


4-±=*3  3- 4 


2 
C 


Figure  4/15/1. 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


4/16 


4/15/1  (A).     It  is  easy  to  verify  that  such  a  system  contains 
twenty  interlaced  circuits,  two  of  which  are  shown  at  B  and  C. 

The  further  development  of  the  theory  of  systems  with  feed- 
back cannot  be  made  without  mathematics.  But  here  it  is 
sufficient  to  note  two  facts:  a  system  which  possesses  feedback 
is  usually  actively  stable  or  actively  unstable;  and  whether  it  is 
stable  or  unstable  depends  on  the  quantitative  details  of  the 
particular  arrangement. 


Goal-seeking 

4/16.  Every  stable  system  has  the  property  that  if  displaced 
from  a  state  of  equilibrium  and  released,  the  subsequent  movement 
is  so  matched  to  the  initial  displacement  that  the  system  is 
brought  back  to  the  state  of  equilibrium.  A  variety  of  disturbances 
will  therefore  evoke  a  variety  of  matched  reactions.  Reference  to  a 
simple  field  such  as  that  of  Figure  4/5/1  will  establish  the 
point. 

This  pairing  of  the  line  of  return  to  the  initial  displacement 
has  sometimes  been  regarded  as  '  intelligent '  and  peculiar  to  living 
things.  But  a  simple  refutation  is  given  by  the  ordinary  pen- 
dulum: if  we  displace  it  to  the  right,  it  develops  a  force  which 
tends  to  move  it  to  the  left;  and  if  we  displace  it  to  the  left,  it 
develops  a  force  which  tends  to  move  it  to  the  right.  Noticing 
that  the  pendulum  reacted  with  forces  which  though  varied  in 
direction  always  pointed  towards  the  centre,  the  mediaeval  scien- 
tist would  have  said  '  the  pendulum  seeks  the  centre  '.  By  this 
phrase  he  would  have  recognised  that  the  behaviour  of  a  stable 
system  may  be  described  as  '  goal-seeking  '.  Without  introducing 
any  metaphysical  implications  we  may  recognise  that  this  type  of 
behaviour  does  occur  in  the  stable  dynamic  systems.  Thus 
Figure  4/16/1  shows  how,  as  the  control  setting  of  a  thermostat 


Figure  4/16/1  :  Tracing  of  the  temperature  (solid  line),  of  a  thermostatically 
controlled  bath,  and  of  the  control  setting  (broken  line). 

54 


4/17  STABILITY 

was  altered,  the  temperature  of  the  apparatus  always  followed  it, 
the  set  temperature  being  treated  as  if  it  were  a  goal. 

Such  a  movement  occurs  here  in  only  one  dimension  (tempera- 
ture), but  other  goal-seeking  devices  may  use  more.  The  radar- 
controlled  searchlight,  for  example,  uses  the  reflected  impulses 
to  alter  its  direction  of  aim  so  as  to  minimise  the  angle  between 
its  direction  of  aim  and  the  bearing  of  the  source  of  the  reflected 
impulses.  So  if  the  aircraft  swerves,  the  searchlight  will  follow 
it  actively,  just  as  the  temperature  followed  the  setting.  Such 
a  system  is  goal-seeking  in  two  dimensions. 

The  examples  show  the  common  feature  that  each  is  '  error- 
controlled  ' :  each  is  partly  controlled  by  the  deviation  of  the 
system's  state  from  the  state  of  equilibrium  (which,  in  these 
examples,  can  be  moved  by  an  outside  operation).  The  thermo- 
stat is  affected  by  the  difference  between  the  actual  and  the  set 
temperatures.  The  searchlight  is  affected  by  the  difference 
between  the  two  directions.  Thus,  machines  with  feedback  are  not 
subject  to  the  oft-repeated  dictum  that  machines  must  act  blindly  and 
cannot  correct  their  errors.  Such  a  statement  is  true  of  machines 
without  feedback,  but  not  of  machines  in  general  (S.  3/11). 

Once  it  is  appreciated  that  feedback  can  be  used  to  correct  any 
deviation  we  like,  it  is  easy  to  understand  that  there  is  no  limit 
to  the  complexity  of  goal-seeking  behaviour  which  may  occur  in 
machines  quite  devoid  of  any  '  vital  '  factor.  Thus,  an  automatic 
anti-aircraft  gun  may  be  controlled  by  the  radar-pulses  reflected 
back  both  from  the  target  aeroplane  and  from  its  own  bursting 
shells,  in  such  a  way  that  it  tends  to  minimise  the  distance  between 
shell-burst  and  plane.  Such  a  system,  wholly  automatic,  cannot 
be  distinguished  by  its  behaviour  from  a  humanly  operated  gun: 
both  will  fire  at  the  target,  following  it  through  all  manoeuvres, 
continually  using  the  errors  to  improve  the  next  shot.  It  will  be 
seen,  therefore,  that  a  system  with  feedback  may  be  both  wholly 
automatic  and  yet  actively  and  complexly  goal-seeking.  There 
is  no  incompatibility. 

4/17.  It  will  have  been  noticed  that  stability,  as  defined,  in  no 
way  implies  fixity  or  rigidity.  It  is  true  that  the  stable  system 
usually  has  a  state  of  equilibrium  at  which  it  shows  no  change; 
but  the  lack  of  change  is  deceptive  if  it  suggests  rigidity:  if  dis- 
placed from  the  state  of  equilibrium  it  will  show  active,  perhaps 

55 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  4/18 

extensive  and  complex,  movements.  The  stable  system  is  re- 
stricted only  in  that  it  doe£  not  show  the  unrestricted  divergencies 
of  instability. 

Stability  and  the  whole 

4/18.  An  important  feature  of  a  system's  stability  (or  instability) 
is  that  it  is  a  property  of  the  whole  system  and  can  be  assigned  to 
no  part  of  it.  The  statement  may  be  illustrated  by  a  consideration 
of  the  first  diagram  of  S.  4/14  as  it  is  related  to  the  practical 
construction  of  the  thermostat.  In  order  to  ensure  the  stability 
of  the  final  assembly,  the  designer  must  consider: 

(1)  The  effect  of  the  temperature  on  the  diameter  of  the  cap- 

sule, i.e.  whether  a  rise  in  temperature  makes  the  capsule 
expand  or  shrink. 

(2)  Which  way  an  expansion  of  the  capsule  moves  the  lever. 

(3)  Which  way  a  movement  of  the  lever  moves  the  gas-tap. 

(4)  Whether   a   given   movement   of  the   gas -tap   makes   the 

velocity  of  gas-flow  increase  or  decrease. 

(5)  Whether  an  increase  of  gas-flow  makes  the  size  of  the  gas- 

flame  increase  or  decrease. 

(6)  How  an  increase  in  size  of  the  gas-flame  will  affect  the  tem- 

perature of  the  capsule. 

Some  of  the  answers  are  obvious,  but  they  must  none  the  less 
be  included.  When  the  six  answers  are  known,  the  designer  can 
ensure  stability  only  by  arranging  the  components  (chiefly  by 
manipulating  (2),  (3)  and  (5))  so  that  as  a  whole  they  form  an 
appropriate  combination.  Thus  five  of  the  effects  may  be  decided, 
yet  the  stability  will  still  depend  on  how  the  sixth  is  related  to 
them.  The  stability  belongs  only  to  the  combination;  it  cannot  be 
related  to  the  parts  considered  separately. 

In  order  to  emphasise  that  the  stability  of  a  system  is  inde- 
pendent of  any  conditions  which  may  hold  over  the  parts  which 
compose  the  whole,  some  further  examples  will  be  given.  (Proofs 
of  the  statements  will  be  found  in  Ss.  20/9  and  21  /12.) 

(a)  Two  systems  may  be  joined  so  that  they  act  and  interact 
on  one  another  to  form  a  single  system:  to  know  that  the  two 
systems  when  separate  were  both  stable  is  to  know  nothing  about 
the  stability  of  the  system  formed  by  their  junction:  it  may  be 
stable  or  unstable. 

56 


4/19  STABILITY 

(b)  Two  systems,  both  unstable,  may  join  to  form  a  whole 
which  is  stable. 

(c)  Two  systems  may  form  a  stable  whole  if  joined  in  one  wray, 
and  may  form  an  unstable  whole  if  joined  in  another  way. 

(d)  In  a  stable  system  the  effect  of  fixing  a  variable  may  be  to 
render  the  remainder  unstable. 

Such  examples  could  be  multiplied  almost  indefinitely.  They 
illustrate  the  rule  that  the  stability  (or  instability)  of  a  dynamic 
system  depends  on  the  parts  and  their  interrelations  as  a  whole. 

4/19.  The  fact  that  the  stability  of  a  system  is  a  property  of  the 
system  as  a  whole  is  related  to  the  fact  that  the  presence  of  stability 
always  implies  some  co-ordination  of  the  actions  between  the  parts. 
In  the  thermostat  the  necessity  for  co-ordination  is  clear,  for  if 
the  components  were  assembled  at  random  there  would  be  only 
an  even  chance  that  the  assembly  would  be  stable.  But  as  the 
system  and  the  feedbacks  become  more  complex,  so  does  the 
achievement  of  stability  become  more  difficult  and  the  likelihood 
of  instability  greater.  Radio  engineers  know  only  too  well  how 
readily  complex  systems  with  feedback  become  unstable,  and  how 
difficult  is  the  discovery  of  just  that  combination  of  parts  and 
linkages  which  will  give  stability. 

The  subject  is  discussed  more  fully  in  S.  20/10:  here  it  is 
sufficient  to  note  that  as  the  number  of  variables  increases  so 
usually  do  the  effects  of  variable  on  variable  have  to  be  co- 
ordinated with  more  and  more  care  if  stability  is  to  be  achieved. 


57 


CHAPTER   5 

Adaptation  as  Stability 

5/1.  The  concept  of  '  adaptation  '  has  so  far  been  used  without 
definition;  this  vagueness  must  be  corrected.  Not  only  must 
the  definition  be  precise,  but  it  must,  by  S.  2/10,  be  given  in  terms 
that  can  be  reduced  wholly  to  primary  operations. 

5/2.  The  suggestion  that  an  animal's  behaviour  is  '  adaptive  ' 
if  the  animal  4  responds  correctly  to  a  stimulus  '  may  be  rejected 
at  once.  First,  it  presupposes  an  action  by  an  experimenter  and 
therefore  cannot  be  applied  when  the  free-living  organism  and 
its  environment  affect  each  other  reciprocally.  Secondly,  the 
definition  provides  no  meaning  for  '  correctly  '  unless  it  means 
4  conforming  to  what  the  experimenter  thinks  the  animal  ought 
to  do  '.     Such  a  definition  is  useless. 

Homeostasis 

5/3.  I  propose  the  definition  that  a  form  of  behaviour  is  adaptive 
if  it  maintains  the  essential  variables  (S.  3/14)  within  physiological 
limits.  The  full  justification  of  such  a  definition  would  involve 
its  comparison  with  all  the  known  facts — an  impossibly  large 
task.  Nevertheless  it  is  fundamental  in  this  subject  and  I  must 
discuss  it  sufficiently  to  show  how  fundamental  it  is  and  how 
wide  is  its  applicability. 

First  I  shall  outline  the  facts  underlying  Cannon's  concept  of 
1  homeostasis  '.  They  are  not  directly  relevant  to  the  problem 
of  learning,  for  the  mechanisms  are  inborn;  but  the  mechanisms 
are  so  clear  and  well  known  that  they  provide  an  ideal  basic 
illustration.     They  show  that: 

(1)  Each  mechanism  is  c  adapted  '  to  its  end. 

(2)  Its  end  is  the  maintenance  of  the  values  of  some  essential 

variables  within  physiological  limits. 

(3)  Almost  all  the  behaviour  of  an  animal's  vegetative  system 

is  due  to  such  mechanisms. 
58 


5/4  ADAPTATION     AS     STABILITY 

5/4.  As  first  example  may  be  quoted  the  mechanisms  which 
tend  to  maintain  within  limits  the  concentration  of  glucose  in 
the  blood.  The  concentration  should  not  fall  below  about  0-06 
per  cent  or  the  tissues  will  be  starved  of  their  chief  source  of 
energy;  and  the  concentration  should  not  rise  above  about 
0.18  per  cent  or  other  undesirable  effects  will  occur.  If  the 
blood-glucose  falls  below  about  0-07  per  cent  the  adrenal  glands 
secrete  adrenaline,  which  makes  the  liver  turn  its  stores  of  glycogen 
into  glucose;  this  passes  into  the  blood  and  the  fall  is  opposed. 
In  addition,  a  falling  blood-glucose  stimulates  the  appetite  so  that 
food  is  taken,  and  this,  after  digestion,  provides  glucose.  On 
the  other  hand,  if  it  rises  excessively,  the  secretion  of  insulin  by 
the  pancreas  is  increased,  causing  the  liver  to  remove  glucose 
from  the  blood.  The  muscles  and  skin  also  remove  it;  and  the 
kidneys  help  by  excreting  glucose  into  the  urine  if  the  concentra- 
tion in  the  blood  exceeds  0-18  per  cent.  Here  then  are  five 
activities  all  of  which  have  the  same  final  effect.  Each  one 
acts  so  as  to  restrict  the  fluctuations  which  might  otherwise  occur. 
Each  may  justly  be  described  as  '  adaptive  ',  for  it  acts  to  preserve 
the  animal's  life. 

The  temperature  of  the  interior  of  the  warm-blooded  animal's 
body  may  be  disturbed  by  exertion,  or  illness,  or  by  exposure  to 
the  weather.  If  the  body  temperature  becomes  raised,  the  skin 
flushes  and  more  heat  passes  from  the  body  to  the  surrounding 
air;  sweating  commences,  and  the  evaporation  of  the  water 
removes  heat  from  the  body ;  and  the  metabolism  of  the  body  is 
slowed,  so  that  less  heat  is  generated  within  it.  If  the  body  is 
chilled,  these  changes  are  reversed.  Shivering  may  start,  and  the 
extra  muscular  activity  provides  heat  which  warms  the  body. 
Adrenaline  is  secreted,  raising  the  muscular  tone  and  the  metabolic 
rate,  which  again  supplies  increased  heat  to  the  body.  The  hairs 
or  feathers  are  moved  by  small  muscles  in  the  skin  so  that  they 
stand  more  erect,  enclosing  more  air  in  the  interstices  and  thus 
conserving  the  body's  heat.  In  extreme  cold  the  human  being, 
when  almost  unconscious,  reflexly  takes  a  posture  of  extreme 
flexion  with  the  arms  pressed  firmly  against  the  chest  and  the 
legs  fully  drawn  up  against  the  abdomen.  The  posture  is  clearly 
one  which  exposes  to  the  air  a  minimum  of  surface.  In  all  these 
ways,  the  body  acts  so  as  to  maintain  its  temperature  within 
limits. 

59 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  5/4 

The  amount  of  carbon  dioxide  in  the  blood  is  important  in 
its  effect  on  the  blood's  alkalinity.  If  the  amount  rises,  the  rate 
and  depth  of  respiration  are  increased,  and  carbon  dioxide  is 
exhaled  at  an  increased  rate.  If  the  amount  falls,  the  reaction 
is  reversed.  By  this  means  the  alkalinity  of  the  blood  is  kept 
within  limits. 

The  retina  works  best  at  a  certain  intensity  of  illumination. 
In  bright  light  the  nervous  system  contracts  the  pupil,  and  in 
dim  relaxes  it.  Thus  the  amount  of  light  entering  the  eye  is 
maintained  within  limits. 

If  the  eye  is  persistently  exposed  to  bright  light,  as  happens 
when  one  goes  to  the  tropics,  the  pigment-cells  in  the  retina 
grow  forward  day  by  day  until  they  absorb  a  large  portion  of  the 
incident  light  before  it  reaches  the  sensitive  cells.  In  this  way 
the  illumination  on  the  sensitive  cells  is  kept  within  limits. 

If  exposed  to  sunshine,  the  pigment-bearing  cells  in  the  skin 
increase  in  number,  extent,  and  pigment-content.  By  this  change 
the  degree  of  illumination  of  the  deeper  layers  of  the  skin  is  kept 
within  limits. 

When  dry  food  is  chewed,  a  copious  supply  of  saliva  is  poured 
into  the  mouth.  Saliva  lubricates  the  food  and  converts  it  from 
a  harsh  and  abrasive  texture  to  one  which  can  be  chewed  without 
injury.  The  secretion  therefore  keeps  the  frictional  stresses  below 
the  destructive  level. 

The  volume  of  the  circulating  blood  may  be  disturbed  by 
haemorrhage.  Immediately  after  a  severe  haemorrhage  a  number 
of  changes  occur:  the  capillaries  in  limbs  and  muscles  undergo 
constriction,  driving  the  blood  from  these  vessels  to  the  more 
essential  internal  organs;  thirst  becomes  extreme,  impelling  the 
subject  to  obtain  extra  supplies  of  fluid;  fluid  from  the  tissues 
passes  into  the  blood-stream  and  augments  its  volume;  and 
clotting  at  the  wound  helps  to  stem  the  haemorrhage.  A  haemor- 
rhage has  a  second  effect  in  that,  by  reducing  the  number  of 
red  corpuscles,  it  reduces  the  amount  of  oxygen  which  can  be 
carried  to  the  tissues;  the  reduction,  however,  itself  stimulates 
the  bone-marrow  to  an  increased  production  of  red  corpuscles. 
All  these  actions  tend  to  keep  the  variables  '  volume  of  circu- 
lating blood  '  and  '  oxygen  supplied  to  the  tissues  '  within  normal 
limits. 

Every  fast-moving  animal  is  liable  to  injury  by  collision  with 

60 


5/6  ADAPTATION    AS     STABILITY 

hard  objects.  Animals,  however,  are  provided  with  reflexes  that 
tend  to  minimise  the  chance  of  collision  and  of  mechanical  injury. 
A  mechanical  stress  causes  injury — laceration,  dislocation,  or 
fracture — only  if  the  stress  exceeds  some  definite  value,  depending 
on  the  stressed  tissue — skin,  ligament,  or  bone.  So  these  reflexes 
act  to  keep  the  mechanical  stresses  within  physiological  limits. 

Many  more  examples  could  be  given,  but  all  can  be  included 
within  the  same  formula.  Some  external  disturbance  tends  to 
drive  an  essential  variable  outside  its  normal  limits;  but  the 
commencing  change  itself  activates  a  mechanism  that  opposes  the 
external  disturbance.  By  this  mechanism  the  essential  variable 
is  maintained  within  limits  much  narrower  than  would  occur  if 
the  external  disturbance  were  unopposed.  The  narrowing  is  the 
objective  manifestation  of  the  mechanism's  adaptation. 

5/5.  The  mechanisms  of  the  previous  section  act  mostly  within 
the  body,  but  it  should  be  noted  that  some  of  them  have  acted 
partly  through  the  environment.  Thus,  if  the  body-temperature 
is  raised,  the  nervous  system  lessens  the  generation  of  heat  within 
the  body  and  the  body-temperature  falls,  but  only  because  the 
body  is  continuously  losing  heat  to  its  surroundings.  Flushing 
of  the  skin  cools  the  body  only  if  the  surrounding  air  is  cool; 
and  sweating  lowers  the  body-temperature  only  if  the  surround- 
ing air  is  unsaturated.  Increasing  respiration  lowers  the  carbon 
dioxide  content  of  the  blood,  but  only  if  the  atmosphere  contains 
less  than  5  per  cent.  In  each  case  the  chain  of  cause  and  effect 
passes  partly  through  the  environment.  The  mechanisms  that 
work  wholly  within  the  body  and  those  that  make  extensive  use 
of  the  environment  are  thus  only  the  extremes  of  a  continuous 
series.  Thus,  a  thirsty  animal  seeks  water:  if  it  is  a  fish  it  does 
no  more  than  swallow,  while  if  it  is  an  antelope  in  the  veldt  it 
has  to  go  through  an  elaborate  process  of  search,  of  travel,  and 
of  finding  a  suitable  way  down  to  the  river  or  pond.  The  homeo- 
static  mechanisms  thus  extend  from  those  that  work  wholly 
within  the  animal  to  those  that  involve  its  widest-ranging  acti- 
vities ;  the  principles  are  uniform  throughout. 

Generalised  homeostasis 
5/6.     Just  the  same  criterion  for  '  adaptation  '  may  be  used  in 
judging  the  behaviour  of  the  free-living  animal  in  its  learned 

61 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  5/6 

reactions.  Take  the  type-problem  of  the  kitten  and  the  fire. 
When  the  kitten  first  approaches  an  open  fire,  it  may  paw  at  the 
fire  as  if  at  a  mouse,  or  it  may  crouch  down  and  start  to  '  stalk  ' 
the  fire,  or  it  may  attempt  to  sniff  at  the  fire,  or  it  may  walk  un- 
concernedly on  to  it.  Every  one  of  these  actions  is  liable  to  lead 
to  the  animal's  being  burned.  Equally  the  kitten,  if  it  is  cold, 
may  sit  far  from  the  fire  and  thus  stay  cold.  The  kitten's 
behaviour  cannot  be  called  adapted,  for  the  temperature  of  its 
skin  is  not  kept  within  normal  limits.  The  animal,  in  other  words, 
is  not  acting  homeostatically  for  skin  temperature.  Contrast  this 
behaviour  with  that  of  the  experienced  cat:  on  a  cold  day  it 
approaches  the  fire  to  a  distance  adjusted  so  that  the  skin  tempera- 
ture is  neither  too  hot  nor  too  cold.  If  the  fire  burns  fiercer,  the 
cat  will  move  away  until  the  skin  is  again  warmed  to  a  moderate 
degree.  If  the  fire  burns  low  the  cat  will  move  nearer.  If  a  red- 
hot  coal  drops  from  the  fire  the  cat  takes  such  action  as  will  keep 
the  skin  temperature  within  normal  limits.  Without  making  any 
enquiry  at  this  stage  into  what  has  happened  to  the  kitten's  brain, 
we  can  at  least  say  that  whereas  at  first  the  kitten's  behaviour 
was  not  hom'eostatic  for  skin  temperature,  it  has  now  become  so. 
Such  behaviour  is  '  adapted  ' :  it  preserves  the  life  of  the  animal 
by  keeping  the  essential  variables  within  limits. 

The  same  thesis  can  be  applied  to  a  great  deal,  if  not  all,  of 
the  normal  human  adult's  behaviour.  In  order  to  demonstrate 
the  wide  application  of  this  thesis,  and  in  order  to  show  that  even 
Man's  civilised  life  is  not  exceptional,  some  of  the  surroundings 
which  he  has  provided  for  himself  will  be  examined  for  their 
known  physical  and  physiological  effects.  It  will  be  shown  that 
each  item  acts  so  as  to  narrow  the  range  of  variation  of  his 
essential  variables. 

The  first  requirement  of  a  civilised  man  is  a  house;  and  its 
first  effect  is  to  keep  the  air  in  which  he  lives  at  a  more  equable 
temperature.  The  roof  keeps  his  skin  at  a  more  constant  dryness. 
The  windows,  if  open  in  summer  and  closed  in  winter,  assist  in 
the  maintenance  of  an  even  temperature,  and  so  do  fires  and 
stoves.  The  glass  in  the  windows  keeps  the  illumination  of  the 
rooms  nearer  the  optimum,  and  artificial  lighting  has  the  same 
effect.  The  chimneys  keep  the  amount  of  irritating  smoke  in  the 
rooms  near  the  optimum,  which  is  zero. 

Many  of  the  other  conveniences  of  civilisation  could,  with  little 

62 


5/7  ADAPTATION     AS     STABILITY 

difficulty,  be  shown  to  be  similarly  variation-limiting.  An  attempt 
to  demonstrate  them  all  would  be  interminable.  But  to  confirm 
the  argument  we  will  examine  a  motor-car,  part  by  part,  in  order 
to  show  its  homeostatic  relation  to  man. 

Travel  in  a  vehicle,  as  contrasted  with  travel  on  foot,  keeps 
several  essential  variables  within  narrower  limits.  The  fatigue 
induced  by  walking  for  a  long  distance  implies  that  some  vari- 
ables, as  yet  not  clearly  known,  have  exceeded  limits  not  trans- 
gressed when  the  subject  is  carried  in  a  vehicle.  The  reserves 
of  food  in  the  body  will  be  less  depleted,  the  skin  on  the  soles  of 
the  feet  will  be  less  chafed,  the  muscles  will  have  endured  less 
strain,  in  winter  the  body  will  have  been  less  chilled,  and  in 
summer  it  will  have  been  less  heated,  than  would  have  happened 
had  the  subject  travelled  on  foot. 

When  examined  in  more  detail,  many  ways  are  found  in  which 
it  serves  us  by  maintaining  our  essential  variables  within  narrower 
limits.  The  roof  maintains  our  skin  at  a  constant  dryness.  The 
windows  protect  us  from  a  cold  wind,  and  if  open  in  summer, 
help  to  cool  us.  The  carpet  on  the  floor  acts  similarly  in  winter, 
helping  to  prevent  the  temperature  of  the  feet  from  falling  below 
its  optimal  value.  The  jolts  of  the  road  cause,  on  the  skin  and 
bone  of  the  human  frame,  stresses  which  are  much  lessened  by 
the  presence  of  springs.  Similar  in  action  are  the  shock-absorbers 
and  tyres.  A  collision  would  cause  an  extreme  deceleration  which 
leads  to  very  high  values  for  the  stress  on  the  skin  and  bone  of 
the  passengers.  By  the  brakes  these  very  high  values  may  be 
avoided,  and  in  this  way  the  brakes  keep  the  variables  '  stress  on 
bone  '  within  narrower  limits.  Good  headlights  keep  the  lumin- 
osity of  the  road  within  limits  narrower  than  would  occur  in  their 
absence. 

The  thesis  that 4  adaptation  '  means  the  maintenance  of  essential 
variables  within  physiological  limits  is  thus  seen  to  hold  not  only 
over  the  simpler  activities  of  primitive  animals  but  over  the  more 
complex  activities  of  the  '  higher  '  organisms. 

5/7.  Before  proceeding  further,  it  must  be  noted  that  the  word 
'  adaptation  '  is  commonly  used  in  two  senses  which  refer  to 
different  processes. 

The  distinction  may  best  be  illustrated  by  the  inborn  homeo- 
static mechanisms :  the  reaction  to  cold  by  shivering,  for  instance. 

63 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  5/8 

Such  a  mechanism  may  undergo  two  types  of  '  adaptation  '.  The 
first  occurred  long  ago  and  was  the  change  from  a  species  too 
primitive  to  show  such  a  reaction  to  a  species  which,  by  natural 
selection,  had  developed  the  reaction  as  a  characteristic  inborn 
feature.  The  second  type  of  4  adaptation  '  occurs  when  a  member 
of  the  species,  born  with  the  mechanism,  is  subjected  to  cold  and 
changes  from  not-shivering  to  shivering.  The  first  change 
involved  the  development  of  the  mechanism  itself;  the  second 
change  occurs  when  the  mechanism  is  stimulated  into  showing 
its  properties. 

In  the  learning  process,  the  first  stage  occurs  when  the  animal 
4  learns  ' :  when  it  changes  from  an  animal  not  having  an  adapted 
mechanism  to  one  which  has  such  a  mechanism.  The  second 
stage  occurs  when  the  developed  mechanism  changes  from  in- 
activity to  activity.  In  this  chapter  we  are  concerned  with  the 
characteristics  of  the  developed  mechanism.  The  processes  which 
led  to  its  development  are  discussed  in  Chapter  9. 

5/8.  We  can  now  recognise  that '  adaptive  '  behaviour  is  equivalent 
to  the  behaviour  of  a  stable  system,  the  region  of  the  stability  being 
the  region  of  the  phase-space  in  which  all  the  essential  variables  lie 
within  their  normal  limits. 

The  view  is  not  new  (though  it  can  now  be  stated  with  more 
precision): 

4  Every  phase  of  activity  in  a  living  being  must  be  not 
only  a  necessary  sequence  of  some  antecedent  change  in  its 
environment,  but  must  be  so  adapted  to  this  change  as  to 
tend  to  its  neutralisation,  and  so  to  the  survival  of  the 
organism.  ...  It  must  also  apply  to  all  the  relations  of 
living  beings.  It  must  therefore  be  the  guiding  principle, 
not  only  in  physiology  .  .  .  but  also  in  the  other  branches 
of  biology  which  treat  of  the  relations  of  the  living  animal 
to  its  environment  and  of  the  factors  determining  its  survival 
in  the  struggle  for  existence.' 

(Starling.) 

4  In  an  open  system,  such  as  our  bodies  represent,  com- 
pounded of  unstable  material  and  subjected  continuously  to 
disturbing  conditions,  constancy  is  in  itself  evidence  that 
agencies  are  acting  or  ready  to  act,  to  maintain  this  constancy.' 

(Cannon.) 

4  Every  material  system  can  exist  as  an  entity  only  so  long 
as  its  internal  forces,  attraction,  cohesion,  etc.,  balance  the 

64 


5/9  ADAPTATION     AS     STABILITY 

external  forces  acting  upon  it.  This  is  true  for  an  ordinary 
stone  just  as  much  as  for  the  most  complex  substances;  and 
its  truth  should  be  recognised  also  for  the  animal  organism. 
Being  a  definite  circumscribed  material  system,  it  can  only 
continue  to  exist  so  long  as  it  is  in  continuous  equilibrium 
with  the.  forces  external  to  it:  so  soon  as  this  equilibrium 
is  seriously  disturbed  the  organism  will  cease  to  exist  as  the 
entity  it  was.' 

(Pavlov.) 

McDougall  never  used  the  concept  of  '  stability  '  explicitly,  but 
when  describing  the  type  of  behaviour  which  he  considered  to 
be  most  characteristic  of  the  living  organism,  he  wrote: 

4  Take  a  billard  ball  from  the  pocket  and  place  it  upon  the 
table.  It  remains  at  rest,  and  would  continue  to  remain  so 
for  an  indefinitely  long  time,  if  no  forces  were  applied  to  it. 
Push  it  in  any  direction,  and  its  movement  in  that  direction 
persists  until  its  momentum  is  exhausted,  or  until  it  is 
deflected  by  the  resistance  of  the  cushion  and  follows  a  new 
path  mechanically  determined.  .  .  .  Now  contrast  with  this 
an  instance  of  behaviour.  Take  a  timid  animal  such  as  a 
guinea-pig  from  its  hole  or  nest,  and  put  it  upon  the  grass 
plot.  Instead  of  remaining  at  rest,  it  runs  back  to  its  hole; 
push  it  in  any  other  direction,  and,  as  soon  as  you  withdraw 
your  hand,  it  turns  back  towards  its  hole ;  place  any  obstacle 
in  its  way,  and  it  seeks  to  circumvent  or  surmount  it,  rest- 
lessly persisting  until  it  achieves  its  end  or  until  its  energy 
is  exhausted.' 

He  could  hardly  have  chosen  an  example  showing  more  clearly 
the  features  of  stability. 


Survival 

5/9.  Are  there  aspects  of  '  adaptation  '  not  included  within  the 
definition  of  '  stability  '  ?  Is  '  survival '  to  be  the  sole  criterion 
of  adaptation  ?  Is  it  to  be  maintained  that  the  Roman  soldier 
who  killed  Archimedes  in  Syracuse  was  better  '  adapted  '  in  his 
behaviour  than  Archimedes  ? 

The  question  is  not  easily  answered.  It  is  similar  to  that  of 
S.  3/4  where  it  was  asked  whether  all  the  qualities  of  the  living 
organism  could  be  represented  by  number;  and  the  answer  must 
be  similar.  It  is  assumed  that  we  are  dealing  primarily  with 
the  simpler  rather  than  with  the  more  complex  creatures,  though 

65 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


5/10 


the  examples  of  S.  5/6  have  shown  that  some  at  least  of  man's 

activities  may  be  judged  properly  by  this  criterion. 

In  order  to  survey  rapidly  the  types  of  behaviour  of  the  more 

primitive  animals,  we  may  examine  the  classification  of  Holmes, 

who  intended  his  list  to  be  exhaustive  but  constructed  it  with 

no  reference  to  the  concept  of  stability.     The  reader  will  be  able 

to  judge  how  far  our  formulation  (S.  5/8)  is  consistent  with  his 

scheme,  which  is  given  in  Table  5/9/1. 

'Useless  tropistic  reaction. 
Misdirected  instinct. 
Abnormal  sex  behaviour. 
Non-adaptive  ^  Pathological  behaviour. 

Useless  social  activity. 
Superfluous  random 
movements. 

'Capture,      devouring      of 

food. 
Activities  preparatory,  as 

making  snares,  stalking. 
Collection  of  food,  digging. 
Migration. 
Caring  for  food,   storing, 

burying,  hiding. 
Preparing  of  food. 


Behaviour  - 


Adaptive 


Self- 
maintaining 


Sustentative 


{Against      enemies — fight, 
flight. 
Against  inanimate  forces. 
Reactions  to  heat,  gravity, 
chemicals. 
Against  inanimate  objects. 


Ameliorative  Rest,  sleep,  play,  basking. 

^maintaining   {  <With   thesec  w,e  Qaxre  not  concerned, 

Table  5/9/1  :    All  forms  of  animal  behaviour,  classified  by  Holmes. 

For  the  primitive  organism,  and  excluding  behaviour  related  to 
racial  survival,  there  seems  to  be  little  doubt  that  the  '  adaptive- 
ness  '  of  behaviour  is  properly  measured  by  its  tendency  to 
promote  the  organism's  survival. 

5/10.  A  most  impressive  characteristic  of  living  organisms  is 
their  mobility,  their  tendency  to  change.  McDougall  expressed 
this  characteristic  well  in  the  example  of  S.  5/8.  Yet  our  formula- 
tion transfers  the  centre  of  interest  to  the  state  of  equilibrium, 
to  the  fact  that  the  essential  variables  of  the  adapted  organism 
change  less  than  they  would  if  it  were  unadapted.  Which  is 
important :  constancy  or  change  ? 

66 


5/11  ADAPTATION     AS     STABILITY 

The  two  aspects  are  not  incompatible,  for  the  constancy  of  some 
variables  may  involve  the  vigorous  activity  of  others.  A  good 
thermostat  reacts  vigorously  to  a  small  change  of  temperature, 
and  the  vigorous  activity  of  some  of  its  variables  keeps  the  others 
within  narrow  limits.  The  point  of  view  taken  here  is  that  the 
constancy  of  the  essential  variables  is  fundamentally  important, 
and  that  the  activity  of  the  other  variables  is  important  only  in 
so  far  as  it  contributes  to  this  end.  (The  matter  is  discussed 
more  thoroughly  in  /.  to  C,  Chapter  10.) 

Stability  and  co-ordination 

5/11.  So  far  the  discussion  has  traced  the  relation  between  the 
concepts  of  '  adaptation  '  and  of  '  stability  '.  It  will  now  be 
proposed  that  '  motor  co-ordination  '  also  has  an  essential  con- 
nexion with  stability. 

4  Motor-co-ordination  '  is  a  concept  well  understood  in  physio- 
logy, where  it  refers  to  the  ability  of  the  organism  to  combine  the 
activities  of  several  muscles  so  that  the  resulting  movement 
follows  accurately  its  appropriate  path.  Contrasted  to  it  are  the 
concepts  of  clumsiness,  tremor,  ataxia,  athetosis.  It  is  suggested 
that  the  presence  or  absence  of  co-ordination  may  be  decided,  in 
accordance  with  our  methods,  by  observing  whether  the  move- 
ment does,  or  does  not,  deviate  outside  given  limits. 


Figure  5/11/1. 

The  formulation  seems  to  be  adequate  provided  that  we  measure 
the  limb's  deviations  from  some  line  which  is  given  arbitrarily, 
usually  by  a  knowledge  of  the  line  followed  by  the  normal  limb. 
A  first  example  is  given  by  Figure  5/11/1,  which  shows  the  line 
traced  by  the  point  of  an  expert  fencer's  foil  during  a  lunge. 
Any  inco-ordination  would  be  shown  by  a  divergence  from  the 
intended  line. 

A  second  example  is  given  by  the  record  of  Figure  5/11/2.  The 
subject,  a  patient  with  a  tumour  in  the  left  cerebellum,  was  asked 

67 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN 


5/12 


to  follow  the  dotted  lines  with  a  pen.  The  left-  and  right-hand 
curves  were  drawn  with  the  respective  hands.  The  tracing  shows 
clearly  that  the  co-ordination  is  poorer  in  the  left  hand.  What 
criterion  reveals  the  fact  ?  The  essential 
distinction  is  that  the  deviations  of  the 
lines  from  the  dots  are  larger  on  the  left 
than  on  the  right. 

The  degree  of  motor  co-ordination 
achieved  may  therefore  be  measured  by 
the  smallness  of  the  deviations  from  some 
standard  line.  Later  it  will  be  suggested 
that  there  are  mechanisms  which  act  to 
maintain  variables  within  narrow  limits. 
If  the  identification  of  this  section  is 
accepted,  such  mechanisms  could  be 
regarded  as  appropriate  for  the  co-ordina- 
tion of  motor  activity. 


Figure  5/11/2  :  Record 
of  the  attempts  of  a 
patient  to  follow  the 
dotted  lines  with  the  left 
and  right  hands.  (By 
the  courtesy  of  Dr.W.T. 
Grant  of  Los  Angeles.) 


5/12.  So  far  we  have  noticed  in  stable 
systems  only  their  property  of  keeping 
variables  within  limits.  But  such  sys- 
tems have  other  properties  of  which  we  shall  notice  two.  They 
are  also  shown  by  animals,  and  are  then  sometimes  considered 
to  provide  evidence  that  the  organism  has  some  power  of 
4  intelligence  '  not  shared  by  non-living  systems.  In  these  two 
instances  the  assumption  is  unnecessary. 

The  first  property  is  shown  by  a  stable  system  when  the  lines 
of  behaviour  do  not  return  directly,  by  a  straight  line,  to  the  state 
of  equilibrium  (e.g.  Figure  4/5/3). 
When  this  occurs,  variables  may  be 
observed  to  move  away  from  their 
values  in  the  state  of  equilibrium,  only 
to  return  to  them  later.  Thus,  sup- 
pose in  Figure  5/12/1  that  the  field 
is  stable  and  that  at  the  equilibrial 
state  R  x  and  y  have  the  values  X 
and  Y.  For  clarity,  only  one  line  of 
behaviour  is  drawn.  Let  the  system  be  displaced  to  A  and 
its  subsequent  behaviour  observed.  At  first,  while  the  repre- 
sentative point  moves  towards  B,  y  hardly  alters;  but  xt  which 

68 


y 

A 

fl 

Y 

R 

j 

Z 

X' 

X 

X 

Figure  5/12/1. 


5/13  ADAPTATION     AS     STABILITY 

started  at  X\  moves  to  Ar  and  goes  past  it  to  X".  Then  x  remains 
almost  constant  and  y  changes  until  the  representative  point 
reaches  C.  Then  y  stops  changing,  and  x  changes  towards,  and 
reaches,  its  resting  value  X.  The  system  has  now  reached  a  state 
of  equilibrium  and  no  further  changes  occur.  This  account  is  just 
a  transcription  into  words  of  what  the  field  defines  graphically. 

Now  the  shape  and  features  of  any  field  depend  ultimately  on 
the  real  physical  and  chemical  construction  of  the  '  machine  ' 
from  which  the  variables  are  abstracted.  The  fact  that  the  line 
of  behaviour  does  not  run  straight  from  A  to  R  must  be  due  to 
some  feature  in  the  4  machine  '  such  that  if  the  machine  is  to 
get  from  state  A  to  state  R,  states  B  and  C  must  be  passed 
through  of  necessity.  Thus,  if  the  machine  contained  moving 
parts,  their  shapes  might  prohibit  the  direct  route  from  A  to  R; 
or  if  the  system  were  chemical  the  prohibition  might  be  thermo- 
dynamic. But  in  either  case,  if  the  observer  watched  the  machine 
work,  and  thought  it  alive,  he  might  say :  '  How  clever  !  x 
couldn't  get  from  A  to  R  directly  because  this  bar  was  in  the 
way;  so  x  went  to  B,  which  made  y  carry  x  from  B  to  C;  and 
once  at  C,  x  could  get  straight  back  to  R.  I  believe  x  shows 
foresight.' 

Both  points  of  view  are  reasonable.  A  stable  system  may  be 
regarded  both  as  blindly  obeying  the  laws  of  its  nature,  and  also 
as  showing  skill  in  getting  back  to  its  state  of  equilibrium  in  spite 
of  obstacles.* 

5/13.  The  second  property  is  shown  when  an  organism  reacts  to 
a  variable  with  which  it  is  not  directly  in  contact.  Suppose, 
for  instance,  that  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  (S.  4/12)  is 
that  of  Figure  5/13/1;  the  variables  have  been  divided  by  the 
dotted  line  into  '  animal  '  on  the  right  and  '  environment  '  on 
the  left,  and  the  animal  is  not  in  direct  contact  with  the  variable 
marked  X.     The  system  is  assumed  to  be  stable,  i.e.  to  have 

*  I  would  like  to  acknowledge  that  much  of  what  I  am  describing  was 
arrived  at  independently  by  G.  Sommerhoff.  I  met  his  Analytical  Biology 
only  when  the  first  edition  of  Design  for  a  Brain  was  in  proof,  and  I  could  do 
no  more  than  add  his  title  to  my  list  of  references.  Since  then  it  has  become 
apparent  that  our  work  was  developing  in  parallel,  for  there  is  a  deep  similarity 
of  outlook  and  method  in  the  two  books.  The  superficial  reader  might  notice 
some  differences  and  think  we  are  opposed,  but  I  am  sure  the  distinctions  are 
only  on  minor  matters  of  definition  or  emphasis.  The  reader  who  wishes  to 
explore  these  topics  further  should  consult  his  book  as  a  valuable  independent 
contribution. 

69 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


5/14 


arrived  at  the  '  adapted  '  condition  (S.  5/7).  If  disturbed,  its 
changes  will  show  co-ordination  of  part  with  part  (S.  5/12),  and 
this  co-ordination  will  hold  over  the  whole  system  (S.  4/18).  It 
follows  that  the  behaviour  of  the  '  animal  '-part  will  be  co- 
ordinated with  the  behaviour  of  X  although  the  '  animal  '  has 
no  immediate  contact  with  it.     (Example  in  S.  8/7.) 

In  the  higher  organisms,  and  especially  in  Man,  the  power  to 
react  correctly  to  something  not  immediately  visible  or  tangible 
has  been  called  '  imagination  ',  or  '  abstract  thinking  ',  or  several 
other  names  whose  precise  meaning  need  not  be  discussed  at 
the  moment.     Here  we  should  notice  that  the  co-ordination  of 


-< — . 

"* — I 

! > 

'-. > 


Figure  5/13/1. 

the  behaviour  of  one  part  with  that  of  another  part  not  in  direct 
contact  with  it  is  simply  an  elementary  property  of  the  stable 
system. 

5/14.  Let  us  now  re-state  our  problem  in  the  new  vocabulary. 
If,  for  brevity,  we  omit  minor  qualifications,  we  can  state  it  thus : 
A  determinate  '  machine  '  changes  from  a  form  that  produces 
chaotic,  unadapted  behaviour  to  a  form  in  which  the  parts  are 
so  co-ordinated  that  the  whole  is  stable,  acting  to  maintain  its 
essential  variables  within  certain  limits — how  can  this  happen  ? 
For  example,  what  sort  of  a  thermostat  could,  if  assembled  at 
random,  rearrange  its  own  parts  to  get  itself  stable  for  temperature? 
It  will  be  noticed  that  the  new  statement  involves  the  concept 
of  a  machine  changing  its  internal  organisation.  So  far,  nothing 
has  been  said  of  this  important  concept;  so  it  will  be  treated  in 
the  next  chapter. 

70 


CHAPTER   6 

Parameters 

6/1.  So  far,  we  have  discussed  the  changes  shown  by  the  vari- 
ables of  a  state-determined  system,  and  have  ignored  the  fact  that 
all  its  changes  occur  on  a  background,  or  on  a  foundation,  of 
constancies.  Thus,  a  particular  simple  pendulum  provides  two 
variables  which  are  known  (S.  2/15)  to  be  such  that,  if  we  are 
given  a  particular  state  of  the  system,  we  can  predict  correctly 
its  ensuing  behaviour  ;  what  has  not  been  stated  explicitly  is  that 
this  is  true  only  if  the  length  of  the'  string  remains  constant.  The 
background,  and  these  constancies,  must  now  be  considered. 

Every  system  is  formed  by  selecting  some  variables  out  of  the 
totality  of  possible  variables.  '  Forming  a  system  '  means  dividing 
the  variables  of  the  universe  into  two  classes:  those  within  the 
system  and  those  without.  These  two  types  of  variable  are  in 
no  way  different  in  their  intrinsic  physical  nature,  but  they  stand 
in  very  different  relations  to  the  system. 

6/2.  Given  a  system,  a  variable  not  included  in  it  is  a  parameter. 
The  word  variable  will,  from  now  on,  be  reserved  for  one  within 
the  system. 

In  general,  given  a  system,  the  parameters  will  differ  in  their 
closeness  of  relation  to  it.  Some  will  have  a  direct  relation  to  it  : 
change  of  their  value  would  affect  the  system  to  a  major  degree; 
such  is  the  parameter  '  length  of  pendulum  '  in  its  relation  to  the 
two-variable  system  of  the  previous  section.  Some  are  less  closely 
related  to  it,  their  changes  producing  only  a  slight  effect  on  it; 
such  is  the  parameter  4  viscosity  of  the  air  '  in  relation  to  the  same 
system.  And  finally,  for  completeness,  may  be  mentioned  the 
infinite  number  of  parameters  that  are  without  detectable  effect 
on  the  system;  such  are  the  brightness  of  the  light  shining  on 
the  pendulum,  the  events  in  an  adjacent  room,  and  the  events  in 
the  distant  nebulae.  Those  without  detectable  effect  may  be 
ignored;  but  the  relationship  of  an  effective  parameter  to  a 
system  must  be  clearly  understood. 

71 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


6/3 


Given  a  system,  the  effective  parameters  are  usually  innumer- 
able, so  that  a  list  is  bounded  only  by  the  imagination  of  the 
writer.  Thus,  parameters  whose  change  might  affect  the  be- 
haviour of  the  same  system  of  two  variables  are: 

( 1 )  the  length  of  the  pendulum  (hitherto  assumed  constant), 

(2)  the  lateral  velocity  of  the  air  (hitherto  assumed  to  be  con- 

stant at  zero), 

(3)  the  viscosity  of  the  surrounding  medium  (hitherto  assumed 

constant), 

(4)  the  movement,  if  any,  of  the  point  of  support, 

(5)  the  force  of  gravity, 

(6)  the  magnetic  field  in  which  it  swings, 

(7)  the  elastic  constant  of  the  string  of  the  pendulum, 

(8)  its  electrostatic  charge,  and  the  charges  on  bodies  nearby  ; 
but  the  list  has  no  end. 

Parameter  and  field 

6/3.     The  effect  on  a  state-determined  system  of  a  change  of 
parameter-value   will   now   be   shown.     Table   6/3/1    shows   the 


Length 
(cm.) 

Line 

Vari- 
able 

Time 

0 

005 

010 

015 

0-20 

0-25 

0-30 

1 

X 

0 

14 

20 

25 

28 

29 

y 

147 

142 

129 

108 

80 

48 

12 

40 

2 

X 

14 

20 

25 

28 

29 

29 

27 

y 

129 

108 

80 

48 

12 

-  24 

-  58 

3 

X 

0 

7 

14 

21 

26 

31 

34 

y 

147 

144 

135 

121 

101 

78 

51 

60 

4 

X 

21 

2G 

31 

34 

36 

36 

35 

y 

121 

101 

78 

51 

23 

-  6 

-  36 

Table  6/3/1. 


results  of  twenty-four  primary  operations  applied  to  the  two- 
variable  system  mentioned  above,     x  is  the  angular  deviation 

72 


6/4 


PARAMETERS 


from  the  vertical,  in  degrees;   y  is  the  angular  velocity,  in  degrees 
per  second;    the  time  is  in  seconds. 

The  first  two  Lines  show  that  the  lines  of  behaviour  following 
the  state  x  =  14,  y  =  129  are  equal,  so  the  system,  as  far  as 
it  has  been  tested,  is  state-determined.  The  line  of  behaviour  is 
shown  solid  in  Figure  6/3/1.  In  these  swings  the  length  of  the 
pendulum  was  40  cm.  This  parameter  was  then  changed  to  60  cm. 
and  two  further  lines  of  behaviour  were  observed.  On  these  two, 
the  lines  of  behaviour  following 
the  state  x  =  21,  y  =  121  are 
equal,  so  the  system  is  again 
state-determined.  The  line  of 
behaviour  is  shown  dotted  in  the 
same  figure.  But  the  change  of 
parameter-value  has  caused  the 
line  of  behaviour  from  x  =  0, 
y  =  147  to  change. 

The  relationship  which  the  para- 
meter bears  to  the  two  variables 
is  therefore  as  follows  : 

(1)  So  long  as  the  parameter  is  constant,  the  system  of  x  and 
y  is  state-determined,  and  has  a  definite  field. 

(2)  After  the  parameter  changes  from  one  constant  value  to 
another,  the  system  of  x  and  y  becomes  again  state-determined,  and 
has  a  definite  field,  but  this  field  is  not  the  same  as  the  previous  one. 

The  relation  is  general.  A  change  in  the  value  of  an  effective 
parameter  changes  the  line  of  behaviour  from  each  state.  From 
this  follows  at  once :  a  change  in  the  value  of  an  effective  parameter 
changes  the  field. 

From  this  follows  the  important  quantitative  relation :  a  system 
can,  in  general,  show  as  many  fields  as  its  parameters  can  show 
combinations  of  values. 


IOO 

y 

\ 

o 

20 

i 

Figure  6/3/1, 


6/4.  The  importance  of  distinguishing  between  change  of  a 
variable  and  change  of  a  parameter,  that  is,  between  change  of 
state  and  change  of  field,  can  hardly  be  over-estimated.  It  is  this 
distinction  that  will  enable  us  to  avoid  the  confusion  threatened 
in  S.  2/1  between  those  changes  that  are  behaviour  and  changes 
that  occur  from  one  behaviour  to  another.  In  order  to  make  the 
distinction  clear  I  will  give  some  examples. 

73 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


6/4 


In  a  working  clock,  the  single  variable  defined  by  the  reading 
of  the  minute-hand  on  the  face  is  state-determined  as  a  one- 
variable  system;  for  after  some  observations  of  its  behaviour,  we 
can  predict  the  line  of  behaviour  which  will  follow  any  given  state. 
If  now  the  regulator  (the  parameter)  is  moved  to  a  new  position, 
so  that  the  clock  runs  at  a  different  rate,  and  the  system  is  re- 
examined, it  will  be  found  to  be  still  state-determined  but  to  have 
a  different  field. 

If  a  healthy  person  drinks  100  g.  of  glucose  dissolved  in  water, 
the  amount  of  glucose  in  his  blood  usually  rises  and  falls  as  A 
in  Figure  6/4/1.     The  single  variable  '  blood-glucose  '  is  not  state- 


Figure  6/4/1  :    Changes  in  blood-glucose  after  the  ingestion  of  100  g. 
of  glucose  :    (A)  in  the  normal  person,  (B)  in  the  diabetic. 

determined,  for  a  given  state  (e.g.  120  mg./lOO  ml.)  does  not 
define  the  subsequent  behaviour,  for  the  blood-glucose  may  rise  or 
fall.  By  adding  a  second  variable,  however,  such  as  4  rate  of 
change  of  blood-glucose  ',  which  may  be  positive  or  negative,  we 
obtain  a  two-variable  system  which  is  sufficiently  state-determined 
for  illustration.  The  field  of  this  two-variable  system  will  re- 
semble that  of  A  in  Figure  6/4/2.  But  if  the  subject  is  diabetic, 
the  curve  of  the  blood-glucose,  even  if  it  starts  at  the  same  initial 
value,  rises  much  higher,  as  B  in  Figure  6/4/1.  When  the  field 
of  this  behaviour  is  drawn  (B,  Figure  6/4/2),  it  is  seen  to  be  not  the 
same  as  that  of  the  normal  subject.  The  change  of  value  of  the 
parameter  '  degree  of  diabetes  present  '  has  thus  changed  the 
field. 

Girden  and  Culler  developed  a  conditioned  response  in  a  dog 
which  was  under  the  influence  of  curare   (a  paralysing  drug)- 

74 


6/5  PARAMETERS 

When  later  the  animal  was  not  under  its  influence,  the  conditioned 
response  could  not  be  elicited.  But  when  the  dog  was  again  put 
under   its   influence,   the   conditioned  response   returned.     Thus 


St  .200- 

A 

/^\ 

B 

blood 
100  ml 

o 

f 

( 

si 

u  ""  -IOC 
o 

J 

V 

0l 

t 1 

(£  100  200  100  200  300 

BLOOD     GLUCOSE    (mg.  per  100  ml J 

Figure  6/4/2  :   Fields  of  the  two  lines  of  behaviour,  A  and  B  from 
Figure  6/4/1.     Cross-strokes  mark  each  quarter-hour. 

two  characteristic  lines  of  behaviour  (two  responses  to  the  stimulus) 
existed,  and  one  line  of  behaviour  was  shown  when  the  parameter 
*  concentration  of  curare  in  the  tissues  '  had  a  high  value,  and 
the  other  when  the  parameter  had  a  low  value. 


Stimuli 

6/5.  Many  stimuli  may  be  represented  adequately  as  a  change 
of  parameter- value,  so  it  is  convenient  here  to  relate  the  physio- 
logical and  psychological  concept  of  a  '  stimulus  '  to  our  methods. 

In  all  cases  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  is 

(experimenter)  — - >  stimulator  — ►  animal  — >  recorders. 

In  some  cases  the  animal,  at  some  state  of  equilibrium,  is 
subjected  to  a  sudden  change  in  the  value  of  the  stimulator,  and 
the  second  value  is  sustained  throughout  the  observation.  Thus, 
the  pupillary  reaction  to  light  is  demonstrated  by  first  accustoming 
the  eye  to  a  low  intensity  of  illumination,  and  then  suddenly 
raising  the  illumination  to  a  high  level  which  is  maintained  while 
the  reaction  proceeds.  In  such  cases  the  stimulator  is  parameter 
to  the  system  '  animal  and  recorders  ' ;  and  the  physiologist's 
comparison  of  the  previous  control-behaviour  with  the  behaviour 
after  stimulation  is  equivalent,  in  our  method,  to  a  comparison  of 
the  two  lines  of  behaviour  that,  starting  from  the  same  initial 
state,  run  in  the  two  fields  provided  by  the  two  values  of  the 
stimulator.  In  this  type,  the  stimulator  behaves  as  a  step- 
function  (S.  7/13). 

75 


DESIGN     FOE    A    BRAIN  6/6 

Sometimes  a  parameter  is  changed  sharply  and  is  immediately 
returned  to  its  initial  value,  as  when  the  experimenter  applies  a 
a  tap  on  a  tendon.  The  effect  of  the  parameter-change  is  a  brief 
change  of  field  which,  while  it  lasts,  carries  the  representative 
point  away  from  its  original  position.  When  the  parameter  is 
returned  to  its  original  value,  the  original  field  and  state  of  equili- 
brium are  restored,  but  the  representative  point  is  now  away 
from  the  state  of  equilibrium;  it  therefore  moves  along  a  line  of 
behaviour,  and  the  organism  '  responds  '.  (Usually  the  point 
returns  to  the  same  state  of  equilibrium :  but  if  there  is  more  than 
one,  it  may  go  to  some  other  state  of  equilibrium.)  Such  a 
stimulus  will  be  called  impulsive. 

It  will  be  necessary  later  to  be  more  precise  about  what  we  mean 
by  '  the  '  stimulus.  Consider,  for  instance,  a  dog  developing  a 
conditioned  reflex  to  the  ringing  of  an  electric  bell.  What  is  the 
stimulus  exactly  ?  Is  it  the  closing  of  the  contact  switch  ?  The 
intermittent  striking  of  the  hammer  on  the  bell  ?  The  vibrations 
in  the  air  ?  The  vibrations  of  the  ear-drum,  of  the  ossicles,  of 
the  basilar  membrane  ?  The  impulses  in  the  acoustic  nerve,  in  the 
temporal  cortex  ?  If  we  are  to  be  precise  we  must  recognise  that 
the  experimenter  controls  directly  only  the  contact  switch,  and 
that  this  acts  as  parameter  to  the  complexly-acting  system  of 
electric  bell,  middle  ear,  and  the  rest. 

When  the  '  stimulus  '  becomes  more  complex  we  must  generalise. 
One  generalisation  increases  the  number  of  parameters  made  to 
alter,  as  when  a  conditioned  dog  is  subjected  to  combinations  of  a 
ticking  metronome,  a  smell  of  camphor,  a  touch  on  the  back,  and 
a  flashing  light.  Here  we  should  notice  that  if  the  parameters 
are  not  all  independent  but  change  in  groups,  like  the  variables 
in  S.  3/3,  we  can  represent  each  undivided  group  by  a  single 
value  and  thus  avoid  using  unnecessarily  large  numbers  of 
parameters. 

Joining  dynamic  systems 

6/6.     We  can  now  make  clear  what  is  meant,  essentially,  by  the 
concept  of  two  (or  more)  systems  being  '  joined  '. 

This  concept  is  of  the  highest  importance  in  biology,  in  which  it 
occurs  frequently  and  prominently.  It  occurs  whenever  we  think 
of  one  system  having  an  effect  on  another,  or  communicating  with 
it,  or  forcing  it,  or  signalling  to  it. 

76 


6/7  PARAMETERS 

(The  exact  nature  of  the  operation  of  joining  is  shown  most 
clearly  in  the  mathematical  form  (S.  21/9)  for  there  one  can  see 
what  is  essential  and  what  irrelevant.  A  detailed  treatment  has 
been  given  in  /.  to  C,  S.  4/6;  here  we  can  discuss  it  less  rigorously.) 

To  join  two  systems,  A  and  B  say,  so  that  A  affects  B,  A  must 
affect  2?'s  conditions.  In  other  words,  the  values  of  some  of  B's 
parameters  (perhaps  one  only)  must  become  functions  of  (de- 
pendent on)  the  values  of  A's  variables.  Thus,  if  B  is  a  developing 
egg  in  an  incubator  and  A  is  the  height  of  the  barometer,  then 
A  could  be  i  joined  '  so  as  to  affect  B  if  the  temperature  (or  other 
suitable  parameter)  were  made  sensitive  to  the  pressure. 

In  this  example  there  is  no  obvious  way  of  making  the  develop- 
ment of  the  egg  affect  the  height  of  the  barometer,  so  the  joining 
of  B  to  A  can  hardly  be  done.  In  most  cases,  however,  joinings 
are  possible  in  either  direction.  If  both  are  made,  then  feedback 
has  been  set  up  between  the  two  systems. 

In  very  simple  cases,  the  behaviour  of  the  whole  formed  by 
joining  parts  can  be  traced  step  by  step  by  logical  or  mathematical 
deduction.  Each  part  can  be  thought  of  as  having  its  own  phase- 
space,  filled  by  a  field ;  which  field  it  is  will  depend  on  the  position 
of  the  other  part's  representative  point.  Each  representative 
point  now  undergoes  a  transition,  guided  by  its  own  field,  whose 
form  depends  on  the  position  of  the  other.  So  step  by  step,  each 
goes  forward  guided  by  the  other  and  also  guiding  it.  (The  process 
has  been  traced  in  detail  in  /.  to  C,  S.  4/7.) 

This  picture  is  too  complicated  for  any  imaginative  grasp  of 
how  two  actual  systems  will  behave;  the  details  must  be  worked 
out  by  some  other  method.  What  is  important  is  that  the  nature 
of  the  process  is  conceptually  quite  free  from  vagueness  or  ambi- 
guity; so  it  may  properly  be  included  in  a  rigorous  theory  of 
dynamic  systems. 


Parameter  and  stability 

6/7.  We  now  reach  the  main  point  of  the  chapter.  Because 
a  change  of  parameter-value  changes  the  field,  and  because  a 
system's  stability  depends  on  its  field,  a  change  of  parameter- 
value  will  in  general  change  a  system's  stability  in  some  way. 

A  simple  example  is  given  by  a  mixture  of  hydrogen,  nitrogen, 
and  ammonia,  which  combine  or  dissociate  until  the  concentrations 

77 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  6/8 

reach  the  state  of  equilibrium.  If  the  mixture  was  originally 
derived  from  pure  ammonia,  the  single  variable  '  percentage 
dissociated  '  forms  a  one-variable  state-determined  system. 
Among  its  parameters  are  temperature  and  pressure.  As  is  well 
known,  changes  in  these  parameters  affect  the  position  of  the 
state  of  equilibrium. 

Such  a  system  is  simple  and  responds  to  the  changes  of  the 
parameters  with  only  a  simple  shift  of  equilibrium.  No  such 
limitation  applies  generally.  Change  of  parameter-value  may 
result  in  any  change  which  can  be  produced  by  the  substitution  of 
one  field  for  another:  stable  systems  may  become  unstable,  states 
of  equilibrium  may  be  moved,  single  states  of  equilibrium  may 
become  multiple,  states  of  equilibrium  may  become  cycles;  and 
so  on.     Figure  21/8/1  provides  an  illustration. 

Here  we  need  only  the  relationship,  which  is  reciprocal:  in 
a  state-determined  system,  a  change  of  stability  can  only  be  due  to 
change  of  value  of  a  parameter,  and  change  of  value  of  a  parameter 
causes  a  change  in  stability. 


Equilibria  of  part  and  whole 

6/8.  In  general,  as  S.  4/18  showed,  the  relation  between  the 
stabilities  of  the  parts  and  that  of  the  whole  may  be  complex, 
and  may  require  specialised  methods  for  its  treatment.  There  is, 
however,  one  quite  simple  relationship  that  will  be  of  the  greatest 
use  to  us  and  which  can  be  readily  described. 

Suppose  we  join  two  parts,  A  with  variables  u  and  v,  and  B 
with  variables  w,  x  and  y.  If  A's  variables  have  values  7  and  2, 
and  B's  have  values  3,  1  and  5,  then  the  whole  is,  naturally,  a 
system  with  the  five  variables  u,  v,  w,  x  and  y;  and  in  the  cor- 
responding state  the  variables  of  the  whole  have  the  values  7, 
2,  3,  1  and  5  respectively. 

Suppose  now  that  this  state — (7,  2,  3,  1,  5) — of  the  whole  is  a 
state  of  equilibrium  of  the  whole.  This  implies  that  the  transi- 
tion is  from  that  state  to  itself  (S.  4/4).  This  implies  that  A, 
with  the  values  3,  1,  5  on  its  parameters,  goes  from  (7,  2)  to  (7,  2); 
i.e.  does  not  change.  Thus,  the  whole's  being  at  a  state  of  equili- 
brium at  (7,  2,  3,  1,  5)  implies  that  A,  when  at  (7,  2),  with  values 
(3,  1,  5)  on  its  parameters,  must  be  at  a  state  of  equilibrium. 
Similarly  B,  when  its  parameters  are  at  (7,  2),  must  have  a  state 

78 


6/10  PARAMETERS 

of  equilibrium  at  (3,  1,  5).  So,  the  whole's  being  at  a  state  of 
equilibrium  implies  that  each  part  must  be  at  a  state  of  equilibrium, 
in  the  conditions  provided  (at  its  parameters)  by  the  other  parts. 

Conversely,  suppose  A  is  in  equilibrium  at  state  (7,  2)  when 
its  parameters  have  the  values  (3,  1,  5);  and  that  B  is  in  equi- 
librium at  state  (3,  1,  5)  when  its  parameters  are  at  (7,  2).  It 
follows  that  the  whole  will  have  a  state  of  equilibrium  at  the 
state  (7,  2,  3,  1,  5),  for  at  this  state  neither  A  nor  B  can  change. 

To  sum  up :  That  a  whole  dynamic  system  should  be  in  equilibrium 
at  a  particular  state  it  is  necessary  and  sufficient  that  each  part  should 
be  in  equilibrium  at  that  state,  in  the  conditions  given  to  it  by  the 
other  parts. 

6/9.  Suppose  now  that  a  whole,  made  by  joining  parts,  is  moving 
along  a  line  of  behaviour.  Suppose  the  line  of  behaviour  meets  a 
state  that  is  one  of  equilibrium  for  one  part  (in  the  conditions 
given  at  that  moment  by  the  others)  but  not  equilibrial  for  the 
other  parts.  The  part  in  equilibrium  will  stop,  momentarily; 
but  the  other  parts,  not  in  equilibrium,  will  change  their  states 
and  will  thereby  change  the  conditions  of  the  part  in  equilibrium. 
Usually  the  change  of  conditions  (change  of  parameter- values) 
will  make  the  state  no  longer  one  of  equilibrium:  so  the  part  that 
stopped  willl  now  start  moving  again. 

Clearly,  at  any  state  of  the  whole,  if  a  single  part  is  not  at 
equilibrium  (even  though  the  remainder  are)  this  part  will  change, 
will  provide  new  conditions  for  the  other  parts,  will  thus  start 
them  moving  again,  and  will  thus  prevent  that  state  from  being 
one  of  equilibrium  for  the  whole.  As  equilibrium  of  the  whole 
requires  that  all  the  parts  be  in  equilibrium,  we  can  say  (meta- 
phorically) that  every  part  has  a  power  of  veto  over  the  states  of 
equilibrium  of  the  whole. 

6/10.  The  importance  of  this  fact  can  now  be  indicated.  By 
this  fact  each  part  acts  selectively  towards  the  set  of  possible 
equilibria  of  the  whole.  Since  Chapter  1  we  have  been  looking 
for  some  factor  that  can  be  both  mechanistic  and  also  selective. 
The  next  chapter  will  show  this  factor  in  action. 


79 


CHAPTER   7 

The  Ultrastable  System 

7/1.  We  have  now  assembled  the  necessary  concepts.  They 
are  all  denned  as  relations  between  primary  operations,  so  they 
are  fully  objective  and  conform  to  the  basic  requirements  of 
S.  2/10.  We  can  now  reconsider  the  basic  problem  of  S.  5/14, 
and  can  consider  what  is  implied  by  the  fact  that  the  kitten 
changes  from  having  a  cerebral  mechanism  that  produces  un- 
adapted  behaviour  to  having  one  which  produces  behaviour  that 
is  adapted. 

The  implications  of  adaptation 

7/2.  In  accordance  with  S.  3/11,  the  kitten  and  environment 
are  to  be  considered  as  interacting;  so  the  diagram  of  immediate 
effects  will  be  of  the  form  of  Figure  7/2/1 .  (The  diagram  resembles 
t  that  of  Figure  5/13/1,  except  that  the  fine  net- 

£ny*  ..^  work  of  linkages  that  actually  exists  in  environ- 
ment and  R  has  been  represented  by  shading.) 
The  arrows  to  and  from  R  represent,  of  course,  the 

t  sensory  and  motor  channels.     The  part  R  belongs 

f  to  the  organism,*  but  is  here  defined  purely  func- 

tionally; at  this  stage  any  attempt  to  identify  R 
with  anatomical  or  histological  structures  must  be 
QpJffT  made  with  caution.  R  is  defined  as  the  system 
Figure  7/2/1  tnat  acts  wnen  tne  kitten  reacts  to  the  fire — the 
part  responsible  for  the  overt  behaviour. 
It  was  also  given,  in  S.  5/14,  that  the  kitten  has  a  variety  of 
possible  reactions,  some  wrong,  some  right.  This  variety  of 
reactions  implies,  by  S.  6/3,  that  some  parameters,  call  them  S, 
have  a  variety  of  values,  i.e.  are  not  fixed  throughout.  These 
parameters,  since  their  primary  action  is  to  affect  the  kitten's 
behaviour  (and  only  mediately  that  of  the  environment),  evidently 
have  an  immediate  effect  on   R  but  not  on  the  environment. 

80 


tiny. 


UU 


7/3  THE     ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 

Thus  we  get  Figure   7/2/2.     By  S.   6/3,  Enyt 

the  number  of  distinct  values  possible  to 
S  must  be  at  least  as  great  as  the  num- 
ber of  distinct  ways  of  behaving  (both 
adapted  and  non-adapted)  possible  to  R. 


Figure  7/2/2. 


7/3.  The  essential  variables  must  now  be 
introduced;  what  affects  them  ?  Clearly 
they  must  be  affected  by  something,  for 
we  are  not  interested  in  the  case  of  the 
organism  that  is  immortal  because  nothing 
threatens  it.  Possibilities  are  that  they 
are  affected  by  the  environment,  by  R,  or  by  both. 

The  case  of  most  interest  is  that  in  which  they  are  immediately 
affected  by  the  environment  only.  This  case  makes  the  problem 
for  the  kitten  as  harsh,  as  realistic  as  possible.  This  is  the  case 
when  a  hot  coal  falls  from  the  fire  and  rolls  towards  the  kitten: 
the  environment  threatens  to  have  a  direct  effect  on  the  essential 
variables,  for  if  the  kitten's  brain  does  nothing  the  kitten  will 
get  burnt.  This  is  the  case  when  the  animal  in  the  desert  is  being 
dried  by  the  heat,  so  that  if  the  animal  does  nothing  it  will  die  of 
thirst. 

