Skip to main content

Full text of "Essays in legal history read before the International Congress of Historical Studies, held in London in 1913"

See other formats


ESSAYS   IN   LEGAL   HISTORY 


HUMPHREY  MILFORD 
PUBLISHER  TO  THE  UNIVERSITY  OF  OXFORD 


ESSAYS 

IN 

LEGAL  HISTORY 

READ  BEFORE  THE  INTERNATIONAL 

CONGRESS    OF    HISTORICAL   STUDIES 

HELD  IN  LONDON  IN  1913 


EDITED    BY 


PAUL  VINOGRADOFF,  F.B.A. 

CORPUS    PROFESSOR    OF    JURISPRUDENCE    IN    THE    UNIVERSITY    OF    OXFORD 
ACTING-PRESIDENT    OF    THE    SECTION    OF    LEGAL    HISTORY    OF    THE    CONGRESS 


OXFORD  UNIVERSITY  PRESS 

LONDON,  EDINBURGH,  GLASGOW 

NEW  YORK,  TORONTO,  MELBOURNE,  BOMBAY 


V  \ 


-.'n't 


INTRODUCTORY    NOTE 

THE  collection  of  papers  in  this  volume  consists  of  the  communi- 
cations made  to  the  Section  of  Legal  History  (Via)  of  the  Inter- 
national Congress  of  Historical  Studies  held  in  London  in  April  1913. 
All  the  papers  read  in  the  Section  have  been  kindly  contributed 
by  their  authors  for  this  publication.  In  some  cases,  where  the 
communications  actually  read  were  in  the  nature  of  extracts  from 
longer  treatises,  the  papers  have  been  reproduced  here  in  extenso. 
The  papers  of  Geheimrath  O.  von  Gierke  and  Dr.  A.  Lappo- 
Danilevskij  were  read  at  General  Meetings  of  the  Congress,  but 
were  written  for  the  Section  of  Legal  History,  and  naturally 
take  a  place  in  its  transactions.  The  essays  in  the  present  volume 
are  presented  in  a  different  order  from  that  in  which  they  followed 
each  other  at  the  Congress,  as  it  was  desirable  to  group  them  some- 
what more  systematically.  On  several  occasions  some  discussion 
followed  the  reading  of  the  papers,  but  it  proved  unnecessary  to 
publish  the  minutes  of  such  discussions,  as  most  of  the  principal 
points  were  afterwards  embodied  in  the  revised  texts  of  the 
communications. 

The  general  course  of  the  proceedings  in  the  Section  was  as 
follows : — 

Thursday,  April  3. — The  first  meeting  was  held  at  2  P.M.  in 
the  Old  Hall  of  Lincoln's  Inn,  which  was  kindly  lent  by  the 
Treasurer  (Mr.  Douglas  Walker,  K.C.)  and  the  Masters  of  the 
Bench  of  Lincoln's  Inn.  Sir  Frederick  Pollock,  on  behalf  of  the 
President,  Lord  Alverstone,  Lord  Chief  Justice  of  England,  who  was 
absent  through  ill  health,  welcomed  the  meeting.  The  Presidential 
Address  was  delivered  by  Professor  Vinogradoff,  Acting-President. 
Geheimrath  O.  von  Gierke  took  the  chair.  Papers  were  read  by 
Professor  Wenger  (No.  Ill  of  this  volume)  and  Professor  Galante 
(No.  XVIII). 

Friday,  April  4. — Professor  Vinogradoff  in  the  chair.  Papers 
by  Dr.  W.  Blake  Odgers,  K.C.  (No.  XII),  discussed  by  Professor 
Galante,  Mr.  Bolland,  Professor  Vinogradoff;  Dr.  H.  D.  Hazeltine 


vi  Introductory  Note 

(No.  XIII),  discussed  by  Professor  Vinogradoff ;  Dr.  W.  S.  Holds- 
worth  (No.  XV). 

Saturday,  April  5. — In  the  chair — Professor  Vinogradoff  in 
the  morning,  Professor  Fockema-Andreae  of  Ley  den  in  the 
afternoon.  Papers  by  Geheimrath  Lenel  (No.  V),  discussed  by 
Professor  Ehrlich  of  Czernowitz,  Professor  Goudy,  Professor 
Koschaher  of  Prague;  Professor  Riccobono  (No.  IV),  discussed 
by  Professor  Ehrlich,  Geheimrath  Lenel,  Professor  Galante, 
Geheimrath  von  Gierke ;  Professor  E.  C.  Clark  (No.  VI),  discussed 
by  Dr.  Strachan- Davidson  of  Oxford  and  Geheimrath  Lenel. 

Monday,  April  7. — In  the  chair — Sir  Courtenay  Ilbert  in  the 
morning,  Geheimrath  Lenel  in  the  afternoon.  Papers  by  Sir 
Frederick  Pollock  (No.  XIV),  discussed  by  Professor  Vinogradoff ; 
Professor  Goudy  (No.  XI),  discussed  by  Sir  Frederick  Pollock  and 
Professor  Astoul  of  Caen  ;  the  late  Professor  A.  Esmein x  (No.  X), 
read  in  the  absence  of  the  writer  by  Professor  Huvelin  of  Lyons ; 
Professor  Hiibner  (No.  XX),  discussed  by  Sir  Courtenay  Ilbert. 

Tuesday,  April  8. — Professor  Galante  in  the  chair.  Papers 
by  Professor  Schreuer  (No.  VII),  discussed  by  Professor  Fockema- 
Andreae,  Geheimrath  von  Gierke,  Professor  Hiibner,  Professor 
Huvelin  ;  Professor  Caillemer  (No.  IX),  read  in  the  absence  of 
the  writer  by  Professor  Astoul ;  Professor  Taranger  (No.  VIII) ; 
Dr.  W.  Konopczynski  (No.  XVII). 

Professor  Galante  from  the  chair  proposed  a  vote  of  thanks 
to  the  Acting-President,  Professor  Vinogradoff;  to  the  Vice-Presi- 
dents,  Sir  Frederick  Pollock  and  Sir  Courtenay  Ilbert ;  and  to  the 
Hon.  Secretaries,  Dr.  W.  S.  Holdsworth  and  Mr.  F.  de  Zulueta. 
Professors  Schreuer,  Huvelin,  and  Riccobono  having  spoken  in 
the  same  sense,  the  vote  was  unanimously  carried.  Sir  Frederick 
Pollock  and  Sir  Courtenay  Ilbert  returned  thanks. 

The  difficult  enterprise  of  publishing  a  polyglot  volume  of  this 
kind  has  only  been  rendered  possible  by  the  liberal  support  which 
the  Delegates  of  the  Oxford  University  Press  have  placed  at  the 
disposal  of  the  Section  of  Legal  History. 

1  While  these  sheets  were  in  the  press,  the  sad  news  arrived  of  the  death 
of  one  of  our  most  distinguished  contributors,  Professor  A  *  Esmein.  We  are 
indebted  to  his  son,  Monsieur  Paul  Esmein,  for  the  correction  of  the  proofs 
which  were  forwarded  to  his  late  father. 


TABLE    OF    CONTENTS 


I.  Welcome  to  the  Members  of  the  Legal  Section.     The  Right  Hon. 

Sir  FREDERICK  POLLOCK,  F.B.A.  i 

II.  Presidential  Address.     Professor  PAUL  VINOGRADOFF,  F.B.A., 

University  of  Oxford  .....  3 

III.   Die  heutigen  Aufgaben  einer  romischen  Rechtsgeschichte.      Pro- 
fessor L.  WENGER,  University  of  Munich    .  .  .13 
IV.   Dalla  Communio  del  diritto  quiritario  alia  comproprieta  moderna. 

Professor  S.  RiCCOBONO,  University  of  Palermo       .  .          33 

V.  Zur  Geschichte  der  Heredis  Institutio.     Geheimrath   Professor 

O.  LENEL,  University  of  Freiburg-im-Breisgau          .  .120 

VI.   Numismatic  Illustrations  of  the  History  of  Roman  Law.      Pro- 
fessor E.  C.  CLARK,  University  of  Cambridge  .  .143 
VII.   Cotter  und  Tote  als  Rechtssubjekte  bei  den  alten  Germanen. 

Professor  H.  SCHREUER,  University  of  Bonn  .  .        153 

VIII.  The   Meaning   of  the   Words    Oftal  and   Skeyting  in  the  Old 
Laws  of  Norway.     Professor  A.  TARANGER,   University  of 
Christiania  .  .  .  .  .  159 

IX.   Les   Idees   coutumieres    et   la    Renaissance   du   Droit    romain 
dans  le  Sud-Est  de  la  France.     Professor  R.  CAILLEMER, 
University  of  Grenoble        .  .  .  .  .174 

X.   La   Maxime  Princeps.  legibus  solutus  est  dans   1'ancien    Droit 
public  frangais.      By  the  late  Professor  A.  ESMEIN,  of  the 
Institute  of  France,  and  of  the  University  of  Paris   .  .        2oiy 

XI.  Two  Ancient   Brocards.      Professor  H.   GOUDY,    University  of 

Oxford        .  .  .  .  .  .  .215 

XII.  A  Sketch  of  the  History  of  the  Four  Inns  of  Court.  Dr. 
W.  BLAKE  ODGERS,  K.'C,  Director  of  Legal  Education  in 
the  Inns  of  Court,  London  .  .  .  -233 

XIII.  The  Early  History  of  English  Equity.     Dr.  H.  D.  HAZELTINE, 

Reader  in  the  University  of  Cambridge        .  «  '.•          .      (261) 

vii 


viii  Table  of  Contents 

XIV.  The     Transformation    of    Equity.        The     Right    Hon.     Sir 

FREDERICK  POLLOCK,  F.B.A.  .  .  .  .  (  286 

The  Influence  of  Coke  on  the  Development  of  English  Law. 

Dr.   W.    S.    HOLDSWORTH,   Reader  in   the   University   of 

Oxford      .......        297 

XVI.  Uber  die  Geschichte  des  Majoritatsprinzips.  Geheimrath 

Professor  Otto  von  GlERKE,  University  of  Berlin  .  .  312 

XVII.  Une  Antithese  du  Principe  majoritaire  en  Droit  polonais.  Dr. 

W.  KONOPCZYNSKI,  Decent  in  the  University  of  Cracow  .  336 
XVIII.  The  Modern  Study  of  Canon  Law.  Professor  ANDREA 

GALANTE,  of  the  Italian  Legal  Faculty  formerly  at  Innsbruck  348 
XIX.  L'Idee  de  1'Etat  et  son  Evolution  en  Russie  depuis  les 

Troubles  du  xvne   Siecle  jusqu'aux   Reformes  du   xvme. 

Dr.  A.  LAPPO-DANILEVSKIJ,  of  the  Imperial  Academy  of 

Sciences,  St.  Petersburg  .  .  .  .  356 

XX.  Der  Verfassungsentwurf  der  Siebzehn  Vertrauensmanner.  Ein 

Beitrag     zur     Geschichte     des     Frankfurter     Parlaments. 

Professor  R.  HUBNER,  University  of  Giessen         .  .       384 


I 

WELCOME   TO   THE    SECTION 

DELIVERED  BY 

SIR  FREDERICK  POLLOCK 

BY  the  Lord  Chief  Justice  of  England's  desire  I  have  to  inform  you 
that  to  his  great  regret,  a  regret  in  which  I  am  sure  every  one  here 
fully  concurs  for  our  sake  as  well  as  his,  ill  health  prevents  him 
from  carrying  out  his  intention  of  welcoming  the  Section  of  Legal 
History  and  delivering  the  inaugural  address.  I  am  charged  to 
bid  you  welcome  in  the  Chief  Justice's  name  and  as  his  deputy  ;  the 
inaugural  address  will  be  given  by  my  friend  Professor  Vinogradoff, 
who  is  specially  qualified  for  the  task  by  his  cosmopolitan  learning 
and  his  mastery  of  historical  and  comparative  jurisprudence. 

As  one  of  the  delegates  to  this  Congress  of  the  Honourable 
Society  of  Lincoln's  Inn,  in  whose  Old  Hall  we  now  meet,  I  beg  to 
add  a  hearty  welcome  on  behalf  of  the  Treasurer  and  my  fellow 
Masters  of  the  Bench. 

This  year  1913  is  the  year  which  some  of  our  amateur  alarmists, 
only  a  little  while  ago,  had  fixed  upon  as  the  time  appointed  for 
an  invasion  of  this  realm  from  lands  beyond  sea.  We  now  see 
their  prediction  fulfilled  after  a  sort,  perhaps  as  near  the  letter  as 
most  amateur  predictions  are.  The  invaders  are  here,  and  the 
British  Academy,  we  hope,  was  not  altogether  unprepared.  For 
some  months,  at  any  rate,  its  heralds  cried,  like  Hagen  when 
he  stands  on  the  rock  in  the  Gotterddmmerung,  '  Waffen  durch's 
Land  !  Gute  Waffen  !  Starke  Waffen  ! '  A  multitude  of  more  or 
less  learned  and  academic  persons,  even  more  diversely  equipped 
in  their  several  Faculties  than  Gunther's  vassals,  answered  the  call, 
and  when  they  came  with  like  words  in  their  mouth — '  Was  soil 

i  B 


2  F.  Pollock  [i 

ihm  das  Heer  nun  noch  helfen  ?  ' — the  instructions  they  received, 
though  not  unexpected,  were  otherwise  not  unlike  Hagen's.  '  Starke 
Stiere  sollt  ihr  schlachten ' :  whatever  else  the  invading  host  of 
historians  were  to  find,  there  should  be  a  festive  meeting  with  the 
usual  accompaniments.  Committees  and  sub  -  committees  have 
accordingly  been  engaged  in  preparations  which  may  be  called,  in 
a  general  way,  serving  tables — I  do  not  mean  exclusively  or  chiefly 
dining  tables.  These  preparations,  useful  and  needful  as  they  are, 
do  not  make  it  easier  for  those  who  are  occupied  with  them  to  give 
adequate  attention  to  making  ready  the  feast  of  reason  contemplated 
as  the  main  object  of  our  gathering.  Nor  can  we  expect,  at  this 
time  of  year,  much  reinforcement  from  our  English-speaking 
brethren  of  the  American  schools. 

But  our  spiritual  feast  is  such  that  the  guests  do  not  come 
empty-handed,  and  the  list  of  papers  to  be  read  gives  ample  warrant 
that  any  defects  on  the  part  of  the  British  Academy  and  the 
British  Faculties  will  be  more  than  made  good  by  contributions  in 
which  Continental  seats  of  learning  from  Christiania  to  Palermo 
will  be  worthily  represented. 

I  call  on  Professor  Vinogradoff  to  take  the  chair. 


II 

PRESIDENTIAL   ADDRESS 

DELIVERED   BY 

PROFESSOR  P.  VINOGRADOFF 

IT  is  to  be  regretted  that  our  proceedings  should  not  be  inaugurated 
by  a  distinguished  member  of  the  English  Bench :  in  England 
more  than  in  any  other  country  one  has  to  look  to  the  considered 
decisions  of  learned  judges  for  the  historical  development  of  legal 
doctrine.  It  is  not  mere  chance  that  the  two  most  influential 
expositors  of  English  law — Bracton  and  Blackstone — were  judges. 
As,  however,  the  task  of  giving  the  inaugural  address  has  been 
entrusted  to  me,  I  must  approach  it  from  what  may  be  called  the 
academic  point  of  view.  The  duty  of  addressing  an  audience 
composed  of  representative  jurists  from  the  principal  countries  of 
Europe  is  not  an  easy  one,  but  it  would  not  be  amiss,  I  think,  if, 
before  speakers  take  up  the  thread  of  their  various  subjects,  I  dwelt 
very  briefly  on  some  of  the  points  which  unite  us  all  and  supply  the 
connecting  links  between  the  various  researches  in  Roman  and 
English,  German  and  Slavonic,  Civil,  Canon,  and  Common  Law. 
The  attempt  is  not  so  presumptuous  as  it  may  seem  at  first  sight, 
because  certain  guiding  lines  have  been  traced  by  generations  of 
leading  workers,  and  what  is  chiefly  required  on  the  present 
occasion  is  a  summing-up  of  familiar  inquiries.  After  all,  every 
one  of  us,  whether  he  treats  expressly  of  general  principles  or  not, 
is  bound  to  make  up  his  mind  on  this  subject :  investigations  as  to 
the  legal  systems  of  particular  nations,  states  and  periods,  bear 
necessarily  on  the  theory  of  law,  and  embody  in  concrete  forms 
conceptions  and  methods  of  jurisprudence. 

The  fundamental  unity  of  our  study  may  be  realized  from  two 

3 


4  P.  Vinogradoff  [n 

main  points  of  view.  They  are  provided  by  continuity  on  the 
one  hand  and  by  similarity  on  the  other.  There  are  streams  of 
doctrines  and  institutional  facts  which  pass  through  the  ages  and 
cross  national  boundaries  from  one  historical  formation  to  another. 
These  constitute  what  may  be  called  the  current  of  cultural 
tradition.  Again,  the  solutions  of  legal  problems  on  different 
occasions  fall  into  groups  according  to  similarities  and  contrasts, 
for  which  there  is  a  common  basis  in  the  nature  of  the  problems 
themselves.  This  gives  rise  to  the  application  of  the  comparative 
method.  The  continuity  of  culture  and  comparative  jurisprudence 
produce  the  atmosphere  of  what  might  have  been  called  Inter- 
national Law,  had  not  the  term  been  appropriated  to  other  uses. 

It  is  not  necessary  to  dwell  at  length  on  the  progress  which 
has  been  made  in  tracing  cultural  continuity  in  the  history  of  legal 
systems.  A  classical  example  used  to  be  drawn  from  the  reception 
of  Roman  Law  by  mediaeval  and  modern  Europe.  In  recent 
years  we  have  witnessed  another  and  hardly  less  remarkable  move- 
ment of  investigation  in  regard  to  the  force  of  cultural  traditions : 
the  study  of  inscriptions  and  papyri  has  led  to  a  rediscovery  of 
Hellenism.  In  the  hands  of  Mitteis,  Dareste,  Grenfell  and  Hunt, 
Rostowzew,  Wenger,  and  many  others,  it  has  entirely  changed  the 
aspect  of  ancient  history,  connecting,  as  it  does,  the  doctrines  of 
the  Digest  and  of  the  Code  with  Greek  and  Oriental  antecedents. 
The  other  day  Sir  William  Ramsay,  one  of  the  pioneers  of  this 
study,  called  attention  to  an  interesting  fact  of  this  kind.  In  St. 
Luke's  Gospel  (ii.  1-5)  it  is  stated  that  Joseph  and  Mary  had  to 
leave  the  town  of  Nazareth  where  they  dwelt  to  go  to  Bethlehem, 
Joseph's  birthplace,  in  order  to  be  enrolled  there  for  the  census. 

1.  And  it  came  to  pass  in  those  days,  that  there  went  out  a 
decree  from  Caesar  Augustus,  that  all  the  world  should  be  enrolled 
(A.V.  taxed).  .  .  . 

2.  And  all  went  to  be  enrolled,  every  one  to  his  own  city. 

4.  And  Joseph  also  went  up  from  Galilee,  out  of  the  city  of 
Nazareth,  into  Judaea,  unto  the  city  of  David,  which  is  called 
Bethlehem  ;  (because  he  was  of  the  house  and  lineage  of  David  :) 

5.  To  be  enrolled  with  Mary,  his  espoused  wife,  being  great 
with  child. 

This  idea,  that  a  person's  birthplace  is  a  home  to  which  he 
remains  perpetually  attached,  is  quite  foreign  to  modern  notions, 
but  it  played  an  important  part  in  the  legal  arrangements  of  the 


n]  Presidential  Address  5 

ancient  world.  It  appears  as  the  Origo  so  rigidly  kept  up  by  the 
Emperors  of  the  Lower  Empire — Diocletian,  Constantine,  and 
their  successors — and  it  has  to  be  considered  as  one  of  the  principal 
rules  of  the  state  of  siege  in  which  the  Empire  lived  from  the 
fourth  century  A.D.  Yet  the  verses  of  St.  Luke  just  quoted,  and 
many  other  indications  (e.g.  a  decree  of  a  Roman  governor  of 
Egypt  in  1 54  A.D.),  connect  it  with  another  set  of  facts — viz.  with 
the  Eastern  conception  of  populations  firmly  established  in  their 
homes — a  notion  expressed  by  the  Hellenistic  term  ISia.  We  may 
add  that  it  connects  it  also,  with  Oriental  forms  of  absolute  rule 
tending  to  register  and  tax  subject  populations  according  to  the 
requirements  of  fiscal  utility.1 

In  this  case  the  continuity  of  principle  rests  on  the  broad  basis 
of  social  traditions.  Sometimes  similar  results  are  produced  by  the 
development  of  what  may  be  called  juridical  invention.  When  a 
technical  method  has  been  discovered  which  provides  simple  and 
adequate  means  for  satisfying  certain  needs,  it  is  not  likely  to  dis- 
appear, even  after  vast  changes  have  taken  place  in  social  conditions. 
For  example,  the  law  of  jettison  and  salvage  from  shipwreck  was 
settled  by  the  naval  customs  of  the  Greeks.  As  Rhodian  law,2  it 
was  received  by  the  Romans  and  incorporated  in  the  Digest  (xiv.  2). 
It  remained  the  basis  of  maritime  law  in  the  Byzantine  Empire  and 
took  shape  in  the  tract  called  No/xos  Navmcos.  Thence  it  spread 
through  the  customs  of  Mediterranean  and  Adriatic  cities,  as 
exemplified,  for  instance,  by  the  ordinances  of  Ragusa.3  In  sub- 
stance, the  rules  formulated  in  this  way  still  remain  the  basis  of 
modern  maritime  law  in  European  countries,  including  England. 

The  second  method  of  connecting  materials  belonging  to  different 
spheres  of  national  development  arises  from  the  comparison  of 
analogous  and  contrasting  formations  of  law.  What  I  have 
particularly  in  view  is  not  the  accumulation  of  more  or  less  similai 
facts  which  used  to  be  the  aim  of  writers  like  Post.  The  enthusiasm 
for  comparison  frequently  led  in  this  case  to  confusion  :  interesting 

1  See  The  Expositor,  Dec.  1912.     Cf.  Rostowzew,  Studien  zur  Geschichte 
d.    rbmischen    Kolonats ;     and  de    Zulueta,     De    Patrociniis     Vicorum,     in 
Vinogradoff 's  Oxford  Studies,  1 909. 

2  See  Ashburner,  The  Lex  Rhodia. 

3  See  Liber  Statutorum  Civitatis  Ragusii,  ed.  BogiSic  and  Jirecek,  1904. 
Cf.  Dareste,    £tudes  d'Histoire  du  Droit,  iii.    93  ;    and    Vinogradoff,    Law 
Quarterly  Review,  1903. 


6  P.  Vinogradoff  [n 

data  might  be  reduced  to  a  mixture  of  commonplace  statements  and 
unproved  assumptions  which  on  closer  inspection  were  often  shown 
to  be  anything  but  homogeneous.  The  excesses  of  such  uncritical 
accumulation  have,  indeed,  thrown  some  discredit  on  the  com- 
parative method  itself.  Fortunately  this  method  has  found  a 
better  treatment  at  the  hands  of  writers  equally  skilled  in  historical 
criticism  and  in  juridical  analysis.  It  is  not  the  juxtaposition 
of  resembling  facts,  but  the  dialectical  examination  of  given 
principles  in  various  surroundings,  which  yields  fruitful  and  some- 
times unexpected  results.  Let  me  take  as  an  example  the  curious 
treatment  of  obligation  in  recent  literature.  Brinz,  a  leading  authority 
on  Roman  Law,  dissected  the  notion  of  the  obligatio  of  the  Digest. 
He  observed  that  obligatio  does  not  correspond  to  the  German 
Verpflichtung :  the  latter  points  to  duty,  and  any  duty,  including 
a  legal  one,  resolves  itself  into  a  charge  on  the  will  of  a  person, 
whereas  obligatio  points  at  the  same  time  to  a  state  of  subjection 
or  liability  (Haftung)  which  is  derived  from  physical  sway.1  This 
led  to  a  subtle  analysis  of  the  notions  of  legal  duty  and  of  liability 
as  the  two  constituent  elements  of  Roman  obligation.  Von  Amira 
showed  that  the  two  elements  were  not  only  theoretically  separable 
but  actually  distinct  in  Scandinavian  law 2 ;  while  Puntschart 
conducted  a  similar  demonstration  in  regard  to  the  mediaeval  law 
of  Saxon  Germany.3  Partsch  applied  the  discovery  in  a  brilliant 
manner  to  ancient  Greek  law,  by  showing  that  the  process  of 
enforcing  an  obligation  was  carried  out  by  a  recourse  to  a  pledge  over 
whom  the  obligee  obtained  physical  sway.4  A  striking  instance  of 
this  was  drawn  from  the  scene  in  the  Odyssey  in  which  Poseidon 
comes  forward  to  release  Ares  and  Aphrodite  from  the  net  thrown 
over  them  by  the  deceived  husband,  Hephaestus.5  It  is  recognized 
that  Ares  owes  the  husband  a  customary  compensation  (ato-ipx), 
and  Poseidon  offers  himself  as  a  security  for  the  enforcement  of  the 
payment.  The  sea-god  would  be  primarily  liable  in  his  own  person 
as  a  hostage  for  Ares,  but  Hephaestus  does  not  like  the  idea  of 
binding  so  powerful  a  god,  and  prefers  a  promise  from  the  pledge 

1  Brinz,  Archiv  fur  dmlistische  Praxis,  i.  (1874)  15  ff. 

2  Amira,  Nordgermanisches  Obligationenrecht,  ii.  73. 

3  Puntschart,  Schuldvertrag  u.    Treugelobnis  des  sdchsischen  Rechts  des 
Mittelalters  (1896). 

4  Partsch,  Griechisches  Burgschaftsrecht,  i.  I  o  ff. 

5  Od.  viii.  344  sqq. 


n]  Presidential  Address  7 

to  pay  instead  of  Ares  if  the  latter  should  take  to  flight.  This 
suggestive  interpretation  of  the  scene  serves  as  an  appropriate  in- 
troduction to  the  Greek  law  of  pledge.  Von  Gierke  investigated 
thoroughly  the  dualism  of  duty  and  liability  (Schuld  and  Haftung} 
in  German  law.1  He  showed,  among  other  things,  how  legal  duty 
{Schuld}  came  to  be  treated  as  an  object  in  itself,  how  it  gave  rise  to 
real  right,  and  was  sometimes  combined  with  possession  of  land.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  development  of  securities  for  enforcement  also 
assumed  a  peculiar  bent,  because  the  pledge  was  regarded  not 
as  a  subsidiary  help  to  the- principal,  but  as  a  substitute  for  the 
direct  fulfilment  of  the  legal  duty ;  while  the  wager  was  explained 
as  a  symbol  of  the  surrender  of  property.  It  would  lead  Us  too 
far  afield  to  consider  the  reaction  of  this  historical  analysis  on  the 
well-worn  controversy  as  to  the  meaning  and  operation  of  the  nexum 
in  early  Roman  law.2  I  only  mention  the  renewal  of  this  famous 
dispute  in  order  to  recall  to  your  minds  that  a  discussion  begun  by 
a  Romanist,  carried  on  by  eminent  Germanists  and  by  a  student  of 
Greek  law,  reverted,  as  it  were,  to  the  history  of  Roman  law  in  its 
early  stages. 

The  method  of  comparative  investigation  in  such  cases  is 
characterized  by  the  part  assigned  to  the  dialectics  of  principles. 
It  starts  from  the  definition  of  conceptions  and  traces  their  '  ramifi- 
cation '  (Abzweigung\  their  conflicts  and  compromises.  At  the 
same  time  it  opens  the  way  for  the  study  of  the  material  conditions 
of  development.  It  is  not  only  from  the  point  of  view  of  logical  dis- 
tinctions that  analogies  and  contrasts  in  law  have  to  be  considered. 
It  is  clear  that  there  is  a  background  of  social  conditions  which 
account  to  a  great  extent  for  the  stages  of  the  doctrinal  evolution. 
As  regards  this  very  dualism  of  legal  duty  and  liability,  for  example, 
it  was  called  forth  historically  by  the  characteristic  attitude  of 
early  commonwealths  to  the  question  of  the  enforcement  of  law. 
We  are  so  accustomed  nowadays  to  the  correspondence  between 
legal  rights  and  legal  remedies  that  it  is  difficult  for  us  to  imagine 
a  state  of  society  in  which  such  a  direct  correspondence  did  not 
exist.  And  yet  it  is  with  such  states  of  society  that  we  have  to 
deal  in  early  Germanic  as  well  as  in  early  Greek  and  Roman  law. 
When  self-help  was  the  principal  mode  of  enforcing  right,  when 

1  Von  Gierke,  Schuld  u.  Haftung  im  alterer  deutschen  Recht. 

2  See  de  Zulueta,  The  Recent  Controversy  about  Nexum,  Oxford,  1912. 


8  P.  Vinogradoff  [n 

juridical  conflicts  commonly  resolved  themselves  into  feuds,  or  had 
to  be  managed  by  arbitration,  when  even  legal  proceedings  were 
initiated  by  ceremonial  agreements,  the  practical  enforcement  of 
liability  naturally  took  the  shape  of  an  appeal,  not  to  public  force, 
but  to  private  execution.  The  two  necessary  elements  of  such  an 
execution  are  recognition  by  the  parties,  and  assured  substitutes 
for  the  fulfilment  of  a  recognized  duty.  The  importance  of 
recognition  as  a  basis  of  law  is  as  instructive  in  this  case  as  it  is 
in  the  formation  of  modern  Constitutional  and  International  Law. 
It  is  certainly  important  to  realize  that  the  formation  of  law 
proceeds  in  many,  if  not  in  all  cases,  not  from  the  command  of  a 
sovereign,  but  from  recognition  by  parties.  The  process  of  execu- 
tion by  the  taking  of  pledges  is  quite  as  characteristic.  The  pledge 
is  originally  a  hostage.1  The  treaties  between  contracting  parties 
and  litigants  in  Iceland,  Norway,  Saxon  England,  or  Germany, 
had  to  be  supplemented  by  the  giving  of  pledge-hostages,  and 
sometimes  these  pledges  experienced  the  treatment  of  hostages  in 
a  literal  sense :  they  might  be  imprisoned  or  coerced  until  the 
obligation  had  been  fulfilled  either  by  them  or  by  the  principal.2 
It  is  by  comparing  the  evidence  of  Greek,  Roman,  and  Germanic 
practice  that  we  realize  to  what  extent  these  features  of  technical 
law  depended  on  the  conditions  of  societies  in  the  stage  of  what 
may  be  called  primitive  confederation. 

This  leads  to  a  further  step  in  the  application  of  the  comparative 
method.  If  juridical  conceptions  can  serve  as  links  in  comparative 
analysis,  it  is  natural  to  ask  whether  these  links  are  themselves 
perennial  or  subject  to  transformation.  How  far  have  we  to  deal 
with  certain  constant  attributes  of  legal  thought  which  provided  a 
frame  for  varying  contents,  and  how  far  do  vital  and  important 
legal  doctrines  take  shape  from  historical  conditions?  Attempts 
to  construct  a  science  of  law  composed  of  constant  and  ever- 
recurring  rules  have  been  made  again  and  again.  Quite  recently, 
an  eminent  representative  of  the  Neo-Kantian  school,  Stammler, 
has  brought  together  in  a  voluminous  book  the  absolute  require- 
ments of  juridical  logic,  and  has  inscribed  on  his  work  the  significant 
motto — Non  est  mortale  quod  opto.  Undoubtedly  a  certain  amount 

1  Rintelen,  Schuldhaft  u.  Einlager  im  Vollstreckungsverfahren. 

2  Esmein,  Melanges  de  Rome,  viii.  (1888)  426-436  ;  cf.  Glotz,  La  Solidarity 
de  la  Famille. 


n]  Presidential  Address  9 

of  logical  doctrine  arises  in  connection  with  law ;  it  is  necessary 
not  only  in  order  to  explain  the  common  phraseology  of  law,  but 
to  guide  us  in  the  process  of  juridical  reasoning.  But  when  too 
much  insistence  is  laid  on  this  department  of  jurisprudence,  it  is 
apt  to  degenerate  into  scholasticism,  and  to  recall  the  famous 
strictures  of  Goethe's  Mephistopheles  on  the  teaching  of  logic : 

Then,  the  philosopher  steps  in 
And  shows,  no  otherwise  it  could  have  been  : 
The  First  was  so,  the  Second  so, 
Therefore  the  Third  and  Fourth  are  so ; 
Were  not  the  First  and  Second,  then 
The  Third  and  Fourth  had  never  been.1 

As  in  every  other  branch  of  knowledge,  it  is  the  contents  of  law 
that  interest  men  rather  than  the  formal  framework ;  and  the 
contents,  even  the  most  fundamental,  are  admittedly  subject  to 
variation.  As  Ihering  has  forcibly  expressed  it : 

Law  is  not  less  a  product  of  history  than  handicraft,  naval 
construction,  technical  skill :  as  Nature  did  not  provide  Adam's 
soul  with  a  ready-made  conception  of  a  kettle,  of  a  ship,  or  of  a 
steamer,  even  so  she  has  not  presented  him  with  property,  marriage, 
binding  contracts,  the  State.  And  the  same  may  be  said  of  all 
moral  rules.  .  .  .  The  whole  moral  order  is  a  product  of  history, 
or,  to  put  it  more  definitely,  of  the  striving  towards  ends,  of  the 
untiring  activity  and  work  of  human  .reason  tending  to  satisfy 
wants  and  to  provide  against  difficulties.2 

The  causes  producing  variations  of  legal  principles  are  many : 
the  influence  of  economic  surroundings,  of  national  character,  of 
historical  collisions,  of  cultural  loans,  the  cross-currents  of  religious 
and  philosophical  thought,  may  be  mentioned  among  the  factors 
which  lead  to  variations.  It  would  be  out  of  the  question  to  make 
anything  but  a  passing  reference  to  these  factors.  One  class  of 
causes,  however,  deserves  particular  attention,  because  they  not 
only  differentiate  theories  and  systems  of  law,  but  combine  them 

1  Der  Philosoph,  der  tritt  herein 
Und  beweist  euch,  es  musst'  so  sein : 
Das  Erst'  war'  so,  das  Zweite  so, 
Und  drum  das  Dritt'  und  Vierte  so  ; 
Und  wenn  das  Erst'  und  Zweit'  nicht  war', 
Das  Dritt'  und  Viert'  war7  nimmermehr. 
2  Ziveck  im  Recht,  ii.  112. 


io  P.  Vinogradoff  [n 

into  groups.  I  mean  the  effect  of  the  social  type  on  the  formation 
of  definite  sets  of  jurisprudential  theory.  There  have  not  been  so 
many  fundamental  types  of  social  organization — at  least  in  the 
Western  world.  Roughly  speaking,  we  have  to  reckon  with  six 
great  types.  Human  society  has  assumed  the  form  of  a  tribe,  that 
is,  an  association  based  mainly  on  real  or  supposed  kinship ;  it  has 
been  concentrated  in  cities  ;  it  has  adapted  itself  to  the  relations  of 
a  landed  estate  ;  it  has  expanded  into  churches  ;  it  has  been  made 
to  serve  the  aims  of  free  individuals  under  state  control ;  lastly,  it 
may  be  organized  as  an  association  for  the  purpose  of  controlling 
the  production  and  distribution  of  goods. 

According  to  the  road  selected  by  a  community  among  these 
classes,  certain  points  of  view  are  created  for  the  formulation  and 
solution  of  juridical  problems,  as  may  be  gathered  from  familiar 
examples.  Property  will  be  treated  differently  by  individualistic 
and  by  socialistic  communities,  but  it  has  also  received  a  peculiar 
treatment  at  the  hands  of  the  Church  and  of  the  City-State,  as  well 
as  in  feudal  and  in  tribal  law.  Again,  the  notions  of  crime  and 
punishment  have  been  differentiated  according  to  the  character  of 
the  social  tie.  In  tribal  society,  crime  was  substantially  '  contempt 
of  court'  or  a  direct  offence  against  the  tribe,  while  punishment 
appeared  chiefly  as  revenge ;  the  City  was  unsparing  in  its  require- 
ments from  its  children,  the  citizens,  and  relentless  in  its  methods 
of  educating  and  eventually  suppressing  them.  The  notion  of 
breach  of  faith  is  as  characteristic  of  feudal  jurisprudence  as  the 
notion  of  sin  is  characteristic  of  the  Church.  The  treatment  of 
crime  as  an  expression  of  perverse  will  and  the  psychology  of 
deterrent  punishment  are  natural  to  individualistic  communities  ; 
whereas  in  societies  with  a-  socialistic  bent  crime  comes  to  be 
considered  from  the  pathological  point  of  view,  and  punishment 
assumes  the  aspect  of  medical  treatment.  Even  the  fundamental 
conceptions  of  law  itself  are  to  a  great  extent  dependent  on  sub- 
mission to  one  or  the  other  type  of  social  order.  In  tribal  societies, 
law  is  a  declaration  of  custom ;  in  city-states  it  is  justice  as  con- 
ceived by  the  city — So£a  rrjs  n-oAews ;  in  feudal  organizations  it  is 
based  on  express  or  tacit  agreements  ;  from  the  point  of  view  of  the 
Church,  it  is  the  recognition  of  Divine  precepts  in  the  govern- 
ment of  the  world ;  in  individualistic  societies  it  is  the  command 
of  the  sovereign  will ;  from  the  socialistic  point  of  view,  it  should 


n]  Presidential  Address  1 1 

be  the  means  for  carrying  out  social  justice  and  expediency  in  the 
attribution  of  rights. 

In  laying  stress  on  jurisprudential  principles  as  realized  by 
history,  I  do  not  wish  to  suggest  for  a  moment  that  any  one  of 
these  notions  has  reigned  supreme  in  a  particular  commonwealth 
to  the  exclusion  of  all  others.  Juridical  history,  as  well  as  history 
in  general,  shows  to  what  extent  political  ideas  slide  and  shade  off 
one  into  the  other,  and  how,  on  the  other  hand,  every  epoch 
presents  contradictions  and  compromises  between  rival  forces. 
Nevertheless,  the  study  of  juridical  evolution  discloses  prevailing 
tendencies  which  change  with  the  times — as  has  been  brilliantly 
illustrated,  for  example,  in  reference  to  our  own  age.  in  Dicev's 


ERRATA 

Page  7  note  I  for  al&erer  read  alteren 
Page  n,  1.  20  for  Wenger  read  Menger 

Vinogradoff,  Legal  History  Face  p.  10 

Nov.  1913 


its  necessary  complement,  in  Bentham's  theory  of  the  summation 
of  individual  expediencies.  Both  elements  are,  as  a  matter  of  fact, 
blended  in  the  rationalistic  system  of  Austin.  All  these  doctrines 
take  root  in  the  competition  of  the  modern  commercial  world,  and 
find  a  curious  counterpart  in  the  individualistic  jurisprudence  of 
the  Pax  Romana  as  encased  in  the  political  fabric  of  the  Empire. 
It  I  seems,  in  fact,  as  if,  instead  of  seeking  for  the  philosopher's 
stone  in  the  shape  of  a  single  theory  of  law,  we  had  better  attend 
for  the  present  to  five  or  six  theories  of  law  derived  from  different 
social  premisses. 

However  this  may  be,  one  thing  seems  clear.  Jurists  approach 
historical  problems  on  their  own  lines,  with  their  particular  habits 
of  mind.  Whatever  attention  they  may  give  to  the  careful  study 
of  evidence,  to  the  proper  sequence  of  events,  and  to  exact 


io  P.  Vinogradoff  [n 

into  groups.  I  mean  the  effect  of  the  social  type  on  the  formation 
of  definite  sets  of  jurisprudential  theory.  There  have  not  been  so 
many  fundamental  types  of  social  organization — at  least  in  the 
Western  world.  Roughly  speaking,  we  have  to  reckon  with  six 
great  types.  Human  society  has  assumed  the  form  of  a  tribe,  that 
is,  an  association  based  mainly  on  real  or  supposed  kinship ;  it  has 
been  concentrated  in  cities  ;  it  has  adapted  itself  to  the  relations  of 
a  landed  estate  ;  it  has  expanded  into  churches  ;  it  has  been  made 
to  serve  the  aims  of  free  individuals  under  state  control ;  lastly,  it 
may  be  organized  as  an  association  for  the  purpose  of  controlling 
the  production  and  distribution  of  goods. 

According  to  the  road  selected  by  a  community  among  these 


notion  of  sin  is  characteristic  of  the  Church.  The  treatment  of 
crime  as  an  expression  of  perverse  will  and  the  psychology  of 
deterrent  punishment  are  natural  to  individualistic  communities  ; 
whereas  in  societies  with  a  socialistic  bent  crime  comes  to  be 
considered  from  the  pathological  point  of  view,  and  punishment 
assumes  the  aspect  of  medical  treatment.  Even  the  fundamental 
conceptions  of  law  itself  are  to  a  great  extent  dependent  on  sub- 
mission to  one  or  the  other  type  of  social  order.  In  tribal  societies, 
law  is  a  declaration  of  custom ;  in  city-states  it  is  justice  as  con- 
ceived by  the  city — 86ga  -njs  iroAcws ;  in  feudal  organizations  it  is 
based  on  express  or  tacit  agreements  ;  from  the  point  of  view  of  the 
Church,  it  is  the  recognition  of  Divine  precepts  in  the  govern- 
ment of  the  world ;  in  individualistic  societies  it  is  the  command 
of  the  sovereign  will ;  from  the  socialistic  point  of  view,  it  should 


n]  Presidential  Address  1 1 

be  the  means  for  carrying  out  social  justice  and  expediency  in  the 
attribution  of  rights. 

In  laying  stress  on  jurisprudential  principles  as  realized  by 
history,  I  do  not  wish  to  suggest  for  a  moment  that  any  one  of 
these  notions  has  reigned  supreme  in  a  particular  commonwealth 
to  the  exclusion  of  all  others.  Juridical  history,  as  well  as  history 
in  general,  shows  to  what  extent  political  ideas  slide  and  shade  off 
one  into  the  other,  and  how,  on  the  other  hand,  every  epoch 
presents  contradictions  and  compromises  between  rival  forces. 
Nevertheless,  the  study  of  juridical  evolution  discloses  prevailing 
tendencies  which  change  with  the  times — as  has  been  brilliantly 
illustrated,  for  example,  in  reference  to  our  own  age,  in  Dicey's 
Law  and  Opinion  in  England. 

This  makes  it  both  possible  and  desirable  to  group  the  facts 
supplied  by  history  not  only  in  their  organic  sequences  of  national 
development,  but  also  according  to  the  social  types  to  which  they 
correspond.  Many  partial  attempts  have  been  made  in  this  direc- 
tion. I  may  refer,  for  example,  to  Maine's  and  Leist's  books  on 
Aryan  tribal  law  ;  to  statements  of  jurisprudence  by  Catholic  writers 
like  Cathrein,  and  by  socialists  like  Wenger.  But  the  method  is 
worthy  of  a  much  wider  application.  For  example,  it  would  be 
an  interesting  task  to  treat  from  this  point  of  view  the  theories  of 
jurisprudence  which  correspond  to  modern  systems  of  public  and 
private  law.  It  would  be  found,  perhaps,  that  Hobbes'  theory  of 
the  omnipotent  state  finds  its  opposite  pole,  and  at  the  same  time 
its  necessary  complement,  in  Bentham's  theory  of  the  summation 
of  individual  expediencies.  Both  elements  are,  as  a  matter  of  fact, 
blended  in  the  rationalistic  system  of  Austin.  All  these  doctrines 
take  root  in  the  competition  of  the  modern  commercial  world,  and 
find  a  curious  counterpart  in  the  individualistic  jurisprudence  of 
the  Pax  Romana  as  encased  in  the  political  fabric  of  the  Empire. 
It  !  seems,  in  fact,  as  if,  instead  of  seeking  for  the  philosopher's 
stone  in  the  shape  of  a  single  theory  of  law,  we  had  better  attend 
for  the  present  to  five  or  six  theories  of  law  derived  from  different 
social  premisses. 

However  this  may  be,  one  thing  seems  clear.  Jurists  approach 
historical  problems  on  their  own  lines,  with  their  particular  habits 
of  mind.  Whatever  attention  they  may  give  to  the  careful  study 
of  evidence,  to  the  proper  sequence  of  events,  and  to  exact 


12  P.  Vinogradoff  [n 

knowledge  of  historical  environment,  they  are  sure  to  look  out  for 
doctrine  in  the  end — that  is,  for  statements  of  principles,  of  their 
consequences  in  theory  and  their  application  in  practice.  This 
being  so,  methods  of  analysis  and  of  constructive  reasoning  which 
are  exercised  daily  in  pleading  and  deciding  cases,  in  stating  and 
interpreting  rules,  in  formulating  and  safeguarding  rights,  are 
bound  to  reappear  in  the  grouping  and  discussion  of  historical 
material  by  lawyers.  Legal  history  as  an  exact  reproduction  of 
the  past  has,  indeed,  to  be  supplemented  by  historical  jurisprudence 
in  the  sense  of  a  reasoned  account  of  the  evolution  of  legal 
principles.  Such  a  jurisprudence  is  free  from  the  delimitations 
imposed  on  nations  and  periods :  it  derives  its  divisions  and 
chapters  from  conceptional  distinctions. 

This  feature  is  especially  noticeable  in  those  connecting  studies 
with  which  I  have  been  dealing  in  my  address.  The  gravitation 
towards  the  home  (or  the  traditions  of  maritime  law)  are  not 
circumscribed  by  the  boundaries  of  monarchies.  The  principles  of 
legal  duty  and  liability  unfold  their  contents  not  only  in  theoretical 
discussion,  but  in  the  analogies  and  contrasts  of  various  legal 
systems.  The  conceptions  of  property,  of  crime  and  punishment, 
of  law  itself,  appear  in  correspondence  to  the  social  type  in  their 
environment.  And,  I  should  like  to  say  in  conclusion,  it  is  perhaps 
this  alliance  between  exact  observation  and  dialectical  reasoning 
which  makes  our  mode  of  studying  history,  despite  technical  diffi- 
culties and  the  dryness  of  many  details,  so  attractive  to  the  mind. 
Thanks  to  the  juridical  method,  masses  of  historical  facts,  accumulated 
as  if  by  accident,  are  sifted  and  become  capable  of  being  treated  as 
manifestations  of  a  certain  Aoyos — of  reason  governing  the  moral 
world. 


Ill 

ROMISCHE   RECHTSGESCHICHTE 

DIE  Frage,  welche  ich  vor  Ihnen,  wenn  nicht  zu  beantworten,  so 
doch  zu  erortern  versuchen  will,  veranlasst  mich,  obwohl  vor  einem 
internationalen  Forum  von  Historikern  und  Rechtsgelehrten  spre- 
chend,  doch  einen  nationalen  Ausgangspunkt  zu  wahlen.  Wie 
Ihnen  alien  bekannt,  hat  Deutschl^nd  zur  Jahrhundertswende  sich 
ein  neues  nationales  Privatrecht  geschaffen  und  damit  die  friiher 
weit  verbreitete  Geltung  des  altehrwiirdigen  Corpus  Juris  Civilis 
beseitigt.  Der  notwendige  Riickschlag,  den  diese  Neuregelung 
eines  so  wichtigen  Gebietes  der  staatlichen  Ordnung  auf  das 
Studium  dieser  Ordnung  selbs.t  ausiiben  musste,  hat  eine  arge 
Unruhe  in  den  Studienbetrieb  an  den  juristischen  Fakultaten 
hineingetragen.  Die  Zeiten,  in  denen  das  Pandektenstudium — im 
deutschen  Sinne,  d.h.  also  das  Studium  des  durch  Wissenschaft 
und  Praxis  ausgestalteten  „  gemeinen  Rechts  " — die  vornehmste 
Aufgabe  fur  Forschung  und  Lehre  an  den  deutschen  Universitaten 
war,  sind  dahin  :  Lehrer  und  in  neuerer  Zeit  auch  Schiller  schlagen 
sich  ubersturzende  Reformen  vor:  von  Riickkehr  zur  alten 
Ordnung,  Wiedereinfuhrung  des  Pandektenstudiums  erhoffen  die 
einen  Forderung,  von  Beseitigung  des  romischen  Rechtsstudiums, 
insbesondere  der  sogenannten  Rechtsgeschichte,  aber  nicht  bloss 
der  romischen,  auch  der  deutschen,  von  rein  praktischer  Gegen- 
wartsausbildung  schwarmen  die  anderen.  Ich  brauche  vor  dieser 
Versammlung  von  Mannern,  die  ihre  Lebensarbeit  in  den  Dienst 
historischer  Forschung  gestellt  haben,  die  geschichtliche  Methode 
des  Rechtsunterrichts  und  der  juristischen  Forschung  nicht  zu 
verteidigen,  nicht  zu  betonen,  wie  jene  „ Reformer"  die  Jurisprudenz 
in  ihrem  Lebensnerv  bedrohen,  die  sie  aus  einer  Wissenschaft  zu 

13 


14  L.  IVenger  [m 

einer  positiven  Kunde  von  Bestimmungen  degradieren  wollen,  welche 
man  im  praktischen  Leben  unmittelbar  brauchen  konne.  Es  sind 
Banausen,  die  nicht  nach  der  Idee  der  Publizitat  fur  den  Im- 
mobiliarrechtsverkehr  fragen,  sondern  nach  der  Art,  wie  ein  Grund- 
buchsgesuch  ausserlich  aussehen  muss,  die  nicht  von  den  Gedanken 
gehandelt  wissen  wollen,  die  sich  im  Recht  der  Wertpapiere 
verkorpern,  sondern  verlangen,  dass  der  Rechtsunterricht  auf  alle 
Einzelheiten  der  gegenwartig  geltenden  Wechselordnung  eingehend 
vorbereite ! 

Aber  gerade  dieser  Ansturm  gegen  allesGeschichtliche  zwingt  die 
Vertreter  einer  historischen  Rechtsforschung  zur  Anspannung  aller 
Krafte  der  Verteidigung.  Es  soil,  um  von  der  romischen  Rechts- 
geschichte  zu  sprechen,  der  Beweis  erbracht  werden,  dass  sie  mehr 
ist,  als  was  jene  unkundigen  Verachter  von  ihr  behaupten,  ,mehr 
als  eine  blosse  Aufzahlung  von  Leges  und  Senatsbeschliissen,  von 
Juristennamen  und  Juristenschriften,  die  heute  niemanden  mehr 
interessieren.  Ich  bin  damit  bei  meinem  Thema  angelangt  und 
werde  in  der  Kiirze  der  mir  zu  Gebote  stehenden  Zeit  auf  einiges 
von  dem  hinzuweisen  versuchen,  was  meines  Erachtens  heute 
Aufgabe  einer  Darstellung  der  romischen  Rechtsgeschichte  ist. 

Ich  meine  dabei  eine  Darstellung,  welche  dem  Studierenden 
und  dem  Gebildeten  geboten  werden  kann,  welche  die  Resultate 
der  Forschung  zusammenfasst  und  die  Zusammenhange  aufweist, 
die  das  Einst  und  Jetzt  verbinden,  aber  auch  die  Gegensatze  nicht 
verhiillt,  die  Vergangenheit  und  Gegenwart  von  einander  scheiden. 
Und  ich  meine,  dass  es  zur  Zeit  an  einer  liber  den  Grundriss  sich 
erhebenden  Darstellung,  die  der  Forschung  auf  alien  Gebieten  des 
offentlichen  und  privaten  Rechtslebens  der  Antike  folgt,  tatsachlich 
fehle.  Es  sei  mir  gestattet,  wieder  an  einer  deutschen  Parallele 
zu  exemplifizieren.  Ein  entsprechendes  Werk  wie  etwa  Schroders 
Lehrbuch  der  deutschen  Rechtsgeschichte ,  oder  auch  nur  Brunners 
Grundzuge  der  deutschen  Rechtsgeschichte  fehlt  den  Romanisten. 
Es  existieren  gute  Arbeiten  aus  friiherer  Zeit :  es  liegt  mir  feme, 
sie  hier  aufzuzahlen  oder  gar  zu  kritisieren.  Aber  seit  einem 
Vierteljahrhundert  ist  kein  deutsches  Lehrbuch  der  romischen 
Rechtsgeschichte  mehr  erschienen  :  auch  keine  Neuauflage  eines 
alteren  Buchs.  Erst  in  aller  jiingster  Zeit  (1912-13)  macht  Robert 
von  Mayr  in  der  bekannten  Sammlung  Goeschen  den  Versuch,  die 
romische  Rechtsgeschichte  darzustellen — die  Enge  des  verfiigbaren 


in]  Romische  Rechtsgeschichte  15 

Raums,  der  Zweck  der  Sammlung  bindet  aber  den  Verfasser,  der, 
wenn  ich  ihm  nachempfinden  darf,  uberall  durch  die  ihm  gezogenen 
Grenzen  beengt  ist.  Man  vergleiche  etwa  Schroders  Lehrbuch 
mit  Schroders  eben  erscheinender  Darstellung  der  deutschen 
Rechtsgeschichte  in  Goeschens  Sammlung !  In  gewisser  Hin- 
sicht  gilt,  wenn  ich  mir  liber  eigene  Arbeit  ein  Urteil  erlauben 
darf,  dasselbe  auch  von  den  Partien  iiber  Verfassung  und  Ver- 
waltung  des  europ&ischen  Alter  turns  (1911)  und  von  der  eben 
im  Druck  befindlichen  Abhandlung  iiber  das  Recht  der  Griechen 
und  Romer  in  Hinnebergs  Kultur  der  Gegenwart.  Ich  habe  in 
wiederholten  Gesprachen  mit  Kollegen  an  deutschen  und  oster- 
reichischen  Universitaten  zu  konstatieren  Gelegenheit  gehabt,  dass 
dieser  Mangel  und  die  Wichtigkeit  der  Aufgabe  einer  Neu- 
darstellung  allgemeiner  empfunden  wird.  Die  romische  Rechts- 
geschichte ist  ihrem  umspannenden  Namen  untreu  geworden,  sie 
ist  zur  Geschichte  der  Quellen  und  Literatur  zusammengeschrumpft, 
obwohl  sie  sich — wenigstens  in  den  Universitatskatalogen — noch 
„  romische  Rechtsgeschichte  "  nennt.  Ja,  ich  begegnete  auch  der 
Ansicht,  dass  eben  nur  das  als  „  Rechtsgeschichte "  in  Betracht 
kame.  Die  gangbaren  Lehrbiicher  des  Privatrechts  —  ich  nenne 
etwa  als  Vertreter  Sohm,  Czyhlarz,  Girard,  Costa  —  beschranken 
sich  darauf,  eine  Quellengeschichte  oder  den  Abriss  einer  solchen 
voranzustellen.  Diese  selbst  erfreut  sich  eingehender  Bearbeitung  : 
P.  Kriiger  ist  (1913)  in  zweiter,  Kipp  (schon  1909)  in  dritter 
Auflage  erschienen. 

Eine  Arbeit  allerdings  erfullt  in  ihrer  eben  erschienenen  Neu- 
auflage  eine  auch  weit  gespannte  Erwartung :  Lenels  Neudar- 
stellung  von  Bruns*  Geschichte  und  Quellen  des  romischen  Rechts.1 
Hier  finden  wir  in  knappster  Skizzierung  grosse  Partien  einer 
modernen  romischen  Rechtsgeschichte,  leider  war  der  Verfasser 
durch  Bruns'  StofTabgrenzung  und  die  Anlage  des  ganzen  enzyklo- 
padischen  Werkes  gebunden. 

Nicht  unerwahnt  soil  endlich  Pacchionis  Corso  (1905)  bleiben, 
wenngleich  auch  er  prinzipiell  nur  Staatsverfassung  und  Quellen 
bringen  will. 

Uberall  sind  die  wichtigen  Probleme  der  —  ich  mochte  zusam- 
menfassend  sagen  —  Staatsverwaltung  in  den  Hintergrund  gedrangt, 

1  Holtzendorff- Kohler,  Enzyklopddie  der  Rechtswissenschaft,  7.  Aufl. 
(1913),  Bd.  i.  S.  303  ff. 


1 6  L.  IVenger  [m 

hochstens  gelegentlich  gestreift,  das  interessante  Gebiet  des  Straf- 
rechts  ist  ganz  vernachlassigt,  nur  das  Privatprozessrecht  erfreut 
sich  im  Anschluss  an  das  dominierende  Privatrecht  eingehenderer 
Beachtung.  Aber  wahrend  die  Darstellung  des  Privatprozessrechts 
meist  kaum  bis  zum  Kognitionsverfahren,  jedenfalls  nicht  bis  zum 
justinianischen  Prozessrecht  herabgefiihrt  wird,  liegt  im  Privatrecht 
alles  Gewicht  auf  dem  vom  Rechtskaiser  kodifizierten  Recht. 

Ich  will  hier  die  alte  theoretisch  naturlich  unlosbare,  praktisch- 
empirisch  nach  den  Erfahrungen  des  einen  so,  des  anderen  anders 
zu  beantwortende  Frage  nicht  erortern,  ob  die  Darstellung 
geschichtliche  Perioden  der  Entwickelung  des  Rechts  fixieren  und 
innerhalb  dieser  den  ganzen  Werdegang  des  Rechts  darstellen,  oder 
ein  Rechtsinstitut  von  den  grauesten  Anfangen  durch  alle  Zeit  hin- 
durch  verfolgen  soil.  Beide  Methoden  haben  ihre  Vor-  und  Nach- 
teile,  beide  lassen  sich  im  miindlichen  Unterricht  verwerten,  doch 
fur  buchmassige  Darstellung  ist  meines  Erachtens  die  Perioden- 
teilung  brauchbarer. 

Die  Frage,  ob  die  herkommliche  Teilung  der  romischen  Rechts- 
geschichte  in  die  bekannten  vier  Perioden  beibehalten  oder  aufge- 
geben  zu  werden  verdient,  ist  schwer  zu  entscheiden.  Wenn  man 
das  Privatrecht  oder  den  Prozess  im  Auge  hat,  da  wird  man  an  die 
Zwolftafeln,  an  die  neu  einsetzende  Entwickelung  des  Rechts-  und 
Wirtschaftslebens  seit  den  siegreichen  Kampfen  mit  Karthago, 
oder  im  Privatprozessrecht  an  die  Bedeutung  der  aebutischen  Lex 
denken  :  aber  die  Verfassungsgeschichte  heischt  doch  die  alther- 
kommliche  Teilung  in  Konigsherrschaft,  Republik,  Prinzipatszeit 
und  Despotic.  Auch  der  Abschluss  der  Darstellung  der  Rechts- 
geschichte  ist  von  selbst  mit  Justinians  Werk  gegeben.  Das 
offentliche  Recht  ist  von  der  Zeit  der  Griindung  germanischer 
Reiche  auf  romischer  Erde  der  Domane  der  nationalen  Rechts- 
geschichte  zugewiesen ;  naturgemass  ist  auch  die  Darstellung  des 
Privatrechts  von  da  ab  nationale  Rechtsgeschichte,  die  ihrerseits 
freilich  die  Aufnahme  der  fremden  Rechte  in  den  Bereich  der 
Darstellung  ziehen  muss.  Ganz  eigenartig  und  nur  mit  dem 
iiberragenden  Einfluss  der  rezipierten  romischen  Rechtsmassen 
auf  deutscher  Erde  erklarlich  ist  die  Entstehung  der  deutschen 
Pandektenlehre  und  -Praxis,  des  im  neuen  biirgerlichen  Gesetzbuch 
noch  so  lebhaft  nachwirkenden  „  gemeinen  Rechts." 

Nach    den    zu    behandelnden    Gegenstanden    wird    sich    eine 


in]  Rmnische  Rechtsgeschichte  1 7 

Darstellung  der  „  romischen  Rechtsgeschichte "  am  besten  in 
folgende  Abschnitte  gliedern  konnen :  Staatsverfassung  uiid  Quellen- 
geschichte,  Staatsverwaltung,  .  Strafrecht  und  Strafprozessrecht, 
Privatrecht  und  Privatprozessrecht.  Es  sei  gestattet,  einige 
Fragen  aus  diesen  Kapiteln  fur  die  einzelnen  Perioden  naher 
zu  behandeln. 

I.  DieKonigszei  t. — Bei  alien  Z  weifeln  liber  die  Anfange  Roms, 
bei  aller  Uberwucherung  der  Konigsgeschichte  mit  sagenhafter 
Ausschmiickung,  wird  doch  soviel  behauptet  werden  diirfen,  dass 
auch  Rom  beim  Eintritt  in  die  Geschichte  von  Konigen  beherrscht 
war — und  dies  selbst  dann,  wenn  die  Griinder  der  ewigen  Stadt 
Etrusker  gewesen  sein  sollten.  So  sehr  schon  hier  die  Hypothese 
anstelle  sicherer  Erkenntnis  tritt,  so  miissen  wir  selbst  den  Versuch 
wagen,  in  die  Zeit  vor  der  „  Griindung  "  der  Stadt  zuriickzublicken. 
All  die  reizvollen  Probleme  der  vorhistorischen  Zeit  tauchen  da 
auch  vor  dem  Auge  des  romischen  Rechtshistorikers  auf :  wo  sind 
die  Vorvater  der  Romer  her?  wo  sassen  die  Indogermanen ?  was 
weiss  man  liber  ihre  Kultur?  wo  fangt  die  reine  Hypothese  an? 
Dann  das  grakoitalische  Problem.  1st  etwas  Wahres  an  der  lange 
behaupteten  engeren  Verwandtschaft  zwischen  Griechen  und 
Italikern?  Gerade  hier  kann  neben  der  Sprachvergleichung  die 
Rechtsgeschichte  der  allgemeinen,  Geschichte  durch  Vergleichung 
der  Rechtsinstitute  einen  Dienst  erweisen.  Endlich  das  italische 
Volkerproblem.  Wo  sind  sie  alle  her,  die  in  Italien  sesshaft 
geworden,  die  Japygen,  die  Etrusker,  die  Latiner  und  die  Samniten  ? 

Und  dann  die  Anfange  Roms  :  die  Fragen  nach  der  personalen 
Gliederung  des  Volks,  nach  Familie  und  Geschlecht  und  nach  den 
Mannerverbanden,  den  Phratrien  und  Kurien,  aber  auch  nach  der 
territorialen  Gliederung  der  sesshaft  Gewordenen,  nach  Dorf  und 
Gau  und  der  jungeren  Tribus. 

Die  Grundung  der  Stadt,  die  Bedeutung  der  Stadt  und  des 
Stadtbiirgertums  fiihren  zur  Frage  nach  dem  Stadtstaat  und  seinem 
Gegensatz  zum  Territorialstaat.  Senatus  populusque  Romanus  ist 
Rom  und  <n  'A&jvcuoi  Athen,  auch  wenn  der  Feind  die  heimische 
Scholle  erobert  hat.  Wir  diirfen  auch  an  diesem  Punkte  Halt 
machen  und  der  griechischen  Staatsphilosophie  gedenken,  die 
politische  und  wirtschaftliche  Autarkic  der  Polis  noch  zu  der  Zeit 
forderte,  als  Alexander  das  Erbe  der  orientalischen  Weltmonarchie, 
des  grossartigsten  Territorialstaates,  angetreten  hatte. 

C 


i8  L.  IVenger  [m 

Die  Griindung  der  Stadt  und  die  Konigsgeschichte  riihrt  aber 
wiederholt  auch  an  das  etruskische  Ratsel.  Dann  Uberhaupt :  wie 
ist  das  Konigtum  gekommen,  wie  hat  es  gewirkt,  wie  ist  es 
beseitigt  worden  ?  Welch  bose  Schuld  hat  es  auf  sich  geladen, 
dass  selbst  Caesar  noch  fur  den  Zuruf  Rex  mit  dem  Tode  biissen 
musste  ?  Welcher  historische  Kern  liegt  der  „  servianischen  Reform  " 
zugrunde  und  ist  etwa  die  Episode  der  Tarquinier  absolutistische 
Restauration  ? 1 

Dann  die  Stande  des  Volks :  Patrizier  und  Plebejer.  Worin 
lag  der  Gegensatz  begriindet  ?  Ist  er  zuerst  nur  wirtschaftlicher, 
sekundar  politischer  Natur  ?  Wie  stellen  sich  die  Plebejer  zu  den 
Klienten  ? 

Die  in  dem  Abschnitt  liber  Staatsverwaltung  zu  erorternden 
Fragen  nach  Gross-  und  Kleinbesitz  treten  schon  in  der  Konigszeit 
entgegen :  dann  muss  auch  der  primitivste  Organismus  —  der 
librigens  das  konigliche  Rom  gewiss  nicht  mehr  gewesen  ist — die 
Heeres-  und  Finanzverwaltung  regeln. 

Ebenso  schwierige  als  interessante  Probleme  stellen  die  in 
dieser  altesten  Zeit  der  romischen  Rechtsgeschichte  wurzelnden 
Institute  des  Privat-  und  des  damit  innig  zusammenhangenden 
Privatprozessrechts  dar.  Eher  noch  konnen  wir  liber  Familien- 
und  Erbrecht  Genaueres  wenn  nicht  behaupten,  so  doch  vermuten. 
Freilich  auch  da  ist  Raum  flir  Zweifel  genug :  schon  die  Erklarung 
der  verschiedenen  Eheschliessungsformen  mit  dem  gleichen  Er- 
gebnis  legitimer  Vollgewalt  des  Mannes  tiber  die  Frau  ist  nur 
in  hypothetischer  Form  moglich.  Adoption  und  Testament,  die 
wir  recht  frlih  ansetzen  dlirfen,  erinnern  an  Parallelen  aus  der 
griechischen  Entwickelung.  Natlirlich  ist  gerade  bei  dieser  Rechts- 
vergleichung  ausserste  Vorsicht  am  Platze.  Noch  unsicherer 
sind  die  Anfange  des  Vermogensrechts.  Da  stehen  zunachst  die 
Anschauungen  in  einem  Punkte  einander  ganz  entgegen  :  ist  das 
Eigentum  Gemeineigentum  oder  Individualeigentum  ?  Hier  kann 
wohl  nur  weitausgreifende  Rechtsvergleichung,  wie  sie  ja  gerade  auf 
diesem  Gebiete  schon  angewendet  ist,  zu  einem  Resultate  flihren, 

1  Wieviel  hier  unsichere  Uberlieferung  ist,  wie  wenig  wir  hier  und  in  der 
Folgezeit  bis  auf  die  Zeit  der  Gracchen  Sicheres  wissen,  ist  so  recht  wieder 
bei  einer  Besprechung  dieser  Fragen  im  Freundeskreise  der  ,,  Miinchener 
Philologischen  Gesellschaft  "  zum  Ausdruck  gekommen.  Es  ist  richtig  :  auch 
die  neueste  juristische  Literatur  ist  recht  konservativ. 


in]  Romische  Rechtsgeschichte  19 

das  Anspruch  auf  Wahrscheinlichkeit  erheben  darf.  Hier  hat  sich 
auch  Mommsen  zur  Konstruktion  einer  kommunistischen  Agrar- 
genossenschaft  verleiten  lassen,  von  der,  wie  Pohlmanns  scharfe 
Kritik1  dartut,  nichts  iibrig  bleibt,  als  die  blosse  Moglichkeit 
gemeinwirtschaftlicher  Elemente  in  der  altesten  Agrarverfassung. 
Da  gilt  es,  manche  landlaufige  Theorie  zu  revidieren  und  manche 
Behauptung  zu  iiberpriifen,  die  sich  wie  ein  Axiom  von  Lehrbuch 
zu  Lehrbuch  vererbt.  Auf  dem  Gebiete  des  Vertragsrechts  haben 
sich  wohl  auch  im  altesten  Rom  die  Prinzipien  der  Barleistung 
und  der  Entgeltlichkeit  geltend  gemacht,  wahrend  das  spater  so 
iiberall  vorbildliche  romische  Obligationenrecht  von  der  scharfen 
begrifflichen  Scheidung  von  Schuld  und  Haftung,  dem  Leistensollen 
des  Schuldners  und  dem  Einstehen  des  Biirgen  oder  selbstbiirgen- 
den  Schuldners,  nicht  minder  beherrscht  gewesen  sein  wird,  als 
das  Recht  der  Germanen  und  das  der  Griechen,  ja  auch  das  der 
Babylonier  und  der  Assyrer.  Gerade  diese  Fragen  miissen  fiir  die 
romische  Rechtsgeschichte  noch  der  Antwort  naher  gebracht 
werden,  als  dies  bisher  der  Fall  ist.  Und  hier  hilft,  wie  die  neuen 
Arbeiten  von  Partsch  und  Koschaker  gezeigt  haben,  die  Rechts- 
vergleichung  weiter.  Dass  auch  wichtige  Fragen  des  Prozessrechts 
mit  der  Schuld-Haftungslehre  zusammenhangen,  ist  nach  neueren 
Vermutungen  recht  wahrscheinlich. 

Noch  ist  der  Anfange  des  staatlichen  Strafrechts  zu  gedenken, 
dabei  aber  die  Vorstufe  nicht  zu  ubersehen,  die  das  Straf-  oder 
richtiger  Racheverfahren  der  Familie  und  der  Sippe  bildet.  Schon 
in  diese  Zeit  ist  aber  gewiss  die  Scheidung  der  delicta  privata  von 
den  crimina  publica  zu  verlegen,  und  die  bewusste  oder  unbewusste 
Erweiterung  des  Kreises  der  letztgenannten  auf  Kosten  der 
Delikte  zu  beachten,  die  der  privaten  Ahndung — wenn  auch  nicht 
mehr  immer  der  Selbsthilfe — iiberlassen  sind. 

Schon  ins  „  konigliche  "  Rom  miissen  endlich  die  Anfange  des 
Verkehrs  mit  dem  Auslande  fallen  :  die  verschiedenartigen  Vertrage 
mit  anderen  Stadten  iiber  Rechtshilfe  und  gegenseitigen  Rechts- 
schutz  der  Burger  und  iiber  das  hospitium,  das  dem  staatlichen 
Recht  auch  hier  vorangeht.  Es  ist  von  grossem  Interesse,  diese 

1  Geschichte  der  sozialen  Frage  und  des  Sozialismus  in  der  antiken  Welt, 
2.  Aufl.  (1912),  ii.  415-433.  Vgl.  auch  Bruns-Lenel,  a.  a.  O.  311.  Vgl.  fur 
Hellas  Pohlmann  Bd.  i.  Vgl.  auch  allgemein  und  insbesondere  fur  die 
Germanen  R.  Hildebrand,  Recht  und  Sitte^  2.  Aufl.  (1907). 


2O  L.  Wenger  [m 

Wurzeln  des  ,,V6lkerrechts"  blosszulegen  und  bedeutende  Arbeiten 
gerade  englischer  Herkunft l  haben  diese  Probleme  wesentlich 
gefordert.  Neben  diesen  losen  Beziehungen  zum  Auslande  steht 
aber  der  eigenartige  latinische  Bund,  dessen  Bedeutung  fiir  den 
spater  so  fruchtbaren  Gedanken,  dass  es  iiber  der  Poliszusammen- 
gehorigkeit  noch  grossere  Zusammenhange  geben  konne,  nicht 
gering  eingeschatzt  werden  darf.2  Uberall  und  nicht  zuletzt  auf 
dem  Gebiete  der  internationalen  Beziehungen  werden  aber  mit 
Vorteil  die  griechischen  Parallelen  heranzuziehen  sein. 

II.  Die  Zeit  der  Re'publik. — In  helleres  Licht  scheint  die 
Geschichte  Roms  nach  dem  Sturz  seiner  Konige  zu  treten.  Die 
von  der  romischen  Uberlieferung  geschilderten  Verfassungskampfe 
sind  uns  in  grossen  Ziigen  schon  von  der  Schule  her  bekannt :  wir 
sehen  die  nicht  immer  parallel  verlaufenden,  sondern  sich  wieder- 
holt  auch  kreuzenden  wirtschaftlichen  und  politischen  Gegensatze. 
Darin  wird  bei  alien  sonstigen  Zweifeln  gewiss  Wahres  stecken. 
Wir  verstehen  die  Bedeutung  der  Zwolftafelgesetzgebung,  deren 
Authentizitat  freilich  in  neuerer  Zeit  hart  angefochten,  aber  dank 
Girards,  Lenels  und  anderer  Gegenkritik  nun  als  fester  erhartet 
gelten  mag,  als  vor  Pais'  und  dem  viel  weiter  gehenden  Angriff 
Lamberts.  Dabei  haben  freilich  auch  die  Angreifer  manches 
Richtige  beobachtet  und  namentlich  Pais'  besonnene  Stellungnahme 
auf  unserem  letzten  Kongress  in  Berlin  sei  noch  in  Erinnerung 
gebracht.3  Auch  weiten  Juristenkreisen  Frankreichs  und  Deutsch- 
lands  ist  aber  die  Beachtung  der  historischen  Tatsache  recht  ein- 
dringlich  nahezulegen,  dass  „  freies  Recht "  kein  Freiheitspostulat 
ist,  und  dass  das  antike  Richterkonigtum  Uberall  der  Herrschaft 
des  Gesetzes  wich,  unter  dessen  Tyrannis  sich  auch  der  Grieche 
willig  beugte. 

Die  romischen  Verfassungskampfe  fiihren  nach  der  Uber- 
lieferung wenigstens  formell  zu  einer  Demokratie,  wie  sie  selbst 
Athen  nie  gekannt  hat :  ich  meine  den  fiir  verschiedene  Jahr- 
hunderte  bezeugten,  und  freilich  schon  darum  bedenklichen  Satz  ut 
quod  tributim  plebes  iussisset  populum  teneret.  Die  Gesetze  der 

1  Coleman  Phillipson,    The  International  Law  and  Custom  of  Ancient 
Greece  and  Rome.     2  Bde.      1911. 

2  Fiir  die  Konigszeit  freilich  mit  alien  notigen  Vorbehalten  und  Frage- 
zeichen. 

3  Literaturiibersicht  neuestens  bei  Bruns-Lenel,  a.  a.  O.  325  A.  2  und  3. 


HI]  Romische  Rechtsgeschichte 

Plebejerversammlung,  zu  welcher  der  Patrizier  nicht  Vejmjxalx 
Zutritt  hat,  sollten  auch  ihn  binden.  Die  Geschichte  der  Verfas- 
sungskampfe  bietet  auch  sonst  noch  genug  des  Dunkleri :  'manches 
Licht  ist  in  jiingster  Zeit  erst  angesteckt  worden.  Sicher  erscheint 
aber  im  Widerspruch  zur  Theorie  der  Uberlieferung  die  Tatsache, 
dass  Rom  praktisch  eine  vollendete  Demokratie  doch  nie 
geworden  ist.  Wir  diirfen  ja  bei  all  den  Schilderungen  der  inneren 
Kampfe,  die  schliesslich  angeblich  das  Ubergewicht  der  Plebejer 
endgiltig  festlegen,  nicht  vergessen,  dass  die  aussere  Geschichte 
Roms  von  dieser  Demokratisierung  der  Verfassung,  wenn  sie 
wirklich  so  oder  ahnlich,  wie  uns  erzahlt  wird,  vor  sich  gegangen 
ist,  wenig  spiiren  lasst.  Wahrend  die  Regierung  der  Imperien- 
trager  fiihrt,  der  Inhaber  von  Gewalten,  deren  Vereinigung  ihm  eine 
ganz  besondere  Stellung  verlieh,  liegt  die  aussere  Politik  —  auch 
damals  die  ungemein  wichtigere  Ausserung  des  Staatslebens — in 
den  Handen  des  Senats. 

Was  ist  aber  „  Rom  "  in  der  republikanischen  Zeit  geworden  ? 
Drei  Bestandteile  hat  es :  die  herrschende  Stadt,  die  dienenden 
Provinzen  und  die  verbiindeten  oder  sonstwie  angegliederten 
Stadte.  Hier  muss  eindringlich  auf  die  merkwiirdige  Verleihung 
des  Burgerrechts  an  Leute  hingewiesen  werden,  die  politisch 
mangels  einer  Reprasentativverfassung  damit  nichts  anzufangen 
wissen :  denn  wer  wollte  nach  Rom  reisen,  um  dort  in  die 
Volksversammlung  zu  gehen,  wenn  er  in  Spanien  seine  Heimat 
hatte  ?  Rom  hat  den  Fehler  vermieden,  der  Athens  Herrlichkeit 
zu  Fall  gebracht  hat :  es  hat  den  Bundesgenossen  in  weitestem  Aus- 
mass  das  Danaergeschenk  seines  Burgerrechts  gemacht.  Da  der 
romische  Zivitat  erwerbende  Burger  einer  Landstadt  die  Eigen- 
schaft  eines  Burgers  dieser  Stadt  nicht  verliert,  so  ist  damit  der 
Gegensatz  zwischen  dem  Staatsburgerrecht  und  dem  Stadtburger- 
recht  tatsachlich  gegeben. 

In  aller  Stille  vollzieht  sich  auch  die  Latinisierung  erst  Italiens, 
dann  des  ganzen  Westens,  soweit  der  Romer  Herrschaft  reicht. 
Das  ist  eine  Erscheinung,  die  mir  wenigstens  immer  zu  den  merk- 
wiirdigsten  der  ganzen  romischen  Geschichte  zahlte.  Die  Stadt, 
die  von  sich  aus  eine  solche  Entnationalisierung  weiter  Gebiete 
durchfiihrt,  wie  wir  sie  doch  annehmen  miissen,  muss  eine  ganz 
gewaltige  Lebenskraft  besessen  haben.  Freilich  sind  wir  im  ganzen 
Westen  liber  das  Fortleben  des  nationalen  Elements  und  seine 


22  L.  Wenger  [m 

Ausserung  in  der  Volkssprache  und  dem  Volksrecht  viel  schlechter 
orientiert,  als  im  Osten  —  aber  es  muss  doch  wohl  ein  bedeutender 
Unterschied  zwischen  den  Beziehungen  Roms  zu  dem  kulturell  so 
viel  tiefer  stehenden  Westen  und  zu  den  politisch  unterworfenen, 
kulturell  aber  stets  als  Lehrer  verehrten  Griechen  bestanden  haben. 

Wir  kommen  damit  auf  ein  besonders  wichtiges  Gebiet  der 
romischen  Rechtsgeschichte,  auf  die  Frage  des  griechischen  Ein- 
flusses.  Sie  ist  oft  und  viel  erortert  worden,  aber  sie  ist  noch 
keineswegs  erledigt.  In  der  republikanischen  Periode  begegnet 
sie,  Antwort  verlangend,  in  der  Zwolftafelgesetzgebung  ;  sie  be- 
gegnet allgemein  bei  den  Beziehungen  Roms  zu  Grossgriechenland 
und  weiter  zum  griechischen  Mutterlande  und  alien  Gebieten  des 
hellenistischen  Ostens.  Wir  diirfen  aber,  wenn  wir  das  Mass 
griechischen  Einflusses  auf  der  Romer  Recht  zu  ergriinden  suchen, 
auch  nicht  vergessen,  die  Frage  zu  iiberprlifen,  inwieferne  etwa 
unsere  Quellen  tatsachlich  griechisches  Recht  bringen,  wenn  sie 
lateinisches  zu  geben  scheinen :  ich  denke  natiirlich  in  erster 
Linie  an  Plautus  und  Terenz. 

In  der  Darstellung  der  Staatsverwaltung  dieser  Zeit  wird 
neben  der  voranstehenden  Erorterung  des  Staatsgebietes  und 
der  Verwaltungskorper,  worauf  schon  die  Sprache  kam,  die  des 
Heer-  und  Finanzwesens,  dann  aber  der  Agrargeschichte  und 
der  Entwickelung  des  Handels  einen  breiten  Raum  einnehmen. 
„  Recht  und  Wirtschaft"  ist  kein  bloss  modernes  Schlagwort : 
kein  Rechtshistoriker  darf  die  Wirtschaftsgeschichte  beiseite- 
schieben. 

Das  fiihrt  zu  Partien,  die  mit  mehr  oder  weniger  Grund 
herkommlich  im  Privatrecht  verhandelt  werden  :  Standegliederung, 
steigende  Bedeutung  der  Sklaverei,  damit  wohl  zusammenhangend 
der  privatrechtliche  Grundsatz  von  der  Unzulassigkeit  freier 
Stellvertretung,  Zwischenbildungen  verschiedener  Arten  von 
Halbfreiheit,  dann  aber  auch  die  Bildung  des  neuen  Adels,  der 
Nobiles l  und  der  Ritter. 

Fur  das  Privatrecht  der  republikanischen  und  der  Prinzipats- 
zeit  ist  jetzt  Mitteis'  Romisches  Privatrecht  bis  auf  die  Zeit 
Diokletians  richtunggebend.  Zwar  behandelt  der  bisher  vorlie- 
gende  erste  Band  (1908)  nur  die  Grundbegriffe  und  die  Lehre 
von  den  juristischen  Personen,  aber  diese  Gebiete  eingehend 

1  Dazu  jetzt  M.  Gelzer,  Die  Nobilitiit  der  romischen  Republik  (1912) 


in]  Rmnische  Rechtsgeschichte  23 

und  grossenteils  ganz  in  neue  Bahnen  weisend.  In  seiner 
Stellungnahme  zu  grundlegenden  Fragen,  die  bereits  gestreift 
wurden,  ist  das  Werk  vorbildlich :  so  zum  Problem  des  arischen 
Rechts,  zum  Verhaltnis  des  Romerrechts  zu  dem  der  Umbro- 
Samniten,  endlich  zum  griechischen  Recht. 

Ungeschrieben  ist  noch  eine  Geschichte  des  romischen 
Privatprozessrechts,  die  Wlassaks  peinlich  sorgfaltige  For- 
schungen  verwertet  hatte,  von  den  ,,Prozessgesetzen"  an  bis  zu 
den  neuesten  Arbeiten  liber  Exzeptionen  und  Praskriptionen. 
Lenels  Ediktsrekonstruktion,  Girards  Studien  und  so  manche 
andere  Arbeit  muss  erst  erworben  werden,  damit  wir  sie  auch  voll 
besitzen.  Kellers  vorzligliches  Zivilprozessbiichlein  ist  seit  1883 
nicht  wieder  erschienen  und  seither  auch  kein  anderes.  Wie 
viel  Arbeit  steckt  aber  in  einzelnen  Artikeln  von  Pauly-Wissowas 
Realenzyklopadie ! 

III.  Die  Zeit  des  Prinzipats. — Bewundernswert  ist  Augustus' 
kluges  Werk,  mit  dem  die  Revolutibnsepoche  abschliesst.  Die 
Republik  ist  scheinbar  wiederhergestellt :  eadem  magistratuum 
vocabula,  und  doch  :  quotus  quisque  reliquus  qui  rempublicam 
vidisset?  Wie  viel  besagt  diese  taziteische  Charakteristik  des 
Reichs  beim  Regierungsantritt  des  Tiberius  (Annal.  i.  3) !  Die 
staatsrechtliche  Umgestaltung  ist  unschwer  zu  schildern,  aber  der 
im  modernen  Staatsrecht  zutn  Kampfe  zweier  Richtungen 
gewordene  Gegensatz  zwischen  juristischer  und  politischer 
Betrachtung  des  Staatslebens  tritt  hier  klar  entgegen.  Politisch 
ist  die  Republik  tot  und  die  Monarchic  auf  dem  Wege,  und  in 
dieser  Hinsicht  darf  man  jetzt  schon  sagen,  dass  der  Schwerpunkt 
des  Reichs  in  den  hellenistischen  Osten  verlegt  ist.  Sind  doch 
dort  die  Kaiser  Gotter,  ein  Gedanke,  der  dem  Romer,  auch  seit  die 
alte  Virtus  nur  selten  mehr  auf  Erden  wandelte,  doch  hart  in  den 
Kopf  ging.  Die  Verfassungsgeschichte  dieser  Zeit  muss  zeigen, 
wie  aus  der  Republik  die  Monarchic  wird,  wie  erst  die  Volksver- 
sammlung  depossediert  wird  und  wie  dann  in  energischem  Ringen 
die  beiden  iibrig  bleibenden  Gewalten,  Senat  und  Prinzeps,  nach 
der  Beseitigung  des  Rivalen  streben,  bis  endlich  der  Reorganisator 
Diokletian  den  Staat  als  orientalische  Despotic  neu  aufrichtet. 

In  der  Staatsverwaltung  spielen  die  Provinzen  eine  immer 
mehr  hervortretende  Rolle.  Und  da  ist  aus  Inschriften  und 
neuerdings  aus  den  Papyri  ein  Erkenntnismaterial  geboten,  wie  es 


24  L.  Wenger  [in 

lange  den  antiken  Rechtshistorikern  vorenthalten  geblieben  war. 
Wir  haben  aus  den  Papyri  Einzelheiten  einer  romischen  Provinzial- 
verwaltung  kennen  gelernt,  nach  denen  fruher  kein  Einsichtiger 
zu  fragen  gewagt  hatte.  Wir  lernten  dabei  aber  auch  das  Mass 
dessen  richtiger  einschatzen,  was  die  Romer  neu  eingefiihrt,  und 
dessen,  was  sie  von  ihren  Vorgangern  in  der  Macht  iibernommen 
hatten.  Und  das  war  auf  verwaltungsrechtlichem  Gebiete  gewiss 
nicht  wenig.  Freilich  Agypten,  wo  wir  diese  Dinge  an  den  Papyri 
am  besten  studieren  konnen,  ist  nicht  der  Typus  einer  normalen 
Provinz.  In  diesem  richtiger  als  kaiserliche  Domane  bezeichneten 
Erbe  der  Ptolemaer  ist  der  Prinzeps  von  je  das  gewesen,  was  'er 
erst  nach  und  nach  in  den  anderen  Reichsgebieten  wurde :  der 
gottliche  Konig  oder  auch  der  konigliche  Gott.  Aber  je  mehr 
eben  die  Gewalt  des  Prinzeps  steigt,  umsomehr  darf  Agypten  als 
Typus  des  romischen  Provinziallands  genommen  werden.  In 
Agypten  lernen  wir,  wie  die  Regierung  Gesetze  und  Verordnungen 
durch  eingehende  Publikationshandlungen  zur  allgemeinenKenntnis 
brachte,  wie  Beamte  und  deren  Stellvertreter  amtierten,  wie  sie 
mit  den  Parteien,  wie  mit  den  vor-  und  nachgeordneten  Behorden 
verkehrten,  wie  und  welche  Steuern  und  Abgaben  erhoben  wurden, 
aber  auch  wie  der  grosse  und  der  kleine  Grundbesitz  verwaltet 
wurde. 

Aber  die  Papyri  zeigen  noch  mehr.  Aus  ihnen  lernen  wir  das 
Leben  des  kleinen  Mannes  mit  all  seinen  Freuden  und  Leiden,  mit 
seinen  hasslichen  und  schonen  Ziigen  kennen :  wir  lernen  ihn  als 
Glaubiger  und  Schuldner,  als  Hausherrn  und  Mieter  kennen,  als 
Ubeltater  und  Beleidigten,  als  Klager  und  Verklagten,  wir  sehen 
ihn  in  der  Familie  als  Eheherrn  und  Hausvater,  wir  finden  ihn 
als  Arbeiter  und  Arbeitgeber,  als  Gutsherrn  und  Verwalter,  als 
Schiffer  und  Soldaten.  Schubarts  eben  erschienene  Sammlung 
verdeutschter  Briefe  aus  dem  Altertum1  sagt  auch  dem  Rechts- 
historiker  sehr  viel.  „  Antike  Seelen,  die  fur  immer  verschollen 
schienen,  werden  wieder  lebendig  "  :  ein  Wort,  das  ich  Deissmann  2 
nachspreche.  Die  Prosopographie  der  ersten  drei  Jahrhunderte 
der  Kaiserzeit  hat  nur  die  der  antiken  aristokratischen  Geschichts- 
betrachtung  bedeutsam  erscheinende  Oberschicht  beriicksichtigt, 

1  Ein  Jahrtausend  am  Nil  (1912). 

2  Licht  vom  Osten^   2.  u.  3.  Aufl.  (1909),  S.  217.      Vgl.  zum  Folgenden 
Deissman  217  f. 


in]  Romische  Rechtsgeschichte  25 

sed  hominum  plebeiorum  infinita  ilia  turba  qua  scripta  ecclesiastica 
et  auctorum  iuris  referta  sunt  procul  semota  est.1  Fur  Verwaltungs-, 
Prozess-  und  Privatrecht  sind;aber  diese  die  in  Betracht  kommenden 
Personen. 

Aber  noch  fur  etwas  anderes :  unter  diesen  Kleinen,  unter  den 
Armen  und  Demiitigen  ist  die  Saat  des  Christentums  aufgegangen, 
unter  der  ,,  grossen  Schar,  die  niemand  zahlen  konnte/  aus  alien 
Volkern  und  Stammen,  und  Nationen  und  Sprachen "  (OfFenb. 
Job.  vii.  9).  Wie  das  grosse  Problem  des  Verhaltnisses  des  Staats 
zu  seinen  Nationen,  tritt  jetzt  auch  das  weltbewegende  Problem 
„  Staat  und  Kirche  "  in  die  Rechtsgeschichte  ein.  Der  heidnische 
Staat  kennt  das  Problem  nicht,  er  kann  es  nicht  kennen,  da  der 
Gotterkult  ein  durchaus  nationaler  ist,  und  als  solcher  der  staatlichen, 
nicht  irgendwelcher  vom  Staate  unabhangigen  Macht,  eigen  ist. 
Die  Stellung  des  Staats  zum  Christentum  verdient  eine  eingehende 
Betrachtung.  Auch  hiezu,  insbesondere  zu  den  Christenverfol- 
gungen  unter  Decius  haben  die  Papyri  viel  Material  beigesteuert.2 
Um  sich  vom  Verdachte  mangelnder  Gotterverehrung  zu  reinigen, 
reichen  die  in  diesen  Verdacht  gekommenen  libelli  ein,  dass  sie 
mit  Weib  und  Kind  immer  und  so  auch  jetzt  vor  der  Opferkom- 
mission  geopfert  und  vom  Opferfleisch  genossen  haben,  und  die 
Kommission  bestatigt  diese  libelli  durch  einen  Bescheinigungs- 
vermerk. 

Fiir  Privatrecht  und  Prozess  mochte  ich  auch  nur  dessen  in 
wenigen  Worten  Erwahnung  tun,  was  wir  aus  den  Papyri  zulernen 
konnen  und  miissen.  Nach  antiker  AufTassung  lebt  jeder  nach 
seinem  Personalrecht.  So  natiirlich  vor  allem  der  Grieche  in  der 
griechischen  Reichshalfte.  Als  nun  Caracalla  das  Burgerrecht  in 
weitem  Ausmasse  austeilte,  waren  demgemass  alle  damit  Begliickten 
zur  romischen  Rechtsordnung  verpflichtet.  Das  Volksrecht  aber 
lebte  nichtsdestoweniger  fort:  das  hat  L.  Mitteis3  schon  vor  mehr 
als  zwei  Dezennien  festgestellt  und  das  hat  die  rechtshistorische 
Papyrusforschung  seither  durchaus  bestatigt.  Nicht  anders  als  in 
Agypten  war  es  aber  in  den  anderen  Diadochenstaaten :  eine  Tat- 

1  Klebs,  Praefatio  zur  Pros.  \.  p.  viii. 

2  P.    M.    Meyer,    Die   Libelli  aus   der  decianischen    Christenverfolgung 
(1910). 

3  Reichsrecht  und  Volksrecht  in  den   bstlichcn  Provinzen  des  romischen 
Kaiserreichs  (1891). 


26  L.  IVenger  [in 

sache,  die  uns  am  besten  im  syrisch  -  romischen  Rechtsbuche 
entgegentritt.  Jetzt  erst  konnen  wir  eine  Reihe  kaiserlicher 
Konstitutionen  bewerten,  die  anscheinend — fur  den  Kenner  bloss 
des  romischen  Rechts — Selbstverstandliches  mit  Emphase  einschar- 
fen :  es  ist  da  stets  die  Annahme  berechtigt,  dass  irgend  ein 
volksrechtlicher  Brauch  sich  der  romischen  Ordnung  zum  Trotz 
hartnackig  erhielt.  Doch  ich  darf  bei  diesen  Dingen,  iiber  die  sich 
sovieles  sagen  liesse,  nicht  langer  verweilen,  so  schwer  es  hier  wird, 
auch  nur  Schlagworte  dariiber  zuruckzudrangen,  wie  uns  diese 
wunderbaren  Quellen  die  romische  Rechtsgeschichte  der  Wirklich- 
keit,  nicht  der,  wenn  auch  antiken,  Theorie,  naher  gebracht 
haben. 

IV.  Der  absolute  Staat. — 'Ev  ovoynart  TOV  Kvpiov  /cat  SecrTroTOv 
X|OMrrov  TOV  Beov  KOI  (rwnj/oos  ^yawv  /?a<rtAetas  rov  Of.iOTO.rov  KOL 
TTaTov  i^uicov  SecrTrorov  *$*XavLOV  NLavptKLov  Ti^Septov  TOV  alwvtov  A.V- 
yovcrrov  AvroKpdropos  erovs  SwSeKarov  KOL  VTrareias  T^S  avrutv  yaX-^vor^TOS 
GTOVS  zvSeKOiTov  f  Me^etp  Ka  r^s  L/3  tvStKTiovos  tv  ^vrjvr)  f.  So  beginnt 

eine  Dialysisurkunde,  die  am  15.  Februar  594  n.  Chr.  zwischen 
Schwagern  abgeschlossen  wird,  nachdem  ein  Presbyter  den  Frieden 
vermittelt  hat.  Die  Urkunde,  der  Miinchener  Papyrus  Inv.  Nr. 
IO2,1  ist  typisch  fiir  das  Ende  der  Entwickelung  des  Absolutismus. 
Wohl  ist  der  Staat  christlich,  aber  das  hindert  nicht,  Christus 
Seo-TTorqs  zu  nennen  und  in  einem  Atem  damit  auch  dem  Kaiser 
dasselbe  Beiwort  zu  geben  ;  bei  Gott  dem  Allmachtigen,  bei  der  hi. 
und  wesensgleichen  Dreieinigkeit  zu  schworen  und  zugleich  VLK^V  /cat 
Sta/Aoiojv,  ja  selbst  rrjv  ddav  KOI  ovpdviov  rvx^v  des  Kaiserpaars  im  Eide 
anzurufen,2  der  Herrscher  der  Welt,  der  ewigen  Erlauchten  und 
Selbstherrscher.  Nirgends,  in  keiner  offiziellen  Rechtsquelle,  in 
keinem  Schriftstellertext  spiegelt  sich  der  Wandel  der  Zeiten  so 
sehr  wieder,  wie  in  unseren  Papyrusurkunden.  Ihre  Formalien  sind 
keine  Zufalligkeit,  sie  zeigen  den  Wandel  der  Zeiten  und  den 
Wandel  der  Menschen.  Was  den  Orientalen  gewohnt  sein  mochte, 
ist  jetzt  auch  den  Romern  gelaufig  geworden,  denn  unter  den 
Parteien  und  Zeugen  der  Grenzgarnison  in  Syene,  die  uns  in  den 
genannten  Miinchenerurkunden  begegnen,  zu  denen  die  erganzenden 

1  Nr.  14  in  der  im  Druck  befindlichen,  von  Heisenberg  und  mir  heraus- 
gegebenen  Sammlung   byzantinischer  Papyri   in  der    K.    Hof-    und    Staats- 
bibliothek  zu  Miinchen. 

2  So  P.  Mon.  Inv.  Nr.  104  Z.  46-48  ;  Nr.  12  der  Ausgabe. 


in]  Romische  Rechtsgeschichte  27 

Paralleltexte  das  British  Museum  birgt;1  finden  wir  Kopten,  Griechen 
und  Romer  in  buntem  Gemisch,  alle  aber  dem  Staatsblirgerrecht 
nach  romische  Burger. 

Die  Theorie  der  Staatsverfassung  ist  die  einfachste  der  Welt : 
alles  ist  der  Kaiser,  Gesetzgeber,  Regent  und  Richter ;  alles,  was 
geschieht,  geschieht  in  seinem  Namen.  Die  Juristen,  die  in  der 
fruheren  Epoche  selbstandig  redend  aufgetreten  sind  und  das 
grossartige  romische  Privatrecht  geschaffen  haben,  sie  sprechen 
jetzt  nur  mehr  im  geheimen  kaiserlichen  Konsistorium  und  das 
Ergebnis  ihrer  Arbeit  ist  formell  ein  Wort  aus  des  Kaisers  Munde. 
Sie  sind  aufgegangen  in  der  namenlosen  Schar  der  Untertanen, 
deren  hochstes  Gliick  es  sein  muss,  dem  kaiserlichen  Herren  zu 
dienen. 

Aber  auch  der  0eioTaros  CUJTOK/HXTW/O  kann  die  Welt  nicht  ohne 
Organe  verwalten.  Wiederum  zeigen  uns  die  Papyri  die  Staats- 
verwaltung  dieser  neuen  Epoche.  Jetzt  gibt  das  agyptische  Bild 
noch  getreuer  die  Lage  im  ganzen  Reiche  wieder.  Denn  die 
Romer  selbst  sind  uberall  Untertanen  geworden  und  die  Zeiten, 
da  der  Kaiser  nur  princeps  civium  gewesen,  sind  langst  dahin. 

Die  Verkleinerung  der  Provinzen,  die  Zerschlagung  historisch 
gewordener  Individualitaten  und  all  die  sonstigen  Mittel  zentrali- 
stischer  Verwaltungsversuche  konnen  doch  nicht  den  Zerfall  des 
Reiches  in  das  Westreich  und  Ostreich  verhindern,  und  sie  konnen 
im  Innern  des  Reichs  den  Feudalisierungsprozess,  das  unverkenn- 
bare  Zeichen  schwacher  Zentralgewalt,  nicht  aufhalten.  Die 
dunkle  Zeit  des  vierten  und  fiinften  Jahrhunderts  ist  auch  durch 
die  Papyri  noch  nicht  geniigend  erhellt  worden.  Aber  die  Grund- 
ziige  der  Entwickelung  konnen  wir  sehen.  Von  entscheidender 
Bedeutung  sind  die  Agrarverhaltnisse.  Dem  Kolonat  muss  in 
einer  romischen  Rechtsgeschichte  ein  besonders  eingehendes 
Kapitel  gewidmet  werden.  Wir  sind  jetzt  dank  Rostowzews 
Studien2  liber  die  weit  in  die  hellenistische  Zeit  hineinragenden 
Wurzeln  dieses  Instituts  und  iiber  seine  Entwickelung,  insbesondere 
in  Afrika,  aufgeklart.  Wir  sehen  eine  auch  sonst  wiederkehrende 
Erscheinung.  Der  Latifundienbesitz  miisste  brach  liegen,  gelange 
es  nicht,  Bauern  in  halber,  stets  wachsender  Abhangigkeit  zur 
Bewirtschaftung  heranzuziehen.  Neben  der  Ausnutzung  wirtschaft- 

1  Vgl.  Bell,  A'/wxiii.  160-174. 

2  Studien  zur  Geschichte  des  romischen  Kolonates  (1910). 


28  L.  IVenger  [m 

licher  Abhangigkeit  kam  es  dabei  wohl  auch  oft  genug  zu  brutaler 
Gewaltanwendung,  die  den  freien  Nachbarn  in  den  Gutsleibeigenen 
verwandelte.  Die  Bindung  an  die  Scholle  lasst  sich  deutlich 
verfolgen,  bis  sie  zur  Rechtsinstitution  wird  und  nur  mehr  als 
natiirliche  Folge  der  Erblichkeit  der  Berufe  erscheint.  Aber  der 
staatliche  Steuerzwang  hat  nicht  minder  der  Feudalisierung  indirekt 
Vorschub  geleistet.  Um  der  Steuererpressung  zu  entgehen,  ver- 
kauft  manch  ein  Freier  sein  bischen  Freiheit  und  wird  Klient 
eines  Patrons.  Diese  Patroziniumsbewegung,  die,  unter  schliess- 
licher  staatlicher  Sanktion,  eine  Reihe  von  Freien  zu  Halbfreien 
und  zu  Horigen  macht,  haben  in  neuester  Zeit  Gelzer1  und  de 
Zulueta 2  genau  untersucht.3 

Von  den  traurigen  Verwaltungszustanden  des  6.  Jahrhunderts 
geben  uns  jetzt  die  Papyri  aus  dem  Museum  zu  Cairo,  die  Jean 
Maspero  in  dankenswert  rascher  Folge  publiziert,4  Auskunft.  Sie 
haben  bei  den  Historikern  und  Juristen  berechtigtes  Aufsehen  erregt, 
sie  zeigen  uns  Dinge,  welche  die  Rechtsbiicher  verbieten,  in  vielfach 
praktischer  Anwendung,  zeigen  uns  die  Gewaltigen,  die  das  Recht 
wohl  prinzipiell  als  Macht  werten,  und  die  Kleinen,  die  um  Haus 
und  Hof  kommen,  die  im  Schuldturm  sitzen  und  Peinigungen  aller 
Art  erdulden  miissen,  deren  Leben  nicht  sicher  ist,  wenn  nicht  ein 
Patronus  den  Schutz  bietet,  den  der  Staat  nicht  mehr  bieten  kann, 
und  den  seine  pflichtvergessenen  und  geldgierigen  Beamten  nicht 
bieten  wollen.  Auch  die  Mlinchener  Papyri  werden  dazu  einen 
Beitrag  bringen,  den  ich  fiir  so  unwahrscheinlich  hielt,  dass  ich 
lange  nach  anderer  Erklarung  suchte.  In  einem  Prozesse  Inv.  Nr. 
103  5  kommt  zum  Vorschein,  dass  der  mit  seiner  Mutter  in  einen 
Erbstreit  verwickelte  Sohn  dem  einen  Richter  eine  Nachlassquote 
angeboten  hat,  wenn  dieser  der  Mutter  die  strittigen  Objekte  durch 

1  M.  Gelzer,  Studien  zur  byzantin.  Verwaltung  Agyptens  (1909). 

2  F.  de  Zulueta,  De  patrociniis  vicorum,   in  Vinogradoff,  Oxford  Studies 
in  Social  and  Legal  History,  vol.  i.  (1909). 

3  Vgl.   zur    ganzen    Frage    die    Ausfiihrungen    Wilckens,    Grundzuge  d. 
Papyruskunde,  314-326. 

4  Catalogue    general    des    antiquites    tgyptiennes  du   Musee   du  Caire,    i. 
(1910-11),  ii.  (1911-13). 

5  P.  Mon.  6  der  Ausgabe.     Ein  Stuck  der  Urkunde  befmdet  sich  als  Lond. 
Inv.  Nr.   1807  im  British  Museum.      Danach  ist  die  Datierung  auf  das  Jahr 
583  moglich.      Ich  darf  schon  hier  den  Herren  Kenyon  und  Bell  fiir  freund- 
liche  Mitteilungen  und  Gestattung  der  Einsichtnahme  in  die  Londoner  Gruppe 
der  Syene-Papyri  herzlichst  danken. 


in]  Romische  Rechtsgeschichte  29 

einen  Exekutor  kurzerhand  wegnehmen  lasse,  der  Richter  aber  ist 
dazu  bereit  gewesen  ;  und  der  andere  Richter,  vor  den  die  Frage  zur 
neuerlichen  Entscheidung  kommt,  hat  das  mit  dem  milden  Tadel 
zugegeben,  die  Richter  sollten  nicht  x^fyv  vorgehen. 

Auch  die  Militarverwaltung  wird  erst  durch  diese  Papyri  in 
rechtes  Licht  gestellt.  Eine  vor  Kurzem  erschienene  Arbeit 
Masperos1  hat  denn  auch  ausser  den  Kairenern  schon  die 
Miinchenertexte  ausfiihrlich  herangezogen. 

Fur  die  Heeresverwaltung  ist  entsprechend  dem  Streben  nach 
zentralistischer  Einheit  die  starke  Verwendung  lateinischer  termini 
nur  natiirlich.  Eine  Auslese  aus  den  Miinchenertexten  bringt  den 

dSiovriop,  aKTOvdpios,  avyowraAios,  /^t/capios,  /3iKa/uavos,  Sov£,  SpaKovdpios, 
Ka(3a\\dpLo<s,  Kcvrvpiwv,  opSivdpcos,  Trpcu'^eKTOs,  Tr/ai/xi/ce^ios,  die  Trpiopes,  den 

reiptov  und  rpi(3ovvo<$.  Neben  dem  fypovpiov  steht  das  Kacrr/ooi/,  neben 
dem  apifyios  die  Aeyewv.  Auf  Grund  der  Tcpo^ar^pia  wird  der  Rekrut 
(vcoo-T/aaTos,  TCI/MOV)  in  die  /xar/nf  eingetragen  und  am  Ende  schreibt 
man  ihm  auf  die  Bescheinigung  in  woKl  griechischen  Lettern  /?eve 
/3aAea9.  In  der  Prozesssprache  begegnen  die  Ocia  dSvovranw,  die 
divina  adnotatio,  und  die  Beta  ftp/la  des  Kaisers.2 

Neben  dem  Verwaltungsrecht  haben  die  byzantinischen  Papyri 
aber  auch  das  Privat-  und  Prozessrecht  ungemein  bereichert.  Hier 
ist  die  herkommliche  Darstellung  noch  durchaus  ruckstandig.  Das 
hat  schon  bald  nach  dem  Erscheinen  des  ersten  Heftes  der  Kairo- 
Papyri  Mitteis  konstatiert  und  eine  zusammenfassende  Betrachtung 
des  justinianischen  Rechts  nicht  als  Endpunkt  von  Untersuchungen 
iiber  friihere  Zeiten,  sondern  als  eines  selbstandigen  Erkenntnis- 
gegenstandes  als  dringendes  Bediirfnis  bezeichnet.3  Partsch 4  hat 
aus  diesen  Urkunden  wertvolle  neue  Resultate  zum  justinianischen 
Reskriptenprozess  gewonnen,  und  Collinet6  hat  kiirzlich  einem 
beginnenden  Werke  uber  das  justinianische  Recht  den  Untertitel 
gegeben :  Le  caractere  oriental  de  Pauvre  legislative  de  Justinien 
et  les  destinies  des  institutions  classiques  en  Occident.  In  der 
Betrachtung  der  justinianischen  Gesetzgebung  droht  uber  der  Inter - 

1  Organisation  militaire  de  vAgypte  Byzantine  (1912). 

2  Zu  alledem  vervveise  ich  auf  die   alsbald    erscheinende  Ausgabe   der 
Miinchener  Papyri  und  einstweilen  auf  meinen  Vorbericht  in  den  Sitz.  Ber. 
Bayer.  Akad.  (1911),  8.  Abh. 

3  Zeitschr.  Sa-uigny  Stiff,  f.  Rechtsgesch.,  Rom,  Abt.  xxxi.  S.  393. 

4  Gott.  Nachrichten,  phil.-hist.  Kl.  (1911),  201  ff. 

5  £tudes  historiques  sur  le  Droit  de  Justinien^  i.  (1912). 


30  L.  IVenger  [in 

polationenjagd  die  Wertung  der  interpolierten  Texte,  das  eigentlich 
Justinianische  am  ganzen  Werk,  zu  kurz  zu  kommen. 

Diese  Justinianische  Gesetzgebung  darf  aber  nicht  bloss  nicht 
als  Endpunkt  vorhergehender  Rechtsentwickelung,  sondern  auch 
nicht  bloss  als  Anfangspunkt  der  spateren  nationalen  Privatrechts- 
geschichte  in  den  Landern  der  Rezeption  aufgefasst  werden. 
Flir  sich,  als  selbstandige  Grosse  gehort  sie  in  die  Darstellung  der 
vierten  Periode  der  romischen  Rechtsgeschichte. 

Ich  habe  endlich  des  Strafrechts  nur  ganz  zu  Anfang  Erwah- 
nung  getan.  Es  muss  natiirlich  in  seiner  Entwickelung  durch 
alle  Perioden  verfolgt  werden.  Mommsens  Romisches  Strafrecht 
erleichtert  uns  diese  Aufgabe  ganz  besonders.  Auch  dieses  Werk 
des  Meisters  darf  nicht  ungeniitzt  verstauben.  Und  wenn  jiingst, 
von  der  Kritik  Mommsens  ausgehend,  James  Leigh  Strachan- 
Davidson1  einzelne  Fragen  des  romischen  Kriminalrechts  in 
ausfuhrlicher  Behandlung  gesammelt  hat,  so  hat  er  gewiss  in 
Mommsens  Sinne  gehandelt,  der  nichts  weniger  wollte,  als  dass  auch 
mit  seiner  Arbeit  ein  Arbeitsgebiet  als  ausgeschopft  verlassen  werde. 

Kaum  irgendwo  sehen  wir  so  wie  im  Strafrechte  eine  Wellen- 
bewegung  in  der  romischen  Kulturentwickelung  :  die  Frage  nach 
dem,  was  Straftat  sein  konne  und  die  Frage  nach  dem  Ubel,  nach 
der  Strafe,  welche  die  Tat  vergelten  oder  den  Tater  bessern  oder 
andere  von  gleicher  Tat  abschrecken  soil,  und  was  an  Strafrechts- 
theorien  es  sonst  noch  geben  mag,  all  diese  Fragen  beantworten  die 
Jahrhunderte  auch  der  romischen  Geschichte  verschieden.  Wie  hat 
sich,  um  nur  eines  zu  nennen,  Begriff  und  Ahndung  des  Staats- 
verbrechens  und  des  crimen  laesae  maiestatis  im  Laufe  der  Zeiten 
gewandelt !  Hier  auch  zeigen  uns  jetzt  die  Urkunden  Menschen, 
die  fehlen  und  biissen,  Richter,  die  verurteilen  und  strafen.  Ich 
erinnere  etwa  nur  an  den  Papyruskodex,  Berliner  Griechische 
Urkunden  IV.  Nr.  1024,  worin  uns  Prozesse  vor  dem  Statthalter 
aus  dem  4.  Jhd.  n.  Chr.  iiberliefert  sind.  Immer  resiimiert  der 
Statthalter  den  Tatbestand  und  schliesst  daran  das  Urteil :  einmal 
handelt  es  sich  um  Ermordung  der  mit  dem  Ehebrecher  ertappten 
Frau  durch  den  beleidigten  Gatten,  hier  ist  das  Urteil  verloren  ;  in 
einem  anderen  Falle  hat  der  Tater  sich  Grabschandung  zu  Schulden 
kommen  lassen :  da  sagt  der  Richter  in  rhetorisch  gehobener 
Sprache : 

1  Problems  of  the  Roman  Criminal  Law ',,2  Bde.,  1912. 


in]  Romische  Rechtsgeschichte  31 

„  Du  hast  den  Toten  ausgegraben,  den  die  Stadt  auf  Volks- 
beschluss  beerdigt  und  betrauert  hat.  Du  scheinst  mir  das  Herz 
eines  Tieres  zu  haben  und  nicht  eines  Menschen,  oder  eigentlich 
auch  nicht  einmal  das  eines  Tieres.  Denn  auch  die  Tiere 
greifen  zwar  die  Menschen  an,  sie  schonen  aber  die  Toten.  Du 
aber  hast  dich  an  einem  Leichnam  vergriffen,  der  schon  ausge- 
schieden  war  aus  dem  Geschlechte  der  Menschen.  Wo  nahmst  du 
den  Mut  her,  den  schon  zur  Ruhe  Gelegten  auch  noch  der  letzten 
Hoffnung  zu  berauben?  Fiirwahr  beim  Zeus  es  war  der  letzte 
Schmuck,  den  die  Gesetze  gewahren,  es  waren  Geschenke  der 
Stadt  an  den  Toten,  es  waren  Siihngaben.  So  wirst  du  denn  fur 
deine  Tat  mit  deinem  Haupte  biissen." 

Nicht  weniger  wirken  schon  rein  menschlich  die  folgenden  Falle, 
die  in  der  genannten  Urkunde  beisammen  stehen.1 

Doch  ich  muss  mit  Einzelheiten  abbrechen. 

Wie  im  Strafrecht,  so  in  der  Geschichte  der  Latifundien, 
wie  in  der  Schutzvorschrift  fur  den  Schuldner  gegen  den 
wuchernden  Glaubiger,  so  in  der  Norm  der  freien  Beweiswiirdigung 
und  der  entgegenstehenden  Festlegung  bestimmter  Beweisregeln, 
wie  in  der  Regelung  des  Erbrechts,  so  in  der  Frage,  wer  im  Heere 
dienen  soil,  jeder  Burger  oder  der  fremde  Soldling,  wie  in  den 
Problemen  der  Steuergesetzgebung,  so  in  denen  des  Verhaltnisses 
des  Staats  zu  seinen  Nationen'  und  Konfessionen,  und  wie  die 
Fragen  alle  heissen  mogen,  die  der  Rechtshistoriker  stellt  und 
beantwortet  zu  sehen  wiinschte — Uberall  sind  es  nicht  bloss  Probleme, 
die  den  Juristen  interessieren,  sondern  Probleme  der  Geschichte  der 
Menschheitskultur. 

Das  alles  aber  —  wir  diirfen  mit  einem  Schlagwort  sagen : 
Mommsens  Lebensarbeit — soil  in  einer  romischen  Rechtsgeschichte 
verarbeitet  sein.  Sie  wird  dann  allerdings  an  Umfang  zunehmen 
miissen,  aber  es  lasst  sich  vielleicht  auch  hier  ein  Mass  finden,  das 
dem  Studierenden  und  Gebildeten  doch  mehr  bietet,  als  eine  Auf- 
zahlung  von  Leges  und  Senatuskonsulten,  als  eine  trockene  Anein- 
anderreihung  der  Namen  der  Juristen,  die  das  romische  Recht 
geschaffen  haben,  und  der  Titel  ihrer  Werke.  Nie  darf  der 
Ausblick  auf  die  antike  Rechtsgeschichte  uberhaupt  versaumt 
werden.  Nie  sollte  aber  auch  der  Rechtshistoriker  an  dem  vor- 

1  Besprochen  von  Wenger  in  Gross'  Archiv  fur  Kriminal- Anthro- 
pologie^  xvi.  304-323. 


32  L.  JVenger  [m 

iibergehen,  was  auf  anderen  Gebieten  der  antiken  Geschichts- 
forschung  und  der  Philologie  zu  Tage  kommt.  Die  Zeit  der 
splendid  isolation  der  romischen  Rechtswissenschaft  ist  auch  fur 
Deutschland  voriiber  und  soil,  so  wollen  wir  hoffen,  nicht  wieder 
kommen. 

Mag  es  unerfullbarer  Optimismus  sein,  dass  ein  einzelner,  dessen 
eigene  Arbeit  nur  auf  kleinem  Gebiete  sich  bewegt,  das  weite 
Arbeitsfeld  auch  nur  ganz  zu  ubersehen  vermochte,  dass  es  ihm, 
auch  wo  er  bescheiden  nur  sichten  und  sammeln  wollte,  gelange, 
iiberall  die  Spreu  vom  Weizen  zu  sondern — aber  welche  Arbeit  ist 
je  ohne  frischen  Optimismus  begonnen  worden  ?  Freilich,  mehr 
denn  bisher  bedarf  das  neu  zustromende  Quellenmaterial  der 
Bearbeitung  in  entsagender  Einzelforschung  und  hier  darf  vielleicht 
der  Jurist  an  die  Universalhistoriker  die  Bitte  richten,  mehr  noch 
als  bisher  den  juristischen  Quellen,  den  Rechtsurkunden  vor  allem, 
ihr  Augenmerk  zuzuwenden.  Viel  gemeinsame  Arbeit  ist  noch  zu 
tun,  um  auch  auf  dem  Gebiete  der  Rechtserkenntnis  vorwarts- 
zukommen,  um  auch  hier  aus  der  Geschichte  die  Lehre  furs  Leben 
zu  ziehen,  zu  sehen,  welche  kulturellen  Voraussetzungen  diese  oder 
jene  Folgen  zeitigen,  das  Ideal  zu  verwirklichen,  soweit  Menschen- 
kraft  es  vermag,  das,  wie  jedem  Geschichtsforscher,  so  auch  dem 
Rechtshistoriker  vorschwebt : 

Rerum  cognoscere  causas. 

L.  WENGER. 


IV 

DALLA   COMMUNIO   DEL   DIRITTO   QUIRI- 
TARIO  ALLA  COMPROPRIETA  MODERNA 

1.  LA  comproprieta   osservata   negli  scritti    dei    giureconsulti 
romani  ha  la  proporzione  di  una  figura  geometrica,  in  cui  P  insieme 
dei  punti  e  delle  linee  concorrono  a  formare  una  superficie  com- 
passata  con  precisione  e  che  percio  costituisce  ancora  la  base  di 
tutte  le  trattazioni  moderne ;    cioe  a  partire  dal  sec.  xvi  fino  ai 
nostri  giorni.     Ma  nondimeno  e  vero  che  hel  Corpus  Juris  Civilis, 
lungo  quelle  linee  regolari,  tratto  tratto  appariscono  delle  curve  che 
sono  delle  incognite  nella  scienza ;   e  siccome  esse   premono  sui 
punti  fondamentali  dell'  istituto,  ne  turbano  d'  un  tratto  P  armonia  e 
conducono  gli  scrittori  a  formule  indecise,  complicate  e  tortuose. 

La  presente  trattazione  e  dedicata  a  svelare  la  natura  di  quelle 
deviazioni  ed  il  loro  valore,  che  e  veramente  altissimo ;  perche 
quelle  linee  divergenti  nella  figura  della  communio  romana  costi- 
tuiscono  in  realta  i  fondamenti  della  comproprieta  moderna. 

Ma  e  imprescindibile  che  anche  qui  P  impostatura  dello  istituto 
classico  sia  designata  come  quella  che  costituisce  il  punto  di  par- 
tenza  da  cui  si  muove  la  formazione  dell'  opera  futura. 

CAP.  I 

DIRITTO  CLASSICO 

2.  La  comproprieta  romana  vive  e  si  esplica  in  tutto  secondo  i 
principii  fondamentali  del  dominio  quiritario,  che  e  essenzialmente 
esclusivo  ed  abbraccia  la  cosa  intera  in  tutti  i  suoi  rapporti. 

Di  conseguenza  e  impossibile  che  il  dominio  su  di  una  cosa 
possa  appartenere  in  solidum  a  piu  persone.  E  possibile  invece  che 
diritti  molteplici  di  dominio  coesistano  sulla  cosa  medesima  in 

33  D 


34  S-  Riccobono  [iv 

maniera  da  limitarsi  a  vicenda.  La  limitazione  e  di  natura 
meccanica ;  nel  senso  che  il  diritto  di  ciascuno  dei  titolari  incontra 
un  ostacolo  nel  concorrente  diritto  di  altri ;  e  perci6  esso  deve  di 
necessita  arrestarsi  entro  un  limite  insuperabile.  E  la  limitazione  e 
di  natura  meccanica  ancora  nel  senso  che  essa  non  porta  tra  i 
diritti  molteplici  alcun  coordinamento ;  e  quindi  nessuna  distri- 
buzione  delle  facolta  di  dominio  e  nessuna  dipendenza  tra  i  titolari 
del  medesimo.  I  quali  sono  tutti  domini?-  ed  hanno  tutti  rispetto 
alia  cosa  una  posizione  pari.  Tale  posizione  si  manifesta  in  tutta  la 
sua  efficienza  nelle  conseguenze. 

(a)  Ciascuno  dei  titolari  esercita  il  suo  potere  di  dominio  colla 
massima  indipendenza  dagli  altri ;  puo  disporre  del  suo  diritto  come 
e  quando  vuole,  presupposto  che  con  ci6  non  offenda  il  diritto  pari 
degli  altri.     Tale  carattere  hanno,  di  regola,  tutti  gli  atti  di  disposi- 
zione  giuridica  della  cosa.     E  pertanto  guardata  da  questo  punto  di 
vista  la  comproprieta  romana  ha  nulla  di  particolare  ;  essa  si  esplica 
in  tutto  nel  modo  consueto,  secondo  i  principii  e  le  norme  che  valgono 
per  il  dominio  solitario. 

(b)  All'  opposto  qualsiasi  disposizione  che  si  realizza  con  atti 
materiali  sulla  cosa,  ovvero  quella  disposizione  giuridica  che  per 
sua  natura  investe  la  cosa  intera,  non  sono  consentite  ad  uno  dei 
condomini  singolarmente ;  infatti  1'  agire  in  quel  modo  di  un  socio 
verrebbe  a  costituire  una  menomazione  del  diritto,  una  invadenza 
della  sfera  giuridica  degli  altri : 

quodammodo  sibi  alienum  quoque  ius  praeripit,  si  quasi  solus 
dominus  ad  suum  arbitrium  uti  iure  commune  velit.2 

Atti  di  questa  sorta  possono  effettuarsi  sulla  cosa  comune  soltanto 
col  consenso  di  tutti  i  titolari,  nessuno  eccettuato.  Se  la  volonta 
di  un  solo  manca,  abbia  pur  questi  nella  comunione  una  parte 
minima,  1*  atto  e  illegittimo.  E  perci6,  quando  le  volonta  dei  singoli 
condomini  sono  in  disaccordo  rispetto  a  quella  data  categoria  di 
disposizioni  della  cosa  ne  deriva  un  conflitto  di  diritti,  e  1'  effetto 
che  segue  deve  di  necessita  essere  negative :  colui  che  nega  e 
poziore.  Ci6  e  inevitabile. 

Onde  il    principio  potior  est  causa  prohibentis  forma  precisa- 

1  D.  x.  i,  4,  5,  Paul,  xxiii.  ad  ed.  plures  dominos  \  D.  viii.  2,  26  ;   10 ;  3, 
28,  nemo  dominorum. 

2  D.  viii.  5,  1 1. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  35 

mente  P  asse  dell'  istituto  della  communio ;  in  quanto  1'  istituto 
assurge,  per  aspetti  determinati,  ad  una  figura  particolare  di  diritto. 
Ed  il  principio  entra  in  azione,  come  s'  e  detto,  tutte  le  volte 
che  i  titolari  dei  dominii  non  si  accordano  circa  1*  uso,  il  godimento, 
la  conservazione,  la  destinazione  della  cosa,  o  rispetto  ad  atti  di  dis- 
posizione  giuridica  che  colpiscono  necessariamente  la  cosa  intera. 
fe  appena  necessario  poi  notare  che  quel  principio  stesso  rappre- 
senta  pure  la  manifestazione  piu  vivace  ed  estrema  della  indipen- 
denza  assoluta  dei  singoli  condomini.  Ed  invero,  nel  disaccordo  il 
potere  dei  singoli  si  paralizza  e  P  azione  deve  arrestarsi,  perche  la 
risultante  di  piu  forze  eguali  applicate  in  senso  contrario  sullo  stesso 
corpo  non  pu6  essere  che  negativa  :  I'immobilita. 

3.  Tale  effetto  fu  constatato  dai  giuristi  piu  antichi.    Labeone 

10  applica  come  di  evidenza  intuitiva ;  percio  nega  tra  condomini 
la  denuncia  di  nuova  opera :  et  putat  Labeo  non  posse  nuntiare, 
quia  possum  eum  alia  ratione  prohibere  aedificare.'1 

E  Proculo,  citato  da  Paolo,  asseriva  gia  non  posse  prohiberi 
vicinum,  quo  minus  balineum  habeat  secundum  parietem  com- 
munem. 2  II  giurista  contemplava  in  questo  luogo  casi  in  cui  uno 
dei  condomini  del  muro  avesse  operate  qualcosa  entro  i  confini 
della  sua  proprieta  attigua  in  suoy  in  maniera  da  non  invadere  la 
cosa  comune.  Per  contrario  si  deduce  che  posse  prohiberi  quando 
1'  opera  o  qualsiasi  disposizione  materiale  si  realizzino^  sulla  cosa 
medesima. 

4.  Ma  la  dottrina  dello  ius  prohibendi  va  particolarmente  sotto 

11  nome  di  Sabino,  il  quale  la  formu!6  in  una  massima  celeberrima, 
che  costituisce  appunto  il  cardine  dello  istituto  della  comproprieta. 

fr.  28  D.  x.  3,  Pap.  vii.  qu.  Sabinus  ait  in  re  communi  neminem 
dominorum  iure  facere  quicquam  invito  altero  posse.  Unde  mani- 
festum  est  prohibendi  ius  esse  ;  in  re  enim  pari potiorem  causam  esse 
prohibentis  constat. 

La  massima  propria  di  Sabino  e  riferita  da  Papiniano  integral- 
mente,  e  si  contiene  nel  primo  periodo :  Sabinus  .  .  .  posse,  come 
e  palese  per  la  costruzione  indiretta  e  dai  confronti  che  vedremo 
subito. 

Nei  periodi  che  seguono  Papiniano  enuncia  :  dapprima  la  con- 
seguenza  immediata  che  scaturisce  da  quel  principio  di  diritto,  cioe 
1  D.  xxxix.  i,  3,  2.  2  D.  viii.  2,  19  pr. 


36  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

10  ius  prohibendi  \  ingiunge  poi  la  ragione  intrinseca  di  tal  diritto 
in  modo  positive,  vale  a  dire :  «  perche  essendo  pari  la  condizione 
dei  titolari  dei  dominii  il  diritto  di  veto  e  necessariamente  poziore. » 

11  testo  contiene  cosl  tutta  la  dottrina  della  communio  romana  :  il 
principio  di  fondo,  la  conseguenza  piu  diretta  ed  operativa,  ed  infine 
la  ragione  dommatica  che  rivela  la  intima  essenza  di  tutte  le  norme 
e  degli  effetti  specifici  del  condominio,  e  li  coordina. 

II  testo  merita  per  cio  di  essere  annoverato  tra  i  piu  cospicui 
usciti  dalla  penna  del  grande  giurista.  Papiniano  vi  e  tutto 
presente,  con  la  visione  completa  dell'  istituto,  con  la  sua  logica 
temprata,  che  sa  concatenare  in  modo  rapido  e  saldo  i  fatti,  i 
principii  di  diritto  ed  insieme  gli  effetti.1 

5.  Ora  sappiamo  dunque  che  lo  ius  prohibendi  aveva  costituito 
gia  il  punto  di  partenza  nella  formazione  della  dottrina  della  com- 
proprieta,  e  che  e  veramente  il  cardine  su  cui  1'  istituto  si  muove. 
Per  ci6  si  riscontra  in  applicazioni  varie  negli  scritti  dei  giurecon- 
sulti,  che  vanno  qui  considerate. 

fr.  ii  D.  viii.  5,  Marcell.  vi.  dig.  .  .  .  prohibendi  potius  quam 
faciendi  esse  ius  socio,  quia  magis  ille,  qui  facere  conatur,  ut  dixi, 
quodammodo  sibi  alienum  quoque  ius  praeripit,  si  quasi  solus 
dominus  ad  suum  arbitrium  uti  iure 2  communi  velit. 

II  fondamento  che  Marcello  attribuisce  qui  allo  ius  prohibendi 
ha  una  direzione  particolare,  che  verra  posta  in  luce  piu  oltre ;  per 
ora  dico  solo  che  quell'  elemento  approssimativo  espresso  dal 
quodammodo  non  diminuisce,  in  confronto,  la  ratio  iuris  espressa 
da  Papiniano  ;  ma  anzi  la  esalta,  perche  Marcello  giunge  a  con- 
siderare,  in  certo  modo,  il  socio  che  opera  senza  il  consenso  del- 
T  altro  sulla  cosa  comune,  come  un  estraneo  che  affronti  il  diritto  di 
proprieta  altrui.  L'  analogia  e  di  grande  rilievo,  come  T  effetto  che 
ne  deriva,  che  vedremo  ben  tosto. 

fr.  27  D.  viii.  2,  Pomp,  xxxiii.  ad  Sab.  .  .  .  socius  prohibendi 
ius  habet  .  .  .  quia  invito  socio  in  iure*  communi  non  habeas 
ius  aedificandi. 

Qui  la  massima  di  Sabino  serve  di  base  alia  decisione,  ed  ha  la 
forza  di  una  regola  di  diritto  da  cui  quella  conseguenza  promana. 

1  Si  noti  per  altro  che  la  parita  della  posizione  giuridica  dei  condomini  e 
messa  in  evidenza  da  Giuliano :  fr.   27   D.  viii.   3  ...  quia  par  utriusque 
domini  ius  in  utroque  fundo  esse  incipit. 

2  re  Mo.  3  re  leg. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  37 

Ed  infine  Paolo  ne  fa  un'  applicazione  particolarissima  in  materia 
di  servitu : 

fr.  26  D.  viii.  2,  Paul.  xv.  ad  Sab.  In  re  communi  nemo 
dominorum  \iure  servitutis\  neque  facere  quicquam  invito  altero 
potest  neque  prohibere  quo  minus  alter  faciat ;  nulli  enim  res  sua 
servit. 

Nella  prima  parte  la  formula  di  Paolo  combacia  perfettamente 
con  quella  di  Papiniano  ;  essa  e  dunque  tratta  alia  lettera  dal- 
F  opera  di  Sabino.  Ma  vi  e  tuttavia  una  differenza  rimarchevole  che 
si  manifesta  subitamente  per  la  parola  servitutis  incuneata  nella 
formulazione  di  Sabino,  e  che  viene  a  limitare  inaspettatamente 
ed  in  maniera  essenziale  la  forza  e  la  estensione  della  regola 
medesima. 

Secondo  Sabino  il  socio  pu6  nulla  fare  sulla  cosa  comune  senza 
il  consenso  degli  altri ;  e  ci6  iure  =  per  diritto,  e  non  gia  iure 
servitutis. 

Tra  T  una  cosa  e  F  altra,  come  ognun  vede,  la  distanza  e  enorme. 
Non  si  tratta  di  semplice  proporzione,  come  di  cose  che  stanno  fra 
loro  nel  rapporto  del  generale  al  particolare,  ma  di  enunciazioni 
sostanzialmente  diverse.  Quella  che  si  legge  nel  testo  di  Paolo  e 
falsa  ;  perche  il  socio  puo  mai  operare  sul  fondo  comune  iure 
servitutis,  nemmeno  col  consenso  delF  altro.  Infatti  F  ostacolo 
alia  servitu  e  nel  potere  di  dominio  che  egli  ha  sulla  cosa  comune, 
e  non  gia  nel  divieto  del  socio. 

Questo  principio,  che  peraltro  discende  dalla  struttura  del 
condominio  romano,  e  messo  in  evidenza  da  Giavoleno,  il  quale 
nega  tra  socii  la  possibilita  dell'  actio  negatoria,  appunto  perch& 
quel  che  e  comune  appartiene  a  ciascuno  dei  compartecipi  di  pieno 
diritto :  nam  quod  communiter  socius  habet  et.  in  iure l  eum  habere 
constitit. 

Per  la  stessa  ragione  non  e  possibile  la  costituzione  di  servitu 
tra  due  fondi,  dei  quali  uno  sia  comune  e  F  altro  di  proprieta 
esclusiva  di  uno  dei  socii.2 

1  fr.  4  D.  xxxiii.  3,  Jav.  ix.  ep.     La  preposizione  in  e  nel  brano  riferito 
sicuramente  inopportuna ;    Mommsen   corregge  :    item  iure  me  habere,  ma 
1'  emendazione  e  arbitraria  e  nel  risultato  banale  ;   io  proporrei :  pleno  iure 
\domini  iure?}  eum  habere ;    cfr.  D.  x.  i,  4,  7  ;  xi.   3,    14,   2  .   .  .  perinde 
atque  si proprius  meus  servus  cet ;  D.  xlvii.  io,  15,  36  .   .  .  cum  iure  domini 
idfecerit. 

2  Cfr.  32  D.  viii.  3,  Afric.  vi.  quaest. 


38  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

E  nelle  stesse  condizioni  di  fatto  e  esclusa  1'  actio  finium  re- 
gundorum  perche  ego  et  socius  meus  .  .  .  unius  loco  habemurl 

E  perci6  la  frase  invito  socio>  che  e  essenziale  nella  formula 
di  Sabino,  respinge  con  fermezza  qualsiasi  riferimento  alia  servitus. 
E  tuttavia  non  bisogna  supporre  una  grave  alterazione  del  testo, 
dacche  io  credo  si  possa  rimettere  in  ordine  con  un  semplice 
spostamento  della  parola  servitutis^  che  deve  avere  piuttosto 
la  sua  collocazione  nel  secondo  membro  del  periodo,  come  segue : 

In  re  communi  nemo  dominorum  neque  facere  [iure']  quicquam 
invito  altero  potest  neque  prohibere  [iure  servitutis~\  quo  minus  alter 
facial :  nulli  enim  res  sua  servit. 

Paolo,  dunque,  metteva  in  relazione  la  massima  di  Sabino  con 
la  dottrina  delle  servitu,  e  cio  in  modo  veramente  opportuno, 
perche  egli  trattava  in  quel  luogo  de  servitutibus?  ed  intendeva 
precipuamente  far  notare  che  il  socio  nemmeno  ha  facolta  di 
proibire  iure  servitutis  quo  minus  alter  faciat. 

La  ragione  e  manifesta ;  che  avendo  ciascuno  dei  condomini 
un  pieno  diritto  sulla  cosa,  tra  i  medesimi  non  vi  e  possibilita  di 
esercizio  o  pretesa  di  servitu,  e  di  conseguenza  e  preclusa  la  via 
allo  esperimento  dell'  actio  negatoria  :  nulli  res  sua  servit.  Questo 
punto  di  diritto,  per  altro,  ci  e  noto  dal  passo  di  Giavoleno  sopra 
riferito,  e  da  altri  testi  classici  che  verranno  subito  in  esame  ;  esso 
fu  posto  in  grande  evidenza  da  Cuiacio,  che  interpreto  rettamente 
il  fr.  in  esame,  senza  proporne  1'  emendamento.3 

I  moderni  hanno  avvertito  le  difficolta  del  passo,  ma  non  le 
hanno  superate.  Se  poi  la  dislocazione  della  frase  iure  servitutis 
debba  attribuirsi  a  svista  di  amanuensi  ovvero  all'  opera  dei  com- 
pilatori  e  cosa  che  non  posso  giudicare. 

Certo  molti  argomenti  rendono  piu  verisimile  la  seconda  ipotesi ; 
infatti  il  lettore  trovera  piu  oltre  prove  sufficienti  per  convincersi  che 
Giustiniano  si  adopr6  deliberatamente  a  stremare  in  tutti  i  modi 
la  regola  di  Sabino,  che  affermava  nella  maniera  piu  recisa  la 
indipendenza  dei  singoli  condomini  rispetto  alia  cosa  comune,  e  che 
inoltre  egli  trasformo  lo  ius  prohibendi  in  un'  azione  giudiziaria. 

6.  E  lo  ius  prohibendi  si  determina  ora  con  precisione.     Esso 

1  D.  x.  i,  4,  7. 

2  Cfr.  Lenel,  Pal  \.  c.  1289. 

3  Cfr.    Opp.  vol.  vii.  p.  676  ad  1.  27  (8-2)  ;  ibid.  p.  674  ad  1.  26  eod.  ; 
ibid.  p.  737  ad  1.  n  (8-5);  ibid.  p.  945  e,  p.  2223  ad  1.  4,  D.  xxxiii.  3. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  39 

scaturisce,  come  conseguenza  ineluttabile,  dalla  posizione  pari  dei 
condomini.  E  un  effetto  naturale  del  dominio  posto  in  quella 
particolare  situazione ;  e  perci6  e  enunciate  come  un  diritto  fonda- 
mentale  e  caratteristico,  che  entra  in  azione  tutte  le  volte  che 
T  accordo  tra  i  condomini  si  rompe. 

Prohibere  non  s'  intende  nel  senso  che  al  socio  competa  1*  actio 
negatoria  o  prohibitoria  contro  T  altro.  Ma  significa,  invece,  che 
ciascuno  dei  socii  pu6  direttamente  impedire  con  la  forza,  di  sua 
autorita,  T  opera  o  qualsiasi  azione  sulla  cosa  intrapresa  dall'  altro. 
Tale  significato  e  fuori  dubbio.  Marcello  contrappone  prohibere 
&  facere,  ed  i  due  termini  si  rapportano  sicuramente  all'  ingerenza 
materiale,  che  e  positivamente  (facere)  inibita  a  ciascuno  dei  socii 
ove  manchi  il  consenso  degli  altri ;  ed  e  invece  negativamente 
(prohibere)  permessa  a  ciascuno  per  impedire  qualsiasi  uso  della 
cosa  contro  la  sua  volonta.  Ma  il  passo  di  Marcello  subl  una  grave 
mutilazione  ed  e  nei  Digesti  del  seguente  tenore : 

fr.  1 1  D.  viii.  5,  Marc.  vi.  dig.  An  unus  ex  sociis  in  communi  loco 
invitis  ceteris  iure  aedificare  possit,  id  est  an,  si  prohibeatur  a  sociis, 
possit  cum  his  ita  experiri  ius  sibi  esse  aedificare,  et  an  socii  cum  eo 
ita  agere  possint  ius  sibi  prohibendi  esse  vel  illi  ius  aedificandi  non 
esse :  et  si  aedificatum  iam  sit,  num  possint l  cum  eo  ita  experiri 
ius  tibi  non  esse  ita  aedificatum  habere,  quaeritur  \et  magis  did 
potesf\ 2  prohibendi  potius  quam  faciendi  esse  ius  socio,  quia  magis 
ille,  qui  facere  conatur,  ut  dixi,  quodammodo.  sibi  alienum  quoque 


1  num  possint  Hal.  ;  non  possit  F. 

2  La  frase  et  magis  did  potest   e  interpolatizia,  inserita  dai  compilatori 
per  sopprimere  la  piu  estesa  dimostrazione  di  Marcello.      Sospetta  e  la  frase 
per  se  stessa,  che  ritorna  in  molti  testi  rimaneggiati  da  Triboniano  (magis 
infinite  volte  ;  potest  did  qualche  volta ;  cfr.  D.  xlvii.  2,  9,  i  ;  D.  ix.  4,  19  pr.) 
inoltre,  a  breve  distanza,  s'  incontra  di  nuovo  magis  che  era  nel  testo  genuine, 
e  1'  espressione  ut  dixi  non  ha  piu  riscontro  nel  passo  dei  Digesti,  mentre 
Marcello  ricollegava  cosi  la  decisione  alia  argomentazione  piu  ampia  (quaeritur) 
che  precedeva. 

Anche  il  Lenel  (ZSS.  vol.  xii.  p.  12)  osservo  con  il  solito  acume  la  di- 
minuzione  del  testo  operata  dai  compilatori,  ma  non  la  precisa,  e  percio  nel- 
1'  interpretazione  tien  conto  degli  elementi  che  vi  si  leggono,  concludendo  che 
Marcello  ammetteva  1'  actio  prohibitoria  e  non  la  negatoria.  Di  cio  piu  oltre. 

Non  ha  invece  fondamento  il  sospetto  da  Beseler  (Beitrage,  i.  p.  79,  i) 
manifestato  sul  periodo  :  id  est  .  .  .  habere ;  perche,  in  verita,  il  giurista  aveva 
posto  quesiti  fondamentali  che  si  presentavano  naturalmente  in  una  trattazione 
larga  della  dottrina. 

Ed  &  ovvio  che  tutte  quelle  formule  rassegnate  da  Marcello  rappresentavano 


40  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

ius  praeripit,  si  quasi  solus  dominus  ad  suum  arbitrium  uti  iure1 
communi  velit. 

Marcello  aveva  dovuto  negare  recisamente  la  possibilita  di 
qualsiasi  azione  tra  i  socii  a  titolo  di  servitu,  come  1'  aveva  negate 
Giavoleno ;  ed  aveva  dovuto  invece  ammettere  il  diritto  del  socio 
ad  impedire  1'  opera  comechesia,  nel  senso  che  ho  dichiarato  di 
sopra.  La  motivazione  di  Marcello,  sopravvissuta  nel  testo,  acquista 
cosl  il  suo  giusto  valore  e  perfetta  proporzione ;  perche  essa  e 
indirizzata  a  giustificare  la  violenza  privata  contro  il  socio  che 
disponendo  della  cosa  a  suo  arbitrio :  sibi  alienum  quoque  ius 
praeripit.  Ne  pu6  sorprendere  in  questo  luogo  la  legittimazione 
della  privata  difesa ;  avvegnache  il  diritto  di  ciascuno  dei  socii 
d'  impedire  con  la  forza  qualsiasi  ingerenza  o  di  distruggere  1'  opera 
eseguita  sulla  cosa  comune,  senza  preventivo  accordo,  deriva  dal 
potere  essenziale  di  dominio  che  ciascuno  ha  sulla  medesima.  II 
proprietario  non  e  tenuto  a  tollerare  che  altri  faccia  in  suo 
alcunche  contro  il  suo  volere ;  piuttosto  egli  puo  distruggere 
P  opera  di  sua  autorita  :  iure  suo  posse  eum  intercidere,  et  merito^  .  .  . 
quod  hie  in  suo  protexit? 

Questo  principio  non  soffre  restrizione  nel  condominio ;  pre- 
cisamente  per  il  motive  che  i  condomini  sono  tutti  in  pari  causa 
ed  indipendenti  P  uno  dalP  altro.  E  siffatta  conseguenza  era  pro- 
babilmente  affermata  da  Pomponio  nel  fr.  27  D.  viii.  2,  con  la  frase 
rent  perdere,  ove  le  si  attribuisca  il  valore  che  le  diedero  gl'  inter- 
preti  fin  dalla  Glossa,  cioe  che  il  socio  possa  opus  sua  auctoritate 
destruere  quando  il  condomino  agisca  senza  il  suo  consenso ;  la 
quale  frase  perci6  deve  essere  genuina,  nel  testo  rifatto  largamente 
dai  compilatori.3 

7.  Onde  i  Romani,  considerando  lo  stato  di  anarchia  in  cui  i 
socii  si  trovavano  rispetto  all'  uso  ed  al  godimento  della  cosa, 
poterono  dire  che  la  communio  e  mater  rixarum,  e  constatare,  di 

varii  attegiamenti  dell'  a.  negatoria  secondo  le  diverse  ipotesi.      Ne  la  parola 
prohibere  inclusa  in  quelle  formule  ha  un  valore  speciale  : 

cfr.  D.  viii.  5,  8,  5  :  prohiberi  posse  fumum  immittere  .  .  .  agique  sic  posse 
.  .  .  ius  ei  non  esse  fumum  immittere. 

1  re  scr. 

2  fr.  29  §  i  D.  ix.  2. 

3  Per  T  esame  di  questo  passo  v.  cap.  ii.  n.  29,  p.  61. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  41 

conseguenza,    ogni    giorno    che    propter    immensas    contentiones 
plerumque  res  ad  divisionem  pervenitl 

E  questa  affermazione  &  vera  nella  sua  interezza,  per  la  stessa 
struttura  del  condominio  e  per  le  attestazioni  concordi  degli  antichi;2 
comunque,  per  altro,  il  periodo  che  la  contiene  possa  essere  stato 
rimosso  o  ricollegato  dai  compilatori. 

8.  Affermato   cosl  il  punto  centrale  della   dottrina   del   con- 
dominio e  agevole  ora  procedere  all1  esame  di  tutte  le  conseguenze 
giuridiche  che  ne  derivano,  che  debbono  per  cio  stesso  manifestarsi 
chiare  ed  incontestabili. 

La  posizione  dei  socii  nella  comunione  e,  come  s'  e  visto,  de- 
terminata  sempre  dai  principii  fondamentali  del  dominio,  senza 
attenuazione  o  modificazione  di  sorta.  Nei  particolari  cio  si 
dimostra  mirabilmente  con  un  rapido  esame  degli  effetti  giuridici 
che  scaturiscono  dallo  stato  di  comproprieta,  sotto  T  aspetto  positive 
e  negative  ;  e  cioe  : 

(a)  in  ordine  alia  disposizione  giuridica  della  cosa  comune,  che 
compete  a  ciascuno  dei  socii. 

(£)  in  ordine  agli  atti  di  disposizione  materiale  della  cosa,  che 
non  possono  attuarsi  senza  il  concorso  di  tutti  i  compartecipi.  In 
questa  categoria  va  pure  annoverata  qualsiasi  disposizione  giuridica 
che  investe  di  necessita  la  cosa  intera,  come  avviene  per  le  servitu 
attive  o  passive. 

9.  Rispetto  al  primo  punto  e  certo  che  ognuno  dei  compro- 
prietarii  puo  esercitare  tutte  le  facolta  di  disposizione  giuridica  del 
dominio  con  lamassima  indipendenza.  Ciascuno  quindi  puovendere,8 
donare,  sottoporre  ad  ipoteca,4  costituire  usufrutto,  dare  in  dote,5 
disporre  per  testamento  o  altrimenti  alienare  la  cosa,  in  proporzione 
della  parte  che  gli  spetta,  senza  attendere  il  consenso  dei  socii,  e 
senza  che  una  qualsiasi  ingerenza  di  essi  sia  ammessa.6     L'  atto 
dispositive  dell'  alienante  ha  naturalmente  efficacia  reale  solo  nel 
limite  del  diritto  che  effettivamente  gli  compete  sulla  cosa  comune. 

1  fr.  26  D.  viii.  2. 

2  fr.   77  §  20  D.  xxxi.    .  .   .    cum   discordiis  propinquorum  sedandis  pro- 
spexei  it,  quas  materia  communionis  solet  excitare. 

3  Cod.  iv.  52,  3  (DiocL  et  Max.} ;  c.  4  e  5  eod. ;  D.  x.  2,  44,  2. 

4  D.  x.  3,  6,  9  ;  xx.  4,  3,  2  ;  xx.  6,  7,  4. 

5  Cod.  v.  12,  1 6  (DiocL  et  Max.). 

6  D.  1.  17,  26;  cfr.  Lenel,  Pal.  Ulp.  n.  2748  ;  Cod.  iv.  52,  3. 


42  5.  Riccobono  [iv 

Tale  conseguenza  e  affermata  da  Papiniano  per  la  vendita  come  per 
T  ipoteca  disposta  dal  condomino. 

II  passo  che  si  riferisce  alia  vendita  e  alquanto  oscuro  rispetto 
agli  element!  di  fatto,  che  furono  certamente  ridotti  dai  compilatori ; 
ma  per  quel  che  concerne  il  punto  in  esame  il  testo  e  sicuro  e  di 
grande  significazione. 

Nei  Digesti  &  cosi  riferito  : 

fr.  64  §  4  D.  xxi.  2,  Pap.  vii.  9.  Qui  unum  iugerum  pro 
indiviso  solum  habuit,  tradidit :  secundum  omnium  sententias  non 
totum  dominium  transtulit,  sed  partem  dimidiam  iugeri,  quemad- 
modum  si  locum  cerium  aut  fundum  similiter  tradidisset^ 

L'  alienazione  per  cio  ha  efficacia  solo  per  la  parte  che  il  socio  ha 
nella  comunione.2  E  lo  stesso  vale  per  1'  ipoteca  ;  onde  Papiniano 
con  una  fine  argomentazione  ne  deduce  che  si  possono  avere  su  di 
una  parte  d'  un  fondo  ipoteche  non  concorrenti ;  cioe  T  una  costituita 
durante  la  comunione,  che  gravera,  dopo  la  divisione,  sulle  parti  pro 
diviso,  in  ragione  di  meta  :  e  P  altra  costituita  per  garanzia  in  favore 
del  socio,  nell'  atto  divisorio,  che  investe  1'  altra  meta  :  sed  priorem 

1  Nel  passo  la  traditio  fu  sostituita  alia  mancipatio  (Lenel,  Pal.  ad  h.  1.) ; 
ma  i  compilatori  soppressero  inoltre  molti  element!  nella  relazione  del  fatto, 
che  era  certamente  piu  complicato.      Cosl  il  solum,  aggettivo  o  avverbio  che 
sia,  resto  nel  passo  senza  alcun  significato  ;  ed   invero  che  importa  cio  nel 
trasferimento    per    mane,    di    cosa   determinata  ?      Ma    il    similiter  tradid., 
poi,  rivela  che  il  giureconsulto  aveva  riferito  avanti  una  speciale  clausola  della 
mancipatio. 

lo  suppongo  che  in  un  fondo  di  Tizio  era  stato  legato  un  solo  iugero  a  due 
conliberti  senza  designazione  della  regione,  e  che  uno  dei  legatarii  mancipo 
1'  intero  ingero  che  era/r<?  indiviso  nel  fondo  di  Tizio. 

Papin.  pot&  scrivere  : 

Qui  unum  iugerum  pro  indiviso  solum  \in  fundo  Titii  commune  cum 
Simplici  conliberto  habuit  mancipio  dedit  Seio  hac  formula :  unum  iugerum 
quod  est  in  praedio  Titii  pro  indiviso\  cet. 

Si  spiegherebbe  allora  1'  aw.  similiter  che  presuppone  un'  analogia  di  specie 
che  Papiniano  usa  altre  volte,  ed  inoltre  il  confronto  con  il  locus  certus  Q/undus. 
Nel  caso  esaminato  da  Papiniano  si  doveva  trattare  di  locus  indeterminate  : 

cfr.  D.  1.  1 6,  60  :  locus  est  .  .  .  portio  aliqua  fundi  ...  §  2  ...  locus 
vero  latere  potest  quatenus  determine tur  et  definiatur.  La  mancipatio  di  pars 
pro  indiviso  doveva  del  resto  essere  frequente  nella  comunicazione  di  fondi 
societatis  causa,  cfr.  Riccobono,  Traditio  ficta,  c.  iii. 

E  quindi  errava  Cuiacio  (Opp.  iv.  p.  795  ad  h.  1.)  supponendo  che  la  traditio 
fosse  avvenuta  nel  testo  in  esame  mediante  la  semplice  consegna  dei  titoli  di 
proprieta,  in  base  all'  erroneo  concetto  che  non  fosse  possibile  tradizione  cor- 
porale  di  pars  pro  indiviso. 

2  fr.  68  D.  xvii.  2. 


iv]  Communio  e  Compropritfa  43 

secundo  non  esse  potiorem,  quoniam  secundum  pignus  ad  earn  partem 
directum  videbatur,  quam  ultra  partem  suam  f  rater  non  consentiente 
socio  non  potuit  obligare.1 

E  parimenti  i  frutti  del  fondo  spettano  a  ciascuno  dei  soci 
iure  soli,  in  proporzione  della  parte  di  dominio  che  risulta  dalla 
concorrenza  dei  diritti  degli  altri :  ita  qui  communem  fundum 
posszdet,  nonfaciet  suos  fructus  pro  ea  parte  >  qua  fundus  ad  socium 
eius  pertinebit?  La  stessa  attribuzione  vien  fatta  per  gli  increment! 
del  fondo.3 

II  quale  principle  assume  poi  una  grande  importanza  nella 
comunione  di  schiavi,  dacche  conduce  alia  regola  generale  che 
gli  acquisti  dello  schiavo  comune,  anche  se  fatti  ex  re  alterius 
dominorum,  vanno  attribuiti,  per  lo  meno  quanto  alia  forma,  a 
tutti  i  socii  pro  parte  dominiit  Effetti  cotesti  ben  congrui  e 
proporzionati  alia  struttura  del  condominio,  e  per  cio  sotto  ogni 
riguardo  necessarii  ed  inderogabili ;  avvegnache,  se,  come  si  esprime 
Papiniano,5  i  condomini  hanno  sulla  cosa  una  posizione  pari,  ne 
deriva  per  necessita  imprescindibile  che  ciascuno  dei  titolari  non 
puo  avere  una  facolta  di  disposizione  al  di  la  della  sua  parte,  e 
ciascuno  non  puo  far  suoi  i  frutti,  o  pretendere  dagli  acquisti  a 
mezzo  di  schiavi,  che  una  parte  corrispondente  a  quella  ex  qua 
dominus  est.  Ne  vi  e  ragione  per  cio  di  concepire  il  con- 
dominio romano  come  un  concorso  di  proprieta  parziali  sulla 
cosa  medesima ;  perche  cotali  effetti  si  coordinano  con  perfetta 
misura  al  concetto  della  comproprieta  integrate ;  in  cui  ciascuno 
dei  titolari  incontra  un  limite  insuperabile  nel  diritto  concorrente 
degli  altri.  Onde  necessariamente  tutte  le  facolta  del  dominio  si 
riducono  entro  quel  limite  in  cui  esso  e  in  realta  ristretto,  a  causa 
del  concorso  degli  altri  diritti. 

II  che  vuol  dire,  che  la  posizione  pari  dei  condomini  rispetto 
al  diritto  sulla  cosa,  e  poi  immanente  in  tutti  gli  effetti  giuridici 
proprii  del  dominio.  E  cosl  deve  essere.  Un'  affermazione 

1  fr.  3  §  2  D.  xx.  4,  Pap.  xi.  resp.  ;  cfr.  Gai  in  D.  xx.  6,  7,  4  :  ...  dimsione 
facta  cum  socio  non  utique  earn  partem  creditori  obligatam  esse,  quae  ei  optingit, 
qui  pignori  dedit^  sed  utriusque  pars  pro  indiviso  pro  parte  dimidia  manebit 
obligata.  2  fn  25  pr.  D.  xxii.  i  Jul.  vii.  dig. 

3  fr.  4  §  5  D.  x.  i  unusquisque  portionem  habebit  quam  in  fundo  habet  et 
pro  indiviso. 

4  D.  xli.  i,  45,  Gai  vii.  ad  ed.  pr.  ;  D.  x.  3,  24,  pr.  Jul.  viii.  dig. 

5  D.  x.  3,  28. 


44  -S1-  Riccobono  [iv 

diversa  non  avrebbe  che  un  valore  metafisico,  contrario  alia  natura 
ed  alia  forza  del  diritto. 

10.  E  per  altro  se  la  struttura  del  condominio  si  manifesta  cosl 
limpida,  osservata  dal  lato  positive,  cioe  rispetto  alle  facolta  che 
ciascuno  dei  titolari  pu6  esercitare  in  modcx  indipendente  dagli 
altri,  e  che  dai  giureconsulti  romani  sono  ammesse  con  tutta 
naturalezza ;  essa  deve  poi  mostrarsi  in  maggior  rilievo,  esplorata 
nelle  sue  manifestazioni  negative,  che  rivelano  appunto  la  im- 
possibilita  di  qualsiasi  regolamento  obbiettivo  della  comunione,  in 
ordine  agli  atti  dispositivi  sulla  cosa.  I  quali,  come  la  natura  della 
proprieta  esige,  in  qualsiasi  contingenza,  dipendono  unicamente 
dalla  volonta  unanime  dei  compartecipi.  In  contrapposto  agli 
atti  di  disposizione  giuridica  compiuti  dal  condomino,  che  mai 
possono  ledere  il  diritto  degli  altri,  sotto  il  secondo  aspetto  si  con- 
templano,  in  primo  luogo,  gli  atti  materiali  sulla  cosa  comune, 
i  quali  per  la  loro  natura,  necessariamente,  invadono  in  una  volta 
il  diritto  dei  socii.  Per  ci6  essi  sono  inibiti  ai  singoli  compartecipi 
in  modo  assoluto.  Onde  qui  entra  in  azione  e  spiega  la  sua  forza 
la  regola  di  Sabino  :  in  re  communi  neminem  dominorum  iure  facere 
quicquam  invito  alter o  posset  II  verbo  facere  si  riferisce  appunto 
a  tutti  gli  atti  materiali.  E  da  cio  segue,  che  nessuno  dei  socii  pu6 
di  propria  iniziativa  usare  la  cosa,  coltivare  il  fondo  o  eseguirvi 
miglioramenti,  costruzioni  o  in  generale  opere  nuove,  nemmeno 
semplicemente  conservative,  senza  il  consenso  di  tutti  i  condomini. 

Ne  giova  distinguere  qui  tra  gli  atti  che  sono  rivolti  ad  un  uso 
normale  della  cosa,  conforme  alia  sua  destinazione,  e  gli  atti  che 
esorbitano  da  questo  limite  e  che  importano  un  utilizzamento 
difforme  o  contrario  alia  destinazione  della  medesima. 

La  distinzione  non  puo  aver  luogo ;  perche  il  divieto  del 
facere,  qualunque  esso  sia,  deriva  dalla  forza  del  diritto  degli  altri, 
e  per  cio  e  assoluto,  ed  ha  nulla  che  vedere  con  la  natura  dell'  uso 
e  la  specie  degli  atti. 

E  pertanto,  come  la  volonta  unanime  dei  socii  e  necessaria  per 
abbattere  o  riedificare  un  muro  o  parte  di  un  edificio,  cosi  pure  le 
riparazioni  necessarie  ai  muri  ed  agli  edificii  comuni  esigono  il  volere 
concorde  di  tutti.2  A  nessuno  quindi  e  consentito  fare  uso  del 
muro  comune  o  utilizzarlo  in  qualsiasi  modo,  come  appoggiandovi 
fabbriche  o  scale  o  tubi  per  la  condotta  delle  acque. 

1  fr.  26  D.  viii.  2  ;  fr.  28  D.  x.  3.  2  D.  viii.  2,  8,  Gai  vii.  ad  ed. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  45 

II.  Su  questo  punto  per6  e  bene  fermarsi ;  perche  fin  dalla 
Glossa  si  asserisce  il  contrario,  particolarmente  rispetto  a  determinati 
utilizzamenti  della  parete  comune,  non  che  per  le  opere  riparative 
degli  edificii.  La  quale  affermazione  e  esatta  ove  si  abbia 
riguardo  al  diritto  giustinianeo,  come  vedremo  piu  oltre  ;  ma  per 
il  diritto  classico,  invece,  e  sicuramente  falsa. 

Infatti  se  in  frammenti  notissimi  dei  giuristi  romani  si  permette 
al  condomino  di  tenere  il  bagno  dappresso  la  parete  comune,  o  di 
costruire  una  camera  o  una  scala  addossata  alia  stessa,  in  tutte 
quelle  decisioni  e  presupposto  che  egli  deve  eseguire  le  opere  entro 
i  limiti  della  sua  proprieta  esclusiva ;  e  non  solo  che  il  bagno,  la 
camera  o  la  scala  non  debbono  recar  danno  al  muro,  ma  che 
debbono  inoltre  stare  del  tutto  indipendenti  da  esso.  I  testi  cui 
alludevo  sono  lucidissimi  in  questo  senso,  e  si  esprimono  nel  modo 
seguente : 

fr.  19  D.  viii.  2,  Paul.  vii.  ad  Sab.  Fistulam  iunctam  parieti 
communi,  quae  aut  ex  castello  aut  ex  coelo  aquam  capit,  non 
iure  haberi  Proculus  ait ;  sed  non  posse  prohiberi  vicinum,  quo 
minus  balineum  habeat  secundum  parietem  communem,  quamvis 
humorem  capiat  paries  ;  non  magis  quam  si  vel  in  triclinio  suo  vel 
in  cubiculo  aquam  effunderet.  Sed  Neratius  ait,  si  talis  sit  usus 
tepidarii  ut  assiduum  humorem  habeat,  et  id  noceat  vicino,  posse 
prohiberi  eum. 

§  i.  luxta  communem  parietem  cameram  ex  figlino  opere  factam, 
si  ita  retineatur,  ut  etiam  sublato  pariete  maneat  [si  modo  non 
impediat  refectionem  communis  parietis\,  iure  habere  licet. 

§  2.  Scalas  posse  me  ad  parietem  communem  habere,  Sabinus 
recte  scribit,  quia  removeri  hae  possunt. 

Tutti  i  giuristi,  come  si  vede,  sono  concordi  nell'  enunciare 
condizioni  di  fatto  tali  che  escludono  1'  uso  del  muro  comune  a 
sostegno  di  quelle  opere  o  impianti ;  che  son  fatti  bensi  tuxta, 
secundum  parietem^  cioe  addossati  al  muro  ma  non  sostenuti  da 
esso.  II  muro  comune  e  dunque  fuori  quistione  ;  tan  to  e  vero  che 
si  esige  pure  che  la  costruzione  etiam  sublato  pariete  maneat?- 

Nello  stesso  senso  e  diretta  la  argomentazione  di  Proculo  rispetto 
al  bagno :  egli  dice,  giustamente,  che  non  e  sufficiente  motivo 

1  E  per  ci6  1'  inciso  *  si  modo  non  impediat  refectionem  communis  parietis ' 
e  evidentemente  interpolatizio  ;  perche  la  condizione  enunciata  dal  giurista 
e  gia  assorbente.  Indizii  della  interpolazione :  si  modo  —  la  superflua 
ripetizione  del  sostantivo :  communis  parietis,  che  precede  immediatamente. 
La  ragione  dell'  inciso  verra  in  evidenza  nel  c.  ii.  n.  47. 


46  5.  Riccobono  [iv 

d'  impedire  al  socio  di  tenere  il  bagno  addossato  alia  parete  il  fatto 
che  vi  si  comunica  1'  umidita  ;  perche  cio  avviene  pure  nel  lavare  il 
pavimento  del  triclinio  o  del  cubiculo  versandovi  1'  acqua  a  getto. 

Da  ci6  si  desume  che  in  tutti  quei  casi  presi  in  esame  la  parete 
comune  non  e  adibita  a  sostegno  delle  opere.  II  presupposto 
essenziale  e  questo  appunto.  Se  ci6  non  e,  in  fatto,  interviene  il 
divieto.  Cosl  nel  caso  di  tubi  infissi  al  muro  per  lo  scarico  delle 
acque  piovane  o  dal  castello,  o  di  appoggio  di  una  fabbrica.1 

Ma  il  divieto  poi  di  tenere  un  forno  applicato  alia  parete 
comune 2  o  caloriferi  ha  un'  altra  ragione  piu  generale,  il  danno  cioe 
che  ne  viene  alia  fabbrica  dal  continue  calore  o  dalla  fiamma.  E 
Proculo  fa  notare  precisamente  la  distinzione  tra  i  due  casi,  con  le 
parole  :  de  tubulis  eo  amplius  hoc  iuris  esty  quod  per  eos  fiamma 
torretur  paries? 

E  evidente,  dunque,  che  il  richiamo  di  quei  passi  e  erroneo ; 
e  che  in  essi  non  pu6  trovar  appoggio  quell'  antica  dottrina  che 
consente  al  socio  P  uso  normale  della  cosa  comune,  secondo  la  sua 
destinazione.4  E  soggiungo  che  tale  dottrina  nemmeno  si  giustifica, 
per  quanto  attiene  al  diritto  classico,  invocando  la  facolta  che  ha  il 
condomino  di  abbellire  con  pitture  o  stucchi  la  parete  comune ; 
perche  se  e  lo  stesso  Proculo5  che  ammette  ci6,  egli  non  poteva 
contradirsi ;  mentre  a  togliere  qualsiasi  valore  alia  decisione  per  la 
dottrina  in  esame  della  destinazione,  basta  osservare  che  le  pareti 
non  si  costruiscono  per  le  pitture  o  per  gli  stucchi,  ne  quando  vi  si 
eseguano  pu6  dirsi  che  si  faccia  un  uso  normale  della  cosa.  La 
permissione  deve  avere  percio  altri  motivi ;  e  cioe  in  primo  luogo 
quello  che  le  pitture  e  gli  stucchi  non  toccano  e  non  ledono  la 
sostanza  della  cosa  comune ;  ed  inoltre  poi  la  considerazione  che  le 
esigenze  del  diritto  non  vengono  mai  a  porsi  in  contrasto  col  buon 
senso,  come  verrebbero  a  trovarsi  vietando  al  condomino  di  tenere 
la  parete  decorosa  o  di  spazzar  via  i  ragnateli  dalla  medesima, 
senza  il  consenso  degli  altri.6 

12.    Dopo  tutto  resta  la  sola  quistione  delle  riparazioni  agli 

1  Z>.  viii.  2,  13  pr.  2  D.  ix.  2,  27,  10. 

3  D.  viii.  2,  13  pr. 

4  Cfr.  p.  es.  Ferrini,  Pand.  p.  450. 

5  D.  viii.  2,  13,  i. 

6  Ma  pur  troppo  il  diritto  e  trascinato  spesso  non  solo  in  contrasto  col 
buon  senso  ma  pure  in  situazioni  ridicole,  come  avviene  oggi  presso  di  noi  con 
la  ormai  famosa  iscririone  d'  ufficio  del  Re  nelle  liste  elettorali  politiche. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  47 

edificii  e  muri  comuni,  che  e  in  realta  assai  intricata.  Ma  1'  esame 
piu  largo  di  essa  deve  essere  rimandato  al  c.  ii.,  appunto  perche  le 
interpolazioni  giustinianee  sono  in  questa  materia  emergenti  nel 
Corpus  luris. 

Or  per  quel  che  concerne  il  diritto  classico  abbiamo  due  dati 
certi  per  ritenere  anche  in  questo  punto  di  diritto  il  vigore  della 
regola  di  Sabino. 

In  primo  luogo  il  passo  di  Gaio,  piu  volte  richiamato,  che 
attesta  nella  maniera  piu  esplicita  per  il  muro  comune  alterutri 
.  .  .  reficiendi  ius  non  esse.1  E  poi  il  Senato  consulto  provocato 
da  M.  Aurelio,  che  concedette  ai  singoli  condomini,  che  avessero 
eseguite  le  riparazioni  necessarie  agli  edificii,  il  diritto  di  esigere  in 
proporzione  la  spesa  erogata  entro  4  mesi  con  gl'  interessi,  e,  nel 
caso  di  mora  dei  socii  al  pagamento  o  di  rifiuto,  1*  acquisto  della 
proprieta  delle  parti  dell'  edificio  loro  spettanti.  Soltanto  queste 
disposizioni  attribuiscono  le  fonti 2  alia  Oratio  di  M.  Aurelio ;  ma 
essa  doveva  contenere  certamente,  come  premessa,  I1  obbligo  rivolto 
ai  singoli  condomini  di  tenere  in  ordine  gli  edificii,  ai  fini  principal- 
mente  della  loro  stabilita. 

LJ  occasione  a  tali  provvedimenti  pote  essere  apprestata  dalla 
inondazione  del  Tevere,  che,  giusto  in  quel  tempo,  fu  spaventevole 
e  che  a  dire  di  Capitolino 3  multa  urbis  aedificia  vexavit  et  pluri- 
mum  animalium  inter  emit  et  famem  gravissimam  peperit. 

Del  resto  e  nota  la  cura  somma  degli  Imperatori  e  del  Senate4 
per  il  decoro  edilizio  della  Citta,  che  diede  luogo  a  disposizioni 
gravissime  limitatrici  della  proprieta,  che  furono  estese  pure  alle 
Provincie 5  e  severamente  custodite.  E  pertanto  il  provvedimento 
legislative  di  carattere  eccezionale  conferma,  come  a  me  sembra,  la 
regola  dello  ius  civile,  quale  e  riferita  da  Gaio ;  nel  senso  che  ai 

1  D.  viii.  2,  8. 

2  D.  xvii.   2,   52,    10  (Ulp.-Papin.) ;    Cod.  viii.    10,   4  (Philipp.    a.   245); 
Harmenopulo,  Exab.  x.  3,  27. —  Male  Cuiacio,  Opp.  iv.  p.  785  ad  1.  28  D.  x. 
3  spiega  pure  con  la   Oratio  dim  Marti  la   1.  32  D.  xxxix.  2.      Cf.   c.  ii.  n. 
Nelle  Leges  saeculares  (L.  98  ed.  Ferrini)  le  disposizioni  del  SC.  sono  applicate 
pure  ai  proprietarii  dei  diversi  piani  di  una  casa,  essendo,  come  ora  sappiamo, 
nelle  provincie  orientali  ammessa  la  proprieta  divisa  dei  piani  di  un  edificio  ; 
cfr.  Wenger,  ZSS.  v.  32,  p.  334  ;  ma  v.  Partsch,  Archiv  Pap.  v.  p.  496. 

3  Hist.  M.  Ant.  Philoph.  8. 

4  Cfr.  Riccobono,  Fontes,  p.  233. 

5  Cfr.  Epistula  Hadriani  ad  Stralonicenses  Hadrianopolitas  (Riccobono, 
Fontes,  p.  325  ed  ivi  citati). 


48  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

singoli  condomini  non  e  data  facolta  di  provvedere  alle  riparazioni 
necessarie  agli  edificii,  senza  il  concorso  della  volonta  degli  altri. 
Mentre,  d'  altro  lato,  pu6  ben  dirsi  che  la  disposizione  del  Senate 
non  venne  qui  ad  alterare  nessun  principio  fondamentale  del- 
1'  istituto  della  comproprieta ;  avvegnache  il  singolo  condomino,  se 
pu6  e  deve  ora  eseguire  le  riparazioni  agli  edificii  cadenti,  ci6 
facendo  non  esercita  una  facolta  di  dominio,  ma  adempie  piuttosto 
un  precetto  d'  indole  amministrativa,  munito  perci6  di  speciale 
sanzione. 

