Skip to main content

Full text of "The Emotions Volume I"

See other formats


121 768 



PSYCHOLOGY CLASSICS 



A SERIES OF REPRINTS ANT> TRANSLATIONS 

EI>ITEI> BY 

KNIGHT I>TJNLAP 

Johns Hopkins University 



THE EMOTIONS 



CARL GEORG LANGE (1834^-1900) 
University of Copenhagen 



WILLIAM JAMES (1&42-1910) 
Harvard University 



VOLUME I 



BALTIMORE 

WILLIAMS & WILKINS COMPANY 
1922 



COPYRIGHT 1922 
WILLIAMS & WILKINS COMPANY 

Made in United States of America 

All rights reserved, including that of translation 

into foreign languages, including 

the Scandinavian 



The Emotions, Chapter XXV, from 
James: Principles of Psychology. Copy- 
right 1890 by Henry Holt and Company 



COMPOSED AND FEINTED AT THE 

WAVERLY PRESS 

BY ram WILLIAMS & WILSONS COMPAKT 

BALXIMOBB, MD., TJ. S. A. 



CONTENTS 

PAGE 

EDITOB'S PREFACE 5 

WHAT is AN EMOTION? William James 11 

THE EMOTIONS, Carl Georg Lange 33 

THE EMOTIONS, William James 93 



EDITOR'S PREFACE 

The publication, in 1872, of Darwin's The Expression of the 
Emotions in Man and Animals had a profound effect upon the 
development of Psychology. Darwin's book gave to three men 
the impetus to develop the theory of the emotions as organic 
processes, and this theory has not only become so strongly en- 
trenched in scientific thought that it is practically assumed to- 
day as the basis for the study of the emotional life, but has also 
led to the development of the hypothesis of reaction or response 
as the basis of all mental life: a hypothesis which is rapidly sup- 
planting the phrenologists' theory of brain-activity. 

The three men who independently developed the organic theory 
of the emotions were Carl Georg Lange in Denmark, William 
James in America, and Alexander Sutherland in Australia. The 
writings of James and Lange had profound influence on contempo- 
rary and later psychologists, and on this account it is not unfair 
to apply the name " James-Lange Theory" to the organic theory 
of the emotions, as is customarily done. This implies no lack of 
appreciation of the work of Sutherland, or of the contributions of 
Ribot, Mosso, and later investigators. 

We present in this volume a new translation of Lange's Ueler 
Omuthsbewegungen, made by Miss Istar A. Haupt from Karelia's 
German version: together with a reprinting of James' What is an 
Emotion? and his chapter on "The Emotions" from the Principles 
of Psychology. These important foundations of modern psychol- 
ogy are thus made readily accessible to students of psychology, 
philosophy, and physiology; and a real need is served. 

In the chapter in the Principles, James repeated some of the 
material which had already been presented in the Mind article. 
It has however been deemed advisable to reprint the earlier article 
as well as the chapter. Historical considerations alone would war- 
rant this, since the chapter is based both on the article and upon 
Lange's monograph, and it is important to have these two inde- 
pendent foundations presented side by side. But there is a still 

5 



6 EDITOB'S PREFACE 

more important reason, in that the Mind article gives a much 
more clear-cut presentation of the organic theory of the emotions 
than does the chapter from the Principles: and in the latter James 
concedes much more to the esthetic and spiritual emotions in 
the way of independence of somatic and visceral processes than 
he does in the former. Whatever may have caused James to 
soften his views on this point, his first formulation of the theory 
is in this respect the more important. 

Carl (or Karl) Georg Lange was born at Vordingborg, Zealand, 
Denmark, in 1834. He studied medicine at the University of 
Copenhagen, and received his degree in 1859. In 1877 he was 
made Professor of Pathological Anatomy in the same University 
and held that position until his death in 1900. He was a man of 
eminence in the field of medicine, but his monograph on the 
emotions is by far his greatest achievement. 

William James was born in New York City in 1842, and gradu- 
ated from Harvard in medicine in 1872. His interests even then 
were in psychology and philosophy rather than in medicine, and 
although his first university appointment, in 1872, was as Lec- 
turer in Physiology in the Harvard Department of Natural 
History, he expressed a strong preference for a position in 
philosophy then vacant. His poor health, however, prevented 
his attempting to secure the latter position. 

James' first academic duty was to assist in a course in Physi- 
ology and Hygiene given to undergraduates: but in 1876 he offered 
a course in Physiological Psychology, and organized a psychological 
laboratory. The following year, the course was transferred to 
the Department of Philosophy. By later appointments, James 
was successively made Assistant Professor of Philosophy (1880), 
Professor of Philosophy (1885), Professor of Psychology (1889), 
and again Professor of Philosophy (1897). He died in 1910. 

Lange's monograph appeared (in Danish) in 1885. A German 
translation by Dr. Kurella appeared in 1887, and from this 
Georges Dumas made in 1895 a French translation which ran 
through several editions. So far as we know, no English transla- 
tion has been published. James 7 article appeared in Mind in 1884, 
and his Principles of Psychotogy in 1893. Sutherland's Origin and 
Growth of the Moral Instinct was printed in 1898, but he had f ormu- 



EDITOR'S PREFACE 7 

lated his version of the organic theory of the emotions, presented 
in that book, some time earlier, apparently before reading either 
James or Lange. We have not deemed it expedient to reprint 
Sutherland's chapters at this time. 

The translation of Lange's monograph was not made from 
the Danish original, but from Kurella's version, published by 
Theodor Thomas (Leipzic), and compared with the French text. 

For permission to print James' Mind article we are indebted 
to the editor of that journal, and for permission to reprint the 
chapter of the Principles, to Henry Holt and Company. 



KNIGHT 



The Johns Hopkins University 
March 4, 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION? 



BY 
WILLIAM JAMES 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION? 

WILLIAM JAMES 
iMind, 1884, vol. IX, pp. 188-205] 

The physiologists who, during the past few years, have been so 
industriously exploring the functions of the brain, have limited 
their attempts at explanation to its cognitive and volitional per- 
formances. Dividing the brain into sensorial and motor centers, 
they have found their division to be exactly paralleled by the 
analysis made by empirical psychology, of the perceptive and 
volitional parts of the mind into their simplest elements. But 
the (esthetic sphere of the mind, its longings, its pleasures and 
pains, and its emotions, have been so ignored in all these researches 
that one is tempted to suppose that if either Dr. Ferrier or Dr. 
Munk were asked for a theory in brain-terms of the latter mental 
facts, they might both reply, either that they had as yet bestowed 
no thought upon the subject, or that they had found it so difficult 
to make distinct hypotheses, that the matter lay for them among 
the problems of the future, only to be taken up after the simpler 
ones of the present should have been definitely solved. 
y^ And yet it is even now certain that of two things concerning the 
emotions, one must be true. Either separate and special centers 
affectecLtp. them ak>ne r are their, brain-seat, or else they correspond 
to processes occurring in the motor and sensory centers, already 
assigned, or in others like them, not yet mapped out, , If the for- 
mer be the case we must deny the current view, and hold the 
cortex to be something more than the surface of "projection" for 
every sensitive spot and every muscle in the body. If the latter 
be the case, we must ask whether the emotional "process" in the 
sensory or motor center be an altogether peculiar one, or whether 
it resembles the ordinary perceptive processes of which those 
centers are already recognized to be the seat. The purpose of the 
following pages is to show that the last alternative comes nearest 
to the truth, and that the emotional brain-processes not only 

11 



12 WILLIAM JAMBS 

resemble the ordinary sensorial brain-processes, but in very truth' 
are nothing but such processes variously combined. The main 
result of this will be to simplify our notions of the possible com- 
plications of brain-physiology, and to make us see that we have- 
already a brain-scheme in our hands whose applications are much 
wider than its authors dreamed. But although this seems to be, 
the chief result of the arguments I am to urge, I should say that 
they were not originally framed for the sake of any such result. 
They grew out of fragmentary introspective observations, and it' 
was only when these had already combined into a theory that the 
thought of the simplification the theory might bring to cerebral 
physiology occurred to me, and made it seem more important 
than before. 

I should say first of all that the only emotions I propose ex- 
pressly to consider here are those that have a distinct bodily 
expression. That there are feelings of pleasure and displeasure, of 
interest and excitement, bound up with mental operations, but 
having no obvious bodily expression for their consequence, would, 
I suppose, be held true by most readers. Certain arrangements 
of sounds, of lines, of colours, are agreeable, and others the re- 
verse, without the degree of the feeling being sufficient to quicken 
the pulse or breathing, or to prompt to movements of either the 
body or the face. Certain sequences of ideas charm us as much 
as others tire us. It is a real intellectual delight to get a problem 
solved, and a real intellectual torment to have to leave it un- 
finished. The first set of examples, the sounds, lines, and colours 
are either bodily sensations, or the images of such. The second* 
set seem to depend on processes in the ideational centers exclu- 
sively. Taken together, they appear to prove that there are 
pleasures and pains inherent in certain forms of- nerve-action as 
such, wherever that action occur. The case of these feelings we 
will at present leave entirely aside, and confine our attention to 
the more complicated cases in which a wave of bodily disturbance 
of some kind accompanies the perception of the interesting sights 
or sounds, or the passage of the exciting train of ideas. Surprise, 
curiosity, rapture, fear, anger, lust, greed, and the like, become 
then the names of the mental states with which the person is 
nossessed. The bodily disturbances are said to be the "mani- 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION 13 

festation" of thepe several emotions, their "expression" or "natu- 
ral language;" and these emotions themselves, being so strongly 
characterised both from within and without, may be called the 
standard emotions. 

Our natural way of thinking about these standard emotions is 
(that the mental perception of some fact excites the mental affec- 
tion called the emotion, and that this latter state of mind gives 
rise to the bodily expression. My thesis on the contrary is that 
the bodily changes follow directly the PERCEPTION of the exciting 
fact) and that our feeling of the same changes as they occur is the 
emotion. Common sense says, we lose our fortune, are sorry and 
weep; we meet a bear, are frightened and run; we are insulted by 
p, rival, are angry and strike. The hypothesis here to be defended 
says that this order of sequence is incorrect, that the one mental 
state *is not immediately induced by the other, that the bodily 
manifestations must first be interposed between, and that the 
more rational statement is that we feel sorry because we cry, 
angry because we strike, afraid because we tremble, and not that 
We cry, strike, or tremble, because we are sorry, angry, or fearful 
as the case may be. Without the bodily states following on the 
perception, the latter would be purely cognitive in form, pale, 
colourless, destitute of emotional warmth. We might then see 
the bear, and judge it best to run, receive the insult and deem it 
right to strike, but we could not actually feel afraid or angry. 

Stated in this crude way, the hypothesis is pretty sure to meet 
with immediate disbelief. And yet neither many nor far-fetched 
considerations are required to mitigate its paradoxical character, 
and possibly to produce conviction of its truth. 

To begin with, readers of the Journal do not need to be reminded 
that the nervous system of every living thing is but a bundle of 
predispositions to react in particular ways upon the contact of 
particular features of the environment. As surely as the hermit- 
crab's abdomen presupposes the existence of empty whelk-shells 
somewhere to be found, so surely do the hound's olfactories imply 
the existence, on the one hand, of deer's or foxes 7 feet, and on the 
other, the tendency to follow up their tracks. The neural machin- 
ery is but a hyphen between determinate arrangements of matter 
outside the bodv and determinate imnulses to inhibition or dis- 



14 WILLIAM JAMES 

charge within its organs. When the hen sees a white oval object 
on the ground she cannot leave it; she must keep upon it and re- 
turn to it, until at last its transformation into a little mass of 
moving chirping down elicits from her machinery an entirely new 
set of performances. The love of man for woman, or of the human 
mother for her babe, our wrath at snakes and our fear of precipices, 
may all be described similarly, as instances of the way in which 
peculiarly conformed pieces of the world's furniture will fatally 
call forth most particular mental and bodily reactions, in advance 
of, and often, in direct opposition to, the verdict of our deliberate 
reason concerning them* The labours of Darwin and his succes- 
sors are only just beginning to reveal the universal parasitism of 
each special creature upon other special things, and the way in 
which each creature brings the signature of its special relations 
stamped on its nervous system with it upon the scene. 

Every living creature is in fact a sort of lock, whose wards and 
springs presuppose special forms of keys, which keys however are 
not born attached to the locks, but are sure to be found in the 
world near by as life goes op. And the locks are indifferent to any 
but their own keys. The gg fails to fascinate the hound, the bird 
does not fear the precipice, the snake waxes not wroth at his kind, 
the deer cares nothing for the woman or the human babe. Those 
who wish for a full development of this point of view, should read 
Schneider's Der thierische Witte no other book shows how ac- 
'curately anticipatory are the actions of animals, of the specific 
features of the environment in which they are to live. 

Now among these nervous anticipations are of course to be 
reckoned the emotions, so far as these may be called forth directly 
by the perception of certain facts. In advance of all experience 
of elephants no child can but be frightened if he suddenly finds 
one trumpeting and charging upon him. No woman can see a 
handsome little naked baby without delight, no man in the wilder- 
ness see a human form in the distance without excitement and 
curiosity. I said I should consider these emotions only so v far as 
they have bodily movements of some sort for their accompani- 
ments. But my first point is to show that their bodily accompani- 
ments are much more far-reaching and complicated than we 
ordinarily suppose. 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION 15 

In the earlier books on Expression, written mostly from the 
artistic point of view, the signs of emotion visible from without 
were the only ones taken account of. Sir Charles Bell's cele- 
brated Anatomy of Expression noticed the respiratory changes; 
and Bain's and Darwin's treatises went more thoroughly still into 
the study of the visceral factors involved, changes in the func- 
tioning of glands and muscles, and in that of the circulatory ap- 
paratus. But not even a Darwin has exhaustively enumerated 
all the bodily affections characteristic of any one of the standard 
emotions. More and more, as physiology advances, we begin to 
discern how almost infinitely numerous and subtle they must be. 
The researches of Mosso with the plethysmograph have shown that 
not only the heart, but the entire circulatory system, forms a 
sort of sounding-board, which every change of our consciousness, 
however slight, may make reverberate. Hardly a sensation comes 
to us without sending waves of alternate constriction and dilata- 
tion down the arteries of our arms. The blood-vessels of the 
abdomen act reciprocally with those of the more outward parts. 
The bladder and bowels, the glands of the mouth, throat, and 
skin, and the liver, are known to be affected gravely in certain 
severe emotions, and are unquestionably affected transiently 
when the emotions are of a lighter sort. That the heart-beats 
and the rhythm of breathing play a leading part in all emotions 
whatsoever, is a matter too notorious for proof. And what is 
really equally prominent, but less likely to be admitted until 
special attention is drawn to the fact, is the continuous coopera- 
tion of the voluntary muscles in our emotional states. Even 
when no change of outward attitude is produced, their inward 
tetision alters to suit each varying mood, and is felt as a difference 
of tone or of strain. In depression the flexors tend to prevail; in 
elation or belligerent excitement the extensors take the lead. And 
the various permutations and combinations of which these organic 
activities are susceptible make it abstractly possible that no shade 
of emotion, however slight, should be without a bodily reverbera- 
tion as unique, when taken in its totality, as is the mental mood 
itself. 

The im.Tn.ense number of parts modified in each emotion is what 
makes it so difficult for us to reproduce in cold blood the total and 
integral expression of any one of them. We may catch the trick 



16 WILLIAM JAMES 

with the voluntary muscles, but fail with the skin, glands, heart, 
and other viscera. Just as an artificially imitated sneeze lacks 
something of the reality, so the attempt to imitate an emotion in 
the absence of its normal instigating cause is apt to be rather 
"hollow." 

The next thing to be noticed is this, that every one of the bodily 
changes, whatsoever it be, is/eZ, acutely or obscurely, the moment 
it occurs. If the reader has never paid attention to this matter, 
he will be both interested and astonished to learn how many 
different local bodily feelings he can detect in himself as character- 
istic of his various emotional moods. It would be perhaps too 
much to expect him to arrest the tide of any strong gust of passion 
for the sake of any such curious analysis as this; but he can ob- 
serve more tranquil states, and that may be assumed here to be 
true of the greater which is shown to be true of the less. Our 
whole cubic capacity is sensibly alive; and each morsel of it con- 
tributes its pulsations of feeling, dim or sharp, pleasant, painful, 
or dubious, to that sense of personality that everyone of us un- 
failingly carries with him. It is surprising what little items give 
accent to these complexes of sensibility. When worried by any 
slight trouble, one may find that the focus of one's bodily con- 
sciousness is the contraction, often quite inconsiderable, of the 
eyes and brows. When momentarily embarrassed, it is some- 
thing in the pharynx that compels either a swallow, a clearing of 
the throat, or a slight cough; and so on for as many more instances 
as might be named. Our concern here being with the general 
view rather than with the details, I will not linger to discuss these 
but, assuming the point admitted that every change that occurs 
must be felt, I will pass on. 1 

1 Of course the physiological question arises, how are the changes felt? 
after they are produced, by the sensory nerves of the organs bringing 
back to the brain a report of the modifications that have occurred? or 
before they are produced, by our being conscious of the outgoing nerve- 
currents starting on their way downward towards the parts they are to 
excite? I believe all the evidence we have to be in favour of the former al- 
ternative. The question is too minute for discussion here, but I have said 
something about it in a paper entitled The Feeling of Effort, in the An- 
niversary Memoirs of the Boston Natural History Society, 1880 (translated 
in La Critique Philosophique for that year, and summarized in Mind XX., 
582). See also O. E. Miiller's Grundlegung der Psychophysik, 110. 



WHAT IS AN^EMOTION 17 

I now proceed to urge the vital point of my whole theory, which 
is this. If we fancy some strong emotion, and then try to ab- 
stract from our consciousness of it all the feelings of its character- 
istic bodily symptoms, we find we have nothing left behind, no 
"mind-stuff" out of which the emotion can be constituted, and 
that a cold and neutral state of intellectual perception is all that 
remains. It is true that although most people, when asked, say 
that their introspection verifies this statement, some persist in 
saying theirs does not. Many cannot be made to understand the 
question. When you beg them to imagine away every feeling of 
laughter and of tendency to laugh from their consciousness of the 
ludicrousness of an object, and then to tell you what the feeling of 
of its ludicrousness would be like, whether it be anything more 
than the perception that the object belongs to the class "funny," 
they persist in replying that the thing proposed is a physical 
impossibility, and that they always must laugh, if they see a funny 
object. Of course the task proposed is not the practical one of 
seeing a ludicrous object and annihilating one's tendency to laugh. 
It is the purely speculative one of subtracting certain elements of 
feeling from an emotional state supposed to exist in its fulness, 
and saying what the residual elements are. I cannot help thinking 
that all who rightly apprehend this problem will agree with the 
proposition above laid down. What kind of an emotion of fear 
would be left, if the feelings neither of quickened heart-beats nor of 
shallow breathing, neither of trembling lips nor of weakened limbs, 
neither of goose-flesh nor of visceral stirrings, were present, it is 
quite impossible to think. Can one fancy the state of rage and 
picture no ebullition of it in the chest, no flushing of the face, no 
dilatation of the nostrils, no clenching of the teeth, no impulse to 
vigorous action, but in their stead limp muscles, calm breathing, 
and a placid face? The present* writer, for one, certainly cannot. 
The rage is as completely evaporated as the sensation of its so- 
called manifestations, and the only thing that can possibly be 
supposed to take its place is some cold-blooded and dispassionate 
judicial sentence, confined entirely to the intellectual realm, to the 
effect that a certain person or -persons merit chastisement for their 
sins. In like manner of grief: what would it be without its tears, 
its sobs, its suffocation of the heart, its pang in the breast-bone? 



18 WILLIAM JAMES 

A f eelingless cognition that certain circumstances are deplorable, 
and nothing more. Every passion in turn tells the same story. 
A purely disembodied human emotion is a nonentity. I do not 
say that it is a contradiction in the nature of things, or that pure 
spirits are necessarily condemned to cold intellectual lives; but 
I say that for ws, emotion dissociated from all bodily feeling is 
inconceivable. The more closely I scrutinise my states, the more 
persuaded I become, that whatever moods, affections, and passions 
I have, are in very truth constituted by, and made up of, those 
bodily changes we ordinarily call their expression or consequence; 
and the more it seems to me that if I were to become corporeally 
anaesthetic, I should be excluded from the life of the affections, 
harsh and tender alike, and drag out an existence of merely cogni- 
tive or intellectual form. Such an existence, although it seems to 
have been the ideal of ancient sages, is too apathetic to be keenly 
sought after by those born after the revival of the worship of 
sensibility, a few generations ago. 

But if the emotion is nothing but the feeling of the reflex bodily 
effects of what we call its "object," effects due to the connate 
adaptation of the nervous system to that object, we seem im- 
mediately faced by this objection: most of the objects of civilised 
man's emotions are things to which it would be preposterous to 
suppose their nervous systems connately adapted. Most occa- 
sions of shame and many insults are purely conventional, and vary 
with the social environment. The same is true of many matters 
of dread and of desire, and of many occasions of melancholy and 
regret. In these cases, at least, it would seem that the ideas of 
shame, desire, regret, etc., must first have been attached by educa- 
tion and association to these conventional objects before the bodily 
changes could possibly be awakened. And if in these cases the 
b'odily changes follow the ideas, instead of giving rise to them, 
why not then in all cases? 

To discuss thoroughly this objection would carry us deep into 
the study of purely intellectual ^Esthetics. A few words must 
aere suffice. We will say nothing of the argument's failure to 
iistinguish between the idea of an emotion and the emotion it- 
jelf . We will only recall the well-known evolutionary principle 
;hat when a certain power has once been fixed in an animal by 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION 19 

virtue of its utility in presence of certain features of the environ- 
ment, it may turn out to be useful in presence of other features of 
the environment that had originally nothing to do with either 
producing or preserving it, A nervous tendency to discharge being 
once there, all sorts of unforeseen things may pull the trigger and 
let* loose the effects. That among these things should be con- 
ventionalities of man's contriving is a matter of no psychological 
consequence whatever. The most important part of my environ- 
ment is my fellow-man. The consciousness of his attitude 
towards me is the perception that normally unlocks most of my 
shames and indignations and fears. The extraordinary sensitive- 
ness of this consciousness is shown by the bodily modifications 
wrought in us by the awareness that our fellow-man is noticing us 
at all. No one can walk across the platform at a public meeting 
with just the same muscular innervation he uses to walk across his 
room at home. No one can give a message to such a meeting with- 
out organic excitement. "Stage-fright" is only the extreme 
degree of that wholly irrational personal self-consciousness which 
everyone gets in some measure, as soon as he feels the eyes of a 
number of strangers fixed upon him, even though he be inwardly 
convinced that their feeling towards him is of no practical account. 2 
This being so, it is not surprising that the additional persuasion 
that my fellow-man's attitude means either well or ill for me 
should awaken stronger emotions still. In primitive societies 
"well" may mean handing me a piece of beef, and "ill" may 
mean aiming a blow at my skull. In our "cultured age," "ill" 
may mean cutting me in the street, and "well," giving me an 
honorary degree. What the action itself may be is quite insignifi- 
cant, so long as I can perceive in it intent or animus. That is the 
emotion-arousing perception; and may give rise to as strong 
bodily convulsions in me, a civilised man experiencing the treat- 
ment of an artificial society, as in any savage prisoner of war, 

2 Let it 'be noted in passing that this personal self -consciousness seems 
an altogether bodily affair, largely a consciousness of our attitude, and 
that, like other emotions, it reacts on its physical condition, and leads to 
modifications of the attitude, to a certain rigidity in most men, but in 
children to a regular twisting and squirming fit, and in women to various 
gracefully shy poses. 



20 WILLIAM JAMES 

learning whether his captors are about to eat him or to make him 
a member of their tribe. 

But now, this objection disposed of, there arises a more general 
doubt. Is there any evidence, it may be asked, for the assump- 
tion that particular perceptions do produce widespread bodily 
effects -by a sort of immediate physical influence, antecedent to 
the arousal of an emotion or emotional idea? 

The only possible reply is, that there is most assuredly such 
evidence. In listening to poetry, drama, or heroic narrative, we 
are often surprised at the cutaneous shiver which like a sudden 
wave flows over us, and at the heart-swelling and the lachrymal 
effusion that unexpectedly catch us at intervals. In listening to 
music, the same is even more strikingly true. If we abruptly see 
a dark moving form in the woods, our heart stops beating, and we 
catch our breath instantly and before any articulate idea of danger 
can arise. If our friend goes near to the edge of a precipice, we 
get the well-known feeling of "all-overishness/ 7 and we shrink 
back, although we positively know htm to be safe, and have no 
distinct imagination of his fall. The writer well remembers his 
astonishment, when a boy of seven or eight, at fainting when he 
saw a horse bled. The blood was in a bucket, with a stick in it, 
and, if memory does not deceive him, he stirred it round and saw 
it drip from the stick with no feeling save that of childish curiosity. 
Suddenly the world grew black before his eyes, his ears began to 
buzz, and he knew no more. He had never heard of the sight of blood 
producing f aintness or sickness, and he had so little repugnance to 
it, and so little apprehension of any other sort of danger from it, 
that even at that tender age, as he well remembers, he could not 
help wondering how the mere physical presence of a pailful of 
crimson fluid could occasion in him such formidable bodily effects. 
"-^Imagine two steel knife-blades with their keen edges crossing 
each other at right angles, and moving to and fro. Our whole 
nervous organisation is "on-edge" at the thought; and yet what 
emotion can be there except the unpleasant nervous feeling itself, 
or the dread that more of it may come? The entire fund and 
capital of the emotion here is the senseless bodily effect the blades 
immediately arouse. This case is typical of a class: where an 
ideal emotion seems to precede the bodily symptoms, it is often 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION 21 

nothing but a representation of the symptoms themselves. One 
who has already fainted at the sight of blood may witness the 
preparations for a surgical operation with uncontrollable heart- 
sinking and anxiety. He anticipates certain feelings, and the 
anticipation precipitates their arrival. I am told of a case of mor- 
bid terror, of which the subject confessed that what possessed 
her seemed, more than anything, to be the fear of fear itself. In 
the various forms of what Professor Bain calls "tender emotion/' 
although the appropriate object must usually be directly con- 
templated before the emotion can be aroused, yet sometimes 
thinking of the symptoms of the emotion itself may have the same 
effect. In sentimental natures, the thought of " yearning" will 
produce real "yearning." And, not to speak of coarser examples, 
a mother's imagination of the caresses she bestows on her child 
may arouse a spasm of parental longing. 

In such cases as these, we see plainly how the emotion both be- 
gins and ends with what we call its effects or manifestations. It 
has no mental status except as either the presented feeling, or the 
idea, of the manifestations; which latter thus constitute its entire 
material, its sum and substance, and its stock-in-trade. And 
these cases ought to make us see how in all cases the feeling of the 
manifestations may play a much deeper part in the constitution 
of the emotion than we are wont to suppose. 

If our theory be true, a necessary corollary of it ought to be 
that any voluntary arousal of the so-called manifestations of a 
special emotion ought to give us the emotion itself. Of course 
in the majority of emotions, this test is inapplicable; for many of 
the manifestations are in organs over which we have no volitional 
control. Still, within the limits in which it can be verified, experi- 
ence fully corroborates this test. Everyone knows how panic is 
increased by flight, and how the giving way to the symptoms of 
grief or anger increases those passions themselves. Each fit of 
sobbing makes the sorrow more acute, and calls forth another fit 
stronger still, until at last repose only ensues with lassitude and 
with the apparent exhaustion of the machinery. In rage, it is 
notorious how we "work ourselves up" to a climax by repeated 
outbreaks of expression. Refuse to express a passion, and it dies. 
Count ten before venting your anger, and its occasion seems 



22 WILLIAM JAMES 

ridiculous. Whistling to keep up courage is no mere figure of 
speech. On the other hand, sit all day in a moping posture, sigh, 
and reply to everything with a dismal voice, and your melancholy 
lingers. There is no more valuable precept in moral education 
than this, as all who have experience know: if we wish to conquer 
undesirable emotional tendencies in ourselves, we must assiduously, 
and in the first instance cold-bloodedly, go through the outward 
motions of those contrary dispositions we prefer to cultivate. The 
reward of persistency will infallibly come, in the fading out of the 
sullenness or depression, and the advent of real cheerfulness and 
kindliness in their stead. Smooth the brow, brighten the eye, 
contract the dorsal rather than the ventral aspect of the frame, 
and speak in a major key, pass the genial compliment, and your 
heart must be frigid indeed if it does not gradually thaw! 

The only exceptions to this are apparent, not real. The great 
emotional expressiveness and mobility of certain persons often 
lead us to say " They would feel more if they talked less." And in 
another class of persons, the explosive energy with which passion 
manifests itself on critical occasions, seems correlated with the 
way in which they bottle it up during the intervals. But these are 
only eccentric types of character, and within each type the law of 
the last paragraph prevails. The sentimentalist is so constructed 
that "gushing" is his or her normal mode of expression. Putting 
a stopper on the "gush" will Only to a limited extent cause more 
"real" activities to take its place; in the main it will simply pro- 
duce listlessness. On the other hand the ponderous and bilious 
"slumbering volcano," let him repress the expression of his pas- 
sions as he will, will find them expire if they get no vent at all; 
whilst if the rare occasions multiply which he deems worthjr of 
their outbreak, he will find them grow in intensity as life proceeds. 

I feel persuaded there is no real exception to the law. The 
formidable effects of suppressed tears might be mentioned, and 
the calming results of speaking out your mind when angry and 
having done with it. But these are also but specious wanderings 
from the rule. Every perception must lead to some nervous 
result. If this be the normal emotional expression, it soon ex- 
pends itself, and in the natural course of things a calm succeeds. 
But if the normal issue be blocked from any cause, the currents 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION 23 

may under certain circumstances invade other tracts, and there 
work different and worse effects. Thus vengeful brooding may 
replace a burst of indignation; a dry heat may consume the frame 
of one who fain would weep, or he may, as Dante says, turn to 
stone within; and then tears or a storming-fit may bring a grateful 
relief. When we teach children to repress their emotions, it is 
not that they may feel more; quite the reverse. It is that they 
may think more; for to a certain extent whatever nerve-currents 
are diverted from the regions below, must swell the activity of the 
thought-tracts of the brain. 3 

The last great argument in favour of the priority of the bodily 
symptoms to the felt emotion, is the ease with which we formulate 
by its means pathological cases and normal cases under a common 
scheme. In every asylum we find examples of absolutely unmo- 
tived fear, anger, melancholy, or conceit; and others of an equally 
unmotived apathy which persists in spite of the best of outward 
reasons why it should give way. In the former cases we must 
suppose the nervous machinery to be so "labile" in some one 
emotional direction, that almost every stimulus, however inap- 
propriate, will cause it to upset in that way, and as a consequence 
to engender the particular complex of feelings of which the psychic 
body of the emotion consists. Thus, to take one special instance, 
-* inability to draw deep breath, fluttering of the heart, and that 
peculiar epigastric change felt as "precordial anxiety, '* with an 
irresistible tendency to take a somewhat crouching attitude and 
to sit still, and with perhaps other visceral processes not now 
known, all spontaneously occur together in a certain person; his 
feeling of their combination is the emotion of dread, and he is 
the victim of what is known as morbid fear. A friend who has had 
occasional attacks of this most distressing of all maladies, tells me 

8 This is the opposite of what happens in injuries to the brain, whether 
from outward violence, inward rupture or tumor, or mere starvation from 
disease. The cortical permeability seems reduced, so that excitement, 
instead of propagating itself laterally through the ideational channels as 
before tends to take the downward track into the organs of the body. The 
consequence is that we have tears, laughter, and temper-fits, on the most 
insignificant provocation, accompanying a proportional feebleness in 
logical thought and the power of volitional attention and decision. 