Immediate  effects  from  R  to  the  essential  variables  would  be 
appropriate  if  the  kitten's  brain  could  act  so  as  to  change  it  from 
an  organism  that  must  not  get  burnt  to  one  that  benefited  by 
being  burnt  !  (Such  a  change  of  goal  may  be  of  importance  in 
the  higher  functionings  of  the  nervous  system,  when  a  sub-goal 
may  be  established  or  changed  provisionally;  but  the  situation 
does  not  occur  at  the  fundamental  level 
that  we  are  considering  here,  and  we 
shall  not  consider  such  possibilities 
further.) 

The  diagram  of  immediate  effects  now 
has  the  form  of  Figure  7/3/1.  The 
essential  variables  have  been  represented 
collectively  by  a  dial  with  a  pointer,  and 
with  two  limit-marks,  to  emphasise  that 
what  matters  about  the  essential  variables 
is  whether  or  not  the  value  is  within 
Figure  7/3/1.  physiological  limits. 

81 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  7/4 

7/4.  Continuing  to  examine  the  case  that  gives  the  kitten  the 
maximal  difficulty,  let  us  consider  the  case  in  which  the  effects  that 
the  various  states  of  the  environment  will  have  on  the  essential 
variables,  though  definite,  is  not  known  to  the  reacting  part  R. 
This  is  the  case  of  a  bird,  driven  to  a  strange  island  and  seeing  a 
strange  berry,  who  does  not  know  whether  it  is  poisonous  or  not. 
It  is  the  case  of  the  cat  in  Thorndike's  cage,  who  does  not  know 
whether  the  lever  must  be  pushed  to  right  or  left  for  the  door  to 
open.  It  is  the  assumption  made  in  S.l/17,  where  the  kitten  was 
confronted  with  a  fire  as  an  example  of  an  organism  in  a  situation 
where  its  previous  experience  gave  no  reliable  indication  of  how 
the  various  states  of  the  environment  were  paired  to  the  states 
1  within  '  and  c  without  '  the  physiological  limits  of  the  essential 
variables. 

To  be  adapted,  the  organism,  guided  by  information  from  the 
environment,  must  control  its  essential  variables,  forcing  them  to 
go  within  the  proper  limits,  by  so  manipulating  the  environment 
(through  its  motor  control  of  it)  that  the  environment  then  acts 
on  them  appropriately.  Thus  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects 
of  this  process  is 


Reacting 
part  R 

Environment 


Essential 
variables 


In  the  case  we  are  considering,  the  reacting  part  R  is  not  specially 
related  or  adjusted  to  what  is  in  the  environment  and  how  it  is 
joined  to  the  essential  variables.  Thus  the  reacting  part  R  can 
be  thought  of  as  an  organism  trying  to  control  the  output  of  a 
Black  Box  (the  environment),  the  contents  of  which  is  unknown 
to  it. 

It  is  axiomatic  (for  any  Black  Box  when  the  range  of  its  inputs 
is  given)  that  the  only  way  in  which  the  nature  of  its  contents 
can  be  elicited  is  by  the  transmission  of  actions  through  it.  This 
means  that  input-values  must  be  given,  output-values  observed, 
and  the  relationships  in  the  paired  values  noticed.  In  the  kitten's 
case,  this  means  that  the  kitten  must  do  various  things  to  the 
environment  and  must  later  act  in  accordance  with  how  these 
actions  affected  the  essential  variables.  In  other  words,  it  must 
proceed  by  trial  and  error. 

Adaptation  by  trial  and  error  is  sometimes  treated  in  psycho- 

82 


7/5  THE     ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 

logical  writings  as  if  it  were  merely  one  way  of  adaptation,  and 
an  inferior  way  at  that.  The  argument  given  above  shows  that 
the  method  of  trial  and  error  holds  a  much  more  fundamental 
place  in  the  methods  of  adaptation.  The  argument  shows,  in 
fact,  that  when  the  organism  has  to  adapt  (to  get  its  essential 
variables  within  physiological  limits)  by  working  through  an 
environment  that  is  of  the  nature  of  a  Black  Box,  then  the  process 
of  trial  and  error  is  necessary,  for  only  such  a  process  can  elicit 
the  required  information. 

The  process  of  trial  and  error  can  thus  be  viewed  from  two  very 
different  points  of  view.  On  the  one  hand  it  can  be  regarded  as 
simply  an  attempt  at  success;  so  that  when  it  fails  we  give  zero 
marks  for  success.  From  this  point  of  view  it  is  merely  a  second- 
rate  way  of  getting  to  success.  There  is,  however,  the  other  point 
of  view  that  gives  it  an  altogether  higher  status,  for  the  process 
may  be  playing  the  invaluable  part  of  gathering  information, 
information  that  is  absolutely  necessary  if  adaptation  is  to  be 
successfully  achieved.  It  is  for  this  reason  that  the  process  must 
enter  into  the  kitten's  adaptation. 

7/5.     As  the  kitten  proceeds  by  trial  and  error,  its  final  behaviour 

will  depend  on  the  outcome  of  the  trials,  on  how  the  essential 

variables  have  been  affected.     This  is  equivalent  to  saying  that 

the  essential  variables  are  to  have  an  effect  on  which  behaviour 

the    kitten    will    produce;    and    this    is  * 

Env  • 
equivalent,  to  saying  that  in  the  diagram 

of  immediate   effects  there   must    be    a 

channel  from  the   essential  variables   to 

the   parameters   S;   so   it   will  resemble 

Figure  7/5/1.     The   organism  that  can 

adapt  thus  has   a  motor  output  to  the 

environment    and    two    feedback    loops. 

The  first  loop  was  shown  in  Figure  7/2/1 ; 

it  consists  of  the  ordinary  sensory  input 

from   eye,   ear,   joints,   etc.,   giving   the  Fjgure  7/5/1* 

organism  non-affective  information  about 

the  world  around  it.      The  second  feedback  goes  through  the 

essential  variables  (including  such  correlated  variables  as  the  pain 

receptors,    S.  3/15);    it   carries    information    about  whether  the 

essential  variables  are  or  are  not  driven  outside  the  normal  limits, 

83 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  7/6 

and  it  acts  on  the  parameters  S.  The  first  feedback  plays  its 
part  within  each  reaction;  the  second  determines  which  reaction 
shall  occur. 

7/6.  Since  the  argument  here  is  crucial,  let  us  trace  it  in  detail, 
using  the  basic  operational  concepts  of  S.  2/7-10. 

We  start  with  the  common  observation  that  the  burned  kitten 
dreads  the  fire.  Translated  into  full  operational  form,  this 
observation  becomes: 

(1)  with  the  essential  variables  within  their  limits,  the  overt 

behaviour  (of  R)  is  such  as  is  consequent  on  the  parameters 
having  values  S^ 

(2)  when  the  essential  variables  are  sent  outside  the  limits  (i.e 

if  the  kitten  is  burned),  the  overt  behaviour  is  such  as  is 
consequent  on  their  having  values  52. 

That  the  overt  behaviour  is  changed  shows  that  S2  is  not  the  same 
as  Sv  Thus  the  two  different  values  at  the  essential  variables 
have  led  to  different  values  at  S;  there  is  therefore  an  immediate 
effect  from  the  essential  variables  to  the  parameters  S. 

111.  The  same  data  will  now  provide  us  with  the  necessary 
information  about  what  happens  within  the  second  loop,  i.e. 
how  the  essential  variables  affect  the  parameters. 

The  basic  rule  for  adaptation  by  trial  and  error  is: — If  the 
trial  is  unsuccessful,  change  the  way  of  behaving ;  when  and  only 
when  it  is  successful,  retain  the  way  of  behaving.  Now  consider 
the  system  S  and  how  it  must  behave.  Within  this  system  are 
the  variables  that  are  identical  with  the  parameters  to  R  (a  mere 
change  of  name),  and  to  this  system  the  essential  variables  are 
parameters,  i.e.  come  as  input.  The  basic  rule  is  equivalent  to 
the  following  formulation: 

(1)  When  the  essential  variables  are  not  all  within  their  normal 

limits  (i.e.  when  the  trial  has  failed),  no  state  of  S  is  to 
be  equilibrial  (for  the  rule  here  is  that  S  must  go  to  some 
other  state). 

(2)  When  the  essential  variables  are  all  within  normal  limits 

then  every  state  of  *S  is  to  be  equilibrial  (i.e.  S  is  to  be  in 
neutral  equilibrium). 

84 


7/10  THE    ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 

7/8.  What  has  been  deduced  so  far  in  this  Chapter  is  necessary. 
That  is  to  say,  any  system  that  has  essential  variables  with  given 
limits,  and  that  adapts  by  the  process  of  testing  various  behaviours 
by  how  each  affects  ultimately  the  essential  variables,  must  have 
a  second  feedback  formally  identical  (isomorphic)  with  that 
described  here.  This  deduction  holds  equally  for  brains  living 
and  mechanical. 

To  be  quite  clear  in  this  matter,  let  us  consider  the  alternative. 
Suppose  some  new  species,  or  some  new  mechanical  brain,  were 
found  to  change  from  the  non-adapted  to  the  adapted  condition 
(S.  5/7),  doing  this  consistently  even  when  confronted  with  quite 
new  situations ;  and  suppose  that,  in  spite  of  what  was  said  above, 
investigation  showed  conclusively  that  there  was  no  second  feed- 
back of  the  type  described — what  would  we  say  ? 

There  seem  to  be  only  two  possibilities.  We  must  either  invoke 
a  hitherto  unknown  channel  (in  spite  of  the  investigations),  as 
one  was  invoked  after  the  demonstration  by  Hertz  (S.  4/13); 
or  we  must  be  willing  to  accept  as  natural  that  the  system  S 
should  go  to  correct  values  without  being  given  an  appropriate 
input.  This  second  possibility  would  be  accepted  by  no  one, 
for  the  situation  would  be  like  asking  an  examiner  to  accept  as 
natural  a  candidate  who  gives  the  correct  answers  without  being 
given  the  questions  !  If  this  possibility  is  rejected,  we  are  left 
only  with  the  possibility  that  the  second  channel,  in  some  form 
or  other,  must  be  there. 


The  implications  of  double  feedback 

7/9.  We  may  now  usefully  consider  the  relation  between  adaptive 
behaviour  and  mechanism  from  the  opposite  point  of  view.  So 
far  in  this  chapter  we  have  taken  the  facts  of  adaptive  behaviour 
as  given  and  have  deduced  something  of  the  underlying  mech- 
anism. We  will  now  take  the  mechanism  and  ask:  Given  such  a 
mechanism,  in  whatever  material"  form,  will  it  necessarily  show 
adaptive  behaviour  ?  The  answer  to  this  question  will  occupy 
the  remainder  of  this  chapter  and  the  next. 

7/10.  Let  us  get  the  basic  assumptions  clear  for  a  completely 
new  start,  assuming  from  here  to  the  end  of  the  chapter  only 
what  is  stated  explicitly. 

85 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  7/11 

We  assume  that  we  have  before  us  some  system  that  has  the 
diagram  of  immediate  effects  shown  in  Figure  7/5/1.  Some 
variable,  or  several,  called  '  essential  ',  is  given  to  act  on  a  system 
S  so  that  if  the  variable  (or  all  of  them)  is  within  given  limits, 
S  is  unchanging;  but  if  it  is  outside  the  limits,  S  changes  always. 
(An.  adequate  variety  of  values  is  assumed  possible  to  S  so  that 
it  does  not  develop,  for  instance,  simple  cyclic  repetitions.)  A 
system  called  *  environment  '  interacts  with  another  system  R. 
Environment  has  some  effect  on  the  variable  called  essential,  and 
S  has  some  effect  on  R.  Given  this,  and  nothing  more,  does  it 
follow  that  the  system  R  will  change  from  acting  non-adaptively 
towards  the  environment,  to  acting  adaptively  towards  it?  (At 
the  moment  I  wish  to  add  no  further  assumption;  in  particular 
I  do  not  wish  to  restrict  the  generality  by  making  any  assumption 
that  R  is  composed  of  parts  resembling  neurons.) 

7/11.  Because  the  whole  consists  of  two  parts  coupled — on  the 
one  side  the  environment  and  reacting  part  R,  and  on  the  other 
the  essential  variables  and  S — we  can  use  the  veto-theorem  of 
S.  6/9.  This  says  that  the  whole  can  have  as  states  of  equilibrium 
only  such  states  as  allow  a  state  of  equilibrium  in  both  the  essen- 
tial variables  and  S.  Now  S  is  at  equilibrium  only  when  the 
essential  variables  are  within  the  given  limits.  It  follows  that  all 
the  possible  equilibria  of  the  whole  have  the  essential  variables 
within  the  given  limits.  So  if  the  whole  is  started  at  some  state 
and  goes  along  the  corresponding  line  of  behaviour,  then  if  it 
goes  to  an  equilibrium,  the  equilibrium  will  always  be  found  to 
be  an  adapted  one. 

Thus  we  arrive  at  the  solution  of  the  problem  posed  at  the 
end  of  Chapter  1 ;  the  mechanism  has  been  shown  to  be  necessary 
by  S.  7/8,  and  sufficient  by  the  present  section. 

7/12.  This  solution,  however,  is  severely  abstract  and  leaves 
unanswered  a  great  number  of  supplementary  questions  that  are 
apt  to  be  asked  on  the  topic.  Further,  it  leaves  one  with  no 
vivid  imaginative  or  intuitive  conception  of  what  is  going  on  when 
a  system  (one  as  complex  as  a  human  being,  say)  goes  about  its 
business.  The  remainder  of  the  book  will  therefore  be  concerned 
with  expanding  the  solution's  many  implications  and  specialisa- 
tions. 

86 


7/13  THE     ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 

Here,  however,  a  difficulty  arises.  The  attempt  to  follow, 
conceptually  and  imaginatively,  the  actual  events  in  the  whole 
system,  as  environment  poses  problems  to  the  essential  variables 
(by  threatening  to  drive  them  outside  their  normal  limits),  as 
the  values  in  S  determine  a  particular  way  of  behaving  in  R,  as 
R  behaves  in  that  way,  interacting  with  the  environment  at  every 
moment,  as  the  outcome  falls  on  the  essential  variables,  as  S  is 
(or  perhaps  is  not)  changed,  as  R  behaves  in  a  new  way — all  this 
is  apt  to  be  exceedingly  complex  and  difficult  to  grasp  conceptually 
if  the  variables  in  environment,  R,  and  S  all  change  continuously, 
i.e.  by  infinitesimal  steps. 

Experience  has  shown  that  the  whole  system,  and  its  psycho- 
logical and  physiological  implications,  are  much  easier  to  grasp 
and  understand  if  we  study  the  particular  case  in  which  the 
variables  in  environment  and  R  all  vary  continuously,  while 
those  in  S  vary  discretely  (i.e.  by  finite  jumps,  occurring  at  finite 
intervals).  Evidence  will  be  given,  in  S.  9/4,  suggesting  that 
such  discrete  variables  are  in  fact  likely  sometimes  to  be  of  real 
importance  in  the  subject;  for  the  time,  however,  let  us  regard 
them  as  merely  selected  by  us  for  our  easier  apprehension. 


Step-functions 

7/13.  Sometimes  the  behaviour  of  a  variable  (or  parameter)  can 
be  described  without  reference  to  the  cause  of  the  behaviour:  if 
we  say  a  variable  or  system  is  a  4  simple  harmonic  oscillator  ' 
the  meaning  of  the  phrase  is  well  understood.  In  this  book  we 
shall  be  more  interested  in  the  extent  to  which  a  variable  displays 
constancy.  Four  types  may  be  distinguished,  and  are  illustrated 
in  Figure  7/13/1.  (A)  The  full-function  has  no  finite  interval  of 
constancy ;  many  common  physical  variables  are  of  this  type :  the 
height  of  the  barometer,  for  instance.  (B)  The  part-function  has 
finite  intervals  of  change  and  finite  intervals  of  constancy;  it 
will  be  considered  more  fully  in  S.  12/18.  (C)  The  step-function 
has  finite  intervals  of  constancy  separated  by  instantaneous  jumps. 
And,  to  complete  the  set,  we  need  (D)  the  null- function,  which 
shows  no  change  over  the  whole  period  of  observation.  The  four 
types  obviously  include  all  the  possibilities,  except  for  mixed 
forms.  The  variables  of  Figure  2/12/1  will  be  found  to  be  part-, 
full-,  step-,  and  step-functions  respectively. 

87 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


7/14 


^V 


TIME— > 

Figure  7/13/1  :    Types  of  behaviour  of  a  variable  :    A,  the  full-function  ; 
B,  the  part-function  ;    C,  the  step-function  ;    D,  the  null-function. 

In  all  cases  the  type-property  is  assumed  to  hold  only  over 
the  period  of  observation:  what  might  happen  at  other  times 
is  irrelevant. 

Sometimes  physical  entities  cannot  readily  be  allotted  their 
type.  Thus,  a  steady  musical  note  may  be  considered  either  as 
unvarying  in  intensity,  and  therefore  a  null-function,  or  as 
represented  by  particles  of  air  which  move  continuously,  and 
therefore  a  full -function.  In  all  such  cases  the  confusion  is  at 
once  removed  if  one  ceases  to  think  of  the  real  physical  object 
with  its  manifold  properties,  and  selects  that  variable  in  which 
one  happens  to  be  interested. 


7/14.  Step-functions  occur  abundantly  in  nature,  though  the 
very  simplicity  of  their  properties  tends  to  keep  them  incon- 
spicuous. '  Things  in  motion  sooner  catch  the  eye  than  what 
not  stirs  '.  The  following  examples  approximate  to  the  step- 
function,  and  show  its  ubiquity: 

(1)  The  electric  switch  has  an  electrical  resistance  which  remains 

constant  except  when  it  changes  by  a  sudden  jump. 

(2)  The  electrical  resistance  of  a  fuse  similarly  stays  at  a  low 

value  for  a  time  and  then  suddenly  changes  to  a  very 
high  value. 

88 


7/15 


THE     ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 


(3)  If  a  piece  of  rubber  is  stretched,  the  pull  it  exerts  is  approxi- 

mately proportional  to  its  length.  The  constant  of  pro- 
portionality has  a  definite  constant  value  unless  the  elastic 
is  stretched  so  far  that  it  breaks.  When  this  happens 
the  constant  of  proportionality  suddenly  becomes  zero, 
i.e.  it  changes  as  a  step-function. 

(4)  If  strong  acid  is  added  in  a  steady  stream  to  an  unbuffered 

alkaline  solution,  the  pH  changes  in  approximately  step- 
function  form. 

(5)  If  alcohol   is   added   slowly   with   mixing  to   an   aqueous 

solution  of  protein,  the  amount  of  protein  precipitated 
changes  in  approximately  step-function  form. 

(6)  As  the  pK  is  changed,  the  amount  of  adsorbed  substance 

often  changes  in  approximately  step-function  form. 

(7)  By  quantum  principles,  many  atomic  and  molecular  variables 

change  in  step-function  form. 

(8)  Any  variable  which  acts  only  in  '  all  or  none  '  degree  shows 

this  form  of  behaviour  if  each  degree  is  sustained  over  a 
•  finite  interval. 


7/15.  Whether  a  real  variable  may  or  may  not  be  represented 
by  a  step-function  will  usually  depend  on  the  method  and  perhaps 
instrumentation  of  observation.  Observers  and  instruments  do 
not,  in  practice,  record  values  over  both  very  short  and  very  long 
intervals  simultaneously.  Thus  if  the  honey-gathering  flights  of 
a  bee  are  being  studied  throughout  a  day,  the  observer  does  not 


B 


Time  — >• 

Figure  7/15/1  :   The  same  change  viewed  :    (^4)  over  one  interval 
of  time,  (B)  over  an  interval  twenty  times  as  long. 

89 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  7/16 

usually  follow  the  bee's  movements  into  the  details  of  the  wing 
going  up  and  down,  neither  does  he  follow  the  changes  that 
correspond  to  the  bee's  being  a  little  older  after  the  day's  work. 
The  changes  of  wing-position  are  ignored  as  being  too  fast,  only 
an  average  being  noticed,  and  the  changes  of  age  are  ignored  as 
being  too  slow,  the  values  being  treated  as  approximately  con- 
stant. Thus,  whether  a  variable  of  a  real  object  behaves  as  a 
step-function  cannot  in  general  be  decided  until  the  details  of  the 
method  of  observation  is  specified. 

The  distinction  is  illustrated  in  Figure  7/15/1  in  which 
x  =  tanh  t  has  been  graphed.  If  observed  from  t  =  —  2  to 
t  =  -J-  2,  the  graph  has  form  A,  and  is  obviously  not  of  step- 
function  form.  But  if  graphed  from  t  =  —  100  to  t  =  +100, 
the  result  is  B,  and  the  curve  is  approximating  to  the  step-function 
form. 

7/16.  As  a  second  example,  consider  the  Post  Office  type  relay. 
If  observed  from  second  to  second  the  conductivity  across  its 
contacts  varies  almost  exactly  in  step-function  form.  If,  how- 
ever, the  conductivity  is  observed  over  microseconds,  the  values 
change  in  a  much  more  continuous  way,  for  the  contacts  can  now 
be  seen  to  accelerate,  decelerate,  and  bounce  with  a  graceful  and 
continuous  trajectory.  And  if  the  relay  is  observed  over  many 
years  and  the  conductivity  plotted,  the  curve  will  not  be  flat 
but  will  fall  gradually  as  oxidation  and  wear  affect  the  contacts. 
We  have  here  yet  another  example  of  the  thesis  that  specifying 
a  real  object  does  not  uniquely  specify  the  system  or  the  behaviour 
(Ss.  2/4  and  6/2).  A  question  such  as  '  Is  the  behaviour  of  the 
Post  Office  relay  really  of  step-function  form  ?  '  is  improperly  put, 
for  it  asks  about  a  real  object  what  is  determined  only  by  the 
system,  which  must  be  specified.  (The  matter  is  taken  up  again 
in  S.  9/10.) 

7/17.  Behaviour  of  step-function  form  is  likely  to  be  seen  when- 
ever we  observe  a  '  machine  '  whose  component  parts  are  fast- 
acting.  Thus,  if  we  casually  alter  the  settings  of  an  unknown 
electronic  machine  we  are  not  unlikely  to  observe,  from  time  to 
time,  sudden  changes  of  step-function  form,  the  suddenness  being 
due  to  the  speed  with  which  the  machine  changes. 

A  reason  can  be  given  most  simply  by  reference  to  Figure  4/3/1 . 

90 


7/18  THE     ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 

Suppose  that  the  curvature  of  the  surface  is  controlled  by  a  para- 
meter which  makes  A  rise  and  B  fall.  If  the  ball  is  resting  at  A, 
the  parameter's  first  change  will  make  no  difference  to  the  ball's 
lateral  position,  for  it  will  continue  to  rest  at  A  (though  with 
lessened  reaction  if  displaced).  As  the  parameter  is  changed 
further,  the  ball  will  continue  to  remain  at  A  until  A  and  B  are 
level.  Still  the  ball  will  make  no  movement.  But  if  the  para- 
meter goes  on  changing  and  A  rises  above  B,  and  if  gravitation  is 
intense  and  the  ball  fast-moving,  then  the  ball  will  suddenly  move 
to  B.  And  here  it  will  remain,  however  high  A  becomes  and 
however  low  B.  So,  if  the  parameter  changes  steadily,  the 
lateral  position  of  the  ball  will  tend  to  change  in  step-function 
form,  approximating  more  closely  as  the  passage  of  the  ball  for 
a  given  degree  of  slope  becomes  swifter. 

The  possibility  need  not  be  examined  further,  for  no  exact 
deductions  will  be  drawn  from  it.  The  section  is  intended  only 
to  show  that  step-functions  occur  not  uncommonly  when  the 
system  under  observation  contains  fast-acting  components.  The 
subject  will  be  referred  to  again  in  S.  9/8. 

7/18.  In  any  state-determined  system,  the  behaviour  of  a  variable 
at  any  instant  depends  on  the  values  which  the  variable  and  the 
others  have  at  that  instant  (S.  2/15).  If  one  of  the  variables 
behaves  as  a  step-function  the  rule  still  applies:  whether  the 
variable  remains  constant  or  undergoes  a  change  is  determined 
both  by  the  value  of  the  variable  and  by  the  values  of  the  other 
variables.  So,  given  a  state-determined  system  with  a  step- 
mechanism*  at  a  particular  value,  all  the  states  with  the  step- 
mechanism  at  that  value  can  be  divided  into  two  classes :  those 
whose  occurrence  does  and  those  whose  occurrence  does  not  lead 
to  a  change  in  the  step-mechanism's  value.  The  former  are  its 
critical  states:  should  one  of  them  occur,  the  step-function  will 
change  value.  The  critical  state  of  an  electric  fuse  is  the  number 
of  amperes  which  will  cause  it  to  blow.  The  critical  state  of  the 
1  constant  of  proportionality  '  of  an  elastic  strand  is  the  length 
at  which  it  breaks. 

An  example  from  physiology  is  provided  by  the  urinary  bladder 

*  I  am  indebted  to  Dr.  J.  O.  Wisdom  for  the  suggestion  that  a  mechanism 
showing  a  step-function  as  its  main  characteristic  could  conveniently  be  called 
a  '  step-mechanism  '. 

91 


DESIGN     FOR    A    BRAIN 


7/19 


when  it  has  developed  an  automatic  intermittently-emptying 
action  after  spinal  section.  The  bladder  fills  steadily  with  urine, 
while  at  first  the  spinal  centres  for  micturition  remain  inactive. 
When  the  volume  of  urine  exceeds  a  certain  value  the  centres 
become  active  and  urine  is  passed.     When  the  volume  falls  below 


— TIME— *- 

Figure  7/18/1  :  Diagram  of  the  changes  in  x,  volume  of  urine  in  the  bladder, 
and  y,  activity  in  the  centre  for  micturition,  when  automatic  action  has 
been  established  after  spinal  section. 

a  certain  value,  the  centre  becomes  inactive  and  the  bladder  refills. 
A  graph  of  the  two  variables  would  resemble  Figure  7/18/1.  The 
two-variable  system  is  state-determined,  for  it  has  the  field  of 
Figure  7/18/2.     The  variable  y  is  approximately  a  step-function. 


o    x,  x2 

Figure  7/18/2  :    Field  of  the  changes  shown  in  Figure  7/18/1. 

When  it  is  at  0,  its  critical  state  is  x  =  X2,  y  =  0,  for  the  occur- 
rence of  this  state  determines  a  jump  from  0  to  Y.  When  it  is  at 
Y,  its  critical  state  is  x  =  Xlt  y  =  Y,  for  the  occurrence  of  this 
state  determines  a  jump  from  Y  to  0. 

7/19.  A  common,  though  despised,  property  of  every  machine  is 
that  it  may  '  break  ',  This  event  is  in  no  sense  unnatural,  since 
it  must  follow  the  basic  laws  of  physics  and  chemistry  and  is 
therefore  predictable  from  its  immediately  preceding  state.  In 
general,  when  a  machine  '  breaks  '  the  representative  point  has  met 
some  critical  state,  and  the  corresponding  step-function  has 
changed  value. 

As  is  well  known,  almost  any  machine  or  physical  system  will 

92 


7/20 


THE  ULTRA STABLE  SYSTEM 


break  if  its  variables  are  driven  far  enough  away  from  their  usual 
values.  Thus,  machines  with  moving  parts,  if  driven  ever  faster, 
will  break  mechanically;  electrical  apparatus,  if  subjected  to 
ever  higher  voltages  or  currents,  will  break  in  insulation ;  machines 
made  too  hot  will  melt — if  made  too  cold  they  may  encounter 
other  sudden  changes,  such  as  the  condensation  which  stops  a 
steam-engine  from  working  below  100°  C;  in  chemical  dynamics, 
increasing  concentrations  may  meet  saturation,  or  may  cause 
precipitation  of  proteins. 

Although  there  is  no  rigorous  law,  there  is  nevertheless  a  wide- 
spread tendency  for  systems  to  show  changes  of  step-function 
form  if  their  variables  are  driven  far  from  some  usual  value. 
Later  (S.  9/7)  it  will  be  suggested  that  the  nervous  system  is  not 
exceptional  in  this  respect. 


Systems  containing  step-mechanisms 

7/20.  When  a  state-determined  system  includes  a  step-function 
among  its  variables,  the  whole  behaviour  can  undergo  a  simplifica- 
tion not  possible  when  the  variables  are  all  full-functions. 

Suppose  that  we  have  a  system  with  three  variables,  A,  B,  S; 
that  it  has  been  tested  and  found  state-determined;  that  A  and 
B  are  full-functions ;  and  that  S  is  a  step-mechanism.  (Variables 
A  and  B,  as  in  S.  21/7,  will  be  referred  to  as  main  variables.) 
The  phase-space  of  this  system  will  resemble  that  of  Figure  7/20/1 
(a  possible  field  has  been  sketched  in).  The  phase-space  no  longer 
fills  all  three  dimensions,  but  as  S  can  take  only  discrete  values, 
here  assumed  for  simplicity  to  be  a  pair,  the  phase-space  is 
restricted  to  two  planes  normal  to  S,  each  plane  corresponding  to  a 


Figure  7/20/1  :  Field  of  a  state-determined  system  of  three  variables,  of 
which  S  is  a  step-function.  The  states  from  C  to  C  are  the  critical  states 
of  the  step-function  for  lines  in  the  lower  plane. 

93 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


7/20 


particular  value  of  S.  A  and  B  being  full-functions,  the  represen- 
tative point  will  move  on  curves  in  each  plane,  describing  a  line  of 
behaviour  such  as  that  drawn  more  heavily  in  the  Figure.  When 
the  line  of  behaviour  meets  the  row  of  critical  states  at  C — C,  S 
jumps  to  its  other  value,  and  the  representative  point  continues 
along  the  heavily  marked  line  in  the  upper  plane.  In  such  a  field 
the  movement  of  the  representative  point  is  everywhere  state- 
determined,  for  the  number  of  lines  from  any  point  never  exceeds 
one. 

If,  still  dealing  with  the  same  real  '  machine  ',  we  ignore  S, 
and  repeatedly  form  the  field  of  the  system  composed  of  A  and  B 
(S  being  free  to  take  sometimes  one  value  and  sometimes  the  other), 
we  shall  find  that  we  get  sometimes  a  field  like  I  in  Figure  7/20/2, 

1  A 


B  B  C 

Figure  7/20/2  :    The  two  fields  of  the  system  composed  of  A  and  B. 
P  is  in  the  same  position  in  each  field. 

and  sometimes  a  field  like  II,  the  one  or  the  other  appearing 
according  to  the  value  that  S  happens  to  have  at  the  time. 

The  behaviour  of  the  system  AB,  in  its  apparent  possession  of 
two  fields,  should  be  compared  with  that  of  the  system  described 
in  S.  6/3,  where  the  use  of  two  parameter- values  also  caused  the 
appearance  of  two  fields.  But  in  the  earlier  case  the  change  of 
the  field  was  caused  by  the  arbitrary  action  of  the  experimenter, 
who  forced  the  parameter  to  change  value,  while  in  this  case  the 
change  of  the  field  of  AB  is  caused  by  the  inner  mechanisms  of  the 
'  machine  '  itself. 

The  property  may  now  be  stated  in  general  terms.  Suppose, 
in  a  state-determined  system,  that  some  of  the  variables  are  due  to 
step-mechanisms,  and  that  these  are  ignored  while  the  remainder 
(the  main  variables)  are  observed  on  many  occasions  by  having 
their   field   constructed.     Then   so   long   as   no   step-mechanism 

94 


7/23  THE     ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 

changes  value  during  the  construction,  the  main  variables  will  be 
found  to  form  a  state-determined  system,  and  to  have  a  definite 
field.     But  on  different  occasions  different  fields  may  be  found. 

7/21.  These  considerations  throw  light  on  an  old  problem  in  the 
theory  of  mechanisms. 

Can  a  '  machine  '  be  at  once  determinate  and  capable  of  spon- 
taneous change  ?  The  question  would  be  contradictory  if  posed 
by  one  person,  but  it  exists  in  fact  because,  when  talking  of  living 
organisms,  one  school  maintains  that  they  are  strictly  determinate 
while  another  school  maintains  that  they  are  capable  of  spon- 
taneous change.     Can  the  schools  be  reconciled  ? 

The  presence  of  step-mechanisms  in  a  state-determined  system 
enables  both  schools  to  be  right,  provided  that  those  who  maintain 
the  determination  are  speaking  of  the  system  which  comprises  all 
the  variables,  while  those  who  maintain  the  possibility  of  spon- 
taneous change  are  speaking  of  the  main  variables  only.  For  the 
whole  system,  which  includes  the  step-mechanisms,  has  one  field 
only,  and  is  completely  state-determined  (like  Figure  7/20/1). 
But  the  system  of  main  variables  may  show  as  many  different 
forms  of  behaviour  (like  Figure  7/20/2,  I  and  II)  as  the  step- 
mechanisms  possess  combinations  of  values.  And  if  the  step- 
mechanisms  are  not  accessible  to  observation,  the  change  of  the 
main  variables  from  one  form  of  behaviour  to  another  will  seem 
to  be  spontaneous,  for  no  change  or  state  in  the  main  variables 
can  be  assigned  as  its  cause. 

7/22.  If  the  system  had  contained  two  step-mechanisms,  each 
of  two  values,  there  would  have  been  four  fields  of  the  main 
variables.  In  general,  n  step-mechanisms,  each  of  two  values, 
will  give  2n  fields.  A  moderate  number  of  step-mechanisms  may 
thus  give  a  very  much  larger  number  of  fields. 

7/23.  After  this  digression  on  step-functions  we  can  return  to  the 
system  of  S.  7/9,  with  its  corrective  feedback,  and  consider  its 
behaviour. 

To  bring  the  concepts  into  correspondence,  we  assume  that  the 
main  variables  (the  continuous)  are  in  the  environment,  in  R, 
and  in  the  essential  variables.  The  step-functions  will  be  in  S. 
It  follows  that  their  critical  states  will  be  distributed  over  those 
regions  of  the  main  variables'  phase-space  at  which  the  essential 

95 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  7/23 

variables  are  outside  their  normal  limits.  Thus  if  the  main 
variables  were  as  few  as  two  (for  graphical  purposes),  the  dis- 
tribution might  be  as  the* dots  in  I  of  Figure  7/23/1.  The  dis- 
tribution means  that  the  organism  is  in  tolerable  physiological 
conditions  if  the  representative  point  stays  within  the  undotted 
region. 


Ill 


Figure  7/23/1  :    Changes  of  field  in  an  ultrastable  system. 

states  are  dotted. 


The  critical 


Suppose  now  that  the  first  set  of  values  on  the  step-functions  S 
gives  such  a  field  as  is  shown  in  I,  and  that  the  representative 
point  is  at  X.  The  line  of  behaviour  from  X  is  not  stable  in  the 
region,  and  the  representative  point  follows  the  line  to  the 
boundary.  Here  (Y)  it  meets  a  critical  state  and  a  step-function 
changes  value ;  a  new  field,  perhaps  like  II,  arises.  The  representa- 
tive point  is  now  at  Y,  and  the  line  from  this  point  is  still  unstable 
in  regard  to  the  region.  The  point  follows  the  line  of  behaviour, 
meets  a  critical  state  at  Z,  and  causes  a  change  of  a  step-function : 
a  new  field  (III)  arises.  The  point  is  at  Z,  and  the  field  includes  a 
state  of  stable  equilibrium,  but  from  Z  the  line  leads  further  out 
of  the  region.  So  another  critical  state  is  met,  another  step- 
function  changes  value,  and  a  new  field  (IV)  arises.     In  this  field, 

96 


7/25  THE     ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 

the  line  of  behaviour  from  Z  is  stable  with  regard  to  the  region, 
so  the  representative  point  moves  to  the  state  of  equilibrium  and 
stops  there.  No  further  critical  states  are  met,  no  further  step- 
functions  change  value,  and  therefore  no  further  changes  of  field 
take  place.  From  now  on,  if  the  field  of  the  main  variables  is 
examined,  it  will  be  found  to  be  stable.  The  organism,  if  dis- 
placed moderately  from  the  state  of  equilibrium,  will  return  to  it, 
thus  demonstrating  the  various  evidences  of  adaptation  noticed 
in  Chapter  5. 

7/24.  This  field,  and  this  state  of  equilibrium,  will,  under  con- 
stant external  conditions,  persist  indefinitely.  If  the  system  is 
now  subjected  to  occasional  small  impulsive  disturbances  (that 
simply  displace  the  representative  point  as  in  S.  6/5)  the  whole 
will  as  often  display  its  stability ;  in  the  same  action,  the  organismal 
part  will  display  that  it  now  possesses  an  '  adapted  '  mechanism 
for  dealing  with  the  environmental  part. 

During  the  description  of  the  previous  section,  much  notice  was 
taken  of  the  trials  and  failures,  and  field  IV  seemed  to  be  only 
the  end  of  a  succession  of  failures.  We  thus  tended  to  lose  a 
sense  of  proportion ;  for  what  is  really  important  to  the  living  and 
learning  organism  is  the  great  number  of  times  on  which  it  can 
display  that  it  has  already  achieved  adaptation;  in  fact,  unless 
the  circumstances  allow  this  number  to  be  fairly  large  and  the 
number  of  trial-failures  to  be  fairly  small,  there  is  no  gain  to  the 
organism  in  having  a  brain  that  can  learn. 

7/25.  It  should  be  noticed  that  the  second  feedback  makes,  for 
its  success,  no  demands  either  on  the  construction  of  the  reacting 
part  R  or  on  the  successive  values  that  are  taken  by  S.  Another 
way  of  saying  this  is  to  say  that  the  mechanism  is  in  no  way  put 
out  of  order  if  R  is  initially  constructed  at  random  or  if  the  successive 
values  at  S  occur  at  random.  (The  meaning  of  '  constructed  at 
random  '  is  given  in  S.  13/1.) 

Such  a  construction  at  random  probably  occurs  to  some  extent 
in  the  nervous  system,  where  the  ultimate  units  (dendrons,  pieds 
terminaux,  protein  molecules  perhaps)  occur  in  numbers  far  too 
great  for  their  determination  by  the  gene-pattern  in  detail  (S.  1/9). 
In  the  formation  of  the  embryo  brain,  therefore,  some  of  the  final 
details  may  be  determined  by  the  accidents  of  local  minutiae — 

97 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  7/26 

of  oxygen  or  salt  concentration  perhaps,  or  local  strains.  If  the 
reacting  part  R  is  initially  formed  by  such  a  process,  then  the 
action  of  the  second  feedback  is  unaffected:  it  will  bring  the 
organism  to  adaptation. 

In  the  same  way,  nothing  was  supposed  about  the  successive 
values  at  S  (except  that  they  must  not  be  appreciably  correlated 
with  the  events  within  the  field).  Any  uncorrelated  source  will 
therefore  serve  for  their  supply ;  so  they  too  can  be,  in  the  denned 
sense,  random. 

The  ultrastable  system 

7/26.  In  the  first  edition  the  system  described  in  this  chapter 
was  called  '  ultrastable  ',  and  S.  8/6  will  show  why  the  adjective 
is  defensible.  At  that  time  the  system  was  thought  to  be  unique, 
but  further  experience  (outlined  in  /.  to  C,  S.  12/8-20)  has  shown 
that  this  form  is  only  one  of  a  large  class  of  related  forms,  in 
which  it  is  conspicuous  only  because  it  shows  certain  features,  of 
outstanding  biological  interest,  with  unusual  clarity.  The  word 
may  usefully  be  retained,  in  accordance  with  the  strategy  of 
S.  2/17,  because  it  represents  a  well-defined  type,  useful  as  a  fixed 
type  around  which  discussion  may  move  without  ambiguity,  and 
to  which  a  multitude  of  approximately  similar  forms,  occurring 
mostly  in  the  biological  world,  may  be  related. 

For  convenience,  its  definition  will  be  stated  formally.  Two 
systems  of  continuous  variables  (that  we  called  '  environment  ' 
and  '  reacting  part  ')  interact,  so  that  a  primary  feedback  (through 
complex  sensory  and  motor  channels)  exists  between  them. 
Another  feedback,  working  intermittently  and  at  a  much  slower 
order  of  speed,  goes  from  the  environment  to  certain  continuous 
variables  which  in  their  turn  affect  some  step-mechanisms,  the 
effect  being  that  the  step-mechanisms  change  value  when  and 
only  when  these  variables  pass  outside  given  limits.  The  step- 
mechanisms  affect  the  reacting  part;  by  acting  as  parameters  to 
it  they  determine  how  it  shall  react  to  the  environment. 

(From  this  basic  type  a  multitude  of  variations  can  be  made. 
Their  study  is  made  much  easier  by  a  thorough  grasp  of  the 
properties  of  the  basic  form  just  defined.) 

7/27.  The  basic  form  has  many  more  properties  of  interest  than 
have  yet  been  indicated.     Their  description  in  words,  however,  is 

98 


7/27 


THE     ULTRASTABLE     SYSTEM 


apt  to  be  tedious  and  unconvincing.  A  better  demonstration  can 
be  given  by  a  machine,  built  so  that  we  know  its  nature  exactly 
and  on  which  we  can  observe  just  what  will  happen  in  various 
conditions.  (We  can  describe  it  either  as  '  a  machine  to  do  our 
thinking  for  us'  or,  more  respectably,  as  '  an  analogue  computer  \) 
One  was  built  and  called  the  '  Homeostat  '.  Its  construction, 
and  how  it  behaved,  will  be  described  in  the  next  chapter. 


«A*5 


99 


CHAPTER   8 

The  Homeostat 

8/1.  The  ultrastable  system  is  much  richer  in  interesting  pro- 
perties than  might  at  first  be  suspected.  Some  of  these  pro- 
perties are  of  special  interest  to  the  physiologist  and  the  psycho- 
logist, but  they  have  to  be  suitably  displayed  before  their  physio- 
logical and  psychological  applications  can  be  perceived.  For 
their  display,  a  machine  was  built  according  to  the  definition  of 
the  ultrastable  system.  What  it  is,  and  how  it  behaves,  are  the 
subjects  of  this  chapter.* 

8/2.  The  Homeostat  (Figure  8/2/1)  consists  of  four  units,  each  of 
which  carries  on  top  a  pivoted  magnet  (Figure  8/2/2,  M  in 
Figure  8/2/3).  The  angular  deviations  of  the  four  magnets  from 
the  central  positions  provide  the  four  main  variables. 

Its  construction  will  be  described  in  stages.  Each  unit  emits 
a  D.C.  output  proportional  to  the  deviation  of  its  magnet  from 
the  central  position.  The  output  is  controlled  in  the  following 
way.  In  front  of  each  magnet  is  a  trough  of  water;  electrodes 
at  each  end  provide  a  potential  gradient.  The  magnet  carries 
a  wire  which  dips  into  the  water,  picks  up  a  potential  depending 
on  the  position  of  the  magnet,  and  sends  it  to  the  grid  of  the 
triode.  J  provides  the  anode-potential  at  150  V.,  while  H  is  at 
180  V. ;  so  E  carries  a  constant  current.  If  the  grid-potential  allows 
just  this  current  to  pass  through  the  valve,  then  no  current  will  flow 
through  the  output.  But  if  the  valve  passes  more,  or  less,  current 
than  this,  the  output  circuit  will  carry  the  difference  in  one  direc- 
tion or  the  other.  So  after  E  is  adjusted,  the  output  is  approxi- 
mately proportional  to  M's  deviation  from  its  central  position. j* 

*  It  was  given  the  name  of  '  Homeostat '  for  convenience  of  reference,  and 
the  noun  seems  to  be  acceptable.  The  derivatives  '  homeostatic '  and 
1  homeostatically  ',  however,  are  unfortunate,  for  they  suggest  reference  to 
the  machine,  whereas  priority  demands  that  they  be  used  only  as  derivatives 
of  Cannon's  '  homeostasis  '. 

t  Following  the  original  machine  in  principle,  Mr.  Earl  J.  Kletsky,  at  the 
Technische  Hogeschool,  Delft,  Holland,  has  designed  and  built  a  form  that 
replaces  the  magnet,  coils,  vane  and  water  by  Kirchhoff  adding  circuits  and 
capacitors. 

100 


8/2 


THE    HOMEOSTAT 


Figure  8/2/1  :  The  Homeostat.  Each  unit  carries  on  top  a  magnet  and 
coil  such  as  that  shown  in  Figure  8/2/2.  Of  the  controls  on  the  front 
panel,  those  of  the  upper  row  control  the  potentiometers,  those  of  the 
middle  row  the  commutators,  and  those  of  the  lower  row  the  switches  S 
of  Figure  8/2/3. 


Figure  8/2/2  :  Typical  magnet  (just  visible),  coil,  pivot,  vane,  and  water 
potentiometer  with  electrodes  at  each  end.  The  coil  is  quadruple,  con- 
sisting of  A,  B,  C  and  D  of  Figure  8/2/3. 


101 


DESIGN     FOR    A    BRAIN 


8/2 


fi^hs. 


°<3^ 


Figure  8/2/3  :    Wiring  diagram  of  one  unit.     (The  letters  are  explained 

in  the  text.) 

Next,  the  units  are  joined  together  so  that  each  sends  its 
output  to  the  other  three;  and  thereby  each  receives  an  input 
from  each  of  the  other  three. 

These  inputs  act  on  the  unit's  magnet  through  the  coils  A, 

B,  and  C,  so  that  the  torque  on  the  magnet  is  approximately 
proportional  to  the  algebraic  sum  of  the  currents  in  A,  B,  and 

C.  (D  also  affects  M  as  a  self -feedback.)  But  before  each  input 
current  reaches  its  coil,  it  passes  through  a  commutator  (X), 
which  determines  the  polarity  of  entry  to  the  coil,  and  through 
a  potentiometer  (P),  which  determines  what  fraction  of  the  input 
shall  reach  the  coil. 

As  soon  as  the  system  is  switched  on,  the  magnets  are  moved 
by  the  currents  from  the  other  units,  but  these  movements  change 
the  currents,  which  modify  the  movements,  and  so  on.  It  may 
be  shown  (S.  19/11)  that  if  there  is  sufficient  viscosity  in  the 
troughs,  the  four-variable  system  of  the  magnet-positions  is 
approximately  state-determined.  To  this  system  the  com- 
mutators and  potentiometers  act  as  parameters. 

When  these  parameters  are  given  a  definite  set  of  values,  the 
magnets  show  some  definite  pattern  of  behaviour;  for  the  para- 
meters determine  the  field,  and  thus  the  lines  of  behaviour.     If 

102 


8/3  THE     HOMEOSTAT 

the  field  is  stable,  the  four  magnets  move  to  the  central  position, 
where  they  actively  resist  any  attempt  to  displace  them.  If 
displaced,  a  co-ordinated  activity  brings  them  back  to  the  centre. 
Other  parameter-settings  may,  however,  give  instability;  in  which 
case  a  '  runaway  '  occurs  and  the  magnets  diverge  from  the  central 
positions  with  increasing  velocity — till  they  hit  the  ends  of  the 
troughs. 

So  far,  the  system  of  four  variables  has  been  shown  to  be 
dynamic,  to  have  Figure  4/15/1  (A)  as  its  diagram  of  immediate 
effects,  and  to  be  state-determined.  Its  field  depends  on  the 
thirty-two  parameters  X  and  P.  It  is  not  yet  ultrastable.  But 
the  inputs,  instead  of  being  controlled  by  parameters  set  by  hand, 
can  be  sent  by  the  switches  S  through  similar  components  arranged 
on  a  uniselector  (or  '  stepping-switch  ')  U.  The  values  of  the 
components  in  U  were  deliberately  randomised  by  taking  the 
actual  numerical  values  from  Fisher  and  Yates'  Table  of  Random 
Numbers.  Once  built  on  to  the  uniselectors,  the  values  of  these 
parameters  are  determined  at  any  moment  by  the  positions  of 
the  uniselectors.  Twenty-five  positions  on  each  of  four  uni- 
selectors (one  to  each  unit)  provide  390,625  combinations  of 
parameter- values . 

F  represents  the  essential  variable  of  the  unit.  Its  contacts 
close  when  and  only  when  the  output  current  exceeds  a  certain 
value.  When  this  happens,  the  coils  G  of  the  uniselector  can  be 
energised,  moving  the  parameters  to  new  values.  The  power  to 
G  is  also  interrupted  by  a  device  (not  shown)  that  allows  the  power 
to  test  F's  contacts  only  at  intervals  of  one  to  ten  seconds  (the 
operator  can  adjust  the  frequency).  Thus,  if  set  at  3-second 
intervals,  at  every  third  second  the  uniselector  will  either  move  to 
new  values  (if  F  be  receiving  a  current  exceeding  the  limits)  or 
stay  where  it  is  (if  F's  current  be  within). 

8/3.  That  the  machine  described  is  ultrastable  can  be  verified 
by  an  examination  of  the  correspondences. 

There  are  four  main  variables — the  positions  of  the  four  magnets. 
(There  can,  of  course,  be  fewer  if  not  all  the  units  are  used.) 
These  four  represent  both  the  environment  and  the  reacting  part 
R  of  Figure  7/2/1,  the  allotment  of  the  four  to  the  two  subsystems 
being  arbitrary.  The  relays  F  correspond  to  the  essential 
variables,  and  the  physiological  limits  correspond  to  the  currents 

103 


DESIGN    FOR    A    BRAIN  8/4 

that  flow  in  F  when  the  needles  are  deviated  to  more  than  about 
45  degrees  from  the  central  positions.  The  main  variables  are 
continuous,  and  act  and  react  on  one  another,  giving  the  primary 
feedback,  which  is  complex,  like  A  of  Figure  4/15/1.  The  field 
of  the  four  main  variables  has  only  one  state  of  equilibrium  (at 
the  centre),  which  may  be  stable  or  unstable.  Thus  the  system 
is  either  stable  and  self-correcting  for  small  impulsive  displace- 
ments to  the  needles,  or  unstable  and  self-aggravating,  running 
away  to  the  limits  of  the  troughs.  Which  it  will  be  depends  on 
the  quantitative  details  of  the  primary  feedbacks,  which  are 
dependent  on  the  values  on  the  step-mechanisms. 

The  step-mechanisms  of  S.  7/12  can  be  made  to  correspond  to 
structures  on  the  Homeostat  in  several  ways,  which  are  equivalent. 
Perhaps  the  simplest  way  is  to  identify  them  with  the  twelve 
values  presented  by  the  uniselectors  at  any  given  moment  (three 
on  each).  If  the  needle  of  a  unit  diverges  for  more  than  a  few 
seconds  outside  the  limits  of  ±45°,  the  three  values  of  its  step- 
functions  will  be  changed  to  three  new  values.  These  new  values 
have  no  special  relation  either  to  the  previous  values  or  to  the 
problem  in  hand — they  are  just  the  values  that  next  follow  in 
Fisher  and  Yates'  table. 

It  is  easily  seen  that  if  any  one,  two,  or  three  of  the  units  are 
used  (as  is  often  done  for  simplicity)  this  subsystem  will  still  be 
ultrastable. 

The  Homeostat  as  adapter 

8/4.  A  remarkable  property  of  the  nervous  system  is  its  ability 
to  adapt  itself  to  surgical  alterations  of  the  bodily  structure. 
From  the  first  work  of  Marina  to  the  recent  work  of  Sperry,  such 
experiments  have  aroused  interest  and  no  little  surprise. 

Over  forty  years  ago,  Marina  severed  the  attachments  of  the 
internal  and  external  recti  muscles  of  a  monkey's  eyeball  and 
re-attached  them  in  crossed  position  so  that  a  contraction  of 
the  external  rectus  would  cause  the  eyeball  to  turn  not  outwards 
but  inwards.  When  the  wound  had  healed,  he  was  surprised  to 
discover  that  the  two  eyeballs  still  moved  together,  so  that 
binocular  vision  was  preserved. 

More  recently  Sperry  severed  the  nerves  supplying  the  flexor 
and  extensor  muscles  in  the  arm  of  the  spider  monkey,  and  re- 
joined them  in  crossed  position.     After  the  nerves  had  regenerated, 

104 


8/4  THE     HOMEOSTAT 

the  animal's  arm  movements  were  at  first  grossly  inco-ordinated, 
but  improved  until  an  essentially  normal  mode  of  progression 
was  re-established.  The  two  examples  are  typical  of  a  great 
number  of  experiments,  and  will  suffice  for  the  discussion.  Let 
us  see  what  the  Homeostat  will  do  under  a  similar  operation. 
Figure   8/4/1    shows   the  Homeostat  simplified   to   two   units 


1 


Ri 


u 


°1      °2 


Time 


Figure  8/4/1  :  Two  units  (1  and  2)  interacting.  Line  1  represents  the  side- 
to-side  movements  of  Unit  l's  needle  by  vertical  changes.  Similarly 
line  2  shows  the  behaviour  of  Unit  2's  needle.  The  lowest  line  (U)  shows 
a  mark  whenever  Unit  l's  uniselector  advanced  a  step.  The  dotted  lines 
correspond  to  critical  states.  The  displacements  D  were  caused  by  the 
operator  so  as  to  force  the  system  to  show  its  response. 

interacting.  The  diagram  of  immediate  effects  was  1  ^±  2 ;  the 
effect  1  — >-  2  was  hand-controlled,  and  2  — >  1  was  uniselector- 
controlled.  At  first  the  step-mechanism  values  combined  to  give 
stability,  shown  by  the  responses  to  Dv  (The  reader  should  bear 
in  mind,  of  course,  that  this  trifling  return  after  displacement  is 
representative  of  all  the  complex  returns  after  displacement  con- 
sidered in  Chapter  5:  Adaptation  as  stability.)  At  Rv  reversal 
of  the  commutator  by  hand  rendered  the  system  unstable,  a 
runaway  occurred,  and  the  variables  transgressed  the  critical 
states.  The  uniselector  in  Unit  1  changed  position  and,  as  it 
happened,  gave  at  its  first  trial  a'  stable  field.  It  will  be  noticed 
that  whereas  before  Rx  the  upstroke  of  D±  in  2  caused  an  up- 
stroke  in  1,  it  caused  a  downstroke  in  1  after  Rv  showing  that  the 
action  2  — >  1  had  been  reversed  by  the  uniselector.  This  reversal 
compensated  for  the  reversal  of  1  — >  2  caused  at  Rv 

At  R2  the  whole  process  was  repeated.     This  time  three  uni- 
selector changes  were  required  before  stability  was  restored.     A 

105 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  8/5 

comparison  of  the  effect  of  D3  on  1  with  that  of  D2  shows  that 
compensation  has  occurred  again. 

If  the  two  phenomena  are  to  be  brought  into  correspondence, 
we  must  notice,  as  in  S.  3/12,  that  the  anatomical  criterion  for 
dividing  the  system  into  '  animal  '  and  i  environment  '  is  not 
the  only  possible:  a  functional  criterion  is  also  possible.  Suppose 
a  monkey,  to  get  food  from  a  box,  has  to  pull  a  lever  towards 
itself;  if  we  sever  the  flexor  and  extensor  muscles  of  the  arm 
and  re-attach  them  in  crossed  position  then,  so  far  as  the  cerebral 
cortex  is  concerned,  the  change  is  not  essentially  different  from 
that  of  dismantling  the  box  and  re-assembling  it  so  that  the 
lever  has  to  be  pushed  instead  of  pulled.  Spinal  cord,  peripheral 
nerves,  muscles,  bones,  lever,  and  box — all  are  '  environment ' 
to  the  cerebral  cortex.  A  reversal  in  the  cerebral  cortex  will 
compensate  for  a  reversal  in  its  environment  whether  in  spinal 
cord,  muscles,  or  lever.  It  seems  reasonable,  therefore,  to  expect 
that  the  cerebral  cortex  will  use  the  same  compensatory  process 
whatever  the  site  of  reversal. 

To  apply  the  principle  of  ultrastability  we  must  add  an  assump- 
tion that  i  binocular  vision  '  and  '  normal  progression  '  have 
neural  correlates  such  that  deviations  from  binocular  vision  or 
from  normal  progression  cause  an  excitation  sufficient  to  cause 
changes  of  step-function  form  in  those  cerebral  mechanisms  that 
determine  the  actions.  (The  plausibility  of  this  assumption  will 
be  discussed  in  S.  9/4.)  Ultrastability  will  then  automatically 
lead  to  the  emergence  of  behaviour  which  produces  binocular 
vision  or  normal  progression. 

8/5.  A  more  complex  example  is  shown  in  Figure  8/5/1.  The 
machine  was  arranged  so  that  its  diagram  of  immediate  effects 
was 


>3 


The  effect  3  — >  1  was  set  permanently  so  that  a  movement  of 
3  made  1  move  in  the  opposite  direction.  The  action  1  — >  2 
was  uniselector-controlled,  and  2  — >►  3  hand-controlled.  When 
the  tracing  commenced,  the  actions  1  — >•  2  and  2  — >  3  were 
demonstrated  by  the  downward  movement,  forced  by  the  operator, 
of  1   at  S^.  2  followed  1  downward  (similar  movement),  and  3 

106 


8/5  THE     HOMEOSTAT 


v     \j — y 


S2 


Time 


Figure  8/5/1  :    Three  units  interacting.     At  R  the  effect 
of  2  on  3  was  reversed  in  polarity. 

followed  2  downward  (similar  movement).  3  then  forced  1  up- 
ward, opposed  the  original  movement,  and  produced  stability. 

At  R,  the  hand-control  (2  — >■  3)  was  reversed,  so  that  2  now 
forced  3  to  move  in  the  opposite  direction  to  itself.  This  change 
set  up  a  vicious  circle  and  destroyed  the  stability;  but  uniselector 
changes  occurred  until  the  stability  was  restored.  A  forced  down- 
ward movement  of  1,  at  S2,  demonstrated  the  regained  stability. 

The  tracing,  however,  deserves  closer  study.  The  action  2  — >  3 
was  reversed  at  R,  and  the  responses  of  2  and  3  at  S2  demonstrate 
this  reversal;  for  while  at  S±  they  moved  similarly,  at  S2  they 
moved  oppositely.  Again,  a  comparison  of  the  uniselector- 
controlled  action  1  — >  2  before  and  after  R  shows  that  whereas 
beforehand  2  moved  similarly  to  1,  afterwards  it  moved  oppo- 
sitely. The  reversal  in  2  — >  3,  caused  by  the  operator,  thus 
evoked  a  reversal  in  1  — >  2  controlled  by  the  uniselector.  The 
second  reversal  is  compensatory  to  the  first. 

The  nervous  system  provides  many  illustrations  of  such  a  series 
of  events:  first  the  established  reaction,  then  an  alteration  made 
in  the  environment  by  the  experimenter,  and  finally  a.  reorganisa- 
tion within  the  nervous  system,  compensating  for  the  experimental 
alteration.  The  Homeostat  can  thus  show,  in  elementary  form, 
this  power  of  self -reorganisation. 


107 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  8/6 

8/6.  We  can  now  appreciate  how  different  an  ultrastable  system 
is  from  a  simple  stable  system  when  the  conditions  allow  the 
difference  to  show  clearly. 

The  difference  can  best  be  shown  by  an  example.  The  auto- 
matic pilot  is  a  device  which,  amongst  other  actions,  keeps  the 
aeroplane  horizontal.  It  must  therefore  be  connected  to  the 
ailerons  in  such  a  way  that  when  the  plane  rolls  to  the  right,  its 
output  must  act  on  them  so  as  to  roll  the  plane  to  the  left.  If 
properly  joined,  the  whole  system  is  stable  and  self-correcting:  it 
can  now  fly  safely  through  turbulent  air,  for  though  it  will  roll 
frequently,  it  will  always  come  back  to  the  level.  The  Homeostat, 
if  joined  in  this  way,  would  tend  to  do  the  same.  (Though  not 
well  suited,  it  would,  in  principle,  if  given  a  gyroscope,  be  able  to 
correct  roll.) 

So  far  they  show  no  difference;  but  connect  the  ailerons  in 
reverse  and  compare  them.  The  automatic  pilot  would  act,  after 
a  small  disturbance,  to  increase  the  roll,  and  would  persist  in  its 
wrong  action  to  the  very  end.  The  Homeostat,  however,  would 
persist  in  its  wrong  action  only  until  the  increasing  deviation 
made  the  step-mechanisms  start  changing.  On  the  occurrence 
of  the  first  suitable  new  value,  the  Homeostat  would  act  to  stabilise 
instead  of  to  overthrow ;  it  would  return  the  plane  to  the  horizontal ; 
and  it  would  then  be  ordinarily  self-correcting  for  disturbances. 

There  is  therefore  some  justification  for  the  name  '  ultrastable  '; 
for  if  the  main  variables  are  assembled  so  as  to  make  their  field 
unstable,  the  ultrastable  system  will  change  this  field  till  it  is 
stable.  The  degree  of  stability  shown  is  therefore  of  an  order 
higher  than  that  of  the  system  with  a  single  field. 

8/7.  The  experiments  of  Marina  and  Sperry  provide  an  excellent 
introduction  because  they  are  conceptually  so  simple.  Some- 
times a  simple  experiment  on  adaptation  may  need  a  little  thought 
before  we  can  identify  the  essential  features.  Thus  Mowrer  put 
a  rat  into  a  box  with  a  grilled  metal  floor.  The  grill  could  be 
electrified  so  as  to  give  shocks  to  the  rat's  paws.  Inside  the  box 
was  a  pedal  which,  if  depressed,  at  once  stopped  the  shocks. 

When  a  rat  was  put  into  the  box  and  the  electric  stimulation 
started,  the  rat  would  produce  various  undirected  activities  such 
as  jumping,  running,  squealing,  biting  at  the  grill,  and  random 
thrashing  about.     Sooner  or  later  it  would  depress  the  pedal  and 

108 


8/7 


THE     HOMEOSTAT 


stop  the  shocks.  After  the  tenth  trial,  the  application  of  the 
shock  would  usually  cause  the  rat  to  go  straight  to  the  pedal  and 
depress  it.     These,  briefly,  are  the  observed  facts. 

Consider  the  internal  linkages  in  this  system.  We  can  suffi- 
ciently specify  what  is  happening  by  using  six  variables,  or  sets 
of  variables:  those  shown  in  the  box-diagram  below.     By  con- 


Events  in 

6 

Events  in 

sensory  cortex 

motor  cortex 

> 
5 

k 

1 

V 

Excitation 
in  skin 

Position  of 
limbs 

> 
4 

k 

2 

Voltage 

Position 

on 

grill 

3 

of  pedal 

sidering  the  known  actions  of  part  on  part  in  the  real  system  we 
can  construct  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects.  Thus,  the  excita- 
tions in  the  motor  cortex  certainly  control  the  rat's  bodily  move- 
ments, and  such  excitations  have  no  direct  effect  on  any  of  the 
other  five  groups  of  variables;  so  we  can  insert  arrow  1,  and 
know  that  no  other  arrow  leaves  that  box.  (The  single  arrow,  of 
course,  represents  a  complex  channel.)  Similarly,  the  other  arrows 
of  the  diagram  can  be  inserted.  Some  of  the  arrows,  e.g.  2  and  4, 
represent  a  linkage  in  which  there  is  not  a  positive  physical  action 
all  the  time;  but  here,  in  accordance  with  S.  2/3,  we  regard  them 
as  permanently  linked  though  sometimes  acting  at  zero  degree. 

Having  completed  the  diagram,  we  notice  that  it  forms  a 
functional  circuit.  The  system  is  complete  and  isolated,  and 
may  therefore  be  treated  as  state-determined.  To  apply  our 
thesis,  we  assume  that  the  cerebral  part,  represented  by  the  boxes 
around  arrow  6,  contains  step-mechanisms  whose  critical  states 
will  be  transgressed  if  stimuli  of  more  than  physiological  intensity 
are  sent  to  the  brain. 

We  now  regard  the  system  as  ultrastable,  and  predict  what 
its  behaviour  must  be.  It  is  started,  by  hypothesis,  from  an 
initial  state  at  which  the  voltage  is  high.  This  being  so,  the 
excitation  at  the  skin  and  in  the  brain  will  be  high.     At  first 

109 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  8/8 

the  pattern  of  impulses  sent  to  the  muscles  does  not  cause  that 
pedal  movement  which  would  lower  the  voltage  on  the  grill. 
These  high  excitations  in  the  brain  will  cause  some  step-mech- 
anisms to  change  value,  thus  causing  different  patterns  of  body 
movement  to  occur.  The  step-mechanisms  act  directly  only  at 
stage  6,  but  changes  there  will  (S.  12/9)  affect  the  field  of  all 
six  groups  of  main  variables.  These  changes  of  field  will  continue 
to  occur  as  long  as  the  high  excitation  in  the  brain  persists. 
They  will  cease  when,  and  only  when,  the  linkages  at  stage  6 
transform  an  excitation  of  skin  receptors  into  such  a  bodily 
movement  as  will  cause,  through  the  pedal,  a  reduction  in  the 
excitation  of  the  skin  receptors;  for  only  such  linkages  can  stop 
further  encounters  with  critical  states.  The  system,  that  is, 
will  change  until  there  occurs  a  stable  field.  The  stability  will 
be  shown  by  an  increase  in  the  voltage  on  the  grill  leading  to 
changes  through  skin,  brain,  muscles,  and  pedal  that  have  the 
effect  of  opposing  the  increase  in  voltage.  The  stability,  in 
addition,  has  the  property  that  it  keeps  the  essential  variables 
within  physiological  limits;  for  by  it  the  rat  is  protected  from 
electrical  injury,  and  the  nervous  system  from  exhaustion. 

It  will  be  noted  that  although  action  3  has  no  direct  con- 
nexion, either  visually  in  the  real  apparatus  or  functionally  in  the 
diagram  of  immediate  effects,  with  the  site  of  the  changes  at  6, 
yet  the  latter  become  adapted  to  the  nature  of  the  action  at  3. 
(The  subject  was  discussed  in  S.  5/13.) 

This  example  shows,  therefore,  that  if  the  rat  and  its  environ- 
ment formed  an  ultrastable  system  and  acted  purely  automati- 
cally, they  would  go  through  the  same  changes  as  were  observed 
by  Mowrer. 

Training 

8/8.  The  process  of  '  training  '  will  now  be  shown  in  its  relation 
to  ultrastability. 

All  training  involves  some  use  of  '  punishment  '  or  '  reward  ', 
and  we  must  translate  these  concepts  into  our  form.  i  Punish- 
ment '  is  simple,  for  it  means  that  some  sensory  organs  or  nerve 
endings  have  been  stimulated  with  an  intensity  high  enough  to 
cause  step-function  changes  in  the  nervous  system  (S.  7/19  and 
9/7).  The  concept  of  '  reward  '  is  more  complex.  It  usually 
involves  the  supplying  of  some  substance  (e.g.  food)  or  condition 

110 


8/8 


THE     HOMEOSTAT 


(e.g.  escape)  whose  absence  would  act  as  '  punishment  '.  The 
chief  difficulty  is  that  the  evidence  suggests  that  the  nervous 
system,  especially  the  mammalian,  contains  intricate  and  special- 
ised mechanisms  which  give  the  animals  properties  not  to  be 
deduced  from  basic  principles  alone.  Thus  it  has  been  shown 
that  dogs  with  an  oesophageal  fistula,  deprived  of  water  for  some 
hours,  would,  when  offered  water,  drink  approximately  the 
quantity  that  would  correct  the  deprivation,  and  would  then 
stop  drinking;  they  would  stop  although  no  water  had  entered 
stomach  or  system.  The  properties  of  these  mechanisms  have  not 
yet  been  fully  elucidated;  so  training  by  reward  uses  mechanisms 
of  unknown  properties.  Here  we  shall  ignore  these  complica- 
tions. We  shall  assume  that  the  training  is  by  pain,  i.e.  by  some 
change  which  threatens  to  drive  the  essential  variables  outside 
their  normal  limits;  and  we  shall  assume  that  training  by  reward 
is  not  essentially  dissimilar. 

It  should  be  noticed  that  in  training-experiments  the  experi- 
menter often  plays  a  dual  role.  He  first  plans  the  experiment, 
deciding  what  rules  shall  be  obeyed  during  it.  Then,  when 
these  have  been  fixed,  he  takes  part  in  the  experiment  and  obeys 
these  rules.  With  the  first  role  we  are  not  concerned.  In  the 
second,  however,  it  is  important  to  note  that  the  experimenter 
is  now  within  the  functional  machinery  of  the  experiment.  The 
truth  of  this  statement  can  be  appreciated  more  readily  if  his 
place  is  taken  by  an  untrained  but  obedient  assistant  who  carries 
out  the  instructions  blindly;  or  better  still  if  his  place  is  taken  by 
an  apparatus  which  carries  out  the  prescribed  actions  automatically. 

When  the  whole  training  is  arranged  to  occur  automatically 
the  feedback  is  readily  demonstrated  if  we  construct  the  diagram 
of  immediate  effects.  Thus,  a  pike  in  an  aquarium  was  separated 
from  some  minnows  by  a  sheet  of  glass;  every  time  he  dashed 
at  the  minnows  he  struck  the  glass.  The  following  immediate 
effects  can  be  clearly  distinguished: 


Activities  in 

1 

Activities  in 

motor  cortex 

muscles 

4 

< 

> 

2 

> 

Activities  in 
sensory  cortex 

Pressure  on 
nose 

3 
111 

DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


8/8 


The  effect  1  represents  the  control  exerted  through  spinal  cord 
and  motor  nerves.  Effect  2  is  discontinuous  but  none  the  less 
clear:  the  experiment  implies  that  some  activities  Jed  to  a  high 
pressure  on  the  nose  while  others  led  to  a  zero  pressure.  Effects 
3  and  4  are  the  simple  neuro-physiological  results  of  pressures 
on  the  nose. 