13.  Onde  per  quel  che  riguarda  il  facere  possiamo  con- 
ch iudere  che  le  applicazioni  della  regola  di  Sabino  sono  tutte 
concordanti  nello  stesso  senso,  come  dovevano  essere ;  perche  la 
materia  non  poteva  qui  offrire  occasione  a  dubbii  e  controversie, 
trattandosi  di  deduzioni  semplici  ed  incontrovertibili  dei  principii 
fondamentali  del  dominio.1 

Infatti,  se  la  condizione  dei  singoli  compartecipi  e  pari  in  diritto, 
qualsiasi  atto  compiuto  nella  cosa  da  uno  o  dai  piu  contro  la 
volonta  di  altri  costituisce  certamente  una  menomazione  del  diritto 
di  questi  ultimi,  un'  invadenza  della  loro  sfera  giuridica.  Ma, 
d'  altro  lato,  non  vi  e  ragione  ne  posto  per  ammettere  la  prevalenza 
della  volonta  di  uno  sull'  altro,  o  anche  dei  piu  contro  uno.  Perche, 
essendo  tutti  domini,  ciascuno  puo  disporre  della  cosa  come  vuole ; 
e  qualunque  cosa  voglia  non  puo  essere  soggetta  a  contraddizione. 

E  percio  1'  effetto  deve  essere  negative ;  colui  che  nega  e 
poziore,  nel  senso  che  qualsiasi  disposizione  materiale  della  cosa 
comune  viene  ad  essere  impedita.  E  cosl  e  vero,  negativamente, 
che  nessuno  pu6  disporre  di  fatto  della  cosa  a  suo  talento,  per 
1'  energia  del  diritto  pari  degli  altri ;  come  e  pur  vero,  in  senso 
positivo,  che  ciascuno  ha  il  potere  d'  impedire  con  la  forza  il 
tentative  del  socio  che  voglia  far  prevalere  la  sua  volonta  operando 
sulla  cosa ;  perche  questi  allora  quodammodo  sibi  alienum  quoque 
ius  praeripit)  si  quasi  solus  dominus  ad  suum  arbitrium  uti  \re\ 
communi  velit. 

1  Nella  presente  trattazione  non  sono  considerati  i  casi  di  comunione  di 
sepolcri  e  le  facolta  di  seppellire  nel  luogo  puro  comune  ;  perche  in  questa 
materia  le  innovazioni  di  Giustiniano  sono  ancora  piu  profonde  e  determinate 
da  1'  idea  prettamente  religiosa.  Onde  mi  parve  necessario  dedicare  all'  ar- 
gomento  un  lavoro  speciale.  E  per  altro,  per  quel  che  qui  interessa,  e  fuori 
dubbio  che  nel  diritto  classico  il  condomino  non  ha  facolta  di  far  religiose  il 
luogo  puro  introducendovi  il  cadavere ;  cfr.  D.  xi.  7,  41,  che  del  resto  e  inter- 
polate nella  seconda  parte  :  cum  extranei  .  .  sepeliretur ;  e  D.  x.  3,  6,  6. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  49 

14.  E  la  posizione  e  identica  e  quindi  identico  lo  effetto,  quando 
per  via  di  atti  giuridici  la  disposizione  di  uno  dei  socii  investe  di 
necessita  la  cosa  intera ;  perche  anche  in  questo  caso  si  determina 
un  conflitto  tra  i  molteplici  dominii  come  in  seguito  al  facere ;  e 
perci6  il  potere  del  singolo  socio  deve  arrestarsi. 

Nessuno  dei  socii  pu6  quindi  acquistare  al  fondo  una  servitu,  per 
quanto  ne  sia  evidente  il  vantaggio  o  la  necessita  ; l  e  nessuno  pu6 
singolarmente  gravare  il  fondo  di  servitu.2 

Nell'  uno  e  neir  altro  caso  si  richiede  il  consensus  omnium,  o, 
per  meglio  dire,  quell'  atto  dispositive  congruo  a  costituire  la  servitu, 
che  puo  essere  simultaneo  ovvero  successive  da  parte  dei  singoli.3 

La  denunzia  di  nuova  opera  rispetto  al  fondo  comune  puo  essere 
attiva  o  passiva ;  e  cioe  da  parte  dei  condomini  a  causa  di  opera 
eseguita  in  alieno  e  che  invade  il  fondo  o  ne  minaccia  in  modo 
qualsiasi  la  liberta  o  la  consistenza  fisica ;  ovvero,  dal  lato  passivo, 
contro  i  condomini  per  opera  che  s'  inizia  sul  fondo  comune. 

Ma  in  ambo  i  casi  gli  effetti  giuridici  si  riflettono  su  tutti  i 
condomini  solo  quando  vi  sia  il  consenso  di  tutti.4  Ove  tale 
consenso  non  vi  sia  per  la  denunzia,  o  nel  caso  inverso  per  F  opera, 
la  responsabilita  incombe  solo  all'  autore  della  denunzia ;  nel 
secondo  caso  a  chi  inizio  F  opera  sul  fondo.5  E  pari  &  la  decisione 
intorno  alia  cautio  damni  in/ecti,  nei  casi  in  cui  ha  luogo.6 

Abbiamo  qui  dunque  esempii  perspicui  per  dimostrare  che  il 
principio  della  indipendenza  dei  socii  &  inalterable  nella  comunione, 
e  che  il  diritto  romano  in  nessun  caso  pervenne  a  riconoscere  la 
facolta  di  un  socio  di  rappresentare  gli  altri,  per  garentire  F  interesse 
comune  o  per  la  responsabilita  di  fronte  ai  terzi.  Ne  questa  afferma- 
zione  resta  infirmata  dal  fatto  che  ciascuno  dei  condomini  ha  potere 
di  rivendicare  in  solidum  la  servitu  dovuta  al  fondo 7  o  di  assicurare 
con  F  esercizio  F  esistenza  della  medesima,8  perche  cotali  effetti, 

1  D.  viii.  3,  19. 

2  D.  xxxix.  3,  i  o  pr.  omnium  voluntatem  esse  sequendam  ;  D.  viii.  1,2; 
D.  xxi.  2,  10. 

3  D.  viii.  3,  n,  per  altro  interpolate. 

4  D.  xxxix.   I,  18,  Pap.  3  qu.  si  .  .  .  ex  voluntate  omnium  opus  fiat. 
5  §  6  D.  eod. 

5  fr.  1 8  D.  xxxix.  i  in  solidum  obligabitur. 

6  D.  x.    3,    6,    7    necesse  tibi  non  fuerit  in  solidum   cavere,  sed  sufficere 
pro  parte  tua. 

7  D.  viii.  5,  4,  3  \itaque  .   .   .  posstt\     Trib.  conf.  Eisele,  ZSS.  xxx.  p.  120. 

8  D.  viii.  6,  1 6. 

E 


50  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

come  e  ovvio,  dipendono  unicamente  dalla  natura  della  servitu,  che 
e  per  se  stessa  indivisibile,  e  quindi  non  si  puo  ne  acquistare  ne 
rivendicare  ne  perdere  pro  parted 

15.  Sono  disegnati  cosi  i  lineamenti  essenziali,  cioe  quelli  che 
appariscono  i  soli  necessarii  a  rappresentare  la  struttura  piu  rilevata 
e   caratteristica  dell'   istituto   del   condominio,   secondo  i  classici. 
Essi  ci  hanno  rivelato  che  i  singoli  hanno  sulla  cosa  comune  un  vero 
e  pieno  diritto  di  proprieta,  e  che  questo  diritto  si  comporta  del 
tutto  con  la  stessa  forza  e  la  stessa  energia  come  nella  proprieta 
unica,  secondo  i  principii  del  diritto  quiritario ;  per  cui  il  domino 
ovvero   i   condomini   hanno   sulla   cosa    un    potere    assoluto    che 
esercitano  con  la  massima  indipendenza  in  qualsiasi  momento  e 
situazione.     Le  conseguenze  di  questa  posizione  sono  evidenti  e 
note.     Le  facolta   di   disposizione  giuridica  restano  illimitate  nei 
singoli  condomini.     Ma  1'  uso  ed  il  godimento  della  cosa  non  pu6 
aver  luogo  che  mediante  F  accordo  di  tutti,  per  ogni  singolo  atto 
ed  in  ogni  momento. 

Quando  quest'  accordo  non  si  raggiunga  la  comunione  si 
paralizza  subitamente.  Si  tratta  pertanto  di  un  rapporto  senza 
disciplina  e  senza  regolamento  di  sorta,  ed  in  questo  senso 
addirittura  anarchico ;  in  cui  il  sistema  individualistico  romano  si 
manifesta  in  tutta  la  sua  potenza. 

II  risultato  e  sicuramente  antieconomico  ed  antisociale,  ma  non 
in  modo  diverse  che  tutto  F  ordinamento  della  proprieta.  E  percio 
non  e  a  pensare  che  i  Romani  abbiano  avvertito  le  durezze  del  loro 
sistema  di  comproprieta ;  di  certo  non  tentarono  mai  di  apportarvi 
alcuna  mitigazione,  che,  come  s'  e  visto,  applicarono  sempre  il 
principio  di  fondo  con  tutte  le  conseguenze  sopra  rilevate,  con  la 
logica  piu  perfetta  ed  inesorabile. 

1 6.  Quando  il  disaccordo  si  manifesta  tra  i  socii,  in  ordine  al- 
F  esercizio  delle  facolta  di  dominio  sulla  cosa,  vuoi  per  la  maniera 
o  la   distribuzione  del   godimento,  vuoi  per  la  condotta  di  uno 
pregiudizievole   agli   interessi    degli    altri    o    semplicemente    alia 
volonta  degli  altri,  non  vi  ha  nessun  mezzo  e  nessuna  azione  che 
intervenga  a  comporre  il  dissidio,  che  rimetta  F  ordine,  che  costringa 
F  uno  o  gli  altri  a  consentire  od  agire  in  modo  ragionevole  e  vantag- 
gioso  per  F  interesse  comune  ;  ovvero  che  possa  impedire  F  abuso  o  il 
danneggiamento  della  cosa.     Preminente,  sempre,  resta  il  principio  : 

1  D.  viii.  i,  ii. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  51 

potior  est  condicio  prohibentis,  lo  stato  cioe  d'  inazione,  di  paralisi. 
E  potior  s'  intende  iure ;  per  cio  in  qualsiasi  evenienza,  al  di  sopra 
di  qualsiasi  interesse,  vantaggio  o  danno  dei  singoli  cointeressati. 

17.  E  la  paralisi  pu6  risolversi  soltanto  con  un  mezzo  energico 
e  definitive,  cioe  con  lo  scioglimento  della  comunione. 

Per  ci6  ciascuno  dei  socii  puo  chiedere  la  divisione  mediante 
T  actio  communi  dividundo  in  qualsiasi  momenta.1  Ed  a  questo 
diritto  non  si  ammette  rinunzia.  Ma  di  piu  i  giureconsulti  con 
esitanza,  come  pare,  riconobbero  la  validita  del  pactum  ne  intra 
cerium  tempus  dividatur?  II  motive  ne  era  evidente.  Dacche  il 
patto  di  non  dividere,  anche  limitato  nel  tempo,  non  poteva  avere 
efficacia  reale,  e  se  in  un  modo  qualsiasi  si  fosse  potuto  consentire 
siffatto  valore,  esso  avrebbe  arrecato  una  limitazione  essenziale  al 
diritto  assoluto  ed  alia  indipendenza  dei  condomini. 

Giustiniano,  s'  intende,  superc-  la  barriera  facilmente  accordando 
alia  convenzione  efficacia  reale.3 

In  questo  punto  pero,  giova  rilevarlo,  anche  la  giurisprudenza 
classica  aveva  ammesso  un'  eccezione  al  principio  dell'  assoluta 
liberta  dello  scioglimento  della  comunione  in  qualsiasi  momento  e 
per  volonta  di  un  solo ;  cio&  rispetto  al  vestibolo  comune,  che  non 
puo  essere  dedotto  nel  giudizio  divisorio  invito  altero : 

fr.  19  §  I  D.  x.  3,  Paul.  vi.  ad  Sab.  De  vestibule  communi 
binarum  aedium  arbiter  communi  dividundo  invito  utrolibet  dari  non 
debet,  quia  qui  de  vestibule  liceri  cogatur,  necesse  habeat  interdum 
totarum  aedium  pretium  facere,  si  alias  aditum  non  habeat. 

Come  si  vede  il  motive  e  di  quelli  che  rompono  qualsiasi  teoria, 
sia  pure  costruita  su  basi  di  granito,  quale  era  quella  romana  della 
comproprieta.4 

1 8.  Raccogliamo  ora  i  fili  sparsi  in  questo  breve  saggio.     E  la 
prima  constatazione  che  emerge  spontanea  dall'  insieme  ci  mostra 
F  istituto  del  condominio  rigorosamente  costruito  sui  principii  della 
proprieta   solitaria,    senza   alcuna   attenuazione.      Cosl   gli   effetti 
giuridici  di  sopra  descritti  sono  tutti  normali,  e  dipendenti  dalla 

1  D.  x.  3,  8  pr.  ;  x.  2,  43  ;  viii.  2,  26,  nella  parte  genuina. 

2  D.  xvii.  2,  14,  pr.,  vedi  la  nota  appresso. 

3  D.  xvii.  2,  1 6,  i,  fortemente  interpolate;   17  pr.  eod.  aut  c.  div.  Trib.\ 
x.   3,   14,   2:   Trib.\   §  3   eod.  rimaneggiato  da  Triboniano :   quare  emptor 
\quoque\  communi  dividundo  agenda  eadem  exceptione  \non  Paul]  summo- 
vebitur,  qua  actor  eius  summoveretur. 

4  Cfr.  Harmenopuli  Exab.  ill.  x.  30 ;  Bos.  xii.  2,  1 9  e  scolii. 


52  >S.  Riccobono  [iv 

teoria  del  dominio  quiritario,  che  esiste  illeso  in  ciascuno  dei 
compartecipi.  Per  ci6  e  manifesto  che  quelle  dottrine  che  vedono 
nella  communio  una  proprieta  unica,  attribuita  ad  una  molte- 
plicita  di  subbietti  ovvero  all'  insieme  dei  titolari  considerate  come 
un  gruppo  collettivo,  con  o  senza  personalita  giuridica,  sono 
certamente  erronee  e  lontane  dall'  ordinamento  della  comproprieta 
classica.  E  vero,  per  altro,  che  esse  hanno  nelle  fonti  un  qualche 
fondamento,  ma  lo  hanno  precisamente  in  passi  interpolati  da 
Giustiniano,  e  percio  saranno  a  suo  luogo  prese  in  considerazione.1 

19.  La  comproprieta  classica,  invece,  quale  ci  si  e  manifestata 
nelle  trattazioni  dei  giureconsulti  si  determina  nettamente  come 
una  pluralita  di  dominii  su  di  una  cosa  medesima,  coesistenti  in 
maniera  che  il  singolo  diritto  rimane  compresso  dalla  forza  del- 
1'  altro ;  e  per  ci6  ciascuno  dei  titolari  ha,  per  effetto  del  concorso 
di  diritti  molteplici  di  pari  forza,  un  dominio  sulla  cosa  intera  pro 
indiviso  pro  parte.  E  questa  appunto  la  designazione  molto 
precisa  che  Celso  attribuisce  al  condominio  in  D.  xiii.  6,  5,  15 — sed 
totius  corporis  pro  indiviso  pro  parte  dominium  habere\  dove  i 
due  caratteri  salienti  della  figura  del  condominio  sono  perfetta- 
mente  messi  in  evidenza ;  e  cioe  in  primo  luogo  la  proprieta 
integrate  di  ciascuno,  e  poi  la  forzata  riduzione  di  essa  quanto 
agli  effetti  dinamici  entro  un  limite  insuperabile,  a  causa  del 
concorso  degli  altri  dominii. 

Nello  stesso  senso  si  esprime  Ulpiano,  di  cui  il  pensiero  come 
di  solito  assume  una  forma  piu  trasparente : 

D.  xxxix.  2,  15,  1 8  :  equaliter  omnes  quasi  in  totum  missi  con- 
cursu  partes  habebunt. 

II  testo  si  riferisce  alia  missio  in  possessionem  damni  infecti 
nomine ',  ex  primo  decreto,  che  non  attribuisce  in  vero  il  dominio. 

Ma  alia  missio  puo  seguire  in  un  secondo  momento  la  proprieta, 
e  non  si  vede  davvero  ragione  per  sospettare  che  la  posizione 
giuridica  dei  missi  debba,  per  questo  rispetto,  vale  a  dire  quanto 
alia  struttura  dei  rapporti  tra  i  concorrenti,  mutarsi  col  sopravve- 
nire  del  dominio.  Si  pu6  dire  anzi  il  contrario ;  che  cioe  il  giure- 
consulto  si  sforza  di  attribuire  ai  missi  non  proprietarii  quella  tale 
relazione  giuridica  che  &  nota  dal  condominio. 

Nella  comproprieta  quindi  il  rapporto  tra  i  condomini  e  per- 

1  Cfr.  c.  iv. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  53 

fettamente  identico  a  quello  dei  coeredi  nella  hereditas.  I  coeredi 
sono  tutti  chiamati  alia  eredita  intera,  e  solo  per  effetto  del  concorso 
ciascuno  consegue  una  parte  proporzionale  al  numero  dei  con- 
correnti,  o  quella  parte  che  la  legge  o  il  testatore  gli  conferisce. 
Anche  qui  il  diritto  di  ciascuno  sull'  asse  ereditario  si  determina 
precisamente  pro  indiviso  pro  parte.  Di  conseguenza,  se  uno 
dei  chiamati  rinuncia  o  non  pu6  acquistare  la  parte  che  gli  era 
designata,  essa  si  accresce,  di  regola,  agli  altri  coeredi,  in  pro- 
porzione  della  quota  di  ciascuno. 

20.  Cosi  avviene  nella  communio.  Se  uno  dei  condomini,  in 
un  modo  qualsiasi,  rinuncia  al  suo  dominio,  per  manomissione  del 
servo  o  per  derelizione  etcc.,  la  parte  si  accresce  ipso  iure  agli 
altri  socii.  Ci6  e  attestato  rispetto  allo  schiavo.1 

Ma  sicuramente  non  vi  e  ragione  di  negare  lo  stesso  effetto  per 
la  derelizione  di  altri  oggetti  della  proprieta,  come  si  suol  fare.2 
Perche  in  nessun  caso  il  diritto  romano  ammise  una  differenza 
qualsiasi  tra  il  dominium  su  schiavi  e  quello  su  altre  res  mancipi, 
ne  per  il  contenuto  ne  per  1'  intensita  ne  per  le  forme  di  trasferi- 
mento.  Una  differenza  si  nota  bensi,  ma  solo  riguardo  al  possesso, 
perche  e  res  facti ;  e  quindi  il  possesso  si  configura  diversamente 
secondo  la  natura  dell'  obbietto.3  In  materia  di  diritto,  al- 
T  opposto,  tale  distinzione  non  ha  senso. 

E  per  altro  P  applicazione  dello  ius  adcrescendi  tra  condomini 
si  evince  in  generale  da  un  testo  di  Modestino,  annoverato  sempre 
tra  i  loci  conclamati^  e  che  realmente  e  oscuro,  per  il  fatto  che  la 
conclusione  vi  fu  soppressa.  II  testo  dice  : 

fr.  3  D.  xli.  7,  Mod.  vi.  differ.  An  pars  pro  derelicto  haberi 
possit,  quaeri  solet  et  quidem  si  in  re  communi  socius  partem 
suam  reliquerit,  eius  esse  desinit,  ut  hoc  sit  in  parte,  quod  in  toto : 
at  quin  totius  rei  dominus  efficere  non  potest,  ut  partem  retineat, 
partem  pro  derelicto  habeat  [verius  est  partem  pro  derelicto  haberi 
non  posse,  nam  socius  rei  communis,  si  alter  partem  suam  reliquerit, 
totius  rei  solus  dominus  efficitur]. 

1  Dosithei,  fr.  10;  Ulp.  Reg.  i.  18  ;  Paul.  S.  iv.  12,  i  ;  cfr.  7.  ii.  7,  4. 

2  V.   Pernice,  ZSS.  xix.  p.    177  n.    i.      Lo   ius  adcrescendi  rispetto  allo 
schiavo  sarebbe  per  il  P.  un  effetto  della  potestas  ;  e  non  si  accorge  che  la 
sua    opinione    s'   infrange   dinanzi   alia   dottrina   di    Proculo   [testi    cit.]    che 
ammetteva  appunto  lo  ius  adcrescendi  anche  in  seguito  a  man.  inter  amicos, 
per  ci6,  necessariamente,  sul  fondamente  della  derelizione,  compiuta  da  uno 
dei  condomini. 

3  Cfr.  D.  xli.  2,  3,  13;  fr.  47  eod. 


54  S-  Riccobono  LIV 

II  completamento  del  passo,  cosl  come  io  1'  ho  tentato  ai  fini 
della  dimostrazione,  mi  sembra  necessario,  perche  la  incompiutezza 
ne  e  evidente. 

II  testo  ha  un  indirizzo  teorico,  conforme  all'  indole  dell'  opera 
da  cui  fu  ricavato,1  e  vuol  risolvere  una  quistione  sorta  tra  i  giuristi 
intorno  alia  possibilita  della  derelictio  partis.  La  conclusione 
manca.  Ma  se  noi  indaghiamo  la  ragione  dei  dubbii  elevati  dai 
giuristi,  e  certo  che  non  pu6  rinvenirsi  dal  lato  soggettivo,  cioe 
rispetto  alia  perdita  della  proprieta  di  colui  che  non  vuole  esser 
domino  della  parte,  dacche  negarlo  sarebbe  assurdo :  ut  hoc  sit  in 
parte  quod  in  toto.  Ma  il  contrast©  poteva  bensi  pronunziarsi  dal 
lato  obbiettivo,  cio&  se  la  parte  ora  relitta  dal  socio  poteva  conside- 
rarsi  come  derelitta  in  senso  giuridico,  e  quindi  acquistarsi  dall'  altro 
socio  o  da  qualunque  terzo  come  res  nullius ;  ovvero,  data  la 
natura  del  condominio,  in  cui  ciascuno :  totius  rei  pro  indiviso  pro 
parte  dominium  habety  non  si  dovesse  piuttosto  ritenere  la  cosa 
comune  soggetta  interamente  al  dominio  di  ciascuno,  e  quindi  in 
nessun  momento  priva  in  parte  di  domino,  per  effetto  dell'  abban- 
dono  di  uno  dei  titolari.  L'  argomentazione  di  Modestino  si 
appunta  verso  quest'  ultima  conclusione,  che  e  ben  fondata. 
E  pertanto  lo  ius  adcrescendi  tra  condomini  appare  sicuramente 
discusso  tra  i  giuristi,  ed  ammesso  in  generale,  con  argomenti  tratti 
dalla  struttura  stessa  dell'  istituto. 

21.  Ed  il  riconoscimento  di  tale  effetto  e  d'  una  importanza 
decisiva ;    che  esso  rivela  nella  maniera  piu  sfolgorante  1'  intima 
essenza  della  comproprieta,  quando  la  si  valuti,  come  si  deve,  alia 
stregua  di  quella  regola  enunciata  da  Celso  che  suona :  totiens  ius 
adcrescendi  esse,  quotiens  in  duobus,  qui  solidum  habuerunt,  concursu 
divisus  est? 

II  principio  invero  e  applicato  qui  al  concorso  nell'  usufrutto ; 
ma  esso  e  del  pari  efficace  ed  incontrovertibile  in  tutti  i  casi  in  cui 
un  diritto  e  attribuito  per  intero  a  piu  persone ;  quindi  ha  vigore 
nella  hereditas^  nel  legato,  come  nel  condominio,  qualunque  sia  la 
causa  che  lo  determina. 

22.  Ed  accertato  questo  punto,   quella  dottrina  che  vede  nel 
condominio   romano   una  comproprieta   plurima   parziale  diviene 

1  Cfr.  fr.  1 1  D.  viii.  i  :  estratto  dallo  stesso  libro  e  che  concerne  1'  acquisto 
o  la  perdita  della  servitu  pro  parte  [Lenel,  Pal.  i.  c.  704]. 

2  V.  F.  79. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  55 

esanime.  Perche  un  diritto  parziale,  in  se,  non  pu6  aver  forza  in 
nessun  caso  di  espandersi  al  di  la  del  suo  limite,  come  non  ha  forza 
di  dilatarsi  P  obbligazione  parziaria,  che  in  realta  cade  su  piu  oggetti 
varii,  unificati  casualmente  in  un  oggetto  complessivo.  E  1'  errore 
per  altro  nella  dottrina  del  condominio  e  visibile,  determinato  dal- 
1'  osservazione  che  tutti  gli  atti  dispositivi  del  socio  hanno  valore, 
e  gli  emolumenti  che  provengono  dalla  cosa  comune  si  dividono, 
sempre  pro  parted  Ma  tali  effetti,  fu  gia  avvertito,  dipendono  dalla 
resistenza  opposta  dagli  altri  diritti  di  pari  forza,  che  per  cio 
formano  un  limite  insuperabile. 

23.  Ed  ora  che  da  un  nucleo  centrale  compatto  e  forte  abbiamo 
visto  irradiarsi  in  linee  ben  precise,  quanto  in  direzioni  necessaria- 
mente  varie,  tutti  gli  effetti  del  condominio  romano,  fatti  ormai 
chiari  nella  loro  essenza,  possiamo  e  dobbiamo  intendere  che  tra  il 
condominio  del  diritto  private  e  la  collegialita  dei  magistrati  non 
vi  e  nessun  punto  di  contatto.  Tra  1*  esercizio  della  potestas, 
infatti,  dei  magistrati  e  P  esercizio  del  potere  dei  condomini  la 
differenza  e  essenziale.  Perche  1'  attribuzione  della  potestas  ai 
colleghi  nella  magistratura  e  intera  ed  indipendente,  nel  senso  che 
ciascuno  di  essi  pu6  esercitarla  in  ogni  momento  senza  la  coopera- 
zione  ed  il  concorso  della  volonta  dell'  altro.  Nel  condominio  invece 
qualsiasi  atto  esecutivo  sulla  cosa  deve  essere  necessariamente 
consentito  da  tutti,  in  modo  positive,  come  afferm6  gia  splendida- 
mente  il  piu  grande  interprete  del  diritto  classico,  Cuiacio,2  il  quale 
scrisse :  invitum  .  .  .  accipere  debemus  non  eum  qui  contradicit^  sed 
eum  qui  non  consentit. 

II  dubbio  in  questo  punto  non  e  lecito.3 

E  se  nell'  un  ordine  e  neir  altro  puo  intervenire  lo  ius  prohibendi, 
si  tratta  di  una  coincidenza  del  tutto  esteriore,  diversa  nel  fonda- 
mento,  nella  forma  e  nell'  efficacia  e  che  non  puo  farci  smarrire  la 
esatta  nozione  delle  cose.  Vero  e  per  altro  che  lo  ius  prohibendi, 
che  ricorre  nei  due  casi,  se  pote  impressionare  la  mente  del 

1  Cfr.  avanti  al  n.  9. 

2  Opp.  vol.  iv.  p.  944  :  ma  s'  intende  che  Cuiacio  attribuisce  pure  alia  parola 
un  altro  significato  secondo  i  testi  che  comentava.     Cosl  nel  v.  iv.  p.  783  ad  1. 
28  D.  x.  3  scrive  :  invitus  est proprie  quiprohibet  alteri  .  .  .  invitus  est  etiam  ius 
qui  abest  et  per  absentiam  prohibere  non  pot  est.      Ma  il  Cuiacio  si  trovava  qui  di 
fronte  ad  un  testo  interpolato,  come  vedremo  piu  oltre.    Varii  significati  ammette 
Fadda,  Studii  Brugi,  p.  145. 

3  Cfr.  Perozzi,  MM.  Girard,  ii.  p.  371. 


56  5*.  Riccobono  [iv 

Mommsen  e  di  cultori  insigni  del  diritto  private,  quali  il  Fadda,1  il 
Bonfante  ed  il  Pacchioni,  ci6  si  deve,  in  buona  parte,  alia  deforma- 
zione  dello  ius  prohibendi  tra  condomini  operata  da  Giustiniano,  e 
che  sara  tosto  messa  in  chiaro. 

24.  Dalla  struttura  del  condominio  classico  derivano  altre 
conseguenze  di  maggior  rilievo,  di  cui  fu  fatto  cenno,  e  che  si  co- 
ordinano  convenientemente  al  concetto  fondamentale  qui  svolto. 

Tra  condomini  sono  ammissibili  ben  poche  azioni  ;  e  cio&  solo 
quelle  che  mirano  a  fare  ottenere  ad  uno  dei  titolari  il  riconosci- 
mento  del  suo  diritto  o  la  partecipazione  al  possesso  e  godimento 
della  cosa  ;  e  percio  e  possibile  la  reivindicatio,  la  publiciana  o  la 
condictio  furtiva.  L'  esperimento  di  queste  azioni  non  puo  trovare 
ostacolo  di  sorta  in  qualsiasi  contingenza  ;  cio  e  intuitive,  perche  si 
tratta  in  definitive  dell'  attivazione  del  diritto  di  proprieta,  che  e 
essenzialmente  leso  per  la  perdita  del  possesso. 

Ma  le  altre  azioni,  che  di  solito  competono  al  domino,  non  sono 
ammesse  tra  socii.  Cosi  se  uno  di  essi  abusa  della  cosa  comune  o 
la  danneggia  o  tenta  di  stabilire  uno  stato  di  cose  che  agguagli  1'  onere 
di  una  servitu  o  delle  opere,  di  suo  arbitrio,  non  vi  e  un  mezzo 
giudiziario  per  reprimere  1'  abuso,  ottenere  il  risarcimento  del  danno 
o  una  penale,  ovvero  per  impedire  o  far  rimuovere  le  opere. 

Quindi  tra  socii  non  si  puo  esperire  1'  actio  legis  Aquiliaef  non  la 
negator  ia?  non  1'  a.  finium  regundorumf  nemmeno  1'  a.  de  servo 
corrupto 5  o  iniuriarumf  o  T  actio  noxalis  per  delitto  del  servo 
comune.7 

Anche  il  rimedio  della  cautio  damni  infecti  fu  oggetto  di 
discussione  tra  le  scuole  dei  giuristi.8  E  tutto  cio  e  ben  intelligibile. 

1  Studii  Brugi,  p.  142  ed  ivi  citati. 

2  D.  ix.  2,   27,    i  :    \ne  sit  in  potestate  servi  ut  tibi  soli  serviaf\   Trib.\ 
§  10  eod.  \et  ideo  aequius  puto  .  .  .  cautionem~\  Trib.\   cfr.  26  D.  x.  3,  Alfen. 

3  D.  xxxiii.  3,  4  ;  cfr.  avanti  n.  5. 

4  D.   x.    1,4,  6,  7,  Paul,  xxiii.  ad  ed. :    quia  ego  et  socius  meus  (in  hac 
actione  ?  glossa)  adversarii  esse  non  possumus,  sed  unius  loco  habemur. 

5  D.  xi.   3,   14,  2,   Paul.  xix.  ad  ed.:   Sabinus  non  posse  agi  cum  soa'o, 
perinde  atque  si  proprius  meus  serwts  corrupisset  conservum.       II  fr.  9  pr. 
eod.  e  interpolate. 

6  D.  xlvii.    10,    15,   36,    Ulp.   77  ad   ed. :     cum    iure  domini  id  fecerit. 
Cfr.  17  §9  eod. 

7  D.  ix.  4,  8,  Ulp.  37  ad  ed.:  dominus  enim  pro  parte  factus  non  potest 
cum  socio  noxali  experiri ;  quel  che  segue  contiene  element!  giustinianei. 

8  Cfr.  D.  xxxix.  2,  32,  Gai  xxviii.  ad  ed.  pr.  ;  D.  viii.  2,  13,  i  ;  D.  ix.  2, 
27,  10. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  57 

L'  ostacolo  insuperabile  per  tutte  quelle  azioni  sta  nella  posizione 
giuridica  che  hanno  i  socii  tra  loro.  Se  ciascuno  &  dominus,  ed  ha 
un  diritto  sulla  cosa  pari  a  quello  dell'  altro,  ne  deriva  che  qualunque 
sia  1'  agire  del  socio  e  qualunque  cosa  faccia,  egli  opera  in  suo  e 
non  in  alieno.  E  quindi  nessuna  delle  formule  di  quelle  azioni 
potrebbe  dirigersi  contro  di  lui,  che  esse  competono  al  proprietario 
avverso  chi  tale  diritto  non  puo  vantare  sulla  cosa.  Manca  quindi 
la  condizione  precipua  per  la  legittimita  e  1'  efficacia  di  quelle  azioni, 
come  e  dichiarato  espressamente  dai  giureconsulti  nei  passi  rimasti 
illesi  nella  Compilazione  di  Giustiniano.1 

Ne  da  cio  deriva  che  T  agire  inconsulto,arbitrario  o  pregiudizievole 
di  un  socio  sia,  in  tutti  quei  casi,  senza  alcun  rimedio ;  che  ciascuno 
ha  contro  1'  altro  lo  ius  prohibendi\  di  propria  autorita,  suis 
manibus,  in  forza  del  suo  diritto  che  e  pari  a  quello  dell'  altro,  che 
tenta  di  sopraffare  il  suo.  Prohibere,  come  sappiamo,  significa 
vietare,  impedire  in  qualsiasi  modo. 

Ed  in  ultima  analisi  se  la  cooperazione  e  T  accordo  si  rendono 
impossibili,  chi  desidera  la  pace  puo  chiedere  lo  scioglimento  della 
comunione  con  1'  actio  c.  dividundo ;  nella  quale  inoltre  vengono 
dedotte  tutte  le  ragioni  personali  per  danni,  spese  ed  utili,  suscitate 
dalla  comunione. 

CAP.  II 

DIRITTO   GIUSTINIANEO 

25.  Tutta  la  struttura  della  communio  appare  profondamente 
alterata  nella  compilazione  di  Giustiniano,  dove  i  passi  relativi  alia 
materia  sono  folti  di  interpolazioni,  sparse  nei  diversi  volumi  a 
guisa  di  temperamenti  e  correzioni,  nella  forma  consueta,  come  per 
smorzare  la  durezza  delle  decisioni  classiche.  E  la  critica  moderna 
ha  potuto  facilmente  scovrire  molte  delle  aggiunte  inserte  dal 
legislatore  del  vi  sec.  nei  testi  classici,  ma  nessuna  attenzione  ha 
rivolto  ai  passi  mutilati,  e  sopratutto  poi  non  si  e  curata  di  abbrac- 

1  Non  e  possibile  affrontare  in  questo  luogo  tutto  il  problema  delle  azioni 
che  competono  tra  condomini,  perche  esso  richiede  un  esame  analitico  di  un 
numero  considerevole  di  passi,  che  di  regola  furono  alterati  da  Giustiniano 
nelle  forme  piu  varie.  La  dimostrazione  per  ci6  sara  data  a  parte.  Ma  per 
quel  che  urge  qui  credo  si  debbano  ritenere  sufficient!  i  motivi  resi  dai  giurist 
per  escludere  tra  condomini  1'  ammissibilita  delle  azioni  piu  gravi ;  motivi  che 
ho  riportati  nelle  note  che  precedono. 


58  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

ciare  in  una  sintesi  complessiva  1'  insieme  di  quelle  riforme,  onde 
non  ha  potuto  giudicare  se  effettivamente  1'  istituto  classico  sia  uscito 
dalle  mani  di  Giustiniano  solo  attenuate  o  non  piuttosto  svelto 
dalle  sue  basi. 

In  realta  il  nucleo  centrale,  e  quindi  le  linee  piu  rilevate  del- 
1'  istituto,  ne  furono  spezzati,  come  mi  accingo  a  dimostrare. 

I.    I  US  PROHIBENDI 
(a)  La  prohibitio  tra  condomini 

26.  La  regola  di  Sabino  e  ancora  riportata  nei  Digesti,  come 
sappiamo  :  ma  effettivamente  essa  ha  ora  un  campo  di  applicazione 
piu  ristretto  e  quindi  un  valore  diverse.  La  conseguenza  piu 
immediata  ed  energica  di  essa,  a  dire  di  Papiniano,  si  manifestava 
nello  ius  prohibendi ;  per  cui  ciascuno  dei  socii  poteva  proibire  con 
tutti  i  mezzi,  di  propria  autorita,  qualsiasi  azione  iniziata  dagli  altri 
sulla  cosa  e  distruggere  P  opera  compiuta  senza  il  suo  consenso. 
Questo  diritto  essenziale  aveva  fondamento  nel  potere  di  dominio 
assoluto  ed  indipendente  che  ciascuno  dei  titolari  conserva  nella 
comproprieta. 

Nel  diritto  giustinianeo,  invece,  lo  ius  prohibendi  ha  un  contenuto 
diverse  ed  una  nuova  direzione ;  fu  trasformato  in  un  mezzo  giu- 
diziario,  che  si  pu6  sperimentare  per  via  di  actiones  varie  ed  inter- 
dicta.  La  riforma  legislativa  determin6  in  primo  luogo  la  mutilazione 
del  fr.  1 1  D.  viii.  5  di  Marcello,  esaminato  di  sopra,1  e  che  pertanto 
assunse  altro  significato.  E  questo,  dunque,  un  caso  insigne  in  cui 
ha  luogo  la  duplex  interpretatio. 

Soppressa2  dai  compilatori,  come  fu  notato,  la  dimostrazione 
di  Marcello,  diretta  ad  escludere  nella  specie  lf  applicability  della 
negatoria,  la  frase  \et  magis  did  potesf\  prohibendi  potius  esse  ius 
si  riallaccia  nel  nuovo  testo,  immediatamente,  alle  varie  formule  di 
azioni  proposte  nella  introduzione  della  quaestio,  delle  quali  una  per 
lo  meno  figura  ammessa. 

Dubbia  pu6  essere  solo  la  scelta.  E  la  designazione  di  essa  e 
stata  per  piu  di  mezzo  secolo  oggetto  di  sapienti  discussioni.  Gli 
antichi  si  attennero  di  preferenza  all'  actio  c.  div.,  per  evitare  la 

1  Cfr.  n.  5. 

2  Anche  il  Lenel,  ZSS.  xii.  p.    12,  sospetto  nel  testo,  come  dissi,  una 
mutilazione;  cfr.  ora  Segre,  Mel.  Girard,  ii.  p.  528. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieth  59 

contraddizione  con  altri  testi ;  ma  si  affermo  pure  1'  applicability 
della  negatoria1  o,  piu  recentemente,  della  prohibitoria,  rivelata 
giusto  dallo  Zacharia,2  o  dell'  una  e  dell'  altra  insieme.3  N&  in 
contrario  c'  e  nulla  da  dire ;  perchk  come  afferm6  il  Lenel,  cui 
dobbiamo  1'  analisi  piu  profonda  del  passo,  da  quel  che  di  esso 
sopravanza  si  desume  con  certezza  che  il  socio  pu6  impedire  1'  opera 
iniziata  dalP  altro  sulla  cosa  comune  per  via  di  una  azione.  Se 
per6  questa  norma,  come  io  dico,  e  di  Giustiniano,  la  quistione 
della  specie  dell'  actio  svanisce ;  diviene  cosa  di  secondaria  impor- 
tanza.  I  compilatori  infatti  poterono  bene  riferirsi  alia  negatoria  o 
alia  prohibitoria  od  al  indicium  c.  d.,  come  vedremo  piu  oltre. 

27.  Per  ora  urge  radunare  i  testi  nei  quali  si  tratta  dello  ius  pro- 
hibendi,  onde  vedere  come  si  esplica  nel  diritto  di  Giustiniano.  E 
sul  proposito  e  ovvio  pensare  che  la  ricerca  deve  dirigersi  su  quei 
passi  che  nelle  trattazioni  dei  giureconsulti  riportavano  giusto  i 
fondamenti  dell'  istituto  della  comproprieta ;  perch&  se  la  trasfor- 
mazione  dello  ius  prohibendi  &  vera,  come  io  la  suppongo,  quei 
passi  dovevano  tutti  esser  rifatti  da  Triboniano,  per  togliere  per 
sempre  dalla  vista  degli  interpreti  il  significato  classico  del  pro- 
hibere  in  questo  luogo. 

E  cosl  e  di  fatto. 

La  riforma  fu  applicata  immediatamente  nei  due  frammenti  piu 
cospicui  della  materia  che  tramandavano  la  dottrina  di  Sabino,  cioe 
in  quello  di  Paolo :  D.  viii.  2,  26  ed  in  quello  di  Papiniano :  D. 
x.  3,  28. 

Nel  passo  di  Paolo  la  massima  di  Sabino  era  ricondotta  alia 
materia  della  servitu,  e  vi  si  affermava,  convenientemente,  che  il 
socio  nulla  pu6  facere  sulla  cosa  comune  invito  altero,  ne  pro- 
hibere  iure  servitutis.  Cosi  il  giureconsulto  escludeva  direttamente 
la  possibility  della  negatoria  tra  socii ;  e  doveva  nel  seguito,  come 

1  Per  gli  antichi  v.  Zacharia,  Zeit.  f.  g.  RW.  vol.  xii.  p.  277  (a.  1845). 

2  L.  c.  p.  259  seg. 

3  Cosl  Ferrini,  Per  /'    viii  cent.  delF  Universitcl  di  Bologna,  p.   96,  che 
riporta  p.  99  n.  5  1'  opinione  posteriore  dello  Zacharia,  che  avrebbe  in  seguito 
riconosciuto  le  due  formule  egualmente  applicabili,  mentre  sagacemente  nel- 
1'  art.  cit.  aveva  escluso  la  negatoria,  come  fa  tuttora  il  Lenel,  ZSS.  vol.  xii.  /.  c.  ; 
Segre,  /.  c.  p.    525   segue  il  Ferrini.      Secondo   una  opinione   particolare    di 
Beseler,  Beitrage,  i.  p.  79,  «  Marcellus  meint  in  Wirklichkeit  die  a°  pro  socio  »  ; 
uno  svarione  certamente,  generato  dalla  critica  « a  turbina »  ;  che  s'  indulge 
volentieri,  per   altro,  per  il   prezioso   contribute    di    nuove    osservazioni  che 
P  illustre  scrittore  ha  saputo  portare  allo  studio  del  Digesto. 


6o  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

io  ritengo,  far  menzione  della  proibizione  privata  che  il  socio 
dissenziente  poteva  adoperare.  II  tratto  pero  fu  dai  compilatori 
eliminate  e  sostituito  dal  seguente  periodo : 

[Sed  per  communi  dividundo  actionem  consequitur  socius,  quo 
minus  opus  fiat  aut  ut  id  opus  quod  fecit  tollat,  si  modo  toti 
societati  prodest  opus  tolli.] 

L'  a.  c.  d.  serve,  dunque,  ora  a  regolare  i  rapporti  tra  i  socii 
durante  la  comunione,  e  serve  qui  particolarmente  ad  impedire 
P  opera  che  uno  dei  socii  voglia  eseguire  sulla  cosa  invito  altero, 
ovvero  quando  sia  compiuta  a  farla  rimuovere.  E  pertanto  la 
interpolazione  di  questo  passo  combacia  perfettamente,  quanto  al 
risultato  sostanziale,  con  quella  osservata  di  sopra  nel  testo  di 
Marcello. 

E  la  sovrapposizione  e  piu  visibile  nelP  altro  di  Papiniano,  gia 
noto,  e  che  cosl  continua  : 

[fr.  28  D.  x.  3.  Sed  etsi  in  communi  prohiberi  socius  a  socio  ne 
quid  faciat  potest,  ut  tamen  factum  opus  tollat,  cogi  non  potest,  si 
cum  prohibere  poterat,  hoc  praetermisit :  et  ideo  per  communi 
dividundo  actionem  damnum  sarciri  poterit  ;  sin  autem  facienti 
consensit,  nee  pro  damno  habet  actionem,  quod  si  quid  absente 
socio  ad  laesionem  eius  fecit,  tune  etiam  toliere  cogitur.] 

Lo  ius  prohibendiy  nel  senso  a  noi  chiaro,  che  Papiniano  riportava 
all'  uguaglianza  dei  diritti  dei  socii,  subl  qui  un'  illustrazione 
sovversiva,  da  parte  di  Triboniano,  mediante  varie  distinzioni  di 
cui  ci  occuperemo  in  luogo  opportune,  ma  che  son  dirette  pure  a 
render  palese  che  il  mezzo  con  cui  esso  si  esplica  e  appunto  P  a.  c. 
d.>  resa  ora  necessaria  per  chiedere  risarcimento  del  danno  o  per  far 
rimuovere  P  opera,  e  quindi  anche  per  ostacolarne  P  inizio. 

Anche  questo  testo,  cosl,  si  riannoda  a  quelli  di  Marcello  e  di 
Paolo,  in  quanto  concerne  la  forma  giudiziaria  del  prohibere. 

28.  In  altri  due  testi  accanto  al  indicium  c.  d.  si  fa  pure 
menzione  del  pretore  che  pu6  essere  adito  per  attuare  P  impedi- 
mento  alP  opera  iniziata  da  uno  dei  socii.  I  passi  sono  consecutivi 
e  del  seguente  tenore  : 

fr.  3,  §  i,  D.  xxxix.  i,  Ulp.  52  ad  ed.  Si  in  loco  communi 
quid  fiat,  nuntiatio  locum  habebit  adversus  vicinum,  plane  si  unus 
nostrum  in  communi  loco  faciat,  non  possum  ego  socius  opus  novum 
ei  nuntiare,  sed  eum  prohibebo  [communi  dividundo  iudicio  vel  per 
praetorem~\. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  61 

§  2.  Quod  si  socius  meus  in  communi  insula  opus  novum  faciat 
et  ego  propriam  habeam,  cui  nocetur,  an  opus  novum  nuntiare  ei 
possim  ?  et  putat  Labeo  non  posse  nuntiare,  quia  possum  eiim  alia 
ratione  prohibere  aedificare,  \hoc  est  vel  per  praetorem  vel  per 
arbitrum  communi  dividundo :]  quae  sententia  vera  est. 

Le  aggiunte  tribonianee  sono  evidentissime  : J  e  mirano  appunto 
a  dare  all'  indicium  c.  d.  quella  funzione  a  noi  nota  di  regolare 
i  rapporti  dei  socii,  in  qualsiasi  evenienza. 

I  giureconsulti  negavano  1'  applicabilita  tra  socii  della  o.  n.  n.y 
per  la  natura  stessa  del  condominio,  perche,  essendo  ciascuno  di 
essi  domino,  poteva,  secondo  la  frase  di  Labeone :  alia  ratione 
prohibere^  cioe  di  propria  mano.  fe  possibile  anzi  che  Ulpiano 
avesse  in  questo  luogo  dichiarata  la  forma  della  proibizione,  cui 
poteva  ricorrere  il  socio,  ma  i  compilatori  si  affrettarono  a  sostituirvi 
quella  legale  ;  o  per  mezzo  del  iudicium  c.  d.  ovvero  per  praetorem. 
In  quest'  ultimo  caso  con  quale  formula  ?  Non  certamente  con 
T  Uti possidetiS)  come  si  ritiene,  perche  tra  due  possessor!  T  interdetto 
resterebbe  inefficace.2  E  se  la  domanda  ed  il  dubbio  restano  qui 
senza  una  congrua  risposta,  noi  vedremo  che  in  questa  materia  il 
caso  si  ripetera  assai  di  frequente.  Tenga  pertanto  il  lettore 
memoria,  per  ora,  della  frase  per  praetorem  ripetuta  nei  due  testi, 
e  che  incontreremo  in  altri  passi. 

29.  Anche  Pomponio,  che  escludeva,  come  sappiamo,3  tra 
condomini  il  iudicium  finium  regundorum,  appare  in  altro  luogo 
fermo  nell'  ammettere  tra  essi  un'  azione  per  impedire  immissioni 
da  parte  di  uno  nell'  edificio  comune : 

27  D.  viii.  2  Pomp,  xxxiii.  ad  Sab.  Sed  si  inter  te  et  me 
communes  sunt  Titianae  aedes,  et  ex  his  aliquid  non  iure  in  alias 
aedes  meas  proprias  immissum  sit,  nempe  tecum  mihi  agere  licet 
aut  rem  perdere.  Idem  fiet  si  ex  tuis  propriis  aedibus  in  communes 
meas  et  tuas  aedes  quid  similiter  esset  proiectum  :  mihi  enim  soli 
tecum  est  actio. 

L'  azione  accordata  con  una  certa  baldanza  non  e  poi  determi- 
nata,  nemmeno  qui.  Intanto  la  negatoria  non  puo  essere,  che 
Giavoleno  1'  esclude  recisamente,4  tanto  meno  il  iudicium  c.  d.  che 
non  aveva  siffatta  funzione. 

1  Cfr.  Berger,  TeilungskL  p.  235  ;  ivi  per  la  letteratura. 

2  D.  xliii.  17,  3  pr. 

3  Cfr.  D.  x.  i,  4,  7,  e  sopra  n.  24.  4  D.  xxxiii.  3,  4. 


62  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

Dunque  e  un  mezzo  nuovo  introdotto  dai  compilatori,  e  che 
si  ricongiunge  al  fr.  26  di  Paolo,  che  precede  nel  titolo,  dove  la 
proibizione  del  socio  si  esplica  mediante  il  indicium  c.  d. ;  o  che  si 
puo  riconnettere  al  fr.  1 1  D.  viii.  5  di  Marcello,  vale  a  dire  ad  una  di 
quelle  formule  della  negatoria  o  della  cosl  detta  prohibitoria,  che  gia 
conosciamo.  E  di  fatto  le  due  interpretazioni  sono  rappresentate.1 

Ma  per  il  diritto  classico  la  cosa  e  ben  diversa.  Pomponio 
doveva  ivi  contemplare  la  negatoria,  escludendola  appunto,  come 
1'  aveva  esclusa  Paolo,  nella  maniera  che  sappiamo,  nel  luogo 
corrispondente  dell'  opera  ad  Sabinum ;  e  Pomponio  doveva  pure 
ricordare  in  quel  tratto  che  il  socio  ha  sovratutto  lo  ius  prohibendi, 
in  forza  del  quale  pu6  distruggere  di  sua  autorita  1'  opera  fatta  nel- 
T  edificio  comune  :  aut  rem  perdere. 

Se  questa  frase,  come  e  stato  sempre  ritenuto,2  ha  un  tal 
significato,  noi  abbiamo  qui  una  traccia  ben  marcata  dell'  indirizzo 
che  aveva  il  passo  di  Pomponio,  e  delle  alterazioni  compiutevi  dai 
compilatori.3  Tentarne  la  restituzione  non  e  possibile,  perche  gli 
elementi  sono  scarsi ;  ma  la  dimostrazione  esauriente  che  ne  ho  data, 
e  sopratutto  la  confluenza  di  tutte  le  interpolazioni  verso  lo  stesso 
punto  non  possono  lasciare  dubbio  di  sorta.4 

E  cosi  e  provato  che  1'  attuazione  dello  ius  prohibendi  a  mezzo 
del  magistrate,  con  una  formula  qualsiasi  spesso  neppure  designata, 
e  un'  innovazione  di  Giustiniano. 

1  Ferrini  (Per  F  viii  centenario  della  Univ.  di  Bologna,  pp.  97,  99  ;  Pand. 
p.  449  n.  i)  riferisce  la  decisione  alia  negatoria,  e  vi  si  richiama  per  spiegare 
altri  passi  ;  cosi  ora  Segre,  MM.  Girard,  ii.  p.  525  nota. 

2  Cf.    Glossa   e   Gotofredo  ad    h.    L,    che   danno  della   frase  una   doppia 
spiegazione  ;  (a)  perdam  ius  prohibendi  \  (b)  id  est  destruere  opus.     Cuiacio  ac- 
colse  la  prima  (Opp.  v.  p.  550)  :  si  non  egero  rent  perdidero  ;  ed  in  altro  luogo 
spiega :  libertatem  praedii  amittere.     Ma  la  maggioranza    degli   interpret!   e 
Gliick  stesso  che  ne  riferisce   (Erldut.   v.   x.   p.   76)  abbraccib   la  seconda 
spiegazione,  cioe  :  opus  factum  propria  auctoritate  destruere,  con  richiamo  al 
fr.  29  §  i  D.  ix.  2. 

3  Un  altro  passo  di  Pomponio  alterato  nello  stesso  senso  si  ha  in  D.  viii.  5, 
1 4,  pr.   .   .   \irno  etiam  agere  tecum  potero,  ut  ea,  quae  nova  immiseris  to  lias] 
mentre  il  giurista  ammetteva  sola  la  proibizione  :  prohiberi  a  me  potes.     E 
cosl  nel  §  i,  .   .  .  potero  tecum  agere :  Pomp,   avrk  scritto  :  non  potero  t.  a. 
L'  interpolazione  e  visibile  nel  pr.  del  testo,  dacche  la  prohibitio  vi  appare  in 
contrasto  (immo)  con  1'  agere. 

4  Come  semplice  chiarimento  della  dimostrazione  fatta,  si  puo  supporre 
che   Pomp,   avesse  scritto  nella  parte  centrale  cosl  :  nempe  tecum  mihi  agere 
\nori\  licet ;  [ius  tibi  non  esse  it  a  immissum  habere  ;  sed  possuin\  rem  perdere. 
[Quod  si]  .   .  . 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  63 

(b)  Formula  prohibitoria 

30.  E  dalla  dimostrazione  che  precede  fluisce  un'  altra  conse- 
guenza  di  singolare  rilievo,  che  riflette  la  formula  prohibitoria  messa 
in  luce  dallo  Zacharia1  da  uno  scolio  di  Stefano  al  fr.  5,  §  I,  D.  vii. 
6,  e  che  ha  avuto  un'  esistenza  travagliata.2  Ma  in  ultimo  essa 
ebbe  posto  onorevole  nell1  Editto,  per  F  adesione  manifestata  dal 
Lenel,  che  ne  era  state  1*  avversario  piu  formidabile  ed  autorevole.3 
Tra  i  casi  di  applicazione  della  prohibitoria  quello  offerto  dal  fr.  1 1 
D.  viii.  5  di  Marcello  era  certamente  il  piu  insigne,  sovratutto  il  piu 
verisimile,  perche  gia  lo  Zacharia  e  poi  il  Lenel  avevano  notato  la 
inamissibilita  della  negatoria  tra  condomini.  Si  disse,  per  ci6,  che 

10  ius  prohibendi  consentito   da    Marcello  doveva   riportarsi   alia 
formula  prohibitoria. 

II  risultato  qui  raggiunto  intorno  al  significato  del  prohibere  tra 
condomini,  ed  in  particolare  nel  passo  genuine  di  Marcello,  toglie 
ogni  base  a  quelle  interpretazioni,  e  di  conseguenza  a  questa 
applicazione  precipua  della  formula  prohibitoria. 

E  cosi  e  chiusa  la  breve  storia  della  nuova  formula  rivelata  da 
Stefano  ;  avvegnache  tolto  di  mezzo  il  testo  di  Marcello,  quell'  altro 
concernente  1'  usufrutto,  cui  il  maestro  bizantino  direttamente  si 
riferisce  nella  sua  parafrasi,  e  meno  che  mai  idoneo  a  giustificare 
F  esistenza  nell'  editto  d'  una  speciale  azione  proibitoria.  Ne  per  cio 
abbiamo  noi  bisogno  di  svalutare  le  notizie  dei  giuristi  bizantini  e 
delle  fonti  greche  in  generale.  Perch&  esse  hanno  importanza  di 
prim'  ordine  sotto  un  doppio  aspetto :  (a)  per  il  diritto  classico,  e 
quindi  per  ricostruire  i  testi  antichi,  quando  lo  scoliaste  trae  i  suoi 
materiali  dai  lavori  compiuti  dagli  ^/awes  sulle  fonti  romane  ;4  (b)  per 

11  diritto  giustinianeo,  negli  altri  casi  in  cui  F  interprete  greco  lavora 
direttamente  sui  libri  di  Giustiniano. 

Nel  caso  nostro  non  e  dubbio  che  Stefano  in  quel  punto  inter- 
pretava  e  commentava  il  passo  dei  Digesti^  senza  F  aiuto  di  esemplari 

1  Zeitschrift  f.  g.  RW.  v.  xii.  (1844),  p.  259  seg.    Bas.   Suppl.  p.  112, 
scol.  6. 

2  Contro  specialmente,  Lenel,  ZSS.  ii.  p.  72  seg. ;  in  favore  Ferrini,  Per 
F  viii  centencuio  della  Univ.  di  Bologna^  p.  92  seg. 

3  ZSS.  v.  12,  p.  i  seg.  ;  Ed.  Perp.  2a  ed.  p.  186.     Per  la  letteratura  cfr. 
Audibert,  Studii per  Fadda,  v.  5,  p.  363  seg.  ;  Segre,  Mil.  Girard,\\.  p.  525 
seg. 

4  Molti  esempii  nei  miei  scritti :  cfr.  ZSS.  v.  33,  p.  288,  e  citazioni  ivi, 
n.  i. 


64  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

antichi.  La  parafrasi  in  discorso  e  sotto  molti  aspetti  miserabile, 
tra  i  prodotti  piu  scadenti  del  maestro  coevo  di  Giustiniano.  Ma 
della  notizia  che  egli  da  non  si  puo  ne  si  deve  dubitare.1  La  formula 
prohibitoria  e  riportata  dal  comentatore,  particolareggiata,  in  con- 
trapposto  alia  negatoria :  aAAoi/  TVTTOV  Trpovifitropiov ;  ed  e  poi 
confermata  da  altre  testimonianze ; 2  ed  e  applicata  ad  un  testo 
sicuramente3  rimaneggiato  dai  compilatori,  come  io  credo  con 
1'  aggiunta  delle  parole  vel  sibi  ius  esse  prohibendi ;  e  per  cio  non 
abbiamo  motivo  per  negar  fede  a  Stefano,  che  riferisce  appunto  lo 
stato  del  diritto  e  della  pratica  del  suo  tempo.  Se  la  formula  in 
discussione  sia  poi  da  considerare  come  un  mero  prodotto  della 
Compilazione,  o  piuttosto  della  pratica  bizantina  avanti  Giustiniano, 
e  un  problema  su  cui  d'  ora  innanzi  potra  1'  indagine  indirizzarsi. 
Per  ora  e  accertato  questo  :  che  nei  Digesti  e  visibile  la  distinzione 
tra  una  formula  negatoria  e  altra  prohibitoria^  come  Stefano 
insegna ;  e  poi,  che  i  compilatori  diedero  sicuramente  significato  e 
valore  processuale  al  prohiberey  che  era  inteso  dai  classici  in  altro 
senso.4 

(c)  La  difesa  privata 

3 1.  L' affermazione  ultima  fatta  nella  chiusa  del  paragrafo  che  pre- 
cede deve  essere  posta  qui  al  sicuro  da  ogni  dubbio,  ed  approfondita 
per  via  di  una  rapida  indagine  sul  diritto  alia  difesa  privata,  che  era 
ammesso  in   molti   casi    neir  ordinamento   giuridico   del    periodo 
classico ;  ed  appare,  invece,  con  singolare  perseveranza,  soppresso 
da   Giustiniano,   surrogate   dovunque   con    un    mezzo  processuale 
qualsiasi. 

32.  I  casi  sono  di  vario  ordine  : 

(a)  II  proprietario  poteva  impedire  di  propria  autorita,  anche 

1  Per  Beseler,  Beitrage,  i.  p.  79,  e  una  « leggenda  ». 

2  Cfr.  Zacharia,  /.  c.  ;  Lenel,  Ed.  p.  186,  n.  i. 

8  Cos!  gia  Zacharia,  Z.  cit.  p.  263,  n.  4,  che  vi  suppone  «  etwas  ausgefallen 
e  poi  Ferrini,  /.  c.  p.  96,  e  Lenel,  Z.  cit.  12,  p.  12  ;  Beseler,  Beitrdge,  i.  78, 
dichiara  interpolata  tutta  la  parte  centrale  ;  Segre,  Mel.  Girard,  ii.  p.  527,  la 
frase  vel  .  .  .  prohibendi. 

4  Per  cio  riprendono  ora  tutta  la  loro  forza  i  relievi  del  Lenel  fatti  in  ZSS. 
ii.  loc.  cit.,  e  principalmente  la  constatazione  che  nei  comentarii  all1  Ed.  non  vi 
e  traccia  di  una  tale  formula.  II  Ferrini  (/.  c.  p.  95),  nei  fervore  per  1'  actio 
prohibitoria,  giunse  a  dire  che  essa  dovette  essere  oscurata  dai  compilatori, 
che  intendevano  fonderla  con  la  negatoria ;  asserzione  questa  del  tutto 
gratuita. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  65 

con  la  forza,  qualsiasi  costruzione  o  immissione  nel  fondo,  senza 
ricorrere  alia  denuncia  di  nuova  opera.  Giustiniano  ne  ha  fatto 
divieto,  come  si  pu6  dimostrare  con  1'  esame  del  passo  che  segue : 

5  §   10  D.  xxxix.  I,  Ulp.  52         Ulpianus. 

ad  ed.     Meminisse  autem  opor-         Meminisse    autem    oportebit, 
tebit,    quotiens   quis    in    nostro     quotiens.quis  in  nostro  aedificare 
aedificare    vel    in    nostrum    im-     vel    in   nostrum    immittere    vel 
mittere  vel  proicere  vult  \melius     proicere  vult  [posse  nos  eum  per 
esse  eum  per  praetorem  vel  per     manum]  prohibere,  quam  operis 
manum    id    est    lapilli    ictum~\     novi  nuntiatione  cet. 
prohibere,    quam     operis     novi 
nuntiatione.       Ceterum     operis 
novi     nuntiatione     possessorem 
eum  faciemus,  cui  nuntiaverimus. 
At  si  in  suo  quid  faciat,  quod 
nobis  noceat,   tune  operis   novi 
denuntiatio  erit  necessaria. 

\_Et  si  forte  in  nostro  aliquid 
facer  e  quis  per s  ever  at  >  'aequis  si- 
mum  erit  interdicto  adversus  eum 
quod  vi  aut  clam  aut  uti  possidetis 
uti.} 

La  ragione  per  cui  Ulpiano  sconsigliava  il  mezzo  della  denuncia 
e  rimarchevole ;  e  qui  va  notata  particolarmente,  perche  non  se 
n'  e  fatto  il  conto  che  merita.  Infatti  e  ovvio  che  il  proprietario 
non  deve  esser  messo  nella  condizione  piu  sfavorevole  processual- 
mente,  come  lo  sarebbe  con  la  denuncia ;  la  quale  costituisce 
P  avversario  possessore1  e  riversa  gli  oneri  della  prova,  ed  un  pericolo 
maggiore  per  1*  esito  della  lite,  a  chi  e  gia  nel  possesso  del  fondo. 
Questi  pertanto  ha  facolta  momentaneamente  di  respingere  il 
tentative  fatto  dal  terzo,  che  menoma  il  sup  diritto ;  e  lo  pu6 
respingere  con  la  forza,  per  manum^  come  si  esprimeva  Ulpiano  in 
maniera  significativa  ed  appropriate  Ma  Giustiniano  reprime  il 
consiglio  turbolento  e,  sconvolgendo  il  testo,  addita  la  via  migliore 
cioe  per  praetor em^  ovvero  mediante  P  innocuo  getto  del  lapillo,  che 
qui  diventa  ridicolo.2  II  rinvio  al  pretore,  con  1'  identica  frase  e 
nella  medesima  situazione  occorre,  come  sappiamo,  due  volte  nel 
fr.  3  dello  stesso  titolo ;  ed  in  tutti  cotesti  casi  solo  la  credenza 

1  D.  xxxix.  i,  i,  6. 

2  E  percib  la  frase  si  e  ritenuta  una  glossa :  cfr.  Windscheid,  Pand.  §  465, 
n.  1 8  ;  Lenel,  Pal.  ii.  c.  745  n.  2  ;  Audibert,  I.e.  p.  360,  n.  2. 

F 


66  5*.  Riccobono  [iv 

radicata  nell'  incontaminata  riproduzione  dei  passi  dei  giuristi  ha 
potuto  intendervi  T  Uti  possidetisy  cosi  designate  da  uno  scrittore 
classico.  Certo  nella  compilazione  tale  significato  non  solo  e 
possibile  ma  e  piano ;  come  lo  dimostra  gia  la  chiusa  dello  stesso 
frammento,  che  e  pure  evidentemente  interpolatizia.1 

33.  (b)  Colui  che  si  trova  nel  godimento  pacifico  di  una  servitu 
pu6  impedire  prontamente,  di  sua  autorita,  qualsiasi  innovazione 
sul  fondo  servente,  che  verrebbe  a  ledere  1'  esercizio  del  suo  diritto. 

fr.  6  §  i  D.  viii.  5,  Ulp.  17  ad  ed. 

Sciendum  tamen  in  his  servitutibus  possessorem  esse  eum 
\iuris  et  petitorem~\ ;  et  si  forte  non  habeam  aedificatum  altius  in 
meo  adversarius  meus  possessor  est :  nam  cum  nihil  sit  innovatum, 
ille  possidet  et  aedificantem  me  prohibere  potest  [et  civili  actione 
et  inter dicto  Quod  vi  aut  clam :  idem  et  si  lapilli  iactu  impedieritJ] 
sed  et  si  patiente  eo  aedificavero  ego  possessor  ero  effectus. 

Questo  passo  si  agguaglia  in  tutto  al  precedente.  Sullo  stesso 
fondamento  il  giureconsulto  insegnava  che  colui  il  quale  gode  il 
possesso  della  servitu  non  deve  perdere  tale  vantaggio  per  T  opera 
o  il  fatto  arbitrario  di  chi  1*  appresta  ;  ne  deve  egli  per  cio  assumere 
le  parti  di  attore  ;  ch&  piuttosto  puo  prohibere  con  qualsiasi  mezzo, 
1'  inizio  delle  opere  che  modificherebbero  lo  stato  delle  cose.  Ma  se 
poi  egli  non  si  oppone  alia  edificazione  e  tollera  le  opere  intraprese 
dair  avversario,  allora  perde  la  qualita  di  possessore  e  deve  assumere, 
quando  voglia,  le  parti  di  attore. 

II  testo  di  Ulpiano  era,  dunque,  lucidissimo  e  cospicuo ;  ma  fu 
rovinato  da  Giustiniano  per  bandire  ogni  traccia  della  difesa 
privata.  E  pertanto  egli  ingiunge,  che  il  possessore  di  siffatte 
servitu  deve  di  necessita  essere  pure  petitorem^  quando  T  avversario 
per  via  di  opere  o  altrimenti  menoma  il  suo  diritto ;  ed  in  luogo 
della  prohibitio  privata  regala  al  possessore  i  mezzi  piu  varii :  una 
civilis  actio,  un  interdetto  e,  dopo  tutto  questo,  con  atroce  ironia, 
il  diritto  del  «lapillo». 

S'  intende  che  nessuno  di  cotali  mezzi  s'  e  potuto  finora  giusti- 
ficare  o  soltanto  spiegare  ;  come  ha  mostrato  di  recente  P  Audibert 2 
in  una  speciale  dissertazione,  persuasiva  e  stringente  nella  parte 

1  Osserva :   si  forte  .  .   .  aequissimum  erit  .  .  .   uti.     Ma  perche  molto 
equo  ?     E  vero  per  altro  che  quando  la  proibizione  privata  resta  inefficace  vi 
hanno  tutte  le  condizioni  per  esperire  1'  Int.  Quod  m  aut  clam. 

2  Studii  per  Fadda,  vol.  v.  p.  341  seg. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprietct  67 

critica  o  negativa  che  si  voglia  dire,  ma  che  per  il  resto  risuscita 
piu  vivo  lo  sconforto  per  la  soluzione  del  problema. 

Infatti  I1  Audibert  ha  voluto  vedere  nella  civilis  actio  indicata 
nel  testo  nientemeno  che  la  o.  n.  nuntiatio ;  cioe  giusto  quel  mezzo 
che  Ulpiano  escludeva  nel  fr.  5  §  10  D.  xxxix.  I,  onde  il  posses- 
sore  non  avesse  a  perdere  il  vantaggio  della  sua  posizione  ed  esser 
costretto  a  iniziare  la  lite  da  attore.  Ed  e  questo  rilievo  e  le 
ulteriori  coincidenze  tra  i  due  passi  che  debbono  attirare  la  nostra 
attenzione,  senza  per  altro  indugiare  sulla  strana  terminologia  che 
si  attribuisce  ad  Ulpiano  per  designare  la  nuntiatio.  lo  affermo 
per  cic-  che  i  due  testi  coincidevano  anche  rispetto  al  mezzo  di 
difesa  additato  da  Ulpiano. 

34.  Ma  si  dira  che  tra  i  due  passi  v'  e  un  punto  di  differenza 
che  non  si  pu6  colmare ;  perche  il  fr.  5  §  ioZ>.  xxxix.  I,  riguarda  il 
proprietario,  che  al  postutto  puo  essere  autorizzato  a  distruggere  le 
opere  o  impedire  1'  invasione  del  proprio  fondo,  perche  agisce  in 
suo ;  mentre  nel  caso  del  fr.  in  esame  ammettere  la  proibizione 
privata  contro  colui  che  inizia  le  costruzioni  entro  i  confini  della 
sua  proprieta  sarebbe  cosa  gravissima  ed  inaudita. 

La  osservazione  e  impressionante  a  prima  vista ;  ma  non  nella 
sostanza.  Perche  giusto  1'  elemento  del  possesso  attuale,  nell'  uno 
e  neir  altro  testo,  e  messo  in  rilievo  dal  giureconsulto  ai  fini  pro- 
cessuali ;  e  su  quell'  elemento  e  fondata  la  decisione,  eguale  nei 
due  casi,  perche  pari  e  la  posizione.  Chi  e  nel  godimento  di  una 
servitu,  che  presuppone  uno  stato  di  cose  permanente,  e  considerate 
possessore,  ed  ha  diritto  di  fronte  all'  avversario  di  veder  mantenuto 
quello  stato,  fino  a  tanto  che  non  intervenga  un  pronunziato  del 
giudice  che  dichiari  la  liberta  del  fondo  servente.  E  percic-  il 
tentative  di  alterare,  arbitrariamente,  la  faccia  dei  luoghi,  in  modo 
lesivo  per  1'  esercizio  della  servitu,  pu6  essere  represso  con  la  forza ; 
nella  stessa  misura  che  il  proprietario  pu6  respingere  con  la  forza 
1'  invasione  di  altri  nel  proprio  fondo.  La  differenza  tra  chi  opera 
in  alieno  ovvero  in  suo  esiste  certamente  ai  fini  della  liceita  o 
meno  della  difesa  privata ;  ma  essa  viene  in  considerazione  solo 
quando  colui  che  opera  in  suo  non  lede  uno  stato  di  diritto  che 
altri  gode.1  Quando  cio  avvenga,  invece,  anche  colui  che  opera 
in  suo  secondo  la  felice  espressione  di  Marcello :  quodammodo 

1  E  il  caso  del  fr.  29  §  i  D.  ix.  2  :  nullo  iure  habebam. 


68  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

sibi  alienum  quoque  ius  praeripit.     E  per  ci6  la  proibizione  im- 
mediata  e  legittima.1 

35.  E  del  resto  nelle  fonti  vi  hanno  tracce  evident!  di  tale 
diritto,  in  materia  di  servitti  precipuamente.  Cosl  Africano  in 
D.  xxxix.  i,  15  dice :  che  quando  il  possessore  della  servitus  altius 
non  tollendi — ed  e  proprio  il  caso  del  fr.  6  §  I  in  esame — non  si 
difende,  vien  punito  ut  iure  suo  probare  necesse  haberet ;  e  per 
cio  deve  prestar  cauzione  nee  opus  novum  se  nuntiaturum  nee 
aedificanti  vim  facturum.  Or  io  chiedo,  perche  deve  egli  garentire 
che  non  opporra  violenza  air  opera  che  sara  per  fare  il  proprietario 
del  fondo  servente  ?  La  risposta  e  semplice :  perche  ha  il  diritto 
di  servitu  ed  il  godimento  attuale.2  E  pertanto  solo  ai  fini  pro- 
cessuali,  per  pena,  gli  e  inibito  di  proibire  con  la  forza  P  alterazione 
dello  stato  dei  luoghi  che  il  proprietario  del  fondo  servente  potra 
con  nuove  opere  arrecare.  Se  ha  ragioni  da  far  valere :  iure  suo 
probare  necesse  habet.  Nel  fr.  15  D.  viii.  2,  Ulpiano,  a  proposito 
di  opere  fatte  che  impediscono  la  servitus  luminis  pone,  in  primo 
luogo,  il  diritto  del  titolare  della  medesima  a  prohibere  e  cosl  si 
esprime :  quodcunque  igitur  faciat  ad  luminis  impedimentum,  pro- 
hiberi  potest,  si  servitus  debeatur ;  \ppusque  ei  novum  nuntiari  potest, 

1  La  riforma  di  Giustiniano  in  questo  punto  di  diritto  ha  per  ci6  una  grande 
importanza,  che  essa  venne  a  stabilire  una  eccezione  gravissima  al  principio 
che  spetta  all'  attore,  cioe  a  colui  che  non  ha  il  possesso  della  cosa  o  il  godi- 
mento del  diritto,  1'  onere  della  prova.     Qui  per  reprimere  la  difesa  privata  si 
rovescio  quella  massima,  e  si  disse :  possessorem  eum  esse  iuris  et  petitorem. 
Io  ritengo  ora  fermamente  che  sia  questo  appunto  1'  unus  casus  famoso  delle 
Inst.  iv.  6,  2.      Infatti  la  riforma  cosi  grave  attuata  dai  compilatori  doveva 
bene  aderire  alia  loro  mente,  e  poteve  inoltre  essere  accennata  di  sfuggita  nel 
libro  di  scuola,  come  quella  che  nei  latioribus  digestorum  libris  era  indicata 
apertis  verbis.     Cfr.  per  altro,  da  ultimo,  Segre,  Studii  Brugi,  p.  411  e  seg. 

2  Che  questo  elemento  sia  decisivo  emerge  sotto  altro  aspetto  dal  fr.  7 
§  2  D.  xliii.  24  :  lulianus  ait  .   .  .   licere  enim  debet  aedificare  ei,  qui  satis- 
dederit,  cum  possessor  hoc  ipso  constituatur  cet.     Dunque,  chi  e  in  possesso 
pu6  edificare  senza  temere  proibizione  di  sorta  ;  mentre  la  quistione  di  diritto 
rimane  impregiudicata.     Ma  quando  il  possesso  e  dalla  parte  del  titolare  della 
servitu,  questi  puo  impedire  con  la  forza  qualsiasi  opera  che  muti  Io  stato  dei 
luoghi.      Si  noti  ancora  nel  testo  di  Giuliano  la  frase  possessor  .  .  .  con- 
stituatur usata  rispetto  all'  esercizio  o  meno  di  una  servitu,  nella  specie  per  la 
liberta  del  fondo,  e  quindi  ai  fini  unicamente  processuali ;  dal  che  emerge 
che  Ulpiano  nel  fr.  6  §  i   D.  viii.   5,  non  poteva  scrivere  possessorem  esse 
eum   turisl      La  determinazione   iuris  fu  aggiunta  dai  Compilatori    certa- 
mente  ;  perche  per  1'  attribuzione  delle  parti  di  attore  o  convenuto  in  processo 
e  decisivo  solo  possessorem  esse  cioe  che  sia  nel  godimento  di  un  certo  stato, 
di  una  posizione  di  fatto. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  69 

si  modo  sicfaciat,  ut  lumini  noceaf\.  La  prohibitio  ha  luogo  dtmque 
se  la  servitus  &  dovuta.  La  nuntiatio.  forma  nel  passo  un'  appendice 
tribonianea,  che  si  manifesta  tale  per  la  ripetizione  del  verbo 
(potesf)  e  del  presupposto  dell'  impedimento  alia  servitu  (si  modo 
.  .  .  noceaf). 

Per  ci6  anche  nel  fr.  6  §  7  D.  viii.  5.  Ulpiano  doveva  am- 
mettere  in  primo  luogo  la  proibizione  privata  contro  il  proprietario 
delF  edificio  che  deteriora  il  muro  gravato  dalla  servitus  oneris, 
mentre  Giustiniano  vi  sostituisce  delle  azioni :  deteriorem  si  facit 
\aut  per  hanc  actionem  aut  per  operis  novi  nuntiationem\  prohibetur. 

36.  E  la  proibizione  privata  la  sorprendiamo  viva  in  molti  testi, 
nel  momento  della  sua  attuazione  e  del  conflitto. 

i  §  II  D.  xliii.  24:  si  te  volentem  ad  prohibendum  venire 
deterruerit  aliquis. 

20  §  I  eod.  :  Prohibitus  autem  intellegitur  quolibet  prohibentis 
actu,  id  est  vel  dicentis  se  prohibere  vel  manum  opponentis 
lapillumve  iactantis  prohibendi  gratia. 

5  §  I  eod. :  ut  intra  diem  occurrere  ad  prohibendum  non  possit. 

4  §  7  D.  viii.  5  :  adversus  dominum  Seianarum  volo  experiri 
altius  me  tollere  prohibentem. 

in  D.  xlv.  I  :  si  me  non  prohibeas,  uxorem  autem  meam 
prohiberes,  vel  contra  uxore  mea  stipulata  me  prohiberes,  an 
committatur  stipulatio? 

14  fr.  D.  viii.  5  :  prohiberi  a  me  potes. 

Ed  in  tutti  questi  casi  il  divieto  si  esplica  in  difesa  della  pro- 
prieta  o  della  cosa  comune,  o  del  possesso  di  una  servitu,  per 
opere  fatte  in  privato  o  in  pubblico  e  con  tutti  i  mezzi,  fino  alia 
distruzione  dell'  opera  eseguita  in  alieno,  come  si  vede  dagli  esempi 
che  seguono. 

(c]  fr.  7  §  3  D.  xliii.  24,  Ulp.  72  ad  ed.  Bellissime  apud  lulianum 
quaeritur,  an  haec  exceptio  noceat  in  hoc  interdicto,  '  quod  non  tu 
vi  aut  clam  feceris '  ?  ut  puta  utor  adversus  te  interdicto  quod  vi 
aut  clam,  an  possis  obicere  mihi  eandem  exceptionem  quod  non  tu 
vi  aut  clam  fecisti  ? 

et  ait  lulianus  aequissimum  esse  hanc  exceptionem  dare :  nam 
si  tu,  inquit,  aedificaveris  vi  aut  clam,  ego  idem  demolitus  fuero 
vi  aut  clam  et  utaris  adversus  me  interdicto,  hanc  exceptionem 
profuturam  [quod  non  aliter  procedere  debet,  nisi  ex  magna  et  satis 
necessaria  causa :  alioquin  haec  omnia  officio  iudicis  celebrari  oportet\ 

L'  eccezione  giova  a  colui  che  us6  violenza  e  che  distrusse 
1'  opera  fatta  in  alieno,  soltanto  perche  egli  proteggeva  in  tal  modo  il 


70  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

possesso  di  un  diritto,  che  1*  avversario,  malgrado  la  proibizione, 
aveva  leso  con  le  nuove  costruzioni.  Da  che  si  deduce,  che  se  e 
ammissibile  la  difesa  privata  quando  T  opera  e  compiuta,  a  maggior 
ragione  la  si  pu6  esplicare  in  tutti  i  modi  per  impedire  1'  inizio 
della  stessa. 

L'  interpolazione  dell'  ultimo  brano  fu  avvertita  dal  Fabro. 
E  di  fatto  Giustiniano  non  poteva  lasciar  correre  senza  protesta 
un  esempio  cosl  improbo. 

37.  (d)  fr.  2  §  33  D.  xliii.  8  :  Scio  tractatum,  an  permittendum 
sit  specus  et  pontem  per  viam  publicam  facere  :  \et  plerique  probant 
interdicto  eum  teneri\\  non  enim  oportere  eum  deteriorem  viam 
facere. 

II  passo  &  stato  di  recente  discusso 1  e  denunziato  per  le  mende 
formali  evidentissime.  Che  il  brano  dovette  essere  compresso  dai 
compilatori  e  rilevato  dal  Mitteis,  che  suppone  sagacemente,  al 
posto  di  plerique.  Ulpiano  avesse  riportati  nomi  dei  veteres. 
Certo  il  giureconsulto  inizia  con  certa  solennita  la  trattazione,  che 
e  poi  ridotta  a  nulla.  Ed  io  suppongo  che  anche  qui  Ulpiano 
faceva  menzione  della  privata  difesa,2  come  si  legge,  a  proposito 
di  un  caso  che  ha  una  certa  analogia  con  il  presente,  nel 

fr.  50  D.  xli.  I  Pomp.  vi.  :  ex  Plautio :  Quamvis  quod  in  litore 
publico  vel  in  mare  exstruxerimus  nostrum  fiat,  tamen  decretum 
praetoris  adhibendum  'est,  ut  id  facere  liceat :  immo  etiam  manu 
prohibendus  est,  si  cum  incommodo  ceterorum  id  faciat;  nam 
civilem  eum  actionem  de  faciendo  nullam  habere  non  dubito. 

E  questo  1'  unico  esempio,  per  quanto  e  a  mia  conoscenza,  in 
cui  e  ammessa  la  legittimita  della  difesa  privata,  ed  e  veramente 
prezioso,  come  una  sopravvivenza  storica. 

Ma  nella  compilazione  il  testo  genuino  fu  indubbiamente 
annullato  in  D.  xxxix.  I,  cioe  nel  titolo  in  cui  Triboniano  us6  piu 
vigilanza  nell'  eliminare  lo  ius  prohibendi  nel  senso  classico,  e 
percio  noi  leggiamo  ora  nel  fr.  I  §  18 — {si  quis  igitur  velit  ibi 
aedificantem  prohibere,  nullo  iure  prohibet ;  neque  opus  novum 
nuntiare  ;  nisi  ex  una  causa  potest  si  forte  damni  infecti  velit  sibi 

1  Cfr.  Beseler,  Beitrage,  ii.  p.  16  ;  Mitteis,  ZSS.  vol.  xxxiii.  p.  193. 

2  Non  affronto  qui  la  quistione  se  1'  ed.  de  damno  infecto  avesse  contenuto 
una  clausola  relativa  a  opus  quod  in  via  publica  fiet,  cio  che  io  negherei.      Ma 
v.  Lenel,  Ed.  p.  360,  n.  i,  che  ha  gia  ben  valutato  le  ragioni  del  dubbio. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  71 

caveri\.     I  contorcimenti  del  periodo  e  le  forme  bizantine  consuete 
rivelano  1'  alterazione  del  testo. 

38.  (e)  Nel  caso  di  rilascio  del  possesso  da  parte  dei  mis  si  in 
possessionem. 

fr.  i  §  2  D.  xxv.  5,  Ulp.  34  ad  ed.  Necessario  praetor  adiecit, 
ut,  qui  per  dolum  venit  in  possessionem,  cogatur  decedere :  coget 
autem  eum  decedere  [non]  praetoria  potestate  vel  manu  ministrorum 
[ sed  melius  et  civilius  faciet  si  eum  per  interdictum  ad  ius  ordinarium 
remiserit\. 

Qui  sembra  che  il  giurista  dia  al  pretore  il  consiglio  di  agire 
con  piu  correttezza  e  piu  civilmente,  costringendo  il  possessore 
doloso  ad  abbandonare  il  possesso  per  mezzo  di  un  interdetto. 
Quale  non  si  scorge  ne  si  rinviene.1  Ed  e  vero,  invece,  che  la 
costrizione  aveva  luogo  in  simili  casi  praetoria  potestate,  ed 
occorrendo  manu  ministrorum.  Ci6  vieta  Giustiniano. 

00  fr-  5  §  2  D.  xlii.  4,  Ulp.  59  ad  ed.  Ait  praetor  :  si  is  pupillus 
in   suam    tutelam  venerit  eave  pupilla  viripotens  fuerit  et   recte 
defendetur :    eos,    qui    bona    possident,  de    possessione    decedere 
iubebo. 

§3.  ...  ergo  oblata  defensione  deici  poterit  \interdicto  reddito\ 

Finita  la  causa  che  diede  luogo  alia  missio  in  possessionem^  e 
nel  caso  in  esame  quando  il  pupillo  e  gia  in  grado  di  difendersi  o 
e  difeso  da  altri,  il  pretore  ordina  ai  missi  il  rilascio  del  possesso. 
E  venuta  meno  la  iusta  causa  possidendi  autorizzata  dal  magistrate, 
ove  il  detentore  non  ubbidisca  air  ordine  di  abbandonarlo,  pu6 
esserne  impunemente  deietto  per  mano  degli  interessati.  Infatti 
ora  il  suo  possesso  e  vizioso. 

C'  e  bisogno  per  ci6  di  un  interdetto  ?  Ma  dove  mai  si  rinviene 
un  interdetto  che  permetta  la  deiectio  ?  Non  lo  ritrova  appunto  il 
Lenel  che  noi  veneriamo  come  il  piu  insigne  conoscitore  del- 
P  Editto,  dopo  Salvio  Giuliano. 

La  interpolazione  per  altro  e  lampante ; z  oltre  il  mistero  del- 
1'  interdetto,  due  ablativi  assoluti  riferiti  a  diversi  agenti,  nessuna 

1  Cfr.  Lenel,  M Jiang.  Girard,  ii.  p.  82. 

2  Identica  interpolazione  in  D.  xxxvi.  3,  u,  Gai  xiii.  ad  ed.  .  .  .  \mihi 
praetor  accommodat  interdictum  quo'] ;  quel  che  resta  corrisponde  al  procedi- 
mento  effetivo  in  tutti  i  casi  di  missio  ;  cf.  D.  xlii.   5,   33,    I — satisdatione 
interposita  iudicium  accipiatur  et  a  possessione  discedatur.     Quindi,  senz'  altro 
rimedio  processuale. 


72  5.  Riccobono  [iv 

traccia  di  soggetto  del  verbo  poteritl  Identica  interpolazione 
si  riscontra  nel  fr.  40  D.  xlvi.  3  Marc.  3  Inst.  .  .  .  \alioquin  nascitur 
heredi  inter  dictum,  ut  eos  deicere  possif\^  Qui  la  mano  di  Triboniano 
si  manifesta  nel  nascitur  che  non  mi  sembra  possa  adoperarsi  per 
un  rimedio  che  presuppone  ogni  volta  speciale  formulazione.3 
E  finalmente  nella  chiusa  del 

fr.  i  §  9  D.  xliii.  3  :  .  .  .  [  Tutius  tamen  erit  dicendum  hoc  inter- 
dictum  competere,  maxime  si  satisdatum  sit  iam  legatorum  nomine 
nee  recedat,  tune  enim  etiam  possidere  videtur\. 

II  rimedio  che  Ulpiano  indicava  in  questo  luogo  e  gia 
visibile  nel  Digesto  dal  fr.  5  §  2  D.  xlii.  4,  sopra  richiamato,  da 
cui  risulta  che  T  Editto  provvedeva  particolarmente  perche  i  missi 
in  possessionem  si  ritraessero  dal  possesso  quando  la  causa  della 
immissione  era  cessata.  All'  ordine  del  pretore  poteva  seguire  la 
deiectio,  come  rilevai  or  ora. 

Direi  anzi  che  cio  e  attestato  direttamente  da  Ulpiano,  a 
proposito  della  missio  d.  inf.  nomine,  in 

D.  xxxix.  2,  4,  4 ;  si  forte  duretur  non  caveri  ut  possideri  liceat, 
quod  causa  cognita  fieri  solet,  non  duumviros  sed  Praetorem  vel 
Praesidem  permissuros,  item  ut  ex  causa  decedatur  de  possessione. 

Che  questo  brano  possa  essere  stato  compresso  dai  compilatori, 
come  dimostra  la  forma  infelice,  non  importa  ;  1'  ultimo  periodo,  che 
qui  interessa,  e  sicuramente  genuino ;  e  vi  si  attesta  che  il  pretore 
provvede,  senz'  altro,  con  decreti  alle  ulteriori  fasi  della  missio ;  cioe  : 

(a)  ut  possidere  liceat  (cfr.  Lenel,  Ed.  p.  53). 

(b)  ut  decedatur  de  possessione. 

E  pertanto  si  manifesta  in  tutta  la  sua  evidenza  in  tutti  quei 
passi  avanti  esaminati  il  motivo  delle  interpolazioni,  foggiate  tutte 
su  di  uno  stampo,  con  le  frasi  consuete :  melius,  civilius,  tutius  e 
che  introducono  un  mezzo  processuale  qualsiasi,  sostituito  alia 
difesa  privata.  Nel  brano  ultimo,  riferito  i  caratteri  dello  stile 
bizantino  vi  sono  impress!*.4 

1  II  Lenel  (/.  c.  p.  83)  pensa  a  interdetti  formulati  per  i  singoli  casi  infactum. 

2  Lotmar  (ZSS.  vol.  xxxi.  p.  100)  intende  1'  Int.  Quod  legatorum  ;  contro 
Lenel,  /.  c.  p.  81. 

3  Cfr.  Lotmar,  /.  c.  p.  101  ;  ma  vedi  Lenel,  /.  c.  p.  83,  n.  i. 

4  Per  altri  argomenti  sostanziali  v.  Lenel,  /.  c.  p.  84 ;  ma  essi  hanno  per 
me  un  valore  ancora  piu  assoluto,  da  escludere  nel  caso  fatto  da  Ulpiano  1'  Int. 
Quod  legatorum,  o  altro  mezzo  giudiziario.     Diversamente  Lotmar,  /.  c.  p.  103. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  73 

39.  (g)  Una  costituzione  dell'  a.  205  attesta,  anche  per  il  diritto 
dell'  Impero,  1'  uso  e  1'  efficacia  del  patto  in  forza  di  cui  il  creditore 
ipotecario  era  autorizzato  ad  immettersi  di  propria  autorita  nel 
possesso  deir  ipoteca,  quando  al  termine  stabilito  il  suo  credito  non 
fosse  sodisfatto.     Se  tale  convenzione  era  pure  inclusa  nella  lex 
commissoria  non  possiamo  giudicare.1     Ma  dal  diritto  dei  papiri 
greco-egizii   e   documentata   ora   a   dovizia   1'   efficacia   del   titolo 
esecutivo    munito  della  clausola  Ka.Qa.Trep  €/c  Sticks  2   in   forza  della 
quale,  sembra,3  che  il  creditore  avesse  diritto  di  pervenire  senza 
alcun  procedimento  nel  possesso  e  nel  dominio  del  fondo.     Ma  nel 
diritto  di  Giustiniano,  a   parte   il   divieto   della   lex  commissoria 
stabilito   da   Costantino,    e   inibito   al  creditore  d'  immettersi  nel 
possesso  senza  1'  autorizzazione  del  magistrate,  come  risulta  dalla  c. 
seguente : 

3  C.  viii.  14  (Impp.  Sev.  et  Ant.) :  Creditores  qui  non  reddita 
sibi  pecunia  conventionis  legem,  ingressi    possessionem  exercent, 
vim  \quidem\  facere   non   videntur  \attamen   auctoritate  praesidis 
possessionem  adipisci  debent\. 

L'  interpolazione  delle  parole  segnate  in  corsivo  e  nota,4  ed  essa, 
come  fu  pure  avvertito  dal  Naber  determine  inoltre  la  soppressione 
del  non  avanti  al  verbo  potest  nella  c.  5  Cod.  ix.  12,  dell'  a.  294. 5 

40.  E  Giustiniano  a  ricacciare  da  ogni  angolo  della  sua  opera 
qualsiasi  vestigio  di  privata  difesa  attacca .  pure  le  massime  piu 
venerande,  che  secondo  i  Romani  erano  fondate  sulla  naturalis  ratio. 
E  cosi  la  legge  decemvirale :  Si  nox  furtum  faxsit,  si  im  occisit, 
iure  caesus  esto,  fu  ridotta  nei  Digesti  nei  termini  seguenti : 6 

4  §  i  D.   ix.  2,  Gai  vii.  ad  ed.     Lex  XII.  tab.  furem  noctu 
deprehensum  occidere  permittit  \ut  tamen  id  ipsum  cum  clamore  testi- 

ficetur~\ :  interdiu  autem  deprehensum  ita  permittit  occidere,  si  is  se 
telo  defendat,  \ut  tamen  aeque  cum  clamore  testificetur\ 

1  Papin.  V.  F.  9. 

2  Per  la  letteratura  v.  Bertalan  Schwarz,  Hypothek  und  Hypallagma,  p.  7 1 
n.  2  ;  cfr.  Mitteis,  Grundzuge,  ii.  I,  p.  94. 

3  Cfr.  Bertalan,  o.  c.  p.  94. 

4  Cfr.    Naber,  Mnemos.  vol.  xxiv.  p.    171;   Gradenwitz,  ZSS.  vol.  xxvi. 
p.  348  n.  i. 

5  Un  altro  caso  di  vis  legittima  punita  da  Giustiniano  e  in  D.  xlvii.  8,  2, 
1 8  :    quidem  .  .  .  sed  aliter  multabitur.      Ma    sul  proposito  della  violenza 
nelF  esercizio  del  diritto  abbiamo  la  nota  legge  di  Valentiniano  dell'  a.  389 
riportata  nel  Cod.  Just.  viii.  4,  7,  che  commina  la  grave  pena  della  perdita 
del  dominio.  6  Cfr.  Riccobono,  Fontes,  p.  47  n.  B. 


74  S-  Riccobono  [iv 

II  clamore  deve  qui  togliere  il  dubbio  che  1'  uccisore  non  abbia 
agito  in  state  di  necessita,  per  la  difesa  della  persona.1  I  vicini 
accorrenti  ne  potranno  fare  la  verificazione. 

Ed  il  vivo  senso  di  repulsione  per  qualsiasi  atto  di  privata  difesa 
manifesta  con  forza  il  legislatore  in  una  delle  solite  motivazioni 
aggressive,  che  egli  aggiunge  alle  decisioni  pratiche :  Cur  enim, 
inquit  lulianus,  ad  arma  et  rixam  procedere  patiatur  praetor ',  quos 
potest  iurisdictione  sua  componere?^  L'  interrogazione  e  tutto 
un  programma  legislative ;  da  cui  scaturisce  poi  quella  massima 
di  diritto,  una  tra  le  piu  cospicue  e  realmente  universali  nel 
sistema  nuovo,  cioe : 

fr.  176  pr.  D.  L.  xvii.  Paul.  13  ad  Plaut.  Non  est  singulis 
concedendum,  quod  per  magistratum  publice  possit  fieri :  ne 
occasio  sit  maioris  tumultus  faciendi. 

La  quale  pel  diritto  elaborato  dai  giureconsulti  non  e  vera.  Se 
essa  fu  scritta  effettivamente  da  Paolo,  doveva  avere  una  struttura 
piu  limitata,  e  riferimento  particolarissimo.3 

41.  Ed  ora  possiamo  conchiudere  ed  affermare  che  la  riforma  di 
Giustiniano  rispetto  allo  ius  prohibendi  trascende  di  molto  i 
confini  e  I1  importanza  del  tema  in  esame.  Poiche  essa  ci  ha 
rivelato  un  nuovo  atteggiamento  della  legislazione  di  Giustiniano, 
rispetto  al  diritto  classico,  che  appare  per  ci6  diffuse  in  tutta  T  opera 
ed  attuato  con  fermezza,  mediante  amputazioni  profonde  di  decisioni 
e  motivi  e  principi  classici,  tanto  da  sconvolgere  tutta  la  fine 
orditura  delle  actiones  e  dei  mezzi  di  difesa  giudiziaria  del  diritto 
antico.  E  1*  importanza  della  riforma  non'va  ricercata  alia  superficie, 
ma  nell'  intimo  pensiero  e  nella  forza  da  cui  fu  prodotta.  Perche 
essa  non  e  vicenda  esteriore,  quanto  nuova  luce,  che  rivela  nel 
contrasto  aspetti  profondi  delle  due  piu  grandi  civilta  della  storia. 

In  quel  nucleo  di  norme,  infatti,  che  e  venuto  alia  luce,  rimettendo 
a  posto  nel  libro  immortale  ogni  parola  della  sapienza  antica,  vi 
e  un  grande  movimento  di  vita  e  di  forza,  che  si  esplica  con 
T  affermazione  energica  della  volonta  individuale,  e  quindi  con  la 

1  Cfr.    per  altro  fr.    5   pr.  D.   ix.   2  =  Collatio  vii.    ii.    iii.    3  :    sin  autem 
.  .   .  tenebitur ;  che  contiene  certe  limitazioni  in  proposito,  che  non  possono 
derivare  dai  giuristi  classici. 

2  fr.  13  §  3  D.  vii.  i.     Cfr.  Beseler,  Beitrage,  ii.  p.  88. 

3  Ma  il  nesso  non  e  dato  scorgerlo  :  cfr.  Lenel,  Pal.  i.  c.  1 167  n.  5  :  haec 
adinterdicta  multa  posse  referri palam  est.    Ed  il  campo  ora  e  davvero  ristretto. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  75 

potenza  del  diritto  dei  singoli,  che  non  soffre  menomazione  alcuna, 
neanche  momentanea.  E  di  sopra  a  questo  punto  centrale  e 
incardinato  e  si  muove  tutto  il  sistema  del  diritto  private,  elaborate 
con  saggezza  profonda. 

Ma  quella  base  si  corrodeva  ogni  giorno,  e  la  forza  del  diritto 
individuale  si  svigoriva  nell'  ultima  fase  dell'  Impero  fino  a 
Giustiniano ;  in  quel  periodo  in  cui  i  piu  grandi  rivolgimenti  sociali 
e  politici  e  spirituali  si  maturarono.  Ora  la  prepotenza1  piu 
facilmente  usurpava  il  posto  del  diritto,  e  nell'  esquilibrio  delle 
forze  sociali  lo  Stato  doveva  assumere  a  se  un  potere  maggiore, 
che  si  estrinseca  nella  organizzazione  amministrativa  dioclezianea, 
salda,  ordinata  nei  piu  minuti  particolari,  e  preveggente. 

Lo  Stato  ne  esce  rinvigorito,  ed  allarga  ogni  giorno  piu  le 
sue  funzioni,  assumendo  un  carattere  pacificatore  ;  e  per  ci6  per 
ottenere  1'  ordine,  la  disciplina,  il  vantaggio  generale  Esso  esige 
qualsiasi  restrizione  della  liberta  dei  singoli,  ed  in  primo  luogo  dello 
assoluto  diritto  individuale. 

Questa  evoluzione  si  compie  nella  legislazione  del  VI  secolo ; 
essa  ebbe  nel  suo  cammino  la  cooperazione  di  una  grande  forza, 
quale  era  quella  della  dottrina  cristiana,2  che  deprime  e  annulla 
i  sentimenti  egoistici  ed  inculca,  come  primi  doveri,  la  pace  e 
T  amore  fra  tutti  gli  uomini,  anc.he  per  conseguire  i  fini  della  vita 
terrena ;  sentimenti  che  ebbero  in  realta  una  potente  penetrazione 
in  tutti  gli  atti  della  vita.3 

1  Cfr.  Mitteis,  Melang.  Girard,  ii.  p.  226. 

2  In  questo  senso  Leonhard,  Inst.  p.  531  n.  2  ed.  ivi  cit.;  cfr.  ora  anche 
Lenel,  Holttendorff" s   Enc.   7   ed.    p.    375   §   63.     Quanto  poi  al    problema 
generale  dell'  influenza  cristiana  sul  diritto  private  potremo  volutarla  via  via 
con  la  conoscenza  dei  principi  direttivi  della  Compilazione  del  sec.  VI,  che, 
come    si    vede,    sono    per   noi   tutti  ancora  un  mistero ;  cfr.  piu  oltre,   nota 
ultima  del  presente  cap. 

8  E  percio  il  motivo  della  tolleranza,  della  pace,  della  consideraziorie  del 
prossimo  s'  insinua  pure  nella  legislazione,  come  si  osserva  in  una  decisione 
cospicua  che  si  ricollega  alia  difesa  privata  e  quindi  all'  argomento  in  esame. 
Nessun  dubbio,  come  diceva  Q.  Mucio,  che  il  proprietario  puo  cacciar  via  dal 
fondo  gli  animali  penetrativi,  con  tutti  i  mezzi  idonei  allo  scopo,  e  che  non 
puo  rispondere  con  la  lex  Aquilia  qualora  un  danno  ne  derivi  alle  bestie  ;  fr. 
39  D.  ix.  2,  Pomp.  7  ad  Q.  M.  Ma  Giustiniano  soggiunge  subito  ;  Pomponius  : 
quamvis  alienum  pecus  in  agro  suo  quis  deprehendit,  sic  illud  expellere 
debet  quomodo  si  suum  deprehendisset,  quoniam  si  quid  ex  ea  re  damnum  cepit, 
habet  proprias  actiones.  itaque  qui  pecus  alienum  in  agro  suo  deprehenderit, 
non  hire  id  includit,  nee  agere  illud  aliter  debet,  quam  ut  supra  diximus 


76  5.  Riccobono  [iv 

Nel  diritto  giustinianeo  si  manifesta  per  cio  un  mondo  tutto 
nuovo,  in  cui  la  difesa  privata  del  diritto  era  inconcepibile.  Ed  essa 
e  surrogata  dal  piu  svariato  campionario  di  actiones,  interdicta, 
provvedimenti  e  mezzi  giudiziari ;  perche  ciascuno  deve  in  ogni 
evenienza  invocare  1'  aiuto  del  magistrate,  che  e  il  solo  tutore  dei 
diritti  dei  singoli. 

Tra  i  nuovi  mezzi  escogitati  dal  legislatore  o  dalla  pratica 
bizantina  si  annovera  la  irpovifiiTopia, 


II.    IUD1CIUM  COMMUNI  DIVIDUNDO 

42.  Ma  1'  azione  che  puo  dirsi  propria  e  generale  per  il  regola- 
mento  dei  rapporti  tra  condomini  e  1'  a.  c.  div.,  che  da  Giustiniano 
fu  adibita  insietne  agli  altri  mezzi  processuali  nei  casi  piu  svariati. 
E  per  ci6  pu6  affermarsi  che  all'  azione  divisoria  venne  conferita 
nella  Compilazione  una  nuova  funzione,  cio&  quella  di  dirimere 
tutti  i  conflitti  tra  i  socii  e  regolare  la  vita  della  comunione,  senza 
per  altro  condurre  allo  scioglimento  della  medesima.  Nei  passi 
dianzi  esaminati  si  hanno  le  testimonianze  piu  cospicue  del  nuovo 
carattere  assunto  dal  indicium  c,  d. 

E  ci  e  noto  pure  che  in  tal  modo  Giustiniano  ne  altero  in 

quasi  suum :  sed  vel  abigere  debet  sine  damno  vel  admonere  dominum  ut 
suum  recipiat.  E  qui,  come  si  vede,  la  mansuetudire  evangelica  si  scioglie 
in  precetti  e  consigli  che  suonano  duri  anzi  sovrumani  al  fiero  agricoltore  : 
quod  tibi  non  vis  alteri  ne  feceris.  E  percio  il  proprietario  deve  trattare  gli 
animali  altrui  come  i  proprii,  non  deve  loro  far  male,  non  deve  includerli, 
perch£  del  resto  ha  per  il  danno  ricevuto  proprias  actiones.  Deve  piuttosto 
avvertire  I3  interessato  (!).  Indizii  della  mano  di  Triboniano  :  quamvis  .  .  . 
deprehendit,  in  agro,  proptias  actiones,  quasi,  ut  suum  recipiat,  e  poi  la 
ripetizione  del  concetto  fondamentale  e  sovratutto  lo  spirito.  Sospetti  gia 
in  Di  Marzo,  Libri  ad  Q.  Mucium,  p.  89. 

E  lo  stesso  motive  opera  nella  chiusa  del  celebre  frammento  di  Alfeno  II. 
dig.  che  tratta  del  bettoliere  che  rincorre  in  semita  noctu  colui  che  gli 
aveva  rapita  la  lucerna  :  fr.  52  §  i  D.  ix.  2.  .  .  .  \sed  si  ab  eo  non  prior 
vapulasset,  sed  cum  ei  lucernam  eripere  vellet,  rixatus  essel,  tabernarii  culpa 
factum  videri\.  Giustiniano,  dunque,  ammonisce,  che  chi  esercita  la  difesa 
del  proprio  diritto  e  rincorre  il  rapitore  delle  cose  proprie,  deve  usare 
moderazione  e  pacatezza  ;  cerchera  di  strappare  al  malvivente  le  cose  sottratte, 
ma  non  deve  attaccare  la  persona ;  deve  prima  lasciarsi  battere,  e  poi  magari 
non  avra  colpa  del  danno  che  nella  reazione  apportera  all'  altro.  Per  la  critica 
del  brano,  vedi  le  osservazioni  finissime  di  Huvelin,  MM.  Girard,  i.  p.  259  seg., 
il  quale  per  altro  non  attribuisce  le  addizioni  ai  Compilatori.  lo  ritengo 
decisive  il  confronto  con  le  aggiunte  al  testo  di  Q.  Mucio,  avanti  riportato. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  77 

maniera  essenziale  la  natura;  poiche  nel  diritto  classico  ogni  azione 
divisoria  mirava  in  via  principale  ad  effettuare  lo  scioglimento  della 
comunione,  con  1*  attribuzione  della  parte  spettante  a  ciascuno  dei 
socii ;  ed  in  secondo  luogo  poi  a  definire  in  una  volta  tutti  i  rapporti 
personali  sorti  per  causa  della  comunione. 

Cosl  si  spiega  che  un  profondo  conoscitore  delle  fonti  romane 
quale  era  Cuiacio *  pote  vigorosamente  negare  1'  ammissibilita  del 
indicium  c.  d.  durante  la  comunione ;  perche  in  realta  la  Compi- 
lazione  di  Giustiniano  contiene  tutti  gli  elementi  proprii  delP  uno 
e  dell'  altro  sistema,  in  linee  rilevate ;  ma  al  grande  interprete  si 
manifestava  solo  quello  arcaico,  perche  egli  accostava  il  Corpus  luris 
con  spirito  d'  umanista,  che  gP  impediva  di  scorgere  e  comprendere 
1'  opera  di  Giustiniano.  E  P  influenza  del  Cuiacio  fu  somma,  come 
si  sa,  ed  anche  qui  perniciosa ;  e  valse  a  velare  la  verita  per  lungo 
tempo,  tanto  che  il  Windscheid2  giustamente  lamentava,  che 
P  actio  c.  d.  era  stata  trascurata  nella  dottrina  rispetto  alia  sua 
funzione  regolatrice  dei  rapporti  tra  socii,  e  riporta  pure  decisioni 
giudiziarie  che  fino  agli  ultimi  tempi  si  ostinavano  a  negarla. 

Ma  i  Greci  e  la  Glossa  avevano  ben  conosciuto  P  indole  delP  a. 
c.  div.  giustinianea,  senza  ombra  di  dubbio.  E  la  critica  piu  recente 
ha  definitivamente 3  stabilito  i  confini  tra  il  vecchio  ed  il  nuovo  in 
questa  materia,  come  e  tramandato  alia  rinfusa  nel  Corpus  luris. 

43.  E  pertanto  in  questo  luogo  non  interessa  prendere  in  esame 
tutti  i  singoli  testi  che  provano  la  nuova  funzione  delP  a.  c.  d., 
quanto  piuttosto  adunare  i  precipui  tra  essi,  o  quelli  che  offrono 
maggiori  difficolta  d'  interpretazione,  e  presentarli  ordinati  in  V 
categoric,  alle  quali  si  aggregano  i  passi  adibiti : 

(a)  per  attuare  lo  ius  prohibendi,  nei  casi  e  nei  limiti  in  cui  esso 
ha  luogo  nella  Compilazione  ; 

(£)  per  la  partizione  ed  il  conseguimento  delle  spese  fatte  da 
uno  dei  socii ; 

(c)  per  il  danneggiamento  apportato  dal  socio  alia  cosa  comune ; 

(d}  per  la  esecuzione  di  opere  conservative  sulla  cosa,  ed  in 
particolare  per  le  opere  relative  ad  edifici  e  muri  comuni ; 

1  Opp.  vol.  vii.  p.  575  ad  1.  3  D.  Com.  div. 

2  Pand.  §  449  n.  4,  ed  ivi  citati. 

3  Accenni  gia  in   Pernice,  ZSS.  vol.  xix.  p.   173  n.  4;  ma  ora  in  modo 
esauriente  Berger,    Teilungsklagen,  p.   221   seg.,  che  tuttavia  lascia  insoluti 
molti  punti,  del  resto  secondari. 


78  5.  Riccobono  [iv 

(e)  per  applicazioni  varie  del  iud.  c.  d.  e  fam.  ere.,  anche  per 
conferire  efficacia  giuridica  a  rapporti  che  non  1'  avevano  nel  diritto 
classico. 

44.  (a)  Prohibitio. 

E  per  quanto  concerne  il  primo  gruppo  non  occorre  indugiare 
oltre  sul  tema  dello  ius  prohibendi,  che  e  stato  discusso  sotto  ogni 
aspetto  nelle  pagine  che  precedono ;  onde  e  sufficiente  qui  referirci 
all'  esame  compiuto  sui  fr.  26  D.  viii.  2 ;  28  D.  x.  3  ;  3  §§  2,  3  D. 
xxxix.  i. 

45.  (b)  Impensae. 

II  indicium  c.  d.  adibito,  durante  la  comunione,  per  il  consegui- 
mento  di  spese  fatte  da  uno  dei  socii  e  piu  direttamente  attestato 
dai  seguenti  passi. 

fr.  14  §  I  D.  x.  3,  Paul.  3  ad  Plaut. — quae  cum  ita  sint,  rectissime 
dicitur  etiam  impendiorum  nomine  utile  iudicium  dari  debere  mihi 
in  socium  [etiam  manente  rei  communione]  .  .  .  igitur  et  si  abalie- 
navero  praedium  quia  in  ea  causa  fuit,  ut  mihi  actio  dari  deberet, 
danda  mihi  erit,  ut  lulianus  quoque  scribit  \negotiorum  gestorum 
actio]. 

Questo  frammento  collocato  in  sede  materiae  contiene  delle 
riforme  gravissime,  ed  e  interpolate  in  vari  luoghi.  Ma  qui  non  e 
il  caso  di  prendere  in  esame  il  testo  intero,  tanto  piu  che  la  rico- 
struzione  di  esso,  fatta  gia  or  sono  parecchi  anni  nel  mio  Seminario, 
sara  pubblicata  fra  breve.1 

Ma  i  due  punti  che  qui  occorre  rilevare  possono  ora  dirsi  lievi. 
Nel  passo  si  accorda  il  iud.  c.  d.  utile  per  le  spese  fatte  da  un  socio 
sulla  cosa  comune,  che  deve  pur  aver  luogo  etiam  manente  rei 
communione.  In  secondo  luogo  si  da  1'  actio  negotiorum  gestorum 
al  socio  che  abbia  alienato  il  fondo.  E  sono  appunto  coteste  azioni 
che  furono  in  ogni  tempo  causa  di  dubbii  e  discussioni. 

Infatti  1'  ammissibilita  di  quelle  azioni  nei  termini  presupposti 
perturba  nel  modo  piu  strano  tutte  le  nostre  conoscenze.  E  per 
cio,  rispetto  al  primo  punto,  si  voile  ristabilire  una  concordanza 
artificiale  con  T  inserzione2  di  un  non  dopo  la  parola  etiam 

1  V.   per  ora  Berger,  o.  c.  p.  2 1  o  e  seg.  ed  ivi  citati ;  per  altro  i  punti 
essenziali  in  cui  dissento  dal  Berger  e  dagli  altri  scrittori,  circa  1'  interpre- 
tazione  del  passo  giustinianeo,  si  mostreranno  da  s£  stessi. 

2  Cuiacio,  Opp.  vol.  v.  p.  907,  e  cosi  ancora  1'  opinione  dominante. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  79 

della  prima  frase  sopra  trascritta ;  e  si  attribui  facilmente  poi  ad 
una  glossa  maldestra  la  menzione  dell'  actio  negotiorum  gestorum}- 

Rimedii  vani  ed  arbitrari,  consueti  per  altro  e  suggeriti  soltanto 
dalla  imperfetta  conoscenza  che  si  e  avuta  del  dritto  giustinianeo, 
che  e  restate  fin  dal  sec.  xvi,  in  grazia  degli  studi  piii  profondi, 
come  offuscato  dallo  splendore  dei  passi  classici,  serrati,  tersi  e 
coordinati  sempre  in  una  suprema  armonia. 

Ma  oggi  quei  -dibattiti  hanno  termine.  Si  sa  che  il  indicium 
c.  d.  fu  ammesso  dai  Compilatori  in  realta  etiam  manente  rei 
communione,  e  si  dirige  appunto  per  costringere  il  socio  a  non 
impedire  un'  opera  sulla  cosa  comune,  ovvero  a  pagare  gli  oneri 
che  gli  incombono,  o  la  parte  delle  spese,  e  cosi  via.  E  parimenti 
dovrebbe  esser  noto  che  Giustiniano  accordc-  pure  al  socio,  accanto 
all'  actio  c.  d.>  anche  la  negot.  gest.  per  rendergli  possibile  il  con- 
seguimento  delle  spese  fatte.  E  1'  actio  neg.  gest.  ritorna,  precisa- 
mente  congiunta  ai  indicia  divisoria,  nelle  costituzioni,  18  C.  iii. 
36 ;  20  C.  eod.,  inserita  nei  rescritti  con  le  parole  vel  negotiorum 
gestorum. 

La  stessa  interpolazione  che  abbiamo  riscontrata  nel  fr.  14  §  I 
in  esame  si  riaffaccia  poi,  in  una  forma  piu  larvata,  nel  fr.  29  D. 
x.  3,  Paul.  2  quaest.  e  che  tratta  una  delle  ipotesi  contenute  in  quel 
testo ;  cioe  di  spese  fatte  da  un  socio  sulla  cosa  comune  nella 
credenza  che  il  compartecipe  fosse  Tizio  invece  di  Gaio.  Ebbene 
nel  fr.  29  si  legge  : 

recte  dicitur  etiam  communi  dividundo  indicium  ei  sufficere. 

Paolo  aveva  scritto  assai  probabilmente  recte  dicitur  in  com- 
muni dividundo  indicium  ea  quae  impendisset  venire. 

Nel  testo  rifatto  da  Giustiniano  e  la  congiunzione  etiam  ed  il 
verbo  sufficere'1  stanno  ad  indicare  che  il  socio  a  conseguire  dal- 
1'  altro  la  parte  delle  spese  puo  adoperare  vari  mezzi,  anche  T  actio 
c.  d.  laddove  il  giureconsulto  non  poteva  ammettere  qui  che  il 
giudizio  divisorio,  e  mai  altra  azione  personale.  Infatti  la  spesa 
sulla  cosa  comune,  non  essendo  eseguita  in  considerazione  della 

1  Cosl  gia  Cuiacio,  /.  c,;  Scialoja  ad  h.  1.  nella  nostra  edizione  del  Digesto  ; 
Berger,  Teilungskl.  p.  217,  ma  v.  Kriiger  ad  h.  1.  (ed.  1 2a). 

2  Verbo  frequente  nei  brani  interpolati :  D.  vi.  2,  7,  17  :  Nee  quisquam 
putet  hoc  nos  existimare,  sufficere ; — D.   xv.    i,    19,    2:   Idem  etiam   contra 
eveniet  quamvis  in  duobus  dominis  sufficiat  pro  socio  vel  communi  dividundo 
actio :  Ulp.  aveva  scritto  presso  a  poco  :  contra  eveniet  in  duobus  dominis, 
nam  inter  eos  est  c.  d.  iudicium. 


8o  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

persona,  non  pu6  mai  dar  luogo  all'  actio  negot.  gest.  La  quale  e 
esclusa  dal  giureconsulto  nella  stessa  dimostrazione,  esplicitamente  : 
neque  enim  negotia  socii  gero,  sed  propriam  rem  tueor,  et  magis  ex  re, 
in  quam  impenditur  quam  ex  persona  socii  actio  nasciturl  Ho 
ragione  per  ci6  di  ritenere  che  il  sufficere  fu  inserto  dai  Com- 
pilatori  al  posto  della  proposizione  in  cui  Paolo  escludeva  nel  caso 
in  esame  1J  a.  negot.  gest. 

46.  (c)  damnum. 

II  danno  arrecato  da  uno  dei  socii  alia  cosa  comune  puo  ora 
immediatamente  essere  perseguito  in  giudizio  per  mezzo  del  c.  d. 

II  principio  e  appunto  codificato  nel  celebre  passo  di  Papiniano, 
che  giova  qui  riportare  per  intero : 

fr.  28  D.  x.  3 — Sabinus  ait  in  re  communi  neminem  dominorum 
iure  facere  quicquam  invito  altero  posse,  unde  manifestum  esse 
prohibendi  ius  esse :  in  re  enim  pari  potiorem  causam  esse  pro- 
hibentis  constat  [sed  etsi  in  communi  prohiberi  socius  a  socio  ne 
quidfaciat  potest,  ut  tamen  factum  opus  tollat,  cogi  non  potest  si  cum 
prohibere  poterat,  hoc  praetermisit :  et  ideo  per  communi  dividundo 
actionem  damnum  sarciri  poterit  sin  autem  facienti  consensit,  nee  pro 
damno  habet  actionem.  quod  si  quid  absenti  socio  ad  laesionem  eius 
fecit)  tune  etiam  t  oiler  e  cogitur\. 

L'  interpolazione  e  variamente  indicata.2  Ma  io  ritengo  che  in 
realta  essa  comprenda  tutta  la  seconda  parte  dello  squarcio.3  Nel 
periodo  sed  etsi  .  .  .  praetermisit,  si  dispone  che  il  socio  non  ha 
diritto  di  ottenere  la  rimozione  dell'  opera  fatta  dair  altro,  qualora 
egli  abbia  omesso,  potendolo,  di  opporre  il  suo  divieto.  Questo  e 
sicuramente  un  concetto  nuovo,  che  e  in  vivo  contrasto,  come 
sappiamo,  con  la  natura  del  condominio  classico,  in  cui  ciascuno 
dei  socii  conserva  una  signoria  piena  ed  indipendente,  pro  indiviso^ 
sulla  cosa  comune ;  e  che  perci6  non  pu6  soffrire  menomazione 

1  Si   sa  che  1'  a.  negot.   gest.  puo  aver  luogo   tra  condomini,  ma  solo 
quando  si  verifichino  le  condizioni  espresse  appunto  da  Paolo  nel  testo ;  cfr. 
D.  iii.   5,  39,  Paul.  x.  ad  Sab. — quia  potui  partem  meant  ita  defender  e,  ut 
socii  partem  defendere  non  cogerer.     D.  x.  3,  6,  2  Ulp.  19  ad  ed. — ceterum 
non  alias  c.  d.  iudicio^  locus  erit,  ut  et  Papinianus  scribit,  nisi  id  demum  gessit, 
sine  quo  partem  suam  recte  administrare  non  potuit :  alioquin  si  potuit^  habet 
negotiorum  gestorum  actionem  eaque  tenetur. 

2  Cfr.   Lenel,  ZSS.  xii.  p.    1 4  n.  3  [si  cum  prohibere  .  .   .  praetermisit]  ; 
Fadda  in  Studii  Brugi,  p.  144  n.  2  [sin  autem  .  .  .  cogitur^. 

3  Cosl  gik  Segre,  Rivista  it.  per  le  scienze  giur.  vol.  viii.  p.  373  ;  Berger, 
Teilungskl.  p.  233  ;  Paozzi,  Melanges  Girard,  ii.  /.  c. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  81 

per  un  semplice  atto  di  negligenza.  Ma  di  piu  la  forma  del  tratto 
ha  vari  indizii  rivelatori  della  mano  di  Triboniano ;  e  cioe  il 
mutamento  del  soggetto  a  cominciare  dalla  proposizione  cum 
prohibere  poterat  ;  1'  imperfetto  indicative  poterat ;  la  frase  ut  tamen 
—  dummodo,  adoperata  con  vera  prodigalita  dai  compilatori,  per 
introdurre  limitazioni  e  nuovi  presupposti  alle  massime  riferite  dai 
classici.1 

Nella  continuazione  poi  1'  aggiunta  interpolatizia  e  manifesta 
per  i  riscontri  ormai  noti :  e  qui  appunto  si  rinviene  I1  actio  c.  d. 
diretta  unicamente  al  risarcimento  del  danno.  Ed  inoltre,  nella 
chiusa,  emerge  quel  concetto  tutto  giustinianeo :  che  1'  opera  fatta 
nellj  assenza  del  socio  deve  esser  rimossa,  si  .  .  .  ad  laesionem  eius 
fecit.  Significa  questo  che  P  elemento  della  lesione  dell'  interesse 
del  socio  e  essenziale,  onde  sia  autorizzata  dalla  legge  la  rimozione 
della  opera  ?  Ma  se  cosl  e,  si  deve  certamente  riconoscere  che  il 
socio  in  assenza  dell'  altro,  o  quando  questi  non  contraddica,  pu6 
fare  sulla  medesima  tutte  le  opere  che  siano  di  vantaggio,  senza 
timore  ne  dello  ius  prohibendi?  ne  dello  ius  tollendi  e  nemmeno 
del  risarcimento  del  danno.3  La  questione  e  molto  grave,  e  sara 
esaminata  piu  oltre.  Qui  interessava  solo  accertare,  che  per  il 
danno  dato  da  uno  dei  socii  si  pu6  provocare  il  iud.  c.  div.^  senza 
chiedere  lo  scioglimento  della  cormmione,  e  che  questo  principio  e 
d'  origine  giustinianea. 

47.  (d)  refectiones  aedificiorum. 

II  condomino  secondo  il  diritto  classico  non  poteva  fare 
nemmeno  le  riparazioni  necessarie  all'  edificio  o  muro  comune  senza 
il  consenso  degli  altri.  E  non  e  dubbio  che  questa  norma  e 
schietta  applicazione  di  un  principio  fondamentale.  Ma  tosto  essa 
e  abbandonata  da  Giustiniano  : 

fr.  12  D.  x.  3,  Ulp.  71  ad  ed.  Si  aedes  communes  sint  aut 
paries  communis  et  eum  reficere  vel  demolire  \vel  in  eum  immittere 
quid  opus  sit>  communi  dividundo  iudicio  erit  agendum ,  aut  interdicto 
uti  possidetis  experimur\. 

II  significato  di  questo  passo  e  molto  piano,  e  la  interpretazione 
ferma  fin  dalla  Glossa.  Vi  si  dice  che  ciascuno  dei  condomini  di 

1  Cfr.  D.  vi.  i,  21  (due  volte);  D.  ix.  2,  4  (due  volte);  D.  xli.  i,  54, 
2-3  (due  volte) ;  D.  xlvii.  8,  i.  2  Cfr.  fr.  26  D.  viii.  2. 

3  In  questo  senso  giustamente  il  Fadda,  Studii  Brugi,  p.  144  ;  e  cosi  gli 
antichi,  cfr.  Baldo  ad  h.  1. 

G 


82  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

un  edificio  o  di  un  muro  puo  costringere  gli  altri  socii  a  riparare  o 
demolire  P  edificio,  ed  anche  a  consentire  una  immissione  nel  muro. 
La  coazione  cui  il  testo  si  riferisce  e  giudiziaria.  II  socio  ha  a  sua 
disposizione  vari  mezzi,  e  cioe  P  actio  c.  d.  o  P  int.  Uti  possidetis,  coi 
quali  puo  costringere  P  altro  a  non  impedire  la  riparazione  o 
demolizione  delP  edificio,  ovvero  qualsiasi  opera  necessaria. 

E  P  int.  Uti  possidetis  serviva  in  realta  al  possessore  solitario 
allo  scopo  indicate,  cioe  per  respingere  la  violenza  dei  terzi : 

fr.  3  §  2  D.  xliii.  17,  Ulp.  69  ad  ed.  Hoc  interdictum  sufficit  ei, 
qui  aedificare  in  suo  prohibetur :  etenim  videris  mihi  possessionis 
controversiam  facere,  qui  prohibes  me  uti  mea  possessione. 

Ma  nuova  e  P  applicazione  che  Giustiniano  voile  fare  di  questo 
mezzo  nei  rapporti  fra  i  condomini ;  perche  nel  dritto  classico 
P  interdetto  non  poteva  avere  effetto  alcuno  tra  due  possessori.  Lo 
stesso  Ulpiano  nel  fr.  3  pr.  eod.  scrive  :  neuter  nostrum  vincetur  nam 
et  tu  possides  et  ego.  E  se  vi  e  caso  in  cui  si  deve  applicare  questa 
massima,  quello  qui  considerato  della  comproprieta  e  il  piu  sicuro. 

Non  occorre  quindi  di  cercare  altre  spiegazioni  del  testo  in 
esame,  perche  certamente  Giustiniano  voile  concedere  anche 
P  interdetto  possessorio  tra  comproprietari.  E  P  actio  c.  d.  e  pur  qui 
rivolta  al  fine  di  comprimere  il  divieto  del  socio,  che  impedisce  le 
riparazioni,  o  le  nuove  opere  sulP  edificio  comune,  la  quale  funzione 
del  indicium  c.  d.  sappiamo  che  e  giustinianea. 

L'  interpolazione  del  testo  e  nota,  per  altro  ; l  ma  io  ritengo  che 
salvo  le  parole  paries  communis  et  eum  reficere  vel  demolire  tutto 
il  resto  e  opera  di  Triboniano.  E  credo  che  il  testo  dicesse  sempli- 
cemente  che  mediante  P  actio  c.  d.  il  socio  puo  ottenere  nel  caso  di 
disaccordo  la  divisione  del  muro  comune.  I  compilatori  lo  amplia- 
rono,  come  di  solito,  con  altri  esempii,  perche  in  esso  avevano 
consacrato  un  nuovo  ordinamento  che  giovava  mettere  in  evidenza. 

48.  Piu  fine  e  perci6  difficile  a  dimostrare  e  P  alterazione  intro- 
dotta  in  un  altro  passo  di  Gaio,  che  ha  un  significato  di  grande 
rilievo : 

fr.  32  D.  xxxix.  2,  Gai.  28  ad  ed.  prov.  Si  aedibus  meis  proximae 
sint  aedes  meae  et  tuae,  quaeritur,  an,  si  hae  vitium  mihi  faciant, 
cavere  mihi  debeas  pro  damno  propriarum  mearum  aedium,  scilicet 

1  Pernice,  ZSS.  xix.  p.  173  n.  3  ;  ed  ora  piu  pienamente  Berger, 
TeilungskL  p.  237. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  83 

pro  qua  parte  dorninus  existes.  et  hoc  plerisque l  placet :  sed 
movet  me,  quod  ipse  meas 2  aedes  reficere  possim  et  impensas  pro 
socio  aut  communi  dividundo  iudicio  pro  parte  consequi.  nam  et  si 
unas  aedes  communes  tecum  habui  eaeque  vitium  faciant  et  circa 
refectionem  earum  cessare  videaris,  nostri  praeceptores  negant 
cavere  te  debere  [quia  ipse  reficere  possim  recepturus  pro  parte,  quod 
impenderim  iudicio  societatis  auf\  communi  dividundo :  ideo  et 
interpositam  cautionem  minus  utilem  futuram,  quia  alia  ratione 
damnum  mihi  posset  sarciri.  [et  est  plane  nostrorum  praeceptorum 
haec  sententia,  ut  credamus  inutilem  esse  damni  infecti  stipulationem, 
quo  casu  damnum  alia  actione  sarciri  possit :  quod  et  in  superiore 
casu  intelligendum  est.~] 

II  passo  di  Gaio  a  prima  giunta  appare  perfetto  nella  struttura 
ed  illibato  nella  forma;  percio  e  bene  qui  procedere  con  ogni 
circospezione. 

Quello  che  si  enuncia  nei  punti  segnati  in  corsivo  e  sicuramente 
prodotto  di  alterazioni  giustinianee.  Di  piu  il  caso  esaminato  nel- 
1'  inizio  del  passo  fu  male  compreso  dal  Mommsen,  che,  seguendo  la 
Glossa,  propose  la  correzione  meas  in  eas,  per  significare  che  il 
socio  ha  facolta  di  riparare  liberamente  la  cosa  comune.  Questo 
senso  del  passo  e  arbitrario,  e  svisa  i  presupposti  di  fatto  e  turba  la 
limpidezza  delle  norme  giuridiche  vigenti  in  questa  materia.  Infatti 
Gaio  suppone  il  caso  di  chi  abbia  comune  un  edificio  con  altri,  e 
contiguo  allo  stesso  uno  di  sua  'esclusiva  proprieta.  L'  edificio 
comune  ha  cagionato  danno  a  quello  proprio  del  socio,  e  si  cerca 
il  mezzo  per  il  risarcimento.  La  maggioranza  degli  autori,  dice  il 
testo,  accordavano  tra  socii  la  cautio  damni  infecti ;3  Gaio  invece 
oppone :  che  nella  specie  il  proprietario  danneggiato  puo  riparare 
il  suo  edificio,  meas  aedes,  e  chiedere  poi  dal  socio  la  quota  delle 
spese  coll'  actio  c.  d.  ovvero  con  1'  actio  pro  socio*  Gaio  rafforza  la 
decisione  supponendo  un  altro  caso  piu  tipico,  in  cui  il  danno  sia 
avvenuto  nell'  unico  edificio  comune  ai  due  condomini ;  nel  qual 
caso,  se  il  socio  indugia  o  vien  meno  a  provvedere  alle  riparazioni 
necessarie  all'  edificio,  secondo  la  sentenza  dei  Sabiniani,  non  si  puo 
ricorrere  alia  cautio  damni  infecti.  Quale  la  ragione  ?  Qui  appunto 

1  Cassio  ?  cfr.  apud  Ulp.  fr.  28  D.  xxxix.  2. 

2  Eas  Mo.,  e  certamente  male. 

3  Cfr.  fr.   35,   37  D.  xxxix.   2;  D.   ix.   2,  27,  io  =  Collatio  xii.  7,  8  ;  D. 
xxxix.  2,  39,  Pomp.  21  ad  Sab. 

4  Cfr.  D.  xxxix.  2,  28,  Ulp.  81  ad  ed. :  propter  vitium  communis  parietis 
.  .  .  aedificia  suafulsit. 


84  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

si  nasconde  il  vizio  del  testo,  poiche  vi  si  dice  cosa  del  tutto  con- 
traria  alia  essenza  della  communio^  affermandosi  che  il  socio  dili- 
gente  possa,  malgrado  la  negligenza  o  il  diniego  dell'  altro,  eseguire 
le  riparazioni  ed  ottenere  poi  coll'  actio  c.  d.  la  quota  di  spese  dal 
socio.  Ma  noi  sappiamo,  e  per  fortuna  da  Gaio  stesso  e  dalla 
medesima  opera,  che  il  socio  non  pu6  senza  il  consenso  degli  altri 
riparare  il  muro  comune  : 

fr.  8  D.  8,  2,  Gaio  7  ad  ed.  prov.  Parietem  qui  naturali  ratione 
communis  est,  alterutri  vicinorum  demoliendi  eum  et  reficiendi  ius 
non  est,  quia  non  solus  dominus  est.1 

E  questa  decisione  ha  un  fondamento  certissimo  nella  essenza 
della  comunione  classica,  e  nelP  insegnamento  di  Sabino,  maestro 
ed  autore  del  nostro  Gaio.  II  quale  non  poteva  non  applicare  in 
proposito  la  celebre  massima :  Sabinus,  in  re  communi  neminem 
dominorum  iure  facer  e  quicquam  invito  altero  posse. 

La  contraddizione  quindi  e  patente.  E  come  tale  non  poteva 
sfuggire  alia  Glossa,  perche  il  testo  in  esame  di  Gaio  [fr.  32]  dice : 
ipse  reficere  possim^  cioe  in  ogni  caso,  senza  alcuna  considerazione 
del  consenso  degli  altri.  E  percio  la  Glossa  us6  qui  il  consueto 
espediente,  distinguendo :  le  riparazioni  dalle  opere  nuove ;  Glossa 
possim  ;  sed  hie  de  reficiendo,  ibi  de  novo  opere  faciendo? 

Ma  per  sostenere  siffatta  distinzione  la  Glossa  richiamava  in  con- 
fronto  il  fr.  12  D.  x.  3  ;  giusto  quello  in  cui  1*  alterazione  giustinia- 
nea  e  oggi  accertata.  Non  resta  pertanto  alcuna  via  di  scampo  per 
mantenere  il  testo  di  Gaio  come  ci  e  tramandato,  e  per  ci6  deve 
ritenersi  dimostrata  1*  origine  emblematica  del  periodo :  quia  ipse 
reficere  possim  recepturus  pro  parte  quod  impenderim.  E  T  inter- 
polazione  consente,  in  modo  ben  preciso,  che  ciascuno  dei  socii 
possa,  in  ogni  caso,  eseguire  nell'  edificio  comune  le  opere  necessarie, 
e  costringere  poi  gli  altri  a  contribuire  la  loro  quota  mediante  il 
iudicium  c.  d. 

Ed  a  chiarire  1*  interpolazione,  altri  argomenti  balzano  ora 
fuori ;  invero  il  bel  periodo  di  stile  gaiano,  uscito  dalle  mani  dei 
compilatori,  non  e  in  realta  che  una  riproduzione  di  quello  redatto  da 
Gaio  nel  caso  esposto  avanti,  e  che  si  riferiva,  come  sappiamo,  ad 
una  specie  ben  diversa  :  quod  ipse  meas  aedes  reficere  possim  et  im- 
pensas  pro  socio  aut  communi  dividundo  iudicio  pro  parte  consequi. 

1  Cfr.  D.  viii.  2,  40  :  nullo  iure  fenestras  immisisse. 

2  Vedremo  nel  c.  iv.  che  questa  opinione  e  ancora  dominante. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  85 

I  due  brani  coincidono  appieno  nella  sostanza,  e"'parzialmente 
anche  nelle  parole.     Per  i  compilatori  una  decisione  unica  per  i 
due  casi,  che  ritennero  assai  vicini  nei  presupposti  di  fatto,  esercitava 
sempre  una  grande  attrattiva.     La  semplificazione  del  diritto,  e 
particolarmente  dei  mezzi  di  attuazione,  era  obbiettivo  precipuo  che 
Giustiniano  si  propose  e  con  tutte  le  forze  si  sforz6  di  conseguire. 
Sappiamo  altresl  che  1'  abuso  dei  mezzi  gener6  equivoci,  contrad- 
dizioni  e  quindi  dibattiti  senza  fine. 

L'  interpolazione  inoltre  risulta  dalla  designazione  giustinianea 
dell'  actio  pro  socio  comunemente  indicata  :  iud.  societatis,  e  poi 
dal  confronto  con  la  motivazione  classica  che  segue  nel  testo :  ideo 
et  interpositam  cautionem  minus  utilem  futuram,  quia  alia  ratione 
damnum  mihi  posset  sarciri. 

Dove  e  facile  notare  come  Gaio  nella  seconda  ipotesi 
contemplava  unicamente  il  mezzo  per  il  risarcimento  del  damnum,  e 
non  per  il  compenso  delle  impensae.  Puo  mai  il  termine  damnum 
includere  anche  le  impensae  fatte  appunto  per  evitarlo  ?  Non  credo 
che  ci6  sia  conforme  alle  consuetudini  dei  giuristi,  che  possedevano 
un  linguaggio  tecnico  meraviglioso,  per  cui  potevano  sempre 
esprimere  i  loro  concetti  con  grande  rilievo,  precisione  e  simmetria. 

Anche  la  chiusa  del  testo  e  sospetta ;  avvegnache  essa  non 
contiene  nulla  di  nuovo,  ma  riassume  parafrasandola  la  motivazione 
che  precede :  inoltre  alia  actione  e  troppo  determinate  in  una 
formula  di  carattere  generale,  e  Gaio  poco  avanti  aveva  bene 
scritto  alia  ratione ;  e  cosl  Labeone  in  una  specie  analoga  riferita 
da  Ulpiano  in  D.  xxxix.  I,  3,  2. 

II  plane  &  ora  segnalato  come  indizio  per  scorgere  la  mano  di 
Triboniano.1     E  nel  riepilogo  del  testo  vi  e  per  altro  un  pensiero 
legislative  ben  intellegibile  ;  che  avendo  Giustiniano  ammesso  tra 
socii  il  iud.  c.  d.  per  regolamento  di  tutti  i  rapporti,  la  cautio  d. 
infecti  perdeva  qualsiasi  funzione.2 

1  Cfr.  Peters,  ZSS.  vol.  xxxii.  p.  254. 

2  E  il  disfavore  per  la  cautio  d.  inf.  si  manifesta  in  altri  passi  interpolati, 
cosl  in  D.  xxxix.  2,  39,  Pomp.  2 1  ad  Sab.  :  Inter  quos  paries  communis  est, 
aedificiorum  nomine,  quae  quisque  propria  habet  stipulari  d.  inf.   \solet.    sed 
tune  ea  cautio  necessaria  est,  cum  aut  alter  solus  aedificat  et  vitium  ex  opere 

futurum  est,  aut  alter  pretiosiora  aedificia  habet  et  plus  damni  sensurus  sit 
decidente  pariete ;  alioquin  si  aequale  periculum  est,  quantum  quis  vicino 
praestat  tantum  ab  eo  consequitur.~\ 

Distinzioni  tutte  balorde  queste,  che  provano  soltanto  la  inutilita  della 
cautio.  Per  1'  interpolazione  del  verbo  solet  vedi  piu  oltre  p.  101,  n.  i. 


86  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

Dunque,  in  conclusione,  abbiamo  qui  un  testo  fondamentale,  che 
fu  alterato  dai  compilatori,1  e  che  rende  una  precisa  testimonianza 
del  mutamento  del  diritto  in  questa  materia.  Poiche  i  Sabiniani 
reputavano  inutile  la  cautio  damni  infecti  tra  socii,  adducendo  che 
ciascuno  potesse  far  valere  le  proprie  ragioni  nelF  indicium  c.  </., 
nel  momento  della  divisione ;  Giustiniano  invece  dispone  che 
ciascuno  dei  socii  puo  riparare  la  casa  senza  attendere  il  consenso 
e  la  cooperazione  degli  altri,  e  che  mediante  F  actio  c.  d.  egli  puo 
ottenere,  in  qualsiasi  momento,  da  ciascuno  la  parte  di  spese  che 
gli  spetta.  A  togliere  ogni  dubbiezza  in  questa  materia  o  ragione 
di  equivoco,  e  bene  ricordare  che  nelle  fonti  e  frequentissimo  il  caso 
di  ripetizione  di  spese  fatte  sulla  cosa  comune  da  uno  dei  socii  nel 
giudizio  divisorio.  Ma  appunto  nei  testi  genuini  si  intende  sempre 
che  il  giudizio  e  ordinato  per  la  divisione,  ed  inoltre  che  le  spese 
furono  fatte  o  da  chi  aveva  la  amministrazione  della  cosa  comune, 
e  quindi  col  consenso  dei  socii,  ovvero  in  casi  in  cui  il  condomino 
e  ignoto ;  mai  per6  in  seguito  ad  un  dissenso  come  pu6  intendersi 
il  testo  di  Gaio  che  abbiamo  esaminato ;  in  cui  il  contrasto  tra  i 
condomini  e  per  lo  meno  possibile,  e  la  decisione  e  formulata  in  un 
modo  assoluto.  La  cosa  dunque  e  ben  diversa.  I  passi  piu 
notevoli,  nei  quali  si  accenna  alia  valutazione  di  spese  fatte  in  re 
communi  nell'  indicium  c.  </.,  sono  riportati  in  nota.2 

La  opinione  infine  di  Cuiacio,3  che  spiegava  la  decisione  gaiana 
con  1'  Oratio  divi  Marci  non  ha  bisogno  di  confutazione,  perche 
F  opera  ad  ed.  da  cui  il  fr.  deriva  fu  compiuta  avanti  di  Marco 
Aurelio  ; 4  ma  poi,  e  questo  e  decisivo,  la  coazione  dei  socii  a  pagare 
le  spese  di  riparazioni  agli  edificii  non  si  attuava  secondo  il  SC. 
mediante  il  iud.  'c.  d.>  sibbene  con  la  minaccia  della  perdita  della 
proprieta.5 

Probabilmente  Pomponio  riferiva  la  dottrina  contraria  di  Sabino,  i  compilatori, 
per  cio,  soppressero  tutta  la  trattazione. 

1  Diversamente  Berger,  Teilungsklagen,  p.  230. 

2  fr.  4  §  4  e  5  D.  x.  3  (vi  si  discute  dell'  actio,  non  dei  presupposti) ;  6  §  12 
D.  x.   3  (pena)  ;  6  pr.  D.  x.  3  (socio  ignoto) ;   1 1  pr.  D.  x.  3  (presupposto 
accordo)  ;  38  §  i   D.  xvii.  2  (accordo);  65  §  13  D.  xvii.   2  (si  discute  solo 
delP  actio);   15  §  19  D.  xxxix.  2  (come  il  precedente)  ;  46  D.  xliv.  7  (cosa 
comune  col  pupillo  amministrata  dal  socio  ?  ). 

3  Opp.  v.  iv.  p.  785  ;  cfr.  c.  i.  n.  12,  p.  47. 

4  Cfr.  Fitting,  Alter  und  Folge,  p.  54  ;  Lenel,  Pal.  i.  p.  189  n.  i. 

5  I  compilatori  non  fecero  ricorso  mai  nei  Dig.  all'   Oratio  divi  Mara, 
perche  le  riforme  da  loro  introdotte  in  questa  materia  erano  piu  profonde. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  87 

49.  Ed  ora  possiano  valutare  un  passo  di  Paolo  riferito  dai 
Visigoti  e  che  e  sorprendente : 

Paul.  Sent.  v.  10,  2  :  De  communi  pariete  utilitatis  causa  hoc 
coepit  observari,  ut  aedificet  quidem  cuius  aedificare  interest^  cogatur 
vero  socius  portionis  suae  impensas  agnoscere 

II  testo  e  veramente  strano,  e  non  ha  riscontro  alcuno  nemmeno 
nei  libri  di  Giustiniano.  Ma  e  davvero  un'  inezia,  quando  si  con- 
sideri  che  la  credibilita  di  quest'  altra  fonte  scade  ogni  giorno 
sempre  piu. 

II  senso  della  sentenza  e  piano.  Vi  si  afferma  che  il  condomino 
del  muro  comune  pu6  edificare  senza  il  consenso  del  socio,  e  che 
questi  pu6  esser  costretto  a  pagare  la  sua  quota  di  spese.  E  qui 
non  e  dubbio  che  vi  si  supponga  un  socio  dissenziente,  come  lo 
prova  la  coazione  cui  si  ricorre  per  obbligarlo  al  contributo.  Di 
piu,  la  frase  utilitatis  causa  indica  gia  che  vi  si  enuncia  una 
nor  ma  eccezionale ;  e  1'  altra  cuius  aedificare  interest  presuppone 
e  designa  un  interesse  particolare  o  piu  immediate  di  uno  dei  socii. 
Ma  e  cio  possibile?  Come  poteva  affermarlo  un  giureconsulto, 
quando  tutti  i  testi  classici  negano  ad  uno  dei  socii  anche  la 
semplice  facolta  di  reficere  il  muro  comune,  anche  nell'  interesse 
di  tutti  ?  II  nostro  testo  invece  ammette  pure  la  aedificatio.  Ma 
1'  origine  spuria  del  testo  si  mostra  per  vari  indizi :  non  e  indicata 
P  azione  con  la  quale  il  socio  pu6  costringere  1'  altro  a  contribuire 
per  P  opera  fatta ;  manca  il  soggetto  di  aedificet^  e  la  frase  coepit 
observari  e  indeterminata  ed  insolita  ai  giuristi.  Tutto  ci6  induce 
a  ritenere  che  i  compilatori  visigoti  ebbero  a  mutare  profondamente 
il  passo  di  Paolo,  riferendosi  alia  pratica  del  loro  tempo.  Certo 
ad  una  pratica  male  appresa  ;  perche  in  nessun  diritto  e  tanto  meno 
nella  vita  pratica,  puo  esser  mai  consentito  ad  uno  dei  socii,  che  ha 
un  interesse  esclusivo  (sic)  ad  innalzare  il  muro  comune,  che  egli 
possa  costringere  il  male  avventurato  condomino  a  pagare  una 
parte  della  spesa.  La  norma  di  diritto  in  tali  casi  e  ben  diversa, 
come  appare  dalle  legislazioni  moderne.1 

Ed  e  rimarchevole  che  la  interpretatio  visigota  riconduce  quella 

Ma  i  Compilatori  del  Codice  accolsero  un  rescritto  di  Filippo  :  c.  4  Cod.  viii,  10, 
che  vi  si  riferiva,  e,  come  sembra,  lo  ampliarono  pure  ;  infatti  il  brano  :  etenim 
.  .  .  constiterit  e  fortemente  sospetto  \aedificaveris  ?]  e  certamente  spuria  la 
frase  mndicare  vel. 

1   Cod.  civ.  italianO)  art.  555. 


88  5.  Riccobono  [iv 

sentenza  cosi  sbalestrata  alia  sua  giusta  misura,  e  cosl  spiega  : 
sed  si  ab  uno  ex  his  communis  paries  propter  metum  ruinae  fuerit 
reparatus  expensas  fabricae  socius  illi  pro  portione  sua  praestare 
cogendus  est. 

Cosl  per  lo  meno  si  ritorna  all'  ipotesi  delle  riparazioni.  E  la 
interpretatio  inoltre  premette  al  periodo  ora  riferito  una  nozione 
esatta  della  cautio  damni  infecti,  che  sicuramente  e  tratta  da  buone 
fonti. 

50.  E  cosl  tutta  questa  materia  del  paries  communis,  giustamente 
malfamata  in  ogni  tempo  per  le  sfrontate  contraddizioni  con  cui  fu 
presentata  nei  Digestif  riprende  la  sua  figura  semplice  e  dignitosa ; 
separando  precisamente  le  norme  del  diritto  classico  dal  nuovo 
assetto  che  Giustiniano  le  diede.     Onde  non  solo  essa  ebbe  un'  im- 
pronta  che  'puo  servire  di  modello  al  diritto  moderno'  come  gia 
osserv6  il  Brugi,2  ma  costituisce  nelle  sue  linee  essenziali  il  diritto 
moderno. 

51.  (e)  Applicazioni  varie. 

In  questo  gruppo  ho  raccolti  casi  varii  che  dimostrano  1'  applica- 
zione  costante  del  c.  d.  iudicium  per  definire  subito,  in  tutte  le 
evenienze,  i  rapporti  obbligatori  sorti  per  causa  della  res  communis. 

fr.  15  D.  x.  3,  Paul.  5  ad  Plaut.  Si  socius  servi  communis 
nomine  conventus  et  condemnatus  sit  \aget  c.  d.  et  antequam  praestet\ ; 
nam  et  si  noxali  iudicio  cum  uno  actum  sit  \statim  aget  cum  socio  ut 
ei  pars  trader etur,  cautionibus  interpositis,  ut,  si  non  dederit,  reddat\. 

Che  il  c.  d.  serve  qui  al  socio  per  ottenere  immediatamente  la 
prestazione  dalF  altro  e  detto  nel  testo :  statim  .  .  .  ut ;  percic-  il 
testo  e  giustinianeo ;  come  inoltre  si  dimostra  dalla  forma  aget,  che 
nel  secondo  periodo  manca  poi  del  soggetto,  invece  di  agere  potest. 
Ed  invero  il  verbo  agere  al  futuro  o  al  congiuntivo  concessivo  agas 
e  indizio  certo  d'  interpolazioni.8 

1  Cfr.  Zacharia,  Zeitschr.  f.  g.  RW.  vol.  xii.  p.  271  in  nota,  che  la  designa 
come  una  delle  materie  piu  aggrovigliate  ;  Berger,  Teilungskl.  p.  238  ed  ivi  cit. 

2  Rivista  ital.  per  le  s.  gtur.  vol.  iv.  p.  405. 

3  Cotali  forme  sono  soltanto  giustificate  nelle  Epistulae  o  nei  brani  da  esse 
derivati,  cosi  p.  es.  in  D.  xii.  5,  15  ;  d'  ordinario  hanno  impronta  legislativa  in 
quanto  esprimono  la  facolta  concessa  dal  legislature,  e  non  quella  che  viene 
all'  individuo  dal  proprio  diritto.      Esempii  :  30  §  I  D.  xxxiii.  2  (Riccobono,  in 
BIDR.  vi.  p.    139);    fr.  20  D.  xliii.   16  (forse  un  sunto  dell'  originale)  ;    fr. 
60  §  2  D.  xix.  2  (cfr.  Gradenwitz,  Interpol.  p.  29  ;  ma  1'  interpolazione  s'  inizia 
con  la  parola  agis  ;  fr.  1 8  §  2  D.  x.  3  (cfr.  piu  oltre  in  questo  lavoro) ;  fr.  2 1  D. 
xvii.  2  (il  brano  e  indicate  da  Eisele  e  Kriiger  come  glossa;  certamente  male). 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  89 

La  trattazione  di  questa  materia  nelle  opere  dei  giuristi  era  ben 
piu  complicata,  come  e  ancora  visibile  dal  fr.  8  D.  ix.  4  di  Ulpiano, 
che  peraltro  e  fortemente  interpolate.  Ma  I1  argomento  potra  essere 
esaminato  nel  capitolo  relativo  alle  azioni  tra  condomini.1 

52.  fr.  23  D.  x.  3,  Ulp.  32  ad  Ed.      Si  convenerit  inter  te  et 
socium  tuum,  ut  alternis  annis  fructum  perciperetis,  et  non  patiatur 
te  socius  tui  anni  fructum  percipere,  videndum,  utrum  ex  conducto 
sit  actio  an  vero  communi  dividundo.     Eadem  quaestio  est  et  si 
socius,  qui  convenerat  ut  alternis  annis  frueretur,  pecus  immisit  et 
effecit,  ut  futuri  anni  fructus  quos  socius  percipere  oportuit,  corrum- 
perentur.      [et  puto  magis  communi  dividundo  iudicium  quam   ex 
conducto  locum  habere  (quae  enim  locatio  est  cum  merces  non  inter- 
cesserit  ?)  aut  certe  actionem  incerti  civilem  reddendamJ] 

La  frase  locum  habere  si  riporta  al  iud.  c.  d.  nella  sua  nuova 
funzione  regolatrice  della  comunione,  ed  e  perci6  giustinianea. 
La  soluzione  e  sostanzialmente  di  Ulpiano  ;  il  puto  magis  avverte 
per6  che  i  compilatori  hanno  eliminato  la  trattazione  piu  ampia 
del  giurista,  condensandone  il  risultato  e  aggiungendovi  la  famosa 
civilis  incerti  a.2 

fr.  17  D.  xvii.  2,  Paul.  6  ad  Sab.  Sed  et  si  socius  alienaverit 
contra  pactionem  accipit  committit  et  tenetur  \societatis  aut  communi 
dividundo\  iudicio.3 

Paolo  aveva  scritto  :  iudicio  pro  socio. 

fr.  19  §  2  D.  xv.  I  ;  cfr.  supra,  p.  79,  n.  2. 

fr.  4  D.  xxxiii.  3.  lavol.  9  rp.  \itaque  de  ea  re  arbiter  com- 
muni div.  sumendus  est^~\ 

53.  E  la  riforma  attuata  con  perfetta  vigilanza  si  propaga  quasi 
natural  men  te  al  iudicium  familiae  erciscundae,  in  cui  fu  applicata 
pure  per  munire  di  coazione  rapporti  che  nel  diritto  classico  non 
avevano   sanzione    giuridica.      Un    esempio    insigne    si    rinviene 
appunto  nel 

fr.  1 8  §  2  D.  x.  2,  Ulp.  19  ad  ed.  Idem  quaerit,  si  quis  testa- 
mento  caverit,  ut  servus  exportandus  veneat,  officio  familiae  ere. 
iudicis  contineri,  ut  voluntas  defuncti  non  intercidat.  sed  et  cum 

1  Diversamente  Berger,  Teilungskl.  p.  227. 

2  Cfr.  Pernice,  ZSS.  xix.  p.  174  nota. 

8  La  denominazione  iudicium  societatis  deve  considerarsi  sospetta. 

4  Pernice,  ZSS.  xix.  p.  174,  considera  qui  il  iud.  come  «  ein  letztes  Aus- 
kunftsmittel  »  e  cosl  Berger,  Teilungskl.  p.  239.  Ma  Giavoleno  discuteva 
solo  il  diritto  o  meno  del  socio  di  fare  immissioni  nel  paries  communis,  e 
percio  la  quistione  della  divisione  non  gli  si  poteva  presentare  alia  mente. 


90  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

monumentum  iussit  testator  fieri,  familiae  erciscundae  [agent,  ut 
fiat],  idem  tamen  temptat,  quia  heredum  interest,  quos  ius 
monumenti  sequitur,  praescriptis  verbis  posse  eos  experiri,  ut 
monumentum  fiat. 

Nel  §  che  precede  Pomponio  negava,  ed  Ulpiano  plaudiva 
vivamente  (rectissime],  che  si  potessero  dedurre  nel  indicium  f. 
ere.  indagini  circa  la  morte  del  testatore  ecc.,  poiche :  haec  ad 
divisionem  rerum  hereditariarum  non  pertinere.  L'  introduzione 
del  §  sopra  trascritto :  idem  quaerit  e  dell'  amanuense  (F1),  ma  nel 
ms.  si  legge  pure  1'  emendazione  del  correttore  (F2) :  idemque  erit,  che 
rappresentava  la  dizione  originaria  del  testo.  Infatti  i  casi  che 
seguono  dovevano  avere  entrambi 1  la  stessa  soluzione  negativa, 
approvata  avanti  da  Ulpiano.  L'  interpolazione  e  evidentissima 
nella  frase  :  agent,  ut  fiat\  di  cui  invano  si  cercherebbe  il  soggetto. 
Anche  il  seguito  e  mal  connesso  col  precedente,  perche  i  Com- 
pilatori,  nel  mutare  e  condensare  la  trattazione,  vi  eliminarono  i 
nuovi  presupposti  considerati  dal  giurista  (cfr.  quia  heredum  interest, 
quos  ius  m.  sequitur]. 

L'  alterazione  del  testo  e  dunque,  anche  in  questo  luogo,  di 
grande  rilievo ;  perche  il  iud.  f.  ere.  e  adoperato  come  il  c.  div. 
(26  D.  viii.  2)  per  costringere  il  coerede  a  fare  qualche  cosa,  e  quindi 
per  regolare  singoli  rapporti  dei  coeredi.2 

54.  II  motivo  per  altro  dell'  interpolazione  e  dichiarato,  per  il 
caso  concernente  il  monumento,  dal  legislatore  in  altro  luogo  ed  in 
una  formula  generale,  che  si  legge  a  guisa  di  riepilogo  nel  testo 
che  segue : 

fr.  7  D.  xxxiii.  i,  Pomp.  8  ad  Q.M.  —  Pomponius.  In  testamentis 
quaedam  scribuntur,  quae  ad  auctoritatem  dumtaxat  scribentis 
referuntur  nee  obligationem  pariunt.  haec  tamen  talia  sunt.  si  te 
heredem  solum  instituam  et  scribam,  uti  monumentum  mihi  certa 
pecunia  facias  :  \nullam  enim  obligationem  ea  scriptura  recipit,  sed\ 
ad  auctoritatem  meam  conservandam  poteris,  si  velis,  facere  \aliter 
atque'] 3  si  coherede  tibi  dato  idem  scripsero :  nam  sive  te  solum 

1  II  primo  esempio  relative  all'  ordine  dato  dal  testatore  :    vendita  del 
servo  con  la  condizione  che  sia  esportato,  e  contemplato  dalla  c.  5  Cod.  iii.  36 
di  Aless.  Severe,  e  la  decisione  e  conforme  a  quella  che   si  legge  ora  nei 
Digesti.       Ma  la   struttura  del  rescritto  e  quanto  mai   strana,  perche  nella 
decisione,  contenuta  nella  seconda  parte  :  proinde  .  .   .  sequetur  spunta  una 
folia  di  nuovi  presupposti  del  tutto  inaspettati.     Per  cio  dovette  pure  essere 
modificata  1'  introduzione :  in  ipsius  .  .   .  mutare. 

2  V.  in  senso  contrario :  Ulp.  in  D.  x.  2,  2  pr.  3  item.  Pomp. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  91 

damnavero,  uti  monumentum  facias,  coheres  tuus1  agere  tecum 
poterit  familiae  herciscundae,  uti  facias,  quoniam 2  interest  illius : 
qui  etiam  si  utrique  iussi  estis  hoc  facere,  invicem  actionem3  habebitis. 
ad  auctoritatem  scribentis  hoc  quoque  pertinet,  cum  quis  iussit  in 
municipio  imagines  poni :  '  nam  si  non  honoris  municipii  gratia  id 
fecisset,  sed  sua,  actio  eo  nomine  nulli  competit'  itaque  haec 
Quinti  Mucii  scriptura  :  *  liberi  mei  ibi  sunto,  ubi  eos  mater  sua  esse 
volet'  nullam  obligationem  parit,  sed  ad  auctoritatem  defuncti 
conservandam  id  pertinebit,  ut  ubi  iusserit  ibi  sint.  nee  tamen 
semper  voluntas  eius  aut  iussum  conservari  debet,  veluti  si  praetor 
doctus  sit  non  expedire  pupillum  eo  morari  ubi  pater  iusserit 
'  propter  vitium,  quod  pater  forte  ignoravit  in  eis  personis  esse,  apud 
quas  morari  iussit.'  si  autem  pro  cibariis  eorum  in  annos  singulos 
aurei  decem  relicti  sint,  sive  hoc  sermone  significantur,  apud  quos 
morari  mater  pupillos  voluerit,  sive  ita  acceperinus  hunc  sermonem, 
ut  ipsis  filiis  id  legatum  debeatur,  utile  erit :  et  magis  enim  est,  ut 
providentia  filiorum  suorum  hoc  fecisse  videatur.  [et  in  omnibus 
ubi  auctoritas  sola  testatoris  est,  neque  omnimodo  spernenda  neque 
omnimodo  observanda  est.  sed  interventu  iudicis  haec  omnia  debent> 
si  non  ad  turpem  causam  feruntur,  ad  effectum  perduci^\ 

La  trattazione  di  Pomponio  riprende  il  suo  carattere  perspicuo 
e  quindi  la  sua  forza  riponendo  a  posto,  come  ho  fatto  nelle  note, 
le  negazioni  eliminate  dai  Compilatori,  per  ridurre  la  decisione  di 
alcuni  casi  nel  senso  affermativo.  E  malgrado  le  inversioni 
giustinianee  il  ragionamento  di'  Pomponio  e  ancora  trasparente. 
Vi  hanno  disposizioni  del  testatore,  egli  dice,  che  non  sono 
coercibili,  ma  riescono  tuttavia  efficaci,  perche  la  loro  effettuazione 
e  assicurata  dalla  sua  autorita  morale,  come  avviene  nel  caso  che 
egli  imponga  all'  erede  di  fargli  un  monumento ;  ne  il  valore 
giuridico  dell'  ordine  si  muta  se  gli  eredi  sono  due  o  piu ;  perche 
in  ogni  caso  per  la  disposizione  concernente  la  statua  o  il  monu- 
mento, se  mira  ad  onorare  la  memoria  del  testatore  :  actio  eo  nomine 
nulli  competit. 

E  quel  che  Pomponio  insegnava  e  accertato  per  ogni  rispetto. 
Sappiamo  che  i  Romani  custodivano  religiosamente  la  volonta 
espressa  del  testatore,  anche  se  non  munita  di  efficacia  giuridica ; 
gli  scrittori,  a  cominciare  da  Cicerone,  attestano  con  orgoglio  ed 
esaltano  questo  tratto  del  costume  romano.  Cosi  Plinio 4  scrive  ad 
un  coerede :  Confido  accessurum  te  sententiae  meae^  cum  religiosissime 
soleas  custodire  defunctorum  voluntatem,  quam  bonis  heredibus 

1  non.  Pomp.          2  non.  Pomp.  8  non.  Pomp.          4  Epist.  iv.  10. 


92  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

intellexisse  pro  iure  est.  Neque  enim  minus  apud  nos  honestas  quam 
apud  alios  necessitas  valet.  Nella  specie  contemplata  da  Plinio  si 
trattava  di  una  manomissione  e  d'  un  legato  allo  stesso  servo 
inefficaci. 

Ma  sovratutto  poi  si  deve  considerare  che  il  coerede  non  pu6 
avere  un'  azione  contro  1'  altro  se  non  ha  un  interesse ;  e  nel  caso 
della  statua  in  memoria  del  testatore  la  posizione  dei  coeredi  e  pari, 
nel  senso  che  ne  I1  uno  ne  1'  altro  vi  ha  interesse.  Onde  a  conseguire 
tali  fini  il  legato  con  un  modus  era  di  consueto  ordinato  in  favore 
d'  un  terzo  ovvero  d'  un  Ente,  ed  in  particolare  di  Municipt.1 

La  riforma  di  Giustiniano,  pertanto,  in  questa  materia  mirava 
a  dar  forza  giuridica,  per  lo  meno  nel  caso  che  vi  fossero  piu  eredi, 
alle  disposizioni  testamentarie  che  avevano  lo  scopo  di  onorare 
la  memoria  del  defunto ;  ed  allora  il  legislatore  attribul  un'  azione 
all'  uno  degli  eredi  contro  1'  altro.  Nella  chiusa  del  testo  anzi  la 
formulazione  e  piu  larga ;  perche  vi  si  dice  che  in  tutti  i  casi,  la 
volonta  del  testatore  che  sia  onesta  e  meritevole  di  protezione,  deve 
essere  osservata  merce  1'  opera  del  giudice.  Ma  qui  evidentemente 
intervenne  Triboniano,2  che  con  due  tratti  di  penna  condense  nella 
chiusa  tutto  il  pensiero  legislative. 

55.  Ed  un  altra  applicazione  immediata  e  cospicua  della  stessa 
norma  si  rinviene  appunto  in  sede  materiae,  cioe  nel 

fr.  44  §  8  D.  x.  2,  Paul.  6  ad  Sab.  Si  duo  coheredes  damnati 
sint  statuam  ponere  et  altero  cessante  alter  earn  fecerit,  non 
\esse  iniquum\  lulianus  ait  familiae  erciscundae  iudicium  \dare\  ut 
pars  impendiorum  boni  viri  arbitratu  praestetur. 

II  termine  damnati  era  pure  di  frequente  usato  nei  testamenti 
con  riferimento  a  disposizioni  incoercibili ; 8  come  nella  specie  in 
esame.  Ma  la  decisione  affermativa  ora  non  sorprende  ;  e  si  rivela 
come  opera  di  Giustiniano  per  il  nudo  richiamo  all'  equita  ;  laddove, 
come  sappiamo,  1'  elemento  decisive  era  1'  esistenza  dell'  interesse 
giuridico  di  uno  degli  eredi  a  fare,  che  solo  poteva  generare 
1'  azione.4  E  1'  alterazione  del  testo  si  manifesta  poi  nella  forma 

1  Cfr.  D,  xxxiii.  i,  21,  3,  Scaev.  22  digest.  ;   Testamentum  Postumii  luliani 
in  Bruns-Gradenwitz,  Forties,  n.  121  p.  316. 

2  Cfr.  Pernice,  Labeo,  iii.  p.  39  ed  ivi  cit.      Di   Marzo  :  Libri  di  Pomp,  ad 
Q.  M.  p.  67. 

3  Pernice,  /.  c.  p.  32. 

4  Cfr.  D.  x.  2,  1 8,  2 — quiaheredum  interest,  quos  ius  monumenti  sequitur. 
Cfr.  avanti  al  n.  53. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  93 

impersonale  della  seconda  parte  (praestetur)  in  disaccordo  con  i 
presupposti  riferiti ;  ed  inoltre  nella  frase :  iud.  dare,  che  mette  in 
evidenza  la  nuova  funzione  dei  iud.  divisoria.  Forse  il  testo  diceva : l 
non  posse  eum  lulianus  ait,  familiae  erciscundae  iudicio  consequi,  ut 
pars  impendiorum  sibi  praestetur? 

Ma  qui  bisogna  interrompere  la  revisione  critica  dei  testi  che 
provano  il  nuovo  ufficio  delle  azioni  divisorie  nel  diritto  di  Giu- 
stiniano,  perche  gli  esempii  recati  dimostrano  a  dovizia  come  i 
compilatori,  con  sovrapposizioni  pazienti  e  continue,  tendevano  a 
coprire  i  tratti  che  ricordavano  la  funzione  determinata  dei  indicia 
divisoria^  e  che  invece  seppero  rivolgere  agli  scopi  piu  varJ,  per 
disciplinare  la  vita  dell'  istituto  della  comunione. 


III.   LA  UTILITA  SOCIALE 

56.  Azioni,  interdetti  e  mezzi  vari,  per  lo  piu  innominati  ed  a  volte 
maldestri  ed  anche  contradditori,  accordati  da  Giustiniano  ai  condo- 
mini  sono  tutti  convergenti  verso  un  segno  ben  determinate.  E  lo 
scopo,  come  ho  avuto  occasione  di  rilevare  piu  fiate,  era  quello  di  re- 
golare  la  vita  della  comunione,  disciplinarla,  onde  potesse  durare  ed 
esplicarsi  in  perfetta  pace,  con  la  cooperazione  di  tutti  per  il  vantaggio 
comune.  Per  conseguire  un  tale  effetto  il  legislatore  doveva  in 
primo  luogo  annullare  il  principio  della  indipendenza  assoluta  dei 
singoli  condomini,  che  costituiva  il  punto  centrale  della  comunione 
classica.  E  quel  principio  fu  annullato.  Infatti  ciascuno  socio  ha 
ora  potere  e  mezzi  di  costringere  gli  altri  ad  eseguire  riparazioni  sulla 
cosa  comune,  a  consentire  una  particolare  opera  o  qualsiasi  altra 
cosa ;  e  viceversa  ciascuno  pu6  impedire  il  socio  dal  fare  un'  opera 
o  immissioni  ecc.,  sempre  mediante  prohibitio  giudiziaria.  Tutto 
ci6  e  stato  dimostrato  nelle  pagine  che  precedono. 

Ora,  per  ci6,  bisogna  vedere  il  risultato  del  nuovo  ordinamento 
stabilito  da  Giustiniano.  Dacche  e  evidente  che  tutte  quelle  azioni 
concesse  ai  condomini  presuppongono  una  serie  di  diritti  e  facolta, 
che  ciascuno  di  essi  ha  ormai  sulla  cosa  comune,  e  che  pu6  eserci- 

1  II  modello  per  la  restituzione  del  passo  si  ha  in  D.  x.  3,  4,  §  4  :  scribit 
lulianus  .  .  .  sumptum  istum  c.  d.  itidido  conseqiti  me  non  posse. 

2  Cfr.  c.  5,  Cod.  iii.  44  dell'  a.  224,  dove  appunto  la  incoercibilita  di  tale 
disposizione  anche  nel  testamento  militare  e  presupposta.     E  per  ci6  erronea- 
mente  il   Pernice,  ZSS.  xix.  p.  173  n.  4,  attribuisce  quelle  decision!  ad  un 
progresso  della  giurisprudenza,  per  opera  di  Giuliano. 


94  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

tare  mediante  opere  e  disposizioni,  anche  senza  il  consenso  degli 
altri.  Nel  caso  di  opposizione  ha  mezzi  coercitivi  legali.  Ed  allora 
e  certo,  in  primo  luogo,  che  se  ciascuno  dei  condomini  ha  ora,  posi- 
tivamente,  facolta  di  agire  sulla  cosa  in  contraddizione  agli  altri : 
La  regola  di  Sabino  fu  sostanzialmente  abolita ;  perche  essa 
negava  che  il  socio  quicquam  facere  posse  invito  altero. 

Ma  fino  a  qual  punto  fu  quel  principio  messo  da  parte  ?  E  nella 
ricerca  della  risposta  a  questa  domanda,  si  deve  pure  necessaria- 
mente  porre  in  evidenza  il  principio  che  fu  collocate  al  posto  di 
quello  classico ;  perche  senza  un  nuovo  regolamento,  senza  una 
vera  organizzazione  dei  compartecipi,  le  facolta  dei  singoli  avrebbero 
condotto  ora  ad  un'  anarchia  ancora  piu  grave  di  quella  che  avevano 
sperimentato  i  giureconsulti  classici.  Tutto  questo  sara  messo  in 
luce  nella  trattazione  che  segue. 

57.  Cominciamo  dall'  osservare  il 

fr.  6  §  12  D.  x.  3,  Ulp.  19  ad  ed.  Urseius  ait,  cum  in  communi 
aedificio  vicinus  nuntiavit,  ne  quid  operis  fieret,  si  unus  ex  sociis  ex 
hac  causa  damnatus  fuisset,  posse  earn  poenam  a  socio  pro  parte 
servare.  lulianus  autem  recte  notat  ita  demum  hoc  verum  esse,  si 
[interfuit  aedium  hoc  fieri]. 

