Skip to main content

Full text of "The ethics of the Greek philosophers, Socrates, Plato and Aristotle;"

See other formats


EVOLUTION    OF    ETHICS 

VOLUME  I. 

THE  GREEK  PHILOSOPHERS, 
PROF.  HYSLOP. 


BROOKLYN  ETHICAL  ASSOCIATION. 


THE   ETHICS 


OF    THE 


GREEK  PHILOSOPHERS 

SOCRATES,  PLATO  AND  ARISTOTLE. 


A     LECTURE     GIVEN     BEFORE     THE      BROOKLYN      ETHICAL     ASSOCIATION, 
SEASON   OF    1896-1897, 


BY 

PROF.  JAMES  H.  HYSLOP, 

PROFESSOR   OF    LOGIC   AND    ETHICS,    COLUMBIA    UNIVERSITY. 

AUTHOR    OF    "ELEMENTS    OF   LOGIC,"    "ELEMENTS    OF    ETHICS,"    "HUME'S 
TREATISE  ON  MORALS,"  "  DEMOCRACY,"  AND    "  LESSONS    IN    LOGIC." 


Edited  by  Chas.  M  Higgins,  with  portraits  of  the  Philosophers, 

together  with  extracts  from  their  works,  and  Editorial  Notes 

to  show  their  close  relation  to  modern  thought.    Concluding 

with  a  brief  Life  of  Socrates. 


PUBLISHED   FOR  THE 

BROOKLYN    ETHICAL    ASSOCIATION, 

BY 

CHARLES   M.   HIGGINS    &    CO. 

NEW  YORK— CHICAGO— LONDON, 
1903. 


A 


COPYRIGHT,  1903, 

BY 
CHARLES  M.  HIGGINS, 


Z.  SIDNEY  SAMPSON. 


To  Z.  SIDNEY  SAMPSON, 

BORN    NOV  .  26th,   1842  ;   DIED  JULY   2gth,  1897. 
THE   SECOND   PRESIDENT   OF  THE 

BROOKLYN    ETHICAL    ASSOCIATION. 

SERVING   TWO    TERMS,  1883-1884. 
RE-ELECTED   FOR   THIRD   TERM,    1897. 

ESTEEMED    AS    A    MAN  :    BELOVED    AS    A    FRIEND  : 
HONORED    AS    AN   ABLE     OFFICER    AND    MEMBER. 


PRESIDENTS  OF  THE  BROOKLYN 
ETHICAL  ASSOCIATION. 

PROF.  FRANKLIN  W.  HOOPER, 

1881-1882. 
MR.  Z.  SIDNEY  SAMPSON, 

1883-1884. 
DR.  LEWIS  G.  JANES, 

1885  to  1896. 

MR.  Z.  SIDNEY  SAMPSON, 
1897. 

MR.  HENRY  HOYT  MOORE, 
1898-1900. 


CONTENTS. 

PAGB 

INTRODUCTION,  »   ' i-xi 

PRELUDE. — "  Foretastes  and  Keynotes  from  the  Great  Pa 
gan  Prophets,"  being  choice  texts  from  Socrates, 
Plato  and  Aristotle,  illustrating  some  of  their  best 
thoughts  on  Religion,  Ethics  and  Politics.  .  xn-xxiv 

PREFACE, .  xxv 

GREEK  PHILOSOPHY. — Its  study  a  constant  charm.  Its 
spontaneity,  naturalness  and  penetration.  Philoso 
phers  preceding  the  age  of  Socrates,  Pythagoras, 
Thales,  Democritus,  Anaxagoras  and  others,  and 
their  influence  on  Socrates.  Their  cosmic  specula 
tions,  moral  and  religious  doctrines.  Conceptions  of 
morality,  harmony  with  natural  law,  similar  to  views 
of  Herbert  Spencer  and  the  Evolutionists,  .  .  1-13 
SOCRATES,  430  B.C. — His  environment,  personality,  method, 
doctrines,  and  influence.  Opposition  to  Skeptics  and 
Sophists.  His  sagacious  assertion  of  Ignorance  and 
his  ingenious  and  misunderstood  doctrine  of  Knowl 
edge  as  the  basis  of  Virtue-  A  marvelous  conversa 
tionalist  and  profound  reasoner.  A  great  moral  phi 
losopher,  opposed  to  all  cosmic  speculation  or  abstract 
science,  putting  the  stress  on  practical  ethics  or  the 
laws  of  true  human  conduct  for  happiness  in  this  natu 
ral  L  e  and  beatitude  in  the  future  supernatural  life  of 
the  oul.  One  of  the  greatest  moral  and  religious 
teachers  of  the  world,  pre-eminent  in  the  teaching  of 
unworldliness  and  immortality  in  the  Christian  sense, 
400  B.  c.  A  unique  personality — mystic,  theistic,  ra 
tionalistic  and  utilitarian,  the  father  of  modern  utilita 
rian  theories  and  of  many  ancient  philosophic  sects.  13-39 
(a) 


b  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

PLATO,  400  B.C. — The  all-around  genius  in  Philosophy  and 
abstract  thought.  The  idealistic,  transcendental  and 
universal  scope  and  character  of  his  philosophy.  The 
great  pupil  of  Socrates,  the  mouthpiece  and  modifier 
of  his  thought.  His  ideal  State  a  communistic  and  so 
cialistic  "  Republic,"  and  an  ancient  high  exponent  of 
modern  "Civil  Service  Reform."  Plato's  Morality,  or 
right,  an  eternal  absolute  law,  inherent  in  the  nature 
of  things,  not  dependent  on  caprice  or  authority,  hu 
man  or  divine.  Author  of  the  Golden  Rule,  400  B.  c. 
His  impersonal  pantheistic  or  monistic  conceptions 
of  God  and  the  Universe.  Conception  of  immortality 
and  the  soul,  personal  and  impersonal — like  the  Ori 
entals  or  Buddhists — involving  pre-existence,  reincar 
nation  and  absorption.  His  ascetic  and  high  moral 
ideals — hater  of  the  sensual  and  lover  of  the  ideal ; 
exalter  of"  Good  "  above  "  Pleasure."  His  deep  in 
fluence  on  Jewish  and  Christian  sects,  and  on  all  sub 
sequent  thought, 39-54 

ARISTOTLE,  350  B.  c.— The  rational  world  student,  a  natu 
ral,  moral  and  political  philosopher  in  a  pre-eminent 
modern  sense.  Pupil  of  Plato  and  blender  of  the 
Socratic  and  Platonic  thought  with  his  own  original 
and  scientific  rationalism.  The  great  rationalist  or  sci 
entist  of  the  Greek  schools  and  father  of  the  modern 
scientific  and  evolutionary  methods.  A  great  political 
student,  humanitarian,  and  democratic  statesman  of 
the  broadest  type,  harmonious  with  the  best  modern 
standards, ...  54-67 

PYTHAGORAS  AND  HIS  SCHOOL,  500  B.  c. — Sketch  of  his 
life  and  work  and  outline  of  his  doctrines,  which  had 
deep  influence  on  Socrates  and  Plato.  The  Pluralistic 
and  Unit  conceptions  of  God.  Incarnations,  Pagan 
and  Christian.  Lyman  Abbott's  idea,  .  .  68-74 


CONTENTS. 


APPENDIX. 

Extracts  from  Socrates,  Plato  and  Aristotle,  with 
Notes  and  Comments  illustrating  the  correspondence 
of  ancient  and  modern  thought. 

EXTRACTS  FROM  PLATO. 

PAGE 

1.  The  Supreme  God  or  Creator,  and  His  Creation  of 

the  Universe.  .        .        .        .        .        .        .        75 

2.  Great  Antiquity  of  Egypt,  and  her  early  influence  on 

ancient  Greece.  Tale  of  "  The  Lost  Atlantis."  82 
(^  The  Principle  of  Universal  Beneficent  Love.  From 

Plato's  Symposium.  .  .  .  •  ./  .  .  88 

(4.,  Agathon  and  Socrates  on  Love.  .  .  *>.'.,  91 
5.  Plato  and  St.  Paul  paralleled  in  Hymn  to  Love.  Paul 

in  i  Cor.  13  (A.  D.  57).    Compared  with  Agathon 

in  the  Symposium,  B.  C.  416.  ....  102 

(6j  The  Golden  Rule.  From  Plato's  Laws,  400  B.  C.  .  106 

7.  Return  not  evil  for  evil.     Socrates'  answer  to  Crito.  109 

8.  Good,  not  Pleasure,  the  supreme  aim  of  Conduct.      .  in 

9.  Suicide  Condemned.     Socrates  in  the  Phaedo.       .        .  112 
10.     A  virtuous  life,  fearless  death,  and  glorious  hereafter 

commended  to  all  men.  .        •        .        .        .       1 14 

n.    The  soul's  improvement,  not  worldly  success,  the  true 

aim  of  man's  life.      .......       116 

12.  The  true  life,  the  life  of  the  soul,  not  of  the  world 

or  the  body.    Socrates  in  the  Phaedo.     .        .        .118 

13.  Death  is  a  good  and  not  an  evil.     Socrates  in  the 

the  Apology .•       .        .        .       120 

1 4.  The  Immortality  of  the  Soul  and  its  future  rewards 

and  punishments.     Socrates  in  the  Phaedo.          .       122 

15.  Best  texts  from  the  Old  Testament  on   Immortality 

as  compared  to  Plato's  Phaedo 130 

16.  The  Doctrine  of  Purgatory— Pagan  and  Christian.     .       135 

17.  Reincarnation.          .         . 138 


d  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

18.  Mind  inheres  in  and  rules  the  universe.          .  .141 

19.  The  Greek  Conception  of  Soul  and  Deity.     A  Prime 

Mover  or  Force,  which  is  Self-Moved.  .  144 

20.  The  Universal  Soul.          .  .        .  145 

21.  The  Platonic  Doctrine  of  Ideas 147 

22.  The  Socratic  Utilitarian  Theory  of  Ethics.      .        .  157 

23.  Socrates  the  Father  of  Modern  Utilitarian  Ethics.        .  168 

24.  Influence  of  Socrates  on  Aristotle  and  Epicurus  and 

the  substantial  identity  of  their  ethical  doctrines.         169 

25.  The   Hedonistic  School  of  Aristippus— the  false  Epi 

curean  and  perverter  of  Socratic  Doctrine.  .        172 

26.  Harmony  of  Herbert  Spencer  with  the  Socratic  School 

of  Ethics.        .  .        .        176 

27.  Socratic  and  Theistic   Ethics — a  comparison  of  the 

Utilitarian  and  the  Theistic  Theories  of  Ethics.  179 

EXTRACTS  FROM  ARISTOTLE. 

28.  Aristotle  on  the  Idea  of  God. 182 

29.  Aristotle  on  the  Theory  of  Evolution 186 

30.  Abstract  of  Aristotle's  Theory  of  Ethics.       .         .        .  193 

ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS. 

31.  The  fundamental  nature  of  a  political  state  or  govern 

ment.     Status  of  property.     Socialistic  and  Indi 
vidualistic  considered 205 

32.  Citizens    and    States    of   various    kinds    considered. 

The  best  form  of  government  and  the  best  citizen 
discussed. •  210 

33.  The    best   constitution    for    a    state.     Preponderance 

of  the  middle  class  recommended.  .         .         .  231 

34.  Cause  of  Revolutions  Considered.  ....  235 

35.  Democracy  analyzed  and  commended.  .        .        .  243 

36.  The  Best  Life  for  Individuals  and  States        .         .         .  251 

37.  Public  Schools  and  Liberal    Education,  Gymnastics, 

Music  and  Morals.  272 

LIFE  OF  SOCRATES. 

The  nativity,  parentage  and  training  of  Socrates,         .         .        286 
His  orig'     1  profession  of  sculptor  abandoned  to  adopt  the 
ro1     ^1  moral  philosopher,  public  reformer  and  teacher 
of  virtue,  without  fees,  287 


CONTENTS.  e 

PAGB 

His  asceticism  and  voluntary  poverty  and  his  claim  to  divine 
inspiration  and  a  divine  mission  to  mankind.     His  pro 
phetic  spirit  and  his  spiritual  attendant  or  "  daemon."  288 
The  personal  appearance,  character  and  virtues  of  Socrates.  289 

His  wives  and  children, '.  295 

The  Masters  and  Teachers  of  Socrates,       ....  297 

His  school  and  pupils, 298 

Philosophic  sects  influenced  by  and  formed  from  his  teach 
ings.     Cynics,  Stoics,  Hedonists,  Platonists,  Aristotel 
ians,  etc.           .        .        .        ....        .        .        .        .  307 

Writings  of  Socrates— Poetry  and  Tragedy,        .        .        .  311 

Socrates  as  a  soldier — his  military  services  and  actions,     .  312 
His  quarrel  with  the  Sophists  and  Rhetoricians  and  cause 

of  his  death,                      , 314 

The  trial  of  Socrates, 318 

His  imprisonment,          .        ...        .        .                 .        .  325 

After  his  death.    Decline  of  Greece.     Honors  paid  and  re 
morse  and  sorrow  shown  by  Greeks  and  others,         .  331 


LIST    OF    ILLUSTRATIONS. 

PAQH 

1.  Portrait  of  Z.  Sidney  Sampson,  President  Brooklyn 

Ethical    Association   during    this    lecture   course. 
From  photograph  loaned  by  Mrs.  Sampson.     Frontispiece 

2.  Portrait  of  Prof.  James  H.  Hyslop,      ....        xxv 

3.  Pouch  Mansion,    Brooklyn,    N.    Y.      Lecture   Hall  of 

Brooklyn  Ethical  Association,          .        .        .        .^  in 

4.  Studio  House  of  Mrs.  Ole  Bull,  Cambridge,  Mass.      .  vin 

5.  Library  Columbia  University, ix 

6.  Head  of  Pythagoras,  from  an  Ancient  Cameo.     Kind 

ness  of  Open  Court  Pub.  Co.,  Chicago,          .         .  4 

7.  Figure  of  Pythagoras.      From  Stanley's   History  of 

Philosophy,  London,  1701, 68 

8.  Head  of  Socrates.     From  Bust  in  Villa  Albani.     Kind 

ness  of  Walter  Thorp  Co.,  of  New  York.     From 
World's  Great  Classics, xm 

9.  Figure  of  Socrates.     From  Stanley's   History  of  Phi 

losophy.    London,  1701, 34 

10.     Head  of  Plato.     From  Bust  in  the  Vatican.     Kindness 
of  Walter  Thorp  Co.,  New  York,   publishers  of 

World's  Great  Classics xix 

n.     Figure  of  Plato.    From  Stanley's  History  of  Philosophy.       49 

12.  Head  of  Aristotle.     From  a  Sculpture  in  the  Gal.  Du 

Capitole.     Kindness  of  the  Open  Court  Pub.  Co., 
Chicago,  .  231 

13.  Head  of  Aristotle.     From  Sculpture  in  Spada  Palace, 

Rome.    Kindness  of  Walter  Thorp  Co. ,  New  York. 
Illustration  from  World's  Great  Classics,        .        .      xxn 

14.  Figure  of  Aristotle.     From  statue  in  Spada   Palace, 

Rome.    Kindness  of  Geo.  Putnam's  Sons  ;  plate 
from  "Alexander  the  Great,"  by  Wheeler,      .        .        55 

15.  Figure  of  Aristotle.    From  Stanley's  History  of  Phi 

losophy,  ........         197 

(g) 


h  ILLUSTRATIONS. 

PAGB 

16.  Head  of  Epicurus.    From  Bust  in  Museo  Capitolino, 

Rome, 169 

17.  Figure  of  Epicurus.     From  Stanley's  History  of  Phi 

losophy,     176 

18.  Aristippus  the  "Hedonist."    From  Stanley's  History 

of  Philosophy, 172 

19.  Empedocles — a  pioneer  of  Evolution.    From  Stanley's 

History  of  Philosophy, 191 

20.  Herbert  Spencer. — The  Modern  Aristotle.    From  pho 

tograph  presented  in  1894  to  Dr.  Lewis  G.  Janes, 
President  of  The  Brooklyn  Ethical  Association. 
Kindness  of  Mrs.  Janes, 178 

21.  Gateway    of  Mount   Auburn  Cemetery,  Cambridge, 

Mass.,  with  its  misconceived  Scriptural  text  for 
Immortality, 133 


INTRODUCTION. 

THE  present  lecture  on  The  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Phi 
losophers  is  one  of  a  course  on  The  Evolution  of 
Ethics  delivered  before  the  Brooklyn  Ethical  Associa 
tion  in  the  years  1896  and  1897.  Some  of  these  lectures 
were  also  given  at  the  Cambridge  Conferences  at  "  The 
Studio  House  "  of  Mrs.  Ole  Bull  in  Cambridge,  Mass., 
of  which  conferences  the  late  Dr.  Lewis  G.  Janes  was 
then  director,  having  been  previously  President  of  The 
Brooklyn  Ethical  Association  for  several  terms.  The 
full  list  of  these  lectures  is  as  follows : — 

ORIGIN  OF  ETHICAL  IDEAS, 
Dr.  Lewis  G.  Janes,  M.  A. 

ETHICAL  IDEAS  OF  THE  HINDUS, 
Swami  Saradananda  of  India. 

ETHICS  OF  ZOROASTER  AND  THE  PARSIS, 

Mr.  Jehanghile  Dossabhoy  Cola,  of  Bombay,  India. 

ETHICS  OF  BUDDHISM, 

Anagarika  H.  Dharmapala,  of  Colombo,  Ceylon. 

ETHICS  OF  THE  CHINESE  SAGES, 

Prof.  F.  Huberty  James,  Imperial  University,  Peking 

(i) 


ii  Introduction. 

ETHICS  OF  THE  GREEK  PHILOSOPHERS, 

Prof.  Jas.  H.  Hyslop,  Columbia  University,  New  York 

ETHICS  OF  THE  STOICS  AND  EPICUREANS, 

Rev.  Merle  St.  Croix  Wright  of  New  York. 

ETHICS  OF  THE  HEBREWS, 

Rabbi  Joseph  Silverman  of  New  York. 

ETHICS  OF  THE  MOHAMMEDANS, 

Mr.  Z.  Sidney  Sampson  of  New  York. 

ETHICS  OF  THE  NEW  TESTAMENT, 

Prof.  Crawford  Ho  well  Toy,  D.D.,  of  Harvard  Uni 
versity. 

ETHICS  OF  THE  GERMAN  SCHOOLS, 

Miss  Anna  Bo}rnton  Thompson  of  Boston. 

UTILITARIAN  ETHICS, 

Dr.  Robert  G.  Eccles  of  Brooklyn  and 

Prof.  Benjamin  Underwood  of  Quincy,  111. 

ETHICS  OF  EVOLUTION, 

Rev.  John  C.  Kimball  of  Sharon,  Mass.,  and 
M.  Mangassarin  of  New  York. 

This  series  of  lectures  was  proposed  and  arranged 
chiefly  by  our  former  esteemed  President,  Mr.  Z.  Sidney 
Sampson,  whose  death  in  1897,  followed  by  some  changes 
in  the  Association,  has  been  one  of  the  causes  which 
have  helped  to  delay  the  publication,  but  it  has  now 
devolved  on  the  undersigned,  a  member  of  our  Commit 
tee  on  Comparative  Religion,  to  edit  and  publish  this 
interesting  series,  which  it  is  believed  will  be  found  to 
be  an  important  addition  to  the  previous  volumes  of 
lectures  issued  by  the  Association,  as  it  contains  perhaps 
some  of  the  best  work  of  the  Association  and  one  which 
is  particularly  harmonious  with  our  title  and  scope,  giv 
ing  as  it  does  a  complete  outline  or  general  comprehen- 


POUCH  MANSION,  BROOKLYN,  N.  Y, 

LECTURE  HALL,  BROOKLYN  ETHICAL  ASS'N. 


Introduction.  iii 

sion  of  the  history  and  philosophy  of  Ethics  as  shown 
in  the  various  schools  or  sects  of  the  world. 

Most  of  the  lectures  of  the  series  as  above  listed  are 
now  in  plates  ready  for  printing,  and  all  of  these  lec 
tures  will  be  ultimately  included  in  one  large  volume 
which  will  be  issued  in  due  course,  while  some  one  or 
more  lectures  will  be  issued  in  smaller  special  volumes 
according  as  their  special  importance  or  popularity  may 
warrant. 

The  present  lecture  of  Prof.  Hyslop  on  The  Ethics  of 
Socrates,  Plato  and  Aristotle  has  been  thought  of  suffi 
cient  individual  importance  and  interest  to  form  a  little 
volume  by  itself  which  is  now  issued  as  one  of  the  first 
of  the  series.  And  we  think  that  a  glance  through  this 
little  book  will  justify  our  estimate  and  show  that  Prof. 
Hyslop  is  a  great  student  and  able  expositor  of  the 
teachings  of  that  great  trinity  of  Grecian  intellect  who 
have  probably  left  more  effect  on  the  thought  and  belief 
of  our  European  races  and  civilizations  than  any  other 
men  in  History.  Prof.  Hyslop  has  thus  given  us  in  this 
little  treatise  a  very  comprehensive  view  of  the  general 
character  and  special  influence  of  each  great  thinker  and 
with  a  keen  and  clear  analysis  and  easy  presentation 
has  so  distinguished  and  epitomized  their  distinctive 
teachings  that  at  one  sitting  we  can  get  a  fairly  good 
and  general  view  of  the  three  most  influential  philoso 
phers  of  the  past,  putting  in  a  popular,  easily  assimi 
lable  form  what  is  generally  regarded  as  a  rather  abstruse 
subject. 

To  better  illustrate  the  points  in  the  lecture  and  more 
clearly  show  the  exact  character  of  the  ancient  thought, 
we  have,  with  the  assistance  of  Prof.  Hyslop,  selected 
and  arranged  a  series  of  quotations  from  the  best  trans- 
lations  of  the  works  of  the  philosophers,  which  we  have 


iv  Introduction. 

included  in  the  appendix,  and  which  will  demonstrate 
the  beauty,  clearness  and  force  of  the  actual  thought  of 
these  giants  of  the  ancient  intellectual  world  and  prove 
to  us  how  much  we  are  really  their  heirs  and  debtors 
along  so  many  lines  of  thought  and  influence.  On  the 
subjects  of  The  Nature  and  Constitution  of  the  Uni 
verse,  on  Matter  and  Spirit,  Soul,  Deity,  Ethics  and 
Immortality,  Socrates,  Plato,  and  Aristotle  have  proba 
bly  left  on  us  a  greater  impression  than  all  other  men, 
and  will  be  found  to  have  furnished  most  of  the  philo 
sophical  arguments  which  have  been  echoed  and  re 
echoed,  more  or  less  consciously  or  unconsciously,  by 
others  ever  since  that  distant  age  when  these  great  origi 
nal  thinkers  or  expounders  first  expressed  or  recorded 
them,  and  with  little  real  advance  over  these  old  think 
ers.  We  therefore  regard  it  of  the  greatest  interest  and 
importance  that  men  of  the  modern  age  should  pay 
more  attention  to  the  study  of  ancient  thought  and 
appreciate  far  more  than  they  do  the  great  wrork  done 
by  the  old  thinkers,  as  only  in  this  way  can  we  get  a 
correct  view  of  our  own  age  and  understand  what  prog 
ress  we  have  really  made  ourselves,  and  in  many  cases 
it  will  be  a  good  check  to  our  conceit,  and  a  great  help 
to  modest  and  truthful  views  to  find  that  we  have  not 
made  as  many  or  as  great  or  as  original  contributions 
to  our  "  progress"  as  we  may  have  imagined. 

In  this  age  of  advancing  womanhood,  it  is  interesting 
to  look  back  to  that  brilliant  age  of  Greece,  when  woman- 
philosophers,  poets,  and  rhetoricians,  contended  for 
prizes  with  men  and  often  won  them  on  their  merits,  and 
when  we  might  see  the  greatest  masculine  intellects  of 
the  day  sitting  at  the  feet  of  brilliantly  educated  women 
and  learning  from  them,  Socrates  for  instance  at  the  feet 
of  Diotima,  the  great  Pythagorean  woman-philosopher 


Introduction.  v 

who  taught  him  the  true  philosophy  of  the  universal 
principle  of  Beneficent  and  Creative  Love,  as  is  shown 
in  the  extracts  from  the  Symposium. 

The  names  of  Sappho,  B.  C.  600,  and  Myrtis  and 
Corinna,  B.  C.  500,  are  famous  in  the  annals  of  poetry 
and  the  history  of  Greece.  Corinna  was  a  great  edu 
cator  as  well  as  a  great  poetess,  and  the  teacher  of  Pindar, 
the  chief  lyric  poet  of  Greece,  over  whom  she  won  the 
prize  for  poetry  five  times  in  public  contests.  Aspasia 
to  whom — whether  rightly  or  wrongly — a  questionable 
name  has  been  popularly  attached,  was,  without  ques 
tion,  a  most  brilliant  and  accomplished  woman,  a  teacher 
of  philosophy  and  rhetoric  in  Athens  and  the  composer 
of  the  orations  of  Pericles,  one  of  the  greatest  statesmen 
of  Greece,  in  the  most  brilliant  period  of  her  history. 
It  would  be  hard  to  find  women  in  our  own  day  of  such 
relative  eminence  in  letters  and  public  life,  and  this 
striking  fact  should  help  to  make  the  study  of  ancient 
thought  and  ancient  thinkers  and  writers  attractive  and 
interesting  to  us  at  this  da}r. 

Special  attention  is  also  called  to  the  extracts  from  the 
Phsedo  and  other  works  on  Virtue  and  the  Immortality 
of  the  Soul,  giving  the  remarkable  thoughts  and  argu 
ments  of  Socrates  and  showing  the  exaltation  of  ideas, 
and  the  clearness  and  beauty  of  the  old  Greek  thought. 
And  these  thoughts,  it  must  be  remembered,  were  re 
corded  nearly  five  hundred  years  before  any  part  of  the 
New  Testament  was  composed  and  will  be  found  to  give 
a  clearer  statement  of  the  main  doctrines  of  the  prevail 
ing  popular  religions  than  can  be  found  in  the  Old  or 
New  Testaments  themselves,  such  doctrines  for  example 
as  absorption  in  ideal  virtue,  abstraction  from  a  worldly 
life  and  living  for  a  future  state  of  perfection  after 


vi  Introduction. 

death ;  Immortality  of  the  Soul,  Heaven,  Purgatory,  and 
Hell,  etc. 

The  ancient  Egyptians,  above  all  other  peoples,  seem 
to  have  had  the  most  elaborate  and  intense  belief  in 
immortality  of  the  soul,  resurrection  of  the  body  and 
future  states  of  rewards  and  punishments,  and  from  them 
these  doctrines  seem  to  have  spread  to  the  races  on  both 
shores  of  the  Mediterranean.  Indeed,  modern  investiga 
tions  have  clearly  shown  the  undoubted  influence  that 
ancient  Egypt  had  on  ancient  Greece  in  art,  religion  and 
philosophy,  and  have  also  shown  that  Europe  was 
probably  first  peopled,  or  at  least  most  influenced  in  its 
civilization,  from  the  adjacent  Africa  and  not  from  the 
distant  India  as  had  been  the  most  popular  theory  for 
many  years.*  The  clear  teaching  of  the  Greek  phi 
losophers  on  immortality,  etc.,  as  now  shown  in  the  ex 
tracts  herein  given,  is  therefore  a  good  illustration  of 
this  Egyptian  influence  long  before  the  Christian  era,  as 
the  Greek  teaching  is  almost  identical  with  that  which 
was  prevalent  in  ancient  Egypt,f  and  the  Greeks  gen 
erally  acknowledged  their  debt  to  Egypt  and  Chaldea 
for  many  of  their  ideas  (see  the  extracts  from  the  Timaeus 
in  the  appendix). 

It  is  also  interesting  to  here  note  that  in  Aristotle  we 
will  find  the  great  prototype  of  the  modern  Scientific, 
Rational,  and  Evolutionary  Schools,  as  he  had  clearly 
anticipated  the  modern  ideas  of  Natural  Development  or 
"Evolution,"  also  "Utilitarianism"  in  Ethics  and  a 
broad  "  Democracy "  in  Politics.  Indeed,  in  reading 
over  the  strong  sentences  of  Aristotle,  we  will  be  often 

*  See  works  of  Maspero,  Petrie  and  others  on  Egypt.  Also  lectures  of  Amelia 
B.  Edwards  (Harper  &  Bros.)  and  Prof.  Sergi  on  The  Mediterranean  Race 
(Scribner  &  Sons). 

t  See  new  translation  of  the  Egyptian  ' '  Book  of  the  Dead  "  by  E.  A.  Wallis 
Budge  of  the  British  Museum— Open  Court  Pub.  Co.,  Chicago. 


Introduction.  vii 

struck  with  what  we  might  call  the  remarkable  modernity 
of  his  thought,  and  in  his  Politics  this  is  particularly 
apparent,  so  that  if  we  did  not  know  the  author  we  might 
now  and  then  suppose  that  we  were  looking  over  a 
recent  high-class  political  speech,  an  editorial  in  the 
day's  paper,  or  a  magazine  article  from  the  latest 
issue. 

We  therefore  think  it  will  be  interesting  and  agreeably 
surprising  if  the  man  of  to-day  will  read  over  our  ex 
tracts  from  the  Politics  giving  Aristotle's  clear  ideas  on 
Public  Schools  and  the  careful  education  of  the  young 
on  physical,  mental  and  moral  lines  ;  his  remarkable 
emphasis  on  the  use  of  music  in  education  and  its  ethical 
values  and  dangers,  etc. ;  his  denunciation  of  excessive 
athletics  in  education  and  his  exposure  of  the  fallacy 
that  the  professional  athlete  is  necessarily  a  good  physical 
type,  which  some  of  our  best  modern  authorities  are  only 
now  beginning  to  rediscover.  It  will  be  equally  inter 
esting  and  refreshing  to  note  what  is  said  on  " business" 
and  "leisure"  and  on  war  and  peace  in  his  views  on  the 
Best  or  Ideal  Life,  and  the  superiority  of  culture  and 
character  or  "  goods  of  the  soul  "  over  mere  wealth  or 
worldly  success  ;  his  condemnation  of  all  government 
except  that  based  on  the  consent  and  for  "  the  good  of 
the  governed  "  and  his  denunciations  of  all  wars  of  con 
quest  and  the  domination  of  one  race  by  another  through 
mere  force.  All  of  this  will  be  found  to  have  an  ex 
tremely  "  advanced  "  or  "  modern  "  tone,  yet  it  was 
written  nearly  twenty-four  centuries  ago  by  a  thinker 
who  was  one  of  the  highest  products  of  an  old  civiliza 
tion,  which  with  all  our  modern  conceit  we  must  admit 
was  probably,  in  its  best  examples,  characterized  by  as 
high  a  standard  in  the  physical,  the  ethical  and  the 
artistic  as  the  human  creature  has  ever  attained  on  earth. 


viii  Introduction. 

We  have  therefore  made  the  most  extensive  extracts 
from  the  "  Politics"  because  of  this  great  general  inter 
est  and  because  they  contain  so  many  points  illustrating 
the  true  principles  of  general  or  applied  ethics  as  well 
as  of  broad  politics. 

The  little  states  of  ancient  Greece  with  their  active 
versatile  peoples,  their  able  statesmen  and  philosophers, 
seem  indeed  to  have  experienced  almost  every  phase  and 
kind  of  politics  and  form  of  government,  and  had  thus 
worked  out  for  us  the  examples  and  problems  of  almost 
every  kind  that  we  have  since  had  or  now  have  to  deal 
with  in  modern  ethics  and  politics,  and  it  will  certainly 
be  both  interesting  and  instructive  for  us  to  now  look 
over  the  treatment  of  these  questions  and  problems  by 
one  of  the  greatest  political  philosophers  who  lived 
twenty-four  centuries  before  us,  and  to  note  his  criticisms 
and  commendations  of  the  false  and  true  in  Ethics,  in 
Democracy  and  in  Free  Institutions  from  that  distance 
of  time.  In  our  natural  "Anglo-Saxon "  and  "Teu 
tonic"  bias,  we  have  been  perhaps  too  much  inclined  to 
accept  the  too  popular  idea  that  the  main  inspiration  for 
all  our  modern  free  institutions  originated  in  "  the  for 
ests  of  Germany"  or  on  "the  shores  of  the  Baltic," 
forgetting  that  most  of  our  modern  institutions  were  first 
thought  out  and  most  of  our  modern  problems  tested  at 
a  much  earlier  age  in  a  more  complete  way  on  the  classic 
shores  of  the  Mediterranean  from  whence  we  have  un 
doubtedly  also  got  so  much  of  our  speech,  our  thought 
and  our  civilization.* 

*In  an  old  English  History  by  Nath.  Bacon,  published  in  London  in  1647,  an 
interesting  theory  of  the  origin  of  the  Saxons  is  given,  viz. ,  that  they  sprang 
from  some  of  the  Macedonian  legions  of  Alexander's  army  which  penetrated  to 
the  far  north  of  Europe.  If  this  should  be  true,  we  cou*d  thus,  after  all,  trace 
the  free  institutions  and  liberal  ideas  of  the  Saxon  directly  back  to  the  old 
Greek  period  and  to  the  broad  influence  of  Aristotle,  who  was  the  tutor  of 
Alexander  and  the  great  political  and  ethical  philosopher  of  the  Macedonian 
Court. 


02 


o 
W 

e  S 
fe  § 

2    ^ 

§  2 

&     "^a 

^  S 
^  P? 
^  ca 


bd 
c=l 
tr1 


Introduction.  \  •/.. 

The  central  figure  among  the  Greek  Philosophers  wa  9 
however,  the  great  old  Master,  Socrates,  who  for  his  hig 
moral  sense  and  wonderful  reasoning  powers  was  called 
by  his  distinguished  young  pupil  Alcibiades,  the  en 
chanter  and  conqueror  of  all  men  in  conversation  or  dis 
putation,  as  expressed  in  the  "  Symposium."  And  it 
must  not  be  forgotten  that  Socrates  was  more  eminent 
in  Moral  Philosophy  than  in  anything  else,  his  work  be 
ing  devoted  chiefly  to  Ethics  and  but  little  to  Physics,  for 
which  latter  he  seems  to  have  had  more  or  less  contempt. 
Even  the  most  superficial  student  cannot  fail  to  notice  a 
remarkable  parallel  between  Socrates  and  Christ  in  many 
features  connected  with  their  life  and  death,  and  in  their 
character  and  teachings,  so  much  so  that  Socrates  might 
properly  be  called  the  "Pagan  Christian"  if  not  the 
"  Pagan  Christ,"  and  the  several  extracts  given  in  the 
Appendix  and  in  the  inserts  from  the  teachings  of  Soc 
rates  will,  we  think,  show  this  resemblance  or  relation 
at  a  glance.  In  his  pure  theistic  conception  of  God  and 
the  government  of  the  Universe  (which  was  not  of 
course  uncommon  in  the  Pagan  world),  in  his  vivid  be 
lief  in  the  personal  immortality  of  the  soul  and  its  future 
states  of  probation,  reward  and  punishment,  his  serious 
belief  in  Divine  Inspiration,  his  doctrine  of  Love,  and 
his  earnest  contention  for  a  life  of  ideal  virtue  and  un- 
worldliness,  he  approached  most  closely  to  the  belief  of 
the  primitive  Christian  sect  itself.  And  not  only  is  it 
strictly  true  to  say,  as  before  indicated,  that  the 
Christian's  own  scripture  nowhere  contains  such  a  clear, 
distinct,  and  detailed  account  of  their  own  doctrine  of 
the  soul  and  its  future,  as  can  be  found  expressed  in  the 
words  of  Socrates,  but  it  is  perhaps  not  too  much  to  say 
that  no  extant  writing  anywhere  contains  so  good  an 
expression  of  these  doctrines  and  of  the  philosophic 


jr  -      t  Introduction. 

K<~v. 

irguments  in  support  of  them  as  could  be  found  in  the 
ivords  of  Socrates  in  Plato's  Phaedo  over  four  hundred 
years  before  the  appearance  of  the  Christian  sect. 

Not  only,  therefore,  is  this  old  Greek  Master  found  to 
stand  pre-eminent  in  the  teaching  and  exposition  of 
some  great  religious  doctrines,  but  a  further  notable  and 
most  interesting  fact,  which  should  be  more  appreciated 
by  ethical  students  of  our  own  day,  is  that  Socrates  also 
seems  to  have  been  really  the  father  of  Modern  Utilitari 
an  Ethics.  This  modernly  revised  ethical  theory  was 
clearly  outlined  and  developed  by  Socrates  and  after 
wards  was  taught  by  Aristotle,  the  pupil  of  Socrates' 
chief  pupil — Plato — and  later  on  was  given  a  very  full 
expression  by  Epicurus,  an  immediate  successor  of  Aris 
totle,  who,  after  Socrates,  was  probably  the  clearest  ex 
ponent  of  the  Utilitarian  school  of  ethics  in  ancient 
times:  And  we  have  shown  in  the  Appendix  how  iden 
tical  is  the  teaching  of  Socrates  with  the  teaching  of 
that  great  master  of  the  modern  utilitarian  school, 
Herbert  Spencer,  in  his  Data  of  Ethics,  a  point  which 
should  be  more  known  and  appreciated  than  it  now 
seems  to  be — and  should  add  interest  to  the  stud}^  of 
those  great  pioneers  of  thought,  the  Greek  Philosophers, 
in  which  we  hope  this  little  work  may  be  of  some  help. 
To  add  a  pictorial  interest  we  have  obtained  and  in 
serted  a  number  of  portraits  of  the  Greek  philosophers, 
some  of  which  are  seldom  seen,  to  better  acquaint  our 
readers,  not  only  with  the  ancient  thought,  but  writh  the 
personal  appearance  of  the  great  thinkers  themselves, 
who  have  so  deeply  influenced  the  morals  and  the 
thought  of  the  human  race. 

We  have  also  added  a  brief  sketch  of  Pythagoras  and 
his  school,  the  great  predecessor  of  Socrates  and  Plato, 
who  had  probably  the  greatest  influence  on  their  thought, 


LIBRARY  COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


Introduction.  xi 

and  we  have  concluded  the  work  with  a  life  of  Socrates 
in  condensed  form  to  give  a  better  idea  of  the  great  per 
sonality  who  so  dominated  and  influenced  all  later 
schools  of  Greek  thinking. 

We  have  to  thank  the  Open  Court  Publishing  Co.  of 
Chicago,  and  also  the  Walter  Thorp  Co.  and  G.  P- 
Putnam's  Sons  of  New  York,  for  the  use  of  some  of 
these  portraits. 

CHAS.  M.  HIGGINS, 

Of  Committee  on  Comparative  Religion, 

Brooklyn  Ethical  Association. 

271   Ninth  Street,  Brooklyn,  N.  Y., 
May  ist,   1903. 


FORETASTES  AND  KEYNOTES 


FROM 


THE  GREAT  PAGAN  PROPHETS 

SOCRATES, 

PLATO, 
ARISTOTLE. 

"  Outside  the  sacred  literature  of  the  world,  Socrates 
Plato,  and  Aristotle  were  the  main  factors  of  civiliza 
tion.  They  fulfilled  a  truly  sublime  mission  in  their 
day  and  nation,  for  in  the  fourth  century  B.  C.  these 
philosophers  and  their  disciples  made  an  end  to  the 
more  ancient  materialism  and  built  up  those  systems 
of  philosophy,  including  the  natural  sciences,  which 
have  exercised  so  vast  an  influence  upon  the  progress 
of  man,  and  still  do  in  very  many  instances.  They 
were  the  great  prophets  of  the  human  conscience  in  the 
pagan  world" 

Davis — u  Greek  &  Roman  Stoicism." 


(xii) 


SOCRATES  ON  IMMORTALITY. 

B.  C.  399- 

"  And  are  we  to  suppose  that  the  soul,  which  is  invisible,  in  pass 
ing  to  the  true  Hades,  which  like  her  is  invisible,  and  pure,  and 
noble,  and  on  her  way  to  the  good  and  wise  God,  whither,  if  God 
will,  my  soul  is  soon  to  go — that  the  soul,  I  repeat,  if  this  be  her 
nature  and  origin,  is  blown  away  and  perishes  immediately  on 
quitting  the  body,  as  the  many  say  ?  That  can  never  be,  my  dear 
Simmias  and  Cedes. 

*•  Then,  Cebes,  beyond  question  the  soul  is  immortal  and  imper 
ishable,  and  our  souls  will  truly  exist  in  another  world! 
.  "But  then,  O  my  friends,  if  the  soul  is  really  immortal,  what 
care  should  be  taken  of  her,  not  only  in  respect  of  the  portion  of 
time  which  is  called  life,  but  of  eternity  !  And  the  danger  of  neg 
lecting  her  from  this  point  of  view  does  indeed  appear  to  be 
awful.  If  death  had  only  been  the  end  of  all,  the  wicked  would 
have  a  good  bargain  in  dying,  for  they  would  have  been  happily 
quit,  not  only  of  their  body  but  of  their  own  evil,  together  with 
their  souls.  But  now,  as  the  soul  plainly  appears  to  be  immortal, 
there  is  no  release  or  salvation  from  evil  except  the  attainment  of 
the  highest  virtue  and  wisdom. 

"  Wherefore,  Simmias,  seeing  all  these  things,  what  ought  not  we 
to  do,  in  order  to  obtain  virtue  and  wisdom  in  this  life  ?  Fair  is 
the  prize  and  the  hope  great. 

"  Wherefore  I  say,  let  a  man  be  of  good  cheer  about  his  soul, 
who  has  cast  away  the  pleasures  and  ornaments  of  the  body  as  alien 
to  him,  and  rather  hurtful  in  their  effects,  and  has  followed  after 
the  pleasures  of  knowledge  in  this  life  ;  who  has  adorned  the  soul 
^  in  her  own  proper  jewels,  which  are  temperance,  and  justice,  and 
J  courage,  and  nobility,  and  truth — in  these  arrayed  she  is  ready  to 
l  go  on  her  journey  below  when  her  time  comes." 
*  Plato's  Ph&do. 

THE  SOCRATIC-UTILITARIAN  THEORY  OF 
ETHICS. 

4 '  Then  I  should  say  to  them  in  my  name  and  yours  :  Do  you 
think  them  evil  for  any  other  reason  except  that  they  end  in  pain 
and  rob  us  of  other  pleasures  ?  ' ' 

"  And  do  you  call  them  good  because  they  occasion  the  greatest 
immediate  suffering  and  pain  ;  or  because  afterwards  they  bring 
health  and  improvement  of  the  bodily  condition  and  the  salvation 
of  states,  and  empires,  and  wealth." 

"  Are  these  things  good  for  any  other  reason  except  that  they 
end  in  pleasure  and  get  rid  of  and  avert  pain  ?  Are  you  looking 
to  any  other  standard  but  pleasure  and  pain  when  you  call  them 
good?" 

Plato's  "Protagoras." 


• 


SOCRATES, 

B.  C.  468  to  399. 

THE  GREAT  ANCIENT  EXPONENT   OF   THE  RELIGIOUS  DOCTRINE 

OF  THE  IMMORTAL  SOUL,   AND  THE  ETHICAL 

DOCTRINE  OF  UTILITARIANISM. 

(From  bust  iu  Villa  Albani. ) 


XIII 


WISDOM  AND    KNOWLEDGE. 
FOLLY  AND  IGNORANCE. 

To  be  ignorant  of  ourselves,  to  seem  to  know  those 
things  whereof  we  are  ignorant,  is  next  to  madness.  , 

The  chief  wisdom  of  man  consists  in  not  thinking 
he  understands  those  things  which  he  doth  not  under 
stand. 

There  is  but  one  good,  knowledge,  one  ill,  ignorance. 

Socrates  300,  B.  C. 


XIV 


CHARACTER  AND  SINCERITY. 

There  is  no  better  way  to  glory  than  to  endeavor 
to  be  good  as  well  as  to  seem  such. 

Good  men  must  let  the  world  see  that  their  manners 
are  more  firm  than  an  oath. 

In  the  life  of  man,  as  in  an  image,  every  part  ought 
to  be  beautiful. 

An  honest  death  is  better  than  a  dishonest  life. 

Socrates. 


XV 


POLITICAL    MORALITY. 

They  are  not  kings  who  are  in  possession  of  a 
throne  or  come  unjustly  by  it,  but  they  who  know  how 
to  govern. 

A  king  is  ruler  of  willing  subjects  according  to  the 
laws,  a  tyrant  is  ruler  of  subjects  against  their  will, 
not  according  to  the  laws,  but  arbitrarily. 

That  city  is  strongest  which  hath  virtuous  men; 
that  city  is  best  wherein  are  proposed  most  rewards 
of  virtue.  That  city  lives  best  which  liveth  according 
to  law  and  punisheth  the  unjust. 

Faith  should  be  kept  more  strictly  with  a  city  than 
with  private  persons. 
•  Whatever  inconvenience  may  ensue,  nothing  is  to  be 

preferred  before  justice. 

Socrates. 


XVI 


VIRTUE    AND    FILIAL   DUTY. 

Virtue  is  the  beauty,  vice  the  deformity  of  the  soul. 

The  greatest  of  vices  is  ingratitude. 

The  greatest  obligation  is  that  to  parents. 

Socrates. 


XVII 


RELIGION. 

The  Gods  are  to  be  worshipped  according  to  the  law 
of  the  city  where  a  man  lives. 

The  best  way  of  worshipping  God  is  to  do  what  He 
commands. 

Our  prayers  should  be  for  blessings  in  general,  for 
God  knows  best  what  is  good  for  us,  our  offerings  pro 
portioned  to  our  abilities,  for  He  considers  integrity 
not  munificence. 

Socrates. 


XVIII 


PRUDENCE. 

Be  not  forward  in  speech,  for  many  times  the  tongue 
has  cut  off  the  head. 

When   a  man  opens  his  mouth,  his   virtues  are  as 
manifest  as  images  in  a  temple. 

In  war,  steel  is  better  than  gold:  In  life,  wisdom 
excelleth  wealth. 

When  a  woman  saith  she  loveth  thee,  take  heed  of 
these  words  more  than  when  she  revileth  thee. 

A  young  man's  virtue  is  to  do  nothing  too  much. 

Socrates. 


PLATO,  the  great  idealistic  philosopher  of  the 
Grecian  schools,  having  the  deepest  influence  on  both 
the  religious  and  philosophic  thought  of  Jewish  and 
Christian  sects.  It  has  been  said  of  the  great  Jewish 
Philosopher  Philo — contemporary  with  Christ  and  the 
Apostles — that  he  was  so  great  a  follower  of  Plato, 
that  it  was  a  common  saying  among  the  ancients  that 
"either  Plato  Philonises  or  Philo  Platonises."  (See 
Preface  in  the  works  of  Philo  Judaeus,  translated  by 
C.  D.  Yonge.)  St.  Augustine^  one  of  the  most  learned 
and  influential  of  the  Christian  "Fathers"  in  his 
"  City  of  God"  naively  acknowledges  that  "  none  come 
nearer  to  us  than  the  Platonists" 

It  is  interesting  also  to  note  that  a  mystic  or  divine 
quality  was  imputed  to  Plato  by  his  followers,  similar 
to  that  claimed  for  Christ,  viz.,  that  he  was  a  divine 
incarnation  or  super-human  being.  In  the  life  of 
Plato  given  in  Stanley^  s  History  of  Philosophy,  he 
states  that: — "Plutarch,  Suidas  and  others  affirm  it 
to  have  been  commonly  reported  at  Athens  that  he 
(Plato)  was  the  son  of  Apollo,  who  appearing  in  a 
vision  to  his  mother,  a  woman  of  extraordinary 
beauty — she  thereupon  conceived." 

"  He  did  not  issue  from  a  mortal  bed. 
"  A  God  his  sire,  a  Godlike  life  he  led. ' ' 

"Some  therefore  affirmed  he  was  born  of  a  Virgin, 
and  it  was  a  common  speech  among  the  Athenians  that 
Phcebus  begat  Esculapius  and  Plato,  one  to  cure 
bodies,  the  other  souls." 

The  name  "Plato"  seems  to  mean  broad,  and  was 
given  by  his  father  Ariston,  on  account  of  the  literal 
or  figurative  "  broadness"  in  the  physical  and  mental 
qualities  of  his  gifted  son.  It  will  be  seen  in  the 
portraits  that  the  brow  on  the  handsome  face  of  Plato 
has  the  broadness  and  smoothness  of  a  "plateau," 
which  doubtless  means  the  same  as  "Plato."  And  as 
to  the  mental  sense  of  the  word,  it  is  certain  that  few 
thinkers  were  more  elevated  and  extended  in  their 
writings  or  so  broad  and  profound  in  their  thinking 
as  this  immortal  pupil  of  Socrates,  hence  the  fitness 
and  beauty  of  his  name  "  Plato." 


PLATO, 

B.  C.  400. 
From  original  marble  bust  in  the  Vatican. 


xtx- 


HONESTY  AND  RECIPROCITY. 

u  In  the  next  place,  dealings  between  man  and  man 
require  to  be  suitably  regulated.  The  principle  of 
them  is  very  simple:  Thou  shalt  not  touch  that  which 
is  mine,  if  thou  canst  help,  or  remove  the  least  thing 
which  belongs  to  me  without  my  consent;  and  may  I, 
being  of  sound  mind,  do  to  others  as  I  would  that  they 
should  do  to  me" 

Plates  "Laws,"  400  B.  C. 


THE   ETERNAL. 

"Now  the  beginning  is  unbegotten,  for  that  which 
is  begotten  has  a  beginning,  but  the  beginning  has  no 
beginning •,  for  if  a  beginning  were  begotten  of  some 
thing,  that  would  have  no  beginning.  But  that  which 
is  unbegotten  must  also  be  indestructible ;  for  if  be 
ginning  were  destroyed,  there  could  be  no  beginning 
out  of  anything,  or  anything  out  of  a  beginning  ;  and 
all  things  must  have  a  beginning.  And  therefore  the 
self-moving  is  the  beginning  of  motion;  and  this  can 
neither  be  destroyed  nor  begotten.  But  if  the  self- 
moving  is  immortal,  he  who  affirms  that  self-motion  is 
the  very  idea  and  essence  of  the  soul  will  not  be  put  to 
confusion.  But  if  the  soul  be  trzdy  affirmed  to  be  the 
self-moving,  then  must  she  also  be  without  beginning 
and  immortal" 

Plato^s  Phczdrus, 


XXI 


CIVIC  VIRTUE  AND  TRUE  STATESMANSHIP. 

"  Facts  easily  prove  that  mankind  do  not  acquire  or 
preserve  virtue  by  the  help  of  external  goods,  but  ex 
ternal  goods  by  the  help  of  virtue,  and  that  happiness, 
whether  consisting  in  pleasure  or  virtzie,  or  both,  is 
more  often  found  with  those  who  are  most  highly  culti 
vated  in  their  mind  and  in  their  character  and  have 
only  a  moderate  share  of  external  goods,  than  among 
those  who  possess  external  goods  to  a  useless  extent 
but  are  deficient  in  higher  qualities." 

"  Let  us  acknowledge  then  that  each  one  has  just  so 
much  of  happiness  as  he  has  of  virtue  and  wisdom  and 
of  virtuous  and  wise  action.  God  is  witness  to  us  of 
this  truth,  for  He  is  happy  and  blessed,  not  by  reason 
of  any  external  goods,  but  in  Himself  and  by  reason 
of  His  own  nature" 

"  Let  us  assume  then  that  the  best  life,  both  for  in 
dividuals  and  states,  is  the  life  of  virtue,  having  ex 
ternal  goods  enough  for  the  performance  of  good  ac 
tions.  Now  it  is  evident  that  the  form  of  government 
is  best  in  which  every  man,  whoever  he  is,  can  act  for 
the  best  and  live  happily." 

Aristotle.    350  B.  C. 


XXII 


LIFE   AND    PEACE. 

"  The  whole  of  life  is  fitrther  divided  into  two  parts, 
business  and  leisure,  war  and  peace,  and  all  actions 
into  those  which  are  necessary  and  useful  and  those 
which  are  honorable  :  there  must  be  war  for  the  sake 
of  peace,  business  for  the  sake  of  leisure,  things  useful 
and  necessary  for  the  sake  of  things  honorable.  For 
men  must  engage  in  business  and  go  to  war,  but 
leisure  and  peace  are  better ;  they  must  do  what  is 
useful  and  necessary,  but  what  is  honorable  is  better^ 
In  such  principles  children  and  persons  of  every  age 
should  be  trained,  whereas  even  the  Hellenes  of  the 
present  day,  who  are  reputed  to  be  the  best  governed, 
and  the  legislators  who  gave  them  their  constitutions, 
do  not  appear  to  have  framed  their  governments  with 
regard  to  the  best  end,  or  to  have  given  them  laws  and 
education  with  a  view  to  all  the  virtues,  but  in  a 
vulgar  spirit  have  fallen  back  on  those  which  promised 
to  be  more  useful  and  profitable" 

"  Facts  as  well  as  arguments  prove  that  the  legis 
lator  should  direct  all  his  military  and  other  measures 
to  the  provision  of  leisure  and  the  establishment  of 
peace.  For  most  of  those  military  states  are  safe  only 
while  they  are  at  war,  but  fall  when  they  have  ac 
quired  their  empire :  like  unused  iron  they  rust  in 
time  of  peace.  And  for  this  the  legislator  is  to  blame, 
he  never  having  taught  them  how  to  lead  the  life  of 
peace" 

Aristotle.     B.  C.  350. 


, 


A  R  IS  TO  TLE  may  be  truly  called  the  great  systematic  ra 
tionalist  or  scientist  of  the  Greek  schools,  a  father  of  the  modern 
scientific  method  who  taught — "  First  get  your  facts,  then  rea- 
son  on  them."  He  was  one  of  the  pioneers  in  the  theory  of 
"  Evolution  "  and  the  "  Utilitarian  "  theory  of  ethics,  purely  ra 
tionalistic  in  his  general  lines  of  thought,' highly  moral,  and 
scientific  in  his" ethics"  and  broadly  democratic  in  his  "Poli 
tics"  In  theology,  he  might  be  called  either  a  Theist  or  a  Pan 
theist. 

GIST  OF  ARISTOTLE'S  ETHICS. 
B.  C.  350. 

"  The  best  of  all  things  must  be  something  final.  If  then  there 
be  only  one  final  end,  this  will  be  what  we  are  seeking,  or  if  there 
be  more  than  one,  then  the  most  final  of  them. 

' '  Now  that  which  is  pursued  as  an  end  in  itself  is  more  final 
than  that  which  is  pursued  as  means  to  something  else,  and  that  is 
strictly  final  which  is  always  chosen  as  an  end  in  itself  and  never 
as  a  means. 

"Happiness  or  we  If  are  seems  more  than  anything  else  to  answer 
to  this  description  ;  for  we  always  choose  it  for  itself,  and  never 
for  the  sake  of  something  else. 

' '  Virtue  then  is  a  kind  of  moderation  in  as  much  as  it  aims  at 
the  mean  or  moderate  amount.  And  it  is  a  moderation  in  as  much 
as  it  comes  in  the  middle  or  mean  between  two  vices,  one  on  the 
side  of  excess,  the  other  on  the  side  of  defect,  and  in  as  much  as, 
while  these  vices  fall  short  of  or  exceed  the  due  measure  in  feeling 
and  in  action,  it  finds  and  chooses  the  'mean. 

1 '  Now  that  we  have  discussed  the  several  kinds  of  virtue,  it  re 
mains  to  give  a  summary  account  of  happiness,  since  we  are  to 
assume  that  it  is  the  end  of  all  that  man  does. 

' '  As  we  have  often  said,  that  is  truly  valuable  and  pleasant 
which  is  so  to  the  perfect  man.  Now,  the  exercise  of  those  trained 
faculties  which  are  proper  to  him  is  what  each  man  finds  most  de 
sirable  ;  what  the  perfect  man  finds  most  desirable,  therefore,  is 
the  exercise  of  virtue.  Happiness,  consequently,  does  not  consist 
in  amusement,  and  indeed  it  is  absurd  to  suppose  that  the  end  is 
amusement,  and  that  we  toil  and  moil  all  our  life  long  for  the  sake 
of  amusing  ourselves.  77ie  happy  life  is  thought  to  be  that  which 
exhibits  virtue,  and  such  a  life  must  be  serious  and  cannot  consist 
in  amusement. 

"  But  if  happiness  be  the  exercise  of  virtue,  it  is  reasonable  to 
suppose  that  it  will  be  the  exercise  of  the  highest  virtue  ;  and  that 
it  will  be  the  virtue  or  excellence  of  the  best  part  of  us.  Now  that 
part  or  faculty — call  it  reason  or  what  you  will— which  seems 
naturally  to  rule  and  take  the  lead,  and  to  apprehend  things  noble 
and  divine — whether  it  be  itself  divine ,  or  only  the  divine  st  part  of 
us — js  the  faculty  the  exercise  of  which,  in  its  proper  excellence, 
will  be  perfect  happiness. ' ' 


ARISTOTLE, 

MORAL,    POLITICAL    AND   NATURAL    PHILOSOPHER, 

B.  C.  350. 
From  marble  statue  in  Ppada  Palace.  Rome. 


CONSENT  OF  THEGOVERNED. 
RIGHT  vs.  MIGHT. 

"  Yet  to  a  reflecting  mind  it  imist  appear  very 
strange  that  the  statesman  should  be  always  consider 
ing  how  he  can  dominate  and  tyrannize  over  others, 
^tuhether  they  will  or  not.  How  can  that  which  is  not 
even  lawful  be  the  business  of  the  statesman  or  legis 
lator  f  Unlawful  it  certainly  is  to  rule  without  re 
gard  to  justice,  for  there  may  be  might  where  there  is 
no  right" 

"  Yet  many  appear  to  think  that  a  despotic  govern 
ment  is  a  trite  political  form,  and  what  men  affirm  to 
be  unjust  and  inexpedient  in  their  own  case  they  are 
not  ashamed  of  practicing  towards  others ;  they  de 
mand  justice  for  themselves,  but  where  other  men  are 
concerned  they  care  nothing  about  it.  Such  behavior 
is  irrational." 

' '  Neither  is  a  city  to  be  deemed  happy  or  a  legis 
lator  to  be  praised  because  he  trains  his  citizens  to 
conquer  and  obtain  domination  over  their  neighbors, 
for  there  is  great  evil  in  this.  No  such  principle  and 
no  law  having  this  object  is  'either  statesmanlike,  or 
useful,  or  right.  For  the  same  things  are  best  for  in 
dividuals  and  for  states  and  these  are  the  things  which 
the  legislator  should  implant  in  the  minds  of  his 
citizens." 

"  Neither  should  men  study  war  with  a  vieiv  to  the 
enslavement  of  those  who  do  not  deserve  to  be  enslaved, 
but  first  of  all  they  should  provide  against  their  en 
slavement  and  in  the  second  place  obtain  empire  for 
the  good  of  the  governed  and  not  for  the  sake  of  ex 
cising  a  general  despotism" 

Aristotle,  B.  C.  350. 


THE   DIVINE   MISSION   OF   SOCRATES. 

"  For  this  is  the  command  of  God,  as  I  would  have 
you  know ;  and  I  believe  that  to  this  day  no  greater 
good  has  ever  happened  in  the  state  than  my  service 
to  the  God.  For  I  do  nothing  but  go  about  persuading 
you  all,  old  and  young  alike,  not  to  take  thought  for 
your  persons  or  your  properties,  but  first  and  chiefly 
to  care  about  the  greatest  improvement  of  the  soul.  I 
tell  you  that  virtue  is  not  given  by  money,  but  that 
from  virtue  come  money  and  every  other  good  of  man, 
public  as  well  as  private  "  *  * 

"  I am  that  gadfly  which  God  has  given  the  state,  and 
all  day  long  and  in  all  places  am  always  fastening 
upon  you,  arousing  and  persuading  and  reproaching 
you.  *  *  *  And  that  I  am  given  to  you  by  God 
is  proved  by  this  :  that  if  I  had  been  like  other  men,  I 
should  not  have  neglected  all  my  own  concerns,  or 
patiently  seen  the  neglect  of  them  during  all  these 
years,  and  have  been  doing  yours,  coming  to  you  in 
dividually,  like  a  father  or  elder  brother,  exhorting 
you  to  regard  virtue ;  this,  I  say,  would  not  be  like 
human  nature.  And  had  I  gained  anything,  or  if 
my  exhortations  had  been  paid,  there  would  have  been 
some  sense  in  that ;  but  jiow,  as  you  will  perceive,  not 
even  the  impudence  of  my  accusers  dares  to  say  that  I 
have  ever  exacted  or  sought  pay  of  any  one  ;  they  have 
no  witness  of  that.  And  I  have  a  witness  of  the  truth 

of  what  I  say ;  my  poverty  is  a  sufficient  witness" 
*         *         *         * 

"For  if,  O  men  of  Athens,  by  force  of  persuasion 
and  entreaty,  I  could  overpower  your  oaths,  then  I 
should  be  teaching  you  to  believe  that  there  are  no 
Gods,  and  convict  myself,  in  my  own  defense,  of  not 
believing  in  them.  But  that  is  not  the  case ;  for  I 
do  believe  that  there  are  Gods,  and  in  a  far  higher 
sense  than  that  in  which  any  of  my  accusers  believe  in 
them"  From  the  Apology. 


Prof,  JAMES  H  HYSLOP, 


XXV 


PREFACE. 

The  lecture  which  is  here  published  in  book  form  was 
an  attempt  to  reduce  the  conceptions  of  Greek  ethics  to 
the  same  terms  as  those  in  which  modern  problems  in 
this  field  express  themselves.  Too  many  philosophers 
merely  transliterate  the  language  of  antiquity  instead  of 
translating  it.  The  consequence  is  that  we  as  often  fail 
to  discover  that  in  the  past  we  are  dealing  with  the  same 
intellectual  and  moral  problems  as  in  the  present.  I 
have  endeavored,  therefore,  to  see  the  Greek  thought  on 
ethics  with  the  eyes  of  a  modern  student.  How  far  I 
have  been  successful  must  be  left  to  others  to  decide. 
But  there  seems  to  me  a  perennial  lesson  for  serious 
men  and  women  in  the  efforts  of  Socrates,  Plato  and 
Aristotle  to  reanimate  while  they  modified  the  sturdy 
morality  which  they  thought  produced  the  civilization 
they  saw  on  the  decline.  The  Republic  and  the  Laws  of 
Plato,  and  the  Ethics  and  Politics  of  Aristotle  are  equally 
good  as  missionary  appeals  to  revivify  the  conscience  of 
the  race  as  they  are  scientific  treatises  to  enlighten  its 
intellect.  They  should  be  read  with  constant  reference 
to  the  problems  that  interest  in  social  and  political  mo 
rality.  The  selections  from  Plato  and  Aristotle  which 
have  been  made  by  the  Editor  and  myself  are  designed 
both  to  illustrate  the  conceptions  of  Greek  philosophy 
and  to  show  their  affinity  with  present  day  questions. 

JAMES  H.  HYSLOP. 
New  York,  March  26,  1903. 


XXVI 


PUBLISHERS  NOTE. 

The  series  of  lectures  on  The  Evolution  of  Ethics 
will  probably  be  issued  in  three  volumes  as  follows  : 

Vol.  i,  The  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

Vol.  2,  Origin  of  Ethical  Ideas,  Ethics  of  Evolution, 
and  Utilitarian  Ethics. 

Vol.  3  will  probably  contain  all  the  remaining  lectures 
of  the  course. 

We  now  ivSsue  the  volume  on  the  Greek  Philosophers 
as  the  first  of  the  series,  not  because  the  Greek  systems 
are  necessarily  first  in  order  of  importance  or  chronol 
ogy,  but  because  they  properly  deserve  first  place  in  our 
regards,  as  we  believe  it  cannot  be  denied  that  to  the 
Greek  and  Latin  thinkers  we  are  most  indebted  for  the 
greatest  and  most  direct  influence  on  our  own  political, 
moral,  religious  and  scientific  thought. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers, 


BY  PROF.  JAS.  H.  HYSLOP. 


The  interest  in  Greek  philosophy  is  perennial.  It 
resembles  the  immortality  of  Homer.  The  Iliad  and  the 
Odyssey  have  not  done  more  to  stimulate  and  nourish 
the  imagination  than  the  philosophers  have  done  for  the 
understanding  and  the  conscience.  Whenever  we  wish 
to  discuss  fundamental  principles  in  philosophy  and 
literature,  or  the  great  outlines  of  theory  in  both  depart 
ments  of  thought,  we  return  to  Greece,  and  there  we  find 
the  object  of  our  suit  in  all  its  simplicity  and  fascination. 
Homer,  like  his  own  Cimmerian  shades,  is  found  only  in 
the  twilight  of  fable,  and  philosophy,  like  epic  poetry  in 
its  antiquity,  traces  its  origin  to  the  confines  of  myth 
ology.  But  in  both  branches  of  its  intellectual  activity 
Greece  reflects  the  naivete  of  childhood,  until  its  problems 
become  well  defined  in  the  speculations  of  the  later 
schools.  It  is  this  very  simplicity,  however,  that  con 
stitutes  both  the  fascination  and  the  value  of  Greek  phil 
osophic  thought.  It  deals  with  first  principles  in  a 
way  that  seerns  always  and  everywhere  to  characterize 
the  rise  of  philosophic  reflection.  The  spontaneity  and 
naturalness  of  this  development  make  it  especia 


2  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

attractive  to  all  who  enjoy  an  emancipation  from  the 
artificial  methods  and  burdensome  shackles  of  scholastic 
dogmatism.  It  goes  direct  to  nature  and  fact  for  its  data, 
and  keeps  near  enough  to  common  experience  to  avoid 
mere  romancing,  while  it  remains  profound  enough  to 
originate  the  spirit  and  methods  of  science  and  philoso 
phy.  This  naturalness  of  Greek  reflection  was  and  is  the 
true  genius  of  speculative  inquiry,  and  naive  as  were 
many  of  its  thoughts,  they  exhibit  a  sagacity  and  pene 
tration  that  astonishes  us  when  we  consider  the  character 
of  the  period  as  compared  with  the  advantages  of  our 
own.  The  concrete  form  of  these  speculations  often 
seem  odd  and  childish  enough,  but  the  general  princi 
ples  at  their  basis  were  as  profound  and  far  reaching  as 
anything  that  can  to-day  boast  of  an  origin  in  riper 
reflection.  Hence  whenever  we  wish  to  divest  ourselves  of 
the  impediments  adhering  to  existing  formulas  and  illus 
trations  with  their  illusory  associations  we  have  only  to 
return  to  those  sources  of  philosophy  which,  though  they 
border  on  the  simplicity  of  childhood,  have  power  to 
stimulate  inquiry  in  a  way  that  is  not  rivaled  by  any 
other  race  of  thinkers.  This  is  the  one  reason  that  Greece 
is  the  great  academic  source  of  philosophic  education  and 
culture. 

The  chief  interest,  however,  with  which  we  are  here 
occupied  is  that  period  of  reflection  which  begins  with 
Socrates  and  ends  with  Aristotle.  Not  even  all  of  the 
aspects  of  this  period  will  require  our  attention,  but  only 
those  which  deal  with  its  ethics. 

It  was  an  age  of  unexampled  intellectual,  as  it  was  of 
political,  activity,  both  having  been  brought  about  by 
the  same  causes :  namely,  the  emancipation  of  the  Greek 
consciousness  from  the  thralls  of  tradition,  and  the  vic 
tory  over  Persia  at  Marathon  and  Salamis.  The  former 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  3 

secured  intellectual,  and  the  latter  political,  freedom,  and 
both  a  civilization  without  a  rival  at  that  time,  and  which 
remained  as  long  as  the  old  morality  retained  its  leaven 
ing  power.  Greece  became  conscious  of  herself  and  of 
her  power  in  this  emancipation  of  her  people,  and  so 
secured  that  spontaneity  of  action,  intellectual  and  politi 
cal,  which  is  the  only  guarantee  and  protector  of  a  great 
civilization.  Her  strength  against  outside  enemies  gave 
her  self-reliance,  and  the  taste  of  freedom  fortified  her 
against  hostile  forces  within.  Besides  all  these  there 
was,  of  course,  a  variety  of  influences,  social,  literary, 
and  philosophical,  which  stimulated  intellectual  activity 
of  all  kinds,  and  so  supplemented  the  purely  political 
agencies  in  awakening  Greek  life  to  a  consciousness 
of  its  powers  and  vocation.  There  was  a  large  class  of  .-fa- 
people,  aristocratic  in  possessions,  tastes,  and  habits,  and 
with  leisure,  or  free  from  toil  and  pain  as  the  Greeks 
expressed  it,  to  lead  a  contemplative  or  reflective  life. 
This  class  set  to  thinking  about  things  cosmic,  personal, 
and  social,  and  the  very  first  impulse  opened  up  a  fairy 
land  of  wonders  in  nature  that  fascinated  the  imagination 
like  the  discoveries  of  Columbus  and  the  theories  of 
Darwin  in  later  times.  In  thus  opening  up  the  secrets  of 
nature,  the  Greeks  were  stimulated  in  an  inquiry  as  intoxi 
cating  as  the  gold  fever  of  Peru  and  California.  Trees, 
plants,  ocean,  seasons,  stars,  numbers,  elements,  and  all 
animate  or  inanimate  things  were  objects  of  mingled  wor 
ship  and  curiosity.  A  discovery  in  any  of  these  fields  was 
the  signal  for  the  most  impetuous  and  childish  theories. 
It  was  only  natural,  and  though  their  systems  were  very 
naive  at  first,  they  soon  gave  rise  to  problems  which 
have  a  perennial  interest  and  an  importance  for  every 
individual  who  seeks  a  knowledge  of  nature  as  well  as 
culture.  "Consider,"  says  Mr.  Alfred  Benn,  "the  lively 


4  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

emotions  excited  among  an  intelligent  people  at  a  time 
when  multiplication  and  division,  squaring  and  cubing, 
the  rule  of  three,  the  construction  and  equivalence  of 
figures,  with  all  their  manifold  applications  to  indus 
try,  commerce,  fine  art,  and  (military)  tactics,  were  just 
as  strange  and  wonderful  as  electrical  phenomena  to 
us;  consider  also  the  magical  influence  still  commonly 
attributed  to  particular  numbers,  and  the  intense  eager 
ness  to  obtain  exact  numerical  statements,  even  when 
they  are  of  no  practical  value,  exhibited  by  all  who 
are  thrown  back  upon  primitive  ways  of  living,  as,  for 
example,  in  Alpine  traveling,  or  on  board  an  Atlantic 
steamer,  and  we  shall  cease  to  wonder  that  a  mere  form 
of  thought,  a  lifeless  abstraction,  should  once  have  been 
regarded  as  the  solution  of  every  problem,  the  cause  of 
all  existence."  What  is  said  in  this  passage  referring  to 
Pythagoras  can  also  be  said  of  Thales,  Anaximander, 
Parmenides,  Heraclitus,  and  Anaxagoras.  The  physical 
speculations  of  the  Ionian  school,  the  pantheistic  con 
ceptions  of  Anaximander  and  the  two  Eleatics,  Xeno- 
phanes  and  Parmenides,  the  dialectic  of  Zeno,  the  per 
petual  flux  or  evolution  of  Heraclitus,  the  naive  atomic 
theories  of  Empedocles  and  Democritus,  and  the  theolog 
ical  system  of  Anaxagoras — all  of  these  indicated  an 
intellectual  fermentation  of  vast  significance  both  in 
their  destructive  influence  upon  traditional  ideas  and  in 
their  constructive  power  for  molding  a  new  civilization. 
But  upon  these  influences  I  cannot  dwell  further,  and 
allude  to  them  at  all  only  to  remark  their  importance  in 
a  complete  estimate  of  the  period  which  I  am  to  discuss 
more  carefully.  I  can  only  examine  in  the  briefest  com 
pass  possible  the  most  general  philosophic  and  moral 
attitude  of  mind  characterizing  the  whole  period  preced 
ing  Socrates. 


PYTHAGORAS. 

(569-471 .     B.  C  ) 
From  an  ancient  Cameo. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  5 

Preceding  the  Socratic  period,  which  I  am  to  consider, 
there  were  two  phases  of  intellectual  development  whose 
characteristics  require  to  be  noticed  in  order  to  compre 
hend  rightly  the  new  tendencies  inaugurated  by  Socrates. 
They  may  be  called  the  philosophic  and  religious  move 
ments.  Both  of  them  terminate  with  the  skepticism  of 
the  sophists,  who  will  come  in  for  some  consideration. 
But  the  philosophic  attitude  of  mind  was  characterized 
by  cosmic  speculation.  They  were  first  attempts  to 
explain  the  universe  and  afterward  endeavors  to  formu 
late  maxims  for  the  regulation  of  conduct.  The  phe 
nomena  of  nature  were  reduced  to  some  kind  of  unity, 
wnether  of  being  or  of  motion,  elements  or  substance, 
and  their  action  according  to  some  definite  law.  When 
ethical  maxims  were  reached  they  took  the  form  of  in 
junctions  to  conform  conduct  to  this  unity,  to  the  law  of 
nature,  to  the  harmony  of  the  universe.  It  is  important 
to  remark  the  conception  of  morality  involved  in  such  a 
view  of  things.  It  is  identical  in  general  conception  and 
terms  with  that  of  Mr.  Spencer  and  evolutionists  usually, 
in  that  it  represents  morality  to  be  an  adjustment  to  the 
laws  of  nature,  or  in  evolutionistic  parlance,  environ 
ment.  This  conception  and  point  of  view  make  morality 
external.  It  represents  morality  merely  as  action  ad 
justed  to  external  forces  and  requires  nothing  but  the 
intelligence  and  prudence  instigated  by  fear  to  achieve 
it  Such  a  thing  as  the  Kantian  good-will  is  either 
unnecessary  or  unintelligible  in  this  condition  of  mind. 
Obedience  to  the  fixed  laws  of  the  cosmos  is  the  one 
course  that  leads  to  the  highest  good,  which  to  the  Greek 
was  always  pleasure,  unless  we  except  Plato  and  the 
Stoics.  It  is  hardly  proper  to  say  that  this  obedience 
was  a  duty,  or  felt  as  a  duty,  because  the  very  con 
ception  of  moral  obligation,  born  from  the  sense  of  a 


6  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

conflict  between  one's  own  inclinations  and  the  constraint 
of  conscience,  which  looked  at  an  ideal  above  nature  and 
more  especially  characterized  Christianity,  was  unknown 
to  the  period  of  which  I  am  treating.  The  sense  of  con 
flict  was  often  enough  felt,  but  it  was  the  sense  of  a  con 
flict  between  a  weaker  and  a  stronger  power,  and  not 
between  human  desires  and  a  divine  will  preconceived 
as  just  and  benevolent  The  Greek  consciousness  or 
belief  was  that  man  was  a  part  of  nature,  not  dualisti- 
cally  opposed  to  it,  as  either  equal  or  inferior  to  it,  and 
this  conception  held  the  mind  to  the  assumption  of  a 
complete  harmony  between  the  ultimate  order  of  the 
iworld  and  man's  interest.  yThe  highest  good,  therefore, 
kvas  conceived  as  man's  interest  in  obedience  to  superior 
•power,  and  not  respect  for  its  laws  as  the  expression  of  a 
personal  will.  Consequently,  prudence  became  the 
highest  virtue,  which  was  wise  obedience  to  power,  not 
respect  for  moral  personality.  This  prudence,  therefore, 
did  not  involve  merit  for  good-will  as  distinct  from 
knowledge  or  intelligence,  but  threw  the  whole  responsi 
bility  for  virtue  or  excellence  upon  wisdom  or  knowl- 
edge  of  the  laws  of  nature.  The  good  man  was  the  wise 
man;  the  man  who  knew  the  laws  oFthe  cosmos"  and 
obeyed  them  whether  he  had  any  respect  for  them  or 
not.  The  prudent  (vorsichtiger)  man  was  as  good  as  the 
religious  saint,  or  even  better,  and  had  his  rewards  for 
mere  prudent  self-interest  quite  equal  those  of  the  seekar 
after  eternal  life.  It  was  assumed  that  his  will  inevita 
bly  lay  in  the  direction  of  the  good,  which  was  con 
ceived  as  personal  interest  and  pleasure,  and  all  that  any 
one  could  be  said  to  lack  when  he  failed  to  achieve  it,  or 
"  virtue,"  was  wisdom  or  rational  knowledge  of  the  uni 
verse.  Man's  whole  duty  was  to  get  a  knowledge  of 
nature  and  to  prudently  adjust  his  conduct  to  its  laws, 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosopher*.  7 

not  to  seek  an  ideal  above  nature  in  some  transcendental 
state  of  existence.  The  ignorant  man,  if  he  ever  attained 
the  good  at  all,  merely  stumbled  upon  it,  but  the  rational 
man  who  was  conscious  of  what  he  aimed  at  was 
"virtuous"  for  that  reason.  Consciousness  or  self-con 
sciousness  was  the  Greek's  conception  of  virtue.  Con 
scientiousness  is  the  increment  which  later  thought  adds 
to  that  as  the  conception  of  morality,  and  so  supple 
ments  knowledge  by  good-will  as  a  condition  of  virtue. 

In  order  to  see  the  close  relation  between  early  phil 
osophy  and  ethics  we  must  keep  in  mind  that  both  in 
his  speculative  and  practical  reflections  the  pre-Socratic 
thinker  directed  his  attention  to  the  external  world. 
Both  his  philosophy  and  his  ethics  were  cosmic.  To 
state  it  more  technically  his  point  of  view  was  cosmolog- 
ical,  that  is,  cosmocentric,  as  distinct  from  anthropologi 
cal,  that  is,  anthropocentric.  This  position  favored 
humility  and  obedience,  as  the  anthropocentric  view, 
whatever  its  merits  in  other  respects,  often  tends  to  an 
exaggerated  self-estimation.  Nevertheless  the  Greek  had 
no  humility  and  the  later  Christian  had  less  pride.  There 
were  other  reasons  for  this  fact.  But  the  reference  to 
cosmic  and  external  conditions,  under  the  philosophic 
impulse,  was  not  accompanied  or  inspired  by  any  sense  of 
fear,  at  least  among  the  philosophers.  The  common  mind 
may  have  lived  in  terror  of  the  forces  of  nature,  because 
it  thought  them  the  manifestation  of  lawless  gods  and 
demons.  But  in  the  reflective  stage  of  development  this 
fear  was  banished.  This  was  probably  because  the 
movement  was  controlled  by  the  more  philosophic  minds 
of  Greece,  who  were  in  their  times  the  ideals  of  calm  and 
dispassionate  temperament,  and  hence  the  ethical  con 
sciousness  represented  by  them  was  of  the  rational  type, 
duly  exempt  from  fear  and  superstition  on  the  one  hand, 


8  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

and  from  an  exalted  and  exaggerated  estimate  of  human 
life  on  the  other.  Not  being  able  to  awaken  the  in 
fluence  of  love  for  an  impersonal  law,  as  Christianity 
awakened  it  for  the  law  of  an  idealized  personal  Grod,  the 
ethics  of  the  period  under  notice  could  have  no  other 
motive  than  a  calculating  prudence,  exempt  from  the 
disturbing  influence  of  fear,  hope,  and  love.  Its  whole 
principle  was  adjustment  to  an  external  order,  and 
morality  was  rational  submission  to  it.  There  was  no 
high  estimation  placed  upon  man  in  any  sense  that  his 
good  lay  in  conquering  the  world,  but  only  in  conform 
ing  to  it.  The  point  of  view,  as  I  have  said,  was  cosmo- 
centric,  not  anthropocentric,  and  this  meant  that  man 
must  subordinate  his  life  to  the  cosmos  instead  of  sub 
ordinating  nature  to  himself.  This  same  conception  was 
reflected  in  politics,  in  which  the  ethical  norm  was  "pas 
sive  obedience  "  to  authority  minus  the  "  divine  right  of 
kings,"  though  there  are  traces  of  even  this  idea,  with 
none  of  its  idealization,  however,  as  later  civilization 
tried  to  construe  it.  Bat  morality  in  this  conception 
expressed  a  sense  of  limitation,  and  though  the  whole 
movement  was  characterized  by  a  calm  and  rational 
view  of  this  limitation,  its  tendency  was  to  make  the 
Greek  conscious  of  thwarted  effort  and  restricted  liberty 
in  the  satisfaction  of  desire,  and  this  he  resented  with  all 
the  bitterness  characteristic  of  a  liberty-loving  race. 
Hence  the  universal  lamentation  at  the  hardness  of  fate, 
though  this  weakness  generally  escaped  the  philosophers 
whose  habits  of  thought  and  action  insured  a  mental 
equilibrium  that  has  fixed  the  popular  conception  of 
their  character  for  all  time.  They  taught  and  practised 
that  balance  of  feeling  and  will  which  enables  men  to 
battle  with  the  storms  of  nature  and  destiny,  and  to  seek 
their  highest  good  rather  in  obedience  to  cosmic  laws 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  9 

than  in  rebellion  against  them.  The  average  Greek  was 
a  born  rebel,  because  he  could  respect  neither  nature  nor 
the  gods,  and  it  was  a  hard  lesson  to  learn  that  the 
cosmos  had  the  first  claim  upon  his  allegiance.  But  this 
necessity — for  it  was  a  necessity  rather  than  a  duty  to 
the  Greek,  because,  on  the  one  hand,  he  found  neither  per 
sonality  in  nature  nor  morality  in  the  gods,  and  on  the 
other,  his  own  conception  of  the  good  did  not  transcend 
personal  interest — this  necessity  of  submission  to  nature 
was  the  whole  ethical  teaching  of  the  philosophic  move 
ment  previous  to  Socrates,  and  it  was  identical  with  the 
religious  attitude  of  mind  in  the  same  period,  except 
that  the  forces  that  exacted  obedience  were  impersonal 
and  could  not  utilize  all  those  associations  which  are 
connected  with  the  idea  of  personality.  Though  they 
could  not  evoke  love,  as  the  human  attitude  of  mind 
toward  them,  they  did  not  awaken  in  the  philosophers 
the  sentiment  of  fear.  The  age  and  its  necessities 
taught  the  fatuity  of  cowardice  and  the  benefits  of 
rational  adjustment  to  nature. 

The  second  intellectual  movement  which  both  pre 
ceded  and  accompanied  the  philosophical  was  the  relig 
ious  system  of  ideas.  This  founded  all  morality  upon 
the  will  of  the  gods.  It  was  not  reflective  in  its  type, 
but  manifested  those  naive  ideas  regarding  the  basis  of 
morals  which  characterize  all  religious  beliefs.  It  fos 
tered  the  morality  of  fear.  It  was  like  the  philosophical 
movement  in  producing  the  sense  of  subjection  to  an 
external  law,  or  authority,  but  it  was  unlike  that  move 
ment  in  its  conception  of  the  law  to  be  obeyed.  The 
religious  consciousness  of  that  time  obeyed  divinities 
that  were  the  embodied  genii  of  caprice  and  libertinism, 
and  hence  it  could  live  only  under  the  domination  of  fear, 
which  such  beings  would  inspire,  especially  that  they 


10  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Pldlosophers. 

held  men's  life  and  fortune,  in  their  hands.  At  first  men 
animated  even  nature  with  capricious  laws  and  lived  in 
terror  under  it.  Long  after  they  had  found  the  cosmos 
a  seat  of  fixed  laws  they  still  attributed  to  the  gods  the 
caprice  and  wontonness  that  nature  had  shared  at  an 
earlier  time.  No  genuine  morality  is  possible  under 
such  a  system.  The  calculations  of  prudence  and  virtue 
are  not  possible  where  nature  and  the  gods  are  not 
regular,  and  to  caprice  the  gods  added  personality  with 
out  morality.  Hence  they  could  inspire  nothing  but 
fear.  On  the  other  hand,  the  philosopher's  cosmos  was 
the  seat  of  irrevocable  order,  and  he  could  learn  to  cal 
culate  its  action,  to  sacrifice  his  desires  to  it  for  remoter 
rewards,  and  to  contemplate  its  course  with  equanimity, 
while  the  religious  mind  had  to  quake  and  tremble  before 
the  prospect  of  an  arbitrary  and  unjust  interference  with 
its  plans,  hopes,  and  aspirations.  Nothing  but  super 
stitious  fear  could  exist  under  such  a  system  of  concep 
tions,  and  man  still  remained  the  servant  of  external 
agents,  and  his  morality  or  conduct  nothing  more 
than  prudential  obedience  under  restraint.  The  philo 
sophic  mind  could  cultivate  an  intellectual  calm,  the 
calm  of  Fate,  or  the  consciousness  that  the  course  of 
things  was  inexorable,  and  that  it  could  be  propitiated 
by  neither  fear,  nor  hope,  nor  love,  but  the  religious 
mind,  having  no  fixed  order  with  which  to  reckon,  but 
only  a  lot  of  capricious  personal  beings  to  propitiate, 
could  only  lead  a  life  of  fear  and  terror.  In  the  absence, 
therefore,  of  the  philosopher's  calm  and  insight,  the  two 
alternatives  for  man's  regeneration  were  either  to  deny 
the  existence  of  the  gods,  or  to  moralize  them.  Skepti 
cism  did  the  former  ;  Christianity  did  the  latter. 

This    skeptical     tendency   was    represented    by    the 
sophistic  movement  in  which  there  were  three   factors 


L 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  11 

having  much  interest  in  the  development  of  philosophy. 
They  were :     (1}  Itsdoctrine  of  the  so-called  relativity 
of    knowledge,  ^offTntellectual    and    moral.      (2)  Its 
agnosti cism,  or   even  denial,  regarding  the  existence_of_ 
TEe  godsT      (3)  Its  theory 


the  origin  of~morafity! There  was  also  in  the  school  an 
incipient  recognition  of  the  place  occupied  by  pleasure 
in  the  determination  of  conduct  in  so  far  as  the  indi 
vidual  is  concerned.  This  might  very  well  be  called 
the  fourth  factor  in  sophistic  thought.  All  of  them 
exercised  a  profound  influence  upon  current  conceptions 
of  morality.  The  first  led  to  a  change  from  the  cosmo- 
logical  to  the  anthropological  point  of  view.  The  second 
led  to  a  denial  of  the  religious  consciousness  and  the 
authority  of  the  gods.  The  third  and  fourth  in  connection 
with  religious  skepticism  created  a  tendency  toward 
libertinism. 

The  meaning  of  the  sophistic  theory  of  the  relativity 
of  knowledge  was  that  all  ideas  and  truths  were  relative 
to  the  individual  who  perceived  them.     At  this  period 
of  reflection  many  of  the  Greeks,  and  more   particularly 
the   sophists,    became   conscious   of    the    contradictions 
in   human  experience  and  beliefs.     For  instance,  what 
appeared  hot  to  one  man  was  cold  to  another  ;  what  one 
called  large  another  called  small  ;  what  one  called  rigl 
another  called   wrong.     Differences   of   opinion  seernec 
irreconcilable.     Every   man  appeared_tg_jmye   nothing 
but  his  own   sensation. -3  tn  ponsir]pr  in    his  reflections  anc 
was  without  assurance  that  they    were    in    any   respec 
like  those  of  his  neighbor.     All  this  was  expressed  by*" 
saying  that   all  knowledge   and  ideas  were   relative  and 
none  of  them  absolute,   which  was  only  to   maintain  that 
there  was  no  common  measure  of  experience  and  truth, 
that  every  idea  was  true,  every  act  right  for  the  man  who 


12  Ethics  of  t/te  G reek  Philosophers. 

thought  so.  I  cannot  go  fully  into  this  doctrine  at  present, 
but  I  hope  I  have  made  it  clear  that  it  was  a  most 
radical  skepticism  in  regard  to  all  the  beliefs  of  common 
sense.  The  consequences  of  it  are,  or  ought  to  be, 
apparent  to  every  one.  It  leaves  every  one  free  to  follow 
his  own  convictions  and  impulses  without  hindrance 
except  from  superior  power.  There  can  be  no  appeal  to 
common  ideas  and  principles,  and  reason  can  only  mean 
what  each  man  thinks  and  believes  for  himself  and  with 
out  regard  to  others.  The  doctrine  of  conventionalism 
carried  the  principles  of  skepticism  still  farther.  After 
denying  the  existence  of  the  gods  and  their  relation  to 
morality,  and  the  existence  of  absolute  truth,  this  doc 
trine  of  conventionalism  was  an  attempt  to  explain  how 
the  actual  code  of  moral  practice  came  to  be  accepted 
and  to  be  a  common  one.  There  was  no  doubt  about  the 
fact  that  a  common  code  existed,  but  so  far  from  being 
the  spontaneous  adoption  of  the  individuals  in  society 
the  sophists^  held  that  it  was  due  to  the  passive  conven 
tion  of  citizens  in  obedience  to  the  superior  power  of  the 
state,  which  in  most  cases  was  an  arbitrary  prince.  With 
the  growing  demand  for  individual  and  political  liberty, 
and  the  hatred  against  tyrannical  rulers,  this  idea  only 
reinforced  the  individualism  of  sophistic  psychology,  and 
tended  to  destroy  the  authority  of  the  state  in  the  esti 
mation  of  the  citizen  who  could  claim  upon  the  basis  of 
this  philosophy  the  sole  right  to  determine  his  own  con 
duct.  When  pleasure  was  set  up  as  the  positive  motive 
for  every  man's  action,  and  each  individual  was  regarded 
as  his  own  rightful  judge  of  what  was  right  or  wrong,  or 
what  pleasure  he  could  pursue  without  the  legitimacy  of 
hindrance  or  interference  on  the  part  of  others,  we  can 
well  imagine  what  moral  chaos  must  follow  upon  the 
application  of  such  a  theory  to  social  and  political  action. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  13 

Now  Socrates  originates  the  reaction  against  sophistic 
doctrine  in  philosophy,  ethics,  and  politics.  In  order  to 
understand  what  he  accomplished  and  what  he  represents 
in  the  history  of  thought,  at  least  by  way  of  suggestion, 
we  must  examine  three  characteristics  of  the  man  : 
(1)  His  method.  (2)  His  doctrine.  (3)  His  personality. 

The  method  of  Socrates  begins  with  his  attack  upon 
thesophists,  which  covered  his  ownjjretense  of  ignorance  — 
behind  the  keenest-.  ofLinnii  e  n  d  o  an  d  _  sati  re  against  the 
sophisms  'of  these  skeptical  wiseacres.  He  did  not  queg^__ 
tion  their  theology,  or  rather  anti-theological  beliefs,  as 
the  mam  point  of  attack.  He  might  have  defended  the 
existence  of  the  gods  as  the  first  position  to  be  sustained 
in  the  reconstruction  of  ethics.  But  he  did  not  choose 
this  resource.  Whatever  belief  in  the  gods  he  main 
tained  he  held  either  as  a  pious  opinion  of  his  own  or  as 
the  terminus  ad  quern  of  his  philosophical  theories.  But 
avoiding  the  prior  reconstruction  of  theology,  he  pushed 
sophistic  skepticism  to  its  logical  consequences  and 
directed  his  attack  upon  the  sophists'  boastful  claim  to 
acknowledge  of  virtue  and  of  the  best  means  to  attain  it 
He  ridiculed  their  personal  arrogance  and  resented  their 
conceited  and  ignorant  claims  to  superior  knowledge  in 
all  matters  of  virtue.  But  in  his  argument  with  them 
he  showed  great  shrewdness  and  sagacity.  He  made  no 
pretensions  to  knowledge  himself.  He  confessed  that  he 
wjis_on]y_ajie£ke^  instead  of  asserting 

anything  that  would  require  proof  on  his  part,  he  carried  1 
on  his  discussion?  with  the  sophists  bj  a  series  of  ques-  u 
tlona  which  shitted  the  obligation  of  assertion  upon  them   v 
and  which  were  couched  in  a  way  to  expose  their  igno 
rance  by  exhibiting  their  contradictions  while  pretending 
to  be  instructors  of  youth  in  matters  of  knowledge  and 
virtue.     He  asked  for  definition  and  meaning  where  the 


j 


14  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

ordinary  man  wanted  facts.  Consequently  he  had  to  deal 
with  conceptions,  ideas,  rather  than  with  objects,  external 
things  and  laws.  His  process  of  induction,  definition, 
and  dialectic  argument  turned  on  the  clarification  of 
one's  ideas,  and  the  establishment  of  a  real  or  certain,  as 
distinct  from  an  illusory  or  uncertain,  knowledge.  His 
object  in  this  was,  of  course,  to  show  the  sophist  that  he 
had  not  thought  out  his  ideas  to  their  consequences,  and 
that  his  contradictory  conceptions,  with  his  psychological 
individualism,  unfitted  him  to  be  the  intellectual  and 
moral  guide  to  the  Athenian  youth.  But  in  the  process 
Socrates  assumed  and  used  a  point  of  view  of  whose 
significance  he  was  not  himself  conscious.  He  began  his 
inquiries  with  ideas  and  not  with  things,  and  the  conse 
quence  was  that  he  completely  reversed  the  point  of  view 
from  which  the  study  of  philosophy  began.  Instead  of 
looking  primarily  at  the  external  world,  or  the  objective 
facts  which  skepticism  denied  or  questioned,  he  forced 
the  sophist  to  discover  in  his  individual  ideas  the 
contradictions  which  this  class  hud  found  in  general 
knowledge,  and  consequently  he  compelled  his  opponent 
either  to  admit  his  own  confusion  or  to  reconstruct  his 
view  of  knowledge.  But  in  the  intensity  of  his  occupa 
tion  with  mere  ideas  Socrates  ceased  to  take  an  interest 
in  speculations  about  the  cosmos.  The  sophists,  of 
course,  prepared  the  way  for  this  by  their  skepticism 
in  regard  to  the  validity  of  sensory  knowledge.  But 
they  did  not  openly  avow  any  contempt  for  physical 
speculation.  Socrates,  however,  ridiculed  all  attempts  at 
determining  the  nature  of  the  stars,  for  instance,  or 
explaining  the  physical  universe.  He  said  he  could  learn 
nothing  from  the  study  of  nature.  He  did  not  care  for 
a  walk  along  the  river  bank  for  the  contemplation  of  the 
trees,  or  for  any  study  of  physical  phenomena.  He  was, 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  15 

on  the  contrary,  a  complete  agnostic  in  regard  to  the 
possibility  of  physical  science,  as  it  was  then  called.  Man 
and  his  conceptions  were  his  supreme  interest,  while  a 
knowledge  of  the  physical  world  was  ridiculed  either  as 
impossible  or  as  a  hot-bed  of  fancies  and  illusions. 
This  position,  of  course,  was  only  the  logical  conse 
quence  of  sophistic  psychology,  though  with  Socrates 
this  attitude  of  mind  was  rather  a  matter  of  moral  tem 
perament  than  of  logical  reflection  upon  the  philosophical 
problems  of  the  time.  It  was  due  to  the  intensity  of  his 
interest  in  ideas  which  monopolized  attention  and  tended 
to  turn  men  from  the  contemplation  of  the  external 
universe  to  reflection  upon  themselves.  It  was  a  quiet 
substitution  of  the  anthropocentric  for  the  cosmocentric 
point  of  view  in  the  consideration  of  truth. 

But  this  agnosticism  in  physical  science  requires  some 
attention  in  the  light  of  the  criticism  which  is  sometimes 
directed  against  it.  The  contempt  for  physical  science 
which  Socrates  expressed  sounds  very  strange  in  our 
ears,  especially  after  all  the  triumphs  of  modern  inquiry 
under  that  name.  Had  it  been  called  metaphysics, 
which  it  really  was,  there  would  be  no  protest  against 
his  judgment  by  those  who  are  inclined  to  ridicule  him 
for  his  opinion.  But,  as  it  is,  Socrates'  impeachment  of 
physical  science  is  taken  as  a  defense  of  the  process  of 
burrowing  in  one's  own  reflections  for  a  solution  of  the 
world's  mystery,  like  the  Hindu  sage  who  is  said  to  solve 
the  riddle  of  the  sphinx  by  sitting  under  his  palm  tree 
and  looking  into  his  navel.  Socrates  here  seems  to 
favor  the  scholastic  method  which  science  so  vehemently 
despises  in  philosophy,  and  which  it  illustrates  so  vigor 
ously  in  the  weaknesses  of  Hegelian  language,  namely, 
the  attempt  to  construe  the  whole  universe  from  the 
standpoint  of  self-consciousness. 