24 WILLIAM JAMES 

that in his case the whole drama seems to centre about the region 
of the heart and respiratory apparatus, that his main effort during 
the attacks is to get control of his inspirations and to slow his 
heart, pad that the moment he attains to breathing deeply and to 
holding himself erect, the dread, ipso facto, seems to depart. 4 

The account given to Brachet by one of his own patients of her 
opposite condition, that of emotional insensibility, has been often 
quoted, and deserves to be quoted again: 

I still continue (she says) to suffer constantly; I have not a moment of 
comfort, and no human sensations. Surrounded by all that can render 
life happy and agreeable, still to me the faculty of enjoyment and of feel- 
ing is wantingboth have become physical impossibilities . In everything, 
even in -the most tender caresses of my children, I find only bitterness. 
I cover them with kisses, but there is something between their lips and 
mine; and this horrid something is between me and all the enjoyments of 
life. My existence is incomplete. The functions and acts of ordinary 
life, it is true, still remain to me ; but in every one of them there is something 
wantingto wit, the feeling which is proper to them, and the pleasure 

which follows them Each of my senses, each part of my proper 

self, is as if it were separated from me and can no longer afford me any feeling; 
this impossibility seems to depend upon a void which I feel in the front of my 
head, and to be due to the diminution of the sensibility over the whole surface 
of my body, for it seems to me that I never actually reach the objects which I 

touch I feel well enough the changes of temperature on my 

sJcin but I no longer experience the internal feeling of the air when I breathe. 

4 It must be confessed that there are cases of morbid fear in which ob- 
jectively the heart is not much perturbed. These however fail to prove 
anything against our theory, for it is of course possible that the cortical 
centres normally percipient, of dread as a complex of cardiac and other 
organic sensations due to real bodily change, should become primarily 
excited in brain-disease, and give rise to an hallucination of the changes 
being there, an hallucination of dread, consequently, coexistent with a 
comparatively calm pulse, <fec. I say it is possible, for I am ignorant of 
observations which might test the fact. Trance, ecstasy, &c., offer analo- 
gous examplesnot to speak of ordinary dreaming. Under all these con- 
ditions one may have the liveliest subjective feelings, either of eye or ear, 
or of the more visceral and emotional sort, as a result of pure nerve-central 
activity, with complete peripheral repose. Whether the subjective 
strength of the feeling be due in these cases to the actual energy of the 
central disturbance, or merely to the narrowing of the field of conscious- 
ness, need not concern us. In the asylum cases of melancholy, there is 
usually a narrowing of the field. 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION 25 

.... AH this would be a small matter enough, but for its frightful re- 
sult, which is that of the impossibility of any other kind of feeling and of 
any sort of enjoyment, although I experience a need and desire of them that 
render my life an incomprehensible torture. Every function, every ac- 
tion of my life remains, but deprived of the feeling that belongs to it, of 
the enjoyment that should follow it. My feet are cold, I warm them, 
but gain no pleasure from the warmth. I recognize the taste of all I eat, 

without getting any pleasure from it My children are growing 

handsome and healthy, everyone tells me so, I see it myself, but the delight, 
the inward comfort I ought to feel, I fail to get. Music has lost all charm 
for me, I used to love it dearly. My daughter plays very well, but for me 
it is mere noise. That lively interest which a year ago made me hear a 
delicious concert in the smallest air their fingers played, 'that thrill, that 
general vibration which made me shed such tender tears, all that exists no 
more. 5 

Other victims describe themselves as closed in walls of ice or 
covered with an india-rubber integument, through which no 
impression penetrates to the sealed-up sensibility. 

If our hypothesis be true, it makes us realize more deeply than 
ever how much our mental life is knit up with our corporeal frame, 
in the strictest sense of the term. Bapture, love, ambition, indig- 
nation, and pride, considered as feelings, are fruits of the same soil 
with the grossest bodily sensations of pleasure and of pain. But 
it was said at the outset that this would be affirmed only of what 
we then agreed to call the "standard" emotions; and that those 
inward sensibilities that appeared devoid at first sight of bodily 
results should be left out of our account. We had better, before 
closing, say a word or two about these latter feelings. 

They are, the reader will remember, the moral, intellectual, and 
aesthetic feelings. Concords of sounds, of colours, of lines, 
logical consistencies, teleological fitnesses, affect us with a pleasure 
that seems ingrained in the very form of the representation itself, 
and to borrow nothing from any reverberation surging up from the 
parts below the brain. The Herbartian psychologists have tried 
to distinguish feelings due to the form in which ideas may be ar- 
ranged. A geometrical demonstration may be as "pretty" and 
an act of justice as "neat" as a drawing or a tune, although the 
prettiness and neatness seem here to be a pure matter of sensation, 

5 Quoted by Semal: De la SensibilitS g&n&rale dans Us Affections m&an- 
coliques, Paris, 1876, pp. 130-135. 



26 WILLIAM JAMBS 

and there to have nothing to do with sensation. We have, then, 
or some of us seem to have, genuinely cerebral forms of pleasure 
and displeasure, apparently not agreeing in their mode of pro- 
duction with the so-called " standard" emotions we have been 
analysing. And it is certain that readers whom our reasons have 
hitherto failed to convince will now start up at this admission, 
and consider that by it we give up our whole case. Since musical 
perceptions, since logical ideas, can immediately arouse a form 
of emotional feeling, they will say: Is it not more natural to sup- 
pose that in the case if the so-called "standard" emotions, 
prompted by the presence of objects or the experience of events, 
the emotional feeling is equally immediate, and the bodily expres- 
sion something that comes later and is added on? 

But a sober scrutiny of the cases of pure cerebral emotion gives 
little force to this assimilation. Unless in them there actually 
be coupled with the intellectual feeling a bodily reverberation of 
some kind, unless we actually laugh at the neatness of the mechani- 
cal device, thrill at the justice of the act, or tingle at the perfection 
of the musical form, our mental condition is more allied to a judg- 
ment of right than to anything else. And such a judgment is 
rather to be classed among awarenesses of truth: it is a cognitive 
act. But as a matter of fact the intellectual feeling hardly ever 
does exist thus unaccompanied. The bodily sounding-board is 
at work, as careful introspection will show, far more than we 
usually suppose. Still, where long familiarity with a certain class 
of effects has blunted emotional sensibility thereto as much as it 
has sharpened the taste and judgment, we do get the intellectual 
emotion, if such it can be called, pure and undefiled. And the 
dryness of it, the paleness, the absence of all glow, as it may exist 
in a thoroughly expert critic's mind, not only shows us what an 
altogether different thing it is from the "standard" emotions we 
considered first, but makes us suspect that almost the entire dif- 
ference lies in the fact that the bodily sounding-board, vibrating 
in the one case, is in the other mute. "Not so very bad" is, in a 
person of consummate taste, apt to be the highest limit of approv- 
ing expression. "Rien ne me choque" is said to have been Chopin's 
superlative of praise of new music. A sentimental layman would 
feel, and ought to feel, horrified, on being admitted into such a 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION 27 

critic's mind, to see how cold, how thin, how void of human 
significance, are the motives for favour or disfavour that there 
prevail. The capacity to make a nice spot on the wall will out- 
weigh a picture's whole content; a foolish trick of words will pre- 
serve a poem; an utterly meaningless fitness of sequence in one 
musical composition set at naught any amount of "expressiveness" 
in another. 

I remember seeing an English couple sit for more than an hour 
on a piercing February day in the Academy at Venice before the 
celebrated "Assumption" by Titian; and when I, after being 
chased from room to room by the cold, concluded to get into the 
sunshine as fast as possible and let the pictures go, but before leav- 
ing drew reverently near to them to learn with what superior forms 
of susceptibility they might be endowed, all I overheard was the 
woman's voice murmuring: "What a deprecatory expression her 
face wears! What self-abne^afe'on/ How unworthy she feels of 
the honour she is receiving!" Their honest hearts had been kept 
warm all the time by a glow of spurious sentiment that would have 
fairly made old Titian sick. Mr. Ruskin somewhere makes the 
(for him) terrible admission that religious people as a rule care little 
for pictures, and that when they do care for them they generally 
prefer the worst ones to the best. Yes! in every art, in every 
science, there is the keen perception of certain relations being 
right or not, and there is the emotional flush and thrill consequent 
thereupon. And these are two things, not one. In the former of 
them it is that experts and masters are at home. The latter ac- 
companiments are bodily commotions that they may hardly feel, 
but that may be experienced in their fulness by critins and Philis- 
tines in whom the critical judgment is at its lowest ebb. The 
"marvels" of Science, about which so much edifying popular 
literature is written, are apt to be "caviare" to the men in the 
laboratories. Cognition and emotion are parted even in this last 
retreat, who shall say that their antagonism may not just be one 
phase of the world-old struggle known as that between the spirit 
and the flesh? a struggle in which it seems pretty certain that 
neither party will definitively drive the other off the field. 

To return now to our starting-point, the physiology of the brain. 
If we suppose its cortex to contain centres for the perception of 



28 WILLIAM JAMES 

changes in each special sense-organ, in each portion of the skin, 
in each muscle, each joint, and each viscus, and to contain abso- 
lutely nothing else, we still have a scheme perfectly capable of 
representing the process of the emotions. An object falls on a 
sense-organ and is apperceived by the appropriate cortical centre; 
or else the latter, excited in some other way, gives rise to an idea 
of the same object. Quick as a flash, the reflex currents pass 
down through their preordained channels, alter the condition of 
muscle, skin and viscus; and these alterations, apperceived like the 
original object, in as many specific portions of the cortex, combine 
with it in consciousness and transform it from an object-simply- 
apprehended into an object-emotionally-felt. No new principles 
have to be invoked, nothing is postulated beyond the ordinary 
reflex circuit, and the topical centres admitted in one shape or 
another by all to exist. 

It must be confessed that a crucial test of the truth of the 
hypothesis is quite as hard to obtain as its decisive refutation. A 
case of complete internal and external corporeal anaesthesia, 
without motor alteration or alteration of intelligence except 
emotional apathy, would afford, if not a crucial test, at least a 
strong presumption, in favour of the truth of the view we have 
set forth; whilst the persistence of strong emotional feeling in 
such a case would completely overthrow our case. Hysterical 
anaesthesias seem never to be complete enough to cover the 
ground. Complete anaesthesias from organic disease, on the 
other hand, are excessively rare. In the famous case of Remigius 
Leims, no mention is made by the reporters of his emotional 
condition, a circumstance which by itself affords no presumption 
that it was normal, since as a rule nothing ever is noticed without 
a pre-existing question in the mind. Dr. Georg Winter has 
recently described a case somewhat similar, 6 and in reply to a 
question, kindly writes to me as follows: 

The case has been for a year and a half entirely removed from my ob- 
servation. But so far as I am. able to state, the man was characterised by 
a certain mental inertia and indolence. He was tranquil, and had on the 

6 "Ein Fall von allgemeiner Anaesthesie," Inaugural-Dissertation. 
Heidelberg, Winter, 1882, 



WHAT IS AN EMOTION 29 

whole the temperament of a phlegmatic. He was not irritable, not quarrel- 
some, went quietly about his farm-work, and left the care of his business 
and house-keeping to other people. In short, he gave one the impression 
of a placid countryman, who has no interests beyond his work. 

Dr. Winter adds that in studying the case he paid no particular 
attention to the man's psychic condition, as this seemed "neben- 
sachlich" to his main purpose. I should add that the form of my 
question to Dr. Winter could give him no clue as to the kind of 
answer I expected. 

Of course, this case proves nothing, but it is to be hoped that 
asylum-physicians and nervous specialists may begin methodically 
to study the relation between anaesthesia and emotional apathy. 
If the hypothesis here suggested is ever to be definitively confirmed 
or disproved it seems as if it must be by them, for they alone have 
the data in their hands. 

P.S. By an unpardonable forgetfulness at the time of despatching my 
MS. to the Editor, I ignored the existence of the extraordinary case of total 
anaesthesia published by Professor Striimpell in Ziemssen's Deutsches 
Archiv fiir klinische Meditin xxii., 321, of which I had nevertheless read 
.reports at the time of its publication. (C/. first report of the case in 
Mind X., 263, translated from Pfltiger's Archiv. ED.) I believe that it 
constitutes the only remaining case of the sort in medical literature, so 
that with it our survey is complete. On referring to the original, which is 
important in many connections, I found that the patient, a shoemaker's 
apprentice of 15, entirely anaesthetic, inside and out, with the exception 
of one eye and one ear, had shown shame on the occasion of soiling his 
bed, and grief, when a formerly favourite dish was set before him, at the 
thought that he could no longer taste its flavour. As Dr. Striimpell seemed 
however to have paid no special attention to his psychic states, so far as 
these are matter for our theory, I wrote to him in a few words what the 
essence of the theory was, and asked him to say whether he fait sure the 
grief and shame mentioned were real feelings in the boy's mind, or only 
the reflex manifestations provoked by certain perceptions, manifestations 
that an outside observer might note, but to which the boy himself might be 
insensible. 

Dr. Striimpell has sent me a very obliging reply, of which I translate the 
most important passage. 

"1 must indeed confess that I naturally failed to institute with my Anaes- 
thetiker observations as special as the sense of your theory would require. 
Nevertheless I think I can decidedly make the statement, that he was by 
no means completely lacking in emotional affections. In addition to the 
feelings of grief and shame mentioned in my paper, I recall distinctly 



30 WILLIAM JAMES 

that he showed, e.g., anger, and frequently quarrelled with the hospital 
attendants. He also manifested fear lest I should punish him. In short, 
I do not think that my case speaks exactly in favour of your theory. On 
the other hand, I will not affirm that it positively refutes your theory. 
For my case was certainly one of a very centrally conditioned anaesthesia 
(perception-anaesthesia, like that of hysterics) and therefore the conduc- 
tion of outward impressions may in him have been undisturbed." 

I confess that I do not see the relevancy of the last consideration, and 
this makes me suspect that my own letter was too briefly or obscurely 
expressed to put my correspondent fully in possession of my own thought. 
For his reply still makes no explicit reference to anything but the outward 
manifestations of emotion in the boy. Is it not at least conceivable that, 
just as a stranger, brought into the boy's presence for the first time, and 
seeing him eat and drink and satisfy other natural necessities, would sup- 
pose him to have the feelings of hunger, thirst, &c., until informed by the 
boy himself that he did all these things with no feeling at all but that of 
sight and sound is it not, I say, at least possible, that Dr. Strtimpell, 
addressing no direct introspective questions to his patient, and the patient 
not being of a class from which one could expect voluntary revelations of 
that sort, should have similarly omitted to discriminate between a feeling 
and its habitual motor accompaniment, and erroneously taken the latter 
as proof that the former was there? Such a mistake is of course possible, 
and I must therefore repeat Dr. StriimpelPs own words, that his case does 
not yet refute my theory. Should a similar case recur, it ought to be in- 
terrogated as to the inward emotional state that co-existed with the out- 
ward expressions of shame, anger, &c. And if it then turned out that the 
patient recognized explicitly the same mood of feeling known under those 
names in his former normal state, my theory would of course fall. It is, 
however, to me incredible that the patient should have an identical feel- 
ing, for the dropping out of the organic sounding-board would necessarily 
diminish its volume in some way. The teacher of Dr. StrumpeH's patient 
found a mental deficiency in him during his anaesthesia, that may possibly 
have been due to the consequences resulting to his general intellectual 
vivacity from the subtraction of so important a mass of feelings, even 
though they were not the whole of his emotional life. Whoever wishes to 
extract from the next case of total anaesthesia the maximum of knowledge 
about the emotions, will have to interrogate the patient with some such 
notion as that of my article in his mind. We can define the pure psychic 
emotions far better by starting from such an hypothesis and modifying it 
in the way of restriction and subtraction, than by having no definite hy- 
pothesis at all. Thus will the publication of my article have been justified, 
even though the theory it advocates, rigorously taken, be erroneous. The 
best thing I can say for it is, that in writing it, I have almost persuaded 
myself it may be true. 



THE EMOTIONS 

BT 
CARL GEORG IANGE, M.D. 



THE EMOTIONS 

A PSYCHOPHYSIOLOGICAL STUDY 

GAEL GEORG LANGE, M.D. 
Professor of Medicine in Copenhagen 

TBANSLATED BY ISTAR A. EATTPT 
From the Authorized German Translation of H. Kurella, M.D. 

Kant, in a passage in his Anthropologiej qualifies the affections 
as diseases of the mind. 

He considers the mind normal only as long as it is under the 
incontrovertible and absolute control of reason. Anything that 
causes it to be disturbed seems to him to be abnormal and harm- 
ful to the individual. 

To a more realistic school of psychology, which knows no ab- 
stract "Ideal" man, but rather "takes men as they are," such a 
doctrine of the soul must appear strange. It must be but a 
meager conception of man's existence, to consider pain and pleas- 
ure, pity and anger, defiance and humility, as conditions foreign 
to normal life, or even as something from which one must turn 
away if one wishes to recognize the actual nature of man-kind. 
A theory which makes the power of admiring the great, of deriving 
pleasure from the beautiful, and of being moved by misfortune, 
a disease, results in a limitation of the extent of our mental life. 
Such a theory will consider the imperturbable arithmetic teacher, 
to whom every impression is merely an impulse to draw rational 
conclusions, as the only normal, healthy individual. It is a 
strange conception of the interaction of mental powers to consider 
as accidental that which plays a larger and more vital part than 
normal reason in the mental life of most men, and which deter- 
mines to a much higher degree than reason the fate of nations as 
well as of individuals. 

Who would wish to cure an unhealthy mind, if by so doing ne 
would rob man of all that goes to make him a sympathetic crea- 



34 CARL GEORG LANGE 

ture; that enables him to share the pleasure and pain of those of 
his kind; and to admire his like or to hate them? No, however 
true it may be that we must eliminate our passions wherever it is 
a question of calm consideration, clear recognition, or unbiased 
judgment, it is undoubtedly just as true that we cannot consider 
an individual who can only think, recognize, judge but not suffer, 
fear or rejoice a true, healthy, complete human being, even if 
occasionally these abilities may be detrimental to his power of 
understanding and judgment. 

Emotions are not only the most important factors in the life 
of the individual human being, but they are also the most power- 
fid forces of nature known to us. Every page in the history of 
nations testifies to their invincible power. 

The storm of passions has cost more lives and has destroyed 
more lands than hurricanes; their floods have wiped out more 
towns than floods of water. Wherefore, it must seem strange, 
indeed, to us that careful measures have not been taken to study 
their nature and behavior. Whereas the greatest efforts have 
been made to obtain knowledge of the causes and activities of 
other forces of nature for the sake of controlling them as much as 
possible, the investigation of the greatest force of all, the one which 
concerns us so vitally and personally, has been neglected to such 
an extent that we can be said scarcely to possess even the most 
superficial understanding of its more immediate conditions and 
its true nature. 

In this article no attempt has been made to give a complete 
representation of the physiology of the emotions, or even a 
general review of the main points. The study is limited entirely 
to one aspect of the problem. It owes its origin primarily to the 
necessity of clearing up, for practical medical purposes of my own, 
the relation of the emotions to bodily conditions (often patho- 
logical) ; and if possible to ascertain this relation by means of a 
more precise, physiological method than has heretofore been 
attempted. 

As often happens, I was led further in my work than I intended 
to go originally. A somewhat more searching investigation of the 
subject very soon led me to the conclusion that the task which I 
had set myself namely, to determine (in agreement with popular 



THE EMOTIONS 35 

psychology) "what effects the emotions have upon body func- 
tions" offered not only great difficulties, but in point of fact was 
also absolutely impossible, simply because the question had been 
put in reverse order. 

It soon became apparent that to throw some light upon the 
matter, the investigation must encompass a wider field because 
the point of departure namely, the conception of "Emotions" 
is entirely without scientific definiteness, especially if more rigorous 
demands are made than those which would satisfy the purely 
..speculative psychologist. 

What is an emotion? I hope the result of this little study will 
be to obtain a clear, more positive conception of this term. But 
even at the very outset, one meets with the necessity of setting 
some sort of territorial limitation to the conception of "emotion" 
for the sake of preliminary comprehension, since neither popular 
nor scientific speech gives us any definition, at least, none that is 
accepted generally. To say that we wish to deal here chiefly with 
the "affections" does not clearly define our field of activity. 

However, I do not mean to say that it would be difficult to 
enumerate all the phenomena which might be included under this 
heading, all the various kinds of affections. That is of no con- 
sequence to me since I do not aim at completeness in that regard, 
even if it be permissible to speak of completeness here. On the 
contrary, as will be evident further on, I intend to confine myself 
to a very narrow field. It is, however, of some importance to deal 
with as clear a conception as possible; I mean, a conception which 
includes, physiologically, only phenomena that are analogous. In 
this regard, it is not possible to start from any one point that will 
satisfy all conditions. Heterogeneous conceptions overlap, in 
popular speech as well as in scientific psychology, because of a 
certain family resemblance, so to speak. Sorrow, joy, fear, anger 1 
and the like, on the one hand, and on the other, love, hate, scorn, 
admiration, etc., are obviously two groups of phenomena which, 
from the point of view of psychology, must be kept apart. I shall 
retain the term "Emotions" with reference to the first group only, 
whereas I shall let the others be called passions, feelings, or any- 
thing else appropriate. 



36 GAEL GEOBG LANGE 

Yet the line of demarcation between the two has never been 
clearly defined (I), 1 although it is difficult to explain why scientific 
psychology, at least, has not felt the necessity for a more rigorous 
definition. For it is absolutely necessary to keep these two apart 
as much as possible; at least, when one is dealing with the physiol- 
ogy of these phenomena (2). We cannot throw conditions such 
as fright, rage, joy, together with jealousy, love, desire for freedom, 
etc. And the difference between these two groups lies not only in 
the fact that the latter is more complicated, and includes dis- 
similar disturbances of the mind so that .disturbances in imagina- 
tion and reflexion especially play a part in their origin (3) ; but also 
they are complicated and heterogeneous in the conditions of their 
origin. Feelings such as love, hate, admiration, etc., consist of 
quite complex psychic phenomena, in which the emotions of joy, 
anger, fear, etc., enter as separate elements, the latter being simple, 
single phenomena. 

A much greater difficulty confronts us as soon as we try to 
determine the scope of the individual emotions, to limit the con- 
ceptions sorrow, joy, etc., so that we may have a basis of dif- 
ferentiation by means of which we can consider to what affection 
.we may attribute each emotion. This indeed seems to be the 
problem which presents itself as soon as an attempt is made to 
define the various emotions, or even to submit them to scientific 
investigation. What is Joy? What is Fright? The answer to 
such a question, at least more recently, seems to be considered 
entirely unnecessary, even where an exact treatment of psychology 
is intended (4). 

On the one hand, the matter is considered obvious, as something 
which needs no further explanation: everyone can obtain suf- 
ficient enlightenment by drawing on his own experience. " Every- 
body knows what joy and sorrow are." On the other hand, the 
emotions are believed to be so subjective as to be outside the 
scope of any definition, just like the color sensation of red or blue. 
But as long as such a purely subjective conception is maintained, 
a scientific investigation of their relation is, of course, impossible. 

1 Numbers in parentheses refer to the author's addenda. 



THE EMOTIONS 37 

No object can be dealt with scientifically unless it posseses 
objective qualities, concerning whose properties investigators 
agree. By these it may become an object of general perception 
and understanding, and may at least be discussed. Whatever 
lies outside the range of discussion, as for instance color-percep- 
tion or sensations of fright or anger, therefore also lies outside of 
the range of science. The study of colors had nothing to do with 
science as long as the individual knew nothing of it except the effect, 
that colors had on him personally. The scientific color theory de- 
veloped only after an objective quality of the color rays had been 
finally discovered by Newton. In the same way the emotions will 
be excluded from scientific investigation until their objective 
qualities are discovered and these are taken as points of departure. 

It is now sufficiently well known that such processes, open to 
objective investigation, are present. That a man is sorry or 
afraid or enraged is no longer only a matter of his subjective per- 
ception, but also is easily recognized by his associates on account 
of various sorts of involuntary bodily manifestations, which go 
hand in hand with the subjective feelings of fear, joy, etc. For 
this reason it is difficult to conceal a strong affection. It is these 
physiological manifestations of emotions which serve us as step- 
ping-stones assuredly the only ones to their scientific investi- 
gation. But until now, they have not been used as such. Of 
course, this does not mean that physiology and psychology have 
let these phenomena pass unnoticed. On the contrary, they were 
turned to with particular preference, especially in the past. Since 
the time of Aristotle masses of literature are on hand to explain 
the "Influence of the affections upon the body," or at least, the 
effect of particular phenomena which are included here (5). 

Nevertheless, a scientific result, a clearer insight into the nature 
of the affections, has not yet been achieved. In spite of all these 
notes for they are hardly more than notes collected in the 
course of centuries, no considerable advance has been made. 
There are various reasons for this: in the first place, the various 
studies date from an early period, when the necessary physiological 
assumptions were almost entirely wanting. Even now, as we 
shall see later, they are all too meager, partly because until recently 
physiognomy, in its narrower sense, has been too closely adhered 



38 CARL GEORG LANGB 

to. The changes of facial expression under varying emotions are 
precisely those manifestations which yield the least scientific re- 
sults. This is partly due to the fact that they are limited to one 
aspect alone of the physiological manifestations, and partly to 
the fact that they still elude physiological analysis. Finally, and 
essentially, the reason lies in the fact that examinations of the 
affections have never been based upon these bodily manifesta- 
tions, but have always considered these to be secondary phenom- 
ena, which might perhaps be interesting and important, but 
which, nevertheless, possessed only subordinate significance. 
Bodily expressions were considered to be more or less accidental 
Concomitants of the main phenomena the mental affection. 
\, In fact, it might be declared without exaggeration that scien- 
tifically we have absolutely no understanding of the emotions. 
We have not even a shadow of insight into the nature of the 
affections in general, or of the individual emotions. It is thought 
that something is known of their mutual relation, and their 
similarity and dissimilarity; but this view is based solely upon 
indefinite impressions, and is not scientifically supported. It is 
said for instance that joy and sorrow are opposites. This happens 
to be true, as we shall see later, but it is hardly possible to say 
that we understand fully wherein this opposition lies, or even that 
we can form a clear idea of it. To cite another case: anger is 
probably often considered to stand in closer relation to sorrow than 
to joy, 2 whereas physiological investigation will prove that the 
opposite is actually the case, etc., etc. 

If now, although no scientific definition of the affections can be 
given at the outset, I proceed, in this investigation from the tradi- 
tional conceptions and the popular affections, and put the question 
in the following way: "What bodily manifestations accompany 
each of the affections?" I do so with full consciousness of the fact 
that the problem is hereby reversed, and that the starting point 
is anything but precise and scientific. Nevertheless, this way will 
presumably prove to be the most expedient one for reaching a 
tentative conception. This method does not differ too much from 

a Cf. Kant's definition of anger as a fright which suddenly awakens the 
power of resistance to threatened evil (Anthropologie, Bk. 3, 73). Even 
though anger and fright are diametrically opposed physiologically. 



THE EMOTIONS 39 

the popular one, and it is possible by means of it to reach the 
correct conclusion, even if in a more round-about way. The in- 
vestigation will be limited to only a few of the most decided and 
best defined affections: joy, sorrow, fear, anger, and to a certain 
extent, embarrassment, suspense, and disappointment. The rea- 
son for this limitation is that I am interested in the demonstrations 
of the method of scientific analysis of emotions rather than in 
carrying it out in full detail, and that in the case of most 
of the other emotions, the bodily manifestations are so slight that 
they cannot be used in any of the present crude and insufficient 
methods for physiological analysis. 

Material and methods are unfortunately more limited in the 
physiological investigation of the affections than in any other 
physiological investigation. The most important method, the 
experimental, is here of but little, if of any use, since animal 
psychology is still too vague to draw conclusions from the study 
of animals as to the behavior of human beings. It is also only rarely 
that opportunities present themselves for even approximately 
accurate experimental work with human beings. And so we are 
reduced essentially to simple observation of ourselves and others, 
to "clinical' 7 observation, to use the medical term, where all ob- 
servation of the symptoms which appear casually are included, 
as opposed to experimental investigation, where the symptoms 
are controlled. Especially instructive are the cases where the 
affections appear with such powerful and persistent disturbances 
that we enter into the field of pathology. The degree of intensity 
which the symptoms reach here, and especially the fact that, owing 
to their seriousness, they fall under the observation and treatment 
of competent physicians, makes the study of the "emotional" 
diseases particularly important for psychology, or, rather, it will 
be made so as soon as they are dealt with more systematically. 

We must compare these conscious observations with the simpler, 
less voluntary experiences that generations have recorded in the 
past, and which have become the property of popular conscious- 
ness. These are preserved in many various verbal expressions 
and figures of speech. For these, we turn gladly to the poet. In 
articles on the bodily expression of the emotions, we usually find 
innumerable quotations from earlier and more recent poets. This 



40 CARL GEOEG LANGB 

fact may be justified in so far as a picturesque or striking expres- 
sion of the external characteristics of emotions is often found in 
poetical works. But we must not look there for new material 
for observation. Poets are no longer "do'ctores huius scientiae 
praetipui"* as at the time of Bacon, for the problems of our 
time lead us elsewhere than to the "innumerable" subtle questions 
with which former representatives of this branch of psychology 
dealt. 

New-born infants offer very interesting material for obser- 
vation along certain lines, particularly because of the relative 
simplicity of the conditions and the predominance of affections 
undisturbed and uninterfered with by reason; also because of the 
feedom from acquired conventional expression of the affections. 

This condition holds also for the study of the affections among 
primitive peoples, where the emotions are often very strongly and 
immediately expressed. On the other hand, we meet with the 
same difficulties in dealing with infants and primitive peoples, as 
we do when we study animal behavior, namely the uncertainty of 
our psychological understanding, the inevitable consequence of 
the subject's unsatisfactory reports. 

SORROW 

The most striking characteristic in the physiology and also in 
the physiognomy of sorrow is its inhibitory effect upon the volun- 
tary motor apparatus. The paralysis caused by sorrow is, how- 
ever, not nearly as pronounced as that produced by fright. As 
we shall see later, in the case of sorrow, the motor weakening 
seldom goes further than to require effort and exertion for the 
performance of movements which ordinarily are accomplished with 
ease. There is, in other words, a feeling of lassitude, and, as in 
the case of any fatigue, the movements are effected but slowly, 
and languidly, with effort, want of power and pleasure, and are 
therefore reduced to a minimum. This also accounts for the 
external expression by which a sorrowful person is so easily rec- 
ognized.,**^^ walks slowly, uncertainly, dragging his steps and 
letting his arms hang limp at his sides. His voice is weak and 

*De dignitate et augmentis scienitarum, lib, 7, cap. 3, 



THE EMOTIONS 41 

thin, as a result of the weakened activity of the expiratory and 
laryngeal muscles. He prefers to sit silent and lost in thought. 
The "latent innervation" (6) of the muscles also is conspicuously 
weakened. His neck is bent, his head droops "cast down/' 
"bent" by woe, his face is lengthened and narrowed by the laxity 
of the muscles of the cheek and jaw; his jaw may even hang down. 
His eyes appear large, as is always the case when the orbicularis 
oculi muscles are weakened. On the other hand, they may be 
abnormally covered by the upper lid, as happens when the levator 
palpebrae superioris muscles become weakened. Concomitant 
with this weakened condition of the voluntary nerve and muscle 
apparatus of the entire body, there appears also a feeling of lassi- 
tude, of heaviness, as if you were weighed down by something. 
You feel "oppressed/' "dejected/' you speak of "weighty" sorrow, 
you must bear your woe, whereas you must bridle your anger or 
joy. Many are so overpowered by sorrow that they can not even 
hold themselves erect. The sufferer leans on or supports himself 
by the surroundings, falls on his knees, or in desperation even 
throws himself upon the floor, as Romeo did in the monk's cell. \ 
This weakness of the whole apparatus of nerves and muscles of 
animal life, and subordination to the will, is, however, only one 
aspect of the physiology of sorrow. Another aspect, hardly less 
important, and perhaps even more significant in its consequences, 
belongs to another division of the motor mechanism; to the in- 
voluntary, organic muscles, especially to those which are found in 
the walls of the blood-vessels, and by whose constriction these 
vessels may be narrowed. The vascular muscles and their 
nerves, together with the vaso-motor apparatus, function in 
exactly the opposite way from that in which the voluntary mus- 
cular apparatus functions. Whereas the former became flaccid 
and weakened, on the contrary, the vascular muscles contract 
more than usually, so that the blood is forced out of the capillaries 
and decreases the supply to the tissues, and organs of the body (7). 
The immediate consequences of insufficient blood-supply are pal- 
lor, collapse and hypoemia. The pale color and sunken features 
are just those peculiarities which, together with the weakened 
face muscles, produce the lineaments characteristic of the woeful, 
and give the impression of such rapid emaciation that it cannot 



42 CARL GEOKG LANGE 

possibly be attributed to either a change in metabolism or to 
uncompensated consumption of the body tissues. Other regular 
results of insufficient blood supply to the skin are sensations of 
cold, cold shivers, difficulty in warming the body and sensitiveness 
to cold. These conditions belong also to the rather constant 
attributes of sorrow. The bloodless condition of the skin is no 
doubt paralleled in the condition of the internal organs, and though 
not so obvious, it may be recognized, nevertheless, by various 
symptoms. This supposition is supported by the fact of the de- 
creased secretions, at least of those which are controlled more 
easily. The mouth becomes dry, the tongue clings to the palate, 
and a bitter taste is produced, which seems to be a simple conse- 
quence of the drying of the tongue. 4 In the case of nursing 
women, the secretion of milk is decreased or often ceases entirely. 
As a contrast to the above mentioned physiological symptoms, 
there is one of the most regular attributes of sorrow which is 
weeping, with the plentiful tear secretion and the swollen, reddened 
condition of the face, the increased flow of the mucous secretion of 
the nose: all appearances which point to a considerable dilation 
of the skin tissues of the face and of the mucous membrane. And 
yet it may very well be assumed that such a dilation follows as a 
reaction to a previous constriction, that is, of a relaxing of the 
vascular muscles after their extreme tension. Similarly, we fre- 
quently find fatigue or laxity as results of any overstraining of the 
nerves and muscles. This, for example, may be strikingly mani- 
fested whenever a part of the skin which has been exposed to 
intense cold is suddenly brought to conditions of normal tempera- 
ture (8). This explanation of weeping seems to become more 
plausible when we consider the fact that weeping does not begin 
until the sorrow has abated somewhat. This circumstance is 
popularly understood to mean that "Tears bring relief," and we 
say "Cry it out," especially since at the same time solace is found 
in weeping. 
If the capillaries of the lungs constrict suddenly so that these 

4 The expression "bitter woe" is commonly considered to be metaphori- 
cal, but it may well be assumed that it originated from the often very 
intense bitter taste that accompanies the perception of depressing 
impressions. 