II  testo  e  piano.  Vi  si  dice  che  uno  dei  condomini  che  aveva 
fatta  una  nuova  opera  nell'  edificio  comune  fu  condannato  in  seguito 
alia  denuncia  del  vicino.  Debbono  i  socii  contribuire  al  pagamento 
della  pena?  Urseio  lo  affermava.  Giuliano  appose  al  response 
una  delle  solite  note  esplicative,  che  pero  fu  modificata  dai  compi- 
latori.  La  frase  finale  si  interfuit  aedium  hoc  fieri  e  sicuramente 
interpolata ;  lo  si  desume  dalla  personificazione  delle  aedes,  che  e 
di  stile  bizantino,  in  luogo  della  utilitas  rei\  e  poi,  perche  aedium 
e  non  aedificiorum,  cioe  il  termine  piu  generico  che  era  nell'  ipotesi 
proposta?  Di  piu  hoc  si  riferisce  a  damnatus  fuisset^  mentre 
evidentemente  1'  interpolatore  voleva  significare  hoc  =  opus  fieri. 

E  per  altro  la  nota  di  Giuliano  si  ricostruisce  sicuramente  col 
sussidio  di  un  passo  di  Papiniano  che  tratta  lo  stesso  caso : 

fr.  1 8  D.  xxxix.  I,  Pap.  3  quaest.  Aedibus  communibus,  si  ob 
opus  novum  nuntiatio  uni  fiat,  si  quidem  ex  voluntate  omnium  opus 
fiat,  omnes  nuntiatio  tenebit,  si  vero  quidem  ignorent,  in  solidum 
obligabitur,  qui  contra  edictum  praetoris  fecerit. 

La  decisione  qui  e  correttissima  e  proporzionata  in  ogni  sua 
parte  ai  principii  fondamentali  della  comunione. 


1VJ  Communio  e  Comproprieta  95 

E  perci6  la  nota  di  Giuliano  doveva  dire : 

lulianus  autem  recte  notat :  ita  demum  hoc  verum  esse  si  ex 
voluntate  omnium  opus  fieret,  quod  si  quidam  ignorent  in  solidum 
obligabitur  qui  contra  edictum  praetoris  fecerit. 

La  ragione,  che  indusse  i  compilatori  a  sopprimere  una  dis- 
tinzione  cosi  equilibrata,  non  puo  essere  ora  occulta ;  quel  che 
dispiacque  appunto  fu  il  consenso  omnium,  come  fondamento  e 
norma  dei  rapporti  tra  condomini ;  cui  si  sostitul  un  elemento 
obbiettivo,  il  vantaggio  della  cosa  comune,  che  pertanto  e  in- 
dipendente  dall'  arbitrio  dei  singoli  e  dal  concorso  della  volonta  di 
tutti. 

Lo  spostamento  dei  concetti  e  qui  essenziale,  dunque.  E 
percio  1'  interpolazione  in  questo  punto  ha  investito  il  principio 
centrale  dell'  istituto  del  condominio. 

58.  Ed  ora  si  scorge  tutto  il  significato  di  una  frase  adoperata 
da  Giustiniano  dove  egli   ammette  tra  condomini   1'  efficacia  del 
patto  ne  intra  certum  tempus  dividatur.     Perche  il  legislatore  pone 
ivi   in   risalto   questo   nuovo    elemento   del   vantaggio    collettivo, 
dichiarando  valido  il  patto  :  quod  etiam  ipsius  rei  qualitati  prodest1, 
cosl  non  la  volonta  unanime  dei  socii  ne  determina  la  validita,  ma 
bensl  T  utilita  per  se  stessa,  il  vantaggio  della  cosa  comune. 

59.  Or,  se  un  siffatto  principio,  che  aveva  in  se  la  potenza  di 
travolgere  d'  un  tratto  tutta  la  struttura  della  communio,  era  in 
realta  nella  mente  del  legislatore,  egli  doveva  di  necessita  metterlo 
in   evidenza    immediata    la   dove   i    giureconsulti   avean    posti   i 
fondamenti  incrollabili  del  nostro  istituto,  e  doveva  precisamente 
sovrapporlo   all'  altro  di   Sabino,  che   esigeva   essenzialmente,  in 
ogni  momento  e  per  qualsiasi  disposizione  materiale  della  cosa, 
il  concorso  di  tutti  i  socii.     E  cio  era  imprescindibile,  perche  la 
comunione  classica,  come  sappiamo,  era  tutta  improntata  come  in 
un  conio  nella  formulazione  di  Sabino,  in  cui  lo  schema  di  mirabile 
perfezione,  dai  tratti  vigorosi  ed  indelebili,  si  mostrava  tutto.     Per 
ci6  la  regola  di  Sabino  precludeva  la  via  a  qualsiasi  riforma  o 
deviazione   nella   materia   della   comunione.     Anche    la   semplice 
vicinanza  era  fatale.     E  Giustiniano  quindi  senti  la  necessita  di 
stremarla  la  sul  posto,  con  sovrapposizioni  ponderose,  che  dovevano 
opprimerla. 

i  D.  x.  3,  14,  2. 


96  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

I  passi  che  riportavano  la  massima  di  Sabino  erano  due,  e 
furono  entrambi,  come  sappiamo,  transfigurati. 

60.  Al  fr.  di  Paolo  fu  aggiunto  il  periodo  che  segue  : 

26  D.  viii.  2 — sed  per  communi  dividundo  actionem  consequitur 
socius,  quo  minus  opus  fiat  aut  ut  id  opus  quod  fecit  tollat,  si  modo 
toti  societati  prodest  opus  tolli. 

Quest'  interpolazione  si  determina  soltanto  ora  nei  suoi  par- 
ticolari,  ed  illumina  1*  istituto  giustinianeo.  Essa  rende  tutta  la 
nuova  struttura  del  la  comproprieta.  Lo  ius  prohibendi  vi  e 
rinnovellato  ;  e  T  actio  c.  d.  serve  ormai  a  regolare  tutti  gl'  interessi 
dei  socii.  Mediante  essa  si  impedisce  T  opera  che  uno  voglia 
eseguire  sulla  cosa ;  ovvero  quando  1'  opera  sia  compiuta  se  ne 
ottiene  la  rimozione.  La  quale  non  deve  aver  luogo  in  ogni  caso, 
bensl  quando  giovi  alia  comunione,  o  meglio  alia  societa,  come 
Giustiniano  vuole  si  dica  :  si  modo  toti  societati  prodest  opus  tolli. 

La  volonta  dei  singoli  socii  anche  qui  e  interclusa,  di  fronte  al 
vantaggio  della  collettivita.  Ne  occorre  avvertire  che  tra  le  due 
cose  non  v'  e  coincidenza.  La  voluntas  omnium  da  una  parte  ed 
il  prodesse  societati  dall'  altra  sono  quantita  eterogenee.  Anzi 
nella  formula  sovrapposta  da  Giustiniano,  e  prospettato  un  caso 
in  cui  si  giunge  alia  distruzione  dell'  opera  eseguita  da  uno  dei 
socii,  perche  torna  di  vantaggio  alia  collettivita.  E  quindi  il 
proposito  di  uno  e  frustrate.  Naturalmente ;  perche  il  criterio 
della  utilitas  rei  e  obbiettivo,  quello  della  voluntas  e  soggettivo ; 
e  per  ci6  1'  uno  e  indipendente  dall'  altro. 

E  cosl  siamo  ritornati  allo  stesso  principio  che  ci  si  rive!6 
avanti,  in  altri  testi,  quasi  di  soppiatto.  Vale  a  dire,  mentre  nel 
diritto  classico  solo  la  volonta  di  tutti  i  socii  ha  efficacia  rispetto  al 
facere  sulla  cosa  comune,  e  la  volonta  di  un  solo,  per  conseguenza, 
puo  impedire  qualsiasi  atto  od  opera  sulla  medesima,  in  forza  della 
prohibitio ;  al  contrario,  nella  compilazione,  alia  volonta  dei  singoli 
si  surroga  la  utilitas  rei,  la  quale  ora  determina  e  regola  i  poteri 
dei  socii  sulla  cosa.  Lo  ius  prohibendi  e  non  solo  trasformato, 
ma  in  molti  casi  pure  escluso.  Fino  a  qual  punto  ? 

61.  La  risposta  la  ricaviamo  dal  celebre  testo  di  Papiniano,  la 
dove  egli  enunciava  precisamente  la  massima  di  Sabino,  ed  in  cui 
la  violenza  usata  da  Giustiniano  all'  antica  dottrina  si  manifesta 
nella  maniera  piu  aperta. 


iv]  Communio  e  Coniproprieta  97 

II  testo  ben  noto  continua  cosl : 

fr.  28  D.  x.  3  .  .  .  sed  etsi  in  communi  prohiberi  socius  a  socio 
ne  quid  faciat  potest,  ut  tamen  factum  opus  tollat,  cogi  non  potest, 
sz,  cum  prohibere  poterat,  hoc  praetermisit :  et  ideo  per  communi 
^dividundo  actionem  damnum  sarciri  poterit^  sin  autem  facienti 
consensit,  nee  pro  damno  habet  actionem.  quod  si  quid  absente  socio 
ad  laesionem  eius  fecit ',  tune  etiam  toller  e  cogitur. 

Dunque,  lo  ius  prohibendi  c'  e  ancora,  ma  solo  per  impedire 
P  inizio  dell'  opera.  Che  se  questa  fu  compiuta  senza  proibizione  di 
alcuno,  allora,  chi  omise  di  intervenire  a  tempo  non  pu6  altro 
pretendere  che  il  risarcimento  del  danno,  mediante  I1  actio  c.  d. 
E  se  poi,  per  un  motivo  giustificato,  egli  non  pote  interporre  divieto 
in  tempo  opportune,  allora  P  opera  dev1  essere  rimossa  da  chi  la 
esegul,  solo  quando  risulti  che  ridonda  a  danno  del  socio ;  anzi,  il 
testo  dice :  quando  risulti  che  fu  fatta  a  danno  del  socio :«".., 
ad  laesionem  eius  fecit. 

Ed  anche  qui  P  aggiunta,  con  le  molteplici  distinzioni,  rivela 
in  tutta  la  sua  comprensione  il  nuovo  principio  regolatore  della 
communio. 

Lasciamo  da  parte  la  questione  che  e  secondaria,  se  nella  frase 
ad  laesionem  eius  fecit  non  si  rifletta  pure  un  raggio  della  nota 
dottrina  giustinianea  del  divieto  di  atti  emulativi,  ma  qui  preme 
sopratutto  trarre  da  quest*  ultimo  inciso  le  conseguenze  piu  certe 
ed  immediate.  E  cioe,  che  secondo  quel  dettato,  I1  opera  fatta  da 
uno  dei  condomini  senza  la  volonta  dell'  altro  non  si  puo  rimuovere, 
per  disposto  di  legge,  quando  non  leda  1'  interesse  del  socio  che 
nega.  fe  il  lato  positive  della  nuova  formula.  E  perci6  quando 
la  disposizione  di  uno  dei  socii,  o  1'  opera  eseguita,  tornano  di 
vantaggio  alia  comunione,  e  non  ledono  gli  interessi  dell'  altro, 
allora  la  volonta  di  colui  che  ha  ordinato  1'  opera  prevale;  o  meglio, 
in  realta,  prevale  1'  interesse  sociale. 

Coincidenza  dunque  perfetta  di  parole,  di  concetti  e  di  norme 
in  tutte  le  correzioni  ed  aggiunte  fatte  da  Giustiniano  nella  materia 
in  esame. 

62.  Ne  P  attivita  di  Giustiniano  s'  arresta  a  paralizzare  solo  la 
forza  dei  principi  astratti ;  ch&  le  riforme  in  quella  nuova  direzione 
investono,  di  necessita,  tutti  i  punti  della  teoria  della  communio,  e 
tutte  le  conseguenze ;  e  dimostrano  che  il  nuovo  regolamento  di 
essa  ebbe  nella  compilazione  pieno  e  decisive  sviluppo. 

H 


98  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

Cosl  circa  la  costituzione  di  servitu  sul  fondo  comune 
leggiamo  nel 

fr.  10  D.  xxxix.  3,  Ulp.  53  ad  ed.  Si  autem  plures  sint 
eiusdem  loci  domini,  unde  aqua  ducitur,  omnium  voluntatem  esse 
sequendam  non  ambigitur :  \iniquum  enim  visum  est  voluntatem 
unius  ex  modica  forte  portiuncula  domini  praeiudicium  sociis  facere1^. 
An  tamen  subsequi  voluntas  possit,  videamus.  [et  placet  nihil 
interesse  utrum  praecedat  voluntas  aquae  ductionem  an  subsequatur, 
quia  et  posteriorem  voluntatem  praetor  tueri  debet^\ 

Ulpiano  esigeva  la  voluntas  omnium.  E  non  si  poteva  dubi- 
tarne :  non  ambigitur.  Ma  Giustiniano  nota  «  essere  iniquo  che  la 
volonta  di  uno  che  abbia  nella  comunione  una  piccola  porziuncola 
possa  pregiudicare  gli  altri». 

Sarebbe  errore  intendere  quell'  inciso  che  e  nel  pr.  del  testo, 
come  giustificazione  o  comento  alia  parola  omnium ;  perche  se 
si  esige  la  volonta  unanime  dei  socii  il  plus  o  il  minus  delle  quote 
non  conta.  Per  ci6  la  Glossa  con  semplicita  spontanea  disse  :  idem 
et  si  maximam  partem  habet.  E  cio  e  vero.  Ma  allora,  nemmeno 
e  giusto  attribuire  ai  compilatori  un  comento  cosl  stupido.  Ed  in 
verita  il  periodo  aggiunto  ha  valore  per  se  stesso,  per  quel  che  dice. 
Esso  ha  non  il  valore  di  una  chiosa  alia  decisione  che  precede,  ma 
quello  piuttosto  di  una  limitazione,  e  cioe  per  significare  che  in  ogni 
caso  la  volonta  di  uno  che  ha  nella  comunione  un  interesse  minimo 
non  deve  pregiudicare  agli  altri. 

Ecco  di  nuovo  T  interesse  collettivo  posto  in  risalto  da 
Giustiniano,  in  confronto  della  volonta  dei  singoli.  E  per  ci6  e 
sicuro  che  anche  il  testo  in  esame  rappresenta  un  punto  di  vista  che 
si  coordina  perfettamente  al  nuovo  principio  qui  posto  in  evidenza, 
e  fatto  palese  dai  frammenti  piu  cospicui  della  materia.  Se  poi  la 
decisione  del  comune  vantaggio  spetti  alia  maggioranza  numerica 
dei  socii,  ovvero  a  coloro  che  hanno  la  prevalenza  degli  interessi,  e 
cosa  che  vedremo  piu  oltre. 

L'  applicazione  del  nuovo  principio  in  materia  di  servitu  sul  fondo 
comune  deve  valere,  a  fortiori^  per  1'  acquisto,  precisamente  il 
contrario  di  quello  che  insegnavano  i  classici.2 

Ma  ritornando  al  testo  in  esame  osservo  che  la  interpolazione 
contenuta  nel  §  I  ha  un  significato  ancora  piu  sovversivo ;  perche 
essa  ammette  la  validita  di  concessione  di  servitu  fatta  da  un  gruppo 

1  Eisele,  ZSS.  vol.  xxx.  pp.  133,  135.        2  D.  viii.  3,  19,  si  omnes  stipulentur. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprietct  99 

di  socii,  cui  piii  tardi  potranno  accedere  gli  altri  quando  sia 
costituita.  II  senso  del  periodo  non  pu6  essere  equivoco.  Non  si 
vuol  dire  certamente  che  la  servitu  viene  ad  esistere  coir  atto  di 
concessione  fatto  dall'  ultimo,  perche  invece  vi  si  suppone,  espressa- 
mente,  che  altri  possano  accedere  alia  concessione  della  servitu 
costituita  :  et  placet  nihil  interesse,  utrum  praecedat  voluntas  aquae 
ductionem  an  subsequatur.  Ed  allora  se  non  si  vuole  attribuire  a 
Giustiniano,  oltre  che  un'  eresia  giuridica  pure  un'  incongruenza,  e 
d'  uopo  sottintendere  anche  qui  ripetuta  la  condizione  posta  avanti, 
nel  principio  del  testo ;  cioe  che  la  concessione  deve  aver  luogo  con 
P  effettivo  vantaggio  della  collettivita,  e  che  non  pu6  esser  posta  nel 
nulla  da  coloro  che  hanno  nella  comunione  un  minimo  interesse. 

Ed  allo  stesso  risultato,  per  quanto  concerne  la  possibilita  della 
cessione  della  servitu  da  una  parte  dei  socii,  conduce  il 

fr.  1 1  D.  viii.  3,  Celsus  27  dig.  Per  fundum,  qui  plurium  est,  ius 
mihi  esse  eundi  agendi  potest  separatim  cedi.  ergo  \subtili  ratione~\ 
non  aliter  meum  fiet  ius,  quam  si  omnes  cedant  et  novissima  demum 
cessione  superiores  omnes  confirmabuntur  :  \benignius  tamen  dicetur^ 
et  antequam  novissimus  cesserit,  eos,  qui  antea  cesserunt,  vetari  uti 
cesso  iure  non  posse]. 

Le  superstrutture  giustinianee  sono  qui  evidenti  e  notissime.1 
II  legislatore  dispone  la  efficacia  giuridica  della  cessione  fatta  da 
una  parte  dei  condomini,  che  e  irrevocabile,  e  per  ci6  produttiva 
degli  effetti  propri  ad  essa,  anche  prima  che  avvenga  la  disposizione 
dell'  ultimo.  Proprio  il  contrario  di  quel  che  insegnava  Celso  nel 
testo  originale,  e  che  era  inevitabile  per  la  natura  del  dritto  che 
compete  ai  singoli  titolari  della  cosa  comune,  che  dava  a  ciascuno 
una  posizione  pari  ed  indipendente  sulla  cosa,  per  cui :  non  aliter 
meum  fiet  tus,  quam  si  omnes  cedant ',  et  novissima  demum  cessione 
superiores  omnes  confirmabuntur. * 

Cosi  sono  anche  questi  testi  coordinati  attorno  al  nuovo 
principio,  e  lo  determinano  e  lo  confermano  in  tutte  le  conseguenze. 

63.  Ma  un  altro  punto,  che  riguarda  lo  scioglimento  della 
comunione  di  cose,  inita  per  contratto,  dev'  essere  qui  con- 
siderate ;  non  solo  per  il  motivo  che  gl'  interpreti  antichi  lo  col- 
legarono  al  fr.  26  D.  viii.  2,  ma  perche  in  realta  il  nuovo  ordina- 
mento  di  Giustiniano  vi  si  manifesta  con  grande  rilievo.  II  passo 
cui  alludo  e  il 

1  Kruger  ad  h.  1.  2  Cfr.  D.  viii.  4,  6,  2. 


ioo  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

fr.  65  §  5  D.  xvii.  2,  Ulp.  32  ad  ed.  Labeo  autem  posteriorum 
libris  scripsit,  si  renuntiaverit  societati  unus  ex  sociis  eo  tempore, 
quo  interfuit  socii  non  dirimi  societatem,  committere  eum  in  pro 
socio  actione :  nam  si  emimus  mancipia  inita  societate,  deinde 
renunties  mihi  eo  tempore,  quo  vendere  mancipia  non  expedit,  hoc 
casu.  quia  deteriorem  causam  meam  facis,  teneri  te  pro  socio 
iudicio.  Proculus  hoc  ita  verum  esse  ait,  [si  societatis  non  intersit 
dirimi  societatem:  semper  enim  non  idy  quod  privatim  interest 
unius  ex  sociis,  servari  solet,  sed  quod  societati  expedit.  haec  ita 
accipienda  sunt,']  si  nihil  de  hoc  in  coeunda  societate  convenit. 

La  decisione  di  Labeone  era  indubbiamente  per  ogni  rispetto 
giusta,  come  quella  che  discendeva  dai  principi  piu  fermi,  che 
regolano  la  societa.  La  quale  al  pari  della  comunione  non  era 
riguardata  dai  giureconsulti  classici  come  un  ente  organizzato,  con 
interessi  distinti  da  quelli  dei  singoli,  bensi  come  una  semplice 
aggregazione  d'  individui  per  conseguire  determinati  scopi ;  e  per 
ci6,  quando  la  societa  fosse  convenuta  senza  termine,  ciascun  socio 
poteva  rinunziarvi,  in  qualsiasi  momento,  salvo  la  responsabilita  che 
gli  incombeva  per  la  rinunzia  fatta  in  tempo  inopportune  pregiu- 
dizievole  ai  singoli  come  tali :  interfuit  socii  non  dirimi  societatem. 
II  che  vuol  dire  che  il  fondamento  dell'  actio  pro  socio  si  deve 
ricercare  nella  lesione  dell'  interesse  dei  singoli,  e  non  gia  nel 
pregiudizio  che  uno  possa  arrecare  all'  interesse  collettivo. 

Proculo  consentiva  certamente  in  cio :  verum  esse.  Ma  a  rimuovere 
qualsiasi  ragione  di  equivoco  notava :  Proculus  hoc  ita  verum  esse 
[...]  si  nihil  de  hoc  in  coeunda  societate  convenit'^  perche  allora  il 
socio  e  legato  dai  contratto,  che  limita  la  sua  liberta  di  rinunzia. 
Tutto  il  resto  che  si  legge  nel  passo  e  opera  dei  compilatori.  Nella 
F  manca  la  frase  ait  si  e  cotali  omissioni  sono  di  frequente  una 
conseguenza  delle  saldature  delle  interpolazioni.2  Nella  frase 
servari  solet  si  manifesta  la  incertezza  di  un  principio  direttivo, 
la  quale  non  puo  essere  nemmeno  tolta  di  mezzo  dai  semper 
che  precede.  E  solet  e  verbo  frequentissimo  nelle  correzioni 

1  L'  identica  chiusa  in  7.  iii.  25,  5. 

?  Non  sappiamo  ancora  il  procedimento  pratico  adottato  dai  compilatori 
nel  correggere  i  passi ;  ma  indizii  di  vario  ordine  fanno  ritenere  che  le 
modificazioni  erano  apposte  sui  mss.,  tra  le  righe  o  nel  margine  con  richiami. 
Nel  punto  in  esame  sono  visibili  direi  come  due  note  sovrapposte  :  hoc  ita 
verum  esse  .  .  .  haec  ita  accipienda  sunt  che  non  possono  derivare  dalla 
stessa  mano.  E  perche  il  plurale  :  accipienda  sunt  in  luogo  del  singolare 
accipiendum  ?  L'  uso  del  plurale  in  questi  casi  e  indizio  d3  interpolazione  ; 
cfr.  D.  xli.  3,  xliv.  3  ;  Riccobono,  ZSS.  vol.  xxxi.  p.  359. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  101 

giustinianee  ai  testi  classici,  adoperato  sia  nelle  aggiunte  che 
portano  una  modificazione  ai  principii  fondamentali,  sia  per 
attenuare  le  decisioni  ferme  della  giurisprudenza  classica,  ovvero 
per  limitare  una  sentenza  avulsa  dai  suoi  presupposti.1  Nel  nostro 
caso  il  verbo  in  parola  e  incongruo  ed  impressionante ;  poiche  tra 
1'  interesse  della  societas  considerata  come  unita  e  quello  dei  singoli 
socii  come  tali  la  distanza  e  enorme.  Se  Proculo  mirava  veramente 
a  contraddire  il  maestro,  in  un  punto  cosl  essenziale,  avrebbe  scritto 
con  fermezza  servatur.  Di  piu  se  Proculo,  contrastando,  riusciva 
a  colpire  cosl  in  pieno  la  decisione  di  Labeone,  egli  non  avrebbe 
potuto  iniziare  la  nota  con  la  frase  :  hoc  ita  verum  esse.  II  dissenso 
su  di  un  principio  fondamentale  non  ammette  concessioni.  Or 
alia  stregua  della  dottrina  esposta  nella  nota  la  decisione  di 
Labeone  cade  tutta,  irremissibilmente,  perche  non  e  piu  vero  che 
contro  il  socio  rinunziante  possa  accordarsi  un'  azione,  si  interfuit 
socii  non  dirimi  societatem.  Questo  motive  non  ha  piu  valore  ;  e 
per  conseguenza  nulla  conta  che  a  causa  della  rinunzia  intempestiva, 
come  si  esprimeva  Labeone,  deteriorem  causam  meam  facts, 

Ecco  pertanto  come  la  nota  di  Proculo  investe  a  fondo  la 
decisione  che  precede ;  appunto  perche  quella  muove  da  un 
principio  diverse,  secondo  cui  e  1'  interesse  sociale  .<non  quello  dei 
singoli  che  va  tenuto  in  considerazione.2 

E  se  guardiamo  i  termini  del  dissenso  tra  Labeone  e  Proculo 
da  un  altro  punto  di  vista  la  contraddizione  diviene  ancora  piu 
stridente ;  avvegnache  Labeone  ammetteva  1'  actio  pro  socio  in 
seguito  alia  rinunzia  intempestiva  fatta  da  uno  dei  coobbligati,  e 
ci6  in  quanto  derivasse  una  lesione  all'  interesse  dell'  attore : 
interfuit  socii  non  dirimi  societatem  ;  Proculo  invece  avrebbe  detta 
questa  decisione  vera,  ma  solo  nel  caso  si  societatis  non  intersit 
dirimi  societatem  ;  cioe  giusto  enunciando  un  presupposto  di  fatto 
contrario  a  quello  indicate  da  Labeone,  e  che  induce  per  se  la 
inammissibilita  dell'  actio ,  e  di  conseguenza  la  decisione  contraria  a 
quella  data  dal  suo  maestro. 

1  Cfr.  Cod.  viii.  53,  7  ;  Riccobono,  ZSS.  vol.  xxxiii.  p.  292  ;  D.  iv.  4,  7 
§  2  ;  D.  xxvii.  10,  I  pr.  ;  D.  1.  17,  in,  in  confronto  col  fr.  23  §  8  D.  ix.  2  ; 
e  specialmente  nel  titolo  de  R.  I.  ha  una  funzione  limitatrice  come  fere, 
Praesertim,  maxime^  plerumque^  saepe,  onde  contenere  entro  certi  limiti  la 
massima  che  avulsa  dai  suoi  presupposti  assumeva  una  portata  generale : 
cfr.  fr.  19,  58,  86,  94,  114  D.  1.  17.  Pel  fr.  39  pr.  D.  xxxix.  2  di  Pomponio 
cfr.  p.  85,  sotto  il  n.  48.  2  Cfr.  B.  xii.  I,  62  scol.  8  (Heimb.  i,  p.  774). 


IO2  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

Si  puo  immaginare  incongruenza  piu  manifesta  tra  due  termini, 
cosl  discordanti  sia  nei  presupposti,  nel  fondamento,  nella  decisione 
e  tuttavia  congiunti  P  uno  all'  altro  con  la  frase :  ita  verum  esse  ? 
Si  sarebbe  dovuto  perlomeno  aspettare  nella  nota :  si  societatis 
intersit  non  dirimi  societatem,  come  corresse  Aloandro,  e  gia  il 
glossatore  Giovanni,  ed  ora  i  moderni  contro  la  F.1 

II  lettore  ha  ora  tutti  gli  elementi  per  decidere.  E  dira  che 
la  correzione  del  testo  e  necessaria ;  ma  che  insieme  il  brano 
esaminato  e  tutto  dei  compilatori ;  il  quale  giudizio,  a  mio  modo 
di  vedere,  s'  impone  in  questo  luogo  per  le  considerazioni  di  vario 
ordine  esposte  avanti,  ma  sopratutto  poi  per  il  riflesso  che  la  nota 
attribuita  a  Proculo  s'  inquadra  perfettamente  nell'  ordine  di  idee 
di  Giustiniano. 

64.  Fu  infatti  Giustiniano  che,  come  sappiamo,  sostitui  ogni 
volta  nella  comunione  alia  volonta  dei  singoli  P  interesse  sociale ;  e 
cosi  Egli  giunse  pure  a  considerare  la  societa  come  un  gruppo 
collettivo,  che  ha  volonta  ed  interessi  distinti  da  quelli  dei  singoli 
socii.  E  perci6  i  compilatori  ritoccando  i  testi,  con  tutta  sponta- 
neita,  rappresentavano  la  societas  come  una  unita,  e  scrivevano : 

fr.  49  D.  xvii.  2,  Ulp.  31  ad  ed.  \Si  hoc  facto  societatem  laesit^ 
si  verbi  gratia  negotiatorem  servum  vulneraverit  vel  occiderit. 

In  questo  passo  il  primo  periodo  e  emblematico  ;  i  giuristi 
esprimono  il  concetto  con  le  frasi  damnum  in  re  communi  socius 
dedit  fr.  47  §  I  eod. ;  rei  communi  socius  nocuit  fr.  52  §  2  eod. 

Nello  stesso  ordine  di  confronti  e  caratteristico  il 

fr.  58  §  I  D.  xvii.  2,  Ulp.  31  ad  ed. 

Item  Celsus  tractat,  si  pecuniam  contulissemus  ad  mercem 
emendam  et  mea  pecunia  perisset,  cui  perierit  ea.  et  ait,  si  post 
collationem  evenit,  ut  pecunia  periret,  quod  non  fieret,  nisi  societas 
coita  esset,  utrique  perire,  ut  puta  si  pecunia,  cum  peregre 
portaretur  ad  mercem  emendam,  periit ;  \si  vero  ante  collationem, 
posteaquam  earn  destinasses,  tune  perierit,  nihil  eo  nomine 
consequeris,  inquit,  quia  non  societati  periit\. 

L'  interpolazione  della  parte  riprodotta  in  corsivo  e  manifesta 

1  La  correzione  e  gia  nella  Glossa  (Giovanni),  seguita  da  Aloandro,  dagli 
edd.  italiani,  ed  ha  un  appoggio  nei  B.  xii.  i,  62  (Heimb.  v.  i,  p.  775),  dove 
Stefano  nella  paragrafe  (scol.  10)  scrive :  et  p)  rfj  Koivcoviy  Sia</>e/oei  TO 
Tavnrjv 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  103 

principalmente  per  la  inversione  dei  soggetti l ;  poiche  1'  ipotesi 
fondamentale,  esaminata  dal  giurista  era  :  et  mea  pecunia  periisset, 
la  quale  si  capovolge  nel  seguito  del  testo:  si  vero  .  .  .  destinasses 
.  .  .  quia  non  societati  periit?  E  pertanto  nella  parte  prima  si 
dice  utrique  perire,  nella  seconda  invece  non  societati  periit.  fe 
vero  che  qui  la  frase  e  senza  conseguenze. 

Tutta  la  dottrina  della  societas  merita  per  ci6  una  revisione  da 
questo  punto  di  vista ;  perche  come  s'  e  constatato  il  fr.  65  §  5, 
nella  parte  interpolata  coincide  precisamente  con  quelle  riforme 
introdotte  da  Giustiniano  nella  comunione.  In  questo  luogo 
interessava  porre  in  relievo  il  confronto,  che  da  forza  alia  nostra 
dimostrazione. 

IV.  LA  VOLONTA  DELLA  MAGGIORANZA 

65.  L'  autonomia  dei  singoli  nella  comunione  e  nella  societa  fu 
certamente  soppressa  nella  Compilazione  di  Giustiniano,  in  cui, 
come  s'  e  visto,  la  considerazione  dell'  interesse  collettivo  prende  il 
posto  del  vantaggio  e  del  volere  dei  singoli  compartecipi.  Ed  in 
rispondenza  perfetta  con  questo  nuovo  principio  si  rinviene  pure 
surrogata  alia  unanimita  del  consenso  di  tutti,  per  qualsiasi 
disposizione  materiale  della  cosa,  la  volonta  della  maggioranza,  la 

1  Essa  aveva  soltanto  lo  scope  di  completare  1'  esame  del  caso,  invertendo 
i  presupposti    enunciati    avanti.       Indizii :    si   vero.  .   .   .  tune  perierit  .  .   . 
periit.     Cfr.  Harmenopuli  Exab.  iii.  10,  21. 

2  Nei  fr.  genuini  dei  giureconsulti  e  costante  la  terminologia  conferre  in 
societatem,    imputare    societati,    omnibus,    ceteris,    le    quali    frasi    sono    per- 
fettamente  equivalent!,  e  si  riferiscono  sempre  all'  interesse  dei  singoli  socii 
considerato  in  complesso  solo  per  il  lato  economico,  ma  non  giuridicamente. 
Infatti  per  quel  che  concerne  le  conseguenze  giuridiche  soltanto  1'  interesse  e 
la  persona  dei  singoli  vengono  posti  in  azione ;  cosl  in  D.  xvii.  2,  fr.  60  Pomp. 
13    ad    Lab.  .  .  .  usuras   quoque  eum  praestare  debere   Labeo  ait  .  .  .  sed 
quod  socii  intersit  moram  eum  non  adhibuisse.  —  fr.  73  eod.  Ulp.  I  resp.  .  .  . 
ea   quoque,    quae    in    honorem    alterius    liberorum    erogata    sunt,    utrisque 
imputanda.  —  2-3  pr.  eod.  .   .  .  sociis  praestet. 

E  piu  rimarchevole  ancora  e  vedere  che  nello  stesso  fr.  65  D.  xvii.  2, 
richiamato  sopra,  Cassio  e  Paolo  usano  gli  stessi  termini  adoperati  da 
Labeone  nel  decidere  i  singoli  casi :  §  3  (Cassius)  .  .  .  se  autem  ab  tilts  non 
liber  are.  §  4  ...  teneberis  qiianti  interest  mea.  §  5  (Labeo)  .  .  .  interfuit 
socii  non  dirimi  societatem  .  .  .  deteriorem  causam  meam  fads.  §  6.  (Paulus) 
.  .  .  socium  a  se,  non  se  a  socio  liberat\  cfr.  21  D.  eod.  (Ulpjanus)  .  .  . 
nos  cum  eo  non  communicabimus.  Cfr.  Cuq,  Inst.  ii.  p.  442.  E  vero,  per 
altro,  che  le  alterazioni  tribonianee  sono  continue  nel  senso  inverso  accennato 
in  questo  scritto. 


IO4  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

quale  ora  ha  il  potere  di  deliberare   intorno  al   godimento,  alia 
conservazione  o  destinazione  della  cosa  comune. 

Come  di  solito  le  interpolazioni  giustinianee  sono  anche  in 
questo  proposito  saltuarie,  e  non  rendono  a  prima  giunta  una  norma 
ben  precisa  e  determinata  ;  ma  la  cosa  tuttavia  e  certissima,  come 
si  scorge  dalla  dimostrazione  che  precede,  e  come  deve  emergere 
con  evidenza  osservando  i  testi  fondamentali  che  si  riferiscono 
alia  comunione,  e  che  riunisco  qui  per  coordinarli  in  una  sintesi : 

fr.  ii  D.  viii.  3  ...  benignius  tamen  dicetur  et  antequam 
novissimus  cesserit,  eos,  qui  antea  cesserunt,  vetare  uti  cesso  iure 
non  posse. 

fr.  10  D.  xxxix.  3.  ...  iniquum  enim  visum  est  voluntatem 
unius  ex  modica  forte  portiuricula  dominii  praeiudicium  sociis  facere. 

fr.  26  D.  viii.  2.  ...  si  modo  toti  societati  prodest  opus  tolli. 

fr.  65  §  5  D.  xvii.  2.     si  societatis  intersit  non  dirimi  societatem. 

Nei  quali  passi  al  consenso  unanime  dei  socii  e  costantemente 
sostituita  la  volonta  o  la  disposizione  di  una  parte  di  essi,  che,  a 
volte  espressamente,  e  autorizzata  ad  agire  in  opposizione  ad  uno 
dei  socii,  che  ha  nella  communio  un  interesse  minore. 

Ed  allo  stesso  risultato  si  giunge  quando  si  tenga  conto  di 
quelle  altre  frasi  in  cui  Giustiniano  non  si  riporta  alia  volonta  dei 
socii,  ma  si  bene  all'  interesse  della  cosa  medesima ;  perche,  come 
s'  &  detto,  1'  interesse  obbiettivo  non  coincide  per  s&  stesso  con  la 
volonta  dei  singoli  socii : 

fr.  6  §  12  D.  x.  3.      si  interfuit  aedium  hoc  fieri, 
fr.  14  §  2  D.  x.  3.     quod  etiam  ipsius  rei  qualitati  prodest. 
fr.  28  D.  x.  3.     ut  tamen  factum  opus  tollat  cogi  non  potest  [in 
confronto  con  26  D.  viii.  2]. 

66.  E  del  resto  su  questo  proposito  vi  e  un  passo  di  grande 
importanza  che  pu6  essere  ora  esaminato  con  ben  altra  perspicacia  : 

fr.  14  D.  xvi.  3,  Gai.  ix.  ad  ed.  Si  plures  heredes  exstiterint 
ei  qui  deposuerit,  [dicitur,  si  maior  pars  adierit,  restituendam  rent 
praesentibus :  maiorem  autem  partem  non  ex  numero  utique 
personarum,  sed  ex  magnitudine  portionum  hereditariarum  in- 
telligendam  :  cautela  idonea  reddendd}. 

Questa  decisione  e  nuova,1  ed  ha  un'  importanza  di  prim'  ordine 
neir  argomento  in  esame. 

1  L'  interpolazione  si  manifesta  per  varii  indizii :  1'  ablative  assoluto  finale 
fu  rilevato  dagli  antichi,  dal  Brissonio  e  dal  Fabro  :  Coniect.  xii.  1 6,  6  ;  il  quale 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  105 

E  dico  avanti  tutto  che  non  c'  e  modo  di  aggregate  una  siffatta 
decisione  ai  principii  piu  certi  seguiti  dai  giureconsulti.  Infatti, 
ove  si  supponga  che  i  coeredi  siano  condomini  della  cosa  depositata 
e  che  vogliano  agire  con  la  ret  vindicatio  non  e  dubbio  che  ciascuno 
deve  agire  pro  parte ;  e  parimenti  se  esperiscono  P  actio  depositi 
deve  ciascuno  agire  pro  parte,  sul  fondamento  del  titolo  di  eredita. 
Tutto  ci6  e  sicuro.  II  dubbio  ha  ragion  d'  essere  solo  nella 
compilazione  di  Giustiniano,  e  particolarmente  rispetto  al  deposito 
di  cose  indivisibili ;  perche  anche  questa  materia  fu  profondamente 
rimescolata  da  Giustiniano.  Ma  secondo  il  diritto  classico  ne  uno 
degli  eredi  ne  la  maggioranza  di  essi  hanno  diritto  a  richiedere  la 
restituzione  dell'  intero,  che  li  esporrebbe  alia  plus  petitio.  Cia- 
scuno deve  invece  chiedere  sempre  la  parte  che  gli  spetta  per  il 
titolo  di  erede.  Soltanto  questo  e  vero,  che  il  depositario  puo 
evitare  la  condanna  dichiarandosi  pronto  a  restituere  rem  anche 
ad  un  solo,  quando  gli  si  offra  cauzione  per  le  possibili  molestie  da 
parte  degli  altri  coeredi.  Tale  procedimento  e  attestato  dallo  stesso 
Giustiniano,  che  lo  accolse  in  passi  interpolati  (cfr.  fr.  I  §36/7.  xvi. 
3)  in  confronto  con  quello  in  esame,  ed  e  per  altro  il  rimedio 
consueto  in  qualsiasi  evenienza. 

Esso  e  applicato  da  Giuliano  nella  specie  che  segue : 

fr.  i  §  37  D.  xvi.  3  Ulp.  30  aded.  Apud  Julianum  libro  tertio 
decimo  digestorum  talis  species  relata  est :  ait  enim,  si  depositor 
decesserit  et  duo  existant,  qui  inter  se  contendant  unusquisque  solum 
se  heredem  dicens,  ei  tradendam  rem,  qui  paratus  est  adversus  alterum 

raccolse  altre  identiche  aggiunte  di  Triboniano  ;  cfr.  De  Ruggiero,  Studii 
Fadda,  ii.  p.  217  nota  ;  appare  inoltre  dalle  molteplici  ellissi  che  si  riscontrano 
nello  squarcio ;  e  cioe  dopo  deposuerit  si  richiederebbe  rem,  il  genitive 
eorum  dopo  maior  pars ;  ed  infine  vanno  notati  i  due  gerundii :  restituen- 
dam,  intellegendam  privi  del  verbo  ausiliare.  Ma  piu  di  tutti  cotesti  indizii 
ha  peso  quel  disgraziato  adierit  non  determinate  nell3  oggetto,  e  che  perci6 
ha  fatto  difficolta  di  interpretazione.  L'  opinione  dominante  presso  gli  antichi 
voile  intendere  :  adierit  hereditatem  [cfr.  Gliick,  Erldut.  vol.  xv.  p.  231],  ed 
essa  ha  il  conforto  dei  B.  xiii.  2,  14,  scolio  i  di  Stefano  (Heimb.  v.  ii.  p.  47). 
La  Glossa  piti.  accorta  spiego :  ad  repetundum  depositum.  A.  Fabro,  /.  c., 
corresse  il  testo  in  modo  arbitrario  ;  ma  la  sua  argomentazione  nella  parte 
negativa  e  ineccepibile.  Egli  scriveva :  legendumque  aderit,  nam  priora  ilia 
'  si  plures  heredes  exstiterint '  ostendunt  ab  omnibus  heredibus  aditam  fuisse 
hereditatem^  quia  nee  testamentarii  nee  legitimi  heredes  nee  alii  denique 
quam  sui  prius  exstiterunt  heredes  quam  adierint.  sequentia  vero  '  restituen- 
dam  rem  praesentibus '  demonstrant  eum  casum  tractari  quo  pars  tantum 
heredum  adsit  petatque  depositum. 


io6  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

reum  defendere,  [hoc  est  eum  qui  depositum  suscepit]  : 1  quod  si 
neuter  hoc  onus  suscipiat  commodissime  dici  ait  non  esse  cogendum 
a  praetore  iudicium  suscipere :  \pportere  igitur  rent  deponi  in  aede 
aliqua,  donee  de  her  edit  ate  iudicetur\? 

E  per  altro  P  azione  di  deposito  si  da  pro  parte  quando  due  o  piu 
sono  i  deponenti : 

fr.  17  pr.  D.  xvi.  3  ...  quod  aliter  est  [scilicet  non  in  solidum], 
cum  rem  communem  plures  deponunt ;  —  fr.  I  §  3 1  D.  eod.  .  .  . 
unicuique  dominorum  in  partem  competit  depositi. 

Dunque  la  soluzione  del  quesito  proposto  da  Gaio  nel  fr.  in  esame 
era  pronta ;  perche  i  coeredi  debbono  esperire  P  actio  depositi  pro  parte. 
E  se  la  cosa  e  indivisibile  P  attore  deve  offrire  cauzione  al  convenuto 
per  la  parte  degli  altri  coeredi,  dai  quali  il  depositario  deve  essere 
garentito  e  protetto  da  ogni  possibile  molestia.  La  cautio  mette  in 
evidenza  che  ciascuno  dei  coeredi  ha  diritto  di  esercitare  le  azioni 
del  defunto  solo  per  la  quota  di  eredita  a  lui  pervenuta  ;  non  potendo 
il  dritto  degli  altri  essere  in  modo  alcuno  leso  o  solo  menomato 
dalP  azione  di  uno  o  di  una  maggioranza  qualsiasi  degli  eredi. 

E  percio  possiamo  ritenere  sicura  in  questo  punto  la  innovazione 
legislativa  di  Giustiniano,  il  quale  all'  accordo  di  tutti  i  coeredi 
all'  azione  dei  singoli  pro  parte  sostitul  P  azione  concessa  ad  un 
gruppo,  costituito  da  coloro  che  nelP  eredita  rappresentano  la 
maggioranza  degli  interessi.  Si  noti  che  nel  passo  non  e  fatta 
distinzione  di  obbietto  divisibile  o  indivisibile ;  quale  rilievo  e 
gravissimo,  perche  induce  un'  evidente  contraddizione  tra  il  passo 
in  esame  e  gli  altri  citati  piu  sopra.  Giustiniano  per  altro  tratto  con 
vera  predilezione  e  cura  la  materia  del  deposito,  e  voile  particolar- 
mente  porre  riparo  a  quel  sistema  delP  actio  pro  parte,  specie  in  se- 
guito  ad  eredita,  che  a  suo  modo  d'  intendere  era  complicata ;  e  che 
poteva  dar  luogo  a  tergiversazioni  da  parte  di  uno  o  dei  pochi, 
che  avendo  nella  eredita  una  modica portiuncula,  potevano  facilmente 
assumere  un  atteggiamento  astioso,  pregiudizievole  agli  altri.3 

1  Glossa,  cf.  Lenel,  Pal.  ii.  c. 

2  Triboniano.  Infatti  la  conseguenza  (igitur)  non  si  ricava  dalle  premesse 
contenute  nel  testo  e  riguarda  per  nulla  la  lite  tra  i  pretendenti  della  eredita. 
La  depositio  in  aede,  del  resto,  e  rimedio  consueto  adoperato  da  Giustiniano, 
come  si  vedrk  subito. 

3  Le  riforme  di  Giustiniano   in   questa  materia   indicate   sommariamente 
furono  le  seguenti : 

(a)  Egli  stabili  che  ove  la  cosa  depositata  sia  indivisibile  la  restituzione 
deve  essere  in  solidum  a  ciascuno  dei  titolari ; 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  107 

La  riforma,  dunque,  anche  in  questo  luogo  e  determinata  da 

fr.  22  D.  xvi.  3  :  [ — et  nisi  pro  solido  res  non  potest  restitui.  nee  tamen 
absurde  sentiet,  qui  hoc  putaverit,  plane  nisi  integrae  ret  restitutione  eum,  cum 
quo  actum  fuerit,  liberari  non  posse,  condemnandum  tamen,  si  res  non  resti- 
tuetur,  pro  qua  parte  heres  extitit.]  II  giureconsulto  trattava  solo  de!la 
responsabilita  solidale  del  coeredi  per  la  contrettazione  dolosa  del  deposito, 
e  Giustiniano  rivolge  la  decisione  alia  restituzione  della  res.  Per  la  interpola- 
zione  del  brano :  Nee  tamen  .  .  .  extitit  cfr.  Eisele,  ZSS.  xxx.  p.  1 20. 

Altra  interpolazione,  che  in  alcuni  punti  coincide  con  quella  or  indicata, 
nel  fr.  i  §  44  eod.  Sed  si  duo  deposuerint  et  ambo  agant,  [si  quidem  sic 
deposuerunt;  ut  vel  unus  tollat  totum,  poterit  in  solidum  agere ;  sin  vero  pro 
parte,  pro  quae  eorum  interest,  tune  dicendum  est  in  partem  condemnationem 
faciendam\  La  conclusione  e  banale,  e  la  forma  del  testo  pessima,  d'  im- 
pronta  bizantina. 

(ft)  Ammise  1'  intervento  del  magistrato  per  la  consegna  ai  coeredi  della 
loro  parte  ;  ed  ove  la  cosa  fosse  indivisibile  anche  il  deposito  in  aede  :  cfr.  I 
§  36  D.  eod.  interamente  interpolate,  come  vide  gia  Fabro,  Con.  xii.  16,  8. 
II  rimedio  del  deposito  si  riscontra  pure  nel  fr.  5  in  f.  eod.  nisi  .  .  .  deponi. 
E  cosl  in  materia  di  pagamenti  da  fare  al  minore  nel  fr.  7  §  2  D.  iv.  4.  .  .  . 
[Sed  hodie  solet  pecunia  in  aedem  deponi],  ut  Pomponius  1.  xxviii  scribit,  ne 
vel  debitor  ultra  usuris  oneretur,  vel  creditor  minor  perdat  pecuniam,  \aut 
curatoribus  solvi,  si  sunt~\.  La  citazione  di  Pomp,  si  riferiva  appunto  alia 
necessita  di  nominare  un  curator  al  minore,  di  cui  si  tratta  nel  seguito  del 
testo. 

(c)  In  armonia  col  fr.  14  D.  xvi.  3,  esaminato  sopra,  ammise  che  la  cosa 
depositata  indivisibile  si  restituisse  alia  pars  heredum  ma  in  seguito  a  iussus 
praetoris  ;  fr.  8 1  §  i  D.  xlvi.  3  :  Si  lancem  deposuerit  apud  me  Titius  et  pluribus 
heredibus  relictis  decesserit :  [si pars  heredum  me  interpellet  optimum  quidem 
esse,  si  praetor  aditus  iussisset  me  parti  heredum  earn  lancem  tradere,  quo  casu 
depositi  me  reliqtds  coheredibus  non  teneri.  sed  et  si  sine  praetore  sine  dolo 
malo  hoc  fecero  liberabor  aut  (quod  verius  est)  non  incidam  in  obligationem. 
optimum  autem  est  id  per  magistratum  facere\. 

La  struttura  del  passo,  a  cominciare  dalla  frase  :  si  pars  heredum  me 
interpellet  da  luogo  a  gravi  sospetti  per  le  ripetizioni :  si  lancem  .  .  .  earn 
lancem  .  .  .  pars  heredum  .  .  .  parti  heredum  .  .  .  reliquis  .  .  .  Per  i 
tempi  dei  verbi  etcc.  cfr.  anche  Di  Marzo,  Libri  'di  Pomp,  ad  Q.  M.  p.  52  ; 
1'  interpolazione  del  periodo  finale  sed  etsi  .  .  .  facere  fu  notata  dal  Pernice 
(Berliner  Sitzungsber.  a.  1886  p.  1 180  n.  5);  ed  ora  sappiamo  meglio  che  tutti 
questi  espedienti  per  effettuare  la  restituzione  del  deposito  a  parte  degli  eredi 
sono  giustinianei.  Solo  che  qui,  richiedendosi  1'  intervento  del  magistrato,  non 
si  esige  la  consegna  ne  sia  fatta  alia  maior  pars  heredum.  E  per  ci6  tutta  la 
materia  e  folta  d'  interpolazioni  che  suscitarono  in  ogni  tempo  controversie  ; 
Accursio  da  come  opinione  dominante  fra  i  glossatori  quella  che  ammetteva 
sempre  1'  actio  pro  parte,  salvo  patto  in  contrario :  fr.  i  §  44  D.  xvi.  3  ;  altri 
per6  distinguevano  1'  oggetto  divisibile  da  quello  indivisibile,  accordando  in 
quest'  ultimo  caso  la  petizione  in  solido :  cosi  Baldo  ad  1.  14  D.  xvi.  3  ; 
Duareno,  Opp..\\\.  p.  500;  e  gia  gl'  interpret!  greci :  Stefano  :  B.  xiii.  2,  14 
(Heimbach,  ii.  p.  47). 


io8  5.  Riccobono  [iv 

quello  stesso  ordine  di  idee  e  da  quel  medesimo  spirito,  che  indussero 
un  cosi  profondo  mutamento  in  tutto  il  diritto  di  comproprieta. 

67.  Ma  qui  conviene  indugiare  un  memento  per  gettare  uno 
sguardo  su  altri  rapporti  regolati  ex  novo  nella  compilazione,  e  dai 
quali  potremo  apprendere,  che  in  realta  il  diritto  di  disposizione 
della  cosa  comune,  conferito  da  Giustiniano  alia  maggioranza  dei 
socii,  risponde  ad  un  principle  generale  applicato  dal  legislatore 
tutte  le  volte  che  piu  persone  si  trovano  in  una  medesima  situazione, 
collegate  da  un  comune  interesse.  Lo  rinveniamo,  pertanto,  adottato 
tra  coeredi  e  condomini,  nella  cessione  dei  beni  come  nel  concorso 
dei  creditori,  sempre  negli  stessi  termini,  cioe  con  la  prevalenza 
accordata,  in  primo  luogo,  a  coloro  che  hanno  la  parte  o  1*  interesse 
maggiore. 

In  ordine  alia  cessione  dei  beni  la  innovazione  e  annunziata  da 
Giustiniano  direttamente  nella  c.  8  Cod.  vii.  71,  diretta  a  Giovanni, 
emanata  durante  la  formazione  dei  Digesti. 

II  legislatore  dice :  Et  sancimus  ut  vel  ex  cumulo  debiti  vel  ex 
numero  creditorum  causa  iudicetur.  I  creditori  che  hanno  il  maggiore 
interesse,  sia  uno  o  piu,  hanno  il  diritto  di  decidere  :  ipsius  sententia 
optineat — amplior  debiti  cumulus  minori  summae  praeferatur — Part 
autem  quantitate  debiti  inventa  .  .  .  tune  amplior  pars  creditorum 
optineat)  ut  quod  pluribus  placeat  statuatur.  Sin  vero  undique 
aequalitas  emergat — tune  eos  anteponi  qui  ad  humaniorem  declinant 
sententiam,  non  cessionem  exigentes  sed  inducias. 

Le  stesse  statuizioni  si  riscontrano  applicate  nei  Digesti  con 
grande  coerenza,  quantunque  saltuariamente. 

In  primo  luogo  nel 

fr.  7  §  19  D.  ii.  14  Ulp.  4  ad  ed.  Hodie  tamen  ita  demum  pactio 
huiusmodi  creditoribus  obest,  si  convenerint  in  unum  et  communi 
consensu  declaraverint  quota  parte  debiti  contenti  sint :  si  vero  dis- 
sentiant)  tune praetoris  paries  necessariae  sunt,  qui  decreto  suo  sequetur 
maioris  partis  voluntatem. 

L'  interpolazione  in  questo  punto1  fu  inserita  per  dare  ai 
creditori,  che  siano  d'  accordo,  un  potere  dispositive,  nel  senso  che 
la  loro  deliberazione  e  munita  per  se  stessa  d'  efficacia  giuridica. 
L'  intervento  del  pretore  si  esige  soltanto  nel  disaccordo  degli 
stessi,  e  solo  in  questa  ipotesi  il  magistrate  con  decreto  dara 
esecuzione  alia  volonta  della  maggioranza.  Tale  ordinamento  e 
1  Beseler,  Beitrdge^  ii.  97. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  109 

nuovo.  Perche  nel  diritto  classico  ove  e  fatta  menzione  del- 
1'  assemblea  del  creditor!  e  della  maggioranza  di  essi,  per  la  creazione 
del  magister?  per  la  nomina  del  curator  bonorum?  per  la  lex  bono- 
rum  vendundorum*  si  richiede  sempre  la  proposta  o  il  consenso 
degli  interessati,  della  maggioranza  di  essi,  essendo  per  altro  la 
creazione  del  magister  o  la  nomina  del  curator  o  le  condizioni  della 
vendita  poste  in  essere  da  un  decreto  del  pretore.  La  differenza 
dunque  risalta :  nel  diritto  classico  i  creditori  cooperano  col  magi- 
strate e  sono  adunati  per  far  proposte ;  nel  diritto  di  Giustiniano 
hanno  entro  certi  limiti  facolta  di  disporre  direttamente. 

II  passo  che  segue  nei  Digesti  contiene  applicazioni  di  altre 
norme  sancite  nella  c.  8  cit,  ed  e  cosl  riportato : 

fr.  8  eod.  Pap.  10  resp.  Maiorem  esse  partem  pro  modo  debiti, 
non  pro  numero  personarum  placuit  [quod  si  aequales  sint  in  cumulo 
debiti)  tune  plurium  numerus  creditorum  praeferendus  est ;  in  numero 
autem  pari  creditorum  auctoritatem  eius  sequetur praetor \  qui  dignitate 
inter  eos  praecellit.  sin  autem  omnia  undique  in  unam  aequalitatem 
concurrant)  humanior  sententia  a  praetor  e  eligenda  esi\  hoc  enim  ex 
divi  Marci  rescripto  colligi  potest. 

L'  interpolazione  della  parte  centrale  del  testo  fu  accertata  dal 
Gradenwitz ; 4  il  quale,  con  la  consueta  perspicacia,  rinvenne  pure 
di  recente,  nella  cosl  detta  legge  delle  citazioni  di  Teodosio  e 
Valentiniano  il  modello  di  cui  si  servirono  i  compilatori.5 

Lo  schema  di  quella  celebre  legge  e  davvero  interessante  e  val 
la  pena  di  riprodurlo  qui  per  un  altro  riscontro  che  ci  occorrera 
subito. 

c.  3  Th.  i.  4 :  Ubi  autem  diversae  sententiae  proferuntur,  potior 
numerus  vincat  auctorum,  vel  si  numerus  aequalis  sit  eius  partis 
praecedat  auctoritas,  in  qua  excellentis  ingenii  vir  Papinianus 
emineat.  .  .  .  Ubi  autem  pares  eorum  sententiae  recitantur,  quorum 
par  censetur  auctoritas,  quod  sequi  debeat  eligat  moderatio  iudi- 
cantis. 

68.  Or  e  degno  di  nota  che  cotesto  criterio  della  maggioranza  e 

1  Gai  iii.  79  (creari)  ;  Theoph.  iii.  12  (7iy>o/:?aAA«r#ai);  su  questi  passi  v. 
Kniep  (MM.  Girard^  i.  p.  630  e  seg.  ;  Cic.  ad  Att.  vi.  i,  15). 

2  fr.  2  pr.  §  i  D.  xlii.  7  ;  Lenel  Ed.  p.  419. 

3  fr.  58  §  i  D.  xvii.  i  ;  Paul.  4  quaest. — maiore  parte  creditorum  consen- 
tiente  a  praetore  decretum  est. 

4  Interpoldtionen,  pp.  62,  63  ;  Lenel,  Pal.  Pap.  650. 

5  ZSS.  vol.  xxxii.  p.  383. 


no  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

della  parita  di  voti  si  rinviene  adottato,  negli  stessi  termini  come 
nei  passi  avanti  riferiti,  pure  in  un'  opera  occidentale  contemporanea, 
cioe  in  un  passo  di  Paolo  Visigoto  a  proposito  del  servo  comune : 

Paul.  S.  iv.  12,  5.  Communem  servum  unus  ex  sociis  vinciendo 
futurae  libertati  non  nocebit.  \Inter  pares  enim  sententia  clementior 
severiori praefertur :  et  certe  humanae  rationis  estfavere  miserioribus, 
prope  et  innocentes  dicere  quos  absolute  nocentes  pronuntiare  non 
possunt  J] 

Nella  parita  dei  voti  dei  compartecipi  si  dice  anche  qui  che  deve 
prevalere  sententia  clementior  ;  come  nella  c.  8  Cod.  si  antepon- 
gono  :  qui  ad  humaniorem  declinant  sententiam,  e  nel  fr.  8  D*  ii.  14, 
humanior  sententia  .  .  .  eligenda  est.  Ma  in  qual  momento  pote 
introdursi  tale  principio  per  il  diritto  private  ?  lo  dico  che  il  passo 
or  riferito  non  pu6  essere  di  Paolo.  La  frase  inter  pares  priva  di 
un  sostantivo  ha  fatto  difficolta.  Huschke  ridusse  all'  accusative  la 
parola  sententia  che  segue,  senza  accorgersi  che  allora  il  compara- 
tive clementior  resta  in  aria.  Ma  tutto  cio  importa  poco.  II 
senso  del  passo  e  chiaro  e  si  determina  nella  continuazione,  dove  si 
dice  certamente  che  nella  parita  dei  voti  deve  prevalere  la  disposi- 
zione  piu  clemente  in  favore  della  liberta ;  e  dove  la  massima  si 
costruisce  pure  con  un  argomento  che  e  proprio  per  i  corpi  delibe- 
ranti  di  diritto  pubblico,  cioe  che  nella  parita  non  vi  pu6  essere 
condanna,  perche  il  giudizio  sfavorevole  e  annullato  dai  voti  con- 
trarii :  quos  absolute  nocentes  pronuntiare  non  possunt.  II  lettore 
vede  gia  che  il  verbo  possunt  spunta  come  un  fungo,  e  attesta  in 
maniera  irrefutabile  che  tutto  il  brano  e  d'  origine  postclassica. 
Genuine  e  solo  il  primo  periodo :  communem  .  .  .  non  nocebit^  che 
contiene  precisamente  1'  applicazione  del  principio  classico  del  condo- 
minio,  per  cui  uno  dei  socii  non  puo  menomamente  pregiudicare  la 
facolta  di  disposizione  dell'  altro  rispetto  alia  cosa  comune  ; x  e  non 
puo,  pertanto,  ne  dare  la  liberta  al  servo  ne  impedirla  in  mode 
assoluto.  Piu  tardi,  e  vero,  anche  nel  periodo  della  giurisprudenza 
classica,  furono  adottate  disposizioni  di  favore  per  la  liberta  dei 
servi,  svolte  poi  largamente  da  Giustiniano.2 

69.  Tutti  cotesti  elementi,  dunque,  raccolti  da  fonti  tarde3  e 

1  Cfr.  Paul.  S.  iv.  12,  i. 

2  Const,   un.    Cod.   7,   7  ;   Riccobono,   BIDR.   vol.    vii.  p.   244 ;  Mitteis, 
Archiv f.  Pap.  iii.  p.  252  seg. 

3  Per  quel  che  concerne  il  diritto  private  si  trova  menzione  della  facolta 
di   disposizione  della   maior  pars  in  una  lex  mandpio  dicta,  aggiunta   alia 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  in 

varie  rendono  piu  chiara  la  visione  del  nostro  problema  ;  perche  in 
realta  noi  rinveniamo  applicati  nella  Compilazione  di  Giustiniano 
gli  stessi  principii  al  condominio ;  in  primo  luogo  il  diritto  della 
maggioranza  di  disporre  della  cosa  comune. 

E  per  ci6  la  posizione  indipendente  che  i  singoli  avevano  nelJa 
comproprieta,  secondo  la  struttura  classica  dell'  istituto,  resta,  nel 
nuovo  sistema  inaugurate  da  Giustiniano,  essenzialmente  annullata. 
Ora,  invece,  la  comunione  puo  dirsi  organizzata  in  una  certa 
forma ;  ha  una  volonta  complessiva,  la  quale  custodisce,  regola  ed 
esplica  1'  interesse  collettivo  sotto  tutti  gli  aspetti.  Di  con- 
seguenza,  al  consenso  di  tutti  i  socii,  che  era  necessario  per 
qualsiasi  disposizione  materiale  della  cosa  comune,  si  sostitul  la 
facolta  di  disposizione  della  maggioranza. 

70.  E  pertanto  le  aggiunte  giustinianee  ai  passi  dei  giuristi 
classici  acquistano  ora  un  significato  preciso  e  grande  rilievo,  che 
esse  si  aggregano  tutte  perfettamente  attorno  al  nuovo  ordinamento, 
che  ha  un  deciso  carattere  sociale.  Si  puo  negare  forse  un  tale 
significato  a  quella  norma  legislativa  che  permette  la  rimozione 
dell'  opera  fatta  da  un  socio  solo  nel  caso  che  giovi  alia  colletti- 
vita  ?  :  si  toti  societati  prodest  opus  tolli>  26  D.  viii.  2.  E  la  stessa 
formula,  come  sappiamo,  ritorna  nel  fr.  65  §  5  D.  xvii.  2  :  si  intersit 
societati  non  dirimi  societatem.  E  piu  vivamente  ancora  quel  con- 
cetto e  accentuate  nel  fr.  10  pr.  D.  xxxix.  3.:  iniquum  enim  visum 
est  voluntatem  unius  ex  modica  forte  portiuncula  dominii  prae- 
iudicium  sociis  facer  e.  Che  eresia  giuridica  e  mai  questa?  Colui 
che  ha  parte  nella  comunione,  e  sia  una  minima  parte,  ha  diritto 
di  far  valere  la  sua  volonta  come  gli  altri,  perche  la  sua  posizione 
giuridica  e  pari  a  quella  degli  altri.  Cosl  ragionava  la  giuri- 
sprudenza  aurea.  Ma  nell'  inciso  giustinianeo  si  da  un  gran  rilievo 

donatio  Flavii  Syntrophi  del  II  o  in  sec.  p.  C.  (Bruns-Gradenwitz,  n.  1 39,  p. 
337)  :  et  &  quis  ibi  inhabitare  voluerit  ex  communi  omnium  consensu 
maiorisve  partis  eorum  qui  vivent^  id  ei  liceat.  Naturalmente  il  potere  con- 
ferito  alia  maggioranza  non  ha  qui  un  valore  speciale,  perche  si  tratta  di  una 
condizione  espressa  dal  disponente,  e  nulla  si  oppone,  inoltre,  alia  validita  di 
una  tale  convenzione  tra  condomini  che  sia  diretta  a  regolare  il  godimento  o 
P  amministrazione  della  cosa  comune.  Nel  documento  citato  si  tratta  in 
realta  di  condominio  ;  perch&  se  la  mancipatio  degli  orti  fu  fatta  ad  un  liberto, 
egli  deve  comunicarli  a  tutti  i  conliberti,  e  tutti  insieme  devono  godere  del 
reddito  dei  beni,  che  sara  impiegato  per  il  culto  della  tomba  del  disponente, 
nei  giorni  designati. 


112  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

alia  utilita  ed  alia  considerazione  dei  maggiori  interessati,  e  quindi 
la  prevalenza  a  coloro  che  rappresentano  la  parte  maggiore  ;  il  quale 
interesse  non  deve  essere  paralizzato,  si  dice,  da  colui  che  ha  nella 
comunione  una  modica  porzioncella.  Nella  frase  stessa  usata  dal 
legislatore,  P  interesse  del  singolo,  e  per  giunta  minore  al  confronto, 
scade  fino  al  dispregio.  Naturalmente.  Perche  nella  Compilazione 
di  Giustiniano  P  idea  dell'  interesse  sociale,  del  vantaggio  dei  piu, 
considerate  sempre  in  modo  obbiettivo,  irrompe  su  ogni  angolo,  e 
si  diffonde  come  un  getto  di  sole  vivo.  E  per  cio  nella  comunione 
e  nella  societa  alia  volonta  ed  agli  interessi  dei  singoli  debbono 
sempre  prevalere  la  volonta  della  maggioranza,  e  P  utilita  sociale. 
Cosl  nelP  eredita  :  la  maior  pars  degli  eredi  ha  diritto  di  chiedere 
il  deposito  fatto  dal  loro  autore,  qualunque  esso  sia  ;  e  la  maggio- 
ranza si  determina  ex  magnitudine  portionum  hereditariarum} 

E  la  maggioranza  che  in  caso  di  conflitto  sceglie,  per  votazione, 
il  depositario  delle  cautiones  hereditariae :  fr.  5  D.  x.  2  \yel 
suffragio\?  E,  cosa  veramente  sorprendente,  alia  maggioranza  dei 
coeredi  si  attribuisce  la  facolta  di  alienare  validamente  P  intera  cosa 
ereditaria : 

fr.  44  §  2  D.  x.  2.  Si  coheredes  absente  uno  coherede  rem  ven- 
diderunt  et  in  ea  re  dolo  malo  fecerunt,  quo  plus  ad  eos  perveniret 
[vel  familiae  erciscundae  iudicio  praestabunt  ei  qui  abfuit  vel  heredi- 
tatis  petitione]. 

L'  interpolazione  si  manifesta  nel  praestare  senza  oggetto ; 
dacche  la  correzione  del  Mo.  e  arbitraria.  Or  se  P  assente,  come 
dice  il  testo,  ha  soltanto  le  azioni  contro  i  coeredi,  ci6  significa  che 
P  alienazione  e  considerata  efficace  per  la  cosa  intera.  Vedi  contro 
fr.  64  §  4  D.  xxi.  2,  esaminato  piu  sopra  a  p.  42,  e  principalmente 
poi  il  fr.  54  D.  x.  2  di  Nerazio,  che  esclude  il  iud.  fam.  ere.  rispetto 
al  fondo  venduto  da  parte  di  alcuni  eredi. 


V.    LA    STRUTTURA    DELLA    COMMUN1O    NEL    DIRITTO 
GIUSTINIANEO 

71.  La  ricostruzione  dommatica  di  un  istituto  di  dritto  pre- 
suppone  ferma  conoscenza  dei  principii  di  fondo  del  medesimo  e 

1  fr.  14  pr.  D.  xvi.  3. 

2  L3  interpolazione  nel  testo  e  forse  piu  estesa. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  113 

delle  norme  particolari ;  e  quindi  la  determinazione  precisa  del  loro 
valore. 

Nella  legislazione  di  Giustiniano  esistono,  come  si  e  visto,  due 
ordini  di  principii  riguardo  alia  comunione ;  e  di  conseguenza 
molte  disposiztoni  particolari  sono  in  perfetta  opposizione  tra  loro. 

Qui  dunque  bisogna  intendersi  preliminarmente  sui  criterii  che 
T  interprete  deve  seguire  nella  ricostruzione  dello  istituto.  Ed  io 
suppongo  che  per  questo  rispetto  P  accordo  non  dovrebbe  incon- 
trare  ostacolo  di  sorta ;  avvegnache  tutti  debbono  consentire  in 
ci6 :  che  ove  la  compilazione  di  Giustiniano  si  voglia  considerare 
come  un  Codice,  per  ricavarne  i  principii  fondamentali  dei  singoli 
istituti,  per  1*  applicazione  pratica  o  per  la  trattazione  scientifica,  e 
sempre  necessario  procedere  ad  un  confronto  tra  i  testi  contrad- 
dittorii,  dar  la  prevalenza  ai  concetti  affermati  dal  legislatore  nella 
sua  opera,  lasciando  cadere  poi  quegl'  altri  che  nel  corpo  della 
Compilazione  figurano  come  una  sopravvivenza  storica,  e  perci6 
come  punti  morti  nell'  organismo  del  nuovo  diritto. 

Siffatto  metodo  e  imposto  dalla  natura  stessa  dell'  opera 
legislativa,  formata  in  una  maniera  cosl  singolare. 

La  Glossa  adoper6,  se  guardiamo  i  risultati,  un  processo  identico. 
Essa,  come  e  noto,  mise  alia  luce  tutto  il  contenuto  del  Corpus 
Juris,  e  lo  doto  di  nuova  forza,  ma  secondo  1'  indole  dei  tempi  giunse 
a  quel  risultato  mediante  distinzioni,  conciliazioni  ed  artifici  molti, 
considerati  nei  singoli  casi  come  idonei  a  superare  le  difficolta  dei 
testi  contraddittori.  Oggi  noi  arriviamo  piu  direttamente  e  con 
maggior  sicurezza  alia  meta,  merce  la  critica  storica. 

II  metodo  e  quindi  diverso,  ma  i  risultamenti  debbono  pareg- 
giarsi,  come  vedremo  tosto  nel  c.  iii.  della  presente  trattazione. 

72.  Or  applicando  cotali  criterii  nello  studio  della  communio, 
noi  siamo  costretti  a  tagliar  fuori  avanti  tutto  il  principio  di  fondo, 
quale  era  rappresentato  dai  giuristi  classici,  e  che  appare  in  tutta 
la  sua  energia  nella  formulazione  di  Sabino,  che  e  stata  gia  larga- 
mente  discussa. 

Secondo  i  giuristi  ciascuno  dei  socii  ha  pieno  il  diritto  di  pro- 
prieta  sulla  cosa  comune.  E  perci6  i  singoli  hanno  una  posizione 
di  dritto  perfettamente  uguale ;  sono  liberi  ed  indipendenti ;  e  per 
consequenza  la  volonta  di  ciascuno  deve  valere  quanto  la  volonta 
degli  altri.  Da'cic-  deriva  necessariamente  la  regola  :  che  colui  che 
vieta  e  poziore ;  effetto  inevitabile  per  il  concorso  di  dritti  che 

I 


ii4  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

hanno  forza  pari.  La  comunione  pertanto  e  un  istituto  senza  di- 
sciplina,  che  non  sopporta  norme  regolatrici,  le  quali  sarebbero  in 
contrasto  col  dritto  assoluto  dei  titolari  della  proprieta.  Quando 
il  disaccordo  si  manifesta  non  v'  e  altro  rimedio  che  la  divisione. 

Or  e  certo  che  tutta  questa  struttura  della  communio  fu  distrutta 
da  Giustiniano,  perche  i  testi  che  contenevano  appunto  i  principii  e 
le  conseguenze  or  esposti  furono  annullati  direttamente  dalle  nuove 
aggiunte  legislative,  applicate  giusto  in  tutti  i  passi  fondamentali 
dei  diversi  titoli  del  Digesto.  E  sono  queste  aggiunte  e  quelle 
riforme  che  debbono  apprestare  all'  interprete  gli  elementi  precipui 
per  la  ricostruzione  del  nuovo  istituto ;  perche,  come  bene  osservo 
il  Lenel,1  una  interpolazione,  ed  a  maggior  ragione  una  serie  di 
interpolazioni,  costituiscono  sempre  un  «  deliberate  atto  legislative  » 
ed  il  risultato  als  bewusster  Gesetzgebungsakt  lega  1'  interprete 
con  la  forza  di  un  ordine. 

Ed  abbracciando  per  cio  in  una  volta,  in  una  sintesi  generale, 
tutte  quelle  riforme  dianzi  discusse,  la  struttura  della  communio 
risulta  nella  legislazione  di  Giustiniano  come  segue. 

73.  La  comunione  del  diritto  giustinianeo  e  disciplinata  da 
norme  generali,  le  quali  elisero  in  primo  luogo  quella  indipendenza 
che  i  socii  avevano  in  virtu  della  loro  posizione  pari,  secondo  il 
diritto  quiritario  del  dominio. 

Ed  accertata  questa  nozione  fondamentale  e  generalissima,  il 
nuovo  schema  dell'  istituto  si  disegna  come  appresso. 

(1)  La  regola  centrale  di  tutto  1'  istituto  classico  formulata  da 
Sabino,  che  vietava  a  ciascun  socio  qualsiasi  disposizione  materiale 
della  cosa,  fu  essenzialmente  abolita. 

(2)  Ogni  condomino  pu6  ora,  positivamente,  compiere  atti  dis- 
positivi  che  si  esplicano  sulla  cosa,  anche  contro  la  volonta  degli 
altri ;  esigendosi  soltanto  che  gli  atti  di  disposizione  o  le  opere  siano 
di  vantaggio  alia  collettivita. 

(3)  Di  conseguenza,  lo  ius  prohibendi,  rinnegato  come  privata 
difesa,  fu  ammesso  in  via  giudiziaria  entro  certi  limiti  soltanto  ;  e 
cioe  prima  dell'  inizio  delle  opere  o  per  rimuovere  quelle  che  fossero 
riconosciute  pregiudizievoli  all'  interesse  della  comunione. 

(4)  I  condomini  hanno  rispetto  alia  cosa  una  posizione  pari,  come 
prima  ;  ma  essi  nori  sono  piu  indipendenti  e  sciolti,  sibbene  collegati 
tra  loro  ed  organizzati  in  un  gruppo  collettivo. 

1  Archil)  f.  civ.  Praxis^  vol.  Ixxviii.  p.  362. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprietct  115 

(5)  L'  organizzazione  dei  socii  si  manifesta  nel  diritto  che  spetta 
alia  maggioranza  di  essi  di  decidere  intorno  al  godimento,  alia  con- 
servazione  ed  alia  destinazione  della   cosa.      La  maggioranza  si 
determina  anche  qui  mediante  il  compute  del  maggior  valore  delle 
quote  rappresentate  dai  singoli  socii. 

(6)  A  tutelare  le  facolta  attribuite  ai  singoli  compartecipi  servono 
ora  tutte  le  azioni  che  di  norma  competono  al  domino  solitario,  e 
che  possono   esperirsi  tra   socii  vicendevolmente  ;   e  ci6   sia   per 
costringere  gli  altri  a  prestare  il  loro  consenso  per  1'  esecuzione  di 
un'  opera  o  1*  attuazione  di  qualsiasi  atto  dispositivo,  sia  per  im- 
pedire  nuove  opere  ovvero  ottenere  la  rimozione  di  quelle  fatte,  sia 
per  conseguire  indennizzo  per  il  danno  arrecato  da  uno  alia  cosa 
comune  ;  ed  infine  per  la  partizione  di  spese  e  utili. 

(7)  II  iud.  communi  dividundo  pu6  esperirsi  durante  la  comu- 
nione,  per  far  valere  tutte  le  ragioni  di  sopra  indicate.     Come  tale 
il  indicium  c.  d.  pu6  designarsi  quale  un  mezzo  generale  e  proprio 
a  tutela  dei  diritti  dei  condomini ;  F  azione  per  antonomasia  che 
regola  la  vita  ed  il  buon  andamento  della  comunione  in  qualsiasi 
evenienza.     Ma  tutte  le  altre  azioni  speciali,  di  cui  si  disse  (6),  con- 
corrono,  a  scelta  dell'  interessato,  per  ovviare  o  reprimere  abusi, 
danni,  immissioni,  etcc.  a  seconda  i  particolari  presupposti  richiesti 
per  F  esercizio  delle  medesime. 

Tutte  queste  proposizioni  nel  loro  insieme  costituiscono  la 
nuova  struttura  della  communio  del  diritto  giustinianeo ;  esse  non 
esigono  alcuna  illustrazione  e  nemmeno  citazioni  di  testi ;  perche  si 
appoggiano,  in  tutti  i  particolari,  sulla  dimostrazione  che  precede. 

74.  Ma  se  le  aggiunte  e  gF  incisi  giustinianei  piu  sbalestrati  e 
finora  deserti  acquistano  nella  presente  trattazione  un  carattere  di 
unita  cosl  saldo,  io  chiedo,  mi  siano  consentite,  nel  chiudere  questo 
capitolo,  alcune  riflessioni  d'  indole  piu  generale. 

La  dimostrazione  fornita  ha  accertato  nel  modo  piu  sicuro  che 
la  comunione  ebbe  nel  diritto  giustinianeo  una  disciplina,  nel  senso 
piu  particolare  che  i  socii  sono  ormai  reciprocamente  legati  da  un 
ordinamento  che  viene  dalla  legge,  e  che  deve  in  ogni  caso  attuarsi, 
anche  contro  la  volonta  dei  compartecipi.  Ma  caratteristico  e 
nel  contempo  insigne  e  il  pensiero  centrale  che  anima  tutta  quella 
nuova  disciplina,  e  che  e  costituito  dalla  utilita  collettiva  che  deve 
attuarsi  in  ogni  caso,  senza  considerazione  degli  interessi  dei  singoli. 


ii6  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

E  questo  pensiero,  inciso  fortemente  in  tutte  le  norme,  ebbe  la 
potenza  di  soppiantare  tutte  le  regole  del  diritto  classico  in  materia 
di  comunione :  colpl  anzitutto  >la  concezione  stessa  del  dominio 
nella  sua  radice  piu  vigorosa,  ed  annient6  cosl  la  indipendenza  dei 
singoli  socii ;  e  per  conseguenza  F  arbitrio,  la  onnipotenza  della 
volonta,  e  lo  ius  prohibendi,  affermazione  virile  sempre  pronta  del 
diritto  individuale.  Ora,  invece,  F  interesse  sociale  deve  in  ogni 
caso  prevalere.  La  volonta  della  maggioranza  annulla  quella  dei 
singoli  socii.  In  caso  di  dissenso  o  di  opposizione  materiale  ha 
luogo  la  coazione  giudiziaria  ;  qualunque  ne  sia  la  causa ;  si  mani- 
festi  cio6  per  il  godimento  della  cosa,  per  le  opere  conservative 
ovvero  per  innovazioni  sulla  cosa  comune.  In  proposito  non  vi  ha 
limite  alcuno  nei  testi,  come  pretese  la  Glossa,1  e  non  occorre  per 
ci6  distinguere  tra  atti  dispositivi  riguardanti  F  uso  normale  della 
cosa  e  altri  che  importerebbero  innovazioni. 

E  cosi,  io  dico,  nel  diritto  giustinianeo  la  comunione  dei  beni, 
comunque  derivata,  ebbe  un  assetto  del  tutto  nuovo  e  diametral- 
mente  opposto  a  quello  che  aveva  nelle  opere  dei  giureconsulti. 
E  pertanto  su  questo  punto  abbiamo  elementi  nuovi  che  ci  inducono 
a  modificare  le  idee  e  le  conoscenze  ritenute  finora  come  verita 
infallibili.  E  cio  va  bene. 

75.  Ma  lo  scopo  piu  essenziale  di  questo  risultato  andrebbe  per- 
duto,  in  gran  parte,  se  noi  si  tralasciasse  una  ulteriore  indagine,  onde 
porre  in  evidenza  le  forze  che  hanno  determinato  trasformazioni 
cosl  essenziali,  che  appaiono  d'  un  tratto  nelF  opera  legislativa, 
travolgendo  tutto  un  sistema  di  diritto,  che  aveva  radici  profonde  e, 
sovratutto,  una  grande  perfezione  e  proporzione  in  tutti  i  particolari, 
e   lo   splendore  e  la  dignita  che  i  giureconsulti  avevano  saputo 
conferirgli  nella  trattazione.     Quelle  forze  dissolventi  di  un'  opera 
cotanto  insigne  dovevano  per  ci6  essere  irresistibili ;   energie  vive  e 
possenti  nel  tempo  in  cui  la  legislazione  fu  compiuta. 

76.  E  F  indagine  si  rende  piu  attraente  ed  ansiosa  quando  subito  ci 
accorgiamo   che   un  ricollegamento  delle  riforme   giustinianee   al 
diritto  greco,  considerato  pure  nella  sua  ultima  fase  del   periodo 
bizantino,  non  e  possibile  in  questo  punto.     Infatti  il  condominio, 
quale  ci  si  rivela  nei  documenti  greco-egizii,  ha  la  struttura  ferma 
di  una  proprieta  divisa  tra  i  titolari,2   che   si   manifesta   in   ogni 

1  Cfr.  c.  iii. 

2  Cfr.  Weiss,  Archiv  f.  Papyr.  iv.  p.  353  e  seg. 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  117 

direzione  ;  e  cioe  nell'  assenza  del  t'us  adcrescendi  tra  condomini,1 
nella  facolta  di  disposizione  giuridica  che  compete  ad  ognuno  senza 
il  concorso  degli  altri 2 ;  nelle  singole  denunzie  catastali  e  nei  libri 
catastali,  dove  ciascun  comproprietario  figura  iscritto  per  la  sua 
parte  anche  infinitesimale ;  nella  obbligazione  parziale  e  nori 
solidale  di  ognuno  per  1'  imposta.3 

Un  condominio  che  ha  tutte  queste  linee  diritte  e  semplici 
si  raffigura,  perci6,  come  una  comproprieta  parziale  su  di  una 
stessa  cosa,  che  non  ammette  legami  di  sorta  e  reciproca 
dipendenza. 

E  se  nessuna  traccia  si  rinviene  nel  diritto  greco  degli  ordina- 
menti  giustinianei  in  questa  materia ;  e  nessun  possibile  nesso  pu6 
esistere  tra  quelle  riforme  ed  i  diritti  provinciali  che  avevano  subita 
influenza  ellenica,  bisogna  rivolgersi  altrove.  Dal  nulla,  nulla  pu6 
divenire. 

77.  Ma  e  sufficiente  il  semplice  confronto  dei  due  sistemi,  il  classico 
ed  il  giustinianeo,  per  stabilire  nella  maniera  piu  semplice  il  nesso 
storico,  ed  insieme  la  energia  che  apport6  un  cosl  profondo  muta- 
mento  in  questa  materia. 

L'  istituto  romano,  come  sappiamo,  traeva  la  sua  struttura  dal- 
F  ordinamento  prettamente  individualistico  della  proprieta.  Per  ci6 
F  autonomia  individuate  nel  sistema  del  diritto  privato  non  si  piega 
e  non  si  arresta  ne  davanti  alia  posizione  pari  o  alia  liberta  degli  altri, 
ne  davanti  agli  interessi  collettivi ;  perche  il  principio  fondamentale 
e  F  individuo,  F  affermazione  della  propria  volonta,  della  propria 
indipendenza,  che  contiene  in  se  F  anarchia.  In  contrasto  F  istituto 
giustinianeo  e  regolato  in  conformita  della  piu  viva  considerazione 
degli  interessi  sociali ;  e  tutto  compenetrato  dal  principio  etico,  che 
ove  gli  uomini  s'  incontrino  in  un  comune  interesse,  la  non  vi  e 
ragione  di  lotta,  ma  ragione  permanente  di  cooperazione.4  Le 
conseguenze  sono  immediate :  F  interesse  individuale,  F  arbitrio,  la 
indipendenza  dei  singoli  sono  annullati,  irremissibilmente. 

E  questo  principio  di  socialita  rinvigorito  e  diffuso  soltanto 
dalla  dottrina  cristiana,  divenne  coscienza  popolare  e  si  tradusse 
in  norme  giuridiche  nella  prima  codificazione  dell'  epoca  cristiana. 

1  Cfr.  Mitteis,  Archiv  f.  Papyr.  iii.  p.  253  ;  e  Reichsrecht,  p.  386. 

2  Cfr.  Wenger,  Gott.  g.  Anz.  1907,  p.  291  ;  e  Weiss,  /.  c.  p.  358. 
8  Weiss,  L  c.  p.  356. 

4  Riccobono,  Rivista  di  diritto  civile^  vol.  iii.  p.  52. 


u8  S.  Riccobono  [iv 

78.  Cosl  il  divenire  del  diritto  si  rende  visibile  ed  appare 
naturale,  come  il  prodotto  di  quella  specie  d'  atmosfera  in  cui  la 
legislazione  fu  compiuta,  e  si  ricollega  a  tutte  quelle  forze  vive  del 
tempo.  Ne  le  riforme  poste  qui  in  luce  possono  essere  isolate. 
Perche,  in  realta,  la  penetrazione  di  quell'  idea  fondamentale  della 
solidarieta  umana  si  manifesta  in  tutto  il  campo  del  diritto  privato, 
e  piu  energicamente  nell'  istituto  della  proprieta,  che  ne  esce  svigorito 
nella  sua  complessione,  per  via  di  limitazioni  infinite,  d'  ogni  ordine, 
dirette  sempre  a  soddisfare  esigenze  sociali,  ad  attuare  il  principle 
che  la  proprieta  deve  per  quanto  e  possibile  essere  utile  ai  piu, 
e  contribuire  nella  maggiore  misura  al  benessere  sociale.1  Nel 
condominio  1'  applicazione  di  questi  nuovi  ideali  era  soltanto  piu 
ovvia  edjmmediata.  E  nel  condominio,  come  fu  ordinato  da 
Giustiniano,  si  mostra  gagliardo  quel  vivo  e  comune  sentimento  di 
cooperazione  e  di  fratellanza,  che  doveva  prontamente  trasformare 
T  istituto  nella  sua  struttura  e  nelle  norme  particolari.  Alia 
volonta  libera  ed  indipendente  dei  singoli  fu,  per  cio,  sostituita 
1'  utilita  sociale  che  e  ora  il  centre  attivo  che  da  vita  a  questa  figura 
di  diritto  e  la  disciplina  in  ogni  sua  parte. 

La  spiegazione  ed  il  nesso  sono  quindi  semplici,  piu  che  si 
possa  richiedere ;  non  potendosi  mettere  in  dubbio  che  quel 
principio  della  utilita  generale,  quei  sentimenti  di  solidarieta 
umana  furono  diffusi  e  resi  attivi  nel  mondo  dalla  dottrina 
cristiana ;  e  che  soltanto  essi  poterono  via  via  travolgere  tutto  il 
sistema  individualistico  romano,  e  fin  da  principio  comprimerlo 
nell'  opera  legislativa,  quanto  alle  sue  manifestazioni  piu  spietate. 

Chi  non  sa  vedere  tale  ricollegamento  nella  materia  che  ci 
occupa,  dovrebbe  mostrare,  positivamente,  che  sul  cadere  del 
mondo  antico  altre  forze  operarono  un  rivolgimento,  cosl  essenziale 
nella  concezione  della  vita  e  negli  ordinamenti  giuridici. 

Certo  le  difficolta  piu  gravi  si  riscontrano  quando  noi  ci  facciamo 
a  valutare  i  fattori  morali  della  civilta,  perche  non  si  possono 
misurare  n&  pesare,  non  hanno  corpo,  sono  niente ;  e  pur  sono 
tutto.  Fattori  prodigiosi,  invisibili  che  giorno  per  giorno  creano 
situazioni  nuove,  portano  argomentazioni  definitive,  insinuano  negli 
uomini  sentimenti  che  divengono  forze  vive  nel  campo  dell'  azione, 
per  cui  visibilmente  ne  appare  spostato  il  corso  della  civilta.2 

1  Riccobono,  Rivista  di  dir.  civ.  iii.  p.  54. 

2  Per  cio  non   posso  consentire  nella  spiegazione  che  in  deffinitivo  da  il 


iv]  Communio  e  Comproprieta  119 

Ed  ora  potremo  meglio  valutare  e  stabilire  in  quale  misura 
la  legislazione  di  Giustiniano  influl  sulla  formazione  del,  diritto 
comune,  ed  in  particolare  dell'  istituto  della  comunione,  che  e 
argomento  della  trattazione.1 

S.  RlCCOBONO. 


Lenel  (Holtzendorff Js  Enc.  p.  375)  di  quelle  tendenze  filantropiche  che  si 
mostrano  nella  legislazione  da  Costantino  in  poi,  e  particolarmente  in  quella 
di  Giustiniano.  II  Maestro  e  disposto  ad  ammettere  I3  influenza  cristiana, 
particolarmente  rispetto  alia  protezione  dei  deboli,  in  largo  senso,  al  divieto 
della  difesa  privata,  al  favore  per  la  beneficenza.  E  tutto  ci6  non  sarebbe 
poco ;  perche  se  si  ammette  1'  influsso  di  quelle  idee  cosi  generali  nel- 
P  opera  legislativa,  esse  dovevano  agire  come  un  fermento  in  tutta  la  materia 
del  diritto  privato.  Ma  qui  non  importa  discutere  i  limiti ;  dacche  il  Lenel 
poi  inclina  a  ricondurre  tutte  le  manifestazioni  accennate  «  a  quella  tendenza 
propria  al  despotismo  di  mostrarsi  generoso  con  la  borsa  di  altri  ».  Or  questa 
spiegazione,  dico,  mi  sembra  esteriore.  Perch£  in  verita  nel  corso  del  diritto 
possono  in  dati  momenti  manifestarsi  direzioni  o  deviazioni  speciali,  determinate 
da  forze  e  tendenze  precarie ;  ma  che  necessariamente  si  irrigidiscono  e 
si  annullano  col  cessare  della  causa.  Se  gli  effetti,  invece,  sono  permanent], 
e  sempre  piu  rigogliosi,  come  e  nel  nostro  caso,  tutte  quelle  riforme  debbono 
aver  radici  piu  profonde  e  vive,  nel  sentimento  comune  degli  uomini.  E  si 
sa  che  quell'  idea  cristiana  della  fratellanza,  che  viene  qui  particolarmente  in 
considerazione,  costitul  appunto  il  fulcro  di  tutta  la  civilta  nuova,  in  contrasto 
aperto  per  questo  riguardo,  con  quella  del  mondo  antico. 

1  La  trattazione  ha  preso  uno  sviluppo  cosi  esteso  quale  io  non  supponevo 
da  principio,  e  che  non  pu6  essere  oltre  tollerato  in  questo  luogo.  Mi  riserbo 
percio  di  pubblicare  a  parte  la  continuazione  (c.  iii.  Dalla  Glossa  alle  legis- 
lazioni  moderne  e  c.  iv.  La  dottrina  dal  sec.  xvi  al  sec.  xx)  che  sara  esposta 
oralmente  al  Congresso. 


V 

ZUR  GESCHICHTE   DER   HEREDIS 
INSTITUTIO 

UBER  das  Wesen  der  romischen  Erbfolge  und  folgeweise  auch  der 
romischen  Erbeinsetzung  herrscht  bekanntlich  Streit.  Der  rein 
vermogensrechtlichen  Auffassung  beider  steht  eine  familienrecht- 
liche  gegeniiber,  die  in  dem  heres  der  Urzeit  einen  Nachfolger  in 
der  Hausherrschaft  erblickt1  und  sich  in  Bezug  auf  die  heredis 
institutio  bei  manchen  Schriftstellern  zu  der  bestimmten  Hypothese 
verdichtet,  dass  diese  aus  einer  urspriinglichen  Adoption  hervor- 
gegangen  sei,2  ja  in  ihrer  altesten  Gestalt  noch  selbst  als  eine  — 
von  der  Arrogation  verschiedene  —  adoptio  in  hereditatem  gedacht 
werden  miisse.3  Dabei  besteht  wieder  Meinungsverschiedenheit 
dariiber,  ob  die  Loslosung  der  Erbeinsetzung  von  der  Adoption 
im  Recht  der  zwolf  Tafeln  bereits  vollzogen  sei  oder  nicht.4 

In  diesem  Widerstreit  der  Meinungen  ist  eine  Vorfrage  nicht 
geniigend  erwogen  worden,  die  m.  E.  der  Erorterung  recht 
sehr  bedarf :  die  Frage  nach  dem  Alter  der  testamentarischen 
Erbeinsetzung  iiberhaupt.  Man  halt  es  eben  sehr  allgemein  fur 
selbstverstandlich,  dass  die  heredis  institutio  bereits  dem  Rechte 

1  Scialoja,  Bullett.  iii.  176  f.  ;    Bonfante,  Bullett.  iv.  97  f.,  Istitt  511  f .  ; 
Costa,  Storia  del  dir.  rom.  priv.  462  f.     Auch  Mitteis,  rom.  Privatr.  i.  93  f., 
und  v.  Mayr,  rom.  R.  Gesch.  i.2  91  f.,  betonen  die  familienrechtliche  Grundlage 
der  romischen  Universalsukzession. 

2  Cans,  das  Erbrecht  in  weltgeschichtl.  Entivicklung   (1825)    ii.   49   f., 
Schulin,  d.  griech.    Testament  -vergl.  mit  dem  rom.  (1882)   50  f.,  Lehrb.  d. 
Gesch.  d.  r.  R.  458  ;  Lambert,  La  Tradition  rom.  sur  la  succession  des  formes 
du  testament  (1901)  ;  Appleton,  Le  Test.  rom.  (1903)  61  f.  ;  Sohm,  Institute 
721  ;  Perozzi,  Istit.  ii.  359  f. 

8  So  bestimmt  Lambert,  a.  a.  O. 

4  In  ersterem  Sinn  Appleton,  in  letzterem  Lambert,  a.  a.  O. 

120 


v]  Romisches  Testament  121 

der  zwolf  Tafeln  angehore,  dass  der  Satz  heredis  institutio  est 
caput  et  fundamentum  testamenti  so  alt  sei  wie  das  romische 
Testament  selber.1  Ganz  unbestritten  ist  freilich  diese  Meinung 
schon  bisher  nicht  geblieben.  In  einer  1886  veroffentlichten 
Abhandlung  spricht  Cuq  dem  altromischen  Testament  die  Erbein- 
setzung  zwar  nicht  geradezu  ab,  aber  er  lehrt  doch,  dass  der  heres 
extraneus  „  ne  diffe"rait  alors  du  le"gataire  que  par  l'e"tendue  de  ses 
droits."2  Weiter  ging  Ehrlich  in  einem  1903  vor  dem  historischen 
Kongress  in  Rom  gehaltenen  Vortrag.3  Das  alteste  Testament 
war  nach  ihm  ein  reines  Legatentestament.  Allerdings  nimmt  er 
an,  dass  es  „  in  Rom  schon  in  sehr  friiher  Zeit  bei  der  testamenta- 
rischen  Erbfolge  neben  Legataren  auch  heredes  gegeben  habe "; 
diese  heredes  waren  aber  nach  ihm  die  gesetzlichen  Erben,  nicht 
beliebige  heredes  institute  Ebenso  findet  sich  bei  Binder 
(die  Plebs,  1909,  S.  353)  die  Ausserung,  dass  „  erst  das  jiingere 
Manzipationstestament  ein  letztwilliges  Erbeinsetzungsgeschaft 
im  Sinne  des  klassischen  romischen  Rechts  gewesen  sein  kann." 
Im  folgenden  soil  die  Frage  nach  dem  Inhalt  des  altromischen 
Testaments  einer  erneuten  Priifung  unterzogen  werden :  hat  das 
Recht  der  zwolf  Tafeln  eine  heredis  institutio  gekannt  ?  war 
nicht  der  einzige  Weg,  auf  dem  sich  damals  ein  Erblasser  klinstlich 
einen  Universalsukzessor  zu  scha.ffen  vermochte,  der  allbekannte 
der  Arrogation  ? 

Bei  dieser  Untersuchung  nehme  ich  zwei  Thesen  als  feststehend 
an,  die,  obwohl  bestritten,  doch  immer  noch  der  herrschenden 
Meinung  entsprechen.  Erstens:  dass  die  Zwolftafelgesetzgebung 
im  5.  Jahrhundert  v.  Chr.  entstanden  ist,  —  meine  Griinde  dafiir 

1  Dieser   herrschenden   Meinung   gibt   Appleton,  a.  a.  O.    86,  scharfen 
Ausdruck,  wenn  er  die  heredis  institutio  fur  „  1'essence  meme  du  testament 
k  Rome  "  erklart. 

2  NRH.  x.  542.     Wendungen,  die  Cuq  537  f.  gebraucht  („  en  presence 
de  sui  le  testament  .  .  .  ne  devait  contenir  que  des  dispositions  particulieres, 
comme    un    legs,"  „  en    Pabsence  d'heritiers   siens,   on   pouvait   le"guer  tous 
ses  biens  k  une  personne  etrangere  k  la  famille  "),  legen  den  Gedanken  nahe, 
dass-  er  fur  das  alte  Testament  die  Erbeinsetzung  auch  formell  leugne  ;  doch 
ist  dies  nach  dem  obigen  Zitat  wohl  nicht  seine  Meinung  gewesen.     Ganz 
ausdriicklich  spricht  er  sich  fur  das  Vorhandensein  der  Erbeinsetzung  schon 
vor  den  zwolf  Tafeln  in  seinen  Instit.  jurid.'2'  i.    124  aus;    nur  beschrankt  er 
ihre  Mbglichkeit  auch  hier  auf  den  Fall,  dass  keine  sui  vorhanden  sind. 

8  Z.  f.  vgl.  Rechtswiss.  xvii.  99  f. 
4  a.  a.  O.  101  f. 


122  O.  Lenel  [v 

habe  ich  anderwarts  ausgefiihrt.1  Zweitens:  dass  das  Testament 
der  zwolf  Tafeln  noch  das  Komitialtestament  war ; 2  daflir  ist  mir 
schon  entscheidend  der  Umstand,  dass  den  Romern  schwerlich 
eine  Erinnerung  an  das  Komitialtestament  geblieben  sein  wiirde, 
wenn  es  bereits  in  so  grauer  Vorzeit  aus  der  Anwendung 
verschwunden  ware.  Ein  naheres  Eingehen  auf  diese  Thesen  ist 
im  Zusammenhang  dieses  Vortrags  nicht  moglich,  wohl  auch 
nicht  notig. 

Wer  eine  Frage,  wie  die  vorliegende,  zu  beantworten  versucht, 
wird  gut  tun,  nicht  von  den  Erorterungen  der  klassischen  Juristen 
auszugehen,  die  durch  eine  vielhundertjahrige  Entwicklung  von 
den  zwolf  Tafeln  geschieden  sind,  sondern  —  ohne  auf  der  anderen 
Seite  diese  Erorterungen  zu  ignorieren  —  von  dem  liberlieferten 
Texte  des  Gesetzes  selbst.  Jedem  aufmerksamen  Leser  dieses 
Textes  muss  es  auffallen,  dass  das  Gesetz  das  Wort  heres  nur  in 
Bezug  auf  den  suus  heres  verwendet  zu  haben  scheint,  und  dass  in 
eben  dem  Satze,  wo  dies  geschieht,  der  proximus  adgnatus  nicht 
durch  ein  heres  esto,  sondern  mit  den  Worten  familiam  habeto 
berufen  wird.  Man  hat  daraus  schliessen  wollen,  dass  der  Name 
heres  damals  nur  fur  den  suus  heres  gebraucht  und  auf  den 
sukzedierenden  Agnaten  nicht  angewendet  worden  sei.3  Es  wird 
eine  Zeit  gegeben  haben,  fur  die  dies  zutrifft ;  fur  die  zwolf  Tafeln 
ist  mir  der  Schluss  bedenklich.  Umgekehrt :  wenn  es  keine 
anderen  heredes  gab,  als  die  sui  heredes^  wozu  dann  die  Wendung 
cut  suus  heres  nee  escif*  Mir  scheint  die  Beifiigung  des  Wortes 
suus  an  dieser  Stelle  kaum  anders  zu  erklaren,  als  durch  die 
Annahme,  dass  es  eben  schon  damals  auch  extranet  heredes  gab. 
Aber  allerdings  verlangt  die  beriihrte  Terminologie  eine  Erklarung. 
Sollte  man  befiirchtet  haben,  durch  ein  gesetzliches  heres  esto 
den  Agnaten  zum  Zwangserben  gleich  dem  suus  zu  machen? 
Aber  dem  ware  ja  durch  Hinzufiigen  eines  si  volet >  wie  es  die 
zwolf  Tafeln  anderwarts  zu  ahnlichem  Zwecke  verwenden,  leicht 
vorzubeugen  gewesen.  Die  richtige  Erklarung  liegt  anderswo. 
Uns  Modernen  ist  der  Ausspruch  Papinians  in  D.  v.  3,.  50 
pr.  hereditas  etiam  sine  ullo  corpore  iuris  intellectum  habet  in 

1  ZRG.  xxxix.  498  f.,  Holtzendorff-Kohlers  Enzyclop?  1.  324  f. 

2  Vgl.  dazu  noch  Mitteis,  rom.  Privatr.  i.  82  n.  24,  und  die  dort  Angeff. 
8  Perozzi,  Istit.  ii.   362   (vgl.  356)  ,,  il  nome  di  heres  esprimeva  non  il 

solo  fatto  della  successione,  ma  anche  la  qualita  di  figlio.  "  S.  auch  Cuq 
Instit.  jurid?  i.  123. 


v]  Romisches  Testament  123 

Fleisch  und  Blut  ubergegangen.  Aber  diirfen  wir  eine  solche 
Abstraction  schon  dem  fiinften  Jahrhundert  V.  Chr.  zutrauen? 
Ich  meine,  fiir  die  naiv-sinnliche  Vorstellungsweise,  die  wir  in 
dieser  friihen  Zeit  voraussetzen  miissen,  konnte  die  hereditas  kein 
blosses  Gedankending  sein ;  den  Romern  der  zwolf  Tafeln  war  sie 
etwas  korperlich  greifbares : l  Haus  und  Hof,  Sklaven  und  Vieh. 
So  darf  man  denn  auch  die  klassischen  Begriffe  von  Delation  und 
Acquisition  der  Erbschaft  nicht  in  das  Zwolftafelrecht  versetzen. 
Diese  Begriffe  beruhen  auf  der  Vorstellung,  dass  die  hereditas  eine 
blosse  Rechtsstellung  sei,  die  dem  extraneus  vom  Gesetz  angeboten 
und  dann  von  ihm  durch  einfachen  Willensakt  erworben  werde.  1st 
aber  die  hereditas  etwas  korperliches,  so  kann  sie,  so  wenig  wie 
sonst  eine  herrenlose  Sache,  durch  eine  blosse  Willenserklarung 
erworben  werden.  Wer  vielmehr  nicht  schon  wie  der  suus  als 
Hausherr  im  Hause  sitzt,  wird  heres  nur  dadurch,  dass  er  sich  der 
familia  tatsachlich  bemachtigt,  und  eben  darum  erblickt  das 
Gesetz  seine  Aufgabe  lediglich  darin,  denjenigen  zu  bezeichnen, 
der  sich  in  Ermangelung  eines  suus  heres  der  familia  bemachtigen 
diirfe,  — familiam  habeto  ;  heres  wird  er  dann  durch  die  wirkliche 
Inbesitznahme.2  Dass  dies  in  der  Tat  die  alte  Auffassung  war, 
lasst  sich,  wie  ich  glaube,  mit  grosser  Sicherheit  erweisen.  Der 
Beweis  liegt  in  dem  Mangel  einer.  zivilen  Form  fiir  den  Antritt  der 
Intestaterbschaft.  Erwagt  man,  eine  wie  ausnahmslose  Herrschaft 
die  Form  sonst  im  alten  Zivilrecht  iibt,  so  erscheint  es  unbegreif- 
lich,  dass  sich  fiir  ein  so  ungemein  wichtiges  Geschaft  wie  den 
Erbschaftsantritt  keine  Form  ausgebildet  hatte,  wenn  man  darin 
iiberhaupt  ein  Geschaft  erblickt  hatte.  Nun  glaubt  ja  freilich 
eine  heute  weitverbreitete  Ansicht  eine  solche  Form  wirklich 
entdeckt  zu  haben,  —  in  der  cretio  namlich.?  Aber  diese  Ansicht 

1  Das  empfand  schon  ganz  richtig  Kuntze  in  seinem  Programm  Vber  die 
Erbeinsetzung  auf  bestimmte  Nachlassstucke  (1875)  9f->  nur  dass  die  Art>  wie 
er  dieser  Empfindung  Ausdruck  gibt,   durch  die  Hereinziehung  der  Begriffe 
Tauschwert  und  Gebrauchswert  Anstoss  erregen  muss.     Ganz  im  Sinne  des 
Texts  Cuq,  NRH.  x.  542  f. 

2  Wie  aber,  wenn  er  —  vielleicht  von  einem  anderen  Pratendenten  —  an 
dieser  Inbesitznahme    gehindert   wird  ?     Man  beachte,   dass  die  legis   actio 
der  hereditatis  petitio  immer  mit  einem  symbolischen  Besitzakt,  dem  vindicare, 
verbunden  ist,  und  dass  der  Gegner  gezwungen  wird,  die  Vornahme  dieses 
Besitzaktes  zu  dulden. 

3  Vgl.  u.  a.  -Karlowa,  RG.  ii.  896  und  die  dort  Angeff.  ;  Girard,  Manuel* 
871   n.  7  ;    Sohm,  Institute  698  n.  7  ;   Czyhlarz,  Institut.  §  124;    Bonfante, 


124  O.  Lend  [v 

steht  nicht  nur  mit  der  klassischen  Uberlieferung  im  Widerspruch, 
die  nur  von  testamentarischer  Festsetzung,  nichts  von  gesetzlicher 
Geltung  der  cretio  weiss,  sondern  sie  tmterstellt  auch  eine  sachlich 
unmogliche  Entwicklung.  Wenn  man  in  Testamenten  die  cretio 
festzusetzen  pflegte  —  solet  cretio  dari,  wie  Gaius  ii.  164  sagt  — ,  so 
kann  das  doch  nur  geschehen  sein,  weil  man  eine  solche  Form  fur 
den  Erbschaftsantritt  zweckmassig  fand.  Wie  vertragt  sich  damit 
die  Annahme,  dass  man  diese  selbe  zweckmassig  befundene  Form 
da,  wo  sie  kraft  rechtens  gefordert  war,  soil  haben  fallen  lassen? 
Nein :  dies  Formalgeschaft  ist  dem  alten  Rechte  fremd ;  es  ist  fur 
die  testamentarische  Erbfolge,  einerlei  einstweilen  wann,  erfunden 
worden ;  der  Erwerb  der  Intestaterbschaft  aber  fand  von  jeher 
nicht  durch  cretio^  sondern  durch  korperliche  Inbesitznahme  statt.1 
Das  adire  ist  in  seinem  ursprunglichen  Sinn  ganz  wortlich  zu 
nehmen  als  ein  Betreten  der  Erbschaftsgrundstiicke,  wie  das 
griechische  l/z/JaTeveti/  ets  T^V  ovo-tav  und  das  germanische  ,,zu  dem 
Erbe  gehen."2  Und  das  familiam  habeto  der  zwolf  Tafeln  hat 
genau  den  gleichen  Sinn,  wie  ursprlinglich  das  do  lego  des  Vin- 
dikationslegats,  dem  ja  in  der  Tat  spaterhin  ein  sumito  oder 
sibi  habeto  oder  capito  gleichgeachtet  wurde : 3  es  will  eben  jene 
Inbesitznahme  gestatten. 

Habe  ich  in  obigem  das  familiam  habeto  des  Gesetzes  richtig 
gedeutet,  so  ergeben  sich  daraus  wichtige  Folgerungen.  fur  das 
altromische  Testament.  Denn  wenn  das  Gesetz  die  Wendung 
heres  esto  deshalb  nicht  gebrauchte,  weil  man  Herr  der  korperlich 
gedachten  Erbschaft  nicht  durch  ein  blosses  Wort  des  Gesetzes 
werden  kann,  sondern  nur  durch  die  Tat,  so  scheint  es  undenkbar, 
dass  im  Testament  gerade  jene  Wendung  auch  nur  liblich, 
geschweige  denn,  dass  sie  fur  die  Giltigkeit  des  Testaments 
geradezu  vorgeschrieben  gewesen  sein  sollte.  Auch  der  Testator 
verfiigte  nicht  iiber  das  Gedankending  der  Erbschaft,  sondern  iiber 

Istit.*  488  n.  i  ;  Costa,  Storia  del  dir.  pr.  rom.  520.  Anders  Perozzi,  Istit. 
ii.  505. 

1  Damit  diirfte  auch  zusammenhangen,  dass  die  usucapio  p.  h.  nach  Gai. 
ii.  5  2  nur  zugelassen  war  in  Bezug  auf  eine  res  hereditaria,  cuius  possessionem 
heres  nondum  nactus  est.      Die  Inbesitznahme  war  der  Erwerbsakt.     In  dieser 
Beziehung  iibereinstimmend  :  Perozzi,  Istit.  ii.  505. 

2  Grimm,  Rechtsaltertiimerf  \.  659. 

3  Man  beachte,  dass  es    auch  fur   den    Erwerb    des    Vindikationslegats 
keine  Form  gab. 


v]  Romisches  Testament  125 

sein  Haus,  seinen  Hof,  seine  Sachen  iiberhaupt,  indem  er  den 
Bedachten  ermachtigte,  sie  nach  seinem  Tode  an  sich  zu  nehmen. 
Dafiir  aber  war  die  gegebene  Form  nicht  die  Erbeinsetzung,  sondern 
die  alteste l  Form  des  Legats,  das  Vindikationslegat :  das  Komitial- 
testament  war  ein  reines  Legatentestament.  Dafiir,  dass  dem  so 
war,  haben  wir  sichere  Anhaltspunkte.  Vor  allem  :  die  einzige 
Bestimmung,  die  die  zwolf  Tafeln  liber  Testamente  enthielten, 
handelt  nur  vom  Legat,  unter  welchen  BegrirT  nach  dem  alten 
Sprachgebrauch  allerdings  auch  die  tutoris  datio  gefallen  sein 
muss : 2  uti  legassit  (super  pecunia  tutelave) 3  suae  ra',  ita  ius  esto. 
Pomponius  in  einer  allbekannten  Stelle4  findet  in  diesem  Satze 
freilich  auch  die  Ermachtigung  zur  Erbeinsetzung  ausgesprochen  : 
latissima  potestas  tributa  videtur  et  heredis  instituendi  u.s.w. 
Die  Stelle,  mag  sie  nun  lediglich  Ausserung  des  Pomponius  sein 
oder  auf  den  von  ihm  kommentierten  Q.  Mucius  zuriickgehen,  ist 
als  historisches  Zeugnis  wichtig,  nicht  um  ihres  positiven  Inhalts 
willen,  —  sie  belehrt  uns  nicht  liber  den  ursprlinglichen  Sinn  des 
Satzes,  sondern  liber  den  Sinn,  den  eine  weit  spatere  interpretatio 
ihm  beilegte  — ,  wohl  aber  deshalb,  weil  sie  beweist,  dass  die  zwolf 
Tafeln  eine  die  heredis  institutio  zulassende  Bestimmung  nicht 
enthielten.  Ausgeschlossen  scheint  mir,  dass  das  Gesetz,  wenn 
ihm  neben  dem  Legat  auch  die  Erbeinsetzung  bekannt  war,  das 
fur  ersteres  formelmassig  technische  Wort  auch  fur  die  letztere 
verwendet  hatte.5  Ausgeschlossen  aber  nicht  minder  auch  der 
schon  mehrfach  laut  gewordene  Gedanke,  jener  Satz  habe  fur 
Legate,  nur  fur  Legate  (oder  auch  nur  fur  Legate  von  res  nee 
mancipi)  die  von  der  Zustimmung  der  Komitien  unabhangige 
Autonomie  des  Erblassers  proklamieren  wollen,  wahrend  fur 
Erbeinsetzungen  (oder  wenigstens  fur  die  von  Nichtintestaterben) 
jene  Zustimmung  noch  immer  erforderlich  sein  sollte.6  Ich  unter- 
suche  hier  nicht,  ob  das  Testament  Iiberhaupt  jemals  eine  der 

1  Vgl.   hierzu   die   iiberzeugenden    Ausfiihrungen  Wlassaks,    ZRG.   xliv. 
198  f. 

2  Holder,  ZRG.  xliii.  72. 

3  Die  Authentizitat  der  eingeklammerten  Worte  kann  hier  dahin  gestellt 
bleiben.      Vgl.  dazu  und  dagegen  besonders  Appleton,  Le  Test.  rom.  59  n.  i. 

4  D.  1.  16,  120;  vgl.  auch  Gai.  ii.  224. 

6  Vgl.  Mitteis,  rom.  Privatr.  i.  82  n.  24  ;  Wlassak,  ZRG.  xli.  70  n.  i, 
auch  Holder,  Beitrage,  65. 

6  Sohm,  Instit.^  722,  Cuq,  Instit.  i.2  130  f.,  und  in  anderer  Formulierung 
Mitteis,  a.  a.  O.,  Wlassak,  ZRG.  xliv.  2 1 8. 


126  O.  Lenel  [v 

Zustimmung  des  Volkes  bedurftige  lex  gewesen  ist;  undenkbar 
scheint  mir,  dass,  wenn  es  dies  war,  die  Zustimmung  zu  irgend 
einer  Zeit  fur  etwas  anderes  gefordert  gewesen  sein  kann,  als  fur 
die  Totalitat  des  letzten  Willens.  Es  ist  ja  doch  klar,  dass  es  fur 
die  Genehmigung  der  Erbeinsetzung,  wenn  eine  solche  erforderlich 
war,  nicht  hatte  gleichgiltig  sein  konnen,  ob  und  welche  Legate 
der  Erblasser  z.  B.  enterbten  oder  ubergangenen  Verwandten 
hinterliess ;  dass  es  eine  Farce  gewesen  ware,  wenn  man  fur  die 
Erbeinsetzung  Zustimmung  der  Komitien  verlangt,  den  Erblassern 
aber  gestattet  hatte,  die  institutio  durch  Legate  mehr  oder  weniger 
ihres  Inhalts  zu  berauben.1  Der  ganze  Testamentsinhalt  bildet 
vielmehr  eine  untrennbare  Einheit,  die  nur  in  ihrer  Gesamtheit 
einer  Genehmigung  des  Volkes  hatte  unterliegen  konnen. 

Fiir  die  Auffassung  des  Komitialtestaments  als  Legatentestament 
spricht  nun  aber  noch  eine  zweite  ganz  sichere  historische  Tatsache, 
die  Fassung  der  Nunkupationsformel  des  testamentum  per  aes 
et  libram,  die  allein  auf  Legate  und  zwar  Vindikationslegate 2 
zugeschnitten  war,  ita  do  ita  lego  ita  tester  itaque  vos  Quirites 
testimonium  mihi  perhibetote.  Dass  diese  Formel  zu  einem 
Erbeinsetzungstestament  nicht  passt,  wird  heute  sehr  allgemein 
anerkannt.3  Man  erklart  aber  den  Mangel  einer  Bezugnahme  auf 
die  heredis  institutio  daraus,  dass  im  alteren  testamentum  per  aes 
et  libram  derfamzlzae  emptor  selbst  heredis  loco  gewesen  sei,  sodass 
sich  die  Beschrankung  der  Formel  auf  die  Bestatigung  von  Legaten 
von  selbst  ergeben  habe.  Gewiss !  Nur  bleibt  dabei  unerklart, 
warum  man,  als  auch  die  heredis  institutio  im  Manzipationstesta- 
mentUnterkommen  fand,  nicht  jetzt  zuriickgriff  auf  die  umfassendere 
Formel,  die  die  herrschende  Meinung  notwendig  dem  Komitial- 
testament  zuschreiben  muss.  War  die  Erbeinsetzung  selbst  trotz 
Aufkommens  des  alteren  Manzipationstestaments  [nicht  in  Ver- 
gessenheit  geraten,  dann,  so  miisste  man  annehmen,  kann  man 
auch  den  auf  sie  beziiglichen  Teil  der  alten  Bestatigungsformel 
nicht  vergessen  haben.  Die  Erbeinsetzung,  wenn  sie  dem  Komitial- 
testament  eigen  war,  hatte  aber  niemals  in  Vergessenheit  geraten 

1  Dies  gilt,  wenn  gleich  in  gemindertem  Masse,  auch  dann,  wenn  man  fiir 
die  zwolf  Tafeln  nicht  voile  Legierfreiheit,  sondern,  was  ich  freilich  fiir  unbe- 
griindet  halte,  solche  nur  hinsichtlich  der  res  nee  mancipi  annimmt.     Auch 
diese  konnten  ein  recht  betrachtlicher  Bestandteil  des  Vermogens  sein. 

2  Wlassak,  a.  a.  O.  206. 

3  Vgl.  etwa  Sohm,  Instit.™  725,  Wlassak,  a.  a.  O. 


v]  Romisches  Testament  127 

konnen,  aus  dem  einfachen  Grunde  nicht,  well  das  Komitialtesta- 
ment  als  Testament  mit  Erbeinsetzung  vor  dem  blossen  Legaten- 
testament  die  wesentlichsten  Vorziige  besessen  und  sich  daher  ohne 
Zweifel  so  lange  erhalten  haben  wiirde,  bis  die  Erbeinsetzung  in 
das  Manzipationstestament  Aufnahme  fand.1  Als  dieser  letzte 
bedeutsame  Schritt  geschah,  ware  also  die  umfassendere  Formel 
nicht  nur  noch  bekannt,  sondern  in  haufigem  praktischem  Gebrauch 
gewesen  ;  alles  hatte  darauf  hingewiesen,  sie  nunmehr  auch  fur  das 
Manzipationstestament  zu  verwerten,  und  gleichwohl  hatte  man 
dies  unbegreiflicherweise  unterlassen !  Glatt  und  einfach  erklart 
sich  dagegen  das  iiberlieferte  ita  do  ita  lego>  wenn  man  mit  der 
hier  vertretenen  Anschauung  annimmt,  dass  auch  das  Komitial- 
testament  selbst  ein  blosses  Legatentestament  war  und  gerade  in 
der  iiberlieferten  Formel  seine  zutreffende  Bestatigung  fand.  Dann 
hat  eben  hier  wie  so  oft  eine  uralte  Formel  trotz  Wechsels  des 
durch  sie  zu  deckenden  Inhalts  sich  unverandert  durch  die  Jahr- 
hunderte  erhalten,  ein  redendes  Zeugnis  des  alteren  Rechtszustands. 
Wer  mit  uns  glaubt,  das  Komitialtestament  sei  ein  reines 
Legatentestament  gewesen,  steht  nun  freilich  vor  gewissen  Fragen, 
die  der  Antwort  harren. 

Wir  sind  vom  klassischen  Testament  her  gewohnt,  uns  als 
unentbehrliche  Basis  fiir  die  Legate  eine  heredis  institutio  zu 
denken.  Wenn  nun  das  alte  Testament  keihe  solche  enthielt,  wer 
figurierte  dann  als  heres  ?  wer  haftete  fiir  die  Erbschaftsschulden  ? 
etwa  der  heres  legitimus  ?  Der  Wortlaut  der  zwolf  Tafeln  fiihrt 
zur  Verneinung  der  letzteren  Frage.  Der  heres  legitimus  ist 
nur  berufen,  si  intestate  moritur,  d.  h.  in  Ermangelung  eines 
Testaments ;  der  Satz,  dass  niemand  ex  parte  testatus,  ex  parte 
intestatus  sterben  konne,  ist  allem  Anscheiri  nach  schon  Bestand- 
teil  des  altesten  Rechts.2  Dieser  Satz  nun  gilt  immer  noch  als  das 
grosse  Ratsel  des  romischen  Erbrechts,  und  man  macht  immer  neue 
Versuche,  ihm  eine  oft  mehr  oder  weniger  mystische  Erklarung 
zu  geben.  Gerade  fiir  ein  Legatentestament  aber  war  jener 
Grundsatz  das  natiirlichste  von  der  Welt.  Man  muss  sich  hier 
folgendes  klar  machen.  Ein  Testament,  zu  dem  man  die  Komitien 
bemiihte,  war  sicherlich  nicht  gedacht  als  ein  Mittel,  dem  oder 

1  Vgl.  hierzu  auch  Wlassak,  a.  a.  O.  214. 

2  A.    M.    Ehrlich,    Z.  f.   vgl.    Rswiss.    xvii.    102.       Vgl.    fiir  das  testa- 
mentum  per  aes  et  libram  auch  Schulin,  Lehrb.  d.  Gesch.  d.  r.  R.  460. 


128  O.  Lenel  [v 

jenem  ein  kleines  Andenken  zu  hinterlassen  ;  dazu  hatten  sich  die 
Komitien  sicher  auch  als  Zeuge  nicht  gebrauchen  lassen.  Es  muss 
vielmehr  gedacht  und  auch  geiibt  gewesen  sein  als  planmassige 
Verteilung  des  ganzen  Verrnogens,  als  divisio  bonorum^  bei  der 
normalerweise  nur  durch  ein  Versehen  irgend  ein  Stuck  unverteilt 
bleiben  konnte.1  Wenn  nun  der  Testator  bei  Aufstellung  eines 
solchen  Verteilungsplanes  den  Intestaterben,der  ohne  das  Testament 
alles  erhalten  hatte,  ubergangen  oder  mit  irgend  einem  einzelnen 
Stiick  bedacht  hatte,  so  war  damit  auf  das  klarste  zu  erkennen 
gegeben,  dass  er  ihn  von  der  Erbschaft  sei  es  ganz  und  gar  sei  es 
im  ubrigen  habe  ausschliessen  wollen,  und  alles  musste  daher  den 
alten  Juristen  naher  liegen,  als  dennoch  gerade  dem  Intestaterben 
auf  die  etwa  versehentlich  unverteilt  gebliebenen  Sachen  ein 
Vorrecht  zuzugestehen.2  Jeder  beliebige  stand  fur  sie  diesen 
Sachen  mindestens  ebenso  nahe  oder  naher  als  der  Intestaterbe. 
Diese  Sachen  waren  vakant,  und  ihr  rechtliches  Schicksal  wird 
bestimmt  worden  sein  durch  jenes  Rechtsinstitut,  das  als  ein 
Rudiment  uralten  Rechtes  noch  bis  in  die  klassische  Zeit  hereinragt : 
die  usucapio  pro  herede.  Tatsachlich  wird  diese  wohl  in  der 
Regel  hauptsachlich  den  Legataren  von  Haus  und  Hof  zugute 

1  Ahnlich  schon  Jhering,  Geist  des  r.  R.  iv.    147,  der  aber  ein  Erbein- 
setzungstestament  annimmt,    wo  die   Sache   minder  klar  liegt.     Aus  jenem 
Charakter  des  alten  Testaments  erklart  sich  auch,  dass  ein  neues  Testament 
notwendig   das   alte   aufhebt.       Man  kann  nicht   zwei    Verteilungsplane    fur 
dieselbe  Erbschaft  aufstellen. 

2  Es  scheint  mir  nicht  iiberfliissig,  darauf  hinzuweisen,  dass  auch  unser 
modernes  Recht  die  Intestaterben  neben  einem  Testament  im  Grunde  nur 
beruft,  well  wir  annehmen,  dass  dies  dem  vermutlichen  Willen  des  Erblassers 
entspreche,  und  von  ihrer  Berufung  absieht,  wo  diese  Vermutung  offenbar 
nicht  zutrifft.     Wenn  z.  B.  ein  Vater  von  seinen  drei  Kindern  das  alteste  auf 
die  Halfte  einsetzt,  so  wird  es  niemandem  einfallen,  auf  die  andere  unvergebene 
Halfte  die  Intestaterbfolge  zu  eroffnen,  wo  das  alteste  wieder  zu  1/3  partizipieren 
wiirde,  sondern  diese  Halfte  erhalten  die  beiden  jiingeren  allein.      Hat  ferner 
jemand  in   einem   Testament   unter   Ubergehung   der   Intestaterben   den  A. 
zum  Alleinerben  und  dann  in  einem  zweiten  den  B.  auf  die  Halfte  eingesetzt, 
so  wird  man  die  in  dem  zweiten  Testament  nicht  vergebene  Halfte  dem  A. 
und  nicht  etwa  den  Intestaterben  iiberweisen.      Man  konnte  mit  gutem  Fug 
behaupten,  auch  das  moderne  Recht  kenne  keine  wirkliche  Konkurrenz  von 
Testaments-  und  Intestaterbfolge ;    der  Unterschied  vom  altromischen  liege 
vielmehr  allein  darin,  dass  es  —  was  in  dem  vom  Formalismus  beherrschten 
altromischen  Recht  freilich  unmoglich  war  —  neben  dem  erklarten  Willen  auch 
den   unausgesprochenen,  aber  aus  den   Umstanden   erkennbaren  Willen  des 
Testators   beriicksichtige,  moge   dieser  nun  auf  Berufung  der  Intestaterben 
oder  anderer  Personen  gehen. 


v]  R&misches  Testament  129 

gekommen  sein,  die  meist  am  ehesten  in  der  Lage  sein  mussten, 
sich  auch  der  unvergebenen  Sachen  zu  bemachtigen. 

Die  Erwahnung  der  usucapio  pro  herede  fiihrt  uns  sofort  zu  der 
anderen  oben  aufgeworfenen  Frage :  wer  haftet  auf  Grund  des 
Legatentestaments  fur  die  Erbschaftsschulden?  Wir  miissen  uns 
hiiten,  die  Ideen,  nach  denen  sich  in  klassischer  Zeit  die  Haftung 
fur  die  Erbschaftsschulden  regelte,  in  die  Zeit  der  zwolf  Tafeln  zu 
iibertragen  ;  Uber  die  Anschauung  der  alten  Zeit  gibt  uns,  wie  ich 
glaube,  die  usucapio  pro  herede,  deren  rohe  Struktur  hochstes 
Alter  verrat,  ganz  sicheren  Aufschluss,  vorausgesetzt  nur,  dass 
man  sich  an  das  halt,  was  liber  dieses  Institut  authentisch  iiber- 
liefert  ist,  und  darauf  verzichtet,  eine  durch  nichts  beglaubigte 
Urgeschichte  desselben  zu  erfinden.1  Jeder  Beliebige,  so  berichtet 
uns  Gaius  ii.  52  f.,  konnte  sich  der  Sachen  einer  nicht  in  Besitz 
genommenen  (und  so  sicher  auch  der  einer  vollig  vakanten) 
Erbschaft  bemachtigen  und  sie  durch  einjahrigen  Besitz  usukapieren. 
Dadurch  aber  erwarb  er  nach  der  alten  (olim)  Anschauung  nicht 
etwa  bloss  diese  Sachen,  sondern  ipsam  hereditatem  und  wurde 
fur  die  Erbschaftsschulden  haftbar.  Dieser  Bericht  lasst  freilich 
mancherlei  Zweifel  ubrig.  Zunachst :  was  bedeutet  das  velut 
ipsae  hereditates  usucapi  credebantur  bei  Gaius?  Soil  das  etwa 
heissen,dass  jeder  Usukapient  einer  beliebigen  Erbschaftssache  nach 
vollendeter  Usukapion  als  successor  in  universum  ius  defuncti 
behandelt  wurde?  Man  braucht  sich  diese  Frage  nur  vorzulegen, 
um  zu  sehen,  dass  man  auf  diesem  Wege  zu  Unmoglichkeiten 
gelangt.2  Dann  wlirde  ja  die  Vollendung  der  ersten  Usukapion 
sei  es  auch  an  dem  geringwertigsten  Gegenstand,  da  nunmehr 
die  Erbschaft  einen  Herrn  gehabt  hatte,  jede  weitere  Usukapion 
ausgeschlossen  haben,  und  der  Usukapient  etwa  eines  Schafes 

1  Dahin  gehort  insbesondere  die  Hypothese,  die  usucapio  p.  h.  sei  ihrer 
urspriinglichen    Idee   nach    dazu    bestimmt  gewesen,  den    Mangel  der  zum 
Erbschaftserwerb   eigentlich  erforderlich  gewesenen   cretio  zu   decken.       So 
Karlowa,   RG.   ii.    897   f.,   ihm   folgend   Sohm,  Instit.^  694.      Wir   haben 
gesehen,  dass    das    alte    Recht  die   cretio  noch  gar  nicht  kennt.      Ebenso 
willkiirlich  scheint  mir  die  Annahme  Perozzis,  die  usucapio  p.  h.  sei  urspriing- 
lich  nur  z.  G.  des  familiae  emptor  zugelassen  worden  und  habe  lediglich  die 
Unwirksamkeit  fax  familiae  mancipatio  gedeckt  (Istit.  ii.  383  f.). 

2  Dagegen  auch  Holder,  Beitrage  129  f.  und  Karlowa,  RG.  ii.  899,  der 
aber  (so  auch  Scheurl,  Krit.  Vjschr.  xxiv.  219)  willkiirlich  annimmt,  in  alter 
Zeit  habe  der  Besitz  der  maior  pars  pecuniae  geniigt,  um  zur  Ersitzung  der 
ganzen  Erbschaft  zu  fiihren. 


130  O.  Lenel  [v 

wiirde  dem  von  Haus  und  Hof,  wenn  dieser  vielleicht  einen  Tag 
spater  als  er  den  Besitz  ergriffen  hatte,  Haus  und  Hof  haben 
abfordern  konnen.  Oder,  wenn  man  dies  nicht  annehmen  will, 
nach  welchem  Massstab  sollten  die  verschiedenen  Usukapienten  die 
Gesamterbschaft  untereinander  teilen  ?  Vielmehr  scheint  mir  klar 
und  sicher,  dass  der  Usukapient  pro  herede  an  Aktiven  niemals 
mehr  erwarb  als  er  sich  angeeignet  hatte,1  und  mit  der  bei 
Gaius  liber lieferten  Wendung  wird  nicht  auf  eine  Gesamtnachfolge 
in  die  Aktiva,  sondern  nur  auf  die  mit  dem  Erwerb  verbundene 
Schuldenhaftung  hingedeutet.  Wer  nun  diese  Schuldenhaftung 
jemandes,  der  nicht  Universalsukzessor  ist,  von  dem  Vorstellungs- 
kreis  des  klassischen  Rechts  aus  betrachtet,  dem  muss  sie  freilich 
als  unbegreifliche  Anomalie  erscheinen.  Ganz  anders  aber,  wenn 
man  sie  unter  das  Licht  stellt,  das  von  der  Rechtsvergleichung 
ausgeht.  Dann  erscheint  die  Haftung  des  Usukapienten  nur  als 
eine  allerdings  eigentiimliche  Anwendung  eines  Prinzips,  das  auch 
das  germanische  und,  wie  kaum  zu  bezweifeln,  auch  das  griechische 
Recht  beherrscht:2  die  Schuldenhaftung  ruht  auf  der  Erb- 
schaft.  Ein  Recht  aber,  das,  wie  das  romische,  in  Ermangelung 
von  heredes  die  Usukapion  der  Erbschaftssachen  gestattete,  musste 
notwendig  dazu  kommen,  die  Erbenhaftung  an  jede  einzelne 
Erbschaftssache  zu  kniipfen  und  also  jeden  haften  zu  lassen,  der 
etwas  aus  der  Erbschaft  sich  aneignete.  Gait  aber  dies  Prinzip 
bei  der  usucapio  pro  herede^  so  ist  es  sehr  unwahrscheinlich,  dass 
seine  Geltung  sich  auf  diesen  einen  Fall  beschrankt  habe,  und 
wer  mit  uns  uberzeugt  ist,  dass  das  Komitialtestament  ein  reines 
Legatentestament  war,  darf  nicht  zogern,  neben  die  Schulden- 
haftung des  Usukapienten  die  des  Legatars  zu  stellen,  der  sich 
der  ihm  legierten  Sache  bemachtigt  hat.  Vielleicht  erscheint 
manchen  eine  solche  Annahme  als  unerhorte  Ketzerei.  Aber  man 
beachte  wohl :  die  Schuldenhaftung  der  Legatare  war  im  alten 
Recht  praktisch  gar  nicht  zu  entbehren,  selbst  dann  nicht  zu 

1  Dass   dem  z.  Zt.   des   Q.   Mucius  so  war,  diirfte  daraus   hervorgehen, 
dass  er  die  Haftung  fiir  die  sacra  in  Ermangelung  von  heredes  demjenigen 
auferlegte,  qui  de  bonis  .  .   .  usu  ceperit  plurimum  possidendo  (Cic.  de  leg. 
ii.  48).     Aber  auch  schon  in  der  alteren  Ordnung  (Cic.  eod.  ii.  49)  war  bei 
dem  si  maiorem  par  tern  pecuniae  capiat  der  Usukapient  gewiss  mitverstanden 
und  nicht  als  Universalsukzessor  gedacht.     A.  M.  Karlowa,  RG.  ii.  901. 

2  Wegen  des  germanischen  Rechts  bedarf  es  wohl  keiner  Nachweisungen  ; 
wegen  des  griechischen  vgl.  Partsch,  Burgschaftsrecht,  i.  232  f. 


v] 


R&misches  Testament 


entbehren,  wenn  die  heredis  institutio  entgegen  unserer  Ansicht 
ein  Urbestandteil  des  romischen  Testaments  gewesen  ware.  Man 
setze  den  Fall,  ein  mittelloser  oder  iiberschuldeter  Erbe  habe  die 
Erbschaft  angetreten.  Im  klassischen  Recht  gewahrt  hier  das 
beneficium  separationis  den  Erbschaftsglaubigern  die  Moglichkeit, 
im  Weg  des  Separatkonkurses  die  ganze  Erbschaft  zu  ihrer 
Befriedigung  heranzuziehen  und  sich  so  vor  Schaden  zu  schiitzen. 
In  die  Zeit  der  zwolf  Tafeln  wird  niemand  dies  Benefiz  zuriick- 
riicken  wollen.  Sollten  damals  die  Glaubiger  kein  Mittel  gehabt 
haben,  auf  die  per  vindicationem  legierten  Sachen  zu  greifen  ? 
Sollten  sie  darauf  beschrankt  gewesen  sein,  sich  an  den  heres 
institutus  zu  halten,  und  leer  ausgegangen  sein,  indes  die  lachenden 
Legatare  die  Erbschaftssachen  okkupierten  ? 1  Und  zu  diesem 
Argument  tritt  eine  sichere  historische  Tatsache,  die  beweist,  dass 
den  alten  Romern  eine  Schuldenhaftung  der  Legatare  durchaus 
nicht  so  fremdartig  vorgekommen  sein  kann,  wie  man  glaubt. 
Ich  denke  an  die  bekannte  Ordnung  der  Haftung  fiir  die  sacra 
hereditaria,  wie  sie  uns  bei  Cicero  (de  legib.  ii.  48  ff.)  uberliefert  ist. 
Zu  Ciceros  Zeit  hafteten  fur  die  sacra  in  Ermangelung  von  heredes 
freilich  nicht  mehr  alle  Legatare,  sondern  nur  der  Partitionslegatar 
qui  tantundem  capit  quantum  omnes  heredes.  Aber  Cicero  selbst 
berichtet  von  einer  alteren  Ordnung,  wonach  die  Haftung  auf  drei 
Weisen  begriindet  werden  konnte :  hereditate  aut  si  maiorem 
partem  pecuniae  capiat  aut  [si  maior  pars  pecuniae  legata  esf\ 
si  inde  quidpiam  ceperit.  Die  beiden  letzten  Haftungsgriinde 
beziehen  sich  selbstverstandlich  nicht  bloss  auf  Usukapienten,2 
sondern  auch  auf  Legatare,  und  streicht  man,  wie  man  m.  E.  muss, 
die  eingeklammerten  Worte  als  in  den  Text  geratenes  Glossem,3 
so  ist  hier  fiir  die  sacra  sogar  die  Haftung  jedes  einzelnen  Legatars 
bezeugt,  die  wir  auch  fiir  die  Schulden  behaupten.  Der  Gedanke 

1  Keinen  Gegenbeweis  kann  C.  iv.  16,  7  liefern.      Der  Schluss  von  der  in 
den  zwolf  Tafeln  sanktionierten  Haftung  der  Erben,  worunter  im  Sinne  des 
Gesetzes  m.  E.  nur  die  Intestaterben  zu  verstehen  waren,  auf  die  Nichthaftung 
der  Legatare  ist  keineswegs  zwingend. 

2  Andere  (z.  B.  Scheurl,  Krit.    Vjschr.  xxiv.  220)  nehmen  an,  dass  der 
Usukapient  schon  von  dem  Haftungsgrund  hereditate  mitgetroffen  wurde. 

3  Das  Glossem  sollte  den  zweiten  Haftungsgrund  erlautern.      Es  verrat 
sich    schon    durch   den    Indikativ  est  statt  des  in    der  indirekten    Rede   zu 
erwartenden  sit..    Sachlich  erscheint  es  mir  unverstandlich,  warum   haftbar 
erwartden   Erwerb  irgend  eines  Stiicks  nur  der  werden  soil,  dem  die  maior 
durch   ecuniae  vermacht    ist.       A.    M.    freilich    Holder,    Beitrdge^    140    f., 


132  O.  Lenel  [v 

liegt  nahe,  dass  der  zwischen  der  Haftung  des  Erben  und 
des  einzelnen  Legatars  eingeschobene  zweite  Haftungsgrund  —  qui 
maiorem  partem  pecuniae  capiat  —  bereits  eine  Abwandlung  des 
noch  alteren  nur  zweigliedrigen  Haftungssystems  enthalte.  Sei 
dem  wie  ihm  wolle,  der  Schluss  von  der  Sacrahaftung  der  Legatare 
auf  die  Schuldenhaftung  drangt  sich  geradezu  zwingend  auf: 
warum  sollte  man  den  Glaubigern  verweigert  haben,  was  den 
Gottern  recht  war?  Aller  Wahrscheinlichkeit  nach  handelt  es 
sich  hier  um  eine  Erscheinung,  die  wir  auch  sonst  sowohl  im 
griechischen  wie  im  romischen  Recht  beobachten  konnen  :  dass 
namlich  eine  ursprlinglich  allgemeine  Haftungsform  im  Laufe  der 
Zeiten  auf  solche  Anspriiche  beschrankt  wird,  bei  denen  ein 
offentliches  oder  religioses  Interesse  obwaltet.1 

Die  Haftung  der  Legatare  —  wir  diirfen  dieser  Frage  nicht  aus- 
weichen  —  kann  nur  als  beschrankte  gedacht  werden.  Niemand 
wird  annehmen  wollen,  dass  die  Aneignung  des  geringfiigigsten 
Legats  unbeschrankte  Schuldenhaftung  mit  sich  brachte.  Wir 
sind  vom  klassischen  Rechte  her  so  sehr  daran  gewohnt,  in  der 
unbeschrankten  Schuldenhaftung  des  Erben  ein  Grundprinzip  des 
romischen  Rechts  zu  erblicken,  dass  es  fast  verwegen  aussieht, 
dem  altromischen  Recht  eine  beschrankte  Schuldenhaftung  zu- 
zuschreiben.  In  der  Tat  glaube  auch  ich,  dass  die  unbeschrankte 
Schuldenhaftung  schon  dem  altesten  romischen  Rechte  bekannt 
war,  namlich  als  Haftung  des  suus  heres.  In  alter  Zeit  wird  sich 
das  Zugriffsrecht  der  Glaubiger  auch  auf  die  Gewaltunterworfenen 
des  Schuldners  erstreckt  haben,  und  diese  personliche  Haftung 
erlosch  sehr  natiirlich  nicht  mit  dem  Tode  des  Schuldners.2  Dem 
suus  heres  mag  dann  aus  Griinden  praktischer  Zweckmassigkeit, 

Karlowa,  a.  a.  O.  902.  Von  den  Editoren  streichen  den  Passus  Christ  und 
Baiter,  wahrend  Vahlen  ihn  beibehalt,  mit  der  unzureichenden  Begriindung, 
dass  sonst  das  folgende  si  inde  quidpiam  in  der  Luft  schwebe.  Inde,  d.  h. 
ex  ca  pecunia. 

1  Ich   erinnere   aus   dem    romischen    Recht   an    die    Beschrankung   der 
urspriinglich  gewiss  allgemein  zulassigen  Privatpfandung  auf  die  wenigen  bei 
Gaius  erwahnten  Falle  der  legis  actio  per  pignoris  capionem.      Ganz  anders 
freilich   Mitteis,  rom.  Privatr.  i.  98  n.  12:    das   die  sacra  betreffende   Pon- 
tifikaledikt  habe  mit  der  Schuldenhaftung  nichts  zu  tun.      Diese  Behauptung 
erklart  sich  nur  daraus,  dass  Mitteis  Vorstellungen,  die  aus  dem  Gedankenkreis 
des  klassischen  Rechtes  stammen,  ohne  weiteres  in  das  alteste  Recht  versetzt. 

2  Lenel,  krit.  Vjschr.  xxviii.  175.       So  auch  Cuq,  NRH.  x.  547,  freilich 
mit  Beschrankung  auf  das  problematische  nexum. 


v]  Romisches  Testament  133 

auf  die  ich  noch  komme,  im  Laufe  der  Zeit  der  proximus  adgnatus 
angeglichen  worden  sein  ;  die  Legatare  aber  werden  fiir  die  sacra 
wie  fiir  die  Schulden  personlich  nur  dann  gehaftet  haben,  wenn  sie 
die  Sache,  an  der  die  Haftung  hing,  dem  Glaubiger  nicht  iiber- 
liessen.1  Ebenso  kann  ich  mir  auch  die  Haftung  des  Usukapienten 
pro  herede  nur  als  beschrankte  vorstellen.  Das  Gegenteil  ist  ja 
herrschende  Meinung,  die  besonders  drastisch  in  der  bekannten 
scherzhaften  Darstellung  Jherings2  hervortritt,  wo  die  usucapio 
pro  herede  als  „  die  Mausefalle  des  alien  Erbrechts  "  figuriert.  Ich 
halte  diese  Auffassung  fiir  kaum  moglich.  Man  konnte  sie  sich 
allenfalls  zurechtlegen,  wenn  die  alte  Zeit  in  der  usucapio  pro 
herede  ein  Delikt  erblickt  hatte,  das  durch  die  Schuldenhaftung 
hatte  gewissermassen  bestraft  werden  sollen.  Aber  von  diesem 
Standpunkt  aus  bliebe  die  Zulassung  dieser  Art  Usukapion  ein 
Ratsel,  und  die  Schuldenhaftung  hatte  man  dann  wohl  nicht 
an  die  vollendete  Usukapion,  sondern  an  die  blosse  Aneignung 
gekniipft.  Der  alten  Zeit  war  die  usucapio  p.  h.  m.  E.  nichts  als 
eine  Erganzung  des  engbegrenzten  Intestaterbrechts,  die  wohl 
meist  den  Nachststehenden  zugute  gekommen  sein  wird.  Und 
gab  es  nicht  eine  auch  im  modernen  Sinn  durchaus  redliche 
usucapio  p.  h.y  seitens  dessen  namlich,  der  sich  bona  fide  fiir  den 
Erben  hielt?  Ist  es  glaublich,  dass  man  diesen,  der  alles,  was  er 
nicht  bereits  usukapiert  hatte,  dem  wahren  Erben  herausgeben 
musste,  unbeschrankt  fiir  die  Schulden  haften  Hess  ?  Dass  wir  bei 
Gaius  von  der  Beschrankung  der  Haftung3  nichts  mehr  erfahren, 
darf  nicht  wundernehmen.  Fiir  ihn  war  ja  die  ganze  Haftung  des 
Usukapienten  eine  verschollene  Antiquitat,  auf  deren  Details 
einzugehen  er  keinerlei  Veranlassung  hatte,  vorausgesetzt,  dass  er 
davon  iiberhaupt  noch  etwas  wusste. 

1  Wie    aber,    wenn    ein    Legatar    aus    Besorgnis    vor    dem   Angriff  von 
Erbschaftsglaubigern  den    Erwerb  seines   Legates    ganz   unterliess  ?      Dann 
muss  es  den  Erbschaftsglaubigern  freigestanden  haben,  sich  zu  ihrer  Befriedi- 
gung  der  so  freigewordenen  Erbschaftssachen  zu  bemachtigen,  und  dies  wird 
nicht  als  usucapio  p.  h.  gegolten  haben. 

2  Scherz  und  Ernst  in  der  Jurisprudens^  127  f.,  384  f. 

3  Dagegen   wird  die  Haftung  dessen  qui  usu  cepeiit  plurimum  possi- 
dendo  fiir  die  sacra  (Cic.  I.e.]  allerdings  als  unbeschrankte  zu  denken  sein. 
Den   Gottern  soil  ihre  Befriedigung  erleichtert  werden  ;    darum  konnen  sie 
sich  fiir  ihre  ganze  Forderung  an  jenen  einen  halten.      Solange  aber  jeder 
einzelne  Usukapient   haftete,  scheint  mir  die  unbeschrankte  Haftung  kaum 
denkbar. 


134  O.  Lend  [v 

Ich  habe  im  bisherigen  versucht,  ein  Bild  des  Rechtszustandes 
zur  Zeit  des  alten  Legatentestaments  zu  geben.  Je  welter  nun  dies 
Bild  von  verbreiteten  Vorstellungen  abweicht,  um  so  unerlasslicher 
ist  es,  darzulegen,  wie  sich  von  hier  aus  der  ganz  andere  Rechts- 
zustand  entwickeln  konnte,  der  uns  im  klassischen  Recht  vor 
Augen  steht.  Wie  ist  die  heredis  institutio  aufgekommen  ?  Es 
versteht  sich,  dass  wir,  bei  dem  Mangel  jeder  zuverlassigen  Uber- 
lieferung  iiber  die  auf  die  zwolf  Tafeln  folgenden  Jahrhunderte,  auf 
Hypothesen  angewiesen  sind ;  aber  diese  Hypothesen  diirften  sich 
zu  einem  hohen  Grade  der  Wahrscheinlichkeit  fiihren  lassen.  Es 
war,  wie  ich  glaube,  die  Sach-  und  Rechtslage  beim  alteren  Manzi- 
pationstestamente,  was  die  romischen  Juristen  auf  den  Gedanken 
der  heredis  institutio  brachte.  Gaius  berichtet  bekanntlich,  der 
familiae  emptor  bei  diesem  Testament  sei  heredis  loco  gewesen 
(heredis  locum  optinebaf}.  Was  Gaius  sich  bei  dieser  Charak- 
terisierung  dachte,  ob  er  damit  eine  vollkommene  Gleichheit  oder  nur 
eine  weitgehende  Ahnlichkeit  mit  der  Erbenstellung  ausdriicken 
wollte,  kann  hier  dahingestellt  bleiben.  Denn  auch  im  zweiten 
Fall  bleibt  die  von  mir  vermutete  Entwicklung  verstandlich, 
und  dass  eine  solche  Ahnlichkeit  vorlag,  kann  auch  der  nicht 
bezweifeln,  der,  wie  auch  ich  es  fur  richtig  halte,  in  dem  familiae 
emptor  wesentlich  nur  einen  Treuhander  oder  Testamentsvoll- 
strecker  sieht.1  Zunachst  war  die  Giltigkeit  aller  von  dem 
Erblasser  getroffenen  Verfiigungen,  wie  spaterhin  von  der  der 
heredis  institutio^  so  in  alter  Zeit  von  der  der  familiae  manci- 
patio  abhangig.  Der  familiae  emptor  muss  ferner  in  der  Lage 
gewesen  sein,  seine  Rechtsstellung,  mit  der  das  Testament  stand  und 
fiel,  gegen  den  drohenden  Angriffder  Intestaterben  zu  verteidigen,  es 
muss  ihm  eine  legis  actio  nach  Art  der  hereditatis  petitio  zuge- 
standen  haben ;  die  Gefahr  eines  solchen  Angriffs  mag  bei  dem  im 
Angesicht  des  ganzen  Volks  errichteten  Komitialtestament  gering 
gewesen  sein,  musste  sich  aber  notwendig  einstellen,  als  man  den 
Versuch  machte,  die  alte  Form  durch  den  Kunstbau  des  Manzi- 
pationstestaments  zu  ersetzen,  und  wer  hatte  sonst  die  Verteidigung 
des  Testaments  iibernehmen  sollen  ?  Der  familiae  emptor  wird 
weiter — wahrscheinlich  beschrankt  und  neben  den  Legataren — fiir 
die  Erbschaftsschulden  gehaftet  haben.  Eine  solche  Haftung  des 

1  Vgl.  u.  a.   Sohm,  Institut.  722  f .  ;   Cuq,   Instit.  jurid.  i.  128,  und  be- 
sonders  Lambert,  a.  a.  O.  52  f. 


v]  Romisches  Testament  135 

Treuhanders  oder  Testamentsvollstreckers  findet  sich  bekanntlich 
auch  in  anderen  Rechten ; l  bei  der  Sachlage,  wie  sie  sich  aus  der 
familiae  mancipatio  ergab,  war  sie  kaum  zu  entbehren.  Nimmt 
man,  was  ich  fur  sehr  wahrscheinlich  halte,  an,  dass  das  uns 
uberlieferte  Formular  der  familiae  mancipatio  nicht  das  urspriing- 
liche  ist,  dass  urspriinglich  der  familiae  emptor  nicht  bloss  die 
custodela,  sondern  das  Vermogen  des  Erblassers  selbst  erwarb 
und  zur  Ausfiihrung  der  Anordnungen  des  Erblassers  damals  gar 
nicht  juristisch,  sondern  nur  moralisch  verpflichtet  war,2  so  zwang 
sich  seine  Haftung  geradezu  auf.  Aber  auch  in  der  Zeit,  wo  der 
familiae  emptor  nunmehr  die  custodela  am  Vermogen  fur  sich  in 
Anspruch  nahm,  und  man  das  Eigentum  an  den  vermachten 
Sachen  vermoge  der  nuncupatio  unmittelbar  den  Vindikations- 
legataren  zufallen  Hess,  war  nichts  natiirlicher,  als  dass  man  die 
Erbschaftsglaubiger  gleichwohl  nicht  bloss  auf  letztere,  sondern 
auch  auf  den  familiae  emptor  verwies  ;  blieb  doch  immer  die 
Moglichkeit,  dass  Legatare  vor  dem  Erblasser  starben  oder  das 
ihnen  Hinterlassene  nicht  an  sich  nehmen  wollten,  oder  die 
Annahme  sich  verzogerte,  oder  dass  nach  Entrichtung  samtlicher 
Legate  noch  ein  unvergebener  Rest  der  Erbschaft  sich  herausstellte, 
der  doch  ebenfalls  den  Glaubigern  haften  musste.  Ein  solcher 
Rest  diirfte,  solange  die  familiae  mancipatio  in  irgend  einem  Sinne 
ernst  genommen  wurde,  dem  familiae  emptor  verblieben  sein  und 
so  seine  Haftung  begriindet  haben.  Ja,  es  darf  angenommen 
werden,  dass  die  Testatoren  in  der  Regel  die  Erbschaft  durch 
Legate  nicht  erschopft,  sondern  mindestens  soviel  davon  freigelassen 
haben  werden,  als  zur  Befriedigung  der  (irdischen  und  himm- 
lischen)  Erbschaftsglaubiger  erforderlich  war ;  musste  ihnen  doch 
daran  gelegen  sein,  dass  die  Legatare  das  ihnen  Hinterlassene 
unverkiirzt  und  ohne  Besorgnis  vor  dem  Angriff  durch  Glaubiger 
erhalten  konnten.  In  alledem  also  war  die  Stellung  des  familiae 
emptor  der  des  Erben  verwandt.  Aber  daneben  bestanden  er- 

1  Fur  die   germanische   Treuhand    vgl.   A.   Schultze,   die   langobardische 
Treuhand,  50  n.    15,    112  n.   24,    178;  ferner  Caillemer,   Orig.  et  dtvel.  de 
rexfr.  test.  74  f.,  429  f.,  431  f. 

2  So  Cuq,   NRH.   x.  755  ;    Lambert,  a.  a.   O.  79.      Auf  Gaius,  ii.  103, 
mochte  ich  mich  freilich  hiefiir  nicht  berufen.      Gaius  hat  von  dieser  Stufe 
der  Entwicklung  des  Testaments  schwerlich  mehr  irgend  eine  Kenntnis,  und 
mit  den  ungeriauen   Worten  ob  id  ei  mandabat  wird  er  nicht   auf  formlose 
Auftrage,  sondern  auf  die  nuncupatio  haben  hinweisen  wollen. 


136  O.  Lend  [v 

hebliche  Verschiedenheiten,  und  gerade  in  diesen  werden  wir  die 
Motive  zu  suchen  haben,  die  die  Juristen  dahin  fiihrten,  die  familiae 
emptio  zu  einem  blossen  Scheinakt  zu  degradieren  und  an  Stelle 
des  familiae  emptor  einen  kiinstlichen  im  Testamente  selbst  zu 
ernennenden  heres  zu  setzen.  Vor  allem  war,  solange  diefamttiae 
mancipatio  ernst  genommen  wurde,  ein  Widerruf  des  Testaments 
nur  mittels  remancipatio  familiae  moglich,  die  die  Mitwirkung  des 
familiae  emptor  erforderte,  so  dass  der  Testator  von  dessen  gutem 
Willen  abhangig  war.  Weiter :  der  familiae  emptor  konnte  vor 
dem  Testator  sterben ;  dann  konnte  schwerlich  das  Testament 
bestehen  bleiben,  —  eine  Substitution  in  die  Rolle  des  familiae 
emptor  war  ausgeschlossen.  Endlich :  die  Schuldenhaftung  des 
familiae  emptor  ist  kaum  anders  denn  als  beschrankte  zu  denken ; 
diese  beschrankte  Haftung  aber,  neben  der  die  der  Legatare 
unentbehrlich  blieb,  musste  zu  grossen  Schwierigkeiten  fiihren. 
Denn  haftete  den  Erbschaftsglaubigern  in  seiner  Hand  nur  das, 
was  nach  Befriedigung  samtlicher  Legatare  iibrig  blieb,  so  wird 
dessen  Belauf,  in  Ermangelung  der  Vorsorgemassregeln,  die  das 
moderne  Recht  trifft,  unendlich  oft  sehr  schwer  festzustellen 
gewesen  sein ;  hafteten  aber,  was  ich  fur  viel  wahrscheinlicher 
halte,  solange  die  Legatare  die  vermachten  Sachen  nicht  an  sich 
genommen  hatten,  diese  den  Glaubigern  auch  in  der  Hand  des 
familiae  emptor^  so  litten  die  Interessen  der  Legatare  not.  Sollten 
diese  Ubelstande  die  Juristen  nicht  beschaftigt  haben?  Such  ten 
sie  aber  nach  Mitteln  der  Abhilfe,  so  wurden  sie  notwendig  auf 
den  Weg  gewiesen,  den  sie  auch  eingeschlagen  haben :  namlich 
einerseits  die  familiae  emptio^  in  der  die  Wurzel  jener  Ubelstande 
lag,  der  ernstlichen  Bedeutung  zu  entkleiden,  andererseits  dem  im 
Testament  zum  Vorschein  kommenden  letzten  Willen  einen 
breiteren  Spielraum  zu  gewahren.  Fur  letzteres  gab  der  Zwolf- 
tafelsatz  cum  nexum  faciet  jederzeit  den  formalen  Anhalt ;  frei 
interpretiert,  bot  dieser  Satz  die  Moglichkeit,  die  Wirksamkeit  der 
nuncupatio  soweit  zu  erstrecken,  als  man  irgend  zweckmassig  fand. 
Wie  sollte  man  aber  vorgehen  ?  Es  kam  darauf  an,  die  familiae 
mancipatio  durch  eine  Form  der  Bedenkung  zu  ersetzen,  die  dem 
Bedachten  den  ganzen  Nachlass  uberwies,  soweit  nicht  durch 
Legate  dariiber  verfiigt  war,  Substitution  zuliess  und  zugleich  die 
Schwierigkeiten  beseitigte,  die  die  beschrankte  Haftung  mit  sich 
brachte.  Durch  ein  Legat,  wie  man  es  auch  formulieren  mochte, 


v]  Romisches  Testament  137 

konnte  man  dies  letztere  niemals  bewirken ;  einen  Legatar  hin- 
sichtlich  der  Schuldenhaftung  anderen  Grundsatzen  zu  unterwerfen 
als  die  sonstigen  Legatare,  dazu  wiirde  es  an  jeder  Handhabe 
gefehlt  haben.  Ein  legatum  familiae  ferner  —  worauf  man  durch 
die  Erwagung  hatte  kommen  konnen,  dass  es  sich  um  einen  Ersatz 
fiir  den  familiae  emptor  handelte  —  wiirde  ja  die  ganze  familia 
umfasst  haben,  also  auch  die  einzeln  vermachten  Sachen,  und 
wiirde  daher,  der  Absicht  zuwider,  die  Einzellegatare  eingeschrankt 
haben,  indem  sie  samtlich  dem  Legatar  der  familia  gegeniiber 
blosse  collegatarii  re  coniuncti  gewesen  waren.  Es  gait  also,  eine 
neue  Art  letztwilliger  Verfiigung  zu  erfinden,  und  dies  wird  auf 
den  kiihnen  Gedanken  gefiihrt  haben,  den  heres ^  der  bis  dahin  nur 
im  Intestaterbrecht  eine  Rolle  gespielt  hatte,  in  das  Testament 
einzufiihren  und  mit  den  Legataren  zu  kombinieren.  Ich  vermute, 
dass  man  den  heres  scriptus  nach  dem  Vorbild  des  suus  heres, 
dem  der  heres  legitimus  wohl  langst  gleichgestellt  worden  war, 
von  allem  Anfang  an  unbeschrankt  fiir  die  Schulden  haften  liess.1 
Wie  sehr  man  aber  die  ganze  Neuerung  der  heredis  institutio  als 
kiinstliche  empfand,  auf  wie  unsicherem  Boden  man  sich  fiihlte,  das 
konnen  wir  noch  heute  erkennen  an  der  merkwurdigen,  gewiss  sehr 
alten  Formel  der  cretio  cum  exheredatione,  die  urspriinglich  jede 
heredis  institutio  begleitet  haben  wird.  Quodni  ita  creveris, 
exheres  esto  !  Wie  kam  man  dazu,  jemanden,  der  doch  —  nach  der 
klassischen  Auffassung  —  noch  gar  nicht  Erbe  ist,  ausdriicklich  zu 
exheredieren,  wie  den  suus  heres ?  Wer  diese  Formel  verfasste, 
der  wusste  sicher  noch  nichts  von  hereditas  delata  und  hereditas 
adquisita.  Er  stand  vielmehr,  wie  mir  scheint,  unter  der  Vor- 
stellung,  das  heres  esto  des  Testaments,  in  Verbindung  mit  dem 
uti  lingua  nuncupassit,  ita  ius  esto  der  zwolf  Tafeln  wiirde  den 
Ernannten,  gleich  einem  suus  heresy  auch  ohne  und  wider  seinen 
Willen  zum  Erben  machen,  wenn  ihm  das  Testament  nicht  selber 
die  Moglichkeit  eroffne,  sich  der  Erbeneigenschaft  zu  entledigen  ; 
darum  wird  ihm,  fiir  den  Fall,  dass  er  die  Erbschaft  haben  will,  die 

1  Daneben  wird  man  die  beschrankte  Sachhaftung  der  Legatare  gewiss 
nicht  alsbald  aufgegeben  haben  ;  sie  war,  wie  gezeigt,  bis  zur  Einfuhrung  des 
beneficiiim  separationis  gar  nicht  zu  entbehren.  Aber  sie  wird  subsidiar 
geworden  und  damit  praktisch  in  den  Hintergrund  getreten  sein,  sodass  ihre 
spatere  Beseitigung,  als  man  sie  nicht  mehr  brauchte,  nicht  als  grundstiirzende 
Reform  erschien. 


138  O.  Lenel  [v 

Beobachtung  einer  Form  auferlegt,  und  wird  er,  wenn  er  diese 
Form  nicht  beobachtet,  ausdriicklich  exherediert. 

Den  Satz  heredis  institutio  est  caput  et  fundamentum  testa- 
menti  halt  die  herrschende  Meinung  fiir  einen  Urbestandteil  des 
romischen  Testamentsrechts.1  Wie  ware  dies  moglich,  da  doch 
jedenfalls  das  altere  Manzipationstestament  die  Erbeinsetzung 
gar  nicht  kannte !  M.  E.  gehort  er  erst  der  Zeit  an,  da  sich 
die  Umwandlung  des  Manzipationstestaments  vollzog.  Mehreres 
mag  da  ztisammengewirkt  haben.  Man  hatte  in  dem  familiae 
emptor  einen  Verteidiger  und  Vollstrecker  des  Testaments 
besessen  und  war  der  Vorteile  einer  solchen  Einrichtung  inne 
geworden :  man  wird  diese  Vorteile  nicht  haben  aufgeben  wollen, 
als  man  ihn  durch  den  heres  scriptus  ersetzte.  Vor  allem  aber : 
die  Juristen  miissen  die  Gefahren  der  beschrankten  Schulden- 
haftung,  die  sich  notwendig  einstellen,  wo  nicht,  wie  im  justinia- 
nischen  und  den  neueren  Rechten  besondere  Schutzmassregeln 
getroffen  werden,  durch  vielfaltige  Erfahrung  kennen  gelernt 
haben.  War  es  da  nicht  ganz  natiirlich,  dass  man  die  Giltigkeit 
des  Testaments  von  dem  Vorhandensein  des  unbeschrankt  haften- 
den  heres  scriptus  abhangig  machte,  der  den  Glaubigern  die 
Notwendigkeit  ersparte,  ein  Dutzend  verschiedener  Legatare 
angehen  zu  miissen?  Fiir  den  Fall,  dass  der  Eingesetzte  nicht 
Erbe  wurde,  konnte  der  Testator  durch  Substitution  Vorsorge 
treffen.  Ausserlich  wird  die  Abhangigkeit  des  Testaments  von  der 
Erbeinsetzung  kaum  sehr  aufgefallen  sein ;  war  man  doch  daran 
gewohnt,  dass  der  Universalerwerb  —  des  familiae  emptor  —  die 
samtlichen  Singularerwerbe  bedingte.  Uns  ist  die  Regel  nur 
deshalb  ein  Stein  des  Anstosses,  weil  wir  es  als  das  natiirliche 
ansehen,  dass,  was  die  letztwilligen  Verfugungen  iibrig  lassen, 
den  Intestaterben  zufalle.  Den  Romern  aber,  die  von  altersher 
sowohl  (wie  ich  oben  zu  zeigen  versuchte)  beim  Komitialtestament 
wie  beim  Manzipationstestament  daran  gewohnt  waren,  das 
Testament  als  Verfiigung  liber  das  ganze  Vermogen  anzusehen, 
wird  das  Gegenteil  natiirlich  erschienen  sein ;  sie  werden  von 
demjenigen,  der  seinen  Intestaterben  bedenken  wollte,  erwartet 
haben,  dass  er  dies  ausdriicklich  tue. 

Dass  die  republikanische  Jurisprudenz  eine  Neuerung  von 
solcher  Tragweite  durchzusetzen  vermochte,  darf  nicht  wunder- 
1  Anders  Cuq,  NRH.  x.  550,  568. 


v]  Romisches  Testament  139 

nehmen.  Man  erinnere  sich,  dass  dieselbe  Jurisprudenz  Rechts- 
institute  wie  die  Emanzipation  und  Adoption  geschaffen,  das 
gesetzliche  Intestaterbrecht  der  Frauen  eingeschrankt,1  das  Frauen- 
testament  ermoglicht,  das  Pflichtteilsrecht  erfunden  hat  u.  a.  m. 
Das  waren  Neuerungen  von  nicht  geringerer  Kiihnheit.  Man 
kann  die  produktive  Kraft  und  die  Macht  jener  Jurisprudenz  gar 
nicht  hoch  genug  einschatzen.  Was  Pomponius  von  P.  Mucius, 
Brutus  und  Manilius  berichtet  —  qui  fundaverunt  ius  civile  — ,  darf 
nicht  als  leere  Redensart  angesehen  werden  ;  an  dieser  Fundierungs- 
arbeit  aber  hatten  sicherlich  auch  zahlreiche  literarisch  nicht 
hervorgetretene  Vorganger  ihren  Anteil,  und  zu  ihrem  Werk 
gehort  auch  die  Schopfung  der  heredis  institutio. 

Das  Datum  der  Neuerung  entzieht  sich,  wie  so  vieles  in  den 
auf  die  zwolf  Tafeln  folgenden  Jahrhunderten  der  Rechtsent- 
wicklung,  unserer  Kenntnis.  Bei  Plautus  lasst  sich,  wie  schon 
Lambert2  gezeigt  hat,  die  Erbeinsetzung  nicht  nachweisen.  Wir 
begegnen  allerdings  wiederholt  bei  ihm  der  Wendung  heredem 
facere,  bald  in  Verbindung  mit  einer  vorgangigen  Adoption  3  bald 
ohne  solche.4  Man  muss  sich  aber  wohl  hiiten,  in  diesen  Worten 
einen  sicheren  Beweis  der  damaligen  Existenz  der  Erbeinsetzung 
zu  sehen.  In  den  erstgenannten  Stellen  heisst  es  ubereinstimmend  : 

adoptat  (puerum)  .  .  . 

eumque  heredem  fecit,  quum  ipse  obiit  diem. 

In  diesem  Zusammenhang  aber  diirfte  heredem  fecit  nicht  auf 
einen  besonderen  Einsetzungsakt  hinweisen,  sondern  einfach  als 
die  rechtliche  Folge  des  Adoptionsakt  gedacht  sein  :  der  Erblasser 
adoptiert  und  macht  demgemass  den  Adoptierten  durch  seinen 
Tod  (quum  ipse  obiit  diem}  zum  Erben.5  Darum  heisst  es  auch 
Poen.  iv.  2,  82  von  dem  gleichen  Falle  schlechthin  : 

1  Die  Uberlieferung  dariiber  wird  bekanntlich  von  manchen  angezweifelt 
und  die  obige  Beschrankung  schon  dem  altromischen  Rechte  zugeschrieben, 
—  wie  mir  scheint,  ohne  Grund.      Solange  die  Frauentutel    in  voller  Kraft 
bestand,  waren   die  Frauen    in   der  Hand    ihrer  Agnaten,  und   ebendeshalb 
eine  Einschrankung  ihres  Intestaterbrechts  uberfliissig. 

2  a.  a.  O.  98  n.  i. 

3  Menaechm.  prol.  60-62,  Poen.  prol.  76,  77. 

4  Poen.  prol'.  68-70,  v.  2,  109,  10.      Vgl.  auch  iv.  2,  17. 

5  Im  griechischen  Vorbild  mag  K\^pov6jjLov  iroifurOat  im  Sinn  von  „  sich 
einen  Erben  schaffen  "  gestanden  haben. 