Although  the  diagram  has  some  freedom  in  the  selection  of 
variables  for  naming,  the  system,  regarded  as  a  whole,  clearly 
has  feedback. 

In  other  training  experiments,  the  regularity  of  action  2 
(supplied  above  by  the  constant  physical  properties  of  glass)  may 
be  supplied  by  an  assistant  who  constantly  obeys  the  rules  laid 
down  by  the  experimenter.  Grindley,  for  instance,  kept  a 
guinea-pig  in  a  silent  room  in  which  a  buzzer  was  sounded  from 
time  to  time.  If  and  only  if  its  head  turned  to  the  right  did  a 
tray  swing  out  and  present  it  with  a  piece  of  carrot;  after  a  few 
nibbles  the  carrot  was  withdrawn  and  the  process  repeated. 
Feedback  is  demonstrably  present  in  this  system,  for  the  diagram 
of  immediate  effects  is: 


Activities  in 

1 

Position  of 

motor  cortex 

head 

> 
4 

k 

' 

2 

t 

Activities  in 

Amount  of 

sensory 

cortex 

3 

carrot  pi 

^esented 

The  buzzer,  omitted  for  clarity,  comes  in  as  parameter  and  serve 
merely  to  call  this  dynamic  system  into  functional  existence; 
for  only  when  the  buzzer  sounds  does  the  linkage  2  exist. 

This  type  of  experiment  reveals  its  essential  dynamic  structure 
more  clearly  if  contrasted  with  elementary  Pavlovian  condition- 
ing. In  the  experiments  of  Grindley  and  Pavlov,  both  use  the 
sequences  '.  .  .  buzzer,  animal's  response,  food  .  .  .'  In  Grind- 
ley's  experiment,  the  value  of  the  variable  '  food  '  depended  on  the 
animaVs  response:  if  the  head  turned  to  the  left,  '  food  '  was  '  no 
carrot  ',  while  if  the  head  turned  to  the  right,  '  food  '  was  '  carrot 
given  '.  But  in  Pavlov's  experiments  the  nature  of  every  stimulus 
throughout  the  session  was  already  determined  before  the  session 
commenced.     The    Pavlovian    experiment,    therefore,    allows    no 

112 


8/9  THE     HOMEOSTAT 

effect  from  the  variable  '  animal's  behaviour  '  to  '  quantity  of 
food  given  ' ;  there  is  no  functional  circuit  and  no  feedback. 

It  may  be  thought  that  the  distinction  (which  corresponds  to 
that  made  by  Hilgard  and  Marquis  between  '  conditioning  '  and 
'  instrumental  learning  ')  is  purely  verbal.  This  is  not  so,  for 
the  description  given  above  shows  that  the  distinction  may  be 
made  objectively  by  examining  the  structure  of  the  experiment. 

It  will  be  seen,  therefore,  that  the  '  training  '  situation  neces- 
sarily implies  that  the  trainer,  or  some  similar  device,  is  an 
integral  part  of  the  whole  system,  which  has  feedback: 


Trainer 

w 

Animal 

We  shall  now  suppose  this  system  to  be  ultrastable,  and  we 
shall  trace  its  behaviour  on  this  supposition.  The  step-mechanisms 
are,  of  course,  assumed  to  be  confined  to  the  animal;  both  because 
the  human  trainer  may  be  replaced  in  some  experiments  by  a 
device  as  simple  as  a  sheet  of  glass  (in  the  example  of  the  pike); 
and  because  the  rules  of  the  training  are  to  be  decided  in  advance 
(as  when  we  decide  to  punish  a  house-dog  whenever  he  jumps 
into  a  chair),  and  therefore  to  be  invariant  throughout  the  process. 
Suppose  then  that  jumping  into  a  chair  always  results  in  the 
dog's  sensory  receptors  being  excessively  stimulated.  As  an 
ultrastable  system,  step-function  values  which  lead  to  jumps  into 
chairs  will  be  followed  by  stimulations  likely  to  cause  them  to 
change  value.  But  on  the  occurrence  of  a  set  of  step-function 
values  leading  to  a  remaining  on  the  ground,  excessive  stimula- 
tion will  not  occur,  and  the  values  will  remain.  (The  cessation 
of  punishment  when  the  right  action  occurs  is  no  less  important 
in  training  than  its  administration  after  the  wrong  action.) 

8/9.     The  process  can  be  shown  on  the  Homeostat.     Figure  8/9/1 
provides  an  example.     Three  units  were  joined: 


>2 


3 

and  to  this  system  was  joined  a  '  trainer  ',  actually  myself,  which 
acted  on  the  rule  that  if  the  Homeostat  did  not  respond  to  a 

113 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


8/9 


forced  movement  of  1  by  an  opposite  movement  of  2,  then  the 
trainer  would  force  3  over  to  an  extreme  position.  The  diagram 
of  immediate  effects  is  therefore  really 


Part  of  the  system's  feedbacks,  it  will  be  noticed,  pass  through  T. 


V 


Di  Dp 

1 w- 


Time   »- 


Figure  8/9/1  :  Three  units  interacting.  The  downstrokes  at  S  are 
forced  by  the  operator.  If  2  responds  with  a  downstroke,  the 
trainer  drives  3  past  its  critical  surface. 

At  Sv  1  was  moved  and  2  moved  similarly.  This  is  the  '  for- 
bidden '  response;  so  at  Dv  3  was  forced  by  the  trainer  to  an 
extreme  position.  Step-mechanisms  changed  value.  At  S2,  the 
Homeostat  was  tested  again:  again  it  produced  the  forbidden 
response;  so  at  D2,  3  was  again  forced  to  an  extreme  position. 
At  S3,  the  Homeostat  was  tested  again:  it  moved  in  the  desired 
way,  so  no  further  deviation  was  forced  on  3.  And  at  S±  and 
S5  the  Homeostat  continued  to  show  the  desired  reaction. 

From  Sx  onwards,  T's  behaviour  is  determinate  at  every  instant; 
so  the  system  composed  of  1,  2,  3,  T,  and  the  uniselectors,  is 
state-determined. 

Another  property  of  the  whole  system  should  be  noticed. 
When  the  movement-combination  '  1  and  2  moving  similarly  ' 
occurs,  T  is  thereby  impelled,  under  the  rules  of  the  experiment, 
to  force  3  outside  the  region  bounded  by  the  critical  states.     Of 

114 


8/10  THE     HOMEOSTAT 

any  inanimate  system  which  behaved  in  this  way  we  would  say, 
simply,  that  the  line  of  behaviour  from  the  state  at  which  1  and  2 
started  moving  was  unstable.  So,  to  say  in  psychological  terms 
that  the  '  trainer  '  has  '  punished  '  the  '  animal  '  is  equivalent  to 
saying  in  our  terms  that  the  system  has  a  set  of  parameter-values 
that  make  it  unstable. 

In  general,  then,  we  may  identify  the  behaviour  of  the  animal 
in  '  training  '  with  that  of  the  ultrastable  system  adapting  to 
another  system  of  fixed  characteristics. 

8/10.  How  will  the  ultrastable  system  behave  if  it  has  to  adapt 
to  two  environments,  which  alternate  ?  Such  a  situation  is  not 
uncommon:  the  diving  bird  has  to  adapt  to  situations  both  on 
land  and  in  the  water;  British  birds  have  to  adapt  both  to  full 
foliage  in  the  summer  and  to  bare  branches  in  the  winter;  and 
the  kitten  has  to  adapt  both  to  the  mouse  that  tries  to  escape  into 
a  hole  and  to  the  bird  that  tries  to  escape  by  flying  upwards. 

Such  cases  are  equivalent  (by  Ss.  6/3  and  7/20)  to  the  case  in 
which  there  is  one  environment  affected  by  a  parameter  with  two 
values.  Each  value,  provided  it  is  sustained  long  enough  for  the 
characteristic  behaviours  of  adaptation  to  be  displayed,  gives  one 
form  to  the  environment;  and  the  two  forms  may,  if  we  please, 
be  thought  of  as  two  environments.  The  question  can  therefore 
be  investigated  by  allowing  the  Homeostat  to  adapt  in  the  pres- 
ence of  an  alternating  parameter,  each  value  of  which  must  be 
sustained  long  enough  so  that  the  change  does  not  interrupt  the 
process  of  trial  and  error. 

Let  the  Homeostat  be  arranged  so  that  it  is  partly  under  uni- 
selector-, and  partly  under  hand-,  control.  Let  it  be  started  so 
that  it  works  as  an  ultrastable  system.  Select  a  commutator 
switch,  and  from  time  to  time  reverse  its  polarity.  This  reversal 
provides  the  system  with  the  equivalent  of  two  environments 
which  alternate.  We  can  now  predict  that  it  will  be  selective  for 
fields  that  give  adaptation  to  both  environments.  For  consider 
what  field  can  be  terminal :  a  field  that  is  terminal  for  only  one  of 
the  parameter-values  will  be  lost  when  the  parameter  next  changes ; 
but  the  first  field  terminal  for  both  will  be  retained.  Figure 
8/10/1  illustrates  the  process.  At  Rv  R2,  R3,  and  R±  the  hand- 
controlled  commutator  H  was  reversed.  At  first  the  change  of 
value  caused  a  change  of  field,  shown  at  A.     But  the  second 

115 


DESIGN     FOR    A    BRAIN  8/11 


H 

R1 

ff 

-1R3 

R4 

"1 

r" 

1 

4* /\-^ 7n 5u- 


++ 


Time 


Figure  8/10/1  :  Record  of  Homeostat's  behaviour  when  a  commutator  H 
was  reversed  from  time  to  time  (at  the  R's).  The  first  set  of  uniselector 
values  which  gave  stability  for  both  commutator  positions  was  terminal. 

uniselector  position  happened  to  provide  a  field  which  gave 
stability  with  both  values  of  H.  So  afterwards,  the  changes  of 
H  no  longer  caused  changes  in  the  step-mechanisms.  The  re- 
sponses to  the  displacements  Z),  forced  by  the  operator,  show  that 
the  system  is  stable  for  both  values  of  H.  The  slight  but  distinct 
difference  in  the  behaviour  after  D  at  the  two  values  of  H  show 
that  the  two  fields  are  different. 

The  ultrastable  system  is,  therefore,  selective  for  step-mechanism 
values  which  give  stability  for  both  values  of  an  alternating 
parameter. 

8/11.  What  will  happen  if  the  ultrastable  system  is  given  an 
unusual  environment  ?  Before  the  question  is  answered  we  must 
be  clear  about  what  is  meant  by  '  unusual '. 

In  S.  6/2  it  was  shown  that  every  dynamic  system  is  acted 
on  by  an  indefinitely  large  number  of  parameters,  many  of  which 
are  taken  for  granted,  for  they  are  always  given  well-understood 
'  obvious  '  values.  Thus,  in  mechanical  systems  it  is  taken  for 
granted,  unless  specially  mentioned,  that  the  bodies  carry  a 
zero  electrostatic  charge;  in  physiological  experiments,  that  the 
tissues,  unless  specially  mentioned,  contain  no  unusual  drug;  in 
biological  experiments,  that  the  animal,  unless  specially  mentioned, 
is  in  good  health.  All  these  parameters,  however,  are  effective 
in  that,  had  their  values  been  different,  the  variables  would  not 
have  followed  the  same  line  of  behaviour.  Clearly  the  field  of 
a  state-determined  system  depends  not  only  on  those  para- 
meters which  have  been  fixed  individually  and  specifically,  but 
on  all  the  great  number  which  have  been  fixed  incidentally. 

116 


8/11 


THE     HOMEOSTAT 


Now  the  ultrastable  system  proceeds  to  a  terminal  field  which 
is  stable  in  conjunction  with  all  the  system's  parameter- values 
(and  it  is  clear  that  this  must  be  so,  for  whether  the  parameters 
are  at  their  '  usual  '  values  or  not  is  irrelevant).  The  ultrastable 
system  will  therefore  always  produce  a  set  of  step-mechanism 
values  which  is  so  related  to  the  particular  set  of  parameter- values 
that,  in  conjunction  with  them,  the  system  is  stable.  If  the  para- 
meters have  unusual  values,  the  step-mechanisms  will  also  finish 
with  values  that  are  compensatingly  unusual.  To  the  casual 
observer  this  adjustment  of  the  step-mechanism  values  to  the 
parameter- values  may  be  surprising;  we,  however,  can  see  that 
it  is  inevitable. 

The  fact  is  demonstrable  on  the  Homeostat.  After  the  machine 
was  completed,  some  '  unusual '  complications  were  imposed  on 
it  ('  unusual  '  in  the  sense  that  they  were  not  thought  of  till  the 
machine  had  been  built),  and  the  machine  was  then  tested  to  see 
how  it  would  succeed  in  finding  a  stable  field  when  affected  by 
the  peculiar  complications.     One  such  test  was  made  by  joining 


U 


m 


Time 


Figure  8/11/1  :  Three  units  interacting.  At  J,  units  1  and  2  were  con- 
strained to  move  together.  New  step-mechanism  values  were  found 
which  produced  stability.  These  values  give  stability  in  conjunction 
with  the  constraint,  for  when  it  is  removed,  at  R,  the  system  becomes 
unstable. 

117 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  8/12 

the  front  two  magnets  by  a  light  glass  fibre  so  that  they  had  to 
move  together.  Figure  8/11/1  shows  a  typical  record  of  the 
changes.  Three  units  were  joined  together  and  were  at  first 
stable,  as  shown  by  the  response  when  the  operator  displaced 
magnet  1  at  Dv  At  J,  the  magnets  of  1  and  2  were  joined  so 
that  they  could  move  only  together.  The  result  of  the  constraint 
in  this  case  was  to  make  the  system  unstable.  But  the  instability 
evoked  step-mechanism  changes,  and  a  new  terminal  field  was 
found.  This  was,  of  course,  stable,  as  was  shown  by  its  response 
to  the  displacement,  made  by  the  operator,  at  D2.  But  it  should 
be  noticed  that  the  new  set  of  step-mechanism  values  was  adjusted 
to,  or  '  took  notice  of ',  the  constraint  and,  in  fact,  used  it  in  the 
maintenance  of  stability;  for  when,  at  R,  the  operator  gently 
lifted  the  fibre  away  the  system  became  unstable. 

There  are  other  unusual  problems,  of  course,  for  which  the 
Homeostat's  repertoire  contains  no  solution;  putting  too  powerful 
a  magnet  at  one  side  to  draw  the  magnets  over  would  set  such  a 
1  problem  ' ;  so  would  a  shorting  of  the  relay  F  (Figure  8/2/3). 
In  such  a  situation  the  Homeostat,  or  any  ultrastable  system, 
would  have  no  state  of  equilibrium  and  would  thus  fail  to  adapt. 
So,  too,  would  a  living  organism,  if  set  a  problem  for  which  its 
total  repertoire  contained  no  solution. 


Some  apparent  faults 

8/12.  It  will  be  apparent  that  the  principle  of  ultrastability,  as 
demonstrated  by  the  Homeostat,  does  not  seem  to  represent 
adequately  the  great  richness  of  adaptations  developed  by  the 
higher  animals ;  with  some  of  the  inadequacies  we  shall  deal  later 
in  the  book.  There  are,  however,  some  '  faults  '  of  the  ultrastable 
system  that  are  found  on  closer  scrutiny  actually  to  support  the 
thesis  that  the  living  brain  adapts  by  ultrastability.  We  will 
examine  them  in  the  next  few  sections. 

8/13.  If  the  relation  of  S.  7/5  does  not  hold  between  the  essential 
variables  and  the  step-mechanisms,  that  is,  if  an  ultrastable 
system's  critical  surfaces  are  not  disposed  in  proper  relation  to 
the  limits  of  the  essential  variables,  the  system  may  seek  an 
inappropriate  goal  or  may  fail  to  take  corrective  action  when  the 
essential  variables  are  dangerously  near  their  limits. 

118 


8/14  THE     HOMEOSTAT 

In  animals,  though  we  cannot  yet  say  much  about  their  critical 
states,  we  can  observe  failures  of  adaptation  that  may  well  be  due 
to  a  defect  of  this  type.  Thus,  though  animals  usually  react 
defensively  to  poisons  like  strychnine — for  it  has  an  intensely 
bitter  taste,  stimulates  the  taste  buds  strongly,  and  is  spat  out 
— they  are  characteristically  defenceless  against  a  tasteless  or 
odourless  poison:  precisely  because  it  stimulates  no  nerve-fibre 
excessively  and  causes  no  deviation  from  the  routine  of  chewing 
and  swallowing. 

An  even  more  dramatic  example,  showing  how  defenceless  is 
the  living  organism  if  pain  has  not  its  normal  effect  of  causing 
behaviour  to  change,  is  given  by  those  children  who  congenitally 
lack  the  normal  self-protective  reflexes.  Boyd  and  Nie  have 
described  such  a  case:  a  girl,  aged  7,  who  seemed  healthy  and 
normal  in  all  respects  except  that  she  was  quite  insensitive  to 
pain.  Even  before  she  was  a  year  old  her  parents  noticed  that 
she  did  not  cry  when  injured.  At  one  year  of  age  her  arm  was 
noticed  to  be  crooked:  X-rays  showed  a  recent  fracture-disloca- 
tion. The  child  had  made  no  complaint,  nor  did  she  show  any 
sign  of  pain  when  the  fragments  were  re-set  without  an  anaesthetic. 
Three  months  later  the  same  injury  occurred  to  her  right  elbow. 
At  the  seaside  she  crawled  on  the  rocks  until  her  hands  and  knees 
were  torn  and  denuded  of  skin.  At  home  her  mother  on  several 
occasions  smelt  burning  flesh  and  found  the  child  leaning  uncon- 
cernedly against  the  hot  stove. 

It  seems,  then,  that  if  an  imperfectly  formed  ultrastable  system 
is,  under  certain  conditions,  defenceless,  so  may  be  an  imperfectly 
formed  living  organism. 

8/14.  Even  if  the  ultrastable  system  is  suitably  arranged — if  the 
critical  states  are  encountered  before  the  essential  variables  reach 
their  limits — it  usually  cannot  adapt  to  an  environment '  that 
behaves  with  sudden  discontinuities.  In  the  earlier  examples  of 
the  Homeostat's  successful  adaptations  the  actions  were  always 
arranged  to  be  continuous;  but  suppose  the  Homeostat  had  con- 
trolled a  relay  which  was  usually  unchanging  but  which,  if  the 
Homeostat  passed  through  some  arbitrarily  selected  state,  would 
suddenly  release  a  powerful  spring  that  would  drag  the  magnets 
away  from  their  'optimal  '  central  positions:  the  Homeostat,  if 
it  happened  to  approach  the  special  state,  would  take  no  step 

119 


DESIGN     FOR    A    BRAIN  8/15 

to  avoid  it  and  would  blindly  evoke  the  '  lethal  '  action.  The 
Homeostat's  method  for  achieving  adaptation  is  thus  essentially 
useless  when  its  environment  contains  such 4  lethal '  discontinuities. 

The  living  organism,  however,  is  also  apt  to  fail  with  just  the 
same  type  of  environment.  The  pike  that  collided  with  the 
glass  plate  while  chasing  minnows  failed  at  first  to  avoid  collision 
precisely  because  of  the  suddenness  of  the  transition  from  not 
seeing  clear  glass  to  feeling  the  impact  on  its  nose.  This  flaw 
in  the  living  organism's  defences  has,  in  fact,  long  been  known 
and  made  use  of  by  the  hunter.  The  stalking  cat's  movements 
are  such  as  will  maintain  as  long  as  possible,  for  the  prey,  the 
appearance  of  a  peaceful  landscape,  to  be  changed  with  the 
utmost  possible  suddenness  into  one  of  mortal  threat.  In  the 
whole  process  the  suddenness  is  essential.  Consider  too  the 
essential  features  of  any  successful  trap;  and  the  necessity,  in 
poisoning  vermin,  of  ensuring  that  the  first  dose  is  lethal. 

If,  then,  the  ultrastable  system  usually  fails  when  attempting  to 
adapt  to  an  environment  with  sudden  discontinuities,  so  too  does 
the  living  organism. 

8/15.  Another  weakness  shown  by  the  ultrastable  system's 
method  is  that  success  is  dependent  on  the  system's  using  a  suitable 
period  of  delay  between  each  trial.  Thus,  the  system  shown  in 
Figure  7/23/1  must  persist  in  Trial  IV  long  enough  for  the  repre- 
sentative point  to  get  away  from  the  region  of  the  critical  states. 
Both  extremes  of  delay  may  be  fatal:  too  hurried  a  change  from 
trial  to  trial  may  not  allow  time  for  '  success  '  to  declare  itself; 
and  too  prolonged  a  testing  of  a  wrong  trial  may  allow  serious 
damage  to  occur.  The  optimal  duration  of  a  trial  is  clearly  the 
time  taken  by  information  to  travel  from  the  step-mechanisms 
that  initiate  the  trial,  through  the  environment,  to  the  essential 
variable  that  shows  the  outcome.  If  the  ultrastable  system  re- 
quires the  duration  to  be  adjusted,  so  does  the  living  organism;  for 
there  can  be  little  doubt  that  on  many  occasions  living  organisms 
have  missed  success  either  by  abandoning  a  trial  too  quickly,  or 
by  persisting  too  long  with  a  trial  that  was  actually  useless.  (The 
topic  is  referred  to  again  in  S.  17/10.) 

The  same  difficulty,  then,  confronts  both  ultrastable  system  and 
living  organism. 

120 


8/17  THE     IIOMEOSTAT 

8/16.  If  we  grade  an  ultrastable  system's  environments  accord- 
ing to  the  difficulty  they  present,  we  shall  find  that  at  the  '  easy  ' 
end  are  those  that  consist  of  a  few  variables,  independent  of  each 
other,  and  that  at  the  '  difficult  '  end  are  those  that  contain  many 
variables  richly  cross-linked  to  form  a  complex  whole.  (The 
topic  is  developed  from  Chapter  11  on.) 

The  living  organism,  too,  would  classify  environments  in 
essentially  the  same  way.  Not  only  does  common  experience 
show  this,  but  the  construction  and  use  of  '  intelligence  tests  ' 
has  shown  in  endless  ways  that  the  easy  problem  is  the  one 
whose  components  are  few  and  independent,  while  the  difficult 
problem  is  the  one  with  many  components  that  form  a  complex 
whole.  So  when  confronted  with  environments  of  various  '  diffi- 
culties ',  the  ultrastable  system  and  the  living  organism  arc  likely 
to  fail  together. 

8/17.  The  last  few  sections  have  shown,  in  several  ways,  how 
several  '  inadequacies  '  of  the  ultrastable  system  have  made  us 
realise,  on  closer  scrutiny,  the  inadequacies  not  of  the  ultrastable 
system  but  of  the  living  brain.  Clearly  we  must  beware  of  con- 
demning a  proposed  model  for  not  showing  a  certain  property 
until  we  are  sure  that  the  living  organism  really  shows  it. 

Since  this  book  was  first  published,  I  have  often  had  put  to  me 
some  objection  of  the  form  '  Surely  an  ultrastable  system  could 
not  .  .  .  '  When  one  goes  into  the  matter,  it  is  surprising  how 
often  the  reply  proves  to  be  '  No,  and  a  human  being  couldn't  do 
it  either  !  ' 


121 


CHAPTER  9 

Ultrastability  in  the  Organism 

9/1.  In  the  early  sections  of  Chapter  7  we  considered  the  ele- 
mentary behavioural  facts  of  the  kitten  adapting,  and  related 
them  to  a  mechanistic  theoretical  construction,  the  '  ultrastable  ' 
system.  In  the  present  chapter  we  will  consider  some  further 
elementary  relations  between  the  real  organism  and  the  theoretical 
construct.  We  will  consider,  in  particular,  what  can  be  said 
about  the  simple  theoretical  system  shown  in  Figure  7/5/1.  How 
does  it  correspond  to  the  real  organism  and  the  real  environment  ? 
We  must  go  with  caution,  for  experience  has  shown  that  a  jump 
to  conclusions  that  are  grossly  in  error  is  only  too  easy. 

9/2.  We  must  be  particularly  careful  not  to  take  for  granted 
that  a  diagram  of  immediate  effects — that  of  Figure  7/5/1  for 
instance — gives  a  picture  of  what  is  to  be  seen  in  the  nervous 
system.  Just  as  one  real  '  machine  '  can  give  rise  to  a  variety 
of  systems,  so  it  can  give  rise  to  a  variety  of  diagrams  of  immediate 
effects,  if  the  experimenter  examines  the  real  '  machine  '  with  a 
variety  of  different  technical  methods.  An  electrical  network,  for 
instance,  may  give  very  different  diagrams  of  functional  con- 
nexion if  it  is  explored  first  with  slowly  varying  potentials  and 
then  with  potentials  oscillating  at  a  high  frequency.  Sometimes 
it  happens  that  two  techniques  may  give  the  same  diagram — 
exploring  a  metallic  network  firstly  with  direct  currents  and  then 
by  the  sense  of  touch,  say.  When  this  happens  we  are  delighted, 
for  we  have  found  a  simplicity;  but  we  must  not  expect  this  to 
happen  always. 

Many  simple  bodies  have  one  diagram  that  is  so  obtrusive  that 
one  is  apt  to  think  of  it  as  the  specification  of  how  the  parts  are 
joined.  This  is  the  diagram  built  up  by  considering  the  parts' 
positions  in  three-dimensional  space,  and  studying  how  each  part 
moves  when  some  other  part  is  moved.  In  this  way  (using  a 
method  just  the  same  as  that  of  S.  4/12)  scientist  and  man  in 

122 


9/4  ULTRASTABILITY     IN     THE     ORGANISM 

the  street  alike  build  up  their  ideas  of  how  things  are  connected  in 
the  simple  material  or  anatomical  sense.  So  the  child  learns  that 
when  he  picks  up  one  end  of  a  rattle  the  other  end  comes  up  too ; 
and  so  the  demonstrator  of  anatomy  shows  that  if  a  certain  tendon 
in  the  forearm  is  pulled,  the  thumb  moves.  These  operations 
specify  a  diagram  of  immediate  effects,  a  pattern  of  connectivity, 
of  great  commonness  and  importance.  But  we  must  beware  of 
thinking  that  it  is  the  only  pattern;  for  there  are  also  systems 
whose  parts  or  variables  have  no  particular  position  in  space 
relative  to  one  another,  but  are  related  dynamically  in  some 
quite  different  way.  Such  occurs  when  a  mixture  of  substrates, 
enzymes,  and  other  substances  occur  in  a  flask,  and  in  which  the 
variables  are  concentrations.  Then  the  '  system  '  is  a  set  of  con- 
centrations, and  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  shows  how  the 
concentrations  affect  one  another.  Such  a  diagram,  of  course, 
shows  nothing  that  can  be  seen  in  the  distribution  of  matter  in 
space;  it  is  purely  functional.  Nothing  that  has  been  said  so 
far  excludes  the  possibility  that  the  anatomical-looking  Figure 
7 1 5  /l  may  not  be  of  the  latter  type.     We  must  proceed  warily. 

9/3.  The  chief  part  of  Figure  7/5/1  that  calls  for  comment  is  the 
feedback  from  environment,  through  essential  variables  and  step- 
mechanisms,  to  the  reacting  part  R.  The  channel  from  environ- 
ment to  essential  variables  hardly  concerns  us,  for  it  will  depend 
on  the  practical  details  for  the  particular  circumstances  in  which, 
at  any  particular  time,  the  free-living  organism  finds  itself. 

The  essential  variables,  being  determined  by  the  gene-pattern 
(S.  3/14),  will  often  have  some  simple  anatomical  localisation. 
Some  of  them,  for  instance,  are  well  known  to  be  sited  in  the 
medulla  oblongata;  and  others,  such  as  the  signals  for  pain,  are 
known  to  pass  through  certain  sites  in  the  midbrain  and  optic 
thalamus.  More  accurate  identification  of  these  variables  demands 
only  detailed  study. 


Step -mechanisms  in  the  organism 

9/4.  Quite  otherwise  is  it  with  the  step-mechanisms.  We  have 
at  present  practically  no  idea  of  where  to  look,  nor  what  to  look 
for.  In  these  matters  we  must  be  very  careful  to  avoid  making 
assumptions  unwittingly,  for  the  possibilities  are  very  wide. 

123 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN 


9/5 


We  must  beware,  for  instance,  of  asking  where  they  are;  for 
this  question  assumes  that  they  must  be  somewhere,  and  then  the 
1  where  '  is  apt  to  be  interpreted  anatomically,  or  histologically, 
or  in  some  other  way  that  is  not  appropriate  to  the  actual  variable. 
Some  calculating  machines,  for  instance,  carry  their  records  in 
the  form  of  a  train  of  pulses  that  circulates  around  a  cyclic  path 
that  includes  a  long  column  of  mercury.  Each  pulse  behaves  as  a 
step-function  in  that  it  has  only  two  values:  present  or  absent. 
It  is  localised  by  its  position  in  the  sequence,  but  it  has  no  localisa- 
tion in  any  particular  part  of  the  column.  (This  is  the  sort  of 
4  localisation  '  that  the  Fraunhofer  lines  have  as  sunlight  comes  to 
us:  they  occupy  a  definite  place  in  the  spectrum  but  no  unique 
place  in  three-dimensional  space.) 

With  these  warnings  in  mind,  a  brief  review  will  now  be  given 
of  some  of  the  possibilities.  (The  list  is  almost  certainly  not 
complete,  and  at  the  present  time  it  is  probably  most  important 
that  we  should  be  alert  for  forms  not  yet  considered.) 

9/5.  A  possibility  early  suggested  by  Young  was  that  a  closed 
circuit  of  neurons  might  carry  a  stream  of  impulses  and  be  self- 
maintaining  in  this  excited  state.  Unexcited  it  would  stay  at 
rest,  excited  it  would  be  active  maximally;  such  a  system  could 
carry  permanently  the  effects  of  some  event. 

Lorente  de  No  has  provided  abundant  histological  evidence  that 
neurons  form  not  only  chains  but  circuits.     Figure  9/5/1  is  taken 


Figure  9/5/1  : 
reflex  arc. 


Neurons  and  their  connexions  in  the  trigeminal 
(Semi-diagrammatic  ;    from  Lorente  de  No.) 


from  one  of  his  papers.  Such  circuits  are  so  common  that  he  has 
enunciated  a  '  Law  of  Reciprocity  of  Connexions  ' :  *  if  a  cell- 
complex  A  sends  fibres  to  cell  or  cell-complex  B,  then  B  also  sends 
fibres  to  A,  either  direct  or  by  means  of  one  internuncial  neuron  '. 

124 


9/6  ULTRASTABILITY    IN    THE     ORGANISM 

A  simple  circuit,  if  excited,  would  tend  either  to  sink  back  to 
zero  excitation,  if  the  amplification-factor  was  less  than  unity, 
or  to  rise  to  maximal  excitation  if  it  was  greater  than  unity. 
Such  a  circuit  tends  to  maintain  only  two  degrees  of  activity: 
the  inactive  and  the  maximal.  Its  activity  will  therefore  be  of 
step-function  form  if  the  time  taken  by  the  chain  to  build  up  to 
maximal  excitation  can  be  neglected.  Its  critical  states  would 
be  the  smallest  excitation  capable  of  raising  it  to  full  activity, 
and  the  smallest  inhibition  capable  of  stopping  it.  McCulloch 
has  referred  to  such  circuits  as  '  endromes  '  and  has  studied  some 
of  their  properties. 

9/6.  Another  source  of  step-functions  would  be  provided  if 
neurons  were  amoeboid,  so  that  their  processes  could  make  or 
break  contact  with  other  cells. 

That  nerve-cells  are  amoeboid  in  tissue-culture  has  been  known 
since  the  first  observations  of  Harrison.  When  nerve-tissue  from 
chick-embryo  is  grown  in  clotted  plasma,  filaments  grow  outwards 
at  about  0-05  mm.  per  hour.  The  filament  terminates  in  an 
expanded  end,  about  15  X  25/^  in  size,  which  is  actively  amoeboid, 
continually  throwing  out  processes  as  though  exploring  the 
medium  around.  Levi  studied  tissue-cultures  by  micro-dissection, 
so  that  individual  cells  could  be  stimulated.  He  found  that  a 
nerve-cell,  touched  with  the  needle-point,  would  sometimes  throw 
out  processes  by  amoeboid  movement. 

The  conditions  of  tissue-culture  are  somewhat  abnormal,  and 
artefacts  are  common;  but  this  objection  cannot  be  raised  against 
the  work  of  Speidel,  who  observed  nerve-fibres  growing  into  the 
living  tadpole's  tail.  The  ends  of  the  fibres,  like  those  in  the 
tissue-culture,  were  actively  amoeboid.  Later  he  observed  the 
effects  of  metrazol  in  the  same  way:  there  occurred  an  active 
retraction  and,  later,  re-extension.  More  recently  Carey  and 
others  have  studied  the  motor  end-plate.  They  found  that  it, 
too,  is  amoeboid,  for  it  contracted  to  a  ball  after  physical  injury. 

To  react  to  a  stimulus  by  amoeboid  movement  is  perhaps  the 
most  ancient  of  reactions.  So  the  hypothesis  that  neurons  are 
amoeboid  assumes  only  that  they  have  never  lost  their  original 
property.  It  is  possible,  therefore,  that  step-functions  are  pro- 
vided in  this  way. 

125 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  9/7 

9/7.  Every  cell  contains  many  variables  that  might  change  in 
a  way  approximating  to  the  step-function  form,  especially  if  the 
time  of  observation  is  long  compared  with  the  average  time  of 
cellular  events.  Monomolecular  films,  protein  solutions,  enzyme 
systems,  concentrations  of  hydrogen  and  other  ions,  oxidation- 
reduction  potentials,  adsorbed  layers,  and  many  other  constituents 
or  processes  might  act  as  step-mechanisms. 

If  the  cell  is  sufficiently  sensitive  to  be  affected  by  changes  of 
atomic  size,  then  such  changes  might  be  of  step-function  form, 
for  they  could  change  only  by  a  quantum  jump.  But  this  source 
of  step-functions  is  probably  unavailable,  for  changes  of  this 
size  may  be  too  indeterminate  for  the  production  of  the  regular 
and  reproducible  behaviour  considered  in  this  book  (S.  1/14). 

Round  the  neuron,  and  especially  round  its  dendrons  and  axons, 
there  is  a  sensitive  membrane  that  might  provide  step-functions, 
though  the  membrane  is  probably  wholly  employed  in  the  trans- 
mission of  the  action  potential.  Nerve  '  fibrils  '  have  been  des- 
cribed for  many  years,  though  the  possibility  that  they  are  an  arte- 
fact cannot  yet  be  excluded.  If  they  are  real  their  extreme 
delicacy  of  structure  suggests  that  they  might  behave  as  step- 
functions. 

The  delicacy  everywhere  evident  in  the  nervous  system  has 
often  been  remarked.  This  delicacy  must  surely  imply  the 
existence  of  step-functions ;  for  the  property  of  being  '  delicate  ' 
can  mean  little  other  than  '  easily  broken  ' ;  and  it  was  observed 
in  S.  7/19  that  the  phenomenon  of  something  '  breaking  '  is  the 
expression  of  a  step-function  changing  value.  Though  the  argu- 
ment is  largely  verbal,  it  gives  some  justification  for  the  opinion 
that  step-mechanisms  are  by  no  means  unlikely  in  the  nervous 
system. 

'  The  idea  of  a  steady,  continuous  development  ',  said 
Jacques  Loeb,  '  is  inconsistent-  with  the  general  physical 
qualities  of  protoplasm  or  colloidal  material.  The  colloidal 
substances  in  our  protoplasm  possess  critical  points.  .  . 
The  colloids  change  their  state  very  easily,  and  a  number  of 
conditions  .  .  .  are  able  to  bring  about  a  change  in  their 
state.  Such  material  lends  itself  very  readily  to  a  discon- 
tinuous series  of  changes. ' 


126 


9/9  ULTRA  STABILITY      IN     THE     ORGANISM 

A  molecular  basis  for  memory? 

9/8.  What  is  necessary  that  any  material  entity  should  serve  as  a 
step-mechanism  in  ultrastability  ?  Only  that  it  should  be  a 
step-mechanism,  that  it  should  be  able  to  be  changed  by  the 
essentia]  variables,  and  that  it  should  have  an  effective  action  on 
the  reacting  part   R. 

As  a  dynamic  system,  the  brain  is  so  extremely  sensitive,  and 
is  such  a  powerful  amplifier,  that  we  can  hardly  put  a  limit  to  the 
smallness  of  a  physical  change  that  still  has  a  major  effect  in 
behaviour.  Even  a  change  on  a  single  molecule  cannot  be  dis- 
missed as  ineffective,  for  many  events  in  the  nervous  system 
depend  critically  on  how  some  variable  is  related  to  a  threshold; 
and  near  the  threshold  a  small  change  may  have  great  con- 
sequences. 

It  is  therefore  not  impossible  that  molecular  events  should 
provide  the  step-functions.  There  are  plenty  of  events  that 
might  provide  such  forms:  whether  a  molecule  is  in  the  dextro- 
or  the  laevo-  state,  in  the  cis-  or  trans-  state;  whether  a  hydrogen 
bond  does  or  does  not  exist;  whether  a  double  bond  between 
carbon  atoms  lies  in  this  plane  or  that;  and  so  on.  Such  bases 
would  have  the  advantage  in  the  living  organism  of  providing  the 
necessary  function  at  a  minimal  cost  in  weight  and  bulk,  matters 
of  considerable  importance  to  the  free-living  organism. 

Pauling  has  discussed  these  possibilities  and  has  suggested 
limits  that  would  narrow  the  field  of  search.  If  the  molecular 
entity  is  too  small,  thermal  agitation  will  prevent  it  from  showing 
the  constancy  which  it  must  have  if  it  is  to  act  as  basis  for  such 
behaviour  as  that  of  Skinner's  pigeons  (S.  1/14).  If  too  large,  it 
will  be  unsuitable  for  the  miracle  of  '  miniaturisation  '  that  has 
actually  been  achieved  in  the  mammalian  brain. 

9/9.  With  all  these  possible  forms  of  step-mechanism  in  mind, 
it  is  difficult  for  us  to  say  much  that  is  definite  about  the  feedback 
channels  from  essential  variable  through  step-mechanisms  to  the 
reacting  part  R  of  Figure  7/5/1.  Clearly  there  is  not  the  least 
necessity  for  the  channels  to  consist  of  anatomical  or  histological 
tracts ;  for  if  the  step-mechanisms  were  molecular,  the  channel  to 
them  might  be  biochemical  or  hormonic  in  nature;  while  the 
channel  from  them  to  R  might  be  extremely  short,  and  of  almost 

127 


DESIGN    FOR    A    BRAIN  9/10 

any  nature,  if  they  were  sited  inside  the  neurons  in  which  they 
exerted  their  action. 

Evidently  much  more  knowledge  will  be  necessary  before  we 
can  identify  accurately  this  part  of  the  second-order  feedback. 
What  is  most  important  at  the  present  time  is  that  we  should 
avoid  unwittingly  taking  for  granted  what  has  yet  to  be  demon- 
strated. 


Are  step-mechanisms  necessary  ? 

9/10.  Since  S.  7/12  we  have  been  considering  adaptation  when 
the  variables  affecting  the  reacting  part  R  of  Figure  7/5/1  behave 
as  step-functions.  The  justification  given  then  was  that  this  case 
is  of  central  theoretic  importance  because  of  its  peculiar  simplicity 
and  clarity:  even  if  the  nervous  system  contained  no  step- 
mechanisms,  the  student  of  the  subject  would  still  find  considera- 
tion of  this  form  helpful  to  get  a  clear  grasp  of  how  a  nervous 
system  can  adapt.  But  is  there  no  justification  stronger  than 
this  ?  Does  the  evidence,  perhaps,  prove  that  the  process  of 
adaptation  implies  the  existence  of  step-mechanisms  ? 

9/11.  We  have  already  seen  (S.  7/16)  that  even  so  typical  a 
mechanism  as  a  Post  Office  relay  cannot  be  said  to  be  (uncondi- 
tionally) a  step-mechanism,  for  some  ways  of  observing  it  (e.g. 
over  microseconds  or  over  years)  do  not  show  this  form;  and  no 
particular  mode  of  observation  can  claim  absolute  priority.  Thus 
even  if  some  object  in  a  Black  Box  gave  convincing  evidence  that 
it  was  a  Post  Office  relay,  the  observer  still  could  not  claim  that 
the  real  object  was  a  step-mechanism  unconditionally. 

9/12.  On  the  other  hand,  contrasted  with  a  full-function  the 
step-function  has  a  remarkable  simplicity  of  behaviour,  and  not 
every  real  object  can  be  made  to  show  such  a  simplicity.  To 
say  of  the  object  in  the  Black  Box  that  it  can  be  made  to  show 
behaviour  of  step-function  type  is  thus  to  say  something  un- 
conditionally true  about  it. 

Again,  if  a  system  of  three  variables  is  studied  and  found  to 
produce  such  a  field  as  that  of  Figure  7/20/1  (in  which  three 
possible  dimensions  are  reduced  to  two  two-dimensional  planes), 
then  again  the  observer  can  claim  that  he  has  demonstrated  some- 

128 


9/13  ULTRASTABILITY     IN     THE     ORGANISM 

thing  special,  in  the  sense  that  the  fully  three-dimensional  fields 
(e.g.  that  of  Figure  3/5/2)  cannot  be  reduced  to  the  simple  form. 
Thus  certain  behaviours,  though  they  do  not  permit  the  deduc- 
tion that  they  are  due  to  something  that  is  a  step-mechanism, 
may  none  the  less  permit  the  deduction  that  they  are  produced 
by  some  entity  with  the  special  property  that  its  behaviour  can 
be  reduced  to  step-function  form;  and  the  latter  is  a  meaningful 
statement,  for  not  all  entities  produce  behaviour  that  can  be  so 
reduced. 

9/13.  What  of  the  nervous  system  ?  If  the  variables  in  S  (of 
Figure  7/5/1)  were  to  vary  as  full-functions,  the  observer  would 
see  only  one  very  complex  system  moving  by  a  complex  continuous 
trajectory  to  an  eventual  equilibrium.  Often,  however,  he 
observes  that  the  organism  '  makes  a  trial  ',  i.e.  produces  some 
recognisable  form  of  behaviour  and  then  persists  in  this  way  of 
behaving  for  some  appreciable  time.  Then  the  trial  is  aban- 
doned, a  new  way  of  behaving  occurs,  and  this  too  is  persisted  in 
for  an  appreciable  time;  and  so  on. 

When  this  happens,  the  observer  may  justly  claim  that  the 
system  is  showing  less  than  its  full  complexity;  for,  through  the 
duration  of  the  trial,  the  fact  that  it  is  persisting  as  this  particular 
form  of  trial  means  that  some  redundancy  is  occurring.  The 
redundancy  is  similar  to  that  of  the  sequence  of  letters  that  goes, 
e.g. 

FFFFFLLLLLLLTTTTTJJJJJJJ 

rather  than  with  full  variety: 

EJYMSNASGCGHLAAPEYPJVRQJ 

Within  each  trial,  if  it  shows  a  characteristic  way  of  behaving, 
there  will  be  defined  a  field ;  and  these  fields  will  follow  one  another 
in  a  discrete  succession,  as  in  Figure  7/23/1.  When  this  occurs, 
if  the  observer  is  willing  to  assume  that  the  changes  of  field  are 
occurring  in  a  state-determined  whole,  he  may  legitimately  deduce 
that  the  parameters  responsible  for  the  changes  from  field  to  field 
are  of  such  a  nature,  and  so  joined  to  the  main  variables,  that 
they  may  be  represented  by  step-functions  (for  full-functions 
could  not  give  the  discrete  movement  from  distinct  trial  to  distinct 
trial).  That  they  may  be  so  represented  is  a  meaningful  restriction 
on  their  nature. 

If  now  we  couple  this  deduction  with  what  has  been  called 

129 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  9/14 

Dancoff  s  principle — that  systems  made  efficient  by  natural  selec- 
tion will  not  use  variety  or  channel  capacity  much  in  excess  of 
the  minimum — then  we  can  deduce  that  when  organisms  regularly 
use  the  method  of  trials  there  is  strong  presumptive  (though  not 
conclusive)  evidence  that  their  trials  will  be  controlled  by  material 
entities  having  (relative  to  the  rest  of  the  system)  not  much  more 
than  the  minimal  variety.  There  is  therefore  strong  presumptive 
evidence  that  the  significant  variables  in  S  (of  Figure  7/5/1)  are 
step-functions,  and  that  the  material  entities  embodying  them  are 
of  such  a  nature  as  will  easily  show  such  functional  forms. 


Levels  of  feedback 

9/14.  We  can  next  consider  how  the  formulation  of  Chapter  7, 
and  Figure  7/5/1,  compares  with  the  real  organism's  organisation 
in  respect  of  the  division  of  the  feedbacks  into  two  clearly  dis- 
tinguishable orders:  between  organism  and  environment  by  the 
usual  sensory  and  motor  channels,  and  that  passing  through  the 
essential  variables  and  step-mechanisms  to  the  reacting  part  R. 

Chapter  7  followed  the  strategy  described  in  S.  2/17:  we 
attempted  to  get  a  type-system  perfectly  clear,  so  that  it  would 
act  as  a  suitable  reference  for  many  real  systems  that  do  not 
correspond  to  it  exactly.  To  get  a  clear  case  we  assumed  that 
the  system  (organism  and  environment  joined)  was  subject  to 
just  two  types  of  disturbance  from  outside.  Of  one  type  is  the 
impulsive  disturbance  to  the  system's  main  variables ;  by  this  their 
state  is  displaced  to  some  non-equilibrial  position;  this  happens  if 
a  Homeostat's  needle  is  pushed  away  from  the  centre,  as  at  Dx 
in  Figure  8/4/1 ;  or  if  the  fire  by  the  kitten  suddenly  blazes  up. 
Then  the  organism,  if  adapted,  demonstrates  its  adaptation  by 
taking  the  action  appropriate  to  the  new  state.  A  number  of 
such  impulsive  disturbances,  each  with  an  interval  for  reaction 
to  occur,  are  necessary  if  the  organism's  adaptation  is  to  be  tested 
and  demonstrated. 

Of  the  other  type  is  the  disturbance  in  which  some  parameter 
to  the  whole  system  is  changed  (from  the  value  it  had  over  the 
many  impulsive  disturbances,  to  some  new  value).  This  change 
stands  in  quite  a  different  relation  to  the  system  from  the  change 
implied  by  the  impulse.  Whereas  the  impulse  made  the  system 
demonstrate  its  stability,  the  change  at  the  parameter  made  the 

130 


9/16  ULTRASTABILITY     IN     THE     ORGANISM 

system  demonstrate  (if  possible)  its  ultrastability.  Whereas  the 
system  demonstrates,  after  the  impulse,  its  power  of  returning  to 
the  state  of  equilibrium,  it  demonstrates,  after  the  change  of 
parameter-value,  its  power  of  returning  the  field  (of  its  main 
variables)  to  a  stable  form.  The  ultrastable  system  is  thus  the 
appropriate'  form  for  the  organism  if  the  disturbances  that  come 
to  it  from  the  world  around  fall  into  two  clearly  defined  classes: 

(1)  Frequent  (or  even  continuous)  small  impulsive  disturbances 

to  the  main  variables. 

(2)  Occasional  changes,  of  step-function  form,  to  its  parameters. 

The  ultrastable  system  is  thus  not  merely  a  didactic  device; 
it  may,  in  some  cases,  actually  be  the  optimal  mechanism  by  which 
an  organism  can  ensure  its  survival.  When  the  disturbances  that 
threaten  the  organism  have,  over  many  generations,  had  the  bi-modal 
form  just  described,  we  may  expect  to  find  that  the  organism  will, 
under  natural  selection,  have  developed  a  form  fairly  close  to  the 
ultrastable,  in  that  it  will  have  developed  two  readily  distinguishable 
feedbacks. 

9/15.  It  is  not  for  a  moment  suggested  that  all  natural  stimuli, 
disturbances,  and  problems  come  to  kittens  in  the  tidily  dichoto- 
mous  way  in  which  we  have  brought  them  to  the  Homeostat. 
Neither  is  it  suggested  that  the  real  brain  can  always  be  viewed  as 
ultrastable,  if  only  we  can  find  the  right  way  of  approach.  On 
the  contrary,  it  is  only  when  we  scientists  are  fortunate  that  we 
will  find  that  a  complex  system  can  be  reduced  conceptually  into 
manageable  subsystems,  as  the  Homeostat  is  reducible  into  its 
continuous  part  with  feedbacks  between  the  needles,  and  its 
stepwise  varying  part  around  the  second  feedback.  If  there  are 
many  feedback  loops,  and  there  is  no  convenient  way  of  indi- 
vidualising them,  then  simplicity  is  not  to  be  had,  and  there  is 
nothing  for  it  but  to  treat  the  system  as  one  whole,  of  high  com- 
plexity. (The  subject  is  discussed  from  Chapter  11  through  the 
remainder  of  the  book.) 

The  control  of  aim 

9/16.  The  ultrastable  systems  discussed  so  far,  though  develop- 
ing a  variety  of  fields,  have  sought  a  constant  goal.  The  Homeo- 
stat sought  central  positions  and  the  rat  sought  zero  grill-potential. 

131 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


9/16 


In  this  section  will  be  described  some  methods  by  which  the 
goal  may  be  varied.  Variations  in  the  goal  will  be  important  in 
those  cases  in  which  the  goal  is  only  a  sub-goal,  sought  temporarily 
or  provisionally  for  the  achievement  of  some  other  goal  that  is 
permanent  (S.  3/15). 

If  the  critical  states'  distribution  in  the  main-variables'  phase- 
space  is  altered  by  any  means  whatever,  the  ultrastable  system 
will  be  altered  in  the  goal  it  seeks.  For  the  ultrastable  system 
will  always  develop  a  field  which  keeps  the  representative  point 
within  the  region  of  the  critical  states  (S.  7/23).  Thus  if  (Figure 
9/16/1)  for  some  reason  the  critical  states  moved  to  surround  B 


JO- 


S' 


10 


2Q 


U 


Figure  9/16/1. 

instead  of  A,  then  the  terminal  field  would  change  from  one  which 
kept  x  between  0  and  5  to  one  which  kept  x  between  15  and  20. 
A  related  method  is  illustrated  by  Figure  9/16/2.  An  ultra- 
stable  system  U  interacts  with  a  variable  A. 
E  and  R  represent  the  immediate  effects  which 
U  and  A  have  on  each  other;  they  may  be 
thought  of  as  C/'s  effectors  and  receptors.  If  A 
should  have  a  marked  effect  on  the  ultrastable 
system,  the  latter  will,  of  course,  develop  a  field 
stabilising  A ;  at  what  value  will  depend  markedly 
on  the  action  of  R.  Suppose,  for  instance,  that 
U  has  its  critical  states  all  at  values  0  and  10,  so 
that  it  always  selects  a  field  stabilising  all  its 
main  variables  between  these  values.  If  R  is  such  that,  if  A 
has  some  value  «,  R  transmits  to  U  the  value  5a  —  20,  then 
it  is  easy  to  see  that  U  will  develop  a  field  holding  A  within 
one  unit  of  the  value  5;  for  if  the  field  makes  A  go  outside  the 
range  4  to  6,  it  will  make  U  go  outside  the  range  0  to  10,  and 

132 


Figure    9/16/2. 


9/16  ULTRASTABILITY     IN     THE     ORGANISM 

this  will  destroy  the  field.  So  U  becomes  '  5-seeking  '.  If  the 
action  of  R  is  now  changed  to  transmitting,  not  5a  —  20  but 
5a  +  5,  then  U  will  change  fields  until  it  holds  A  within  one 
unit  of  0;  and  U  is  now  '  0-seeking'.  So  anything  that  controls 
the  b  in  R  =  5a  +  b  controls  the  '  goal  '  sought  by  U. 

As  a  more  practical  example,  suppose  U  is  mobile  and  is 
ultrastable,  with  its  critical  states  set  so  that  it  seeks  situations 
of  high  illumination;  such  would  occur  if  its  critical  states 
resembled,  in  Figure  9/16/1,  B  rather  than  A.  Suppose  too  that 
R  is  a  ray  of  light.  If  in  the  path  of  R  we  place  a  red  colour- 
filter,  then  green  light  will  count  as  '  no  light  '  and  the  system 
will  actively  seek  the  red  places  and  avoid  the  green.  If  now 
we  merely  replace  the  red  filter  by  a  green,  the  whole  aim  of 
its  movements  will  be  altered,  for  it  will  now  seek  the  green 
places  and  avoid  the  red. 

Next,  suppose  R  is  a  transducer  that  converts  a  temperature 
at  A  into  an  illumination  which  it  transmits  to  U.  If  R  is 
arranged  so  that  a  high  temperature  at  A  is  converted  into  a  high 
illumination,  then  U  will  become  actively  goal-seeking  for  hot 
places.  And  if  the  relation  within  R  is  reversed,  U  will  seek 
for  cold  places.     Clearly,  whatever  controls  R  controls  C/'s  goal. 

There  is  therefore  in  general  no  difficulty  in  accounting  for 
the  fact  that  a  system  may  seek  one  goal  at  one  time  and  another 
goal  at  another  time. 

Sometimes  the  change,  of  critical  states  or  of  the  transducer 
R.  may  be  under  the  control  of  a  single  parameter.  When  this 
happens  we  must  distinguish  two  complexities.  Suppose  the 
parameter  can  take  only  two  values  and  the  system  U  is  very 
complicated.  Then  the  system  is  simple  in  the  sense  that  it 
will  seek  one  of  only  two  goals,  and  is  complicated  in  the  sense 
that  the  behaviour  with  which  it  gets  to  the  goal  is  complicated. 
That  the  behaviour  is  complicated  is  no  proof,  or  even  sugges- 
tion, that  the  parameter's  relations  to  the  system  must  be  com- 
plicated; for,  as  was  shown  in  S.  6/3,  the  number  of  fields  is 
equal  to  the  number  of  values  the  parameter  can  take,  and  has 
nothing  to  do  with  the  number  of  main  variables.  It  is  this 
latter  that  determines,  in  general,  the  complexity  of  the  goal- 
seeking  behaviour. 

These  considerations  may  clarify  the  relations  between  the 
change   of  concentration   of  a  sex-hormone  in  the   blood   of  a 

133 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  9/17 

mammal  and  its  consequent  sexual  goal-seeking  behaviour.  A 
simple  alternation  between  '  present  '  and  '  absent  ',  or  between 
two  levels  with  a  threshold,  would  be  sufficient  to  account  for 
any  degree  of  complexity  in  the  two  behaviours,  for  the  com- 
plexity is  not  to  be  related  to  the  hormone-parameter  but  to  the 
nervous  system  that  is  affected  by  it.  Since  the  mammalian 
nervous  system  is  extremely  complex,  and  since  it  is,  at  almost 
every  point,  sensitive  to  both  physical  and  chemical  influences, 
there  seems  to  be  no  reason  to  suppose  that  the  directiveness  of 
the  sex-hormones  on  the  brain's  behaviour  is  essentially  different 
from  that  of  any  parameter  on  the  system  it  controls.  (That 
the  sex-hormones  evoke  specifically  sexual  behaviour  is,  of  course, 
explicable  by  the  fact  that  evolution,  through  natural  selection, 
has  constructed  specific  mechanisms  that  react  to  the  hormone 
in  the  specific  way.) 


The  gene-pattern  and  ultrastability 

9/17.  We  can  now  return  to  the  questions  of  S.  1/9  and  ask 
what  part  is  played  by  the  gene-pattern  in  the  determination  of 
the  process  of  adaptation. 

Taking  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  (Figure  7/5/1)  as 
basis,  the  question  is  answerable  without  difficulty  if  we  take  the 
system  part  by  part  and  channel  by  channel. 

The  environment  is,  of  course,  assumed  to  be  given  arbitrarily; 
so  is  the  channel  by  which  the  environment  affects  the  essential 
variables  (S.  7/3).  The  essential  variables  and  their  limits  are 
determined  by  the  gene-pattern  (S.  3/14);  for  these  are  species' 
characteristics. 

In  the  living  organism,  the  reacting  part  R  has,  in  effect,  three 
types  of  '  input  ' :  there  is  the  sensory  input  from  the  environment, 
there  are  the  values  of  its  parameters  in  S,  and  there  are  those 
parameters  that  were  determined  genetically  during  embryonic 
development.  (That  all  three  may  be  regarded  as  '  input  '  has 
been  shown  in  /.  to  C,  S.  13/11).  These  three  sets  of  parameters 
vary  on  very  different  time-scales:  the  genetic  parameters,  those 
that  make  this  a  dog-brain  and  that  a  bird-brain,  are  in  evidence 
only  at  one  period  in  a  lifetime ;  the  parameters  in  S,  if  the  adapta- 
tion proceeds  by  clearly  marked  trials,  change  only  between  trial 
and  trial;  and  the  parameters  at  the  sensory  input  vary  more  or 

134 


9/18  ULTRA  STABILITY     IN     THE     ORGANISM 

less  continuously.  The  influence  of  the  gene-pattern  can  thus  be 
traced  in  R,  giving  it  certain  anatomical  tracts,  biochemical  pro- 
cesses, histological  structures,  and  thus  determining  whether  it 
shall  adapt  as  a  dog  does  or  as  a  starfish  does. 

The  nature  of  the  parameters  in  S  is  wholly  under  genetic 
control,  for  their  physical  .embodiment  has  probably  been  selected 
for  suitability  by  natural  selection.  (Here  the  nature  of  the 
parameters — whether  they  are  reverberating  circuits,  or  molecular 
configurations,  etc. — must  be  clearly  distinguished  from  the  values 
that  any  one  parameter  may  take.) 

Finally  there  is  the  relation  between  the  essential  variables  and 
those  in  S — that  the  essential  variables  must  force  those  in  S  to 
change  when  the  essential  variables  are  outside  their  physiological 
limits,  and  not  to  change  otherwise  (S.  7/7).  As  this  relation  is 
entirely  ad  hoc,  it  must  be  determined  by  the  gene-pattern,  for 
there  is  no  other  source  for  its  selection. 

These  are  the  ways,  then,  in  which  the  gene-pattern  must  act 
as  determinant  to  the  living  organism's  mechanism  for  adaptation. 

9/18.  A  question  that  must  be  answered  is  whether  ultrasta- 
bility,  as  described  here,  can  reasonably  be  supposed  to  have  been 
developed  by  natural  selection;  for  the  ad  hoc  features  of  the 
previous  section  have  no  other  determinant  adequate  for  their 
selection  and  adjustment. 

For  ultrastability  to  have  been  developed  by  natural  selection, 
it  is  necessary  and  sufficient  that  there  should  exist  a  sequence  of 
forms,  from  the  simplest  to  the  most  complex,  such  that  each  form 
has  better  survival-value  than  that  before  it.  In  other  words, 
ultrastability  must  not  become  of  value  to  the  organism  only 
when  some  complex  form  has  all  its  parts  and  relations  correct 
simultaneously,  for  such  an  event  occurs  only  rarely. 

Suppose  the  original  organism  had  no  step-mechanisms;  such  an 
organism  would  have  a  permanent,  invariable  set  of  reactions. 
If  a  mutation  should  lead  to  the  formation  of  a  single  step-mech- 
anism whose  critical  states  were  such  that,  when  the  organism 
became  distressed,  it  changed  value  before  the  essential  variables 
transgressed  their  limits,  and  if  the  step-mechanism  affected  in  any 
way  the  reaction  between  the  organism  and  the  environment, 
then  such  a  step-mechanism  might  increase  the  organism's  chance 
of  survival.     A  single  mutation  causing  a  single  step-mechanism 

135 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  9/19 

might  therefore  prove  advantageous;  and  this  advantage,  though 
slight,  might  be  sufficient  to  establish  the  mutation  as  a  species 
characteristic.  Then  a  second  mutation  might  continue  the  pro- 
cess. The  change  from  the  original  system  to  the  ultras  table 
can  therefore  be  made  by  a  long  series  of  small  changes,  each 
of  which  improves  the  chance  of  survival.  The  change  is  thus 
possible  under  the  action  of  natural  selection. 


Summary 

9/19.  The  solution  of  the  problem  of  Chapter  1  is  now  completed 
in  its  essentials.     It  may  be  summarised  as  follows: 

In  the  type-problem  of  S.  1/17  the  disturbances  that  come  to 
the  organism  are  of  two  widely  different  types  (the  distribution 
is  bi-modal).  One  type  is  small,  frequent,  impulsive,  and  acts  on 
the  main  variables.  The  other  is  large,  infrequent,  and  induces  a 
change  of  step-function  form  on  the  parameters  to  the  reacting 
part.  Included  in  the  latter  type  is  the  major  disturbance  of 
embryogenesis,  which  first  sends  the  organism  into  the  world  with 
a  brain  sufficiently  disorganised  to  require  correction  (in  this 
respect,  learning  and  adaptation  are  related,  for  the  same  solution 
is  valid  for  both). 

To  such  a  distribution  of  disturbances  the  appropriate  regulator 
(to  keep  the  essential  variables  within  physiological  limits)  is  one 
whose  total  feedbacks  fall  into  a  correspondingly  bi-modal  form. 
There  will  be  feedbacks  to  give  stability  against  the  frequent 
impulsive  disturbances  to  the  main  variables,  and  there  will  be  a 
slower-acting  feedback  giving  changes  of  step-function  form  to 
give  stability  against  the  infrequent  disturbances  of  step-function 
form. 

Such  a  whole  can  be  regarded  simply  as  one  complex  regulator 
that  is  stable  against  a  complex  (bi-modal)  set  of  disturbances. 
Or  it  can  equivalently  be  regarded  as  a  first-order  regulator 
(against  the  small  impulsive  disturbances)  that  can  reorganise 
itself  to  achieve  this  stability  after  the  disturbance  of  embryo- 
genesis  or  after  a  major  change  in  its  conditions  has  destroyed  this 
stability.  When  the  biologist  regards  the  system  in  this  second 
way,  he  says  that  the  organism  has  '  learned  ',  and  he  notices  that 
the  learning  always  tends  towards  the  better  way  of  behaving 

136 


9/20  ULTRASTABILITY     IN    THE     ORGANISM 

9/20.  Such  is  the  solution  in  outline.  The  reader,  however,  may 
well  feel  that  the  amount  of  information  given  by  the  solution  is 
small. 

To  some  extent,  the  generality  of  the  ultrastable  system,  the 
degree  to  which  it  does  not  specify  details,  is  correct.  Adaptation 
can  be  shown  by  systems  far  wider  in  extent  than  the  mammalian 
and  cerebral,  and  any  proposed  solution  would  manifestly  be 
wrong  if  it  stated  that,  say,  myelin  was  necessary,  when  the 
Homeostat  obviously  contains  none.  Thus  the  generality,  or  if 
you  will  the  vagueness,  of  the  ultrastable  system  is,  from  that  point 
of  view,  as  it  should  be. 

However,  the  attempt  to  apply  this  general  formulation  to  the 
real  nervous  system  soon  encounters  major  difficulties.  What 
these  are,  and  how  they  are  to  be  treated,  will  occupy  the  remainder 
of  the  book. 


137 


CHAPTER   10 

The  Recurrent  Situation 

10/1.  With  the  previous  chapter  we  came  to  the  end  of  our 
study  of  how  the  organism  changes  from  the  unadapted  to  the 
adapted  condition.  But  this  simple  problem  and  solution  is  only 
a  first  step  towards  our  understanding  of  the  living,  and  especially 
of  the  human,  brain.  To  the  simple  ultrastable  system  we  must 
obviously  add  further  complications.  Thus  the  living  organism 
not  only  becomes  adapted,  but  it  does  so  by  a  process  that  shows 
some  evidence  of  efficiency,  in  the  sense  that  the  adaptation  is 
reached  by  a  path  that  is  not  grossly  far  from  the  path  that  would 
involve  the  least  time,  and  energy,  and  risk.  Though  '  efficiency  ' 
is  not  yet  accurately  defined  in  this  context,  few  would  deny  that 
the  Homeostat's  performance  suggests  something  of  inefficiency. 
But  before  we  rush  in  to  make  4  improvements  '  we  must  be  clear 
about  what  we  are  assuming. 

10/2.  Let  us  return  to  first  principles.  '  Success  \  or  '  adapta- 
tion ',  means  to  an  organism  that,  in  spite  of  the  world  doing  its 
worst,  the  organism  so  responded  that  it  survived  for  the  duration 
necessary  for  reproduction. 

Now  i  what  the  world  did  '  can  be  regarded  as  a  single,  life- 
long, and  very  complex  Grand  Disturbance  (7.  to  C,  Chapter  10), 
to  which  the  organism  produces  a  single,  life-long,  and  very 
complex  Grand  Response;  how  they  are  related  determines  the 
Grand  Outcome — success  or  failure.  In  the  most  general  case, 
the  partial  disturbances  that  make  up  this  Grand  Disturbance, 
and  the  partial  responses  that  make  up  the  organism's  Grand 
Response  (I.  to  C,  S.  13/8)  may  be  interrelated  to  any  degree, 
from  zero  to  complete.  (The  interrelation  is  '  complete  '  when  the 
Grand  Outcome  is  a  function  of  all  the  partial  responses;  it  would 
correspond  to  an  extremely  complex  relation  between  partial 
responses  and  final  outcome.) 

The  case  of  the  complete  interrelation,  though  fundamental 

138 


10/4  THE     RECURRENT     SITUATION 

theoretically  (because  of  its  complete  generality),  is  of  little 
importance  in  practice,  for  its  occurrence  in  the  terrestrial  world 
is  rare  (though  it  may  occur  more  commonly  in  models  or  in  pro- 
cesses of  adaptation  set  up  in  large  computers).  Were  it  common, 
a  brain  would  be  useless  (/.  to  C,  S.  13/5).  In  fact,  brains  have 
been  developed  because  the  terrestrial  environment  usually  con- 
fronts the  organism  with  a  Grand  Disturbance  that  has  a  major 
degree  of  constraint  within  its  component  parts,  of  which  the 
organism  can  take  advantage.  Thus  the  organism  commonly 
faces  a  world  that  repeats  itself,  that  is  consistent  to  some  degree 
in  obeying  laws,  that  is  not  wholly  chaotic.  The  greater  the 
degree  of  constraint,  the  more  can  the  adapting  organism  specialise 
against  the  particular  forms  of  environment  thsft  do  occur.  As 
it  specialises  so  will  its  efficiency  against  the  particular  form  of 
environment  increase.  If  the  reader  feels  the  ultrastable  system, 
as  described  so  far,  to  be  extremely  low  in  efficiency,  this  is  because 
it  is  as  yet  quite  unspecialised ;  and  the  reader  is  evidently  uncon- 
sciously pitting  it  against  a  set  of  environments  that  he  has 
restricted  in  some  way  not  yet  stated  explicitly  in  this  book. 

10/3.  The  chapters  that  follow  will  consider  several  constraints 
of  outstanding  commonness  and  will  show  how  the  appropriate 
specialisations  exemplify  the  above  propositions  in  several  ways. 
They  will  consider  certain  ways  in  which  the  ordinary  terrestrial 
environments  fail  to  show  the  full  range ;  and  we  will  see  how  these 
restrictions  indicate  ways  in  which  the  living  organism  can 
specialise  so  as  to  take  advantage  of  them. 


The  recurrent  situation 

10/4.  In  this  chapter  we  will  consider  the  case,  of  great  importance 
in  real  life,  in  which  the  occasional  disturbances  (class"  2  of  S.  9/14) 
are  sometimes  repetitive,  and  in  which  a  response,  if  adaptive  on 
the  disturbance's  first  appearance,  is  also  adaptive  when  the  same 
disturbance  appears  for  the  second,  third,  and  later  times. 

We  must  not  take  for  granted  that  one  response  will  be  adaptive 
to  all  occurrences  of  the  disturbance,  for  there  are  cases  in  which 
what  is  appropriate  to  a  disturbance  depends  on  how  many  times 
it  has  appeared  before.  An  outstanding  example  is  given  by  the 
rat  facing  that  environment  (a  natural  one  by  S.  3/1)  in  which  food 

139 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  10/5 

will  appear  on  two  successive  nights  at  the  same  place,  followed, 
on  the  third  night,  by  a  lethal  mixture  of  the  same  food  and  poison 
(the  method  of  '  pre-baiting  ').  Environments  such  as  this  are 
intrinsically  complex.  Complete  adaptation  here  (under  the 
assumptions  made)  demands  the  reaction-pattern:  eat,  eat, 
abstain.  This  reaction-pattern  is  more  complex  than  the  simple 
reaction-pattern  of  eating,  or  of  abstaining:  for  the  three  parts 
must  be  related,  and  the  triple  organised  holistically. 

In  this  chapter  we  shall  consider  the  other  case,  of  frequent 
occurrence,  in  which  what  is  appropriate  to  the  disturbance  is 
conditional  on  which  disturbance  it  is,  but  not  on  when  it  occurs 
in  the  sequence  of  disturbances. 