J6  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

But  accusations  of  this  kind  betray  complete  igno 
rance  of  both  the  acuteness  of  Socrates  and  of  the  actual 
conception  of  physical  science  which,  he  attacked.  Mere 
propositions  are  not  safe  guides  in  regard  to  the  mean 
ing  of  past  ideas.  'The  form  of  expression  which  literally 
translates  the  past  may  conceal  its  real  content.  The 
physical  science  of  Socrates'  time,  as  denominated  in  the 
doctrines  of  Thales,  Parmenides,  Heraclitus,  Democritus, 
and  Anaxagoras,  along  with  others,  was  nothing  but 
a  priori  metaphysical  speculation  about  the  physical 
universe,  and  deludes  the  average  scientist  of  the 
present  day  because  he  allows  himself  to  be  deceived 
by  the  name  and  contents  of  ancient  inquiry  without 
regarding  the  viciousness  of  ancient  method.  Moreover 
the  admirer  of  Mr.  Spencer  should  not  be  counted  among 
the  critics  of  Socrates.  But  physical  science  in  Greece 
was  not  an  attempt  to  catalogue  the  facts  of  nature  after 
the  method  of  modern  scientific  and  inductive  procedure, 
and  to  suspend  explanation  until  the  laws  and  uniformi 
ties  of  nature  were  adequately  known,  but  it  was  a 
resort  to  the  widest  and  wildest  speculation  upon  the 
most  meager  data  conceivable,  and  under  conditions  that 
made  it  impossible  to  penetrate  the  mysteries  of  the 
cosmos.  The  limitations  of  such  knowledge,  as  suspected 
by  Socrates,  were  entirely  justifiable  suppositions,  and 
nothing  would  meet  the  modern  condemnation  of  science 
more  readily  than  this  a  priori  speculation  about  the  uni 
verse  which  Socrates  eschewed,  though  with  even  better 
reasons  than  he  knew.  It_  was  rather  a  spontaneous 
mterest  in  man  and  his  conduct  that  animated  Socrates 


diy^rteH^hTrn  from  walching  ^fliestare^tliari  any 
philosophic  conception  of  the  limitations  of  human 
knowledge.  His  agnosticism  was  thus  not  against 
physical  science  as  we  understand  the  term,  namely,  as 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  17 

a  process  for  empirically  determining  the  laws  of  nature, 
but  against  metaphysical  efforts  to  construe  the  origin  of 
phenomena  and  of  organic  existence  in  terms  of  some 
simple  substance  and  by  a  purely  speculative  method. 
This  is  precisely  the  contention  of  modern  science, 
which  ought  to  claim  Socrates  as  the  father  of  empirical 
inquiry  in  the  field  of  physical  phenomena,  or  at  least  as 
no  opponent  of  it,  though  he  formulated  no  principles 
by  which  the  limitations  of  knowledge  to  phenomena 
could  be  determined,  instead  of  reproaching  \\m  with 
the  introspective  method  of  studying  nature.  What 
Socrates  actually  aimed  at  was  identical  with  the  prac 
tical  interests  of  present  science,  except  that  it  was  moral, 
not  physical.  His  object  was  to  turn  men  to  attainable 
results,  even  if  they  were  only  the  clarification  of  ideas 
and  the  moralization  of  the  will. 

But  the  mere  fact  that  he  turned  away  from  current 
physical  speculations  and  demanded  an  examination  of 
our  logical  conceptions,  while  he  applied  a  dialectic  use 
of  them  against  the  sophistries  of  Protagoras,  Prodicus, 
Oorgias,  and  their  class  generally,  created  a  new  tend 
ency,  and  a  new  point  of  view,  the  anthropocentric  as 
opposed  to  the  cosmocentric,  as  they  have  already  been 
denominated.  Besides  its  influence  upon  philosophic 
method,  which  was  to  make  it  psychological  and  idealistic, 
as  distinct  from  the  physical  and  realistic  type  of 
thought,  it  established  an  entirely  new  direction  for  ethical 
reflection.  This  too  became  subjective  as  against  the 
objective  point  of  view  in  the  older  philosophy.  Man 
was  turned  in  upon  himself  for  a  knowledge  of  the  moral 
law.  Reflection  upon  himself  and  not  upon  external 

'^-    '  ^ m •••••—••« — »—• ^ • 

nature  became  the  method  of  determining  one's  duties. 
The  habit  of  self-analysis  thus  initiated  and  involved  in 
the  criticism  of  one's  conceptions  transmitted  its  influence 


18  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

to  the  desires,  and  they  became  objects  of  introspective 
examination  and  regulation.  The  ethical  conscious 
ness  thus  turned  away  from  the  cosmological  order  of 
nature  to  find  the  law  of  action  and  its  promised  reward 
in  the  subject  itself.  The  effect  of  this  with  its  emphasis 
upon  the  virtue  of  self-control,  which  is  the  index  of 
man's  own  responsibility  for  the  good  and  not  nature, 
was  to  create  in  man  a  wholly  new  idea  of  himself, 
namely,  that  sense  of  his  dignity  and  worth  which  was 
wholly  impossible  under  the  idea  that  he  was  merely  an 
instrument  in  the  hands  of  Fate,  of  nature,  or  of  the 
ruler  to  accomplish  some  other  end  than  his  own.  The 
old  cosmological  ethics  had  taught  submission,  if  not 
humility,  though  it  could  not  wholly  prevent  fear  and 
slavish  obedience.  The  new  psychological  and  anthropo 
logical  point  of  view  awakened  courage  and  self-confidence, 
and  with  them  reinforced  the  pride  which  an  aristocratic 
society  had  fostered,  even  when  the  order  of  nature 
elicited  no  respect  for  itself.  This  pride  could  take 
the  direction  of  vanity,  or  of  man's  dignity,  importance, 
and  moral  mission  in  the  universe,  according  to-  the 
character  of  the  individual  who  maintained  it.  The  last 
was  its  form  in  Socrates  and  Plato,  and  it  marked  the 
rise  of  that  conception  of  man  which  no  subsequent 
morality  has  forgotten,  and  which  no  future  ethics  can 
ignore,  even  when  it  is  necessary  to  correct  its  aberra 
tions,  and  though  it  is  incumbent  upon  it  not  to  ignore 
the  limitations  which  an  eternal  order  places  upon  self- 
estimation.  "Know  thyself,"  PvodQi  Geavrov,  is 
an  important  maxim  for  a  man  who  wishes  to  secure 
self-control  and  for  one  who  would  possess  the  psycho 
logical  equipment  for  instructing  and  leading  his  fellows 
in  the  path  of  truth  and  virtue  ;  but  if  it  conduces  only 
to  pride  and  vanity,  an  exaggerated  sense  of  human 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  19 

importance  in  the  economy  of  nature,  or  to  a  demand  for 
liberty  and  impunity  in  conduct,  it  requires  to  be  cor 
rected  by  emphasizing  that  subordination  to  external 
nature,  or  adjustment  to  the  laws  of  the  universe,  which 
the  old  cosmological  point  of  view  so  effectively  instilled, 
and  which  checks  transcendental  aspirations,  based  upon 
wishes  instead  of  facts,  by  substituting  obedience  for 
libertinism  on  the  one  hand,  and  impracticable  idealism 
with  other-worldliness  on  the  other.  But  self-examina 
tion  is  necessary  to  avoid  both  extremes,  and  the  method 
of  reflection  which  Socrates  initiated  supplied  this  want. 
Somuch  for  the  method  of  Socrates.  But  the  most 
interesting  feature  about  his  position  is  the  con  tent  of  his 
doctrine.  In  spite  of  his  departure  from  the  cosmologi 
cal  method  he  adopted  one  of  the  fundamental  ideasofthe 
cosmological  school.  We  have  seen  that  the  cosmocentric 
point  of  view  emphasizes  the  necessity  of  knowledge  as  a 
condition  of  securing  the  fruits  of  prudence  and  of  success 
ful  adjustment  to  nature.  Obedience  to  the  laws  of 
nature  was  the  form  of  expression  that  this  pre-Socratic 
ethics  assumed,  but  it  demanded  for  its  realization 
rational  knowledge.  Socrates,  presupposing  the  natural 
prudence  of  men,  took  up  this  assumption  of  the  cosmo 
logical  school  and  advanced  it  to  the  position  of  the 
highest  good.  This  was  that  knowledge  is  the  one  great 
"virtue"  (in  Greek  parlance,  excellence)  or  condition  of 
moral  life.  The  idea  in  its  main  features  was  thus  not 
entirely  new,  but  in  fact  the  distinctive  doctrine  of 
Greek  thought,  though  Socrates  had  raised  it  to  the 
supreme  place,  whereas  before  it  had  been  one  of  many 
ideals.  The  Greek  admiidd  knowledge  on  its  own  ac 
count  as  well  as  for  its  utility,  and  hence  Socrates  only 
kept  within  the  limits  of  racial  ideals  when  he  chose  one 
of  them  for  the  pinnacle  of  an  ethical  system.  But  he 


20  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

simply  retained  the  main  principle  of  the  cosmological 
period  without  its  method  or  its  object.  Previous 
thought  assumed  that  men  resented  obedience  to  nature 
and  required  adjustment  of  will  to  attain  virtue.  But 
Socrates,  assuming  that  the  will  was  already  set  in  the 
direction  of  its  desires,  thought  that  the  want  of  knowl 
edge  was  the  only  reason  for  man's  failure  to  attain  the 
object  of  desire.  Hence  he  did  not  make  "virtue"  a 
product  of  will  alone  but  an  object  of  the  intellect, 
wholly  forgetting  the  attributes  of  will  that  constituted 
morality  for  the  majority  of  men,  though  realizing  them 
in  his  personal  character,  and  remaining  unconscious  of 
the  maxim  so  often  quoted  from  Ovid,  as  indicating  the 
frequent  discord  between  knowledge  and  virtue : 

Video  meliora  proboque,  deteriora  sequor. 

But  assuming  that  men  would  pursue  the  good  or  virtue 
if  they  knew  what  it  was,  he  made  knowledge  the  highest 
good  and  excused  vice  by  tracing  it  merely  to  ignorance. 
The  two  formulas  which  expressed  his  doctrine,  and 
which  were  paradoxical  even  to  the  Greeks,  though  less 
so  to  them  than  to  us,  were,  first,  that  "knowledge  is 
virtue,"  and  second,  that  "no  man  is  voluntarily  bad." 
Both  of  them  should  be  examined  carefully. 

It  seems  exceedingly  strange  that  any  man  should 
advocate  the  proposition  that  knowledge  is  virtue. 
Nothing  appears  more  absurd  than  this  real  or  apparent 
identification  of  knowledge  and  morality.  The  dis 
tinction  between  them  is  radical  with  us.  But  the  fact 
is  that  the  whole  paradoxical  character  of  his  formula 
lies  in  the  errors  of  translators.  Stated  in  this  literal,  or 
transliteral,  manner  it  wholly  conceals  the  real  intention 
of  Socrates.  Translators  should  know  more  of  psychol 
ogy  and  philosophy  before  they  attempt  to  interpret  the 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  21 

Greeks  for  us,  and  I  know  of  no  better  illustration  of 
their  intellectual  poverty  as  a  rule  than  the  usual 
formula  which  they  adopt  to  express  the  idea  of  Socrates, 
confusing  the  conceptions  and  associations  of  the  term 
for  us  with  the  very  different  ideas  of  the  Greeks. 
"  Virtue"  with  them  was  a  general  term  for  excellence  of 
any  kind,  whether  physical,  intellectual,  or  moral, 
though  there  was  at  least  a  vague  feeling  that  a  decided 
difference  existed  between  physical  and  moral  excellence. 
Socrates,  indeed,  thought  of  this  "  virtue  "  or  excellence, 
namely,  knowledge,  as  a  good  to  be  attained  as  a  condi 
tion  of  successfully  pursuing  personal  and  other  interests, 
but  not  as  a  quality  of  will,  nor  of  the  act  attaining  and 
aiming  at  this  end,  and  hence  in  order  to  obtain  the  true 
conception  of  Socrates'  doctrine  we  have  to  interpret  his 
11  virtue,  "  not  as  a  quality  of  will  or  conduct,  but  as  the 
skill  or  intelligence  required  to  obtain  the  good  which 
the  individual  was  supposed  to  be  seeking.  Conse 
quently,  when  he  says  that  knowledge  is  "  virtue,  "  he 
means  that  it  is  the  most  important  excellence  or  quality 
of  being  which  man  can  aim  to  attain.  It  stood  for 
Socrates  as  the  summum  bonum,  in  so  far  as  it  was  the 
necessary  condition  to  the  satisfaction  of  desire,  though 
he  admitted  or  assumed  that  it  was  the  means  to  the 
good  which  all  persons  seek  without  the  necessity  of 
being  urged  to  do  so,  or  without  failure,  namely,  interest 
or  pleasure.  With  Socrates  men's  intentions  were  righk 
and  their  failure  to  attain  the  object  of  volition  was  not 
due  to  any  moral  depravity  of  will  asjwe  conceive  the 
matter,  ]put  was  traceable  to  ignorance,  and  hence  the 
imperative  duty  rfto  gain  knowledge,  if  desire  was  to  be 
satisfied  without  miscarriage  ;  that  is,  if  the  good  was  to 
be  attained.  This  conception  of  his  doctrine  is  not  so 
paradoxical  as  it  seems  in  the  usual  form  of  statement, 


22  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

f 
because  of  two  facts  :     (1)  Because  "  virtue  "  is  found  to 

mean  excellence  in  general,  and  (2)  Because  Socrates 
conceived  knowledge  as  a  means  to  an  end  already 
sought,  and  not  as  the  real  ultimate  good,  though  it 
seemed  to  stand  for  this  in  his  system. 

This  interpretation  of  the  formula  of  Socrates  is  born 
out  by  a  similar  examination  of  the  second  paradox  in 
his  theory,    namely,  the  proposition  that  "  no    man   is 
voluntarily  bad."     Ilere  again   translators  are  at  fault 
They    have  assumed  too  readily  that  both  "  bad  "  and 
"  voluntary  "  connote  the  same  in  English  as  in  Greek,  an 
assumption  which  is  totally  false.     In  modern  parlance, 
itself  due  to  conceptions  and  a  history  which  we  cannot 
recount  here,  "bad"  denotes  either  depravity  of  will,  or 
evil  consequences,  such  as  pain,  or  both  ;  and  "  voluntary  " 
expresses  three  facts,  namely,  consciousness,   autonomy, 
and  purpose.     But  in  Greek  thought  "  bad  ", denoted  only 
disagreeable  results,  and  "voluntary"  (excov)   mere   in 
tention  without  reference  or  implication    in  regard  to 
autonomy.       Consequently,   to  say  in   our  phraseology 
that  "  no  man  is  voluntarily  bad  "  is  both  to  deny  the 
freedom  of  the  will  and  to  deny  the  idea  of   moral  de 
pravity  of  will.     But  if  translators  had  said  that  Socrates 
taught  that  no  man  intentionally  or  consciously  sought 
what  he  thought  injurious  to  himself  they  would  have 
expressed  exactly  what  Socrates  meant,  and  the  proposi 
tion  would  not  have  appeared  so  paradoxical.     The  prop 
osition  seems  absurd  to  us  because,  as  I  have  said,  it  ap 
pears  to  deny  the  freedom  of  the  will  on  the  one  hand, 
and  the  fact  that  man  does  consciously,  if  not  purposely, 
choose  the  worse  act  on  the  other.     Bat  if  Socrates  had 
been  told  that  his  doctrine  contradicted  the  freedom  of 
the  will  he  would  either  have  laughed  at  us  or  told  us 
that  he  could  not  understand  such  an  accusation.     The 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  23 

fact  is  that  "  involuntary  "  is  not  the  proper  translation  of 
the  Greek  term  for  which  it  stands  in  the  proposition. 
The  reason,  or  one  reason  at  least,  for  this  is  that  the 
Greek  language  did  not  distinguish  between  will  and 
desire.  The  same  term  did  service  for  both  conceptions, 
while  modern  philosophy  makes  the  distinction  between 
choice  and  desire  (organic  or  instinctive  craving)  so  clear 
that  there  is  no  illusion  as  to  the  meaning  of  the  volun 
tary  and  involuntary.  The  term  desire,  of  course,  is 
equivocal.  But  no  man  to-day  calls  his  desires  voluntary 
in  so  far  as  the  term  describes  merely  natural  or  consti 
tutional  appetites,  but  only  when  he  conceives  them  as 
conscious  acts  of  decision  or  preference.  When  he  con 
trasts  desire  with  will  he  means  distinctly  to  imply  that 
desire  is  either  an  organic  state  of  consciousness  which 
we  find  in  experience  to  be  an  index  of  a  want,  or  crav 
ing  minus  the  final  act  of  excluding  its  alternative  object 
from  possible  election.  The  former  has  no  element  of 
will  in  it,  and  the  latter,  though  it  may  represent  one 
stage  of  consciousness  involving  will,  can  only  be  the 
will  in  deliberation.  But  distinguishing  as  we  do 
between  will  and  desire  we  can  very  well  suppose  that 
a  man  can  will  what  he  does  not  desire.  Socrates, 
however,  could  not  do  this  because  psychology  had  not 
yet  sufficiently  analyzed  the  phenomena  of  conation. 
Neither  he  nor  his  contemporaries  clearly  saw  the  need 
of  this  distinction,  though  they  instinctively  felt  that  there 
was  something  paradoxical  and  illusory  about  his  propo 
sition,  while  they  left  the  riddle  where  they  found  it 
If,  therefore,  we  attempt  to  bring  out  his  meaning  we 
should  read  his  formula  so  that  it  should  express  the 
fact  that  no  man  purposely  desires  evil.  This  would 
sound  much  less  paradoxical,  because  we  concede  easily 
enough  in  common  parlance  that  men  can  act  against 


24  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

their  desires  and  do  wrong  though  they  do  not  desire  the 
wrong  on  its  own  account  Still  there  is  something 
equivocal  in  this  statement,  because  we  know  or  believe 
that  some  men  do  desire  what  is  wrong  or  evil.  But 
here  again  our  word  "  evil  "  does  duty  for  two  different 
conceptions  which  we  at  least  try  to  distinguish  clearly, 
namely,  physical  evil  and  moral  evil.  Physical  or  non- 
moral  evil  is  conceived  as  some  form  of  pain,  or  conse 
quence  that  is  opposed  to  desire,  and  moral  evil  as  a  per 
version  of  will  or  quality  of  action  in  volition  that 
excites  the  resistance  of  conscience.  Now  Socrates  could 
conceive  but  one  "evil,"  and  this  did  not  distinguish 
between  the  physical  and  the  moral ;  that  is,  physical 
and  moral  evil  were  the  same  thing,  and  the  defect  called 
vice  was  a  defect  of  knowledge.  This  evil  or  pain  he 
always  conceived  egoistically  and  for  this  reason  did  not 
see  the  necessity  or  occasion  for  recognizing  a  prohibition 
on  anything  that  was  not  so  related.  We  can  say  that  a 
man  can  desire  the  wrong,  but  not  the  evil,  but  Socrates, 
not  distinguishing  between  wrong  and  evil,  could  not 
use  both  propositions,  but  had  to  choose  between  say 
ing  that  man  consciously  desired  evil  and  that  man  did 
not  consciously  desire  evil.  Socrates  was,  of  course, 
asserting  a  truism  in  his  doctrine  when  we  understand 
what  he  meant  to  maintain.  With  him  there  was  no 
evil,  that  is,  moral  evil,  out  of  relation  to  consciousness 
or  intention,  which  is  perfectly  true.  But  his  formula 
for  expressing  this  truth  was  equivocal.  He  did  not 
always  distinguish  between  consciously  doing  what  is 
evil  and  consciously  doing  what  we  know  to  be  evil. 
Assujnjj^jyiejxlhal_^  never  desire  e^il^jthat  desire  and 
will  are  the  same,  and  that  there  is  no  eviljDut  of  relation 
_tp__desireI  jve  earn  _see  what  -the  proposition  of  Socrates 
meant  to  express.  It  was  that  no  man  consciously 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  25 

desires  what  he  knows  to  be  evil  or  opposed  to  his  per 
sonal  interests.  The  pain  or  evil  which  he  considered  as 
opposed  to  desire  always  had  a  reference  to  the  subject 
of  the  act  or  volition.  The  wrong  was  always  to  himself, 
and  this  was  never  purposive. 

But  then  why  did  Socrates  enunciate  such  a  truiam? 
The  answer  to  this  question  is  that  he  was  aiming  to  assert, 
in  the  interest  of  the  importance  which  he  attached 

"to.  knowledge,  that  all  men  sought  the  same  object, 
nameljL_theiL.  own  personal  interest,  but  were  ignorant 

,_ofthe  means  of  attaining  it.  He  thus  assumed,  as  every 
Greek  would  assume  in  agreement  with  our  Manchester 
economists  perhaps,  that  the  highest  good,  in  so  far 
as  it  is  an  object  of  desire,  is  known,  this  being  his  own 
interest,  but  that,  in  so  far  as  it  was  an  object  of  knowl 
edge,  it  is  not  always  known.  Socrates  did  not  enter 
into  any  inquiry  to  determine  or  prove  what  the  highest 
good,  as  the  ultimate  end  of  volition,  should  be,  because 
he  assumed  that  this  was  both  known  and  unquestion 
able.  This  was  a  problem  of  later  ethics.  He  wanted 
to  emphasize  the  fact  that  the  failure  to  attain  it  was  a 
defect  of  knowledge  in  regard  to  the  means,  and  not  of 
will.  Socrates  was  in  no  respect  a  believer  in  total  de 
pravity,  in  so  far  as  this  characterized  a  bad  will,  but 
the  great  sin  of  man,  if  sin  it  could  be  called,  was  igno 
rance,  the  want  of  the  intelligence  and  skill  to  attain  the 
good  which  he  naturally  sought.  Hence  Socrates  said, 
on  the  one  hand,  that  no  man  consciously  sought  his 
own  injury,  and  on  the  other,  as  an  explanation  of  the 
evil  which  men  actually  suffered,  that  knowledge  was 
the  one  need  which  man  required  to  supply  in  order  to 
satisfy  the  real  object  of  his  volition. 

This  analysis  of  the  position  of  Socrates  brings  us  to 
two  conclusions  which  it  has  been  our  object  to  show, 


26  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

and  which  could  not  have  been  indicated  clearly  without 
removing  the  paradoxes  of  his  doctrine.  They  are :  (1) 
The  purelypracj-^  and 

(2)  TheirNex^r?meTyniidividualistic  character,  at  least  in 
respect  of  the  reference  of  the  good  to  be  realized.  Both 
of  these  require  further  comments  in  order  to  understand 
the  fundamental  trend  of  the  Greek  moral  consciousness. 
Socrates  after  all  did  not  transcend  sophistic  doctrine 
in  his  theory.  He  was  himself  a  sophist  in  the  best 
sense  of  that  term,  which  literally  denoted  a  wise  man, 
but  in  the  person  of  the  later  members  of  the  school  had 
degenerated  into  a  synonym  for  conceit  and  charlatan 
wisdom.  In  regard  to  method,  however,  Socrates  was  a 
sophist,  and  in  both  his  psychological  and  ethical  as 
sumptions  remained,  at  least  for  the  sake  of  argument, 
upon  the  level  of  the  men  whose  doctrines  he  so  critically 
examined.  He  argued  and  debated  precisely  as  they  did, 
and  took  the  attitude  of  an  instructor  of  youth T  though 
careful  to  exhibit  more  modesty,  humility,  and  consistent 
agnosticism  than  these  purveyors  of  wisdom.  In  it  all, 
however,  he  was  te^riblyin  earnest,  and  less  governed 
by  personal  gain  than  the  sophists  whom  Plato  lam 
pooned.  It  was  only  in  a  latent  sympathy  with  the  reli 
gious  conception  of  the  world  that  he  departed  from  the 
skepticism  of  the  sophists.  But  in  spite  of  the  religious 
tinge  of  thought  in  his  mind  he  did  not  start  with  this 
doctrine  as  the  basis  of  his  ethics.  He  was  too  dexterous 
a  logician  to  be  entrapped  in  this  way.  He  made  no 
effort  to  combat  sophistic  skepticism  by  proving  the 
existence  of  the  gods,  nor  did  he  try  to  show  that  moral 
ity  was  founded  in  the  will  of  such  gods  as  he  admitted 
to  exist.  He  kept  silence  upon  this  point,  whether  from 
discretion  or  not  it  is  not  necessary  to  say,  though  it  may 
be  a  libel  to  suspect  that  Socrates  had  any  discretion  at 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  27 

all.  But  he  showed  no  tendency  to  revert  to  the  old 
religious  view  of  morality.  Nor  did  he  question  the 
sophistic  doctrines  that  every  one  must  be  the  measure 
of  truth,  and  that  pleasure  or  personal  interest  was  the 
real  summum  lonum  for  every  man.  With  this  settled 
or  assumed  he  had  only  to  show,  as  already  indicated, 
what  means  were  necessary  to  attain  this  good.  Even 
when  he  sought  a  definition  of  virtue  itself  he  was  not 
trying  to  determine  any  other  end  in  conduct  than  per 
sonal  happiness  or  satisfaction,  but  only  to  show  the 
form  in  which  that  happiness  could  be  gained  without 
any  admixture  of  evil.  The  Socratic  morality,  therefore, 
was  practical,  not  theoretical.  He  was  bent  on  showing 
men  that  the  chief  pcohlem  was  a  knowledge,  of  the_ 
"_popd"  as  the  means  to  the  d paired  fmrl.  Hence  he 
could  maintain  that  "  virtue  "  could  be  taught,  because  it 
was  merely  the  problem  of  imparting  knowledge  of  the 
causal  relation  between  certain  acts  and  their  conse 
quences.  It  is  only  when  we  reach  Plato  and  Aristotle 
that  we  find  a  definite  conscious  effort  to  reconstruct 
ethical  theory  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  end  of  con 
duct  as  well  as  the  means.  But  Socrates  was  still  a 
sophist  in  the  conception  of  both  his  ethics  and  his  call 
ing,  namely,  in  considering  himself  an  instructor  respect 
ing  the  means  to  a  good  already  assumed  rather  than 
respecting  the  correction  of  men's  idea  of  this  good, 
though  his  method  of  criticizing  conceptions  led  to  this 
very  result.  Nevertheless,  his  whole  conception  of  the 
ethical  problem  was  that  of  a  man  who  felt  only  the  need 
of  educating  the  intellect  in  regard  to  the  conditions 
necessary  for  attaining  a  presupposed  end.  These  he 
conceived  as  knowledge,  as  the  education  of  the  logical 
faculties,  as  the  sharpening  of  the  cognitive  insight,  as 
nothing  but  clear  ideas.  Such  a  thing  as  a  perverted 


28  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

will  he  could  not  understand,  but  only  a  perverted  intel 
lect.  TR^jJ-aanmftd  thfl.t  fl.  ma.T\  will  always  dojfchft  right,  if 
only  be  knows  what lf-  ^  This  is  true  enough  when  the 
man  is  conscientious,  a  condition  of  mind  which  includes 
respect  for  the  interests  of  others  as  well  as  self.  But 
when  he  regards  nothing  but  his  own  interest,  or  per 
sonal  satisfaction  in  a  form  incompatible  with  the  welfare 
of  others,  though  knowing  what  this  good  for  others  is, 
there  is  much  more  than  the  education  of  the  intellect 
necessary.  Socrates  is  here  banking  on  the  flexibility  of 
the  will,  which  is  ready  to  modify  its  ideal  at  the  demand 
of  better  insight,  while  the  fact  is  that  the  form  of  our 
ideal  concretely  conceived  often  requires  as  much  modi 
fication  of  the  will  to  arrive  at  the  true  good  as  it  does 
education  of  the  intellect  or  reason  to  see  the  way  to  it. 
Hence  Socrates  gets  no  further  in  his  conception  of 
ethics  than  the  problem  of  educating  the  intellect.  The 
problem  of  u  educating "  the  will  he  did  not  see,  and 
perhaps  would  not  have  seen  or  understood  had  it  been 
pointed  out  to  him.  He  remained  upon  the  general 
level  of  the  Greek  consciousness  of  his  time,  which  was 
extravagantly  absorbed  in  the  pursuit  of  knowledge. 
The  Greek  exaggerated  the  importance  of  reason,  and 
especially  of  speculative  reason,  so  that  a  life  of  mere 
knowledge  seemed  the  only  satisfaction  necessary  for  the 
attainment  of  perfection,  the  socio-economic  system  with 
slavery  on  the  one  side  and  aristocratic  habits  and  tastes 
on  the  other  favoring  leisure  and  scientific  pursuits  as 
the  occupation  of  gentlemen.  In  such  a  civilization  will 
or  action  would  not  be  idealized.  Knowledge  would 
naturally  be  the  highest  good,  or  the  excellence  which 
free  men  would  estimate  most  highly,  while  the  moral 
virtues  of  will  which  we  consider  would  be  limited  to 
the  dependent  classes.  Socrates,  though  nothing  of  an 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  29 

aristocrat  in  his  taste,  person,  or  manners,  remained  by 
this  conception,  which  led  to  the  contemplative  rather 
than  the  active  life. 

The  second  characteristic  of  the  Socratic  ethics  is  no 
less  interesting  than  the  first.  It  is  the  individualistic 
point  of  view  assumed  by  him,  if  not  in  the  means  of 
attaining  self-satisfaction,  certainly  in  the  end  which  action 
had  to  subserve.  We  have  already  remarked  that  Soc 
rates  did  not  transcend  the  sophistic  view  in  his  tacit 
assumption  that  every  man  is  governed  in  his  conduct 
by  his  own  personal  interest.  This  was  a  truism  with 
Socrates.  The  high  tone  of  language  employed  about 
virtue,  which  we  understand  from  a  changed  point  of 
view,  charging  it  with  conceptions  and  implications  of 
later  history,  availed  to  conceal  from  the  modern  mind 
either  the  naked  individualism  of  his  doctrine  or  the 
complete  absence  of  an  altruistic  object,  though  it  recog 
nized  altruistic  means  to  an  egoistic  end.  Socrates  never 
thought  of  making  the  interest  of  others  an  end,  but  only 
a  means  to  one's  own  higher  interest.  In  this  way  his 
individualism  was  made  objectively  consistent  with 
social  welfare.  Modern  ideas  make  others  than  the  sub 
ject  ends  in  themselves,  and  not  merely  means  to  the 
subject's  interest  That  is,  we  treat  justice  as  an  end 
and  not  merely  as  a  means  to  personal  welfare.  But 
Socrates,  though  he  went  beyond  his  contemporaries  in 
the  recognition  of  the  means  to  virtue,  did  not  transcend 
them  in  the  motive  which  he  advanced.  Consequently, 
in  spite  of  the  social  content  of  his  ethical  position,  it 
was  individualistic  in  its  motive  efficient.  It  may  be 
objected,  of  course,  that  this  view  is  not  pure  individual 
ism,  and  I  do  not  care  to  insist  too  vehemently  for  the 
position.  But  when  we  consider  that,  besides  the  indi 
vidualistic  motive  in  his  doctrine,  there  was  not  a  clear 


30  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

consciousness  in  Socrates  of  the  conflict  between  individ 
ual  and  social  interest,  not  ideally,  but  in  fact,  we  can 
understand  both  the  paradox  and  the  egoism  of  his  theory. 
He  was  understood  by  the  average  Greek  to  mean, 
when  he  taught  that  justice  would  result  in  good  to  the 
agent  of  it,  that  this  good  would  be  the  satisfaction  of  the 
personal  interest  which  the  individual  sought  without 
regard  to  the  welfare  of  others.  This  is  well  illustrated 
by  the  question  raised  in  Plato's  "Kepublic,"  asking 
whether  justice  always  results  in  satisfying  personal 
interest.  Socrates  no  doubt  had  an  ideal  that  was  calcu 
lated  to  change  the  conception  of  his  race,  but  his  instinct 
for  practical  ethics,  and  the  desire  to  put  his  doctrine  in 
terms  of  common  experience,  made  him  appeal  to  con 
ceptions  that  were  lower  than  his  ideal.  Hence  he  was 
not  understood  to  maintain  or  admit  a  real  conflict  be 
tween  personal  and  social  interest.  The  whole  practical 
effect  of  his  position  was  to  keep  alive,  not  by  his  life, 
but  by  his  theory,  the  egoistic  assumptions  of  the  Greek 
consciousness.  The  Greek  ideal  was:  "Everyman  for 
himself  and  the  devil  take  the  hindmost" — the  true  naked 
conception  involved  in  the  struggle  for  existence  as  con 
ceived  when  we  try  to  eliminate  its  moral  character. 
Socrates  never  thought  to  question  such  a  view  as  inhu 
man,  nor  to  teach  definitely  that  a  sacrifice  of  one  pleas 
ure  or  ideal  had  to  be  made  to  secure  another.  The  idea 
of  sacrifice  for  attaining  the  true  good  was  not  a  Greek 
conception,  and  Socrates  did  not  inculcate  it,  so  that  his 
individualism,  though  it  was  in  its  means  identical  with 
the  social  ethics  of  later  times,  had  for  its  motive  and  its 
material  results  the  same  effect  as  that  individualism 
which  passes  for  egoism  and  selfishness.  His  own 
strength  of  will  and  respect  for  justice  prevented  him 
from  both  appearing  and  being  egoistic  in  his  personal 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  31 

and  objective  conduct,  but  his  subjective  psychology  and 
egoistic  motive  in  ethical  theory  kept  him  within  the 
limits  of  his  race,  and,  consciously  or  unconsciously, 
favored  personal  interest  as  the  only  ultimate  end  of  con 
duct,  as  against  all  men  being  ends  in  themselves  and 
while  invoking  altruistic  motives,  represent  the  point  of 
view  that  still  justifies  the  characterization  of  individual 
ism  in  Socratic  ethics. 

But  if  this  view  of  Socrates  be  correct,  why  is  it  that 
he  has  created  so  much  interest  in  subsequent  ages  ?  If 
his  theory  of  virtue  was  so  individualistic,  and  if  he  did 
not  transcend  the  moral  consciousness  of  his  age,  which 
was  so  individualistic  in  its  motives  and  objects,  why 
has  he  been  so  universally  admired,  and  why  has  his 
doctrine  been  so  extravagantly  extolled?  Why  is  he 
regarded  as  so  superior  to  his  contemporaries? 

The  answer  to  this  question  lies  in  his  personality,  not 
in  his  philosophy.  Socrates,  as  a  man,  was  either  better 
than  his  theory,  or  he  gave  it  that  meaning  in  his  life  and 
conduct  which  it  logically  concealed.  That  is  to  say, 
his  theoretical  doctrine  did  not  give  logical  expression  to 
the  ideas  which  his  conduct  embodied.  It  was  his  per 
sonality  that  struck  his  comtemporaries,  and  that  stands 
out  in  the  estimation  of  succeeding  ages,  giving  the  real 
meaning  to  his  formulas  when  his  own  conceptions  did 
not  transcend  the  main  trend  of  his  time.  Men  see 
character  and  interpret  theories  according  to  the  conduct 
with  which  theories  are  associated.  Ideas  are  rightly 
supposed  either  to  express  facts  or  to  indicate  the  path 
of  virtue,  and  assuming  that  men  really  intend  to  pursue 
the  latter  when  pointed  out,  a  theory  pretending  to  di 
rect  the  will  into  a  presumably  desired  course  will  be 
adjudged  by  its  influence  upon  the  man  who  proposes  it 
as  a  moral  guide.  Socrates  had  one  of  those  interesting 


32  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

personalities  of  the  highest  moral  type,  mixed  also  with 
something  of  the  grotesque,  which  was  bound  to  attract 
the  attention  of  mankind,  and  it  is  to  this  that  we  must 
trace  both  the  extraordinary  interest  in  the  man  and  the 
concealment  of  the  real  import  of  his  doctrine.  It  was 
his  character  rather  than  his  logic  that  revolutionized 
the  subsequent  conception  of  morality,  and  it  may  be 
safe  to  say  that  it  is  always  personality,  and  not  abstract 
philosophy,  that  creates  mankind's  conception  of  moral 
conduct  and  the  value  of  moral  theory.  Abstract  philo 
sophical  dogmas  have  no  meaning  or  influence  upon  the 
majority  until  embodied  in  a  personal  life.  Now  Socra 
tes  was  not  individualistic  in  his  conduct,  whatever  his 
motives.  His  will  always  waited  on  his  intellect,  and 
hence  he  was  ever  ready  to  do  what  he  conceived  to  be 
right  and  just,  which  he  conceived  to  be  his  interest. 
He  refused  to  recognize  any  personal  interest  but  that 
which  was  consistent  with  justice  or  the  welfare  of 
others.  Hence  he  never  appeared  to  be  an  egoist  or  the 
subject  of  selfishness.  With  his  fellows,  personal  interest 
was  often  in  conflict  with  that  of  others,  and  when  the 
good  was  proposed  to  any  one  it  was  conceivable  only  in 
individualistic  terms  which  assumed  this  conflict.  But 
Socrates  felt  no  interest  but  that  of  justice,  and  in  so 
doing  generalized  the  conception  so  that  it  was  consist 
ent  with  his  will,  while  his  fellows  heard  the  conceptions 
of  an  egoist  and  saw  the  volitions  of  an  idealist.  Thus 
his  personal  life  evoked  veneration  and  gave  meaning  to 
his  appeal  to  interest,  though  his  contemporaries  could 
not  feel  the  identification  of  justice  and  interest  which  he 
taught,  because  their  interest  was  on  the  lower  plane  of 
that  individualism  which  could  not  transcend  the  conflict 
between  personal  interest  and  that  of  others,  or  would  not 
extend  the  range  of  its  objects,  so  that  an  individualistic 


MODERATION  AND   CONTENTMENT. 

We  should  refrain  most  from  sordid  unjust  pleas- 
ures. 

Happiness  consists  not  in  luxury  and  pride.  To 
want  nothing  is  divine,  to  want  the  least,  next  to 
divine. 

He  is  richest  who  is  content  with  least,  for  content 
ment  is  the  riches  of  nature. 

It  is  the  property  of  God  to  need  nothing,  to  need 
least  the  nighest  to  God. 

Socrates. 


SOCRATES, 

THIS  PHILOSOPHIC  TRAMP  AND   MORAL  PREACHER  OF  ATHENS. 
(See  p.  33-34.) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  35 

lost  in  his  logical  acumen  without  caring  for  his  appear 
ance.  In  fact  he  was  like  the  man  who  always  wants  to 
talk  politics  with  people  who  do  not  care  a  picayune 
about  them,  or  to  ventilate  some  hobby  like  the  schemes 
which  are  to  cure  all  the  ills  of  humanity.  He  reminds 
us  of  some  too  wise  farmer  who  neglects  his  stock  and 
crops  to  sit  on  the  fence  all  day,  debating  prohibition, 
free  silver,  or  the  money  power.  Everywhere  we  meet 
this  type  of  man,  and  we  inevitably  set  him  down  at 
once  as  a  crank  and  a  bore,  if  we  are  very  esthetic  and 
not  very  serious  about  life.  And  this  habit  brought 
Socrates,  as  it  does  his  modern  after-type,  into  trouble 
with  his  wife.  Xantippe  complained  that  Socrates 
roamed  the  streets  talking  about  philosophy  when  he 
should  have  been  at  work  supporting  her  and  his  chil 
dren.  We  do  not  know  that  Xantippe  supported 
Socrates  in  his  pedestrian  philosophy  and  idleness  on  the 
streets  by  washing,  as  is  often  the  case  with  our  modern 
"dead  beats,"  but  the  situation  described  has  a  marvel 
ous  resemblance  to  this  very  thing.  Socrates,  however, 
grunted  out  a  not  very  chivalrous  excuse  for  himself, 
reflecting  on  the  temper  of  his  other  half,  himself  and  the 
age  being  impervious  to  the  finer  sentiments  and  duties 
of  a  husband,  and  modern  civilization  sides  with  Xan 
tippe.  But  neither  Xantippe's  rightful  claims  nor  the 
alleged  acidity  of  her  temper  and  observations  deterred 
Socrates  from  keeping  up  his  life  of  dialectic  mischief 
with  every  one  he  could  buttonhole  on  the  street  corners. 
But  he  could  not  have  succeeded  in  producing  the 
effect  he  did,  had  he  not  been  as  thick-skinned  as  he  was 
shrewd  and  talented,  and  inspired  'with  lofty  ideals 
which  shone  out  behind  the  covering  of  oddities,  physi 
cal  and  intellectual,  in  a  way  to  defeat  all  concealment. 
He  laughed  at  his  own  defects,  perfectly  conscious  of 


36  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

the  way  lie  was  regarded  by  his  countrymen,  cynically 
indifferent  to  it,  a  good-humored  stolid  Greek,  who  could 
not  be  offended  by  any  ridicule,  nor  silenced  by  any 
criticism  except  that  which  led  to  his  own  conclusions. 
He  was  an  adept  at  the  art  of  controversy,  even  when  he 
had  no  positive  doctrine  to  defend,  and  if  the  Greeks 
ever  loved  anything  it  was  logical  discussion.  They 
were  forever  at  it,  whether  on  the  streets  or  the  hustings, 
and  they  liked  a  man,  especially  in  this  period  of  transi 
tion  from  the  age  of  belief  to  philosophic  ideas,  who 
could  either  produce  or  solve  logical  puzzles  without 
discriminating  too  nicely  about  his  manners  and  appear 
ance.  In  this  art  Socrates  showed  unusual  shrewdness, 
because  he  insisted  upon  his  ignorance,  thus  escaping 
responsibility  for  any  assertion  whatever,  though  this  pro 
fession  was  ironical,  and  shifting  the  duty  of  proof  upon 
his  antagonists.  This  made  him  a  perfect  master  of  the 
true  art  of  a  skeptic,  who  shelters  himself  behind  ques 
tions  while  his  informant  must  do  all  the  asserting  and 
gets  into  deeper  and  deeper  water  with  every  question 
that  he  tries  to  answer.  Moreover  the  average  Greeks  of 
common  sense  had  felt  the  destructive  influence  of 
sophistic  and  skeptical  thought  and  did  not  like  the 
intellectual  and  moral  confusion  that  it  produced.  They 
were  also  no  less  impressed  than  Socrates  with  sophistic 
conceit  and  pretension,  and  hence  they  looked  on  with 
delight  at  the  shafts  of  logic  which  this  Silenus  of  a  man 
thrust  into  skeptical  armor,  and  though  he  often  pro 
duced  as  much  embarrassment  in  his  hearers  as  he  cured, 
he  created  much  satisfaction  in  the  interest  of  truth  and 
morality  by  puzzling  skepticism  upon  its  own  premises, 
and  this  satisfaction  was  enough  for  a  people  who  did 
not  want  the  paradoxes  or  logical  tricks  of  the  sophists 
for  their  every-day  philosophy.  The  Greeks  had  not 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  37 

forgotten  the  logical  legerdemain  of  Zeno,  and  though 
they  were  not  disposed  to  follow  him  in  denying  the 
possibility  of  motion,  they  admired  logic  and  were  great 
sticklers  for  the  importance  of  its  method  and  the  con 
sistency  which  it  demanded.  Hence,  when  they  found 
Socrates  using  it  in  his  masterful  way  to  make  the  con 
fusion  of  the  sophists  worse  confounded,  they  gave  him 
an  enthusiastic  hearing  in  spite  of  homely  illustrations, 
grotesque  personal  appearance,  odd  manners,  and  indif 
ference  to  family  obligations.  He  had  a  genius  for  em 
barrassing  charlatans  in  philosophy,  and  his  own  delight 
was  not  less  than  his  auditors'  when  he  saw  some  over 
confident  antagonist  writhing  at  the  bottom  of  a  syllo 
gism  for  some  indiscretion  in  starting  an  argument^  before 
he  had  matured  and  mastered  the  conceptions  which  he 
so  glibly  used. 

But  it  was  the  moral  character  of  Socrates,  his  strength 
of  will,  that  created  the  profoundest  influence  even  upon 
the  pleasure-loving  Greeks.  They  were  not  all  of  them 
given  to  libertinism.  A  few  choice  spirits,  even  when 
they  saw  no  way  out  of  sophistic  logic  on  matters  of 
morality,  felt  their  better  instincts  groping  after  an  ideal 
that  involved  neither  slavish  obedience  to  arbitrary 
power  nor  unrestrained  indulgence  of  passion.  They 
awaited  only  the  voice  of  some  one  crying  in  the  wilder 
ness  to  enlist  and  encourage  their  moral  natures,  and 
though  they  may  have  enjoyed  most  the  keen,  Damascus- 
like  thrusts  of  Socrates'  logic  against  sophistic  illusions 
in  morality,  they  were  not  wholly  insensible  to  the 
monitions  of  conscience,  when  any  noble  aspirations  were 
suggested  in  keeping  with  the  best  features  of  the  civili 
zation  which  they  had  already  reached,  and  hence 
Socrates,  both  in  his  personality  and  his  method,  awak 
ened  ideals  that  were  in  danger  of  suffocation  under 


V 

38  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

skepticism  and  libertinism.  Behind  all  his  indifference 
to  ridicule,  tolerance  of  others'  opinions,  and  uncouth 
manners,  Socrates  was  a  man  of  great  moral  earnestness, 
and  this  fact  did  not  escape  the  notice  of  the  better  men 
who  formed  a  part  of  his  audience.  The  chief  feature 
of  his  character  which  struck  the  Athenians  was 
his  strength  of  will,  his  splendid  self-control,  and  hia 
unselfish  devotion  to  justice.  At  least  they  found  in  his 
resolute  purpose  to  do  the  right  when  he  knew  it  his 
political  firmness  against  the  majority  in  the  Prytaneum 
who  wished  to  violate  the  law,  his  determined  attach 
ment  to  some  ideal  in  the  midst  of  every  temptation  that 
might  be  used  as  an  excuse  for  libertinism,  his  submis 
sion  to  the  law  in  the  matter  of  his  own  sentence  and 
execution  when  offered  an  opportunity  to  escape,  and 
the  perpetual  moderation  of  his  appetites — in  all  these 
they  found  the  traits  of  moral  character  which  they  had 
learned  to  admire  so  much  in  such  heroes  as  Solon, 
Aristides,  and  others,  who  in  firmness  and  constancy  of 
principle,  and  devotion  to  justice,  which  was  the  Greek 
righteousness,  were  prototypes  of  Socrates  in  his  com 
mon  life.  The  Greeks  recognized  a  noble  man  when 
they  saw  him  quite  as  readily  as  we  can,  as  is  clearly 
shown  in  many  of  their  heroes,  even  if  their  general 
standard  of  life  was  lower  than  ours.  It  was  this  moral 
strength  of  will  that  struck  the  imagination  and  com 
manded  respect  when  his  theory  of  virtue  was  either  mis 
understood  or  felt  to  be  paradoxical  and  unsatisfactory. 
Perfect  self-control  was  his  peculiar  virtue.  He  did  not 
get  tipsy  at  a  banquet  while  his  companions  were  often 
said  to  be  found  under  the  table.  Perhaps  the  cynic 
and  skeptic  will  say  that  his  associates  admired  him 
because  he  could  drink  more  than  they  could  without  get 
ting  drunk,  and  if  the  Greek  who  wished  that  his  throat 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  39 

was  a  mile  long  when  he  drank  good  wine  was  a  typical 
man  of  his  race,  this  cynical  view  might  be  plausible. 
But  with  all  deference  to  the  pessimist's  view  of  human 
nature,  many  of  the  admirers  of  Socrates  were  possessed 
of  adequate  self-control  and  of  insight  into  the  real 
character  of  their  master,  which  was  as  much  morally  as 
it  was  physically  constitutional,  while  those  who  were 
themselves  the  victims  of  imprudence  when  they  knew 
the  better  course  saw  well  enough  in  the  midst  of  Soc 
rates'  geniality  of  temperament  that  the  master  spirit  of 
his  life  was  a  strong  will  thoroughly  in  subjection  to 
moral  law.  This  was  the  ideal  side  of  his  character,  and 
it  had  the  effect  when  contrasting  Socrates  with  others 
of  eliciting  a  new  analysis  of  the  ethical  problem,  and  a 
new  conception  of  morality,  a  conception  that  interpreted 
it  in  terms  of  a  righteous  will  instead  of  mere  knowl 
edge^ 

y^rlato  more  clearly  than  any  one  else  saw  the  ideal 
Socrates  and  painted  him  in  colors  which  will  never  be 
effaced  from  the  memory  of  history.  While  he  began 
with  admiration  for  his  method  and  the  place  which  he 
assigned  to  knowledge  as  the  highest  "  virtue,"  he  went 
far  beyond  Socrates  in  the  conception  and  analysis  of 
morality,  though  he  still  left  enough  undone  for  the 
critical  and  analytical  power  of  Aristotle  to  secure  an 
equal  immortality  by  a  still  profounder  development  of 
ethical  problems. 

In  estimating  Platonic  ethics  we  must  ascertain  his 
point  of  departure  from  Socrates.  Plato  still  remained 
by  the  pyschological  method  of  his  master,  but  not  by 
the  Socratic  contempt  for  metaphysics.  We  have 
already  seen  how  Socrates  treated  the  physical  specula 
tions  of  his  predecessors,  refusing  to  learn  anything  from 
nature  or  to  look  at  the  external  order  of  the  world  for 


40  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

the  moral  ideal  by  which  to  govern  his  conduct.  Not 
so  with  Plato.  He  showed  a  profounder  insight  into  all 
the  facts  with  which  the  human  mind  is  called  to  deal. 
He  was  an  all-round  genius,  the  beau  ideal  of  his  race. 
It  is  hard  to  say  whether  his  sympathies  with  art,  which 
was  little  less  than  the  divinity  of  Greece,  were  any  less 
than  his  enthusiasm  and  power  for  the  speculations  of 
abstract  philosophy,  a  very  rare  combination  of  talents 
and  tastes  in  any  age,  and  especially  conspicuous  and 
striking  in  the  disciple  of  Socrates,  and  which  took  the 
form  best  calculated  to  throw  all  their  splendid  illumina 
tion  upon  the  conception  and  purpose  of  ethics.  The 
interest  in  metaphysics  showed  itself  in  his  antagonism 
to  Heraclitus,  whose  doctrine  of  change  and  phenomenal 
evanescence  of  everything  resulted  in  the  sophists'  sub 
jective  psychology  and  conventional  ethics,  the  denial  of 
any  universal  truths,  and  of  any  law  for  the  individual 
will  except  its  own  caprices,  and  in  his  attachment  to  the 
ideas  of  Parmenides,  who  had  emphasized  the_import- 
ance  of  the  permanent,  the  universal,  and  the  eternal  in 
the  nature  of  things  including  human  thought  and 
action.  Plato  took  up  the  thought  of  the  permanent 
and  worked  it  out  as  his  own  in  the  field  of  ethics  as 
Parmenides  had  done  in  the  physical  world,  and  we 
have  as  a  consequence  two  characteristics  of  his  position  : 
(1)  That  morality  expresses  a  law  in  the  nature  of 
things,  eternal  and  absolute,  and  in  no  way  subject  to 
the  caprice  of  power,  divine  or  human.  (2)  The  subor 
dination  of  the  individual  to  the  whole,  or  the  law  of  the 
good  which  he  found  in  nature  as  well  as  in  man,  and 
the  consequent  importance  of  objective  (physical)  as  well 
as  subjective  (psychological)  knowledge  for  the  attain 
ment  of  this  end.  The  first  of  these  positions  was 
Plato's  answer  to  the  sophists  whose  morality  was  the 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  41 

whim  of  the  moment;  that  is,  no  morality  at  all;  and 
the  second  was  the  doctrine  in  which  we  find  Plato 
transcending  the  pure  individualism  of  his  race,  though 
it  coincides  exactly  with  the  universal  civic  ideal  of 
Greece,  the  sacrifice  of  the  citizen  to  the  state,  and 
explains  the  socialism  of  the  Platonic  Republic.  This 
tendency  of  his  system  requires  for  its  understanding  a 
most  careful  examination  of  his  general  position. 

Socrates,  as  we  have  seen,  taught  that  knowledge  was 
necessary  to  virtue,  but  he  assumed  that  the  will  was 
already  set  in  the  direction  of  the  good  and  that  it 
lacked  only  intelligence  to  guide  it.  That  is  to  say,  the 
practical  ethics  of  Socrates  neglected  the  theoretical 
problem  of  determining  the  end  of  morality,  and  was 
employed  about  the  means  to  an  end  which  was  assumed 
to  be  known.  But  Plato  early  discovered  that  men  were 
very  concrete  in  their  choice  of  objects  to  realize,  and 
that  the  abstract  idea  of  interest  or  pleasure  drew  no  dis 
tinction  between  vice  and  virtue.  Consequently,  he  saw, 
or  believed  he  saw,  that  men  were  as  ignorant  of  the 
true  e.nd-oLli£G  as  Socrates  thought  them  in  regard  to  the 
right  means  to  a  presupposed  interest,  and  so  he  set 
about  correcting  the  Socratic  assumption  that  pleasure 
or  personal  interest  was  the  highest  good,  at  least  when 
conceived  as  sacrificing  the  universal  good.  Both  his 
metaphysics  and  his  psychology  led  him  away  from  the 
subordination  of  everything  to  the  individual.  His 
metaphysics,  which  seized  upon  the  permanent  elements 
in  nature  and  mind  as  opposed  to  the  transient,  and  the 
ordinary  Greek  consciousness  of  the  limitations  placed 
upon  the  arbitrary  human  will  by  the  cosmos,  taught 
him  to  find  in  nature  an  order  to  which  it  was  the  chief 
duty  and^end  of  man  to  subject  himself.  This  end  he 
called  the  Good,  which  he  identified  with  God,  regarding 


42  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

God,  however,  as  impersonal  and  as  merely  the 
moral  order  of  the  world,  a  position  that  was  reiterated 
by  Fichte  in  later  times.  Man's  duty  was  to  find  out 
this  end  and  then  to  ascertain  how  he  could  attain  it 
Thus  a  double  knowledge  was  required  :  first,  a  knowl 
edge,  reasoned  and  speculative  in  its  nature,  of  this 
eternal  law,  of  the  end,  goal,  destiny,  state,  or  condition 
which  nature  intended  man  to  realize,  and  second,  a 
knowledge  of  the  correct  means  to  reach  it.  In  the  first 
of  these  conceptions  the  human  will  is  wholly  subor 
dinated  to  an  end,  which,  if  it  is  not  outside  itself  in  the 
results  attained,  is  outside  of  it  in  the  way  that  duty  is 
presented  to  it,  and  so  leads  to  that  sacrifice  of  the 
individual  to  the  whole  which  is  so  prominent  in  the 
Kepublic,  and  which  prepares  us  for  the  Stoic  pantheism 
and  the  Neoplatonic  absorption.  An  end  that  was  not 
pleasure,  that  was  not  consciousness  of  any  kind,  and 
that  involved  a  result  out  of  relation  to  one's  personal 
identity,  but  that  was  an  objective  universe  of  law  and 
order,  necessitated  the  complete  sacrifice  of  the  individual 
to  realize  it. 

Plato's  psychological  analysis  led  him  no  less  certainly 
in  the  same  direction.  He  saw  that  pleasure  was  a 
criterion  that  had  no  other  meaning  for  the  average 
Greek  than  individual  personal  interest,  and  more 
especially  the  interest  of  the  moment.  His  predilection 
for  the  idea  of  law,  of  an  eternal  order,  set  him  about 
reconstructing  the  internal  principle  of  morality  in 
harmony  with  the  cosmic  order.  All  sensations  and 
feelings  of  sense  being  transient  phenomena,  while  the 
objects  of  reason  were  permanent  realities,  or  facts  of 
highest  worth  on  that  account,  he  described  the  pursuit 
of  pleasure  as  the  anarchic  reign  of  passion  and  impulse. 
To  restrain  these  inclinations  he  proposed  the  imperial 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  43 

authority  of  reason.  His  famous  myth  of  the  chariot  drawn 
by  two  unruly  steeds  but  controlled  by  the  charioteer 
called  reason  brilliantly  illustrates  his  conception  of  the 
source  of  supreme  power  in  the  determination  of  virtue. 
Keason  was  required,  in  this  illustration,  to  restrain 
passion  and  impulse,  or  better  to  guide  them,  the 
idea  that  it  restrains  being  in  fact  a  conception  of 
later  thought.  And  this  view  represents  Plato's  doctrine 
of  conscience.  But  with  him  conscience  was  not  a 
motive  power  or  a  sense  of  duty,  an  injunction  imposed 
upon  the  will,  but  it  was  a  cognitive  power  to  point 
out  the  right  way  for  impulse  to  attain  the  desirable 
end.  In  spite  of  this  view,  however,  Plato's  very 
illustration  introduced  the  idea  of  a  regulative  function 
for  reason  having  the  nature  of  will,  as  such  control  of 
motive  forces  implied  similar  agency,  and  hence  it  was 
only  a  short  step  to  the  idea  of  conscience  combining  the 
functions  of  intellect  and  will,  moving  as  well  as  direct 
ing  volition.  With  us  conscience  is  insight  plus  motive, 
the  motive  of  duty  and  reverence  for  an  ideal  above  and 
beyond  passion.  With  Plato  reason  was  only  insight 
into  the  course  which  was  a  harmony  between  passion  and 
impulse,  and  it  guided  the  man,  not  as  an  impelling 
force,  but  as  a  chaperon  that  could  furnish  wisdom  but 
no  power.  This  conception  of  it  at  once  took  it  out  of 
the  region  of  pleasure.  The  function  of  reason  was  to 
furnish  the  abstract  true,  beautiful,  and  good,  not  to 
move  the  will.  In  this  Plato  still  remained  by  the  con 
ception  of  his  master.  He  exalted  the  importance  of 
knowledge.  But  at  this  point  he  widened  the  range  of 
its  power  and  objects.  Reason  or  knowledge  occupied 
itself  with  the  whole  cosmos  of  facts,  physical  and 
mental,  and  as  Plato  refused  to  recognize  anything  tran 
sient,  like  feeling  or  pleasure,  as  the  highest  good,  he 


44  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

had  to  look  beyond  the  individual  for  it,  and  he  found  it 
in  the  eternal  reality,  law,  or  order  behind  phenomena,  a 
transcendental  ideal  condition  of  things  independent  of 
sense  and  consciousness  which  only  a  mystical  philoso 
pher  like  Plato  could  see  or  find.  But  it  was  the  end 
which  he  thought  nature  had  in  view,  independent  of 
the  capricious  pleasures  of  passion  and  impluse.  These 
anarchic  tendencies  could  never  discover  it,  but  only 
attain  it  after  reason  had  seen  the  vision  of  its  beauty. 

But  Plato,  as  Greek  thinkers  generally,  was  monistic 
and  pantheistic  in  his  conception  of  nature  and  man,  and 
consequently  when  he  saw  reason  in  nature  he  assigned 
it  the  same  function  there  as  in  the  regulation  of  the 
passion,  namely,  the  determination  of  order.  Reason 
in  both  the  macrocosmos  and  the  microcosmos  was  the 
producer  of  order,  and  this  object  was  not  a  mere  feeling 
in  the  former,  so  that  man's  chief  end  could  not  be  a 
pleasure.  As  the  psychological  good  was  the  harmony 
between  the  appetites  and  the  metaphysical  good  the 
harmony  in  nature,  and  as  reason  was  the  function  for 
determining  it  in  both  fields,  ethics  looked  beyond 
pleasure  for  the  ideal,  this  being  merely  a  transient  and 
subjective  feeling,  and  had  in  this  way  to  sacrifice  the 
individual  psychologically  as  well  as  metaphysically. 
The  order  of  nature  being  an  objective  end  for  realiza 
tion  and  demanding  the  subjection  of  the  will,  the  whole 
system  subordinated  man  to  an  end  other  than  himself,  and 
virtually  demanded  a  self-sacrifice  that  no  other  system 
of  Greek  ethics  proposed.  But  he  recognized  that  this 
subordination  brought  man  his  true  good,  and  nothing 
was  lost  in  the  sacrifice.  The  only  thing,  however,  that 
mars  this  beautiful  picture  of  Plato's  ethics  is  the  fact  that 
his  system  saw  nothing  of  worth  in  the  individual  but 
his  conformity  to  law.  Personality  and  consciousness 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  45 

were  sacrificed  to  an  impersonal  end.  Plato  recon 
ciled  tlie  interests  of  man  to  the  order  of  nature,  but  he 
partly  lost  sight  of  the  anthropological  point  of  view 
in  getting  his  position.  Consequently  there  was  a  tend 
ency  in  his  system  to  asceticism  and  mysticism  which  led 
to  the  doctrine  of  absorption. 

Perhaps  we  should  be  told  that  his  doctrine  of  immor 
tality  recognized  the  worth  of  the  individual  and  supple 
mented  the  tendencies  of  the  system  to  sacrifice  man  to 
the  whole.  But  the  reply  is  that  there  is  no  better  proof 
of  the  subordination  of  the  individual  to  an  end  not  him 
self  than  Plato's  conception  of  immortality.  This  theory 
may  be  very  fine  to  those  who  imagine  that  it  has  any 
resemblance  to  the  Christian  idea  of  it.  Words  are  too 
often  a  source  of  illusion  and  deception  to  those  who  do 
not  take  the  trouble  to  go  deeper,  and  if  they  can  only 
enlist  the  support  of  philosophic  language  they  are  con 
tent  to  live  under  a  delusion.  But  Plato  never  dreamed 
of  a  personal  survival  after  death.  Such  a  thing  as  the 
retention  of  personal  identity  after  the  dissolution  of  the 
body,  the  continuity  of  consciousness  in  all  time,  was  as 
absurd,  or  at  least  as  discredited  a  possibility  with  him 
as  with  the  materialists  whom  he  criticized.  There  was 
no  resemblance  between  the  Christian  and  the  Platonic 
immortality.  So  far  as  the  consciousness  of  the  past  is 
concerned  Plato's  conception  was  in  sympathy  with  the 
materialists.  But  the  substance  of  the  soul,  the  subject 
of  consciousness  survived,  the  present  personal  stream  of 
mental  events  not  being  a  part  of  its  essence  or  essential 
activity,  as  it  was  conceived  after  the  teaching  of  Chris 
tianity  on  the  one  hand  and  Cartesian  philosophy  on  the 
other.  This  soul  or  substance  of  mind  could  pass  into 
any  other  embodiment  and  continue  another  life,  upward 
or  downward  according  to  its  nature,  just  as  the  atom 


46  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

can  pass  from  one  form  of  combination  to  another  in 
modern  and  ancient  physics  without  destruction.  But 
no  consciousness  of  its  past  is  at  all  necessary  to  this 
continuance.  Such  a  conception  involves  the  most  tre 
mendous  self-sacrifice  on  the  part  of  any  man  who  should 
regulate  his  conduct  in  reference  to  his  soul's  future  in 
which  present  consciousness  could  not  participate  by 
way  of  memory  and  personal  identity.  To  restrain  pas 
sion  and  impulse  in  order  that  my  soul  may  not  pass  into 
a  brute  form  where  I  should  never  know  the  degrada 
tion,  is  not  a  conception  of  immortality  that  would  suc 
ceed  in  prompting  many  to  virtue,  more  especially  a 
Christian.  There  is  scarcely  any  parallel  to  the  demand 
on  unselfishness  which  is  implied  in  the  Platonic  idea  of 
immortality,  and  hence  again  we  find  in  this  very  feature 
of  his  philosophy  the  most  radical  and  far-reaching  con 
ception  of  the  subordination  of  the  individual  to  the 
order  of  the  cosmos  which  any  one  can  imagine.  Plato, 
of  course,  was  hardly  conscious  of  this  way  of  stating  his 
position,  because  the  distinction  between  the  selfish 
and  unselfish,  the  egoistic  and  altruistic,  conception  of 
life  was  not  yet  drawn,  and  could  hardly  have  been 
drawn  at  his  time.  Greek  philosophy  was  too  monistic 
to  conceive  any  antagonism  between  man  and  nature, 
between  the  individual  and  society.  The  interests  of  the 
individual  and  of  the  whole  were  conceived  by  Socrates 
and  Plato  as  the  same.  This,  of  course,  is  true  ideally 
but  not  really,  and  the  average  Greek  was  the  last  to  act 
up  to  such  a  doctrine  even  when  the  philosophic  trend  of 
his  time  forced  the  conviction  of  such  a  unity  upon  him. 
It  required  the  dualism  of  Christianity  and  Cartesianism 
to  develop  the  opposition  between  man  and  nature  into 
formal  recognition,  placing  the  greatest  value  upon  the 
individual,  and  with  it  the  duty  to  respect  one's  neighbor 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  47 

as   one's   self,    the  very    condition    of    preserving  any 
morality  at  all,   because  dualism  or  pluralism  tends  to 
establish  the  same  opposition    between  individuals    as 
between  man  and  nature,  and  in  order  to  save   ethics 
must  place  the  stress  of  morality  upon  making  man,  or 
others,  ends  in  themselves  in  lieu  of  insisting  upon  the 
identity  of  their  interests.     But  the  method  of  reconciling 
the  individual  and  the  whole  by  self-sacrifice,  consciously 
affirmed  and   formulated    as  above   duty   to  self,   does 
not  appear  in  Plato,  and  least  of  all  in    his  conception 
of  immortality,  in  which  the  associations  of  the   term 
affected  by  later  history  connect  it  with  the  notion  of 
personal  survival,  while  the  idea  of  regulating  conduct 
with  reference  to  the  destiny  of  a   being  in  whose  life 
no  connection  with  the  conscious  past  of  the  soul  surviv 
ing  is  to  be  found  makes  a  demand  upon  unselfishness 
which  few   men   would  venture  to   make  on  the  race, 
especially   upon   an   average   Greek   who   was   a    good 
embodiment  of  the  idea  taught  by  the  Manchester  school 
of  political  economists.     But  Plato  makes  it,  and  in  his 
conception  returns  in  a  different  phraseology  to  that  sac 
rifice  of  the  individual    which   had   characterized   the 
cosmological   type  of    thought.      The    peculiarity   and 
sublimity  of  the  demand  lies  in  the  fact  that  the_sacrifice 
has  to  be  made  without  a  personal  and  individual  interest 
in  its  object.     In  Christianity  the  demand  for  sacrifice  in 
behalf  of  others  was  attended  with  an  individual  interest 
in  the  consequences  of  it.     That  is  to  say,  Christianity 
combined  individualism  and  altruism  in  a  way  to  secure 
a  general  hearing.     Plato  demanded  the  sacrifice  with 
out  satisfying  individual  interest,    and   hence  his   idea 
of  immortality  cannot  be  considered  as  favoring  the  posi 
tion  that  man  is  an  end  to  himself. 

But  Plato  shows  none  of  the  nightmare  of  terror  which 


48 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 


troubled  the  average  Greek  when  he  reflected  upon  such 
a  fate,  or  such  a  sacrifice  as  this  doctrine  involved.  Plato 
was  above  all  a  philosopher  and  had  learned  to  reconcile 
himself  to  fact,  to  accept  the  judgment  of  his  intellect  in 
regard  to  the  law  of  nature  as  reflecting  what  is  best  for 
the  will.  Hence  his  reconciliation  was  not  that  of  a  man 
bent  on  obstinately  displaying  his  courage  against  adverse 
fortune,  standing  like  an  Athanasius  contra  mundum,  or 
a  Stoic  dying  joyfully  on  a  funeral  pyre,  but  it  was 
that  of  a  man  who  denied  the  opposition  of  nature  to  his 
real  welfare  and  loved  it  for  its  beauty  and  harmony. 
He  did  not  quarrel  with  Fate,  because  he  saw  in  the 
world's  order  a  type  of  action  to  be  imitated,  and  a 
beauty  and  goodness  to  be  worshiped.  Hence  rebellion 
had  no  temptations  for  him  as  it  had  for  the  individ 
ualist  who,  emancipated  from  the  tyranny  of  the  gods 
and  princes,  set  up  his  own  will  as  the  only  thing  to  be 
satisfied  in  the  world.  Plato  loved  what  his  intellect 
told  him  was  the  good,  and  had  no  temptations  which 
had  kept  his  race  between  the  terror  of  the  gods  and  the 
anarchy  of  libertinism.  Consequently  he  was  the  first 
of  the  philosophers  who  both  in  his  person  and  his 
philosophy  substituted  respect  for  fear  of  the  law  as  the 
condition  of  virtue  and  of  attaining  the  good  which  is 
the  same  in  man  as  in  nature. 

But  Plato  had  his  philosophic  difficulties  nevertheless. 
Ha-found  it  jj^stmggla-for  the__average  man  to  realize  the 
ther  there  was  a  harmonybetween^man  and 
lature  or  not.     His  problemwas  not  completely~&Qlved 
•pointed 

was  a_fac±  to  be  reckoned 
iization 


u 


EMERSON  ON  PLATO. 

"  In  Plato  you  explore  modern  Europe  in  its  causes 
and  seed — all  that  in  thought  which  the  history  of 
Europe  embodies  or  has  yet  to  embody.  The  well  in 
formed  man  finds  himself  anticipated — Plato  is  up 
with  him  too.  Nothing  has  escaped  him.  Every  new 
crop  in  the  fertile  harvest  of  reform,  every  fresh  sug 
gestion  of  modern  humanity  is  there.  Why  should 
not  young  men  be  educated  on  this  book  f  It  would 
suffice  for  the  tuition  of  the  race — to  test  the  under 
standing  and  to  express  the  reason.  Who  can  over 
estimate  the  images  with  which  Plato  has  enriched  the 
minds  of  men,  and  which  pass  like  bullion  in  the  cur 
rency  of  all  nations  ?  Read  the  Ph<zdo,  the  Protago 
ras,  the  Phczdrus,  the  Timczus,  the  Republic  and  the 

Apology  of  Socrates. 

Emersotfs  Essay  on  Books 


PLATO. 

B.  C.  427  to  347. 
Prom  Stanley's  History. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  49 

lind  to  seek  this  orood  and  to  make  the  sacrifices  neces- 


mn      o  se 

*v^-«^  ___ 

sartcTrea 


j-~- 

problem  was  easy,  but 
the'  practical  one  was  j^ery  jIifferent__^heEormeriad 


the 


will    and    secure   itejermanent_adhesipn 
Finding  in  man  a  hieraTcTij"ofconflictinJg 
to^evilflie  had  ^g^HTscoveFa^way  jtp_ 
contr^Fthem,  to  reduce  them^EO"SuB5iissiiiT  oTTo  direct 
will    toward 


for    accom- 
whosefunctionifc'^was  to 


te 

plistjiing  this~e 

establish 


objective  reasoii 
The   passions   were  blind 


of  action  without 
were  calculated  "to  turn 


Lo  a  carnival_of  debauch, 
curbing  their  caprices  lay  in   the 
regujjitiyj^o^  it  couTdrlufnTsh 

no^m^ive^p>gwej^j^  insigaXTand   directFye 

ideasv  impulse. having  to^gacrificejts  natural  and  immedi: 
ate  object  for  the  good  which  reason  discovered.  In 
his  conception,  therefore,  the  natural  passions  did  not 
have  the  good  for  their  end,  and  though  they  remained 
the  motive  efficient  of  the  action  suggested  by  reason, 
their  natural  object  had  to  be  wholly  sacrificed  in  the 
attainment  of  the  rational  ideal.  Here  we  see  the  ascetic 
type  of  philosopher  in  Plato,  and  it  is  the  ground  of  the 
sympathy  of  Christianity  with  his  system.  -^[n_his  view 
virtue  or  the  good  could  only  be  attained  bjr  heroic 
the^  sublime  though  repressive  restraints 
hermit,  sa^g^nc%nrite7^r^martyr.  ^"o 
quarter  walTTxTbe  given  toimputse-rrr  natural  desire  in 
the  ideal  world.  A  merciless  and  rigid  asceticism  was 
the  only  sure  way  to  the  paradise  of  the  ideal.  We  find 
in  the  ISTeoplatonist  the  logical  outcome  of  this  doctrine, 
a  hatred  of  the  things  of  sense  that  turns  into  a  morbid 


50  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

and  maudlin  antipathy  against  the  world  that  hardly 
comports  with  the  philosophic  calm  and  admiration  of 
nature.  It  is  true  that  the  Neoplatonist  only  carried  into 
his  ethics  Plato's  doctrine  of  matter  as  representing  his 
metaphysics  of  the  cosmos  and  its  depreciation  of  the 
things  of  sense,  showing  the  reductio  absurdum  of  both 
metaphysics  and  ethics  which  neither  completed  its 
evolution  nor  found  its  recoil  in  Plato,  because  his 
esthetic  instincts  on  the  one  hand  and  his  political 
enthusiasm  on  the  other  were  adequate  restraints  upon 
pessimism  and  philosophic  insanity. 

It  was  the  fact  that  Plato  was  a  healthy  human  being, 
coupled  with  the  present  prospect  that  Greece  would 
remain  upon  the  high  level  of  her  accomplished  civiliza 
tion,  that  prevented  his  own  action  from  being  an  absurd 
concession  to  the  popular  idea  of  logic  in  the  inter 
pretation  of  his  doctrine,  or  a  rush  of  despair  into  the 
transcendental  as  the  only  escape  of  a  noble  mind  from 
the  vices  of  a  dying  world.  His  nature  and  insight  were 
proof  against  abstract  logic,  and  however  rigid  might  be 
his  theory  in  its  conception  of  the  opposition  between 
the  life  of  sense  and  the  life  of  reason,  as  alternatives,  no 
one  knew  better  than  he  the  limitations  under  which  it 
was  applicable.  This  is  strikingly  reflected  in  his  composi 
tion  of  the  "  Laws  "  after  he  had  written  the  "  Republic." 
He  knew  the  conditions  under  which  human  nature  had 
to  exist  and  work,  and  his  own  conduct,  because  of  a 
healthy  and  balanced  nature,  reflected  the  necessary  con 
cessions  to  sense  in  the  world  as  we  find  it,  though  he 
did  not  find  it  ideal.  Plato  enjoyed  a  banquet  as  well 
as  any  one,  but  he  enjoyed  the  philosophic  ecstasy  still 
more,  and  he  constructed  his  ideal  world  of  opposition  to 
sensuous  pleasures  as  the  only  clear  way  of  getting  virtue 
appreciated  at  all,  especially  by  a  race  that  was  little 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  51 

disposed  to  transcend  the  world  of  sense  for  its  ideals,  as 
is  shown  by  its  art.  He  probably  saw  that  it  was  strength 
of  will  in  Socrates  rather  than  knowledge  or  insight  that 
secured  him  the  virtue  he  loved,  and  "  sizing  up  "  the  aver 
age  Greek  of  his  day  as  a  possible  or  probable  debauchee,he 
told  his  fellow  men  who  had  weaker  wills  than  Socrates 
that  they  could  not  see  or  realize  the  glory  of  the  true, 
the  beautiful,  and  the  good  until  they  had  gained  com 
plete  control  of  a  sensuous  life.  Every  reformer  has  to 
tell  the  victim  of  vice  that  he  has  no  hope  of  salvation 
except  in  total  abstinence.  Not  because  it  is  necessarily 
wrong  to  gratify  sense  at  all,  but  because  the  individual 
once  addicted  to  intemperance  must  exhibit  a  weaker 
will  when  the  slightest  concession  is  made  to  temptation 
than  when  he  absolutely  rejects  its  solicitations.  This 
antithesis  between  pleasure  and  the  good  thus  becomes  a 
necessary  practical  device  for  securing  moral  strength  of 
will,  whatever  be  its  theoretical  defects  in  a  world  other 
than  the  present  one :  and  hence  what  was  to  Plato  a  practi 
cal  means  for  securing  both  a  vision  and  a  realization  of 
virtue  in  a  people  too  much  committed  to  the  worship 
of  sense  easily  assumed  the  coloring  of  asceticism, 
especially  in  an  age  when  the  political  ideals  of  Athens 
were  sacrificed  to  the  conservatism  of  Sparta  and  the 
ambition  of  Macedonia. 

It  would  take  too  much  time  to  examine  the  "  Republic  " 
and  all  that  it  means  for  a  true  estimate  of  Plato's  genius. 
Among  our  every -day  men  of  the  world  it  is  called  an 
ideal  and  impractical  scheme,  a  brilliant  dream  of  a  noble 
but  impossible  mind,  repeated  from  age  to  age,  as  the 
OivitasDei  of  Augustine,  More's  "Utopia,"  Bacon's  "New 
Atlantis,"  or  even  Mr.  Bellamy's  "Looking  Backward." 
But  this  whole  characterization  of  it  with  the  insinuation 
that  it  is  a  visionary  idealism  and  representative  of  just 


52  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

about  what  the  public  may  expect  of  a  philosopher,  spinning 
fancies  out  of  his  contemplative  moods,  is  not  wholly  fair  to 
Plato.  Most  sensible  readers  of  it  will  find  little  idealism 
in  it,  and  nothing  Utopian,  as  those  terms  are  under 
stood,  though  it  may  be  only  a  difference  of  ideals  that 
makes  us  hesitate  to  apply  these  terms  to  it.  But  whether 
ideal  or  not,  the  scheme  was  communistic  and  socialistic, 
and  in  respect  of  both  the  family  and  the  individual  runs 
directly  counter  to  all  that  evolution  has  produced  in  the 
course  of  later  history.  But  in  spite  of  such  provisions 
and  of  its  assumption  of  Hobbe's  state  of  perpetual  war 
(not  a  very  ideal  condition  for  Utopia  in  our  idea  of  it), 
the  "  Kepublic  "  is  not  to  be  condemned  by  men  who  have 
never  studied  it  with  care  and  who  have  not  caught  the 
fundamental  principle  that  lay  at  the  basis  of  it.  Plato 
was  undoubtedly  hampered,  as  all  men  are,  by  the  con 
crete  conceptions  of  his  time  in  the  attempt  to  give  form 
and  body  to  his  ideas,  but  his  ideal  of  good  government 
was  not  much,  if  any,  different  from  our  own.  The  fii 
man  in  the  Jit  place  was  the  maxim  upon  .which  he  built. 
He  thoroughly  believed  in  the  doctrine  of  Carlyle,  that 
"  the  tools  should  belong  to  him  who  can  handle  them," 
and  we  to-day  after  more  than  one  hundred  years  of  repub 
lican  institutions  are  just  learning  the  value  of  applying 
this  principle  to  the  civil  service.  The  "  Kepublic  "  is  only 
a  treatise  on  civil  service  reform.  The  conduct  of  men 
like  Alcibiades  was  a  justification  of  Plato's  intentions. 
We  may  not  be  satisfied  with  the  means  by  which  he 
would  secure  an  ideal  government,  namely,  the  selection 
of  aristocratic  philosophers  for  our  rulers,  and  we  may 
perceive  more  readily  than  he  the  limitations  of  environ 
ment  under  which  all  reconstructions  of  society  must  be 
made,  but  if  we  lay  too  much  emphasis  upon  this  defect 
we  shall  forget  the  crucial  principle  upon  which  all  good 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  53 

government  must  rest,  namely,  the  intelligence  and  disinter 
estedness  of  its  riders.  Mr.  Pater  calls  attention  to  this 
feature  of  Plato's  doctrine,  and  it  explains  why  Plato 
chose  philosophers  for  his  ideal  kings. 

Philosophers  may  not  be  a  very  practical  tribe  to-day. 
They  are  supposed,  at  least  by  the  general  public  and 
so-called  practical  men,  to  be  a  class  of  idealists  who  are 
forever  playing  with  purely  abstract  conceptions,  and  this 
is  often  the  case.  But  in  Plato's  time  and  before  him  they 
were  all-round  .men  of  knowledge.  They  were  intellec 
tually  and  morally  the  best  men  in  the  community.  We 
have  seen  that  it  was  the  philosopher  that  had  overcome 
the  terrors  of  Fate  and  counseled  a  life  of  calm  respectful 
obedience  to  the  inflexible  laws  of  nature.  Everywhere 
about  them  the  common  people  were  steeped  in  ignorance 
and  showed  no  disinterestedness  even  toward  nature,  much 
less  toward  their  fellow  men,  while  their  lives  were  a  con 
stant  moral  panic  in  the  presence  of  both  nature  and  the 
gods.  The  philosophers,  however,  had  not  only  attained 
a  superior  knowledge  of  nature,  but  had  also  acquired 
that  disinterested  temper  of  mind  and  will  which  can  sup 
press  individualistic  passions  and  interests  identified  with 
the  moment,  and  maintain  a  far-reaching  insight  and  calm 
faith  in  the  ultimate  beneficence  of  nature  and  justice. 
Hence  with  their  habits  of  will,  on  the  one  hand,  involv 
ing  the  sacrifice  of  libertine  desires,  and  their  superior 
knowledge,  on  the  other,  involving  a  comprehensive  view 
of  nature  and  man,  it  was  only  natural  that  Plato  should 
look  to  them  for  ideal  prophets,  priests,  and  kings ;  if 
only  we  refer  to  the  arrogance  and  self-conceit  of  our 
modern  politicians  who  so  unanimously  laugh  at  the  far 
sightedness  of  the  more  intelligent  classes,  we  shall  obtain 
abundant  confirmation  of  Plato's  insight  into  the  social 
need  of  every  age  for  the  intelligent  and  disinterested  man 


54  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

to  guide  its  destiny,  though  we  have  not  yet  found,  any 
more  than  Plato,  the  proper  way  to  secure  his  services. 
Moreover  both  the  existence  of  the  "  Laws "  and  an 
occasional  sense  of  humor  and  idealistic  weakness  con 
sciously  recognized  even  in  the  "  Eepublic  "  itself  show  that 
Plato  was  building  for  a  world  that  he  did  not  expect  to 
realize,  and  so  was  trying,  as  he  did  for  the  individual  in 
the  sacrifice  of  the  passions  to  the  reason,  to  present  for 
the  ruler  an  ideal  which  might  stir  the  conscience  of  his 
country,  and  to  demand  of  its  aristocracy,  duties  as  well 
as  privileges. 

Aristotle  shows  a  wholly  different  type  of  intellect  from 
that  of  his  master.  He  is  more  rigidly  scientific.  He  is 
almost,  if  not  absolutely,  without  an  esthetic  sense,  and 
never  indulges  in  humor.  Plato  was  a  typical  Greek  in 
his  esthetic  appreciation,  while  he  had  as  keen  a  sense  of 
humor,  though  it  was  lofty  and  refined,  as  any  laughter- 
loving  man  could  demand.  Aristotle  had  neither  time 
nor  taste  for  the  pleasantries  of  life,  but  was  serious  in 
temperament,  though  not  puritanical,  and  eliminating  the 
sentimental  and  emotional  from  his  reflections  he  made  him 
self  severely  scientific  in  his  study  of  philosophicalproblems, 
so  that  when  we  come  to  read  him  we  miss  the  literary  charm, 
the  delicate  touch  of  humor,  and  the  brilliant  play  of  imagi 
nation  and  figure  that  confer  immortality  upon  Plato,  even 
when  much  of  his  philosophy  seems  unintelligible  or  absurd. 
But  if  we  lose  these  characteristics  when  we  come  to  the 
disciple,  we  gain  in  thoroughn^.  j  and  clearness  of  psycho 
logical  analysis  and  limitation  to  facts  for  knowledge  and 
the  regulation  of  conduct.  This  fact  must  be  appreciated 
by  an  age  which  especially  admires  scientific  method  and 
the  severe  elimination  of  literary  embellishment  and  padding 
from  the  discussion  of  profound  philosophic  problems, 
and  emotional  interests  from  the  determination  of  truth. 


ARISTOTLE, 

AFTER  THE  STATUE  IN  THE  SPADA  PALACE,  ROME 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  55 

Plato  never  separated  metaphysics  from  ethics,  but 
Aristotle  makes  this  separation  the  first  step  in  his 
procedure.  He  does  not  say  that  this  is  a  necessary  condi 
tion  of  his  system,  nor  does  he  discuss  such  a  problem  as 
their  relation.  He  simply  writes  on  ethical  science  with 
out  alluding  to  metaphysics  at  all.  One  might  imagine 
that  he  had  no  interest  in  this  recondite  subject,  or  that 
he  knew  nothing  about  it,  if  we  had  to  judge  him  by  his 
treatise  on  ethics  alone.  But  the  fact  is  that  no  one  in 
antiquity  wrote  a  more  elaborate  and  profound  system  of 
metaphysics  than  Aristotle,  and  we  can  wonder  how  he 
could  indulge  his  sense  of  the  unity  of  science  when  he 
came  to  deal  with  the  theory  of  morality. 

The  explanation  of  the  peculiarity  just  mentioned  is 
the  fact  that  Aristotle  was  a  true  Socratic  in  ethics  with 
out  sharing  the  contempt  which  Socrates  had  for  specu 
lative  philosophy.  He  realized  that,  whatever  man  had 
to  consider  in  adjusting  his  conduct  to  cosmic  law,  he 
must  find  in  himself  the  spring  to  this  adjustment  and 
the  benefit  that  was  to  accrue  from  it,  and  not  condition 
the  practical  rules  of  life  upon  some  prior  system  of 
reflective  philosophy  which  should  be  the  result  and  not 
the  determinant  of  a  moral  life.  Not  that  Aristotle 
would  deny  a  reflex  influence  from  speculative  doctrine 
upon  ethics,  or  a  value  for  practical  conduct  in  meta 
physical  theories,  but  only  that  both  ethical  science  and 
much  of  practical  action  are  not  dependent  upon  a  prior 
philosophic  system  of  the  external  universe.  Perhaps 
his  sense  of  the  unity  between  man  and  nature  was 
stronger  than  that  of  the  Greeks  generally,  so  that  in  tacitly 
abandoning  the  dualism  of  Plato  he  had  no  occasion  to 
determine  morality  by  the  transcendental  goal  which  the 
cosmos  reserves  for  man's  pursuit  Hence,  though  he 
recognized  the  necessity  of  metaphysics  as  the  completion 


56  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

of  man's  Knowledge,  the  unity  between  man  and  nature 
made  it  unnecessary  to  condition  ethics,  at  least  of  a  prac 
tical  kind,  and  this  was  largely  all  that  he  sought,  upon 
a  previously  constructed  system  of  metaphysics.  In  this 
method  he  in  reality  followed  the  spirit  of  Socrates, 
though  he  had  emancipated  himself  from  the  contempt 
which  Socrates  entertained  for  cosmic  knowledge. 

The  first  step,  therefore,  which  Aristotle  takes  in  the 
discussion  of  the  ethical  problem  is  to  show  that  all  moral 
action  is  determined  wholly  by  reference  to  the  end,  or 
the  object  at  which  the  will  aims,  the  rzXoS  of  volition. 
lie  would  admit  that  the  object  of  nature  and  that  of  the 
human  will  ought  to  be  the  same,  but  he  would,  like  Soc 
rates,  turn  the  mind  to  self-reflection  for  its  determination 
of  this  object  rather  than  first  deciding  the  purpose  of 
nature,  as  in  Plato.  Hence  he  says  absolutely  nothing 
about  cosrnological,  theological,  or  conventional  theories, 
but  rises  at  once  into  heights  superior  to  all  of  them,  while 
at  the  same  time  asserting  a  criterion  of  ethical  conduct 
which  can,  in  its  first  power  at  least,  be  determined  within 
the  limits  of  the  individual  consciousness.  Socrates  and 
Plato,  by  emphasizing  human  ignorance  as  the  great  sin, 
practically  left  the  impression  that  it  was  what  men  did 
not  know  that  determined  the  good  or  virtue,  but 
Aristotle,  by  putting  the  stress  upon  the  end  of  volitions, 
limited  morality  to  what  man  could  be  conscious  of.  In 
all  of  them  it  was  an  object  to  be  known  that  determined 
virtue,  but  in  the  former  the  knowledge  of  the  object  was 
all  that  was  necessary,  while  in  the  latter  the  intention  was 
the  main  desideratum.  In  this  last  conception  ignorance 
of  the  means  played  a  minor  part  in  virtue,  so  that  virtue 
became  a  quality  of  will  rather  than,  or  as  well  as,  knowl 
edge.  Consequently  the  initial  basis  of  ethics  with 
Aristotle  took  on  a  scientific  form.  If  cosmological  and 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  57 

theological  or  conventional  theories  are  to  obtain  any 
standing  after  such  an  enunciation  of  principles,  it  will  be 
on  the  condition  that  their  norm  be  capable  of  interpretation 
as  an  end  related  to  human  welfare  and  volition,  and  not 
either  a  blind  limitation  of  man  s  liberty,  the  passive  sub 
mission  to  external  law,  or  the  non-purposive  action  that 
may  happen  to  realize  objective  good.  The  criterion  of 
Aristotle  is  first  subjective,  that  is,  determinable  by  human 
consciousness,  and  then  if  objective  forces  have  their 
resultants  expressible  as  possible  ends  of  volition,  they  have 
a  recognizable  place  in  ethics.  But  they  cannot  otherwise 
obtain  it,  and  we  are  left  with  the  broad  universal  princi 
ple  that  the  final  determinant  of  moral  action,  whether  the 
expression  of  divine  or  human  agencies,  must  be  an  end, 
or  object  aimed  at,  the  quality  of  conduct  being  thus 
determined  by  the  will  rather  than  by  the  intellect  alone. 
The  law  of  nature,  the  will  of  the  gods,  or  the  decrees  of 
political  authority  and  convention  have  no  meaning  or 
relevancy  in  this  conception  unless  they  recognize  ends 
applicable  to  the  volitions  of  the  subject  upon  which 
they  are  binding.  Aristotle's  predecessors  would  have 
admitted  as  much  had  this  analysis  been  presented  to  them. 
But  they  were  so  bent  upon  emphasizing  the  importance 
of  speculative  knowledge  that  they  consciously  or 
unconsciously  concealed  the  place  which  the  will  and 
intentions  had  in  morality. 

But  Aristotle  is  not  on  this  account  individualistic  in  his 
conception  of  ethics.  He  recognizes,  implicitly  or  explicitly, 
that  the  ethical  postulate  must  be  within  the  reach  of 
scientific  method,  and  thus  be  an  object  of  purposive 
intelligent  consciousness  which  he  finds  in  the  individual 
man.  But  lie  does  not  thereby  exclude  from  this 
object  the  idea  that  it  shall  be  an  extra-personal  fact.  His 
most  general  principle,  affirmed  or  implied,  is  that,  whatever 


58  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

it  is,  it  must  be  conceived  as  an  end  to  the  being  who  is  to 
realize  it,  and  who  is  to  be  responsible  for  it  only  as 
intending  it.  The  individual  supplies  the  knowledge  and 
the  initiative,  and  receives  the  praise  or  blame,  or,  in  other 
words,  has  moral  responsibility  apportioned  according  to 
the  intention  and  not  according  to  consequences  beyond  the 
ken  of  consciousness.  This,  of  course,  is  not  the  language 
of  Aristotle,  but  it  is  the  meaning  of  his  conception  of 
morality,  in  which  he  terminates  before  he  completes 
his  analysis.  The  individualistic  element,  therefore,  in 
his  system,  though  not  egoistic  in  its  intention,  is  found 
in  the  part  which  the  subject  must  play  in  the  recognition 
and  initiation  of  the  end,  which  last  is  not  limited  to  a 
subjective  result,  though  always  consistent  with  it,  as  con 
ceived  by  Socrates.  This  extra-personal  element  he 
recognizes  in  the  end  of  action  when  lie  comes  to  define  it, 
and  he  thus  transcends  the  individualism  of  the  sophists 
who  never  admitted  an  extra-personal  element  at  all. 
Aristotle  does  not  define  the  end  as  pleasure  (rfdovff),  nor 
as  comformity  to  nature,  to  convention,  or  to  the  will  of 
the  gods,  but  as  welfare  (fydai  juovia),  which  is  sometimes 
translated  as  happiness,  but  which  ought  to  be  translated 
a  well-ordered  condition  of  being,  or  a  well-organized  and 
disposed  state  of  functions.  Perhaps  the  conception 
can  be  best  expressed,  at  least  approximately,  by  the 
modern  term  perfection,  which  would  mean  for  Aristotle 
the  proper  condition  of  being  for  a  healthy  and  harmonious 
exercise  of  functions.  This  idea  not  only  takes  him 
beyond  the  individualistic  hedonism  of  the  sophistic  school, 
because  pleasure  is  not  the  only  end  for  action,  but 
repeats  in  a  psychological  form  that  which  had  been  given 
a  metaphysical  and  cosmological  meaning  -in  Plato.  Plato 
recognized  an  extra- personal  end  to  which  the  individual 
was  sacrificed,  as  we  have  seen,  but  it  was  not  so  clearly 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  59 

reconciled  with  personal  good  as  was  the  conception  of 
his  disciple.  Aristotle,  however,  in  choosing  welfare,  or 
perfection,  interpreted  as  the  ideal  condition  of  organic 
beings,  prepared  the  way  for  the  recognition  of  others  as 
ends  in  themselves,  instead  of  their  being  mere  means  to 
a  personal  end,  as  in  Socrates,  or  means  to  an  impersonal 
end,  as  in  Plato.  This  perfection  could  be  either 
or  both  personal  and  extra-personal.  Moreover,  inas 
much  as  the  end  recognized  by  Aristotle  was  not  a 
transient  feeling  like  pleasure,  it  reinstates  Plato's  con 
ception  of  reality  or  permanence  as  the  moral  object  of 
volition,  though  it  is  made  personal  in  the  disciple,  while 
it  was  impersonal  in  the  master.  I  mean  by  personal,  of 
course,  a  condition  in  man  himself.  Hence  Aristotle 
simply  gives  personal  meaning  to  the  Platonic  reality. 