140  O.  Lend  [v 

is  in  divitias  homo  adoptavit  hunc,  quum  diem  obiit  suum.1 

Damit  verlieren  aber  auch  die  Stellen  ihre  Beweiskraft,  wo  das 
heredem  facere  ohne  Adoption  vorkommt.  Es  handelt  sich  da 
(Poen.  prol.  68-70,  v.  2,  109,  no)  um  das  Erbewerden  ernes  frater 
patruelis  des  Verstorbenen,  und  wenn  es  da  von  heisst  et  is  me 
heredem  fecit,  quum  suum  obiit  diem,  so  diirfte  es  auch  hier  viel 
naher  liegen,  diese  Worte  davon  zu  verstehen,  dass  der  Verstorbene 
durch  seinen  Tod  den  anderen  als  nachsten  Verwandten  zum  Erben 
„  machte",  als  von  einer  dem  Tod  vorausgehenden  Erbeinsetzung.  So 
bleibt  nur  die  eine  Stelle  iibrig,  in  der  liber  einen  Sklaven  gesagt  wird : 

omnia  edepol  mira  sunt,  nisi  erus  hunc  heredem  facit 

(Poen.  iv.  2,  17).  Gewiss  geht  daraus  die  Moglichkeit  hervor,  einen 
Sklaven  kiinstlich  zum  Erben  zu  machen.  Den  Weg  aber,  auf 
dem  dies  geschah,  lasst  die  Stelle  im  Dunkeln,  und  nichts  zwingt 
dazu,  hier  eher  an  eine  eigentliche  heredis  institutio  als  an  eine 
Adoption  wie  in  den  ersterwahnten  Fallen  zu  denken.2  1st  hie- 
nach  das  Rechtsinstitut  der  Erbeinsetzung  in  den  Komodien  des 
Plautus  nicht  nachzuweisen,  so  folgt  freilich  daraus  keineswegs, 
dass  es  nicht  damals  schon  bestand.  Die  folgende  Erwagung  aber 
macht  es  wahrscheinlich,  dass  es  doch  nicht  sehr  viel  alter  ist. 
Sobald  das  Erbeinsetzungstestament  aufkam,  brachte  es  die  Gefahr 
mit  sich,  dass  der  heres  scriptus  infolge  von  Uberlastung  mit 
Legaten  die  cretio  unterliess  und  so  das  ganze  Testament  zum 
Scheitern  brachte.  Dieser  Gefahr  entgegenzutreten  hatte  man 
Ursache  sowohl  deshalb,  weil  man  damals  wohl  bereits  die  Ordnung 
der  Sukzession  durch  letzten  Willen  gegenuber  der  Intestaterbfolge 
begunstigte,  als  auch  deshalb,  weil  bei  der  Enge  des  Kreises  der 
heredes  legitimi  die  Intestaterbfolge  gewiss  sehr  oft  versagte,  ein 
insbesondere  fiir  die  Erbschaftsglaubiger  sehr  unerwiinschter  Fall. 
Die  altesten  Gesetze  nun,  die  nach  der  Uberlieferung3  jener 

1  Zu  Grunde  liegt  natiirlich  eine  cunroirjcris  im  griechischen  Vorbild. 

2  S.  auch  Lambert,  a.  a.  O. 

3  Gaius   ii.  225  f.      Diese  Uberlieferung  scheint   mir  aus   den   im    Text 
angefuhrten  Griinden  durchaus   glaublich,    und   ich   kann  mich   den  Schrift- 
stellern,  die  dem  iiberlieferten  Zweck  einen  anderen  substituieren  wollen  (vgl. 
besonders  Lambert,  a.  a.  O.  100,  Ehrlich,  Z.  f.  vgl.  Rwiss.  xvii.  104  f.),  nicht 
anschliessen.      Auch  an  eine  Verwandtschaft  der  Tendenz  der  lex  Furia  mit 
der  der  lex  Cintia  glaube  ich  nicht.      Die  Gefahr,  der  diese  entgegenwirken 
sollte,  bestand  bei  den  stets  widerruflichen  letztwilligen  Verfiigungen  nicht. 


v]  Romisckes  Testament  141 

Gefahr  zu  begegnen  bestimmt  waren,  die  leges  Furia  und  Voconia^ 
liegen  schwerlich  sehr  weit  auseinander,  und  die  lex  Voconia 
datiert  erst  vom  Jahre  169  v.  Chr.  Die  Tatsache  ist  vom  Stand- 
punkt  der  herrschenden  Meinung,  die  von  uraltersher  Erbein- 
setzung  und  Legate  nebeneinander  stehen  lasst,  auffallend  genug. 
Sie  lasst  sich  nicht  durch  die  Annahme  erklaren,  dass  in  alterer 
Zeit  Uberlastungen  des  heres  nicht  oder  nur  selten  vorgekommen 
seien.  Bewusst  wird  freilich  nicht  leicht  jemand  die  Erben  iiber- 
lasten,  wenn  er  weiss,  dass  von  ihrem  Antritt  die  Giltigkeit  des 
ganzen  Testamentes  abhangt ;  aber  unabsichtliche  Uberlastungen — 
infolge  von  Uberschatzung  des  Vermogensbestands,  nachtraglich 
eingetretener  Vermogensverluste,  neu  erwachsener  Schulden  - 
sind  bei  dem  Erbeinsetzungstestament  immer  eine  sich  leicht 
verwirklichende  Moglichkeit.  Sehr  einfach  lost  sich  das  Ratsel, 
wenn  man  unserer  Vermutung  folgt,  dass  die  Erbeinsetzung  selber 
die  lex  Furia  gar  nicht  so  sehr  an  Alter  iiberragt.1 

Wenn  der  Entwicklungsgang  des  testamentarischen  Erbrechts 
im  obigen  richtig  gezeichnet  sein  sollte,  so  tritt  das  altromische 
Erbrecht  aus  der  isolierten  Stellung  heraus,  die  es  nach  der 
herrschenden  Ansicht  gegeniiber  alien  anderen  Rechten  ahnlicher 
Entwicklungsstufe  einnehmen  wtirde.  Eine  Universalsukzession, 
die  unabhangig  ware  von  jeder  sei  es  leiblichen  sei  es  kiinstlichen 
Verwandtschaft,  hat  das  altromische  Recht  ebensowenig  gekannt 
wie  das  altgriechische  und  altdeutsche.  Das  altromische  Legaten- 
testament  stellt  sich  neben  die  Arrogation,  wie  das  altgriechische 
neben  die  cunroirpris,  wie  die  altdeutsche  donatio  post  obitum  neben 
die  affatomie  und  die  thingatio.  Sicherlich  bestehen  zwischen 
diesen  Rechtsinstituten  sehr  erhebliche  Unterschiede ;  aber  das 

1  Ahnliche  Folgerungen,  freilich  anders  motiviert,  zieht  auch  Lambert, 
nur  nicht  fur  das  Alter  der  Erbeinsetzung  iiberhaupt,  sondern  fur  den 
Zeitpunkt  ihres  Auftretens  im  Manzipationstestament. 

Wie  kommt  es,  dass  die  lex  Furia  die  Legate  so  mechanisch  durch 
Festsetzung  eines  absoluten  Maximums  einschrankte  ?  Wenn  die  Romer  von 
jeher  daran  gewohnt  waren,  iiber  ihr  ganzes  Vermogen  in  Form  von  Legaten 
zu  verfiigen,  so  begreift  sich,  dass  infolge  dieser  Gewohnheit  die  Einfiihrung 
der  Erbeinsetzung  in  die  Praxis  auf  Schwierigkeiten  stiess,  und  die  Tendenz 
der  lex  Fuiia  wird  gewesen  sein,  die  Testatoren  im  Interesse  der  Erbschafts- 
glaubiger  zu  notigen,  die  Hauptbedenkungen  in  die  Form  der  Erbeinsetzung 
zu  kleiden.  Dass  man  mit  dem  absoluten  Maximum  zu  weit  gegangen  war, 
wird  man  spater  eingesehen  haben,  und  so  trat  dann  an  seine  Stelle  das 
relative  der  lex  Voconia. 


142  O.  Lenel  [v 

ist  den  drei  Rechten  gemeinsam,  dass  der  Ausgangspunkt  des 
testamentarischen  Erbrechts  die  Einzelvergabung,  nicht  die  Erb- 
einsetzung  ist.  Die  Einfiihrung  und  Ausgestaltung  dieser  erscheint 
als  eine  Grosstat  der  romischen  Jurisprudenz,  ist  aber  auch 
nur  als  solche  verstandlich,  und  nicht  als  Produkt  primitiven 
Gewohnheitsrechts. 

O.  LENEL. 


VI 

NUMISMATIC    ILLUSTRATIONS    OF 
ROMAN    LAW 

I  FEAR  the  title  of  my  subject  is  somewhat  misleading.  Starting 
with  a  much  wider  plan,  I  find  myself  narrowed,  by  shortness  of 
time  for  the  making  and  the  reading  of  my  paper,  to  archaeological 
illustration  by  coins  only,  and  that  extending  over  a  comparatively 
limited  period. 

I  do  not  propose  to  enter  on  the  obscure  early  history  of  the 
subject,  but  will  accept  without  remark  what  I  think  is  still  the 
general  view,1  that  the  beginning  of  any  regular  coinage  at  Rome 
cannot  be  admitted  before  that  'codification  of  customary  law  by 
the  Decemviri,  in  which  I  still  believe,  and  which  is  dated  about 
450  B.C.  I  need  not  give  specimens  of  its  well-known  devices.  I 
incline  to  believe  the  head  of  Janus  borrowed  from  Greek  art.2 
The  ship's  prow  was  persistently  connected  by  the  Romans  them- 
selves with  victories  over  the  maritime  power  of  Antium,  by  some 
referred  to  a  time  just  before  the  Decemviri  (468  B.C.),3  by  some 
to  a  considerably  later  date  (338)  at  which  C.  Maenius  is  repre- 
sented as  carrying  the  rostra  of  the  Antiates  to  Rome.4  We  have 
an  obvious  reference  to  this  family  legend  in  a  triens  of  P.  Maenius 
AntiaticuSy  a  moneyer  of  no  B.C.5 

Of  the  political  changes  effected  at  this  time,  or  later,  by 
members  of  the  Maenian  gens  I  have  no  note  to  show  you. 

1  Babelon,  Monnaies  de  la  rtpublique  romaine,  Introd.  p.  vi. 

2  Babelon,  ib.  x. 

3  Livy  ii.  65  ;  Babelon,  ib.  vii. 

4  Pliny  xxxiv.  5.  II  ;  Livy  viii.  14. 

5  No.  i  on  p.  145  ;  Babelon  ii.  164  (see,  however,  Introd.  p.  vii.). 


144  E.  C.  Clark  [vi 

A  silver  coinage  was,  according  to  Pliny,  introduced  for  the  first 
time  at  Rome  in  269  B.C.,  a  date  when  the  defeat  of  Pyrrhus  and 
the  conquest  of  Southern  Italy  had  brought  a  supply  of  the  more 
precious  and  portable  metal  into  the  Treasury.1  Shortly  after- 
wards the  officers  charged  with  the  administration  of  the  mint 
began  to  insert 2  on  their  coins  both  of  bronze  and  silver  symbols 
of  high  office  held  by  some  member  of  their  family,  or  of  canting 
heraldry  on  its  name,  or  abbreviations  of  the  name  itself,  with 
which  I  will  not  trouble  you.  But  in  the  last  two  centuries  B.C. 
the  silver  coinage  came  to  bear  artistic  representations  of  family 
history  or  legend.  It  is  in  these  so-called  Consular  coins  that 
I  have  sought  to  find  some  record  of  the  political  movements 
or  of  the  stages  of  development  of  which  we  read  in  Roman 
Law.  I  am  afraid  I  must  confess  to  having  drawn  almost  a 
blank. 

With  but  few  exceptions  these  beautiful  denarii  refer  to  successes 
in  war  or  treaty  claimed  for  the  moneyer's  family,  to  its  divine 
or  heroic  lineage,  furnished  probably  by  some  Greek  Burke  or 
Debrett ;  but  very  little  to  such  ordinary  human  matters  as  the 
peaceful  growth  of  law. 

The  well-known  reverse  of  the  Dioscuri  is  now  most  frequently 
traced  to  a  prevalent  cult  in  maritime  Magna  Graecia,  where  a 
coasting  commerce  thoroughly  appreciated  a  clear  sky  with  the 
two  great  stars — lucida  sidera — in  the  stormy  nights  of  March. 
But  their  symbol  was  appropriated,  in  another  light  no  doubt,  by 
many  an  ancient  family  whose  ancestors  fought  at  the  battle  of 
the  Regillus,  as  some  of  our  own  were  at  Hastings  or  at  least 
came  over  with  the  Conqueror.  There  are,  however,  rather  special 
presentations  of  Castor  and  Pollux  washing  or  watering  their 
horses  '  at  the  well  that  springs  by  Vesta's  fane '  on  coins  struck 
by  members  of  the  gens  boasting  among  its  ancestors  the  dictator 
of  that  day.3  This  reverse  of  the  gens  Postumia  dates  actually 
from  89  B.C.  It  is  interesting  to  note  that  among  the  families 
which  were,  if  we  can  place  any  reliance  upon  the  Fasti,  of  com- 
paratively later  'arrival,'  we  find,  as  is  perhaps  not  unusual  in 
modern  times,  claims  of  the  highest  descent.  A  denarius,  for 

1  Ridgeway,  Origin  of  Currency  and  Weight-Standards^  p.  383. 

2  Babelon,  Introd.  p.  xxxiv. 

3  No.  2  on  p.  145  ;  Babelon  ii.  379. 


I.   Coh.  p.  Iviii.  Marcia  2. 


2.   Coh.  p.  xxxv.  Postumia  4. 


3.  Coh.  p.  xxvi.  Marcia  8. 


4.  Coh.  p.  xxxiv.  Pomponia  2. 


5.   Coh.  p.  xxiii.  Junia  12. 


6.  Coh.  xl.  Valeria  5. 


146  E.  C.  Clark  [vi 

instance,  of  the  Marcian  gens?  of  actual  date  about  60  B.C., 
besides  indicating  real  achievements  of  alliance  or  conflict  with  the 
last  kings  of  Macedonia,  or  of  bringing  the  first  great  aqueduct,  the 
Aqua  Marcia,  to  Rome,  will  find  a  founder  of  the  family  in  Ancus, 
the  august  doublet  of  Numa,  fourth  among  the  many  questionable 
predecessors  of  the  probably  historical  Tarquinii.  Beyond  this 
fabulous  ancestry  there  is  no  indication  of  patrician  rank  in  the 
Marcian  gens,  except  the  beautiful  story,  which  one  scarce  has 
the  heart  to  touch,  about  Caius  of  Corioli.  Neither  is  there 
among  the  Pomponii,  whose  heraldic  history  goes  back  to  Numa 
himself.2 

To  return,  however,  to  quasi  -  historical  times  of  the  early 
Republic,  I  have  sometimes  hazarded  the  suggestion  that  a  Junius 
in  the  first  reported  pair  of  Republican  Consuls  may  possibly 
indicate  some  tradition  of  a  brief  union  against  a  common  tyranny, 
and  some  idea  of  representing  both  orders  in  the  famous  dual 
magistracy,  which  was  not  permanently  realized  till  the  Licinian 
Rogations.  Anyhow  the  coin  which  was  struck  by  the  murderer 
of  Caesar  about  43  B.C.  represents  his  supposed  ancestor,  Brutus 
the  Ancient,  simply  in  a  dignified  procession  as  Consul?  It  has 
nothing  to  do  with  the  story  of  his  sons'  execution  which  Vergil 
skates  over  so  dexterously  in  the  6th  Aeneid  (820-824). 

With  regard  to  another  hero  of  the  same  revolution,  if  there  is 
in  the  coins  of  the  historical  Valerii  any  reference  to  the  ancient 
Publicola,  it  is  not  to  a  limitation  of  the  new  magistracy  by  an 
alleged  lex  de  provocatione,  but  solely  to  the  overthrow  of  the  old 
Royalty.4  Of  the  convenient  charge  of  conspiring  for  the  restora- 
tion (regni  affectandi)  of  kingly  power  we  have  a  memorial  in 
another  Junian  denarius  of  43  B.C.  Here  we  see,  coupled  with  the 
Brutus  of  the  early  Republic,5  that  Servilius  Ahala  who  is  so 
warmly  eulogized  in  Livy  (iv.  14)  for  the  butchery  of  Sp.  Maelius 
439  B.C.  And  to  the  alleged  informer  against  Maelius,  on  this 
occasion,  I  find  an  undoubted  reference  in  a  denarius  of  an  old 
plebeian  family.  This  informer  was,  we  are  told,  one  Lucius 

1  No.  3  on  p.  145  ;  Babelon  ii.  187,  197. 

2  Ib.  No.  4. 

8  Ib.  No.  5  ;  see  Cohen,  Texte,  174. 

*  Ib.  No.  6. 

5  No.  7  on  p.  147. 


7.  Coh.  p.  xxiii.  Junia  n. 


8.  Coh.  p.  xxviii.  Minucia  4. 


9.  Coh.  p.  xviii.  Flaminia  2. 


10.  Coh.  p.  xli.  Veturia. 


II.  Coh.  p.  xxxiv.  Porcia  3. 


148  E.  C.  Clark  [vi 

Minucius,  who  gained  a  temporary  popularity,  and  had  a  statue 
erected  to  him  (Livy  iv.  13,  16)  for  distributing  at  a  low  price  the 
confiscated  corn  stores  of  the  unfortunate  Maelius.  Here1  we 
have  the  corn  and  the  statue  on  the  coin  of  a  moneyer,  Ti. 
Minucius,  of  whose  cognomen  I  shall  speak  presently.  Besides 
this  Act  of  Attainder,  if  I  may  dignify  it  with  that  name,  there  is 
scarcely  any  numismatic  notice,  during  the  whole  time  occupied 
by  the  struggle  between  the  two  Orders,  of  aught  but  achievements 
in  the  field. 

Ap.  Claudius,  obviously  the  main  author  of  the  XII  Tables,  and 
probably  the  victim  of  an  aristocratic  reaction,  has  been  so 
successfully  blackened  by  family  spite  or  sensational  romancing 
that  we  are  not  surprised  to  find  little  record  but  lies  of  his 
legislation.  When  we  pass  on,  however,  to  the  influential  and 
wealthy  gens  Licinia,  in  which  the  family  of  Stolones  were  still  of 
high  rank  and  importance  under  Augustus,  we  look  naturally  for 
some  reference  to  the  famous  Rogations  of  367  B.C.  or  their  result. 
But  we  look  in  vain. 

Of  the  Q.  Publilius  Philo  who  comes  in  so  abruptly  in  Livy's 
8th  Book,  339  B.C.,  with  his  convenient  dictatorship  and  his  Junius 
Brutus  for  a  magister  equitum>  and  his  laws  anticipating  the  Hor- 
tensian  settlement  of  fifty  years  later — of  all  this  the  only  numismatic 
record  that  I  can  find  is  on  a  Greek  coin  of  Naples  (of  which  I  do 
not  give  a  drawing,  as  it  is  not  Roman),  apparently  referring  to  the 
dubious  success  gained  by  Publilius  about  this  time,  with  the  help 
of  a  traitor,  over  Palaepolis,  henceforth  Neapolis  (Naples).2 

To  take  up  once  again  the  strange  story  of  the  Claudian 
reformers,  on  whom  Mommsen  has  shed  the  first  true  light.  Claudii 
occur,  as  we  know,  still  bearing  the  ancient  name  of  Appius,  quite  to 
the  close  of  the  Republic.  But  there  is  no  record  on  their  denarii 
of  the  famous  Censorship  of  Ap.  Claudius  Caecus  in  312 — no 
Censorinus  to  follow,  though  that  achievement  is  common  in  at 
least  two  other  gentes.  One  trace  only  can  I  find  of  the  many 
consequences  of  Appius's  reform,  and  that  indirectly  as  a  result  of 
the  lex  Ogulnia^  which  law,  by  the  way,  is  entirely  ignored  in  the 
denarii  of  the  gens  Ogulnia  itself. 

The  lex  Ogulnia  of  300  B.C.,  as  we  learn  from  Livy,3  threw 

1  No.  8  on  p.  147.  2  Livy  viii.  26  ;  see  Babelon  i.  15. 

3  Livy  x.  6.  9. 


12.  Coh.  p.  xxxviii.  Silia. 


13.  Coh.  p.  x.  Calpurnia  24. 


14.  Coh.  p.  xviii.  Fufia. 


All  the  drawings,  except  the  last,  are  from  H.  Cohen's  Medailles  Consulaires,  1857  (Planches). 


150  E.  C.  Clark  [vi 

open  the  Pontificate  and  Augurate  to  the  Plebeians,  one  of  those 
elected  to  the  latter  office  being  a  Minucius.  It  is  clearly  to  the 
first  attainment  of  this  honour  by  one  of  the  family  that  the 
cognomen  Augurinus  refers  on  the  coin  last  cited.1  The 
whole  matter  may  seem  unimportant,  but  students  of  Roman 
Private  Law  know  how  much  of  its  development  results  from  this 
primarily  religious  career  becoming  ouverte  aux  talents. 

Of  the  dictatorship  of  Quintus  Hortensius  or  his  law,  which  fills 
so  important  a  place  in  our  legal  records,  I  can  find  no  illustration, 
nor  to  my  knowledge  does  a  gens  Hortensia  appear  at  all  on  any 
known  Republican  coin. 

The  introduction  of  a  silver  coinage  in  269,  of  which  I  spoke 
just  now,  is  by  many  good  authorities  connected  with  a  reduction 
of  the  original  heavy  bronze  (as  libralis}  to  what  was  practically  a 
token.2  It  is  perhaps  more  probable  that  this  was  a  depreciation 
of  the  coinage  due  to  the  troubles  of  the  First  Punic  War,  which  was 
followed  by  a  more  serious  one  during  those  of  the  Second.3  This 
last  reduction  is  generally  attributed  to  a  lex  Flaminia  connected 
with  the  name  of  the  unfortunate  general  who  fell  in  the  disastrous 
battle  of  Thrasimenus  in  217,  of  which  Livy  and  Polybius  make  him 
the  scapegoat.4  The  history  of  this  C.  Flaminius  is  important,  but 
obscure  to  a  degree.  He  is  undoubtedly  the  champion  of  the  later 
plebs  as  against  the  senatorial  party,  and  in  the  demoralization  of 
the  assemblies,  attributed  to  him,  we  clearly  recognize  a  principal 
turning-point  in  the  history  of  Rome.  Of  all  this  we  have  no 
numismatic  record.  I  hardly  dare  to  suggest  that  in  the  much 
contested  legend  of  a  Flaminian  denarius  we  may  possibly  recognize 
an  exceptional  attainment  of  the  rigidly  guarded  office  of  Flamen 
by  some  ancestor  of  low  birth,  and  even  the  formation  of  a  quasi- 
gentile  name.  I  refer  to  the  Pri.  Fla.  of  a  Flaminian  moneyer, 
struck  44  B.C.,  which  has  been  interpreted  Primus  Flamen?  though 
Mommsen,  more  in  accordance,  no  doubt,  with  the  rest  of  the  legend, 
reads  Primus  Flavit. 

I  wish  briefly  to  mention  here  a  reference  not  indeed  directly  to 
law,  but  to  an  early  treaty  between  Rome  and  some  Campanian  or 
other  Greek  nationality,  on  a  coin  of  the  Veturii,  the  idea  of  which 

1   No.  8  on  p.  147.  2  Babelon,   Introd.  p.  xiii. 

3  Pliny  xxiii.  44,  46.  4  Livy  xxii.  4-6  ;   Polybius  iii.  82,  83. 

5  No.  9  on  p.  147  ;  Babelon  i.  494,  496. 


iv]  Numismatic  Illustrations  1 5 1 

is  supposed  to  have  been  furnished  by  the  reduction  of  Capua  in 
2ITB.C.1  A  Roman  and  a  Greek  lay  their  hands  jointly  on  a  pig 
held  ready  for  sacrifice  by  a  sacerdos  fecialis.  This  is  interesting  as 
illustrating  Livy's  picturesque  account  (in  i.  24)  of  the  ancient 
ceremony  foedus  ferire. 

The  obscurity  surrounding  the  institution  of  a  second  Praetor, 
and  the  reform  in  Private  Law  which  we  vaguely  describe  as  the 
lex  Aebutia,  derive  no  light  from  numismatics. 

The  first  undoubted  direct  reference  to  a  historical  enactment 
on  a  coin  is  to  be  found  in  the  provoco  of  Publius  Laeca,  a  moneyer 
of  about  no  B.C.2  It  symbolizes  that  final  narrowing  of  the 
imperium  which  was  effected  in  the  leges  Porciae.  This  appeal 
against  sentence  of  flogging  was  carried  or  first  brought  forward  in 
199  B.C. 

A  denarius  of  about  the  same  minting  date  (no  B.C.)  by  P. 
Licinius  Nerva,  gives  an  interesting  representation  of  the  ballot- 
voting  introduced  by  his  ancestor  C.  Licinius  Crassus  in  145  B.C.3 
The  voter,  you  see,  steps  up  to  the  rogator,  receives  his  ballot,  and 
passes  singly  over  the  pans  to  deposit  it  in  the  urn. 

What  was  practically  a  beginning  of  the  largesses  of  the  later 
Republic  and  the  Empire  may  be  recognized  in  a  coinage 
expressly  issued  to  meet  a  scarcity  of  corn  under  the  lexfrumen- 
taria  of  Saturninus,  100  B.C.4  Note  the  quaestors  ad  fru\inentuin\ 
emu\ndum~\  (Piso,  Caepio,  Q.)  and  the  head  of  Saturn  with  hisfa/x, 
for  the  Treasury,  and  probably  a  reference  to  the  name  Saturninus. 

The  end  of  the  formidable  Social  War,  and  the  incorporation 
of  the  Italian  allies  with  the  Roman  people,  is  indicated  in  a  denarius 
of  the  genus  Fufia?  This  striking  coin  of  the  moneyer  Q.  Fufius 
Calenus  is  dated  by  Babelon  82  B.C.,  when  the  pacification  of  Italy 
was  completed. 

In  the  stormy  close  of  the  Republic  there  are  not  wanting 
occasional  coins  of  legal  or  political  significance,  nor  in  the  Julian 
and  Augustan  or  in  the  first  centuries  of  the  Empire  generally. 
These  I  am  obliged  to  omit  for  lack  of  time.  In  one  coin  only  I 

1  No.  10  on  p.  147  ;  Babelon  ii.  534. 

2  Ib.  No.  1 1  ;  Babelon  ii.  370. 

3  No.  12  on  p.  149  ;  Babelon  ii.  129  ;  see  Varro,  De  re  rustica,  ii.  2. 

4  Ib.  No.  13  ;  Babelon  i.  288. 

5  Ib.  No.  14  ;  Babelon  i.  512. 


152  E.  C.  Clark  [vi 

should  like  to  bring  to  your  notice  what  has  been  regarded  as  the 
numismatic  record  of  a  wider  gift  of  Roman  citizenship  than  that  last 
mentioned,  in  fact  throughout  the  Roman  world,  in  orbe  Romano,  as 
Ulpian  says.1  This  gift  is  attributed  by  Justinian  2  to  the  Emperor 
Antoninus  Pius,  erroneously,  as  is  usually  held  by  modern  writers 
on  the  strength  of  a  passage  in  Dio  Cassius,3  which  gives  the 
credit,  though  not  on  any  very  high  ground,  to  Caracalla,  who 
amongst  several  other  later  Emperors  debased  that  honoured  name. 
There  is,  however,  in  the  Cabinet  de  France  a  bronze  medallion  of 
Pius4  bearing  the  striking  legend  Ampliatori  civium  within  a  wreath 
of  oak-leaves.  That  this  really  refers  to  a  vast  extension  of  citizen- 
ship by  that  great  and  humane  Emperor  has  been  strongly 
maintained  by  authorities  who  were  quite  aware  of  the  passage  in 
Dio.5  The  difficulties  arising  in  subsequent  law  are  about  the  same 
in  both  cases.  This  medallion  is  placed  by  Cohen  between  A.D. 
140  and  143.  The  disputed  question  as  to  its  meaning  I  leave 
to  you.6 

E.  C.  CLARK. 

1  Dig.  1.  5.  17. 

2  Nov.  78.  5. 

3  Dio  Cassius,  Ixxvii.  9. 

4  Cohen,  Monnaies  de   VEmpire,  ii.  347,  no.   789  ;    see  last  drawing  on 
p.  149. 

5  E.g.  Hommel. 

6  The  discovery  of  the  papyrus  published  as  P.  Giess.  40  seems,  as  has 
been  pointed  out  to  me  by  Professor  Lenel,  to  confirm  the  conclusion   that 
thejan^ersaypaji^-oiURDjman  citizenship  is  to  be_attribute.d_to  Caracalla.      I 
still  think  that  the  medallion  of  Pius  may  refer  to  some  less  advanced  or  less 
effective  measure  in  the  same  direction,  of  which  we  otherwise  know  nothing. 


VII 

COTTER  UND  TOTE  ALS  RECHTS- 
SUBJEKTE  BEI  DEN  ALTEN  GERMANEN 

UNTER  Rechtssubjekt  verstehen  wir  ein  Wesen,  das  Rechte  (und 
allenfalls  auch.  Pflichten)  haben  kann.  Wir  nennen  ein  solches 
Wesen  auch  Person  im  Rechtssinne.  Die  Gottheit  in  unserem 
modernen  Sinne  ist  sicherlich  auch  Person.  Wir  legen  ihr  Vernunft, 
Willen,  Handlungsfahigkeit  bei.  Wir  glauben  an  einen  personlichen 
Gott.  Aber  unser  Gott  ist  Person  nur  im  moralischen,  im  ethischen 
Sinne.  Nicht  im  Rechtssinn.  Unser  Gott  ist  nicht  Eigentumer 
im  Rechtssinn. 

Anders  schon  das  Mittelalter.  Das  Mittelalter  spricht  Gott  und 
den  Heiligen  Rechtspersonlichkdt  zu.  Sie  haben  Eigentum  an 
Grundstiicken  und  Fahrnis.  Sie  haben  Vasallen,  Dienstmannen 
und  Horige.  Die  Heiligen  gehen  Vertrage  ein  und  werden  daraus 
berechtigt  und  verpflichtet.  Sie  haben  offentliche  Rechte.  Die 
Rolle  des  heiligen  Petrus  in  der  Entwicklung  der  staats-  und 
kirchenrechtlichen  Verhaltnisse  ist  bekannt.  Gott  als  Grundherr 
und  Eigentumer  der  Welt  hat  Anspruch  auf  Zehent.  Raub  von 
Kirchengut  ist  Beraubung  Gottes  und  seiner  Heiligen.  Das  hat 
bereits  vor  rund  50  Jahren  Otto  Gierke  festgestellt  und  voll  ein- 
dringend  erortert. 

Ich  meine,  man  kann  eine  solche  iiberaus  lebendige,  sinnliche 
Auffassung  auch  schon  im  vorchristlichen  Germanentum  nach- 
weisen.  Die  anthropomorphistisch  theokratische  Anschauung 
des  Mittelalters  findet  sich  bereits  im  germanischen  Altertum 
vorgebildet.  Nicht  nur  im  Keim,  sondern  womoglich  noch  viel 
sinnlicher. 

Es  scheint  mir  reizvoll,  diesem  Problem  nachzugehen,  umsomehr, 
als  sich  <3abei  tiefere  Einblicke  in  die  Rechtsinstitutionen  des 


154  H.  Schreuer  [vn 

menschlichen  Verkehrs  ergeben.  In  einer  in  Kiirze  erscheinenden 
Publikation  1  biete  ich  eingehende  Erorterungen.  Hier  mochte  ich 
eine  gedrangte  Ubersicht  der  Hauptresultate  vorfuhren,  die  sich 
mir  ergeben  haben. 


I.  DAS  WESEN  DER  GERMANISCHEN  COTTER 

Es  ist  notwendig,  zuerst  das  Wesen  der  germanischen  Cotter 
einigermassen  herauszuarbeiten.  Die  germanischen  Cotter,  soweit 
wir  ihrer  habhaft  werden  konnen,  sind  von  Haus  aus  reale  Machte, 
die  sich  handgreiflich  bemerkbar  machen.  Caesar  B.  G.  vi.  21  nennt 
Sol,  Vulcanus,  Luna ;  reliquos  ne  fama  quidem  acceperunt.  Das 
waren  also  zunachst  Naturkrafte,  die  uns  als  gegebene,  aussermen- 
schliche  und  iibermenschliche  Machte  von  ungeheurer  Wirksamkeit 
entgegentreten,  die  man  zu  spiiren  bekommt.  Das  ware  das  Reale. 
Die  Naturvolker  lieben  es  aber,  Krafte,  denen  sie  begegnen, 
als  Ausserungen  menschenahnlicher  Subjekte  sich  vorzustellen. 
Hinter  den  Naturerscheinungen  von  Sonne,  Mond  und  Blitz 
(Feuer)  sieht  der  Germane.  Wesen,  die  der  menschlichen  Seele  ver- 
wandt  sind.  Die — wirklichen  oder  auch  eingebildeten — Funkzionen 
von  Sonne,  Blitz  und  Mond  sind  ihm  Tatigkeiten  psychischer 
Wesen.  Der  Schade,  den  sie  verursachen,  erscheint  ihm  als 
Feindseligkeit,  der  Nutzen  als  Wohlwollen  (Animatismus,  Animis- 
mus).  Die  Ohnmacht  des  Menschen  gegeniiber  den  Naturgewalten 
wird  so  zur  Unterordnung  unter  die  Herrschaft  ubermachtiger 
Cotter.  Es  ist  kein  Wunder,  dass  man  diesen  uberlegenen  Geistern 
auch  hoheres  Wissen  beilegt. 

So  schon  nach  den  Angaben  Caesars.  Dies  beweist  unter 
Anderem  der  Gebrauch  von  Orakel  und  Opfer.  Vulcanus  ist  der 
germanische  Thonaraz,  Sol  ist  Tiwaz.  Es  kann  auch  gar  kein 
Zweifel  sein,  dass  diese  Cotter  mannlich  gedacht  sind.  Ihnen 
gegenuber  steht  eine  weibliche  Gottheit,  Luna,  wie  ich  meine  die 
weibliche  Gottheit  KO.T  efox^.  Das  ist  schon  eine  sehr  weitgehende 
Vermenschlichung. 

Noch  weiter  geht  die  Vermenschlichung  der  Cotter  nach  den 
Angaben  des  Tacitus.  Die  Cotter  stehen  da  zu  einander  in  men- 
schlichen Familienverhaltnissen,  ja  die  germanischen  Volker  leiten 
ihre  Herkunft  von  den  Gottern  ab,  vor  allem  von  dem  uralten 

1  ZSS,  1913. 


vn]  Goiter  und  Tote  1 55 

Haupt-  und  Obergott  Tin.  Ich  glaube  nicht  zu  viel  zu  sagen, 
wenn  ich  den  Germanen  auch  eine  gottliche  Stammesmutter, 
etwa  kurz  gesagt,  die  Mutter  Erde,  zuschreibe.  Nicht  mit  alien 
physiologischen  Einzelheiten,  aber  doch  unter  Festhaltung  der 
Familienrechtsbegriffe  :  Vater  und  Mutter. 

Diese  Auffassung  hat  sich  mir  als  gemeingermanisch,  urger- 
manisch  ergeben.  Die  Germanen  sind  von  Haus  aus  Tiu-Sohne 
gewesen,  wie  es  noch  zur  Zeit  des  Tacitus  ganz  besonders  die 
Herminonen  (Sueben),  speziell  die  Semnonen  sind.  Ja  ich  bin 
sehr  geneigt,  diese  Vorstellungen  als  arisches  Urerbe  anzusehen. 

Diese  Versippung  der  Gotterwelt  mit  dem  Menschengeschlechte 
ist  fur  das  religiose  aber  auch  fur  das  Rechtsleben  von  tiefstgrei- 
fender  Bedeutung. 

Gotter  und  Menschen  sind  durch  den  Friedens-  und  Rechts- 
verband  der  Sippe  organisch  zusammengeschlossen.  In  religioser 
Beziehung  tritt  zur  Macht  die  Liebe,  die  Innigkeit.  In  juristischer 
Beziehung  erscheint  die  sakrale  Gotterherrschaft  ahnenkultlich 
konstruiert.  Die  religiose  Vorstellung  der  Gotterherrschaft  wird 
durch  das  ahnenkultliche  Element  der  rnenschlichen  Rechtsordnung 
eingegliedert. 

II.  RECHTSSTELLUNG  DES  TOTEN 

Die  Verschmelzung  der  Gotter  mit  den  Ahnen  fiihrt  auf  die 
Rechtsstellung  des  Toten.  Die  Lehre  von  der  Fortdauer  der 
Rechtspersonlichkeit  nach  dem  Tode  ist  in  letzter  Zeit  namentlich 
durch  Heinrich  Brunner  belebt  und  vertieft  worden.  Einiges 
kann  ich  aus  eigenen  Untersuchungen,  die  nun  neun  Jahre  zuriick- 
liegen,  hinzufiigen. 

Nach  altgermanischer  Anschauung  erlischt  die  Personlichkeit 
des  Menschen  mit  dem  Tode  nicht.  Im  Gegenteil  bewirkt  der  Tod 
eher  eine  Steigerung  der  Personlichkeit  an  Wissen  und  Konnen. 
Fiir  das  Rechtsgebiet  kann  man  geradezu  den  Grundsatz  aufstellen, 
dass  prinzipiell  die  Rechtsfahigkeit  und  die  Handlungsfahigkeit, 
dass  die  Rechtsverhaltnisse,  soweit  nicht  besondere  Griinde 
eintreten,  auch  nach  dem  Tode  fortbestehen.  Als  Sitte  und  Pietat 
ragen  ja  diese  Vorstellungen  noch  in  unsere  Tage  hinein.  Nach 
altgermanischem  Rechte  dauert  das  Personenrecht  des  Toten  fort. 
Schon  am  Korper  kann  eine  Ehrung,  Beschimpfung,  Bestrafung 
des  Toten  vollzogen  werden.  Die  eheliche  Treue  und  die  Gefolg- 


156  H.  Schreuer  [vn 

schaft  wahren  liber  das  Grab  hinaus.  Ebenso  das  Vermogensrecht. 
Der  Tote  hat  Eigentum  an  seinem  Grabe  (als  an  seiner  Behausung) 
und  an  Allem,  was  er  mitbekommt. 

Mit  eherner  Logik  und  in  scharfster  Auspragung  haben  die 
Romer  das  Recht  des  Toten  festgehalten.  ^^paterfamilias 
bleibt  Rechtssubjekt  seines  Vermogens.  So  erklart  sich  m.  E.  die 
eigentiimliche  Anschauung,  dass  der  Erbe,  der  heres^  die  Person- 
lichkeit  des  Toten  in  sich  aufnimmt,  dass  er  sie  fortsetzt.  Daher 
auch  die  ungeheuer  friihzeitige  Testirfreiheit  der  Romer.  Weil 
eben  dem  Toten  wie  bei  Lebzeiten  das  Gut  gehort,  und  zwar  das 
ganze  Gut,  darum  kann  der  Lebende  ohne  weiteres  liber  den  Tod 
hinaus  dariiber  verfiigen.  Noch  tiefer  fassend  und  in  fernste  Zeiten 
zuriickgreifend  wird  man  wohl  sagen  diirfen,  dass  auch  die  patria 
potestas  den  Sohnen,  den  sui  heredes,  durch  Absorpzion  der  Seele 
des  Vaters  iiberkommen  sei.  Die  romischen  Begrabnis-  und 
Totengebrauche  zeigen  die  zu  Grunde  liegende  Anschauung  in 
grosser  Lebhaftigkeit.  Der  Tote  lebt  in  dem  Erben  fort. 

Auch  bei  den  Germanen  stirbt  der  Tote  nicht.  Der  Tote, 
der  Ahn,  bleibt  insbesondere  Eigentiimer  seines  Hauses,  er  bleibt 
Hausherr.  Noch  im  Mittelalter  ist  im  deutschen  Handgemal,  im 
englischen  frumstol,  eftel,  im  nordischen  d§al — kurz  im  Erbgut  der 
Gedanke  von  Eigentum  und  Herrschaft  des  Toten  lebendig.  Noch 
in  spater,  geschichtlicher  Zeit  okkupiert  ein  toter  Norweger 
(Kvelldulfr]  Land  auf  Island.  Und  ausdriicklich  erklaren  die 
Hochsitzpfeiler  des  nordischen  Bauernhauses,  die  ondvegissulur, 
dass  an  dem  Hochsitz  die  Seele  des  Ahnen  hause.  Auch  fiir  das 
deutsche  Institut  des  sog.  „  Dreissigsten  "  und  dessen  Parallele,  das 
nordische  Erbbier,  muss  ich  —  entgegen  Homeyer  —  als  den  einen 
Grundgedanken  das  Recht  des  Toten  in  Anspruch  nehmen. 

Selbst  die  familienrechtliche  Gewalt  des  Hausvaters  bleibt 
bestehen.  Nicht  nur  folgt  ihm  freiwillig  die  Treue  liber  das  Grab. 
Der  Tote  erscheint  auch  selbst  und  stellt  Forderungen.  Bei  wich- 
tigen  Anlassen  wird  er  beschworen  und  um  Weisungen  ersucht. 

'Andererseits  zeigen  die  germanischen  Anschauungen  gegenliber 
dem  romischen  Recht  eine  Abschwachung  der  Rechte  des  Toten. 
Der  Tote  ist  da  nicht  Eigentiimer  seines  ganzen  Nachlasses,  wie  in 
Rom.  Er  erhalt  bios  bestimmte  Vermogensstiicke  oder  eine 
Quote,  kurz  den  Totenteil.  Das  entspricht  aber  dem  Verhaltnis 
schon  bei  Lebzeiten.  Schon  bei  Lebzeiten  steht  das  Vermogen  in 


vn]  Cotter  und  Tote  157 

gemeinschaftlichem  Eigentum  der  Familienglieder,  allerdings  unter 
voller  Gewere  des  Vaters.  Ich  will  ganz  davon  absehen,  in  wiefern 
die  Bestattung  ausserhalb  des  Hauses,  der  Gedanke  von  Walhall 
und  christlichem  Jenseits  nach  germanischer  Anschauung  losend 
wirken  musste.  In  dem  deutschen  „  Dreissigsten "  sehe  ich  als 
zweiten  Grundgedanken  die  Abfindung,  Abschichtung  des  aus- 
wandernden  Toten.  Aber  schon  fur  die  Urzeit  tritt  der  Gesichts- 
punkt  in  Kraft,  dass  die  laufende  Ausiibung  der  Rechte  dem 
Toten  genomnen  war.  Die  Gewere  hat  der  Erbe.  (Dieser  Vor- 
stellung  mag  auch  der  spatere  Satz  entsprechen :  Le  mort  saisit 
le  vif.)  So  ergibt  sich  ein  Nebeneinander,  Miteinander  in  der 
Herrschaft,  in  dem  Haus-  und  Familienregiment  des  Ahnen  und 
des  Erben.  Der  Erbe  hat  eine  unmittelbare  Gewere,  die  in  histo- 
rischer  Entwicklung  leicht  zu  Nutzungseigentum  und  schliesslich 
Ablosung,  Abstossung  des  Obereigentums  fiihrt. 


III.  DAS  RECHT  DER  COTTER  UND  MENSCHENRECHT 

Zieht  man  nun  das  ahnenkultliche  Element  der  altgermanischen 
Religion  heran,  so  werden  nicht  nur  diese  erbrechtlichen  Grundsatze 
bekraftigt.  Durch  das  Totenrecht  tritt  auch  das  Sakralrecht  mit 
juristischer  Plastik  hervor  —  sowohl  das  sakrale  Vermogensrecht, 
wie  das  sakrale  Personenrecht.  Zweifellos  ist  die  Gottheit  Eigen- 
tiimerin  ihres  Haines,  ihres  Tempels,  ihrer  Schatze,  der  Tiere  in 
ihrem  Gehege..  Auch  die  bekannten  nordischen  Privattempel  sind 
Eigentum  der  Gottheit.  Der  Gode  ist  von  Haus  aus  nur  Priester,  wie 
die  Gydja  Priesterin.  Als  solcher  ist  er  allerdings  Organ  der  Gott- 
heit ;  er  fiihrt  deren  Handlungen  aus  ;  er  libt  Amtsgewere,  diedann 
freilich  weitgehender  Sakularisierung,  Allodialisierung  fahig  ist. 
Ja  selbst  der  einfache  Hausvater  ist  in  seiner  Stellung  als  Haus- 
und  Grundherr  transzendental,  gotter-  und  ahnenkultlich  verankert. 
Der  Hausfriede  ist  nicht  sein  Friede  sondern  sakral.  Die  zwangs- 
weisen  Grundanweisungen  durch  die  Fiirsten  Caesars  konnen  nur 
durch  das  sakrale  Eigentum  resp.  Obereigentum  der  in  der 
Volksversammlung  anwesenden  Gottheit  erklart  werden.  Und  noch 
in  spatgeschichtlicher  Zeit  weisen  Heiligkeit  der  Grenzzeichen, 
feierliche  Umgange,  das  nordischefara  eldium  landit,  der  Hammer- 
wurf  u.  A.  auf  die  sakrale  Wurzel  des  Grundeigentums.  Auch  im 


158  H.  Schreuer  [vn 

Personenrecht  regiert  die  Gottheit,  die  vom  Konige,  Landespriester 
oder  Hausvater  um  ihre  Weisung  befragt  wird. 

Die  Heiligkeit  der  Eltern  aber  auch  die  Banngewalt  der 
Obrigkeit,  die  iubendi  potestas  hat  eine  gotter-  und  ahnenkultliche 
Wurzel.  Das  cogere  der  principes  Caesars,  dessen  magistratus, 
qui  vitae  necisque  habent  potestatem,  all  das  ist  bei  dem  charakter- 
istischen  Unabhangigkeitssinn  der  Germanen  nur  auf  sakraler 
Grundlage  moglich. 

IV.  DER  RECHTSVERKEHR 

Es  eriibrigen  noch  einige  Worte  zu  der  Frage,  wie  sich  diese 
transzendenten  Rechtssubjekte  im  Rechtsverkehr  dieser  Welt 
geltend  machen.  Sie  bringen  sich  selbstandig  oder  befragt,  be- 
schworen  durch  sinnlich  wahrnehmbare  Ausserungen  zur  Geltung. 
Es  sind  reale  Geschehnisse,  die  als  Ausserungen  der  gottlichen 
Ahnen,  Freunde  oder  Feinde,  gedeutet  werden.  Die  Personen,  an 
welche  und  durch  welche  sich  die  Gottheit  an  die  anderen  wendet, 
erscheinen  da  in  priesterlicher  Funkzion.  Von  besonderer  Wich- 
tigkeit  sind  dabei  gewisse  Attribute  der  Gottheit.  Uber  die 
Vorstellungen,  welche  hier  durchgreifen,  gibt  vor  Allen  Tacitus 
Auskunft :  Deum  adesse  bellantibus  credunt.  Effigiesque  et  signa 
quaedam  detracta  lucis  in  proelium  ferunt.  Diese  Wahrzeichen 
des  Gottes  sind  Wahrzeichen  seiner  Anwesenheit.  Der  Gott  ist 
da,  sichtbar  durch  sein  Wahrzeichen.  Derjenige,  der  das  Wahr- 
zeichen handhabt,  ist  ein  Werkzeug  in  der  Hand  des  Gottes.  Er 
bringt  den  gottlichen  Willen  zur  sichtbaren,  vernehmbaren  Aus- 
serung.  Daher  umgekehrt :  wer  das  Wahrzeichen  des  Gottes  hat, 
ist  dessen  Priester,  Bote,  Stellvertreter.  Daher  soil  der  islandische 
Gode,  wenn  er  in  Funkzion  tritt,  den  Opferring  an  der  Hand 
tragen.  Dann  ist  es  der  Gott,  der  aus  ihm  spricht.  So  wird  mit 
dem  Feuer  das  Land  geheiligt,  ebenso  mit  dem  Hammer  Thors 
das  Land  ausgemessen.  Das  ist  die  tiefere  Bedeutung  des  germa- 
nischen  Konigsspeers,  der  Konigsfahne,  des  Schwertes  und  wohl  auch 
des  Gerichtsstabes.  Noch  die  spateren  Kronungsformeln  lassen 
den  Stab  als  Zauberstab  erkennen.  Auch  hier  tritt  der  Gedanke 
der  Amtsgewere  und  Allodialisierung  ein  :  Der  Bote  wird  zum 
Stellvertreter,  dieser  zum  Eigenberechtigten  von  Gottes  Gnaden. 

H.  SCHREUER. 


VIII 

THE  MEANING  OF  THE  WORDS  6DAL 
AND  SKEYTING  IN  THE  OLD  LAWS  OF 
NORWAY 

I.  THE  LEGAL  TERMINOLOGY 

O§al. — If  we  consider  the  terms  used  in  contrast  to  the  word  cftal, 
we  shall  best  understand  its  original  meaning. 

The  first  term  of  this  kind  is  aurar  (moveables).  This  distinc- 
tion is  observed  throughout  in  the  oldest  of  our  legal  sources,  the 
Gulat  kings  law.  A  deceased  person's  property  is  either  oftal  or 
aurar  \  tertium  non  datur.1  In  ihe  Pros  tat  kings  law,  dated  100 
years  earlier,  we  find  the  same  distinction  indicated  by  the  words 
jgr^>  and  aurar? 

Another  term  used  in  contradistinction  to  cfcal  isfyng  (acquired 
land) 3  or  kaupijqrft  (purchased  land).4  The  last  distinction  also  re- 
appears in  the  Frostathingslaw,  where  we  find  kauplendingr  (the 
owner  of  kaupland  or  kaupijqr^}  distinguished  from  &§alsma!§r 
(the  odaller).5  In  the  Landslaw  of  Magnus  Lagab0tir  (the  Law- 
mender),  1 274,  fqng  and  kaupijqtQ  are  comprised  in  the  term  utjqr'S 
(outland).6 

S  key  ting. — The  s  key  ting  (L&\..  scotatid]  is  the  very  ancient  Scan- 
dinavian form  for  '  transfer  of  property  in  land.'  This  at  least  is  the 
communis  opinio  doctorum?  But  in  my  opinion  the  correct  defini- 
tion of  the  legal  act  of  skeyting  is  this  :  the  skeyting  is  originally 
the  legal  form  for  '  transfer  of  $fo/-right  in  $fo/-land.'  '  To  buy  land 

1  G.  103,  104;  cpr.  270,  275.  2  F.  v.  13;  cpr.  G.  53. 

3  G.  285.  4  G.  223.  5  F.  xiii.  25.  6  L.  v.  7. 

7  See  Ebbe  Hertzberg,  Glossary  to  the  Old  Laws  of  Norway,  s.v.  '  Skeyting.' 

159 


160  A.  Tar  anger  [vm 

for  skeyting'  (at  kaupa  jqr§  til  skeytingar)1  is  the  same  as  'to  buy 
land  for  ffiat'  (at  kaupa  jqr^  ser  til  cftals}?  The  old  provincial  laws 
for  Gulathing3  and  Frostathing4  only  use  the  terms  skeyta  and 
skeyting  in  connexion  with  transfer  of  <ftta/-land,  and  the  same  is 
the  case  in  Lands  law? 


II.  THE  ORIGINAL  MEANING  OF  ODAL  AND  SKEYTING 

In  1907  Professor  Vinogradoff  published  in  the  Harvard  Law 
Review  a  paper  on  '  Transfer  of  Land  in  Old  English  Law.'  It  is 
this  paper  which  has  prompted  me  to  make  the  following  remarks 
about  the  original  meaning  of  the  words  &§al  and  skeyting  in  the 
old  laws  of  Norway. 

As  to  the  general  meaning  of  the  word  d$al\  it  signifies  the 
family -ownership  of  land,  and  also  land  as  the  object  of  such 
ownership.  Mr.  Hertzberg  in  his  Glossary  of  our  old  laws,  how- 
ever, has  put  this  conception  of  the  word  as  a  secondary  one,  and 
has  made  it  evident,  or  at  least  tried  to  make  it  evident,  that  the 
original  legal  meaning  of  cfoal  was  simply  ownership  in  land  and 
land  as  an  object  of  such  ownership.  The  word  concerns  only 
property  in  land  or  soil. 

My  own  investigations  have  led  me  to  the  same  conclusion. 
But  what  does  '  property  in  land '  indicate  ?  What  kind  of  '  land  ' 
is  owned  ? 

Everywhere  in  the  Teutonic  world  we  observe  that  the  oldest 
valuation  of  land  only  comprises  the  arable  land.  And  I  believe  it 
to  be  just  as  certain  that  only  the  arable  land  originally  was  the 
object  of  ownership.  The  real  basis  of  land-ownership  is  the  tilling 
of  the  soil.6 

Having  studied  our  old  laws,  particularly  the  oldest  one,  the 
Gulathing -slaw \  I  found  that  the  real  $ta/-land  was  the  arable  land, 

1  G.  278,  279.  2  F.  xii.  4.  3  G.  278,  279,  292. 

4  F.  xii.  i,  2,  4  ;  ix.  4  (jqtfS).      I  do  not  think  that  F.  xii.  i  is  against  my 
opinion,  that  the  common  intention  of  the  skeyting  originally  is  transfer  of 
<?oW-right  in  <?3tf/-land  ;  but,  as  I  will  show  later  on  (p.  1 70),  the  skeyting  in  F. 
has  more  the  character  of  transferring  the  gewere  than  that  of  transfer  of  a 
'  right.'      This  was  formerly  my  view  of  the  skeyting ;   see  my  paper  '  Den 
norske  besiddelsesret '  in  Tidsskrift  for  Retsvidenskab,  x.  105  sqq. 

5  L.  vi.  8,  10. 

6  Adolf  Astrom,  Svensk  jordaganderatt  (Stockholm,  1897),  has  treated  this 
subject  at  large  and  in  a  very  convincing  way. 


vni]  Odal  and  Skeyting  161 

the  tilled  ground,  the  '  fenced-in '  fields,  meadows  and  pastures,  in 
fact  the  homestead.  This  is  the  original  6$al,  both  in  the  vulgar  and 
the  legal  meaning  of  the  word.1  We  have  two  convincing  evidences 
of  this  fact.  The  one  is  the  act  of  &§alsskipti>  the  other  is  the  act 
of  skeyting. 

The  act  of  6§alsskipti  (division  of  the  o^af)  is,  according  to  the 
Gulathingslaw,  87,  only  a  division  of  houses  or  tilled  ground  (hus 
&8a  JQrti),  or  of  b<t>ar  (townships).  The  division  of  mountain- 
pastures  (s&tr)  or  forest  (mqrk)  is  regulated  in  quite  a  different 
way  in  G.  86. 

The  act  of  skeyting  is  once  described  in  the  Gulathingslaw  before 
its  revision  by  King  Olaf  the  Saint  (ob.  A.D.  1030)  or  King  Magnus 
Erlingsson  (A.D.  1 163).  Of  this  description  we  still  have  a  notice  in 
G.  292,  which  gives  us  a  clear  idea  of  its  peculiarities. 

The  most  essential  act  of  the  skeyting  was  the  '  mould-taking ' 
(moldtaka\  generally  performed  by  the  seller ;  but  if  the  seller 
refused  to  perform  this  duty,  the  purchaser  himself  might  do  so. 
In  the  latter  case  G.  292  provides :  '  He  shall  take  the  mould 
according  to  the  order  of  the  law  :  Take  some  mould  from  the  four 
corners  of  the  hearth,  from  the  seat  of  honour  (the  gndvegissceti, 
the  'high  seat'),  from  where  the  field  and  meadow  meet,  from  where 
the  fenced-in  pastureland  and  grove  meet.' 2  From  other  sources 
we  know  that  the  mould  thus  taken  was  cast  into  the  lap  (skauf) 
of  the  purchaser,  and  hence  the  whole  ceremony  was  named 
skeyting)  which  verbally  would  correspond  to  an  English  word 
'  lapping '  (from  c  lap  '). 

This  old  ceremony  of  skeyting  takes  us  back  to  the  very 
primitive  days  of  Norwegian  peasant  life.  We  find  ourselves  in 
the  ancient  peasant  house  with  its  hearth  in  the  middle  of  the 

1  According  to  Falk  u.  Torp,  Etym.  WB.^  d§al  means  "  « eigentum,  heimat, 
vaterland,  grundbesitz,   vorkaufrecht '  =  ags.    6]?el,   e]?el    'heimatland,'  afries. 
othol,  ethel,  as.  othil  *  erbgut,'  oht.  uodal  in  ders.  bedeut.  ;  vgl.  got.  haimopli 
'  heimatliches    gut.'       Eine    urspriinglichere    bedeutung    liegt   vor    in   poet, 
anord.  otSal  'gemiit,  natur,  wesen '  =  aoal,  eoli.     Daraus  entwickelte  sich  die 
bedeutung  « geschlecht,  herkunft '  (so  bei  anord.  eoli  und  bei  adel)  und  daraus 
wieder  'heimat'  usw.     Die  alteste  bedeutung  der  wortgruppe  ware  'einge- 
weide,'  falls  as.  inothri,   ahd.    inuodili    und   inadiri   '  eingeweide,'   Gr.   ^TO/>, 
'hertz'  verwandt  sind." 

2  *  Hann  £  mold  at   taca  sem  i  logum  er  maelt :  Taca  at  arenshornom 
fiorum  oc  i  ondveges   saete.      oc  ]?ar  sem   acr  oc  eng  m0tezt.   oc  ]?ar  sem 
holt  oc  hage  m0tezt.' 

M 


1 62  A.  Tar  anger  [vm 

earthen  floor,  and  the  seat  of  honour,  belonging  to  the  master, 
placed  in  direct  contact  with  the  same  earthen  floor.  The  hearth 
and  the  high  seat  were  the  chief  things  within  the  old  <?&z/-house 
of  Norway.  The  ancient  Norwegian  peasant,  looking  at  his  oftal- 
homestead,  would,  I  believe,  consider  himself  as  much  a  lord  as 
the  English  landowner  when  he  declares,  '  My  house  is  my 
castle.'1  Nobody  could  enter  against  the  will  of  the  ^^/-house- 
holder. If  anybody  wished  to  summon  him  before  the  Thing,  or 
tribunal,  he  had  first  to  summon  him  '  home ' ;  because  the 
summoning  to  the  courts  of  law  was  not  lawful  when  the  defendant 
was  not  sitting  *  in  his  qndvegi? 2  When  the  heir  took  the  seisin 
of  the  ancestral  property  the  act  was  symbolized  by  the  heirs 
taking  their  place  in  the  high  seat.3  Thus  the  qndvegi  may  be 
named  the  'throne'  in  the  ^/-householder's  realm,  which  comprised 
the  house  and  the  fenced-in  land,  the  fields,  meadows,  grove,  and 
home-pasture.  When  transferring  this  *  realm  '  to  another  house- 
holder, he  had  to  make  it  over  to  his  successor  in  this  dramatic 
way  of  '  mould-taking '  and  '  mwld-skeyting* 

I  presume  we  are  not  very  far  from  the  truth  in  asserting 
that  the  above-mentioned  formula  of  skeyting  dates  from  a  time 
when  every  Norwegian  free  peasant  was  an  $ta/-man,  that  is,  the 
owner  and  the  farmer  of  his  own  <?S<z/-homestead.  Leaseholders 
(leigulendingar}  of  <?oW-land  had  not  yet  made  their  appearance  in 
the  agrarian  history  of  Norway,  in  which  they  were  afterwards  to 
play  so  prominent  a  part.  The  ^/-householder  farmed  his  land 
himself  with  the  assistance  of  his  family  and  his  serfs. 

How  far  back  in  our  history  have  we  to  go  in  order  to  find 
such  conditions  ?  The  answer  to  that  question  was  given  as  long 
ago  as  1889  by  Konrad  Maurer  in  his  paper  on  Die  norwegischen 
holdar.  He  has  proved  that  the  word  hauldr  (holdr  ags.  hold] 
originally  was  synonymous  with  the  word  bondi  (husband,  free 
peasant),  and  we  still  find  these  words  used  as  synonyms  in  the 
laws  of  Eastern  Norway  in  the  twelfth  century.  But  in  the  laws 
of  Western  Norway  (the  Gulathingslgg  and  the  Frostathingslqg) 

1  Note  the  answer  of  a  defendant  in  the  procedure  of  redeeming  <?&W-land  : 
*  thou  shall  never  get  this  land  from  me,  without  taking  it  from  my  corpse ' 
fyufcer  Ipd  iord  eigi  of  mtr.  nema  ]>u  af  mer  datiftum  drager,  G.  268,  cpr.  265). 

2  See  G.  35,  266  ;  F.  x.  2. 

3  G.  115:  '  Nu  er  maftr  dauSr,  arve  skal  i  ondvegi  setjazt.' 


vm]  6dal  and  Skeyting  163 


hauldr  is  synonymous  with  fiftalborinn  maftr  or 
while  bondi  here  means  an  inferior  class  of  free  peasants, 
who  are  not  $fo/-born  or  <?&z/-men.  This  division  of  the  peasant 
community  may  have  taken  place  before  the  beginning  of  the 
ninth  century,  when  we  meet  the  Norwegian  hold  in  the 
Anglo-Saxon  Chronicles  and  in  the  Northleoda  laga  as  a  man 
standing  in  the  middle  rank  between  the  ealdorman  and  the 
\egn^  just  as  the  Norwegian  hauldr  ranks  between  the  lendrma&r 
and  the  bondi. 

This  division  of  the  peasants  living  round  the  Western  fjords 
is  no  doubt  one  of  the  many  evolutionary  factors  which  the  raids 
of  the  Vikings  introduced  into  Norway.  During  this  period  the 
sons  of  the  ancient  ^/-families  developed  more  and  more  into 
a  class  of  warriors  and  merchants,  to  whom  farming  seemed 
degrading  and  inadequate  for  the  economic  needs  of  their  new 
households,  which  were  greater  and  more  costly  than  under  the 
old  standard  of  living  on  a  single  $fo/-estate.  They  developed 
from  <?tfo/-peasants  into  landlords.  The  story  of  Harek  in  Tjotta 
(first  half  of  the  eleventh  century)  is  very  significant  in  this  respect.2 
His  father,  Eyvind  Skaldaspiller,  had  not  been  storaudigr  (very  rich), 
and  in  his  time  there  lived  in  Tjotta  many  small  peasants.  His 
son  Harek  at  first  bought  only  one  farm,  and  that  not  very  large  ; 
but  in  a  few  years  he  bought  out  all  the  small  bfindr,  who  had 
lived  there  before,  so  that  he  himself  alone  owned  the  whole  island 
and  built  a  big  '  manse  '  upon  it. 

Under  such  circumstances  the  small  <?&z/-peasants  were  trans- 
formed into  leaseholders  of  <?&z/-land  belonging  to  others,  or  they 
founded,  new  <ftfo/-estates  by  clearing  away  the  forests  and  tilling 
uncultivated  soil.  About  a  thousand  years  after  the  advent  of 
Christianity  this  development  got  a  new  impulse  in  that  Christianity 
did  away  with  serfdom.  Olaf  and  his  Anglo-Saxon  court  bishop, 
Grimkell,  had  very  effectively  advocated  the  abolition  of  serfdom. 
They  ordered  in  their  new  Christian  law  that  every  year  at  every 


,r  einn 


1  Maurer,  Die  holdar,  pp.  198-99. 

2  '  I  ftottu  bjoggu  >a  smair  b0ndr  ok  eigi  allfair.      Hdrekr  keypti  J?a.  ™.« 
b0  fyrst  ok  eigi  allmikinn  ok  for  J?ar  buSum  til  ;    en  a  fam  misserum  hafSi 
hann  rutt  i  brot  gllum  b6ndum,  >eim  er  ]?ar  bjoggu  aSr,  sva  at  harm  atti  pa 
einn  alia  eyna  ok  gerfti  ]?ar  ]?a  h9fudb0  mikinn '  (Heimskringla,  ed.  Firinur 
Jonsson,  ii.  215). 


164  A.  Tar  anger  [vm 

Lawthing  and  Fylkisthing  in  the  land  a  serf  should  be  set  free;1  the 
inhabitants  of  the  thinglqg  should  every  year  give  the  sum  of 
money  which  was  needed  to  pay  the  freedgeld  to  the  owner  of  the 
serf,  and  the  solemn  act  of  free-giving  was  performed  on  the  first 
Sunday  in  the  session.  K.  Maurer  has  expressed  the  opinion 
that  the  object  of  this  act  of  free-giving  was  to  establish  a  contrast 
to  the  heathen  sacrifices  of  serfs  at  the  commencement  of  the  earlier 
things.  It  was  truly  an  effective  way  of  preaching  the  Gospel, 
and  one  which  commended  itself  to  the  understanding  of  the 
people.  Its  consequences  were  that  1  50  years  after  the  death  of 
King  Olaf  (1030)  there  existed  no  more  serfs  in  Norway,  this  being 
100  years  earlier  than  their  disappearance  in  Denmark  and  about 
200  years  before  their  disappearance  in  Sweden. 


III.  THE  EVOLUTION  OF  THE 

(IITH  TO  I3TH  CENTURIES) 

From  the  unfree  population  there  now  grew  up  a  stock  of  free 
labourers,  who  naturally  found  their  way  into  the  class  of  small 
leaseholders  and  new  settlers.2  The  cultivation  of  the  land  was 
extended.  During  the  first  Christian  centuries  the  woods  and 
valleys  of  Norway  are  cleared,  and  the  inhabited  land  gets  the 
shape  and  extension  it  has  kept  up  to  recent  times.  The  place- 
names  composed  with  ru^  —  about  3000  in  number  —  spread 
over  all  the  inland  districts,  show  us  the  value  of  the  cultivation 
carried  on  by  these  petty  strugglers  for  life. 

There  was  created  a  great  deal  of  fresh  ffial,  in  the  ancient 
meaning  of  the  word,  i.e.  cultivated  land.  But  who  were  the  *  8&al- 
men'  to  this  oftat?  Were  they  the  tillers  and  settlers  themselves, 
or  were  they  the  old  <?S<2/-families  whose  domains  were  extended 
in  this  way,  or  were  they  the  King  and  Crown,  whose  *  commons  ' 
(almenningar)  were  transformed  into  bygftir  (inhabited  districts)  ? 

Of  course  both  these  things  happened,  and  the  principal 
result  of  the  riftningr  (reclaiming  of  land)  is  an  immense 
increase  of  the  leaseholders.  An  undated  statute  of  King  Magnus 
Lagab0tir  (1263-80)  assumes  that  every  inhabitant  of  a  ruftstaftr 

1  G.  4  :  '  Pat  er  nu  ]?vi  nest,  at  ver  skolom  geva  manne  fraelsi  dr  hvert  her 
i  Gula.'  —  5  :   *  pat  er  nu  J?vi  nest  at  ver  scolom  manne  fraelsi  geva  i  fylki  hveriu 
i  Gula]?ings  logum.' 

2  In  the  sense  of  persons  reclaiming  land  for  cultivation  (ry§ningsm<znd). 


vm]  Octal  and  Skeyting  165 

is  a  leaseholder ;  but  it  assumes,  too,  that  many  of  these  settlers 
do  not  know  who  is  their  landlord.  It  is  therefore  their  duty  to 
go  to  the  heraftsthing  and  *  call  for  a  landlord  (bondt] ' ;  and  if 
they  do  not  find  one,  the  King  is  the  owner  of  the  ruftstaftr.1 

But,  after  all,  we  must  presume  that  in  these  early  Christian 
centuries  there  also  grew  up  a  new  class  of  independent  owners — 
in  other  words,  new  $te/-men  and  <?o#/-families.  In  Eastern 
Norway  such  parvenus,  when  free-born,  seem  to  have  been  regarded 
as  b0ndr  and  hauldar  in  the  eye  of  the  law.  Perhaps  this  view  was 
not  taken  as  early  as  the  first  generation ;  but  when  their  home- 
stead had  passed  from  father  to  son,  it  became  dSal  in  Norway  as  it 
became  arvejord  (terra  hereditarid)  in  Sweden.2 

In  Western  Norway  also  this  rule  originally  prevailed.  In  G. 
270  are  mentioned  *  the  land  tycer  jarftir)  which  shall  follow  the 
cfoals :  it  is  that  which  the  forefather  has  left  to  his  successor  (su  er 
ein  er  ave  hever  ava  leiff]'  The  use  of  the  word  ave  for  both  of 
them  indicates  that  the  land  for  many  generations  has  been  in  the 
same  family.3  But  when  we  remember  that  fiSal  simply  means 
tilled  ground,  we  are  bound  to  assume  that  originally  it  was 
enough  to  make  it  oftal,  in  the  sense  of  terra  hereditaria,  that  it 
had  at  some  time  or  other  passed  to  an  heir. 

Now  we  meet  in  the  Gulathingslaw,  266,  another  provision 
for  the  8§alsbrig§  (the  redemption  of  <?tta/-land).  The  person 
redeeming  the  land  must  '  tell  off  (count)  his  5  ancestors,  who 
have  owned  (the  land),  and  the  6th,  who  held  both  in  ownership 
and  in  dSal.' 4  And  the  Frostathingslaw,  xii.  4,  provides :  *  The 
land  of  no  man  shall  become  fiSal  before  3  ancestors  have 
owned  it  and  it  has  come  into  the  possession  of  the  4th  without 
interruption.'5  These  regulations,  I  think,  are  consequences  of 
the  above-mentioned  aristocratic  tendencies  in  West  Norway  to 
distinguish  between  the  $ta/-born  men  and  the  common  peasants 
(b0ndr).  I  do  not  think  it  was  the  original  rule  that  a  homestead 

1  Norges  gamle  Love,  ii.  485. 

2  Nordstrom,  Svenska  Samhalls  forfatningens  historia,  ii.  140  sqq. 

3  See  Hertzberg,    Glossarium  s.v.    *  af  i ' ;    Fritzner,   Ordbog,  s.v.   *  af  i '   2. 
DN.  iv.  No.  848  :   'J?at  hefir  fylgt  afi  eptir  afa.' 

4  *  Peir  scolo  telia  til  langfe<5ra  sinna  v.  er  att  hava,  en  sa  hinn  sette  er 
baeSe  atte  at  eign  oc  at  oSrle.' 

5  « Engum  manni  verSr  iqrft  at  oSali  fyrr  en  iij.  langfeSr  hafa  att  oc  kemr 
undir  hinn  iiij.  samfleytt.' 


1 66  A.  Tar  anger  [vm 

first  got  the  quality  of  fi$al  after  six  or  four  generations  of 
successive  possession  in  the  same  family.  In  ancient  times  it 
becomes  fi§al  as  soon  as  it  is  established  as  a  homestead  for  a 
free-born  bondi.  In  my  opinion  it  was  the  extensive  and  common 
'  free-giving '  of  serfs  which  was  the  chief  cause  of  the  provision  as 
to  the  six  or  four  generations.  Then  it  was  an  old  rule  that  the 
family  of  a  freedman  could  not  enter  the  class  of  the  b0ndr  till 
after  at  least  four  generations.1 

The  natural  effect  of  the  above-mentioned  regulation  was  to 
diminish  both  the  <?&?/- land  and  the  cftal- families.  Magnus 
Lagab0tir  accepted  in  his  Landslaw  (vi.  2)  the  rule  of  the 
Pros  tat  kings  law  relating  to  the  four  generations.  But  the 
common  rule  amongst  the  people  was  that  an  <?tS<2/-witness  should 
make  clear  the  pedigree  of  the  ancestors  '  as  far  back  as  the  haugr 
(burial  mounds)  of  heathen  times.'2 

A  perfect  $$<2/-estate  possessed  a  burial-mound  (haugr)  of  the 
heathen  ancestor.  In  the  pedigrees  of  the  ancient  ruling  families 
in  Sondmor  we  find  the  following  characteristic  remarks : 

Herbjorn  ligger  i  hougen  i  Drifftvig.  Aatte  til  eigu  och  odel 
Helgabostad  och  Holm  och  Starrin. 

Barder  Nessiakonung  ligger  i  hougen  paa  Bardarstad ;  hand 
aatte  all  Roma  och  alia  Strandarvig  och  Gudoy  och  Hundeidavig. 

Eilifr  jarl  ligger  i  Eilifshoug  i  Gudo. 

Tosten  Blafotr  ligger  indeni  Hundeid. 

Rafn  som  ligger  i  Hval  i  Heimdal. 

Grimr  ligger  i  hougen  paa  Hjordal  paa  Sundmor.3 

It  cannot  be  wondered  at  that  under  such  conditions  the  class 
of  haulds  was  decreasing.  Both  the  Frostathingslaw  (xiv.  7)  and 
the  Landslaw  (vii.  61)  reckon  with  the  possibility  that  in  a  fylke 
(county)  there  may  not  be  found  as  many  as  twelve  haulds. 
Indeed,  the  exact  meaning  of  the  term  hauldr  is  no  longer  familiar 
to  the  common  mind ;  therefore  the  Landslaw  (vii.  64)  must 

1  See  Konrad  Maurer,  Die  Freigelassenen  nach  altnorwegischem    Rechte 
(1878).      Seebohm,    Tribal   Custom    in    Anglo-Saxon   Law,    p.    319.      Paul 
Vinogradoff,   '  Geschlecht  imd  Verwandtschaft    im  altnorwegischem  Rechte ' 
(Zeitschrift  fur  Social  und  Wirtschaftsgeschichte,  vii.  i  sqq.). 

2  *  Greinande  skilvislega    langfaeSgatal    til    haugs  ok    til    heiSni,'    Norges 
gamle  Love,  iii.  121  (1316).     In  the  Landslaw  vi.  16  this  o^al  is  named  haugs 
or  haugao^al.      It  is  opposed  to  utjar^ir  in  DN.  ii.  No.  694  (A.D.  1427). 

3  Gustav  Storm,  'Indskuddene  i  Fagrskinna'  (Kristiania  Videnskabsselskabs 
Forhandlinger,  1875,  pp.  100-106). 


vm]  Octal  and  Skeyting  167 

define  it  :  *  But  he  is  hauldr  who  has  foals  by  inheritance  both 
from  his  father  and  his  mother,  which  his  forefathers  have  owned 
before  them  and  which  have  not  been  the  (foals  of  other  men,  who 
have  got  it  by  purchase  or  by  collateral  inheritance.'1  This 
definition  makes  it  evident  that  the  genuine  cftal  is  the  cftal 
inherited  from  lineal  ancestors,  not  from  collaterals.  The  o^al  is 
terra  hereditaria  /car 


IV.  TRANSFER  AND  PRESCRIPTION  OF  &X4Z.-RIGHT 

The  ordinary  way  of  acquiring  <?tta/-right  in  <?S<z/-land  was  that 
of  inheritance.  In  G.  270  inheritance  is  mentioned  as  the  first 
method  of  acquiring  $ta/-right  to  land.  The  second  is  forfeiture  of 
land  as  gjold  for  a  manslaughter.  The  third  is  branderfft  ;  that  is, 
when  a  man  takes  into  his  household  another  man  with  all  his 
property  in  order  '  to  maintain  him  until  he  is  carried  to  the  funeral- 
pyre  '  (til  brannz  oc  til  bals}?  The  fourth  is  the  '  gift  of  honour  ' 
(hefolauri)  from  a  king  or  prince.  The  fifth  is  the  *  gift  for  drink  ' 
(drekkulauri)*  if  it  is  given  by  the  king.  The  sixth  the  '  gift  for 
child-fostering  '  (barnfostrlaun).  The  seventh  is  the  foalsskipti. 

Although  it  is  not  stated  in  the  law,  we  must  presume  that  the 
form  of  skeyting  originally  was  in  use  for  all  these  '  gifts,'  and  also 
for  the  gjold  (forfeiture),  where  it  was  performed  by  the  thing 
with  wapentak)  unless  the  manslaier  performed  it  himself  on  the 
^/-estate. 

But  it  is  to  be  observed  that  'sale'  is  not  mentioned  in 
G.  270  as  a  title  creating  0tta/-right.  Our  old  laws  knew  different 
kinds  of  'sale,'  as  sal  til  stefnu  (for  15  years)  or  sal  til  mala 
(pawn),  all  of  which  were  conditional  and  possessed  a  form  of 
pledging  the  land.  But  in  G.  278  and  279  we  hear  of  a  sal  til 
skeytingar,  and,  as  I  have  said  before  (p.  160),  that  must  have  been 
a  sale  of  the  $fo/-right,  and  skeyting  is  the  form  of  transferring  that 
right.  If  the  seller  refuse  to  perform  it,  the  thing  shall  perform 

1  *  En  sa  er  hauldr  er  hann  hefir  oSaul  at  erfSum  tekit  bseSe  eptir  faSur  oc 
moSor  )?au  er  bans  forellrar  hafa  att  aSr  firir  J>eim  oc  eigi  annara    manna 
oSaul  i  at  telia,  ]?au  er  meS  kaupi  eru  at  komin  eSa  uterfftum.' 

2  *  Su  er  bin  xvi.  (erfS)  er  heitir  branderfS.  ef  maSr  tecr  mann  d  bond  ser 
at  liufu  oc  at  leiSu.  oc  f0Ser  hann  til  brannz  oc  til  bdls,  kveSr  at  ferno  male  ' 
(G.  108). 

3  Cp.  drikkelaun  in  the  North,  preosta  lagu,  i.  67  §  I.      See  Vinogradoff, 
Transfer  of  Land,  pp.  537  sqq. 


1 68  A.  Taranger  [vin 

it  by  wapentak,  if  the  purchaser  can  prove  that  he  has  lawfully 
'  taken  mould '  (G.  279,  292).  In  selling  <?oW-land,  the  vendor  had 
first  of  all  to  offer  it  publicly  in  the  thing  to  his  <?oW-fellows,  who 
had  the  right  of  'first  refusal.'  If  none  of  them  would  buy  it  at 
the  price  which  he  might  be  expected  to  get  from  outsiders,  he 
could  sell  it  out  of  the  $fo/-group.  But  if  he  sold  it '  unoffered,'  the 
<?&z/-men  could  redeem  it  in  twelve  months.  Such  is  the  provision 
in  G.  278  by  sal  til  skeytingar.  l 

If  the  land  was  sold  with  a  right  of  redemption  by  the  seller,  he 
had  to  keep  this  right  alive  by  '  publication '  (lysing)  in  the  thing. 
If  lysing  was  neglected  for  twenty  years  the  contractual  right  of 
redemption  was  deemed  to  be  extinct  by  prescription ;  the  seller, 
however,  still  had  his  $fo/-right  of  redemption,  if  the  land  was  his 
&&al\  but  he  had  now  to  pay  full  value  for  the  land,  not  merely 
the  sum  he  had  got  by  the  conditional  sale.2  In  this  case  the 
Gulathingslaw  says  that  'the  land  has  become  <?3<2/,'  viz.  for  the 
purchaser ;  *  then  he  (the  purchaser)  may  deny  the  cftal  (of  the  seller) 
and  assert  it  for  himself.' 3  Here  we  have  clear  evidence  that  &§al 
means  simple  ownership,  not  family  ownership ;  but  it  is  assumed 
that  the  latter  is  still  retained  by  the  seller,  who  can  redeem  it  by 
faalsbrigG. 

We  have  seen  that  the  0S#/-group  lost  their  right  of  redemption 
in  regard  to  'offered'  <?tfo/-land  after  a  very  short  period  of  pre- 
scription, viz.  twelve  months.  I  think  this  provision  dates  from  a 
time  which  regarded  $5tf/-right  mainly  as  simple  ownership.  But 
whether  it  is  old  or  not,  it  is  a  valuable  concession  to  the  right  of 
free  disposition  by  the  actual  owner  of  the  land.  Then,  of  course, 
the  family  right  of  redemption  was  a  hampering  restriction  on  the 
free  trade  in  <$5<2/-land,  which  as  early  as  the  first  centuries  after  the 
introduction  of  Christianity  had  become  more  and  more  extensive. 

It  is,  however,  quite  another  question  whether  the  sold  0S<z/-land 
became  the  family-<?oW  of  the  purchaser  and  his  kinsmen  at  once 

1  *  Nu  kaupir  maSr  iorS  til  skeytingar.  oc  tecr  skeyting  a"  J>d  scolo  }?eir 
oSalnautar  bans  ef  their  ero  innan  fylkis.  oc  vilia  brigt  hava.  ]>£  scolo  ]?eir 
brigt  hava  d  fyrstum  xii.  mdnatfom.  ellar  seal  sd.  hava  er  keypt  hafSe'  (G. 
278,  cp.  289). 

2  G.  272  and  276  in  fine. 

3  *  Nu  liggr  ior<5  um  stefnu.  oc  liggr  xx.  vetr.  oc  hava  ]?eir  enga  lysing  }>ar 
a\  }?a"  er  hon  at  oSrle  orSen.  J?a"  md.  hann  (purchaser)  dula  8&als  oc  kenna 
ser'  (G.  276). 


vm]  Octal  and  Skeyting  169 

or  in  a  twelvemonth.  Personally  I  am  convinced  that  the 
skeyting-diC.^  was  intended  to  transfer  the  $ta/-right,  not  merely  the 
ownership,  from  the  seller  and  his  offspring  to  the  buyer  and  his 
offspring.  None  of  the  seller's  offspring  had  any  right  of  redeem- 
ing sold  $ta/-land,  if  it  had  been  lawfully  *  offered.'  On  the  contrary, 
he  had  to  '  offer '  it  even  to  his  own  son.1  Only,  if  he  would  sell 
til  stefnu  and  not  til  8§als,  he  was  not  required  to  'offer'  to  his 
son.2  That  this  is  the  intention  of  the  skeyting  is  stated  expressly 
in  many  s&eyti*g~dceds.  I  will  quote  as  an  instance  one  of  the 
oldest  that  has  come  down  to  us,  viz.  a  donation-deed  of  1281. 
The  donor  says :  '  This  land,  which  hitherto  has  been  my  d§aly 
shall  henceforth  be  considered  by  everybody  as  the  cftal  of  the  said 
monastery.'3  The  common  phrase  runs  that  the  land  is  sold  or 
given  til  alda  oftals,  or  til  cefiligrar  eignar  ok  alda  cftals,  or  ///  alda 
foals  ok  ubrig&ligrar  eignar*  Here  redemption  by  the  seller  or 
donor  and  his  offspring  is  certainly  excluded. 

But  in  regard  to  the  acquisition  of  family  $te/-right  by  pre- 
scription, the  old  provincial  laws  have  only  the  above-mentioned 
(p.  165)  rules  relating  to  possession  for  five  (£.)  or  three  (F.)  genera- 
tions. The  last  rule  is  the  later  in  date  and  was  first,  I  think, 
introduced  in  favour  of  the  King  and  the  Church.  As  an  exception 
it  is  in  G.  271  applied  to  the  King,  who  acquires  $to/-right  by  pre- 
scription in  '  three  kings'  time.'  According  to  F.  xiv.  7  the 
possessor  of  land,  cultivated  in  the  King's  Commons,  gets  owner- 
ship if  the  land  was  cultivated  '  before  three  kings'  time,  of  whom 
none  was  in  the  land  for  a  shorter  space  than  10  years.'  The 
shortest  time  of  prescription  is  thus  thirty  years,  or  just  the  term 
within  which  the  Church  may  obtain  prescriptive  ownership  of 
$W-right.5  Of  course  the  $fcz/-right  of  '  offering '  and  '  redemption  ' 
was  not  favourable  to  the  greatest  landlords,  the  King  and  the 
Church;  but  in  the  old  Gulathingslaw  (271)  the  King  is  bound  to 

1  G.  276. 

2  G.  288.     I    do  not  agree  with   the  conjecture  of  Boden,  'Das  altnor- 
wegische  Stammgiiterrecht '  (ZSS,  xxii.  109),  that  the  phrase  in   G.  288  in 
fine,  *  ef  hann  vill,'  means  *  if  the  son  will.' 

3  DN.  xii.   No.   5  :    c  seal  J»essi  eigh[n]  er  mit  hefuir  vaerith  odhal  her  til, 
uerdha  hsedhan  af  odhal  firir  sagdz  stadhar  firir  huariom  manne.' 

4  See  Fritzner,  Ordbog  s.v.  « 6Sal,'  i. 

5  F.  xiv.  3  :   '  En  )?at  verSr  kirkiu  at  oSali  ef  hon  hefir  at  xxx.  vetra.  en  ]?at 
vitni  beri  henni  kirkiusdcnar  menn.' 


170  A.  Tar  anger  [vm 

allow  the  bftndr  to  make  use  of  them  both  against  him.  In  the 
Frostathingslaw,  however,  none  of  them  may  be  used  against  the 
King ;  and  if  the  King  skeytir  land  to  a  man,  the  possessor  may 
not  offer  it  to  anybody  if  the  King  was  before  the  lawful  owner.1 
This  provision  shows  that  the  s  key  ting  in  the  Frostathingslaw  was 
not  always  intended  to  transfer  $fo/-right ;  indeed,  the  skeyting  is 
used  even  in  *  conditional '  sales,  where  the  seller  has  reserved  a 
right  of  redemption.2  The  skeyting  in  F.  is  rather  a  form 
for  transfer  of  gewere  than  of  a  right  of  ownership.  In  fact, 
there  aje  in  this  law  of  the  twelfth  century  many  'modern' 
tendencies  which  obscure  the  more  archaic  features  of  Norwegian 
land-law  in  the  provincial  law  as  shown  in  the  Gulatkingslqg. 

The  Norwegian  Justinian,  King  Magnus  Lagab0tir,  had  a  sharp 
eye  for  these  '  modern '  tendencies,  which  threatened  to  weaken  the 
bond  which  the  <?&z/-right  had  set  between  the  land  and  the  people. 
And  before  he  published  his  new  Norwegian  Code,  he  issued  a  statute 
about  acquisition  of  0&2/-right.  Here  he  laid  down  the  new  provi- 
sion that  0&z/-right  should  be  acquired  by  sixty  years'  prescription. 
This  new  rule  he  put  in  the  first  paragraph  in  his  Code  which  re- 
lates to  this  matter.  In  the  second  paragraph  he  put  the  old 
rule  from  the  Gulat kings  law,  270,  that  land  given  by  the  King 
is  6$al,  '  if  he  has  not  given  it  subject  to  other  conditions.'  In  the 
third  place,  he  took  the  rule  from  the  Frostathingslaw  concerning 
possession  for  three  generations ;  and  in  the  fourth  the  foalsskipti.* 

Next,  he  laid  down  new  provisions  for  the  'offer'  and  the 
1  redemption.'  I  shall  not  go  into  details ;  but  the  alterations  are 
essential  and  go  very  far  in  favour  of  the  person  redeeming  the 
land.  His  redemption-right  is  not  lost  by  prescription  in  a  twelve- 
month as  in  the  Gulat  kings  law,  but  in  ten  years.  And  if  he 
has  lawful  exceptions  (nauftsyn),  he  may  publish  them  every  tenth 
year,  and  (thus  keep  Jiis  $fo/-right  alive  for  sixty  years.  The  first 
exception  is  very  favourable  to  a  poor  man  using  the  right  of 
redemption  :  he  can  publish  his  '  lack  of  money,'  and  that  suffices. 
Another  provision,  quite  as  favourable  to  him,  is  that  the  sum  of 

1  F.  xii.  4  :   « En  ef  konungr  sceytir  manni   iorft,  ]?d  seal  ]?£  iorS  engum 
manni  bioSa  ]?6  at  hann  vili  selia  hvergi  er  atti  aftr,  ef  konungr  atti  sigan 
heimila.      En   engi   ma5r  seal   bioSa  konungi   iorS.  oc   eigi  konungr  65rum 
manni.' 

2  See  F.  xii.  i.  8  L.  vi.  2. 


vni]  Octal  and  Skeyting  171 

redemption-money  should  not  be  the  price  the  owner  could  get  in 
free  trade,  but  the  sum  assessed  by  a  body  of  six  men.1 

It  is  evident  that  the  new  $ta/-law  was  intended  to  secure  the 
$ta/-right  for  the  common  peasantry.  But  the  popular  King  did 
not  achieve  his  object.  In  every  decade  before  the  great  disaster 
of  the  Black  Death  (1349-50)  both  the  nobility  and  the  clergy 
grew  richer  by  land  which  for  centuries  had  been  got  out  of  the 
foal  possessions  of  the  b$ndr.  It  is  the  common  view  that  the 
Church  obtained  most  of  her  landed  property  by  gifts  or  testa- 
ments. In  some  degree  this  view  is  right  in  regard  to  the  parish 
churches  and  chapels ;  but  it  is  not  so  in  regard  to  the  greater 
ecclesiastical  institutions — the  episcopal  sees,  the  cathedrals,  the 
chapters,  and  the  monasteries.  The  only  instance  in  which  we  can 
verify  the  truth  of  this  assertion  is  that  of  the  monastery  of  Munkelif 
to  Bergen.  Between  1223  and  1349  this  institution  acquired  64! 
mdnaftsmatabol  by  gifts,  157!  by  purchase  of  prevent  ("board"  in 
the  cloister),  181  by  purchase,  and  232  by  conditional  sale  with 
right  of  redemption  reserved  by  the  seller.  But  none  of  these  sellers 
were  economically  in  a  strong  enough  position  to  make  use  of  their 
redemption-right,  and  the  land  became  the  property  and  the  dSal  of 
the  monastery.  Thus  the  great  ecclesiastical  institution  played  the 
same  part  in  the  economic  life  -of  the  Norwegian  peasant  in  the 
Middle  Ages  as  the  '  Hypothecary  Banks '  to-day,  furnishing  them 
with  ready  money  and  getting  their  land  in  mortgage.  The  best 
and  most  favourable  $ta/-right  could  not  prevent  this  economic 
evolution,  or  rather  degradation,  of  the  peasantry.  Against  the 
want  of  money  nothing  is  of  avail  but  money ;  and  for  ready 
money  the  Norwegian  peasants  sold  not  only  their  land,  but  also 
their  $fo/-right.  If  the  buyer  was  willing  to  pay  the  skey tings- 
aurar*  or  cfoalskaup*  or  oftalslausn,*  he  got  the  c®al~ rights  of 
the  seller  at  once. 

It  is,  however,  a  significant  fact  that  from  the  time  of  Magnus 
Lagab0tir  the  terms  skeyta  and  skeyting  disappear  in  the  title-deeds 
of  land.  We  have  thousands  of  such  deeds  published  in  Diplo- 

1  L.  vi.  4. 

2  DN.   iv.    No.  147    (1321),   899   (1447);    cp.   von  Amira,  OR.  ii.  687, 
who  has  a  different  view. 

8  Dipl.  Oread,  i.  No.  48  (1575). 

4  DN.  ix.  No.  577  (1526),  793  (1565). 


172  A.  Taranger  [vm 

matarium  Norwegicum,  but  as  far  as  my  knowledge  goes  we  shall 
scarcely  find  the  terms  skeyta  and  skeyting  in  fifty  of  them. 
According  to  von  Amira1  they  were  changed  into  afhenda  and 
afhending.  I  am  not  convinced  that  the  last-named  terms  really 
took  the  places  of  skeyta  and  skeyting.  In  the  title-deeds 
prevail  the  terms  selja  (sell)  and  sal  (sale),  or  kaupa  (buy)  and 
kaup  (purchase).  The  fact  is,  in  my  opinion,  that  skeyta  and 
skeyting  disappear,  because  the  transfer  of  $ta/-right  became  more 
and  more  infrequent.  As  we  learn  from  the  title-deed  book  of  Mun- 
kelif  the  '  conditional '  sales  are  in  an  absolute  majority. 

V.  THE  EXPANSION  OF  THE  OEMZ-CONCEPTION 

Finally,  I  shall  in  a  few  words,  and  without  collecting  the 
evidence,  try  to  point  out  another  change  which  the  Middle  Ages 
brought  into  the  old  <9cta/-conception.  This  was,  as  already  men- 
tioned, originally  meant  to  include  only  the  tilled  field  and  the 
fenced-in  pastureland.  Outside  this  lay  the  commons  (almennin- 
gar\  and  the  commons  were  not  an  object  of  ownership  (eiga,  eign} 
but  of  possession  (hafa).  In  the  Gulat kings  law,  however,  a  part  of 
the  common  is  already  attached  to  the  cftal,  viz.  the  mqrk  (forest) 
and  the  scetr  (summer  pastures  in  the  mountains).  Of  this  the 
odaller  can  get  ownership  by  twenty  years'  use  (prescription).  Never- 
theless it  is  not  yet  o^al  and  not  included  in  the  foakskipti?  In  the 
later  skeyting  formulas  the  chief  object  of  the  transfer  is  the  oftat, 
or  more  commonly  the  jgrft  (the  tilled  ground)  and  the  '  appurten- 
ances '  (lunnendi)  belonging  to  the  same.  '  Appurtenances '  include 
hafn  (pasture),  hogg  (wood),  vatn  (water),  veiftista&ir  (fishing  or 
hunting  places),  and  various  other  uses.  All  these  '  appurtenances ' 
are  included  in  the  term  eign  (owned  land),  but  not  in  the  term 
oftal.  We  see  that  the  right  of  ownership  in  untilled  land  surround- 
ing the  o^al  grew  up  out  of  these  many  '  uses '  in  it.  Originally 
only  the  &§al  is  owned,  and  8§al  is  obviously  synonymous  with  eign, 
and  was  perhaps  the  most  common  term  for  eign.  Afterwards  the 
eign  was  expanded  to  the  regularly  *  used '  woods  and  pastures 
outside  the  cfoal  in  the  commons.  And  lastly,  the  ^/-conception 
comprises  the  whole  eign.  Such  is  its  meaning  in  the  o^alsskipti 
of  Magnus  Lagab0tir's  Landslaw  (vi.  3),  which,  as  opposed  to  its 

1  OR.  ii.  §  64  2  G.  86  compared  with  87. 


vm]  Odal  and  Skeyting  173 

source,  G.  87,  includes  the  whole  eign,  inside  and  outside  the  fence, 
and  not  merely  the  fenced-in  &8al.  But  the  tilled  ground,  as  being 
the  more  valuable,  has  to  be  divided  by  stick  (skapf]  or  string 
(albur^r] ;  for  the  land  outside  the  fence  the  '  eye-measure '  (aug- 
naskof]  is  sufficient. 

Takmgrk  and  heimrqst  are  the  terms  which  are  used  in  Magnus 
Lagab0tir's  Code  to  indicate  the  eign  as  a  whole,  or  most  commonly 
the  land  outside  the  fences.  Takmqrk^  according  to  Hertzberg's 
Glossary -,  means  '  boundary,'  but  the  common  term  for  '  boundary ' 
is  takmark,  I  am  inclined  to  believe  that  the  takmqrk  is  the  taken 
mqrk  (wood,  forest),  which  also  is  a  feminine  word;  but  it  is 
impossible  for  me  to  establish  this  view  with  philological  precision. 
The  term  heimrqst  may  be  verbally  translated  by  '  home-mile.' 
In  the  Landslaw  it  evidently  means  '  homeway,'  viz.  '  the  way  from 
the  highway  to  the  beer' 2  or  '  the  way  from  the  home  to  the  out- 
pastures.'3  In  a  document  from  Gudbrandsdalen  (1432)  we  learn 
that  the  heimrqst  reaches  from  the  storehouse  to  the  commons,4  a 
distance  of  6-7  kilometres.5  This  document  gives  us  an  idea  of  an 
tfoW-peasant's  claims  in  regard  to  wood  and  pasture-land.  Under 
such  circumstances  it  is  not  surprising  that  the  commons  soon 
became  private  property  ;  and  the  fixing  of  the  boundaries  between 
eign  and  common  was  placed  in  the  hands  of  the  haulds  or  *  best 
peasants.'  The  thing  was  to  elect  twelve  of  them,  and  two  of 
the  twelve  were  to  *  swear  to  the  limit.' 6  As  a  contrasting  fact  I 
will  mention  that  a  settler  in  the  common  had  no  power  of 
disposition  over  a  greater  distance  from  his  fence  than  he  could 
throw  his  snidl,  a  knife  for  cutting  twigs.  But  in  later  times  the 
lagretsmen  (a  kind  of  jury),  who  had  to  fix  the  boundaries  of  the 
reclaimed  plots,  were  more  generous,  and  considerable  portions  of 
the  commons  were  often  attached  to  them.  There  was  land  enough 
to  draw  from,  and  the  poor  eremites  sometimes  obtained  forests 
which  are  now  sold  for  fortunes. 

A.  TARANGER. 

1  L.  vii.  60.          2  L.  vii.  46.          3  L.  vii.  41,  58.          4  DN.  iii.  No.  717. 

5  In  Shetland  hemrost  is  synonymous  with  hemhoga,  the  nearest  pasture- 
land  outside  the  hedges.     In  the  Pharoes  heimrustir  means  the  ground  around 
the  houses  =  I  eel.  and  Norw.  tun.     See  Jakobsen,  Etymologisk  ordbog  over 
det  norrone  sprog  paa  Shetland,  s.v.    'hemrost,'  and   Tillceg  til  Forslag  og 
Betcenkninger  afgivne  af  den  fceroiske  Landbokommission^  p.  426. 

6  F.  xiv.  7  ;  L.  vii.  6 1 . 


IX 

LES  ID£ES  COUTUMI£RES  ET  LA  RENAIS- 
SANCE DU  DROIT  ROMAIN  DANS  LE  SUD- 
EST  DE  LA  FRANCE 

LES  regions  du  Sud  -  Est  de  la  France,  qui  ont  constitue"  au 
moyen  age  la  partie  me"ridionale  du  royaume  d'Arles,1  vallee  du 
Rhone  et  versant  occidental  des  Alpes,  Lyonnais,  Bresse,  Savoie, 
Dauphin^  et  Provence,  ont  £te*  comprises  dans  les  « pays  de  droit 
ecrit».  Mais  on  oublie  trop  que,  pendant  le  haut  moyen  age,  ces 
regions  ont  pratique  un  droit  coutumier  original,  tres  nettement 
distinct  du  droit  remain,  tres  voisin  du  droit  des  «  pays  coutumiers  » 
de  la  France  du  Nord.  Ces  idees  coutumieres  n'ont  pas  brusque- 
ment  disparu,  au  xile  siecle  et  au  XIIP,  au  contact  des  ide"es 
romaines.  La  renaissance  de  1'etude  et  de  1'enseignement  du 
droit  romain  n'a  pas  change  soudainement  le  droit  ante"rieur.  Les 
survivances  des  vieilles  ide"es  coutumieres,  au  Xllle  siecle  et  au 
xive,  sont  nombreuses  et  frappantes ;  elles  montrent  que  le 
triomphe  des  id£es  romaines  fut,  sur  beaucoup  de  points,  lent, 
difficile  et  incomplet. 

Cette  lenteur  de  la  penetration  des  ide"es  romaines  est  d'autant 
plus  remarquable  que,  de  tres  bonne  heure,  ce  pays  a  ete"  touche" 
par  la  renaissance  du  droit  romain  savant,  plus  t6t  que  le  reste  de 
la  Gaule.  II  n'est  pas  certain  que  les  Exceptiones  Petri  aient  e*te" 

1  Ces  regions,  politiquement  separees  du  reste  de  la  Gaule  lors  du  de- 
membrement  de  1'Empire  carolingien,  ont  vecu  d'une  vie  independante 
durant  une  grande  partie  du  moyen  age.  Meme  lorsque,  en  1032,  elles 
furent  rattachees  au  Saint  Empire,  Faction  des  Empereurs  ne  fut  que  tres 
intermittente,  leur  influence  resta  presque  nulle,  et  1'autonomie  politique  de 
la  region  a  durd  jusqu'au  jour  ou  les  Capetiens  s'en  emparerent. 

174 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  175 

composes  a  Valence.  Par  centre,  au  milieu  du  xir  siecle,  un 
livre  remarquable,  le  Codt,  a  e"t£  compost  a  Aries ;  puis,  au  xilie 
siecle,  des  jurisconsultes  tels  que  Johannes  Blancus  en  Provence, 
Johannes  de  Blanosco  en  Maconnais,  ont  apporte"  dans  notre  region 
les  id£es  qu'ils  avaient  apprises  dans  les  e"coles  d'ltalie.  II  ne  faut 
pas  oublier  aussi  que  Henri  de  Suze  a  compose",  alors  qu'il  e"tait 
archeveque  d'Embrun,  au  moins  une  partie  de  sa  Somme  des 
De"cre"  tales.  II  ne  semble  pas  qu'aucune  influence  politique  ou 
religieuse  se  soit  exerce"e  dans  nos  regions,  comme  la  chose  a  pu 
se  produire  ailleurs,  contre  1'enseignement  du  droit  romain.  Le 
terrain  paraissait  done  admirablement  prepare*  pour  la  reception 
pratique  des  id£es  romaines.  La  resistance  des  anciennes  ide"es 
coutumieres  n'en  est  que  plus  caracteristique. 

C'est  a  dessein  que  nous  employons  ce  mot :  «  droit  coutumier». 
Ce  droit  est,  comme  le  droit  coutumier  de  la  France  du  Nord,  un 
droit  d'origine  assez  hybride,  ou  se  sont  fondus  des  elements 
germaniques  et  des  elements  pris  au  droit  romain  vulgaire,  mais 
qui  contient  surtout  des  elements  nes  spontane"ment,  destines  a 
satisfaire  des  besoins  nouveaux,  ceux  de  la  socie"t£  du  moyen  age, 
qui  ne  ressemble  ni  a  la  societ£  romaine,  ni  a  la  societe*  des 
Germains  avant  les  Invasions.  Dans  la  vallee  de  la  Saone  et  du 
Rhone,  des  races  tres  diverses  se  coudoient ;  les  professiones  juris 
mentionnent  la  loi  salique,  la  loi  romaine,  la  loi  burgonde,  la  loi 
lombarde.  En  realite,  le  droit  que  Ton  y  pratique  est  un  droit  tres 
unifi6,  et  qui  n'est  ni  franc,  ni  burgonde,  ni  romain. 

Cependant  la  these  de  la  survie  de  Pancien  droit  burgonde  a 
£te"  parfois  soutenue,  et,  recemment,  Julius  Ficker  s'en  est  fait  le 
deTenseur.  Etudiant  1'extension  de  1'augment  de  dot  dans  les 
coutumes  de  la  fin  du  moyen  age,  il  a  cru  trouver  une  coincidence 
entre  cette  extension  et  la  sphere  d'action  des  Burgondes ;  il 
a  attribue"  a  1'augment  de  dot  une  origine  tres  ancienne,  et  1'a 
rattache  au  vieux  droit  burgonde ;  puis  il  a  entrepris  une  demons- 
tration du  m£me  genre  pour  quelques  autres  particularity  du  droit 
de  la  Bourgogne  et  de  TAuvergne.1  Mais  sa  these,  que  nous  ne 
pouvons  discuter  ici  en  detail,  nous  semble  inadmissible.  Nous 
verrons  plus  loin  que  1'augment  de  dot  date  tout  au  plus  du  XIIIe 

1  Ficker,  Untersuchungen  zur  Erbenfolge  der  ostgermanischen  Rechte ;  v. 
surtout  Nos.  1300  et  suiv.  R.  Caillemer,  La  Formation  du  droit  franqais 
mtditval  et  les  travaux  de  Julius  Ficker -,  p.  34  et  s. 


1 76 


R.  Caillemer  [ix 


siecle  et  n'a  jamais  etc"  une  institution  ge"nerale  dans  nos  regions  : 
jusqu'au  Xlir  siecle,  les  coutumes  de  la  region  que  nous  etudions 
ont  connu  un  droit  de  survie  tout  different.1 

Comme  exemple  de  ces  idees  coutumieres,  tres  diffe"rentes  des 
idees  romaines,  nous  avons  de\ja  pu,  dans  des  travaux  ante"rieurs, 
signaler  la  conception  de  la  proprie'te'  fonciere  et  des  droits  re"els 
sur  les  immeubles.  Loin  d'opposer  la  proprie'te'  proprement  dite 
et  les  jura  in  re  aliena,  les  textes  de  notre  region,  au  haut 
moyen  age,  considerent  les  divers  droits  de  jouissance,  se  tra- 
duisant  par  la  possession  d'un  immeuble,  comme  des  modalite's 
d'un  meme  droit  re"el  fondamental.  Le  droit  de  Pusufruitier  (p. 
ex.  du  donateur  avec  reserve  d'usufruit  ou  de  beneficium)  est  un 
droit  de  proprie'te'  viagere ;  le  droit  du  creancier  gagiste  est  un 
droit  de  proprie'te'  limite'e,  et  les  textes  lyonnais  appellent  toujours 
1'engagiste  emptor*  Un  acte  lyonnais  preVoit,  le  cas  e"che"ant, 
Palienation  de  la  terre  soumise  a  1'usufruit  par  Pusufruitier.3  Le 

1  Dans  cette  etude,  nous  nous  servirons  surtout  des  nombreux  recueils  de 
documents  lyonnais  et  dauphinois  publics  :  M.-C.  Guigue,  Cartulaire  lyonnais, 
2  vol.  in -4°,   Lyon,    1885-1893;    Aug.    Bernard,   Cartulaire  de  Vabbaye  de 
Savigny,  suivi  du  Petit  Cartulaire  de  Vabbaye  d'Ainay,  2  vol.,  Paris,  1853  ;  De 
Charpin  -  Feugerolles  et  M.-C.  Guigue,  Grand  Cartulaire  de  Pabbaye  d'Ainay, 
2  vol.  in-4°,  Lyon,  1885  ;  De  Charpin-Feugerolles  et  M.-C.  Guigue,  Cartulaire 
du  prieure  de  Saint-Sauveur  en  Rue,  I  vol.  in-4°,  Lyon,  1881  ;  De  Charpin- 
Feugerolles,  Cartulaire  des  Francs-fiefs  du  Forez,  Lyon,    i  vol.  in-4°,   1882  ; 
Valentin  Smith  et  M.-C.  Guigue,  Bibliotheca  Dumbensis,  2  vol.  in-4°,  Trevoux, 
1884-1885  ;    M.-C.   et  G.  Guigue,    Bibliothtque  historique   du   Lyonnais,    I, 
Lyon,    1886,  in- 8°;    M.-C.   Guigue,   Petit  Cartulaire  de  Fabbaye  de   Saint- 
Sulpice  en  Bugey,  Lyon,    1884,  in-8° ;  Aug.  Bernard  et  Aug.  Bruel,  Recueil 
des  chartes  de  tabbaye  de  Cluny^  6  vol.  in- 4°,  Paris,   1876-1903;  Valbonnais, 
Histoire  de  Dauphin^    Geneve,    2   vol.    in-f°,    1722;    M.    Fornier,    Histoire 
gtntrale  des  Alpes,  publiee  par  1'abbe  Guillaume,  3  vol.  in-8°,  Paris  et  Gap, 

1890-1892;  Ul.  Chevalier,  Collection  de  cartulaires  dauphinois,  notamment 
le  t.  ier,  Cartulaire  de  Saint-Andrt  le  Bas,  Vienne  et  Lyon,  1869,  in-8° ;  le 
t.  vii,  Choix  de  documents  historiques  ine"dits  sur  le  Dauphine1,  Montbeliard  et 
Lyon,  1874,  in-8° ;  et  le  t.  ix,  ie  livr.,  Codex  diplomaticus  ordinis  Sancti  Rufi 
Valentiae,  Valence,  1891,  in-8° ;  P.  Guillaume;  Chartes  de  Durbon,  Paris, 
1893,  in-8° ;  Auvergne,  Cartulaire  de  Saint-Robert  et  Cartulaire  des  £couges, 
Grenoble,  1865,  in-8°.  Pour  les  regions  plus  meridionales,  nous  avons  utilise 
surtout  le  Cartulaire  de  Vabbaye  de  Saint-Victor  de  Marseille,  public*  par 
Guerard,  Paris,  2  vol.  in-4°,  1857;  et  le  Cartulaire  de  la  commanderie  de 
Richerenches,  public  par  M.  de  Ripert-Monclar,  Avignon  et  Paris,  1907,  in-8°. 

2  V.  notre   etude    sur   Pengagement,    Festschrift  Heinrich   Brunner,    p. 
294  et  s. 

3  Cart,  de  S.-Andrt  le  Bos,  app.,  N°   114  :  usufruitier  qui  a  le  droit  de 
vendre,  de  donner,  d'echanger,  etc. 


ix]  Droit  Cout^lmier  177 

droit  de  1'usufruitier  ou  du  cre"ancier  gagiste  n'est  pas  un  simple 
jus  in  re  aliena :  c'est  une  propriete  temporaire,  un  estate  in  use, 
comme  dirait  le  droit  anglais,  qui  a  admirablement  conserv£  sur 
ce  point  la  vieille  idee  me'die'vale  ;  saisine  actuelle,  que  vient  limiter 
un  estate  futur,  en  reversion  ou  en  remainder. 

Nous  pourrions  encore  signaler  une  autre  idee  coutumiere,  tout 
a  fait  etrangere  au  droit  remain,  et  que  Ton  releve  dans  les  actes 
du  Sud-Est  de  la  France,  comme  dans  les  actes  d'autres  regions : 
1'idee  que  les  seuls  actes  stables  et  definitifs  sont  les  actes  a  titre 
one"reux,  assurant  a  chacune  des  parties  un  avantage  en  ^change 
du  sacrifice  qu'elle  consent ;  idee  commune  aux  diverses  races 
germaniques,  et  qui  se  manifeste  si  nettement  dans  le  launegild 
des  coutumes  lombardes.  Elle  revit,  en  plein  moyen  age,  dans 
divers  documents,  et  notamment  dans  les  chartes  du  cartulaire 
de  Richerenches.  Les  donataires  remettent  aux  donateurs 
une  caritas  ou  une  securitas,  en  argent  ou  en  nature ;  et  cette 
petite  contre-prestation  a  pour  but  d'assurer  la  stability  de  la 
donation :  les  chartes  le  disent  expressement.  Dans  un  autre 
document,  nous  trouvons  une  donation,  accompagne"e  de  cette 
contre-partie,  que  Ton  pense  rendre  plus  stable  en  lui  donnant 
Paspect  d'un  acte  a  titre  onereux,  et  en  la  qualifiant  de  emptio  et 
de  venditio.^ 

On  a  quelquefois  soutenu  que  1'emphyteose  avait  persiste  dans 

1  C.  de  Richerenches,  N°  43  (1148):  transaction:  «  Et,  ut  sic  observem 
et  sic  faciam,  seccuritatis  nomine  ab  Ugone  de  Bolbotone  de  helemosinis 
Templi  xiicim  sextarios  accipio  boni  frumenti,  et  iiiior  ordei,  et  unum  equum, 
id  est  caballum,  precio  1  sol.  Val. »  N°  49  (1149):  autre  dimissio\  «  Ut 
autem  ista  nostra  dimissio  et  libera  desemparatio  semper  seccura  et  firma 
remaneat  .  .  .  xcem  solidos  bone  monete  Val.  et  imam  saumatam  de 
frumento  accipimus,  caritatis  nomine.  »  N°  50  (1149):  « Ut  autem  ista 
mea  donacio  firma  et  stabilis  perpetuo  remaneat,  de  bonis  de  Templo  habui 
xicim  sol.  et  dim.  Val.,  et  unum  palafridum  cum  sella  et  freno.  »  N°  51 
(1150):  « Facta  est  hec  donacio  et  guirpicio  ...  in  manu  .  .  .  militum 
Templi,  a  quibus  caritative  helemosinis  Templi  accepimus  ccc  sol.  Val. 
monete. »  N°  54  (1147):  « Ut  autem  hec  nostra  donatio  stabilitatem  et 
securam  semper  habeat  firmitatem,  .  .  .  accepimus  septuaginta  solidos  vet. 
den.  Melg. »  On  peut  rapprocher  de  ce  dernier  acte  le  N°  5  8,  qui  est  qualifie 
de  venditio-empcio,  sans  indication  de  prix  de  vente,  dans  le  corps  de  1'acte. 
Mais,  apres  la  signature,  vient  la  note  suivante  :  «  Propter  hanc  empcionem 
fratres  milicie  Templi  his  supradictis  venditoribus  septuaginta  solidos  vet.  Melg. 
dederunt. »  L'acte  se  presente  plutot  comme  une  donation,  suivie  d'une  caritas 
de  70  sous,  comme  dans  le  N°  54.  Cf.  Schroder,  Deutsche  Rechtsgeschichte,  3* 
dd.,  p.  294  et  s. 

N 


178  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

le  Sud-Est  de  la  France  pendant  tout  le  moyen  age ;  mais  aucun 
texte  n'en  parle  avant  le  XIII6  siecle;  les  nombreux  contrats  que  nous 
avons  conserves,  relatifs  a  la  culture  de  la  terre,  sont,  soit  des 
contrats  de  prestaria  (on  ne  dit  guere :  precaria  dans  notre  region), 
soit  des  concessions  ad  medium  plantum,  soit,  dans  la  suite,  des 
albergements.  Ce  n'est  que  plus  tard,  apres  la  renaissance  du 
droit  romain,  que  le  nom  d'emphyteose  a  e"t£  donn£  a  1'alberge- 
ment.1 

Nous  pourrions  encore  noter,  dans  le  domaine  du  droit  des 
obligations,  la  persistance  des  anciennes  formes  de  garantie  reelle 
(impignoratio^)  et  de  garantie  personnelle  (hostagium).  U  hostagium, 
meme  d£cor£  du  nom  romain  de  fidejussio>  n'a  rien  de  commun 
avec  le  cautionnement  romain.3 

Mais  nous  voudrions  surtout  parler  du  droit  de  famille,  et 
montrer  que,  sur  ce  point,  le  triomphe  du  droit  romain  a  e"t£ 
incomplet,  tardif  et  pe"niblement  achete". 

§   Ier   LAUD  AT  10  DES   H^RITIERS 

Nous  noterons  d'abord,  a  ce  point  de  vue,  la  force  des  liens 
familiaux,  se  traduisant  par  la  necessity  du  concours  des  plus 
proches  heritiers  de  1'alienateur  aux  alienations  immobilieres.  Aux 
XIe  et  xile  siecles,  les  transferts  d'immeubles  sont  faits  avec  la 
laudatio  des  hoirs ;  s'il  n'y  a  pas  eu  de  laudatio,  a  la  mort  de 

1  Dans  les  actes  lyonnais,  1'emphyte'ose  apparait  en  1255  (C.  lyonnais^  ii. 
N°  518)  :  «  Donant  ...   in  emphiteosim  nomine  albergamenti  im  perpetuum, 
pro  xl  solidis  nomine  intragii  jam  solutis,  et  pro  xviii  denariis  .  .   .  annuatim 
de  supra  servicio  persolvendis.   .   .  .   Renunciant  .  .  .  exceptioni  intragii  non 
soluti. »     Dans  le  recueil  des  chartes  de  Durbon,  le  mot  emphyteose  n'apparait 
qu'en  1327  (N°  687). 

2  V.  notre  etude  sur  1'engagement,  citee  plus  haut. 

8  C.  lyonnais •,  i.  N°  219  (1226):  «  Dederunt  fidejussores  .  .  .  qui  .  .  . 
juraverunt  quod  si  ...  prefata  Michola  vel  filii  vel  filie  sue  ea  que  supra 
dicta  sunt  non  observarent  vel  in  aliquo  contravenirent,  ipsi  .  .  .  ostagium 
tenerent  inl  oco  sibi  .  .  .  designate.  »  N°  235  (1228)  :  «  Dederunt  fidejussores 
.  .  .  qui  similiter  juraverunt  se  tenere  ostagia  Lugduni  si  premissi  Hugo  et 
frater  suus  non  observarent  premissa. »  N°  389  (1244):  « Dedit  ecclesie 
fidejussores  pads  juratos  de  dicta  vendicione  in  perpetuum  tenenda  in  pace  .  .  . 
qui  ad  ammonicionem  dicte  ecclesie  infra  xv  dies  postquam  fuerint  moniti, 
juraverunt  tenere  tanidiu  ostagium  Lugduni,  donee  a  dicta  ecclesia  licentiam 
habuerint  recedendi. »  N°  402  (1245),  acte  tres  curieux,  ou  des  tuteurs, 
vendant  des  biens  de  mineur,  se  portent  fidtjusseurs  et  promettent  de  tenir 
ostagium. 


IX] 


Droit  Coutumier 


179 


l'alie"nateur  ses  he"ritiers  s'efforcent  de  reprendre  les  biens  alie"ne"s, 
et  se  font  souvent  payer  tres  cher  par  I'acque'reur  leur  ratification.1 
Get  usage  de  la  laudatio  persiste  apres  la  renaissance  du  droit 
remain,  et  il  n'est  pas  rare,  meme  dans  la  seconde  moitie"  du 
Xlir  siecle,  de  voir  Pali^nateur,  donateur  ou  vendeur,  promettre 
d'obtenir  la  laudatio  de  ses  fils  ou  de  ses  freres,  alors  absents  ou 
empeche"s.2  Dans  toute  donation  importante,  le  donateur  tient  a 
s'entourer  du  concours  de  ses  parents  et  de  ses  amis,  a  obtenir 
leur  consentement,  qui  parfois  ne  sera  donne  que  moyennant  des 
sacrifices  pecuniaires,  plus  ou  moins  considerables,  consentis  par 
l'acque"reur.3  Ces  pratiques  ont  leur  utilite",  et  ces  precautions  ne 
sont  pas  superflues.  Au  Xlir  siecle  comme  pre"ce"demment,  il 
n'est  pas  rare  de  voir,  apres  la  mort  de  1'alienateur,  ses  he"ritiers 

1  Exemples  de   reclamations    d'heritiers,  au    xne    siecle :    Valbonnais,    i. 
p.  39,  S  (1132)  :  a  la  suite  d'une  transaction,  les  deux  fils  de  1'une  des  parties 
attaquent   1'acte,  disant :    « absque   consilio  et   assensu  eorum   fuisse  factum, 
ideo  minime  tenendum. »     Selon  la  vieille  conception  medievale,  les  temoins 
de   1'acte  viennent  prendre  sa  defense,   et  obtiennent  une   renonciation   des 
enfants.     Giraud,  C.  de  S.-Barnard  de  Romans^  ii.  preuves,  p.  20  :  «...  Im- 
posueramus    calumpniam    super    unam  terram  .  .  .,    quam    terram    ecclesia 
Romanensis  Sd  Bernardi  ab  antiquo  tempore  acquisierat  de  nostro  genere. » 
Les  reclamants  cedent,  moyennant  13  sous,  et  la  concession  a  Tun  d'entre  eux 
de  la  jouissance  viagere  du  bien  litigieux.      C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  163  (i  190  env.)  : 
«  Moricinus  vendidit  domum  suam.   .* .  .  Postea  vero  tres   filii  ejus  calum- 
niaverunt  .   .  .  vendicionem  » ;  on  leur  donne  22  sous. 

2  Alienateurs  promettant  d'obtenir  la  laudatio  de  leurs  fils  :  C.  lyonnais, 
i.  N°  465  (1251)  :  «Promitto  nichilominus  sub  virtute  prestiti  juramenti,  quod 
omnia  premissa  et  singula  faciam  in  perpetuum  a  filiis  meis  Bosone,  Symboudo 
et  Alberto  rata  habere  et  firma,  et  servare  illesa,  prout  superius  sunt  expressa.» 
ii.    N°   552    (1259):    acte   de  vente :    « Promittit  rnsuper  sepedictus    Berlio 
venditor,  sub  prestito  juramento  et  sub  obligatione  omnium  bonorum  suorum, 
quod  ipse  procurabit,  faciet  et  efficiet  quod  dominus  Jacobus  de  Spina  miles, 
Guillelmus  de   Spina  domicellus,    Albertus   de   Gorgi   frater  ipsius   Berlionis, 
Quarta  uxor,  Jaquemetus  et  Guionetus  filii  ejusdem  Alberti,  ad  requisitionem 
dicte  domine  Brune  .   .  .  dictam  venditionem  .  .  .  laudabunt,  approbabunt, 
gratificabunt  et  acceptabunt  per  juramentum  et  sub  testimonio  litterarum » : 
ainsi  le  frere,  1'epouse,  deux  neveux  du  vendeur,  et  deux  milites^  sans  doute 
deux  vassaux  (parmi  les  biens  vendus  figurent  les  «  taschiae  illorum  de  Spina  »). 
N°  589  (1261) :  transaction  ;  consentement  d'un  frere  present,  et  promesse  de 
laudatio  de  deux  freres  absents. 

3  C.  de  S.-Sulpice  en  Bugey^  N°  29  (1239),  p.  83  :  don  fait  par  £tienne 
de  Luyrieux  avant  de  partir  pour  la  Terre  Sainte,  «  de  voluntate  et  consilio 
amicorum  meorum  et  parentum  sive  consanguineorum,  assensuque  G.  domini 
de   Luyrieux  nepotis   mei   et   Hu.,  fratris   ejus,    super  hoc   accedente. »      Le 
donateur  revolt  300  florins  « nomine  placiti»,  1'un  des  neveux  20  florins,  et 
1'autre  10. 


180  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

revendiquer  les  biens  ali£n£s,  sous  ce  pre"texte  qu'ils  n'ont  pas 
donn£  leur  laudatio,  et  ne  renoncer  a  leurs  preventions  que  moyennant 
un  de"dommagement  p^cuniaire.1 

La  necessity  de  ce  consentement  des  plus  proches  he"ritiers 
prend  meme,  a  ce  moment,  une  nettete"  plus  grande.  Les  conditions 
de  la  laudatio  se  pre"cisent.  Lorsque  I'he'ritier  dont  la  laudatio  est 
requise  a  moins  de  14  ans,  on  assure,  au  moyen  de  promesses 
spe"ciales,  garanties  par  des  fidejusseurs,  sa  laudatio  ulte"rieure, 
lorsqu'il  aura  atteint  ses  anni  legitimi?  Les  enfants  de  plus  de  14 

1  C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  409  (1246)  :  «  Asserebat  .  .  .   Stephanus  (Etienne  de 
Chandieu)  duas  vercherias  .   .  .,   quas  .  .   .  prior  de   Plateria  nomine  dicte 
ecclesie  detinebat,  ad  se  jure  hereditario  pertinere,  et  ideo   eas  sibi  restitui 
postulabat,  nonobstante  quadam  venditione,  quam  eo  inscio  et  minime  requisite, 
Berlio  frater  suus  .  .   .  fecerat. »      Sentence   arbitrate :    le    reclamant   devra 
ceder  tous   ses    droits,  moyennant^  7  livres   et  20  sous.     V.  encore  N°  251 
(1229)  ;  N°  444  (1250).      C  des  Ecouges,  N°  20  (1232) :  Lantelme  de  Saint- 
Quentin  a  donne  divers  biens  aux  religieux  des  Ecouges,  mais,  apres  sa  mort, 
ses  fils  veulent  reprendre  les  biens  donne's.     A  la  fin,  grace  a  1'intervention 
du  Doyen  de  1'eglise  de  Grenoble,  Tun  des  fils,  Guillaume  de  Saint-Quentin, 
renonce  a  sa  reclamation,  et  promet  meme  de  defendre  le  monastere  contre 
toute  attaque,  toute  «calumnia»  nouvelle.     II  se  fera  le  defenseur  de  la  donation 
meme  vis-a-vis  de  ses  freres  ;  toutefois,  il  ne  s'engage  pas  a  leur  faire  la  guerre 
ni  a  depenser  sa  fortune  a  ce  sujet :  «  excepto  quod  belluin  contra  fratres  facere 
vel  sua  expendere  non  tenetur  »  ! 

2  Sur  cette  question  de  la  laudatio  de  1'enfant,  il  y  a,  au  haut  moyen  age, 
des  systemes  divergents  :  tantot  on  fait  intervenir  Penfant   lui-meme,  tantot 
on  assure,  par  des  fidejusseurs  ou  par  des  serments,  qu'il  donnera  plus  tard  sa 
laudatio.     Ce  dernier  systeme  triomphe  dans  les  actes  lyonnais  du  xnie  siecle. 
On  n'admet  plus  la  laudatio  emanee  des  enfants  eux-memes.     V.  C.  lyonnais, 
i.   N°   167   (1220);    laudatio  des  fils,  « qui   talis   erant   etatis   quod   ad   eos 
laudare  pertinebat.»     N°  188  (1222):  les  fils  ne  donnent  pas  de  laudatio  : 
« nullus  adhuc  erat  talis  etatis,  quod  ad  eum   laudare  pertineret. »     N°  2 1 6 
(1225):  «laudaverunt  omnes  filii  mei,  qui  tales  erant  etatis,  quod  ad  ipsos 
laudare  pertinebat. »     Des  lors,  si  1'enfant  est  trop  jeune,  on  promet  sa  laudatio 
pour  le  jour  ou  il  arrivera  a  ses  anni  legitimi,  ad  plenam  etatem.     N°  2 1 9 
(1226):    « et   quum  minor  filius  Odo  nondum  videbatur  ad  annos  legitimos 
pervenisse. »      N°  221    (1226);    « Ut  hec  venditio   rata   et   firma  habeatur, 
dederunt   fidejussorem  Vincencium  de   Poimia,    donee   eorum   infantuli    per- 
venerint    ad  plenam   etatem    et   concesserint   plenarie   dictam  venditionem. » 
V.  encore  t.  ii.  N°  508  (1255) :  ad  etatem  congruam.      Quelques  textes  parlent 
de  minors*,  de  major  aetas :  i.  N°  287  (1234):  «  Promisit  etiam  sub  eodem 
juramento  quod,  cum  Jaquemeta  filia  ipsius,  qui  tune  temporis  minoris  etatis 
erat,  ad  annos  legitimos  pervenerit,  faciat  earn  laudare  et  jurare  pacem  de  hac 
venditione. »     N°  269  (1231):    « Et   obligamus  nos  eodem  juramento  quod 
heredes  nostri,  qui  tempore  donationis  erant  in  minori  etate,  quando  essent  in 
majori,  eamdem  donationem  laudarent  et  confirmarent.  »    Mais  ces  expressions  : 
minor  aetas,  major  aetas  ne  doivent  pas  etre  interpreters  comme  des  allusions 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  181 

ans,  mais  mineurs  de  25  ans,  fournissent  eux-memes  leur  laudatio  ^ 
sur  le  mandat  de  leur  pere,  en  renonc.ant  aux  exceptions  de 
minority  et  de  puissance  paternelle.1  L'importance  de  la  laudatio 
parait  telle,  que  cette  laudatio  est  souvent  consignee  dans  une 
charte  spe"ciale,  attested  par  des  temoins  particuliers.2  Et  enfin, 
pour  entourer  cette  institution,  si  completement  e"trangere  au  droit 
romain,  de  formes  romaines,  on  voit  apparaitre  a  la  fin  des  actes 
une  renonciation  nouvelle :  a  Vexceptio  concessionis  et  laudationis 
non  fact e? 

Get  ancien  usage  de  la  laudatio  des  heritiers  a  laisse",  en 
Provence  et  en  Dauphine",  des  traces  curieuses.  En  1456,  Louis 
II,  le  futur  Louis  XI,  alors  Dauphin  de  Viennois,  promulgua  un 
statut  exigeant,  pour  la  validite  d'une  donation,  la  presence  du  bailli, 
du  juge  ou  du  chatelain  du  domicile  du  donateur,  et,  de  plus,  le 
concours  de  trois  de  ses  plus  proches  parents  habitant  la  meme 

a  la  majorite  de  25  ans.  II  s'agit  en  realite  de  la  puberte,  que  nos  coutumes 
fixent  a  14  ans.  N°  445  (1250):  «  Dictus  siquidem  Stephanus  promisit  per 
stipulationem  et  sub  prestito  juramento  quod,  quam  cito  Hugo,  Uldricus  et 
Placencia  liberi  ipsius  ad  annos  pubertatis  pervenerint,  ipse  faciat  et  efficiet, 
quod  ipsi  liberi  .  .  .  dictam  venditionem  laudabunt  et  approbabunt.  »  ii. 
N°  511  (1255):  « Hanc  autem  venditionem  Zacharias  films  dicti  Guidonis, 
major  quatuordecim  annis,  prout  ipsi  pater  et  films  per  juramentum  asserunt, 
sponte  sciens  et  prudens  laudat,  approbat,  gratific'at  et  acceptat. »  V.  aussi 
N°  522  (1255):  «facti  puberes,  prout  ipsi  per  juramentum  asserunt. » 

1  C.    lyonnais,   ii.    N°    536    (1256):    reprise   de   fief:    «  Hanc   autem   re- 
ceptionem    feudi  .   .   .   Petrus,    filius   dicti   Aemari,  coram   nobis   constitutus, 
sciens,  prudens  et  spontaneus,  de  mandate  ipsius  Aemari,  laudat,  approbat, 
gratificat    et    acceptat.    .    .    .    Renuntiant  .   .   .,  et .  dictus    Petrus    exception! 
quod    metus    causa,  minoris    etatis,    beneficio   patrie   potestatis.  »      V.  aussi 
N°  509  (1255),  ou  les  trois  fils  du  donateur,  accordant  leur  laudatio,  renoncent 
«  minoris  etatis  auxilio  et  beneficio,  et  patrie  potestati.  » 

2  Cart,  de  S.-Ruf,  N°  93  (1205) :  «  Quando  Guntardus  et  Eicburgis,  amita 
Raimundi,  hoc  laudaverunt,  presentes  erant.  .  .   .   Quando  Ymbertus  Runini 
(frere  du  donateur  Raimond)  hoc  laudavit  in  claustro  Sancti  Jacobi,  et  etiam 
super  iiiior  evangelia  juravit,  presentes  erant.   ...»     De  meme  N°  96  (1207). 

3  C.  lyonnais,  ii.  N°  757  (1279):  confirmation  par  4  freres  :  « Johannes, 
Guillermetus,  majores  viginti  et  quinque   annis,  Bartholomeus   et    Jaquetus, 
minores  viginti  quinque  annis,  majores  tamen  decem  et  septem  annis  » ;   et 
renonciation :   « exception!    .    .    .    concessionis   et   confessionis  .   .  .  legitime 
non    factarum. »     N°    813    (1287):    laudatio    d'un   neveu :    « renuncians   ex- 
ceptioni    ratifications,    acceptationis,    confessionis,    concessionis,    remissionis 
et  promissionis  .  .  .  non  factarum  vel  sine  justa  causa  factarum.  »     N°  827 
(1290) :  confirmation  par  les  deux  fils  du  donateur  (donation  d'une  rente  d'un 
fromage)  :  ils  renoncent  «  exception!  dictarum  quittationis,  laudationis  et  con- 
cessionis non  factarum. » 


1 82  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

paroisse.1  Et  c'e"tait  seulement  si  Ton  ne  pouvait  trouver  ces  trois 
parents,  ou  s'ils  refusaient  d'intervenir  a  1'acte,  que  le  magistrat 
pouvait  appeller  comme  te"moins  d'autres  probi  viri. 

Du  Dauphine",  la  regie  est  passed  en  Provence.  En  1472,  un 
statut  du  roi  Rene"  est  venu  exiger,  pour  la  validity  des  donations, 
la  presence  de  deux  parents  du  donateur ;  et  ici  ce  ne  sont  plus  de 
simples  te"moins ;  ils  viennent  eclairer  le  donateur  sur  la  portee  de 
la  donation.  Le  statut  exige,  non  seulement  leur  presence,  mais 
leur  conscientia?  Visiblement,  le  but  de  ces  deux  statuts  est 
moins  de  proteger  la  famille  du  donateur,  que  de  garantir  le 
donateur  lui-meme  contre  ses  propres  entrainements.  Mais,  dans 
le  precede  qu'ils  emploient  pour  atteindre  ce  but,  en  faisant 
intervenir  les  parents  du  donateur,  ces  statuts  nous  pre"sentent  une 
curieuse  survie  des  anciennes  id£es  medievales. 

D'autre  part,  le  retrait  lignager  s'est  developpe,  a  la  fin  du 
moyen  age,  dans  un  assez  grand  nombre  de  coutumes  locales  de 
la  region.  II  est  ne"  d'un  desir  de  concilier  les  inte"rets  de  la 
famille  de  Palie"nateur  avec  la  necessite  des  alienations  immobilieres. 
Dans  quelques  documents,  nous  voyons  des  disposants  instituer 
une  sorte  de  retrait  lignager  conventionnel.  Alie"nant  un  de  leurs 
biens,  ils  prevoient  la  possibilite  d'un  rachat  de  ce  bien  par  leurs 
heritiers ; 3  ou  encore,  re"glant  le  sort  de  Pensemble  de  leur  fortune 

1  Ce  statut   a  etc  souvent   imprime  ;    il  figure,   avec  le  commentaire  de 
Joannes  a  Cruce,  a  la  suite  de  certaines  editions  des  Decisiones  de  Guy  Pape. 
V.,  p.  ex.,  1'ed.  de  Geneve,  1653,  2e  pagin.,  p.  69  et  s.  :  « .   .  .    Decernimus 
donationes  praedictas  (inter  vivos)  de  caetero  fiendas  non  esse  aliter  valituras, 
quam  si  in  baillivi,  judicis  aut  castellani  loci  sive  parochiae  domicilii  donatoris, 
vel    locatenentis    eorumdem,   et   trium   ex  proximioribus    consanguineis    sive 
parentibus  ipsius  donatoris  in  dicta  parochia  existentibus,  vel,  ubi  non  reperi- 
rentur  in  dicta  parochia,  aut  vocati  adesse  nollent  in  donatione  praedicta, 
aliorum  virorum  proborum  dictae  parochiae  non  suspectorum,  per  alterum  ex 
dictis  officiariis,  pro  numero  parentum  non  repertorum,  aut  adesse  ut  supra 
nolentium,  surrogandorum,  praesentia  factae  fuerint,  recitatae  et  publicatae.  » 

2  V.  notre  etude  sur  le  Retrait  lignager  dans  le  droit  proven$al  (Studi  in 
onore  di  Carlo  Fadda\  p.  1 1  et  s.  (Naples,  1 906). 

3  On  trouve,  des  le  xie  siecle,  des  actes  de  ce  genre  dans  les  Ch.  de  Cluny, 
iv.   N°  2525  (1000   env.)  :    «  Facio  autem  hanc   donationem   eo    tenore,  ut, 
dum  aliquis  ex  filiis  meis  ad  perfectam  etatem  venerit,  si  redimere  voluerit, 
redimat  xlta  solidis.  »     N°  2972  (1048-1049):  « Dono  .  .   .   unum  mansum 
.    .    .    ea  ratione  ut  filius   meus  Wichardus,  si   voluerit  eum   redimere,  det 
pro  ipso  manso  habitatoribus    supranominati   loci    (monasterii  Cluniacensis) 
xx  solidos  ;   sin  alias,  ipsi  monachi  teneant  et  possideant.  »     V.  aussi  le  N° 
2973  (meme  date),  acte  mutil£ :  « Dono  ...   si  legalem  heredem  de  uxore 


ix]  Droit  Coutuniier  183 

par  un  partage  d'ascendant,  ils  stipulent  que,  si  Tun  des  biens  de 
la  succession  est  vendu  par  un  de  leurs  heritiers,  les  autres  he"ritiers 
auront  a  son  e*gard  un  droit  de  preemption.  Ainsi,  dans  un  acte 
lyonnais  de  1243,  une  veuve,  repartissant  sa  fortune  entre  ses 
enfants,  decide  que,  si  Tun  des  enfants  veut  vendre  ou  obliger  les 
biens  compris  dans  son  lot,  il  devra  d'abord  les  offrir  a  ses  freres, 
ou  meme  a  d'autres  parents.1 

Cette  institution  du  retrait  lignager  ne  s'est  pas  developpee 
partout  dans  la  region  qui  nous  occupe.  On  ne  la  rencontre  ni 
en  Savoie,  ni  en  Bresse,  ni  en  Lyonnais ;  mais,  au  XIIIe  siecle  et 
au  XIV6,  elle  a  e*t£  consacre"e  par  d'assez  nombreuses  coutumes 
locales  du  Dauphin^  et  de  la  Provence ;  et  elle  a  e"te"  enfin  e"tendue 
a  tout  le  comt£  de  Provence  par  un  statut  de  1469.2 

§  2.  REGIME  MATRIMONIAL 

L'etude  du  regime  des  gens  maries  est  aussi  caracteristique, 
qu'il  s'agisse  des  apports  de  la  femme,  ou  des  donations  que  son 
mari  lui  fait  au  moment  du  mariage. 

A.  Apports  de  la  femme. — Inalienability  de  la  dot. 

Pendant  tout  le  haut  moyen  age,  nous  trouvons  dans  nos 
regions,  comme  dans  la  France  coutumiere,  une  association  etroite 
des  deux  epoux  dans  tous  les  actes  qui  se  rapportent  a  la  gestion 
des  biens  du  manage.  Qu'il  s'agisse  des  biens  du  mari,  ou  qu'il 

habuero,  si  tenere  voluerit,  ducentos  solidos  .  .  .  redimi.  ...»  Cf. 
Festschrift  Brunner,  p.  294,  note  I.  C.  lyonnais,  ii.  N°  570  (1260): 
testament  d'un  bourgeois  de  Beaujeu,  Mguant,  pour  son  anniversaire  et  celui 
de  sa  femme,  une  vigne  a  Peglise  Notre-Dame  de  Beaujeu  :  «  Si  autem  dilecti 
filii  mei  Johannes  et  Bernardus  vel  alter  ipsorum  potuerit  assignare  dictis 
presbiteris  quindecim  solidos  Viennensium  debitales  vel  solvere  quindecim 
libras  Viennensium  ad  emendos  redditus  pro  dicto  anniversario  faciendo,  volo 
quod  dicta  vinea,  hoc  facto,  ad  ipsos  redeat  pleno  jure.  »  Acte  de  1272, 
cite"  dans  notre  etude  sur  le  Retrait  lignager  dans  le  droit  proven^al,  p.  1 6. 
Dans  d'autres  actes,  le  droit  de  rachat  est  limite  a  certains  cas  determines, 
p.  ex.,  au  cas  ou  le  donataire  ne  respecterait  pas  les  clauses  de  la  donation,  ou 
les  biens  donnes  ne  seraient  pas  laisses  a  1'usage  collectif  des  moines. 

1  C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  378  :    «...   Item  voluit  et  ordinavit  dicta  A.,  quod, 
si  predicti  filii  sui  vel  alter  eorum  de  rebus  supradictis  .  .   .  vellent  aliquid 
vendere,  obligare  seu  alio  modo  alienare,  primo  presentarent  sive  presentaret 
fratribus  suis  aliis  predictis  vel  eorum  propinquis.  »     V.  aussi  BibL  Dumbcnsis, 
i.  p.  331  (1402). 

2  V.  notre  etude  sur  le  Retrait  lignager,  1.  cit.,  p.  16  et  s.,  25  et  s. 


184  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

s'agisse  des  apports  de  la  femme  (de"signes,  non  pas  du  terme  de 
dos\  mais  des  noms  de  maritagium,  matrimonium,  mar  it  amentum,1 
vercheria  en  Provence2),  les  deux  6poux  agissent  ensemble  et 
disposent  ensemble  de  leurs  biens.  Aucune  trace  de  Tinalie'nabilite' 
dotale  ne  peut  etre  releve'e.  Encore  au  milieu 'du  XIIP  siecle  nous 
trouvons  93.  et  la  des  femmes  alie"nant  leurs  immeubles  dotaux  avec 
le  concours  de  leur  mari,  sans  qu'aucun  doute  s'eleve  sur  la  validite" 
de  ces  actes.3  Pendant  tout  le  haut  moyen  age,  la  ne"cessite"  de  la 
laudatio  des  plus  proches  heritiers  de  la  femme  pour  1'alienation 
des  immeubles  de  celle-ci  rendait  superflu  tout  autre  systeme  de 
protection.  Certains  documents  sont,  a  cet  e*gard,  tres  caracteris- 
tiques.  En  Bugey,  en  1234,  Pierre  de  Noiret  donne  aux  Chartreux 
de  Meyriat,  du  consentement  de  sa  femme,  des  biens  faisant  partie 
de  la  dos  de  celle-ci.  Plus  tard,  il  attaque  cette  alienation  ;  or,  il 
n'invoque  nullement  le  caractere  dotal  des  biens  alienes ;  il  allegue 
des  raisons  toutes  differentes  :  ces  biens  sont  occupe"s  par  des  tiers, 
qui  les  detiennent  en  vertu  d'un  albergement ;  et  ces  tenanciers, 
n'ayant  pas  consenti  a  1'alienation,  declarent  qu'elle  ne  leur  est  pas 
opposable.  L'arbitre  choisi,  1'eveque  de  Belley,  oblige  Pierre  de 
Noiret  a  faire  laudatio  de  sa  propre  donation,  en  obtenant  cette  fois 
la  laudatio  de  ses  fils  et  des  tenanciers  recalcitrants.  II  ne  semble 
pas  mettre  en  doute,  au  point  de  vue  du  regime  matrimonial,  la 
pleine  validite  de  cet  acte.4 

1  Maritagium :    Bibl.  Hist,  du  Lyonnais,  p.  29  (1229);  C.  lyonnais,  i. 
N°  2 56  (i 229) ;  236  (1228).    Maritamentum  :  C.  de  S.-Andre1  le  Bas,  N°  1 93. 
Matrimonium:    C.    lyonnais,    i.    N°   163   (1219).      Cf.    C.   de  S. -Vincent  de 
Mdcon,  N°  477  :  «  Nepti  sue  donavit  in  maritatu.   ...» 

2  Vercheria  :  hommage  d'Amauri  de  Montfort  a  1'archeveque  d'Embrun, 
en  1222,  a  raison  des  biens  de  sa  femme  en  Embrunais,  Fornier,  iii.  p.  226. 
Le  mot  est  reste  dans  la  langue  proven^ale.     V.  Mistral,  Lou  Tresor  dou  feli- 
brige,  v°  verquiero  : 

Fiho  poulido  porto  sa  verquiero  au  front. 

3  P.  ex.,  en   1247   (C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  417),  une  femme  vend  une  maison 
avec  le  consentement  de  son  mari,  sans  que  1'acte  contienne  la  moindre  allusion 
aux  obstacles  tenant  au  regime  dotal ;  v.  encore  NOS22I  (1226);  287  (1234). 
C.  de  S.-Sauveur  en  Rue,    N°  cxxxviii.  (1253):  « Ego  Pictavina,  .   .  .  con- 
sentiente  et  volente  praedicto  viro  meo,  .  .   .  dono  et  concede  .   .   .  terram 
meam  dotalem  .  .  .   cum  censibus  et  usagiis  et  pleno  dominio  dictae  terrae. » 
Peu  importe  le  mode  d'alienation,  vente  ou  donation,  et  Ton  pourrait  multiplier 
les  exemples  de  ce  genre. 

4  C.  de  S.-Sulpice  en  Bugey,  N°  27  (1234).     Cette  question  de  la  necessite 
du  consentement  des  tenanciers  dans  les  alienations  a  etc,  jusqu'ici,  assez  peu 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  185 

L'idee  de  la  communaute  entre  e"poux,  qui  triomphera  plus  tard 
dans  la  France  coutumiere,  mais  que  le  regime  dotal  remain 
chassera  de  la  region  que  nous  e"tudions,  se  manifeste  dans  diverses 
chartes,  et  notamment  dans  certains  documents  lyonnais  du  haut 
moyen  age.  II  arrive  souvent  que  deux  e"poux,  faisant  une 
donation  avec  reserve  d'usufruit,  stipulent  que,  au  d£ces  du  pre"- 
mourant,  1'usufruit  s'e"teindra  pour  une  moitie,  que  cette  moitie"  ira 
au  couvent  et  servira  de  donation  pro  sepultura  pour  ce  premourant ; 
tandis  que  1'usufruit  se  continuera  pour  moitie"  au  profit  du  conjoint 
survivant.1  Et  ce  partage  par  moitie"  est  particulierement  remar- 
quable  quand  le  bien  donne  par  les  e"poux  est  un  bien  qu'ils  ont 
acquis  au  cours  du  mariage,  p.  ex.,  par  suite  d'un  contrat  de 
concession  fonciere  ad  medium  plantum? 

etudiee  dans  les  actes  frai^ais.  Cette  question  se  rattache  a  celle  de  la 
necessite  de  la  saisine  pour  une  alienation  valable,  principe  qui  s'affirme  des 
1'epoque  franque,  et  qui  a  subsiste  dans  certaines  coutumes  (p.  ex.  dans  les 
coutumes  anglaises)  avec  une  grande  nettete. 

1  C.   de   Savigny,    N°   83    (env.    970):    « Tali   convenientia    ut,    quandiu 
vixerimus,  teneamus,  .  .  .  et  qualiscumque  de  nobis  duobus  primus  obierit, 
medietas  ipsius  mansi  in  dominicatum  veniat. »     N°   170  (env.   980):     « Eo 
videlicet   tenore  ut   quamdiu   vixero   fructum   percipiam  ;    post  mortem   vero 
meam    ex    medietate    ejus    sepulturam    habeam\    aliam    autem    medietatem 
Adalendis  uxor  mea,  quamdiu  vixerit,  possideat ;  et,  qualiscumque  ex  nobis 
prius  obierit,  absque  ulla  contradictione,  ad  cultores  ipsius  ecclesiae  medietas 
de  ipsa  haereditate  perveniat ;  post  decessum  vero  utrorumque  omnia  vobis 
cedo. »     C.  d^Ainay  (Bernard),  N°  72  (av.  993)  :  deux  epoux  donnent  «aliquid 
ex  rebus  nostris,  hoc  est  curtilem  unum, »  avec  reserve  d'usufruit ;  «  et,  quisquis 
ex  nobis  duobus  primus  obierit,  unam  medietatem  predicti  monachi  ex  supra- 
scriptis    rebus    recipiant.       Post    amborum    quoque    discessu  .   .  .  totum   ad 
integrum  teneant  et  possideant. »     N°  105  (989)  :  memes  formules.      N°  1 1 1 
(env.  1000)  :  «  Ita  ut  quicumque  de  nobis  duobus  prius  mortuus  fuerit,  statim 
monachi   prescripti   loci  suam   medietatem   accipiant,   subsequens   vero  stiam 
medietatem  teneat  dum  vixerit ;  post  mortem  autem  illius,  medietatem  illam 
monachi  prefati  in  suo  jure  ponant. » 

2  V.  notamment  C.  de  Savigny,  N°  266  (970  env.).     Deux  epoux  donnent 
des  terres  qu'ils  ont  acquises  par  un  partage  avec  les  moines  de  1'Ile-Barbe  : 
«quicquid  cum  monachis  Insulae  Barbarae  partiendo  visi  sumus  habere  ;  .  .  . 
ita  tamen  ut  medietas  de  ipsis  rebus  ad  ipsam  ecclesiam  pro  sepultura  corporis 
mei  a  die  praesenti  perveniat ;  aliam  vero   medietatem,    quamdiu    Dulcisina 
uxor  mea  vixerit,  possideat,  et  post  suum  decessum  sepulturae  locum  exinde 
accipiat.»     La  terre  acquise  se  partage  done  egalement  entre  les  deux  epoux, 
et  chacun  d'eux  dispose  de  sa  part/n?  sepultura.     V.,  sur  ces  tendances  des 
coutumes  de  la  France  meridionale,  avant  la  renaissance  du  droit  remain,  les 
tres  justes  observations  de  M.   Lefebvre,  Nouv.  Rev.  hist,  de  Droit,   1911, 
p.  369  et  s.,  notamment  p.   390,   ou  1'auteur  cite  encore  d'autres   actes  des 
cartulaires  d'Ainay  et  de  Grenoble. 


1 86  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

Tel  e"tait  le  droit  de  nos  regions  avant  la  renaissance  du  droit 
remain,  et  il  ressemblait  en  somme  singulierement  a  celui  de  la 
France  coutumiere.  La  romanisation  s'est  faite  peu  a  peu  ;  elle 
ne  se  traduit  d'abord  que  dans  les  mots  et  dans  les  formules,  et 
elle  ne  modifie  pas  au  debut  le  fond  du  droit. 

Le  mot  dos  reparait  avec  son  sens  remain,  et  il  remplace  peu  a 
peu,  pour  designer  le  patrimoine  de  la  femme,  les  autres  termes 
rappele"s  plus  haut.1  Puis,  dans  les  renonciations  qui  terminent  les 
actes,  on  voit  apparaitre  des  clauses  se  rapportant  a  la  lex  Julia 
(avec  le  sens  que  les  romanistes  du  moyen  age  donnent  a  ces  mots), 
au  Se"natus-consulte  Velle"ien,  au  privilege  de  dot,  a  1'hypotheque 
de  la  femme  sur  les  biens  du  mari.2  Quand  une  femme  reprend  en 
fief  une  de  ses  terres,  elle  renonce  juri  prohibenti  ne  super  re 

1  Parmi   les  actes   des  Dauphins,  le   premier  qui   parle   de  dos  au  sens 
remain  est  1'acte  de  1202  par  lequel  Guillaume,  comte  de  Forcalquier,  donne 
a  sa  fille  Beatrix,  qui  doit  epouser  Andre  Dauphin,  ses  possessions  de  Gap 
et  d'Embrun.      Fornier,  iii.  p.   222.      Vers   la   meme  epoque,  dans  un  acte 
lyonnais  de  1206  (C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  99),  dos  designe  sans  doute  aussi  la  dot 
romaine.       Pour  1'epoque  anterieure,   on  ne   peut  relever  que  quelques   tres 
rares   documents  ou  dos  designe   1'apport  de   la  femme  :  Ch.   de  Cluny,  N° 
2528  (acte  maconnais  non  date,  des  environs  de  1'an  1000  ?).     Partout  ailleurs, 
jusqu'a  la  fin  du  xne  siecle,  le   mot   designe  la  donation   du  mari  (Ch.  de 
Cluny,  Nos  1777,  2628,  etc.). 

2  Dans  le  C.  de  S. -Victor  de  Marseille,  les  premieres  renonciations  de  ce 
genre  remontent  aux  annees  1202  (N°  977),  1212  (N°  930),  1229  (N°  909) ; 
ces  documents  ont  etc  deja  signales  par  M.  Meynial,  Nouv.  Rev.  hist,  de  Droit, 
1901,  p.  275,  n.  2,  et  p.  689,  n.  2.      Dans  les  actes  lyonnais,  on  trouve  vers 
1215,  sous  une  forme  encore  rudimentaire,  les  premieres  renonciations  relatives 
au  regime  matrimonial.      C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  140  (1216):  «  Renuncians  omni 
juri   sibi   in  his   rebus   competenti  vel   in   futurum  ratione  dotis  vel   propter 
nuptias   donationis  vel  alicujus   melioramenti   competituro,  juramento   ab   ea 
interposito.  »     N°   164  (1219):    « Preterea  predicte  Dideria  et  Rollenz  pro- 
miserunt  sub  eodem  juramento,  quod  ratione  dotis  vel  alia  qualibet  ratione 
contra    hanc   venditionem    non  venirent,   nee   eundem    Stephanum   super  re 
vendita    presumerent    aliquatenus    molestare.  »       N°    233     (1228):     « abre- 
nuntiantes  .  .   .  exception!   dotis.  »     N°  236  (1228):    « Abrenunciavit   omni 
juri  quod  habebat  in  eisdem  mansis  ratione  maritagii  vel  aliqua  alia  ratione.  » 
N°  261    (1230):    « Expresse    renuncians   omni   exceptioni  et  omni   benefitio 
et  auxilio  juris  canonici  et  civilis,  que  ipsam  contingerent  in  hac  parte.  »     Au 
N°  256  (1229),  la  femme  renonce   simplement  au  privilegium  dotis.      Les 
renonciations   detaillees   n'apparaissent  que   plus   tard :    Bibl.   Dumbensis,   ii. 
Suppl.    N°    in    (1253).       V.,    sur    Phistoire   des  renonciations    en    general, 
Petude  precitee  de  M.  Meynial.     On  rencontre  des  renonciations  en  Dauphine" 
et  en  Lyonnais  depuis  le  debut  du  xme  siecle  seulement.     Au  xiie  siecle, 
elles  sont  exceptionnelles  :   C.  des  fecouges,  N°  5  (1139) ;  mais  cette  charte  ne 
nous  est  parvenue  que  par  un  vidimus  du  xive  siecle. 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  187 

dotali  aliqua  servitus  imponatur. x  Ces  clauses  sont  inse"r£es 
re"gulierement  et  sans  discernement  dans  tous  les  actes  ou  des 
femmes  interviennent,  meme  s'il  s'agit  de  femmes  non  marines  ou 
veuves.2 

Peu  a  peu,  cependant,  I'id^e  d'une  veritable  protection  de  la 
dot  se  d£gage ;  et  cette  protection  deviendra  de  plus  en  plus 
necessaire,  au  fur  et  a  mesure  que  s'att^nuera  1'ancienne  garantie 
resultant  de  la  laudatio  des  proches  parents.  Et  il  est  meme  tres 
remarquable  que  cette  idee  nouvelle  va  pe"netrer  en  de"pit  des 
renonciations  et  des  cauteles.  Meme  dans  les  actes  ou  les  femmes 
de"clareront  renoncer  au  be"ne"fice  de  la  loi  Julia,  Pidee  d'inaliena- 
bilit£  dotale  triomphera ;  en  de"pit  de  leur  renonciation,  les  femmes 
se  pr£occuperont  de  garantir  leur  dot.  Tant  il  est  vrai  qu'il  y  a 
deux  romanisations  distinctes :  celle  des  formes,  la  plus  connue  et 
la  plus  facile  a  e"tudier ;  celle  du  fond  du  droit,  plus  lente,  parfois 
moins  complete,  mais  dont  les  resultats,  une  fois  acquis,  seront 
infiniment  plus  solides.3 

Mais,  au  XHP  siecle,  au  moins  dans  la  region  lyonnaise,4  ce 
n'est  point  l'inalienabilit£  absolue  du  droit  romain  qui  s'introduit. 
La  dot  reste  alienable,  a  condition  que  le  mari  fournisse  a  sa  femme 

1  C.  lyonnais,  ii.  N°  546  (1258):  «  I.  R.  miles  et  domina  A.  uxor  ejus 
.   .  .  recipiunt   in  francum  feudum  .   .   .   quicquid  juris  dictus  miles  nomine 
dicte  domine  uxoris  sue  et  ipsa  habent.  .  .  .  Renunciantes  .  .  .  exception!  .  .  . 
dotis  et  Velleiani  privilegio,  et  juri  prohibenti  ne  super  re  dotali  aliqua  servitus 
imponatur. » 

2  C.  lyonnais,  ii.  N°  535  (1256) :  Jaquette  de  Vaux,  non  mariee,  reprenant 
des  biens  en  fief  du  chapitre  de  Saint-Paul,  renonce  au  «  privilegium  dotis  et 
ypothece  ». 

3  Peut-etre   trouvons-nous,  dans   un   litige  survenu   en    1229,  1'une   des 
premieres  manifestations  de   Pinalienabilite  dotale   (C.  lyonnais,  i.   N°  257). 
Aymon  d'Escullon,  avec  le  concours  de  son  fils,  vend  a  1'eglise  Saint-Just  de 
Lyon  un  bien  appartenant  a  sa  femme.      Puis  il  veut  reprendre  le  bien  vendu, 
et    son    beau-frere   soutient   cette    reclamation :    «  Duranz  Gaudemars,  cujus 
sororem  idem  Aymo  habuerat  in  uxorem,  de  cujus  dote  idem  Duranz  dicebat 
res    predictas   fuisse.  ...»    Les    reclamants    renoncent    cependant  a  leurs 
preventions,    moyennant    12    livres    viennoises.       Toutefois    Pacte    n'indique 
nullement  que  la  base  de  ces  reclamations  soit   le  caractere  dotal   du   bien 
vendu  ;  et,  dans  les  renonciations  qui  terminent  cette  transaction,  il  n'est  fait 
aucune  allusion  a  la  dotalite. 

4  Les  documents  imprimes  relatifs  aux  autres  regions  que  nous  etudions, 
et  en  particulier  a  la  Provence,  sont  trop  peu  nombreux  pour  nous  permettre 
de  connaitre  1'extension  territoriale  du  systeme  que  nous  presentent  les  textes 
lyonnais. 


1 88  jR.  Caillemer  [ix 

une  recompensatio,  un  excambium,  en  lui  ce"dant  des  immeubles  ou 
des  droits  immobiliers ;  au  besoin,  il  devra  acheter  des  immeubles 
pour  les  donner  a  sa  femme  en  echange  du  bien  dotal  alie'ne'.  Le 
principe  est  pose  tres  nettement  dans  un  acte  lyonnais  de  1236: 
Res  dotales  vendi  vel  distrahi  a  maritis  non  possunt,  sine  recom- 
pensatione  sufficienti  facta  uxoribus.1 

Dans  les  premieres  annees  du  Xlir  siecle,  ce  systeme  nouveau 
n'est  pas  encore  constitue,  et  la  dot  semble  encore  pleinement 
alienable.2  Vers  1200,  B.  d'Andilly,  faisant  son  testament,  legue  a 
sa  femme  divers  immeubles,  pour  lui  tenir  lieu  des  biens  dotaux 
vendus  ou  engages.3  Mais  il  semble  bien  qu'il  n'y  ait  encore  la 
qu'un  scrupule  du  mari,  et  non  pas  une  obligation  stricte  ;  peut-etre 
aussi  la  femme  n'avait-elle  pas  consenti  a  1'alienation. 

Mais,  a  partir  de  Tan  1220,  la  doctrine  se  fait  plus  precise  et 
plus  exigeante.  Desormais  le  remploi  doit  etre  deja  effectue  et 
accept^  par  la  femme,  au  moment  ou  l'ali£nation  du  bien  dotal 
devient  definitive.  Dans  quelques  documents,  la  femme  se  contente 
de  declarer  qu'elle  a  regu  une  recompensatio  suffisante ; 4  mais 
d'ordinaire,  dans  1'acte  d'alienation  du  bien  dotal,  les  biens  fournis 
en  remploi  par  le  mari  sont  indiques  avec  precision.  Peu  importe 
d'ailleurs  le  mode  d'alienation  du  bien  dotal,  qu'il  s'agisse  d'une  vente,5 

1  C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  305.  2  V.  les  actes  cites  plus  haut. 

3  C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  80  :  «  Uxori  sue,  pro  terra  sua  quam  vendiderat,  et  pro 
quadem  curte  sua  quod  invadiaverat,  dimisit,   pro  velle  suo    facere,   curtem 
.   .   .   et  vineam  .  .   .  et  terram  .  .  .  et  gageriam. » 

4  Bibl.  Dumbensis,  ii.  Suppl.  N°  74  (1228) :  «  Confessa  est  insuper  comi- 
tissa    se  pro    predicto    castro,   quod    ad   ipsam   ratione   successionis   et  jure 
hereditario  pertinebat,  a  domino  et  marito  suo  Johanne  prefato  comite  per- 
mutadonem   sufficientem   et   ydoneam    recepisse ;    et   supradicta    omnia    rata 
habuit  et  sponte  in  manu  nostra  concessit.  »     Gr.   Cart.  d^Ainay,  ii.  p.  181 
(1263):  «Et  quoniam  dicte  res  vendite  erant  de  dote  dicte  Guigone,  ut  ipsa 
asserit,    ipsa  confitetur  se  habuisse   et   recepisse   a   dicto    marito   bonum  et 
legitimum  escambium  pro  ipsis  rebus  de  dote  sua,  ut  asserit,  existentibus,  de 
quo  ipsa  se  tenet  integre  pro  pagata.  » 

5  C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  256  (1229):   «  Cum  autem  hec  essent  de  maritagio 
predicte  Guicharde,  facta  sibi  recompensatione  ab  Umberto  marito  suo  de  eo 
quod  apud  Chal  habebat,  ambo  laudaverunt  predictum  curtile.  »    N°  26 1  (i  230): 
vente  de  3  solidi  debitales  aux  Templiers  de  Laumusse  :  « Et  cum  dicti  tres 
solidi  debitales  nominate  Dannon  fuissent  a  matre  sua  legati,  propter  quod  ad 
dotem  suam  videbantur  pertinere  vel  dotis  privilegio  fungi,  ne  super  hoc  dicti 

fratres  vel  alius pro  ipsis possent  in posterum  molestari,  prenominatus  Willelmus, 
uxori  sue  recompensationem  faciens,  tres  solidos  debitales  eidem  assignavit 
in  appendiciis  .  .  .,  propter  quod  eadem  dictis  tribus  solidis  renunciavit. » 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  189 

d'une    donation,    ou    encore    d'une    transaction.1      A    en    croire 


N°  305  (1236),  acte  cite*  plus  haut :  «  Quum  igitur  res  dotales  vendi  vel  distrahi 
a  maritis  non  possunt  sine  recompensatione  sufficient!  facta  uxoribus,  dictus  G. 
in  sufficientem  recompensationem  dedit  in  perpetuum  dicte  Agneti  uxori  sue  et 
heredibus  ejus  clausum.  ...»  Entre  autres  elements  de  la  recompensatio 
figure  la  renonciation  du  mari  et  de  son  frere  a  une  obligation  de  100  livres 
grevant  a  leur  profit  les  biens  dotaux.  V.  encore  le  N°  437  (1249)  :  «  In  con- 
cambium  vero  et  permutationem  rerum  venditarum  dotalium  dicte  Petronille, 
assignat  et  concedit  dictus  Jarento  miles  prefate  Petronille  uxori  ejusdem  .  .  ., 
de  quibus  rebus  sibi  nomine  dicte  concambii  et  permutationis  assignatis  dicta 
Petronilla  se  tenet  et  tenuit  coram  nobis  integre  pro  pagata. »  T.  ii.  N°  522 
(1255):  vente  de  bien  dotal  par  le  pere  du  mari :  «  que  res  vendite  ad  Beatricem, 
filiam  quondam  dicti  Hugonis,  nunc  uxorem  Thomassini  filii  dicte  Thome  mi- 
litis  jure  hereditario  pertinebant. »  Les  jeunes  epoux,/«^//  puberes,  approuvent. 
« Dictus  vero  Thomas  in  recompensationem  et  escambium  dictarum  rerum 
venditarum  reddit,  tradit  et  assignat  et  concedit  dicte  Beatrici  curtile.  .  .  . 
De  qua  recompensatione  et  escambio  dicta  Beatrix  et  dictus  Thomassinus  de 
mandate  dicti  Thome  se  tenent  pro  pagatis  ;  asserentes  per  juramentum  quod 
propter  hoc  eorum  condicio  non  est  in  aliquo  pejorata,  immo  quod  melior  est 
effecta. »  N°  555  (1259):  «  Et  quoniam  dicte  res  erant  .  .  .  de  dote  dicte 
Ysabelle,  dictus  Stephanus  (le  vendeur)  maritus  suus  reddidit  ei  .  .  .  in 
escambium  et  recompensationem  ipsarum  rerum  quicquid  idem  Stephanus  habet 
in  parrochiis  .  .  .  ;  de  quo  escambio  et  recompensatione  dicta  Ysabella  se 
tenet  per  juramentum  pro  pagata  ;  asserens  per  idem  juramentum  quod  propter 
hoc  dotis  sue  conditio  melior  est  effecta. » 

On  pourrait  relever  encore,  dans  les  autres  recueils  lyonnais,  au  xnie  sjecle, 
de  nombreux  exemples  de  ces  alienations  de  biens  dotaux,  moyennant  remploi 
en  biens  du  mari.  Gr.  C.  d'Ainay,  ii.  N°  xi  (1279) :  *  Et  cum  dicte  res  vendite 
essent  de  dote  dicte  domine  Margarite,  idem  miles  in  recompensationem  et 
escambium  .  .  .  reddit  et  assignat  eidem  domine  res  que  secuntur.  ...»  C 
des  francs-fiefs  du  b'orez,  N°  41  (1257):  vente  de  5  sous  de  rente  et  du  haut 
domaine  d'une  vigne  :  «  Et  quia  predict!  quinque  solidi  forcium  novorum  et 
dominium  ad  dictam  Aalis  pertinent  racione  dotis,  dictus  Petrus  eidem  volenti 
et  ex  certa  scientia  recipient!  reddit  et  assignat  in  recompensacionem  predictorum 
tres  jornalatas  vinee  .  .  . ;  et  de  istis  rebus  habitis  et  receptis  dicta  Aalis, 
cerciorata  de  jure  et  de  facto,  pro  supradictis  venditis  dicto  capellano,  se  tenet 
integre,  ut  asserit,  pro  pagata. » 

II  arrive  que  le  mari,  au  lieu  de  donner  a  sa  femme  la  propriete  meme  de 
ses  immeubles,  en  remploi,  lui  assigne  une  rente  sur  ses  immeubles.  C. 
lyonnais,  i.  N°  173  (1221):  vente  d'un  courtil  et  de  vignes  :  « Et  ob  recon- 
pensacionem  rei  vendite,  Johannes  Dumbeis  dedit  et  concessit  uxori  sue  Proetan 
x  libras  et  x  solidos  super  domum  quam  habet  apud  Ansam,  et  inde  pacem 
ipse  et  filii  sui  eidem  Proetan  in  perpetuum  juraverunt. »  Ce  texte  est  1'un 
des  plus  anciens  ou  Ton  voie  fonctionner  le  systeme  de  la  recompen- 
satio. 

1  La  plupart  des  documents  que  nous  venons  de  citer  concernent  la  vente 
d'un  bien  dotal.  Mais  le  meme  systeme  d'alienabilite  moyennant  remploi  se 
rencontre  aussi  dans  des  donations,  ou  dans  des  transactions  portant  sur  la  dot. 


i  go  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

certains  documents,  il  faut  meme  que  le  bien  donne"  en  recompen- 
satio  ait  une  valeur  nettement  supe"rieure  a  celle  du  bien  dotal 
alie"ne".  On  exige,  par  exemple,  que  les  biens  donnas  en  remploi 
rapportent  60  sous  de  rente,  si  les  biens  dotaux  ali£ne"s  valaient  50 
livres,  ce  qui  fait  un  revenu  de  6  %.J  Ajoutons  enfin  que  cet  usage 
de  1'ali^nation  moyennant  remploi  a  sa  repercussion  sur  la  liste  des 
renonciations  :  Ton  voit  apparaitre,  a  cote  de  la  renonciation  a  la  loi 
Julia  ou  au  Velle"ien,  la  renonciation  exceptioni  legitime  remunera- 
tionis  non  habile? 

D'ordinaire,  les  deux  operations,  vente  du  bien  dotal  et  recom- 
pensatio,  sont  reunies  dans  le  meme  acte,  mais  logiquement  elles 
restent  distinctes,  et  la  recompensatio,  \excambium  doit  meme 
theoriquement  pr£ceder  1'alienation.  Un  document  lyonnais  de 
1 244  est  particulierement  curieux  a  cet  e"gard.  Au  lieu  de  vendre 
directement  le  bien  dotal  a  l'acque"reur,  sauf  a  assigner  a  sa  femme 
une  recompensatio,  le  mari  commence  par  conclure  avec  sa  femme 
un  echange.  Le  mari  et  son  frere  cedent  a  la  femme  un  immeuble 
qui  leur  appartient,  en  ^change  de  I'immeuble  dotal ;  ce  premier 
acte  est  fait  avec  le  consentement  des  enfants  d'un  premier  lit  de 
cette  femme,  et  celle-ci  declare  que  1'echange  est  avantageux 
pour  elle.  Puis  le  mari  et  son  frere,  ayant  ainsi  acquis  la  libre 
disposition  du  bien  dotal,  le  vendent  a  une  Maison  de  1'Ordre  de 
Malte.3 


Gr.  C.  tfAinay,  ii.  N°  xlix.  p.  89  (1227)  :  proces  relatif  a  un  moulin,  «  que  ad 
se  pertinere  dicebat  (Radulphus)  ratione  Aalis  uxoris  sue. »  Une  transaction 
intervient ;  les  epoux  renoncent  a  leurs  droits  sur  le  moulin,  moyennant  1 2 
livres  viennoises :  «  Quia  vero  jus  prefate  querele  ad  uxorem  dicti  Radulphi 
militis  pertinebat,  ut  ipsi  dicebant,  reddidit  ei  maritus  ejus  ex  causa  permuta- 
tionis  quicquid  habebat  apud  .  .  .,  quam  permutationem  ipsa  domina  gratam 
habuit  et  recepit. » 

1  C.    des  francs -fiefs   du   Forez,   N°   27   (1246),  p.   121  :    Guigues    de 
Montagny  et   sa  femme  vendent,  pour   50  livres,  des   droits   immobiliers  a 
Feurs  :  «  Et  qum  res  superius  nominate  erant  de  dote  vel  de  patrimonio  dicte 
Agnetis,  dictus  Guigo  dedit  et  tradidit  ei,  in  recompensationem  earumdem, 
quicquid    habebat.   .  .  .   Et,   si  hec   non  valerent   sexaginta  solidos  fortium 
censuales,  dictus  Guigo  debet  eos  dicte  Agneti  perficere  de  redditibus  suis 
quos  habet  in  mandamento   de  Fontaneis ;  ut  de  eis  faciat  quicquid  facere 
poterat  de  rebus  que  erant  de  dote  vel  de  patrimonio  ejus.» 

2  Gr.  C.  d'Ainay,  ii.  N°  vii.  (1268):  «  exceptioni  legitime  remunerationis 
non  habite»;  N°  xi.  (1279):  « exceptioni  legitimi  escambii  non  habiti.»     C. 
lyonnais,  ii.  N°  522  (1255)  :  «  exceptioni  legitime  remunerationis  non  habite. » 

3  C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  393  (1244)  :  «...  Uxor  domini  Willermi  de  Pavenens, 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  191 

Ainsi,  au  XIIIs  siecle,  dans  la  region  lyonnaise,  la  dot,  e"chappe 
encore  a  1'application  rigoureuse  des  regies  romaines  relatives  a 
Pinalie'nabilite"  dotale,  et  est  soumise  a  un  regime  en  somme  assez 
different  du  systeme  romain.  La  regie  romaine  d'inalie"nabilit£ 
absolue  ne  triomphera  que  plus  tard.1 

Cette  inalienability  relative  ne  s'est  appliquee  tout  d'abord, 
semble-t-il,  qu'aux  immeubles  dotaux  de  la  femme.  Mais,  dans 
le  courant  du  Xlir  siecle,  un  systeme  de  protection  analogue, 
quoique  moins  net  et  moins  e"nergique,  a  e"te  e"tendu  aux  immeubles 
du  mari,  dans  la  mesure  ou  la  dot  mobiliere  de  la  femme  e"tait 
assignee  sur  ces  immeubles,  et  ou  ils  en  garantissaient  la  restitution. 

Au  de"but  du  Xllle  siecle,  aucune  protection  spe"ciale  de  la  dot 
mobiliere  de  la  femme  n'apparait  encore.  Quand  le  mari  vend  un 
de  ses  biens  propres,  la  femme  renonce  purement  et  simplement  a 
tous  les  droits  qu'elle  peut  exercer  sur  ce  bien  a  raison  de  sa  dot.2 
L'hypotheque  que  le  droit  romain  lui  accordait  sur  les  immeubles 
de  son  mari  ne  semble  guere  avoir  eu  d'application  pratique :  on  la 
mentionne  rarement,  et  seulement  pour  y  renoncer.3  II  arrive 

dicta  Boicharda,  laudantibus  et  consentientibus  .  .  .  liberis  dicte  domine 
Boicharde,  quos  ab  alio  marito  suscepit,  permutavit  dicto  W.  de  Pavenens 
marito  suo  et  Jocerando  de  Pavenens  militi,  fratribus  .  .  .  mansum  .  .  ., 
quern  dederat  dicto  Willermo  in  dotem  cum  earn  accepit  in  uxorem,  cum 
manso  .  .  .  et  cum  his  que  habebant  vel  possidebant  dicti  milites  apud 
Granges  .  .  .  ;  et  juravit  dicta  domina  super  sancta  Dei  evangel ia  dictam 
permutationem  sibi  utilem  esse,  et  se  imperpetuum  per  se  vel  per  alium  contra 
non  venturam.  —  Deinde  dicti  W.  et  Jocerandus  .  .  .  dictum  mansum  .  .  ., 
quern  ex  dicta  permutatione  habuerunt,  vendiderunt  ...» 