So  far,  the  ultrastable  system  (represented,  say,  by  the  Homeo- 
stat)  has  been  presented  (e.g.  in  the  Figures  throughout  Chapter  8) 
with  changes  of  parameter-value  such  that  the  later  value  is 
merely  different  from  the  earlier;  now  we  consider  the  case  in 
which  the  parameter  takes  a  sequence  of  values,  e.g. 

in  which  repetitions  occur  at  irregular  intervals,  and  in  which  a 
response  to  P2,  say,  if  adaptive  on  P2s  first  occurrence,  is  also 
adaptive  to  P2  on  its  later  occurrences. 

When  this  is  the  case,  the  opportunity  exists  for  advantage  to 
be  taken  of  the  fact  that  P2  can  be  responded  to  at  once  on  its 
later  occurrences,  without  the  necessity  of  a  second  exploratory 
series  of  trials  and  errors. 

This  case  is  particularly  important  because  (S.  8/10)  it  includes 
the  case  in  which  the  changes  of  P-value  correspond  to  changes 
from  one  environment  to  another.  Suppose,  for  instance,  that  a 
wild  rat  learns  first  to  adapt  to  conditions  in  a  stable  {P2),  then 
to  conditions  in  a  nearby  barn  (P3),  and  so  on.  Haying  adapted 
first  to  the  stable  and  then  to  the  barn,  its  survival  value  would 
obviously  be  enhanced  if  it  could  return  to  the  stable  and  at  once 
resume  the  adaptations  that  it  had  previously  developed  there. 
An  organism  with  such  a  power  can  accumulate  adaptations. 

10/5.  To  see  what  is  necessary,  let  us  see  what  happens  in  the 
Homeostat.  A  little  reflection,  or  an  actual  test,  soon  shows  that 
the  present  model  is  totally  devoid  of  such  power  of  accumulation. 
Thus  in  Figure  8/4/1  the  reversal  at  R2  restores  the  external 

140 


10/7  THE     RECURRENT     SITUATION 

conditions  to  which  it  was  already  adapted  at  Dx;  yet  after  the 
events  following  the  first  reversal  (at  R^),  the  first  adaptation  (at 
Dj)  is  totally  lost;  and  the  Homeostat  treats  the  situation  after 
R2  as  if  the  situation  had  occurred  for  the  first  time. 

In  general,  if  the  Homeostat  is  given  a  problem  A,  then  a  prob- 
lem B,  and  then  A  again,  it  treats  A  as  if  it  had  never  encountered 
A  before;  the  activities  during  the  adaptation  to  B  have  totally 
destroyed  the  previous  adaptation  to  A.  (The  psychologist  would 
say  that  retroactive  inhibition  was  complete,  S.  16/12.) 

This  way  of  adapting  to  A  on  its  second  presentation  cannot  be 
improved  upon  if  the  environment  is  such  that  there  is  no  implica- 
tion that  the  second  reaction  to  A  should  be  the  same  as  the  first. 
The  Homeostat's  behaviour  might  then  be  described  as  that  of  a 
system  that  '  does  not  jump  to  conclusions  '  and  that  '  treats  every 
new  situation  on  its  merits  '.  In  a  world  in  which  pre-baiting  was 
the  rule,  the  Homeostat  would  be  better  than  the  rat  !  When, 
however,  the  environment  does  show  the  constraint  assumed  in 
this  chapter,  the  Homeostat  fails  to  take  advantage  of  it.  How 
should  it  be  modified  to  make  this  possible  ? 

10/6.  The  Homeostat  has,  in  fact,  a  small  resource  for  dealing 
with  recurrent  situations,  but  the  method  is  of  small  practical  use. 
In  S.  8/10  we  saw  that  the  Homeostat's  ultimate  field  is  one  that 
is  stable  to  all  the  situations,  so  that  a  change  from  one  to  another 
demands  no  new  trials. 

10/7.  This  method,  however,  cannot  be  used  extensively  in  the 
adaptations  of  real  life,  for  two  reasons.  The  first  is  that  when 
the  number  of  values  is  increased  beyond  a  few,  the  time  taken 
for  a  suitable  set  of  step-function  values  to  be  found  is  likely  to 
increase  beyond  anything  ordinarily  available,  a  topic  that  will 
be  treated  more  thoroughly  in  Chapter  11.  The  second  is  that 
the  adaptation,  even  if  established,  is  secure  only  if  the  set  of 
parameter-values  is  closed,  i.e.  so  long  as  no  new  value  occurs. 
Should  a  new  value  occur,  everything  goes  back  into  the  melting- 
pot,  and  adaptation  to  the  new  set  of  values  (the  old  set  increased 
by  one  new  member)  has  to  start  from  scratch.  Common  observa- 
tion shows,  of  course,  that  each  new  adaptation  does  not  destroy 
all  the  old;  evidently  the  method  of  S.  8/10  is  of  little  practical 
importance. 

141 


DESIGN     FOR    A    BRAIN  10/8 

The  accumulator  of  adaptations 

10/8.  To  see  what  is  necessary,  let  us  take  for  granted  that 
organisms  are  usually  able  to  add  new  adaptations  without  destroy- 
ing the  old.  Let  us  take  this  as  given,  and  deduce  what  modifica- 
tions it  enforces  on  the  formulation  of  S.  7/5.  Suppose,  then, 
that  an  organism  has  adapted  to  a  value  P1%  has  then  adapted  to 
P2  by  trial  and  error  as  in  S.  7/23,  and  that  when  P1  is  restored 
the  organism  is  found  to  be  adapted  at  once,  without  further 
trials.     What  can  we  deduce  ? 

(The  arguments  that  culminated  in  S.  7/8  apply  here  without 
alteration,  so  we  can  take  for  granted  that  the  adaptation  to  each 
individual  value  of  P  takes  place  through  the  second  feedback, 
with  essential  variables  controlling  step-functions  as  in  S.  7/7. 
The  modification  to  be  made  can  be  found  by  a  direct  application 
of  the  method  of  S.  4/12,  seeing  whether  variation  at  one  variable 
leads  to  variation  at  another.) 

To  follow  the  argument  through,  let  us  define  two  sub-sets  of 
the  step-mechanisms  in  S  that  affect  R  (Figure  7/5/1): 

Sx :  those  step-mechanisms  whose  change,  with  P  at  Pv  would 
cause  a  loss  of  the  adaptation  to  Px  (i.e.  those  step- 
mechanisms  that  are  effective  towards  R  when  P  is  at 

Pi); 

S2:  those  step-mechanisms  that  were  permanently  changed  in 
value  after  the  trials  that  led  to  the  adaptation  to  P2. 

First  it  follows  that  the  sets  Sx  and  S2  are  disjunct,  i.e.  have  no 
common  member.  For  if  there  were  such  a  common  member  it 
would  (as  a  member  of  S2)  be  changed  in  value  when  Px  was 
applied  for  the  second  time,  and  therefore  (as  a  member  of  Sx) 
would  force  the  behaviour  at  Px  to  be  changed  on  Px's  second 
presentation,  contrary  to  hypothesis.  Thus,  for  the  retention  of 
adaptation  to  Plf  in  spite  of  that  to  P2,  the  step-mechanisms  must 
fall  into  separate  classes. 

(That  the  step-mechanisms  must  be  split  into  classes  can  be 
made  plausible  by  thinking  of  the  step-mechanisms,  in  any  ultra- 
stable  system,  as  carrying  information  about  how  the  essential 
variables  have  behaved  in  the  past.  When  Px  is  presented  for  the 
second  time,  for  the  behaviour  to  be  at  once  adaptive,  information 
must  be  available  somewhere  about  how  the  essential  variables 

142 


10/9  THE     RECURRENT     SITUATION 

behaved  in  the  past  (for  by  hypothesis  they  are  to  give  none  now, 
and  they  are  the  only  source).  Thus  somewhere  in  the  system 
there  must  be  this  information  stored;  and  these  stores  must  not 
be  accessible  while  P2  is  acting,  or  they  will  be  affected  by  the 
events  and  the  stored  information  over-written.  Thus  there  must 
be  separate  stores  for  P±  and  P2,  and  provision  for  their  separate 
use.) 

Next,  consider  the  channel  from  the  essential  variables.  In 
condition  P2,  the  channel  from  them  to  the  step-mechanisms  in 
#2  was  evidently  open,  for  events  at  the  essential  variables  (whether 
within  physiological  limits  or  not)  affected  what  happened  in 
S2  (by  the  ordinary  processes  of  adaptation).  On  the  other  hand, 
during  this  time  the  channel  from  the  essential  variables  to  the 
step-mechanisms  in  Sx  was  evidently  closed,  for  changes  in  the 
essential  variables  were  followed  by  no  changes  in  the  step- 
mechanisms  of  Sv  Thus  the  channel  from  the  essential  variables 
to  the  step-mechanisms  S  must  be  divisible  into  sections,  so  that 
some  can  conduct  while  the  others  do  not;  and  the  determination 
of  which  is  to  conduct  must  be,  at  least  partly,  under  the  control 
of  the  conditions  P,  varying  as  P  varies  between  P±  and  P2. 

Finally,  consider  the  channels  from  S±  and  S2  to  the  reacting 
part  R.  When  Px  is  applied  for  the  second  time,  the  channel 
from  S2  to  R  is  evidently  closed,  for  though  the  parameters  in  S2 
are  changed  (before  and  after  P2),  yet  no  change  occurs  in  R's 
behaviour  (by  hypothesis).  On  the  other  hand,  that  from  Sx  is 
evidently  open,  for  it  is  S^s  values  that  determine  the  behaviour 
under  Pv  and  it  is  the  adapted  form  that  is  made  to  appear. 

10/9.  To  summarise: — Let  it  be  given  that  the  organism  has 
adapted  to  Px  by  trial  and  error,  then  it  adapted  similarly  to  P2, 
and  that  when  P1  was  given  for  the  second  time  the  organism 
was  adapted  at  once,  without  further  trials.  From  this  we  may 
deduce  that  the  step-mechanisms  must  be  divisible  into  non- 
overlapping  sets,  that  the  reactions  to  Px  and  P2  must  each  be 
due  to  their  particular  sets,  and  that  the  presentation  of  the 
problem  (i.e.  the  value  of  P)  must  determine  which  set  is  to 
be  brought  into  functional  connexion,  the  remainder  being  left  in 
functional  isolation. 

Thus  if  the  diagram  of  Figure  7/5/1  is  taken  as  basic,  it  must 
be  modified  so  that  the  step-mechanisms  are  split  into  sets,  there 

143 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN 


10/10 


must  be  some  gating  mechanism  r  to  determine  which  set  shall 
be  on  the  feedback  circuit,  and  the  gating  mechanism  r  must  be 
controlled  (usually  through  R,  as  this  is  the  organism's  structure) 
by  the  value  of  P. 


Envt 


Figure  10/9/1. 

Figure  10/9/1  presents  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects,  but 
the  Figure  is  best  thought  of  as  a  mere  mnemonic  for  the  functional 
relations,  lest  it  suggest  some  anatomical  form  too  strongly.  The 
parameter  P  can  be  set  at  various  values,  Plt  P2,  .  .  .  The  step- 
mechanisms  are  divided  into  sets,  and  there  is  a  gating  mechanism 
r,  controlled  by  P  through  the  environment  and  the  reacting 
part  R,  that  determines  which  of  the  sets  shall  be  effective  in 
the  second  feedback  via  the  essential  variables. 


10/10.  The  diagram  of  Figure  10/9/1  and  the  behaviour  of  the 
gating  mechanism  may  seem  somewhat  complex,  but  we  must 
beware  of  seeing  into  it  more  complexity  than  is  necessary.  All 
that  is  necessary  is  that  the  step-mechanisms  involved  in  any 
particular  problem  P{  be  distinct  from  those  involved  in  the 
others,  that  if  S{  be  affected  by  the  essential  variables  then  St  shall 
be  the  mechanisms  that  affect  R,  and  that  there  shall  be  a  corre- 
spondence between  the  problems  and  the  sets  of  step-mechanisms. 
This  latter  correspondence  need  not  be  orderly  or  '  rational  ' ;  it 
may  be  perfectly  well  set  up  at  random  (i.e.  determined  by  factors 

144 


10/11  THE     RECURRENT     SITUATION 

outside  our  present  view)  provided  only  that  if  the  presentation 
of  a  particular  problem  Pt  got  through  to  some  set  St,  then  always 
when  Pt  is  presented  again  the  actions  shall  again  go  through  to 
S{.  Such  a  case  would  occur  if  the  connexions  were,  say,  electrical 
and  made  by  plugging  connexions  at  random  into  a  plug-board. 
Once  made*  they  would  ensure  that  recurrence  of  Pt  would  give 
the  same  pattern  for  the  selection  of  S{ ;  and  the  change  from  Pt 
to  some  other  problem,  Pi  say,  by  involving  some  change  in  the 
sensory  input  to  R,  would  cause  some  change  in  the  distribution 
over  the  step-mechanisms. 

In  the  same  way,  if  nerve-cells  were  to  grow  at  random  (i.e. 
determined  in  their  growth  by  local  temporary  details  of  oxygen 
supply,  mechanical  forces,  etc.)  until  their  histological  details  were 
established,  and  if  the  paths  taken  by  impulses  depended  on  the 
concatentation  of  stimuli  coming  in,  then  the  recurrence  of  Pt 
would  always  give  access  to  Si3  and  a  change  from  Pz  to  P„  by 
changing  the  sensory  stimuli,  would  change  the  distribution. 

An  easy  method  by  which  J7  may  be  provided  is  given  in  S.  16/13. 

These  details  need  not  detain  us.  They  are  mentioned  only  to 
show  that  the  basic  requirements  are  easily  met,  and  that  the 
mechanism  meeting  them  may  look  far  less  tidy  than  Figure 
10/9/1  might  suggest.  In  this  sense  the  Figure,  though  helpful 
in  some  ways,  is  apt  to  be  seriously  misleading.  In  S.  16/12  we 
return  to  the  matter. 

10/11.  In  the  previous  sections,  the  various  situations  Pl9  P2, 
P3,  .  .  .  were  arbitrary,  and  not  assumed  to  have  any  particular 
relation  between  them.  A  special  case,  common  enough  to  be  of 
interest,  occurs  when  the  situations  usually  occur  in  a  particular 
sequence.  Thus  a  young  child,  reaching  across  the  table  for  a 
biscuit,  may  have  first  to  get  his  hand  past  the  edge  of  the  table 
without  striking  it,  then  the  hand  past  his  cup  without  spilling 
it,  then  past  the  jam  without  his  sleeve  wiping  it,  and  so  on: 
a  sequence  of  actions,  each  of  Which  calls  for  some  adaptation. 
Much  of  life  consists  of  just  such  sequences. 

The  system  of  Figure  10/9/1  can  readily  give  such  sequences 
in  which  every  part  is  adapted  to  its  own  little  problem.  The 
situation  of  '  hand  coming  past  the  edge  of  the  table  and  in  danger 
of  striking  it  '  is  Pv  say.  Adaptation  to  this  situation  can  occur 
in  the  usual  way,  by  the  basic  method  of  the  ultrastable  system. 

145 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  10/12 

The  sleeve  passing  near  open  jam  is  another  situation,  P2;  adapta- 
tion to  this,  too,  can  occur.  And  the  alterations  necessary  in 
adaptation  to  P2  will  not,  in  our  present  system,  cause  loss  of 
the  adaptation  to  Pv 

Whether  the  whole  situation  can  be  adapted  to  by  such  a 
sequence  of  sub-adaptations  (to  Pv  to  P2,  etc.)  depends  on  the 
environment:  only  certain  types  of  environment  will  allow  such 
fragmentation.  If  such  types  of  environment  are  frequent  in  an 
organism's  life,  then  there  will  be  advantage  in  evolution  if  the 
species  changes  so  that  each  organism  is  provided,  genetically, 
with  a  mechanism  similar  to  that  of  Figure  10/9/1. 

10/12.  To  amplify  the  point,  we  may  consider  the  case  of  an 
organism  that  lives  in  an  environment  that  consists  of  many 
sensorily-different  situations,  and  such  that  each  situation  is 
adequately  met  by  one  of  two  reactions,  eat  or  flee  say,  so  that 
the  organism's  problem  in  life  is  to  allot  one  of  the  two  reactions 
to  each  of  many  situations.  In  such  an  environment,  the  reacting 
part  R  of  Figures  7/5/1  or  10/9/1  could  be  quite  small,  for  it 
requires  only  mechanism  capable  of  performing  two  reflexes.  The 
stores  of  step-mechanisms,  however,  would  have  to  be  large,  and 
the  gating  mechanism  r  perhaps  elaborate;  for  here  would  have 
to  be  as  many  records  as  there  are  sensory  situations.  Each 
would  require  its  own  locus  of  storage,  and  the  gating  mechanism 
would  have  to  be  able  to  ensure  that  each  situation  led  to  its 
particular  locus.  In  such  a  world  we  would,  therefore,  expect  the 
organism  to  have  a  differently  proportioned  brain  from  one  that 
lived  in  a  world  such  as  was  presented  to  the  Homeostat. 

It  should  not  be  beyond  the  biologist's  powers  to  identify  a 
species  with  such  an  environment.  Examination  of  the  organism's 
nervous  system  might  then  enable  some  fundamental  identifica- 
tions to  be  made. 

10/13.  The  objection  may  be  raised  that  the  specification  deduced 
in  this  chapter  is  too  vague  to  be  of  use  to  the  worker  who  wants 
to  find  the  corresponding  mechanism  in,  say,  the  human  brain. 
The  reply  must  be  that  the  specification  is  right  to  be  vague;  for 
what  is  given — that  adaptation  occurs  with  accumulation — 
specifies  an  extremely  broad  class  of  mechanisms,  so  that  a  very 
great  diversity  of  actual  machines  could  all  show  adaptation  with 

146 


10/13  THE     RECURRENT     SITUATION 

accumulation.  If  they  can  all  show  it,  a  deduction  would  be 
patently  wrong  if,  without  further  data,  it  proceeded  to  indicate 
some  one  of  the  class. 

What  the  deduction  has  shown  is  that  we  must  give  up  our 
naive  conviction  that  the  outstanding  behavioural  properties  of 
adaptation  indicate  some  unique  cerebral  mechanism,  or  that  they 
will  provide  the  unique  explanation  of  the  features  of  the  living 
brain.  'Many  of  these  features  cannot  be  related  uniquely  to  the 
processes  of  adaptation,  for  these  processes  can  go  on  in  systems 
that  lack  those  neurophysiological  features,  systems  very  different 
from  the  living  brain,  such  as  the  modern  computer.  Only  further 
information,  beyond  that  assumed  in  this  chapter,  can  take  the 
identification  further. 


147 


CHAPTER   11 

The  Fully-joined  System 

11/1.  The  Homeostat  is,  of  course,  grossly  different  from  the 
brain  in  many  respects,  one  of  the  most  obvious  being  that  while 
the  brain  has  a  very  great  number  of  component  parts  the  Homeo- 
stat has,  effectively,  only  four.  This  difference  does  not  make 
the  theory  of  the  ultrastable  system  totally  inapplicable,  for  much 
of  the  theory  is  true  regardless  of  the  number  of  parts,  which  is 
simply  irrelevant.  Nevertheless,  we  are  in  danger,  after  spending 
so  much  time  getting  to  know  a  system  of  four  parts,  of  developing 
a  set  of  images,  a  set  of  working  mental  concepts,  that  is  seriously 
out  of  proportion  if  considered  as  a  set  of  working  concepts  with 
which  to  think  about  the  real  brain.  Let  us  therefore  consider 
specifically  the  properties  of  the  ultrastable  system  that  has  a  very 
great  number  of  parts.  We  shall  find  that  one  difficulty  becomes 
outstanding,  and  we  shall  spend  the  remainder  of  the  book  dealing 
with  it,  for  it  is  the  main  problem  in  the  adaptation  of  large 
systems. 

Adaptation-time 

11/2.  Suppose  the  Homeostat  were  of  a  thousand  units.  Such 
a  size  goes  only  a  small  fraction  of  the  way  to  brain-size,  but  it 
will  serve  our  purpose.  Such  a  system  will  have  a  thousand  relays 
(F,  Figure  8/2/3);  let  us  suppose  that  all  but  a  hundred  are 
shorted  out,  so  that  the  system  is  left  with  one  hundred  essential 
variables.  This  number  may  be  of  the  same  order  of  size  as  the 
number  of  essential  variables  in  a  living  organism. 

Since  these  variables  are  essential,  adaptation  implies  that  all 
are  to  be  kept  within  their  proper  limits.  Let  us  try  a  rough 
preliminary  calculation.  Simplifying  the  situation  further,  let  us 
suppose  that  the  step-mechanisms,  as  they  change,  give  to  each 
essential  variable  a  50-50  chance  of  going  within,  or  outside  of, 
its  limits,  and  that  the  chances  are  independent.  (The  case  of 
independence  should  be  considered,  by  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17, 

148 


11/3  THE     FULLY-JOINED     SYSTEM 

as  the  case  is  central.)  We  ask,  how  many  trials  will,  on  the  average, 
be  required  for  adaptation  ? 

Each  variable  has  a  probability  J  of  being  kept  within  its  limits. 
At  any  one  trial  the  probability  that  all  of  100  will  be  kept  in  is 
(J)100,  and  so  the  average  number  of  trials  will  be  2100,  by  S.  22/7. 
How  long  will  this  take,  at,  say,  one  per  second  ?  The  answer  is: 
about  1022  years,  a  time  unimaginably  vaster  than  all  astronomic- 
ally meaningful  time  !  For  practical  purposes  this  is  equivalent 
to  never,  and  so  we  arrive  at  our  major  problem :  the  brain,  though 
having  many  components,  does  adapt  in  a  fairly  short  time — the 
1,000-unit  Homeostat,  though  of  vastly  fewer  components,  does 
not.     What  is  wrong  ? 

It  can  hardly  be  that  the  brain  does  not  use  the  basic  process  of 
ultrast ability,  for  the  arguments  of  S.  7/8  show  that  any  system 
made  of  parts  that  obey  the  ordinary  laws  of  cause  and  effect 
must  use  this  method.  Further,  there  is  no  reason  to  suppose 
that  the  function  2N,  where  N  is  the  number  of  essential  variables, 
is  seriously  in  error,  even  though  it  is  somewhat  uncertain:  other 
lines  of  reasoning  (given  below)  also  lead  to  the  same  order  of 
size,  a  size  far  too  large  to  be  compatible  with  the  known  facts. 
There  seems  to  be  little  doubt  that  a  1,000-unit  Homeostat  would 
quite  fail,  by  its  slowness  in  getting  adapted,  to  resemble  the 
mammalian  brain.  Wherein,  then,  does  this  system  not  resemble 
(in  an  essential  way)  the  system  of  brain  and  environment  ? 

11/3.  In  the  previous  section  the  dynamic  nature  of  the  brain  and 
environment  was  really  ignored,  for  the  calculation  was  based  on 
a  direct  relation  between  step-mechanisms  and  essential  variables, 
while  what  connected  them  was  ignored.  Let  us  now  ask  the 
question  again,  ignoring  the  essential  variables  but  observing  the 
dynamic  systems  of  environment  and  reacting  part  (Figure  7/2/1). 
Two  type-cases  are  worth  consideration  (by  S.  2/17). 

The  first  case  occurs  when  the  system  is  linear,  like  the  Homeo- 
stat, so  that  it  has  only  one  state  of  equilibrium,  which  can  be 
stable  or  unstable.  In  this  case,  unstable  fields  are  of  no  use  to 
the  organism,  for  they  do  not  persist;  only  the  stable  can  be  of 
enduring  use,  for  only  they  persist.  Let  us  ask  then:  if  a  Homeo- 
stat had  a  thousand  units,  how  many  trials  would  be  necessary 
for  a  stable  field  to  be  found  ?  Though  the  answer  to  this  ques- 
tion is  not  known,  for  the  mathematical  problem  has  not  yet 

149 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  11/4 

been  solved,  there  is  evidence  (S.  20/10)  suggesting  that  in  some 
typical  cases  the  number  will  be  of  the  order  of  2-^,  where  N  is 
the  number  of  variables.  There  seems  to  be  little  doubt  that  if 
a  Homeostat  were  made  with  a  thousand  units,  practically  every 
field  would  be  unstable,  and  the  chance  of  one  occurring  in  a 
lifetime  would  be  practically  zero.  We  thus  arrive  at  much  the 
same  conclusion  as  before. 

The  second  case  to  be  considered  is  that  of  the  system  that  has 
the  transformation  on  its  states  formed  at  random,  so  that  every 
state  goes  equiprobably  to  every  state.  Such  systems  have  been 
studied  by  Rubin  and  Sitgreaves.  Among  their  results  they  find 
that  the  modal  length  of  trajectory  is  \/n,  where  n  is  the  number 
of  states.  Now  if  the  whole  is  made  of  N  parts,  each  of  which 
can  take  any  one  of  a  states,  then  the  whole  can  take  any  one  of 
aN.  This  is  n;  so  the  modal  length  of  trajectory  is  VoN,  which 
can  be  written  as  (\Zo)N.  Again,  if  we  fill  in  some  plausible 
numbers,  with  N  =  1,000,  we  find  that  the  length  of  trajectory, 
and  therefore  the  time  before  the  system  settles  to  some  equili- 
brium, takes  a  time  utterly  beyond  that  ordinarily  observed  to 
be  taken  by  the  living  brain. 

11/4.  The  three  functions  given  by  the  three  calculations  are  all 
of  the  exponential  type,  in  that  the  number  of  trials  is  proportional 
to  some  number  raised  to  the  power  of  the  number  of  essential 
variables  or  parts.  Exponential  functions  have  a  fundamental 
peculiarity:  they  increase  with  deceptive  slowness  when  the 
exponent  is  small,  and  then  develop  with  breath-taking  speed  as 
the  exponent  gets  larger.  Thus,  so  long  as  the  Homeostat  has 
only  a  few  units,  the  number  of  trials  it  requires  is  not  large. 
Let  its  size  undergo  the  moderate  increase  to  a  thousand  parts, 
however,  and  the  number  of  trials  rushes  up  to  numbers  that  make 
even  the  astronomical  look  insignificant.  In  the  presence  of  this 
exponential  form,  a  mere  speeding  up  of  the  individual  trials,  or 
similar  modification,  will  not  bring  the  numbers  down  to  an 
ordinary  size. 

11/5.  What  had  made  the  processes  of  the  last  two  sections  so 
excessively  time-consuming  is  that  partial  successes  go  for  nothing. 
To  see  how  potent  is  this  fact,  consider  a  simple  calculation  which 
will  illustrate  the  point. 

150 


11/5  THR    FULLY -JOINED     SYSTEM 

Suppose  N  events  each  have  a  probability  p  of  success,  and 
the  probabilities  are  independent.  An  example  would  occur  if  N 
wheels  bore  letters  A  and  B  on  the  rim,  with  A's  occupying  the 
fraction  p  of  the  circumference  and  2?'s  the  remainder.  All  are 
spun  and  allowed  to  come  to  rest;  those  that  stop  at  an  A  count 
as  successes.  Let  us  compare  three  ways  of  compounding  these 
minor  successes  to  a  Grand  Success,*  which,  we  assume,  occurs 
only  when  every  wheel  is  stopped  at  an  A. 

Case  1:  All  N  wheels  are  spun;  if  all  show  an  A,  Success  is 
recorded  and  the  trials  ended;  otherwise  all  are  spun  again,  and 
so  on  till  '  all  A's  '  comes  up  at  one  spin. 

Case  2:  The  first  wheel  is  spun;  if  it  stops  at  an  A  it  is  left 
there;  otherwise  it  is  spun  again.  When  it  eventually  stops  at  an 
A  the  second  wheel  is  spun  similarly;  and  so  on  down  the  line  of 
N  wheels,  one  at  a  time,  till  all  show^'s. 

Case  3:  All  N  wheels  are  spun;  those  that  show  an  A  are  left 
to  continue  showing  it,  and  those  that  show  a  B  are  spun  again. 
When  further  A's  occur  they  also  are  left  alone.  So  the  number 
spun  gets  fewer  and  fewer,  until  all  are  at  A's. 

Regard  each  spin  (regardless  of  the  number  of  wheels  turned) 
as  one  trial.  We  now  ask,  how  many  trials,  on  the  average,  will 
the  three  cases  require  ? 

Case  1  will  require  ( -  )N,  as  in  S.  11/2.     Case  2  will  require,  on 


the  average,  l/'p  for  the  first  wheel,  then  \/p  for  the  second,  and 
so  on;  and  thus  N/p  for  them  all.  Case  3  is  difficult  to  calculate 
but  will  be  the  average  of  the  longest  of  a  sample  of  N  drawn  from 
the  distribution  of  length  of  run  for  one  wheel ;  it  will  be  somewhat 
larger  than  I /p. 

The  calculations  are  of  interest  not  for  their  quantitative  exact- 
ness but  because  when  N  gets  large  they  tend  to  widely  differing 
values.  Suppose,  for  instance,  that  p  is  \,  that  spins  occur  at 
one  a  second,  and  that  N  is  1,000.  Then  if  Tv  T2,  and  T3  are 
the  average  times  to  reach  Success  in  Cases  1,  2,  and  3  respectively, 
Ti  =  2iooo  seconds, 

T2  =  — — —  seconds, 

Li 

T3  =  rather  more  than  \  second. 

*  As  we  shall  have  to  consider  several  compoundings  of  minor  events  to 
major  events,  I  shall  use  the  convention  of  I.  to  C,  S.  13/8,  and  distinguish 
them  respectively  by  a  lower  case,  or  a  capital,  initial. 

151 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  11/6 

When  these  values  are  converted  to  ordinary  quantities,  Tx  is 
about  10293  years,  T2  is  about  8  minutes,  and  T3  is  a  few  seconds. 
Thus,  while  getting  Success  under  the  rules  of  Case  1  (all  simul- 
taneously) is  practically  impossible,  getting  it  under  Cases  2  and  3 
is  easy. 

The  final  conclusion — that  Case  1  is  very  different  from  Cases 
2  and  3 — does  not  depend  closely  on  the  particular  values  of  p 
ahd  N.  It  illustrates  the  general  fact  that  the  exponential 
function  (Case  1)  tends  to  become  large  at  an  altogether  faster 
rate  than  the  linear.  If  the  reader  likes  to  try  other  numbers 
he  is  likely  to  arrive  at  results  showing  much  the  same  features. 

11/6.  Comparison  of  the  three  Cases  soon  shows  why  Cases  2 
and  3  can  arrive  at  Success  so  much  sooner  than  Case  1 :  they  can 
benefit  by  partial  successes,  which  1  cannot.  Suppose,  for 
instance,  that,  under  Case  1,  a  spin  gave  999  A's  and  1  B.  This  is 
very  near  complete  Success;  yet  it  counts  for  nothing,  and  all  the 
A's  have  to  be  thrown  back  into  the  melting-pot.  In  Case  3, 
however,  only  one  wheel  would  remain  to  be  spun;  while  Case  2 
would  perhaps  get  a  good  run  of  A's  at  the  left-hand  end  and  could 
thus  benefit  somewhat. 

The  examples  thus  show  the  great,  the  very  great,  reduction 
in  time  taken  that  occurs  when  the  final  Success  can  be  reached 
by  stages,  in  which  partial  successes  can  be  conserved  and 
accumulated. 

11/7.  It  is  difficult  to  find  a  real  example  which  shows  in  one 
system  the  three  ways  of  progression  to  Success,  for  few  systems 
are  constructed  so  flexibly.  It  is,  however,  possible  to  construct, 
by  the  theory  of  probability,  examples  which  show  the  differences 
referred  to.  Thus  suppose  that,  as  the  traffic  passes,  we  note  the 
final  digit  on  each  car's  number-plate,  and  decide  that  we  want 
to  see  cars  go  past  with  the  final  digits  0,  1,  2,  3,  4,  5,  6,  7,  8,  9,  in 
that  order.  If  we  insist  that  the  ten  cars  shall  pass  consecutively, 
as  in  Case  1,  then  on  the  average  we  shall  have  to  wait  till  about 
10,000,000,000  cars  have  passed:  for  practical  purposes  such  an 
event  is  impossible.  But  if  we  allow  success  to  be  achieved  by 
first  finding  a  '  0  ',  then  finding  a  '  1  ',  and  so  on  until  a  '  9  '  is 
seen,  as  in  Case  2,  then  the  number  of  cars  which  must  pass  will 
be  about  fifty,  and  this  number  makes  '  Success  '  easily  achievable. 

152 


11/9  THE     FULLY -JOIN  ED     SYSTEM 

11/8.  A  well-known  physical  example  illustrating  the  difference 
is  the  crystallisation  of  a  solid  from  solution.  When  in  solution, 
the  molecules  of  the  solute  move  at  random  so  that  in  any  given 
interval  of  time  there  is  a  definite  probability  that  a  given  molecule 
will  possess  a  motion  and  position  suitable  for  its  adherence  to 
the  crystal.  Now  the  smallest  visible  crystal  contains  billions  of 
molecules :  if  a  visible  crystal  could  form  only  when  all  its  mole- 
cules happened  simultaneously  to  be  properly  related  in  position 
and  motion  to  one  another  (Case  1),  then  crystallisation  could 
never  occur:  it  would  be  too  improbable.  But  in  fact  crystallisa- 
tion can  occur  by  succession  (Case  2),  for  once  a  crystal  has  begun 
to  form,  a  single  molecule  which  happens  to  possess  the  right 
position  and  motion  can  join  the  crystal  regardless  of  the  positions 
and  motions  of  the  other  molecules  in  the  solution.  So  the  crystal- 
lisation can  proceed  by  stages,  and  the  time  taken  resembles  T2 
rather  than  7\. 

We  may  draw,  then,  the  following  conclusion.  A  compound 
event  that  is  impossible  if  the  components  have  to  occur  simul- 
taneously may  be  readily  achievable  if  they  can  occur  in  sequence 
or  independently. 

11/9.  It  is  now  becoming  apparent  in  what  way  the  1,000-unit 
Homeostat,  which  takes  such  an  excessively  long  time  to  adapt, 
differs  from  the  living  organism,  which  usually  gets  adapted  in  a 
fraction  of  its  generation-time.  The  organism,  of  course,  does  not 
reach  its  full  adult  adaptation  by  making  trial  after  trial,  all  of 
which  count  for  nothing  until  suddenly  everything  comes  right  ! 
On  the  contrary,  it  conforms  more  to  the  rules  of  Cases  2  or  3, 
achieving  partial  successes  and  then  retaining  them  while  improving 
what  is  still  unsatisfactory. 

However,  before  we  turn  to  consider  the  latter  cases  we  should 
notice  that  the  1,000-unit  Homeostat  is  not  wholly  atypical,  for 
environments  do  exist,  though  they  are  rare,  that  demand  that 
all  successes  occur  simultaneously  and  against  which  partial 
successes  count  for  nothing.  When  they  occur,  it  is  notorious 
that  they  give  the  living  organism  great  difficulty.  A  trifling 
example  occurs  when  a  trout  would  take  a  fly  on  the  surface;  the 
trout  must  both  break  the  surface  at  the  correct  place  and  must 
also  close  its  jaws  at  the  right  moment;  two  variables  here  are 
essential  in  the  sense  that  both  their  values  must  be  within  proper 

153 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


11/10 


limits  for  success  to  be  achieved;  failure  in  either  respect  means 
failure  totally. 

The  example  par  excellence  occurs  when  the  burglar,  homeo- 
statically  trying  to  earn  his  daily  bread  by  stealing,  faces  that 
particular  environment  known  as  the  combination  lock.  This 
environment  has,  of  course,  been  selected  to  be  as  difficult  for 
him  as  possible;  and  its  peculiar  difficulty  lies  precisely  in  the  fact 
that' partial  successes — getting,  say,  six  letters  right  out  of  seven 
— count  for  nothing.  Thus  there  can  be  no  progression  towards 
the  solution.  Thus,  confronted  with  an  environment  that  does 
not  permit  use  to  be  made  of  partial  adaptation,  human  and 
Homeostat  fail  alike. 


Cumulative  adaptation 

11/10.  In  terrestrial  environments,  however,  such  problems  are 
not  common.  Usually  the  organism  has  many  essential  variables, 
and  also  it  manages  to  reach  an  adaptation  of  all  fairly  quickly. 
Let  us  take  these  apparently  contradictory  facts  as  data,  and  see 
what  can  be  deduced  from  them  (following  essentially  the  method 
of  S.  4/12). 

Quite  a  simple  example  will  suffice  to  show  the  point.  Let  us 
suppose  that  an  organism  has  three  essential  variables  (marked 
1,  2  and  3)  all  affected  by  the  environment,  and  all  able  to  veto 
the  stability  of  the  step-mechanisms  S,  as  in  Figure  11/10/1. 

Let  us  suppose  that  the  organism  has  reached  the  state  of  being 


Figure  11/10/1. 
154 


11/10  THR    FULLY -JOINED     SYSTEM 

adapted  at  essential  variables  1  and  2.  (More  precisely:  the 
disturbance  that  comes  to  the  environment  finds  such  a  set  of 
values  on  the  step-mechanisms  S  that  in  the  reaction  to  it,  essential 
variables  1  and  2  never  go  outside  their  proper  limits.)  The 
reaction  does,  however,  send  essential  variable  3  outside  its  limit. 

We  now  take  as  given  that  the  system  will  go  through  a  process 
like  that  of  S.  7/23,  and  that  after  it  is  over  the  step-mechanisms 
will  be  changed  to  new  values  such  that  now  essential  variable  3 
is  kept  within  limits,  and  also  that  the  other  two  still  react  in  the 
same  way  as  before  (this  being  necessary  if  we  are  to  assume  that 
adaptations  once  formed  are  held,  as  we  wish  to). 

To  see  what  this  implies,  let  S3  be  the  set  of  those  step-mechan- 
isms that  ended  with  changed  values  after  the  trials  due  to  3's 
adaptation  (some  such  there  must  be,  or  the  change  of  3's  response 
to  the  disturbance  is  an  effect  without  a  cause).  Now  apply  the 
operational  test  of  S.  4/12:  as  the  step-mechanisms  in  S3  are 
changed  in  value,  but  the  behaviours  showing  at  1  and  2  are  not, 
it  follows  that,  whatever  is  shown  in  Figure  11/10/1,  there  can 
be  no  effective  channel  of  communication  from  the  step- 
mechanisms  S3  (in  S)  through  R  and  the  environment  to  1  and  2. 

Next,  let  M12  represent  all  those  parts,  in  R  and  the  environment, 
that  play  a  part  in  determining  how  the  disturbance  eventually 
affects  1  and  2.  By  M3  represent  similarly  the  parts  on  the  channel 
from  S3  through  R  and  the  environment  to  3.  (Nothing  is  assumed 
about  how  M12  and  M3  are  related.)  Now  M3  cannot  be  void 
(or  S3  would  have  no  channel  to  affect  3,  and  the  final  adaptation 
of  3  could  not  have  occurred).  Similarly,  neither  can  M12  be 
void.  Finally,  the  earlier  deduction  that  there  is  no  channel  from 
S3  (through  R  and  environment)  to  1  or  2  implies  that  there  are 
no  common  variables  to  M12  and  M3,  nor  any  channel  from  M3  to 
M12  (for  otherwise  changes  at  S3  would  show  at  1  and  2,  contrary 
to  hypothesis). 

It  has  thus  been  shown  that,  for  adaptations  to  accumulate, 
there  must  not  be  channels  from  some  step-mechanisms  (e.g.  S3) 
to  some  variables  (e.g.  M12),  nor  from  some  variables  (e.g.  M3) 
to  others  (e.g.  M12).  Thus,  for  the  accumulation  of  adaptations 
to  be  possible  the  system  must  not  be  fully  joined.  The  idea  so 
often  implicit  in  physiological  writings,  that  all  will  be  well  if  only 
sufficient  cross-connexions  are  available,  is,  in  this  .context,  quite 
wrong. 

155 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  11/11 

This  is  the  point.  If  the  method  of  ultrastability  is  to  succeed 
within  a  reasonably  short  time,  then  partial  successes  must  be 
retained.  For  this  to  be  possible  it  is  necessary  that  certain  parts 
should  not  communicate  to,  or  have  an  effect  on,  certain  other  parts. 

11/11.  Now  we  can  see  where  the  Homeostat  was  misleading. 
From  the  beginning  of  the  book  (from  S.  1/7)  we  have  treated  the 
brain  and  the  environment  as  richly  joined,  each  within  its  own 
parts  and  each  to  the  other.  Thus  the  Homeostat  was  built  so 
that  every  unit  did  in  fact  interact  with  every  other  unit.  In  this 
way  we  developed  the  theory  of  the  system  that  is  integrated 
totally. 

By  working  throughout  with  systems  which  were  always  assumed 
to  be  as  richly  connected  as  the  reader  cared  to  think  them,  we 
avoided  the  possibility  of  talking  much  about  integration,  and 
then  discussing  a  mechanism  that,  in  fact,  really  worked  in 
separate  parts.  The  reacting  parts  and  the  environments  that  we 
have  discussed  have  so  far  been  integrated  in  the  extreme. 

11/12.  Nevertheless,  it  is  now  clear  that  one  can  go  too  far  in 
this  direction.  The  Homeostat  goes  too  far;  it  is  too  well  inte- 
grated, cannot  accumulate  adaptations,  and  thereby  takes  a  quite 
un-brainlike  time  in  reaching  adaptation.  What  we  must  discuss 
now  is  a  system  similar  to  the  Homeostat  in  its  ultrastability, 
but  not  so  richly  cross-joined.  To  what  degree,  then,  should  it 
be  cross- joined  if  it  is  to  resemble  the  nervoils  system  ? 

The  views  held  about  the  amount  of  internal  connexion  in  the 
nervous  system — its  degree  of  '  wholeness  ' — have  tended  to  range 
from  one  extreme  to  the  other.  The  '  reflexologists  '  from  Bell 
onwards  recognised  that  in  some  of  its  activities  the  nervous 
system  could  be  treated  as  a  collection  of  independent  parts.  They 
pointed  to  the  fact,  for  instance,  that  the  pupillary  reflex  to  light 
and  the  patellar  reflex  occur  in  their  usual  forms  whether  the 
other  reflex  is  being  elicited  or  not.  The  coughing  reflex  follows 
the  same  pattern  whether  the  subject  is  standing  or  sitting.  And 
the  acquirement  of  a  new  conditioned  response  might  leave  a  pre- 
viously established  response  largely  unaffected.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  Gestalt  school  recognised  that  many  activities  of  the 
nervous  system  were  characterised  by  wholeness,  so  that  what 
happened  at  one  point  was  conditional  on  what  was  happening  at 

156 


11/13  THE     FULLY-JOINED     SYSTEM 

other  points.  The  two  sets  of  facts  were  sometimes  treated  as 
irreconcilable. 

Yet  Sherrington  in  1906  had  shown  by  the  spinal  reflexes  that 
the  nervous  system  was  neither  divided  into  permanently  separated 
parts  nor  so  wholly  joined  that  every  event  always  influenced 
every  other.  Rather,  it  showed  a  richer,  and  a  more  intricate 
picture— one  in  which  interactions  and  independencies  fluctuated. 
'Thus,  a  weak  reflex  may  be  excited  from  the  tail  of  the  spinal 
dog  without  interference  with  the  stepping-reflex  '.  .  .  .  '  Two 
reflexes  may  be  neutral  to  each  other  when  both  are  weak,  but 
may  interfere  when  either  or  both  are  strong  '.  .  .  .  *  But  to 
show  that  reflexes  may  be  neutral  to  each  other  in  a  spinal  dog 
is  not  evidence  that  they  will  be  neutral  in  the  animal  with  its 
whole  nervous  system  intact  and  unmutilated.'  The  separation 
into  many  parts  and  the  union  into  a  single  whole  are  simply  the 
two  extremes  on  the  scale  of  '  degree  of  connectedness  '. 

Being  chiefly  concerned  with  the  origin  of  adaptation  and  co- 
ordination, I  have  tended  so  far  to  stress  the  connectedness  of 
the  nervous  system.  Yet  it  must  not  be  overlooked  that  adapta- 
tion may  demand  independence  as  well  as  interaction.  The 
learner-driver  of  a  motor-car,  for  instance,  who  can  only  just 
keep  the  car  in  the  centre  of  the  road,  may  find  that  any  attempt 
at  changing  gear  results  in  the  car,  apparently,  trying  to  leave 
the  road.  Later,  when  he  is  more  skilled,  the  act  of  changing 
gear  will  have  no  effect  on  the  direction  of  the  car's  travel.  Adap- 
tation thus  demands  not  only  the  integration  of  related  activities 
but  the  independence  of  unrelated  activities. 

11/13.  From  now  on,  therefore,  we'will  no  longer  hold  the  implicit 
assumption  that  all  parts  are  richly  joined.  This  freedom  makes 
possible  various  modifications  that  have  not  so  far  been  explicitly 
considered,  and  that  give  new  forms  of  ultrastable  system.  These 
forms  are  still  ultrastable,  for  they  conform  to  the  definition 
(which  does  not  involve  explicitly  the  amount  of  connexion),  but 
they  will  not  be  so  excessively  slow  in  becoming  adapted  as  the 
simple  form  of  S.  11/2.  They  do  this  by  developing  partial, 
fluctuating,  and  temporary  independencies  within  the  whole,  so 
that  the  whole  becomes  an  assembly  of  subsystems  within  which 
communication  is  rich  and  between  which  it  is  more  restricted. 
The  study  of  such  systems  will  occupy  the  remainder  of  the  book. 

157 


CHAPTER   12 

Temporary  Independence 

12/1.  Several  times  we  have  used,  without  definition,  the  con- 
cept of  one  variable  or  system  being  '  independent  '  of  another. 
It  was  stated  that  a  system,  to  be  state-determined,  must  be 
'  properly  isolated  '  ;  and  some  parameters  in  S.  6/2  were  described 
as  '  ineffective  '.  So  far  the  simple  method  of  S.  4/12  has  been 
adequate,  but  as  it  is  now  intended  to  treat  of  systems  that  are 
neither  wholly  joined  nor  wholly  separated,  a  more  rigorous 
method  is  necessary. 

The  concept  of  the  '  independence  '  of  two  dynamic  systems 
might  at  first  seem  simple:  is  not  a  lack  of  material  connexion 
sufficient  ?  Examples  soon  show  that  this  criterion  is  unreliable. 
Two  electrical  parts  may  be  in  firm  mechanical  union,  yet  if 
the  bond  is  an  insulator  the  two  parts  may  be  functionally  inde- 
pendent. And  two  reflex  mechanisms  in  the  spinal  cord  may  be 
inextricably  interwoven,  and  yet  be  functionally  independent. 

On  the  other  hand,  one  system  may  have  no  material  con- 
nexion with  another  and  yet  be  affected  by  it  markedly:  the 
radio  receiver,  for  instance,  in  its  relation  to  the  transmitter. 
Even  the  widest  separation  we  can  conceive — the  distance  between 
our  planet  and  the  most  distant  nebulae — is  no  guarantee  of 
functional  separation ;  for  the  light  emitted  by  those  nebulae  is  yet 
capable  of  stirring  the  astronomers  of  this  planet  into  controversy. 
The  criterion  of  physical  connexion  or  separation  is  thus  useless. 

12/2.  Can  we  make  the  test  for  independence  depend  on  whether 
one  variable  (or  system)  gives  energy  or  matter  to  the  other  ? 
The  suggestion  is  plausible,  but  experience  with  simple  mechanisms 
is  misleading.  When  my  finger  strikes  the  key  of  a  typewriter, 
the  movement  of  my  finger  determines  the  movement  of  the 
type;  and  the  finger  also  supplies  the  energy  necessary  for  the 
type's  movement.     The  diagram 


B 

158 


12/3  TEMPORARY     INDEPENDENCE 

would  state,  in  this  case,  both  that  energy,  measurable  in  ergs, 
is  transmitted  from  A  to  B,  and  also  that  the  behaviour  of  B 
is  determined  by,  or  predictable  from,  that  of  A.  If,  however, 
power  is  freely  available  to  B,  the  transmission  of  energy  from 
A  to  B  becomes  irrelevant  to  the  question  of  the  control  exerted. 
It  is  easy,  in  fact,  to  devise  a  mechanism  in  which  the  flow  of 
both  energy  and  matter  is  from  B  to  A  and  yet  the  control  is 
exerted  by  A  over  B.  Thus,  suppose  B  contains  a  compressor 
which  pumps  air  at  a  constant  rate  into  a  cylinder,  creating  a 
pressure  that  is  shown  on  a  dial.  From  the  cylinder  a  pipe  goes 
to  A,  where  there  is  a  tap  which  allows  air  to  escape  and  can 
thus  control  the  pressure  in  the  cylinder.  Now  suppose  a  stranger 
comes  along;  he  knows  nothing  of  the  internal  mechanism,  but 
tests  the  relations  between  the  two  variables:  A,  the  position  of 
the  tap,  and  B,  the  reading  on  the  dial.  By  direct  testing  he  soon 
finds  that  A  controls  B,  but  that  B  has  no  effect  on  A.  The 
direction  of  control  has  thus  no  necessary  relation  to  the  direction 
of  flow  of  either  energy  or  matter  when  the  system  is  such  that 
all  parts  are  supplied  freely  with  energy. 


Independence 

12/3.  The  test  for  independence  can,  in  fact,  be  built  up  from 
the  results  of  primary  operations  (S.  2/10),  without  any  reference 
to  other  concepts  or  to  knowledge  of  the  system  borrowed  from 
any  other  source. 

The  basic  definition  simply  makes  formal  what  was  used 
intuitively  in  S.  4/12.  To  test  whether  a  variable  X  has  an  effect 
on  a  variable  Y,  the  observer  sets  the  system  at  a  state,  allows 
one  transition  to  occur,  and  notices  the  value  of  Y  that  follows. 
(The  new  value  of  X  does  not  matter.)  He  then  sets  the  system 
at  a  state  that  differs  from  the  first  only  in  the  value  of  X  (in 
particular,  Y  must  be  returned  to  its  original  initial  state).  Again 
he  allows  a  transition  to  occur,  and  he  notices  again  the  value 
of  Y  that  results.  (He  thus  obtains  two  transitions  of  Y  from 
two  states  that  differ  only  in  the  value  of  X.)  If  these  two  values 
of  Y  are  the  same,  then  Y  is  defined  to  be  independent  of  X  so 
far  as  the  particular  initial  states  and  other  conditions  are 
concerned. 

By  dependent  we  shall  mean  simply  '  not  independent  '. 

159 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  12/4 

This  operational  test  provides  the  '  atom  '  of  independence. 
Two  transitions  are  needed:  the  concept  of  'independence'  is 
meaningless  with  less. 

12/4.  In  general,  what  happens  when  the  test  is  applied  to  one 
pair  of  initial  states  docs  not  restrict  what  may  happen  if  it  is 
applied  to  other  pairs.  The  possibility  cannot  be  excluded  that 
the  test  may  give  results  varying  arbitrarily  over  the  possible 
pairs.  Often,  however,  it  happens  that,  for  some  given  value  of 
all  other  variables  or  parameters,  Z,  Wf  .  .  .  ,  Y  is  independent 
of  X  for  all  pairs  of  initial  states  that  differ  only  in  the  value  of  X. 
In  this  case,  for  that  particular  field  and  for  that  particular  value 
of  the  other  variables  and  parameters,  Y  is  independent  of  X  in  a 
more  extended  sense.  Provided  the  field  and  the  initial  values 
of  Y,  Z,  W,  etc.,  do  not  change,  Y's  transition  is  unaffected  by 
X's  initial  value.  In  this  case,  Y  is  independent  of  X  over  a 
region  (in  the  phase  space)  represented  by  a  line  parallel  to  the 
.Y-axis,  '  independent '  in  the  sense  that  whenever  the  representa- 
tive point,  moving  on  a  line  of  behaviour,  leaves  this  region,  Y 
will  undergo  the  same  transition. 

Sometimes  it  may  happen  that  Y  is  independent  of  X  not  only 
for  all  values  of  X  but  also  for  all  values  of  the  other  variables 
and  parameters — Z,  W,  etc.  In  the  previous  paragraph  a  change 
of  Z's  value  might  have  changed  the  field  or  region  so  that  Y 
was  no  longer  independent  of  X.  In  the  present  case,  F's  transi- 
tion (from  a  uniform  Y- value)  is  the  same  regardless  of  the  initial 
values  of  X,  Z,  W,  etc.   Y  is  then  independent  of  X  unconditionally. 

It  will  be  seen  that  two  variables  may  be  '  independent  '  to 
varying  degrees :  at  two  points,  over  a  line,  over  a  region,  over  the 
whole  phase-space,  over  a  set  of  fields.  The  word  is  thus  capable 
of  many  degrees  of  application.  The  definitions  given  above  are 
not  intended  to  answer  the  question  (of  doubtful  validity)  '  what 
is  independence  really  ?  '  but  simply  to  show  how  this  word  must 
be  used  if  a  speaker  is  to  convey  an  unambiguous  message  to  his 
audience.  Clearly,  the  word  often  needs  supplementary  specifica- 
tion (e.g.  does  i  Y  independent  of  X  '  mean  l  over  this  field  '  or 
1  over  all  fields  '  ?);  the  supplementary  specification  must  then  be 
given,  either  by  the  context  or  explicitly. 

The  word  '  independent  '  is  thus  similar  to  the  word  '  stable  ' : 
both  words  are  often  useful  in  that  they  can  convey  information 

160 


12/8  TEMPORARY  INDEPENDENCE 

about  a  system  quickly  and  easily  when  the  system  has  a  suitable 
simplicity  and  when  it  is  known  that  the  listener  will  interpret 
them  suitably.  But  always  the  speaker  must  be  prepared,  if  the 
system  is  not  simple,  to  add  supplementary  details  or  even  to  go 
back  to  a  description  of  the  transitions  themselves ;  here  there  is 
always  security,  for  here  the  information  is  complete. 

12/5.  Because  there  are  various  degrees  of  independence,  so  that 
Y  may  be  independent  of  X  over  a  small  region  of  the  field  but 
not  independent  if  the  same  region  is  extended,  it  follows  that 
one  system  can  give  a  variety  of  diagrams  of  immediate  effects — 
as  many  as  there  are  ranges  and  conditions  of  independence 
considered.  This  implication  is  unpleasant  for  us;  but  we  cannot 
evade  the  fact.  (Fortunately  it  commonly  happens  that  the  inde- 
pendencies in  which  we  are  interested  give  much  the  same  diagram, 
so  often  one  diagram  will  represent  all  the  significant  aspects  of 
independence.) 

12/6.  So  far  we  have  discussed  F's  independence  of  X.  What- 
ever this  is,  it  in  no  way  restricts,  in  general,  whether  X  is  or  is 
not  independent  of  Y.  If  X  is  independent  of  Y,  but  Y  is  not 
independent  of  X,  then  X  dominates  F. 

12/7.  The  definition  given  so  far  refers  to  independence  between 
two  variables.  It  may  happen  that  every  variable  in  a  system  A 
is  independent  of  every  variable  in  a  system  B,  all  possible  pairs 
being  considered.  We  then  say  that  system  A  is  independent  of 
system  B. 

Again,  such  independence  does  not,  in  general,  restrict  the 
possibilities  whether  B  is  or  is  not  independent  of  A;  A  may 
dominate  B. 

12/8.  To  illustrate  the  definition's  use,  and  to  show  that  its 
answers  accord  with  common  experience,  here  are  some  examples. 
If  a  bacteriologist  wishes  to  test  whether  the  growth  of  a  micro- 
organism is  affected  by  a  chemical  substance,  he  prepares  two 
tubes  of  nutrient  medium  containing  the  chemical  in  different 
concentrations  (X)  but  with  all  other  constituents  equal;  he  seeds 
them  with  equal  numbers  of  organisms ;  and  he  observes  how  the 
numbers  (Y)  change  as  time  goes  on.     Then  he  compares  the  two 

161 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  12/8 

later  numbers  of  organisms  after  two  initial  states  that  differed 
only  in  the  concentrations  of  chemical. 

To  test  whether  a  state-determined  system  is  dependent  on  a 
parameter,  i.e.  to  test  whether  the  parameter  is  '  effective  ',  the 
observer  records  the  system's  behaviour  on  two  occasions  when 
the  parameter  has  different  values.  Thus,  to  test  whether  a 
thermostat  is  really  affected  by  its  regulator  he  sets  the  regulator 
at  some  value,  checks  that  the  temperature  is  at  its  usual  value, 
and  records  the  subsequent  behaviour  of  the  temperature;  then 
he  returns  the  temperature  to  its  previous  value,  changes  the 
position  of  the  regulator,  and  observes  again.  A  change  of 
behaviour  implies  an  effective  regulator. 

Finally,  an  example  from  animal  behaviour.  Parker  tested  the 
sea-anemone  to  see  whether  the  behaviour  of  a  tentacle  was 
independent  of  its  connexion  with  the  body. 

4  When  small  fragments  of  meat  are  placed  on  the  tentacles 
of  a  sea-anemone,  these  organs  wind  around  the  bits  of  food 
and,  by  bending  in  the  appropriate  direction,  deliver  them 
to  the  mouth.' 

(He  has  established  that  the  behaviour  is  regular,  and  that  the 
system  of  tentacle-position  and  food-position  is  approximately 
state-determined.  He  has  described  the  line  of  behaviour  follow- 
ing the  initial  state:  tentacle  extended,  food  on  tentacle.) 

'If,  now,  a  distending  tentacle  on  a  quiet  and  expanded 
sea-anemone  is  suddenly  seized  at  its  base  by  forceps,  cut 
off  and  held  in  position  so  that  its  original  relations  to  the 
animal  as  a  whole  can  be  kept  clearly  in  mind,  the  tentacle 
will  still  be  found  to  respond  to  food  brought  in  contact 
with  it  and  will  eventually  turn  toward  that  side  which  was 
originally  toward  the  mouth.' 

(He  has  now  described  the  line  of  behaviour  that  follows  an  initial 
state  identical  with  the  first  except  that  the  parameter  '  con- 
nexion with  the  body '  has  a  different  value.  He  observed  that 
the  two  behaviours  of  the  variable  '  tentacle-position  '  are  identi- 
cal.) He  draws  the  deduction  that  the  tentacle-system  is,  in  this 
aspect,  independent  of  the  body-system: 

'  Thus  the  tentacle  has  within  itself  a  complete  neuro- 
muscular mechanism  for  its  own  responses.' 

The  definition,  then,  agrees  with  what  is  usually  accepted* 
Though  clumsy  in  simple  cases,  it  has  the  advantage  in  complex 

162 


12/9 


TEMPORARY     INDEPENDENCE 


cases  of  providing  a  clear  and  precise  foundation.  By  its  use 
the  independencies  within  a  system  can  be  proved  by  primary 
operations  only. 


12/9.  The  definition  makes  'independence  '  depend  on  how  the 
system  behaves  over  a  single  unit  of  time  (over  a  single  step  if 
changing  in  steps,  or  over  an  infinitesimal  time  if  changing  con- 
tinuously). The  dependencies  so  defined  between  all  pairs  of 
variables  give,  as  defined  in  S.  4/12,  the  diagram  of  immediate 
effects. 

In  general,  this  diagram  is  not  restricted:  all  geometrically 
drawable  forms  may  occur  in  a  wide  enough  variety  of  machines. 
This  freedom,  however,  is  not  always  possible  if  we  consider  the 
relation  between  two  variables  over  an  extended  period  of  time. 
Thus,  suppose  Z  is  dependent  on  F,  and  Y  dependent  on  X,  so 
that  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  contains  arrows: 


X 

Y 

Z 

X  may  have  no  immediate  effect  on  Z,  but  over  two  steps  the 
relation  is  not  free;  for  two  different  initial  values  of  X  will  lead, 
one  step  later,  to  two  different  values  of  Y;  and  these  two  different 
values  of  Y  will  lead  (as  Z  is  dependent  on  Y)  to  two  different 
values  of  Z.  Thus  after  two  steps,  whether  X  has  an  immediate 
effect  on  Z  or  not,  changes  at  X  will  give  changes  at  Z;  and  thus 
X  does  have  an  effect  on  Z,  though  delayed. 

Another  sort  of  independence  is  thus  possible :  whether  changes 
at  X  are  followed  at  any  time  by  changes  at  Z.  These  relations 
can  be  represented  by  a  diagram  of  ultimate  effects.  It  must  be 
carefully  distinguished  from  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects.  It 
is  related  to  the  latter  in  that  it  can  be  formed  by  taking  the 
diagram  of  immediate  effects  and  adding  further  arrows  by  the 
rule  that  if  any  two  arrows  are  joined  head  to  tail, 


/ 

Y      s 

\ 

/ 

^ 

X 

Z 

163 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN 

a  third  arrow  is  added  from  tail  to  head,  thus 


12/10 


X     >     z 


The  rule  is  applied  repeatedly  till  no  further  addition  of  arrows 
is  possible.  Thus  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  I  in  Figure 
12/9/1  would  yield  the  diagram  of  ultimate  effects  II. 


I 


>-  2 


K2 


I 


=^3 


Figure  12/9/1. 


The  diagram  of  ultimate  effects  shows  at  once  the  dependencies 
in  the  case  when  we  allow  time  for  the  effects  to  work  round  the 
system.  Thus  from  II  of  the  Figure  we  see  that  variable  1  is 
permanently  independent  of  2,  3,  and  4,  and  that  the  latter  three 
are  all  ultimately  dependent  on  each  other. 


The  effects  of  constancy 

12/10.  Suppose  eight  variables  have  been  joined,  by  the  method 
of  S.  6/6,  to  give  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  shown  in 
Figure    12/10/1.     We   now   ask:    what   behaviour   at   the   three 


ABC 
Figure  12/10/1. 

variables  in  B  will  make  A  and  C  independent,  in  the  ultimate 
sense,  and  also  leave  both  A  and  C  state-determined  ?  That  is, 
what  behaviour  at  B  will  sever  the  whole  into  independent  parts, 
giving  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  of  Figure  12/10/2: 

164 


12/11  TEMPORARY  INDEPENDENCE 


A  C 

Figure  12/10/2. 

The  question  has  not  only  theoretical  but  practical  importance. 
Many  experiments  require  that  one  system  be  shielded  from  effects 
coming  from  others.  Thus,  a  system  using  magnets  may  have  to 
be  shielded  from  the  effects  of  the  earth's  magnetism ;  or  a  thermal 
system  may  have  to  be  shielded  from  the  effects  of  changes  in 
the  atmospheric  temperature;  or  the  pressure  which  drives  blood 
through  the  kidneys  may  have  to  be  kept  independent  of  changes 
in  the  pulse-rate. 

A  first  suggestion  might  be  that  the  three  variables  B  should 
be  removed.  But  this  conceptual  removal  corresponds  to  no 
physical  reality:  the  earth's  magnetic  field,  the  atmospheric 
temperature,  the  pulse-rate  cannot  be  4  removed  '.  In  fact  the 
answer  is  capable  of  proof  (S.  22/14):  that  A  and  C  should  be 
independent  and  state-determined  it  is  necessary  and  sufficient  that 
the  variables  B  should  be  null-functions.  In  other  words,  A  and  C 
must  be  separated  by  a  wall  of  constancies. 

It  also  follows  that  if  the  variables  B  can  be  sometimes  fluctu- 
ating and  sometimes  constant  (i.e.  if  they  behave  as  part-functions), 
then  A  and  C  can  be  sometimes  functionally  joined  and  sometimes 
independent,  according  to  B's  behaviour. 

12/11.     Here  are  some  illustrations  to  show  that  the  theorem 
accords  with  common  experience. 

(a)  If  A  (of  Figure  12/10/1)  is  a  system  in  which  heat-changes 
are  being  studied,  B  the  temperatures  of  the  parts  of  the  con- 
tainer, and  C  the  temperatures  of  the  surroundings,  then  for  A 
to  be  isolated  from  C  and  state-determined,  it  is  necessary  and 
sufficient  for  the  .B's  to  be  kept  constant,  (b)  Two  electrical 
systems  joined  by  an  insulator  are  independent,  if  varying  slowly, 
because  electrically  the  insulator  is  unvarying,  (c)  The  centres 
in  the  spinal  cord  are  often  made  independent  of  the  activities  in 
the  brain  by  a  transection  of  the  cord;  but  a  break  in  physical 
continuity  is   not   necessary:   a  segment   may   be   poisoned,   or 

165 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


12/12 


anaesthetised,  or  frozen;  what  is  necessary  is  that  the  segment 
should  be  unvarying. 

Physical  separation,  already  noticed  to  give  no  certain  inde- 
pendence, is  sometimes  effective  because  it  sometimes  creates  an 
intervening  region  of  constancy. 

12/12.  The  example  of  Figure  12/10/1  showed  one  way  in  which 
the  behaviour  of  a  set  of  variables,  by  sometimes  fluctuating  and 
sometimes  being  constant,  could  affect  the  independencies  within 
a  system.     The  range  of  ways  is,  however,  much  greater. 

To  demonstrate  the  variety  we  need  a  rule  by  which  we  can 
make  the  appropriate  modifications  in  the  diagram  of  ultimate 
effects  when  one  or  more  of  the  variables  is  held  constant.  The 
rule  is: — Take  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects.  If  a  variable  V 
is  constant,  remove  all  arrows  whose  heads  are  at  V;  then, 
treating  this  modified  diagram  as  one  of  immediate  effects,  com- 
plete the  diagram  of  ultimate  effects,  using  the  rule  of  S.  12/9. 
The  resulting  diagram  will  be  that  of  the  ultimate  effects  when 


lixiixu/i 


«  4-f==r3  4  + 3  4 


Figure  12/12/1  :  If  a  four- variable  system  has  the  diagram  of  immediate 
effects  A,  and  if  1  and  2  are  part-functions,  then  its  diagram  of  ultimate 
effects  will  be  B,  C,  D  or  E  as  none,  1,  2,  or  both  1  and  2  become  inactive, 
respectively. 


V  is  constant.  (It  will  be  noticed  that  the  effect  of  making  V 
constant  cannot  be  deduced  from  the  original  diagram  of  ultimate 
effects  alone.)  Thus,  if  the  system  of  Figure  12/12/1  has  the 
diagram  of  immediate  effects  A,  then  the  diagram  of  ultimate 
effects  will  be  B,  C,  D  or  E  according  as  none,  1,  2,  or  both  1  and 
2  are  constant,  respectively. 

It  can  be  seen  that  with  only  four  variables,  and  with  only 
two  of  the  four  possibly  becoming  constant,  the  patterns  of  inde- 

166 


12/14  TEMPORARY  INDEPENDENCE 

pendence  show  a  remarkable  variety.  Thus,  in  C,  1  dominates 
3;  but  in  D,  3  dominates  1.  As  the  variables  become  more 
numerous  so  does  the  variety  increase  rapidly. 

12/13.  The  multiplicity  of  inter-connexions  possible  in  a  tele- 
phone exchange  is  due  primarily  to  the  widespread  use  of 
temporary  constancies.  The  example  serves  to  remind  us  that 
'  switching  '  is  merely  one  of  the  changes  producible  by  a  re- 
distribution   of    constancies.     For    suppose    a    system    has    the 


->• 


>.D 


^« 


B 

Figure  12/13/1. 

diagram  of  immediate  effects  shown  in  Figure  12/13/1.  If  an 
effect  coming  from  C  goes  down  the  branch  AD  only,  then,  for 
the  branch  BE  to  be  independent,  B  must  be  constant.  How  the 
constancy  is  obtained  is  here  irrelevant.  When  the  effect  from 
C  is  to  be  '  switched '  to  the  BE  branch,  B  must  be  freed  and  A 
must  become  constant.  Any  system  with  a  i  switching  '  process 
must  use,  therefore,  an  alterable  distribution  of  constancies. 
Conversely,  a  system  whose  variables  can  be  sometimes  fluctuating 
and  sometimes  constant  is  adequately  equipped  for  switching. 

The  effects  of  local  stabilities 

12/14.  The  last  few  sections  have  shown  how  important,  in  any 
system  that  is  to  have  temporary  independencies,  are  variables 
that  temporarily  go  constant.  As  such-  variables  play  a  funda- 
mental part  in  what  follows,  let  us  examine  them  more  closely. 

Any  subsystem  (including  the  case  of  the  single  variable)  that 
stays  constant  is,  by  definition,  at  a  state  of  equilibrium.  If  the 
subsystem's  surrounding  conditions  (parameters)  are  constant,  the 
subsystem  evidently  has  a  state  of  equilibrium  in  the  corresponding 
field ;  if  it  stays  constant  while  its  parameters  are  changing,  then 
that  state  is  evidently  one  of  equilibrium  in  all  the  fields  occurring. 
Thus,  constancy  in  a  subsystem's  state  implies  that  the  state  is 

167 


DESIGN    FOR    A    BRAIN  12/15 

one  of  equilibrium;  and  constancy  in  the  presence  of  small  impul- 
sive disturbances  implies  stability. 

The  converse  is  also  >  true.  If  a  subsystem  is  at  a  state  of 
equilibrium,  then  it  will  stay  at  that  state,  i.e.  hold  a  constant 
value  (so  long  as  its  parameters  do  not  change  value). 

Constancy,  equilibrium,  and  stability  are  thus  closely  related. 