This  conception  of  welfare  took  Aristotle  directly  away 
from  the  asceticism  of  Plato.     Welfare  demanded  some 
concessions  to  sensuous  objects  ;   the  life  of  pure  reason 
did  not.     With   Plato   reason   furnished   the  object  of 
action,  and  passion  the  motive  power.     With  Aristotle 
passion  might  furnish  an  object  as  well  as  motive,  while 
reason  could  furnish  also  an  object  of  its  own,  but  never 
any  motive,  though  it  was  always  the  only  guide  to  the 
rational,  whether  in  the  domain  of  sense  or  other  func 
tions.     Hence,  instead  of  sacrificing  the  desires  to  obtain 
morality,  Aristotle  granted   them   a   legitimate   field  of 
activity  and  merely  subordinated  their  gratification  to  the 
o,ir^macy  Of  reasoiL    Plato  also  insisted  upon  the  suprem- 
of  reason,  but  it  was  a  supremacy  based  upon  the 
il  of  all  moral  rights  to  desire.     With  Aristotle  its 
emacy  was  consistent  with  a  legitimate  function  for 
•e.     Instead,   therefore,    of   subordinating  the   indi- 
al   to   the  whole  by  requiring  some  transcendental 
ition  like  the  moral  order  of  the  universe  as  we  found 


60  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

it  in  Plato,  we  see  in  Aristotle  that  concessions  are  made 
to  the  ends  of  sense,  and  the  ideals  of  the  concrete  man. 
Though  Aristotle  made  a  contemplative  life  the  highest 
ideal,  this  being  for  the  Greeks  of  that  time  a  speculative 
or  philosophic,  as  we  should  now  call  it  a  scientific,  voca 
tion,  he  admitted  moral  possibilities  below  this  height 
He  allowed  the  natural  functions  of  man  to  determine  an 
object  for  volition,  and  simply  required  that  their  proper 
action  be  regulated  by  reason,  whereas  we  should  say 
conscience,  giving  it  both  cognitive  and  motive  power. 
In  this  concession  to  the  desires  we  see  that  Aristotle  did 
not  require  the  inrmorkilj^  of  the  soul,  a  transcendental 
survival  from  the  toils  of  our  prison  house,  in  order  to 
realize  morality,  though  this  view  did  not  antagonize  or 
deny  the  value  of  an  ideal  world  beyond  the  grave.  The 
virtue  of  Aristotle  lay  in  volition,  not  in  the  object 
attained  by  it,  though  the  good  might  lie  beyond  the 
action  in  which  virtue  was  realized.  With  Plato,  as  we 
found,  virtue  was  realized  in  the  conscious  attainment  of 
the  good  which  lay  beyond  mere  action  and  the  will.  But 
with  virtue  consisting  in  the  intention  and  the  good  in 
some  realizable  perfection  of  the  subject  within  the  limits 
of  actual  existence,  Aristotle  reinstates  the  value  of  the 
individual  which  his  master  had  sacrificed,  and  in  doing 
so  he  lays  the  foundation  for  opposition  to  both  the 
socialism  and  the  pantheism  of  Plato,  and  finds  an  escape 
from  the  temptation  to  build  ideal  republics,  supported 
upon  the  immolation  of  their  citizens.  But  after  the  saner 
attempt  of  Plato  in  the  "  Laws,"  he  constructs  his  theory  of 
governmental  institutions  with  greater  reference  to  indi 
vidual  development  as  well  as  to  the  conditions  of  human 
nature,  and  his  work  in  this  direction  has  remained  monu 
mental 

The  simple  principle  that  determined  the  whole  result 


Elhic.s  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  61 

of  his  thought,  in  politics  as  well  as  ethics,  was  the  doc 
trine  of  the  mean  (yutcror^S'),  as  it  was  called.  Armed 
with  Plato's  conception  of  reason  regulating  passion,  and 
with  the  universal  Greek  notion  of  moderation,  the 
jj,rj6ev  ayav,  "nothing  overmuch,"  Aristotle  con 
ceded  desire  not  only  a  legitimate  but  an  ethical  func 
tion,  provided  its  satisfaction  observed  a  mean  between 
excess  and  deficiency,  and  thus  placed  himself  upon  ter 
restrial  ground  in  his  doctrine  of  morality,  though  not 
displacing  the  ideal  that  might  require  a  transcendental 
world  for  its  realization.  He  thus  became  the  sanest  and 
healthiest  type  of  the  Greek  philosophers,  at  least  in  his 
scientific  conception  of  the  ethical  problem,  whatever  we 
may  think  of  the  practical  difficulties  involved  in  the 
concession  to  the  appetites,  which,  as  Plato  saw,  could  be 
more  easily  controlled  by  abstinence  than  by  moderation. 
But  with  all  such  practical  obstacles  to  its  application 
without  insight  and  common  sense,  Aristotle's  position 
has  the  merit  of  theoretical  accuracy,  and  of  boldness  in 
recognizing  that  man  must  construct  his  ethical  ideals 
within  the  limits  of  realizable  human  ends,  and  that  he 
should-  not  run  after  will-o'-the-wisps  in  impossible 
worlds.  He  saw  that  the  conditions  of  man's  present  life 
luid  to  be  satisfied,  whatever  the  hereafter  might  be,  and 
rightly  regulated ;  that  conscience  has  for  its  object  and 
duty  the  restraint  of  passion  and  the  direction  of  higher 
desires  instead  of  moaning  over  the  limitations  of  sense 
and  longing  for  release  from  the  body  in  order  to  gain 
the  reward  of  virtue.  Thus  the  doctrine  of  the  mean 
kept  Aristotle  in  the  world  of  real  life  while  it  allowed 
for  any  ideal  condition  that  might  come  within  the  ken 
of  knowledge. 

Other  doctrines  can  only  receive  mention,  as  carrying  the 
analysis  of  ethical  problems  farther  than  his  predecessors. 


62  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

By  the  distinction  between  intellectual  or  natural  and 
moral  or  acquired  virtues  (excellences)  Aristotle  escaped 
the  paradoxes  of  Socrates  and  Plato  about  the  identity 
of  virtue  and  knowledge,  and  the  question  whether 
virtue  could  be  taught.  _Aristotle,l  at  least  in  effect, 
maintained  that  the  natural  virtues  or  excellences 
were  constitutional  perfections  in  the  individual,  while 
the  moral  virtues  were  the  direct  product  of  the  will. 
Consequently  he  was  enabled  to  maintain  against  his 
masters  the  voluntary  nature  of  vice,  and  ever  since  his 
time  the  term  "  virtue  "  has  denoted  only  a  quality  of 
will,  except  in  those  survivals  which  speak  of  the  "  vir 
tues  "  of  medicine,  etc.  His  outline  of  freedom  and 
responsibility,  the  distinction  between  the  two  ideas  not 
being  explicitly  drawn,  can  hardly  be  surpassed  by  any 
modern  writer.  His  conception  of,  moral^irtue,  the  term 
moral  being  tautological  to  us  owing  to  Aristotle's  own 
influence,  was  that  of  a  confirmed  habit  of  will,  not  any 
fortuitously  capricious  motive.  This  view  was  a  natural 
consequence  of  the  general  conception  of  virtue  as  an 
excellence  of  any  kind  in  which  it  was  most  easily  con 
ceived  as  constitutional  and  static.  Hence  an  individual 
act  which  did  not  represent  a  habit,  no  matter  what  the 
motive,  could  not  be  called  a  "virtue,'1  though  the 
Aristotelian  distinction  between  natural  and  acquired 
excellence  finally  led  to  the  recognition  of  even  individual 
acts  as  morally  good,  and  character  came  to  stand  for  the 
fixed  nature  of  the  will  which  makes  it  "virtuous."  But 
Aristotle's  idea  conceived  moral  merit  as  a  quality  of  the 
subject  indicating  some  inner  fixity  of  character,  and 
thus  to  some  extent  anticipated  the  position  of  Kant,  who 
insisted  that  morality  essentially  consists  in  the  idea  of 
law,  both  as  an  imperative  and  as  uniformity  of  action. 
Aristotle,  of  course,  did  not  recognize  the  notion  of  an 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  63 

imperative,  but  he  did  remark  the  idea  of  uniformity 
which  puts  the  "  virtue  "  in  the  will,  whatever  merit  we 
may  come  to  assign  to  the  volition  itself. 

Aristotle's  treatment  of  the  particular  virtues  is  coldly 
analytical,  somewhat  uninteresting  to  the  modern  mind, 
and  is  carried  out  along  the  line  of  his  principle  ;  namely, 
the  mean  between  excess  and  deficiency  in  the  gratifica 
tion  of  impulse.  No  special  importance  for  us  attaches 
to  this  part  of  his  work,  except  the  length  of  the  discus 
sion  on  friendship,  which,  with  the  fact  that  quite  as 
much  attention  was  given  to  it  by  Plato,  raises  the  ques- 
'tion  whether  it  does  not  indicate  the  conscious  necessity 
for  emphasis  by  the  moralists  of  the  time  upon  some  of 
the  social  virtues  as  a  counter- influence  to  the  naturally 
egoistic  tendencies  of  Greek  life. 

When  it  comes  finally  to  a  summary  of  the  influence 
which  Socrates,  Plato,  and  Aristotle  exercised  upon 
modern  ethical  doctrines  there  is  an  interesting  and  com 
plicated  problem  to  solve.  Each  of  these  philosophers 
appeals  to  a  different  type  of  mind.  It  was  the  person 
ality  of  Socrates  that  gave  him  an  influence  upon  after 
ages  more  than  his  method ;  for  this  latter  had  to  be 
developed  by  other  hands  before  its  usefulness  could  be 
appreciated.  His  strength  of  will  and  martyrdom  for  his 
convictions  made  him,  as  in  the  case  of  all  men  like  him, 
the  center  of  interest  for  that  class  of  hero-worshipers  who 
like  moral  courage  better  than  mere  intellectual  insight, 
and  example  better  than  precept  Plato,  on  the  other 
hand,  is  attractive  to  all  speculative  minds  of  a  mystical 
sort  and  who  delight  in  transcendental  conceptions,  the 
airy  visionary  universe  of  pure  thought,  demanding  those 
empyrean  flights  of  fancy  which  justify  the  description  of 
metaphysics  as  the  poetry  of  reasW.  Over  these  Plato 
exercises  an  influence  bordedj^on  enchantment,  and 


64  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

scarcely  any  man  with  philosophic,  literary,  and  humane 
instincts  of  any  kind  can  escape  the  magical  charm  which 
he  inspires.  Aristotle,  however,  is  the  antithesis  of  this. 
He  was  to  some  extent  the  moral  contrast  of  Socrates  and 
the  intellectual  contrast  of  Plato.  He  was  the  embodi 
ment  of  the  strictly  scientific  mind,  too  prudent  to  die  for 
the  sake  of  obstinacy,  as  his  flight  from  Athens  to  avoid 
a  second  disgrace  to  philosophy  very  well  shows,  and  too 
critical  to  indulge  in  poetical  metaphysics.  His  moral 
ideals  involved  no  sacrifices  like  those  of  Socrates,  and 
his  philosophy  no  passion  like  that  of  Plato.  He  was 
coldly  critical  and  scientific  in  method  and  temperament, 
poised  equally  between  the  two  extremes  of  moral  enthu 
siasm  and  speculative  idealism.  He  is  the  philosopher  of 
/acfe,  an  example  and  the  hero  of  those  who  ask  no  favors 
of  the  universe  but  to  know  the  truth,  and  no  transcen 
dental  world  to  stimulate  the  inspiration  and  hopes  of 
their  morality.  The  general  influence  of  all  of  them, 
however,  lies  in  the  spirit  of  reflective  thinking  which 
they  cultivated.  This  has  not  thrown  much  light  on 
modern  practical  issues,  but  only  upon  the  theoretical 
basis  of  morality.  Whatever  has  been  required  for  solv 
ing  the  perplexities  of  theoretical  ethics  has  received  its 
impulse  from  this  school  of  thinkers.  They  furnish  the 
dry  light  of  reason  in  the  determination  of  what  morality 
is  and  means,  but  none  of  the  warmth  of  feeling  and 
motive  power  which  practical  life  demands,  and  though 
this  fact  is  no  discredit  to  the  work  of  scientific  analysis, 
which  is  always  important,  it  indicates  the  limitations  of 
Greek  speculation.  Insight  and  truth  are  of  primary 
importance,  though  ineffective  without  power.  Greek 
consciousness  was  almost  wholly  scientific  curiosity, 
even  when  it  toucl^L  upon  the  moral  issues  of  life, 
and  the  shadows  of  ijj^aggerated  worship  of  reason 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  65 

still  extend  over  all  countries  that  have  been  molded  by 
its  culture. 

To  measure  its  value,  however,  by  its  inefficiency  upon 
moral  life  in  individual  cases  is  to  mistake  both  its 
nature  and  its  mission,  though  such  an  accusation  of  its 
defects  would  be  a  pertinent  criticism  against  those  who 
identified  knowledge  and  virtue.  But  to  him  who  had 
distinguished,  as  Aristotle  had  done,  between  the  specula 
tive  efforts  of  the  intellect  and  the  moral  impulses  and 
products  of  the  will,  it  was  only  a  recognition  of  individ 
ual  responsibility  for  practical  results  to  maintain  that 
philosophy  only  furnished  enlightenment  and  not  moral 
character.  Reason  could  point  out  the  path  of  rectitude, 
but  it  could  not  impel  a  man  to  take  it,  except  at  the 
expense  of  that  freedom  which  is  as  dear  to  the  moralist 
and  philosopher  as  knowledge  can  be.  The  intellect  could 
supply  the  truth,  but  the  will  had  to  supply  the  moral 
impulse.  Nevertheless,  the  distance  between  light  and 
power  is  a  short  one,  and  the  whole  intellectual  momen 
tum  of  Greek  thought,  though  circumscribed  by  the 
horizon  of  mere  knowledge  or  wisdom,  expended  its  illu 
minating  power  upon  the  speculative  ideals  of  truth, 
beauty,  and  courage,  and  halted  only  at  the  limits  of  that 
moral  enthusiasm  which  characterized  the  impulse  of 
Christianity.  Plato  and  Aristotle  were  the  highest 
development  of  this  tendency,  though  they  represent  the 
obverse  and  reverse  sides  of  human  genius,  both  in 
regard  to  the  accomplishments  and  the  spiritual  influence 
of  speculative  thought.  Plato  was  the  idealist,  and 
Aristotle  was  the  realist.  The  one  lived  in  the  transcen 
dental  world  of  abstractions,  and  gained  possession  of 
human  aspirations  by  directing  them  into  the  fairy-land  of 
ideals;  the  other  remained  in  the  empirical  world  of  con 
crete  facts,  actual  reality  which  chastened  the  speculative 


66  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.   • 

impulses  of  reason  by  counseling  the  lessons  of  humility. 
If  philosophy  ever  betrays  her  genius  in  her  incarna 
tions,  the  characteristics  thus  described  are  even  reflected 
in  the  creations  which  sculpture  has  brought  down  to  us  of 
these  two  men.  Plato  appears  with  his  broad  and  elevated 
brow,  cheerful  countenance,  and  speculative  eye  looking 
dreamily  into  the  great  infinite  of  invisible  existence,  and 
with  ecstatic  vision  keeping  watch  over  the  gates  of 
immortality  and  God,  as  if  he  could  utter  the  language  of 
Tennyson's  "  Ulysses  "  : 

Yet  all  experience  is  an  arcb  where  through 
Gleams  that  untraveled  world  whose  margin  fades 
Forever  and  forever  as  we  more. 

But  Aristotle  with  frigid,  resolute,  and  drawn  features, 
as  if  repressing  the  temptations  of  fancy,  looks  straight 
into  nature,  and  having  no  purpose, 

To  sail  beyond  the  sunset,  and  the  baths 
Of  all  the  western  stars, 

sternly  represents  man's  messenger  of  fact  within  the 
limits  of  reality.  For  him  the  abstractions  of  time  and 
eternity  have  no  fascination,  and  he  will  follow  no  will- 
o'-the-wisps  into  the  bogs  of  transcendentalism.  But 
making  the  real  not  so  bad,  and  the  ideal  not  so  fine  as 
IJlato,  he  circumscribes  the  objects  of  duty  by  the  world 
of  .scientific  facts,  and  hence  the  main  virtue  which  his 
philosophy  was  calculated  to  inspire  was  that  of  every 
truly  scientific  mind  ;  namely,  the  courage  to  disenchant 
the  will  of  its  demoniac  passion  for  aspirations  which 
neglect  the  most  important  duties  of  actual  life,  and  hence 
to  reconcile  desire  to  the  limitations  of  the  world  He 
knew,  to  appropriate  the  language  of  Carlyle  in  reference 
to  Mt.  Vesuvius,  that  "  the  earth,  green  as  she  looks,  rests 
everywhere  on  dread  foundations  were  we  further  down, 
and  Pan,  to  whose  music  the  nymphs  dance,  has  a  cry  in 


"Pythagoras  was  eminently  a  practical  person,  the 
founder  of  a  school  of  ascetics  and  socialists,  a  planter 
of  colonies,  and  nowise  a  man  of  abstract  studies 
alone" 

Emerson's  Essay  on  "Books" 


PYTHAGORAS, 


500  B.  C. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  67 

him  that  can  drive  all  men  distracted  "  :  and  hence,  as  in 
such  conditions  every  man  must  choose  between  bravery 
and  death,  the  resources  of  virtue  must  lie  in  the  cultiva 
tion  of  knowledge  and  a  resolute  obedience  to  the  laws 
of  nature.  But  Aristotle  also  knew  that  nature  had  her 
compensations  for  the  man  whose  moral  consciousness,  like 
that  of  the  Stoic,  gathers  its  impulses  from  courage  and 
reverence  for  the  actual  world,  and  fearless  of  fate, 
serenely  assaults  the  illusions  which  one  finds  in  the  real 
and  the  other  in  the  ideal.  He  found  both  in  nature,  and 
his  cairn  scientific  spirit,  with  something  of  the  vindictive 
austerity  of  Stoicism  and  the  brave  humility  of  Spinoza, 
demands  of  human  life 

One  equal  temper  of  heroic  hearts, 

Made  weak  by  time  and  fate,  but  strong  in  will 

To  strive,  to  seek,  to  find  and  not  to  yield. 

The  passing  of  the  gods  under  the  aegis  of  skepticism 
may  be  marked  by  a  shadow,  and  hope  may  be  frustrated 
for  a  moment  by  the  loss  of  its  previous  ideals,  but  the 
recovery  of  self-possession  and  the  consciousness  that  life 
offers  its  best  rewards  to  him  who  respects  facts  bring 
with  them  the  "  everlasting  yea  "  of  Carlyle,  the  light  of 
truth  and  the  power  of  virtue  to  shed  their  luster  over 
the  speculations  both  of  history  and  of  hope. 

JAMES  H.  HYSLOP. 

Columbia  University. 


PYTHAGORAS  AND  HIS  SCHOOL. 

PYTHAGORAS  was  one  of  the  greatest,  if  not  the 
greatest  philosopher  preceding  the  age  of  Socrates  and 
Plato,  and  had  a  deep  influence  on  their  thought.  He 
traveled  over  most  of  the  known  world  to  study  the 
wisdom  of  its  sages  and  is  presumed  to  have  learned 
much  from  the  Brahmans  of  India,  the  Priests  of 
Chaldea  and  Egypt,  and  the  Magi  of  Persia,  and  he  lived 
for  many  years  in  Babylon  and  Egypt  before  returning 
to  Greece  and  Italy. 

He  established  most  extensive  religious  or  monastic 
orders  throughout  Greece,  Italy,  and  other  Mediterranean 
countries  which  in  discipline  and  doctrine  closely  re 
sembled  the  early  Hindoo  and  later  Christian  orders. 
For  example,  they  practiced  abstinence  from  animal 
foods,  and  also,  strange  as  it  may  seem,  from  beans.  They 
also  observed  celibacy,  avoided  bloody  sacrifices,  used  a 
special  dress  and  believed  in  the  reincarnation  of  souls, 
like  the  Hindoo  and  Buddhist  orders,  and  counselled  a 
life  of  great  purity  and  moderation. 

Pythagoras  seems  not  only  to  have  been  a  world- 
student  of  Religion,  Ethics  and  Philosophy,  but  also  a 
great  Moral  Reformer  and  Cosmic  Philosopher,  as  well 
as  an  able  Politician.  His  religious  confraternities  of 
men  and  women  became  so  numerous  and  powerful  in 
Greece  and  Italy,  and  of  such  intellectual  and  political 
influence,  that  they  were  considered  a  menace  to  the 

(68) 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers,  69 

state,  and  were  finally  suppressed  as  dangerous  to  it, 
just  as  in  a  similar  way  Christian  religious  orders  have 
been  suppressed  in  some  European  States  in  modern 
times. 

Pythagoras  was  also  believed  by  his  followers  to  be 
more  than  human,  or  actually  divine,  a  son  of  Apollo, 
through  a  miraculous  or  divine  conception  by  his 
mother,  and  thus  an  incarnation  of  God  in  human  form. 
And  it  is  also  related  of  him  that  he  rose  from  the  dead 
after  a  long  burial. 

These  ideas  of  human  deification  or  divine  incarnation 
were,  however,  not  unusual  in  the  beliefs,  mythologies 
or  legends  of  the  Mediterranean  and  Oriental  races  be 
fore  the  time  of  Christ.  And  the  same  idea  of  divine 
incarnation  was  indeed  also  applied  to  Plato,  and  of 
course  many  of  the  Greek  and  Roman  rulers  were  actu 
ally  declared  to  be  incarnations  of  God  and  reverenced 
as  divine,  for  example,  Alexander  the  Great,  Nero,  and 
others. 

The  common  belief  held  by  the  Mediterranean  and 
Oriental  races  in  the  pre-existence  and  eternal  nature  of 
the  soul  and  its  repeated  rebirths  or  reincarnations,  to 
gether  with  the  general  belief  in  the  multiple  personality 
of  God,  as  shown  by  their  Polytheistic  and  Henotheistic 
conceptions,  as  well  as  the  popular  belief  in  the  close 
personal  relations  existing  between  Gods  and  men — and 
women  too — led  to  the  easy  adoption  of  this  doctrine 
of  miraculous  conception  and  divine  incarnations,  as 
one  of  the  most  simple  and  natural  mental  results 
under  the  circumstances.  And  it  is  therefore  not  to 
be  wondered  at  that  teachers  of  such  unusual  mental 
and  moral  power  as  Pythagoras  and  Plato,  and  of  such 
deep  and  wide  influence  among  men,  should  come  to  be 
regarded  as  superhuman  in  nature  and  divinely  engen- 


yo  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

dered  in  origin  where  such  mystic  religious  ideas  were 
commonly  held.* 

With  regard  to  the  conception  of  God  held  commonly 
in  the  Pagan  world,  it  is  interesting  to  note  that  Prof. 
James,  the  great  religious  philosopher  of  Harvard  Uni 
versity  and  a  deep  student  of  ancient  philosophic  con 
ceptions,  in  his  recent  notable  work,  "  Varieties  of  Re 
ligious  Experience,"  seems  to  make  the  remarkable  ad 
mission  that  he  considers  it  rational  to  conceive  God  either 
as  "  pluralistic "  or  as  "one  and  only."  This  is  practically 
the  conception  of  God  held  by  the  great  philosophic 
Pagans  among  the  Hindoos,  Chaldeans,  Egyptians, 
Greeks  and  Romans,  who  considered  God  as  existing  in 
many  manifestations  or  personifications,  such  as  Jupiter, 
Minerva,  Neptune,  Vesta,  &c.,  or  their  equivalents,  but 
that  these  pluralistic  personifications  or  manifestations 
were  really  to  be  considered  as  all  one  in  unison.  Now 
many  things  in  unity  is  obviously  a  better  conception  of 
God  than  mere  "oneness"  in  itself:  And  we  think  it 
must  also  be  admitted  that  "Allness"  is  a  better  concep 
tion  of  Infinity  and  Omnipotence  than  mere  oneness, 
and  "  Allness"  certainly  involves  the  conception  of  multi 
tude  primarily  and  unity  or  oneness  secondarily.  The 
"All  in  All"  or  The  Completeness  of  Everything  are  cer 
tainly  good  conceptions  of  God,  at  least  in  the  Pan 
theistic  sense;  and  all  Theism  necessarily  involves  more 
or  less  Pantheism,  so  that  we  therefore  think  it  is  logic 
ally  indisputable  to  say  with  Prof.  James  and  the  old 
Pagans,  that  it  is  rationally  admissible  to  conceive  God 
either  as  "pluralistic"  or  as  "one."  At  all  events,  the 
Christian  conception  of  multi-personifications  in  unity 

*  The  Rev.  Lyman  Abbott  in  a  serious  address  to  the  students  of  Yale  College 
some  time  ago,  made  a  most  remarkable  statement  in  referring  to  the  Christian 
doctrine  of  Incarnation.  He  stated  that  he  sometimes  wondered  if  the  Church 
really  believed  that  doctrine,  and  if  he  really  believed  it  himself,  but  he  was 
certain  on  one  point,  that  it  was  easier  to  believe  that  God  could  produce  such 
a  mystery,  than  that  men  could  have  invented  it.  And  this  peculiar  state 
ment  would  seem  to  imply  that  men  had  never  believed  or  ' '  invented  "  this 
doctrine  before  the  Christian  Era  ! 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  71 

is  much  nearer  to  the  conceptions  common  to  the  philo 
sophic  Pagans  than  it  is  to  the  simple  uncompromising 
monotheism  of  the  Jewish  and  Mohammedan  worlds 
who  have  so  persistently  rejected  the  Christian  creed, 
whereas  the  Greek,  Latin,  Coptic,  Celtic,  and  Teutonic 
races  who  were  used  to  a  multi  or  pluralistic  conception, 
are  practically  the  only  races  who  have  ever  adopted 
that  creed. 

The  Pythagorean  conception  of  God  and  the  soul  is 
briefly  described  in  the  following  paragraphs,  which  we 
take  from  Stanley's  History  of  Philosophy,  1701. — Ed. 
PYTHAGOREAN  CONCEPTION  OF  GOD. 

Pythagoras  denned  what  God  is,  thus,  A  mind  which 
commeateth  and  is  diffused  through  every  part  of  the 
world  and  through  all  nature,  and  from  whom  all  ani 
mals  that  are  produced  receive  life. 

God  is  one.  He  is  not  (as  some  conceive)  out  of  the 
world,  but  entire  within  Himself,  in  a  complete  circle 
surveying  all  generations.  He  is  the  temperament  of 
all  ages,  the  agent  of  His  own  powers  and  works,  the 
principle  of  all  things,  one,  in  heavenly  luminary,  and 
Father  of  all  things ;  mind  and  animation  of  the  whole, 
the  motion  of  all  circles. 

God  (as  Pythagoras  learned  of  the  Magi,  who  term 
Him  Oromasdes)  in  His  body  resembles  light,  in  His 
soul,  truth. 

He  said  that  God  only  is  wise. 

He  conceiveth  that  the  first  (being)  God,  is  neither 
sensible  nor  passible,  but  invisible  and  intelligible. 

Next  to  the  Supreme  God,  there  are  three  kinds  of  in- 
telligibles,  gods,  daemons,  heroes.  That  Pythagoras  thus 
distinguished  them,  is  manifest  from  his  precept,  that 
we  must  in  worship  prefer  gods  before  daemons,  heroes 
before  men:  But  in  Jamblichus,  he  seems  either  to  ob 
serve  a  different  method,  or  to  confound  the  terms: 


72  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

teaching  first  of  gods,  then  of  heroes,  last  of  daemons ; 

which  order  perhaps  is  the  same  with  that  of  the  Golden 

Verses, 

First,  as  decreed,  th'  immortal  gods  adore 
Thy  oath  keep  ;  next  great  heroes,  then  implore 
Terrestrial  daemons  with  due  sacrifice. 

By  terrestrial  daemons  seems  to  be  understood  (not 
princes,  as  Hierocles,  but)  the  daemons  themselves,  con 
fined  to  several  offices  upon  earth ;  for 

All  the  air  is  full  of  souls,  which  are  esteemed  daemons 
and  heroes;  from  these  are  sent  to  men  dreams  and 
presages  of  sickness  and  of  health ;  and  not  only  to  men, 
but  to  sheep  also,  and  to  other  cattle:  to  these  certain 
expiations  and  averrunciations,  and  all  divinations, 
cledons,  and  the  like. 

All  the  parts  of  the  world  above  the  moon  are  gov 
erned  according  to  Providence  and  firm  order,  and  the 
decree  of  God,  which  they  follow,  but  those  beneath  the 
moon  by  four  causes  :  by  God,  by  fate,  by  our  election, 
by  fortune.  For  instance,  to  go  aboard  into  a  ship  or 
not,  is  in  our  power  :  storms  and  tempests  to  arise  out  of 
calm  is  by  fortune :  for  the  ship  being  under  water  to  be 
preserved,  is  by  the  providence  of  God.  Of  fate,  there 
are  many  manners  and  differences,  it  differs  from  fortune, 
as  having  a  determination,  order  and  consequence  but 
fortune  is  spontaneous  and  casual,  as  to  proceed  from  a 
boy  to  a  youth,  and  orderly  to  pass  through  the  other 
degrees  of  age  happens  by  one  manner  of  fate. 

Man  is  of  affinity  with  the  gods,  by  reason  that  he 
participates  of  heat,  wherefore  God  hath  a  providential 
care  of  us.  There  is  also  a  fate  of  all  things  in  general 
and  in  particular,  the  cause  of  their  administration. 

In  Pythagoras  his  definition  of  the  soul  is  a  self-mov 
ing  number,  Plutarch  saith,  he  takes  number  for  mind. 
The  mind  is  induced  into  the  soul,  ab  extrinseco,  from 
without,  by  divine  participation,  delibated  of  the  Uni 
versal  Divine  Mind.  For  there  is  a  soul  intent  and 
commeant  through  the  whole  nature  of  things,  from 
which  our  souls  are  plucked.  She  is  immortal,  because 
that  from  which  she  is  taken  is  immortal ;  yet  not  a  God, 
but  the  work  of  the  eternal  God.  Thus  Pythagoras  ex- 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  73 

ceedingly  confirmed  the  opinion  of  his  master  Pherecides, 
who  first  taught,  that  the  souls  of  men  are  sempiternal. 

The  soul  hath  a  twofold  life,  separate  and  in  the  body  ; 
her  faculties  are  otherwise  in  anima,  otherwise  in  animali. 

The  soul  is  incorruptible ;  for  when  it  goes  out  of  the 
body,  it  goes  to  the  soul  of  the  world,  which  is  of  the 
same  kind.* 

When  she  goeth  out  upon  the  earth,  she  walketh  in 
the  air  like  a  body.  Mercury  is  the  keeper  of  souls,  he 
brings  souls  out  of  bodies  in  the  earth  and  the  sea ;  of 
which,  those  that  are  pure,  he  leadeth  into  an  high  place ; 
the  impure  come  not  to  them,  nor  to  one  another,  but 
are  bound  by  the  Furies  in  indissoluble  chains. 

A  summary  of  the  Pythagoric  Doctrine  is  extant  in 
verse,  entitled,  the  Golden  Verses  of  Pythagoras ;  or  as 
others  say,  of  the  Pythagoreans.  For  that,  saith  Hiero- 
cles,  as  gold  is  the  best  and  purest  of  metals,  so  these 
are  the  best  and  most  divine  of  verses. 

THE  GOLDEN  VERSES  OF  PYTHAGORAS. 

First,  in  their  ranks,  the  Immortal  Gods  adore. 
Thy  oath  keep  ;  next,  great  Heroes  ;  then  implore 
Terrestrial  Daemons  with  due  sacrifice. 
Thy  parents  reverence,  and  near  allies  ; 
Him  that  is  first  in  virtue  make  thy  friend, 
And  with  observance  his  kind  speech  attend  ; 
Nor  (to  thy  power)  for  light  faults  cast  him  by, 
Thy  pow'r  is  neighbor  to  necessity. 

These  know,  and  with  intentive  care  pursue  ; 
But  anger,  sloth,  and  luxury  subdue. 

In  sight  of  others  or  thy  self  forbear 
What's  ill ;  but  of  thyself  stand  most  in  fear. 
Let  Justice  all  thy  words  and  actions  sway  : 
Nor  from  the  even  course  of  Reason  stray  : 
For  know,  that  all  men  are  to  die  ordain'd, 
And  riches  are  as  quickly  lost  as  gain'd. 
Crosses  that  happen  by  divine  decree, 
(If  such  thy  lot)  bear  not  impatiently. 
Yet  seek  to  remedy  with  all  thy  care, 
And  think  the  just  have  not  the  greatest  share. 
'Mongst  men,  discourses  good  and  bad  are  spread, 
Despise  not  those,  nor  be  by  these  misled. 
If  any  some  notorious  falsehood  say, 
Thou  the  report  with  equal  judgment  weigh. 

*  This  idea  seems  to  be  identical  with  the  Platonic  and  Buddhistic  concep 
tions  of  soul.— Ed. 


74  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

Let  not  men's  smoother  promises  invite, 

Nor  rougher  threats  from  just  resolves  thee  fright. 

If  ought  thou  shouldst  attempt,  first  ponder  it ; 

Fools  only  inconsiderate  acts  commit ; 

Nor  do  what  afterwards  thou  mayest  repent ; 

First  learn  to  know  the  thing  on  which  th'  art  bent. 

Thus  thou  a  life  shalt  lead  with  joy  replete. 

Nor  must  thou  care  of  outward  health  forget. 
Such  temp'rance  use  in  exercise  and  diet, 
As  may  preserve  thee  in  a  settled  quiet. 
Meats  unprohibited,  not  curious,  choose  ; 
Decline  what  any  other  may  accuse. 
The  rash  expense  of  vanity  detest, 
And  sordidness  :  A  mean  in  all  is  best. 
Hurt  not  thyself;  Before  thou  act,  advise  ; 
Nor  suffer  sleep  at  night  to  close  thine  eyes, 
Till  thrice  thy  acts  that  day  thou  hast  o'errun, 
How  slipt,  what  deeds,  what  duty  left  undone  ? 
Thus  thy  account  summ'd  up  from  first  to  last, 
Grieve  for  the  ill,  joy  for  what  good  hath  past. 

These  study,  practice  these,  and  these  affect ; 
To  sacred  virtue  these  thy  steps  direct. 
Eternal  Nature's  fountain  I  attest, 
Who  the  Tetractis  on  our  souls  imprest. 
Before  thy  mind  thou  to  this  study  bend, 
Invoke  the  Gods  to  grant  it  a  good  end. 
These  if  thy  labour  vanquish,  thou  shalt  then 
Know  the  connexure  both  of  Gods  and  men  ; 
How  everything  proceeds,  or  by  what  staid, 
And  know  (as  far  as  fit  to  be  survey'd) 
Nature  alike  throughout ;  that  thou  mayest  learn 
Not  to  hope  hopeless  things,  but  all  discern  ; 
And  know  those  wretches  whose  perverser  wills 
Draw  down  upon  their  head  spontaneous  ills  ; 
Unto  the  good  that's  nigh  them,  deaf  and  blind  : 
Some  few  the  cure  of  these  misfortunes  find. 
This  only  is  the  Fate  that  harms,  and  rolls, 
Through  miseries  successive,  human  souls. 
Within  is  a  continual  hidden  fight 
Which  we  to  shun  must  study,  not  excite. 
Great  Jove  !  how  little  trouble  should  we  know, 
If  thou  to  all  men  wouldst  their  genius  show  ! 
But  fear  not  thou  ;  men  come  of  heav'nly  race, 
Taught  by  diviner  Nature  what  t'  embrace  : 
Which  if  pursu'd,  thou  all  I  nam'd  shall  gain, 
And  keep  thy  soul  clear  from  thy  body's  stain. 
In  time  of  Pray'r  and  cleansing,  meat's  deni'd 
Abstain  from  :  thy  mind's  reins  let  reason  guide  : 
Then,  strip'd  of  flesh,  up  to  free  yEther  soar, 
A  deathless  God,  Divine,  mortal  no  more. 


APPENDIX. 


EXTRACTS  FROM  WORKS 


PLATO  AND  ARISTOTLE. 


ILLUSTRATING  THE  ETHICS  OF  THE  GREEK  PHILOSO 
PHERS,  SOCRATES,  PLATO  AND  ARISTOTLE. 


APPENDIX. 


EXPLANATORY   NOTE. 

These  extracts  are  taken  from  the  following  English 
works : — 

Jowett's  Translation  of  Plato's  Works,  published  by 
Chas.  Scribner's  Sons,  1889. 

Jowett's  Politics  of  Aristotle,  Oxford  Edition,  Claren 
don  Press,  1885. 

Aristotle's  Niomachean  Ethics,  Peter's  Translation. 

Aristotle's  History  of  Animals,  Cresswell's  Translation, 
Bohn  Edition. 

Aristotle's  Metaphysics. 

The  paragraphs  quoted  in  these  extracts  are  all  given 
exactly  as  they  appear  in  the  translations,  but  not  al 
ways  in  complete  continuity,  that  is,  for  purpose  of  con 
densation  many  intervening  clauses  between  several  of 
the  paragraphs  in  the  original  have  been  omitted  in  our 
extracts  as  being  irrelevant  or  redundant  or  obscure. 
The  places  where  such  omissions  have  been  made  have 
not  been  indicated  in  our  text,  for  the  sake  of  smoother 
appearance  and  easier  reading,  and  the  quotations  have 
thus  been  printed  by  us  as  if  they  were  continuous  or 
uninterupted  from  the  original,  but  we  have  been  always 
careful  in  our  selection  and  arrangement  of  the  quota 
tions  that  the  omitted  phrases  do  not  affect  the  sense 
and  context  which  has  been  everywhere  carefully  pre 
served  by  a  juxtaposition  and  succession  substantially 

as  it  is  in  the  original. 

(74b) 


APPENDIX. 


CONTENTS. 

Extracts  from  Socrates,  Plato  and  Aristotle,  with 
Notes  and  Comments  illustrating  the  correspondence 
of  ancient  and  modern  thought. 

EXTRACTS  FROM  PLATO. 

PAGE 

1.  The  Supreme  God  or  Creator  and  His  Creation  of 

the  Universe. •        75 

2.  Great  Antiquity  of  Egypt,  and  her  early  influence  on 

ancient  Greece.     Tale  of  "  The  Lost  Atlantis."  82 

3.  The  Principle  of  Universal  Beneficent  Love.       From 

Plato's  Symposium.  .        .        .        .        .        .        88 

4.  Agathon  and  Socrates  on  Love 91 

5.  Plato  and  St.  Paul  paralleled  in  Hymn  to  Love.      Paul 

in  i  Cor.  13  (A.  D.  57).    Compared  with  Agathon 

in  the  Symposium,  B.  C  416.  ....  102 

6.  The  Golden  Rule.    From  Plato's  Laws,  400  B.  C.        .  106 

7.  Return  not  evil  for  evil.    Socrates'  answer  to  Crito.  109 

8.  Good,  not  Pleasure,  the  supreme  aim  of  Conduct.      .  in 

9.  Suicide  Condemned.     Socrates  in  the  Phaedo.       .         .  112 
10.    A  virtuous  life,  fearless  death,  and  glorious  hereafter 

commended  to  all  men.  .         •        .        .        .       114 

n.    The  soul's  improvement,  not  worldly  success,  the  true 

aim  of  man's  life.      .        .        .        ,        .        .        .116 

12.  The  true  life,  the  life  of  the  soul,  not  of  the  world 

or  the  body.    Socrates  in  the  Phaedo.     .        .        .118 

13.  Death  is  a  good  and  not  an  evil.     Socrates  in  the 

the  Apology I2o 

14.  The  Immortality  of  the  Soul  and  its  future  rewards 

and  punishments.     Socrates  in  the  Phaedo.          .       122 

15.  Best  texts  from  the  Old  Testament  on   Immortality 

as  compared  to  Plato's  Phaedo 130 

16.  The  Doctrine  of  Purgatory— Pagan  and  Christian.     .       135 

17.  Reincarnation. 138 

(74c) 


CONTENTS.  ^-CONTINUED. 

PAGB 

18.  Mind  inheres  in  and  rules  the  universe.          .        .        .       141 

19.  The  Greek  Conception  of  Soul  and   Deity.     A  Prime 

Mover  or  Force,  which  is  Self-Moved.      .       .        .  144 

20.  The  Universal  Soul. 145 

21.  The  Platonic  Doctrine  of  Ideas 147 

22.  The  Socratic  Utilitarian  Theory  of  Ethics.      .  157 

23.  Socrates  the  Father  of  Modern  Utilitarian  Ethics.        .  168 

24.  Influence  of  Socrates  on  Aristotle  and  Epicurus  and 

the  substantial  identity  of  their  ethical  do&rines.        169 

25.  The   Hedonistic  School  of  Aristippus— the  false  Epi 

curean  and  perverter  of  Socratic  Doctrine.          .        172 

26.  Harmony  of  Herbert  Spencer  with  the  Socratic  School 

of  Ethics.  .  .  176 

27.  Socratic  and  Theistic  Ethics — a  comparison  of  the 

Utilitarian  and  the  Theistic  Theories  of  Ethics.  179 

EXTRACTS  FROM  ARISTOTLE. 

28.  Aristotle  on  the  Idea  of  God.  .        .        .        .        .182 

29.  Aristotle  on  the  Theory  of  Evolution.     ....       186 

30.  Abstract  of  Aristotle's  Theory  of  Ethics.       .        .        .       193 

ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS. 

31.  The  fundamental  nature  of  a  political  state  or  govern 

ment.    Status  of  property.    Socialistic  and  Indi 
vidualistic  considered 205 

32.  Citizens    and    States    of   various    kinds    considered. 

The  best  form  of  government  and  the  best  citizen 
discussed. .      210 

33.  The    best   constitution    for   a    state.     Preponderance 

of  the  middle  class  recommended.  .        .        .      231 

34.  Cause  of  Revolutions  Considered.  ....      235 

35.  Democracy  analyzed  and  commended.  .        .        .      243 

36.  The  Best  Life  for  Individuals  and  States        .        .        .251 

37.  Public  Schools  and  Liberal    Education,  Gymnastics, 

Music  and  Morals.  .        .        .        .*  .      272 


THE    SUPREME    GOD     OR    CREATOR    AND    HIS 

CREATION  OF  THE  UNIVERSE. 

FROM  PLATO'S  TIM^US. 

Introductory  Note : — 

A  CCORDING  to  the  latest  Biblical  critics,  the  Book 
f\  of  Genesis  is  a  literary  mosaic  made  up  of  literary 
fragments  of  various  dates  and  authorships,  and  the 
dates  of  its  various  parts  vary  from  about  700  to  400  B.  C. 
Now  it  is  very  interesting  to  here  note  that  the  fol 
lowing  extract  from  Plato,  giving  the  story  of  the  Crea 
tion,  is  not  far  from  being  contemporary  with  Genesis 
itself,  as  it  was  written  about  400  B.  C.  Note  also  the 
reference  to  a  great  deluge  in  the  tale  of  the  lost  Atlantis. 
— C.  M.  H. 

"Let  me  tell  you  then,  why  the  Creator  of  the  world 
generated  and  created  this  universe.  He  was  good,  and 
no  goodness  can  ever  have  any  jealousy  of  anything. 
And  being  free  from  jealousy,  He  desired  that  all  things 
should  be  as  like  Himself  as  possible.  This  is  the  true 
beginning  of  Creation  and  of  the  world,  which  we  shall 
do  well  in  receiving  on  the  testimony  of  wise  men  :  God 
desired  that  all  things  should  be  good  and  nothing  bad 
as  far  as  this  could  be  accomplished. 

(75) 


7  6  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"  Now  that  which  is  created  is  of  necessity  corporeal, 
and  also  visible  and  tangible.  And  nothing  is  visible 
when  there  is  no  fire,  or  tangible  which  is  not  solid,  and 
nothing  is  solid  without  earth.  Wherefore  also,  God  in 
the  beginning  of  creation  made  the  body  of  the  universe 
to  consist  of  fire  and  earth.* 

"  Now  the  Creation  took  up  the  whole  of  each  of  the 
four  elements ;  for  the  Creator  compounded  the  world 
out  of  all  the  fire  and  all  the  water  and  all  the  air  and 
all  the  earth,  leaving  no  part  of  any  of  them  nor  any 
power  of  them  outside.  He  intended,  in  the  first  place, 
that  the  whole  animal  should  be  perfect,  as  far  as  pos 
sible,  and  that  the  parts  of  which  he  was  formed  should 
be  perfect ;  and  that  he  should  be  one,  leaving  no 
remnants  out  of  which  another  such  world  might  be 
created ;  and  also,  that  he  should  be  free  from  old  age 
and  unaffected  by  disease. 

"  Such  was  the  whole  scheme  of  the  eternal  God  about 
the  god  that  was  to  be,  to  whom  He  for  all  these  reasons 
gave  a  body,  smooth,  even,  and  in  every  direction 
equidistant  from  a  centre,  entire  and  perfect,  and  formed 
out  of  perfect  bodies.  And  in  the  centre  He  put  the  soul, 
which  He  diffused  through  the  whole,  and  also  spread 
over  all  the  body  round  about ;  and  He  made  one  solitary 
and  only  heaven  a  circle  moving  in  a  circle,  having  such 
excellence  as  to  be  able  to  hold  converse  with  itself,  and 
needing  no  other  friendship  or  acquaintance.  Having 
these  purposes  in  view  He  created  the  world  to  be  a 
blessed  god. 

"  Now  God  did  not  make  the  soul  after  the  body,  al 
though  we  have  spoken  of  them  in  this  order  ;  for  when 
He  put  them  together  He  would  never  have  allowed  that 
the  elder  should  serve  the  younger,  but  this  is  what  we 

*  "  In  the  beginning  God  created  the  heaven  and  the  earth." 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  77 

say  at  random,  because  we  ourselves  too  are  very  largely 
affected  by  chance.  Whereas  He  made  the  soul  in  origin 
and  excellence  prior  to  and  older  than  the  body,  to  be 
the  ruler  and  mistress,  of  whom  the  body  was  to  be  the 
subject.  And  the  soul  he  made  out  of  the  following 
elements  and  on  this  manner  :  He  took  of  the  unchange 
able  and  indivisible  essence,  and  also  of  the  divisible  and 
corporeal  which  is  generated,  and  He  made  a  third  sort 
of  intermediate  essence  out  of  them*  both,  partaking  of 
the  nature  of  the  same  and  of  the  other,  and  thus  He 
compounded  a  nature  which  was  in  a  mean  between  the 
indivisible  and  the  divisible  and  corporeal.  These  three 
elements  he  took  and  mingled  them  all  in  one  form, 
compressing  the  reluctant  and  unsociable  nature  of  the 
other  into  the  same.  And  when  He  had  mixed  them  with 
the  essence  and  out  of  all  the  three  made  one,  He  again 
divided  this  whole  into  as  many  portions  as  was  fitting, 
eack  of  them  containing  an  admixture  of  the  same  and 
of  the  other  and  of  the  essence. 

"  Now  when  the  Creator  had  framed  the  soul  according 
to  His  will,  He  formed  within  the  mind  the  corporeal  uni 
verse,  and  brought  them  together,  and  united  them  from 
center  to  center.  The  soul,  interfused  everywhere  from 
the  center  to  the  circumference  of  heaven,  of  which  she 
is  the  external  envelopment,  herself  turning  in  herself, 
began  a  divine  beginning  of  never-ceasing  and  rational 
life  enduring  throughout  all  time.  The  body  of  heaven 
is  visible,  but  the  soul  invisible,  and  partakes  of  reason 
and  harmony,  and  being  made  by  the  best  of  intelligible 
and  everlasting  beings,  is  the  best  of  things  created. 

"  When  the  Father  and  Creator  saw  the  image  that  He 
had  made  of  the  eternal  gods  moving  and  living,  he  was 
delighted,  and  in  his  joy  determined  to  make  His  work 
still  more  like  the  pattern  ;  and  as  the  pattern  was  an 


78  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

eternal  creature,  He  sought  to  make  the  universe  the 
same  as  far  as  might  be.  Now  the  nature  of  the  in 
telligible  being  is  eternal,  and  to  bestow  eternity  on  the 
creature  was  wholly  impossible.  But  He  resolved  to 
make  a  moving  image  of  eternity,  and  as  He  set  in  order 
the  heaven  He  made,  this  eternal  image  having  a  motion 
according  to  number,  while  eternity  rested  in  unity ;  and 
this  is  what  we  call  time. 

"  Such  was  the  mind  and  thought  of  God  in  the  creation 
of  time.  And  in  order  to  accomplish  this  creation,  He 
made  the  sun  and  moon  and  five  other  stars,  which  are 
called  the  planets,  to  distinguish  and  preserve  the  num 
bers  of  time,  and  when  God  made  the  bodies  of  these 
several  stars  He  gave  them  orbits  in  the  circle  of  the 
other. 

"  Until  the  creation  of  time,  all  things  had  been  made 
in  the  likeness  of  that  which  was  their  pattern,  but  in 
so  far  as  the  universe  did  not  as  yet  include  within  itself 
all  animals,  there  was  a  difference.  This  defect  the 
Creator  supplied  by  fashioning  them  after  the  nature  of 
the  pattern.  And  as  the  mind  perceives  ideas  or  species 
of  a  certain  nature  and  number  in  the  ideal  animal,  He 
thought  that  this  created  world  ought  to  have  them  of  a 
like  nature  and  number.  There  are  four  such ;  one  of 
them  is  the  heavenly  race  of  the  gods  ;  another,  the  race 
of  birds  moving  in  the  air;  the  third  the  watery  species ; 
and  the  fourth,  the  pedestrian  and  land  animals.  Of  the 
divine,  He  made  the  greater  part  out  of  fire,  that  they 
might  be  the  brightest  and  fairest  to  the  sight,  and  He 
made  them  after  the  likeness  of  the  universe  in  the  form 
of  a  circle,  and  gave  them  to  know  and  follow  the  best, 
distributing  them  over  the  whole  circumference  of  the 
heaven,  which  was  to  be  a  true  cosmos  or  glory  spangled 
with  them. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  79 

"To  tell  of  other  divinities,  and  to  know  their  origin, 
is  beyond  us,  and  we  must  accept  the  traditions  of  the 
men  of  old  time  who  affirm  themselves  to  be  the  off 
spring  of  the  gods,  and  they  must  surely  have  known 
the  truth  about  their  own  ancestors.  How  can  we  doubt 
the  word  of  the  children  of  the  gods  ?  Although  they 
give  no  probable  or  certain  proofs,  still,  as  they  declare 
that  they  are  speaking  of  family  traditions,  we  must  be 
lieve  them  in  accordance  to  the  law.  In  this  manner, 
then,  according  to  them,  the  genealogy  of  these  gods  is 
to  be  received  and  narrated. 

"  Now,  when  all  of  them,  both  those  who  visibly  appear 
in  their  revolutions  as  well  as  those  other  gods  W7ho  are 
of  a  more  retiring  nature,  had  come  into  being,  the 
Creator  of  the  universe  spoke  as  follows  : — 

"  Gods  and  sons  of  gods  who  are  my  works,  and  of 
whom  I  am  the  Artificer  and  Father,  my  creations  are 
indissoluble,  if  so  I  will.  All  that  is  bound  may  be  dis 
solved,  but  only  an  evil  being  would  wish  to  dissolve 
that  which  is  harmonious  and  happy.  And  although 
being  created,  ye  are  not  altogether  immortal  and  indis 
soluble,  ye  shall  certainly  not  be  dissolved,  nor  be  liable 
to  the  fate  of  death  ;  having  in  my  will  a  greater  and 
mightier  bond  than  those  which  bound  you  when  ye 
were  created.  And  now,  listen  to  my  instructions  : 
Three  tribes  of  mortal  beings  remain  to  be  created, — 
without  them  the  universe  will  be  incomplete,  for  it  will 
not  have  in  it  every  kind  of  animal  which  a  perfect 
world  ought  to  have.  On  the  other  hand,  if  they  were 
created  and  received  life  from  me,  they  would  be  on  an 
equality  with  the  gods.  In  order  then  that  there  may 
be  mortals,  and  that  this  universe  may  be  truly  univer 
sal,  do  ye,  according  to  your  natures,  betake  yourselves 
to  the  formation  of  animals,  imitating  the  power  which 


8o  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

I  showed  in  creating  you.  The  divine  and  immortal 
part  of  them,  which  is  the  guiding  principle  of  those 
who  are  willing  to  follow  justice  and  the  gods — of  that 
divine  part  I  will  myself  give  you  the  seed  and  begin 
ning.  And  do  you  then  weave  together  the  mortal  and 
immortal,  and  make  and  beget  living  creatures,  and  give 
them  food,  and  make  them  to  grow,  and  receive  them 
again  in  death.  Thus  He  spake,  and  once  more  and  in 
the  same  manner  poured  the  remains  of  the  elements 
into  the  cup  in  which  he  had  previously  mingled  the 
soul  of  the  universe,  no  longer,  however,  pure  as  before, 
but  diluted  to  the  second  and  third  degree.  And  when 
He  had  framed  the  universe  He  distributed  souls  equal  in 
number  to  the  stars,  and  assigned  each  soul  to  a  star; 
and  having  placed  them  as  in  a  chariot,  He  showed  them 
the  nature  of  the  universe,  and  the  decrees  of  destiny 
appointed  for  them,  and  told  them  that  their  first  birth 
would  be  one  and  the  same  for  all,  and  that  no  one 
should  suffer  at  His  hands ;  and  that  they  must  be  sown 
in  the  vessels  of  the  times  severally  adapted  to  them, 
and  then  there  would  come  forth  the  most  religious  of 
animals ;  and  as  human  nature  was  of  two  kinds,  the 
superior  race  would  hereafter  be  called  man.  Now,  as 
they  were  implanted  in  bodies  by  necessity,  and  objects 
were  always  approaching  or  receding  from  them,  in  the 
first  place  there  was  a  necessity  that  they  should  have 
one  natural  mode  of  perceiving  external  force ;  in  the 
second  place,  they  must  have  love,  which  is  a  mixture 
of  pleasure  and  pain  ;  also  fear  and  anger,  and  the  feel 
ings  which  are  akin  or  opposite  to  them ;  if  they  con 
quered  these  they  would  live  righteously,  and  if  they 
were  unconquered  by  them,  unrighteously.  Also,  He 
said,  that  he  who  lived  well  during  his  appointed  time 
would  return  to  the  habitation  of  his  star,  and  there 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  81 

have  a  blessed  and  suitable  existence.  But  if  he  failed 
in  attaining  this,  in  the  second  generation  he  would  pass 
into  a  woman,  and  should  he  not  cease  from  evil  in  that 
condition,  he  would  be  changed  into  some  brute  who 
resembled  him  in  his  evil  ways,  and  would  not  cease 
from  his  toils  and  transformations  until  he  followed  the 
original  principle  of  sameness  and  likeness  within  him, 
and  overcame,  by  the  help  of  reason,  the  later  accretions 
of  turbulent  and  irrational  elements  composed  of  fire 
and  air  and  water  and  earth,  and  returned  to  the  form  of 
his  first  and  better  nature.  When  He  had  given  all 
these  laws  to  His  creatures,  that  He  might  be  guiltless 
of  their  future  evil,  He  sowed  some  of  them  in  the  earth, 
and  some  in  the  moon,  and  some  in  the  other  stars  which 
are  the  measures  of  time ;  and  when  He  had  sown  them 
He  committed  to  the  younger  gods  the  fashioning  of  their 
mortal  bodies,  and  desired  them  to  furnish  what  was 
still  lacking  to  the  human  soul,  and  make  all  the  suit 
able  additions,  and  rule  and  pilot  the  mortal  animal  in 
the  best  and  wisest  manner  that  they  could,  and  avert 
all  but  self -inflicted  evils." 


GREAT  ANTIQUITY  OF  EGYPT  AND  HER  EARLY 

INFLUENCE  ON  ANCIENT  GREECE.     TALE 

OF  "  THE  LOST  ATLANTIS." 

FROM  PLATO'S  TIM^EUS. 

"Then  listen,  Socrates,  to  a  strange  tale  which  is,  how 
ever,  certainly  true,  as  Solon,  who  was  the  wisest  of  the 
seven  sages,  declared.  He  was  a  relative  and  a  great 
friend  of  my  great-grandfather,  Dropidas,  as  he  himself 
says  in  several  of  his  poems  :  and  Dropidas  told  Critias, 
my  grandfather,  who  remembered  and  told  us :  That 
there  were  of  old  great  and  marvelous  actions  of  the 
Athenians,  which  have  passed  into  oblivion  through 
time  and  the  destruction  of  the  human  race,  and  one  in 
particular,  which  was  the  greatest  of  them  all,  the  re 
cital  of  which  will  be  a  suitable  testimony  of  our  grati 
tude  to  you,  and  also  a  hymn  of  praise  true  and  worthy 
of  the  goddess,  which  may  be  sung  by  us  at  the  festival 
in  her  honor. 

"  Tell  us,  said  the  other,  the  whole  story,  and  how  and 
from  whom  Solon  heard  this  veritable  tradition. 

"  He  replied  :  At  the  head  of  the  Egyptian  Delta,  where 
the  river  Nile  divides,  there  is  a  certain  district  which  is 
called  the  district  of  Sais,  and  the  great  city  of  the  dis 
trict  is  also  called  Sais,  and  is  the  city  from  which 

Amasis  the  king  was  sprung.     And  the  citizens  have  a 

(82) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  83 

deity  who  is  their  foundress :  she  is  called  in  the  Egyptian 
tongue  Neith,  and  is  asserted  by  them  to  be  the  same 
whom  the  Hellenes  called  Athene.  Now  the  citizens  of 
this  city  are  great  lovers  of  the  Athenians,  and  say  that 
they  are  in  some  way  related  to  them.  Thither  came 
Solon,  who  was  received  by  them  with  great  honor  ;  and 
he  asked  the  priests,  who  were  most  skillful  in  such 
matters,  about  antiquity,  and  made  the  discovery  that 
neither  he  nor  any  other  Hellene  knew  anything  worth 
mentioning  about  the  times  of  old.  On  one  occasion, 
when  he  was  drawing  them  on  to  speak  of  antiquity,  he 
began  to  tell  about  the  most  ancient  things  in  our  part 
of  the  world — about  Phoroneus,  who  is  called  "  the  first," 
and  about  Niobe  :  and  after  the  Deluge,  to  tell  of  the 
lives  of  Deucalion  and  Pyrrha :  and  he  traced  the 
genealogy  of  their  descendants,  and  attempted  to  reckon 
how  many  years  old  were  the  events  of  which  he  was 
speaking,  and  to  give  the  dates.  Thereupon,  one  of  the 
priests,  who  was  of  a  very  great  age,  said  :  O  Solon, 
Solon,  you  Hellenes  are  but  children,  and  there  is  never 
an  old  man  who  is  an  Hellene.  Solon  hearing  this,  said, 
What  do  you  mean  ?  I  mean  to  say,  he  replied,  that  in 
mind  you  are  all  young :  there  is  no  old  opinion  handed 
down  among  you  by  ancient  tradition  :  nor  any  science 
which  is  hoary  with  age.  And  I  will  tell  you  the  reason 
of  this.  There  have  been,  and  will  be  again,  many  de 
structions  of  mankind  arising  out  of  many  causes:  the 
greatest  have  been  brought  about  by  the  agencies  of  fire 
and  water,  and  other  lesser  ones  by  innumerable  other 
causes.  There  is  a  story,  which  even  you  have  preserved, 
that  once  upon  a  time  Phsethon,  the  son  of  Helios,  hav 
ing  yoked  the  steeds  in  his  father's  chariot,  because  he 
was  not  able  to  drive  them  in  the  path  of  his  father, 
burnt  up  all  that  was  upon  the  earth,  and  was  himself 


84  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

destroyed  by  a  thunderbolt.  Now,  this  has  the  form  of 
a  myth,  but  really  signifies  a  declination  of  the  bodies 
moving  around  the  earth  and  in  the  heavens,  and  a  great 
conflagration  of  things  upon  the  earth  recurring  at  long 
intervals  of  time  ;  when  this  happens,  those  who  live 
upon  the  mountains  and  in  dry  and  lofty  places  are  more 
liable  to  destruction  than  those  who  dwell  by  rivers  or 
on  the  sea-shore.  And  from  this  calamity  the  Nile,  who 
is  our  never-failing  saviour,  saves  and  delivers  us. 
When,  on  the  other  hand,  the  gods  purge  the  earth  with 
a  deluge  of  water,  among  you,  herdsmen  and  shepherds 
on  the  mountains  are  the  survivors,  whereas  those  of  you 
who  live  in  cities  are  carried  by  the  rivers  into  the  sea. 
But  in  this  country,  neither  at  that  time  nor  at  any  other, 
does  the  water  come  from  above  on  the  fields,  having 
always  a  tendency  to  come  up  from  below,  for  which 
reason  the  things  preserved  here  are  said  to  be  the  oldest. 
The  fact  is,  that  wherever  the  extremity  of  winter  frost 
or  of  summer  sun  does  not  prevent,  the  human  race  is 
always  increasing  at  times,  and  at  other  times  diminish 
ing  in  numbers.  And  whatever  happened  either  in  your 
country  or  in  ours,  or  in  any  other  region  of  which  we  are 
informed — if  any  action  which  is  noble  or  great  or  in  any 
other  way  remarkable,  has  taken  place,  all  that  has  been 
written  down  of  old,  and  is  preserved  in  our  temples ; 
whereas  you  and  other  nations  are  just  being  provided 
with  letters  and  the  other  things  which  States  require  ; 
and  then,  at  the  usual  period,  the  stream  from  heaven 
descends  like  a  pestilence,  and  leaves  only  those  of  you 
who  are  destitute  of  letters  and  education ;  and  thus  you 
have  to  begin  all  over  again  as  children,  and  know 
nothing  of  what  happened  in  ancient  times,  either  among 
us  or  among  yourselves.  As  for  those  genealogies  of 
yours  which  you  have  recounted  to  us,  Solon,  they  are 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosopher*  85 

no  better  than  the  tales  of  children  ;  for  in  the  first  place 
you  remember  one  deluge  only,  whereas  there  were  many 
of  them ;  and  in  the  next  place,  you  do  not  know  that 
there  dwelt  in  your  land  the  fairest  and  noblest  race  of 
men  which  ever  lived,  of  whom  you  and  your  whole  city 
are  but  a  seed  or  remnant.  And  this  was  unknown  to 
you,  because  for  many  generations  the  survivors  of  that 
destruction  died  and  made  no  sign.  For  there  was  a 
time,  Solon,  before  the  great  deluge  of  all,  when  the 
city  which  now  is  Athens,  was  first  in  war  and  was  pre 
eminent  for  the  excellence  of  her  laws,  and  is  said  to 
have  performed  the  noblest  deeds  and  to  have  had  the 
fairest  constitution  of  any  of  which  tradition  tells,  under 
the  face  of  heaven.  Solon  marveled  at  this,  and  earnestly 
requested  the  priest  to  inform  him  exactly  and  in  order 
about  these  former  citizens.  You  are  welcome  to  hear 
about  them,  Solon,  said  the  priest,  both  for  your  own 
sake  and  for  that  of  the  city,  and  above  all,  for  the  sake 
of  the  goddess  who  is  the  common  patron  and  protector 
and  educator  of  both  our  cities.  She  founded  your  city 
a  thousand  years  before  ours,  receiving  from  the  Earth 
and  Hephaestus  the  seed  of  your  race,  and  then  she 
founded  ours,  the  constitution  of  which  is  set  down  in 
our  sacred  registers  as  eight  thousand  years  old.  As 
touching  the  citizens  of  nine  thousand  years  ago,  I  will 
briefly  inform  you  of  their  laws  and  of  the  noblest  of 
their  actions  ;  and  the  exact  particulars  of  the  whole  we 
will  hereafter  go  through  at  our  leisure  in  the  sacred 
registers  themselves.  If  you  compare  these  very  laws 
with  your  own  you  will  find  that  many  of  ours  are  the 
counterpart  of  yours  as  they  were  in  the  olden  time.  In 
the  first  place,  there  is  the  caste  of  priests,  which  is 
separated  from  all  the  others ;  next  there  are  the  artificers, 
who  exercise  their  several  crafts  by  themselves  and  with- 


86  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

out  admixture  of  any  other  ;  and  also  there  is  the  class 
of  shepherds  and  that  of  hunters,  as  well  as  that  of  hus 
bandmen  ;  and  you  will  observe,  too,  that  the  warriors  in 
Egypt  are  separated  from  all  the  other  classes,  and  are 
commanded  by  the  law  only  to  engage  in  war ;  moreover, 
the  weapons  with  which  they  are  equipped  are  shields 
and  spears,  and  this  the  goddess  taught  first  among  you, 
and  then  in  Asiatic  countries,  and  we  among  the  Asiatics 
first  adopted.  Then  as  to  wisdom,  do  you  observe  what 
care  the  law  took  from  the  very  first,  searching  out  and 
comprehending  the  whole  order  of  things  down  to 
prophecy  and  medicine  (the  latter  with  a  view  to  health)  ; 
and  out  of  these  divine  elements  drawing  what  was  need 
ful  for  human  life,  and  adding  every  sort  of  knowledge 
which  was  connected  with  them.  All  this  order  and 
arrangement  the  goddess  first  imparted  to  you  when  es 
tablishing  your  city  ;  and  she  chose  the  spot  of  earth  in 
which  you  were  born,  because  she  saw  that  the  happy 
temperament  of  the  seasons  in  that  land  would  produce 
the  wisest  of  men.  Wherefore  the  goddess  who  was  a 
lover  both  of  war  and  of  wisdom,  selected,  and  first  of 
all  settled  that  spot  which  was  the  most  likely  to  pro 
duce  men  likest  herself.  And  there  you  dwelt,  having 
such  laws  as  these  and  still  better  ones,  and  excelled  all 
mankind  in  all  virtue  as  became  the  children  and 
disciples  of  the  gods. 

"  Many  great  and  wonderful  deeds  are  recorded  of  your 
State  in  our  histories.  But  one  of  them  exceeds  all  the 
rest  in  greatness  and  valor.  For  these  histories  tell  of 
a  mighty  power  which  was  aggressing  wantonly  against 
the  whole  of  Europe  and  Asia,  and  to  which  your  city 
put  an  end.  This  power  came  forth  out  of  the  Atlantic 
Ocean,  for  in  those  days  the  Atlantic  was  navigable;' 
and  there  was  an  island  situated  in  front  of  the  straits 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  87 

which  you  call  the  columns  of  Heracles ;  the  island  was 
larger  than  Libya  and  Asia  put  together,  and  was  the 
way  to  other  islands,  and  from  the  islands  you  might 
pass  through  the  whole  of  the  opposite  continent  which 
surrounded  the  true  ocean  ;  for  this  sea  which  is  within 
the  Straits  of  Heracles  is  only  a  harbor,  having  a  narrow 
entrance,  but  that  other  is  a  real  sea,  and  the  surround 
ing  land  may  be  most  truly  called  a  continent.  Now  in 
this  island  of  Atlantis  there  was  a  great  and  wonderful 
empire  which  had  rule  over  the  whole  island  and  several 
others,  as  well  as  over  parts  of  the  continent,  and,  be 
sides  these,  they  subjected  the  parts  of  Libya  within  the 
columns  of  Heracles  as  far  as  Egypt,  and  of  Europe  as 
far  as  Tyrrhenia.  The  vast  power  thus  gathered  into 
one,  endeavored  to  subdue  at  one  blow  our  country  and 
yours  and  the  whole  of  the  land  which  was  within  the 
straits ;  and  then,  Solon,  your  country  shone  forth,  in 
the  excellence  of  her  virtue  and  strength,  among  all 
mankind;  for  she  was  the  first  in  courage  and  military 
skill,  and  was  the  leader  of  the  Hellenes.  And  when 
the  rest  fell  off  from  her,  being  compelled  to  stand  alone 
after  having  undergone  the  very  extremity  of  danger, 
she  defeated  and  triumphed  over  the  invaders,  and  pre 
served  from  slavery  those  who  were  not  yet  subjected, 
and  freely  liberated  all  the  others  who  dwelt  within  the 
limits  of  Heracles.  But  afterwards  there  occurred  vio 
lent  earthquakes  and  floods ;  and  in  a  single  day  and 
night  of  rain  all  your  warlike  men  in  a  body  sank  into 
the  earth,  and  the  island  of  Atlantis  in  like  manner  dis 
appeared,  and  was  sunk  beneath  the  sea.  And  this  is  the 
reason  why  the  sea  in  those  parts  is  impassable  and  im 
penetrable,  because  there  is  such  a  quantity  of  shallow 
mud  in  the  way ;  and  this  was  caused  by  the  subsidence 
of  the  island." 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  UNIVERSAL  BENEFICENT 
LOVE. 

FROM  PLATO'S  SYMPOSIUM. 

Introductory  Note  : — We  have  here  assembled  the  best 
parts  of  Plato's  Symposium  on  the  subject  of  Love  to 
show  the  beauty  and  profundity  of  much  of  the  old 
thought  on  this  subject,  and  have  thus  given  most  of  the 
speeches  of  the  tragic  poet  Agathon  and  of  Socrates  the 
sculptor  and  philosopher.  The  moral  as  well  as  poetic 
beauty  of  Agathon's  analysis  and  remarks  will  be  readily 
noted,  and  it  may  recall  to  us  the  beautiful  and  famous 
hymn  to  love  or  "Charity"  given  by  St.  Paul  in  ist 
Corinthians,  i3th  Chapter.  "  Charity  "  and  "  love  "  are 
of  course  interchangeable  terms,  and  "  love  "  is  the  term 
which  is  now  used  by  the  translators  in  the  late  revised 
version  of  the  New  Testament.  As  to  the  word  "  charity  " 
itself,  it  should  also  be  noted  that  it  is  derived  from  the 
Greek  word  "  Charites  "  which  is  the  Greek  name  of 
the  "  three  graces"  who  were  believed  to  have  presided 
over  all  the  kind  and  social  relations  and  "  graces  "  of 
life.  It  will  be  noted  in  the  parallel  which  we  have 
drawn  farther  on  between  the  words  of  Paul  and 
Agathon,  that  practically  identical  thoughts  or  ideas  ap 
pear  in  each,  Agathon  being  earlier  by  nearly  five  hun 
dred  years. 

In  the   remarks   of  Socrates  will  be  found  the  true 

(88) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  89 

doctrine  of  "  Platonic  Love  "  which  has  popularly  and 
incorrectly  been  regarded  as  a  pure  or  sexless  love  be 
tween  the  sexes,  whereas  it  does  not  necessarily  involve 
a  friendship  between  the  opposite  sexes  at  all,  but  rather 
between  old  men  and  youths,  and  relates  particularly  to 
the  influence  of  the  great  or  creative  souls  in  producing 
a  moral  and  intellectual  offspring  by  influencing  the 
minds  and  characters  of  others  for  their  good  and  chiefly 
between  old  and  young  men.  Note  also  the  appearance 
here  of  that  remarkable  character  of  whom  little  seems 
to  be  known,  viz.,  the  Greek  woman  Diotima,  who  seems 
to  have  been  a  great  Pythagorean  philosopher  and  also 
a  priestess  of  Zeus  from  the  ancient  democratic  city  of 
Mautinea  in  the  Greek  state  of  Arcadia  where  women 
had  more  freedom  and  independence  than  in  the  more 
aristocratic  state  of  Athens,  and  who  it  seems  was  the 
teacher  in  philosophy  of  the  great  Socrates  himself  who 
shows  man)7  traces  of  the  P}Tthagorean  discipline  and 
doctrine  in  his  mode  of  life  and  teachings.  The  discourse 
between  Socrates  and  Diotima  is  deeply  interesting  and 
profound,  and  it  will  be  seen  that  one  of  the  remarkable 
definitions  which  she  gives  of  Love  is  that  it  is  "the  de 
sire  of  the  everlasting  possession  of  the  good."  Another  of 
her  remarkable  statements  is  that,  all  desire  of  good  and 
happiness  is  due  to  the  great  and  subtle  power  of  love, 
that  love  is  only  birth  in  beauty,  whether  of  body  or  of 
soul,  and  that  love  exists  essentially  for  the  purpose  of 
realizing  immortality,  as  only  by  rebirth,  whether  of 
body  or  soul,  is  immortality  made  a  practical  reality  or 
fact.  Thus,  physical  man  simply  passes  on  his  physical 
life  to  his  mortal  children,  and  intellectual  and  soulful 
man  transmits  his  mental  and  moral  attainments  to  his 
disciples — his  children  of  the  soul — all  through  "  the 
great  and  subtle  power  of  Love." 


go  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

An  illustration  of  the  Socratic  ethical  doctrine  that 
"  Knowledge  "  essentially  constitutes  Good  or  Virtue  is 
seen  in  Diotima's  positive  statement  to  Socrates  that 
"  There  is  nothing  which  men  love  but  the  good." 
Hence  Socrates  insisted  that  virtue  can  be  taught  for  it 
is  essentially  "  knowledge,"  and  that  if  men  only  knew 
what  "  Good  "  was,  they  would  always  love  and  practice 
it,  and  it  is  thus  chiefly  through  pure  "ignorance"  that 
they  are  not  virtuous.  Note  also  how  this  Socratic 
ethical  theory  corresponds  with  the  interesting  statement 
quoted  in  the  extracts  from  Aristotle  where  he  says,  re 
ferring  to  Plato,  "And  therefore  as  Plato  says  man  needs 
to  be  trained  from  his  youth  up  to  find  pleasure  and  pain 
in  the  right  objects.  This  is  what  a  sound  education 
means."— C.  M.  H. 


AGATHON  AND  SOCRATES  ON  LOVE. 
FROM  PLATO'S  SYMPOSIUM. 

The  ancient  things  of  which  Hesiod  and  Parmenides 
speak,  if  they  were  done  at  all,  were  done  of  necessity 
and  not  of  love ;  had  love  been  in  those  days,  there 
would  have  been  no  chaining  or  mutilation  of  the  gods, 
or  other  violence  but  peace  and  sweetness,  as  there  is 
now  in  heaven,  since  the  rule  of  Love  began.  Love  is 
young  and  also  tender ;  he  ought  to  have  a  poet  like 
Homer  to  describe  his  tenderness,  as  Homer  says  of 
Ate,  that  she  is  a  goddess  and  tender  : — 

"  Her  feet  are  tender,  for  she  sets  her  steps, 
Not  on  the  ground  but  on  the  heads  of  men  :" 

which  is  an  excellent  proof  of  her  tenderness,  because 
she  walks  not  upon  the  hard  but  upon  the  soft.  Let  us 
adduce  a  similar  proof  of  the  tenderness  of  Love  :  for 
he  walks  not  upon  the  earth,  nor  yet  upon  the  skulls 
of  men,  which  are  hard  enough,  but  in  the  hearts  and 
souls  of  men  ;  in  them  he  walks  and  dwells  and  has  his 
home.  Not  in  every  soul  without  exception,  for  where 
there  is  a  hardness  he  departs,  where  there  is  softness 
there  he  dwells  ;  and  clinging  always  with  his  feet  and 
in  all  manner  of  ways  in  the  softest  of  soft  places,  how 
can  he  be  other  than  the  softest  of  all  things  ?  And  he 

(90 


92  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

is  the  youngest  as  well  as  the  tenderest,  and  also  he  is 
of  flexile  form  ;  for  without  flexure  he  could  not  enfold 
all  things,  or  wind  his  way  into  and  out  of  every  soul 
of  man  without  being  discovered,  if  he  were  hard.  And 
a  proof  of  his  flexibility  and  symmetry  of  form  is  his 
grace,  which  is  universally  admitted  to  be  in  an  especial 
manner  the  attribute  of  Love :  ungrace  and  love  are 
always  at  war  with  one  another.  *  *  But  I  must 
now  speak  of  his  virtue ;  his  greatest  glory  is  that  he 
can  neither  do  nor  suffer  wrong  from  any  god  or  any 
man  :  for  he  suffers  not  by  force  if  he  suffers,  for  force 
comes  not  near  him,  neither  does  he  act  by  force.  For 
all  serve  him  of  their  own  free-will,  and  where  there  is 
love  as  well  as  obedience,  there,  as  the  laws  which  are 
the  lords  of  the  city  say,  is  justice.  And  not  only  is  he 
just  but  exceedingly  temperate,  for  Temperance  is  the 
acknowledged  ruler  of  the  pleasures  and  desires,  and  no 
pleasure  ever  masters  Love  ;  he  is  their  master  and  they 
are  his  servants ;  and  if  he  conquers  them  he  must  be 
temperate  indeed.  As  to  courage,  even  the  God  of  War 
is  no  match  for  him  ;  he  is  the  captive  and  Love  is  the 
lord,  for  love,  the  love  of  Aphrodite,  masters  him,  as  the 
tale  runs  :  and  the  master  is  stronger  than  the  servant. 
And  if  he  conquers  the  bravest  of  all  he  must  be  himself 
the  bravest.  Of  his  courage  and  justice  and  temper 
ance  I  have  spoken  ;  but  I  have  yet  to  speak  of  his  wis 
dom,  and  I  must  try  to  do  my  best,  according  to  the 
measure  of  my  ability.  For  in  the  first  place  he  is  a 
poet,  (and  here,  like  Eryximachus,  I  magnify  my  art,) 
and  he  is  also  the  source  of  poesy  in  others,  which  he 
could  not  be  if  he  were  not  himself  a  poet.  And  at  the 
touch  of  him  every  one  becomes  a  poet,  even  though  he 
had  no  music  in  him  before ;  this  also  is  a  proof  that 
Love  is  a  good  poet  and  accomplished  in  all  the  musical 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  93 

arts  ;  for  no  one  can  give  to  another  that  which  he  has 
not  himself,  or  teach  that  of  which  he  has  no  knowl 
edge. 

And  as  to  the  artists,  do  we  not  know  that  he  only  of 
them  whom  love  inspires  has  the  light  of  fame? — he 
whom  love  touches  not  walks  in  darkness.  Love  set  in 
order  the  empire  of  the  gods.  And  formerly,  as  I  was 
saying,  dreadful  deeds  were  done  among  the  gods,  be 
cause  of  the  rule  of  necessity  ;  but  now  since  the  birth 
of  Love,  and  from  the  love  of  the  beautiful,  has  sprung 
every  good  in  heaven  and  earth.  Therefore,  Phaedrus, 
I  say  of  Love  that  he  is  the  fairest  and  best  in  himself, 
and  the  cause  of  what  is  fairest  and  best  in  all  other 
things.  And  I  have  a  mind  to  say  of  him  in  verse  that 
he  is  the  god  who — 

"  Gives  peace  on  earth  and  calms  the  stormy  deep, 
Who  stills  the   waves  and  bids  the  sufferer  sleep." 

He  makes  men  to  be  of  one  mind  at  a  banquet  such  as 
this,  fulfilling  them  with  affection  and  emptying  them 
of  disaffection.  In  sacrifices,  banquets,  dances,  he  is  our 
lord, — supplying  kindness  and  banishing  unkindness, 
giving  friendship  and  forgiving  enmity,  the  joy  of  the 
good,  the  wonder  of  the  wise,  the  amazement  of  the 
gods ;  desired  by  those  who  have  no  part  in  him,  and 
precious  to  those  who  have  the  better  part  in  him  ; 
parent  of  delicacy,  luxury,  desire,  fondness,  softness, 
grace ;  careful  of  the  good,  uncareful  of  the  evil.  In 
every  word,  work,  wish,  fear, — pilot,  helper,  defender, 
savior  ;  glory  of  gods  and  men,  leader  best  and  brightest : 
in  whose  footsteps  let  every  man  follow,  chanting  a 
hymn  and  joining  in  that  fair  strain  with  which  Love 
charms  the  souls  of  gods  and  men.  Such  is  the  dis 
course,  Phaedrus,  half  playful,  yet  having  a  certain 


94  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

measure  of  seriousness,  which,  according  to  my  ability, 

I  dedicate  to  the  God. 

#***         *         *         *         #         * 

Socrates  then  proceeded  as  follows  : — 

In  the  magnificent  discourse  which  you  have  uttered, 
I  think  that  you  were  right,  my  dear  Agathon,  in  saying 
that  you  would  begin  with  the  nature  of  Love  and  then 
afterwards  speak  of  his  works — that  is  a  way  of  begin 
ning  which  I  very  much  approve. 

And  now  I  will  take  my  leave  of  you,  and  rehearse 
the  tale  of  love  which  I  heard  once  upon  a  time  from 
Diotima  of  Mantinea,  who  was  a  wise  woman  in  this 
and  many  other  branches  of  knowledge.  She  was  the 
same  who  deferred  the  plague  of  Athens  ten  years  by  a 
sacrifice,  and  was  niy  instructress  in  the  art  of  love.  In 
the  attempt  which  I  am  about  to  make  I  shall  pursue 
Agathon's  method,  and  begin  with  his  admissions 
which  are  nearly  if  not  quite  the  same  which  I  made  to 
the  wise  woman  when  she  questioned  me :  this  will  be 
the  easiest  way,  and  I  shall  take  both  parts  myself  as 
well  I  can.  For,  like  Agathon,  she  spoke  first  of  the 
being  and  nature  of  Love,  and  then  of  his  \vorks. 

"What  then  is  Love?"  I  asked;  "Is  he  mortal?" 
"No."  "What  then?"  "As  in  the  former  instance, 
he  is  neither  mortal  or  immortal,  but  in  a  mean  between 
them."  "  What  is  he  then,  Diotima?  "  "  He  is  a  great 
spirit,  and  like  all  that  is  spiritual  he  is  intermediate 
between  the  divine  and  the  mortal."  "  And  what  is  the 
nature  of  this  spiritual  power?"  I  said.  "This  is  the 
power,"  she  said,  "which  interprets  and  conveys  to  the 
gods  the  prayers  and  sacrifices  of  men,  and  to  men  the 
commands  and  rewards  of  the  gods :  and  this  power 
spans  the  chasm  which  divides  them,  and  in  this  all  is 
bound  together,  and  through  this  the  arts  of  the  prophet 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  95 

and  the  priest,  their  sacrifices  and  mysteries  and  charms, 
and  all  prophecy  and  incantation,  find  their  way.  For 
God  mingles  not  with  man ;  and  through  this  power  all 
the  intercourse  and  speech  of  God  with  man,  whether 
awake  or  asleep,  is  carried  on.  The  wisdom  which  un 
derstands  this  is  spiritual :  all  other  wisdom,  such  as 
that  of  arts  or  handicrafts,  is  mean  and  vulgar.  Now 
these  spirits  or  intermediate  powers  are  many  and 
divine,  and  one  of  them  is  Love." 

"  But  all  men,  Socrates,"  she  rejoined,  "  are  not  said 
to  love,  but  only  some  of  them;  and  you  say  that  all 
men  are  always  loving  the  same  things."  "  I  myself 
wonder,"  I  said,  "  why  that  is."  "  There  is  nothing  to 
wonder  at,"  she  replied ;  "  the  reason  is  that  one  part  of 
love  is  separated  off  and  receives  the  name  of  the  whole, 
but  the  other  parts  have  other  names."  "  Give  an 
example,"  I  said.  She  answered  me  as  follows  :  "  There 
is  poetry,  which,  as  you  know,  is  complex  and  manifold. 
And  all  creation  or  passage  of  non-being  into  being  is 
poetry  or  making,  and  the  processes  of  all  art  are  crea 
tive  ;  and  the  masters  of  arts  are  all  poets."  "  Very 
true."-  "Still, "she  said,  "  you  know  that  they  are  not 
called  poets,  but  have  other  names ;  the  generic  term 
'  poetry '  is  confined  to  that  specific  art  which  is  sepa 
rated  off  from  the  rest  of  poetry,  and  is  concerned  with 
music  and  metre ;  and  this  is  what  is  called  poetry,  and 
they  who  possess  this  kind  of  poetrjr  are  called  poets." 
11  Very  true,"  I  said.  "  And  the  same  holds  of  love. 
For  you  may  say  generally  that  all  desire  of  good  and 
happiness  is  due  to  the  great  and  subtle  power  of  Love ; 
but  those  who,  having  their  affections  set  upon  him,  are 
yet  diverted  into  the  paths  of  money -making  or  gym 
nastic  philosophy,  are  not  called  lovers, — the  name  of 
the  genus  is  reserved  for  those  whose  devotion  takes 


96  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

one  form  only, — they  alone  are  said  to  love,  or  to  be 
lovers."  "  In  that,"  I  said,  "  I  am  of  opinion  that  you 
are  right."  "Yes,"  she  said,  "  and  you  hear  people  say 
that  lovers  are  seeking  for  the  half  of  themselves ;  but  I 
say  that  they  are  seeking  neither  for  the  half,  nor  for 
the  whole,  unless  the  half  or  the  whole  be  also  a  good. 
And  they  will  cut  off  their  own  hands  and  feet  and  cast 
them  away,  if  they  are  evil ;  for  they  love  them  not  be 
cause  they  are  their  own,  but  because  they  are  good, 
and  dislike  them  not  because  they  are  another's,  but 
because  they  are  evil.  There  is  nothing  which  men  love 
but  the  good.  Do  you  think  that  there  is?  "  "  Indeed," 
I  answered,  "  I  should  say  not."  "  Then,"  she  said, 
"  the  conclusion  of  the  whole  matter  is,  that  men  love 
the  good."  "  Yes,"  I  said.  "  To  which  may  be  added 
that  they  love  the  possession  of  the  good  ?  "  "  Yes,  that 
may  be  added."  "  And  not  only  the  possession,  but  the 
everlasting  possession  of  the  good?"  "That  maybe 
added  too."  "  Then  love,"  she  said,  "may  be  described 
generally  as  the  love  of  the  everlasting  possession  of 
the  good  ?  "  "  That  is  most  true,"  I  said. 

"  Then  if  this  be  the  nature  of  love,  can  you  tell  me 
further,"  she  said,  "  what  is  the  manner  of  the  pursuit? 
w7hat  are  they  doing  who  show  all  this  eagerness  and 
heat  which  is  called  love  ?  Answer  me  that."  "  Nay, 
Diotima,"  I  said,  "if  I  had  known  I  should  not  have 
wondered  at  your  wisdom,  or  have  come  to  you  to  learn." 
"  Well,"  she  said,  "  I  will  teach  you  ;  love  is  only  birth 
in  beauty,  whether  of  body  or  soul." 

"  For  love,  Socrates,  is  not,  as  you  imagine,  the  love 
of  the  beautiful  only."  "What  then?"  "  The  love  of 
generation  and  birth  in  beauty."  "Yes,"  I  said.  "Yes, 
indeed,"  she  replied.  "But  why  of  birth?"  I  said. 
"  Because  to  the  mortal,  birth  is  a  sort  of  eternity  and 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  97 

immortality,"  she  replied  ;  "  and  as  has  been  already 
admitted,  all  men  will  necessarily  desire  immortality 
together  with  good,  if  love  is  of  the  everlasting  posses 
sion  of  the  good." 

All  this  she  taught  me  at  various  times  when  she 
spoke  of  love.  And  on  another  occasion  she  said  to  me, 
"What  is  the  reason,  Socrates,  of  this  love,  and  the 
attendant  desire  ?  See  you  not  how  all  animals,  birds 
as  well  as  beasts,  in  their  desire  of  procreation,  are  in 
agony  when  they  take  the  infection  of  love  ;  this  begins 
with  the  desire  of  union,  to  which  is  added  the  care  of 
offspring,  on  behalf  of  whom  the  weakest  are  ready  to 
battle  against  the  strongest  even  to  the  uttermost,  and 
to  die  for  them,  and  will  let  themselves  be  tormented 
with  hunger  or  suffer  anything  in  order  to  maintain 
their  offspring.  Man  may  be  supposed  to  do  this  from 
reason  ;  but  why  should  animals  have  these  passionate 
feelings?  Can  you  tell  me  why?"  Again  I  replied, 
"that  I  did  not  know."  She  said  to  me  :  "And  do  you 
expect  ever  to  become  a  master  in  the  art  of  love,  if  you 
do  not  know  this?"  "But  that,"  I  said,  "  Diotima,  is 
the  reason  why  I  come  to  you,  because,  as  I  have  told 
you  already,  I  am  awrare  that  I  want  a  teacher ;  and  I 
wish  that  you  would  explain  to  me  this  and  the  other 
mysteries  of  love."  "  Marvel  not  at  this,"  she  said,  "  if 
you  believe  that  love  is  of  the  immortal,  as  we  have  al 
ready  admitted  ;  for  here  again,  and  on  the  same  principle 
too,  the  mortal  nature  is  seeking  as  far  as  is  possible  to 
be  everlasting  and  immortal  :  and  this  is  only  to  be  at 
tained  by  generation,  because  the  new  is  always  left  in 
the  place  of  the  old.  For  even  in  the  same  individual 
there  is  succession  and  not  absolute  unity  :  a  man  is 
called  the  same  :  but  yet  in  the  short  interval  which 
elapses  between  youth  and  age,  and  in  which  every 


98  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

animal  is  said  to  have  life  and  identity,  he  is  undergoing 
a  perpetual  process  of  loss  and  reparation — hair,  flesh 
bones,  blood,  and  the  whole  body,  are  always  changing. 
And  this  is  true,  not  only  of  the  body,  but  also  of  the 
soul,,  whose  habits,  tempers,  opinions,  desires,  pleasures, 
pains,  fears,  never  remain  the  same  in  any  one  of  us,  but 
are  always  coming  and  going.  And  what  is  yet  more 
surprising  is,  that  this  is  also  true  of  knowledge ;  and 
not  only  does  knowledge  in  general  come  and  go,  so  that 
in  this  respect  we  are  never  the  same ;  but  particular 
knowledge  also  experiences  a  like  change.  For  what  is 
implied  in  the  word  'recollection/ but  the  departure  of 
knowledge,  which  is  ever  being  forgotten  and  is  renewed 
and  preserved  by  recollection,  appearing  to  be  the  same 
although  in  reality  new,  according  to  that  law  of  suc 
cession  by  which  all  mortal  things  are  preserved,  not  by 
absolute  sameness  of  existence,  but  by  substitution,  the 
old  worn-out  mortality  leaving  another  new  and  similar 
one  behind — unlike  the  immortal  in  this,  which  is  always 
the  same  and  not  another  ?  And  in  this  way,  Socrates, 
the  mortal  body,  or  mortal  anything,  partakes  of  im 
mortality  ;  but  the  immortal  in  another  way.  Marvel 
not  then  at  the  love  which  all  men  have  of  their  off 
spring;  for  that  universal  love  and  interest  is  for  the 
sake  of  immortality." 

"Men  whose  bodies  only  are  creative,  betake  them 
selves  to  women  and  beget  children — this  is  the  character 
of  their  love  ;  their  offspring,  as  they  hope,  will  preserve 
their  memory  and  give  them  the  blessedness  and  immor 
tality  which  they  desire  in  the  future.  But  creative  souls 
—for  there  are  men  who  are  more  creative  in  their  souls 
than  in  their  bodies — conceive  that  which  is  proper  for 
the  soul  to  conceive  or  retain.  And  what  are  these  con 
ceptions  ? — wisdom  and  virtue  in  general.  And  such 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  99 

creators  are  all  poets  and  other  artists  who  may  be  said 
to  have  invention.  But  the  greatest  and  fairest  sort  of 
wisdom  by  far,  is  that  which  is  concerned  with  the  order 
ing  of  states  and  families,  and  which  is  called  temper 
ance  and  justice.  And  he  who  in  youth  has  the  seed  of 
these  implanted  in  him  and  is  himself  inspired,  when  he 
comes  to  maturity,  desires  to  beget  and  generate.  And 
he  wanders  about  seeking  beauty  that  he  may  beget  off 
spring — for  in  deformity  he  will  beget  nothing — and 
embraces  the  beautiful  rather  than  the  deformed;  and 
when  he  finds  a  fair,  and  noble,  and  well-nurtured  soul, 
and  there  is  union  of  the  two  in  one  person,  he  gladly 
embraces  him,  and  to  such  a  one  he  is  full  of  fair  speech 
about  virtue  and  the  nature  and  pursuits  of  a  good  man  : 
and  he  tries  to  educate  him  ;  and  at  the  touch  and  pres 
ence  of  the  beautiful  he  brings  forth  the  beautiful  which 
he  conceived  long  before,  and  the  beautiful  is  ever  pres 
ent  with  him  and  in  his  memory  even  when  absent,  and 
in  company  they  tend  that  which  he  brings  forth,  and 
they  are  bound  together  by  a  far  nearer  tie,  and  have  a 
closer  friendship  than  those  who  beget  mortal  children, 
for  the  children  who  are  their  common  offspring  are  fairer 
and  more  immortal.  Who,  when  he  thinks  of  Homer 
and  Hesiod  and  other  great  poets,  would  not  rather  have 
their  children  than  ordinary  human  ones  ?  Who  would 
not  emulate  them  in  the  creation  of  children  such  as 
theirs,  which  have  preserved  their  memory  and  given 
them  everlasting  glory  ?  Or  who  would  not  have  such 
children  as  Lycurgus  left  behind  to  be  the  saviors,  not 
only  of  Lacedaemon,  but  of  Hellas,  as  one  may  say  ? 
There  is  Solon,  too,  who  is  the  revered  father  of  Athenian 
laws  ;  and  man}'  others  there  are  in  many  other  places, 
both  among  Hellenes  and  barbarians.  All  of  them  have 
done  many  noble  works,  and  have  been  the  parents  of 


ioo  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

virtue  of  every  kind,  and  many  temples  have  been  raised 
in  honor  of  their  children,  which  were  never  raised  in 
honor  of  the  mortal  children  of  any  one." 

"  And  the  true  order  of  going  or  being  led  by  another 
to  the  things  of  love,  is  to  use  the  beauties  of  earth  as 
steps  along  which  he  mounts  upwards  for  the  sake  of 
that  other  beauty,  going  from  one  to  two,  and  from  two 
to  all  fair  forms,  and  from  fair  forms  to  fair  actions,  and 
from  fair  actions  to  fair  notions,  until  from  fair  notions 
he  arrives  at  the  notion  of  absolute  beauty,  and  at  last 
knows  what  the  essence  of  beauty  is.  This,  my  dear 
Socrates,"  said  the  stranger  of  Mantineia,  "  is  that  life 
above  all  others  which  man  should  live,  in  the  contem 
plation  of  beauty  absolute  ;  a  beauty  which,  if  you  once 
beheld,  you  would  see  not  to  be  after  the  measure  of 
gold,  and  garments,  and  fair  boys  and  youths,  which, 
when  you  now  behold,  you  are  in  fond  amazement,  and 
you  and  many  a  one  are  content  to  live  seeing  only  and 
conversing  with  them  without  meat  or  drink,  if  that 
were  possible — you  only  want  to  be  with  them  and  to 
look  at  them.  But  what  if  man  had  eyes  to  see  the  true 
beauty — the  divine  beauty,  I  mean,  pure  and  clear  and 
unalloyed,  not  clogged  with  the  pollutions  of  mortality, 
and  all  the  colors  and  vanities  of  human  life — thither 
looking,  and  holding  converse  with  the  true  beauty, 
divine  and  simple,  and  bringing  into  being  and  educating 
true  creations  of  virtue  and  not  idols  only  ?  Do  you  not 
see  that  in  that  communion  only,  beholding  beauty  with 
the  eye  of  the  mind,  he  will  be  enabled  to  bring  forth, 
not  images  of  beauty,  but  realities  ;  for  he  has  hold,  not 
of  an  image,  but  of  a  reality,  and  bringing  forth  and 
educating  true  virtue  to  become  the  friend  of  God  and 
be  immortal,  if  mortal  man  may.  Would  that  be  an 
ignoble  life?" 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  101 

Such,  Phaedrus— and  I  speak  not  only  to  you,  but  to 
all  men — were  the  words  of  Diotima ;  and  I  am  persuaded 
of  their  truth.  And  being  persuaded  of  them,  I  try  to 
persuade  others,  that  in  the  attainment  of  this  end  human 
nature  will  not  easily  find  a  better  helper  than  Love. 
And  therefore,  also,  I  say  that  every  man  ought  to  honor 
him  as  I  myself  honor  him,  and  walk  in  his  ways,  and 
exhort  others  to  do  the  same,  even  as  I  praise  the  power 
and  spirit  of  love  according  to  the  measure  of  my  ability, 
now  and  ever. 


PAUL  AND    PLATO    PARALLELED. 

—HYMN   TO    LOVE. — 

Paul  in  I  Corinthians,  13.      Agathon  in  Plato's  Sympo- 
REVISED  VERSION,  smm,  B.  C. 

About  A.  D.  57. 


SECTION  FIRST. 

"If  I  speak  with  the 
tongues  of  men  and  of  an 
gels,  but  have  not  love,  I 
am  become  sounding  brass 
or  a  clanging  cymbal.  And 
if  I  have  the  gift  of  proph 
ecy  and  know  all  mysteries 
and  all  knowledge,  and  if  I 
have  all  faith  so  as  to  re 
move  mountains,  but  have 
not  love,  I  am  nothing. 


SECTION  SECOND. 

"And  if  I  bestow  all  my 
goods  to  feed  the  poor,  and 


SECTION  FIRST. 

"And  as  to  the  artists,  do 
we  not  know  that  he  only 
of  them  whom  love  inspires 
has  the  light  of  fame?  He 
whom  love  touches  not 
walks  in  darkness.  Love 
set  in  order  the  empire  of 
the  Gods.  Therefore  Phae- 
drus  I  say  of  Love  that  he 
is  the  fairest  and  best  in 
himself  and  the  cause  of 
what  is  fairest  and  best  in 
all  other  things." 