THE EMOTIONS 43 

organs are deprived of their normal blood supply, then a feeling 
of suffocation arises, just as always happens when the respiratory 
mechanism suffers. We also feel a pressure on the chest (oppres- 
sion) and these "torturing, depressing" sensations add to the 
sufferings of the sorrowful who try involuntarily to relieve them- 
selves by deep, slow breathing sighs a method which anyone 
who experiences difficulty in breathing from any cause whatever, 
instinctively pursues. 

The deficient blood-supply to the brain is manifested by mental 
lassitude, dullness, a feeling of mental fatigue and effort, by an 
indisposition for mental work and frequently by sleeplessness. 5 
In the same way, as we shall see later, it is probably the absence 
of blood in the motor organs of the brain which is the fundamental 
cause of the weakened force of the voluntary movements. 

If the anxiety be lasting so that the above mentioned dis- 
turbances of the blood-supply continue for a year and a day, 
then external changes in the organs must occur, as always hap- 
pens if the blood supply and consequently the nourishment be 
insufficient for any length of time. These changes are well 
known in pathology, under the name of " atrophies," but as 
yet too little attention has been paid to the possible effects of pro- 
longed emotional disturbances, and modern pathology is all too 
ready to laugh at old beliefs in the fundamental significance of 
certain organic affections. Nevertheless, there can be little doubt, 
however difficult or impossible it may be to furnish positive proof, 
that continuous sorrow may have an atrophying effect upon the 
internal organs, especially since the effects upon the visible parts 
of the body are so conspicuous. It is well known that a sor- 
rowful person ages prematurely, but this early impression of 
senility depends solely upon atrophied changes in the skin and 
other external parts of the body. The body becomes emaci- 
ated by the disappearance of all the adipose and muscular 
tissues. The hair turns gray because it is not sufficiently 

5 1 keep for another occasion the proof that sleeplessness is caused by the 
spasmodic contraction of the brain cells. The much controverted physio- 
logical explanation of sleep may be supposed to be that sleep is caused by 
a periodic laxity of the brain cells, by a loss of tone resulting from fatigue 
of the nerves of the brain. 



44: GAEL GEORG LANGE 

nourished and because the pigment vanishes and is prematurely 
lost (9) . Similarly the wrinkling of the skin and the furrowing of 
the brow by sorrow, both simple phenomena of atrophy, 
occur prematurely and contribute to the early ageing of the suf- 
ferer. In short, all atrophic changes in the visible parts of the 
body that take place with the normal ageing are hastened by 
sorrow. Is there then anything improbable in the assumption 
that changes analogous to the senile changes take place in the 
case of the internal organs? 6 

The bodily phenomena which accompany sorrow may also be 
explained on the basis of paralysis of the voluntary muscles, and 
a kind of convulsive condition of the vascular muscles. 

JOY 

In popular consciousness, joy constitutes the opposite of sorrow, 
and an examination of its physiological manifestations agrees with 
this direct conception. The "Effect of Joy upon the Body" 
to use this popular mode of expressing the relation is in fact the 
opposite of that of sorrow. In the case of joy, a heightening of the 
functioning of the voluntary motor apparatus takes place, together 
with a dilation of the arterioles and capillaries. These are the two 
fundamental physiological symptoms by which the joyous one 
sustains his entire peculiar physiology. The heightened function 
of the voluntary muscles and nerves causes the feeling of lightness 
of joy, such as everyone experiences whose muscles are strong and 
unfatigued. 7 He feels an increased motor impulse, moves swiftly 
and alertly, and gesticulates violently. Children jump, dance, 
clap their hands for joy. The facial muscles contract as a result 
of heightened latent innervation, and become round compared 
with the long, lax, hanging features of the melancholic person. 
Smiling and laughing are the results of the heightened impulse of 
facial and breathing muscles, as are also the high-pitched voice, 

6 A -well-known English pathologist has given proof in a series of cases 
that emotional complaints may lead to atrophy of the kidneys. (Dr. 
Clifford Allbut, British Medical Journal, 10 February, 1877.) 

7 To explain this feeling of lightness a positive decrease in b9dy weight 
was formerly assumed. Cf. de Mar6es, De animi perturbatione in corpora 
potentia. 1775 (Ludwig, Scriptores neurolog. minores, Tome IV). 



THE EMOTIONS 45 

singing, rejoicing and the expression of involuntary impulses of 
the laryngeal and respiratory muscles. The eyes of a joyous per- 
son beam, sparkle, in short, assume a peculiar playful expression, 
which is due to the combined contraction of the lid-muscles 
(vrbicularis oculi pcdpebrarum and levator palpebrae), to be seen 
in connection with the pupilary change. 8 The general dilation of 
the capillaries in joy results very strikingly in an increased flow 
of blood to the skin. A child's or a young girl's skin, which is 
white and transparent, reddens and glows with pleasure. The 
joyous person feels warm, his skin becomes fuller, he swells with 
pleasure. Increased glandular secretion also is observed: it is a 
common expression of satisfaction to say "the mouth waters" 
and "tears come easy." 

Whereas the woe-begone person with his slow movements, his 
bent figure, his sunken features, assumes the appearance of an old 
man, contrariwise the joyous man appears youthful because of 
his swift and powerful movements, his singing and loud speaking 
"Joy rejuvenates." But it is not only the external stamp of 
health which accompanies joy. Whereas in the case of sorrow 
the body-organs become aged because of the lack of nourishment 
due to the constricted state of the blood-vessels, normal circula- 
tion produces just the opposite effect in a contented person. A 
rich blood supply to the organs and tissues of the body is naturally 
conducive to a strong nourishing activity, and hence all parts of 
the body thrive and are long preserved. The contented, active 
person is well-nourished and keeps young. That fat men are 
jovial or rather, that jovial men are fat is commonly accepted. 
It is based upon sound fact, that despots like to be surrounded by 
fat men, 9 since their thriving condition bears witness of their 
contentedness, and therefore they are not easily dangerous. The 
part which the brain plays in the increased flow of the blood, as 
probably all parts of the body share it in a joyful mood, leads us 
to make the supposition that mental functions take place rapidly; 

8 It seems to me that the pupil contracts in joy, which would pre-suppose 
heightened innervation of the superior division of the oculomotorius. 
Wilks, on the other hand, believes that the pupil dilates, but he records no 
observations. (Bain, April, 1883, p. 4.) 

'Shakespeare, Julius Caesar, Act I., Sc. 2. 



46 CABL GEORG LANGE 

there is a flow of ideas and fancies. A joyous person talks rap- 
idly and fluently; his work proceeds swiftly, not only because his 
muscles are strong, but also because he reaches decisions quickly 
and puts them into prompt execution. 

*Jx* 

FRIGHT 

Fright is, as has been indicated above, closely related to sorrow. 
We find the same paralyzing effect on the voluntary motor appara- 
tus, the same convulsive conditions of the constrictor muscles, 
only we find both appearing more suddenly and in a more exag- 
gerated degree. To this, however, we must add another condition 
which we did not observe in the case of sorrow, namely, a similar 
convulsive contraction of other organic muscles. In sorrow this 
is limited to the vascular muscles. The essential physiological 
difference between sorrow and fright lies in the fact that in the 
latter, the convulsive spasmodic condition of the voluntary muscles 
is shared by all muscles as far as can be judged, whereas in the 
former it is limited to individual groups of muscles. How con- 
spicuous it is that the paralyzation due to fright is stronger than 
that due to sorrow is evident from the common verbal expression 
for the two phenomena. A man is " burdened with," "weighed 
down by," "bent with" sorrow, but he is "paralyzed" with fear, 
is motionless, petrified, transfixed by fright. The paralysis of the 
muscles of speech makes it difficult or impossible to utter a word; 
the voice becomes hoarse and broken; he is "struck dumb" with 
terror. The tongue becomes immovable, the face relaxes, the eyes 
are very large, motionless, staring, fixed, because of the paralysis 
of the muscles of the lid. A person overcome by a sudden fear 
may fall down paralyzed, or the innervation of the muscles may 
at least be so uncertain as to make him quake, tremble, stammer 
with fear. 

It is characteristic in the case of fright as contrasted with sorrow 
that the paralysis of the voluntary muscles is often preceded by a 
momentary convulsive twitch in which a sudden start is mani- 
fested, and there is a cry in the first instant of fear. That de- 
pends upon the suddenness of the effect, which leads to the paraly- 
sis, and it has several pathological analogues. If a motor nerve 
is suddenly crushed, the corresponding muscles are momentarily 



THE EMOTIONS 47 

contracted before paralysis sets in; but if the nerve be slowly and 
gradually pressed, then the paralysis takes place equally and 
gradually with no preliminary contractions. The convulsive con- 
traction of the constrictor muscles because of fright and the re- 
sulting lack of blood in the skin occasions here and there, only 
more suddenly and to a higher degree, pallor, 10 coldness, a "cold 
shiver," (the blood "freezes"), and numbness. It is probably 
this sudden and complete lack of blood in the skin which causes the 
very rapid turning gray of the hair, as is sometimes observed to be 
the result of extreme terror. Reliable examples of the sudden 
"falling out" of the hair have been found due to fright (10). u 
In spite of the lack of blood in the skin, it may be covered with 
sweat, but with a "cold sweat." There is no explanation for this; 
however, I may mention that according to the more recent investi- 
gations of sweat secretion, there is no discrepancy between the 
increased secretion and the decreased blood supply to the skin. 
It is not exactly known in what relation other secretions stand to 
fright, but on the whole they decrease or even cease entirely. So, 
for example, in the case of the salivary secretions: the mouth 
becomes dry, the tongue clings to the roof of the mouth. It is a 
well-known fact that the secretion of milk in the case of nursing 
women decreases, and that existing menstruation may cease as 
the result of fright. Vascular convulsions and consequent defi- 
ciency in the blood supply always lead to shivers, trembling, 
chattering teeth, whatever their cause may be. They are 
well-known in fever or as the sudden effects of cold on the skin, 
and these too belong to the characteristic manifestations of fear. 
"Shiver," "shudder," "tremble" are, in fact synonymous expres- 
sions for a "sensation of fear" and for the "power to inspire fear." 
Comparisons between the sensations of fear, cold or fever are met 
with frequently in verbal expressions or in popular consciousness. 12 
At first, fear acts upon the heart in such a way as to cause an 

10 "Go prick thy face and over-red thy fear, thou lily-liver'd boy." 
Macbeth, Act V., Sc. 3. 

11 Older pathologists have assumed that the blood actually coagulated 
under the influence of fear. Sanguis in toto coagulatur. (Willis, De 
anima brutorum, Cap. 9.) 

12 Cf. The Danish "Buxefeber;" fever-terror, the cold hand of fear, etc. 



48 CAEL GEOBG LANGE 

increased activity; but overwhelming fright seems to paralyze the 
heart and thus even cause death (11). 

Whereas fright, if we were to confine ourselves to the above 
mentioned attributes, might be looked upon as a more intense or 
acute form of sorrow, there is, as has been pointed out, a large 
class of phenomena, by means of which we may recognize that 
fear has its own peculiar physiognomy, which is very different 
from that of sorrow. They are those symptoms which are caused 
by the apparent participation in the general convulsive condition 
of all the voluntary organic muscles, that are under no control of 
the will, causing movements and contractions of our inner organs, 
whereas in sorrow, the participation is limited to the vascular 
muscles. In the discussion on the convulsion of the vascular 
muscles, I have already mentioned the effect of fright upon the 
heart action. Perhaps these disturbances which aid considerably 
in distinguishing fright from sorrow should be assigned to that 
department. Rembrandt, as is well known, did not hesitate to 
depict realistically the effect of the convulsive contraction of the 
bladder of the unfortunate Ganymede, who found himself suddenly 
hovering between heaven and earth, his life depending upon the 
grasp of the eagle and the durability of his shirt. 

That young recruits, on the eve of battle, are often confronted 
with the necessity of stepping out of rank, and are not always the 
pleasantest neighbors as long as they remain in rank, is due to the 
uncontrollable effect of fear upon the muscles of the intestines (12). 
It is apparent to any one who has suffered from fear, that every 
strong and convulsive peristaltic motion may very well be accom- 
panied by colic pains: "cramps." The phenomena considered 
here belong to the more drastic concomitants of fear, which indeed 
usually occur only in the case of youthful individuals and members 
of the lower classes, in short of those who offer favorable condi- 
tions for violent emotional phenomena (see below). There is 
another group of phenomena which depend upon the same physio- 
logical influence on the system of involuntary muscles, and it is 
by means of these that fright assumes its peculiar pathetic physiog- 
nomy when we speak of the hair "standing on end," with terror. 
This expression, even though somewhat exaggerated, applies to 
the effect of the spasmodic contraction of the fine muscle-fibers 



THE EMOTIONS 49 

attached to the hair bulbs in the skin; "goose-flesh" is due to the 
same cause. The "protruding" eyes which "bulge" from their 
sockets and the enlarged pupils point to an irritation of the sympa- 
thetic nervous system, just as the vascular spasm does. 

In the case of many individuals sudden fright arouses a peculiar 
subjective sensation, a sticking or pricking, which often spreads 
from the abdomen upwards, and is particularly noticeable on the 
tongue, and frequently extends over the entire body, even to the 
tips of the fingers and toes. To this sensation a feeling of oppres- 
sion is often added, a torturing, constricting sensation, especially 
in the throat "choking." The first mentioned of these sensa- 
tions is undoubtably an eccentric one (projected) (13), and arises 
through stimulation of the cerebral organs of sensation, condi- 
tioned by the sudden contraction of the blood vessels. They 
have the character of subjective sensations arising in the brain, 
and nothing is more common than such sensations in cases of 
functional or organic diseases of the brain. The origin of the 
sensations of suffocation which so often accompany fright is less 
obvious. According to their form there is nothing to stand in the 
way of considering them eccentric perceptions which come from 
the spinal cord; a stimulation of the gray matter of the cord, 
brought about by the spasmodic contraction of its fine arteries, 
can undoubtably have such sensations as a consequence, but they 
are not as characteristic as the corresponding brain symptoms and 
therefore not as conclusive. Of all emotional disturbances, fright 
is probably the one which most frequently causes symptoms and 
conditions of disease that are often lasting and even incurable. 
It is not my purpose here to enter into the entire pathological 
meaning of the affections. I wish only to remark briefly that, 
even with the most critical estimation of the facts, it is quite 
indubitable that fright may cause paralysis, epilepsy, mental 
disturbance, and numerous other nervous diseases, and similarly, 
as I have already stated, sudden fright may lead even to death. 

ANGEK BAGE 

As a rule, it is undoubtedly easy for an observer to distinguish 
an embittered, raging person, from a cheerful, joyous one, by 
general bodily conditions, appearance, and attitude. But if the 



50 CABL GEOEG LANGE 

physiological conditions characteristic of these two affections are 
analyzed rather more carefully, such striking agreement of funda- 
mental relations will be found that it is not at all easy to specify 
the difference. 

In the first place, both anger and joy manifest a dilation of the 
fine blood vessels, an increased circulation to the skin, which 
causes reddening, heat, swelling, "turgor." An angry person 
"seethes," is "consumed" with anger; the blood rushes to his head 
he "boils/ 7 he must " cool" his wrath, work off his rage, he swells 
up with rage, as is evident from these and similar figures of speech 
by which common popular opinions on the influence of anger upon 
the circulation is expressed. Yet the symptoms are on the whole 
more exaggerated in anger than in joy, so strong indeed that rage 
causes diseases and brings with it a feeling of dissatisfaction, in- 
stead of the content due to temperature increase which accom- 
panies joy. The mucous membranes share in the increased blood 
supply, the eyes are bloodshot, and we find that where there is a 
predisposition hemorrhages may even occur; nose bleedings and 
lung hemorrhages have come under my personal observation. 

However, the irregularities of circulation differ not alone in degree 
and intensity in the two cases, but in anger we find an entirely new 
element added of which we find no trace in joy, namely a swelling 
and enlargement of the great blood vessels, especially of the veins. 
This is most conspicuous on the forehead "the veins of the 
temples swell" 13 (14), but is noticeable in other parts too in the 
neck and hands for instance. In what physiological relation these 
phenomena stand is not perfectly clear to me: there can, of course, 
be no question of an actual dilation of the blood vessels as in 
congestion. Such a dilation is not detectable even in the larger 
blood vessels; nor can it be assumed that a paralysis of the insig- 
nificant muscular apparatus of these veins lies at the root of these 
swellings. No other explanation remains for these dilations except 
in the congestion of the blood resulting from some obstacle in the 
passage of the blood to the heart or from a defect in the secondary 
circuit from the right ventricle through the lungs back to the 
left ventricle. It is here perhaps only a question of a minor 
phenomenon depending upon the irregular breathing, the strong 

13 Or a tument ira, nigrescunt sanguine venae . Ovid, Ars am. Ill cf . 



THE EMOTIONS 51 

expiration in consequence of the impulse of an enraged person to 
call or cry out and upon all the powerful and somewhat tumul- 
tuous innervation; all of which factors favor the congestion of the 
blood (15). An increased innervation of the voluntary muscles 
and a consequent impulse to quick and forceful movements is 
indeed the second point in the physiology of rage. Here again 
we find a new agreement with joy, the physiognomy of which 
obtains one of its most conspicuous characteristics from the feeling 
of lightness, of desire for an inclination to lively movements that 
accompany the feeling. But this impulse is again exaggerated in 
anger. Instead of becoming lively, as a joyful person does, he 
becomes indignant "goes up in the air," clenches his fists, waves 
his arms, marches with long strides (paxpaftipas), clenches his 
teeth, grits them, threatens, cries out, stamps his feet, thunders, 
"carries on" and yells in his rage. Whereas we can be satisfied to 
control our joy, we must "check" our anger like a wild animal. 
Even when anger, at its height ("foaming with rage"), assumes a 
comical aspect, when it causes its victim to jump and dance 
around in-such a way as to remind us of a joyful individual, yet 
these movements are much more powerful, less controlled, clumsy, 
and leave us no doubt as to the actual state of affairs. The im- 
pulse of an embittered person to use his strength, the physiological, 
immediate expression of motor innervation; assumes a character 
of power and vandalism by his indiscriminate attacks upon every- 
thing that crosses his path. Unintentionally, and without dis- 
crimination, he strikes at friend and foe alike, simply to use his 
muscles. In some cases where there is a certain amount of self- 
control, he merely strikes the table with his fist, bangs the door, 
tears something to pieces or otherwise destroys it. He would like 
to demolish the earth, and he may evince a power in his rage that 
exceeds anything he is able to do under normal conditions. The 
motions of a person in a rage are, however, not distinguishable as 
much by their force as by their lack of control, their inaccuracy 
and incoordination: again the opposite state of affairs from joy. 
A joyful individual has easy flowing speech and a tendency to 
measured rhythmical movements, as in dancing. The enraged 
man stammers and stutters and howls when at last he is not suc- 
cessful in uttering a word; his muscular innervation is so uncertain 



52 GAEL GEORG LANGE 

that he " trembles with rage." He misses his aim strikes blindly 
and consequently is little to be feared by a cold blooded opponent. 

In rage as in joy but contrary to fear and sorrow, the face 
shows decided muscular contractions. Wrinkles appear upon the 
brow in rage, whereas, as has been mentioned above, sorrow pro- 
duces folds, an effect produced by the vanishing of the skin tissue. 
The unequal activity of the individual facial muscles in anger and 
sorrow produce the difference in physiognomic expression of these 
two emotions. I do not want to enter into their analysis here, 
as has been done many times; for we lack all basis for conjecturing 
why it is that the facial nerves are unequally innervated in different 
emotions (16). 

The physiological difference between pleasure and anger is, 
therefore, in the main, limited to a difference in the degree of 
dilation of the blood-vessels and the heightened innervation of the 
voluntary muscles, and, therefore, in the coordination (17) of the 
voluntary muscles. The measure of their strength ceases under 
the rule of anger, so that the movements become uncontrolled 
and inaccurate. Thus joy and anger may be considered to be 
the opposites of sorrow and fear and to stand in mutual relation- 
ship in the same way as the latter do. Anger also seems to have 
an effect upon the secretions, at least upon some, which is of the 
opposite nature to that produced by sorrow or fear. Where 
sorrow and fear cause the salivary secretion to decrease, and the 
tongue and larvnx to become dry, we find expressions like "to 
foam with rage" or to " snort" that point to a very different situa- 
tion in anger. In the same way, we find it a well established 
tradition that anger causes an increased gall secretion, "the gall 
runs over" in anger, he "lets his gall flow freely," for fear of letting 
his worry cause jaundice. Even if the observation that probably 
gave rise to these expressions that a persistent, embittered dis- 
position may cause jaundice were true, it would be, of course, 
no positive proof of the increased gall secretion in any given indi- 
vidual. It is, in fact, difficult to designate the actual peculiar 
behavior of an enraged person in a physiologically incontrovertible 
way. It is not sufficient to say that they are mighty and uncon- 
trolled activities. Rage is accompanied by an impulse to general 
violent movements, not only to satisfy the desire for simple mus- 



THE EMOTIONS 53 

cular exertion, but also to gratify the craving for noisy, wanton 
activity which may even cause the subject pain or at least a very 
strong sense impression. A silent struggling with his hands and 
feet would not satisfy his impulse; he must hear his movements 
as well as feel them. He strikes the table, stamps his feet, slams 
the door, smashes a mirror, throws down everything that he can 
lay his hands on, showing a preference for hard breakable objects 
that make a lot of noise. 14 He might just as well exert his respira- 
tory muscles by rapid and deep breathing, without exactly yelling 
and howling, but he requires "noise." In his desire for strong 
sense impressions, he does not spare himself bodily injury; he 
beats his head against the wall, tears his hair, pulls his beard, 
bites his lips. How can this craving for sound and sense impres- 
sions be explained physiologically? I can think of only one ex- 
planation, which has, in fact, a great deal of probability. A desire 
for abnormally strong sense-impressions can generally have no 
other cause but an abnormally weak perception of sense-impres- 
sions; a weakening of the powers of feeling, hearing, etc. It is 
necessary to our well-being that our central sensory nerve-cells 
be active to a certain degree determined by the amount of stimu- 
lation carried to them by the sensory nerves. If, for any reason 
whatever, as for example by a decrease in the functional power 
of these cells, a weakening or anaesthesia is produced, then the 
impulse to set these cells in their normal activity again, requires 
an increased external sense-impression to neutralize the decreased 
sensitivity. It can hardly be rigorously proved that such an 
anaesthesia actually exists in anger, and it is hardly legitimate to 
fall back upon such expressions as "blind with rage," "deafened 
by passion" to bear witness to the agreement of popular observa- 
tion. But for the sense of feeling, the matter is quite clear. In a 
bitter fight, both parties may inflict upon each other serious 
injuries, which are not felt until the heat of the excitement has 
subsided. We can even beat two fighters or two dogs unmSrci- 
fully, and they will take no notice. 

Anger, which can present in bodily manifestations such a de- 
ceptive picture of maniacal conditions (ira furor brews), becomes 

14 When Bonaparte, in Udine, wished to scare the Austrian agent by 
pretended rage, he did the right thing in smashing the costly china. 



54 CARL GEORG LANGE 

a cause for permanent mental disturbance as rarely as joy does, 
and even more rarely leads to sudden death. Galen even observed 
that only fright and joy kill, but not anger (irtpi din&v av^ro- 
/zarcov, I. 5), and Willis (De anima brutor) says that women 
faint for joy and men die of it but not of anger. With the 
restriction that death, due to joy, occurs very rarely, at least 
nowadays, when the affections on the whole are less overwhelming, 
nevertheless the rule holds generally, with the possible exception 
of one woman, who died at the height of her rage (cf. Schauen- 
stein, in Maschka's Handbuch der gerichtlichen Median } Vol. I, 
page 813) (18). 

As I have mentioned before, it is not my purpose here to enter 
into a physiological analysis of all the bodily phenomena occurring 
with the different affections. 

At present, I am satisfied with the attempt to deal with these 
four great affections and then only with their most decided forms 
their conventional state so to speak. For, indeed, it is obvious 
that psychic conditions exist which come under the heads of 
pleasure, anger, etc., but still do not fit the above representations 
in their physiological manifestations. This is no sign of erroneous 
or incomplete analysis, but merely the inevitable consequence of 
the circumstance that I have already discussed, namely, that the 
entire method of procedure used here, in which the starting 
point was taken from popular conceptions, is in and for itself 
wrong and illogical, even though it may serve as a means to attain 
a tentative understanding. 

A complete analysis of the less strong, that is, of physically less 
decided affections, would hardly be successful, since our methods 
of observation are still so crude, and therefore I shall not attempt 
it here, although there are some among them whose physiological 
peculiarities are obvious and instructive, and I shall give them 
some brief discussion. 

^Embarrassment (shyness) is perhaps not characterized by a 
very decided weakening of the voluntary innervation although 
a certain feeling of weakness always accompanies shyness, which 
gives rise to the sensation of "sinking through the floor" yet by 
a very decided uncertainty of innervation, so that the amount is 
not properly limited and other muscles are unintentionally set 



THE EMOTIONS 55 

in action, with excessive contraction of some and insijfl5l.cie.nt 
contraction of others, resulting briefly in "uncoordinated" 
movements. 15 

An embarrassed person has only imperfect control of his mus- 
cles. He can hardly articulate his words, stutters and stammers 
in speaking, gesticulates, drops whatever he is holding, rolls his 
eyes, walks unsteadily and even stumbles over his own feet. 

A child that is very much embarrassed may present such a 
perfect illusion of the first symptoms of St. Vitus' dance (a 
disease which, in its early stages, is manifested by poor coordina- 
tion of voluntary movements) as totally to deceive one. We also 
find a similar uncertainty of innervation of the vascular muscles. 
The capillaries are alternately contracted and dilated, apparently 
without cause, and this accounts for the rapid change of color in 
embarrassment, the one moment pale, and the next blushing. All 
these physical conditions are accompanied by a decided disturb- 
ance in the power to think, especially to concentrate on one line 
of thought, and the embarrassed person becomes confused, 
"muddled." 

Suspense and expectation resemble fear in so far as they are ac- 
companied by an apathetic condition, a tendency to contract the 
organic, involuntary muscles, and the various consequences of 
such contractions. The desire for evacuation of the different 
secretions and excretions; a feverish condition, which really shows 
some of the most striking symptoms of fever; palpitation of heart, 
quickened pulse, cold shivers, sleeplessness; all may be present. 
But the paralysis of the voluntary muscles, as in fear, is absent. 
On the other hand, suspense is accompanied by an animated and 
lively innervation of the voluntary muscular system, which ex- 
presses itself in a desire for motion. A person held in suspense 
becomes restless, can not stand still, but is as if on "pins" or "hot 
coals," "on edge." He can not sit quiet for one instant, but con- 
stantly jumps up, incessantly tramps up and down, tosses sleep- 

15 But of a somewhat different nature from the coordination disturbance 
in rage. The difference is undoubtedly due to the fact that the latter 
originate from functional disturbances in the brain, whereas the incoor- 
dination of embarrassment is attributable to disturbances increased 
irradiation -of the functions of the spinal cord. 



56 CABL GEOEG LANG-E 

lessly in bed at night. We say therefore that it is "disturbing' 7 
to take part in events the results of which are unknown to us. 

Disappointment is closely related to sorrow, since it is accom- 
panied by a paralysis of the voluntary innervation, which is rec- 
ognizable by a feeling of weariness, laxity ("long face") and 
indisposition for any effort. But all spasmodic contractions of the 
vessels, which are among the most conspicuous phenomena in 
sorrow, are absent. 

The above examples will, in spite of their brevity, show suf- 
ficiently what such an analysis may lead to and what may be ex- 
pected of it, with the assumptions that we canmaketoday. They 
may be considered numerous and various enough to give an idea 
of what fundamental physiological phenomena are brought into 
play by our affections. It is evident that they include all func- 
tions of the nervous system, and appear partly as disturbances of 
innervation, i.e., as disturbances of impulses which the muscles 
(and also the glands) receive from the nerves; partly also, although 
less conspicuously, as disturbances of sensibility, as weakening 
or heightening of sensibility and subjective sensation; and 
finally, as disturbances of intelligence, by which mental life is 
either lowered or elevated. 

The disturbances of innervation, which not only forms the most 
conspicuous phenomenon of the affections, but which, perhaps, 
as we shall try to prove later, is their real immediate physical 
expression, spread over the different parts of the entire system 
of muscles and affect now the voluntary, now the organic, and 
especially the vascular muscles, and the muscular apparatus of the 
different vital organs. The disturbances may assume various 
forms. The innervation may increase and the muscles contract 
more strongly and easily than under ordinary conditions; or the 
innervation may be decreased and be followed by weariness, 
weakness and relaxing of the blood vessels, and other muscular 
organs; finally, the innervation without actual increase or 
decrease, may reach the muscles in variable strength and produce 
incoordination (19) and a lack of precision in the concerted action 
of the muscles. The kinds of innervational disturbances of the 
various parts of the muscular system are not entirely analogous in 
different affections. One part, the voluntary muscles for instance, 



THE EMOTIONS 57 

may be paralyzed, whereas another, the vascular muscles, may be 
in a convulsive condition, etc. 16 

We have, therefore, a series of different combinations which are 
represented by the individual affections. As we have to deal with 
three different systems of muscles, of which each, perhaps, may 
be affected in three different ways, and suffer at times only one 
or two functional disturbances, we seem to have 127 different 
combinations to give somatic forms of affections, and this only 
with regard to disturbances of innervation. Of course, we can 
not assume a priori that all these hypothetical combinations 
actually exist, while on the other hand the variabilities of the 
relative strength of the phenomena require an endless number of 
steps. We could represent the seven above mentioned forms of 
affections by the following scheme. 

Weakness of voluntary innervation. 

Weakness of voluntary innervation + vascular contraction - dis- 
appointment. 

Weakness of voluntary innervation + vascular contraction + con- 
vulsion of organic muscles = fright. 

Weakness of voluntary innervation + incoordination = embarrass- 
ment. 

Increase of voluntary innervation -j- spasm of voluntary muscles =* 
suspense. 

Increase of voluntary innervation -f vascular dilation = joy. 

Increase of voluntary innervation -1- vascular dilation and incoordina- 
tion = anger. 