1  Guy  Pape  ne  semble  plus  connaitre  Palienabilite  de  la  dot  moyennant  un 
remploi.      La  seule  question  qu'il  se  pose  est  la  fameuse  question  de  savoir  si 
un  serment  de  la  femme  peut  valider  Palienation  de  la  dot. — Qu.  1 90  ;  cf. 
Expilly,   Arrtts,   ch.    123.  —  On   sait  que   plus   tard,  le    20   avril   1664,   une 
ordonnance   royale,   rendue  a  la   requete  du   prevot   des   marchands  et  des 
echevins  de  Lyon,  est  venue  abroger  Pinalienabilite  de  la  dot  dans  le  Lyonnais, 
le  Maconnais,  le  Forez  et  le  Beaujolais.     Cf.  Lefebvre,  article  precite,  p.  428 
et  s. 

2  V.  C.  lyonnais,  i.  N°  236  (1228),  cite  plus  haut,  et  un  grand  nombre 
d'actes  du  meme  recueil. 

3  V.,  p.  ex.,  Bibl.  Dumb.  ii.  Suppl.  N°  73  (1228),  a  la  suite  d'une  obliga- 
tion d'immeubles  :  «  Blancha  quoque,  dicti  domicelli  uxor,  dictam  obligationem 
expresse  laudavit,  .   .  .  renuncians  cum  juramento  ypothece  dotis  generali  vel 
special!,  tacite  vel  expresse,  in  rebus  supradictis,  et  omni  juri  et  auxilio  legum 
vel  canonum  sibi  competent!  vel  competituro. »     N°  in   (1253),  a  la  suite 
d'une  receptio  feudi  faite  par  un  mari  avec  la  laudatio  de  sa  femme  :  «  Re- 
nunciantes  .   .   .  exception!  .  .   .  dotis  et  ypothece  tacite  et  expresse  privilegio, 
et  Velleiani  privilegio,  legi  Julie  de  fundo  dotali  non  alienando. » 


192  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

meme  que  la  femme  du  vendeur  cede  expressdment  a  Pacheteur  les 
sommes  dotales  que  1'immeuble  vendu  garantissait.1 

Cependant  son  desinteressement  n'est  pas  toujours  aussi  complet. 
II  arrive  que  la  femme,  apportant  ainsi  sa  laudatio  a  1'alienation  de 
I'immeuble  du  mari,  se  fasse  payer  par  1'acquereur  cette  laudatio 
et  cette  renonciation  a  ses  droits  e"ventuels 2 ;  ou  bien  encore  elle  se 
fait  donner  par  l'acque"reur  les  «drouillesi>,  les  prestations  accessoires 
qu'il  est  d'usage  de  joindre  au  prix  de  vente.3  Quelquefois  enfin, 
la  femme  revolt,  lors  de  1'alienation,  une  somme  d'argent  plus  con- 
siderable encore  :  elle  se  fait  remettre  par  son  mari,  a  concurrence 
du  montant  de  sa  dot,  le  prix  du  bien  vendu.f  Mais  ces  precedes, 

1  C.  lyonnais,   i.   N°  99   (1206):    « Supradicta  vero  domina  in  omnibus 
possessionibus  supradictis  habet  1  Irbras  de  dote,  quas  predicte  domui  Templi 
dedit  et  concessit. »     N°  163  :  meme  acte  refait  en  1219. 

2  C.  lyonnais,  ii.  N°  557  (1259):  transaction  entre  Albert  de  La  Tour  et 
Pabbe  d'Ambronay  au  sujet  de  leurs  droits  a  Lagnieu  ;  Pabbe  remet,  pro  bono 
pacts,   1 1    1.   vienn.  a  Albert   et   30  sous  a  son  epouse :   «  Nos  vero  Alasia, 
domina    de    Turre,    receptis    dictis    xxx    solidis  pro    laudibus,   laudamus    et 
approbamus  compositionem  predictam. » 

3  C.  lyonnais,  ii.  N°  573  (1261)  :  vente  par  Bertrand  de  Tassin  a  1'eglise 
de    Lyon :    «  Hanc  autem  venditionem   et   precii    solutionem   domina  Elyoz, 
uxor  dicti  militis  .   .  .  sponte  sua  laudat,  approbat,  ratificat  et  acceptat,  et 
omne  jus  et  ypothecam  .  .   .  quitat.   .  .   .   Confitetur  etiam  ipsa  domina  se 
habuisse  a  dictis  emptoribus  sex  solidos  Viennensium  pro  druelliis. »     V.  Du 
Cange,  vis  druaylia,  drueleria,  droillia,  drolia  et  draulia  ;  Collet,  Explication 
.  .   .  des  statuts  .  .   .  de  Bresse,  art.    83.       Chartes  de   Cluny,  vi.   N°47ii 
(1237)  :  «  pro  laudationibus  seu  drueleriis, »  acte  deja  signale  par  Du  Cange. 

4  Cart,  lyonnais,  i.  N°  193  (1223)  :  vente  par  Guillaume  Bernard  a  1'eglise 
de  Lyon  :  «  De  precio  quoque  supradicto  confessus  est  coram  nobis  predictus 
Willelmus  sibi  plene  satisfactum  fuisse,  et  illud  totum  Willelme  uxori  sue  pro 
dote  sua  solvit ;  unde  propter  hoc  tarn  dictus  Willelmus  quam  Willelma  uxor 
ejus  omni  juri  sibi  in  prefatis  rebus  aliquando  competenti  vel  competituro  cum 
juramento    renuntiarunt.  »     N°  271    (1231):    Berard  de  Pizay  et  sa  femme 
Guillelmine,  ne  pouvant  payer  leurs  dettes,  vendent  a  Amedee  de  Miribel, 
frere  de  Berard,  tous  leurs  immeubles  situes  a  Soucieu,  moyennant  25   livres 
payees  immediatement  et  un  complement  a  percevoir  sur  les  revenus  d' Amedee 
a   Ornacieu,  jusqu'a    ce    que  les   vendeurs   aient  regu   en   tout    7500   sous: 
«  Dictum  autem  rerum  venditarum  precium  et  dictos  redditus  .  .  .    pro  precio 
assignatos  dictus  Berardus  assignavit  dicte  Willelme  uxori  sue  pro  dote  sua  ; 
quam  assignationem  ipsa  gratam  habuit  et  acceptam,  confitens  et  recognoscens 
dictas  res  sibi  assignatas  plus  valere  quam  res  que  in  dotem  fuerant  sibi  date. 
Preterea    domina    Willelma  .  .  .  renuntians  .  .   .  juri    ypothecarum    quod 
habebat  generaliter  vel  specialiter  in  rebus  et  possessionibus  omnibus  supra- 
nominatis.   .   .  .   Sub  eodem  quoque  juramento  renuntiavit  sepedicta  Willelma 
litteris,    si    quas    habebat,    quod   dicte    res    sibi    essent   pro   dote   specialiter 
assignate  ;  et  promisit  se  eis  decetero  non  usuram. »    N°  274  (1232):   Etienne 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  193 

aboutissant  a  remettre  entre  les  mains  de  la  femme,  au  cours  du 
manage,  des  sommes  d'argent  plus  ou  moins  importantes,  sont 
evidemment  tres  imparfaits.  Une  telle  restitution  anticipe"e  de  la 
dot  n'est  guere  admissible. 

Aussi,  depuis  1240  environ,  apparait  un  autre  systeme,  plus 
conforme  aux  regies  normales  du  regime  matrimonial,  plus  voisin 
des  regies  qui  protegent  la  dot  immobiliere.  L'alie"nation  de 
1'immeuble  garantissant  la  dot  n'est  valable  que  si  la  femme  declare 
formellement,  au  besoin  sous  la  foi  du  serment,  que  la  restitution 
de  sa  dot  est  assuree  au  moyen  d'autres  biens  du  mari,  que  de 
nouveaux  immeubles  ont  £te"  affecte"s  a  la  garantie  de  la  dot,  en 
recompensatio  des  immeubles  aliened,1  ou  du  moins  que  son  mari 
possede  d'autres  biens  «  apparents  »,  suffisants  a  assurer  la  restitution 
de  sa  dot.2  Toutefois  il  convient  de  noter  que  1'acte  n'indique 

Charreton  et  son  epouse  vendent  une  maison  pour  28  livres.  «  Et  ipsa 
Petronilla  expresse  renunciavit  sub  eodem  juramento  omni  juri  ypothecarum 
et  omni  alii  juri  quod  ratione  maritagii  vel  qualibet  alia  ratione  posset  ei 
competere  in  domo  supradicta  vel  prodesse  quoquomodo.  Confessa  fuit 
etiam  quod  de  pecunia  memorata  satisfactum  ei  fuit  in  xxilll  libris  forcium, 
quas  maritus  ipsius  confessus  fuerat  ab  eadem  se  in  dotem  recepisse. » 

1  BibL  Dtimbensis,  ii.  Suppl.,  N°  91  (1236)  :  «  Recognoscens  dicta  Maria 
sibi  satisfactum   de  dote   sua,   et   sibi  fuisse  cautum  alibi  de  eadem  » :    ces 
derniers  mots  semblent  indiquer  que  la  dot  n'a  pas  ete  restituee,  mais  a  etc 
assignee  sur  de  nouveaux  biens.  —  C.  de  Saint-Sauveur  en  Rue,  N°  civ.  (1242)  : 
«  Hec    omnia    facta    sunt    praesente    et    consentiente    Luca    uxore    mea,    et 
renuntiante  per  juramentum  privilegio  in  hoc  sibi  competent!  ratione  rei  dotalis, 
recognoscente  et  confitente  cautum  sibi  a  me  alibi  de  dote  sua.  » — Grand  Cart. 
(fAinay,  i.   N°  49  (1256):  «  Hanc  autem  venditionem  .  .  .   domina  Sibilla 
mater  dicti  Petri  et  Eliouz  uxor  sua  .   .  .   laudant  .   .   .,  et,  si  forte  eis  vel 
alter!  ipsarum  predicta  fuerunt  pro  dote  vel  dotalicio  aut  alia  causa  obligata 
tacite  vel  expresse,  obligationem  et  omne  jus,  quod  in  predictis  habent,  quittant 
dicto   priori   .    .    .,  asserentes   se   recepisse  a  dicto   P.   alias  possessiones  in 
recompensationem   plus   valentes,  in   quibus   condicio  sua  melioratur,  et  non 
modicum  aumentatur;  et  hoc  ita  esse  .  .   .  juraverunt.  » — V.  aussi  C.  de  Saint- 
Sauveur  en  Rue,   N°  cxii.   (1251):     engagement   realise  par  Hugue   Falco, 
sa  femme,  son  fils  et  sa  belle  -  fille  :    «  Et  nos   praedictae  Aalis  et   Beatrix 
renuntiamus    praestitis   juramentis    .    .    .    omni    juri    et    privilegiis    dotis    et 
donationis   propter  nuptias,  et   tacitis  sive  expressis   hipothecis   pro  dotibus 
nostris,  confitentes  alibi  in  terra  dicti  militis  et  filii   sui   de  dotibus  nostris 
sufficienter  cautum  esse. » 

2  C.  lyonnais,  N°  386  (1244) :  a  la  suite  d'une  vente  de  rentes  :  «confessa 
est  etiam   dicta  nobilis  (femme  du  vendeur)  sub  prestito  sacramento,  quod 
alias  de  bonis  dicti  B.  mariti  sui  de  dote  sua  potest  sibi  consuli  competenter. » 

—  N°  426(1247)  :  «  Hanc  autem  venditionem  et  precii  solutionem  laudavit  et 
approbavit  et  ratam  habuit  domina  Guibors,  uxor  dicti  Hugonis,  promittens 

O 


194  -#•  Caillemer  [ix 

jamais  avec  precision  quels  sont  les  nouveaux  biens  du  mari  ainsi 
affectes  a  la  garantie  de  la  dot ;  et,  des  lors,  ce  systeme  de 
recompensatio  ne  fonctionne  pas  ici  avec  la  meme  nettete"  et  la 
meme  rigueur  que  lorsqu'il  s'applique  aux  alienations  de  la  dot 
immobiliere. 

Ainsi,  soit  en  ce  qui  concerne  Pinalie'nabilite'  de  la  dot 
immobiliere,  soit  en  ce  qui  touche  la  garantie  de  la  dot  mobiliere, 
nous  voyons  apparaitre  au  Xllle  siecle,  non  pas  les  pures  ide"es 
romaines,  mais  des  systemes  originaux  de  protection  des  int£rets 
de  la  femme :  ni  1'inalienabilite"  absolue,  ni  la  garantie  resultant  de 
Phypotheque  de  la  femme  sur  les  biens  du  mari  n'ont  pene'tre'  a 
cette  epoque  dans  la  pratique. 

Quant  aux  paraphernaux,  la  pratique  les  a  longtemps  ignores. 
Les  chartes  parlent  bien  des  bona  dotalia  et  parafernalia,  mais  sans 
que  les  contractants  sachent  ce  que  ce  dernier  mot  signifie.  Une 
charte  provengale,  au  de"but  du  Xllle  siecle,  englobe  meme  les  para- 
phernaux dans  l'inalie"nabilite  dotale.1  L'ide"e  de  biens  reserves  a  la 
femme,  laiss^s  a  son  administration  et  a  sa  jouissance,  etait  trop 
contraire  aux  anciennes  conceptions  medievales  pour  pouvoir 
pen£trer  dans  la  pratique.2 

per  sacramentum  se  contra  aliquatenus  non  venturam  de  jure  vel  de  facto,  .  .  . 
confitens  et  asserens  sub  eodem  juramento  quod  ob  hanc  alienationem  seu 
venditionem  sue  dotis  conditio  deterior  non  fiebat,  cum  vir  suus  plura  alia 
bona  habeat,  ob  quorum  existentiam,  prout  ipsa  asserebat,  dos  sua  sibi  large 
potest  salva  consistere  et  manere. » 

Grand  Cart.  tfAinay,  ii.  p.  191,  Suppl.,  N°  20  (1272):  «  predicta  Amfelisia, 
uxore  dicti  domini  Guichardi,  per  juramentum  asserente  sibi  posse  satis 
consuli  alibi  de  dote  sua  super  certis  rebus  et  possessionibus  apparentibus 
mariti  supradicti. » 

1  C.  de  S.    Victor  de  Marseille,  ii.   N°  909  (1229):    Barrale  des  Baux, 
faisant  avec  le   consentement  de  son   mari  et  de  ses  enfants  une  donation 
immobiliere  a  Saint-Victor,  renonce  :  « specialiter  juribus  que  decernunt  res 
dotales  seu  parafernales  alienari  non  posse. » 

2  La  jurisprudence  de  la  France  du  Midi  declarera  que,  s'il  n'y  a  pas  con- 
stitution de  dot  prefixe,  ou  s'il  n'y  a  pas  du  tout  de  contrat  de  mariage,  tous 
les  biens  de  la  femme  sont  tenus  pour  dotaux :  Roussilhe,  Traitt  de  la  Dot,  i. 
p.  165  et  s.     Les  paraphernaux  sont  une  anomalie,  une  institution  etrangere 
et  que  Ton  tend  a  restreindre.      De  plus,  cette  meme  jurisprudence  tend  a 
donner  au  mari  Padministration  et  la  jouissance  des  paraphernaux.     V.  Guy 
Pape,  qu.  468  :  il  distingue  trois  especes  de  biens  de  la  femme,  i°,  la  dot; 
2°,  les  paraphernaux,  dont  il  donne  la  definition  suivante  :  «  Bona  parapher- 
nalia sunt  ilia  quae  ipsa  uxor,  tempore  quo  inducitur  in  domum  mariti,  secum 
defert,  et  in  quibus  administrationem  concedit  marito  tacite  vel  expresse »  ; 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  195 

B.  Gains  de  survie 

Comme  dans  les  regions  plus  septentrionales,  nous  rencontrons 
dans  nos  pays,  au  haut  moyen  age,  le  douaire.  Tantot  le  mari,  au 
moment  du  manage,  attribue  a  la  femme  certains  biens  de"termine"s 
(sponsalicium\  tantot  il  lui  donne  une  quote-part  de  tous  ses  biens 
(dotalicium  ;  mais  cette  terminologie  n'est  pas  tres  ferme) :  souvent, 
dans  un  meme  acte,  ces  deux  genres  de  libe"ralite  sont  re'unis.1  Ce 
douaire  appartient  en  proprie'te'  a  la  femme,  mais  on  releve  nette- 
ment  dans  nos  regions,  comme  dans  beaucoup  d'autres,  des  tendances 
a  re"server  le  douaire  aux  enfants  a  naitre  du  mariage,  et  aussi,  a 
deTaut  d'enfants,  a  stipuler  le  retour  du  douaire  aux  parents  du 
mari :  tendances  qui,  dans  d'autres  pays,  conduiront  au  douaire  des 
enfants  et  au  douaire  en  usufruit? 

A  partir  du  XIIP  siecle,  il  se  fait  un  changement  dans  les 
termes,  et  dans  le  fond  du  droit. 

L'ide"e  coutumiere  et  germanique  du  calcul  du  douaire  sur  la 
fortune  du  mari  va  faire  place  a  l'ide"e  d'un  gain  de  survie  propor- 
tionne"  a  la  dot :  ce  sera  V augment  de  dot  des  pays  meridionaux, 
largement  inspire  des  regies  romaines  relatives  a  la  donatio  propter 
nuptias.  Toutefois  l'e"galite"  entre  la  dot  et  la  donatio  propter  nuptias, 
qui  a  triomphe"  dans  quelques  coutumes  locales  du  Midi,  semble 
n'avoir  jamais  pe"ne"tre"  dans  la  region  qui  nous  occupe.  D'ailleurs 
1'augment  de  dot  n'a  pas  remplac£  des  la  fin  du  moyen  age  tous  les 
autres  gains  de  survie.  La  transformation  a  e"te  plus  complexe. 
Encore  aux  XIVe  et  XVe  siecles,  on  retrouve  le  mot  dotalicium.  Ce 
mot  a  pris,  il  est  vrai,  des  sens  varies.  Tantdt  il  s'agit,  comme 
dans  les  siecles  precedents,  d'un  douaire  veritable,  calcule  sur  la 

enfin  3°,  les  biens  qui  ne  sont  ni  dotaux,  ni  paraphernaux,  «  quae  mulier  habet 
omnino  separata  a  viro  et  in  suo  regimine  ac  dominio  reservata. » 

1  V.,  comme  exemple  tres  caracteristique  de  cette  institution,  le  douaire 
(in  sponsalitio  sive  in  dotalitio}  constitue  par  Guigue  le  Gras,  comte  d'Albon, 
en  1070,  au  profit  de  sa  fiancee,  Agnes  (Bull,  de  PAcad.  delphinale,  3e  Serie, 
t.  xx.  p.  369  et  s.) :  ce  douaire  comprend  une  serie  de  castra  determines,  avec 
leurs  mandements,  et  le  tiers  des  placita.     V.  aussi  Marion,  C.  de  Ptglise  de 
Grenoble,  A,  N°  21  (1023) ;  Ch.  de  Cluny,  Nos  7,  88,  105,  229,  439,  659,  686, 
687,  etc.  ;  C.  de  S.  Victor  de  Marseille,  Nos  65,  189,  704,  705.     Lemotj/^- 
salicium  se  retrouve  encore,  en  1257,  dans  le  C.  de  Saint-Sauveur  en  Rue, 
N°  cviii.     Cf.  Gavet,  Sponsalitium  et  Dotalitium  dans  les  chartes  de  Pabbaye 
de  Cluny  (Melanges  F.  Ciccaglione,  i.). 

2  V.  notre  etude  sur  les  origines  du  douaire  des  enfants  (Studi  in  onore  di 
Vittorio  Scialoja,  Prato,  1904). 


196  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

fortune  du  mari  ou  fix£  a  une  somme  determined.  En  1273,  le 
contrat  de  manage  entre  Anne,  heritiere  des  Dauphins  de  la  seconde 
race,  et  Humbert  de  La  Tour,  contient  un  dotalicium  et  doarium 
«  selon  les  usages  de  la  Bourgogne  » :  le  fianc£  attribue  a  sa  future 
Spouse,  outre  certains  biens  determines,  Pusufruit  de  la  moiti£  de 
tous  ses  biens.1  De  meme,  en  1347,  dans  un  projet  de  mariage 
entre  Humbert  II  et  Blanche,  sceur  du  comte  de  Savoie  Am£dee, 
Humbert  promet  a  sa  fiancee,  en  dotalicium^  une  rente  annuelle  de 
10,000  florins.  Mais  ce  dotalicium  doit  cesser  lorsque  la  dot  aura 
£te  restitute,  et,  pour  ce  cas,  on  stipule  un  augment  de  dot,  si  la 
femme  survit  et  s'il  n'y  a  pas  d'enfants  du  mariage  :  la  rente  annuelle 
fera  place  alors  a  un  capital  une  fois  paye.2 

Au  xve  siecle  encore,  Guy  Pape  connait  et  etudie  le  douaire, 
dotalicium  ou  doariumy  constitue  par  le  mari  au  profit  de  sa 
femme  pour  le  cas  de  survie  de  celle-ci ;  et,  suivant  sur  ce  point  la 
vieille  conception  medievale,  il  declare  que  la  femme,  bien  que 
n'ayant  sur  ce  douaire  qu'une  jouissance  viagere,  en  est  cependant 
vraiment  proprietaire,  et  qu'elle  doit  supporter  toutes  les  charges 
qui  pesent  sur  la  propriety  fonciere,  impots,  cens,  etc.3 

Dans  d'autres  textes  cependant,  le  mot  dotalicium  prend  des 

1  Valbonnais,  Hist,  de  Dauphin^  ii.  p.  1 1  et  s. 

2  Ibid.  ii.  p.  569  et  s.,  N°  cell.  :  «  Item  actum  est  quod  dictus  dominus 
Dalphinus  teneatur  dare  et  assignare  dictae  dominae  Blanchae  ratione  dotalitii 
10,000  flor.  annuales,  assignandos  in  castris  Visiliae,  etc.  .  .   .   et  quod  dicta 
castra  sibi  tradantur. »     Et  plus  loin  :  «  Item,  in  casu  ubi  restitutio  praedictae 
dotis  fuerit  plenarie  facta,  quod  tune  cesset  totaliter  dotalitium  supradictum.  » 
Si  Blanche,  devenue  veuve,  se  remarie,  le  douaire  s'eteindra  aussitot,  ou  bien 
il  faudra  imputer  les  produits  de  ce  douaire  sur  le  chiffre  de  la  dot  a  restituer. 
Si  Blanche  ne  se  remarie  pas,  et  reprend  cependant  sa  dot  par  fractions,  a 
chacun  des  termes  de  restitution  de  la  dot,  le  douaire  sera  reduit  de   1200 
florins.     V.  encore,  en  1369,  le  dotalicium  de  Beatrix  de  Chalon,  mentionne 
dans  le  testament  de  son  mari  Humbert  de  Villars,  et  qui  comprend  un  certain 
nombre  de  castra,  avec  leurs  mandements.     Bibl.  Dumbensis,  i.  p.  305. 

3  Guy  Pape,  Decisiones,  qu.  524-525  :    «  Si  dotalitium  seu  doarium  con- 
stituatur  sponsae  futurae  in  casu  quo  vir  praedecederet,  utrum  valeat  ?     Die 
quod  sic   ...    Et  ita  in  judicando  servatur  .  .   .  —  Sed   .  .   .    pone  quod 
maritus  assignat  uxori  doarium  in  vitam^  vel  aliquam  rem  ad  alimenta  aut  pro 
statu  suo  tenendo  sibi  donat  vel  legat,  nunquid  istis  casibus  censebitur  uxor 
proprietaria  ?  .   .  .  Et  per  hoc  dico  quod  mulier,  vita  sua  durante,  tenetur 
pro  talibus  rebus  solvere  collectas  quae  pro  ipsis  rebus  imponentur,  census  et 
alia  onera  ex  ipsis  bonis  debita,  cum  etiam  in  mulierem  talium  rerum  transeat 
dominium  .  .  .   Et  ita  de  consuetudine  etiam  servatur  in  hac  patria,  in  locis 
in  quibus  collectae  et  subsidia  Delphinalia  solvuntur. » 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  197 

significations  nouvelles,  inconnues  pendant  le  haut  moyen  age. 
Tantdt  le  mot  de'signe  une  assignation  d'immeubles  du  mari, 
destinee  a  garantir  a  la  femme  la  restitution  de  sa  dot  en  deniers  : 
assignatio  facta  mulieri  causa  dotis  assequrande^  Tantdt  enfin  le 
mot  dotalicium  de'signe  un  «  contre  -  douaire »,  un  droit  d'usufruit 
constitue  par  la  femme  ou  par  les  parents  de  la  femme  au  profit  du 
mari,  pour  le  cas  de  sa  survie.2 

Puis  apparait  un  gain  de  survie  appele  supravita,  qui  est 
mentionne"  dans  les  textes  lyonnais  depuis  le  xille  siecle,3  et  qui, 
plus  tard,  usite"  en  Maconnais,  en  Bresse,4  en  Dauphine,5  en  Provence,6 
consiste  en  une  donation  reciproque  d'une  somme  d'argent,  que  le 
survivant  prendra  dans  la  fortune  du  pre'de'cede.  Ordinairement, 
la  «  survie  »  de  la  femme  est  double  de  celle  du  mari. 

1  Telle  est  la  definition  du  dotalicium  donnee  au  cours  d'une  contestation 
entre  1'avocat  fiscal  et  le  procureur  general  du  Dauphin  et  le  seigneur  de 
Sassenage,  en   1420,  au  sujet  de  la  terre  de  Pont  en  Royans.      Cette  terre 
avait  ete  constitute  en  dotalicium  par  le  seigneur  de  Sassenage  au  profit  de 
son  epouse,  Alice  de  Chalon,  pour  garantir,  a  concurrence  de  10,000  florins, 
la  restitution  de   la  dot   de  celle-ci.      Les  gens   du   Dauphin  reclament,  sur 
cette  constitution  de  dotalicium,  le  paiement  des  lods  et  ventes  dus  en  cas 
d'alienation  immobiliere.     Le  seigneur  de  Sassenage  «  dixit  se  non  teneri,  quia 
tale  dotalicium,   sive  assignacio  facta  mulieri  causa   dotis  assequrande,  non 
transfert  dominium.  »     II  ajoute  que  la  coutume  dauphinoise  n'impose  pas  en 
pareil  cas  le  paiement  des  lods  et  ventes,  puisque  la  terre  doit  lui  revenir  des 
que   la  dot  aura  ete  restituee.       U.   Chevalier,   Choix  de  documents  inedits, 
p.  254  et  s. 

2  Guigue,  BibL  Hist,  du  Lyonnais,  p.  29  (1229):  Humbert  de  Beaujeu, 
apres  avoir  constitue  un  maritagium  a  sa  sceur,  Sibille,  fiancee  a  Renaud  de 
Bage,  ajoute  :  «  Ego  siquidem  H.,  de  voluntate  et  mandato  expresso  S.  sororis 
mee,  dicto  R.  contuli  in  dotalicium  medietatem  omnium  rerum  supradictarum, 
si  forte,  quod  absit,  earn  absque  libero  mori  contingeret,  quoad  vixerit  possi- 
dendam,  et  post  mortem  ipsius  ad  me  et  ad  meos  pleno  jure  revertetur. » 

3  C.  Lyonnais,  i.  N°  464  (1251) :  «  Hanc  autem  venditionem.  .  .  .  Aalys, 
uxor  dicti    Guigonis,   sponte   sua   laudat,  .  .  .  et   omnem  ypotecam  .  .   .  et 
omnes  actiones,  si  quas  habet  in  dictis  rebus  venditis  .  .   .  pro  dote  sua  aut 
supra-uita  .  .  .  quitat. » 

4  V.,  sur  les  donations  de  survie,  Ch.  Revel,  D  Usage  des  pays  de  Bresse, 
n.  ed.,  Bourg,  1729,  p.  253  :  «  Item,  lesdits  Epoux  et  Epouses  futurs  se  sont 
faits  les  donations  de  survie  suivantes  :     Sgavoir,  que  le  dit  Epoux  venant 
a  mourir  avant  ladite  Epouse,  ayant  enfans  ou  non,  ce  Mariage  consomme  ou 
non,  il  lui  donne  de  survie  100.      Et  au  meme  cas  de  predeces,  ladite  epouse 
donne  audit  epoux  50.  » 

5  Guy  Pape,  qu.  565. 

6  De    Cormis,    Consult,    i.    col.    1363.  —  En    Provence,    cette    donation 
reciproque  est  le  seul  gain  de  survie  pratique. 


198 


./?.  Caillemer  [ix 


Quant  aux  mots :  augmentum  dotis,  melioratio,  melior -amentum ,  ils 
ont  design^  tout  d'abord  un  accroissement  quelconque  de  la  dot,  qu'il 
vint  du  mari,  ou  des  parents  du  mari,  ou  meme  des  parents  de  la 
femme.1  Puis  le  mot  augment  de  dot  a  pris  un  sens  plus  e"troit,  et 
a  de"sign£  un  gain  de  survie  calcule"  sur  la  dot.  Get  augment  de 
dot  n'a  jamais  eu,  dans  le  Sud  -  Est  de  la  France,  une  grande 
extension.  II  a  pris  le  caractere  d'un  gain  de  survie  ttgal  dans 
quelques  pays  (Suisse  romande,  Savoie,  Lyonnais,  et  aussi  Franche- 
Comte,  ou  les  roturiers  le  pratiquent  sous  le  nom  de  douaire)? 
En  Dauphine,  il  n'a  jamais  existe"  qu'en  vertu  d'une  clause  formelle.3 

1  Bibl.  hist,  du  Lyonnais ',  p.  29  (1229):  melioramenttim  const! tue  par  le 
frere   de  la  femme   au   profit   du  mari.      Valb.  ii.  p.  61  :    augmentum  dotis 
constitute  par  le  pere  de  la  femme.    C.  Lyonnais,  i.  N°  1 40  (i  2 1 6)  :  « Renuncians 
omni  juri   .    .   .  ratione  .  .    .  alicujus   melioramenti  competituro  » ;    N°  220 
(1226):    melioratio  dotis  constitute  par  le  pere  du  marie:   « Cum  Johannes 
films   meus  contraxisset   matrimonium  cum  filia    Boni   Johannis,   dedi   ei   et 
concessi   in  melioration^  quicquid  idem  Johannes  acquisierat  vel   acquirere 
poterat  cum  vinea  mea  de  Poimie. »     De  meme  pour  un  autre  fils. 

2  V.,    pour    la    Suisse    Romande,    von    Wyss,  Eh.    Guterrechte,   p.    177, 
178  et  s.,  194  et  s.,  197  et  s.  ;  pour  la  Savoie,  le  Bugey,  le  Valromey,  le  pays 
de  Gex,  Ant.  Favre,  Codex  Fabrianus,  v.  i,  De  don.  ante  nupt.  3  et  s. :  pour  la 
Franche-Comte,  cout.  de  1459,  art.  26.     Au  contraire  « le  douaire  »  des  nobles 
francs-comtois  est  un  veritable  douaire,  calcule  sur  les  immeubles  du  mari. 

8  On  peut  voir  un  exemple  d'augment  (sans  le  nom)  en  1309,  dans 
Valbonnais,  i.  p.  199,  HHH  ;  la  fiancee  apportant  une  dot  de  20,000  1.,  son 
fiance  lui  fait  une  donation  entre-vifs  de  10,000  1.  La  donation  du  mari  est 
ainsi  egale  a  la  moitie  de  la  dot. 

\}  augmentum  dotis  figure  dans  le  projet  de  mariage,  cite  plus  haut,  entre 
Humbert  II  et  Blanche  de  Savoie,  en  1347,  Valbonnais,  ii.  p.  370;  cet 
augment  ne  doit  prendre  naissance  que  si  la  dot  est  restituee  a  la  veuve,  et 
s'il  n'y  a  pas  d'enfants  nes  du  mariage  :  «  Item  memorandum  quod,  si  dotis 
restitutio  locum  haberet,  domino  Dalphino  praemoriente,  non  superstitibus 
liberis  ab  eisdem  communibus,  dat  sibi  dominus  in  augmentum  dotis  decem 
millia  flor.  »  En  cas  de  predeces  de  Blanche,  le  Dauphin  doit  garder  de  meme 
10,000  florins  sur  la  dot  :  on  nommera  ce  droit,  plus  tard,  le  contre- 
augment. 

Guy  Pape  parle  a  plusieurs  reprises  de  1'augment :  qu.  274,  363,  430,  en 
se  preoccupant  surtout  d'ecarter  Papplication  a  1'augment  des  regies  romaines 
sur  la  donatio  propter  nuptias.  II  cherche  a  etablir  que  1'augment  sera  du  a 
la  femme,  meme  si  la  dot  n'a  pas  etc  payee  au  mari  :  «  et  ita  in  judicando 
servatur  in  hac  curia  Parlamenti »  (qu.  274).  II  montre  que  1'augment  de  dot 
peut  fort  bien  ne  pas  etre  egal  a  la  dot :  «  Licet  in  pactis  de  dote  et  dotis 
augmento  lucrandis  aequalitas  debeat  servari  .  .  .,  tamen  inaequalitas  dotis 
et  augmenti  quandoque  toleratur  .  .  .  ,  primo  videlicet,  si  usus  et  consuetudo 
patriae  habeat  oppositum  .  .  .  :  sicut  est  in  patria  Delph.,  quia  videmus 
quotidie  quod  ex  pacto  maritus  de  dote  lucratur  pro  supermta  centum  vel 


ix]  Droit  Coutumier  199 

II  est  reste"  a  peu  pres  inconnu  en  Bresse1et  en  Provence.2  N£ 
tardivement,  apres  la  renaissance  du  droit  remain,  1'augment  ne 
saurait  eVidemment  e"tre  rattache,  comme  le  voulait  Ficker,  au 
vieux  droit  burgonde. 

En  somme,  malgre'  la  renaissance  du  droit  romain,  les  coutumes 
du  Sud-Est  de  la  France  n'ont  pas  adopt£  le  systeme  romain  de  la 
donatio  propter  nuptias.  Ici  encore,  en  matiere  de  gains  de  survie 
comme  en  matiere  de  protection  de  la  dot,  ces  coutumes  ont  e"labor<§ 
une  se"rie  d'institutions  originales,  et  ici  la  resistance  aux  id£es 
romaines  a  e"te"  plus  durable,  car,  tandis  que  I'lnali^nabilite"  dotale  a 
fini  par  triompher,  cette  organisation  spontane"e  des  gains  de  survie 
a  persiste  jusqu'a  la  Revolution. 

Nous  pourrions  faire,  en  ce  qui  concerne  les  actes  a  cause  de 
mort,  des  observations  analogues.  Jusqu'au  XIP  siecle,  le  Sud-Est 
de  la  France  a  completement  ignore^  le  testament  proprement  dit, 
unilateral  et  revocable.  Les  actes  appeles  « testaments »  sont. 
des  donations  ou  des  ventes.  On  ne  connait  que  la  donation 
avec  reserve  de  jouissance  viagere.  Le  gadium  dauphinois  et  pro- 
vengal,  difficilement  revocable,  n'est  qu'une  donation  post  obitum. 
Lorsque,  au  XIF  et  surtout  au  XIIP  siecle,  le  testament  reparait,  il 
se  de"barrasse  pe"niblement  de  ces  anciens  caracteres  des  actes  a 
cause  de  mort.  L'institution  d'heritier  n'apparait  qu'avec  des 
formes  hesitantes  (institution  de  Dieu  ou  des  Saints ;  tres 
nombreuses  institutions  ex  re  certa).  Le  contenu  du  testament 
continue  de  s'inspirer  d'ide'es  etrangeres  au  droit  romain.  —  Mais 
cette  etude  est  faite  ou  va  £tre  faite  ailleurs,  et  elle  nous  entrainerait 
trop  loin. 

ducentos  florenos,  et  uxor  duplum. »  II  est  curieux  de  voir  Guy  Pape,  voulant 
donner  un  exemple  de  1'augment  dauphinois,  choisir  un  cas  de  supravita. 

1  V.,  pour  la  Bresse,  Ch.  Revel,  D  Usage  des  pays  de  Bresse,  nouv.  ed., 
Bourg,  1729,  p.  254  et  s. :  «  L'augment  est  une  complaisance  efeminee  et  une 
mauvaise  drogue  qui  nous  est  venue  de  de-la  les  Monts  ou  de  la  Savoye  :  le 
droit  romain   ne  1'a  jamais  ape^u  ;  nos  Coutumes  n'en  parlent  point.  .  .  . 
Get  augment  est  descendu  jusqu'en  Bugey,  mais  il  n'a  pas  passe  la  riviere 
d'Ain  ...»     En  Bresse,  il  n'existe  que  s'il  est  expressement  stipule,  «  et  on  le 
peut  apeller  Poprobre  et  Pinfamie  de  notre  siecle. »     Dans  la  seconde  partie 
de  cet  ouvrage,  p.  119  et  s.,  Revel  etudie  Paugment  tel  qu'il  fonctionne  dans 
le  Bugey,  le  Valromey  et  le  pays  de  Gex. 

2  V.,  sur  cette  extension  de  Paugment   a  la  fin  de  notre  ancien  droit, 
Boucher  d'Argis,  Traiti  des  gains  nuptiaux,  ed.  de  1787,  p.  37. 


2oo  R.  Caillemer  [ix 

Pour  terminer,  nous  indiquerons  encore  que  les  idees  romaines 
sur  la  tutelle,  la  curatelle,  la  puissance  paternelle,  I'emancipation 
sont  absentes  du  droit  du  haut  moyen  age.  Les  premiers  actes 
d'emancipation  re"ve"lateurs  d'une  puissance  paternelle  perpetuelle, 
sont  du  xnr  siecle.  En  1204,  Andre  Dauphin,  donnant  des 
franchises  a  St-  Vallier,  date  1'acte :  anno  mee  milicie  primo ;  il  a 
environ  20  ans ;  jusqu'alors,  sa  mere  administrait  le  comt£ 
d'Albon  :  c'est  encore  la  majorit£  feodale,  marquee  par  1'adoubement.1 
Au  contraire,  en  1237,  dans  son  testament,  il  distingue,  pour  son 
jeune  fils  Guigue,  la  periode  de  la  tutelle  (jusqu'a  14  ans)  et  celle  de  la 
curatelle : 2  les  ide"es  romaines  ont  done,  en  cette  matiere,  pe"ne"tre" 
dans  le  premier  tiers  du  xille  siecle  dans  la  Maison  des  comtes 
d'Albon. 

Ces  quelques  indications,  que  Ton  pourrait  encore  allonger,  nous 
paraissent  caracte"ristiques  :  ces  «  pays  de  droit  e"crit »  ont  e"te",  au  haut 
moyen  age,  profondement  p^n^tr^s  d'id^es  coutumieres,  qui  ont 
sur  quelques  points  oppose,  a  la  reception  du  droit  remain,  une 
vive  resistance. 

R.  CAILLEMER. 


1  Franchises    de    Saint- Vallier,    dans    la    Petite    Revue   des    bibliophiles 
dauphinois^  Grenoble,  1869-1874,  p.  59. 

2  Valbonnais,  i.  p.  60  :  «  Item  dedit  eidem  Guigoni  tutricem  Beatricem. 
.  .   .  Item   post    expirationem    tutelae   dedit  eandem    Beatricem    curatricem 
filio  suo  supradicto. » 


X 

LA  MAXIME  PRINCEPS  LEGIBUS  SOLUTUS 
EST  DANS   L'ANCIEN  DROIT   PUBLIC  FRAN- 


I 

LE  Digeste,  au  titre  de  legibus  senatusconsultis  et  longa  consuetudine 
(i.  3),  contient  un  fragment  d'Ulpien  (L.  31)  qui  commence  ainsi  : 
Princeps  legibus  solutus  est.  Peu  de  textes  ont  exerce"  une 
influence  plus  profond  sur  le  deVeloppement  du  droit  public  dans 
certains  pays  d'Europe  et  surtout  en  France.  Seul  peut  reven- 
diquer  le  meme  prestige  et  meme  1'emporter  a  cet  e"gard  un  autre 
fragment  du  meme  jurisconsulte  Ulpien  qui  forme  la  loi  du  titre 
suivant,  de  Constitutionibus  principum  et  qui  commence  par  cette 
assertion  celebre  et  mena^ante  :  Quod  principi  placuit  legis  habet 
vigor  em. 

La  premiere  regie  formulee  par  Ulpien  et  sur  laquelle  porte 
notre  e"tude,  avait  dans  le  droit  romain  du  nr  siecle  une  porte"e 
precise  et  limite'e.  L'Empereur  n'e"tait  point  affranchi  des  lois  ;  il 
leur  e"tait  au  contraire  soumis  en  principe.  Mais  il  arrivait  que 
telle  ou  telle  loi  nouvelle  exemptait  le  prince  re"gnant  de  certaines 
des  regies  qu'elle  £dictait,  et  la  Lex  de  imperio  Vespasiani  montre 
que  1'habitude  e"tait  de  maintenir  ces  exemptions  a  ses  successeurs.1 
En  dehors  de  ces  franchises  spe'ciales  et  legalement  e"dicte"es, 
1'Empereur  pouvait  obtenir  du  S^nat,  competent  a  cet  egard,  la 
dispense  de  certaines  regies  le"gales.  Puis,  et  c'est  la  un  nouvel  e"tat 
du  droit  romain  deja  ^tabli  au  temps  d'Ulpien,  on  admit  que 
1'Empereur  pouvait  lui-meme  accorder  des  dispenses  de  cette 

1  Lex  de  imperio  Vespasiani^  dans  P.  F.  Girard,  Textes  de  droit  romain 
public's  et  annote"s,  46ine  edition,  p.  108  :  <t  Utique  quibus  legibus  plebisve  scitis 
scriptum  fuit  ne  divus  Aug(ustus),  Tiberiusve  Julius  Caesar  Aug(ustus), 
Tiberiusque  Claudius  Caesar  Aug(ustus)  Germanicus  tenerentur,  iis  legibus 
plebisque  scitis  imp(erator)  Caesar  Vespasianus  solutus  sit.  » 

201 


2O2  A.  Esmein  [x 

espece  et,  comme  il  pouvait  le  cas  e'che'ant  se  les  accorder  a  lui- 
meme,  on  admit  qu'une  telle  dispense  pour  lui-meme  allait  de  soi : 
pour  plus  de  simplicity  il  fut  conside're'  comme  affranchi  des  regies 
le"gales  dont  il  pouvait  accorder  la  dispense.  Tel  est  le  sens  vrai 
et  la  porte"e  originelle  de  cette  petite  phrase  e"crite  par  Ulpien  : 
Princeps  legibus  solutus  est. *•  Mais  cette  faculte"  ne  s'appliquait 
qu'aux  lois  concernant  le  droit  prive"2  et,  ajoute  Mommsen,  aux 
lois  de  police.3  L'Empereur  restait  tenu  des  lois  concernant  le 
droit  public4  et  meme  des  lois  criminelles,  bien  qu'en  vertu  des 
principes  g6neraux  aucune  poursuite  ne  fut  possible  centre  lui 
pendant  son  principat.5 

Mais  lorsque,  lors  de  la  premiere  renaissance  des  e*tudes  de 
droit  romain,  le  texte  d'Ulpien  sortit  de  la  poussiere  et  fut  remis 

1  Voyez  le  magistral  expose   de  Theodor   Mommsen  sur  cette  question, 
Romischer  Staatsrecht,  zweiter  Band,  II.  Abtheilung,  zweite  Auflage,  p.  728 
et  s.  —  traduction  franchise  par  P.  F.  Girard. 

2  Mommsen  fait  justement  remarquer  que  le  texte  d'Ulpien  est  tire  de 
son  commentaire  ad  legem  Juliam   et  Papiam,  c'est-a-dire,  sur  une  matiere 
essentiellement  de  droit  prive,  et  que  cela  est  confirme  par  ce  qui  y  est  dit  de 
V  Augusta^  laquelle  n'avait  aucune  part  au  gouvernement  et  pour  laquelle  il  ne 
pouvait  s'agir  que  de  privileges  se  rapportant  au  droit  prive  :  «  Augusta  tamen 
licet  legibus  soluta  non  est,  principes  tamen  eadem  illi  privilegia  tribuunt  quae 
ipsi  habent. »     Dans  ce  dernier  cas  il  y  a  manifestement  une  dispense  accor- 
dee  par  1'Empereur.      D'apres  une  constitution  de   1'empereur  Alexandre    il 
semblerait    meme    que    les   princes    sur  certains   points    aient  de   parti  pris 
restreint  leur  exemption,  Cod.  Just.  vi.  23,  3  :  «  Ex  imperfecto  testamento  nee 
imperatorem   hereditatem   vindicare  saepe   constitutum   est.     Licet  enim   lex 
imperil  solemnibus  juris   imperatorem  solverit,   nihil    tamen   tarn   proprium 
imperii  est  quam  legibus  vivere. »     Mais  la  vraie  raison  de  la  decision  donnee 
la  est  qu'il   s'agissait  de  la  validite   d'un  acte  accompli  non  par  le   Prince, 
mais  par  un  tiers.     Voyez  une  constitution  de  Justinien  (Cod.  v.   16,  26)  qui 
declare  absolument   et  immediatement    valables    les    donations   entre    epoux 
faites  par  I'Empereur  a  V Augusta  ou  par  V Augusta  a  1'Empereur. 

3  Mommsen,  op.  tit.  p.  728  :  «  Nicht  mit  Unrecht  wurde  darum  spaterhin, 
wenn  ein  vom  Kaiser  vollzogener  Rechtsakt  einer  privatrechtlicher  oder  nur 
poliseilichen  Prohibitivvorschrift  zuwiderlief,  derselbe  aufrecht  erhalten  als  die 
Dispensation  derselben  in  sich  tragend. » 

4  Un  passage  de  Suetone  me  parait  montrer  que,  dans  1' Administration 
de  la  justice   qu'il   rendait    en    personne,   Auguste    se   croyait    oblige  de   se 
conformer  aux  lois,  Divus  Augustus,  c.  33  :     «  Dixit  autem  jus  non  diligentia 
modo  summa   sed  et  lenitate,   siquidem  manifesti  parricidii  reum,  ne  culleo 
insueretur,  quod  nonnisi  confessi  adficiuntur  hac  poena,  ita  fertur  interrogasse  : 
Certe  patrem  tuum  non  occidisti  ?  »     Si,  par  sa  seule  volonte  Auguste  avait  pu 
ecarter  la  peine  du  culleus,  il  n'aurait  pas  eu  besoin  d'arreter  1'aveu  sur  les 
levres  du  coupable. 

5  Mommsen,  op.  cit.  p.  729. 


x]  Princeps  legibus  solutus  est  203 

au   jour   avec   les   autres,   on    lui   donna   une  porte"e  nouvelle   et 
absolue.     On  lui  fit  dire  que  le  monarque  n'etait  pas  tenu  des  lois, 
qu'il  en  e*tait  affranchi  d'une  maniere  ge"ne>ale.     Les  Glossateurs,^1 
qui   avaient   fait   un   de"pouillement   integral   des   textes    compris   / 
dans  la  Compilation  de  Justinien,  en  trouvaient  bien  qui  leur  parais- 
saient  contraires  a  cette  regie ;  mais  ils  les  e"cartaient  par  cet  argu- 
ment principal  que  le  Prince,  quoique  non  tenu.des  lois,  pouvait  s'y 
soumettre  de  sa  libre  volonte.1 

On  regardait  done  comme  une  regie  incontest£  et  absolue  du 
droit  remain  que  le  Prince  e"tait  affranchi  de  1'observation  des  lois 
et  cette  regie,  comme  tant  d'autres  appartenant  au  meme  fonds,  se 
fit  recevoir  en  France.  Elle  s'y  fit  recevoir  dans  le  cours  du  XIII6 
siecle,  car,  comme  on  le  verra  plus  loin,  elle  est  visee  comme  certaine 
dans  la  Practica  aurea  libellorum  de  Petrus  Jacobi  qui  fut  terminee 
en  13 1 1.2  Dans  le  dernier  tiers  du  XIVe  siecle  elle  est  invoquee  dans 
un  texte  officiel,  dans  1'ordonnance  de  Charles  V  de  1374,  qui  fixe 
a  quatorze  ans  la  majorit£  des  rois.3 

1  Le    texte    principal    qui   semblait    contraire  etait   une   constitution   des 
empereurs  Theodose  et  Valentinien  (Cod.  i.  14,  4)  ainsi  con9ue  :  «  Digna  vox 
majestate  regnantis  legibus  alligatum  se  principem  profiteri :  adeo  de  auctoritate 
juris    nostra    pendet    auctoritas.      Et   re    vera  majus   imperio  est  submittere 
legibus  principatum.      Et  oraculo  praesentis  edicti  quod  nobis  licere  non  patimur 
indicamus. »     C'est  sur  ce  texte  que  la  glose  produit  les  diverses  conciliations 
qu'avait  trouvees  1'ecole.      L'une  consistait  a  dire  qu'il  etait  noble  et  digne  de 
declarer  que  Pempereur  etait  soumis  aux  lois,  bien  que  cela  fut  faux  ;  glose,  vis 
Digna  vox  :  «  Sed  quomodo  est  digna  vox,  cum  sit  falsum  1  ff.  L.  Princeps  et 
ff.  de  leg.  Ill  ex  imperfecto  et  in  authent.  de  considibus  \fin(ali)  cap.  Ill,  et  I(nfra) 
I.  ex  imperfecto  ?  Responde  :  digna  est  si  dicat  se  velle  quod  non  sit,  Inst. 
quibus  modis  injir(inantur  testamentd]  §  finali  et  in  praeallegata  l(ege)   ex 
imperfecto.))  —  Une  autre  opinion  soutenait  qu'en  pareil  cas  il  etait  permis  de 
mentir ;    la    glose   citee    continue    ainsi :    « Alii    dicunt   quod  hie   permittitur 
mentiri  ut  Inst.  de  act(ionibus')  §  alia,  quod  non  placet. »     Enfin  on  soutenait 
que  cela  s'appliquait  parce  que  c'etait  en  vertu  de  la  loi  meme  que  le  Prince 
etait  affranchi  des  lois,  par  1'effet  de  la  lex  regia  de  imperio  ;  glose  sur  la  loi 
Digna  vox,  vls  de  auctoritate  :  <t  hoc  est  ratio  primi  dicti  et  quod  dicit  juris,  s(ci- 
licet)  regis  regiae  quae  est  de  imperio  transferendo  de  populo  in  imperatorem. » 

2  Savigny,  Geschichte  des  romischen  Rechts  im  Mittelalter,  zweite  Ausgabe, 
sechster  Band,  §  12,  p.  37. 

3  (Dupuy),  Traite"  de  la  majorite"  des  rois  et  des  r/gences  du  royaume,  1722, 
t.  i.  p.  237  :  «  Super  adoptione  et  administratione  regni  non  reperiatur  certa 
aetas  constituta  vel  praefinita  a  jure  in  Rege,  qui  solutus  est  legibus,  cum  jura 
dicentia  aetatem  exigi  in  minoribus  loquantur  (de)  jurium  ditioni  subjectis. » 
Le  texte  repousse  ici  1'application  des  regies  du  droit  remain  sur  les  mineurs 
de  vingt  cinq  ans  parce  que  le  roi  legibus  solutus  est,  et  constate  d' autre  part 
que  ce  droit  n'a  pas  de  regies  speciales  sur  la  majorite*  des  rois. 


2O4  A.  Esmein  [x 

D'autres  pays  avaient  eu  le  bonheur  d'echapper  a  cette  in- 
fluence. Telle  1'Angleterre.  Des  le  XIIP  siecle  Bracton  y  pro- 
clamait  1'empire  absolu  de  la  loi ;  le  roi  lui-meme  lui  £tait  soumis 
car  «c'e"tait  la  loi  qui  faisait  le  roi)).1  Au  XVe  siecle  Fortescue 
expose  magistralement  la  meme  these.  II  montre  que  1'Angleterre 
de  son  temps  vit  sous  le  regimen  politician  et  non  simplement  sous 
le  regimen  regale  ;  c'est  une  monarchie  limited,  tandis  que  la  France 
lui  apparait  comme  une  monarchie  absolue,  bien  qu'en  re"alite"  elle 
ne  le  fut  pas  encore  a  cette  £poque.  Fortescue  e"tablit  clairement 
la  souverainete"  des  lois  anglaises.  Non  seulement  il  declare  que 
toutes  les  lois  humaines  sont  sacre"es  aussi  bien  que  celles  du 
Deute"ronome,2  mais  il  rappelle  qu'a  son  couronnement  le  roi 
d'Angleterre  promet  par  serment  d'observer  ses  propres  lois.3 
Fortescue  s'attaque  d'ailleurs,  non  proprement  a  la  regie  Princeps 
legibus  solutus  est,  mais  a  la  regie  Quod  principi  placuit  legis  habet 
vigorem.  II  reconnait  encore  au  roi,  du  moins  dans  un  de  ses 
ouvrages,  le  droit  de  dispenser  des  lois,  lequel  ne  sera  definitive- 
men  t  aboli  que  par  le  Bill  of  Rights.^ 

1  Henrici  de  Bracton  de  legibus  et  consuetudinibus  Angliae  libri  quinque, 
Londini,  1640,  L.  i.  c.  8,  §  5,  p.  5  :  «  Ipse  tamen  rex  non  debet  esse  sub  homine 
sed  sub  Deo  et  sub  lege,  quia  lex  facit  regem.     Attribuat  igitur  rex  legi  quod  lex 
ei  attribuit,  videlicet  dominationem  et  potestatem  ;  non  est  enim  rex  ubi  domi- 
natur  voluntas  et  non  lex.      Et  quod  sub  lege  esse  debeat,  cum  sit  Dei  vicarius, 
evidenter  apparet  ex  similitudine  Jesu  Christi. » — Cf.  Pollock  and  Maitland,  The 
History  of  English  Law  before  the  Time  of  Edward  I,  tome  i.  pp.  160-1. 

2  Fortescue,  De  laudibus  legum  Angliae  .  .  .,  Londini,  I775>  c-  3)  P-  3  : 
«  Scire  igitur  te  volo  quod  non  solum  Deuter.  leges  sed  et  omnes  leges  humanae 
sacrae  sunt,  quia  lex  his  verbis  definitur  :  lex  est  sanctio  sancta,  jubens  honesta, 
prohibens  contraria. » 

3  De  laudibus  legum  Angliae,  c.  34,  p.  28  :  «  Audisti  namque  superius  quod 
inter  leges  civiles  praecipua  sententia  est  maxima  sive  regula  ilia  quae  cavit  quod 
principi  placuit  legis  habet  vigorem  :  qualiter  non  sanciunt  leges  Angliae,  dum 
nedum  regulariter  sed  politice  rex  ejusdem  dominatur  in  populum  suum,  quo 
ipse  in  coronatione  sua  ad  legis  suae  observantiam  astringitur  sacramento. » 

4  The  Governance  of  England :  otherwise  called  The  Difference  between  an 
Absohite  and  a  Limited  Monarchy,  by  Sir  John  Fortescue,  a  revised  text  edited 
with  introduction,  notes,  and  appendices  by  Charles  Plummer,  M.A.,  Oxford, 
Clarendon  Press,  1885,  p.  83  :  «  There  is,  however,  in  the  De  Natura  a  pass- 
age (c.  24  sq.  Works,  pp.  85-87)  not  found  in  his  other  works.       Et  a  la  note 
3  M.  Plummer  ajoute  :  «  As  this  passage  is  rather  important  as  bearing  on  the 
question  of  the  dispensing  power,  I  give  Fortescue's  exact  words  :  «  Ad  libitum 
«  etiam  tuum  tu  semper  regis  omnia  criminalia  et  poenas  cunctas  moderaris  vel 
« remittis :    omnimodo   sic  facere  poteris  sine   subditorum   iactura  et  offensa 
«  consuetudinum  et  statutorum  regni  tui. »     On  this  dispensing  power  of  the 


x]  Princeps  legibus  solutus  est  205 


II 

En  France,  nous  1'avons  dit,  la  maxima  Princeps  legibus  solutus 
est  fut  re^ue  dans  le  cours  du  XIIIe  siecle  et  elle  se  maintint  dans 
la  suite ;  elle  faisait  vraiment  partie  du  droit  public  de  1'ancienne 
monarchic.  Elle  y  avait  une  grande  porte"e  et  Ton  en  tirait  deux 
series  de  consequences. 

Les  premieres  concernaient  le  droit  prive.  Si  le  roi  accomplissait 
un  acte  rentrant  dans  le  droit  prive",  un  acte  qu'aurait  pu  faire  un 
particulier,  s'il  faisait  son  testament,  une  donation,  un  contrat,  il 
les  faisait  valablement  sans  tenir  compte  des  regies  e"tablies  par  les 
lois  ou  par  les  coutumes,  en  violant  ces  regies  et  en  les  ecartant. 
C'e"tait,  somme  toute,  ce  qu'avait  permis  jadis  aux  empereurs  remains 
la  regie  Princeps  legibus  solutus  est.  Bodin  en  cite  des  applications 
topiques,  notamment  le  testament  de  Philippe  de  Valois  «  portant 
la  clause  derogatoire  aux  coutumes  et  loix  civiles,  comme  n'e"tant 
pas  oblige"  a  icelles  &.1  II  cite  aussi  une  donation  du  meme  roi  a  sa 
femme,  de  Tan  1330,  qui  e"tait  ferme  et  valable,  bien  que  les  dona- 
tions entre  epoux  fussent  prohibe"es  par  la  plupart  des  coutumes 
de  France.  Les  contrats  de  manage  des  rois  fournissent  de 
notables  exemples.  Celui  de  Louis  XIII  et  de  «l'infante  Anne» 
portait :  « que  leurs  dites  Majesty's  tres-chre'tiennes  et  catholiques 
approuveront  et  ratifieront  ladite  capitulation  et  tout  le  contenu  en 
icelle,  s'obligeant  et  promettant  par  leurs  foy  et  paroles  royales  de 
le  garder  et  accomplir  inviolablement  et  seront  de"pechees  toutes 
lettres  en  la  forme  et  maniere  accoutum^e,  avec  les  derogations  a 
quelconques  loix,  coutumes  et  dispositions  qui  sont  au  contraire.» 

Mais  la  seconde  se"rie  de  consequences  etait  autrement  grave  et 
importante,  visant  le  droit  public.  On  tenait  que  lorsque  le  roi 
intervenait  en  personne,  pour  decider  lui-meme  un  acte  d'adminis- 
tration  ou  de  juridiction,  il  pouvait  le  faire  valablement  sans  tenir 
compte  des  lois,  que  ses  officiers,  au  contraire,  e"taient  tenus  d'observer 
et  de  respecter.  Cela  £tait  surtout  remarquable  quand  il  s'agissait 

Crown  during  the  Middle  Ages  see  S.CM.  iii.  579,  582.  The  exercise  of 
this  power  was  more  frequent  in  the  Middle  Ages  than  we  should  consider 
consistent  with  Constitutional  Government,  but  it  was  often  rendered  necessary 
by  the  unwise  minuteness  of  many  mediaeval  statutes. » 

1  Bodin,  Les  Six  Livres  de  la  R'epublique^  edit.  Geneve,  1629,  L.  i.  ch.  8, 
P-  154- 


206  A.  Esmein  [x 

de  1'administration  de  la  justice,  que  le  roi,  s'il  le  voulait,  pouvait 
rendre  lui-meme  a  ses  sujets.  Cette  intervention  directe  et  per- 
sonnelle  du  monarque  justicier  e"tait  d'ailleurs  conforme  a  la  tradi- 
tion ancienne  ;  et  Bodin  discute  encore  une  opinion,  d'apres  laquelle 
ce  serait  la  la  meilleure  forme  de  1'administration  de  la  justice.  II 
note  en  meme  temps  que  le  roi  jugeant  en  personne  pouvait,  en 
toute  libert^,  ne  juger  que  d'apres  sa  conscience :  « Si  le  Prince 
jugeoit,  lui  qui  est  la  loi  vive  et  par-dessus  toutes  les  lois  civiles, 
accompagn£  de  son  Conseil,  il  feroit  bonne  et  brieve  justice,  ayant 
esgard  au  fond  sans  beaucoup  s'attacher  aux  formalite's.»1  C'est 
par  la  meme  conception  qu'il  interprete  un  privilege  obtenu  par 
les  nobles  polonais :  «  La  noblesse  de  Pologne  obtint  de  Louis  roy 
de  Hongrie  et  de  Pologne  un  privilege  que  les  nobles  ne  pourroient 
etre  juge"s  que  par  le  roy  quand  il  y  va  de  la  vie  et  de  1'honneur, 
croyant  qu'ils  pouvoient  aisement  e"chapper  le  jugement  du  roy  et 
non  pas  des  juges  qui  sont  obligez  aux  loix.»2 

II  resultait  de  la  que  le  Conseil  du  roi,  quand  il  jugeait  au 
fond  les  causes  des  particuliers,  pouvait  toujours  decider  en 
ne  consultant  que  le  sentiment  de  Pe"quite ;  car  le  Conseil  du 
roi,  c'£tait  le  roi  lui-meme,  celui-ci  e"tant  toujours  cense"  present 
dans  son  Conseil  ;  c'etait  lui  que  faisaient  parler  les  arrets 
du  Conseil.3  Nos  anciens  auteurs  insistaient  sur  ce  pouvoir 
general  de  juger  en  simple  &iuite" ; 4  ils  relevaient  que,  dans  les 

1  Les  Six  Livres  de  la  Rtpublique,  L.  iv.  ch.  6,  p.  612. 

2  Ibid.  p.  623. 

3  Histoire  du  Conseil  du  roy,  par  Guillard,  avocat  au  Conseil  du  roy,  Paris 
1717,  p.  68  :  «  Mais  si  les  Cours  ont  cette  liberte  (d'evoquer  les  causes)  dans 
quelques  occasions,  celui  qui  la  leur  a  donnee  conserve  toujours  en  sa  per- 
sonne la  plenitude  de  puissance  dont  il  peut  user  selon  son  bon  plaisir  et  son 
Conseil  etant  inseparable  de  sa  majeste,  dont  il  n'est  que  1'organe,  personne 
ne  peut  dire  que  le  Conseil  ne  puisse  pas  dans  certaines  occasions  connoistre 
des  affaires  des  particuliers,  les  evoquer  a  soy,  les  decider  diffinitivement,  sans 
les  renvoyer  a  des  juges  ordinaires  comme  il  les  renvoie  le  plus  souvent  parce 
qu'il  s'occupe  d'affaires  plus  importantes. » 

4  Guillard,  Histoire  du  Conseil  du  roy,  p.   72  :    «  II    faut    convenir  que 
1'equite  naturelle,  qui  est  Fame  des  lois  et  des  ordonnances,  merite  beaucoup 
d'attention  au  Conseil  du  roy  pour  peu  qu'il  soit  besoin  d'entrer  dans  1'inter- 
pretation  de  quelques  ordonnances,  Edits  ou  Declarations ;  et  quand  on  decouvre 
une  iniquite  evidente  dans  quelque  jugement  des  Cours,  le  Conseil  du  Prince 
est  d'autant  plus  oblige  de  soutenir  la  partie  opprimee  que  1'on  ne  doit  pas 
souffrir  que  pour  quelque  formalite  mal  observee  ou  obmise  les  plaideurs  de 
mauvaise   foi  profitent  du  dol  et  des  surprises  qu'ils  ont  mis  en  usage  pour 
tromper  leurs  juges  et  leurs  parties. » 


x]  Princeps  legibus  solutus  est  207 

serments  du  sacre  le  roi  promettait  de  rendre  la  justice  en 
equitel 

La  il  n'y  avait  encore  que  demi  mal,  bien  que  le  respect  du 
droit  technique  soit  le  meilleur  garant  des  interets  le"gitimes ;  mais 
le  principe  entrainait,  dans  d'autres  applications,  de  terribles 
dangers.  II  en  r£sultait  en  effet  que  le  roi,  statuant  en  personne, 
pouvait  infliger  les  peines  les  plus  graves  sans  qu'elles  fussent 
prononce"es  par  aucune  loi  et  sans  forme  de  proces.  Logiquement  il 
aurait  pu  le  faire  en  siegeant  comme  juge.2  -Mais  dans  les  audiences 
prive'es  que  les  rois  tinrent  pendant  longtemps,3  ils  ne  tranchaient 
que  des  causes  civiles  de  peu  d'importance.  D'autre  part  le  Con- 
seil  du  roi  cessa  de  bonne  heure  de  revendiquer  aucune  competence 
en  matiere  criminelle. 

Mais  les  Lettres  de  cachet  e*taient  surement  une  application 
du  principe.  Elles  pouvaient  contenir  un  ordre  quelconque  du 
monarque.  Mais  en  fait,  employees  comme  moyen  de  repression, 
elles  ne  contenaient  jamais  qu'un  ordre  d'emprisonnement  sans 
jugement  dans  une  prison  d'Etat,  ou  un  ordre  d'exil.  II  est  vrai 
que  les  rois  anciennement  ont  parfois  fait  mettre  a  mort  sans  juge- 
ment, par  ordre  verbal,  des  personnes  qu'ils  conside"raient  comme 

1  Guillard,  op.  tit.  p.  72  :  «  Nos  rois  s'engagent  meme  a  leur  sacre  par 
un  serment  solennel  a  suivre  en  tout  les  regies  de  Ftquiti  et  de  condamner 
Finiquitt  en  toutes  occasions. »     C'etait  Ik  une  interpretation  forcee  ;  dans  les 
serments  du  sacre  le  mot  tquiti  (aequitas)  etait  pris  dans  un  autre  sens  ;  il 
voulait  dire  que  le  roi  statuerait  avec .impartiality.)  On  se  rappelle  que,  d'apres 
Fortescue,  le  roi  d'Angleterre  jurait  d'observer,  non  Tequite,  mais  les  lois,  ses 
propres  lois  ;  voyez  ci-dessus,  note  3,  p.  204. 

2  Fortescue,  De  laudibus,  c.  35,  p.  30,  parait  bien  dire  qu'il  en  etait  ainsi  : 
(tNobilis    tamen    non    sic    exactionibus    opprimitur.      Sed    si    eorum  aliquis 
calumniatus  fuerit  de  crimine,  licet  per  inimicos  suos,  non  semper  coram  judice 
ordinario  ipse  convocari  solet,  sed  quam  saepe  in  Regis  Camera  et  alibi  in 
private  loco,  quandoque  vero  solum  per  internuncios  ipse  inde  alloqui  visus 
est  et  mox  ut  criminosum  eum  Principis  conscientia,  reatu  aliorum,  judicaverit, 
.  .  .  qualiter  et  mori  audivisti  numerum  multo  majorem  hominum  quam  qui 
legitimo  processu  juris  convicti   extiterunt. »     Ce   passage  de  Fortescue   qui 
parait  reposer  sur  des  bruits  non  fondes,  ne  serait  point  inexact  s'il  se  rap- 
portait  aux  lettres  de  cachet ;  mais  les  lettres  de  cachet  ne  contenaient  jamais 
1'ordre  de  mettre  a  mort  une  personne  quelconque.     Ce  passage  ne  peut  pas 
non  plus  se  rapporter  aux  Jugements  par  Commissaires^  dans  lesquels  £tait 
suivie  une  procedure  extraordinaire  mais  complete. 

3  L'ordonnance  de  Blois  de  1579  contient  encore  une  disposition  sur  cette 
administration  de  la  justice  intime  et  familiere. 


208  A.  Rsmein  [x 

coupables.1  Nos  anciens  auteurs  appelaient  cela  proceder  par  des 
votes  defait ;  mais  ils  estimaient  que  le  monarque  ne  devait  pro- 
ceder que  par  des  votes  de  droit,  c'est-a-dire  par  les  procedures 
re"gulieres.2 

Ill 

II  ne  faudrait  pas  croire  cependant  que  la  maxime  Princeps 
legibus  solutus  est  n'ait  pas  rencontre"  en  France  de  contra- 
dicteurs. 

Des  le  premier  tiers  du  XIVe  siecle,  da^ns  sa  Practica  aurea 
libellorum?  Petrus  Jacobi  s'efforce  d'en  e"carter  ^  1'application.  II 
ne  conteste  point  directement  que  le  roi  soit  exempt  des  lois ;  il 
Tadmet  au  contraire  en  droit.  Mais  il  tient  qu'il  est  digne  d'un 
monarque,  que  c'est  meme  son  devoir  de  vouloir  ce  que  veulent  les 
lois  et  ne  pas  e"couter  les  flatteurs,  les  courtisans  qui  tachent  de 
lui  inspirer  une  volonte"  diffe"rente.4  Cette  influence  neTaste  des 
courtisans  reviendra  dans  des  textes  poste"rieurs. 

Mais  c'est   la  une  note  isol^e  et  timide.     II  faut  attendre  la 

1  II  semble  que  Louis  XI  ait  agi  assez  souvent  ainsi  a  1'egard  de  petites 
gens.      La  Roche-Flavin,  Treize  Livres  des  Parlements  de  France,  Bourdeaux, 
1617,  L.  xiii.  ch.   13,  N°  5  :  «  Le  roi  Louis  XI  sur  la  fin  de  ses  jours  trouva 
sa  conscience  grandement  oppressee  du  mepris  de  la  justice  et,  entre  autres, 
d'avoir  pousse  jusqu'a  1'exces  le  pouvoir  absolu  allant  faire  prendre  par  le 
Prevost  les  prisonniers  de  la  Conciergerie  du  Palais  qui  les  faisoit  noyer  a 
1'endroit  de  la  Grange  aux  Merciers,  »     Dans  le  passage  de  Fortescue  (De 
laudibus,  c.  35)  cite  p.  207  n.  2,  il  est  fait  allusion  aux  memes  faits  qui,  sans 
que  le  nom  de  Louis  XI  soit  prononce,  sont  rapportes  comme  une  pratique 
ordinaire  des  monarques  fran^ais  :  «  In  sacco  positus  absque  figura  judicii  per 
Propositi  marischallorum  ministros  noctanter  in  flumine  projectus  submergitur. » 
La  source  a  laquelle  ont  puise  Fortescue  et  La  Roche-Flavin  doit  etre  la  meme. 
Ce  mode  d'execution  etait  surement  familier  au  xve  siecle  ;  qu'on  songe  aux 
vers  de  Villon  : 

Semblablement  ou  est  la  royne 
Qui  commanda  que  Buridan 
Fut  jete  en  un  sac  en  Seine  ? 

2  La  Roche-Flavin,  Treize  Livres  des  Parlements  de  France,  L.  xiii.  ch.  1 2. 

3  Edition  Venetiis,  1502. 

4  Practica  aurea  libellorum  rubrica,  xxv.  de  condictione  ex  lege,  Institution, 
de  actione  §  quadrupli,  N°  19  :«  Princeps  debet  sibi  cavere  ne  alias  laedat  sub 
coloribus  quaesitis  et  per  curiales   suos  adinventis.      Quia,  licet  princeps  sit 
solutus  legibus,  ut  ff.  de  leg.  /.  Princeps,  tamen  dignum  est  sibi  profited  secundum 
leges  vivere  velle,  ut  C.  de  leg.  /.  digna  vox,  et  idem  dicitur  de  Papa,  1 2,  qti. 
2,  c.  non  liceat  papae. » 


x]  Princeps  legibus  solutus  est  209 

seconde  moitie  du  XVF  siecle  pour  trouver  une  repudiation  e"riergique  / 
de  la  maxime,  une  contestation  formulae  en  vertu  de  principes  bien 
arret£s.  Elle  e"mane  des  £crivains  qui,  dans  la  pe"riode  des  guerres 
de  religion,  s'efforcerent  de  deVelopper  en  France  les  principes  de 
liberty  politique.  Elle  est  particulierement  nette  dans  les  Vindiciae 
contra  tyrannos  et  dans  le  Dejure  magistratuum  in  subditos  et  officio 
subditorum  erga  magistratus.1  L'auteur,  pour  respecter  la  grande 
autorite  du  droit  remain,  conserve  pourtant  a  la  maxime  la  premiere 
se"rie  d'effets  qu'on  lui  attribuait,  celle  qui  se  rapportait  aux  regies 
du  droit  priv£  dont  le  Prince  e"tait  exempt,  mais  il  l'e"carte,  avec 
preuves  a  1'appui,  en  ce  qui  concerne  le  droit  public  et  le  gouverne- 
ment  de  1'Etat.  II  affirme  aussi  en  termes  saisissants  que  le  roi 
est  tenu  par  le  droit  naturel  et  par  le  droit  divin ;  mais  cela  alors 
personne  ne  le  contestait.  L'auteur  des  Vindiciae  contra  tyrannos 
parait  contester  meme  que  le  roi  soit  exempt  des  regies  du 
droit  prive.2  II  s'eleve  spe"cialement  centre  l'id£e  que  le  roi  peut 
juger  sans  respecter  les  lois  et  les  formes  de  la  justice,3  et  qu'il  ait 
sur  ses  sujets  le  droit  de  vie  et  de  mort.4 

1  Edition  Ursellis  apud  Cornelium  Sutorium,  1 600,  a  la  suite  des  Vindiciae 
contra  tyrannos,  p.  2  5  3,  Repetitio  quaest.  vi. :  «  Quod  excipere  solent  Regem  legibus 
non  astringi  in  genere  nee  potest  nee  debet  accipi,  ut  dicunt  regum  assentatores 
regnorumque  eversores.      Nam  ut  taceam  tot  omnium  fere  nationum  exempla, 
quae  supra  allata  sunt,  quot  sunt  graves  veterum  juris  consultorum  sententiae 
e  jure  naturae  excerptae  ?     Cujusmodi  sunt :  eos  qui  leges  ferunt  legibus  quoque 
obtemperare.     Et  quod  quisque  juris  in  alium  statuit  erit,  ipse  ut  eodem  jure 
utatur.       Et    nihil   imperio   magis   conducere   quam  ut  rex  legibus  utatur ; 
dignam  denique  vocem  esse  Principem  se  legibus  subditum  profiteri.      Itaque 
quod  alibi  a  juris  consultis  dici  videtur  Principem  esse  supra  leges  aut  Principem 
legibus  esse  solutum  nonnisi  de  legibus  civilibus  deque  particular!  privatorum 
jure  est  intelligendum,  verbi  gratia  de  testamentis,  de  detractione  Trebellianae 
vel  Falcidianae  :  non  autem  de  jure  publico  et  ad  statum,  ut  dici  solet,  pertinente, 
multoque  minus  de  jure  natural!  et  divino,  cui  cum  omnes  singuli  homines 
subiciantur,  quatenus  homines  nati  sunt,  omnino  efficitur  aut  reges  homines 
non  esse  aut  illos  hoc  jure  teneri. » 

2  En  effet  (quaest.  iii.   p.    91)  il  montre  que  des  Princes,  pour  pouvoir 
faire  ce  que  la  loi  defendait,  ont  change  celle-ci  a  1'egard  de  tous  :  «  Valenti- 
nianus,  imperator  bonus  alioquin,  quia  duas  uxores  simul  habere  voluit,  singulis 
lege    permisit.      Cambyses,    Cyri    films,   nuptias    cum   germana  sorore,  quia 
sororem  appetebat,  licitas  esse  voluit.     Chabades,  Persarum  rex,  adulteriorum 
poenam  sustulit. » 

3  Vindiciae,  quaest.  iii.  p.  89  :  «  An  autem  rex,  quia  juri  dicendo  praeest, 
ex  arbitrio  jus  dicet  ?     Rexne,  inquam,  a  lege  an  lex  a  rege  pendebit  ? » 

4  Vindiciae,  quaest.  iii.  p.  98  :  «  Adulatorum  aulicorum  axioma  percelebre 
est  Principes  in  subditos  earn  quam  domini  olim  in  servos  potestatem  vitae, 

P 


2io  A.  Esmein  [x 

Ce  ne  sont  pas  seulement  au  XVP  siecle  des  £crivains  poli- 
tiques,  dont  les  ouvrages  d'ailleurs  sont  profonde'ment  impre'gnes 
de  droit  technique,  qui  d£clarent  le  roi  soumis  aux  lois,  ce  sont 
aussi  de  purs  juristes.  En  voici  un,  qui  n'est  pas  a  proprement 
parler  un  homme  supe"rieur,  mais  qui  a  joue"  un  role  notable 
de  son  temps,  e"ditant  ou  re"editant  de  vieux  textes  qu'il  com- 
mente,  tels  que  la  Somme  rural  de  Boutillier,  composant  des 
livres  dont  les  titres  sont  presque  remains  mais  qui  se  rapportent 
au  droit  frangais.  C'est  Charondas  le  Caron,  dont  les  deux 
principaux  ouvrages  sont  Les  Reponses  du  droit  frangais  et  les 
Pandectes  du  droit  fran$ais.  C'est  dans  ce  dernier  £crit  qu'il  a  traite" 
notre  question.1  II  1'aborde  avec  une  grande  nettete",  car  il  se 
demande  si  les  rois  sont  exempts  des  lois  qui  concernent  le  droit 
public  et  le  gouvernement  de  l'£tat.2  II  admet  que  les  rois  peuvent 
facilement  se  dispenser  d'observer  les  dispositions  de  droit  prive"  et 
sont  exempts  des  peines  portees  par  les  lois.3  Ce  n'est  pas  qu'il  passe 
sous  silence  le  texte  d'Ulpien ;  il  en  exagere  meme  la  ported.4 
Mais  il  a  pour  soutenir  sa  these  des  raisons  meilleures  que  des 

inquam,  et  necis  habere.  Adeo  vero  istis  nugis  principibus  imposuerunt  ut 
plerique  ea  saevitia  non  utantur  non  minus  tamen  sibi  licere  putent  sed  de  suo 
jure  quodammodo  cedere  videantur.  Dicimus  vero  nos  contra  Principem 
tanquam  legis  ministrum  et  executorem  in  eos  tantum  quos  lex  jusserit  gladium 
stringere  posse.  Sin  fecerit^  non  regem  amplius  sed  tyrannum,  non  judicem 
sed  praedonem,  non  legis  custodem  sed  violatorem  esse.» 

1  Pandectes  ou  Digested  du  droit  fran^ais,  par  Charondas  le  Caron,  docteur 
es  droits,  conseiller  du  roy  et  son  lieutenant  general  au  bailliage  et  Comte  de 
Clermont  en  Beauvoisis,  Lyon,  1 5  96,  ch.  iii.  Des  loix  et  ordonnances  et  quelles 
doivent  estre  et  si  le  souverain  est  exempt  d*icelles,  p.  29  sq. 

2  Pandectes  du  droit  frangais,  loc.  cit.  p.  4 1  :  «  On  demande  s'il  est  sub- 
ject aux  loix  establies  pour  1'estat  public,  honnestes  et  politiques. » 

3  Pandectes^  loc.  cit.  p.  43  :  « Je  n'ignore  qu'il  y  ait  des  Edits  et  Ordon- 
nances qui  ne  concernent  1'estat  public  dont  les  roys  se  peuvent  facilement 
dispenser,  d'autant  que  la  transgression  n'est  de  grande  consequence  et  ne 
prejudicie  a  Putilite  commune ;  aussi  les  rois  sont  exempts  des  peines  portees 
par  les  loix,  parce  que  leurs  personnes  ne  sont  subjectes  a  aucuns  juges,  ne 
recognoissans  que  Dieu  pour  souverain  et  seul  juge  de  leurs  actions. » 

4  Pandectes^  loc.  cit.  p.   42:   «Je  sgay  bien  que  le  jurisconsulte  Ulpian 
dit  que  le  Prince  est  exempt  et  absous  des  loix,  ce  qu'aucuns  ont  voulu  res- 
traindre  aux  loix  penales,  c'est  a  dire  a  celles  qui  sont  ordonnees  contre  ceux 
qui  delinquent,  puisque  le   Prince  n'y  est  subject :    mais   il  semble  que  les 
Romains  ont  entendu  plus  largement  ceste  exemption  et  absolution  des  loix, 
comme  declare  Dion  au  livre  cinquante-troisiesme  de  son  histoire,  parlant  de 
1'empereur  Auguste  auquel  fut  donnee  ceste  prerogative,  et  Pinterprete  n'estre 
tenu  a  aucune  necessite  de  loy,  ains  estre  exempt  de  tout  droit  escrit.  » 


x]  Princeps  legibus  solutus  est  211 

textes,  des  plus  belles  et  des  plus  fortes,  et  il  expose  courageusement 
son  opinion,  malgre  les  discours  des  courtisans,  dont  la  mention 
revient  constamment  en  cette  matiere.1  Pour  Charondas  la  loi  est 
la  regie  normale  de  tous  les  etres  raisonnables,  et  il  rappelle  que  le 
roi  doit  gouverner  par  raison  ; 2  d'autres  disaient  qu'il  devait  gou- 
verner  conforme'ment  a  la  loi  naturelle.  Devangant  sur  ce  point 
Montesquieu,  il  dit,  dans  le  langage  de  son  temps,  que  Dieu  m£me  a 
des  lois.3  Comme  le  disaient  les  Monarchomaques^  ses  contemporains, 
en  parlant  surtout  des  lois  fondamentales,  il  affirme  que  la  loi  est  une 
convention  entre  le  Prince  et  ses  sujets,  qui  lie  les  deux  parties. 
Comme  Bracton,  il  proclame  que  le  Prince  doit  respecter  la  loi, 
parce  qu'il  ne  regne  que  par  elle.4  II  considere  d'ailleurs  que  le 
monarque  est  un  officier  public  et  remplit  une  charge,5  et  il  doit 
a  ses  sujets  1'exemple  ne"cessaire  du  respect  des  lois. 

Dans  un  pareil  milieu  I'autorite'   de  la  regie  Princeps  legibus 
solutus  est  devait  decroitre  progressivement.     On  tendait  a  y  voir 

1  Pandectes,  loc.  cit.  p.  4 1  :    «  La  question  qui  se  presente  est  tres  espi- 
neuse  et  ne  se  peut  qu'avec  difficulte  traicter  en  une  monarchic  a  cause  des 
flaneurs  courtisans  qui  tirent  souvent  en  mauvaise  part  ce  qu'on  allegue  de 
la  bonte   et  moderation  du  Prince.      Toutesfoys  j'en  diray  mon  opinion  con- 
formement  a  ce  que  nos  Roys,  vrais  et  excellens  princes,  ont  tousjours  observe.)) 
P.  42  :  «  Si  quelques  courtisans  veulent  dire  qu'il  ne  faut  donner  frein  ni  bride 
au  souverain,  je  leur  respondray  que  la  Loy  n'est  une  bride  forcee,  ains  un 
doux  lien  qui  le  retient  en  son  devoir  et  rend  plus  fort  son  estat. » 

2  Pandectes,  loc.  cit.  p.  41  :  «  Mais  le  Prince,  qui  est  homme  et  commande 
aux  hommes  libres  qui  sont  participans  d'une  mesme  nature  et  sgavent  que 
c'est  de  gouverner  par  raison,  ne  se  peut  plus  seurement  maintenir  avec  eux 
que  par  commun  lien  et  accord  de  la  loy. » 

3  Pandectes,   loc.  cit.  p.  4 1  :  «  S'il  faut  plus  avant  philosopher,  il  semble 
combien  que  Dieu  par  sa  puissance  souveraine  et  absolue  puisse  remuer  tout 
1'ordre  de  1'Univers  et  n'y  soit  aucunement  astraint,  toutesfoys  que  pour  le 
conserver  il   s'y  rende  aucunement  subject,  c'est  a  dire   qu'il  y  accommode 
sa  volonte  et  puissance  qu'on  appelle  ordinaire.* 

4  Pandectes,  loc.  cit.  p.  4 1  :  «  La  loy  qui  est  (a  bien  dire  en  peu  de  paroles) 
une  tnutuelle  convention  entre  le  souverain  et  le  peuple  de  bien  commander 
et  bien  obeir,  pourquoy  done  le  souverain  n'y  sera  subject  ?     Tous  les  roys, 
empereurs  et  monarques  qui  ont  merite  le  tiltre  de  bons  princes,  ont  tousjours 
diet  que  le  Prince  devoit  obeir  aux  loix,  d'autant  qu'il  regnoit  par  Pauctorite 
d'icelles.  1> 

5  Pandectes,  loc.  cit.  p.  42  :  «  Car  si  le  Prince  doit  obeyir  a  la  loi  divine 
et  naturelle,  il  peut  apprendre  par  icelle  qu'il  faut  que  par  son  exemple  il  incite 
ses  subjects  a  bien  vivre,  ce  qu'il  ne  peut  faire  s'il  ne  se  rend  subject  aux  loix 
de  son  royaume,  parce  que  la  personne  publique  ne  doit  seulement  bien  vivre 
en  son  particulier,  ains  aussi  selon  le  droit  que  requiert  sa  charge. » 


212  A.  Esmein  [x 

une  ressource,  fondle  en  droit,  mais  qui  normalement  restait  dor- 
mante  par  la  volont£  meme  du  monarque,  celui-ci  preTe"rant  le 
regne  des  lois.1  Nos  anciens  auteurs  signalaient  en  particulier  et 
avec  raison  sa  jurisprudence  regue  en  France,  qui  rendait  le  roi 
justiciable  de  ses  propres  cours,  et  permettaient  a  ses  sujets  d'agir 
centre  lui,  pour  faire  valoir  le  droit  resultant  de  la  propri£t£  ou  des 
contrats.  II  est  vrai  qu'alors  le  procureur  du  roi  figurait  seul  en 
nom  au  proces ;  c'£tait  centre  lui  que  le  jugement  £tait  rendu,  mais 
c'etait  le  roi  qui  en  subissait  les  consequences.  Tout  cela  d'ailleurs 
n'empechait  point  que  la  pratique  des  lettres  de  cachet  n'entrat 
dans  son  plein  ;  mais  elle  prenait  1'aspect  d'une  institution  par- 
ticuliere,  ayant  sa  valeur  propre. 

Dans  la  seconde  moitie"  du  XVIP  siecle,  les  grands  esprits  qui 
construisaient  la  the"orie  de  la  monarchic  absolue,  alors  re~alise"e, 
s'efforcaient  de  re"duire,  autant  qu'il  e"tait  possible,  la  porte"e  de  la 
maxime ;  ils  en  avaient  vraiment  honte.  Ecoutons  Bossuet,  dans 
sa  Politique  tiree  des  propres  paroles  de  V&criture  Sainte  :  «  Les  rois 
ne  sont  pas  pour  cela  affranchis  des  lois.  C'est  ce  que  les  Princes 
ont  peine  a  entendre.  .  .  .  De  la  cette  belle  loi  d'un  empereur 
romain  :  c'est  une  parole  digne  de  la  Majeste"  du  Prince  que  de  se 
reconnaitre  soumis  aux  lois.  » 2  Et,  continuant,  voici  en  quels 
termes  il  expose  sa  th£orie :  «  Les  rois  sont  done  soumis  comme  les 
autres  a  l'equit£  des  lois,  et  parce  qu'ils  doivent  etre  justes  et  parce 
qu'ils  doivent  aux  sujets  1'exemple  de  garder  la  justice ;  mais  ils  ne 
sont  pas  soumis  aux  peines  des  lois,  ou,  comme  parle  la  the"ologie, 
ils  sont  soumis  aux  lois,  non  quant  a  la  puissance  coactive,  mais 
quant  a  la  puissance  directive. »  Dans  la  proposition  pre"ce"dente, 
intituled  qu'il  riy  a  point  de  puissance  coactive  contre  le  Prince,  il 
avait  e"crit :  «  On  entend  par  force  coactive  une  puissance  pour  con- 
traindre  a  executer  ce  qui  est  ordonne"  le"galement.  Au  Prince 
seul  appartient  le  commandement  le"gitime,  a  lui  seul  appartient 
la  force  coactive. »  Cela  revenait  a  dire  que  moralement  et  meme 
juridiquement  le  Prince  e"tait  tenu  de  se  conformer  aux  lois, 
mais  qu'il  pouvait  s'en  ^carter  impunement,  n'£tant  pas  soumis  aux 
peines  des  lois,  et  aucune  sanction  n'e"tant  possible  contre  lui. 

1  La  Roche-Flavin,   Treize  Livres  des  Parlements,  L.  xiii.  ch.  13,  N°  6: 
«  Chose  digne  de  la  majeste  d'un  Prince  que  nos  rois,  a  qui  Dieu  a  donne 
puissance  absolue,  aient  d'ancienne  institution  voulu  reduire  leurs  volontes  k 
la  civilite  des  lois. » 

2  Livre  iv.  article  i,  quatrieme  proposition. 


x]  Princeps  legibus  solutus  est  213 

La  doctrine  du  grand  jurisconsulte  Domat,  dans  son  Droit 
public,  est  a  peu  pres  la  meme :  «  On  peut  ajouter  pour  dernier 
devoir  du  souverain  et  qui  renferme  aussi  tous  les  autres,  qu'encore 
que  sa  puissance  semble  le  mettre  au-dessus  des  lois,  personne 
n'ayant  droit  de  lui  faire  rendre  compte  de  sa  conduite,  il  doit 
observer  celles  qui  peuvent  le  regarder  et  y  est  oblige,  non  seulement 
pour  donner  1'exemple  aux  sujets  et  leur  rendre  leur  devoir  aimable, 
mais  encore  parce  qu'il  n'est  pas  dispense  du  sien  par  cette  puissance 
de  souverain  et  qu'au  contraire  ce  rang  1'oblige  meme  a  preT£rer  a 
ses  interets  particuliers  le  bien  commun  de  TEtat  et  qu'il  est  de  sa 
gloire  de  regarder  comme  le  sien  propre.))1 

Cependant  jusqu'a  la  fin  de  Pancien  regime  la  regie  resta  dans 
le  droit  public,  comme  subsisterent  les  lettres  de  cachet,  qui 
ne  furent  abolies  que  par  PAssemblee  Constituante.  Les  esprits 
liberaux  qui  restaient  attache's  aux  principes  traditionnels  de 
1'ancienne  monarchic  n'osaient  pas  repudier  ce  droit  anormal  du 
roi.  Voici  ce  qu'on  lit  encore  dans  un  livre  publi£  quelques  annees 
avant  la  Revolution  et  qui  cut  plusieurs  editions :  «  De  quelque 
utilite  que  soient  les  formes  legales  pour  intimider  le  coupable 
par  la  certitude  de  la  peine  que  la  loi  prononce  et  pour  tranquilliser 
Pinnocence  centre  les  efforts  de  la  calomnie,  pour  mettre  le  monarque 
a  1'abri  des  surprises,  elles  lui  laissent  cependant  1'administration 
libre,  force"es  de  ceder  elles-memes  a  1'interet  public  dont  le  monarque 
est  le  seul  juge. » 2  L'auteur,  qui  est  un  esprit  eclair^  cependant, 
considere  cette  faculte  laisse"e  au  roi  comme  une  loi  fondamentale 
de  1'Etat,  et  il  y  rattache  les  lettres  de  cachet,  qu'il  approuve  dans 
leurs  principales  applications.  Moreau,  dans  son  livre  intitule 
Les  Devoirs  du  Prince  ramenes  a  un  seul  principe  ou  Discours  sur  la 
justice  dedie  au  roi?  qui  avait  £t£  compost  pour  1'education  de 
Louis  XVI  et  de  ses  freres,  soutient  une  these  semblable.  Voici 
comment  il  defend  les  lettres  de  cachet  contenant  un  ordre  d'em- 
prisonnement ;  il  est  vrai  que  suivant  lui  ce  doit  etre  la  simplement 
une  mesure  provisoire  et  le  prisonnier  doit  etre  dans  un  court  delai 
renvoy£  devant  ses  juges  naturels  :  «  Les  formes  qui  accompagnent 
essentiellement  la  marche  de  celle-ci  (la  justice)  sont  lentes  et 

1  Domat,  Droit  public,  L.  i.  tit.  2,  sect.  3,  N°  14. 

2  Les  Vrais  Principes  du  gouvernement  fran$ais,  dhnontre's  par  la  raison  et 
par  les  faits,  par  un  Frangois,  Geneve  1782,  p.  66. 

3  A  Versailles  de  I'imprimerie  du  roi,  Depart,  des  aff.  etr.  1775,  p.  160. 


214  ^-  Esmein  [x 

tardives.  Elles  furent  invente"es  pour  etre  le  rempart  de  1'inno- 
cence.  Doit-on  souffrir  qu'elles  facilitent  1'evasion  du  crime  et  lui 
servant  en  quelque  fagon  de  barriere  ?  Non.  Les  ordres  rapides  de 
1'administration  dans  ce  moment  vont  au  secours  de  la  juridiction 
elle-meme.  Le  coupable  que  de"signe  la  voix  publique  est  alors 
arrete"  par  le  commandement  du  Prince.  Ce  n'est  point  un  jugement 
qu'il  prononce.  C'est  une  precaution  par  laquelle  il  empeche  que 
ce  jugement  soit  un  jour  inutile.  Mais  cette  meme  autorite"  qui 
a  6t£  au  malfaiteur  le  pouvoir  de  fuir,  le  doit  livrer  aussitot  a  la 
justice,  dont  elle  n'a  fait  que  preVenir  et  faciliter  les  demarches. » 

Mais  la  philosophic  du  XVIII6  siecle,  reprenant  avec  une  force 
nouvelle  la  doctrine  exposed  par  les  Monarchomaques  du  XVIe  siecle, 
proclamait,  comme  une  regie  essentielle  de  1'Etat,  1'empire  absolu 
et  inevitable  de  la  loi.  Je  ne  citerai  qu'un  passage  de  Voltaire,  qui 
dans  un  de  ses  Dialogues  fait  ainsi  parler  un  Anglais  :  «  Ce  que  je 
trouve  de  plus  juste  c'est  liberte  et  proprUte.  .  .  .  Je  veux  que 
chacun  ait  sa  prerogative.  Je  ne  connais  de  lois  que  celles  qui  me 
protegent,  et  je  trouve  notre  gouvernement  le  meilleur  de  la  terre 
parce  que  chacun  y  sait  ce  qu'il  a,  ce  qu'il  doit  et  ce  qu'il  peut.  Tout 
est  soumis  a  la  loi,  a  commencer  par  la  royaut£  et  par  la  religion.  »* 
C'e"tait  une  cause  gagne"e  devant  1'opinion  publique,  et  la  Constitu- 
tion frangaise  de  1791  enregistrait  la  regie  nouvelle  dans  ces  termes, 
d'une  precision  et  d'une  elevation  admirables :  « II  n'y  a  point  en 
France  d'autorite"  superieure  a  celle  de  la  loi.  Le  roi  ne  regne  que  par 
elle,  et  ce  n'est  qu'au  nom  de  la  loi  qu'il  peut  exiger  l'obeissance.»2 

A.  ESMEIN. 


1  DA,  B,  C  ou  Dialogues  entre  A,  B,  C,  traduit  de  1'anglais  de  M.  Huet, 
troisieme  dialogue. 

2  Constitution  du  3  septembre  1791,  tit.  ii.  ch.  2,  sect,  i,  art.  3. 


XI 

I 

TWO   ANCIENT   BROCARDS 

THE  object  of  this  paper  is  to  explain  the  import  and  trace  the 
history,  so  far  as  possible,  of  two  ancient  brocards  familiar  to 
modern  lawyers  and  in  daily  use  in  British  Courts.  The  term 
brocard  (low  Latin  brocarda,  also  brocardica  and  other  forms 1) 
is  mediaeval.  Calvin,  in  his  Lexicon,  says  contemptuously : 
Vocabulum  est  barbarum  in  nostro  eleganti  Jure  Civili ;  relin- 
quendum  igittir  barbaris.  It  means  a  legal  maxim  or  axiom  or 
rule — a  regula  juris.  Brocards  are  rather  apt  to  be  dangerous 
weapons  in  the  armoury  of  lawyers.  They  are  apt  to  represent 
conclusions  based  on  slender  premisses,  or  generalizations  from  an 
inadequate  number  of  particulars,  the  exceptions  to  the  rule  being 
often  more  or  less  disregarded  or  left  out  of  view  in  formulating 
the  rule.  Sometimes  they  have  acted  as  Will-o'-the-wisps  to 
lead  the  Courts  astray  in  their  decisions.  In  his  preface  to  the 
second  edition  of  Barbosa's  Axiomata,  J.  O.  Tabor  discusses 
the  utility  of  collections  of  so-called  loci  communes  and  mentions 
several  noted  jurisconsults  (including  Duarenus  and  Cujacius)  who 
wholly  discountenanced  them.  Plaustra  ista  brocardicorum^  said 
one  old  jurist,  obscurare  sacrosanctam  veritatem  et  cognoscendi 
religionem? 

Nevertheless  brocards  and  maxims  have  a  certain  utility  in 
concentrating  ideas,  stimulating  the  memory,  and  otherwise,  and 
they  have  been  much  employed  both  by  the  classical  jurists  of 
Rome  and  the  great  lawyers  of  the  Middle  Ages. 

1  See  Calvin,  Lexicon  jurid.  and  Du  Cange,  s.v. 

2  Herman  Lather,  de  Cens.  1618,  lib.  2,  c.  3,  Num.  9,  §  60  ;  see  Cujac. 
Epist.  consult,  praefat. 

2-15 


216  H.  Goudy  [xi 

I.  ACTIO  PERSONALIS  MORITUR  CUM  PERSONA 

(a)  Its  Import.  —  General  Observations  on  the  Meaning  of 
Personal  Action  in  English  Law. 

Though  this  is  one  of  the  most  familiar  maxims  of  English 
Law,  the  veil  of  obscurity  covers  not  only  its  origin  but  its  true 
import  and  significance.  It  is  certainly  an  ancient  maxim  ;  the 
late  Lord  Justice  Bowen  claimed  for  it  (though  erroneously,  I 
think)  an  antiquity  as  great  as  that  of  the  English  Common  Law 
itself.1  It  was  not  taken  from  the  Roman  Law  nor  from  any 
mediaeval  civilian ;  indeed  to  a  Roman  lawyer  or  to  a  civilian  it 
would  have  sounded  nonsensical ;  yet  it  has,  as  we  shall  see,  an 
indirect  connexion  with  the  Roman  Law.  Many  cases  in  our 
English  Courts  have  been  decided  on  the  strength  of  it,  and  it  has 
been  the  source  of  not  a  little  injustice.  Though  sometimes  a 
lance  has  been  raised  on  its  behalf,  it  has,  in  my  opinion,  been 
rightly  denounced  by  one  of  our  best  English  lawyers  as  '  a 
barbarous  rule.' 2 

We  may  translate  the  maxim  thus — '  a  personal  right  of  action 
comes  to  an  end  by  the  death  of  either  of  the  parties.'  Now,  first, 
we  must  see  what  is  meant  here  by  personal  action.  The  familiar 
division  of  Roman  Law  into  actions  in  rem  and  in  personam — the 
former  being  vindications  of  property  and  real  rights,  the  latter 
arising  out  of  obligations — was  never  received  into  English  Law. 
On  the  other  hand,  old  English  Common  Law  divided  actions  into 
real  and  personal  in  a  special  and  peculiar  sense :  the  former,  the 
real  actions,  being  those  by  which  rights  to  heritable  property 
(realty)  were  enforced ;  the  latter,  the  personal  actions,  being  those 
by  which  rights  to  moveable  chattels,  choses  in  action,  etc.,  were 
enforced.3  This  division,  old  apparently  as  the  Conquest,  was  due 
to  the  Feudal  Law,  which,  unlike  the  Roman,  made  a  fundamental 
distinction  between  rights  in  lands  and  other  immoveables  and 

1  Phillips  v.  Homfray,  1883,  L.R.  24  Ch.  Div.  439  :   In  Finlay  v.  Chirney^ 
1887,  20  Q.B.  Div.  p.  494,  Bowen  and  Fry,  L.JJ.,  say  of  the  maxim  that  its 
origin  is  '  obscure  and  post-classical.' 

2  Pollock,  Torts,  p.  64. 

8  Mixed  actions  (partly  real  and  partly  personal)  need  not  be  referred  to. 
The  term  realis  actio  is  purely  mediaeval.  The  term  personalis  actio,  in  the 
sense  of  actio  in  personam^  appears  occasionally  in  the  Digest  (e.g.  Dig.  x.  4, 
3  §  3)»  but  it  may  be  due  to  interpolation  of  the  compilers. 


xi]  Two  Ancient  Brocards  217 

rights  in  moveable  or  personal  property.  Real  actions,  however, 
in  the  above  sense  gradually  became  obsolete  and  were  ultimately 
abolished  by  statute,  their  effects  being  obtained  indirectly  by 
personal  actions.  There  is  no  such  thing  as  rei  vindicatio  in 
modern  English  Law. 

Personal  actions  in  English  Law  are,  in  the  words  of  Blackstone, 
'  Such  whereby  a  man  claims  a  debt  or  personal  duty  or  damages 
in  lieu  thereof;  and  likewise  whereby  a  man  claims  a  satisfaction 
in  damages  for  some  injury  done  to  his  person  or  property.  The 
former  are  said  to  be  founded  on  contracts,  the  latter  upon  torts  or 
wrongs.' 1  Now  it  is  in  this  wide  sense  that  actio  personalis  in  our 
brocard  should  be  prima  facie  understood,  but,  as  we  shall  see,  it 
was  never,  from  the  time  it  was  first  formulated,  extended  so  far 
in  practice.  Had  the  maxim  been  taken  literally  the  result  would 
have  been  that  every  right  of  action,  whether  arising  out  of  contract 
or  of  tort  or  other  obligation,  would  have  come  to  an  end  by  the 
death  of  either  party.  A  covenant,  for  instance,  would  have  ceased 
to  be  actionable  by  the  death  of  either  covenantor  or  covenantee  or 
a  contract  of  bailment  by  the  death  of  bailor  or  bailee.  But  an 
examination  of  the  Reports  from  early  times  shows  that  the 
Common  Law  never  went  so  far.  Apart  from  torts,  the  utmost 
that  can  be  said  is  that  the  old  English  Law,  for  a  brief  period, 
refused  to  recognize  the  transmission  passively  of  actions  on 
contract,  and  even  this  can  only  be  admitted  subject  to  exceptions, 
e.g.  actions  on  covenant  under  seal.  But  it  clearly  ceased  to  be 
the  rule  once  a  definite  theory  of  contract  was  developed  and  the 
action  of  assumpsit  established.  When  this  stage  was  reached  we 
find  that,  apart  from  one  or  two  special  contractual  claims  such  as 
the  old  actions  of  Debt  and  Account,2  and  (later)  the  action  of 
breach  of  promise  of  marriage,  actions  on  contract  survived  ab 
utraque  parte,  and  non-transmissibility  on  death  became  restricted 
in  practice  to  actions  based  on  tort  or  on  facts  analogous  to  tort. 
In  other  words,  non-transmissibility  applied  as  a  rule  only  to 
actions  for  reparation  of  damages  for  injuries  and  penalties  for 
wrongful  acts.  As  is  said  in  Dyer's  Reports,  *  actio  personalis 

1  Bl.  Com.  iii.  p.  117. 

2  I.e.  as  regards   passive   liability  of  executors.     The  action  of  account 
seems  not  to  have  transmitted  against  executors.     See  Bacon,  Abridgment, 
ii.  p.  444;  Holdsworth,  Hist,  of  English  Law,  iii.  p.  455. 


2i8  H.  Goiidy  [xi 

quae  oritur  ex  contfactu  dieth  not,  yet  quae  oritur  ex  delicto 
moritur  cum  persona,  as  all  trespasses.'1  This  suggests  that  our 
maxim  was  originally  deduced  from  a  misunderstanding  of  the 
Roman  Law  and,  before  going  further,  it  may  be  useful  to  state 
here  very  briefly  what  the  rules  of  that  Law  were  on  transmissibility 
of  actions  on  death. 

(b)  Transmissibility  of  Actions  on  Death  by  Roman  Law. 

As  is  well  known,  a  material  difference  existed  from  a  pretty 
early  period  in  Roman  Law  between  contracts  on  the  one  hand 
and  delicts  on  the  other  as  regards  transmission  of  actions  to  and 
against  the  heirs  of  the  parties.  In  contracts  the  right  of  action 
almost  invariably  transmitted  both  to  the  heirs  of  the  creditor  and 
against  the  heirs  of  the  debtor ;  in  delicts  transmission  depended 
largely  upon  whether  the  action  was  of  a  penal  nature  or  not.  If 
it  were  poenalis  the  general  rule  was  that  it  transmitted  to  the  heirs 
of  the  injured  party  (i.e.  actively)  but  not  against  the  heirs  of  the 
wrongdoer  (i.e.  passively).  The  maxim  was  actio  poenalis  transit 
heredibus  sed  non  transit  in  heredes?  The  actio  fur ti,  for  example, 
could  be  brought  by  the  heirs  of  the  injured  party  against  the  thief 
but  not  by  the  injured  party  against  the  heirs  of  the  thief.  Where, 
on  the  other  hand,  a  delictal  action  was  not  strictly  penal — e.g.  the 
actio  doli — it  transmitted  both  actively  and  passively,  except  that 
as  a  rule  passive  transmission  was  only  allowed  so  far  as  the 
deceased's  heir  had  received  benefit  from  the  wrong.3 

But  to  the  rule  actio  poenalis  transit  heredi  sed  non  in  heredem 
there  were  several  well-known  exceptions  of  much  importance.  To 
the  first  part  of  the  maxim — viz.  transit  heredi — I  remind  you  of 
the  two  following  : — 

1st. — Injury  to  a  freeman  which  caused  his  death  gave  no  right 
of  action  to  his  heirs  for  damages  either  in  factum  under  the  lex 
Aquilia  or  otherwise.  The  reason  for  this  usually  given  by  the 
jurists  was  that  no  money-value  can  be  put  on  the  life  of  a  free- 
man :  liberum  corpus  nullam  recipit  aestimationem.^  To  this  harsh 
rule  the  Roman  Law  steadily  adhered  down  to  Justinian ;  the 
jurists  were  apparently  obsessed  by  the  idea  that  the  person  of  a 

1  Dyer's  Rep.  271,  143.. 

2  Dig.  xlvii.  i,  i  ;  Gaius,  Com.  iv.  112. 

3  On   the   extent  of  this  exception  the  Roman  texts  are  not  altogether 
consistent.  4  Dig.  ix.  3,  3  ;  ix.  3,  i  §  5  ;  cf.  Dig.  ix.  2,  13  pr. 


xi]  Two  Ancient  Brocards  219 

freeman  had  no  money-value  and  that  there  could  be  no  patri- 
monial loss  to  a  man's  family  where  the  injury  to  himself  could 
not  be  estimated.  This  has  also  always  been  the  rule  of  English 
Common  Law,  based  on  our  brocard,  though,  as  we  shall  see  in  a 
moment,  it  has  been  considerably  modified  by  modern  statutes. 

2nd  Exception. — Injury  to  a  man's  person  or  reputation  done 
wilfully,  as  by  assault,  slander,  etc.,  gave  no  right  of  action  to  his 
heirs.  In  short,  the  actio  injuriarum  and  a  few  similar  actions  did 
not  transmit  at  all.  The  principal  reason  given  by  the  jurists  for 
this  exception  was  that  the  object  of  such  actions  was  more  one 
of  revenge  than  of  reparation — far  from  a  satisfactory  reason  once 
pecuniary  compensation  had  taken  the  place  of  self-revenge.  It 
and  the  other  actively  intransmissible  actions  of  a  similar  character 
in  the  classical  law  were  called  actions  vindictam  spirantesl 

On  the  other  hand,  to  the  second  part  of  the  maxim — viz.  non 
transit  in  heredem — an  important  exception  occurred  in  penal 
actions  for  injuries  to  property ',  in  which  it  could  be  shown  that  the 
estate  of  the  deceased  tort-feasor  had  received  benefit  from  the 
delict  committed.  The  injured  party  was  allowed  in  such  case 
(just  as  I  have  said  in  the  case  of  non-penal  actions  based  on 
delict)  to  sue  the  heirs  of  the  tort-feasor  in  quantum  lucrati  sunt? 
The  actio  legis  Aquiliae  is  a  well-known  example.2 

Finally — all  actions  ex  delicto,  whether  penal  or  not,  transmitted 
both  to  and  against  heirs,  if  the  suit  had  already  begun  in  the  life- 
time of  the  principal  parties.  This  was  on  the  theory  of  litis  con- 
testation having  created  a  judicial  contract  between  the  parties  : 
Litis  contestatione  poenales  actiones  transmit  tuntur  ab  utraque 
parte? 

Such,  then,  broadly  stated,  were  the  rules  of  the  Roman  Law 
as  regards  transmissibility  of  actions  ex  delicto. 

(c)   Transmissibility  of  Actions  on  Death  by  English  Law. 

The  English  Common  Law  from  early  times  proceeded  to  a 
large  extent  on  different  lines  from  these  doctrines  of  the  Roman 
jurists.  I  have  already  broadly  indicated  how  far  it  held  actions 
to  enforce  simple  contracts  to  be  extinguished  by  death  of  either 
party ;  and  for  the  moment  I  leave  contracts  aside.  Apart  from 

1  E.g.  '  querela  inofficiosi  testament!.3      See  Gaius  iv.  112;  Dig.  iii.  6,  4. 

2  Dig.\.  17,  38;  ix.  23  §8. 

3  Dig.  xxvii.  7,  8  §  i. 


22o  H.  Goudy  [xi 

contracts,  English  Common  Law  has,  as  a  rule,  treated  death  of 
either  party  as  sufficient  to  bar  all  action  on  tort  both  by  and 
against  executors.  And  whether  the  plaintiff  was  seeking  damages 
by  way  of  penalty  or  as  simple  reparation  or  otherwise,  and 
whether  the  action  had  been  already  begun  during  the  lifetime  of 
the  principal  parties  or  not,  made  no  difference.  To  this  latter 
point  I  will  recur  in  a  moment.  The  only  Common  Law  excep- 
tion to  the  rule  was  that  property  positively  appropriated  by  a 
deceased  tort-feasor  to  his  benefit,  or  its  value,  could  be  recovered 
from  his  executors  by  an  action  which  was  substantially  one  for 
recovery  of  property.  In  other  words,  passive  liability  of  executors 
was  recognized  where  the  deceased's  estate  had  been  enriched  by 
the  wrong.1  This  Common-Law  bar  to  right  of  action  on  tort  by 
death  of  either  party  often  proved  very  inequitable,  especially  in 
cases  of  damage  to  property,  and  certain  remedies  were  gradually, 
though  tardily,  supplied  by  statute.  The  first  remedial  step  was 
indeed  taken  pretty  early,  viz.  by  4  Edward  III  cap.  7,  which 
enacted  that  for  trespass  done  to  a  man's  goods  and  chattels 
during  his  lifetime  his  executors  might  sue.  This  statute,  though 
liberally  construed,  did  not  go  far,  being  limited  to  active  trans- 
missibility  and  to  personal  property.  But  nearly  five  centuries 
had  to  elapse  before  a  wider  step  in  the  same  direction  was  taken, 
viz.  by  3  and  4  William  IV  cap.  42.  This  Act,  in  the  first  place, 
made  actions  for  wrongful  damage  to  real  property  transmissible 
to  personal  representatives  of  the  injured  party,  just  as  the  Act  of 
Edward  had  done  for  personal  property,  but  subject  to  the  con- 
dition that  the  damage  had  been  done  within  six  months  prior  to 
the  death  and  that  the  action  was  begun  within  twelve  months 
after  the  death.  In  the  second  place  it  sanctioned  passive  trans- 
missibility  by  providing  that  the  personal  representatives  of  one 
who  had  caused  wrongful  damage  to  property,  whether  real  or 
personal,  of  another  should  be  liable  by  action  of  trespass  or  tres- 
pass on  the  case  to  the  extent  of  his  assets,  but  subject  always  to 
similar  limitations  as  to  time  of  injury  and  of  raising  action. 

The  practical  effect  of  these  statutes  of  Edward  and  William 
was  to  put  the  English  Law  (as  regards  transmission  on  death  of 
actions  for  damage  to  property)  on  pretty  nearly  the  'same  footing 

1  See  Phillips  v.  Homfray,  supra,  per  Bowen,  LJ.;  Holdsworth,  Hist. 
E.  L.  iii.  455. 


XI] 


Two  Ancient  Brocards 


221 


as  the  Roman  Law  on  the  subject,  apart  from  the  just-mentioned 
limitations  of  time.1  One  great  difference  was  left  unaltered,  viz. 
the  effect  of  action  begun  ante  mortem.  While  by  Roman  Law,  as 
we  have  seen,  litis  contestation  ensured  transmissibility  of  the 
action  to  the  heirs  in  every  case,  English  Common  Law  gave  no 
effect  to  it.  If,  after  an  action  on  tort  has  been  competently 
brought,  one  of  the  parties  dies,  the  action  abates  by  English  Law 
in  accordance  with  our  brocard,  and  does  not  pass  to  or  against 
his  personal  representatives.  Despite  some  slight  attenuations 
introduced  into  modern  practice,2  the  rule  remains  as  stated. 
This  is  strongly  illustrated  by  the  case  of  Bowker  v.  Evans,  in 
1885,  where  an  action  on  tort  having  been  referred  by  the  judge 
to  arbitration,  in  accordance  with  previous  agreement  of  parties, 
and  one  of  the  parties  having  died  while  the  arbitration  was  pend- 
ing, his  executor  was  not  allowed  to  take  his  place,  although  it 
had  been  expressly  stipulated  by  the  parties  that  the  award  should 
take  effect  though  either  party  died  before  it  was  issued.3  It 
seems  impossible  to  justify  this  in  equity  or  good  sense.4 

The  statutes  of  Edward  and  William  just  mentioned  relate,  it 
will  be  noticed,  solely  to  injuries  to  property.5  For  injuries  to 
person,  on  the  other  hand,  little  change  was  made  by  legislation. 
One  or  two  recent  statutes,  however,  have  caused  English  Law  in 
one  respect  to  make  a  step  in  advance  of  the  Roman,  viz.  by 
allowing  actions  of  damages  to  be  brought  under  certain  circum- 
stances by  the  personal  representatives  of  persons  killed  by  fault 
(actual  or  constructive)  of  others.  This  was  first  done  in  1846  by 
the  Fatal  Accidents  Act  (commonly  called,  after  its  author,  Lord 

1  Equity  in  this  matter  follows  the  law.      See  Peek  v.  Gurney,  1873,  6 
H.L.  App.  393. 

2  See  Twy  cross  v.  Grant,  1878,  4  C.P.D.  40.      But  see  note  4  infra. 

3  15  Q.B.D.  565.     The  agreement  for  reference  to  arbitration  was  held 
to  be  mere  matter  of  procedure,  which  could  not  affect  the  rights  of  parties 
under  the  action. 

4  Oddly  enough,  in  a  marginal  note  to  some  MSS.  of  Bracton,  fol.  U4b 
(which  cannot  be  well  attributed  to  B.  himself),  it  is  said  :   '  Notandum  quod 
poenalis  actio  non  datur  in  heredes  nee  transit  in  eos  nisi  lis  fuerit  contestata 
cum  defuncto.'      See  Maitland,  Bracton  and  Azo  (Selden  Series),  p.  213. 

5  It  should  be  noticed  that  while  the  Roman  Law  only  allowed  damages 
to  be  claimed  from  heredes,  so  far  as  they  were  lucrati  by  the  wrongful  act, 
English  Law  under  3  and  4  Wm.  IV  allows  action  for  injury  to  property,  if 
timeously  brought,  to  have  effect  so  far  as  the  deceased  left  assets.     This  is 
in  accordance  with  Canon  Law  and  mediaeval  practice.     See  infra^  p.  228  n.  i. 


222  H.  Goudy  [xi 

Campbell's  Act),1  which  enabled  children  and  certain  other  near 
relatives  of  persons  killed  to  recover  through  the  executors  (under 
certain  conditions  as  to  time  of  raising  action,  etc.)  damages 
for  pecuniary  loss  thereby  sustained  by  them.  Subsequently  the 
Employers  Liability  Act  enabled  executors  of  certain  employees 
to  sue  where  death  was  caused  by  injuries  specified  in  the  Act.2 
This  is  a  more  enlightened  view  than  is  contained  in  the  Roman 
maxim  liberum  corpus  nullam  recipit  aestimationem. 

But  these  several  statutory  reforms,  important  though  they 
are,  do  not  after  all  go  very  far.  The  Common  Law  still  remains 
in  force  as  regards  ordinary  actions  on  tort,  and  so  far  actio  personalia 
moritur  cum  persona  retains  its  force  as  a  binding  maxim. 

(a7)   Traces  of  Origin  of  Brocard. 

I  shall  now  endeavour  to  trace  the  origin  of  our  brocard.  We 
have  seen  that  it  is  not  Roman  ;  neither  is  it  traceable  to  any  of  the 
post-Justinian  civilians  or  to  the  Corpus  Juris  Canonici.  We  must, 
I  think,  turn  in  the  first  place  to  Bracton.  The  maxim  indeed  is 
not  to  be  found  in  his  pages,  but  he  may  be  none  the  less  its  fons 
et  origo.  Bracton,  who  wrote  his  De  Legibus  et  Consuetudinibus 
Angliae  in  the  middle  of  the  thirteenth  century,  borrowed,  as  is  well 
known,  a  large  amount  of  his  matter  (not  purely  feudal)  from  the 
Roman  Law.  He  did  so  in  part  (but  only  in  small  part)  from  the 
texts  of  the  Corpus  Juris  directly,  but  to  a  large  extent,  as  Dr. 
Carl  Giiterbock  pointed  out  long  ago,  from  the  Summa  of  the  Code 
and  Institutes  of  the  famous  glossarist  Azo.  Now,  in  dealing  with 
obligations,  which  he  does  under  the  general  head  of  actions,  he 
says  this  about  the  modes  of  their  extinction  (fol.  101):  Item 
tollitur  \pbligatio\  morte  alterius  contrahentium,  vel  utriusque> 
maxime  si  sit  poenalis ,  vel  simplex — si  autem  duple  x,  scilicet 
poenalis  et  rei  persecutoriae^  in  hoc  quod  poenalis  est  tollitur ;  et  non 
extenditur  contra  heredes,  nee  datur  heredibusy  quia  poena  tenet  suos 
auctores  et  extinguitur  cum  persona,  i.e.  an  obligation  is  '  also 
got  rid  of  by  the  death  of  either  of  the  contracting  parties  or  of 
both,  especially  if  it  is  a  penal  obligation  or  a  simple  one ;  but  if 
it  be  a  double  one,  namely  penal  and  for  recovery,  it  is  got  rid  of 
as  far  as  it  is  penal  and  it  does  not  extend  to  the  heirs,  nor  is  it 

1  9  and  10  Viet.  c.  93,  ss.  I,  2. 

2  43  and  44  Viet.  c.  42,  s.  i.     See  also  Workmen's  Compensation  Act 
(1906),  s.  13. 


xi]  Two  Ancient  Brocards  223 

allowed  to  the  heirs,  because  a  penalty  binds  the  original  parties 
and  is  extinguished  with  the  person.' l  This  is  wholly  confused. 
It  is  evident  that  in  seeking  to  apply  the  Roman  doctrine  on  this 
matter  to  English  Law  (and  he  is  plainly  not  stating  existing  English 
rules)  he  has  failed  to  distinguish  between  obligatio  and  actio.  As 
I  have  said,  he  treats  the  doctrine  of  obligations  under  the  head  of 
actions  (which  in  itself  is  not  without  justification,  as  we  know 
from  Theophilus) ;  but  he  mixes  them  up  in  a  strange  way.  The 
whole  section  about  the  dissolution  of  obligations  has  been  taken, 
as  Maitland  points  out,2  in  part  from  Azo's  Commentary  on  Inst. 
iii.  29  (Quibus  modis  obligatio  dissolvitur)  and  in  part  from  the 
Institutes  directly.  But  the  passage  I  have  just  cited  is  not  in  Azo, 
nor  anything  like  it,  much  less  in  the  Institutes •,  and  is,  I  need 
hardly  say,  very  far  from  representing  Roman  Law.  Whether  it  is 
Bracton's  own  or  was  taken  by  him  from  some  other  source,  I  am 
unable  to  say.  It  looks  like  his  own.3  What  Bracton  may  perhaps 
have  had  before  his  mind  in  composing  it  was  contracts  of  a  penal 
character,  i.e.  contracts  in  which  non-performance  was  treated  as 
delictal  and  punished  by  a  penalty  or  amercement  (e.g.  the  action 
of  debt).  Nearly  all  contracts  seem  to  have  been  of  this  character 
in  his  age ;  they  were,  with  few  exceptions  (as  where  made  in 
writing  by  solemn  form,  or  perhaps  where  there  was  res  data\ 
enforceable  only  by  actions  of  a  delictal  character.  Contracts 
and  torts  were,  in  short,  hardly  distinguished.  The  fact  is — one 
cannot  dispute  it — that,  great  as  were  Bracton's  merits  in  other 
respects,  his  knowledge  of  Roman  Law  was  utterly  defective.  In 
appropriating  passages  from  the  Corpus  Juris  and  from  Azo,  he 
over  and  over  again  fails  to  understand  them,  makes  the  most 
bewildering  statements,  and  is  not  seldom  self-contradictory.  This 
must  be  said  even  in  view  of  Professor  Maitland's  warning  about 
possible  defects  in  the  manuscripts.4  As  glaring  illustrations  of 
such  blunders,  I  may  be  permitted  to  refer  to  one  or  two  other 
passages  in  addition  to  the  one  cited.  Thus  in  the  same  section  as 

1  Edition  of  Twiss,  ii.  p.  123.      Cited  by  Bowen,  L.J.,  in  Finlay  v.  Chirney^ 
supra,  p.  216  n. 

2  Bracton  and  Azo  (Selden  Series),  p.  162. 

3  '  Culpa  tenet  suos  auctores'  is  in  Code  De  Poem's,  1.  24.     That  Bracton 
borrowed  from  some  other  civilian  than  Azo  is  very  probable  ;  who  this  was 
remains  to  be  discovered. 

4  Bracton  and  Azo  (Selden  Series),  p.  xvii. 


224  H*  Goudy  [xi 

the  above  he  explains  the  dissolution  of  obligations  confusione  in 
this  way :  Item  per  confusionem  \pbligatio  tollitur\  ut  si  massa 
confusa  fuerit  cum  alia,  ita  quod  non  appareat,  here  understanding 
confusio  in  the  sense  it  has  in  the  doctrine  of  property — mixture  of 
different  materials.  Again,  on  folio  99b,  he  applies  a  sentence  in 
Justinian's  Institutes,  iii.  14,  which  relates  to  mutuum  to  the 
contract  of  commodatum,  so  as  to  make  the  commodo  accipiens 
liable  for  injury  to  the  thing  by  casus,  though  a  little  farther  on  he 
negatives  such  liability.  Attempts  have  been  made  to  rectify  this 
passage  as  a  MS.  error,  but  to  me  it  appears  an  evident  blunder 
due  to  want  of  knowledge.  Again,  on  folio  102,  he  treats  actions 
rei  persequendae  causa  as  equivalent  to  actions  in  rem  and  says : 
Omnes  fere  personates  actiones  sunt  ex  contractu,  sicut  mutui 
commodati,  etc.,  obviously  misunderstanding  the  passage  in  the 
Institutes,  iv.  6,  §  17,  which  runs :  Earum  vero  actionum  quae  in 
personam  sunt,  hae  quidem  quae  ex  contractu  nascuntur  fere 
omnes  rei  persequendae  causa  videntur.  But  it  is  needless  to 
multiply  examples ;  they  abound.1  In  view  of  what  I  have  just 
said,  it  is  impossible  to  be  sure  of  what  Bracton  intended  in  the 
passage  above  cited,  asserting  that  contracts  perished  by  the  death 
of  either  of  the  contracting  parties.  I  think  he  probably  meant  no 
more  than  that  contracts  were  so  dissolved  in  which  non-performance 
was  treated  as  delictal  and  amercement  or  fine  followed  judgment 
(e.g.  Action  of  Debt),  because  he  says  later,  fol.  102  :  Personates 
vero  actiones  .  .  .  locum  habent  adversus  eum  qui  contraxit  et 
heredem  suum,  nisi  sint  poenales?  But,  whatever  he  meant, 
his  statement  was  copied  by  Fleta,3  and  to  some  extent  influenced 

1  These  and  other  instances  have  been  noted  by  Maitland  in  Bracton  and 
Azo,  supra.     A  specially  glaring  case  is  iii.  3,  §  9,  fol.  1030,  which  Maitland 
describes  as  a  '  marvellous  mess.' 

Where  Azo  (or  his  MS.)  is  wrong  Bracton  follows  him — e.g.  compare  Azo 
in  Inst.  ii.  i,  f.  244,  No.  7  with  Bracton  ii.  I,  §  2,  where  both  use  apprehen- 
sionem  apparently  for  aucupium  and  misunderstand  Dig.  xli.  I,  55.  Did 
Bracton  in  his  constant  slight  changes  in  the  phraseology  of  Azo  (e.g.  substitut- 
ing Sempronius  for  Seius  and  Maenius  for  Maevius)  intend  to  compound  with 
his  conscience  for  plagiarizing  him  ? 

2  See  also  folio  loib,  where,  dealing  specially  with  delictual  actions,  he 
says  :  '  In  iis  autem  delictis  sive  maleficiis  obligatur  ille  qui  delinquit  ei  contra 
quern  delinquitur,  nee  dissolvitur  obligatio  quoad poenam  nisi  morte  utriusque 
vel  alterius.' 

3  ii.  60,  §  9.     The  extent  of  the  influence  of  Bracton  on  the  Common  Law 


XI] 


Two  Ancient  Brocards 


225 


the  Courts,  so  that  for  a  time  apparently  nearly  all  personal  actions 
(whether  on  contract  or  delict)  were  held  to  be  intransmissible 
(either  actively  or  passively)  on  death  of  one  of  the  parties,  though, 
as  already  indicated,  this  soon  became  restricted  to  actions  on  tort. 
But  however  this  be,  in  the  Year  Books  after  Edward  I  there  is 
little  evidence  that  an  action  purely  on  contract  was  intransmissible 
either  to  or  against  executors,  apart  from  the  passive  intransmissi- 
bility  of  actions  of  Debt  and  Account  already  mentioned.  The  law, 
however,  was  anything  but  settled.  The  Report  in  Y.B.  15,  Ed.  IV 
Term.  Hill.  16,  3,  bears  that  in  certain  cases  an  action  for  debt  did  not 
lie  against  an  executor  of  a  testator,  for  the  reason  that  the  testator 
might  have  waged  his  law,  which  executors  could  not  do.1  Most,  if 
not  all,  other  cases  in  the  Year  Books  in  which  transmission  was 
not  allowed  (so  far  at  least  as  text-writers  have  noticed  them)  were 
in  form  actions  for  damages  to  person  and  property  (e.g.  actions  of 
waste  and  trespass).  In  Y.B.  19  Hen.  VI  66,  pi.  10  (A.D.  1440) 
(an  action  by  churchwardens  for  things  carried  off  from  a  church), 
Chief  Justice  Newton  said,  *  If  one  doeth  a  trespass  to  me  and 
dieth,  the  action  is  dead  also,  because  it  should  be  inconvenient  to 
recover  against  one  who  was  not  a  party  to  the  wrong.'  It  is 
curious,  however,  that  we  do  not  find  our  maxim,  actio  personalis 
moritur,  cited  in  the  Year  Books  anywhere.  It  is  said  indeed  by 
Reeves  to  have  been  employed  in  Y.B.  12  Hen.  VIII.2  This  Report 
is  interesting.  It  was  an  action  on  the  case  brought  by  executors 
to  enforce  a  personal  promise  of  guarantee,  and  the  Court  was 
unanimous  in  holding  the  action  competent.  Fineux,  Chief  Justice, 
said — and  his  words  deserve  attention — *  This  is  not  a  case  where 
actio  moritur  cum  persona,  for  that  only  applied  where  the  hurt  or 
damage  is  corporal  ;  as  if  one  beats  me,  and  dies,  my  action  is 
gone  ;  or  if  I  die,  my  executors  will  not  have  an  action,  for  the 
party  cannot  be  punished  when  he  is  dead.'  This  means,  I  take  it, 
that  in  the  opinion  of  the  Chief  Justice  it  was  only  penal  actions 
that  were  terminated  by  death  of  party.  But  Reeves 3  apparently 
makes  a  mistake  in  attributing  to  the  Chief  Justice  the  words  actio 
personalis  moritur  \  the  words  of  the  Report  in  the  black-letter 

is  much  disputed.     It  may  be  perhaps  compared  to  that  of  Craig  (Jus  Feudale) 
in  Scots  Law. 

1  See  also  Bacon,  Abr.  s.v.  Executors,  ii.  p.  444. 

2  Fol.  n,  pi.  3.  8  History  of  English  Law^  iii.  p.  403. 

Q 


226  H.  Goudy  [xi 

edition  of  the  Year  Books  are  simply  actio  moritur  cum  persona, 
and  there  seems  no  reason  for  supplying  the  word  personalis  rather 
than  poenalis. 

The  decision  in  this  case  of  12  Henry  VIII  is  subsequently 
denounced  by  Fitzherbert  in  an  opinion  delivered  by  him  in  the 
year  1536  and  reported  in  the  Year  Book  27  Henry  VIII,  fol.  23. 
Though  this  eminent  judge  does  not  cite  our  maxim,  he  expressly 
declares  that  the  last-mentioned  decision  was  bad  law,  telling  us  at 
the  same  time  that  he  himself  had  been  counsel  for  one  of  the 
parties  in  it.  It  is  difficult  to  avoid  the  conclusion  that  Fitzherbert 
took  the  view  that  personal  actions  generally  (whether  on  contract 
or  on  tort)  did  not  transmit  at  Common  Law  either  to  or  against 
executors.  No  reason  is  reported  to  have  been  given  by  him  ;  and, 
though  his  opinion  may  have  governed  the  practice  of  the  Courts 
for  a  time,1  the  question  was  soon  after  settled  by  the  case  of 
Norwood  v.  Rezdz  and  that  of  Pinchon,  tempore  James  I  (1609), 
reported  by  Coke.3  The  latter  of  these  was  an  action  on  Contract 
(as  sump  sit) ;  and  here  for  the  first  time,  so  far  as  I  have  been 
able  to  discover,  the  phrase  actio  personalis  moritur  cum  persona 
was  judicially  used.  Perhaps  Coke  himself  invented  it.  In 
Pinchon's  case  the  Court  disregarded  the  opinion  of  Fitzherbert 
and  in  effect  followed  the  earlier  judgment  in  12  Henry  VIII, 
above  cited.  After  this,  our  maxim  seems  to  have  become 
common  in  practice,  but,  save  in  the  old  action  of  Debt  and  the 
modern  action  for  breach  of  promise  of  marriage,  it  never  received 
any  effect  in  actions  on  contract  or  quasi-contract.  Its  currency 
in  the  Law  Courts  after  Elizabeth  is  undoubted.  It  appears  in 
Noy's  Grounds  and  Maxims  of  the  English  Lawsf  first  published 
in  1640.  Noy,  who  was  Attorney-General  under  Charles  I,  seems 
to  have  understood  the  maxim  in  its  literal  sense  as  applicable 
to  contractual  as  well  as  delictual  obligations.  As  a  legal 
writer,  however,  he  is  of  little  authority.  What  is  rather  inter- 
esting is  that  in  the  fifth  edition  of  this  book,  published  with 
notes  and  additions  in  1757,  Bacon  is  referred  to  as  authority  for 
the  maxim.  Now  Lord  Bacon  did  write  a  small  work  on  legal 
maxims.  It  is  styled  Rules  and  Maximes  of  the  Common  Lawes  of 
England,  and  was  dedicated  to  Queen  Elizabeth.  It  was  not 

1  Reeves,  ut  supra.  2  Plowd.  p.  180. 

3  9  Rep.  86b.  4  Noy,  6th  ed.  1794,  Maxim  14. 


xi]  Two  Ancient  Brocards  227 

published,  however,  till  1630.  When  we  turn  to  this  work  we  find 
that  Bacon  does  not  include  actio  personalis  moritur  among  his 
collected  maxims,  nor  does  he  make  the  mistake  of  using  that 
expression  at  all.  But,  oddly  enough,  he  does  give  incidentally  a 
maxim  which  differs  by  only  one  word  from  Noy's,  viz.  actio 
injuriarum  moritur  cum  persona,  and  it  is  to  this  presumably  that 
Noy's  editor  refers.  Now,  this  maxim  of  Bacon,  if  taken  in  its 
literal  sense,  would,  as  I  have  shown,  quite  accurately  represent  the 
Roman  Law.  But  unfortunately  Bacon  misunderstands,  on  his  part, 
the  meaning  of  actio  injuriarum — showing  that  his  knowledge  of 
Roman  Law  must  have  been  very  slight.  He  applies  it  to  damage 
to  property — viz.  waste  by  a  tenant  for  years,  thus  failing  to 
distinguish  between  injuria  as  a  personal  wrong  and  injury  to 
property  or  damnum  injuria  datum. 

Such,  then,  is  the  early  history  of  our  maxim.  If  I  am  right  in 
my  reading  of  the  authorities,  I  think  it  came  into  our  law  owing 
to  the  misunderstanding  by  Bracton  of  the  Roman  Law,  his 
inaccurate  use  of  its  language,  and  the  consequently  erroneous 
doctrine  adopted  by  Fitzherbert  and  others.  We  can  see  from 
the  older  cases  cited  in  Bacon's  Abridgment  how  fluctuating 
and  diverse  were  the  applications  of  the  maxim  in  practice. 
It  has  been  suggested  that  the  expression  actio  personalis 
is  merely  a  mistake  for  actio  poenalis,  due  originally  to  some 
careless  manuscript  copyist.1  But  in  view  of  the  language  of 
Bracton  and  Fitzherbert  this  conjecture  may  be  discarded.  Nor 
of  course,  as  we  have  seen,  would  actio  poenalis  moritur  cum 
persona  be  at  all  correct  for  Roman  Law. 

(e)  Its  Application  in  Scots  Law. 

Till  quite  recent  times  our  brocard  was  unknown  to  Scots  Law. 
It  is  nowhere  referred  to  by  the  great  Scotch  institutional  writers, 
such  as  Stair  and  Erskine,  nor  does  it  appear  in  any  of  the  Reports 
of  Cases  prior  to  the  nineteenth  century.  It  has  indeed  crept  into 
the  terminology  of  the  Courts  in  some  recent  decisions,  but  without 
being,  in  my  opinion,  properly  appreciated — an  exotic  borrowed 
from  English  Law.  Speaking  generally,  both  as  regards  active  and 
passive  transmission  of  penal  actions  (i.e.  actions  for  damages  in 
excess  of  bare  reparation),  Scots  Law  has  for  the  most  part  followed 
the  Roman,  but  in  part  the  Canon  Law.  Thus  for  passive  survival 
1  See  B.  Abridg.  ii.  pp.  444-5. 


228  H.  Goudy  [xi 

the  rule  of  the  Canon  Law  is  applied,  and  personal  representatives 
are  liable  only  so  far  as  deceased  left  assets.1  On  the  other  hand, 
as  regards  the  effect  of  litis  contestation  or  pendency  of  suit  at 
death  of  either  the  wrongdoer  or  the  injured  party,  Scots  Law 
follows  the  rule  of  the  Corpus  Juris?  Nevertheless  in  one  or  two 
respects,  and  particularly  as  regards  transmission  to  representatives 
of  the  injured  party,  Scots  Law  has  varied  from  the  Roman  rather 
remarkably.  It  has  done  so,  in  my  opinion,  on  grounds  of  logic 
and  good  sense.  Thus  actions  for  personal  injury,  corresponding 
to  the  actio  injuriarum,  seem  not  to  have  been  in  older  Scots  Law 
barred  as  vindictam  spir antes  or  on  other  grounds,  but  were  held 
transmissible  actively  to  the  executors  of  the  injured  party.  Such 
at  least  was  decided  in  1874  in  an  action  of  slander  raised  by  an 
executrix  of  the  person  alleged  to  be  slandered,  in  which  the 
early  authorities  were  all  carefully  considered.3  The  executrix 
averred  that  patrimonial  damage  had  been  caused  to  the  deceased 
by  the  slander,  and  the  action  was  held  to  be  competent.  It  must, 
however,  be  admitted  that  in  one  or  two  recent  cases  of  a  similar 
nature  the  trend  of  judicial  decision  has  been  unfortunately  to 
depart  from  this  doctrine  and  accept,  as  regards  personal  injuries, 
our  English  brocard  to  a  considerable  extent.  The  doctrine  on 
this  point  seems  hardly  settled.4 

Further  the  law  of  Scotland,  by  long  and  well-established 
custom,  allows  the  near  relatives  of  persons  who  have  been  killed 
wilfully  or  negligently  to  sue  the  wrongdoer  for  damages — such 
damages  including  not  only  patrimonial  loss  but  also  solatium  for 
mental  distress.  Only  near  relatives,  however,  who  are  in  the 

1  Davidson  v.    Tulloch,    1860,  3   Macq.  783.      Canon  Law  allowed  trans- 
mission against    executors,    but    only  so    far    as    the    deceased's    estate  was 
available.     This  was  a  consequence  doubtless  of  the  limited  representation  by 
personal  representatives  in  that  system,  but  was  based  on  religious  grounds. 
See  Savigny,  System,  v.  §  211  ;  and  infra,  p.  229  n.  3. 

2  Neilson  v.  Rodger ;  16  D.  325  ;    Wood  v.  Gray,  19  Ret.  (H.L.)  31. 

3  Auld  v.   Shairp,   1874,  2   Ret.  pp.   199,  940.      In  this  case  Moncrieff, 
J.C.,  seems  to  speak  of 'actio  personalis  moritur'  as  a  Roman  maxim,  and 
fails  to  distinguish  between  personalis  and  poenalis. 

4  See  General  Bill  Posting  Co.  v.   Yonde,  1910,  S.C.  934,  and  cases  there 
cited.     The  case  of  Bern's  Executor,   1893,  2O  Ret-   859>  where  the  Court 
refused  an  action  to  the  executor  of  a  deceased  lunatic  for  injuries  done  to  the 
lunatic,  causing  patrimonial  damage,  was,  in  my  opinion,  a  retrograde  step. 
See  criticism  by  Mr.  R.   M.  Williamson  in  L.Q.R.  x.  p.   182,  with  which  I 
agree. 


xi]  Two  Ancient  Brocards  229 

position  of  dependents  on  the  deceased,  can  sue,  at  least  where 
death  has  been  instantaneous.  They  sue  in  their  own  right  and 
not  in  any  representative  capacity.1  So  far,  then,  Scots  Law 
has  disregarded  the  Roman  maxim,  liberum  corpus  nullam  recipit 
aestimationem.  The  doctrine  is  one  peculiar  to  Scotland,  and  was 
judicially  admitted  many  centuries  ago  in  the  action  of  so-called 
assythment  or  kinbuit  by  which  the  near  relatives  of  a  murdered 
man  could  recover  under  certain  conditions  pecuniary  damages 
from  his  murderer.2  This  action  of  assythment  is  now  in  desuetude, 
but  an  ordinary  action  for  damages  for  fatal  injury  due  to  fault  can 
always  be  brought.  Lord  Campbell's  Act  had  no  application  to 
Scotland,  and  was  never  needed  there. 

In  my  judgment  these  variations  of  Scots  Law  from  both  the 
Roman  and  English  Law  are  based  on  sound  principles  of  equity. 
There  is  no  sufficient  reason  why  the  representatives  of  a  deceased 
person  to  whom  personal  wrong  has  been  done  should  not  have  a 
right  to  damages  which  such  person  would  have  been  able  to 
enforce  had  he  lived.  It  is  a  civil  debt  which  should  transmit  like 
other  debts.  In  short,  there  is  no  good  reason  why  a  deceased's 
estate,  if  he  leaves  assets,  should  not  be  held  liable  for  every  kind 
of  injury  done  by  him  causing  damage  to  another,  and  that 
whether  the  estate  was  positively  enriched  by  the  wrongful  act  or 
not.3 

II.    CUJUS  EST   SOLUM   EJUS    EST    USQUE  AD   COELUM 

This  brocard  may  be  translated,  '  He  who  owns  land  owns 
also  that  which  is  above  it,'  or,  more  literally,  *  He  who  owns  land 
owns  everything  above  it  up  to  the  sky.'4  It  appears  also  in  the 

1  In  McEvaney  v.  Caledonian  Railway  Co.,  Scot.  Law  Times,  April  1913, 
the  right  of  executors  and  other  personal  representatives  of  a  person  killed  by 
negligence  of  another  to  sue  for  damages  was  held  to  depend  on  the  deceased 
having  made  a  claim  for  damages  antecedent  to  his  death.      See  also  Erskine, 
Principles,  2oth  ed.  p.  100. 

2  See  Balfour,    Practicks,    p.    516 — case  of  Bairnis  of  James  Steuart  v. 
Robert  Steuart,  1539 — for  the  grounds  on  which  the  rule  is  based. 

3  On  the  want  of  equity  in  the  Roman  Law  as  regards  the  limited  trans- 
mission of  delictal  actions  against  heirs,  see  Savigny,  System,  v.  §  211  (p.  50 
sq.).      Compare  Bethmann-Hollweg,  Civil  Progress,  ii.  p.  298,  n.  19,  who  takes 
a  different  view. 

4  See  Broom,  Maxims,  pp.  300,  371,  376. 


230  H.  Goudy  [xi 

form  Cujus  est  solum  ejus  est  a  coelo  usque  ad  centrum  (or  usque 
ad  inferos),  i.e.  '  He  who  owns  land  does  so  from  the  sky  above  it 
to  the  centre  of  the  earth  (or  to  Hades)  below  it.' x  It  is  cited  in 
Croke's  Reports,  in  an  action  for  stopping  lights,  as  Cujus  est 
solum  ejus  est  summitas  usque  ad  coelum,  and  a  reference  is 
there  2  made  to  its  use  in  the  time  of  Edward  I.  It  is  as  old  as 
the  glossarists,  though  whether  due  to  Irnerius  or  another  I  am 
unable  to  say.  It  appears  in  the  Accursian  gloss  in  the  form 
Cujus  solum  ejus  esse  debet  usque  ad  coelum?  On  the  other  hand, 
I  do  not  find  that  it  was  much  used  by  the  commentators  or 
other  Continental  civilians  after  Accursius.  Cujacius  gives  a 
somewhat  different  locution,  viz.  Quo  jure  est  coelum  eodem  jure 
esse  debet  solum  et  contra.  Barbosa  does  not  give  our  maxim 
at  all. 

Unlike  actio  personalis  moritur  cum  persona,  our  present  brocard, 
though  it  appears  nowhere  in  the  Roman  texts,  is  consistent  with 
the  Roman  Law,  and  would  not  have  sounded  strange  to  the 
classical  jurisconsults.  The  text  that  comes  nearest  to  illustrating 
it  is  Dig.  xliii.  24  fr.  22  §  4.  It  is  from  Venuleius,  and  he  tells  us 
there  that  the  interdict  Quod  vi  aut  clam  could  be  raised  against 
anyone  who  caused  anything  to  project  over  another's  burial-place, 
for  the  reason  that  a  burial-place  includes  not  only  the  solum 
but  the  air-space  (coelum}  above  it :  Si  quis  projectum  aut 
stillicidium  in  sepulcrum  immiserit,  etiamsi  ipsum  monumentum 
non  tangeret,  recte  cum  eo  agi  quod  in  sepulcro  vi  aut  clam  factum 
sit,  quia  sepulcri  sit  non  solum  is  locus  qui  recipiat  humationem  sed 
omne  etiam  supra  ad  coelum. 

The  case  figured  is — Some  one  has  placed  a  projectum  which 
interferes  with  the  free  air-space  above  the  burial-ground  of  a 
neighbour  (sepulcrum).  If  no  right  of  servitude  exists  the  owner 
can  have  the  interdict  Quod  vi  aut  clam  just  as  much  as  if  the 
solum  itself  had  been  encroached  upon  by  an  opus  manufactum* 

Another  text  is  Dig.  viii.  2,  I  pr.,  where  it  is  stated  that  no 
servitude  projiciendi  or  stillicidii  could  exist  where  a  public  place, 
such  as  a  public  road,  intervened  between  the  dominant  and  servient 
tenement,  because  coelum  liberum  esse  debet,  which  means,  I  take 

1  See  Lord   Mackenzie,  Roman  Law,  p.    170;    Dart,  Vendors  and  Pur- 
chasers, p.  129. 

2  Croke,  Elist.  p.  118.  3  Gloss  to  Dig.  viii.  2,  i  pr. 


xi]  Two  Ancient  Brocards  231 

it,  that  the  air-space  above  the  road  should  be  free  to  all,  like 
the  road  itself.1  It  was  only  from  the  point  of  view  of  vicinage 
and  servitude  that  the  Romans  had  occasion  to  consider  the 
coelum  in  this  sense.  And  it  was  the  same  with  the  mediaevalists. 
By  our  older  British  lawyers  the  maxim  was  usually  cited  in  the 
following  connexions:  (i)  in  describing  the  nature  and  extent 
of  property  generally  ; 2  (2)  in  affirming  the  acquisition  ipso  jure 
by  the  owner  of  the  soil  of  what  is  built  or  planted  on  it ; 3  (3)  in 
asserting  the  legal  right  not  to  have  one's  uses  of  one's  own  land 
prevented  or  restricted  by  one's  neighbour  using  his  for  building, 
etc.  (Baten's  Case,  tempore  James  I) ; 4  (4)  in  connexion  with 
restrictions  by  servitudes  of  light,  air,  prospect,  etc. 

The  maxim  also,  in  its  form  Cujus  est  solum  ejus  est  a 
coelo  usque  ad  centrum,  has  been  used  in  relation  to  mining 
claims  and  the  like,  in  support  of  the  doctrine  that  ownership  of 
land  extends  beneath  the  surface  in  a  direct  line  to  the  centre  of 
the  earth.5 

Neither  the  Romans  nor  the  mediaevalists  had  to  consider  the 
important  questions  of  overhead  rights  that  we  moderns  have  to 
consider.  Balloons  and  aeroplanes  and  other  air-craft  were  beyond 
their  ken.  How  the  Romans  would  have  dealt  with  such  questions 
as  interference  with  privacy,  disturbance  from  noise,  etc.,  arising 
from  air-craft  must,  of  course,  be  left  to  conjecture.  But  I  venture 
to  think  that  the  right  of  property  in  the  coelum  would  have  sufficed 
to  prevent  air-transit  over  a  man's  ground  and  interdicts  to  prevent 
it  would  have  been  granted  had  damage  been  caused  or  threatened. 
The  assertion  of  some  recent  writers  that  because  the  air,  like  the 
sea,  is  res  communis  and  free  to  all,  the  circulation  of  air-craft 
would  not  have  been  prevented  by  Roman  Law,  is,  to  my  mind, 
based  on  an  erroneous  assumption.  It  is  assumed  that  aer  and 
coelum  mean  the  same  thing.  But  though  no  formal  distinction  was 
made  between  them  by  the  Roman  jurists,  and  though  the  terms 
are  sometimes  used  as  equivalents,  a  distinction  none  the  less 
existed.  It  was  the  aer — the  omnipresent  medium,  never  at  rest 
and  incapable  of  appropriation — that  was  res  communis.  It  was 

1  See  also  Dig.  xliii.  24,  21  §  2.  2  Coke  on  Littleton,  4a. 

3  Stair,  Inst.  i.  p.  296. 

4  8  Jac.  I,  9  Co.  54.     This  case  is  similar  to  Dig.  xliii.  24,  22  §  4. 

5  Broom,  Legal  Maxims,  p.  302. 


232  H.  Goudy  [xi 

so  because  necessary  for  the  life  and  health  of  all.  But  in  contrast 
with  it  the  coelum  was  res  sotiand  capable  more  or  less  of  appropria- 
tion by  the  owner  of  the  soil.  In  this  sense  it  was  not  so  much 
aer  as  spatium  (or  regie)  a'eris,  and  it  is  only  in  this  sense  that  it 
can  be  understood  in  the  two  passages  above  cited.  The  common 
user  of  aer  is  indeed  asserted  by  many  passages  in  the  Digest,  but 
private  ownership  of  the  coelum  is  also  asserted.  There  is  no 
inconsistency. 

Whether  and  how  far  actions  of  trespass,  nuisance,  or  the  like 
are  by  English  Law  competent  to  prevent  transit  by  aeroplanes, 
etc.,  over  private  ground,  are  questions  on  which  I  do  not  enter. 
They  have  been  abundantly  discussed  by  recent  writers,  and  the 
balance  of  authority  seems  greatly  in  favour  of  such  actions  being 
competent.1  But  whatever  view  may  be  taken,  it  is  plain  that 
our  maxim  will  have  much  play  in  the  judicial  discussions  that 
are  likely  to  arise  on  the  subject  in  the  near  future,  and  the  matter 
is  one  that  calls  for  regulation  by  statute.  On  the  other  hand,  for 
International  Law — resting  partly  on  the  same  principles  as  the 
private  law  and  partly  on  other  considerations — we  must  hold  that 
every  State  has  the  right  of  sovereignty  over  the  air-space  above 
its  territory,  and  the  consequent  right  to  exclude  foreigners  from 
it,  and  rules  for  transit  will  have  to  be  provided  by  international 
treaties.  From  the  point  of  view  of  international  rights  air  cannot 
be  treated  like  the  high  seas,  and  we  do  not  need  a  second  Grotius 
to  write  an  aer  liber. 

H.  GOUDY. 

1  See  the  interesting  French  case,  Brinquant  and  others  v.  Farman  and 
others^  July  1912,  discussed  by  Valentine  in  Juridical  Review,  vol.  xxiv. 
p.  321. 


XII 


A   SKETCH    OF   THE    HISTORY   OF   THE 
FOUR   INNS   OF   COURT 

THE  LAND  ACROSS  THE  FLEET 

THERE  was  no  town  or  village  on  the  site  of  the  present  City  of 
London  when  Julius  Caesar  landed  in  Britain  in  55  B.C.  At  that 
time,  indeed,  the  estuary  of  the  Thames  was  probably  eight  or  ten 
times  as  wide  as  it  is  now ;  there  was  a  considerable  ebb  and  flow 
of  the  tide ;  and  most  of  the  land  to  the  south  of  our  present 
Holborn  and  Cheapside  was  then  mere  marsh  or  fen.  Nor  was 
there  any  London  when  the  Romans  occupied  Britain  for  the 
second  time  in  A.D.  43.  This  is  shown  by  the  fact  that  those  who 
originally  constructed  the  Watling  Street — probably  on  the  track 
of  an  earlier  British  road — ignored  our  metropolis  and  made  their 
road  pass  half  a  mile  or  so  on  the  western  side  of  Westminster 
where  it  could  more  safely  cross  the  Thames. 

But  there  was  a  London  of  some  kind  before  Agricola  left 
England ;  Tacitus  in  his  Annals  (xiv.  33)  mentions  a  Londinium 
as  existing  in  A.D.  61.  At  first  it  was  nothing  more  than  a 
fortified  barrack  posted  on  a  rocky  hillock  that  rose  out  of  the 
marshes  of  the  Thames,  on  or  near  what  we  now  call  Ludgate 
Hill,  and  occupied  only  by  soldiers  and  camp-followers.  As  trade 
developed  merchants  and  hucksters  and  other  non-combatants 
came  to  reside  under  its  shelter,  and  London  grew  to  be  a  colony. 
About  A.D.  340,  in  all  probability,  it  became  a  municipality,  and 
at  some  date  between  A.D.  350  and  370  the  famous  Roman  wall 
was  built.  It  enclosed  not  only  buildings  but  nearly  a  square  mile 
of  open  country  as  well,  in  order  to  secure  a  supply  of  water  and 
grazing  for  horses  and  cattle.  This  wall  played  a  most  important 

233 


234  W.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

part  in  the  subsequent  history  of  London.  It  was  wonderfully  well 
and  strongly  built,  and  portions  of  it  still  exist. 

We  are  not  concerned  to-day  with  the  history  of  the  City  of 
London,  most  interesting  though  it  is.  I  have  to  deal  only  with  a 
small  portion  of  the  land  which  lay  to  the  immediate  west  of  the 
old  Roman  wall.  This  locality  has  for  many  centuries  been 
largely  frequented  by  lawyers,  and  it  has  therefore  been  sometimes 
styled  the  'legal  quarter  of  London.'  In  Norman  times  the 
monks  called  it  the  '  territory  ultra  Fletam.1 

The  Holeburn,  or  the  stream  in  the  hollow,  rose  in  the  High- 
gate  ponds  beneath  Ken  woods,  and  soon  met  another  brook, 
which  had  its  source  in  the  Hampstead  ponds  that  lie  to  the  east  of 
Haverstock  Hill.  The  united  stream  ran  down  by  Battle  Bridge, 
round  the  north  of  Holborn  Hill,  and  discharged  itself  into  the 
estuary  known  as  the  Fleet.  This  was  a  tidal  creek  of  the  Thames 
flanked  on  each  side  by  high  banks  where  Holborn  Viaduct  now 
stands,  but  opening  out  more  widely  at  the  foot  of  Fleet  Hill, 
which  we  now  call  Ludgate  Hill,  and  then  running  into  the 
Thames  close  under  the  Roman  wall.  At  high  tide  it  was  wider 
than  Farringdon  Street  is  now.  Poor  little  Fleet  brook  !  After 
helping  for  centuries  to  guard  the  City  of  London  on  its  western 
side,  it  came  to  be  called  the  *  Fleet  ditch,1  and  is  now  shut  up  in 
a  sewer  under  Bridge  Street.  You  may  see  it  at  low  tide  pouring 
its  contents  into  the  Thames  through  a  round  opening  in  the  wall 
which  supports  St.  Paul's  railway  station. 

The  land  bordering  on  the  Thames  to  the  immediate  west  of 
the  Fleet  brook  was  in  Roman  and  Saxon  times  full  of  creeks  and 
runnels,  though  meadows  were  gradually  emerging  from  the  marsh. 
This  is  shown  by  the  names  which  we  still  find  there — such  as 
Bridewell,  Water  Lane,  Milford  Lane,  etc.  There  was  a  nameless 
stream  which  was  once  the  chief  tributary  of  the  Thames  between 
the  Fleet  and  the  Tyburn.  Its  source  was  near  the  Church  of  St. 
Giles-in-the-Fields,  whence  it  ran  across  the  meadows  in  a  south- 
easterly direction  towards  the  site  of  the  future  Church  of  St. 
Clement  Danes.  Before  it  reached  what  we  till  lately  knew  as 
Wych  Street,  it  fell  into  the  creek  which  was  called  the  Old  Wych  ; 
and  close  to  this  spot  there  was  subsequently  a  water  mill  and  a 
ford,  at  the  top  of  what  we  now  call  Milford  Lane.  The  Old  Wych 
then  curled  round  and  fell  into  the  Thames  *  just  at  the  bottom ' 


xn]          The  Inns  of  Court         235 

of  Essex  Street,  where  the  barges  lay  in  the  days  of  Sir  George 
Rose !  Then  a  little  farther  on,  between  what  we  now  call 
Catherine  Street  and  Wellington  Street,  there  was  a  bridge  called 
Strand  Bridge ;  so  there  must  have  been  another  stream  running 
into  the  Thames  just  there.  This  all  tends  to  show  that  the 
southern  portion  of  the  territory  ultra  Fletam  was  originally  more 
or  less  a  marsh.  It  was  indeed  sometimes  called  '  London  Fen.' 

A  little  farther  inland  from  the  Thames  there  soon  came  to  be 
fair  meadows,  sloping  up  towards  Holborn  Hill.  But  in  Roman 
and  in  Saxon  times  there  were  practically  no  houses  to  the  west  of 
the  Fleet  brook — no  Fleet  Street  and  no  Strand  existed  before  the 
Conquest.  There  was  no  road  or  lane  at  this  time  south  of 
Holborn,  and  there  was  no  gate  in  the  Roman  wall  at  the  foot  of 
Fleet  Hill.  There  was  indeed  no  use  or  need  for  such  a  gate,  as 
the  Fleet  brook  was  there  too  wide  to  jump  and  too  deep  to  ford, 
and  there  was  no  bridge.  For  800  years  after  the  Romans  left 
Britain  the  only  gate  in  the  Roman  wall  on  the  west  side  of 
the.  City  was  the  one  afterwards  called  New  Gate.  An  abbey 
was  founded  at  Westminster  a  little  more  than  a  century 
before  the  Norman  Conquest ;  and  shortly  after  that  event  the 
King  had  a  palace  at  Westminster.  But  if  either  Abbot  or  King 
desired  to  journey  from  Westminster  to  the  City  of  London,  he 
had  either  to  go  by  water — for  the  Thames  was  the  great  highway 
between  the  two  cities — or  else  he  had  to  go  by  road  through  the 
village  of  Charing  and  farther  northwards  till  he  joined  the  road 
from  Oxford,  then  along  Holborn  and  enter  the  City  at  the  New 
Gate.  That  was  then  the  only  way  by  road  from  Westminster  to 
London. 

Very  few  people  before  the  accession  of  Henry  I  ventured  to 
live  outside  the  Roman  wall ;  and  indeed  there  was  no  reason  why 
they  should  do  so,  as  there  was  plenty  of  room  within  its  protection. 
Those  who  were  bold  enough  to  reside  outside  it  naturally  clustered 
round  the  existing  highway  and  the  neighbourhood  of  the  City 
gate.  There  were  houses  on  both  sides  of  Holborn  almost  to  the 
top  of  the  hill  for  at  least  a  hundred  years  before  there  was  anything 
like  a  street  nearer  the  Thames.  But  all  the  flat  ground  on  the 
crest  of  the  hill  was  devoid  of  any  buildings.  In  the  Manor  of 
Portpool — that  is  where  now  stands  Gray's  Inn — there  were  no 
houses  at  the  time  of  which  I  am  speaking,  but  merely  a  windmill 


236  W.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

and  a  chantry.  The  priest  who  served  this  chantry  came  from  St. 
Bartholomew  the  Great  in  Smithfield.  He  did  not  dare  to  sleep  in 
the  wild  unknown  country  of  Portpool ;  he  returned  every  night  to 
St.  Bartholomew's, 

But  in  the  eleventh  and  twelfth  centuries  attempts  were 
successfully  made  to  embank  a  portion  of  the  Thames  and  the 
mouth  of  the  Fleet  brook.  Thus  much  of  the  marshy  ground 
came  to  be  meadows  which  attracted  a  few  bold  persons  to  come 
and  live  outside  the  City  walls.  At  first  these  were  chiefly 
ecclesiastics,  as  monasteries  and  churches  were  less  likely  to  be 
attacked  by  robbers  and  housebreakers  than  private  dwelling- 
houses,  and  priests  could  rely  both  on  their  sanctity  and  their 
poverty.  The  churches  of  St.  Bride  and  St.  Dunstan  were  built 
on  the  west  side  of  the  Fleet,  and  in  1115  we  know  that  the  Dean 
and  Chapter  of  St.  Paul's  owned  four  tenements  ultra  Fletam, 
one  of  which  was  occupied  by  a  loriner.  There  must  have  been 
some  road  or  lane  by  which  folk  could  go  to  these  churches  and 
to  this  loriner's.  This  is  the  beginning  of  Fleet  Street.  Then 
about  1 1 50  or  a  little  later  the  Lud  Gate  was  opened,  and  a  bridge 
of  some  kind  was  no  doubt  made  across  the  Fleet.  King  Lud 
never  had  anything  to  do  with  this  gate ;  it  was  not  even  named 
after  him.  The  word  *  ludgate '  simply  means  the  back  gate, 
the  postern  gate. 

For  centuries  there  had  been  wrangling  between  the  City  of 
London  and  the  Abbot  of  Westminster  as  to  how  much  of  the 
marshy  ground  south  of  the  Holborn  Road  belonged  to  each  of 
them.  At  last  in  the  reign  of  Henry  II — about  the  year  1183 — 
this  dispute  was  settled,  and  a  clear  line  was  drawn  separating  the 
two  dominions,  which  to  the  present  day  is  still  the  boundary 
between  the  City  of  London  and  the  City  of  Westminster.  This 
line  started  from  the  New  Gate,  crossed  the  Hole -burn,  and 
came  up  Holborn  Hill  to  where  still  stand  Holborn  Bars.  A  little 
further  on,  it  turned  sharply  to  the  left  and  ran  southwards  to  where 
Temple  Bar  afterwards  stood.  At  first  there  were  only  two  posts 
and  a  chain  there  to  guard  the  new  entrance  to  the  City ;  this  was 
known  as  the  Barra  Novi  Templi  as  early  as  1301.  Later  a  gate  of 
stone  was  built  there,  but  not  the  Temple  Bar  which  we  older  men 
so  well  remember — that  was  built  by  Sir  Christopher  Wren  in  1672, 
and  removed  in  1879.  The  boundary  line  between  the  two  cities 


xii]  The  Inns  of  Court  237 

then  passes  due  south  through  the  corner  of  Messrs.  Twinings' 
tea  warehouse  at  the  top  of  New  Court,  then  by  Ruth  Pinch's 
fountain  and  through  Garden  Court.  It  cuts  off  a  portion  of  the 
Middle  Temple  library,  and  emerges  on  the  Thames  Embankment 
just  where  there  is  a  monument  to  Queen  Victoria  on  the  railing 
of  the  Middle  Temple  Garden. 

The  area  between  this  boundary  and  the  old  Roman  wall  was 
at  once  treated  as  a  suburb  of  the  City  and  placed  under  civic  rule, 
although  it  was  not  till  1223  that  it  was  expressly  declared  to  be 
a  City  ward.  It  was  called  at  first  the  ward  of  Holborn  and  Fleet 
Street,  and  later  the  ward  of  Farringdon.  Half  of  our  Inns  of 
Court  and  of  Chancery  lay  within  this  new  ward,  and  half  without 
it.  Thus  it  contained  both  the  Inner  and  the  Middle  Temple, 
Staple  Inn,  Barnard's  Inn,  Thavie's  Inn,  Clifford's  Inn,  and  both 
the  Serjeants  Inns ;  while  Lincoln's  Inn,  Gray's  Inn,  Clement's 
Inn,  and  New  Inn  never  were  within  the  City  of  London. 

We  will  now  briefly  trace  the  history  of  each  separate  Inn  of 
Court. 

THE  KNIGHTS  TEMPLARS 

It  was  in  the  year  1118  that  the  Knights  of  the  Holy  Sepulchre 
at  Jerusalem  first  came  to  England.  They  were  bound  by  the 
strictest  vows  to  poverty,  chastity,  obedience,  to  succour  the  Holy 
Land,  and  especially  to  '  save  the  Holy  Sepulchre  from  thrall.' 
But  they  did  not  always  devote  the  whole  of  their  time  to  com- 
pliance with  these  vows.  Being  both  soldiers  and  ecclesiastics, 
they  did  not  fear  to  live  outside  the  Roman  wall,  so  they  settled 
on  a  vacant  piece  of  land  on  the  south  side  of  Holborn  between 
the  future  Staple  Inn  and  the  top  of  the  future  Chancery  Lane. 
There  they  built  a  hall  and  a  round  chapel ;  all  the  churches 
dedicated  to  the  Holy  Sepulchre  were  round.  They  remained  for 
over  forty  years  on  this  site,  which  was  long  afterwards  known  as 
the  *  Old  Temple.' 

When  the  Templars  came  to  England  it  was  natural,  no  doubt, 
for  them  to  settle  near  Holborn,  for  that  was  then  the  only  road 
out  of  London  on  the  western  side.  But  towards  the  close  of  the 
twelfth  century,  as  we  have  seen,  Ludgate  had  been  opened  and 
a  road  carried  over  the  lower  Fleet  and  along  what  we  now  call 
Fleet  Street.  And  eventually  the  Templars,  wanting  more  room 


238  JV.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

than  they  could  get  in  Holborn,  where  houses  were  springing  up 
all  around  them,  obtained  from  Robert  de  Beaumont,  second  Earl 
of  Leicester  and  Lord  High  Steward  of  England,  the  grant  of 
a  fine  open  meadow  sloping  down  to  the  Thames  on  the  southern 
side  of  the  new  road,  and  there  built  a  great  house  and  a  second 
round  church.  They  also  acquired  a  field  on  the  north  side  of  the 
new  road ;  it  was  called  Fickett's  Field,  and  extended  from  the 
Church  of  St.  Clement  Danes  almost  to  the  future  Chancery  Lane. 
This  field  they  used  for  tilting ;  and  doubtless  the  forge  in  the 
south-east  corner  of  it,  for  which  the  City  still  pays,  I  believe,  a 
rent  to  the  Crown,  was  the  place  where  the  armour  of  the  Templars 
was  fitted  and  riveted,  and  their  horses  shod. 

The  exact  date  when  the  Knights  Templars  left  the  Old 
Temple  and  settled  in  their  new  habitation,  cannot  be  now 
definitely  fixed,  but  it  was  probably  about  the  year  1162.  At 
first  they  had  no  chapel  of  their  own  ;  they  held  their  services  in 
the  Church  of  St.  Clement  Danes,  over  which  King  Henry  II 
gave  them  certain  rights,  but  they  were  busy  building  the  circular 
portion  of  our  present  Temple  Church.  And  on  February  10,  1185 
this  was  consecrated  by  Heraclius,  Patriarch  of  the  Church  of  the 
Holy  Resurrection,  Jerusalem,  in  the  presence  of  King  Henry  II, 
his  consort,  and  his  Court.  King  James  I  in  his  Charter  of  1608 
still  described  this  matchless  specimen  of  pure  Norman  architecture 
as  '  the  Church  of  the  New  Temple  of  London.'  There  are  only 
two  other  examples  of  the  true  Norman  work  above  ground  in 
London — the  Chapel  of  St.  John  at  the  Tower  of  London,  and  the 
Church  of  St.  Bartholomew  the  Great  at  Smithfield — though  there 
are  two  or  three  Norman  crypts  in  the  City  under  ground. 

Later,  in  1220,  was  built  St.  Ann's  Chapel,  the  crypt  of  which 
is  still  to  be  seen.  The  Templars  also  erected  a  noble  refectory  of 
stone,  which  stood  upon  the  site  of  the  present  Inner  Temple  Hall ; 
indeed  two  arched  crypts  which  belonged  to  the  refectory  are 
still  standing  there.  And  here  the  Templars  lived  in  pride  and 
pomp.  They  associated  only  with  the  nobles.  King  John  himself 
came  and  lodged  with  them  for  a  week  at  a  time.  They  looked 
down  upon  the  knights  of  all  other  religious  orders,  and  at  last 
their  arrogance  was  their  ruin.  At  the  beginning  of  the  fourteenth 
century  grave  charges  were  brought  against  them,  most  of  which, 
I  believe,  were  unfounded.  They  were  accused,  among  other  things, 


xn]  The  Inns  of  Court  239 

of  conducting  in  secret  unholy  Rosicrucian  ceremonies  and  other 
mystic  rites,  which  they  were  said  to  have  brought  from  Palestine. 
An  inquiry  was  held  in  St.  Dunstan's  Church  in  1312,  and  the 
charges  were  declared  to  be  proved.  Under  rigorous  cross- 
examination,  and  probably  under  torture,  some  of  the  weaker 
brethren  confessed  to  crimes  which  they  had  never  committed,  and, 
what  was  worse,  to  heresies,  which  they  possibly  may  have  held. 
All  the  property  of  the  Knights  Templars  was  confiscated,  and 
they  were  expelled  from  the  kingdom  in  the  year  1313. 

There  were  many  reasons  for  their  expulsion.  First  and  fore- 
most they  were  reputed  to  be  very  wealthy.  Then  they  had  done 
nothing  for  many  years  in  performance  of  their  vows.  The  Knights 
Hospitallers  of  St.  John  of  Jerusalem  were  jealous  of  them. 
Lastly,  the  Pope  turned  against  them,  and  then  their  doom  was 
sealed. 

But  the  King  obtained  little  or  no  booty  from  his  cruel  and 
unjust  treatment  of  the  Knights  Templars.  The  Pope  intervened 
on  the  ground  that  their  property  was  consecrated,  and  by  a  decree 
made  at  Vienne  in  1312  gave  their  possessions  in  England  to  the 
rival  Knights  of  St.  John,  who  continued  to  hold  them  till  the 
dissolution  of  the  monastic  orders  under  Henry  VIII.  This 
property  included  what  was  afterwards  known  as  the  Inner  and 
Middle  Temple. 