SECTION   SECOND. 
(Note.     This  thought  of 


Paul    is   not    paralleled   in 
(102) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 


if  I  give  my  body  to  be  Agathon,  being  simply  a 
burned,  but  have  not  love,  denunciation  of  ostenta 
tious  or  Pharisaic  virtue 
without  real  kindness  or 
charity  in  the  heart. — Ed.) 


it  profiteth  me  nothing. 


SECTION  THIRD. 

"  Love  suffereth  long  and 
is  kind,  love  envieth  not, 
love  vaunteth  not  itself,  is 
not  puffed  up,  doth  not 
behave  itself  unseemly, 
seeketh  not  its  own,  is  not 
provoked,  taketh  not  ac 
count  of  evil,  rejoiceth  not 
in  unrighteousness,  but  re 
joiceth  with  the  truth,  bear- 
eth  all  things,  believeth  all 
things,  hopeth  all  things, 
endureth  all  things. 


SECTION  THIRD. 

'  And  I  have  a  mind  to 
say  of  him  in  verse  that  he 
is  the  god  who 

Gives  peace  on  earth,  and 
calms  the  stormy  deep, 

Who  stills  the  waves,  and 
bids  the  sufferer  sleep. 

He  makes  men  to  be  of  one 
mind  at  a  banquet  such  as 
this,  filling  them  with  affec- 
tion  and  emptying  them  of 
disaffection.  In  sacrifices, 
banquets,  dances,  he  is  our 
lord,  supplying  kindness 
and  banishing  unkindness, 
giving  friendship  and  for 
giving  enmity,  the  joy  of 
the  good,  the  wonder  of  the 
wise,  the  amazement  of  the 
gods ;  desired  by  those  who 
have  no  part  in  him  and 
precious  to  those  who  have 
the  better  part  in  him,  par 
ent  of  delicacy,  luxury, 
desire,  fondness,  softness, 
grace,  careful  of  the  good, 
uncareful  of  the  evil.  ;•:  : 


104  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

SECTION  FOURTH.  SECTION  FOURTH. 

"  Love  never  faileth  .  .  "In  every  word,  work, 
.  But  now  abideth  faith,  wish,  fear — pilot,  helper, 
hope,  love,  these  three,  and  defender,  saviour,  glory  of 
the  greatest  of  these  is  love,  gods  and  men,  leader  best 
Follow  after  love.  .  ."  and  brightest  in  whose  foot 
steps  let  every  man  follow." 


Note  i. — Paul  was  an  edu-  Note  2. — Agathon  was  a 

cated  Greek-Jew  and  doubt-  tragic  poet  of  Athens,  and 

less   familiar    with    Greek  his  beautiful  encomium  to 

literature.     He  was  a  Ro-  Love  as  recorded  by  Plato 

man  citizen  and  a  resident  is   necessarily   in   a    more 

of  the  great  Greek  City  of  poetic  and  festive  vein  than 

Tarsus  in  Asia  Minor  which  that  of  Paul,  as  it  was  ut- 

was  a  rival  of  Athens  itself,  tered  at  a  banquet  given  to 

His  epistles  contain  many  the  great  men  of  Athens  on 

phrases     evidently     taken  the  occasion  of  his  winning 

from     old    Greek     works,  the  prize  in   poetry  about 

Several  instances  of  these  the  year  41 6  B.C.  Although 

could  be  easily  given,  but  Paul's   encomium   is  more 

it   is   not   here    necessary,  serious  and  religious  in  tone 

Suffice  it  to  say  that  in  the  yet  it  will  be  noted  that  his 

very  Chapter  of  Corinthi-  ideas  are  substantially  iden- 

ans  from  which  we  quote,  tical  with  those  of  Agathon, 

Paul  uses  the  noted  phrase  and  while  it  is   not  to  be 

"for  now  we  see  through  presumed  that  Paul  was  a 

a  glass  darkly,"  which  will  mere  copier  from  Plato,  yet 

be  found  used  by  Socrates  it   is   more   than   probable 

in  the  Phaedo  and  in  other  that  he  was  familiar  with 

places  in  exactly  the  same  and  influenced  by  the  works 

form  and  sense  as  used  by  of  Plato,  as  his  metaphysi- 

Paul. — C.  M.  H.  cal  style  indicates  this,  and 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  105 

it  is  well  known  that  learn 
ed  Jews  in  Alexandria  and 
Palestine  and  the  cities  of 
Greece  and  Rome  were  fa 
miliar  with  Plato's  teach 
ings  and  greatly  influenced 
by  them.— C.  M.  H. 


THE  GOLDEN  RULE. 
FROM  PLATO'S  LAWS,  BOOK  XI,  400  B.  C. 

"  In  the  next  place,  dealings  between  man  and  man 
"  require  to  be  suitably  regulated.  The  principle  of  them 
"  is  very  simple :  Thou  shalt  not  touch  that  which  is 
"  mine,  if  thou  canst  help,  or  remove  the  least  thing  which 
"  belongs  to  me  without  my  consent :  and  may  I,  being 
"  of  sound  mind,  do  to  others  as  I  would  that  they  should 
"  do  to  me." 

Note.  This  is  a  remarkably  clear  and  positive  state 
ment  of  the  famous  Golden  Rule,  uttered  about  one  hun 
dred  years  after  its  statement  by  Confucius,  and  over 
four  hundred  years  before  its  statement  by  Jesus  of 
Nazareth.  It  is  interesting  also  to  here  note  the  careful 
and  judicial  or  legal  manner  in  which  the  rule  is  stated 
by  the  philosophic  Plato  so  as  to  avoid  possible  miscon 
struction  or  perversion  by  the  perverse  mind.  Observe 
carefully  the  effect  of  the  parenthetical  qualifying  clause 
"  being  of  sound  mind  "  which  seems  like  the  careful 
phrasing  of  a  lawyer  in  the  drawing  of  a  statute,  so  as 
to  exclude  misapplications  and  perversions  of  interpreta 
tion,  yet  fully  cover  all  proper  cases.  Now  the  principle 
of  the  Golden  Rule  obviously  is  that  of  a  broad  reciprocal 
justice  and  sympathy  and  a  mutuality  of  self-interest, 

which  makes  a  man's  own  judgment  of  what  he  would 

(106) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  107 

consider  good  and  desirable  for  himself  to  be  his  standard 
for  his  treatment  of  all  other  men. 

Now  no  man  "  of  sound  mind"  will  really  desire  any 
thing  bad,  injurious  or  vicious  for  himself,  and  hence  to 
make  his  judgment  for  self  a  sound  and  true  one,  the 
man  himself  must  first  be  of  sound  or  normal  mind  and 
desires  and  not  one  made  abnormal  by  vice  or  excess  or 
insanity,  otherwise  he  might,  as  in  the  case  of  the 
abandoned  drunkard,  the  libertine  or  madman,  obey 
literally  the  less  carefully  stated  formula  of  Jesus — "All 
things  whatsoever  ye  would  that  men  should  do  to  you,  do  ye 
even  so  to  them  " — and  yet  make  a  great  moral  perversion 
of  the  pure  and  elevated  intention  of  Jesus  to  justify  a 
vicious  end.  For  example,  the  alcoholic  or  opium  de 
generate  would  gladly  welcome  an  intoxication  or  drug 
ging  at  the  expense  of  some  other  man  and  return  the 
compliment  with  reciprocal  good  nature  whenever  he 
could,  thus  literally  obeying  the  loose  and  sweeping  in 
junction  "All  things  whatsoever  ye  would  that  men  should 
do  to  you,  do  you  even  so  to  them." 

But  the  judicial  Plato  evidently  and  clearly  excludes 
this  perversion  by  the  qualifying  clause  "  being  of  sound 
mind"  as  no  man  of  "  sound"  mind  could  apply  the  rule 
in  this  perverted  way,  while  the  man  of  vicious  or  mad 
mind  could  readily  apply  the  formula  of  Jesus  literally 
and  justify  himself  by  it,  something  as  the  witty  Cocotte 
did  by  quoting  the  words  of  Christ  that "  much  would  be 
forgiven  her  because  she  had  loved  much." 

It  is  also  interesting  to  note  that  the  negative  form 
in  which  the  Golden  Rule  was  given  by  Confucius  one 
hundred  years  before  Plato  and  five  hundred  years  before 
Christ,  and  which  Christian  theologians  c.nd  apologists 
usually  try  to  show  is  inferior  to  the  positive  form  of 
Jesus,  is  not  really  inferior  on  examination,  but  if  any- 


io8  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

thing,  legally  and  verbally  superior,  as  it,  like  Plato's 
form,  excludes  perversions  or  is  less  subject  to  perversion. 
For  example,  Confucius'  formula  is  as  follows :  "  What 
you  do  not  like  when  done  to  yourself,  do  not  do  to  others."* 
Now  this,  it  seems  to  us,  is  one  of  the  best  and  simplest 
statements  of  the  Golden  Rule  ever  given,  and,  like  Plato's, 
less  open  to  perversion  than  Christ's,  and  a  little  reflec 
tion  will,  we  think,  show  the  superiority  and  simplicity 
of  this  Confucian  or  negative  form  over  the  Christian 
formula.  Thus,  what  men  desire  to  be  done  to  them 
selves,  as  before  indicated,  is  often  very  vicious,  but  what 
they  do  not  like  to  be  done  to  themselves  is  almost  al 
ways  a  true  evil  to  be  avoided,  and  hence  it  is  an  obvi 
ously  sound,  just  and  true  reciprocal  rule  that  what  they 
thus  recognize  as  an  evil  to  themselves  they  must  avoid 
doing  to  other  men,  and  this  will  be  sound  and  true  in 
almost  all  cases  and  not  easily  perverted,  as  is  the  more 
carelessly  expressed  formula  in  the  Sermon  on  the  Mount. 
Hence  in  basing  the  rule  negatively  on  what  one  does 
not  like  done  to  one's-self,  rather  than  positively  on  what 
one  does  like  to  be  done  to  one's-self,  it  seems  to  be  a  sim 
pler,  safer  and  more  judicious  formula. 

The  form  in  which  the  rule  has  been  stated  by  the 
Confucian  philosopher  Mencius,  who  was  contemporary 
with  Plato,  is  also  very  clear  and  simple,  and  is  probably 
nearest  to  the  positive  formula  of  Christ,  viz.,  "  If  one 
strives  to  treat  others  as  he  would  be  treated  by  them, 
he  will  not  fail  to  come  near  the  perfect  life." 

This  latter  form  is  quoted  in  Prof.  James'  lecture  on 
The  Ethics  of  The  Chinese  Sages,  and  is  perhaps  one  of 
the  most  beautiful  forms  of  the  positive  statement  of  the 
rule  ever  given. — C.  M.  H. 

•  See  Legge's  Chinese  Classics,  also  Prof.  James'  lecture  on  Ethics  of  Chinese 
Sages. 


RETURN    NOT   EVIL    FOR   EVIL. 
SOCRATES'  ANSWER  TO  CRITO  IN  PLATO'S  CRITO. 

"Then  we  must  do  not  wrong.  Nor  when  injured, 
injure  in  return,  for  we  must  injure  no  one  at  all." 

"Then  we  ought  not  to  retaliate  or  render  evil  for  evil 
to  any  one,  whatever  evil  we  may  have  suffered  from  him. 
But  I  would  have  you  consider,  Crito,  whether  you 
really  meant  what  you  were  saying.  For  this  opinion 
has  never  been  held,  and  never  will  be  held,  by  any  con 
siderable  number  of  persons ;  and  those  who  are  agreed 
and  those  who  are  not  agreed  upon  this  point  have  no 
common  ground,  and  can  only  despise  one  another  when 
they  see  how  widely  they  differ.  Tell  me,  then,  whether 
you  agree  with  and  assent  to  my  first  principle,  that 
neither  injury  nor  retaliation,  nor  warding  off  evil  by 
evil  is  ever  right.  And  shall  that  be  the  premise  of  our 
argument  ?  Or  do  you  decline  and  dissent  from  this  ? 
For  this  has  been  of  old  and  is  still  my  opinion ;  but,  if 
you  are  of  another  opinion,  let  me  hear  what  you  have 
to  say.  If,  however,  you  remain  of  the  same  mind  as 
formerly,  I  will  proceed  to  the  next  step. 

" '  Listen,  then,  Socrates,  to  us  who  have  brought  you 
up.  Think  not  of  life  and  children  first,  and  of  justice 
afterwards,  but  of  justice  first,  that  you  may  be  justi 
fied  before  the  princes  of  the  world  below.  For  neither 

(109) 


no  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

will  you  nor  any  that  belong  to  you  be  happier  or  holier 
or  juster  in  this  life,  or  happier  in  another,  if  you  do  as 
Crito  bids.  Now  you  depart  in  innocence,  a  sufferer  and 
not  a  doer  of  evil ;  a  victim,  not  of  the  laws,  but  of  men. 
But  if  you  go  forth,  returning  evil  for  evil,  and  injury 
for  injury,  breaking  the  covenants  and  agreements  which 
you  have  made  with  us,  and  wronging  those  whom  you 
ought  least  to  wrong,  that  is  to  say,  yourself,  your 
friends,  your  country,  and  us,  we  shall  be  angry  with 
you  while  you  live,  and  our  brethren,  the  laws  in  the 
wrorld  below,  will  receive  you  as  an  enemy ;  for  they 
will  know  that  you  have  done  your  best  to  destroy  us. 
Listen,  then,  to  us  and  not  to  Crito.' 

"  This  is  the  voice  which  I  seem  to  hear  murmuring 
in  my  ears,  like  the  sound  of  the  flute  in  the  ears  of  the 
mystic  ;  that  voice,  I  say,  is  humming  in  my  ears,  and 
prevents  me  from  hearing  any  other.  And  I  know  that 
anything  more  which  you  may  say  will  be  vain.  Yet 
speak,  if  you  have  anything  to  say. 

"  CR.     I  have  nothing  to  say,  Socrates. 

"Soc.  Then  let  me  follow  the  intimations  of  the 
will  of  God." 


GOOD,  NOT  !PLEA$UfcE,  THE  SUPREME  AIM 
OF   CONDUCT. 

FROM  PLATO'S  GORGIAS. 

"Socrates.  Because,  if  you  remember,  Polus  and  I 
agreed  that  all  our  actions  are  to  be  done  for  the  sake  of 
the  good ;  and  will  you  agree  with  us  in  saying,  that  the 
good  is  the  end  of  all  our  actions,  and  that  all  our  actions 
are  to  be  done  for  the  sake  of  the  good,  and  not  the 
good  for  the  sake  of  them  ? — will  you  give  a  third  vote 
for  that  proposition  ? 

"Cattias.     I  will. 

"Socrates.  Then  pleasure  as  well  as  all  else  is  for  the 
sake  of  good,  and  not  good  for  the  sake  of  pleasure  ? 

"Callias.     To  be  sure." 


(in) 


SUICIDE  CONDEMNED. 

SOCRATES  IN  THE  PH^EDO. 

"  Then  he,  or  any  man  who  has  the  spirit  of  philoso 
phy,  will  be  willing  to  die,  though  he  will  not  take  his 
own  life,  for  that  is  held  not  to  be  right. 

"  Then  tell  me,  Socrates,  why  is  suicide  held  not  to  be 
right  ?  as  I  have  certainly  heard  Philolaus  affirm  when 
he  was  staying  with  us  at  Thebes ;  and  there  are  others 
who  say  the  same,  although  none  of  them  has  ever  made 
me  understand  him. 

"  But  do  your  best,  replied  Socrates,  and  the  day  may 
come  when  you  will  understand.  I  suppose  that  you 
wonder  why,  as  most  things  which  are  evil  may  be  ac 
cidentally  good,  this  is  to  be  the  only  exception  (for 
may  not  death,  too,  be  better  than  life  in  some  cases  ?) 
and  why,  when  a  man  is  better  dead,  he  is  not  permitted 
to  be  his  own  benefactor,  but  must  wait  for  the  hand  of 
another. 

"  I  admit  the  appearance  of  inconsistency,  replied 
Socrates,  but  there  may  not  be  any  real  inconsistency 
after  all  in  this.  There  is  a  doctrine  uttered  in  secret 
that  man  is  a  prisoner  who  has  no  right  to  open  the 
door  of  his  prison  and  run  away  ;  this  is  a  great  mystery 
which  I  do  not  quite  understand.  Yet  I  too  believe  that 

(112) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  113 

the  gods  are  our  guardians,  and  that  we  are  a  possession 
of  theirs. 

"  And  if  one  of  your  own  possessions,  an  ox  or  an  ass, 
for  example,  took  the  liberty  of  putting  himself  out  of 
the  way  when  you  had  given  no  intimation  of  your  wish 
that  he  should  die,  would  you  not  be  angry  with  him, 
and  would  you  not  punish  him  if  you  could  ? 

"  Then  there  may  be  reason  in  saying  that  a  man 
should  wait,  and  not  take  his  own  life  until  God  sum 
mons  him,  as  he  is  now  summoning  me." 


A    VIRTUOUS   LIFE,    FEARLESS   DEATH,  AND 

GLORIOUS  HEREAFTER,  COMMENDED 

TO  ALL  MEN. 

SOCRATES  IN  THE  GORGIAS. 

"  For  no  man  but  an  utter  fool  and  coward  is  afraid  of 
death  itself,  but  he  is  afraid  of  doing  wrong.  For  to  go 
to  the  world  below,  having  a  soul  which  is  like  a  vessel 
full  of  injustice,  is  the  last  and  worst  of  all  evils. 

"  Now  I,  Callicles,  am  persuaded  of  the  truth  of  these 
things,  and  I  consider  how  I  shall  present  my  soul  whole 
and  undefiled  before  the  judge  in  that  day.  Renouncing 
the  honors  at  which  the  world  aims,  I  desire  only  to 
know  the  truth,  and  to  live  as  well  as  I  can,  and  when 
the  time  comes,  to  die.  And,  to  the  utmost  of  my  power, 
I  exhort  all  other  men  to  do  the  same.  And,  in  return 
for  your  exhortation  of  me,  I  exhort  you  also  to  take 
part  in  the  great  combat,  which  is  the  combat  of  life, 
and  greater  than  every  other  earthly  conflict. 

"Follow  me  then,  and  I  will  lead  you  where  you  will 
be  happy  in  life  and  after  death,  as  your  own  argument 
shows.  And  never  mind  if  some  one  despises  you  as  a 
fool,  and  insults  you,  if  he  has  a  mind  ;  let  him  strike 
you,  by  Zeus,  and  do  you  be  of  good  cheer  and  do  not 

(114) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  1 1 5 

mind  the  insulting  blow,  for  you  will  never  come  to  any 
harm  in  the  practice  of  virtue,  if  you  are  a  really  good 
and  true  man. 

"  Let  us  then,  take  this  discourse  as  our  guide,  which 
signifies  to  us,  that  the  best  way  of  life  is  to  practice 
justice  and  every  virtue  in  life  and  death.  This  way  let 
us  go ;  and  in  this  exhort  all  men  to  follow,  not  in  that 
way  in  which  you  trust  and  in  which  you  exhort  me  to 
follow  you  ;  for  that  way,  Callicles,  is  nothing  worth." 


THE    SOUL'S    IMPROVEMENT,    NOT     WORLDLY 
SUCCESS,  THE  TRUE  AIM  OF  MAN'S  LIFE. 

SOCRATES  IN  PLATO'S  APOLOGY. 

"  Men  of  Athens,  I  honor  and  love  you  :  but  I  shall 
obey  God  rather  than  you,  and  while  I  have  life  and 
strength  I  shall  never  cease  from  the  practice  and  teach 
ing  of  philosophy,  exhorting  any  one  whom  I  meet  after 
my  manner,  and  convincing  him,  saying :  O  my  friend, 
why  do  you,  who  are  a  citizen  of  the  great  and  mighty 
and  wise  city  of  Athens,  care  so  much  about  laying  up 
the  greatest  amount  of  money  and  honor  and  reputation, 
and  so  little  about  wisdom  and  truth  and  the  greatest 
improvement  of  the  soul,  which  you  never  regard  or 
heed  at  all  ?  Are  you  not  ashamed  of  this  ?  And  if  the 
person  with  whom  I  am  arguing,  says  Yes,  but  I  do  care  ; 
I  do  not  depart  or  let  him  go  at  once ;  I  interrogate  and 
examine  and  cross-examine  him,  and  if  I  think  that  he 
has  no  virtue,  but  only  says  that  he  has,  I  reproach  him 
with  undervaluing  the  greater,  and  overvaluing  the  less. 
And  this  I  should  say  to  every  one  whom  I  meet,  young 
and  old,  citizen  and  alien,  but  especially  to  the  citizens, 
inasmuch  as  they  are  my  brethren.  For  this  is  the  com 
mand  to  God,  as  I  would  have  you  know  ;  and  I  believe 

that  to  this  day  no  greater  good  has  ever  happened  in  the 

(116) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  1 1 7 

state  than  my  service  to  the  God.  For  I  do  nothing  but 
go  about  persuading  you  all,  old  and  young  alike,  not  to 
take  thought  for  your  persons  or  your  properties,  but 
first  and  chiefly  to  care  about  the  greatest  improvement 
of  the  soul.  I  tell  you  that  virtue  is  not  given  by  money, 
but  that  from  virtue  come  money  and  every  other  good 
of  man,  public  as  well  as  private.  This  is  my  teaching, 
and  if  this  is  the  doctrine  which  corrupts  the  youth,  my 
influence  is  ruinous  indeed.  But  if  anyone  says  that  this 
is  not  my  teaching,  he  is  speaking  an  untruth.  Where 
fore,  O  men  of  Athens,  I  say  to  you,  do  as  Anytus  bids 
or  not  as  Anytus  bids,  and  either  acquit  me  or  not ;  but 
whatever  you  do,  know  that  I  shall  never  alter  my  ways, 
not  even  if  I  have  to  die  many  times." 


THE  TRUE  LIFE,  THE  LIFE  OF   THE   SOUL,  NOT 
OF  THE  WORLD  OR  OF  THE  BODY. 

SOCRATES  IN  THE  PH^EDO. 

"  Whereas,  Simmias,  the  rest  of  the  world  are  of  opinion 
that  a  life  which  has  no  bodily  pleasures  and  no  part  in 
them,  is  not  worth  having :  but  that  he  who  thinks 
nothing  of  bodily  pleasures  is  almost  as  though  he  were 
dead. 

"  What  again  shall  we  say  of  the  actual  acquirement 
of  knowledge  ? — is  the  body,  if  invited  to  share  in  the 
inquiry,  a  hinderer  or  a  helper  ?  I  mean  to  say,  have 
sight  and  hearing  any  truth  in  them  ?  Are  they  not,  as 
the  poets  are  always  telling  us,  inaccurate  witnesses  ?  and 
yet,  if  even  they  are  inaccurate  and  indistinct,  what  is  to 
be  said  of  the  other  senses  ? — for  you  will  allow  that  they 
are  the  best  of  them  ? 

"  Then  when  does  the  soul  attain  truth  ? — for  in  at 
tempting  to  consider  anything  in  company  with  the  body 
she  is  obviously  deceived. 

"  Then  must  not  existence  be  revealed  to  her  in  thought, 
if  at  all? 

"  And  thought  is  best  when  the  mind  is  gathered  into 
herself  and  none  of  these  things  trouble  her — neither 

sounds  nor  sights  nor  pain  nor  any  pleasure, — when  she 

(118) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  119 

has  as  little  as  possible  to  do  with  the  body,  and  has  no 
bodily  sense  or  feeling,  but  is  aspiring  after  being  ? 

"  And  in  this  the  philosopher  dishonors  the  body ;  his 
soul  runs  away  from  the  body  and  desires  to  be  alone 
and  by  herself  ? 

"  In  this  present  life,  I  reckon  that  we  make  the  near 
est  approach  to  knowledge  when  we  have  the  least  pos 
sible  concern  or  interest  in  the  body,  and  are  not  saturated 
with  the  bodily  nature,  but  remain  pure  until  the  hour 
when  God  himself  is  pleased  to  release  us.  And  then 
the  foolishness  of  the  body  will  be  cleared  away  and  we 
shall  be  pure  and  hold  converse  with  other  pure  souls, 
and  know  of  ourselves  the  clear  light  everywhere  :  and 
this  is  surely  the  light  of  truth.  For  no  impure  thing  is 
allowed  to  approach  the  pure.  These  are  the  sort  of 
words,  Simmias,  which  the  true  lovers  of  wisdom  can 
not  help  saying  to  one  another,  and  thinking.  You  will 
agree  with  me  in  that  ? 

"  But  if  this  is  true,  O  my  friend,  then  there  is  great 
hope  that,  going  whither  I  go,  I  shall  there  be  satisfied 
with  that  which  has  been  the  chief  concern  of  you  and 
me  in  our  past  lives.  And  now  that  the  hour  of  depart 
ure  is  appointed  to  me,  this  is  the  hope  with  which  I 
depart,  and  not  I  only,  but  every  man  who  believes  that 
he  has  his  mind  purified. 

"And  what  is  purification  but  the  separation  of  the  soul 
from  the  body,  as  I  was  saying  before  ;  the  habit  of  the 
soul  gathering  and  collecting  herself  into  herself,  out  of 
all  the  courses  of  the  body ;  the  dwelling  in  her  own 
place  alone,  as  in  another  life,  so  also  in  this,  as  far  as 
she  can ;  the  release  of  the  soul  from  the  chains  of  the 
body?" 


DEATH  IS  A  GOOD  AND  NOT  AN  EVIL. 
SOCRATES  IN  THE   ''APOLOGY." 

"  Let  us  reflect  in  another  way,  and  we  shall  see  that 
there  is  great  reason  to  hope  that  death  is  a  good,  for 
one  of  two  things :  either  death  is  a  state  of  nothingness 
and  utter  unconsciousness,  or,  as  men  say,  there  is  a 
change  and  migration  of  the  soul  from  this  world  to 
another.  Now  if  you  suppose  that  there  is  no  con 
sciousness,  but  a  sleep  like  the  sleep  of  him  who  is  un 
disturbed  even  by  the  sight  of  dreams,  death  will  be  an 
unspeakable  gain.  For  if  a  person  were  to  select  the 
night  in  which  his  sleep  was  undisturbed  even  by  dreams, 
and  were  to  compare  with  this  the  other  days  and  nights 
of  his  life,  and  then  were  to  tell  us  how  many  days  and 
nights  he  had  passed  in  the  course  of  his  life  better,  and 
more  pleasantly  than  this  one,  I  think  that  any  man,  I 
will  not  say  a  private  man,  but  even  the*  great  king  will 
not  find  many  such  days  or  nights,  when  compared  with 
the  others.  Now,  if  death  is  like  this,  I  say  that  to  die 
is  gain  ;  for  eternity  is  then  only  a  single  night.  But  if 
death  is  the  journey  to  another  place,  and  there,  as  men 
say,  all  the  dead  are,  what  good,  O  my  friends  and 
judges,  can  be  greater  than  this  ?  If  indeed  when  the 
pilgrim  arrives  in  the  world  below,  he  is  delivered  from 
the  professors  of  justice  in  this  world,  and  finds  the  true 
judges  who  are  said  to  give  judgment  there,  Minos  and 

(120) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  121 

Rhadamanthus  and  Aeacus  and  Triptolemus,  and  other 
sons  of  God  who  were  righteous  in  their  own  life,  that 
pilgrimage  will  be  worth  making.  What  would  not  a 
man  give  if  he  might  converse  with  Orpheus  and 
Musseus  and  Hesiod  and  Homer  ?  Nay,  if  this  be  true, 
let  me  die  again  and  again.  I,  too,  shall  have  a  wonder 
ful  interest  in  a  place  where  I  can  converse  with  Pala- 
medes,  and  Ajax  the  son  of  Telamon,  and  other  heroes 
of  old,  who  have  suffered  death  through  an  unjust  judg 
ment  :  and  there  will  be  no  small  pleasure,  as  I  think, 
in  comparing  my  own  sufferings  with  theirs.  Above 
all,  I  shall  be  able  to  continue  my  search  into  true  and 
false  knowledge  ;  as  in  this  world,  so  also  in  that ;  I 
shall  find  out  who  is  wise,  and  who  pretends  to  be  wise, 
and  is  not.  What  would  not  a  man  give,  O  judges,  to 
be  able  to  examine  the  leader  of  the  great  Trojan  ex 
pedition  :  or  Odysseus  or  Sisyphus,  or  numberless  others, 
men  and  women  too  !  What  infinite  delight  would  there 
be  in  conversing  with  them  and  asking  them  questions  ! 
For  in  that  world  they  do  not  put  a  man  to  death  for 
this  ;  certainly  not.  For  besides  being  happier  in  that 
world  than  in  this,  they  will  be  immortal,  if  what  is 
said  is  true. 

"Wherefore,  O  judges,  be  of  good  cheer  about  death, 
and  know  this  of  a  truth — that  no  evil  can  happen  to  a 
good  man,  either  in  life  or  after  death.  He  and  his  are 
not  neglected  by  the  gods ;  nor  has  my  own  approaching 
end  happened  by  mere  chance.  But  I  see  clearly  that 
to  die  and  be  released  was  better  for  me  ;  and  therefore 
the  oracle  gave  no  sign.  For  which  reason,  also,  I  am 
not  angry  with  my  accusers  or  my  condemners;  they 
have  done  me  no  harm,  although  neither  of  them  meant 
to  do  me  any  good ;  and  for  this  I  may  gently  blame 
them." 


THE  IMMORTALITY  OF  THE  SOUL  AND  ITS 

FUTURE  REWARDS  AND  PUNISHMENTS. 

FROM  PLATO'S  PH^EDO. 

Introductory  Note.  There  can  be  found  no  text  in 
the  Old  or  New  Testament  in  which  the  doctrines  of  the 
immortal  soul  and  its  future  states,  as  believed  in  by  the 
majority  of  the  Christian  world,  are  so  fully  and  clearly 
set  forth  as  in  these  extracts  from  Plato,  written  nearly 
five  hundred  years  before  any  book  of  the  New  Testa 
ment  was  composed.  All  texts  in  the  Old  Testament 
quoted  for  immortality  and  future  state  are  very  meager 
and  vague  except  a  few  texts  in  the  later  books  such  as 
those  from  Ecclesiastes,  180  B.  C.,  Daniel,  165  B.  C., 
and  Wisdom,  40  A.  D.,  and  it  will  thus  be  seen  that 
Plato's  Phaedo  is  more  than  two  hundred  years  older 
than  the  earliest  of  these  three  Old  Testament  Books, 
which  contain  the  best  texts  on  immortality.  See  supple 
mentary  notes  on  p.  130. — C.  M.  H. 


(122) 


SOCRATES  ON  IMMORTALITY. 

CONVERSATION  OF  SOCRATES  WITH  HIS  DISCIPLES 

SIMMIAS  AND  CEDES  IN  HIS  PRISON  BEFORE  HIS  DEATH. 

Date399,B.  C 

"  Then  reflect  Cebes :  is  not  the  conclusion  of  the  whole 
matter  this, — that  the  soul  is  in  the  very  likeness  of  the 
divine,  and  immortal,  and  intelligible,  and  uniform,  and 
indissoluble,  and  unchangeable ;  and  the  body  is  in  the 
very  likeness  of  the  human,  and  mortal,  and  unintelligi 
ble,  and  multiform,  and  dissoluble,  and  changeable? 
Can  this  my  dear  Cebes,  be  denied  ? 

"  And  are  we  to  suppose  that  the  soul,  which  is  invis 
ible,  in  passing  to  the  true  Hades,  which  like  her  is  in 
visible,  and  pure,  and  noble,  and  on  her  way  to  the  good 
and  wise  God,  whither,  if  God  will,  my  .soul  is  also  soon 
to  go, — that  the  soul,  I  repeat,  if  this  be  her  nature  and 
origin,  is  blown  away  and  perishes  immediately,  on 
quitting  the  body,  as  the  many  say?  That  can  never 
be,  my  dear  Simmias  and  Cebes.  The  truth  rather  is, 
that  the  soul  which  is  pure  at  departing  draws  after  her 
no  bodily  taint,  having  never  voluntarily  had  connection 
with  the  body,  and  which  she  is  ever  avoiding,  herself 
gathered  into  herself  (for  such  abstraction  has  been  the 

(123) 


124  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

study  of  her  life).  And  what  does  this  mean  but  that 
she  has  been  a  true  disciple  of  philosophy,  and  has 
practiced  how  to  die  easily  ?  And  is  not  philosophy  the 
practice  of  death  ? 

"  That  soul,  I  say,  herself  invisible,  departs  to  the 
invisible  world, — to  the  divine  and  immortal  and  ration 
al:  thither  arriving,  she  lives  in  bliss  and  is  released 
from  the  error  and  folly  of  men,  their  fears  and  wild 
passions,  and  all  other  human  ills,  and  forever  dwells, 
as  they  say  of  the  initiated,  in  company  with  the  gods  ? 
Is  not  this  true,  Cebes  ? 

"  But  the  soul  which  has  been  polluted  and  is  impure 
at  the  time  of  her  departure,  and  is  the  companion  and 
servant  of  the  body  always,  and  is  in  love  with  and 
fascinated  by  the  body  and  by  the  desires  and  pleasures 
of  the  body,  until  she  is  led  to  believe  that  the  truth  only 
exists  in  a  bodily  form,  which  a  man  may  touch  and  see 
and  taste  and  use  for  the  purposes  of  his  lusts, — the 
soul,  I  mean,  accustomed  to  hate  and  fear  and  avoid  the 
intellectual  principle,  which  to  the  bodily  eye  is  dark 
and  invisible,  and  can  be  attained  only  by  philosophy ; 
do  you  suppose  that  such  a  soul  as  this  will  depart  pure 
and  unalloyed  ? 

"  And  this,  Cebes,  is  the  reason  why  the  true  lovers  of 
knowledge  are  temperate  and  brave;  and  not  for  the 
reason  which  the  world  gives. 

"  Certainly  not !  For  not  in  that  way  does  the  soul 
of  a  philosopher  reason ;  she  will  not  ask  philosophy  to 
release  her  in  order  that  when  released  she  may  deliver 
herself  up  again  to  the  thraldom  of  pleasures  and  pains 
doing  a  work  only  to  be  undone  again,  weaving  instead 
of  unweaving  her  Penelope's  web.  But  she  will  make 
herself  a  calm  of  passion,  and  follow  Reason,  and  dwell 
in  her,  beholding  the  true  and  divine  (which  is  not  mat- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  125 

ter  of  opinion),  and  thence  derive  nourishment.  Thus 
she  seeks  to  live  while  she  lives,  and  after  death  she 
hopes  to  go  to  her  own  kindred  and  to  be  freed  from 
human  ills.  Never  fear,  Simmiasand  Cebes,  that  a  soul 
which  has  been  thus  nurtured  and  has  had  these  pursuits, 
will  at  her  departure  from  the  body,  be  scattered  and 
blown  away  by  the  winds  and  be  nowhere  and  nothing. 

"There  is  nothing  new,  he  said,  in  what  I  am  about 
to  tell  you ;  but  only  what  I  have  been  always  and 
everywhere  repeating  in  the  previous  discussion  and  on 
other  occasions :  I  want  to  show  you  the  nature  of  that 
cause  which  has  occupied  my  thoughts,  and  I  shall  have 
to  go  back  to  those  familiar  words  which  are  in  the 
mouth  of  every  one,  and  first  of  all  assume  that  there 
is  an  absolute  beauty  and  goodness,  and  greatness,  and 
the  like  ;  grant  me  this,  and  I  hope  to  be  able  to  show 
you  the  nature  of  the  cause,  and  to  prove  the  immor 
tality  of  the  soul. 

"  Yes,  replied  Socrates,  all  men  will  agree  that  God, 
and  the  essential  form  of  life,  and  the  immortal  in  gen 
eral,  will  never  perish. 

"  Then  when  death  attacks  a  man,  the  mortal  portion 
of  him  may  be  supposed  to  die,  but  the  immortal  goes 
out  of  the  way  of  death  and  is  preserved  safe  and  sound  ? 

"  Then,  Cebes,  beyond  question,  the  soul  is  immortal 
and  imperishable,  and  our  souls  will  truly  exist  in  an 
other  world  ! 

"  But  then,  O  my  friends,  if  the  soul  is  really  im 
mortal,  what  care  should  be  taken  of  her,  not  only  in 
respect  of  the  portion  of  time  which  is  called  life,  but  of 
eternity !  And  the  danger  of  neglecting  her  from  this 
point  of  view  does  indeed  appear  to  be  awful.  If  death 
had  only  been  the  end  of  all,  the  wicked  would  have  had 
a  good  bargain  in  dying,  for  they  would  have  been 


126  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

happily  quit,  not  only  of  their  body,  but  of  their  own 
evil  together  with  their  souls.  But  now,  as  the  soul 
plainly  appears  to  be  immortal,  there  is  no  release  or 
salvation  from  evil  except  the  attainment  of  the  highest 
virtue  and  wisdom.  For  the  soul  when  on  her  progress 
to  the  world  below  takes  nothing  with  her  but  nurture 
and  education  ;  which  are  indeed  said  greatly  to  benefit 
or  greatly  to  injure  the  departed,  at  the  very  beginning 
of  his  pilgrimage  in  the  other  world. 

"  For  after  death,  as  they  say,  the  genius  of  each  in 
dividual,  to  whom  he  belonged  in  life,  leads  him  to  a 
certain  place  in  which  the  dead  are  gathered  together 
for  judgment,  whence  they  go  into  the  world  below,  fol 
lowing  the  guide,  who  is  appointed  to  conduct  them 
from  this  world  to  the  other  :  and  when  they  have  there 
received  their  due,  and  remained  their  time,  another 
guide  brings  them  back  again  after  many  revolutions  of 
ages.  Now  this  journey  to  the  other  world  is  not,  as 
Aeschylus  says  in  the  Telephus,  a  single  and  straight 
path, — no  guide  would  be  wanted  for  that,  and  no  one 
could  miss  a  single  path ;  but  there  are  many  partings 
of  the  road,  and  windings,  as  I  must  infer  from  the  rites 
and  sacrifices  which  are  offered  to  the  gods  below  in 
places  where  three  ways  meet  on  earth.  The  wise  and 
orderly  soul  is  conscious  of  her  situation,  and  follows 
in  the  path  ;  but  the  soul  which  desires  the  body,  and 
which,  as  I  was  relating  before,  has  long  been  fluttering 
about  the  lifeless  frame  and  the  world  of  sight,  is  after 
many  struggles  and  many  sufferings  hardly  and  with 
violence  carried  away  by  her  attendant  genius,  and  when 
she  arrives  at  the  place  where  the  other  souls  are  gather 
ed,  if  she  be' impure  and  have  done  impure  deeds,  or  been 
concerned  in  foul  murders  or  other  crimes  which  are 
the  brothers  of  these,  and  the  works  of  brothers  in 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  127 

crime, — from  that  soul  every  one  flees  and  turns  away  ; 
no  one  will  be  her  companion,  no  one  her  guide,  but 
alone  she  wanders  in  extremity  of  evil  until  certain 
times  are  fulfilled,  and  when  they  are  fulfilled,  she  is 
borne  irresistibly  to  her  own  fitting  habitation  ;  as  every 
pure  and  just  soul  which  has  passed  through  life  in  the 
company  and  under  the  guidance  of  the  gods,  has  also 
her  own  proper  home. 

"  Such  is  the  nature  of  the  other  world  ;  and  when  the 
dead  arrive  at  the  place  to  which  the  genius  of  each 
severally  conveys  them,  first  of  all,  they  have  sentence 
passed  upon  them,  as  they  have  lived  well  and  piously 
or  not.  And  those  who  appear  to  have  lived  neither 
well  nor  ill,  go  to  the  river  Acheron,  and  mount  such 
conveyances  as  they  can  get,  and  are  carried  in  them  to 
the  lake,  and  there  they  dwell  and  are  purified  of  their 
evil  deeds,  and  suffer  the  penalty  of  the  wrongs  which 
they  have  done  to  others,  and  are  absolved,  and  receive 
the  rewards  of  their  good  deeds  according  to  their  de 
serts.  But  those  who  appear  to  be  incurable  by  reason 
of  the  greatness  of  their  crimes — who  have  committed 
many  and  terrible  deeds  of  sacrilege,  murders  foul  and 
violent,  or  the  like — such  are  hurled  into  Tartarus, 
which  is  their  suitable  destiny,  and  they  never  come  out. 
Those  again  who  have  committed  crimes,  which,  al 
though  great,  are  not  unpardonable — who  in  a  moment 
of  anger,  for  example,  have  done  violence  to  a  father  or 
a  mother,  and  have  repented  for  the  remainder  of  their 
lives,  or  who  kave  taken  the  life  of  another  under  the 
like  extenuating  circumstances— these  are  plunged  into 
Tartarus,  the  pains  of  which  they  are  compelled  to  un 
dergo  for  a  year,  but  at  the  end  of  the  year  the  wave 
casts  them  forth— mere  homicides  by  way  of  Cocytus, 
parricides  and  matricides  by  Pyriphlegethon— and  they 


128  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers, 

are  borne  to  the  Acherusian  lake,  and  there  they  lift  up 
their  voices  and  call  upon  the  victims  whom  they  have 
slain  or  wronged,  to  have  pity  on  them,  and  to  receive 
them,  and  to  let  them  come  out  of  the  river  into  the  lake. 
And  if  they  prevail,  then  they  come  forth  and  cease  from 
their  troubles ;  but  if  not,  they  are  carried  back  again 
into  Tartarus  and  from  thence  into  the  rivers  unceasing 
ly,  until  they  obtain  mercy  from  those  whom  they  have 
wronged,  for  that  is  the  sentence  inflicted  upon  them  by 
their  judges.  Those  who  are  remarkable  for  having 
led  holy  lives  are  released  from  this  earthly  prison,  and 
go  to  their  pure  home  which  is  above,  and  dwell  in  the 
purer  earth;  and  those  who  have  duly  purified  them 
selves  with  philosophy,  live  henceforth  altogether  with 
out  the  body,  in  mansions  fairer  far  than  these,  which 
may  not  be  described,  and  of  which  the  time  would  fail 
me  to  tell. 

"  Wherefore,  Simmias,  seeing  all  these  things,  what 
ought  not  we  to  do  in  order  to  obtain  virtue  and  wisdom 
in  this  life?  Fair  is  the  prize,  and  the  hope  great. 

"  I  do  not  mean  to  affirm  that  the  description  which  I 
have  given  of  the  soul  and  her  mansions  is  exactly 
true — a  man  of  sense  ought  hardly  to  say  that.  But  I  do 
say  that,  inasmuch  as  the  soul  is  shown  to  be  immortal, 
he  may  venture  to  think,  not  improperly  or  unworthily, 
that  something  of  the  kind  is  true.  The  venture  is  a 
glorious  one,  and  he  ought  to  comfort  himself  with 
words  like  these,  which  is  the  reason  why  I  lengthen 
out  the  tale.  Wherefore,  I  say,  let  a  man  be  of  good 
cheer  about  his  soul,  who  has  cast  away  the  pleasures 
and  ornaments  of  the  body  as  alien  to  him,  and  rather 
hurtful  in  their  effects,  and  has  followed  after  the 
pleasures  of  knowledge  in  this  life  ;  who  has  adorned 
the  soul  in  her  own  proper  jewels,  which  are  temperance, 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  129 

and  justice,  and  courage,  and  nobility,  and  truth — in 
these  arrayed,  she  is  ready  to  go  on  her  journey  to  the 
world  below,  when  her  time  comes.  You,  Simmiasand 
Cebes,  and  all  other  men,  will  depart  at  some  time  or 
other.  Me  already,  as  the  tragic  poet  would  say,  the 
voice  of  fate  calls.  Soon  I  must  drink  the  poison." 


SUPPLEMENTARY  NOTES  ON  IMMORTALITY. 

BEST  TEXTS  ON   IMMORTALITY  FROM  THE  OLD  TESTA 
MENT  AS  COMPARED  WITH  PLATO'S 


The  three  clearest  extracts  from  the  Old  Testament 
on  the  Immortality  of  the  Soul,  referred  to  in  the  intro 
ductory  note,  are  as  follows  : 

ist.  —  Daniel,  Chapter  XII,  verses  2  and  3. 

"And  many  of  them  that  sleep  in  the  dust  of  the  earth  shall 
awake,  some  to  everlasting  life  and  some  to  shame  and  everlast 
ing  contempt. 

"And  they  that  be  wise  shall  shine  as  the  brightness  of  the 
firmament  :  and  they  that  turn  many  to  righteousness  as  the  stars 
forever  and  ever." 

2nd.  —  Ecclesiastes,  Chapter  XII,  verse  7. 

"  Then  shall  the  dust  return  to  the  earth  as  it  was,  and  the  spirit 
shall  return  unto  God  who  gave  it." 

We  have  used  the  St.  James  Version  in  both  quota 
tions,  above  given,  but  the  language  and  ideas  are  sub 
stantially  the  same  in  both  the  Jewish  and  Douay  ver 
sions. 

3rd.  —  The  Book  of  Wisdom,  Douay  Version,  Chapter 
II,  verses  23  and  24  : 

"  For  God  created  man  incorruptible  and  to  the  image  of  his 
own  likeness  he  made  him-" 

*'  But  by  the  envy  of  the  devil  death  came  into  the  world." 

Chapter  III,  verses  i,  2,  3,  4  : 

44  But  the  souls  of  the  just  are  in  the  hand  of  God,  and  the  tor 
ment  of  death  shall  not  touch  them." 

4<  In  the  sight  of  the  unwise  they  seemed  to  die  ;  and  their  de 
parture  was  taken  for  misery." 

"And  their  going  away  from  us  for  utter  destruction  :  but  they 
are  in  peace."  (130) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  131 

"  And  though  in  the  sight  of  men  they  suffered  torments,  their 
hope  is  full  of  immortality. " 

Chapter  V,  verses  15,  1 6  and  17  : 

"  For  the  hope  of  the  wicked  is  as  dust,  which  is  blown  away 
with  the  wind  ;  and  as  a  thin  froth  which  is  dispersed  by  the  storm  ; 
and  as  smoke  that  is  scattered  abroad  by  the  wind  ;  and  as  the 
remembrance  of  a  guest  of  one  day  that  passeth  by." 

"  But  the  just  shall  live  for  evermore  :  and  their  reward  is  with 
the  Lord,  and  the  care  of  them  with  the  Most  High." 

"  Therefore  shall  they  receive  a  kingdom  of  glory,  and  a  crown 
of  beauty  at  the  hand  of  the  Lord  :  for  with  his  right  hand  he  will 
cover  them  ;  and  with  his  holy  arm  he  will  defend  them." 

Now  it  is  interesting  to  note  that  the  above  texts  are 
perhaps  the  very  best  and  clearest  that  can  be  found 
anywhere  in  the  Old  Testament  for  the  doctrine  of  the 
immortality  of  the  soul,  and  yet  these  best  Hebrew  texts 
when  compared  to  the  Platonic  texts  already  given  are 
obviously  very  vague  and  meagre  and  also  of  much  later 
date.  Many  other  texts  are  quoted  and  used  to  prove 
immortality  by  Jews  and  Christians  from  the  Psalms  and 
from  Job,  Isaiah  and  Hosea,  but  they  will  all  be  found 
to  be  much  more  vague  and  meagre  than  the  Hebrew 
texts  now  given  and  of  very  doubtful  significance  com 
pared  to  them. 

It  will  be  now  further  interesting  to  consider  the  rela 
tive  dates  of  these  best  Hebrew7  texts  in  comparison  with 
that  of  the  Platonic  texts  previously  given.  Thus 
Ecclesiastes,  which  contains  the  text  which  is  probably 
most  known  and  used  as  a  proof  for  immortality,  not 
withstanding  its  very  doubtful  significance,  dates  only 
from  about  180  B.  C.,  whereas  Plato's  Phsedo  antedates 
it  by  more  than  two  hundred  years.  Daniel,  which  con 
tains  some  very  good  texts  for  immortality,  dates  only 
about  165  B.  C.,  and  Wisdom,  which  has  some  of  the 
best  and  clearest  texts,  dates  actually  within  the 
Christian  Era,  or  about  40  A.  D.* 

'See  "  The  Bible  of  To-Day,11  by  John  W.  Chadwick. 


132  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

How  the  Jewish  people  could  have  lived  so  long  in 
a  land  like  Egypt,  which  was  saturated  with  the  doctrine 
of  immortality,  without  imbibing  that  doctrine,  and  how 
they  could  have  left  this  wonderful  old  land  pre-eminent 
in  the  doctrines  of  resurrection  of  the  body  and  immor 
tality  of  the  soul,  without  taking  these  doctrines  with 
them,  is  somewhat  of  a  mystery  :  But  the  best  students 
of  the  subject  are,  we  think,  now  agreed  that  the  old 
Hebrews  had  no  definite  knowledge  or  belief  in  these 
doctrines  as  the  peoples  all  surrounding  them  had,  such 
as  the  Egyptians,  Persians  and  Greeks.  At  least  the 
oldest  Hebrew  literature  known  to  us,  the  old  books  of 
the  Bible,  contain  no  evidence  of  this  belief  in  immor 
tality,  but  if  anything  rather  an  indication  of  positive 
disbelief  in  it,  as  shown  clearly  in  Job,  Ecclesiastes  and 
elsewhere,  whereas  the  contemporary  literature  of  the 
surrounding  so-called  pagan  peoples  is  full  of  this  doc 
trine  stated  in  the  most  clear,  detailed  and  beautiful  man 
ner  possible,  as  we  have  already  seen  in  Plato's  Phsedo. 

Matthew  Arnold,  in  his  "Literature  and  Dogma"  p. 
68  has  this  to  say  of  the  status  of  the  Old  Testament  on 
Immortality : 

"  An  impartial  criticism  will  hardly  find  in  the  Old 
Testament  writers  before  the  times  of  the  Maccabees 
(and  certainly  not  in  the  passage  usually  quoted  to  prove 
it)  the  set  doctrine  of  the  immortality  of  the  soul  or  of 
the  resurrection  of  the  dead.  But  by  the  time  of  the 
Maccabees,  when  this  passage  of  the  book  of  Daniel  was 
written,  in  the  second  century  before  Christ,  the  Jews 
have  undoubtedly  become  familiar,  not  indeed  with  the 
idea  of  immortality  of  the  soul  as  the  philosophers  like 
Plato  conceived  it,  but  with  the  notion  of  a  resurrection 
of  the  dead  to  take  their  trial  for  acceptance  or  rejection 
in  the  Most  High's  judgment  and  Kingdom." 


ECCLESIASTES,    XII,    7. 

* 

"  Stranger  than  this  is  the  conceit  that  the  purpose 
of  Ecclesiastes  is  to  teach  explicitly  the  doctrine  of  a 
future  state.  7^he  strongest  text  for  this  position  is 
that  which  has  been  graven  as  a  motto  over  the 
entrance  to  Mount  Auburn  : — 

THEN  SHALL  THE  DUST  RETURN  TO  THE  EARTH, 
AS  IT  WAS  :  AND  THE  SPIRIT  SHALL  RETURN 
UNTO  GOD  WHO  GAVE  IT. 

But  what  this  text  asserts  is  just  the  opposite  of  Im 
mortality.  *  *  What  it  asserts  is  the  absorption 
of  the  individual  in  God,  the  annihilation  of  all  indi 
vidual  existence" 

Dr.  John   W.  Chadwick, 

In  "Bible  of  To-day." 
(Seep, 


V 


GATE  OP  MT,  AUBURN  CEMETERY, 

CAMBRIDGE,  MASS. 
With  its  misconceived  text  for  Immortality 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  133 

In  that  comprehensive  little  work,  "The  Bible  of 
To-day,"  p.  140,  Dr.  John  White  Chadwick  makes  this 
scathing  criticism  on  the  generally  false  interpretation 
and  application  of  that  vague  but  popular  text  from 
Ecclesiastes : 

"  But  your  thorough-going  apologist  is  never  at  a  loss 
for  explanations.  The  object  of  Ecclesiastes,  he  informs 
us,  is  to  compel  us  to  infer  the  doctrine  of  another  life 
from  the  futility  of  all  enjoyment  here.  Stranger  than 
this  is  the  conceit  that  the  purpose  of  Ecclesiastes  is  to 
teach  explicitly  the  doctrine  of  a  future  life.  The 
strongest  text  for  this  position  is  that  which  has  been 
graven  as  a  motto  over  the  entrance  to  Mount  Auburn.* 
'Then  shall  the  dust  return  to  the  earth  as  it  was,  and 
the  spirit  shall  return  to  God  who  gave  it.'  But  what 
this  text  asserts  is  just  the  opposite  of  immortality,  as 
every  critic  knows  who  is  not  consciously  or  unconscious 
ly  a  special  pleader.  What  it  asserts  is  the  absorption 
of  the  individual  in  God,  the  annihilation  of  all  individual 
existence.  Interpreting,  as  we  are  bound  to  do,  the 
more  or  less  obscure  statement,  we  must  interpret  this 
by  Chapter  III,  verses  19  and  20  :  '  For  that  which  be- 
falleth  the  sons  of  men  befalleth  beasts  ;  even  one  thing 
befalleth  them  ;  as  the  one  dieth  so  dieth  the  other.  Yea, 
they  have  all  one  breath;  so  that  a  man  has  no  pre 
eminence  above  a  beast  ;  for  all  is  vanity.'  Read  in  the 
light  of  these  clear-shining  words,  the  motto  of  Mount 
Auburn  is  a  denial  of  any  personal  immortality." 

Now  in  view  of  the  clear  comparison  here  afforded 
between  the  Platonic  and  the  Hebrew  texts,  it  is  hardly 
necessary  to  state  that  the  Platonic  texts  will  be  found 
to  give  not  only  the  clearest  and  fullest  possible  state 
ment  of  the  doctrine  of  personal  immortality  of  the  soul, 

*  A  beautiful  cemetery  near  Boston,  Mass. 


134  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

and  its  different  states  of  future  rewards  and  punish 
ments,  but  that  practically  no  question  exists  as  to  the 
meaning  conveyed  by  these  texts  at  any  point  as  exists 
even  to  some  extent  in  the  best  Hebrew  texts.  And 
another  remarkable  thing  about  these  Platonic  texts  is 
the  fact  that  the  doctrine  there  stated  is  in  substance  and 
details  substantially  if  not  identically  the  same  as  that 
held  by  the  old  Pharisees  of  Christ's  day,  and  by  the 
Christians  of  our  own  times,  particularly  that  oldest  and 
largest  section  of  Christians  known  as  the  Roman  Church. 
And  what  is  still  more  remarkable  is  that  the  doctrine  of 
immortal  soul,  Heaven,  Purgatory  and  Hell  as  now  be 
lieved  in  by  the  majority  of  Christians  is  more  fully  and 
clearly  set  forth  in  this  work  of  Plato  than  can  be  found 
in  any  part  even  of  the  New  Testament  itself,  which  was 
not  composed  until  about  half  a  millennium  after  the 
work  of  Plato  was  written. 

From  the  clear  and  beautiful  words  of  Socrates  in 
the  Phaedo,  it  is  also  evident  that  these  beliefs  were  not 
at  all  new  with  him  or  with  his  age,  but  were  a  common 
belief  coming  down  from  remote  times,  so  that  if  any 
thing  seems  clear  from  these  facts  it  is  the  conclusion 
that  these  doctrines  of  the  Phaedo  have  been  undoubtedly 
transmitted  as  a  heritage  from  the  great  old  pagan*  peoples 
to  the  Jewish  and  Christian  sects. — C.  M.  H. 

*  We  use  under  protest  this  really  absurd  term  "Pagan,"  and  only  in 
deference  to  the  now  almost  universal  Christian  custom  or  usage.  This  term, 
originally  meaning  1 1  rustic  "  or  "  villager, "  is  supposed  to  describe  the  more 
ignorant,  superstitious  and  idolatrous  state  of  the  rustic  or  peasant,  as  com 
pared  to  the  more  rational  and  enlightened  dweller  in  cities.  Its  general 
application,  however,  to  races  like  the  Egyptians,  Chinese,  Hindoos,  Greeks 
and  Romans,  distinguished  for  their  great  intellectual  and  artistic  culture 
and  their  development  of  city  life,  seems  to  be  a  most  absurd  usage  of 
Christian  custom,  and  it  should  have  been  displaced  long  ago  by  a  term  which 
would  be  more  correct  and  would  more  fitly  describe  those  great  civilized 
Gentile  races  who  have  given  us  so  much  "  enlightenment "  in  art,  philosophy 
and  religion. 


NOTE  ON  THE  DOCTRINE  OF  PURGATORY. 

In  referring  above  to  the  doctrine  of  Purgatory,  that 
is,  a  probationary  state  of  souls  in  the  future  life,  which 
is  so  clearly  stated  in  the  Phaedo,  we  cannot  let  this 
occasion  pass  without  an  explanatory  note  to  show  the 
relation  of  this  great  old  Egyptian  and  Greek  doc 
trine  to  the  doctrine  now  prevailing  in  the  Christian 
Church. 

The  first  Christians  must  of  course  be  regarded  as  truly 
a  sect  of  the  Jews,  and  this  sect  arose  at  a  time  when  the 
Jews  had  been  most  surrounded  and  influenced  by  the 
pagan  civilizations  of  Persia,  Greece  and  Rome,  and  it 
also  must  not  be  forgotten  that  the  great  Jewish  sect  of 
the  Pharisees,  which  preceded  the  sect  of  Christians, 
notwithstanding  their  severe  denunciation  by  Christ, 
were  closely  related  to  the  early  Christians  in  many 
ways,  and  especially  in  the  fact  that  both  held  almost 
exactly  the  same  belief  as  to  immortality  of  the  soul  and 
its  future  states  in  Heaven,  Purgatory  or  Hell.*  Hence 
the  belief  of  the  old  Pharisee  as  to  the  soul  and  its 
future,  was  not  only  almost  the  same  as  that  of  the  early 
Christians,  but  substantially  the  same  as  that  of  the 
Roman  Church  of  to-day,  and  this,  as  we  have  already 

*  It  has  been  suggested  that  the  true  derivation  of  "  Pharisee"  is  from 
"Parsee.  "  meaning  the  doctrine  of  the  Parsees  or  Persians  who  believed  in 
immortality,  resurrection,  good  and  evil  spirits,  etc.,  and  who  influenced  the 
formation  of  this  great  Jewish  sect  to  which  both  Christ  and  St.  Paul  belonged. 

(135) 


136  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

indicated,  was  not  substantially  different  from  the  com 
mon  belief  held  in  the  Greek-Roman  world  at  the  time 
of  Christ  and  substantially  identical  with  the  belief  of 
the  old  Greeks  and  Egyptians  extending  back  to  almost 
prehistoric  times. 

While  we  are  at  this  point,  it  might  be  well  to  refer 
to  "  The  Apostles  Creed "  for  a  moment,  and  note  the 
old  Greek  or  Socratic  doctrine  it  contains: — "He  de 
scended  into  Hell,  the  third  day  He  rose  again  from  the 
dead;  He  ascended  into  Heaven."  Now  the  Church 
takes  pains  to  explain  that  the  "  Hell  "  here  referred  to 
is  not  the  Hell  of  the  damned,  but  the  "  limbo  "  or  pre 
paratory  prison  in  which  the  redeemed  souls  are  held 
previous  to  their  release  and  ascent  to  Heaven:  How 
this  corresponds  to  the  "Hades"  or  "  Under  World"  of 
the  old  Egyptians  and  Greeks  and  to  the  "  earthly 
prison"  described  by  Socrates  in  the  Phaedo,  to  which 
the  soul  after  the  death  of  the  body  first  "descends," 
and  to  the  "pure  home  which  is  above,"  to  which  the 
soul  afterwards  "ascends"  and  to  "mansions  fairer," 
etc.,  is  obvious  and  needs  no  further  remark.  Note  also 
how  the  "  seventh  heaven  "  of  which  that  Greek- 
Christian-Jew,  Paul,  had  a  vision  which  he  could  not 
even  describe,  corresponds  to  what  Socrates  hinted  at. 
Notwithstanding  therefore  the  peculiar  and  fallacious 
repugnance  which  the  average  Protestant  displays  to  the 
doctrine  of  purgatory  as  being  in  his  mind  unscriptural, 
unhistoric  and  immoral,  a  little  investigation  and  reflec 
tion  will  show  that  it  is  neither  one  nor  the  other,  but  is 
in  fact  a  very  old  and  respectable  and  morally  comforting 
doctrine  and  made  trebly  so  by  its  undoubted  prevalence 
among  ancient  Jews  and  Christians,  and  above  all  among 
the  ancient,  ethical  pagans  —  Egyptians,  Greeks  and 
Romans,  who  undoubtedly  transmitted  it  to  the  Jews  and 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  137 

Christians.  The  modern  Protestant  is  beginning  at  last 
to  full}7  recognize  and  appreciate  this  point,  that  is,  the 
morality,  antiquity  and  orthodoxy  of  the  doctrine  of 
purgatory  or  a  probationary  state  of  future  life,  as  is 
shown  in  such  works  as  "Our  Life  After  Death"  by 
Rev.  Arthur  Chambers,  (Philadelphia,  Geo.  W.  Jacobs 
&  Co.)  which  is  a  great  Protestant  plea  for  the  sound 
ness  of  the  doctrine  of  Purgatory  from  an  ethical, 
historic  and  Christian  standpoint. — C.  M.  H. 


REINCARNATION. 
FROM  PLATO'S  PHAEDRUS. 

And  there  is  a  law  of  the  goddess  Retribution,  that 
the  soul  which  attains  any  vision  of  truth  in  company 
with  the  god  is  preserved  from  harm  until  the  next 
period,  and  he  who  always  attains  is  always  unharmed. 
But  when  she  is  unable  to  follow,  and  fails  to  behold  the 
vision  of  truth,  and  through  some  ill-hap  sinks  beneath 
the  double  load  of  forgetfulness  and  vice,  and  her 
feathers  fall  from  her  and  she  drops  to  earth,  then  the 
law  ordains  that  this  soul  shall  in  the  first  generation 
pass,  not  into  that  of  any  other  animal,  but  only  of  man; 
and  the  soul  which  has  seen  most  of  truth  shall  come  to 
the  birth  as  a  philosopher  or  artist,  or  musician  or  lover; 
that  which  has  seen  truth  in  the  second  degree  shall  be 
a  righteous  king  or  warrior  or  lord  ;  the  soul  which  is 
of  the  third  class  shall  be  a  politician  or  economist  or 
trader ;  the  fourth  shall  be  a  lover  of  gymnastic  toils  or 
a  physician  ;  the  fifth  a  prophet  or  hierophant ;  to  the 
sixth  a  poet  or  imitator  will  be  appropriate ;  to  the 
seventh  the  life  of  an  artisan  or  husbandman;  to  the 
eighth  that  of  a  Sophist  or  demagogue ;  to  the  ninth 

that  of  a  tyrant;    all  these  are  states  of  probation,  in 

(138) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  139 

which  he  who  lives  righteously  improves,  and  he  who 
lives  unrighteously  deteriorates  his  lot. 

Ten  thousand  years  must  elapse  before  the  soul  can 
return  to  the  place  from  whence  she  came,  for  she  can 
not  grow  her  wings  in  less ;  only  the  soul  of  a  philoso 
pher,  guileless  and  true,  or  the  soul  of  a  lover,  who  is 
not  without  philosophy,  may  acquire  wings  in  the  third 
recurring  period  of  a  thousand  years ;  and  if  they  choose 
this  life  three  times  in  succession,  then  they  have  their 
wings  given  them,  and  go  away  at  the  end  of  three 
thousand  years.  But  the  others  receive  judgment  when 
they  have  completed  their  first  life,  and  after  the  judg 
ment  they  go,  some  of  them  to  the  houses  of  correction 
w7hich  are  under  the  earth,  and  are  punished ;  others  to 
some  place  in  heaven  whither  they  are  lightly  borne  by 
justice,  and  there  they  live  in  a  manner  worthy  of  the 
life  which  they  led  here  when  in  the  form  of  men.  And 
at  the  end  of  the  first  thousand  years  the  good  souls  and 
also  the  evil  souls  both  come  to  cast  lots  and  choose 
their  second  life,  and  they  may  take  any  that,  they  like. 
And  then  the  soul  of  the  man  may  pass  into  the  life  of  a 
beast,  or  from  the  beast  again  into  the  man.  But  the 
soul  of  him  who  has  never  seen  the  truth  will  not  pass 
into  the  human  form,  for  man  ought  to  have  intelligence, 
as  they  say,  "secundum  speciem,"  proceeding  from 
many  particulars  of  sense  to  one  conception  of 
reason;  and  this  is  the  recollection  of  those  things 
which  our  soul  once  saw  when  in  company  with  God — 
when  looking  down  from  above  on  that  which  we  now 
call  being  and  upwards  towards  the  true  being.  And 
therefore  the  mind  of  the  philosopher  alone  has  wings ; 
and  this  is  just;  for  he  is  always,  according  to  the 
measure  of  his  abilities,  clinging  in  recollection  to  those 
things  in  which  God  abides,  and  in  beholding  which  He 


140  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

is  what  he  is.  And  he  who  employs  aright  these  mem 
ories  is  ever  being  initiated  into  perfect  mysteries  and 
alone  becomes  truly  perfect.  But,  as  he  forgets  earthly 
interests  and  is  rapt  in  the  divine,  the  vulgar  deem  him 
mad,  and  rebuke  him ;  they  do  not  see  that  he  is  in 
spired. 


MIND  INHERES  IN  AND  RULES  THE  UNIVERSE. 
FROM  PLATO'S  PHILEBUS. 

SOCRATES.  I  must  obey  you,  O  Protarchus ;  nor  is  the 
task  which  you  impose  a  difficult  one ;  but  have  I  really, 
as  Philebus  says,  disconcerted  you  with  my  playful  so 
lemnity,  in  asking  the  question  to  what  class  mind  and 
knowledge  belong? 

Yet  the  answer  is  easy,  as  all  philosophers  are  agreed 
that  mind  is  the  king  of  heaven  and  earth ;  in  this  way 
truly  they  magnify  themselves.  And  perhaps  they  are 
right.  But  still  I  should  like  to  consider  the  class  of 
mind,  if  you  do  not  object,  a  little  more  fully. 

Very  good ;  let  us  begin  then,  Protarchus,  by  asking 
whether  all  this  which  they  call  the  universe  is  left  to 
the  guidance  of  an  irrational  and  random  chance,  or,  on 
the  contrary,  as  our  fathers  have  declared,  ordered  and 
governed  by  a  marvelous  intelligence  and  wisdom. 

Shall  we,  then,  agree  with  them  of  old  time  in  main 
taining  this  doctrine, — nor  merely  reasserting  the  notions 
of  others,  without  risk  to  ourselves, — but  shall  we  ven 
ture  also  to  share  in  the  risk,  and  bear  the  reproaches 
which  will  await  us,  when  an  ingenious  individual  de 
clares  that  all  is  disorder? 

We  see  the  elements  which  enter  into  the  nature  of 
the  bodies  of  all  animals,  fire,  water,  air,  and,  as  the 
storm-tossed  sailor  cries,  "  Land  ahead,"  in  the  consti 
tution  of  the  world. 

(MO 


142  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

Consider  now  that  any  one  of  the  elements,  as  they 
exist  in  us,  is  but  a  small  fraction  of  them,  and  of  a 
mean  sort,  and  not  in  any  way  pure,  or  having  any 
power  worthy  of  its  nature.  One  instance  will  prove 
this  of  all  of  them ;  there  is  a  fire  within  us,  and  in  the 
universe. 

And  is  not  our  fire  small  and  weak  and  mean,  but  the 
fire  in  the  universe  is  wonderful  in  quantity  and  beauty, 
and  in  every  power  that  fire  has? 

And  is  that  universal  element  nourished  and  generated 
and  ruled  by  our  fire,  or  is  the  fire  in  you  and  me,  and 
in  other  animals,  dependent  on  the  universal  fire? 

PRO.  That  is  a  question  that  does  not  deserve  an 
answer. 

Soc.  Right ;  and  you  would  say  the  same,  if  I  am 
not  mistaken,  of  the  earth  which  is  in  animals  and  the 
earth  which  is  in  the  universe,  and  you  would  give  a 
similar  reply  about  all  the  other  elements  ? 

PRO.  Why,  how  could  any  man  who  gave  any  other 
be  deemed  in  his  senses  ? 

Soc.  I  do  not  think  that  he  could, — but  now  go  a 
step  further;  when  we  see  those  elements  of  which  we 
have  been  speaking  gathered  up  in  one,  do  we  not  call 
them  a  body  ? 

And  the  same  may  be  said  of  the  cosmos,  which  for 
the  same  reason  may  be  considered  as  a  body,  because 
made  up  of  the  same  elements. 

But  is  our  body  nourished  wholly  by  this  body,  or  is 
this  body  nourished  by  our  body,  thence  deriving  and 
having  the  qualities  of  which  we  were  just  now 
speaking? 

May  our  body  be  said  to  have  a  soul  ? 

And  whence  comes  that  soul,  my  dear  Protarchus, 
unless  the  body  of  the  universe,  which  contains  elements 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  143 

similar  and  fairer  far,  had  also  a  soul  ?  Can  there  be 
another  source  ? 

Why  yes,  Protarchus,  for  surely  we  cannot  imagine 
that  of  the  four  elements,  the  finite,  the  infinite,  the 
composition  of  the  two,  and  the  cause  or  fourth  element, 
which  enters  into  all  things,  giving  to  our  bodies  souls, 
and  the  art  of  self-management,  and  of  healing  disease, 
and  operating  in  other  ways  to  heal  and  organize, — that 
this  last,  I  say,  should  be  called  by  all  the  names  of 
wisdom,  and  not  imagine  that  while  the  other  elements 
equally  exist  in  a  larger  form,  both  in  the  entire  heaven, 
and  in  great  provinces  of  the  heaven,  only  fairer  and 
purer,  in  this  higher  sphere  the  cause  which  is  the 
noblest  and  fairest  of  all  natures  has  still  no  existence  ? 

But  if  that  is  not  true,  should  we  not  be  wiser  in 
assenting  to  that  other  argument,  which  says,  as  we  have 
often  repeated,  that  there  is  in  the  universe  a  mighty 
infinite  and  an  adequate  limit,  as  well  as  a  cause  of  no 
mean  power,  which  orders  and  arranges  years  and 
seasons  and  months,  and  may  be  justly  called  wisdom 
and  mind  ? 

And  wisdom  and  mind  cannot  exist  without  soul  ? 

PRO.     Certainly  not. 

Soc.  And  in  the  divine  nature  of  Zeus  would  you 
not  say  that  there  is  the  soul  and  mind  of  a  king,  and 
that  the  power  of  the  cause  engenders  this  ?  And  other 
gods  will  have  other  noble  attributes,  whereby  they  love 
severally  to  be  called. 

PRO.     Very  true. 

Soc.  Do  not  then  suppose  that  these  words  are  rashly 
spoken  by  us,  O  Protarchus,  for  they  are  in  harmony 
with  the  testimony  of  those  who  said  of  old  time  that 
mind  rules  the  universe. 


THE  GREEK  CONCEPTION  OF  SOUL  AND  DEITY. 
FROM  PLATO'S  "PHAEDRUS." 

"The  soul  is  immortal,  for  that  is  immortal  which  is 
ever  in  motion ;  but  that  which  moves  and  is  moved  by 
another,  in  ceasing  to  move  ceases  also  to  live.  There 
fore,  only  that  which  is  self-moving,  never  failing  of 
self,  never  ceases  to  move,  and  is  the  fountain  and 
beginning  of  motion  to  all  that  moves  besides.  Now,  the 
beginning  is  unbegotten,  for  that  which  is  begotten  has 
a  beginning,  but  the  beginning  has  no  beginning,  for  if 
a  beginning  were  begotten  of  something,  that  would 
have  no  beginning.  But  that,  which  is  unbegotten  must 
also  be  indestructible  ;  for  if  beginning  were  destroyed, 
there  could  be  no  beginning  out  of  anything,  or  any 
thing  out  of  a  beginning ;  and  all  things  must  have  a 
beginning.  And  therefore  the  self-moving  is  the  begin 
ning  of  motion  ;  and  this  can  neither  be  destroy ed  nor 
begotten,  for  in  that  case  the  whole  heavens  and  all 
generation  would  collapse  and  stand  still,  and  never 
again  have  motion  or  birth.  But  if  the  self-moving  is 
immortal,  he  who  affirms  that  self-motion  is  the  very 
idea  and  essence  of  the  soul  will  not  be  put  to  confusion. 
For  the  body  which  is  moved  from  without  is  soulless; 
but  that  which  is  moved  from  within  has  a  soul,  and 
this  is  involved  in  the  nature  of  the  soul.  But  if  the 
soul  be  truly  affirmed  to  be  the  self-moving,  then  must 
she  also  be  without  beginning,  and  immortal.  Enough 
of  the  soul's  immortality." 

(i44) 


THE  UNIVERSAL  SOUL. 
FROM  PLATO'S  LAWS,  BOOK  X. 

ATHENIAN.  Nearly  all  of  them,  my  friends,  seem  to  be 
ignorant  of  the  nature  and  power  of  the  soul,  especially 
in  what  relates  to  her  origin  ;  they  do  not  know  that  she 
is  among  the  first  of  bodies,  and  before  them  all,  and  is  the 
chief  author  of  their  changes  and  transpositions.  And 
if  this  is  true,  and  if  the  soul  is  older  than  the  body, 
must  not  the  things  which  are  of  the  soul's  kindred  be 
of  necessity  before  those  which  appertain  to  the  body  ? 

CLEINIAS.    But  why  is  the  word  "  nature  "  wrong? 

ATH.  Because  those  who  use  the  term  mean  to  say 
that  nature  is  the  first  creative  power ;  but  if  the  soul 
turn  out  to  be  the  primeval  element  and  not  fire  or 
air,  then  in  the  truest  sense  and  beyond  other  things  the 
soul  may  be  said  to  have  a  natural  or  creative  power  : 
and  this  w'ould  be  true  if  you  proved  that  the  soul  is 
older  than  the  body,  but  not  otherwise. 

Let  us  assume  that  there  is  a  motion  able  to  move 
other  things,  but  not  to  move  itself, — that  is  one  kind  ; 
and  there  is  another  kind  which  can  move  itself  as 
well  as  other  things,  working  in  composition  and  de 
composition,  by  increase  and  diminution,  and  genera 
tion  and  destruction, — that  is  also  one  of  the  many  kinds 
of  motion. 

Then  we  must  say  that  self-motion  being  the  ori 
gin  and  beginning  of  motion,  as  well  among  things  at 
rest  as  among  things  in  motion,  is  the  eldest  and  might  - 

(H5) 


146  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

iest  principle  of  change,  and  that  which  is  changed  by 
another  and  yet  moves  other  is  second. 

And  what  is  the  definition  of  that  which  is  named 
"soul?"  Can  we  conceive  of  any  other  than  that 
which  has  been  already  given — the  motion  which  is  self- 
moved  ? 

Yes ;  and  if  this  is  true,  do  we  still  maintain  that 
there  is  anything  wanting  in  the  proof  that  the  soul 
is  the  first  origin  and  moving  power  of  all  that  is,  or  has 
been,  or  will  be,  and  their  contraries,  when  she  has 
been  clearly  shown  to  be  the  source  of  change  and  mo 
tion  in  all  things  ? 

Then  we  are  right,  and  speak  the  most  perfect  and 
absolute  truth,  when  we  say  that  the  soul  is  prior  to 
the  body,  and  that  the  body  is  second  and  conies  after 
wards,  and  is  born  to  obey  the  soul  which  is  the  ruler? 

In  the  next  place,  must  we  not  of  necessity  admit  that 
the  soul  is  the  cause  of  good  and  evil,  base  and  honor 
able,  just  and  unjust,  and  of  all  other  opposites,  if  we 
suppose  her  to  be  the  cause  of  all  things  ? 

CLE.     Certainly. 

ATH.  And  as  the  soul  orders  and  inhabits,  all  things 
moving  every  way,  must  we  not  say  that  she  orders 
also  the  heavens  ? 

CLE.     Of  course. 

ATH.  One  soul  or  more  ?  More  than  one — I  will  an 
swer  for  you ;  at  any  rate  we  must  not  suppose  that 
there  are  less  than  two — one  the  author  of  good,  and  the 
other  of  evil.* 

*  NOTE.— By  referring  to  Aristotle' s  idea  of  God  as  given  on  page  182,  it  will  be 
seen  that  he  has  substantially  the  same  conception  as  above  given  in  the 
two  preceding  extracts  from  Plato,  viz.  a  Motion  which  is  self-moved  or  a 
Prime  Mover  which  is  self -moved.  Plato  applies  this  conception  to  describe  the 
"  Soul ' '  in  general,  while  Aristotle  applies  it  to  describe  God  in  particular,  but 
of  course  the  "Universal  Soul'1  or  the  "Soul  of  the  Universe,"  as  meant 
by  Plato,  is  only  another  name  for  ' '  God  '  '—and  Aristotle  doubtless  got  his 
conception  from  this  source. — C.  M.  H. 


THE  PLATONIC  DOCTRINE  OF  IDEAS. 
FROM  PLATO'S  "THEAETETUS"  AND  "  THE  REPUBLIC." 

Note: — The  English  word  "  idea"  does  not  adequately 
express  what  Plato  meant  by  the  Greek  term  of  which  it 
is  a  translation.  Associations  and  implications  connected 
with  the  development  of  the  philosophy  of  Locke  and 
Berkeley,  and  perhaps  German  Idealism  generally,  give 
the  word  a  meaning  that  conceals  the  Platonic  import 
altogether.  The  Platonic  "  idea"  was  the  equivalent  of 
the  permanent  or  "  universal"  as  opposed  to  the  transient 
or  "individual."  It  appears  throughout  his  system  in 
various  forms  and  is  variously  represented  in  modern 
conceptions  by  the  terms  "reality,"  "substance,"  "uni 
versal,"  "essence,"  "subject,"  "absolute,"  "ultimate," 
"  God,"  etc.  It  is  not  easy  to  select  passages  from  his 
works  clearly  representative  of  its  wide  meaning,  as  it  did 
duty  for  the  fields  of  both  metaphysic  and  the  theory  of 
knowledge.  It  is  most  clearly  developed  in  the  Theaete- 
tus,  at  least  for  its  place  in  the  theory  of  knowledge.  In 
the  Phaedrus  it  is  mythically  treated.  I  select  a  passage 
from  the  former  dialogue  as  perhaps  the  best  from  which 
to  choose.  Plato,  as  philosophers  generally,  starts  with 
sensations  as  the  primordial  elements  of  knowledge  and 

(H7) 


148  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

proceeds  to  the  discovery  of  supersensible  mental  states 
which  have  as  their  objects  the  permanent  in  phe 
nomena. — J.  H.  H. 

"  SOCRATES.  The  simple  sensations  which  reach  the 
soul  through  the  body  are  given  at  birth  to  men  and 
animals  by  nature,  but  their  reflections  on  these  and  on 
their  relations  to  being  and  use,  are  slowly  and  hardly 
gained,  if  they  are  ever  gained,  by  education  and  long 
experience. 

"  THEAETETUS.     Assuredly. 

"  Soc.  And  can  a  man  attain  truth  who  fails  of  attain 
ing  being? 

"  THEAET.     Impossible. 

"Soc.  And  can  he  who  misses  the  truth  of  anything 
have  a  knowledge  of  that  thing? 

"  THEAET.     He  cannot. 

"  Soc.  Then  knowledge  does  not  consist  in  impres 
sions  of  sense,  but  in  reasoning  about  them ;  in  that 
only,  and  not  in  the  mere  impression,  truth  and  being 
can  be  obtained  ? 

"  THEAET.     Clearly. 

"  Soc.  And  would  you  call  the  two  processes  by  the 
same  name,  when  there  is  so  great  a  difference  between 
them? 

"  THEAET.     That  will  not  be  right. 

"Soc.  And  what  name  would  you  give  to  seeing, 
hearing,  smelling,  being  cold  and  being  hot  ? 

"THEAET.  I  should  call  all  that  perceiving — what 
other  name  could  be  given  them  ? 

''Soc.  Perception  would  be  the  collective  name  of 
them? 

"  THEAET.     Certainly. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  149 

"Soc.  Which,  as  we  say,  has  no  part  in  the  attain 
ment  of  truth  any  more  than  of  being  ? 

"THEAET.     Certainly  not. 

"  Soc.  And  therefore  cannot  have  any  part  in  science 
and  knowledge? 

"  THEAET.     No. 

"  Soc.  Then  perception,  Theaetetus,  can  never  be  the 
same  as  knowledge  or  science  ? 

"THEAET.  That  is  evident,  Socrates;  and  knowledge 
is  now  most  clearly  proved  to  be  different  from  per 
ception. 

"Soc.  But  the  Original  aim  of  our  discussion  was  to 
find  out  rather  what  knowledge  is,  than  wrhat  it  is  not ; 
at  the  same  time  we  have  made  some  progress,  for  we 
no  longer  seek  for  knowledge  in  perception  at  all,  but 
in  that  other  process,  however  called,  in  which  the  mind 
is  alone  and  engaged  with  being." 

Note: — In  further  discussing  the  question  whether 
"knowledge"  coincided  with  "true  opinion"  Plato 
advances  to  the  examination  of  definition  as  the  determin 
ant  of  the  former.  He  now  makes  Socrates  start  the 
inquiry. — J.  H.  H. 

"Soc.  Knowledge  is  not  attained  until,  combined 
with  true  opinion,  there  is  an  enumeration  of  the  elements 
out  of  which  anything  is  composed. 

"  THEAET.     Yes. 

"  Soc.  In  the  same  general  way,  we  might  also  have 
true  opinion  about  a  wagon;  but  he  who  can  describe 
the  essence  by  an  enumeration  of  the  hundred  planks, 
adds  rational  explanation  to  true  opinion,  and  instead  of 
opinion  has  art  and  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  a  wagon, 


150  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

in  that  he  attains  to  a  knowledge  of  the  whole  through 
the  elements. 

"  THEAET.     Is  not  that  your  view,  Socrates? 

"Soc.  I  want  to  know  what  is  your  view,  my  friend, 
and  whether  you  admit  the  resolution  of  all  things  into 
their  elements  to  be  a  rational  explanation  of  them,  and 
the  consideration  of  them  in  syllables  (elements)  or 
larger  combinations  of  them  to  be  irrational ;  I  should 
like  to  know  whether  this  is  your  view,  that  we  may 
examine  it  ? 

"  THEAET.     That  is  quite  my  view. 

"Soc.  Well,  and  do  you  conceive  that  a  man  has 
knowledge  who  thinks  that  the  same  attribute  belongs 
at  one  time  to  one  thing,  and  at  another  time  to  another 
thing,  or  that  the  same  thing  has  different  attributes  at 
different  times  ? 

"  THEAT.     Assuredly  not. 

"  Soc.  Then,  my  friend,  there  is  such  a  thing  as 
right  opinion  united  with  definition  or  explanation, 
which  does  not  as  yet  attain  to  the  exactness  of  knowl 
edge. 

"THEAET.     That  seems  to  be  true. 

"Soc.  But  what  have  we  gained?  For  this  perfect 
definition  of  knowledge  is  a  dream  only.  And  yet  per 
haps  we  had  better  not  say  that  at  present,  for  very 
likely  there  may  be  found  some  one  who  will  prefer  the 
third  of  the  three  explanations  of  the  definition  of 
knowledge,  one  of  which,  as  we  said,  must  be  adopted 
by  the  definer. 

"THEAET.  You  are  right  in  reminding  me  of  that; 
for  there  is  still  one  remaining  :  the  first  was  the  image 
or  expression  of  the  mind  in  sound ;  and  that  which  has 
just  been  mentioned  is  a  way  of  reaching  the  whole  by 
an  enumeration  of  the  elements.  What  is  the  third  way  ? 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  151 

"  Soc.  There  is  further,  the  popular  notion  of  telling 
the  mark  or  sign  of  difference  which  distinguishes  the 
thing  in  question  from  all  others. 

"  THEAET.  Can  you  give  me  an  example  of  such  a 
definition  ? 

"Soc.  As,  for  example,  in  the  case  of  the  sun,  I 
think  that  you  need  only  know  that  the  sun  is  the 
brightest  of  the  heavenly  bodies  which  revolves  about 
the  earth. 

"  THEAET.     Certainly. 

"Soc.  Understand  why  I  say  this:  the  reason  is,  as 
I  was  saying,  that  if  you  get  at  the  difference  and  dis 
tinguishing  characteristic  of  each  thing,  then,  as  many 
persons  say,  3^ou  will  get  at  the  definition  or  explanation 
of  it;  but  will  you  lay  hold  of  the  common  and  not  of 
the  characteristic  notion,  you  will  only  have  the  defini 
tion  of  those  things  to  which  this  common  quality 
belongs. 

"THEAET.  I  understand,  and  am  of  the  opinion  that 
you  are  quite  right  in  calling  that  a  definition. 

"  Soc.  But  he,  who  having  a  right  opinion  about  any 
thing,  can  find  out  the  difference  which  distinguishes  it 
from  other  things,  will  know  that  of  which  before  he  had 
only  had  an  opinion. 

"  THEAET.     That  is  what  we  are  maintaining. 

"Soc.  Nevertheless,  Theaetetus,  on  a  nearer  view,  I 
find  myself  quite  disappointed  in  the  picture,  which  at 
the  distance  was  not  so  bad. 

"  THEAET.     What  do  you  mean  ? 

"  Soc.  I  will  endeavor  to  explain :  I  will  suppose 
myself  to  have  a  true  opinion  of  you,  and  if  to  this  I  add 
your  definition,  then  I  have  knowledge,  but  if  not,  opin 
ion  only. 

"THEAET.     Yes. 


152  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"  Soc.  The  definition  was  assumed  to  be  the  inter 
pretation  of  your  difference. 

"  THEAET.     True. 

"  Soc.  But  when  I  had  only  opinion,  I  had  no  con 
ception  of  your  distinguishing  characteristics  ? 

"  THEAET.     I  suppose  not. 

"  Soc.  Then  I  must  have  conceived  of  some  general 
or  common  nature  which  no  more  belonged  to  you  than 
to  another. 

"  THEAET.     True. 

"  Soc.  Tell  me,  now  ;  how  in  that  case  could  I  have 
formed  a  judgment  of  you  any  more  than  of  any  one 
else  ?  Suppose  that  I  knew  Theaetetus  to  be  a  man  who 
has  nose,  eyes,  and  mouth,  and  every  member  complete: 
how  could  that  enable  me  to  distinguish  Theaetetus 
from  Theodorus,  or  from  some  other  unknown  barbarian  ? 

"  THEAET.     Very  true. 

"  Soc.  Or  if  I  had  further  known  you,  not  only  as 
having  nose  and  eyes,  but  as  having  a  snub  nose  and 
prominent  eyes,  should  I  have  any  more  notion  of  you 
than  of  myself  and  of  others  who  resemble  me? 

11  THEAET.     Certainly  not. 

"Soc.  Surely  I  can  have  no  conception  of  Theaetetus 
until  the  distinction  between  your  snub-nosedness  and 
the  snub-nosedness  of  others,  as  well  as  the  other  pecu 
liarities  which  distinguish  you,  have  stamped  their 
memorial  on  my  mind,  so  that  when  I  meet  you  to 
morrow  the  right  impression  may  be  recalled  ? 

"THEAET.     Most  true. 

"Soc.  Then  right  opinion  implies  the  perception  of 
differences  ? 

"THEAET.     That  is  evident. 

"Soc.  What,  then,  shall  we  say  of  adding  reason  or 
explanation  to  right  opinion  ?  If  the  meaning  is  that  we 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  153 

should  form  an  opinion  of  the  way  in  which  something 
differs  from  another  thing,  the  proposal  is  ridiculous. 

"  THEAET.     How  so  ? 

"  Soc.  We  are  required  to  have  a  right  opinion  of 
the  differences  which  distinguish  one  thing  from  another 
when  we  already  have  a  right  opinion  of  them,  and  so 
we  go  round  and  round  ;  the  revolution  of  the  scytal,  or 
pestle,  or  any  other  rotatory  engine,  in  the  same  circles, 
is  nothing  to  us ;  and  we  may  be  truly  described  as  the 
blind  leading  the  blind ;  for  to  bid  us  add  those  things 
which  we  already  have,  in  order  that  we  may  learn  what 
we  already  think,  is  a  rare  sort  of  darkness. 

"THEAET.  Tell  me,  then ;  what  were  you  going  to 
say  just  now,  when  you  asked  the  question? 

"  Soc.  If,  my  boy,  the  argument,  when  speaking  of 
adding  the  definition,  had  used  the  word  'to  know/  and 
not  merely  *  have  an  opinion '  of  the  difference,  this 
which  is  the  best  of  all  the  definitions  of  knowledge 
would  have  come  to  a  pretty  end,  for  to  know  is  surely 
to  get  knowledge. 

"  THEAET.     True. 

"Soc.  Then  when  the  question  is  asked,  What  is 
knowledge?  this  fair  argument  will  answer  '  Right  opin 
ion  with  knowledge/ — knowledge,  that  is,  of  difference, 
for  this,  as  the  said  argument  maintains,  is  the  explana 
tion  or  definition  to  be  added. 

"  THEAET.     That  seems  to  be  true. 

"Soc.  But  how  utterly  foolish,  when  we  are  asking 
what  is  knowledge,  that  the  reply  should  only  be,  right 
opinion  with  knowledge  of  difference  or  of  anything. 
And  so,  Theaetetus,  knowledge  is  neither  sensation  nor 
true  opinion,  nor  yet  definition  and  explanation  accom 
panying  true  opinion  ? 

"  THEAET.     I  suppose  not. 


154  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"  Soc.  And  are  you  still  in  labor  and  travail,  my  dear 
friend,  or  have  you  brought  all  that  you  have  to  say 
about  knowledge  to  the  birth  ? 

"  THEAET.  I  am  sure,  Socrates,  that  you  have  brought 
a  good  deal  more  out  of  me  than  was  ever  in  me. 

' 'Soc.  And  does  not  my  art  show  that  you  have 
brought  forth  wind,  and  that  the  offspring  of  your  brain 
are  not  worth  bringing  up  ? 

"THEAET.     Very  true. 

"Soc.  But  if,  Theatetus,  you  have,  or  wish  to  have, 
any  more  embryo  thoughts,  they  will  be  all  the  better 
for  the  present  investigation,  and  if  you  have  none,  you 
will  be  soberer  and  humbler  and  gentler  to  other  men, 
not  fancying  that  you  know  what  you  do  not  know. 
These  are  the  limits  of  my  art ;  I  can  no  further  go,  nor 
do  I  know  aught  of  the  things  which  great  and  famous 
men  know,  or  have  known,  in  this,  or  former  ages.  The 
office  of  a  mid-wife,  I,  like  my  mother,  have  received 
from  God ;  she  delivered  women,  and  I  deliver  men ;  but 
they  must  be  young,  and  noble,  and  fair." 

(Plato's  Dialogues:  Theaetetus.     Jowett  Trans.) 

Note : — There  is  a  passage  on  dialectic  in  the  Republic 
which  obtains  its  interest  from  its  alliance  with  the 
doctrine  of  Ideas,  and  which  I  here  quote  as  follows : — 
J.  H.  H. 

"  Dear  Glaucon,  I  said,  you  will  not  be  able  to  follow 
me  here,  though  I  would  do  my  best,  and  you  should 
behold,  not  an  image  only,  but  the  absolute  truth,  but 
that  something  like  this  is  the  truth  I  am  confident. 

"  Certainly,  he  replied. 

"  And   further,    I   must   tell   you  that   the   power  of 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  155 

dialectic  alone  can  reveal  this,  and  only  to  one  who  is  a 
disciple  of  the  previous  sciences. 

"  Of  that  too,  he  said,  you  may  be  confident. 

"  And  no  one,  I  said,  will  argue  that  there  is  any  other 
process  or  way  of  comprehending  all  true  existence ;  for 
the  arts  in  general  are  referable  to  the  wants  or  opinions 
of  men,  or  are  cultivated  for  the  sake  of  production  and 
construction,  or  for  the  care  of  such  productions  and 
constructions;  and  as  to  the  mathematical  arts  which,  as 
we  were  saying,  have  some  apprehension  of  true  being- 
geometry  and  the  like — they  only  dream  about  being, 
but  never  can  they  behold  the  waking  reality  so  long  as 
they  leave  the  hypotheses  which  they  use  undisturbed, 
and  are  unable  to  give  an  account  of  them.  For  when 
a  man  knows  not  his  own  first  principle,  and  when  the 
conclusion  and  intermediate  steps  are  also  constructed 
out  of  he  knows  not  what,  how  can  he  imagine  that  such 
an  arbitrary  agreement  will  ever  become  science? 

"  Impossible,  he  said. 

"  Then  dialectic,  and  dialectic  alone,  goes  to  a  principle, 
and  is  the  only  science  which  does  away  with  hypotheses 
in  order  to  establish  them  ;  the  eye  of  the  soul,  which  is 
literally  buried  in  some  outlandish  slough,  is  by  her 
taught  to  look  upwards ;  and  she  uses  as  handmaids,  in 
the  work  of  conversion,  the  sciences  which  we  have  been 
discussing.  Custom  terms  them  sciences,  but  they  ought 
to  have  some  other  name,  implying  greater  clearness  than 
opinion  and  less  clearness  than  science :  and  this  in  our 
previous  sketch,  was  called  understanding.  But  there  is 
no  use  in  our  disputing  about  names  when  we  have 
realities  of  such  importance  to  consider. 

"  No,  he  said,  any  name  will  do  which  expresses  the 
thought  clearly. 

"At  any  rate,  we  are  satisfied,  as  before,  to  have  four 


156  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

divisions,  two  for  intellect  and  two  for  opinion ;  and  to 
call  the  first  division  science,  the  second  understanding, 
the  third  belief,  and  the  fourth  knowledge  of  shadows: 
opinion  being  concerned  with  generation,  and  intellect 
with  true  being;  and  then  to  make  a  proportion: — as 
being  is  to  generation,  so  is  pure  intellect  to  opinion :  and, 
as  science  is  to  belief,  so  is  understanding  to  knowledge 
of  shadows. 

"But  let  us  leave  the  further  distribution  and  division 
of  the  objects  of  opinion  and  of  intellect,  which  will  be 
a  long  inquiry  many  times  longer  than  this  has  been. 

"  As  far  as  I  understand,  he  said,  I  agree. 

"And  do  you  also  agree,  I  said,  in  describing  the 
dialectician  as  one  who  has  a  conception  of  the  essence 
of  each  thing?  And  may  he  who  is  unable  to  acquire 
and  impart  this  conception,  in  whatever  degree  he  fails, 
in  that  degree  also  be  said  to  fail  in  intelligence?  Will 
you  admit  that  ? 

"Yes,  he  said;  how  can  I  deny  that? 

"And  you  would  say  the  same  of  the  conception  of 
the  good?  Until  a  person  is  able  to  abstract  and  define 
the  idea  of  the  good,  and  unless  he  can  run  the  gauntlet 
of  all  objections,  and  is  ready  to  disprove  them,  not  by 
appeals  to  opinion,  but  to  true  existence,  never  faltering 
at  any  step  of  the  argument — unless  he  can  do  all  this, 
you  would  say  that  he  knows  neither  absolute  good  nor 
any  other  good ;  he  apprehends  only  a  shadow,  which 
is  given  by  opinion  and  not  by  knowledge;  dream 
ing  and  slumbering  in  this  life,  before  he  is  well  awake, 
here  he  arrives  at  the  world  below,  and  finally  has  his 
quietus." 

Plato's  Republic,  Book  VII.     (Jowett's  Trans.) 


THE  SOCRATIC  UTILITARIAN  THEORY  OF 
ETHICS. 

Brief : — Pleasure  is  essentially  Good,  and  Pain  essen 
tially  Evil.  Virtue  is  simply  the  right  choice  of  pleasures 
and  pains,  and  for  this  right  choice  "  knowledge "  or 
"  wisdom "  is  necessary.  Hence  Virtue,  in  the  last 
analysis,  is  essentially  knowledge  or  wisdom,  and  vice 
essentially  ignorance  or  foolishness. — See  Supplementary 
Notes  at  end  of  extract. — C.  M.  H. 