It is clear that it is not correct to state offhand as a general 
rule of affections, that they are accompanied by increased muscular 
activity, 17 and the division of the affections into active and passive, 
sthenic or asthenic, or however this contrast is to be expressed, is 
unjustified, both from the physiological and the psychological 

18 Perhaps, however, the functional disturbance of the vascular and other 
organic muscles is always the same. 

17 The diffuse discharge, which accompanies feelings of every sort, pro- 
duces an effect on the body, namely, stimulating the musculature. These 
feelings arouse bodily activity, which is the more lively, the more intense 
the feelings are. The most striking peculiarity of the discharge, which 
accompanies feelings of every sort, is the circumstance that it arouses 
muscular contraction, which is proportional to the degree of feeling. (H. 
Spencer, Principles of Psychology, II, 496, 497.) 



58 CARL GEORG LANGE 

point of view, as we shall endeavor to show. Most emotions 
possess an active as well as a passive, a sthenic and an astheriic 
element, and some possess even a third, which we cannot call 
either active or passive. 

And so, a question arises concerning the various physical phe- 
nomena of the affections, whose answer is of considerable signifi- 
cance for the physiology of the affections, namely, whether these 
phenomena are physiologically of equal value, are parallel; or 
whether certain appearances are to be considered as caused by 
others, and secondary to these; whether, for example, paralysis 
and vascular convulsions of a mournful person are due immediately 
to one and the same cause, or whether the original influence acted 
only on one of these manifestations and that this one then caused 
the others. In this last case, the further question arises: Which is 
primary, and which is secondary? 

Now, all the phenomena discussed so far can be reduced to two 
main groups: changes in the vascular innervation and changes in 
the functions of the other nerves and since, according to all our 
physiological experiences, we can not assume that disturbances of 
functions of the second group may become vasomotor changes, 
whereas there is no a priori objection to the opposite state of 
affairs, the problem finally reduces to the following question: 
Is it possible that vasomotor disturbances, varied dilation of .the 
blood vessels, and consequent excess of blood, in the separate 
organs, are the real, primary effects of the affections, whereas the 
other phenomena, motor abnormalities, sensation paralysis, sub- 
jective sensations, disturbances of secretion and intelligence are 
only secondary disturbances, which have their cause in anomalies 
of vascular innervation? Is it not, for example, possible that the 
muscular weakness in the case of an anxious person may be due 
to the fact that his nervous system may receive too little blood 
just as his skin and other organs do, due to the contraction of the 
fine arteries; and that the power and wildness of rage may be due 
to the excessive blood supply to the brain, as this organ surely 
must be involved, just as much as the skin and mucous membrane? 

Our insight into the physiology of the nervous system is still 
incomplete, especially our understanding of the very important 
Questions of the significance of the blood contained in the 



THE EMOTIONS 59 

nervous organs in relation to their functions. In the face of 
this incomplete comprehension of the subject, it is obvious that 
the question as stated here cannot be answered with any decisive- 
ness. Nevertheless, this much is known positively, that the indi- 
vidual parts of the nervous system; brain, spinal cord, etc.; are 
greatly influenced in their functional power by the condition of 
their blood supply. An excessive blood supply, as well as a defi- 
cient one, is a symptom of disease. We can easily convince our- 
selves of the significance of excessive blood supply to the head by 
a very simple experiment on ourselves; if we press the large pulse- 
arteries in the neck, we rob the brain of its normal blood supply, 
and the immediate results of this disturbance are dizziness, sensa- 
tions of weakness, and faintness, decreased consciousness, which 
soon forces us to terminate the experiment, whereupon the condi- 
tions immediately become normal again. But if we interrupt the 
circulation by means of a bandage, as is sometimes done in surgery, 
there results a paralysis of that side of the body which is controlled 
by the motor impulses of that side of the brain in question. This 
paralysis endures until the circulation reaches a state of equili- 
brium again in a round about way. Another experiment which 
can be performed easily on certain animals, consists in artificially 
cutting off the blood supply to the lower part of the spinal cord by 
compressing the aorta. (Stenson's experiment.) As soon as the 
pressure has been administered for some moments, a paralysis of 
the abdomen and hind legs sets in. Movement and sensation are 
made possible again as soon as the pressure is removed. That a 
human being behaves in the same way is evident in certain dis- 
eased conditions, in which the circulation through the aorta sup- 
plying most of the blood to the spinal cord is for some reason in- 
terrupted. These and similar experiments and attempts are, to 
be sure, crude- and coarse, in comparison to the processes of vaso- 
motor disturbances, and changes in the innervation of the fine 
blood-vessels, and their consequent degree of dilation. Such 
disturbances may show innumerable degrees and may be limited 
to certain parts of each organ in question, so that the effects occur 
in steps of intensity, and assume many forms and variations that 
can not be imitated experimentally. Certainly, the above facts 



60 CARL GEOBG LANGE 

offer sufficient proof of the immediate and far reaching effect of the 
varying blood-content upon the functional power of those organs 
which are concerned in our movements, the sensations and psychi- 
cal activities. The fact that vascular spasms in the central 
nervous organs lie at the root of the many and often intensive 
disturbances of the functions of these organs, even when these 
are merely temporary, as for example, in epilepsy and maniacal 
paroxysms, is also evidence. This fact is hardly disputed by the 
physiologists and pathologists of today; this circumstance is cer- 
tainly strongly in favor of the mutual connection between the 
emotions as here described. 

If, then, no essential objection can be made to the theory 
which holds that the various emotional disturbances are due to 
disturbances in the vascular innervation that accompanies the 
affections, and which, therefore, makes these vasomotor disturb- 
ances the only primary symptoms; (20) nevertheless, there still 
remains for us to investigate the problem whether those disturb- 
ances which are so obvious if they involve the blood vessels in 
the skin, by blushing or paling, by swelling or contracting, 
by heat or cold, are as obvious if they involve the inner 
organs, especially the central nervous system from which 
most of the other emotional phenomena spring (21). That this 
affection of the blood vessels occurs also in the nervous system is 
a necessary assumption for the theory that they are fundamental 
to the other disturbances of innervation. A priori, the assump- 
tion that the change in degree of contraction of the blood vessels 
during affection is not limited to the skin, but is spread all over 
the entire organism, is undoubtedly the most probable. There 
are, as we have already mentioned above, plenty of data, and I 
have proceeded from the assumption of some such general dis- 
tribution of hyperaemia or anaemia in my explanation of the dif- 
ferent phenomena of the affections. Nevertheless, it would be 
valuable if we could perform immediate observations and experi- 
ments by which the truth or fallacy of my point of view might 
be shown. But the number and value of such experiences leave 
much to be desired for our physiological insight. It is not easy 
to get rid of this inadequacy of empirical data, since experiments 



THE EMOTIONS 61 

performed on animals are of little or no use in this field; 18 and in 
regard to human beings, we have so far been limited to drawing 
our conclusions from very rare cases, which require direct observa- 
tion of the brain and its blood vessels, which, under normal condi- 
tions, possessed at least enough life to permit of changing 
dispositions. 

Attempts have been made to measure the changes in the blood 
supply of the brain by temperature measurements outside of the 
head. This method can easily be applied to all individuals, in 
order to produce a wide range for the experiments. It has then 
been attempted to prove that an increase in temperature occurs 
following every mental effort, due to an increased blood flow to 
the b^ain. But, even if this method is indisputable, as it seems in 
fact to be, it can hardly have any application to the study of the 
affections, because the relations here change so rapidly that the 
sudden changes in circulation hardly endure long enough to vary 
the temperature outside of the head, and especially not in the case 
of individuals who know that they are under observation. And 
so our present immediate experiences of the blood-content of the 
brain during dispositional changes depend upon such cases, 
where rather large parts of the skull have been removed so that 
the brain, or its skins, are laid bare, but where the patient is 
nevertheless in a pretty normal mental condition. But the possi- 
bility of observing such a case is, however, not sufficient; in order 
to obtain results, one must have the good fortune to be present 
as observer at just that moment when the patient is disturbed 
naturally by a rather strong emotion, for of course it cannot be 
controlled artificially; and not every one knows how to appreciate 
the relations in question, especially the changes in pulsatory 
brain-movements. 

Obviously, our present data are insignificant, and sufficient only 

18 There are a few series of experiments (v. Bezold, Danilevsky, Conty 
and Charpentier) which illustrate the change in blood pressure under the 
influence of the emotions, especially of fright, the only emotion which can 
be aroused experimentally, if need be. This influence is very obvious; a 
sudden fright results even after severing the N. vagus in increased blood- 
pressure in the large arteries, and that means a contraction of the fine 
blood-vessels, as we have assumed to be the case in the effect of fear on 
man. 



62 CARL GEORG LANGE 

to prove rather tentatively that emotions are in fact accompanied 
by disturbances in the brain circulation. Earlier observations of 
this fact have been made. The remowned English surgeon, 
Astley Cooper, who lived at the beginning of this century, had 
opportunity to observe a man, who suffered from a significant 
defect of the base of the skull, and declared that the pulsations 
of the brain were increased every time anything was said that dis- 
pleased the patient. Several years ago, the Italian physiologist, 
Mosso, 19 made more accurate observations under similar con- 
ditions. A man, whose brain was laid open over a rather large 
area, showed that any insult or sensation of anger increased the 
pulsation of the brain, and also the pulse of the arteries in the 
arm, even though the activity of the heart did not seem to be af- 
fected in any way. One striking change in brain pulsation was 
evidenced at noon, when the chimes began to ring: this Mosso 
declared to be due to the fact that the patient was disturbed 
because he could not cross himself as usual to say his Ave Maria. 
On the whole, Mosso found that emotional disturbances affected 
the brain-circulation much more than thought-activity, no mat- 
ter how great the effort. 

According to all physiological experiences, nothing opposes the 
assumption that the immediate bodily expression of the affections 
is a change in the function of the vasomotor apparatus, different 
for each affection, and that the other bodily appearances, which 
accompany the affections, are due to these vaso-motor disturbances, 
these changes in the blood-content of the various organs, and 
members of the body. Thus the changes in appearance (skin) 
and in the functions (22) (nervous-system, secretory glands) of 
the organs are explained. The assumption of such a relation 
greatly simplifies the condition as a whole, and facilitates, as we 
shall soon see, the physiological comprehension, which would 
be difficult if we had to assume a direct primary origin for all 
these various phenomena. Besides, we must mention particularly 
that my fundamental conception of the psychology of the affec- 
tions is in no way disturbed, if we should in future be forced to 
the last mentioned conception. So far, there is on hand so great 
a probability for a vasomotor theory, that we may proceed from 
its assumption. 

19 A. Mosso, The Blond Circulation in the Human Brain. 1881. p. 13. 



THE EMOTIONS 63 

We now face a problem of essential interest from a psycho- 
physiological point of view, and which therefore constitutes the 
main point of this investigation, namely: the question concerning 
the nature of the relation of the emotions to the concomitant 
body-phenomena. 

So far, I have always, even if under protest, employed such 
phrases as "the physiological phenomena produced by emotions" 
or "the physiological phenomena which accompany the affec- 
tions," in order, by using the popular expressions for the relation 
in question, to facilitate temporarily their comprehension. 
Strange to say this relation has never been defined even broadly; 
I know of no attempt made to establish its real nature. For the 
popular conception, the matter is very simple. The emotions 
are entities, substances, forces, demons, which attack human 
beings and cause physical as well as mental disturbances: "I was 
seized with sorrow," "I met with a great pleasure," "I was con- 
trolled by anger," "fear overwhelmed me," etc. (23); or one 
may substitute the more English expressions : " seized with anger," 
"in the clutches of fear." This naive conception, which, like 
many other things in popular psychology and some in scientific 
psychology, owes its force only to a certain demonstrativeness, 
would hardly be recognized in modern psychology, if we could 
substitute a more comprehensible and exact explanation. Most 
modern authors of scientific psychology do not recognize this 
question at all; 20 in fact, they seem purposely to pass over it in 
silence, perhaps in order not to be forced f or lack of a physiolog- 
ical explanation to have recourse to the code-language of specu- 
lative psychology. In fact, it may be said that even scientific 
psychology shares in the belief that the affections call forth, cause, 
the physical phenomena. But as to the real nature of the affec- 
tions, that they can have such great influence upon the body, no 
word of explanation is to be found in all modern psychology even 
in Wundt (Physiological-psychology, 2 ed., Vol. II, Ch. 33). 

If a clear understanding of relations which I have discussed 
above is to be made possible, we must I think, put the facts in the 

20 TJie external motions are always due to internal emotions (Wundt, 
Concerning the Expression of Emotions, Deutsche Rundschau, April, 
1877). 



64 GAEL GEOEG LANGE 

following form: We have in every emotion as sure and tangible 
factors: (1) a cause asensoryimpressionwhichusuaUyismodified 
by memory or a previous associated image; and (2) an effect 
namely, the above mentioned vaso-motor changes and consequent 
changes in bodily and mental functions. And now we have the 
question: What lies between these two factors; or dos anything 
lie between them? If I start to tremble when I am threatened 
with a loaded pistol, does a purely mental process arise, fear, 
which is what causes my trembling, palpitation of the heart, and 
confusion; or are these bodily phenomena aroused immediately 
by the frightening cause, so that the emotion consists exclusively 
of these functional disturbances of the body? 

The answer to this question is obviously not only of far-reaching 
significance in the psychology of the affections, but also of the 
greatest practical importance for every physician who has anything 
to do with the pathological results of violent emotions. 

The popular opinion seems to be that, as has been mentioned, 
the immediate outcome of a situation which arouses an emotion 
is a purely psychic one, that is, either a new power is generated in 
the mind, or a modification of the mental condition takes place; 
and furthermore, that this mental activity is the actual affection, 
the real pleasure, pain, etc., whereas the physical phenomena are 
merely secondary, always present, to be sure, but in themselves 
quite unessential. 

The purely mental affection is a hypothesis and, like every 
hypothesis, is justified only if (1) it explains the phenomena it is 
assumed to explain, and (2) it is necessary for the explanation of 
these phenomena. 

In regard to the first of the above requirements, the questionable 
hypothesis has as good chances as any hypothesis of speculative 
science. Without objections being offered by experience, hypoth- 
eses can be broadened at will and they can be endowed with any 
attribute or power, and consequently they serve any purpose 
which may be required of them. Can mental fear explain why we 
turn pale and tremble? Even though we do not understand that, 
we are free to assume it to be true, and as a rule that is sufficient 
for us. 



THE EMOTIONS 65 

If the hypothesis of the psychical nature of the affections, there- 
fore, is indisputable in this point, especially because it lies outside 
of the realm of proof, the question arises whether it fulfills the 
second requirement; to be necessary for the explanation of that 
group of phenomena which we call affections, so that they cannot 
be understood without its help. 

If anyone were to dispute it, if, for example, some one attempted 
to prove to a man who has grown up with the popular conception of 
this problem that when he is frightened, his fear is only a percep- 
tion of the changes in his body, he would very probably meet with 
the following objection first: "The assumption of this relation 
is disproved by personal experience, for fear, like every emotion, 
has a distinct sensation of a peculiar change, a specific condition 
of the mind, quite independent of the body." I can well under- 
stand how this objection may appear very significant to most 
people, and be difficult to refute, and yet it has obviously no value 
whatever, in and for itself, since we have absolutely no immediate 
means of differentiating between a sensation of mental and one of 
physical nature. No man, in fact, is capable of differentiating 
between a sensation of mental and one of physical nature. No 
man, in fact, is capable of differentiating between psychical and 
somatic feelings. Whoever attributes a sensation to the mind, 
does so only on basis of theory, not on basis of immediate percep- 
tion. I have no doubt that a mother who mourns the death of 
her child would resent, yes, be indignant, if any one were to tell 
her that what she feels: the weariness and laxity of her muscles, 
the coldness of her bloodless skin, the impossibility of her brain 
to concentrate in clear, quick thought; 21 may be attributed to an 
image of the cause of these phenomena. But this is no ground for 
indignation, for her feeling is just as strong, just as deep and pure, 
if attributed to one as to the other cause. It cannot exist, how- 
ever, without its physical attributes. 

21 1 will not delay to consider the objection which might be offered, 
namely, that a purely mental sorrow, joy, etc., can be experienced when- 
ever the affection is not strong enough to cause bodily symptoms. Such 
an assumption obviously rests upon very incomplete observation, or upon 
this, that purely subjective sensations of lightness or of pressure, of 
strength or weakness sire considered psychical. 



66 CARL GEOBG LA3STGE 

Take away the bodily symptoms from a frightened individual; 
let his pulse beat calmly, his look be firm, his color normal, his 
movements quick and sure, his speech strong, his thoughts clear; 
and what remains of his fear? 

If, therefore, we .cannot rely upon the testimony of personal, 
subjective experiences in this question because they are incom- 
petent here, nevertheless the question is by no means cleared up. 
Even if this hypothesis of psychical affections is not made neces- 
sary by subjective experiences, it may still be indispensable, since 
perhaps we cannot understand how the bodily phenomena of the 
affections arise 22 without it. 

And so, next we have to examine whether the physical expres- 
sions of affections may arise in a purely physical way; if this be 
the case, then the necessity of the hypothesis is obviated. 

As a matter of fact, it is not difficult to prove now, and by means 
of the most ordinary and well known experiences, that emotions may 
be induced by a variety of causes which are utterly independent of 
disturbances of the mind, and that, on the other hand, they may 
be suppressed and modified by pure physical means. The fact 
that our whole manner of living, our daily diet, has developed in 
the course of generations with this aim in view, to favor the pleas- 
ant affections and to modify or entirely remove the unpleasant 
ones, is very well accepted, even if without clear consciousness of 
the actual connection of things. I will offer only one example: 
it will suffice to recall many. It is one of the oldest experiences of 
mankind that "wine gladdens the heart' 7 and the power of alcohol- 
ic liquors to reduce sorrow and fear and to substitute joy and 
courage has found application, which is in and for itself natural 
enough, and would be most wholesome, if the substance did not 
produce other effects in addition. 

We all understand "why Jeppe drinks." 23 He seeks to free 
himself from his marital troubles and bis fear of Master Erich, and 

22 It is hardly necessary to point out that the assumption of processes in 
the mind for the explanation of the physical symptoms for a scientific con- 
ception is in reality only another expression for the fact that the origin of 
these symptoms is still a mystery to us. 

23 Jeppe am Berge. Character in a classic comedy by Holberg (note 
added by Kurella). 



THE EMOTIONS 67 

he ./ishes once again to sing and recall the happy past when he was 
still "with Maliz." Brandy makes him gay and brave, without 
requiring even a single brightening or enlivening impression, which 
might act directly upon his mind, and without causing him to for- 
get his cares or his enemies in the least. He wants only to look at 
them from another point of view, under the influence of brandy; 
he wants to impress the sexton and to beat his wife again; for 
alcohol has excited his vasomotor apparatus, has increased the 
speed and strength of his heart-beats, has dilated his capillaries, 
thereby increasing his innervation enough to make him chatter 
loudly, sing and row, instead of dragging himself over the road, 
moaning and whirring. He receives a sensation of warmth, levity 
and power, instead of his customary laxity and incompetence. 
His dull brain wakes up under the influence of heightened circula- 
tion, thoughts begin to come to him, old memories appear and 
drive away the habitual feeling of misery, and all for one peg of 
brandy, whose effect on the circulation we can understand and 
which requires no intervention of the mind to affect the vaso- 
motor centers. 

All those who drink brandy bear a similar relation to it, and we 
possess this relation to our daily luxuries and comforts, and to our 
various arrangements which we make to ensure our comfort and 
convenience. So long as we find ourselves in the easy, accustomed 
path of our daily life, the relation of our emotions to material 
influences (for example, to nourishment) is, of course, not so 
obvious. A different relation obtains when certain substances are 
partaken of, substances which have such a strong effect on the 
system that they are used either as medicines or belong to the 
category of poisons. This is well known in the case of certain 
mushrooms, especially of the toad-stool, which call forth violent 
outbreaks of rage and brutality in whoever partakes of them. 
Our belligerent ancestors are supposed to have used them to get 
into the proper spirit for the "Berserk rage," just as we today 
"take a drink" to "get up" our courage. Attacks of rage may 
also occur after using Hashish (Indian hemp), which as a rule, only 
stimulates the system to unrestrained joyfulness in much the same 
way that alcohol does. 



68 CAUL GEORG LANGE 

Certain sickening drugs, such as tartar emetic, ipecacuanha, ;tc., 
have a depressing effect, which is in some respects comparaHe to 
fear and sorrow, and, like these, is accompanied by phenomena of 
collapse. 

If emotional states can be induced by taking certain substances, 
or in any other purely physical way, it follows that troublesome 
affections can be counteracted and modified in a similar way. If 
brandy or opium induces joy, then they will oppose sorrow, etc. 

The power of a "cold shower" to dampen violence and wrath 
sometimes finds practical application, and yet this method can 
hardly have any direct effect upon the mind, if applied in natura; 
so much the stronger is the effect upon the vasomotor functions. 
By means of one drug the well-known potassium bromide 
which has a paralyzing effect on the vasomotor apparatus, we have 
it in our power not only to allay fear and sorrow and other similar 
unpleasant affections, but also to induce a condition of apathy, 
which makes it impossible for the subject to be either lively or 
depressed, fearful or angry, simply because the vasomotor func- 
tions have been suspended. 

^If the conception of the nature of the affections as here repre- 
sented is established, then we may expect that every influence 
involving general changes in the vascular nervous system must 
have an emotional expression. Of course, we cannot expect that 
these emotions will coincide exactly with the phenomena for which 
, we usually reserve this denotation; the differences in cause will 
naturally result in various effects. The various psychical causes 
also have effects which are not at all congruent. Fear of a ghost, 
for example, does not manifest itself in the same way as the fear 
of the guns of the enemy. Nevertheless, the similarity between 
physically and mentally induced affections has, in many cases, 
deen so conspicuous as to force the immediate conception, as many 
verbal expressions prove. We have the same expression for 
mental and physical pain in many languages: their great physio- 
logical similarity has been recognized, although the eminent 
characteristic of physical pain, the subjective sensation resulting 
from the transference of the peripheral stimulation to the sensory 
center, is entirely absent in mental pain. The cause of the simi-.. 
larity to emotional pain is the reflexive innervation of the vascular 



THE EMOTIONS 69 

nerves, a regular effect of every strong stimulation of the sensory 
nerves. 

In the same way "shudder" is used in speech for both the effect 
of sudden cold upon the skin, and for phenomena due to impres- 
sions from fright. That this naive conception knows no difference 
between emotional and purely physical "shudders" is evident 
from the story of the boy who set out to "get a thrill," and after 
he had tried in vain to "thrill" in the presence of dead and of 
ghosts, finally obtained his wish when he was thrown out of his 
bed into a tub of cold water. This produced a far stronger effect 
upon his vasomotor appartus than did the sight of death-beds or 
ghosts. To call a man "feverish" who suffers great suspense is 
another example of how striking is the similarity between the 
slight symptoms of fever which are induced chiefly by vasomotor 
disturbances, and those physical conditions which are caused by 
anxious expectation, etc. (24). 

As has been mentioned, I do not wish to enter upon the great 
problem of the relation of the affections to actual pathological 
conditions, and to psychical and 'physical diseases. 

But one relation does obtaip here, which I cannot quite pass 
over, because it will throw gr,eat light upon the question, so vital 
to us, of the necessity of the hypothesis of purely mental affec- 
tions. If anything can prove absolutely the dispensibility of this 
hypothesis, it certainly must be the fact that affections which 
influence our psychical life are induced without any external 
influence or circumstance, and aside from memory or association 
of ideas; and that they occur %n optima forma on the mere basis 
of conditions of disease which develop in the body or are inherited. 

If we proceed from the conception represented here, this cannot 
appear strange to us; for, of course, the vasomotor apparatus may 
also be affected by disease at times, just like any other part of the 
nervous system, and be caused to function abnormally, or to be 
put out of commission entirely. We may consider it especially 
exposed to the danger of abnormal functioning, because it is a 
part of the nervous system, which enjoys less rest and is more 
frequently attacked by functional disturbances than any other or- 
gan. Wherever this occurs, the patient becomes either depressed, 
or raging, terrified, or excessively lively, or embarrassed, etc., 



70 CABL GEORG LANGE 

all without motive, even though he is conscious of not having any 
reason for his anger, his fear or joy. What support can we find 
here for an assumption of "mental affections?" 

Such cases are extraordinarily common. Every psychiatrist 
knows the sharply defined characteristics which occur in melan- 
cholia or mania. Every physician, who is interested in nervous 
diseases, has plenty of opportunity to observe the still more in- 
structive cases which lie on the border between real insanity and 
mere "indispositions," which come under the head of "irritabil- 
ity," "eccentricity," "dejection," etc. Most frequently we find 
"dejection" (the image of sorrow or even of despair), which often 
leads to suicide in spite of the full, clear consciousness that there 
is absolutely no mental motive for sorrow. Less frequent is the 
diseased condition of fear, which is often combined with related 
affection, with sorrow, but also occurs alone. Sometimes we also 
find that joy occurs in disease; the mere fact that joy appears 
unmotivated and without cause is not sufficient proof for the lay- 
man to consider it diseased, and still less to suggest medical 
treatment . 

It is usuaEy necessary for the joy to express itself most unre- 
strainedly as a more or less decided mania, or that it alternate in a 
striking manner with periods of depression: circumstances which 
cause it to appear abnormal. The same holds true of anger. As 
regards this affection, we are wont to accept much that presup- 
poses no corresponding pathological condition, and we are not as 
particular regarding the motivation. However, everything has its 
limits and frequently there are outbreaks of anger which have so 
little motive, and are so unbridled, that all will agree in considering 
them expressions of a pathological condition. 

There is perhaps nothing that can be more enlightening to a 
non-medical man than the observation of such a pathological 
attack of rage, especially if it appears unmodified by any other 
psychic disturbances, as happens rarely, by the way, in the so- 
called "transitory mania" form of disease. Often the attack 
comes without the slightest provocation to predisposed patients, 
who are otherwise quite rational, and puts them (to speak with 
the latest writer 24 on the subject) in condition of "wild paroxysms 

24 0. Schwartzer, Die transitorische Tobsucht. Wien, 1880. 



THE EMOTIONS 71 

of rage, with a terrible, blind raving impulse to destruction and 
violence." The patient suddenly attacks his surroundings, 
strikes, stamps his feet, kicks, crushes everything he can lay hands 
on, throws down everything he can get hold of, smashes and tears 
to pieces whatever is near him, tears his clothes, screams, yells, 
howls and rolls his gleaming eyes and shows all symptoms of 
vasomotor congestion that we have become acquainted with 
before in rage. The face is reddened, swollen, the cheeks are 
hot, the eyes protrude and their choroids become bloodshot, 
the beat of the heart increases, and the pulse beats 100 to 120 
times a minute. The arteries of the neck swell and pulsate, the 
veins swell, salivation is increased. The attack lasts only a few 
hours and comes to a sudden end in an 8 to 12 hour sleep, and the 
patient on awakening has forgotten all th^t happened. 

The pathological affections discussed above are due to physical 
abnormalities and may appear either as symptoms of other dis- 
eases, or because of some disturbance in metabolism or digestion, 
eta Hence, they are influenced by purely material therapy and 
may be improved and cured thereby. The above quoted case of 
transitory mania, which obviously is due to a sudden congestion 
in the brain can sometimes, according to the above quoted 
author, be cured by ice compresses around the head (25). 

Here I foresee one objection, which I do not wish to pass over 
unnoticed, in spite of its weakness logically. Undoubtedly many, 
in agreement with daily usage of speech, will say: "The condi- 
tions which are brought about by purely physical influences, or by 
diseased conditions of the body, may look like affections, but are 
not." 

The raving caused by a toadstool, for example, or by mania, 
may have the same appearance as rage, but is not the real rage, 
just as little as the joy which comes of drinking wine is not real 
joy; therefore, in absence of a mental joy, in cases of toadstool 
poisoning, or mania, we cannot conclude that no such purely 
mental state exists, if rage is as a rule caused by a mental im- 
pression. 

Now, it is easy to comprehend that such a division of affections 
into real and apparent, such a limiting of the range of "real affec- 
tions," is quite consciously based upon a petitio printipii. The 



72 CAUL GEOEG LANGB 

reason for suggesting that such a group of the "real affections" 
is due to purely mental influences, is the only possible assumption 
that can be made, in which the disposition (Gemuth) is involved. 
But that is precisely the point of this investigation. 

In reality, the difference between the Berserk-madness of a 
man poisoned by a toad-stool, the maniacal-madness and the rage 
of one who has suffered a bloody insult, lies only in the difference 
of cause and in the consciousness of the respective causes, or ill the 
lack of consciousness of a cause. If we want to differentiate be- 
tween these differences, there is, of course, no objection to offer; 
only it must be clearly understood wherein the difference lies. 

Indeed, it is not so easy to draw a line between material and 
mental causes for affections; and if we try to sound the physiolog- 
ical differences, they vanish into something quite insignificant 
physiologically, and slip through our fingers. It has never 
occurred to anyone to separate the emotion due to a suddenly 
discharged shot, from the true affections. No one hesitates to 
call it fright, and it presents all the ordinary characteristics of 
fright. Nevertheless, it has no connection with any image of 
danger, and is not caused by any association of ideas, memory, 
or any other mental process. The phenomena of fright follow 
the shot immediately, without any trace of "mental" fright. 
Many will never grow accustomed to standing beside a gun when 
it is fired, merely on account of the noise, although they know 
perfectly well that there is no danger present, either to them or to 
any one else. We can also consider the case of the infant, which 
presents all the phenomena of fright at every strong impression of 
sound; we cannot assume that the sound arouses an image of 
danger in this case. 

Here, where we must assume that the pure vasomotor reflex is 
released by a direct circuit from the center of hearing, if not in- 
directly by the auditory nerves, we have an emotion of purely 
material origin. 25 And so, we must either exclude this fright from 

26 It is not probable that this is a case of a pure, simple reflex of the motor 
nerves, as Preyer, for example, seems to assume (Die Seele des Kindes, 
2d ed v p. 51), partly because the apparent movements do not look as if they 
were caused by a sudden impression that releases a reflex, partly, also, 
because the effects are not limited to the motor phenomena. 



THE EMOTIONS 73 

the real affections, or we cannot support the differentiation be- 
tween mentally and physically induced affections. We meet with 
the same difficulty in the case of the usually less intense, but 
nevertheless sufficiently decided, emotions that are aroused by 
simple impressions made upon other sense organs, which have no 
connection with any association of ideas; the pleasure we take in 
a pretty color, or color combination, our repulsion towards a bad 
taste or odor, discomfort in pain. 

If we have begun to feel uncertain about the establishment of a 
border line between the mental and physical causes of affections, 
we will discover a strong impulse to examine what physiological 
significance this difference possesses, i.e:, what difference exists in 
the cerebral mechanism of emotions, in the brain activity when the 
cause is mental and when it is purely material. 

In the face of our present still incomplete knowledge of the 
physiology of the brain, it is of course not very tempting to attempt 
an explanation of what happens in the brain in mental activity. 
It of course can be only a question of the crudest fundamental 
outlines, and with every qualification regarding the accuracy of 
the results. Nevertheless, in physiological investigations, it is not 
only justified, but even correct and desirable to determine defi- 
nitely just what can be done in the light of our present physio- 
logical knowledge. At least, we may derive encouragement from 
the fact that these relations as described here are very easy to 
grasp, in their fundamental outlines. 

Whatever the causes may be that arouse affections, the effects 
on the nervous system are identical in one point; in the effect upon 
the vasomotor center, that group of nerve cells which regulates 
the innervation of the bloodvessels. The stimulation of these 
cells, which lie chiefly in the part of the cord between the brain 
and the spinal cord, is the root of the causes of the affections, 
however else they may be constituted; and is fundamental to the 
physiological phenomena which are the essential components of 
the affections. But the paths which lead thither are various, 
according to the nature of the causes, not only according to 
whether they enter by one or another sense-organ, but also accord- 
ing to whether they are simple sense impressions, or complicated, 
so-called psychic processes. It seems that for the formation of 



74 



GAEL GEORG LANGE 



those emotions which are due to a simple sense impression, a loud 
noise, a beautiful color combination, etc., the path to the vaso- 
motor center must be quite direct, and the cerebral mechanism 
but slightly complicated. Consider to be the sense organ in the 
following figure, the eye for example, which received the impres- 
sion in question and which subsequently passes along the optic 
nerve (tf.O.) to the central optic organ (C.O/), is diverted by a 
simple nerve connection to the vasomotor center (C.F.) to lead off 
the impulse first aroused in the eye and in this way to effect the 
emotional changes in the vascular innervation (26). 