12/15.  Are  such  variables  (or  subsystems)  common?  Later 
(S.  15/2)  it  will  be  suggested  that  they  are  extremely  common, 
and  examples  will  be  given.  Here  we  can  notice  two  types  that 
are  specially  worth  notice. 

One  form,  uncommon  perhaps  in  the  real  world  but  of  basic 
importance  as  a  type-form  in  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17,  is  that  in 
which  the  subsystem  has  a  definite  probability  p  that  any  particu- 
lar state,  selected  at  random,  is  equilibrial.  We  shall  be  con- 
cerned with  this  form  in  S.  13/2.  (In  explanation,  it  should  be 
mentioned  that  the  sample  space  for  the  probabilities  is  that  given 
by  a  set  of  subsystems,  each  a  machine  with  input  and  therefore 
determinate  in  whether  a  given  state,  with  given  input-value,  is 
or  is  not  equilibrial.)  The  case  would  arise  when  the  observer 
faced  a  subsystem  that  was  known  (or  might  reasonably  be 
assumed)  to  be  a  determinate  machine  with  input,  but  did  not 
know  which  subsystem,  out  of  a  possible  set,  was  before  him ;  the 
sample  space  being  provided  by  the  set  suitably  weighted,  the 
observer  could  legitimately  speak  of  the  probability  that  this 
system,  at  this  state,  and  with  this  input,  should  be  in  equilibrium. 

The  other  form,  very  much  commoner,  is  that  which  shows 
8  threshold  ',  so  that  all  states  are  equilibrial  when  some  para- 
metric function  is  less  than  a  certain  value,  and  few  or  none  are 
equilibrial  when  it  exceeds  that  value.  Well-known  examples  are 
that  a  weight  on  the  ground  will  not  rise  until  the  lifting  force 
exceeds  a  certain  value,  and  a  nerve  will  not  respond  with  an 
impulse  until  the  electric  intensity,  in  some  form,  rises  above  a 
certain  value. 

What  is  important  for  us  here  is  to  notice  that  threshold,  by 
readily  giving  constancy,  can  readily  give  what  is  necessary  for 
the  connexions  between  variable  and  variable  to  be  temporary. 
Thus  the  changes  in  the  diagram  of  Figure  12/12/1  could  readily 
be  produced  by  parts  showing  the  phenomenon  of  threshold. 

168 


12/18 


TEMPORARY     INDEPENDENCE 


12/16.  These  deductions  can  now  be  joined  to  those  of  S.  12/10. 
If  three  subsystems  are  joined  so  that  their  diagram  of  immediate 
effects  is 


and  if  B  is  at  a  state  that  is  equilibrial  for  all  values  coming  from 
A  and  C,  then  A  and  C  are  (unconditionally)  independent.  Thus, 
Z?'s  being  at  a  state  of  equilibrium  severs  the  functional  connexion 
between  A  and  C. 

Suppose  now  that  2?'s  states  are  equilibrial  for  some  states  of 
A  and  C,  but  not  for  others.  As  A  and  C,  on  some  line  of  behaviour 
of  the  wrhole  system,  pass  through  various  values,  so  will  they 
(according  to  whether  2?\s  state  at  the  moment  is  equilibrial  or 
not)  be  sometimes  dependent  and  sometimes  independent. 

Thus  we  have  achieved  the  first  aim  of  this  chapter:  to  make 
rigorously  clear,  and  demonstrable  by  primary  operations,  what 
is  meant  by  '  temporary  functional  connexions  ',  when  the  control 
comes  from  factors  within  the  system,  and  not  imposed  arbitrarily 
from  outside. 

12/17.  The  same  ideas  can  be  extended  to  cover  any  system  as 
large  and  as  richly  connected  as  we  please.  Let  the  system  consist 
of  many  parts,  or  subsystems,  joined  as  in  S.  6/6,  and  thus  pro-, 
vid'ed  with  basic  connexions.  If  some  of  the  variables  or  sub- 
systems are  constant  for  a  time,  then  during  that  time  the  con- 
nexions through  them  are  reduced  functionally  to  zero,  and  the 
effect  is  as  if  the  connexions  had  been  severed  in  some  material 
way  during  that  time. 

If  a  high  proportion  of  the  variables  go  constant,  the  severings 
may  reach  an  intensity  that  cuts  the  whole  system  into  subsystems 
that  are  (temporarily)  quite  independent  of  one  another.  Thus  a 
whole,  connected  system  may,  if  a  sufficient  proportion  of  its 
variables  go  constant,  be  temporarily  equivalent  to  a  set  of  un- 
connected subsystems.  Constancies,  in  other  words,  can  cut  a 
system  to  pieces.     (I.  to  C,  S.  4/20,  gives  an  illustration  of  the  fact.) 


12/18.  The  field  of  a  state-determined  system  whose  variables 
often  go  constant  has  only  the  peculiarity  that  the  lines  of 
behaviour  often  run  in  a  sub-space  orthogonal  to  the  axes.     Thus, 

169 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN 


12/18 


over  an  interval  in  which  all  variables  but  one  are  constant,  the 
corresponding  line  of  behaviour  must  run  as  a  straight  line  parallel 
to  the  axis  of  the  variable  that  is  changing.     If  all  but  two  are 

inactive  (along  some  line  of  behaviour), 
that  line  in  the  phase-space  may  curve 
but  it  must  remain  in  the  two-dimen- 
sional plane  parallel  to  the  two  corre- 
sponding axes;  and  so  on.  If  all  the 
variables  are  constant,  the  line 
naturally  becomes  a  point — at  the 
state  of  equilibrium.  Thus  a  three- 
variable  system  might  give  the  line  of 
behaviour  shown  in  Figure  12/18/1. 

In  the  interval  before  they  reach 
equilibrium,  such  variables  will,  of 
course,  behave  as  part-functions. 
Through  the  remaining  chapters  they 
will  show  their  importance.  For  convenience  of  description,  a 
part-function  (described  in  time  by  a  variable)  will  be  said  to  be 
active  or  inactive  (at  a  given  point  on  a  line  of  behaviour) 
according  to  whether  the  variable  is  changing  or  remaining 
constant. 


Figure  12/18/1.  In  the  dif- 
ferent stages  the  active 
variables  are  :  A,  y  ;  B,  y 
and  2  ;  C,z;  D  x  ;  E  y  ; 
F    x  and  z. 


170 


CHAPTER   13 

The  System  with  Local  Stabilities 

13/1.  Having  examined  what  is  meant  by  a  system  that  has 
'  partial,  fluctuating,  and  temporary  independencies  within  the 
whole  '  we  can  now  consider  some  of  the  properties  that  a  system 
of  such  a  type  will  show  in  its  behaviour. 

In  saying  4  a  system  of  such  a  type  '  we  have  not,  of  course, 
defined  a  system  with  precision:  we  have  only  defined  a  set  or 
class  of  systems.  How  shall  we  achieve  precision  ?  Two  ways 
are  open  to  us. 

One  way  is  to  add  further  details  until  we  have  defined  a  parti- 
cular system  with  full  precision,  so  that  its  behaviour  is  deter- 
minate and  uniquely  defined;  we  then  follow  the  behaviour  in  all 
detail.  Such  a  study  would  give  us  an  exact  conclusion,  but  it 
would  give  us  far  more  detail  than  we  require,  or  can  conveniently 
handle,  in  the  remaining  chapters. 

Another  way  is  to  talk  about  such  systems  '  in  general '.  Here 
nothing  is  easier  than  to  relax  our  grasp  and  to  talk  vaguely  about 
what  will  '  usually  '  happen,  regardless  of  the  fact  that  whether 
particular  properties  (such  as  linearity,  or  the  presence  of  thres- 
hold) are  '  usually  '  present  differs  widely  in  the  systems  of  the 
sociologist,  the  neurophysiologist,  and  the  physicist.  Rigour  and 
precision  are  possible  while  speaking  of  systems  '  in  general  ' 
provided  two  requirements  are  met:  the  set  of  systems  under 
discussion  must  be  defined  precisely,  and  statements  made  must 
be  precise  statements  about  the  properties  of  the  set.  In  other 
words,  we  give  up  the  aim  of  being  precise  about  the  individual 
system,  and  accept  the  responsibility  of  being  precise  about  the 
set.  This  second  way  is  the  method  we  shall  largely  follow  in  the 
remaining  chapters. 

Having  changed  to  the  new  aim,  we  shall  often  find  that  the 
argument  about  the  set  is  conducted  most  readily  in  terms  of 
some  individual  system  that  is  followed  in  detail;  when  this 
happens,    the   individual   system   must   be   understood   to   have 

171 


DESIGN     FOR    A    BRAIN  13/2 

importance  only  as  a  typical,  generic,  or  '  random  '  element  of  the 
set  it  belongs  to.  Though  the  argument  will  often  appear  verbally 
to  be  focused  on  an  individual  system,  it  is  directed  really  at  the 
properties  of  the  set,  the  individual  system  being  introduced  only 
as  a  means  to  an  end. 

We  shall  have  much  to  do,  in  what  follows,  with  systems  con- 
structed in  some  4  random  '  way.  The  word  will  always  mean  that 
we  are  discussing  some  generic  system  so  as  to  find  its  typical 
properties,  and  thus  to  arrive  at  some  precise  deduction  about  the 
defined  set  of  systems. 

13/2.  A  set  of  systems  of  special  importance  for  the  later 
chapters  is  the  set  of  those  systems  that  are  made  of  parts  that 
have  a  high  proportion  of  their  states  equilibrial,  and  are  made 
by  the  parts  being  joined  at  random. 

More  precisely,  assume  that  we  have  before  us  a  very  great 
number  of  parts,  assumed  to  be  fairly  homogeneous,  so  that  there 
is  a  defined  '  universe  ',  or  distribution,  of  them.  Each  is  assumed 
to  be  state-determined,  and  thus  to  have  in  it  no  randomness 
whatever.  As  a  little  machine  with  input,  if  it  is  at  a  certain  state 
and  in  certain  conditions  it  will  do  a  certain  thing;  and  it  will  do 
this  thing  whenever  the  state  and  conditions  recur. 

We  now  take  a  sample  of  these  parts  by  some  clearly  defined 
sampling  process  and  thus  arrive  at  some  particular  set  of  parts. 
(It  is  not  assumed  that  all  parts  have  an  equal  probability  of  being 
taken.)  Again  we  take  a  sample  from  the  possible  ways  of 
joining  them,  taking  it  by  a  clearly  defined  sampling  process,  and 
thus  arrive  at  some  one  way  of  joining  them. 

The  particular  set  of  parts,  joined  in  the  particular  way,  now 
gives  the  final  system. 

This  particular  final  system,  be  it  noticed,  is  state-determined. 
It  is  not  stochastic  in  the  sense  of  being  able,  from  a  given  state 
and  in  given  conditions,  to  undergo  various  transitions  with 
various  probabilities.  Thus  the  particular  system  is  not  random 
at  all.  The  randomness  enters  with  the  observer  or  experi- 
menter; he  is  little  interested  in  the  particular  system  taken  by 
the  sampling,  but  is  much  interested  in  the  population  from 
which  the  particular  system  has  come,  as  the  neurophysiologist  is 
interested  in  the  set  of  mammalian  brains.  The  '  randomness  ' 
comes  in  because  the  observer  faces  a  system  that  interests  him 

172 


13/4 


THE  SYSTEM  WITH  LOCAL  STABILITIES 


only  because  it  is  typical  of  the  set.  With  the  population  as  his 
sample  space  (derived  from  the  two  primary  sample  spaces)  he 
may  then  legitimately  speak  of  the  probability  of  the  system 
showing  a  certain  event,  or  having  a  certain  property. 

If  to  this  specification  we  add  the  restriction  that  the  original 
parts  are  rich  in  states  of  equilibrium  (e.g.  as  in  S.  12/15),  we  get  a 
type  of  system  that  will  be  referred  to  frequently  in  what  follows. 
For  lack  of  a  better  name  I  shall  call  it  a  polystable  system. 
Briefly,  it  is  any  system  whose  parts  have  many  equilibria  and 
that  has  been  formed  by  taking  parts  at  random  and  joining  them 
at  random  (provided  that  these  words  are  understood  in  the  exact 
sense  given  above). 

Definitions  can  only  be  justified  ultimately,  however,  by  their 
works.  The  remainder  of  the  book  will  demonstrate  something 
of  the  properties  of  this  interesting  type  of  system,  a  key-system 
in  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17. 

13/3.  In  such  demonstrations  we  shall  not  be  discussing  one 
particular  system,  specified  in  all  detail:  we  shall  be  discussing  a 
set.  When  a  set  is  discussed  we  must  be  careful  to  keep  an 
important  distinction  in  mind,  and  we  must  make  the  distinction 
arbitrarily:  (1)  are  we  discussing  what  can  happen? — a  question 
which  focuses  attention  on  the  extreme  possibilities,  and  therefore 
on  the  rare  and  exceptional;  or  (2)  are  we  discussing  what  usually 
happens? — which  focuses  attention  on  the  central  mass  of  cases, 
and  therefore  on  the  common  and  ordinary.  Both  questions  have 
their  uses ;  but  as  the  answers  are  often  quite  different,  we  must  be 
careful  not  to  confuse  them. 


13/4.  A  property  shown  by  all  state-determined  systems,  and 
one  that  will  be  important  later  is  the  following.  In  a  state- 
determined  system,  if  a  subsystem  has  been  constant  and  then 
commences  to  show  changes  in  its  variables,  we  can  deduce  that 


A  B 

\^ 

C 


173 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  13/5 

among  its  parameters  must  have  been,  when  it  started  changing, 
at  least  one  that  was  itself  changing.  Picturesquely  one  might 
say  that  change  can  come  only  from  change.  The  reason  is  not 
difficult  to  see.  If  variable  or  subsystem  C  is  affected  immediately 
only  by  parameters  A  and  B,  and  if  A  and  B  are  constant  over 
some  interval,  and  if,  within  this  interval,  C  has  gone  from  a  state 
c  to  the  same  state  (i.e.  if  c  is  a  state  of  equilibrium),  then  for 
C  to  be  consistent  in  its  behaviour  it  must  continue  to  repeat  the 
transition  '  c  to  c  '  so  long  as  A  and  B  retain  their  values,  i.e.  so 
long  as  A  and  B  remain  constant.  If  C  is  state-determined,  a 
transition  from  c  to  some  other  state  can  occur  only  after  A  or  B, 
for  whatever  reason,  has  changed  its  value. 

Thus  a  state-determined  subsystem  that  is  at  a  state  of  equili- 
brium and  is  surrounded  by  constant  parameters  (variables  of 
other  subsystems  perhaps)  is,  as  it  were,  trapped  in  equilibrium. 
Once  at  the  state  of  equilibrium  it  cannot  escape  from  it  until  an 
external  source  of  change  allows  it  to  change  too.  The  sparks 
that  wander  in  charred  paper  give  a  vivid  example  of  this  property, 
for  each  portion,  even  though  combustible,  is  stable  when  cold; 
one  spark  can  become  two,  and  various  events  can  happen,  but  a 
cold  portion  cannot  develop  a  spark  unless  at  least  one  adjacent 
point  has  a  spark.  So  long  as  one  spark  is  left  we  cannot  put 
bounds  to  what  may  happen ;  but  if  the  whole  should  reach  a  state 
of  l  no  sparks  ',  then  from  that  time  on  it  is  unchanging. 

Progression  to  equilibrium 

13/5.  Let  us  now  consider  how  a  polystable  system  will  move 
towards  its  final  state  of  equilibrium.  From  one  point  of  view 
there  is  nothing  to  discuss,  for  if  the  parts  are  state-determined 
and  the  joining  defined,  the  whole  is  a  state-determined  system 
that,  if  released  from  an  initial  state,  will  go  to  a  terminal  cycle  or 
equilibrium  by  a  line  of  behaviour  exactly  as  in  any  other  case. 
The  fact,  however,  that  the  polystable  system  has  parts  with 
many  equilibria,  which  will  often  stay  constant  for  a  time,  adds 
special  features  that  deserve  attention;  for,  as  will  be  seen  later, 
they  have  interesting  implications  in  the  behaviours  of  living 
organisms. 

13/6.  A  useful  device  for  following  the  behaviour  of  these  some- 
what complex  wholes  is  to  find  the  value  of  the  following  index. 

174 


13/8  THE     SYSTEM    WITH     LOCAL    STABILITIES 

At  any  given  moment,  the  whole  system  is  at  a  definite  state,  and 
therefore  so  is  each  variable ;  the  state  of  each  variable  either  is  or 
is  not  a  state  of  equilibrium  for  that  variable  (in  the  conditions 
given  by  the  other  variables).  The  number  of  variables  that  are 
at  a  state  of  equilibrium  will  be  represented  by  i.  If  the  whole  is 
of  n  variables  then  obviously  i  must  lie  in  the  range  of  0  to  n. 
If  i  equals  n,  then  every  variable  is  at  a  state  of  equilibrium 
in  the  conditions  given  by  the  others,  so  the  whole  is  at  a  state  of 
equilibrium  (S.  6/8).  If  i  is  not  equal  to  n,  the  other  variables, 
n  —  i  in  number,  will  change  value  at  the  next  step  in  time.  A 
new  state  of  the  whole  will  then  occur,  and  i  will  have  a  new  value. 
Thus,  as  the  whole  moves  along  a  line  of  behaviour,  i  will  change 
in  value ;  and  we  can  get  a  useful  insight  into  the  behaviour  of  the 
whole  by  considering  how  i  will  behave  as  time  progresses. 

13/7.  The  behaviour  of  i  is  strictly  determinate  once  the  system 
and  its  initial  state  have  been  given.  In  a  set  of  systems,  how- 
ever, the  behaviour  of  i  is  difficult  to  characterise  except  at  the 
two  extremes,  where  its  behaviour  is  simple  and  clear.  Com- 
parison of  what  happens  at  the  extremes  will  give  us  an  insight 
that  will  be  invaluable  in  the  later  chapters,  for  it  will  go  a  long 
way  towards  answering  the  fundamental  problem  of  Chapter  11. 
(By  establishing  what  happens  in  the  two  specially  simple  and 
clear  cases  we  are  following  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17.) 

13/8.  At  one  extreme  is  the  polystable  system  that  has  been 
joined  very  richly,  so  that  almost  every  variable  is  joined  to  almost 
every  other.  (Such  a  system's  diagram  of  immediate  effects 
would  show  that  almost  all  of  the  n(n  —  1)  arrows  were  present.) 
Let  us  consider  the  case  in  which,  as  in  S.  12/15,  every  subsystem 
has  a  high  probability  p  of  being  at  a  state  of  equilibrium,  and  in 
which  the  probabilities  are  all  independent.  How  will  *  behave  ? 
(Here  we  want  to  know  what  will  usually  happen;  what  can 
happen  is  of  little  interest.) 

The  probability  of  each  part  being  at  a  state  of  equilibrium  is 
p,  and  so,  if  independence  (of  probability)  holds,  the  probability 
that  the  whole  (of  n  variables)  is  at  a  state  of  equilibrium  will  be 
pn  (by  S.  6/8).  If  p  is  not  very  close  to  1,  and  n  is  large,  this 
quantity  will  be  extremely  small  (S.  11/4).  i  will  usually  have 
a  value  not  far  from  np  (i.e.  about  a  fraction  p  of  the  total  will  be 

175 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  13/9 

at  equilibrium  at  any  moment).  Then  the  line  of  behaviour 
will  perform  a  sort  of  random  walk  around  this  value,  the  whole 
reaching  a  state  of  equilibrium  if  and  only  if  i  should  chance  on 
the  extreme  value  of  n.  Thus  we  get  essentially  the  same  picture 
as  we  got  in  S.  11/3:  a  system  whose  lines  of  behaviour  are  long 
and  complex,  and  whose  chance  of  reaching  an  equilibrium  in  a 
fairly  short  time  is,  if  n  is  large,  extremely  small.  In  this  case 
the  time  taken  by  the  whole  to  arrive  at  a  state  of  equilibrium 
will  be  extremely  long,  like  2\  of  S.  11/5. 

13/9.  Particularly  worth  noting  is  what  happens  if  i  should 
happen  to  be  large  but  not  quite  equal  to  n.  Suppose,  for  in- 
stance, i  were  999  in  a  1,000-variable  system  of  the  type  now  being 
considered.  The  whole  is  now  near  to  equilibrium,  but  what  will 
happen  ?  One  variable  is  not  at  equilibrium  and  will  change. 
As  the  system  is  richly  connected,  most  of  the  999  other  variables 
will,  at  the  next  instant  (or  step),  find  themselves  in  changed 
conditions;  whether  the  state  each  is  at  is  now  equilibrial  will 
depend  on  factors  such  that  (by  hypothesis)  999p  will  still  be 
equilibrial,  and  thus  i  is  likely  to  drop  back  simply  to  its  average 
value.  Thus  the  richly-joined  form  of  the  polystable  system, 
even  if  it  should  get  very  near  to  equilibrium  (in  the  sense  that 
most  of  its  parts  are  so)  will  be  unable  to  retain  this  nearness  but 
will  almost  certainly  fall  back  to  an  average  state.  Such  a  system 
is  thus  typically  unable  to  retain  partial  or  local  successes. 

13/10.  With  the  number  n  still  large,  and  the  probabilities  p 
still  independent,  contrast  the  behaviour  of  the  previous  section 
(in  which  the  system  was  assumed  to  be  richly  or  completely 
joined)  with  that  of  the  polystable  system  in  which  the  primary 
joins  between  variables  are  scanty.  (A  similar  system  also  occurs 
if  p  is  made  very  near  to  1 ;  for,  by  S.  12/17,  as  most  of  the  variables 
will  be  at  states  of  equilibrium,  and  thus  constant  for  most  of  the 
time,  the  functional  connexions  will  also  be  scanty.)  How  will  i 
behave  in  this  case,  especially  as  the  scantiness  approaches  its 
limit  ? 

Consider  the  case  in  which  the  scantiness  has  actually  reached 
its  limit.  The  system  is  now  identical  with  one  of  n  variables 
that  has  no  connexions  between  any  of  them;  it  is  a  '  system  ' 
only  in  the  nominal  sense.     In  it,  any  part  that  comes  to  a  state 

170 


13/12        THE     SYSTEM     WITH     LOCAL     STABILITIES 

of  equilibrium  must  remain  there,  for  no  disturbance  can  come 
to  it.  So  if  two  states  of  the  whole,  earlier  and  later,  are  com- 
pared, all  parts  contributing  to  i  in  the  earlier  will  contribute  in 
the  later;  so  the  value  of  i  cannot  fall  with  time.  It  will,  of  course, 
usually  increase.  Thus,  this  type  of  system  goes  to  its  final  state 
of  equilibrium  progressively.  Its  progression,  in  fact,  is  like  that 
of  Case  3  of  S.  11/5;  for  the  final  equilibrium  has  only  to  wait  for 
the  part  that  takes  longest.  The  time  that  the  whole  takes  will 
therefore  be  like  T3,  and  thus  not  excessively  long. 

13/11.  The  two  types  of  polystable  system  are  at  opposite  poles, 
and  systems  in  the  real  world  will  seldom  be  found  to  correspond 
precisely  with  either.  Nevertheless,  the  two  types  are  important 
by  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17,  for  they  provide  clear-cut  types  with 
clear-cut  properties;  if  a  real  system  is  similar  to  either,  we  may 
legitimately  argue  that  its  properties  will  approximate  to  those 
of  the  nearer. 

Polystable  systems  midway  between  the  two  will  show  a  some- 
what confused  picture.  Subsystems  will  be  formed  (e.g.  as  in 
S.  12/17)  with  kaleidoscopic  variety  and  will  persist  only  for  short 
times ;  some  will  hold  stable  for  a  brief  interval,  only  to  be  changed 
and  to  disintegrate  as  delimitable  subsystems.  The  number  of 
variables  stable,  i,  will  keep  tending  to  climb  up,  as  a  few  sub- 
systems hold  stable,  only  to  fall  back  by  a  larger  or  smaller 
amount  as  they  become  unstable.  Oscillations  will  be  large,  until 
one  swing  happens  to  land  i  at  the  value  n,  where  it  will  stick. 

More  interesting  to  us  will  be  the  systems  nearer  the  limit  of 
disconnexion,  when  i's  tendency  to  increase  cumulatively  is  better 
marked,  so  that  i,  although  oscillating  somewhat  and  often  slipping 
back  a  little,  shows  a  recognisable  tendency  to  move  to  the  value 
n.  This  is  the  sort  of  system  that,  after  the  experimenter  has 
seen  i  repeatedly  return  to  n  after  displacement,  is  apt  to  make 
him  feel  that  i  is  '  trying  '  to  get  to  n. ' 

13/12.  So  far  we  have  discussed  only  the  first  case  of  S.  12/15; 
what  if  the  polystable  system  were  composed  of  parts  that  all  had 
their  states  of  equilibrium  characterised  by  a  threshold  ?  This 
question  will  specially  interest  the  neurophysiologist,  though  it 
will  be  of  less  interest  to  those  who  are  intending  to  work  with 
adapting  systems  of  other  types. 

177 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  13/13 

The  presence  of  threshold  precludes  the  previous  assumption  of 
independence  in  the  probabilities;  for  now  a  variable's  chance  of 
being  at  a  state  of  equilibrium  will  vary  in  some  correspondence 
with  the  values  of  the  variable's  parameters.  In  the  case  of  two 
or  more  neurons,  the  correspondence  will  be  one  way  if  the  effect 
is  excitatory,  and  inversely  if  it  is  inhibitory.  (If  there  is  a  mixture 
of  excitatory  and  inhibitory  modes,  the  outcome  may  be  an 
approximation  to  the  independent  form.)  To  follow  the  subject 
further  would  lead  us  into  more  detail  than  is  appropriate  in 
this  survey;  and  at  the  present  time  little  can  be  said  on  the 
matter. 

13/13.  To  sum  up:  The  polystable  system,  if  composed  of 
parts  whose  states  of  equilibrium  are  distributed  independently 
of  the  states  of  their  inputs,  goes  to  a  final  equilibrium  in  a  way 
that  depends  much  on  the  amount  of  functional  connexion. 

When  the  connexion  is  rich,  the  line  of  behaviour  tends  to  be 
complex  and,  if  n  is  large,  exceedingly  long;  so  the  whole  tends  to 
take  an  exceedingly  long  time  to  come  to  equilibrium.  When 
the  line  meets  a  state  at  which  an  unusually  large  number  of  the 
variables  are  stable,  it  cannot  retain  the  excess  over  the  average. 

When  the  connexion  is  poor  (either  by  few  primary  joins  or  by 
many  constancies  in  the  parts),  the  line  of  behaviour  tends  to  be 
short,  so  that  the  whole  arrives  at  a  state  of  equilibrium  soon. 
When  the  line  meets  a  state  at  which  an  unusually  large  number 
of  the  variables  are  stable,  it  tends  to  retain  the  excess  for  a  time, 
and  thus  to  progress  to  total  equilibrium  by  an  accumulation  of 
local  equilibria. 

Dispersion 
13/14.     The    polystable    system    shows    another    property    that 
deserves  special  notice. 

Take  a  portion  of  any  line  of  behaviour  of  such  a  system.  On 
it  we  can  notice,  for  every  variable,  whether  it  did  or  did  not 
change  value  along  the  given  portion.  Thus,  in  Figure  12/18/1, 
in  the  portion  indicated  by  the  letters  B  and  C  both  y  and  z 
change  but  x  does  not.  In  the  portion  indicated  by  F,  x  and  ~ 
change  but  y  does  not.  By  dispersion  I  shall  refer  to  the  fact  that 
the  active  variables  (y  and  z)  in  the  first  portion  are  not  identical 
with  those  (x  and  z)  of  the  second.     (In  the  example  the  portions 

178 


13/16       THE     SYSTEM     WITH     LOCAL    STABILITIES 

come  from  the  same  line,  but  the  two  portions  may  also  come 
from  different  lines.)  As  the  example  shows,  it  is  not  implied 
that  the  two  sets  shall  contain  no  common  element,  only  that  the 
two  sets  are  not  identical. 

The  importance  of  dispersion  will  be  indicated  in  S.  13/17. 
Here  we  should  notice  the  essential  feature:  though  the  two  por- 
tions may  start  from  points  that  differ  only  in  one,  or  a  few, 
variables  (as  in  S.  12/3)  the  changes  that  result  may  distribute 
the  activations  (S.  12/18)  to  different  sets  of  variables,  i.e.  to 
different  places  in  the  system.  Thus,  the  important  phenomenon 
of  different  patterns  (or  values)  at  one  place  leading  to  activations 
in  different  places  in  the  system  demands  no  special  mechanism : 
any  polystable  system  tends  to  show  it. 

13/15.  If  the  two  places  are  to  have  minimal  overlap,  and  if  the 
system  is  not  to  be  specially  designed  for  the  separation  of  parti- 
cular patterns  of  input,  then  all  that  is  necessary  is  that  the  parts 
should  have  almost  all  their  states  equilibrial.  Then  the  number 
active  will  be  few;  if  the  fraction  of  the  total  number  is  usually 
about  r,  and  if  the  active  variables  are  distributed  independently, 
the  fraction  that  will  be  common  to  the  two  sets  (i.e.  the  overlap) 
will  be  about  r2.  This  quantity  can  be  as  small  as  one  pleases  by 
a  sufficient  reduction  in  the  value  of  r,  which  can  be  done  by 
making  the  parts  such  that  the  proportion  of  states  equilibrial  is 
almost  1.  Thus  the  polystable  system  may  respond,  to  two 
different  input  states,  with  two  responses  on  two  sets  of  variables 
that  have  only  small  overlap. 

13/16.  It  will  be  proposed  later  that  dispersion  is  used  widely 
in  the  nervous  system.  First  we  should  notice  that  it  is  used 
widely  in  the  sense-organs. 

The  fact  that  the  sense-organs  are  not  identical  enforces  an 
initial  dispersion.  Thus  if  a  beam  of  radiation  of  wave-length 
0*5  ii  is  directed  to  the  face,  the  eye  will  be  stimulated  but  not 
the  skin ;  so  the  optic  nerve  will  be  excited  but  not  the  trigeminal. 
But  if  the  wave-length  is  increased  beyond  0-8  yu,  the  excitation 
changes  from  the  optic  nerve  to  the  trigeminal.  Dispersion  has 
occurred  because  a  change  in  the  stimulus  has  moved  the  excita- 
tion (activity)  from  one  set  of  anatomical  elements  (variables) 
to  another. 

179 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  13/17 

In  the  skin  are  histologically-distinguishable  receptors  sensitive 
to  touch,  pain,  heat,  and  cold.  If  a  needle  on  the  skin  is  changed 
from  lightly  touching  it  to  piercing  it,  the  excitation  is  shifted 
from  the  '  touch  '  to  the  '  pain  '  type  of  receptor;  i.e.  dispersion 
occurs. 

Whether  a  change  in  colour  of  a  stimulating  light  changes 
the  excitation  from  one  set  of  elements  in  the  retina  to  another 
is  at  present  uncertain.  But  dispersion  clearly  occurs  when  the 
light  changes  its  position  in  space;  for,  if  the  eyeball  does  not 
move,  the  excitation  is  changed  from  one  set  of  elements  to 
another.  The  lens  is,  in  fact,  a  device  for  ensuring  that  disper- 
sion occurs:  from  the  primitive  light-spot  of  a  Protozoon  dis- 
persion cannot  occur. 

It  will  be  seen  therefore  that  a  considerable  amount  of  dis- 
persion is  enforced  before  the  effects  of  stimuli  reach  the  central 
nervous  system:  the  different  stimuli  not  only  arrive  at  the 
central  nervous  system  different  in  their  qualities  but  they  often 
arrive  by  different  paths,  and  excite  different  groups  of  cells. 

13/17.  The  sense  organs  evidently  have  as  an  important  function 
the  achievement  of  dispersion.  That  it  occurs  or  is  maintained 
in  the  nervous  system  is  supported  by  two  pieces  of  evidence. 

The  fact  that  neuronic  processes  frequently  show  threshold, 
and  the  fact  that  this  property  implies  that  the  functioning 
elements  will  often  be  constant  (S.  12/15)  suggest  that  dispersion 
is  bound  to  occur,  by  S.  12/16. 

More  direct  evidence  is  provided  by  the  fact  that,  in  such  cases 
as  are  known,  the  tracts  from  sense-organ  to  cortex  at  least 
maintain  such  dispersion  as  has  occurred  in  the  sense  organ. 
The  point-to-point  representation  of  the  retina  on  the  visual 
cortex,  for  instance,  ensures  that  the  dispersion  achieved  in  the 
retina  will  at  least  not  be  lost.  Similarly  the  point-to-point 
representation  now  known  to  be  made  by  the  projection  of  the 
auditory  nerve  on  the  temporal  cortex  ensures  that  the  dispersion 
due  to  pitch  will  also  not  be  lost.  There  are  therefore  good 
reasons  for  believing  that  dispersion  plays  an  important  part  in 
the  nervous  system. 


180 


13/19       THE     SYSTEM    WITH     LOCAL    STABILITIES 

Localisation  in  the  polystable  system 

13/18.  How  will  responses  to  a  stimulus  be  localised  in  a  poly- 
stable system? — how  will  the  set  of  the  active  variables  be  dis- 
tributed over  the  whole  set  ? 

In  such  a  system,  the  reaction  to  a  given  stimulus,  from  a  given 
state,  will  be  regular  and  reproducible,  for  the  whole  is  state- 
determined.  To  this  extent  its  behaviour  is  lawful.  But  when 
the  observer  notices  which  variables  have  shown  the  activity  it 
will  probably  seem  lawless,  for  the  details  of  where  the  activation 
spreads  to  have  been  determined  by  the  sampling  process,  and 
the  activated  variables  will  probably  be  scattered  over  the  system 
apparently  haphazardly  (subject  to  S.  13/4).  Thus  the  question 
1  Is  the  reaction  localised  ?  '  is  ambiguous,  for  two  different 
answers  can  be  given.  In  the  sense  that  the  activity  is  restricted 
to  certain  variables  of  the  whole  system,  the  answer  is  '  yes  ' ;  but 
in  the  sense  that  these  variables  occur  in  no  simply  describable 
way,  the  answer  is  '  no  '. 

An  illustration  that  may  be  helpful  is  given  by  the  distribution 
over  a  town  of  the  chimneys  that  '  smoke  '  (suffer  from  a  forced 
down-draught)  when  the  wind  blows  from  a  particular  direction. 
The  smoking  or  not  of  a  particular  chimney  will  be  locally  deter- 
minate ;  for  a  wind  of  a  particular  force  and  direction,  striking  the 
adjacent  roofs  at  a  particular  angle,  will  regularly  produce  the 
same  eddies,  which  will  determine  the  smoking  or  not  of  the 
chimney.  But  geographically  the  smoking  chimneys  are  not 
distributed  with  any  simple  regularity ;  for  if  a  plan  of  the  town  is 
marked  with  a  black  dot  for  every  chimney  that  smokes  in  an 
east  wind,  and  a  red  dot  for  every  one  that  smokes  in  a  west  wind, 
the  black  and  red  dots  will  probably  be  mixed  irregularly.  The 
phenomenon  of  '  smoking '  is  thus  determined  in  detail  yet 
distributed  geographically  at  random. 

13/19.  Such  is  the  '  localisation  '  shown  by  a  polystable  system. 
In  so  far  as  the  brain,  and  especially  the  cerebral  cortex,  cor- 
responds to  the  polystable,  we  may  expect  it  to  show  '  localisation  ' 
of  the  same  type.  On  this  hypothesis  we  would  expect  the  brain 
to  behave  as  follows. 

The  events  in  the  environment  will  provide  a  continuous  stream 
of  information  which  will  pour  through  the  sense  organs  into  the 

181 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  13/19 

nervous  system.  The  set  of  variables  activated  at  one  moment 
will  usually  differ  from  the  set  activated  at  a  later  moment; 
and  the  activity  will  spread  and  wander  with  as  little  apparent 
orderliness  as  the  drops  of  rain  that  run,  joining  and  separating, 
down  a  window-pane.  But  though  the  wanderings  seem  dis- 
orderly, the  whole  is  reproducible  and  state-determined ;  so  that  if 
the  same  reaction  is  started  again  later,  the  same  initial  stimuli 
will  meet  the  same  local  details,  will  develop  into  the  same  patterns, 
which  will  interact  with  the  later  stimuli  as  they  did  before,  and 
the  behaviour  will  consequently  proceed  as  it  did  before. 

This  type  of  system  would  be  affected  by  removals  of  material 
in  a  way  not  unlike  that  demonstrated  by  many  workers  on  the 
cerebral  cortex.  The  works  of  Pavlov  and  of  Lashley  are  typical. 
Pavlov  established  various  conditioned  responses  in  dogs,  removed 
various  parts  of  the  cerebral  cortex,  and  observed  the  effects  on 
the  conditioned  responses.  Lashley  taught  rats  to  run  through 
mazes  and  to  jump  to  marked  holes,  and  observed  the  effects  of 
similar  operations  on  their  learned  habits.  The  results  were 
complicated,  but  certain  general  tendencies  showed  clearly. 
Operations  involving  a  sensory  organ  or  a  part  of  the  nervous 
system  first  traversed  by  the  incoming  impulses  are  usually 
severely  destructive  to  reactions  that  use  that  sensory  organ. 
Thus,  a  conditioned  response  to  the  sound  of  a  bell  is  usually 
abolished  by  destruction  of  the  cochleae,  by  section  of  the  auditory 
nerves,  or  by  ablation  of  the  temporal  lobes.  Equally,  reactions 
involving  some  type  of  motor  activity  are  apt  to  be  severely  upset 
if  the  centre  for  this  type  of  motor  activity  is  damaged.  But 
removal  of  cerebral  cortex  from  other  parts  of  the  brain  gave 
vague  results.  Removal  of  almost  any  part  caused  some  dis- 
turbance, no  matter  from  where  it  was  removed  or  what  type  of 
response  or  habit  was  being  tested;  and  no  part  could  be  found 
whose  removal  would  destroy  the  response  or  habit  specifically. 

These  results  have  offered  great  difficulties  to  many  theories  of 
cerebral  mechanisms,  but  are  not  incompatible  with  the  theory 
put  forward  here.  For  in  a  large  polystable  system  the  whole 
reaction  will  be  based  on  activations  that  are  both  numerous  and 
widely  scattered.  And,  while  any  exact  statement  would  have 
to  be  carefully  qualified,  we  can  see  that,  just  as  England's  paper- 
making  industry  is  not  to  be  stopped  by  the  devastation  of  any 
single   county,    so   a   reaction   based   on   numerous   and   widely 

182 


13/20       THE     SYSTEM     WITH     LOCAL     STABILITIES 

scattered  elements  will  tend  to  have  more  immunity  to  localised 
injury  than  one  whose  elements  are  few  and  compact. 

13/20.  Lashley  had  noticed  this  possibility  in  1929,  remarking 
that  the  memory-traces  might  be  localised  individually  without 
conflicting  with  the  main  facts,  provided  there  were  many  traces 
and  that  they  were  scattered  widely  over  the  cerebral  cortex, 
unified  functionally  but  not  anatomically.  He  did  not,  how- 
ever, develop  the  possibility  further;  and  the  reason  is  not  far 
to  seek  when  one  considers  its  implications. 

Such  a  localisation  would,  of  course,  be  untidy;  but  mere  un- 
tidiness as  such  matters  little.  Thus,  in  a  car  factory  the  spare 
parts  might  be  kept  so  that  rear  lamps  were  stored  next  to  radia- 
tors, and  ash-trays  next  to  grease  guns;  but  the  lack  of  obvious 
order  would  not  matter  if  in  some  way  every  item  could  be 
produced  when  wanted.  More  serious  in  the  cortex  are  the  effects 
of  adding  a  second  reaction;  for  merely  random  dispersion  provides 
no  means  for  relating  their  locations.  It  not  only  allows  related 
reactions  to  activate  widely  separated  variables,  but  it  has  no 
means  of  keeping  unrelated  reactions  apart;  it  even  allows  them 
to  use  common  variables.  We  cannot  assume  that  unrelated 
reactions  will  always  differ  sufficiently  in  their  sensory  forms  to 
ensure  that  the  resulting  activations  stay  always  apart,  for  two 
stimuli  may  be  unrelated  yet  closely  similar.  Nor  is  the  differen- 
tiation trivial,  for  it  includes  the  problem  of  deciding  whether  a 
few  vertical  stripes  in  a  jungle  belong  to  some  reeds  or  to  a  tiger. 

Not  only  does  random  dispersion  lead  to  the  intermingling  of  sub- 
systems, with  abundant  chances  of  random  interaction  and  con- 
fusion, but  even  more  confusion  is  added  with  every  fresh  act  of 
learning.  Even  if  some  order  has  been  established  among  the 
previous  reactions,  each  addition  of  a  new  reaction  is  preceded 
by  a  period  of  random  trial  and  error  which  will  necessarily  cause 
the  changing  of  step-mechanisms  which  were  already  adjusted  to 
previous  reactions,  which  will  be  thereby  upset.  At  first  sight, 
then,  such  a  system  might  well  seem  doomed  to  fall  into  chaos. 
Nevertheless,  I  hope  to  show,  from  S.  15/4  on,  that  there  are 
good  reasons  for  believing  that  its  tendency  will  actually  be 
towards  ever-increasing  adaptation. 


183 


CHAPTER  14 

Repetitive  Stimuli  and  Habituation 

14/1.  This  chapter  continues  the  study  of  the  polystable  system 
but  is  something  of  a  digression;  and  the  reader  who  proceeds 
directly  to  Chapter  15  will  lose  nothing  of  the  logical  thread. 
Nevertheless,  it  has  been  included  for  two  reasons. 

The  first  is  that  it  will  give  us  practice  in  understanding  the 
polystable  system,  and  will  show  how  systems  of  that  type  can 
be  discussed  in  terms  that  are  both  general  and  precise. 

A  second  reason  is  that  it  gives  another  example  of  the  thesis 
that  pervades  the  book : — -When  a  system  '  runs  to  equilibrium  ' 
one's  first  impression  is  that  what  is  interesting  has  now  come  to 
an  end — an  impression  that  is  often  valid  when  the  system  is 
simple,  and  the  equilibrium  that  of  a  run-down  clock.  What  has 
been  largely  overlooked,  and  what  this  book  attempts  to  display, 
is  that  when  a  complex  system  runs  to  equilibrium,  the  equilibrium 
necessarily  implies  a  complex  relationship  between  the  states  of 
the  various  parts.  When  the  relationship  between  the  states  of 
the  parts  is  examined,  they  will  show  unusual  and  striking 
features,  features  that  are  of  peculiar  interest  to  the  student  of 
behaviour.  Thus  Chapter  8,  on  the  Homeostat,  showed  '  only  '  a 
system  running  to  equilibrium  (e.g.  Figure  8/5/1);  yet  because  the 
system  and  conditions  were  structured,  interesting  relations  could 
be  traced  between  the  actions  and  interactions  of  the  various 
parts  at  and  around  the  terminal  equilibrium.  These  relations 
are  what  we  identified  in  Chapter  5  as  '  adaptation  '.  The  present 
chapter  will  give  another  example  of  how  a  system,  '  merely  ' 
running  to  equilibrium  under  a  complex  repetitive  input,  also 
produces  behaviour  of  psychological  and  physiological  interest. 

14/2.  First  a  definition.  When  there  are  many  states  of  equili- 
brium in  a  field,  then  as  every  line  of  behaviour  must  end  at  some 
state  of  equilibrium  (or  cycle),  the  lines  of  behaviour  collect  into 
sets,  such  that  the  lines  in  one  set  come  to  one  common  termina- 

184 


14/3        REPETITIVE     STIMULI    AND     HABITUATION 

tion  (cycle  or  state  of  equilibrium).  The  whole  field  is  thus 
divisible  into  regions  (each  a  confluent)  such  that  each  region 
contains  one  and  only  one  state  of  equilibrium  or  cycle,  to  which 
every  line  of  behaviour  in  it  eventually  comes.  The  chief  pro- 
perty of  a  confluent  is  that  the  representative  point,  if  released 
from  any  point  within  it,  (a)  cannot  leave  the  confluent,  (b)  will 
go  to  the  state  of  equilibrium  or  cycle,  where  it  will  remain  so 
long  as  the  parametric  conditions  persist. 

The  division  of  the  whole  field  into  confluents  is  not  peculiar  to 
machines  of  special  type,  but  is  common  to  all  systems  that  are 
state-determined  and  that  have  more  than  one  state  of  equilibrium 
or  cycle. 


Habituation 

14/3.  Consider  now  what  will  happen  if  a  polystable  system  be 
subjected  to  an  impulsive  (S.  6/5)  stimulus  S  repetitively,  the 
stimulus  being  unvarying,  and  with  intervals  between  its  applica- 
tions sufficiently  long  for  the  system  to  come  to  equilibrium 
before-  the  next  application  is  made. 

By  S.  6/5,  the  stimulus  S,  being  impulsive,  will  displace  the 
representative  point  from  any  given  state  to  some  definite  state. 
Thus  the  effect  of  S  (acting  on  the  representative  point  at  a  state 
of  equilibrium  by  the  previous  paragraph)  is  to  transfer  it  to  some 


Figure  14/3/1  :  Field  of  system  with  twelve  confluents,  each  containing  a 
state  of  equilibrium  (shown  as  a  dot),  or  a  cycle  (X  at  the  left).  The 
arrows  show  the  displacements  caused  by  S  when  it  is  applied  to  the 
representative  point  at  any  state  of  equilibrium  or  on  X. 

185 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  14/4 

definite  state  in  the  field  and  there  to  release  it.  The  possibilities 
sketched  in  Figure  14/3/1  will  illustrate  the  process  sufficiently. 

Suppose  the  system  is  in  equilibrium  at  A.  S  is  applied;  its 
effect  is  to  move  the  representative  point  to  the  end  of  the  arrow, 
in  this  example  moving  it  into  another  confluent.  The  system  is 
now,  by  hypothesis,  left  alone  until  it  has  settled :  this  means  that 
the  basic  field  operates,  carrying  it,  in  this  example,  to  the  state 
of  equilibrium  B.  Here  it  will  remain  until  the  next  application 
of  S,  which  in  this  example,  again  moves  it  to  a  new  confluent ; 
here  the  basic  field  takes  it  to  the  state  of  equilibrium  C.  So  does 
the  alternation  of  S  and  the  basic  field  take  it  from  equilibrium  to 
equilibrium  till  it  arrives  at  E.  From  this  state,  S  moves  it  only 
to  within  the  same  confluent  and  the  '  leaving  alone  '  results  in  its 
coming  back  to  E.  S  (having  by  hypothesis  a  unique  effect)  now 
takes  it  to  the  arrow  head,  and  again  it  comes  back  to  E.  This 
state  of  affairs  is  now  terminal,  and  the  representative  point  is 
trapped  within  the  i?-confluent. 

It  can  now  be  seen  that  the  process  is  selective;  the  representa- 
tive point  ends  in  a  confluent  such  that  the  ^-displacement  carries 
it  to  some  point  within  the  confluent.  Confluents  such  as  A,  C, 
and  D,  with  the  S- displacement  going  outside,  cannot  hold  the 
representative  point  under  the  process  considered;  confluents 
such  as  E,  J,  and  L  can  trap  it. 

14/4.  The  diagram  shows  two  complications  that  must  be  con- 
sidered for  completeness'  sake. 

The  first  is  that  the  events  of  the  right-hand  side  may  occur, 
where  the  process  considered  takes  the  representative  point 
cyclically  through  confluents  P,  Q,  R,  P,  Q,  R,  P,  .  .  . 

The  second  is  shown  on  the  left  at  X,  where  the  confluent  comes 
to  a  cycle.  From  this  cycle  a  variety  of  displacements  may  be 
caused  by  S,  depending  on  the  precise  moment  at  which  S  is 
applied  (i.e.  on  just  where  the  representative  point  happens  to  be). 

Whether  such  cycles  (between  or  within  confluents)  are  com- 
mon in  the  nervous  system  is  a  question  to  be  settled  by  experi- 
ment. The  cycle  within  the  confluent,  as  at  X,  will  hardly  dis- 
turb the  conclusions  below;  for  either  all  ^-displacements  fall 
within  the  confluent  (in  which  case  it  is  trapped  as  stated  above) 
or  it  will  sooner  or  later  leave  the  confluent  (and  we  are  no  longer 
concerned  with  the  cycle).     Thus  in  the  Figure,  unless  the  period 

186 


14/5        REPETITIVE     STIMULI     AND     HABITUATION 

of  the  cycle  bears  some  exact  simple  relation  to  that  of  the  applica- 
tions of  S  (an  event  of  zero  probability  if  they  can  vary  con- 
tinuously), the  representative  point  will  in  fact  leave  X  and 
eventually  be  trapped  at  E.  (The  cycle  around  P,  Q,  R  adds 
complications  that  can  be  dealt  with  in  a  more  detailed  discussion.) 

14/5.  The  description  given  is  not  rigorous,  but  can  easily  be 
made  so.  It  is  intended  only  to  illustrate  the  thesis  that  under 
repetitive  applications  of  a  stimulus  (with  sufficient  delay  between 
the  applications  for  the  system  to  come  to  equilibrium)  the 
polystable  system  is  selective,  for  it  sticks  sooner  or  later  at  a  state 
from  whose  confluent  the  stimulus  cannot  shift  it.  And,  if  there  is  a 
metric  and  continuity  over  the  phase  space,  this  distance  that  the 
stimulus  S  finally  moves  the  point  will  be  less  than  the  average 
distance,  for  short  arrows  are  favoured.  Thus  the  amounts  of 
change  caused  by  the  successive  applications  of  S  change  from 
average  to  less  than  average. 

We  need  not  attempt  here  to  formulate  calculations  about  the 
exact  amount:  they  can  be  left  to  those  specially  interested. 
What  we  should  notice  is  that  the  outcome  of  the  process  is  not 
symmetric.  When  we  think  of  a  randomly  assembled  system  of 
random  parts  we  are  apt  to  deduce  that  its  response  to  repeti- 
tive stimulation  will  be  equally  likely  to  decrease  or  to  increase. 
The  argument  shows  that  this  is  not  so:  there  is  a  fundamental 
tendency  for  the  response  to  get  smaller. 

There  is  a  line  of  argument,  much  weaker,  which  may  help  to 
make  the  conclusion  more  evident.  We  may  take  it  as  axiomatic 
that  large  responses  tend  to  cause  more  change  (or  are  associated 
with  more  change)  within  the  system  than  small.  If  the  responses 
have  any  action  back  on  their  own  causes,  then  large  responses 
tend  to  cause  a  large  change  in  what  made  them  large;  but  the 
small  only  act  to  small  degree  on  the  factors  that  made  them 
small.  Thus  factors  making  for  smallness  have  a  fundamentally 
better  chance  of  surviving  than  those  that  make  for  largeness. 
Hence  the  tendency  to  smallness. 

(If  the  point  requires  illustration,  we  could  consider  the  question  : 
Of  two  boys  making  their  own  fireworks,  who  has  the  better 
chance  of  survival  ? — the  boy  who  is  trying  to  produce  the  biggest 
firework  ever,  or  the  boy  who  is  trying  to  produce  the  tiniest  !) 

187 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN 


14/6 


14/6.  The  process  can  readily  be  demonstrated,  almost  in 
truistic  form,  on  the  Homeostat  (which  is  here  treated  as  a  system 
whose  variables  include  4  position  of  uniselector  '  so  that  it  has 
many  states  of  equilibrium,  differing  from  one  another  according 
to  the  uniselector's  position). 

The  process  is  shown  in  Figure  14/6/1.     Two  units  were  joined 


Time 


Figure  14/6/1  :  Homeostat  tracing.  At  each  D,  l's  magnet  is  displaced 
by  the  operator  through  a  fixed  angle.  2  receives  this  action  through 
its  uniselector.  When  the  uniselector's  value  makes  2's  magnet  meet 
the  critical  state  (shown  dotted)  the  value  is  changed.  After  the 
fourth  change  the  value  causes  only  a  small  movement  of  2,  so  the  value 
is  retained  permanently. 

1  — >  2.  The  effect  of  1  on  2  was  determined  by  2's  uniselector, 
which  changed  position  if  2  exceeded  its  critical  states.  The 
operator  then  repeatedly  disturbed  2  by  moving  1,  at  D.  As 
often  as  the  uniselector  transmitted  a  large  effect  to  2,  so  often 
did  2  shift  its  uniselector.  But  as  soon  as  the  uniselector  arrived 
at  a  position  that  gave  a  transmission  insufficient  to  bring  2  to  its 
critical  states,  that  position  was  retained.  So  under  constant 
stimulation  by  D  the  amplitude  of  2's  response  changed  from 
larger  to  smaller. 

The  same  process  in  a  more  complex  form  is  shown  in  Figure 
14/6/2.     Two   units   are   interacting:    1  ^±  2.     Both   effects   go 


Time 
U 


3l 


Figure  14/6/2  :  Homeostat  arranged  as  ultrastable  system  with  two  units 
interacting.  At  each  D  the  operator  moved  l's  magnet  through  a  fixed 
angle.  The  first  field  such  that  D  does  not  cause  a  critical  state  to  be 
met  is  retained  permanently. 

188 


14/7       REPETITIVE     STIMULI    AND     HABITUATION 

through  the  uniselectors,  so  the  whole  is  ultrastable.  At  each  D 
the  operator  displaced  l's  magnet  through  a  constant  distance. 
On  the  first  '  stimulation  ',  2's  response  brought  the  system  to 
its  critical  states,  so  the  ultrastability  found  a  new  terminal  field. 
The  second  stimulation  again  evoked  the  process.  But  the  new 
terminal  field  was  such  that  the  displacement  D  no  longer  caused 
2  to  reach  its  critical  states;  so  this  field  was  retained.  Again 
under  constant  stimulation  the  response  had  diminished. 

14/7.  In  animal  behaviour  the  phenomenon  of  '  habituation  ' 
is  met  with  frequently:  if  an  animal  is  subjected  to  repeated 
stimuli,  the  response  evoked  tends  to  diminish.  The  change  has 
been  considered  by  some  to  be  the  simplest  form  of  learning. 
Neuronic  mechanisms  are  not  necessary,  for  the  Protozoa  show  it 
clearly : 

'Amoebae  react  negatively  to  tap  water  or  to  water  from  a 
foreign  culture,  but  after  transference  to  such  water  they 
behave  normally.' 

4  If  Paramecium  is  dropped  into  \°/0  sodium  chloride  it 
at  once  gives  the  avoiding  reaction  ...  If  the  stimulating 
agent  is  not  so  powerful  as  to  be  directly  destructive,  the 
reaction  ceases  after  a  time,  and  the  Paramecia  swim  about 
within  the  solution  as  they  did  before  in  water.'     (Jennings.) 

Fatigue  has  sometimes  been  suggested  as  the  cause  of  the 
phenomenon,  but  in  Humphrey's  experiments  it  could  be  excluded. 
He  worked  with  the  snail,  and  used  the  fact  that  if  its  support  is 
tapped  the  snail  withdraws  into  its  shell.  If  the  taps  are  repeated 
at  short  intervals  the  snail  no  longer  reacts.  He  found  that  when 
the  taps  were  light,  habituation  appeared  early;  but  when  they 
were  heavy,  it  was  postponed  indefinitely.  This  is  the  opposite 
of  what  would  be  expected  from  fatigue,  which  should  follow  more 
rapidly  when  the  heavier  taps  caused  more  vigorous  withdrawals. 

A  variety  of  special  explanations  have  been  put  forward  to 
explain  its  origin,  but  the  almost  universal  distribution  of  its 
occurrence  in  living  organisms  should  warn  us  that  the  basis 
must  be  some  factor  much  more  widely  spread  than  the  neuro- 
physiological.  The  argument  of  this  chapter  suggests  that  it  is  to 
be  expected  to  some  degree  in  all  polystable  systems  when  they 
are  subjected  to  a  repetitive  stimulus  or  disturbance. 


189 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  14/8 


Minor  disturbances 


14/8.  Exactly  the  same  type  of  argument — of  looking  for  what 
can  be  terminal — can  be  used  when  S  is  not  an  accurately  repeated 
stimulus  but  is,  on  each  application,  a  sample  from  a  set  of  dis- 
turbances having  some  definite  distribution.  In  this  case,  Figure 
14/3/1,  for  example,  would  remain  unchanged  in  its  confluents 
and  states  of  equilibrium,  but  the  arrow  going  from  each  state  of 
equilibrium  would  lose  its  uniqueness  and  become  a  cluster  or 
distribution  of  arrows  from  which,  at  each  disturbance,  some  one 
would  be  selected  by  some  process  of  sampling. 

The  outcome  is  similar.  The  equilibrium  whose  arrows  all  go 
far  away  to  other  confluents  is  soon  left  by  the  representative 
point;  while  the  equilibrium  whose  arrows  end  wholly  within  its 
own  confluent  acts  as  a  trap  for  it.  Thus  the  polystable  system 
(if  free  from  cycles)  goes  selectively  to  such  equilibria  as  are 
immune  to  the  action  of  small  irregular  disturbances. 

14/9.  The  fields  (of  the  main  variables)  selected  by  the  ultrastable 
system  are  subject  to  this  fact.  Thus,  consider  the  three  fields 
of  Figure  14/9/1  as  they  might  have  occurred  as  terminal  fields 
in  Figure  7/23/1.     In  fields  A  and  C  the  undisturbed  representa- 


Figure  14/9/1  :  Three  fields  of  an  ultrastable  system,  differing  in  their 
liability  to  change  when  the  system  is  subjected  to  small  random  dis- 
turbances.    (The  critical  states  are  shown  by  the  dots.) 

tive  points  will  go  to,  and  remain  at,  the  states  of  equilibrium. 
When  they  are  there,  a  leftwards  displacement  sufficient  to 
cause  the  representative  point  of  A  to  encounter  the  critical  states 
may  be  insufficient  if  applied  to  C;  so  C's  field  may  survive 
a  displacement  that  destroyed  A's.  Similarly  a  displacement  ap- 
plied to  the  representative  point  on  the  cycle  in  B  is  more  likely 

190 


14/10     REPETITIVE     STIMULI     AND     HABITUATION 

to  change  the  field  than  if  applied  to  C.  A  field  like  C,  therefore, 
with  its  state  of  equilibrium  near  the  centre  of  the  region,  tends 
to  have  a  higher  immunity  to  displacement  than  fields  whose 
states  of  equilibrium  or  cycles  go  near  the  edge  of  the  region. 

14/10.  How  would  this  tendency  show  itself  in  the  behaviour  of 
the  living  organism  ? 

The  processes  of  S.  7/23  allow  a  field  to  be  terminal  and  yet 
to  show  all  sorts  of  bizarre  features :  cycles,  states  of  equilibrium 
near  the  edge  of  the  region,  stable  and  unstable  lines  mixed, 
multiple  states  of  equilibrium,  multiple  cycles,  and  so  on.  These 
possibilities  obscured  the  relation  between  a  field's  being  terminal 
and  its  being  suitable  for  keeping  essential  variables  within  normal 
limits.  But  a  detailed  study  was  not  necessary;  for  we  have 
just  seen  that  all  such  bizarre  fields  tend  selectively  to  be  destroyed 
when  the  system  is  subjected  to  small,  occasional,  and  random  dis- 
turbances. Since  such  disturbances  are  inseparable  from  practical 
existence,  the  process  of  '  roughing  it  '  tends  to  cause  their  replace- 
ment by  fields  that  look  like  C  of  Figure  14/9/1  and  act  simply 
to  keep  the  representative  point  well  away  from  the  critical  states. 


191 


CHAPTER   15 

Adaptation  in  Iterated  and 
Serial  Systems 

15/1.  The  last  three  chapters  have  been  concerned  primarily 
with  technique,  with  the  logic  of  mechanism,  when  the  mechanism 
shows  partial,  fluctuating  and  temporary  divisions  into  sub- 
systems within  the  whole ;  they  have  considered  specially  the  case 
when  the  subsystems  are  rich  in  states  of  equilibrium.  We  can 
now  take  up  again  the  thread  left  at  S.  11/13,  and  can  go  on  to 
consider  the  problem  of  how  a  large  and  complex  organism  can 
adapt  to  a  large  and  complex  environment  without  taking  the 
almost  infinite  time  suggested  by  S.  11/5. 

The  remaining  chapters  will  offer  evidence  that  the  facts  are 
as  follows: 

(1)  The  ordinary  terrestrial  environment  has  a  distribution  of 
properties  very  different  from  the  distribution  assumed  when  the 
estimate  of  S.  11/2  came  out  so  high. 

(2)  Against  the  actual  distribution  of  terrestrial  environments 
the  process  of  ultrastability  can  often  give  adaptation  in  a  reason- 
ably short  time. 

(3)  When  particular  environments  do  get  more  complex,  the 
time  of  adaptation  goes  up,  not  only  in  theoretical  ultrastable 
systems  but  in  real  living  ones. 

(4)  When  the  environment  is  excessively  complex  and  close- 
knit,  the  theoretical  ultrastable  system  and  the  real  living  fail 
alike. 

In  this  chapter  and  the  next  we  will  examine  environments  of 
gradually  increasing  complexity.  (What  is  meant  by  4  com- 
plexity '  will  appear  as  we  proceed.) 

15/2.  In  S.  11/11  it  was  suggested  that  the  Homeostat  (i.e.  the 
two  units  or  so  marked  off  to  represent  '  environment  ')  is  not 
typical  of  the  terrestrial  environment  because  in  the  Homeostat 
every  variable  is  joined  directly  to  every  other  variable,  so  that 

192 


15/2      ADAPTATION    IN    ITERATED    AND    SERIAL    SYSTEMS 

what  happens  at  each  variable  is  conditional,  at  that  moment, 
on  the  values  of  all  the  other  variables  in  the  system.  What, 
then,  does  characterise  the  ordinary  terrestrial  environments  from 
this  point  of  view  ? 

Common  observation  shows  that  the  ordinary  terrestrial 
environment  usually  shows  several  features,  which  are  closely 
related  : 

(1)  Many  of  the  variables,  often  the  majority,  are  constant  over 
appreciable  intervals  of  time,  and  thus  behave  as  part-functions. 
Thus,  the  mammal  stands  on  ground  that  is  almost  always  im- 
mobile; tree-trunks  keep  their  positions;  a  cup  placed  on  a  table 
will  stay  there  till  a  force  of  more  than  a  certain  amount  arrives. 
If  one  looks  around  one,  only  in  the  most  chaotic  surroundings 
will  all  the  variables  be  changing.  This  constancy,  this  common- 
ness of  part-functions,  must,  by  S.  12/14,  be  due  to  commonness 
of  states  of  equilibrium  in  the  parts  that  compose  the  terrestrial 
environment.  Thus  the  environment  of  the  living  organism  tends 
typically  to  consist  of  parts  that  are  rich  in  states  of  equilibrium. 

(2)  Associated  with  this  constancy  (naturally  enough  by  S. 
12/17)  is  the  fact  that  most  variables  of  the  environment  have  an 
immediate  effect  on  only  a  few  of  the  totality  of  variables.  At 
the  moment,  for  instance,  if  I  dip  my  pen  in  the  ink-well,  hardly 
a  single  other  variable  in  the  room  is  affected.  Opening  of  the 
door  may  disturb  the  positions  of  a  few  sheets  of  paper,  but  will 
not  affect  the  chairs,  the  electric  light,  the  books  on  the  shelves, 
and  a  host  of  others. 

We  are,  in  fact,  led  again  to  consider  the  properties  of  a  system 
whose  connexions  are  fluctuating  and  conditional — the  type 
encountered  before  in  S.  11/12,  and  therefore  treatable  by  the 
same  method.  I  suggest,  therefore,  that  most  of  the  environ- 
ments encountered  on  this  earth  by  living  organisms  contain  many 
part-functions.  Conversely,  a  system  of  part-functions  adequately 
represents  a  very  wide  class  of  commonly  occurring  environ- 
ments. 

As  a  confirmatory  example,  here  is  Jennings'  description  of  an 
hour  in  the  life  of  Paramecium,  with  the  part-functions  indicated 
as  they  occur. 

(It  swims  upwards  and)  '.  .  .  thus  reaches  the  surface  film.' 

The  effects  of  the  surface,  being  constant  at  zero  throughout  the 

193 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  15/2 

depths  of  the  pond,  will  vary  as  part-functions.  A  discontinuity 
like  a  surface  will  generate  part-functions  in  a  variety  of  ways. 

'  Now  there  is  a  strong  mechanical  jar — someone  throws  a 
stone  into  the  water  perhaps.' 

Intermittent  variations  of  this  type  will  cause  variations  of  part- 
function  form  in  many  variables. 

(The  Paramecium  dives)  '.  .  .  this  soon  brings  it  into  water 
that  is  notably  lacking  in  oxygen.' 

The  content  of  oxygen  will  vary  sometimes  as  part-,  sometimes  as 
full-,  function,  depending  on  what  range  is  considered.  Jennings, 
by  not  mentioning  the  oxygen  content  before,  was  evidently 
assuming  its  constancy. 

'.  .  .  it  approaches  a  region  where  the  sun  has  been  .  .  . 
heating  the  water.' 

Temperature  of  the  water  will  behave  sometimes  as  part-,  some- 
times as  full-,  function. 

(It  wanders  on)  '.  .  .  into  the  region  of  a  fresh  plant  stem 
which  has  lately  been  crushed.  The  plant -juice,  oozing  out, 
alters  markedly  the  chemical  constitution  of  the  water.' 

Elsewhere  the  concentration  (at  zero)  of  these  substances  is 
constant. 

8  Other  Paramecia  .  .  .  often  strike  together  '  (collide). 

The  pressure  on  the  Parameciwri's  anterior  end  varies  as  a  part- 
function. 

'  The  animal  may  strike  against  stones.' 
Similar  part-functions. 

'  Our  animal  comes  against  a  decayed,  softened,  leaf.' 

More  part-functions. 

'.  .  .  till  it  comes  to  a  region  containing  more  carbon  dioxide 
than  usual.' 

Concentration  of  carbon  dioxide,  being  generally  uniform  with 
local  increases,  will  vary  in  space  as  a  part-function. 

1  Finally  it  comes  to  the  source  of  the  carbon  dioxide — a  large 
mass  of  bacteria,  embedded  in  zoogloea.' 

Another  part-function  due  to  contact. 

194 


15/2      ADAPTATION    IN    ITERATED    AND    SERIAL    SYSTEMS 

It  is  clear  that  the  ecological  world  of  Paramecium  contains 
many  part-functions,  and  so  too  do  the  worlds  of  most  living 
organisms. 

A  total  environment,  or  universe,  that  contains  many  part- 
functions,  will  show  dispersion,  in  that  the  set  of  variables  active 
at  one  moment  will  often  be  different  from  the  set  active  at  another. 
The  pattern  of  activity  within  the  environment  will  therefore  tend, 
as  in  S.  13/18,  to  be  fluctuating  and  conditional  rather  than 
invariant.  As  an  animal  interacts  with  its  environment,  the 
observer  will  see  that  the  activity  in  the  environment  is  limited 
now  to  this  set,  now  to  that.  If  one  set  persists  active  for  a  long 
time  and  the  rest  remains  inactive  and  inconspicuous,  the  observer 
may,  if  he  pleases,  call  the  first  set  '  the  '  environment.  And  if 
later  the  activity  changes  to  another  set  he  may,  if  he  pleases, 
call  it  a  '  second  '  environment.  It  is  the  presence  of  part- 
functions  and  dispersion  that  makes  this  change  of  view  reasonable. 

An  organism  that  tries  to  adapt  to  an  environment  composed 
largely  of  part-functions  will  find  that  the  environment  is  composed 
of  subsystems  which  sometimes  are  independent  but  which  from 
time  to  time  show  linkage.  The  alternation  is  shown  clearly 
when  one  learns  to  drive  a  car.  The  beginner  has  to  struggle 
with  several  subsystems:  he  has  to  learn  to  control  the  steering- 
wheel  and  the  car's  relation  to  road  and  pedestrian;  he  has  to 
learn  to  control  the  accelerator  and  its  relation  to  engine-speed, 
learning  neither  to, race  the  engine  nor  to  stall  it;  and  he  has  to 
learn  to  change  gear,  neither  burning  the  clutch  nor  stripping  the 
cogs.  On  an  open,  level,  empty  road  he  can  ignore  accelerator 
and  gear  and  can  study  steering  as  if  the  other  two  systems  did 
not  exist ;  and  at  the  bench  he  can  learn  to  change  gear  as  if  steer- 
ing did  not  exist.  But  on  an  ordinary  journey  the  relations  vary. 
For  much  of  the  time  the  three  systems 

driver  +  steering  wheel  +  .  .  . 
driver  +  accelerator  +  .  .  . 
driver  -f-  gear  lever  -J-  •  •  • 

could  be  regarded  as  independent,  each  complete  in  itself.  But 
from  time  to  time  they  interact.  Not  only  may  any  two  use 
common  variables  in  the  driver  (in  arms,  legs,  brain)  but  some 
linkage  is  provided  by  the  machine  and  the  world  around.  Thus, 
any  attempt  to  change  gear  must  involve  the  position  of  the 
accelerator  and  the  speed  of  the  engine;   and  turning  sharply 

195 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  15/3 

round  a  corner  should  be  preceded  both  by  a  slowing  down  and 
by  a  change  of  gear.  The  whole  system  thus  shows  that  temporary 
and  conditional  division  into  subsystems  that  is  typical  of  the 
whole  that  is  composed  largely  of  part-functions. 