FROM  DIALOGUE  OF  SOCRATES  WITH  PROTAGORAS, 
IN  PLATO'S    "PROTAGORAS." 

"You  would  admit,  Protagoras,  that  some  men  live 
well  and  others  ill  ? 

"  He  agreed  to  this. 

"And  do  you  think  that  a  man  lives  well  who  lives  in 
pain  and  grief? 

"  He  does  not. 

"  But  if  he  lives  pieasantly  to  the  end  of  his  life,  don't 
you  think  that  in  that  case  he  will  have  lived  well? 

"  I  do. 

"  Then  to  live  pleasantly  is  a  good,  and  to  live  un 
pleasantly  an  evil  ? 

"  Yes,  he  said,  if  the  pleasure  be  good  and  honorable. 


158  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"And  do  you,  Protagoras,  like  the  rest  of  the  world, 
call  some  pleasant  things  evil  and  some  painful  things 
good  ? — for  lam  rather  disposed  to  say  that  things  are 
good  in  as  far  as  they  are  pleasant,  if  they  have  no  con 
sequences  of  another  sort,  and  in  as  far  as  they  are 
painful  they  are  bad. 

"  I  do  not  know,  Socrates,  he  said,  whether  I  can  ven 
ture  to  assert  in  that  unqualified  manner  that  the  pleas 
ant  is  the  good  and  the  painful  the  evil.  Having  regard 
not  only  to  my  present  answer,  but  also  to  the  rest  of 
my  life,  I  shall  be  safer,  if  I  am  not  mistaken,  in  saying 
that  there  are  some  pleasant  things  which  are  not  good, 
and  that  there  are  some  painful  things  which  are  good, 
and  some  which  are  not  good,  and  that  there  are  some 
which  are  neither  good  nor  evil. 

"And  you  would  call  pleasant,  I  said,  the  things 
which  participate  in  pleasure  or  create  pleasure  ? 

"  Certainly,  he  said. 

"  Then  my  meaning  is,  that  in  as  far  as  they  are 
pleasant  they  are  good  ;  and  my  question  would  imply 
that  pleasure  is  a  good  in  itself. 

"According  to  your  favorite  mode  of  speech,  Socrates, 
let  us  inquire  about  this,  he  said ;  and  if  the  result  of 
the  inquiry  is  to  show  that  pleasure  and  good  are  really 
the  same,  then  we  will  agree ;  but  if  not,  then  we  will 
argue. 

"  Having  seen  what  your  opinion  is  about  good  and 
pleasure,  I  am  minded  to  say  to  you :  Uncover  your 
mind  to  me  Protagoras,  and  reveal  your  opinion  about 
knowledge,  that  I  may  know  whether  you  agree  with 
the  rest  of  the  world.  Now  the  rest  of  the  world  are  of 
opinion  that  knowledge  is  a  principle  not  of  strength,  or 
of  rule,  or  of  command :  their  notion  is  that  a  man  may 
have  knowledge,  and  yet  that  the  knowledge  which  is  in 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  159 

him  may  be  overmastered  by  anger,  or  pleasure,  or 
pain,  or  love,  or  perhaps  fear, — just  as  if  knowledge 
were  a  slave,  and  might  be  dragged  about  anyhow. 
Now  is  that  your  view7  ?  or  do  you  think  that  knowledge 
is  a  noble  and  commanding  thing,  which  cannot  be 
overcome,  and  will  not  allow  a  man,  if  he  only  knows 
the  difference  of  good  and  evil,  to  do  anything  which  is 
contrary  to  knowledge,  but  that  wisdom  will  have 
strength  to  help  him  ? 

"  I  agree  with  you,  Socrates,  said  Protagoras  ;  and  not 
only  that  but  I,  above  all  other  men,  am  bound  to  say 
that  wisdom  and  knowledge  are  the  highest  of  human 
things. 

"  Good,  I  said,  and  true.  But  are  you  aware  that  the 
majority  of  the  world  are  of  another  mind  ;  and  that  men 
are  commonly  supposed  to  know  the  things  which  are 
best,  and  not  to  do  them  when  they  might?  And  most 
persons  of  whom  I  have  asked  the  reason  of  this  have 
said,  that  those  who  did  thus  were  overcome  by  pain,  or 
pleasure,  or  some  of  those  affections  which  I  was  now 
mentioning. 

"  Yes,  Socrates,  he  replied  ;  and  that  is  not  the  only 
point  about  which  mankind  are  in  error. 

"  Suppose,  then,  that  you  and  I  endeavor  to  instruct 
and  inform  them  what  is  the  nature  of  this  affection, 
which  is  called  by  them  being  overcome  by  pleasure, 
and  which,  as  they  declare,  is  the  reason  why  they  know 
the  better  and  choose  the  worse.  When  we  say  to  them : 
Friends,  you  are  mistaken,  and  are  saying  what  is  not 
true,  they  would  reply  ;  Socrates  and  Protagoras,  if  this 
affection  of  the  soul  is  not  to  be  described  as  being  over 
come  by  pleasure,  what  is  it,  and  how  do  you  call  it? 
Tell  us  that. 

"When   men  are  overcome  by  eating  and  drinking 


160  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

and  other  sensual  desires  which  are  pleasant,  and  they, 
knowing  them  to  be  evil,  nevertheless  indulge  in  them, 
is  not  that  what  you  would  call  being  overcome  by 
pleasure?  That  they  will  admit.  And  suppose  that 
you  and  I  were  to  go  on  and  ask  them  again :  In  what 
way  do  you  say  that  they  are  evil, — in  that  they  are 
pleasant  and  give  pleasure  at  the  moment,  or  because 
they  cause  disease  and  poverty  and  other  like  evils  in 
the  future?  Would  they  still  be  evil,  if  they  had  no 
attendant  evil  consequences,  simply  because  they  give 
the  consciousness  of  pleasure  of  whatever  nature? 
Would  they  not  answer  that  they  are  not  evil  on  ac 
count  of  the  pleasure  which  is  immediately  given  by 
them,  but  on  account  of  the  after  consequences — diseases 
and  the  like? 

"  I  believe,  said  Protagoras,  that  the  world  in  general 
would  give  that  answer. 

"And  in  causing  diseases  do  they  not  cause  pain  ?  and 
in  causing  poverty  do  they  not  cause  pain ;  they  would 
agree  to  that  also,  if  I  am  not  mistaken  ? 

"  Protagoras  assented. 

"  Then  I  should  say  to  them,  in  my  name  and  yours : 
Do  you  think  them  evil  for  any  other  reason,  except 
that  they  end  in  pain  and  rob  us  of  other  pleasures  ? — 
that  again  they  would  admit. 

"We  both  of  us  thought  that  they  would. 

'*  And  that  I  should  take  the  question  from  the  opposite 
point  of  view,  and  say:  Friends,  when  you  speak  of 
goods  being  painful,  do  you  mean  remedial  goods,  such 
as  gymnastic  exercises  and  military  services,  and  the 
physician's  use  of  burning,  cutting,  drugging,  and  starv 
ing  ?  Are  these  the  things  which  are  good  but  painful  ?— 
they  would  assent  to  that  ? 

"He  agreed. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  161 

"  And  do  you  call  them  good  because  they  occasion  the 
greatest  immediate  suffering  and  pain ;  or  because,  after 
wards,  they  bring  health  and  improvement  of  the  bodily 
condition  and  the  salvation  of  states,  and  empires,  and 
wealth?— they  would  agree  to  that,  if  I  am  not  mistaken? 

"He  assented. 

"  Are  these  things  good  for  any  other  reason  except 
that  they  end  in  pleasure,  and  get  rid  of  and  avert  pain  ? 
Are  you  looking  to  any  other  standard  but  pleasure  and 
pain  when  you  call  them  good? — they  would  acknowl 
edge  that  they  were  not  ? 

"I  think  that  they  would,  said  Protagoras. 

"And  do  you  not  pursue  after  pleasure  as  a  good,  and 
avoid  pain  as  an  evil  ? 

"He  assented. 

"  Then  you  think  that  pain  is  an  evil  and  pleasure  is 
a  good ;  and  even  pleasure  you  deem  an  evil,  when  it 
robs  you  of  greater  pleasures  than  it  gives,  or  causes 
greater  pain  than  the  pleasures  which  it  has.  If,  how 
ever,  you  call  pleasure  an  evil  in  relation  to  some  other 
end  or  standard,  you  will  be  able  to  show  us  that  stand 
ard.  But  you  have  none  to  show. 

"I  do  not  think  that  they  have,  said  Protagoras. 

"  And  have  you  not  a  similar  way  of  speaking  about 
pain  ?  You  call  pain  a  good  when  it  takes  away  greater 
pains  than  those  which  it  has,  or  gives  pleasures  greater 
than  the  pains ;  for  I  say  that  if  you  have  some  standard 
other  than  pleasure  and  pain  to  which  you  refer  when 
you  call  actual  pain  a  good,  you  can  show  what  that  is. 
But  you  cannot. 

"  That  is  true,  said  Protagoras. 

"Suppose  again,  I  said,  that  the  world  says  to  me: 
Why  do  you  spend  many  words  and  speak  in  many  ways 
on  this  subject  ?  Excuse  me,  friends,  I  should  reply  ; 


1 62  Ethics  of  the   Greek  Philosophers. 

but  in  the  first  place  there  is  a  difficulty  in  explaining  the 
meaning  of  the  expression  '  overcome  by  pleasure  ; ' 
and  the  whole  argument  turns  upon  this.  And  even 
now,  if  you  see  any  possible  way  in  which  evil  can  be 
explained  as  other  than  pain,  or  good  as  other  than 
pleasure,  you  may  still  retract.  But  I  suppose  that  you 
are  satisfied  at  having  a  life  of  pleasure  which  is  without 
pain.  And  if  you  are  satisfied,  and  if  you  are  unable  to 
show  any  good  or  evil  which  does  not  end  in  pleasure 
and  pain,  hear  the  consequences. — If  this  is  true,  then  I 
say  that  the  argument  is  absurd  which  affirms  that  a  man 
often  does  evil  knowingly,  when  he  might  abstain,  be 
cause  he  is  seduced  and  amazed  by  pleasure ;  or  again, 
when  you  say  that  a  man  knowingly  refuses  to  do  what 
is  good  because  he  is  overcome  at  the  moment  by  pleas 
ure.  Now  that  this  is  ridiculous  will  be  evident  if  only 
we  give  up  the  use  of  various  names,  such  as  pleasant 
and  painful,  and  good  and  evil.  As  there  are  two  things, 
let  us  call  them  by  two  names, — first,  good  and  evil,  and 
then  pleasant  and  painful.  Assuming  this,  let  us  go  on 
to  say  that  a  man  does  evil  knowing  that  he  does  evil. 
But  some  one  will  ask,  Why  ?  Because  he  is  overcome, 
is  the  first  answer.  And  by  what  is  he  overcome  ?  the 
inquirer  will  proceed  to  ask.  And  we  shall  not  be  able 
to  reply,  '  By  pleasure,'  for  the  name  of  pleasure  has 
been  exchanged  for  that  of  good.  In  our  answer,  then, 
we  shall  only  say  that  he  is  overcome.  '  By  what?'  he 
will  reiterate.  By  the  good,  we  shall  have  to  reply;  in 
deed  we  shall.  Nay,  but  our  questioner  will  rejoin  with 
a  laugh,  if  he.be  one  of  the  swaggering  sort,  That  is  too 
ridiculous,  that  a  man  should  do  what  he  knows  to  be 
evil  when  he  ought  not,  because  he  is  overcome  by  good. 
Is  that,  he  will  ask,  because  the  good  was  worthy  or  not 
worthy  of  conquering  the  evil  ?  And  in  answer  to  that 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  163 

we  shall  clearly  reply,  Because  it  was  not  worthy :  for 
if  it  had  been  worthy,  then  he  who,  as  we  say,  was  over 
come  by  pleasure,  would  not  have  been  wrong.  But 
how,  he  will  reply,  can  the  good  be  unworthy  of  the  evil, 
or  the  evil  of  the  good?  Is  not  the  real  explanation  that 
they  are  out  of  proportion  to  one  another,  either  as 
greater  and  smaller,  or  more  and  fewer  ?  This  we  cannot 
deny.  And  when  you  speak  of  being  overcome, — what 
do  you  mean,  he  will  say,  but  that  you  choose  the  greater 
evil  in  exchange  for  the  lesser  good  ?  This  being  the 
case,  let  us  now  substitute  the  names  of  pleasure  and 
pain,  and  say,  not  as  before,  that  a  man  does  what  is  evil 
knowingly,  but  that  he  does  what  is  painful  knowingly, 
and  because  he  is  overcome  by  pleasure,  which  is  un 
worthy  to  overcome.  And  what  measure  is  there  of  the 
relations  of  pleasure  to  pain  other  than  excess  and  defect, 
which  means  that  they  become  greater  and  smaller,  and 
more  and  fewer,  and  differ  in  degree  ?  For  if  any  one 
says,  '  Yes,  Socrates,  but  immediate  pleasure  differs 
widely  from  future  pleasure  and  pain,' — to  that  I  should 
reply  :  And  do  they  differ  in  any  other  way  except  by 
reason  of  pleasure  and  pain  ?  There  can  be  no  other 
measure  of  them.  And  do  you,  like  a  skillful  weigher, 
put  into  the  balance  the  pleasures  and  the  pains,  near 
and  distant,  and  weigh  them,  and  then  say  which  out 
weighs  the  other  ?  If  you  weigh  pleasures  against  pleas 
ures,  you,  of  course,  take  the  more  and  greater ;  or  if 
you  weigh  pains  against  pains,  you  take  the  fewer  and 
the  less  ;  or  if  pleasures  against  pains,  then  you  choose 
that  course  of  action  in  which  the  painful  is  exceeded  by 
the  pleasant,  whether  the  distant  by  the  near,  or  the  near 
by  the  distant ;  and  you  avoid  that  course  of  action  in 
which  the  pleasant  is  exceeded  by  the  painful.  Would 


164  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

you  not  admit,  my  friends,  that  this  is  true  ?  I  am  con 
fident  that  they  cannot  deny  this. 

"  He  agreed  with  me. 

"  Now  supposing  that  happiness  consisted  in  making 
and  taking  large  things,  what  would  be  the  saving 
principle  of  human  life  ?  Would  the  art  of  measuring 
be  the  saving  principle,  or  would  the  power  of  appear 
ance  ?  Is  not  the  latter  that  deceiving  art  which  makes 
us  wander  up  and  down  and  take  the  things  at  one  time 
of  which  we  repent  at  another,  both  in  our  actions  and 
in  our  choice  of  things,  great  and  small  ?  But  the  art  of 
measurement  is  that  which  would  do  away  with  the  effect 
of  appearances,  and,  showing  the  truth,  would  fain  teach 
the  soul  at  last  to  find  rest  in  the  truth,  and  would  thus 
save  our  life.  Would  not  mankind  generally  acknowl 
edge  that  the  art  which  accomplishes  this  is  the  art  of 
measurement  ? 

"Yes,  he  said,  the  art  of  measurement. 

"Suppose,  again,  the  salvation  of  human  life  to  depend 
on  the  choice  of  odd  and  even,  and  on  the  knowledge  of 
when  men  ought  to  choose  the  greater  or  less,  either  in 
reference  to  themselves  or  to  each  other,  whether  near 
or  at  a  distance  ;  what  would  be  the  saving  principle  of 
our  lives?  Would  not  knowledge? — a  knowledge  of 
measuring,  when  the  question  is  one  of  excess  and  defect, 
and  a  knowledge  of  number,  when  the  question  is  of  odd 
and  even?  The  world  will  acknowledge  that,  will 
they  not? 

"  Protagoras  admitted  that  they  would. 

"Well,  then,  I  say  to  them,  my  friends;  seeing  that 
the  salvation  of  human  life  has  been  found  to  consist  in 
the  right  choice  of  pleasures  and  pains, — in  the  choice  of 
the  more  and  the  fewer  and  the  greater  and  the  less,  and 
the  nearer  and  remoter,  must  not  this  measuring  be  a 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  165 

consideration  of  excess  and  defect  and  equality  in  rela 
tion  to  each  other  ? 

"That  is  undeniably  true. 

"And  this,  as  possessing  measure,  must  undeniably 
also  be  an  art  and  science  ? 

"They  will  agree  to  that. 

"  The  nature  of  that  art  or  science,  will  be  a  matter  of 
future  consideration ;  the  demonstration  of  the  existence 
of  such  a  science  is  a  sufficient  answer  to  the  question 
which  you  asked  of  me  and  Protagoras.  At  the  time 
when  you  asked  the  question,  if  you  remember,  both  of 
us  were  agreeing  that  there  was  nothing  mightier  than 
knowledge,  and  that  knowledge,  in  whatever  existing, 
must  have  the  advantage  over  pleasure  and  all  other 
things ;  and  then  you  said  that  pleasure  often  got  the 
advantage  even  over  a  man  who  has  knowledge;  and  we 
refused  to  allow  this,  and  you  said :  O  Protagoras  and 
Socrates,  if  this  state  is  not  to  be  called  being  overcome 
by  pleasure,  tell  us  what  it  is  ;  what  would  you  call  it? 
If  we  had  immediately  and  at  the  time  answered  "  Igno 
rance,"  you  would  have  laughed  at  us.  But  now,  in 
laughing  at  us,  you  will  be  laughing  at  yourselves:  for 
you  also  admitted  that  men  err  in  their  choice  of  pleas 
ures  and  pains ;  that  is,  in  their  choice  of  good  and  evil, 
from  defect  of  knowledge ;  and  you  admitted  further  that 
they  err,  not  only  from  defect  of  knowledge  in  general, 
but  of  that  particular  knowledge  which  is  called  measur 
ing.  And  you  are  also  aware  that  the  erring  act  which 
is  done  without  knowledge  is  done  in  ignorance.  This, 
therefore,  is  the  meaning  of  being  overcome  by  pleas 
ure, — ignorance,  and  that  the  greatest. 

"Then  you  agree,  I  said,  that  the  pleasant  is  the  good, 
and  the  painful  evil  ? 

"Are  not  all  actions,  the  tendency  of  which  is  to  make 


1 66  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

life  painless  and  pleasant,  honorable  and  useful  ?     The 
honorable  work  is  also  useful  and  good  ? 

"  This  was  admitted. 

"  Then,  if  the  pleasant  is  the  good,  nobody  does  any 
thing  under  the  idea  or  conviction  that  some  other  thing 
would  be  better  and  is  also  attainable,  when  he  might  do 
the  better.  And  this  inferiority  of  a  man  to  himself  is 
merely  ignorance,  as  the  superiority  of  a  man  to  himself 
is  wisdom. 

"  They  all  assented. 

"  And  is  not  ignorance  the  having  a  false  opinion  and 
being  deceived  about  important  matters  ? 

"  To  that  they  also  unanimously  assented. 

"  Then,  no  man  voluntarily  pursues  evil,  or  that  which 
he  thinks  to  be  evil.  To  prefer  evil  to  good  is  not  in 
human  nature ;  and  when  a  man  is  compelled  to  choose 
one  of  two  evils,  no  one  will  choose  the  greater  when  he 
might  have  the  less. 

"  All  of  us  agreed  to  every  word  of  this. 

"  My  only  object,  I  said,  in  continuing  the  discussion, 
has  been  the  desire  to  ascertain  the  relations  of  virtue 
and  the  essential  nature  of  virtue ;  for  if  this  were  clear, 
I  am  very  sure  that  the  other  controversy  which  has 
been  carried  on  at  great  length  by  both  of  us — you  affirm 
ing  and  I  denying,  that  virtue  can  be  taught — would  also 
have  become  clear.  The  result  of  our  discussion  appears 
to  me  to  be  singular.  For  if  the  argument  had  a  human 
voice,  that  voice  would  be  heard  laughing  at  us  and  say 
ing  :  Protagoras  and  Socrates,  you  are  strange  beings ; 
there  are  you  who  were  saying  that  virtue  cannot  be 
taught,  contradicting  yourself  now  in  the  attempt  to  show 
that  all  things  are  knowledge,  including  justice,  and 
temperance,  and  courage, — which  tends  to  show  that 
virtue  can  certainly  be  taught ;  for  if  virtue  were  other 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  167 

than  knowledge,  as  Protagoras  attempted  to  show,  then 
clearly  virtue  cannot  be  taught ;  but  if  virtue  is  entirely 
knowledge,  as  you,  Socrates,  are  seeking  to  show,  then  I 
cannot  but  suppose  that  virtue  is  capable  of  being  taught. 
Protagoras,  on  the  other  hand,  who  started  by  saying 
that  it  might  be  taught,  is  now  eager  to  show  that  it  is 
anything  rather  than  knowledge ;  and  if  this  is  true,  it 
must  be  quite  incapable  of  being  taught  " 


SUPPLEMENTARY  NOTES. 

SOCRATES   THE  FATHER  OF  MODERN  OR 
UTILITARIAN  ETHICS. 

The  preceding  extract  from  the  dialogue  of  Socrates 
with  Protagoras,  should  have  great  interest  for  students 
of  ethics,  as  it  presents  in  probably  the  earliest  and  most 
complete  form  the  great  modern  theory  of  ethics  known 
as  the  Utilitarian  and  Spencerian  theory,  which  is,  as 
may  be  here  seen,  simply  a  revival  of  one  of  the  old 
Greek  schools  of  ethics.  This  theory,  that  pleasure  is 
essentially  good  and  pain  essentially  evil,  has  probably 
no  better  and  clearer  statement  anywhere  than  in  this 
extract  from  Socrates  recorded  by  Plato  about  400  B.  C. 
The  same  theory  was  later  used  with  modifications  by 
Aristotle,  350  B.  C.,  who  copied  many  ideas  from  Plato 
and  Socrates,  and  will  be  found  freely  in  Aristotle's 
Ethics,  as  shown  in  the  extracts  given  farther  on, 
where  he  distinctly  teaches  that  Virtue  is  that  course  of 
conduct  which  secures  or  leads  to  a  beneficent  final  result 
or  "end"  which  is  desirable  in  itself  as  such  final  end 
and  not  merely  as  a  "  means  "  to  something  else.  Hence 
he  distinctly  states  that  "  The  best  of  all  things  must  be 
something  final,"  and  that  "  Happiness  or  welfare  seems 

more  than  anything  else  to  answer  to  this  description, 

(168) 


EPICURUS)  the  much  maligned  and  misunder 
stood  "  Philosopher  of  the  Garden"  was  a  great  advo 
cate  of  the  moderate  and  simple  life,  and,  after  Soc 
rates,  one  of  the  clearest  exponents  of  the.  true  rational 
theory  of  Pleasure — the  modern  utilitarian  or  u  Spen- 
cerian  "  theory  of  ethics.  He  was  a  Deist  in  religion, 
but  a  disbeliever  in  immortality,  a  consistent  rational 
ist  and  materialist  in  general  thought,  and  a  great 
exponent  of  the  "atomic"  theory  of  matter  in  a  Uni 
verse  governed  by  fixed  laws. 

GIST  OF  EPICUREAN  ETHICS. 

"  Yet  some  there  are,  who,  with  great  flourishes, 
have  so  discoursed  against  pleasure  itself,  as  if  it  were 
something  ill  in  its  own  nature,  and  consequently  not 
appertaining  to  wisdom  and  felicity." 

u  When,  therefore,  we  say  in  general  terms,  pleas 
ure  is  the  end  of  happy  life,  we  are  far  from  meaning 
the  pleasures  of  luxurious  persons,  or  of  others,  as 
some,  either  through  ignorance,  dissent,  or  ill  will,  in 
terpret.  We  mean  no  more  but  this — Not  pained  in 
body  nor  troubled  in  mind." 

"For  it  is  not  perpetual  feasting  and  drinking,  not 
the  conversation  of  beautiful  women ;  not  rarities  of 
fish,  nor  any  dainties  of  a  profuse  table,  that  make  a 
happy  life  ;  but  reason,  with  sobriety  and  a  serene 
mind" 

"  Concerning  Temperance,  we  must  first  observe 
that  it  is  desired  not  for  its  own  sake,  but  for  that  it 
procureth  pleasure,  that  is,  brings  peace  to  the  minds 
of  men,  pleasing  and  soothing  them  with  a  kind  of 
concord." 

"  Hence  it  is  understood  that  Temperance  is  to  be 
desired,  not  for  that  it  avoids  some  pleasures,  but  be 
cause  he  who  refrains  from  them  declines  troubles, 
which  being  avoided  he  obtains  greater  pleasures. 
Which  it  so  doth  that  the  action  becomes  honest  and 
decent,  and  we  may  clearly  understand  that  the  same 
men  may  be  lovers  both  of  pleasure  and  of  decency." 


EPICURUS, 


B.   C.  300. 
From  bu>t  in  Museo  Cap'tolino,  Rome, 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  169 

for  we  always  choose  it  for  itself  and  never  for  the  sake 
of  something  else."  After  Aristotle,  Epicurus  (about 
300  B.  C.)  fully  adopted  and  clearly  taught  this  doctrine, 
which,  therefore,  also  came  to  be  called  the  "  Epicurean" 
theory,  and  under  that  name  has  been  probably  the  most 
maligned  and  misunderstood  theory  that  has  ever  been 
held  in  the  history  of  ethics,  particularly  during  the 
Christian  era  and  among  Christian  peoples,  where  it  has 
been  persistently  misrepresented  or  misunderstood. 
Thus  the  term  "Epicure"  or  "Epicurean"  has  come  to 
mean  in  a  gross  sense  a  mere  glutton  or  sensualist,  and 
in  a  more  exact  sense  a  person  of  most  elaborate  and  re 
fined  tastes  in  sensuous  delights  and  indulgences :  And 
Epicureanism  is  regarded  as  a  system  of  moral  philosophy 
which  simply  places  "  virtue  "  or  "good"  as  consisting 
essentially  in  a  life  of  mere  pleasure  or  sensuous  in 
dulgence.  The  truth  is,  however,  that  Epicurus  was  a 
man  of  the  greatest  simplicity  and  moderation — the 
"philosopher  of  the  Garden  " — who  boasted  of  his  ability 
to  live  on  the  simple  products  of  his  own  little  field,  of 
the  entire  sufficiency  of  "  barley  cakes  and  water"  for  all 
the  needs  of  life,  and  on  his  capacity  to  properly  live  on 
a  mere  "obolus" — one  cent — a  day  !  Not  only  this,  he 
denounced  in  the  clearest  terms  a  life  of  so-called  "  pleas 
ure"  or  sensuous  indulgence  and  showed  that  this  was 
the  very  course  best  calculated  to  produce  an  overplus 
of  pain  and  prevent  the  attainment  of  the  truly  happy 
life  with  the  overplus  or  true  balance  of  pleasure,  and 
the  minimum  of  pain  which  temperance  and  right  living 
inevitably  bring. 

In  order  to  clearly  show  what  this  true  Epicureanism 
is,  and  how  it  follows  on  the  lines  laid  down  by  Socrates 
and  Aristotle,  we  will  here  quote  a  few  paragraphs  from 
the  ethics  of  Epicurus : 


170  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"For  the  end  of  life,  by  the  tacit  consent  of  all  men,  is 
felicity. 

"  Therefore,  before  we  inquire  whether  felicity  really 
consists  in  pleasure,  we  must  show,  that  pleasure  is  in 
its  own  nature  good,  as  its  contrary,  pain,  is  in  its  own 
nature  ill. 

"There  needs  not  therefore  any  reasoning  to  prove, 
that  pleasure  is  to  be  desired,  pain  to  be  shunned ;  for" 
this  is  manifest  to  our  sense,  as  that  fire  is  hot,  snow 
white,  honey  sweet.  We  need  no  arguments  to  prove 
this,  it  is  enough  that  we  give  notice  of  it. 

"First,  therefore,  we  must  consider  of  felicity  no 
otherwise  than  as  of  health ;  it  being  manifest,  that  the 
state,  in  which  the  mind  is  free  from  perturbation,  the 
body  from  pain,  is  no  other  than  the  perfect  health  of  the 
whole  man. 

"Yet  some  there  are,  who,  with  great  flourishes,  have 
so  discoursed  against  pleasure  itself,  as  if  it  were  some 
thing  ill  in  its  own  nature,  and  consequently  not  apper 
taining  to  wisdom  and  felicity. 

"When,  therefore,  we  say  in  general  terms,  pleasure 
is  the  end  of  happy  life,  we  are  far  from  meaning  the 
pleasures  of  luxurious  persons,  or  of  others,  as  some, 
either  through  ignorance,  dissent,  or  ill  will,  interpret. 
We  mean  110  more  but  this,  (to  repeat  it  once  more)  Not 
pained  in  body,  nor  troubled  in  mind. 

"  For  it  is  not  perpetual  feasting  and  drinking ;  not  the 
conversation  of  beautiful  women ;  not  rarities  of  fish,  nor 
any  other  dainties  of  a  profuse  table,  that  make  a  happy 
life  ;  but  reason,  with  sobriety,  and  a  serene  mind. 

"Others  condemn,  and  exclaim  on  us,  for  affirming, 
that  the  virtues  are  of  such  a  nature,  as  that  they  con 
duce  to  pleasure  or  felicity,  as  if  we  meant  that  pleasure 
which  is  obscene  and  infamous,  but  let  them  rail  as  they 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  171 

please.  For  as  they  make  virtue  the  chief  good,  so  do 
we.  But  if  the  discourse  be  of  living  happily,  or  felicity, 
why  should  not  this  be  a  good  superior  to  virtue,  to  the 
attainment  whereof  virtue  itself  is  but  subservient? 

"  For  while  nature  is  our  guide,  whatsoever  we  do 
tends  to  this,  that  we  neither  be  pained  in  body  nor 
troubled  in  mind ;  and  as  soon  as  we  have  attained  this, 
all  disturbances  of  the  mind  are  quieted,  and  there  is 
nothing  beyond  it  that  we  can  aim  at  to  complete  the 
good,  both  of  our  soul  and  body ;  for  that  absolute  good 
of  human  nature  is  contained  in  the  peace  of  the  soul 
and  the  body. 

"Hence  is  manifest,  when  I  formerly  said,  A  sober  or 
well  ordered  reason  procures  a  pleasant  and  happy  life ; 
we  are  to  understand,  that  it  procures  it  by  means  of  the 
virtues  which  it  ingenerates  and  preserves. 

"  By  this  you  find  why  I  conceive,  that  the  virtues  are 
connatural  to  a  happy  life,  and  that  it  is  impossible  to 
separate  happy   life   from   them.     All   other  things,  as 
being  frail  and  mortal,  are  transitory,   separable  from 
true  and  constant  pleasure  ;  only  virtue,  as  being  a  per 
petual  and  immortal  good,  is  inseparable  from  it." 
(From  History  of  Philosophy,  by  Thos.  Stanley, 
London,  1701). 

Now  a  little  consideration  will  show  that  what  Aristotle 
meant  by  the  final  end,  "happiness"  or  "welfare"  is 
exactly  what  Socrates  before  him  and  Epicurus  after 
him  meant  by  "  pleasure."  And  in  the  last  analysis  it 
will  be  found,  we  think,  to  be  an  irrefutable  proposition 
that  "  pleasure"  is  the  essence  of  what  we  call  "  happi 
ness  "  or  well-being,  and  "  pain  "  the  essence  of  what  we 
term  tinhappiness  or  ill-being,  as  demonstrated  in  the 
cogent  reasonings  of  Socrates  with  Protagoras  twenty- 


172  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

four  centuries  ago  in  the  clear  and  simple  argument  of 
that  great  rationalist,  Epicurus,  two  centuries  later,  no 
less  than  in  the  almost  identical  and  unanswerable  rea 
sonings  of  that  great  Socratic  and  Epicurean  rationalist 
of  our  own  day — Herbert  Spencer,  in  his  Data  of  Ethics. 
But  opponents  of  this  great  ancient  and  modern  school 
of  rational  ethics  will  persist  in  misunderstanding  and 
misapplying  this  great  decisive  term  "  pleasure "  as  the 
true  test  of  the  final  Tightness  of  conduct,  and  one  of  the 
first  men  responsible  for  bringing  about  this  confusion 
was  probably  the  first  great  "  Hedonist,"  Aristippus,  a 
pupil  of  Socrates,  who  grossly  misapplied  the  Socratic 
ethical  theory  that  "  pleasure  "  was  the  only  good  and 
pain  the  only  evil,  to  mean  merely  the  initial  or  immediate 
pleasure  of  an  act,  without  any  regard  to  the  ultimate, 
final  or  actual  pleasure  when  all  the  results  and  conse 
quences  of  the  initial  act  had  been  duly  allowed  for  and 
adjusted.  This  is  the  great  error  of  the  so-called  "  He 
donistic  school "  which  has  too  long  been  mistaken  for 
the  true .  "  Epicurean  "  or  utilitarian  school.  Hence, 
when  the  term  "  pleasure  "  is  used  in  a  philosophical, 
ethical  sense,  it  will  be  obvious  that  it  must  be  under 
stood  not  only  in  the  positive  form,  but  also,  and  even 
much  more  so,  in  the  negative  form,  that  is,  in  absence 
from  pain  or  disturbance,  "not  pained  in  body  nor 
troubled  in  mind  "  as  Epicurus  says,  for  it  is  undeniable 
that  this  negative  form  of  pleasure,  the  mere  tranquil 
quiescent  state,  free  from  pain,  which  a  state  of  normal 
simple  health  gives,  is  absolutely  the  chief  and  greatest 
element  of  a  normal,  moral,  happy  or  wrell  adjusted  life, 
and  not  mere  tense,  positive  pleasures,  gratifications  or 
indulgences.  And  in  this  logical  view  of  the  matter  we 
can  therefore  readily  recognize  the  real  soundness  of  the 
great  Socratic  theory  that  "  knowledge"  or  "wisdom  "  is 


o 
-V 


ARISTIPPUS  might  probably  be  called  the  original 
"Hedonist,"  the  perverter  of  the  Socratic  doctrine  of 
"  Pleasure"  as  the  greatest  good,  and  the  exponent  of 
the  voluptuous  theory  of  ethics,  which  afterwards  came 
to  be  incorrectly  called  "Epicureanism"  but  which 
was  really  a  false  Epicureanism.  True  Epicurean 
ism  is  the  doctrine  of  rational  moderation  resulting  not 
in  the  greatest  immediate  delight  but  in  the  greatest 
ultimate  utility  or  final  permanent  pleasure.  (See  p. 
169,  &c. 

SKETCH  OF  ARISTIPPUS. 

FROM  STANLEY'S  HISTORY  OF  PHILOSOPHY. 

From  Cyrene  Aristippus  went  first  to  Athens,  in 
vited  by  the  fame  of  Socrates,  concerning  whom  he  fell 
into  discourse  with  Ischomachus,  meeting  him  casually 
at  the  Olympic  Games,  and  inquiring  what  disputes 
they  were  wherewith  Socrates  prevailed  so  much  upon 
the  yoiing  men,  he  received  from  him  some  little  seeds 
and  scatterings  thereof,  wherewith  he  was  so  passion 
ately  affected,  that  he  grew  pale  and  lean,  till,  to 
assuage  his  fervent  thirst,  he  took  a  voyage  to  Athens^ 
and  there  drunk  at  the  fountain,  satisfying  himself 
with  the  person,  his  discourse  and  philosophy,  the  end 
whereof  was  to  know  our  evils  and  to  acquit  ourselves 
of  them.  Aristotle  said,  philosophy  doth  harm  to  those 
who  misinterpret  things  well  said.  Aristippus  chiefly 
delighted  with  the  more  voluptuous  disputes  of  Soc 
rates,  asserted  pleasure  to  be  the  ultimate  end  wherein 
all  happiness  doth  consist. 

Hi's  life  was  agreeable  to  the  opinion,  which  he  em 
ployed  in  luxury,  sweet  unguents,  rich  garments, 
wine  and  women  ;  maintained  by  a  course  as  different 
from  the  precepts  and  practice  of  Socrates  as  the  things 
themselves  were.  For,  notwithstanding  he  had  a  good 
estate  (and  three  country  seats)  he  first  of  the  Socratic 
disciples  took  money  for  teaching.  Which  Socrates 
observing,  asked  him  how  he  came  to  have  so  much. 
He  replied,  "How  came  you  to  have  so  little?"  A 
further  dislike  of  this  course  Socrates  expressed,  when 
Aristippus  sending  him  twenty  min<z,  he  returned  it, 
saying,  his  Dczmon  would  not  suffer  him  to  take  it. 


ARI3TIPPUS 

THE   lt  HEDONIST'1   OR  FALSE  EPICUREAN. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  173 

the  essence  of  virtue,  and  that  a  true  resultant  in  actual 
final  pleasure  or  happiness  is  the  test  of  what  is  virtuous, 
for  it  is  obvious  that  a  true  wisdom  or  knowledge  of 
causes  and  effects  is  necessary  to  determine  how  to 
abstain  and  how  to  indulge  so  as  to  result  in  the  highest 
degree  of  ultimate  pleasure  or  happiness,  positive  or 
negative. 

The  neglect,  therefore,  to  duly  weigh  and  consider  this 
aspect  of  negative  pleasure  and  to  regard  the  relation  of 
initial  and  ultimate  pleasure  in  striking  a  true  resultant  or 
balance,  will  be  found  to  be  one  of  the  great  errors  which 
the  critics  of  the  utilitarian  theory  of  ethics  constantly 
fall  into,  and  it  is  time  that  this  error  was  abandoned  by 
ethical  reasoners,  for  we  think  that  if  "  pleasure "  be 
considered  both  in  the  positive  and  negative  aspects,  and 
in  the  broad  sense,  and  the  adjustment  made  between 
initial  and  ultimate  pleasures,  and  a  true  balance  struck, 
then  the  dicta  of  Socratic-Epicurean  or  Utilitarian  ethics, 
that  conduct  is  good  or  bad  simply  because  it  tends  to 
produce  pleasure  or  pain,  happiness  or  unhappiness,  wel 
fare  or  injury,  is  simply  impregnable,  ethically,  logically 
and  philosophically,  and  the  opposite  theory  that  regards 
"virtue"  itself  as  the  "  end"  of  ethics,  and  not  "health," 
"pleasure,"  "happiness"  or  "  welfare,"  is  clearly  irra 
tional  and  a  reductio  ad  absurdum  as  it  is  simply  prefer 
ring  the  "  means"  to  the  "  end." 

A  most  interesting  point,  however,  to  be  noted,  just 
at  this  connection,  is  that  not  only  is  the  modern 
utilitarian  theory  of  ethics  found  stated  in  the  teachings 
of  Socrates  in  the  most  clear  and  positive  manner,  as 
above  shown,  but  the  distinctions  here  pointed  out  of 
the  necessity  of  making  a  true  adjustment  of  all  the 
consequences  or  results  of  the  act,  for  pain  Or  pleasure, 
to  strike  the  true  resultant  or  actual  balance  of  pleasure 


174  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

which  must  determine  the  real  character  of  the  act  as 
"  good  "  or  "  virtuous,"  is  also  as  clearly  set  forth  by  that 
"  Wizard  of  Conversation,"  the  great  old  Socrates — the 
real  father  of  modern  rational  ethics.  Let  us  therefore, 
here  juxtapose  a  few  telling  paragraphs  from  the  dialogue 
of  Socrates,  and  we  will  readily  see  how  clearly  these 
points  and  distinctions  are  brought  out : 

:f  Then  you  think  that  pain  is  an  evil  and  pleasure  is 
a  good ;  and  even  pleasure  you  deem  an  evil  when  it  robs 
you  of  greater  pleasures  than  it  gives,  or  causes  greater 
pain  than  the  pleasures  which  it  has :  If,  however,  you 
call  pleasure  an  evil  in  relation  to  some  other  end  or 
standard,  you  will  be  able  to  show  us  that  standard. 
But  you  have  none  to  show. 

"  Would  they  still  be  evil  if  they  had  no  attendant  evil 
consequences  simply  because  they  give  the  consciousness 
of  pleasure  of  whatever  nature  ?  Would  they  not  an 
swer  that  they  are  not  evil  on  account  of  the  pleasure 
which  is  immediately  given  by  them,  but  on  account  of 
the  after  consequences — diseases  and  the  like. 

"And  have  you  not  a  similar  way  of  speaking  about 
pain  ?  You  call  pain  a  good  when  it  takes  away  greater 
pains  than  those  which  it  has  or  gives  pleasures  greater 
than  the  pains ;  for  I  say  that  if  you  have  some  standards 
other  than  pleasure  and  pain  to  which  you  refer  when 
you  call  actual  pain  a  good,  you  can  show  what  that  is. 
But  you  cannot. 

"  If  you  weigh  pleasures  against  pleasures,  }^ou,  of 
course,  take  the  more  and  greater ;  or  if  you  weigh  pains 
against  pains,  you  take  the  fewer  and  the  less;  or  if 
pleasures  against  pains,  then  you  choose  that  course  of 
action  in  which  the  painful  is  exceeded  by  the  pleasant, 
whether  the*  distant  by  the  near  or  the  near  by  the  dis 
tant,  and  you  avoid  that  course  of  action  in  which  the 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  175 

pleasant  is  exceeded  by  the  painful.  Would  you  not 
admit,  my  friends,  that  this  is  true  ?  I  am  confident  that 
they  cannot  deny  this. 

"  But  now  in  laughing  at  us  you  will  be  laughing  at 
yourselves,  for  you  also  admitted  that  men  err  in  their 
choice  of  pleasures  and  pains ;  that  is,  in  their  choice  of 
good  and  evil,  from  defect  of  knowledge,  and  you  ad 
mitted  further  that  they  err  not  only  from  defect  of 
knowledge  in  general,  but  of  that  particular  knowledge 
which  is  called  measuring. 

"Then  I  should  say  to  them  in  my  name  and  yours: 
Do  you  think  them  evil  for  any  other  reason  except  that 
they  end  in  pain  and  rob  us  of  other  pleasures? 

"And  do  you  call  them  good  because  they  occasion 
the  greatest  immediate  suffering  and  pain ;  or  because 
afterwards  they  bring  health  and  improvement  of  the 
bodily  condition  and  the  salvation  of  states,  and  empires, 
and  wealth  ? 

"  Are  these  things  good  for  any  other  reason  except 
that  they  end  in  pleasure  and  get  rid  of  and  avert  pain  ? 
Are  you  looking  to  any  other  standard  but  pleasure  and 
pain  when  you  call  them  good?" 

Note  again  how  the  clear-thinking  Epicurus  voices  the 
Socratic  theory  of  the  true  ethics  of  pleasure  in  his  dis 
course  on  "  Temperance : " — 

"  Concerning  Temperance  we  must  first  observe  that 
it  is  desired  not  for  its  own  sake  but  for  that  it  procureth 
pleasure,  that  is,  brings  peace  to  the  minds  of  men, 
pleasing  and  soothing  them  with  a  kind  of  concord. 

"  But  most  men  not  able  to  hold  and  keep  to  what  they 
have  resolved  on,  being  vanquished  and  debilitated  by 
the  appearance  of  present  pleasure,  resign  themselves  to 
the  fetters  of  lust,  not  foreseeing  what  will  follow.  But 


176  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

they  who  enjoy  pleasures  so  that  no  pain  shall  ensue, 
and  who  preserve  their  judgment  constant,  nor  are  over 
come  by  pleasure,  to  the  doing  of  what  they  know  ought 
not  to  be  done,  these  men  obtain  the  greatest  pleasure  by 
pretermitting  pleasure:  They  also  many  times  suffer 
some  pain  to  prevent  falling  into  greater. 

"  Hence  it  is  understood  that  Temperance  is  to  be  de 
sired,  not  for  that  it  avoids  some  pleasures,  but  because 
he  who  refrains  from  them  declines  troubles,  which  being 
avoided  he  obtains  greater  pleasures.  Which  it  so  doth 
that  the  action  becomes  honest  and  decent  and  we  may 
clearly  understand  that  the  same  men  may  be  lovers 
both  of  pleasure  and  of  decency." 
(History  of  Philosophy,  Thos.  Stanley,  London,  1701.) 

Now  it  only  remains  to  be  shown  how  identical  is  the 
standpoint  of  Herbert  Spencer  in  his  Data  of  Ethics  with 
that  of  Socrates  in  his  dialogue  with  Protagoras,  and 
how  absolutely  similar  the  arguments  and  challenges  are 
in  both  cases,  to  demonstrate  the  truth  of  the  statement 
in  Prof.  Hyslop's  lecture  that  the  ethical  philosophy  of 
the  Socratic  period  is  identical  with  modern  evolutionary 
philosophy,  and  this  is  particularly  true  of  the  Socratic 
school  itself,  as  shown  by  Socrates,  Aristotle  and  Epi 
curus,  in  the  extracts  already  given. 

Let  us,  therefore,  now  compare  a  few  test  paragraphs 
from  Spencer's  Data  of  Ethics  with  the  paragraphs  just 
quoted  from  Socrates  and  Epicurus,  and  we  will  see  that 
the  identity  of  thought  is  absolute : — 

"Thus  there  is  no  escape  from  the  admission  that  in 
calling  good  the  conduct  which  subserves  life,  and  bad 
the  conduct  which  hinders  or  destroys  it,  and  in  so  im 
plying  that  life  is  a  blessing  and  not  a  curse,  we  are  in- 


THE    VOLUPTUOUS    (?)    "PLEASURES"   OF   THE 
REAL    EPICURUS. 

"  For  my  part,  when  I  eat  coarse  bread  and  drink 
water,  or  sometimes  augment  my  commons  with  a 
little  Cytheridian  Cheese,  (^.vhen  I  have  a  mind  to 
feast  extraordinarily],  I  take  great  delight  in  it,  and 
bid  defiance  to  those  pleasures  which  accompany  the 
usual  magnificence  of  feasts ;  so  that  if  I  have  but 
bread,  or  barley-cakes  and  water,  I  am  furnished  to 
content  even  with  Jove  himself  in  point  of  felicity" 

"  For  my  part,  truly  (that  I  may  with  modesty  in 
stance  myself}  I  am  content,  and  highly  pleased  with 
the  plants  and  fruits  of  my  own  little  gardens  ;  and 
will,  that  this  inscription  be  set  over  the  Gate, 
Stranger,  here  you  may  stay  ;  here  the  Supreme  Good 
is  pleasure ;  the  Master  of  this  little  house  is  hospit 
able,  friendly,  and  will  entertain  you  with  polenta, 
and  afford  you  water  plentifzilly ,  and  will  ask  you, 
how  you  like  your  entertainment  f  These  little 
Gardens  invite  not  hunger,  but  satisfy  it ;  nor  increase 
thirst  with  drinks,  but  extinguish  it  with  the  natural 
and  pleasant  remedy." 

"  In  this  pleasure  I  have  grown  old,  finding  by  ac 
count,  that  my  diet  amounts  not  fully  to  an  obolus  a 
day,  and  yet  some  days  there  are,  in  which  I  abate 
somewhat  even  of  that,  to  make  trial,  whether  I  want 
any  thing  of  full  and  perfect  pleasure,  or  how  much, 
and  whether  it  be  worth  great  labour" 

(u  Polenta  "—a  thick  cereal  mush  ;    ' '  obolus  "  —one  cent. ) 


EPIGURU3  IN  HIS  GARDEN, 

From  Stanley's  History. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  177 

evitably  asserting  that  conduct  is  good  or  bad  according 
as  its  total  effects  are  pleasurable  or  painful. 

" Omitting  people  of  this  class  (Devil  Worshippers), 
if  there  are  any,  as  beyond  or  beneath  argument,  we  find 
that  all  others  avowedly  or  tacitly  hold  that  the  final 
justification  for  maintaining  life,  can  only  be  the  recep 
tion  from  it  of  a  surplus  of  pleasurable  feeling  over  pain 
ful  feeling  ;  and  that  goodness  or  badness  can  be  ascribed 
to  acts  which  subserve  life  or  hinder  life,  only  on  this 
supposition. 

"  Using,  then,  as  our  tests,  these  most  pronounced 
forms  of  good  and  bad  conduct,  we  find  it  unquestion 
able  that  our  ideas  of  their  goodness  and  badness  really 
originate  from  our  consciousness  of  the  certainty  or 
probability  that  they  will  produce  pleasures  or  pains 
somewhere. 

"  Unless  it  is  asserted  that  courage  and  chastity  could 
still  be  thought  of  as  virtues  though  thus  productive  of 
misery,  it  must  be  admitted  that  the  conceptions  of 
virtue  cannot  be  separated  from  the  conception  of  happi 
ness-producing  conduct ;  and  that  as  this  holds  of  all  the 
virtues,  however  otherwise  unlike,  it  is  from  their  con- 
ducivness  to  happiness  that  they  come  to  be  classed  as 
virtues. 

"So  that  no  school  can  avoid  taking  for  the  ultimate 
moral  aim  a  desirable  state  of  feeling  called  by  whatever 
name — gratification,  enjoyment,  happiness.  Pleasure 
somewhere,  at  some  time,  to  some  being  or  beings,  is  an 
inexpugnable  element  of  the  conception.  It  is  as  much 
a  necessary  form  of  moral  intuition  as  space  is  a  neces 
sary  form  of  intellectual  intuition." 

Now  we  think  it  will  be  readily  admitted  on  com 
parison  that  the  point  of  view  and  the  argument  of  the 
old  Greek  thinkers  could  not  be  any  nearer  to  that  of  our 


1 78  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

modern  rationalists,  unless  the  very  words  themselves 
were  identical.  Note,  for  example,  how  alike  are  the 
concluding  keynotes  in  both  Socrates  and  Spencer.  Thus 
Socrates  asks  twenty-four  centuries  ago,  "  Are  these 
things  good  for  any  other  reason  except  that  they  end 
in  pleasure  and  get  rid  of  and  avert  pain  ?  Are  you  look 
ing  to  any  other  standard  but  pleasure  and  pain  when 
you  call  them  good?"  And  Spencer  thus  agrees  with 
and  answers  Socrates  over  a  gap  of  twenty-four  centuries 
as  follows  : — "We  find  it  unquestionable  that  our  ideas 
of  their  goodness  and  badness  really  originate  from  our 
consciousness  of  the  certainty  or  probability  that  they 
will  produce  pleasure  or  pain  somewhere.  It  must  be 
admitted  that  the  conceptions  of  virtue  cannot  be  sepa 
rated  from  the  conception  of  happiness-producing  con 
duct.  So  that  no  school  can  avoid  taking  for  the  ultimate 
moral  aim  a  desirable  state  of  feeling  called  by  whatever 
name,  gratification,  enjoyment,  happiness.  Pleasure 
somewhere,  at  some  time,  to  some  being  or  beings,  is  an 
inexpugnable  element  of  the  conception." 

Thus  we  find  an  absolute  unity  in  the  basic  ethical 
philosophy  of  the  greatest  thinkers  among  the  highest 
civilizations  of  the  past  with  the  teachings  of  the  greatest 
scientific  moralists  of  our  own  day,  and  this  fact  should 
certainly  lead  us  to  give  more  honor  and  credit  to  these 
grand  old  ethical  " pagans"  than  they  generally  get  in 
popular  estimation,  and  it  should  also  increase  our  respect 
for  the  modern  evolutionary  and  utilitarian  school  of 
ethics  as  being  not  only  natural  and  rational,  but  simple 
and  practical,  and  combining  the  dicta  of  a  consensus  of 
some  of  the  greatest  moral  intellects  in  past  and  present 
times.— C.  M.  H. 


A 


HERBERT  SPENCER.  Born  at  Derby,  England, 
April  2j,  1820.  The  great  modern  exponent  of 
Evolution  and  the  Utilitarian  Theory  of  Ethics. 
The  oldest  living  philosopher  and  the  greatest 
rationalistic  thinker  of  the  nineteenth  century — the 
Socrates,  Aristotle  and  Epicurus  of  our  day. 

GIST  OF  SPENCERIAN  ETHICS,  A.  D.,  1893. 

Thus  there  is  no  escape  from  the  admission  that  in 
calling  good  the  conduct  which  siibserves  life,  and  bad 
the  conduct  which  hinders  or  destroys  it,  and  in  so 
implying  that  life  is  a  blessing  and  not  a  ctirse,  we  are 
inevitably  asserting  that  conduct  is  good  or  bad  ac 
cording  as  its  total  effects  are  pleasurable  or  painful. 

Using,  then,  as  our  tests,  these  most  pronounced 
forms  of  good  and  bad  conduct,  we  find  it  unquestion 
able  that  our  ideas  of  their  goodness  and  badness 
really  originate  from  our  consciousness  of  the  cer 
tainty  or  probability  that  they  will  prodiice  pleasures 
or  pains  somewhere. 

Unless  it  is  asserted  that  courage  and  chastity  could 
still  be  thought  of  as  virtues  though  thus  productive 
of  misery,  it  must  be  admitted  that  the  conceptions 
of  virtue  cannot  be  separated  from  the  conception  of 
happiness-producing  conduct ;  and  that  as  this  holds 
of  all  the  virtues,  however  otherwise  unlike,  it  is  from 
their  conduciveness  to  happiness  that  they  come  to  be 
classed  as  virtues. 

So  that  no  school  can  avoid  taking  for  the  ultimate 
moral  aim  a  desirable  state  of  feeling  called  by 
whatever  name — gratification,  enjoyment,  happiness. 
Pleasure  somewhere,  at  some  time,  to  some  being  or 
beings,  is  an  inexpugnable  element  of  the  conception. 
It  is  as  much  a  necessary  form  of  moral  intuition  as 
space  is  a  necessary  form  of  intellectual  intuition. 
Spencer* s  Data  of  Ethics,  Edition  1897. 


HERBERT  SPENCER, 

From  a  photograph  presented  by  Mr.  Spencer  to  Dr.  Lewis  G.  Janes. 


SOCRATES  AND  THEIST1C  ETHICS. 

The  chief  opponent  of  the  Socratic-Epicurean  or 
Utilitarian  School  of  Ethics,  has  always  been,  as  it  now 
is,  what  may  be  termed  the  "  Theistic  School  of  Ethics." 
And  by  "Theistic"  we  mean  that  school — under  what 
ever  religious  or  denominational  name  it  may  assume 
from  time  to  time  in  the  world's  history — which  holds 
that  the  true  standard  and  motive  for  human  conduct  is 
accordance  with  the  "Will  of  God"  or  that  course  of  con 
duct  in  man  which  may  be  held  to  harmonize  with  the 
"  pleasure"  or  "desire"  of  the  Infinite  and  contribute 
primarily  or  essentially  to  the  "honor"  and  "glory"  of 
God,  and  not  primarily  and  essentially  to  the  pleasure, 
welfare  or  utility  of  man. 

As,  however,  the  Theistic  School  of  Ethics  is  essen 
tially  religious  and  dogmatic  in  its  character  and  origin, 
it  cannot  be  expected  to  show  to  logical  or  philosophic 
advantage  with  that  humane  utilitarian  system  which,  as 
we  have  shown,  has  been  developed  rationally  from  a 
natural  and  logical  basis  by  some  of  the  greatest  and 
most  reverent  minds  of  the  world  in  past  and  present 
times,  and  who  have  thereby  placed  ethics  on  a  rational, 
natural  and  self-commending  basis  as  distinct  from  the 
purely  arbitrary  and  dogmatic  ground  of  Theistic  Schools. 
And  it  is  very  interesting  to  here  note  that  our  old  friend, 

(i79) 


i8o  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

Socrates,  who  we  have  already  found  to  be  the  real 
father  of  the  modern  utilitarian  school  of  rational  ethics, 
was  yet  one  of  the  greatest  Theists  among  the  Pagan 
philosophers,  and  in  many  features  of  his  religious  belief, 
as  we  have  already  shown,  very  closely  approached  the 
belief  of  the  Jew  and  Christian  of  apostolic  days.  And 
yet,  again,  this  great  philosophic  and  religious  Socrates 
—the  almost  Christian  Pagan — saw  nothing  derogatory 
to  his  Theistic  conception  of  God  and  the  government  of 
the  Universe  in  founding  the  true  motive-basis  of  ethics 
or  good  conduct  in  man  on  the  ground  primarily  and 
essentially  of  benefit,  utility,  pleasure,  happiness,  or 
welfare,  to  man  himself  and  not  primarily  on  the  "  will," 
" pleasure,"  "  honor,"  or  "glory  "  of  God  as  in  the  purely 
Theistic  system  of  ethics  formulated  both  before  and 
since  the  days  of  Socrates. 

Now  to  found  the  motive-basis  for  good  conduct  in 
man  on  the  ground  primarily  of  "benefit"  to  an  "Infinite 
and  All-Perfect  Being,"  instead  of  primarily  on  benefit 
to  man  himself,  would  to  the  logical  and  rational  utili 
tarian  seem  not  only  extravagant  and  essentially  irrever 
ent  and  absurd,  but  as  a  vain  and  childish  attempt  to 
patronize  the  Infinite.  For,  obviously,  "The  Infinite" 
stands  in  no  need  of  "benefits"  from  man,  but  man  does 
very  much  need  the  great  benefits  which  right  conduct 
can  confer  upon  himself.  Hence  it  is  reverently  believed 
that  there  can  be  no  higher,  more  sane,  or  more  practical 
ground  for  human  ethics  than  that  of  "enlightened  self- 
interest  "  for  one's-self  and  one's  neighbor  on  the  great 
lines  of  Prudence,  Justice  and  Fortitude,  which  form  the 
trinity  of  practical  Virtue. 

Not  only  do  the  greatest  philosophers  of  the  Greek 
and  Roman  civilizations  agree  with  the  ethics  of  our 
modern  rationalists  as  already  shown,  but  it  is  further 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  181 

interesting  to  note  that  a  still  more  ancient  and  extensive 
rational  school — the  Confucianists  of  China — is  also  in 
full  accord  with  them.  Thus  the  Chinese  Sages  teach 
these  clear  utilitarian  doctrines : 

"  The  senses  and  the  mind  are  what  Heaven  has  given 
us.  To  preserve  our  mental  constitution  and  nourish 
our  nature  is  the  way  to  serve  Heaven." 

"  To  give  one's-self  earnestly  to  the  duties  due  to  men, 
and  while  respecting  spiritual  beings  to  keep  aloof  from 
them,  may  be  called  Wisdom." 

"  The  doctrine  of  our  Master  is  to  be  true  to  the  prin 
ciples  of  our  nature  and  the  benevolent  exercise  of  them 
to  others — this  and  nothing  more."  * 

Now  the  foregoing  texts  give  us  a  pure  utilitarianism 
in  the  Chinese  form  which  is  as  true  and  rational  in  tone 
as  anything  expressed  by  Socrates,  Epicurus  or  Herbert 
Spencer,  and  when  taken  in  connection  with  what  we 
have  quoted  from  the  Greek  Philosophers,  proves  how 
wide  and  deep  is  the  philosophic  support  for  the  utili 
tarian  theory  in  ancient  as  well  as  in  modern  thought. 

Even  that  great  old  ethical  Hebrew,  the  prophet  Micah, 
who  was  almost  contemporary  with  Confucius,  may  be 
claimed  also  as  a  true  utilitarian  in  Ethics,  as  is  shown 
in  that  grand  little  verse  which  may  be  said  to  be  one  of 
the  purest  pieces  of  ethics  in  the  Old  Testament : 

"  What  doth  the  Lord  require  of  thee  but  to  do  justly, 
and  to  love  mercy,  and  to  walk  humbly."f  In  this  we 
have  a  purely  ethical  creed,  sufficient  for  the  regulation 
of  any  life— Justice,  Kindness,  Simplicity  and  Reason 
ableness — and  it  is  purely  utilitarian,  as  it  concerns  itself 
primarily  and  directly  with  benefit  to  man. — C.  M.  H. 

•See  Legge's  Chinese  Classics,  and  Prof.  James'  Ethics  of  Chinese  Sages, 
t  Micah,  VI.  8.  King  James  Version. 


ARISTOTLE  ON  THE  IDEA  OF  GOD. 

Note: — This  extract  is  taken  from  Aristotle's  Meta 
physics. 

After  having  presented  the  arguments  for  the  exist 
ence  of  God  as  the  first  cause  of  the  world's  order,  Aris 
totle  proceeds  to  describe  His  nature  more  definitely  in 
a  separate  chapter.  The  argument  consists  in  the  ne 
cessity  of  a  prime  mover  as  the  condition  of  the  world's 
motion  which  is  supposed  to  be  circular. — J.  H.  H. 

"  Since  this  is  the  fact  of  the  case,  and  since,  if  it  is 
not  so,  the  world  must  have  originated  from  chaos  and 
nothing,  which  difficulties  are  removed  by  the  above 
supposition,  there  exists  something  which  never  ceases 
to  move  and  which  moves  in  a  circle.  This  is  evident, 
both  from  reason  and  from  the  facts  of  observation. 
Consequently  the  first  heaven  is  eternal  and  there  exists 
something  that  moves  it,  and  as  that  which  is  both 
moved  and  moving  stands  between  these,  there  must  also 
exist  something  which  moves  without  being  moved, 
which  is  eternal  and  a  self-existent  reality.  It  imparts 
motion  thus.  The  appetitive  and  the  conscious  move 
without  being  moved.  Both  are  in  their  origin  one  and 

the  same.     For  that  which  appears  as  pleasant  is  desired 

(182) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers,  183 

and  the  original  object  of  the  will  is  that  which  appears 
pleasant.  We  desire  it  because  it  is  pleasant,  but  it  does 
not  appear  pleasant  because  it  is  beautiful.  The  begin 
ning  is  thought.  Reason,  however,  is  moved  by  the 
thought  of  the  intelligible.  But  the  intelligible  is  in 
itself  only  a  series  of  things  of  like  kind,  and  in  this  is 
the  independent  first  cause,  and  from  it  comes  the  simple 
and  actual.  The  one  and  the  simple  are  nevertheless 
not  the  same.  The  one  is  that  which  indicates  a  limit ; 
the  simple  is  that  which  indicates  quality.  But  the 
pleasant  and  that  which  is  desirable  on  its  own  account, 
is  also  found  in  this  series,  and  the  first  cause  is  always 
the  highest  or  something  like  it.  Also  the  final  cause 
exists  in  the  unmoved,  and  is  shown  in  this  division 
itself.  For  the  final  cause  is  contained  in  something. 
The  one  is  or  exists  already,  the  other  does  not.  The 
final  cause  moves  as  a  thing  that  is  desired.  The  moved 
imparts  motion  to  other  things.  When  now  anything 
is  moved  it  is  such  that  it  might  have  been  otherwise. 
Circular  motion  is  the  first  form  and  if  this  is  actual  this 
motion  cannot  occur  otherwise  than  in  space,  although 
this  is  not  according  to  its  nature  in  itself.  But  if  a 
moving  cause  which  is  itself  unmoved  but  active,  be 
assumed,  it  is  impossible  that  its  conduct  should  be 
otherwise.  Motion  is  the  first  step  in  evolution  and  this 
first  motion  is  circular  and  was  caused  by  the  first  mover. 
For  this  reason  must  the  first  mover  be  necessarily  ex 
istent,  and  in  so  far  as  it  is  necessary  it  is  also  noble,  and 
with  this  constitutes  the  first  principle.  Necessity  or 
the  necessary  has  two  meanings.  One  of  them  is  that 
which  is  effected  by  some  power  against  a  natural 
impulse.  Then  there  is  one  which  denotes  that  without 
which  the  good  cannot  take  place,  and  finally,  it  denotes 
that  which  cannot  be  otherwise,  that  which  is  absolutely. 


184  Rthics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

On  such  a  first  cause  depends  both  the  heavens  and  the 
order  of  physical  nature.  His  life  is  of  such  excellence 
that  we  can  only  realize  it  for  a  limited  period.  But 
this  Being  remains  always  so.  For  us  this  is  impossible, 
but  not  for  this  Supreme  Being  for  whom  also  pleasure 
is  activity.  For  this  reason  also  consciousness,  per 
ception,  and  thought  are  the  most  pleasant.  Hopes 
and  recollection,  however,  are  effected  through  these. 
Thought  belongs  to  God  as  his  best  attribute  and  the 
highest  degree  of  thought  belongs  to  the  best  Being  in 
the  highest  degree.  Reason  knows  itself  by  compre 
hending  or  participating  in  its  object.  It  is  through  this 
comprehension  and  reflection  that  it  becomes  a  thinking 
Being,  so  that  Reason  and  the  object  thought  are  one 
and  the  same :  for  reason  is  that  which  can  comprehend 
the  thinkable  and  the  real  or  existent.  It  is  active  in  as 
much  as  it  has  this  within  itself.  What  Reason  seems 
to  possess  as  divine,  God  also  has  in  a  higher  degree, 
and  this  intuitive  thought  is  the  noblest  and  best.  If 
now  God  is  always  so  excellent  in  his  nature,  as  we  are 
only  at  times  and  for  a  limited  period,  and  this  quality 
is  worthy  of  reverence,  so  it  is  still  more  to  be  reverenced 
when  it  is  possessed  by  God  in  a  higher  degree.  This 
is  the  fact  in  his  case.  He  is  the  seat  of  life :  for  the 
activity  of  Reason  is  life  and  the  nature  of  God  is  activity. 
We  say  of  Divinity  that  it  is  the  eternal  and  most  ex 
cellent  form  of  life,  so  that  this  quality  must  belong  to 
the  eternal  and  uninterrupted  existence  of  the  Godhead." 

Note : — It  will  be  observed  that  Aristotle's  conception 
of  God  as  above  given  is  substantially  the  same  as  Plato's 
conception  of  "  Soul,"  as  given  in  the  extract  from  the 
Phaedrus  and  the  Laws  on  pages  144-5,  the  "Universal 
Soul"  or  the  "Soul  of  the  Universe"  being  of  course 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  185 

only  another  name  for  "  the  Deity."  And  it  is  plain  that 
Aristotle  got  his  conception  of  God  from  the  Platonic 
conception  of  soul,  which  in  both  cases  is  declared  to  be 
in  essence  Motion  which  is  self-moved. 

For  further  light  on  Aristotle's  conception  of  God, 
see  the  last  paragraphs  given  in  the  abstract  of  his 
Ethics.— C.  M.  H. 


ARISTOTLE  ON   THE   THEORY   OF  EVOLUTION. 

Note : — This  extract  is  taken  from  Aristotle's  "His 
tory  of  Animals,"  Cresswell's  Translation,  Bohn  Edition. 
J.  H.  H. 

"Nature  passes  so  gradually  from  inanimate  to  ani 
mate  things,  that  from  their  continuity  their  boundary 
and  the  intermediate  forms  are  indistinct  or  indeter 
minate.  The  race  of  plants  succeeds  immediately  that 
of  inanimate  objects,  and  these  differ  from  each  other  in 
the  proportion  of  life  in  which  they  participate;  for  com 
pared  with  other  objects  appear  to  possess  life,  though 
when  compared  with  animals,  they  appear  inanimate. 

"The  change  from  plants  to  animals,  however,  is 
gradual,  as  I  before  observed.  For  a  person  might  ques 
tion  to  which  of  these  classes  some  marine  objects  be 
long:  for  many  of  them  are  attached  to  the  rocks  and 
perish  as  soon  as  they  are  separated  from  it.  The  pinnae 
(mollusk)  are  attached  to  the  rocks,  the  solens  (shell 
fish)  cannot  live  after  they  are  taken  away  from  their 
localities ;  and,  on  the  whole,  all  the  testacea  resemble 
plants,  if  we  compare  them  with  locomotive  animals. 
Some  of  them  appear  to  have  no  sensation ;  in  others  it 

is  very  dull.     The  body  of  some  of  them  is  naturally 

(186) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  187 

flesh-like,  as  in  those  called  tethides  (gastropod) ;  and 
the  Medusae  and  the  sponges  entirely  resemble  plants. 
The  progress  is  always  gradual  by  which  one  appears 
to  have  more  life  and  motion  than  another." 

Note : — In  that  very  interesting  and  informing  work 
"  From  the  Greeks  to  Darwin,"  by  Prof.  Osborn  of 
Columbia  University,  we  quote  the  following  paragraphs 
which  will  show  the  great  contribution  which  Aristotle 
has  made  to  the  Evolution  Theory  as  one  of  its  early 
pioneers. — C.  M.  H. 

"  With  Aristotle  (384-322  B.  C.)  we  enter  a  new  world. 
He  towered  above  his  predecessors,  and  by  the  force  of 
his  own  genius  created  Natural  History.  In  his  own 
words,  lately  quoted  by  Romanes,  we  learn  that  the  cen 
turies  preceding  him  yielded  him  nothing  but  vague 
speculation  :— 

"I  found  no  basis  prepared;  no  models  to  copy.  .  .  . 
Mine  is  the  first  step,  and  therefore  a  small  one,  though 
worked  out  with  much  thought  and  hard  labor.  It  must 
be  looked  at  as  a  first  step  and  judged  with  indulgence. 
You,  my  readers,  or  hearers  of  my  lectures,  if  you  think 
I  have  done  as  much  as  can  fairly  be  required  for  an 
initiatory  start,  as  compared  with  more  advanced  depart 
ments  of  theory,  will  acknowledge  what  I  have  achieved 
and  pardon  what  I  have  left  for  others  to  accomplish.' 
****** 

"  He  was  attracted  to  natural  history  by  his  boyhood 
life  upon  the  seashore,  and  the  main  parts  of  his  ideas 
upon  Evolution  were  evidently  drawn  from  his  own  ob 
servations  upon  the  gradations  between  marine  plants 
and  the  lower  and  higher  forms  of  marine  animals.  He 
was  the  first  to  conceive  of  a  genetic  series,  and  his  con- 


1 88  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

ception  of  a  single  chain  of  evolution  from  the  polyps 
to  man  was  never  fully  replaced  until  the  beginning  of 
this  century.  It  appeared  over  and  over  again  in  differ 
ent  guises.  In  all  his  philosophy  of  Nature,  Aristotle 
was  guided  partly  by  his  preconceived  opinions  derived 
from  Plato  and  Socrates,  and  parti)7  by  convictions  de 
rived  from  his  own  observations  upon  the  wonderful 
order  and  perfection  of  the  Universe.  His  '  perfecting 
principle '  in  Nature  is  only  one  of  a  score  of  his  legacies 
to  later  speculation  upon  Evolution  causation.  Many 
of  our  later  writers  are  Aristotelians  without  apparently 
being  conscious  of  it. 

****** 
"We  can  pass  leniently  by  errors  which  are  strewn 
among  such  grand  contributions  to  Biology  and  to  the 
very  foundation-stones  of  the  Evolution  idea. 

****** 

"While  Plato  had  relied  upon  intuitions  as  the  main 
ground  of  true  knowledge,  Aristotle  relied  upon  experi 
ment  and  induction.  '  We  must  not/  he  said,  '  accept 
a  general  principle  from  logic  only,  but  must  prove  its 
application  to  each  fact ;  for  it  is  in  facts  that  we  must 
seek  general  principles,  and  these  must  always  accord 
with  facts.  Experience  furnishes  the  particular  facts 
from  which  induction  is  the  pathway  to  general  laws ' 
(History  of  Animals,  1.6.)  He  held  that  errors  do  not 
arise  because  the  senses  are  false  media,  but  because  we 
put  false  interpretations  upon  their  testimony. 

"  Aristotle's  theories  as  to  the  origin  and  succession  of 
life  went  far  beyond  what  he  could  have  reached  by  the 
legitimate  application  of  his  professed  method  of  pro 
cedure.  Having  now  briefly  considered  the  materials  of 
his  knowledge,  let  us  carefully  examine  how  he  put  his 
facts  together  into  an  Evolution  system  which  had  the 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  189 

teachings  of  Plato  and  Socrates  for  its  primary  philo 
sophical  basis. 

"  Aristotle  believed  in  a  complete  gradation  in  Nature, 
a  progressive  development  corresponding  with  the  pro 
gressive  life  of  the  soul.  Nature,  he  says,  proceeds  con 
stantly  by  the  aid  of  gradual  transitions  from  the  most 
imperfect  to  the  most  perfect,  while  the  numerous 
analogies  which  we  find  in  the  various  parts  of  the  ani 
mal  scale,  show  that  all  is  governed  by  the  same  laws,— 
in  other  words,  Nature  is  a  unit  as  to  its  causation.  The 
lowest  stage  is  the  inorganic,  and  this  passes  into  the 
organic  by  direct  metamorphosis,  matter  being  trans 
formed  into  life.  Plants  are  animate  as  compared  with 
minerals,  and  inanimate  as  compared  with  animals  ;  they 
have  powers  of  nourishment  and  reproduction,  but  no 
feeling  or  sensibility.  Then  come  the  plant-animals,  or 
Zoophytes ;  these  are  the  marine  creatures,  such  as 
sponges  and  sea  anemones,  which  leave  the  observer  most 
in  doubt,  for  they  grow  upon  rocks  and  die  if  detached. 
(Polyps,  Aristotle  wrongly  thought  were  plants,  while 
sponges  he  rightly  considered  animals).  The  third  step 
taken  by  Nature  is  the  development  of  animals  with 
sensibility, — hence  desire  for  food  and  other  needs  of  life, 
and  hence  locomotion  to  fulfil  these  desires.  Here  was 
a  more  complex  and  energetic  form  of  the  original  life. 
Man  is  the  highest  point  of  one  long  and  continuous 
ascent;  other  animals  have  the  faculty  of  thought;  man 
alone  generalizes  and  forms  abstractions;  he  is  physically 
superior  in  his  erect  position,  in  his  purest  and  largest 
blood  supply,  largest  brain,  and  highest  temperature. 
*  *  * 

"  Aristotle  perceived  a  most  marvelous  adaptation  in 
the  arrangement  of  the  world,  and  felt  compelled  to  as 
sume  Intelligent  Design  as  the  primary  cause  of  things, 


I  go  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

by  the  perfection  and  regularity  which  he  observed  in 
Nature.  Nothing,  he  held,  which  occurs  regularly,  can 
be  the  result  of  accident.  This  perfection  is  the  outcome 
of  an  all-pervading  movement,  which  we  should,  in  nine 
teenth-century  language,  speak  of  as  an  '  internal  per 
fecting  tendency.'  In  Aristotle's  conception  of  '  move 
ment,'  as  outlined  in  his  Physics,  we  find  something  very 
analogous  to  our  modern  biological  conception  of  trans 
formation  in  development,  for  he  analyzes  'movement* 
as  every  change,  as  every  realization  of  what  is  possible, 
consisting  in:  (a)  Substantial  movement,  origin  and 
decay,  as  we  should  now  sa)%  development  and  degenera 
tion  ;  (b)  Quantitative  movement,  addition  and  subtrac 
tion,  or,  in  modern  terms,  the  gain  and  loss  of  parts;  (c) 
Qualitative  movement,  or  the  transition  of  one  material 
into  another,  in  metamorphosis  and  change  of  function  ; 
(d)  Local  movement,  or  change  of  place,  in  the  trans 
position  of  parts. 

"  Thus  Aristotle  thought  out  the  four  essential  features 
of  Evolution  as  a  process ;  but  we  have  found  no  evi 
dence  that  he  actually  applied  this  conception  to  the 
development  of  organisms  or  of  organs,  as  we  do  now 
in  the  light  of  our  modern  knowledge  of  the  actual  stages 
of  Evolution.  This  enables  us  to  understand  Aristotle's 
view  of  Nature  as  the  principle  of  motion  and  rest  com. 
prised  in  his  four  Causes.  Here  again  he  is  more  or 
less  metaphysical.  The  first  is  the  '  physical  Material 
cause,'  or  matter  itself ;  the  second  is  the  '  physical 
Formal  cause,'  or  the  forces  of  the '  perfecting  principle ; ' 
the  third  is  the  'abstract  Final  cause,'  the  fitness,  adapta 
tion,  or  purpose,  the  good  of  each  and  all  ;  the  fourth, 
presiding  over  all,  is  the  '  Efficient  cause,'  the  Prime 

Mover,  or  God. 

*  *  *  .  *  *  *  * 


EMPEDOCLES, 


B.C.  450. 
One  of  the  Pioneers  of  Evolution.     (See  P.  1W.) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  191 

"Whether  or  not  Aristotle  viewed  the  Prime  Mover 
as  sustaining  his  laws  or  as  having  preordained  them, 
he  certainly  does  not  believe  in  Special  Creation,  either 
of  adaptations  or  of  organisms,  nor  in  the  interference  of 
the  Prime  Mover  in  Nature ;  the  struggle  towards  per 
fection  is  a  natural  process,  as  where  he  says :  '  It  is  due 
to  the  resistance  of  matter  to  form  that  Nature  can 
only  rise  by  degrees  from  lower  to  higher  types.'  There 
is,  therefore,  no  doubt  that  he  was  not  a  teleologist  in 
the  ordinary  sense  ;  at  the  very  heart  of  his  theory  of 
Evolution  was  this  '  internal  perfecting  tendency,'  driv 
ing  organisms  progressively  forward  into  more  perfect 
types.  He  viewed  man  as  the  flower  of  Nature,  towards 
which  all  had  been  tending,  the  crowning  end,  purpose, 
or  final  cause.  His  theory  was  then  anthropocentric  : 
1  plants  are  evidently  for  the  sake  of  animals,  and  animals 
for  the  sake  of  man  ;  thus  Nature,  which  does  nothing 
in  vain,  has  done  all  things  for  the  sake  of  man.' 

"  Aristotle's  view  is  brought  out  clearly  and  emphatic 
ally  in  the  most  striking  passage  of  all  his  writings 
where  he  undertakes  to  refute  Empedocles.  This  is  of 
the  greatest  interest  to-day,  because  Aristotle  clearly 
states  and  rejects  a  theory  of  the  origin  or  adaptive 
structures  in  animals  altogether  similar  to  that  of 
Darwin. 

****** 

"These  passages  seem  to  contain  absolute  evidence 
that  Aristotle  had  substantially  the  modern  conception 
of  the  Evolution  of  life,  from  a  primordial,  soft  mass  of 
living  matter  to  the  most  perfect  forms,  and  that  even 
in  these  he  believed  Evolution  was  incomplete,  for  they 
were  progressing  to  higher  forms.  His  argument  of  the 
analogy  between  the  operation  of  natural  law,  rather 
than  of  chance,  in  the  lifeless  and  in  the  living  world,  is 


1 92  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

a  perfectly  logical  one,  and  his  consequent  rejection  of 
the  hypothesis  of  the  Survival  of  the  Fittest,  a  sound 
induction  from  his  own  limited  knowledge  of  Nature. 
It  seems  perfectly  clear  that  he  placed  all  under  second 
ary  natural  laws.  If  he  had  accepted  Etnpedocles' 
hypothesis,  he  would  have  been  the  literal  prophet  of 
Darwinism." 


ABSTRACT  OF  ARISTOTLE'S  ETHICS. 

Note: — After  indicating  that  the  ground  of  what  is 
right  is  the  end,  as  distinguished  from  the  theories  of 
earlier  writers,  Aristotle  defines  this  end  as  follows: — 
J.  H.  H. 

"The  best  of  all  things  must  be  something  final.  If 
then  there  be  only  one  final  end,  this  will  be  what  we 
are  seeking,  or  if  there  be  more  than  one,  then  the  most 
final  of  them. 

"Now  that  which  is  pursued  as  an  end  in  itself  is  more 
final  than  that  which  is  pursued  as  means  to  something 
else,  and  that  is  strictly  final  which  is  always  chosen  as 
an  end  in  itself  and  never  as  a  means. 

"Happiness  or  welfare  seems  more  than  anything  else 
to  answer  to  this  description;  for  wre  always  choose  it  for 
itself,  and  never  for  the  sake  of  something  else. 

"  But  a  still  more  precise  definition  is  needed.  This 
will  be  gained  by  asking,  what  is  the  function  of  man? 
For  as  the  good  or  excellence  of  a  piper  or  a  sculptor, 
or  the  practiser  of  any  art,  and  generally  of  those  who 
have  any  function  or  business  to  do,  lies  in  that  function, 
so  man's  good  would  seem  to  lie  in  his  function,  if  he 
has  one.  What  then  is  it  ? 

(i93) 


194  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"The  function  of  man  is  exercise  of  his  vital  faculties 
on  one  side  in  obedience  to  reason,  and  on  the  other  with 
reason.  Man's  function  then  being,  as  we  say,  a  kind 
of  life  or  exercise  of  his  faculties,  the  good  man's  function 
is  to  do  this  well  and  nobly. 

"  Nothing  human  is  so  constant  as  the  exercise  of  our 
faculties.  The  highest  of  these  exercises  are  the  most 
abiding,  because  the  happy  are  occupied  with  them  most 
of  all  and  most  continuously.  The  happy  man,  then,  as 
we  define  him,  will  have  this  required  property  of  con 
stancy,  and  all  through  life  will  preserve  his  character; 
for  he  will  be  occupied  continually,  or  with  the  least 
possible  interruption,  in  excellent  deeds  and  excellent 
speculations :  and  whatever  his  fortune  be  he  will  take 
it  in  the  noblest  fashion,  and  bear  himself  always  and 
in  all  things  suitably,  since  he  is  truly  good  and  '  four 
square  without  a  flaw.' 

"  But  the  dispensations  of  fortune  are  many,  some 
great,  some  small.  The  small  ones,  whether  good  or 
evil,  plainly  are  of  no  weight  in  the  scale.  But  the  great 
ones,  when  numerous,  will  make  life  happier  if  they  be 
good;  for  they  help  to  give  a  grace  to  life  themselves, 
and  their  use  is  noble  and  good.  But  if  they  be  evil, 
they  will  enfeeble  and  spoil  happiness,  for  they  bring 
pain,  and  often  impede  the  exercise  of  our  faculties. 

"  But  nevertheless  true  worth  shines  out  even  here,  in 
the  calm  endurance  of  many  great  misfortunes,  not 
through  insensibility,  but  through  nobility  and  greatness 
of  soul.  And  if  it  is  what  man  does  that  determines  the 
character  of  his  life,  then  no  happy  man  will  become 
afflicted  ;  for  he  will  never  do  what  is  hateful  and  base. 
For  we  hold  that  the  man  who  is  truly  good  and  wise 
will  bear  with  dignity  whatever  fortune  sends,  and  will 
always  make  the  best  of  his  circumstances,  as  a  good 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  195 

general  will  turn  the  forces  at  his  command  to  the  best 
account."  Nic.  Eth.  Book  I. 

"  Excellence  being  of  these  two  kinds,  intellectual  and 
moral,  intellectual  excellence  owes  its  birth  and  growth 
mainly  to  instruction,  and  so  requires  time  and  experi 
ence,  while  moral  excellence  is  the  result  of  habit  or 
custom.  From  this  it  is  plain  that  none  of  the  moral 
excellences  or  virtues  is  implanted  in  us  by  nature:  for 
that  which  is  by  nature  cannot  be  altered  by  training. 
For  instance,  a  stone  naturally  tends  to  fall  downwards, 
and  you  could  not  train  it  to  rise  upwards,  though  you 
tried  to  do  so  by  throwing  it  up  ten  thousand  times,  nor 
could  you  train  fire  to  move  downwards,  nor  accustom 
anything  which  naturally  behaves  in  one  way  to  behave 
in  another  way.  The  virtues  then  come  neither  by 
nature  nor  against  nature,  but  nature  gives  the  capacity 
for  acquiring  them,  and  this  is  developed  by  training. 

"  Both  virtues  and  vices  result  from  and  are  formed 
by  the  same  acts  in  which  they  manifest  themselves,  as 
is  the  case  with  the  arts  also.  It  is  by  harping  that  good 
harpers  and  bad  harpers  alike  are  produced ;  and  so  with 
builders  and  the  rest.  Indeed,  if  it  were  not  so,  they 
would  not  want  anybody  to  teach  them,  but  would  all  be 
born  either  good  or  bad  at  their  trades.  And  it  is  just 
the  same  with  the  virtues  also.  It  is  by  our  conduct  in 
our  intercourse  with  other  men  that  we  become  just  or 
unjust,  and  by  acting  in  circumstances  of  danger,  and 
training  ourselves  to  feel  fear  and  confidence,  that  we 
become  courageous  or  cowardly.  In  a  word,  the  several 
habits  or  characters  are  formed  by  the  same  kind  of  acts 
as  those  which  they  produce. 

"  The  pleasure  or  pain  that  accompanies  the  acts  must 
be  taken  as  a  test  of  the  formed  habit  or  character.  He 
who  abstains  from  the  pleasures  of  the  body  and  rejoices 


196  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

in  abstinence,  is  temperate,  while  he  who  is  vexed  at 
having  to  abstain,  is  profligate.  It  is  pleasure  that  moves 
us  to  do  what  is  base,  and  pain  moves  us  to  refrain  from 
what  is  noble.  And  therefore,  as  Plato  says,  man  needs 
to  be  so  trained  from  his  youth  up  as  to  find  pleasure 
and  pain  in  the  right  objects.  This  is  what  a  sound 
education  means. 

"  Virtue,  then,  has  to  do  with  feelings  or  passions  and 
with  outward  acts  in  which  excess  is  wrong  and  de 
ficiency  is  also  blamed,  but  the  mean  is  praised  and  is 
right  —  both  of  which  are  characteristics  of  virtue. 
Virtue,  then,  is  a  kind  of  moderation  in  as  much  as  it 
aims  at  the  mean  or  moderate  amount.  And  it  is  a 
moderation  in  as  much  as  it  comes  in  the  middle  or  mean 
between  two  vices,  one  on  the  side  of  excess,  the  other 
on  the  side  of  defect,  and  in  as  much  as,  while  these  vices 
fall  short  of  or  exceed  the  due  measure  in  feeling  and  in 
action,  it  finds  and  chooses  the  mean."  Nic.  Eth. 
Book  II. 

"  Virtue,  as  we  have  seen,  has  to  do  with  feelings  and 
actions.  Now  praise  or  blame  is  given  only  to  what  is 
voluntary:  that  which  is  involuntary  receives  pardon, 
and  sometimes  pity. 

"  It  seems,  therefore,  that  a  clear  distinction  between 
the  voluntary  and  the  involuntary  is  necessary  for  those 
who  are  investigating  the  nature  of  virtue,  and  will  also 
help  legislators  in  assigning  rewards  and  punishments. 
That  is  generally  held  to  be  involuntary  which  is  done 
under  compulsion  or  through  ignorance.  (That  is 
voluntary  which  is  intentional  and  done  with  knowl 
edge.) 

"  Now  that  we  have  distinguished  voluntary  from  in 
voluntary  acts,  our  next  task  is  to  discuss  choice  or  pur 
pose.  For  it  seems  to  be  most  intimately  connected  with 


THE  TRUE   LIFE    OF    REASON    AND 
RIGHTEOUSNESS. 

"  This  exercise  of  faculty  must  be  the  highest  pos 
sible ;  for  reason  is  the  highest  of  our  faculties,  and  of 
all  knowable  things  those  that  reason  deals  with  are 
the  highest. 

"  The  exercise  of  reason  seems  to  be  superior  in 
seriousness,  and  to  aim  at  no  end  beside  itself,  and  to 
have  its  proper  pleasure.  Its  exercise  seems  further 
to  be  self-sufficient  and  inexhaustible,  and  to  have  all 
the  other  characteristics  ascribed  to  happiness.  A  life 
that  realised  this  idea  would  be  something  more  than 
human  ;  for  it  would  not  be  the  expression  of  mart  s 
nature,  but  of  some  divine  element  in  that  nature — the 
exercise  of  which  is  as  far  superior  to  the  exercise  of 
the  other  kind  of  virtue  as  this  divine  element  is  su 
perior  to  our  compound  nature.  If  then  reason  be  di 
vine  as  compared  with  man,  the  life  which  consists  in 
the  exercise  of  reason  zvill  also  be  divine  in  comparison 
with  human  life.  Nevertheless,  instead  of  listening 
to  those  who  advise  us  as  men  and  mortals  not  to  lift 
our  thoughts  above  what  is  human  and  mortal,  we 
ought  rather,  as  far  as  possible,  to  put  off  our  mor 
tality  and  make  every  effort  to  live  in  the  exercise  of 
the  highest  of  our  facilities ;  for  though  it  be  but  a 
small  part  of  us,  yet  in  power  and  value  it  far  sur 
passes  all  the  rest.  And  indeed  this  part  would  seem 
to  constitute  our  true  self,  since  it  is  the  sovereign  and 
the  better  part.  It  would  be  strange,  then,  if  a  man 
were  to  prefer  the  life  of  something  else  to  the  life  of 
his  true  self. ' ' 

From  Aristotle**  s  Ethics. 

B.  C.35o. 


1 


ARISTOTLE 

THE    "PERIPATETIC"    PHILOSOPHER-WALKING  AS    HE  TAUGHT. 
(From  Stanley's  History.) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  197 

virtue,  and  to  be  a  surer  test  of  character  than  virtue 
itself. 

"  It  seems  that  choosing  is  willing,  but  that  the  two 
terms  are  not  identical,  willing  being  the  wider.  For 
children  and  animals  have  will,  but  not  choice  or  pur 
pose:  and  acts  done  upon  the  spur  of  the  moment  are 
said  to  be  voluntary,  but  not  to  be  done  with  deliberate 
purpose. 

"  We  have  seen  that,  while  we  wish  for  the  end,  we  de 
liberate  upon  and  choose  the  means  thereto.  Actions 
that  are  concerned  with  means  will  be  guided  by  choice, 
and  so  will  be  voluntary.  But  the  acts  in  which  the 
virtues  are  manifested  are  concerned  with  means. 

"  Therefore,  virtue  depends  upon  ourselves :  and  vice 
likewise.  For  where  it  lies  with  us  to  do,  it  lies  with  us 
not  to  do.  Where  we  can  say  no,  we  can  say  yes.  If 
then  the  doing  of  a  deed,  which  is  noble,  lies  with  us, 
the  not  doing  it,  which  is  disgraceful,  also  lies  with  us. 

"  If  these  statements  commend  themselves  to  us,  and  if 
we  are  unable  to  trace  our  acts  to  any  other  sources  than 
those  that  depend  upon  ourselves,  then  that  whose  source 
is  within  us  must  depend  upon  us  and  be  voluntary. 
This  seems  to  be  attested  by  each  one  of  us  in  private 
life,  and  also  by  the  legislators ;  for  they  correct  and 
punish  those  that  do  evil,  except  when  it  is  done  under 
compulsion,  or  through  ignorance  for  which  the  agent  is 
not  responsible,  and  honor  those  that  do  noble  deeds. 

"  I  say  *  ignorance  for  which  the  agent  is  not  re 
sponsible,'  for  the  ignorance  itself  is  punished  by  the 
law,  if  the  agent  appears  to  be  responsible  for  his  defect 
ive  knowledge.  Ignorance  of  any  of  the  ordinances  of 
the  law,  which  a  man  ought  to  know,  and  easily  can 
know,  does  not  avert  punishment.  And  so  in  other 
cases,  where  ignorance  seems  to  be  the  result  of  negli- 


198  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

gence,  the  offender  is  punished,  since  it  lay  with  him  to 
remove  this  ignorance,  for  he  might  have  taken  the  req 
uisite  trouble. 

"  It  might  be  objected  that  it  was  the  man's  character 
not  to  take  the  trouble. 

"We  reply  that  men  are  themselves  responsible  for  ac 
quiring  such  a  character  by  a  dissolute  life,  and  for  being 
unjust  or  profligate  in  consequence  of  repeated  acts  of 
wrong,  or  of  spending  their  time  in  drinking,  and  so  on. 
For  it  is  repeated  acts  of  a  particular  kind  that  give  a 
man  a  particular  character. 

"  We  see,  then,  that  of  the  vices  of  the  body  it  is  those 
that  depend  on  ourselves  that  are  censured,  while  those 
that  do  not  depend  upon  ourselves  are  not  censured. 
And  if  this  be  so,  then  in  other  fields  also  those  vices 
that  are  blamed  must  depend  upon  ourselves. 

"  Some  people  may  perhaps  object  to  this.  'All  men/ 
they  may  say,  '  desire  that  which  appears  good  to  them, 
but  cannot  control  this  appearance ;  a  man's  character, 
whatever  it  be,  decides  what  shall  appear  to  him  to  be 
the  end.' 

"  If,  I  answer,  each  man  be  in  some  way  responsible  for 
his  habits  of  character,  then  in  some  way  he  must  be 
responsible  for  this  appearance  also.  But  if  this  be  not 
the  case,  then  a  man  is  not  responsible  for,  or  is  not  the 
cause  of,  his  own  evil  doing,  but  it  is  through  ignorance 
of  the  end  that  he  does  evil. 

"  Now  supposing  this  to  be  true,  how  will  virtue  be  any 
more  voluntary  than  vice?  For  whether  it  be  nature  or 
anything  else  that  determines  what  shall  appear  to  be  the 
end,  it  is  determined  in  the  same  way  for  both  alike,  for 
the  good  man  as  well  as  the  bad,  and  both  alike  refer  all 
their  acts  of  whatever  kind,  to  it. 

"And  so  whether  we  hold  that  it  is  not  merely  nature 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  199 

that  decides  what  appears  to  each  to  be  the  end,  but  that 
the  man  himself  contributes  something;  or  whether  we 
hold  that  the  end  is  fixed  by  nature,  but  that  virtue  is 
voluntary,  in  as  much  as  the  good  man  voluntarily  takes 
the  steps  to  that  end — in  either  case  vice  will  be  just  as 
voluntary  as  virtue,  for  self  is  active  in  the  bad  man  just 
as  much  as  in  the  good  man,  in  choosing  the  particular 
acts  at  least,  if  not  in  determining  the  end. 

"  We  have  thus  described  in  outline  the  nature  of  the 
virtues  in  general,  viz.,  that  they  are  forms  of  modera 
tion  or  modes  of  observing  the  mean,  and  that  they  are 
habits  or  trained  faculties ;  and  we  have  shown  what 
produces  them,  and  how  they  themselves  issue  in  the 
performance  of  the  same  acts  which  produce  them,  and 
that  they  depend  on  ourselves  and  are  voluntary,  and 
that  they  follow  the  guidance  of  right  reason. 

"  But  our  particular  acts  are  not  voluntary  in  the  same 
sense  as  our  habits.  We  are  masters  of  our  acts  from 
beginning  to  end,  when  we  know  the  particular  circum 
stances;  but  we  are  masters  of  the  beginnings  only  of 
our  habits  or  characters,  while  their,  growth  by  gradual 
steps  is  imperceptible,  like  the  growth  of  disease.  In  as 
much,  however,  as  it  lay  with  us  to  employ  our  faculties 
in  this  way,  the  resulting  characters  are  on  that  account 
voluntary."  Nic.  Eth.  Book  III. 

"  We  have  now  to  inquire  about  justice  and  injustice, 
and  to  ask  what  sort  of  acts  they  are  concerned  with, 
and  in  what  sense  justice  observes  the  mean,  and  what 
are  the  extremes  whose  mean  is  that  which  is  just. 

"We  see  that  all  men  intend  by  justice  to  signify  the 
sort  of  habit  or  character  that  makes  men  apt  to  do  what 
is  lawful,  and  which  further  makes  them  act  lawfully 
and  wish  what  is  lawful  or  just.  By  injustice  they  in 
tend  in  like  manner  to  signify  the  sort  of  character  that 


2OO  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

makes  men  act  unlawfully  and  wish  what  is  unlawful 
or  unjust. 

"  Plainly,  then,  a  just  man  will  be  ( i )  a  law-abiding  and 
(2)  a  fair  man.  A  just  thing,  then,  will  be  (i)  that 
which  is  in  accordance  with  law,  (2)  that  which  is  fair; 
and  the  unjust  thing  will  be  (i)  that  which  is  contrary 
to  law,  and  (2)  that  which  is  unfair. 