FIG. 1 

The matter becomes somewhat more complicated when those 
affections are involved which are produced not by a simple im- 
pression upon some sense-organ, but by some "mental process," 
some memory or association of ideas, even if the latter be due to 
sense-impression. Such causes usually produce a much stronger 
emotional effect than do the simple sense-impressions. The latter 
usually only arouse affections when they are very powerful, 
and their effects are usually not so deep nor so lasting, especially 
when compared with those aroused psychically. 

Fortunately, things are arranged so that most sense-impres- 
sions are entirely without emotional effects, and that they obtain 
such effects only by stimulation through mental activity. When* 



THE EMOTIONS 75 

I begin to tremble, if threatened by a loaded gun, it is evidently 
not the sense-impression which causes the fear, for a loaded gun 
looks just like an empty one, which I would not have noticed at 
all. What, then, happens in the brain, when an affection is induced 
by a sense impression that can have no direct effect upon the 
vascular nerve center as can a loud report, etc.? In order possibly 
to give a somewhat adequate answer to this question, we must 
proceed from the consideration of the simplest imaginable case. 
There are undoubtedly an infinite number of possibilities which 
are for the most part very complicated and impossible of analysis. 
But, on the other hand, a very simple case contributes by its sug- 
gestion of the relation, to the solution of this complicated problem 
for future physiological research. 

As an example of the simplest type, I shall offer the following 
case, for the correctness of which every mother would testify. 
A young child will cry at the sight of the spoon which has pre- 
viously been used several times to give him nasty medicine; how 
does that happen? Such a case, or analogous ones, are frequently 
cited from the psychological point of view, and very diverse answers 
will be found for our question. " He cries, because he considers the 
spoon to be the cause of his former distress," we say. But this does 
not help to explain the fact. Or he cries "because the spoon re- 
awakens memories of former sufferings," which may be quite true, 
but does not transfer the case to the field of physiology; or "be- 
cause the spoon arouses fear of future discomforts;" but the ques- 
tion is, just how does the sight of the spoon arouse fear because of 
its previous use, i.e., how is it capable of setting the vaso-motor 
center in action in a certain way? 

Whenever the child received medicine from that spoon, his 
visual sense was stimulated as well as his gustatory sense, by the 
sight of the spoon as well as by the taste of the medicine. Both 
impressions are conveyed to the brain from the peripheral sense 
organs, and there, after they have become sensations in the cen- 
tral sense organ (in C.QJ and C.O.' in the above figure), they are 
brought to consciousness in that they are brought to the centers 
of taste and vision in the cortex (in C.G." and C.O."). But the 
dispositional outbreaks of the child show conclusively that each 
impression of taste is always conveyed to the vaso-motor center 



76 CARL GEORG 

(C.K from C.(?/) and hereby arouses the phenomena which express 
fright, disgust, et al. The sight of the spoon alone therefore can 
not set the vascular nerves in action; if we show the spoon to a 
child in a condition of ignorance, before he has tasted the bitters 
that he may receive from it, he will reach for it instead of begin- 
ning to cry. 

But if he has seen the spoon in action a few times, and has 
noticed that this sight is always followed by a disgusting taste, 
it becomes evident that the sight of the spoon alone has the power 
to make the child cry, i.e.j to stimulate his vasomotor center to 
activity. This must now be capable of being aroused either from 
the point C.O/ or from the point C.O.", which before had no 
influence whatever. 

From which of these points now does the impulse to C.V. start, 
when the child sees the hated spoon? Surely from C.O.", the 
cortical center, since this is the first organ where an image of the 
spoon becomes conscious. Now it is a question why the group of 
cells C.O/', which formerly had no influence upon the vasomotor 
center, is now capable of stimulating it to emotional activity. 
When we recall that the fact that visual and gustatory impressions 
have been received simultaneously numerous times is the cause, 
we begin to think immediately that a functional connection must 
have been established by these simultaneous stimulations between 
the two cell groups C.O." and C,G.", the conscious centers for the 
appearance of the spoon and the taste of the medicine; so we must 
add that whenever C.O." are activated by the sight of the spoon, 
the impulse is conducted to C .(?.", from whence again, as is evi- 
dent in view of the well known power of memory to arouse 
emotions, it is easily conducted to C.V. 26 I fear that the assump- 
tion of a new, so far untried, functional relation between C.O." 
and C.O." must, at first sight, look like one of the many subter- 
fuges which physiological psychology does not always scorn 

36 Whether this takes place over the paths C.G."-C.G.' and C.G.'- 
C.V., or over other unknown ones, cannot be determined. But there is 
no reason to object to the above mentioned courses, for they also take 
care of a reversed direction, since the reversible conduction of the nerve 
fibers, which obviously cannot be observed in the peripheral nerves, cer- 
tainly must play an important part in the central organs, when their 
amphicellular arrangement favors and necessitates.it. 



THE EMOTIONS 77 

to make use of in its theories. It is temptingly easy to " open new 
roads" by a pen-stroke, when we wish to have something done 
between two points in the brain, which before have possessed no 
relation. If then we consider such "roads" to be represented by 
nerve-fibers, we certainly build on a very shaky hypothesis; for, 
outside of early evolutionary periods, we have no proof of the con- 
dition that nerve fibers which formerly have been inert will begin 
activity. But the matter is different, if we consider the conduc- 
tion of an impulse from one place to another by means of connected 
nerve-cells, as we would have to assume the path of conduction 
between C.O." and C.G." to be. The numerous phenomena of 
irradiation, ordinary and pathological, demonstrate adequately 
that the "blazing of the trail" easily takes place under these con- 
ditions as a result of repeated stimulation of one or the other cell 
group. 

But we must not be satisfied with such an indeterminate rep- 
resentation like the one contained in the expression ^to blaze a 
new trail." We must make it clear to ourselves, how this relation 
is to be understood in each individual case; the new connection 
between the two points may be established in a number of dif- 
ferent ways. 

In the above case, we see that the point C.G." which originally 
was not stimulated when an impulse reached C.O.", now is acti- 
vated by an impression received at C.O/', after both points have 
been simultaneously stimulated a few times. If we were to say 
now, that this is a simple phenomenon of irradiation; the stimula- 
tion at C.O/' spreads, irradiates by means of cell connections to 
C.G/'; nothing would, in fact, be explained, for it would still 
remain a mystery just what leads the irradiation to C.G/ 7 , as we 
can assume beforehand that the phenomenon can take place in 
any direction from C.O/', with equal ease. Our supposition does 
not justify our assuming that the process of irradiation takes 
place in one direction only, although this is very possible. We 
must proceed from the theory that it radiates from C.O/' in all 
directions, and decreases in intensity with the distance from this 
point. 

What has occurred in the above case is not a "blazing of a new 
trail" in the sense of opening paths which have not been traversed 



78 CAEL GEORG LAJSTGE 

before. The new effect of this sense-impression upon the child 
does not depend upon his being led along new paths, which for- 
merly were closed, but upon the fact that the point C.G." is in a 
condition to be influenced by the irradiation from the point C.O.", 
more strongly than any other group of cells which may be affected; 
or rather, C.G" is the only group which responds recognizably 
to the impulse propagated by irradiation. 

We can only consider the fact that this group has previously 
been stimulated simultaneously with C.O." as a reason for this 
greater sensitivity. A change has hereby been produced in its 
cells, a condition of excitability, which is not to be found in the 
other brain cells, which may be reached by irradiation. A sum- 
mation of functional activity occurs in C.G." due to the existing 
activity and the additional activity conducted to it from C.O. 27 
The reason for the fact that C.G." is only stimulated by irradia- 
tion coining from C.O/', and not by that coming from any other 
point in the cortex, is quite easily explained. But an investiga- 
tion of this point would require trespassing in other fields of 
psychophysiology. Therefore, I pass over the question, and that 
the more willingly, since it is here only a question of sketching the 
main direction of the path over which we can conceive the proc- 
ess of stimulation of the vasomotor centers to pass, wherever it is 
a question of an indirect "mental" affection. 

The exemplary case quoted above, as has been mentioned, has 
been taken as simple and as uncomplicated as possible. Of 
course, the process is much more complicated in most indirect 
affections; in other words, the impulse coming from outside must 
traverse a much more round-about path in the brain, must pass 
more stations, before it reaches the vasomotor center (27) ; but 
the outlines of the physiological procedure will essentially remain 

27 This relation will perhaps become clearer when we recall the phe- 
nomena of interference, which shows that one wave motion may be reinforced 
by another wave of the same nature. The irradiation which proceeds from 
the point C.O." and which spreads with decreasing intensity in all direc- 
tions may be compared to the circular wave motion set up when a stone is 
thrown into a pool of still water. If, now, one of the disturbances coming 
from C.O." meets a similar one that has started earlier, but which is still 
active and coming from C.G.", then the tract between may be set into 
stronger motion by interference than any other ray from C.O." 



THE EMOTIONS 79 

constant: a conduction of the stimulation from the cells of the 
central sense organs to the cortical cells, and from these finally to 
the vasomotor cells in the mid-brain. 

And, so, I probably was justified in my statement (on page 72) 
that the difference between emotions induced by material and 
mental methods was not absolute, not even essential, from a 
physiological point of view. The chief requisites for formation 
remains the same for both, the stimulation of the vasomotor 
centers; the difference lies in the path which the impulse pursues 
to reach this center. To this we must still add the fact that an 
increase of impulse occurs in the case of indirect, "mental" affec- 
tions, due to a previous brain stimulation which has not yet quite 
died away, and the effect of which is added to the impulse coming 
from the external impression. 

I hope that it will now be obvious that, as I have already re- 
marked in the introduction, the problem is reversed, if we, as 
often has been done in the past, and as still happens, set out to 
determine the physiological and pathological effects of affections 
upon the body. 

The statement of the problem is wrong in principle, for the 
emotions are not forces which stand outside of the body and con- 
trol it, and whoever proceeds conscientiously in his investigation 
will soon come to the conclusion that this problem is practically 
insolvable. If, nevertheless, it has been believed that it is possible 
to offer a thousand answers to the question of the influence of joy 
and sorrow, of fright and anger, etc., upon the pshsiological expres- 
sions of life, only a quite arbitrary and impossible schematization 
has been obtained, by which every phenomenon which did not fit 
into the scheme was excluded. And so I too have proceeded in 
the above sketch of the bodily expressions of the affections. Any- 
one who has followed this sketch will easily see that it holds good 
only for certain cases which we will call the typical, or better still, 
the conventional ones, because it is they that have gradually 
assumed in the course of time a kind of symbolic significance in 
art and literature, representing groups of related phenomena. 
But we have all seen people struck dumb with joy, rather than 
made loquacious, we have seen fright rush the blood to the head 
of its victim, instead of making him turn pale, and have seen the 



80 CARL GEOKG LANGE - 

mourner rush about restless and moaning, rather than silent and 
dejected, etc. This is natural, for the same cause may have a 
different effect upon the vascular nerves of different people, since 
these do not always give the same reaction in different individuals, 
and -besides, the impulse has been influenced by various factors 
previous to its path through the brain, under the psychological 
form of memories and associated ideas. But he who states the 
problem in the traditional form must do violence to the facts in 
another respect, namely, in a conscious schematization of the 
affections, an establishment of definite forms; whereas in reality 
a multitude of unnoticeable transitions occur. That is a deliberate 
act, which is perhaps more flagrant than would be the establishing 
of seven definite colors to represent the entire range of colors. 
Such an act might be permissible in daily speech, but is quite out 
of the question in a scientific investigation, where it can only 
happen by trespassing and neglecting all the innumerable shades 
of transition, which so far have no name in speech. 

How often are we not embarrassed when called upon to decide 
how to classify our momentary disposition under the conventional 
headings? How often must we not be satisfied with vague ex- 
pressions for some emotional process ("I became excited/' "I was 
irritated," "my disposition was upset," etc.), and be unable 
to bring it under any one affection that has a name in the language? 

The truly scientific problem in this field is the determination of 
the emotional reaction of the vasomotor system to various influ- 
ences. The solution of this problem is still a long ways off. The 
present investigation goes no further than to point out the 
problem. 

We owe all the emotional side of our mental life, our joys and 
sorrows, our happy and unhappy hours, to our vasomotor system. 
If the impressions ^hich fall upon our senses did not possess the 
power of stimulating it, we would wander through life unsympa- 
thetic and passionless, all impressions of the outer world would 
only enrich our experience, increase our knowledge, but would 
arouse neither joy nor anger, would give us neither care nor fear 



It is true of the vasomotor apparatus as well as of all parts of the 
nervous system, that its irritability is very different for different 



THE EMOTIONS 81 

people. In some, it is easily stimulated and reacts to compara- 
tively slight impulses. 

Everyday experience teaches how much more easily some indi- 
viduals' hearts palpitate than others; how much more easily some 
blush or pale; how some are more sensitive to heat and cold; and 
we all know that those individuals whose vasomotor systems are 
so easily stimulated are the ones who easily become violent and 
angry, or excessively joyful, etc. Not only individual, but also 
inherited differences frequently occur here; more general and fre- 
quently highly significant relations play a part. Women, whose 
nervous system and especially the vasomotor division, proves to 
be much more sensitive than that of men, are much oftener the 
prey of affections than is the other sex. The same analogy holds 
true for children in comparison with adults. As is well known, 
racial peculiarities may cause differences, and since we cannot 
learn very much about the difference in sensitivity of the 
vasomotor systems of the various races, we may be allowed to 
reverse the conclusion and consider the greater or lesser mobility 
of the vascular nerves in response to a given stimulus. On account 
of the perspective into the future which it gives, one circumstance 
deserves particular notice, namely that individuals as well as races 
are subject to a greater degree of emotion the lower their posi- 
tion in society. 

The so-called savage races, when racial peculiarities do not act 
in the opposite direction, are more violent and unrestrained, more 
excessive in their joy, more subjugated by sorrow, than civilized 
nations. The same difference occurs between the various genera- 
tions of one and the same race; we are calm and tame compared 
to our barbarian ancestors, whose greatest delight lay in working 
themselves up to an insane rage for battle, but who, on the other 
hand, were so depressed by misfortune as to end their lives for a 
mere bagatelle. And, finally, we see a similar difference existing 
between "the various classes of society in the same generation. 
The surest sign of . "refinement" is the self-control with which 
educated persons bear misfortunes that would call forth out- 
breaks of passion in the uneducated. 

This repression of emotion during the progressive education of 
individuals and of generations proceeds hand in hand, not only 



82 CARL GEOBG LANGE 

with advancing development of mental life, but is also a result of 
this development. 

Mental life, too, is dependant upon vasomotor function, though 
in a somewhat different manner from emotional life. Intellectual 
operations cause, and are due to, an increase of blood supply to 
the brain, naturally, to parts of the brain other than those which 
are especially involved in emotions. 

To a certain degree a contradiction exists between the mental 
life and the emotional. The former acts " derivatively" (in the 
original sense of the word), conducting the blood away from the 
latter; and when Hermann von Bremen counts twenty, he relieves 
the motor part of his brain of such an amount of blood by this bit 
of intellectual activity that he no longer feels the impulse to 
strike. 28 

Education acts along the same lines. The aim of all education, 
(which must not be confused with instruction) is to increase self- 
control and the opposition or suppression of impulses, which are 
the immediate effects of our bodily organization, but which do not 
fit into established social conditions. Physiologically, we consider 
education to consist in practice in the ability to control simple 
elementary reflexes by higher ones. We are taught from earliest 
childhood to control the vasomotor reflexes of emotions and other 
reflexes not fitting for decent society. A child is punished when 
he starts to cry as a result of emotional vascular convulsions, just 
as much as when he does not keep himself clean, because of the 
uncontrolled reflexes of his bladder. 

In the course of years, the center of the vascular nerves loses 
more and more of its emotional activity by reason of the influence 
of control and lack of practice, and, as we have discovered so 
often in acquired characters, this result of development of the 
mental life and of education is transmitted to posterity by inherit- 
ance; generations arise which have less and less prompt emotional 
vascular innervation, and with always slighter innervation of the 
vascular nerves for the organs of intelligence. If our develop- 
ment continues to progress along these lines, we shall finally reach 

28 Hermann V. Br., a hero of the Holberg classical comedy, always counted 
twenty after his wife had struck him a blow, and he was then in a position 
to remain calm (note by Kurella). 



THE EMOTIONS 83 

Kant's ideal of the "man of pure reason," who will consider every 
affection, every joy and sadness, fear and fright, as a disease, a 
mental disturbance, which is not proper for him. 

ADDENDA 

(1) In the older philosophical terminology, the word "passiones" was 

used for both groups of phenomena. Thus, Descartes recognizes 
six primitivae passiones": "astonishment, love, hate, desire, joy and 
sorrow (De passionibus Art. 69) } and does not differentiate between 
the two kinds of psychical phenonena. Similarly, Spinoza uses the 
word "affectus" in a like manner. His five kinds are: desire, joy, 
sorrow, astonishment, scorn (Ethics ps. Ill, De origine et natura 
affectum). Later, however, attempts began to be made to estab- 
lish a certain difference between affectus and passiones passions 
and to make affections correspond to our emotions and "passions" 
to our passions. Kant differentiates between affections and pas- 
sions (passiones animi), but does not divide the phenomena under 
these heads. He considers love, hope, modesty, to be affections 
just like joy and sorrow. And although there is a tendency in 
later psychological usage to assign to "passiones" a definition which 
approximately corresponds to the German "Gemtithsbewegung," 
and the French and English "emotions," which we are dealing with 
here, yet we find even in the most recent works of the most rigorous 
scientific character that "Passion" and "Emotion" "Gemuthsbewe- 
gung," "Affect" and "Leidenschdft" are used rather interchange- 
ably, with no attempt at differentiation of the individual psychical 
disturbances. 

One author alone, the court-physician Lion, has made an attempt 
to differentiate between affections and passions (affections and 
passions from the point of view of modern science and of the legis- 
lature of 1866). After he justly bemoaned the fact of this general 
confusion, he established a series of diagnostic characteristics for 
both, but meeting, it seems to me, with no greater success than 
every other attempt at definition which proceeds from that unfor- 
tunate realistic conception to which our science is still wedded. 

(2) A sharp, and therefore scientific, differentiation can, of course, only 

be reached as a conclusion to a scientific investigation of the emo- 
tional phenomena. For immediate application here, it is fortu- 
nately not of the least importance to have a detailed differentiation 
between the two groups of phenomena as a starting point. We 
are only interested in obtaining homogeneous material for our in- 
vestigation, and that is not difficult since we can ourselves make the 
differentiation between the psychic phenomena that are involved 
in our investigation. 



84 CARL GEOKG 

(3) Kant bases his definition of affections as sensations which (contrary 

to passions) permit of no consideration, whether we surrender our- 
selves to them, or whether we oppose them, on the part that 
reflection plays in passion. (Anthropologie, book 3, 70). 

(4) In older psychological writers, we may still meet with attempts to 

define the individual emotions; but we find no explanation of the 
nature of the affections in these definitions. As a rule, they are 
purely causal, like those of Descartes, who defines joy as "jucunda 
commotio animae in qua consistit possessio boni quod impressiones 
cerebri ei repraesentant ut suum (I. c. Art. 91); and so he attributes 
joy to a consciousness of the possession of good; but about what 
joy itself really is, he says nothing. In the same way, Kant: when 
he defines modesty as fear due to anxious scorn of a person present 
(Anthropologie , book 3, 79) . A definition like Spinoza's : "Laetitia 
est hominis transitio a minore ad major em perfectionem" (Ethics 
ps. Ill), is purely nominal. 

(5) In Denmark, we find the brief and superficial presentation of Professor 

Klingberg's in the "Skandinavisk I/iteraturselskabs Skrifter," 9 de 
Aargang, 1813. More thorough and detailed is the work of 
Sibbern in his book, "Om Forholdet mellem Sj&el og Legeme," 1849. 
Also, the work of A. Sell ("Om Betydn. af. Sindsbevaegeh. Som 
Sygdomsaarsager, 1884). This deals chiefly with the pathological 
relations. 

(6) I have (c/. Lecture on the pathology of the spinal cord, Forlaesn over 

Rygmarvens Patol., p. 455 ff.) used the term "patent innervation" 
to describe a phenomenon which is very significant for the under- 
standing of many pathological symptoms, but which so far has not 
been noticed by physiologists and pathologists. For, besides the 
obvious impulses from the brain, which control the so-called volunt- 
ary muscles, there are other continuous motor impulses which, as a 
rule, are not observed under normal conditions, because they are 
so slight that they do not effect an actual contraction of the 
muscles, but only cause a slight tension. Thus, our muscles suffer 
a slight contraction, even when at rest, as in sleep, so that our body 
usually assumes a position in sleep which it could not hold in 
death. 

(7) A heightened activity of the constrictor apparatus of the blood- 

vessels (vascular spasm, vascular convulsion) may, as a rule, only 
cause a contraction of the smaller vessels, whose thin walls possess 
a relatively strong muscular coat. The consequence of a vascular 
convulsion is a change in the distribution of the blood in the vessels, 
so that the large vessels, which are not contracted, are over-filled 
with blood, whereas the smaller ones receive less blood than usual, 
or are even so completely contracted as to allow no blood to enter. 

(8) I am myself not so sure of the truth of my above explanation of the 

apparent paradox that a sorrowful person weeps. We might also 



THE EMOTIONS 85 

assume that weeping is the effect of a spasmodic dilatation of the 
blood-vessels, and the profuse secretions which so frequently cause 
the swelling and reddening of the fleshy parts of the face are facts 
in favor of the assumption, this spasmodic dilation occurring fre- 
quently in sorrow, instead of the usual contraction. Physiological 
and pathological experiments prove adequately that one and the 
same vascular nerves may be caused to contract or dilate by the 
same stimulus, and we can discover no reason for the different 
effects. 

(9) That an overwhelming sorrow can turn the hair gray very rapidly, 
over night, is an old experience, and we have reliable observations 
of the phenomenon of recent date. An experienced and keen ob- 
server, our well-known psychiatrist Selmer, with whom I was dis- 
cussing the subject, was inclined to attribute the rapid turning 
gray of the hair, especially of women, after violent emotion, to the 
fact that they no longer took the trouble to conceal the gray hairs 
under the others so carefully, and he has often noticed that the 
original color returned as soon as the patients regained their normal 
self-control. It may be, of course, that this explanation is adequate 
for certain cases, especially in such cases where the hair literally 
turns gray ** over night." Such a sudden change defies all explana- 
tion, even if we consider the only existing observation made by 
Laudois (Virchows Archiv vol. 35), who thought it was due to an 
acute generation of gas in the hair. But that such a conspicuous 
fading of the hair should occur in an inconceivably short time, at 
least in the course of a few weeks, when the sorrow is extreme, I 
have myself observed to happen in a few cases. 

(10) The Italian physiologist, Mantegazza, relates how, a few years ago, 

an animal trainer raised great excitement because, after a dangerous 
fight with a lion that attacked him in the cage, all his hair fell out 
over night. 

A few years ago, it happened in a French town that a young 
girl, who saved herself in the collapse of a house by clinging to a 
rafter, lost not only the hair on her head, but also her eye-brows 
and eye-lashes, in short, all the hairs on her body, within the fol- 
lowing few days, (Cf. Arch, gen&rales de medetine, June 1879, p. 

WO 

Undoubtedly it is easier to explain a sudden falling out of the 
hair than a sudden turning gray, which plays a certain part in 
popular imagination and in novels. (Cf. Addenda 9.) 

The nails, too, are supposed to drop off under the influence of 
fear, though not as rapidly. (Cardanus, De subtilitate, lib. XV.) 

(11) That fright can, according to its degree, produce either an increase 

or a paralysis of the activity of the heart, is not difficult to explain 
physiologically; at least, this holds true for that conception ac- 
cording to which the vagus nerve acts as the motor nerve for the 



86 GAEL GEORG LANGE 

heart and possesses the power of causing the contractions of the 
heart to increase at every slight stimulation, no matter of what kind, 
and to inhibit the contraction at any stronger stimulation. 

(12) The involuntary evacuation of the bladder and intestine are, as a 

rule, described as paralytic phenomena, caused by a paralysis 
of the sphincter muscles. In another place, I have demonstrated 
the fallacy of this conception. (Cf. Hospitals-Tidende 187$, No. 
SO, J., and Forlaes over Rygm. Patologi, p. 175$.) Besides, De Marges 
(Z.c., p. 370) has come to the conclusion that these phenomena involve 
a convulsion. In those not rare cases where sudden fear necessi- 
tates an evacuation, it can only be a question of a convulsion of 
those involuntary muscles. 

(13) When the sensory elements of one of the nervous centers, the brain 

or spinal cord, are subjected to stimulation, sensations do not arise 
at the place of stimulation, but at the peripheral end of the nerve- 
fiber. This sensation is called eccentric or projected, according to 
its origin. 

(14) Surely it rests upon an illusion to claim to observe a pulsation of this 

blood-vessel in cases of anger. (Thus the Mohammedans claim 
that "the great artery in the center of the Prophet's brow beat 
when he was angry.") 

(15) Perhaps we will be asked here whether the above described con- 

gestion of the capillaries is not also of a nervous nature and attrib- 
utable to the same stemming of the blood as the dilation of the 
larger veins. However, various facts contradict this explanation. 
On the one hand, a rich blood-supply occurs in anger without show- 
ing any dilation of the larger blood-vessels. On the other hand, 
the skin does not retain its peculiar blue (cyanotic) coloring, which 
occurs in eases of superfluity of venous blood. Finally, an experi- 
ment on turkeys shows that after severing certain nerves, making 
the active dilation of the blood-vessels in the neck and head im- 
possible, the characteristic high red coloring and the swelling of 
their beak and throat gills does not take place, even in violent 
attacks of anger. 

(16) It is well known that Darwin made an attempt to demonstrate the 

theory of evolution in physiognomic expression and in emotional 
movements. The very entertaining and inspiring book in which he 
published these observations and theories (The Expression of 
Emotions in Man and Animals) bears, as do all the works from the 
pen of that great investigator, the stamp of genius and contains a 
quantity of fine observations and remarks. But his theories in 
this field are not tenable. It is questionable whether the decided 
evolutionary tendency which his pioneer researches have imparted 
to modern, and especially to English, psychology has been fortunate. 
Surely not in so far as the psychology of the emotions is concerned, 
for here this tendency has led to a neglect o real physiological 



THE EMOTIONS 87 

analysis and hence has digressed from the only true way by which 
Malebranche, Leuhossek, Libbern, and others have tried to reach 
their aim, and they would have attained it, too, if the essential 
physiological fact, the vasomotor function, had not been unknown 
at that time. 

(17) By coordination, we mean the distribution of motor impulse, which 

reaches only those muscles which are requisite to the performance 
of a certain determined action, and by which the amount of impulse 
sent to each part is properly regulated. As I have pointed out 
elsewhere, it is for this reason that coordination is an acquired 
skill, not a faculty innate in any specific organ of the nervous sys- 
tem as is so frequently assumed. There is one coordination which 
is active in the brain, another which is situated in the spinal cord. 
The disturbance in coordination discussed here must proceed 
probably from the brain. However, I cannot deal with the question 
in detail here. 

(18) Tissot (TraiU des nerfs, T. II, ps. I, p. S58) contradicts Galen ab- 

solutely and offers several partly plausible examples of sudden death 
due to a violent attack of rage. Brain hemorrhages, however, were 
the cause of these deaths, and, in the light of our modern knowledge 
of the causes of apoplexy, we can assume that a predisposition to 
these was present, even if the congestion due to the emotion did 
cause the catastrophy. 

(19) The phenomenon of incoordination, as considered here, is only to be 

found in voluntary muscle action. However, a simultaneous 
analogous uncertainty of vascular innervation may possibly occur 
with incoordination. Whether anything similar to this takes place 
in other organs, it is not in my power to state. 

(20) So far, I have brought the vasomotor function into opposition with 

the rest of the nervous activity, essentially in order to simplify the 
matter. Yet I have not lost sight of the fact that, in the question 
of the expression of the affection, it may occur to one that the vaso- 
motor apparatus is involved only as a part of the involuntary nerve- 
muscle apparatus, and that it is the latter which, in emotion, is 
opposed to the rest of the primarily affected nervous system, so that 
the disturbances of the bladder and intestinal movements would 
have to be considered to be primary phenomena. Since this problem 
cannot yet be decided definitely, and since its solution had no par- 
ticular significance for our investigation, I shall confine myself to 
a suggestion of this possibility. On the other hand, I wish to re- 
call the fact that a spasmodic vascular contraction can undoubtedly 
stimulate the organic muscles to contraction, and also the reflex 
center for the changes in circulation. Thus we will meet with no 
difficulty of a physiological nature in tracing the convulsive condi- 
tion to changes in circulation. 



88 CAEL GEOBG LANTGB 

(21) Changes in the blood content of the skin must necessarily be accom- 

panied by variations in the blood supply in the brain and other 
internal organs. Either the processes in the inner organs are the 
same as those in the skin, or the vessels in the former do not share in 
the changes which occur in the innervation of the skin-vessels. In 
that case hyperaemia in the skin must cause a derived anaemia in 
the other organs, and conversely anaemia in the skin will result in 
hyperaemia in the other organs. These latter changes compared 
to the secondary ones in the skin in the blood content, may be 
very significant, partly because the skin can take up a great deal 
of blood, and also because it may be deprived of very nearly all its 
blood as a result of motor effects. Consider, for example the several 
stages of fever. 

(22) It is rather strange that it was possible to establish a complete vaso- 

motor theory for the bodily expressions of the emotions almost 200 
years ago. It was Malebranche, who, in spite of the total absence 
of any physiological assumptions, knowing nothing of vascular 
muscles and nerves, was able to recognize the situation. In his 
famous work " De la recherche de la verite" (1674) he gives an explana- 
tion of the part which the heart plays in violent emotions corres- 
ponding to the physiology of his time, and then proceeds (liber V) : 
"Besides this, there are nerves to the brain for the more rapid and 
finer regulation of the flow of the essence of life, which surround 
the arteries of the brain as well as those which lead to other organs. 

"This is how it can happen that an unexpected sight or movement 
in the brain, accompanying any other circumstance, which must 
modify all the affections, will cause the essence of life to flow to 
those nerves which surround the arteries. Thus, a contraction of 
the arteries leading to the brain can cut off the circulation and a 
dilation can open the way which leads to every part of the body." 

"If those arteries which supply the brain are empty, and all other 
arteries of the body are contracted by these nerves, then the head 
must be overfilled with blood and the face must be reddened. But 
if this distribution of blood is changed by a change in the condition 
of the brain, then the contracted arteries relax and the others con- 
tract. Thus the head is emptied of blood, the face turns pale and the 
slight amount of blood that leaves the heart all streams to the 
low extremities of the body. The life essence in the brain decreases, 
and the rest of the body begins to tremble and weaken." 

Translated into modern physiological terms, the theory of Male- 
branche means that every strong emotional impression causes a 
heightened vasomotor innervation and a contraction of the arteries. 
If this contraction involves the arteries of the brain, then too little 
blood reaches the brain, and too much stays in the body. Anemia 
of the brain leads to general appearances of paralysis. If, on the 
other hand, in another kind of affection, the head arteries are 



THE EMOTIONS 89 

relaxed, while others are contracted, then brain and face are flooded 
with blood. 

Malebranche's theory necessarily had to be rather vague in view 
of the time, when nothing was known in physiology about the ac- 
tive changes in caliber of the blood vessels, and did not arouse much 
notice. Incomplete, as obviously it had to be, and inaccurate in 
some of the details, nevertheless the theory is very remarkable be- 
cause of the fact that the originator considered the disturbances 
of circulation to be the only primary symptoms of the physical con- 
comitants of emotions. 

(23) "Man has only one soul, which influences the entire body, and so, 

if a simple affection directs the whole force of the soul to one point 
and fills it with ideas and sensations of one kind, then the whole 
body must share in the expression of this affection and every move- 
ment, every member must contribute to it." (Engle, Ideen zu 
einer Mimik, Part I, page S10.) We can hardly wish for a clearer 
expression of the popular conception that affections are some sort of 
demons, sometimes good, sometimes bad, which occasionally dis- 
turb the soul of man. 