But  the  Knights  of  St.  John  found  their  new  acquisition  rather 
a  white  elephant.  They  preferred  the  open  country  at  Clerkenwell 
in  which  they  had  been  for  several  years  comfortably  established. 
They  had,  moreover,  a  struggle  with  the  King  before  they  could 
obtain  possession  of  the  Templars'  Hall  and  its  precincts,  for  that 
monarch  had  put  into  possession  of  it,  first  Aymer  de  Valence, 
Earl  of  Pembroke,  and  then  his  own  cousin  Thomas,  Earl  of 
Lancaster.  But  the  latter  nobleman  was  executed  in  1322,  and  in 
1324  the  Pope  again  insisted  that  all  the  property  of  the  Templars 
must  be  handed  over  to  the  Knights  of  St.  John,  lest,  as  the  decree 
ran,  '  the  same  should  be  put  to  profane  uses.'  And  so,  some 
years  later,  in  the  early  part  of  the  reign  of  Edward  III,  the 
Knights  of  St.  John  leased  it  to  the  lawyers ! 


240  W.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

THE  INNER  AND  THE  MIDDLE  TEMPLE 

The  exact  date  of  this  letting  (or,  more  technically,  subinfeuda- 
tion)  is  unknown  ;  Master  Worsley  is  content  to  say  that  it  took 
place  in  'some  part  of  the  reign  of  Edward  III.'1  Still  less  do 
we  know  to  what  lawyers  the  land  was  leased.  Was  it  to  an 
accidental  group  of  persons  who  had  never  previously  been 
associated  ?  Was  it  to  a  Society  of  lawyers,  who  till  then  occupied 
some  neighbouring  hospice  ?  We  know  that  there  were  already 
many  little  communities  in  the  City  of  London  of  professors  and 
students  of  the  law  residing  each  in  its  separate  hostel,  taking 
their  meals  in  common,  and  governed  by  their  Readers  or 
Benchers  as  the  colleges  in  Oxford  and  Cambridge  were  by  their 
fellows.  Did  one  of  these  Societies  march  westward  and  occupy 
the  chambers  left  empty  by  the  Knights  Templars  within  the  new 
City  boundary?  Or  was  this  land,  as  some  maintain,  divided 
from  the  first  between  two  already  existing  Societies  of  lawyers 
who  had  previously  been  occupying  separate  hospices?  These 
questions  we  cannot  answer  positively,  because  we  have  not  the 
deeds.  In  the  year  1381  the  followers  of  Wat  Tyler  went  to  the 
Temple,  broke  into  the  Church,  seized  all  the  books  and  papers, 
and  all  the  reports  of  cases  which  were  in  the  lockers  of  the 
apprentices  of  the  law  in  the  Temple,  took  them  up  to  the  high 
road,  and  burnt  them  there.  The  existing  registers  of  the  Middle 
Temple  begin  in  1501,  those  of  the  Inner  Temple  in  1505  ;  both 
contain  references  to  older  records  now  unfortunately  lost. 

There  is  no  doubt  some  reason  to  believe  that  while  the 
Knights  Templars  occupied  this  land  there  were  on  it  two  halls. 
One,  their  refectory,  stood  where  the  Inner  Temple  Hall  now 
stands — it  was  consecrated  because  the  prior  slept  over  it.  The 
other  hall  stood  on  unconsecrated  ground  occupying  a  portion  of 
the  site  on  which  at  present  stand  Pump  Court  and  Elm  Court — 
in  other  words,  in  what  is  now  the  Middle  Temple.  But  there  is 
no  reason  why  the  same  society  may  not  own  two  halls  ;  Lincoln's 
Inn  does  so  at  the  present  moment,  and  ex  hypothesi,  the  Order  of 
the  Knights  Templars  did  so  before  their  exile.  The  presumed 
existence,  therefore,  of  the  two  halls  does  nothing  to  settle  the 
dispute. 

1  Master  Worsteds  Book,  edition  of  1910,  p.  89. 


xii]  The  Inns  of  Court  241 

More  may  perhaps  be  made  of  the  undoubted  existence  of  two 
rents.     In  the  year  1331  William  de  Langford  was  Keeper  of  the 
New  Temple  under  the  Order  of  the  Knights  Hospitallers  of  St. 
John  of  Clerkenwell.     He  paid  annually  into  the  King's  Exchequer 
for  the  Temple  the  sum  of  £24,  namely  ^"12:4:1  for  the  con- 
secrated portion  and  ;£ii:  15:11  for  the  unconsecrated  portion. 
But  then  a  claim  was  made  to  the  consecrated  portion  by  Hugh  le 
Despenser,  who  alleged  that  it  had  been  sold  to  him  by  the  Prior 
of  the  Order  in  the  year    1324.     The    Prior,  however,  with   the 
assistance  of  William  de  Langford,  was  able  in   1336  to  satisfy  the 
King  that  this  sale  had  been  extorted  from  him  by  force  by  the 
said   Hugh ;  so  William  de  Langford  remained  in  possession  as 
tenant  of  the  Prior.     Two  years  afterwards,  on  i8th  June  1338,  the 
King,  being  in  need  of  money  for  his  foreign  expedition,  agreed  for 
the  sum  of  ;£ioo  to  allow  the  Prior  the  residue  or  unconsecrated 
portion  of  the  manor  of  the  New  Temple,  together  with  the  rent 
due  therefrom  of  £j :  5  :  2.     It   is  explained  in  the  Calendar  of 
Patent  Rolls  of  this  date  how  the  rent  had  become  reduced  from 
;£ii  :  15  :  II  to  this  figure ;  and  it  is  stated  that  if  this  residue  of 
the  manor  should  be  found  by  valuation  to  be  worth  more  than 
£10  the  Prior  should  pay  the  excess  into  the  Exchequer.     Thus  it 
came  about  that  the  lawyers  in  occupation  of  this  portion  of  the 
land  paid  the   Prior  only  £10  a  year  rental ;  the  Prior  was  not 
interested  in  obtaining  more.     But  it  was  not  until  the  year  1521 
that  a  later  prior  agreed  to  reduce  the  rent  of  the  consecrated 
portion  to  the  same  amount.1     The  Order  of  the  Knights  of  St. 
John  of  Clerkenwell  was  dissolved  in  1539  and  their  property  all 
passed  to  the  Crown.     So  from  that  time  forward  the  Societies  of 
the  Inner  and  the  Middle  Temple  each  paid  the  King  £10  a  year, 
and  these  rents  were  retained  by  the  Charter  which  King  James  I 
granted  to  the  two  Societies  in  1609.     It  will  be  observed,  how- 
ever, that  the  two  rents  were  originally  one  rent ;  and,  again,  there 
is  no  reason  why  two  different  rents  may  not  be  paid  by  the  same 
society  for  two  different  properties  if  that  society  occupies  them 
both. 

We  cannot,  therefore,  on   the   materials   before   us,  definitely 
determine   whether  there  were   from  the   beginning   two  distinct 

1  For  this  detailed  account  of  the  two  rents  I  am  indebted  to  Mr.  E. 
Williams,  F.R.G.S.,  of  the  Prudential  Assurance  Company. 

R 


242  IV.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

societies  settled  in  the  Temple.  But  this  much  is  clear  that  within 
some  fifty  or  sixty  years  after  the  first  entry  of  the  lawyers  two 
separate  societies  were  located  there.  The  Prologue  to  the  Canter- 
bury Tales  was  written  when  Chaucer  was  on  a  journey  in  the  year 
1388,  and  it  contains  a  well-known  reference  to  a  manciple,  on 
which  Dugdale x  bases  an  argument :  '  That  they  were  here  seated 
in  King  Edward  the  third's  time,  is  out  of  all  doubt,  from  what 
our  famous  old  Poet  Geffrey  Chaucer  expresseth  in  his  Prologue 
to  the  Manciple,  concerning  them  (he  having  also  been  a  Student 
of  this  House,  as  the  History  of  his  life,  printed  in  the  front  of  his 
works,2  sheweth).' 

A  Manciple  there  was  of  the  Temple, 

Of  which  all  Catours  might  taken  ensemple. 

But  Dugdale  here  is  clearly  quoting  from  an  inferior  version  of 
the  Prologue.  In  the  best  manuscript,  the  Ellesmere,  the  lines 
run  thus": — 

A  Gentil  Maunciple  was  ther  of  a  temple, 
Of  which  achatours  mighte  take  exemple. 

And  the  use  of  the  phrase  '  a  temple '  is  some  evidence  that  there 
was  more  than  one  temple  known  to  Chaucer  in  the  year  1388. 

Next,  we  are  indebted  to  Mr.  W.  C.  Bolland  of  Lincoln's  Inn 
for  an  interesting  discovery.3  He  found  an  old  will  preserved  at 
Somerset  House  which  is  dated  St.  Bartholomew's, day,  24th  August 
1404.  It  was  made  by  John  Bownt  of  Bristol,  and  is  written  in 
Latin.  It  contains  a  bequest  of  two  marks  to  Robert,  the  manciple 
of  the  Middle  Temple  (Roberto  mancipio  medii  Templi}.  Can  this 
be  the  very  man  who  rode  with  Chaucer  along  the  Pilgrim's  Way 
to  Canterbury  ?  Again  in  the  year  1440  in  the  Paston  letters  we 
find  one  of  the  Pastons  writing  to  his  son  and  bidding  him  '  quan 
your  leysyr  is,  resorte  ageyn  on  to  your  college,  the  Inner  Temple.' 
So  by  this  time  there  were  two  distinct  *  colleges '  or  schools  of  law 
established  on  the  lands  formerly  held  by  the  Knights  Templars 
within  the  boundary  between  the  City  of  London  and  the  county 
of  Middlesex. 

1  Origines  Jurididales^  p.    145.     The    first    edition    of   this    book    was 
published  in  1666. 

2  Dugdale  is  no  doubt  referring  to  Speght's  edition,  published  in  1574. 

3  See  an  article  by  him   in  the  Law   Quarterly  Review ',   vol.   xxiv.,  at 
p.  402. 


xii]  The  Inns  of  Court  243 

The  lands  of  the  Knights  Templars  which  lay  outside  that 
boundary  came  naturally  to  be  known  as  the  Outer  Temple.  The 
lawyers  never  got  possession  of  any  of  this.  The  portion  of  this 
land  which  lay  to  the  south  of  the  Strand  became  the  property 
first  of  the  bishops  of  Exeter,  then  of  Lord  Paget,  and  later  of  the 
Earl  of  Leicester,  and  then  of  his  stepson  Robert  Devereux,  Earl 
of  Essex.  Upon  it  now  stand  Essex  Hall,  Essex  Street,  and 
Devereux  Court.  Much  history  lingers  in  the  names  of  streets 
and  houses.  The  portion  north  of  the  Strand  formerly  known  as 
Fickett's  Field  was  in  the  eighteenth  century  covered  with  a  net- 
work of  disreputable  slums.  These  were  later  cleared  away  to 
make  room  for  the  stately  pile  of  the  Royal  Courts  of  Justice, 
which  were  opened  on  4th  December  1882. 


THE  LEGEND  OF  THAW'S  INN 

But  before  proceeding  farther  northwards,  we  must  pause  to 
discuss  a  tradition  mentioned  by  Dugdale  connecting  the  Temple 
with  Thavy's  Inn.  He  tells  us  on  p.  144  of  his  great  work  the 
Origines  Juridiciales  that 

by  a  Decree  made  in  the  great  Councel  at  Vienna  in  anno  1324  (sic) 
(about  the  iQth  year  of  the  same  King  Edward  the  II  reign)  the 
lands  of  the  Templars,  being  generally  bestowed  upon  the  Knights 
Hospitalers  of  St.  John  of  Hierusalem,  King  Edward  the  3d 
granted  this  Mansion  unto  the  Knights  of  that  Order  here  in 
England ;  who,  soon  after  (as  the  tradition  is)  demised  the  same, 
for  the  Rent  of  x1-  per  annum,  unto  divers  professors  of  the  Common 
law,  that  came  from  Thavyes  Inne  in  Holburne.  Now  that  there 
is  nothing  but  tradition  left  to  us ;  for  this  cannot  seem  strange, 
considering  what  spoil  Wat  Tyler,  with  his  fellow  Rebells,  made 
here,  in  4  Ric.  2.  by  destroying  and  burning  their  Books  and 
Records. 

You  will  observe  how  guardedly  Dugdale  speaks  of  this 
'  tradition/  that  the  first  Templars  came  from  Thavy's  Inn.  Never- 
theless a  less  learned  and  therefore  a  bolder  writer  makes  the  same 
statement  in  a  manuscript  still  in  the  possession  of  the  Society  of 
the  Inner  Temple.  His  name  is  unknown,  but  he  wrote  at  some 
date  after  the  middle  of  the  reign  of  Charles  I,  and  he  ventures  to 
assign  a  precise  date  for  the  alleged  migration.  His  statement  is1 

1  Calendar,  Inner  Temple,  i.  p.  xvii. 


244  ^  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

that  the  lawyers  came  from  Thavie's  Inn 

about  the  year  1347,  ever  since  which  time  they  and  their  suc- 
cessors, professors  and  students  of  the  Common  Law,  have  there 
resided,  who  in  tract  of  time  converted  and  regulated  the  same 
first  into  one  Inne  of  Court  and  afterwards,  viz.,  in  the  reign  of 
King  Henry  VI,  divided  themselves  into  those  two  Societies  or 
Inns  of  Court,  viz.,  the  Inner  and  the  Middle  Temple. 

We  shall  see  shortly x  why  the  writer  fixed  on  the  year  1 347 ;  but 
his  extraordinary  looseness  as  to  dates  is  shown  by  his  startling 
statement  that  there  was  only  one  society  of  lawyers  at  the  Temple 
till  the  reign  of  Henry  VI !  Indeed  a  few  sentences  later  (p.  xviii) 
he  asserts  that  there  was  only  one  Hall  in  the  Temple  till  the  reign 
of  Henry  VI- 

then  the  lawyers  were  multiplied  and  grown  into  soe  great  a  bulke 
as  could  not  conveniently  be  regulated  into  one  society,  nor,  indeed, 
was  the  old  hall  capable  of  containing  so  great  a  number,  whereupon 
they  were  forced  to  divide  themselves.  A  new  hall  was  then  erected, 
which  is  now  the  Junior  Temple  Hall,  whereunto  divers  of  those 
who  before  took  their  repast  and  diet  in  the  old  hall  resorted,  and 
in  process  of  time  became  a  distinct  and  divided  society. 

These  are,  I  believe,  the  only  'authorities'  for  the  suggestion 
that  the  first  Templars  came  from  Thavy's  Inn  ;  and  neither  of 
them  carries  any  weight.  As  we  shall  shortly  see,  no  Thavy's  Inn 
existed  in  1347.  Moreover,  at  that  date,  in  all  probability,  some 
lawyers  had  already  entered  the  Temple. 

But  where  was  Thavy's  Inn,  and  who  was  Thavy?  Was  he 
the  same  person  as  Tavy  or  Davy,  who  are  also  accredited  by 
some  with  having  founded  Inns  of  Chancery  in  the  fourteenth 
century  ? 

There  was  in  the  reign  of  Edward  III  'an  honest  citizen' 
called  John  Tavy  who  owned  three  shops  on  the  south  side  of 
Holborn,  and  behind  them  a  house  or  hostel  in  which  apprentices 
were  boarded.  They  lay  to  the  east  of  Fetter  Lane,  pretty  much 
on  the  site  of  the  present  Bartlett's  Buildings  ;  Tavy  had  purchased 
these  in  1323.  He  was  by  trade  an  armourer,  and  a  member  of 
the  Company  of  Armourers,  and  was  one  of  the  four  members  of 
that  Company  who  were  appointed  in  1342  to  supervise  the  new 

1  Post,  p.  247. 


xn]          The  Inns  of  Court          245 

regulations  as  to  the  making  and  selling  of  armour.  He  was  also 
an  armiger,  which  shows  that  he  was  a  person  of  some  little  dis- 
tinction in  the  City. 

John  Tavy  made  his  will  on  I2th  March  1348,  and  it  was 
proved  and  enrolled  in  the  Husting  on  23rd  November  1349.  He 
directed  his  executors  to  sell  a  certain  tenement  which  he  had 
acquired  from  John  Cok,  and  with  the  proceeds  to  pay  his  debts, 
etc.  To  Isabella,  his  daughter,  he  left  a  certain  shop,  and  to  his 
wife  Alice  all  his  other  tenements  in  Holborn.  After  her  decease 
*  the  hostel  in  which  the  apprentices  used  to  dwell '  was  to  be  sold 
and  the  proceeds  devoted  to  the  maintenance  of  a  chantry. 

On  1 6th  January  1350-51,  that  is,  fourteen  months  later,  the 
executors,  at  Alice's  request,  sold  the  hostel  and  two  shops  and 
the  reversion  of  the  third  shop  held  by  Isabel,  the  testator's 
daughter,  to  Sir  John  de  Houton,  Baron  of  the  Exchequer.1  But 
this  sale  was  only  for  the  life  of  Alice.  On  the  death  of  Alice,  in 
1366,  the  hostel  was  sold  in  fee  to  Roger  de  Barnburgh  and  Sir 
Ely  de  Sutton,  clerks  of  the  Chancery  (St.  Andrew's  Church  taking 
a  rent).  This  was  in  accordance  with  the  will  of  John  Tavy, 
which  directed  that  it  should  be  sold  after  the  death  of  Alice  to 
provide  a  chaplain  to  pray  for  the  souls  of  Alice  and  John.2 

There  was  another  and  a  very  different  man,  John  Davy,  who 
in  the  year  1376  occupied  the  land  which  lay  to  the  south  of 
Holborn  on  the  east  side  of  John  Tavy's  land,  stretching  away 
towards  St.  Andrew's  Church  and  Shoe  Lane.  He  was  a  Chancery 
clerk,  Receiver  for  the  King  for  the  counties  of  Carmarthen  and 
Cardigan,  and  a  man  of  great  prominence  in  Holborn  from  1350 
to  1397,  when  he  died.  The  land  which  he  occupied  is  quite 
distinct  from  that  which  John  Tavy  owned  in  1348.  It  extended 
from  a  tenement  of  John  Tavy  on  the  west  to  a  tenement  of 
John  de  Besville  on  the  east,  and  stretched  from  the  King's  high- 
way on  the  north  to  the  tenements  of  John  de  Besville  and  John 
Tavy  on  the  south,  and  is  so  described  in  a  deed  of  26th  June 
1346.  And  on  this  land  there  undoubtedly  grew  up,  under  the 
superintendence  of  Davy,  a  little  school  of  law  which  was  named 

1  The  leading  witness   to  this   deed   of  sale  was   Thomas  de   Lincoln, 
serjeant-at-law,  who  at  that  time  was  the  owner  of  the  first  *  Lyncolnesyn ' 
in  Holborn. 

2  For  all   these  details  as  to  the  various  properties  in  Holborn   I  am 
indebted  to  Mr.  E.  Williams,  who  holds  the  deeds. 


246  IV.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

after  him  Davy's  Inn.  It  was  sometimes  called  Thavy's  Inn,  but 
why  we  can  only  conjecture.  Possibly  Davy,  the  Receiver  for  the 
counties  of  Carmarthen  and  Cardigan,  spelt  his  name  with  two 
'  D's,'  for  the  Welsh  are  fond  of  double  initials,  and  I  am  informed 
by  a  high  authority  that  in  Welsh  *  dd '  is  pronounced  like  '  th '  in 
*  this  '  or  '  that.'  Anyhow,  both  names  seem  to  have  been  used  in- 
discriminately for  centuries.  But  '  Thavies  Inn  '  eventually  gained 
the  mastery,  and  the  place  was  called  by  that  name  till  within 
living  memory.  The  property  is  referred  to  as  '  Davysynne '  in  an 
old  Inquisition  post-mortem  in  1419,  and  in  the  minister's  accounts 
of  the  Bishop  of  Ely  in  1444.  On  25th  January  1550  Gregory 
Nicholas,  citizen,  quit -claimed  to  Edward  Gryffith  and  others 
gubernatoribus  hospitii  de  Lyncolnsyn  a  'messuage  with  a  garden 
adjoining  commonly  called  Davyes  Inne  and  of  old  time  (olim) 
called  Thavye's  Inne  with  chambers,  etc.,'  in  Holbourne. 

It  is  clear  from  the  title-deeds  that  John  Tavy,  the  armourer, 
never  owned  any  portion  of  what  was  called  Davy's  or  Thavie's 
Inn.  Yet  legal  writers  soon  jumped  to  the  conclusion  that  this  inn 
was  called  after  the  armourer.  The  confusion  has,  no  doubt,  been 
caused  by  the  similarity  between  the  names,  but  I  think  my  Lord 
Coke  was  also  to  blame  in  the  matter. 

He  stumbled  one  day  in  the  Court  of  Husting  upon  John  Tavy's 
will,  and  was  struck  by  the  fact  that  it  contained  the  word  appren- 
ticii.  It  described  the  house  behind  the  three  shops  as  hospitium 
in  quo  apprenticii  habitare  solebant,  and  this  collocation  of  the 
words  hospitium  and  apprenticii  made  a  great  impression  upon 
Lord  Coke's  mind.  Remembering  that  John  Tavy  was  an 
armourer,  and  a  member  of  the  Guild  of  Armourers,  we  should  now 
naturally  translate  the  Latin  phrase  as  'the  house  in  which  my 
apprentices  used  to  dwell.'  No  doubt  Tavy  had  a  year  before  his 
death  retired  from  business,  and  his  apprentices  had  left  him  and 
set  up  for  themselves.  But  in  the  fifteenth  and  sixteenth  centuries 
the  apprenticii  had  played  a  very  important  part  in  legal  circles. 
There  were  the  apprenticii  ad  legem — the  men  who  lived  in  the 
Inns  of  Court,  and  who  roughly  corresponded  to  what  we  now  call 
the  'junior  Bar' — and  the  apprenticii  attached  to  the  various 
courts,  who  were  in  fact  apprenticed  to  the  clerks  of  those  courts, 
and  resided  in  the  Inns  of  Chancery.  With  these  looming  large  in 
his  eye,  Lord  Coke  jumped  to  the  conclusion  that  apprentices  of 


xii]  The  Inns  of  Court  247 

the  law  had  lived  in  Tavy's  house — though  why  students  of  law 
should  reside  with  an  armourer  I  cannot  understand !  And  later 
came  our  friend  who  wrote  the  Inner  Temple  manuscript,  from 
which  I  have  copied  on  p.  244,  and  he  said  to  himself :  *  John  Tavy's 
will  was  made  in  1 348,  and  in  it  he  says  that  the  apprentices  used 
to  dwell  in  his  hostel  (habitare  solebanf] ;  so  they  must  have  left 
before  he  made  his  will.  Ah,  I  see ;  they  all  moved  in  a  body  to 
the  Temple  in  1347  !' 

However  this  may  be,  Lord  Coke  refers  to  the  matter  on 
p.  xxxvii  of  the  Preface  to  the  Reader  in  Part  X  of  his  Reports. 
After  quoting  the  case  of  Thomas  de  Weylond  (19  Edw.  I)  as  to 
the  antiquity  of  the  Order  of  Serjeants,  he  adds  : — 

And  in  I  Edw.  Ill  'there  is  mention  made  of  an  apprentice, 
and  he  is  called  an  apprentice  of  the  law  .  .  .  and  is  next  in  degree 
under  a  serjeant.'  See  also  the  ordinance  of  20  Edw.  I,  rot.  5, 
addressed  to  Sir  John  de  Metingham,  etc.  :  'And  so  is  farther  proved 
by  a  record  inter  communia  placita  tenta  in  Hustingo,  London, 
die  Lunae  in  festo  Sancti  dementis  Papae,  anno  regni  Edw.  Ill  viz. 
die  Jovis  proxime  ante  festum  Sancti  Gregorii  Papae,  anno  domini 
1348.  Ego  Johannes  Tavie  Armiger  lego  animam  meam  Deo,  &c. 
Item  lego  omnia  tenementa  mea  cum  omnibus  pertinentiis  quae 
habeo  in  parte  australi  in  parochia  Sancti  Andreae,  &c.  Aliciae 
uxori  meae  ad  totum  terminum  vitae  suae  ;  et  quod  post  decessum 
praedictae  Aliciae,  totum  illud  Hospitium  in  quo  Apprenticii  legis 
habitare  solebant.' 

This  legend  as  to  Davy's  (alias  Thavy's)  Inn  rapidly  gained 
ground.  Sir  George  Buc,  who  had  himself  been  a  student  there, 
wrote  an  Account  of  the  Schools  of  Learning  in  London,  which 
he  presented  to  Lord  Coke,  and  which  was  published  in  1631 
as  an  appendix  to  Stow's  Chronicle  of  England.  And  therein  he 
speaks  in  glowing  terms  of  his  former  inn. 

And  I  must  and  will  begin  with  Thavis  Inne,  for  besides  that 
at  my  first  comming  to  London,  I  was  admitted  for  probation, 
into  that  good  house,  I  take  it  to  be  the  oldest  Inne  of  Chancery, 
at  the  least  in  Holborne,  and  so  may  justly  challenge  precedence 
by  Seigniority,  and  antiquitie :  it  was  before  the  dwelling  of  an 
honest  Citizen  called  John  Thavie  an  armorer,  and  was  rented  of 
him  in  the  time  of  King  Edward  the  3.  by  the  chiefe  professors 
then  of  the  Law,  viz.  Apprentises,  as  it  is  yet  extant  in  a  record 
in  the  hustings,  and  whereof  my  Lord  Coke,  shewed  to  me  the 


248  W.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

transcript,  but  since  that  time  it  was  purchased  for  the  students 
and  other  professors  of  the  Law  of  Chauncery  by  the  Benchers  of 
Lincolns  Inne,  about  the  Raigne  of  King  Henry  the  seaventh,  and 
retaineth  the  name  of  the  olde  Land-lord  or  owner,  master  Thavie. 

There  are  two  glaring  misstatements  in  this  passage.  The 
apprentices  certainly  never  were  '  the  chief  professors  then  of  the 
law.'  They  always  took  rank  below  the  Serjeants  and  readers. 
Again,  the  Society  of  Lincoln's  Inn  did  not  acquire  Davy's  Inn 
in  the  reign  of  King  Henry  VII,  but  in  the  year  1550,  when  his 
grandson,  Edward  VI,  was  King.  Note  also  that  what  Lord  Coke 
showed  to  Sir  George  Buc  was  not  the  original  will  in  the 
Husting,  but  only  a  transcript  of  it. 

Lastly,  let  us  have  Dugdale's  version  of  this  legend  ;  it  was 
written  before  the  year  I666.1 

In  this  Inne  of  Chancery  were  Students  of  the  Law  resident 
in  King  Edward  the  third's  time,  as  may  appear  by  these  follow- 
ing words,  taken  out  of  the  last  Will  and  Testament  of  John 
Tavye,  whose  House  it  then  was,  and  of  whom  it  took  this  name  ; 
viz. — ego  Johannes  Tavie  Armiger,  &c.  lego  animam  meam  Deo, 
&c.  Item  lego  omnia  tenementa  mea,  cum  omnibus  suis  pertinentiis, 
quae  habeo  in  parte  Australi,  in  parochia  S.  Andreae,  &c.  Aliciae, 
uxori  meae,  ad  terminum  vitse  suae :  Et  quod  post  decessum 
praedictae  Aliciae,  totum  illud  Hospicium,  in  quo  Apprenticii 
ad  Legem  habitare  solebant,  per  Executores  meos,  si  superstites 
fuerint,  una  cum  Executoribus  praedictae  Aliciae,  vendatur,  et  quod 
de  pecunia  inde  precepta,  unus  Capellanus  idoneus,  pro  anima  mea, 
et  anima  praedictae  Aliciae  inveniatur,  &c. 

But  in  process  of  time,  the  inheritance  thereof,  coming  to  the 
hands  of  Gregory  Nicholls,  Citizen  and  Mercer  of  London  ;  he,  by 
his  Deed,  bearing  date  .  .  .  Jan.  4,  E.  6,  granted  it  to  the  then 
Benchers  of  Lincolns  Inne,  and  their  successors  for  the  use  of 
Students  of  the  Law :  After  which  time,  it  was  by  them  demised 
to  the  Principal  and  Fellows  of  this  House,  for  the  Rent  iii1.  vis.  viiid. 
per  annum  ;  and  hath  had  the  like  privilege,  for  admission  of  their 
Students  into  the  Society  of  Lincolns  Inne,  as  those  of  Furnivals 
Inne  had,  and  still  have. 

When  I  compared  the  two  versions  cited  above  of  the  will 
of  John  Tavy,  the  armourer,  I  was  struck  by  the  difference  of 
phraseology  at  the  all-important  point — Lord  Coke  writing  legis 
and  Dugdale  writing  ad  legem.  A  suspicion  entered  my  mind 
that  these  words  must  in  each  case  be  a  gloss  placed  by  the  learned 

1  Orig.  Jur.  p.  271. 


xn]  The  Inns  of  Court  249 

writer  on  the  language  of  the  original  will ;  each  felt  sure  in 
his  own  mind  that  the  apprentices  referred  to  must  have  been 
apprentices  of  law,  and  each  of  them  put  in  a  word  or  two  to  make 
this  quite  clear  to  others.  I  naturally  endeavoured  to  obtain  an 
unimproved  transcript  of  the  original  will.  I  searched  in  vain  in 
the  Calendar  of  Wills  proved  and  enrolled  in  the  Court  of  Husting, 
London,  under  the  name  both  of  Tavy  and  Thavy.  Then  a 
friend  suggested  to  me  to  look  under  the  name  of  Tany,  as  an 
n  and  a  v  are  often  written  much  alike  in  old  manuscripts.  And  so 
under  the  name  of  John  Tany,  on  p.  619,  I  found  the  following: — 

Tany  (John),  'armurer.' — The  tenement  which  he  acquired 
from  Master  John  Cok  to  be  sold  by  his  executors  to  pay  his  debts, 
and  the  residue  to  be  devoted  to  pious  uses.  To  Isabella  his 
daughter  a  certain  shop.  All  his  tenements  in  the  parish  of  S. 
Andrew  (sic),  with  the  exception  of  the  aforesaid  shop,  he  leaves 
to  Alice  his  wife  for  life,  after  whose  decease  a  hostel  wherein  his 
apprentices  used  to  live  is  to  be  sold,  and  the  proceeds  devoted  to 
the  maintenance  of  a  chantry,  and  his  mansion  house  and  shops 
to  be  given  to  the  fabric  of  the  church  of  S.  Andrew  in  Holbourn. 
Dated  in  the  parish  of  S.  Andrew  in  Holbourn,  Thursday  next 
before  the  Feast  of  S.  Gregory,  Pope  [12  March],  A.D.  1348. 
Roll  77  (242). 

It  is  clear  then  that  neither  the  word  legis  nor  the  phrase 
ad  legem  occurs  in  the  original  will.  Moreover,  I  am  assured 
by  my  friend  Mr.  E.  Williams,  who  holds  the  deed,  that  in  the 
grant  of  1366  by  which  the  hostel  was  sold  in  fee  to  Roger  de 
Barnburgh  and  Sir  Ely  de  Sutton — only  seventeen  years  after  the 
death  of  Tavy — it  is  expressly  described  as  '  a  messuage  or  hospitium 
in  which  the  apprentices  of  John  Tavy  used  to  dwell.' 

I  conclude  therefore  (a)  that  there  is  no  evidence  to  show  that 
any  student  of  law  ever  dwelt  on  the  land  which  John  Tavy  the 
armourer  owned  in  1348  ;  (b)  that  a  School  of  Law  existed  in  1376, 
and  probably  a  few  years  prior  to  that  date,  on  the  land  which  John 
Davy  occupied  in  that  year ;  (c)  that  there  is  no  evidence  that  this 
School  of  Law  ever  had  anything  to  do  with  either  Temple  ;  it  was 
no  doubt  from  an  early  date  intimately  connected  with  the  Society 
of  Lincoln's  Inn,  which  till  1412  or  a  few  years  later  was  located  in 
its  immediate  neighbourhood. 


250  W.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

LINCOLN'S  INN 

As  we  have  already  seen,  the  ecclesiastics  were  the  first  to 
venture  outside  the  City  walls ;  take,  for  example,  the  Bishop  of 
Ely  who  lived  at  Hatton  Garden  and  the  Bishop  of  Exeter  who 
took  up  his  abode  in  the  Outer  Temple.  So  it  was  that  when 
Ralph  Neville,  the  great  Bishop  of  Chichester,  needed  a  town 
house  for  himself  and  his  successors  in  that  See,  his  eye  fell  on 
the  meadows  to  the  immediate  north  and  east  of  Fickett's  Field 
just  outside  the  new  City  boundary.  And  there  he  built  himself 
a  stately  mansion  in  the  year  1227,  in  which  he  died  in  1244. 
This  mansion  must  have  occupied  the  site  of  the  buildings  which 
lie  to  the  immediate  south  of  Lincoln's  Inn  Old  Hall.  And  behind 
his  house  was  a  garden,  to  the  north  of  it  a  paddock,  and  on  the 
west  side  of  garden  and  paddock  a  coneygarth  or  warren  for  tame 
rabbits.  This  word  was  afterwards  corrupted  into  coninger ;  for 
at  a  later  date  the  spot  is  referred  to  as  Coninger  Field,  and  is 
now  part  of  the  'gardens  of  Lincoln's  Inn.  It  probably  stretched 
as  far  north  as  the  back  gardens  of  the  houses  on  the  south  side 
of  Holborn. 

Anyone  can  find  out  for  himself  exactly  where  the  Bishop's 
mansion  stood  by  walking  up  Chancery  Lane  from  Fleet  Street, 
crossing  Carey  Street  (which  did  not  then  exist),  and  before  he 
comes  to  the  gateway  of  Lincoln's  Inn  he  will  find  on  his  left  hand 
two  courts — Chichester  Rents  and  then  Bishop's  Court.  These 
names  still  commemorate  the  approach  to  the  Bishop's  house  and 
identify  its  situation.  And  in  this  house  successive  Bishops  of 
Chichester  lived  for  nearly  two  hundred  years.  One  of  them,  John 
de  Langton,  was  Chancellor  of  England  from  1292  to  1302,  and 
again  from  1307  to  1310.  After  him,  it  is  said,  the  lane  on  the 
east  side  of  his  house  was  called  Chancellor's  Lane,  which  is  now 
corrupted  into  Chancery  Lane.  The  last  Bishop  who  occupied 
this  house  died  there  in  the  year  1412;  his  successor  preferred  to 
live  elsewhere. 

What  happened  in  the  next  ten  years  we  do  not  know  for 
certain ;  but  by  the  year  1422  we  find  a  fully  constituted  Society 
in  occupation  of  the  Bishop's  property,  which  is  henceforth  known 
by  the  quaint  name  of  the  '  Inn  of  Lincoln's  Inn.'  The  records, 
which  are  known  as  the  Black  Books,  describe  the  life  of  the 


xii]  The  Inns  of  Court  251 

Society  in  delightfully  varied  detail ;  but  they  tell  us  nothing  of 
its  origin.  The  first  Black  Book  begins  in  the  year  1422 ;  it 
contains  entries  which  show  that  at  this  time  the  Society  was 
paying  a  rent  of  ten  marks  a  year  to  the  Bishop  of  Chichester  for 
the  occupation  of  all  that  portion  of  his  premises  that  lay  to  the 
west  of  Chancery  Lane.  The  exact  date  of  the  original  demise  is 
not  known  ;  it  must  have  been  between  1412  and  1422. 

Ralph  Neville,  Bishop  of  Chichester,  also  held  land  on  the 
other  side  of  Chancery  Lane  prior  to  I235.1  He  owned  a  garden 
there  to  the  north  of  the  land  which  the  King  had  granted  to  the 
House  for  the  support  of  the  brethren  converted  from  Judaism  to 
the  Catholic  faith  (afterwards  part  of  the  Liberty  of  the  Rolls). 
This  garden  was  bounded  on  the  north  by  a  ditch  known  in  1262  as 
'  Chaunceleresdich.'  A  portion  of  the  land  which  lay  to  the  north 
of  this  Chancellor's  ditch — between  it  and  Holborn — was  occupied 
in  the  middle  of  the  fourteenth  century  by  Thomas  de  Lincoln,  the 
King's  serjeant,  and  certain  students  of  the  law.  Their  territory 
may  be  roughly  defined  as  the  site  of  Furnival  Street,  which  we 
used  to  call  Castle  Street,  and  of  the  present  Patent  Office  to  the 
south  of  Staple  Inn.  It  was  acquired  in  the  following  way. 

In  1334  the  executors  of  Robert  le  Hende  de  Worcester  granted 
a  plot  of  land  extending  from  the  King's  Street  on  the  north  to 
the  tenement  of  the  Bishop  of  Chichester  on  the  south  to  Thomas 
de  Lincoln  of  the  Common  Bench,  the  King's  serjeant,  who  is 
described  as  the  son  of  Thomas  de  Lincoln.  In  1331  John  de 
Totel  de  Lincoln  had  granted  to  Thomas  de  Lincoln  some  land 
to  the  east  of  this,  and  in  1332  Andrew  Courtays  had  granted  a 
garden  to  the  south-east  of  this  property  to  Thomas  de  Lincoln. 
He  combined  these  three  properties,  and  they  formed  the  first  home 
of  the  Society  of  *  Lyncolnesynne.'  Mr.  Paley  Baildon  has  dis- 
covered that  there  was  an  enormous  increase  in  the  work  of  the 
law  courts  about  1 340,  and  this  would  no  doubt  lead  to  an  increase 
in  the  number  of  the  students  of  the  law  and  necessitate  the 
erection  of  new  hostels. 

In  1348  Thomas  de  Bedic  granted  all  his  rights  of  lordship 
over  this  land  to  Thomas  de  Lincoln.  By  three  deeds  dated 
1364,  1366,  and  1369,  the  fee  simple  of  the  whole  property  was 

1  That  is  perhaps  why  we  still  find  a  court  called  Nevill's  Court  on  the 
east  side  of  Fetter  Lane. 


252  IV.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

conveyed  by  Thomas  de  Lincoln  to  the  Abbot  and  Convent  of 
Malmesbury.  In  1399  a  'Rental'  of  the  property  of  the  Convent 
of  Malmesbury  was  drawn  up  which  shows  a  payment  to  the 
Abbot  of  £8  De  Firmario  novi  hospicii  apud  Londoniam  vocati 
Lyncolnesynne.  And  in  this  Rental  there  is  a  later  entry  on  the 
bottom  margin  of  the  same  page  ;  it  is  undated  but  it  was  probably 
written  early  in  the  fifteenth  century.  It  is  to  the  following 
effect: — Hospicium  Armigeri  jam  magnum  hospitium  quod  est 
ruinosum  reddit  per  annum  40^.  The  rent  had  no  doubt  been 
reduced  from  £8  to  403.  because  of  the  ruinous  condition  of  the 
big  mansion.1 

Hence,  early  in  the  fifteenth  century,  we  find  the  Society  of 
Lincoln's  Inn  located  in  a  mansion  on  the  east  side  of  Chancery 
Lane  which  had  become  ruinous.  The  landlord  apparently  did 
nothing  towards  the  repair  of  the  mansion.  And  so  it  seems  clear 
that  the  Society  moved  across  Chancery  Lane  and  entered  into 
occupation  of  the  house  and  premises  of  the  Bishop  of  Chichester, 

1  For  the  above  details  as  to  the  title  of  these  various  properties  I  am 
indebted  to  Mr.  E.  Williams,  who  is  in  possession  of  the  title-deeds. 
See  also  an  article  by  Mr.  G.  J.  Turner  of  Lincoln's  Inn  in  the  Athenaum, 
September  22,  1906,  p.  335.  It  may  be  interesting  to  subjoin  the  text  of 
the  most  important  entries. 

EXTRACT  FROM  THE  RENTAL  OF  THE  PROPERTY  OF  THE  CONVENT 
OF  MALMESBURY  1399 

'  De  Firmario  novi  hospicii  apud  Londoniam  vocati         .  J 
Lyncolnesynne  ad  iiiior  terininos  solvendo  per  annum   .  \  *!,,     . 

De  tenemento  quondam  Gaillardi  Poet  in  Holbourne     xxs 
De  tenemento  quondam  Walter  Bartone  Allutarii    .     xiils  mid ' 
Written  in  a  different  hand,  with  different  coloured  ink,  at  the  bottom 
margin  of  the  page,  and  certainly  of  a  later  date,  the  following  remarks  have 
been  added  : 

'  London.      Hospicium  Armigeri  jam  magnum  hospitium 

quod  est  ruinosum  reddit  per  annum    .     XLs 
Tenura     Celda  proxima  annexa  hospicio  reddit  per 
tenencium  annum       ......      ixs 

infra  silvam     Secunda  celda  reddit  per  annum        .          .     xs 
magni  hospicii     Tertia  celda  reddit  per  annum  .          .     vills 

Quarta  celda  que  est        .          .          .' 

[Here  the  page  is  cut  away] 

The  ( hospicium  armigeri '  of  the  marginal  note  is  obviously  the  same 
building  as  the  '  Lyncolnesynne '  of  the  former  entry.  Serjeants  were  ex 
officio  'armigeri,'  and,  according  to  Foss,  were  often  so  designated  in  the 
fourteenth  century. 


xii]  The  Inns  of  Court  253 

which  had  lain  empty  since  1412.  The  exact  date  of  this  removal 
we  cannot  fix,  but  it  must  have  been  before  1422  ;  for  in  that  year 
commence  the  Black  Books,  the  first  volume  of  which  is  entitled 
Liber  Hospitii  de  Lincolnsin.  The  earliest  entries  in  this  volume 
show  that  the  persons  then  in  possession  of  those  premises  formed 
a  fully  established  society,  possessing  the  constitution,  powers,  and 
privileges  of  an  Inn  of  Court.  And  those  persons  retained  their 
former  title  of  the  Society  of  Lincoln's  Inn,  and  never  called  them- 
selves Bishop's  Inn  or  Chichester  Inn,  as  would  have  been  the  case 
with  a  society  newly  created.  That  the  Society  of  Lincoln's  Inn 
existed  before  1422  is  clear  from  the  fact  that  in  the  Corporation 
Letter  Books  one  Thomas  Broun  is  described  as  Maunciple  of 
Lincoln's  Inn,  under  date  of  1417. 

Lastly,  we  find  in  the  Black  Books  another  entry  which 
seems  to  establish  the  continuity  of  the  present  Society  with  that 
formed  on  the  other  side  of  Chancery  Lane  by  the  King's  serjeant. 
In  1466  the  Society  was  paying  95.  yearly  to  the  Prior  of  St.  Giles' 
Hospital  for  Lepers  for  another  part  of  its  property ;  and  no  other 
rents,  apparently,  were  being  paid  for  any  other  part  on  the  west 
side  of  Chancery  Lane.  But  on  p.  8  of  vol.  i  of  the  Black  Books 
of  the  present  Society  the  following  entry  occurs  : — 

In  the  vigil  of  the  Apostles  Peter  and  Paul  16  Henry  VI 
(1438)  John  Row  delivered  to  John  Fortescue  and  others  in  the 
name  of  the  Society  to  be  paid  to  ...  Halssewylle  for  the  farm  of 
Lyncollysyn  in  arrear  for  the  I5th  year  (Henry  VI)  in  the  time  of 
Bartholomew  Bolney  then  Pensioner  in  full  payment  403.  out  of 
money  received  by  him. 

That  is  to  say,  the  Society  of  Lincoln's  Inn,  now  settled  in  the 
Bishop  of  Chichester's  mansion,  was  still  paying  the  identical  rent 
of  403.  which  it  paid  at  the  commencement  of  the  century  for  the 
ruinous  hospitium  of  Lyncolnesynne. 

THE  LEGEND  OF  THE  EARL  OF  LINCOLN 

But,  as  time  ran  on,  the  King's  serjeant  was  forgotten ;  no  one 
remembered  Thomas  de  Lincoln  and  his  hospice  to  the  north  of 
the  Chancellor's  ditch.  And  men  began  to  wonder  why  the  Society 
was  called  'Lincoln's  Inn/  The  name  did  not  seem  to  have « any 
connexion  with  the  history  of  the  Society's  present  abode ;  from 


254  ^  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

what  source  then  did  it  come  ?  And  some  one  must  have  recol- 
lected that  there  was  an  Earl  of  Lincoln  who  was  a  famous  man  in 
the  reign  of  Edward  I,  and  who  resided  somewhere  in  this  locality  ; 
possibly  he  was  the  founder  of  the  Society.  And  in  that  uncritical 
age  the  suggestion  soon  found  favour. 

Hence  it  is  that  we  find  in  the  Origines  Juridiciales  (at  p.  231) 
the  following  remarkable  passage  : — 

After  this  Ralph  Nevill,  Richard  de  Wihtz  (commonly  called 
Saint  Richard)  had  also  his  residence  here.  But  in  the  next  age 
Henry  Lacy,  Earl  of  Lincolne  became  possest  thereof,  and  resided 
in  it ;  whereupon  as  many  other  great  Houses,  did  in  those  dayes 
take  denomination  from  their  Owners,  this  had  then  accordingly 
the  name  of  Lincolnes  Inne,  and  hath  ever  since  been  so  called. 

Of  this  Henry,  Earl  of  Lincolne,  is  the  tradition  still  current 
amongst  the  Antients  here ;  that  he,  about  the  beginning  of  King 
Edward  the  seconds  time,  being  a  person  well  affected  to  the 
knowledge  of  the  Lawes,  first  brought  in  the  professors  of  that 
honourable  and  necessary  study,  to  settle  in  this  place  :  but  direct 
proof  thereof  from  good  Authority,  I  have  not  as  yet  seen  any. 

There  was  good  ground  for  Dugdale's  scepticism.  No  Earl  of 
Lincoln  ever  owned  or  occupied  any  portion  of  the  land  which 
belonged  in  Dugdale's  day  to  the  Honourable  Society  of  Lincoln's 
Inn.  Every  square  inch  of  this  land  was  the  property  of  the  See 
of  Chichester  from  1227,  when  it  was  granted  to  Bishop  Neville,  to 
1537)  when  Bishop  Sampson  sold  it  to  the  Inn.  And  the  only 
mansion  on  the  land  was,  as  we  have  seen,  occupied  by  successive 
bishops  from  1227  till  1412. 

There  was  no  doubt  at  the  beginning  of  the  fourteenth  century 
a  great  man  living  in  this  neighbourhood,  Henry  De  Lacy,  Earl  of 
Lincoln  and  Salisbury.  He  owned  the  whole  manor  of  Holborn, 
having  purchased  it  in  1286  for  550  marks  from  the  Black  Friars, 
who  had  occupied  it  from  1215.  His  mansion  stood  in  Shoe  Lane 
on  the  slope  of  Holborn  Hill,  to  the  south-east  of  St.  Andrew's 
Church.  He  was  a  valiant  knight  and  an  able  statesman  ;  he  was 
also  a  successful  market-gardener.  He  made  a  considerable  sum 
of  money  (for  those  days)  by  the  sale  of  his  fruit  and  vegetables. 
He  was  famous  for  the  beauty  of  his  gardens,  which  stretched 
down  almost  to  Fleet  Street.  Think  of  him  in  his  manor  house  on 
the  slope  of  Holborn  Hill  looking  across  the  Fleet  brook  at  the  little 
city  still  encircled  by  its  Roman  wall. 


xn]  The  Inns  of  Court  255 

Forget  six  counties  overhung  with  smoke, 
Forget  the  snorting  steam  and  piston  stroke, 
Forget  the  spreading  of  the  hideous  town  ; 
Think  rather  of  the  pack-horse  on  the  down, 
And  dream  of  London,  small,  and  white,  and  clean, 
The  clear  Thames  bordered  by  its  gardens  green. 

And  in  this  house  Henry  De  Lacy,  Earl  of  Lincoln,  died  in 
1311  ;  and  his  mansion  and  his  manor  passed  to  his  son-in-law  the 
Earl  of  Lancaster,  Lord  High  Steward  of  England  and  cousin  of 
the  King,  and  was  subsequently  owned  by  other  persons  of  high 
rank,  whose  title  to  them  is  well  known.  There  is  not  the  faintest 
evidence  that  any  professors  or  students  of  the  law  ever  occupied 
any  portion  of  Earl  De  Lacy's  house  or  grounds. 

To  get  over  this  difficulty  it  has  recently  been  suggested  that 
what  the  Earl  did  was  to  establish  the  lawyers  not  in  his  residence, 
but  in  Thavie's  Inn,  which  stood  at  a  little  distance  from  it  on 
the  other  side  of  Shoe  Lane.  But  this  he  would  have  had  no 
right  to  do.  The  Earl  never  owned  either  the  house  which  was 
later  called  Davy's  or  Thavie's  Inn,  nor  that  which  twelve  years 
after  the  Earl's  death  became  the  property  of  John  Tavy,  the 
armourer.  The  Earl  would  have  had  no  possible  right  *  to  bring 
in '  professors  of  the  law  into  either  house. 

And  note  that  the  tradition  recorded  by  Dugdale  does  not 
assert  either  of  these  propositions.  Still  less  does  it  assert  that 
the  Earl  brought  the  lawyers  into  his  house  in  Shoe  Lane.  It 
rests  upon  the  assumption  that  in  the  reign  of  Edward  II.  he 
'  became  possessed  of,  and  resided  in/  the  mansion  built  by  Ralph 
Neville,  which  we  know  to  be  untrue.  The  fact  is  that  the  name 
'  Lincoln's  Inn '  is  in  no  way  derived  from  or  connected  with 
Henry  De  Lacy,  Earl  of  Lincoln.  Yet  the  Society  in  1518  placed 
his  arms  on  the  side  of  their  gatehouse  facing  Chancery  Lane, 
where  they  still  remain.  And  in  1553  they  placed  them  with 
other  coats  on  the  '  loover  or  lanthorn '  over  their  Old  Hall.1 


GRAY'S  INN 

Gray's  Inn,  like  Lincoln's  Inn,  lies  wholly  without  the  City 
boundary ;  for  though  it  is  in  the  parish  of  St.  Andrew's,  Holborn, 
none  of  it  is  within  the  ward  of  Farringdon.  It  is,  in  all  prob- 

1  Dugdale,  Orig.  Jurid.^  p.  232. 


256  IV.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

ability,  as  old  or  nearly  as  old  as  the  other  Inns  of  Court.  Sir 
George  Buc  records  a  tradition  currrent  at  the  Bar  in  Elizabeth's 
reign  that  Gray's  Inn  had  been  an  Inn  of  Court  since  the  days 
of  Edward  •III.1  It  lies  within  the  Manor  of  Portpool ;  and  this 
Manor  undoubtedly  belonged  as  early  as  1298  to  Reginald,  Lord 
Grey  de  Wilton,  Chief  Justice  of  Chester.  But  there  were  no 
lawyers  there  during  his  lifetime.  The  precise  date  at  which  the 
students  of  the  law  ventured  to  come  outside  the  City  walls  and 
settle  in  or  near  the  ancient  manor  house  of  Lord  Grey  de  Wilton 
cannot  be  precisely  ascertained.  They  came  no  doubt  from  the 
Inns  of  Chancery  on  the  south  side  of  Holborn,  and  especially 
from  Staple  Inn  and  Barnard's  Inn. 

The  earliest  records  which  Gray's  Inn  now  possesses  are  the 
Pension  Books,  which  begin  in  the  year  1 569 ;  there  was  an  older 
volume,  to  which  Dugdale  had  access,  but  which  now  is  lost.  The 
Inn  also  has  preserved  a  list  of  its  Benchers  and  Readers,  prepared 
by  its  butler  Segar  in  the  time  of  Charles  II,  which  makes  the 
Inn  date  back  to  1355  ;  but  this  list  is  not  trustworthy.  In  1589 
Yelverton,  J.,  spoke  of  Gray's  Inn  as  having  been  founded  *  two 
hundred  years  ago  at  least,'  but  we  cannot  implicitly  rely  on  a 
statement  in  round  numbers  such  as  this.  One  thing,  however, 
is  certain.  I  have  already  quoted  the  Paston  Letters,  and  it  is 
marvellous  what  valuable  things  we  find  in  that  collection  of 
letters,  discovered  almost  by  an  accident.  In  1454  William  Paston 
wrote  to  his  father  that  when  on  a  journey  he  had  met  Sir  William 
Bylling,  Chief  Justice  of  the  King's  Bench,  and  this  learned  judge 
said  to  him:  'I  was  a  felaw  in  Gray's  Inn  along  with  Ledam.' 
The  word  *  felaw '  was  applied  in  those  days  to  any  member  of 
one  of  these  Societies,  and  it  would  probably  even  then  take  a 
student  forty  years  to  attain  to  the  dignity  of  a  Chief  Justice ;  so 
that  there  must  have  been  a  fully-constituted  Inn,  either  of  Court 
or  of  Chancery,  on  this  spot  at  or  soon  after  the  accession  of 
Henry  V  in  1413. 

In  1 505  the  ninth  Lord  Grey  de  Wilton,  by  indenture  of  bargain 
and  sale,  assigned  '  to  Hugh  Denys,  Esquire,  his  heirs  and  assigns, 
the  manor  of  Portpool,  otherwise  called  Gray's  Inn,  including  two 
messuages,  four  gardens,  the  site  of  a  windmill,  eight  acres  of  land, 
ten  shillings  of  free  rent,  and  the  advowson  of  the  chantry  of  Port- 
1  S tow's  Chronicle,  p.  1073. 


xn]  The  Inns  of  Court  257 

poole  aforesaid.'  Some  eight  years  later,  in  1513,  the  Prior  and 
convent  of  Shene  (that  is  Richmond,  in  Surrey)  bought  the  manor 
from  Denys'  trustees.  In  1516  a  society  consisting  of  two  Serjeants 
and  four  barristers  took  a  lease  of  the  Manor  of  Portpool  from  the 
Prior  of  Shene  for  los.  a  year  and  a  fine  of  £6: 13:4.  On  this 
manor  still  stood  the  ancient  house  of  Lord  Grey  de  Wilton,  of 
which  probably  this  society  was  already  in  occupation.  The  manor 
escheated  to  the  Crown  at  the  dissolution  of  the  monasteries,  but 
Henry  VIII  renewed  the  lease,  and  the  Inn  has  long  ago  bought 
the  freehold. 

The  beautiful  Hall  of  Gray's  Inn  was  finished  in  1563 — eight 
years  before  the  Hall  of  the  Middle  Temple,  which  it  much 
resembles.  At  this  time  houses  had  been  built  along  Holborn, 
almost  as  far  as  Southampton  Row ;  Warwick  Court  was  already 
in  existence,  but  there  was  no  entrance  into  South  Square  from 
Holborn  ;  that  was  made  by  Francis  Bacon  at  a  later  date.  Gray's 
Inn  was  approached  by  a  gate  leading  into  Gray's  Inn  Square,  to 
the  north  of  the  chapel  and  the  Hall ;  that  is  why  the  old  gate  of 
the  Hall  is  on  its  northern  side.  And  once  more  I  would  point  out 
how  history  lingers  in  the  names  of  streets.  There  is  still  a  street 
called  Portpool  Lane,  that  runs  in  a  line  with  Hatton  Wall  from 
Leather  Lane  to  Gray's  Inn,  which  it  strikes  to  the  north  of  the 
chapel  and  the  Hall.  This  was  no  doubt  a  short  cut  from  the 
bottom  of  Holborn  Hill  to  the  Manor  of  Portpool,  and  later  to  the 
northern  gate  of  Gray's  Inn. 

THE  INNS  OF  CHANCERY 

It  is  clear  then  that  the  Inner  and  Middle  Temple,  Lincoln's 
Inn,  and  Gray's  Inn  were  all  established  as  distinct  societies  by 
the  end  of  the  fourteenth  century.  They  were  by  that  time 
accepted  as  general  schools  of  law,  and  had  acquired  recognized 
privileges  as  Inns  of  Court  although  they  held  no  charter  from 
the  Crown.  But,  in  addition  to  these  four  Inns  of  Court,  there 
were — as  we  learn  from  Sir  John  Fortescue,  who  wrote  in  1470 — 
'ten  lesser  Inns,  and  sometimes  more,  which  are  called  Inns  of 
Chancery,  in  each  of  which  there  are  an  hundred  students  at  the 
least.'  In  Lord  Coke's  time  there  were  only  eight. 

There  is  much  that  might  be  said  about  the  Inns  of  Chancery 

s 


258  IV.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

if  time  permitted.  In  the  Inns  of  Court  dwelt  those  advocates  who 
had  not  attained  to  the  degree  of  serjeant-at-law,  and  also  the  more 
advanced  students.  In  the  Inns  of  Chancery  resided  the  Clerks  of 
the  Chancery,  who  prepared  the  original  writs  for  the  King's  Courts, 
and  also  the  younger  apprentices  who  copied  these  writs,  and  thus 
acquired  some  elementary  knowledge  of  civil  procedure.  With  the 
possible  exception  of  Simond's  Inn  and  Staple  Inn,  the  Inns  of 
Chancery  differed  in  their  constitutions  in  no  essential  particular 
from  the  Inns  of  Court.  But  the  main  distinction  between  these 
two  classes  of  Inns  was  this — that  the  Inns  of  Court  could  call  men 
to  the  Bar,  and  thus  confer  upon  them  the  privilege  of  acting  as 
advocates  in  the  King's  Courts.  This  no  Inn  of  Chancery  could 
do.  How  the  Inns  of  Court  acquired  this  privilege  it  seems  now 
impossible  definitely  to  ascertain.  Nor  is  it  clear  why  the  Inns  of 
Chancery  did  not  possess  it  also  ;  for  some  of  these — Clifford's  Inn, 
for  instance — appear  to  be  of  as  ancient  a  date  as  the  present  Inns 
of  Court.  But  the  four  Inns  of  Court  in  some  way  acquired  the 
mastery,  while  the  Inns  of  Chancery  fell  into  the  second  rank. 
They  served  as  preparatory  schools  for  the  Inns  of  Court  up  to  the 
end  of  the  sixteenth  century  ;  each  Inn  of  Court  appears  to  have 
periodically  sent  to  every  Inn  of  Chancery  attached  to  it  a  reader,1 
accompanied  by  two  '  utter  barristers/  who  there  discussed  points 
of  law  and  presided  over  '  moots.'  This  committee  of  three  had 
the  power  of  bringing  over  each  term  the  two  most  promising 
students  of  the  Inn  of  Chancery  and  passing  them  into  the  Inn 
of  Court.  Hence  many  students  entered  an  Inn  of  Chancery  in 
the  first  instance,  and  were  thence  transferred  to  an  Inn  of  Court. 
Throughout  the  Tudor  period  this  custom  was  generally  observed, 
though  by  the  time  of  Sir  Matthew  Hale  it  had  become  obsolete. 

In  the  reigns  of  Queen  Elizabeth  and  James  I.  Orders  were 
passed  by  the  four  Inns  forbidding  '  common  attorneys '  and 
solicitors  from  joining  an  Inn  of  Court,  and  this  exclusion  was 
confirmed  by  further  Orders  passed  by  the  judges  and  also  by 
the  Privy  Council.  But  these  new  regulations  were  not  strictly 
observed.  Attorneys  and  solicitors  were  not  wholly  excluded 
from  the  Inns  of  Court  until  towards  the  close  of  the  eighteenth 

1  Thus  Mr.  Thomas  More  of  Lincoln's  Inn  went  as  reader  to  Furnival's 
Inn  in  the  reign  of  Henry  VIII,  and  Mr.  Edward  Coke  of  the  Inner  Temple 
was  reader  at  Lyon's  Inn  in  the  reign  of  Elizabeth. 


xii]  The  Inns  of  Court  259 

century.  One  consequence  of  this  exclusion  was  that  it  now 
became  impossible  for  attorneys  and  solicitors  to  be  heard  as 
advocates  in  the  superior  courts  of  law  and  equity.  Another 
and  a  later  result  was  the  rule  of  our  profession  that  a  barrister 
can  only  plead  in  those  courts  when  he  has  been  instructed  >  by 
an  attorney  or  solicitor.  But  in  the  meantime  the  attorneys, 
being  thus  excluded  from  the  Inns  of  Court,  gradually  obtained 
entire  control  of  the  Inns  of  Chancery. 

The  Inns  of  Chancery  have  now  all  ceased  to  exist  as  schools 
of  law.  Staple  Inn,  which  Sir  George  Buc  described  as  'the 
fayrest  Inne  of  Chancery  in  this  University,'  still  stands  intact ; 
for  this  we  have  to  thank  the  Prudential  Assurance  Company,  its 
present  owners.  Barnard's  Inn,  close  at  hand,  is  now  the  property 
of  the  Mercers'  Company.  The  boys  of  the  Mercers'  School  have 
their  lunch  daily  in  its  old  hall,  which  the  Company  has  carefully 
preserved.  We  have  already  traced  the  early  history  of  Thavie's 
Inn ;  a  small  portion  of  one  wall  is  all  that  is  left  standing ;  the 
rest  is  occupied  by  part  of  a  modern  street  called  St.  Bride's  Street. 
Furnival's  Inn  was  pulled  down  in  the  reign  of  Charles  I,  but 
was  rebuilt  by  Inigo  Jones  and  lasted  until  1820;  it  stood  on 
the  site  now  occupied  by  the  offices  of  the  Prudential  Assurance 
Company.  Passing  south  to  Fleet  Street  we  find  Clifford's  Inn  still 
standing,  close  to  St.  Dunstan's  Church.  It  was  founded  as  a  school 
of  law  by  Lady  Clifford  in  1344.  It  was  from  the  first  connected 
with  the  Inner  Temple,  and  many  of  its  students  have  from  time 
to  time  crossed  Fleet  Street  to  join  that  Inn  of  Court.  But  there  is 
no  evidence  that  there  ever  was  a  migration  of  any  considerable  body 
of  students  from  one  to  the  other.  Clement's  Inn,  which  adjoined 
St.  Clement's  Church  and  the  Holy-well,  is  now  a  row  of  handsome 
offices.  New  Inn  was  demolished  when  Holywell  Street  and  Wych 
Street  were  pulled  down  in  order  to  widen  the  Strand.  Lyon's  Inn, 
which  stood  between  Holywell  Street  and  Wych  Street,  was  pulled 
down  in  1863  to  make  room  for  the  Globe  Theatre.  Strand  Inn, 
which  stood  on  the  south  side  of  the  Strand,  opposite  the  Church  of 
St.  Mary-le-Strand,  was  demolished  by  Protector  Somerset  in  the 
reign  of  Edward  VI,  in  order  to  make  room  for  his  new  palace, 
which  we  now  know  as  Somerset  House. 

So  the  Inns  of  Chancery  have  one  by  one  disappeared ;  none 
of  them,  at  all  events,  are  in  use  to-day  as  places  of  legal  education. 


260  W.  Blake  Odgers  [xn 

But  the  Inns  of  Court  still  stand  four-square — the  Inns  which 
were  described  by  James  I  in  his  charter  of  August  13,  1608, 
as  '  those  four  colleges,  the  most  famous  in  all  Europe.'  Long 
may  they  flourish !  To  them  has  been  entrusted  the  exclusive 
power  of  admitting  students  of  law  to  the  Bar  of  England ; 
on  them  has  been  conferred  the  right  and  the  duty  of  selecting 
those  who  shall  enjoy  the  monopoly  of  audience  in  the  superior 
courts  of  England.  His  call  to  the  Bar  confers  great  privileges 
and  powers  on  the  young  advocate.  He  is  given  the  right,  the 
terrible  right,  of  almost  unfettered  cross-examination.  He  has 
also  the  right  in  his  discretion  to  attack  the  character  of  a  party 
or  a  witness,  and  no  action  for  slander  can  be  brought  against  him. 
Such  powers  must  be  entrusted  only  to  persons  who  will  use  them 
honourably  and  well.  Should  they  pass  into  the  hands  of  unfit 
and  dishonourable  men  they  will  be  taken  away  from  the  whole 
Bar.  Those  who  confer  the  privilege  of  audience  in  the  High 
Court  of  the  Kingdom  must  therefore  also  have  the  power  to  take 
that  privilege  away. 

The  ancient  Inns  of  Court,  whose  history  1  have  been  endeavour- 
ing to  impart  to  you  to-day,  still  retain,  and  rightly  retain,  the  two 
high  privileges  of  calling  worthy  men  to  the  Bar,  and  of  disbarring 
those  who  prove  to.be  unworthy.  And  I  may  add,  I  think,  that 
they  exercise  these  powers  to  the  general  satisfaction  of  the  English 
nation. 

W.  BLAKE  ODGERS. 


XIII 

THE    EARLY    HISTORY   OF    ENGLISH 
EQUITY 

ONE  of  the  most  striking  features  of  the  English  system  of  justice 
prior  to  the  Judjrature  Acts  was  the  dual  system  of  courts  adminis- 
tering a  dual  system  of  justice — common  law  rules  and  remedies 
and  equitable  rules  and  remedies.  This  dual  system  of  courts  had 
not  always  existed ;  and  the  significance  of  the  Judicature  Acts 
lies  in  the  fact  that  it  brought  back  conditions  that  existed  before 
the  Chancery  acquired  its  position  as  a  court  of  equity.  Even  the 
Chancery  exercised  a  common  law  as  well  as  an  equitable  jurisdic- 
tion, and  long  before  the  establishment  of  the  Chancery  as  a  court 
of  justice  older  tribunals  had  exercised  a  jurisdiction  both  at  law 
and  in  equity.  The  beginnings  of  English  equity  are  to  be  sought 
in  the  history  of  these  older  courts — the  common  law  courts  them- 
selves, the  local  courts,  the  ecclesiastical  courts,  and  Parliament 
and  the  Council  acting  in  their  judicial  capacity.  In  the  present 
paper  I  wish  to  draw  attention  to  the  equitable  jurisdiction  of  the 
early  common  law  courts,  omitting  all  reference  to  the  equity  of 
local  and  ecclesiastical  courts  and  of  Parliament  and  the  Council. 

The  Prankish  king's  court  exercised  what  amounted  to  an 
equitable  jurisdiction.  Based,  perhaps,  partly  upon  this  earlier 
practice  in  the  land  of  our  legal  ancestors  and  partly  upon  the 
royal  justice  of  Anglo-Saxon  times,  the  English  king's  courts  in 
the  centuries  immediately  following  the  Norman  Conquest  not 
only  developed  the  principles  of  the  early  common  law,  but  also 
administered  a  softening  and  supplementing  equity  that  was  dis- 
tinguished, both  in  the  theory  and  in  the  practice  of  the  times, 

261 


262  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xm 

from  the  rigour  of  the  common  law  itself.  As  the  king's  courts 
were  not  yet  greatly  checked  by  legislation  and  by  judicial 
precedent,  but  were  possessed  rather  of  very  wide  discretionary 
powers,  the  need  of  a  separate  and  distinct  equity  court  seems  not 
to  have  been  felt :  the  king's  courts  themselves  could  do  whatever 
equity  required.  But  this  early  equity  of  the  common  law  courts 
— the  King's  Bench,  Common  Pleas,  and  Exchequer — was  much 
more  than  a  broad,  vague,  and  mystical  doing  of  justice ;  for  these 
courts  developed  a  rudimentary  system  of  equitable  principles  and 
equitable  remedies  very  like,  in  some  respects,  the  more  fully 
and  elaborately  developed  system  of  the  Chancery  in  a  later  age.1 
Procedure  by  bills  in  eyre,  as  we  have  so  recently  learned  from 
Mr.  Bolland,  seems  actually  to  have  been  the  predecessor  of  the 
Chancery's  procedure  by  bills  in  equity.2  But  what  I  am  now 
desirous  of  showing  is  that  even  the  common  law  system  of 
original  and  judicial  writs  gave  the  common  law  courts  an  oppor- 
tunity to  administer  equity.  The  oldest  actions  of  the  common 
law  seem  indeed  to  have  been  mostly  actions  brought  not  so  much 
for  'damages,'  the  characteristic  relief  of  the  classical  common 
law,  as  for  what  Chancery  lawyers,  at  a  later  day,  designated 
'specific  relief;  and  in  administering  justice  by  writ  process,  the 
early  justices  not  only  gave  judgments  in  rem,  but  also  what  we 
must  designate  ( decrees  in  personamj  decrees  that  under  the  in- 
fluence of  the  subpoena  became  so  marked  a  feature  of  the  equity 
of  the  Chancellors.3 

I  propose  in  the  present  paper  to  give  a  short  account  of  the 
following  branches  of  this  early  equity  of  the  common  law  courts  : 
(i)  Uses,  (2)  Gages,  (3)  Penalties,  (4)  Specific  Performance,  (5) 
Prohibitions,  (6)  Writs  Quia  Timet. 

I.  USES 

The  recent  researches  of  Pollock,  Maitland,  and  other  legal 
historians  prove  that  the  practice  of  conveying  land  to  uses  began 

1  See  the  present  writer's  essay  entitled   '  Early  History  of  Specific  Per- 
formance of  Contract  in  English  Law'  (Festgabe fur  Kohler,  68,  69). 

2  Y.B.  Edward  II,  Eyre  of  Kent,  6  and  7  Edward  II  1313-14  (Selden 
Soc.),  vol.  ii.  (1912),  xxi-xxx. 

3  See  further  the  present  writer's  essay  referred  to  in  note   i   supra,  and 
the  literature  therein  cited  ;  also  Bigelow,  Hist,  of  Proced.  in  Eng.  chap.  iv. 


xin]  Early  Equity  263 

long  before  the  interest  of  the  cestui  que  use  was  protected  by  the 
subpoena  of  the  Chancellor.  It  is  the  generally  accepted  view 
that  in  this  earliest  period  of  the  history  of  the  use  of  land  the 
obligation  of  the  feoffee  to  uses  was  purely  moral,  and  was  un- 
enforced  by  judicial  process  in  royal  courts.1 

In  opposition  to  this  view  Mr.  Justice  Holmes  maintains,  in 
his  essay  on  '  Early  English  Equity/ 2  that  the  enforcement  of  uses 
did  not  originate  in  the  Chancery  and  was  not  based  upon  the 
personal  obedience  of  the  feoffee  to  the  subpoena.  According  to 
Holmes  the  early  feoffee  to  uses  was  but  the  salman  or  treuhand 
of  early  German  law  transplanted  to  English  soil.  This  position 
is  confirmed,  in  Holmes's  view,  by  the  fact  that  the  executor  of 
the  Continent  was  simply  the  Germanic  treuhand  somewhat 
modified  under  the  influence  of  Roman  legal  notions,  and  that  the 
Continental  executor  and  the  English  executor  of  Glanvill's  time 
were  undoubtedly  identical.  When  we  look  at  the  protection 
accorded  to  the  cestui  que  use,  contends  the  learned  justice,  we 
find  that  both  the  common  law  and  the  ecclesiastical  courts  were 
prepared  to  give  remedies.  It  was  usual  for  feoffees  to  uses  to 
enter  into  covenants  in  favour  of  their  feoffors.  In  cases  therefore 
where  feoffors  were  themselves  the  cestuis  que  usent,  they  were 
protected  as  against  their  feoffees  by  the  common  law  writ  of 
covenant :  and  by  this  writ  the  feoffor  might  even  recover  the 
land  itself.  If  the  cestui  que  use  was  a  third  person  and  thus  a 
stranger  to  the  covenant,  he  was  unable  to  invoke  the  protection 
of  the  common  law  courts  on  their  doctrine  of  covenants,  but  he 
could  and  did  reach  the  feoffee,  in  the  ecclesiastical  courts,  for 
breach  of  faith.  At  a  later  time  ecclesiastical  Chancellors  developed 
the  use  more  fully  than  their  predecessors  of  the  church  courts 
had  been  able  to  do. 

Into  the  arguments  that  have  been  advanced  against  Mr.  Justice 
Holmes's  view  I  cannot  now  enter.  I  must  be  content  to  have 
drawn  your  attention  to  the  fact  that,  at  least  in  Holmes's  view, 
the  early  common  law  courts  were  employing  their  writ  of  covenant 
for  the  enforcement  of  uses  long  before  the  Chancellor  made  use  of 
a  more  comprehensive  and  effective  remedy — the  subpoena. 

1  See  Pollock  and  Maitland,  History  of  English  Law,  2nd  ed.,  228-239  ; 
Ames,  'The  Origin  of  Uses'  (Lectures  on  Legal  History,  1913,  pp.  233-247). 

2  Select  Essays  in  Anglo-American  Legal  History,  vol.  ii.  705-721. 


264  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xra 

It  appears  also  that  the  early  common  law  courts  were  enforcing 
uses  or  trusts  of  chattels  and  money  by  the  writs  of  detinue  and 
account.  Ames,  in  his  essays  on  the  '  History  of  Parol  Contracts 
Prior  to  Assumpsit ' 1  and  the  '  Origin  of  Uses  and  Trusts,' 2  has 
dealt  fully  with  this  phase  of  the  equity  of  the  common  law  courts. 
He  has  shown  that  on  the  delivery  of  money  by  one  man  to 
another  to  the  use  of  a  third,  this  third  person — the  beneficiary — 
was  permitted  to  bring  the  action  of  account  against  the  one  who 
had  received  the  money  to  his  use.  In  the  same  way  the  bailment 
of  a  chattel  to  the  use  of  a  third  party  was  enforced  by  this  third 
party — the  beneficiary — in  the  action  of  detinue.  It  is  Ames's 
view,  to  quote  his  own  words,  that  '  a  defendant's  duty  to  account, 
whether  as  bailiff  or  receiver,  arose  from  his  receipt  of  property  as 
a  trustee,  and  that  a  plaintiff  entitled  to  an  account  was  strictly  a 
cestui  que  trust.  In  other  words,  trusts  for  the  payment  of  money 
were  enforced  at  common  law  long  before  Chancery  gave  effect  to 
trusts  of  land.  .  .  .  Account  against  a  receiver  was  long  ago  super- 
seded by  the  common  count  for  money  had  and  received  by  the 
defendant  to  the  use  of  the  plaintiff.  But  the  words  "to  the 
use  of"  still  bear  witness  to  the  trust  relation.'  '  It  must  have  been 
all  the  easier  for  the  Chancellor,'  says  Ames  in  another  place,  '  to 
allow  the  subpoena  against  the  feoffee  to  uses  because  the  common 
law  gave  a  remedy  against  a  fiduciary  who  had  received  chattels 
or  money  to  be  delivered  to  a  third  person,  or,  as  it  was  often 
expressed,  to  the  use  of  a  third  person,  or  to  be  redelivered  to  the 
person  from  whom  he  had  received  the  chattels  or  the  money.' 

It  is  likewise  contended  by  this  distinguished  historian  of 
English  law  that '  as  the  Chancellor,  in  giving  effect  to  uses  declared 
upon  a  feoffment,  followed  the  analogy  of  the  common  law  bailment 
of  chattels,  or  the  delivery  of  money  upon  the  common  law  trust, 
so  in  enforcing  the  use  growing  out  of  a  bargain  and  sale,  he 
followed  another  analogy  of  the  common  law,  that  of  the  sale  of  a 
chattel.  The  purchaser  of  a  chattel,  who  had  paid  or  become 
indebted  for  the  purchase  money,  had  an  action  of  detinue  against 
the  seller.  Similarly  the  buyer  of  land  who  had  paid  or  become  a 
debtor  for  the  price  of  the  land,  was  given  the  right  of  a  cestui  que 
use  [by  the  Chancellor].' 

1  Select  Essays  in  Anglo-American  Legal  History,  vol.  iii.  304-319. 

2  Ibid.  vol.  ii.  737-752. 


xiii}  Early  Equity  265 

Ames's  doctrine  as  to  the  so-called  common  law  trust  of  chattels 
and  money  has  not  gone  unchallenged.  Hening,  for  example,  in 
his  'History  of  the  Beneficiary's  Action  in  Assumpsit,'1  contends 
that  the  obligation  of  the  bailee  of  a  chattel  and  the  receiver  of 
money  as  regards  the  beneficiary  cannot  be  ranged  under  the 
category  of  trusts,  in  the  modern  sense,  because  the  conception  of 
an  '  equitable  ownership '  in  the  beneficiary  was  lacking  in  the  early 
common  law.  Although  we  cannot  pursue  this  inquiry  further  at 
the  present  time,  we  should  note  in  passing  that,  whether  or  not 
we  agree  fully  with  Ames's  view,  certainly  the  early  common  law 
courts  were  enforcing  by  means  of  the  writs  of  detinue  and  account, 
obligations  of  at  least  a  fiduciary  character — the  obligations  of 
persons  who  received  chattels  and  money  to  the  use  of  others. 

II.  GAGES 

A  study  of  the  law  of  securities  on  property  in  the  time  of 
Henry  the  Second  throws  much  light  upon  the  equitable  nature  of 
certain  features  of  the  procedure  in  the  king's  court.2  The  court 
enforced  both  the  usufruct-gage  and  the  property-gage  of  land. 
The  property -gage  assumed  the  form  of  a  conveyance  under 
condition  precedent.  If  the  parties  include  a  clause  of  forfeiture  in 
their  contract,  the  gaged  land,  already  in  the  creditor's  possession, 
will  at  once  become  his  absolute  property,  upon  the  principle  of 
forfeiture,  on  the  debtor's  failure  to  pay  at  the  fixed  day.  On  the 
other  hand,  should  the  contract  contain  no  clause  of  forfeiture, 
the  creditor  must  go  into  court,  and  there  must  be  certain  legal 
proceedings  before  the  law  will  view  the  gaged  land  as  absolutely 
forfeited  to  the  creditor  for  non-payment  of  the  debt.  These 
proceedings  are  essentially  equitable  in  character,  and  show  very 
clearly  that  the  common  law  courts  of  the  twelfth  century  had 
already  arrived  at  a  conception  of  what  Chancery  judges  of  later 
times  will  designate  the  '  equity  of  redemption '  and  the  '  decree  of 
foreclosure.'  What  are  these  equitable  proceedings  of  the  king's 
court  ? 

1  Select  Essays  in  Anglo-American  Legal  History,  vol.  iii.  339-367. 

2  See    the    present    writer's     '  Gage    of    Land    in    Medieval     England ' 
(Harvard  Law  Review,  xviii.  552  seq.  ;  also  Select  Essays  in  Anglo-American 
Legal   History,   vol.    iii.    646-672),   and    also    his    Geschichte   des  englischen 
Pfandrechts,  29,  198,  200,  213-232,  248  seq. 


266  H.  D.  Plazeltine  [xm 

If  the  land  be  gaged  for  a  term,  and  if  the  debtor  fail  to  pay  at 
the  end  of  the  term,  the  creditor  must  sue  him.  The  debtor  is  then 
compelled  to  appear  in  court  in  answer  to  a  writ  ordering  him  to 
' acquit'  or  redeem  the  gage.  If  then  in  court  the  debt  and  the 
gage  be  confessed  by  the  debtor  or  otherwise  proved  by  the 
creditor,  the  debtor  is  ordered  by  the  court  to  redeem  the  gage 
within  a  *  reasonable '  time  by  payment  of  the  debt ;  and  the  court 
at  the  same  time  declares  that,  in  case  of  default  in  payment  at 
the  end  of  this  new  period,  the  gaged  land  shall  become  the 
property  of  the  gagee  and  thus  forfeited  for  the  debt.1 

If,  on  the  other  hand,  the  gage  be  given  indefinitely  or  without 
a  term,  the  creditor  may  at  any  time  demand  the  debt.  To  all 
seeming  this  means  that  the  creditor  can  at  any  time  go  into  court 
and  get  a  judgment  ordering  the  debtor  to  redeem  within  some 
fixed  and  reasonable  period ;  and  that  the  court  will  at  the  same 
time  declare  that,  if  the  debtor  fail  thus  to  redeem,  the  creditor 
may  do  anything  he  pleases  with  the  gaged  land,  as  it  has  been 
forfeited  by  reason  of  the  debtor's  default.2 

At  a  later  time,  when  the  dual  system  of  Common  Law  and 
Equity,  administered  by  two  separate  and  distinct  sets  of  tribunals, 
was  fully  developed,  the  equitable  jurisdiction  over  gages  of  law 
belonged  exclusively  to  the  Court  of  Chancery.  The  property- 
gage  of  the  time  of  Henry  the  Second  had  become  obsolete,  and 
the  classical  common  law  mortgage  by  conveyance  under  condition 
subsequent  had  taken  its  place.  The  common  law  courts  rigidly 
enforced  the  forfeiture  of  the  mortgaged  land  for  non-payment  of 
the  debt  at  the  very  time  fixed  by  the  parties  in  their  contract.  It 
was  the  Chancery  alone  which  gave  relief.  The  equitable  right  of 
the  debtor  to  redeem  the  mortgaged  land,  after  absolute  forfeiture 
at  law,  became  known  as  the  *  equity  of  redemption ' ;  and  the  equit- 
able right  of  the  creditor  to  obtain  a  decree  of  Chancery  ordering 
the  debtor  to  pay  or  for  all  time  to  lose  his  mortgaged  land  by  for- 
feiture, in  equity  as  well  as  at  law,  became  known  as  the  '  right  to 
a  decree  of  foreclosure.'  Now  the  interesting  thing  about  the 
procedure  of  the  earlier  period — the  time  of  Henry  the  Second 
— is  that  it  was  the  procedure  of  the  king's  court,  the  court  of  the 
common  law.  This  procedure  is  indeed  a  very  enlightening  illus- 

1  Glanvill,  x.  6-8. 

2  Glanvill,  x.  8  ;  Pollock  and  Maitland,  op.  cit.  ii.  120. 


[xiii  Early  Equity  267 

tration  of  the  fact  that,  before  the  development  of  a  system  of 
equity  administered  by  the  Court  of  Chancery,  the  courts  of  the 
common  law  were  accustomed,  in  the  interests  of  justice  and  equity, 
to  soften  the  harshness  and  rigour  of  the  law  by  the  exercise  of 
what  is  known  in  later  times  as  equitable  jurisdiction.  Even  after  , 
non-payment  of  the  debt  on  the  day  set  by  the  parties  in  their 
contract  of  gage,  the  debtor  was  given  a  further  opportunity  of - 
redeeming  the  land ;  and  this  second  opportunity  of  the  debtor 
essentially  amounted  to  a  rudimentary  equity  of  redemption.1  The 
patience  of  the  creditor  and  of  the  court  had  its  limits,  however, 
and  if  the  debtor  failed  to  exercise  his  equitable  right  to  redeem 
within  the  new  period  fixed  by  the  court,  the  land  then  belonged, 
by  decree  of  the  court,  finally,  absolutely,  and  irrevocably  to  the 
creditor  as  a  forfeiture  for  non-payment  of  the  debt ;  and  this  final 
decree  of  the  court  essentially  amounted  to  a  rudimentary  decree 
of  foreclosure. 

By  the  time  of  Edward  the  First  the  common  law  appears  to  have 
taken  the  position  which  it  has  ever  since  maintained ;  for  Britton 
tells  us  that  the  equity  (equite)  of  the  common  law  will  not  assist 
the  mortgagor  who  has  allowed  the  set  day  to  pass  without  pay- 
ment of  the  debt.2  After  the  early  common  law  courts  had  thus 
ceased  to  give  relief  against  forfeiture  by  means  of  the  '  equity  of 
redemption/  it  was  left  to  the  Chancellors  of  later  times  to  reintro- 
duce  it  into  the  law  of  mortgages  in  the  form  in  which  it  has  ever 
since  played  a  conspicuous  r61e  in  the  equity  of  Chancery.  By 
failing  thus  to  retain  the  equity  of  redemption  as  a  working  prin- 
ciple of  their  system  of  justice  the  common  law  courts  lost  for  all 
subsequent  ages  jurisdiction  over  a  highly  important  branch  of 
English  law. 

III.  PENALTIES 

The  relief  of  the  early  justices  in  cases  of  gage  of  property  was 

1  The  spirit  of  the  twelfth-century  common  law  courts  is  expressed  in  the 
1  words  of  Glanvill,  x.   8  :    '  It  is,  however,  sometimes  requisite  that  he  [the 

debtor]  should  be  present  in  court,  before  the  thing  in  question  be  adjudged 
absolutely  to  the  creditor ;  since,  were  he  present,  he  might  allege  some 
reason  why  the  thing  should  not  irrevocably  belong  to  the  creditor/ 

2  Britton,  Book  III.  chap.  xv.  6  (Nichols'  ed.  ii.  128):   « Et  si  les  pleintifs 
dient,  qe  equite  les  deit  eyder  pur  la  petitesce  de  la  dette,  ceo  ne  lour  vaille 
rien  .  .  .'     See  Holdsworth,  History  of  English  Law^  vol.  ii.  249. 


268  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xui 

relief  against  forfeiture.  There  is  some  evidence  that  the  equity  of 
the  early  common  law  courts  also  anticipated  the  equity  of  the 
Chancery  in  relieving  against  penalties. 

Maitland,  in  his  Introduction  to.  the  Selden  Society's  edition  of 
the  -  Year  Books  of  2  and  3  Edward  II,  •  drew  attention1  to  the 
case  of  Umfraville  v.  Lonstede?  decided  in  the  second  year  of 
Edward  II  (1308-9),  which,  in  his  view,  'seems  to  deserve  the 
notice  of  every  future  historian  of  English  equity.'  In  this  case,  to 
quote  Maitland's  words,  'a  man  has  bound  himself  to  pay  a 
certain  sum  if  he  does  not  hand  over  a  certain  document  on  a 
certain  day.  Being  sued  upon  his  bond,  he  is  unable  to  deny  that 
he  did  not  tender  the  document  on  the  day  fixed  for  the  transfer ; 
but  he  tenders  it  now,  excuses  himself  by  saying  that  he  was 
beyond  the  sea,  having  left  the  document  with  his  wife  for  delivery, 
and  urges  that  the  plaintiff  has  suffered  no  damage.  The  plaintiff 
relies  upon  the  words  of  the  bond,  and  we  must  confess  to  having 
thought  that  in  and  about  the  year  1309  judgment  for  the  plaintiff 
would  have  followed  as  a  matter  of  course.  But,  to  our  surprise, 
Bereford,  C.J.,  after  remarking  that  what  is  sought  to  be  recovered 
is  not,  properly  speaking,  a  debt  (purement  dette)  but  a  penalty 
(une  peine\  exclaims,  "  What  equity  would  it  be  to  award  you  the 
debt  when  the  document  is  tendered  and  you  cannot  show  that 
you  have  been  damaged  by  the  detention  ? " 3  In  the  end  the 
plaintiff  is  told  that  he  will  have  to  wait  seven  years  for  his  judg- 
ment. Here  certainly,'  concludes  Maitland, '  we  seem  to  see  "  relief 
against  penalties  "  and  relief  that  is  granted  in  the  name  of  "  equity," 
though  it  takes  the  clumsy  form  of  an  indefinite  postponement  of 
that  judgment  which  is  dictated  by  the  rigour  of  the  law.' 4 

I  have  not  searched  for  other  cases  in  which  common  law  courts 

1    Y.B.  2  and  3  Edward  II  (Selden  Soc.),  p.  xiii. 
5   Y.B.  2  and  3  Edward  II  (Selden  Soc.),  58. 

3  Quel  equite  serra  de  agarder  a  vous  le  dette  de  pus  qe  1'escrit  est  prest, 
si  vous  ne  porriez  moustrer  qe  vous  fustes  endamage  par  la  de[tenue]  ?      Par 
qei  volez  receivre  1'escrit  ? 

In  another  version  Bereford's  words  are  these  : — D'autrepart,  ceo  n'est 
pas  purement  dette,  mes  une  peyne,  et  veez  par  quele  equite  vous  poez 
demander  ceo  peyne  (Moreover,  this  is  not,  properly  speaking,  a  debt ;  it  is 
a  penalty  ;  and  with  what  equity  (look  you  !)  can  you  demand  this  penalty  ?). 

4  In  a  footnote  to  the  report  of  the  case   Maitland  remarks  :   '  Observe 
that  the  court  does  not  propose  to  give  judgment  against  the  plaintiff,  who  has 
the  letter  of  the  bond  on  his  side.' 


xin]  Early  Equity  269 

gave  relief  against  penalties  ;  but  I  do  not  believe  that  this  remark- 
able case  referred  to  by  Maitland  stands  alone. 


IV.  SPECIFIC  PERFORMANCE 

< 

We  associate  specific  performance  o£contracts  with  the  Chancery, 
but  the  history  of  this  form  of  relief  begins  at  least  two  hundred 
years  before  the  earliest  decree  by  the  Chancellor  ;  for  the  common 
law  courts  of  Henry  II  and  Henry  III  were  giving,  in  their  own 
way,  much  the  same  remedy,1  and  what  the  courts  of  the  king  were 
doing  the  courts  of  the  fair  and  the  manor  and  the  church  were 
doing  also.  The  early  common  law  courts,  exercising  very  wide 
discretionary  or  equitable  powers,  and  using  their  own  judicial 
machinery,  made  indeed  an  honest  and  a  fairly  effectual  effort  to 
enforce  the  specific  performance  of  contractual  obligations.  They 
thus  enforced  the  covenant  of  the  lessor,  the  covenant  to  convey, 
the  obligations  arising  out  of  final  concords,  the  agreements  of 
lords  to  acquit  their  tenants  from  suit  of  court,  the  obligations  of 
warrantors.  Specific  performance  of  these  contractual  obligations 
was  compelled  by  the  court  in  various  ways.  Sometimes  the  court 
ordered  the  defendant  in  general  terms  to  keep  his  promise,  i.e.  to 
specifically  perform ;  and  sometimes  the  court  ordered  the  de- 
fendant to  perform  his  covenant  by  giving  the  plaintiff  possession 
of  the  land  or  by  executing  a  conveyance.  On  the  defendant's 
failure  to  comply  with  the  judicial  order,  performance  was  then 
enforced  by  the  exaction  of  security  from  the  defendant,  by  dis- 
traint, or  even  by  the  threatened  loss  of  the  promisor's  land.  We 
have  here,  in  these  cases,  not  judgments  in  rem,  but  what  we  must 
designate  'decrees  in  personamj  the  characteristic  relief  of  the 
equity  of  chancery  in  later  times.  The  early  common  law  courts 
seem,  in  fact,  to  have  been  striving  as  best  they  could  to  bring  the 
contractual  obligations  of  defendants  home  to  their  consciences. 
To  that  end  the  court  directed  the  sheriff  to  command  the  defendant 
to  specifically  perform  his  agreement ;  and  only  on  disobedience 
to  this  command  was  pressure  exerted  upon  him.  This  common 
law  method  of  enforcing  specific  performance  seems  to  have  served 
a  highly  useful  purpose  in  the  days  before  Chancery's  advent  as  a 

1  See  the  present  writer's  '  Early  History  of  Specific  Performance  of  Con- 
tract in  English  Law'  (Festgabe  fur  Kohler,  67-87). 


270  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xni 

judicial  tribunal.  The  weak  point  in  the  common  law  method  lay, 
after  all,  in  the  inability  of  the  court  to  do  more  than  distrain  the 
disobedient  party.  Chancery's  procedure  by  subpoena,  resulting  as 
it  might  in  the  imprisonment  of  the  party  guilty  of  contempt  of 
court  by  refusal  to  obey  the  court's  decree,  was  undoubtedly  a  more 
effectual  remedy,  and  naturally  supplanted  in  time  the  older  process 
of  the  common  law. 

V.  PROHIBITIONS 

I  pass  now  to  the  common  law  writs  of  prohibition.  In  Chancery 
the  injunction  was  a  judicial  process,  employed  for  various  pur- 
poses, whereby  a  party  was  ordered  to  do  a  particular  thing  or  to 
refrain  from  doing  a  particular  thing  ;  and  injunctions,  owing  largely 
to  the  fact  that  they  were  judicial  orders  in  personam,  have  gener- 
ally been  viewed  as  distinctively  characteristic  of  Chancery  as  distin- 
guished from  common  law  procedure.  Common  lawyers  have  not 
been  slow  in  drawing  attention  to  the  writ  of  prohibition  as  a  com- 
mon law  process  analogous  to  the  injunction  ;  but  they  have  usually 
emphasized  just  that  employment  of  this  writ  which  has  nothing 
to  do  with  anything  the  Chancery  lawyers  call  equitable;  for, 
although  common  law  courts  made  use  of  the  prohibition  to  restrain 
ecclesiastical  and  other  courts,  Chancery  never  restrained  common 
law  or  other  courts  by  means  of  the  injunction.  What  I  wish  now 
to  point  out  is  that,  in  the  procedure  of  the  early  common  law 
courts,  writs  of  prohibition  and  of  estrepement  and  judicial  orders 
issued  in  proceedings  begun  by  various  other  common  law  writs 
anticipated  the  Chancery  injunction  as  a  process  in  personam 
whereby  parties,  as  well  as  courts,  were  commanded  to  do  or  to 
refrain  from  doing  a  particular  thing. 

Let  us  glance  for  a  moment  at  the  prohibition  of  waste. 

Bracton,  in  his  account  of  common  law  procedure  in  cases  of 
waste  by  tenant  in  dower,1  makes  it  quite  clear  that  the  first  step 
to  be  taken  was  one  of  self-help.  The  law  gave  the  one  entitled 
to  the  inheritance  in  the  land  full  permission,  without  injury  to 
anyone,  to  stop  the  committing  of  waste.  If  these  private  efforts 
proved  unavailing,  recourse  to  the  court  was  then  necessary.  A 
writ  of  prohibition  of  waste  was  issued  to  the  sheriff,  wherein  he 
was  enjoined  that  he  do  not  permit  the  woman  to  cause  waste ; 
1  Bracton,  ff.  315,  316. 


[xni  Early  Equity  27  1 

and  the  sheriff  was  required  to  act  promptly  in  carrying  out  this 
order  of  the  court,1  lest  irreparable  injury  be  done.  If  the  dowress 
still  persisted  in  committing  waste  contrary  to  the  court's  pro- 
hibition, the  next  step  was  for  the  heir,  or  other  owner,  to  sue 
her  in  a  common  law  writ  of  waste.  She  was  attached  to  appear 
before  the  court  to  show  cause  why  she  committed  waste  contrary 
to  the  court's  prohibition.  On  the  woman's  denial  of  waste,  a 
view  was  taken  of  the  property,  and  an  inquest  was  held.  On 
proof  of  the  waste  the  woman  was  obliged  to  make  amends 
(emendetur  vastum)  by  payment  of  damages. 

If  the  waste  had  been  committed  in  a  wood  the  court  could,  in 
exercise  of  its  discretionary  power  (de  consilio  curiae\  prohibit  any 
further  waste  and  issue  a  writ  for  the  appointment  of  a  forester  2 
by  the  heir.  The  duty  of  the  forester  was  to  protect  the  wood  and 
to  see  that  the  dowress  took  only  her  reasonable  estovers  and 
committed  no  further  waste  contrary  to  the  prohibition.  If  the 
waste  had  been  committed  in  houses,  gardens,  and  pastures,  the 
court  could  add  a  clause  to  the  writ  which  empowered  the  heir 
to  appoint  one  of  his  servants  whose  duty  was  to  see  that  the 
dowress  committed  no  further  waste.  The  writ3  was  directed  to 
the  sheriff,  who  was  enjoined  not  to  impede  in  any  way  the  appoint- 
ment of  forester  and  servant  by  the  heir.4 

It  is  carefully  to  be  observed  that  we  have  here  in  this  method 
of  enforcing  the  court's  order  a  procedure  which  is  distinctly 
equitable  in  character  and  which,  so  far  as  we  can  see,  had  been 
developed  by  the  common  law  courts  since  the  time  of  Glanvill.5 
In  certain  respects  it  may  be  looked  upon  as  an  anticipation  of  the 
administrative  side  of  the  Chancery's  activity. 

Bracton's  Note-Book  contains  two  instructive  cases  upon  pro- 
hibition of  waste  by  dowress.  In  John  Sanfordv.  Cecilia  Sanford 


1  Bracton,  f. 

2  Coke,  Second  Institute,  300,  states  that  in  the  old  books  forestarius  is 
equivalent  to  custos  boscorum,  a  woodward.     On  woodwards  see  Select  Pleas 
of  the  Forest  (Selden  Soc.),  pp.  xxiv-xxv,  xlv,  Ixvii. 

8  Bracton,  f.  316. 

4  See  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  27,  56,  fora  case  of  the  year  1219  (referred 
to  by  Bracton,  f.  316)  in  which  the  court  ordered  the  appointment  of  a  forester 
to  prevent  the  dowress  and  her  husband  from  committing  waste  by  taking 
more  from  the  wood  than  haybote  and  housebote.     See  also  ibid.  pi.  672. 

5  See  Twiss,  Bracton  (R.S.),  vol.  iv.  pp.  Ixi,  Ixii  ;  Pollock  and  Maitland, 
op.  cit.  ii.  596. 


272  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xm 

the  defendant,  a  dowress,  was  sued  for  breach  of  a  prohibition  of 
waste.  So  far  as  one  can  see,  this  is  a  case  where  the  court  had 
prohibited  not  only  voluntary  waste  but  also  permissive  waste — 
permitting  a  fish-pond  and  mill  to  go  dry  (molendinum  omnino 
desiccatum  est  et  fractum  et  vivarium  similiter)!  In  another  case 
writ  of  waste  was  brought  without  prior  prohibition.  In  rendering 
judgment  the  court  required  the  defendant  to  pay  damages  and 
an  amercement ;  and  in  addition  it  ordered  the  defendant  not  to 
commit  further  waste  under  penalty  of  loss  of  her  land.2 

On  waste  by  a  guardian  he  could  be  reached  by  the  plaintiff 
with  the  common  law  writ  of  waste  either  before  or  after  the  issue 
of  a  writ  of  prohibition ;  although  we  may  perhaps  gather  from 
Bracton's  account  that  the  usual  course  was  first  to  issue  the 
prohibition,  and  then,  on  breach  of  the  prohibition,  to  bring  the  writ 
of  waste.  The  writ  of  prohibition  was  directed  to  the  sheriff,  and 
in  it  he  was  enjoined  not  to  permit  the  guardian  to  commit  further 
waste.  If  breach  of  the  prohibition  necessitated  the  bringing  of 
the  writ  of  waste,  and  if  the  waste  was  proved,  judgment  was 
rendered  that  the  guardian  lose  the  guardianship,  render  damages 
to  the  plaintiff,  and  pay  an  amercement  to  the  king.  A  distinction 
was  thus  drawn  by  the  law  between  waste  by  a  guardian  and 
waste  by  a  dowress,  for  the  dowress  did  not,  on  committing 
waste,  lose  her  dower,  whereas  the  guardian,  on  the  other  hand, 
did  lose  his  guardianship.3 

This  distinction  between  the  penalties  inflicted  on  dowress  and 
guardian  resulted,  as  will  be  observed,  in  an  important  difference 
between  the  judgment  in  the  writ  of  waste  against  a  guardian  and 
the  judgment  in  the  writ  of  waste  against  a  dowress.  As  the  guardian 
lost  his  guardianship  it  was  unnecessary  for  the  court  to  include  in 
its  judgment  a  perpetual  prohibition  of  waste.  On  the  other  Kand, 
as  the  dowress  did  not  lose  her  dower  land,  it  was  necessary  for 
the  court  in  its  judgment  to  restrain  waste  for  the  future,  and 
sometimes  even  to  order  the  appointment  of  forester  and  servant 
to  see  that  the  prohibition  was  complied  with  by  the  defendant. 

1  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.   1617  (A.D.    1223);  s.c.   Fitz.    Wast,  pi.   141. 
Plowden,  3223,  refers  to  this  case.     On  this  and  other  cases  of  waste  in  Brae. 
N.-B.  see  Kirch  wey's  valuable  'Liability  for  Waste'  (Columbia  Law  Review, 
viii.  425-437).     Modern  equity  courts  do  not  restrain  permissive  waste. 

2  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  540. 

3  Bracton,  ff.  316,  317. 


xin]  Early  Equity  273 

Attention  should  be  drawn  to  two  interesting  cases  in  Bracton's 
Note-Book.  In  Royesia  de  la  Dene  a  guardian  in  chivalry  was 
sued  for  waste  contrary  to  a  prohibition.  In  its  judgment  the 
court  ordered  the  defendant  to  restore  a  kitchen,  which  was  burned 
during  the  tenancy,  and  two  farm  buildings,  which  had  collapsed 
owing  to  non-repair,  and  also  to  repair  all  other  buildings  upon 
the  land ;  while  the  court  also  prohibited  her  from  causing  any 
waste  for  the  future.1 

In  another  case 2  a  guardian  had  given  two  houses  and  two 
trees  to  a  dowress,  who  had  taken  them  off  the  land.  The  guardian 
was  amerced  to  the  king.  In  addition  he  was  ordered  to  build 
two  other  houses  of  the  same  value  as  those  he  had  given  away, 
and  was  required  to  find  pledges  that  he  would  neither  carry  off 
trees  nor  commit  any  other  waste,  and  that  he  would  build  the  two 
houses  as  he  had  been  ordered  by  the  court.3 

Bracton's  Note-Book  contains  cases  which  show  us  that  tenants 
for  life  and  lessees  for  years  were  also  prohibited  by  the  king's 
courts  from  committing  waste.  In  the  case  of  Nicholas  Creusquer 
v.  Peter  Pejure  the  defendant,  who  held  lands  ad  terminum,  was 
attached  to  answer  the  plaintiff  for  waste.  The  case  was  dismissed 
because  the  waste  was  of  such  slight  value ;  but  at  the  same 
time  the  court  issued  a  prohibition,  ordering  the  defendant  to 
commit  no  further  waste  in  the  future.4  Ranulf  de  Gatesdena  v. 
Matilda  de  Gatesdena  was  a  case  in  which  the  defendant,  a  tenant 
for  life,  was  attached  for  waste.  The  inquest  found  that  waste 

1  Bracton's   Note-Book,    pi.    1165    (A.D.     1235):    consideratum   est   quod 
nullum  fecit  uastum,   ita  tamen  quod  tales   etc.   manuceperunt  quod  eadem 
Roeysia  reparari  faceret  coquinam  et  grangias  et  ea  que  ceciderunt  tempore 
quo  eadem  custodia  exstitit  in  manu  sua  infra  hunc  annum,  et  quod  de  cetero 
sustentabit  omnia  alia  edificia  et  quod  nullum  uastum  faciet  in  situ  mesuagii 
nee  alibi  ad  exheredacionem  predict!  heredis. 

This  case  is  also  fully  given  in  Fitz.  Wast,  pi.  139,  where  the  report 
concludes  :  et  inuenit  pleg.  ad  hec  omnia  etc. 

2  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  1075  (A.D.  1225). 

8  Et  idea  pro  paruitate  uasti  et  modo  uastandi  consideratum  est  quod 
Godefridus  faciet  alias  duas  domos  ad  ualenciam  predictarum  domorum  et 
sit  in  misericordia.  Et  invenit  tales  plegios  quod  amplius  non  faciet  uastum 
nee  arbores  asportabit  et  quod  faciet  domos  sicut  predictum  est  etc. 

4  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  607  (A.D.  1231):  Consideratum  est  quod 
Petrus  inde  sine  die,  et  prohibitum  est  ei  quod  de  cetero  nullum  uastum 
faciat. 

Bracton,  f.  3160,  refers  to  this  case.     See  also  Fitz.  Wast,  pi.  134. 


274  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xm 

had  been  committed.  The  judgment  of  the  court  was  that  the 
defendant  be  in  mercy,  pay  the  amount  of  the  waste  to  the  plaintiff, 
and  find  pledges ;  while  in  addition  the  prohibition  of  the  court 
issued  forbidding  her  to  commit  any  further  waste  under  penalty 
of  the  loss  of  her  land.1  In  Richard  de  Elmham  v.  Robert  de 
Corneville  the  plaintiff  alleged  that  the  defendant,  a  life  tenant,  had 
committed  waste  contrary  to  a  prohibition.  Both  parties  put 
themselves  upon  the  country,  and  an  inquest  was  ordered.2 

Bracton's  Note-Book  contains  twenty-six  cases  on  waste.  In 
twelve  cases  the  writ  of  prohibition  first  issued ;  and  then  later,  on 
breach  of  the  prohibition,  the  aggrieved  party  brought  the  common 
law  writ  of  waste.3  In  fourteen  cases,  on  the  other  hand,  the  writ 
of  waste  appears  to  have  been  brought  at  once  without  a  prior 
prohibition.4  Proceedings  upon  the  writ  of  waste  ended,  in  six 
instances,  in  a  prohibition  of  waste.5 

Readers  of  the  Second  Institute  will  recall  Coke's  high  praise  of 
the  writ  of  the  prohibition  of  waste.  I  cannot  forbear  quoting  his 
words,  for  they  express  very  clearly  the  equitable  character  of  this 
common  law  remedy  in  effecting  the  preventive  justice  that  was 
later  to  be  claimed  by  the  Chancery  as  its  own  peculiar  province. 
Coke  draws  attention  to  two  common  law  remedies  for  waste,  the 

1  Bracton's   Note-Book,    pi.   443   (A.D.    1230),    540  (A.D.    1231):    Con- 
sideratum  est  quod  ipsa  sit  in  misericordia  et  satisfaciat  eidem  Ranulfo  de 
predictis  denariis  et  dictum  est  ei  quod  de  cetero  sub  pena  amissionis  predicte 
terre  non  faciat  uastum  uel  destruccionem  et  ipsa  inuenit  pleg'. 

See  Bracton,  f.  3i6b;  Fitz.  Wast,  pi.  132. 

2  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  1304  (A.D.  1217),  1371  (A.D.  1220):  Robertus 
de   Corneuilla   summonitus  fuit  ad  respondendum   Ricardo    de  Elmham  de 
placito  quare  ipse  fecit  uastum  contra  prohibicionem  Dom.   Regis  de  bosco 
in  Tolleslund'.   .  .  .   Et  Robertus  uenit  et  defendit  contra  eum  et  contra  sectam 
suam  quod  nullum  dampnum  uel  uastum  fecit  post  prohibicionem  ei  factam 
sicut  curia  considerauerit,  et  inde  ponit  se  super  iuratam  patrie.     Et  Ricardus 
similiter. 

See  Bracton,  f.  316.  The  principal  case  will  be  found  in  Fitz.  Wast, 
pi.  140. 

On  the  writ  of  prohibition  in  cases  of  waste  by  ecclesiastics,  see  Cruise, 
Digest  of  the  Laws  of  England  respecting  Real  Property,  4th  ed.  vol.  i.  tit.  iii. 
ch.  ii.  §  71. 

3  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  27,   56,  388,  580,  632,  640,  718,  739,  880, 
1075,  I37i,  1617. 

4  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  115,  443,  461,  485,  527,  540,  574,  607,  691, 
717,  1131,  1165,  1304,  1743. 

5  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  56,  540,  574,  607,  1075,  1165. 


xin]  Early  Equity  275 

writ  of  prohibition  and  the  action  of  waste.  '  Now  the  remedy  at 
the  common  law/  says  Coke,1  '  was  in  two  degrees :  first,  if  he  that 
had  the  inheritance  did  feare  (for  example)  that  tenant  in  dower 
would  doe  waste,  he  that  had  the  inheritance  might  before  any 
waste  done  have  a  prohibition  directed  to  the  sheriffe,  that  he  shall 
not  permit  her  to  do  waste  in  this  forme.  Rex  vicecom?  salutem. 
Praecipimus  tibi  quod  non  permittas  quod  talis  mulier  faciat  vastum, 
vel  venditionem,  vel  exilium  de  terris,  hominibus,  redditibus,  domibus, 
boscis,  vel  gardinis,  quae  tenent  in  dotem  de  haereditate  talis  in  tali 
villa,  ad  exhaeredationem  ipsius  talis  ne  amplius,  etc.  And  Bracton's 
advice  hereupon  is  as  followeth :  Et  hoc  faciat  tempestive,  ne  per 
negligentiam  damnum  incurrat,  quia  melius  est  in  tempore  occurrere, 
quam  post  causam  vulneratam  remedium  quaerere.  And  the  sheriffe 
having  the  warrant  of  this  writ  may,  as  in  case  of  a  writ  of 
estrepement,  take  posse  comitatus,  and  withstand  the  doing  of  any 
waste.  And  this  was  the  remedy  [by  prohibition]  that  the  law 
appointed  before  the  waste  done  by  the  tenant  in  dower,  tenant  by 
the  curtesie,  or  the  gardien,  to  prevent  the  same,  and  this  was  an 
excellent  law,  for  praestat  cautela  quam  medela,  and  preventing 
justice  excelleth  punishing  justice.  And  this  remedy  may  be  used 
at  this  day.' 

Another  striking  illustration  of  the  preventive  justice  admini- 
stered by  the  early  common  law  courts  is  furnished  by  the  writs  of 
estrepement  f  writs  that  prohibited  the  commission  of  waste  during 
the  course  of  judicial  process. 

At  common  law  the  writ  of  estrepement  could  be  brought  after 
judgment  in  any  real  action  and  before  execution  of  the  judgment 
by  delivery  of  possession  on  the  part  of  the  sheriff ;  and  the  object 
of  the  writ  was  to  prevent  the  commission  of  waste  by  the  one 
who,  although  in  possession  of  the  land,  was  not  entitled  to  the 
land  as  his  own  by  reason  of  the  judgment  against  him  in  the  real 
action.3 

1  Second  Institute -,  299. 

2  Blackstone,  Commentaries  (ed.  1768),  iii.   225,  says  that  estrepement  is 
'  an  old  French  word,  signifying  the  same  as  waste  or  extirpation.' 

Upon  the  writs  of  estrepement  see  Fitz.  Estrepement ;  Brooke,  Estrepement ; 
Coke,  Second  Institute,  327-329  ;  Fitzherbert,  Natura  Brevium,  9th  ed.,  60, 
6 1  ;  Blackstone,  Commentaries  (ed.  1768),  iii.  225-227.  For  the  writs  them- 
selves see  Registrum  Brevium  Originalium,  76,  77  ;  Regi 'strum  Judiciale,  33. 

3  Coke,    Second    Institute,    327,    328  ;     Blackstone,    Commentaries    (ed. 
1768),  iii.  225-227. 


276  H.  D.  Hazel  tine  [xui 

So  far  as  one  can  see,  this  common  law  writ  of  estrepement  could 
not  be  brought  at  any  stage  in  legal  proceedings  prior  to  judg- 
ment.1 To  remedy  this  defect  in  the  common  law  system  of 
preventive  justice  the  Statute  of  Gloucester  introduced,  in  the 
sixth  year  of  the  reign  of  Edward  I,  a  new  writ  of  estrepement. 
If  a  plaintiff  justly  feared  that  the  tenant — perhaps  fully  knowing 
the  weakness  of  his  title — might  commit  waste  while  the  legal 
proceedings  were  going  on,  he  could  bring  this  statutory  writ  of 
estrepement  whereby  the  tenant  would  be  prohibited  from  com- 
mitting waste  pending  the  suit.2 

The  writ  of  estrepement,  if  directed  to  the  sheriff,  ordered  him 
firmly  to  prohibit  the  tenant  from  committing  waste  so  long  as  the 
legal  proceedings  in  regard  to  the  land  were  in  progress.3  If  the 
writ  was  addressed  directly  to  the  party  himself,  the  tenant,  he 
was  likewise  ordered  by  the  court  not  to  commit  waste  pendente  lite.^ 

Suppose  the  defendant  failed  to  observe  the  court's  prohibition  ? 
If  the  writ  was  addressed  to  the  sheriff,  then  he  was  obliged  to  see 
to  it  that  the  waste  was  stopped,  and  in  fulfilment  of  his  duty  he 
could  use  necessary  force,  even  to  the  extent  of  imprisonment  or 
the  raising  of  the  posse  comitatus  to  go  to  his  assistance,  '  so  odious 
in  law/  in  Coke's  words,  '  is  waste  and  destruction ' :  the  court 
itself  would  not  imprison  the  waster,  for  the  duty  of  preventing 
the  waste  rested  solely  upon  the  sheriff  who  had  already  received 
his  orders  in  the  writ  addressed  to  him.  On  the  other  hand,  if  the 
writ  was  addressed  directly  to  the  waster  himself,  the  aggrieved 
party  could,  on  breach  of  the  court's  prohibition,  sue  the  waster, 
recovering  costs  and  damages,  and  get  the  court  to  imprison  the 
defendant  for  his  contempt  of  court  in  disobeying  the  prohibition.5 

The  interlocutory  injunction  of  Chancery  is  an  order  of  the 
court,  issued  before  the  final  determination  of  the  rights  of  the 
parties,  and  its  object  is  the  protection  of  the  rights  of  the  plaintiff 
pending  trial  and  judgment.  How  like  unto  the  interlocutory 

1  But  see  Coke,  Second  Institute ',  327. 

2  Statute  of  Gloucester,   6  Ed.  I,   c.    13  ;    Coke,  Second  Institute,  327, 
329  ;  Blackstone,  Commentaries •,  iii.  225-227. 

3  Registrum  Brev.  Orig.  77  ;  Blackstone,  Commentaries,  iii.  225-227. 

4  Registrum  Judiciale,  2 1 . 

5  Fitz.  N.B.   60,   6 1  ;    Coke,    Second  Institute,    329;    Blackstone,    Com- 
mentaries, iii.   225-227;  Play  stow  v.  Bacheller,  Moore,    100;  Cumberland  v. 
Dowager,  Hobart,  85  ;  Foliamtfs  Case,  Coke's  Reports,  v.  f.  U5a. 


xni]  Early  Equity  277 

injunction  was  the  old  common  law  writ  of  estrepement  \  In  its 
form  it  was  an  interlocutory  order  in  personam  and  in  its  object 
it  was  a  remedy  of  preventive  justice.  After  the  Chancery  had 
fashioned  its  own  interlocutory  injunction,  possibly  in  imitation 
of  the  writ  of  esirepement^  the  Court  of  Common  Pleas  made  an 
ineffectual  effort  to  extend  its  own  power  to  give  preventive  relief 
by  a  further  development  of  the  writ  of  estrepement ;  but  in  1594 
Lord  Keeper  Egerton  made  an  order  that  no  writ  of  estrepement 
should  be  issued  by  the  cursitors  unless  it  be  in  accordance  with 
the  ancient  course  of  the  law.2  But  for  this  order  by  the  Lord 
Keeper  the  old  writ  of  estrepement  might  well  have  held  its  own 
ground,  at  least  for  a  time,  as  against  the  injunction.  But  Chancery's 
remedy  gained  the  upper  hand  ;  and  to-day,  while  the  estrepement 
is  obsolete  and  well-nigh  forgotten,  the  interlocutory  injunction 
is  in  almost  daily  use  and  in  the  minds  of  all  who  have  to  do  with 
the  administration  of  English  justice. 

In  the  long  struggle  of  the  common  law  courts  with  their  rivals 
—in  the  Middle  Ages,  chiefly  the  ecclesiastical  tribunals — the  writ 
of  prohibition  proved  itself  a  weapon  of  wonderful  power.  It  was 
a  writ  which  could  be  and  was  directed  not  only  against  parties, 
but  also  against  tribunals.  In  cases  involving  subject  matter 
claimed  by  the  common  law  courts  as  falling  within  their  own 
exclusive  jurisdiction,  not  only  were  parties  restrained  by  pro- 
hibition from  suing  in  ecclesiastical  courts,  but  those  courts  were 
themselves  restrained  by  prohibition  from  entertaining  such 
proceedings.  It  was  thus  largely  by  this  writ  that  the  courts  of 
common  law  preserved  and  extended  their  jurisdiction,  keeping  other 
tribunals  to  their  own  peculiar  province,  and  that  they  protected 
parties  in  their  common  law  rights  as  opposed  to  rights  good  at 
ecclesiastical  law.  At  a  later  day  the  Chancery,  in  its  struggle 
with  common  law  courts,  employed  the  injunction  to  effect  a  similar 
purpose ;  but  there  was  this  important  difference  between  the  pro- 
hibition of  common  law  courts  and  the  injunction  of  Chancery,  that 

1  Ashburner,  in  his  Principles  of  Equity,  ed.   1902,  p.  494,  note  (d),  has 
suggested   that   it   was   the  writ  of  estrepement  'which   perhaps  formed   the 
model  for  the  equitable  remedy  by  injunction.' 

2  Kerly,    History   of  Equity,    150;    Spence,    Equitable  Jurisdiction    oj 
Chancery,  i.  672. 

On  the  scope  of  the  writ  of  estrepement  see  Fitz.  N.-B.  60,  6 1  ;  Blackstone, 
Commentaries,  iii.  225-227. 


278  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xm 

the  injunction  restrained  only  parties,  while  the  prohibition  restrained 
both  parties  and  courts.1  Only,  therefore,  in  its  effect  in  restraining 
parties  can  we  say  that  the  prohibition  anticipated  the  injunction. 

Bracton  is  careful  to  explain  why  there  should  be  two  prohibi- 
tions— one  to  the  ecclesiastical  court  and  one  to  the  party.  At 
first  sight,  he  says,  it  might  seem  that  a  prohibition  to  the  judge 
alone  or  to  the  party  alone  should  suffice,  for  if  the  judge,  in 
obedience  to  the  prohibition,  refused  to  hear  the  case,  the  party's 
attempt  to  sue  would  be  of  no  avail,  and  if  the  party,  in  obedience 
to  the  prohibition,  did  not  proceed  with  his  suit,  the  judge  could 
give  no  judgment  for  lack  of  a  plaintiff.  But  two  prohibitions  are 
nevertheless  better  than  one,  maintains  Bracton,  lest  either  the 
judge  or  the  party  might  proceed  in  the  matter  with  impunity. 
Apparently  he  means  that  two  prohibitions,  rather  than  one,  will 
make  assurance  doubly  sure  by  giving  no  loop-hole  for  either  judge 
or  party  to  assert  that  he  has  not  been  prohibited.2  3 

Not  forgetting  that  the  writ  might  serve  either  as  an  inter- 
locutory or  as  a  final  prohibition,4  and  is  thus  directly  analogous  to 
the  temporary  and  perpetual  injunctions  of  the  Chancery,  we  must 
now  ask  the  question  as  to  whether  the  writ  of  prohibition  was 
addressed  to  the  sheriff  or  directly  to  the  ecclesiastical  judge  and  the 
party.  Glanvill's  only  form  of  the  writ  restraining  a  party  from 
suing  in  the  ecclesiastical  court  is  addressed  to  the  sheriff,  and 
orders  him  not  to  permit  the  party  to  sue ; 5  but  his  form  of  the 

1  See  Glanvill,  vi.  12-14,  xii.  21,  22;  Bracton,  ff.  401-412;  Spence, 
op.  c it.  i.  371,  673-676;  Kerly,  op.  cit.  89,  109,  116,  293;  Pollock  and 
Maitland,  op.  cit.  ii.  596;  Holdsworth,  op.  M.  ii.  196,  197,  211,  251, 
260,  395.  2  Bracton,  f.  4050. 

8  To  enter  into  a  consideration  of  the  question  as  to  when  a  prohibition 
could  and  could  not  be  brought  (see  thereon,  Bracton,  ff.  401-412)  would  take 
us  beyond  the  scope  of  the  present  paper,  for  my  only  concern  is  to  indicate 
the  procedural  significance  of  the  writ. 

4  Bracton,  ff.  401-412,  makes  this  quite  clear. 

5  Glanvill,  xii.  22  :  Rex  vie'  salutem.      Prohibe  R.  ne  sequatur  placitum 
in  curia  christianitatis  quod  est  inter  N.  et  ipsum  de  laico  feodo  ipsius  R.  in 
villa  ipsa  unde  ipse  queritur  quod  prefatus  N.  inde  eum  traxit  in  placitum  in 
curia  Christianitatis  coram  iudicibus  illis.      Et  si  praefatus  R.  fecerit  te  securum 
de  clamore  suo  prosequendo,  tune  pone  per  vadium  et  salvos  plegios  predictum 
N.  quod  sit  coram  me  vel  lustic'  meis  eo  die,  ostensurus  quare  traxit  eum  in 
placitum  in  curia  Christianitatis  de  laico  feodo  suo  in  ilia  villa,  de  sicut  illud 
placitum  spectat  ad  coronam  et  dignitatem  meam.      T.  etc. 

Beames,  Translation  of  Glanville^  Beale's  1900  ed.  p.  243,  note  2  :  'This 
writ  stands  in  need  of  a  transposition  of  the  capitals  to  render  it  intelligible.5 


xni]  Early  Equity  279 

writ  restraining  the  court  is  addressed  to  the  court  directly.1  By 
Bracton's  time  the  writs  appear  always  to  be  addressed  directly  to 
the  court  and  directly  to  the  party,  without  the  interposition  of  the 
sheriff  as  an  intermediary  between  the  common  law  court  and  the 
party  restrained ; 2  and  so  far  as  we  can  see,  from  an  examination 
of  later  sources,  this  continued  to  be  the  usual  course  of  procedure.3 

In  studying  the  equitable  procedure  of  the  early  common  courts, 
this  fact  that  the  writs  of  prohibition  in  these  cases  are  addressed 
in  this  direct  and  personal  way  to  the  ecclesiastical  judge  and  the 
party  is,  it  seems  to  me,  of  significance  ;  for  it  shows  us  clearly  that 
the  courts  of  the  common  law  were  in  this  earlier  period  exercising 
a  jurisdiction  inpersonam  by  prohibition  which  anticipated  Chancery 
jurisdiction  in  personam  by  injunction.  Even  writs  of  prohibition 
addressed  to  the  sheriff,  as  the  court's  official,  seem  to  have  been 
essentially  orders  directed  against  the  person  of  the  defendant,  as 
I  shall  hope  to  explain  later  on  ;  but  the  point  that  the  jurisdiction 
was  in  personam  is  brought  out  with  even  greater  clearness  by 
study  of  the  writs  addressed  directly  and  personally  to  the  parties 
themselves. 

But  even  a  royal  prerogative  writ  of  prohibition  without  the 
infliction  of  a  penalty  for  its  breach  would  be  a  weak  thing  indeed  ; 
and  we  need  not  be  surprised  to  find  that  the  common  law  courts 
of  Bracton's  time  were  possessed  of  powers  to  inflict  severe 
penalties — even  imprisonment — upon  judge  or  party  who  dared 
disobey  the  king's  order.  The  writs  of  prohibition,  as  given  by 
Bracton,  contain  in  themselves  no  hint  as  to  penalty  for  breach 
of  the  court's  order;  but  that  the  disobedient  judge  or  party 
will  actually  surfer  a  penalty  is  made  quite  clear  by  Bracton,  who 

1  Glanvill,  xii.  21  :  Rex  illis  ludicibus  ecclesiasticis  salutem.       Prohibeo 
vobis  ne  teneatis  placitum  in  curia  christianitatis  quod  est  inter  N.  et  R.  de 
laico  feodo  predicti  R.  unde  ipse  queritur  quod  N.  eum  trahit  in  placitum  in 
curia  christianitatis  coram  vobis,  quia  placitum  illud  spectat  ad  coronam  et 
dignitatem  meam.     T.  etc. 

2  All  of  the  writs  -given  by  Bracton,  ff.  401-412,  are  of  this  direct  and 
personal  character. 

3  See  on  writs  of  prohibition  addressed  directly  to  the  party  suing  in  the 
ecclesiastical  court,    Y.B.   i   and  2  Ed.   II  (Selden  Soc.),  pi.  5>  Io  ;    Y-B-  2 
and  3  Ed.  II  (Selden  Soc.),  pi.  33  ;    Y.B.  2  and  3  Ed.   II  (Selden  Soc.),  p. 
203  (Appendix  II.);    Y.B.  3  Ed.  II  (Selden  Soc.),  pi.  45  (and  see  p.  135  for 
note  from  the  record)  ;  Regis trum  Brev.  Orig.  ff.  33  seq.     Cf.  also  Bracton's 
Note-Book,  pi.  351. 


280  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xm 

gives  a  full  account  of  the  procedure  on  breach  of  prohibition.1  If 
either  judge  or  party  has  been  guilty  of  a  breach  of  prohibition  the 
aggrieved  party  may  sue  him.  In  case  the  aggrieved  party  gives 
proper  security  for  prosecuting  his  suit,  a  writ  of  attachment, 
directed  to  the  sheriff,  will  issue.  The  sheriff  must  then  place  the 
offending  judge  or  party  under  gage  and  pledge  that  he  will  appear 
before  the  royal  justices  to  show  cause  why  he  has  held  the  plea 
in  the  church  court  contrary  to  the  prohibition,  or  why  he  has 
prosecuted  the  plea  in  the  church  court  contrary  to  the  prohibition. 
If  either  the  judge  or  the  party  fail  to  appear  on  the  set  day,  he  is 
then  attached  by  better  pledges  and  distrained  by  all  his  lands  to 
be  present  in  court  on  another  day,  the  order  of  attachment  to  be 
observed  in  other  personal  actions  being  followed.  But  if  the 
defendant  be  a  clerk,  and  if  he  be  unwilling  to  find  pledges,  and 
have  no  lay  fee  by  which  he  can  be  distrained,  a  mandate  is  then 
sent  to  the  ordinaries  and  bishop  that  they  shall  cause  the 
defendants  to  come  before  the  royal  court.  When  at  last  the 
parties  and  the  offending  judge  are  before  the  court,  the  plaintiff 
declares  that  the  defendant,  the  party,  has  vexed  and  aggrieved 
him  by  suing  in  the  ecclesiastical  court  in  a  temporal  matter  con- 
trary to  the  prohibition.  The  plaintiff  proceeds  at  once  with  his 
proof.  Then  the  offending  party  and  the  judge  are  heard,  several 
defences  being  open  to  them.  If  judgment  be  given  against  either 
the  defendant  party  or  the  defendant  judge,  he  must  pay  the 
plaintiff  damages  and  may  even  be  severely  punished  by  a  heavy 
amercement.2  If  the  defendant  be  a  layman  he  will  also  be  im- 
prisoned as  a  presumer  against  the  royal  dignity  because  he  has 
disobeyed  the  prerogative  writ  of  prohibition ;  he  is  treated  as 
if  he  had  committed  the  crime  of  high  treason.  If,  however,  the 
defendant  be  a  clerk,  he  is  sometimes  dealt  with  more  mildly  by 
grace  and  out  of  reverence  for  the  clerical  order. 

This  method  of  enforcing  the  court's  prohibition  certainly  seems 
rigorous  and  effective.  Indeed,  in  certain  of  its  features  it  is  closely 
analogous  to  the  method  of  the  Chancellors — the  writ  of  subpoena. 

Before  concluding  this  account  of  common  law  writs  analogous 
to  the  injunction  of  Chancery,  attention  must  be  drawn  to  a 
remarkable  case  recorded  on  the  De  Banco  Roll  of  Hilary, 

1  Bracton,  ff.  401,  402,  409,  410. 

2  See  Bracton,  f.  402. 


xm]  Early  Equity  281 

2  Edward  II.1  In  this  case,  Prior  of  Coventry  v.  William  Graumpe 
of  Coventry  and  others?  the  plaintiff  complained  that  the  defendants, 
men  of  Coventry,  had  been  buying  and  selling  outside  his  market 
upon  market  days.  The  Prior's  right  was  denied  by  the  defendants ; 
but  verdict  was  found  against  them  for  sixty  pounds  damages. 
The  judgment  reads :  '  And  therefore  it  is  considered  that  the 
said  Prior  recover  his  said  damages  against  them,  and  that  the 
said  William  and  the  others  henceforth  on  Fridays  on  which  the 
said  Prior  has  his  said  market  do  not  expose  for  sale  their  vendible 
wares  within  the  town  of  Coventry  elsewhere  than  in  the  said 
market.' 3 

In  commenting  on  this  judgment  Maitland  says  :  '  If  this  is  not 
an  "injunction"  and  a  "perpetual  injunction,"  we  hardly  know 
what  to  call  it.  How  could  this  "  injunction,"  if  such  we  may  call 
it,  have  been  enforced  ?  It  seems  possible  that  if  the  defendants 
had  repeated  the  tort,  the  plaintiff  might  have  obtained  a  specially 
worded  writ  reciting  the  breach  of  the  "injunction,"  and  that  in 
this  new  action  the  judgment  would  be  that  the  defendants  be 
taken  and  imprisoned,  and  not  merely  that  they  be  amerced.  It 
is  to  be  remembered  that  the  action  known  as  contra  formam 
feoff amenti^  was  based  on  the  breach  of  a  royal  prohibition ;  and 
the  same  had  been  true  of  the  action  of  waste.' 5 

1  See  Maitland's  comments,  Y.B.  2  and  3  Edward  II  (Selden  Soc.),  p.  xiii. 

2  Y.B.  2  and  3  Edward  II  (Selden  Soc.),  74. 

3  Et    idea    consideration  est  quod   predictus   Prior  recuperet   versus  eos 
dampna  sua  predicta,  et  quod  predict!  Willelmus  et  alii  decetero  mercimonia 
sua  vendalia  per  dies  Veneris  quibus  idem  Prior  habet  mercatum  suum  pre- 
dictum  alibi  in  predicta  villa  de  Coventre  quam  in  predicto  mercato  suo  non 
vendant  seu  vendicioni   exponant,    etc.      Et  predictus   Willelmus   et   alii    in 
misericordia  etc. 

In  the  Y.B.  report  of  this  same  case  Brabazon,  J.,  says  (see  Y.B.  2  and  3 
Edward  II,  71  ;  Selden  Soc.  ed.)  :  'Where  the  King  grants  a  market  to  a 
man,  he  grants  a  market  in  such  wise  that  no  man  may,  in  the  same  town 
in  which  the  market  is,  sell  any  merchandise  save  in  the  market.  So,  since 
you  have  confessed  that  the  Prior  has  a  market  in  this  town  by  the  King's 
grant  and  that  you  are  resident  in  the  same  town,  common  law  will  drive 
you  to  his  market  and  prevent  your  marketing  elsewhere  in  the  same  town 
(comune  ley  vous  chacera  de  venir  a  son  marche  sans  aillours  marchander  en 
mesme  la  ville).' 

4  Maitland  here  refers  to  cases  in  Y.B.  2  and  3  Edward  II  (Selden  Soc.), 

93,  95- 

5  In  a  footnote  to.  the  report  of  the  case  Maitland  remarks:   'We  can 
hardly  say  that  the  idea  of  an  injunction  was  foreign  to  the  common  law. 


282  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xm 

Let  me  summarize  what  I  desire  to  say  in  regard  to  prohibitions. 

The  early  common-law  jurisdiction  in  personam  by  means  of 
prohibitions  was  not  narrow.  The  orders  of  the  court  were  not 
only  issued  in  cases  of  waste,1  nuisance,2  and  other  torts,3  but  also 
in  cases  of  contract  4  and  property.5  They  not  only  effected,  in  a 
negative  way,  a  restraint  upon  the  doing  of  an  act,  but  also 
effected,  in  a  positive  and  mandatory  way,  the  actual  doing  of  an 
act ;  for  parties  were  not  only  ordered  not  to  commit  waste,6  not 
to  commit  nuisance,7  not  to  sell  land,8  not  to  distrain  the  plaintiff 
to  do  suit  of  court,9  not  to  destroy  the  wood  in  which  the  plaintiff 
has  house-bote  and  hay-bote,10  not  to  expose  wares  for  sale  elsewhere 
than  in  the  plaintiffs  market,11  not  to  sue  in  the  ecclesiastical 
courts  ; 12  but  parties  were  ordered  to  repair  walls  and  buildings,13  to 
erect  houses,14  to  place  property  in  the  same  condition  in  which  it 
had  been,15  and  to  remove  existing  nuisances.16  The  orders  of  the 
court  were  also  not  only  temporary  or  interlocutory  in  character, 
but  they  were  final  or  perpetual ;  for  parties  were  not  only  ordered 
not  to  commit  waste  while  legal  proceedings  were  in  progress,  and 
not  to  sue  in  the  ecclesiastical  court  till  the  rights  of  the  parties  at 
common  law  had  been  determined  in  the  common  law  court,  but 
they  were  also  ordered  never  to  commit  waste,  never  to  expose 

But  could  this  mandate  have  any  other  effect  than  that  of  estopping  the  de- 
fendants from  raising  the  same  question  over  again  ?  As  to  this  case  see 
Mary  Dormer  Harris,  Life  in  an  Old  English  Town  (1898),  p.  64,  where  the 
history  of  the  Prior's  Half  and  the  Earl's  Half  at  Coventry  is  related.' 

1  See  the  cases  cited  pp.  270-77,  supra. 

2  See  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  1081,  1162,  1253,  1284;  Fitz.  N.-B.  184, 
185. 

3  See  Y.B.  2  and  3  Ed.   II   (Selden  Soc.),  p.  xiii.,  71,   74  ;    Y.B.  18  Ed. 
Ill  (R.S.),  236. 

4  See  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  1920. 

5  See    Y.B.  30  and  31  Ed.  I  (R.S.),  324  ;    Y.B.   2  and  3  Ed.  II  (Selden 
Soc.),  pp.  93-96. 

6  See  pp.  270-77,  supra.  7  See  note  2,  supra. 

8  See  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  1920. 

9  See  Y.B.  2  and  3  Ed.  II  (Selden  Soc.),  pp.  93-96. 
™  See  Y.B.  30  and  31  Ed.  I  (R.S.),  324. 

11  See  Y.B.  2  and  3  Ed.  II  (Selden  Soc.),  p.  xiii.,  71,  74. 

12  See  pp.  277-80,  supra. 

13  See  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  1165  ;    Y.B.  18  Ed.  Ill  (R.S.),  236  ;  Fitz. 
N.-B.  184,  185. 

14  See  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  1165. 

15  Bracton's  Note-Book,  pi.  1081.  16  Fitz.  N.-B.  184,  185. 


xin]  Early  Equity  283 

wares  for  sale  elsewhere  than  in  the  plaintiffs  market,  never  to  sue 
in  the  ecclesiastical  court,  and  never  to  do  other  similar  things.1 

The  order  of  the  court  was  sometimes  contained  in  the  writ  of 
prohibition  itself;  sometimes  it  was  issued  at  the  conclusion  of  pro- 
ceedings, such  as  the  common  law  writ  of  waste,  brought  upon 
breach  of  a  prior  prohibition  ;  while  sometimes  it  was  issued  at  the 
conclusion  of  actions,  such  as  trespass,  brought  independently  of 
the  breach  of  a  prior  prohibition. 

I  have  stated  that  the  jurisdiction  of  the  common-law  courts  in 
cases  of  prohibition  was  a  jurisdiction  in  personam,  and  such  I 
believe  it  was.  In  all  cases  the  prohibition  was  issued  by  the  court 
itself.  In  some  cases  the  writ  was  addressed  to  the  sheriff,  and  it 
was  through  him,  an  officer  of  the  court,  that  the  court's  order  was 
conveyed  to  the  party.  In  other  cases  the  writ  containing  the  pro- 
hibition of  the  court  was  addressed  directly  to  the  party  without 
the  employment  of  the  sheriff  as  the  court's  instrument.  In  still 
other  cases  the  court's  prohibition  was  laid  upon  the  party  directly, 
especially  at  the  close  of  legal  proceedings,  without  the  employ- 
ment of  writ  or  sheriff.  As  I  have  already  indicated,  I  cannot 
think  that  in  cases  of  the  interposition  of  the  sheriff  the  writ  of  pro- 
hibition is  robbed  of  its  character  as  the  court's  order  in  personam  ; 
for  the  sheriff  acts  merely  as  the  court's  officer  in  informing  the 
party  of  the  court's  command.  Even  if  this  view  of  the  writ 
addressed  to  the  sheriff  be  not  adopted,  there  is  still  evidence  in 
plenty  that  the  court  frequently  gave  orders  to  the  party  directly, 
either  by  writ  or  by  command  issued  to  the  party  as  he  stood  before  k 
the  court  in  person. 

Although  the  writs  of  prohibition  contain  no  hint  of  the 
penalties  attendant  upon  disobedience  to  the  command  of  the  royal 
court,  it  is  nevertheless  clear  from  our  study  of  the  sources  that 
disobedience  resulted  in  serious  consequences.  In  some  cases 
breach  of  the  prohibition  gave  rise  to  self-help  on  the  part  of 
the  aggrieved  person,  forceful  measures  by  the  sheriff,  and  even 
imprisonment  of  the  disobedient  party.  So,  too,  breach  of  the 
prohibition  might  result  in  legal  proceedings  by  the  injured  party, 
and  in  these  proceedings  the  court  might  inflict  severe  penalties 
for  past  disobedience  and  might  also  take  measures  of  severe 
character  to  ensure  that  no  further  breaches  of  prohibition  take 
1  See  pp.  270-82,  supra. 


284  H.  D.  Hazeltine  [xni 

place.  Appearance  of  the  offending  parties  could  be  compelled  by 
one  or  more  attachments  by  gage  and  pledge  and  even  by  distraint 
of  all  their  lands ;  and  if,  on  inquest,  the  breach  of  prohibition  was 
proved,  there  might  result  payment  of  damages  to  the  plaintiffs, 
heavy  amercements  to  the  King,  loss  of  the  defendants'  lands,  and 
even  imprisonment  for  contempt  of  the  King's  prohibition.  On  the 
conclusion  of  the  legal  proceedings  the  court  usually  issued  a 
further  prohibition  and  ensured  obedience  to  this  new  order  by 
requiring  the  party  to  furnish  sureties,  by  threat  of  loss  of  the 
party's  land,  or  by  appointment  of  persons,  such  as  foresters  and 
servants,  whose  duty  it  was  to  see  that  there  should  be  no  further 
breach  of  prohibition. 

Surely  the  way  of  the  disobedient  party  was  not  made  easy  by 
the  early  common  law ;  and  we  may  well  believe  that  fear  of  the 
process  of  the  courts  acted,  in  the  great  majority  of  cases,  as  a 
wholesome  restraint.  The  early  common  law  tribunals  had  not 
the  writ  of  subpoena  at  their  command,  but  they  did  on 
occasion  issue  orders  which  closely  resembled  that  writ,  and  they 
did  have  an  effective  machinery  of  punitive  and  preventive  justice 
which  operated  both  upon  the  person  and  the  property  of  the  one 
who  did  not  comply  with  their  prohibitions. 

VI. — WRITS  QUIA   TIMEI 

I  have  dwelt  upon  the  writs  of  prohibition  because  they 
illustrate  so  clearly  the  preventive  justice  of  the  early  common  law  ; 
but  I  cannot  conclude  this  paper  without  a  bare  reference  to 
certain  other  writs  which  are  closely  related  to  writs  of  prohibition. 
I  refer  to  the  writs  quia  timet.  These  writs  anticipated  the 
Chancery's  bills  quia  timet,  which  are  so  called  in  analogy  to  the 
common  law  writs  which  they  supplanted.  Coke,  in  his  com- 
mentary on  Littleton,  draws  attention  to  the  writs  in  these 
words  :  '  And  note,  that  there  be  six  writs  in  law,  that  may  be 
maintained,  quia  timit  (sic),  before  any  molestation,  distresse,  or 
impleading :  as  I.  A  man  may  have  his  writ  of  mesne  (whereof 
Littleton  here  [§  142]  speaks)  before  he  be  distreyned.  2.  A 
warrantia  cartae,  before  he  be  impleaded.  3.  A  monstraverunt, 
before  any  distresse  or  vexation.  4.  An  audita  querela,  before  any 
execution  sued.  5.  A  curia  claudenda^  before  any  default  of 


xin]  Early  Equity  285 

inclosure.  6.  A  ne  injustl  vexes,  before  any  distresse  or  molesta- 
tion. And  these  be  called  brevia  anticipantia,  writs  of  prevention.' x 
As  explained  by  Story,  in  his  Equity  Jurisprudence,  the  bills  in 
equity  quia  timet  *  answer  precisely  to  this  latter  description. 
They  are  in  the  nature  of  writs  of  prevention,  to  accomplish  the 
ends  of  precautionary  justice.  They  are,  ordinarily,  applied  to 
prevent  wrongs  or  anticipated  mischiefs,  and  not  merely  to  redress 
them  when  done.  The  party  seeks  the  aid  of  a  court  of  equity, 
because  he  fears  (quia  timet}  some  future  probable  injury  to  his 
rights  or  interests,  and  not  because  an  injury  has  already  occurred, 
which  requires  any  compensation  or  other  relief/  2 

In  the  present  paper  I  have  not  attempted  to  give  an  exhaust- 
ive account  of  the  equity  of  the  early  common  law  courts.  What 
I  have  said  should  be  taken  as  merely  suggestive  of  results  that 
future  detailed  investigation  may  disclose  ;  for  there  are  evidences 
in  plenty  that  in  various  ways  other  than  those  I  have  mentioned 
to-day  the  early  justices  were  administering  principles  of  equity. 
But  enough  has  already  been  said,  I  hope,  to  indicate  that  not 
all  the  ideas  which  we  associate  with  English  Equity  were  either 
borrowed  from  the  Roman  system  by  the  Chancellors  or  original 
with  them.  The  advent  of  the  Chancellor  as  a  judicial  officer  of 
the  Crown  was  at  a  time  when  the  older  tribunals,  although  ex- 
panding their  own  system  to  meet  the  needs  of  a  growing  society, 
were  nevertheless  fettered  in  their  powers  by  statute  and  precedent 
as  well  as  by  the  conservatism  and  technicality  of  the  legal  pro- 
fession. The  Chancellor's  court,  exercising  very  wide  discretionary 
powers,  gradually  developed  the  elaborate  and  effective  system  of 
rules  and  principles  which  we  of  the  twentieth  century  know  as 
English  Equity.  But  while  fully  recognizing  the  achievements  of 
the  Chancery,  let  us  not  forget  that  the  new  tribunal  built  partly 
upon  the  older  practice  of  the  common  law  and  other  courts  whose 
equitable  jurisdiction  it  supplanted.  The  new  tribunal  did  not 
originate  English  Equity,  for  it  simply  carried  on  the  work  of  the 
older  courts  by  developing  in  greater  fulness  and  with  a  different 
machinery  the  equity  inherent  in  royal  justice. 

H.  D.  HAZELTINE. 

1  Co.  Litt.  looa. 

2  Story,  Equity  Jurisprudence,  2nd  Eng.  ed.,  §§  825,  826. 


XIV 

THE    TRANSFORMATION    OF    EQUITY1 

EQUITY,  aequitas,  eViei/ceia,  and  equivalents  in  modern  Continental 
tongues,  have  for  several  centuries  been  current  terms  among 
jurists  and  publicists.  In  England,  and  in  jurisdictions  beyond  seas 
which  took  their  law  from  England,  Equity  has  become,  by  a 
peculiar  historical  development,  the  name  of  a  special  body  of 
judicial  rules  administered  in  the  exercise  of  a  special  jurisdiction 
which  in  its  origin  was  extraordinary.  Historical  students  of  legal 
ideas  have  to  remember  that  this  technical  use  of  the  word  '  equity  ' 
is  much  less  ancient  than  the  jurisdiction  itself.  In  the  proceed- 
ings of  the  Court  of  Chancery  before  the  sixteenth  century  the 
complainants  appeal  to  the  Chancellor  most  commonly  in  the  name 
of  conscience,  pretty  often  in  that  of  good  faith,  right,  or  reason, 
very  seldom  in  that  of  equity.2  Perhaps  it  is  not  too  much  to  say 
that  the  term  was  only  becoming  current  among  English  lawyers 
when  St.  German  discussed  it  in  his  Doctor  and  Student,  a  discus- 
sion to  which  we  shall  presently  return.3  In  the  course  of  the  six- 
teenth century  the  Greek  word  €7rtetKeta  was  used  by  a  few  writers 
in  an  Anglicized  form  (see  the  Oxford  English  Dictionary,  s.v. 
'  Epiky '),  but  the  experiment  was  short-lived.  Whatever  words 
are  used,  the  general  notion  underlying  them  is  that  of  a  doctrine 
or  authority  capable  of  preventing  the  hardship  which  otherwise 
would  ensue  either  from  the  literal  extension  of  positive  rules  to 

1  The  present  paper  may  be  taken  as  in  some  measure  supplementary  to 
Professor  Vinogradoff's  on  Reason  and  Conscience  in  Sixteenth-Century  Juris- 
prudence^ read  at  the  Berlin  Congress  in   1908,  and  published  in  the  Law 
Quarterly  Review,  xxiv.  373. 

2  See  Baildon,  Select  Cases  in  Chancery  (Selden  Soc.),  1896,  Introduction, 
p.  xxix. 

3  St.  German's  immediate  authority  for  the  Aristotelian  doctrine  of  equity 
was  Gerson  :  ib.  374. 

286 


xiv]  Transformation  of  Equity  287 

extreme  cases  or  from  the  exclusion,  also  by  a  strictly  literal  con- 
struction, of  cases  that  fall  within  the  true  intention  of  the  rule. 

Such  being  the  purpose  of  equity  stated  in  the  widest  terms, 
there  are  two  quite  distinct  and  almost  opposite  aspects  under 
which  it  may  be  realized.  In  the  first  and  more  ancient  of  these 
we  find  equitable  power  exercised  by  some  one,  usually  the  king 
or  a  great  officer  of  state,  who  can  dispense  with  rules  according  to 
his  discretion,  conceived  as  a  reasonable  discretion  but  not  defined 
beforehand.  The  other  and  modern  form  is  the  rational  interpreta- 
tion and  qualification  of  the  rules  themselves  by  a  dialectic  and 
scientific  process. 

The  first  method  works  by  occasional  interference ;  the  occa- 
sions may  be  frequent  or  not,  but  each  interference  is  still  an 
isolated  act.  The  second  method  works,  on  the  contrary,  by  con- 
tinuous development.  It  is  by  this  time  almost  a  commonplace 
that  the  more  archaic  dispensing  power,  when  it  falls  into  a  regular 
course  of  official  administration,  loses  its  arbitrary  character  and 
gradually  assumes  all  the  features  of  scientific  law,  becoming,  as 
Blackstone  said  a  century  and  a  half  ago,  an  artificial  system.  In 
the  technical  English  terms,  extraordinary  jurisdiction  ends  by 
being  ordinary.  So  gradual  is  the  change  that  it  is  not  altogether 
easy  for  the  modern  student  to  realize  its  extent  or  the  discrepance 
of  the  original  points  of  view. 

Let  us  consider  the  nature  of  superior  dispensing  power  apart 
from  any  particular  forms.  It  appears  to  be  called  for  and 
determined  by  the  nature  of  archaic  legal  rules  and  archaic  juris- 
diction. Process  of  law  was,  in  the  beginning,  a  substitute  for 
unrestrained  private  vengeance  or  self-help.  For  a  long  time 
there  were  no  regular  means  at  all,  and  for  a  much  longer  time 
no  adequate  means,  of  compelling  parties  to  use  it.  Hence  early 
legal  formulas  do  not  necessarily  represent  the  general  sense,  at 
the  date  of  their  origin,  of  what  is  just  and  reasonable.  They 
rather  mark  an  outside  limit  beyond  which  vengeance  or  self-help 
will  not  be  tolerated,  and  that  limit  has  to  be  fixed  with  regard  to 
the  passions  of  ordinary  men  under  provocation.  The  lawgiver 
does  not  advise  taking  an  eye  for  an  eye  and  a  tooth  for  a  tooth ; 
he  forbids  taking  the  whole  head.  In  like  manner  the  harshness 
of  archaic  law  towards  debtors  is  capable  of  several  explanations, 
and  there  may  well  be  some  truth  in  all  of  them.  But  this  one, 


288  F.  Pollock  [xiv 

I  think,  is  fairly  certain,  that  the  law  had  to  compromise  with 
creditors  on  the  least  amount  of  power  over  the  debtor  which  must 
be  left  to  them  if  they  were  to  renounce  the  use  of  lawless  private 
force.  At  the  date  of  the  Twelve  Tables  that  amount  included,  in 
the  last  resort,  the  power  of  life  and  death,  although  there  is 
no  reason  to  believe  that  the  partis  secanto  clause  was  ever 
executed  in  historical  times.1  In  matters  of  family  law  we  know 
that  early  Indo-European  custom  hardly  touched  the  despotic 
authority  of  the  eldest  ancestor.  Accordingly  the  just  man,  in  the 
estimation  of  archaic  morality,  is  not  he  who  stands  on  his  right 
and  expects  others  to  stand  on  theirs,  but  he  who  knows  how  and 
when  to  forego  the  uttermost  farthing:  and,  when  once  a  competent 
executive  authority  has  been  established,  the  just  ruler  is  he  who 
gives  effect  to  the  moral  sense  of  the  commonwealth  by  relaxing 
penalties  in  cases  of  hardship  and  by  putting  forth  his  pre-eminent 
strength  against  enormous  evil-doers.  Such,  indeed,  is  the  pre- 
vailing sentiment  in  Eastern  countries  to  this  day.  Great  men 
and  superior  officials  are  conceived  not  as  ministers  of  rule,  but  as 
wielders  of  a  discretion  transcending  rule.  Even  educated  Asiatics 
appear  to  have  great  difficulty  in  understanding  that  there  can  be 
such  a  thing  as  a  rule  not  subject  to  a  power  of  administrative 
dispensation  in  some  one.  A  normal  Eastern  ruler  would  find 
nothing  strange  in  one  Pope  treating  Benvenuto  Cellini  as  exempt 
from  law  and  another  subjecting  him  to  rigorous  imprisonment  on 
mere  suspicion,  and  would  see  nothing  in  the  indignation  roused 
by  James  II.'s  prosecution  of  the  seven  bishops  but  one  proof  more 
that  all  Europeans  are  mad. 

Not  that  it  is  an  unknown  thing  in  Western  lands  to  sue  for 
personal  favour  or  indulgence  unwarranted  by  rule,  but  the  suitor, 
unless  he  is  very  ignorant,  knows  that  he  is  begging  for  something 
irregular  and  hopes  to  persuade  the  man  in  authority,  perhaps 
tries  to  persuade  himself,  that  a  small  breach  of  duty  will  be 
venial.  To  find  an  European  parallel  to  the  normal  Eastern  attitude 
we  must  look  outside  the  region  of  secular  law  to  the  popular  and 
still  half-pagan  cult  of  the  saints  in  the  Mediterranean  countries, 

1  '  Dissectum  esse  antiquitus  neminem  equidem  legi  neque  audivi ' :  A. 
Gellius,  xx.  i.  52  :  his  guess  as  to  the  original  intention  of  the  extreme 
penalty,  '  eo  consilio  tanta  inmanitas  poenae  denuntiatast  ne  ad  earn  unquam 
perveniretur J  is  of  course  uncritical,  but  many  modern  antiquaries  have  made 
as  bad  guesses  or  worse. 


xiv]  Transformation  of  Equity  289 

where,  as  an  ingenious  French  scholar  has  shown,  the  saints  have 
taken  up  the  heritage  of  the  gods.  There,  to  this  day,  patron  and 
other  saints  are  besought  and  expected,  sometimes  on  pain  of 
losing  their  worshipper's  devotion,  to  perform  a  variety  of  good 
offices  in  the  celestial  court,  often  of  a  kind  hardly  in  accordance 
with  the  doctrine  or  discipline  of  the  Church.  Among  the  more 
innocent  of  these  favours  is  that  of  helping  students  to  pass  their 
examinations,  for  which  it  seems  Ste.  Radegonde  of  Poitiers  has 
a  special  reputation.  I  know  not  whether  the  operation  is  in  the 
nature  of  strengthening  the  candidate's  brain  (which  the  psychologist 
may  regard  as  a  not  improbable  effect  of  his  faith)  or  of  softening 
the  examiner's  heart.  When  it  comes  to  invoking  St.  Antony  of 
Padua  to  save  a  man  harmless  in  a  duel,  in  other  words  to  protect 
him  from  the  temporal  inconvenience,  and  the  still  graver  spiritual 
danger,  of  being  killed  in  the  commission  of  a  wilful  and  deliberate 
mortal  sin,  the  notion  of  dispensing  power  appears  to  be  consider- 
ably strained.  Such  a  votive  tablet,  however,  I  have  seen,  and  I 
do  not  suppose  they  are  hard  to  find  in  Italy.  These  archaic 
observances  of  imperfectly  instructed  Catholics  may  be  regarded, 
it  seems  to  me,  as  modern  survivals  from  the  prehistoric  conception 
of  executive  authority  in  general. 

To  return  to  the  ground  of  our  own  faculty,  I  took  the  lex 
talionis  as  a  typical  example  of  archaic  positive  ordinance,  although 
it  is  strange  to  our  own  legal  history :  for  the  system  of  wergild 
and  composition  which,  at  the  opening  of  that  history,  we  find  in 
force  among  all  people  of  Germanic  stock  would  not  be  appropriate 
for  the  same  purpose.  It  seems  to  me  to  belong  to  a  much  later 
and  more  rational  stage  of  ancient  law,  for  it  presupposes  a  long 
course  of  bargaining  and  settlement  of  feuds,  not  so  much  between 
individuals  as  between  families  and  clans ;  and  that  again  pre- 
supposes a  more  or  less  effectual  desire  for  peace,  not  by  way  of 
submission  to  a  ruler  but  by  free  consent  of  both  parties.  We 
know  that  such  a  process  took  place  in  the  heroic  age  of  Greece. 
The  famous  trial  scene  on  the  Homeric  shield  of  Achilles  exhibits 
this  at  the  very  moment  when  public  opinion  begins  to  enforce  the 
acceptance  of  a  wergild  under  proper  conditions. 

Homer  omits  to  tell  us  what  those  conditions  were.  This  is 
unlucky  for  our  archaeology,  but  quite  right  for  the  artistic  purpose, 
which  is  to  describe  not  the  cause  in  dispute  or  the  scene  itself, 

U 


290  F.  Pollock  [xiv 

but  the  representation  of  it.  According  to  the  interpretation  in 
which  I  agree  with  my  friend  Dr.  Leaf,  the  question  is  precisely 
whether  an  aggrieved  party  who  refuses  the  offer  of  a  composition 
is  not  bound  to  accept  it :  there  does  not  appear  to  be  any  difficulty 
about  the  amount.  The  choice  on  the  other  side,  the  manslayer's 
or  offender's,  to  pay  or  to  bear  the  feud,  lasted  into  a  comparatively 
recent  period  of  Germanic  antiquity,  as  is  well  known.  On  the 
Homeric  development  the  curtain  goes  down  abruptly,  and  when 
it  next  rises  we  are  in  a  different  order  of  civilization  altogether, 
with  very  slight  materials  for  guessing  what  has  happened  in  the 
meantime.  In  any  case,  and  even  before  acceptance  or  offer  of  a 
composition  has  become  compulsory  in  form  or  in  fact,  the  existence 
of  an  assessable  value  shows  that  something  has  been  arrived  at 
corresponding  to  what  we  call  a  market  price  or  a  reasonable  price 
in  the  world  of  modern  business.  Thus  the  wergild  presents  itself 
not  as  the  utmost  that  can  be  exacted  by  strict  law  but  rather  as 
an  early  form  of  equitable  compromise ;  and  the  fixed  scales  of  the 
early  Germanic  law-books  are  really  codification  of  a  fairly  settled 
customary  rule  of  aequum  et  bonum.  It  might  be  shown,  I  think, 
without  much  trouble,  that  such  a  scale  of  compensation  was  in  its 
time  and  circumstances  a  much  more  sensible  institution  than  it 
appears  to  us  at  first  sight ;  but  to  pursue  this  would  be  somewhat 
too  remote  from  the  argument. 

In  England  the  archaic  form  of  equity  predominated  in  the 
king's  administration  of  special  remedial  justice  during  the  fourteenth 
and  fifteenth  centuries ;  the  sixteenth  was'  a  period  of  transition ; 
before  the  end  of  the  seventeenth  the  Court  of  Chancery  was  not 
only  a  regular  court  of  justice  but  had  started  on  the  road  of 
technical  and  scientific  elaboration. 

We  have  only  within  the  last  year  become  acquainted  with  a 
form  of  this  jurisdiction  earlier  than  its  exercise  by  the  Chancellor 
or  even  by  the  Council,  so  early  that  all  remembrance  of  it  was 
long  lost.  Mr.  Bolland,  in  the  course  of  editing  for  the  Selden 
Society  the  proceedings  of  Edward  II's  itinerant  justices  in 
Kent,  found  a  course  of  practice  of  which  no  intermediate  mention 
is  known  through  very  nearly  six  centuries.1  Causes  of  action 
arising  or  continuing  while  the  Eyre  was  in  the  county  were  brought 

1  2  Eyre  of  Kent  (Seld.  Soc.  1912),  Introd.  p.  xxi.  As  to  bills  on  the 
Crown  side,  p.  xxii. 


xiv]  Transformation  of  Equity  291 

before  the  justices  by  presenting  a  bill  instead  of  suing  out  a  writ 
in  the  appropriate  form  of  action.  Many  of  these  bills  are  pre- 
served, and  they  have  a  marked  resemblance  in  their  frame,  and 
in  many  cases  as  to  their  contents  also,  to  the  earliest  bills  irt 
Chancery.  To  understand  the  jurisdiction  it  must  be  remembered 
that  the  justices  in  eyre  represented  the  king's  authority  in  a 
special  and  eminent  manner.  If  we  may  borrow  a  canonical  term, 
they  carried  with  them  high  legatine  powers ;  they  superseded  all 
ordinary  tribunals.  Only  the  King's  Bench,  the  Court  held  in 
contemplation  of  law  before  the  king  himself,  could  claim  to  rank 
above  them.  Thus  the  king's  residual  or  extraordinary  function  of 
causing  justice  to  be  done  where  ordinary  means  failed  lay  in  their 
hand,  and  they  were  not  only  entitled  but  bound  to  exercise  it. 
Students  of  our  legal  history  do  not  need  to  be  reminded  that  this 
function  had  been  recognized  from  the  earliest  times,  and  was 
treated  as  living  much  later.  The  witnesses  for  it  extend  from 
King  Alfred's  companion  and  biographer,  the  Welsh  bishop  Asser, 
to  the  Kentish  antiquary  Lambarde,  one  of  Elizabeth's  justices  of 
peace.  So  the  justices  in  eyre,  being  such  exalted  ministers  of 
the  king's  power,  were  quite  natural  depositaries  of  this  royal 
discretion  when  as  yet  the  Court  of  Chancery  was  not. 

Applications  to  the  justices  in  eyre  by  way  of  bill  were 
multifarious  enough.  Some  of  those  which  Mr.  Bolland  has 
published  are  founded  on  money  claims  for  considerable  sums,  and 
the  parties  appear  to  be  of  good  standing.  But  there  is  also  a 
class  of  petitions  by  humble  suitors  for  relief  against  oppression  or 
extortion,  alleging  their  poverty  and  inability  to  cope  with  their 
adversaries  by  regular  process  of  law.  This  class  anticipates,  in 
almost  every  detail,  the  petitions  to  the  Council  and  the  Chancellor 
of  which  specimens  were  published  in  1820  by  the  old  Record 
Commission,  and  in  1896  by  the  Selden  Society.  We  find  here 
exactly  the  same  characteristic  mark  that  distinguishes  those  early 
Chancery  proceedings,  but  in  still  greater  prominence.  In  a  large 
proportion  of  cases  the  complaint  is  such  as,  in  the  later  settled 
practice,  would  have  justified  a  demurrer  'for  want  of  equity.' 
The  justices  are  not  called  op  to  administer  any  special  rules  or  to 
recognize  rights  outside  the  ordinary  law.  What  the  suitor  asks 
them  to  dispense  with  is  the  formality  of  process ;  he  claims  a 
summary  investigation,  to  use  canonical  language  once  more, 


292  F.  Pollock  [xiv 

sinefigura  et  strepitu  iudicii.  Considering  the  predominant  import- 
ance of  procedure  in  medieval  law,1  this  again  is  quite  natural. 
Sometimes  the  petitions  are  so  illiterate  that  the  manner  of  the 
halting  Anglo-French  is  almost  more  eloquent  of  the  petitioner's 
distress  than  the  matter.  A  specially  illiterate  one,  which  gave 
Mr.  Bolland  and  myself  a  good  deal  of  trouble  before  we  arrived 
at  the  true  rendering  by  the  help  of  a  French  medievalist,  relates 
the  misfortunes  of  a  man  who  had  paid  a  sum  down  to  secure 
board  and  lodging  for  the  rest  of  his  days.  Obviously  this  crude 
makeshift  for  a  life  annuity 2  was  at  the  mercy  of  the  host's  good 
faith ;  in  this  case  avarice  prevailed,  and  the  host  not  only  failed 
to  make  decent  provision  for  his  paying  guest,  but  imprisoned  him, 
tied  him  up,  it  seems,  with  a  chain.  This,  of  course,  was  a  plain 
trespass  at  common  law,  supposing  the  fact  to  have  been  as 
stated.  Perhaps  the  story  gained  something  in  the  telling;  at 
any  rate  the  result  was  a  settlement  of  some  kind  between  the 
parties.  We  have  said  that  there  was  no  question,  at  this  time, 
of  applying  any  peculiar  law  to  the  suits  initiated  by  bills  in  eyre ; 
but  it  does  appear  that  the  justices,  when  once  they  had  a  case 
in  their  hands,  could  proceed  in  a  summary  manner  and  use  a 
pretty  free  discretion.  They  could  even  interrogate  the  parties,  a 
thing  unknown  to  common-law  process.  On  the  other  hand,  a  case 
begun  in  this  way  sometimes  runs  its  later  course  to  judgment  as 
regularly  as  if  it  had  started  with  a  writ;  and  this  may  throw 
some  light  on  singularities  of  early  Chancery  procedure  to  which 
Mr.  Pike  had  called  attention  long  before  we  knew  that  there  was 
such  a  thing  as  a  bill  in  eyre. 

It  is  needless  to  say  more  here  of  Chancery  suits  in  the 
fourteenth  and  fifteenth  centuries,  as  the  information  is  easily 
accessible  in  the  Selden  Society  volume  already  referred  to, 
and  is  summarized  by  Dr.  Holdsworth.  There  is,  however,  one 
rather  curious  head  of  jurisdiction  of  which  I  have  found  no 
mention  in  text-books.  It  was  not  very  uncommon  to  apply  to 
the  Chancellor  for  an  injunction  to  restrain  the  defendant  from 

1  The  'lex  terrae'  of  Magna  Carta,  for  example,  is  rather  due  process 
of  law  than  the  substantive  law  defining  offences. 

2  Similar  agreements  were  still  in  use  in  the  latest  years  of  the  fifteenth 
century:    Trice  Martin  in  Archaeologia,  Ix.   (i)  at  p.  378,  where  the  com- 
plaint is  of  refusal  '  to  fynd  or  kepe '  the  plaintiff. 


xiv]  Transformation  of  Equity  293 

practising  witchcraft  against  the  plaintiff,  or,  it  might  be,  from 
making  false  charges  of  witchcraft  against  him.  This  appears  from 
a  group  of  cases  in  which  clergymen  were  concerned,  printed  in 
1907  by  Mr.  Trice  Martin  in  the  Archaeology*?  as  well  as  from 
the  more  generally  known  publications.  If  there  was  any  usurpation 
of  jurisdiction  in  matters  of '  nygromancy '  it  was  against  the  Court 
Christian. 

There  is  no  reason  to  believe  that  the  jurisdiction  of  the 
mediaeval  Chancellors  was  unpopular.  Complaints  began  to  be 
loud  in  the  sixteenth  century,  and  were  heard  of  earlier.2  But 
these  were  for  the  most  part,  if  not  altogether,  made  or  instigated 
by  practitioners  of  the  common  law  who  were  aggrieved  by  the 
growing  competition  of  the  Chancery.  If  the  competition  had  not 
met  a  public  want  it  would  not  have  been  effective.  What  concerns 
us  to  note  here  is  that  the  grievance  was  expressly  founded  on 
charges  of  arbitrary  and  uncertain  interference  with  legal  rights ; 
the  Chancellor  and  his  officers  went,  it  was  said,  by  their  <  conscience 
and  discretion/  which  might  mean  reasons  borrowed  from  Roman 
law  or  anything  else  they  chose.  The  only  final  and  satisfying 
answer  to  such  objections  in  a  civilized  country  was  to  make  it 
clear  that  the  Court  of  Chancery  was  not  a  fountain  of  unlimited 
dispensations,  but  as  regular  a  court  of  judicature  as  any  other,  a 
court  whose  existence  precluded  the  king  from  setting  up  any  new 
tribunals  with  like  jurisdiction,  or  administering  its  remedies  in  any 
other  way ;  and  this  was  in  fact  the  line  taken  by  James  I  with 
Bacon's  advice  when  the  conflict  became  open  and  official. 

Meanwhile  Christopher  St.  German,  a  writer  in  advance  of  his 
contemporaries  in  many  things,  put  an  explanation  of  Equity  in 
the  mouth  of  his  imaginary  Doctor  of  Divinity,3  and  appropriately 
so,  when  it  was  still  exceptional  for  the  Chancellor  to  be  a  layman. 
The  Doctor  speaks,  of  course,  from  the  canonical  point  of  view,  and 
does  not  profess  to  know  Chancery  practice.  Equity  is  not  yet  a 
term  of  art  among  lawyers.  The  Student  knows  something,  it 
appears  later,  about  the  cases  in  which  the  writ  of  sub  poena  does 
and  does  not  lie,  but  does  not  care  to  go  into  details.  Now  the 

1  Vol.  lx.  (or  2nd  ser.  10)  pt.  i,  353;  cp.  the  same  writer's  miscellaneous 
specimens  in  vol.  lix.,  pt.  i,  I  (1904). 

2  Holdsworth,  H.  E.  L.  i.  246. 

3  Doct.  and  Stud.,  dial,  i,  c.  16. 


294  F>  Pollock  [xiv 

Doctor  quite  clearly  takes  the  view  that  the  fundamental  principle 
of  equity  is  not  occasional  and  overriding  interference,  but 
enlightened  scientific  interpretation.  I  am  putting  St.  German's 
thought  into  modern  language,  but  I  believe  the^  words  bear  me 
out.  '  Equity  is  a  righteousness  that  considereth  all  the  particular 
circumstances  of  the  deed  .  .  .  and  it  is  called  also  by  some  men 
epieikeia ;  the  which  is  no  other  thing  but  an  exception  of  the  law 
of  God,  or  of  the  law  of  reason,  from  the  general  rules  of  the  law  of 
man,  when  they  by  reason  of  their  generality  would  in  any 
particular  case  judge  against  the  law  of  God  or  the  law  of  reason 
— the  which  exception  is  secretly  understood  in  every  general  rule  of 
general  positive  law'  Of  these  last  words  it  is  hardly  too  much  to 
say  that  they  anticipate  the  reforming  and  constructive  spirit  of 
Mansfield.  The  conception  of  Equity  as  expounded  by  St.  German 
was  in  itself  nothing  new.  He  was  quite  openly  following  the 
scholastic  tradition  which  went  back  partly  by  direct  and  partly  by 
indirect  ways  to  Aristotle.  But  the  treatment  of  it  as  practically 
applicable  to  English  law  shows  a  grasp  and  insight  quite 
exceptional  at  the  time.  The  Doctor  goes  on  to  suggest  that 
there  may  be  *  some  like  equities  grounded  on  the  general  rules  of 
the  law  of  the  realm '  and  elicits  from  the  Student  examples  of 
equitable  construction  applied  within  the  common  law  itself.  In 
the  next  chapter  the  Student  goes  so  far  as  to  say  that  the  only 
reason  why  the  equitable  relief  granted  upon  bills  in  Chancery  does 
not  count  as  part  of  the  common  law  is  the  absence  of  a  formal 
record  in  the  king's  court.  '  Forasmuch  as  no  record  remaineth  in 
the  king's  court  of  no  such  bill,  nor  of  the  writ  of  sub  poena  or  injunc- 
tion that  is  used  thereupon ;  therefore  it  is  not  set  as  for  a  special 
ground  of  the  law,  but  as  a  thing  that  is  suffered  by  the  law.' 

About  a  century  later  the  Court  of  Chancery  was  solemnly 
recognized  as  a  perfect  and  regular  court  of  justice.  Yet  it  was 
not  till  the  end  of  the  seventeenth  century  that  James  I's  decisive 
action  bore  its  due  fruit.  The  causes  of  the  check  were  not  legal 
but  political,  and  are  to  be  found  in  the  controversies  between  king 
and  parliament,  between  prelates  and  Puritans,  which  led  to  the 
Civil  War.  The  Chancellor  was  still  eminently  the  king's  minister  ; 
his  jurisdiction  was  practically  uncontrolled,  for  there  was  no 
appellate  Court ;  and  men  saw  in  the  Chancellor's  discretion,  as  they 
had  seen  in  the  criminal  equity  of  the  Star  Chamber,  a  power  of 


xiv]  Transformation  of  Equity  295 

being  abused  to  political  ends.  Here,  and  not  in  any  merely 
technical  prejudice,  is  the  explanation  of  Selden's  famous  gibe 
1  Equity  is  a  roguish  thing.'  It  is  so  because  the  measure  of  the 
Chancellor's  foot  may  go  too  near  to  follow  the  measure  of  King 
Charles  I.'s  foot,  peradventure  even  Archbishop  Laud's :  and  so 
the  fuller  working  out  of  equity  on  St.  German's  lines  had  to  wait 
for  the  settlement  of  a  free  political  constitution. 