"Now  the  laws  prescribe  about  all  manner  of  things, 
aiming  at  the  common  interest  of  all,  or  of  the  best  men, 
or  of  those  who  are  supreme  in  the  state  ;  and  so  in  one 
sense  we  apply  the  term  'just'  to  whatever  tends  to  pro 
duce  and  preserve  the  happiness  of  the  community,  and 
the  several  elements  of  that  happiness.  The  law  bids 
us  to  display  courage  (as  not  to  leave  our  ranks,  or  to 
run,  or  throw  away  our  arms),  and  temperance,  (as  not 
to  commit  adultery  or  outrage),  and  gentleness,  (as  not 
to  strike  or  revile  our  neighbors),  and  so  on  with  all  the 
other  virtues  and  vices. 

"Justice,  then,  in  this  sense  of  the  word,  is  complete 
virtue,  with  the  addition  that  it  is  displayed  toward 
others.  On  this  account  it  is  often  spoken  of  as  the  chief 
of  the  virtues,  and  such  that  '  neither  evening  nor  morn 
ing  star  is  so  lovely ; '  and  the  saying  has  become 
proverbial,  'Justice  sums  up  all  virtues  in  itself.' 

"It  is  complete  virtue  because  it  is  the  exhibition  of 
complete  excellence :  it  is  also  complete  because  he  that 
has  it  is  able  to  exhibit  virtue  in  dealing  with  his  neigh 
bors,  and  not  merely  in  his  private  affairs ;  for  there  are 
many  who  can  be  virtuous  at  home,  but  fail  in  dealing 
with  their  neighbors.  This  is  the  reason  why  people 
commend  the  saying  of  Bias :  '  Office  will  show  the  man ; ' 
for  he  that  is  in  office  ipso  facto  stands  in  relation  to 
others  and  has  dealings  with  them. 

"This  too  is  the  reason  why  justice  alone  of  all  the 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  201 

virtues  is  thought  to  be  another's  good,  as  implying  this 
relation  to  others:  for  it  is  another's  interest  that  justice 
aims  at — the  interest,  namely,  of  the  ruler  or  of  our 
fellow-citizens. 

"  We  have  next  to  speak  of  equity  and  of  that  which 
is  equitable,  and  to  inquire  how  equity  is  related  to  jus 
tice,  and  how  that  which  is  equitable  to  that  which  is  just. 
For,  on  consideration,  they  do  not  seem  to  be  absolutely 
identical,  nor  yet  generically  different.  At  one  time  we 
praise  that  which  is  equitable  and  the  equitable  man, 
and  even  use  the  word  metaphorically  as  a  term  of  praise 
synonymous  with  good,  showing  that  we  consider  that 
the  more  equitable  a  thing  is  the  better  it  is.  At  another 
time  we  reflect  and  find  it  strange  that  what  is  equitable 
should  be  praiseworthy,  if  it  be  different  from  what  is 
just;  for,  we  argue,  if  it  be  something  else,  either  what 
is  just  is  not  good,  or  what  is  equitable  is  not  good;  if 
both  be  good,  they  are  the  same. 

"  But  what  obscures  the  matter  is  that,  though  what 
is  equitable  is  just,  it  is  not  identical  with,  but  a  correc 
tion  of,  that  which  is  just  according  to  law.  The  reason 
for  this  is  that  every  law  is  laid  down  in  general  terms, 
while  there  are  matters  about  which  it  is  impossible  to 
speak  correctly  in  general  terms.  Where,  then,  it  is  nec 
essary  to  speak  in  general  terms,  but  impossible  to  do  so 
correctly,  the  legislator  lays  down  that  which  holds  good 
for  the  majority  of  cases,  being  quite  aware  that  it  does 
not  hold  good  for  all.  What  is  equitable,  then,  is  just, 
and  better  than  what  is  just  in  one  sense  of  the  word- 
not  better  than  what  is  absolutely  just,  but  better  than 
that  which  fails  through  its  lack  of  qualification.  And 
the  essence  of  what  is  equitable  is  that  it  is  an  amend 
ment  of  the  law,  in  those  points  where  it  fails  through 
the  generality  of  its  language."  Nic.  Eth.  Book  V. 


2O2  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"  Now  that  we  have  discussed  the  several  kinds  of 
virtue,  it  remains  to  give  a  summary  account  of  happi 
ness,  since  we  are  to  assume  that  it  is  the  end  of  all  that 
man  does. 

"As  we  have  often  said,  that  is  truly  valuable  and 
pleasant  which  is  so  to  the  perfect  man.  Now,  the  ex 
ercise  of  those  trained  faculties  which  are  proper  to  him 
is  what  each  man  finds  most  desirable ;  what  the  perfect 
man  finds  most  desirable,  therefore,  is  the  exercise  of 
virtue.  Happiness,  consequently,  does  not  consist  in 
amusement,  and,  indeed,  it  is  absurd  to  suppose  that  the 
end  is  amusement,  and  that  we  toil  and  moil  all  our  life 
long  for  the  sake  of  amusing  ourselves.  The  happy  life 
is  thought  to  be  that  which  exhibits  virtue ;  and  such  a 
life  must  be  serious  and  cannot  consist  in  amusement. 

"  But  if  happiness  be  the  exercise  of  virtue,  it  is  rea 
sonable  to  suppose  that  it  will  be  the  exercise  of  the 
highest  virtue,  and  that  it  will  be  the  virtue  or  excellence 
of  the  best  part  of  us.  Now  that  part  or  faculty — call  it 
reason  or  what  you  will — which  seems  naturally  to  rule 
and  take  the  lead,  and  to  apprehend  things  noble  and 
divine — whether  it  be  itself  divine,  or  only  the  divinest 
part  of  us — is  the  faculty,  the  exercise  of  which,  in  its 
proper  excellence,  will  be  perfect  happiness. 

"  That  this  consists  in  the  contemplative  life  we  have 
already  said.  This  exercise  of  faculty  must  be  the  high 
est  possible ;  for  reason  is  the  highest  of  our  faculties, 
and  of  all  knowable  things  those  that  reason  deals  with 
are  the  highest.  We  think  too,  that  pleasure  ought  to 
be  one  of  the  ingredients  of  happiness ;  but  of  all  virtu 
ous  exercises  it  is  allowed  that  the  pleasantest  is  the 
exercise  of  wisdom.  At  least  philosophy  is  thought  to 
have  pleasures  that  are  admirable  in  purity  and  stead 
fastness.  What  is  called  self-sufficiency  will  be  most  of 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  203 

all  found  in  the  reflective  life.  The  necessaries  of  life, 
indeed,  are  needed  by  the  wise  man  as  well  as  by  the  just 
man  and  others ;  but,  when  these  have  been  provided  in 
due  quantity,  the  just  man  further  needs  further  persons 
towards  whom,  and  along  with  whom,  he  may  act  justly, 
while  the  wise  man  is  able  to  contemplate  even  by  him 
self,  and  the  wiser  he  is  the  more  he  is  able  to  do  this. 

"  The  exercise  of  reason  seems  to  be  superior  in  seri 
ousness,  and  to  aim  at  no  end  besides  itself,  and  to  have 
its  proper  pleasure.  Its  exercise  seems  further  to  be 
self-sufficient  and  inexhaustible,  and  to  have  all  the  other 
characteristics  ascribed  to  happiness.  A  life  that  realized 
this  idea  would  be  something  more  than  human ;  for  it 
would  not  be  the  expression  of  man's  nature,  but  of  some 
divine  element  in  that  nature — the  exercise  of  which  is 
as  far  superior  to  the  exercise  of  the  other  kind  of  virtue, 
as  this  divine  element  is  superior  to  our  compound 
nature.  If  then  reason  be  divine  as  compared  with  man, 
the  life  which  consists  in  the  exercise  of  reason  will  also 
be  divine  in  comparison  with  human  life.  Nevertheless, 
instead  of  listening  to  those  who  advise  us  as  men  and 
mortals,  not  to  lift  our  thoughts  above  what  is  human 
and  mortal,  we  ought  rather,  as  far  as  possible,  to  put 
off  our  mortality  and  make  every  effort  to  live  in  the 
exercise  of  the  highest  of  our  faculties ;  for  though  it  be 
but  a  small  part  of  us,  yet  in  power  and  value  it  far  sur 
passes  all  the  rest.  And  indeed,  this  part  would  seem  to 
constitute  our  true  self,  since  it  is  the  sovereign  and  the 
better  part.  It  would  be  strange,  then,  if  a  man  were 
to  prefer  the  life  of  something  else  to  the  life  of  his  true 
self. 

"The  life  that  consists  in  the  exercise  of  the  other 
kind  of  virtue  is  happy  in  a  secondary  sense;  for  the 
manifestation  of  moral  virtue  is  emphatically  human. 


204  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

Justice,  I  mean,  and  courage  and  the  other  moral  virtues 
(contrasted  with  the  intellectual)  are  displayed  in  our 
relations  towards  one  another  by  the  observance,  in  every 
case,  of  what  is  due  in  contracts  and  services,  and  all 
sorts  of  outward  acts  as  well  as  in  our  inward  feelings. 
All  these  seem  to  be  emphatically  human  affairs.  But 
the  happiness  which  consists  in  the  exercise  of  the 
reason,  is  separate  from  our  lower  nature. 

"That  perfect  happiness  is  some  kind  of  speculative 
or  reflective  activity  may  also  be  shown  in  the  following 
way : 

"  It  is  always  supposed  that  the  gods  are,  of  all  beings, 
the  most  blessed  and  happy;  but  what  kind  of  actions 
shall  we  ascribe  to  them ?  Acts  of  justice?  Surely  it  is 
ridiculous  to  conceive  the  gods  engaged  in  trade  and  re 
storing  deposits,  and  so  on.  Or  acts  of  courage?  Can 
we  conceive  them  enduring  fearful  risks  and  facing 
danger  because  it  is  noble  to  do  so  ?  Or  acts  of  liberality  ? 
But  to  whom  are  they  to  give?  Is  it  not  absurd  to  sup 
pose  that  they  have  any  money  or  anything  of  the  kind? 
And  what  could  acts  of  temperance  mean  with  them  ? 
Surely  it  would  be  an  insult  to  praise  them  for  having 
no  evil  desires.  In  short,  if  we  were  to  go  through  the 
whole  list,  we  should  find  that  all  action  is  petty  and 
unworthy  of  the  gods. 

"  And  yet  it  is  universally  supposed  that  they  live, 
and  therefore  that  they  exert  their  powers ;  for  we  can 
not  suppose  that  they  are  sleeping  like  Endymion. 
Now  if  a  being  lives,  and  action  cannot  be  ascribed  to 
him,  still  less  production,  what  remains  but  contempla 
tion?  It  follows,  then,  that  the  divine  life,  which  sur 
passes  all  others  in  blessedness,  consists  in  contempla 
tion."  Nic.  Eth.  Book  X. 


FROM  ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS. 

BOOKS  i  and  2. 

TliE  FUNDAMENTAL  NATURE  OF  A  POLITICAL 
STATE  OR  GOVERNMENT. 

STATUS    OF    PROPERTY  —  SOCIALISTIC    AND 
INDIVIDUALISTIC  CONSIDERED. 

"Every  state  is  a  community  of  some  kind,  and  every 
community  is  established  with  a  view  to  some  good ;  for 
mankind  always  act  in  order  to  obtain  that  which  they 
think  good.  But,  if  all  communities  aim  at  some  good, 
the  state  or  political  community,  which  is  the  highest  of 
all,  and  which  embraces  all  the  rest,  aims,  and  in  a 
greater  degree  than  any  other,  at  the  highest  good. 

"The  family  is  the  association  established  by  nature 
for  the  supply  of  men's  every  day  wants,  and  the  mem 
bers  of  it  are  called  by  Charondas  '  companions  of  the 
cupboard,'  and  by  Epimenides  the  Cretan,  'companions 
of  the  manger.'  But  when  several  families  are  united, 
and  the  association  aims  at  something  more  than  the 
supply  of  daily  needs,  then  comes  into  existence  the 
village. 

"  When  several  villages  are  united  in  a  single  com 
munity,  perfect  and  large  enough  to  be  nearly  or  quite 
self-sufficing,  the  state  comes  into  existence,  originating 
in  the  bare  needs  of  life,  and  continuing  in  existence  for 
the  sake  of  a  good  life.  And  therefore,  if  the  earlier 

(205) 


206  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

forms  of  society  are  natural,  so  is  the  state,  for  it  is  the 
end  of  them,  and  the  (completed)  nature  is  the  end. 
For  what  each  thing  is  when  fully  developed,  we  call 
its  nature,  whether  we  are  speaking  of  a  man,  a  horse, 
or  a  family.  Besides,  the  final  cause  and  end  of  a  thing 
is  the  best,  and  to  be  self-sufficing  is  the  end  and  the 
best. 

"  Hence  it  is  evident  that  the  state  is  a  creation  of  na 
ture,  and  that  man  is  by  nature  a  political  animal.  And 
he  who  by  nature  and  not  by  mere  accident  is  without 
a  state,  is  either  above  humanity,  or  below  it ;  he  is  the 

4  Tribeless,  lawless,  hearthless  one,' 

whom  Homer  denounces — the  outcast  who  is  a  lover  of 
war;  he  may  be  compared  to  a  bird  which  flies  alone. 

"  Now  the  reason  why  man  is  more  of  a  political  ani 
mal  than  bees  or  any  other  gregarious  animals  is  evi 
dent.  Nature,  as  we  often  say,  makes  nothing  in  vain, 
and  man  is  the  only  animal  whom  she  has  endowed  with 
the  gift  of  speech. 

"And  it  is  a  characteristic  of  man  that  he  alone  has 
any  sense  of  good  and  evil,  of  just  and  unjust,  and  the 
association  of  living  beings  who  have  this  sense  makes 
a  family  and  a  state. 

"  The  proof  that  the  state  is  a  creation  of  nature  and 
prior  to  the  individual  is  that  the  individual,  when 
isolated,  is  not  self-sufficing ;  and  therefore  he  is  like  a 
part  in  relation  to  the  whole.  But  he  who  is  unable  to 
live  in  society,  or  who  has  no  need  because  he  is  suffi 
cient  for  himself,  must  be  either  a  beast  or  a  god :  he  is 
no  part  of  a  state.  A  social  instinct  is  implanted  in  all 
men  by  nature,  and  yet  he  who  first  founded  the  state 
was  the  greatest  of  benefactors.  For  man,  when  per 
fected,  is  the  best  of  animals,  but,  when  separated  from 
law  and  justice,  he  is  the  worst  of  all  ;  since  armed  in- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  207 

justice  is  the  more  dangerous,  and  he  is  equipped  at  birth 
with  the  arms  of  intelligence  and  with  moral  qualities 
which  he  may  use  for  the  worst  ends.  Wherefore,  if  he 
have  not  virtue,  he  is  the  most  unholy  and  the  most 
savage  of  animals,  and  the  most  full  of  lust  and  gluttony. 
But  justice  is  the  bond  of  men  in  states,  and  the  ad 
ministration  of  justice,  which  is  the  determination  of 
what  is  just,  is  the  principle  of  order  in  political  society. 

"  The  relations  of  husband  and  wife,  parent  and  child, 
their  several  virtues,  what  in  their  intercourse  with  one 
another  is  good,  and  what  is  evil,  and  how  we  may 
pursue  the  good  and  escape  the  evil,  will  have  to  be  dis 
cussed  when  we  speak  of  the  different  forms  of  govern 
ment.  For,  inasmuch  as  every  family  is  a  part  of  a 
state,  and  these  relationships  are  the  parts  of  a  family, 
the  virtue  of  the  part  must  have  regard  to  the  virtue  of 
the  whole.  And  therefore  women  and  children  must  be  *•/ 
trained  by  education  with  an  eye  to  the  state,  if  the 
virtues  of  either  of  them  are  supposed  to  make  any  dif 
ference  in  the  virtues  of  the  state.  And  they  must  make 
a  difference:  for  the  children  grow  up  to  be  citizens,  and 
half  the  free  persons  in  a  state  are  wonen. 

"Next  let  us  consider  what  should  be  our  arrangements 
about  property :  should  the  citizens  of  the  perfect  state 
have  their  possessions  in  common  or  not? 

"  Property  should  be  in  a  certain  sense  common,  but,  as 
a  general  rule,  private ;  for,  when  everyone  has  a  distinct 
interest,  men  will  not  complain  of  one  another,  and  they 
will  make  more  progress,  because  every  one  will  be  at 
tending  to  his  own  business.  And  yet  among  the  good, 
and  in  respect  of  use,  'Friends,'  as  the  proverb  says, 
'will  have  all  things  common.' 

"  No  one,  when  men  have  all  things  in  common,  w7ill 
any  longer  set  an  example  of  liberality  or  do  any  liberal 


208  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

action ;  for  liberality  consists  in  the  use  which  is  made 
of  property. 

"Such  legislation  may  have  a  specious  appearance  of 
benevolence;  men  readily  listen  to  it,  and  are  easily  in 
duced  to  believe  that  in  some  wonderful  manner  every 
body  will  become  everybody's  friend,  especially  when 
some  one  is  heard  denouncing  the  evils  now  existing  in 
states,  suits  about  contracts,  convictions  for  perjury, 
flatteries  of  rich  men  and  the  like,  which  are  said  to 
arise  out  of  the  possession  of  private  property.  These 
evils,  however,  are  due  to  a  very  different  cause — the 
wickedness  of  human  nature.  Indeed,  we  see  that  there 
is  more  quarreling  among  those  who  have  all  things  in 
common,  though  there  are  not  many  of  them  when  com 
pared  with  the  vast  numbers  who  have  private  property. 

"  Some,  indeed,  say  that  the  best  constitution  is  a  com 
bination  of  all  existing  forms,  and  they  praise  the 
Lacedaemonian  because  it  is  made  up  of  oligarchy, 
monarchy,  and  democracy,  the  king  forming  the  mon 
archy,  and  the  council  of  elders  the  oligarchy,  while  the 
democratic  element  is  represented  by  the  Ephors;  for 
the  Ephors  are  selected  from  the  people.  Others,  how 
ever,  declare  the  Ephoralty  to  be  a  tyranny,  and  find  the 
element  of  democracy  in  the  common  meals  and  in  the 
habits  of  daily  life.  In  the  Laws,*  it  is  maintained  that 
the  best  state  is  made  up  of  democracy  and  tyranny, 
which  are  either  not  constitutions  at  all,  or  are  the  worst 
of  all.  But  they  are  nearer  the  truth  who  combine  many 
forms;  for  the  state  is  better  which  is  made  up  of  more 
numerous  elements.  The  constitution  proposed  in  the 
Laws  has  no  element  of  monarchy  at  all ;  it  is  nothing 
but  oligarchy  and  democracy,  leaning  rather  to  oligarchy. 

"Jn  the  opinion  of  some,  the  regulation  of  property  is 
the  chief  point  of  all,  that  being  the  question  upon  which 

*  Plato1  s  ' '  Laws  "  is  here  referred  to. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  209 

all  revolutions  turn.  This  danger  was  recognized  by 
Phaleas  of  Chalcedon,  who  was  the  first  to  affirm  that 
the  citizens  of  a  state  ought  to  have  equal  possessions. 
He  thought  that  in  a  new  colony  the  equalization  might 
be  accomplished  without  difficulty,  not  so  easily  when 
a  state  was  already  established  ;  and  that  then  the  short 
est  way  of  compassing  the  desired  end  would  be  for  the 
rich  to  give  and  not  to  receive  marriage  portions,  and 
for  the  poor  not  to  give  but  to  receive  them. 

"  Plato  in  the  Laws  was  of  opinion  that,  to  a  certain 
extent,  accumulation  should  be  allowed,  forbidding,  as 
I  have  already  observed,  any  citizen  to  possess  more 
than  five  times  the  minimum  qualification.  But  those 
who  make  such  laws  should  remember  what  they  are 
apt  to  forget, — that  the  legislator  who  fixes  the  amount 
of  property  should  also  fix  the  number  of  children ;  for, 
if  the  children  are  too  many  for  the  property,  the  law 
must  be  broken.  And,  besides  the  violation  of  the  law, 
it  is  a  bad  thing  that  many  from  being  rich  should  be 
come  poor ;  for  men  of  ruined  fortunes  are  sure  to  stir 
up  revolutions.  That  the  equalization  of  property 
exercises  an  influence  on  political  society  was  clearly 
understood  even  by  some  of  the  old  legislators.  Laws 
were  made  by  Solon  and  others  prohibiting  an  individual 
from  possessing  as  much  land  as  he  pleased  ;  and  there 
are  other  laws  in  states  which  forbid  the  sale  of  property  : 
among  the  Locrians,  for  example,  there  is  a  law  that  a 
man  is  not  to  sell  his  property  unless  he  can  prove  un 
mistakably  that  some  misfortune  has  befallen  him. 
Again,  there  have  been  laws  which  enjoin  the  preserva 
tion  of  the  original  lots.  Such  a  law  existed  in  the 
island  of  Leucas,  and  the  abrogation  of  it  made  the  con 
stitution  too  democratic,  for  the  rulers  no  longer  had  the 
prescribed  qualification." 


FROM  ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS, 
BOOK  III. 

CITIZENS  AND  STATES  OF  VARIOUS  KINDS  CONSIDERED. 

THE  BEST  FORMS  OF  GOVERNMENT  AND 

THE  BEST  CITIZEN  DISCUSSED. 

"  He  who  would  inquire  into  the  nature  and  various 
kinds  of  government  must  first  of  all  determine  '  What  is 
a  state? '  At  present  this  is  a  disputed  question.  But  a 
state  is  composite,  and,  like  any  other  whole,  made  up 
of  many  parts  —  these  are  the  citizens,  who  compose  it. 
It  is  evident,  therefore,  that  we  must  begin  by  asking, 
Who  is  the  citizen,  and  what  is  the  meaning  of  the  term  ? 
For  here  again  there  may  be  a  difference  of  opinion. 
He  who  is  a  citizen  in  a  democracy  will  often  not  be  a 
citizen  in  an  oligarchy. 

"But  the  citizen,  whom  we  are  seeking  to  define,  is  a 
citizen  in  the  strictest  sense,  against  whom  no  such  ex 
ception  can  be  taken,  and  his  special  characteristic  is 
that  he  shares  in  the  administration  of  justice,  and  in 
offices. 

"  The  citizen  then  of  necessity  differs  under  each  form 
of  government ;  and  our  definition  is  best  adapted  to  the 
citizens  of  a  democracy;  but  not  necessarily  to  other 
states. 

"  He  who  has  the  power  to  take  part  in  the  deliberative 

or  judicial  administration  of  any  state  is  said  by  us  to 

(210) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  211 

be  a  citizen  of  that  state ;  and  speaking  generally,  a  state 
is  a  body  of  citizens  sufficing  for  the  purposes  of  life. 

"  But  in  practice  a  citizen  is  defined  to  be  one  of  whom 
both  the  parents  are  citizens;  others  insist  on  going 
further  back ;  say  to  two  or  three  or  more  grandparents. 
This  is  a  short  and  practical  definition ;  but  there  are 
some  who  raise  the  further  question  :  How  this  third  or 
fourth  ancestor  came  to  be  a  citizen  ?  Gorgias  of 
Leontina,  partly  because  he  was  in  a  difficulty,  partly 
in  irony,  said — '  Mortars  are  made  by  the  mortar-makers, 
and  the  citizens  of  Larissa  are  also  a  manufactured 
article,  made,  like  the  kettles  which  bear  their  name, 
by  the  magistrates.'  Yet  the  question  is  really  simple, 
for,  if  according  to  the  definition  just  given  they  shared 
in  the  government,  they  were  citizens.  (This  is  a  better 
definition  than  the  other).  For  the  words,  'born  of  a 
father  or  mother,  who  is  a  citizen,'  cannot  possibly 
apply  to  the  first  inhabitants  or  founders  of  a  state. 

"It  has  been  well  said  that  'he  who  has  never  learned 
to  obey  cannot  be  a  good  commander.'  The  two  are 
not  the  same,  but  the  good  citizen  ought  to  be  capable 
of  both  ;  he  should  know  how  to  govern  like  a  freeman, 
and  how  to  obey  like  a  freeman — these  are  the  virtues 
of  a  citizen.  And,  although  the  temperance  and  justice 
of  a  ruler  are  distinct  from  those  of  a  subject,  the  virtue 
of  a  good  man  will  include  both  :  for  the  good  man,  who 
is  free  and  also  a  subject,  will  not  have  one  virtue  only, 
say  justice — but  he  will  have  distinct  kinds  of  virtue, 
the  one  qualifying  him  to  rule,  the  other  to  obey,  and 
differing  as  the  temperance  and  courage  of  men  and 
women  differ. 

"Since  there  are  many  forms  of  government,  there  must 
be  many  varieties  of  citizens,  and  especially  of  citizens 
who  are  subjects;  so  that  under  some  governments  the 


212  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

mechanic  and  the  laborer  will  be  citizens,  but  not  in 
others,  as,  for  example,  in  aristocracy  or  the  so-called 
government  of  the  best  (if  there  be  such  an  one),  in 
which  honors  are  given  according  to  virtue  and  merit; 
for  no  man  can  practice  virtue  who  is  living  the  life  of  a 
mechanic  or  laborer.  In  oligarchies  the  qualification 
for  office  is  high,  and  therefore  no  laborer  can  ever  be 
a  citizen ;  but  a  mechanic  may,  for  many  of  them  are 
rich.  At  Thebes  there  was  a  law  that  no  man  could 
hold  office  who  had  not  retired  from  business  for  ten 
years.  In  many  states  the  law  goes  to  the  length  of 
admitting  aliens ;  for  in  some  democracies  a  man  is  a 
citizen  though  his  mother  only  be  a  citizen  (and  his 
father  an  alien) ;  and  a  similar  principle  is  applied  to 
illegitimate  children ;  the  law  is  relaxed  when  there  is  a 
dearth  of  population.  But  when  the  number  of  citizens 
increases,  first  the  children  of  a  male  or  a  female  slave 
are  excluded ;  then  those  whose  mothers  only  are  citizens ; 
and  at  last  the  right  of  citizenship  is  confined  to  those 
whose  fathers  and  mothers  are  both  citizens. 

"  Hence,  as  is  evident,  there  are  different  kinds  of 
citizens;  and  he  is  a  citizen  in  the  highest  sense  who 
shares  in  the  honors  of  the  state.  In  the  poems  of 
Homer  (Achilles  complains  of  Agamemnon  treating 
him)  'like  some  dishonored  stranger,'  for  he  who  is  ex 
cluded  from  the  honors  of  the  state  is  no  better  than  an 
alien.  But  when  this  exclusion  is  concealed,  then  the 
object  is  to  deceive  the  inhabitants. 

"  Having  determined  these  questions,  we  have  next  to 
consider  whether  there  is  only  one  form  of  government 
or  many,  and  if  many,  what  they  are,  and  how  many, 
and  what  are  the  differences  between  them. 

"A  constitution  is  the  arrangement  of  magistracies  in 
a  state,  especially  of  the  highest  of  all.  The  govern- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  213 

ment  is  everywhere  sovereign  in  the  state,  and  the  con 
stitution  is  in  fact  the  government.  For  example,  in 
democracies  the  people  are  supreme,  but  in  oligarchies, 
the  few;  and,  therefore,  we  say  that  these  two  forms  of 
government  are  different ;  and  so  in  other  cases. 

"  First,  let  us  consider  what  is  the  purpose  of  a  state, 
and  how  many  forms  of  government  there  are  by  which 
human  society  is  regulated.  We  have  already  said,  in 
the  former  part  of  this  treatise,  when  drawing  a  dis 
tinction  between  household  management  and  the  rule 
of  a  master,  that  man  is  by  nature  a  political  animal. 
And  therefore,  men,  even  when  they  do  not  require  one 
another's  help,  desire  to  live  together  all  the  same,  and 
are  in  fact  brought  together  by  their  common  interests 
in  proportion  as  they  severally  attain  to  any  measure  of 
well-being.  This  is  certainly  the  chief  end,  both  of  in 
dividuals  and  of  states.  And  also  for  the  sake  of  mere 
life  (in  which  there  is  possibly  some"  noble  element) 
mankind  meet  together  and  maintain  the  political  com 
munity,  so  long  as  the  evils  of  existence  do  not  greatly 
overbalance  the  good.  And  we  all  see  that  men  cling 
to  life  even  in  the  midst  of  misfortune,  seeming  to  find 
in  it  a  natural  sweetness  and  happiness. 

"There  is  no  difficulty  in  distinguishing  the  various 
kinds  of  authority ;  they  have  been  often  defined  already 
in  popular  works.  The  rule  of  a  master,  although  the 
slave  by  nature  and  the  master  by  nature,  have  in  reality 
the  same  interests,  is  nevertheless  exercised  primarily 
with  a  view  to  the  interest  of  the  master,  but  acciden 
tally  considers  the  slave,  since,  if  the  slave  perish,  the 
rule  of  the  master  perishes  with  him.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  government  of  a  wife  and  children  and  of  a 
household,  which  we  have  called  household-management, 
is  exercised  in  the  first  instance  for  the  good  of  the 


214  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

governed  or  for  the  common  good  of  both  parties,  but 
essentially  for  the  good  of  the  governed. 

"  Having  determined  these  points,  we  have  next  to 
consider  how  many  forms  of  government  there  are,  and 
what  the>r  are ;  and  in  the  first  place  what  are  the  true 
forms,  for  when  they  are  determined  the  perversions  of 
them  will  at  once  be  apparent.  The  words  constitution 
and  government  have  the  same  meaning,  and  the  gov 
ernment,  which  is  the  supreme  authority  in  states,  must 
be  in  the  hands  of  one,  or  of  a  few,  or  of  many.  The 
true  forms  of  government,  therefore,  are  those  in  which 
the  one,  or  the  few,  or  the  many,  govern  with  a  view  to 
the  common  interest;  but  governments  which  rule  with 
a  view  to  the  private  interest,  whether  of  the  one,  or  of 
the  few,  or  of  the  many,  are  perversions.  For  citizens, 
if  they  are  truly  citizens,  ought  to  participate  in  the  ad 
vantages  of  a  state.  Of  forms  of  government  in  which 
one  rules,  we  call  that  which  regards  the  common  in 
terests,  kingship  or  royalty ;  that  in  which  more  than 
one,  but  not  many,  rule,  aristocracy  (the  rule  of  the 
best)  ;  and  it  is  so  called,  either  because  the  rulers  are 
the  best  men,  or  because  they  have  at  heart  the  best  in 
terests  of  the  state  and  of  the  citizens.  But  when  the 
citizens  at  large  administer  the  state  for  the  common  in 
terest,  the  government  is  called  by  the  generic  name, — 
a  constitution.  And  there  is  a  reason  for  this  use  of 
language.  One  man  or  a  few  may  excel  in  virtue;  but 
of  virtue  there  are  many  kinds :  and  as  the  number  in 
creases  it  becomes  more  difficult  for  them  to  attain  per 
fection  in  every  kind,  though  they  may  in  military  virtue, 
for  this  is  found  in  the  masses.  Hence,  in  a  constitu 
tional  government  the  fighting-men  have  the  supreme 
pow7er,  and  those  who  possess  arms  are  the  citizens. 

"Of  the  above-mentioned  forms,  the  perversions  areas 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  215 

follows: — of  royalty,  tyranny  ;  of  aristocracy,  oligarchy  ; 
of  constitutional  government,  democracy.  For  tyranny 
is  a  kind  of  monarchy  which  has  in  view  the  interests 
of  the  monarch  only;  oligarchy  has  in  view  the  interest 
of  the  wealthy ;  democracy,  of  the  needy ;  none  of  them 
the  common  good  of  all. 

"The  argument  seems  to  show  that,  whether  in  oli 
garchies  or  in  democracies,  the  number  of  the  governing 
body,  whether  the  greater  number,  as  in  a  democracy, 
or  the  smaller  number,  as  in  an  oligarchy,  is  an  accident 
due  to  the  fact  that  the  rich  everywhere  are  few,  and 
the  poor  numerous.  But  if  so,  there  is  a  misapprehen 
sion  of  the  causes  of  the  difference  between  them.  For 
the  real  difference  between  democracy  and  oligarchy  is 
poverty  and  wealth.  Wherever  men  rule  by  reason  of 
their  wealth,  whether  they  be  few  or  many,  that  is  an 
oligarchy,  and  where  the  poor  rule,  that  is  a  democracy. 
But  as  a  fact  the  rich  are  few  and  the  poor  many  ;  for 
few  are  well-to-do,  whereas,  freedom  is  enjoyed  by  all, 
and  wealth  and  freedom  are  the  grounds  on  which  the 
oligarchical  and  democratical  parties  respectively  claim 
power  in  the  state. 

"Let  us  begin  by  considering  the  common  definitions 
of  oligarchy  and  democracy,  and  what  is  justice  oli 
garchical  and  democratical.  For  all  men  cling  to  justice 
of  some  kind,  but  their  conceptions  are  imperfect  and 
they  do  not  express  the  whole  idea.  For  example,  jus 
tice  is  thought  by  them  to  be,  and  is,  equality,  not,  how 
ever,  for  all,  but  only  for  equals.  And  inequality  is 
thought  to  be,  and  is,  justice;  neither  is  this  for  all,  but 
only  for  unequals.  When  the  persons  are  omitted,  then 
men  judge  erroneously.  The  reason  is  that  they  are 
passing  judgment  on  themselves,  and  most  people  are 
bad  judges  in  their  own  case. 


216  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"  But  a  state  exists  for  the  sake  of  a  good  life,  and  not 
for  the  sake  of  life  only:  if  life  only  were  the  object, 
slaves  and  brute  animals  might  form  a  state,  but  they 
cannot,  for  they  have  no  share  in  happiness  or  in  a  life 
of  free  choice.  Nor  does  a  state  exist  for  the  sake  of 
alliance  and  security  from  injustice,  nor  yet  for  the  sake 
of  exchange  and  mutual  intercourse ;  for  then  the 
Tyrrhenians  and  the  Carthaginians,  and  all  who  have 
commercial  treaties  with  one  another,  would  be  the 
citizens  of  one  state. 

"Whereas,  those  who  are  for  good  government  take 
into  consideration  (the  larger  question  of)  virtue  and 
vice  in  states.  Whence  it  may  be  further  inferred  that 
virtue  must  be  the  serious  care  of  a  state  which  truly 
deserves  the  name;  for  (without  this  ethical  end)  the 
community  becomes  a  mere  alliance  which  differs  only 
in  place  from  alliances  of  w?hich  the  members  live  apart ; 
and  law  is  only  a  convention,  '  a  surety  to  one  another 
of  justice,'  as  the  sophist  Lycophron  says,  and  has  no 
real  power  to  make  the  citizens  good  and  just. 

"  It  is  clear,  then,  that  a  state  is  not  a  mere  society, 
having  a  common  place,  established  for  the  prevention 
of  crime  and  for  the  sake  of  exchange.  These  are  con 
ditions  without  wrhich  a  state  cannot  exist;  but  all  of 
them  together  do  not  constitute  a  state,  which  is  a  com 
munity  of  well-being  in  families  and  aggregations  of 
families,  for  the  sake  of  a  perfect  and  self-sufficing  life. 
Such  a  community  can  only  be  established  among  those 
who  live  in  the  same  place  and  intermarry.  Hence  arise 
in  cities  family  connections,  brotherhoods,  common 
sacrifices,  amusements  which  draw  men  together.  They 
are  created  by  friendship,  for  friendship  is  the  motive  of 
society.  The  end  is  the  good  life,  and  these  are  the 
means  towards  it.  And  the  state  is  the  union  of  families 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  217 

and  villages  having  for  an  end  a  perfect  and  self-suffic 
ing  life,  by  which  we  mean  a  happy  and  honorable  life. 

"  Our  conclusion,  then,  is  that  political  society  exists 
for  the  sake  of  noble  actions,  and  not  of  mere  companion 
ship.  And  they  who  contribute  most  to  such  a  society 
have  a  greater  share  in  it  than  those  who  have  the  same 
or  a  greater  freedom  or  nobility  of  birth  but  are  inferior 
to  them  in  political  virtue;  or  than  those  who  exceed 
them  in  wealth  but  are  surpassed  by  them  in  virtue. 

"  From  what  has  been  said  it  will  be  clearly  seen  that 
all  the  partisans  of  different  forms  of  government  speak 
of  a  part  of  justice  only. 

"  There  is  also  a  doubt  as  to  what  is  to  be  the  supreme 
power  in  the  state:  —  Is  it  the  multitude?  Or  the 
wealthy  ?  Or  the  good  ?  Or  the  one  best  man  ?  Or  a 
tyrant?  Any  of  these  alternatives  seems  to  involve 
disagreeable  consequences.  If  the  poor,  for  example, 
because  they  are  more  in  number,  divide  among  them 
selves  the  property  of  the  rich, — is  not  this  unjust  ?  No, 
by  heaven  (will  be  the  reply),  for  the  lawful  authority 
(i.  e.y  the  people)  willed  it.  But  if  this  is  not  injustice, 
pray  what  is?  Again,  when  (in  the  first  division)  all 
has  been  taken,  and  the  majority  divide  anew  the  prop 
erty  of  the  minority,  is  it  not  evident,  if  this  goes  on, 
that  they  will  ruin  the  state  ?  Yet  surely,  virtue  is  not 
the  ruin  of  those  who  possess  her,  nor  is  justice  destruc 
tive  of  a  state ;  and  therefore  this  law  of  confiscation 
clearly  cannot  be  just.  If  it  were,  all  the  acts  of  a  tyrant 
must  of  necessity  be  just;  for  he  only  coerces  other  men 
by  superior  power,  just  as  the  multitude  coerce  the  rich. 
But  is  it  just  then  that  the  few  and  the  wealthy  should 
be  the  rulers?  And  what  if  they,  in  like  manner,  rob 
and  plunder  the  people, — is  this  just?  If  so,  the  other 
case  (z.  e.,  the  case  of  the  majority  plundering  the 


218  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

minority)  will  likewise  be  just.     But  there  can  be  no 
doubt  that  all  these  things  are  wrong  and  unjust. 

"  Most  of  these  questions  may  be  reserved  for  another 
occasion.  The  principle  that  the  multitude  ought  to  be 
supreme  rather  than  the  few  best  is  capable  of  a  satis 
factory  explanation,  and,  though  not  free  from  difficulty, 
yet  seems  to  contain  an  element  of  truth.  For  the  many, 
of  whom  each  individual  is  but  an  ordinary  person, 
when  they  meet  together  may  very  likely  be  better  than 
the  few  good,  if  regarded  not  individually  but  collective 
ly,  just  as  a  feast  to  which  many  contribute,  is  better 
than  a  dinner  provided  out  of  a  single  purse.  For  each 
individual  among  the  many  has  a  share  of  virtue  and 
prudence,  and  when  they  meet  together  they  become  in 
a  manner  one  man,  who  has  many  feet,  and  hands,  and 
senses ;  that  is,  a  figure  of  their  mind  and  disposition. 
Hence  the  many  are  better  judges  than  a  single  man  of 
music  and  poetry  ;  for  some  understand  one  part,  and 
some  another,  and  among  them,  they  understand  the 
whole.  There  is  a  similar  combination  of  qualities  in 
good  men,  who  differ  from  any  individual  of  the  many, 
as  the  beautiful  are  said  to  differ  from  those  who  are 
not  beautiful,  and  works  of  art  from  realities,  because 
in  them  the  scattered  elements  are  combined,  although, 
if  taken  separately,  the  eye  of  one  person  or  some  other 
feature  in  another  person,  would  be  fairer  than  in  the 
picture.  Whether  this  principle  can  apply  to  every 
democracy,  and  to  all  bodies  of  men,  is  not  clear.  Or 
rather,  by  heaven,  in  some  cases  it  is  impossible  of  ap 
plication  ;  for  the  argument  would  equally  hold  about 
brutes ;  and  wherein,  it  will  be  asked,  do  some  men  differ 
from  brutes?  But  there  may  be  bodies  of  men  about 
whom  our  statement  is  nevertheless  true.  And  if  so, 
the  difficulty  which  has  been  already  raised,  and  also 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  219 

another  which  is  akin  to  it — viz.,  what  power  should  be 
assigned  to  the  mass  of  freemen  and  citizens,  who  are 
not  rich  and  have  no  personal  merit — are  both  solved. 
There  is  still  a  danger  in  allowing  them  to  share  the 
great  offices  of  state,  for  their  folly  will  lead  them  into 
error,  and  their  dishonesty  into  crime.  But  there  is  a 
danger  also  in  not  letting  them  share,  for  a  state,  in 
which  many  poor  men  are  excluded  from  office  will  nec 
essarily  be  full  of  enemies.  The  only  way  of  escape  is 
to  assign  to  them  some  deliberative  and  judicial 
functions.  For  this  reason  Solon  and  certain  other 
legislators  give  them  the  power  of  electing  to  offices,  and 
of  calling  the  magistrates  to  account,  but  they  do  not 
allow  them  to  hold  office  singly.  When  they  meet  to 
gether  their  perceptions  are  quite  good  enough,  and 
combined  with  the  better  class  they  are  useful  to  the 
state  (just  as  impure  food  when  mixed  with  what  is 
pure,  sometimes  makes  the  entire  mass  more  wholesome 
than  a  small  quantity  of  the  pure  would  be),  but  each 
individual,  left  to  himself,  forms  an  imperfect  judgment. 
"  Now,  does  not  the  same  principle  apply  to  elections? 
For  a  right  election  can  only  be  made  by  those  who 
have  knowledge ;  a  geometrician,  for  example,  will 
choose  rightly  in  matters  of  geometry,  or  a  pilot  in  mat 
ters  of  steering;  and,  even  if  there  be  some  occupations 
and  arts  with  which  private  persons  are  familiar,  they 
certainly  cannot  judge  better  than  those  who  know. 
So  that,  according  to  this  argument,  neither  the  election 
of  magistrates,  nor  the  calling  of  them  to  account,  should 
be  intrusted  to  the  many.  Yet  possibly  these  objections 
are  to  a  great  extent  met  by  our  old  answer,  that  if  the 
people  are  not  utterly  degraded,  although  individually 
they  may  bo  worse  judges  than  those  who  have  special 
knowledge — as  a  body  they  are  as  good  or  better.  More- 


22O  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

over,  there  are  some  artists  whose  works  are  judged  of 
solely,  or  in  the  best  manner,  not  by  themselves,  but  by 
those  who  do  not  possess  the  art ;  for  example,  the 
knowledge  of  the  house  is  not  limited  to  the  builder  only ; 
the  user,  or,  in  other  words,  the  master,  of  the  house 
will  even  be  a  better  judge  than  the  builder,  just  as  the 
pilot  will  judge  better  of  a  rudder  than  the  carpenter, 
and  the  guest  will  judge  better  of  a  feast  than  the  cook. 

"  In  all  sciences  and  arts  the  end  is  a  good,  and  especi 
ally  and  above  all  in  the  highest  of  all — this  is  the 
political  science  of  which  the  good  is  justice,  in  other 
words,  the  common  interest.  All  men  think  justice  to 
be  a  sort  of  equality ;  and  to  a  certain  extent  they  agree 
in  the  philosophical  distinctions  which  have  been  laid 
down  by  us  about  Ethics.  For  they  admit  that  justice 
is  a  thing  having  relation  to  persons,  and  that  equals 
ought  to  have  equality.  But  there  still  remains  a  ques 
tion  ;  equality  or  inequality  of  what  ?  Here  is  a  difficulty 
which  the  political  philosopher  has  to  resolve.  For 
very  likely  some  persons  will  say  that  offices  of  state 
ought  to  be  unequally  distributed  according  to  superior 
excellence,  in  whatever  respect,  of  the  citizen,  although 
there  is  no  other  difference  between  him  and  the  rest  of 
the  community ;  for  that  those  who  differ  in  any  one 
respect  have  different  rights  and  claims.  But,  surely,  if 
this  is  true,  the  complexion  or  height  of  a  man,  or  any 
other  advantage,  will  be  a  reason  for  his  obtaining  a 
greater  share  of  political  rights. 

"But  since  no  such  comparison  can  be  made,  it  is  evi 
dent  that  there  is  good  reason,  why  in  politics  men  do 
not  ground  their  claim  to  office  on  every  sort  of  in 
equality  any  more  than  in  the  arts.  For  if  some  be 
slow,  and  others  swift,  that  is  no  reason  why  the  one 
should  have  little  and  the  others  much ;  it  is  in  gymnastic 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  221 

contests  that  such  excellence  is  rewarded.  Whereas  the 
rival  claims  of  candidates  for  office  can  only  be  based  on 
the  possession  of  elements  which  enter  into  the  com 
position  of  a  state,  (such  as  wealth,  virtue,  etc.)  And 
therefore  the  noble,  or  free-born,  or  rich,  may  with  good 
reason  claim  office;  for  holders  of  offices  must  be  free 
men  and  taxpayers ;  a  state  can  be  no  more  composed 
entirely  of  poor  men  than  entirely  of  slaves.  But  if 
wealth  and  freedom  are  necessary  elements,  justice  and 
valor  are  equally  so  ;  for  without  the  former  a  state 
cannot  exist  at  all,  without  the  latter,  not  well. 

"  If  the  existence  of  the  state  is  alone  to  be  considered, 
then  it  would  seem  that  all,  or  some  at  least,  of  these 
claims  are  just;  but,  if  we  take  into  account  a  good  life, 
as  I  have  already  said,  education  and  virtue  have  su 
perior  claims.  As,  however,  those  who  are  equal  in  one 
thing  ought  not  to  be  equal  in  all,  nor  those  who  are 
unequal  in  one  thing  to  be  unequal  in  all,  it  is  certain 
that  all  forms  of  government  which  rest  on  either  of 
these  principles  are  perversions.  All  men  have  a  claim 
in  a  certain  sense,  as  I  have  already  admitted,  but  they 
have  not  an  absolute  claim.  The  rich  claim  because 
they  have  a  greater  share  in  the  land,  and  land  is  the 
common  element  of  the  state  ;  also  they  are  generally 
more  trustworthy  in  contracts.  The  free  claim  under 
the  same  title  as  the  noble;  for  they  are  nearly  akin. 
And  the  noble  are  citizens  in  a  truer  sense  than  the 
ignoble,  since  good  birth  is  always  valued  in  a  man's 
own  home  and  country.  Another  reason  is,  that  those 
who  are  sprung  from  better  ancestors  are  likely  to  be 
better  men,  for  nobility  is  excellence  of  race.  Virtue, 
too,  may  be  truly  said  to  have  a  claim,  for  justice  has 
been  acknowledged  by  us  to  be  a  social  virtue,  and  it 
implies  all  others.  Again,  the  many  may  urge  their 


222  Ethics  $f  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

claim  against  the  few ;  for,  when  taken  collectively,  and 
compared  with  the  few,  they  are  stronger  and  richer  and 
better.  But,  what  if  the  good,  the  rich,  the  noble,  and 
the  other  classes  who  make  up  a  state,  are  all  living  to 
gether  in  the  same  city,  will  there,  or  will  there  not,  be 
any  doubt  who  shall  rule? — No  doubt  at  all  in  determin 
ing  who  ought  to  rule  in  each  of  the  above-mentioned 
forms  of  government.  For  states  are  characterized  by 
differences  in  their  governing  bodies — one  of  them  has 
a  government  of  the  rich,  another  of  the  virtuous,  and 
so  on.  But  a  difficulty  arises  when  all  these  elements 
co-exist.  How  are  we  to  decide?  Suppose  the  virtuous 
to  be  very  few  in  number ;  may  we  consider  their 
numbers  in  relation  to  their  duties,  and  ask  whether 
they  are  enough  to  administer  the  state,  or  must  they 
be  so  many  as  will  make  up  a  state?  Objections  may 
be  urged  against  all  the  aspirants  to  political  power. 
For  those  who  found  their  claims  on  wealth  or  family 
have  no  basis  of  justice;  on  this  principle,  if  any  one 
person  were  richer  than  all  the  rest,  it  is  clear  that  he 
ought  to  be  the  ruler  of  them.  In  like  manner  he  who 
is  very  distinguished  by  his  birth  ought  to  have  the 
superiority  over  all  those  who  claim  on  the  ground  that 
they  are  free-born.  In  an  aristocracy,  or  government  of 
the  best,  a  like  difficulty  occurs  about  virtue ;  for  if  one 
citizen  be  better  than  the  other  members  of  the  govern 
ment,  however  good  they  may  be,  he  too,  upon  the  same 
principle  of  justice,  should  rule  over  them.  And  if  the 
people  are  to  be  supreme  because  they  are  stronger  than 
the  few,  then  if  one  man,  or  more  than  one,  but  not  a 
majority,  is  stronger  than  the  many,  they  ought  to  rule, 
and  not  the  many. 

"All  these  considerations  appear  to  show  that  none  of 
the  principles  on  which  men  claim  to  rule,  and  hold  all 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  223 

other  men  in  subjection  to  them,  are  strictly  right.  To 
those  who  claim  to  be  masters  of  the  state  on  the  ground 
of  their  virtue  or  their  wealth,  the  many  might  fairly 
answer  that  they  themselves  are  often  better  and  richer 
than  the  few — I  do  not  say  individually,  but  collectively. 
And  another  ingenious  objection  which  is  sometimes 
put  forward  may  be  met  in  a  similar  manner.  Some 
persons  doubt  whether  the  legislator  who  desires  to 
make  the  justest  laws  ought  to  legislate  with  a  view  to 
the  good  of  the  higher  classes  or  of  the  many,  when  the 
case  which  we  have  mentioned  occurs  (i.  e.  when  all  the 
elements  co-exist.)  Now  what  is  just  or  right  is  to  be 
interpreted  in  the  sense  of  "what  is  equal;"  and  that 
which  is  right  in  the  sense  of  being  equal  is  to  be  con 
sidered  with  reference  to  the  advantage  of  the  state,  and 
the  common  good  of  the  citizens.  And  a  citizen  is  one 
who  shares  in  governing  and  being  governed.  He 
differs  under  different  forms  of  government,  but  in  the 
best  state  he  is  one  who  is  able  and  willing  to  be 
governed  and  to  govern  with  a  view  to  the  life  of  virtue. 
"  If,  however,  there  be  some  one  person,  or  more  than 
one,  although  not  enough  to  make  up  the  full  comple 
ment  of  a  state,  whose  virtue  is  so  pre-eminent  that  the 
virtues  or  the  political  power  of  all  the  rest  admit  of  no 
comparison  with  his  or  theirs,  he  or  they  can  be  no 
longer  regarded  as  part  of  a  state;  for  justice  will  not 
be  done  to  the  superior,  if  he  is  reckoned  only  as  the 
equal  of  those  who  are  so  far  inferior  to  him  in  virtue 
and  in  political  power.  Such  an  one  may  truly  be 
deemed  a  God  among  men.  Hence  we  see  that  legisla 
tion  is  necessarily  concerned  only  with  those  who  are 
equal  in  birth  and  in  power ;  and  that  for  men  of  pre 
eminent  virtue  there  is  no  law— they  are  themselves  a 
law.  Any  one  would  be  ridiculous  who  attempted  to 


224  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers, 

make  laws  for  them.  And  for  this  reason  democratic 
states  have  instituted  ostracism ;  equality  is  above  all 
things  their  aim,  and  therefore  they  ostracise  and  banish 
from  the  city  for  a  time  those  who  seem  to  predominate 
too  much  through  their  wealth,  or  the  number  of  their 
friends,  or  through  any  other  political  influence. 

"  The  problem  is  a  universal  one,  and  equally  concerns 
all  forms  of  government,  true  as  well  as  false;  for, 
although  perverted  forms  with  a  view  to  their  own  in 
terests  may  adopt  this  policy,  those  which  seek  the 
common  interest  do  so  likewise. 

"  Hence  where  there  is  an  acknowledged  superiority  the 
argument  in  favor  of  ostracism  is  based  upon  a  kind  of 
political  justice.  It  would  certainly  be  better  that  the 
legislator  should,  from  the  first  so  order  his  state  as  to 
have  no  need  of  such  a  remedy.  But  if  the  need  arises, 
the  next  best  thing  is  that  he  should  endeavor  to  correct 
the  evil  by  this  or  some  similar  measure.  The  principle, 
however,  has  not  been  fairly  applied  in  states ;  for,  in 
stead  of  looking  to  the  public  good,  they  have  used 
ostracism  for  factious  purposes.  It  is  true  that  under 
perverted  forms  of  government,  and  from  their  special 
point  of  view,  such  a  measure  is  just  and  expedient,  but 
it  is  also  clear  that  it  is  not  absolutely  just.  In  the 
perfect  state  there  would  be  great  doubts  about  the  use 
of  it,  not  when  applied  to  excess  in  strength,  wealth, 
popularity,  or  the  like,  but  when  used  against  some  one 
who  is  pre-eminent  in  virtue, — what  is  to  be  done  with 
him?  Mankind  will  not  say  that  such  an  one  is  to  be 
expelled  and  exiled;  on  the  other  hand,  he  ought  not 
to  be  a  subject — that  would  be  as  if  in  the  division  of 
the  empire  of  the  Gods,  the  other  Gods  should  claim  to 
rule  over  Zeus.  The  only  alternative  is  that  all  should 
joyfully  obey  such  a  ruler,  according  to  what  seems  to 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  225 

be  the  order  of  nature,  and  that  men  like  him  should  be 
kings  in  their  state  for  life. 

"The  preceding  discussion,  by  a  natural  transition, 
leads  to  the  consideration  of  royalty,  which  we  admit  to 
be  one  of  the  true  forms  of  government.  Let  us  see 
whether,  in  order  to  be  well  governed,  a  state  or  country 
should  be  under  the  rule  of  a  king  or  under  some  other 
form  of  government;  and  whether  monarchy,  although 
good  for  some,  may  not  be  bad  for  others.  But  first  we 
must  determine  whether  there  is  one  species  of  royalty 
or  many.  It  is  easy  to  see  that  there  are  many,  and  that 
the  manner  of  government  is  not  the  same  in  all  of  them. 

"  These,  then,  are  the  four  kinds  of  royalty.  First  the 
monarchy  of  the  heroic  ages;  this  was  exercised  over 
voluntary  subjects,  but  limited  to  certain  functions;  the 
king  was  a  general  and  a  judge,  and  had  the  control  of 
religion.  The  second  is  that  of  the  barbarians,  which  is 
an  hereditary  despotic  government  in  accordance  with 
law.  A  third  is  the  power  of  the  so-called  Aesymnete 
or  Dictator ;  this  is  an  elective  tyranny.  The  fourth  is 
the  Lacedaemonian,  which  is  in  fact  a  generalship,  he 
reditary  and  perpetual.  These  four  forms  differ  from 
one  another  in  the  manner  which  I  have  described. 

"  There  is  a  fifth  form  of  kingly  rule  in  which  one  has 
the  disposal  of  all,  just  as  each  tribe  or  each  state  has 
the  disposal  of  the  public  property;  this  form  corre 
sponds  to  the  control  of  a  household.  For  as  household 
management  is  the  kingly  rule  of  a  house,  so  kingly  rule 
is  the  household  management  of  a  city,  or  of  a  nation, 
or  of  many  nations. 

"  Of  these  forms  we  need  only  consider  two,  the 
Lacedaemonian  and  the  absolute  royalty ;  for  most  of  the 
others  lie  in  a  region  between  them,  having  less  power 
than  the  last,  and  more  than  the  first.  Thus  the  inquiry 


226  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

is  reduced  to  two  points:  first,  is  it  advantageous  to  the 
state  that  there  should  be  a  perpetual  general,  and  if  so, 
should  the  office  be  confined  to  one  family,  or  open  to 
the  citizens  in  turn  ?  Secondly,  is  it  well  that  a  single 
man  should  have  the  supreme  power  in  all  things?  The 
first  question  falls  under  the  head  of  laws  rather  than  of 
constitutions;  for  perpetual  generalship  might  equally 
exist  under  any  form  of  government,  so  that  this  matter 
may  be  dismissed  for  the  present.  The  other  kind  of 
royalty  is  a  sort  of  constitution ;  this  we  have  now  to 
consider,  and  briefly  to  run  over  the  difficulties  involved 
in  it.  We  will  begin  by  inquiring  whether  it  is  more 
advantageous  to  be  ruled  by  the  best  man  or  by  the  best 
laws. 

"  The  advocates  of  royalty  maintain  that  the  laws  speak 
only  in  general  terms,  and  cannot  provide  for  circum 
stances;  and  that  for  any  science  to  abide  by  written 
rules  is  absurd.  Even  in  Egypt  the  physician  is  allowed 
to  alter  his  treatment  after  the  fourth  day,  but  if  sooner, 
he  takes  the  risk.  Hence  it  is  argued  that  a  govern 
ment  acting  according  to  written  laws  is  plainly  not  the 
best.  Yet  surely  the  ruler  cannot  dispense  with  the 
general  principle  which  exists  in  law ;  and  he  is  a  better 
ruler  who  is  free  from  passion  than  he  who  is  passionate. 
Whereas  the  law  is  passionless,  passion  must  ever  sway 
the  heart  of  man. 

"  Yes,  some  one  will  answer,  but  then  on  the  other  hand 
an  individual  will  be  better  able  to  advise  in  particular 
cases.  (To  whom  we  in  turn  make  reply:)  A  king 
must  legislate,  and  laws  must  be  passed,  but  these  laws 
will  have  no  authority  when  they  miss  the  mark,  though 
in  all  other  cases  retaining  their  authority.  (Yet  a 
further  question  remains  behind  :)  When  the  law  can 
not  determine  a  point  at  all,  or  not  well,  should  the  one 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  227 

best  man,  or  should  all,  decide?  According  to  our  pres 
ent  practice  assemblies  meet,  sit  in  judgment,  deliberate 
and  decide,  and  their  judgments  all  relate  to  individual 
cases.  Now  any  member  of  the  assembly,  taken  sepa 
rately,  is  certainly  inferior  to  the  wise  man.  But  the 
state  is  made  up  of  many  individuals.  And  as  a  feast 
to  which  all  the  guests  contribute  is  better  than  a 
banquet  furnished  by  a  single  man,  so  a  multitude  is  a 
better  judge  of  many  things  than  any  individual. 

" Again,  the  many  are  more  incorruptible  than  the  few; 
they  are  like  the  greater  quantity  of  water  which  is  less 
easily  corrupted  than  a  little.  The  individual  is  liable 
to  be  overcome  by  anger  or  by  some  other  passion,  and 
then  his  judgment  is  necessarily  perverted;  but  it  is 
hardly  to  be  supposed  that  a  great  number  of  persons 
would  all  get  into  a  passion  and  go  wrong  at  the  same 
moment.  Let  us  assume  that  they  are  freemen,  never 
acting  in  violation  of  the  law,  but  filling  up  the  gaps 
which  the  law  is  obliged  to  leave.  Or,  if  such  virtue  is 
scarcely  attainable  by  the  multitude,  we  need  only  sup 
pose  that  the  majority  are  good  men  and  good  citizens, 
and  ask  which  will  be  the  more  incorruptible,  the  one 
good  ruler,  or  the  many  who  are  all  good?  Will  not 
the  many?  But,  you  will  say,  there  may  be  parties 
among  them,  whereas  the  one  man  is  not  divided  against 
himself.  To  which  we  may  answer  that  their  character 
is  as  good  as  his.  If  we  call  the  rule  of  many  men,  who 
are  all  of  them  good,  aristocracy,  and  the  rule  of  one 
man  royalty,  then  aristocracy  will  be  better  for  states 
than  royalty,  whether  the  government  is  supported  by 
force  or  not,  provided  only  that  a  number  of  men  equal 
in  virtue,  can  be  found. 

"  The  first  governments  were  kingships,  probably  for 
this  reason,  because  of  old,  when  cities  were  small,  men 


228  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

of  eminent  virtue  were  few.  They  were  made  kings 
because  they  were  benefactors,  and  benefits  can  only  be 
bestowed  by  good  men.  But  when  many  persons  equal 
in  merit  arose,  no  longer  enduring  the  pre-eminence  of 
one,  they  desired  to  have  a  commonwealth,  and  set  up  a 
constitution.  The  ruling  class  soon  deteriorated  and 
enriched  themselves  out  of  the  public  treasury ;  riches 
became  the  path  to  honor,  and  so  oligarchies  naturally 
grew  up.  These  passed  into  tyrannies  and  tyrannies 
into  democracies;  for  love  of  gain  in  the  ruling  classes 
was  always  tending  to  diminish  their  number,  and  so  to 
strengthen  the  masses,  who  in  the  end  set  upon  their 
masters  and  established  democracies.  Since  cities  have 
increased  in  size,  no  other  form  of  government  appears 
to  be  any  longer  possible. 

"  Now,  absolute  monarchy,  or  the  arbitrary  rule  of  a 
sovereign  over  all  the  citizens,  in  a  city  which  consists 
of  equals,  is  thought  by  some  to  be  quite  contrary  to 
nature ;  it  is  argued  that  those  who  are  by  nature  equals 
must  have  the  same  natural  right  and  worth,  and  that 
for  unequals  to  have  an  equal  share,  or  for  equals  to 
have  an  unequal  share,  in  the  offices  of  state,  is  as  bad 
as  for  different  bodily  constitutions  to  have  the  same 
food  and  clothing  or  the  same  different.  Wherefore,  it 
is  thought  to  be  just,  that  among  equals  every  one  be 
ruled  as  well  as  rule,  and  that  all  should  have  their  turn. 
We  thus  arrive  at  law ;  for  an  order  of  succession  implies 
law.  And  the  rule  of  the  law  is  preferable  to  that  of 
any  individual.  On  the  same  principle,  even  if  it  be 
better  for  certain  individuals  to  govern,  they  should  be 
made  only  guardians  and  ministers  of  the  law. 

"  He  who  bids  the  law  rule, may  be  deemed  to  bid  God 
and  Reason  alone  rule,  but  he  who  bids  man  rule  adds 
an  element  of  the  beast ;  for  desire  is  a  wild  beast,  and 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  229 

passion  perverts  the  minds  of  rulers,  even  when  they 
are  the  best  of  men.  The  law  is  reason  unaffected  by 
desire. 

"Hence  it  is  evident,  that  in  seeking  for  justice  men 
seek  for  the  mean  or  neutral,  and  the  law  is  the  mean. 
Again,  customary  laws  have  more  weight,  and  relate  to 
more  important  matters,  than  written  laws,  and  a  man 
may  be  a  safer  ruler  than  the  written  law,  but  not  safer 
than  the  customary  law. 

"If,  as  I  said  before,  the  good  man  has  a  right  to  rule 
because  he  is  better,  then  two  good  men  are  better  than 
one:  this  is  the  old  saying. 

"Now,  from  what  has  been  said,  it  is  manifest  that, 
where  men  are  alike  and  equal,  it  is  neither  expedient 
nor  just  that  one  man  should  be  lord  of  all,  whether 
there  are  laws  or  whether  there  are  no  laws,  but  he  him 
self  is  in  the  place  of  law.  Neither  should  a  good  man 
be  lord  over  good  men,  or  a  bad  man  over  bad;  nor,  even 
if  he  excels  in  virtue,  should  he  have  a  right  to  rule,  un 
less  in  a  particular  case,  which  I  have  already  mentioned, 
and  to  which  I  will  once  more  recur.  But  first  of  all,  I 
must  determine  what  natures  are  suited  for  royalties, 
and  what  for  an  aristocracy,  and  what  for  a  constitution 
al  government. 

"A  people  who  are  by  nature  capable  of  producing  a 
race  superior  in  virtue  and  political  talent  are  fitted  for 
kingly  government;  and  a  people  submitting  to  be  ruled 
as  freemen  by  men  whose  virtue  renders  them  capable 
of  political  command  are  adapted  for  aD  aristocracy ; 
while  the  people  who  are  suited  for  constitutional  free 
dom,  are  those  among  whom  there  naturally  exists  a 
warlike  multitude  able  to  rule  and  to  obey  in  turn  by  a 
law  which  gives  office  to  the  well-to-do  according  to 
their  desert. 


230  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"  We  maintain  that  the  true  forms  of  government  are 
three,  and  that  the  best  must  be  that  which  is  ad 
ministered  by  the  best,  and  in  which  there  is  one  man, 
or  a  whole  family,  or  many  persons,  excelling  in  virtue, 
and  both  rulers  and  subjects  are  fitted,  the  one  to  rule, 
the  others  to  be  ruled,  in  such  a  manner  as  to  attain  the 
most  eligible  life.  We  showed  at  the  commencement  of 
our  inquiry  that  the  virtue  of  the  good  man  is  neces 
sarily  the  same  as  the  virtue  of  the  citizen  of  the  perfect 
state.  Clearly  then  in  the  same  manner,  and  by  the 
same  means  through  which  a  man  becomes  truly  good, 
he  will  frame  a  state  (which  will  be  truly  good)  whether 
aristocratical,  or  under  kingly  rule,  and  the  same  educa 
tion  and  same  habits  will  be  found  to  make  a  good  man, 
and  a  good  statesman  and  king." 


THE  BEST  CONSTITUTION  FOR  A  STATE. 

PREPONDERANCE  OF  THE  MIDDLE  CLASS  RECOMMENDED. 

FROM  ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS,  BOOK  IV. 

"  We  have  now  to  enquire  what  is  the  best  constitution 
for  most  states,  and  the  best  life  for  most  men,  neither 
assuming  a  standard  of  virtue  which  is  above  ordinary 
persons,  nor  an  education  which  is  exceptionally  favored 
by  nature  and  circumstances,  nor  yet  an  ideal  state 
which  is  an  aspiration  only,  but  having  regard  to  the 
life  in  which  the  majority  are  able  to  share,  and  to  the 
form  of  government  which  states  in  general  can  attain. 
As  to  those  aristocracies,  as  they  are  called,  of  which  we 
were  just  now  speaking,  they  either  lie  beyond  the  pos 
sibilities  of  the  greater  number  of  states,  or  they  ap 
proximate  to  the  so-called  constitutional  government, 
and  therefore  need  no  separate  discussion.  And  in  fact 
the  conclusion  at  which  we  arrive  respecting  all  these 
forms  rests  upon  the  same  grounds.  For  if  it  has  been 
truly  said  in  the  Ethics  that  the  happy  life  is  the  life 
according  to  unimpeded  virtue,  and  that  virtue  is  a  mean, 
then  the  life  which  is  in  a  mean,  and  in  a  mean  attain 
able  by  every  one,  must  be  the  best.  And  the  same 
principles  of  virtue  and  vice  are  characteristic  of  cities 
and  of  constitutions ;  for  the  constitution  is  in  a  figure 

the  life  of  the  city. 

(231) 


232  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"Now  in  all  states  there  are  three  elements;  one  class  is 
very  rich,  another  very  poor,  and  a  third  in  a  mean.  It 
is  admitted  that  moderation  and  the  mean  are  best,  and 
therefore  it  will  clearly  be  best  to  possess  the  gifts  of 
fortune  in  moderation ;  for  in  that  condition  of  life  men 
are  most  ready  to  listen  to  reason.  But  a  city  ought  to 
be  composed,  as  far  as  possible,  of  equals  and  similars; 
and  these  are  generally  the  middle  classes.  Wherefore, 
the  city  which  is  composed  of  middle-class  citizens  is 
necessarily  best  governed;  they  are,  as  we  say,  the 
natural  elements  of  a  state.  And  this  is  the  class  of 
citizens  which  is  most  secure  in  a  state,  for  they  do  not, 
like  the  poor,  covet  their  neighbors'  goods ;  nor  do  others 
covet  theirs,  as  the  poor  covet  the  goods  of  the  rich ;  and 
as  they  neither  plot  against  others,  nor  are  themselves 
plotted  against,  they  pass  through  life  safely.  Wisely 
then,  did  Phocylides  pray, — 

"Many  things  are  best  in  the  mean;  I  desire  to  be  of 
a  middle  condition  in  my  city." 

"Thus it  is  manifest  that  the  best  political  community 
is  formed  by  citizens  of  the  middle  class,  and  that  those 
states  are  likely  to  be  well-administered,  in  which  the 
middle  class  is  large,  and  larger  if  possible,  than  both 
the  other  classes,  or  at  any  rate,  than  either  singly ;  for 
the  addition  of  the  middle  class  turns  the  scale,  and 
prevents  either  of  the  extremes  from  being  dominant. 
Great,  then,  is  the  good  fortune  of  a  state  in  which  the 
citizens  have  a  moderate  and  sufficient  property;  for 
where  some  possess  much,  and  the  others  nothing,  there 
may  arise  an  extreme  democracy,  or  a  pure  oligarchy ; 
or  a  tyranny  may  grow  out  of  either  extreme, — either 
out  of  the  most  rampant  democracy,  or  out  of  an  oli 
garchy  ;  but  it  is  not  so  likely  to  arise  out  of  a  middle 
and  nearly  equal  condition.  I  will  explain  the  reason 


THE  BEST  AND  SAFEST  GOVERNMENT. 

A    DEMOCRACY   WITH    THE    MIDDLE     CLASS    PREPON 
DERATING. 

"  The  mean  condition  of  states  is  clearly  best,  for  no 
other  is  free  from  faction  ;  and  where  the  middle  class 
is  large  there  are  least  likely  to  be  factions  and  dis 
sensions.  For  a  similar  reason,  large  states  are  less 
liable  to  faction  than  small  ones,  because  in  them  the 
middle  class  is  large ;  whereas  in  small  states  it  is 
easy  to  divide  all  the  citizens  into  two  classes  who  are 
either  rich  or  poor,  and  to  leave  nothing  in  the  middle. 
And  democracies  are  safer  and  more  permanent  than 
oligarchies,  because  they  have  a  middle  class  which  is 
more  numerous  and  has  a  greater  share  in  the  gov 
ernment ;  for  when  there  is  no  middle  class  and  the 
poor  greatly  exceed  in  number,  troubles  arise,  and  the 
state  soon  comes  to  an  end.  A  proof  of  the  superiority 
of  the  middle  class  is  that  the  best  legislators  have  been 
of  a  middle  condition  ;  for  example,  Solon,  as  his  own 
verses  testify ;  and  Lycurgus,  for  he  was  not  a  King  ; 
and  Charondas,  and  almost  all  legislators." 

Aristotle'*  s  Politics- 


ARISTOTLE. 

B.  C.  350. 
From  a  Sculpture  in  the  Gal.   Du  Capitole. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  233 

of  this  hereafter,  when  I  speak  of  the  revolutions  of 
states.  The  mean  condition  of  states  is  clearly  best,  for 
no  other  is  free  from  faction  ;  and  where  the  middle  class 
is  large,  there  are  least  likely  to  be  factions  and  dissen 
sions.  For  a  similar  reason  large  states  are  less  liable 
to  faction  than  small  ones,  because  in  them  the  middle 
class  is  large  ;  whereas  in  small  states  it  is  easy  to  divide 
all  the  citizens  into  two  classes  who  are  either  rich  or 
poor,  and  to  leave  nothing  in  the  middle.  And 
democracies  are  safer  and  more  permanent  than  oli 
garchies,  because  they  have  a  middle  class  which  is  more 
numerous  and  has  a  greater  share  in  the  government; 
for  when  there  is  no  middle  class,  and  the  poor  greatly 
exceed  in  number,  troubles  arise,  and  the  state  soon 
comes  to  an  end.  A  proof  of  the  superiority  of  the 
middle  class  is  that  the  best  legislators  have  been  of  a 
middle  condition ;  for  example,  Solon,  as  his  own  verses 
testify;  and  Lycurgus,  for  he  was  not  a  king;  and 
Charondas,  and  almost  all  legislators. 

"  We  have  now  to  consider  what,  and  what  kind  of  gov 
ernment  is  suitable,  to  what,  and  what  kind  of  men.  I 
may  begin  by  assuming,  as  a  general  principle  common 
to  all  governments,  that  the  portion  of  the  state  which 
desires  permanence  ought  to  be  stronger  than  that  which 
desires  the  reverse.  Now  every  city  is  composed  of 
quality  and  quantity.  By  quality  I  mean  freedom, 
wealth,  education,  good  birth,  and  by  quantity,  su 
periority  of  numbers.  Quality  may  exist  in  one  of  the 
classes  which  make  up  the  state,  and  quantity  in  the 
other.  For  example,  the  meanly-born  may  be  more  in 
number  than  the  well-born,  or  the  poor  than  the  rich, 
yet  they  may  not  so  much  exceed  in  quantity  as  they  fall 
short  in  quality ;  and  therefore  there  must  be  a  com 
parison  of  quantity  and  quality.  Where  the  number  of 


234  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

the  poor  is  more  than  proportioned  to  the  wealth  of  the 
rich,  there  will  naturally  be  a  democracy,  varying  in 
form  with  the  sort  of  people  who  compose  it  in  each 
case.  If,  for  example,  the  husbandmen  exceed  in  num 
ber,  the  first  form  of  democracy  will  then  arise;  if  the 
artisans  and  laboring  class,  the  last;  and  so  with  the 
intermediate  forms.  But  where  the  rich  and  the  notables 
exceed  in  quality  more  than  they  fall  short  in  quantity, 
there  oligarchy  arises,  similarly  assuming  various  forms 
according  to  the  kind  of  superiority  possessed  by  the 
oligarchs. 

"  The  legislator  should  always  include  the  middle  class 
in  his  government;  if  he  makes  his  laws  oligarchical,  to 
the  middle  class  let  him  look;  if  he  makes  them  demo- 
cratical,  he  should  equally  by  his  laws  try  to  attach  this 
class  to  the  state.  There  only  can  the  government  ever 
be  stable  where  the  middle  class  exceeds  one  or  both  of 
the  others,  and  in  that  case  there  will  be  no  fear  that  the 
rich  will  unite  with  the  poor  against  the  rulers.  For 
neither  of  them  will  ever  be  willing  to  serve  the  other, 
and  if  they  look  for  some  form  of  government  more  suit 
able  to  both,  they  will  find  none  better  than  this,  for  the 
rich  and  the  poor  will  never  consent  to  rule  in  turn,  be 
cause  they  mi.strust  one  another.  The  arbiter  is  always 
the  one  trusted,  and  he  who  is  in  the  middle  is  an  arbiter. 
The  more  perfect  the  admixture  of  the  political  elements, 
the  more  lasting  will  be  the  state.  Many  even  of  those 
who  desire  to  form  aristocratical  governments  make  a 
mistake,  not  only  in  giving  too  much  power  to  the  rich, 
but  in  attempting  to  overreach  the  people.  There  comes 
a  time  when,  out  of  a  false  good  there  arises  a  true  evil, 
since  the  encroachments  of  the  rich  are  more  destructive 
to  the  state  than  those  of  the  people." 


EXTRACTS  FROM  ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS, 

BOOK  V. 
CAUSE  OF  REVOLUTIONS. 

"  Still  democracy  appears  to  be  safer  and  less  liable  to 
revolution  than  oligarchy.  For  in  oligarchies  there  is 
the  double  danger  of  the  oligarchs  falling  out  among 
themselves  and  also  with  the  people ;  but  in  democracies 
there  is  only  the  danger  of  a  quarrel  with  the  oligarchs. 
No  dissension  worth  mentioning  arises  among  the  people 
themselves.  And  we  may  further  remark  that  a  gov 
ernment  which  is  composed  of  the  middle  class,  more 
nearly  approximates  to  democracy  than  to  oligarchy, 
and  is  the  safest  of  the  imperfect  forms  of  government. 

"  In  considering  how  dissensions  and  political  revolu 
tions  arise,  we  must  first  of  all  ascertain  the  beginnings 
and  causes  of  them  which  affect  constitutions  generally. 
They  may  be  said  to  be  three  in  number;  and  we  have 
now  to  give  an  outline  of  each.  We  want  to  know  ( i ) 
what  is  the  feeling?  and  (2)  what  are  the  motives  of 
those  who  make  them?  (3)  whence  arise  political  dis 
turbances  and  quarrels?  The  universal  and  chief  cause 
of  this  revolutionary  feeling  has  been  already  mentioned  ; 
viz.,  the  desire  of  equality,  wrhen  men  think  that  they 
are  equal  to  others  who  have  more  than  themselves  ;  or, 
again,  the  desire  of  inequality  and  superiority,  when 
conceiving  themselves  to  be  superior  they  think  that 

(235) 


236  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

they  have,  not  more,  but  the  same  or  less  than  their  in 
feriors;  pretensions  which  may,  and  may  not,  be  just. 
Inferiors  revolt  in  order  that  they  may  be  equal,  and 
equals  that  they  may  be  superior.  Such  is  the  state  of 
mind  which  creates  revolutions.  The  motives  for  mak 
ing  them  are  the  desire  of  gain  and  honor,  or  the  fear  of 
dishonor  and  loss ;  the  authors  of  them  want  to  divert 
punishment  or  dishonor  from  themselves  or  their  friends. 
The  causes  and  reasons  of  these  motives  and  dispo 
sitions  which  are  excited  in  men,  about  the  things  which 
I  have  mentioned,  viewed  in  one  way,  may  be  regarded 
as  seven,  and  in  another,  as  more  than  seven.  Two  of 
them  have  been  already  noticed;  but  they  act  in  a 
different  manner,  for  men  are  excited  against  one  an 
other  by  the  love  of  gain  and  honor — not,  as  in  the  case 
which  I  have  just  supposed,  in  order  to  obtain  them  for 
themselves,  but  at  seeing  others,  justly  or  unjustly,  en 
grossing  them.  Other  causes  are  insolence,  fear,  love  of 
superiority,  contempt,  disproportionate  increase  in  some 
part  of  the  state  ;  causes  of  another  sort  are  election 
intrigues,  carelessness,  neglect  about  trifles,  dissimilarity 
of  elements. 

"Political  revolutions  also  spring  from  a  disproportion 
ate  increase  in  any  part  of  the  state.  For  as  a  body  is 
made  up  of  many  members,  and  every  member  ought  to 
grow  in  proportion,  that  symmetry  may  be  preserved ; 
but  loses  its  nature  if  the  foot  be  four  cubits  long  and 
the  rest  of  the  body  two  spans;  and,  should  the  abnormal 
increase  be  one  of  quality  as  well  as  of  quantity,  may 
even  take  the  form  of  another  animal :  even  so  a  state 
has  many  parts,  of  which  some  one  may  often  grow  im 
perceptibly  ;  for  example,  the  number  of  poor  in  de 
mocracies  and  in  constitutional  states.  And  this  dis 
proportion  may  sometimes  happen  by  an  accident,  as  at 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  237 

Tarentum,  from  a  defeat  in  which  many  of  the  notables 
were  slain  in  a  battle  with  the  lapygians  just  after  the 
Persian  War,  the  constitutional  government  in  conse 
quence  becoming  a  democracy;  or,  as  was  the  case  at 
Argos,  where,  after  the  battle  at  Hebdomk,  the  Argives, 
having  been  cut  to  pieces  by  Cleomenes  the  Lacedae 
monian,  were  compelled  to  admit  to  citizenship  some  of 
their  perioeci ;  and  at  Athens,  when,  after  frequent  de 
feats  of  their  infantry  in  the  times  of  the  Peloponnesian 
War,  the  notables  were  reduced  in  number,  because  the 
soldiers  had  to  be  taken  from  the  roll  of  citizens. 
Revolutions  arise  from  this  cause  in  democracies  as  well 
as  in  other  forms  of  government,  but  not  to  so  great  an 
extent.  When  the  rich  grow  numerous  or  properties 
increase,  the  form  of  government  changes  into  an  oli 
garchy  or  a  government  of  families.  Forms  of  govern 
ment  also  change — sometimes  even  without  revolution, 
owing  to  election  contests,  as  at  Hersea  (where,  instead 
of  electing  their  magistrates,  they  took  them  by  lot,  be 
cause  the  electors  were  in  the  habit  of  choosing  their 
own  partisans) ;  or  owing  to  carelessness,  when  disloyal 
persons  are  allowed  to  find  their  way  into  the  highest 
offices,  as  at  Oreum,  where,  upon  the  accession  of 
Heracleodorus  to  office,  the  oligarchy  was  overthrown, 
and  changed  by  him  into  a  constitutional  and  demo- 
cratical  government. 

"Another  cause  of  revolution  is  difference  of  races 
which  do  not  at  once  acquire  a  common  spirit;  for  a 
state  is  not  the  growth  of  a  day,  neither  is  it  a  multitude 
brought  together  by  accident.  Hence  the  reception  of 
strangers  in  colonies,  either  at  the  time  of  their  founda 
tion  or  afterwards,  has  generally  produced  revolution ; 
for  example,  the  Achseans  who  joined  the  Troezenians 
in  the  foundation  of  Sybaris,  being  the  more  numerous, 


238  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

afterwards  expelled  them;  hence  the  curse  fell  upon 
Sybaris.  At  Thurii  the  Sybarites  quarreled  with  their 
fellow-colonists;  thinking  that  the  land  belonged  to 
them,  they  wanted  too  much  of  it  and  were  driven  out. 
At  Byzantium  the  new  colonists  were  detected  in  a  con 
spiracy,  and  were  expelled  by  force  of  arms;  the  people 
of  Antissa,  who  had  received  the  Chian  exiles,  fought 
with  them,  and  drove  them  out ;  and  the  Zancleans,  after 
having  received  the  Samians,  were  driven  by  them  out 
of  their  own  city.  The  citizens  of  Apollonia  on  the 
Euxine,  after  the  introduction  of  a  fresh  body  of  colon 
ists,  had  a  revolution ;  the  Syracusans,  after  the  expul 
sion  of  their  tyrants,  having  admitted  strangers  and 
mercenaries  to  the  rights  of  citizenship,  quarreled  and 
came  to  blows;  the  people  of  Amphipolis,  having  re 
ceived  Chalcidian  colonists,  were  nearly  all  expelled  by 
them. 

"Now,  in  oligarchies  the  masses  make  revolution  under 
the  idea  that  they  are  unjustly  treated,  becau.se,  as  I  said 
before,  they  are  equals,  and  have  not  an  equal  share,  and 
in  democracies  the  notables  revolt,  because  they  are  not 
equals,  and  yet  have  only  an  equal  share. 

"Again,  the  situation  of  cities  is  a  cause  of  revolution 
when  the  country  is  not  naturally  adapted  to  preserve 
the  unity  of  the  state.  For  example,  the  Chytrians  at 
Clazomenae  did  not  agree  with  the  people  of  the  island  ; 
and  the  people  of  Colophon  quarreled  with  the  Notians ; 
at  Athens,  too,  the  inhabitants  of  the  Piraeus  are  more 
democratic  than  those  who  live  in  the  city.  For  just  as 
in  war,  the  impediment  of  a  ditch,  though  ever  so  small, 
may  break  a  regiment,  so  every  cause  of  difference,  how 
ever  slight,  makes  a  breach  in  a  city.  The  greatest 
opposition  is  confessedly  that  of  virtue  and  vice ;  next 
comes  that  of  wealth  and  poverty ;  and  there  are  other 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  239 

antagonistic  elements,  greater  or  less,  of  which  one  is 
this  difference  of  place. 

"  Governments  also  change  into  oligarchy  or  into  de 
mocracy  or  into  a  constitutional  government,  because 
the  magistrates,  or  some  other  section  of  the  state,  in 
crease  in  power  or  renown.  Thus  at  Athens  the  reputa 
tion  gained  by  the  court  of  the  Areopagus,  in  the  Persian 
War,  seemed  to  tighten  the  reins  of  government.  On 
the  other  hand,  the  victory  of  Salamis,  which  was  gained 
by  the  common  people  who  served  in  the  fleet,  and  won 
for  the  Athenians  the  empire  of  the  sea,  strengthened 
the  democracy.  At  Argos,  the  notables,  having  dis 
tinguished  themselves  against  the  Lacedaemonians  in  the 
battle  of  Mantinea,  attempted  to  put  down  the  democracy. 
At  Syracuse,  the  people  having  been  the  chief  authors 
of  the  victory  in  the  war  with  the  Athenians,  changed 
the  constitutional  government  into  democracy.  At 
Chalcis,  the  people,  uniting  with  the  notables,  killed 
Phoxus  the  tyrant,  and  then  seized  the  government.  At 
Ambracia,  the  people,  in  like  manner,  having  joined 
with  the  conspirators  in  expelling  the  tyrant  Periander, 
transferred  the  government  to  themselves.  And  gen 
erally,  it  should  be  remembered  that  those  who  have 
secured  power  to  the  state,  whether  private  citizens,  or 
magistrates,  or  tribes,  or  any  other  part  or  section  of  the 
state,  are  apt  to  cause  revolutions.  For  either  envy  of 
their  greatness  draws  others  into  rebellion,  or  they  them 
selves,  in  their  pride  of  superiority,  are  unwilling  to 
remain  on  a  level  with  others. 

"  Revolutions  break  out  when  opposite  parties,  e.g.,  the 
rich  and  the  poor,  are  equally  balanced,  and  there  is 
little  or  nothing  between  them ;  for,  if  either  party  were 
manifestly  superior,  the  other  would  not  risk  an  attack 
upon  them.  And,  for  this  reason,  those  who  are  eminent 


240  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

in  virtue  do  not  stir  up  insurrections,  being  always  a 
minority.  Such  are  the  beginnings  and  causes  of  the 
disturbances  and  revolutions  to  which  every  form  of 
government  is  liable. 

"Revolutions  in  democracies  are  generally  caused  by 
the  intemperance  of  demagogues,  who  either  in  their 
private  capacity  lay  information  against  rich  men  until 
they  compel  them  to  combine,  (for  a  common  danger 
unites  even  the  bitterest  enemies),  or  coming  forward  in 
public  they  stir  up  the  people  against  them.  The  truth 
of  this  remark  is  proved  by  a  variety  of  examples.  At 
Cos  the  democracy  was  overthrown  because  wicked 
demagogues  arose,  and  the  notables  combined.  At 
Rhodes  the  demagogues  not  only  provided  pay  for  the 
multitude,  but  prevented  them  from  making  good  to  the 
trierarchs  the  sums  which  had  been  expended  by  them ; 
and  they,  in  consequence  of  the  suits  which  were  brought 
against  them,  were  compelled  to  combine  and  put  down 
the  democracy.  The  democracy  at  Heraclea  was  over 
thrown  shortly  after  the  foundation  of  the  colony  by  the 
injustice  of  the  demagogues,  which  drove  out  the 
notables,  who  came  back  in  a  body  and  put  an  end  to 
the  democracy.  Much  in  the  same  manner  the  de 
mocracy  at  Megara  was  overturned ;  there  the  dema 
gogues  drove  out  many  of  the  notables  in  order  that 
they  might  be  able  to  confiscate  their  property.  At 
length  the  exiles,  becoming  numerous,  returned,  and 
engaging  and  defeating  the  people,  established  an  oli 
garchy.  .  The  same  thing  happened  with  the  democracy 
of  Cyme  which  was  overthrown  by  Thrasymachus. 
And  we  may  observe  that  in  most  states  the  changes 
have  been  of  this  character.  For  sometimes  the  dema 
gogues,  in  order  to  curry  favor  with  the  people,  wrong 
the  notables  and  so  force  them  to  combine;  either  they 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  241 

make  a  division  of  their  property,  or  diminish  their  in 
comes  by  the  imposition  of  public  services,  and  some 
times  they  bring  accusations  against  the  rich  that  they 
may  have  their  wealth  to  confiscate. 

"Of  old,  the  demagogue  was  also  a  general,  and  then 
democracies  changed  into  tyrannies.  Most  of  the  ancient 
tyrants  were  originally  demagogues.  They  are  not  so 
now,  but  they  were  then ;  and  the  reason  is,  that  they 
were  generals  and  not  orators,  for  oratory  had  not  yet 
come  into  fashion.  Whereas  in  our  day,  when  the  art 
of  rhetoric  has  made  such  progress,  the  orators  lead  the 
people,  but  their  ignorance  of  military  matters  prevents 
them  from  usurping  power ;  at  any  rate  instances  to  the 
contrary  are  few  and  slight.  Formerly  tyrannies  were 
more  common  than  they  now  are,  because  great  power 
was  often  placed  in  the  hands  of  individuals;  thus  a 
tyranny  arose  at  Miletus  out  of  the  office  of  the  Prytanis, 
who  had  supreme  authority  in  many  important  matters. 
Moreover,  in  those  days,  when  cities  were  not  large,  the 
people  dwelt  in  the  fields,  busy  at  their  work ;  and  their 
chiefs,  if  they  possessed  any  military  talent,  seized  the 
opportunity,  and  winning  the  confidence  of  the  masses 
by  professing  their  hatred  of  the  wealthy,  they  succeeded 
in  obtaining  the  tyranny.  Thus  at  Athens  Peisistratus 
led  a  faction  against  the  men  of  the  plain,  and  Theagenes 
at  Megara  slaughtered  the  cattle  of  the  wealthy,  which 
he  found  by  the  river  side  where  they  put  them  to  graze. 
Dionysius,  again,  was  thought  worthy  of  the  tyranny 
because  he  denounced  Daphnaeus  and  the  rich;  his 
enmity  to  the  notables  won  for  him  the  confidence  of 
the  people.  Changes  also  take  place  from  the  ancient 
to  the  latest  form  of  democracy ;  for  where  there  is  a 
popular  election  of  the  magistrates  and  no  property 
qualification,  the  aspirants  for  office  get  hold  of  the 


242  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

people,  and  contrive  at  last  even  to  set  them  above  the 
laws.  A  more  or  less  complete  cure  for  this  state  of 
things  is  for  the  separate  tribes,  and  not  the  whole  people, 
to  elect  the  magistrates. 

"  These  are  the  principal  causes  of  revolutions  in  de 
mocracies." 


EXTRACTS  FROM  ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS. 

BOOK  VI. 
DEMOCRACY  ANALYZED  AND  COMMENDED. 

"The  basis  of  a  democratic  state  is  liberty;  which  ac 
cording  to  the  common  opinion  of  men,  can  only  be  en 
joyed  in  such  a  state; — this  they  affirm  to  be  the  great 
end  of  every  democracy.  One  principle  of  liberty  is  for 
all  to  rule  and  be  ruled  in  turn,  and  indeed  democratic 
justice  is  the  application  of  numerical  not  proportionate 
equality;  whence  it  follows  that  the  majority  must  be 
supreme,  and  that  whatever  the  majority  approve  must 
be  the  end  and  the  just.  Every  citizen,  it  is  said,  must 
have  equality,  and  therefore  in  a  democracy  the  poor 
have  more  power  than  the  rich,  because  there  are  more 
of  them,  and  the  will  of  the  majority  is  supreme.  This, 
then,  is  one  note  of  liberty  which  all  democrats  affirm  to 
be  the  principle  of  their  state.  Another  is  that  a  man 
should  live  as  he  likes.  This,  they  say,  is  the  privilege 
of  a  freeman,  and,  on  the  other  hand,  not  to  live  as  a 
man  likes  is  the  mark  of  a  slave.  This  is  the  second 
characteristic  of  democracy,  whence  has  arisen  the  claim 
of  men  to  be  ruled  by  none,  if  possible,  or,  if  this  is  im 
possible,  to  rule  and  be  ruled  in  turn ;  and  so  it  coincides 
with  the  freedom  based  upon  equality  (which  was  the 

first  characteristic.) 

(243) 


244  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"These  are  points  common  to  all  democracies;  but 
democracy  and  demos  in  their  truest  form  are  based  upon 
the  recognized  principle  of  democratic  justice,  that  all 
should  count  equally  ;  for  equality  implies  that  the  rich 
should  have  no  more  share  in  the  government  than  the 
poor,  and  should  not  be  the  only  rulers,  but  that  all 
should  rule  equally  according  to  their  numbers.  And 
in  this  way  men  think  that  they  will  secure  equality  and 
freedom  in  their  state. 

"Next  comes  the  question,  how  is  this  equality  to  be 
obtained?  Is  the  qualification  to  be  so  distributed  that 
five  hundred  rich  shall  be  equal  to  a  thousand  poor  ? 
and  shall  we  give  the  thousand  a  power  equal  to  that  of 
the  five  hundred?  or,  if  this  is  not  to  be  the  mode,  ought 
we,  still  retaining  the  same  ratio,  to  take  equal  numbers 
from  each  and  give  them  the  control  of  the  elections 
and  of  the  courts  ? — Which,  according  to  the  democratical 
notion,  is  the  juster  form  of  the  constitution, — this  or 
one  based  on  numbers  only  ?  Democrats  say  that  justice 
is  that  to  which  the  majority  agree,  oligarchs  that  to 
which  the  wealthier  class;  in  their  opinion  the  decision 
should  be  given  according  to  the  amount  of  property. 
In  both  principles  there  is  some  inequality  and  injustice. 
For  if  justice  is  the  will  of  the  few,  any  one  person  who 
has  more  wrealth  than  all  the  rest  of  his  class  put  to 
gether,  ought,  upon  the  oligarchical  principle,  to  have 
the  sole  power — but  this  would  be  tyranny;  or  if  justice 
is  the  will  of  the  majority,  as  I  was  before  saying,  they 
will  unjustly  confiscate  the  property  of  the  wealthy 
minority.  To  find  a  principle  of  equality  in  which  they 
both  agree  we  must  inquire  into  their  respective  ideas  of 
justice. 

44  Now  they  agree  in  saying  that  whatever  is  decided  by 
the  majority  of  the  citizens  is  to  be  deemed  law.  Grant- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  245 

ed : — but  not  without  some  reserve ;  since  there  are  two 
classes  out  of  which  a  state  is  composed, — the  poor  and 
the  rich, — that  is  to  be  deemed  law,  on  which  both  or 
the  greater  part  of  both  agree ;  and  if  they  disagree,  that 
which  is  approved  by  the  greater  number,  and  by  those 
who  have  the  higher  qualification.  For  example,  sup 
pose  that  there  are  ten  rich  and  twenty  poor,  and  some 
measure  is  approved  by  six  of  the  rich  and  is  dis 
approved  by  fifteen  of  the  poor,  and  the  remaining  four 
of  the  rich  join  with  the  party  of  the  poor,  and  the  re 
maining  five  of  the  poor  with  that  of  the  rich ;  in  such 
a  case  the  will  of  those  whose  qualifications,  when  both 
sides  are  added  up,  are  the  greatest,  should  prevail.  If 
they  turn  out  to  be  equal,  there  is  no  greater  difficulty 
than  at  present,  when,  if  the  assembly  or  the  courts  are 
divided,  recourse  is  had  to  the  lot,  or  to  some  similar 
expedient.  But,  although  it  may  be  difficult  in  theory 
to  know  what  is  just  and  equal,  the  practical  difficulty 
of  inducing  those  to  forbear  who  can,  if  they  like,  en 
croach  is  far  greater,  for  the  weaker  are  always  asking 
for  equality  and  justice,  but  the  stronger  care  for  none 
of  these  things. 