(24) I also wish to recall the oft quoted etymology of the word "Angst" 

according to Max Muller's theory. From the Sanskrit root ah or 
anh (to crush, torture, murder) we have the Sanskrit ahi, snake 
the latin anguis; furthermore, the latin ango, to compress, frighten 
and angor, which applies to the physical sensation of oppression, 
contraction of the throat (angina) as well as the emotional feeling. 
From the same root we have the Gothic ages, fear, and the English 
anguish, the Germanic Angst, the Latin angustiae, the French 
angoisse, etc. 

(25) Still more instructive are the cases where emotional outbreaks are 

caused by inadequate stimuli. I have found no reference to this 
phenomena in other authors, and it seems to be rare; however, I 
have observed several cases. One of these was a very intelligent 
man, not at all nervous, whom I was treating with a painful caustic 
for a small sore on his tongue. Invariably a fit of laughter appeared 
at the height of this operation, although there was nothing to laugh 
at. In the case of a lady, who suffered from paralysis of one side 
in consequence of a brain disease, but whose mental life had not 
been impaired in the least, she suddenly began to laugh whenever 
anyone told her a sad or disagreeable tale, although she was not at 
all humorously affected. It is evident that a case like the latter can 
contribute greatly to the solution of our problem if it be subjected 
to a rigorous analysis. Unfortunately, my observations took place 
at a time when I could not devote myself to their study. 

(26) From more recent times, we have experiments of Bechtereff in St. 

Petersburg (cf. Neurolog. Centralblatt 1888, No. 4), in which he 
believes to have proved that the occipital lobe "involves essentially 



90 CARL GEOBG LANGE 

tlie so-called movements of expression and expressive sounds." 
This surely does not follow from his observations, and might just 
as well prove that emotions may arise even after the destruction of 
the hemispheres. 

(27) Since sometimes a mere "memory" may call forth an emotion, with- 

out any sense-impression, and with only internal brain processes; 
then the process may for the moment be even simpler than the ex- 
ample quoted in the text. Nevertheless, a process must be pre- 
supposed to have happened in the past; a circumstance which has 
conditioned a permanent change in certain brain cells; and this 
process must, strictly speaking, be considered an emotional process, 
even though separated by an interval of time. 

(28) I do not know whether a similar conception of the nature of the affec- 

tions has ever been made before. At least, there are no records of 
it in scientific physiology. Spinoza approaches it most closely, in 
so far as he does not make the bodily phenomena in affections de- 
pendent upon mental activity, but in that he places them in the 
same plane as the latter, as is evident from his definition: "Per 
affectum intelligo corporis affectiones quibus ipsius corporis potentia 
augetur, vel mimiturjuvatur, vel coercetur, et simul harum affectionem 
idefis ." (Ethics p . HI . ) But he pursues the problem no further. 

In an Italian book of the last century* which bears the curious 
title "Delia, Fisiinomia, Principi derivati dall* Anatomia t dalla 
Fisiologiaj e Dinamica del corpo umano par mezzo de' guali si di$- 
tinguono Gli Aristocratici, ed i Realisti dai Democratic! di Girolamo 
Bocalosi, V. ed Milano } Anno VI repubbl." However, it has an 
otherwise very scientific point of view. I found in it (p. 20 f) the 
following declaration. "Jo chiamo passione d'un corpo quella tal 
tendenza e disposizione che hanno le parti componenti t e il tuttin- 
sieme di qualunque corpo a un tale e tal movimento a azione qualunque, 
dipendente da una causa estrinseca, e per cui quella data azione e 
necessario effeto di quella tal causa. 1 ' 

"Se questa e la vera definizione delle passioni in genere, noi avremo 
adesso una limpida idea della parola passione, e vedrassi ora da 
questo, che dalla tal data organizzazione d j un homo, dalla struttura 
de' suoi nervi, de suoi vasi, e della tempra ed equilibrio de suoi umori 
dee dipender la natura, la diver sita e I'energia maggiore o minor e delle 
sue passioni. A parlar dunque propriamente le passioni sono negli 
organi dell' uomo, e non nello spirito, e cosl le loro buone o rie 
qualitd, dalla contruzione dipender devono di tuto I'organico, mentre 
la spirito non sembra che un attributo di quello o se si vuole, ci non 
agisce che in consequenza della natura e testura delV organo." 

The author does not seem to approach very closely the theory which 
I have set forth here; but the last passage of the quoted abstract, 
which he does not carry out with more detail, makes his point seem 
somewhat hazy to me. 



THE EMOTIONS 

BY 
WILLIAM JAMES 



THE EMOTIONS 1 
WILLIAM JAMES 
[Chapter XXV of the Principles of Psychology] 

In speaking of the instincts it has been impossible to keep them 
separate from the emotional excitements which go with them. 
Objects of rage, love, fear, etc., not only prompt a man to outward 
deeds, but provoke characteristic alterations in his attitude and 
visage, and affect his breathing, circulation, and other organic 
functions in specific ways. When the outward deeds are inhibited, 
these latter emotional expressions still remain, and we read the 
anger in the face, though the blow may not be struck, and the 
fear betrays itself in vpice and color, though one may suppress all 
other sign. Instinctive reactions and emotional expressions thus 
shade imperceptibly into each other. Every object that excites an 
instinct excites an emotion as well. Emotions, howeve'r, fall short of 
instincts, in that the emotional reaction usually terminates in the 
subject's own body, whilst the instinctive reaction is apt to go 
farther and enter into practical relations with the exciting object. 

Emotional reactions are often excited by objects with which we 
have no practical dealings. A ludicrous object, for example, or a 
beautiful object are not necessarily objects to which we do any- 
thing; we simply laugh, or stand in admiration, as the case may be. 
The class of emotional, is thus rather larger than that of instinctive, 
impulses, commonly so called. Its stimuli are more numerous, 
and its expressions are more internal and delicate, and often less 
practical. The physiological plan and essence of the two classes 
of impulse, however, is the same. 

As with instincts, so with emotions, the mere memory or imagi- 
nation of the object may suffice to liberate the excitement. One 
may get angrier in thinking over one's insult than at the moment 
of receiving it; and we melt more over a mother who is dead than 
we eyeyjfii, when she was living. In the rest of the chapter I 

1 Parts of this chapter have already appeared in an article published in 
1884 in Mind. 



94 WILLIAM JAMES 

shall use the word object of emotion indifferently to mean one 
which is physically present or one which is merely thought of. 

It would be tedious to go through a complete list of the reactions 
which characterize the various emotions. For that 'the special 
treatises must be referred to. A few examples of their variety, 
however, ought to find a place here. Let me begin with the 
manifestations of Grief as a Danish physiologist, C. Lange, 
describes them: 2 

The chief feature in the physiognomy of grief is perhaps its paralyzing 
effect on the voluntary movements. This effect is by no means as extreme . 
as that which fright produces, being seldom more than that degree of weak- 
ening which makes it cost an effort to perform actions usually done with 
ease. It is, in other words, a feeling of weariness; and (as in all weariness) 
movements are made slowly, heavily, without strength, unwillingly, and 
with exertion, and are limited to the fewest possible. By this the grieving 
person gets his outward stamp : he walks slowly, unsteadily, dragging his 
feet and hanging his arms. His voice is weak and without resonance, 
in consequence of the feeble activity of the muscles of expiration and of the 
larynx. He prefers to sit still, sunk in himself and silent. The tonicity or 
" la tent innervation" of the muscles is strikingly diminished. The neck 
is bent, the head hangs ("bowed down" with grief), the relaxation of the 
cheek- and jaw-muscles makes the face look long and narrow ; the jaw may 
even hang open. The eyes appear large, as is always the case where the 
orbicularis muscle is paralyzed, but they may often be partly covered by 
the upper lid which droops in consequence of the laming of its own levator. 
With this condition of weakness of the voluntary nerve- and muscJe-appara- 
tus of the whole body, there coexists, as aforesaid, just as in all states of 
similar motor weakness, a subjective feeling of weariness and heaviness, 
of something which weighs upon one; one feels "downcast," "oppressed," 
"laden," one speaks of his "weight of sorrow," one must "bear up" 
under it, just as one must "keep down" his anger. Many there are who 
"succumb" to sorrow to such a degree that they literally cannot stand up- 
right, but sink or lean against surrounding objects, fall on their knees, 
or, like Romeo in the monk's cell, throw themselves upon the earth in their 
despair. 

But this weakness of the entire voluntary motor apparatus (the so-called 
apparatus of "animal" life) is only one side of the physiology of grief. 
Another side, hardly less important, and in its consequences perhaps even 
more so, belongs to another subdivision of the motor apparatus, namely, 
the involuntary or "organic" muscles, especially those which are found in 

2 Ueber*Gemuthsbewegungen, uebersetzt von H. Kurella (Leipzig, 1887), 



THE EMOTIONS 95 

the walls of the blood-vessels, and the use of which is, by contracting, to 
diminish the latter's calibre. These muscles and their nerves, forming 
together the "vaso-motor apparatus/' act in grief contrarily to the volun- 
tary motor apparatus. Instead of being paralyzed, like the latter, the vas- 
cular muscles are more strongly contracted than usual, so that the tissues 
and organs of the body become anaemic. The immediate consequence of 
this bloodlessness is pallor and shrunkenness, and the pale color and col- 
lapsed features are the peculiarities which, in connection with the relaxa- 
tion of the visage, give to the victim of grief his characteristic physiognomy, 
and often give an impression of emaciation which ensues too rapidly to be 
possibly due to real disturbance of nutrition, or waste uncompensated by 
repair. Another regular consequence of the bloodlessness of the skin is a 
feeling of cold, and shivering. A constant symptom of grief is sensitive- 
ness to cold, and difficulty in keeping warm. In grief, the inner organs 
are unquestionably anssmic as well as the skin. This is of course not 
obvious to the eye, but many phenomena prove it. Such is the diminu- 
tion of the various secretions, at least of such as are accessible to observa- 
tion. The mouth grows dry, the tongue sticky, and a bitter taste ensues 
which it would appear, is only a consequence of the tongue's dryness. [The 
expression -"bitter sorrow" may possibly arise from this.] In nursing 
women the milk diminishes or altogether dries up. There is one of the 
most regular manifestations of grief, which apparently contradicts these 
other physiological phenomena, and that is the weeping, with its profuse 
secretion of tears, its swollen reddened face, red eyes, and augmented se- 
cretion from the nasal mucous membrane. 

Larige goes on to suggest that this may be a reaction from a 
previously contracted vaso-motor state. The explanation seems 
a forced one. The fact is that there are changeable expressions 
of grief. The weeping is as apt as not to be immediate, especially 
in women and children. Some men can never weep. The tear- 
ful and the dry phases alternate in all who can weep, sobbing 
storms being followed by periods of calm; and the shrunken, cold 
and pale condition which Lange describes so well is more charac- 
teristic of a severe settled sorrow than of an acute mental pain. 
Properly we have two distinct emotions here, both prompted by 
the same object, it is true, but affecting different persons, or the 
same person at different times, and feeling quite differently whilst 
they last, as anyone's consciousness will testify. There is an 
excitment during the crying fit which is not without a certain 
pungent pleasure of its own; but it would take a genius for felicity 
to discover any dash of redeeming quality in the feeling of dry and 
shrunken sorrow. Our author continues: 



96 WILLIAM JAMES 

If the smaller vessels of the lungs contract so that these organs become 
anaemic, we have (as is usual under such conditions) the feeling of insuffi- 
cient breath, and of oppression of the chest, and these tormenting sensa- 
tions increase the sufferings of the griever, who seeks relief by long-drawn 
sighs, instinctively, like every one who lacks breath from whatever cause. 3 

The anaemia of the brain in grief is shown by intellectual inertia, dull- 
ness, a feeling of mental weariness, effort, and indisposition to work, often 
by sleeplessness. Indeed it is the anaemia of the motor centres of the brain 
which lies at the bottom of all that weakening of the voluntary powers 
of motion which we described in the first instance. 

My impression is that Dr. Lange simplifies and universalizes 
the phenomena a little too much in this description, and in partic- 
ular that he very likely overdoes the anaemia business. But such 
as it is, his account may stand as a favorable specimen of the sort 
of descriptive work to which the emotions have given rise. 

Take next another emotion, Fear, and read what Mr. Darwin 
says of its effects: 

Fear is often preceded by astonishment, and is so far akin to it that 
both lead to the senses of sight and hearing being instantly aroused. In 
both cases the eyes and mouth are widely opened and the eyebrows raised. 

3 The bronchial tubes may be contracted as well as the ramifications of 
the pulmonary artery. Professor J. Henle has, amongst his Anthropolo- 
gische Vortrage, an exquisite one on the "National History of the Sigh," 
in which he represents our inspirations as the result of a battle between the 
red muscles of our skeleton, ribs, and diaphragm, and the white ones of 
the lungs, which seek to narrow the calibre of the air-tubes. "In the 
normal state the former easily conquer, but under other conditions they 

either conquer with difficulty or are defeated The contrasted 

emotions express themselves in similarly contrasted wise, by spasm and 
paralysis of the unstriped muscles, and for the most part alike in all the 
organs which are provided with them, as arteries, skin, and bronchial 
tubes. The contrast among the emotions is generally expressed by divid- 
ing them into exciting and depressing ones. It is a remarkable fact that 
the depressing emotions, like fear, horror, disgust, increase the contraction 
of these smooth muscles, whilst the exciting emotions, like joy, anger, 
etc., make them relax. Contrasts of temperature act similarly, cold like 
the depressing, and warmth like the exciting, emotions. Cold produces 
pallor and goose-flesh, warmth smopths out the skin and widens the vessels. 
If one notices the uncomfortable mood brought about by strained expec- 
tation, anxiety before a public address, vexation at an unmerited affront, 
etc., one finds that the suffering part of it concentrates itself principally in 



THE EMOTIONS 97 

The frightened man at first stands like a statue, motionless and breathless, 
or crouches down as if instinctively to escape observation. The heart 
beats quickly and violently, so that it palpitates or knocks against the 
ribs; but it is very doubtful if it then works more efficiently than usual, 
so as to send a greater supply of blood to all parts of the body; for the skin 
instantly becomes pale as during incipient faintness. This paleness of the 
surface, however, is probably in large part, or is exclusively, due to the 
vaso-motor centre being affected in such a manner as to cause the con- 
traction of the small arteries of the skin. That the skin is much affected 
under the sense of great fear, we see in the marvellous manner in which 
perspiration immediately exudes from it. This exudation is all the more 
remarkable, as the surface is then cold, and hence the term, a cold sweat; 
whereas the sudorific glands are properly excited into action when the sur- 
face is heated. The hairs also on the skin stand erect, and the superficial 
muscles shiver. In connection with the disturbed action of the heart the 
breathing is hurried. The salivary glands act imperfectly; the mouth be- 
comes dry and is often opened and shut. I have also noticed that under 
slight fear there is strong tendency to yawn. One of the best marked 
symptoms is the trembling of all the muscles of the body; and this is often 
first seen in the lips. From this cause, and from the dryness of the mouth, 
the voice becomes husky or indistinct or may altogether fail. "Obstupui 
steteruntque comae, et vox faucibus hsesit." .... As fear increases 
into an agony of terror, we behold, as under all violent emotions, diversi- 

the chest, and that it consists in a soreness, hardly to be called pain, felt in 
the middle of the breast and due to an unpleasant resistance which is 
offered to the movements of inspiration, and sets a limit to their extent. 
The insufficiency of the diaphragm is obtruded upon consciousness, and 
we try by the aid of the external voluntary chest-muscles to draw a deeper 
breath. [This is the sigh.] If we fail, the unpleasantness of the situation 
is increased, for then to our mental distress is added the corporeally re- 
pugnant feeling of lack of air, a slight degree of suffocation. If, on the 
contrary, the outer muscles overcome the resistance of the inner ones, 
the oppressed breast is lightened. We think we speak symbolically when 
we speak of a stone weighing on our heart, or of a burden rolled from off 
our breast. But really we only express the exact fact for we should have to 
raise the entire weight of the atmosphere (about 820 kilog.) at each inspi- 
ration, if the air did not balance it by streaming into our lungs' ' (p . 55) . It 
must not be forgotten that an inhibition of the inspiratory centre similar 
to that produced by exciting the superior laryngeal nerve may possibly 
play a part in these phenomena. For a very interesting discussion of 
the respiratory difficulty and its connection with anxiety and fear see 
"A Case of Hydrophobia/' by the lamented Thomas B. Curtis in the 
Boston Med. and Surg. Journal, November 7 and 14, 1878, and remarks 
thereon by James J. Putnam, ilid, November 21. 



98 WILLIAM JAMES 

fied results. The heart beats wildly or must fail to act and faintness 
ensues; there is a death-like pallor; the breathing is labored; the wings of 
the nostrils are widely dilated; there is a gasping and convulsive motion 
of the lips, a tremor on the hollow cheek, a gulping and catching of the 
throat; the uncovered and protruding eyeballs are fixed on the object of 
terror; or they may roll restlessly from side to side, hue illuc volens oculos 
totumque pererraL The pupils are said to be enormously dilated. All the 
muscles of the body may become rigid or may be thrown into convulsive 
movements. The hands are alternately clenched and opened, often with 
a twitching movement. The arms may be protruded as if to avert some 
dreadful danger, or may be thrown wildly over the head. The Rev. Mr. 
Hagenauer has seen this latter action in a terrified Australian. In other 
cases there is a sudden and uncontrollable tendency to headlong flight; 
and so strong is this that the boldest soldiers may be seized with a sudden 
panic. 4 

Finally take Hatred, and read the synopsis of its possible effects 
as given by Sig. Mantegazza: 5 

Withdrawal of the head backwards, withdrawal of the trunk; projec- 
tion forwards of the hands, as if to defend one's self against the hated 
object; contraction or closure of the eyes; elevation of the upper lip and 
closure of the nose, these are all elementary movements of turning away. 
Next threatening movements, as: intense frowning; eyes wide open; 
display of teeth; grinding teeth and contracting jaws; opened mouth with 
tongue advanced; clenched fists; threatening action of arms; stamping with 
the feet; deep inspirations panting; growling and various cries; automatic 
repetition of one word or syllable; sudden weakness and trembling of 
voice; spitting. Finally, various miscellaneous reactions and vaso-motor 
symptoms: general trembling; convulsions of lips and facial muscles, of 
limbs and of trunk; acts of violence to one's self, as biting fist or nails; 
sardonic laughter; bright redness of face; sudden pallor of face; extreme 
dilatation of nostrils; standing up of hair on head. 

Were we to go through the whole list of emotions which have 
been named by men, and study their organic manifestations, we 
should but ring the changes on the elements which these three 
typical cases involve. Rigidity of this muscle, relaxation of that, 
constriction of arteries here, dilatation -there, breathing of this 
sort or that, pulse slowing or quickening, this gland secreting and 
that one dry, etc., etc. We should, moreover, find that our de- 
scriptions had no absolute truth; that they only applied to the 

^Origin of the Emotions, Darwin, pp. 290-2 

6 La Physionomie et I' Expression des Sentiments (Paris, 1885), p. 140. 



THE EMOTIONS 99 

average man; that every one of us, almost, has some personal 
idiosyncrasy of expression, laughing or sobbing differently from 
his neighbor, or reddening or growing pale where others do not. 
We should find a like variation in the objects which excite emotion 
in different persons. Jokes at which one explodes with laughter 
nauseate another, and seem blasphemous to a third; and occa- 
sions which overwhelm me with fear or bashfulness are just what 
give you the full sense of ease and power. The internal shadings of 
emotional feeling, moreover, merge endlessly into each other. 
Language has discriminated some of them, as hatred, antipathy, 
animosity, dislike, aversion, malice, spite, vengefulness, abhor- 
rence, etc., etc.; but in the dictionaries of synonyms we find these 
feelings distinguished more by their severally appropriate objective 
stimuli than by their conscious or subjective tone. 

The result of all this flux is that the merely descriptive literature 
of the emotions is one of the most tedious parts of psychology. 
And not only is it tedious, but you feel that its subdivisions are to 
a great extent either fictitious or unimportant, and that its pre- 
tences to accuracy are a sham. But unfortunately there is little 
psychological writing about the emotions which is not merely 
descriptive. As emotions are described in novels, they interest 
us, for we are made to share them. We have grown acquainted 
with the concrete objects and emergencies which call them forth 
and any knowing touch of introspection which may grace the page 
meets with a quick and feeling response. Confessedly literary 
works of aphoristic philosophy also flash lights into our emotional 
life, and give us a fitful delight. But as far as "scientific psy- 
chology" of the emotions goes, I may have been surfeited by too 
much reading of classic works on the subject, but I should as lief 
read verbal descriptions of the shapes of the rocks on a New Hamp- 
shire farm as toil through them again. They give one nowhere a 
central point of view, or a deductive or generative principle. 
They distinguish and refine and specify in infinitum without ever 
getting on to another logical level. Whereas the beauty of all 
truly scientific work is to get to ever deeper levels. Is there no 
way out from this level of individual description in the case of the 
emotions? I believe there is a way out, but I fear that few will 
take it. 



100 WILLIAM JAMES 

The trouble with the emotions in psychology is that they are 
regarded too much as absolutely individual things. So long as 
they are set down as so many eternal and sacred psychic entities, 
like the old immutable species in natural history, so long all that 
can be done with them is reverently to catalogue their separate 
characters, points, and effects. But if we regard them as prod- 
ucts of more general causes (as "species" are now regarded 
as products of heredity and variation), the mere distinguishing 
and cataloguing becomes of subsidiary importance. Having the 
goose which lays the golden eggs, the description of each egg 
already laid is a minor matter. Now the general causes of the 
emotions are indubitably physiological. Prof. C. Lange, of Copen- 
hagen, in the pamphlet from which I have already quoted, pub- 
lished in 1885 a physiological theory of their constitution and 
conditioning, which I had already broached the previous year in 
an article in Mind. Ifone of the criticisms which I have heard 
of it have made me doubt its essential truth. I will therefore 
devote the next few pages to explaining what it is* I shall limit 
myself in the first instance to what may be called the coarser emo- 
tions, grief, fear, rage, love, in which every one recognizes a 
strong organic reverberation, and afterwards speak of the subtler 
emotions, or of those whose organic reverberation is less obvious 
and strong. 

EMOTION FOLLOWS UPON THE BODILY EXPRESSION IN THE 
COABSEB EMOTIONS AT LEAST 

Our natural way of thinking about these coarser emotions is 
that the mental perception of some fact excites the mental affec- 
tion called the emotion, and that this latter state of mind gives 
rise to the bodily expression. My theory, on the contrary, is 
that the lodily changes follow directly the perception of the exciting 
fact, and that our feeling of the same changes as they occur is the 
emotion. Common-sense says, we lose our fortune, are sorry and 
weep; we meet a bear, are frightened and run; we are insulted by 
a rival, are angry and strike. The hypothesis here to be defended 
says that this order of sequence is incorrect, that the one mental 
state is not immediately induced by the other, that the bodily 
manifestations must first be interposed between, and that the more 



THE EMOTIONS 101 

rational statement is that we feel sorry because we cry, angry be- 
cause we strike, afraid because we tremble, and not that we cry, 
strike, or tremble, because we are sorry, angry, or fearful, as the 
case may be. Without the bodily states following on the percep- 
tion, the latter would be purely cognitive in form, pale, colorless, 
destitute of emotional warmth. We might then see the bear, 
and judge it best to run, receive the insult and deem it right to 
strike, but we should not actually jeel afraid or angry. 

Stated in this crude way, the hypothesis is pretty sure to meet 
with immediate disbelief. And yet neither many nor far-fetched 
considerations are required to mitigate its paradoxical character, 
and possibly to produce conviction of its truth. 

To begin with, no reader of the last two chapters* will be inclined 
to doubt the fact that objects do excite bodily changes by a preor- 
ganized mechanism, or the farther fact that the changes are so 
indefinitely numerous and subtle that the entire organism may be 
called a sounding-board, which every change of consciousness, 
however slight, may make reverberate. The various permuta- 
tions and combinations of which these organic activities are sus- 
ceptible make it abstractly possible that no shade of emotion, 
however slight, should be without a bodily reverberation as unique, 
when taken in its totality, as is the mental mood itself. The 
immense number of parts modified in each emotion is what makes 
it so difficult for us to reproduce in cold blood the total and inte- 
gral expression of any one of them. We may catch the trick with 
the voluntary muscles, but fail with the skin, glands, heart, and 
other viscera. Just as an artificially imitated sneeze lacks some* 
thing of the reality, so the attempt to imitate an emotion in the 
absence of its normal instigating cause is apt to be rather "hollow." 

The next thing to be noticed is this, that every one of the bodily 
changes, whatsoever it be, is FELT, acutely or obscurely, the moment 
it occurs. If the reader has never paid attention to this matter, 
he will be both interested and astonished to learn how many 
different local bodily feelings he can detect in himself as charac- 
teristic of his various emotional moods. It would be perhaps too 
much to expect him to arrest the tide of any strong gust of pas- 

* The chapters on The Production of Movement and on Instinct are 
in the Principles. [EcLl 



102 WILLIAM JAMES 

sion for the sake of any such curious analysis as this; but he can 
observe more tranquil states, and that may be assumed here to 
be true of the greater which is shown to be true of the less. 
Our whole cubic capacity is sensibly alive; and each morsel 
of it contributes its pulsations of feeling, dim or sharp, pleas- 
ant, painful, or dubious, to that sense of personality that 
every one of us unfailingly carries with him. It is surprising 
what little items give accent to these complexes of sensibility. 
When worried by any slight trouble; one may find that the focus 
of one's bodily consciousness is the contraction, often quite incon- 
siderable, of the eyes and brows. When momentarily embarrassed, 
it is something in the pharynx that compels either a swallow, 
a clearing of the throat, or a slight cough; and so on for as many 
more instances as might be named. Our concern here being with 
the general view rather than with the details, I will not linger to 
discuss these, but, assuming the point admitted that every change 
that occurs must be felt, I will pass on. 

I now proceed to urge the vital point of my whole theory, which 
is this: // we fancy some strong emotion, and then try to abstract 
from our consciousness of it all the feelings of its "bodily symptoms, 
we find we have nothing left behind, no "mind-stuff" out of which 
the emotion can be constituted, and that a cold and neutral state 
of intellectual perception is all that remains. It is true that, 
although most people when asked say that their introspection ver- 
ifies this statement, some persist in saying theirs does not. Many 
cannot be made to understand the question. When you beg them 
to imagine away every feeling of laughter and of tendency to laugh 
from their consciousness of the ludicrousness of an object, and then 
to tell you what the feeling of its ludicrousness would be like, 
whether it be anything more than the perception that the object 
belongs fc to the class "funny," they persist in replying that the 
thing proposed is a physical impossibility, and that they always 
must laugh if they see a funny object. Of course the task pro- 
posed is not the practical one of seeing a ludicrous object and anni- 
hilating one's tendency to laugh. It is the purely speculative 
one of subtracting certain elements of feeling from an emotional 
state supposed to exist in its fulness, and saying what the residual 
elements are. I cannot help thinking that all who rightly appre- 



THE EMOTIONS 103 

hend this problem will agree with the proposition above laid down. 
What kind of an emotion of fear would be left if the feeling neither 
of quickened heart-beats nor of shallow breathing, neither of 
trembling lips nor of weakened limbs, neither of goose-flesh nor 
of visceral stirrings, were present, it is quite impossible for me to 
think. Can one fancy the state of rage and picture no ebullition 
in the chest, no flushing of the face, no dilatation of the nostrils, 
no clenching of the teeth, no impulse to vigorous action, but in 
their stead limp muscles, calm breathing, and a placid face? The 
present writer, for one, certainly cannot. The rage is as com- 
pletely evaporated as the sensation of its so-called manifestations, 
and the only thing that can possibly be supposed to take its place 
is some cold-blooded and dispassionate judicial sentence, confined 
entirely to the intellectual realm, to the effect that a certain 
person or persons merit chastisement for their sins. In like 
manner of grief: what would it be without its tears, its sobs, its 
suffocation of the heart, its pang in the breast-bone? A feeling- 
less cognition that certain circumstances are deplorable, and noth- 
ing more. Every passion in turn tells the same story. A purely 
disembodied human emotion is a nonentity. I do not say that it 
is a contradiction in the nature of things, or that pure spirits are 
necessarily condemned to cold intellectual lives; but I say that for 
us, emotion dissociated from all bodily feeling is inconceivable. 
The more, closely I scrutinize my states, the more persuaded I 
become that whatever moods, affections," and passions I have are 
in very truth constituted by, and made up of, those bodily changes 
which we ordinarily call their expression or consequence; and the 
more it seems to me that if I were to become corporeally anaes- 
thetic, I should be excluded from the life of the affections, harsh 
and tender alike, and drag out an existence of merely cognitive 
or intellectual form. Such an existence, although it seems to 
have been the ideal of ancient sages, is too apathetic to be keenly 
sought after by those born after the revival of the worship of 
sensibility, a few generations ago. 

Let not this view be called materialistic. It is neither more nor 
less materialistic than any other view which says that our emo- 
tions are conditioned by nervous processes. No reader of this 
book is likely to rebel against such a saying so long as it is ex- 



104 WILLIAM JAMES 

pressed in general terms; and if any one still finds materialism in 
the thesis now defended, that must be because of the special pro- 
cesses invoked. They are sensational processes, processes due to 
inward currents set up by physical happenings. Such processes 
have, it is true, always been regarded by the platonizers in 
psychology as having something peculiarly base about them. 
But our emotions must always be inwardly what they are, 
whatever be the physiological ground of their apparition. If 
they are deep, pure, worthy, spiritual facts on any conceivable 
theory of their physiological source, they remain no less deep, 
pure, spiritual, and worthy of regard on this present sensational 
theory. They carry their own inner measure of worth with them; 
and it is just as logical to use the present theory of the emotions 
for proving that sensational processes need not be vile and ma- 
terial, as to use their vileness and materiality as a proof that such 
a theory cannot be true. 

If such a theory is true, then each emotion is the resultant of a 
sum of elements, and each element is caused by a physiological 
process of a sort already well known. The elements are all organic 
changes, and each of them is the reflex effect of the exciting object. 
Definite questions now immediately arise questions very dif- 
ferent from those which were the only possible ones without this 
view. Those were questions of classification: "Which are the 
proper genera of emotion, and which the species under each?" or 
of description: "By what expression is each emotion charac- 
terized?" The questions now are caudal: "Just what changes does 
this object and what changes does that object excite?" and "How 
come they to excite these particular changes and not others?" 
We step from a superficial to a deep order of inquiry. Classifi- 
cation and description are the lowest stage of science. They sink 
into the background the moment questions of genesis are formu- 
lated, and remain important only so far as they facilitate our 
answering these. Now the moment the genesis of an emotion is 
accounted for, as the arousal by an object of a lot of reflex acts 
which are forthwith felt, we immediately see why there is no limit 
to the number of possible different emotions which may exist, and why 
the emotions of different individuals may vary indefinitely) both as to 
their constitution and as to objects which call them forth. For 



THE EMOTIONS 105 

there is nothing sacramental or eternally fixed in reflex action. 
Any sort of reflex effect is possible, and reflexes actually vary 
indefinitely, as we know. 

We have all seen men dumb, instead of talkative, with joy; we have 
seen fright drive the blood into the head of its victim, instead of making 
him pale; we have seen grief run restlessly about lamenting, instead of 
sitting bowed down and mute; etc., etc.; and this naturally enough, for one 
and the same cause can work differently on different men's blood-vessels 
(since these do not always react alike), whilst moreover the impulse on its 
way through the brain to the vaso-motor centre is differently influenced 
by different earlier impressions in the form of recollections or associations 
of ideas. 8 

In short, any classification of the emotions is seen to be as true and 
as "natural" as any other, if it only serves some purpose; and such 
a question as "What is the 'real' or 'typical' expression of anger, 
or fear?" is seen to have no objective meaning at all. Instead 
of it we now have the question as to how any given "expres- 
sion" of anger or fear may have come to exist; and that is a real 
question of physiological mechanics on the one hand, and of 
history on the other, which (like all real questions) is in essence 
answerable, although the answer may be hard to find. On a later 
page I shall mention the attempts to answer it which have been 
made. 