Thus  the  terrestrial  environment  conforms  largely  to  the  poly- 
stable  type. 

15/3.  To  study  how  ultrastability  will  act  when  the  environment 
is  not  fully  joined,  we  shall  have  to  use  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17  and 
pick  out  certain  cases  as  type-forms.  We  will  therefore  consider 
environments  with  four  degrees  of  connectedness. 

First  we  will  consider  (in  S.  15/4-7)  the  '  whole  '  in  which  the 
connexion  between  the  parts  is  actually  zero — the  limiting  case 
as  the  connexions  get  less  and  less. 

In  S.  15/8-11  we  will  consider  the  case  in  which  actual  con- 
nexions exist,  but  in  which  the  subsystems  are  connected  in  a 
chain,  without  feedback  between  subsystems.  These  two  cases 
will  suffice  to  demonstrate  certain  basic  properties. 

In  the  next  chapter  we  will  consider  the  more  realistic  case  in 
which  the  subsystems  are  joined  unrestrictedly  in  direction,  so 
that  feedback  occurs  between  the  subsystems.  This  case  will  be 
considered  in  two  stages:  first,  in  S.  16/2-4  we  will  dispose  of  the 
case  in  which  the  connexions  are  rich;  and  then,  from  S.  16/5 
onwards,  we  will  consider  the  most  interesting  case,  that  in  which 
the  connexions  are  in  all  directions,  so  that  feedback  occurs 
between  the  subsystems,  but  in  which  the  connexions  are  not  rich 
so  that  the  whole  can  be  regarded  as  formed  from  subsystems 
each  of  which  is  richly  connected  internally,  joined  by  connexions 
(between  the  subsystems)  that  are  much  poorer — the  case,  in  fact, 
of  the  system  that  is  neither  richly  joined  nor  unjoined. 


Adaptation  in  iterated  systems 

15/4.  The  first  case  to  be  considered  is  that  in  which  the  whole 
system,  of  organism  and  environment,  is  actually  divided  into 
subsystems  that  (at  least  during  the  time  of  observation)  do  not 
have  any  effective  action  on  one  another.  Thus  instead  of  A 
in  Figure  15/4/1  we  are  considering  B.  (For  simplicity,  the 
diagram  shows  lines  instead  of  arrows.)  If  the  whole  system 
consists  of  organism  and  environment,  the  actual  division  between 

196 


15/5      ADAPTATION    IN    ITERATED    AND    SERIAL    SYSTEMS 


• • 


B 


Figure  15/4/1. 

the  two  might  be  that  shown  in  Figure  15/4/2.  Such  an  arrange- 
ment would  be  shown  functionally  by  any  organism  that  deals 
with  its  environment  by  several  independent  reactions.  Such  a 
whole  will  be  said  to  consist  of  iterated  systems. 

Environment. 


1 

/ 

\ 

Animal 

Figure  15/4/2  :  Diagrammatic  representation  of  an  animalof  eight  variables 
interacting  with  its  environment  as  five  independent  systems. 

S.  13/10  exemplified  the  argument  applicable  to  such  a  '  whole  \ 
If  i  is  the  number  of  subsystems  that  are  at  a  state  of  equilibrium 
at  any  particular  moment,  then  in  an  iterated  set  i  cannot  fall, 
and  will  usually  rise.  As  subsystem  after  subsystem  reaches 
equilibrium  so  will  each  stay  there ;  and  thus  the  whole  will  change 
cumulatively  towards  total  equilibrium. 

15/5.  Whether  the  feedbacks  in  Figure  15/4/2  are  first  order  or 
second  (S.  7/5)  is  here  irrelevant:  the  whole  still  moves  to  equili- 
brium progressively.  Thus,  if  each  subsystem  has  essential 
variables  and  step-mechanisms  as  in  Figure  7/5/1,  the  stability 
of  the  second  order  will  develop  as  in  S.  7/23;  and  thus  the 
adaptation  of  the  whole  to  this  environment  will  also  develop 
cumulatively  and  progressively. 

In  this  case,  the  processes  of  learning  by  trial  and  error  will 
go  on  in  one  subsystem  independently  of  what  is  going  on  in  the 
others.  That  such  independent,  localised  learning  can  occur 
within  one  animal  was  shown  by  Parker  in  the  following  experi- 
ment: 

4  If  a  sea-anemone  is  fed  from  one  side  of  its  mouth,  it  will 

197 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  15/6 

take  in,  by  means  of  the  tentacles  on  that  side,  one  fragment 
of  food  after  another.  If  now  bits  of  food  be  alternated  with 
bits  of  filter  paper  soaked  in  meat  juice,  the  two  materials 
will  be  accepted  indiscriminately  for  some  eight  or  ten  trials, 
after  which  only  the  meat  will  be  taken  and  the  filter  paper 
will  be  discharged  into  the  sea  water  without  being  brought 
to  the  mouth.  If,  after  having  developed  this  state  of  affairs 
on  one  side  of  the  mouth,  the  experiment  is  now  transferred 
to  the  opposite  side,  both  the  filter  paper  and  the  meat  will 
again  be  taken  in  till  this  side  has  also  been  brought  to  a  state 
of  discriminating.' 

15/6.  What  of  the  time  taken  by  the  iterated  set  to  become 
adapted  ?  T3  (of  S.  11/5)  is  applicable  here;  so  the  extremeness 
of  Tx  is  not  to  be  feared.  Thus,  however  large  the  whole,  if  it 
should  actually  consist  of  iterated  subsystems,  then  the  time  it 
takes  to  get  adapted  may  be  expected  to  be  of  the  same  order  as 
that  taken  by  one  of  its  subsystems.  If  this  time  is  fairly  short, 
the  whole  may  be  very  large  and  yet  become  adapted  in  a  fairly 
short  time. 

15/7.  If  Figure  15/4/2  is  re-drawn  so  as  to  show  explicitly  its 
relation  to  the  system  of  Figure  7/5/1  the  result  is  that  shown 
in  Figure  15/7/1  (where  the  subsystems  have  been  reduced  to 
three  for  simplicity  in  the  diagram). 

At  once  the  reader  may  be  struck  by  the  fact  that  the  three 
reacting  parts  in  the  organism  (in  its  brain  usually)  are  represented 
as  having  no  connexion  between  them:  is  this  not  a  fatal  flaw  ? 

The  subject  is  discussed  more  thoroughly  in  S.  17/2;  here  a 
partial  answer  can  be  given.  Let  us  compare  the  course  of 
adaptation  as  it  would  proceed  (1)  with  the  two  left-hand  sub- 
systems wholly  unconnected  as  shown,  and  (2)  with  the  reacting 
part  of  subsystem  A  having  some  immediate  effect  on  subsystem  B. 

The  first  case  is  straightforward:  each  subsystem  is  a  little 
ultrastable  system,  homologous  with  that  of  S.  7/5/1,  and  each 
would  proceed  to  adaptation  in  the  usual  way. 

When  B  is  joined  so  as  to  be  affected  by  A,  however,  the  whole 
course  is  somewhat  changed.  A  is  unaffected,  so  it  will  proceed 
to  adaptation  as  before;  but  B,  previously  isolated,  is  now  affected 
by  one  or  more  parameters  that  need  no  longer  be  constant.  The 
effect  on  B  will  depend  on  whether  the  effect  comes  to  B  from  A's 
reacting  part  or  from  A's  step-mechanisms.     If  from  the  step- 

198 


15/7       ADAPTATION     IN    ITERATED    AND     SERIAL    SYSTEMS 

Environment 


Organism 

Figure  15/7/1  :  Sketch  of  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  of  an  organism 
adapting  to  an  environment  as  three  separate  subsystems.  (Compare 
Figures  15/8/1  and  16/6/1.) 

mechanisms,  B  can  achieve  no  permanent  adaptation  until  A  has 
reached  adaptation,  for  their  values  will  keep  changing.  However, 
once  A's  step-mechanisms  have  reached  their  terminal  values,  B's 
parameters  will  be  constant,  and  B  can  then  commence  profitably 
its  own  search,  undisturbed  by  further  changes.  Thus  the  join 
from  A's  step-mechanisms  will  about  double  the  time  taken  for  the 
whole  to  reach  adaptation. 

If,  however,  the  effect  comes  to  B  from  A's  reacting  part,  then 
even  after  A  has  reached  adaptation,  every  time  that  A  shows  its 
adaptation  (by  responding  appropriately  to  a  disturbance  to  its 
environment),  the  lines  of  behaviour  that  A's  reacting  part  follow 
will  provide  B  with  a  varying  set  of  values  at  its  parameters. 
B  is  thus  in  a  situation  homologous  to  that  of  the  Homeostat 
in  S.  8/10,  except  that  B  may  be  subject  to  parameter-values 
many  more  than  two.  The  time  that  B  will  take  to  reach  adapta- 
tion under  all  these  values  is  thus  apt  to  resemble  Tx  (S.  11/5),  and 
thus  to  be  excessively  long.  Thus  a  joining  from  the  reacting 
part  of  A  to  that  of  B  may  have  the  effect  of  postponing  the  whole's 
adaptation  almost  indefinitely. 

199 


DESIGN     FOR    A    BRAIN 


15/8 


These  remaiks  are  probably  sufficient  for  the  moment  to  show 
that  the  absence  of  connexions  between  organismal  subsystems 
in  Figure  15/7/1  does  not  condemn  the  representation  off-hand. 
There  is  more  to  this  matter  of  joining  than  is  immediately 
evident.     (The  topic  is  resumed  in  S.  17/2.) 

Serial  adaptation 

15/8.  By  S.  15/3,  our  second  stage  of  connectedness  in  the  system 
occurs  when  the  parts  of  the  environment  are  joined  as  a  chain. 
Figure  15/8/1  illustrates  the  case. 


Figure  15/8/1. 

Without  enquiring  at  the  moment  into  exactly  what  will 
happen,  it  is  obvious,  by  analogy  with  the  previous  section,  that 
adaptation  must  occur  in  the  sequence — A  first,  then  B,  then  C. 
Thus  we  are  considering  the  case  of  the  organism  that  faces  an 
environment  whose  parts  are  so  related  that  the  environment  can 
be  adapted  to  only  by  a  process  that  respects  its  natural  articulation. 


15/9.  Such  environments  are  of  common  occurrence.  A  puppy 
can  learn  rabbit-catching  only  after  it  has  learned  how  to  run: 
the  environment  does  not  allow  the  two  reactions  to  be  learned  in 
the  opposite  order.  A  great  deal  of  learning  occurs  in  this  way. 
Mathematics,  for  instance,  though  too  vast  and  intricate  for  one 
all-comprehending  flash,  can  be  mastered  by  stages.  The  stages 
have  a  natural  articulation  which  must  be  respected  if  mastery  is 

200 


15/10   ADAPTATION    IN    ITERATED    AND    SERIAL    SYSTEMS 

to  be  achieved.  Thus,  the  learner  can  proceed  in  the  order 
'  Addition,  long  multiplication,  .  .  .'  but  not  in  the  order  '  Long 
multiplication,  addition,  .  .  .'  Our  present  knowledge  of  mathe- 
matics has  in  fact  been  reached  only  because  the  subject  contains 
such  stage-by-stage  routes. 

As  a  clear  illustration  of  such  a  process,  here  is  Lloyd  Morgan 
on  the  training  of  a  falcon: 

1  She  is  trained  to  the  lure — a  dead  pigeon  .  .  . — at  first  with 
the  leash.  Later  a  light  string  is  attached  to  the  leash,  and 
the  falcon  is  unhooded  by  an  assistant,  while  the  falconer, 
standing  at  a  distance  of  five  to  ten  yards,  calls  her  by  shout- 
ing and  casting  out  the  lure.  Gradually  day  after  day  the 
distance  is  increased,  till  the  hawk  will  come  thirty  yards  or 
so  without  hesitation;  then  she  may  be  trusted  to  fly  to  the 
lure  at  liberty,  and  by  degrees  from  any  distance,  say  a 
thousand  yards.  This  accomplished,  she  should  learn  to 
stoop  to  the  lure.  .  .  .  This  should  be  done  at  first  only 
once,  and  then  progressively  until  she  will  stoop  backwards 
and  forwards  at  the  lure  as  often  as  desired.  Next  she  should 
be  entered  at  her  quarry  .  .  .' 

The  same  process  has  also  been  demonstrated  more  formally. 
Wolfe  and  Cowles,  for  instance,  taught  chimpanzees  that  tokens 
could  be  exchanged  for  fruit:  the  chimpanzees  would  then  learn 
to  open  problem  boxes  to  get  tokens;  but  this  way  of  getting  fruit 
(the  '  adaptive  '  reaction)  was  learned  only  if  the  procedure  for 
the  exchange  of  tokens  had  been  well  learned  first.  In  other 
words,  the  environment  was  beyond  their  power  of  adaptation 
if  presented  as  a  complex  whole — they  could  not  get  the  fruit — 
but  if  taken  as  two  stages  in  a  particular  order,  could  be  adapted  to. 

\  .  .  the  growing  child  fashions  day  by  day,  year  by  year,  a 
complex  concatenation  of  acquired  knowledge  and  skills,  adding 
one  unit  to  another  in  endless  sequence  ',  said  Culler.  I  need  not 
further  emphasise  the  importance  of  serial  adaptation. 

15/10.  To  see  the  process  in  more  detail,  consider  the  following 
example.  A  young  animal  has  already  learned  how  to  move  about 
the  world  without  colliding  with  objects.  (Though  this  learning 
is  itself  complex,  it  will  serve  for  illustration,  and  has  the  advantage 
of  making  the  example  more  vivid.)  This  learning  process  was 
due  to  ultrastability :  it  has  established  a  set  of  values  on  the 
step-mechanisms  which  give  a  field  such  that  the  system  composed 

201 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


15/10 


of  eyes,  muscles,  skin-receptors,  some  parts  of  the  brain,  and  hard 
external  objects  is  stable  and  always  acts  so  as  to  keep  within 
limits  the  mechanical  stresses  and  pressures  caused  by  objects  in 
contact  with  the  skin-receptors  (S.  5/4).  The  diagram  of  immedi- 
ate effects  will  therefore  resemble  Figure  15/10/1.  This  system 
will  be  referred  to  as  part  A,  the  '  avoiding  '  system. 


BRAIN   -«- 


EYES 


SKIN 


MUSCLE  S 


^-OBJECTS 


Figure  15/10/1  : 
system. 


Diagram  of  immediate  effects  of  the  '  avoiding  ' 
Each  word  represents  many  variables. 


As  the  animal  must  now  get  its  own  food,  the  brain  must 
develop  a  set  of  values  on  step-me'chanisms  that  will  give  a  field 
in  which  the  brain  and  the  food-supply  occur  as  variables,  and 
which  is  stable  so  that  it  holds  the  blood-glucose  concentration 
within  normal  limits.  (This  system  will  be  referred  to  as  part  B, 
the  '  feeding  '  system.)  This  development  will  also  occur  by 
ultrastability ;  but  while  this  is  happening  the  two  systems  will 
interact. 

The  interaction  will  occur  because,  while  the  animal  is  making 
trial-and-error  attempts  to  get  food,  it  will  repeatedly  meet 
objects  with  which  it  might  collide.  The  interaction  is  very 
obvious  when  a  dog  chases  a  rabbit  through  a  wood.  Further, 
there  is  the  possibility  that  the  processes  of  dispersion  within  brain 
and  environment  may  allow  the  two  reactions  to  use  common 
variables.  When  the  systems  interact,  the  diagram  of  immediate 
effects  will  resemble  Figure  15/10/2. 


BLOOD 

glucose' 


-^-  BRAIN     -<- 


f 


FOOD       . 
SUPPLY  "*" 


V 


EYES 


SKIN 


V 

MUSC  LES 


— >OBJECTS 

B  A 

Figure  15/10/2. 

Let  us  assume  at  this  point  (simply  to  get  a  clear  discussable 
case)  that  the  step-mechanisms  affecting  A  are,  for  whatever 
reason,  not  changeable  while  the  adaptation  to  B  is  occurring 
(compare  S.  10/8).     As  the  '  avoiding  '  system  A  is  not  subject 

202 


15/11    ADAPTATION     IN     ITERATED     AND     SERIAL    SYSTEMS 

to  further  step-function  changes,  its  field  will  not  alter,  and  it 
will  at  all  times  react  in  its  characteristic  way.  So  the  whole 
system  is  equivalent  to  an  ultrastable  system  B  interacting  with 
an  '  environment  '  A.  It  would  also  be  equivalent  to  an  ultra- 
stable  system  interacting  with  an  inborn  reflex,  as  in  S.  3/12.  B 
will  therefore  change  its  step-mechanism  values  until  the  whole 
has  a  field  which  is  stable  and  which  holds  within  limits  the 
variable  (blood-glucose  concentration)  whose  extreme  deviations 
cause  the  step-mechanisms  to  change.  We  know  from  S.  8/11 
that,  whatever  the  peculiarities  of  A,  B's  terminal  field  will  be 
adapted  to  them. 

It  should  be  noticed  that  the  seven  sets  of  variables  (Figure 
15/10/2)  are  grouped  in  one  way  when  viewed  anatomically  and 
in  a  very  different  way  when  viewed  functionally.  The  anato- 
mical point  of  view  sees  five  sets  in  the  animal's  body  and  two  sets 
in  the  outside  world.  The  functional  point  of  view  sees  the  whole 
as  composed  of  two  parts :  an  '  adapting  '  part  B,  to  which  A 
is  '  environment '. 

It  is  now  possible  to  predict  how  the  system  will  behave  after 
the  above  processes  have  occurred.  Because  part  A,  the  '  avoid- 
ing '  system,  is  unchanged,  the  behaviour  of  the  whole  will  still 
be  such  that  collisions  do  not  occur;  and  the  reactions  to  the 
food  supply  will  maintain  the  blood-glucose  within  normal  limits. 
But,  in  addition,  because  B  became  adapted  to  A,  the  getting  of 
food  will  be  modified  so  that  it  does  not  involve  collisions,  for  all 
such  variations  will  have  been  eliminated. 

15/11.  What  of  the  time  required  for  adaptation  of  all  the  essen- 
tial variables  when  the  environment  is  so  joined  in  a  chain  ? 

The  dominating  subsystem  A  will,  of  course,  proceed  to  adapta- 
tion in  the  ordinary  way.  B,  however,  even  when  A  is  adapted 
may  still  be  disturbed  to  some  degree  by  changes  coming  to  it 
from  A,  changes  that  come  ultimately  from  the  disturbances  to 
A  that  A  must  adapt  against.  C  -also  may  get  upset  by  some  of 
these  disturbances,  transmitted  through  B,  and  so  on.  Thus  each 
subsystem  down  the  chain  is  likely  to  be  disturbed  by  all  the 
disturbances  that  come  to  the  subsystems  that  dominate  it,  and 
also  by  the  reactive,  adaptive  changes  made  by  the  same  domin- 
ating subsystems. 

It  is  now  clear  how  important  is  the  channel-capacity  of  the 

203 


DESIGN     FOR    A    BRAIN  15/11 

connexions  that  transmit  disturbances  down  the  chain.  If  their 
capacity  is  high,  so  much  disturbance  may  be  transmitted  to  the 
lower  members  of  the  chain  that  their  adaptations  may  be  post- 
poned indefinitely.  If  their  capacity  is  low,  the  attenuation  may 
be  so  rapid  that  C,  though  affected  by  B,  may  be  practically 
unaffected  by  what  happens  at  A;  and  a  further  subsystem  D 
may  be  practically  unaffected  by  those  at  B;  and  so  on.  Thus, 
as  the  connexions  between  the  subsystems  get  weaker,  so  does 
adaptation  tend  to  the  sequential — first  A,  then  B,  then  C,  and 
so  on.     (The  limit,  of  course,  is  the  iterated  set.) 

If  the  adaptation  is  sequential,  the  behaviour  corresponds  to 
that  of  Case  2  (S.  11/5).  The  time  of  adaptation  will  then  be 
that  of  the  moderate  T2  rather  than  that  of  the  excessively  long 
2\.  Thus  adaptation,  even  with  a  large  organism  facing  a  large 
environment,  may  be  achievable  in  a  moderate  time  if  the  environ- 
ment consists  of  subsystems  in  a  chain,  with  only  channels  of 
small  capacity  between  them. 


204 


CHAPTER   16 

Adaptation  in  the  Multistable  System 

16/1.  Continuing  our  study  of  types  of  environment  we  next 
consider,  after  Figures  15/7/1  and  15/8/1,  the  case  in  which  the 
subsystems  of  the  environment  are  connected  unrestrictedly  in 
direction,  so  that  feedbacks  occur  between  them.  This  type  of 
environment  may  vary  according  to  the  amounts  of  communica- 
tion (variety)  that  are  transmitted  between  subsystem  and  sub- 
system.    Two  degrees  are  of  special  interest  as  types: 

(1)  those  in  which  it  is  near  the  maximum — the  richly  joined 

environment.     (The  exposition  is  more  convenient  if  we 
consider  this  case  first,  as  it  can  be  dismissed  briefly.) 

(2)  those  in  which  the  amount  is  small. 

The  richly  joined  environment 
16/2.     When  a  set  of  subsystems  is  richly  joined,  each  variable 
is  as  much  affected  by  variables  in  other  subsystems  as  by  those 
in  its  own.     When  this  occurs,  the  division  of  the  whole  into 
subsystems  ceases  to  have  any  natural  basis. 

The  case  of  the  richly  joined  environment  thus  leads  us  back  to 
the  case  discussed  in  Chapter  11. 

16/3.  Examples  of  environments  that  are  both  large  and  richly 
connected  are  not  common,  for  our  terrestrial  environment  is 
widely  characterised  by  being  highly  subdivided  (S.  15/2).  A 
richly  connected  environment  would  therefore  intuitively  be  per- 
ceived as  something  unusual,  or  even  unnatural.  The  examples 
given  below  are  somewhat  recherche,  but  they  will  suffice  to  make 
clear  what  is  to  be  expected  in  this  case. 

The  combination  lock  was  mentioned  in  S.  11/9.  Though  not 
vigorous  dynamically,  its  parts,  so  far  as  they  affect  the  output 
at  the  bolt,  are  connected  in  that  the  relations  between  them 
are  highly  conditional.  Thus,  if  there  are  seven  dials  that  allow 
the  bolt  to  move  only  when  set  at  RHOMBUS,  then  the  effect 

205 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  16/3 

of  the  first  dial  going  to  R  on  the  movement  of  the  bolt  is  con- 
ditional on  the  positions  of  all  the  other  six;  and  similarly  for 
the  second  and  remaining  letters. 

A  second  example  is  given  by  a  set  of  simultaneous  equations, 
which  can  legitimately  be  regarded  as  the  temporary  environment 
of  a  professional  computer  if  he  is  paid  simply  to  get  correct 
answers.     Sometimes  they  come  in  the  simplest  form,  e.g. 

2x  =  8     ^| 
3y  =  -7\ 

iz  =  S     J 

Then  they  correspond  to  the  iterated  form  ;    and  each  line  can 
be  treated  without  reference  to  the  others,  as  in  S.  15/4. 
Sometimes  they  are  rather  more  complex,  e.g. 

2x  =  3^ 

3x  —  2y  =  2 

x  +    y  —  z  =  0. 

This  form  can  be  solved  serially,  as  in  S.  15/8;  for  the  first  line 
can  be  treated  without  reference  to  the  other  two;  then  when 
the  first  process  has  been  successful  the  second  line  can  be  treated 
without  reference  to  the  last;  and  so  to  the  end.  The  peculiarity 
of  this  form  is  that  the  value  of  x  is  not  conditional  on  the  values 
of  the  coefficients  in  the  second  and  third  lines. 
Sometimes  the  forms  are  more  complex,  e.g. 

2x  +    y  —  3z  =  2^ 

x  —    y  +  2z  =  0 

-x  _  sy  +    2  =  1. 

Now  the  value  of  x  is  conditional  on  the  values  of  all  the  coeffi- 
cients; and  in  finding  x,  no  coefficient  can  be  ignored.  The  same 
is  true  of  y  and  z.  Thus  if  we  regard  the  coefficients  as  the 
environment  and  the  values  of  x,  y  and  z  as  output,  correctness 
in  the  answer  demands  that,  in  getting  any  part  of  the  answer 
(any  one  of  the  three  values),  all  the  environment  must  be  taken 
into  account. 

A  third,  and  more  practical,  example  of  a  richly  connected 
environment  (now,  thank  goodness,  no  more)  faced  the  experi- 
menter in  the  early  days  of  the  cathode-ray  oscilloscope.  Adjust- 
ing the  first  experimental  models  was  a  matter  of  considerable 
complexity.     An  attempt  to  improve  the  brightness  of  the  spot 

200 


16/4        ADAPTATION     IN     THE     MULTISTABLE     SYSTEM 

might  make  the  spot  also  move  off  the  screen.  The  attempt  to 
bring  it  back  might  alter  its  rate  of  sweep  and  start  it  oscillating 
vertically.  An  attempt  to  correct  this  might  make  its  line  of 
sweep  leave  the  horizontal;  and  so  on.  This  system's  variables 
(brightness  of  spot,  rate  of  sweep,  etc.)  were  dynamically  linked 
in  a  rich  and  complex  manner.  Attempts  to  control  it  through 
the  available  parameters  were  difficult  precisely  because  the 
variables  were  richly  joined. 

16/4.  How  long  will  an  ultrastable  system  that  includes  such 
an  environment  take  to  get  adapted  ? 

This  is  the  question  of  S.  11/2.  Unless  a  large  fraction  of  the 
outcomes  are  acceptable,  the  time  taken  tends  to  be  like  Tx  of 
S.  11/5.  As  the  system  is  made  larger,  so  does  the  time  of 
adaptation  tend  to  increase  beyond  all  bounds  of  what  is  practical; 
in  other  words,  the  ultrastable  system  probably  fails.  But  this 
failure  does  not  discredit  the  ultrastable  system  as  a  model  of 
the  brain  (S.  8/17),  for  such  an  environment  is  one  that  is  also 
likely  to  defeat  the  living  brain.  That  the  living  organism  is 
notoriously  apt  to  find  such  environments  difficult  or  impossible 
for  adaptation  is  precisely  the  reason  why  the  combination  lock 
is  relied  on  for  protection. 

Even  when  a  skilled  thief  defeats  the  combination  lock  he 
supports,  rather  than  refutes,  the  thesis.  Thus  if  he  can  hear,  as 
each  dial  moves,  a  tumbler  fall  into  position,  then  the  environ- 
ment is  to  him  a  serial  one  (S.  15/8);  for  he  can  get  the  first  dial- 
setting  right  without  reference  to  the  others,  then  the  second,  and 
so  on.  The  time  of  its  opening  is  thus  made  vastly  shorter. 
Thus  the  skilled  thief  does  not  really  adapt  successfully  to  the 
richly  joined  environment — he  demonstrates  that  what  to  others 
is  richly  joined  is  to  him  joined  serially. 

Thus  the  first  answer  to  the  question :  how  does  the  ultrastable 
system,  or  the  brain,  adapt  to  a  richly  joined  environment  ?  is — it 
doesn't.  After  the  reasonableness  of  this  answer  has  been  made 
clear,  we  may  then  notice  that  sometimes  there  are  ways  in 
which  an  environment,  apparently  too  complex  for  adaptation, 
may  eventually  be  adapted  to;  perhaps  by  the  discovery  of 
ways  of  getting  through  the  necessary  trials  much  faster,  or 
perhaps  by  the  discovery  that  the  environment  is  not  really  as 
complex  as  it  looks.     (/.  to  C,  S.  13/4,  discusses  the  matter.) 

207 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  16/5 

The  poorly  joined  environment 

16/5.  We  will  finally  consider  the  case  in  which  the  environment 
consists  of  subsystems  joined  so  that  they  affect  one  another  only 
weakly,  or  occasionally,  or  only  through  other  subsystems.  It 
was  suggested  in  S.  15/2  that  this  is  the  common  case  in  almost 
all  natural  terrestrial  environments. 

If  the  degree  of  interaction  between  the  subsystems  varies,  its 
limits  are:  at  the  lower  end,  the  iterated  systems  of  S.  15/4  (as 
the  communication  between  subsystems  falls  to  zero),  and  at  the 
upper  end,  the  richly  connected  systems  of  S.  16/2  (as  the  com- 
munication rises  to  its  maximum). 

When  the  communication  between  subsystems  falls  much  below 
that  within  subsystems,  the  subsystems  will  show  naturally  and 
prominently  (S.  12/17). 

If  such  an  environment  acts  within  an  ultrastable  system,  what 
will  happen  ?  Will  adaptation  occur  ?  As  the  discussion  below 
will  show,  the  number  of  cases  is  so  many,  and  the  forms  so 
various,  that  no  detailed  and  exhaustive  account  is  possible.  We 
must  therefore  use  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17,  getting  certain  type- 
forms  quite  clear,  and  then  covering  the  remainder  by  some  appeal 
to  continuity:  that  so  far  as  other  forms  resemble  the  type-forms 
in  their  construction,  to  a  somewhat  similar  degree  will  they 
resemble  the  type-forms  in  their  behaviour. 

16/6.  To  obtain  a  secure  basis  for  the  discussion  of  this  most 
important  case,  let  us  state  explicitly  what  is  now  assumed: 

(1)  The  environment  is  assumed  to  be  as  described  in  S.  15/2, 
so  that  it  consists  of  large  numbers  of  subsystems  that  have  many 
states  of  equilibrium.  The  environment  is  thus  assumed  to  be 
polystable. 

(2)  Whether  because  the  primary  joins  between  the  subsystems 
are  few,  or  because  equilibria  in  the  subsystems  are  common,  the 
interaction  between  subsystems  is  assumed  to  be  weak. 

(3)  The  organism  coupled  to  this  environment  will  adapt  by 
the  basic  method  of  ultrastability,  i.e.  by  providing  second-order 
feedbacks  that  veto  all  states  of  equilibrium  except  those  that 
leave  each  essential  variable  within  its  proper  limits. 

(4)  The  organism's  reacting  part  is  itself  divided  into  sub- 
systems between  which  there  is  no  direct  connexion.     Each  sub- 

208 


16/7      ADAPTATION     IN     THE     MULTISTABLE     SYSTEM 

system  is  assumed  to  have  its  own  essential  variables  and  second 
order  feedback.  Figure  16/6/1  illustrates  the  connexions,  but 
somewhat  inadequately,  for  it  shows  only  three  subsystems.  (It 
should  be  compared  with  Figures  15/7/1  and  15/8/1.) 


k 

A 

B 

C 

> 

r 

>  r 

I       > 

r          1 

1        v 

Figure  16/6/1. 

Such  a  system  is  essentially  similar  to  the  multistable  system 
denned  in  the  first  edition.  (The  system  denned  there  allowed 
more  freedom  in  the  connexions  between  the  main  variables,  e.g. 
from  reacting  part  to  reacting  part,  and  between  reacting  part  and 
an  environmental  subsystem  other  than  that  chiefly  joined  to  it; 
these  minor  variations  are  a  nuisance  and  of  little  importance — 
in  the  next  chapter  we  shall  be  considering  such  variations.) 

16/7.  To  trace  the  behaviour  of  the  multistable  system,  suppose 
that  we  are  observing  two  of  the  subsystems,  e.g.  A  and  B  of 
Figure  16/6/1,  that  their  main  variables  are  directly  linked  so 
that  changes  of  either  immediately  affects  the  other,  and  that  for 
some  reason  all  the  other  subsystems  are  inactive. 

The  first  point  to  notice  is  that,  as  the  other  subsystems  are 
inactive,  their  presence  may  be  ignored;  for  they  become  like  the 
4  background  '  of  S.  6/1.  Even  if  some  are  active,  they  can  still 
be  ignored  if  the  two  observed  subsystems  are  separated  from 
them  by  a  wall  of  inactive  subsystems  (S.  12/10). 

The  next  point  to  notice  is  that  the  two  subsystems,  regarded 
as  a  unit,  form  a  whole  which  is  ultrastable.  This  whole  will 
therefore  proceed,  through  the  usual  series  of  events,  to  a  terminal 

209 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  16/8 

field.  Its  behaviour  will  not  be  essentially  different  from  that 
recorded  in  Figure  8/4/1.  If,  however,  we  regard  the  same 
series  of  events  as  occurring,  not  within  one  ultrastable  whole, 
but  as  interactions  between  a  minor  environment  and  a  minor 
organism,  each  of  two  subsystems,  then  we  shall  observe 
behaviours  homologous  with  those  observed  when  interaction 
occurs  between  4  organism  '  and  '  environment  '.  In  other  words, 
within  a  multistable  system,  subsystem  adapts  to  subsystem  in  exactly 
the  same  way  as  animal  adapts  to  environment.  Trial  and  error 
will  appear  to  be  used;  and,  when  the  process  is  completed,  the 
activities  of  the  two  parts  will  show  co-ordination  to  the  common 
end  of  maintaining  the  essential  variables  of  the  double  system 
within  their  proper  limits. 

Exactly  the  same  principle  governs  the  interactions  between  three 
subsystems.  If  the  three  are  in  continuous  interaction,  they  form 
a  single  ultrastable  system  which  will  have  the  usual  properties. 

As  illustration  we  can  take  the  interesting  case  in  which  two 
of  them,  A  and  C  say,  while  having  no  immediate  connexion 
with  each  other,  are  joined  to  an  intervening  system  B,  inter- 
mittently but  not  simultaneously.  Suppose  B  interacts  first  with 
A:  by  their  ultrastability  they  will  arrive  at  a  terminal  field. 
Next  let  B  and  C  interact.  If  B's  step-mechanisms,  together  with 
those  of  C,  give  a  stable  field  to  the  main  variables  of  B  and  C, 
then  that  set  of  B's  step-mechanism  values  will  persist  indefinitely; 
for  when  B  rejoins  A  the  original  stable  field  will  be  re-formed. 
But  if  B's  set  with  C's  does  not  give  stability,  then  it  will  be 
changed  to  another  set.  It  follows  that  2?'s  step-mechanisms  will 
stop  changing  when,  and  only  when,  they  have  a  set  of  values 
which  forms  fields  stable  with  both  A  and  C.  (The  identity  in 
principle  with  the  process  described  in  S.  8/10  should  be  noted.) 

16/8.  The  process  can  be  illustrated  on  the  Homeostat.  Three 
units  were  connected  so  that  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  was 
2  ^±  1  ^±  3  (corresponding  to  A,  B,  and  C  respectively).  To 
separate  the  effects  of  2  and  3  on  1,  bars  were  placed  across  the 
potentiometer  dishes  (Figure  8/2/2)  of  2  and  3  so  that  they  could 
move  only  in  the  direction  recorded  as  downwards  in  Figure 
16/8/1,  while  1  could  move  either  upwards  or  downwards.  If 
1  was  above  the  central  line  (shown  broken),  1  and  2  interacted, 
and  3  was  independent;  but  if  1  was  below  the  central  line,  then 

210 


16/8         ADAPTATION     IN    THE     MULTISTABLE     SYSTEM 


u    j'k'l»m»-T7 


-\j — \r 


v 


Tim<z 


Figure  16/8/1  :  Three  units  of  the  Homeostat  interacting.  Bars  in  the 
central  positions  prevent  2  and  3  from  moving  in  the  direction  corre- 
sponding here  to  upwards.  Vertical  strokes  on  U  record  changes  of 
uniselector  position  in  unit  1.  Disturbance  D,  made  by  the  operator, 
demonstrates  the  whole's  stability. 

1  and  3  interacted,  and  2  was  independent.     1  was  set  to  act  on 

2  negatively  and  on  3  positively,  while  the  effects  2  — >  1  and 

3  — >  1  were  uniselector-controlled. 

When  switched  on,  at  J,  1  and  2  formed  an  unstable  system 
and  the  critical  state  was  transgressed.  The  next  uniselector 
connexions  (K)  made  1  and  2  stable,  but  1  and  3  were  unstable. 
This  led  to  the  next  position  (L)  where  1  and  3  were  stable  but 
1  and  2  became  again  unstable.  The  next  position  (M)  did 
not  remedy  this;  but  the  following  position  (N)  happened  to 
provide  connexions  which  made  both  systems  stable.  The  values 
of  the  step-mechanisms  are  now  permanent;  1  can  interact  re- 
peatedly with  both  2  and  3  without  loss  of  stability. 

It  has  already  been  noticed  that  if  A,  B  and  C  should  form 
from  time  to  time  a  triple  combination,  then  the  step-mechanisms 
of  all  three  parts  will  stop  changing  when,  and  only  when,  the 
triple  combination  has  a  stable  field.  But  we  can  go  further 
than  that.  If  A,  B  and  C  should  join  intermittently  in  various 
ways,  sometimes  joining  as  pairs,  sometimes  as  a  triple,  and 
sometimes  remaining  independent,  then  their  step-mechanisms 
will  stop  changing  when,  and  only  when,  they  arrive  at  a  set  of 
values  which  gives  stability  to  all  the  arrangements. 

Clearly  the  same  line  of  reasoning  will  apply  no  matter  how 
many  subsystems  interact  or  in  what  groups  or  patterns  they 

211 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN  16/9 

join.  Always  we  can  predict  that  their  step -mechanisms  will  stop 
changing  when,  and  only  when,  the  combinations  are  all  stable. 
Ultrastable  systems,  whether  isolated  or  joined  in  multistable 
systems,  act  always  selectively  towards  those  step-mechanism 
values  which  provide  stability. 

16/9.  At  the  beginning  of  the  preceding  section  it  was  assumed, 
for  simplicity,  that  the  process  of  dispersion  was  suspended,  for 
we  assumed  that  the  two  subsystems  interacting  remained  the 
same  two  (e.g.  A  and  B  of  Figure  16/6/1)  during  the  whole  pro- 
cess. What  modifications  must  be  made  when  we  allow  for  the 
fact  that  in  a  multistable  system  the  number  and  distribution  of 
subsystems  active  at  each  moment  may  fluctuate  by  dispersion  ? 

The  progression  to  equilibrium  of  the  whole,  to  a  terminal  field, 
and  thus  to  adaptation  of  the  whole,  will  occur  whether  dispersion 
occurs  or  not.  The  effect  of  dispersion  is  to  destroy  the  indi- 
viduality of  the  subsystems  considered  in  the  previous  section. 
There  two  subsystems  were  pictured  as  going  through  the  complex 
processes  of  ultrastability,  their  main  variables  being  repeatedly 
active  while  those  of  the  surrounding  subsystems  remained 
inactive.  This  permanence  of  individuality  can  hardly  occur 
when  dispersion  occurs.  Thus,  suppose  that  a  multistable 
system's  field  of  all  its  main  variables  is  stable,  and  that  its  repre- 
sentative point  is  at  a  state  of  equilibrium  R.  If  the  representa- 
tive point  is  displaced  to  a  point  P,  the  lines  from  this  point  will 
lead  it  back  to  R.  As  the  point  travels  back  from  P  to  R,  sub- 
systems will  come  into  action,  perhaps  singly,  perhaps  in  com- 
bination, becoming  active  and  inactive  in  kaleidoscopic  variety 
and  apparent  confusion.  Travel  along  another  line  to  R  will 
also  activate  various  combinations  of  subsystems;  and  the  set 
made  active  in  the  second  line  may  be  very  different  from  that 
made  active  by  the  first. 

In  such  conditions  it  is  no  longer  profitable  to  observe  par- 
ticular sybsystems  when  a  multistable  system  adapts.  What 
will  happen  is  that  so  long  as  some  essential  variables  are  outside 
their  limits,  so  long  will  change  at  step-mechanisms  cause  com- 
bination after  combination  of  subsystems  to  become  active.  But 
when  a  stable  field  arises  not  causing  step-mechanisms  to  change, 
it  will,  as  usual,  be  retained.  If  now  the  multistable  system's 
adaptation  be  tested  by  displacements  of  its  representative  point, 

212 


16/11       ADAPTATION     IN     THE     MULTISTABLE     SYSTEM 

the  system  will  be  found  to  respond  by  various  activities  of  various 
subsystems,  all  co-ordinated  to  the  common  end.  But  though 
co-ordinated  in  this  way,  there  will,  in  general,  be  no  simple 
relation  between  the  actions  of  subsystem  on  subsystem :  knowing 
which  subsystems  were  activated  on  one  line  of  behaviour,  and 
how  they  interacted,  gives  no  certainty  about  which  will  be 
activated  on  some  other  line  of  behaviour,  or  how  they  will  interact. 
Later  I  shall  pefer  again  to  '  subsystem  A  adapting  to,  or 
interacting  with,  subsystem  B  ',  but  this  will  be  only  a  form  of 
words,  convenient  for  description:  it  is  to  be  understood  that 
what  is  A  and  what  is  B  may  change  from  moment  to  moment. 

16/10.  This  new  picture  answers  the  objection  to  Figure  16/6/1 
(and  the  others)  that  it  shows  a  tidiness  nowhere  evident  when  the 
organism  (or  the  environment)  is  examined  anatomically  or 
histologically.  The  Figures  are  diagrams  of  immediate  effects, 
and  are  intended  purely  as  an  aid  to  easier  thinking  about  func- 
tional and  behavioural  relationships.  They  must  be  regarded 
as  showing  only  functional  connexions,  and  of  these  only  those 
between  variables  that  are  active  over  some  small  interval  of 
time.  Figure  16/6/1  is  thus  apt  to  mislead  both  by  suggesting 
a  permanence  of  structure  that  does  not  exist  when  dispersion 
occurs,  and  by  suggesting  an  actual  two-dimensional  form  that 
may  well  have  no  anatomical  or  histological  existence.  Neverthe- 
less, the  functional  relationships  are  indisputable,  and  the  Figure 
represents  them.  How  they  are  related  to  variables  physically 
identifiable  in  the  brain  has  yet  to  be  discovered. 

16/11.  Though  the  multistable  system  may  look  chaotic  in 
action,  as  the  activity  fluctuates  over  the  subsystems  with  the 
same  apparent  lack  of  order  as  that  shown  by  the  smoking 
chimneys  of  S.  13/18,  yet  the  tendency  is  always  towards  ultimate 
equilibrium  and  adaptation.  So  the  next  question  to  ask  is  that 
of  Chapter  11 :  will  the  adaptation  take  an  excessively  long  time  ? 

Clearly,  following  the  arguments  of  the  previous  chapter,  much 
will  depend  on  the  richness  of  connexion  between  the  subsystems 
— on  how  much  disturbance  comes  to  each  subsystem  from  the 
others. 

At  the  limit,  when  the  transfers  of  disturbance  are  all  zero, 
the  whole  system  becomes  identical  with  the  iterated  systems  of 

213 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  16/12 

S.  15/6,  and  the  whole  will  progress  to  adaptation  similarly.  In 
this  case  the  time  taken  to  reach  adaptation  will  be  the  moderate 
time  of  T3,  rather  than  the  excessive  time  of  Tv 

As  the  connexions  become  richer,  whether  by  more  basic  joins 
or  by  the  subsystems  having  fewer  states  of  equilibrium,  so  will 
the  system  move  towards  the  richly-connected  type  of  S.  16/4; 
and  so  will  the  time  required  for  adaptation  increase  towards 
that  of  Tv  % 

Summary.  We  are  now  in  a  position  to  summarise  the  answer, 
given  by  the  intervening  chapters,  to  the  objection,  raised  in 
S.  11/2,  that  ultrastability  cannot  be  the  mode  of  adaptation  used 
by  living  organisms  because  it  would  take  too  long.  We  can  now 
appreciate  that  the  objection  was  unwittingly  using  the  assumption 
that  the  organism  and  the  environment  were  richly  joined  both 
within  themselves  and  to  each  other.  Evidence  has  been  given, 
in  S.  15/2,  that  the  actual  richness  is  by  no  means  high.  Then 
Chapters  15  and  16  have  shown  that  when  it  is  not  high,  adaptation 
by  ultrastability  can  occur  in  a  time  that  is  no  longer  impossibly 
long.  Thus  the  objection  has  been  answered,  at  least  in  outline. 
There  we  must  leave  the  matter,  for  a  closer  examination  would 
have  to  depend  on  measurements  of  actual  brains  adapting  to 
actual  environments.  The  study  of  the  matter  should  not  be 
beyond  the  powers  of  the  present-day  experimenter. 

Retroactive  inhibition 

16/12.  The  suggestion  now  before  the  reader  is  that  the  system 
of  Figure  7/5/1,  when  looked  at  more  closely  in  the  forms  in 
which  it  occurs  in  actual  organisms  and  environments,  will  be 
found  to  break  up  into  parts  more  like  those  of  Figure  16/6/1 — 
the  multistable  system.  Let  us  trace  out  some  of  the  properties 
of  this  system — extra  to  those  it  possesses  by  being  basically 
ultrastable  and  only  a  particular  form  of  Figure  7/5/1 — and  see 
how  they  accord  with  what  is  known  of  the  living  organism. 

A  first  question  to  be  asked  about  the  multistable  system  is 
whether  it  can  take  advantage  of  the  recurrent  situation,  a  matter 
considered  earlier  in  Chapter  10.  Thus,  after  a  multistable  system 
has  adapted  to  a  parameter's  taking  the  value  P2>  then  to  its 
value  P8,  will  it,  when  given  P2  again,  retain  anything  of  its  first 
adaptation  ? 

214 


16/12      ADAPTATION     IN     THE     MULTISTABLE     SYSTEM 

Before  attempting  the  answer,  let  us  recall  that,  in  any  poly- 
stable  system,  any  two  different  lines  of  behaviour  will  give 
changes  in  two  sets  of  variables  (S.  13/14)  which  may  or  may  not 
overlap.  Each  set  will  be  distributed  over  the  system  somewhat 
as  the  smoking  chimneys  of  S.  13/18  were  distributed  over  the 
town.  Two  disturbances  (D1  and  D2),  to  a  polystable  system, 
will  give  two  sets  of  active  variables,  as  two  winds  (W1  and  W2), 
to  a  town,  would  ?give  two  sets  of  smoking  chimneys. 

Of  the  chimneys  in  the  town,  what  fraction  will  smoke  with 
both  the  winds  ?  The  precise  answer  would  depend  on  precise 
conditions;  but  we  can  see  as  a  first  approximation  (as  in  S.  13/15) 
that  if  only  a  small  fraction  smoke  under  Wv  and  a  small  fraction 
under  W2,  then  if  the  two  fractions  are  independent,  the  fraction 
smoking  under  both  will  be  the  product  of  the  single  fractions,  and 
thus  much  smaller  than  either.  Thus  if  a  random  1  per  cent 
smoke  under  W1  and  another  random  1  per  cent  under  W2,  those 
that  smoke  under  both  will  be  only  y^-  of  1  per  cent. 

The  independence,  and  the  smallness  of  the  overlap,  can  occur 
only  if  Wx  and  W2  are  well  separated  in  direction.  If  W2  should 
be  very  close  to  W^s  direction,  it  will  probably  cause  smoking  in 
many  of  I^'s  chimneys  (in  the  limit,  of  course,  as  it  matches 
W^s  direction,  it  will  make  all  W^s  chimneys  smoke). 

Thus  a  polystable  system  (subject  to  certain  conditions  of 
statistical  independence  which  would  require  detailed  examina- 
tion) will  respond  to  two  parameter-values  (or  disturbances,  or 
stimuli)  with  two  sets  of  variables  whose  overlap  depends  on: — 
(1)  the  amount  of  activation  that  each  causes,  and  (2)  the  resem- 
blance between  the  parameter- values. 

Suppose  now  that  the  parameter  values  correspond,  as  in 
S.  10/8,  to  environments  that  have  to  be  adapted  to  (or  to  problems 
that  have  to  be  solved).  Since  the  multistable  system  is  also 
polystable,  what  has  just  been  said  will  be  true  of  the  multistable 
system.  Here  the  two  lines  of  behaviour  will  include  trials  and 
will  cause  changes  in  the  step-mechanisms  as  well  as  in  the  main 
variables.  The  degree  to  which  the  two  sets  of  activated  step- 
mechanisms  overlap  will  again  depend  on  what  fraction  of  all 
step-mechanisms  are  activated  and  on  the  degree  of  resemblance 
of  the  parameter- values  (or  environments).  In  particular,  if  the 
lines  of  behaviour  overlap  on  only  a  few  step-mechanisms,  the 
second  set  of  trials  may  cause  little  change  in  the  step-mechanisms 

215 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  16/13 

that  have  an  effect  on  the  first  reaction,  and  thus  little  loss  in  the 
first  adaptation.  Thus  the  multistable  system,  without  further  ad 
hoc  modification,  will  tend  to  take  advantage  of  the  recurrent  situation. 

16/13.  It  is  of  interest  to  notice  that  when  two  stimuli  (or 
parameter- values)  are  widely  different,  the  multistable  system 
will  tend  to  direct  the  activations  to  widely  different  sets  of 
step-mechanisms.  It  thus  provides,  without  further  ad  hoc 
modification,  a  functional  equivalent  of  the  gating  mechanism 

r  of  s.  10/9. 

16/14.  Conversely,  as  the  two  disturbances  (or  stimuli,  or  para- 
meter-values) tend  to  equality,  so  will  the  overlap  of  the  two 
activated  sets  tend  to  increase.  A  large  overlap  in  the  step- 
mechanisms  will  mean  that  the  second  set  of  trials  will  be  severely 
destructive  to  the  first  adaptation.  Now  the  tendency  for  new 
learning  to  upset  old  is  by  no  means  unknown  in  psychology ;  and 
an  examination  of  the  facts  shows  that  the  details  are  strikingly 
similar  to  those  that  would  be  expected  to  occur  if  the  nervous 
system  and  its  environment  were  multistable.  In  experimental  psy- 
chology 4  retroactive  inhibition  '  has  long  been  recognised.  The 
evidence  is  well  known  and  too  extensive  to  be  discussed  here,  so 
I  will  give  simply  a  typical  example.  Muller  and  Pilzecker  found 
that  if  a  lesson  were  learned  and  then  tested  after  a  half -hour 
interval,  those  who  passed  the  half-hour  idle  recalled  56  per  cent 
of  what  they  had  learned,  while  those  who  filled  the  half-hour 
with  new  learning  recalled  only  26  per  cent.  Hilgard  and  Marquis, 
in  fact,  after  reviewing  the  evidence,  consider  that  the  phenomenon 
is  sufficiently  ubiquitous  to  justify  its  elevation  to  a  4  principle  of 
interference  \  There  can  therefore  be  no  doubt  that  the  pheno- 
menon is  of  common  occurrence.  New  learning  does  tend  to 
destroy  old. 

In  a  multistable  system,  the  more  the  stimuli  used  in  new  learn- 
ing resemble  those  used  in  previous  learning,  the  more  will  the 
new  tend  to  upset  the  old;  for,  by  the  method  of  dispersion 
assumed  here,  the  more  similar  are  two  stimuli  the  greater  is  the 
chance  that  the  dispersion  will  lead  them  to  common  variables 
and  to  common  step-mechanisms.  In  psychological  experiments 
it  has  repeatedly  been  found  that  the  more  the  new  learning 
resembled  the  old  the  more  marked  was  the  interference.     Thus 

216 


16/15      ADAPTATION     IN     THE     MULTISTABLE     SYSTEM 

Robinson  made  subjects  learn  four-figure  numbers,  perform  a 
second  task,  and  then  attempt  to  recall  the  numbers;  he  found 
that  maximal  interference  occurred  when  the  second  task  consisted 
of  learning  more  four-figure  numbers.  Similarly  Skaggs  found 
that  after  learning  five-men  positions  on  the  chessboard,  the 
maximal  failure  of  memory  was  caused  by  learning  other  such 
arrangements.  The  multistable  system's  tendency  to  be  dis- 
organised by  new  reactions  is  thus  matched  by  a  similar  tendency 
in  the  nervous  system. 

16/15.  It  should  be  noticed  that  the  demands  that  a  brain 
model  should  show  both  retroactive  inhibition  and  the  ability 
to  accumulate  adaptations  are  opposed;  for  retroactive  inhibition 
demands  that  later  adaptations  shall  be  destructive  to  earlier 
adaptations,  while  the  power  to  accumulate  adaptations  demands 
that  the  later  shall  not  be  destructive  to  the  earlier.  The  Homeo- 
stat  showed  retroactive  inhibition  at  maximal  intensity  (S.  10/5), 
for  any  later  adaptation  destroyed  the  earlier  totally.  A  set  of 
iterated  systems,  with  some  suitable  gating-mechanism,  shows 
the  maximal  power  of  accumulating  adaptations.  A  multistable 
system  of  some  intermediate  degree  can  show  both  features 
partially,  and  will  thus  resemble  the  living  organism. 


217 


CHAPTER   17 

Ancillary  Regulations 

17/1.  Our  study  of  adaptation  has  led  us  to  the  ultrastable 
system,  and  then  to  some  difficulties,  in  S.  11/2,  about  how  long 
an  ultrastable  system  would  take  to  get  adapted.  These  diffi- 
culties have  been  largely  resolved  by  our  identification  of  the 
multistable  system.  (This  is  not  to  say  that  the  topic  of  adapta- 
tion is  exhausted,  for  it  extends  to  innumerable  special  cases  that 
deserve  particular  study.)  In  this  chapter  and  the  next  we  will 
consider  some  other  objections  that  may  be  raised  to  the  thesis 
that  the  brain  is  to  a  major  degree  multistable.  In  dealing  with 
them  we  shall  encounter  some  new  aspects  of  the  subject  that  are 
worthy  of  attention. 

Communication  within  the  brain 

17/2.  If  it  is  accepted  from  here  onwards  that  the  formulation 
of  S.  16/6  and  its  Figure  (the  multistable  system)  solves,  at  least 
in  its  major  features,  the  problem  posed  in  Chapter  1,  there  arises 
the  question  why  Figure  16/6/1  shows,  in  the  lower  part  (the 
organism),  no  joins  between  subsystem  and  subsystem.  Does  not 
this  absence  make  the  representation  a  travesty  of  the  facts  ? — 
a  brain  with  no  communication  between  its  parts  ! 

17/3.  In  this  matter  let  us  dispose  once  for  all  of  the  idea, 
fostered  in  almost  every  book  on  the  brain  written  in  the  last 
century,  that  the  more  communication  there  is  within  the  brain 
the  better.  It  will  suffice  if  we  remember  the  three  following  ways 
in  which  we  have  already  seen  that  some  function  can  be  success- 
ful only  if  certain  pairs  of  variables  are  not  allowed  to  communicate, 
or  between  which  the  communication  must  not  be  allowed  to 
increase  beyond  a  certain  degree. 

(1)  In  S.  8/15  we  saw  that  when  an  organism  is  adapting  by 
discrete  trials,  the  essential  variables  must"  change  the  step- 
mechanisms  at  a  rate  much  slower  than  the  rate  at  which  the 

218 


17/4  ANCILLARY     REGULATIONS 

main  variables  change.  Too  rapid  a  change  at  the  step- 
mechanisms  means  that  the  appropriateness  (or  not)  of  a  set  of 
values  does  not  have  time  to  be  communicated  round,  through 
the  brain  and  environment  as  they  carry  out  the  trial,  to  the 
essential  variables,  which  would  thus  be  acting  before  the  arrival 
of  their  necessary  information.  If  it  takes  ten  seconds  for  the 
goodness  of  a  trial  to  be  tested,  then  alterations  should  obviously 
not  be  made  more  frequently  than  at  about  eleven-second  intervals. 
And  if  it  takes  ten  years  to  observe  adequately  the  effect  of  a 
profound  re-organisation  of  a  Civil  Service,  then  such  re-organisa- 
tions ought  not  to  occur  more  frequently  than  at  eleven-year 
intervals.  The  amount  of  communication  from  essential  variables 
to  step-functions  can  thus  become  harmful  if  excessive. 

(2)  In  Chapter  10  we  considered  how  the  organism  could  take 
advantage  of  the  recurrent  situation,  so  that  if,  having  adapted 
first  to  A  and  then  to  B,  A  were  presented  again,  it  could  produce 
the  behaviour  appropriate  to  A  at  once.  It  was  shown  in  S.  10/8 
that  during  the  adaptation  to  B,  the  step-mechanisms  concerned 
with  the  adaptation  to  A  must  not  be  affected  by  what  happens 
at  the  essential  variables.  The  allowing  of  such  communication 
would  thus  be  harmful. 

(3)  In  S.  16/11  it  was  shown  that  a  multistable  system's 
chance  of  getting  adapted  in  a  reasonably  short  time  is  closely 
related  to  its  approximation  to  the  iterated  form.  Thus  every 
addition  of  channels  of  communication  takes  the  system  further 
from  the  iterated  form  and,  whatever  else  it  may  do,  increases 
the  time  taken  to  arrive  at  adaptation. 

Thus,  in  adapting  systems,  there  are  occasions  when  an  increase 
in  the  amount  of  communication  can  be  harmful. 

17/4.  It  may  still  be  objected  that  Figure  16/6/1  should  show 
connexions  directly  between  the  reacting  parts,  because  such 
connexions  are  necessary  for  co-ordination  to  be  achieved  between 
part  and  part.  The  objection  in  fact  is  mistaken;  connexions  are 
not  necessary.     Let  me  explain. 

First  we  can  dismiss  at  once  the  case  in  which  the  parts  of  the 
environment  (as  in  Figure  15/7/1)  are  not  joined;  for  then  the 
threats  to  the  various  essential  variables  come  independently  and 
can  be  responded  to  independently.  In  this  case  the  necessity 
for  co-ordination  between  parts  does  not  arise. 

219 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  17/4 

What  of  the  case  of  Figure  16/6/1,  when  the  parts  of  the  environ- 
ment are  joined,  and  when  what  is  done  by,  say,  the  reacting  part 
of  A  may  affect,  through  the  part  B  of  the  environment,  what 
happens  at  the  second  (B)  essential  variable  ?  In  this  case 
co-ordination  between  the  actions  of  the  two  reacting  parts  is 
certainly  necessary,  for  the  desirable  state  of  all  essential  variables 
being  kept  within  limits  can  be  achieved  only  by  each  part's 
actions  being  properly  related  to  what  the  others  are  doing;  for 
all  actions  meet  in  the  common  environment. 

Given,  then,  that  co-ordination  between  the  reacting  parts  is 
demanded,  does  this  imply  that  the  reacting  parts  must  be  in  direct 
communication  ?  It  does  not ;  for  communication  between  them  is 
already  available  (in  the  case  considered)  through  the  environment 

The  anatomist  may  be  excused  for  thinking  that  communication 
between  part  and  part  in  the  brain  can  take  place  only  through 
some  anatomically  or  histologically  demonstrable  tract  or  fibres. 
The  student  of  function  will,  however,  be  aware  that  channels  are 
also  possible  through  the  environment.  An  elementary  example 
occurs  when  the  brain  monitors  the  acts  of  the  vocal  cords  by 
a  feedback  that  passes,  partly  at  least,  through  the  air  before 
reaching  the  brain. 

As  the  matter  is  of  considerable  importance  in  the  general 
theory  of  how  organism  and  environment  interact,  and  as  it  has 
hitherto  received  little  attention  (though  S.  5/13  touched  on  it), 
let  us  consider  an  example  that  shows  how  functioning  parts  of 
the  brain  may  sometimes  be  co-ordinated  by  a  channel  of  com- 
munication that  passes  through  the  environment. 

Consider  the  player  serving  at  tennis.  His  left  arm  makes  a 
movement  that  projects  the  ball  into  the  air;  a  moment  later, 
his  right  arm  makes  a  movement  that,  we  will  assume,  strikes  the 
ball  correctly  into  the  opposite  court.  We  will  also  assume  that 
the  movements  of  the  left  arm  are  (for  whatever  reason)  not 
invariable  but  are  subject  to  small  random  variations  between 
service  and  service.  We  assume  that  these  variations  are  appreci- 
able, so  that  unless  the  movements  of  the  right  arm  are  also  varied, 
and  properly  paired  to  those  of  the  left,  the  ball  is  likely  to  go 
out.  Nevertheless  we  are  assuming  that  the  right  arm's  move- 
ments are  so  paired  that  the  ball  arrives  safely  in  the  proper  place 
('  position  of  the  ball's  arrival '  is  the  essential  variable,  and  its 
normal  limits  are  the  bounds  of  the  opposite  court). 

220 


17/4 


ANCILLARY     REGULATIONS 


For  the  co-ordination  to  occur,  there  must  be  some  channel 
from  the  source  of  the  left  arm's  variations  to  the  right  arm's 
movements  (/.  to  C,  S.  11/11;  the  pairing  proves  as  much  by 
S.  4/13  above).  Our  question  now  is:  must  this  channel  lie  within 
the  brain  ? 

Not  only  it  need  not,  it  usually  does  not;  as  the  following 
argument  will  show.  Consider  the  situation  at  the  moment  when 
the  ball  is  in  mid-air:  is  the  right  arm's  developing  movement 
now  guided  by  messages  from  the  left  arm's  centre*  or  from  the 
position  of  the  ball  in  the  air  ?  The  operational  test  (of  S.  4/12 
and  12/3)  is  decisive :  let  the  left  arm's  movements  remain  unaltered 
but  assume  now  that  the  position  of  the  ball  be  altered,  by  a  sharp 
gust  say;  is  the  right  arm's  movement  altered?  The  normal 
player,  if  the  ball  should  be  affected  by  a  gust,  will  at  once  modify 
his  right-arm  movements  accordingly.  These  modifications,  by 
the  basic  operational  test,  show  that  the  right  arm  is  immediately 


ORGANISM 


Figure  17/4/1. 

*  We  must  avoid  the  tangles  caused  by  the  fact  that  the  right  arm  is 
controlled  by  the  left  motor  cortex,  and  vice  versa. 

221 


DESIGN    FOR    A     BRAIN 


17/5 


affected,  in  part  at  least,  by  the  position  of  the  ball  in  the  air. 
Thus  the  server  at  tennis  normally  co-ordinates  his  left  and  right 
arms'  movements  by  the  method:  Left  arm  throws  up  the  ball 
with  imperfect  accuracy,  then  the  position  of  the  ball  in  the  air 
(through  vision)  guides  the  right  arm.  The  diagram  of  immediate 
effects  is  (to  show  the  correspondence  with  Figure  16/6/1)  as 
shown  in  Figure  17/4/1. 

Thus,  within  the  assumptions  bounding  this  example,  co- 
ordination between  parts  can  take  place  through  the  environment; 
communication  within  the  nervous  system  is  not  always  necessary. 

17/5.  After  these  observations,  one  may  begin  to  wonder  why 
the  brain  should  have  connexions  between  its  parts  at  all.  There 
are  at  least  two  reasons. 

The  first  comes  from  the  fact  that,  in  the  organism's  life-long 
struggle  to  defend  its  essential  variables  against  disturbance,  there 
is  a  fundamental  advantage  in  getting  information  about  the 
disturbance  early.  (The  fact  can  either  be  accepted  as  obvious, 
or  proved  more  formally,  as  in  /.  to  C,  S.  12/5.)  Now  while 
many  of  the  disturbances  that  threaten  an  essential  variable  come 
ultimately  from  the  environment,  some  of  them  may  come  from 
other  parts  of  the  same  organism.  Thus  every  child  that  is 
learning  to  feed  itself  discovers  that  its  lip  may  be  hurt  both  by 
environmental  objects  and  also  by  its  own  attempt  to  pass  a 
spoonful  of  food  into  its  closed  mouth.  If  the  lip  is  not  to  be 
struck,  the  mouth  must  be  opened  in  advance  of  the  spoon's 
arrival ;  for  this  to  be  possible,  information  that  the  spoon  is 
approaching  must  get  to  the  '  mouth  centre  '  before  the  spoon 
arrives.  Sometimes  the  information  may  come  through  the 
environment  (by  the  child  watching  the  spoon),  with  the  diagram 
of  immediate  effects: 


Centre  for 

hand 
movements 


— > 

Position 

of 

spoon 

— > 

Pattern 

on 
retina 

— > 

Centre  for 

mouth 
movements 


Muscles 

of 
mouth 


But  if,  for  whatever  reason,  communication  from  hand  to  mouth 
is  not  possible  through  the  environment,  then  communication 
within  the  brain,  from  hand-centre  to  mouth-centre,  is  necessary 
if  the  mouth  is  to  be  opened  before  the  spoon  arrives.     Thus 

222 


17/7  ANCILLARY     REGULATIONS 

communication  within  the  brain  can  clearly  be  necessary  or 
advantageous. 

17/6.  A  second  reason  why  communication  within  the  brain  may 
be  desirable  can  be  discussed  rigorously  only  in  the  concepts  of 
/.  to  C,  S.  7/7,  but  the  reason  can  be  sketched  here. 

When  a  system  is  described,  it  starts  by  being  a  member  of  a 
large  class  of  possible  forms;  as  each  specification  is  added,  so 
does  the  class  that  it  may  belong  to  shrink.  Start  with  a  system 
restricted  only  by  having  the  states  possible  to  it  fixed  at  a  certain 
number.  If  now  is  added  the  further  specification  '  its  diagram 
of  immediate  effects  contains  all  possible  arrows  ',  the  possibilities 
in  its  fields  are  restricted  only  slightly.  But  had  it  been  added 
that  the  diagram  contained  few  arrows,  the  possibilities  in  the 
fields  would  have  been  restricted  severely. 

Thus,  other  things  being  equal,  the  fewer  the  joins,  the  fewer 
are  the  modes  of  behaviour  available  to  the  system.  From  this 
point  of  view,  extra  connexions  within  the  brain  can  be  advan- 
tageous, for  they  make  possible  a  greater  repertoire  of  behaviours. 

Another  way  by  which  the  same  fact  can  be  seen  is  to  consider 
the  reacting  parts  before  they  wrere  joined.  The  parameters  used 
in  the  joining  must,  before  the  joining,  have  had  fixed  values  (for 
otherwise  the  parts  would  not  have  been  state-determined).  Thus 
before  the  joining  each  parameter  must  have  been  fixed  at  some 
one  of  its  possible  values;  after  the  joining  the  parameter  would  be 
capable  of  variation  as  it  was  affected  by  the  other  part.  With 
the  variation  would  have  come,  to  the  part,  a  corresponding 
variety  in  its  fields,  and  ways  of  behaving  (S.  6/3).  Thus  joining, 
by  mobilising  parameters  that  would  otherwise  be  fixed,  adds  to 
the  variety  of  possible  behaviours. 

It  can  now  be  admitted,  without  misunderstanding,  that  Figure 
16/6/1  would  have  been  more  realistic  with  some  connexions 
drawn  between  the  reacting  parts.  The  presentation  and  dis- 
cussion at  S.  16/6,  however,  was  simpler  without  them. 

17/7.  If  increased  connexions  between  the  reacting  parts  in  the 
organism  bring  in  the  two  advantages  just  described,  they  also 
bring  in,  as  S.  16/4  showed,  the  disadvantage  of  lengthening, 
perhaps  to  a  very  great  degree,  the  time  required  for  adaptation. 
Doubtless  there  are   even  more  factors  to  be  reckoned  in  the 

223 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  17/8 

balance,  but  what  we  have  seen  is  sufficient  to  show  that  richness 
of  corwcr ion  between  the  parts  in  the  brain  has  both  advantages  and 
disadvantages.  Clearly  the  organism  must  develop  so  that  its 
brain  finds,  in  this  respect,  an  optimum. 

It  is  not  suggested  that  what  is  wanted  is  the  optimum  in  the 
strict  sense.  Finding  an  optimum  is  a  much  more  complex 
operation  than  finding  a  value  that  is  acceptable  (according  to  a 
given  criterion).  Thus,  suppose  a  man  comes  to  a  foreign  market 
containing  a  hundred  kinds  of  fruit  that  are  quite  new  to  him. 
To  find  the  optimum  for  his  palate  he  must  (1)  taste  all  the  hundred, 
(2)  make  at  least  ninety-nine  comparisons,  and  (3)  remember  the 
results  so  that  he  can  finally  go  back  to  the  optimal  form.  On 
the  other  hand,  to  find  a  fruit  that  is  acceptable  he  need  merely 
try  them  in  succession  or  at  random  (taking  no  trouble  to  remember 
the  past),  stopping  only  at  the  first  that  passes  the  test.  To 
demand  the  optimum,  then,  may  be  excessive;  all  that  is  required 
in  biological  systems  is  that  the  organism  finds  a  state  or  value 
between  given  limits. 

Thus,  for  the  organism  to  adapt  with  some  efficiency  against 
the  terrestrial  environment,  it  is  necessary  that  the  degree  of 
connexion  between  the  reacting  parts  lie  between  certain  limits. 

Ancillary  regulations 
17/8.     '  Between   certain   limits  ' — we   have   heard   that   phrase 
before  !     Are  we  arguing  in  a  circle  ?     Not  really,  for  two  different 
adaptations  are  involved,  of  two  types  or  levels  or  orders. 

To  see  the  two  adaptations  and  their  relation,  recall  that  we 
started  (S.  3/14)  by  assuming  that  certain  essential  variables  were 
to  be  kept  within  limits.  Call  them  Ev  E2,  E3,  and  224;  in  Figure 
8/2/1  they  are  clearly  evident;  keeping  them  within  limits  is  one 
adaptation.  In  Chapter  11  we  added  another  essential  variable 
F:  the  time  taken  by  the  four  E's  to  get  stable  within  their  limits; 
keeping  it  within  limits  is  another  adaptation.  This  F  is  quite 
distinct  from  a  fifth  E,  which  would  enter  the  system  in  quite  a 
different  way.  Yet  F  does  come  to  the  whole  as  an  essential 
variable,  for  from  S.  11/2  onwards  we  have  consistently  discussed 
the  case  in  which  it  has  certain  limits  which  we  do  not  want  it 
to  exceed.  (The  possibility  of  various  classes  of  essential  variables 
was  mentioned  in  S.  3/15.) 