So  far  as  England  is  concerned,  the  Puritan  dislike  of  Chancery 
jurisdiction  may  be  taken  as  belonging  to  the  common  knowledge 
of  legal  and  other  historians ;  and  we  know  in  a  general  way  that 
it  was  carried  across  the  Atlantic.  The  full  extent  of  its  working 
on  the  western  continent  has  been  disclosed  to  the  learned  world 
only  by  pretty  recent  publications  of  American  scholars.  While 
Story  was  setting  forth  the  beauties  of  equity  jurisprudence  in  his 
most  elegant  periods,  the  power  of  administering  equitable  remedies 
was  still,  in  more  than  one  State,  altogether  lacking  or  rudimentary. 
Traces  of  the  old  prejudice  may  be  found  even  in  much  later 
American  writers.  We  have  to  remember,  however,  that  the 
Common  Law  itself  found  but  little  favour  in  the  eyes  of  the 
Pilgrim  Fathers  and  their  successors.  For  a  time  it  was  in  danger 
of  being  replaced  by  the  Pentateuch,  and  its  reception  was  pre- 
carious, even  beyond  the  Puritan  commonwealths  of  New  England, 
down  to  the  eighteenth  century.1  We  have  also  to  remember  in 
extenuation  that  for  some  little  time  after  the  Restoration  English 
Common  Law  judges  themselves  had  not  got  clear  of  the  old 
notions  about  equity,  and  wondered  what  it  should  have  to  do  with 
precedents. 

In  our  own  time,  it  is  almost  needless  to  say,  courts  of  equitable 
jurisdiction  wholly  disclaim  any  such  roving  powers  of  dispensation 
and  administrative  interference  as  were  exercised  by  the  medieval 
Chancellors.  A  judge  of  the  Chancery  Division  can  in  plain  terms 
deny  that  his  Court  is  a  Court  of  conscience.2  It  would  be  beyond 
my  present  scope,  and  beyond  my  competence,  to  look  for  any 
similar  process  of  transformation  in  other  systems  of  law ;  but  the 

1  S.  D.  Wilson,  '  Courts  of  Chancery  in  the  American  Colonies,'  Essays  in 
Anglo-American  Legal  History,  ii.  779  ;  Fisher,  '  The  Administration  of  Equity 
through  Common  Law  Forms,'  ibid.  ii.  810  ;  Reinsch,  'English  Common  Law 
in  the  Early  American  Colonies,'  ibid.  i.  369. 

2  Lord  Justice  (then  Justice)  Buckley  [1903]  2  Ch.  at  p.  195. 


296  F.  Pollock  [xiv 

case  of  droit  administratif  in  France  is  so  near  at  hand  and  so 
generally  known  that  I  may  allow  myself  to  mention  it.  The 
semi-political  jurisdiction  of  the  Conseil  d'Etat,  established  under 
the  First  Empire  in  the  interest  of  the  government  rather  than  of  the 
citizen,  has  by  this  time  acquired  a  perfectly  judicial  character,  and 
it  is  said  that  the  result  is  at  times  better  for  the  suitor  than  what 
he  could  look  for  under  the  ordinary  law. 

During  the  last  two  centuries  the  scientific  construction  of 
equity  jurisprudence  in  England  has  been  in  the  hands  of  a  highly 
specialized  section  of  the  Bench  and  Bar,  concentrated  in  these  very 
precincts  of  Lincoln's  Inn  where  we  are  sitting.  Practitioners  of 
the  common  law  regarded  equity  much  as  the  lay  people  regarded 
all  legal  science,  that  is,  as  an  inscrutable  kind  of  magic,  and  rather 
black  than  white.  Even  since  the  jurisdiction  of  our  present 
Supreme  Court  in  all  its  branches  has  been  made  uniform  this 
frame  of  mind  has  hardly  become  extinct,  and  there  is  still  some- 
thing esoteric  about  the  doctrines  of  equity  and  conveyancing.  The 
whole  of  the  ground  sacred  to  these  mysteries  would  be  included  in 
a  radius  of  five  hundred  yards,  or  for  abundant  caution  let  us  say 
metres,  drawn  from  this  Old  Hall  of  Lincoln's  Inn,  within  or  near 
whose  walls  the  law  of  the  Court  of  Chancery  was  discussed  and 
settled  by  several  generations  of  lawyers. 

F.   POLLOCK. 


XV 

THE  INFLUENCE  OF  COKE  ON  THE 
DEVELOPMENT  OF  ENGLISH  LAW1 

THE  age  of  Coke  was  a  critical  period  in  the  history  of  our  common 
law.  During  the  sixteenth  century  the  work  of  making  England  a 
territorial  state  of  the  modern  type  had  been  accomplished,  partly 
by  the  legislature,  partly  by  newly  created  or  newly  organized  courts 
and  councils,  and  partly  by  the  common  law  courts.  With  the 
natural  expansion  of  the  jurisdiction  of  these  courts  and  councils 
conflicts  between  them  had  become  frequent ;  and  they  became 
more  frequent  and  more  bitter  when  the  restraining  influence  of 
Elizabeth  was  removed.  A  settlement  based  upon  an  impartial 
consideration  of  the  claims  of  these  rival  courts  was  eminently 
desirable.  But  it  was  never  reached,  because  these  disputes  about 
jurisdiction  soon  became  merged  in  that  larger  question  of  the 
whereabouts  of  the  sovereign  power  in  the  State  which  underlay 
the  various  causes  of  conflict  between  the  King  and  his  Parliament. 
The  newly  created  or  newly  organized  courts  naturally  magnified 
the  prerogative  on  which  they  leaned,  and  to  which  they  owed  their 
authority.  They  therefore  gravitated  to  the  royalist  view  that  in 
the  last  resort  the  prerogative  was  the  sovereign  power  in  the  State. 
On  the  other  hand  the  common  law  was  firmly  based  upon  the 

1  This  paper  is  printed  in  the  form  in  which  it  was  written  for  the  Inter- 
national Historical  Congress.  It  is  a  summary  of  a  fuller  account  of  Coke's 
career  and  influence  which  will  appear  in  the  succeeding  volumes  of  the 
author's  History  of  English  Law.  For  this  reason  the  author  has  thought  it 
best  not  to  overweight  it  by  inserting  the  authorities  for  the  statements  con- 
tained in  it.  He  has  therefore  only  inserted  explanatory  references  when  these 
appeared  to  be  necessary  for  the  understanding  of  the  text.  The  fuller  account 
of  Coke  will,  of  course,  contain  detailed  references  to  the  authorities. 

297 


298  IV.  S.  Holdsworth  [xv 

mediaeval  idea  that  in  the  State  the  law  was  supreme,  and  that  the 
prerogative  was  limited  by  it.  The  common  lawyers  therefore 
gravitated  to  the  Parliamentary  view  that  definite  legal  limits 
should  be  assigned  to  the  prerogative,  and  that  ministers  who 
overstepped  those  limits  should  be  made  responsible  to  the  law. 
Conversely  the  Parliamentary  leaders  naturally  held  that  the  law 
to  which  they  were  responsible  was  that  common  law  in  which 
alone  they  could  find  a  legal  justification  for  their  political  views. 

But  the  additions  made  by  the  modern  cases  and  statutes  to 
the  mediaeval  principles  on  which  the  common  law  was  founded 
made  it  often  obscure  and  sometimes  irrational.  Was  it  capable, 
it  might  fairly  be  asked,  of  supplying  the  principles  needed  to 
guide  the  development  of  the  public  and  private  law  of  a  modern 
state  ?  The  common  lawyers  maintained  that  it  was  all  sufficient 
for  this  purpose ;  and  though  the  growth  of  an  independent  system 
of  equity,  and  the  slow  development  of  a  reasonable  system  of  com- 
mercial law,  show  that  they  to  some  extent  exaggerated  the  capacity 
of  their  system,  the  history  of  English  public  law  in  the  seventeenth 
century,  and  the  growth  of  new  branches  of  private  law  in  the 
eighteenth  and  nineteenth  centuries,  have  justified  their  faith. 
That  the  common  law  was  given  this  chance  of  justifying  the 
faith  of  those  who  believed  in  its  capacity  is  largely  due  to  the 
career  and  writings  of  Edward  Coke. 

The  main  facts  of  Coke's  career  are  well  known  and  a  very  brief 
recapitulation  will  suffice.  He  was  born  in  1551-2,  and  was  called 
to  the  bar  in  1578.  He  became  Solicitor-General  in  1592,  and  was 
Attorney-General  from  1593  to  1606.  It  was  during  the  latter  part 
of  this  period  that  he  published  the  first  three  volumes  of  his 
Reports,  and  gained  the  reputation  of  being  the  most  learned 
lawyer  in  England.  It  was  during  this  period  also  that  he  acquired 
that  reverence  for  the  common  law  which  is  the  keynote  of  his 
whole  career.  In  1606  he  became  Chief  Justice  of  the  Common 
Pleas,  and  at  once  claimed  for  the  common  law  the  position  of 
supremacy  in  the  State  to  which  he  believed  it  to  be  entitled. 
This  involved  him  in  disputes  with  rival  Courts,  and,  as  James  I 
claimed  to  be  the  arbiter  of  all  these  disputes  about  jurisdiction, 
with  the  king  himself.  These  disputes  merely  confirmed  Coke  in 
his  fixed  belief  as  to  the  position  of  the  common  law  in  the  State. 
Thus,  when,  in  1613,  ne  was  made  Chief  Justice  of  the  King's  Bench, 


XV] 


Coke 


299 


the  quarrel  still  continued  ;  and  at  length,  in  1618,  he  was  dismissed 
from  the  Bench  and  ordered  to  revise  his  Reports.  After  a  period 
of  hesitancy  he,  in  1620,  decisively  threw  in  his  lot  with  the  Parlia- 
mentary opposition.  Till  1628  he  took  a  leading  part  in  all  the 
Parliaments  of  James  I's  and  Charles  I's  reigns,  except  that  of  1626. 
In  the  Parliament  of  1628  he  drafted  and  helped  to  carry  the  Petition 
of  Right ;  and  the  stormy  scenes  which  marked  its  passage  were  his 
last  appearance  in  public  life.  His  remaining  six  years  were  spent 
in  retirement.  Charles  I,  on  his  death  in  1634,  seized  all  his 
manuscripts,  lest  they  should  contain  matter  to  the  prejudice  of  the 
prerogative  ;  for,  as  he  said,  ( he  is  held  too  great  an  oracle  among 
the  people,  and  they  may  be  misled  by  anything  that  carries  such 
an  authority  as  all  things  do  that  he  either  speaks  or  writes.' 

The  fears  of  Charles  are  the  best  evidence  of  Coke's  reputation. 
It  was  a  reputation  fairly  earned  by  the  manner  in  which  he  had 
devoted  all  his  great  powers  to  the  single  object  of  understanding, 
applying,  explaining,  and  systematizing  the  common  law.  The 
large  place  which  he  fills  in  English  history  is  no  doubt  due  in  a 
great  degree  to  the  character  of  the  age.  In  quieter  times  he  would 
simply  have  been  a  great  common  lawyer  with  conservative 
prejudices.  But  in  the  seventeenth  century  a  great  common  lawyer, 
who  was  passionately  convinced  of  the  excellence  of  the  common 
law  and  of  its  right  to  be  the  supreme  law  in  the  State,  was 
necessarily  drawn  into  politics  in  order  to  defend  its  claims.  The 
fact  that  he  was  thus  drawn  into  politics  causes  an  apparent 
inconsistency  in  his  career,  and  some  real  inconsistency  in  his 
statements  of  the  doctrines  of  constitutional  law.  At  first  sight, 
there  seems  to  be  little  in  common  between  Elizabeth's  zealous 
Attorney-General,  and  the  man  who  framed  and  helped  to  carry 
the  Petition  of  Right.  But  this  inconsistency  is,  to  a  large  extent, 
only  apparent.  He  could  be  a  zealous  servant  of  the  Crown  under 
the  balanced  Tudor  monarchy,  which  so  skilfully  and  diplomatically 
shelved  fundamental  questions.  Under  James  I  he  was  driven 
to  resist  the  attempts  to  substitute  the  supremacy  of  the  Crown  for 
the  supremacy  of  the  common  law.  In  the  later  years  of  James  I's 
reign,  and  under  Charles  I,  he  was  driven  into  alliance  with  the 
Parliamentary  opposition  in  order  to  uphold  as  against  the 
Crown  the  laws  which  secured  the  rights  and  privileges  of  Parlia- 
ment, and  the  liberties  of  the  subject.  He  stood  still.  His 


3OO  W.  S.  Holdsworth  [xv 

outlook  was  always  that  of  a  statesman  of  the  latter  part  of  the 
Tudor  period.  It  was  the  changing  political  scene  which  seemed  to 
place  him  in  constantly  fresh  positions,  and  necessarily  led  him  to 
modify  his  views  as  to  important  doctrines  of  constitutional  law. 

The  character  of  the  man  and  of  the  age  fully  accounts  for  his 
vast  influence  upon  the  law  and  politics  of  the  seventeenth 
century.  But  they  do  not  fully  account  for  the  permanence  of  his 
influence  upon  the  future  development  of  English  law.  This 
permanence  is  due  to  the  fact  that  his  devotion  to  the  common  law 
led  him  to  consider  it  to  be  his  duty  to  employ  the  scanty  leisure 
of  a  busy  career  in  the  work  of  restating  in  his  writings  all  its 
principal  doctrines.  If,  therefore,  we  would  understand  the  reasons 
for  the  permanence  of  his  influence,  if  we  would  estimate  its  nature 
and  extent  we  must  examine  the  character  of  these  writings. 

The  two  works  which  have  had  this  great  influence  are  the 
Reports  and  the  Institutes. 

The  first  part  of  the  Reports  was  published  in  1600,  the  next 
two  shortly  after,  and  the  remaining  eight  at  intervals  between 
1603  and  1615.  The  twelfth  and  thirteenth  parts  were  published 
after  Coke's  death  in  1655  and  1658.  They  were  not  prepared  by 
him  for  the  press ;  and  are  in  fact  simply  rough  notes  of  cases 
and  other  transactions  in  which  he  had  taken  part.  They  have 
never  had  the  same  authority  as  the  other  eleven  parts,  which  he 
himself  published  as  his  considered  views  upon  the  matters  therein 
contained. 

When  Coke  wrote  his  Reports  there  was  no  agreement  as  to  the 
proper  style  of  making  a  law  report.  The  Year  Book  reports  are 
often  very  discursive  narratives  of  the  proceedings  in  Court.  But 
it  is  clear  that  in  Coke's  day  much  more  attention  was  being  paid 
both  to  the  actual  discussion,  and  to  the  reasons  on  which  it  was 
based,  than  in  the  earlier  period.  The  constant  and  frequent 
citation  of  cases  in  court,  sometimes  on  the  point  and  sometimes 
at  a  great  distance  from  that  point,  is  noted  by  Coke  and  contrasted 
with  the  earlier  practice.  But  the  report  was  still  made  primarily 
for  the  benefit  of  the  reporter ;  and  reporters  adopted  all  styles 
from  the  short  notes  of  Bendloe  to  the  elaborate  statements  of 
record,  argument,  and  judgment  contained  in  Plowden.  Coke  did 
not  adopt  any  one  style.  To  a  certain  extent  he  was  guided  by  the 
nature  of  the  case  which  he  was  reporting.  Occasionally  he  makes 


xv]  Coke  301 

a  case  a  mere  peg  for  a  disquisition  on  some  branch  of  law.1 
Sometimes  he  groups  together  the  reports  of  several  cases  on  one 
topic,  e.g.  slander,  by-laws,  usury,  copyhold;2  and  these  reports 
are  usually  summary.  When  the  case  is  important  he  often  gives 
the  pleadings  at  length,  a  summary  of  the  argument  on  both  sides, 
and  the  decision,  together  with  the  reasons  for  it.  In  these  cases 
Coke  no  doubt  intended  to  give  the  effect  of  what  was  said  in 
Court.  But  it  is  probable  that  he  added  both  explanations  and 
disquisitions  which  his  own  reading,  and  his  enthusiasm  for  what  he 
regarded  as  sound  doctrine,  suggested  to  him.  Bacon  once  said 
that  in  his  Reports  there  was  too  much  '  de  proprio.' 

The  cases  reported  form  a  corpus  of  the  common  law  in  the 
sixteenth  century.  All  parts  of  the  law  old  and  new  are  reviewed. 
The  older  learning  where  applicable  is  restated ;  the  manner  in 
which  it  had  been  modified  by  the  statutes  of  the  sixteenth  and 
early  seventeenth  centuries  is  explained  ;  and  the  statutes  which 
introduced  new  branches  of  law  are  applied  and  interpreted.  The 
new  developments  of  the  common  law — such  as  the  beginning  of 
the  struggle  against  perpetuities,  the  development  of  assumpsit,  the 
practice  of  allowing  actions  on  contracts  made  abroad — are  noted 
and  justified.  Numerous  cases,  heard  before  courts  other  than  the 
common  law  courts  (e.g.  the  Court  of  Wards  and  the  Court  of 
Star  Chamber),  appear.  The  fact  that  the  common  law  could 
appeal  to  some  of  these  precedents  was  very  useful  to  it  when 
the  results  of  the  Great  Rebellion  gave  it  all  and  even  more  than 
all  the  jurisdiction  which  Coke  had  claimed  for  it. 

The  four  books  of  the  Institutes  were  designed  to  supply  the 
student  with  a  general  introduction  to  the  law.  The  older  methods 
of  legal  education  were  hardly  sufficient  by  themselves,  now  that 
the  law  was  growing  more  complex.  Coke  set  himself  to  write, 
for  the  benefit  of  the  student,  the  earliest  of  our  text-books  on  the 
modern  common  law.  The  First  Institute  contains  his  com- 
mentary on  Littleton.  The  Second  is  a  discursive  commentary 
on  some  39  statutes,  of  which  28  belonged  to  the  mediaeval  period. 
Many  of  them  deal  with  matters  of  public  law.  The  Third 
deals  with  the  criminal  law,  and  the  Fourth  with  the  jurisdiction  of 

1  Blackamore's  Case,  8  Co.  Rep.  i  $6a — amendments  of  process  ;  Beecher's 
Case  8  Co.  Rep.  $8a — amercements. 

2  4  Co.  Rep.  I2b-2ia  (slander) ;  5  Co.  Rep.  620-643  (by-laws)  ;  ibid.  6ga, 
7ob  (usury)  ;  4  Co.  Rep.  2ia-32a  (copyhold). 


302  IV.  S.  Holdswortk  [xv 

courts.  Throughout  the  Second,  Third,  and  Fourth  Institutes  Coke 
insists  on  his  views  as  to  the  supremacy  of  the  common  law  courts 
which  had  cost  him  his  seat  on  the  bench.  'The  First  Institute  was 
the  only  one  which  Coke  published  in  his  lifetime.  The  other 
three  were  published  in  1641. 

The  First  Institute  is  a  book  of  a  very  different  character  to 
the  other  three.  Littleton  was  one  of  the  first  books  which  a 
student  read,  and  Coke  had  been  collecting  material  for  it  all  his 
life — from  the  time  probably  that  he  first  read  it  as  a  student. 
Coke  upon  Littleton  was  meant  to  be  Littleton  up-to-date — bearing 
somewhat  the  same  relation  to  Littleton  as  Justinian's  Institutes 
bear  to  the  Institutes  of  Gams.  But  it  is  much  more  than  this. 
The  commentary  is  extraordinarily  minute.  It  gives  the  most 
elementary  pieces  of  information,  and  also  disquisitions  upon  the 
most  abstruse  points  of  law.  All  parts  of  the  law  not  dealt  with  in 
the  other  three  books,  and  many  that  are,  are  introduced  into  this 
wonderful  commentary.  It  could  never  have  been  a  good  students' 
text-book,  and  it  is  rather  difficult  to  see  how  even  its  author 
could  have  supposed  that  it  was  suitable  for  this  purpose.  One 
reason  may  be  found  in  the  fact  that  he  did  not  intend  the  student 
to  read  it  all  at  once,  and  another  in  the  fact  that  it  was  supple- 
mented by  the  instruction  given  by  the  Inns  of  Court.  Moreover, 
what  is  to  our  eyes  one  source  of  confusion,  the  grouping  of  a 
large  number  of  miscellaneous  legal  topics  round  the  land  law,  was 
the  traditional  historic  order  of  the  common  law.  Just  as  in 
Roman  law  many  topics  belonging  to  the  general  law  of  contract 
are  grouped  round  the  stipulatio,  because  it  was  the  most  general 
form  of  contract  known  to  Roman  law ;  so  in  English  law,  from 
the  days  of  Bracton,  many  various  topics  had  been  grouped  round 
the  land  law,  because  it  was  the  most  highly  developed  branch 
of  the  common  law.  The  rapid  development  of  the  common  law 
was  fast  making  this  grouping  of  topics  obsolete — the  law  of 
contract  and  the  law  of  personal  property  were  fast  becoming 
independent  branches  of  law,  and  as  important  as  the  land  law. 
But  it  was  hardly  to  be  expected  that  Coke,  whose  outlook  was 
always  to  the  past,  should  appreciate  this.  That  was  a  point  of 
view  which  came  more  naturally  to  a  man  like  Bacon  whose 
outlook  was  towards  the  future. 

It  is  easy  to  see  why  Coke  did  not  care  to  publish  the  last 


xv]  Coke  303 

three  parts  of  the  Institutes  in  his  lifetime.  The  First  Institute 
dealt  with  branches  of  the  law  very  remote  from  any  of  the  con- 
stitutional controversies  of  the  day.  But  a  large  number  of  the  topics 
treated  of  in  the  other  three  books  touched  them  at  many  points. 
In  1628,  when  the  Second  and  Third  Institutes  were  finished, 
Coke's  active  career  was  over ;  and,  when  the  Fourth  Institute 
was  finished,  Parliament  had  been  dissolved  and  the  country  was 
being  governed  by  the  Prerogative.  We  cannot  blame  Coke  for 
not  wishing  to  shorten  his  few  remaining  years  by  a  close  im- 
prisonment in  the  Tower.  He  had  recorded  his  opinions  :  their 
publication  could  well  wait  for  a  more  favourable  season. 

When  they  were  published  in  1641  it  was  the  hour  of  the 
victory  of  the  common  law  and  of  the  Parliament.  Men  did  not 
stop  to  consider  the  accuracy  or  the  validity  of  the  arguments  upon 
which  Coke  based  his  claim  that  the  common  law  and  the  Parlia- 
ment were  supreme  in  the  State.  They  simply  accepted  them  and 
made  them  the  basis,  not  only  of  our  modern  constitutional  law, 
but  also  of  the  whole  of  that  large  part  of  our  modern  English  law 
which  is  comprised  under  the  general  term  'common  law.'  It  is 
not  surprising  therefore  that,  almost  down  to  our  own  days,  there 
have  been  many  lawyers  who  would  hardly  admit  of  the  existence 
of  any  serious  shortcomings  in  Coke's  work.  But  during  the  last 
century  there  has  been  a  reaction.  Coke  has  been  attacked  on 
opposite  grounds  by  two  very  different  schools  of  lawyers.  In  the 
first  place  he  has  been  attacked  by  the  historical  school  on  the 
ground  that  he  has  sometimes  carelessly  and  sometimes,  it  is  even 
said,  intentionally  misrepresented  historical  facts.  In  the  second 
place  he  has  been  attacked  by  lawyers  of  the  school  of  Austin  and 
Bentham  on  the  ground  that  both  the  material  and  the  form  of  his 
writings  are  obscure,  illogical,  and  ill-arranged.  Let  us  look  at 
these  two  classes  of  criticism,  and  see  to  what  extent  they  are 
justified. 

(i)  THE  EXCEPTIONS  TAKEN  BY  THE  HISTORIANS 

Time  has  its  revenges.  Coke  in  his  lifetime  was  at  pains  to 
advise  and  correct  historians  if  they  ventured  into  the  domain  of 
law.  Now  the  historians  have  turned  upon  Coke  and  pointed  out 
that  his  history  is  often  inaccurate,  and  that  his  law  is  not  the 
true  mediaeval  law  that  he  represented  it  to  be ;  and  it  must  be 


304  W.  S.  Holdsworth  [xv 

admitted  that  there  is  a  large  amount  of  substantial  truth  in  their 
criticisms.  Coke  was  always  the  lawyer,  always  the  advocate,  and, 
in  the  latter  part  of  his  life,  a  keen  politician.  The  lawyer,  the 
advocate,  and  the  politician  must  needs  make  excursions  into  the 
domain  of  the  historian  for  their  own  special  purposes.  But 
history  so  produced  will  generally  be,  as  history,  worthless.  If  we 
remember  that  Coke's  excursions  into  the  domain  of  history  are  all 
made  with  a  purpose,  and  that  in  addition  he  had  no  conception  of 
history  for  its  own  sake,  and  no  power  of  criticizing  the  historical 
sources  which  he  used,  we  shall  not  be  surprised  that,  as  compared 
with  the  work  of  true  historians  like  Selden  or  Bacon,  his  historical 
work  is  almost  contemptible.  If  we  glance  at  the  various  purposes 
for  which  Coke  was  obliged  to  trespass  upon  the  domain  of  the 
historian,  we  shall  be  the  better  able  to  understand  why,  in  this 
historical  age,  Coke's  reputation  has  fallen  to  perhaps  an  unduly 
low  ebb. 

As  a  lawyer  Coke  was  obliged  to  make  a  large  use  of  history  in 
order  to  explain  his  law.  The  continuity  of  the  common  law  must 
make  every  sound  common  lawyer  something  of  a  historian.  At 
the  same  time  the  peculiarities  of  our  system  of  case  law  cause 
lawyers  to  exaggerate  the  amount  of  continuity  which  there  is  in 
the  law.  They  talk  as  if  the  new  decisions  were  merely  develop- 
ments of  the  old  law ;  and  this  method  of  reasoning  may  easily 
deceive  historians  who  are  not  lawyers.  Moreover  the  present 
state  of  our  knowledge  of  English  legal  history  has  led  historians 
who  are  lawyers  to  join  in  condemning  Coke.  We  know  more 
about  the  legal  doctrines  of  the  twelfth  and  thirteenth  centuries 
than  about  the  legal  doctrines  of  the  fifteenth  and  sixteenth 
centuries.  We  see  a  doctrine  in  Bracton  or  the  earlier  Year  Books. 
We  see  it  in  a  somewhat  different  form  in  Coke,  and  we  are  apt 
to  conclude  that  Coke  has  been  perverting  his  sources.  To  take 
an  illustration.  Mr.  Pike  x  has  pointed  out  that  when  Coke,  com- 
menting on  Littleton,  states  that  an  advowson  lies  in  grant  but  not 
in  livery ',  he  is  introducing  a  negative  statement  for  which  there 
is  no  warrant  in  Littleton.  But  Coke  had  authority.  In  1490 2 
Brian  and  Vavisor  agreed  that,  because  an  advowson  passed  by 
grant,  it  could  not  pass  by  livery.  Coke  was  not  writing  legal 
history.  He  was  only  using  legal  history  to  explain  the  law  of 

1  L.Q.R.  v.  36.  2   Y.B.  6  Hy.  VII,  Pasch.  pi.  5,  p.  3. 


xv]  Coke  305 

his  own  day.  Possibly  many  of  his  statements  which  seem  at 
variance  with  the  older  authorities  are  based  upon  more  recent 
authorities  which  he  was  bound  to  follow.  A  judge  who  at  the 
present  day  followed  seventeenth-century  in  preference  to  nineteenth- 
century  decisions  would  find  that  his  judgments  were  frequently 
reversed.  I  cannot,  of  course,  say  how  many  of  Coke's  departures 
from  thirteenth-century  law  can  be  justified  in  this  way — that  would 
involve  a  knowledge  to  which  I  cannot  pretend.  But  probably  a 
good  many  can  be  so  justified ;  and  clearly  for  errors  of  this  kind 
he  cannot  be  censured.  But  this  plea  cannot  be  urged  in  defence 
of  the  errors  into  which  he  was  led  either  from  his  habits  of 
indiscreet  advocacy  or  from  his  political  bias. 

A  very  cursory  acquaintance  with  Coke's  writings  will  show 
that  he  approached  both  law  and  history  with  the  mind  of  a 
strenuous  advocate.  All  through  his  life  he  never  ceased  to  be 
an  advocate  of  legal  doctrines  or  political  causes.  Whether  he  is 
reporting  a  case,  or  arguing  for  the  supremacy  of  the  common  law 
in  the  State,  or  upholding  the  rights  and  privileges  of  Parliament, 
he  does  it  with  all  his  strength  ;  and  the  result  is  that  he  writes  or 
talks  himself  into  a  decided  view  on  the  subject.  I  very  much 
doubt  whether  in  all  Coke's  writings  a  passage  could  be  found  in 
which  he  admits  that  he  has  left  the  law  uncertain.  On  the  other 
hand  there  are  many  passages  in  which  he  states  that  he  has 
solved  all  doubts  and  reconciled  all  conflicting  cases.  No  doubt 
he  honestly  thought  he  had  done  so.  Now  this  defect  in  Coke's 
mind  has  led  to  two  very  grave  shortcomings  in  his  writings, 
(i)  The  various  causes  which  he  advocated  during  his  long  life  were 
not  always  quite  consistent.  Thus  the  dicta  in  Bonham's  case 1  as 
to  the  power  of  the  common  law  to  overrule  Acts  of  Parliament 
are  not  quite  consistent  with  the  views  which  he  elsewhere  expresses 
as  to  the  supremacy  of  Parliament.  Some  of  the  dicta  in  the  case 
of  Non  Obstante 2  as  to  inseparable  prerogatives  of  the  Crown  which 
no  Act  of  Parliament  can  take  away,  are  not  quite  consistent  with 
his  more  considered  statements  that  the  prerogative  is  subject  to 
the  law.  (2)  This  defect  made  him  very  uncritical  in  the  use  of 
his  sources.  He  swallowed  all  the  statements  in  the  Mirror  of 
Justices  because  they  fitted  in  with  his  preconceived  ideas  as  to  the 
immemorial  antiquity  of  the  common  law.  Moreover,  it  led  him  to 
1  8  Co.  Rep  107.  2  12  Co.  Rep.  18. 

X 


306  IV.  S.  Holdsworth  [xv 

read  into  his  authorities  meanings  which  they  never  possessed.  I 
have  elsewhere  shown  that  he  twice  repeats  a  statement  that  one 
of  the  counts  in  an  indictment  of  Wolsey  contained  an  accusation 
that  Wolsey  had  attempted  to  subvert  the  common  law, — the  facts 
being  that  the  indictment  cited  is  not  of  Wolsey  at  all,  and  that 
the  passage  as  to  subverting  the  common  law  was  the  common 
form  of  an  indictment  under  the  statute  of  Praemunire.1  The 
similar  errors  into  which  he  fell  in  connexion  with  his  account  of 
the  Admiralty  jurisdiction  have  been  exposed  by  Prynne  in  the 
seventeenth  century,  and  by  Mr.  Marsden  in  our  own  times.  But 
this  last  illustration  of  Coke's  use  of  his  history  to  advocate  his 
views  is  closely  connected  with  the  political  uses  to  which  he 
turned  it. 

We  have  seen  that  Coke  in  his  later  years  had  become  a  leader 
of  the  Parliamentary  opposition.  This  naturally  involved  a 
reconsideration  of  some  of  his  earlier  opinions  on  such  matters  of 
public  law  as  the  right  of  the  Crown  to  legislate  by  proclamation,2 
to  levy  impositions  and  exact  loans,3  to  commit  to  prison  without 
cause  shown,4  to  get  extra-judicial  opinions  from  the  judges.5  In 
earlier  days  these  recantations  tended  to  make  men  believe  in  the 
infallibility  of  Coke.  When  men  thought  that  the  constitutional 
principles  established  in  the  seventeenth  century  were  not  merely 
beneficial  to  the  State,  but  also  incontestably  sound  law,  the  views 
of  Coke  on  these  matters  in  his  published  writings  were  taken  to 
prove  his  legal  infallibility  on  all  matters.  But  in  our  own  days 
they  have  had  the  opposite  effect.  We  see  now  that  the  public 
law  of  the  seventeenth  century  was  very  obscure  ;  and  that  though 
the  victory  of  constitutional  principles  was  undoubtedly  beneficial 
to  the  State,  the  legal  principles  upon  which  the  leaders  of  the 
constitutional  opposition  relied  were  often  very  dubious.  Hence 
we  see  in  these  recantations  of  Coke  mere  evidences  of  his  political 

1  L.Q.R.  xxviii.  135-6. 

2  Cp.    Notes   on   the  Prerogative  in   State  Papers,  Dom.   (1598-1601), 
cclxxvi.  8 1,  and  the  opinion  given  while  Attorney-General,  with  the  case  of 
Proclamations  (1611),  12  Co.  Rep.  74. 

8  Spedding,  Life  and  Letters  of  Bacon,  v.  146  ;  12  Co.  Rep.  119  ;  Rush- 
worth,  Pt.  i.  497  ;  State  Papers,  Dom.  (1634),  cclxxviii.  35  ;  ibid.  (1603-1610), 
Iv.  52. 

4  See  his  speech  in  the  House  of  Commons,  cited  Foster,  Elliot,  ii.  26-28; 
and  cp.  his  views  in  1620—21,  Proceedings  and  Debates,  ii.  25,  109. 

5  Spedding,  Life  and  Letters  of  Bacon,  v.  114-18. 


xv]  Coke  307 

bias,  and  are  apt  to  doubt  whether  in  other  branches  of  the  law  he 
is  as  infallible  as  our  forefathers  thought  him.  I  do  not  think  that 
either  line  of  argument  is  quite  legitimate.  We  must  clearly 
separate  Coke's  views  on  matters  which  related  to  the  political 
controversies  of  the  day  from  matters  which  did  not ;  and  I  think 
that  on  matters  of  law  unconnected  with  these  controversies  a 
general  charge  of  inaccuracy  is  not  proved.  No  doubt  dicta  can 
be  found  which  disparage  his  accuracy.  But  of  some  of  these 
Mr.  Wallace  in  his  book  on  the  Reporters  has  successfully  disposed. 
No  doubt  later  cases  show  that  he  was  sometimes  wrong.  But 
they  are  small  in  number  compared  with  the  cases  in  which  his 
ruling  has  been  accepted.  Neither  Bacon  nor  Ellesmere  found 
any  serious  faults  with  his  Reports,  except  in  cases  of  a  political  or 
semi-political  character ;  and  Bacon  admitted  that  the  Reports, 
'  though  they  may  have  errors,  and  some  peremptory  and  extra- 
judicial  resolutions  more  than  are  warranted,  yet  contain  infinite 
good  decisions  and  rulings  over  of  cases/  Bacon  and  the  lawyers 
who  were  the  contemporaries  or  the  immediate  successors  of  Coke 
knew  more  of  the  older  authorities  at  first  hand  than  we  do.  I 
should  therefore  contend  that  the  view  that  Coke  is  inaccurate  in 
his  statements  of  law  on  matters  unconnected  with  the  political 
controversies  of  the  day  is  not  proved. 

Let  us  now  turn  to  the  criticisms  made  by  the  writers  of  another 
school. 

(2)  THE  EXCEPTIONS  TAKEN  BY  THE  ANALYTICAL  JURISTS 

Though  Coke's  history  is  often  unhistorical  he  was  for  all  that 
a  lawyer  of  the  historical  school.  '  Out  of  the  old  fields  must  grow 
the  new  corn '  was  one  of  his  favourite  proverbs.  And  he  had  all  the 
defects  of  the  historical  school  in  an  exaggerated  form.  Thus  he  is 
ready  with  a  defence  for  all  the  anomalies  and  anachronisms  by 
which  English  law  was  disfigured.  He  could  explain  them ;  and 
between  explanation  and  justification  it  never  occurred  to  him  that 
there  could  be  any  distinction.  On  the  other  hand  he  had  the  virtues 
of  the  historical  school.  The  analytical  lawyer  usually  bases  his 
analysis  mainly  upon  the  ideas  current  in  his  own  day.  He  is 
therefore  inclined  to  reject  as  useless  all  that  is  not  in  accord  with 
these  current  ideas.  But  the  historical  lawyer  preserves  the  ideas 
of  a  past  age  ;  and  these  ideas  often  come  into  their  own  again  in 


308  W.  S.  Holdsworth  [xv 

a  future  age.  Coke's  writings  preserved  for  England  the  mediaeval 
idea  of  the  supremacy  of  the  law  at  a  time  when  political  specula- 
tion was  tending  in  the  direction  of  the  supremacy  of  a  sovereign 
body  or  person  who  was  above  the  law ;  and  the  obscurity  and 
indefinite  character  of  some  of  the  mediaeval  rules  of  law  which 
he  states  preserved  for  the  common  law  a  flexibility  which  is  a 
condition  precedent  of  natural  development  and  expansion. 

As  Coke's  writings  thus  possess  the  vices  and  the  virtues  of 
the  historical  school,  they  have  naturally  attracted  the  censure  of 
those  whose  minds  are  cast  in  an  analytical  mould.  Hobbes,  the 
forefather  of  the  school  of  analytical  jurists,  attacks  Coke  in  his 
Dialogue  of  the  Common  Law  with  all  the  accustomed  weapons  of 
that  school.  Law  should  be  defined  as  the  command  of  the 
sovereign.  Case  law  is  no  true  law.  Useless  distinctions  should 
be  got  rid  of.  Absurd  rules  should  be  altered.  Law  should  be 
stated  so  plainly  that  the  non- lawyer  should  be  able  to  give  a 
sound  opinion  upon  its  meaning.  Hobbes's  criticisms  are  approved 
by  Sir  James  Stephen.  But  we  should  do  well  to  remember  that, 
though  Stephen  is  the  historian  of  our  criminal  law,  he  had  the 
mind  of  an  analytical  jurist.  And  when  we  read  his  condemna- 
tion of  Coke's  disorderly  mind,  of  his  technical  and  pedantic 
divisions,  of  his  puerile  speculations,  we  might  also  recall  the  fact 
that,  in  Austin's  opinion,  Coke's  mastery  of  the  legal  system  as  a 
whole  was  equalled  only  by  that  of  the  great  Roman  jurists. 
Hobbes  and  Stephen  saw  part  of  the  truth,  but  not  all. 

That  at  the  end  of  the  sixteenth  century  a  restatement  of 
English  law  was  needed  was  obvious  to  the  leading  lawyers  and 
statesmen  of  the  day.  But  what  form  should  that  restatement 
take  ?  It  was  clear  to  Bacon  that  the  construction  of  a  logical  code 
was  impossible.  '  I  dare  not,'  he  wrote,  '  advise  to  cast  the  law 
into  a  new  mould.'  Instead,  he  had  visions  of  doing  for  English  law 
something  of  the  same  nature  that  Justinian  had  done  for  Roman 
law.  There  was  to  be  a  revision  of  the  statute  book,  a  revision 
of  the  reports,  a  book  of  institutes,  and  a  book  of  legal  history. 
But  political  causes  rendered  Bacon's  scheme  impossible  of  realiza- 
tion at  the  time  when  it  was  propounded  ;  and  the  merits  of  Coke's 
writings  rendered  such  a  restatement  at  a  later  period  less  pressing. 

His  writings  had,  it  seems  to  me,  five  very  considerable  merits. 


xv]  Coke  309 

(1)  They  cover  the  whole  field  of  English  law,  and  restate  it 
from  the  point  of  view  of  the  sixteenth  century.     In  any  age  in 
which  large  political,  social,  and  intellectual  changes  have  taken 
place  the  law  will  need  to  be  reconsidered  and  restated.     And  it 
is  not  one  of  the  least  of  the  advantages  of  our  system  of  case  law 
that   it   can   thus  be  adapted  to  a  new  environment.      What  a 
succession  of  eminent  lawyers  have  done  for  the  common  law  in 
the  nineteenth  century,  Coke  did  for  the  common  law  of  his  own 
day.     Professor- Maitland  once  said  in  a  letter  to  me,  '  Coke's  books 
are  the  great  dividing  line,  and  we  are  hardly  out  of  the  Middle 
Ages  till  he  has  dogmatized  its  results.' 

(2)  He  deduces  from  the  scattered  and  inconsistent  dicta  in  the 
Year  Books  positive  rules  of  law.     All  through  his  writings  Coke 
is  reconciling  Year  Books.     We  could  with  considerable  justice 
apply  to  his  work  the  title  applied  to  Gratian's  work — Concordia 
discordantium  canonum. 

(3)  His  writings  not  only  brought  the  Year  Books  into  line 
with  the  modern  reports,  they  brought  the  mediaeval  literature  of 
the  common  law  into  line  with  the  modern  literature.     The  great 
mediaeval  books — Glanvil,  Bracton,  Britton,  and  Fleta — were  made 
to   explain   and   illustrate   the   law  expounded  by  Perkins,  Fitz- 
herbert,  Staundford,  and  Lambard. 

(4)  By  the  information  which  they  gave  as  to  the  doings  of 
other  courts — notably  the  Star  Chamber,  the  Chancery,  and  the 
Admiralty — they  tended  to  familiarize  the  common  lawyers  with 
the  new  ideas  which,  in  those  courts,  were  giving  rise  to  new  legal 
developments.     This  made  it  easier  for  the  common  law  to  fill  the 
great  position  which  it  acquired  as  a  result  of  the  constitutional 
conflicts  of  the  seventeenth  century. 

(5)  As  a  result,  his  writings  ensured   the   continuity   of  the 
development  of  the  common  law  amidst  all  the  vast  changes  of 
this  century  of  Renaissance,  Reformation,  and  Reception.     This 
signal  merit  of  Coke's  writings  was  fully  recognized  in  his  own 
day.     'Had  it  not  been  for  Sir  Edward  Coke's  Reports ,'  wrote 
Bacon,  '  the  law  of  this  time  had  almost  been  like  a  ship  without 
ballast ;   for  that  the  cases  of  modern  experience  are  fled  from 
those  that  are  adjudged  and  ruled  in  former  times.' 

Coke  had  thus  adapted  a  thoroughly  mediaeval  body  of  law  to 
the  needs  of  the  modern  State,  without  any  appreciable  sacrifice  of 


310  IV.  S.  Holdsworth  [xv 

the  mediaeval  ideas  contained  in  it.  He  had  maintained  that  this 
body  of  law  ought  to  be  the  supreme  law  in  the  State ;  and  the 
results  of  the  Great  Rebellion  had  caused  his  views  to  prevail. 
Naturally  the  effect  of  his  writings  on  the  future  development  of 
English  law  has  been  enormous  both  for  evil  and  for  good. 

It  can  hardly  be  denied  that  the  victory  of  Coke's  views  has 
had  unfortunate  effects  upon  the  form  and  the  substance  of  English 
law.  Rules  and  doctrines  were  retained  which  were  already  half 
obsolete  in  his  day ;  and,  as  a  result,  it  is  hard  to  draw  the  line 
between  obsolete  and  living  law.  Then,  too,  the  appropriation  by 
the  common  law  of  commercial  causes  made  the  growth  of  a 
reasonable  system  of  commercial  law  very  slow.  Till  the  codifying 
statutes  of  the  nineteenth  century,  English  law  could  show  no 
measures  dealing  with  this  topic  comparable  with  the  French 
ordonnances  of  two  centuries  earlier.  And  till  the  reforms  of  the 
same  century  our  law  of  bankruptcy  was  a  disgrace  to  a  civilized 
community. 

On  the  other  hand  we  cannot  doubt  that  the  result  of  Coke's 
writings  has  been  to  make  English  law  a  very  much  more  uniform 
system  of  law  than  it  would  otherwise  have  been.  The  result  of 
the  success  of  the  Court  of  Chancery  in  its  quarrel  with  the 
common  law  was  to  split  our  English  law  into  two  halves.  If  all 
the  other  rival  courts  had  been  equally  successful,  English  law 
would  have  been  split  into  many  fragments.  Coke's  writings 
helped  to  save  English  law  from  this  fate  because  they  successfully 
asserted  the  supremacy  of  the  common  law. 

And  more  was  involved  in  the  maintenance  of  the  supremacy 
of  the  common  law  than  the  settlement  of  a  mere  legal  quarrel 
about  jurisdiction.  If  the  common  law  had  lost  its  supremacy, 
would  Parliament,  we  may  fairly  ask,  have  gained  the  victory? 
And  if  it  had  gained  the  victory  without  the  help  of  a  common 
law  which  claimed  to  be  the  supreme  law  in  the  State,  would  our 
constitutional  law  be  what  it  is  to-day  ?  This  we  may  well  doubt. 
In  the  past  the  common  lawyers  had  helped  to  make  the  English 
Parliament  an  efficient  representative  assembly.  In  the  seventeenth 
century  the  Parliament  handsomely  repaid  the  debt  by  helping 
Coke  and  his  fellows  to  maintain  the  mediaeval  conception  of  the 
rule  of  law,  and  to  apply  it  to  the  government  of  a  modern  State. 
It  was  in  Coke's  writings  that  this,  together  with  other  mediaeval 


xv]  Coke.  311 

conceptions,  were  given  their  modern  form ;  and  therefore  it  is 
largely  owing  to  the  influence  of  his  writings  that  these  mediaeval 
conceptions  have  become  part  of  our  modern  law.  If  their  influence 
upon  some  parts  of  our  modern  law  has  not  been  wholly  satis- 
factory, let  us  remember  that  they  have  preserved  for  England  and 
the  world  the  constitutional  doctrine  of  the  rule  of  law. 

The  effects  of  this  doctrine  were  destined  in  the  succeeding 
ages  to  be  felt  beyond  the  bounds  of  England,  beyond  the  bounds 
even  of  English-speaking  peoples — in  all  places  and  at  all  times 
wherever  and  whenever  men  have  had  the  will  and  the  power  to 
establish  constitutional  government.  We  may  surely  claim  that 
these  large  results  of  this  part  of  Coke's  work  upon  the  civilized 
world  of  to-day  entitle  the  most  English  of  our  English  common 
lawyers  to  a  place  among  the  great  jurists  of  the  world. 

W.  S.  HOLDSWORTH.    ; 


XVI 

UBER   DIE   GESCHICHTE    DES 
MAJORITATSPRINZIPS 

Zu  keiner  Zeit  vielleicht  hat  das  Majoritatsprinzip  eine  so 
gewaltige  Rolle  gespielt  wie  in  der  Gegenwart.  Bei  staatlichen 
und  kommunalen  Wahlen,  bei  den  Beschlussfassungen  von 
Parlamenten  und  Gemeindevertretungen,  in  administrativen  und 
richterlichen  Kollegien,  in  alien  offentlichen  und  privaten  Korper- 
schaften,  in  Vereinen  fur  wirtschaftliche  wie  fur  ideale  Zwecke 
entscheidet  Stimmenmehrheit.  Uberall  gilt,  was  die  Mehrheit 
will,  als  Ausdruck  des  Gemeinwillens.  Durch  ein  Rechenexempel 
wird  festgestellt,  was  alle  Beteiligten  als  fiir  sie  bindend  anerkennen 
miissen,  mag  es  sich  nun  um  16  Millionen  Stimmender,  wie  jiingst 
bei  der  amerikanischen  Prasidentenwahl,  oder  mag  es  sich  um 
die  Abstimmung  in  einem  Dreimannerkollegium  handeln.  Erst 
unterhalb  der  Dreizahl  versagt  dieses  Allheilmittel  fiir  Meinungs- 
verschiedenheiten.  In  der  Gemeinschaft  zu  Zweien  gibt  es  keine 
Majoritat.  Die  innigste  aller  menschlichen  Verbindungen,  die 
Ehe,  muss  sich  ohne  Abstimmungen  behelfen. 

Infolge  solcher  allgemeinen  Anerkennung  nehmen  wir  heute 
das  Majoritatsprinzip  <als  etwas  Selbstverstandliches  hin  und 
zerbrechen  uns  nicht  viel  den  Kopf  dariiber,  warum  denn  hier 
Uberall  der  Teil  so  viel  gilt  wie  das  Ganze.  Auch  in  juristischen, 
politischen  und  philosophischen  Schriften  begegnen  nur  selten 
eingehendere  Versuche  seiner  Rechtfertigung.1 

Dem  war  nicht  immer  so  !     Das  Majoritatsprinzip  hat  keines- 

1  Eindringlich  erortert  das  Problem  Simmel,  Soziologie,  1908,  S. 
186-97  (Exkurs  iiber  Uberstimmung).  Eine  Erklarung,  die  aber  in  den 
sinnlichen  Vorstellungen  primitiver  Zeitalter  stecken  bleibt,  versucht  auch 
Bolze,  Der  Begriff  der  juristischen  Person,  1879,  S.  109  ff. 

312 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  313 

wegs  von  jeher  in  Kraft  gestanden.  Es  hat  sich  erst  in  langem 
geschichtlichen  Ringen  durchgesetzt  und  dabei  sehr  verschiedene 
Entwicklungsstufen  durchlaufen.  Sein  Geltungsgrund  ist  in 
mannigfach  ungleicher  Weise  aufgefasst  und  formuliert  worden. 
Ein  Blick  auf  diesen  Werdeprozess  bietet  um  so  grosseres 
historisches  Interesse,  als  er  sich  in  engem  Zusammenhange  mit 
dem  Wandel  der  Grundanschauungen  liber  das  Wesen  der 
menschlichen  Verbande  abgespielt  hat.  Zugleich  aber  mag  er 
dazu  dienen,  ein  tieferes  Verstandnis  unseres  heutigen  Rechts- 
zustandes  zu  fordern. 

In  diesem  Sinne  mochte  ich  es  unternehmen,  Ihre  Auf- 
merksamkeit  auf  die  Geschichte  des  Majoritatsprinzips  zu 
lenken.  Dabei  beschranke  ich  mich  aber  auf  die  Darlegung  der 
auf  Grund  des  germanischen  Rechts  im  Mittelalter  und  in  der 
Neuzeit  vollzogenen  Entwicklung.  Insbesondere  gehe  ich  auf 
eine  Untersuchung  der  Geschichte  des  Majoritatsprinzips  in  der 
antiken  Kulturwelt  nicht  naher  ein.  Bei  Griechen  und  Romern 
erfreut  sich  in  den  reifen  Zeiten,  von  denen  wir  genauere  Kenntnis 
haben,  das  Majoritatsprinzip  bei  alien  Versammlungsbeschliissen 
unbestrittener  Herrschaft.  Uber  Vorstadien,  die  es  vermutlich 
gegeben  hat,  sind  wir  nicht  sicher  unterrichtet.  Jedenfalls  war 
man  sich  solcher  nicht  mehr  bewusst,  hegte  vielmehr  an  der 
Berechtigung  der  Entscheidung  durch  Stimmenzahlung  keinerlei 
Zweifel.  In  der  griechischen  Staatslehre  stossen  wir  iiber- 
haupt  nicht  auf  Reflexionen  Uber  den  Grund  der  Geltung  des 
Stimmenmehrs.  Erst  die  romischen  Juristen  suchen  nach  dem 
Geltungsgrunde.  Sie  begniigen  sich  aber  mit  einer  sehr  ausser- 
lichen  Rechtfertigung.  Refertur  ad  universes  quod  pub  lice  fit 
per  majorem  partem,  sagt  Ulpian  in  1.  160  §  I  D.  de  R.  J.  Ahn- 
lich  meint  Scaevola  in  1.  19  D.  ad  municipalem  (56,  i):  Quod 
major  pars  curiae  effecit  pro  eo  habetur,  ac  si  omnes  egerint. 
Diese  Aussprliche,  die  spater  eine  grosse  Rolle  gespielt  haben, 
laufen  auf  eine  juristische  Fiktion  hinaus,  kraft  deren  die  Mehrheit 
gelten  soil,  als  seien  es  Alle.  Wie  sich  zu  dieser  Fiktion  der 
bekannte  positive  Rechtssatz  verhalt,  der  zur  Gultigkeit  eines 
Majoritatsbeschlusses  der  stadtischen  Kurie  die  Anwesenheit  von 
zwei  Dritteln  fordert,  lassen  die  romischen  Juristen,  die  eine 
allgemeine  Theorie  der  Korporationsbeschlusse  uberhaupt  nicht 
ausgebildet  haben,  unerortert. 


314  O.  V.  Gierke  [xvi 

Dem  germanischen  Recht  war  auf  der  ungleich  primitiveren 
Stufe,  auf  der  es  bei  seinem  Eintritt  in  das  Licht  der  Geschichte 
stand,  das  Majoritatsprinzip  fremd.  Ihm  deckte  sich  der  Gesamt- 
wille  mit  dem  Versammlungswillen  und  der  Versammlungswille 
mit;  dem  Willen  aller  Versammelten.  Fur  das  durchaus  sinn- 
liche  und  konkrete  Denken  der  alten  Zeit  waren  Trager  alles  Ver- 
bandsrechtes  sichtbare  Versammlungen  und  sichtbare  Herrscher. 
So  wenig  man  bei  dem  Herrscher  die  Individualpersonlichkeit 
und  die  Stellung  als  Verbandshaupt  unterschied,  ebenso  wenig 
unterschied  man  bei  der  Versammlung  die  Gesamteinheit  von 
der  Gesamtvielheit.  Alles  Gemeinschaftsrecht  hatte  daher  die 
Versammlung  der  vollberechtigten  Genossen  in  ihrer  zugleich 
einheitlichen  und  vielkopfigen  Erscheinung  auszuiiben.  In  dem 
kollektiven  Wollen  und  Handeln  Aller  offenbarte  sich  das 
lebendige  Ganze. 

Grundsatzlich  bedurfte  es  also  zu  jedem  Volks-  oder  Ge- 
meindebeschluss  eines  einhelligen  Gesamtaktes.  Im  Falle 
der  Meinungsverschiedenheit  zu  einem  solchen  zu  gelangen,  war  das 
Ziel  der  Beratung.  Wenn  aber  die  Uberzeugungskraft  der  Griinde 
oder  das  Ansehen  und  die  Beredsamkeit  der  fiihrenden  Manner 
nicht  zur  Ubereinstimmung  fiihrten,  so  setzte  sich  freilich  in 
der  Regel  die  Meinung  der  uberwiegenden  Mehrheit  durch.  Allein 
dies  geschah  urspriinglich  keineswegs  im  Wege  einer  die  Minder- 
heit  von  Rechtswegen  bindenden  Abstimmung.  Von  Stimmabgabe 
und  Stimmzahlung  war  nicht  die  Rede.  Vielmehr  gab  die  ver- 
sammelte  Menge  mit  gesamter  Hand  und  mit  gemeinem  Munde 
ihre  Willensmeinung  kund.  Zusammenschlagen  der  Waffen  mit 
Beifallsruf  oder  sonstige  Billigung  mit  Hand  und  Mund  gait  als 
Annahme,  lautes  Murren  oder  missbilligender  Zuruf  als  Verwer- 
fung  eines  Vorschlags.  So  schildert  uns  Tacitus  die  Beschluss- 
fassung  in  der  altgermanischen  Volksversammlung,  und  jiingere 
Quellen  bestatigen  es  als  gemeingermanische  Ubung.1  Verhielten 

1  Germ,  c.  1 1  :  sin  placuit,  frameas  concutiunt;  honoratissimum  assensus 
genus  est  armis  laudare.  Vgl.  Hist.  v.  1 7.  Die  Waffenriihrung  begegnet  auch 
spater  bei  den  Franken  als  besonders  feierliche  Form  des  Volksbeschlusses  : 
Zusammenschlagen  der  Schilde  und  Beifallsruf  bei  der  Wahl  Chlodwigs 
durch  die  ripuarischen  Franken  nach  Gregor  =  Gregor  Tur.  ii.  40  ;  votibusque 
simul  et  armorum  plausu  sententiam  ducis  firmaveruntr^^  Annales  Mettenses 
z.  J.  690,  MG.  S.S.  i.  318.  Bei  den  nordischen  Volkern  als  vdpnatak  bei 
GesetzgebungsaktenundKonigsannahme.  —  Doch  war,  wie  sichschonausG^r;;/. 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  315 

sich  Dissentierende  schweigend,  so  hatte  schliesslich  doch  die 
Versammlung  mit  gesamter  Hand  und  gemeinem  Munde  ihren 
Willen  erklart.  Und  auch  der  Widerspruch  des  einen  oder 
andern  mochte,  wenn  er  iiberhort  oder  ubertont  wurde,  die  Ver- 
kiindigung  des  Ergebnisses  als  eines  einstimmigen  Versammlungs- 
beschlusses  nicht  hindern. 

Eine  rechtliche  Verpflichtung  aber,  sich  dem  Mehrheits- 
beschlusse  zu  fiigen,  und  ihn  so  zugleich  als  eigenen  Beschluss 
anzuerkennen,  gab  es  nicht.  Wer  seinen  Widerspruch  trotzig  auf- 
recht  hielt,  war  durch  den  Beschluss  der  andern  Genossen,  die 
nicht  mehr  Alle  waren,  nicht  gebunden.  Allein  er  loste  sich  damit 
von  der  in  sich  einigen  Gesamtheit  der  Anderen,  er  trat  ihr  als 
Feind  gegeniiber  und  setzte  sich  ihrem  gewaltsamen  Zwange  aus. 
War  der  Widerstand  gegen  solche  Uberwaltigung  wegen  der 
Starke  der  Mehrheit  aussichtslos,  so  musste  regelmassig  schon  die 
Erwagung  der  Folgen  die  Minderheit  bewegen,  den  Widerspruch 
fallen  zu  lassen.  Allein  den  Halsstarrigen  konnte  nur  die  tatsach- 
liche  Macht  iiberwinden.  Und  wenn  auch  die  Minderheit  stark  war 
und  sich  den  Sieg  zutraute,  so  trat  an  Stelle  des  einheitlichen  Ver- 
sammlungsbeschlusses  die  Spaltung  in  Teilgesamtheiten,  zwischen 
denen  dann  aussersten  Falles  die  Waffen  entschieden. 

Ein  deutliches  Bild  der  Fortdauer  dieser  urspriinglichen  An- 
schauungen  bieten  bis  tief  in  das  Mittelalter  hinein  die  deutschen 
Konigswahlen.  Sie  forderten  Einstimmigkeit,  anfangs  Ein- 
stimmigkeit  der  versammelten  Stammeshaupter  und  der  zu- 
stimmenden  Volksmenge,  sodann  Einstimmigkeit  der  Fiirsten l  und 
dann  noch,  seitdem  die  Kurfiirsten  aus  Vorwahlern  zu  alleinigen 
Wahlern  geworden  waren,  Einstimmigkeit  der  Kurfiirsten.  Erst 
die  goldene  Bulle  fiihrte  das  Majoritatsprinzip  als  Grundsatz 
des  Reichsrechtes  ein.2  Bis  dahin  musste  eine  Minderheit,  die 

c.  1 1  ergibt,  der  Waffenschlag  nicht  die  einzige  Form  der  Zustimmung.  Es 
geniigte  die  acclamatio.  Bei  den  deutschen  Konigswahlen  wird  Emporheben 
der  Hande  neben  dem  Beifallsruf  erwahnt ;  Widukind,  Res  gest.  Sax.  i.  26, 
ii.  i.  Also,  wie  dies  dem  alten  Rechtsformalismus  entspricht,  Billigtmg  mit 
Hand  und  Mund. 

1  Noch  der  Sachsensp.,  iii.   57  §  2,  fordert  Einigung  aller  Fiirsten  iiber 
die  Wahl  als  Grundlage  des  formellen  Kurspruchs  :  „  sven  die  vorsten  alle  to 
koninge  erwelt,  den  solen  sie  (die  Kurfiirsten)  aller  erst  bi  namen  kiesen." 

2  Fur  die  kurfiirstliche  Genehmigung  koniglicher  Verausserungen  hatte 
schon   ein  Reichsweistum  von   1281    (MG.   Const,   iii.   290)  das  Mehrheits- 


316  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

sich  nicht  freiwillig  ftigte,  durch  Waffengewalt  zur  Anerkennung 
des  gewahlten  Konigs  gezwungen  werden.  Die  zahlreichen  Waffen- 
gange  zwischen  Konigen  und  Gegenkonigen  bei  zwiespaltigen 
Wahlen  sind  aus  der  Geschichte  bekannt. 

Auch  sonst  erhielten  sich  vielfach  mit  Zahigkeit  die  alten 
Anschauungen.  Im  deutschen  wie  im  frankischen  Reichstage 
war  zunachst  zur  Beschlussfassung  Einigung  erforderlich  und  die 
Unterwerfung  derer,  die  sich  ausschlossen,  vom  Zwange  der  Uber- 
macht  abhangig.  Friihestens  seit  dem  Ende  des  dreizehnten 
Jahrhunderts  wurden  Mehrheitsbeschliisse  als  bindend  anerkannt, 
sehr  viel  spater  erst  Stimmzahlungen  unter  Fixierung  des  Stim- 
mengewichts  eingefiihrt,  bis  zuletzt  in  den  drei  Kollegien,  in  die 
er  zerfiel,  das  Majoritatsprinzip  durchdrang  und  nur  Einstimmig- 
keit  der  Kollegien  oder  im  Falle  der  itio  in  paries  der  beiden 
Religionskorper  notwendig  blieb.  Langsam  und  anfanglich  nur 
in  beschranktem  Umfange  wurde  in  den  landstandischen  Ver- 
sammlungen  und  auch  hier  immer  nur  innerhalb  der  einzelnen 
standischen  Korper  der  Grundsatz  der  Einstimmigkeit  durch  die 
Mehrheitsentscheidung  liberwunden,  langsamer  noch  in  den  foe- 
derativen  Verbanden,  wie  in  der  deutschen  Hanse  und  der 
schweizerischen  Eidgenossenschaft.  Ebenso  musste  uberall  in 
Europa  das  Majoritatsprinzip  in  den  politischen  Versammlungen 
die  formale  Geltung,  die  es  endlich  errang,  sich  erst  miihsam 
erkampfen.  In  manchen  Landern  wurde  sogar  ihm  gegeniiber  das 
Einstimmigkeitsprinzip  zu  formaler  Geltung  erhoben,1  dem  jedoch 
der  endgiiltige  Sieg  nur  im  polnischen  Reichstage  mit  dem 
beriichtigten  liberum  veto  beschieden  war. 

Langer  noch,  als  auf  den  Hohen  des  offentlichen  Lebens, 
behauptete  sich  in  dessen  Niederungen  das  alte  Recht.  Insbeson- 
dere  wurden  auf  dem  Lande  in  Markgenossenschaften  und 
Bauerschaften  die  Beschliisse  stets  von  der  versammelten 
Menge  der  Vollgenossen  einmiitig  gefasst  und  einmiindig 
erklart.  Dass  Beschlusse,  die  das  Sonderrecht  des  einzelnen 
Genossen  kranken,  dessen  Zustimmung  forderten,  ist  begreif  lich ; 

prinzip  anerkannt.     Bei   der    Konigswahl    wurde  zuerst  in  der  Const.  Lud. 
Licet  juris   v.   6.    Aug.    1338    die    Beschlussfahigkeit    einer    Mehrheit   von 
vier  Kurfursten  festgesetzt,  mit  dem  Erforderniss  der  Einhelligkeit  der  Ver- 
sammelten aber  noch  nicht  gebrochen. 
1  So  bis  1292  in  Arragonien. 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  3 1 7 

zu  diesen  aber  rechnete  man  unter  dem  Gesichtspunkte  des  alten 
Gesamteigentums  an  der  Mark  vielfach  auch  die  Aufnahme  neuer 
anteilsberechtigter  Genossen  und  jede  Verfiigung  liber  die  All-, 
mende  oder  deren  Ertrage  zu  Gunsten  von  Ungenossen,raumte  daher 
in  solchen  Fallen  jedem  Genossen  ein  formales  Widerspruchsrecht 
ein,  das  erst  durch  Verschweigung  in  Jahr  und  Tag  erlosch.1 
Allein  auch  wo  es  sich  lediglich  um  die  Ausiibung  des  Gesamtrechtes 
oder  um  das  gemeine  Beste  handelte,  wo  Recht  gewiesen  oder 
Recht  gesetzt,  wo  ein  Vorsteher  oder  ein  Beamter  gewahlt  wurde, 
bedurfte  es  eines  ungezweiten  Versammlungsaktes.  Hierbei 
machte  sich  nun  freilich  stets  das  Ubergewicht  der  Mehrheit 
geltend.  Und  seit  dem  dreizehnten  Jahrhundert  wurde  mehr  und 
mehr  auch  in  den  Landgemeinden  der  Stimmenmehrheit  ein 
rechtlicher  Vorzug  zugestanden.2  Allein  damit  wurde,  wie  wir 
sehen  werden,  zunachst  das  Erfordernis  der  schliesslichen  Uber- 
einstimmung  Aller  keineswegs  aufgegeben,  sodass  ausweislich 
unzahliger  Weistiimer  und  Urkunden  fort  und  fort  die  Gemeinde- 
beschlusse  als  einstimmige  Versammlungserklarungen  verkiindigt 
wurden.3 

Nicht  minder  lebendig  blieb  die  ererbte  Denkweise  bei  dem 
Urteilsspruch  in  alien  Gerichtsversammlungen.  Das 
gefundene  Urteil  erlangte  Rechtskraft  nur  durch  die  vulbort,  die 
allgemeine  Zustimmung  der  vollberechtigten  Dingleute.  Wo 
Schoffen  oder  andere  Urtelsfinder  ohne  Umstand  zu  entscheiden 

1  Fur   die   Aufnahme    neuer   Genossen    vgl.    mein    Genossenschaftsr.    ii. 
232,  Anm.    156,    Maurer,  Einl.    141    ff.,   Markenv.   112   ff.,    und  dazu   tiber 
das    urspriingliche   Recht,   wie  es   der  richtig  verstandene    Tit.  leg.    Sal.  de 
migrantibus    bekundet,    mein   Genossenschaftsr.   i.    76   ff.      Fur  Verfiigungen 
iiber    die    Allmende    mein    Genossenschaftsr.    ii.     232,    Anm.    153,     158-60, 
Lamprecht,  Deutsches  Wirtschaftsleben  im  M.A.  i.  310,  Anm.  6  ;  insbesondere 
noch   die  Kundschaft  von    1487,   b.    Grimm,    W.  i.    400.       Fiir    Gestattung 
der  Rodung  nach   Zeugenaussage  v.   1560,   b.  Landau,   Territories  S.    117, 
Anm.  i. — Dazu  vgl.  man  Pollock  and  Maitland,  i.  684. 

2  Ausdriicklich    heisst    es    schon    im    Sachsensp.    ii.    55:    „  Svat   so   die 
burmester  schept  des  dorpes  vromen  mit  wilkore  der  merren  menie  der  bure, 
dat  ne  mach  die  minre  deil  nicht  wederreden."    Vgl.  Schwabensp.  (L.)  214 
(mit  dem    Zusatz :    „  dass    selbe    recht   sol   man    halden  in  den    stetten "). 
Rupr.    Freis.    i.     142.        Dazu    zahlreiche    Belege    aus    den    Weistiimern 
in    meinem     Genossenschaftsr.    iii.     220    ff.,     478     ff.      Vgl.    auch    Maurer, 
Markenv.   S.   359  ff.,  Dorfv.  i.  220,  ii.  86  ff.  ;    Thudichum,  Gau.  u.  Markv. 

8.315- 

3  Vgl.  mein  Genossenschaftsr.  iii.  483,  501  ff. 


318  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

hatten,  war  mindestens  ihre  einhellige  Billigung  unerlasslich. 
Und  dieser  Grundsatz  iiberdauerte  wieder  die  Einfiihrung  des 
Majoritatsprinzips.  Etwas  anders  verhielt  es  sich  bei  dem 
Wahrspruch  der  Geschworenen,  der  ja  von  Hause  aus  nicht 
Urteil  sondern  Zeugnis  war.1  Aber  auch  das  Gesamtzeugnis 
forderte  eine  einhellige  Gesamtaussage  und  scheiterte  am  Zwiespalt 
der  Meinungen.  Das  blosse  Nichtwissen  des  Einen  oder  Andern 
mochte  der  Kraft  des  gemeinen  Wahrspruches  nicht  schaden,  wie 
denn  im  normannischen  Recht  die  feste  Regel  ausgebildet  wurde, 
dass  der  einstimmige  Wahrspruch  von  elf  unter  den  zwolf  Ge- 
schworenen geniige.  Der  ausdriickliche  Widerspruch  aber  auch  nur 
eines  einzigen  Geschworenen  hinderte  das  Zustandekommen  eines 
giiltigen  Spruchs.2  Von  hier  aus  konnte  sich  das  starre  Erfordernis 
der  Einstimmigkeit  in  der  englischen  Jury  entwickeln.3  Es  konnte 
aber  auch  das  Majoritatsprinzip  durchdringen,  sei  es  nun,  dass  eine 
iiberwiegende  Mehrheit  erforderlich  blieb,  sei  es,  dass  mit  einfacher 
Mehrheit  entschieden  wurde,  wie  dies  im  normannischen  Recht  bei 
Besitzprozessen  der  Fall  war4  und  in  Deutschland  bei  der  hier 
allein  ubrig  gebliebenen  Bekundung  von  Besitzverhaltnissen  durch 
die  Umsassen  gait.5 

Die  allgemeine  Entwicklungstendenz  war,  wie  wir  gesehen 
haben,  auf  die  fortschreitende  Anerkennung  des  Majoritats- 
prinzips gerichtet,  das  in  der  zweiten  Halfte  des  Mittelalters 
auch  in  Deutschland  unbestritten  in  standischen  Versammlungen, 
Gerichten,  Landgemeinden,  Stadten,  Gilden  und  Ziinften  gait  und 
in  den  Rechtsbiichern,  den  Weistiimern  und  zahlreichen  anderen 
Rechtsquellen  als  generelle  Regel  ausgesprochen  wird.  Allein 
ich  habe  schon  darauf  hingewiesen,  dass  es  zunachst  keineswegs 
einen  Bruch  mit  den  alten  Anschauungen  bedeutete,  sondern  sich 
in  deren  Rahmen  als  ein  juristisches  Mittel  zur  Erzielung  eines 
einheitlichen  Versammlungsbeschlusses  einfugte.  Denn  es  empfangt 
die  Fassung:  „  Die  Minderheit  soil  der  Mehrheit  folgen," 

1  Eingehend   handelt    von   dem    Stimmenverhaltniss  beim    Wahrspruch 
Brunner,  Entstehung  der  Schwurgerichte,  S.  363-71. 

2  Brunner,  a.  a.  O.,  S.  365. 

3  Pollock  and  Maitland,  ii.  625  ff. 

4  Brunner,  a.  a.  O.,  S.  367  ff. 

6  Sachsensp.  iii.  2 1  §  i  a.l. :  „  Sve  de  merren  mennie  an'me  getiige  hevet, 
die  behalt  dat  gut." 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  3 1 9 

minor  pars  sequatur  majorem.1  Durch  diese  Wendung  aber  oder 
durch  ahnliche  gleichbedeutende  Wendungen  wird  ausgedruckt, 
dass  die  Minderheit  ihren  Widerspruch  aufgeben  und  der  Mehrheit 
zustimmen  soil,  damit  ein  einhelliger  Gemeinwille  zu  Stande 
komme :  eine  sententia  per  approbationem  et  collaudationem 
communem^  quae  volga  dicitur^  ab  omnibus  et  singulis  stability 
wie  ein  Weistum  von  1340  sagt.2 

Hierin  bekundet  sich  ein  ausserordentlicher  Fortschritt  der 
Rechtsauffassung.  Die  Uberwindung  des  Meinungszwiespaltes 
soil  nicht  mehr  von  tatsachlichem  tfbergewicht  und  gewaltsamem 
Zwange  abhangen,  sondern  durch  Erfiillung  einer  der  Minderheit 
auferlegten  Rechtspflicht  herbeigefiihrt  werden.  Aus  dem 
genossenschaftlichen  Verhaltnis  entspringt  fiir  den  Genossen  die 
Pflicht,  um  der  Einheit  des  Ganzen  willen  sich  dem  Ergebnis  der 
Abstimmung  zu  fiigen  und  durch  seinen  Beitritt  den  Mehrheitswillen 
zum  Gesamtwillen  zu  erheben.  Allein  immer  noch  ist  schliessliche 
Einstimmigkeit  erforderlich,  sodass  der  Beschluss  nur  Kraft  erlangt, 
wenn  wirklich  die  Minderheit  der  Mehrheit  folgt.  Verharrt  sie  bei 
ihrem  Widerspruch,  so  begeht  sie  vielleicht  ein  strafbares  Unrecht,3 
ein  rechtsgiiltiger  Gemeinbeschluss  aber  kommt  dann  nicht  zu 
Stande.  Ist  eine  Losung  des  Konfliktes  im  Wege  Rechtens  un- 
erlasslich,  so  kann  sie  nur  durch  hohere  Entscheidung  erfolgen.4 

In  besonders  klarer  Auspragung  treten  diese  Anschauungen 
im  gerichtlichen  Verfahren  zu  Tage.5  Ist  auf  die  richterliche 
Frage  ein  Urteil  gefunden,  so  kann  ihm  jeder  Schoffe  oder  Ding- 
mann  ein  ihm  besser  dunkendes  Urteil  entgegen  stellen.  Damit 
beredet  er  die  vulbort.  Dann  behalt  der,  dem  bei  der  Abstimmung 
die  meisten  folgen,  sein  Urteil.  Dieses  Urteil  erhalt  dann  dadurch, 
dass  sich  die  Minderheit  der  Mehrheit  anschliesst,  die  vulbort 
und  steht  nun  als  Rechtsspruch  der  Gesamtheit,  als  „  gemeines  ", 

1  Zusammenstellung  zahlreicher  Belegstellen  in  meinem  Genossenschaftsr. 
ii.  482-3. 

2  W.  v.  Treyse  b.  Grimm,  i.  810. 

3  Bisweilen    wird    die    Erfiillung   der   Folgepflicht   im    Voraus   formlich 
versprochen,  ein  solches  Versprechen  auch  in  den  Schoffeneid  aufgenommen  ; 
mein  Genossenschaftsr.  ii.  484,  Anm.  25-26. 

4  Vgl.  mein  Genossenschaftsr.  ii.  483,  Anm.  23. 

5  Vor  allem  im  Sachsensp.  ii.  a.  12,  mit  dem  aber  die  anderen  sachsischen 
und  im  Kern  auch  die  siiddeutschen  Quellen  iibereinstimmen.     Vgl.  iiber  die 
hier    in    Betracht    kommenden    Gesichtspunkte    mein    Genossenschaftsr.    ii. 
483  ff. 


320  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

„  gesamtes  ",  „  einstimmiges  ",  „  ungezweites  "  Urteil  unanfechtbar 
da.     Allein  der  dissentierende  SchofTe  oder  Dingmann  kann,  so 
lange  die  vulbort  nicht  erteilt  ist,  auch  anders  verfahren.     Er  kann 
das   Urteil    „  schelten "  oder  „  verwerfen."     Damit  wirft   er   dem 
Urteilsvorschlage   Rechtswidrigkeit    vor   und   erklart   auf  eigene 
Gefahr  bin,  dass  er  demselben  niemals  und  auch  nicht,  wenn  ihm 
die  Mehrheit  folgt,  zustimmen  werde.      In  diesem  Falle  kommt 
ein  gemeines  Urteil  nicht  zu  Stande,  es  wird  um  vulbort  uberhaupt 
nicht  gefragt  und  jede  Moglichkeit  rechtskraftiger  Entscheidung 
durch  das  verhandelnde  Gericht  ist  zerstort.     Die  Streiterledigung 
erfolgt  durch  Zug  an  ein  anderes  und  womoglich  hoheres  Gericht, 
vor  dem  in  einem  neuen   Prozess  liber   Gerechtigkeit   oder   Un- 
gerechtigkeit    des    mit    der    Urteilsschelte    erhobenen    Vorwurfs 
entschieden  wird.     Wer  unterliegt,  verliert  nicht  nur  sein  Urteil, 
sondern  wird  auch  bussfallig.     Der  Sachsenspiegel  aber  betont  es  als 
ein  besonderes  Vorrecht  des  Sachsen,  dass  er  auch  einen  anderen 
Weg   wahlen   kann,    indem    er    das    gescholtene    Urteil    an    die 
rechte  Hand  zieht.      Dann  entscheidet  gerichtlicher  Zweikampf. 
Selbsiebent  seiner  Genossen  muss  er  wider  andere  sieben  fechten  ; 
auf  welcher   Seite    die    Mehrheit   siegt,    die    behalt   das    Urteil.1 
Hier   ist   also    in   eigenartiger    Weise   das    Majoritatsprinzip    in 
die    altertiimliche  Waffenentscheidung,    die   in    den    Rechtsgang 
verlegt   ist,   hineingetragen :    wo    die    Stimmenmehrheit   versagt, 
dringt  die  Siegermehrheit  durch. 

Doch  ist  auch  im  Bereiche  vorbehaltloser  Geltung  der  Stim- 
menmehrheit mit  dem  Satze  „  Die  Minderheit  soil  der  Mehrheit 
folgen  "  die  alte  sinnliche  Vorstellung  von  den  Verbandseinheiten 
noch  nicht  uberwunden.  Denn  im'mer  noch  wird  dabei  die 
Gesamtheit  als  Einheit  mit  der  Vielheit  Aller  identifiziert.  Eine 
Anderung  tritt  erst  ein,  wenn  der  Mehrheitsbeschluss  un- 
mittelbar  als  Ausdruck  des  Gesamtwillens  gilt.  Diese 
Entwicklungsstufe  musste  erreicht  werden,  sobald  der  alte  Genos- 
senschaftsbegriff  zum  Korperschafts.begriff  gesteigert  wurde, 
was  am  friihesten  in  den  Stadten  geschah.2  In  der  Tat  lasst  sich 
verfolgen,  wie  mit  der  korporativen  Ausgestaltung  der  Verbande 
diese  neue  Auffassung  des  Majoritatsprinzips  Hand  in  Hand  geht 

1  Sachsensp.  ii.  12  §  8  und  i.   18  §  3  u.  Lehnr.  69  §  3.     Jeder  Besiegte 
muss  dem  Richter  Wette  und  dem  Gegner  Busse  zahlen. 

2  Hiervon  handelt  mein  Genossenschaftsr.  ii.  573  ff.,  829  ff. 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  321 

und  demgemass  die  nachtragliche  Zustimmung  der  Minderheit 
mehr  und  mehr  als  uberflussige  Formalitat  in  Wegfall  kommt. 

Vollzog  das  germanische  Recht  eine  derartige  Umbildung  des 
Majoritatsprinzips  aus  sich  heraus,  so  empfing  sie  doch  ihre  begriff- 
liche  Fassung  durch  die  vom  romischen  und  kanonischen 
Recht  ausgehende  mittelalterliche  Jurisprudenz.  Sie 
zuerst  stellte  eine  bis  in  die  feinsten  Einzelheiten  ausgearbeitete, 
fiir  die  ganze  Folgezeit  grundlegend  gewordene  Korporationstheorie 
auf,  in  der  das  Majoritatsprinzip  eine  zentrale  Rolle  spielte. 

Die  Legisten  entnahmen  dem  Corpus  Juris  Civilis  die  grund- 
satzliche  Geltung  von  Mehrheitsbeschliissen  und  deren  Rechtferti- 
gung  durch  eine  Fiktion,  kraft  deren  die  Mehrheit  rechtlich  so 
angesehen  wird,  als  seien  es  Alle.  Wahrend  aber  die  Glossatoren  noch 
uberwiegend  in  der  Vorstellung  befangen  blieben,  dass  die  Gesamt- 
heit  sich  mit  der  Summe  der  Einzelnen  deckt,1  fuhrten  die 
Postglossatoren  die  Unterscheidung  von  omnes  ut  universi  und 
omnes  ut  singuli  ein,  die  schon  bei  O  do f red  us  das  Funda- 
ment der  Lehre  von  den  Korporationsbeschliissen  bildet  und  bei 
Bartolus  ihre  abschliessende  Gestalt  empfangt.2  Nur  wo  das 
Gesetz  eine  Vielheit  als  universitas  zusammenfasse,  stelle  es  die 
Mehrheit  Allen  gleich,  wahrend  iiberall,  wo  eine  Vielheit  nur  als 
Summe  von  Einzelnen  gelte,  der  Widerspruch  eines  Einzigen  die 
iibereinstimmung  aller  Ubrigen  iiberwinde.  Von  hier  aus  erkannte 
man  in  dem  Vorrang  des  Mehrheitswillens  ein  spezifisch  korpora- 
tives  Prinzip.  Man  leitete  ihn  aus  dem  Wesen  der  Korporation 
her,  weil  diese  eben  die  Mitglieder  zur  universitas  verbinde,  und 
versagte  umgekehrt,  von  singularen  Ausnahmen  abgesehen,  dem 
Majoritatsprinzip  die  Anerkennung  in  der  blossen  Gesellschaft  oder 
Gemeinschaft,  weil  diese  nur  ein  Verhaltnis  von  plures  ut  singuli 
sei.  Weiter  aber  band  man  die  Kraft  des  Mehrheitsbeschlusses  an 
dessen  Zustandekommen  in  einer  gehorig  berufenen  und  ordnungs- 
massig  verhandelnden  Versammlung,  da  nur  in  einer  solchen  die 
Gesamtheit  sich  rechtlich  als  Einheit  darstelle,  und  baute  die  Lehre 
von  den  Erfordernissen  eines  jeglichen  Korporationsbeschlusses  im 
Einzelnen  aus.  Die  Beschlussfahigkeit  der  Versammlung  machte 

1  Uber  die  Lehre  der  Glossatoren  vgl.  mein  Genossenschaftsr.  iii.  220  ff. 
In  der  Gl.  ord.  zu  1.   7   §  I  D.  h.t.v.  non  debetur  (ebend.  Anm.   107)  heisst 
es  noch  :  universitas  nihil  aliud  est  quam  singuli  homines  qui  ibi  sunt. 

2  Mein  Genossenschaftsr.  iii.  391  ff. 

Y 


322  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

man  unter  Verallgemeinerung  des  romischen  Dekurionenrechtes 
von  der  Anwesenheit  von  zwei  Dritteln  der  Mitglieder  abhangig, 
sah  aber  abweichende  Verfassungsbestimmungen  als  zulassig  an. 
Endlich  entwickelte  man  auf  Grund  der  Unterscheidung  von  omnes 
ut  universi  und  omnes  ut  singuli  die  Theorie  von  den  fiir  den 
Mehrheitsbeschluss  unantastbaren  jura  singulorum^  die  dann  durch 
die  Jahrhunderte  hindurch  sich  behauptet  hat,  wahrend  die  Abgren- 
zung  der  Sonderrechte  bis  heute  das  umstrittenste  Problem  des 
Korperschaftsrechtes  geblieben  ist.  Konnte  doch  einerseits  durch 
libermassige  Ausdehnung  des  Begriffes  der  jura  singulorum  alle 
Kraft  der  Gemeinschaftsgewalt  gebrochen  werden,  wie  ja  vielfach 
bei  der  standischen  Steuerbewilligung  die  Geltung  des  Stimmen- 
mehrs  unter  dem  Gesichtspunkt,  dass  die  Verfiigung  iiber  den 
Geldbeutel  des  Genossen  sicherlich  in  dessen  Sonderrecht  eingreife, 
in  Frage  gestellt  und  spater  in  Deutschland  sogar  die  Reichsgewalt 
durch  die  Versteifung  der  jura  singulorum  lahmgelegt  wurde.  Auf 
der  anderen  Seite  aber  lag  in  der  Festhaltung  dieser  Schranke  ein 
unentbehrlicher  Schutz  gegen  Majoritatstyrannei.  Doch  bildet  der 
wechselvolle  Kampf  um  die  jura  singulorum  ein  eigenes  Kapitel 
der  Rechtsgeschichte. 

Mit  der  Lehre  der  Legisten  beriihrte  sich  die  Lehre  des 
kanonischen  Rechtes  und  der  Kanonisten,2  die  mehr  und 
mehr  auch  auf  jene  einen  tiefgreifenden  Einfluss  gewann.  Wenn 
in  der  Kirche  das  Majoritatsprinzip  in  Glaubenssachen  stets  aus- 
geschlossen  blieb,  so  drang  es  doch  bei  Wahlen  und  bei  alien 
kollegialen  Beschliissen  liber  aussere  Angelegenheiten,  obschon 
auch  hier  Einstimmigkeit  als  das  Erwiinschtere  gait,  allgemein 
durch.  Dabei  wirkten  im  friiheren  Mittelalter  auf  die  Ausgestaltung 
des  Majoritatsprinzips  germanische  Anschauungen  ein,  sodass  es 
nur  als  Mittel  behandelt  wurde,  den  Weg  zum  communis  consensus 
zu  ebnen.3  Die  ausgebildete  kanonistische  Theorie  aber  stimmte 
mit  der  romanistischen  Theorie  in  der  Gleichsetzung  des  Mehr- 
heitswillens  mit  dem  Gesamtwillen  uberein.  Auch  sie  lehrte, 
dass  im  Gegensatz  zu  den  res  communes  pluribus  ut  singulis 
bei  alien  negotia  universitatis  kraft  gesetzlicher  Fiktion  quod 

1  Die  Anfange  schon  bei  Azo  und  in  der  Glosse  ;  a.  a.  O.,  S.  222,  Anm. 
108.      Uber  die  spatere  Jurisprudenz  S.  393,  Anm.  163,  S.  445  ff.,  S.  472  ff. 

2  A.  a.  O.,  S.  312  ff. 

3  A.  a.  O.,  S.  323  ff. 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  323 

major  pars  facit^  totum  facere  videtur.  Sie  suchte  jedoch  nach 
einem  inneren  Grunde  dafiir  und  fand  ihn  in  der  Wahrscheinlich- 
keit,  dass  Viele  leichter  als  Wenige  das  Richtige  treffen  werden  : 
quia  per  plures  melius  veritas  inquiritur.1 

Dies  war  der  treibende  Gedanke  fur  die  eigenartige  Umpragung, 
die  das  Majoritatsprinzip  durch  die  Einfiihrung  des  Satzes  erfuhr, 
dass  wahre  Mehrheit  nur  die  major  et  sanior  pars  ist.2  Die  pars 
numerosior  hat  nur  die  Vermutung  der  besseren  Einsicht  fur  sich, 
kann  aber  nicht  als  der  grossere  Teil  gelten,  sobald  diese  Vermu- 
tung widerlegt  wird.  Von  Theorie  und  Gesetzgebung  seit  dem 
I2ten  Jahrhundert  allmahlich  ausgebildet  und  im  Jahre  1179  von 
Alexander  III.  auf  dem  dritten  Lateranensischen  Konzil  bereits 
als  allgemeingiiltig  behandelt,  errang  sich  das  Dogma  von  der 
major  et  sanior  pars  alsbald  die  unbestrittene  Herrschaft  im  kirch- 
lichen  Recht.  Die  Anschauung,  dass  die  Stimmen  nicht  nur  zu 
zahlen,  sondern  zu  wagen  sind,  war  ja  auch  dem  germanischen 
Recht  nicht  fremd  und  kam  in  dem  Ubergewicht  der  Stimmen 
der  Angesehensten  bei  der  Feststellung  des  Versammlungsbe- 
schlusses  zum  Ausdruck.  Das  kanonische  Recht  aber  goss  sie  in 
juristische  Form  und  verinnerlichte  den  Massstab  der  Abwagung. 
Bei  der  Ermittlung,  welcher  Teil  der  „  gesundere  "  ist,  sollen  neben 
dem  Ansehen  (auctoritas)  der  Stimmenden  ihre  geistigen  und 
sittlichen  Eigenschaften  (ratio  et  pietas)  und  die  Lauterkeit  ihrer 
Motive  (bonus  zelus  et  aequitas)  in  Erwagung  gezogen,  zugleich 
aber  soil  die  Vernlinftigkeit  des  Ergebnisses  (insbesondere  bei 
Wahlen  die  Wiirdigkeit  des  Gewahlten)  gepriift  werden.  In  den 
genauen  Regeln  iiber  die  Bewertung  der  einzelnen  Momente 
offenbart  sich  in  charakteristischer  Weise  der  spiritual  istische 
Zug  des  kanonischen  Rechts.  Gleichzeitig  aber  bedeutet  das 
Erfordernis  der  sanioritas  die  Beugung  des  Majoritatsprinzips 
unter  das  hierarchische  Autoritatsprinzip.  Denn  die  Entscheidung 
liegt  ausschliesslich  in  der  Hand  des  kirchlichen  Oberen.  Vielfach 
wurde  sogar  die  Ansicht  verfochten,  dass  auch  eine  Minderzahl 
durch  sanioritas  zur  major  pars  werde,  womit  im  Grunde  das 
Majoritatsprinzip  uberhaupt  in  die  Luft  gesprengt  war.  Doch 
siegte  schliesslich  die  Meinung,  dass  zum  giiltigen  Beschluss  major 
et  sanior  pars  unerlasslich  sei,  also  Ubergewicht  der  Zahl  und  des 

1  Ausspruch  von  Innocenz  IV.  ebd.  S.  324,  Anm.  246. 

2  Uber  Ursprung  und  Entfaltung  dieser  Lehne  a.  a.  O.,  S.  324  ff.,  475. 


324  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

Wertes  der  Stimmen  zusammentreffen  miisse.  Und  mindestens 
bei  Wahlen  drang  die  Anschauung  durch,  dass  bei  einer  Zweidrit- 
telsmehrheit  die  Vermutung  fur  sanioritas  sich  zur  Gewissheit  stei- 
gere.  In  dem  einzigen  Falle,  in  dem  es  an  der  Moglichkeit  einer 
Priifung  der  sanioritas  durch  einen  kirchlichen  Oberen  fehlte,  bei  der 
Papstwahl,  war  gerade  deshalb  Zweidrittelsmehrheit  erforderlich. 

Wenn  die  Kanonisten  anfanglich  fiir  ihre  Forderung  der  major 
et  sanior  pars  Allgemeingultigkeit  beanspruchten  und  hier  und  da 
hiermit  Beifall  fanden,1  so  siegte  schliesslich  die  Meinung,  dass  es 
sich  um  eine  Besonderheit  des  kirchlichen  Rechtes  handle.2 
Nur  vereinzelt  begegnen  Nachbildungen  im  weltlichen  Recht.3 
Dagegen  gewann  die  kanonistische  Anschauung,  dass  ein  starkes 
und  zwar  mindestens  doppeltes  Ubergewicht  der  Zahl  eine  Gewahr 
fiir  die  Verniinftigkeit  der  Mehrheitsentscheidung  biete,  allgemeine 
Bedeutung.  Auf  sie  geht  das  Erfordernis  einer  Zweidrittels-  oder 
Dreiviertelsmehrheit  zu  besonders  wichtigen  Beschliissen,  insbeson- 
dere  zu  Verfassungsanderungen  zuriick,  das  schon  im  Mittelalter 
oft  vorkommt 4  und  heute  zu  den  verbreitetsten  Einschrankungen 
des  Majoritatsprinzips  gehort. 

In  vielen  anderen  Punkten  fiihrten  die  Kanonisten  der  Lehre 
von  den  Korporationsbeschliissen  bleibenden  Gewinn  zu.  Nur  auf 
zweierlei  will  ich  hinweisen.  Gegenliber  der  von  den  Legisten 
verfochtenen  Regel,  dass  zur  Beschlussfahigkeit  einer  Ver- 
sammlung  die  Anwesenheit  von  zwei  Dritteln  erforderlich  sei, 
setzten  sie  die  Ansicht  durch,  dass  an  sich  bei  ordnungsmassiger 
Versammlung  die  Anwesenheit  einer  noch  so  geringen  Zahl  geniige, 
weil  die  Ausgebliebenen  fiir  dieses  Mai  sich  selbst  ausgeschlossen 
haben  (se  alienos  fecerunf)?  Alle  Falle,  in  denen  die  Beschluss- 
fahigheit  von  der  Anwesenheit  einer  bestimmten  Zahl  von  Mit- 

1  Vgl.  die  Nachweise  a.  a.  O.,  S.  394,  Anm.  169,  S.  475,  Anm.  284. 

2  A.  a.  O.,  S.  475.      Im  kirchlichen  Recht  wurde  das  Prinzip  der  major 
et   sanior  pars  niemals    aufgegeben,   allmahlich    aber  zuriickgedrangt.      Mit 
der  Zulassung  geheimer  Abstimmungen  wurde  es  praktisch  undurchfiihrbar. 

3  Vgl.  die  Stellen  aus  Weistiimern  in  meinem  Genossenschaftsr.   ii.  481, 
Anm.   14.     Man  denke  auch  an  die  Befugnis  des  Reichshofratsprasidenten, 
eine  Entscheidung  des  Kollegiums,  wenn  sie  nur  eine  geringe  Mehrheit  und 
nicht  zugleich  die  offenbar  besseren  Griinde  fiir  sich  hat,  ad  votum  Imperatoris 
zu  bringen.  4  Mein  Genossenschaftsr.  ii.  481,  Anm.  15. 

5  A.  a.  O.  iii.  320  ff.,  467  ff.  Die  Folge  ist,  dass  jus  universitatis  reridit 
in  ceteros  velin  unum.  Man  sprach  von  einer  ,,magna  controversia  "  zwischen 
Legisten  und  Kanonisten. 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  325 

gliedern  abhangt,  erscheinen  demgemass,  wie  ja  auch  in  heutigen 
Recht,  als  besonders  begriindete  Ausnahmen.  Sodann  befruchteten 
die  Kanonisten  die  Lehre  von  den  Einzelrechten  durch  die  erst- 
malige  Unterscheidung  zwischen  den  freien  Individualrechten  und 
den  korperschaftlichen  Sonderrechten,  den  jura  singulorum  propria 
und  den  jura  singulorum  collegialia  oder  in  universitate^ 

Fragen  wir  nach  dem  Verhaltnis  der  romanistisch-kanonisti- 
schen  Korporationstheorie  zur  Grundauffassung  vom  Wesen  der 
Verbande,  so  leuchtet  ein,  dass  sie  mil  der  durchgangigen  Unter- 
scheidung der  omnes  ut  universi  und  der  omnes  ut  singuli  die  der 
alteren  germanischen  Vorstellung  noch  nicht  gelaufige  Abstraktion 
der  Gesamteinheit  von  der  Gesamtvielheit  vollzogen  hatte.  Allein 
in  der  Identifizierung  der  Korperschaft  mit  der  Gesamtheit  als 
einheitlichem  InbegrifF  blieb  sie  zunachst  stecken.  Die  univer- 
sitas deckt  sich  eben  mit  den  omnes  ut  universi  \  darumwurde 
in  stets  wiederkehrenden  Wendungen  die  wollende  und  handelnde 
Mitgliederversammlung  als  die  Korperschaft  selbst,  die  univer- 
sitas  ipsa  bezeichnet.2  Im  Bereiche  der  Geltung  des  Majo- 
ritatsprinzips  kommt  in  der  major  pars  die  universitas  ipsa  zur 
Erscheinung.  Kraft  einer  neuen  Fiktion  werden  Reprasentanten- 
versammlungen,  z.B.  Stadtrate,  der  universitas  ipsa  gleichgestellt.3 
Hier  liberal  1  handelt  die  universitas  per  se.  Dagegen  liegt  ein 
agere  per  alium  vor,  wenn  Vorsteher  und  Beamte  tatig  werden. 
Sie  sind  blosse  Vertreter  der  Gesamtheit  und  handeln  nur  da,  wo 
die  universitas  ipsa  nicht  zu  handeln  vermag,  kraft  gesetzlicher 
oder  rechtsgeschaftlicher  Vollmacht  an  ihrer  Stelle.  Diese  Unter- 
scheidung zwischen  dem  eignen  Handeln  der  Korperschaft  und 
dem  Handeln  ihrer  Vertreter  war  fur  den  Aufbau  der  mittel- 
alterlichen  Korporationstheorie  von  fundamentaler  Bedeutung 
und  beherrschte  namentlich  die  viel  umstrittene  Lehre  von  den 
Korperschaftsdelikten.4 

Neben  der  kollektiven  Verbandsauffassung  aber  brach  sich  eine 
ganz  andere  Auffassung  Bahn,  die  von  den  Kanonisten  und  zwar 
in  voller  Scharfe  zuerst  von  Innocenz  IV.  im  Sinne  des  kirch- 

1  A.  a.  O.,  S.  297  ff,  wo  die  wichtigsten  Stellen  aus  Innocenz  IV.,  Job. 
Andreae,   Antonius  de  Butrio  und  Panormitanus  wiedergegeben  sind  ;  dazu 
S.  445  ff,  472. 

2  A.  a.  O.,  S.  219  ff.,  390  ff.,  461  ff,  477  ff. 

3  A.  a.  O.,  S.  222  ff,  394  ff,  478  ff. 

4  A.  a.  O.,  S.  234  ff,  402  ff.,  491  ff. 


326  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

lichen  Anstaltsbegriffes  entwickelt  und  dann  auf  alle  korporativen 
Verbande  erstreckt  wurde.  Sie  findet  die  Verbandseinheit  in  einer 
der  Mitgliedergesamtheit  transzendenten  Wesenheit,  einer 
besonderen  Verbandspersonlichkeit,  die  so  gut  von  der 
Versammlung  aller  Mitglieder,  wie  von  Vorstehern  und  Beamten 
nur  reprasentiert  wird.  Das  Mittel  ihrer  Konstruktion  aber  ist  eine 
neue  Fiktion.  Es  ist  die  im  Corpus  Juris  Civilis  erst  angedeu- 
tete,  nun  jedoch  scharf  herausgemeisselte  und  in  den  Mittelpunkt 
geriickte  fingierte  Person,  die  persona  ficta,  repraesentata^ 
imaginaria,  das  erdichtete  kiinstliche  Individuum !  Bei  folgerichtiger 
Durchfiihrung  dieser  neuen  Fiktion  verschwindet  die  Gleichsetzung 
der  Gesamtheit  der  Mitglieder  mit  der  universitas  ipsa.  Die 
universitas  ipsa  ist  allein  das  unsichtbare  ideale  Rechtssubjekt,  das 
auch,  wenn  die  Versammlung  beschliesst,  per  alium  agit.  Damit 
wird  die  Theorie  der  Korporationsbeschliisse  auf  eine  hohere  Stufe 
gehoben.  Denn  nunmehr  kann  die  Wirksamkeit  aller  Ver- 
sammlungsakte  in  Korporationsangelegenheiten  in  die  Schranken 
einer  der  Versammlung  selbst  zugewiesenen  verfassungsmassigen 
Zustandigkeit,  innerhalb  deren  allein  sie  die  fingierte  Person  re- 
prasentiert, gebannt  werden.  Diese  Zustandigkeit  wird  vor  Allem 
durch  den  korporativen  Lebensbereich,  aber  auch  durch  die  Zu- 
standigkeiten  eines  Vorstandes  oder  anderer  Vertreter  des  klinst- 
lichen  Rechtssubjektes  begrenzt.  Dariiber  hinaus  vermag  auch 
der  einstimmige  Versammlungsbeschluss  nichts  auszurichten, 
versagt  daher  erst  recht  das  Majoritatsprinzip,  das  nur  den 
Mehrheitswillen  zum  Versammlungswillen  stempelt.  Alle  solche 
Fortschritte  aber  werden  mit  der  Verdrangung  der  lebendigen 
Verbandseinheit  durch  das  Gespenst  der  fingierten  Personlichkeit 
erkauft.  Die  neue  Herrin  der  gemeinheitlichen  Spharen  ist  ein 
willens-  und  handlungsunfahiges  Begriffswesen.  Sie  gleicht  dem 
Kinde  oder  vielmehr,  da  das  Kind  einmal  mundig  wird,  dem 
unheilbar  Wahnsinnigen.  Die  Verantwortlichkeit  fur  unerlaubte 
Handlungen  wird  ihr  abgenommen,  sie  wird  aber  zugleich  in  allem 
Handeln  vormundschaftlicher  Vertretung  unterstellt.  Der  ger- 
manische  Genossenschaftsgedanke  wird  ausgetilgt.  Der  Korpora- 
tionsbegriff  empfangt  eine  rein  anstaltliche  Farbung.1 

1  Uber  den  kanonistischen  Ursprung  der  Theorie  der  persona  ficta  und 
ihre  Bedeutung  fur  die  Lehre  vom  korperschaftlichen  Wollen  und  Handeln 
vgl.  a.  a.  O.,  S.  277  ff.,  308  ff.,  342  ff. 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  327 

Die  Theorie  der  persona  ficta  wurde  auch  von  den  Zivili- 
sten  angenommen  und  beherrschte  ausserlich  die  gesamte  Jurispru- 
denz  der  folgenden  Jahrhunderte.  Sie  leistete  bei  der  Umbildung 
alles  Verbandsrechtes  im  Geiste  des  obrigkeitlichen  Staates  wichtige 
Dienste.  Allein  selten  wurde  sie  folgerichtig  durchgefiihrt,  ging 
vielmehr  fast  durchweg  ein  Kompromiss  mit  der  zah  festgehaltenen 
kollektiven  Auffassung  ein.  So  setzte  sich  auch  in  der  Lehre 
von  den  Korporationsbeschliissen  immer  wieder  die  Behandlung  des 
ubereinstimmenden  Willens  aller  Mitglieder  als  Willens  der  Kor- 
perschaft  selbst  durch.  Fort  und  fort  wurde  daher,  so  weit  die 
rechtliche  Gleichsetzung  der  Majoritat  mit  Allen  reichte,  der 
Mehrheitsbeschluss  als  Willenserklarung  der  universitas  ipsa 
betrachtet  und  zwischen  dem  eigenen  Handeln  der  Gemeinheit 
und  ihrem  Handeln  durch  Vertreter  unterschieden.1  Damit  ver- 
wickelte  man  sich  in  zahlreiche  Widerspriiche,  gewann  aber  die 
Moglichkeit,  nach  Beniirfnis  den  fortlebenden  Gebilden  germa- 
nischer  Herkunft  gerecht  zu  werden  und  genossenschaftlichen 
Gedanken  Raum  zu  geben.  Erst  im  neunzehnten  Jahrhundert 
machten  Savigny  und  seine  Schiiler  mit  dem  Begriffe  der  fingierten 
Person  als  eines  der  verbundenen  Gesamtheit  fremden  kiinstlichen 
Individuums  wieder  Ernst  und  legten  ihn  ihrem  Neubau  der  Lehre 
von  den  „  juristischen  Personen",  wie  man  nun  sagte,  zu  Grunde,  in 
dem  auch  das  Majoritatsprinzip  wieder  die  entsprechende  Fassung 
empfing. 

Diese  Restauration  aber  entsprang  vor  Allem  dem  Gegensatz 
gegen  die  naturrechtliche  Gesellschaftslehre,  die  inzwischen 
zur  Ubermacht  emporgediehen  war  und  das  positive  Recht  liber- 
schwemmt  hatte.  Denn  das  Naturrecht  trieb  die  rein  kollektive 
Auffassung  aller  menschlichen  Verbande  auf  die  Spitze.  Es  leitete 
alle  Verbande  bis  aufwarts  zum  Staat  aus  der  vertragsmassigen 
Vereinigung  der  von  Hause  aus  freien  und  gleichen  Individuen  her 
und  konstruierte  alles  Verbandsrecht  als  vergemeinschaftetes 
Individualrecht.  Ihm  war  so  gut  der  Staat  wie  die  Ehe  und 
jede  Erwerbsgesellschaft  eine  vertragsmassig  begriindete  societas. 
Der  Sozietatsbegriff  verschlang  den  Korporationsbegriff  wie  den 
Anstaltsbegriff.  Nun  fordert  aber  der  Vertrag  den  Konsens  aller 

1  A.  a.  O.,  S.  363  ff.,  390  ff.,  402  ff.,  425  ff.,  461  ff.,  491  ff.  Die  Ver- 
neinung  der  Deliktsfahigkeit  der  Korporationen  drang  nicht  einmal  bei  den 
Kanonisten  durch  ;  a.  a.  O.,  S.  343. 


328  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

Kontrahenten.  Darum  bereitete  gerade  das  Majoritatsprinzip  den 
Naturrechtslehrern  nicht  geringe  Schwierigkeiten.  Sie  halfen  sich 
mit  der  Annahme,  dass  in  den  ursprunglichen  Gesellschaftsvertra- 
gen  einstimmig  die  kunftige  Geltung  des  Mehrheitswillens  in 
Gesellschaftsangelegenheiten  vereinbart  sei.  Die  so  errichtete 
Gesellschaft  konnte  dann  durch  Mehrheitsbeschlusse  sich  eine 
Verfassung  kuren.  Dabei  konnte  bestimmt  werden,  dass  kunftig 
die  Gesamtheit  durch  eine  engere  Versammlung  reprasentiert  werde 
und  in  dieser  wieder  der  Mehrheitswille  entscheide.  Weiter  aber 
musste  die  als  societas  aequalis  entstandene  Gesamtheit,  wenn 
die  Innehaltung  des  Gesellschaftsvertrages  gesichert  werden  sollte, 
sich  einer  Zwangsgewalt  unterwerfen  und  so  zur  societas  inae- 
qualis  werden.  So  erschien  denn  vor  Allem  der  Staat  erst  als 
das  Produkt  eines  zweiten  Vertrages,  durch  den  die  biirgerliche 
Gesellschaft  in  irgend  einer  Weise  die  erforderliche  summa  potestas 
auf  einen  imperans  libertragen  hatte.  In  der  Monarchic  hatte  sie 
sich  einem  Einzelherrscher,  in  der  Republik  einem  Kollektivherrscher 
unterworfen.  Und  im  letzteren  Falle  war  es  wieder  eine  Ver- 
sammlungsmehrheit,  der  die  Gewalt  eingeraumt  war,  so  dass  man 
sogar  nicht  davor  zuriickscheute,  in  der  Demokratie  einen  be- 
sonderen  Unterwerfungsvertrag  zwischen  der  mit  Mehrheit  be- 
schliessenden  ursprunglichen  Gesamtheit  und  der  jeweiligen  kiinf- 
tigen  Mehrheit  Aller  zu  konstruieren.  Aus  einem  solchen  Netze 
von  Vertragen  Hess  man  schliesslich  einen  einheitlichen  gesell- 
schaftlichen  Korper  hervorgehen.  Allein  dessen  Einheit  war  das 
Werk  kiinstlich  geschaffner  Kollektiv-  und  Reprasentationsverhalt- 
nisse.  Wenn  man  daher  auch  den  gesellschaftlichen  Einheiten 
Personlichkeit  zuschrieb,  so  erhob  man  sich  doch  nicht  zu  dem 
Begriff  einer  selbstandigen  Personlichkeit  des  Ganzen,  sondern 
blieb  in  den  Begriffen  einer  kollektiven  Personlichkeit  der  Gesamt- 
heiten  und  einer  reprasentativen  Personlichkeit  der  Herrscher 
stecken.  Um  das  Verhaltnis  zwischen  Volkspersonlichkeit  und 
Herrscherpersonlichkeit  drehte  sich  in  der  naturrechtlichen  Staats- 
lehre  der  grosse,  weltbewegende  Streit.  Die  lebendige  Staatsper- 
sonlichkeit  blieb  unentdeckt.  Ausgeschaltet  aber  wurde  mehr  und 
mehr  die  Uberindividuelle  persona  ficta.  An  ihre  Stelle  trat  das, 
was  die  Naturrechtslehrer  als  persona  moralis  bezeichneten.  Unter 
der  moralischen  Person  aber  verstanden  sie  nur  eine  kollektive 
Personeneinheit.  Sie  meinten,  dass  mehrere  Menschen  in  ihrer 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  329 

gesellschaftlichen  Verbundenheit  die  Rolle  einer  einzigen  Person 
spielen,  wie  ja  auch  umgekehrt  ein  einzelner  Mensch  kraft  repra- 
sentativer  Stellung  mehrere  Personenrollen  spielen  kann. 

Verfolgen  wir  noch  etwas  naher  die  naturrechtliche  Auffassung 
des  Majoritatsprinzips,  so  findet  sich  zuerst  bei  Grotius  eine  ein- 
gehende  Begrundung  des  Satzes,  dass  die  Geltung  der  Stimmen- 
mehrheit  auf  einstimmiger  Vereinbarung  im  urspriinglichen  Gesell- 
schaftsvertrage  beruhe.1  Seitdem  wurde  dieser  Satz  zum  Axiom 
der  naturrechtlichen  Soziallehre.  Hobbes  und  Locke,  Ulrich 
Huber,  Pufendorf,  Thomasius,  Christian  Wolff,  Nettelbladt 
und  Ac  hen  wall  tragen  ihn  iibereinstimmend  vor,2  Rousseau  legt 
ihn  zu  Grunde3  und  Kant  erklart  ausdriicklich,  dass  die  in  grossen 
Staaten  unentbehrlichen  Einrichtungen  der  Mehrheitsentscheidung 
und  der  Representation  nur  aus  einer  ,,mit  allgemeiner  Zustimmung, 
also  durch  einen  Kontrakt,"  vollzogenen  Annahme  gerechtfertigt 
werden  konnen.4  Das  Bedenken,  dass  doch  jeder  Einzelne  zur 
Versagung  seines  Konsenses  berechtigt  gewesen  sei,  beseitigte  man 
mit  dem  Hinweis  darauf,  dass  er  damit  sich  von  der  Gesellschaft 
ausgeschlossen  haben  und  diese  ohne  ihn  errichtet  sein  wiirde. 
Hobbes  meint,  dann  hatten  die  zum  Staate  verbundenen  Anderen 
ihm  gegenuber  das  Kriegsrecht  des  Naturzustandes,  der  ja  nach 
Hobbes  ein  bellum  omnium  contra  omnes  war,  behalten.  Die 
meisten  Naturrechtslehrer  aber  bemiihten  sich  gleichzeitig  um  eine 
rationelle  Rechtfertigung  des  Majoritatsprinzips,  aus  der  sie  eine 

1  Grotius,  Dej.  b.  et p.  ii.  c.  5,  §  17.     In  den  friiheren  rechtsphilosophischen 
Erorterungen  liber  den  Staat  und  die  anderen  publizistischen  Verbande  wurde 
die     Geltung    des    Majoritatsprinzips    nebst     den     sonstigen     Regeln    iiber 
Korporationsbeschliisse    in    Anlehnung    an     die    romanistisch-kanonistische 
Theorie  fur  jede   einmal    konstituierte    universitas  und   somit   auch   fur  die 
Volksgesamtheit   ohne   Weiteres   angenommen ;  vgl.    mein   Genossenschaftsr. 
iii.  599  ff.,  meine  Schrift  iiber  Johannes  Althusius,  S.  85,  Anm.  30,  S.  138, 
Anm.  48,  S.  215,  Anm.  14. 

2  Hobbes,  De  cive,  c.  6,  §   1-2  ;  Locke,  ii.  c.  8,  §  96-99  ;  U.  Huber,  De 
jure   civ.  i.   2,  c.   3,  §  27  ff.,  ii.   3,  c.   I,  §  21-22,  !c.  2,  §  3-4;    Pufendorf, 
Elem.  i.  d.    12,   §    27,  Jus   nat.    et  gent.    vii.    c.    2,    §    15-19,    c.    5,    §    6, 
De  officio  civiS)  ii.  c.   6,  §  12;    Thomasius,  Inst.  jur.  div.  iii.  c.   6,  §  64  ; 
Wolff,    Inst.    §    841-845;    Nettelbladt,    Syst.   §  388;     Achenwall,  Jus   nat. 
ii.  §  24-28.      Besonders  ausflihrlich  Ickstatt,  De  jure  majorum  in  conclusis 
civitatis  communibus  formandis^  Opusc.  ii.  op.  i,  insbes.  c.  i,  §  65-68.     Vgl. 
auch  Gundling,  Diss.  de  universitate  delinquente,  §  6-8. 

3  Rousseau,  Contr.  soc.  iv.  c.  2.    Vgl.  auch  Sieyes,  i.  144  ff.,  167,  207  ff. 

4  Kant,  Werke,  vi.  328  ff. 


33°  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

bis  zum  Nachweise  abweichender  Abreden  durchgreifende  Vermu- 
tung  fiir  dessen  vertragsmassige  Einfiihrung  bei  jeder  Gesellschafts- 
griindung  herleiteten.  Es  sei  anzunehmen,  dass,  wer  eine  Gesell- 
schaft  wolle,  auch  ihren  Fortbestand  und  ihre  Aktionsfahigkeit 
wolle.  Zur  Erreichung  dieses  Zieles  aber  sei  die  Anerkennung  von 
Mehrheitsbeschliissen  das  geeignetste  Mittel.  Grotius  fiihrt  aus, 
dass,  da  es  irgend  eine  verniinftige  Art  einheitlicher  Geschafts- 
erledigung  geben  miisse,  das  Verlangen  aber  der  Unterwerfung  der 
Minderheit  unter  die  Mehrheit  unbillig  ware,  nichts  iibrig  bleibe,  als 
der  Mehrheit  das  jus  integri  beizulegen.  Hobbes,  Pufendorf, 
Gun dl ing  und  viele  Andere  betonen,  dass  jede  zur  Sozietat  ver- 
bundene  Gesamtheit  im  Stande  sein  miisse,  einheitlich  zu  wollen, 
dass  es  aber  hierfiir  kein  besseres  Auskunftsmittel  gebe,  als  die 
Gleichsetzung  des  Mehrheitswillens  mit  dem  Willen  Aller.  Locke 
geht  von  dem  Begriffe  des  gesellschaftlichen  Korpers  aus,  der  gleich 
jedem  Korper  durch  eine  einzige  Kraft  in  einheitlicher  Weise  bewegt 
werden  miisse,  und  meint,  dass  hier  die  bewegende  Kraft  nur  in 
der  von  der  Mehrheit  getragenen  grosseren  Kraft  gefunden  werden 
konne  ;  darum  entspreche  es  den  Natur-  und  Vernunftgesetzen,  den 
Mehrheitswillen  als  Willen  des  Ganzen  gelten  zu  lassen.  Auch 
sonst  berief  man  sich  ofter  auf  das  Ubergewicht  der  Mehrzahl  an 
ausserer  Starke,1  griff  aber  auch  hier  und  da  auf  die  germanische 
Vorstellung  einer  rechtlichen  Folgepflicht  der  Minderheit  zuriick.2 
Rousseau  suchte  mit  seiner  beriihmten  Unterscheidung  der  volonte 
generate  von  der  volonte  de  tons  durch  einen  dialektischen  Kunst- 
griff  zu  erweisen,  dass  der  allgemeine  Wille  notwendig  zugleich  der 
verniinftige  und  gerechte  Wille  sei,  weil  er  das  Besondere  und 
Zufallige  der  in  ihm  verschmolzenen  Einzelwillen  nicht  in  sich 
aufnehme ;  allein  die  Erklarung  dafiir,  warum  dieser  allgemeine 
Wille  sich  mit  dem  Mehrheitswillen  decke,  blieb  er  schuldig, 
begniigte  sich  vielmehr  mit  der  nichts  erklarenden  Fiktion  der 
einstimmigen  Vereinbarung  im  Urvertrage.  Im  Grunde  hatte  ihn 

1  So  besonders    Ickstatt,    a.  a.   O.,   der   ausfiihrt,    bei    motiva    disparia 
miissten  die  motiva  fortiora  entscheiden,  der  Massstab  konne  aber  nur  ein 
ausserer  sein. 

2  Daries,  Inst.  jurispr.  univ.  §  750-762  (an  sich  ist  Einstimmigkeit  notig, 
aber  es  besteht  fiir  die  Minderheit  eine  obligatio  perfecta  zum  Beitritt).      So 
meint  auch  Pufendorf,  wer  aus  blosser  pertinacia  sich  seinen  consensus  vorbe- 
halte,  hindere  den  Versammlungsbeschluss  nicht,  dieser  binde  ihn  vielmehr 
kraft  der  allgemeinenVorschrift,  ut  pars  se  conformet  ad  bonum  lotius. 


xvi]  Majoritatsprinzip  33 1 

die  Konsequenz  der  Gedanken,  die  ihn  zur  Ablehnung  des  Repra- 
sentativprinzips  fuhrten,  auch  zur  Verwerfung  des  Majoritatsprinzips 
bewegen  miissen.  Und  zu  dieser  aussersten  Konsequenz  des  Indi- 
vidualismus  schritten  dann  auch  einzelne  Naturrechtslehrer  vor. 
Sie  behaupteten,  dass  aus  dem  Naturrecht  allein  die  Forderung 
einstimmiger  Beschlusse  zu  begriinden  sei,  dass  daher  in  jeder 
Sozietat  die  Vermutung  fur  das  Einstimmigkeitsprinzip  spreche 
und  nur  kraft  besonders  vereinbarter  Ausnahmen  das  Majoritats- 
prinzip gelten  konne.  So  z.B.  die  beiden  Schlozer,  Vater  und 
Sohn.1  Den  Gipfel  aber  erklomm  Fichte,  indem  er  die  rechtliche 
Geltung  des  Majoritatsprinzips  schlankweg  verneinte  und  hochstens 
in  gewissen  Fallen  der  Mehrheit  das  Recht  zur  Ausschliessung  der 
Dissentierenden  zugestand.2 

In  dem  Masse,  in  dem  im  neunzehnten  Jahrhundert  die  natur- 
rechtliche  Gesellschaftslehre  uberwunden  wurde,  verlor  auch  ihre 
individualistische  Erklarung  des  Majoritatsprinzips  an  Ansehen. 
Bleibe/id  aber  behauptete  sich  die  von  ihr  angebahnte  Wieder- 
belebung  des  germanischen  Genossenschaftsgedankens.  Die 
genossenschaftliche  Auffassung  der  menschlichen  Verbande  drang 
gegenuber  der  anstaltlichen  Staats-  und  Korporationsauffassung 
wiederum  siegreich  vor.  Darum  war  auch  in  Ansehung  der 
Mehrheitsbeschliisse  der  restaurierten  romanistisch-kanonistischen 
Theorie  kein  endgiiltiger  Erfolg  beschieden.  Vielmehr  gewannen 
ihr  neue  Anschauungen,  wie  sie  zuerst  von  der  germanistischen 
Genossenschaftstheorie  aus  verjungtem  germanischem  Recht  ent- 
wickelt  wurden,  immer  breiteren  Boden  ab. 

Doch  kann  ich  das  bis  heute  nicht  erledigte  Ringen  der 
gegensatzlichen  Auffassungen  und  die  mannigfachen  Ausgleichs- 
versuche  hier  nicht  verfolgen.  Nur  das  will  ich  kurz  andeuten, 
welche  Gesichtspunkte  fur  die  Wertung  des  Majoritatsprinzips 
bestimmend  sein  miissen,  wenn  die  in  alien  Jahrhunderten 
lebendig  gebliebene  und  im  modernen  Bewusstsein  zur  Vorherr- 
schaft  gelangte,  der  juristischen  Konstruktion  aber  erst  im  Gefolge 
der  Genossenschaftstheorie  zu  Grunde  gelegte  his  tori  sch-orga- 
nische  Verbandsauff  assung  durchgefiihrt  wird. 

1  A.    L.   Schlozer,   Allg.    Staatsr.,   S.   76  ff. ;    Chr.   v.  Schlozer,   De  jure 
suffragii  in  societate  aequali,  Gott,  1795,  §  9-M- 

2  Fichte,  Naturrecht  Einl  Nr.  III.  i.  198,  217  ff.,  225  ff.  (Werke,  iii.  16, 
164,  178  ff.,  184  ff). 


332  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

Sind  die  menschlichen  Verbande  soziale  Organismen,  bringen 
sie    als    selbstandige    Lebewesen     liber    dem     Einzeldasein    das 
Gattungsdasein  zur  Entfaltung,  so  treten  sie  auch  fur  das  Recht 
den  Einzelpersonen  als  Personen  hoherer  Ordnung  gegeniiber. 
Sie  lassen  sich  nicht  im  Sinne  des  Naturrechts  als  blosse  Zusam- 
menballungen  von  Individuen  zu  kollektiven  Einheiten  begreifen. 
Sie  diirfen  aber  auch  nicht  im   Sinne  der  Fiktionstheorieen  als 
kiinstliche    Individuen   von   den   verbundenen    Gesamtheiten   los- 
gerissen   werden.      Vielmehr  sind   sie   reale  Gesamtpersonen, 
selbstandige   Gemeinwesen  mit   immanenter  Lebenseinheit,  orga- 
nische  Ganze,  die  sich  aus  Einzelwesen  aufbauen,  aber  keineswegs 
mit  der  Summe  ihrer  Teile  decken.      Darum  ist  nicht  bloss  das 
aussere,  sondern  auch  'das  innere  Leben  der  Verbandspersonen, 
das  ja  zugleich   ausseres   Leben   der  verbundenen   Personen  ist, 
Gegenstand   der   Rechtsordnung.      Uber   Zusammensetzung    und 
Gliederung  des  Verbandskorpers,  Uber  dessen  Organisation  zum 
einheitlichen  Ganzen,  iiber  die  Beziehungen  der  Teile  zu  einander 
und  zum    Ganzen  entscheiden    Rechtsnormen.      So  entsteht  der 
Rechtsbegriff  des  verfassungsmassigen  Organs.     Organe  sind  die 
in   einem    bestimmten    Tatigkeitsbereiche    zur    Darstellung    der 
Verbandspersonlichkeit  berufenen  Glieder  und  Gliederkomplexe. 
Sie  sind  keine  Vertreter  im   Sinne  des  Individualrechts,  sondern 
sichtbare  Werkzeuge  der  unsichtbaren  Lebenseinheit  des  sozialen 
Korpers.      Was   das    Organ   innerhalb   seiner   Zustandigkeit   will 
und  tut,   das  will  und   tut   im   Rechtssinne   die   Verbandsperson 
selbst.     Durch    Organe   und   nur  durch   Organe   tritt   der   Staat 
und   jeder   andere   korperschaftliche  Verband  als  wollendes  und 
handelndes  Gemeinwesen  in  die  Erscheinung.     So  kann  denn  auch 
die  Gesamtheit  aller    Mitglieder  den  einheitlichen    Gemeinwillen 
nur  insoweit  zum  Ausdruck  bringen,  als  sie  verfassungsmassig  in 
ihrer  rechtlich  geordneten  Versammlung  oder  in  sonstigem  kollek- 
tivem    Zusammenwirken    zum   Willensorgan  der  Verbandsperson 
berufen  ist.      Das  Gemeinwesen   als   solches   ist  etwas  durchaus 
Anderes  als  die  Summe  der  ihm  jeweilig  angehorigen  Individuen, 
und   keine   Kunst   vermag   den    ubereinstimmenden    Einzelwillen 
den  einheitlichen  Staats-  oder  Korperschaftswillen  zu   entlocken. 
Als  Glieder  des  Verbandes  aber  konnen  die  einzelnen  Menschen 
nur  in  ihrem  organisierten  Zusammenhange  das  lebendige  Ganze 
in  seiner  rechtlichen  Einheit  zur  Darstellung  bringen.     Jede  Ver- 


xvi]  Majorittitsprinzip  333 

sammlung  also  ist  nichts  als  Organ.  Sie  ist  selbst  dann,  wenn  sie 
alle  jeweiligen  Mitglieder  umfasst  und  einstimmig  beschliesst,  nur 
Organ  des  Verbandes  und  daher  nur  im  Bereiche  ihrer  verfassungs- 
massigen Zustandigkeit  zur  Bildung  und  Ausserung  des  Gemein- 
willens  befahigt.  In  gleicher  Weise  aber  ist  sie  Organ,  wenn  sie 
kraft  der  Lebensordnung  des  Verbandes  einen  giiltigen  Mehrheits-. 
beschluss  fasst.  Zur  Erklarung  des  Majoritatsprinzips  ist  also  die 
Gleichsetzung  der  Mehrheit  mit  der  Gesamtheit  weder  ausreichend 
noch  erforderlich.  Die  Geltung  des  Mehrheitsbeschlusses  als  eines 
der  verfassungsmassigen  Mittel  zur  Beschaffung  einer  einheitlichen 
Versammlungsaktion  ist  lediglich  ein  Stuck  der  rechtlich  geordneten 
Organbildung.  Sie  ist  ein  Element  der  Organisation  eines  zu- 
sammengesetzten  Organs. 

Von  diesem  Standpunkte  aus  kommtnun  freilich  dem  Majoritats- 
prinzip  keine  im  Wesen  der  menschlichen  Verbande  begrlindete 
absolute  Geltung,  sondern  nur  ein  historisch  bedingter  relativer 
Wert  zu.  Die  Herrschaft  des  Stimmenmehrs  allein  vermag  keinen 
Verband  und  am  wenigsten  den  Staat  zur  lebendigen  Verbands- 
person  zu  stempeln.  Immer  bedarf  es  neben  einer  mit  Mehrheit 
beschliessenden  Mitgliederversammlung  fiihrender  Organe,  damit 
ein  handlungsfahiges  Gemeinwesen  zu  Stande  komme.  So  weit 
durch  eine  monarchische  Verfassung  ein  Verbandshaupt  zum 
obersten  Organ  bestellt  ist,  versteht  es  sich  von  selbst,  dass  keine 
Versammlungsmehrheit  fur  sich  allein  den  einheitlichen  Verbands- 
willen  erzeugen  kann.  Aber  auch  wo  kraft  streng  demokratischer 
Verfassung  der  mit  Mehrheit  beschliessende  Inbegriffder  Mitglieder 
als  oberstes  Organ  fungiert,  offenbart  sich  nur  bei  den  ihm  vor- 
behaltenen  letzten  Entscheidungen  in  dem  Abstimmungsergebnis 
der  Gemeinwille,  wahrend  andere  selbstandige  Organe  in  ihren 
Zustandigkeitsbereichen  gleich  unmittelbar  die  Personlichkeit  des 
Ganzen  zur  Erscheinung  bringen.  Irgendwie  wird  in  jedem  sozialen 
Organismus  kraft  der  verfassungsmassigen  Funktionenverteilung 
das  Majoritatsprinzip  durch  das  Autoritatsprinzip  erganzt.  Darauf 
laufen  auch  die  in  grosseren  Verbanden  unentbehrlichen  reprasenta- 
tiven  Einrichtungen  hinaus,  kraft  deren  anstatt  der  regelmassig 
auf  den  Vollzug  von  Wahlen  beschrankten  Gesamtheit  der  stimm- 
berechtigten  Mitglieder  engere  Versammlungen  oder  Kollegien,  die 
nach  organischer  Auffassung  keineswegs  Vollmachttrager  der 
Gesamtheit,  sondern  unmittelbare  Willensorgane  des  Gemeinwesens 


334  O.  v.  Gierke  [xvi 

sind,  zur  Bildung  des  Gemeinwillens  berufen  werden.  Gilt  fiir  ihre 
Beschlussfassungen  wiederum  das  Majoritatsprinzip,  so  kann  es 
unmoglich  mehr  als  ein  Organisationsprinzip  fiir  einen  Teil  des 
Gesamtorganismus  bedeuten.  Soweit  nun  aber  das  Majoritats- 
prinzip kraft  der  geschichtlich  entwickelten  positiven  Rechtsordnung 
gilt,  hangt  von  dieser  auch  sowohl  seine  Ausgestaltung,  wie  seine 
Begrenzung  ab.  Hinsichtlich  seiner  Ausgestaltung  sind  man- 
cherlei  Einrichtungen  darauf  berechnet,  die  Uberwindung  der 
wahren  Mehrheit  durch  eine  bloss  scheinbare  Mehrheit  zu  ver- 
hindern.  So  die  Anforderungen  an  die  Beschlussfahigheit  von 
Versammlungen,  die  Verhaltniswahlen,  die  Abstimmungs-  oder 
Wahlpflicht.  Andere  Einrichtungen  aber  zielen  auf  Ermassigung 
des  tibergewichtes  der  grosseren  Zahl  ab.  Dahin  gehoren  alle 
Einschrankungen  des  Kreises  der  stimmberechtigten  Mitglieder, 
alle  Abstufungen  des  Stimmgewichts  nach  Fahigkeit,  Bildung 
oder  Besitz  durch  Klassenbildung  oder  Pluralstimrnen,  alle  Gliede- 
rungen  der  Abstimmung  nach  Korporationen  oder  Berufsstanden. 
Sie  alle  sind,  wenn  die  Gleichsetzung  des  Gesamtwillens  mit  dem 
Mehrheitswillen  durchgefiihrt  wird,  verwerfliche  Falschungen  des 
Gesamtwillens.  Dagegen  kann  die  organische  Verbandsauffassung 
dem  mechanischen  Kopfzahlprinzip  keine  Allgemeingiiltigkeit 
zusprechen.  Eine  Begrenzung  des  Majoritatsprinzips  liegt  in 
den  Bestimmungen,  nach  denen  es  zu  gewissen  Beschliissen  einer 
verstarkten  oder  qualifizierten  Mehrheit  oder  gar  der  Einstimmig- 
keit  bedarf.  Wird  hierdurch  oder  durch  andere  Mittel  eine  Minder- 
heit  in  den  Stand  gesetzt,  einen  Mehrheitsbeschluss  zu  verhindern, 
so  neigt  dariiber  hinaus  gerade  das  neueste  Recht  auch  zur  Aner- 
kennung  positiver  Minderheitsrechte,  die  eine  Minderheit  von 
bestimmter  Starke  befahigen,  in  gewissen  Fallen  wirksam  fiir  das 
Ganze  zu  handeln  und  so  als  Organ  der  Verbandsperson  zu  funk- 
tionieren.  Im  Sinne  der  Herleitung  des  Majoritatsprinzips  aus  dem 
Wesen  der  Verbande  sind  solche  Einrichtungen  offenbar  irrationell. 
Selbstverstandlich  wird  endlich  durchweg  die  Geltung  des  Majori- 
tatsprinzips durch  die  Unantastbarkeit  der  Sonderrechte  begrenzt. 
Hier  aber  handelt  es  sich  um  die  Schranken,  die  im  Sinne  unserer 
Rechtsordnung  aller  Verbandsmacht  iiberhaupt  gezogen  sind,  weil 
jeder  Verband  die  ihm  eingegliederten  Menschen  nur  hinsichtlich 
eines  Teiles  ihrer  Wesenheit  in  sich  schliesst  und  dariiber  hinaus 
ihre  freie  Einzelpersonlichkeit  unberiihrt  lasst.  Die  Sonderrechte 


xvi]  Majoritdtsprinzip  335 

aber  fallen,  auch  wenn  sie  im  Verbandsrechte  wurzeln,  in  die  den 
Mitgliedern  vorbehaltenen  Individualbereiche.  Darum  kann  iiber 
sie  nicht  einmal  ein  einstimmiger  Korperschaftsbeschluss  verfUgen. 
Vielmehr  ist  dazu  die  Mitwirkung  eines  individuellen  Zustimmungs- 
aktes  erforderlich. 

So  ist  inder  Tat  fur  die  historisch-organische  Betrachtungs- 
weise  das  Majoritatsprinzip  zwar  ein  bedeutungsvoller  Faktor  fiir 
den  Aufbau  der  Verbande,  aber  fiir  sich  allein  zur  Gestaltung 
lebendiger  sozialer  Korper  nicht  befahigt.  Sein  Geltungsbereich 
kann  nicht  rationell,  sondern  nur  geschichtlich  begriindet,  sein 
Wert  nicht  absolut  bestimmt,  sondern  nur  nach  seiner  jeweiligen 
Wirkungsweise  im  organischen  Leben  der  Gemeinwesen  bemessen 
werden. 

OTTO  VON  GIERKE. 


XVII 

UNE   ANTITHESE    DU    PRINCIPE 
MAJORITAIRE    EN    DROIT    POLONAIS1 

QuiCONQUE  connait  tant  soit  peu  Phistoire  de  Pologne,  ou  qui 
pretend  seulement  la  connaitre,  devinera  aisement  que  par  «  Panti- 
these  du  principe  majoritaire»  nous  entendons  le  trop  fameux 
liberum  veto.  On  salt  bien  en  quoi  consistait  cette  institution 
bizarre,  unique,  semble-t-il,  dans  son  genre :  elle  donnait  a  chaque 
depute"  le  droit  de  rompre  la  diete  et  a  chaque  gentilhomme  celui 
de  rompre  la  di£tine.  Cependant,  les  connaissances  de  la 
litterature  europeenne  ne  vont  guere  au  dela  de  cette  definition. 
Le  veto  tenait  parmi  les  institutions  polonaises  une  place  aussi 
centrale  que  le  principe  majoritaire  dans  la  vie  constitutionnelle 
des  e"tats  modernes  :  il  faisait,  selon  Montesquieu,  « 1'objet »  meme 
de  la  constitution  de  Pologne.  II  entraina  la  ruine  de  1'ind^pendance 
de  la  Pologne,  mais  non  pas  celle  de  sa  nationality  ni  de 
sa  civilisation  distincte.  II  plongea  le  pays  dans  une  affreuse 
anarchic,  mais  lui-meme  n'etait  pas  1'anarchie. 

1  Get  article  resume  d'une  maniere  generate  la  deuxieme  partie  d'un  livre 
polonais  qui  va  paraitre  en  1914  sous  le  titre  :  Liberum  veto.  La  premiere 
partie  sera  consacree  a  1'examen  de  1'origine  et  du  developpement  du  principe 
majoritaire,  surtout  en  Angleterre,  en  France,  en  Allemagne,  en  Suisse  et  en 
Aragon.  L'auteur  conceit  parfaitement  rinsuffisance  des  sources  a  portee 
d'un  specialiste  isole,  ainsi  que  la  necessite  du  concours  des  savants  de  tous  les 
pays,  pour  aprofondir  ce  probleme  obscur  et  complique.  En  communiquant 
cette  esquisse  au  Congres  de  Londres,  nous  avons  tente  d'occasionner  une 
discussion  internationale  sur  la  majorite"  et  le  liberum  veto,  sans  laquelle  les 
efforts  des  erudits  isoles  resteront  dans  ce  domaine  peu  fructueux.  Aussi 
nous  osons  nous  adresser  par  1'intermediaire  de  cette  publication  a  tous  ses 
lecteurs,  pour  les  prier  de  nous  faire  envoyer  leurs  remarques  supplementaires 
ou  critiques.  En  revanche  de  cette  complaisance,  nous  esperons  pouvoir 
offrir  une  version  frangaise  de  la  premiere  partie  de  notre  livre  a  la  disposition 
de  tous  nos  collegues  qui  voudront  bien  nous  fournir  quelques  contributions. 

336 


xvn]  Principe  Majoritaire  337 

Au  point  de  vue  pratique  c'e"tait  une  folie,  mais  une  de  ces 
folies  dont  on  peut  dire  avec  le  vieux  Polonius : 

Though  this  be  madness,  yet  there  is  method  in  't. 

Et  c'est  justement  grace  a  sa  propre  «  me"thode  »  de  deVeloppe- 
ment,  grace  a  sa  propre  m^thode  d'application  pratique  et  syste"- 
matique,  grace  a  cette  me"thode  de  se  combiner  pendant  200  ans 
avec  1'existence  morale  et  politique  d'une  nation,  que  le  veto 
me"rite  1'attention  du  monde  savant  de  1'Europe.  II  le  me"rite  aussi 
pour  une  raison  plus  gene"rale,  bien  qu'ici  secondaire.  Inte"ressante 
par  elle-meme,  1'histoire  du  veto  reflate  a  1'inverse  1'influence  de 
ces  memes  facteurs  qui  sur  un  autre  terrain  ont  conduit  au 
triomphe  du  principe  du  nombre.  Jusqu'a  un  certain  moment 
le  deVeloppement  du  liberum  veto  est  identique  avec  l'e"tablis- 
sement  du  principe  de  1'unanimite",  et  jusqu'a  cette  date  on  se 
demande  plutot  pourquoi  le  principe  majoritaire  ne  s'est-il  pas 
e"tabli  en  Pologne,  au  lieu  de  se  demander  d'ou  provient  le  liberum 
veto. 

Plus  tard,<  l'e"tendue  et  la  force  de  son  fonctionnement  s'e"lar- 
gissent  d'une  maniere  nouvelle  et  imprevue  qui  ne  re"sulte  point  des 
causes  qui  ont  agi  contre  le  regime  majoritaire.  Ainsi  d'une 
simple  negation  il  se  transforme  en  1'antithese  de  la  majorite". 
La  premiere  phase  s'e"tend  jusqu'a  la  moitie"  du  xvile  siecle,  et 
correspond  a  la  phase  que  le  parlement  anglais  parait  avoir 
traversed  a  la  fin  du  XIIP  siecle  et  a  celle  que  les  Etats  Ge"ne"raux 
de  France  avaient  traversed  sous  les  premiers  Valois. 

Dans  1'espace  de  cette  premiere  pe"riode  la  procedure  doit  etre 
essentiellement  la  meme  pour  le  terrain  polonais,  anglais  ou 
espagnol.  II  s'agit  de  d£couvrir  quelles  sont  les  influences  qui 
permettent  au  plus  grand  nombre  d'imposer  ses  decisions  a  la 
minorit^  et  de  constater  si  ces  influences  agissaient  pre"cise"ment 
en  Pologne.  L'induction  et  la  deduction,  le  raisonnement  par 
analogic  et  a  contrario^  concourent  ici  a  decouvrir  des  rapports  de 
cause  a  effet,  pour  ne  pas  dire  «  des  lois  »,  d'apres  lesquels  on  peut, 
en  observant  toutes  les  precautions,  reconstruire  meme  des  faits,  a 
d^faut  de  sources  imm£diates  suffisantes.  Nous  croyons  pouvoir 
nous  dispenser  d'exposer  nos  observations  sur  ce  sujet  a  mesure 
qu'elles  se  sont  pr^sent^es  a  notre  esprit :  il  sera  plus  a  propos 
d'exposer  la  these  definitive  en  l'e"claircissant  par  des  exemples. 

z 


338  W.  Konopczynski  [xvn 

Le  point  de  depart  de  1'evolution  assez  homogene  en  Pologne 
et  dans  TEurope  occidentale  est  cet  etat  primitif  ou  il  n'existe 
aucune  regie  pour  former  la  volonte  generale.  La  decision  incon- 
testable y  provient  de  la  concordance  effective  de  toutes  les 
volontes,  lorsque  personne  ne  proteste,  ni  au  cours  des  delibe"ra- 
tions,  ni  pendant  1'execution  de  ce  qui  a  e"t£  r£solu.  Le  point 
final  du  deVeloppement  des  institutions  chez  nous  et  en  Occident 
n'est  pas  le  meme :  en  Pologne  on  aboutira  a  appliquer  la  regie 
d'unanimite  a  toutes  les  deliberations,  pendant  que  le  reste  de 
1'Europe,  excepte  1'Aragon  et  la  Catalogne,  adoptera  le  regime 
majoritaire,  a  moins  qu'il  ne  se  soumette  a  la  royaute  etablie. 

Comment  expliquer  cette  difference  singuliere  ?  Et,  en  general, 
comment  se  forme  partout  le  principe  majoritaire  ? 

II  ne  fut  octroye"  nulle  part,  ni  emprunte  a  des  Strangers ;  tout 
au  moins  limitation  ne  fut  jamais  assez  puissante  pour  dominer 
les  vieilles  habitudes  dereglees.  Ce  principe  ne  resulte  necessaire- 
ment  d'aucune  the"orie  universellement  reconnue ;  il  ne  fut  jamais 
1'objet  d'une  propagande  suivie. 

Seules  la  force  normative  de  1'habitude  et  celle  du  fait  accompli 
peuvent  nous  fournir  une  explication  r£elle.  Tout  ce  qui  se  re"pete 
plusieurs  fois  s'appelle  normal,  et  tout  ce  qui  est  normal  fait  une 
norme.  Ceci  parait  un  sophisme  ou  un  sorite  mal  construit,  mais 
c'est  par  cette  voie  que  le  sentiment  du  droit  se  re"concilie  avec  la 
force  ouverte  de  la  foule.  Voila  comment  il  faut  entendre  1'opinion 
qui  pretend  que  le  droit  de  la  majorite  repose  sur  la  force :  il 
repose  sur  une  longue  serie  d'antece"dents. 

Reste  a  savoir  dans  quelles  conditions  la  superiority  du  plus 
grand  nombre  devient  constante  et  par  consequent  normale.  II 
faut  a  cet  effet  un  concours  special  de  conjonctures  favorables, 
dont  aucune  separ£ment  ne  suffirait  pour  expliquer  la  genese  du 
principe  du  plus  grand  nombre,  mais  dont  les  combinaisons  semblent 
1'expliquer  suffisamment. 

i°.  D'abord,  le  vote  a  la  majorite  des  voix  suppose  un 
denombrement  des  suffrages  census  e"gaux  en  principe.  Les 
groupements  primitifs  connaissent  une  coutume  r£pandue  de 
ponderer  les  suffrages :  les  volontes  des  elements  nombreux  mais 
peu  signifiants  ont  une  moindre  valeur  que  celles  de  quelques  gens 
riches,  braves  et  accredites.  Au  fur  et  a  mesure  que  les  elements 
les  plus  forts  se  concentrent  en  un  college  special  et  que  les  plus 


xvn]  Principe  Majoritaire  339 

faibles  (quoique  nombreux)  se  re"duisent  a  un  autre  ou  a  plusieurs 
autres  niveaux,  on  rencontre  dans  chaque  college  a  part  la  question 
du  calcul  des  suffrages  de  premiere  classe,  de  deuxieme  classe,  etc. 
Dans  Thistoire  des  elections  allemandes  la  fixation  du  principe 
majoritaire  coi'ncide  avec  Pdtablissement  du  college  des  electeurs. 
II  est  permis  de  supposer  que  dans  les  Chambres  anglaises  ce 
principe  ne  se  serait  pas  £tabli  aussi  facilement  sans  la  division  de 
la  noblesse  en  pairs  et  chevaliers  de  comtes. 

Or,  malgre  toute  la  distance  qui  separe  la  Pologne  du  XVP  et  du 
XVir  siecle  de  celle  de  Pe"tat  primitif,  il  ne  faut  pas  oublier  que  les 
dietes  et  di£tines  polonaises  e"taient  le  rendez-vous  de  la  petite 
noblesse  ainsi  que  des  grands  seigneurs,  puissants  comme  les 
princes  de  PEmpire,  qui  ne  se  sentaient  point  les  e"gaux  de  la 
petite  szlachta.  Aussi  le  liberum  veto  devint  en  re"alite,  entre  les 
mains  des  grands  seigneurs,  un  instrument  de  lutte  centre  la  majorite". 

2°.  Le  nivellement  des  votants  une  fois  accompli,  il  est  in- 
dispensable qu'un  certain  ordre  de  deliberations  s'etablisse  dans  le 
groupe  en  question.  Les  pr£ce"dents  en  faveur  de  la  majorite"  ou 
centre  elle  ne  pourront  se  produire  sans  que  tout  le  monde  ne 
voie  bien  que  c'est  pre"cis£ment  la  majorite  qui  remporte  la  victoire 
et  que  ce  n'est  pas  la  minority  qui  au  cours  des  d£bats  accede 
insensiblement  a  la  majorite",  reconstituant  par  la  les  apparences  de 
Punanimite". 

En  Pologne  le  reglement  des  dietes  s'elabora  dans  la  pe>iode 
ou  la  victoire  penchait  du  c6t£  du  principe  de  Punanimite.  En 
attendant  il  se  forma  une  notion  confuse  des  resolutions  semi- 
obligatoires  auxquelles  les  palatinats  mecontents  accedaient  apres 
coup. 

3°.  Rien  n'inspire  une  telle  solidarity  et  une  telle  discipline  que 
le  danger  menagant  PEtat  entier  ou  au  moins  une  de  ses  corpora- 
tions ;  c'est  lui  qui  force  a  effacer  les  dissensions  intestines  et  a  ne 
tenir  aucun  compte  de  Popposition  vaincue. 

La  Pologne  jouissait  au  XVIe  siecle  d'une  tranquillity  absolue 
du  c6t£  de  POccident ;  sa  puissance  tenait  encore  POrient  en 
respect :  la  R£publique  put  se  permettre  de  ne  pas  user  de  violence 
a  P£gard  des  opposants.  Au  surplus,  la  classe  dominante,  c'est- 
a-dire  la  noblesse,  se  vit  hors  de  la  concurrence  avec  les  autres 
classes :  elle  n'avait  plus  centre  qui  manifester  sa  solidarity  ou 
dissimuler  son  peu  de  discipline  interne.  Cela  a  puissamment 


340  W.  Konopczynski  [xvn 

pousse  aux  exces  les  mecontents  tant  au  cours  des  dietes  ou 
die"tines  qu'apres  leur  separation. 

4°.  Des  crises  reVolutionnaires,  grace  a  leur  caractere  peu 
tolerant,  attaquent  vigoureusement  l'inde"pendance  des  partis  et 
des  corporations.  Elles  soulevent  dans  les  partis  pre"ponderants  des 
passions  qui  leur  font  oublier  tous  les  scrupules  constitutionnels 
envers  leurs  adversaires.  La  Pologne  a  subi  au  XVF  siecle  une 
crise  religieuse ;  et  ce  fut  justement  alors,  sous  Sigismond 
Auguste,  que  la  majorit£  protestante  donna  le  branle  a  la  chambre 
des  nonces ;  quelquefois  elle  sembla  etre  prete  a  faire  ce  coup  de 
force  salutaire,  dont  les  suites  eussent  £te"  incalculables  pour 
1'avenir  de  la  Re"publique.  Malheureusement  ce  coup  de  force 
manqua — la  vague  protestante  recula,  et  la  crise  se  dissipa  sans 
avoir  gue"ri  PEtat  de  ses  infirmite's. 

5°.  Suivons  ce  meme  raisonnement.  A  P£poque  de  la  reunion 
des  premieres  di£tines  et  dietes  tous  les  m£contents  pouvaient  se 
transporter  en  Volhynie,  en  Podolie  et  ensuite  en  Ukraine.  II 
n'existait  aucune  categoric  de  gens  forces  a  s'incliner  devant  les 
decisions  de  la  majorite"  pre"ponderante,  et  pour  celle-ci  il  n'existait 
aucun  adversaire  la  tenant  en  eVeil.  Quand  la  possibilite  de  cette 
emigration  cessa,  le  principe  se"duisant  de  l'unanimit£  etait  deja  bien 
enracine\ 

6°.  A  cette  contexture  de  circonstances  imprevues  s'en  ajoutent 
d'autres  qui  furent  plus  ou  moins  durables  mais  qui  paraissent 
comme  fatalement  assorties  pour  de"biliter  les  dements  centralisa- 
teurs  du  parlementarisme  polonais.  Le  vote  electoral  ou  stricte- 
ment  legislatif,  de  meme  que  celui  sur  les  questions  internationales, 
contribue  assez  bien  a  accumuler  des  pre"ce" dents  favorables  a  la 
formation  du  regime  majoritaire.  Les  affaires  financieres  et 
militaires  sont  moins  propres  a  atteindre  ce  re"sultat.  En  effet,  la 
majorit£  peut  ais^ment  imposer  son  roi  au  pays  ou  son  depute^  a 
une  circonscription  electorale,  car  les  opposants  osent  rarement  elire 
un  contre-roi  ou  meme  un  contre-d£pute\  On  peut  facilement 
contraindre  les  mecontents  a  reconnaitre  soit  une  nouvelle  magis- 
trature,  soit  une  nouvelle  administration  royale,  soit  un  nouveau 
traite"  ratifi£  centre  leur  gre".  Mais  il  est  difficile  de  lever  des 
impdts  directs  ou  de  convoquer  un  arriere-ban,  si  les  opposants 
r^sistent  activement,  ou  meme  passivement.  En  g£ne"ral,  si  1'execu- 
tion  d'une  decision  commune  se  laisse  e"mietter,  ou  si  elle  depend 


xvn]  Principe  Majorit air e  341 

du  concours  d'£lements  r£fractaires,  on  risque  de  cr£er  un  antecedent 
prejudicial  e  a  la  majorite.  C'est  justement  ce^  qui  arriva  en 
Pologne  sous  Sigismond  Ier  (1507-48)  au  moment  ou  les  destinies 
du  parlementarisme  subissaient  une  epreuve  dangereuse :  les  dietines 
particulieres  rejeterent  coup  sur  coup  les  impots,  ainsi  que  la  nouvelle 
organisation  militaire  qui  avait  ete  pr^c^demment  agreee  a  la  dicte 
generate  par  la  plupart  des  nonces,  et  le  gouvernement  dut  plier 
devant  cet  obstacle. 

7°.  La  resistance  aux  mesures  financieres  des  dietes  n'aurait 
pas  entraine  des  consequences  prejudiciables  au  parlementa- 
risme central  si  la  majority  avait  trouve  dans  le  pouvoir  royal 
un  ferme  point  d'appui  et  une  garantie  de  Tex^cution  de  ses 
decisions,  comme  cela  eut  lieu  en  Angleterre  et  en  France.  Ami 
ou  ennemi,  inspirateur  ou  adversaire  des  etats,  le  pouvoir  royal 
donnait  partout  et  toujours  de  la  consistance  aux  corps  deliberants 
et  les  obligeait  de  renoncer  au  principe  de  1'unanimite.  En  Pologne 
cet  appui  salutaire  fit  deTaut  a  la  representation  nationale. 

8°.  Enfin,  le  dernier  et  peut-etre  le  plus  grand  obstacle  ne  fut 
pas  epargne  aux  dietes  de  Pologne.  Nous  voulons  dire  le  mandat 
imperatif,  appele  chez  nous  « instruction  de  nonce ».  Selon  une 
opinion  assez  r£pandue,  cette  entrave  aurait  pu  par  elle-meme  faire 
fourvoyer  la  machine  parlementaire  et  cr£er  le  liberum  veto.  On 
sait  que  la  diete  g^n^rale  se  forma  grace  a  la  jonction  des  delega- 
tions des  dietines  en  assembiees  provinciales  et  de  ces  dernieres  en 
un  seul  corps.  En  principe  les  tendances  particularistes  terriennes 
devaient  s'effacer  au  centre  de  la  province  pour  disparaitre  entiere- 
ment  dans  la  volonte  de  1'assembiee  pieniere  des  etats.  La  realite 
dementit  ces  esperances.  Loin  de  rompre  Tindividualite  des  dietines, 
les  assembiees  provinciales  leur  servirent  de  bouclier  centre  Tautorite 
de  la  nation  entiere ;  ayant  sauve  Tindependance  des  palatinats, 
elles  disparurent,  comme  inutiles.  Grace  a  1'intervention  de  ces 
assembiees,  les  dietines  tinrent  tete  a  la  diete  pendant  la  crise  deja 
signaiee  sous  les  deux  premiers  rois  Sigismonds.  Leurs  « instruc- 
tions »,  appuyees  par  la  menace  d'une  resistance  a  main  armee  des 
grands  palatinats,  montrerent  une  vigueur  infiniment  plus  energique 
que  celle  dont  portent  temoignages  les  cahiers  frangais,  issus  des 
petites  circonscriptions  eiectorales  (bailliages  ou  senechaussees). 
La  diete  prit  Tair  plutot  d'un  congres  de  deiegues  avec  un  pouvoir 
limite  que  d'une  assembiee  nationale  representative  et  souveraine. 


342  IV.  Konopczynski  [xvn 

Sans  doute,  les  mandats  eux-memes  n'auraient  jamais  empeche 
le  regime  majoritaire,  comme  ils  ne  1'ont  pas  empeche  en  France. 
Mais  ce  re"sultat  fut  inevitable  faute  de  tendances  permanentes 
centralisatrices  au  sein  de  la  diete  generate,  et  a  defaut  de  tout 
autre  facteur  sur  lequel  la  majorite  aurait  pu  s'appuyer.  Ainsi 
1'individu,  couvert  par  le  mandat  impe"ratif,  commenga  a  opposer  son 
veto  a  1'accord  du  reste  de  1'assembiee,  et  cela  meme  dans  les  cas  qui 
n'etaient  pas  regies  d'avance  par  ^instruction  ».  L'unanimitedes  man- 
dats imperatifs  se  transforma  peu  a  peu  en  unanimite  de  personnes. 

Resumons  nos  remarques  anterieures.  Le  concours  de  huit 
circonstances,  a  savoir  : 

i°,  1'inegalite  de  fait  des  personnes  participant  aux  dietes  et 
aux  dietines ; 

2°,  1'elaboration  tardive  et  insuffisante  d'un  reglement  pour 
les  deliberations ; 

3°,  1'inexistence  de  toute  pression  du  dehors ; 

4°,  la  faiblesse  des  conflits  intestins ; 

5°,  la  possibility  d'e"migration  des  mecontents  en  masse  dans 
d'autres  provinces  de  la  Republique ; 

6°,  la  nature  divisible  et  susceptible  d'empechement  des  pre- 
mieres decisions  des  dietes ; 

7°,  la  faiblesse  du  pouvoir  executif  separ£  ; 

8°,  la  puissance  des  dietines  et  1'importance  de  leurs  mandats, — 
tout  cela  cre"a  vers  la  fin  de  la  dynastie  des  Jagellons  une  imposante 
se"rie  d'ant^cedents,  apres  lesquels  le  parlementarisme  polonais  ne 
pouvait  sortir  de  sa  stagnation  vers  le  regime  majoritaire, — qu'au 
prix  d'une  revolution  violente. 

Les  trois  interregnes  apres  1 572  ne  firent  qu'aggraver  Tincertitude 
des  principes  centripetes  et  centrifuges  dans  la  constitution  de 
la  Pologne.  Si  les  palatinats  aspiraient  a  la  souverainet£  et 
pr^tendaient  a  gouverner  la  diete,  on  s'en  pouvait  tirer,  en  sub- 
stituant  a  la  forme  quasi  unitaire  de  TEtat  le  fe"de"ralisme  pur  a  1'instar 
des  Provinces -Unies.  Une  semblable  decomposition  aurait  et^ 
une  consequence  naturelle  'et  saine  des  instructions  imperatives. 
Mais  les  interregnes  acheverent  de  fermer  cette  issue.  La  nombreuse 
noblesse  polonaise  remportait  de  ces  immenses  assembles  electorales 
un  sentiment  rafifermi  de  son  unite.  D'un  autre  c6te,  quiconque 
prenait  une  part  personnelle  (yiritiiri)  a  1'eiection,  se  considerait  a 
juste  titre  comme  titulaire  immediat  et  auteur  de  la  souverainete 


xvn]  Principe  Majoritaire  343 

nationale :  il  contractait,  conjointement  avec  ses  pairs,  les  pactes 
fondamentaux  avec  le  roi,  done  il  ne  connaissait  point  d'instance 
intermediate  entre  lui  et  le  chef  d'Etat  elu  a  runanimite".  S'il  a 
conserve  rinte"grite"  de  sa  souverainete"  personnelle  sur  le  champ 
electoral,  il  la  gardera  d'autant  plus  facilement  centre  le  plus  grand 
nombre  a  la  die" tine.  Aussi  ce  ne  fut  que  depuis  1572  que  le 
principe  de  1'unanimite'  commenga  a  infecter  les  di£tines. 

Or,  vers  la  fin  du  XVP  siecle  trois  principes  fondamentaux  se 
sont  e"tablis  dans  le  droit  public  de  la  Pologne : 

Personne  ne  peut  devenir  roi  sans  une  Election  libre  et  unanime 
par  la  noblesse ; 

Aucun  projet  ne  deviendra  loi  sans  1'accord  unanime  du  roi,  du 
senat  et  des  nonces  terriens  donnant  leurs  votes  selon  la  teneur 
des  mandats ; 

Aucune  proposition  ne  pourra  etre  adopte"e  par  la  die"tine  que 
du  consentement  de  tous  les  gentilshommes  qui  y  sont  presents. 
Certainement,  ce  sont  la  des  principes  sans  exemple  dans  1'Europe 
moderne,  excepte  dans  le  royaume  d'Aragon  et  la  principaute" 
de  Catalogne.  Us  meconnaissent  entierement  1'autorite  du  plus 
grand  nombre ;  ils  sont  ge*ne"raux  et  absolus.  Us  convergent 
dans  1'idee  d'un  libre  accord  (consensus)  embrassant  toutes  especes 
de  decisions  collectives.  Ils  contrastent  avec  toute  sorte  de  de"cret 
judiciaire  (decretd]  soumis  a  la  majorite"  des  suffrages.  Ces  principes 
agissent,  en  theorie,  dans  1'ordre  normal  sans  restriction,  quoique 
en  pratique  les  exceptions  n'aient  pas  e"te  rares. 

D'ailleurs,  quelque  nombreuses  qu'aient  e"te"  ces  exceptions,  il 
est  e"tonnant  que  la  nation  ait  pu  vivre  sous  une  telle  constitution 
pendant  deux  siecles.  On  recourait,  il  est  vrai,  dans  les  cas 
extremes  au  lien  d'une  confederation,  c'est-a-dire,  a  une  convention 
qui  suspendait  Texigence  de  Tunanimite  et  soumettait  les  matieres 
les  plus  difficiles  aux  decisions  majoritaires  appelees  sancita.  Jean- 
Jacques  Rousseau  pouvait  s'exprimer  a  ce  propos  que  la  Pologne 
vivait  en  regie  dans  1'etat  de  nature,  ou  il  n'y  avait  qu'une  «  volonte 
de  tous>>,  et  ne  contractait  le  pacte  social  qu'en  cas  d'urgence,  pour 
cre"er  «la  volont^  g^nerale)).  Toutefois,  meme  si  Ton  prend  en  ligne 
de  compte  les  nombreux  abus  ou  les  minorites  etaient  reduites  au 
silence,  on  ne  saurait  me"connaitre  chez  les  Polonais  au  xvie  et  au 
XVII6  siecle  une  flexibility  speciale  vers  cet  accord  unanime  dont  le 
resultat  fut  les  quatre  grands  Volumina  Legum.  II  est  incontestable 


344  ^  Konopczynski  [xvn 

que  cet  ideal  sublime  d'une  « union  des  esprits »  (unio  animorum) 
e"levait  les  multitudes  a  une  abnegation  altruiste ;  les  generations 
successives  apprenaient  sous  son  influence  a  joindre  la  liberte  et 
l'e"galite"  a  une  fraternite"  inconnue  ailleurs,  et  a  retenir  Pe"goisme 
dont  les  exces  auraient  fle"tri  et  compromis  le  principe  meme 
d'unanimite".  Nier  tout  cela  serait  perdre  de  vue  Pensemble  et  le 
principal  pour  se  restreindre  au  particulier. 

Mais  tout  honneur  accorde"  aux  altruistes,  il  ne  convient  pas  de 
fermer  les  yeux  sur  Penvers  de  la  me"daille.  Nous  avons  mentionne" 
les  Volumina  Legum.  Us  sont  vraiment  volumineux,  mais  ils  le 
seraient  dix  fois  davantage  si  cette  forme  de  decision  difficile  et 
presque  impossible  n'eut  pas  gene"  1'initiative  des  nonces  ou  des 
dietines.  Evidemment  il  n'y  avait  qu'une  seule  voie  pour  obtenir 
1'accord :  c'e"tait  de  heurter  de  front  toute  la  chambre,  de  tenir 
ferme,  de  s'opposer  a  toute  autre  initiative,  jusqu'a  ce  qu'on  eut 
accede  aux  propositions  ainsi  violemment  soutenues.  L'entetement 
vaut  mieux  que  toutes  les  raisons.  Les  instructions  exigeaient 
souvent  des  choses  incompatibles  ou  difficiles  a  concilier ;  et  meme 
si  elles  ne  le  faisaient  pas,  elles  en  demandaient  trop  a  la  fois,  et 
parfois  plus  qu'il  n'e"tait  possible  de  faire  aboutir  pendant  les  six 
semaines  prescrites  par  la  loi.  De  la  une  obstruction  re"ciproque 
ouverte  ou  insidieuse  ;  de  la  des  tentatives  de  releguer  tout  ce  qu'il 
y  avait  de  plus  important  a  la  fin  des  seances,  afin  de  Pintroduire 
par  surprise  ou  contrebande ;  de  la  vers  la  cloture  des  stances  des 
abus  multiples  de  la  part  de  la  majorite",  abus  sans  lesquels  PEtat 
serait  reste"  souvent  sans  defense  ni  ressources. 

Peu  a  peu  les  contradicteurs  trouverent  un  moyen  efficace  pour 
resister  aux  tentatives  d'oppression  ou  de  suppression  :  on  n'avait 
qu'a  demander  acte  de  sa  protestation,  ou  bien,  d'apres  le  terme 
courant  en  Pologne :  a  porter  un  manifeste  au  greffe.  D'abord  ce 
fut  tout  un  parti  mecontent  qui  fit  signer  sa  protestation  par  une 
foule  d'opposants,  puis  des  individus  commencerent  a  suivre  cet 
exemple.  Enfin,  meme  a  Pepoque  de  la  pire  anarchic,  le  veto  par 
e"crit,  quoique  signe"  par  un  seul  nonce,  resta  Porgane  des  factions 
et  non  pas  des  individus.  En  vain  le  gouvernement  chercha-t-il  a 
refuser  Pacte  de  protestation.  Si  le  greffe  a  Varsovie  ou  a  Grodno 
etait  ferme",  il  y  en  avait  quantite"  d'autres  a  la  ported  des  mecontents. 

On  vit  de  plus  en  plus  souvent  les  dietes  se  dissoudre  sans 
avoir  obtenu  aucun  resultat.  L'union  des  esprits  demeurait  Pideal 


xvn]  Principe  Majoritaire  345 

de  la  nation,  mais  en  re"alit£  on  n'avait  qu'a  choisir  entre  la 
violation  de  ce  qu'on  appelait  «la  libert£  doree»  ou  le  prejudice 
de  1'Etat.  La  nation  ne  voulait  pas  se  decider  en  faveur  du 
fe"de"ralisme  pur  et  simple,  et  elle  ne  savait  pas  comment  instituer 
la  forme  unitaire  de  la  Republique.  Strictement,  1'infructuosite 
des  dietes  ne  r^sultait  pas  encore  d'une  anarchic:  c'£tait  la  negation 
suivie  du  principe  majoritaire  qui  conduisait  le  plus  re"gulierement 
du  monde  a  la  paralysie  de  1'Etat.  L'anarchie  fut  plutdt  le  fruit 
que  la  racine  du  liberum  veto.  Le  public  voyait  assez  bien  les 
dangers  du  desordre,  les  e"crivains  politiques  sonnaient  le  tocsin, 
mais  toutes  leurs  exhortations  ne  pouvaient  rien  centre  les 
tendances  des  deux  forces  sociales  oppos£es  a  la  reTorme :  les 
magnats  et  la  petite  noblesse.  Les  premiers,  ennemis  naturels 
de  1'Etat,  ne  pouvaient  que  perdre  leur  influence  sous  le  regime 
majoritaire;  1'autre  craignait  en  ce  cas  de  perdre  son  repos  et 
ses  prerogatives  au  profit  de  1'lttat ;  elle  se  contentait  de  sa 
toute-puissance  passive  et  apparente,  sans  aspirer  a  une  libert£  plus 
active,  mais  pe"rilleuse. 

Du  haut  de  sa  liberte  absolue  la  noblesse  polonaise  regardait 
avec  de"dain  ce  qui  s'appelait  liberte  publique  en  Europe,  sans  la 
prerogative  du  veto.  Au  cours  du  XVII6  siecle  elle  voyait  avec 
inquietude  la  lutte  partout  victorieuse  de  la  royaut£  de  droit  divin 
contre  les  privileges  des  classes  sociales.  Elle  voyait  la  moindre 
faiblesse  du  cot£  du  peuple  encourager  les  monarques  a  des 
empietements.  Hongrois,  Tcheques,  Allemands,  Danois,  Su£dois, 
sans  parler  des  Espagnols  et  des  Frangais,  tous  les  peuples  du 
continent  europe"en  qui  s'e"taient  pretes  a  la  regie  majoritaire 
tomberent  au  cours  de  ce  siecle  sous  le  joug  de  la  monarchic 
absolue.  La  Grande-Bretagne  paraissait  plonge"e  dans  des  guerres 
civiles.  En  presence  de  telles  experiences  pouvait-on  ne  pas  avoir 
Pillusion  que  1'unanimite  et  le  veto  constituaient  Punique  garantie 
contre  Pesclavage  ? 

Mais  le  torrent  de  la  vie  ne  s'arrete  pas.  Le  deVeloppement 
qui  tendait  a  e" lever  1'individu  au-dessus  de  1'Etat  n'avait  pas 
encore  atteint  son  terme.  Dans  la  sphere  de  la  conquete  des 
libert^s,  comme  partout,  le  mieux  reste  1'ennemi  du  bien.  Ayant 
re"alis£  la  negation  simple  du  principe  majoritaire,  le  parlemen- 
tarisme  polonais  se  pr£cipita  dans  son  antithese. 

Car  c'est  ainsi  qu'il  faut  qualifier  logiquement  la  pratique  qui 


346  IV.  Konopczynski  [xvn 

s'introduit  aux  dietes  de  Pologne  depuis  la  moitie  du  XVir  siecle, 
ainsi  que  la  th£orie  juridique  qui  devait  1'exprimer.  Pendant 
cette  deuxieme  phase  le  liberum  veto  commence  a  decapiter  des 
assemblees  entieres,  et  non  pas  seulement  leurs  projets.  On 
commence  a  rompre  les  deliberations.  Comment  y  est-on  parvenu? 
Quelle  a  et6  ici  la  «  methode »  de  notre  « folie »  parlementaire  ? 
L'explication  se  trouve,  d'un  cote,  dans  le  conflit  des  interets 
provinciaux  dont  nous  avons  parle*  plus  haut,  de  1'autre  dans  la 
structure  originaire  des  dietes.  On  a  pre"tendu  que  la  premiere 
rupture  de  diete  eut  lieu  en  1652.  En  verite  cette  diete  a  fonctionne" 
jusqu'a  son  terme  legal,  et  ne  fut  dissoute  qu'a  cause  d'une  opposition 
legitime  a  la  prolongation  des  seances.  Ce  n'est  pas  ce  qu'on 
peut  appeler  une  rupture.  Mais  ce  fait  arrive  en  1652  eut  un 
retentissement  dans  tous  les  palatinats.  II  demontra  clairement 
que  les  Etats  de  la  Republique  etaient  pr£ts  a  tout  sacrifier  pour 
1'amour  des  droits  individuels.  Alors  on  fit  un  pas  de  plus  en 
avant.  On  se  mit  a  protester  et  a  quitter  la  salle  des  seances 
avant  la  fin  de  la  diete.  Les  optimistes  pouvaient  attendre 
patiemment  jusqu'au  dernier  jour ;  les  pessimistes  qui  prevoyaient 
que  le  contradicteur  ne  se  laisserait  pas  flechir  rentraient  chez  eux 
desesperant  du  succes  de  la  diete. 

D'ou  venait  ce  desespoir  ?  Pourquoi  ne  sanctionnait-on  pas  au 
moins  cette  partie  des  projets  qui  n'etait  contestee  par  personne  ? 
C'est  qu'aucun  projet  ne  pouvait  passer  loi  avant  la  cloture 
solennelle  des  Etats.  La  diete  polonaise  ressemblait  a  un  congres 
ou  la  noblesse  obtenait  la  sanction  de  ses  demandes  en  echange 
du  consentement  qu'elle  donnait  aux  projets  legislatifs  du  roi,  et 
surtout  en  echange  des  contributions  publiques.  Si  une  partie  des 
contractants  proteste  et  s'absente  de  Tacte  de  conclusion,  tout  le 
marche  est  nul  et  de  nul  effet :  voila  pourquoi  dans  sa  nouvelle 
phase  le  liberum  veto>  lance  contre  telle  ou  telle  proposition,  a  une 
force  retroactive  contre  tous  les  actes  de  la  diete. 

Bientot  tous  les  palatinats  embrasserent  1'opinion  que  chaque 
particulier  avait  le  droit  de  fermer  la  bouche  a  Passembiee  de 
ses  egaux.  La  contagion  devint  generate,  elle  inonda  tous  les 
territoires,  renversant  toutes  les  digues.  Le  moindre  gentilhomme 
s'arrogea  le  droit  non  seulement  de  paralyser  les  decisions,  mais 
aussi  d'empecher  de  les  mettre  aux  voix.  Le  veto  envahit  meme 
les  territoires  qui  avaient  cru  s'en  garantir  en  admettant  dans 


xvn]  Principe  Majoritaire  347 

les  Elections  le  vote  majoritaire :  inutilement  alle"guait-on  cette  loi 
locale,  quand  le  contradicteur  ne  permettait  pas  meme  d'ouvrir  les 
debats !  En  1688  la  diete  ge"ne"rale  fut  rompue  pour  la  premiere 
fois  avant  rejection  du  marshal :  on  pourrait  dire  qu'alors  « la  libre 
voix  du  citoyen  »  eut  plus  de  valeur  que  le  reglement  de  la  diete ! 

Le  veto  devint  une  puissance  sans  bornes,  e"le"mentaire,  ante"- 
rieure  a  toute  constitution, — une  idole,  un  tonnerre  dans  les  mains 
de  milliers  d'insense's. 

Et  voila  1'antithese  du  principe  majoritaire  a  son  apogee. 

Baissons  le  rideau  sur  les  consequences  destructives  et  igno- 
minieuses  de  sa  domination.  Ce  triste  tableau  n'est  que  trop  bien 
connu ;  on  1'expose  fre"quemment  et  de  parti  pris,  pour  sugg£rer 
1'impression  que  la  Pologne  s'est  tue"e  elle-meTne  avant  qu'on  eut 
1'idee  d'abre"ger  son  agonie.  Jusqu'a  quel  point  et  jusqu'a  quelle 
e"poque  le  veto  domina-t-il  la  Pologne  du  consentement  des  Polonais, 
et  d'autre  part,  depuis  quand  fut-il  soutenu  par  la  force  e"trangere, 
pousse"e  jusqu'a  la  menace  de  la  guerre? — c'est  une  question  qui 
n'appartient  pas  a  1'examen  juridique  et  historique  de  son  origine 
ni  de  son  application. 