DIFFICULTY OF TESTING THE THEORY EXPERIMENTALLY 

I have thus fairly propounded what seems to me the most 
fruitful way of conceiving of the emotions. It must be admitted 
that it is so far only a hypothesis, only possibly a true conception, 
and that much is lacking to its definitive proof. The only way 
coercively to disprove it, however, would be to take some emotion, 
and then exhibit qualities of feeling in it which should be demon- 
strdbly additional to all those which could possibly be derived 
from the organs affected at the time. But to detect with cer- 
tainty such purely spiritual qualities of feeling would obviously 
be a task beyond human power. We have, as Professor Lange 
says,|absolutely no immediate criterion by which to distinguish 

6 Lange, op. cit., p, 75. 



106 WILLIAM JAMES 

between spiritual and corporeal feelings; and, I may add, the more 
we sharpen our introspection, the more localized all our qualities 
of feeling become and the more difficult the discrimination conse- 
quently grows. 7 

A positive proof of the theory would, on the other hand, be 
given if we could find a subject absolutely anaesthetic inside and 
out, but not paralytic, so that emotion-inspiring objects might 
evoke the usual bodily expressions from him, but who, on being 
consulted, should say that no subjective emotional affection was 
felt. Such a man would be like one who, because he eats, appears 
to bystanders to be hungry, but who afterwards confesses that he 
had no appetite at all. Cases like this are extremely hard to 
find. Medical literature contains reports, so far as I know, of 
but three. In the famous one of Remigius Leins no mention is 
made by the reporters of his emotional condition. In Dr^ G. 
Winter's case 8 the patient is said to be inert and phlegmatic, but 
no particular attention, as I learn from Dr. W., was paid to his 
psychic condition. In the extraordinary case reported by Pro- 
fessor Strumpell (to which I must refer later in another connec- 
tion) 9 we read that the patient, a shoemaker's apprentice of fifteen, 
entirely anaesthetic, inside and out, with the exception of one eye 
and one ear, had shown shame on the occasion of soiling his bed, 
and grief, when a formerly favorite dish was set before him, at 
the thought that he could no longer taste its flavor. Dr. Strum- 
pell is also kind enough to inform me that he manifested surprise, 
fear, and anger on certain occasions. In observing him, however, 
no such theory as the present one seems to have been thought of; 
and it always remains possible that, just as he satisfied his natural 
appetites and necessities in cold blood, with no inward feeling, so 
his emotional expressions may have been accompanied by a quite 

7 Professor Hoffding, in his excellent treatise on Psychology, admits 
(p. 432) the mixture of bodily sensation with purely spiritual affection 
in the emotions. He does not, however, discuss the difficulties of discern- 
ing the spiritual affection (nor even show that he has fairly considered 
them) in his contention that it exists. 

B Ein Fall von allgemeiner Anaesthesie (Heidelberg, 1882). 

'Ziemssen's Deutsches Archiv fur klinische Medicin, xxii, 321. 



THE EMOTIONS 107 

cold heart. 10 Any new case which turns up of generalized anaes- 
thesia ought to be carefully examined as to the inward emotional 
sensibility as distinct from the "expressions" of emotion which 
circumstances may bring forth. 

Objections considered 

Let me now notice a few objections. The replies will make the 
theory still more plausible. 

First objection. There is no real evidence, it may be said, for the 
assumption that particular perceptions do produce wide-spread 
bodily effects by a sort of immediate physical influence, antecedent 
to the arousal of an emotion or emotional idea? 

Reply. There is most assuredly such evidence. In listening to 
poetry, drama, or lieroic narrative we are often surprised at the 
cutaneous shiver which like a sudden wave flows over us, and at 
the heart-swelling and the lachrymal effusion that unexpectedly 

10 The not very uncommon cases of hysterical hemiansesthesia are not 
complete enough to be utilized in this inquiry. Moreover, the recent re- 
searches, of which some account was given in Chapter IV, tend to show 
that hysterical anaesthesia is not a real absence of sensibility, but a "disso- 
ciation," as M. Pierre Janet calls it, or splitting-off of certain sensations 
from the rest of the person's consciousness, this rest forming the self which 
remains connected with the ordinary organs of expression. The split- 
off consciousness forms a secondary self; and M. Janet writes me that he 
sees no reasons why sensations whose "dissociation" from the body of 
consciousness makes the patient practically anaesthetic, might not, never- 
theless, contribute to the emotional life of the patient. They do still con- 
tribute to the function of locomotion; for in his patient L. there was no 
a taxia in spite of the anaesthesia . M . Janet writes me, a prop os of his anaes- 
thetic patient L., that she seemed to "suffer by hallucination." "I have 
often pricked or burned her without warning, and when she did not see 
me. She never moved, and evidently perceived nothing. But if after- 
wards in her movements she caught sight of her wounded arm, and saw 
on her skin a little drop of blood resulting from a slight cut, she would be- 
gin to cry out and lament as if she suffered a great deal. 'My blood flows,' 
she said one day; 'I must be suffering a great deal.' She suffered by hal- 
lucination. This sort of suffering is very general in hysterics. It is enough 
for them to receive the slightest hint of a modification in their body, when 
their imagination fills up the rest and invents changes that were not felt." 
See the remarks published at a later date in Janet's Automatisme Psycho- 
logique, pp. 214r-15. 



108 WILLIAM JAMES 

catch us at intervals. In listening to music the same is even more 
strikingly true. If we abruptly see a dark moving form in the 
woods, our heart stops beating, and we catch our breath instantly 
and before any articulate idea of danger can arise. If our friend 
goes near to the edge of a precipice, we get the well-known feeling 
of "all-overishness," and we shrink back, although we positively 
know him to be safe, and have no distinct imagination of his fall. 
The writer well remembers his astonishment, when a boy of seven 
or eight, at fainting when he saw a horse bled. The blood was in 
a bucket, with a stick in it, and, if memory does not deceive him, 
he stirred it round and saw it drip from the stick with no feeling 
save that of childish curiosity. Suddenly the world grew black 
before his eyes, his ears began to buzz, and he knew no more. He 
had never heard of the sight of blood producing faintness or sick- 
ness, and he had so little repugnance to it, and so little apprehen- 
sion of any other sort of danger from it, that even at that tender 
age, as he well remembers, he could not help wondering how the 
mere physical presence of a pailful of crimson fluid could occasion 
in him such formidable bodily effects. 
Professor Lange writes: 

N"o one has ever thought of separating the emotion produced by an 
unusually loud sound from the true inward affections. No one hesitates to 
call it a sort of fright, and it shows the ordinary signs of fright. And yet 
it is by no means combined with the idea of danger, or in anyway occasioned 
by associations, memories, or other mental processes. The phenomena 
of fright follow the noise immediately without a trace of " spiritual" 
fear. Many men can never grow used to standing beside a cannon when it 
is fired off, although they perfectly know that there is danger neither for 
themselves nor for others the bare sound is too much for them.. 11 

Imagine two steel knife-blades with their keen edges crossing 
each other at right angles, and moving to and fro. Our whole 
nervous organization is "on-edge" at the thought; and yet what 
emotion can be there except the unpleasant nervous feeling itself, 
or the dread that more of it may come? The entire fund and 
capital of the emotion here is the senseless bodily effect which the 
blades immediately arouse. This case is typical of a class: where 
an ideal emotion seems to precede the bodily symptoms, it is 

p. eft., p. 63. 



THE EMOTIONS 109 

often nothing but an anticipation of the symptoms themselves. 
One who has already fainted at the sight of blood may witness the 
preparations for a surgical operation with uncontrollable heart- 
sinking and anxiety. He anticipates certain feelings, and the 
anticipation precipitates their arrival. In cases of morbid terror 
the subjects often confess that what possesses them seems, more 
than anything, to be fear of the fear itself. In the various forms 
of what Professor Bain calls " tender emotion," although the ap- 
propriate object must usually be directly contemplated before the 
emotion can be aroused, yet sometimes thinking of the symptoms 
of the emotion itself may have the same effect. In sentimental 
natures the thought of "yearning" will produce real "yearning." 
And, not to speak of coarser examples, a mother's imagination of 
the caresses she bestows on her child may arouse a spasm of 
parental longing. 

In such cases as these we see plainly how the emotion both 
begins and ends with what we call its effects or manifestations. 
It has no mental status except as either the vivid feeling of the 
manifestations, or the idea of them; and the latter thus constitute 
its entire material, and sum and substance. And these cases ought 
to make us see how in all cases the feeling of the manifestations 
may play a much deeper part in the constitution of the emotion 
than we are wont to suppose. 

The best proof that the immediate cause of emotion is a physical 
effect on the nerves is furnished by those pathological cases in 
which the emotion is objectless. One of the chief merits, in fact, 
of the view which I propose seems to be that we can so easily 
formulate by its means pathological cases and normal cases under 
a common scheme. In every asylum we find examples of abso- 
lutely unmotived fear, anger, melancholy, or conceit; and others of 
an equally unmotived apathy which persists in spite of the best of 
outward reasons why it should give way. In the former cases we 
must suppose the nervous machinery to be so "labile" in some one 
emotional direction that almost every stimulus (however inappro- 
priate) causes it to upset in that way, and to engender the partic- 
ular complex of feelings of which the psychic body of the emotion 
consists. Thus, to take one special instance, if inability to draw 



110 WILLIAM JAMES 

deep breath, fluttering of the heart, and that peculiar epigastric 
change felt as "precordial anxiety," with an irresistible tendency 
to take a somewhat crouching attitude and to sit still, and with 
perhaps other visceral processes not now known, all spontaneously 
occur together in a certain person; his feeling of their combination 
is the emotion of dread, and he is the victim of what is known as 
morbid fear. A friend who has had occasional attacks of this 
most distressing of all maladies tells me that in his case the whole 
drama seems to centre about the region of the heart and respira- 
tory apparatus, that his main effort during the attacks is to get 
control of his inspirations and to slow his heart, and that the mo- 
ment he attains to breathing deeply and to holding himself erect, 
the dread, ipso facto, seems to depart. 12 

The emotion here is nothing but the feeling of a bodily state, 
and it has a purely bodily cause. 

All physicians who have been much engaged in general practice have seen 
cases of dyspepsia in which constant low spirits and occasional attacks of 
terror rendered the patient's condition pitiable in the extreme. I have 
observed these cases often, and have watched them closely, and I have 
never seen greater stiff ering of any kind than I have witnessed during these 

attacks Thus, a man is suffering from what we call nervous 

dyspepsia. Some day, we will suppose in the middle of the afternoon, 
without any warning or visible cause, one of these attacks of terror comes 
on. The first thing the man feels is great but vague discomfort. Then 
he notices that his heart is beating much too violently. At the same tune 
shocks or flashes as of electrical discharges, so violent as to be almost pain- 
ful, pass one after another through his body and limbs. Then in a few 
minutes he falls into a condition of the most intense fear. He is not afraid 

12 It must be confessed that there are cases of morbid fear in which 
objectively the heart is not much perturbed. These, however, fail to 
prove anything against our theory, for it is of course possible that the 
cortical centres normally percipient of dread as a complex of cardiac and 
other organic sensations due to real bodily change, should become pri- 
marily excited in brain-disease, and give rise to an hallucination of the 
changes being there, an hallucination of dread, consequently, coexistent 
with a comparatively calm pulse, etc. I say it is possible, for I am ignorant 
of observations which might test the fact. Trance, ecstasy, etc., offer an- 
alogous examples, not to speak of ordinary dreaming. Under all these 
conditions one may have the liveliest subjective feelings, either of eye or 
ear, or of the more visceral and emotional sort, as a result of pure nerve- 
central activity, and yet, as I believe, with complete peripheral repose. 



THE EMOTIONS 111 

of anything; he is simply afraid. His mind is perfectly clear. He looks 
for a cause of his wretched condition, but sees none. Presently his terror 
is such that he trembles violently and utters low moans; his body is damp 
with perspiration; his mouth is perfectly dry; and at this stage there are 
no tears in his eyes, though his suffering is intense. When the climax to 
the attack is reached and passed, there is a copious flow of tears, or else a 
mental condition in which the person weeps upon the least provocation. 
At this stage a large quantity of pale urine is passed. Then the heart's 
action becomes again normal, and the attack passes off. 13 

Again: 

There are outbreaks of rage so groundless and unbridled that all must 
admit them to be expressions of disease. For the medical layman hardly 
anything can be more instructive than the observation of such a patholo- 
gical attack of rage, especially when it presents itself pure and unmixed 
with other psychical disturbances. This happens in that rather rare dis- 
ease named transitory mania. The patient predisposed to this^other- 
wise an entirely reasonable person will be attacked suddenly without 
the slightest outward provocation, and thrown (to use the words of the 
latest writer on the subject, 0. Schwartzer, Die transitorische Tobsucht, 
Wien, 1880), "into a paroxysm of the wildest rage, with a fearful and blindly 
furious impulse to do violence and destroy." He flies at those about him; 
strikes, kicks, and throttles whomever he can catch; dashes every object 
about which he can lay his hands on; breaks and crushes what is near him; 
tears his clothes, shouts, howls, and roars, with eyes that flash and roll, 
and shows meanwhile all those symptoms of vaso-motor congestion which 
we have learned to know as the concomitants of anger. His face is red, 
swollen, his cheeks hot, his eyes protuberant and their whites bloodshot, 
the heart beats violently, the pulse marks 100-120 strokes a minute. The 
arteries of the neck are full and pulsating, the veins are swollen, the saliva 
flows. The fit lasts only a few hours, and ends suddenly with a sleep of 
from 8 to 12 hours, on waking from which the patient has entirely forgot- 
ten what has happened. 14 

In these (outwardly) causeless emotional conditions the partic- 
ular paths which are explosive are discharged by any and every 
incoming sensation. Just as, when we are seasick, every smell, 
every taste, every sound, every sight, every movement, every 
sensible experience whatever, augments our nausea, so the morbid 
terror or anger is increased by each and every sensation which 
stirs up the nerve-centres. Absolute quiet is the only treatment 

"R. M. Bucke: Man's Moral Nature (N. Y., 1879), p. 97. 
14 Lange, op. cit., p. 61. 



112 WILLIAM JAMES 

for the time. It seems impossible not to admit that in all this 
the bodily condition takes the lead, and that the mental emotion 
follows. The intellect may, in fact, be so little affected as to play 
the cold-blooded spectator all the while, and note the absence of a 
real object for the emotion. 16 

A few words from Henle may close my reply to this 
first objection: 

Does it not seem as if the excitations of the bodily nerves met the ideas 
half way, in order to raise the latter to the height of emotions? [Note 
how justly this expresses our theory!] That they do so is proved by the 
cases in which particular nerves, when specially irritable, share in the 
emotion and determine its quality. When one is suffering from an open 
wound, any grievous or horrid spectacle will cause pain in the wound. In 
sufferers from heart-disease there is developed a psychic excitability, which 
is often incomprehensible to the patients themselves, but which comes 
from the heart's liability to palpitate. I said that the very quality of the 
emotion is determined by the organs disposed to participate in it. Just 
as surely as a dark foreboding, rightly grounded on interference from the 
constellations, will be accompanied by a feeling of oppression in the chest, 
so surely will a similar feeling of oppression, when due to disease of the 
thoracic organs, be accompanied by groundless forebodings. So small a 
thing as a bubble of air rising from the stomach through the oesophagus, 
and loitering on its way a few minutes and exerting pressure on the heart, 
is able during sleep to occasion a nightmare, and during waking to produce 
a vague anxiety. On the other hand, we see that joyous thoughts dilate 
our blood-vessels, and that a suitable quantity of wine, because it dilates 
the vessels, also disposes us to joyous thoughts. If both the jest and the 

18 1 am inclined to think that in some hysterif orm conditions of grief, 
rage, etc., the visceral disturbances are less strong than those which go to 
outward expression. We have then a tremendous verbal display with a 
hollow inside. Whilst the bystanders are wrung with compassion, or pale 
with alarm, the subject all the while lets himself go, but feels his insincerity, 
and wonders how long he can keep up the performance. The attacks 
are often surprisingly sudden in their onset. The treatment here is to 
intimidate the patient by a stronger will. Take out your temper, if he 
takes out his "Nay, if thou'lt mouth, I'll rant as well as thou." These 
are the cases of apparently great bodily manifestation with comparatively 
little real subjective emotion, which may be used to throw discredit on the 
theory advanced in the text. It is probable that the visceral manifesta- 
tions in these cases are quite disproportionately slight, compared with 
those of the vocal organs. The subject's state is somewhat similar to that 
of an actor who does not feel his part. 



THE EMOTIONS 113 

wine work together, they supplement each other in producing the emotional 
effect, and our demands on the jest are the more modest in proportion as 
the wine takes upon itself a larger part of the task. 16 

Second objection. If our theory be true, a necessary corollary 
of it ought to be this: that any voluntary and cold-blooded arousal 
of the so-called manifestations of a special emotion ought to give 
us the emotion itself. Now this (the objection says) is not found 
to be the case. An actor can perfectly simulate an emotion and 
yet be inwardly cold; and we can all pretend to cry and not feel 
grief; and feign laughter without being amused. 

Reply. In the majority of emotions this test is inapplicable; 
for many of the manifestations are in organs over which we have 
no voluntary control. Few people in pretending to cry can shed 
real tears, for example. But, within the limits in which it can be 
verified, experience corroborates rather than disproves the corol- 
lary from our theory, upon which the present objection rests. 
Every one knows how panic is increased by flight, and how the 
giving way to the symptoms of grief or anger increases those pas- 
sions themselves. Each fit of sobbing makes the sorrow more 
acute, and calls forth another fit stronger still until at last repose 
only ensues with lassitude and with the apparent exhaustion of 
the machinery. In rage, it is notorious how we "work ourselves 
up" to a climax by repeated outbreaks of expression. Refuse to 
express a passion, and it dies. Count ten before venting your 
anger, and its occasion seems ridiculous. Whistling to keep up 
courage is no mere figure of speech. On the other hand, sit all day 
in a moping posture, sigh, and reply to everything with a dismal 
voice, and your melancholy lingers. There is no more valuable 
precept in moral education than this, as all who have experience 
know: if we wish to conquer undesirable emotional tendencies 
in ourselves, we must assiduously, and in the first instance cold- 
bloodedly, go through the outward movements of those contrary- 
dispositions which we prefer to cultivate. The reward of persist- 
ency will infallibly come, in the fading out of the sullenness or 
depression, and the advent of real cheerfulness and kindliness in 

16 Op. tit., p. 72. Lange lays great stress on the neurotic drugs, as part 
of his proof that influences of a physical nature upon the body are the 
first thing in order in the production of emotions. 



114 WILLIAM JAMES 

their stead. Smooth the brow, brighten the eye, contract the 
dorsal rather than the ventral aspect of the frame, and speak in 
a major key, pass the genial compliment, and your heart must be 
frigid indeed if it do not gradually thaw! 

This is recognized by all psychologists, only they fail to see its 
full import. Professor Bain writes, for example: 

We find that a feeble [emotional] wave ... is suspended inwardly 
by being arrested outwardly; the currents of the brain and the agitation of 
the centres die away if the external vent is resisted at every point. It 
is by such restraint that we are in the habit of suppressing pity, anger, fear, 
pride on many trifling occasions. If so, it is a fact that the suppression 
of the actual movements has a tendency to suppress the nervous currents 
that incite them, so that the external quiescence is followed by the internal. 
The effect would not happen in any case; if there were not some dependence 

of the cerebral wave upon the free outward vent or manifestation 

By the same interposition we may summon up a dormant feeling. By 
acting out the external manifestations, we gradually infect the nerves 
leading to them, and finally waken up the diffusive current by a sort of 
action db extra. . . . Thus it is that we are sometimes able to assume 
a cheerful tone of mind by forcing a hilarious expression. 17 

We have a mass of other testimony of similar effect. Burke, 
in his treatise on The Sublime and Beautiful, writes as follows of 
the physiognomist Campanella: 

This man, it seems, had not only made very accurate observations on 
human faces, but was expert in mimicking such as were in any way re- 
markable. When he had a mind to penetrate into the inclinations of those 
he had to deal with, he composed his face, his gesture, and his whole body, 
as nearly as he could, into the exact similitude of the person he intended to 
examine; and then carefully observed what turn of mind he seemed to ac- 
quire by the change. So that, says my author, he was able to enter into 
the dispositions and thoughts of people as effectually as if he had been 
changed into the very men. I have often observed [Burke now goes on 
in his own person] that, on mimicking the looks and gestures of angry, or 
placid, or frightened, or daring men, I have involuntarily found my mind 
turned to that passion whose appearance I strove to imitate; nay, I am con- 
vinced it is hard to avoid it, though one strove to separate the passion from 
its corresponding gestures. 18 

17 Emotions and Will, pp. 361-2. 

"Quoted by Dugald Stewart, Elements, etc. (Hamilton's ed.), Ill, 140. 
Fechner (Vorschule der Aesthetik, 156) says almost the same thing of him- 



THE EMOTIONS 115 

Against this it is to be said that many actors who perfectly 
mimic the outward appearances of emotion in face, gait, and voice 
declare that they feel no emotion at all. Others, however accord- 
ing to Mr. Wm. Archer, who has made a very instructive statistical 
inquiry among them, say that the emotion of the part masters 
them whenever they play it well. 19 Thus: 

"I often turn pale," writes Miss Isabel Bateman, "in scenes of terror or 
great excitement. I have been told this many times, and I can feel myself 
getting very cold and shivering and pale in thrilling situations." "When 
I am playing rage or terror," writes Mr. Lionel Brough, "I believe I do turn 
pale. My mouth gets dry, my tongue cleaves to my palate. In Bob Acres, 
for instance (in the last act), I have to continually moisten my mouth, or 
I shall become inarticulate. I have to 'swallow the lump/ as I call it." 
All artists who have had much experience of emotional parts are absolutely 
unanimous "Playing with the brain," says Miss Alma Mur- 
ray, "is far less fatiguing than playing with the heart. An adventuress 
taxes the physique far less than a sympathetic heroine. Muscular ex- 
ertion has comparatively little to do with it." . . . "Emotion while 
acting," writes Mr. Howe, "will induce perspiration much more than physi- 
cal exertion. I always perspired profusely while acting Joseph Surface, 
which requires little or no exertion." .... "I suffer from fatigue," 
writes Mr. Forbes Robertson, "in proportion to the amount of emotion 
I may have been called upon to go through, and not from physical ex- 
ertion." .... "Though I have played Othello," writes Mr. Cole- 
man, "ever since I was seventeen (at nineteen I had the honor of acting the 
Moor to Macready's lago), husband my resources as I may, this is the one 
part, the part of parts, which always leaves me physically prostrate. I 
have never been able to find a pigment that would stay on my face, though 
I have tried every preparation in existence. Even the titanic Edwin 
Forrest told me that he was always knocked over in Othello, and I have 
heard Charles Kean, Phelps, Brooke, Dillion, say the same thing. On the 
other hand, I have frequently acted Richard III without turning a hair." 20 

self: "One may find by one's own observation that the imitation of the 
bodily expression of a mental condition makes us understand it much 
better than the merely looking on. . . . When I walk behind some one 
whom I do not know, and imitate as accurately as possible his gait and 
carriage, I get the most curious impression of feeling as the person himself 
must feel. To go tripping and mincing after the fashion of a young woman 
puts one, so to speak, in a femine mood of mind." 

19 "The Anatomy of Acting," in Longman Magazine, vol. xi, pp. 266, 
375, 498 (1888), since republished in book form. 

20 Page 394. 



116 WILLIAM JAMBS 

The explanation for the discrepancy amongst actors is probably 
that which, these quotations suggest. The visceral and organic 
part of the expression can be suppressed in some men, but not in 
others, and on this it is probable that the chief part of the felt 
emotion depends. Coquelin and the other actors who are in- 
wardly cold are probably able to affect the dissociation in a com- 
plete way. Prof. Sikorsky of Kieff has contributed an important 
article on the facial expression of the insane to the Neurologischcs 
Centralblatt for 1887. Having practised facial mimicry himself 
a great deal, he says: 

When I contract my facial muscles in any mimetic combination, I 
feel no emotional excitement, so that the mimicry is in the fullest sense of 
the word artificial, although quite irreproachable from the expressive point 
of view, 21 

We find, however, from the context that Professor S.'s practice 
before the mirror has developed in him such a virtuosity in the 
control of his facial muscles that he can entirely disregard their 
natural association and contract them in any order of grouping, 
on either side of the face isolatedly, and each one alone. Probably 
in him the facial mimicry is an entirely restricted and localized 
thing, without sympathetic changes of any sort elsewhere. 

Third objection. Manifesting an emotion, so far from increasing 
it, makes it cease. Rage evaporates after a good outburst; it is 
pent-up emotions that "work like madness in the brain." 
"'Reply. The objection fails to discriminate between what is felt 
during and what is felt after the manifestation. During the mani- 
festation the emotion is always felt. In the normal course of 
things this, being the natural channel of discharge, exhausts the 
nerve-centres, and emotional calm ensues. But if tears or anger 
are simply suppressed, whilst the object of grief or rage remains 
unchanged before the mind, the current which would have invaded 
the normal channels turns into others, for it must find some outlet 
of escape. It may then work different and worse effects later on. 
Thus vengeful brooding may replace a burst of indignation; a dry 
heat may consume the frame of one who fain would weep, or he 
may, as Dante says, turn to stone within; and then tears or a 

"Page 496. 



THE EMOTIONS 117 

storming fit may bring a grateful relief. This is when the current 
is strong enough to strike into a pathological path when the normal 
one is dammed. When this is so, an immediate outpour may be 
best. But here, to quote Professor Bain again: 

There is nothing more implied than the fact that an emotion may be 
too strong to be resisted, and we only waste our strength in the endeavor. 
If we are really able to stem the torrent, there is no more reason for 
refraining from the attempt than in the case of weaker feelings. And 
undoubtedly the habitual control of the emotions is not to be attained 
without a systematic restraint, extended to weak and strong. 

When we teach children to repress their emotional talk and dis- 
play, it is not that they may feel more quite the reverse. It is 
that they may think more; for, to a certain extent, whatever cur- 
rents are diverted from the regions below must swell the activity 
of the thought-tracts of the brain. In apoplexies and other brain 
injuries we get the opposite condition an obstruction, namely, 
to the passage of currents among the thought-tracts, and with 
this an increased tendency of objects to start downward currents 
into the organs of the body. The consequence is tears, laughter, 
and temper-fits, on the most insignificant provocation, accom- 
panying a proportional feebleness in logical thought and the power 
of volitional attention and decision, just the sort of thing from 
which we try to wean our child. It is true that we say of certain 
persons that "they would feel more if they expressed Jess." And 
in another class of persons the explosive energy with which passion 
manifests itself on critical occasions seems correlated with the 
way in which they bottle it up during the intervals. But these 
are only eccentric types of character, and within each type the 
law of the last paragraph prevails. The sentimentalist is so con- 
structed that "gushing" is his or her normal mode of expression. 
Putting a stopper on the "gush" will only to a limited extent 
cause more "real" activities to take its place; in the main it will 
simply produce listlessness. On the other hand, the ponderous 
and bilious "slumbering volcano," let him repress the expression 
of his passions as he will, will find them expire if they get no vent 
at all; whilst if the rare occasions multiply which he deems worthy 
of their outbreak, he will find them grow in intensity as life pro- 
ceeds. On the whole, I cannot see that this third objection carries 
any weight. 



118 WILLIAM JAMBS 

If our hypothesis is true, it makes us realize more deeply than 
ever how much our mental life is knit up with our corporeal frame, 
in the strictest sense of the term. Rapture, love, ambition, 
indignation, and pride, considered as feelings, are fruits of the same 
soil with the grossest bodily sensations of pleasure and of pain. 
But the reader will remember that we agreed at the outset to 
affirm this only of what we then called the "coarser" emotions, 
and that those inward states of emotional sensibility which ap- 
peared devoid at first sight of bodily results should be left out of 
our account. We must now say a word or two about these latter 
feelings, the "subtler" emotions, as we then agreed to call them. 

STJBTLER EMOTIONS 

These are the moral, intellectual, and aesthetic feelings. Con- 
cords of sounds, of colors, of lines, logical consistencies, teleological 
fitnesses, affect us with a pleasure that seems ingrained in the 
very form of the representation itself, and to borrow nothing from 
any reverberation surging up from the parts below the brain. 
The Herbartian psychologists have distinguished feelings due to 
the form in which ideas may be arranged. A mathematical dem- 
onstration may be as "pretty," and an act of justice as "neat," 
as a drawing or a tune, although the prettiness and neatness seem 
to have nothing to do with sensation. We have, then, or some of 
us seem to have, genuinely cerebral forms of pleasure and dis- 
pleasure, apparently not agreeing in their mode of production 
with the "coarser" emotions we have been analyzing. And it is 
certain that readers whom our reasons have hitherto failed to con- 
vince will now start up at this admission, and consider that by 
it we give up our whole case. Since musical perceptions, since 
logical ideas, can immediately arouse a form of emotional feeling, 
they will say, is it not more natural to suppose that in the case of 
the so-called "coarser" emotions, prompted by other kinds of 
objects, the emotional feeling is equally immediate, and the 
bodily expression something that comes later and is added on? 

In reply to this we must immediately insist that aesthetic 
emotion, pure and simple, the pleasure given us by certain lines 
and masses, and combinations of colors and sounds, is an abso- 
lutely sensational experience, an optical or auricular feeling that 



THE EMOTIONS 119 

is primary, and not due to the repercussion backwards of other 
sensations elsewhere consecutively aroused. To this simple pri- 
mary and immediate pleasure in certain pure sensations and har- 
monious combinations of them, there may, it is true, be added 
secondary pleasures; and in the practical enjoyment of works of 
art by the masses of mankind these secondary pleasures play a 
great part. The more classic one's taste is, however, the less 
relatively important are the secondary pleasures felt to be in 
comparison with those of the primary sensation as it comes 
in. 22 Classicism and romanticism have their battles over this 
point. Complex suggestiveness, the awakening of vistas of mem- 
ory and association, and the stirring of our flesh with pictu- 
resque mystery and gloom, make a work of art romantic. The classic 
taste brands these effects as coarse and tawdry, and prefers the 
naked beauty of the optical and auditory sensations, unadorned 
with frippery or foliage. To the romantic mind, on the contrary, 
the immediate beauty of these sensations seems dry and thin. I 
am of course not discussing which view is right, but only showing 
that the discrimination between the primary feeling of beauty, as 
a pure incoming sensible quality, and the secondary emotions 
which are grafted thereupon, is one that must be made. 

These secondary emotions themselves are assuredly for the most 
part constituted of other incoming sensations aroused by the 
diffusive wave of reflex effects which the beautiful object sets up. 
A glow, a pang in the breast, a shudder, a fulness of the breathing, 
a flutter of the heart, a shiver down the back, a moistening of the 

22 Even the feelings of the lower senses may have this secondary escort, 
due to the arousing of associational trains which reverberate. A flavor 
may fairly shake us by the ghosts of " banquet halls deserted/' which it 
suddenly calls up; or a smell may make us feel almost sick with the waft it 
brings over our memory of ''gardens that are ruins, and pleasure-houses 
that are dust . " "In the Pyrenees, ' ; says M . Guyau, ' ' after a summer-day's 
tramp carried to the extreme of fatigue, I met a shepherd and asked him for 
some milk. He went to fetch from his hut, under which a brook ran, a jar 
of milk plunged in the water and kept at a coldness which was almost 
icy. In drinking this fresh milk into which all the mountain had put its 
perfume, and of which each savory swallow seemed to give new life, I cer- 
tainly experienced a series of feelings which the word agreeable is insufficient 
to designate. It was like a pastoral symphony, apprehended by the taste 



120 WILLIAM JAMES 

eyes, a stirring in the hypogastrium, and a thousand unnamable 
symptoms besides, may be felt the moment the beauty excites us. 
And these symptoms also result when we are excited by moral 
perceptions, as of pathos, magnanimity, or courage. The voice 
breaks and the sob rises in the struggling chest, or the nostril 
dilates and the fingers tighten, whilst the heart beats, etc., etc. 