"Of  the  four  kinds  of  democracy,  as  was  said  in  the 
previous  discussion,  the  best  is  that  which  comes  first  in 
order;  it  is  also  the  oldest  of  them  all.  I  am  speaking 
of  them  according  to  the  natural  classification  of  their 
inhabitants.  For  the  best  material  of  democracy  is  an 
agricultural  population ;  there  is  no  difficulty  in  forming 
a  democracy  where  the  mass  of  the  people  live  by  agri 
culture  or  tending  of  cattle.  Being  poor,  they  have  no 
leisure,  and  therefore  do  not  often  attend  the  assembly, 
and  not  having  the  necessaries  of  life  they  are  always  at 
work,  and  do  not  covet  the  property  of  others.  Indeed, 
they  find  their  employment  pleasanter  than  the  cares  of 


246  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

government  or  office  where  no  great  gains  can  be  made 
out  of  them,  for  the  many  are  more  desirous  of  gain 
than  of  honor.  A  proof  is  that  even  the  ancient  tyrannies 
were  patiently  endured  by  them,  as  they  still  endure  oli 
garchies,  if  they  are  allowed  to  work  and  are  not  de 
prived  of  their  property ;  for  some  of  them  grow  quickly 
rich  and  the  others  are  well  enough  off.  Moreover, 
they  have  the  power  of  electing  the  magistrates  and 
calling  them  to  account ;  their  ambition,  if  they  have 
any,  is  thus  satisfied;  and  in  some  democracies,  although 
they  do  not  all  share  in  the  appointment  of  offices,  ex 
cept  through  representatives  elected  in  turn  out  of  the 
whole  people,  as  at  Mantinea; — yet,  if  they  have  the 
power  of  deliberating,  the  many  are  contented.  Even 
this  form  of  government  may  be  regarded  as  a  de 
mocracy,  and  was  such  at  Mantinea.  Hence  it  is  both 
expedient  and  customary  in  such  a  democracy  that  all 
should  elect  to  offices,  and  conduct  scrutinies,  and  sit  in 
the  law-courts,  but  that  the  great  offices  should  be  filled 
up  by  election  and  from  persons  having  a  qualification; 
the  greater  requiring  a  greater  qualification,  or,  if  there 
be  no  offices  for  which  a  qualification  is  required,  then 
those  who  are  marked  out  by  special  ability  should  be 
appointed.  Under  such  a  form  of  government  the 
citizens  are  sure  to  be  governed  well,  (for  the  offices  will 
always  be  held  by  the  best  persons;  the  people  are  will 
ing  enough  to  elect  them  and  are  not  jealous  of  the 
good).  The  good  and  the  notables  will  then  be  satisfied, 
for  they  will  not  be  governed  by  men  who  are  their  in 
feriors,  and  the  persons  elected  will  rule  justly,  because 
others  will  call  them  to  account.  Every  man  should  be 
responsible  to  others,  nor  should  any  one  be  allowed  to 
do  just  as  he  pleases;  for  where  absolute  freedom  is  al 
lowed  there  is  nothing  to  restrain  the  evil  which  is  in- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  247 

herent  in  every  man.  But  the  principle  of  responsibility 
secures  that  which  is  the  greatest  good  in  states ;  the 
right  persons  rule  and  are  prevented  from  doing  wrong, 
and  the  people  have  their  due.  It  is  evident  that  this  is 
the  best  kind  of  democracy,  and  why?  Because  the 
people  are  drawn  from  a  certain  class. 

"Next  best  to  an  agricultural,  and  in  many  respects 
similar,  are  a  pastoral  people,  who  live  by  their  flocks ; 
they  are  the  best  trained  of  any  for  war,  robust  in  body 
and  able  to  camp  out,  the  people  of  whom  other  de 
mocracies  consist  are  far  inferior  to  them,  for  their  life 
is  inferior ;  there  is  no  room  for  moral  excellence  in  any 
of  their  employments,  whether  they  be  mechanics  or 
traders  or  laborers. 

"The  last  form  of  democracy,  that  in  which  all  .share 
alike,  is  one  which  cannot  be  borne  by  all  states,  and 
will  not  last  long  unless  well  regulated  by  laws  and 
customs.  The  more  general  causes  which  tend  to  de 
stroy  this  or  other  kinds  of  government  have  now  been 
pretty  fully  considered.  In  order  to  constitute  such  a 
democracy  and  strengthen  the  people,  the  leaders  have 
been  in  the  habit  of  including  as  many  as  they  can,  and 
making  citizens  not  only  of  those  who  are  legitimate, 
but  even  of  the  illegitimate,  and  of  those  who  have  only 
one  parent,  a  citizen,  whether  father  or  mother;  for 
nothing  of  this  sort  comes  amiss  to  such  a  democracy. 
This  is  the  way  in  which  demagogues  proceed.  Where 
as  the  right  thing  would  be  to  make  no  more  additions 
when  the  number  of  the  commonalty  exceeds  that  of 
the  notables  or  of  the  middle  class, — beyond  this  not  to 
go.  When  in  excess  of  this  point  the  state  becomes  dis 
orderly,  and  the  notables  grow  excited  and  impatient  of 
the  democracy,  as  in  the  insurrection  at  Cyrene ;  for  no 
notice  is  taken  of  a  little  evil,  but  when  it  increases  it 
strikes  the  eye. 


248  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"  The  mere  establishment  of  a  democracy  is  not  the 
only  or  principal  business  of  the  legislator,  or  of  those 
who  wish  to  create  such  a  state,  for  any  state,  however 
badly  constituted,  may  last  one,  two,  or  three  days;  a  far 
greater  difficulty  is  the  preservation  of  it.  The  legis 
lator  should  therefore  endeavor  to  have  a  firm  foundation 
according  to  the  principles  already  laid  down  concerning 
the  preservation  and  destruction  of  states;  he  should 
guard  against  the  destructive  elements,  and  should  make 
laws,  whether  written  or  unwritten,  which  will  contain 
all  the  preservatives  of  states.  He  must  not  think  the 
truly  democratical  or  oligarchical  measure  to  be  that 
which  will  give  the  greatest  amount  of  democracy  or  oli 
garchy,  but  that  which  will  make  them  last  longest.  The 
demagogues  of  our  own  day  often  get  property  confis 
cated  in  the  law-courts  to  please  the  people.  But  those 
who  have  the  welfare  of  the  state  at  heart  should  counter 
act  them,  and  make  a  law  that  the  property  of  the  con 
demned  which  goes  into  the  treasury,  should  not  be 
public  but  sacred.  Thus  offenders  will  be  as  much 
afraid,  for  they  will  be  punished  all  the  same,  and  the 
people,  having  nothing  to  gain,  will  not  be  so  ready  to 
condemn  the  accused.  Care  should  also  be  taken  that 
state  trials  are  as  few  as  possible,  and  heavy  penalties 
should  be  inflicted  on  those  who  bring  groundless  accu 
sations  ;  for  it  is  the  practice  to  indict,  not  members  of 
the  popular  party,  but  the  notables,  although  the  citizens 
ought  to  be  all  equally  attached  to  the  state,  or  at  any 
rate  should  not  regard  their  rulers  as  enemies. 

"  Now,  since  in  the  last  and  worst  form  of  democracy 
the  citizens  are  very  numerous,  and  can  hardly  be  made 
to  assemble  unless  they  are  paid,  and  to  pay  them  when 
there  are  no  revenues,  presses  hardly  upon  the  notables 
(for  the  money  must  be  obtained  by  a  property-tax  and 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  249 

confiscations  and  corrupt  practices  of  the  courts,  things 
which  have  before  now  overthrown  many  democracies)  ; 
where,  I  say,  there  are  no  revenues,  the  government 
should  hold  few  assemblies,  and  the  law-courts  should 
consist  of  many  persons,  but  sit  for  a  few  days  only. 
This  system  has  two  advantages :  first,  the  rich  do  not 
fear  the  expense,  even  although  they  are  unpaid  them 
selves  when  the  poor  are  paid  :  and  secondly,  causes  are 
better  tried,  for  wealthy  persons,  although  they  do  not 
like  to  be  long  absent  from  their  own  affairs,  do  not  mind 
going  for  a  few  days  to  the  law-courts.  Where  there 
are  revenues  the  demagogues  should  not  be  allowed, 
after  their  manner,  to  distribute  the  surplus;  the  poor 
are  always  receiving  and  always  wanting  more  and  more, 
for  such  help  is  like  water  poured  into  a  leaky  cask. 
Yet  the  true  friend  of  the  people  should  see  that  they  be 
not  too  poor,  for  extreme  poverty  lowers  the  character 
of  the  democracy ;  measures  also  should  be  taken  which 
will  give  them  lasting  prosperity ;  and  as  this  is  equalty 
the  interest  of  all  classes,  the  proceeds  of  the  public 
revenues  should  be  accumulated  and  distributed  among 
them,  if  possible,  in  such  quantities  as  may  enable  them 
to  purchase  a  little  farm,  or  at  any  rate,  make  a  begin 
ning  in  trade  and  husbandry.  And  if  this  benevolence 
cannot  be  extended  to  all,  money  should  be  distributed 
in  turn  according  to  tribes  or  other  divisions,  and  in  the 
meantime  the  rich  should  pay  the  fee  for  the  attendance 
of  the  poor  at  the  necessary  assemblies ;  and  should  in 
return  be  excused  from  useless  public  services.  By 
administering  the  state  in  this  spirit  the  Carthaginians 
retain  the  affections  of  the  people;  their  policy  is  from 
time  to  time  to  send  some  of  them  into  their  dependent 
towns,  where  they  grow  rich.  It  is  also  worthy  of  a 
generous  and  sensible  nobility  to  divide  the  poor  amongst 


250  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

them,  and  give  them  the  means  of  going  to  work.  The 
example  of  the  people  of  Tarentum  is  also  well  deserv 
ing  of  imitation,  for,  by  sharing  the  use  of  their  own 
property  with  the  poor,  they  gain  their  good  will. 
Moreover,  they  divide  all  their  offices  into  two  classes, 
one-half  of  them  being  elected  by  vote,  the  other  by  lot; 
the  latter,  that  the  people  may  participate  in  them,  and 
the  former,  that  the  state  may  be  better  administered. 
A  like  result  may  be  gained  by  dividing  the  same  offices, 
so  as  to  have  two  classes  of  magistrates,  one  chosen  by 
vote,  the  other  by  lot." 


EXTRACTS  FROM  ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS. 

BOOK  VII. 
THE  BEST  LIFE  FOR  INDIVIDUALS  AND  STATES. 

"He  who  would  duly  enquire  about  the  best  form 
of  a  state  ought  first  to  determine  which  is  the  most  eli 
gible  life. 

"Assuming  that  enough  has  been  already  said  in 
exoteric  discourses  concerning  the  best  life,  we  will  now 
only  repeat  the  statements  contained  in  them.  Certainly 
no  one  will  dispute  the  propriety  of  that  partition  of 
goods  which  separates  them  into  three  classes,  viz.,  ex 
ternal  goods,  goods  of  the  body,  arid  goods  of  the  soul, 
or  deny  that  the  happy  man  must  have  all  three.  These 
propositions  are  universally  acknowledged  as  soon  as 
they  are  uttered,  but  men  differ  about  the  degree  or 
relative  superiority  of  this  or  that  good.  Some  think 
that  a  very  moderate  amount  of  virtue  is  enough,  but  set 
no  limit  to  their  desires  of  wealth,  property,  power,  repu 
tation,  and  the  like.  To  whom  we  reply  by  an  appeal 
to  facts,  which  easily  prove  that  mankind  do  not  ac 
quire  or  preserve  virtue  by  the  help  of  external  goods, 
but  external  goods  by  the  help  of  virtue,  and  that  happi 
ness,  whether  consisting  in  pleasure  or  virtue,  or  both, 
is  more  often  found  with  those  who  are  most  highly 

(251) 


252  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

cultivated  in  their  mind  and  in  their  character,  and  have 
only  a  moderate  share  of  external  goods,  than  among 
those  who  possess  external  goods  to  a  useless  extent, 
but  are  deficient  in  higher  qualities ;  and  this  is  not  only 
matter  of  experience,  but,  if  reflected  upon,  will  easily 
appear  to  be  in  accordance  with  reason.  For,  \vhereas 
external  goods  have  a  limit,  like  any  other  instrument, 
and  all  things  useful  are  of  such  a  nature  that  where 
there  is  too  much  of  them  they  must  either  do  harm,  or 
at  any  rate  be  of  no  use  to  their  possessors,  every  good 
of  the  vSoul,  the  greater  it  is,  is  also  of  greater  use,  if  the 
epithet,  useful  as  well  as  noble,  is  appropriate  to  such 
subjects. 

"Let  us  acknowledge  then  that  each  one  has  just  so 
much  of  happiness  as  he  has  of  virtue  and  wisdom,  and 
of  virtuous  and  wise  action.  God  is  a  witness  to  us  of 
this  truth,  for  he  is  happy  and  blessed,  not  by  reason  of 
any  external  good,  but  in  himself  and  by  reason  of  his 
own  nature.  And  herein  of  necessity  lies  the  difference 
between  good  fortune  and  happiness;  for  external  goods 
come  of  themselves,  and  chance  is  the  author  of  them, 
but  no  one  is  just  or  temperate  by  or  through  chance. 
In  like  manner,  and  by  a  similar  train  of  argument,  the 
happy  state  may  be  shown  to  be  that  which  is  (morally) 
best,  and  which  acts  rightly ;  and  rightly  it  cannot  act 
without  doing  right  actions,  and  neither  individual  or 
state  can  do  right  actions  without  virtue  and  wisdom. 
Thus  the  courage,  justice,  and  wisdom  of  a  state  have 
the  same  form  and  nature  as  the  qualities  which  give 
the  individual  who  possesses  them  the  name  of  just,  wise, 
or  temperate. 

<(  Let  us  assume  then  that  the  best  life,  both  for  in 
dividuals  and  states,  is  the  life  of  virtue,  having  external 
goods  enough  for  the  performance  of  good  actions.  If 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  253 

there  are  any  who  controvert  our  assertion,  we  will  in 
this  treatise  pass  them  over,  and  consider  their  objec 
tions  hereafter. 

"  Now  it  is  evident  that  the  form  of  government  is  best 
in  which  every  man,  whoever  he  is,  can  act  for  the  best 
and  live  happily.  But  even  those  who  agree  in  thinking 
that  the  life  of  virtue  is  the  most  eligible,  raise  a  ques 
tion,  whether  the  life  of  business  and  politics  is,  or  is 
not,  more  eligible  than  one  which  is  wholly  independent 
of  external  goods,  I  mean  than  a  contemplative  life, 
which  by  some  is  maintained  to  be  the  only  one  worthy 
of  a  philosopher.  For  these  two  lives — the  life  of  the 
philosopher  and  the  life  of  the  statesman — appear  to 
have  been  preferred  by  those  who  have  been  most  keen 
in  the  pursuit  of  virtue,  both  in  our  own  and  in  other 
ages.  Which  is  the  better  is  a  question  of  no  small 
moment ;  for  the  wise  man,  like  the  wise  state,  will  nec 
essarily  regulate  his  life  according  to  the  best  end. 
There  are  some  who  think  that  while  a  despotic  rule  over 
others  is  the  greatest  injustice,  to  exercise  a  constitu 
tional  rule  over  them,  even  though  not  unjust,  is  a  great 
impediment  to  a  man's  individual  well-being.  Others 
take  an  opposite  view ;  they  maintain  that  the  true  life 
of  man  is  the  practical  and  political,  and  that  every 
virtue  admits  of  being  practiced,  quite  as  much  by  states 
men  and  rulers  as  by  private  individuals.  Others,  again, 
are  of  opinion  that  arbitrary  and  tyrannical  rule  alone 
consists  with  happiness ;  indeed,  in  some  states  the  en 
tire  aim  of  the  laws  is  to  give  men  despotic  power  over 
their  neighbors.  And,  therefore,  although  in  most  cities 
the  laws  may  be  said  general \y  to  be  in  a  chaotic  state, 
still,  if  they  aim  at  anything,  they  aim  at  the  mainte 
nance  of  power :  thus  in  LacedLemon  and  Crete  the  system 
of  education  and  the  greater  part  of  the  laws  are  framed 


254  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

with  a  view  to  war.  And  in  all  nations  which  are  able 
to  gratify  their  ambition,  military  power  is  held  in 
esteem,  for  example,  among  the  Scythians  and  Persians 
and  Thracians  and  Celts.  In  some  nations  there  are 
even  laws  tending  to  stimulate  the  war-like  virtues,  as 
at  Carthage,  where  we  are  told  that  men  obtain  the 
honor  of  wearing  as  many  rings  as  they  have  served 
campaigns.  There  was  once  a  law  in  Macedonia  that 
he  who  had  not  killed  an  enemy  should  wear  a  halter, 
and  among  the  Scythians  no  one  who  had  not  slain  his 
man  was  allowed  to  drink  out  of  the  cup  which  was 
handed  round  at  a  certain  feast.  Among  the  Iberians, 
,  a  war-like  nation,  the  number  of  enemies  whom  a  man 
has  slain  is  indicated  by  the  number  of  obelisks  which 
are  fixed  in  the  earth  round  his  tomb ;  and  there  are 
numerous  practices  among  other  nations  of  a  like  kind, 
some  of  them  established  by  law  and  others  by  custom. 
Yet  to  a  reflecting  mind  it  must  appear  very  strange  that 
the  statesman  should  be  always  considering  how  he  can 
dominate  and  tyrannize  over  others,  whether  they  will 
or  not.  How  can  that  which  is  not  even  lawful  be  the 
business  of  the  statesman  or  the  legislator?  Unlawful 
it  certainly  is  to  rule  without  regard  to  justice,  for  there 
may  be  might  where  there  is  no  right.  The  other  arts 
and  sciences  offer  no  parallel ;  a  physician  is  not  ex 
pected  to  persuade  or  coerce  his  patients,  nor  a  pilot  the 
passengers  in  his  ship.  Yet  many  appear  to  think  that 
a  despotic  government  is  a  true  political  form,  and  what 
men  affirm  to  be  unjust  and  inexpedient  in  their  own 
case  they  are  not  ashamed  of  practising  towards  others; 
they  demand  justice  for  themselves,  but  where  other  men 
are  concerned  they  care  nothing  about  it.  Such  be 
havior  is  irrational;  unless  the  one  party  is  born  to 
command,  and  the  other  born  to  serve,  in  which  case 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  255 

men  have  a  right  to  command,  not  indeed  all  their 
fellows,  but  only  those  who  are  intended  to  be  subjects ; 
just  as  we  ought  not  to  hunt  mankind,  whether  for  food 
or  sacrifice,  but  only  the  animals  which  are  intended  for 
food  or  sacrifice,  that  is  to  say,  such  wild  animals  as  are 
eatable.  And  surely  there  may  be  a  city  happy  in  isola 
tion,  which  we  will  assume  to  be  well-governed  (for  it 
is  quite  possible  that  a  city  thus  isolated  might  be  well- 
administered  and  have  good  laws)  ;  but  such  a  city 
would  not  be  constituted  with  any  view  to  war  or  the 
conquest  of  enemies, — all  that  sort  of  thing  must  be  ex 
cluded.  Hence  we  see  very  plainly  that  warlike  pur 
suits,  although  generally  to  be  deemed  honorable,  are 
not  the  supreme  end  of  all  things,  but  only  means.  And 
the  good  lawgiver  should  enquire  how  states  and  races 
of  men  and  communities  may  participate  in  a  good  life, 
and  in  the  happiness  which  is  attainable  by  them.  His 
enactments  will  not  be  always  the  same ;  and  where  there 
are  neighbors  he  will  have  to  deal  with  them  according 
to  their  characters,  and  to  see  what  duties  are  to  be  per 
formed  towards  each.  The  end  at  which  the  best  form 
of  government  should  aim  may  be  properly  made  a  matter 
of  future  consideration. 

"  Let  us  now  address  those  who,  while  they  agree  that 
the  life  of  virtue  is  the  most  eligible,  differ  about  the 
manner  of  practising  it.  For  some  renounce  political 
power,  and  think  that  the  life  of  the  freeman  is  different 
from  the  life  of  the  statesman  and  the  best  of  all ;  but 
others  think  the  life  of  the  statesman  best.  The  argu 
ment  of  the  latter  is,  that  he  who  does  nothing,  cannot 
do  well,  and  that  virtuous  activity  is  identical  with  happi 
ness.  To  both  we  say :  '  You  are  partly  right  and 
partly  wrong.'  The  first  class  are  right  in  affirming 
that  the  life  of  the  freeman  is  better  than  the  life  of  the 


256  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

despot;  for  there  is  nothing  grand  or  noble  in  having 
the  use  of  a  slave,  in  so  far  as  he  is  a  slave  ;  or  in  issuing 
commands  about  necessary  things.  But  it  is  an  error  to 
suppose  that  every  sort  of  rule  is  despotic  like  that  of  a 
master  over  slaves,  for  there  is  as  great  a  difference  be 
tween  the  rule  over  freemen  and  the  rule  over  slaves,  as 
there  is  between  slavery  by  nature  and  freedom  by  na 
ture,  about  which  I  have  said  enough  at  the  commence 
ment  of  this  treatise.  And  it  is  equally  a  mistake  to 
place  inactivity  above  action,  for  happiness  is  activity, 
and  the  actions  of  the  just  and  wise  are  the  realization 
of  much  that  is  noble. 

"  But  perhaps  some  one,  accepting  these  premises,  may 
still  maintain  that  supreme  power  is  the  best  of  all  things, 
because  the  possessors  of  it  are  able  to  perform  the  great 
est  number  of  noble  actions.  If  so,  the  man  who  is  able 
to  rule,  instead  of  giving  up  anything  to  his  neighbor, 
ought  rather  to  take  away  his  power;  and  the  father 
should  make  no  account  of  his  son,  nor  the  son  of  his 
father,  nor  friend  of  friend ;  they  should  not  bestow  a 
thought  on  one  another  in  comparison  with  this  higher 
object,  for  the  best  is  the  most  eligible,  and  '  doing  weir 
is  the  best.  There  might  be  some  truth  in  such  a  view 
if  we  assume  that  robbers  and  plunderers  attain  the  chief 
good.  But  this  can  never  be;  and  hence  we  infer  the 
view  to  be  false.  For  the  actions  of  a  ruler  cannot  really 
be  honorable,  unless  he  is  as  much  superior  to  other  men 
as  a  husband  is  to  a  wife,  or  a  father  to  his  children,  or 
a  master  to  his  slaves.  And  therefore  he  who  violates 
the  law  can  never  recover  by  any  success,  however  great, 
what  he  has  already  lost  in  departing  from  virtue.  For 
equals  share  alike  in  the  honorable  and  the  just,  as  is 
just  and  equal.  But  that  the  unequal  should  be  given 
to  equals,  and  the  unlike  to  those  who  are  like,  is  con- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  257 

trary  to  nature,  and  nothing  which  is  contrary  to  nature 
is  good.  If,  therefore,  there  is  any  one  superior  in  virtue 
and  in  the  power  of  performing  the  best  actions,  him  we 
ought  to  follow  and  obey,  but  he  must  have  the  capacity 
for  action  as  well  as  virtue. 

"  If  we  are  right  in  our  view,  and  happiness  is  assumed 
to  be  virtuous  activity,  the  active  life  will  be  the  best, 
both  for  the  city  collectively,  and  for  individuals.  Not 
that  a  life  of  action  must  necessarily  have  relation  to 
others,  as  some  persons  think,  nor  are  these  ideas  only 
to  be  regarded  as  practical  which  are  pursued  for  the 
sake  of  practical  results,  but  much  more  the  thoughts 
and  contemplations  which  are  independent  and  complete 
in  themselves;  since  virtuous  activity,  and  therefore 
action,  is  an  end,  and  even  in  the  case  of  external  actions, 
the  directing  mind  is  most  truly  said  to  act.  Neither, 
again,  is  it  necessary  that  states  which  are  cut  off  from 
others  and  choose  to  live  alone,  should  be  inactive;  for 
there  may  be  activity  also  in  the  parts ;  there  are  many 
ways  in  which  the  members  of  a  state  act  upon  one  an 
other.  The  same  thing  is  equally  true  of  every  indi 
vidual.  If  this  were  otherwise,  God  and  the  universe, 
who  have  no  external  actions  over  and  above  their  own 
energies,  would  be  far  enough  from  perfection.  Hence 
it  is  evident  that  the  same  life  is  best  for  each  individual, 
and  for  states,  and  for  mankind  collectively. 

'"Thus  far  by  way  of  introduction.  In  what  has  pre 
ceded  I  have  discussed  other  forms  of  government ;  in 
what  remains  the  first  point  to  be  considered  is  what 
should  be  the  conditions  of  the  ideal  or  perfect  state;  fojr 
the  perfect  state  cannot  exist  without  a  due  supply  of 
the  means  of  life.  And  therefore  we  must  pre-suppose 
many  purely  imaginary  conditions,  but  nothing  impos 
sible.  There  will  be,  a  certain  number  of  citizens,  a 


0) 


258  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

country  in  which  to  place  them,  and  the  like.  As  the 
weaver  or  shipbuilder  or  any  other  artisan  must  have 
the  material  proper  for  his  work  (and  in  proportion  as 
this  is  better  prepared,  so  will  the  result  of  his  art  be 
nobler),  so  the  statesman  or  legislator  must  also  have 
the  materials  suited  to  him. 

"First  among  the  materials  required  by  the  statesman 
is  population :  he  will  consider  what  should  be  the  num 
ber  and  character  of  the  citizens,  and  then  what  should 
be  the  size  and  character  of  the  country.  Most  persons 
think  that  a  state  in  order  to  be  happy,  ought  to  be 
large:  but  even  if  they  are  right,  they  have  no  idea  what 
is  a  large  and  what  is  a  small  state. 

"  Moreover,  experience  shows  that  a  very  populous 
city  can  rarely,  if  ever,  be  well  governed ;  since  all  cities 
which  have  a  reputation  for  good  government  have  a 
limit  of  population.  We  may  argue  on  grounds  of  rea 
son,  and  the  same  result  will  follow.  For  law  is  order, 
and  good  law  is  good  order  ;  but  a  very  great  multitude 
cannot  be  orderly ;  to  introduce  order  into  the  unlimited 
is  the  work  of  a  divine  power — of  such  a  power  as  holds 
together  the  universe.  Beauty  is  realized  in  number 
and  magnitude,  and  the  state  which  combines  magnitude 
with  good  order,  must  necessarily  be  the  most  beautiful. 
To  the  size  of  states  there  is  a  limit,  as  there  is  to  other 
things,  plants,  animals,  implements ;  for  none  of  these 
retain  their  natural  power  when  they  are  too  large  or  too 
small,  but  they  either  wholly  lose  their  nature  or  are 
spoiled. 

"  A  state  then  only  begins  to  exist  when  it  has  attained 
a  population  sufficient  for  a  good  life  in  the  political 
community :  it  may  indeed  somewhat  exceed  this  number. 
But,  as  I  was  saying,  there  must  be  a  limit.  What 
should  be  the  limit  will  be  easily  ascertained  by  experi- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  259 

ence.  For  both  governors  and  governed  have  duties  to 
be  performed ;  the  special  functions  of  a  governor  are 
to  command  and  to  judge.  But  if  the  citizens  of  a  state 
are  to  judge  and  to  distribute  offices  according  to  merit, 
then  they  must  know  each  other's  characters ;  where  they 
do  not  possess  this  knowledge,  both  the  election  to  offices 
and  the  decision  of  lawsuits  will  go  wrong.  When  the 
population  is  very  large  they  are  manifestly  settled  at 
haphazard,  which  clearly  ought  not  to  be.  Besides,  in 
an  overpopulous  state  foreigners  and  metics  will  readily 
acquire  the  rights  of  citizens,  for  who  will  find  them  out  ? 
Clearly  then  the  best  limit  of  the  population  of  a  state  is 
the  largest  number  which  suffices  for  the  purposes  of 
life,  and  can  be  taken  in  at  a  single  view.  Enough  con 
cerning  the  size  of  a  city. 

"  Having  spoken  of  the  number  of  the  citizens,  we  will 
proceed  to  speak  of  what  should  be  their  character. 
This  is  a  subject  which  can  be  easily  understood  by  any 
one  who  casts  his  eye  on  the  more  celebrated  states  of 
Hellas,  and  generally  on  the  distribution  of  races  in  the 
habitable  world.  Those  who  live  in  a  cold  climate  and 
in  (northern)  Europe  are  full  of  spirit,  but  wanting  in 
intelligence  and  skill;  and  therefore  they  keep  their 
freedom,  but  have  no  political  organization,  and  are  in 
capable  of  ruling  over  others.  Whereas  the  natives  of 
Asia  are  intelligent  and  inventive,  but  they  are  wanting 
in  spirit,  and  therefore  they  are  always  in  a  state  of  sub 
jection  and  slavery.  But  the  Hellenic  race,  which  is 
situated  between  them,  is  likewise  intermediate  in  charac 
ter,  being  high-spirited  and  also  intelligent.  Hence  it 
continues  free,  and  is  the  best-governed  of  any  nation, 
and,  if  it  could  be  formed  into  one  state,  would  be  able 
to  rule  the  world. 

"  We  must  see  also,  how  jmany  things  are  indispensible 


260  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

to  the  existence  of  a  state,  for  what  we  call  the  parts  of 
a  state  will  be  found  among  them.  Let  us  then  enumer 
ate  the^functions  of  a  state,  and  we  shall  easily  elicit 
what  we  want : 

"First,  there  must  be  jood ;  secondly,  arts,  for  life  re 
quires  many  instruments ;  thirdly,  there  must  be  jarrgs, 
for  the  members  of  a  community  have  need  of  them  in 
order  to  maintain  authority  both  against  disobedient 
subjects  and  against  external  assailants ;  fourthly,  there 
must  be  a  certain  amount  of  revenue,  both  for  internal 
needs,  and  for  the  purposes  of  war ;  fifthly,  or  rather 
first,  there  must  be  a  care  of  religion,  which  is  commonly 
called  worship;  sixthly,  and  most  necessary  of  all,  there 
must  be  a  power  of  deciding  what  is  for  the  public  inter 
est,  and  what  is  just  in  men's  dealings  with  one  another. 

"  These  are  the  things  which  every  state  may  be  said 
to  need.  For  a  state  is  not  a  mere  aggregate  of  persons, 
but  a  union  of  them  sufficing  for  the  purposes  of  life; 
and  if  any  of  these  things  be  wanting,  it  is  simply  im 
possible  that  the  community  can  be  self-sufficing.  A 
state  then  should  be  framed  with  a  view  to  the  fulfil 
ment  of  these  functions. 

"  It  is  no  new  or  recent  discovery  of  political  philoso 
phers,  that  the  state  ought  to  be  divided  into  classes,  and 
that  the  warriors  should  be  separated  from  the  husband 
men.  The  system  has  continued  in  Egypt  and  in  Crete 
to  this  day,  and  was  established,  as  tradition  says,  by  a 
law  of  Sesostris  in  Egypt  and  of  Minos  in  Crete.  The 
institution  of  common  tables  also  appears  to  be  of 
ancient  date,  being  in  Crete  as  old  as  the  reign  of  Minos, 
and  in  Italy  far  older.  The  Italian  historians  say  that 
there  was  a  certain  Italus  king  of  Oenotria,  from  whom 
the  Oenotrians  were  called  Italians,  and  who  gave  the 
name  of  Italy  to  the  promontory  of  Europe  lying  be- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  261 

tween  the  Scylletic  and  Lametic  Gulfs,  which  are  distant 
from  one  another  only  half-a-day's  journey.  They  say 
that  this  Italus  converted  the  Oenotrians  from  shepherds 
into  husbandmen,  and  besides  other  laws  which  he  gave 
them,  was  the  founder  of  their  common  meals ;  even  in 
our  day  some  who  are  derived  from  him  retain  this  in 
stitution  and  certain  other  laws  of  his.  On  the  side  of 
Italy  towards  Tyrrhenia  dwelt  the  Opici,  who  are  now, 
as  of  old,  called  Ausones ;  and  on  the  side  towards 
lapygia  and  the  Ionian  Gulf,  in  the  district  called 
Syrtis,  the  Chones,  who  are  likewise  of  Oenotrian  race. 
From  this  part  of  the  world  originally  came  the  institu 
tion  of  common  tables ;  the  separation  into  castes  (which 
was  much  older)  from  Egypt,  for  the  reign  of  Sesostris 
is  of  far  greater  antiquity  than  that  of  Minos.  It  is  true, 
indeed,  that  these,  and  many  other  things,  have  been  in 
vented  several  times  over  in  the  course  of  ages,  or  rather, 
times  without  number ;  for  necessity  may  be  supposed 
to  have  taught  men  the  inventions  which  were  abso 
lutely  required,  and  when  these  were  provided,  it  was 
natural  that  other  things  which  would  adorn  and  enrich 
life  should  grow  up  by  degrees.  And  we  may  infer  that 
in  political  institutions  the  same  rule  holds.  Egypt 
witnesses  to  the  antiquity  of  all  things,  for  the  Egyptians 
appear  to  be  of  all  people  the  most  ancient ;  and  they 
have  laws  and  a  regular  constitution  (existing  from 
time  immemorial).  We  should  therefore  make  the  best  use 
of  what  has  been  already  discovered,  and  try  to  supply 
defects. 

"Special  care  should  be  taken  of  the  health  of  the  in 
habitants,  which  will  depend  chiefly  on  the  healthiness 
of  the  locality  and  of  the  quarter  to  which  they  are  ex 
posed,  and  secondly,  on  the  use  of  pure  water ;  this  latter 
point  is  by  no  means  a  secondary  consideration.  For 


262  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers., 

the  elements  which  we  use  most  and  oftenest  for  the 
support  of  the  body  contribute  most  to  health,  and 
among  these  are  water  and  air.  Wherefore,  in  all  wise 
states,  if  there  is  a  want  of  pure  water,  and  the  supply, 
is  not  all  equally  good,  the  drinking  water  ought  to  be 
separated  from  that  which  is  used  for  other  purposes. 

"  Returning  to  the  constitution  itself,  let  us  seek  to 
determine  out  of  what  and  what  sort  of  elements  the 
state  which  is  to  be  happy  and  well-governed  should  be 
\  composed.  There  are  two  things  in  which  all  well-being 
consists,  one  of  them  is  the  choice  of  a  right  end  and 
aim  of  action,  and  the  other  the  discovery  of  the  actions 
which  are  means  towards  it ;  for  the  means  and  the  end 
may  agree  or  disagree.  Sometimes  the  right  end  is  set 
before  men,  but  in  practice  they  fail  to  attain  it ;  in  other 
cases  they  are  successful  in  all  the  means,  but  they  pro 
pose  to  themselves  a  bad  end,  and  sometimes  they  fail  in 
both. 

"  The  happiness  and  well-being  which  all  men  mani 
festly  desire,  some  have  the  power  of  attaining,  but  to 
others,  from  some  accident  or  defect  of  nature,  the  at 
tainment  of  them  is  not  granted ;  for  a  good  life  requires 
a  supply  of  external  goods,  in  a  less  degree  when  men 
are  in  a  good  state,  in  a  greater  degree  when  the)7  are  in 
a  lower  state.  Others  again,  who  possess  the  condition 
of  happiness,  go  utterly  wrong  from  the  first  in  the  pur 
suit  of  it.  But  since  our  object  is  to  discover  the  best 
form  of  government,  that,  namely,  under  which  a  city 
will  be  best  governed,  and  since  the  city  is  best  governed 
which  has  the  greatest  opportunity  of  obtaining  happi 
ness,  it  is  evident  that  we  must  clearly  ascertain  the 
nature  of  happiness. 

"We  have  said  in  the  Ethics,  if  the  arguments  there 
adduced  are  of  any  value,  that  happiness  is  the  realiza- 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  263 

tion  and  perfect  exercise  of  virtue,  and  this  not  con 
ditional,  but  absolute.  And  I  used  the  term  '  conditional ' 
to  express  that  which  is  indispensible,  and  'absolute'  to 
express  that  which  is  good  in  itself.  Take  the  case  of 
just  actions;  just  punishments  and  chastisements  do  in 
deed  spring  from  a  good  principle,  but  they  are  good 
only  because  we  cannot  do  without  them — it  would  be 
better  that  neither  individuals  nor  states  should  need 
anything  of  the  sort — but  actions  which  aim  at  honor 
and  advantage  are  absolutely  the  best.  The  conditional 
action  is  only  the  choice  of  a  lesser  evil ;  whereas  these 
are  the  foundation  and  creation  of  good.  A  good  man 
may  make  the  best  even  of  poverty  and  disease,  and  the 
other  ills  of  life ;  but  he  can  only  obtain  happiness  under 
the  opposite  conditions.  As  we  have  already  said  in  the 
Ethics,  the  good  man  is  he  to  whom,  because  he  is 
virtuous,  the  absolute  good  is  his  good.  It  is  also  plain 
that  his  use  of  other  goods  must  be  virtuous  and  in  the 
absolute  sense  good.  This  makes  men  fancy  that  ex 
ternal  goods  are  the  cause  of  happiness,  yet  we  might  as 
well  say  that  a  brilliant  performance  on  the  lyre  was  to 
be  attributed  to  the  instrument  and  not  to  the  skill  of 
the  performer. 

"It  follows  then  from  what  has  been  said  that  some 
things  the  legislator  must  find  ready  to  his  hand  in  a 
state,  others  he  must  provide.  And  therefore  we  can 
only  say  :  May  our  state  be  constituted  in  such  a  manner 
as  to  be  blessed  with  the  goods  of  which  fortune  disposes 
(for  we  acknowledge  her  power) :  whereas  virtue  and 
goodness  in  the  state  are  not  a  matter  of  chance  but  the 
result  of  knowledge  and  purpose.  A  city  can  be  virtu 
ous  only  when  the  citizens  who  have  a  share  in  the 
government  are  virtuous,  and  in  our  state  all  the  citizens 
share  in  the  government ;  let  us  then  enquire  how  a  man 


264  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

jbecomes  virtuous.  For  even  if  we  could  suppose  all  the 
citizens  to  be  virtuous,  and  not  each  of  them,  yet  the 
latter  would  be  better,  for  in  the  virtue  of  each  the  virtue 
of  all  is  involved. 

"  There  are  three  things  which  make  men  good  and 
virtuous :  these  are  nature,  habit,  reason.  In  the  first 
place,  every  one  must  be  born  a  man  and  not  some  other 
animal ;  in  the  second  place,  he  must  have  a  certain 
character,  both  of  body  and  soul.  But  some  qualities 
there  is  no  use  in  having  at  birth,  for  they  are  altered 
by  habit,  and  there  are  some  gifts  of  nature  which  may 
be  turned  by  habit  to  good  or  bad.  Most  animals  lead 
a  life  of  nature,  although  in  lesser  particulars  some 
are  influenced  by  habit  as  well.  Man  has  reason  in  ad 
dition,  and  man  only.  Wherefore  nature,  habit,  reason, 
must  be  in  harmony  with  one  another ;  (for  they  do  not 
always  agree)  ;  men  do  many  things  against  habit  and 
nature,  if  reason  persuades  them  that  they  ought.  We 
have  already  determined  what  natures  are  likely  to  be 
most  easily  moulded  by  the  hands  of  the  legislator.  All 
else  is  the  work  of  education ;  we  learn  some  things  by 
habit  and  some  by  instruction. 

"  Now  the  soul  of  man  is  divided  into  two  parts,  one 
of  which  has  reason  in  itself,  and  the  other,  not  having 
reason  in  itself,  is  able  to  obey  reason.  And  we  call  a 
man  good  because  he  has  the  virtues  of  these  two  parts. 
In  which  of  them  the  end  is  more  likely  to  be  found  is 
no  matter  of  doubt  to  those  who  adopt  our  division  ;  for 
in  the  world  both  of  nature  and  of  art  the  inferior  always 
exists  for  the  sake  of  the  better  or  superior,  and  the 
better  or  superior  is  that  which  has  reason.  The  reason 
too,  in  our  ordinary  way  of  speaking,  is  divided  into  two 
parts,  for  there  is  a  practical  and  a  speculative  reason, 
and  there  must  be  a  corresponding  division  of  actions ; 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  265 

the  actions  of  the  naturally  better  principle  are  to  be 
preferred  by  those  who  have  it  in  their  power  to  attain 
to  both  or  to  all,  for  that  is  always  to  every  one  the  most 
eligible  which  is  the  highest  attainable  by  him.  The 
whole  of  life  is  further  divided  into  two  parts,  business 
and  leisure,  war  and  peace,  and  all  actions  into  those 
which  are  necessary  and  useful,  and  those  which  are 
honorable.  And  the  preference  given  to  one  or  the  other 
class  of  actions  must  necessarily  be  like  the  preference 
given  to  one  or  other  part  of  the  soul  and  its  actions 
over  the  other;  there  must  be  war  for  the  sake  of  peace, 
business  for  the  sake  of  leisure,  things  useful  and  neces 
sary  for  the  sake  of  things  honorable.  All  these  points 
the  statesman  shoiild  keep  in  view  when  he  frames  his 
laws ;  he  should  consider  the  parts  of  the  soul  and  their 
functions,  and  above  all,  the  better  and  the  end ;  he 
should  also  remember  the  diversities  of  human  lives  and 
actions.  For  men  must  engage  in  business  and  go  to 
war,  but  leisure  and  peace  are  better ;  they  must  do  what 
is  necessary  and  useful,  but  what  is  honorable  is  better. 
In  such  principles  children  and  persons  of  every  age 
which  requires  education  should  be  trained.  Whereas 
even  the  Hellenes  of  the  present  day,  who  are  reputed  to 
be  best  governed,  and  the  legislators  who  gave  them 
their  constitutions,  do  not  appear  to  have  framed  their 
governments  with  a  regard  to  the  best  end,  or  to  have 
given  them  laws  and  education  with  a  view  to  all  the 
virtues,  but  in  a  vulgar  spirit  have  fallen  back  on  those 
which  promised  to  be  more  useful  and  profitable.  Many 
modern  writers  have  taken  a  similar  view;  they  com 
mend  the  Lacedaemonian  constitution,  and  praise  the 
legislator  for  making  conquest  and  war  his  sole  aim,  a 
doctrine  which  may  be  refuted  by  argument  and  has  long 
ago  been  refuted  by  facts.  For  most  men  desire  empire 


266  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

in  the  hope  of  accumulating  the  goods  of  fortune ;  and 
on  this  ground  Thibron  and  all  those  who  have  written 
about  the  Lacedaemonian  constitution  have  praised  their 
legislator,  because  the  Lacedaemonians,  by  a  training  in 
hardships,  gained  great  power.  But  surely  they  are  not 
a  happy  people  now  that  their  empire  has  passed  away, 
nor  was  their  legislator  right.  How  ridiculous  is  the 
result,  if,  while  they  are  continuing  in  the  observance  of 
his  laws,  and  no  one  interferes  with  them,  they  have  lost 
the  better  part  of  life.  These  writers  further  err  about 
the  sort  of  government  which  the  legislator  should  ap 
prove,  for  the  government  of  freemen  is  noble,  and  im 
plies  more  virtue  than  despotic  government.  Neither  is 
a  city  to  be  deemed  happy  or  a  legislator  to  be  praised 
because  he  trains  his  citizens  to  conquer  and  obtain 
dominion  over  their  neighbors,  for  there  is  great  evil  in 
this.  On  a  similar  principle  any  citizen  who  could, 
would  obviously  try  to  obtain  the  power  in  his  own 
state, — the  crime  which  the  Lacedaemonians  accuse  King 
Pausanias  of  attempting,  although  he  had  so  great 
honor  already.  No  such  principle  and  no  law  having 
this  object,  is  either  statesmanlike  or  useful  or  right. 
For  the  same  things  are  best  both  for  individuals  and 
for  states,  and  these  are  the  things  which  the  legislator 
ought  to  implant  in  the  minds  of  his  citizens.  Neither 
should  men  study  war  with  a  view  to  the  enslavement  of 
those  who  do  not  deserve  to  be  enslaved ;  but  first  of  all 
they  should  provide  against  their  enslavement,  and  in 
the  second  place  obtain  empire  for  the  good  of  the  gov 
erned,  and  not  for  the  sake  of  exercising  a  general 
despotism,  and  in  the  third  place  they  should  seek  to  be 
masters  only  over  those  who  deserve  to  be  slaves. 
Facts,  as  well  as  arguments,  prove  that  the  legislator 
should  direct  all  his  military  and  other  measures  to  the 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  267 

provision  of  leisure  and  the  establishment  of  peace.  For 
most  of  these  military  states  are  safe  only  while  they  are 
at  war,  but  fall  when  they  have  acquired  their  empire  ; 
like  unused  iron  they  rust  in  time  of  peace.  And  for 
this  the  legislator  is  to  blame,  he  never  having  taught 
them  how  to  lead  the  life  of  peace. 

"  Since  the  end  of  individuals  and  of  states  is  the  same, 
the  end  of  the  best  man  and  of  the  best  state  must  also 
[be  the  same;  it  is  therefore  evident  that  there  ought  to 
jexist  in  both  of  them  the  virtues  of  leisure,  for  peace,  as 
has  been  often  repeated,  is  the  end  of  war,  and  leisure  of 
toil.  But  leisure  and  cultivation  may  be  promoted,  not 
only  by  those  virtues  which  are  practised  in  leisure,  but 
also  by  some  of  those  which  are  useful  to  business. 
For  many  necessaries  of  life  have  to  be  supplied  before 
we  can  have  leisure.  Therefore  a  city  must  be  tem 
perate  and  brave,  and  able  to  endure:  for  truly,  as  the 
proverb  says,  '  There  is  no  leisure  for  slaves,'  and  those 
who  cannot  face  danger  like  men  are  the  slaves  of  any 
invader.  Courage  and  endurance  are  required  for  busi 
ness  and  philosophy  for  leisure,  temperance  and  justice 
for  both,  more  especially  in  times  of  peace  and  leisure, 
for  war  compels  men  to  be  just  and  temperate,  whereas 
the  enjoyment  of  good  fortune  and  the  leisure  \vhich 
comes  with  peace  tends  to  make  them  insolent.  Those, 
then,  who  seem  to  be  the  best-off,  and  to  be  in  the  pos 
session  of  every  good,  have  special  need  of  justice  and 
temperance — for  example,  those  (if  such  there  be,  as  the 
poets  say),  who  dwell  in  the  Islands  of  the  Blest ;  they 
above  all  will  need  philosophy  and  temperance  and  jus 
tice,  and  all  the  more  the  more  leisure  they  have,  living 
in  the  midst  of  abundance.  There  is  no  difficulty  in 
seeing  why  the  state  that  would  be  happy  and  good  ought 
to  have  these  virtues.  If  it  be  disgraceful  in  men  not 


268  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

to  be  able  to  use  the  goods  of  life,  it  is  peculiarly  dis 
graceful  not  to  be  able  to  use  them  in  time  of  peace, — to 
show  excellent  qualities  in  action  and  war,  and  when 
they  have  peace  and  leisure  to  be  no  better  than  slaves. 
Wherefore,  we  should  not  practice  virtue  after  the  man 
ner  of  the  Lacedaemonians.  For  they,  while  agreeing 
with  other  men  in  their  conception  of  the  highest  goods, 
differ  from  the  rest  of  mankind  in  thinking  that  they 
are  to  be  obtained  by  the  practice  of  a  single  virtue. 
And  since  these  goods  and  the  enjoyment  of  them  are 
clearly  greater  than  the  enjoyment  derived  from  the 
virtues  of  which  they  are  the  end,  we  must  now  consider 
how  and  by  what  means  they  are  to  be  attained. 

"We  have  already  determined  that  nature  and  habit 
and  reason  are  required,  and  what  should  be  the  charac 
ter  of  the  citizens  has  also  been  defined  by  us.  But  we 
have  still  to  consider  whether  the  training  of  early  life 
is  to  be  that  of  reason  or  habit,  for  these  two  must  accord, 
and  when  in  accord  they  will  then  form  the  best  of  har 
monies.  Reason  may  make  mistakes  and  fail  in  attain 
ing  the  highest  ideal  of  life,  and  there  may  be  a  like  evil 
influence  of  habit.  Thus  much  is  clear  in  the  first  place, 
that,  as  in  all  other  things,  birth  implies  some  antecedent 
principle,  and  that  the  end  of  anything  has  a  beginning 
in  some  former  end.  Now,  in  men  reason  and  mind  are 
the  end  towards  which  nature  strives,  so  that  the  birth 
and  moral  discipline  of  the  citizens  ought  to  be  ordered 
with  a  view  to  them.  In  the  second  place,  as  the  soul 
and  body  are  two,  we  see  also  that  there  are  two  parts 
of  the  soul,  the  rational  and  the  irrational,  and  two  cor 
responding  states — reason  and  appetite.  And  as  the 
body  is  prior  in  order  of  generation  to  the  soul,  so  the 
irrational  is  prior  to  the  rational.  The  proof  is  that 
anger  and  will  and  desire  are  implanted  in  children  from 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  269 

their  very  birth,  but  reason  and  understanding,  are  de 
veloped  as  they  grow  older.  Wherefore,  the  care  of  the 
body  ought  to  precede  that  of  the  soul,  and  the  training 
of  the  appetitive  part  should  follow ;  none  the  less  our 
care  of  it  must  be  for  the  sake  of  the  reason,  and  our  care 
of  the  body  for  the  sake  of  the  soul.  Since  the  legislator 
should  begin  by  considering  how  the  frames  of  the 
children  whom  he  is  rearing  may  be  as  good  as  possible, 
his  first  care  will  be  about  marriage — at  what  age  should 
his  citizens  marry,  and  who  are  fit  to  marry  ? 

"  Women  should  marry  when  they  are  about  eighteen 
years  of  age,  and  men  at  seven  and  thirty;  then  they  are 
in  the  prime  of  life,  and  the  decline  in  the  powers  of  both 
will  coincide.  Further,  the  children,  if  their  birth  takes 
place  at  the  time  that  may  reasonably  be  expected,  will 
succeed  in  their  prime,  when  the  fathers  are  already  in 
the  decline  of  life,  and  have  nearly  reached  their  term  of 
three-score  years  and  t'en. 

"  What  constitution  in  the  parent  is  most  advantageous 
to  the  offspring  is  a  subject  which  we  will  hereafter  con 
sider  when  we  speak  of  the  education  of  children,  and 
we  will  only  make  a  few  general  remarks  at  present. 
The  temperament  of  an  athlete  is  not  suited  to  the  life 
of  a  citizen,  or  to  health,  or  to  the  procreation  of  children, 
any  more  than  the  valetudinarian  or  exhausted  constitu 
tion,  but  one  which  is  in  a  mean  between  them.  A 
man's  constitution  should  be  inured  to  labor,  but  not  to 
labor  which  is  excessive  or  of  one  sort  only,  such  as  is 
practiced  by  athletes;  he  should  be  capable  of  all  the 
actions  of  a  freeman.  These  remarks  apply  equally  to 
both  parents. 

"After  the  children  have  been  born,  the  manner  of 
rearing  of  them  may  be  supposed  to  have  a  great  effect 
on  their  bodily  strength.  To  accustom  children  to  the 


270  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

cold  from  their  earliest  years  is  also  an  excellent  practice, 
which  greatly  conduces  to  health,  and  hardens  them  for 
military  service.  Hence  many  barbarians  have  a  custom 
of  plunging  their  children  at  birth  into  a  cold  stream: 
others,  like  the  Celts,  clothe  them  in  a  light  wrapper 
only.  For  human  nature  should  be  early  habituated  to 
endure  all  which  by  habit  it  can  be  made  to  endure ;  but 
the  process  must  be  gradual.  And  children,  from  their 
natural  warmth,  may  be  easily  trained  to  bear  cold.  Such 
care  should  attend  them  in  the  first  stage  of  life. 

"  The  next  period  lasts  to  the  age  of  five;  during  this 
no  demand  should  be  made  upon  the  child  for  study  or 
labor,  lest  its  growth  be  impeded  ;  and  there  should  be 
sufficient  motion  to  prevent  the  limbs  from  being  inactive. 
This  can  be  secured,  among  other  ways,  by  amusement, 
but  the  amusement  should  not  be  vulgar  or  tiring  or 
riotous.  The  Directors  of  Education,  as  they  are  termed, 
should  be  careful  what  tales  or  stories  the  children  hear, 
for  the  sports  of  children  are  designed  to  prepare  the 
way  for  the  business  of  later  life,  and  should  be  for  the 
most  part  imitations  of  the  occupations  which  they  will 
hereafter  pursue  in  earnest.  Those  are  wrong  who  (like 
Plato)  in  the  Laws  attempt  to  check  the  loud  crying  and 
screaming  of  children,  for  these  contribute  towards  their 
growth,  and,  in  a  like  manner,  exercise  their  bodies. 
Straining  the  voice  has  an  effect  similar  to  that  produced 
by  the  retention  of  the  breath  in  violent  exertions.  Be 
sides  other  duties,  the  Directors  of  Education  should 
have  an  eye  to  their  bringing  up,  and  should  take  care 
that  they  are  left  as  little  as  possible  with  slaves.  For 
until  they  are  seven  years  old  they  must  live  at  home; 
and  therefore,  even  at  this  early  age,  all  that  is  mean  and 
low  should  be  banished  from  their  sight  and  hearing. 
Indeed,  there  is  nothing  which  the  legislator  should  be 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  271 

more  careful  to  drive  away  than  indecency  of  speech, 
for  the  light  utterance  of  shameful  words  is  akin  to 
shameful  actions.     The  young  especially  should  never 
be  allowed  to  repeat  or  hear  anything  of  the  sort.     A 
freeman  who  is  found  saying  or  doing  what  is  forbidden, 
if  he  be  too  young  as  yet  to  have  the  privilege  of  a  place 
at  the  public  tables,  should  be  disgraced  and  beaten,  and 
an  elder  person  degraded  as  his  slavish  conduct  deserves. 
And  since  we  do  not  allow  improper  language,  clearly 
we  should  also  banish  pictures  or  tales  which  are  in 
decent.     Let  the  rulers  take  care  that  there  be  no  image 
or  picture  representing  unseemly  actions,  except  in  the 
temples  of  those  Gods  at  whose  festivals  the  law  permits 
even  ribaldry,  and  whom  the  law  also  permits  to  be  wor 
shipped  by  persons  of  mature  age  on  behalf  of  them 
selves,  their  children,  and  their  wives.     But  the  legis 
lator  should  not  allow  youth  to  be  hearers  of  satirical 
Iambic  verses  or  spectators  of  comedy  until  they  are  of 
an  age  to  sit  at  the  public  tables  and  to  drink  strong 
wine;  by  that   time  education  will   have   armed  them 
against  the  evil  influences  of  such  representations. 

"And  therefore,  youth  should  be  kept  strangers  to  all 
that  is  bad,  and  especially  all  things  which  suggest  vice 
or  hate.  When  the  five  years  have  passed  away,  during 
the  two  following  years  they  must  look  on  at  the  pursuits 
which  they  are  hereafter  to  learn.  There  are  two  periods 
of  life  into  which  education  has  to  be  divided,  from  seven 
to  the  age  of  puberty,  and  onwards  to  the  age  of  one 
and  twenty.  (The  poets)  who  divide  ages  by  sevens, 
are  not  always  right :  we  should  rather  adhere  to  the 
divisions  actually  made  by  nature  ;  for  the  deficiencies 
of  nature  are  what  art  and  education  seek  to  fill  up." 


EXTRACTS  FROM  ARISTOTLE'S  POLITICS. 

BOOK  VIII. 

PUBLIC  SCHOOLS  AND  LIBERAL  EDUCATION, 
GYMNASTICS,  Music  AND  MORALS. 

"  And  since  the  whole  city  has  one  end,  it  is  manifest 
that  education  should  be  one  and  the  same  for  all,  and 
that  it  should  be  public,  and  not  private, — not  as  at 
present,  when  every  one  looks  after  his  own  children 
separately,  and  gives  them  .separate  instruction  of  the 
sort  which  he  thinks  best ;  the  training  in  things  which 
are  of  common  interest  should  be  the  same  for  all. 
Neither  must  wre  suppose  that  any  one  of  the  citizens  be 
longs  to  himself,  for  they  all  belong  to  the  state,  and  are 
each  of  them  a  part  of  the  state,  and  the  care  of  each 
part  is  inseparable  from  the  care  of  the  whole.  In  this 
particular  the  Lacedaemonians  are  to  be  praised,  for  they 
take  the  greatest  pains  about  their  children,  and  make 
education  the  business  of  the  state. 

''That  education  should  be  regulated  by  law  and 
should  be  an  affair  of  state  is  not  to  be  denied,  but  what 
should  be  the  character  of  this  public  education,  and 
how  young  persons  should  be  educated,  are  questions 
which  remain  to  be  considered.  For  mankind  are  by 

no  means  agreed  about  the  things  to  be  taught,  whether 

(272) 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  273 

we  look  to  virtue  or  the  best  life.  Neither  is  it  clear 
whether  education  is  more  concerned  with  intellectual 
or  with  moral  virtue.  The  existing  practice  is  perplex 
ing  ;  no  one  knows  on  what  principle  we  should  proceed — 
should  the  useful  in  life,  or  should  virtue,  or  should  the 
higher  knowledge,  be  the  aim  of  our  training;  all  three 
opinions  have  been  entertained.  Again,  about  the 
means  there  is  no  agreement ;  for  different  persons,  start 
ing  with  different  ideas  about  the  nature  of  virtue, 
naturally  disagree  about  the  practice  of  it.  There  can 
be  no  doubt  that  children  should  be  taught  those  use 
ful  things  which  are  really  necessary,  but  not  all  things ; 
for  occupations  are  divided  into  liberal  and  illiberal ;  and 
to  young  children  should  be  imparted  only  such  kinds 
of  knowledge  as  will  be  useful  to  them  without  vulgar 
izing  them.  And  any  occupation,  art  or  science,  which 
makes  the  body  or  soul  or  mind  of  the  freeman  less  fit 
for  the  practice  or  exercise  of  virtue,  is  vulgar;  where 
fore,  we  call  those  arts  vulgar  which  tend  to  deform  the 
body,  and  likewise  all  paid  employments,  for  they  ab 
sorb  and  degrade  the  mind.  There  are  also  some  liberal 
arts  quite  proper  for  a  freeman  to  acquire,  but  only  in  a 
certain  degree,  and  if  he  attend  to  them  too  closely,  in 
order  to  attain  perfection  in  them,  the  same  evil  effects 
will  follow.  The  object,  also,  which  a  man  sets  before 
him  makes  a  great  difference ;  if  he  does  or  learns  any 
thing  for  his  own  sake  or  for  the  sake  of  his  friends,  or 
with  a  view  to  excellence,  the  action  will  not  appear 
illiberal  ;  but  if  done  for  the  sake  of  others,  the  very 
same  action  will  be  thought  menial  and  servile.  The 
received  subjects  of  instruction,  as  I  have  already  re 
marked,  are  partly  of  a  liberal  and  partly  of  an  illiberal 
character. 

"The  customary  branches  of  education  are  in  number, 


274  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

four;  they  are — (i)  reading  and  writing,  (2)  gymnastic 
exercises,  (3)  music,  to  which  is  sometimes  added  (4) 
drawing.  Of  these,  reading  and  writing  and  drawing 
are  regarded  as  useful  for  the  purposes  of  life  in  a  variety 
of  ways,  and  gymnastic  exercises  are  thought  to  infuse 
courage.  Concerning  music  a  doubt  may  be  raised — in 
our  own  day  most  men  cultivate  it  for  the  sake  of 
pleasure,  but  originally  it  was  included  in  education, 
because  nature  herself,  as  has  been  often  said,  requires 
that  we  should  be  able,  not  only  to  work  well,  but  to  use 
leisure  well;  for,  as  I  must  repeat  once  and  again,  the 
first  principle  of  all  action  is  leisure.  Both  are  required, 
but  leisure  is  better  than  occupation ;  and  therefore  the 
question  must  be  asked  in  good  earnest,  what  ought  we 
to  do  when  at  leisure?  Clearly  we  ought  not  to  be 
amusing  ourselves,  for  then  amusement  would  be  the  end 
of  life.  But  if  this  is  inconceivable,  and  yet  amid  seri- 
.ous  occupations  amusement  is  needed  more  than  at  other 
times  (for  he  who  is  hard  at  work  has  need  of  relaxation, 
and  amusement  gives  relaxation,  w7hereas  occupation  is 
always  accompanied  with  exertion  and  effort),  at  suitable 
times  we  should  introduce  amusements,  and  they  should 
be  our  medicines,  for  the  emotion  which  they  create  in 
the  soul  is  a  relaxation  and  from  the  pleasure  we  obtain 
rest.  Leisure  of  itself  gives  pleasure  and  happiness  and 
enjoyment  of  life,  which  are  experienced,  not  by  the  busy 
man,  but  by  those  who  have  leisure.  For  he  who  is 
occupied  has  in  view  some  end  which  he  has  not  attained ; 
but  happiness  is  an  end  which  all  men  deem  to  be  ac 
companied  with  pleasure  and  not  with  pain.  This 
pleasure,  however,  is  regarded  differently  by  different 
persons,  and  varies  according  to  the  habit  of  individuals; 
the  pleasure  of  the  best  man  is  the  best,  and  springs  from 
the  noblest  sources.  It  is  clear  then,  that  there  are 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  275 

branches  of  learning  and  education  which  we  must  study 
with  a  view  to  the  enjoyment  of  leisure,  and  these  are 
to  be  valued  for  their  own  sake;  whereas,  those  kinds  of 
knowledge  which  are  useful  in  business  are  to  be  deemed 
necessary,  and  exist  for  the  sake  of  other  things.  And 
therefore  our  fathers  admitted  music  into  education,  not 
on  the  ground  either  of  its  necessity  or  utility,  for  it  is 
not  necessary,  nor  indeed  useful  in  the  same  manner  as 
reading  and  writing,  which  are  useful  in  money-making, 
in  the  management  of  a  household,  in  the  acquisition  of 
knowledge  and  in  political  life,  nor  like  drawing,  useful 
for  a  more  correct  judgment  of  the  works  of  artists,  nor 
again,  like  gymnastics,  which  give  health  and  strength; 
for  neither  of  these  is  to  be  gained  from  music.  There 
remains,  then,  the  use  of  music  for  intellectual  enjoy 
ment  in  leisure;  which  appears  to  have  been  the  reason 
of  its  introduction,  this  being  one  of  the  wa)rs  in  which 
it  is  thought  that  a  freeman  should  pass  his  leisure. 

"Of  those  states  which  in  our  own  day  seem  to  take 
the  greatest  care  of  children,  some  aim  at  producing  in 
them  an  athletic  habit,  but  they  only  injure  their  forms 
and  stunt  their  growth.  Although  the  Lacedaemonians 
have  not  fallen  into  this  mistake,  yet  they  brutalize  their 
children  by  laborious  exercises  which  they  think  will 
make  them  courageous.  But  in  truth,  as  we  have  often 
repeated,  education  should  not  be  exclusively  directed  to 
this  or  to  any  other  single  end.  And  even  if  we  suppose 
the  Lacedaemonians  to  be  right  in  their  end,  they  do  not 
attain  it.  For  among  barbarians  and  among  animals 
courage  is  found  associated,  not  with  the  greatest  ferocity, 
but  with  a  gentle  and  lion-like  temper.  There  are  many 
races  who  are  ready  enough  to  kill  and  eat  men  such  as 
the  Achaeans  and  Heniochi,  who  both  live  about  the 
Black  Sea;  and  there  are  other  inland  tribes,  as  bad  or 


276  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

worse,  who  all  live  by  plunder,  but  have  no  courage.  It 
is  notorious  that  the  Lacedaemonians,  while  they  were 
themselves  assiduous  in  their  laborious  drill,  were  su 
perior  to  others,  but  now  they  are  beaten  both  in  war  and 
gymnastic  exercises.  For  their  ancient  superiority  did 
not  depend  on  their  mode  of  training  their  youth,  but  only 
on  the  circumstance  that  they  trained  them  at  a  time 
when  others  did  not.  Hence  we  may  infer  that  what  is 
noble,  not  what  is  brutal,  should  have  the  first  place;  no 
wolf  or  other  wild  animal  will  face  a  really  noble  danger; 
such  dangers  are  for  the  brave  man.  And  parents  who 
devote  their  children  to  gymnastics  while  they  neglect 
their  necessary  education,  in  reality  vulgarize  them ;  for 
they  make  them  useful  to  the  state  in  one  quality  only, 
and  even  in  this  the  argument  proves  them  to  be  inferior 
to  others.  We  should  judge  the  Lacedaemonians  not 
from  what  they  have  been,  but  from  what  they  are;  for 
now  they  have  rivals  who  compete  with  their  education ; 
formerly  they  had  none. 

"  It  is  an  admitted  principle,  that  gymnastic  exercises 
should  be  employed  in  education,  and  that  for  children 
they  should  be  of  a  lighter  kind,  avoiding  severe 
regimen  or  painful  toil,  lest  the  growth  of  the  body  be 
impaired.  The  evil  of  excessive  training  in  early  years 
is  strikingly  proved  by  the  example  of  the  Olympic 
victors;  for  not  more  than  two  or  three  of  them  have 
gained  a  prize  both  as  boys  and  as  men  ;  their  early  train 
ing  and  severe  gymnastic  exercises  exhausted  their  con 
stitutions.  When  boyhood  is  over,  three  years  should 
be  spent  in  other  studies ;  the  period  of  life  which  follows 
may  then  be  devoted  to  hard  exercise  and  strict  regimen. 
Men  ought  not  to  labor  at  the  same  time  with  their 
minds  and  with  their  bodies ;  for  the  two  kinds  of 
labor  are  opposed  to  one  another,  the  labor  of  the 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  277 

body  impedes  the  mind,  and  the  labor  of  the  mind  the 
body. 

"  Concerning  music  there  are  some  questions  which  we 
have  already  raised ;  these  we  may  now  resume  and  carry 
further. 

"The  first  question  is  whether  music  is  or  is  not  to  be 
a  part  of  education.  Of  the  three  things  mentioned  in 
our  discussion,  which  is  it  ? — Education  or  amusement 
or  intellectual  enjoyment,  for  it  may  be  reckoned  under 
all  three,  and  seems  to  share  in  the  nature  of  all  of  them. 
Amusement  is  for  the  sake  of  relaxation,  and  relaxation 
is  of  necessity  sweet,  for  it  is  the  remedy  of  pain  caused 
by  toil,  and  intellectual  enjoyment  is  universally  acknowl 
edged  to  contain  an  element,  not  only  of  the  noble  but  of 
the  pleasant,  for  happiness  is  made  up  of  both.  All  men 
agree  that  music  is  one  of  the  pleasantest  things,  whether 
with  or  without  song ;  as  Musaeus  says, 

'  Song  is  to  mortals  of  all  things  the  sweetest.' 

"  Hence,  and  with  good  reason  it  is  introduced  into 
social  gatherings  and  entertainments,  because  it  makes 
the  hearts  of  men  glad ;  so  that  on  this  ground  alone  we 
may  assume  that  the  young  ought  to  be  trained  in  it. 
For  innocent  pleasures  are  not  only  in  harmony  with 
the  perfect  end  of  life,  but  they  also  provide  relaxation. 
And  whereas  men  rarely  attain  the  end,  but  often  rest  by 
the  way  and  amuse  themselves,  not  only  with  a  view  to 
some  good,  but  also  for  the  pleasure's  sake,  it  may  be 
well  for  them  at  times  to  find  a  refreshment  in  music. 
It  sometimes  happens  that  men  make  amusement  the 
end,  for  the  end  probably  contains  some  element  of 
pleasure,  though  not  any  ordinary  or  lower  pleasure  ;  but 
they  mistake  the  lower  for  the  higher,  and  in  seeking  for 
the  one  find  the  other,  since  every  pleasure  has  a  like 
ness  to  the  end  of  action.  For  the  end  is  not  eligible, 


278  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

nor  do  the  pleasures  which  we  have  described  exist,  for 
the  sake  of  any  future  good  but  of  the  past,  that  is  to 
say,  they  are  the  alleviation  of  past  toils  and  pains.  And 
we  may  infer  this  to  be  the  reason  why  men  seek  happi 
ness  from  common  pleasures.  But  music  is  pursued, 
not  only  as  an  alleviation  of  past  toil,  but  also  as  pro 
viding  recreation.  And  who  can  say  whether,  having 
this  use,  it  may  not  also  have  a  nobler  one  ?  In  addition 
to  this  common  pleasure,  felt  and  shared  in  by  all  (for 
the  pleasure  given  by  music  is  natural,  and  therefore 
adapted  to  all  ages  and  characters),  may  it  not  have  also 
some  influence  over  the  character  and  the  soul  ?  It  must 
have  such  an  influence  if  characters  are  affected  by  it. 
And  that  they  are  so  affected  is  proved  by  the  power 
which  the  songs  of  Olympus  and  of  many  others  exer 
cise ;  for  beyond  question  they  inspire  enthusiasm,  and 
enthusiasm  is  an  emotion  of  the  ethical  part  of  the  soul. 
Besides,  when  men  hear  imitations,  even  unaccompanied 
by  melody  or  rhythm,  their  feelings  move  in  sympathy. 
Since  then  music  is  a  pleasure,  and  virtue  consists  in 
rejoicing  and  loving  and  hating  aright,  there  is  clearly 
nothing  which  we  are  so  much  concerned  to  acquire  and 
to  cultivate  as  the  power  of  forming  right  judgments, 
and  of  taking  delight  in  good  dispositions  and  noble 
actions.  Rhythm  and  melody  supply  imitations  of  anger 
and  gentleness,  and  also  of  courage  and  temperance,  and 
of  virtues  and  vices  in  general,  which  hardly  fall  short 
of  the  actual  affections,  as  we  know  from  our  own  ex 
perience,  for  in  listening  to  such  strains  our  souls  under 
go  a  change.  The  habit  of  feeling  pleasure  or  pain  at 
mere  representations  is  not  far  removed  from  the  same 
feeling  about  realities  ;  for  example,  if  any  one  delights 
in  the  sight  of  a  statue  for  its  beauty  only,  it  necessarily 
follows  that  the  sight  of  the  original  will  be  pleasant  to 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  279 

him.  No  other  sense,  such  as  taste  or  touch,  has  any 
resemblance  to  moral  qualities ;  in  sight  only  there  is  a 
little,  for  figures  are  to  some  extent  of  a  moral  character, 
and  (so  far)  all  participate  in  the  feeling  about  them. 
Again,  figures  and  colors  are  not  imitations,  but  signs  of 
moral  habits,  indications  which  the  body  gives  of  states 
of  feeling.  The  connection  of  them  with  morals  is  slight, 
but  in  so  far  as  there  is  any,  young  men  should  be  taught 
to  look,  not  at  the  works  of  Pauson,  but  at  those  of 
Polygnotus,  or  any  other  painter  or  statuary  who  ex 
presses  moral  ideas.  On  the  other  hand,  even  in  mere 
melodies  there  is  an  imitation  of  character,  for  the 
musical  modes  differ  essentially  from  one  another,  and 
those  who  hear  them  are  differently  affected  by  each. 
Some  of  them  make  men  sad  and  grave,  like  the  so-called 
Mixolydian,  others  enfeeble  the  mind,  like  the  relaxed 
harmonies,  others,  again,  produce  a  moderate  and  settled 
temper,  which  appears  to  be  the  peculiar  effect  of  the 
Dorian  ;  the  Phrygian  inspires  enthusiasm.  The  whole 
subject  has  been  well  treated  by  philosophical  writers 
on  this  branch  of  education,  and  they  confirm  their 
arguments  by  facts.  The  same  principles  apply  to 
rhythms ;  some  have  a  character  of  rest,  others  of  motion, 
and  of  these  latter  again,  some  have  a  more  vulgar, 
others  a  nobler  movement.  Enough  has  been  said  to 
show  that  music  has  a  power  of  forming  the  character, 
and  should,  therefore,  be  introduced  into  the  education 
of  the  young.  The  study  is  suited  to  the  stage  of  youth, 
for  young  persons  wTill  not,  if  they  can  help,  endure  any 
thing  which  is  not  sweetened  by  pleasure,  and  music  has 
a  natural  sweetness.  There  seems  to  be  in  us  a  sort  of 
affinity  to  harmonies  and  rhythms,  which  makes  some 
philosophers  say  that  the  soul  is  a  harmony,  others,  that 
she  possesses  harmony. 


280  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

"  And  now  we  have  to  determine  the  question  which 
has  been  already  raised,  whether  children  should  be 
themselves  taught  to  sing  and  play,  or  not.  Clearly, 
there  is  a  considerable  difference  made  in  the  character 
by  the  actual  practice  of  the  art.  It  is  difficult,  if  not 
impossible,  for  those  who  do  not  perform  to  be  judges  of 
the  performance  of  others.  Besides,  children  should 
have  something  to  do,  and  the  rattle  of  Archytas,  which 
people  give  to  their  children  in  order  to  amuse  them  and 
prevent  them  from  breaking  anything  in  the  house,  was 
a  capital  invention,  for  a  young  thing  cannot  be  quiet. 
The  rattle  is  a  toy  suited  to  the  infant  mind,  and 
(musical)  education  is  a  rattle  or  toy  for  children  of  a 
larger  growth.  We  conclude  then  that  they  should  be 
taught  music  in  such  a  way  as  to  become  not  only  critics 
but  performers. 

"The  question,  what  is  or  is  not,  suitable  for  different 
ages  may  be  easily  answered;  nor  is  there  any  difficulty 
in  meeting  the  objection  of  those  who  say  that  the  study 
of  music  is  vulgar.  We  reply  (i)  in  the  first  place,  that 
they  who  are  to  be  judges  must  also  be  performers,  and 
that  they  should  begin  to  practice  early,  although  when 
they  are  older  they  may  be  spared  the  execution ;  they 
must  have  learned  to  appreciate  what  is  good  and  to  de 
light  in  it,  thanks  to  the  knowledge  which  they  acquired 
in  their  youth.  As  to  (2)  the  vulgarizing  effect  which 
music  is  supposed  to  exercise,  this  is  a  question  (of 
degree),  which  we  shall  have  no  difficulty  in  determining, 
when  we  have  considered  to  what  extent  freemen  who 
are  being  trained  to  political  virtue,  should  pursue  the 
art,  what  melodies  and  what  rhythms  they  should  be 
allowed  to  use,  and  what  instruments  should  be  em 
ployed  in  teaching  them  to  play,  for  even  the  instrument 
makes  a  difference.  The  answer  to  the  objection  turns 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  281 

upon  these  distinctions;  for  it  is  quite  possible  that  cer 
tain  methods  of  teaching  and  learning  music  do  really 
have  a  degrading  effect.  It  is  evident  then  that  the 
learning  of  music  ought  not  to  impede  the  business  of 
riper  years,  or  to  degrade  the  body  or  render  it  unfit  for 
civil  or  military  duties,  whether  for  the  early  practice  or 
for  the  later  study  of  them. 

"The  right  measure  will  be  attained  if  students  of 
music  stop  short  of  the  arts  which  are  practised  in  pro 
fessional  contests,  and  do  not  seek  to  acquire  those  fan 
tastic  marvels  of  execution  which  are  now  the  fashion 
in  such  contests,  and  from  these  have  passed  into  edu 
cation.  Let  the  young  pursue  their  studies  until  they 
are  able  to  feel  delight  in  noble  melodies  and  rhythms, 
and  not  merely  in  that  common  part  of  music  in  which 
every  slave  or  child,  and  even  some  animals  find  pleasure. 

"From  these  principles  we  may  also  infer  what  instru 
ments  should  be  used.  The  flute,  or  any  other  instru 
ment  which  requires  great  skill,  as  for  example  the  harp, 
ought  not  to  be  admitted  into  education,  but  only  such 
as  will  make  intelligent  students  of  music  or  of  the  other 
parts  of  education.  Besides,  the  flute  is  not  an  instru 
ment  which  has  a  good  moral  effect ;  it  is  too  exciting. 
The  proper  time  for  using  it  is  when  the  performance 
aims,  not  at  instruction,  but  at  the  relief  of  the  passions. 
And  there  is  a  further  objection  ;  the  impediment  which 
the  flute  presents  to  the  use  of  the  voice  detracts  from 
its  educational  value.  The  ancients  were  therefore  right 
in  forbidding  the  flute  to  youths  and  freemen,  although 
they  had  once  allowed  it.  For  when  their  wealth  gave 
them  greater  leisure,  and  they  had  loftier  notions  of  ex 
cellence,  being  also  elated  with  their  success,  both  before 
and  after  the  Persian  War,  with  more  zeal  than  discern 
ment  they  pursued  every  kind  of  knowledge,  and  so  they 


282  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

introduced  the  flute  into  education.  At  Lacedsemon 
there  was  a  Choragus  who  led  the  Chorus  with  a  flute, 
and  at  Athens  the  instrument  became  so  popular  that 
most  freemen  could  play  upon  it.  The  popularity  is 
shown  by  the  tablet  which  Thrasippus  dedicated  when 
he  furnished  the  Chorus  to  Ecphantides.  Later  experi 
ence  enabled  men  to  judge  what  was,  or  was  not,  really 
conducive  to  virtue,  and  they  rejected  both  the  flute  and 
several  other  old-fashioned  instruments,  such  as  the 
Lydian  harp,  the  many-stringed  lyre,  the  'heptagon,' 
'  triangle,'  '  sambuca,'  and  the  like — which  are  intended 
only  to  give  pleasure  to  the  hearer,  and  require  extra 
ordinary  skill  of  hand.  There  is  a  meaning  also  in  the 
myth  of  the  ancients,  which  tells  how  Athene  invented 
the  flute  and  then  threw  it  away.  It  was  not  a  bad  idea 
of  theirs,  that  the  Goddess  disliked  the  instrument  be 
cause  it  made  the  face  ugly ;  but  with  still  more  reason 
may  we  say  that  she  rejected  it  because  the  acquirement 
of  flute-playing  contributes  nothing  to  the  mind,  since 
to  Athene  we  ascribe  both  knowledge  and  art. 

"Thus  then  we  reject  the  professional  instruments  and 
also  the  professional  mode  of  education  in  music — and 
by  professional  we  mean  that  which  is  adopted  in  con 
tests,  for  in  this  the  performer  practises  the  art,  not  for 
the  sake  of  his  own  improvement,  but  in  order  to  give 
pleasure,  and  that  of  a  vulgar  sort,  to  his  hearers.  For 
this  reason  the  execution  of  such  music  is  not  the  part 
of  a  freeman  but  of  a  paid  performer,  and  the  result  is 
that  the  performers  are  vulgarized,  for  the  end  at  which 
they  aim  is  bad.  The  vulgarity  of  the  spectator  tends 
to  lower  the  character  of  the  music  and  therefore  of  the 
performers :  they  look  to  him — he  makes  them  what  they 
are,  and  fashions  even  their  bodies  by  the  movements 
which  he  expects  them  to  exhibit. 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  283 

"  We  have  also  to  consider  rhythms  and  harmonies. 
Shall  we  use  them  all  in  education  or  make  a  distinction? 
and  shall  the  distinction  be  that  which  is  made  by  those 
who  are  engaged  in  education,  or  shall  it  be  some  other? 
For  we  see  that  music  is  produced  by  melody  and  rhythm, 
and  we  ought  to  know  what  influence  these  have  respect 
ively  on  education,  and  whether  we  should  prefer  ex 
cellence  in  melody  or  excellence  in  rhythm.  But  as  the 
subject  has  been  very  well  treated  by  many  musicians  of 
the  present  day,  and  also  by  philosophers  who  have  had 
considerable  experience  of  musical  education,  to  these 
we  would  refer  the  more  exact  student  of  the  subject ; 
we  shall  only  speak  of  it  now  after  the  manner  of  the 
legislator,  having  regard  to  general  principles. 

"  We  accept  the  division  of  melodies  proposed  by  cer 
tain  philosophers  into  ethical  melodies,  melodies  of  action, 
and  passionate  or  inspiring  melodies,  each  having,  as  they 
say,  a  mode  or  harmony  corresponding  to  it.  But  we 
maintain  further  that  music  should  be  studied,  not  for 
the  sake  of  one,  but  of  many  benefits,  that  is  to  say,  with 
a  view  to  (i)  education,  (2)  purification  (the  word  '  puri 
fication  '  we  use  at  present  without  explanation,  but  when 
hereafter  we  speak  of  poetry,  wre  will  treat  the  subject 
with  more  precision);  music  may  also  serve  (3)  for  in 
tellectual  enjoyment,  for  relaxation  and  for  recreation 
after  exertion.  It  is  clear,  therefore,  that  all  the  har 
monies  must  be  employed  by  us,  but  not  all  of  them  in 
the  same  manner.  In  education  ethical  melodies  are  to 
be  preferred,  but  we  may  listen  to  the  melodies  of  action 
and  passion  when  they  are  performed  by  others.  For 
feelings  such  as  pity  and  fear,  or,  again,  enthusiasm,  ex 
ist  very  strongly  in  some  souls,  and  have  more  or  less 
influence  over  all.  Some  persons  fall  into  a  religious 
frenzy,  whom  we  see  disenthralled  by  the  use  of  mystic 


284  Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers. 

melodies,  which  bring  healing  and  purification  to  the 
soul.  Those  who  are  influenced  by  pity  or  fear,  and 
every  emotional  nature,  have  a  like  experience,  others, 
in  their  degree  are  stirred  by  something  which  specially 
affects  them,  and  all  are  in  a  manner  purified,  and  their 
souls  lightened  and  delighted.  The  melodies  of  purifica 
tion  likewise  give  an  innocent  pleasure  to  mankind. 
Such  are  the  harmonies  and  the  melodies  in  which  those 
who  perform  music  at  the  theatre  should  be  invited  to 
compete.  But  since  the  spectators  are  of  two  kinds — the 
one  free  and  educated,  and  the  other  a  vulgar  crowd 
composed  of  mechanics,  laborers,  and  the  like — there 
ought  to  be  contests  and  exhibitions  instituted  for  the 
relaxation  of  the  second  class  also.  And  the  melodies 
will  correspond  to  their  minds ;  for  as  their  minds  are 
perverted  from  the  natural  state,  so  there  are  exaggerated 
and  corrupted  harmonies  which  are  in  like  manner  a  per 
version.  A  man  receives  pleasure  from  what  is  natural 
to  him,  and  therefore  professional  musicians  may  be 
allowed  to  practice  this  lower  sort  of  music  before  an 
audience  of  a  lower  type.  But,  for  the  purposes  of  edu 
cation,  as  I  have  already  said,  those  modes  and  melodies 
should  be  employed  which  are  ethical,  such  as  the  Dorian ; 
though  we  may  include  any  others  which  are  approved 
by  philosophers  who  have  had  a  musical  education.  The 
Socrates  of  the  Republic  is  wrong  in  retaining  only  the 
Phrygian  mode  along  with  the  Dorian,  and  the  more  so 
because  he  rejects  the  flute;  for  the  Phrygian  is  to  the 
modes  what  the  flute  is  to  musical  instruments — both  of 
them  are  exciting  and  emotional.  Poetry  proves  this, 
for  Bacchic  frenzy  and  all  similar  emotions  are  most 
suitably  expressed  by  the  flute,  and  are  better  set  to  the 
Phrygian  than  to  any  other  harmony.  The  dithyramb, 
for  example,  is  acknowledged  to  be  Phrygian,  a  fact  of 


Ethics  of  the  Greek  Philosophers.  285 

which  the  connoisseurs  of  music  offer  many  proofs, 
saying,  among  other  things,  that  Philoxenus,  having  at 
tempted  to  compose  his  tales  as  a  dithyramb  in  the 
Dorian  mode,  found  it  impossible,  and  fell  back  into  the 
more  appropriate  Phrygian.  All  men  agree  that  the 
Dorian  music  is  the  gravest  and  manliest.  And,  whereas 
we  say  that  the  extremes  should  be  avoided  and  the 
mean  followed,  and  whereas  the  Dorian  is  a  mean  between 
the  other  harmonies  (the  Phrygian  and  the  Lydian),  it 
is  evident  that  our  youth  should  be  taught  the  Dorian 
music. 

"Two  principles  have  to  be  kept  in  view,  what  is  pos 
sible,  what  is  becoming :  at  these  every  man  ought  to 
aim.  But  even  these  are  relative  to  age ;  the  old,  who 
have  lost  their  powers,  cannot  very  well  sing  the  severe 
melodies,  and  nature  herself  seems  to  suggest  that  their 
songs  should  be  of  the  more  relaxed  kind.  Wherefore, 
the  musicians  likewise  blame  Socrates,  and  with  justice, 
for  rejecting  the  relaxed  harmonies  in  education  under 
the  idea  that  they  are  intoxicating,  not  in  the  ordinary 
sense  of  intoxication  (for  wine  rather  tends  to  excite 
men),  but  because  they  have  no  strength  in  them.  And 
so  with  a  view  to  a  time  of  life  when  men  begin  to  grow 
old,  they  ought  to  practice  the  gentler  harmonies  and 
melodies  as  well  as  the  others.  And  if  there  be  any 
harmony,  such  as  the  Lydian  above  all  others  appears 
to  be,  which  is  suited  to  children  of  tender  age,  and  pos 
sesses  the  elements  both  of  order  and  of  education,  clearly 
(we  ought  to  use  it,  for)  education  should  be  based  upon 
three  principles — the_mean,  the  possible,  the  becoming, 
these  three." 


c/ 

f. 


LIFE  OF  SOCRATES, 


CONDENSED   FROM 


HISTORY  OF  PHILOSOPHY, 

BY 

THOMAS    STANLEY. 

LONDON,  1701, 
BY  CHAS.   M.   HlGGlNS. 


COPYRIGHT,  1903,  BY  CHAS.  M.  HIGGINS. 


CHARLES  M.  HIGGINS  £  CO. 
NEW  YORK — CHICAGO — LONDON. 
1903. 


u 


LIFE   OF   SOCRATES.  2850! 


CONTENTS. 


PAGE 

The  nativity,  parentage  and  training  of  Socrates,        .        .        286 
His  original  profession  of  sculptor  abandoned  to  adopt  the 
role  of  moral  philosopher,  public  reformer  and  teacher 
of  virtue,  without  fees,  ......        287 

His  asceticism  and  voluntary  poverty  and  his  claim  to  divine 
inspiration  and  a  divine  mission  to  mankind.     His  pro 
phetic  spirit  and  his  spiritual  attendant  or  "  daemon."        288 
The  personal  appearance,  character  and  virtues  of  Socrates.      289 
His  wives  and  children,         .  .....        295 

The  Masters  and  Teachers  of  Socrates,        ....         297 

His  school  and  pupils, 298 

Philosophic  sects  influenced  by  and  formed  from  his  teach 
ings.  Cynics,  Stoics,  Hedonists,  Platonists,  Aristotel 
ians,  etc. 307 

Writings  of  Socrates— Poetry  and  Tragedy,  .  .  .  311 
Socrates  as  a  soldier — his  military  services  and  actions,  .  312 
His  quarrel  with  the  Sophists  and  Rhetoricians  and  cause 

of  his  death,  , 314 

The  trial  of  Socrates, 318 

His  imprisonment, .        325 

After  his  death.  Decline  of  Greece.  Honors  paid  and  re 
morse  and  sorrow  shown  by  Greeks  and  others  .  331 


I 
4? 


LIFE  OF  SOCRATES. 

"The  great  English  philosopher,  John  Stuart  Mill, 
has  somewhere  observed  that  mankind  cannot  be  too 
often  reminded  that  there  was  once  a  man  of  the  name 
of  Socrates." 

Prof.  Harnack— "  What  is  Christianity?" 


"Drink  Socrates  with  Jove,  next  whom  enthroned, 
By  Gods,  and  Wisdom's  self,  as  wisest  own'd. 
Thee  the  Athenians  gave  a  poisonous  draught, 
But  first  thy  wisdom  from  your  lips  they  quaffed." 

Note : — In  this  condensation  we  have  preserved  as  far 
as  possible  the  quaint  language,  punctuation,  and  obso 
lete  words  of  this  deep  and  interesting  old  book  of  two 
centuries  ago. 

C.  M.  H. 


LIFE    OF    SOCRATES. 

CONDENSED  FROM  STANLEY'S  HISTORY  OF  PHILOSOPHY, 
LONDON,  1701. 

Socrates  was  by  country  an  Athenian,  born  at  Alopece, 
a  town  belonging  to  the  Antiochian  Tribe. 

His  parents  were  very  mean  ;  Sophroniscus  (an  Athen 
ian)  his  father,  a  statuary  or  carver  of  images  in  stone; 
Phaenareta,  his  mother,  a  midwife,  a  woman  of  a  bold, 
generous  and  quick  spirit,  as  is  implied  by  the  character 
Plato  gives  her,  of  which  professions  of  his  parents, 
he  is  observed  to  have  been  so  far  from  feeling  ashamed, 
that  he  often  took  occasion  to  mention  them. 
^  The  day  of  Socrates'  birth  was  the  sixth  of  the  month 
Thargelion  (about  May  20)  memorable  for  the  birth  of 
Diana.  The  day  following,  viz.,  the  seventh  of  this 
month,  was  the  birthday  of  Plato,  both  of  which  were 
kept  with  much  solemnity  by  the  Greek  philosophers 
(even  to  the  time  of  Plotinus)  as  is  affirmed  by  Plutarch. 

Plutarch  saith  that  as  soon  as  he  was  born,  Sophron 
iscus,  his  father,  consulting  the  oracle,  was  by  it  advised 
to  suffer  his  son  to  do  what  he  pleased,  never  compelling 
him  to  do  what  he  disliked,  nor  diverting  him  from  that 
whereto  he  was  inclined ;  to  give  thanks  for  him  by 
sacrifice  to  Jupiter  Agorseus  and  the  muses ;  to  be  no 
farther  solicitous  for  him,  he  had  one  guide  of  his  life 
within  him,  better  than  five  hundred  masters. 

But  his  father,  not  observant  of  the  oracle's  direction, 
applied  him  to  his  own  trade  of  carving  statues,  contrary 
to  his  inclination,  whereupon  some  have  argued  him  of 
disobedience,  reporting  that  oftentimes,  when  his  father 
bade  him  work,  he  refused,  and  went  away,  following 
his  own  will.  (286) 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  287 

His  father  dying,  left  him  fourscore  minse,  which,  be 
ing  entrusted  with  a  friend  for  improvement,  they  mis 
carried.  This  loss,  by  which  he  was  reduced  to  incredi 
ble  poverty,  Socrates  passed  over  with  silence,  but  was 
thereupon  necessitated  to  continue  his  trade  for  ordinary 
subsistence.  Duris,  Pausanias,  and  the  Scholiast  of 
Aristophanes  affirm  three  statues  of  the  Graces  clothed 
(for  so  they  were  most  anciently  made,  not  naked)  set 
up  before  the  entrance  into  the  tower  at  Athens,  were  his 
work.  Pausanias  implieth  as  much  of  a  statue  of  Mer 
cury  in  the  same  place ;  which  Pliny  seems  not  to  have 
understood,  who  saith,  they  were  made  by  a  certain  per 
son  named  Socrates,  but  not  the  painter.  But  being 
naturally  averse  to  this  profession,  he  only  followed  it 
when  necessity  enforced  him. 

These  intermissions  from  his  trade  were  bestowed 
upon  philosophy  ;  whereunto  he  was  naturally  addicted, 
which  being  observed  by  Crito^  a  rich  philosopher  of 
Athens,  he  took  him  from  his  shop,  being  much  in  love 
Vwith  his  candor  and  ingenuity,  and  instructed,  or  rather 
gave  him  the  means  to  be  instructed  by  others  ;  taking 
so  much  care  of  him,  that  he  never  suffered  him  to  want 
necessaries.  And  though  his  poverty  was  at  first  so 
great  as  to  be  brought  by  some  into  a  proverb,  yet  he 
became  at  last,  as  Demetrius  affirms,  master  of  a  house, 
and  fourscore  rninse,  which  Crito  put  out  to  interest : 
But  his  mind  (saith  Libanius)  was  raised  far  above  his 
fortune,  and  more  to  the  advantage  of  his  country  ;  not 
aiming  at  wealth,  or  the  acquisition  thereof  by  sordid 
arts,  he  considered  that  of  all  things  which  man  can  call 
his,  the  soul  is  the  chief  ;  that  he  only  is  truly  happy  who 
purifies  that  from  vice ;  that  the  only  means  conducing 
thereto,  is  wisdom,  in  pursuit  whereof  he  neglected  all 
other  ways  of  profit  and  pleasure. 


288  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

We  have  alleged  the  universal  consent  of  authors, 
that  Socrates  possessed  the  spirit  of  prophecy  and  was 
inspired  and  accompanied  by  a  divine  or  spiritual  at 
tendant;  yet  is  there  some  disagreement  concerning  the 
name,  more  concerning  the  nature  of  it. 

It  is  commonly  named  his  "  daemon  ",  by  which  title, 
he  himself  owned  it:  Plato  sometimes  calls  it  his 
guardian;  Apuleius  his  God,  because  (saith  Saint 
Augustine)  the  name  of  daemon  at  last  grows  odious.* 
But  we  must  observe,  that  he  did  not  account  it  a  God, 
but  sent  from  God,  and  in  that  sense  affirmed  the  signs 
to  come  from  God,  to  wit,  by  mediation  of  this  spirit. 
This,  besides  other  places,  we  may  argue  from  his  first 
epistle,  where  he  speaks  of  the  sign  itself  ;  he  useth  the 
word  daemon,  when  of  the  advice,  whereof  that  sign  was 
the  instrument,  he  names  God.  Thus  are  we  to  under 
stand  these,  and  all  other  places  of  the  same  nature  in 
Plato,  where  Socrates,  speaking  of  the  daemon,  saith,  if 
it  pleases  God,  you  shall  learn  much,  and  the  sign  from 
God  did  not  offer  to  stay  me. 

Others  confine  this  prescience  within  the  soul  of  Soc 
rates  himself,  that  he  said,  his  genius  advised  him,  they 
interpret  it,  as  we  usually  say,  his  mind  gave  him,  or  so 
inclined  him :  in  this  sense  indeed  daemon  is  not  seldom 
taken ;  but  this  is  inconsistent  with  the  description 
which  Socrates  gives  of  a  voice  and  signs  ab  exteriore, 
besides,  this  knowledge  is  not  above  human  nature. 

Some  conceive  it  to  be  one  of  those  spirits  which  have 
a  particular  care  of  men ;  which  Maximus  Tyrius,  and 
Apuleius  describe  in  such  manner,  that  they  want  only 
the  name  of  a  good  angel. 

*  By  this  Augustine  probably  meant  that  the  word  "  daemon, ' '  had  come  to 
mean,  as  it  now  does  with  us,  an  evil  spirit  only,  whereas  originally  the  term 
daemon  or  demon,  was  applied  to  a  spiritual  being  either  good  or  evil.  Thus 
in  a  similar  way  practically  the  same  word  or  term  was  originally  used  either 
for  God  or  devil .  For  example,  the  word  '  *  deuce ' '  we  now  apply  to  the  great 
evil  spirit  or  devil  only,  whereas  we  apply  the  term  ' '  Deus ' '  to  the  great  good 
spirit  or  God.  yet  both  words,  as  may  be  seen,  are  substantially  identical.— Ed. 


Ethics   of  the   Greek   Philosophers.  289 

But  there  want  not  those  who  give  it  that  appellation  : 
Lactanius  having  proved  that  God  sends  angels  to  guard 
mankind,  adds,  and  Socrates  affirmed  there  was  a  daemon 
constantly  near  him,  which  kept  him  company  from  a 
child,  by  whose  beck  and  instruction  he  guided  his  life. 
Eusebius  upon  these  words  of  the  Psalmist,  "  He  hath 
given  his  angels  charge  over  thee,  that  they  should  keep 
tnee  in  all  thy  ways."  We  learn  out  of  Scripture  (saith 
he)  that  every  man  hath  a  guardian  appointed  him  from 
above  ;  and  Plato  doubteth  not  to  write  in  this  manner : 
All  souls  having  chosen  a  condition  of  living,  they  pro 
ceed  in  order  thereto,  being  moved  by  the  daemon,  which 
is  proper  to  every  one,  and  is  sent  along  with  them  to 
preserve  them  in  this  life,  and  to  perfect  those  things 
whereof  they  have  made  choice.  And  immediately  after ; 
you  may  believe,  saith  he,  that  Socrates  means  this, 
when  he  often  affirmed  that  he  was  governed  by  a 
daemon.  More  plainly  Eugubinus,  the  daemon  of  Soc 
rates,  saith  he,  mentioned  so  often  by  Plato  (seeing  that 
Socrates  was  a  good  man,  and  exhorted  all  men  to  virtue, 
and  by  the  daemon  was  always  excited  to  that  which  was 
good)  may  perhaps  not  unjustly  be  thought  his  angel, 
as  that  which  appeared  to  Baalam  the  prophet,  and  di 
verted  him  from  his  wickedness.  But,  Ficinus  expressly  ; 
if  you  are  not  pleased,  saith  he,  speaking  of  this  spirit, 
to  call  the  familiar  guide  of  a  man  his  spirit,  call  it  if 
you  please,  his  good  angel. 

OF  HIS  PERSON  AND  VIRTUES. 