The  25' s — the  four  relays  on  the  Homeostat  say — are  clearly 

224 


17/9  ANCILLARY     REGULATIONS 

homologous  and  equivalent;  but  F  comes  into  the  whole  in  a 
different  way.  To  see  how,  suppose  that  it  is  most  desirable  (for 
some  major  essential  variable  S)  that  success,  on  some  lesser 
essential  variable  E,  be  achieved  in  fewer  than  a  hundred  trials 
(i.e.  F  is  to  be  less  than  100).  E,  making  trials,  will  cause  change 
after  change  to  occur  on  its  corresponding  step-mechanisms;  at 
the  same  time  F  (increasing  exhaustion  perhaps)  is  steadily 
mounting  to  its  limit.  What  is  to  happen  if  F  passes  its  limit 
of  100  ?  If  &  is  such  that  the  organism  dies,  nothing  remains 
to  be  said ;  but  if  &  is  not  totally  essential,  the  organism  is  in  the 
condition  of  having  made  many  trials  in  some  way  that  has  failed 
to  bring  success  quickly  (the  situation  discussed  in  Chapter  11). 
What  is  to  be  done  ?  By  the  method  of  ultrastability,  F's  passing 
beyond  its  limit  must  induce  changes,  but  clearly  these  changes 
should  not  be  simply  in  the  same  step-mechanisms  that  E  has 
been  working  on,  or  the  action  by  F  is  no  different  from  a  hundred- 
and-first  trial  by  E.  For  F  to  have  an  appropriately  effective 
action,  its  passage  beyond  the  limit  must  induce  changes  in  those 
conditions  that  have  continued  unchanged  throughout  E's  hundred 
trials.  jE's  trials  must  not  consist  of  further  samples  from  the 
same  set,  but  must  change  to  samples  from  a  new  set.  Thus  if 
the  organism  is  a  cat  in  a  box,  and  if  it  has  made  100  trials  of 
manipulating  the  levers  and  objects  without  success,  now  is  the 
time  for  it  to  make  trials  from  a  new  statistical  population — to 
change  perhaps  to  various  forms  of  mewing  and  calling. 

Thus  the  improvement  of  the  E's  speed  of  adaptation  by  the 
selection  of  an  appropriate  value  for  the  step-mechanisms  under 
F's  control  is  not  the  same  as  making  a  selection  on  the  step- 
mechanisms  that  E  itself  should  make.  Providing  an  examinee 
with  pen,  paper,  and  a  quiet  room  may  be  called  '  helping  the 
examinee  ',  but  it  is  clearly  quite  distinct  from  the  '  help  '  that 
would  show  him  how  to  answer  the  individual  question.  F 
4  helps  '  the  E's  only  in  the  first  sense,  not  the  second. 

Thus  the  conclusion  of  S.  17/7 — that  if  an  organism  is  to  adapt 
with  reasonable  speed,  certain  parameters  will  have  to  be  brought 
within  certain  limits — does  not  involve  a  circular  appeal,  for  the 
two  selections  are  working  at  different  levels,  i.e.  on  different  sets. 

17/9.     It  is  not  for  a  moment  suggested  that  all  naturally  occurring 
organisms  have  essential  variables  that  divide  neatly  into  distinct 

225 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  17/9 

levels:  2£'s,  F's,  and  so  on.  Would  that  it  were  so  !  When  it 
occurs,  the  whole  act  of  adaptation  (really  life-long  as  we  saw  in 
S.  10/2)  can  be  divided  into  portions;  then  the  practical  scientist 
can  study  the  system  portion  by  portion,  level  by  level,  and  can 
thus  greatly  simplify  its  study.  The  Homeostat  was  designed 
partly  so  as  to  enable  two  levels  to  be  obviously  distinguishable: 
(1)  the  four  continuous  variables  at  the  magnets  and  (2)  the 
discontinuous  variables  on  the  uniselectors.  When  a  system  has 
this  natural  internal  division,  the  observer  can  take  advantage 
of  the  fact  to  describe  the  somewhat  complex  whole  in  three 
stages,  each  considerably  simpler:  the  continuous  system  and  its 
properties,  the  discontinuous  system  and  its  properties,  and  the 
interaction  between  them.  But  when  the  whole  system  is  not  so 
divisible  it  remains  merely  a  fearfully  complex  whole,  not  capable 
of  reduction,  and  therefore  as  intractable  to  the  scientist  as  the 
examples  in  S.  16/3. 

This  book  inevitably  concerns  itself  with  the  case  in  which  the 
essential  variables  are  divisible  clearly  into  levels:  the  primary 
levels  (of  Ev  E2,  E3,  EA)  in  Chapters  7  to  10,  and  then  a  sharply 
differentiated  F  in  Chapters  11  to  the  present.  In  this  it  was 
again  following  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17,  getting  a  clear  grasp  of 
the  manageable  cases  so  that  they  could  serve  as  a  basis  for  at 
least  a  distant  survey  of  the  unmanageable.  The  reader  will  now 
appreciate  that  the  simplicity  of  the  earlier  chapters  was  essentially 
a  didactic  device,  not  resembling  the  actual  complexity  of  actual 
organisms.  In  fact,  their  real  complexity  is  greater,  by  many 
orders  of  size,  than  that  considered  here.  Thus,  the  reacting  part 
R  of  Figure  7/5/1,  which  looks  so  simple,  may  not  only  contain 
the  complexities  of  the  multistable  system  (Figure  16/6/1)  but 
also,  in  the  higher  organisms,  many  subsystems  of  the  form  of 
Figure  7/5/1  itself,  each  with  its  own  little  sub-essential  variables 
and  sub-adaptations;  for  much  adaptation  to  long- term  goals  is 
achieved  by  finding  suitable  sets  of  sub-goals,  perhaps  in  complex 
sequences  of  timing  and  conditionality.  Thus  once  we  have  used 
the  carefully  simplified  forms  of  Figures  7/5/1  and  16/6/1  to 
establish  our  understanding,  we  must  be  prepared  to  admit  that 
in  the  real  brain  the  same  principles  work  in  a  complexity  that  is 
of  an  altogether  higher  order,  one  that  may  well  prove  to  be  for  ever 
beyond  the  detailed  comprehension  of  the  human  scientist,  who  has 
an  I.Q.  limited,  for  all  practical  purposes,  to  something  below  200. 

226 


17/10  ANCILLARY     REGULATIONS 

With  this  admitted,  let  us  continue  to  examine  those  cases  in 
which  some  division  into  levels,  and  some  easy  understanding,  are 
possible. 

17/10.  In  Chapter  7  it  was  shown  that  the  simple  ultrastable 
system  would  solve  the  basic  problem  of  getting  the  primary 
essential  variables  stable  within  their  limits.  But  in  Chapter  11 
we  recognised  that  adaptation,  though  it  occurs  in  a  purely  logical 
sense,  may  occur  at  such  a  low  degree  of  efficiency  as  to  be  useless 
for  practical  purposes.  If  we  are  to  find  the  mechanism  that 
resembles  the  living,  and  especially  the  human,  brain  we  must 
find  one  that  adapts,  not  merely  in  a  nominal  sense  but  with  really 
high  efficiency.  In  S.  17/7  we  found  that  such  efficiency  implies 
adjustment  of  the  degree  of  intra-cerebral  connectivity  to  within 
certain  limits. 

We  can  now  notice  explicitly  that  there  are  other  parameters 
that  will  also  have  to  be  adjusted  if  the  degree  of  adaptation  is  to 
be  more  than  merely  nominal.  Several  of  these  have  already 
been  noticed  in  passing: 

(1)  In  S.  8/15  we  noticed  that  the  duration  of  trial  demanded 
adjustment.  In  that  section,  the  adjustment  was,  of  course,  made 
by  the  operator  before  the  tracings  of  the  Homeostat's  behaviour 
were  taken;  but  nothing  has  yet  been  said  about  how  this  adjust- 
ment is  to  be  made  automatically  in  the  organism. 

(2)  In  S.  7/7  it  was  demanded  that  the  essential  variables 
should  act  on  the  step-mechanisms  in  the  particular  way:  hunt 
at  '  bad  '  and  stick  at  '  good  '.  Nothing  was  said  about  how  this 
particular  relation  was  to  be  provided  in  the  organism. 

(3)  In  S.  10/8  it  was  shown  that  if  an  ultrastable  system  was 
to  adapt  efficiently  to  a  recurrent  situation,  a  certain  gating- 
mechanism  was  necessary;  but  nothing  was  said  about  how  the 
organism  should  acquire  one. 

(4)  S.  13/11  showed  how  important  is  the  value  of  the  para- 
meter :  richness  of  equilibria  among  the  states  of  the  parts. 
Nothing  was  said  about  how  this  parameter  should  be  adjusted 
to  within  satisfactory  limits. 

Doubtless  there  are  others  that  we  have  not  yet  noticed.  One 
other  of  outstanding  importance  deserves  a  section  to  itself. 


227 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  17/11 


Distribution  of  feedback 


17/11.  Another  adjustment  that  is  necessary,  if  the  adaptation 
is  to  be  more  than  merely  nominal,  has  already  been  made  in 
Figure  16/6/1,  which  thereby  begged  an  important  question.  In 
the  Figure,  if  we  start  in  the  environment  at  any  subsystem  and 
trace  a  route  through  the  essential  variable  that  it  affects,  on 
through  the  corresponding  step-mechanism,  reacting  part,  and  so 
back  to  the  environment,  we  arrive  at  the  same  subsystem  as  the 
one  we  started  at.  The  Figure  thus  implies  that  if  an  essential 
variable,  Ex  say,  is  being  upset  by  a  part  of  the  environment, 
E^s  actions  will  eventually  affect  the  very  part  of  the  environment 
that  is  the  cause  of  the  trouble. 

The  correspondence  undoubtedly  favours  efficiency  in  adapta- 
tion, as  may  be  seen  by  tracing  explicitly  what  would  happen 
otherwise.  (The  argument  is  clearest  when  the  systems  are 
iterated,  Figure  15/7/1.)  Suppose,  in  it,  that  the  second-order 
loops  were  severed  and  then  re-connected  in  some  random  way: 
so  that  the  essential  variable  of  A  affected  the  reacting  part  of  J?, 
say.  A  disturbance  to  A  that  A  is  not  adapted  to  would  now 
result  in  changes  at  B's  step-mechanisms,  though  the  set  of  values 
here  might  be  perfectly  adapted  to  dealing  with  whatever  disturb- 
ance came  to  B.  Thus  without  proper  distribution  of  the  second- 
order  feedbacks  the  effects  from  the  essential  variables  would 
only  change  at  random,  destroying  in  the  process  minor  adapta- 
tions already  established.  Thus  without  appropriate  distribution 
of  the  second-order  feedbacks  there  cannot  be  that  conservation 
of  correct  adaptations  in  the  subsystems,  and  the  cumulative 
progression  to  adaptation  that  Chapter  10  treated  as  of  major 
importance.  The  system  would  still  adapt  as  a  Homeostat  does, 
but  it  would  take  the  excessive  time  of  T1  rather  than  the  moderate 
time  of  T3  (S.  11/5). 

The  distribution  of  second-order  feedbacks  cannot  be  settled 
once  for  all,  for  a  part  of  each  circuit  is  determined  by,  or  supplied 
by,  the  environment,  and  is  thus  subject  to  change.  To  this  the 
organism  must  make  counter-adjustments,  if  the  distribution  is 
to  remain  appropriate. 

A  well-known  example  that  illustrates  the  necessity  for  finding 
where  to  apply  a  correction  is  given  by  the  aspiring  chess-player 
who  has  just -lost  a  game  and  who  is  considering  how  his  strategy 

228 


17/13  ANCILLARY     REGULATIONS 

should  be  altered  for  the  future.  Often  he  is  acutely  aware  of 
the  fact  that  he  is  not  sure  where  to  apply  the  correction.  Should 
he  examine  the  last  few  moves  and  alter  his  tactics  ?  Should  he, 
in  future,  avoid  that  sort  of  middle-game  ?  Or,  maybe,  should 
he  stop  opening  with  P — Q4  and  change  to  P — K4  ?  The  young 
chess-player  has  not  only  to  solve  the  problems  of  what  move  to 
make  next  but  also  that  of  where  to  feed  back  the  corrections. 
Thus,  there  may  well  be  players  today  who  are  weak  simply 
because,  when  they  lose  a  game,  they  change  their  opening  rather 
than  their  end-game. 

(In  this  example  the  '  parts  '  to  be  modified  are  strung  out  in 
time :  the  modification  has  to  find  the  right  place  in  the  sequence. 
The  example  serves  to  remind  us  that  a  diagram  of  immediate 
effects  (such  as  Figure  16/6/1)  represents  functional,  not  structural 
or  anatomical  relations.) 

17/12.  The  last  two  sections  have  shown  that  at  least  five  ancillary 
regulations  have  to  be  made  if  the  basic  process  of  ultrastability 
is  to  bring  adaptation  with  reasonable  efficiency  and  speed.  The 
next  question  thus  is:  how  are  these  ancillary  regulations  to  be 
achieved  ? 

17/13.  The  answer  can  be  given  with  some  assurance,  for  all 
processes  of  regulation  are  dominated  by  the  law  of  requisite 
variety.  (It  has  been  described  in  i".  to  C,  Chapter  11 ;  here  will 
be  given  only  such  details  as  are  necessary.) 

This  law  (of  which  Shannon's  theorem  10  relating  to  the  sup- 
pression of  noise  is  a  special  case)  says  that  if  a  certain  quantity 
of  disturbance  is  prevented  by  a  regulator  from  reaching  some 
essential  variables,  then  that  regulator  must  be  capable  of  exerting 
at  least  that  quantity  of  selection.  (Were  the  law  to  be  broken, 
we  would  have  a  case  of  appropriate  effects  without  appropriate 
causes,  such  as  an  examinee  giving  correct  answers  before  he  has 
been  given  the  questions  (S.  7/8).  ^Scientists  work  on  the  assump- 
tion that  such  things  do  not  happen;  and  so  far  they  have  found 
no  fact  that  would  make  them  question  the  assumption.)  The 
provision  of  the  ancillary  regulations  thus  demands  that  a  process 
of  selection,  of  appropriate  intensity,  exist.  Where  shall  we  find 
this  process  ? 

The  biologist,  of  course,  can  answer  the  question  at  once;  for 

229 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  17/14 

the  work  of  the  last  century,  and  especially  of  the  last  thirty 
years,  has  demonstrated  beyond  dispute  that  natural,  Darwinian, 
selection  is  responsible  for  all  the  selections  shown  so  abundantly 
in  the  biological  world.  Ultimately,  therefore,  these  ancillary 
regulations  are  to  be  attributed  to  natural  selection.  They  will, 
therefore,  come  to  the  individual  (to  our  kitten  perhaps)  either 
by  the  individual's  gene-pattern  or  they  develop  under  an  ultra- 
stability  of  their  own.     There  is  no  other  source. 

17/14.  The  subject  of  adaptation  in  brain-like  mechanisms,  how- 
ever, today  interests  an  audience  much  wider  than  the  biological. 
I  will,  therefore,  give  a  brief  account  of  these  processes  of  selection 
so  that  the  reader  whose  training  has  not  been  biological  can  see 
just  how  the  ancillary  regulations  must  be  developed  in  brains 
other  than  the  living. 

The  account  will  also  serve  a  second  purpose.  So  far,  the  book 
has  followed  the  method  of  starting,  in  Chapter  1,  with  the  fact 
of  adaptation  as  an  effect,  and  has  argued  back  to  its  causes. 
This  is  not  the  natural  direction  for  argument,  which  goes  alto- 
gether more  simply  and  clearly  if  we  just  take  an  initial  state  and 
then  ask:  what  will  happen  from  now  on  ?  I  propose,  therefore, 
to  sketch  the  process  in  its  natural  direction,  showing  that,  given 
a  certain  very  general  starting  point,  adaptation  as  an  outcome 
is  inevitable. 


230 


CHAPTER   18 

Amplifying  Adaptation 

Selection  in  the  state -determined  system 

18/1.  The  origin  of  selections  ceases  to  be  a  problem  as  soon  as 
it  is  realised  that  selection,  far  from  being  a  rarity,  is  performed 
to  greater  or  less  degree  by  every  isolated  state-determined 
system  (/.  to  C,  S.  13/19).  In  such  a  system,  as  two  lines  of 
behaviour  may  become  one,  but  one  line  cannot  become  two,  so 
the  number  of  states  that  it  can  be  in  can  only  decrease. 

This  selection  is  well  known,  but  in  simple  systems  it  shows  only 
in  trivial  form.  The  spring-driven  clock,  for  instance,  is  selective 
for  the  run-down  state:  start  it  at  any  state  of  partial  winding 
and  it  will  make  its  way  to  the  run-down  state,  where  it  will 
remain.  The  often-made  observation  that  machines  run  to  an 
equilibrium  expresses  the  same  property. 

In  simple  systems  the  property  seems  trivial,  but  as  the  system 
becomes  more  complex  so  does  this  property  become  richer  and 
more  interesting.  The  Homeostat,  for  instance,  can  be  regarded 
simply  as  a  system,  with  magnets  and  uniselectors,  that  runs  to 
a  partial  equilibrium,  where  it  sticks.  But  the  equilibrium  is  only 
partial,  and  therefore  richer  in  content  than  that  of  the  run-down 
clock.  The  uniselectors  are  motionless  but  the  magnets  may  still 
move,  and  the  partial  equilibrium  manifests  a  dynamic  homeostasis 
that  has  been  selected  by  the  uniselector's  process  of  running  to 
equilibrium.  Thus  the  Homeostat  begins  to  show  something  of 
the  richness  of  properties  that  emerge  when  the  system  is  complex 
enough,  or  large  enough,  to  show:  (1)  a  high  intensity  of  selection 
by  running  to  equilibrium,  and  also  (2)  that  this  selected  set  of 
states,  though  only  a  small  fraction  of  the  whole,  is  still  large 
enough  in  itself  to  give  room  for  a  wide  range  of  dynamic  activities. 
Thus,  selection  for  complex  equilibria,  within  which  the  observer  can 
trace  the  phenomenon  of  adaptation,  must  not  be  regarded  as  an 
exceptional  and  remarkable  event:  it  is  the  rule.  The  chief  reason 
why  we  have  failed  to  see  this  fact  in  the  past  is  that  our  terrestrial 

231 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  18/2 

world  is  grossly  bi-modal  in  its  forms:  either  the  forms  in  it  are 
extremely  simple,  like  the  run-down  clock,  so  that  we  dismiss 
them  contemptuously,  or  they  are  extremely  complex,  so  that  we 
think  of  them  as  being  quite  different,  and  say  they  have  Life. 

18/2.  Today  we  can  see  that  the  two  forms  are  simply  at  the 
extremes  of  a  single  scale.  The  Homeostat  made  a  start  at  the 
provision  of  intermediate  forms,  and  modern  machinery,  especially 
the  digital  computers,  will  doubtless  enable  further  forms  to  be 
interpolated,  until  we  can  see  the  essential  unity  of  the  whole  range. 

Further  examples  of  intermediate  forms  are  not  difficult  to 
invent.  Here  is  one  that  shows  how,  in  any  state-determined 
dynamic  system,  some  properties  will  have  a  greater  tendency  to 
persist,  or  '  survive  ',  than  others.  Suppose  a  computer  has  a 
hundred  stores,  labelled  00  to  99,  each  of  which  initially  holds  one 
decimal  digit,  i.e.  one  of  0,  1,  2,  .  .  .  ,  9,  chosen  at  random,  inde- 
pendently and  equiprobably.  It  also  has  a  source  of  random 
numbers  (drawn,  preferably,  from  molecular,  thermal,  agitation). 
It  now  repeatedly  performs  the  following  operation: 

Take  two  random  numbers,  each  of  two  digits;  suppose  82 
and  07  come  up.  In  this  case  multiply  together  the  numbers 
in  stores  82  and  07,  and  replace  the  digit  in  the  first  store 
(no.  82)  by  the  right-hand  digit  of  the  product. 

Now  Even  x  Even  gives  Even,  and  Odd  x  Odd  gives  Odd; 
but  Odd  X  Even  gives  Even,  so  the  number  in  the  first  store  can 
change  from  Odd  to  Even,  but  not  from  Even  to  Odd.  As  a 
result,  the  stores,  which  originally  contained  Odds  and  Evens  in 
about  equal  numbers,  will  change  to  containing  more  and  more 
Evens,  the  Odds  gradually  disappearing.  The  biologist  might  say 
that  in  the  '  struggle  '  to  occupy  the  stores  and  survive  the  Evens 
have  an  advantage  and  will  inevitably  exterminate  the  Odds. 

In  fact,  among  the  Evens  themselves  there  are  degrees  of 
ability  to  survive.  For  the  Zeros  have  a  much  better  chance 
than  the  other  Evens,  and,  as  the  process  goes  on,  so  will  the 
observer  see  the  Zeros  spread  over  the  stores.  In  the  end  they 
will  exterminate  their  competitors  completely. 

18/3.  This  example  is  easily  followed,  but  is  uncomfortably  close 
to  the  trivial.  More  complex  examples  could  easily  be  set  up, 
but  they  would  tell  us  nothing  of  the  principles  at  work  (though 

232 


18/3  AMPLIFYING     ADAPTATION 

they  would  provide  most  valuable  and  convincing  examples). 
What  all  would  show  is  that  when  a  single-valued  operation  is 
performed  repeatedly  on  a  set  of  states  (this  operation  being  the 
4  laws  '  of  the  system),  the  system  tends  to  such  states  as  are  not 
affected  by  the  operation,  or  are  affected  to  less  than  usual  degree. 
In  other  words,  every  single-valued  operation  tends  to  select  forms 
that  are  peculiarly  able  to  resist  its  change-inducing  action.  In 
simple  systems  this  fact  is  almost  truistic,  in  complex  systems 
anything  but.  And  when  it  occurs  on  the  really  grand  scale,  on  a 
system  with  millions  of  variables  and  over  millions  of  years,  then 
the  states  selected  are  likely  to  be  truly  remarkable  and  to  show, 
among  their  parts,  a  marked  co-ordination  tending  to  make  them 
immune  to  the  operation. 

The  development  of  life  on  earth  must  thus  not  be  seen  as 
something  remarkable.  On  the  contrary,  it  was  inevitable.  It 
was  inevitable  in  the  sense  that  if  a  system  as  large  as  the  surface 
of  the  earth,  basically  polystable,  is  kept  gently  simmering 
dynamically  for  five  thousand  million  years,  then  nothing  short 
of  a  miracle  could  keep  the  system  away  from  those  states  in 
which  the  variables  are  aggregated  into  intensely  self-preserving 
forms.  The  amount  of  selection  performed  by  this  system,  of 
which  we  know  only  one  example,  is  of  an  order  of  size  so  vastly 
greater  than  anything  that  we  experience  as  individuals,  that  we 
not  unnaturally  have  some  difficulty  in  grasping  that  the  process 
is  really  the  same  as  that  seen  so  trivially  in  our  everyday  systems. 
Nevertheless  it  is  so;  the  greater  extension  in  space  enables  a 
vastly  greater  number  of  forms  to  be  tested,  and  the  greater 
extension  in  time  enables  the  forms  to  be  worked  up  to  a  vastly 
greater  degree  of  intricate  co-ordination. 

We  can  thus  trace,  from  a  perfectly  natural  origin,  the  gene- 
patterns  that  today  inhabit  the  earth;  we  are  not  surprised  that 
the  earth  has  developed  forms  that  show,  in  conjunction  with  their 
environments,  the  most  remarkable  power  of  being  resistant  to  the 
change-inducing  actions  of  the  world  around  them.  They  are 
resistant,  not  in  the  static  and  uninteresting  way  that  a  piece  of 
granite,  or  a  run-down  clock,  is  resistant,  but  in  the  dynamic  and 
much  more  interesting  way  of  forming  intricate  dynamic  systems 
around  themselves  (their  so-called  '  bodies  ',  with  extensions  such 
as  nests  and  tools)  so  that  the  whole  is  homeostatic  and  self- 
preserving  by  active  defences. 

233 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  18/4 

18/4.  What  concerns  us  in  this  book  is  the  fact  that  the  active 
defences  can  be  direct  or  indirect.  The  direct  were  considered  only 
in  S.  1/3.  They  include  all  the  regulatory  mechanisms  that  are 
specified  in  detail  by  the  gene-pattern.  They  are  adapted  because 
the  conditions  that  insisted  on  them  have  been  constant  over  many 
generations. 

The  earlier  forms  of  gene-pattern  adapted  in  this  way  only.  The 
later  forms,  however,  have  developed  a  specialisation  that  can 
give  them  a  defence  against  a  class  of  disturbances  to  which  the 
earlier  were  vulnerable.  This  class  consists  of  those  disturbances 
that,  though  not  constant  over  a  span  of  many  generations  (and 
thus  not  adaptable  to  by  the  gene-pattern,  for  the  change  is  too 
rapid)  are  none  the  less  constant  over  a  span  of  a  single  generation. 
When  disturbances  of  this  class  are  frequent,  there  is  advantage 
in  the  development  of  an  adapting  mechanism  that  is  (1)  controlled 
in  its  outlines  by  the  gene-pattern  (for  the  same  outlines  are 
wanted  over  many  generations),  and  (2)  controlled  in  details  by  the 
details  applicable  to  that  particular  generation. 

This  is  the  learning  mechanism.  Its  peculiarity  is  that  the 
gene-pattern  delegates  part  of  its  control  over  the  organism  to 
the  environment.  Thus,  it  does  not  specify  in  detail  how  a  kitten 
shall  catch  a  mouse,  but  provides  a  learning  mechanism  and  a 
tendency  to  play,  so  that  it  is  the  mouse  which  teaches  the  kitten 
the  finer  points  of  how  to  catch  mice. 

This  is  regulation,  or  adaptation,  by  the  indirect  method.  The 
gene-pattern  does  not,  as  it  were,  dictate,  but  puts  the  kitten  into 
the  way  of  being  able  to  form  its  own  adaptation,  guided  in  detail 
by  the  environment. 

18/5.  We  can  now  answer  the  question  raised  in  S.  17/12,  and 
can  see  how  the  law  of  requisite  variety  is  to  be  applied  to  the 
question  of  how  the  ancillary  regulations  are  to  be  achieved,  i.e. 
how  the  necessary  parameters  are  to  be  brought  to  their  appro- 
priate values. 

Some  may  be  adjusted  by  the  direct  action  of  the  gene-pattern, 
so  that  the  organism  is  born  with  the  correct  values.  For  this 
to  be  possible,  the  environmental  conditions  must  have  been 
constant  for  a  sufficiently  long  time,  and  the  processes  of  natural 
selection  must  have  been  intense  enough  and  endured  long  enough 
for  the  total  selection  exerted  to  satisfy  the  law. 

234 


18/6  AMPLIFYING     ADAPTATION 

Some  ancillary  regulations  may  be  adjusted  by  the  gene-pattern 
at  one  remove.  In  this  case  the  gene-pattern  would  establish 
values  that  would  result  in  the  appearance  of  a  mechanism, 
actually  a  regulator,  that  would  then  proceed,  by  its  own  action, 
to  bring  the  parameters  to  appropriate  values. 

Other  ancillary  regulators  might  be  adjusted  by  the  gene- 
pattern  at  two  removes ;  but  we  need  not  trace  the  matter  further, 
as  real  systems  will  seldom  be  arranged  neatly  in  distinct  levels 
(S.  17/9).  All  we  need  notice  here  is  that  adaptation  can  be 
achieved  by  the  gene-pattern  either  directly  or  indirectly. 


Amplifying  adaptation 

18/6.  The  method  of  adaptation  by  learning  is  the  only  way  of 
achieving  adaptation  when  what  is  adaptive  is  constant  for  too 
short  a  time  for  adaptation  of  the  gene-pattern  to  be  achieved. 
For  this  reason  alone  we  would  expect  the  more  advanced  organ- 
isms to  show  it.  The  method,  however,  has  also  a  peculiar 
advantage  that  is  worth  notice,  particularly  when  we  consider 
the  limitation  implied  by  the  law  of  requisite  variety,  and  ask 
how  much  regulation  the  gene-pattern  can  achieve  in  the  two  cases. 

Direct  and  indirect  regulation  occur  as  follows.  Suppose  an 
essential  variable  X  has  to  be  kept  between  limits  x'  and  x" . 
Whatever  acts  directly  on  X  to  keep  it  within  the  limits  is  regu- 
lating directly.  It  may  happen,  however,  that  there  is  a  mechan- 
ism M  available  that  affects  X,  and  that  will  act  as  a  regulator 
to  keep  X  within  the  limits  x'  and  x"  provided  that  a  certain 
parameter  P  (parameter  to  M)  is  kept  within  the  limits  p'  andp". 
If,  now,  any  selective  agent  acts  on  P  so  as  to  keep  it  between 
p'  and  p",  the  end  result,  after  M  has  acted,  will  be  that  X  is 
kept  between  x'  and  x" . 

Now,  in  general,  the  quantities  of  regulation  required  to  keep 
P  in  p'  and  p"  and  to  keep  X  in  x'  to  x"  are  independent.  The 
law  of  requisite  variety  does  not  link  them.  Thus  it  may  happen 
that  a  small  amount  of  regulation  supplied  to  P  may  result  in  a 
much  larger  amount  of  regulation  being  shown  by  X. 

When  the  regulation  is  direct,  the  amount  of  regulation  that 
can  be  shown  by  X  is  absolutely  limited  to  what  can  be  supplied 
to  it  (by  the  law  of  requisite  variety) ;  when  it  is  indirect,  however, 
more  regulation  may  be  shown  by  X  than  is  supplied  to  P.     Indirect 

235 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  18/7 

regulation  thus  permits  the  possibility  of  amplifying  the  amount 
of  regulation;  hence  its  importance. 

18/7.  Living  organisms  came  across  this  possibility  aeons  ago, 
for  the  gene-pattern  is  a  channel  of  communication  from  parent 
to  offspring:  4  Grow  a  pair  of  eyes,'  it  says,  '  they'll  probably 
come  in  useful;  and  better  put  haemoglobin  into  your  veins — 
carbon  monoxide  is  rare  and  oxygen  common.'  As  a  channel  of 
communication  it  has  a  definite,  finite  capacity,  Q  say.  If  this 
capacity  is  used  directly,  then,  by  the  law  of  requisite  variety, 
the  amount  of  regulation  that  the  organism  can  use  as  defence 
against  the  environment  cannot  exceed  Q.  To  this  limit,  the 
non-learning  organisms  must  conform.  If,  however,  the  regula- 
tion is  done  indirectly,  then  the  quantity  Q,  used  appropriately, 
may  enable  the  organism  to  achieve,  against  its  environment,  an 
amount  of  regulation  much  greater  than  Q.  Thus  the  learning 
organisms  are  no  longer  restricted  by  the  limit. 

The  possibility  of  such  '  amplification  '  is  well  known  in  other 
ways.  If  a  child  wanted  to  discover  the  meanings  of  English 
words,  and  his  father  had  only  ten  minutes  available  for  instruc- 
tion, the  father  would  have  two  possible  modes  of  action.  One  is 
to  use  the  ten  minutes  in  telling  the  child  the  meanings  of  as  many 
words  as  can  be  described  in  that  time.  Clearly  there  is  a  limit  to 
the  number  of  words  that  can  be  so  explained.  This  is  the  direct 
method.  The  indirect  method  is  for  the  father  to  spend  the  ten 
minutes  showing  the  child  how  to  use  a  dictionary.  At  the  end 
of  the  ten  minutes  the  child  is,  in  one  sense,  no  better  off ;  for  not 
a  single  word  has  been  added  to  his  vocabulary.  Nevertheless 
the  second  method  has  a  fundamental  advantage ;  for  in  the  future 
the  number  of  words  that  the  child  can  understand  is  no  longer 
bounded  by  the  limit  imposed  by  the  ten  minutes.  The  reason 
is  that  if  the  information  about  meanings  has  to  come  through 
the  father  directly,  it  is  limited  to  ten-minutes'  worth;  in  the 
indirect  method  the  information  comes  partly  through  the  father 
and  partly  through  another  channel  (the  dictionary)  that  the 
father's  ten-minute  act  has  made  available. 

In  the  same  way  the  gene-pattern,  when  it  determines  the  growth 
of  a  learning  animal,  expends  part  of  its  resources  in  forming  a 
brain  that  is  adapted  not  only  by  details  in  the  gene-pattern  but 
also  by  details  in  the  environment.     The  environment  acts  as  the 

236 


18/7  AMPLIFYING     ADAPTATION 

dictionary.  While  the  hunting  wasp,  as  it  attacks  its  prey,  is 
guided  in  detail  by  its  genetic  inheritance,  the  kitten  is  taught 
how  to  catch  mice  by  the  mice  themselves.  Thus  in  the  learning 
organism  the  information  that  comes  to  it  by  the  gene-pattern 
is  much  supplemented  by  information  supplied  by  the  environ- 
ment; so  the  total  adaptation  possible,  after  learning,  can  exceed 
the  quantity  transmitted  directly  through  the  gene-pattern. 


237 


Summary 

The  primary  fact  is  that  all  isolated  state-determined 
dynamic  systems  are  selective  :  from  whatever  state  they 
have  initially,  they  go  towards  states  of  equilibrium.  The 
states  of  equilibrium  are  always  characterised,  in  their  rela- 
tion to  the  change-inducing  laws  of  the  system,  by  being 
exceptionally  resistant. 

(Specially  resistant  are  those  forms  whose  occurrence  leads, 
by  whatever  method,  to  the  occurrence  of  further  replicates 
of  the  same  form — the  so-called  c  reproducing  '  forms.) 

If  the  system  permits  the  formation  of  local  equilibria, 
these  will  take  the  form  of  dynamic  subsystems,  exception- 
ally resistant  to  the  disruptive  effects  of  events  occurring 
locally. 

When  such  a  stable  dynamic  subsystem  is  examined  intern- 
ally, it  will  be  found  to  have  parts  that  are  co-ordinated  in 
their  defence  against  disturbance. 

If  the  class  of  disturbance  changes  from  generation  to 
generation  but  is  constant  within  each  generation,  even  more 
resistant  are  those  forms  that  are  born  with  a  mechanism 
such  that  the  environment  will  make  it  act  in  a  regulatory 
way  against  the  particular  environment — the  '  learning ' 
organisms. 

This  book  has  been  largely  concerned  with  the  last  stage 
of  the  process.  It  has  shown,  by  consideration  of  specially 
clear  and  simple  cases,  how  the  gene-pattern  can  provide  a 
mechanism  (with  both  basic  and  ancillary  parts)  that,  when 
acted  on  by  any  given  environment,  will  inevitably  tend  to 
adapt  to  that  particular  environment. 


238 


APPENDIX 


CHAPTER   19 

The  State- determined  System 

19/1.  The  mathematics  necessary  for  the  study  of  adaptation 
does  not  consist  simply  of  the  solution  of  a  particular  mathe- 
matical problem.  The  problem,  to  the  bio-mathematician,  ranges 
from  the  identification  of  the  basic  logic  necessary  for  the  repre- 
sentation of  the  basic  concept  of  mechanism,  through  its  develop- 
ment into  various  branches  (such  as  from  the  discrete  to  the 
continuous  and  from  the  non -metric  to  the  metric),  to  the  eventual 
use  of  specialised  techniques  for  special  particular  problems. 

Since  the  problems  that  interest  the  biologist  usually  come 
from  systems  of  very  great  complexity,  in  which  treatment  of  all 
the  facts  is  not  possible,  special  importance  must  be  given 
to  methods,  such  as  that  of  topology,  that  allow  simple  answers 
to  be  given  to  simple  questions,  even  though  the  basic  facts  are 
complex.  The  mathematical  basis  should  therefore  be  sufficiently 
general  to  allow  specialisation  into  the  methods  of  topology. 
Here  we  have  been  greatly  aided  by  the  magnificent  work  of  the 
French  school  that  writes,  collectively,  under  the  pseudonym  of 
N.  Bourbaki.  In  their  great  Elements  de,  Mathematiques  this 
school  has  shown  how  the  theory  of  sets,  in  a  simple  basic  form, 
can  be  gradually  extended  and  developed,  without  the  least  loss 
of  precision  or  the  least  change  in  the  fundamental  concepts,  into 
the  realms  of  topology,  algebra,  geometry,  theory  of  functions, 
differential  equations,  and  all  the  various  branches  of  mathematics. 

How  the  theory  of  sets,  essentially  in  the  form  used  by  Bourbaki, 
gives  a  secure  basis  for  the  logic  of  mechanism,  has  already  been 
displayed  in  Part  I  of  J.  to  C.  (That  book  does  not  use  Bourbaki's 
symbols  explicitly,  but  his  concepts  are  used  throughout  and  in 
exactly  his  form;  so  the  reader  who  wishes  to  correlate  /.  to  C. 
with  Bourbaki's  work  will  find  that  the  correlation  is  in  most 
places  obvious.) 


241 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  19/2 

The  logic  of  mechanism 

19/2.  Our  starting-point  is  the  idea,  much  more  than  a  century 
old,  that  a  '  machine  '  is  that  which,  whenever  it  is  in  given 
conditions  and  at  a  given  internal  state,  goes  always  to  a  parti- 
cular state  (i.e.  not  to  different  states  on  different  occasions). 
This  definition  at  once  shows  its  formal  correspondence  with 
Bourbaki's  '  algebraic  law  of  external  composition  '.  For  if  the 
external  conditions  can  be  at  any  one  of  a  set  Q,  and  the  internal 
states  of  the  machine  at  any  one  of  a  set  E,  then  the  machine 
defines,  by  its  behaviour,  a  mapping  (Bourbaki's  '  application') 
of  Q  x  E  into  E.  The  concept  of  '  machine  '  thus  corresponds 
exactly  to  one  of  the  most  basic  concepts  in  mathematics. 

After  this  basic  identification  many  others  follow  at  once. 
The  mapping  of  E  into  E  given  by  holding  the  value  of  Q  constant 
corresponds  to  the  machine  when  isolated.  An  element  of  E 
that  is  invariant  in  the  algebra  (for  some  value  of  Q)  corresponds 
to  a  state  of  equilibrium  of  the  machine  when  the  input  (or 
surrounding  conditions)  is  held  constant  (i.e.  for  a  given  field). 
The  compatibility  (or  not)  of  an  equivalence  relation  with  an 
external  law  of  composition  corresponds  to  whether  or  not  a 
proposed  simplification  of  a  state-determined  system  leaves  the 
new  system  still  state-determined.  If  it  does,  then  the  algebraic 
quotient-law  corresponds  to  the  new,  simplified,  canonical  repre- 
sentation. And  so  on,  in  a  manner  that  deserves  extensive 
treatment. 

It  is  not  my  intention  here  to  develop  the  subject  ab  initio 
and  extensively.  As  this  book  is  concerned  primarily  with  the 
brain  and  with  systems  in  which  continuity  is  common,  we  need 
only  notice  that  Bourbaki  has  shown  how  the  basic  concepts, 
stated  in  discrete  form,  can  be  specialised  to  the  continuous  forms 
and  to  those  with  a  metric.  In  this  Appendix  we  will  deal  only 
with  such  forms  as  are  continuous  and  provided  with  a  metric. 

(N.B.  Throughout  this  chapter  the  emphasis  is  on  the  system 
that  is  isolated  and  left  alone  to  show  what  it  will  do,  apart  from 
occasional  interferences  from  the  experimenter.  The  statements 
made  should  be  interpreted  accordingly.  Chapter  21  deals 
explicitly  with  the  system  that  is  being  subjected  to  changes  in 
its  conditions,  or  at  its  input.) 

242 


19/7  THE     STATE-DETERMINED     SYSTEM 

19/3.  A  variable  is  a  function  of  the  time.  A  system  of  n 
variables  will  usually  be  represented  by  xl9  x2,  .  .  .,  xn,  or  some- 
times more  briefly  by  x.  The  case  where  n  =  1  is  not  excluded. 
It  will  be  assumed  throughout  that  n  is  finite;  a  system  with  an 
infinite  number  of  variables  (e.g.  that  of  S.  19/17)  will  be  replaced 
by  a  system  in  which  i  is  discontinuous  and  n  finite,  and  which 
differs  from  the  original  system  by  some  amount  that  is  negligible. 
Each  variable  xt  is  a  function  of  the  time  t;  it  will  sometimes  be 
written  as  x^t)  for  emphasis.  It  must  be  single-valued,  but  need 
not  be  continuous.  A  constant  may  be  regarded  as  a  variable 
which  undergoes  zero  change. 

19/4.  The  state  of  a  system  at  a  time  t  is  the  set  of  numerical 
values  of  x-^t),  .  .  .  ,  xn(t).  Two  states  (xv  .  .  .  ,  xn)  and 
(Vv  •  •  •  >  Vn)  are  e<Iual  if  x%  =  Vi  for  a11  *• 

19/5.  A  transition  can  be  specified  only  after  an  interval  of  time, 
finite  and  represented  by  At  or  infinitesimal  and  represented  by 
dt,  has  been  specified.  It  is  represented  by  the  pair  of  states, 
one  at  time  t  and  one  at  the  specified  time  later. 

A  line  of  behaviour  is  specified  by  a  succession  of  states  and  the 
time-intervals  between  them.  Two  lines  of  behaviour  are  equal 
if  all  the  corresponding  states  and  time-intervals  along  the  suc- 
cession are  equal.  (So  two  lines  of  behaviour  that  differ  only  in 
the  absolute  times  of  their  origin  are  equal.) 

19/6.  A  primary  operation  is  a  physical  event,  not  a  mathe- 
matical, requiring  a  real  machine  and  a  real  operator  or  experi- 
menter. He  selects  an  initial  state  (x\,  .  .  .  ,  a?J),  and  then 
records  the  transition  that  occurs  as  the  system  changes  in 
accordance  with  its  own  internal  drives  and  laws. 

19/7.  If,  on  repeatedly  applying  primary  operations,  he  finds 
that  all  the  lines  of  behaviour  that  follow  an  initial  state  S  are 
equal,  and  if  a  similar  equality  occurs  after  every  other  state 
S',S",   .   .   .  ,  then  the  system  is  regular. 

Such  a  system  can  be  represented  by  equations  of  form 
xx  =  Fx(xl  .  .  .  ,  xl ;    t) 


Xn  —  Fn\x\9    '    •    •    »    xn  i     0 

243 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  19/8 

in  which  the  F's  are  single-valued  functions  of  their  arguments 
but  are  otherwise  quite  unrestricted.  Obviously,  if  the  initial 
state  is  at  t  =  0,  we  must  have 

F,(«J,  .  .  .  ,  4 1   0)  =  a$  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

19/8.  Theorem  :  The  lines  of  behaviour  of  a  state-determined  system 
define  a  group. 

Let  the  initial  state  of  the  variables  be  x°,  where  the  single 
symbol  represents  all  n,  and  let  time  t'  elapse  so  that  x°  changes 
to  x' .  With  x'  as  initial  state  let  time  t"  elapse  so  that  x'  changes 
to  x" .  As  the  system  is  state-determined,  the  same  total  line  of 
behaviour  will  be  followed  if  the  system  starts  at  x°  and  goes  on 
for  time  t'  +  t".     So 

x[  =  Ftih  .  .  .  ,  xn  ;    t")  =  F,(xl  .  .  .  ,  xl ;    f  +  t") 

{i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 
But 

x\  =  F,(4  .  .  .  ,  x°n;  t')  {i  =  1,. .  .  ,  n) 

giving 

Ft{F^;  t'),  .  .  .  ,Fn(x°;  f);  t")  =  F,(4  .  .  .  ,x°n;  V  +  t") 

(i  =  1,  .  .  .  .  ,  n) 

for  all  values  of  x°,  t\  and  t"  over  some  given  region;  and  this  is 
one  way  of  defining  a  one-parameter  finite  continuous  group. 

The  converse  is  not  true.  Thus  x  —  (1  -f-  t)x°  defines  a  group 
(with  n  =  1);  but  the  times  do  not  combine  by  addition,  and  the 
system  is  not  state-determined. 

Example  :    The  system  with  lines  of  behaviour  given  by 
xx  =  x\  +  x?zt  +  t2 
x2  =  x%  +  2i 
is  state-determined,  but  that  with  lines  given  by 

X-t   ^=  X-t   ~\~  X'jl     \~  i 


x2  =  X?z  +  t 


is  not. 


Canonical  representation 

19/9.  Theorem:  That  a  system  xv  .  .  .  ,  xn  should  be  state- 
determined  it  is  necessary  and  sufficient  that  the  x's,  as  functions  oft, 
should  satisfy  equations 

244 


19/9  THE     STATE-DETERMINED     SYSTEM 


(1) 


-^  -M*v  •  •  •  >  *») 

w/^rtf  iheps  are  single-valued,  but  not  necessarily  continuous,  func- 
tions of  their  arguments;  in  other  words,  the  fluxions  of  the  set 
x±,  .  .  .  ,  xn  can  be  specified  as  functions  of  that  set  and  of  no 
other  functions  of  the  time,  explicit  or  implicit.  The  equations,  in 
this  form,  are  said  to  be  the  canonical  representation  of  the  system. 
(The  equations  will  sometimes  be  written 

dxjdt  =f(x1,  .  .  .  ,  xn)  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n)    .     (2) 

and  may  be  abbreviated  even  to  x  =f(x)  if  the  context  makes  the 
meaning  clear.) 

(1)  Let  the  system  be  state-determined.  Start  it  at  x\,  .  .  .  ,  x„ 
at  time  t  =  0  and  let  it  change  to  xv  .  .  .  ,  xn  at  time  t,  and  then 
on  to  xx  +  dxv  .  .  .  ,  xn  +  dxn  at  time  t  +  dt.  Also  start  it  at 
xv  .  .  .  ,  xn  at  time  t  =  0  and  let  time  dt  elapse.  By  the  group 
property  (S.  19/8)  the  final  states  must  be  the  same.  Using 
the  same  notation  as  S.  19/8,  and  starting  from  x\,  xt  changes 
to  Fi  (x°;  t  +  dt  and  starting  at  xt  it  gets  to  F^x;  dt).     Therefore 

F^x0;  t  +  dt)  =  Fix;  dt)  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n). 

Expand  by  Taylor's  theorem  and  write  -xrF^a;  b)  as  F'^a;  b). 

Then 

Ft.(*°;  t)  +  dt.FfaO;  t\  =  Fi(x;  0)  +  dt.F&x;  0) 

(i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

But  both  F{{x°;  t)  and  F{(x;  0)  equal  xt. 

.  ,  n)     .    .  (3) 
.  ,  n) 


Therefore 

JF>°;  t)  =  F'lxi  0) 

(i  =  1, 

But 

xi  =  F^x0;  t) 

(*  =  1, 

so 

dt     dtl{x  '  l) 

=  n+i  t) 

dx 
so  by  (3),  -^  =  F'i(x;  0)  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

which  proves  the  theorem,   since   Fi(x;   0)   contains  t  only  in 
xv  .  .  .  ,  xn  and  not  in  any  other  form,  either  explicit  or  implicit. 

245 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


19/10 


Example  1:  The  state-determined  system  of  S.  19/8,  treated  in 
this  way,  yields  the  differential  equations,  in  canonical  form: 

da\ 
lit 
dx2  _       | 
dt  -2J 

The  second  system  may  not  be  treated  in  this  way  as  it  is  not 
state-determined  and  the  group  property  does  not  hold. 
Corollary: 

d 


fi(xv 


xn) 


diFi(Xli 


««;  0 


(t  =  if 


n) 


*=o 


=  2 


(2)  Given  the  differential  equations,  they  may  be  written 

dxt  =fi{xv  .  .  .  ,  xn).dt  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

and  this  shows  that  a  given  set  of  values  of  xv  .  .  .  ,  xn,  i.e. 
a  given  state  of  the  system,  specifies  completely  what  change, 
dxiy  will  occur  in  each  variable,  x{,  during  the  next  time-interval, 
dt.  By  integration  this  defines  the  line  of  behaviour  from  that 
state.  The  system  is  therefore  state-determined. 
Example  2  :     By  integrating 

dxx 
~dt 
dx2 
~dt 

the  group  equations  of  the  example  of  S.  19/8  are  regained. 

19/10.  Definition.  The  system  is  linear  when  the  functions 
fv  •  •  •  9  fn  are  aN  nnear  functions  of  the  arguments  xv  .  .  .  ,  xn. 

19/11.  Example  3:  The  equations  of  the  Homeostat  may  be 
obtained  thus : — If  xt  is  the  angle  of  deviation  of  the  i-th  magnet 
from  its  central  position,  the  forces  acting  on  xt  are  the  momentum, 
proportional  to  xi3  the  friction,  also  proportional  to  x{,  and  the 
four  currents  in  the  coil,  proportional  to  xv  x2,  xz  and  xA.  If 
linearity  is  assumed,  and  if  all  four  units  are  construct ionally 
identical,  we  have 


dt 


(mxt) 


kx{  +  l(p  -  qftoiM  +  .  .  .   +  auxA) 


{i  =  1,  2,  3,  4) 


246 


19/12  THE     STATE-DETERMINED     SYSTEM 

where  p  and  q  are  the  potentials  at  the  ends  of  the  trough,  I 
depends  on  the  valve,  k  depends  on  the  friction  at  the  vane, 
and  m  depends  on   the   moment  of  inertia  of  the    magnet.     If 
h  =  l(p  —  q)/m  and  j  =  k/m,  the  equations  may  be  written 
dxjdt  —  x{  \  {• 

dxjdt  =  &(««*i  +  .  .  .  +  fl,4a4)  -jxt  J  {l  =  l>  2'  3'  4) 

which  shows  the  8-variable  system  to  be  state-determined  and 
linear. 
They  may  also  be  written 

dati 


dt    ~Xi 


dxt        k  (Up  —  q).  ,  ,  , 


>   (i  =  1,  2,  3,  4) 


Let  m  — >  0.  dxi/dt  becomes  very  large,  but  not  dx{/dt.  So 
±i  tends  rapidly  towards 

k     q  (gfl^l  +  •    •    •  +  ai*Zi) 

while  the  x's,  changing  slowly,  cannot  alter  rapidly  the  value 
towards  which  it  is  tending.     In  the  limit, 

^  =  it  =  ^^(-Bft  +  •  •  •  +  aiiXl)  (i  =  1,  2,  3,  4) 

Change  the  time-scale  by  t  =  ^  t,  and 

dxjdr  =  anxx  +  .  .  .  +  aux4  (i  ==  1,  2,  3,  4) 

showing  the  system  xl9  x2,  x3,  x±  to  be  state-determined  and  linear. 
The  a's  are  now  the  values  set  by  the  input  controls  of  Figure 

8/2/3. 

19/12.  The  theorems  of  the  preceding  sections  show  that  the 
following  properties  are  equivalent,  in  that  the  possession  of  any 
one  implies  the  possession  of  the  remainder. 

(1)  The  system  is  state-determined. 

(2)  From  any  point  of  the  field  departs  only  one  line  of  be- 

haviour. 

(3)  The  lines  of  behaviour  are  specifiable  by  equations  of  form: 

dxi/dt  ='fi(xl,  .  .  .  ,  xn)  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

247 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  19/13 

in  which  the  right-hand  side  contains  no  functions  of  t  except  those 
whose  fluxions  are  given  on  the  left. 

19/13.  A  simple  example  of  a  system  which  is  regular  but  not 
state-determined  is  given  by  the  following  apparatus.  A  table 
top  is  altered  so  that  instead  of  being  flat,  it  undulates  irregularly 
but  gently  like  a  putting-green  (Figure  19/13/1).     Looking  down 


Figure  19/13/1. 

on  it  from  above,  we  can  mark  across  it  a  grid  of  lines  to  act 
as  co-ordinates.  If  we  place  a  ball  at  any  point  and  then  release 
it,  the  ball  will  roll,  and  by  marking  its  position  at,  say,  every 
one-tenth  second  we  can  determine  the  lines  of  behaviour  of  the 
two-variable  system  provided  by  the  two  co-ordinates. 

If  the  table  is  well  made,  the  lines  of  behaviour  will  be  accur- 
ately reproducible  and  the  system  will  be  regular.  Yet  the 
experimenter,  if  he  knew  nothing  of  forces,  gravity,  or  momenta, 
would  find  this  two- variable  system  unsatisfactory.  He  would 
establish  that  the  ball,  started  at  A,  always  went  to  A' \  and 
started  at  B  it  always  went  to  B'.  He  would  find  its  behaviour  at 
C  difficult  to  explain.  And  if  he  tried  to  clarify  the  situation  by 
starting  the  ball  at  C  itself,  he  would  find  it  went  to  D  !  He  would 
say  that  he  could  make  nothing  of  the  system ;  for  although  each 
line  of  behaviour  is  accurately  reproducible,  the  different  lines 
of  behaviour  have  no  simple  relation  to  one  another.  He  will, 
therefore  reject  this  two-variable  system  and  will  not  rest  till 
he  has  discovered,  either  for  himself  or  by  following  Newton, 

248 


19/16       THE  STATE -DETERMINED  SYSTEM 

a  system  that  is  state-determined.  In  my  theory  I  insist  on  the 
systems  being  state-determined  because  I  agree  with  the  experi- 
menter who,  in  his  practical  work,  is  similarly  insistent. 


Transformations  of  the  canonical  representation 

19/14.  Sometimes  systems  that  are  known  to  be  isolated  and 
complete  are  treated  by  some  method  not  identical  with  that  used 
here.  In  those  cases  some  manipulation  may  be  necessary  to 
convert  the  other  form  into  ours.  Some  of  the  possible  manipula- 
tions will  be  shown  in  the  next  few  sections. 

19/15.  Systems  can  sometimes  be  described  better  after  a  change 
of  co-ordinates.  This  means  changing  from  the  original  variables 
xv  .  .  .  ,  xn  to  a  new  set  yl9  .  .  .  ,  yn,  equal  in  number  to  the 
old  and  related  by  single-valued  functions  <j>{: 

Vi  =  <f>i(xv  .-.,#«)  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

If  we  think  of  the  variables  as  being  represented  by  dials,  the 
change  means  changing  to  a  new  set  of  dials  each  of  which  indicates 
some  function  of  the  old.  If  the  functions  </>t-  are  unchanging  in 
time  (as  functions  of  their  arguments),  the  new  system  will  remain 
state-determined. 

19/16.  In  the  '  Homeostat  '  example  of  S.  19/11  a  fluxion  was 
treated  as  an  independent  variable.  I  have  found  this  treat- 
ment to  be  generally  advantageous:  it  leads  to  no  difficulty  or 
inconsistency,  and  gives  a  beautiful  uniformity  of  method. 

For  example,  if  we  have  the  equations  of  a  state-determined 
system  we  can  write  them  as 

*<  -fii^v  ...,#»)  =  0  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

treating  them  as  n  equations  in  2n  algebraically  independent 
variables  xl9  .  .  .  ,  xn,  xv  .  .  .  ,  xn.  Now  differentiate  all  the 
equations  q  times,  getting  (q  -f\l)w  equations  with  (q  +  2)n 
variables  and  derivatives.  We  can  then  select  n  of  these  vari- 
ables arbitrarily,  and  noticing  that  we  also  want  the  next  higher 
derivatives  of  these  w,  we  can  eliminate  the  other  qn  variables, 
using  up  qn  equations.  If  the  variables  selected  were  zv  .  .  .  ,  zn 
we  now  have  n  equations,  in  2n  variables,  of  type 

0((zv  .  .  .  ,  zni  zl9  .  .  .  3  zn)  =  0  (i  =*  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

249 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  19/17 

where  the  z's  are  the  selected  x's,  and  z's  the  corresponding  as's. 
These  have  only  to  be  solved  for  %,...,  zn  in  terms  of 
»!,  .  .  .  ,  Zn  and  the  equations  are  in  canonical  form.  So  the 
new  system  is  also  state-determined  (by  S.  19/9). 

This  transformation  implies  that  in  a  state- determined  system  we 
can  avoid  direct  reference  to  some  of  the  variables  provided  we  use 
derivatives  of  the  remaining  variables  to  replace  them. 

Example:  xx  =  xx  —  x2  \ 

x2  =  oXi  -\-  x2J 

can  be  changed  to  omit  direct  reference  to  x2  by  using  xx  as  a  new 
independent  variable.     It  is  easily  converted  to 

dx1/dt  =  ij 

dxjdt  =  —  4>x±  +  2a?j 

which  is  in  canonical  form  in  the  variables  x,  and  x* 


» 


19/17.  Systems  which  are  isolated  but  in  which  effects  are 
transmitted  from  one  variable  to  another  with  some  finite  delay 
may  be  rendered  state-determined  by  adding  derivatives  as 
variables.  Thus,  if  the  effect  of  x1  takes  2  units  of  time  to  reach 
x2,  while  x2s  effect  takes  1  unit  of  time  to  reach  xv  and  if  we  write 
x(t)  to  show  the  functional  dependence, 

then  dxx(t)/dt  =/iK(0,  oc2(t  -  2)Y 

dx2(t)/dt=f2{x1(t-  1),  x2(t)} 


!} 


This  is  not  in  canonical  form;  but  by  expanding  xx(t  —  1)  and 
x2{t  —  2)  in  Taylor's  series  and  then  adding  to  the  system  as 
many  derivatives  as  are  necessary  to  give  the  accuracy  required, 
we  can  obtain  a  state-determined  system  which  resembles  it  as 
closely  as  we  please. 

19/18.  If  a  variable  depends  on  some  cumulative  effect  so  that, 
say,  x1=f<      (f>(x2)dt  I,  then  if  we  put       <j>(x2)dt  =  y,  we  get  the 

equivalent  form 

dxjdt=f(y) 
dy/dt  =  <f>(x2) 
dxjdt  =  .  .  .  etc. 

which  is  in  canonical  form. 

250 


19/21  THE     STATE-DETERMINED     SYSTEM 

19/19.     If  a  variable  depends   on   velocity   effects   so  that,   for 
instance 


1  ~f\dt'  Xv  xy 


dx 
It 

dX2   _   ft  \ 

fa     —  J2\XV    X2) 

dx 
then  if  we  substitute  for  -—  inf^.  .   .)  we  get  the  canonical  form 


dx 
dx 


i/dt  ==/i{/2(a>i,0a),  xv  x2}^ 
Jdt  =  f2(x1,  x2)  ] 


19/20.  If  one  variable  changes  either  instantaneously  or  fast 
enough  to  be  so  considered  without  serious  error,  then  its  value 
can  be  given  as  a  function  of  those  of  the  other  variables;  and 
it  can  therefore  be  eliminated  from  the  system. 

19/21.     Explicit  solutions  of  the  canonical  equations 

dxjdt  =fi(xv  .  .  .  ,  xn)  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

will  seldom  be  needed  in  our  discussion,  but  some  methods  will 
be  given  as  they  will  be  required  for  the  examples. 

(1)  A  simple  symbolic  solution,  giving  the  first  few  terms  of 
xt  as  a  power  series  in  t,  is  given  by 

e,  =  e**x\  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n)      .         .        (1) 

where  X.  is  the  operator 

fiK  •  •  •  '  O^o  +  •  •  •  +/•«.  ■  •  ■  .  «©5£  •    (2) 

and  etx  =  1jrtX+tlx>  +^X*  +  .  .  .  .        (3) 

It  has  the  important  property  that  any  function  0(xv  .  .  .  ,  xn) 
can  be  shown  as  a  function  of  t,  if  the  x's  start  from  x®,  .  .  .  ,  x„, 

by  0(x19  .  .  .  ,xn)  =  etx${xl  .  .  .  ,  x»)     .         .      (4) 

(2)  If  the  functions  ft  are  linear  so  that 

dxjdt  =  anxx  -f  a12x2  -f   .  .  .   +  alnxn  +  bx 


dxjdt  =  anlxx  -f  an2x2  -f   •  •  •   +  annxn  +  bn 
251 


(5) 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  19/22 

then  if  the  fr's  are  zero  (as  ean  be  arranged  by  a  change  of 
origin)  the  equations  may  be  written  in  matrix  form  as 

x  =  Ax  .  .  .  (6) 

where  x  and  x  are  column  vectors  and  A  is  the  square  matrix 
[aij].     In  matrix  notation  the  solution  may  be  written 

x  =  etAx°  ....       (7) 

(3)  Most  convenient  for  actual  solution  of  the  linear  form  is 
the  recently  developed  method  of  the  Laplace  transform.  The 
standard  text-books  should  be  consulted  for  details. 

19/22.  Any  comparison  of  a  state-determined  system  with  the 
other  types  of  system  treated  in  physics  and  thermodynamics 
must  be  made  with  caution.  Thus,  it  should  be  noticed  that  the 
concept  of  the  state-determined  system  makes  no  reference  to 
energy  or  its  conservation,  treating  it  as  inelevant.  It  will  also  be 
noticed  that  the  state-determined  system,  whatever  the  '  machine  ' 
providing  it,  is  essentially  irreversible.  This  can  be  established 
either  by  examining  the  behaviour  representation  of  S.  19/7,  the 
canonical  representation  of  S.  19/9,  or,  in  a  particular  case,  by 
examining  the  field  of  the  common  pendulum  in  Figure  2/15/1. 


252 


CHAPTER  20 

Stability 

20/1.  As  will  be  seen  in  S.  21/14,  the  canonical  representation 
contains  all  the  information  that  the  real  '  machine  '  can  give 
relative  to  the  selected  system.  By  selecting  a  particular  system 
the  experimenter  has  already  acknowledged  that  he  can  obtain 
only  a  finite  amount  of  information  from  the  infinite  amount  that 
exists  in  the  real  '  machine  ' ;  yet  even  this  reduction  is  often 
insufficient,  for  the  canonical  representation  of  the  behavioural 
properties  of  xv  ...  ,  xn  may  still  convey  an  unmanageably 
large  amount  of  information.  Take  the  case,  for  instance,  of  the 
cluster  of  20,000  stars,  about  which  the  astronomer  asks:  will 
the  cluster  condense  to  a  ball,  or  will  it  disperse  ?  The  canonical 
representation  can  be  set  up  (it  has  120,000  variables),  and  it 
contains  the  answer;  but  the  labour  of  extracting  it  is  so  pro- 
hibitively great  that  astronomers,  and  others  in  like  position, 
have  looked  for  methods  that  do  not  use  all  the  information 
available  in  the  canonical  representation.  Hence  the  introduc- 
tion into  science  of  statistical  and  topological  methods,  and  the 
use  of  concepts  such  as  independence  (S.  12/4)  which  may,  if  the 
case  is  suitable,  enable  us  to  get  a  simple  answer  to  a  simple 
question  without  the  necessity  for  our  going  into  every  detail. 

Prominent  among  such  concepts  is  that  of  stability.  Its  basic 
elements  have  been  given  in  /.  to  C,  Chapter  5.  Here  we  shall 
treat  it  only  in  the  form  suitable  for  continuous  systems,  and  only 
with  such  rigour  as  is  necessary  for  our  main  purpose. 

20/2.  Given  a  state-determined  system  in  unvarying  conditions, 
so  that  it  has  one  field,  and  given  a  region  in  the  field  and  a  point  in 
the  region,  a  line  of  behaviour  from  the  point  is  stable,  with  respect 
to  that  field  and  region  and  point,  if  it  never  leaves  the  region. 

20/3.  If  all  the  lines  within  a  given  region  are  stable  from  all 
points  within  the  region,  and  if  all  the  lines  meet  at  one  point, 
the  system  has  normal  stability. 

253 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  20/4 

20/4.  A  state  of  equilibrium  can  be  denned  in  several  ways.  In 
the  field  it  is  a  terminating  point  of  a  line  of  behaviour.  In  the 
equations  of  S.  19/7  the  state  of  equilibrium  Xv  .  .  .  ,  Xn  is 
given  by  the  equations 

Xt  =  Lim  F^x0;  t)  {i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n)        .      (1) 

t— >00 

if  the  n  limits  exist.     In  the  canonical  equations  the  values  satisfy 
f(Xv  .  .  .  ,  Xn)  =  0  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n)      .      (2) 

A  state  of  equilibrium  is  an  invariant  of  the  group,  for  a  change 
of  t  does  not  alter  its  value. 

3fi 


If  the  Jacobian  of  the/'s,  i.e.  the  determinant 


dxj 


which  will 


be  symbolised  by  J,  is  not  identically  zero,  then  there  will  be 
isolated  states  of  equilibrium.  If,  J  =0,  but  not  all  its  first  minors 
are  zero,  then  the  equations  define  a  curve,  every  point  of  which 
is  a  state  of  equilibrium.  If  J  =  0  and  all  first  minors  but  not  all 
second  minors  are  zero,  then  a  two-way  surface  exists  composed 
of  states  of  equilibrium;  and  so  on. 

20/5.     Theorem:   If  the  f's  are  continuous  and  differ entiable,   a 
state- determined  system  tends  to  the  linear  form  (S.  19/10)  in  the 
neighbourhood  of  a  state  of  equilibrium. 
Let  the  system,  specified  by 

dxjdt  =  fi(x1,  .  .  .  ,  xn)  (i  ==  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

have  a  state  of  equilibrium  Xlf  .  .  .  ,  Xn,  so  that 

fi(Xli  .  .  .  ,  Xn)  =  0  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n>. 

Put  xt  =  Xt ;  -f  £,.  (i  =  t,  .  .  .  ,  n)  so  that  xt  is  measured  as  a 
deviation  £t  from  its  equilibrial  value.     Then 

^(A-<  +  I,.)  =fi(X1  +  ft,  .  .  .  ,  Xn  +  £,)  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

Expanding  the  right-hand  side  by  Taylor's  theorem,  noting  that 
dXJdt  =  0  and  tYi&tf^X)  =  0,  we  find,  if  the  £'s  are  infinitesimal, 
that 

W  =  ^  +  •    •    •    +  WJn  (t  -  1,    .    .    .    ,   »). 

The  partial. derivatives,  taken  at  the  point  Xv  .  .  .  ,  Xn,  are 
numerical  constants.     So  the  system  is  linear. 

254 


20/6  STABILITY 

20/6.  In  general  the  only  test  for  stability  is  to  observe  or 
compute  the  given  line  of  behaviour  and  to  see  what  happens 
as  t  — ►  oo.  For  the  linear  system,  however,  there  are  tests  that 
do  not  involve  the  line  of  behaviour  explicitly.  Since,  by  the 
previous  section,  many  systems  approximate  to  the  linear  within 
the  region  in  which  we  are  interested,  the  methods  to  be  described 
are  often  applicable. 

Let  the  linear  system  be 
dxjdt  =  aixxx  +  ai2x2  +   .  .  .   +  ainxn         (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n)     (1) 

or,  in  the  concise  matrix  notation  (S.  19/21) 

x  =  Ax  .  .  .  .       (2) 

Constant  terms  on  the  right-hand  side  make  no  difference  to 
the  stability  and  can  be  ignored.     If  the  determinant  of  A  is  not 
zero,  there  is  a  single  state  of  equilibrium.     The  determinant 
an  —  A  a12    •  •  •      dm 

#21  #22       A     •     •     •         a2n 


anl  an2      ...  ann—X 

when  expanded,  gives  a  polynomial  in  X  of  degree  n  which,  when 
equated  to  0,  and,  if  necessary,  multiplied  by  —1,  gives  the 
characteristic  equation  of  the  matrix  A : 

Xn  +  mj?-1  +  m2Xn~2  +  .  .  .  +  ™>n  =  0. 
Each  coefficient  rat  is  the  sum  of  all  i-rowed  principal  (co-axial) 
minors  of  A,  multiplied  by  (—  1)*.     Thus, 

mi  =    —  (%1   +  «22  +     •    •    •     +  ann)\    ™n  =  (~   !)"  \  Al 

Example:  The  linear  system 

dxjdt  =  —  5x1  +  4cT2  —  6^3"j 
dxjdt  =  7x±  —  6x2  +  8#3  V 
dxjdt  =  —  2x-l  +  4#2  —  4#3J 

has  the  characteristic  equation 

P  +  15A2  +  2A  +  8  =  0. 
Of  this  equation,  the  roots  Al9  .  .  .  ,  Xn  are  the  latent  roots 
of  A.  The  integral  of  the  canonical  representation  gives  each 
x{  as  a  linear  function  of  the  exponentials  e\*,  .  .  .  ,  exn.  For 
the  sum  to  be  convergent,  every  real  part  of  Xx,  .  .  .  ,  An  must  be 
negative,  and  this  criterion  provides  a  test  for  the  stability  of 
the  system. 

255 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  20/7 

Example:    The    equation    A3  +  15 A2  +  2  A  +  8  =  0    has    roots 
—  14-902  and  —  0-049  ±  0-729  V  —  1,  so  the  system  is  stable. 

20/7.  A  test  which  avoids  finding  the  latent  roots  is  Hurwitz' : 
a  necessary  and  sufficient  condition  that  the  linear  system  is 
stable  is  that  the  series  of  determinants 

etc. 


mly 

m1     1 

» 

m1     1      0 

> 

m1     1      0      0 

ra3  m2 

m3   m2   m1 

ra3  m2  mx     1 

ra5    ra4    m3 

m5  ra4   m3  ra« 

m7  m6  m5  m^ 

(where,  i 

f  q  >  n, 

mg 

=  0),  are  al 

positive. 