As far as these ingredients of the subtler emotions go, then the 
latter form no exception to our account, but rather an additional 
illustration thereof. In all cases of intellectual or moral rapture 
we find that, unless there be coupled a bodily reverberation of 
some kind with the mere thought of the object and cognition of 
its quality; unless we actually laugh at the neatness of the demon- 
stration or witticism; unless we thrill at the case of justice, or 
tingle at the act of magnanimity; our state of mind can hardly 
be called emotional at all. It is in fact a mere intellectual per- 
ception of how certain things are to be called neat, right, witty, 
generous, and the like. Such a judicial state of mind as this is 
to be classed among awarenesses of truth; it is a cognitive act. As 
a matter of fact, however, the moral and intellectual cognitions 

instead of by the ear" (quoted by F. Paulhan from "Les Problkmes de 
I'JSsth&ique Contemporaine, p. 63). Compare the dithyrambic about 
whiskey of Col. R. Ingersoll, to which the presidential campaign of 1888 
gave such notoriety: "I send you some of the most wonderful whiskey 
that ever drove the skeleton from a feast or painted landscapes in the brain 
of man. It is the mingled souls of wheat and corn. In it you will find the 
sunshine and shadow that chase each other over the billowy fields, the 
breath of June, the carol of the lark, the dews of the night, the wealth of 
summer, and autumn's rich content all golden with imprisoned light. 
Drink it, and you will hear the voice of men and maidens singing the 'Har- 
vest Home/ mingled with the laughter of children. Drink it, and you 
will feel within your blood the star-lit dawns, the dreamy, tawny dusks 
of many perfect days. For forty years this liquid joy has been within the 
happy staves of oak, longing to touch the lips of man." It is in this way 
that I should reply to Mr. Gurney's criticism on my theory. My "view," 
this writer says (Mind, ix, 425), "goes far to confound the two things which 
in my opinion it is the prime necessity of musical psychology to distinguish 
the effect chiefly sensuous of mere streams or masses of finely colored 
sound, and the distinctive musical emotion to which the form of a sequence 
of sound, its melodic and harmonic individuality, even realized in com- 
plete silence, is the vital and essential object. It is with the former of 
these two very different things that the physical reactions,, the stirring of 
the hair the tingling and the shiver are by far most markedly connected. 



THE EMOTIONS 121 

hardly ever do exist thus unaccompanied. The bodily sounding- 
board is at work, as careful introspection will show, far more than 
we usually suppose. Still, where long familiarity with a certain 
class of effects, even aesthetic ones, has blunted mere emotional 
excitability as much as it has sharpened taste and judgment, we 
do get the intellectual emotion, if such it can be called, pure and 
undefiled. And the dryness of it, the paleness, the absence of all 
glow, as it may exist in a thoroughly expert critic's mind, not only 
shows us what an altogether different thing it is from the " coarser" 
emotions we considered first, but makes us suspect that almost 
the entire difference lies in the fact that the bodily sounding- 
board, vibrating in the one case, is in the other mute. "Not so 
very bad" is, in a person of consummate taste, apt to be the high- 
est limit of approving expression. "Rien ne me choque" is said 
to have been Chopin's superlative of praise of new music. A 
sentimental layman would feel, and ought to feel, horrified, on 
being admitted into such a critic's mind, to see how cold, how 
thin, how void of human significance, are the motives for favor or 
disfavor that there prevail. The capacity to make a nice spot 

. . . . If I may speak of myself, there is plenty of music from which I 
have received as much emotion in silent representation as when presented 
by the finest orchestra; but it is with the latter condition that I almost 
exclusively associate the cutaneous tingling and hair-stirring. But to 
call my enjoyment of the form, of the note-after-notensss of a melody, a mere 
critical 'judgement of right* [see below, p. 472] would really be to deny to 
me the power of expressing a fact of simple and intimate expression in 

English. It is quint essentially emotion Now there are 

hundreds of other bits of music . . . which I judge to be right without 
receiving an iota of the emotion. For purposes of emotion they are to me 
like geometrical demonstrations or like acts of integrity performed in 
Peru." The Beethoven-rightness of which Gurney then goes on to speak, 
as something different from the Clementi-rightness (even when the respec- 
tive pieces are only heard in idea), is probably a purely auditory-sensational 
thing. The Clementi-rightness also ; only, for reasons impossible to assign, 
the dementi form does not give the same sort of purely auditory satis- 
faction as the Beethoven form, and might better be described perhaps nega- 
tively as non-wrong, i.e., free from positively unpleasant acoustic quality. 
In organizations as musical as Mr. Gurney's, purely acoustic form gives so 
intense a degree of sensible pleasure that the lower bodily reverberation 
is of no account. But I repeat that I see nothing in the facts which Mr. 
Gurney cites, to lead one to believe in an emotion divorced from sensa- 
tional processes of any kind. 



122 WILLIAM JAMES 

on the wall will outweigh a picture's whole content; a foolish trick 
of words will preserve a poem; an utterly meaningless fitness of 
sequence in one musical composition set at naught any amount 
of "expressiveness" in another. 

I remember seeing an English couple sit for more than an hour 
on a piercing February day in the Academy at Venice before the 
celebrated "Assumption" by Titian; and when I, after being 
chased from room to room by the cold, concluded to get into the 
sunshine as fast as possible and let the pictures go, but before 
leaving drew reverently near to them to learn with what superior 
forms of susceptibility they might be endowed, all I overheard was 
the woman's voice murmuring: "What a deprecatory expression 
her face wears! What self-abne^a&'on! How unworthy she feels 
of the honor she is receiving!" Their honest hearts had been 
kept warm all the time by a glow of spurious sentiment that would 
have fairly made old Titian sick. Mr. Ruskin somewhere makes 
the (for "him terrible) admission that religious people as a rule 
care little for pictures, and that when they do care for them they 
generally prefer the worst ones to the best. Yes! in every art, 
in every science, there is the keen perception of certain relations 
being right or not, and there is the emotional flush and thrill con- 
sequent thereupon. And these are two things, not one. In the 
former of them it is that experts and masters are at home. The 
latter accompaniments are bodily commotions that they may hard- 
ly feel, but that may be experienced in their fulness by cretins and 
Philistines in whom the critical judgment is at its lowest ebb. 
The "marvels" of Science, about which so much edifying popular 
literature is written, are apt to be "caviare" to the men in the 
laboratories. And even divine Philosophy itself, which common 
mortals consider so "sublime" an occupation, on account of 
the vastness of its data and outlook, is too apt to the practical 
philosopher himself to be but a sharpening and tightening busi- 
ness, a matter of "points," of screwing down things, of split- 
ting hairs, and of the "intent" rather than the "extent" of 
conceptions. Very little emotion here! except the effort of 
setting the attention fine, and the feeling of ease and relief (mainly 
in the breathing apparatus) when the inconsistencies are overcome 
and the thoughts run smoothly for a while. Emotion and cogni- 



THE EMOTIONS 123 

tion seem then parted even in this last retreat; and cerebral pro- 
cesses are almost feelingless, so far as we can judge, until they 
summon help from parts below. 

NO SPECIAL BKAIN-CENTRES FOB EMOTION 

If the neural process underlying emotional consciousness be 
what I have now sought to prove it, the physiology of the brain be- 
comes a simpler matter than has been hitherto supposed. Sensa- 
tional, associational, and motor elements are all that the organ 
need contain. The physiologists who, during the past few years, 
have been so industriously exploring the brain's functions, have 
limited their explanations to its cognitive and volitional perform- 
ances. Dividing the brain division into sensory and motor 
centres, they have found their division to be exactly paralleled by 
the analysis made by empirical psychology of the perceptive and 
volitional parts of the mind into their simplest elements. But 
the emotions have been so ignored in all these researches that one 
is tempted to suppose that if these investigators were asked for a 
theory of them in brain-terms, they would have to reply, either 
that they had as yet bestowed no thought upon the subject, or 
that they had found it so difficult to make distinct hypotheses 
that the matter lay among the problems of the future, only to be 
taken up after the simpler ones of the present should have been 
definitively solved. 

And yet it is even now certain that of two things concerning the 
emotions, one must be true. Either separate and special centres, 
affected to them alone, are their brain-seat, or else they correspond 
to processes occurring in the motor and sensory centres already 
assigned, or in others like them, not yet known. If the former be 
the case, we must deny the view that is current, and hold the 
cortex to be something more than the surface of "projection" for 
every sensitive spot and every muscle in the body. If the latter 
be the case, we must ask whether the emotional process in the 
sensory or motor centre be an altogether peculiar one, or whether 
it resembles the ordinary perceptive processes of which those cen- 
tres are already recognized to be the seat. Now if the theory I 
have defended be true, the latter alternative is all that it demands. 



124 WILLIAH JAMES 

Supposing the cortex to contain parts, liable to be excited by 
changes in each special sense-organ, in each portion of the skin, 
in each muscle, each joint, and each viscus, and to contain abso- 
lutely nothing else, we still have a scheme capable of representing 
the process of the emotions. An object falls on a sense-organ, 
affects a cortical part, and is perceived; or else the latter, excited 
inwardly, gives rise to an idea of the same object. Quick as a 
flash, the reflex currents pass down through their preordained 
channels, alter the condition of muscle, skin, and viscus; and 
these alterations, perceived, like the original object, in as many 
portions of the cortex, combine with it in consciousness and trans- 
form it from an object-simply-apprehended into an object-emo- 
tionally-felt. No new principles have to be invoked, nothing 
postulated beyond the ordinary reflex circuits, and the local 
centres admitted in one shape or another by all to exist. 

EMOTIONAL DIFFERENCES BETWEEN INDIVIDUALS 

The revivdbility in memory of the emotions, like that of all the 
feelings of the lower senses, is very small. We can remember 
that we underwent grief or rapture, but not just how the grief 
or rapture felt. This difficult ideal revivability is, however, 
more than compensated in the case of the emotions by a very 
easy actual revivability. That is, we can produce, not remem- 
brances of the old grief or rapture, but new griefs and raptures, 
by summoning up a lively thought of their exciting cause. The 
cause is now only an idea, but this idea produces the same organic 
irradiations, or almost the same, which were produced by its 
original, so that the emotion is again a reality. We have "recap- 
tured" it. Shame, love, and anger are particularly liable to be 
thus revived by ideas of their object. Professor Bain admits 23 
that "in their strict character of emotion proper, they [the emo- 
tions] have the minimum of revivability; but being always incor- 
porated with the sensations of the higher senses, they share in 
the superior revivability of sights and sounds." But he fails to 
point out that the revived sights and sounds may be ideal without 
ceasing to be distinct; whilst the emotion, to be distinct, must 

23 In his chapter on "Ideal Emotion/' to which the reader is referred for 
farther details on this subject. 



THE EMOTIONS 125 

become real again. Professor Bain seems to forget that an 
" ideal emotion" and a real emotion prompted by an ideal object 
are two very different things. 

An emotional temperament on the one hand, and a lively imagina- 
tion for objects and circumstances on the other, are thus the conditions, 
necessary and sufficient, for an abundant emotional life. No matter 
how emotional the temperament may be, if the imagination be 
poor, the occasions for touching off the emotional trains will fail 
to be realized, and the life will be pro tanto cold and dry. This 
is perhaps a reason why it may be better that a man of thought 
should not have too strong a visualizing power. He is less likely 
to have his trains of meditation disturbed by emotional interrup- 
tions. It will be remembered that Mr. Galton found the members 
of the Royal Society and of the French Academy of Sciences to be 
below par in visualizing power. If I may speak of myself, I am 
far less able to visualize now, at the age of 46, than in my earlier 
years; and I am strongly inclined to believe that the relative slug- 
gishness of my emotional life at present is quite as much connected 
with this fact as it is with the invading torpor of hoary eld, or 
with the omnibus-horse routine of settled professional and do- 
mestic life. I say this because I occasionally have a flash of the 
old stronger visual imagery, and I notice that the emotional com- 
mentary, so to call it, is then liable to become much more acute 
that is its present wont. Charcot's patient, whose case is given 
in Progrds Medical, 21 juillet, complained of his incapacity for 
emotional feeling after his optical images were gone. His mother's 
death, which in former times would have wrung his heart, left him 
quite cold; largely as he himself suggests, because he could form 
no definite visual image of the event, and of the effect of the loss 
on the rest of the family at home. 

One final generality about the emotions remains to be noted: 
They blunt themselves by repetition more rapidly than any other sort 
of feeling. This is due not only to the general law of ' ' accommoda- 
tion" to their stimulus which we saw to obtain of all feelings what- 
ever, but to the peculiar fact that the " diffusive wave" of reflex 
effects tends always to become more narrow. It seems as if it were 
essentially meant to be a provisional arrangement, on the basis 
of which precise and determinate reactions might arise. The more 



126 WILLIAM JAMES 

we exercise ourselves at anything, the fewer muscles we employ; 
and just so, the oftener we meet an object, the more definitely we 
think and behave about it; and the less is the organic perturbation 
to which it gives rise. The first time we saw it we could perhaps 
neither act nor think at all, and had no reaction but organic 
perturbation. The emotions of startled surprise, wonder, or 
curiosity were the result. Now we look on with absolutely no 
emotion. 24 This tendency to economy in the nerve-paths through 
which our sensations and ideas discharge, is the basis of all growth 
in efficiency, readiness, and skill. Where would the general, 
the surgeon, the presiding chairman, be, if their nerve-currents 
kept running down into their viscera, instead of keeping up amid 
their convolutions? But what they gain for practice by this law, 
they lose, it must be confessed, for feeling. For the world-worn 
and experienced man, the sense of pleasure which he gets from the 
free and powerful flow of thoughts, overcoming obstacles as they 
arise, is the only compensation for that freshness of the heart 
which he once enjoyed. This free and powerful flow means that 
brain-paths of association and memory have more and more 
organized themselves in him, and that through them the stimulus 
is drafted off into nerves which lead merely to the writing finger or 
the speaking tongue. 25 The trains of intellectual association, the 

2 *Those feelings which Professor Bain calls "emotions of relativity," 
excitement of novelty, wonder, rapture of freedom, sense of power, hardly 
survive any repetition of the experience. But as the text goes on to ex- 
plain, and as Goethe as quoted by Prof. Hoffding says, this is because "the 
soul is inwardly grown larger without knowing it, and can no longer be 
filled by that first sensation. The man thinks that he has lost, but really 
he has gained. What he has lost in rapture, he has gained in inward 
growth." "It is," as Professor Eoffding himself adds, in a beautiful figure 
of speech, "with our virgin feelings, as with the first breath drawn by the 
new-born child, in which the lung expands itself so that it can never be 
emptied to the same degree again. JSTo later breath can feel just like that 
first one." On this whole subject of emotional blunting, compare Hoff- 
ding's Psychologic, vi. E., and Bain's Emotions and Will, chapter iv of the 
first part. 

25 M, Fr. Paulhan, in a little work full of accurate observations of detail 
(Les Phenomenes Affectifs et les Lois de leur Apparition), seems to me rather 
to turn the truth upside down by his formula that emotions are due to 
an inhibition of impulsive tendencies. One kind of emotion, namely, 



THE EMOTIONS 127 

memories, the logical relations, may, however, be voluminous in 
the extreme. Past emotions may be among the things remem- 
bered. The more of all these trains an object can set going in us, 
the richer our cognitive intimacy with it is. This cerebral sense 
of richness seems itself to be a source of pleasure, possibly even 
apart from the euphoria which from time to time comes up from 
respiratory organs. If there be such a thing as a purely spiritual 
emotion, I should be inclined to restrict it to this cerebral sense 
of abundance and ease, this feeling, as Sir W. Hamilton would 
call it, of unimpeded and not overstrained activity of thought. 
Under ordinary conditions, it is a fine and serene but not an ex- 
cited state of consciousness. In certain intoxications it becomes 
exciting, and it may be intensely exciting. I can hardly imagine 
a more frenzied excitement than that which goes with the con- 
sciousness of seeing absolute truth, which characterizes the coming 
to from nitrous-oxide drunkenness. Chloroform, ether, and alco- 
hol all produce this deepening sense of insight into truth; and with 
all of them it may be a "strong" emotion; but then there also 
come with it all sorts of strange bodily feelings and changes in the 
incoming sensibilities. I cannot see my way to affirming that 
the emotion is independent of these. I will concede, however, 
that if its independence is anywhere to be maintained, these 
theoretic raptures seem the place at which to begin the defence. 

THE GENESIS OF THE VARIOUS EMOTIONS 

On a former page (pp. 453^i) I said that two questions, and 
only two, are important, if we regard the emotions as constituted 
by feelings due to the diffusive wave. 

(1) What special diffusive effects do the various special objective 
and subjective experiences excite? and 

(2) How come they to excite them? 

uneasiness, annoyance, distress, does occur when any definite impulsive 
tendency is checked, and all of M. P.'s illustrations are drawn from this 
sort. The other emotions are themselves primary impulsive tendencies of 
a diffusive sort (involving, as M. P, rightly says, a multiplicity des phtno- 
mknes) ; and just in proportion as more and more of these multiple tenden- 
cies are checked, and replaced by some few narrow forms of discharge, 
does the original emotion tend to disappear. 



128 WILLIAM JAMES 

The works on physiognomy and expression are all of them at- 
tempts to answer question 1. As is but natural, the effects upon 
the face have received the most careful attention. The reader who 
wishes details additional to those given above on pp. 443-7 is 
referred to the works mentioned in the note below. 26 

As regards question 2, some little progress has of recent years 
been made in answering it. Two things are certain: 

a. The facial muscles of expression are not given us simply for 
expression's sake; 27 

6. Each muscle is not affected to some one emotion exclusively, 
as certain writers have thought. 

Some movements of expression can be accounted for as weakened 
repetitions of movements which formerly (when they were stronger) 
were of utility to the subject. Others are similarly weakened repeti- 
tions of movements which under other conditions were physio- 
logically necessary effects. Of the latter reactions the respiratory 
disturbances in anger and fear might be taken as examples 
organic reminiscences, as it were; reverberations in imagination 
of the blowings of the man making a series of combative efforts, 
of the pantings of one in precipitate flight. Such at least is a 
suggestion made by Mr. Spencer which has found approval. And 
he also was the first, so far as I know, to suggest that other move- 
ments in anger and fear could be explained by the nascent excita- 
tion of formerly useful acts. 

"To have in a slight degree," he says, "such psychical states as accompany 
the reception of wounds, and are experienced during flight, is to be in a state 
of what we call fear. And to have in a slight degree such psychical states as 
the processes of catching, killing, and eating imply, is to have the desires 

28 A list of the older writings on the subject is given in Mantegazza's 
work, La Physionomie et I' Expression, chap, i; others in Darwin's first 
chapter. Bell's Anatomy of Expression, Mosso's La Paura, Piderit's 
WissenschaftUches System der Mimik und Physiognomik, Duchenne's 
Me'canisme de la Physionomie Humaine, are besides Lange and Darwin, 
the most useful works with which I am acquainted. Compare also Sully: 
Sensation and Intuition, chap. n. 

27 One must remember, however, that just in so far forth as sexual selec- 
tion may have played a part in determining the human organism, selec- 
tion of expressive faces must have increased the average mobility of the 
human countenance. 



THE EMOTIONS 129 

to catch, kill, and eat. That the propensities to the acts are nothing else 
than nascent excitations of the psychical state involved in the acts, is 
proved by the natural language of the propensities. Fear, when strong, 
expresses itself in cries, in efforts to escape, in palpitations, in tremblings ; 
and these are just the manifestations that go along with an actual suffer- 
ing of the evil feared. The destructive passion is shown in a general 
tension of the muscular system, in gnashing of teeth and protrusion of the 
claws, in dilated eyes and nostrils, in growls; and these are weaker forms of 
the actions that accompany the killing of prey. To such objective evi- 
dences every one can add subjective evidences. Every one can testify that 
the psychical state called fear consists of mental representations of cer- 
tain painful results; and that the one called anger consists of mental repre- 
sentations of the actions and impressions which would occur while inflict- 
ing some kind of pain." 28 

About fear I shall have more to say presently. Meanwhile the 
principle of revival in weakened form of reactions useful in more 
violent dealings with the object inspiring the emotion has found 
many applications. So slight a symptom as the snarl or sneer, 
the one-sided uncovering of the upper teeth, is accounted for by 
Darwin as a survival from the time when our ancestors had large 
canines, and unfleshed them (as dogs now do) for attack. Simi- 
larly the raising of the eyebrows in outward attention, the opening 
of the mouth in astonishment, come, according to the same author, 
from the utility of these movements in extreme cases. The 
raising of the eyebrows goes with the opening of the eye for better 
vision; the opening of the mouth with the intensest listening, and 
with the rapid catching of the breath which precedes muscular 
effort. The distention of the nostrils in anger is interpreted by 
Spencer as an echo of the way in which our ancestors had to 
breathe when, during combat, their " mouth was filled up by a 
part of an antagonist's body that had been seized (!)." The 
trembling of fear is supposed by Mantegazza to be for the sake of 
warming the blood (!). The reddening of the face and neck is 
called by Wundt a compensatory arrangement for relieving the 
brain of the blood-pressure which the simultaneous excitement of 
the heart brings with it. The effusion of tears is explained both 
by this author and by Darwin to be a blood-withdrawing agency 
of a similar sort. The contraction of the muscles around the eyes, 

**PsychoL, 213. 



130 WILLIAM JAMES 

of which the primitive use is to protect those organs from being 
too much gorged with blood during the screaming fits of infancy, 
survives in adult life in the shape of the frown, which instantly 
comes over the brow when anything difficult or displeasing pre- 
sents itself either to thought or action. 

"As the habit of contracting the brows has been followed by infants 
during innumerable generations, at the commencement of every crying 
or screaming fit," says Darwin, "it has become firmly associated with the 
incipient sense of something distressing or disagreeable. Hence, under 
similar circumstances, it would be apt to be continued during maturity 
although never then developed, into a crying fit. Screaming or weeping 
begins to be voluntarily restrained at an early period of life, whereas frown- 
ing is hardly ever restrained at any age." 29 

The intermittent expirations which constitute laughter have, 
according to Dr. Hecker, the purpose of counteracting the anaemia 
of the brain, which he supposes to be brought about by the action 
of the joyous or comic stimulus upon the vaso-motor nerves. 30 A 
smile is the weak vestige of a laugh. The tight closure of the 
mouth in all effort is useful for retaining the air in the lungs so as 
to fix the chest and give a firm basis of insertion for the muscles 
of the flanks. Accordingly, we see the lips compress themselves 
upon every slight occasion of resolve. The blood-pressure has to 

29 Weeping in childhood is almost as regular a symptom of anger as it 
is of grief, which would account (on Darwin's principles) for the frown of 
anger, Mr. Spencer has an account of the angry frown as having arisen 
through the survival of the fittest, by its utility in keeping the sun out of 
one's eyes when engaged in mortal combat (!). (Principles of Psychology, 
ii. 546). Professor Mosso objects to any explanation of the frown by its 
utility for vision, that it is coupled, during emotional excitement, with a 
dilatation of the pupil which is very unfavorable for distinct vision, and 
that this ought to have been weeded out by natural selection, if natural 
selection had the power to fix the frown (see La Paura, chap, ix, vi). 
Unfortunately this very able author speaks as if all the emotions affected 
the pupil in the same way. Fear certainly does make it dilate. But 
Gratiolet is quoted by Darwin and others as saying that the pupils contract 
in anger. I have made no observations of my own on the point, and Mosso's 
earlier paper on the pupil (Turin, 1875) I have not seen. I must repeat, 
with Darwin, that we need more minute observations on this subject. 

Physiologic u. Psychologic des Lachens und des Komischen (Berlin, 
1873), pp. 13-15. 



THE EMOTIONS 131 

be high during the sexual embrace; hence the palpitations, and 
hence also the tendency to caressing action, which accompanies 
tender emotion in its fainter forms. Other examples might be 
given; but these are quite enough to show the scope of the principle 
of revival of useful action in weaker form. 

Another principle, to which Darwin perhaps hardly does suffi- 
cient justice, may be called .the principle of reacting similarly to 
analogous-feeling stimuli. There is a whole vocabulary of de- 
scriptive adjectives common to impressions belonging to different 
sensible spheres experiences of aU classes are sweet, impressions 
of all classes rich or solid, sensations of all classes sharp. Wundt 
and Piderit accordingly explain many of our most expressive 
reactions upon moral causes as symbolic gustatory movements. 
As soon as any experience arises which has an affinity with the 
feeling of sweet, or bitter, or sour, the same movements are 
executed which would result from the taste in point. 31 "All the 
states of mind which language designates by the metaphors bitter, 
harsh, sweet, combine themselves, therefore, with the correspond- 
ing mimetic movements of the mouth." Certainly the emotions 
of disgust and satisfaction do express themselves in this mimetic 
way. Disgust is an incipient regurgitation or retching, limiting 
its expression often to the grimace of the lips and nose; satisfaction 
goes with a sucking smile, or tasting motion of the lips. In 
Mantegazza's loose if learned work, the attempt is made, much 
less successfully, to bring in the eye and ear as additional sources 
of symbolically expressive reaction. The ordinary gesture of 
negation among us, moving the head about its axis from side to 
side is a reaction originally used by babies to keep disagreeables 
from getting into their mouth, and may be observed in perfection 
in any nursery, 32 It is now evoked where the stimulus is only an 

31 These movements are explained teleologically, in the first instance, 
by the efforts which the tongue is forced to make to adapt itself to the 
better perception or avoidance of the sapid body. (Of. Physiol. Psych., 
n, 423.) 

32 Professor Henle derives the negative wag of the head from an incipient 
shudder, and remarks how fortunate is the abbreviation, as when a lady 
declines a partner in the ballroom. The clapping of the hands for 



132 WILLIAM JAMES 

unwelcome idea. Similarly the nod forward in affirmation is 
after the analogy of taking food into the mouth. The connection 
of the expression of moral or social disdain or dislike, especially 
in women, with movements having a perfectly definite original 
olfactory function, is too obvious for comment. Winking is the 
effect of any threatening surprise, not only of what puts the eyes 
in danger; and a momentary aversion of the eyes is very apt to 
be one's first symptoms of response to an unexpectedly unwelcome 
proposition. These may suffice as examples of movements expres- 
sive from analogy. 

But if certain of our emotional reactions can be explained by 
the two principles invoked and the reader will himself have felt 
how conjectural and fallible in some of the instances the explana- 
tion is there remain many reactions which cannot so be explained 
at all, and these we must write down for the present as purely 
idiopathic effects of the stimulus. Amongst them are the effects 
on the viscera and internal glands, the dryness of the mouth and 
diarrhoea and nausea of fear, the liver-disturbances which sometimes 
produce jaundice after excessive rage, the urinary secretion of san- 
guine excitement, and the bladder-contraction of apprehension, the 
gaping of expectancy, the "lump in the throat" of grief, the 
tickling there and the swallowing of embarrassment, the "pre- 
cordial" anxiety" of dread, the changes in the pupil, the various 
sweatings of the skin, cold or hot, local or general, and its flushings, 
together with other symptoms which probably exist but are too 
hidden to have been noticed or named. It seems as if even the 
changes of blood-pressure and heart-beat during emotional excite- 
ment might, instead of being teleologically determined, prove to 
be purely mechanical or physiological outpourings through the 
easiest drainage-channels the pneumogastrics and sympathetic 
nerve?' happening under ordinary circumstances to be such 
channels. 

Mr. Spencer argues that the smallest muscles must be such 

applause he explains as a symbolic abridgment of an embrace. The pro- 
trusion of the lips (der prtifende Zug) which goes with all sorts of dubious 
and questioning states of mind is derived by Dr. Piderit from the tasting 
movement which we can see on any one's mouth when deciding whether a 
wine is good or not. 



THE EMOTIONS 133 

channels; and instances the tail in dogs, cats, and birds, the ears 
in horses, the crest in parrots, the face and fingers in man, as the 
first organs to be moved by emotional stimuli. 33 This principle 
(if it be one) would apply still more exactly to the muscles of the 
smaller arteries (though not exactly to the heart) ; whilst the great 
variability of the circulatory symptoms would also suggest that 
they are determined by causes into which utility does not enter. 
The quickening of the heart lends itself, it is true, rather easily 
to explanation by inherited habit, organic memory of more violent 
excitement; and Darwin speaks in favor of this view (see his 
Expression, etc., pp. 74-5). But, on the other hand, we have so 
many cases of reaction which are indisputably pathological, as 
we may say, and which could never be serviceable or derived from 
what was serviceable, that I think we should be cautious about 
pushing our explanations of the varied heart-beat too far in the 
teleological direction. Trembling, which is found in many excite- 
ments besides that of terror, is, pace Mr. Spencer and Sig. Mante- 
gazza, quite pathological. So are terror's other strong symptoms. 
Professor Mosso, as the total result of his study, writes as follows: 

We have seen that the graver the peril becomes, the more do the reac- 
tions which are positively harmful to the animal prevail in number and 
inefficacy. We already saw that the trembling and the palsy make it in- 
capable of flight or defense; we have also convinced ourselves that in the 
most decisive moments of danger we are less able to see [or to think] than 
when we are tranquil. In face of such facts we must admit that the phe- 
nomena of fear cannot all be accounted for by "selection." Their extreme 
degrees are morbid phenomena which show an imperfection in the organism. 
We might almost say that Nature had not been able to frame a substance 
which would be excitable enough to compose the brain and spinal marrow, 
and yet which should not be so excited by exceptional stimulation as to 
overstep in its reactions those physiological bounds which are useful to 
the conservation of the creature* 

83 Loc. cit. 497. Why a dog's face-muscles are not more mobile than 
they are Mr. Spencer fails to explain, as also why different stimuli should 
innervate these small muscles in such different ways, if easy drainage be 
the only principle involved. Charles Bell accounted for the special part 
played by the facial muscles in expression by their being accessory muscles 
of respiration, governed by nerves whose origin is close to the respiratory 
centre in the medulla oblongata. They are an adjuvant of voice, and like 
it their function is communication. (See BelPs Anatomy of Expression, 
Appendix by Alexander Shaw.) 



134 WILLIAM JAMES 

Professor Bain, if I mistake not, had long previously commented 
upon fear in a similar way. 

Mr. Darwin accounts for many emotional expressions by what 
he calls the principle of antithesis. In virtue of this principle, 
if a certain stimulus prompted a certain set of movements, then 
a contrary-feeling stimulus would prompt exactly the opposite 
movements, although these might otherwise have neither utility 
nor significance. It is in this wise that Darwin explains the 
expression of impotence, raised eyebrows, and shrugged shoulders, 
dropped arms and open palms, as being the antithesis of the 
frowning brow, the thrown-back shoulders and clenched fists of 
rage, which is the emotion of power. No doubt a certain 
number of movements can be formulated under this law; but 
whether it expresses a causal principle is more than doubtful. 
It has been by most critics considered the least successful of 
Darwin's speculations on this subject. 

To sum up, we see the reason for a few emotional reactions; 
for others a possible species of reason may be guessed; but others 
remain for which no plausible reason can even be conceived. 
These may be reactions which are purely mechanical results of the 
way in which our nervous centres are framed, reactions which, 
although permanent in us now, may be called accidental as far 
as their origin goes. In fact, in an organism as complex as the 
nervous system there must be many such reactions, incidental to 
others evolved for utility's sake, but which would never them- 
selves have been evolved independently, for any utility they 
might possess. Sea-sickness, the love of music, of the various 
intoxicants, nay, the entire aesthetic life of man, shall have to 
trace to this accidental origin. 34 It would be foolish to suppose 
that none of the reactions called emotional could have arisen in 
this grosi-accidental way. 

This is all I have to say about the emotions. If one should 
seek to name each particular one of them of which the human 
heart is the seat, it is plain that the limit to their number would 
lie in the introspective vocabulary of the seeker, each race of men 
having found names for some shade of feeling which other races 
have left undiscriminated. If then we should seek to break 

u La Paura, Appendice, p. 295. 



THE EMOTIONS 135 

the emotions, thus enumerated, into groups, according to their 
affinities, it is again plain that all sorts of groupings would be 
possible, according as we chose this character or that as a basis, 
and that all groupings would be equally real and true. The only 
question would be, does this grouping or that suit our purpose 
best? The reader may then class the emotions as he will, as sad 
or joyous, sthenic or asthenic, natural or acquired, inspired by 
animate or inanimate things, formal or material, sensuous or 
ideal, direct or reflective, egoistic or non-egoistic, retrospective, 
prospective or immediate, organismally or environmentally 
initiated, or what more besides. All these are divisions which 
have been actually proposed. Each of them has its merits, and 
each one brings together some emotions which the others keep 
apart. For a fuller account, and for other classificatory schemes, 
I refer to the Appendix to Bain's Emotions and the Will, and to 
Mercier's, Stanley's and Read's articles on the Emotions, in Mind, 
vols. ix, x, and xi. In vol. nc. p. 421 there is also an article by 
the lamented Edmund Gurney in criticism of the view which in 
this chapter I continue to defend.