Mais  nous  nous  sentirions  coupable  d'avoir  confirme  une 
faussete",  si  nous  ne  rappelions  ici  le  fait  notoire  que  malgr£ 
Paveuglement  de  la  soci^te"  polonaise  avant  le  partage,  malgr£  les 
insinuations  envenime'es  des  voisins,  on  avait  trouve  le  chemin 
qui  conduisait  tout  droit  du  labyrinthe  de  la  « libert£  dore"e »  vers 
la  liberty  publique  moderne.  On  Pavait  trouve",  ce  chemin,  a  la 
lumiere  des  flambeaux  de  la  litte"rature  ^clair^e  du  XVIir  siecle ; 
on  avait  os^  y  marcher,  encourag£  par  Pexemple  de  cette  nation 
unique  qui  seule  avec  nous  et  avec  les  Hongrois,  mais  beaucoup 
mieux  que  nous  autres,  avait  su  conserver  le  tresor  de  ses  libert£s 
au  milieu  des  royaut£s  e"tablies,  —  par  Texemple  de  la  nation 
anglaise.  Prenant  pour  modele  les  lois  de  1'Angleterre,  la  Con- 
stitution du  3  mai  1791  a  aboli  d£finitivement  le  veto  en  de"pit  des 
garanties  e"trangeres,  mais  au  gre  de  tous  les  Polonais.  Elle  n'a 
pas  sauve  l'ind£pendance  de  la  R£publique,  mais  elle  est  arriv^e 
justement  a  temps  pour  sauver  1'ame  nationale  et  pour  donner  un 
dementi  aux  falsificateurs  d'histoire  qui  nous  imputent  un  suicide. 

W.  KONOPCZYNSKI. 


XVIII 

THE  MODERN  STUDY  OF  CANON 
LAW 

AFTER  Gratian,  in  the  eleventh  century,  separated  the  study 
of  Canon  Law  from  that  of  practical  theology,  Canon  Law 
formed,  with  Roman  Law  (utrumque  ius\  the  foundation  of  legal 
studies  in  the  universities  of  the  Middle  Ages. 

The  famous  Decretum  of  Gratian,  the  Concordia  Discordantium 
Canonum,  a  private  work,  which  had  obtained  recognition  in 
the  whole  Church,  was  the  object  of  a  series  of  commentaries 
(Summae  or  Stromae)  by  the  '  Decretists,'  who  were  followed  by 
the  '  Decretalists,'  the  commentators  of  the  official  collections  of 
Decretals,  which  formed  the  second  part  of  the  Corpus  Juris 
Canonici. 

This  great  scientific  elaboration  of  Canon  Law  corresponded  to 
its  importance  in  mediaeval  life.  Canon  Law  covered  at  that  time 
a  much  larger  field  than  in  later  periods.  It  was  international,  it 
was  Christian  and  therefore  universal,  and  it  was  essentially  con- 
servative. For  these  reasons  it  exercised  a  very  wide  influence 
upon  the  development  of  legal  theories  in  the  Middle  Ages  all  over 
the  Western  world. 

The  theory  of  sovereignty  and  of  the  relationship  between 
Church  and  State,  as  well  as  the  various  political  theories,  were 
largely  determined  by  the  Canonists,  as  the  Rev.  A.  J.  Carlyle 
has  demonstrated  recently  in  his  learned  book,  The  Political 
Theories  of  the  Middle  Ages.  But  at  the  same  time  private  law, 
the  systems  of  land  tenures,  and  especially  the  marriage  law — 
this  last  considered  by  the  Church  as  her  exclusive  and  absolute 
domain — were  under  the  direct  influence  of  Canon  Law.  Inter- 

348 


xvin]  Ecclesiastical  Law  349 

national  law  and  the  law  of  procedure  took  their  fundamental  ideas 
and  principles  from  Canon  Law ;  and  for  the  reason  that  many 
crimes  were  subject  to  ecclesiastical  jurisdiction  on  account  of  the 
element  of  '  sin '  connected  with  them,  the  law  of  the  Church  had  a 
decided  influence  on  the  development  of  penal  law.  The  social 
action  of  the  Church,  the  extension  of  her  property,  the  monastic 
institutions  and  the  philanthropic  work  connected  with  them, 
dominate  the  social  and  economic  history  of  the  Middle  Ages, 
and  carry  into  all  branches  of  mediaeval  life  the  influence  of  the 
legal  elements  of  ecclesiastical  ideas. 

Perhaps  in  no  other  period  of  history  have  the  doctrines 
of  the  Canonists  influenced  so  deeply  and  directly  the  formation 
of  the  law  of  the  Church  as  at  this  time,  when  Rolando  Bandinelli, 
the  eminent  decretist,  was  elected  Pope  under  the  name  of  Alex- 
ander III.,  and  Sinibaldo  Fieschi,  the  famous  decretalist,  ascended 
the  papal  throne  as  Innocent  IV. 

At  that  time  Canon  Law  emanated  chiefly  from  the  Papal 
authority.  But  when  the  occidental  schism  weakened  the  position 
of  the  Popes  and  created  the  necessity  for  an  appeal  from  the  con- 
tending Pontiffs  to  a  higher  authority,  in  order  to  re-establish  the 
unity  of  the  Church,  the  so-called  reformatory  Councils  of  Pisa 
(1409),  Constance  (141 1-18),  and  Basel  (1431)  tried  to  substitute  the 
authority  of  the  Council  for  that  of  the  Popes  in  ecclesiastical 
legislation,  and  to  assert  the  position  of  the  bishops  against  the 
supremacy  of  the  Popes  and  of  the  Roman  Court. 

But  if  those  Councils  did  not  succeed  in  establishing  an 
episcopal  system  against  the  Roman  supremacy,  their  canons 
were  partly  accepted  by  the  State  in  France  and  Germany.  The 
Popes  were  obliged  to  make  concessions  to  the  sovereigns,  under 
the  form  of  privileges  granted  to  them  by  the  various  Concordats 
of  the  end  of  the  fifteenth  century  and  the  beginning  of  the 
sixteenth  century. 

Thus,  at  the  end  of  the  Middle  Ages,  the  States  took  up  an 
independent  attitude  towards  the  Church,  and  a  radical  change 
was  brought  about  in  their  position  as  regards  ecclesiastical  matters 
by  the  Protestant  Reformation. 

The  Reformed  Churches  accepted  the  supremacy  of  the  State 
(ius  circa  sacra),  granting  to  sovereigns  a  large  ius  inspiciendi  et 
cavendi  in  their  internal  organizations.  At  the  same  time,  owing 


350  A.  Galante  [xvm 

to  the  fact  that  the  State  authorities  were  confronted  by  different 
denominations,  the  ecclesiastical  legislation  of  the  States  developed 
on  lines  independent  of  the  single  denominations,  and  in  con- 
sequence of  that,  there  arose,  besides  the  strictly  denominational 
canon  law,  an  ecclesiastical  law  of  the  State,  which  only  gradually 
and  with  great  difficulty  applied  the  principles  of  religious  liberty. 

Thus  a  new  field  opened  out  to  the  scientific  study  of  Canon 
Law.  After  the  decline  of  the  Commentators  of  the  Decretals, 
whose  last  works  show  a  lack  of  scientific  individuality  and  an 
excessive  predominance  of  casuistry  and  merely  practical  techni- 
cality, with  the  revival  of  humanistic  studies  France  is  the  leading 
country  in  the  study  of  Ecclesiastical  Law,  and  the  French  school 
can  boast  of  a  series  of  great  canonists,  from  Cujas  to  Thomassin, 
whose  works  are  strictly  connected  with  the  special  relationship  of 
State  and  Church  in  France. 

The  defence  of  the  Libertates  Ecclesiae  Gallicanae,  which  had  in 
the  Assemblies  du  Clerge  very  effective  means  of  safeguarding 
episcopal  rights,  led  to  the  formation  of  a  complete  system  of 
Droit  civil  ecclesiastique,  which  was  only  temporarily  interrupted 
by  the  French  Revolution. 

The  Council  of  Trent  (1545-63),  the  greatest  legislative  work 
of  the  Catholic  Church  in  modern  times,  marks  a  decided  return  to 
mediaeval  theories  of  papal  supremacy.  The  whole  Council  was 
presided  over  by  Papal  Delegates,  all  the  proposals  for  its  decisions 
came  from  Rome,  and  the  canons  of  the  Council  were  formally 
approved  and  promulgated  by  the  Pope. 

At  the  same  time  the  new  legislation  of  the  Council  of  Trent, 
covering  a  very  extensive  field  and  regulating  matters  of  vital 
importance  for  the  State,  as  was  the  case  with  the  marriage  law, 
brought  new  life  into  the  Canon  Law  and  the  studies  connected 
with  it. 

Cardinal  Bellarmino  (1542-1621)  and  Franciscus  Suarez  (1548- 
1617)  affirmed  the  papal  supremacy  in  a  new  form,  sustaining  the 
potestas  indirecta  of  the  Popes  in  temporal  matters  ;  and  the  seven- 
teenth century  witnessed  the  completion  of  the  Annals  of  Caesar 
Baronius  (d.  1607)  and  of  the  Italia  Sacra  of  Ferdinando 
Ughelli  (d.  1670),  while  Antonio  Augustino,  with  his  great  works, 
represents  for  Spain  the  humanistic  revival  of  the  study  of 
Canon  Law. 


xvmjj  Ecclesiastical  Law  35 1 

In  the  struggle  between  the  Papacy  and  different  States  in  the 
seventeenth  and  eighteenth  centuries  in  France,  in  Spain,  and  in 
Italy,  the  defenders  of  the  Erastian  theories  developed  a  whole 
system  of  ius  circa  sacra  of  the  State  towards  the  ecclesiastical 
institutions,  and  the  episcopal  theories  found  a  vigorous  support  in 
the  writings  of  Zeger  van  Espen  (d.  1728),  and  in  the  famous  De 
statu  ecclesiae,  which  John  Nikolaus  von  Hontheim  (d.  1790) 
published  in  1763  under  the  pseudonym  of  Febronius. 

In  Austria  those  Erastian  theories  were  accepted  by  Eybel, 
Pehem,  Riegger,  and  Rautenstrauch,  and  prepared  the  way  for  the 
great  ecclesiastical  reforms  of  Maria  Theresa  and  Joseph  II. 

Besides  the  political  writings  on  Canon  Law,  this  period 
also  produced  the  canonistic  works  of  Prospero  Lambertini 
(Benedict  XIV),  the  researches  of  the  Bishop  of  Oneglia,  Stefano 
Berardi,  and  of  the  brothers  Ballerini  of  Verona  on  the  sources  of 
Canon  Law ;  also  the  Prompta  Bibliotheca  of  Ferraris  and  the 
Theatrum  of  De  Luca,  the  first  encyclopaedic  works  covering  the 
whole  field  of  Canon  Law. 

The  revival  of  the  scientific  study  of  Ecclesiastical  Law  in  the 
nineteenth  century  is  due  to  Germany,  where  Karl  Friedrich 
Eichorn  in  his  Grundsatze  des  Kirchenrechts  der  katholischen  und 
der  evangelischen  Religionspartei  in  Deutschland  (Gottingen,  1831) 
applied  to  Canon  Law  the  principles  of  the  historical  school  of 
Savigny,  and  gave  a  systematic  exposition  of  Canon  Law  based 
on  its  natural  structure,  breaking  the  tradition  of  the  division  into 
personae,  res  et  actiones,  which,  since  Lancellotti,  had  dominated  the 
treatment  of  Ecclesiastical  Law. 

Thus  the  merely  dogmatic  study  of  Canon  Law  was  abandoned, 
and  greater  importance  given  to  the  historical  development  of 
ecclesiastical  institutions. 

The  next  phase  of  the  study  of  Ecclesiastical  Law  in  Germany 
is  closely  connected  with  the  works  of  Friedrich  von  Schulte,  Paul 
Hinschius,  and  Emil  Friedberg,  the  most  eminent  canonists  of  the 
period  of  the  so-called  Kulturkampf. 

Friedrich  von  Schulte,  who  later  was  one  of  the  founders  of  the  Old 
Catholic  movement,  edited  a  series  of  the  Summae  of  the  Decretists, 
and  recorded  in  a  monumental  work  (Geschichte  der  Quellen  und 
Literatur  des  kanonischen  Rechtes  von  Gratian  bis  auf  die  Gegen- 
wart,  Stuttgart,  1875  sq.)  the  works  on  Canon  Law  after  Gratian. 


352  ^4  -  Galante  [xvm 

To  Paul  Hinschius,  the  editor  of  the  Pseudoisidor,  canonistic 
science  owes  the  largest  and  most  exhaustive  treatise  on  Church 
Law  (System  des  Kirchenrechts,  6J  volumes,  Berlin,  1868-96),  which, 
although  not  completed,  will  remain  for  many  years  to  come  the 
basis  for  historical  researches  into  ecclesiastical  institutions. 

Of  the  multifarious  works  of  Friedberg  special  mention  must  be 
made  of  his  great  edition  of  the  Corpus  luris  Canonici^  after  the 
first  Editio  Lipsiensis  by  Emil  Ludwig  Richter. 

Thus  the  tradition  of  the  study  of  Canon  Law  was  kept  in 
Germany,  where,  even  in  distinctly  Protestant  States,  Canon  Law 
was — as  it  still  is — a  subject  of  lectures  and  examinations  not 
only  in  the  theological,  but  also  in  the  legal  Faculties ;  and 
the  German  school  of  Canon  Law  had  a  direct  influence  on  the 
revival  of  the  canonistic  studies  in  Italy. 

In  consequence  of  the  theories  of  separation  of  Church  and 
State  expressed  by  Cavour  in  his  famous  formula  Libera  Chiesa  in 
libero  Stato  ('  A  Free  Church  in  a  Free  State '),  and  only  partially 
applied  in  Italian  ecclesiastical  legislation,  the  Theological  Faculties 
at  the  State  Universities  in  the  Kingdom  of  Italy  were  suppressed 
in  1873,  and  the  teaching  of  Canon  Law  at  the  legal  faculties, 
although  not  formally  abolished,  was  practically  abandoned  for 
many  years. 

The  revival  of  the  study  of  Ecclesiastical  Law  in  Italy  was  due 
to  Francesco  Scaduto,  who  wrote  the  first  exhaustive  treatise  on 
modern  Italian  ecclesiastical  law  (Manuale  del  diritto  ecclesiastic^ 
2  ed.,  Turin,  1894),  and  to  Francesco  Ruffini,  whose  work  on 
Religious  Liberty  has  recently  been  translated  into  English.  They 
were,  with  their  various  writings,  the  pioneers  of  a  flourishing 
school  of  Canon  Law  which  has  now  been  restored  to  the  curri- 
culum of  all  legal  faculties  in  Italy. 

In  France  researches  into  Canon  Law  were  directed  mainly  to 
the  study  of  the  droit  civil  ecclesiastique.  Canon  Law  was  not  taught 
at  the  legal  faculties  as  an  independent  subject,  but  was  included 
partly  in  the  histoire  du  droit  and  in  the  droit  administratif. 

Among  the  most  valuable  contributions  of  French  science  to 
canonistic  subjects  in  modern  times  we  must  record  the  work  of 
Professor  Esmein  on  *  Marriage '  (Le  Mariage  en  droit  canonique, 
Paris,  1891  sq.),  and  the  different  works  on  canonistic  subjects  of 
the  Ecole  de  hautes  etudes. 


xvin]  Ecclesiastical  Law  353 

In  Austria  the  old  tradition  of  the  study  of  Canon  Law  has  been 
kept  up  at  the  theological  and  legal  faculties  of  all  the  Universities. 
To  the  last  generation  of  Austrian  canonists  belonged  Maassen, 
the  author  of  the  great  history  of  the  sources  of  Canon  Law  in  the 
earlier  centuries  of  the  Middle  Ages  (Geschichte  der  Quellen  und 
Literatur  des  kanonischen  Rechtes  im  Abendlande  bis  zum  Ausgang 
des  Mittelalters,  vol.  i.,  Graz,  1870),  and  I  may  point  out  that  one 
of  the  most  prominent  canonists  of  Austria,  Max  von  Hussareck,  is 
at  present  Minister  for  Public  Education  in  Vienna. 

In  Germany,  after  the  period  of  the  settlement  of  the  Kultur- 
kampf,  the  study  of  Canon  Law,  which  had  received  such  important 
assistance  from  the  kindred  studies  of  German  law  and  ecclesi- 
astical history  (I  need  only  recall  the  masterly  chapters  of  Gierke's 
Genossenschaftsrecht  dealing  with  ecclesiastical  corporations,  and 
Hauck's  Kirchengeschichte  Deutschlands),  seemed  for  a  moment  to 
stagnate  as  an  independent  science.  It  was  then  that  Ulrich  Stutz 
with  his  Geschichte  des  kirchlichen  Benefizialwesens  von  seinen 
Aufdngen  bis  auf  Alexander  III.  (Berlin,  1895)  marked  a  new  de- 
parture in  the  German  studies  of  Canon  Law.  With  a  wider  applica- 
tion of  historical  methods  than  had  previously  been  made,  and  with 
great  erudition,  Stutz  pointed  out  in  a  decisive  way  the  importance  of 
proprietary  churches  in  the  development  of  the  ecclesiastical  institu- 
tions of  the  Middle  Ages,  and  in  a  series  of  various  studies  investi- 
gated the  different  aspects  of  the  private  property  of  churches.  His 
work  gave  a  new  impetus  to  the  historical  researches  on  Canon  Law. 

For  the  historical  study  of  ecclesiastical  institutions  Stutz 
founded  in  1902  the  collection  of  Kirchenrechtliche  Abhandlungen 
(Stuttgart,  Enke),  in  which  have  appeared  up  to  the  present  time 
no  fewer  than  eighty  volumes  by  different  authors,  dealing  with 
the  most  various  branches  of  the  historical  development  of  ecclesi- 
astical institutions  in  different  countries,  and  mainly  in  Germany. 

Those  researches,  in  which  scholars  of  different  denominations 
have  taken  part,  united  by  that  impartiality  of  scientific  investiga- 
tion, which  must  be  the  base  of  any  study  of  Canon  Law  worthy 
of  the  name  of  science,  have  brought  into  prominence  the  import- 
ance of  local  elements  in  Canon  Law,  and  have  contributed  to  the 
formation  of  the  '  ecclesiastical  legal  history '  advocated  by  Stutz. 
His  foundation  of  the  Canonistische  Abteilung  of  the  Zeitschrift 
der  Savigny-Stiftung  (1911),  with  contributions  by  canonists  of 

2  A 


354  ^*  Galante  [xvm 

different  nationalities  in  their  own  language,  has  created  an  inter- 
national medium  of  communication  for  the  historical  study  of 
Canon  Law. 

Side  by  side  with  this  historical  investigation  of  Canon  Law  has 
proceeded  the  study  of  the  strictly  legal  questions  connected  in  the 
various  countries  with  ecclesiastical  institutions,  and  what  may  be 
called  the  *  comparative '  study  of  ecclesiastical  law,  i.e.  the  study 
of  the  ecclesiastical  legislation  in  different  States,  so  that  the  field 
of  canonistic  research  has  been  greatly  enlarged  in  modern  times. 
Besides,  a  series  of  historical  publications  threw  new  light  on 
ecclesiastical  institutions,  and  in  this  connexion  may  be  quoted  the 
new  Regesta  Pontificum  by  Kehr,  the  great  collection  of  materials 
on  the  Council  of  Trent  edited  by  the  G^rrcsgesellschaft^  and  the 
reports  of  the  Papal  Nuncii  from  different  countries  published  during 
the  last  few  years  by  various  historical  institutes. 

At  the  conclusion  of  this  brief  survey  of  the  development  of  the 
study  of  Canon  Law,  in  which  of  course  I  have  only  been  able  to 
outline  the  main  current  of  researches,  without  including  all  the 
individual  contributions  to  the  progress  of  our  science,  I  should  like 
to  say  a  few  words  on  the  particular  condition  of  the  study  of  Canon 
Law  in  England. 

Through  the  Middle  Ages  Canon  Law  had  been  one  of  the  chief 
elements  of  the  legal  studies  in  the  English  Universities,  and  was 
the  subject  of  scientific  research.  In  England,  as  on  the  Continent, 
Canon  Law  was  'one  of  the  great  civilizing  and  humanizing  in- 
fluences of  the  Middle  Ages.'  When  Henry  VIII  banished  Canon 
Law  from  the  academical  studies  of  England  he  dealt  a  deadly 
blow  to  canonistic  science  in  England.  Although  we  can  see  in 
the  Ecclesiastical  Polity  of  Hooker  an  attempt  to  give  a  scientific 
basis  to  the  legal  institutions  of  the  Church  of  England,  Canon  Law  as 
an  independent  science  was  abandoned,  and  the  legal  side  of  ecclesi- 
astical matters  was  dealt  with  mainly  from  a  practical  point  of  view. 

And  yet  perhaps  no  other  country  presents  so  much  interest 
for  the  study  of  Ecclesiastical  Law  as  Great  Britain,  not  only  on 
account  of  the  mediaeval  elements  which  are  still  alive  in  her 
ecclesiastical  institutions,  but  also  for  the  variety  and  magnitude 
of  ecclesiastical  questions,  so  prominent  in  English  public  life. 
We  only  need  to  remind  ourselves  of  the  question,  still  sub  judice^ 
of  Welsh  Disestablishment  and  its  connexion  with  innumerable 


xvin]  Ecclesiastical  Law  355 

questions  of  legal  history,  and  we  may  recall  that  the  'Royal 
Commission  on  the  Church  of  England  and  other  Religious  Bodies 
in  Wales  and  Monmouthshire'  of  1906  was  obliged  to  declare  the 
impossibility  of  proceeding  to  a  legal-historical  examination  of  the 
ecclesiastical  foundations  in  Wales. 

Some  parts  of  Canon  Law,  in  regard  to  England,  have  been 
dealt  with  in  the  histories  of  English  Law  (for  example,  by 
Pollock  and  Maitland,  and  Holdsworth),  and  many  valuable  con- 
tributions to  legal  history  of  ecclesiastical  institutions  in  England 
are  contained  in  local  histories  and  in  the  historical  records  of 
bishoprics,  chapters,  parishes,  etc.  Also,  among  the  English  works 
of  general  interest  for  canonists,  we  must  remember  Phillimore's 
Ecclesiastical  Law.  Still,  it  would  be  most  desirable  that  the  study 
of  the  legal  history  of  the  English  ecclesiastical  institutions  should 
be  taken  up  in  England  on  a  wider,  more  comprehensive  scale,  and 
the  results  of  those  investigations  would  be  most  important,  not 
only  for  the  legal  history  of  England,  but  for  the  history  of  the 
development  of  Canon  Law  in  general. 

The  interest  created  by  Maitland's  book,  Roman  Canon  Law  in 
England,  showed  to  a  larger  public  the  great  importance  of  the 
study  of  Canon  Law  for  England. 

1  should  like,  in  conclusion,  speaking  in  this  old  Hall  of 
Lincoln's  Inn,  so  full  of  ecclesiastical  and  legal  memories,  to 
express  the  hope  that  England,  the  country  which  has  given  to 
international  science  Lyndwood,  Hooker,  Stubbs,  and  Maitland, 
may  revive  her  old  canonistic  traditions  and  take  a  vigorous  share 
in  the  modern  researches  of  Canon  Law, 

ANDREA  GALANTE. 

BIBLIOGRAPHICAL  NOTE 

[Conf.  Jacobson,  *  Das  kanonische  und  kirchenrechtliche  Studium  sonst  tmd 
jetzt,  in  Italien,  Frankreich,  in  den  Niederlanden,  Belgien  und  Deutschland' 
(Zeitschrift  fur  Kirchenrecht,  L,  1861);  Schultc,  <  if  her  die  Bedeutung  und 
Aufgabe  des  Kirchenrechts '  (Archiv  fur  kathol.  Kirchenrecht,  L) ;  Gross, 
Zur  Begriffsbestimmung  und  WUrdigung  des  Kirchenrechts,  Graz,  1871  j 
F.  Ruffini,  *  Lo  Studio  e  il  concetto  odierno  del  diritto  ecclesiastico '  (Rivista 
italiana  per  le  scienze  giuridiche,  1892);  Friedberg,  Dot  canonische  Recht 
und  das  Kirchenrecht  (Festrede),  Leipzig,  1696  (printed  also  in  the  Deutsche 
Zeitschrift  fur  Kirchenrechf) ;  Stutz,  Die  kirchliche  Rechtsgeschichte  (Rede), 
Stuttgart,  1905  ;  Galante,  '  Diritto  ecclesiastico  e  storia  locale '  (in  the  Reports 
of  the  International  Historical  Congress  of  Rome ',  1903).] 


XIX 

LJID£E  DE  LJ£TAT  ET  SON  EVOLUTION  EN 
RUSSIE  DEPUIS  LES  TROUBLES  DU  XVIIE 
SIECLE  JUSQU'AUX  R^FORMES  DU  XVIIP 

CONSIDEREE  dans  son  essence  Pide"e  de  Pfitat  est  une  concep- 
tion normative :  c'est  la  notion  de  ce  que  doit  etre  le  rapport  entre 
le  souverain  et  les  sujets,  et  non  seulement  la  notion  du  pouvoir 
coercitif  que  1'Etat  a  sur  les  particuliers.  C'est  done  dans  le  sens 
normatif  qu'on  lui  donnait  jadis,  d'apres  les  principes  d'une  civilisa- 
tion anterieure  a  la  n6tre,  que  je  traiterai  de  l'ide"e  de  1'Etat  et  de 
son  Evolution  en  Russie. 

Cette  Evolution  a  pris  une  direction  qu'il  est  facile  de  pre"ciser : 
au  commencement  du  XVP  siecle  l'ide"e  de  1'Etat  russe  est  plutot 
religieuse  que  se"culiere ;  au  commencement  du  XVIIP  elle  devient 
plutdt  se"culiere  que  religieuse.  Tout  en  suivant  ce  de"veloppement 
dans  ses  grandes  lignes,  je  ne  pretends  pas,  du  reste,  en  donner  ici 
une  exposition  complete.  Pour  y  parvenir  il  ne  suffirait  pas  de 

[  noter   les   theories   qui   contribuerent   a   cette   metamorphose;    il 

)  faudrait  s'arreter  plus  longuement,  que  je  n'ai  pu  le  faire,  aux 

institutions  et  aux  e'venements  qui  d£terminerent  le  cours  re"el  de 

ces  id^es  en  Russie  depuis  les  troubles  du  XVII  siecle  jusqu'aux 

reTormes  du  XVIIP. 

La  conception  de  la  civilisation  qu'on  se  faisait  en  Europe  au 
moyen  age  donnait  une  preeminence  marquee  a  la  religion,  telle 
que  1'entendait  TEglise  chr^tienne ;  mais  pour  syst^matiser  les 
verites  divines  concedees  aux  lai'ques  et  les  impr^gner  de  sa  doctrine 

356 


xix]  LIdde  de  F  Etat  en  Russie  357 

elle  se  servait  de  la  scolastique.  Quoique  1'figlise  grecque  se  soit 
trouv£e  dans  une  position  moins  propice  que  PEglise  latine  pour 
jouer  ce  role,  elle  cultiva,  pourtant,  ces  id£es  non  sans  succes  et 
contribua  a  leur  propagation  dans  des  pays  lointains. 

La  Russie,  qui,  sous  le  rapport  clerical,  d£pendait  au  moyen 
age  du  patriarche  de  Constantinople,  a  naturellement  £prouv£ 
cette  influence ;  mais  elle  n'en  profita  qu'avec  un  grand  retard.  La 
Dialectique  de  Jean  Damascene,  dans  laquelle  il  tachait  d'adap- 
ter  Pancienne  logique  des  £coles  a  la  doctrine  de  1'Eglise,  par 
exemple,  a  £te  traduite  en  «langue  slave »,  et  ses  copies  russes 
datent  du  xve  siecle.  L'un  des  admirateurs  de  Jean  Damascene, 
dej'a  efHeur£  par  la  Renaissance,  Maxime  le  Grec,  pr£conisait 
aussi  «la  logique »  en  tant  qu'elle  servait  a  la  gloire  de  Dieu 
et  enflammait  Tame  d'amour  pour  le  Tres-Haut,  c'est-a-dire 
en  tant  qu'elle  n'etait  pas  contraire  aux  paroles  divines  et 
se  conformait  a  elles.1  En  suivant  ces  regies,  PEglise  grecque 
pouvait  mettre  a  profit  meme  la  scolastique  latine :  Maxime 
le  Grec  n'en  £tait  pas  exempt ;  les  erudits  de  Kiev,  tels  que 
SteTan  Javorskij,  par  exemple,  en  userent  largement  dans  leurs 
travaux. 

Une  doctrine  analogue  ne  tarda  pas  a  se  former  en  Russie 
dans  le  domaine  des  id£es  morales  et  politiques,  soumises,  elles 
aussi,  aux  dogmes  de  1'Eglise :  c'est  du  sein  de  l'£glise  grecque 
que  sont  sortis  les  premiers  doctrinaires  de  PEtat  russe,  et  c'est 
du  point  de  vue  orthodoxe  ou  «  pravoslave  »,  et  en  conformite  avec 
plusieurs  id£es  byzantines,  notamment  avec  celle  du  basileus, 
vicaire  orthodoxe  de  Dieu  et  autocrate,  regnant  par  le  Christ 
qui  Pinspire  et  le  guide,  qu'ils  formulaient  les  principes  de 
cet  Etat. 

L'id£e  religieuse  de  PEtat  formee  a  Byzance  £tait  deja  quelque 
peu  connue  en  Russie  a  P^poque  de  Vladimir  le  Saint  et  de 
ses  successeurs ;  mais  elle  ne  s'est  d£veloppe"e  qu'en  Moscovie. 
Bien  des  circonstances  contribuerent  a  son  developpement,  par- 
ticulierement  celles  qui,  dans  leur  ensemble,  produisirent  la  d£- 
cadence  de  PEmpire  byzantin  et  la  formation  de  PEtat  moscovite, 


1  loaHHi,  J^aMacKHHi,,  fliajteKmum,  pyc.  nep.,  M.  1862,  pp.  9,  10,  104, 
106-107,  1 08  ;  cf.  A.  Co6ojieBCKift.  Hepeeodnafi  jiumepamypa  MOCKOBCKOU 
Pycu,  2  H3A-,  CUB.,  1903,  pp.  20,  281.  MaKCHMt  TpeKi,,  CouuneniH,  Kas., 
1859-1862,  i.  pp.  462-464. 


358  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

de  son  unit6  et  de  son  ind£pendance ;  mais  en  consid£rant  la 
porte"e  subsequente  de  ces  theories,  c'est  plut6t  leurs  principes  que 
leur  genese  qu'il  importe  de  noter. 

L'une  d'elles,  celle  de  Philophe'e  du  couvent  d'6l£azar,  d^velop- 
pait  une  these  que  le  me"tropolite  Zocime  avait  deja  avance"e  en 
1492.  Philoph£e  ia  formulait  au  point  de  vue  religieux  et 
providentiel,  bas£  sur  les  Saintes  Ecritures :  toutes  ses  e"pitres 
sont  imbues  de  1'idee  de  la  Providence,  grace  a  laquelle  tout  ce 
qui  arrive  dans  1'univers  n'arrive  que  par  la  volont£  de  Dieu, 
Cre"ateur  de  toutes  choses,  et  pour  le  bien  de  1'humanite".  C'est  a 
ce  point  de  vue,  renforc£  par  les  allegories  de  I'Apocalypse,  que 
Philophe'e  £crivit  ses  e"pitres  au  grand  due  Basile  III  et  au  tsar 
Jean  IV :  il  y  propose,  de  meme  que  dans  son  e"pitre  au  clerc 
Moune"khine,  sa  doctrine  sur  le  defacement  providentiel  du  centre 
de  la  chre"tiennet£  de  Rome  a  Byzance,  et  de  Byzance  a  Moscou, 
ou  il  s'est  fix£  definitivement,  et  sur  la  mission  providentielle  de  ce 
nouveau  foyer  du  monde  pravoslave.  C'est  de  cette  mission  qu'il 
de"duit  le  r61e  historique  de"sign£  par  Dieu  a  1'Etat  moscovite, 
comme  centre  de  reunion  des  divers  royaumes  de  la  chre"tiennet£ 
pravoslave ;  les  prerogatives  de  1'elu  de  Dieu — du  tsar,  unique 
repr£sentant  du  pouvoir,  qui  doit  observer  et  maintenir  les 
traditions  pravoslaves  dans  1'Orient  chretien,  ses  devoirs  et  ses 
droits  envers  ses  sujets,  etc.1 

La  theorie  de  Philophee  n'^tait  pas  de"nu£e  de  grandeur:  au 
point  de  vue  orthodoxe  ou  pravoslave  on  pouvait  1'appliquer  aux 
relations  internationales  et  au  regime  interieur ;  mais  elle  ne 
developpait  pas  les  principes  de  gouvernement  et  de  suj£tion ; 
c'est  dans  des  doctrines  plus  sp£ciales  qu'on  pouvait  trouver  ces 
deVeloppements. 

Une  theorie,  bas£e  sur  Porthodoxie  la  plus  stricte  et  visiblement 
influenced  par  les  id^es  byzantines — celle  de  Joseph  Sanine — con- 
siderait,  par  exemple,  le  tsar  comme  1'elu  de  Dieu  et  le  gardien 
supreme  de  1'orthodoxie,  et  en  d£duisait  ses  devoirs  et  ses  droits, 
de  meme  que  sa  responsabilit£  envers  Dieu.  L'abb£  de  Woloko- 
lamsk  comparait  le  pouvoir  du  tsar  a  celui  de  Dieu,  et  parlait  de 
Pob£issance  que  lui  devaient  ses  sujets  comme  de  celle  qui  se 
pratique  envers  Dieu  ou  dans  les  cloitres ;  pour  prouver  ses  theses 

1  B.  MajnmHHi,  Cmapew  Ejieasapoea  Mouacmupu  (Duaooeu  u  eio 
nocjianin,  KieBi,  1901  r.,  Ilpmr.,  pp.  36-66. 


xix]  LIdde  de  rEtat  en  Russie  359 

il  s'en  rapportait,  entre  autres,  a  Pautorite"  des  empereurs  byzantins, 
notamment  a  celle  de  Constantin  et  de  Justinien.1 

Une  the"orie  moins  rigoureuse,  de"veloppe"e  par  Maxime  le  Grec, 
introduisait  les  e"le"ments  de  la  justice  ou  de  la  prawda  particuliere- 
ment  dans  le  domaine  de  la  juridiction.  Comme  St-Thomas 
d'Acquin,  il  distingue  les  vertus  th^ologiques  des  vertus  morales  et 
place  a  leur  tete  la  vertu  de  la  justice  (justitia)  ou  de  la  prawda. 
Quoique  Maxime  le  Grec  n'ait  pas  donne"  de  definition  du  concept 
de  la  prawda,  qu'il  considere  tantdt  au  point  de  vue  religieux  et 
me'taphysique,  tantdt  au  point  de  vue  de  la  morale  chre"tienne,  il 
en  de"duit  les  devoirs  et  les  droits  du  souverain,  particulierement 
dans  le  domaine  de  la  juridiction :  le  prince  doit  observer  la 
prawda  et  la  de"fendre  dans  ses  cours  de  justice,  ce  qui  mene  a 
la  «  paix  inte"rieure  et  a  la  force  exte"rieure  » .  Le  prince  qui  plaide 
la  cause  de  la  prawda  regne  conjointement  avec  Dieu,  «qui  est 
Justice, »  et  ne  gouverne  que  comme  son  intermediate ;  cela  donne 
a  son  pouvoir  un  e"clat  surnaturel  et  une  puissance  morale,  et  lui 
reserve  le  droit  d'exiger  la  soumission  absolue  de  ses  sujets.2 

Les  doctrines  de  Philophe"e,  de  Joseph  et  de  Maxime  que  ces 
derniers  enoncaient,  d'ailleurs,  non  sans  reserves,  ont  joui  d'une 
grande  popularite  parmi  les  lettre's  moscovites  :  le  tsar  Jean  IV 
lui-meme  en  a  largement  profite ;  elles  ont  certainement  subi 
quelques  deVeloppements  et  quelques  modifications  poste*rieures ; 
mais  elles  n'ont  pas  e"te"  supplante"es  a  cette  e"poque  par  d'autres 
systemes.  Jean  Peresvje"tov,  par  exemple,  avait  certainement 
donne*  une  conception  diffe"rente  de  1'autorit^  «redoutable»  du 
souverain  envers  ses  sujets  et  avait  indique",  de  meme  qu'Ostrorog, 
quelques  problemes  que  TEtat  moderne  devait  resoudre :  il  recon- 
naissait  1'importance  du  principe  «  a  chacune  selon  ses  ceuvres  »  et  la 
n^cessit^  des  lois  e"crites ;  il  proposait  d'abolir  les  offices  h^r^ditaires 
et  de  re"mune"rer  les  fonctionnaires  ;  il  insistait  sur  1'organisation  des 

1  IOCH(J)T>  Bojioi],KiS,  TIpocerbmumeM,  Kaa.   1896,  3  ed.,  pp.  488,  544- 
551;    pour    les    restrictions   que   Joseph   Sanine  faisait,  en  parlant  des  rois 
heretiques,  voir  ib.  pp.   286-288,  et  M.  J^LUKOHOBI.,  Bjiacmb  MOCKOOCKUXK 
rocydapeiiy  CUB.,  1899,  pp.  26,  95,  103. 

2  MaKCHM-B  rpeKi>,  Couunenifi,  v.  i.  pp.  142,  385,  v.  ii.  pp.  152,  157-184, 
209,  210,  286,  319-357,  v.  iii.  p.  237,  etc.      D'ailleurs,  quelques  elements  de 
cette  theorie  se  trouvent  deja  dans  Le  Discours  sur  la  justice  et  ? injustice  de 
PIsmaragde  « de  la  2e  redaction))  (xv.  sc.);  mais  ils  n'y  sont  pas  developpes 
systematiquement. 


360  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

finances  et  de  Parme"e.  Malgre"  la  haute  porte"e  de  ses  ide"es,  les 
projets  de  Pe"resvje"tov  ne  regurent  pas  la  notori£te  dont  joufesaient 
les  theories  de  Philophee  et  de  ses  e"mules :  celles-ci  ont  prevalu  au 
XVI8  siecle  et  ont  e"te"  transmises  au  XVII6. 

Cependant  ces  doctrines  « pravoslaves  »  sur  Plitat  ne  donnaient 
qu'une  id£e  transcendante  du  rapport  entre  le  souverain  et  les 
sujets ;  elles  s'exposaient,  en  outre,  a  quelques  restrictions  de  la 
part  des  partisans  ze"le"s  de  PEglise,  qui  rehaussaient  Pautorite" 
spirituelle  et  r^clamaient  Pobe"issance  du  monarque  aux  admonitions 
de  ses  repre"sentants ;  elles  ne  s'accordaient  pas  avec  les  serments 
que  quelques-uns  des  tsars  devaient  preter  aux  bojares  a  Pe"poque 
des  troubles ;  elles  ne  preVoyaient  pas  le  role  que  devaient  jouer 
les  assemblies  des  etats  (semskii  ssobory)  au  commencement  du 
XVIIe  siecle. 

II  est  vrai  qu'au  temps  des  troubles  les  Russes  e"prouverent  le 
sentiment  de  la  difference  qu'il  y  a  entre  PEtat  et  la  forme  du 
gouvernement ;  mais  ils  avaient  alors  des  raisons  pour  croire  que 
PEtat  moscovite  ne  pouvait  conserver  son  unite"  et  sa  force  qu'en 
restant  fidele  aux  formes  traditionnelles  du  gouvernement :  le  tsar 
Mihai'l  Fe"dorovicz  trouva  un  appui  dans  les  e"tats  ge"ne"raux  pour 
re"tablir  Pordre  dans  le  pays,  et  les  theories  anciennes  continuerent 
a  y  circuler,  meme  dans  la  seconde  moitie"  du  XVir  siecle. 

Le  tsar  Alexej  Mihajlovicz,  par  exemple,  usait  volontiers  de 
ces  theories,  sans  y  apporter,  du  reste,  de  changements  essentiels ; 
ne"anmoins  il  accepta  la  disposition  que  le  concile  de  1667  avait 
prise  et  qui  consistait  a  conserver  au  monarque  son  autorite"  supreme 
dans  les  affaires  de  Plitat,  tout  en  la  r£servant  au  patriarche  dans 
les  affaires  de  PEglise  ;  mais,  apres  la  deposition  de  Nicone,  ce  de"- 
doublement  du  pouvoir  ne  pouvait  durer  :  il  portait  atteinte  a  Punit£ 
de  PEtat  et  fut  de"finitivement  aboli  par  Pierre  le  Grand. 

Ce  n'est  qu'indirectement — par  Pintroduction  de  la  scolastique, 
a  laquelle  le  tsar  Alexej  Mihajlovicz  avait  accorde"  sa  protection, 
que  ces  theories  «  pravoslaves  »  ont  rec^u  leurs  complements  dans  les 
ide"es,  sorties  du  sein  des  colleges  des  je"suites,  dont  le  re"seau 
couvrait  deja  la  plus  grande  partie  de  la  Pologne. 

Comme  je  Pai  remarque  plus  haut,  la  religion  orthodoxe 
grecque  n'interdisait  pas  Pusage  de  la  scolastique  latine  :  et  c'est 
justement  pour  deTendre  les  droits  de  Pliglise  pravoslave  qu'on 
en  usa  a  Kiev ;  mais  la  scolastique  latine,  qu'on  transplantait  des 


xix]  U  Idee  de  I'Etat  en  Russie  361 

colleges  des  je"suites  polonais  a  Kiev,  et  de  Kiev  a  Moscou, 
contenait  quelques  principes  de  morale  et  de  droit  qui,  de  cette 
maniere,  pe"ne"trerent  dans  le  milieu  des  lettre"s  moscovites. 

Ces  principes  se  reliaient,  au  fond,  a  la  doctrine  de  St-Thomas 
d'Acquin,  et,  par  son  intermediate,  a  quelques  ide"es  d'Aristote ; 
ils  caracte"risaient  en  Moscovie  l'e"poque  de  transition  de  Pide"e 
religieuse  a  1'idee  seculiere  de  l'£tat. 

L'un  des  lettre"s  moscovites  de  ce  temps-la,  Simeon  Polotzkij, 
par  exemple,  s'en  tenait  a  cette  doctrine  mixte.  II  rattachait  les 
origines  de  1'Etat  et  du  pouvoir  souverain  non  seulement  a  la 
volont£  divine,  mais  a  la  tendance  naturelle  qu'ont  les  hommes 
a  s'assembler  en  societ£  :  les  hommes,  les  cit£s  et  les  royaumes 
dependent  re"ciproquement  les  uns  des  autres  dans  les  choses 
mate"rielles  et  spirituelles  ;  ils  e"prouvent  aussi  le  besoin  de  se"curit£ 
qui  les  pousse  a  se  donner  un  chef,  car  une  socie"t£  sans  chef  tend 
a  sa  ruine.  II  se  repre*sentait  le  souverain  non  seulement  comme 
celui  qui  «  mene  ses  sujets  aux  vertus  divines »,  mais  comme  celui  qui 
vaque  a  leur  « bien  commun » ;  il  pre"sumait  que  le  prince  doit 
re"gner  non  seulement  d'apres  les  pre"ceptes  de  la  vertu,  de  la 
prawda^  mais  aussi  d'apres  les  principes  de  la  justice  distributive 
et  commutative,  qu'il  distinguait,  selon  un  schema  assez  re"pandu 
dans  les  manuels  de  ce  temps -la,  de  la  justice  vindicative.  En 
deVeloppant  ces  principes  Sime"on  Polotzkij  ,donnait  une  espece 
de  speculum  principis  christiani,  dans  lequel  on  peut  trouver 
quelques  regies  analogues  a  celles  d'Agapithe  le  diacre  dans  son 
"EK&O-IS  Ke<£aAa«t>v  Trapati/ertKcui/  et  entrevoir,peut-etre,  quelque  influence 
du  traits  De  regimine  principum,  particulierement  dans  les  restric- 
tions du  pouvoir  temporel  en  faveur  du  pouvoir  spirituel  que  Simeon 
Polotzkij  fait  plutdt  sous-entendre  que  formuler  ouvertement.1 

1  CHMGOHT.  IIojion;Ki8,  Sanucxu,  MS.  de  la  Biblotheque  de  la  Typographic 
du  Synode  a  Moscou,  N°  1791,  4078,  ff.  199  sq.  ;  Bepmoipadi,  MHOIO- 
Wrbmnuu,  MS.  conserve  au  departement  des  manuscrits  de  la  Bibliotheque 
de  PAcademie  Imperiale  des  Sciences  de  St-Petersbourg,  N°  19,  Preface, 
ff.  57v.-58v.,  9ov.,  3o6v.-3o8v.,  363v.,  375-375V.,  466v.-477.  Le  moine 
Simeon  Polotzkij  avait  fait  ses  Etudes  k  Kiev  et  au  college  des  jesuites  de 
Wilno ;  il  s'etablit  a  Moscou,  probablement  en  1663.  Les  notes  qu'il  avait 
prises  au  college  de  Wilno,  d'un  cours  de  morale,  c'est-a-dire  de  «  monastique  », 
«  d'economique  »  et  de  «politique»,  qu'il  y  avait  suivi,  le  recueil  de  pieces  qu'il 
a  intitule  Le  Jardin  multiflore  (« Vertograd  Mnogozwetnij »)  et  dirferents 
autres  ecrits  prouvent  qu'il  s'dtait  quelque  peu  familiarise  avec  les  doctrines 
de  St-Thomas  d'Acquin  et  d'Aristote.  Cf.,  d'ailleurs,  p.  359  note  i. 


362  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

Ces  theories  ont  ete  reprises  par  Tun  des  plus  fervents  Sieves  de 
Simeon  Polotzkij,  grand  amateur  de  la  scolastique  et  quelque  peu 
connaisseur  d'Aristote— par  Silvestre  Me"dv£dje>  ;  mais  la  doctrine 
de  la  justice  n'a  regu  des  deVeloppements  sensibles  que  dans  les 
cours  de  the"ologie  caiques  sur  la  Somme  de  St-Thomas  d'Acquin. 

En  effet,  on  distinguait,  d'apres  la  Somme,  les  vertus  morales 
des  vertus  the"ologiques  et  on  y  comprenait  la  prudence,  la  justice, 
la  vaillance  et  la  temperance ;  mais  on  considerait  la  prudence 
comme  une  vertu  intermediate  entre  les  vertus  the"ologiques  et 
morales,  ce  qui  permettait  de  placer  la  justice  a  la  tete  des  vertus 
morales ;  et  on  en  traitait  conjointement  avec  le  droit. 

C'est  done  grace  aux  cours  de  the"ologie,  et  particulierement  a 
leur  partie  intituled  de  jure  et  justitia,  que  les  notions  juridiques 
commencerent  a  s'infiltrer  dans  notre  litterature. 

L'un  des  repr^sentants  les  plus  caracteristiques  de  cette  con- 
ception fut  certainement  un  professeur  de  the"ologie  a  1'academie 
de  Kiev,  qui  y  lisait,  en  1696-1697,  un  cours  contenant  un 
tractatus  theologicus  de  justitia.  L'auteur,  selon  toute  apparence 
Stefan  Javorskij,  donne  dans  son  traite  la  definition  de  la  justice 
autrefois  formulae  par  Ulpien  et  rec^ue  par  St-Thomas  d'Acquin, 
et  tache  d'etablir  sur  ce  principe  le  rapport  du  souverain  et  des 
sujets. 

Stefan  Javorskij  delibere  sur  la  justice  commutative  et 
distributive  d'apres  Aristote,  St-Thomas  d'Acquin  ^et  quelques 
auteurs  scolastiques  plus  regents ;  mais  il  admet,  en  outre,  une  dis- 
tinction posterieure,  quoique  deja  inclue  dans  la  Somme,  de  la  justice 
legale  et  de  la  justice  vindicative,  notions  qu'il  pouvait  puiser,  par 
exemple,  dans  le  traite  de  son  confrere  polonais  Mlodzianowskij. 

D'apres  cette  the"orie  la  justice  commutative  regie  les  rapports 
prives  des  hommes,  les  autres  justices — les  rapports  re"ciproques  du 
souverain  et  des  sujets. 

En  effet,  la  justice  distributive  fixe  les  devoirs  de  la  com- 
munaute  (communitas)  envers  les  personnes  privees :  elle  e"tablit  ce 
a  quoi  chacune  d'elles  a  droit,  comme  membre  de  la  communaute". 
La  justice  le"gale  fixe  les  devoirs  des  personnes  privies  envers  la 
communaut6 — ce  que  chacune  d'elles  doit  faire  pour  le  bien 
commun  de  la  communaute  dont  elle  est  membre ;  ce  nexus 
legal  est  une  sujetion  formelle,  si  celui  qui  devient  membre  de  la 
communaute  exprime  consciemment  sa  volonte  d'en  faire  partie,  ou 


xix]  Ly Idde  de  r&at  en  Russie  363 

reste  traditionnel,  s'il  ne  fait  qu'admettre  sa  suje"tion,  dont  1'acte  a 
e"t£  accompli  ante>ieurement  par  ceux  qui  ont  £t6  admis  par  la 
communaute"  et  reconnu  par  elle.  Done,  chaque  sujet  doit  veiller 
au  bien  commun  (respicere  bonum  commune  titulo  nexus  ad 
communitatem).  D'ailleurs,  les  devoirs  de  la  communaute"  ou  de 
ses  membres  deviennent  respectivement  des  droits  ;  la  communaute", 
par  exemple,  possede  le  pouvoir,  fonde*  sur  le  nexus  le"gal  et  sur  la 
loi  naturelle  (firmata  lege  naturalt),  c'est-a-dire  le  droit  d'exiger  des 
citoyens  le  sacrifice  de  leur  bien  et  meme  de  leur  vie  pour  la  chose 
publique. 

A  1'instar  de  la  justice  distributive  et  de  la  justice  le"gale,  la 
justice  vindicative  a  en  vue  l'inte"r£t  de  la  communaute',  mais  elle  le 
preserve,  en  en  e*cartant  le  mal  (nocumentum)  par  des  peines  qu'elle 
inflige  a  ceux  qui  les  me"ritent ;  elle  les  inflige  « honnetement » 
pour  preVenir  les  dommages,  ou  pour  punir  ceux  qui  les  ont 
occasionne's. 

Comme  on  le  voit,  SteTan  Javorskij  remonte  aux  principes  de 
1'Etat,  fbnde"s  sur  la  justice  ;  et  c'est  deja  en  combinaison  avec  le 
droit  naturel  qu'il  Papplique  au  regime  des  personnes  et  des  biens  ; 
il  en  traite  non  sans  1'influence  de  St-Thomas  d'Acquin  et  d'autres 
the"ologiens,  par  exemple,  de  Becanus.  D'apres  cette  the"orie,  les 
hommes,  de  par  leur  nature  (ex  natura),  sont  tous  e"galement  libres  : 
1'homme  ne  peut  etre  [naturellement]  1'esclave  d'un  autre  homme ; 
mais  il  peut  le  devenir  grace  au  droit  des  gens,  s'il  est  fait 
prisonnier  dans  une  guerre  juste  ou  en  vertu  de  la  loi  positive  (lex 
positivd) ;  il  peut  aussi  devenir  esclave  de  son  propre  gre\  De 
meme  la  proprie'te'  n'est  pas  fondle  sur  le  droit  naturel,  mais  sur  le 
droit  des  gens  (ius  gentium\  c'est-a-dire  sur  le  consentement  des 
hommes,  qui  diviserent  les  biens.  Du  reste,  cette  division  corres- 
pondait  aux  exigences  de  la  raison,  et  en  ce  sens  au  droit  naturel : 
car  1'homme  a  plus  de  soin  de  son  propre  bien  que  du  bien  commun, 
et  dans  l'e"tat  primitif  chacun  pouvait  deTendre  aux  autres  d'user 
du  bien  commun,  ce  qui  devenait  une  source  de  collisions  perpe"- 
tuelles,  qu'on  ne  pouvait  faire  cesser  que  par  la  division  des  biens. 

II  m'est  impossible  d'entrer  dans  les  deVeloppements  que  donne 
Stefan  Javorskij  de  ces  principes :  il  delibere,  de  meme  que 
Mlodzianowski,  sur  «  l'objet»  et  le  «  sujet »  de  la  justice  ;  il  disserte, 
pareillement  a  Becanus,  sur  les  applications  des  principes  de  la 
justice  commutative  et  de  la  justice  vindicative  aux  «  cas  juridiques», 


364  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

et  traite,  dans  sa  Casuistique  des  donations,  des  testaments  et 
des  contrats ;  des  devoirs  du  juge,  de  «  1'accusateur »,  des  te"moins 
et  du  coupable ;  des  arrets  judiciaires,  de  la  restitution  des 
droits,  etc. 

J'espere  tout  de  meme  que  les  remarques  que  j'ai  faites  suffisent 
pour  conclure  que  Stefan  Javorskij  donne  dans  son  cours  de 
the"ologie  une  espece  de  traite  syste"matique  de  jurisprudence 
ge"ne"rale,  de  provenance  scolastique,  mais  d'une  assez  large  porte"e : 
il  commence  a  appliquer  les  principes  du  droit  naturel  du  moyen 
age  dans  le  domaine  du  droit  civil,  mais  ne  s'en  rapporte  pas  a 
ce  droit  dans  celui  du  droit  public  et  n'y  remonte  presque  pas  pour 
en  deduire  le  rapport  du  souverain  et  des  sujets.1  Ce  que  je 
voudrais  noter  encore  c'est  que  ces  idees  commenc^aient  a  s'infiltrer 
dans  la  pratique :  la  legislation  moscovite  du  temps  du  tsar  Fe"odor 
AlexejeVicz  n'y  etait  pas  tout  a  fait  £trangere.  Le  celebre  oukase 
de  1682  (janv.  12,  v.s.)  sur  1'abolition  des  droits  de  rang  et  de 
pre"seance  des  families  nobles,  c'est-a-dire  du  mjestniczestvo>  en 
porte  les  traces.  Dans  1'allocution  que  le  tsar  avait  adresse"e  aux 
etats  assembles,  et  qui  a  e"t£  inclue  dans  1'acte  de  1'abolition,  il 
disait  qu'il  avait  re$u  son  sceptre  de  la  main  de  Dieu  pour  prendre 
soin  de  tout  ce  qui  concerne  le  «  bien  commun  »  et  d'e"carter  tout  ce 
qui  lui  porte  atteinte ;  c'est  de  ce  point  de  vue  qu'il  abolissait  le 
mjestniczestvo,  comme  nuisible  «  au  bien  commun  de  1'fitat  ».2 

Comme  on  le  voit,  le  tsar  Fe"odor  Alexeje"vicz  avait  deja 
quelque  notion  theorique  du  «  bien  commun  de  1'Etat » ;  il  1'^rigeait 
en  principe  de  sa  reTorme,  et  lui  donnait  une  valeur  qu'il  n'a  acquise 
definitivement  qu'aux  temps  de  Pierre  le  Grand. 

L'idee  religieuse  de  1'Etat  en  Russie  a  done  subi  une  Evolution, 
grace  a  laquelle  elle  se  reliait  a  1'id^e  s^culiere  de  TEtat. 

Plusieurs  autres  facteurs  ont  contribue"  a  cette  secularisation ; 
je  n'en  releverai  ici  que  ceux  qui  ont  influe'  plus  bu  moins  directe- 
ment  sur  Involution  de  nos  id^es  politiques  du  XVIIe  siecle. 

D'abord,  c'est  le  mouvement  litteraire  issu  du  milieu  des 
judai'sants. 

1  Tractatus    theologid    collegia    Kiioivo-Mohileano    traditi   et   explicati, 
Tractatus  de  iustitia^  MS.  de  la  Kievo-Petcherskaja  Lawra,  N°  vii.  40. 

2  Codpanie  locyd.  ^paM.  u  doi.,  P.  iv.  N°  130 ;  cf.  IIoji.  Co6p.  3aK.,  t.  ii. 
N°  905,  PP-  373-374- 


xix]  LIdde  de  £  lit  at  en  Russie  365 

Les  judai'sants  (zidowstwoujouchczii)  ont  jou£  en  Russie  au 
XVe-XVIe  siecles  un  r61e  analogue  a  celui  des  averroi'stes  du  Xllle : 
ils  nous  ont  donne"  une  logique  et  une  politique,  inclue  dans  le 
trait^  Secreta  secretorum.  Ce  trait£  a  e"t£  probablement  connu 
en  Russie  dans  une  version  juive  (et  non  pas  arabe  ou  latine), 
re"dige"e  en  Allemagne :  c'est  de  la  qu'elle  a  pu  etre  importee  dans 
la  Russie  de  1'Ouest  et  se  propager  en  Moscovie. 

Les  Secreta  secretorum,  faussement  attribu£s  a  Aristote,  ont, 
certes,  un  caractere  medieval  fort  prononc£ :  ils  ne  sont  pas 
denudes  de  superstitions,  proposent  toutes  sortes  de  conseils  sur 
l'utilit£  de  1'astrologie,  sur  les  proprie"te"s  miraculeuses  ou  salutaires 
des  pierres  pre"cieuses  et  des  plantes,  etc.;  mais  ils  contiennent 
aussi  quelques  principes  plus  rationnels  que  ceux  qui  avaient 
habituellement  cours  dans  notre  litte"rature  du  XVP  siecle.  Les 
Secreta  secretorum  prdnent,  par  exemple,  les  principes  de  la 
raison,  grace  a  laquelle  les  patens  meme  ont  pu  connaitre  et 
e"tablir  quelques  regies  de  justice  et  d'honnetete  utiles  a  1'ordre 
public.  Les  Secreta  secretorum  introduisent  ces  principes  rationnels 
dans  la  politique :  elle  aussi  doit  etre  fonde'e  sur  la  raison  et  sur  la 
justice  qui  en  de"coule ;  c'est  d'apres  ces  principes  que  le  prince  doit 
gouverner  ses  sujets. 

L'occultisme  des  Secreta  secretorum  pre"sentait,  probablement, 
beaucoup  plus  d'inte"ret  pour  nos  lecteurs  que  leur  rationalisme,  ce 
qui  explique,  probablement,  leur  propagation  en  Russie  :  nous  n'en 
connaissons  pas  moins  de  dix  copies,  dont  deux  appartiennent 
meme  au  XVIII6  siecle.1 

D'ailleurs,  outre  ce  mouvement  collateral,  il  est  facile  de  constater 
que  la  Renaissance  et  la  Re"forme  ont  certainement  influe"  sur 
Involution  de  l'id£e  seculiere  de  PEtat  en  Russie. 

C'est  grace  a  1'influence  de  la  Renaissance  que  la  « philosophic 
pratique  »  s'est  quelque  peu  diffe"renci£e  de  la  religion  et  a  commenc£ 
a  servir  de  base  plus  inde"pendante  aux  theories  politiques. 

Du  reste,  les  humanistes  du  xvie  siecle,  tels  que  1'^crivain 
polonais  Petricij,  par  exemple,  se  repr£sentaient  la  philosophic 

1  Aristotelis  philosophorum  maximi  Secretum  Secretorum  ad  Alexandrum 
de  regum  regimine,  etc.;  j'avais  a  ma  portee  1'edition  :  Bononiae,  1516,  de  la 
Bibliotheque  royale  de  Dresde ;  1'ancienne  traduction  russe  a  e^e*  publiee  par 
M.  Speranskij ;  v.  M.  CnepancKiS,  Apucmomejieeu  Bpama,  IlaM.  flpee. 
.  u  Hcnyc.,  N°  clxxi.  CIIB.,  1908. 


366  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

pratique  dans  un  schema  qu'Aristote  avait  deja  admis  dans  ses 
ouvrages,  et  qui  e"tait  depuis  longtemps  regu  dans  la  scolastique. 
Us  y  distinguaient  trois  parties :  la  premiere  traitait  de  la  morale 
individuelle,  en  ge"ne"ral  (monastica  seu  solitaria) ;  la  seconde — des 
regies  de  la  vie  domestique  (economica  seu  domestica) ;  la  troisieme 
— des  principes  de  la  vie  en  commun,  politique  ou  civile  (politico, 
seu  civilis). 

Ces  diverses  parties,  qui  survivent  encore  dans  le  systeme  de 
Chr.  Wolf,  se  retrouvent  dans  notre  litt£rature  du  XVIP  siecle. 

II  est  vrai  qu'elle  n'est  pas  originale,  et  qu'elle  ne  fait  que  repro- 
duire  des  traductions  ou  des  ouvrages  polonais,  par  exemple,  le 
DesideriuS)  dialogue  sur  1'amour  de  Dieu,  e"crit  par  un  catholique, 
mais  dans  un  esprit  mystique  de  morale  individuelle ;  VEconomique 
d'Aristote,  interpreted  par  Petricij,  les  pre"ceptes  que  Lorichius 
proposait  aux  princes  et  autres  «  chefs  »,  etc.1  Tous  ces  trait£s  ont 
e"t6  traduits  en  russe  d'une  maniere  assez  satisfaisante ;  mais  ces 
traductions  ne  sont  pas  toujours  de  fideles  reproductions  des 
originaux.  La  traduction  des  Loci  communes  de  Lorichius,  par 
exemple,  ne  contient,  pour  la  plupart,  que  des  regies  pratiques 
concernant  l'e"ducation  du  «chef»,  et  des  «moyens  secrets  et 
astucieux»  qu'il  a  a  sa  disposition  pour  gouverner  ses  sujets. 

Je  ne  ferais  qu'indiquer  ici  en  passant  que  plusieurs  ide"es  sur  les 
principes  du  gouvernement  se  trouvent  encore  dans  des  dissertations, 
d'ailleurs  aussi  peu  originales,  sur  les  causes  de  la  decadence  des 
empires,  par  exemple,  dans  une  compilation  de  Ssadowskij,  con- 
tenant  quelques  idees  d'Aristote  et  d'autres  auteurs  sur  la  matiere, 
notamment  de  Chokier,  etc.  -  Cette  compilation  a  subi  au  moins  deux 
redactions,  et  fut  assez  prise"e  par  nos  lecteurs  du  XVIF  et  du  com- 
mencement du  XVIII6  siecle. 

Quoique  la  reTorme  n'ait  pas  eu  le  temps  de  s'affermir  en 
Pologne  et  d'y  Jeter  des  racines  plus  ou  moins  profondes,  elle  a 

1  Espejo  de  Religiosos^  Burgos,  J.  Junta,  1548;  trad,  latine  de  1616 
(Desiderosus,  dialogus  .  .  de  expedita  ad  Dei  amorem  vita) ;  trad,  polonaise 
de  G.  Wilkowskij,  1589  (beaucoup  de  reeditions) ;  trad,  russe  du  moine 
Theophane  du  monastere  du  Miracle  de  1'archange  Michel,  faite  en  1688  et 
imprimee  a  Moscou  en  1785.  S.  Petrici,  Oekonomiki  Aristotelesoivej  .  .  . 
ksi$gi  dwoje^  2  ed.  Krak.,  1618  ;  trad,  russe  au  Musee  public  de  Rou- 
mjanzev  a  Moscou,  N°  627,  R.  Lorichius,  Loci  communes  de  institutione 
prinripum>  Marburg,  1558;  trad,  polonaise,  Crac,  1558;  trad,  russe,  MS. 
appartenant  au  monastere  «  Florichtcheva  Poustyn  »,  N°  138/712. 


xix]  LIctte  de  r  lit  at  en  Russie  367 

eu  quelque  influence  sur  plusieurs  hommes  de  lettres  polonais,  par 
exemple  sur  Frycz  (Modrzevskij),  auteur  du  fameux  traite"  de  la 
Republique. 

Frycz  a  passe  plusieurs  anne"es  a  £tudier  les  lettres  dans  les 
centres  protestants  de  la  civilisation  allemande,  a  Wittemberg  et  a 
Nuremberg,  et  est  entre*  en  relations  personnelles  avec  M£lanchthon 
et  ses  collegues ;  cela  a  eu  quelque  influence  sur  son  ouvrage.  L'auteur 
du  traite  de  la  Republique  reste,  il  est  vrai,  catholique,  mais  il  veut 
profiter  de  quelques  idees  promues  par  la  ReTorme,  pour  re"organiser 
le  monde  catholique  et  1'Iitat. 

Grace  a  cette  largeur  de  vues  Frycz  a  pu  introduire  dans  sa 
politique  non  seulement  les  ide*es  d'Aristote,  mais  les  premiers 
Elements  du  droit  naturel,  e'labore'  principalement  par  les  e"crivains 
protestants,  entre  autres  par  Me"lanchthon  et  ses  emules.  Frycz  y 
raisonne  sur  l'e"galite  naturelle  des  hommes  (du  moins  sous  quelques 
rapports),  et  en  de"duit  que  1'exemption  des  nobles  de  la  peine  de 
mort  applique"e  aux  classes  rurales  est  injuste;  il  y  de"montre  que  les 
principes  de  cette  justice  doivent  servir  de  fondement  aux  mceurs 
et  aux  lois ;  il  y  recherche  les  origines  de  1'Etat,  et  le  relie  (non 
sans  quelques  inconsequences)  a  1'acte  de  translation  du  pouvoir  que 
les  hommes  ont  remis  (deferebant]  a  celui  qu'ils  estimaient  le  plus  pru- 
dent et  le  plus  juste,  «  se  soumettant  ainsi  non  pas  a  1'homme,  mais  a 
la  raison,  c'est-a-dire,  a  la  loi  naturelle  .  .  .  »  ;  il  y  proclame,  en  con- 
s£quence  de  ces  principes,  que  le  pouvoir  du  roi  est  e"tabli  pour  le 
bonheur  de  ses  sujets,  qu'il  est  soumis  aux  lois  de  meme  que  ses 
sujets,  que  la  loi  doit  etre  Equitable  pour  tous,  que  (d'apres  une  the"orie 
chere  a  Cice"ron)  le  gouvernement  mixte  est  le  meilleur,  etc. 

C'est  dans  Petition  polonaise  de  1577  du  traite"  de  Frycz  qu'on 
peut  trouver  le  deVeloppement  de  toutes  ces  ide"es  (excepte"  le  livre 
sur  PEglise)  ;  la  traduction  russe  du  traite",  faite  d'apres  cette  Edition 
et  presque  complete,  est  Tune  des  meilleures  que  nous  posse"dons 
en  ce  genre ;  elle  remonte  probablement  au  XVII6  siecle ;  quoique 
elle  ne  soit  connue  que  d'apres  une  copie  du  XVIII6,  et  porte  les  traces 
d'un  remaniement  poste'rieur.1 

1  Andreae  Fricii  Modrevij  Commentariorum  de  Republica  emendanda  libri 
quinque,  I  ed.  (incomplete)  Crac.  Laz.  i  5  5  I  ;  je  me  suis  servi  de  1'edition  de 
Basileae,  1554;  traduction  polonaise,  edition  de  I  577,  drukowano  w  Losku, 
avec  des  additions  ;  le  MS.  de  la  traduction  russe,  faite  probablement  du 
polonais,  se  trouve  dans  la  collection  de  manuscrits  du  Comte  Ouvaroff, 
N°  790.  Le  livre  De  Ecclesia  est  omis  dans  les  traductions  latine  et  russe. 


368  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

II  est  done  possible  de  conclure,  que  la  Renaissance,  et  meme 
la  ReTorme,  ont  eu  quelque  influence  sur  nos  ide"es  politiques  par 
I'interm^diaire  de  la  Pologne ;  mais  les  id£es  essentielles  de  la 
ReTorme,  et  la  litte'rature  poste"rieure  qui  se  rapportait  au  droit 
naturel  et  a  la  jurisprudence  pratique,  nous  sont  parvenues  grace 
aux  relations  directes  de  la  Russie  avec  1'Europe,  et  principalement 
avec  1'Europe  protestante. 

C'est  justement  cette  tendance  qui  a  trouve"  un  adversaire  decide" 
dans  la  personne  de  Crizanicz,  £mule  de  Possevin  et  partisan  secret 
de  l'£glise  grecque  unie. 

Crizanicz  puise  ses  principes  presque  exclusivement  dans  la 
civilisation  catholique :  il  n'est  pas  exempt  des  traditions  scolas- 
tiques ;  meme  dans  ses  theses  politiques  il  s'en  rapporte  plut6t  a 
St-Thomas  d'Acquin  qu'a  Aristote,  aime  mieux  Bellarmin  que 
Mariana,  et  prefere  Juste  Lipse  a  Paruta  et  Botero  a  Bodin. 
Crizanicz  voulait  inoculer  cette  culture  aux  peuples  slaves,  et  par- 
ticulierement  aux  moscovites ;  il  pensait  que  la  monarchic  £tait  la 
forme  de  gouvernement  la  plus  propice  a  la  propagande  des  id£es 
qu'il  s'e"tait  decide"  a  introduire  en  Russie. 

Relativement  a  la  fin  religieuse,  que  Crizanicz  se  proposait 
d'atteindre,  son  traite"  politique  n'e"tait  qu'un  moyen,  par  lequel  il 
croyait  pouvoir  gagner  les  bonnes  graces  du  tsar,  en  lui  disant  des 
choses  «  utiles  et  agr£ables  ».  C'est  pourquoi  il  se  gardait  bien  d'y 
toucher  aux  matieres  religieuses  et  cle>icales,  et  donnait  ainsi  a  son 
contenu  un  caractere  s£culier. 

D'ailleurs,  ce  caractere  se  renforgait  par  la  tendance  nationaliste 
que  Crizanicz  recommandait  aux  peuples  slaves  et  aux  moscovites, 
en  particulier  dans  leur  politique  s£culiere. 

Quant  au  rapport  entre  le  souverain  et  les  sujets,  Crizanicz 
preTere  se  le  repre"senter  sous  la  forme  d'une  monarchic  absolue,  qu'il 
reconnait,  de  meme  que  Juste  Lipse,  comme  la  meilleure  forme  de 
gouvernement — celle  qui  doit  donner  le  plus  de  forces  a  la  nation  ; 
mais  en  distinguant  la  monarchic  le"gitime,  institute  par  Dieu,  de  la 
tyrannic,  il  admet  tout  de  meme  une  espece  de  pacte  entre  le  mo- 
narque  et  ses  sujets  qui  les  garantit  des  exces  de  son  pouvoir.  A  la 
maniere  de  Faust  d'Aschaffenburg,  qui  dissertait  assez  longuement 
sur  le  iuramentum  subiectionis,  Crizanicz  parle  des  «  serments  »  ou 
des  « promesses »,  que  le  souverain  et  les  sujets  se  pretent  ou  se 
donnent  mutuellement,  mais  sans  leur  attribuer  la  valeur  supple"- 


xix]  LIdde  de  r&tat  en  Russie  369 

mentaire  d'obligations  naturelles  :  ces  serments  consistent  en  ce  que 
le  monarque  jure  au  peuple  qu'il  accomplira  ses  devoirs  et  prendra 
soin  du  bien  commun,  et  que  ses  heritiers,  a  leur  couronnement, 
en  feront  de  m£me ;  et  que  le  peuple  jure,  a  son  tour,  apres  le 
monarque,  de  lui  etre  obe"issant  et  fidele.  Tout  en  pensant  que  le 
pouvoir  monarchique  «le"gitime»  avait  e"te"  institue  par  Dieu,  ne 
fusse  que  par  Pinterme'diaire  du  peuple,  et  que  le  monarque  n'£tait 
responsable  qu'a  Dieu,  les  hommes  n'ayant  pas  le  droit  de  le  juger 
et  de  le  punir,  Crizanicz  ne  croit  pas  pouvoir  appliquer  ces  principes 
sans  quelques  restrictions :  il  les  formule,  probablement  non  sans 
Pinfluence  des  theories  de  quelques -uns  de  ses  confreres  sur  la 
souverainete"  du  peuple  dans  les  choses  temporelles ;  il  trouve  que 
cette  suje"tion  a  des  bornes  :  elle  peut  etre  enfreinte,  si  le  monarque, 
malgre"  ses  promesses,  devient  un  here'tique,  ou  livre  son  pays  au 
pouvoir  des  Strangers,  de  m£me  que  s'il  se  transforme  en  tyran,  que 
Dieu  peut  punir  par  Pinterme"diaire  du  peuple  ;  elle  ne  subsiste  plus 
envers  l'e"tranger,  qui  s'est  empare"  du  pouvoir.  Dans  ces  cas-la  le 
peuple  peut  se  choisir  un  autre  monarque,  avec  lequel  il  ^change 
de  nouvelles  promesses  ou  de  nouveaux  serments.1 

Du  reste  Crizanicz  n'a  pas  reussi  a  obtenir  la  confiance  et  le 
credit  qu'il  voulait  acque"rir  aupres  du  tsar,  et  a  entraver  la  pro- 
pagation des  ide"es  nouvelles  sur  PEtat,  meme  en  Moscovie.  Une 
illustration  assez  curieuse  de  Pinfiltration  de  ces  ide"es,  ou  plutdt 
des  Merits  qui  les  contenaient,  nous  presente  la  bibliotheque  d'un 
hollandais  russifie" — Andr£  Vinius. 

Le  djak  moscovite  Andre"  Vinius  s'e"tait  e"tabli  a  Moscou,  mais 
il  avait  conserve"  des  relations  avec  son  pays  natal,  nomme'ment 
avec  Witsen,  le  docte  bourguemestre  d' Amsterdam. 

Vinius  etait  un  grand  amateur  de  livres :  sa  bibliotheque  pre"- 
sentait  un  assortiment  d'ouvrages  assez  vane's,  mais  choisis  non  sans 
quelque  discernement ;  elle  contenait,  par  exemple,  des  Merits  sur 
la  religion,  la  philosophic,  les  belles-lettres,  le  droit,  etc. ;  parmi  les 

1  J.  Crizanicz,  Razgowori  ob  wladdtelstwu^  MS.  de  la  Bibliotheque  de  la 
Typographic  du  Synode  a  Moscou,  N°  I799/43Q?,  ft  33$,  345,  744-745, 
778,  etc.  ;  texte  public  par  Bezssonov,  v.  i.  pp.  276-278,  281,  310  sq.,  331, 
334,  402  sq.  ;  v.  ii.  pp.  29  sq.,  49-80,  168-169,  239-240,  etc.  Voir  aussi  la 
notice  de  1641,  le  rapport  de  Crizanicz  a  Levakovicz  de  1646-1647  et  quelques 
autres  documents,  publics  par  M.  Bjelokourov ;  v.  C.  BiMOKypOBt,  HZT> 
dyxoenuu  wcmnu  MocKoecnaio  OdiM/ecmea  xvii.  B.,  M.  1903,  pp.  87-126, 
144,  173-179,  etc. 

2B 


37°  -^-  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

ouvrages  sur  la  jurisprudence  et  la  politique  pre"dominaient  ceux 
qui  se  rapportaient  principalement  a  la  litte>ature  hollandaise  et 
allemande  du  XVle-XVIIe  siecles.  On  pouvait  y  trouver  quelques 
trace's  concernant  le  droit  naturel,  par  exemple,  celui  de  Grotius 
De  jure  belli  ac  pads  et  les  Annotata  de  son  antagoniste  a  Felde  ; 
les  Enarrationes  de  Kling  et  le  Richterbuchelein  (Gerichtsblichelein) 
de  Vigel,  tous  deux  ayant  quelque  rapport  au  droit  naturel,  et 
meme  le  programme  du  cours  sur  la  jurisprudence  que  Thomasius 
lisait  en  1699  a  Halle.  On  pouvait  y  rencontrer  aussi  quelques 
manuels  relatifs  a  la  jurisprudence  allemande  pratique,  par  exemple, 
le  Viridarium  juridicum_  de  Gilhausen,  la  Synopsis  politicarum 
doctrinarum  de  Besoldus,  etc.1 

La  presence  de  ces  ouvrages  dans  la  bibliotheque  du  djak 
moscovite,  qui  devint  Tun  des  collaborateurs  de  Pierre  le  Grand, 
peut  servir  d'indice  des  interets  qui  commengaient  a  poindre :  dans 
ce  temps-la  1'idee  se"culiere  de  1'Etat  s'introduisait  dej'a  en  Moscovie  ; 
en  somme,  sa  the"orie  se  reliait  au  droit  naturel,  mais  elle  ne  s'est 
affermie  dans  les  esprits  que  grace  a  la  secularisation  ulte"rieure  de 
l'ide"e  de  1'Etat,  promue  par  la  doctrine  de  Pintere^t  de  1'Etat  et 
manifested  dans  le  Polizeistaat. 

L'idee  utilitaire  de  1'Etat  a  traverse",  du  reste,  une  pe>iode  de 
transition  avant  d'acquerir  le  caractere  foncierement  seculier  et 
politique  qui  lui  est  propre. 

En  effet  on  peut  indiquer,  au  XVII6  siecle  et  au  commence- 
ment du  XVIIP,  quelques  doctrines  mixtes,  orthodoxes  et  utili- 
taires;  par  exemple,  celles  d'Ordine-Nachtchokine  et  de  Possochkov. 

Ordine-Nachtchokine,  homme  d'Etat  Eminent  du  temps  d'Alexej 
Mihajlovicz,  professait,  par  exemple,  une  doctrine  dans  laquelle 
les  concepts  de  Moscou,  comme  centre  du  monde  pravoslave  et 
de  la  prawda,  se  combinaient  avec  le  concept  du  profit  du  souverain 
(gossoudarevo  djelo\  qu'il  identifiait  avec  le  profit  de  1'Etat  (gos- 
soudastwennyja  djela).  C'est  au  point  de  vue  utilitaire,  et  non 
seulement  religieux  qu'Ordine-Nachtchokine  preTere,  par  exemple, 
la  monarchic  au  regime  republicain  qui  produit  «toutes  sortes 
d'erreurs  et  de  perturbations*;  c'est  au  meme  point  de  vue  qu'il 

1  Catalogue  de  la  bibliotheque  d' Andre  Vinius,  MS.  de  la  Bibliotheque 
Imperiale  des  Sciences  de  St-Petersbourg,  N°  xxi/a3  ;  transcriptions  russes 
dans  «  le  Cabinet  de  Pierre  le  Grand  »,  Archives  de  1'Etat,  Bxo^;.  N°  42,  ff.  37- 
70,  et  N°92,  ff.  321-357. 


xix]  LIdde  de  lEtat  en  Russie  371 

considere  les  rapports  du  souverain  et  des  sujets,  qu'il  exige  plus 
d'inde"pendance  pour  les  pouvoirs  interme"diaires  et  plus  d'initiative 
dans  le  self-government  des  villes,  qu'il  recommande  1'introduction 
de  plusieurs  institutions  europe"ennes,  etc. 

Ordine-Nachtchokine  n'e"tait  pas  le  seul  a  e"mettre  de  ces  ide"es  : 
on  pourrait  trouver  un  melange  analogue  dans  les  ouvrages  de 
Possochkov. 

La  doctrine  de  l'inte"r£t  de  1'Etat  commengait  meme  en  ce  temps- 
la  a  se  differencier  des  autres  :  Vinius,  qui  est  probablement  1'auteur 
d'un  curieux  projet  sur  les  e"tablissements  de  charite",  y  expose 
quelques-uns  de  ses  e"  laments  :  au  point  de  vue  «du  profit  du 
souverain  »,  qu'il  entend  principalement  dans  le  sens  mercantile,  et 
du  bien  commun,  il  exige  que  les  sujets  s'instruisent  et  travaillent 
«  pour  ne  pas  manger  en  vain  leur  pain  quotidien  ».  En  lisant  ce 
.  projet  on  dirait  que  c'est  Pierre  le  Grand  qui  parle  :  en  tout  cas,  il 
s'est  tres  bien  assimile'  cette  conception  utilitaire  de  1'Etat,  et  a 
grandement  contribue"  a  son  affermissement.1 

Pierre  le  Grand  ne  pouvait,  eVidemment,  rompre  avec  les 
anciennes  traditions  moscovites  :  dans  ses  ordonnances  et  autres 
Merits  il  cite  les  theories  du  tsar  et  de  1'etat  pravoslaves,  et  men- 
tionne  le  principe  de  la  prawda^  particulierement  dans  ses  applica- 
tions a  la  justice  ;  mais  c'est  une  ide"e  seculiere  et  utilitaire,  celle  de 
1'interet  de  1'Etat,  qu'il  prone  le  plus  souvent. 

C'est  bien  la  conception  de  1'interet  de  1'Etat,  intimement 
lie"e  a  celle  de  la  «  police  »,  et  non  pas  la  notion  e"troite  de  la 
«raison  d'Etat»,  que  Pierre  le  Grand  admet  pour  principe  de  sa 
politique. 

Cette  ide"e,  effleure"e  par  Seckendorff,  pr^curseur  des  polic^istes 
du  XVIir  siecle,  s'^tait  d^ja  incorpor^e  dans  la  «  monarchic  absolue  » 
de  Louis  XIV  et  se  pratiquait  par  Colbert  ;  elle  se  d^veloppait  en 
Prusse  dans  le  Polizeistaat,  particulierement  depuis  1'ordonnance 
du  roi  Fre"de"ric  Guillaume  [er  du  2  juin  1713  ;  elle  n'e"tait  pas  tout 
a  fait  ^trangere  aux  hommes  d'etat  russes  du  XVII8  siecle  ;  et 
c'est  plutdt  de  la  pratique  que  de  la  the'orie,  peu  e'labore'e  d'ailleurs, 
que  Pierre  le  Grand  a  naturellement  pulse"  1'id^e  utilitaire  de  1'Etat. 

Pierre  le  Grand  en  a  meme  fait  le  principe  dominant  de  son 
systeme,  et  s'en  rapportait  a  ce  principe,  conforme  a  sa  nature  active 


1  06^  odWfecmeeuuoM-b  npuspnniu  ea  Pocciu,  H3,n.  npn 
A.  CToroMt,  CUB.,  1818  r.,  P.  i.  pp.  31-39. 


372  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

et  a  son  gout  novateur,  pour  motiver  la  plupart  de  ses  reTormes. 
Le  tsar  ne  distinguait  pas  le  « profit  (polza)  du  souverain»  du 
«  profit  de  1'Etat »,  et  identifiait  ces  concepts  avec  ceux  de  l'inte"ret  de 
1'lLtat;  le  reglement  ge"ne"ral  des  colleges,  par  exemple,  explique 
ce  qu'il  faut  entendre  par  ce  terme  :  «l'interet» — c'est  le  «  profit  ou 
Putilite" »  du  souverain  et  de  1'Etat.1 

D'apres  ce  principe  le  tsar  et  son  gouvernement  devait  prendre 
soin  du  bien-etre  de  la  population,  utile  &  1'Etat ;  c'est  en  vue  de 
« 1'utilite"  commune »  qu'il  devait  le"gife"rer,  gouverner,  policer,  pro- 
te"ger  et  juger  ses  sujets ;  d'autre  part,  les  sommations  du  pouvoir, 
dont  il  disposait  envers  ses  sujets,  devenaient  d'autant  plus  irre"- 
fragables,  qu'ils  se  profe"raient  au  nom  de  ce  principe ;  les  sujets 
lui  devaient  une  obe"issance  incontestable. 

Cependant,  tout  en  renforc.ant  les  traditions  du  pouvoir  auto- 
cratique  qu'il  avait  la  possibility  d'exercer  sans  contrainte,  Pierre  le 
Grand  ne  pouvait  conside"rer  1'inte'ret  de  1'Etat  comme  un  principe 
juridique  de  sa  constitution  ;  en  1'interpr^tant  comme  il  1'entendait 
lui-meme,  il  n'en  faisait,  au  fond,  qu'une  regie  de  sa  politique ;  au 
nom  de  1'lLtat,  de  son  inte"r£t  et  du  bien-etre  ge"ne"ral  qu'il  lui  sub- 
ordonnait,  le  tsar  £tablissait  ses  relations  avec  ses  sujets  meme  dans 
les  details  de  leur  vie  prive*e. 

D'ailleurs,  en  prenant  inte"ret  £  la  civilisation  plut6t  protestante 
que  catholique,  Pierre  le  Grand  a  favorise"  lui-meme  la  propagation 
de  quelques  notions  du  droit  naturel,  dans  lequel  on  pouvait  trouver 
les  dements  d'une  conception  juridique  de  1'Etat :  il  a  fait  faire,  par 
exemple,  une  traduction  russe  du  petit  traite"  de  Pufendorff  sur  les 
devoirs  de  1'homme  et  du  citoyen,  et  a  contribue"  a  1'expansion  de 
quelques  ide"es  de  Hobbes,  conformes  a  ses  fins  politiques. 

L'un  des  collaborateurs  de  Pierre  le  Grand — le  gouverneur  de 
Kiev,  Golitzyne — organisa  meme  toute  une  se>ie  de  travaux,  con- 
sistant  a  traduire  les  principaux  ouvrages  sur  le  droit  naturel  et  la 
politique ;  The"ofane  Prokopowicz  y  prenait  part,  avec  quelques 
eleves  de  l'acade"mie  de  Kiev.  C'est  grace  a  cette  organisation  que 
les  grands  traite"s  de  Grotius,  de  Pufendorff,  de  Locke  et  de  bien 
d'autres  moralistes  et  politiques  du  XVIF  et  du  XVIII6  siecles 
ont  paru  dans  des  traductions  russes.  Ces  traductions  ne  sont  pas 
toujours  completes :  elles  pre"sentent  quelquefois  des  coupures  ou 
des  abreViations  faites  non  sans  quelque  conformite  avec  le  but 
i.  Co6p.  3aK.,  v.  vi.  N°  3534. 


xix]  L Idde  de  r  &tat  en  Russie  373 

que  les  traducteurs  se  proposaient — de  donner  un  apergu  g£ne"ral 
de  telle  ou  telle  doctrine. 

Une  notice  pre"liminaire  que  je  trouve  a  la  tete  de  la  traduction 
russe  de  1'essai  de  Locke  sur  le  gouvernement  pre"sente  quelque 
inte"ret :  cette  notice  donne  une  ide"e  de  ce  qu'on  entendait  alors  par 
le  droit  naturel,  et  est  congue  ainsi  qu'il  suit.  «  Chacun  doit  connaitre 
[les  principes]  d'apres  lesquels  il  doit  vivre  en  socie"te"  civile  en  con- 
formite'  avec  les  lois  naturelles.  ...  II  est  ne"cessaire  de  distinguer 
diffe'rents  genres  de  relations  civiles  :  celle  du  mari  et  de  la  femme  ; 
celle  des  parents  et  des  enfants ;  celle  des  maitres  et  des  esclaves ; 
celle  de  plusieurs  families  demeurant  ensemble  et  subordonn£es  a 
une  meme  loi.  Bien  des  auteurs  ont  e"crit  sur  ces  matieres,  mais 
les  modernes  en  ont  traite"  avec  plus  de  perfection  que  les  anciens ; 
ils  ont  e"lucide"  et  affermi  les  principes  de  la  morale  et  de  la  vie  civile. 
Grotius  et  Pufendorff  en  sont  les  fondateurs ;  plusieurs  autres  leur 
ont  succe"de",  mais  ne  s'accordent  pas  entre  eux.  D'ailleurs,  tous 
sont  d'accord  que  la  morale  et  la  vie  civile  sont  fondles  sur  les 
devoirs  que  chacun  a  envers  soi-meme  et  envers  les  autres.  Les 
devoirs  de  chacun  envers  soi-meme  reposent  sur  le  principe  :  connais- 
toi  toi-me'me  ;  les  devoirs  de  chacun  envers  les  autres  sur  le  principe  : 
ne  fais  pas  aux  autres  ce  que  tu  ne  voudrais  pas  qu'on  te  fasse. 
La  divergence  des  opinions  ne  se  fait  jour  que  quand  on  commence 
a  raisonner  sur  1'^tablissement  de  la  societe"  civile,  sur  les  lois  qui 
en  ont  etc*  le  fondement,  et  sur  le  pouvoir,  auquel  elle  doit  e"tre 
subordonne"e.  En  effet,  les  uns  pensent  que  les  hommes  ont  £t£ 
obliges,  pour  se  soustraire  aux  agressions  et  a  la  ruine,  de  se 
subjuguer  au  plus  fort  et  de  vivre  sous  les  lois,  qu'il  voudrait 
bien  leur  donner.  D'autres  supposent  que  les  hommes  se  sont 
spontane"ment  rassemble's  en  societe",  ayant  en  vue  leur  inte*ret 
et  leur  tranquillite",  pour  conserver  leur  liberte",  leur  proprie'te'  et 
leur  vie  de  toute  agression  et  violence ;  que  grace  a  une  entente 
commune  ils  se  sont  faits  des  lois  et  se  sont  choisis  un  gardien  de 
ces  lois,  qui  devait  vivre  selon  elles  et  n'avait  pas  de  pouvoir  sur  la 
liberte",  la  proprie'te'  et  la  vie  des  citoyens.  D'aucuns  pensent  enfin 
que  les  hommes,  rassemble's  en  vue  de  ces  fins,  ont  donne"  les  lois, 
qu'ils  se  sont  faites,  a  garder  non  pas  a  un  seul  homme,  mais  a 
plusieurs,  car  un  seul  est  plus  apte  a  se  tromper  que  plusieurs. » 1 

1  MS.  de  la  traduction  russe  de  1'ouvrage  de  J.  Locke  sur  <tle  gouverne- 
ment civil »,  a  la  Bibliotheque  Imperiale  de  St-Petersbourg,  F.  ii.  41. 


374  <d-  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

C'est  dans  ces  conceptions  differentes  que  le  droit  nature! 
a  eu  quelque  propagation  en  Russie  au  commencement  du  XVIIP 
siecle.  Pierre  le  Grand  et  son  collaborateur  The"ofane  Prokopo- 
vicz  ont  particulierement  prise"  la  the"orie  de  Hobbes,  qu'il  e"tait 
facile  d'adapter  au  pouvoir  autocratique  du  tsar;  Golitzyne  et 
Tatichczev  ont  pre"fe"re"  les  id£es  de  Grotius  et  de  ses  e"mules,  et  en 
ont  profite",  de  fagons  diffe"rentes,  dans  leurs  projets  de  1730. 

Pierre  le  Grand  et  The"ofane  Prokopovicz  ont  expose"  leur  doc- 
trine principalement  dans  le  traite"  intitule"  Prawda  voli  monarchej, 
c'est-a-dire,  «Du  droit  que  le  monarque  a  de  se  designer  un 
successeur  ».  Les  principes  de  ce  traite",  hormis  les  Saintes  ^critures, 
sont  pulse's  en  grande  partie  des  ouvrages  de  Hobbes.  On  peut  y 
remarquer  surtout  cette  influence,  par  exemple,  dans  la  disserta- 
tion sur  1'origine  du  pouvoir  absolu,  dont  le  monarque  est 
revetu  non  seulement  par  la  grace  de  Dieu,  mais  aussi  par 
« le  peuple »  qu'il  inspire ;  « le  peuple »  s'est  destitue"  de  sa 
« volonte"  commune »  et  1'a  donne"e  au  monarque ;  investi  de  ce 
pouvoir  souverain,  le  monarque  absolu  n'est  responsable  qu'a 
Dieu ;  il  n'est  pas  subordonne"  aux  lois  qu'il  donne  a  ses  sujets ; 
il  les  execute  sans  contrainte  par  son  bon  vouloir  ;  et  meme  s'il  les 
transgresse,  il  ne  peut  etre  juge"  par  ses  sujets,  s'il  n'a  pas  e'te' 
e"lu  a  condition  d'observer  certaines  clauses  restrictives,  qu'il  a 
expresse"ment  accepte"es.  Le  monarque  russe,  dont  le  pouvoir  n'a 
pas  e"te"  limite"  par  des  clauses,  est  done  absolu,  et  la  Prawda 
voli  monarchej  lui  attribue  la  summa  potestas,  que  Theofane 
Prokopovicz  de"finit,  d'apres  la  formule  de  Grotius,  comme  «  celle  dont 
les  actes  sont  independants  de  tout  autre  pouvoir  supe"rieur,  en  sorte 
qu'ils  ne  peuvent  etre  annulle*s  par  aucune  autre  volont£  humaine  ».1 

Dans  la  formule  de  1'autocratisme  que  donnent  les  reglements  de 
I'arm6e  et  de  la  marine  de  Pierre  le  Grand  on  retrouve  ces  e"le"ments, 

1  H.  Grotius,  De  jure  belli  ac  pads,  lib.  i.  cap.  3,  §  7.  IIpaB,na  BOM 
MOHapmeft,  CIIB.,  1726,  ff.  n,  15,  i6-i6v.,  etc.  Theophane  Proko- 
povicz a  probablement  puise  ses  idees  non  seulement  dans  les  traites  de 
Hobbes,  Grotius,  etc.,  mais  aussi  dans  celui  de  T.  F.  Buddaeus  intitule  : 
Exercitatio  juris  naturalis  de  successoribus  primogenitorum,  Halle,  1695  ; 
voyez  ses  Selecta  juris  naturae  et  gentium,  1717.  II  est  vrai  que 
Theophane  Prokopovicz  introduit  dans  sa  formule  I'ide'e  du  «  bien  commun  » : 
le  peuple  s'est  destitue  de  sa  volonte  en  faveur  du  monarque  pour  qu'il  le 
gouverne  «  pour  le  bien  commun  »  ;  mais  c'est  plutot  comme  motif  ou  comme 
fin,  que  comme  clause,  expressement  acceptee  par  celui  qu'on  revetait  du 
pouvoir  absolu. 


xix]  Uldde  de  r£tat  en  Russie  375 

exprime"s,  du  reste,  dans  les  termes  de  la  decision  du  rigsdag 
sue"dois  de  1693 ;  mais  la  formule  russe  contient  un  mot,  qui 
porte  peut-etre,  si  je  ne  me  trompe  pas,  les  traces  de  1'influence 
des  id£es  de  Hobbes  ou  de  Pufendorff:  d'apres  cette  formule  le 
souverain  gouverne  non  seulement  selon  «sa  volont£»,  mais 
comme  il  le  trouve  le  plus  « convenable »  (blagomnjenie).  Or, 
Hobbes  admettait  que  le  souverain  peut  user  de  son  pouvoir, 
comme  il  le  trouve  le  plus  convenable  (expedient)  pour  la  conser- 
vation de  la  paix  et  de  la  s£curit£  commune ;  et  Pufendorff  expri- 
mait  aussi  une  idee  analogue  en  disant  que  le  monarque  dispose  du 
pouvoir  absolu,  grace  auquel  il  peut  gouverner  d'apres  son  propre 
jugement  ...  en  tant  que  l'e"tat  present  des  choses  parait  1'exiger.1 

Et  c'est  justement  de  cette  maniere  que  Pierre  le  Grand  pouvait 
relier  la  the"orie  du  pouvoir  absolu  du  monarque  a  la  doctrine  de 
l'inte~ret  de  I'lttat. 

II  serait  facile  de  d£duire  de  ces  propositions  quelques  con- 
clusions concernant  les  prerogatives  du  monarque — la  subordination 
de  1'Eglise  a  1'Etat ;  la  suppression  des  institutions  qui  pouvaient 
gener  le  pouvoir  autocratique,  de  la  douma  des  bojares,  des 
assemblies  des  e"tats  (zemskii  ssobory\  etc. ;  mais  je  n'ai  pas  la 
possibility  d'entrer  dans  ces  developpements. 

D'ailleurs,  les  prerogatives  du  monarque,  indues  dans  la  formule 
pr£cite"e,  ne  demandaient  pas  d'elucidations  aussi  e"tendues  que  ses 
devoirs.  La  Prawda  voli  monarchej  les  d£duit  des  « lois  inscrites 
par  le  Cre"ateur  dans  le  coeur  des  hommes»,  ce  qui  donnait  la 
possibility  de  les  relier  aux  « lois  naturelles  » ;  les  reglements  et  les 
ordonnances  les  rattachent  plutot  a  la  doctrine  utilitaire  de  1'Etat. 

Quoiqu'il  en  soit,  c'est  en  se  basant  sur  la  theologie  naturelle, 
et  particulierement  sur  la  politique  utilitaire,  qu'on  pouvait  se  faire 
une  idee  du  monarque  comme  du  premier  serviteur  de  1'Etat. 
Pierre  le  Grand  a  assez  clairement  exprim£  cette  pens£e,  en  disant 
«  qu'il  n'e"pargnait  pas  sa  personne  pour  l'utilit£  commune  de  1'Etat ». 

C'est  d'apres  des  principes  analogues  que  Pierre  le  Grand 
concevait  les  droits  et  les  devoirs  de  ses  sujets  :  l'£tat  leur  concede 
des  droits  dont  quelques-uns  remontent  meme  au  droit  naturel, 
mais  la  plupart  se  conforme  aux  services  qu'ils  lui  rendent ;  car  ils 

1  Th.  Hobbes,  Leviathan,  Pt.  ii.  ch.  17  (Works,  ed.  W.  Molesworth,  v.  iii. 
p.  158).  S.  Pufendorff,  De  officio  hominis  et  civis,  lib.  ii.  cap.  ix.  §  5.  Ho  A. 
Co6.  3a,K.  v.  v.  N°  3006  (ch.  iii.  §  20)  ;  v.  vi.  N°  3485  (liv.  v.  ch.  i.  §  2,  glose). 


376  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

doivent  incontestablement  servir  au  bien  de  l'£tat ;  ils  deviennent 
ses  serviteurs,  c'est-a-dire  ceux  du  monarque,  comme  son  repre"- 
sentant,  et  ils  lui  en  sont  responsables. 

Cest  un  melange  analogue  d'ide"es  rationnelles  et  utilitaires  qu'on 
retrouve  dans  plusieurs  autres  principes,  assimile's  par  Pierre  le 
Grand,  par  exemple,  dans  celui  de  le"galite". 

L'ide"e  de  «  1'ordre  rationnel »  avait  peut-etre  quelque  peu  influ£ 
sur  le  principe  de  le"galite"  de  Pierre  le  Grand,  qu'il  n'a  pas  re"ussi, 
d'ailleurs,  a  deVelopper  syste"matiquement  dans  un  code  des  Ibis : 
il  distinguait  les  lois  «  perpe"  tuelles  »  des  lois  temporelles,  le  gouverne- 
ment  de  1'administration  de  la  justice,  les  divers  organes  qui  la 
pratiquaient,  les  uns  des  autres,  etc. ;  mais  la  doctrine  de  l'inte"ret  de 
1'foat  donnait  encore  plus  de  force  a  ces  principes :  «  rien  n'est  plus 
indispensable  au  gouvernement  de  1'Etat,  disait  Pierre  le  Grand,  que 
1'observation  des  lois  » ;  c'est  en  correspondance  avec  cette  doctrine 
utilitaire  qu'il  proclamait,  par  exemple,  la  ne"cessit£  de  son  systeme 
de  surveillance  fiscale  et  de  la  justice  administrative  qu'il  commengait 
a  distinguer  de  celle  qui  administrait « les  torts  particuliers  ». 

Ce  m^me  principe  de  tegalite"  re"clamait  eVidemment  1'observation 
obligatoire  des  lois  par  tous  les  particuliers,  qui  ne  pouvaient  s'en 
de"dire  par  leur  ignorance. 

Du  reste,  Pierre  le  Grand  n'e"tait  pas  en  e"tat  de  donner  a  son 
principe  de  le"galite"  des  bases  solides :  comme  monarque  absolu  il 
pouvait  toujours  s'immiscer  dans  toutes  les  affaires,  et  son  regime 
bureaucratique  tenait  a  sa  merci  les  particuliers. 

Ce  n'est  que  dans  le  domaine  de  la  justice  que  ce  principe  a 
regu  une  valeur  plus  inde"pendante.  Le  Tableau  de  la  procedure 
civile,  compose"  sous  1'influence  du  code  de  Saxe,  se  reTere  meme 
au  droit  naturel,  qui  en  est  « la  base  »,  car,  d'apres  le  droit  naturel, 
«  chacun  a  le  droit  de  se  conserver  et  de  se  defendre  des  attentats 
des  autres  » ;  mais  ce  principe  n'y  est  pas  de" veloppe",  par  exemple, 
dans  ses  applications  a  la  proprie"te".  C'est  plut6t  la  doctrine  utili- 
taire du  Polizeistaat  qui  re"servait  plus  d'independance  a  la 
justice.  Le  tsar  preTe>ait  donner  des  regies  generates  aux  cours  de 
justice  que  d'intervenir  dans  les  cas  particuliers  qu'elles  devaient 
juger  d'apres  ces  regies;  mais,  en  conside>ant  «tout  ce  qui  est 
nuisible  a  PJitat »  comme  un  crime,  il  donnait  la  possibility  d'appli- 
quer  ce  point  de  vue  utilitaire  et  politique  a  la  procedure  criminelle  ; 
en  definitive,  il  restait  lui-meme,  pour  bien  des  cas,  1'instance 


xix]  L  Idde  de  r£tat  en  Russie  377 

supreme  ou  unique,  par  exemple,  dans  sa  «  chancellerie  secrete  »,  et 
pouvait  toujours  soumettre  a  son  propre  jugement  tout  ce  que  bon  lui 
semblalt,  et  rendre  ses  decisions  conforme'ment  a  ses  fins  politiques. 

D'ailleurs,  le  principe  de  l^galite*  dans  1'administration  de  la 
justice  garantissait  1'inviolabilite"  des  personnes  et  des  biens  et  leur 
droit  dese  «deTendre  des  attentats  des  autres  »,  mais  avec  les  reserves, 
implique'es  dans  le  regime  politique,  que  je  viens  d'indiquer.1 

La  doctrine  de  1'Etat,  bas£e  sur  le  droit  naturelde  Hobbes,  recelait 
done  une  grave  lacune  qu'elle  ne  re"ussissait  pas  a  combler  par  les 
notions  supplementaires  de"duites  de  Pide"e  utilitaire  de  1'Etat  :  cette 
the"orie  n'etablissait  pas  ce  rapport  juridique  entre  le  souverain  et  les 
sujets,  que  Grotius  pre"supposait  de"ja  dans  son  corpus  voluntate  con- 
tractum,  et  que  ses  e'mules  ont  essaye"  d'elucider  dans  leurs  trait£s. 

Et  c'est  ce  que  quelques  politiques  russes  ont  su  appre"cier  : 
Golitzyne  et  Tatichczev  en  profiterent  dans  leurs  projets  de  la 
constitution  de  1730,  quoique  de  manieres  diffe"  rentes. 

Golitzyne  ne  s'est  mis  a  e"tudier  le  droit  naturel  qu'apres  un 
assez  long  stade  preparatoire,  que  je  n'ai  pas  le  temps  d'elucider 
ici  :  pendant  son  se"jour  en  Italic  il  a  pu  connaitre  quelques  ide"es 
de  Machiavel,  de  Paruta  et  de  Boccalini,  qu'il  pouvait  lire  dans  les 
originaux,  et  quelques  traditions  du  «  Conseil  des  dix  »  de  Venise  ; 
mais  c'est  plutdt  a  Kiev,  et  peut-etre  non  sans  1'influence  de  Th£ofane 
Prokopovicz,  qu'il  s'inte"ressa  aux  trace's  de  Grotius,  de  PufendorfF 
et  de  Locke,  qu'il  a  fait  traduire  a  Pacade"mie  de  Kiev. 

II  est  vrai  qu'au  nombre  de  ces  traductions  Golitzyne  en  a  fait 
faire  plusieurs  qui  ne  concernaient  pas  le  droit  naturel,  comme  celles, 
par  exemple,  des  ouvrages  de  Furius,  de  Clapmaier,  de  Lange,  de 
Richelieu,  de  Fredro,  de  Bessel  et  de  Schroeder  sur  les  regies  de  la 
politique;  que  parmi  les  trace's  qui  rentraient  dans  le  domaine  du 
droit  naturel,  il  ne  distinguait  pas  assez  les  classiques  des  ouvrages 
secondaires,  tels  que  ceux  de  Vernulaeus  ou  de  Cellarius,  de  Faust 
et  de  Felwinger  ;  mais,  m£me  dans  ses  ouvrages  de  seconde  main, 
comme,  par  exemple,  dans  celui  de  Felwinger,  qui  s'en  rapportait 
a  Grotius,  Golitzyne  pouvait  deja  puiser  quelques  idees  sur  la 
the"orie  contractuelle  de  1'Etat.2 


.  Co6p.  3aK.,  v.  v.  N°  3006,  P.  i.  ch.  i.  §§  i,  7  et  8. 
2  Bufid.  3an.,  1861,  v.  iii.  p.  320.     Mamep.  dan  ucmopiu 

v.  iv.    pp.   135,    178-190.     KH.  H.   TojumHiTB,  Hoeua  dannufi   o 
KH.  ft.  M.  rojiuy/una,  M.  1  900. 


378  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

D'ailleurs,  Golitzyne  connaissait  probablement  quelque  peu  les 
ouvrages  classiques  sur  le  droit  nature!,  qu'il  pouvait  £tudier  grace 
aux  traductions  manuscrites  de  sa  bibliotheque.  La  traduction  du 
trait^  de  Grotius,  par  exemple,  du  reste  incomplete,  porte  peut- 
etre  les  traces  de  son  usage :  elle  a  a  ses  marges  quelques  croix, 
faites  a  1'encre.1  La  traduction  du  traite"  de  Pufendorff,  peu  original, 
mais  syste"matique,  en  donne  beaucoup  plus  de  preuves  :  cette 
traduction,  faite  non  sans  quelques  abreViations,  du  reste  assez 
heureuses,  est  marquee  de  croix  justement  aux  endroits  qui  pou- 
vaient  inte"resser  un  homme  et  un  politique  tel  que  Golitzyne :  les 
marges  du  livre  vii.,  qui  traite  de  1'origine  et  de  la  constitution  des 
socie"te"s  civiles  et  des  Etats,  des  fondements  de  la  souverainete,  des 
droits  et  des  devoirs  du  souverain,  des  diverses  formes  de  gouverne- 
ment  et  des  diverses  manieres  d'acque"rir  la  souverainete",  par 
exemple,  sont  bariole"es  de  croix.  D'ailleurs,  les  textes  relatifs  a 
la  the"orie  des  deux  conventions  ge"nerales,  grace  auxquelles  la  societe" 
civile  se  forme,  pre"sentent  sous  ce  rapport  une  particularity  curieuse  : 
ce  n'est  pas  le  §  7,  celui  qui  traite  de  Tengagement  de  chacun  avec 
tous  les  autres,  mais  le  §  8  (correspondant  au  §  7  de  la  traduction) 
qui  est  marque"  de  croix ;  or,  ce  paragraphe  traite  de  la  seconde 
convention,  c'est-a-dire  de  celle  qui  se  fait  apres  1'engagement  de 
chacun  avec  tous  les  autres  a  se  joindre  ensemble  pour  toujours  en 
un  seul  corps,  et  qui  consiste  en  ce  que,  apres  avoir  choisi  une  ou 
plusieurs  personnes  a  qui  Ton  confere  le  pouvoir  de  gouverner  la 
societe",  ceux  qui  sont  revetus  de  cette  autorit£  supreme  s'engagent 
a  veiller  avec  soin  au  bien  public,  et  les  autres,  en  m£me  temps,  leur 
promettent  une  fidele  obe"issance.2 

Les  theories  de  Pufendorff  sur  la  distinction  du  pouvoir  souverain 
et  du  pouvoir  absolu,  sur  la  monarchic  limited  qu'il  en  deduisait, 
sur  les  promesses  solennelles  et  «  particulieres  »  que  les  Princes  font 
en  acceptant  cette  autorite"  borne"e,  sur  la  clause  « commissoire » 
d'apres  laquelle  le  roi  est  declare"  d^chu  de  la  couronne,  s'il  peche 
centre  ces  lois,  sur  1'etablissement  d'un  conseil  sans  le  consente- 
ment  duquel  le  roi  ne  puisse  rien  faire  en  matiere  des  choses  dont 

1  MS.  de  la  Bibliotheque  Imperiale  de  St-Petersbourg,  F.  ii.  36.       Cette 
traduction,  d'ailleurs  incomplete,  ,a  ^te  executee  d'apres  Pedition  d'Amsterdam 
de  1712,  par  les  etudiants  de  Tacademie  de  Kiev,  Oronovskij  et  d'autres. 

2  S.  Pufendorff,  De  jure  naturae  et  gentium,  lib.  vii.  cap.  2,  §§  7  et  8  ;  cap. 
vi.  §§  9  et  10,  etc.      MS.  de  la  traduction  russe,  a  la  Bibliotheque  Imperiale  de 
St-Petersbourg,  F.  ii.  26. 


xix]  Uldde  de  r  lit  at  en  Russie  379 

on  ne  veut  pas  le  laisser  absolument  le  maitre,  ou  bien  sur  d'autres 
institutions  analogues  pouvaient  eVidemment  inte>esser  Golitzyne  : 
il  £tait  imbu  d'ide"es  aristocratiques ;  il  sympathisait  probablement 
au  role  que  les  bojares  et  ses  ancetres  en  particulier  avaient  jou£  aux 
Elections  de  Basile  Schoujskij  et  de  Mihafl  Romanov ;  lui-m£me 
avide  du  pouvoir  que  les  membres  du  conseil  s'e"taient  arrog£ 
quelquesfois,  il  e"tait  tout  pr£t  a  re"diger  la  convention  qu'il  voulait 
conclure  entre  Anna  Ivanovna  et  le  peuple,  repre"sente"  par  le  conseil, 
et  qu'il  avait  probablement  pourvue  dans  sa  redaction  definitive 
d'une  «  clause  commissoire  ». 

C'est  done  une  the*orie  fort  analogue  a  celle  de  Pufendorff  sur 
« la  seconde  convention  »,  et  non  la  doctrine  de  la  souverainete"  du 
peuple  et  du  pouvoir  le"gislatif  de  Locke,  dont  le  trait£  a  e"te*  aussi 
traduit  sous  les  auspices  de  Golitzyne,  que  nous  retrouvons  dans  son 
projet  de  la  constitution  de  I73O.1 

Cette  the"orie  e"tait  applicable  non  seulement  a  1'origine  des 
socie"te"s,  mais  a  un  interregne  dans  le  genre  de  celui  qui  pre"ce"da 
1'election  d'Anna  Ivanovna  en  1730:  et  Golitzyne  voulait  prouver 
aux  membres  du  conseil,  assembles  dans  la  nuit  du  18  and  19 
Janvier,  qu'on  e"tait  en  plein  interregne. 

Dans  ses  projets  Golitzyne  ne  parle  point  de  la  premiere  con- 
vention :  il  n'avait  pas  1'intention  de  convoquer  une  assemble 
ge"ne"rale  pour  re"gler  la  forme  du  gouvernement,  et  se  bornait, 
probablement,  a  conside>er  le  conseil  des  grands  (werhov- 
niki),  a  1'instar  du  conseil  des  electeurs  de  1'empire  germanique, 
comme  repr£sentant  «le  peuple  russe».  En  tout  cas  les  clauses 
de  1730  ont  e"t£  re"dige"es  par  le  conseil  (avec  trois  personnes 
qui  n'y  appartenaient  pas),  et  les  e"tats  supe>ieurs  de  1'empire  n'ont 
e"t£  convoque"s  que  pour  decider  la  question  s'il  fallait  « confier »  le 
pouvoir  a  Anna  Ivanovna. 

D'ailleurs,  Golitzyne  concevait  le  rapport  entre  Anna  Ivanovna 
et  tous  les  e"tats  de  1'empire  comme  une  convention  formelle  :  elle  se 
re"duisait  a  « la  promesse »  solennelle  et  particuliere  de  la  princesse 
d'observer  les  clauses  qui  limitaient  son  pouvoir  monarchique,  entre 
autres  la  clause  commissoire,  et  a  « la  promesse »  des  e*tats  qui 

1  MS.  de  la  Biblioth&que  Imperiale  de  St-Petersbourg,  F.  ii.  41.  La 
traduction  russe  du  traite  de  Locke  est,  peut-etre,  la  meilleure  de  celles  qui 
ont  6t6  faites  sous  les  auspices  de  Golitzyne  ;  Theofane  Prokopovicz  y  a, 
peut-etre,  pris  part.  Golitzyne  a  pourvu  son  exemplaire  de  sa  signature,  ce 
qui  donne  lieu  a  supposer  qu'il  y  attachait  quelque  prix. 


380  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

s'engageaient  a  une  fidele  ob&ssance  envers  elle.  Ce  pacte  devait  etre 
valide"  par  deux  actes  corre"latifs :  les  «  conditions*,  signers  par  Anna 
Ivanovna  et  «le  serment»  (celui  des  16  clauses),  fait  par  ses  sujets. 

Les  clauses  de  cette  convention  correspondaient  en  grande 
partie  non  seulement  aux  theories  de  Pufendorff  et  d'autres  juristes, 
mais  a  la  constitution  sue"doise,  c'est-a-dire  au  «  serment  du  roi »  et  a 
«la  forme  du  gouvernement»  de  1720.  Cependant,  je  ne  pense  pas  que 
Golitzyne  y  ait  pulse*  tout  le  contenu  de  sa  pens^e  intime :  il  murissait 
ses  id£es  depuis  une  trentaine  d'anne'es  sous  diverses  influences ;  dans 
les  actes  sue"dois  de  1720,  sur  lesquels  Pick  a  pu  lui  donner  quelques 
renseignements  opportuns,  il  trouva  des  formules  tout  pretes,  qu'il 
a  pu  utiliser  a  la  hate  apres  la  mort  inattendue  de  Pierre  II.1 

C'est  done  en  se  basant,  du  moins  en  partie,  sur  l'ide"e  juridique 
ou  contractuelle  de  1'Etat,  que  Golitzyne  a  e'labore'  la  convention  de 
1730,  qui  devait  servir  a  ses  fins  politiques. 

Cependant,  la  the'orie  de  Golitzyne  pretait  le  flanc  a  de  se>ieuses 
objections ;  il  supposait  que  le  conseil  des  grands  repre*sentait  le 
peuple  ;  mais  c'est  justement  ce  qu'il  fallait  prouver  ;  et  la  noblesse 
(le  schljahetstwo)  assemble  a  Moscou  pour  les  fetes  qui  devaient 
avoir  lieu  a  1'occasion  du  mariage  de  feu  1'empereur  Pierre  II,  ne 
voulait  pas  y  croire ;  elle  craignait  I'oligarchie  des  grands  et  ne 
pouvait  avoir  confiance  en  Golitzyne,  malgre'  les  quelques  conces- 
sions qu'il  a  du  lui  faire. 

L'un  de  ses  adversaires  politiques  les  plus  eclaire"s,  Tatichczev, 

1  R.  KopcaKOBi),  Boy/apenie  uMnepampimu  AHHU  loannoenu,  Kas. 
1880,  pp.  179-188.  D'ailleurs,  la  question  sur  1'origine  et  la  signification  du 
plan  de  Golitzyne,  que  je  n'ai  pas  la  possibilite  d'analyser  ici  en  detail,  est 
encore  sujette  a  controverse  ;  voir  les  conceptions  differentes  de  MM.  H.  Hjarne, 
«  Ryska  Konstitutions- project  ar  1730  efter  svenska  forebilder, »  dans  Hist. 
Tidskrift,  1884,  pp.  189-272,  et  II.  MHJUOKOBT),  «  BepxoBHHKH  H  uuiaxeTCTBO » 
dans  Kn  ucmopiu  pyccKoii  unmeajiuieHWu,  CUB.,  1902,  pp.  1-51  ;  A. 
AjzeKcfceBi,,  Jleieuda  o6?>  ojimapxuHecKUXT>  mendeHiiiinx*  eepxoeuaio  mauuaio 
coen>ma  ;  CUMHUH  nepconu  e*  eepxoenoM^  maunoM'b  coerbrnvb^  etc., 
M.  1896,  1898  ;  et  W.  Recke,  «  Die  Verfassungsplane  der  russischen  Oligar- 
chen  im  Jahre  1730  und  die  Thronbesteigung  der  Kaiserin  Anna  Ivanovna, » 
dans  Zeitschrift  fur  osteuropdische  Geschichte^  Bd.  ii.  D'ailleurs,  meme  ceux  qui 
supposent,  comme  lefont,  parexemple,  MM.  Filipov  et  Recke,  que  les  rapports 
qui  s'etaient  deja  etablis  entre  le  pouvoir  souverain  et  le  conseil  apres  la  dis- 
grace de  Menchikov  avaient  beaucoup  d'analogies  avec  les  conditions  de  1730, 
pensent  que  celles-ci  donnaient  au  conseil  de  jure  ce  dont  il  disposait  deja  de 
facto ;  mais  c'est  justement  ce  qu'il  importe  d'elucider  ;  v.  W.  Recke,  op.  tit., 
#.,  p.  39- 


xix]  LIdde  de  r  lit  at  en  Russie  381 

s'attacha  a  d6montrer,  en  s'en  rapportant  a  la  raison  et  au  droit 
natural,  que  sa  theorie  pe"chait  par  la  base. 

Tatichczev  avait  e"tudie"  le  droit  naturel  beaucoup  plus 
syste"matiquement  que  Golitzyne  :  il  connaissait  les  principes 
e"tablis  par  Grotius  et  Pufendorff  ;  mais,  en  outre,  il  s'e"tait  assimile" 
quelques  ide"es  de  Wolff  et  de  Thomasius  ;  ceux  de  leurs  trait£s 
qui  £taient  Merits  en  allemand  lui  £taient  accessibles  :  tout  en 
rattachant  au  Cre"ateur  des  hommes  la  «  loi  naturelle  »  qui  leur  est 
«inne'e»,  il  tire,  parexemple,  son  principe  «  fondamental  »  —  Pamour 
rationnel  de  soi-meme  et  quelques  -  unes  de  ses  applications  — 
principalement  de  la  doctrine  de  Thomasius,  interpreted  par  Walch. 

Tatichczev  distingue  le  droit  naturel  de  la  loi  civile,  a  laquelle 
il  doit  servir  de  fondement,  et  disserte  sur  la  convention  qui  a  eu 
lieu  entre  les  hommes  pour  former  une  socie"te"  civile  ;  d'ailleurs,  il 
ne  fait  qu'effleurer  «  Tordonnance  »  par  laquelle  les  hommes,  re"unis 
en  communaute",  reglent  «  la  forme  du  gouvernement  D,  en  parlant, 
par  exemple,  des  changements  que  celui-ci  subit  au  cours  de 
1'histoire,  des  gouvernements  re"guliers  et  irre"guliers,  de  meme  que 
des  gouvernements  mixtes  ;  mais  dans  son  e"crit  de  1730  qu'il  com- 
posait  non  sans  se  rappeler  la  «  forme  du  gouvernement  »  de  1720,  il 
se  base,  comme  Golitzyne,  particulierement  sur  la  theorie  de  la 
seconde  convention,  celle  qui  a  lieu  entre  le  souverain  et  les  sujets  ; 
d'ailleurs,  en  Pappliquant  un  peu  plus  strictement,  il  parvient  tout 
de  meme  a  formuler  des  conclusions  diff^rentes.1 

Dans  son  e"crit  sur  «  le  gouvernement  politique  »  Tatichczev 
raisonne  comme  il  suit.  Ce  n'est  qu'au  monarque  e"lu  ou  he"re"ditaire 
que  nous  avons  pret£  serment  de  fide"lit£  et  d'ob&ssance,  et  que  nous 
avons  confe"re"  le  pouvoir  le"gislatif  ;  or,  si  le  monarque  meurt  sans 
laisser  de  successeur,  sa  mort  dispense  les  sujets  de  leur  serment  ; 
la  souverainete"  revient  done  a  la  communaute'  qui  dispose  du  pouvoir 
le"gislatif  :  comme  dans  l'e"tat  naturel,  les  citoyens  deviennent  tous 
£gaux  les  uns  envers  les  autres.  La  mort  du  souverain  met  aussi 
fin  aux  pouvoirs  interme"diaires,  dont  sont  revetues  les  institutions 
subalternes  ;  et  tant  que  le  nouveau  souverain  ne  les  confirme  dans 


1  B.  TaTumeBi,,  Pasioeop*  o  noMsn  naym  u  ynujiuu^  H3,n.  H.  Ilono- 
BHM'B,  M.  1888,  pp.  19-27,  54,  128-150.  Tatichczev  s'efforce  de  prouver 
que  1'amour  rationnel  de  soi-meme  est  commun  aux  deux  subdivisions  de  la  «  loi 
divine  »,  c'est-a-dire  aux  «  lois  naturelles  »  et  aux  «  lois  traditionnelles  et  ecrites», 
indues  dans  les  Saintes  Ecritures,  tout  en  distinguant  ces  «  lois  »  des  lois  que 
les  hommes  se  donnent  a  eux-memes,  c'est-k-dire  des  lois  canoniques  et  civiles. 


382  A.  Lappo-Danilevskij  [xix 

leurs  pouvoirs  ou  n'en  institue  d'autres  avec  des  pouvoirs  corres- 
pondants,  personne  n'a  de  pouvoir  sur  les  autres.  Comme  1'Etat, 
d'ailleurs,  ne  peut  subsister  sans  gouvernement,  meme  pendant  un 
court  espace  de  temps,  la  communaute"  concede  a  ses  organes  les 
pouvoirs  dont  chacun  d'eux  disposait  d'apres  les  lois  pre"ce"dentes ; 
mais  sans  la  volonte*  de  la  communaute',  expresse"ment  formulae, 
ces  organes  ne  peuvent  s'arroger  de  pouvoirs  supe"  rieurs  ;  il  est  done 
eVident  qu'ils  ne  peuvent  user  du  pouvoir  le"gislatif,  que  la  com- 
munaute' ne  cede  qu'au  souverain,  et  que  le  conseil  des  grands 
n'avait  pas  le  droit  de  le'gife'rer  sur  la  constitution  de  1'empire  et 
de  limiter  la  monarchic  absolue  par  des  clauses.  Ce  n'est  done  que 
la  communaute,  represented  en  partie  directement  par  ses  membres, 
en  partie  par  des  de*pute"s  qui,  selon  la  loi  naturelle,  se  choisit  le 
souverain,  et  non  quatre  ou  cinq  personnes,  qui  veulent  le  faire 
arbitrairement. 

Du  reste,  Tatichczev  n'objectait  pas  a  Election  d'Anna 
Ivanovna ;  il  pouvait  meme  la  concilier  avec  la  resolution  que  les 
£tats  supe"rieurs  de  I'empire  avait  prise,  et  que  « personne  ne  con- 
testait».  En  effet,  la  doctrine  du  droit  naturel  admettait  la  possi- 
bilite"  d'un  «  consentement  tacite  »  de  la  communaute",  et  c'est  ce  que 
Tatichczev  avait  pre'cise'ment  en  vue  en  disant  que  « personne  ne 
contestait»  1'election  d'Anna  Ivanovna.  Mais  en  admettant  cette 
election,  Tatichczev  repliquait  centre  les  «  clauses  »  de  Golitzyne  et 
lui  opposait  son  projet  d'une  assembled  constituante  des  repr£sen- 
tants  du  szljahetstwo.  D'ailleurs,  il  y  pre"conisait  «la  monarchic* 
comme  la  forme  de  gouvernement  « la  plus  utile  »  a  la  Russie,  et  se 
declarait  pour  1'agrandissement  presque  exclusif  des  droits  politiques 
de  la  noblesse,  qui  devait,  du  moins  en  partie  et  temporairement, 
prendre  part  au  gouvernement  supreme  du  pays,  et  recevoir  un 
accroissement  notable  de  ses  privileges.1 

Ce  projet,  qui  avait  me"rite",  d'ailleurs,  1'approbation  de  plusieurs 
de  ses  collegues,  prouve  que  Tatichczev  faisait,  au  fond,  la  faute 
qu'il  imputait  a  Golitzyne  :  pour  appliquer  correctement  la  th£orie 
de  la  convention  il  devait  prouver  que  le  szljahetstwo  avait  le  droit 
de  repre"senter  toute  la  communaute"  et  de"finir  ses  clauses  avec 
moins  d'inde"cision. 

1  B.  TaTHmesi.,  Ilpouseojiwoe  u  couiacnoe  pascywdenie  u  Munnie 
codpaewaiocu  uuifixemcmea  pycwaio  o  npaejieniu  locydapcmeennoM?,,  dans 
le  Recueil  «  Yxpo  »,  M.  1859,  pp.  369-379. 


xix]  Uldde  de  rJELtat  en  Russie  383 

Les  deux  publicistes,  comme  on  le  voit,  adaptaient,  chacun  a  sa 
fagon,  le  droit  naturel  a  leurs  fins  politiques  et  s'efforgaient  de 
les  justifier  par  cette  the"orie :  ils  e"taient  presque  Strangers  a  Pide"e 
de  la  souverainete"  nationale,  et  ne  voulaient  profiler  de  Pide"e  de 
la  seconde  convention  que  dans  les  limites  circonscrites  par  les 
interets  des  classes  dirigeantes ;  mais  tout  de  meme  ils  avaient  une 
ide"e  juridique  de  PEtat,  et  concevaient  le  rapport  du  souverain  et 
des  sujets,  du  moins  en  the"orie,  comme  une  convention  immanente 
a  l'£tat. 

II  surfit  de  ce  coup  d'ceil  jette"  sur  Phistoire  de  Pide"e  de  1'Etat 
en  Russie  pour  apercevoir  1'esprit  nouveau  qui  commen^ait  a  la 
transformer. 

II  est  vrai  que  Phistoire  de  cette  ide"e  en  Russie  pendant  cette 
pe"riode  de  transition  n'avait  pas  encore  acquis  le  caractere  d'une 
Evolution  bien  continue  et  progressive  :  les  chainons  de  cette  chaine 
ne  rentraient  presque  pas  1'un  dans  1'autre  ;  chacun  d'eux  de"pendait 
plutotdu  mouvement  general  et  correspondant  des  idees  europeennes 
que  du  chainon  pre"ce"dent,  et  ne  de"terminait  que  tres  faiblement 
le  chainon  poste"rieur.  C'etait  done  une  Evolution  intermittente 
et  meme  quelques  fois  assez  accidentelle,  sans  caractere  individuel 
bien  prononce" ;  mais  c'e"tait  ne"anmoins  une  Evolution  et  meme  un 
progres. 

En  effet,  Pid^e  du  rapport  entre  le  souverain  et  les  sujets  qu'on 
se  faisait  en  Russie  a  Pe"poque  des  reTormes  avait  subi  quelques 
changements  qui  en  te"moignent :  on  commen^ait  a  se  repr^senter 
ce  rapport,  qu'on  croyait  autrefois  transcendant,  comme  immanent 
a  1'Etat,  et  a  puiser  les  elements  de  ce  concept  du  droit  naturel ;  on 
s'inte"ressait  particulierement  a  la  th^orie  de  la  convention,  et  on 
pouvait  d£ja  y  appre"cier  Pid^e  de  ce  que  devait  etre  ce  rapport,  sa 
valeur  formelle  et  juridique,  et  non  seulement  son  contenu  re"el  et 
sa  fin  utilitaire ;  et,  malgre"  le  regime  autocratique  que  pr£cisaient 
les  «  reglements  »,  on  essayait  meme  parfois  de  mettre  cette  ide"e  en 
pratique,  du  reste,  avec  des  restrictions  et  des  inconsequences  qui 
discreditaient  la  the"orie  et  donnaient  beau  jeu  a  ses  adversaires 
politiques. 

A.  LAPPO-DANILEVSKIJ. 


XX 

DER  VERFASSUNGSENTWURF  DER  SIEB- 
ZEHN  VERTRAUENSMANNER.  EIN  BEITRAG 
ZUR  GESCHICHTE  DES  FRANKFURTER 
PARLAMENTS 


DIE  BEDEUTUNG  DES  ENTWURFS  FUR  DIE  VERFASSUNGS- 
GESCHICHTE  DES  19.  JAHRHUNDERTS 

ICH  mochte  Ihre  Aufmerksamkeit  fiir  wenige  Augenblicke  auf 
einen  Abschnitt  in  der  Verfassungsgeschichte  des  19.  Jahrhunderts 
lenken,  einen  Abschnitt  in  der  Geschichte  der  lange  Zeit  hindurch 
vergeblichen  Bestrebungen,  Deutschland,  das  seit  dem  Untergange 
des  alten  heiligen  romischen  Reiches  zu  einem  geographischen 
Begriff  geworden  war,  von  neuem  staatlich  zu  einigen.  Diese 
Bestrebungen  fanden  bekanntlich  einen  Hohepunkt  in  dem  von  der 
Frankfurter  Nationalversammlung  unternommenen  Versuch  einer 
Reichsgriindung. 

Auch  dieser  Versuch  ist  ja  traurig  gescheitert.  Aber  er  spielt 
trotzdem  nicht  nur  in  der  politischen  und  geistigen  Entwicklungs- 
geschichte  des  deutschen  Volkes  eine  ausserordentlich  wichtige 
Rolle,  sondern  er  darf  auch  die  lebhafte  Aufmerksamkeit  desjenigen 
beanspruchen,  der  die  allgemeine  Verfassungsentwicklung  der 
Neuzeit  sich  zu  vergegenwartigen  sucht. 

Denn  wenn  diese  ohne  Zweifel  ihrem  wesentlichen  Inhalt  nach 
sich  als  die  schliesslich  in  alien  zivilisierten  Staaten  vollzogene 
Rezeption  der  in  England  bodenstandig  erwachsenen  Grundsatze 
des  konstitutionellen  Staatsrechts  darstellt,  so  kommt  auf  diesem 
Gebiet  moderner  Geistesgeschichte  —  und  die  Entwicklung  des 

384 


xx]  Siebzehnerentwurf  von  1848  385 

Rechts  lasst  sich  letzten  Endes  nicht  anders  als  Geistesgeschichte 
erfassen  —  jenem  Versuch  trotz  seiner  Ergebnislosigkeit  eine  nicht 
geringe  Bedeutung  zu. 

Die  Versammlung  der  Paulskirche  hat  zu  einer  so  griindlichen 
Aussprache  liber  die  Probleme  des  konstitutionellen  Staatsrechts 
gefiihrt,  sie  hat  Manner  von  so  tief  begriindeter  theoretischer 
Einsicht  und  doch  vielfach  auch  so  reicher  praktischer  Erfahrung 
zu  Worte  kommen  lassen,  dass  ihre  Verhandlungen  als  ein  hochst 
vielseitiger,  an  Geist  und  Kenntnissen  wenigstens  in  Deutschland 
nicht  wieder  erreichter  parlamentarischer  Ausdruck  der  damaligen 
Staatseinsicht  angesehen  werden  kb'nnen. 

Die  staatsrechtliche  Tatigkeit  der  Frankfurter  Nationalver- 
sammlung  fand  ihren  Mittelpunkt  in  ihrem  Verfassungsausschuss. 
Und  dessen  Arbeiten  wiederum  schlossen  sich  auf  das  engste  an 
den  Verfassungsentwurf  an,  den  noch  vor  dem  Zusammentritt  der 
Nationalversammlung  die  siebzehn  sogenannten  Manner  des  allge- 
meinen  Vertrauens  ausgearbeitet  hatten. 

Diesen  Entwurf  mochte  ich  zum  Gegenstand  meiner  Bemer- 
kungen  machen,  unter  anderem  deshalb,  weil  mir  fur  ihn  einige 
bisher  unoekannt  gebliebene  gleichzeitige  Aufzeichnungen  vorliegen, 
die  wie  ich  glaube  manche  bezeichnende  Lichter  auf  ihn  fallen 
lassen. 

Jene  Manner  wurden  auf  einen  Beschluss  des  durch  die  Februar- 
revolution  gewaltig  aufgeriittelten  Bundestags  von  den  einzelnen 
deutschen  Regierungen  nach  Frankfurt  geschickt,  damit  sie  dort  der 
Bundesversammlung  als  Vertrauensmanner  der  in  ihr  vertretenen 
siebzehn  Staatenstimmen  bei  der  nun  auch  von  ihr  endlich  beab- 
sichtigten  Revision  der  Bundesverfassung  mit  gutachtlichem  Beirate 
an  die  Hand  gingen.  Allein  die  Siebzehn  —  denn  diese  Bezeich- 
nung  blieb  ihnen,  da  bei  der  Abstimmung  stets  jene  Stimmenzahl 
massgebend  war,  wenn  auch  die  Versammlung  selbst  niemals  genau 
aus  siebzehn  Mitgliedern  bestand,  denn  (5sterreich  und  einige  der 
zu  Gesammtstimmen  vereinigten  kleinsten  Staaten  schickten 
mehrere  Vertreter,  wahrend  umgekehrt  Baiern  die  langste  Zeit 
hindurch  unvertreten  blieb  —  die  Siebzehn  setzten  sich  sofort  iiber 
jenen  beschrankten  Auftrag  hinweg  und  machten  sich  an  die  Aus- 
arbeitung  eines  eigenen  Entwurfs  fur  die  kunftige  Verfassung 
Deutschlands. 

Dieser  Entwurf,  nach  seinem  einflussreichsten  Miturheber  wohl 

2  C 


386  J?.  Hubner  [xx 

auch  derDahlmannsche  Verfassungsentwurf  genannt,  ist  die  erste 
ausgeflihrte  Skizze  der  heutigen  Verfassung  des  deutschen  Reiches. 
In  den  Verhandlungen  der  Siebzehn  fand  die  erste  und  fur  die 
Zukunft,  die  nahere  und  die  fernere,  massgebend  gebliebene 
Erorterung  der  schwierigen  staatsrechtlichen  Fragen  statt,  deren 
Losung  die  Voraussetzung  der  schon  damals  als  unbedingt  not- 
wendig  erkannten,  aber  erst  sehr  viel  spater  erreichten  Umwandlung 
Deutschlands  aus  einem  losen  Staatenbund  in  einen  festen  Bundes- 
staat  bildete.  So  heftet  sich  jenes  allgemeine  verfassungsgeschicht- 
liche  und  staatsrechtliche  Interesse,  das  iiberhaupt  das  Frankfurter 
Verfassungswerk  erweckt,  in  ganz  besonderem  Masse  an  die 
Verhandlungen  der  Siebzehn  und  den  von  ihnen  aufgestellten 
Verfassungsentwurf. 

II 

DIE   QUELLEN 

Als  unmittelbare  Quellen,  aus  denen  sich  ein  Einblick  in  die 
Tatigkeit  der  Vertrauensmanner  gewinnen  lasst,  standen  bisher  als 
wichstigste  die  bekannt  gewordenen  offiziellen  Berichte  zur  Ver- 
fligung,  die  einige  der  Siebzehn  liber  die  Tatigkeit  der  Versammlung 
an  ihre  Regierungen  gerichtet  haben.  So  der  ausflihrliche  des 
hannoverschen  Vertreters,  Professors  Zachariae,1  und  der  knappe 
aber  sehr  charakteristische  von  Ludwig  Uhlan d,2  dem  wiirttem- 
bergischen  Vertrauensmann.  Auch  Dahlmann  verdanken  wir 
einige  wichtige  Bemerkungen  liber  das  Werk  der  Siebzehn  und 
seinen  Anteil  daran.3 

Von  erheblichem  Wert  ist  ferner  die  eingehende  Erorterung,  die 
Gervinus,  der  Vertreter  der  freien  Stadte,  liber  den  Entwurf  un- 

1  Bericht  iiber  die  Berathungen  des  Entwurfs  des  deutschen  Reichsgrund- 
gesetzes  im   Schoosse   des   Collegiums  der  17   Beigeordneten   zum    deutschen 
Bundestage,  von  Professor  Zachariae  ;  de  dato  Frankfurt,  den  30.  April  1848. 
Actenstiicke  zur  neuesten  Geschichte  Deutschlands  (mit  besonderer  Beziehung 
auf  Hannover).      Erstes  Heft.      Hannover,   Helwingsche  Hof-Buchhandlung, 
1848,  S.  122-46. 

2  Veroffentlicht  nach  dem  im  Schiller-Museum  zu  Marbach  befindlichen 
Original  von  Walther   Reinohl,    Uhland  als  Politiker  (Beitrage  zur  Partei- 
geschichte  herausgegeben  von  Adalbert  Wahl,  2).     Tubingen,  Mohr,    1911, 
S.  182-5. 

3  Anton  Springer,  Friedrich  Christoph  Dahlmann.     Zweiter  Teil,  Leipzig, 
Hirzel,  1872,  S.  220-23. 


xx]  Siebzehnerentwurf  von  1848  387 

mittelbar  nach  seiner  Veroffentlichung  in  einer  langen  Reihe  von 
Artikeln  in  der  von  ihm  herausgegebenen  Deutschen  Zeitung 
erscheinen  Hess.1  Diese  Abhandlung  verteidigte  die  Arbeit  der 
Vertrauensmanner  gegen  die  ausserordentlich  zahlreichen  Angriffe, 
die  alsbald  von  fast  alien  Seiten  gegen  sie  gerichtet  wurden.  Auch 
diese  Kritiken  wird  man  fur  die  Wiirdigung  des  von  den  Siebzehn 
Geleisteten  nicht  ubersehen  diirfen,  so  unbefriedigend  und  unfrucht- 
bar  die  grosse  Mehrzahl  von  ihnen  auch  ist.  Die  in  Gestalt  von 
selbstandigen  Flugschriften  erschienenen  verzeichnet  in  irgend 
erreichbarer  Vollstandigkeit  das  wertvolle  Sammelwerk  von 
Wentzcke;2  die  bedeutendsten  unter  ihnen  sind  die  von  Otto 
Abel,3  Schaumann,4  Heinrich  von  Sybel,5  dem  Prinz-Gemahl 
Albert  von  England6  und  Bunsen.7 

Bei  weitem  am  unergiebigsten  sind  die  diirftigen  offiziellen 
Protokolle,  die  liber  die  Sitzungen  der  Siebzehn  damals  veroffent- 
licht  worden  sind.8  Dazu  kommt,  dass  sie  von  den  dreizehn 
Sitzungen,  die  der  eigentlichen  Verfassungsberatung  gewidmet 
waren,  elf  vollkommen  iiberspringen  und  nur  die  erste  und  letzte 
von  ihnen  zahlen  und  bekannt  machen. 

Diese  unerfreuliche  Liicke  konnen  wir  aber  nunmehr  aus  dem 

1  Deutsche  Zeitung^  Nr.    121-30,  136,   137,   140-45.      Heidelberg,  i.  24, 
Mai  1848. 

2  Paul  Wentzcke,  Kritische  Bibliographic  der  Flugschriften  zur  deutschen 
Verfassungsfrage  1848-1851.      Halle,  Niemeyer,  1911. 

3  Otto  Abel,  Das  neue  deutsche  Reich  und  sein  Kaiser.      Berlin,  Hertz, 
1848.     Wentzcke,  Nr.  199. 

4  A.    F.    H.    Schaumann,    Kurze  Randglossen  zu    dem    Entwurf  eines 
deutschen   Reichs-Grundgesetzes  (Aus    der   Minerva    besonders   abgedruckt). 
Jena,  Braun,  1848.     Wentzcke,  Nr.  221. 

5  Heinrich  von  Sybel,  Vber  das  Reichsgrundgesetz  der  X  VII  Vertrauens- 
manner.    Marburg,  Elwert,  1848.     Wentzcke,  Nr.  238. 

6  (Prinz-Gemahl  Albert  von  England,)  Meinungsdusserung  eines  Prinzen 
iiber  den  Entwurf  der  Siebzehner.     Wentzcke,  Nr.  240. 

7  Christian  Karl  Josias  Bunsen,  Die  deutsche  Bundesverfasstmg  und  ihr 
eigenthiimliches  Verhaltniss  211  den  Verfasstmgen  Englands  und  der  Vereinigten 
Staaten.      Zur  Prufung  des  Entwurfs  der  Siebzehn.      Sendschreiben  an  die 
zum  deutschen  Parlament  berufene  Versammlung.      Frankfurt  a.   M.,  Suchs- 
land,  1848.      Wentzcke,  Nr.  247. 

8  Sie  sind  gleichlautend  veroffentlicht  worden   in  der  Frankfurter  Ober- 
postamts-Zeitung,  Nr.  102-108,   124,  131.      Frankfurt,   U.-I7.  April,  3.,   10. 

Mai  1848  und  in  der  zweiten  Lieferung  der  von  Jucho  veranstalteten  amtlichen 
Ausgabe  der  Verhandlungen  des  deutschen  Parlaments ;  danach  sind  sie 
abgedruckt  in  Roth  und  Merck,  Quellensammlung  zum  deutschen  bffentlichen 
Recht\  Erster  Band,  Erlangen,  1850. 

2C  2 


388  R.  Hubner  [xx 

Nachlasse  eines  der  Vertrauensmanner  in  sehr  erwunschter  Weise 
ausfullen.  In  den  von  dem  Geschichtsschreiber  Johann  Gustav 
Droysen  hinterlassenen  Papieren  hat  sich  namlich  einmal  ein  wie 
es  scheint  ganz  vollstandiges  Exemplar  des  sogenannten  „  Separat- 
protokolls  "  gefunden,  das  der  eine  Stimmfuhrer  der  sechszehnten 
Stimme, der  in Nachfolge  Uhlan dszum  Schriftfiihrer  bestellte  Petri 
gerade  besonders  iiber  jene  mit  der  Verfassungsberatung  ausge- 
fullten  dreizehn  Sitzungen  gefuhrt  und  beglaubigt  hat  und  das  in 
lithographischer  Vervielfaltigung  an  alle  Vertrauensmanner  verteilt 
worden  zu  sein  scheint. 

Droysen  hat  sich  aber  weiter,  abgesehen  von  einem  iiber  den 
Anfang  seiner  Frankfurter  Zeit  gefiihrten  „  Tagebuch  ",  in  dem  an 
vielen  Stellen  auch  die  Tatigkeit  der  Siebzehn  beriihrt  wird,  iiber 
deren  Verhandlungen  besondere  protokollartige  Aufzeichnungen 
gemacht,  die  sich  gleichfalls,  wie  auch  jenes  „  Tagebuch  ",  in  seinem 
Nachlass  erhalten  haben.  Sie  sind  ganz  ahnlich  gehalten,  wie  die 
von  ihm  kurz  darauf  offiziell  gefiihrten  und  spater  in  ihrem  ersten 
Teil  veroffentlichten  Protokolle  des  Verfassungsausschusses  der 
Nationalversammlung.  Nur  ist  ihnen  erklarlicherweise,  da  sie  nur 
fiir  den  Privatgebrauch  bestimmt  waren,  die  fiir  eine  Veroffent- 
lichung  angebrachte  Durchsicht  und  Glattung  nicht  zu  Teil 
geworden.  Sie  behandeln  die  Verfassungsberatungen  mit  be- 
sonderer  Ausfiihrlichkeit  und  ergangen  gerade  durch  ihre  freiere 
Art  die  offiziellen  Petrischen  Protokolle  auf  das  erfreulichste. 
Denn  ohne  Vollstandigkeit  zu  beabsichtigen  und  erreichen  zu 
konnen,  folgen  sie,  offenbar  unmittelbar  wahrend  der  Beratungen, 
oft  in  fliegender  Eile,  stets  in  kleinster  und  engster  Schrift  auf 
grosse  Folioblatter  niedergeschrieben,  bei  alien  wichtigeren  Gegen- 
standen  dem  Gang  der  Verhandlung  von  Rede  zu  Rede  und  werden 
so  zu  unmittelbaren  Zeugnissen  des  oft  hitzigen  Kampfes  der 
Meinungen.1 

1  Ich  beabsichtige  demnachst  die  Protokolle  Petris  und  die  Aufzeich- 
nungen Droysens  als  Anhang  zu  einer  diesen  Vortrag  etwas  naher  ausfuhrenden 
Studie  iiber  den  Verfassungsentwurf  der  siebzehn  Vertrauensmanner  heraus- 
zugeben.  Damit  soil  auch  ein  synoptischer  Abdruck  des  Dahlmannschen 
Vorentwurfs  und  des  fertigen  Entwurfs  verbunden  werden,  da  die  Texte,  die 
C.  Varrentrapp  in  den  von  ihm  herausgegebenen  Kleinen  Schriften  F.  C. 
Dahlmanns,  Stuttgart,  1886,  S.  378-90,  veroffentlicht  hat,  nicht  ganz  genau 
sind  und  es  von  Wert  sein  diirfte,  das  gesammte  Material  an  einer  Stelle  zu 
vereinigen. 


xx]  Siebzehnerentwiirf  von  1848  389 

III 
DER  GANG  DER  VERHANDLUNGEN 

Werfen  wir  zunachst  einen  kurzen  Blick  auf  den  ausseren  Gang 
der  Verfassungsberatungen  im  Schoosse  der  Siebzehn,1  so  hatten 
bereits  die  offiziellen  Protokolle  ersehen  lassen,  dass  gleich  in  der 
zweiten  Sitzung  (am  5.  April)  eine  Kommission  zur  Ausarbeitung 
eines  Verfassungsentwurfs  niedergesetzt  wurde,  in  die  man  vier 
Mitglieder  unter  Hinzuziehungdes  Vorsitzenden  Max  von  Gagern 
wahlte :  es  waren  Dahlmann,  der  schon  damals  beriihmte 
Geschichtsschreiber  und  Bonner  Professor,  der  das  Konigreich 
Preussen  vertrat ;  Albrecht,  der  Vertreter  der  15.  Stimme,  Pro- 
fessor der  Rechte  in  Leipzig,  einer  der  bedeutendsten  deutschen 
Rechtsgelehrten,  mit  Dahlmann  in  weiten  Kreisen  des  Volkes 
wegen  ihrer  Beteiligung  an  dem  mannhaften  Auftreten  der 
,,  Gottinger  Sieben  "  verehrt  und  bewundert ;  dann  Bassermann, 
der  Abgesandte  Badens,  einer  der  im  Vordergrund  stehenden 
Wortfiihrer  der  liberalen  Patrioten.  Wilhelm  Jordan,  der  spatere 
geschatzte  Dichter,  der  als  viertes  Kommissionsmitglied  gewahlt 
worden  war,  schied  bald  iiberhaupt  aus  dem  Kreise  der  Siebzehn 
aus.  Allein  diese  Viermannerkommission  —  auch  das  ist  seit 
langem  bekannt — uberliess  die  Arbeit  im  wesentlichen  ihren  zwei  am 
meisten  dazu  geeigneten  Mitgliedern,  Dahlmann  und  Albrecht. 
Bereits  nach  9  Tagen  (in  der  9.  Sitzung  am  15.  April)  konnte  der 
Kommissionsentwurf  der  Versammlung  der  Vertrauensmanner 
vorgelegt  werden.  Welchen  Gang  die  Verhandlungen  riun  des 
weiteren  nahmen,  zeigen  deutlich  die  Petrischen  und  Droysen- 
schen  Aufzeichnungen.  Der  Vorentwurf  wurde  zunachst  einer  ersten 
Lesung  unterzogen,  die  sich  meist,  wenn  auch  nfcht  ohne  Aus- 
nahmen,  der  Reihenfolge  seiner  Artikel  und  Paragraphen  anschloss, 
nicht  selten  aber  streitige  Satze  vorlaufig  zuriickstellte  oder  auch 
an  die  Kommission  zuriickverweis,  damit  sie  auf  Grund  des  statt- 
gehabten  Meinungsaustausches  eine  neue  Fassung  ausarbeite. 
Einmal,  bei  Beratung  liber  den  vom  Reichsgericht  handelnden 

1  Eine  Tabelle  iiber  die  Daten  sammtlicher  Sitzungen  und  den  Abdruck 
der  iiber  sie  gefuhrten  Protokolle  soil  der  S.  388  Anm.  I  in  Aussicht  gestellten 
Studie  beigefugt  werden,  wie  auch  dort  ein  Verzeichnis  der  Vertrauensmanner 
gegeben  werden  wird. 


39°  -#•  Hiibner  [xx 

Abschnitt,wurde  eine  neue  Kommission  aus  den  Juristen  Albrecht, 
Bassermann  undZachariae  zur  weiterenVorbereitungdesGegen- 
standes  gebildet.  Todt,  der  Vertreter  des  Konigreichs  Sachsen, 
wurde  mit  der  Ausarbeitung  der  auf  das  Reichsfinanzwesen  bezlig- 
lichen  Bestimmungen  betraut ;  doch  fanden  seine  ins  Einzelne 
gehenden  Vorschlage  schliesslich  keine  Aufnahme  in  den  Entwurf. 
Die  Debatten  verliefen  sich  wohl  gelegentlich  —  wenigstens  nach 
dem  Urteil  Droy sens  —  ins  Kleinliche.  Aber  im  allgemeinen  —  das 
lassen  Droy  sens  Niederschriften  deutlich  erkennen,  wie  es  sich  ja 
auch  bei  der  geistigen  Bedeutung  vieler  der  Siebzehn  von  selbst 
versteht  —  sind  sie  offenbar  wlirdige  Vorlaufer  der  glanzendsten 
Tage  der  Paulskirche  gewesen.  Bei  manchen  Gelegenheiten 
steigerten  sie  sich  zu  lebhaften  dramatischen  Szenen,  so  vor  allem 

—  auch  darin  die  Redekampfe  der  Nationalversammlung  voraus- 
nehmend  —  bei  der  Beratung  liber  das  Reichsoberhaupt.      Auch 
ganz    am    Schluss,   als    der    endgiiltig    redigierte    Gesammttext 
in    letzter   Lesung   angenommen    worden   war,    kam   die    erregte 
Stimmung  noch  einmal  zum  Ausdruck  :   Uhland  verlangte,  dass 
die  nur  durch  Mehrheitsbeschluss  erfolgte  Annahme  des  Entwurfs 
ausdriicklich   bei   der   Veroffentlichung   bekannt   gegeben    werde. 
Nach    offenbar    scharfen    Erorterungen    entsprach    man    diesem 
Verlangen  und  zwar  in  derWeise,dassDahlmann  beauftragt  wurde, 
eine  entsprechende  Bemerkung  in  das  Vorwort  aufzunehmen,  das 
er  auf  Wunsch  der  Versammlung,  wenn  auch  erst  nach  einigem 
Strauben   verfasste,    und    mit   dem    dann    der    Entwurf   gedruckt 
worden  ist. 

IV 

DIE  VERFASSUNGSRECHTLICHEN   PROBLEMS  UND  DER  VERSUCH 

IHRER   L6SUNG 

Nicht  nur  liber  den  ausseren  Gang  der  Verhandlungen,  sondern 

—  was  wichtiger  ist  —  auch  liber  die  Beweggrlinde,  von  denen  sich 
die  Siebzehn  bei  ihrem  Werke  leiten  liessen,  geben  uns  die  neuen 
Materialien,  besonders  die  Droysenschen  Niederschriften,  naheren 
Aufschluss. 

Freilich  zeigt  ja  schon  der  fertige  Verfassungsentwurf  an  sich, 
welcher  Geist  in  der  Versammlung  herrschte.  Aber  wir  sehen 
doch  jetzt  erst  deutlich,  wie  schon  hier  der  vielfaltige  Meinungs- 


xx]  Siebzehncrentwurf  *von  1848  391 

gegensatz  zu  Tage  trat,  der  nur  allzu  bald  das  versuchte 
Einigungswerk  als  aussichtslos  erscheinen  Hess. 

Im  allgemeinen  freilich  hatten  unter  den  Siebzehn  durchaus 
diejenigen  Anschauungen  das  Ubergewicht,  die  spater  wahrend 
der  Nationalversammlung  in  der  Partei  des  sogenannten  rechten 
Zentrums  oder  der  erbkaiserlichen  Partei  ihre  Vertretung  fanden. 
Das  kann  nicht  iiberraschen,  da  nicht  weniger  als  acht  der 
Vertrauensmanner  spater  zu  den  Mitgliedern  dieser  Partei  gehorten 
(Bassermann,  Dahlmann,  Droysen,  M.  v.  Gagern,  Gervinus, 
Schmerling,  Wippermann,  Zachariae);  einige  freilich  nur 
voriibergehend,  andere  aber  als  massgebende  Leiter  (Bassermann, 
Dahlmann,  Droysen).  Von  denjenigen  Vertrauensmannern,  die 
nicht  in  das  Parlament  eintraten,  gehorten  Albrecht  und  wohl 
auch  Gabelentz,  Jaupund  Petri  der  gleichen  Richtung  an.  Dem- 
gegenuber  fand  der  demokratisch-liberale  Standpunkt  eigentlich 
nur  in  Ludwig  Uhland  eine  allerdings  sehr  ausgesprochene  und 
hartnackige  Vertretung.  Er  verband  sich  bei  Uhland  zugleich  mit 
einer  eifersuchtig  partikularistischen  Gesinnung ;  bei  anderen  war 
umgekehrt  diese  Gesinnung  in  immerhin  verschieden  starker 
Auspragung  das  Ergebnis  konservativer,  selbst  reaktionarer 
Anschauungen,  so  bei  dem  Sachsen  Todt,  dem  Hannoveraner 
Zachariae,  dem  Mecklenburger  Stever.  Die  radikale,  eine 
deutsche  Republik  erstrebende  Zeitstromung  kam  in  der  Siebzehner- 
versammlung  nicht  zu  Wort,  auch  Uhlands  Anschauungen  gingen 
nicht  so  weit  nach  links. 

Aber  schon  die  vertretenen  Gegensatze  genligten,  um  wieder- 
holt  und  vor  allem  in  der  grossen  Debatte  liber  das  Reichsoberhaupt 
zu  einem  heftigen  Zusammenstoss  zu  fiihren.  Zwar  war  die 
Versammlung  in  dem  Wunsche  nach  einer  monarchischen  Spitze 
des  Reichs  einig.  Aber  der  demokratische  und  der  konservative 
Partikularismus,auch  hier  durch  Uhland  und  Zachariae  vertreten, 
wollte  nur  einen  Wahlkaiser  zugestehen.  Der  Erbkaiser  konnte 
in  der  ersten  Lesung  nur  mit  acht  gegen  ftinf  Stimmen,1  in  der 
ganz  fiir  den  Schluss  aufgesparten  zweiten  Lesung,  an  der  alle 
Stimmen  mit  einziger  Ausnahme  der  bairischen  teilnahmen,  nur  mit 
neun  gegen  sechs  durchgesetzt  werden ;  die  1 6.  Stimme  (Hohen- 

1  Nach  der  in  Droysens  lithographiertes  Exemplar  des  Entwurfs  der 
Vorkommission  (es  scheint  zweifelhaft,  ob  von  ihm  selbst)  eingetragenen 
Bleistiftangabe  ergibt  sich  fiir  die  erste  am  17.  April  in  der  elften  Sitzung 


392  R-  Hubner  [xx 

zollern,  Liechtenstein,  Reuss,  -Schaumburg-Lippe,  Lippe  und 
Waldeck)  war  bei  der  ersten  und  offenbar  auch  bei  der  zweiten 
Lesung  gespalten.  Selbst  Bassermann  wurde  erst  in  letzter 
Stunde  gewonnen. 

Die  Frage  des  Oberhauptes  war  derjenige  Punkt,  an  dem 
sich  die  Gefahrlichkeit  der  Klippen,  zwischen  denen  es  hindurch- 
zusteuern  gait,  am  scharfsten  offenbarte.  Deutschland  sollte,  das 
war  damals  der  Wunsch  des  ganzen  Volkes,  ein  einheitliches 
Staatswesen  werden,  denn  der  Staatenbund,  die  Negation  eines 
solchen,  hatte  seine  Unzulanglichkeit  zur  Geniige  und  zum  (Jber- 
druss  erwiesen.  Einen  Bundesstaat  also  musste  man  errichten. 
Aber  wie  sollte  und  konnte  man  mehr  als  dreissig  Monarchien, 
darunter  zwei  europaische  Grossmachte,  einer  zentralen  Bundes- 
gewalt  unterstellen,  da  doch  nach  heiliger  Uberlieferung  des 
Bundesrechts  nichts  unverletzlicher  war,  als  die  Souveranitat  der 
Einzelstaaten  ?  Das  war  eine  Aufgabe,  wie  sie  die  Weltgeschichte 
noch  niemals  gestellt  hatte.  Die  in  ihr  liegenden  Schwierigkeiten 
iiberstiegen  selbst  diejenigen,  die  bei  der  Begriindung  des  grossen 
amerikanischen  Bundesstaates,  der  Vereinigten  Staaten,  zu  liber- 
winden  gewesen  waren. 

Dahlmann  und  seine  Gesinnungsgenossen  stellten  es  schon  in 
dem  Siebzehnerentwurf  klar  hin  und  sprachen  es  schon  in  den  ihm 
geltenden  Beratungen  scharf  aus,  dass  an  die  Spitze  Deutschlands 
nicht  nur  ein  erblicher,  sondern  auch  ein  machtiger  Kaiser  treten 
miisse.  Daher  gaben  sie  dem  Reiche  eine  weite  Kompetenz,  in 

vorgenommene  Abstimmung  liber  die  Erblichkeit  folgendes  Stimmenver- 
haltnis  : 

Es  stimmten 

gegen  die  Erblichkeit  fur  die  Erblichkeit 

Zachariae  Gagern 

Todt  Gervinus 

Langen  Droysen 

Willmar  Stever 

Uhland  Gabelentz 

Jaup  fur  die  halbe  16.  Stimme  Schmerling 

Albrecht 

5i*  Dahlmann 

Petri  fur  die  halbe  16.  Stimme 


*  Irrtiimlicherweise  wird  in  dieser  Spalte  auch  Bergk  angefuhrt  ;    er  fehlte  bei   der 
Abstimmung.     Auch  Bassermann  fehlte.      Ebenso  war  Baiern  auch  hier  unvertreten. 


xx]  Siebzehnerentivurf  von  1848  393 

alien  wesentlichen  Stiicken  die  gleiche,  die  heut  unserem  Reiche 
zusteht :  das  Verzeichnis  der  dem  Reich  uberwiesenen  Angelegen- 
heiten,  das  unsere  Reichsverfassung  enthalt,  lasst  deutlich  die 
Herkunft  aus  dem  entsprechenden  Verzeichnis  des  Dahlmann- 
schen  Entwurfs  erkennen. 

Und  wenn  die  Siebzehn  in  einer  damals  gebrauchlichen  Redewen- 
dung  ihre  Verfassung  erklaren  liessen,  dass  „  die  Fiille  der  Reichs- 
gewalt  in  dem  Reichsoberhaupte  und  dem  Reichstage  vereinigt " 
sei  (§  4),  so  gaben  sie  —  anders  wie  die  heutige  Reichsverfassung 
—  dem  Kaiser  die  voile  Stellung  eines  konstitutionellen  Monarchen 
mit  alien  einem  solchen  zustehenden  Befugnissen.  Sie  gaben 
ihm  —  was  auf  anderem  Wege  auch  im  heutigen  Reich  verwirk- 
licht  worden  ist  —  vor  allem  die  voile  Verfiigung  iiber  die  milita- 
rische  Macht :  hier  war  es  besonders  dem  energischen  Eingreifen 
Droysens  zu  verdanken,  dass  dem  Kaiser  das  Ernennungsrecht 
nicht  bios  (wie  Dahlmanns  Vorentwurf  gewollt  hatte)  hinsichtlich 
der  hoheren,  sondern  schlechthin  aller  Offiziere  iibertragen  wurde. 

Und  ferner  machte  der  Entwurf  den  Kaiser  —  wesentlich 
abweichend  von  der  heutigen  Regelung  —  zu  einem  neben  dem 
Reichstag  gleichberechtigten  Faktor  der  Gesetzgebung.  Erst 
durch  seine  Verkiindigung,  so  wurde  festgesetzt,  sollten  die 
Beschliisse  des  Reichstags  verbindliche  Kraft  erhalten.  Man 
nannte  das  damals  ungenau  das  Vetorecht.  „  Der  Monarch",  so 
schreibt  Droysen,  offenbar  das  Ergebnis  der  hierauf  gerichteten 
Beratungen  zusammenfassend,  „  erhalte  diese  grosse  Befugnis ; 
hoffen  wir,  dass  wir  es  iiben  mit  derselben  Diskretion  wie  Englands 
Konige." 

Die  Selbstandigkeit  der  Reichsgewalt,  ihre  den  Einzelstaaten 
iibergeordnete  Souveranitat  fand  auch  darin  Ausdruck,  dass  der 
Entwurf,  an  die  amerikanische  Lehre  von  der  iiberragenden  Kraft 
der  Verfassung  ankniipfend,  alle  mit  dem  Reichsgrundgesetz  in 
Widerspruch  stehenden  Rechtsquellen  des  deutschen  Bundes  und 
der  deutschen  Einzelstaaten  ausser  Kraft  setzte  und  damit  mittelbar 
auch  den  kiinftigen  Erlass  solcher  Bestimmungen  unmoglich 
machen  wollte.  Wenn  damit  auch  noch  nicht  der  unbedingte 
Vorrang  der  Reichsgesetze  vor  den  Landesgesetzen  ausgesprochen 
war  —  wie  dies  in  unserer  Reichsverfassung  geschehen  ist,  —  so 
konnte  doch  Bassermann  nicht  ohne  Grund  schon  jene  Aufhe- 
bung  einen  „  Staatsstreich  "  nennen  ;  denn  sie  traf  die  bisher  fur 


394  &  Hiibner  [xx 

unantastbar   gehaltene   Souveranitat   der    Einzelstaaten   an   ihrer 
Wurzel. 

Wenn  Dahlmann  und  die  Seinen  kein  Bedenken  trugen,  die 
Einzelstaaten  in  dieser  Weise  zu  Gunsten  des  Reichs  zu  beschranken, 
so  waren  die  meisten  von  ihnen  hierzu  nur  in  der  festen  Zuversicht 
entschlossen,  dass  Preussens  Konig  der  Kaiser  des  neuen  Deutsch- 
lands  werden  und  dass  damit  Preussen  das,  was  es  als  Einzelstaat 
aufzugeben  habe,  als  deutsche  Vormacht  reichlich  ersetzt  erhalten 
werde.  Immerhin  gab  doch  auch  in  dieser  Versammlung  ein  so 
gliihender  preussischer  Patriot  wie  Droysen  seiner  auch  schon 
anderwarts  geausserten  Befriedigung  darliber  Ausdruck,  dass 
Preussen  noch  nicht  durch  eine  Verfassung  in  zentraler  Weise 
konstituiert  worden  sei,  denn  ein  solches  einheitliches  Preussen 
wiirde  Deutschland  unmoglich  machen.1 

Lagen  bei  der  Kompetenzverteilung  zwischen  Reich  und 
Einzelstaaten  und  ebenso  beim  Oberhaupt  wenigstens  die 
verschiedenen  gangbaren  Wege  von  vornherein  klar  vor  Augen, 
so  dass  man  nur  zu  entscheiden  hatte,  welchen  die  Mehrheit 
einzuschlagen  wiinschte,  so  tappte  man  bei  der  Gestaltung  des 
Reichstags  vollig  im  Dunkeln.  Man  war  zwar  einig,  dass  nach 
englischem  Vorbild  das  Zweikammersystem  anzunehmen  und  also 
ein  Oberhaus  und  ein  Unterhaus  zu  schaffen  sei.  Auch  fiir  die 
Bildung  des  Unterhauses  standen  die  leitenden  Gesichtspunkte 
ohne  weiteres  fest.  Aber  wie  und  woraus  sollte  das  Oberhaus 
eingerichtet  werden  ?  Das  war  hier  wie  uberall,  wo  man  die  aus 
Englands  eigenartigen  geschichtlichen  Zustanden  erwachsene 
Einrichtung  nachahmen  wollte,  eine  verzweifelte  Frage.  Die 
verschiedensten  Vorschlage  wurden  gemacht ;  die  Debatten  zogen 
sich  in  schleppende  Lange.  Was  schliesslich  beschlossen  wurde, 
namlich  ein  Oberhaus,  in  das  die  regierenden  Fiirsten  und  die 
Vertreter  der  vier  freien  Stadte,  sowie  „  aus  dem  Kreise  der 
bewahrten  Verdienste  des  Vaterlands  "  auf  Zeit  gewahlte  Reichs- 

1  Vgl.  G.  Droysen,  Johann  Gustav  Droysen,  Erster  Teil,  Leipzig  und 
Berlin,  1910,  S.  347  ff.  Friedrich  Meinecke,  Weltburgertum  und  National- 
staat.  Studien  zur  Genesis  des  deutschen  Nationals  taates.  Zweite  durch- 
gesehene  Auflage,  Miinchen  und  Berlin,  1911,  S.  352  ff.  Durch  die  im  Text 
beriihrte  Stelle  in  Droysens  Niederschrift  erledigt  sich  die  von  Meinecke 
a.  a.  O.  S.  356  aufgeworfene  Frage,  ob  Droysen  auch  im  Siebzehnerausschuss 
seine  Gedanken  iiber  das  Aufgehen  Preussens  vertreten  hat,  wohl  zweifellos 
in  bejahendem  Sinne. 


xx]  Siebzehnerentwurf  von  1848  395 

rate  eintreten  sollten,  konnte  kaum  befriedigen ;  mit  Recht  hat 
Dahlmann  selbst  spater  die  betreffenden  Bestimmungen  des 
Entwurfs  als  eine  ungliickliche  Kombination  bezeichnet,  die  der 
Verbesserung  unumganglich  bediirfe.1  Hier  hat  erst  Bismarcks 
Genialitat  in  der  Einrichtung  des  Bundesrats  den  einzig  moglichen 
Ausweg  gefunden. 

Gliicklicher  sind  die  eigenartigen  Bestimmungen  des  Siebzehner- 
entwurfs  liber  das  Reichsgericht,  das  freilich  eine  ganz  andere 
Stellung  erhalten  sollte,  als  sie  der  gegenwartige  hochste  deutsche 
Gerichtshof  in  Leipzig  einnimmt.  Es  sollte  einerseits  eine  Fort- 
setzung  der  alten  sogenannten  Bundesaustragalinstanz  bilden 
und  als  solche  Streitigkeiten  zwischen  den  Einzelstaaten  und  auch 
sonstige  ofTentlichrechtliche  Streitigkeiten  entscheiden,  andrerseits 
gewisse  schwerste  Kriminalfalle  aburteilen  und  schliesslich  auch 
als  politischer  Gerichtshof  fiir  die  Verhandlung  von  Ministeran- 
klagen  dienen.  Hier  waren  offensichtlich  Einrichtungen  der  alten 
Reichs-  und  Bundeszeit  mit  Gedanken  des  englisch-amerikanischen 
Verfassungsrechts  verbunden. 

Ein  naheres  Eingehen  hierauf  wiirde  zu  weit  fiihren,  wie  denn 
auch  iiber  die  im  ganzen  knappen  Bestimmungen  liber  die  ,,Grund- 
rechte  des  deutschen  Volkes  ",  die  der  Entwurf  der  Zeitstromung 
folgend  verzeichnete,  nur  das  bemerkt  werden  soil,  dass  auch  hier 
vor  allem  der  Gedanke  an  die  herzustellende  Einheit,  Einheit  auch 
in  rechtlicher  Beziehung,  im  Vordergrund  stand.  Deshalb  wurde 
ausdriicklich  ausgesprochen,  dass  diese  Grundrechte  auch  zugleich 
der  Verfassung  jedes  einzelnen  deutschen  Staates  zur  Norm 
dienen  sollten. 

Einer  kiinftigen  deutschen  Verfassungsgeschichte,  die  wir 
zumal  fiir  die  neueren  Zeiten  noch  schmerzlich  entbehren,  oder 
einer  Geschichte  des  Frankfurter  Parlaments,  die  gleichfalls  leider 
noch  ungeschrieben  ist,  muss  es  vorbehalten  bleiben,  dem  Ver- 
fassungsentwurf  der  siebzehn  Vertrauensmanner  seine  Stellung  in 
der  allgemeinen  Entwicklung  der  staatsrechtlichen  Anschauungen 
zuzuweisen  und  die  Rolle  des  naheren  zu  schildern,  die  er  in  der 
Geschichte  der  deutschen  Einheitsbestrebungen  und  Verfassungs- 
kampfe  gespielt  hat. 

Hier  sollte  nur  ein  kurzer  Hinweis  auf  die  neuen  demnachst 
1  Springer,  a.  a.  O.  S.  225. 


396  R.  Hubner  [xx 

bekannt  zu  machenden  Materialien  gegeben  werden,  die  demjenigen, 
der  jene  Aufgabe  in  Angriff  nehmen  wird,  wenigstens  nach 
manchen  Richtungen  hin  von  Wert  sein  dlirften. 

Ich  freue  mich,  dass  es  mir  vergonnt  war,  den  Siebzehnerentwurf 
gerade  bei  dieser  Gelegenheit  und  an  dieser  Stelle  zu  besprechen. 
Fiihrt  doch  die  Entwicklung  des  modernen  Staatsrechts  in  letzter 
Linie  stets  in  dieses  Land  und  in  diese  Stadt ! 

R.  HUBNER. 


Printed  by  R.  &  R.  CLARK,  LIMITED,  Edinburgh. 


DIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO 
LIBRARY 


Acme   Library   Card   Pocket 

Under  Pat.  "Ref.  Index  File." 
Made  by  LIBRARY  BUREAU