Example:  The  system  with  characteristic  equation 
A3  +  1522  +  2A  +  8  =  0 
yields  the  series 


+  15, 


15 

8 


0 
15 

8 


15 

8 
0 

These  have  the  values  —15,  +  22,  and  +176.     So  the  system 
is  stable,  agreeing  with  the  previous  test. 

20/8.     Another  test,  related  to  Nyquist's,   states  that  a  linear 
system  is  stable  if,  and  only  if,  the  polynomial 

ln  +  m^""1  +  m2An"2  +  .  .  .  +  mn 
changes    in    amplitude    by    nn    when    A,    a    complex    variable 
(X  =  a  +  hi  where  i  =  V  —  1),  goes  from  —  i  oo  to  +  i  oo  along 
the  6-axis  in  the  complex  A-plane. 

Nyquist's  criterion  of  stability  is  widely  used  in  the  theory 
of  electric  circuits  and  of  servo-mechanisms.  It,  however,  uses 
data  obtained  from  the  response  of  the  system  to  persistent 
harmonic  disturbance.  Such  disturbance  is  of  little  use  in  the 
theory  of  adapting  systems,  and  will  not  be  discussed  here. 

20/9.     Some   examples   will   illustrate   various   facts   relating  to 
stability  in  linear  systems. 

Example  1:  The  diagonal  terms  au  represent  the  intrinsic 
stabilities  of  the  variables;  for  if  all  variables  other  than  xt  are 
held  constant,  the  linear  system's  i-th  equation  becomes 

dx{/dt  =  aHXi  +  c, 
256 


20/9 


STABILITY 


where  c  is  a  constant,  showing  that  under  these  conditions  xt 
will  converge  to  —  c/aH  if  au  be  negative,  and  will  diverge  without 
limit  if  au  be  positive. 

If  the  diagonal  terms  au  are  much  larger  in  absolute  magnitude 
than  the  others,  the  latent  roots  tend  to  the  values  of  au.  It 
follows  that  if  the  diagonal  terms  take  extreme  values  they 
determine  the  stability. 

Example  2:  If  the  terms  au  in  the  first  n  —  1  rows  (or  columns) 
are  given,  the  remaining  n  terms  can  be  adjusted  to  make  the 
latent  roots  take  any  assigned  values. 

Example  3:  The  matrix  of  the  Homeostat  equations  of  S.  19/11 
is 


fliJi     a-iJn     a,Ji 


[n 


a2Ji 
azlh 
aAJi 


12' 

a22h 
a»9h 


13' 

a23h 
azzh 
ai3h 


a 

a24 
a34 

a 


J. 


If  j  =  0,  the  system  must  be  unstable,  for  the  eight  latent  roots 
are  the  four  latent  roots  of  [atJ],  each  taken  with  both  positive  and 
negative  signs.  If  the  matrix  has  latent  roots  pl9  .  .  .  ,  //8,  and 
if  A1?  .  .  .  ,  A4  are  the  latent  roots  of  the  matrix  [a^h],  and  if 
j  ^  0,  then  the  A's  and  ^'s  are  related  by  Xv  =  ju^  +  j/^a-  As 
j  — >  ±  °o  the  8-variable  and  the  4-variable  systems  are  stable 
or  unstable  together. 

Example  4:  In  a  stable  system,  fixing  a  variable  may  make 
the  system  of  the  remainder  unstable.  For  instance,  the  system 
with  matrix 


6 

5 

—  10 

4 

—  3 

—  1 

4 

2 

—  6 

is  stable.     But  if  the  third  variable  is  fixed,  the  system  of  the 
first  two  variables  has  matrix 

6  5" 

4     -  3 

and  is  unstable. 

257 


[_:  _g 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


20/10 


Example  5:  Making  one  variable  more  stable  intrinsically 
(Example  1  of  this  section)  may  make  the  whole  unstable.  For 
instance,  the  system  with  matrix 

—  4      —31 
3  2  J 

is  stable.     But  if  an  becomes  more  negative,  the  system  becomes 


unstable  when  an  becomes  more  negative  than 
Example  6:  In  the  n  x  n  matrix 

a     !     b 


*h 


in  partitioned  form,  let  the  order  of  [a]  be  k  x  k.  If  the  k  diagonal 
elements  au  become  much  larger  in  absolute  value  than  the  rest, 
the  latent  roots  of  the  matrix  tend  to  the  k  values  au  and  the 
n  —  k  latent  roots  of  [d].     Thus  the  matrix,  corresponding  to  [d], 

1      —  3^ 

1  2 


has  latent  roots   +  1-5  ±  l-658t, 
-  100         —  1 


and  the  matrix 
2  0" 


2—100—1  2 

0  —  3  1—3 

2-1  1  2 

has  latent  roots   —  101-39,    —  98-62,  and   +  1-506  ±  l-720t. 

Corollary:  If  system  [d]  is  unstable  but  the  whole  4-variable 
system  is  stable,  then  making  xx  and  x2  more  stable  intrinsically 
will  eventually  make  the  whole  unstable. 

Example  7:  The  holistic  nature  of  stability  is  well  shown  by 
the  system  with  matrix 

—  3     —  2  2^ 


-  5 


5  6 

2      —  4 


in  which  each  variable  individually,  and  every  pair,  is  stable; 
yet  the  whole  is  unstable. 


The  probability  of  stability 

20/10.     The  probability  that  a  system  should  be  stable  can  be 
made  precise  only  after  the  system  has  been  defined,  '  stability  ' 

258 


20/10 


STABILITY 


defined  for  it,  and  then  a  proper  sample  space  denned.  In  general, 
the  number  of  possible  meanings  of  '  probability  of  stability  '  is 
too  large  for  extensive  treatment  here.  Each  case  must  be 
considered  individually  when  such  consideration  is  called  for. 

A  case  of  some  interest  because  of  its  central  position  in  the 
theory  is  the  probability  that  a  linear  system  shall  be  stable, 
when  its  matrix  is  filled  by  random  sampling  from  given  distribu- 
tions.    The  problem  then  becomes: 

A  matrix  of  order  n  x  n  has  elements  which  are  real  and  are 
random  samples  from  given  distributions.  Find  the  probability 
that  all  the  latent  roots  have  negative  real  parts. 

This  problem  seems  to  be  still  unsolved  even  in  the  special 
cases  in  which  all  the  elements  have  the  same  distributions, 
selected  to  be  simple,  as  the  '  normal  '  type  e~x\  or  the  '  rect- 
angular '  type,  constant  between  —  a  and  +  a.  Nevertheless, 
as  I  required  some  indication  of  how  the  probability  changed  with 
increasing  n,  the  rectangular  distribution  (integers  evenly  dis- 
tributed between  —  9  and  +  9)  was  tested  empirically.  Matrices 
were  formed  from  Fisher  and  Yates'  Table  of  Random  Numbers, 
and  each  matrix  was  then  tested  for  stability  by  Hurwitz'  rule 
(S.  20/7).     Thus  a  typical  3x3  matrix  was 

-  1      —  3     —  8^ 

-  5  4-2 
-4     —  4     —  9 

In  this  case  the  second  determinant  is  —  86  ;  so  it  need  not  be 
tested  further.  The  testing  becomes  very  time-consuming  when 
the  matrices  exceed  3x3,  for  the  time  taken  increases  approxi- 
mately as  ?i5.     The  results  are  summarised  in  Table  20/10/1. 


Order  of 
matrix 

Number 
tested 

Number 
found 
stable 

Per  cent 
stable 

2x2 
3x3 

4x4 

320 
100 
100 

77 
12 

1 

24 

12 

1 

Table  20/10/1. 

The  main  feature  is  the  rapidity  with  which  the  probability 
tends   to    zero.     -The   figures   given   are   compatible    (#2  =  4-53, 

259 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


20/10 


P  =  0-10)  with  the  hypothesis  that  the  probability  for  a  matrix 
of  order  n  x  n  is  1/2".  That  this  may  be  the  correct  expression 
for  this  particular  case  is  suggested  partly  by  the  fact  that  it 
may  be  proved  so  when  n  =  1  and  n  =  2,  and  partly  by  the 
fact  that,  for  stability,  the  matrix  has  to  pass  all  of  n  tests. 
And  in  fact  about  a  half  of  the  matrices  failed  at  each  test. 
If  the  signs  of  the  determinants  in  Hurwitz'  test  are  statistically 
independent,  then  l/2n  would  be  the  probability  in  this  case. 

In  these  tests,  the  intrinsic  stabilities  of  the  variables,  as 
judged  by  the  signs  of  the  terms  in  the  main  diagonal,  were 
equally  likely  to  be  stable  or  unstable.  An  interesting  variation, 
therefore,  is  to  consider  the  case  where  the  variables  are  all 
intrinsically  stable  (all  terms  in  the  main  diagonal  distributed 
uniformly  between  0  and  —  9). 

The  effect  is  to  increase  their  probability  of  stability.  Thus 
when  n  is  1  the  probability  is  1  (instead  of  J);  and  when  n  is 
2  the  probability  is  §  (instead  of  J).  Some  empirical  tests  gave 
the  results  of  Table  20/10/2. 


Order  of 
matrix 

Number 
tested 

Number 
found 
stable 

Per  cent 
stable 

2x2 
3x3 

120 
100 

87 
55 

72 
55 

Table  20/10/2. 


The  probability  is  higher,  but  it  still  falls  as  n  is  increased. 

A  similar  series  of  tests  was  made  with  the  Homeostat.  Units 
were  allowed  to  interact  with  settings  determined  by  the  uni- 
selectors, which  were  set  at  one  position  for  one  test,  the  usual 
ultrastable  feedback  being  severed.  The  percentage  of  stable 
combinations  was  found  when  the  number  of  units  was  two. 
Then  the  percentage  was  found  for  the  same  general  conditions 
except  that  three  units  interacted;  and  then  four.  The  general 
conditions  were  then  changed  and  a  new  triple  of  percentages 
found.  And  this  was  repeated  six  times  altogether.  As  the 
general  conditions  sometimes  encouraged,  sometimes  discouraged, 
stability,  some  of  the  triples  were  all  high,  some  all  low;  but  in 
every  case  the  per  cent  stable  fell  as  the  number  of  interacting 

260 


20/10 


STABILITY 


iOOt 


50- 


2  3 

NUMBER     OF     VARIABLES 

Figure  20/1Q/1. 

units  was  increased.     The  results  are  given  in  Figure  20/10/1, 
in  which  each  triple  lies  on  one  line. 

These  results  prove  little;  but  they  suggest  that  the  proba- 
bility of  stability  is  small  in  large  systems  assembled  at  random. 
It  seems,  therefore,  that  large  linear  systems  should  be  assumed 
to  be  unstable  unless  evidence  to  the  contrary  is  produced. 


261 


CHAPTER    21 

Parameters 

21/1.  In  the  previous  two  chapters  we  have  considered  the 
state-determiried  system  when  it  was  isolated,  with  constant 
condition?  around  it,  or  when  no  change  came  to  its  input.  We 
now  turn  to  consider  the  state-determined  system  when  it  is 
affected  by  changes  in  the  conditions  around  it,  when  it  is  no 
longer  isolated,  or  when  changes  come  to  its  input.  We  turn,  in 
other  words,  to  consider  the  '  machine  with  input  '  of  /.  to  C, 
Chapter  4. 

Experience  has  shown  that  this  change  corresponds  to  the 
introduction  of  parameters  into  the  canonical  representations  so 
that  they  become  of  the  form 

dxi/dt  =fi{xv  .  .  .  ,  xn\  als  a2,  .  .  .)  (i  =  1,  .  .  .  ,  n) 

21/2.  If  the  «'s  are  fixed  at  particular  values  the  result  is  to  make 
the/'s  a  particular  set  of  functions  of  the  #'s  and  thus  to  specify 
a  particular  state-determined  system.  From  this  it  follows  that 
each  particular  set  of  values  at  the  a's  specifies  a  particular  field. 
In  other  words,  the  two  sets:  (1)  the  values  at  the  a's  and  (2)  the 
fields  that  the  system  can  show  can  be  set  in  correspondence 
— perhaps  the  most  fundamental  fact  in  the  whole  of  this  book. 
(Figure  21/8/1  will  illustrate  it.) 

It  should  be  noticed  that  the  correspondence  is  not  one-one  but 


Figure  21/2/1. 
262 


21/6 


PARAMETERS 


may  be  many-one,  for  while  one  value  of  the  vector  (av  a2,  .  .  .) 
will  indicate  one  and  only  one  field,  several  such  vectors  may 
indicate  the  same  field.  Thus  the  relation  is  a  mapping  of 
Bourbaki's  type.  The  possibilities  are  sufficiently  indicated  in 
Fig.  21/2/1;  in  the  upper  line  P,  each  dot  represents  one  value 
of  the  vector  of  parameter- values  (av  o2,  .  .  .);  in  the  lower  line 
F,  each  dot  represents  one  field.  Notice  that  (1)  every  vector 
value  indicates  a  field;  (2)  no  vector  value  indicates  more  than 
one  field;  (3)  a  field  may  be  indicated  by  more  than  one  vector 
value;  (4)  some  fields  may  be  unindicatcd. 

21/3.  If  the  a's  can  take  m  combinations  of  values  then  m  fields 
are  possible.  The  m  fields  will  often  be  distinct,  but  the  possibility 
is  not  excluded  that  the  m  may  include  repetitions,  and  thus  not 
be  all  different. 

21/4.  If  a  parameter  changes  continuously  (i.e.  by  steps  that 
may  be  as  small  as  we  please),  then  it  will  often  happen  that  the 
corresponding  changes  in  the  field  will  be  small;  but  nothing  here 
excludes  the  possibility  that  an  arbitrarily  small  change  in  a 
parameter  may  give  an  arbitrarily  large  change  in  the  field. 
Thus  the  fields  will  often  be,  but  need  not  necessarily  be,  a  con- 
tinuous function  of  the  parameters. 


21/5.  If  a  parameter  affects  immediately  only  certain  variables, 
it  will  appear  only  in  the  corresponding  /'s.  Thus  the  canonical 
representation  (of  a  machine  with  input  a) 

dxjdt  =f1(x1,  x2; 
dxjdt  =f2(xlf  x2) 

corresponds  to  a  diagram  of  immediate  effects 


21/6.  Change  of  parameters  can  represent  every  alteration  which 
can  be  made  on  a  state-determined  system,  and  therefore  on  any 
physical  or  biological  4  machine  '.  It  includes  every  possibility  of 
experimental  interference.  Thus  if  a  set  of  variables  that  are 
joined  to  form  the  system  x  =f{x)  are  changed  in  their  relations 

263 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  21/7 

so  that  they  form  the  system  x  =  <j>(x),  then  the  change  can  equally 
well  be  represented  as  a  change  in  the  single  system  x  =  ip(x;  a). 
For  if  a  can  take  two  values,  1  and  2  say,  and  if 

f{x)  =  y>(x;  1) 
<j>{x)  =  y)(x;  2) 

then  the  two  representations  are  identical. 

As  example  of  its  method,  the  action  of  S.  8/11,  where  the  two 
front  magnets  of  the  Homeostat  were  joined  by  a  light  glass  fibre 
and  so  forced  to  move  from  side  to  side  together,  will  be  shown 
so  that  the  joining  and  releasing  are  equivalent  in  the  canonical 
equations  to  a  single  parameter  taking  one  of  two  values. 

Suppose  that  units  xv  x2  and  xz  were  used,  and  that  the  magnets 
of  1  and  2  were  joined.  Before  joining,  the  equations  were 
(S.   19/11) 

dxjdt  =  anxx  +  a12x2  +  a13aO 

2/  —    ttoi^i     ~~ |      Wo?     2      i™    ^S3*»l  i 

dX3/at   =  Cl31X1   -f~  a32<%2   ~T~  a33X3J 

After  joining,  x2  can  be  ignored  as  a  variable  since  xx  and  x2  are 
effectively  only  a  single  variable.  But  x2s  output  still  affects  the 
others,  and  its  force  still  acts  on  the  fibre.  The  equations  there- 
fore become 

dxjdt  =  (an  +  a12  +  a21  +  a22)xx  +  (a13  +  a23)x, 
dxjdt  =  (a31  +  aZ2)xx  +  a33a\ 

It  is  easy  to  verify  that  if  the  full  equations,  including  the  para- 
meter 6,  were: 

dx1/dt  =  {an  +  b(a12  +  a21  +  a22)}x1  +  (1  —  b)a12x2 

+  (a13  +  ba23)x3 

dX2/dt   =  ^21^1  I     ^22*^2     l  ^23^3 

dxjdt  =  (a31  +  ba^Xj^  +  (1  —  b)aZ2x2  +       a33x, 

then  the  joining  and  releasing  are  identical  in  their  effects  with 
giving  b  the  values  1  and  0  respectively.  (These  equations  are 
sufficient  but  not,  of  course,  necessary.) 

21/7.  A  variable  Xk  behaves  as  a  null-function  if  it  has  the 
following  properties,  which  are  easily  shown  to  be  necessary  and 
sufficient  for  each  other: 

(1)  As  a  function  of  the  time,  it  remains  at  its  initial  value  xQk- 

264 


21/7  PARAMETERS 

(2)  In  the  canonical  equations,  fk{x^  .  .  .  ,  xn)  is  identically 

zero. 

(3)  In  the  equations  of  S.  19/7,  Fk(x\,  .  .  .  ,  a>°;  f)  =  #j>. 

(Some  region  of  the  phase-space  is  assumed  given.) 

In  a  state-determined  system,  the  variables  other  than  the  step- 
and  null-functions  will  be  referred  to  as  main  variables. 

Theorem:  In  a  state- determined  system,  the  subsystem  of  the 
main -variables  forms  a  state -determined  system  provided  no  step- 
function  changes  from  its  initial  value. 

Suppose  xv  ....  xk  are  null-  and  step-functions  and  the  main- 
variables  are  Xk+i,  .  .  .  ,  xn.  The  canonical  equations  of  the 
whole  system  are 

dxjdt  —  0 


dxje/dt  =  0 
dxk+i/dt  =fk+1(xi,  .  .  .  ,  X*  xt+i,  .  .  .  ,  xn)\ 


dxjdt  =fn(xl9  .  .  .  ,  xk,  xk+i,  .  .  .  ,  xn) 

The  first  k  equations  can  be  integrated  at  once  to  give  xx  =  x®y 
.  .  .  ,  Xk  =  x%.  Substituting  these  in  the  remaining  equations 
we  get: 

dxt+i/dt  =fk+i(x%,  .  .  .   ,  x\,  xk+i,  .  .  .  ,  xn)) 


dxjdt  =  fn(x°v  .  .  .  ,  x°k,  Xk+i,  .  .  .  ,  xn)j 

The  terms  x\,  .  .  .  ,  a?£  are  now  constants,  not  effectively  functions 
of  t  at  all.  The  equations  are  therefore  in  canonical  form;  so  the 
system  is  state-determined  over  any  interval  not  containing  a 
change  in  x®,  .  .  .  ,  x°k. 

Usually  the  selection  of  variables  to  form  a  state-determined 
system  is  determined  by  the  real,  natural  relationships  existing 
in  the  real  '  machine  ',  and  the  observer  has  no  power  to  alter 
them  without  making  alterations  in  the  c  machine  '  itself.  The 
theorem,  however,  shows  that  without  affecting  whether  it  is 
state-determined  the  observer  may  take  null-functions  into  the 
system  or  remove  them  from  it  as  he  pleases. 

It  also  follows  that  the  statements :  '  parameter  a  was  held  con- 
stant at  a0  ',  and  '  the  system  was  re-defined  to  include  a,  which, 

265 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 


21/8 


as  a  null-function,  remained  at  its  initial  value  of  a0  '  are  merely 
two  ways  of  describing  the  same  facts. 

21/8.  The  fact  that  the  field  is  changed  by  a  change  of  parameter 
implies  that  the  stabilities  of  the  lines  of  behaviour  may  be 
changed.     For  instance,  consider  the  system 

dxjdt  =  —  xt  -f-  «#2>  dxjdt  =  x±  —  x2  +  1. 

When  a  =  0,  1,  and  2  respectively,  the  system  has  the  three 
fields  shown  in  Figure  21/8/1. 


Figure  21  /8/1  :   Three  fields  of  xx  and  x2  when  a  has  the  values  (left  to 
right)  0,  1,  and  2. 

When  a  =  0  there  is  a  stable  state  of  equilibrium  at  x1  =  0, 
x2  =  1 ;  when  a  =  1  there  is  no  state  of  equilibrium ;  when  a  =  2 
there  is  an  unstable  state  of  equilibrium  at  x1  =  —  2,  x2  =  —  1. 
The  system  has  as  many  fields  as  there  are  values  to  a. 


Joining  systems 

21/9.  (Again  the  basic  concepts  have  been  described  in  /.  to  C, 
S.  4/7;  here  we  will  describe  the  theory  in  continuous  systems.) 

The  simple  physical  act  of  joining  two  machines  has,  of  course, 
a  counterpart  in  the  equations,  shown  more  simply  in  the  canonical 
than  in  the  equations  of  S.  19/7. 

One  could,  of  course,  simply  write  down  equations  in  all  the 
variables  and  then  simply  let  some  parameter  a  have  one  value 
when  the  parts  are  joined  and  another  when  they  are  separated. 
This  method,  however,  gives  no  insight  into  the  real  events  in 
4  joining  '  two  systems.  A  better  method  is  to  make  the  para- 
meters of  one  system  into  defined  functions  of  the  variables  of  the 
other.  When  this  is  done,  the  second  dominates  the  first.  If 
parameters  in  each  are  made  functions  of  variables  in  the  other, 

266 


21/10  PARAMETERS 

then  a  two-way  interaction  occurs.     For  instance,   suppose  we 
start  with  the  2-variable  system 

dx/dt  =  f1(x,  y;  a)' 
dy/dt  =  f2{x,  y) 

then  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  is 


and  the  1 -variable  system  dz/dt  =  <f>(z;  b) 


a 

> 

y 

X 

>     z 


If  we  make  a  some  function  of  z,  a  =  z  say  for  simplicity,  the  new 
system  has  the  equations 

dx/dt  =f1(x,  y;  zf\ 
dy/dt  =f2(x,  y)  I 
dz/dt  =  <f>(z;  b)        J 

and  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  becomes 


b 

z 

X 

y 

If  a  further  join  is  made  by  putting  b  =  y,  the  equations  become 

dx/dt  =f1(x,  y;  z) 
dy/dt  =f2{x,  y) 
dz/dt  =  4(z;  y) 

and  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects  becomes 


<  y 

E7 


In  this  method  each  linkage  uses  up  one  parameter.  This  is 
reasonable;  for  the  parameter  used  by  the  other  system  might 
have  been  used  by  the  experimenter  for  arbitrary  control.  So 
the  method  simply  exchanges  the  experimenter  for  another  system. 

This  method  of  joining  does  no  violence  to  each  system's 
internal  activities:  these  proceed  as  before  except  as  modified  by 
the  actions  coming  in  through  the  variables  which  were  once 
parameters. 

21/10.  Theorem:  The  whole  made  by  joining  parts  is  richer  in 
ways  of  behaving  than  the  system  obtained  by  leaving  the  parts 
isolated. 

267 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  21/11 

(The  argument  is  simple  and  clear  if  it  is  supposed  that  each 
part  has  a  finite  number  of  states  possible,  and  if  the  number  of 
input  states  is  also  finite.  The  result  for  the  infinite  case,  being 
the  limit  of  the  finite  case,  is  the  same  as  that  stated,  but  would 
need  a  special  technique  for  its  discussion.) 

Suppose  the  system  consists  of  p  parts,  each  capable  of  being 
in  any  one  of  s  states,  with  p  and  s  assumed  finite.  Then,  whether 
joined  or  not,  the  set  of  all  the  parts  has  sv  states  possible.  (Put 
sv  =  k,  for  convenience.) 

If  the  whole  is  richly  joined,  each  of  these  k  states  may  go,  in  a 
transition,  to  any  of  the  k  states;  for  the  transition  of  each  part 
is  not  restricted  (since  it  is  allowed  to  be  conditional  on,  and  to 
vary  with,  the  states  of  the  other  parts).  The  number  of  trans- 
formations is  thus  kk. 

If,  however,  the  parts  are  not  joined,  the  transformations  of 
each  part  cannot  vary  with  the  states  of  the  others ;  so  the  trans- 
formation of  the  whole  must  be  built  up  by  taking  a  single  trans- 
formation from  each  part.  Each  part,  with  s  states,  has  ss 
transformations;  so  the  whole  will  have  (ss)r  transformations 
possible.     This  equals  ks. 

As  s  is  less  than  k,  ks  is  less  than  kk;  whence  the  theorem. 

21/11.     If  Xv  .  .  .  ,  Xn  is  a  state  of  equilibrium  in  a  system 

dxi/dt  =ft(xv  .  .  .  ,  xn\  14,  .  .  .)  {i  =  1 n) 

for  certain  a- values,  and  the  system  is  then  joined  to  some  ?/'s  by 
making  the  a's  functions  of  the  y's,  then  Xv  .  .  .  ,  Xn  will  still 
be  a  state  of  equilibrium  (of  the  a>system)  when  the  y's  make  the 
a's  take  their  original  values.  Thus  the  zeros  of  the/'s,  and  the 
states  of  equilibrium  of  the  ^-system,  are  not  altered  by  the 
operation  of  joining. 

21/12.     On  the  other  hand,  the  stabilities  may  be  altered  grossly. 

In  the  general  case,  when  the/'s  are  unrestricted,  this  proposi- 
tion is  not  easily  given  a  meaning.  But  in  the  linear  case  (to 
which  all  continuous  systems  approximate,  S.  20/5)  the  meaning 
is  clear.     Three  examples  will  be  given. 

Example  1:  Two  systems  may  give  a  stable  whole  if  joined  one 
way,  but  an  unstable  whole  if  joined  another  way.  Consider  the 
1 -variable  systems  dx/dt  =  x  +  ^V\  +  2han^  dy/dt  =  —  2r  —  3y. 

268 


21/13  PARAMETERS 

If  they  are  joined  by  putting  r  =  x,  px  =  y,  the  system  becomes 
dx/dt  =  x  +  2y  +  p 


dy/dt  =  —  2x  —  3y 

The  latent  roots  of  its  matrix  are  —  1,  —  1;  so  it  is  stable.  But 
if  they  are  joined  by  r  =  x,  p2  =  y,  the  roots  become  +  0«414 
and   —  2-414;  and  it  is  unstable. 

Example  2 :  Stable  systems  may  form  an  unstable  whole  when 
wined.     Join  the  three  systems 

dx/dt  =  —  x  —  2q  —  2r 
dy/dt  =  -  2p  —  y  +  r 
dz/dt  =  p  +  q  —  z 

all  of  which  are  stable,  by  putting  p  =  x,  q  —  y,  r  =  z.  The 
resulting  system  has  latent  roots   +1,   —  2,   —  2. 

Example  3 :   Unstable  systems  may  form  a  stable  whole  when 
joined.     Join  the  2-variable  system 

dx/dt  =  3x  —  Sy  —  3p> 
dy/dt  =  Sx  —  9y  - 

which  is  unstable,  to  dz/dt  =  2lq  +  Sr  +  3z,  which  is  also  un- 
stable, by  q  =  x,  r  =  y,  p  =  z.     The  whole  is  stable. 


:} 


The  state-determined  system 

21/13.  It  is  now  clear  that  there  are,  in  general,  two  ways  of 
getting  to  know  a  complex  dynamic  system  (i.e.  one  made  of 
many  parts). 

One  way  is  to  know  the  parts  (ultimately  the  individual  vari- 
ables) in  isolation,  and  how  they  are  joined.  '  Knowing  '  each 
part,  or  variable,  means  being  able  to  write  down  the  correspond- 
ing lines  of  the  canonical  representation  (if  not  in  mathematical 
symbolism  then  in  any  other  way  that  gives  an  unambiguous 
statement  of  the  same  facts).  Knowing  how  they  are  joined 
means  that  certain  parameters  to  the  parts  can  be  eliminated  (for 
they  are  functions  of  the  variables).  In  this  way  the  canonical 
representation  of  the  whole  is  obtained.  Integration  will  then 
give  the  lines  of  behaviour  of  the  whole.  Thus  we  can  work 
from  an  empirical  knowledge  of  the  parts  and  their  joining  to  a 
deduced  knowledge  of  the  whole. 

The  other  way  is  to  observe  the  whole  and  its  lines  of  behaviour. 

269 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  21/14 

These  observations  give  the  functions  of  S.  19/7.  Differentiation 
of  these  (as  in  the  Corollary  of  S.  19/9)  will  give  the  canonical 
representation,  and  thus  those  of  the  parts,  to  which  the  other 
variables  now  come  as  parameters.  Thus  we  can  also  work  from 
an  empirical  knowledge  of  the  whole  to  a  deduced  knowledge  of 
the  parts  and  their  joining. 

21/14.  It  is  now  becoming  clear  why  the  state-determined 
system,  and  its  associated  canonical  representation,  is  so  central 
in  the  theory  of  mechanism.  If  a  set  of  variables  is  state-deter- 
mined, and  we  elicit  its  canonical  representation  by  primary 
operations,  then  our  knowledge  of  that  system  is  complete.  It  is 
certainly  not  a  complete  knowledge  of  the  real  '  machine  '  that 
provides  the  system,  for  this  is  probably  inexhaustible;  but  it  is 
complete  knowledge  of  the  system  abstracted — complete  in  the 
sense  that  as  our  predictions  are  now  single-valued  and  verified, 
they  have  reached  (a  local)  finality.  If  a  tipster  names  a  single 
horse  for  each  race,  and  if  his  horses  always  win,  then  though  he 
may  be  an  ignorant  man  in  other  respects  we  would  have  to  admit 
that  his  knowledge  in  this  one  respect  was  complete. 

The  state-determined  system  must  therefore  hold  a  key  place 
in  the  theory  of  mechanism,  by  the  strategy  of  S.  2/17.  Because 
knowledge  in  this  form  is  complete  and  maximal,  all  the  other 
branches  of  the  theory,  which  treat  of  what  happens  in  other 
cases,  must  be  obtainable  from  this  central  case  as  variations 
on  the  question:  what  if  my  knowledge  is  incomplete  in  the 
following  way  .  .  .  ? 

So  we  arrive  at  the  systems  that  actually  occur  so  commonly 
in  the  biological  world — systems  whose  variables  are  not  all 
accessible  to  direct  observation,  systems  that  must  be  observed 
in  some  way  that  cannot  distinguish  all  states,  systems  that  can 
be  observed  only  at  certain  intervals  of  time,  and  so  on. 

21/15.  Identical  with  the  state-determined  system  is  the  '  noise- 
less transducer  '  defined  by  Shannon.  This  he  defines  as  one  that, 
having  states  a  and  an  input  x,  will,  if  in  state  a„  and  given  input 
xn,  change  to  a  new  state  an+1  that  is  a  function  only  of  xn  and  an: 

«n+i  =  g(*n>  a«)- 

Though  expressed  in  a  superficially  different  form,  this  equation 

270 


21/15  PARAMETERS 

is  identical  with  a  canonical  representation;  for  it  says  simply 
that  if  the  parameters  x  and  the  state  of  the  system  are  given, 
then  the  system's  next  state  is  determined.  Thus  the  communica- 
tion engineer,  if  he  were  to  observe  the  biologist  and  the  psycho- 
logist for  the  first  time,  would  say  that  they  seem  to  prefer  to 
work  with  noiseless  systems.  His  remark  would  not  be  as  trite 
as  it  seems,  for  from  it  flow  the  possibilities  of  rigorous  deduction. 


271 


CHAPTER   22 

The  Effects  of  Constancy 

22/1.  A  variable  behaves  as  a  step-function  over  some  given 
period  of  observation  if  it  changes  value  at  only  a  finite  number  of 
discrete  instants,  at  which  it  changes  value  instantaneously  and 
by  a  finite  jump. 

22/2.  An  example  of  a  step-function  in  a  system  will  be  given 
to  establish  the  main  properties. 

Suppose  a  mass  m  hangs  downwards  suspended  on  a  massless 
strand  of  elastic.  If  the  elastic  is  stretched  too  far  it  will  break 
and  the  mass  will  fall.  Let  the  elastic  pull  with  a  force  of  k 
dynes  for  each  centimeter  increase  from  its  unstretched  length, 
and,  for  simplicity,  assume  that  it  exerts  an  opposite  force  when 
compressed.  Let  x,  the  position  of  the  mass,  be  measured  verti- 
cally downwards,  taking  as  zero  the  position  of  the  elastic  when 
there  is  no  mass. 

If  the  mass  is  started  from  a  position  vertically  above  or  below 
the  point  of  rest,  the  movement  will  be  given  by  the  equation 

jt{mT)=gm-kx    •     ■     •    (1) 

where  g  is  the  acceleration  due  to  gravity.     This  equation  is  not 
in   canonical  form,   but   may  be   made   so   by  writing  x  =  xv 
dx/dt  =  x2,  when  it  becomes 
dx± 


dx»  k 

dt        6       m  1 


(2) 


If  the  elastic  breaks,  k  becomes  0,  and  the  equations  become 

dxx  _ 

j- 

dXo 

Assume  that  the  elastic  breaks  if  it  is  pulled  longer  than  X. 

272 


22/2  THE  EFFECTS  OF  CONSTANCY 

The  events  may  be  viewed  in  two  ways,  which  are  equivalent. 

We  may  treat  the  change  of  k  as  a  change  of  parameter  to  the 
2-variable  system  xv  cc2,  changing  their  equations  from  (2) 
above  to  (3)  (S.  21/1).  The  field  of  the  2-variable  system  will 
change  from  A  to  B  in  Figure  22/2/1,  where  the  dotted  line  at  X 


A  B 

Figure  22/2/1  :  Two  fields  of  the  system  (xt  and  x2)  of  S.  22/2. 
unbroken  elastic  the  system  behaves  as  A,  with  broken  as  B. 
the  strand  is  stretched  to  position  X  it  breaks. 


With 
When 


shows  that  the  field  to  its  right  may  not  be  used  (for  at  X  the 
elastic  will  break). 

Equivalent  to  this  is  the  view  which  treats  them  as  a  3- variable 
system:  xv  x2>  and  k.  This  system  is  state-determined,  and  has 
one  field,  shown  in  Figure  22/2/2. 


Figure  22/2/2 


Field  of  the  3-variable  system. 
273 


DESIGN    FOR    A    BRAIN  22/3 


In   this   form,    the   step-function   must   be   brought   into   the 
canonical  equations.     A  possible  form  is: 

dk       JK  ,   K 

dt 


=  ?(f  +  f  tanh  {q(X  -*)}-*)  .         (4) 

where  K  is  the  initial  value  of  the  variable  k,  and  q  is  large  and 
positive.  As  q  — >  oo,  the  behaviour  of  &  tends  to  the  step- 
function  form. 

Another  method  is  to  use  Dirac's  ^-function,  defined  by  d(u)  =  0 
if  w  y£  o,  while  if  u  =  0,  (5(w)  tends  to  infinity  in  such  a  way  that 

6(u)du  =  1. 

Then  if  du/dt  =  6{(f>{u,  v,  .  .  .)},  du/dt  will  be  usually  zero;  but 
if  the  changes  of  u,  v,  .  .  .  take  <f>  through  zero,  then  d(u)  becomes 
momentarily  infinite  and  u  will  change  by  a  finite  jump.  These 
representations  are  of  little  practical  use,  but  they  are  important 
theoretically  in  showing  that  a  step-function  can  occur  in  the 
canonical  representation  of  a  system. 

22/3.  In  a  state-determined  system,  a  step-function  will  change 
value  if,  and  only  if,  the  system  arrives  at  certain  states:  the 
critical.  In  Figure  22/2/2,  for  instance,  all  the  points  in  the  plane 
k  =  K  (the  upper  plane)  and  to  the  right  of  the  line  xx  =  X  are 
critical  states  for  the  step-function  k  when  it  has  the  initial 
value  K. 

The  critical  states  may,  of  course,  be  distributed  arbitrarily. 
More  commonly,  however,  the  distribution  is  continuous.  In  this 
case  there  will  be  a  critical  surface 

<j>(k,  a?2 a?n)  =  0 

which,  given  k,  divides  the  critical  from  the  non-critical  states. 
In  Figure  22/2/2,  for  instance,  the  surface  intersects  the  plane 
k  =  K  at  the  line  xx  =  X.  (The  plane  k  =  0  is  not  intersected 
by  it,  for  there  are  no  states  in  this  system  whose  occurrence  will 
result  in  k  changing  from  0.) 

Commonly  </>  is  a  function  of  only  a  few  of  the  variables  of  the 
system.  Thus,  whether  a  Post  Office  type  relay  opens  or  shuts 
depends  only  on  the  two  variables:  the  current  in  the  coil,  and 
whether  the  relay  is  already  open  or  shut. 

Such  relays  and  critical  states  occur  in  the  Homeostat.     When 

274 


22/5  THE  EFFECTS  OF  CONSTANCY 

two,  three  or  four  units  are  in  use,  the  critical  surfaces  will  form 
(to  a  first  approximation)  a  square,  cube,  or  tesseract  respectively 
in  the  phase-space  around  the  origin.  The  critical  states  will  fill 
the  space  outside  this  surface.  As  there  is  some  backlash  in  the 
relays,  the  critical  surfaces  for  opening  are  not  identical  with 
those  for  closing. 


Systems  with  multiple  fields 

22/4.  If,  in  the  previous  example,  someone  unknown  to  us  were 
occasionally  to  break  and  sometimes  to  replace  the  elastic,  and  if 
we  were  to  test  the  behaviour  of  the  system  cclt  x2  over  a  prolonged 
time  including  many  such  actions,  we  would  find  that  the  system 
was  often  state-determined  with  a  field  like  A  of  Figure  22/2/1, 
and  often  state-determined  with  a  field  like  B;  and  that  from  time 
to  time  the  field  changed  suddenly  from  the  one  form  to  the  other. 
Such  a  system  could  be  said  without  ambiguity  to  have  two 
fields.  Similarly,  if  parameters  capable  of  taking  r  combinations 
of  values  were  subject  to  occasional  change  by  some  other, 
unobserved  system,  a  system  might  be  found  to  have  r  fields. 

22/5.  The  argument  can  be  used  to  some  degree  in  the  converse 
direction;  for  the  correspondence  of  S.  21/2  may  be  used,  with 
caution,  conversely;  for  though  the  number  of  fields  does  not 
prescribe  the  number  of  parameter-values  it  does  prescribe  their 
minimal  number  with  precision.  Thus  fields  that  change  like  the 
first  row  of  letters  in  S.  9/13  demand  a  minimum  of  4  parameter- 
values,  while  those  that  change  like  the  second  row  demand  a 
minimum  of  15. 

If  the  observer  should  find  that  one  field  persists,  the  minimal 
number  of  parameter- values  is,  of  course,  one.  If  the  field  should 
change  suddenly  to  a  new  field,  which  persists,  he  may  deduce 
that  the  parameter- value  must  have  changed  (for  no  single  value 
could  give  two  fields),  and  that  -the  minimal  number  of  values 
over  the  new  persistence  is  again  one.  Thus  he  may  legitimately 
deduce  that  the  minimal  variety  attributable  to  the  parameter- 
values  is,  on  the  scale  of  S.  7/13,  that  of  the  step-function — the 
null-function  provides  too  little,  and  the  part-function  an  un- 
necessary excess.     (Compare  S.  9/10-13.) 


275 


DESIGN     FOR    A     BRAIN  22/6 

The  ultrastable  system 

22/6.  The  definition  and  description  already  given  in  S.  7/26 
have  established  the  elementary  properties  of  the  ultrastable 
system.  A  restatement  in  mathematical  form,  however,  has  the 
advantage  of  rendering  a  misunderstanding  less  likely,  and  of 
providing  a  base  for  quantitative  studies. 

If  a  system  is  ultrastable,  it  is  composed  of  main  variables  xt 
and  of  step-functions  ait  so  that  the  whole  is  state-determined: 

dxi/dt  =fi(x\  a)  (i  =  1,  .  .  . ,  n) 

dajdt  =  gi(x;  a)  {i  =  1,  2,  .  .  .) 

The  functions  gt  must  be  given  some  form  like  that  of  S.  22/2. 
The  system  is  started  with  the  representative  point  within  the 
critical  surface  <f>(x)  =  0,  contact  with  which  makes  the  step- 
functions  change  value.  When  they  change,  the  new  values  of 
a{  are  to  be  random  samples  from  some  distribution,  assumed 
given. 

Thus  in  the  Homeostat,  the  equations  of  the  main  variables 
are  (S.  19/11): 

dXi/dt  =  aaxx  +  ai2x2  +  ai3x3  +  a^         (i  =  1,  2,  3,  4) 
The  a's  are  step-functions,  coming  from  a  distribution  of  '  rect- 
angular '  form,  lying  evenly  between  —  1  and  -f-  1.     The  critical 

surfaces  of  the  a's  are  specified  approximately  by  |  x  |  ±  -  =  0. 

Each  individual  step-function  a^  depends  only  on  whether  x} 
crosses  the  critical  surface. 

As  the  a's  change  discontinuously,  an  analytic  integration  of 
the  differential  equations  is  not,  so  far  as  I  am  aware,  possible. 
But  the  equations,  the  description,  and  the  schedule  of  the 
uniselector- wirings  (the  random  samples)  define  uniquely  the 
behaviour  of  the  x's  and  the  a's.  So  the  behaviour  could  be 
computed  to  any  degree  of  accuracy  by  a  numerical  method. 

22/7.  How  many  trials  will  be  necessary,  on  the  average,  for  a 
terminal  field  to  be  found  ?  If  an  ultrastable  system  has  a 
probability  p  that  a  new  field  of  the  main  variables  will  be  stable, 
and  if  the  fields'  probabilities  are  independent,  then  the  number 
of  fields  occurring  (including  the  terminal)  will  be,  on  the  average, 
\/p. 

276 


22/9  THE  EFFECTS  OF  CONSTANCY 

For  at  the  first  field,  a  proportion  p  will  be  terminal,  and 
q  (=  1  —  p)  will  not.  Of  the  latter,  at  the  second  field,  the  pro- 
portion p  will  be  terminal  and  q  not ;  so  the  total  proportion  stable 
at  the  second  field  will  be  pq,  and  the  number  still  unstable  q2. 
Similarly  the  proportion  becoming  terminal  at  the  u-th  field  will 
be  pq*-1.     So  the  average  number  of  trials  made  will  be 

p  +  2pq  +  3pq2  +  •    •    ■  +  upq"-1  +     •   .   .  _  1 
p  +  pq  +  pq2  +  .   .   .  +  pq"-1  -f  .   .   .  p 


Temporary  independence 

22/8.  The  relation  of  variable  to  variable  has  been  treated  by 
observing  the  behaviour  of  the  whole  system.  But  what  of  their 
effects  on  one  another  ?  Thus,  if  a  variable  changes  in  value,  can 
we  distribute  the  cause  of  this  change  among  the  other  variables  ? 
In  general  it  is  not  possible  to  divide  the  effect  into  parts, 
with  so  much  caused  by  this  variable  and  so  much  caused  by  that. 
Only  when  there  are  special  simplicities  is  such  a  division  possible. 
In  general,  the  change  of  a  variable  results  from  the  activity  of 
the  whole  system,  and  cannot  be  subdivided  quantitatively. 
Thus,  if  dx/dt  =  sin  x  +  xey,  and  x  =  \  and  y  =  2,  then  in  the 
next  0-01  unit  of  time  x  will  increase  by  0-042,  but  this  quantity 
cannot  be  divided  into  two  parts,  one  due  to  x  and  one  to  y. 
Only  when  some  special  simplicity  exists  can  the  whole  effect  be 
represented  meaningfully  as  the  sum  of  two  effects,  one  from  each. 
Though  not  uncommon  in  theoretical  physics,  such  simplicities  are 
rare  in  biological  systems. 

22/9.  Given  a  state-determined  system,  its  field,  a  line  of 
behaviour  in  it,  and  a  particular  portion  P  of  the  line;  given  also 
that  xp  is  a  part-function,  then  the  following  are  equivalent,  in 
that  the  truth  (or  falsity)  of  any  one  implies  the  truth  (or  falsity) 
of  all  the  others: 

(1)  xp  is  constant  (inactive); 

(2)  dxp/dt  =  0; 

(S)fp{.  .   .,  x0t  .   .   .)  =0; 

(4)  Xp  =  #jj  independently  of  t; 

(5)  Fp(x°;  t)  ==  x°,  with  such  values  of  t  as  do  not  take  the  line 

out  of  P; 

277 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  22/10 

all  being  understood  to  refer  only  to  the  region  P.  (The  equiva- 
lences follow  readily  from  the  properties  of  the  equations  of  S.  19/9 
and  their  integrals.) 

22/10.  Given  a  state-determined  system  and  two  transitions 
from  two  initial  states  which  differ  only  in  their  values  of  x°,  (the 
difference  being  A#9),  the  variable  xk  is  independent  of  xt  if  xks 
transition  is  identical  in  the  two  cases.  Analytically,  xk  is  inde- 
pendent of  Xj  in  the  conditions  given  if 

Fk{x°v  .  .  . ,  4  .  .  .;  dt)  =  Fk{x\,  .  .  . ,  x]  +  Aaf,  .  .  .;  dt)     (1) 

In  other  words,  xk  is  independent  of  Xj  if  xks  behaviour  is  invariant 
when  the  initial  state  is  changed  by  Ax9.     (This  '  change  '  by 

A#j  must  not  be  confused  with  the  change  dt.) 

This  narrow  definition  provides  the  basis  for  further  develop- 
ment. In  practical  application,  the  identity  (1)  may  hold  over  all 
values  of  Ax®  (within  some  finite  range,  perhaps);  and  may  also 
hold  for  all  initial  states  of  xk  (within  some  finite  range,  perhaps). 
In  such  cases  the  test  whether  xk  is  independent  of  Xj  is  whether 

faoFk(x<>;  t)  =  0. 

The  range  over  which  the  relation  or  equation  holds  must  always 
be  specified  (either  explicitly  or  by  implication). 

Diagrams  of  effects 

22/11.  The  diagram  of  immediate  effects  and  the  canonical 
representation  have  a  simple  relation.  Starting  with  the  prag- 
matic and  empirical  point  of  view  of  S.  2/7,  we  assume  that  the 
observer  gets  his  basic  knowledge  of  the  system  by  primary 
operations.  These  operations  will  give  him  the  functions  Ft  of 
S.  19/7  and  also  (by  S.  4/12)  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects. 
Now  the  test  for  whether  to  draw  an  arrow  from  x,  to  xk  is  essen- 
tially the  same  as  the  test  applied  algebraically  to  see  whether  x°, 
occurs  effectively  in  Fk,  and  the  outcomes  must  correspond.  But 
(by  the  Corollary,  S.  19/9)  whether  Fk  does  or  does  not  contain  x° 
effectively  over  a  single  step  dt  must  correspond  with  whether  fk 
does  or  does  not  contain  x,  effectively.  Thus,  in  the  diagram  of 
immediate  effects  an  arrow  will  run  from  Xj  to  xk  if  and  only  if, 

278 


22/14  THE     EFFECTS     OF     CONSTANCY 

in  the  canonical  representation,  Xj  occurs  effectively  in  /*.  (The 
range  of  /'s  arguments  is  assumed  to  be  specified.) 

22/12.  The  diagram  of  ultimate  effects  can  also  be  shown  to  have 
the  property  that  an  arrow  goes  from  Xj  to  x*  if  and  only  if,  in 
the  equations  of  S.  19/7,  x9  occurs  effectively  in  Fk  (over  some 
specified  range). 

(These  matters  were  discussed  more  fully  in  the  First  Edition, 
but  need  not  be  repeated  at  length.) 

22/13.  It  is  worth  noticing  that,  given  n  arbitrary  points,  a 
diagram  of  immediate  effects  can  be  drawn  by  the  arbitrary 
placing  of  any  number  of  arrows.  That  of  the  ultimate  effects 
cannot,  however,  be  so  drawn ;  for  an  arrow  from  p  to  q  and  one 
from  q  to  r  imply  an  arrow  from  p  to  r.  Thus,  while  diagrams 
of  immediate  effects  are,  in  general,  unrestricted,  those  of  ultimate 
effects  must  be  transitive. 

22/14.  The  thesis  of  S.  12/10  can  now  be  treated  rigorously. 
Figure  12/10/1  is  given  to  be  the  diagram  of  immediate  effects, 
and  the  whole  is  assumed  to  be  isolated  and  state-determined. 
(For  compactness  below,  the  subscript  A  will  be  used  to  mean 
'  any  variable  in  the  ^4-set';  and  similarly  for  B  and  C.)  Then 
the  canonical  representation  of  the  whole  must  be  of  the  form 

xa  =/a(xa,  xb)        1 

xb=/b(xa,  xb,  xc)\        .  .  (1) 

XC  =fc(XB,    XC)  J 

with  xc  not  in/,4,  and  xa  not  in/c.  The  two  parts  of  the  theorem 
can  now  be  proved. 

(1)  Suppose  the  2?'s  are  null-functions  (over  some  specified 
range).  They  are  therefore  constant.  Write  their  values  col- 
lectively as  p.     The  topmost  line  of  (1)  then  becomes 

XA  =fA(XA,    ft) 

which  shows  that  the  system  composed  of  the  variables  xa  is 
state-determined  (so  long  as  (}  is  constant).  Further,  the  integrals 
Fa  of  these  equations  cannot  contain  x°,  so  the  system  A  is  inde- 
pendent of  the  system  C. 

A   similar   proof  will   show   that   C   is    state-determined   and 

279 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN  22/14 

independent  of  A.  Thus  a  wall  of  constancies  (the  B's  null- 
functions)  between  the  systems  A  and  C  is  sufficient  to  leave  them 
each  state-determined  and  independent  of  the  other. 

(2)  Suppose  the  systems  A  and  C  are  each  found  to  be  state- 
determined  and  independent  of  one  another;  the  whole  is  given 
to  be  state-determined,  and  there  is  known  to  be  no  immediate 
connexion  from  A  to  C  or  from  C  to  A,  but  there  is  effective 
connexion  between  A  and  B,  and  between  C  and  B — what  can 
be  deduced  about  the  variables  in  B  ? 

The  lack  of  connexion  between  A  and  C  shows  that  the  canonical 
representation  must  have  the  form  of  (1)  above.     With 

XA  =fA(cCA,    OCb) 

the  A's  can  be  state-determined  only  if  all  the  i5's  are  constant 
(not  effectively  functions  of  the  time).  So  the  2?'s  must  be  null- 
functions. 


280 


References 


Ashby,  W.  Ross.     Adaptiveness  and  equilibrium.     Journal  of  Mental  Science, 

86,  478  ;    1940. 
Idem.     The  physical  origin  of  adaptation  by  trial  and  error.     Journal  of 

general  Psychology,  32,  13  ;    1945. 
Idem.     Effect  of  controls  on  stability.     Nature,  155,  242  ;    1945. 
Idem.     Interrelations  between  stabilities  of  parts  within  a  whole  dynamic 

system.     Journal  of  comparative  and  physiological  Psychology,    40,   1  ; 

1947. 
Idem.     The  nervous  system  as  physical  machine  :    with  special  reference  to 

the  origin  of  adaptive  behaviour.     Mind,  56,  1  ;    1947. 
Idem.     Design  for  a  brain.     Electronic  Engineering,  20,  379  ;  1948. 
Idem.     The    stability    of   a    randomly    assembled    nerve-network.     Electro- 
encephalography and  clinical  N euro-physiology,  2,  471  ;    1950. 
Idem.     Can  a  mechanical  chess-player  outplay  its  designer  ?     British  Journa 

for  the  Philosophy  of  Science,  3,  44  ;    1952. 
Idem.     An  introduction  to  cybernetics.     London,  3rd  imp.,  1958. 
Bourbaki,  N.     The'orie  des  ensembles;  facsicule  de  r£sultats.     A. S.E.I.  No. 

1141  ;   Paris  ;  1951. 
Idem.     Algibre.     A.S.E.I.  No.  1144. 
Idem.     Topologie.     A.S.E.I.  No.  1142. 
Boyd,  D.  A.,  and  Nie,  L.  W.     Congenital  universal  indifference  to  pain. 

Archives  of  Neurology  and  Psychiatry,  61,  402  ;  1949. 
Cannon,  W.  B.  The  wisdom  of  the  body.  London,  1932. 
Carey,  E.  J.,  Massopust,  L.  C,  Zeit,  W.,  Haushalter,  E.,  and  Schmitz,  J. 

Experimental  pathologic  effects  of  traumatic  shock  on  motor  end  plates 

in  skeletal  muscle.     Journal  of  Neuropathology  and  experimental  Neur- 
ology, 4,  134  ;    1945. 
Cowles,   J.   T.     Food-tokens   as   incentives   for   learning  by   chimpanzees. 

Comparative  Psychology  Monographs,  14,  No.  71  ;    1937-8. 
Dancoff,  S.  M.,  and  Quastler,  H.     Information  content  and  error  rate  of 

living  things.     In   Information   theory  in  biology,  edited  H.   Quastler. 

Urbana,  1953. 
Girden,   E.,   and   Culler,   E.     Conditioned  responses   in   curarised  striate 

muscle  in  dogs.     Journal  of  comparative  Psychology,  23,  261  ;    1937. 
Grant,  W.  T.     Graphic  methods  in  the  neurological  examination  :    wavy 

tracings  to  record  motor  control.     Bulletin  of  the  Los  Angeles  Neurological 

Society,  12,  104  ;    1947. 
Grindley,  G.  C.     The  formation  of  a  simple  habit  in  guinea-pigs.     British 

Journal  of  Psychology,  23,  127  ;    1932-3. 
Harrison,  R.  G.     Observations  on  the  living  developing  nerve  fiber.     Pro- 
ceedings of  the  Society  for  experimental  Biology  and  Medicine,  4,  140  ; 

1906-7. 
Hilgard,  E.  R.,  and  Marquis,  D.  G.     Conditioning  and  learning.     New  York, 

1940. 
Holmes,  S.  J.     A  tentative  classification  of  the  forms  of  animal  behavior. 

Journal  of  comparative  Psychology,  2,  173  ;    1922. 
Humphrey,  G.     The  nature  of  learning.     London,  1933. 
Hurwitz,  A.     t)ber  die   Bedingungen,   unter  welchen  eine   Gleichung  nur 

Wurzeln  mit  negativen  reelen  Teilen  besitzt.     Mathematische  Annalen, 

46,  273  ;    1895. 
Jennings,  H.  S.     Behavior  of  the  loiver  organisms.     New  York,  1906. 

281 


DESIGN     FOR     A     BRAIN 

Lash  ley,  K.  S.     Nervous  mechanisms  in  learning.     In  The  foundations  of 

experimental  psychology,  edited  C.  Murchison.     Worcester,  1929. 
Levi,  G.     Ricerche  sperimentali  sovra  elementi  nervosi  sviluppati  '  in  vitro  '. 

Archiv  fur  experimentelle  Zellforschung,  2,  244;    1925-0. 
Lorente   de   X6,   H.     Vestibulo-ocular  reflex    arc.     Archives    of  Neurology 

and  Psychiatry,  30,  245  ;    1933. 
McDoUGALL,   YV.   Psychology.     New  York,   1912. 
Marina,  A.     Die  Relationen  des  Palae-encephalons  (Edinger)  sind  nicht  fix. 

Neurologisches  Centralblatt,  34,  .'538  ;    1915. 
Morgan,  C.  Lloyd.     Habit  and  instinct.     London,  1896. 
Mowrer,  ().  II.     An  experimental  analogue  of  '  regression  '  with  incidental 

observations  on  '  reaction-formation  '.     Journal  of  abnormal  and  social 

Psychology,  35,  56  ;     1940. 
Muller,  G.  E.,  and  Pilzecker,  A.     Experimentelle  Beitrage  zur  Lehre  vom 

Gedachtnis.     Zeitschrift  fur  Psychologie  und  Physiologie  der  Sinnesorgane. 

Erganzungsband  No.   1  ;    1900. 
Nyquist,  H.     Regeneration  theory.     Bell  System  technical  Journal,  11,  126  ; 

1932. 
Parker,  G.     The  evolution  of  man.     New  Haven,  1922. 
Pauling,  L.     In  Cerebral  mechanisms  in  behavior,  edited  Lloyd  A.  Jeffress. 

New  York,  1951. 
Pavlov,   I.   P.     Conditioned  reflexes.     Oxford,  1927. 
Riguet,  J.     Sur  les  rapports  entre  les  concepts  de  machine  de  mnltipole  et  de 

structure  algebrique.     Comptes  rendues  de  V  Academic  des  Sciences,  237, 

425  ;    1953. 
Robinson,  E.  S.     Some  factors  determining  the  degree  of  retroactive  inhibi- 
tion.    Psychological  Monographs,  28,  No.  128  ;    1920. 
Rosenblueth,  A.,  Wiener,  N.,  and  Bigelow,  J.     Behavior,  purpose  and 

teleology.     Philosophy  of  Science,  10,  18  ;    1943. 
Shannon,  C.  E.,  and  Weaver,  W.     The  mathematical  theory  of  communication. 

Urbana,   1949. 
Sherrington,  C.  S.     The  integrative  action  of  the  nervous  system.     New  Haven, 

1906. 
Skaggs,    E.    B.     Further    studies    in    retroactive    inhibition.     Psychological 

Monographs,  34,  No.   161  ;    1925. 
Sommerhoff,  G.     Analytical  biology.     Oxford,  1950. 
Speidel,  C.  C.     Activities  of  amoeboid  growth  cones,  sheath  cells,  and  myelin 

segments  as  revealed  by  prolonged  observation  of  individual  nerve  fibers 

in  frog  tadpoles.     American  Journal  of  Anatomy,  52,  1  ;    1933. 
Idem.     Effects  of  metrazol  on  tissues  of  frog  tadpoles  with  special  reference 

to  the  injury  and  recovery  of  individual  nerve  fibers.     Proceedings  of  the 

American  Philosophical  Society,  83,  349  ;    1940. 
Sperry,  R.  W.     Effect  of  crossing  nerves  to  antagonistic  limb  muscles  in  the 

monkey.     Archives  of  Neurology  and  Psychiatry,  58,  452  ;    1947. 
Temple,  G.     General  principles  of  quantum  theory.     London,  2nd  ed.,  1942. 
Wiener,  N.     Cybernetics.     New  York,  1948. 
Wolfe,  J.  B.     Effectiveness  of  token-rewards  for  chimpanzees.     Comparative 

Psychology  Monographs,  12,  No.  60  ;    1935-6. 
Young,  J.  Z.     In  Evolution,  edited  G.  R.  de  Beer.     Oxford,  1938. 


282 


Index 


The   reference   is   to   the   page.     A   number   in   bold-faced 
type  indicates  a  definition. 


Accumulation,  142 

Active,  170 

Activity.  5 

Adaptation,  58 

Adaptation,  serial,  200 

Adaptation-time,  148 

Adaptive  behaviour,  58 

Aim,  131 

Algebra  of  machine,  242 

All  or  none,  89 

Alternating  environments,   115 

Ammonia,  77 

Amoeboid  process,  125 

Amplification,  235 

Ancillary  regulations,  218,  229 

Archimedes,  65 

Automatic  pilot,  108 

Awareness,   11 

Axioms,  8,  13 

Bartlett,  Sir  F.  C,  38 
Behaviour,  adaptive,  58 
Behaviour,  learned,  1 
Behaviour,  line  of,  20 
Behaviour,  reflex,  1 
Bladder,  92 

Borrowed  knowledge,   19 
Bound,  48 
Bourbaki,  N.,  241 
Bovd,  D.  A.,  119 
Break,  92,  272 
Burglar,   154 

Cannon,  W.  B.,  58,  64 

Canonical  representation,  244 

Cardinal  number,  32 

Carey,  E.  J.,  125 

Change,  13 

Characteristic  equation,  255 

Chewing,  7 

Chimneys,  181 

Circus,  3 

Civilisation,  62 

Clock,  14 

Combination  lock,  154,  205 

Communication,  218 

Complex  system,  28,  33,  148,  192 

Conditioned  response,  2,   16,   113 

Confluent,  185 


Connectivity,   156 
Consciousness,  11 
Constancy,  164 
Constraint,   139 
Construction,  random,  97 
Control,   159 
Control  by  error,  55 
Co-ordinates,  41 
Co-ordination,  57,  67,  103 
Coughing,  2 
Cowles,  J.  T.,  201 
Critical  state,  91,  274 
Critical  surface,  274 
Crystallisation,  153 
Cullen,  E.,  74 
Curare,  74 
Cvcle,  49 
Cycling,  11,  36 

Dancoff,  S.  M.,  130 

Delay,  120 

Demonstration,   12 

Dependence,  159 

Determinancy,  9,  95 

Diabetes,  74 

Diagram  of  immediate  effects,  51,  122, 

278 
Diagram  of  ultimate  effects,  163,  278 
Dial  reading,   14,  30 
Dictionary,  236 
Discontinuity,   120 
Dispersion,  178 
Disturbance,  130,  138 
Dominance,  161 
Ducklings,  39 

Effectiveness,   162 
Effects,  50 
Elastic,  89,  272 
End-plate,  125 
Endrome,  125 
Energy,  159 
Engine  driver,  6 
Environment,  36 
Environment,  alternating,  115 
Equations,  simultaneous,  206 
Equilibrial  index,   175 
Equilibrium,  neutral,  44 
Equilibrium,  state  of,  46,  254 


283 


INDEX 


Equilibrium,  unstable.  44 
Equivalence  relation,  242 
Error-control,  55 
Essential  variables,  42 
Even  v.  Odd,  232 
Exponential  function,  150 
External  composition,  242 
Eye  muscles,  104 

Failure,  118 

Falcon,  201 

Feedback,  37,  228 

Feedback,  second-order,  83 

Fencing,  67 

Field,  23 

Field,  stable,  49 

Fire,  12 

Fraunhofer  lines,  124 

Full-function,  87 

Function,  full-,  87 

Function,  null-,  87 

Function,  part-,  87 

Function,  step-,  87 

Fuse,  88 

Gating  mechanism,  144,  216 
Gene-pattern,  8,  134 
Gestalt,  156 
Girden,  E.,  74 
Goal-seeking,  54,  81,  131 
Governor,  44,  48,  50 
Grant,  W.  T.,  68 
Grindley,  G.  C,  112 
Group,  244 

Habituation,  185 
Harrison,  R.  G.,  125 
Hertz,  Heinrich,  52,  85 
Hilgard,  E.  R.,  113,  216 
Holmes,  S.  J.,  66 
Homeostasis,  58 
Homeostat,  100,  246 
4  Homeostatic  ',  100 
Humphrey,  G.,  189 
Hunter,  120 
Hurvvitz,  A.,  256 

/.  to  C,  vii 

Immediate  effects,  51,  278 
Impulsive  stimulus,  76 
Inactive,  170 
Independence,  159,  278 
Index  of  equilibria,  175 
Initial  state,  20 
Instrumental  learning,  113 
Insulation,  165 
Intelligence  test,  121 
Interference,  216 
Introduction  to  Cybernetics,  vii 
Invariant,  242 


Isolation,  35,  165 
Iterated  systems,  197 

Jennings,  H.  S.,  38,  189,  193 
Joining,  76,  266 

Kitten,  12,  62,  80 
Kletsky,  E.  J.,  100 
Knowledge,  borrowed,  19 

Laplace,  28 
Lashley,  K.  S.,  182 
Latent  roots,  255 
Learned  behaviour,  2 
Learning,  11,  234 
Learning,  instrumental,  113 
Levi,  G.,  125 
Line  of  behaviour,  20,  243 
Linear  system,  246 
Localisation,  124,  181 
Loeb,  J.,  126 
Logic  of  mechanism,  241 
Lorente  de  N6,  R.,  124 

McCulloch,  W.  S.,  125 
McDougall,  W.,  65 
Machine,  13 

Machine  with  input,  25 
Main  variables,  93,  265 
Mapping,  242,  263 
Marina,  A.,  104 
Marquis,  D.  G.,  113,  216 
Maze-running,  3 
Memory,  10 
Microscope,  3 
Micturition,  92 
Miniaturisation,  127 
Monitoring,  220 
Morgan,  C.  Lloyd,  39,  201 
Motor  end-plate,  125 
Mowrer,  O.  H.,  108 
Miiller,  G.  E.,  216 
Multistage  system,  209 

Natural  selection,  8,  134 

Natural  system,  25 

Neuron,  4 

Neutral  equilibrium,  44 

Nie,  L.  W.,  119 

Noise,  270 

Normal  stability,  253 

Null-function,  87,  264 

Number  of  parts,  148 

Nyquist,  H.,  256 

Objectivity,  9 
Observation,   17 
Odd  v.  Even,  232 
Operation,  primary,  18 
Operational  method,  9,  17 


284 


INDEX 


Optimum,  224 
Oscilloscope,  206 
Outcome.  138 

Pain,  43,   110 

Pain  insensitivity,  119 

Paramecium,  189,  193 

Parameter,  71,  262 

Parker,  G.,   162,   197 

Part  and  whole,  5,  78 

Part-function.  87 

Pauling,  L.,   127 

Pavlov,   I.  P.,   15,  65,   182 

Pendulum,   15,  26,  54,  72 

Phase-space,  22 

Pigeon,  10 

Pike,  111 

Pilot,  automatic,  108 

Point,  representative,  22 

Poison,   119,   140 

Poly  stable  system,  173 

Pre-baiting,   140 

Primary  operation,  18,  243 

Principle  of  interference,  216 

Probability  of  stability,  258 

Punishment,  110,  115 

Quotient-law,  242 

Radio,  52 

Random  construction,  97,   172 

Random  system,  150 

Reaction,  53 

Reciprocity  of  connexions,   124 

Recurrent  situation,   138 

References,  281 

Reflex  behaviour,  1 

Reflexologist,  156 

Regular  system,  243 

Regulator,  ancillary,  218 

Relay,  90,   128 

Re-organisation,  107 

Representative  point,  22 

Requisite  variety,  229 

Response,  conditioned,  2,   16,   113 

Retro-active  inhibition,   141,  214 

Reward,  110 

Robinson,  E.  S.,  217 

Rubin,  H.,  150 

Runaway,  53 

Running,  35 

Sea- anemone,   162,   197 
Second-order  feedback,  83 
Selection  by  equilibrium,  186,  231 
Selection  by  veto,  79 
Selection,  natural,  8,   134 
Self-correction,  55 
Sense  organs,   179 
Serial  adaptation,  200 


Serving,  220 

Servo-mechanism,  53 

Shannon,  C.  E.,  229,  270 

Sherrington,  C.  S.,  157 

Shivering,  59 

Signal,  6 

Simultaneous  equations,  206 

Skaggs,  E.  B.,  217 

Skinner,  B.  F.,  10 

Smoking,  181 

Snail,  189 

Solving  equations,  206 

Sommerhoff,  G.,  69 

Sparks,  174 

Speidel,  C.  C,  125 

Sperry,  R.  W.,  104 

Stability,  44,  253 

Stable  field,  49 

Stable  region,  48 

Stable  system,  49 

Stalking,  120 

Starling,  E.  H.,  38,  64 

State,  16,  243 

State,  critical,  91,  274 

State-determined,  26 

State  of  equilibrium,  46,  254 

Steady  state,  44 

Step-function,  75,  87,  272 

Step-mechanism,  91,  123 

Stepping  switch,  103 

Stimulus,  75 

Stimulus,  impulsive,  76 

Strategy,  28 

Sub-goal,  82,  226 

Subjective,  11 

Surface,  critical,  274 

Survival,  8,  43,  65,  232 

Swallows,  17 

Switch,  88,   167 

System,  16,  243 

System,   complex,   28,    33,    148,    192 

System,  linear,  246 

System,  multistable,  209 

System,  natural,  25 

System,  polystable,  173 

System,  random,  150 

System,  regular,  243 

System,  stable,  49 

System,  ultrastable,  80,  98,  276 

Tabes  dorsalis,  39 
Teleology,  9,  54,  131 
Temple,  G.,  28 
Tennis,  220 
Theory  of  sets,  241 
Thermostat,  44 
Threshold,  168 
Thunderstorm,   17 
Time,  16 
Tissue  culture,  125 


285 


INDEX 


Tokens,  201 
Topology,  241 
Tract,  anatomical,  218 
Training,  4,  110 
Trajectory  length,  150 
Transducer,  270 
Transformation,  249 
Transition,  18,  243 
Trial  and  error,  82 
Trial  duration.  120 
Type-problem,  12,  62,  80 

Ultimate  effects,  278 
Ultrastable  system,  80,  98,  27G 
Uniselector,  103 
Unstable  equilibrium,  44 


Unusual,   116 
Urinary  bladder,  92 

Variable,  14,  30,  71,  243 
Variable,  essential,  42 
Variable,  main,  93 
Veto,  79,  86 
Vicious  circle,  53 
Vocal  cords,  220 

Watt's  governor,  44,  48,  50 
Whole  system,  56,   156 
Wireless,  52 
Wolfe,  J.  B.,  201 

Young,  J.  Z.,  124 


286 


mSm 


BMffliiiirr^ 


111