As  to  his  person,  he  was  very  unhandsome,  of  a  melan 
choly  complexion,  bald,  a  flat  nose,  eyes  sticking  out,  a 
severe  downcast  look,  difficult  in  speech,  and  too  concise, 
his  language  rough  and  careless,  but  more  efficacious 
than  all  the  eloquence  of  Themistocles,  Pericles,  or  any 


290  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers, 

other ;  so  acute  that  he  could  maintain  either  side  in  any 
question,  therefore  is  reproached  by  Aristophanes  as 
having  two  languages,  whereof  one  was  to  defend 
wrong ;  fervent  in  dispute,  often  so  transported,  that  he 
would  beat  himself,  and  tear  his  beard,  to  the  derision 
of  the  standers-by,  which  he  took  quietly  :  patient  to  be 
reargued;  sometimes  he  covered  his  face  in  discourse, 
that  he  might  not  be  diverted  by  any  object  of  sight :  his 
constitution  strong  and  hardy,  which  he  preserved  such, 
by  taking  diligent  care  of  his  health  ;  well  bearing  cold, 
hunger,  and  upon  occasion,  excess  of  wine  without  dis 
turbance  :  his  habit  the  same  in  winter  as  in  summer, 
having  but  one  garment  a  year ;  no  shoes,  his  diet  spar 
ing.  In  fine,  his  countenance  promised  so  little,  that 
Zopyrus  a  physiognomist  who  undertook  to  discover  the 
dispositions  of  men  by  their  looks  said  he  was  stupid, 
because  there  were  obstructions  in  his  jugular  parts; 
adding,  he  was  given  to  women  and  many  other  vices ; 
whereat  Alcibiades  and  other  friends  of  his  that  were 
present,  knowing,  him  free  from  those  imputations,  fell 
a  laughing,  but  Socrates  justified  his  skill,  answering, 
he  was  by  nature  prone  to  those  vices,  but  suppressed 
his  inclinations  by  reason,  whence  Alcibiades  used  to 
say,  he  resembled  the  image  of  Silenus  as  he  did  indeed 
in  his  countenance,  baldness,  and  flat  nose  carved  on  the 
outside  of  little  boxes,  sitting  and  playing  on  a  pipe ;  for 
as  those  boxes  within  held  images  of  the  Gods,  so  was 
he  adorned  with  chastity,  integrity,  and  all  inward 
beauty,  ravished,  as  Plutarch  saith,  with  a  divine  zeal  to 
virtue,  in  all  kinds  whereof  Xenophon,  Laertius  and 
others,  assert  these  instances. 

He  was  so  wise,  that  he  never  erred  in  judging  betwixt 
better  and  worse,  nor  thereto  needed  any  other  help : 
Yet  he  constantly  professed,  that  he  only  knew  that  he 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers,  291 

knew  nothing  :  for  which  reason  he  was  by  the  oracle  o  ;*. 
Apollo  at  Delphi,  declared  of  all  men  the  most  wise  in 
this  manner  to  Charephon,  many  witnesses  being 

present : — 

Wise  Sophocles,  wiser  Euripedes, 
But  wisest  of  all  men  is  Socrates. 

Apollo  (saith  Cicero)  conceiving  the  only  wisdom  of 
mankind  to  consist  in  not  thinking  themselves  to  know 
those  things  whereof  they  are  ignorant.  This  oracle, 
though  he  were  nothing  exalted  with  it  himself,  pro 
cured  him  much  envy. 

He  was  so  religious,  that  he  never  did  anything  with 
out  advising,  first  with  the  Gods,  never  was  known  to 
attempt  or  speak  any  impiety. 

He  bore  a  reverence  to  the  Gods,  not  human,  but  such 
as  transcended  the  greatest  fear :  some  say  it  was  out  of 
his  great  reverence  to  the  divinity  that  he  used  to  swear 
by  a  cock,  a  dog,  and  a  plain  tree  (under  which  they 
used  to  sit)  though  it  were  interpreted  atheism. 

He  was  constant,  and  a  lover  of  the  public  good,  as 
appears  in  his  acquitting  the  ten  captains,  in  his  denying 
thirty  tyrants  to  fetch  Leon  in,  his  refusing  to  escape 
out  of  prison,  and  reproving  such  as  grieved  for  his 
death.  Xantippe  used  to  say,  that  when  the  state  was 
oppressed  with  a  thousand  miseries,  he  always  went 
abroad  and  came  home  with  the  same  look,  never  more 
cheerful,  or  more  troubled,  for  he  bore  a  mind  smooth 
and  cheerful  upon  all  occasions,  far  remote  from  grief, 
and  above  all,  fear :  in  his  declining  age,  falling  sick,  he 
was  asked  by  one  that  came  to  visit  him,  how  he  did  ? 
Very  well  (saith  he)  either  way;  if  I  live,  I  shall  have 
more  emulation,  if  I  die,  more  praise. 

He  was  so  temperate,  that  he  never  preferred  that 
which  is  pleasant  before  that  which  is  wholesome.  He 


292  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

never  did  eat  more  than  appetite  (which  was  his  sauce) 
made  delightful ;  all  drink  was  pleasing  to  him,  because 
he  never  drank  but  when  he  was  thirsty,  and  then  with 
such  temperate  caution,  that  he  poured  out  the  first 
draught  of  water  upon  the  ground,  and  if  he  were  at 
any  time  invited  to  a  feast,  he,  which  to  others  is  very 
difficult,  with  much  ease  took  care  not  to  eat  more  than 
consisted  with  his  health,  whereof  he  was  very  careful, 
because  the  exercises  of  the  soul  depend  thereon  and  in 
order  thereto,  used  to  walk  constantly  before  meals, 
whereupon  being  asked  by  one  that  observed  it,  what 
he  did,  I  get  broth,  saith  he,  for  my  supper.  To  this 
temperance  it  is  imputed,  though  Athens  were  often  in 
his  time  visited  with  the  pestilence,  he  alone  escaped  it. 
He  was  so  frugal,  that  how  little  soever  he  had,  it  was 
always  enough.  Wanting  the  means  to  live  splendidly, 
he  taught  not  anxiously  how  to  acquire  more,  but  how 
to  accommodate  his  manner  of  life  to  that  which  he  had, 
wherewith  he  was  so  contented,  that  he  affirmed  himself 
to  come  nearest  the  gods,  because  he  wanted  least.  See 
ing  the  great  variety  of  things  exposed  to  sale,  he  would 
say  to  himself,  how7  many  things  there  are  that  I  need 
not ;  and  often  had  in  his  mouth  these  verses, 

Purple,  which  gold  and  gems  adorn, 
Is  by  tragedians  to  be  worn. 

Alcibiades  ambitiously  munificent,  sent  him  many 
great  presents :  Xantippe  admiring  their  value,  desired 
him  to  accept  them :  We  (answered  Socrates)  will  con 
test  in  liberality  with  Alcibiades,  not  accepting,  by  a 
kind  of  munificence  what  he  hath  sent  us. 

To  the  same,  who  offered  him  a  large  plot  of  ground 
to  build  a  house  upon :  and  if  I  wanted  shoes  (saith  he) 
would  you  give  me  leather  to  make  them  ?  But  deserve 
I  not  to  be  derided  if  I  accepted  it  ? 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  293 

He  slighted  Archelaus,  King  of  Macedonia,  and 
Scopas,  son  of  Cranonias,  and  Euriloeus,  son  of  Larisae- 
us,  not  accepting  their  money  nor  going  to  them. 
Archelaus  sending  to  him  to  desire  his  company,  he  said, 
he  would  not  go  to  one,  from  whom  he  should  receive 
benefits,  which  he  could  not  equal  with  return.  To  Per- 
diccas,  who  demanded  why  he  would  not  come  to  him, 
he  answered,  lest  I  die  the  most  ignoble  death,  that  is 
lest  I  receive  a  benefit  which  I  cannot  requite. 
/  Coming  home  late  one  night  from  a  feast,  some  wild 
young  men  knowing  of  his  return,  lay  in  wait  for  him, 
attired  like  furies,  with  vizards  and  torches,  whereby 
they  used  to  affright  such  as  they  met ;  Socrates  as  soon 
as  he  saw  them,  nothing  troubled,  made  a  stand,  and  fell 
to  questioning  them,  according  to  his  usual  manner,  as 
if  he  had  been  in  the  Lyceum  or  Academy. 

He  despised  those  that  cavilled  at  him.  Being  told 
that  such  an  one  had  reviled  him  behind  his  back :  Let 
him  beat  me,  saith  he,  whilst  I  am  not  by:  And  that 
another  spoke  ill  of  him  :  He  hath  not  yet  learned,  said 
he,  to  speak  well. 

Being  kicked  by  an  insolent  young  fellow,  and  seeing, 
those  that  were  with  him  much  incensed,  ready  to  pursue 
him,  he  said,  what  if  an  ass  kick  me,  would  you  have  me 
kick  again,  or  sue  him  ?  But  the  fellow  escaped  not 
unpunished,  for  every  one  reproached  him  for  this  in 
solence,  and  called  him  the  reviler,  so  that  at  last  for 
vexation  he  hanged  himself. 

Another  striking  him  a  box  on  the  ear,  he  said  no 
more,  but  that  it  was  hard  a  man  knew  not  when  to  go 
abroad  with  a  helmet. 

Another  fell  upon  him  with  much  violence,  which  he 
endured  without  the  least  disturbance,  suffering  him  to 
vent  his  anger,  which  he  did  so  long,  till  he  made  his 


294  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

face  all  swelled  and  bruised.     Whensoever  he  perceived 
himself  to  grow  incensed  with  any  of  his  friends, 

Before  the  storm  arose, 
He  to  the  harbor  goes. 

He  used  to  moderate  his  voice,  to  look  smilingly  and 
moderately  upon  them,  reserving  himself  untainted  with 
passion,  by  recourse  to  the  contrary. 

He  taught  not  such  as  conversed  with  him  to  be 
covetous,  for  he  took  no  money  of  his  scholars,  therein 
expressing  his  own  liberality. 

Hunger  or  want  could  never  force  him  to  flatter  any  : 
Yet  was  he  very  complaisant  and  facete  in  company :  as 
he  one  day  openly  at  dinner  reproved  one  of  his  friends 
somewhat  harshly.  Plato  said  to  him,  had  not  this  been 
better  told  in  private?  Socrates  immediately  answered, 
and  had  you  not  done  better,  if  you  had  told  me  so  in 
private  ?  Being  demanded  what  countryman  he  was,  he 
answered,  neither  of  Athens,  nor  Greece,  but  of  the 
world.  Sometimes  he  would  feast  in  a  fine  robe,  as 
Plato  describes  him,  and  when  the  time  allowed,  learned 
to  sing,  saying,  it  was  no  shame  to  learn  anything  which 
one  knew  not:  He  also  danced  every  day,  conceiving 
that  exercise  healthful ;  nor  was  he  ashamed  to  play  with 
little  children. 

He  was  so  just,  that  he  never  in  the  least  wronged 
any  man,  but  on  the  contrary,  benefited  all  such  as  con 
versed  with  him,  as  much  as  he  could. 

His  continence  was  invincible :  He  despised  the 
beauty  of  Alcibiades,  derided  Theodota  and  Caliste,  two 
eminent  courtezans  of  that  time. 

He  took  great  delight  in  the  conversation  of  good 
men ;  to  such  he  communicated  whatsoever  he  knew ; 
with  them  he  studied  the  writings  of  the  ancient  wise 
men,  selecting  what  was  good  out  of  them. 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  295 

His  WIVES  AND  CHILDREN. 

He  had  two  wives,  the  first  Xantippe,  a  citizen's 
daughter  of  Athens,  as  Theodoret  affirms. 

She  was  (according  to  the  character  A.  Gellius  gives 
her)  curst,  froward,  chiding  and  scolding  always  both 
day  and  night,  and  for  that  reason  he  chose  her,  as  he 
professed  to  Antisthenes,  from  observing,  that  they  who 
would  be  excellent  in  horsemanship,  chose  the  roughest 
horses,  knowing,  if  they  are  able  to  manage  them,  they 
may  easily  rule  others :  He,  desirous  to  use  much  con 
versation  with  men,  took  her  to  wife,  knowing,  if  he 
could  bear  with  her,  he  might  easily  converse  with  all 
men.  To  Alcibiades,  who  said,  her  scolding  was  intoler 
able,  he  professed  it  was  nothing  to  him,  being  used  to 
it,  like  such  as  live  in  the  continual  noise  of  a  mill:  be 
sides,  saith  he,  cannot  you  endure  the  cackling  of  hens  ? 
But  they,  answered  Alcibiades,  bring  me  eggs  and 
chickens :  and  my  Xantippe,  replies  Socrates,  children. 

Of  her  impatience  and  his  sufferance,  there  are  several 
instances :  one  day  before  some  of  his  friends,  she  fell 
into  the  usual  extravagancies  of  her  passion,  whereupon 
he  not  answering  anything,  went  forth  with  them,  but 
was  no  sooner  out  at  the  door,  when  she,  running  up 
into  the  chamber,  threw  down  water  upon  his  head, 
whereat  turning  to  his  friends,  did  I  not  tell  you,  saith 
he,  that  after  so  much  thunder  we  should  have  rain  ? 

Having  brought  Euthydemus  from  the  Palaestrae  to 
dine  with  him,  Xantippe  running  to  the  table,  angry, 
overturned  it ;  Euthydemus,  much  troubled,  rose  up,  and 
would  have  gone  away,  when  Socrates  said  :  did  not  a 
hen  the  other  day,  the  very  same  thing  at  your  house, 
yet  I  was  not  angry  thereat  ? 

His  other  wife  was  named  Myrto,  niece  to  Lysimachus, 


296  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

daughter  of  Aristedes,  not  the  just,  as  Laertius,  and 
from  him  Suida's,  affirms,  but  another  of  that  name,  the 
third  from"  him,  as  is  observed  by  Athenaeus,  for  the 
two  daughters  of  Aristides  the  Just,  could  not  but  be  of 
great  age  before  the  yyth  'Olympiad,  wherein  Socrates 
was  born,  long  before  which  time  Aristides  died  an  old 
man  in  exile  ;  for  that  Themistocles  died  the  second 
year  of  the  yyth  Olympiad  is  certain,  and  as  ^Emilius 
Probus  affirms,  Aristides  died  four  years  before  The 
mistocles  was  banished  from  Athens,  hereupon  Plutarch 
more  cautiously  calls  her  not  the  daughter,  but  niece  of 
Aristides. 

Some,  because  Xantippe  (as  is  manifest  from  Plato) 
outlived  him,  believe  he  was  first  mar-ried  to  Myrto,  but 
that  he  had  both  these  wives  at  the  same  time,  which  is 
attested  by  Demetrius  Phalereus,  Aristoxenus  (to  whom 
Athenaeus  saith,  that  Aristotle  gave  the  ground)  Cal- 
isthenes  and  Porphyrius :  whence  Aristippus  in  his 
epistle  to  his  daughter  Myrto,  advised  her  to  go  to 
Athens,  and  above  all  to  honor  Xantippe  and  Myrto, 
and  to  live  with  them  as  he  with  Socrates. 

The  occasion,  whereupon  the  Athenians,  who  from  the 
time  of  Cecrops  had  strictly  observed  single  marriage, 
allowed  bigamy,  in  the  time  of  Socrates,  was  this  ;  in  the 
second  year  of  the  8yth  Olympiad  and  the  third  of  the 
88th,  Athens  was  visited  extremely  with  the  pestilence, 
which  attended  by  war  and  famine  occasioned  so  great 
a  scarcity  of  men,  that  they  made  an  edict  it  might  be 
lawful  for  any  that  would  to  take  two  wives.  Euripedes 
made  use  of  this  indulgence,  and  that  Socrates  also  did 
so,  is  attested  by  Satyrus  the  peripatetic,  and  Hierony- 
mus  the  Rhodian,  who  recorded  the  Order;  to  which 
Athenseus  imputes  the  silence  of  the  comic  poets  in  this 
particular,  who  omitted  no  grounds  of  reproach.  Plu- 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  297 

tarch  implies,  that  he  took  her  out  of  charity,  for 


a  widow  (without  any  portion  or  dowry)  extremely  in 
want. 

Porphyrus  reports,  that  when  these  two  (Xantippe 
and  Myrto)  quarrelled,  they  would  at  last  fall  both  upon 
Socrates,  and  beat  him,  because  he  stood  by  and  never 
parted  them,  but  laughed  as  well  when  they  fought  with 
him,  as  with  one  another. 

By  Xantippe  he  had  a  son,  named  Lamprocles,  who 
could  not  brook  her  impatience  so  well  as  his  father, 
and  being  vexed  by  her  into  disobedience,  was  reclaimed 
by  Socrates  ;  he  died  young,  as  may  be  gathered  from 
Plutarch,  who  saith,  Timarchus  of  Chseronea,  dying 
very  young,  desired  earnestly  of  Socrates  that  he  might 
be  buried  near  his  son  Lamprocles,  who  died  but  few 
days  before,  being  his  dear  friend,  and  of  the  same  age. 
It  appears  from  Plato,  that  he  had  more  sons  by  her,  for 
in  his  Apology  he  mentions  three,  two  grown  men,  the 
other  a  child,  which  seems  to  be  the  same,  brought  by 
Xantippe  to  him  in  prison  the  day  of  his  death,  and  as 
Plutarch  describes  it,  held  in  her  lap. 

By  Myrto  he  had  two  sons  :  the  eldest  Sophroniscus, 
the  youngest  Menedemus,  or  Menexenus,  though  some 
say  he  had  Menedemus  by  Xantippe. 

THE  TEACHERS  OF  SOCRATES. 

The  first  master  of  Socrates  was  Anaxagoras.  Aris- 
toneus  saith,  that  as  soon  as  Anaxagoras  left  the  city, 
Socrates  applied  himself  to  Archelaus,  which,  according 
to  Porphyrius,  was  in  the  seventeenth  year  of  his  age. 
Of  him  he  was  much  beloved,  and  traveled  with  him  to 
Samos,  to  Pytho,  and  to  the  Isthmus. 

He  was  pupil  likewise  to  Damon,  whom  Plato  calls  a 
most  pleasing  teacher  of  Music,  and  all  other  things  that 


298  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

he  would  teach  himself,  to  young  men.  Damon  was 
pupil  to  Agathocles,  master  to  Pericles,  Clinias  and 
others ;  intimate  with  Prodicus.  He  was  banished  by 
the  unjust  ostracism  of  the  Athenians  for  his  excellence 
in  music. 

To  these  teachers  add  Diotyma  and  Aspasia,  women 
excellently  learned,  the  first  supposed  to  have  been  in 
spired  with  a  prophetical  spirit.  By  her  Socrates 
affirmed  that  he  was  instructed  concerning  love,  by 
corporeal  beauty  to  find  out  that  of  the  soul;  of  the 
angelical  mind,  of  God.  See  Plato's  Phaedrus,  and  that 
long  discourse  in  his  Symposium  upon  this  subject, 
which  Socrates  confesseth  to  be  owing  to  her. 

Aspasia  was  a  famous  Milesian  woman,  not  only  ex 
cellent  herself  in  rhetoric,  but  brought  many  scholars  to 
great  perfection  in  it,  of  whom  were  Pericles  the  Atheni 
an  and  (as  himself  acknowledgeth)  Socrates. 

Of  Euenus  he  learned  poetry,  of  Ichomachus,  hus 
bandry,  of  Theodorus  Geometry. 

Aristagoras  a  Melian,  is  named  likewise  as  his  master. 

His  SCHOOL  AND  PUPILS. 

That  Socrates  had  a  proper  school,  may  be  argued 
from  Aristophanes,  who  derided  some  particulars  in  it, 
and  calls  it  his  Phrontisterium. 

Plato  and  Phsedrus  mention  as  places  frequented  by 
him  and  his  auditors,  the  academy  Lycaeum,  and  a  pleas 
ant  meadow  without  the  city  on  the  side  of  the  River 
Ilissus. 

Xenophon  affirms,  he  was  continually  abroad,  that  in 
the  morning  he  visited  the  places  of  public  walking  and 
exercise  ;  when  it  was  full,  the  forum;  and  the  rest  of 
the  day  he  sought  out  the  most  populous  meetings, 
where  he  disputed  openly  for  every  one  to  hear. 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  299 

He  did  only  teach,  saith  Plutarch,  when  the  benches 
were  prepared,  and  himself  in  the  chair,  or  in  set  hours 
of  reading  and  discourse,  or  appointments  of  walking 
with  his  friends,  but  even  when  he  played,  when  he  ate 
or  drank,  when  he  was  in  the  camp  or  market ;  finally, 
when  he  was  in  prison ;  thus  he  made  every  place  a 
school  of  virtue. 

His  manner  of  teaching  was  answerable  to  his  opinion, 
that  the  soul  pre-existent  to  the  body,  in  her  first  sepa 
rate  condition,  endowed  with  perfect  knowledge,  by 
immersion  into  matter,  became  stupefied,  and  in  a 
manner  lost,  until  awakened  by  discourse  from  sensible 
objects ;  whereby  by  degrees  she  recovers  her  first 
knowledge ;  for  this  reason  he  taught  only  by  irony  and 
induction:  In  this  irony  (saith  Cicero)  and  dissimula 
tion  he  far  exceeded  all  men  in  pleasantness  and 
urbanity. 

Induction  is  by  Cicero  defined  a  manner  of  discourse, 
which  gains  the  assent  of  him  with  whom  it  is  held,  to 
things  not  doubtful,  by  which  assents  it  causeth  that  he 
yield  to  a  doubtful  thing,  by  reason  of  the  likeness  it 
hath  to  those  things  whereunto  he  assented :  This  kind 
of  speech  Socrates  most  used,  because  he  would  not  him 
self  use  any  argument  of  persuasion,  but  rather  chose 
to  work  something  out  of  that  which  was  granted  by 
him  with  whom  he  disputed,  which  he,  by  reason  of  that 
which  he  already  yielded  unto,  must  necessarily  approve ; 
of  which  he  gives  a  large  example  in  Plato's  Meno. 

For  this  reason  he  used  to  say,  his  skill  had  some 
affinity  with  that  of  his  mother,  he  being  like  a  midwife' 
though  barren  (as  he  modestly  affirms)  in  himself,  en 
deavored  with  a  particular  gift  in  assisting  others,  to 
bring  forth  what  they  had  within  themselves ;  and  this 
was  one  reason  why  he  refused  to  take  money,  affirming 


300  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

that  he  knew  nothing  himself,  and  that  he  was  never 
master  to  any. 

These  disputes  of  Socrates  were  committed  to  writing 
by  his  scholars,  wherein  Xenophon  gave  example  to  the 
rest,  in  doing  it  first,  with  most  punctualness,  as  Plato 
with  most  liberty,  intermixing  so  much  of  his  own,  that 
it  is  not  easy  to  distinguish  the  master  from  the  scholar: 
whence  Socrates  hearing  him  recite  his  Lysis,  said,  how 
many  things  doth  this  young  man  feign  of  me? 
OF  His  PHILOSOPHY. 

Porphyrius,  who  traduced  Socrates,  affirms,  he  was 
ingenious  in  nothing,  unlearned  in  all,  scarce  able  to 
write,  which,  when  upon  any  occasion  he  did,  it  was  to 
derision,  and  that  he  could  read  no  better  than  a  stam 
mering  schoolboy:  To  which  we  shall  oppose  these 
authorities  :  Xenophon  who  attests  he  was  excellent  in 
all  kinds  of  learning,  instanceth  in  Arithmetic,  Geome 
try,  and  Astrology;  Plato,  in  Natural  Philosophy; 
Idomeneus,  in  Rhetoric :  Laertius  in  medicine :  in  a 
word,  Cicero  avers,  that  by  the  testimony  of  learned 
men,  and  the  judgment  of  all  Greece,  as  well  in  wisdom, 
acuteness,  politeness  and  subtlety,  as  in  eloquence, 
variety  and  copiousness,  to  whatsoever  part  he  gave  him 
self,  he  was  without  exception  Prince  of  all. 

Noting  how  little  advantage  speculation  brought  to  the 
life  and  conversation  of  mankind,  Socrates  opposed  all 
pure  science  or  speculative  philosophy,  and  applied  him 
self  almost  purely  to  practical  ethics.  He  first,  saith 
Cicero,  called  philosophy  away  from  things  involved  by 
nature  in  secrecy,  wherein,  until  his  time  all  philoso 
phers  had  been  employed,  and  brought  her  to  common 
life,  to  inquire  of  virtues  and  vices,  good  and  evil. 

Man,  who  was  the  sole  subject  of  his  philosophy,  hav 
ing  a  twofold  relation  of  divine  speculation  and  human 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  301 

conversation,  his  doctrines  were  in  the  former  respect 
metaphysical,  in  the  latter  moral. 

His  metaphysical  opinions  may  be  thus  collected  and 
abridged  out  of  Plato,  Xenophon,  Plutarch  and  others. 

Philosophy  is  the  way  to  true  happiness,  the  offices 
whereof  are  two,  to  contemplate  God,  and  to  abstract  the 
soul  from  corporeal  sense. 

There  are  three  principles  of  all  things,  God,  Matter, 
and  Ideas ;  God  is  the  universal  intellect ;  matter  the 
subject  of  generation  and  corruption;  idea  is  an  incor 
poreal  substance,  the  intellect  of  God ;  God  the  Intellect 
of  the  World. 

God  is  one,  perfect  in  Himself,  giving  the  being,  and 
well-being  of  every  creature ;  what  He  is  (saith  he)  I 
know  not,  what  He  is  not,  I  know. 

That  God,  not  chance,  made  the  world  and  all  crea 
tures  ;  that  He  will  reward  such  as  please  Him,  and 
punish  such  as  displease  Him.  That  God  is  such  and 
so  great  that  He  at  once  sees  all,  hears  all,  is  every 
where,  and  orders  all.  This  is  the  sum  of  his  discourse 
with  Aristodemus,  to  which  we  may  annex  what  is  cited 
under  his  name  (if  not  mistaken)  by  Stobaeus. 

Care,  if  by  care  ought  may  effected  be  ; 

If  not,  why  car'st  thou,  when  God  cares  for  thee  ? 

He  held,  that  the  Gods  know  all  things,  said,  done,  or 
silently  desired. 

The  soul  is  immortal,  for  what  is  always  movable  is 
immortal. 

The  soul  is  pre-existent  to  the  body,  endued  with 
knowledge  of  eternal  ideas.  Thus  is  all  her  learning 
only  reminiscence,  a  recovery  of  her  first  knowledge. 

The  body  being  compounded,  that  is,  made  up  of  sev 
eral  combined  elements,  is,  like  all  material  compounds, 
destructible,  and  is  therefore  dissolved  by  death :  The 


302  Ethics    of  the    Greek    Philosophers. 

soul,  being  simple  or  of  the  nature  of  an  element,  is,  like 
all  elements,  indestructible,  and  is  therefore  incapable  of 
corruption,  and  passeth  into  another  life.  The  souls  of 
men  are  divine,  to  whom,  when  they  go  out  of  the  body, 
the  way  of  their  return  to  Heaven  is  open,  which  to  the 
best  and  most  just  is  the  most  expedite. 

The  souls  of  the  good  after  death,  are  in  a  happy 
estate,  united  to  God  in  a  blessed  inaccessible  place ;  the 
bad,  in  convenient  places,  suffer  condign  punishment. 

To  do  good,  is  the  best  course  of  life,  therein  fortune 
hath  share. 

They  are  best,  and  best  pleasing  to  God,  who  do 
anything,  with  any  art  or  calling  ;  who  followeth  none, 
is  useless,  to  the  public,  and  hated  of  God. 

He  taught  everywhere,  that  a  just  man  and  a  happy, 
were  all  one,  and  used  to  curse  him  who  first  by  opinion 
divided  honesty  and  profit  (which  are  coherent  by  na 
ture)  as  having  done  an  impious  act,  for  they  are  truly 
wicked  who  separate  profitable  and  just,  which  depends 
on  law.  The  Stoics  have  followed  him  so  far,  that  what 
soever  is  honest,  the  same  they  esteem  profitable. 

Being  demanded  by  Gorgius,  if  he  accounted  not  the 
great  King  of  Persia  happy  ?  I  know  not,  answered  he, 
how  he  is  furnished  with  learning  and  virtue;  as  con 
ceiving  that  true  happiness  consisteth  in  these  two,  not 
in  the  frail  gifts  of  fortune. 

He  said  he  wondered  at  those  who  carve  images  of 
stone,  that  they  take  such  care  to  make  stones  resemble 
men,  whilst  they  neglect,  and  suffer  themselves  to  re 
semble  stones. 

He  advised  young  men  to  behold  themselves  every 
day  in  a  glass,  that  if  they  were  beautiful,  they  might 
study  to  deserve  it;  if  deformed,  to  supply  or  hide  it  by 
learning. 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  303 

He  said,  to  begin  well  is  not   a  small  thing,  but  de 
pending  on  a  small  moment. 

He  said,  virtue  was  the  beauty,  vice  the  deformity  of 
the  soul. 

He  said,  outward  beauty  was  a  sign  of  inward  beauty, 
and  therefore  chose  such  auditors. 

In  the  life  of  man,  as  in  an   image,  every  part   ought 
to  be  beautiful. 

To  one  who  demanded  what  nobility  is,  he  answered, 
a  good  temper  of  soul  and  body. 

He  said,  the  office  of  a  wise  man  is  to  discern  what  is 
good  and  honest,  and  to  shun  that  which  is  dishonest. 

Justice  and  every  other  virtue  is  wisdom. 

To  be  ignorant  of  ourselves,  to  seem  to  know  those 
things  whereof  we  are  ignorant,  is  next  to  madness. 

That  a  pious  person  is  rightly  defined,  such  a  one  as 
knows  what  is  lawful  as  to  the  God^;  just,  he  that  knows 
what  is  lawful  to  men ;  that  a  man  is  wise  as  far  as  he 
knows;  that  what  is  profitable  is  fair  to  that  whereto  it  is 
profitable. 

He  conceived  the  only  wisdom  of  man  to  consist  in 
not  thinking  he  understands  those  things  which  he  doth 
not  understand. 

He  affirmed,  there  is  but  one  good  thing,  knowledge ; 
one  ill,  ignorance;  but  that  riches  and  nobility  had  no 
thing  in  them  of  worth,  but  on  the  contrary  all  evils. 

When  a  man  openeth  his  mouth,  his  virtues  are  as 
manifest,  as  images  in  a  temple. 

Being  demanded  what  wisdom  was,  he  answered,  the 
composure  of  the  soul ;  being  demanded  who  were  wise, 
they,  said  he,  who  do  not  easily  err. 

He  said,  be  not  forward  in  speech,  for  many  times  the 
tongue  hath  cut  off  the  head. 

In  war,  steel  is  better  than  gold ;  in  life,  wisdom  ex- 
celleth  wealth. 


304  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

That  the  greatest  of  vices  is  ingratitude ;  the  greatest 
of  obligations,  that  to  parents ;  that  a  disobedient  son  the 
Gods  will  not  bless,  nor  men  love. 

Our  prayers  should  be  for  blessings  in  general,  for 
God  knows  best  what  is  good  for  us;  our  offerings  pro 
portioned  to  our  abilities,  for  He  considers  integrity,  not 
munificence. 

He  said  (with  the  Pythian  Oracle)  that  the  Gods  are 
to  be  worshipped  according  to  the  law  of  the  city  where 
a  man  lives,  they  who  do  otherwise,  he  thought  super 
stitious  and  vain. 

The  best  way  of  worshipping  God  is  to  do  what  He 
commands. 

That  a  man  ought  to  inure  himself  to  voluntary  labor 
and  sufferance,  so  as  what  shall  be  imposed  by  necessity, 
may  appear  in  him  not  compulsive  but  free ;  that  soft 
ways  of  living  in  pleasures  beget  no  good  constitution 
of  body,  nor  knowledge  of  the  mind ;  that  tolerance 
raiseth  us  to  high  attempts,  is  the  effect  of  his  discourse 
with  Aristippus. 

He  said,  Death  resembled  either  a  deep  sleep,  or  a 
long  journey  out  of  our  native  country,  or  an  absolute 
annihilation  of  soul  and  body,  examining  all  which  he 
affirmed,  death  to  be  in  none  of  those  respects  evil ;  as 
to  the  first,  saith  Plutarch,  it  is  not  ill  with  those  that 
sleep,  and  we  esteem  that  sleep  sweetest  which  is  deep 
est;  and  if  we  look  on  it  as  a  journey,  it  is  rather  a 
blessing,  for  thereby  we  are  freed  from  the  slavery  and 
affections  of  the  flesh  which  possess  and  infatuate  the 
mind ;  in  the  last  respect,  it  makes  us  insensible  of  ill 
and  pain,  as  well  as  of  good  and  pleasure. 

He  said,  an  honest  death  is  better  than  a  dishonest  life. 

That  happiness  consists  not  in  luxury  and  pride,  that 
to  want  nothing  is  divine,  to  want  the  least  next  to 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  305 

divine,  is  the  conclusion  of  his  discourse  with  Antipho. 
Being  demanded  whom  he  thought  richest,  he  an 
swered,  him  who  is  contented  with  least,  for  content  is 
the  riches  of  nature.  It  is  the  property  of  God  to  need 
nothing;  to  need  least,  nighest  to  God. 

That  health  of  body  ought  diligently  to  be  preserved, 
as  that  whereon  all  knowledge  of  the  soul  depends,  is 
the  sum  of  his  discourse  with  Epigenes. 

He  advised  one  that  complained  he  had  no  delight  in 
his  meat,  to  refrain  from  eating,  whereby  his  diet  would 
become  more  pleasant,  cheap  and  wholesome. 

He  said,  the  hungry  wanted  no  sauce,  the  thirsty  no 
choice  of  wines. 

He  commended  quiet  and  leisure  above  all  things. 

Being  asked  what  was  a  young  man's  virtue,  he  an 
swered,  to  do  nothing  too  much. 

He  said,  we  ought  not  to  seek  pleasures  in  others,  but 
in  ourselves,  the  body  being  predisposed  according  as  it 
ought. 

Being  demanded  from  what  things  we  ought  to  re 
frain  most,  he  answered,  from  sordid  unjust  pleasures. 

When  a  woman  saith  she  loveth  thee,  take  heed  of 
those  w7ords,  more  than  when  she  revileth  thee. 

There  is  no  better  way  to  glory  than  to  endeavor  to 
be  good,  as  well  as  to  seem  such. 

Good  men  must  let  the  world  see  that  their  manners 
are  more  firm  than  an  oath. 

They  are  not  kings,  he  said,  who  are  in  possession  of 
a  throne,  or  come  unjustly  by  it,  but  they  who  know 
how  to  govern. 

A  king  is  a  ruler  of  willing  subjects  according  to  the 
laws,  a  tyrant  is  a  ruler  of  subjects  against  their  will, 
not  according  to  the  laws,  but  arbitrary. 

The  offices  of  a  good  citizen  are  in  peace,  to  enrich  the 


306  Ethics    of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

commonwealth,  in  war  to  subdue  the  enemies  thereof, 
in  embassy  to  make  friends  of  foes,  in  sedition  to  ap 
pease  the  people  by  eloquence. 

Being  demanded,  what  city  was  strongest,  he  said,  that 
which  hath  good  men. 

Being  demanded,  what  city  is  best,  he  said,  that  where 
in  are  proposed  most  rewards  of  virtue. 

Being  demanded,  what  city  lives  best,  he  said,  that 
which  liveth  according  to  law,  and  punisheth  the  unjust. 
His  SCHOLARS  AND  AUDITORS. 

Whereas  (saith  Cicero)  many  springing  from  Soc 
rates  by  reason  that  out  of  his  several  various  disputes 
diffused  everywhere,  one  laid  hold  of  one  thing,  another 
of  another ;  there  were  some,  as  it  were,  so  many  several 
families  differing  amongst  themselves,  much  disjoined 
and  disagreeing,  yet  all  these  philosophers  would  be 
called,  and  conceived  themselves  to  be  the  Socratics :  of 
these  were 

Plato,  from  whom  came  Aristotle  and  Xenocrates,  the 
first  taking  the  name  of  Peripatetic,  the  other  of 
Academic. 

Ajtiisthenes,  who  chiefly  affected  the  patience  and 
hardiness  in  Socrates,  his  discourse,  from  whom  came 
first  the  Cynics,  then  the  Stoics. 

Arjstippus,  who  was  more  delighted  with  his  more 
voluptuous  disputations,  from  him  sprung  the  Cyrenaic 
Philosophy. 

Others  there  were  who  likewise  called  themselves 
Socratics,  but  their  sects  by  the  strength  and  arguments 
of  the  former,  are  broken  and  quite  extinct :  such  were 

Phse,do,  an  Elean,  who  instituted  a  particular  school, 
from  him  called  Eliack,  which  afterwards  was  called 
Eretriack,  from  Menedemus,  who  taught  at  Eretria, 
from  him  Pyrrho,  thence  the  Pyrrhonians. 


Ethics    of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  307 

Euclid  of  Megara,  institutor  of  the  Megaric  school,  so 
named  from  Clinomachus,  his  disciple,  called  the  dia 
lectic,  ending  in  Zeno,  the  Citian,  who  introduced  the 
Stoic. 

The  Herillians  are  named  also,  as  a  sect  that  would 
be  called  Socratic.  To  these  recited  by  Cicero,  Suidas 
adds 

Bryso  of  Heraclea,  who,  together  with  Euclid,  in 
vented  disputative  logic. 

Theodorus,  surnamed  the  -Atheist,  who  invented  a 
peculiar  sect  called  Theodorean,  the  opinion  which  he 
taught  was  indifference. 

Other  disciples  of  Socrates  there  were,  who  followed 
his  philosophy,  not  appropriating  out  of  it  any  par 
ticular  sect,  and  therefore  most  properly  deserve  the 
title  of  Socratics,  such  are  Crito,  Chserephon,  Xenophon 
^Eschines,  Simias,  Cebes,  Glauco,  and  Terpsion. 

The  last  kind  of  his  auditors  were  those  who  made  no 
profession  of  philosophy,  of  whom  were 

Critias  and  Alcibiades,  who  afterwards  proved  the 
most  ambitious  spirits  of  the  Athenians,  but  it  was  dis 
covered  in  neither  whilst  they  conversed  with  Socrates, 
either  that  their  youth  was  not  capable  of  expressing 
their  vice,  or  that  they  cunningly  complied  (as  Xeno 
phon  conjectures)  with  Socrates,  in  hopes  of  being  by 
his  conversation  enabled  to  manage  their  former  designs, 
which  as  soon  as  they  attempted  they  left  off  their  friend 
ship  with  Socrates.  Critias  fell  from  him  and  converted 
his  affection  into  hate,  because  he  reproved  his  love  to 
Euthydemus;  Alcibiades,  naturally  dissolute,  was  re 
claimed  by  Socrates,  and  continued  such  whilst  he  con 
versed  with  him.  He  was  of  form  so  exquisite  as  gave 
occasion  to  some  to  calumniate  the  friendship  betwixt 
him  and  Socrates,  to  which  effect  Aristoxenus  is  cited 


308  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

by  Laertius  and  Athenaeus,  and  some  verses  of  Aspasia 
by  the  latter ;  his  vindication  we  refer  to  Plato  and 
Xenophon. 

Of  Socrates  his  instructions  to  Alcibiades  there  are 
these  instances. 

He  told  him  he  was  nothing  of  what  a  man  ought  to 
be,  that  he  had  no  advantage  by  the  greatness  of  his 
birth  above  an  ordinary  porter;  whereat  Alcibiades, 
much  troubled,  with  tears  besought  him  to  instruct  him 
in  virtue,  and  to  reform  his  vices. 

Perceiving  Alcibiades  to  be  exceedingly  proud  of  his 
riches  and  lands,  he  showed  him  a  map  of  the  world, 
and  bade  him  find  Attica  therein ;  which  done,  he  de 
sired  that  he  would  show  him  his  own  lands,  he  an 
swered,  that  they  were  not  there.  Do  you  boast,  re 
plies  Socrates,  of  that  which  you  see  is  no  (considerable) 
part  of  the  earth  ? 

Alcibiades  being  by  reason  of  his  youth  bashful  and 
fearful  to  make  an  oration  to  the  people,  Socrates  thus 
encouraged  him.  Do  you  not  esteem  (saith  he)  that 
shoemaker  (naming  him)  an  inconsiderable  fellow? 
Alcibiades  assenting;  and  so  likewise  (continues  he) 
that  crier  and  that  tent-maker?  Alcibiades  granting 
this,  doth  not,  saith  he,  the  Athenian  Commonwealth 
consist  of  these  ?  If  you  contemn  them  single,  fear 
them  not  in  an  Assembly.  To  these  add 

The  four  sons  of  Crito  the  philosopher;  the  eldest, 
Critobolus,  exceeding  handsome  and  rich,  but  by  Soc 
rates  (who  valued  his  own  estate  at  five  minae)  demon 
strated  to  be  poorer  than  himself. 

The  second  Aermogenes,  who  falling  into  poverty, 
Socrates  persuaded  Diodorus  his  friend,  to  entertain. 

The  third,  Epigenes,  a  young  man  of  an  infirm  body, 
whom  Socrates  advised  to  study  his  own  health,  as  that 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  309 

wherein  consisted  the  well-being  and  knowledge  of  his 
mind. 

The  youngest,  Cresippus. 

Of  poets,  Euripides  (as  the  writer  of  his  life  affirms) 
and  Euenus. 

Of  orators,  Lysias,  eminent  in  that  kind  easy  to  be  un 
derstood,  hard  to  be  imitated,  he  came  to  Athens  in  the 
second  year  of  the  82 rid  Olympiad.  Lysis,  whom  of  re 
fractory  he  made  pliant,  and  Isocrates,  of  whom  when 
very  young,  Socrates  presaged  great  things. 

In  the  number  of  his  scholars  and  auditors  were  also 

Adirnantus  and  Glauco,  sons  to  Aristo,  brothers  to 
Plato:  and  Charmides,  son  of  Glauco.  Glauco,  before 
he  was  twenty  years  old,  had  taken  upon  him  to  be  an 
orator,  and  aimed  at  some  great  office  in  the  common 
wealth,  not  to  be  wrought  off  from  this  fancy  which 
made  him  eve^where  appear  ridiculous,  until  addressed 
by  some  friends  to  Socrates,  who  made  him  acknowledge 
his  own  error  and  ignorance  of  that  which  he  had  un 
dertaken.  On  the  contrary,  his  son  Glauco,  of  excellent 
parts,  fit  for  any  office  in  the  commonwealth,  3^et  timor 
ously  shunning  all  public  affairs,  was  by  Socrates  in 
duced  to  undertake  the  magistracy. 

Nicostratus,  son  of  Theidotides  and  his  brother 
Theodotus. 

./Eantodorus,  and  his  brother  Apollodorus. 

Lysanias,  father  of  ./Eschines. 

Chaerecrates,  brother  to  Chserephon,  betwixt  whom 
there  was  a  great  quarrel,  but  reconciled  by  Socrates. 

Paralus,  son  of  Demodocus,  whose  brother  was 
Theages. 

Antipho,  a  Cephisiean,  father  of  Epigenes :  with  whom 
he  discoursed  of  self-indulgence,  teaching  gratis,  and  of 
veracity  in  Xenophon. 


310  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

Eumares,  a  Phliasian,  and  Xenomedes,  an  Athe 
nian. 

Besides  these,  there  are  with  whom  Socrates  dis 
coursed  and  instructed, 

Aristodemus,  surnamed  the  little,  who  would  not 
sacrifice,  pray,  or  use  divination,  but  derided  all  such  as 
did,  was  by  Socrates  convinced. 

Aristarchus  troubled  that  he  had  a  charge  of  kindred 
lying  upon  him,  by  Socrates  converted  to  a  willing  lib 
erality  towards  them. 

Eutherus,  who  returning  from  travel,  his  lands  taken 
away,  Iris  father  having  left  him  nothing,  chose  rather 
to  follow  a  trade  than  to  apply  himself  to  friends,  but 
diverted  by  Socrates. 

Diodorus,  whom  Socrates  persuaded  to  take  Herrno- 
genes. 

Enthydemus,  who  had  collected  many  sentences  of 
poets  and  sophists,  thought  he  excelled  all  his  equals, 
and  hoped  no  less  of  his  superiors,  who  was  by  Socrates 
constrained  to  acknowledge  his  own  error  and  ignorance, 
and  departed  much  troubled. 

Hippias,  an  Elean,  with  whom  Socrates  discoursed  of 
justice. 

Nicomedes,  Pericles,  and  Iphicrates,  with  whom  he 
discoursed  concerning  the  office  of  a  General.  Into  the 
last  he  infused  courage,  by  showing  him  the  cocks  of 
Midas  brustling  against  those  of  Callias. 

Thesetetus,  disputing  of  Knowledge,  he  dismissed,  in 
spired  as  it  were  with  divine  wisdom. 

Euthyphron^who  intended  to  accuse  his  own  father, 
he  dissuaded. 

With  Pharrhasius,  a  painter,  Clito,  a  statuary,  and 
Pistias,  an  armorer,  he  disputes  in  Xenophon  concern 
ing  their  several  arts. 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  311 

.     His  WRITINGS. 

They  who  affirm  that  Socrates  wrote  nothing  (as 
Cicero,  Plutarch,  Dion,  Chrysostom,  Aristides,  Origen, 
and  others)  mean  in  respect  to  his  philosophy,  in  which 
kind  he  never  wrote  anything  himself,  but  what  he  dis 
coursed  was  committed  to  writing  by  Xenophon,  Plato 
and  others  of  his  scholars.  Hence  the  works  of  Plato 
(particularly  Phsedo)  went  under  the  name  of  Socrates, 
and  are  so  cited  by  Aristotle  ;  but  that  some  things  were 
written  by  Socrates  himself,  is  evident  from  those  who 
affirm. 

He  wrote,  together  with  Euripides,  and  aided  him  in 
making  tragedies,  whence  Mnesilochus. 

The  Phrygians  is  Euripides  new  play 
But  Socrates  gave  it  the  best  array. 

And  again,  Euripides  is  steered  by  Socrates  and 
Callias. 

Now  thou  with  pride  and  self-conceit  o'erflow'st  ; 
But  all  the  cause  to  Socrates  thou  owest. 

Hither  refer  we  that  of  Cicero,  who  saith,  when 
Euripides  raade  his  play  Orestes,  Socrates  revoked  the 
three  first  verses.  He  wrote  also  some  fables  of  JEsop 
in  verse,  not  very  elegant,  mentioned  by  Plato,  Plutarch, 
and  Laertius,  beginning  thus: 

To  those  who  dwelt  in  Corinth,  ^Esop  said, 
Virtue  with  vulgar  wisdom  be  not  weigh'd. 

A  paean  or  hymn  in  honor  of  Apollo  and  Diana :  One 
that  went  under  his  name,  beginning  thus: 

Daelian  Apollo,  and  thou  fair, 
Diana,  hail ;  immortal  pair. 

is  by  Dyonisidorus  denied  to  be  his :  This  is  mentioned 
also  by  Plato,  to  which  some  add 

The  Encomium  of  Gryllus,  son  of  Xenophon,  slain 
in  the  Mantinean  Fight,  which  the  disagreement  of  times 
will  not  allow  ;  more  certain  it  is  he  framed 


312  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers, 

Dialogues,  which  he  gave  to  .Eschines,  seeing  him  in 
want,  that  he  might  get  money  by  them ;  to  these  add 

Epistles,  some  whereof  are  published  by  Leo  Allatius; 
that  he  writ  more  is  implied  by  Arrian  and  Athenaeus. 
His  MILITARY  ACTIONS. 

It  is  observed  by  many,  that  Socrates  little  affected 
travel,  his  life  being  wholly  spent  at  home,  saving  when 
he  went  out  in  military  service. 

In  the  second  year  of  the  eighty-sixth  Olympiad  broke 
forth  a  war,  the  greatest  that  ever  happened  amongst  the 
Grecians,  betwixt  the  Lacedemonians  and  the  Athenians. 
In  this  war  was  Socrates  thrice  personally  engaged; 
first  at  the  siege  of  Polydaea.  Here  Alcibiades,  his  com 
rade,  attests,  Socrates  outwent  all  soldiers  in  hardiness; 
and  if  at  any  time,  saith  he,  as  it  often  happens  in  war, 
the  provisions  failed,  there  was  none  could  bear  the  want 
of  meat  and  drink  like  him,  yet  on  the  other  side  in 
times  of  feasting,  he  only  seemed  to  enjoy  them,  and 
though  of  himself  he  would  not  drink,  yet  being  invited, 
he  far  out-drank  all  others,  and  which  is  strangest  of 
all,  never  any  man  saw  him  drunk.  The  excesses  of 
cold  in  the  winter,  which  in  that  country  are  extraor 
dinary,  he  as  wonderfully  endured,  when  the  frost  was 
so  sharp,  that  very  few  durst  go  out  of  their  tents,  and 
those  wrapping  their  legs  and  thighs  in  skins  and  furs, 
he  went  along  with  them,  having  no  more  clothes  than 
those  he  usually  wore.  He  walked  barefooted  upon  the 
ice  with  less  tenderness  than  others  in  shoes,  to  the 
wonder  of  the  soldiers,  who  thought  themselves  re 
proached  by  his  hardiness.  His  contemplative  rapture 
at  the  same  time  was  no  less  worthy  admiration  ;  he  fell 
into  a  deep  contemplation  one  morning,  and  continued 
all  the  while  standing  in  the  same  posture  ;  at  noon  it 
was  taken  notice  of  by  the  soldiers ;  who  told  it  from 


Ethics    of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  313 

one  another,  that  Socrates  had  stood  still  in  the  same 
place  all  that  morning:  in  the  evening  some  Ionian 
soldiers  wrapping  themselves  warm,  came  and  lay  down 
by  him  in  the  open  field,  to  watch  if  he  would  continue 
all  night  in  the  same  posture,  which  he  did,  until  the 
morning,  and  as  soon  as  the  sun  arose,  saluted  it,  and 
retired.  Of  these  kind  of  raptures  A.  Gellius  saith  he 
had  many.  We  must  not  omit  how  he  behaved  himself 
there  in  fight ;  seeing  his  friend  Alcibiades  deeply  en 
gaged,  and  much  wounded,  he  stepped  before  him,  de 
fended  him  and  his  arms  from  the  enemy,  and  brought 
him  safely  off.  Nor  was  his  modesty  inferior  to  his  love 
or  courage,  for  whereas  after  the  battle,  the  generals 
were  to  bestow  an  honorable  reward  upon  him  that  had 
fought  best,  the  judges  assigned  it  to  Socrates,  he  de 
clined  it,  and  by  his  earnest  intercession,  procured  that 
it  might  be  conferred  upon  Alcibiades. 

The  second  action  of  Socrates  was  in  the  first  year  of 
the  eighty-ninth  Olympiad  at  Delium,  a  town  in  Boetia. 
Socrates  in  this  engagement  behaved  himself  with  his 
accustomed  valor  (so  well,  that  Laches  confesseth,  if  the 
rest  had  fought  like  him,  they  had  not  lost  the  day)  and 
care  of  his  friends ;  for  seeing  Xenophon  unhorsed  in 
the  flight,  and  thrown  down  on  the  ground  (himself  like 
wise  having  his  horse  slain  under  him,  fought  on  foot) 
he  took  him  upon  his  shoulders  and  carried  him  many  a 
stadia,  and  defended  him  till  they  gave  over  the  pursuit. 
And  being  thus  at  the  loss  of  the  day,  with  others  dis 
persed  in  flight  (amongst  whom  was  Laches  the  Archon, 
and  Alcibiades)  in  the  constant  slowness  of  his  retreat 
expressed  a  courage  far  above  Laches,  frequently  look 
ing  back  and  round  about,  as  greedy  to  be  revenged  of 
the  enemy,  if  any  should  pursue  them  ;  which  was  the 
means  that  brought  him  off  more  safely,  for  they  who 


314  Ethics    of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

express  least  fear  in  their  retreat,  are  less  subject  to  be 
assaulted,  than  such  as  repose  their  confidence  in  flying. 

His    FALLING    OUT    WITH    THE    SOPHISTS    AND    WITH 
ANYTUS.     THE  CAUSE  OF  HIS  DEATH, 

The  Sophists,  masters  of  language  in  those  times, 
saith  Cicero  (whereof  was  Gorgius  of  Lecontium,  Thra- 
simachus  of  Chalcedon,  Protagoras  of  Abdera,  Prodicus 
a  Cian,  Hippias  an  Elian,  and  many  others)  professed 
in  arrogant  words  to  teach,  how  an  inferior  cause  (such 
was  their  phrase)  might  by  speaking,  be  made  superior, 
and  used  a  sweet  fluent  kind  of  rhetoric,  argute  in  sen 
tence,  lofty  in  words,  fitter  for  ostentation  than  pleading, 
for  the  schools  and  academies,  rather  than  the  forum, 
were  so  highly  esteemed,  that  wheresoever  they  came, 
they  could  persuade  the  young  men  to  forsake  all  other 
conversation  for  theirs.  These  Socrates  opposed;  and 
often  by  his  subtlety  of  disputing,  retelling  their  prin 
ciples,  with  his  accustomed  interrogatories,  demonstrated 
that  they  were  indeed  much  beneath  the  esteem  they 
had  gained,  that  they  themselves  understood  nothing  of 
that  which  they  undertook  to  teach  others;  he  withdrew 
the  young  men  from  their  empty  conversation:  these, 
who  till  then  had  been  looked  upon  as  angels  for  wit  and 
eloquence,  he  proved  to  be  vain  affecters  of  words, 
ignorant  of  those  things  which  they  professed,  and  had 
more  need  to  give  money  to  be  taught,  than  to  take  (as 
they  used)  money  for  teaching.  The  Athenians  taken 
with  these  reproofs  which  Socrates  gave  them,  derided 
them,  and  excited  their  children  to  the  study  of  solid 
virtue. 

Another  quarrel  Socrates  had  of  long  continuance,  for 
it  was  the  occasion  of  his  death,  but  begun  many  years 
before,  with  Anytus,  an  orator  by  profession,  privately 


Ethics    of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  315 

maintained  and  enriched  by  leather-dressers :  He  had  put 
two  of  his  sons  to  Socrates  to  be  taught,  but  not  being 
pleased,  that  whilst  they  were  in  that  way,  they  had  not 
learned  so  much,  as  to  be  able  thereby  to  get  their  living; 
he  took  them  from  Socrates,  and  put  them  to  that  trade 
which  himself  was  ashamed  to  own;  wherewith  Socrates 
being  much  displeased  in  respect  of  the  two  youths, 
whose  ruin  he  presaged,  (and  truly,  for  they  fell  after 
wards  into  debaucheries  which  occasioned  it)  spared  not 
to  reproach  Anytus  in  discoursing  to  his  scholars,  telling 
them,  that  the  trade  of  dressing  leather  was  not  fit  to  be 
spoken  of  amongst  young  men,  for  they  who  benefit 
themselves  by  any  art,  cherish  and  profess  it,  as 
Acumenus  Physic,  Damon  and  Connus  Music ;  even 
Anytus,  whilst  his  sons  were  his  scholars,  was  not 
ashamed  of  that  which  they  learned,  though  it  were  not 
sufficient  to  maintain  them  by  pleading ;  but  for  himself, 
he  gloried  that  he  walked  invisible  with  Pluto's  Helmet, 
or  Gyges's  Ring,  concealing  from  the  people  the  true 
means  of  his  subsistence,  which  indeed  was  by  dressing 
leather,  which  was  not  just;  to  be  ashamed  of  the  trade, 
and  not  of  the  profit ;  for  he  ought  to  own  this,  or  to 
disclaim  that. 

Anytus  (saith  ^Elian)  to  answer  this  reproach,  studied 
all  occasions  and  ways  of  revenge;  but  feared  the 
Athenians,  doubting  if  he  should  accuse  Socrates,  how 
they  would  take  it,  his  name  being  in  high  esteem  for 
many  respects,  chiefly  for  opposing  the  Sophists,  who 
neither  taught  nor  knew  any  solid  learning.  He  advised 
with  Melitus,  a  young  man,  an  orator,  unknown  to  Soc 
rates,  described  by  Plato,  with  long  plain  hair,  a  high 
nose,  and  a  thin  beard,  one  that  for  a  drachm  might  be 
bought  into  anything,  by  whose  counsel  he  begins  by 
making  trial  in  lesser  things,  to  found  how  the  Athen- 


316  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

ians  would  entertain  a  charge  against  his  life ;  for  to 
have  accused  him  upon  the  very  first,  he  conceived  un 
safe,  as  well  for  the  reason  already  mentioned,  as  lest 
the  friends  and  followers  of  Socrates  should  divert  the 
anger  of  the  judges  upon  himself,  for  falsely  accusing  a 
person  so  far  from  being  guilty  of  any  wrong  to  the 
state,  that  he  was  the  only  ornament  thereof.  To  this 
end  he  suborns  Aristophanes,  a  comic  poet,  whose  only 
business  was  to  raise  mirth,  to  bring  Socrates  upon  the 
stage,  taxing  him  with  crimes  which  most  men  knew 
him  free  from,  impertinent  discourse,  making  an  ill 
cause  by  argument  seem  good,  introducing  new  and 
strange  deities,  whilst  himself  believed  and  reverenced 
none ;  hereby  to  insinuate  an  ill  opinion  of  him,  even  into 
those  who  most  frequented  him.  Aristophanes  taking 
this  theme,  interweaves  it  with  much  abusive  mirth ;  the 
best  of  the  Grecians  was  his  subject,  not  Cleon,  the 
Lacedaemonians,  the  Thebans,  or  Pericles  himself,  but  a 
person  dear  to  all  the  Gods,  especially  Apollo.  At  first 
(by  reason  of  the  novelty  of  the  thing,  the  unusual  per 
sonating  of  Socrates  upon  the  stage)  the  Athenians, 
who  expected  nothing  less,  were  struck  with  wonder. 
Then  (being  naturally  envious,  apt  to  detract  from  the 
best  persons,  not  only  of  such  as  bore  office  in  the  com 
monwealth,  but  any  that  were  eminent  for  learning  and 
virtue)  they  begun  to  be  taken  with  the  Clouds  (so  was 
the  play  named)  and  cried  up  the  actor  that  personated 
Socrates  with  more  applause  than  ever  any  before,  giv 
ing  him  with  many  shouts  the  victory,  and  sending  word 
to  the  judges,  that  they  should  set  down  no  name  but 
that  of  Aristophanes.  Socrates  came  seldom  to  the 
theatre,  unless  when  Euripides  contested  with  any  new 
tragedian,  there,  or  in  the  Pyrseum,  then  he  went,  for  he 
affected  the  wisdom,  goodness,  and  sweetness  of  his 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  317 

verse ;  sometimes  Alcibiades  and  Critias  would  invite 
him  to  a  comedy,  and  in  a  manner  compel  him ;  for  he 
was  so  far  from  esteeming  comedians,  that  he  contemned 
them  as  lying,  abusing,  and  unprofitable;  whereat  they 
were  much  displeased  :  These  (with  other  things  sug 
gested  by  Anytus  and  Melitus)  wrere  the  ground  of 
Aristophanes  in  his  comedy,  who,  it  is  likely,  got  a  great 
sum  of  money  by  it,  they  being  eager  in  prosecution  of 
their  design,  and  he  prepared  by  want,  and  malice,  to 
receive  their  impression :  In  fine,  the  play  got  extraor 
dinary  credit,  that  of  Cratonus  being  verified. 

The  theatre  was  then 
Fill'd  with  malicious  men. 

It  being  at  that  time  the  feast  of  Bacchus,  a  multitude 
of  Grecians  went  to  see  the  play :  Socrates  being  per 
sonated  on  the  stage  and  often  named,  (nor  was  it  much 
the  players  should  represent  him,  for  the  potters  fre 
quently  did  it  upon  their  stone  jugs)  the  strangers  that 
were  present  (not  knowing  whom  the  comedy  abused) 
raised  a  hum  and  whisper,  everyone  asking  who  that 
Socrates  was,  which  he  observing  (for  he  came  not 
thither  by  chance,  but  because  he  knew  himself  should 
be  abused  in  the  play,  had  chosen  the  most  conspicuous 
seat  in  the  theatre)  to  put  the  strangers  out  of  doubt, 
he  rose  up,  and  all  the  while  the  play  lasted,  continued 
in  that  posture  (laughing).  One  that  was  present  asked 
him  if  it  did  not  vex  him  to  see  himself  brought  upon 
the  stage.  Not  at  all  (answered  he)  methinks  I  am  at 
a  feast  where  every  one  enjoys  me.  This  comedy  was 
first  acted  when  Isarchus  was  Archon,  Cratinus  Victor 
in  the  first  year  of  the  eighty-ninth  Olympiad :  Aristo 
phanes  being  by  some  reprehended  for  it,  to  vindicate 
himself,  caused  it  to  be  acted  again  the  year  following 
Amintas  being  Archon,  but  with  worse  order  than  at  first 


3i 8  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

Amipsias  also  (another  comic  poet)  derided  him  thus 
in  Tribune. 

O  Socrates,  the  best  of  few,  the  vainest 
Of  many  men  ;  and  art  thou  come  amongst  us? 
Where  is  thy  gown  ?  did  not  this  great  misfortune 
Befall  thee  by  the  leather-dresser's  help  ? 

His  TRIAL. 

Many  years  passed  since  the  first  falling  out  betwixt 
Socrates  and  Anytus,  during  which  time  one  continued 
openly  reproving,  the  other,  secretly  undermining,  until 
at  length  Anytus  seeing  the  time  suit  with  his  design, 
procured  Melitus  to  prefer  a  bill  against  him  to  the 
Senate  in  these  terms. 

Melitus,  son  of  Melitus,  a  Pythean,  accuseth  Socrates, 
son  of  Sophroniscus,  an  Alopecian.  Socrates,  violates 
the  law,  not  believing  the  Deities  which  this  city  be- 
lieveth,  but  introducing  other  new  Gods.  He  violates 
the  law  likewise  in  corrupting  youth  ;  the  punishment 
death. 

This  Bill  being  preferred  upon  oath,  Crito  became 
bound  to  the  Judges  for  his  appearance  at  the  day  of 
trial.  Soon  after  Anytus  sent  privately  to  him,  desiring 
him  to  forbear  the  mention  of  his  trade,  and  assuring 
him  that  he  would  thereupon  withdraw  his  action ;  but 
Socrates  returned  answer,  that  he  would  never  forbear 
speaking  truth  as  long  as  he  lived,  that  he  would  always 
use  the  same  speeches  concerning  him  ;  that  his  accusa 
tion  was  not  of  force  enough  to  make  him  refrain  from 
speaking  those  things  which  he  thought  himself  before 
obliged  to  say. 

The  interval  of  time  betwixt  his  accusation  and  trial, 
he  employed  in  his  usual  philosophical  exercises,  not 
taking  any  care  to  provide  his  defence,  for  which  being 
observed  and  questioned  by  Hermogenes,  son  of  Hip- 


Ethics    of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  319 

ponicus,  I  provide  apology  enough  (saith  he)  in  consid 
ering  and  pursuing  the  constant  course  of  my  life ; 
Hermogenes  demanding  how  that  could  be,  because 
(saith  he)  I  never  did  any  unjust  act,  which  I  conceive 
the  best  apology.  But  we  often  see  judges  (saith 
Hermogenes)  overswayed  by  rhetoric,  to  condemn  the 
innocent,  and  acquit  the  guilty.  The  truth  is,  replied 
Socrates,  going  about  to  make  my  apology,  I  was  twice 
withheld  by  the  daemon,  whereat  Hermogenes  wonder 
ing,  is  it  strange  (continues  he)  that  God  should  think 
it  fit  for  me  to  die  at  this  time  ?  Hitherto  no  man  hath 
lived  more  uprightly,  which  as  it  is  now  my  greatest 
comfort,  so  it  was  the  greatest  delight  to  myself  and 
friends ;  if  I  live  longer,  I  know  I  must  undergo  what  is 
proper  to  old  age,  defects  of  hearing  and  sight,  slowness 
to  apprehend,  aptness  to  forget,  how  can  I  then  be 
pleased  to  live  longer  and  grow  worse  :  it  is  likely  God 
in  His  love  to  me  hath  ordained  that  I  should  die  in  the 
most  convenient  age,  and  by  the  gentlest  means ;  for  if  I 
die  by  sentence  I  am  allowed  the  benefit  of  the  most 
easy  kind  of  death  ;  I  shall  give  my  friends  the  least 
trouble,  I  shall  do  nothing  unseemly  before  those  that 
are  present,  and  shall  depart  sound  in  body  and  soul ; 
is  not  this  very  desirable  ?  God  with  much  reason  for 
bids  me  to  make  any  defence.  If  I  could  effect  it,  I 
should  only  stay  longer  to  be  taken  away  by  the  torment 
of  diseases,  and  imperfections  of  age,  which  truly  Her 
mogenes  I  desire  not ;  if  when  I  give  an  account  of  my 
actions  towards  God  and  men,  the  judges  think  fit  to 
condemn  me,  I  will  rather  choose  to  die  than  beg  of 
them  a  life  worse  than  death. 

Other  friends  used  the  same  persuasions  to  him  with 
assurance  of  victory.  Lysias,  an  excellent  orator,  of 
fered  him  an  oration,  which  he  had  written  in  his  de- 


320  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

fence,  desiring  him  if  he  thought  good  to  make  use  of  it 
at  his  trial ;  Socrates  perused  it,  and  told  him,  that  it 
was  a  good  one,  but  not  fit  for  him.  Lysias  asking  how 
that  could  be?  Why  (saith  he)  may  not  a  garment  or 
shoes  be  rich,  yet  not  fit  for  me  ?  If  you  should  bring 
me  Sicionian  shoes,  I  would  not  wear  them  though  they 
were  fit  for  my  feet,  because  they  are  effeminate :  He 
conceived  the  oration  to  be  ingenious  and  eloquent,  but 
not  stout  and  manly  ;  for  though  it  were  very  bitter 
against  the  judges,  yet  was  it  more  rhetorical  than  be 
came  a  philosopher. 

The  da)'  of  trial  being  come,  Anytus,  Lyco,  and  Meli- 
tus  prepared  to  accuse  him,  one  in  behalf  of  the  people, 
the  second  of  the  orators,  the  last  of  the  poets.  Melitus 
first  went  up  into  the  chair  proper  for  that  purpose,  and 
there  spoke  an  oration  which  was  in  itself  mean  enough, 
but  withal  delivered  so  unhappily  and  schoolboy  like, 
that  sometimes  he  was  out  with  fear,  and  turned  about 
to  be  prompted  like  a  player,  enough  to  beget  laughter 
even  in  those  that  were  most  concerned  in  so  serious  a 
cause. 

That  Socrates  persuaded  his  auditors  to  contemn  the 
received  laws,  saying  it  was  fit  only  for  fools  to  be  gov 
erned  by  a  bean  (meaning  the  votes  of  the  Senate 
counted  by  beans.) 

That  he  was  intimately  conversant  with  Critias  and 
Alcibiades,  one  most  covetous  and  violent  in  the  oli 
garchy,  the  other  ambitious  of  tyranny. 

That  he  taught  disrespect  and  disobedience  to  parents, 
telling  his  scholars  he  would  make  them  wiser  than 
their  fathers,  and  that  it  was  lawful  for  any  one  to  bind 
his  father  if  he  were  mad,  and  for  those  that  were  the 
more  wise,  to  do  as  much  to  those  that  were  less  wise. 

That  he  taught  also  disrespect  of  all  other  kinsmen, 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  321 

saying  they  were  not  useful  to  the  sick,  or  to  the  ac 
cused,  the  first  being  in  more  need  of  a  physician,  the 
latter  of  an  orator ;  that  the  goodwill  of  unable  friends 
was  nothing  worth,  that  only  the  most  knowing  persons 
were  most  worthy  of  honor  ;  by  which  means  he  would 
arrogate  all  respect  to  himself. 

That  he  selected  out  of  the  poets  some  ill  places,  and 
perverted  others  that  were  not  so,  to  excite  his  friends  to 
impious  actions. 

That  he  often  repeated  and  misinterpreted  these  words 
of  Homer,  as  if  the  poet  allowed  the  poor  to  be  beaten. 

When  he  a  Prince,  or  some  great  person  meets, 
Such  with  soft  language  kindly  thus  he  greets  ; 
Happy  above  the  reach  of  fear  are  you  ; 
Sit  down,  and  bid  your  followers  do  so  too. 
But  of  the  lower  sort  when  any  speaks, 
Forth  these  words  with  blows  his  anger  breaks, 
Be  quiet ;  to  thy  betters  wretch  submit ; 
For  action  and  advice  alike  unfit. 

Melitus  (his  oration  ended)  came  down;  next  him 
came  Anytus  with  a  long  malicious  speech,  and  last  of 
all  Lyco  with  all  the  artifice  of  rhetoric  concluded  the 
accusation. 

Socrates  would  not  (as  was  the  custom)  procure  an 
advocate  to  plead  for  him  ;  all  the  while  his  accusers 
were  speaking,  he  seemed  to  employ  his  mind  about 
nothing  less  :  as  soon  as  they  had  done,  he  went  up  into 
the  chair,  (in  which  action  he  observed  that  the  daemon 
did  not  withhold  him)  and  with  an  angry  smile  begun 
this  unpremeditated  answer,  not  as  a  suppliant,  or  guilty 
person,  but  as  if  master  of  the  judges  themselves,  with  a 
free  contumacy  proceeding  not  from  pride,  but  the  great 
ness  of  his  mind. 

But  I  wonder  first  (Athenians)  how  Melitus  came  by 
this  knowledge,  that  (as  he  saith)  I  do  not  worship 
those  Gods  the  city  worships  ?  Others  have  seen  me, 


322  Ethics    of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

(and   so   might  Melitus   if  he  had  pleased)  sacrifice  at 
common  festivals  on  the  public  altars  ;  how  do   I  intro 
duce  new  Deities  when  I  profess  to  be  directed  in  all  my 
actions  by  the  voice  of  God  ?     They  who  observe  the 
notes  of   birds,  or  answers  of  men,  are  guided  by  the 
voice  :  none  doubts  of  thunder   whether   it  be  loud  or 
oraculous.     Doth  not  the  priestess  on  the  tripod  convey 
to  us  by  voice  what  the  God  delivers  to  her  ?     And  that 
He   foreknows  events,   communicating   them    to  whom 
pleaseth  him,  all  men  (as  well  as  I)  believe  and  profess. 
Others  call  those  that  foretell  events,  augurs,  soothsay 
ers,  and  diviners,  I  the  daemon,  and   (I  conceive)   more 
religiously    than  they  who    ascribe    a  divine   power  to 
birds.     That  I  am  no  impostor  herein,  many  can  attest 
who  have   asked   my  advice,  and  never  found    it    fail. 
Here  there  arose  a  murmur  in  the  Senate,  some  not  be 
lieving,  others   envying  what   he  said,  that  he  should 
surpass  them   in  such   a  particular  favor  of  the  Deity : 
Let  such  as  are   incredulous  hear  this   also  to  confirm 
their  opinion  that  I  am  not  favored  of  the  Gods ;  when 
Chaerephon  in  the  presence  of   many  witnesses,  ques 
tioned  the  Delphian  Oracle  concerning  me,  Apollo  an 
swered,  that  no  man  was  more  free,  more  just,  or  more 
wise  ;  (here  another  murmur  arose  amongst  the  judges  : 
he  proceeded.)     Yet  the  same   God  said  more  of   Ly- 
curgus  the  Lacedaemonian  Law-giver,  that  he  knew  not 
whether  to  call  him  a  God  or  a  Man ;  me  he  compared 
not  with  the  Gods,  though   he  gave  me   the   priority 
amongst  men.     But  trust  not  the  God  herein,  consider 
me  exactly  yourselves;   whom  know  you  less  a  servant 
to  corporeal  pleasures,  whom  more  free?     I   accept  not 
either  rewards  or  gifts  ;  who  more  just  than  he  who 
conforms  himself  to  the  present  time,  as  he  needs  not 
the  help  of  any  other ;  who  will  say  he  deserves  not  the 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  323 

title  of  wise,  who  since  he  was  able,  never  desisted  to 
learn  by  enquiry  all  good  possible :  and  that  I  took  not 
this  pains  in  vain,  is  evident  in  that,  many  citizens  and 
strangers   studious   of   virtue,   prefer    my   conversation 
above  all  others:    What  is  the  reason  that  though   all 
men  know  I  have  no  wealth  to  requite  them,  so  many 
desire  to  oblige  me  by  gifts  ?     That  I  require  no  return 
from  any,  yet  engage  so  many  ?     That  when   the  city 
being  besieged,  every  one  lamented  his  condition,  I  was 
no  more  moved  than    when    it    was   most    flourishing? 
That  whilst  others   lay  out  money  on  outward  things  to 
please  themselves,  I  furnish  myself,  from  within  myself, 
with  things  that  please  me  better.     If  none  can  disprove 
what  I  have  said,  deserve  I  not  the  commendations  both 
of  Gods  and  men?     And  yet  you   Melitus  pretend  that 
with   these   instructions    I    corrupt   youth;    every   one 
knows  what  it  is  to   corrupt  youth :  can  you   name  but 
one  that  I  of  religious  have  made  impious,  of  modest, 
impudent,  of  frugal,  prodigal,  of  sober,  debauched,  of 
hardy,  effiminate,  or  the  like  ?     But  I  know  those,  an 
swered  Melitus,  whom  you  have  persuaded  to  be  more 
obedient  to  you  than  to  their  own  parents.     That  as  far 
as  concerns  instruction,  replied  Socrates,  I  confess  this 
they  know  to  be  my  proper  care :  For  their  health   men 
obey  physicians  before  their  parents,  in  lawsuits  coun 
sellors  before  their  kindred  ;  do  you  not  in  war  prefer 
the  most  experienced   soldiers  to  command  before  your 
own  allies  ?     Yes,  answers   Melitus,  'tis  fit  we  should  ; 
and   do  you  think  it  reason,  then,  replies  Socrates,  if 
others  are  preferred  for  such  things  as  they  are  excellent 
in,  that  because  in  the  opinion  of  some,  I   have  an  ad 
vantage  beyond  others  in  educating  youth,  which  is  the 
greatest  benefit  amongst  men,  I  ought  therefore  to  die  ? 
Anytus  and  Melitus  (saith  he,  addressing  himself  to  the 


324  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

judges)  may  procure  my  death,  hurt  me  they  cannot: 
To  fear  death  is  to  seem  wise,  and  not  to  be  so  ;  for  it  is 
to  pretend  to  understand  that  which  we  understand  not : 
No  man  knows  what  death  is,  whether  it  be  not  the 
greatest  happiness  that  can  arrive  to  a  man,  and  yet  all 
fear  and  shun  it  as  if  they  were  sure  it  were  the  greatest 
misfortune. 

This  and  more  (saith  Xenophon)  was  said  both  by 
himself  and  his  friends,  but  the  judges  were  so  little 
pleased  with  his  unusual  manner  of  pleading,  that  as 
Plato  went  up  into  the  chair,  and  began  a  speech  in  these 
words,  Though  I,  Athenians,  am  the  youngest  of  those 
that  come  up  in  this  place,  they  all  cried  out,  of  those 
that  go  down,  which  he  thereupon  was  constrained  to 
do,  and  they  proceeding  to  vote,  Socrates  was  cast  by 
281  voices;  it  was  the  custom  of  Athens,  as  Cicero  ob 
serves,  when  any  one  was  cast,  if  the  fault  were  not 
capital,  to  impose  a  pecuniary  mulct ;  when  the  judges 
had  voted  in  that  manner,  the  guilty  person  was  asked 
the  highest  rate  whereat  he  estimated  his  offence ;  the 
judges,  willing  to  favor  Socrates,  propounded  that  de 
mand  to  him,  he  answered  25  (or  as  Eubulides  saith) 
100  drachms,  nor  would  he  suffer  his  friends,  Plato, 
Crito,  Critobolus,  and  Apollodorus  (who  desired  him  to 
estimate  it  at  50  minse,  promising  to  undertake  the  sum) 
to  pay  anything  for  him,  saying,  that  to  pay  a  penalty 
was  to  own  an  offence,  and  telling  the  judges  that  (for 
what  he  stood  accused)  he  deserved  the  highest  honors 
and  rewards,  and  daily  sustenance  at  the  public  charge 
out  of  the  Prytanaeum,  which  was  the  greatest  honor 
that  was  amongst  the  Grecians;  with  this  answer  the 
judges  were  so  exasperated,  that  they  condemned  him 
to  death  by  eighty  votes  more. 

The  sentence  being  past,  he  could  not  forbear  smiling, 


Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  325 

and  turning  to  his  friends,  saith  thus,  They  who  have 
suborned  false  witnesses  against  me,  and  they  who  have 
born  such  testimonies,  are  doubtless  conscious  to  them 
selves  of  great  impiety  and  injustice;  but  as  for  me, 
what  should  more  deject  me  now  than  before  I  wras  con 
demned,  being  nothing  the  more  guilty ;  they  could  not 
prove  I  named  any  new  Gods  for  Jupiter,  Juno,  and  the 
rest,  or  swore  by  such :  how  did  I  corrupt  young  men 
by  inuring  them  to  sufferance  and  frugality?  Of 
capital  offences,  as  Sacrilege,  Theft,  and  Treason,  my 
very  adversaries  acquit  me;  which  makes  me  wonder 
how  I  come  to  be  condemned  to  die ;  yet  that  I  die  un 
justly  will  not  trouble  me,  it  is  not  a  reproach  to  me, 
but  to  those  who  condemned  me ;  I  am  much  satisfied 
with  the  example  of  Palamedes,  who  suffered  death  in 
the  like  manner;  he  is  much  more  commended  than 
Ulysses  the  procurer  of  his  death.  I  know  both  future 
and  past  times  will  witness,  I  never  hurt  or  injured  any, 
but  on  the  contrary,  have  advantaged  all  that  conversed 
writh  me  to  my  utmost  ability,  communicating  what  good 
I  could,  gratis.  This  said,  he  went  away,  his  carriage 
answerable  to  his  words,  his  eyes,  gesture,  and  gait  ex 
pressing  much  cheerfulness. 

His  IMPRISONMENT. 

Socrates  (saith  Seneca)  \vith  the  same  resolved  look, 
wherewith  he  singly  opposed  the  thirty  tyrants,  entered 
the  prison,  and  took  away  all  ignominy  from  the  place, 
which  could  not  be  a  prison  whilst  he  was  there:  Here 
(being  fettered  by  the  eleven  officers)  he  continued 
thirty  days  after  he  was  condemned  upon  this  occasion : 
The  ship  which  carried  Theseus  and  fourteen  more  per 
sons  into  Greet;  he  vowed  if  they  got  safe  home  (as  it 
fortuned  they  did)  to  dedicate  to  Apollo,  and  to  send  it 
every  year  with  a  present  to  Delos,  which  custom  the 


326  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

Athenians  religiously  observed ;  before  the  solemnity, 
they  used  to  lustrate  their  city,  and  all  condemned  per 
sons  were  reprieved  till  it  returned  from  Delos,  which 
sometimes,  the  wind  not  serving,  was  a  long  time.  The 
priest  of  Apollo  began  the  solemnity,  by  crowning  the 
poop  of  the  ship,  which  happening  the  day  before  Soc 
rates  was  condemned,  occasioned  his  lying  in  prison  so 
long  after. 

In  this  interval  he  was  visited  by  his  friend,  with 
whom  he  passed  the  time  in  dispute  after  his  usual 
manner :  he  was  often  solicited  by  them  to  an  escape, 
some  of  them  offered  to  carry  him  away  by  force,  which 
he  not  only  refused,  but  derided,  asking,  if  they  knew 
any  place  out  of  Attica,  whither  death  could  not  come. 
Crito,  two  days  before  his  death,  came  very  early  in  the 
morning  to  him  to  the  same  purpose,  having  by  his  fre 
quent  visits  and  gifts  gained  some  interest  in  the  jailor, 
but  finding  him  asleep,  sat  still  by  him,  admiring  the 
soundness  of  his  sleep,  the  happy  equality  of  his  mind; 
as  soon  as  he  waked,  he  told  him  that  he  came  to  bring 
sad  news,  if  not  such  to  him,  yet  to  all  his  friends,  that 
the  ship  would  certainly  be  at  home  to-morrow  at 
furthest  (some  that  came  from  Suuium  affirming  they 
had  left  it  there)  but  that  in  all  likelihood  it  would 
come  that  day,  and  he  should  die  the  next.  In  good 
time  be  it,  answered  Socrates,  but  I  do  not  believe  it  will 
come  to-day ;  for  the  day  following  I  must  die,  as  they 
say,  who  have  the  power  in  their  hands;  but  that  I  shall 
not  die  to-morrow,  but  the  day  after,  I  guess  by  a  dream 
I  had  this  night,  that  a  woman  very  beautiful,  in  a  white 
garment,  saluted  me  by  my  name,  saying 

Thou,  ere  three  days  are  told, 
Rich  Phithya  shalt  behold. 

(The  same  relation,  according  to  Laertius,  he  made  to 


Ethics    of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  327 

J^schines.)  This  occasion  Crito  took  to  persuade  him  to 
save  himself,  which  he  pressed  with  many  arguments  ; 
that  his  friends  would  be  accused  of  covetousness,  as 
more  desirous  to  spare  their  wealth,  than  to  redeem  him  ; 
that  it  might  be  effected  with  little  trouble  and  expense 
to  them  who  were  provided  for  it;  that  himself  was  rich 
enough  to  do  it,  or  if  not,  Simmias,  Cebes,  and  others 
would  join  with  him  ;  that  he  ought  not  voluntarily  to 
thrust  himself  into  destruction,  when  he  might  avoid  it; 
that  he  should  leave  his  children  in  an  uncertain  mean 
estate ;  that  it  would  not  be  construed  constancy,  but 
want  of  courage.  Consider  well  these  reasons,  saith  he, 
or  rather  (for  it  is  now  no  time  to  stand  considering) 
be  persuaded,  what  is  to  be  done,  must  be  done  this 
night,  or  it  will  be  too  late.  Socrates  answered,  that  his 
cheerful  readiness  to  relieve  him  was  much  to  be  es 
teemed,  if  agreeable  to  justice,  otherwise,  the  less  just, 
the  more  blamable :  that  opinion  and  censure  ought  not 
to  be  regarded,  but  truth  and  equity  ;  that  wrong  must 
not  be  requited  with  wrong;  that  faith  should  be  kept 
more  strictly  with  a  city  than  with  private  persons ;  that 
he  had  voluntarily  subjected  himself  to  the  laws  of  his 
country,  by  living  under  their  government,  and  to  vio 
late  them  at  last,  were  great  injustice  :  That  by  breaking 
prison,  he  should  not  only  draw  his  friends  into  many 
inconveniences,  but  himself  also  into  many  dangers, 
only  to  live  and  die  in  exile;  that  in  such  a  condition, 
he  should  be  nothing  more  capable  to  bring  up  his 
children  well,  but  dying  honestly,  his  friends  would  take 
the  more  care  of  them :  That  whatsoever  inconvenience 
might  ensue,  nothing  was  to  be  preferred  before  justice; 
that  if  he  should  escape  by  treachery,  the  remainder  of 
his  life  would  be  never  the  more  happy,  nor  himself 
after  death  better  entertained  in  the  next  world.  These 


328  Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

things  (saith  he)  I  hear  like  the  Corybantian  Pipes,  the 
sound  of  these  words  makes  me  deaf  to  every  thing  else ; 
therefore,  whatever  you  shall  say  to  the  contrary,  will 
be  to  no  purpose ;  but  if  you  have  any  other  business, 
speak.  Crito  answering,  he  had  not  any  else:  as  for  this 
then  (concludes  he)  speak  no  more  of  it,  let  us  go  the 
way  which  God  points  out  to  us.  *  *  * 

Let  every  one,  therefore,  prepare  for  this  journey 
against  the  time  that  fate  shall  call  him  away:  you 
Simmias,  Cebes,  and  the  rest  here  present  shall  go  at 
your  appointed  hour,  me  fate  now  summons  (as  the 
tragedian  saith),  and  perhaps  it  is  time  that  I  go  into 
the  bath,  for  I  think  it  best  to  wash  before  I  take  the 
poison,  that  I  may  save  the  women  the  labor  of  washing 
me  when  I  am  dead.  ***** 

I  cannot  persuade  Crito,  saith  he,  that  I  am  any  thing 
more  than  the  carcass  you  will  anon  behold,  and  there 
fore  he  takes  this  care  for  my  interment;  it  seems  that 
what  even  now  I  told  him  that  as  soon  as  I  have  taken 
the  poison,  I  shall  go  to  the  joys  of  the  blessed,  hath 
been  to  little  purpose ;  he  was  my  bail,  bound  to  the 
judges  for  my  appearance,  you  must  now  be  my  sureties 
to  him  that  I  am  departed ;  let  him  not  say  that  Socrates 
is  carried  to  the  grave,  or  laid  under  ground,  for  know, 
dear  Crito,  such  a  mistake  were  a  wrong  to  my  soul ;  be 
not  dejected,  tell  the  world  my  body  only  is  buried,  and 
that  after  what  manner  thou  pleasest.  This  said,  he 
arose  and  retired  into  an  inward  room,  taking  Crito 
with  him,  leaving  us  discoursing  upon  our  own  misery, 
shortly  to  be  deprived  like  orphans  of  so  dear  a  father. 
After  his  bathing,  came  his  wife  and  the  other  women 
of  his  family  with  his  sons,  two  of  them  children,  one  a 
youth ;  when  he  had  taken  order  with  these  about  his 
domestic  affairs,  he  dismissed  them  and  came  out  to  us. 


Ethics   of  the    Greek   Philosophers.  329 

It  was  now  sunset,  (for  he  had  staid  long  within) 
when  the  officer  entered,  and  after  a  little  pause  said:  "  I 
have  not,  Socrates  observed  that  carriage  in  you  which 
I  have  found  in  others,  but  as  I  thought  you  the  most 
generous,  the  mildest  and  best  of  all  men  that  ever  came 
into  this  place,  so  I  now  see  you  hate  me  not,  for  that 
whereof  others  are  the  cause :  you  know  the  message  I 
bring,  farewell;  bear  what  you  cannot  remedy:"  With 
that  he  departed  weeping;  "Fare  thee  well,"  (said  Soc 
rates)    "I  will:"    "How  civil  is  this  man!  I  found  him 
the  same  all  the  time  of  my  imprisonment,  he  would 
often   visit   me,   discourse    with   me,    used   me    always 
courteously,  and  now  see  how  kindty  he  weeps  for  me : 
but  come  Crito,  let  us  do  as  he  bids  us,  if  the  poison  be 
ready,  let  it  be  brought  in;"  "The  sun  is  yet  scarce  set," 
answers  Crito:  " others  take  it  late  after  a  plentiful  sup 
per  and  full  cups;  make  not  so  much  haste,  there  is 
time  enough,"  he  replies,  "  They  who  do  so  think  they 
gain  time,  but  what  shall  I  gain  by  drinking  it  late? 
Only  deceive  myself  as  covetous  of  life,  and  sparing  of 
that  which  is  no  longer  mine;  pray  let  it  be  as  I  say:  " 
Then  Crito  sent  one  of  the  attendants,  who  immediately 
returned,  and  with  him  the  man  that  was  to  administer 
the  poison,  bringing  a  cup  in  his  hand,  to  whom  Soc 
rates  said,  "Prithee  honest  friend  (for  thou   art  well 
versed  in  these  businesses)  what  must  I  do?"     "No 
thing,"  said  he,  "but  as  soon  as  you  have  drunk,  walk 
till  you  find  your  legs  begin  to  fail,  then  lie  down,"  and 
in  so  saying,  he  gave  him  the  cup.     Socrates  took  it 
cheerfully,  not  changing  either  countenance   or  color, 
and  looking  pleasantly  upon  him,  demanded  whether  he 
might  spill  any  of   it  in   libation,  who    answered,   he 
had  made  no  more  than  would  just  serve;  "yet,"  saith 
Socrates,  "  I  may  pray  to  God,  and  will,  that  my  passage 


330  Ethics  of  the    Greek   Philosophers. 

hence  may  be  happy,  which  I  beseech  Him  to  grant," 
and  in  the  same  instant  drank  it  off  easily  without  any 
disturbance;  many  of  us  who  till  now  had  refrained 
from  tears,  when  we  saw  him  put  the  cup  to  his  mouth 
and  drink  off  the  poison,  were  not  able  to  contain  any 
longer ;  which  Socrates  observing,  friend  (saith  fce) 
what  mean  you  ?  For  this  reason  I  sent  away  the 
women  lest  they  should  be  so  unquiet :  I  have  heard 
we  should  die  with  gratulation  and  applause,  be  quiet 
then  and  take  it  patiently.  These  words  made  us  with 
shame  suppress  our  tears ;  when  he  had  walked  a  while, 
perceiving  his  legs  to  fail,  he  lay  down  on  his  back  as 
the  executioner  directed  him,  who  looking  on  his  feet 
pinched  them  hard,  asked  him  if  he  felt  it,  he  answered 
no,  he  did  the  like  to  his  legs,  and  showing  us  how 
every  part  successively  grew  cold  and  stiff,  told  us  when 
that  chillness  came  at  his  heart  he  would  die;  not  long 
after  he  spake  these  last  words,  O  Crito,  I  owe  JBscu- 
lapius  a  cock,  pay  it,  neglect  it  not.  It  shall  be  done, 
saith  Crito  ;  will  you  have  any  thing  else  ?  He  made  no 
answer,  lay  still  a  while,  then  stretched  himself  forth; 
with  that  the  executioner  uncovered  him,  his  eyes  were 
set,  Crito  closed  them.  This  (saith  Plato)  was  the 
end  of  the  best,  the  wisest,  and  most  just  of  men :  a 
story,  which  Cicero  professeth,  he  never  read  wihout 
tears. 

Aristotle  saith,  that  a  Magus  coming  from  Syria  to 
Athens,  not  only  reprehended  Socrates  for  many  things, 
but  foretold  him  also  that  he  should  die  a  violent  death. 

Laertius  closeth  his  life  with  this  epigram, 

Drink  Socrates  with  Jove,  next  whom  enthron'd, 
By  Gods,  and  Wisdom's  self  as  wisest  own'd. 
Thee  the  Athenians  gave  a  pois'nous  draught. 
But  first  thy  wisdom  from  your  lips  they  quaft. 


Ethics    of  the  ^Greek   Philosophers.  331 

WHAT  HAPPENED  AFTER  His  DEATH. 

He  was  buried  with  tears  and  much  solemnity  (con 
trary  to  his  own  direction)  by  his  friends,  amongst 
whom  the  excessive  grief  of  Plato  is  observed  by  Plu 
tarch,  and  the  mourning  habit  of  Isocrates :  As  soon  as 
they  had  performed  that  last  service,  fearing  the  cruelty 
of  the  tyrants,  they  stole  out  of  the  city,  the  greater  part 
to  Megara  to  Euclid,  where  they  were  kindly  received, 
the  rest  to  other  parts. 

Soon  after,  a  Lacedaemonian  youth,  who  had  never 
more  acquaintance  with  Socrates  than  what  fame  gave 
him,  took  a  journey  to  Athens,  intending  to  become  his 
disciple ;  being  come  as  far  as  the  City  Gates,  and  ready 
to  enter  with  joy,  to  be  so  near  the  end  at  which  he 
aimed,  instead  of  Socrates,  he  meets  there  the  news  of 
his  death,  whereat  he  was  so  troubled,  that  he  would 
not  go  within  the  City  Gates,  but  enquiring  the  place 
where  he  was  buried,  went  thither,  and  breaks  forth  into 
a  passionate  discourse,  accompanied  with  many  tears, 
to  the  enclosed  dead  body ;  when  night  was  come,  he  fell 
asleep  upon  the  sepulchre;  the  next  morning,  affection 
ately  kissing  the  dust  that  lay  upon  it,  and  with 
much  passion  taking  leave  of  the  place,  he  returned  to 
Megara. 

Suidas  tells  a  like  story,  (for  that  there  were  more 
examples  than  one  of  this  kind,  Libanius  implies)  of  a 
Chian  named  Crysas,  W7ho  coming  to  Athens  to  hear 
Socrates,  went  to  his  tomb,  and  slept  there,  to  whom 
Socrates  appeared  in  a  dream,  and  discoursed  with  him; 
with  which  only  satisfaction  he  went  directly  home 
again. 

By  these  accidents  the  Athenians  were  awakened  into 
a  sense  of  their  injustice,  considering  they  were  ob- 


332  Ethics   of  the    Greek    Philosophers. 

noxious  to  the  censure  of  the  Lacedaemonians  by  extra 
ordinary  crimes,  whose  children  were  so  affectionate  to 
the  philosophers  whom  they  had  murdered,  as  to  take 
such  long  journeys  to  see  Socrates,  whom  they  \vould  not 
keep  when  he  was  with  them ;  hereat  they  became  so 
exasperated,  that  they  were  ready  to  tear  those  wicked 
men  that  were  the  occasion  of  his  death  piecemeal  with 
their  teeth,  the  whole  city  cried  out,  they  disclaimed  the 
act,  and  that  the  authors  thereof  ought  to  be  put  to 
death.  Antisthenes  furthered  their  rage  by  this  means. 
Some  young  men  of  Pontus  invited  to  Athens  by  the 
fame  of  Socrates,  met  with  Antisthenes,  who  carried 
them  to  Anytus,  telling  them  he  was  much  wiser  than 
Socrates;  whereupon  those  that  were  present,  with  much 
indignation,  turned  Anytus  out  of  the  city :  thence  he 
went  to  Heraclea,  where  some  say  the  citizens  also  ex 
pelled  him,  others  that  they  stoned  him  to  death.  Meli- 
tus  was  by  the  Athenians  condemned  and  put  to  death, 
others  affirm  the  like  of  all  his  accusers  without  trial. 
Plutarch,  that  they  so  much  hated  them,  as  they  would 
not  suffer  them  to  kindle  fire  at  their  houses,  they  would 
riot  answer  them  any  question,  they  would  not  wash 
with  them,  but  threw  away  the  water  they  had  touched 
as  impure,  until  unable  to  brook  this  hatred,  they 
hanged  themselves. 

In  further  testimony  of  their  penitence,  they  called 
home  his  friends  to  their  former  liberty  of  meeting,  they 
forbade  public  spectacles  of  games  and  wrestling  for  a 
time,  they  caused  his  statue,  made  in  brass  by  Lysippus, 
to  be  set  up  in  the  Pompeum,  and  (a  plague  ensuing, 
which  they  imputed  to  the  injustice  of  this  act)  they 
made  an  order  that  no  man  should  mention  Socrates 
publicly,  or  on  the  theatre,  that  so  they  might  forget 
what  they  had  done:  Euripides  (restrained  by  this  order 


Ethics    of  the    Greek    Philosophers.  333 

from  doing  it  directly)  reproached  them  overtly  in  a 
tragedy,  named  Palamedes  (in  whom  he  alluded  to  Soc 
rates)  particularly  in  these  verses, 

A  Philomele  ne'r  mischief  knew, 
Is  slain,  alas  !  is  slain  by  you. 

At  which  words,  all  the  spectators  understanding  they 
were  meant  of  Socrates,  fell  a  weeping. 

The  death  of  this  sole  person  (saith  Eunapius) 
brought  a  general  calamity  upon  the  city ;  for  it  may 
easily  be  collected  by  computation  of  times,  that  from 
thenceforward  the  Athenians  did  nothing  considera 
ble,  but  the  city  by  degrees  decayed,  and  with  it  all 
Greece. 


dB 


\r\ 


Unfrcrsify  of  Toronto 
Library 


DO  NOT 
REMOVE 
THE 
CARD 
OM 
/;  HIS 
POCKET 


Acme  Library  Card  Pocket 

Lnder  Pat.  **Ref.  Index  File" 
Made  by  LIBRARY  BUREAU